Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 281

NARRATING UTOPIA

Liverpool Science Fiction Texts and Studies General Editor DAVID SEED
Series Advisers I.F. Clarke, Edward James, Patrick Parrinder and Brian Stableford
1. Robert Crossley Olaf Stapledon: Speaking for the Future 2. David Seed (ed.) Anticipations: Essays on Early Science Fiction and its Precursors 3. Jane L. Donawerth and Carol A. Kolmerten (eds) Utopian and Science Fiction by Women: Worlds of Difference 4. Brian W. Aldiss The Detached Retina: Aspects of SF and Fantasy 5. Carol Farley Kessler Charlotte Perkins Gilman: Her Progress Toward Utopia, with Selected Writings 6. Patrick Parrinder Shadows of the Future: H.G. Wells, Science Fiction and Prophecy 7. I.F. Clarke (ed.) The Tale of the Next Great War, 18711914: Fictions of Future Warfare and of Battles Still-to-come 8. Joseph Conrad and Ford Madox Ford (Foreword by George Hay, Introduction by David Seed) The Inheritors 9. Qingyun Wu Female Rule in Chinese and English Literary Utopias 10. John Clute Look at the Evidence: Essays and Reviews 11. Roger Luckhurst The Angle Between Two Walls: The Fiction of J.G. Ballard 12. I.F. Clarke (ed.) The Great War with Germany, 18901914: Fictions and Fantasies of the War-to-come 13. Franz Rottensteiner (ed.) View from Another Shore: European Science Fiction 14. Val Gough and Jill Rudd (eds) A Very Different Story: Studies in the Fiction of Charlotte Perkins Gilman 15. Gary Westfahl The Mechanics of Wonder: the Creation of the Idea of Science Fiction 16. Gwyneth Jones Deconstructing the Starships: Science, Fiction and Reality 17. Patrick Parrinder (ed.) Learning from Other Worlds: Estrangement, Cognition and the Politics of Science Fiction and Utopia 18. Jeanne Cortiel Demand My Writing: Joanna Russ, Feminism Science Fiction 19. Chris Ferns Narrating Utopia: Ideology, Gender, Form in Utopian Literature 20. E.J. Smyth (ed.) Jules Verne: New Directions

Chris Ferns NARRATING UTOPIA


Ideology, Gender, Form in Utopian Literature

LIVERPOOL UNIVERSITY PRESS

First published 1999 by LIVERPOOL UNIVERSITY PRESS Liverpool L69 3BX 1999 Chris Ferns The right of Chris Ferns to be identified as the author of this work has been asserted by him in accordance with the Copyright, Design and Patents Act, 1988 All rights reserved. No part of this volume may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise without prior written permission of the publishers. British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data A British Library CIP record is available ISBN 0-85323-594-5 (hardback) ISBN 0-85323-604-6 (paperback) Typeset in 10/12.5pt Meridien by XL Publishing Services, Lurley, Tiverton Printed by Bell & Bain, Glasgow

FOR JEANNETTE

Contents
Acknowledgements Preface 1 Introduction DREAMS OF ORDER 2 The Utopian Dream of Order: More and his Successors 3 Bellamy and Wells: The Dream of Order in the Modern World 4 Dystopia: The Dream as Nightmare DREAMS OF FREEDOM 5 Libertarian Alternatives: Morris, News from Nowhere; Bogdanov, Red Star; Huxley, Island 6 A World of Ones Own: Separatist Utopias 7 Dreams of Freedom: Piercy, Le Guin, and the Future of Utopia Notes Bibliography Index 141 176 202 237 256 265 31 67 105 viii ix 1

Acknowledgments
During the apparently endless process of writing and rewriting this book I was assisted by advice, comments, and criticism from numerous friends and colleagues. For especially helpful commentary on earlier drafts of the manuscript I would like to thank Steven Bruhm, Ruth Levitas, Maureen McNeil, Peter Schwenger, Anna Smol, and (last but certainly not least) Rhoda Zuk. Maurice Michauds computer skills were of invaluable assistance, and I am also grateful to the students in my courses on utopian literature at Brock University and Mount Saint Vincent University, whose questions, ideas, and sometimes violent arguments forced me to clarify my own thinking. Parts of Chapters 1 and 7 originally appeared in English Studies in Canada 14.4, an earlier version of part of Chapter 4 in Dalhousie Review 69.3, and part of Chapter 6 in A Very Different Story: Studies on the Fiction of Charlotte Perkins Gilman, ed. Val Gough and Jill Rudd (Liverpool, 1998). This book is dedicated to the memory of Jeannette Mitchell, to whose ideas, and whose living, I owe more than I can say.

Preface
This is a book not so much about utopia, as about the stories people tell about utopia. It does not set out to provide a survey of utopian thought (of which there are already a number of excellent studies), nor indeed an exhaustive history of utopian literature. Rather, its preoccupation is with the nature of utopian narrativewith that curious hybrid of the travellers tale and the classical dialogue which emerges in the Renaissance, and whose outlines remain clearly apparent even in some of the most recent utopian writing. Utopia itself, unsurprisingly, exhibits an enormous range of configurations. Embodying as it does social and political alternatives to the society of the writers own time, its nature is obviously affected by numerous variables: the historical circumstances prevailing at the time and place of composition; the writers gender and class background; psychological factorsvariables which in turn give rise to a bewildering assortment of imagined social structures. Utopian society may be centralized and regimented, or anarchic and diverse; it may be religious, or secular; there may be free love, or rigid control of sexuality; the family may be central to its operation, or abolished altogether. Some utopias have detailed provisions for the division and distribution of wealth and possessions, while in others money and private property have been done away with. In terms of its extent, utopia may be confined to a remote island, or embrace the entire globe. Yet for all this diversity, one thing that exhibits far less variationat least so far as literary utopias are concerned is the story, the framing narrative which accounts for how the narrator or central character reaches the more perfect society and obtains the opportunity to witness its distinctive excellences. This study sets out to examine the nature of that story, and its relation to the social structures that utopia depicts. Given that a central premise of utopian fiction is that the world could be changed for the betterthat it might be possible to create a society preferable to that which existsit is understandable that the first concern of many readers is with the nature of that society. How does it work? Would it work? If it worked, would it be desirableand if so, for whom? Beyond that, however, arises the further question of the purpose served by the representation of such a society. What function does the imagining of utopian alternatives serve? What is the effect on the reader? Is the purpose of utopian fiction narrowly didactic, aimed at securing the readers assent

NARRATING UTOPIA

to a particular sociopolitical vision? Or is it more broadly concerned, as Ernst Bloch suggests, with the education of hope, the stimulation in the reader of the desire for and belief in new possibilities? Does the imagining of utopian alternatives provide the impetus to work for radical social change, or merely serve as a safety valve, reinforcing the status quo by diverting attention from practical possibilities for change in the here and now?1 Yet while these are perhaps the most immediate questions that utopia poses, in recent years increasing attention has been given not simply to the nature of the alternatives utopia presents, but to the ways in which they are presented. Critics such as Darko Suvin and Gary Saul Morson have pointed out the pitfalls that await the reader who sees utopian fiction as merely the uncomplicated expression of the writers political ideals, indistinguishable in effect from any other kind of political platform; while Suvin, Morson, and more recently, Tom Moylan have examined the ways in which it is possible for utopian fiction to fulfil more than a purely didactic function, where narrative serves mainly as a kind of sugar coating designed to ease the swallowing of an otherwise indigestible bolus of political theory. In their discussions of what Morson terms meta-utopia and Moylan critical utopia, they investigate the ways in which the narrative devices of utopian fictionor at least more recent utopian fictioninvolve the reader in a complex dialogue, rather than merely aiming to secure his or her unquestioning assent to the writers sociopolitical agenda.2 What emerges from these, as well as a number of other recent studies, is a growing consensus that, while utopian fiction has its inherent problems, these are capable of being resolved, provided one first abandons the old notion of utopia as a static ideal. Rather than a monolithic ideal, whose unquestionable superiority to existing society is taken for granted, utopia becomes more a matter of exploring possibilities, indicating new directions, offering glimpsesor what Angelika Bammer calls partial visionsof how things might be otherwise. This in its turn, it has been suggested, also involves modification, or even abandonment of the traditional accompanying narrative paradigm, in which a visitor to utopia is provided with a guided tour of the more perfect society. Where such a narrative presents a largely static picturea series of tableaux, in effectthe critical or meta-utopia restores a sense of process, and by doing so seeks to involve the reader in a critical consideration of the utopian enterprise, rather than simply aiming to secure his or her passive assent. Yet while there is much to be said for this view, it remains problematic in certain respects. In the first place, it may be argued that while the critical or meta-utopia avoids many of the pitfalls of traditional utopian narrative, it risks doing so at the cost of sacrificing something valuable, namely, the notion of a functioning utopian society as a practical possibility, rather than

PREFACE

xi

merely a locus of desire.3 In addition, while it is true that a number of writers have set out to represent utopia as other than a prescriptive and authoritarian ideal, the influence of the traditional utopian narrative paradigm has proved more difficult to escape. It is the nature of that influence, the reasons for its persistence, and its effect on the sociopolitical character of the imagined utopia, that constitute the main focus of this study. What this study seeks to show is, first, that specific narratives have their own ideological implications and, second, that in the case of utopian narrative, these are by no means entirely congruent with those of the utopian society described. As Pierre Macherey suggests, while narrative forms may change in response to the ideas they embody, they are also capable of resisting or transforming some of the implications of those ideas. What is proposed here is that the traditional utopian narrative possesses ideological implications of its own, which continue to influence the character of utopian fiction until well into the modern era. To explore what these are, and how they interact with a range of widely differing utopian ideals, this study begins with a discussion of some of the generally acknowledged problems and contradictions inherent in utopian narrativeproblems which have led some commentators to conclude that utopia has reached a dead end, and others to dismiss it as, for example, a relatively minor genre never quite detached from political theory (Frye, Varieties p.40). This is followed by an examination of the ways in which more recent studies of utopia have sought to broaden the scope of utopian inquiry, to clarify its terms of reference, and to explore new ways of articulating utopian desire. It is within this context that the study introduces its consideration of the ideological implications of narrative, and of utopian narrative in particular. Following this introductory chapter, the main body of the discussion falls into two sections, roughly chronological in sequence, which are structured primarily in terms of the content of the utopias under discussion. The first, under the heading Dreams of Order, comprises three chapters all dealing with utopias whose character is centralized and regimented. Chapter Two examines the origins of the traditional narrative paradigm in the Renaissance, when theories as to how a more perfect society might be organized (which date back to before the time of Plato) first find fictional representation. It begins, naturally enough, with a study of Mores Utopia, and then moves on to a discussion of two of the most influential utopias of the later Renaissance: Campanellas The City of the Sun and Bacons New Atlantis. Taken together, these works reveal a number of common narrative features which may be seen as distinctive of the genre. Yet while it is scarcely surprising that the resultant narrative paradigm should clearly reflect the

xii

NARRATING UTOPIA

ideological climate of the period in which it emerges, what is harder to account for is its stubborn persistence in the very different historical context of the modern eraparticularly given the range of alternative narrative models availableand it is the reasons for, and implications of its persistence in a modern context that the remainder of this study sets out to explore. Chapter Three moves forward to examine a number of utopias of the late nineteenth and early twentieth century in which the traditional paradigm is still clearly evident, and considers some of the consequences of its interaction with the very different social and political ideals embodied in the utopian societies depicted. Chapter Four concludes the section with an examination of the dystopian reaction to the centralized utopias of writers such as Bellamy and Wells. As a parodic counter-genre, dystopia is characterized by a very different narrative dynamic than its utopian counterpart; yet for all that, it will argued, is often unable to avoid reinscribing many of the very values implicit in the object of its parody. Section Two, under the heading Dreams of Freedom, looks at a range of attempts to imagine a utopia based on libertarian, rather than authoritarian premises, and examines the extent to which these too remain constrained by the limitations of the traditional narrative paradigm. Chapter Five deals with William Morriss attempt to imagine a utopia as far as possible removed from the regimented vision of Edward Bellamy, with Alexander Bogdanovs Red Star, written to keep alive the vision of revolutionary possibility in the aftermath of the failure of the Russian Revolution of 1905, and with the much later attempt of Aldous Huxley to imagine a utopian alternative to the centralized nightmare depicted in Brave New Worldall attempts, it will be argued, that are undermined by the narrative model they continue to deploy. In the final two chapters the gendered character of that model will be explored, along with the ways in which a number of women authors seek to transcend the limitations of a genre hitherto overwhelmingly dominated by men. Chapter Six examines the separatist visions of Charlotte Perkins Gilman and Sally Miller Gearhart, while Chapter Seven moves into the territory of the critical utopia, with a discussion of the utopian fiction of Marge Piercy and Ursula Le Guin, and includes a further reflection on the contemporary trends in both utopian fiction and utopian studies addressed in the Introduction. Like utopian fiction, the criticism of utopian literature also involves a narrative whether of the death of utopia or of its salvationand the study concludes with a consideration of the implications of such critical narratives.

1. Introduction
When future intellectual historians come to examine the second half of the twentieth century, they may well be struck by what might seem a widespread penchant for premature obituaries. During this period there have been announced not only the Death of the Novel, and of the Author, but also the End of Ideology, and evenin the aftermath of the collapse of the Soviet blocthe End of History. Yet while all the above appear to be carrying on their way unperturbed by announcements of their demise, the status of another alleged casualtyutopiais more questionable. It is significant, for example, that two of the most important surveys of utopian writing in recent years, the Manuels Utopian Thought in the Western World (1979), and Krishan Kumars Utopia and Anti-Utopia in Modern Times (1987), while reflecting widely differing ideological stances, should both reach pessimistic conclusions as to the future of utopia. Against this, of course, one might cite such phenomena as the new wave of feminist utopian writing during the 1970s, the re-evaluation of utopianism by Marxist theorists such as Ernst Bloch, or the significant expansion of the field of utopian studies over the past twenty years. Yet while this has led some commentators to conclude, more optimistically, that new approaches to utopia have opened up a promising new field of oppositional struggle on the cultural front, a more cynical assessment of such renewed critical interest in utopian studies might be that the academy is where ideas end up when they have nowhere else to go. Contradictory viewpoints, however, are scarcely new in the field of utopian studies: indeed, it has become something of a commonplace that the very concept of utopia itself is one fraught with contradictions and ambiguity. Whether such contradictions and ambiguity are disabling, or enabling, however, is another matter. Whether utopias inherent contradictions inevitably undermine the social alternatives portrayed, leading to an equally inevitable reinscription of most of the inequities it seeks to resolve, or whether by contrast such contradictions open the way to the fruitful exploration of diverse possibilities remains open to debate although in recent discussions of utopia an increasingly common critical narrative appears to be that, while the former used to be the case, new ways of both writing and reading utopias are now making the latter increasingly possible. Before exploring the ways in which this bears on a study of utopian narrative as such, however, it might be helpful to first examine the nature of the impasse from which escape is seen as necessary.

NARRATING UTOPIA

The Death of Utopia? The term utopia, of course, notoriously embodies a pun; Sir Thomas Mores coinage is deliberately ambiguous in its derivation. Its root may be taken as either ou-toposno place, or eu-toposgood place. Utopia then, may be defined as both a good place, an ideal (or at any rate, more perfect) society, yet at the same time one that does not existdesirable, perhaps, but at the same time unattainable. In utopian fictions this is reflected in the societys location, almost invariably remote or well insulated from the actual world to which it proposes an alternative: More and Francis Bacon are only two of the many writers who place their utopias on islands; Tomasso Campanellas City of the Sun is rendered impregnable by its sevenfold walls; while more recent writers have set their fictions in the future, on other planets, or both. What does tend to change with the passage of time, however, is the scope of utopia: where earlier utopias were conceived of as isolated bastions of sanity in the midst of a world of chaos and unreason, their more recent counterparts have tended to become more all-embracingthe Wellsian world state being a case in point. While there are exceptions to this rule (such as Charlotte Perkins Gilmans Herland, Aldous Huxleys Island, or Ernest Callenbachs Ecotopia), the overall trend has been toward utopian fictions where the more perfect society, rather than cutting itself off from the real world, seeks instead to replace it. In Marge Piercys feminist utopia, Woman on the Edge of Time, the forces of sexism and technocracy have been marginalized to the arctic regions and outer space; while in Always Coming Home, Ursula Le Guins anarchist vision of freely interacting communities is set so far in the future that our own society is barely even a memory. Yet this separation of utopia from the all-too-imperfect real world can never wholly obscure the links between the two. In theorizing a more perfect world, the writer remains governed by the realities of his or her own society, extrapolating from its more positive aspects, reacting against its more negative ones, recasting it in the light of social and political theories generated by the imperfect reality from which utopia separates itself. Equally, in narrative terms, there has to be some link, some fictional mechanism to render plausible the transmission of information regarding utopia to the non-utopian reader (to whom utopian fiction is, after all, addressed). Thus, no matter how inaccessible utopia might be, it always finds room for at least one visitor, a traveller, whether in time or space, who can observe and later testify to the wonders of the more perfect society. Although utopias isolation is clearly designed to protect it from contamination by the squalor and disorder of the real world, it can never be so isolated as to be inaccessible to the privileged individual who will

INTRODUCTION

eventually return to bear witness to the superiority of the utopian way. However exclusive the writers concentration on the distinctive excellences of utopia, however contemptuous he or she (more often he) may be of the defects of contemporary society, the fact of the connection remains: no matter how deeply buried in the text, the relation between utopia and reality is always a crucial aspect of utopian fiction. More perfect than the real world, yet nonexistent; separate, yet connected: the more closely one examines utopian fiction, the more its ambiguities become apparent. Not the least of these is what might best be described as an ambiguity of intention: often it seems that the writers themselves are not entirely sure what effect they are aiming at. (Indeed, when one considers the range of critical responses to utopian fiction, it becomes clear that this uncertainty is also shared by the audience.) Mores Utopia, for instance, contains what are surely deeply serious considerations of both the nature of good government and the role of the philosopher in societyyet it also contains elements suggesting that the whole work is little more than an elaborate scholarly joke (an impression which Mores subsequent correspondence reinforces).1 In later utopian fictions, serious, even mundane descriptions of political reforms and their consequences coexist with narrative devices whose fantastic nature works to heighten the readers sense of the fictional character of what is described. The incredible (the century-long trance of the narrator in Edward Bellamys Looking Backward, the gas which transforms human nature in H.G. Wellss In the Days of the Comet) go hand-in-hand with practical proposals for social and political reform. While commentators such as Darko Suvin and Gary Saul Morson rightly warn against the dangers of confusing utopian fiction with mere blueprints for social change2, it is only fair to say that the confusion is one that writers of utopian fiction often do little to discourage. Campanella, writing in his Italian prison, clearly saw The City of the Sun as embodying a practical basis for the establishment of an ideal society, while contemporary responses to Bellamys Looking Backward, ranging from William Morriss vehement denunciation to the enthusiastic reactions of those thousands of people who formed Bellamy societies, indicate that, for all its fantastic elements, it was seen as far more than merely wishful speculation. Both its threat and its promise lay in the fact that a substantial part of Bellamys utopian vision was seen as at least potentially realizable. Still more recently, B.F. Skinners Walden Two (1948), while vilified by a large number of critics, nevertheless prompted the foundation of several actual communities based on its principles. Yet even where the element of practical social and political programme is less obtrusive, some degree of persuasive intent remains a fundamental characteristic of utopian fiction. Although, as we shall see, a good deal of

NARRATING UTOPIA

recent criticism has tended to focus on the ways in which utopian fiction may be seen as a kind of thought experiment, presenting alternative forms of social organization to the reader in order to establish a creative dialogue in which the reader questions both his/her own assumptions and those of the author3even here problems remain. While there are works of utopian fictionmainly recent oneswhich seek to create an open-ended format conducive to such continuing dialogue, there is also a powerful tendency, in many cases, for utopian fiction to resort to narrative strategies whose effect is to foreclose such dialogue, rather than stimulate it. Utopian fiction is often characterized by a certain prescriptive quality, suggesting, not simply that things might be otherwise, but that they ought to conform to a specific vision. While utopian fiction may have the potential to open up wider horizons, to suggest the sheer extent of the possible, its effect is often impoverishing rather than enriching: instead of opening up space for the imagination, the utopian vision merely fills it with a construct, to use Ernst Blochs phrase, made banal by the fulfilment (Utopian Function , p.2). This is not to say, of course, that writers of utopian fiction are not aware of the problems inherent in the genre. As Wells suggests, in A Modern Utopia: There must always be a certain effect of hardness and thinness about Utopian speculations. Their common fault is to be comprehensively jejune. That which is the blood and warmth and reality of life is largely absent; there are no individualities, but only generalized people Too often the prospect resembles the key to one of those large pictures of coronations, royal weddings, parliaments, conferences and gatherings so popular in Victorian times, in which, instead of a face, each figure bears a neat oval with its index number legibly inscribed. [pp.910] On the other hand, to recognize a problem is not necessarily to resolve it: the inhabitants of Wellss own utopias are for the most part as bloodless and one-dimensional as the denizens of Bacons Bensalem or Campanellas City of the Sun. As in any fiction, utopian or otherwise, there are inherent problems in presenting characters who are merely ideals. Too often the readers experience of utopian fiction is akin to that of reading a novel whose entire cast is composed of Dickensian heroines. Psychologically speaking, it has been suggested that at least some of these deficiencies are rooted in what may be seen as the essentially regressive character of the fantasy underlying even those utopian visions which purport to describe societies of the future. In the Manuels monumental survey of utopian thought, for example, it is suggested that for all its apparently rational character, utopia embodies the longstanding human dream of a return to paradisea paradise which is in its turn a

INTRODUCTION

metaphor for the prenatal security of the womb. Other critics have pointed to the infantile dependency to which the citizens of many utopias of the authoritarian variety are reduceda dependency ruthlessly satirized by Huxley in his dystopian Brave New Worldwhile David Bleich argues that utopia is informed by a desire for immediate gratification that is typical of adolescence, not to mention being peculiarly masculine (p.3) in character. The failure of utopian fiction to provide what Wells describes as the blood and warmth and reality of life, then, might be seen to reflect a desire to turn away from, or inability to deal with the complexities of adult experience. The validity of such interpretations is a question to which we shall return; on the purely formal level, however, perhaps the basic problem lies in the hybrid character of utopian fiction. Whatever the psychological motivations involved, its aspirations are both political (to convince the reader of the desirability of its particular social vision) and aesthetic (to do so in an artistically convincing manner4). And in trying to do two things at once, it often succeeds in doing neither: the utopian vision is dismissed by political theorists as navely impractical, and by the literary critics as bad art. From a Marxist perspective, for instance, the main weakness of utopian theories is their tendency to make their goal the imposition of a static and often subjective ideal on society, disregarding the fact that historical development is a process involving the conflict and interaction of economic, social, and political forces. Progress is a process, not a finite goal to be attained once and for alland while the utopian vision may well offer a valid critique of society as it exists at a specific time, its static character inevitably dooms it to obsolescence. However radical its initial impulse, the utopian dream is continually outstripped by the course of history. As Engels suggests, the writer or theorist who pursues utopian solutions in a modern context is rather like: someone who, after the discovery and establishment of the laws of modern chemistry, reestablished the old alchemy, and who seeks to utilize the atomic weights, the molecular formulae, the quantivalence of atoms, crystallography and spectral analysis, solely for the discoveryof the philosophers stone. [p.276] Or as Marx puts it, rather more bluntly: the man who draws up a programme for the future is a reactionary.5 Of course, it is not only Marxists who are critical of utopian speculation: in much contemporary political discourse the term utopian is a pejorative oneto label a scheme utopian is often little more than a rhetorical device to rule it unworthy of serious consideration. Yet while the strictures cited above are addressed to utopian theorizing in general, rather than utopian

NARRATING UTOPIA

fiction in particular, their application to the latter is hard to refute. Even so comparatively recent a utopia as Huxleys Island (1962), whose blend of pacifism, eastern mysticism, free love, and the sacramental use of psychedelic drugs seemed briefly prescient in the later 1960s, now appears increasingly quainta period piecewhile earlier fictions, such as those of Bellamy and Wells, at least insofar as they embody what were once seen as practical programmes of social engineering, now seem not so much desirable ideals, as recipes for disaster. Such relevance as they continue to possess for a modern audience lies in what they reveal about the ideology of their specific historical period, and in such aesthetic merit as they may or may not exhibit. In this last regard, however, utopian fiction is often seen as just as deficient as it is when considered in the light of practical politics. Bernard Bergonzis lament that Wells should have deserted the realms of imaginative scientific fantasies such as The Time Machine or The War of the Worlds in favour of arid utopian speculation (p.165), or Frank Kermodes assessment of Island as one of the worst novels ever written (p.472) are scarcely atypical pronouncements. For Northrop Frye, utopian literature remains a relatively minor genre never quite detached from political theory (Varieties, p.40), while Krishan Kumar suggests that few utopias stand out as great works of literature and in many cases utopian authors are perfunctory in the extreme in their selection and use of the form. The didactic purpose overwhelms any literary aspiration (Utopia, p.25). And, once again, such criticisms are hard to refute. Considered in purely aesthetic terms, Wellss utopian fictions do represent, one must admit, a falling-off from his earlier science fiction, Huxleys last utopian vision a decline from the vigour of some of his earlier satire6while Bellamy frankly admitted that in Looking Backward barely enough story was left to decently drape the skeleton of the argument and not enough, I fear, in spots, for even that purpose (quoted in Kumar, p.151). And yetthe question remains whether or not this standpoint is really the most helpful one from which to examine utopian fiction. As with the political criticism that utopian speculation ignores the realities of the historical process, or the psychological reduction of utopia to a regressive fantasy, there remains the nagging suspicion that such readingsrather like that of the clergyman who, on reading Gullivers Travels, allegedly declared that for his part he didnt believe a word of itmay be missing the point. The Survival of Utopia While the problems and contradictions which bedevil utopian literature are real enough, the discussion so far leaves a number of questions

INTRODUCTION

unanswered. Why, given the extent of the problems involved, do writers go on writing utopias? Why, given the often unsatisfactory character of the end product, do readers go on reading them? And what is it that motivates both writers and readers alike to seek ways out of this (at least apparent) impasse? Certainly, presented in the terms above, the problems inherent in utopian narrative may well appear insoluble. Nevertheless, more recent discussions of utopian fiction have gone some way towards either addressing the problems involved, or else finding ways of looking beyond them. To begin with, it is clear that within a political context, while utopian remains a pejorative term, at least within the discourse of those with an interest in the preservation of the status quo, the radical potential of utopianism is considerably greater than might appear from the Marxist strictures cited above. While, as we have seen, both Marx and Engels were critical of utopianism, there has been a growing awareness that this criticism needs to be located in the context of contemporary debates within socialism; and that it by no means rules out a sympathetic consideration of utopia as an enabling vision, rather than a static ideal. Far from dismissing utopianism tout court, in fact, both Marx and Engels were sympathetic to it in many of its aspects, and its compatibility with Marxist thinking is evident in the recuperation of utopianism within a Marxist tradition by writers such as Ernst Bloch7 (although it should be said that Bloch himself remained critical of much utopian literature: witness his scathing dismissal of Wellss Men Like Gods as reducing utopia to a frolicking life like that of naked piano-teachers in Arcadia (Principle of Hope, p.617).) As Ruth Levitas suggests: The roots of Marxist objections to utopia can be found in the writings of Marx and Engels; however, their criticisms of utopian socialism have been used illegitimately as a justification of a general rejection of descriptions of the future socialist society. The concept of utopia deployed in this rejection confounds two issues: speculation about the future, and the possibility and means of transition to socialism. The real dispute between Marx and Engels and the utopian socialists is not about the merit of goals or of images of the future but about the process of transformation, and particularly about the belief that propaganda alone would result in the realisation of socialism. [Concept of Utopia, p.35] Or, as Vincent Geoghegan argues, what is under attack is not anticipation as such, but rather the failure to root this anticipation in a theoretical framework cognizant of the essential dynamics of capitalism (p.27).8

NARRATING UTOPIA

The recovery of a sense that utopia continues to possess at least radical potential has led in its turn to an exploration of ways in which utopian writing might escape the limitations evident in the examples of the past. In critical terms, perhaps the most radical strategy takes the form of what is in itself the highly utopian gesture of drawing a line between past and present, and starting againacknowledging the failure of utopia as traditionally conceived, and charting a new path altogether. Angelika Bammer, for example, argues that: Those who declared that utopia was dead were, of course, in a structural sense, right. In that sense, utopia had always been dead. Rather than describe a vital impulse toward change, utopia as it has traditionally been defined represents a static and, in the most literal sense, reactionary stance: a place which, being perfect, does not need toand will notchange. Conventional utopias thus embody an inherent contradiction. In their vision of a state in which change seems neither desirable nor possible, and even more significantly in their reconstruction of precisely the kind of dichotomous categories (notably the distinction between the actual real and the impossible ideal) that they claim to refute, they tend to reinforce established ways of thinking even as they set out to challenge them. [p.2] Against this, she suggests a range of possible revitalizing approaches, whose common feature is a moving away from the conception of utopia as total system. In place of the traditional utopias detailed description of the workings of an entire alternative sociopolitical structure, she sees more recent utopian writing as offering glimpses, partial visions of utopian possibilitya utopianism experimental rather than prescriptive, speculative rather than predictive propos[ing] a politics of change cast in the subjunctive instead of the imperative mode (p.51). Tom Moylan, while similarly critical of the traditional utopias narrative reduction of the multiple levels of utopian desire to the single, relatively abstract, field of social planning (Demand the Impossible, p.24), also exemplifies the growing tendency to examine utopian fiction in the context of the generic norms of fantasy and science fiction, rather than those of representational realism. Taking a number of examples of recent utopian science fiction, he argues that such writing breaks with the limits of the traditional genre and becomes a self-critical and disturbingly open form that articulates the deep tensions within the political unconscious at the present moment (p.210). The result is what he sees as an entirely new categorythe critical utopia in which the imposed totality of the single utopian text gives way to the contradictory and diverse multiplicity of a broad utopian dialogue (p.210). Yet if both Bammer and Moylan argue not only the possibility but the

INTRODUCTION

necessity of a radical break with the past, others have suggested that at least some earlier utopias encourage precisely the broad utopian dialogue which Moylan identifies as distinctively new. Morson, for example, while acknowledging that a large number of traditional utopias are essentially monologic in character, attempting to establish the absolute authority of a particular viewpoint, points to both Mores Utopia and Wellss A Modern Utopia as examples of what he terms meta-utopiasworks which, notwithstanding the authoritarian character of their imaginary sociopolitical structures, are designedly open to multiple and contradictory readings. Even if the utopian societies described may seem to embody a static ideal, rather than an active principle, they are nevertheless situated in a narrative context that holds that ideal up to critical inspection as one of a range of utopian possibilities. Peter Ruppert, examining the utopian tradition in the light of reader-response theory, goes still further, suggesting that this kind of reading caneven oughtto be the basis of reading all literary utopias. Where Bammer sees the traditional utopias insistence on closure, both in narrative terms and in terms of the total system it describes, as undermining its transformative potential (p.18), Ruppert argues that even though literary utopias are constructed like closed texts that try to elicit a precise response, they also force us to assume a more critical and detached position toward all social propositions, including the ones they offer (p.62). Seen in this light, it might be argued that all utopias are in a sense critical utopiasalthough pursuing this argument leads to a markedly ahistorical disregard for the fact that (for example) the huge success of works such as Looking Backward with contemporary audiences was based on reader responses radically unlike those which Ruppert proposes as normative. Nevertheless, how one reads utopian literature does seem to be at the root of at least some of the problems inherent in utopian narrativeand what is also clear, more broadly, is the extent to which some of these problems derive from definition. When Kermode criticizes Island as one of the worst novels ever written, he is obviously electing to read it in a particular kind of way, within the interpretive conventions of representational realisma decision not without its own ideological implications, and one which, as Wayne Booth points out, does not necessarily provide the most helpful context within which to read utopian fiction (p.631). Conversely, as Morson argues, disregarding the fictional aspect of utopian literature, and regarding it as merely the literary mould into which utopian political theory is poured, leads to equally skewed critical judgements:9 clearly, to read Mores Utopia as though there were no real generic distinction between it and, say, Gerrard Winstanleys The Law of Freedom in a Platform is to ignore a crucial dimension of the work as a whole.

10

NARRATING UTOPIA

Prior to the act of reading, then, it would seem that some kind of informed generic definition is necessaryyet here, once again, problems arise. That utopian fiction, pervaded as it is by ambiguity and contradiction, should present problems of definition is scarcely surprising. The very concept of utopia itself is an oddly slippery one, not only embracing a vast range of possible alternatives to existing society, but also often shading into kindred conceptions of a better worldthe earthly paradise, the Arcadian idyll, the millennium10and utopian fiction has likewise proved resistant to generic classification. It has variously been categorized as a kind of novel (however unsatisfactory), a type of romance, or, more recently, as a subgenre of science fiction.11 Yet, as Suvin has shown, even some of the most apparently commonsensical definitions prove, on closer examination, to be fraught with contradictions and unanalysed assumptions (Metamorphoses, pp.3762).12 Indeed, as Levitas argues, not only is there no real consensus regarding the definition of utopia, there is not even any general agreement as to the basis on which definition might be made: some commentators see utopia as primarily a formal category; others are more concerned with its contentthe nature of the society imagined; while others still focus on the function which utopian imagining is designed to fulfill. Thus, while in practice most commentators limit what they consider to be properly utopia without agreement as to what the proper limits, if any, are, there is a danger of researchers in the area making arbitrary and subjective selections of material; or, even if they are clear and methodical in their own use of the term, using it in an idiosyncratic way and talking past each other; or, indeed, wasting too much time arguing over what is or is not utopian. [Concept of Utopia, p.4] Unsurprisingly, therefore, even when the field is narrowed down to literary utopias alone, some of the most carefully crafted definitions continue to present difficulties. Morson, for example, while acutely aware of the problems involved, avoids the vagueness of some of the other commentators he discusses only at the cost of narrowing his generic definition to the point where it excludes a range of works that most would agree are clearly utopian: A work is a literary utopia if and only if it satisfies each of the following criteria: (1) it was written (or presumed to have been written) in the tradition of previous utopian literary works; (2) it depicts (or is taken to depict) an ideal society; and (3) regarded as a whole, it advocates (or is taken to advocate) the realization of that society. [p.72] The difficulty with this is that, while it works well enough with most works

INTRODUCTION

11

written up until the early twentieth century, it excludes a whole range of more recent examples: those that consciously challenge the tradition of previous utopian works, like Samuel R. Delanys Triton; those that represent societies that, while utopian, are clearly far from ideal, like Le Guins The Dispossessed; or those which, while presenting visions that are clearly utopian, can hardly be taken as advocating their realization, such as Gilmans Herland, or Sally Miller Gearharts The Wanderground. Suvin, by contrast, offers what would appear to be a more inclusive formula: Utopia is the verbal construction of a particular quasi-human community where sociopolitical institutions, norms, and individual relationships are organized according to a more perfect principle than in the authors community, this construction being based on estrangement arising out of an alternative historical hypothesis. [Metamorphoses, p.49] Yet while the more perfect formulation has the virtue of greater comprehensiveness, its effect is at the same time to downplay that prescriptive quality noted earlierthe tendency of many utopian fictions to present their visions not just as better alternatives, but as ideal solutions. Equally, one may question the utility, if not the logic, of a definition which results in the making of generic distinctions between works as closely related as Looking Backward and News from Nowheredenying the latter the status of a utopia (p.182), while according it to the former.13 Which brings us back to the formal problem alluded to earlier: the fact that utopian fiction is an inherently hybrid genre, incorporating so many features of contiguous modes that definition inevitably becomes problematic. Although distinct from the blueprint, or utopian treatise, utopian fiction nevertheless often contains many of its elements; likewise, while distinct from the novel, it often verges on the novelistic. Indeed, one of the recurrent problems in utopian fictionsits often awkward blend of the fantastic with the stolidly mimeticmay be seen as rooted in writers own uneasy consciousness of the novel as a desirable model to emulate. Wells, Huxley, and Le Guin have all suggested that utopian fiction would benefit from being more novelistic, each attempting (albeit with varying success) to work in that direction.14 Whether this is the best way of resolving the problems inherent in the composition of utopian fiction is a different matter; nevertheless, for the purposes of definition, it is as well to bear in mind that the boundaries between utopian fiction and other genres would appear to be more than usually permeable. Indeed, it might be argued that it is only by crossing these boundaries that the problems inherent in utopian narrative can be

12

NARRATING UTOPIA

resolved. Two of Moylans main examples of the critical utopia, for instance, Delanys Triton and Joanna Russs The Female Man, both move away from the straightforward delineation of the more perfect society to an exploration of varying social alternatives, both desirable and undesirable, an exploration more characteristic of the broader genre of science fiction. Delany, indeed (adopting Foucaults terminology), dubs his fiction a heterotopia, rather than a utopiaprompting the question whether it is in fact possible to resolve the problems inherent in the utopian genre without at the same time abandoning most of those elements that render it utopian.15 Yet while approaches such as these do much to recover the possibilities inherent in the category of utopia, and to resolve some of the problems attendant on utopian narrative, it is important to bear in mind that they themselves are also narrativesand, moreover, ones which rehearse a number of typically utopian narrative strategies. In contrast to the critical narrative of the death of utopia, the story they tell is effectively one of its salvation. In one account, utopia does indeed die, but only to be reborn under the new category of the utopian, or the critical utopiaa fresh start which draws a line between utopia and its past history in a manner very much characteristic of traditional utopian narrative. Ruppert uses readerresponse theory to tell a somewhat different story, one in which the contradictions and loose ends of utopian narrative find resolution and completion in a dialectical relationship with the reader,16 yet here again it is possible to detect the old utopian desire for wholeness, for a coherent total system. Even such moves as broadening the scope of utopian inquiry to encompass a whole range of utopian possibilities that go beyond the traditional ideal commonwealth conceived in isolation exhibit what Suvin refers to as a somewhat overweening imperalism (Metamorphoses, p.61) which might be read as parallel to the colonizing impulse of much utopian narrative, in which the problems inherent in the establishment of utopia in isolation are resolved by expanding it to embrace the wider territory of the world itself. While sharing some of the same assumptions, this study seeks to offer not so much a counter, as a counterpoint to the narratives above. Where they are concerned with ways forward, with ways of escaping the pitfalls of the traditional utopia, this study is more concerned with the connectedness of new utopian directions with what went beforeand in particular with the obstinate persistence of some of the characteristic patterns of traditional utopian narrative even into the radically different historical context of the present day. As the study of utopian literature has repeatedly shown, even those utopias which seek to break most radically with the norms of existing society often end up reinscribing many of the

INTRODUCTION

13

values they purport to oppose, and one question that clearly arises is whether the new approaches to both the study and writing of utopias are any more successful in transcending the limitations of the traditional model. Before that can be addressed, however, it is necessary to examine in more detail the nature of utopian narrative as such. The Nature of Utopian Narrative Unusually, given the diversity of opinion to which the discussion of utopia itself normally gives rise, there would appear to be something approaching consensus as to the nature of the traditional utopian narrative.17 What Angelika Bammer describes as the rudimentary plot (p.17) takes the form of a narrative which begins as the narrator/protagonist leaves his world to visit utopia and ends when he leaves utopia to return home (p.17) the choice of pronouns, incidentally, reflecting the fact that the protagonist in such narratives is nearly always male. Barbara Goodwin suggests that the traditional utopian form is that of a voyage to a lost island or into the future (p.15), in which the visitor is introduced to a perfect society which is viewed as an integrated totality (p.16); while Frye offers a slightly more elaborate account: In utopian stories a frequent device is for someone, generally a firstperson narrator, to enter the utopia and be shown around it by a sort of Intourist guide. The story is made up largely of a Socratic dialogue between guide and narrator, in which the narrator asks questions or thinks up objections and the guide answers them As a rule the guide is completely identified with his society and seldom admits to any discrepancy between the reality and the appearance of what he is describing. [Varieties, p.26] Originating in the Renaissance, it was a narrative model which at first proved serviceable enough; with the passage of time, however, its weaknesses begin to become more apparent. Comments on the shortcomings, literary or otherwise, of utopian narrative are, as we have seen, a recurrent phenomenon, and Frye is hardly alone in complaining that [o]ne gets a little weary, in reading a series of such stories, of what seems a pervading smugness of tone (p.26). Nevertheless, notwithstanding such criticisms, and despite radical changes over time in both the ideological character of the utopian societies imagined, and the range of alternative narrative models available, this curious hybrid of classical dialogue and travellers tale has proved remarkably resilient. Full-blown examples, such as Huxleys Island or Callenbachs Ecotopia, can be found as late as the second half of the twentieth century; substantial elements of the form are

14

NARRATING UTOPIA

present in a critical utopia such as Piercys Woman on the Edge of Time; while even dystopias such as Huxleys Brave New World and Orwells Nineteen Eighty-Four are by no means free of its influence. A narrative model, in other words, that evolved to articulate a particular sociopolitical vision in a specific historical context, continues to be deployed in very different historical circumstances, and in the service of a vision whose ideological implications are in many cases virtually antithetical. In order to account for this, a helpful starting point might be to examine the relation between narrative form and utopian content in more detail. In terms of content, for example, it is possible to distinguish, within the broader category of utopian fiction, between three main typeseach characterized by its own distinctive ideological orientation. The first, with roots which go back to Plato and beyond, may be identified as primarily centralist and authoritarian in orientationa dream of order conceived of in a world of disorder. The vast majority of utopias written prior to the twentieth century (News from Nowhere being a notable exception) conform to this pattern, portraying utopian society as something to be imposed on humanity in its own best interests. To modern eyes, of course, this traditional utopia seems regimented, lacking in freedomyet it clearly possessed a considerable appeal in the historical context surrounding its emergence. To a contemporary of More or Campanella, their more perfect societies offered in fact a great deal of freedomalbeit mainly a freedom from a range of existing constraints, rather than individual freedom as it is currently conceived of in western society. What such utopias offered was stability, security, freedom from hunger, from endless toil, from war. More, in the early 1500s, posited a society sufficiently rationally organized as to allow for a six-hour working day; Campanella, writing a century later, reduced it to four hours18and it requires little exercise of the historical imagination to envisage the degree of liberation which this would have offered to members of nearly all levels of society. Moreover, many of the earlier utopias emerged from historical contexts in which the promise of civil order must have seemed especially appealing. For Plato, writing against the background of constant bickering and warfare between rival city states, for More, with the memory of the Wars of the Roses still relatively fresh, for Campanella, living in an Italy torn apart by civil strife and foreign invasion, the notion of a sane, orderly, rational, and above all peaceful society must clearly have exerted an almost irresistible appeal. Ironically, the decline in the appeal of this type of utopia coincides with the development of many of the meanspolitical, economic, technologicalwhich might make such a social ideal a practical possibility. The utopian model of social control is, of course, predicated on the notion that such control would be used wisely, in the best interests of the citizen

INTRODUCTION

15

whereas modern experience of strong central authority has tended almost invariably to contradict this. While writers such as Bellamy and Wells carry the old, centralist, authoritarian tradition into the late nineteenth and early twentieth century, since then much of the gloss has vanished from the old utopian dream. The realities of modern dictatorship have made enthusiasm for the traditional model hard to sustainand this has in turn given rise to both reactions against, and rethinking of the premises of the traditional utopia. Reactions against the traditional utopian ideal take a variety of forms, the most significant being the dystopiaor anti-utopiawhich both parodies and subverts the traditional utopian model as a means of satirizing and warning against some of the more alarming trends in contemporary society. Yevgeny Zamyatins We and Huxleys Brave New World push the premises of the centralist utopia to the point where dream is transformed into nightmarea nightmare in which technological progress, hitherto glorified by writers from Bacon to Wells as central to the realization of the utopian vision, becomes the means to a totalitarian end. Rather than liberating humanity from the constraints imposed by nature, technology becomes the instrument for the imposition of a far more rigorous tyranny a tyranny of purely human agency. Citing Berdiaeff in the epigraph to Brave New World, Huxley implies that it is the growing practicability of utopia that renders it so threatening: from being an impossible ideal of perfection, it has been transformed (not least by technological progress) into a possible futurebut one to be avoided at all costs.19 What makes utopia a nightmare, in effect, is the fact that it is no longer merely a dream. With the proliferation of increasingly effective mechanisms for social control, in fact, dystopian fantasy has become in the modern era almost a myth in its own rightas expressive of the deep-seated dreams and anticipations of modern society as was utopia in the Renaissanceand as such it continues to flourish.20 George Orwells Nineteen Eighty-Four and, still more recently, Margaret Atwoods The Handmaids Tale continue this tradition, extrapolating from such apparently disparate starting points as State Socialism and fundamentalist Christianity, yet arriving at visions of a future society which bear a marked family resemblancemuch as do the more perfect societies presented in earlier utopian fiction. Yet reaction against the utopian ideal is not the only direction writers have explored. Another alternative which has been pursued is the possibility of a utopia which is no longer predicated on order. Writing from a range of libertarian perspectives, writers from Morris to Le Guin and Piercy have created utopian visions which are not so much dreams of order in a world of disorder as dreams of freedom in a world of oppression. Individual freedom and self-fulfilment become the main goals of the more

16

NARRATING UTOPIA

perfect society, rather than the imposition of a static, centralized order, however perfect in theory. Which brings us to the question of the relation between narrative structures and ideology, and the extent to which radically different ideological assumptions are accompanied by the evolution of radically different narrative strategies. Obviously, there are differences in narrative approach: to begin with, in both dystopian fiction and the science-fictional devices of the critical utopia one may see reflected the changing character of the literary models available at the time of writinga transformation which in its turn reflects the changing character of the social formations which produce them. Nevertheless, this fails to account for why certain narrative patterns seem stubbornly to persist even when the literary model from which they derive has become outmoded. In the case of utopian narrative, for example, there is a clear correlation between its character and that of other narrative models prevalent at the time of its emergence and the prevalence of those models is in turn a reflection of the surrounding historical context. Thus the travellers tale format of so many Renaissance utopias (the sailors yarn, as Bloch terms it) clearly reflects the popularity of this form during the age of exploration which constitutes part of the historical context in which they were produced. Equally, the massive resurgence of interest in Greek learning which characterized the Renaissance may be seen as reflected in the influence of the classical dialogue on the narrative practice of writers such as More and Campanella. Likewise, it is evident that the growing influence of the novel with the passage of time determines many of the modifications (greater emphasis on characterization, plot, and dramatic interaction) which utopian fiction comes to exhibitalthough it is at the same time worth noting that, until the early twentieth century, these remain for the most part only modifications, rather than transformations of the original pattern. Dystopian fiction, however, originating at a time when the novel constitutes the dominant narrative model, moves much further in this direction, its typical theme of the struggle of the individual against an oppressive society lending itself readily to a more novelistic treatment. And while some of the earlier efforts at writing utopian fiction from a libertarian perspective (News from Nowhere, Island) may struggle to find an appropriate form, later works have clearly benefited from the example of modernist and postmodernist narrative experiment, as well as from the broader revaluation of fantasy and speculative fiction in recent years. Yet it is not simply a question of writers making use of whatever narrative conventions happen to be current at the time. To begin with, it would seem that, as a genre, utopian fiction is particularly strongly influenced by a sense of its own specific traditionby the writers

INTRODUCTION

17

consciousness of what has gone before. However much it may be the product of its own time, utopian fiction is also, as Gary Saul Morson puts it, designed to be interpreted in the tradition of previous utopian works (p.74). Not only do writers of utopian fiction engage in an ongoing debate with the ideas of earlier writers, they are often clearly very much aware of the narrative example of their predecessors. (The Handmaids Tale is a striking instance of a work which makes self-conscious use of specific episodes in earlier fictionsrewriting, and ultimately subverting them.) This becomes especially significant when one considers the fact that narrative forms themselves possess their own ideological implications implications which in the case of utopian narrative are not always consistent with the ideological message inherent in the nature of the utopian society which that narrative depicts. Now clearly, every narrative has some ideological implications, however deeply buried: the decision to tell one story rather than another, to present a story in one way rather than another, is always to some extenthowever indirectlyconditioned by ideological assumptions. The traditional folktale, with its recurrent message of the possibility of individual self-fulfilment within a rigidly hierarchical social structure, or the Victorian novel which examines the phenomenon of social unrest within the reconciling framework of a bourgeois love story are both cases in point. What utopian fiction does is reveal still more nakedly the nature of the relationship between ideology and narrative strategynot least because of the gaps and contradictions which emerge when the two are considered together. In discussing this relationship, however, it is important to guard against making too simplistic an equation between form and ideological content: to avoid, for instance, a crudely mechanical cause-and-effect model, where ideological base manifests itself in narrative superstructure; or, conversely, the assumption that specific forms necessarily possess corresponding ideological implicationsthat fragmentary and open-ended narratives are ipso facto subversive, for instance, or that narratives characterized by formal coherence and narrative closure are inevitably conventional. (Such assumptions would seem to inform the almost ritual lambasting of Le Guin in which a number of recent studies have engaged.)21 A more sophisticated model of the relationship between ideology and narrative form is proposed by Pierre Macherey, who suggests that, while the history of forms corresponds to the history of ideological themes (p.91), their interaction is in fact a complex one: The form takes shape or changes in response to new imperatives of the idea: but it is also capable of independent transformations, or of an inertia, which bends the path of ideological history. [p.91]

18

NARRATING UTOPIA

While the implications of a specific narrative form may be closely congruent with the ideology prevailing at the time of its inception, the relationship between them often changes with the passage of time: their development does not necessarily proceed in harmonious parallel. To take the example of the detective tale: in the hands of Edgar Allan Poe it is initially expressive of a prevailing ideological ambivalenceof anxiety regarding the dark forces unleashed by the loosening of traditional social constraints under the impact of capitalism, yet at the same time of a countervailing faith in the capacity of unaided human reason to deal with them. In its subsequent manifestations, however, there can be little doubt that the form most often lends itself to the expression of a more conservative ideology. In the tales of Sir Arthur Conan Doyle, the role of the detective as defender of society is emphasized to a greater extent, as is the sense of the social order as a good to be defended; while the detective himself may be a maverick, the end result of his efforts is the affirmation of the existing order. Even the relative ineptness of the police serves only to reinforce faith in the ability of their social superiors: the ruling class can always produce a Holmeswhose brilliance also communicates the comforting message that significant individual action is still possible, notwithstanding the complexities of mass society. In tales where the detective is himself a policeman, the reinforcement of confidence in authority is stronger still. This is not to say, however, that the form itself is inevitably conservative in its implications: while it certainly lends itself more easily to the expression of an essentially conservative ideology, it can also be used for rather different ends. In works such as Jorge Luis Borges Death and the Compass, or Stanislaw Lems The Chain of Chance, the form acquires a renewed ambivalence, communicating a sense of the limitations of human reason in the face of the infinite complexity of reality, rather than a complacent confidence in the resilience of the existing order. The form, in effect, contains its own matrix of sedimented ideological implications,22 some (though not necessarily all) of which can be potentiated even where they run counter to prevailing ideological trends. Yet at the same time, the form is not wholly malleable: it can still undermine or deform the writers intentions, as in the case of designedly progressive detective fictions, where the villain is a policeman, or a corrupt politician, but where the threat they pose is nevertheless susceptible to a comforting resolution, in which their excision from the order of which they constitute part is enough to preserve its structure intact. What in effect becomes apparent, as Fredric Jameson argues, is the extent to which an already constituted narrative paradigm emits an ideological message in its own right (Political Unconscious, p.88). In the case of utopian fiction, a similar pattern is evident. Originally cast

INTRODUCTION

19

in the form of the travellers tale, the utopian narrative has continued over the years to manifest many of the forms characteristic featuresradical changes in the surrounding ideological context notwithstanding. The original appeal of this particular narrative model, as we have seen, is not hard to understand. As Frank and Fritzie Manuel observe: As strange lands were penetrated, the windows of credibility were opened wide. Authentic narratives about new nations and kingdoms with hitherto unheard-of customs were in themselves so marvellous that they lent verisimilitude to the imaginary utopia, however wild it might be. The boundary line between the real and unreal, possible and impossible, faded. [p.82] In an age of exploration, such narratives had a particular immediacy. Indeed, for More and his circle, one senses that this was not simply part of the appeal, but also part of the joke: it was actually possible that someone might take it seriously, as a factual account. Mores Raphael Hythloday, in the account he gives of his travels, is hardly less credible than many other visitors to exotic parts who returned home to tell the world of the wonders they had witnessed. So long as exploration persistsso long as the traveller may, potentially, have something new to sayso too does the appeal of the travellers tale, the sailors yarn, as a narrative model. The utopian tale, be its narrator Mores Hythloday or Campanellas Genoese mariner, has both exoticism and plausibility to commend it: it is incredible, certainly, but hardly more so than a variety of competing narratives which purport to be authentic. In effect, it is a narrative format almost equally suited to the representation of fact or fantasy, inasmuch as both are capable of embodying the radically newand a mode which proceeds by sequentially unveiling the unknown is as apt for articulating the utopian dream, as for relating the wonders of new discovery. Nevertheless, as the age of exploration draws to a close, the fictionality of utopian narrative becomes increasingly transparent. Colonized by the old, known world, the infinite possibilities of the new become closed and finite. Gradually, the traveller gives way to the rather less glamorous figure of the tourist: a cataloguer, not of the new and unknown, but of the meaninglessly exotic; returning home not with news from nowhere, but with holiday snapssouvenirs of an experience of little relevance, or even interest to the reluctant viewer. This transition, in its turn, finds an almost comical reflection in utopian narrative, where, while the form of the travellers tale is preserved well into the twentieth century, the intrepid explorer of the Renaissance utopia is replaced by the more prosaic figure of the holiday-maker. It is no coincidence, for example, that two of Wellss

20

NARRATING UTOPIA

utopian fictions begin with the central character going on vacationwhile in Huxleys Island, Will Farnaby reaches the mysterious utopian island of Pala, not in the course of a voyage of discovery, but when a recreational boating trip goes disastrously awry. At the same time, the emergence of the novel as the dominant form of fictional discourse, and the changing expectations on the part of the reader to which this gives rise, serve to render the limitations of the traditional format more apparent: compared to the novel, the travellers tale appears linear, episodic, lacking in dramatic interactiondeficiencies which only become more obvious when, as is often the case in more recent utopian fiction, the writer introduces novelistic elements (attempts at individual characterization, a love interest, and so forth) in an effort to remedy the problem. The continued survival of this narrative pattern, then, even in a world where the travellers tale seems more suggestive of the guided tour or the advertising brochure than of the exploration of new worlds, might well seem puzzling. Given its persistence even in some of the most recent utopian narratives, however, a consideration of the forms ideological implications may prove helpful. To begin with, it is clear that one essential feature of the travellers tale is that it is already finished: the experience it relates has to be completed before it can be narrated. The very presence of the traveller before his audience indicates his separation from the experience he is about to relate. For him (as has been observed, the traveller in such narratives is almost invariably male), the experience of utopia lies in the past, elsewhere in time, as well as in space. And because that experience has been completed, it can be presented as a whole, a static entirety. In a Renaissance context, where the notion of a static society seemed neither implausible nor undesirable, this presents few problems: while with hindsight we may see the process of historical change leading to the emergence of the modern world as well under way, neither process nor change would have seemed inherent features of society to the writers or readers of the period. While the Renaissance imagination was quite capable of conceiving of alternative, indeed better forms of society, there was less concern with the process of how they might come into being. Indeed, it is significant that a good deal of radical political dissent at the time was informed by millennialist fantasies, not simply of the transformation of society, but of its immediate, and above all, final transformationafter which further change would be unnecessary. It is only with the passage of time, once again, that problems arise: when writers such as Bellamy or Wells, writing in the context of a perceptibly changing world, continue to conceive of utopia in basically static terms. What is it, then, about a static social vision that should prove so problematic in terms of fictional representation? It has, to begin with,

INTRODUCTION

21

radical implications with regard to the depiction of time: if the utopian society is static, immune to change, or at least sufficiently perfect that only minor tinkering is needed to sustain it, then time is deprived of much of its meaning, since nothing that happens in time has any real effect. Mikhail Bakhtins concept of chronotope is helpful in this context: given the mutual interdependence of time and space which this posits, it is clear that the virtual elimination of time as a significant factor will have profound implications for the writers depiction of space. Which is precisely what we find: in the traditional utopian narrative, the absence of any real sense of time can only be compensated for by a corresponding extension in space. All the traveller can really do is visit, moving from place to place in a random and arbitrary order so as to witness the various excellences of utopian society. Since in such a society nothing of significance ever happens (everything of significance has already happened), it is of little consequence whether the visitor learns first about education and health care, and then about domestic arrangements, or vice versa. In addition, the fact that time in any meaningful sense has come to a stop often lends to the traditional utopian narrative a millenarian character which makes still more marked its separation from the reality to which it proposes an alternative. The virtual abolition of time leads to a corresponding lack of interest in process: as Bakhtin puts it, such fiction always sees the segment of a future separating the present from the end as lacking value; this separating segment of time loses its significance and interest, it is merely an unnecessary continuation of an indefinitely prolonged present (Dialogic Imagination, p.148). Which again has obvious narrative repercussions: in a context where time and historical causation have lost all meaning, the concept of individual character likewise becomes meaningless. Where the birth, life, death of the individual make no difference, individual distinguishing characteristics become insignificant; in narrative terms, this tends to result in the replacement of the individual character by that more durable construct, the typical citizen. As Frye remarks, in most cases the utopia-writer is concerned only with the typical actions which are significant of those social elements he is stressing (Varieties, p.26). In Looking Backward, for instance, Edith Leete is characterized (if that is the right word) as an indefatigable shopper (p.52), and it often seems as though her function as love interest is secondary to her utility as a narrative mechanism for taking the narrator shopping, thus opening his eyes to the wonders of utopian commerce. (Although the prevalence in North America of bumper stickers reading Born to Shop might be seen as indicating that such complete lack of character is not unique to utopia.) Interaction between such ciphers inevitably becomes equally meaningless, while that other dramatic staple of the novel, the conflict between individual and

22

NARRATING UTOPIA

society, is likewise precludedfor who would wish to oppose the utopian order?23 (Interestingly enough, however, many utopias provide for just such an eventuality, the penalties for dissidence ranging from exile or slavery to treatment in a mental institutionnot to mention Bellamys enlightened solution of solitary confinement on a diet of bread and water.) Dystopian fiction, by contrast, would seem to suffer from fewer limitations. Although it too posits the existence of a static social order, its parodic elements serve to imply an alternative value system in the light of which utopian society is judged and found wanting. There is an implicit dialectic between the imaginary and the actual which enlivens and gives depth even to so close a parody as Huxleys Brave New World constitutes of the Wellsian world state. In addition, the abandonment of the notion that utopia is desirable make possible that very element of dramatic interaction which the traditional utopian narrative so signally lacks. Since the utopian ideal is no longer seen as positive, the concept of opposition to it is no longer unthinkable. And in resisting the authoritarian aspirations of the State, dystopian dissidents may be seen as offering, at a narrative level, an embodiment of the readers own resistance to the closure and overdetermination which so often characterizes the traditional utopia. Even where the dissident elements are defeated (as they almost invariably are), there remains a degree of conflict, of dramatic process, which gives rise to a very different narrative pattern. Instead of the travellers bland report on the wonders of utopian society, we are given the portrayal of individuals in conflict with societya theme so often central to the novel. Where the static society is presented from a critical perspective, its existence is no longer inimical to successful narrative experiment. And, as a number of commentators have argued, where the concept of utopian stasis is also abandoned, as is the case in much recent utopian fiction, the range of possible narrative experiment is still further extended. All of which might seem to suggest that, in the case of the traditional utopian narrative, the problem is largely one of ideologythat the static character of such utopian visions is not so much a function of the narrative vehicle, but rather inherent in the writers own ideological assumptions. While Wells, for example, whose assertion that utopia should be not static but kinetic (A Modern Utopia, p.5) suggests a keen awareness of the problem, tries to address the issue primarily by means of narrative experiment, the effect of the static social vision he presents serves to neutralize those narrative elements which are freighted with different chronotopic and dramatic implications. His attempts to combine a portrait of utopian society with novelistic elements in In the Days of the Comet, or with social satire in Men Like Gods result in rather awkward hybrid narratives, whose non-utopian elements seem designed more to mask the

INTRODUCTION

23

limitations of utopian narrative than to resolve them. Even A Modern Utopia, which several critics have seen as a more successful attempt to create an open-ended and non-prescriptive utopian vision,24 never entirely succeeds in avoiding the pitfalls of the traditional utopia. For all its elaborate narrative framework and self-consciously speculative tone, the actual portrait of utopian society that emerges remains static, rather than kinetic; as in Men Like Gods and In the Days of the Comet, the impact of the narrative innovations is neutralized by the authoritarian implications of the utopian vision which they accompany. Yet consideration of another aspect of the traditional utopian narrative suggests that its limitations are by no means an automatic reflection of the writers ideological assumptionsthat the actual narrative itself possesses characteristics which may either reinforce or run counter to the writers ideological intent. For example, the earliest utopian narratives are not only modelled on the travellers tale, they are also, as Ruppert observes, structured and organized as dialogues (p.xi). Campanellas The City of the Sun, for instance, is laid out as a formal dialogueand even where this is not the case, it is clear that the dialogue is a fundamental feature of utopian narrative, whether the interlocutors are More and Hythloday, Julian West and Dr Leete, or Morriss William Guest and Old Hammond. Such dialogue, of course, may be seen as serving a purely functional purpose. Just as the travellers tale is a convenient narrative vehicle, in that it accounts for the process of witnessing utopia and returning to describe it, so the dialogue allows for the efficient transmission of the mass of factual detail required to flesh out the outlines of the more perfect society. Nevertheless, a number of critics (Ruppert included) have adduced from this a broader principle: that utopian narrative, by virtue of its origins, is inherently dialogic, even dialectical, inviting readers into active participation in the text, rather than relegating them to the status of passive observers. Yet while it is certainly true that a number of recent utopian fictions invite such interaction, a consideration of the conventions of the Renaissance dialogue, in which the traditional utopian narrative is rooted, might suggest that it is more often designed to have precisely the opposite effectto produce the illusion, rather than the reality of dialogue. Functioning primarily as a rhetorical device, it serves rather to reinforce the authority of a single viewpoint than to reflect a genuine process of debate. Mores Utopia is in fact most unusual in the degree of tension that exists between the conflicting points of view espoused by the narrator and Hythloday; more generally, the Renaissance dialogue (to a far greater extent than the Socratic model from which it derives) uses the appearance of debate or discussion as a rhetorical tool. One speaker either asks questions designed purely to set up the authoritative statements of the other (as is glaringly

24

NARRATING UTOPIA

the case in The City of the Sun), or else voices reservations or opposing arguments whose rebuttal only strengthens the case of the speaker who represents the authors own point of view. As Bakhtin observes: when the genre of the Socratic dialogue entered the service of established, dogmatic worldviews [it] was transformed into a simple form for expounding already found, ready-made irrefutable truth; ultimately, it degenerated completely into a question and answer form for training neophytes (Problems, p.110). Looking at some of the examples referred to above, it would appear that much of the discussion in Looking Backward or News from Nowhere bears this out. Serving a mainly didactic intent, its effect is to foreclose dialogue, rather than encourage it; confronted by such devices, the reader is likelier to feel that the debate has been rigged than that his or her active participation is invited. Rooted in such conventions, utopian narrative is often in fact anti-dialogic, rather than dialectical, enacting the suppression and marginalization of other voices, rather than allowing them free and creative interaction. Utopian narratives may seek to challenge established worldviews, but the alternatives they propose are often presented in a manner hardly less dogmatic. To this extent, then, the traditional utopian narrative may be seen to bear out Jamesons contention that in its generic form, a specific narrative paradigm continues to emit its ideological signals long after its original content has become historically obsolete (Political Unconscious, p.186)in this case serving to reinforce the writers own ideological assumptions, where these are authoritarian in essence, yet also to undercut those of a more libertarian cast. If Wellss attempts to resolve the narrative problems of utopian fiction are thwarted by the ideological limitations of his essentially static conception of utopian society, it might equally be said that the libertarian visions of Morris, and later Huxley, are undermined by the authoritarian implications inherent in their narrative format. A tension between ideology and narrative form, then, is often manifest in utopian fiction, with the one frequently at odds with the other. Utopian narratives, as Bammer argues, are texts in which an oppositional impulse is embedded in an essentially conservative form, and as a result are generically ambiguous (p.45). Yet this tension is reflected not just at the level of structure, but also in matters of detail. Detail, in fact, is a recurrent preoccupation of utopian fiction. Not only are the broad outlines of the utopian social system provided, but also all manner of minutiae whose relevance is not always readily apparent. While Mores explicit account of the seating plan for utopian mealtimes can be seen to have at least some function in the wider scheme of his description of utopian education, it is harder to see the justification for Bacons obsession with the smallest details of utopian clothing and personal jewellerystill less the insistence, in

INTRODUCTION

25

James Harringtons Oceana, on specifying the precise heights of the various ballot boxes! Writers of utopias often seem reluctant to leave anything to chance, and their resultant propensity to systematize even the most trivial aspects of social organization can, as Roland Barthes argues, end up undermining itselfif it is only pursued far enough. In his discussion of the French utopian theorist, Charles Fourier, Barthes suggests that Fouriers mania for classifying everything from social institutions to sexual proclivities (Fourier calculates, for example, that at the rate of 33 per million there are roughly 26,400 males in the world wholike himare predominantly attracted to lesbians) is carried to such extremes that it ultimately subverts the utopian impulse toward rational order (Barthes, p.93). So all-embracing is Fouriers system of classification that, rather than separating and distinguishing categories, it paradoxically suggests potential connections between even the most disparate objects. What, for example, do horses, cats, and fertilizer have in common? Each functions to consume the global surplus of watermelons produced by the utopian state: an infinite system of classification ultimately establishes an infinite series of connections, thereby undermining the whole purpose which classification is designed to serve. Of course, few writers go to such extremes as Fourierwhose theories, incredible though it may seem, were intended, not as fictions, but as the basis for a practical programme of action. It may be that he felt the writing of fiction to be superfluous, given the blossoming of art he envisaged as following inevitably on the realization of his utopian vision: When the globe shall have been organized and brought to a total of three billion inhabitants, there will normally be on earth thirty-seven million poets the equal of Homer, thirty-seven million mathematicians the equal of Newton, thirty-seven million authors of comedies the equal of Molire, and the same number in all other conceivable talents (these are estimates) [Quoted in Manuel and Manuel, p.667] Yet this kind of excess,25 the capacity to imagine possibilities extending so far beyond the actual, is in fact relatively uncommon in utopian fiction, which, at least until relatively recently has tended to limit itself to horizons dictated by what might rationally be anticipated. As opposed to the inventions of Fourier, which in Barthes view address[es] the absolutely new, that about which nothing has yet been said and which preach[es] only what Opinion holds to be impossible (p.88), utopian fiction for the most part remains constrained by a concern for what is at least plausible displaying in the process a caution that Bloch sees as typical of the bourgeois imagination.26 The impulse toward systematization remains, however, as

26

NARRATING UTOPIA

does the obsession with specifying the smallest details of utopian social organization. Underlying much utopian fiction is the implicit assumption that if only everything can be determined, every contingency anticipated, every space within the boundaries of utopia filled, then the disorder and consequent imperfection of reality can somehow be avoided. Yet the completeness to which such fiction aspires invariably proves an unattainable goal. No matter how clear its presentation, how comprehensive its scope, how coherent its organization, there are always contradictions, places where, as we shall see, utopia frays at the edges, revealing conflicting assumptions, incompatible agendas. Given this aspiration to completeness, to say everything, Machereys suggestion, that what is important in the work is what it does not say (p.87), is particularly apt. Underlying any fictional text are the shadows of what might have been said, even perhaps of what was intended or hoped to have been said, and an examination of the nature of the gap that exists between the text and its shadow, the word and the often more suggestive silence that surrounds it is often fruitful. But it is particularly so in the case of utopian fiction: committed as it is to a coherence and order more perfect than that which actually exists, its incoherences and inconsistencies are especially instructive. What does utopian fiction not say? With its stress on the difference, the superiority of its alternative society, it often glosses over the extent to which it continues to resemble the world to which it is designed to be superior. Hence, one question to be asked iswhat aspects of the writers own world does s/he choose not to address, not to reform? As well as examining what is different in utopia, we must also ask what remains the same. For even where it is most coherent, consistent, complete, utopia can never wholly cut itself off from the world of the writer who creates it, or of the reader to whom it is addressed. Equally, on the formal level, it is necessary to examine whether attempts to break away from the traditional narrative pattern are wholly successful, or whether in some of the apparently gratuitous details of the text its shadow remains apparent. When it comes to examining what is not said, however, it is striking that for all the wealth of detail that utopian fiction customarily provides, one area where such detail is conspicuously lacking is that surrounding the question of how the utopian society originateda question which is generally given only the most perfunctory treatment, or even avoided altogether. There are exceptions, of course: in News from Nowhere in particular, and to a lesser extent in Island, there is some attempt to account for the process whereby the more perfect society came into being. But in most cases utopia is achieved by fiatcreated once and for all, whole and perfect, by some King Utopus or Solamona; or else simply emerging from circumstances which are never made clear. In Looking Backward, for

INTRODUCTION

27

example, utopia just happens, inevitably, we are told, while the narrator is conveniently asleep; while Wells resorts to a whole battery of narrative devicesredemptive gases, parallel universes, a twin earth with an alternative historyto avoid altogether the practical issue of how a better society might be created. Such evasion is in itself revealing, suggestive of a reluctance to confront the nature of the relation between the real world and the utopian dream. Indeed, we are often given more detail about the barriers and boundaries that separate utopia from the real worldthe vast earthmoving project with which King Utopus severs Utopia from the mainland, or the sevenfold walls which enclose the City of the Sunthan is provided concerning the origins of the more perfect society. But it is not just the fact of the evasion which is significant: equally revealing is the compensatory elaboration of what might be termed the metaphors of transition which utopian fiction contains. While the question of how utopia came about is often evaded, there is no lack of detailed (and often extremely bizarre) explanations of its narrative link to the real world: although the reader may be starved of details concerning utopias creation, there is frequently a compensatory mass of detail concerning how the visitor to utopia got there. Once again, a characteristic chronotope is evidentone in which the spatial displaces the temporal: descriptions of utopian history may be perfunctory or nonexistent, but utopian geography, and the problems this poses for the traveller, are given extensive treatment. And when these metaphors of transition are examined, they often exhibit a striking family resemblance, suggestive not simply of ideological, but also psychological parallels. What is not said, and still more, what is said instead of what is not said, prove highly revealing of some of the most deep-seated impulses underlying utopian projections. Which in its turn, as this study will seek to demonstrate, points to the need to add one further term to the matrix of historical context, ideological orientation, and narrative structure which has so far been examined: the question of gender. For if the overwhelming majority of utopian dreams of order have been written by men, it is equally the case that the recent resurgence in utopian dreams of freedom has been predominantly the work of women. In the more detailed textual analysis that follows, it will be argued that this is no accident.

DREAMS OF ORDER

2. The Utopian Dream of Order: More and his Successors


Reference has already been made to the emergence of a distinctive pattern of utopian narrative during the Renaissance, and to its relation to some of the other available narrative models of the period. Before exploring its later transformations, however, it would be helpful to examine its distinguishing features in more detail. As has already been argued, utopian fiction reflects not just the ideological climate of its day, not just the influence of available literary models, but also the writers own awareness of and response to a specifically utopian literary tradition. This being so, an examination of the earliest exemplars of this tradition, of the works which in so many ways set the agenda for subsequent utopian fiction, may be seen as an essential prerequisite for an understanding of the radical changes in both ideology and narrative structure which such fiction has undergone in the past hundred years. The obvious starting point for such an examination, of course, is Mores Utopia: the work from which the genre itself takes its name. Yet to examine it in isolation presents some equally obvious problems. While, as Morson observes, the whole notion of genre presupposes shared assumptions on the part of both author and reader as to its nature and ruling conventions, it follows that: the exemplars of a genre occupy a unique status. For a genres first works cannot have been designed to be read in the tradition of previous works, nor can they have been designed to be interpreted according to the conventions of a generic tradition that began only with them works become exemplars only through the unforeseen creation of later works and the unanticipated emergence of a common hermeneutic approach to the entire class. History makes the exemplar; and tradition, insofar as it directs readers to take the exemplar as a member of the genre that it fathers, changes its semiotic nature: the original text is, in effect, re-created by its own progeny. [pp.745] Subsequent utopian fictions, in other words, by their common pursuit of some, but not all of the possibilities adumbrated by More, have served to establish a generic model with which the exemplarUtopiais only partially congruent. Utopia, in short, unlike its successors, is by no means

32

NARRATING UTOPIA

only a work of utopian fictionwitness the volume and diversity of critical commentary to which it has given rise, much of it devoted to the question of just what kind of work it is. It is only when examined in the context of subsequent worksof its utopian progenythat its distinctive generic characteristics become clear. By way of establishing those aspects of Mores fiction that are specific to the traditional utopian narrative model, rather than peculiar to Utopia alone, the present discussion will therefore also focus on two of the most influential utopias of the later Renaissance: Campanellas The City of the Sun (1623), and Bacons The New Atlantis (1627). The Historical Context of Utopia Utopia itself was first published in 1516, but it is clear that what one might term the utopian impulsethe urge to dream or speculate about a more perfect social orderwas hardly something new. Theories as to the nature of an ideal state go back to the time of Plato and beyond, while the basic human yearning for a better world, whether expressed in nostalgia for a lost Eden or vanished Golden Age, or in dreams of a heavenly afterlife, seems practically coterminous with civilization itself. Nevertheless, there can be little doubt that in Mores hands the expression of this impulse takes on a new and distinctive form. Utopia is neither a manifestation of nostalgia for the past nor a millennial dream. It is not an abstract, theoretical discussion of the mechanisms of an ideal state, after the fashion of Platos Republic, and still less is it a pastoral fantasy, whether of the temperate bliss of Arcadia, or the riotous overindulgence of the land of Cockaigne. What More offers is not a blueprint, but the portrait of a more perfect society in operation, and one which has been created by the unaided use of human reason. And it is this last which is perhaps the main source of Utopias lasting appeal, the reason why utopia has passed into the language as word signifying a fundamental cultural conceptthe fact that Mores fiction depicts the real possibility of humanity taking control of its own destiny and, in doing so, creating a world thatabove allmakes sense. This is not to say that in Utopias more perfect society individual human beings have become wholly rational: it is accepted that irrational and instinctual impulses will persist; however, such impulses are channelled and controlled by a social order that is, at all levels, rationally explicable. (Even its rituals and customs are, as Frye observes, susceptible to rational explanation.)1 Utopia portrays a society that is fundamentally orderly, part of its appeal lying in the fact that there is an explanation for everything. Unlike Mores own world, with its frequent lapses into chaos and anarchy which could only be made sense of by recourse to such essentially irrational concepts as the inscrutable workings of Divine Providence, Utopia could

THE UTOPIAN DREAM OF ORDER

33

be explained (and justified) in terms of reason alone. As a social construct, Utopia was simpler, more orderly, more elegant, and perhaps for that very reason more aesthetically appealing than any existing social systemin much the same way that the Copernican model of the universe was more appealing, in its orderly simplicity, than the old Ptolemaic version, with its untidy jumble of planetary epicycles. Nor was the appeal of that simplicity lessened by Mores shrewd decision to preface his purportedly eyewitness description of utopian society by a vivid portrait of some of the real-life alternatives to the rule of reason: the first book of Utopia depicts a world full of ignorant lawyers, foolish priests, grasping landowners, and powermad monarchsa satiric tour de force which inevitably prompts, on the readers part, a sympathetic predisposition toward the discourse that follows. A number of questions remain, however: what, for instance, prompts the emergence of this vision of human and social possibilities at this particular moment in time? And, having emerged, why should it then be so eagerly seized upon as a model for so many reworkings of the theme (many of which would doubtless have horrified the author of the original version)? Clearly, no discussion of the nature and appeal of Utopia can be divorced from a consideration of the historical and intellectual context within which it was composedand while one can scarcely hope, given the present studys terms of reference, to do anything like justice to the appalling complexity of the conflicting beliefs and ideologies underlying Renaissance thought, it might be helpful to point to some of the more significant connections between Utopia and the social and intellectual milieu within which More was writing. Considering when it was written, one of Utopias most striking features isat least at first sightthe unusual degree of what might be termed cultural relativism it displays. In Mores fiction, the society of his own day is judged and found wanting, not in the light of absolute and divinely ordained moral standards, but rather in comparison to specific (if hypothetical) instances of other human societies doing things differently and better. Far from exhibiting a xenophobic preference for the English (or even European) way of doing things, More appears to look to his imaginary foreign societies (Achorians, Macarians, Utopians) for examples from which his own society might profitably learn. And this apparent willingness to judge society by alternative human standards may be seen as, at least in part, the product of a quite literal widening of horizonsboth geographical and intellectual. In intellectual terms, More was both beneficiary and proponent of the resurgence of interest in classical Greek learninga phenomenon which, while prompted by renewed access to the wisdom of the past, rapidly came to offer a challenge to many of the received

34

NARRATING UTOPIA

intellectual assumptions of the present. The influence of Plato, in particular, proved a powerful stimulus to new ways of looking at the world, reinforcing as it did the sense that contemporary society had much to learn from the example of a past civilization whose intellectual accomplishments and modes of political organization were at least as sophisticated as those sixteenth century Europe. The revival of interest in Greek learning, in other words, inspired More with the sense of there being alternative models of social organization which, even if impractical in terms of the political realities of his own day, certainly bore thinking about. The expansion of intellectual horizons, however, might equally be seen as representing a shift in societys temporal perspectives: the opening of a new window on the past, together with the accompanying sense of another time as not only different, but also having value, opens the way to an awareness that the present is by no means immutable, that change inspired by the example of past human achievement is not only possible, but even desirable. And this potential challenge to human acceptance of the worlds existing order is of course reinforced by the simultaneous expansion of geographical horizonsto which More was equally responsive. Writing in the immediate aftermath of the discovery of the New World, and in the dawn of a new era of exploration, More could not help but respond imaginatively to the fact that different forms of social organization were not merely a feature of the past, but actually existed in the world of his own day. Admittedly, the information available concerning the actual nature of such different societies was scanty at best at the time he was writing, but this scarcely mattered: what was important was not so much the details, as the possibilityas may be seen from the way in which More seizes on a throwaway remark in one of Amerigo Vespuccis letters regarding the indigenous South Americans contempt for riches, and extrapolates from this an entire society based on the absence of private property. The expansion of geographical horizons provided a physical space into which the more perfect society could be projected, not merely as an abstract formulation, but as a concrete fictional portrayal, presented in the words of someone who claimed actually to have been there, and seen it with his own eyes. All of which suggestsand rightly sothat More was someone who responded eagerly to new thinking, to new ideas and possibilities: in both its vigorous attack on the shortcomings of the existing order, and its lively exploration of radical alternatives, Utopia is a work clearly reflective of the age of transition in which it was written. Yet it would be wrong to see More, as some critics have done, as therefore progressive. While he was very much a man of his time, that time was characterized by an extraordinary ferment of ideas, quite as many of which were backward-

THE UTOPIAN DREAM OF ORDER

35

looking as progressive. Indeed, even some of the most apparently radical ideas and attitudes prove, on closer inspection, to possess startlingly retrogressive implications. Thus, for example, while Mores was a period when Western society was on the threshold of an era of far-reaching religious reform (a process in which More himself was shortly to become embroiled, and not on the progressive side), an examination of the writings of the would-be reformers themselves suggests that it is doubtful whether their intention was to take religion in a new direction. Rather, it would seem that what is now termed the Reformation was initially conceived of in terms of the recovery of lost purity, of a return to principles and values which had been obscured by latter-day corruptionas a restoration, rather than a revolution. The revival of interest in Greek learning, likewise, was seen in Mores time in a somewhat different light. Where, to the modern eye, its most important aspect might seem to be the stimulus which it gave to new discovery, or the challenge which Platonic philosophy represented to the longstanding primacy of Aristotelianism, at the time the emphasis was rather different. When, for instance, in the early 1460s, Cosimo de Medici ordered Marcilio Ficino to begin translating the Greek manuscripts which his agents had been busy collecting following the fall of Byzantium, he instructed him to begin, not with the works of Plato (manuscripts of which he possessed), but with the Corpus Hermeticum, a collection of mystical and magical writings dating from between AD 100 and 300, but thought at the time to be the work of Hermes Trismegistus, a sage supposed to have been a near contemporary of Moses.2 And while hermetic philosophy, to the modern eye, might appear to be largely mumbo-jumbo, based on a catastrophic misdating (which caused passing references to Christianity to be interpreted as evidence of astonishing prophetic wisdom), it proved at the time to be enormously influentialas influential in its way as the work of Plato. When Copernicus produced his revolutionary heliocentric hypothesis, he appealed to the authority of Trismegistus for support; and when Giordano Bruno defended the Copernican hypothesis at the University of Oxford, he did so primarily because he saw heliocentricity as consistent with and supportive of the greater truths of hermetic philosophy.3 While there is little evidence that More had much sympathy for hermetic thought, he was none the less a great admirer of Pico della Mirandola, whose biography he had earlier translated into English. It was doubtless Picos exemplary piety and immense learning that chiefly commended him to More, but at the same time he can hardly have been unaware that Pico was also a magician, steeped in hermetic and Cabalist lore. Paradoxically, therefore, some of the most apparently progressive ideas of the Renaissance had their roots in dreams of a magical

36

NARRATING UTOPIA

transformation of the worlddreams which had as their goal, not progress, but the restoration of an order, a harmony, an innocence that had once existed, but had long since been lost. Even the scientific and geographical discoveries of the period were by no means immune to interpretations which saw them less as signs of progress than as fulfilments of biblical prophecy, indicative of the imminence of the second coming. Charles Websters study of science in Puritan England, The Great Instauration, reveals that much of the scientific investigation during the first part of the seventeenth century was prompted by the belief that it formed part of the essential preparation for the recovery of wisdom which would accompany the millennium (as prophesied in Daniel 12, 4).4 Even Bacon, so often hailed as one of the most important pioneers of modern science, appears to have believed that scientific discovery could help repair the damage done by the Fall of Adam: For man by the fall fell at the same time from his state of innocency and dominion over creation. Both of these losses however can even in this life be in some part repaired; the former by religion and faith, the latter by arts and sciences. [p.387] Columbus, likewise, while his search for a new trade route to Asia was clearly motivated in part by pragmatic commercial considerations, claimed that the real purpose of the enterprise was to raise funds for the liberation of Jerusalem,5 and even appears to have seriously believed he had discovered the location of the earthly paradise in the course of his voyages.6 Viewed in the light of such grandiose visions of humanity bringingor restoringharmony to the world through its own efforts, Mores Utopia might be seen, in fact, as characterized by a certain modesty, inasmuch as it proposes a harmony which is primarily merely social in character. Later writers, however, such as Campanella and Bacon, clearly had more ambitious designs in mind: designs in which social harmony would be integrated into a larger cosmic patternyet even then, a pattern which human enterprise might well be able to influence. Against such a background, the ambiguity which has been pointed to as a central characteristic of utopian fiction seems less surprising. Emerging from a context where the possibility of religious, scientific, and social transformation seemed increasingly real, but where the direction it might take was less than clear, any attempt to envisage a complete alternative society could scarcely avoid some degree of ambiguity. In the case of Utopia, however, the ambivalence is compounded by the complex and sometimes contradictory character of the author himselfwhich is also reflected in both the nature, and the presentation of the alternative society he proposes. As might be expected of a writer who has been both canonized by the

THE UTOPIAN DREAM OF ORDER

37

Roman Catholic church and hailed by Nikita Khruschev as an honoured precursor of Soviet Communism (Gilison, p.24), his vision of an ideal commonwealth is one which, even by utopian standards, is particularly ambiguous in its implications The element of paradox in Utopia has, of course, frequently been commented on. It is the work of a devout Christian, yet one which portrays a non-Christian society as being in most respects far superior to those of Christian Europe. It proposes as desirable a degree of religious toleration unusual for its time, yet comes from the pen of a man who, in his public capacity, soon proved a fierce and intolerant persecutor of heretics. In the first book, there is a debate concerning the utility of the wise man involving himself in government, in which Hythloday argues forcibly that it is impossible to do so without sacrificing ones principles; yet while, in the book, Hythloday gets much the better of the argument, More himself went on to enter the public serviceand later to die over his refusal to compromise over a question of principle. Nor do the paradoxes end there, for while the issues the work raises could scarcely be more serious (in the last instance, quite literally involving matters of life and death), Utopia is at the same time disconcertingly full of elementspuns, wordplay, ironiessuggestive of an intent which is anything but serious. Mores often ludicrous choice of names for people and places, together with some of his comments, both in the work itself, and in subsequent correspondence, seem explicitly designed to undercut the impact of the radical ideas it containsas, for example, when Hythlodays lengthy description of Utopian society is immediately followed by the narrators caveat: it seemed to me that not a few of the customs and laws he had described as existing among the Utopians were quite absurd. Their methods of waging war, their religious ceremonies, and their social customs were some of these, but my chief objection was to the basis of their whole system, that is, their communal living and their moneyless economy. [p.91] What is quite absurd, in other words, is the entire society! Not all of Mores readers, of course, can be said to have got the joke least of all, perhaps, the modern critic who seriously argued that Utopia was in fact an actual description of the society of the Incas.7 But such spectacular misinterpretations only serve to underline the extent to which the boundaries between fiction and nonfiction become blurred in utopian narrative. While More was clearly concerned to avoid such misunderstandings, deliberately writing in Latin for a select group of friends and acquaintances, all of whom could confidently be expected to recognize the scholarly humour, and enjoy the speculative freedom of its often radical

38

NARRATING UTOPIA

suggestions without mistaking them for a practical programme of action, perhaps the greatest paradox of all is that such a work, although designed for a limited audience, should have gone on to achieve a degree of recognition and influence far beyond anything its author could have intendedor indeed, desired. The Narrative of Utopia Written at the dawn of an age of exploration, Utopia takes as its starting point the Voyages of Amerigo Vespucci: purportedly factual accounts (although ones, interestingly enough, whose authenticity has often been disputed).8 Raphael Hythloday, the visitor to Utopia, is supposed to have accompanied Vespucci on his alleged fourth voyage, and to have been one of those left behind in a fort on the coast of Brazilfrom which he then set out to engage in further exploration. Hythlodays account of his travels is presented, in effect, as an extension of what More believed to have been a real voyage of discovery, its form modelled on that of travel narratives which lay claim to some degree of plausibility and authenticity. In form, then, Utopia takes as its model a narrative of travel and discoveryit is a fiction which begins by describing an actual voyage, and goes on to imagine a further one. Nevertheless, the details provided concerning the latter are curiously sparse. From their starting point on the coast of Brazil, we are told, Hythloday and five companions travelled through many countries At last, by strange good fortune, he got, via Ceylon, to Calcutta, where by good luck he found some Portuguese ships; and so, beyond anyones expectation, he returned to his own country (p.7). Where the regular travel narrative (and Vespuccis is no exception) is customarily full of concrete details concerning distances travelled, and the time taken to cover them, Utopia is conspicuously vague in its treatment of both time and space. As Robert Adams remarks, in a footnote to the passage cited above: More covers in a prepositional phrase the distance from Eastern Brazil to Ceylon, a distance of about fifteen thousand miles. Somewhere in there is Utopia (p.7 n.).9 Yet while this is tantalizingly imprecise, the text does provide us elsewhere with some oddly suggestive details. Utopia is located, as are the ideal commonwealths of Campanella and Bacon, in the southern hemisphere, to speak in literal geographical terms but also in the south land, that quasi-mythical locale which was the half serious goal even of real-life explorers of the New World: both Columbus, as we have seen, and later Ponce de Leon had dreams of locating, not just the Indies, but the Earthly Paradise itself.10 Remote from, and also (as it would be visually represented) below the known world, Utopia is only

THE UTOPIAN DREAM OF ORDER

39

reached after an arduous journey through an equatorial region described as desolate and squalid, grim and uncultivated, inhabited by wild beasts, serpents, and also by men no less wild and dangerous than the beasts themselves (Utopia, p.8). Beyond this region, however, the conditions grow milder: The heat was less fierce, the earth greener, men and even beasts less savage (p.8). There are increasing signs of civilization: ships, primitive at first, but later just as sophisticated as those of Europe. Hythloday and his companions encounter towns and cities commonwealths that were both populous and not badly governed (p.7). Nearer still to Utopia are nationsthe Achorians and Macarianswhose societies, while not perfect, are both cited as examples from which European civilization might well profit. Finally, there is Utopia itself: remote from the known world, separated by an almost impassable barrier, yet at the same time able to diffuse its influence over a wide area. The closer the approach to the ideal, the more its influence (in the best Platonic tradition) becomes apparent, affecting not only humanity, but even natureeven the beasts grow tamer. The precise location of Utopia, however, is never revealed. As its name suggests, it is both (enticingly) the good place and (infuriatingly) no place: desirable, yet unattainable. Its location is the one piece of information conspicuously absent from an account which Hythlodays listeners beg him to make as thorough and exhaustive as possible: Do not try to be brief, but explain in order everything relating to their land, their rivers, towns, people, manors, institutions, laws everything, in short, that you think we would like to know. And you can take it for granted that we want to know everything that we dont know yet. [p.33] Yet while Hythloday does respond, in Book Two, with a comprehensive account of utopian society, this very comprehensiveness serves, paradoxically, to highlight the narratives omissionsto draw attention, as Macherey puts it, to what [the work] does not say (p.87). Given his audiences expressed desire to know everything (a desire, moreover, which Hythloday agrees to satisfy), the omission of the elementary fact of Utopias whereabouts seems all the more glaring. Indeed, in a subsequent letter to Peter Giles, More even makes joking reference to this: it didnt occur to us to ask, nor to him to say, in what area of the New World Utopia is to be found. I wouldnt have missed hearing about this for a sizable sum of money, for Im quite ashamed not to know even the name of the ocean where this island lies about which Ive written so much. [p.111]11

40

NARRATING UTOPIA

Giles, in his turn, takes up the running joke in a subsequent letter to Jerome Busleyden: Raphael did not try in any way to suppress that information, but he mentioned it only briefly and in passing, as if saving it for another occasion. And then an unlucky accident caused both of us to miss what he said. For while Raphael was speaking of it, one of Mores servants came in to whisper something in his ear; and though I was listening, for that very reason, more intently than ever, one of the company, who I suppose had caught cold on shipboard, coughed so loudly that some of Raphaels words escaped me. [p.114] Humour, obviously, can have a wide range of functionsbut there is surely something suggestive about this kind of humour, which depends for its effect on a tantalizing refusal to reveal information, both drawing attention to, yet refusing to disclose a secret. The commonest use of such humour, of course, is in the service of sexual innuendo, where a pose of innocence is combined with the implication of knowingness to create a complicity between speaker and audience: at the literal level, the statement can be taken at its (innocent) face value, yet both speaker and audience understand its true significanceto which, however, neither can allude overtly without the risk of disturbing the delicate balance on which the humour of dealing with the taboo depends. This is not to say, of course, that the humour which More and his circle deploy is identical in character: Utopia is scarcely a work of sexual innuendo; nevertheless, there would seem to be at least some element of the taboo involved in its humour. Utopia can be thought about, but is physically unattainable; the pretence of its existence is sustained by a knowing complicity between author and audience; and the secrecy surrounding it is maintained by barrier of an essentially defensive humourthe kind designed to forestall awkward questions. What, then, is there about Utopia that might involve an element of the taboo, representing unconscious or unavowable desires? Eric Rabkin suggests that part of the appeal of utopian fiction lies in its indulgence of our atavistic desire for a special kind of orderliness, the simple, calm orderliness found in childhood, a bliss ignorant of sex and ignorant of the full knowledge of personal autonomy (Rabkin, 1983, p.10). Yet while this gives some sense of the regressive element inherent in much utopian fantasy, a mere yearning for the simplicity of childhood is hardly sufficient to account for the degree of evasiveness encountered here. More to the point, surely, is the frequently drawn parallel between the actual geography of Utopia and the womb. Formerly a peninsula, we are told, Utopia was transformed into an island at the behest of King Utopus, whose

THE UTOPIAN DREAM OF ORDER

41

first act on coming to power was to sever the link with the mainland by decreeing the excavation of a fifteen-mile-wide channel. By doing so, in Angelika Bammers view, King Utopus symbolically births his own utopia by cutting off the umbilical cord that had joined it to the mainland (p.14). Yet this is surely to miss the point, since what is suggested by the geographical details that More does supply is not so much the birth process, as a return to the womb. What King Utopuss prodigious feat of engineering in fact accomplishes is the creation of an island shaped like a crescent whose horns nearly meet, enclosing a large, placid bay, which can only be entered (and even then with difficulty) by way of a narrow channel: What with shallows on one side, and rocks on the other, the entrance into the bay is very dangerous. Near the middle of the channel, there is one rock that rises above the water, and so presents no dangers in itself; on top of it a tower has been built, and there a garrison is kept. Since the other rocks lie under water, they are very dangerous to navigation. The channels are known only to the Utopians, so hardly any strangers enter the bay without one of their pilots [p.34] If Mores evasiveness concerning Utopias actual location may be seen as suggestive, then the compensatory wealth of physical detail provided in the description of its appearance is still more soparticularly when taken in conjunction with his account of the nature of Utopian society. The analogy between human visions of an ideal world and the mothers womb is by no means a new one: long before Freudindeed, as early as the first century ADthe Gnostic heretic, Simon Magus, proposed that the Garden of Eden had no literal, physical existence, but was merely an allegory of the womb, where the individual was innocent, happy, idle, and plentifully supplied with food.12 And this same ideal persists through any number of fantasized paradises, from Eden, the land of Cockaigne (where geese fly ready-roasted through the air, crying Geese, al hot, al hot!), down to contemporary television advertisements for Caribbean holidays. As Frank and Fritzie Manuel suggest: The human fetus is an island, and in their island utopias men have often expressed a longing for the protective fluid that once surrounded them. The maternal symbols of most Elysian, goldenage, and paradisaical utopias are compelling and need not be laboured. The enclosed gardens, islands, valleys have reappeared with constancy through the ages. There is free feeding, security, peace, plenitude, and no rivalry. [p.76] While it may fairly be objected that the ideal commonwealth depicted

42

NARRATING UTOPIA

in Utopia is neither Elysian, paradisaical, nor golden-age, it nevertheless shares many of their distinctive features. Where Utopia differs is not so much in the character of the dream it represents, as in the fact that it seeks to put that dream on a more rational, plausible footing. If food is not free, there is at any rate a sufficiency: their working hours are ample to provide not only enough but more than enough of the necessities and even the conveniences of life (p.42). And while work is still necessary, to the average Tudor artisan or agricultural labourer, the Utopian six-hour day would surely have seemed, if not paradisaical, then the next best thing to it. There is peace, maintained by the ruthless efficiency with which the otherwise pacific Utopians wage war on aggressors. And there is security, provided by an ordered social hierarchy, clearly defined laws and customs, and the strict routine that governs day-to-day living. It is, as has often been remarked, a highly institutionalized society, and one strongly influenced by the ideals of monasticismyet it also goes a long way toward providing, albeit in a more temperate fashion, many of the essential features of the fantasized paradise. Paradise, however, like the womb, offers something more: a freedom from guilt, the promiseor is it the memory?of an innocence lost by the Fall. And here, at least at first sight, Utopia might seem to diverge from the pattern of the paradisaical fantasy. For there is evil in Utopia: its citizens have to be controllededucated to do right, restrained from doing wrong. The effects of Original Sin are only mitigated, not abolished by its institutions, and while the legal system seems in most respects milder and more civilized than that of Tudor England, some of its provisions are, to say the least, Draconianwitness the Utopian penalty of death for a second conviction of adultery. Yet even here there is evidence that Utopia represents a rationalized version of the underlying Edenic dream. While guilt cannot be eradicated altogetherany more than can hunger, the need to work, or the possibility of warit can, like them, be minimized. Utopian religion, unlike Christianity, lays little stress on humanitys fallen nature; the legal system places, at least by the standards of the time, less emphasis on punishment, more on rehabilitation; and there are, quite simply, far fewer opportunities to do anything one might feel guilty about. The absence of money and private property frees the Utopians from greed and covetousness, and there are few chances of indulging in any of the usual social vices: there is no chance to loaf or kill time, nor pretext for evading work; no taverns, or alehouses, or brothels; no chances for corruption; no hiding places; no spots for secret meetings. But because they live in the full view of all, they are bound to be either

THE UTOPIAN DREAM OF ORDER

43

working at their usual trades, or enjoying their leisure in a respectable way. [p.49] As Utopias provisions concerning adultery would seem to indicate, human sexual instincts remain a problemyet even here every attempt is made to strip sexuality of its mystery and aura of forbidden delight. The notorious provision of opportunities for potential marital partners to view one another naked before finalizing their vows may be seen as a step (however nave) in this direction. But the Utopian obsession with living life entirely in the open clearly has another function: in a world where everything is known, the causes of fear and anxiety are minimized. Indeed, while Utopia depicts a world radically different from that of its author, one of its most striking aspects is the extent to which the element of novelty is downplayed. Not only are there few opportunities to do anything wrong, there are scarcely any opportunities to do anything new. While travel is permitted within Utopia (although only with an official license: the penalty for unlicenced travel is enslavement for a second offence!), there seems little point in it, given that all their cities are exactly alike (p.36). In Hythlodays words, they are identical in language, customs, institutions, and laws. So far as the location permits, all of them are built on the same plan, and have the same appearance (p.35). Everything in Utopia is familiar; everything in Utopia makes sense: there are no surprises. While there are elements of the carnivalesque inversion of customary values which Bakhtin sees as a central element in the Renaissance utopia13 (the use of gold for chamberpots and convicts chains; the mockery of the Anemolian ambassadors, while their servants are treated with respect), these remain subordinate, in Mores scheme of things, to the emphasis on official hierarchical order. What Utopia offers its citizens, above all, is security. Albeit in a rational form, it might be argued, Utopian society offers many of the same attractions as does the fantasized paradise: so far as is humanly possible, the Utopians attempt to rectify the negative consequences of birth, of belonging to a human society, rather than dwelling in the Garden of Eden. The risk of such an interpretation, of course, as with all attempts to psychologize desires for, or attempts to imagine social reform, is that of reductionism: the desire for the radically new is all too readily decoded as mere nostalgia. Nevertheless, to argue that there are powerful, and in many respects regressive unconscious drives underlying the utopian vision is not necessarily to reduce it to a compensatory fantasy of returning to the past, in the face of ones inability to deal with the present. As Bloch suggests, an acceptance of the existence of such drives does not imply automatic acceptance of the Freudian goal of securing the individuals adjustment to

44

NARRATING UTOPIA

the norms of society (which are themselves historically contingent)still less commit one to a Jungian pursuit of primeval archetypes. To suggest that humans are profoundly influenced at an unconscious level by the experience of prenatal security, or by the trauma of birth is not necessarily to argue that such experience is not subsequently socially mediated.14 In addition, even granted that utopian visions have at their roots a regressive fantasy, this does not necessarily render them reactionary per se. Whatever the roots of the desire for a better world, the real issue is the use made of that desire. Indeed, history is full of examples of the past, however fantasized or mythical, being used to legitimate radical political action in the present: witness, for example, Gerrard Winstanleys utopian appeal to the historically quite unfounded, but nevertheless enabling vision of a formerly egalitarian English society that had fallen from grace as the result of the imposition of the Norman Yoke. As Miguel de Unamuno argues: [e]veryone who fights for any ideal whatever, although his ideal may seem to lie in the past, is driving the world on to the future (p.321). Utopian fantasy to the extent that it is merely compensatory, may be reactionary in tendency; to the extent that it uses the gap between the joys of even a mythologised past and the inadequacies of the present as a starting point for the imagining of new alternatives, it contains radical potential. However, this is not to say that the underlying presence of such regressive elements is entirely unproblematic, eitheras becomes apparent when one examines some of the parallels with the discovery narratives on which Utopia is partly modelled. As numerous commentators have pointed out, a striking feature of such narratives is the consistency with which the territory of desire is also conceived of as female.15 For Columbus, as we have seen, the enterprise of discovery was inextricably bound up with fantasies of regaining the paradise of which utopia offers a rationalized version. In his account of his third voyage, indeed, he advanced the singular theory that the earth, far from being spherical, was in fact pear-shaped, or else like a round ball on which there was a protuberance resembling a womans nipple (Jane, Vol. 2, pp.301). This theory, in addition to accounting for apparent anomalies in his observations of the pole star, which he regarded as proof that he was sailing uphill (pp.301), led him to believe that he had actually located the earthly paradise situated on top of the nipple-like summit of the world, somewhere upriver from the mouth of the Orinoco (which he took to be one of the life-giving streams issuing from paradise itself). Paradoxically, however, it was this dream, along with the no less regressive fantasy of recapturing Jerusalem formerly held to be the geographical centre of the worldthat informed Columbuss discovery of an altogether new world. Nevertheless, as Annette

THE UTOPIAN DREAM OF ORDER

45

Kolodny points out, the recurrent gendering of the land as female in narratives of discovery has a range of implications: Implicit in the metaphor of the land-as-woman was both the regressive pull of maternal containment and the seductive invitation to sexual assertion: if the Mother demands passivity, and threatens regression, the Virgin apparently invites sexual assertion and awaits impregnation. [p.67] While Columbus sees the newly discovered territories as the site of a paradise conceived of in maternal terms, a very different relationship with the land is implied by Sir Walter Raleghs celebrated claim that Guiana is a countrey that hath yet her maydenhead (p.347)not to mention the contention of his lieutenant, Laurence Keymis, that whole shires of fruitfull grounds, lying now waste for want of people, do prostitute themselves unto us, like a faire and beautifull woman, in the pride and floure of desired yeeres (p.391).16 Along with what Marcuse describes as the fantasy of the land as woman, the total female principle of gratificationenclosing the individual in an environment of receptivity, repose, and painless and integral satisfaction (Eros and Civilization, pp.2467)17 often goes the desire to assert masculine dominance over that domain. While the project of exploration, although informed in part by regressive fantasies, makes possible the discovery of the genuinely new, it also opens the way for the exercise of traditional modes of domination. Seen in this light, the parallels between Utopia and the discovery narratives to which it owes part of its inspiration become more, rather than less troubling. For while the underlying symbolism of Utopiaits shape and location, its peace, fertility, and securitymay well be maternal in character, indicative of deep-seated and barely acknowledged subconscious yearnings, it is, as Bammer points out, not a world in which women are empowered. On the contrary, male hegemony is reinscribed as normative (p.14). For all the maternal attributes of the underlying utopian dream, the social superstructure erected on these foundations is, by contrast, distinctively patriarchal. This, of course, it might be argued, is hardly surprising: Tudor society, after, was likewise highly patriarchaland to this extent More might be seen as simply reflecting the social realities of his own era. Yet while this is certainly true, it leaves a number of questions unanswered. If Mores own society was patriarchal, it was also a society in which a money economy, the institution of private property, and Christian belief were equally fundamental. Given the extremely radical social transformation which Utopia proposes, it is surely not without significance that there are aspects of the authors own society which he chooses to leave unchanged.

46

NARRATING UTOPIA

Indeed, it might be argued that More (and he is not alone in this: the same might be said of Campanella and Bacon) does not simply reflect the realities of his own world when he envisages utopian society as patriarchal; rather, this is an element which he chooses to reinforce. Utopia is a society in which patriarchy is, one might say, raised to a higher power.18 In discussions of Utopian society, much attention has been given to the political organization of its upper echelonsits hierarchy of syphogrants, tranibors, and so forth. Yet this often serves to obscure (as do the frequent references to the influence on More of mediaeval monasticism) the fact that, as J.H. Hexter observes, the fundamental organizational unit of Utopian society is the patriarchal family (pp.405). The family provides the basic unit of agricultural production; it is the family heads who elect the syphogrants who constitute the lowest tier of government; and it is the family which instils into Utopian citizens the habit of obedience to authority on which the stability of society as a whole depends. Husbands chastise their wives, we are told, and parents their children, unless the offense is so serious that public punishment seems to be in the public interest (p.67). In addition, we learn that: Each city consists of households, the households consisting generally of blood-relations. When the women grow up and are married, they move into their husbands households. On the other hand, male children and after them grandchildren remain in the family, and are subject to the oldest parent, unless his [sic] mind has started to fail, in which case, the next oldest takes his place Wives are subject to their husbands, children to their parents, and generally the younger to the elders. [pp.445] In themselves, such provisions are not far removed from the realities of family life in Tudor Englandalthough the monthly ritual where wives kneel before their husbands to confess their various failures and negligences, and beg forgiveness for their offenses (p.86) is surely less than typical. Nevertheless, there is a difference. What is striking is that Utopia makes explicit aspects of social organization that would more commonly be taken for granted: the patriarchal family, in other words, is represented as being just as fundamental to the workings of Utopian society as any of the sweeping changes that are evident; its maintenance is as crucial as the abolition of money and private property, or as the radically different laws, customs, and rituals which are described in such detail. In Utopia, as in any portrait of a more perfect society, it is not merely what changes that is important: equally significant is what remains the same. And it is here that we encounter one of the essential contradictions inherent in the traditional utopia: the fact that, although suffused by a yearning for the security of

THE UTOPIAN DREAM OF ORDER

47

the maternal womb, it sets out to achieve that security by the imposition of a distinctively masculine order. This is manifested not only in the forms of social organization which utopian narrative depicts, but also at the deeper level of symbol: in the description of Utopias geography already cited, for example, one may see the erasure of the feminine by the masculine enacted in such telling details as the superimposition of the potently phallic tower full of armed men upon the harmless clitoral rock which rises in the entrance to Utopias womb-like bay. Equally, in the decisive act of authority with which the male King Utopus establishes Utopia, severing it from the mainland, one may see a further rewriting of the primal myth. While, as we have seen, some critics view this action as analogous to the severing of the umbilical cord, its implications are actually more ambiguous. Where the cord linking mother and child is severed after the birth process, here the analogous action is a prelude to the wombs creation: the direction of time, in effect, is reversed, as if the hidden intent of the utopian fantasy were to reach back beyond the birth process, beyond the fall into independent conscious life, and start over againonly with the male firmly in control. If the earthly paradise constitutes an allegory of the womb, the utopian dreamat least as first formulatedis rather one of recreating its security by distinctively male means. The articulation of such a dream at this particular point in time, of course, can hardly be seen as purely coincidental. The ambiguity of direction evident in the utopian dream is scarcely an isolated phenomenon: even the process of discovery which revealed the existence of the New World was, as we have seen, similarly informed by dreams of the recovery of a lost paradise. And the utopian vision, which seeks to recover a lost harmony by the creation of a new order, may likewise be seen as looking both forward and backward at the same time. Yet the parallels do not end there. If, in geographical terms, the process of discovery (the disclosure of the new) was informed by a dream of recovery (the regaining of what had been lost), what followed was an entirely different project: that of colonization the superimposition of the existing upon the new. As Christina Thrmer-Rohr points out, while Bloch sees Columbus as exemplifying utopian desire in his search for a lost paradise he does not mention that such a quest for paradise always initiated male campaigns of conquest and domination. The paradises of western menand of their wives, mostly sent for laterare their colonies, large and small. Bloch describes them not as the sites of robbery, of oppression, of presumption, of rape and murder, but rather as geographic utopias, earthly paradises, since heavenly paradise had proved unattainable. [p.23]

48

NARRATING UTOPIA

Which in its turn poses the uncomfortable question as to how far one of the goals of the utopian dream is not also, in a sense, the colonization of terra incognita. In the case of Mores Utopia, of course, it might be argued that nothing could be further removed from the colonialist enterprise than his depiction of an indigenous (albeit hypothetical) New World civilization as in almost every respect superior to that of Europe. In representing such a society as a model, not merely of wisdom and good government, but of tolerance, evenor rather, especiallyin matters of religion, More would appear to evince an outlook radically at odds with that informing the process of conquest and colonization with which discovery soon becomes inextricably linked, whereby the indigene is commonly demonized as prelude either to forcible conversion or extermination. As has already been suggested, such apparent openness to the example of other societies would seem to indicate a degree of cultural relativism unusual for the time. Nevertheless, as Stephen Greenblatt argues, such essentially theoretical tolerance is ultimately a meaningless abstraction: the customs of those at a vast distance in space or time or of imaginary beings may be admired or despised, but such responses are independent of tolerance. They are, in effect, the attitudinal equivalent of the act of categorizing: one may decide that other peoples scarcely merit the name of human beings or that they are models of virtue. In neither case do significant life choices, entailing political decisions with historical consequences, have to be made. A metaphoric embrace of the other is no doubt wonderful, but what is its exigency in the real world? What is to keep it from vanishing into thin air? [pp.456] Indeed, the gap between the degree of religious toleration proposed in Mores utopian vision and his own practice as a fierce and intolerant persecutor of heretics would seem to bear this out. Yet while the perceived contradiction between Mores actions and the apparent implications of the text has attracted voluminous critical comment, of perhaps greater relevance to the present discussion is another, somewhat less obvious contradiction. As has already been observed, Utopia (in common with the overwhelming majority of subsequent utopian narratives) provides an abundance of specific detail concerning the actual workings of a more perfect society, yet remains tantalizingly vague concerning the processes whereby it came into being. What we are offered, however, is in essence a fiction of conquest. Formerly a nation of rude and uncouth inhabitants (p.35), the land of Abraxa is conquered by King Utopus, who, having

THE UTOPIAN DREAM OF ORDER

49

subdued the indigenous population, promptly puts his subjects to work excavating a fifteen-mile-wide channel through the isthmus formerly linking them to the mainland. Having renamed the resultant island after himself, he then proceeds to raise his subjects to such a high level of culture and humanity that they now excel in that regard almost every other people (p.35). Where King Utopus came from, however, and where he acquired his ideals of civic harmony are left as obscure as the actual geographic location of Utopia. In any event, what follows the establishment of the utopian state is a process strikingly similar to that of colonization. While the Utopians, we are told, never fight except in self-defence, or to help various of their neighbours to throw off the yoke of tyranny (p.69), one side-effect of their conspicuous virtue is that their neighbours have made a practice of asking for Utopians to rule over them (p.69).19 Utopian administrators are sent out, in consequence, to serve either one or five year terms, after which others are sent in their place (p.69)for all the world like colonial governors. What emerges, in effect, is less an imaginative response to the example of the other, than to the possibilities inherent in the space opened up by the voyages of discoverya space wherein the values of the Old World could be reconfigured. Where an indigenous population exists, its function is to be moulded in the image of a King Utopus; neighbouring races are portrayed either as enemies to be destroyed, or else as eager to be governed by the superior wisdom of the Utopians. Like the native Americans described by Peter Martyr as rased or vnpaynted tables apte to receaue what formes soo euer are fyrst drawne theron by the hande of the paynter (quoted in Greenblatt, p.95), the indigenous population serves effectively as tabula rasaa blank page on which the patterns of what Michel de Certeau characterizes as Western desire (p.xxv) can be inscribed. As coined by More, the term utopia is, as we have seen, deliberately ambiguous: both eu-topos, the good place, and ou-topos, no placean ideal impossible of attainment. Yet in the actual context of Mores narrative, it becomes something rather differentthe name imposed by a conquering king, remaking the world in his own image. The parallels with Columbus, renaming Guanahani San Salvador, or Ralegh, rechristening Wingandaco Virginia at the behest of Queen Elizabeth,20 are hard to escape. Utopias of the Later Renaissance That these are characteristics of utopian narrative in general, rather than merely features peculiar to Mores Utopia, becomes apparent when one turns to the work of his successors. Published just over a century later, neither Campanellas The City of the Sun nor Bacons The New Atlantis exhibit

50

NARRATING UTOPIA

the narrative complexity or, indeed, possess the narrative fascination of their predecessor: Campanellas work, written in prison, shows signs of having been composed in haste, ending abruptly with its narrator breaking off his account as he rushes to catch his ship; while Bacons is no more than a fragment,21 which leaves many features of his utopian society unclear. Yet while the complex interaction between reality and imagined alternative which emerges from the juxtaposition of Hythlodays narration with the dialogue which prefaces it is lacking, both The City of the Sun and The New Atlantis share much of Utopias pervasive ambiguity. At the same time, however, perhaps by virtue of their greater narrative straightforwardness, they serve to give focus and emphasis to certain elements which the complex ironies of Mores fiction tend to obscure. Campanella, The City of the Sun Campanella, especially, shares with More an ideological ambiguity which is likewise reflected in the conflicting responses of his readers. Although at times an advocate of papal supremacy, not only in religious, but also secular matters, Campanella has also been conscripted, along with More, into the Communist pantheon of honoured precursors of socialism22 and, as in Mores case, there has been no lack of critics anxious to defend him from so terrible a slur. Bernardino Bonansea argues that, like More, Campanella was simply attempting to portray in his ideal society the virtue possible to natural manto show the best that could be achieved by reason alonewhich should in no way detract from his being seen as a good Catholic (p.265). Nevertheless, to present Campanella in this light is problematic, to say the least. Unlike More, who died a martyr for the Catholic faith, Campanella was very nearly martyred by the Catholic church, spending over thirty years in the prisons of the Inquisition, undergoing torture on several occasions, and only avoiding execution by feigning insanity. His thinking is described by D.P. Walker as drenched in hermetic ideas (p.234), and while he did, in the later years of his life, find favour with the papacy, this in itself can scarcely be taken as evidence of Catholic orthodoxy, given that one of his chief services to the Holy See was to perform ceremonies of astral magic with Pope Urban VIII in order to protect him from the ill-effects of an eclipse.23 Clearly Campanella presents almost as many problems to the Catholic apologist as he does to the socialist in search of forerunners of Marx. One important respect in which Campanella does differ from More, however, is in his introduction of what is to become an increasingly central preoccupation in utopian fiction: scientific and technological discoveries become for the first time integral to the creation of a more perfect society.

THE UTOPIAN DREAM OF ORDER

51

Like the inhabitants of Bacons Bensalem, Campanellas Solarians have made extraordinary advances in the fields of medicine and astronomy, and have even discovered the art of flying. Prescient though this may seem, however, the actual role of such discoveries is once again by no means unambiguously forward looking. The Solarians expertise in astronomy, for example, is used primarily in the service of the practice of astrology, which in turn plays a large role both in Solarian medicine andas will be seeneugenics. While clearly important, science remains subordinate, in Campanellas scheme of things, to religion and astral magic. Thus the progressive elements in The City of the Sun remain part of a larger order which is anything but modern. As with Utopia, the orientation of Campanellas ideal commonwealth remains ambiguous, seeming to look both forwards and backwards simultaneously. No such ambiguity, however, surrounds the question of Campanellas intent. Whereas More seemed concerned to ensure that his often radical speculations were seen as just thatspeculations, rather than proposals to be acted uponin Campanellas case there can be little doubt that The City of the Sun expressed what he saw as an ideal toward which practical progress could be made. If Mores vision of a better society may be compared to the contemporary theory of Copernicus, insofar as both remained at the relatively unalarming level of hypothesis, Campanella may be seen as comparable to his contemporary, Galileo, in his activation of the hypothesis radical implications. Thus, while the composition of Utopia in Latin was designed to restrict it to an audience sufficiently educated (and ideologically reliable) to take its speculations in the sense they were meant (More was unwilling to have it translated into English), Campanella translated his work from the vernacular into Latin precisely because his admirers felt this would secure it a wider audience. While The City of the Sun depicts what may now seem an unrealizable ideal, it is one whose premises are wholly consistent with the political activism which got its author into trouble with the Inquisition in the first place. If there are doubts as to the direction in which Campanella wanted society to move, he clearly had no problems with the subversive implications of utopian speculation. As his actions testify, he was only too eager to offer a challenge to established authority. Perhaps for this reason, we find none of the irony, the wordplay, the somewhat defensive humour with which More seeks to undercut the radical implications of his narrative. Nor, indeed, is there any of the rather coy mystification surrounding the location of the more perfect society which is not to say, however, that Campanella is much more informative. In response to an initial question from a Knight Hospitaller, Campanellas Genoese mariner responds:

52

NARRATING UTOPIA

I have already told you how I sailed around the world and came to Taprobana, where I was forced to put ashore, how I hid in a forest to escape the fury of the natives, and how I came out onto a great plain just below the equator. [p.27] Which is all we learn about how utopia is reached: the narrator has already gone into the details, and does not propose to discuss the matter further. Within less than half a page, he is embarked instead on a detailed description of the city itself. What Campanella provides, in other words, is another form of evasion: while elsewhere the mariner is only too happy to respond to the knights eager inquiries (Tell me more, I beg you, tell me more (p.29)) with detailed and explicit accounts of the most minute aspects of Solarian life, his reticence herehis uncharacteristic brevity is all the more striking. Nor are we told much more concerning the origins of Campanellas utopia: all we learn of its foundation is that its inhabitants are a people from India, many of them being philosophers, who fled before the depredations of the Tartars and other plunderers and tyrants, and they resolved to live in a philosophic community (pp.379). Yet, scanty though these details are, one significant parallel between the process of creating a utopian society and that of reaching it does emerge. Both processes take place after exposure to the unbridled hostile impulses of man in his natural state: the Solarians flee from the savage Tartars and other plunderers, while the mariner hides from the fury of the natives. Both find refuge within the circular walls of the City of the Sun: as is the case with Utopia, one of its most essential features is the security it provides. What follows is the depiction of an order whose comprehensiveness surpasses even that of More. Campanella himself was obsessed by order and correspondence (he even believed that seven bumps on his head corresponded to the seven planets), and this passion is reflected in almost every aspect of his imagined society. The city, we learn, is built in a series of concentric circles, seven in number, each named after one of the seven planets, and each girdled by a formidable wall. Since it is built on a hill, each circle is higher than the one which encloses it, and at the summit, within the innermost circle, stands the vast temple of the Sun. This design serves a number of purposes, the most obvious being that of defence: It is constructed in such a way that if the first circuit were taken by assault, more effort would be required to take the second, likewise again the third, and so forth, so that seven assaults would be need to conquer it all. But in my opinion not even the first assault would be successful, so thick is the wall [pp.279] Like Utopia, the City of the Sun is impregnable. Yet this is only one function of its design: as well as protection, the walls also provide educationtheir

THE UTOPIAN DREAM OF ORDER

53

surfaces, apart from those of the outermost, are adorned with paintings illustrating every aspect of knowledge. The City, in fact, forms a kind of encyclopaedia: on the outer walls of the temple are depicted the stars in order; on the inner wall of the first circuit all the mathematical figures; and so outward to the exterior of the sixth circuit, on which appear pictures of great menfounders of laws and of sciences and inventors of weapons (p.37). Living in such an environment, Solarian children without effort, merely while playing come to know all the sciences pictorially before they [are] ten years old (p.37). Most important of all, however, the symmetry and harmony of the citys design is clearly intended to reflect the broader harmony of the universe. With its seven circuits, named after the planets, centred on the Temple of the Sun, the city itself constitutes a microcosm; while within the temple the process repeats itself on a smaller scale, with the stars depicted on the vault of its dome and seven lamps burning to represent the planets. The purpose of Solarian architecture, in other words, is not only defensive and educational, but also religious. Given this preoccupation with celestial design, it comes as little surprise to discover that Solarian religion is inextricably bound up with astrology. Their Priest-Ruler, called interchangeably either Sun or Metaphysic, is invariably a man of great learning, and heads a body of priests who, when not engaged in affairs of state, divide their time between prayer and astrology: Twenty-four priests are stationed high in the temple to sing certain psalms in praise of God in the morning and evening, at midnight and noon. Their task is to gaze at the stars and, using astrolabes, note all their movements and the effects these produce. In this manner, they learn what changes have taken place or are likely to take place in every country. They establish the hour in which conception should take place, the day on which sowing and harvesting should be done, and in general, serve as mediators between God and man. [p.103] Both prayer and astrology are presented as basically similar in purpose, merely constituting different aspects of the priestly taskwhich is to keep the human microcosm attuned to the harmonies of the universe. Even the citys political organization has a religious dimension: the chief officials, we learn, are all priests as welland it is clear from their preoccupation with astrology that the task of securing social harmony is, once again, merely part of the larger enterprise of integrating the human with the celestial order. By the institution of an elaborate system of social control, the Solarians seek to re-establish an unalienated union between the individual and the natural world which may be seen as echoing the organic

54

NARRATING UTOPIA

prenatal connection between mother and foetus, where the rhythms of the foetus are synchronous with those of its surrounding environment. It is an archetypal utopian dream. Nevertheless, just as in Mores Utopia, the emphasis of the social order which Campanella outlines remains resolutely masculine. This is to some extent prefigured in the citys actual design, its womb-like geography being overlaid by the exclusively male symbolism of the pictures that adorn the walls: in the outermost circle of illustrations, for example, the portraits of legislators, scientists, and inventors of weapons are supplemented by images of Moses, Osiris, Jupiter, Mercury, Muhammad Jesus Christ and the twelve Apostles Caesar, Alexander, Pyrrhus, and all the Romans (p.37). Yet in marked contrast to More, for whom the fundamental instrument of patriarchal authority is the family, Campanellas social order is constructed on radically different principles. In the City of the Sun, the family is quite simply abolishedon the grounds that its existence is detrimental to the individuals commitment to the community: They claim that property comes into existence when men have separate homes with their children and wives. From this self-love is born; for in order to increase the wealth or dignity of his offspring or leave him heir to his goods, every man becomes publicly rapacious if he is strong and fearless, or avaricious, deceitful, and hypocritical if he is weak. When self-love is destroyed, only concern for the community remains. [p.39] In this, Campanella is clearly influencedand to a far greater extent than Moreby the ideals of monasticism; yet at the same time he articulates, and in an extreme form, what is to become an increasingly prominent trend in utopian writing: the tendency to do away with all institutions that might mediate between the individual and the monolithic state. It is striking, in fact, how seldom utopias allow for the existence of intermediate groups or organizationsassociations, unions, guilds, clubs, political partiesthat have any degree of independence of the state. In abolishing the family as well, Campanella merely goes farther than most. But if the family in Mores Utopia is the chief mechanism for the maintenance of patriarchal authority, its absence in The City of the Sun by no means signifies that Campanellas emphasis is any less patriarchal. What does emerge, however, is a striking contradiction between the theory and practice of his utopian state. At first sight, it would appear that the quasimonastic social organization of the Solarians serves significantly to diminish sexual inequality: both sexes are trained in all pursuits (p.41), we are toldincluding warfarewhile later it is explicitly stated that men and women do the same work, whether of a mental or mechanical nature

THE UTOPIAN DREAM OF ORDER

55

(p.49). Yet while, by seventeenth century standards, this would seem to represent a revolutionary extension of womens freedom, once Campanella goes into more detail some telling gaps between theory and practice become apparent: all the priests and officials are male, to begin with; while the contention that men and women do the same work is subsequently qualified to the point of outright contradiction. One distinction is observed (p.49), we are told: that is that such tasks as involve hard work or a good deal of walking, like plowing, sowing, harvesting, sheep herding, are performed by the men. Threshing, grape gathering, cheese making, milking, tending to the kitchen gardens, and other light duties [servizi facili], on the other hand, are usually assigned to women. These include weaving, sewing, barbering, pharmacy, every kind of clothes making, but exclude the work of the blacksmith or the arms maker. If a woman has skill in painting she is not forbidden to pursue it. Music, except for the playing of trumpets and drums, is reserved to women and children, since they give the most pleasure by it. Women also prepare food and lay the tables [p.49] Compared to the society of Campanellas day, this still offers some modest extension of womens sphere of activities, but the one distinction referred to does rather more than simply modify the initial assertion. The radical promise of sexual equality proves to be merely an abstraction, translating in practical terms into what is tantamount to a reinscription of the existing order. Nor do the notorious sexual provisions of Campanellas utopia offer women much by way of liberation. Solarian women may not be obliged to confess their failings to their husbands on bended knee, but they are no less subject to the will of the State, in the eyes of which they appear to be little more than a sexual resource, to be disposed of as its officials see fit: No female ever submits to a male until she is nineteen years of age, nor does any male seek to have children until he is twenty-one or, if he is pale and delicate, even older. Before that age some of them are permitted to have intercourse with barren or pregnant women so as to avoid illicit usages. [p.53] Such women are provided by the matrons and seniors in charge of procreation, who first consult with a doctor as to the advisability of the proceeding. The provisions regarding procreational sex are even more specific: Since both males and females, in the manner of the ancient Greeks,

56

NARRATING UTOPIA

are completely naked when they engage in wrestling exercises, their teachers may readily distinguish those who are able to have intercourse from those who are not and can determine whose sexual organs may best be matched with whose. Consequently, every third night, after they have all bathed, the young people are paired off for intercourse. Tall handsome girls are not matched with any but tall brave men, while fat girls are matched with thin men and thin girls with fat ones, so as to avoid extremes in their offspring. On the appointed evening, the boys and girls prepare their beds and go to bed where the matron and senior direct them. Nor may they have intercourse until they have completely digested their food and have said their prayers They sleep in neighbouring cells until they are to have intercourse. At the proper time, the matron goes around and opens the cell doors. The exact time when this must be done is determined by the Astrologer and the Physician [p.55] It must be conceded that men do not appear to have much choice in the matter either, but elsewhere it becomes clear where the balance of power lies. While men are free to copulate with sterile or pregnant women (or ones of scant worth (p.57)), sterile women are barred from a range of privileges, to discourage any woman from making herself sterile in order to become a wanton (p.59). These customs Campanella refers to as community of women (p.65); Solarians, we are told, share their women with respect to both obedience and the bed (p.67). Women are just as subordinate to the male-dominated State in Campanellas utopia as they are to their husbands in Mores; their theoretical equality is repeatedly undercut by details revealing that underlying assumptions as to their inferiority remain unchanged. It may be tempting to write off the sexual provisions of The City of the Sun as merely the heated imaginings of a Dominican monk. Indeed, Thomas Hallidays frequently reprinted 1885 translation omits them altogether an expurgation which one editor rather airily refers to as one or two omissions of detail which can well be spared.24 Nevertheless, they may be seen as representing yet another attempt to restore human innocence by freeing sexuality from guiltin this case by employing astrological means to bring human instinctual drives into harmony with the divine order of the universe. At the same time, however, Campanellas emphasis on selective breeding as integral to the creation of a more perfect society introduces what is to become a recurrent theme in utopian fiction. In many later utopias, in particular those of Bellamy and Wells, the aim is to transform not merely the social institutions which govern humanity, but also the raw human material itself. If human unpredictability and imperfection prove an obstacle to the establishment of a rational, ordered

THE UTOPIAN DREAM OF ORDER

57

society, then the answer is very simple: humans themselves must be altered, usually by means of some form of eugenic control. It is a view which, as we shall see, has alarming implications. In the City of the Sun, however, the transformation of humanity is not yet complete; while Campanella is somewhat equivocal concerning the doctrine of the Fall, his Solarians are still sufficiently imperfect to need laws and legal penalties to deter them from wrongdoing. Like Mores, Campanellas legal provisions are, by the standards of the time, relatively humaneyet there are also (again as in Mores case) some odd exceptions. Indeed, in several places the account we are given of Solarian law is actually contradictory. Although we are told at first that theft, murder, rape, incest, adultery are unknown among them (p.41), we later learn that homicide is punishable by deathas are offences involving injury to the freedom of the public, or to God, or to the highest officials (p.99). We are, however, assured that only a person found guilty of one of these crimes is punished with death (p.99). So far, so enlightened, it would seemexcept that in the course of the discussion of sexuality two further capital offences emerge. Repeated sodomy, it appears, is also punishable by death, as is the wearing by women of cosmetics, high heels, or gowns that cover the heels! Even by the standards of the sumptuary laws of the period, this last is quite extraordinarily Draconianyet when the two offences are considered side by side, it becomes apparent that they do have something in common. Both might be seen as unnatural insofar as they involveat least to the innocent utopian eyean element of deception. A recurrent feature in utopias is their emphasis, not simply on order, but on an order that is absolutely clear, wholly explicable. Confusion and uncertainty threaten the very foundations of utopian order: hence perhaps the insistence that everything should be open, easily knowable, not liable to errors of interpretation. As we have seen, there is in utopian narrative a tendency to try to determine every detail, an unwillingness to leave anything to chance. In such a context, a woman wearing make-up, disguising her real appearance, or a sodomite, engaging in sexual conduct other than that conventionally expected of a real man, both require an effort of interpretation not normally expected of the utopian citizen. In a society where everything is transparent, they represent enigmas which require deciphering. Yet even so, the extremity of the penalty, the disparity between offence and punishment, particularly in the context of a legal code otherwise lenient by the standards of the time, prompts further questions. Just who, or what is so threatened by sodomy, or by a womans use of cosmetics? Whose interests are being safeguarded? The answer in both cases would seem to bemen. While in Campanellas day sodomy did not necessarily specifically imply homosexual conduct, the sodomite

58

NARRATING UTOPIA

represented at least a potential threat to a stable male sexual identity, in that sodomy could transform the recipient into a passive sexual victim. Likewise, a womans use of make-up, with its connotations of sexual display, could be seen as suggesting a degree of predatory sexual aggression again threatening to male sexual dominance. While normal male sexual drives are catered to by the provision of women so as to avoid illicit usages (p.53), conduct which threatens the norm is punishable by death. For all the radical character of Campanellas challenge to the sexual institutions of his day, the emphasis of his alternatives remains distinctively masculine. Nor is this all: as in Mores Utopia, the fantasy of masculine dominance extends beyond the boundaries of the utopian state itself. While, like More, Campanella is capable of imagining a more perfect society located somewhere other than in Europe, it is once again a social structure to be imposed on the indigenous inhabitants in their own interest. Indeed, it would appear from the Genoese mariners account of his first encounter with the natives of the region (from whose fury he has to flee), that Campanellas conception of the indigene owes much to the demonizing accounts of the inhabitants of the Americas found in so many discovery narrativesaccounts, of course, which are then used to legitimate the process of colonization, conversion, or even extermination. In the case of Campanellas utopia, however, there seems to be an inherent contradiction between the representation of the local inhabitants as savages, and what we are subsequently told concerning the City of the Suns relations with its neighbours. The Solarians, it turns out, are constantly at war (although once again, always in self-defence), and, due largely to their sophisticated military skills, invariably win. Conquered cities and their inhabitants, we are told immediately change over to the system of communal ownership of all goods. They receive Solarian officials and a garrison from the City of the Sun and proceed to model their institutions after those of that city, which is henceforth their guide. [p.77] Given this pattern of constant warfare, uninterrupted military success, and the subsequent imposition of the utopian system on conquered territory, it becomes hard to understand how there can be any furious natives left to escape from. One further contradiction remains to be explored. As has already been remarked, Campanella differs from More in his emphasis on the importance of scientific discovery as integral to the creation of a more perfect society. Besides discovering the art of flying, the Solarians have invented vessels that move without wind or oar (p.87), a device which allows them to listen to the music of the spheres, and a secret, marvellous

THE UTOPIAN DREAM OF ORDER

59

art by which they can renew their bodies painlessly every seven years (p.93), which, along with their healthy diet and habits, has led to an average lifespan of roughly a hundred and seventy.25 Marvellous as these may seem, however, it is clear that Campanella sees them as plausible possibilities, given the advances in knowledge the world of his own day had already seen. The Genoese mariner boasts that the previous hundred years has produced more history than the whole world did in the preceding four thousand (p.121),26 citing the invention of the compass, the printing press, and the arquebus. Yet such apparent enthusiasm for change and innovation is difficult to reconcile with the static ideal which the City of the Sun embodies. Indeed, it is hard to see how new knowledge and its implications can actually be incorporated into a structure already complete and perfect. While the startling inventions of the Solarians may be partly attributable to the excellence of their educational system without effort, merely while playing, their children come to know all the sciences pictorially before they are ten years old (p.37)its central feature, the illustration of all human knowledge on the city walls, has problematic implications. As Judah Bierman points out, there is no place for exploring new knowledge; in effect, knowledge is fully known, codified and exhibited (Science and Society, p.495). The City of the Sun is not just the title of a book: it is a book, written on stone, rather than paperand like a books, its contents are finite, fixed and immutable. To extend the city to make space for the depiction of new knowledge would be to violate the archaic principles of harmony and correspondence which are fundamental to its very existence. While the Genoese mariner acknowledges the dynamic principle of new discovery, which has produced more history in a hundred years than did the previous four thousand, the City of the Sun is an embodiment of the end of history: already perfect, its order is immune to change. If there is a dynamic element, it consists rather in the Solarians colonialist project of imposing that order on its neighbours. Bacon, The New Atlantis A similar tension is evident in Bacons The New Atlantis, where the dynamic implications of scientific discovery are again hard to reconcile with the static character of a society portrayed as already perfected.27 While the role of such discovery is still more important (the celebrated account of the wonders of Salomons House comprises roughly one third of the text), a marked ambivalence with regard to its function and direction is likewise evident. Ambivalence, indeed, has been seen by several commentators as an essential aspect of Bacons thinking. J.C. Davis, for example, describes him as:

60

NARRATING UTOPIA

[A] scientific modernist consigning all past philosophy to oblivion yet unable to shake off the mental habits of the scholastic, the jargon of the alchemist and magician; the analyst of the imperfections of the human mind, carefully planning the retrieval of its dominion over nature pessimistic and optimistic, conservative and radical, timid and bold [p.106] While science and scientific research are clearly crucial to Bacons vision of a utopian society, the traditional view of Bacon as perhaps the first truly modern scientist is somewhat misleading, ignoring as it does the complexity and ambiguity of Bacons thought. As Frances Yates observes: Bacons view of the future of science was not that of progress in a straight line. His great instauration of science was directed towards a return to the state of Adam before the Fall, a state of pure and sinless contact with nature and knowledge of her powers. [Rosicrucian, p.119] Thus, while The New Atlantis contains an extensive catalogue of scientific discoveries, they are presented in a context which is anything but suggestive of a modern scientific outlook. The scientists of the House of Salomon, like Campanellas Solarians, have developed the art of flying and the means of prolonging human lifeas well as inventing the submarine, a form of perpetual motion machine, and what sounds like a kind of telephone, which convey[s] sounds in trunks and pipes, in strange lines and distances (p.730). Yet, as in The City of the Sun, these startling innovations are hard to reconcile with some of the other details of the text. In describing the history of Bensalem, for instance, the governor of the Strangers House where the narrator and his companions are lodged indicates that Bensalem has done little more than preserve a level of civilization that was formally global, rather than progressing beyond it. With reference to navigation, for example, he declares: You shall understand (that which perhaps you will scarce think credible) that about three thousand years ago, or somewhat more, the navigation of the world, (especially for remote voyages), was greater than at this day. Do not think with yourselves that I know not how much it is increased with you within these six-score years: I know it well: and yet I say greater then than now [p.718] Given such a starting point, however, it seems curious that so little appears to have changed since. As Davis remarks, it is remarkable that the nineteen hundred years of uninterrupted research following the foundation of Salomons House should have produced so few technological innovations, or indeed so little social impact. Like the discoveries of the Solarians, the

THE UTOPIAN DREAM OF ORDER

61

research of Bacons scientists appears to have few practical applications; rather, the main goal of scientific research would seem to be the restoration of a harmonious union between humanity and nature, which will only be achieved when the latter is fully known. To further complicate the issue, The New Atlantis, for all its emphasis on science, is one of the few utopias in which the supernatural plays an essential role. While astrology and astral magic are integral to the workings of Campanellas ideal society, it is clear that these are seen as having a rational basis; whereas in Bacons case one of the fundamental characteristics of his societyits Christianityis portrayed as the product of a full-blown miracle. Given that neither the Catholic saint, More, nor the Dominican monk, Campanella, found it necessary to make Christianity the religion of their utopian societies, the fact that Bacon did is in itself not without interest28but what is particularly interesting is the nature of the narrative mechanism which he devises to account for it. In sheerly narrative terms, it must be said that the miracle is considerably in excess of requirements: indeed, if mere plausibility were the only consideration (and the desire for plausibility is surely at the root of the relentless specificity of details which characterizes so much utopian fiction, Bacons included) then the navigational prowess of the Bensalemites would surely have sufficed to account for their coming into contact with the revealed truths of the Christian religion. Bacon, however, resorts to a miraclewhat Bloch terms the blasting apart of the accustomed status quo (Principle of Hope, p.1304)and doing so he opens a space for a freer play of the imagination than the constraints of utopian fiction (which is designed to persuade its audience that a specific alternative is workable) normally afford. What he proceeds to imagine, given the limitless possibilities of the miraculous, is revealing. The miracle, we are told, coincided with Christs ascensionat which time there appeared off the coast of Bensalem an enormous pillar of light, not sharp, but in the form of a column or cylinder, rising from the sea a great way up towards heaven (p.716), the whole surmounted by a cross even brighter and more resplendent than the body of the pillar (p.716). What then follows is surely one of the oddest scenes in utopian literature. Numerous concerned citizens put to sea to investigate the apparition, but find themselves unable to get any closer than some sixty yards away. One boat, however, contains a scientist of the House of Salomon, who prostrates himself before the pillar, and then, raising himself to his knees, utters the following prayer: Lord God of heaven and earth, thou hast vouchsafed of thy grace to those of our order, to know thy works of creation, and the secrets of

62

NARRATING UTOPIA

them; and to discern (as far as appertaineth to the generations of men) between divine miracles, works of nature, works of art, and impostures and illusions of all sorts. I do here acknowledge and testify before this people, that the thing which we now see before our eyes is thy Finger and a true miracle [pp.71617] What is presented, in other words, is the spectacle of a trained scientist solemnly affirming a miracle to be miraculous. Having thus acknowledged the phallic pillars divine origin, the scientist is allowed to proceed past the invisible barrier, at which the pillar promptly explodes into a firmament of many stars (p.717), which then vanish, leaving behind only a small ark or chest of cedar, which opens to reveal what proves to be the seed of Christianity: all the canonical books of the Old and New Testament (p.717), even including the ones that had not yet been writtenwhich at the time of the ascension must have been rather a lot. All of which goes to explain why Bensalem, unlike Utopia or the City of the Sun, is a Christian community; extending the analogy between utopia and the womb, Bacons account depicts a process of impregnation by the word of God as the result of what reads remarkably like a symbolic representation of the male orgasm. In most other respects, for all its fragmentary character, The New Atlantis conforms to the pattern already evident in Utopia and The City of the Sun. Bensalem is likewise remote, southerly in location, and unknown to the rest of the worldan isolation decreed some nineteen hundred years before by King Solamona, in the belief that contact with the outside world could only harm a society that might be a thousand ways altered to the worse, but scarce any one way to the better (p.720). Lost, sick and starving, the narrator and his companions reach the coast of Bensalem, there to find many of the characteristic features of the womb-like paradisaical utopia. Entering a safe harbour, their initial attempt at landing is repulsed by the threatening presence of men waving batons, phallic symbols which, as in Utopia, bar entry to the safe haven beyond. Once it emerges that they are Christian, however, they are permitted to land, and are given food and lodging, free of charge, in the Strangers House. A period of quarantine then ensues, during which their sick (who constitute precisely one third of the ships company) are provided with appropriate diet and medicine, and make so rapid a recovery that they thought themselves cast into some divine pool of healing, they mended so kindly and so fast (p.715). Reduced to a state of total dependence, the travellers remain passive and submissive throughout, appreciative of the gracious and parent-like usage (715) they receive, and often prostrating themselves at the feet and kissing the robes of the various authority figures they encounter. When they are finally sufficiently recovered to be allowed to explore their

THE UTOPIAN DREAM OF ORDER

63

surroundingswithin the strict limits laid down by their hoststhey discover a world that is, once again, stable, prosperous, happy, and at peace. And while, compared to More and Campanella, Bacon provides relatively few details of the social organization of his ideal commonwealth, it is clearly characterized by, if possible, an even greater degree of purity and moral rectitude on the part of its inhabitants: there is not under the heavens so chaste a nation as this of Bensalem; nor so free from all pollution or foulness. It is the virgin of the world (p.724). Despite a few passing indications that individual conduct may occasionally require correction, it would appear that Bacons society is, again, one in which innocence has in large measure been recovered. Yet it is also a society in which the maternal security it provides is the product of an order if possible still more exclusively male-dominated than those of Utopia or the City of the Sun. While the brevity of The New Atlantis precludes more than a brief glimpse of its workings, one feature that is described in what seems almost redundant detail is the so-called Feast of the Family, a ceremony held to honour any man that shall live to see thirty persons descended of his body alive together, and all above three years old (p.722). This feast, which is paid for by the state, follows two days of consultations during which the father of the family (called the tirsan) settles any outstanding family disputes, and offers advice or assistance to such members of the family who seem in need of it. He then chooses one of his sons to live with him, who is thereafter called the Son of the Vine, and the feast ensues, after which prayers are offered to the patriarchs, Adam, Noah, and Abraham. The tirsan is served exclusively by his male children, while the women only stand about him, leaning against the wall (p.723), and the ceremony concludes with the tirsan giving his blessing. There is, however, one notable absentee: if there be a mother, from whose body the whole lineage is descended, there is a travers placed in a loft above on the right hand of the chair, with a privy door, and a carved window of glass, leaded with gold and blue; where she sitteth, but is not seen. [p.723] It would be hard to imagine a more explicit image of the displacement of the female by the male, with the mother reduced to peering down, unseen, as the power of the father is celebrated; yet it is an image very much in keeping with the emphasis of the work as a wholeelsewhere, although women presumably do exist, they remain invisible. In such a context, it is perhaps unsurprising that among the discoveries made by the scientists of the House of Salomon is a method of artificially creating life. Not only are women invisible in Bacons utopia, the technology exists to render them superfluous.

64

NARRATING UTOPIA

The Utopian Narrative Paradigm A range of features, then, begin to emerge as characteristic of the utopian narrative model. As has been seen, the ideological ferment of the Renaissance finds a reflection in a series of distinctive ambiguities. In all three of the works so far examined, the direction of the utopian impulse remains unclear: the question of whether utopia embodies the desire to create a genuinely new order, or to recover one that has been lost is in each case difficult to resolve. And while the utopian vision is of a society radically different from that of the writer, it nevertheless excludes any consideration of the process of change. Not only are the utopian societies of More, Campanella, and Bacon fundamentally static, leaving little or no room for alteration (unless for the worse), the process whereby they came into being is passed over or evaded. Mores Utopia is simply decreed; Campanellas is apparently the fruit of a collective resolution; while Bacons was apparently already in existence when King Solamona instituted a policy of isolation designed to preserve it in its perfection. The emphasis of the Renaissance utopian narrative is on stasis rather than process, security rather than change. And while the nature of that security may be seen as distinctively maternal, it is in each case sustained by the imposition of an explicitly patriarchal order. Although utopias may sweep away such fundamental existing institutions as private property, money, or the Christian religion, they rely as heavily on the maintenance of patriarchy for their distinctive character as on the abolition or transformation of other aspects of society. In this regard, there are also clear parallels with the contemporaneous discovery narratives, in whose language a similar fantasy of masculine dominance over territory gendered as female is likewise inscribed, and in which the opening up of the new is only the prelude to the superimposition of existing hierarchies and modes of domination. In both Utopia and The City of the Sun it is significant that, albeit with the best of apparent intentions, one of the major projects of the utopian state is the colonization of its neighbours. Lastly, while utopia proposes an order which appears on the surface distinctively rational, although one which at the same time reproduces significant aspects of existing society, this apparent reasonableness should not be allowed to disguise its essentially fantastic character. As Bloch remarks, the apparent modesty of some aspects of the utopian dream conceals a basic utopia which is much too fantastic to manifest itself openly (Principle of Hope, p.751). Underlying the concrete, even mundane detail of utopian systems for the production and distribution of food, underlying Mores six hour and Campanellas four hour working day, is the old paradisaical dream of free feeding and idleness; while the common

THE UTOPIAN DREAM OF ORDER

65

utopian preoccupation with hygiene, diet, and improved medical techniques conceals an aspiration still more grandiose. Beyond the Solarian life span of between one hundred and two hundred years lies the ultimate dream of eternal life. In narrative terms, the tensions and contradictions inherent in the content of the utopian dream also manifest themselves at the formal level. As has been suggested, the peculiarly static character of the utopian vision gives rise to a distinctive chronotope, in which plenitude in space seems designed to compensate for the virtual erasure of time. While both More and Bacon indicate time-frames presumably intended to enhance the readers sense of utopias permanence (1760 years have elapsed since the foundation of Utopia, 1900 since the reign of Solamona), the fact that nothing of any significance appears to have happened during that time strips it of any real meaning. Time, no matter how extensive, is empty of content; whereas the space of utopia is full. Within the confines of the City of the Sun all human knowledge is encoded, while the House of Salomon has achieved a similar exhaustive mastery of the secrets of nature. The very architecture of utopia, whether Mores or Campanellas, is designed to create an environment in which everything (and everyone) is known. Yet this fullness is lacking in any dynamic quality: it remains, as Wells puts it, static rather than kinetic. The description of utopian geography, while it possesses a concreteness that the account of utopian history so signally lacks, has the quality of a tableaua space frozen in time. Utopian narrative consists primarily of a single process: that of unveiling the tableau to the non-utopian audience. And it is here that one may see the emerging utopian narrative model as in a sense more restrictive than its first exemplar. Where More does provide some sense of narrative interaction between utopia and his own world, both in the vigorous debate which occupies the first book, and in the complex dialectic between the actual account of utopia and the narrative which frames it, this element is far less evident in the work of his successors. In the fictions of Campanella and Bacon, the tension between Hythlodays unequivocal enthusiasm for Utopia and the scepticism of the narrator disappears. Campanellas Knight Hospitaller eagerly interrogates the Genoese mariner, but accepts all he is told with uncritical wonder; while the narrator of The New Atlantis provides a more passive, but equally sympathetic audience for the authoritative discourse of the utopians. While in Mores case there is a sense of genuine dialogue, of an interaction between conflicting viewpoints, the work of his successors serves largely to foreclose such exchanges. The complicating irony of Utopia almost entirely disappears, giving way to a more straightforwardly didactic intent. Even where the form of the dialogue is preserved, albeit in vestigial form, it only serves to highlight the extent to

66

NARRATING UTOPIA

which, as Bakhtin puts it, the content assume[s] a monologic character that contradict[s] the form shaping idea of the genre (Problems, p.110). Dialogue becomes merely a simple means for expounding ready-made ideas (p.110). With the passage of time, then, the purpose of utopian narrative become clearer: its function is primarily to persuade. Such didactic intent is, of course, quite in keeping with the norms of Renaissance narrative practice; it is only later, with the rise of the novel, and the emergence of interpretative conventions rooted in the growing influence of representational realism, that finding a fictional vehicle for such overt didacticism becomes more problematic. Thus, while the most obvious challenge facing later writers of utopian fiction is that of conceiving more desirable sociopolitical alternatives in a context where innovation and growth, rather than stasis, have become evidently the norm, the problem of how such alternatives are to be represented becomes a more pressing one. Moving forward to the modern era, it becomes clear that, despite the ingenuity which writers such as Bellamy and Wells bring to bear on both the ideological and narrative problems involved in the production of literary utopias, the influence of the traditional, and essentially static utopian model is by no means easy to escape. In examining the very different narrative strategies which they adopt, it becomes necessary, once again, to ask not only what changes with the passage of time, but what remains the same.

3. Bellamy and Wells: The Dream of Order in the Modern World


If a certain degree of tension and ambiguity can be seen as inherent in the utopian model as such, it is also clear that much of the complex and contradictory character of the utopian fictions of the Renaissance is a direct reflection of the ideological ferment of the period in which they were written. Indeed, the intellectual exercise of projecting a more desirable alternative to the society of the day often has the effect of highlighting precisely those aspects of Renaissance thinking that are most ambivalent and fraught with contradiction. In an era where new and potentially revolutionary ideas co-exist with a powerful commitment to tradition, the utopian vision, offering the promise of stability while at the same time implying the desirability of change, almost inevitably exposes gaps and disjuncturesthe points where conflicting impulses become impossible to reconcile. That not only the utopian dream of order as such, but also the characteristic narrative paradigm associated with it should survive into the modern era raises a number of issues with regard to the relation between ideology and form. While the endurance of the utopian impulse itself requires little explanationso long as society remains imperfect, more perfect alternatives will always have an appealthe persistence of so many specific features of the Renaissance utopia, in terms both of content and form, is less easy to account for. Obviously, there is the question of direct influence to consider: in many cases later writers are clearly aware of, and respond to the example of their predecessors; nevertheless, as we shall see, that example is one which becomes increasingly problematic with the passage of time. To begin with, it is clear that the writer of utopian fiction at the close of the nineteenth century (which sees the first major flowering of utopian fiction since the Renaissance) is faced with a radically different relationship between text and context. That dramatic changes in the nature of society are likely to dictate changes in the nature of the alternatives envisaged to it goes without saying: a utopia designed to resolve problems of scarcity in a pre-industrial economy will clearly differ radically from one which addresses issues arising from the contradictions of industrial capitalism and the organizational needs of a mass society. What also changes, however, is the nature of the connection between the writers society and the utopian

68

NARRATING UTOPIA

alternatives proposed. For example, when Campanellas Genoese mariner remarks that the past hundred years had seen more history than the preceding four thousand, the implications of his statement had not yet become fully apparent. While to a modern eye it might seem singularly prescient, indicative of an awareness that a process of far-reaching historical change had now begun, in a Renaissance context it might equally be taken as suggesting that history was now hastening to its endtowards a final state of millennial perfection, of which the City of the Sun is an emblem. By the close of the nineteenth century, however, the notion of progressof history as a process of continuous advance, with change as the norm, rather than the exceptionhad become commonplace. Writing in 1890, Sidney Webb (whose thinking clearly influenced Wells, notwithstanding his subsequent break with the Fabians) declared: we can no longer think of the future society as an unchanging state. The social ideal from being statical has become dynamic. The necessity of constant growth and development of the social organism has become axiomatic. [p.5] Given such assumptions, much that in a Renaissance context seemed relatively fixed (social institutions, the relation of human society to nature) now appears provisional, susceptible to modification by human agency. The largely speculative premise of the Renaissance utopiathat human beings, by the unaided use of their powers of reason, might create a more perfect societybegins to seem increasingly plausible. As the evidence mounts that changes once envisaged solely in a utopian context are capable of being embodied in reality, the assumption that social engineering is not only desirable, but practicable becomes more and more widely accepted. The manifest influence of utopian ideas during such historic conflicts as the English Civil War, the American War of Independence, or the French Revolution clearly demonstrates the practical impact of notions once seen as largely hypothetical. Change, in other words, is no longer a dream, but a real possibility, and the increasingly widespread belief in the feasibility of creating, if not an ideal, at any rate a better society obviously affects the ways in which utopian fiction is both imagined and read. If the establishment of a better society is seen as possible, even likely, then the concept of a still more perfect society becomes that much more plausible. In addition, the plausibility of the content of utopian fiction is further enhanced by the fact that accompanying developments in science and technology give substance to another aspect of the utopian dream: that of humanity gaining control over nature. By 1888, when Bellamys Looking Backward was first published, many of the wishful imaginings of Campanella and Bacon had already become realities, with dramatic

BELLAMY AND WELLS

69

advances in hygiene, medicine, long-range transport and communications, and even some degrees of flying in the air (Bacon, p.731). Far from being confined to a research institute such as the House of Salomon, with only minimal effect on the surrounding society, invention becomes instrumental in the process of societal change, which in turn lends a very different resonance to its depiction in a utopian context. In portraying technology as central to the creation of their utopian societies, writers such as Bellamy and Wells are in essence only reflecting the realities of their own world. Not only technological advance, but its impact are depicted with a degree of concreteness wholly lacking in the utopias of Campanella and Bacon: in contrast to their rather abstract formulations, even the most futuristic aspects of Bellamys and Wellss utopias (the underground network of pneumatic tubes in Looking Backward, the genetic engineering of Men Like Gods) are presented in detail, and as integral to the functioning of utopian society as a whole. Yet while it might therefore seem reasonable to conclude that one effect of the passage of time is to render utopian fiction more plausible, in other respects the radically different historical circumstances render the writing of such fiction more, rather than less problematic. As Kumar suggests, where the Renaissance utopia embodied an essentially static ideala society where change was not merely unnecessary, but an actual threat those of the modern era had perforce to be open-ended, to a degree never before attempted or thought necessary. They had to accommodate the requirement for ceaseless innovation and growth, individual and social (Utopia, pp.478). This necessity, however, creates some undeniable formal problems. As Wells was among the first to acknowledge, in order to portray a society in which change is integral, rather than representing a threat of degeneration, it becomes necessary to incorporate a much greater element of processto dramatize what happens in such a society, as opposed to merely describing its outlines. Such an essentially novelistic approach, utilizing the techniques of a genre evolved to represent precisely such a changing society, might seem the obvious solution, yet it is not without its own difficultiesfor if the development of both new technologies and new forms of political organization serve to render the actual content of utopian literature more plausible, in other respects its fictionality becomes more transparent. With the end of the age of exploration, the space into which earlier writers were able to project their utopias disappears. The unknown becomes known; the possible is colonized by the actual: in the end, imperfect reality fills all the territory on the map where utopian perfection could once be imagined. Forced to look elsewhere for a locale, writers of utopias turn increasingly to the space provided by the extension of temporal, rather than geographical horizons. As the old, finite time-

70

NARRATING UTOPIA

frame in which history was conceived of as a matter of a few thousand years, bounded by the creation at one end and the millennium at the other, gives way to the far vaster perspectives afforded by evolutionary theory, the future becomes a new terra incognita into which utopia can be projected. This has certain attendant drawbacks, however: while the emergent genre of science fiction takes full advantage of the imaginative perspectives provided by this larger future, (not to mention the corresponding extension of spatial horizons to which speculation as to the feasibility of space travel gives rise), utopian fiction seems less successful at exploiting the creative possibilities that arise. The exuberance with which Wells uses the techniques of representational realism to lend a veneer of plausibility to such futuristic fantasies as The Time Machine and The War of the Worlds is notably lacking in both his own utopian fictions and those of most of his contemporaries. In part, this may be attributable to the constraints imposed by the more earnest, even didactic intent which utopian fiction evinces; yet this is not the only factor. What is also clear is the extent to which even the most radical fictional experiments (such as Wellss own A Modern Utopia) remain tied to the characteristic narrative paradigm of the Renaissance utopiathat of the travellers tale, in which the visitor explores the more perfect society, and then reports back on the wonders he has seen. Indeed, while it has become something of a critical commonplace that temporal, rather than geographical displacement becomes the norm,1 it is curious how many modern utopias, from Gilmans Herland to Huxleys Island, in fact retain the traditional premise of a utopian society isolated from, but contemporaneous with the writers own: even Wells, a pioneer of futuristic fiction in works such as The Time Machine and The War in the Air, chooses for the most part to locate his utopias in worlds parallel to, rather than chronologically separated from his own. None the less, what does emerge at this period is a recognizable variant of the old forma narrative in which the traditional voyage to utopia is replaced by the process of going to sleep and reawakening in a utopian future. Used by both Bellamy and Morris in their utopias, not to mention Wells, in his far-from-utopian When the Sleeper Wakes (1899), what Peter Beilharz refers to as the Rip Van Winkle genre typically associated with the term [utopia] (p.x)2 soon becomes a narrative device sufficiently familiar as to become an object of parodywitness Stephen Leacocks Afternoons in Utopia (1932), which begins: let us reproduce the familiar scene of the long sleep and the arrival of the awakened sleeper in dear old Utopia. We will introduce, however, the slight, but novel, innovation of supposing that the

BELLAMY AND WELLS

71

narrator in this case arrives withand not, as usually depicted, withouthis brains. [p.3] In a modern context, however, the adequacy of this narrative paradigm, whether modified or not, seems open to doubt. At least part of the Renaissance utopias narrative fascination, as we have seen, lay in its capacity to exploit the conventions of a narrative model that was factual and documentary in origin. At the same time that More, Campanella, and Bacon were writing, there were also actual travellers accounts from the southern hemisphere, allowing the writer of utopias to play with the notion (as More does most teasingly) that the ideal society might actually exist. This is not to say that any but the most literal-minded reader believed it really did exist: the point is that the possibility remained intriguingly plausible. In the case of fictions set in the future, however, in a parallel universe (Men Like Gods), or out beyond Sirius (A Modern Utopia, p.12), the fantasy is unequivocal, thereby bringing into play a rather different set of interpretive conventions. Whereas the actual utopian societies outlined may seem more plausible, more susceptible to practical realization, the narrative form in which they are represented becomes self-evidently fantastic. As a result, the fruitful ambiguity which pervades both the content and the form of the Renaissance utopia gives way, in a modern context, to a certain sense of generic discontinuity, rooted in what Morson describes as the double encoding of utopias as both fiction and non-fiction, literature and nonliterature (p.93). Where Mores manipulation of the conventions of a purportedly factual narrative mode is well suited to his apparent ambivalence of intent, the fantastic narrative mechanisms of the utopias of Bellamy and Wells seem rather less in keeping with the evident seriousness of their sociopolitical prescriptions. The result is often a certain confusion as to how such hybrid fictions are meant to be read. As Morson suggests, problems arise when the set of instructions, which characterizes the text as not a fiction or not just literature, is delayed and the reader consequently led astray. It is not surprising, then, that readers of utopias often feel exploited as well as perplexed. That feeling may be the result not so much of having been led to read a literary work that turned out to be bad as having been led to read one that turned outor did it? to be no literary work at all. Belatedly discovering that the literary and fictional contracts had hidden clauses, readers may feel themselves to be victims of literary fraud. [p.93] Such problems, of course, stem in part from the changing nature of fictions interpretive conventions. In an era when fiction is dominated by the norms of high realism and naturalism, by what Fredric Jameson

72

NARRATING UTOPIA

describes as the threefold imperatives of authorial depersonalization, unity of point of view, and restriction to scenic representation (Political Unconscious, p.104), the formal heterogeneity and tendentiousness of utopian fiction is always liable to appear anomalous. And while Jameson argues that the re-emergence of genres such as the utopian is symptomatic of a reaction against the stifling constraints imposed by such realisms celebration of the merely existing, it is nevertheless the case that writers of utopias seem uneasily aware of the extent to which their fictions fail to secure the consistent suspension of disbelief at which realist fiction aims. Both Bellamy and Wells, for example, while preserving the central features of the traditional narrative paradigm, seek to supplement its by now somewhat limited attractions by the incorporation of more novelistic elements: individual characterization, for example, or plot features such as a love interest. Such window dressing, however, scarcely resolves the underlying narrative problem. Not the least of the difficulties that arises from the use of novelistic elements is an essential incompatibility between utopian narrative and the conventions of a genre which had evolved primarily to register the complex texture of existing reality. As Morson argues: The interpretive conventions of utopias are radically different from those of novelsa difference which, as we shall see, reflects the two genres antithetical philosophical assumptions. First, in the novel, unlike the utopia, the narrative is to be taken as representing a plausible sequence of events (i.e., as designed to be realistic). Second, in a novel, the statements, actions, and beliefs of any principal character (or the narrator) are to be understood as a reflection of his or her personality, and of the biographical events and social milieu that have shaped it. An important corollary for our discussion of utopias follows from this second interpretive convention. The sort of unqualified, absolute truths about morality and society that constantly occur in utopias have no place in novels. [p.77] While novels are by no means invariably free of didactic intent, that intent normally presupposes some common assumptions on the part of both writer and reader as to both the nature of reality and the validity of the value system informing it; where alternative assumptions have to be spelled out, as is the case in most traditional utopian narratives, an unavoidable tension arises between the utopian and novelistic elements in the text. Thus, while characters in a novel may utter unqualified, absolute truths about morality and society they remain utterances made in a particular context. As Morson goes on to suggest:

BELLAMY AND WELLS

73

In novels, but not in utopias, each truth is someones truth, qualified by what might be called an irony of originsthat is, by our knowledge that it reflects a particular persons (or characters) experience and a given set of personal and contextual circumstances. They are consequently understood to be partialthat is, both limited and biasedeven if we (or the author) are inclined to share that partiality. [p.77] Yet it is precisely this awareness that the traditional utopian narrative seeks to discourage: whereas the partial, limited awareness of the inhabitants of existing society may be the target of utopian critiqueas is the case in the utopias of both Bellamy and Wellsthe underlying assumption is that in the more perfect society such limitations have largely vanished, enabling the utopians to see the truth as it is. Given the difficulties associated with the reproduction in a modern context of the Renaissance utopias narrative paradigm, its persistence raises a number of questions. To begin with, the survival of a generic structure rooted in very different historical circumstances should alert us to the possibility that, for all its shortcomings in a modern narrative context, it nevertheless continues to embody some ideological message of enduring relevance. Are there, in other words, any parallels between the differing historical situations which might encourage a specific narrative formulation of utopian alternatives? Equally, the continued evasion by writers such as Bellamy and Wells of the issue of utopias origins (accompanied once again by an often extravagant compensatory elaboration of metaphors of transition), poses a further question: how far is the characteristic psychological pattern of the Renaissance utopia, in which a recurrent element is the reconstitution of the maternal security of the womb under a system of patriarchal control, inherent in the traditional paradigm? If, as we have seen, the very process of exploration and discovery is bound up with primal fantasies of the recovery of Eden, is the travellers tale itself not likely to lend itself particularly easily to the embodiment of this dream? Finally, given the contradictions inherent in the content of Renaissance and modern utopia alike, it must be asked whether, paradoxically, the problematic aspect of its form, its inscription of conflicting impulses in an unresolved tension, is not also a source of its lasting appeal. Yet if a detailed examination of more modern articulations of the utopian dream may help to account for the resilience of the traditional narrative format, it should likewise be borne in mind that the continuing use of a specific narrative form is liable to have ideological consequences in terms of content. As Macherey argues, the relationship between ideology and narrative is by no means a simple one of cause and effect: the form

74

NARRATING UTOPIA

also has its effect on the narratives ideological implications. How far a form originally used for the expression of the static, authoritarian vision of the Renaissance utopian writers affects the avowedly progressive content of the works of Bellamy and Wellsor, as Jameson puts it, how far an already constituted narrative paradigm emits an ideological message in its own right (Political Unconscious, p.88)is a question which the following discussion will address. Bellamy, Looking Backward Bellamys Looking Backward, as we shall see, adheres particularly closely to the traditional narrative paradigm. While the chosen locale for the ideal society is no longer an imaginary island or walled city, but the rather more prosaic setting of Boston, Massachusetts, it is none the less a Boston transfigured by its displacement more than a hundred years into the futureinto the year 2000by which time it has become literally unrecognizable.3 Nevertheless, the fantastic nature of its narrative premise does not appear to have detracted from what was widely seen as the plausibility of its social prescriptions. Indeed, in its day, Looking Backward enjoyed a degree of influence and popularity which now seems barely credible, not only enjoying enormous sales, but inspiring the foundation of Bellamy societies as far afield as Holland, South Africa, Indonesia, and New Zealand. Even as late as the 1930s it was cited by both the philosopher John Dewey and the historian Charles Beard as being second in importance only to Das Kapital among books published in the preceding half-century.4 And for all that Looking Backward now appears terribly dated in most respects, its appeal clearly has much in common with that exerted by the earlier utopias of More, Campanella, and Bacon. Like theirs, Bellamys vision of an ordered society offers a telling, even seductive contrast to the chaos of the actual world to which it proposes an alternative. Endeavouring to account for the appeal of such utopias, Northrop Frye suggests that: the utopian form flourishes best when anarchy seems most a social threat. Since More, utopias have appeared regularly but sporadically in literature, with a great increase around the close of the nineteenth century. This later vogue clearly had much to do with the distrust and dismay aroused by extreme laissez-faire version of capitalism, which were thought of as manifestations of anarchy, [Varieties, p.27] In the case of Looking Backward, this would seem to be particularly true: indeed, some of the most powerful passages in the work occur in the introductory section where, like More before him, Bellamy offers a vivid

BELLAMY AND WELLS

75

depiction of the social evils of his day. It is here, in his portrayal of the periods recurrent financial crises, its often brutal conflicts between capital and labour, its glaring divisions between the conditions of rich and poor, that Bellamy is at his most bitterly satiricalmost notably in the celebrated allegorical passage where society is depicted as a coach, drawn by the mass of humanity: The driver was hunger, and permitted no lagging, though the pace was necessarily very slow. Despite the difficulty of drawing the coach at all along so hard a road, the top was covered with passengers who never got down, even at the steepest ascents. These seats on top were very breezy and comfortable. Well up out of the dust, their occupants could enjoy the scenery at their leisure, or critically discuss the merits of the straining team It was naturally regarded as a terrible misfortune to lose ones seat, and the apprehension that this might happen to them or their friends was a constant cloud upon the happiness of those who rode When the vehicle came to a bad place in the road, as it was constantly doing, or to a particularly steep hill the desperate straining of the team, their agonizing leaping and plunging under the pitiless lash of hunger, the many who fainted at the rope and were trampled in the mire, made a very distressing spectacle, which often called forth highly creditable displays of feeling on the top of the coach It was agreed that it was a great pity that the coach should be so hard to pull, and there was a sense of general relief when the specially bad piece of road was gotten over. The relief was not, indeed, wholly on account of the team, for there was always some danger at these bad places of a general overturn in which all would lose their seats. [pp.1011] Yet while the forcefulness of Bellamys satire on contemporary society recalls the spirit of the first book of Mores Utopia, what follows is closer to the letter of the second. The basic scenario is simple enough. The narrator, Julian West, is a young Bostonian who goes to sleep one May night in 1887, but (due to a somewhat bizarre combination of circumstances) fails to awake until September of the year 2000. While he finds himself still in Boston, the reality he confronts is otherwise wholly unfamiliar. Physically, there are no vestiges of the city of his own day, and it soon becomes clear that the squalor and industrial strife of the 1880s have given way to utopian cooperation. During his century-long slumber the laissez-faire capitalism of the late nineteenth-century has evolvedpainlessly, it would appear into a full-blown command economy: employers and trade unions alike have been superseded by the monopolistic state, and (most other nations

76

NARRATING UTOPIA

having followed the lead of the United States) the world is as a result governed by reason and justice. As Julian West discovers, in a series of lengthy discussions with his utopian host, Dr Leete, there is universal peace, the spread of prosperity and enlightenment having rendered it unnecessary for nations to make war in order to divert attention from suffering and unrest at home, while the combination of centralized economic planning with the elimination of wasteful competition and needless duplication of services ensures a sufficiency of goods for all. Liberation from the demands of unceasing labour is also provided, although in this case by early retirement, rather than the reduction of hours: industrial service, as it is called, terminates at the age of forty-five. What is offered, in other words, is very much the same basic agenda as that of the Renaissance utopia: the technology of Bellamys society is more advanced, the vocabulary he employs rather different, but the end product is remarkably similar. Even where obvious differences occur, they often prove superficial. While peace, in the Renaissance utopia, is only secured by vigorous defensive precautionswitness the ruthlessness with which the otherwise pacific Utopians wage war, or the detailed account we are given of the Solarians sophisticated military tacticsone might think the extension of utopian society worldwide would render such military preoccupations redundant. In Looking Backward, however, while warfare no longer takes place, the military impulse is simply displaced elsewhere: if international harmony has rendered external defence superfluous, the societys internal organization exhibits a strikingly militaristic character. Indeed, the entire system of industrial organization in the United States of the future is explicitly based on a military model: the principle of universal military service, we are told, has simply been applied to the labour question (p.32).5 Bellamy even goes so far as to stateapprovinglythat the efficiency of the utopian workforce is comparable to that of the German army in the time of Von Moltke (p.135)!6 Given that his latter-day Americans were already accustomed to the idea that the obligation of every citizen, not physically disabled, to contribute to the defence of the nation was equal and absolute (p.32), it follows that it is equally the duty of every citizen to contribute his quota of industrial or intellectual services to the maintenance of the nation (p.32). Hence the institution of what Bellamy refers to as the industrial army, whose discipline and efficiency are central to the harmony and prosperity of his utopian future. Even the contrasting chaos of late nineteenth-century society is represented in terms of the same all-pervasive military metaphor. As Dr Leete puts it: People would be prompt enough to ridicule an army in which there were neither companies, battalions, regiments, brigades, divisions,

BELLAMY AND WELLS

77

or army corpsno unit of organization, in fact, larger than the corporals squad, with no officer higher than a corporal, and all the corporals equal in authority. And yet just such an army were the manufacturing industries of nineteenth-century Boston, an army of four thousand independent squads led by four thousand independent corporals, each with a separate plan of campaign. [p.178] No such independence, of course, is either possible or desired in the Boston of the year 2000: all citizens are subject to the central authority of the industrial army, into which recruits are inducted at the age of twentyone on what is significantly called Muster Day. Or rather, almost all: like its Renaissance predecessors, Bellamys utopia has its lite, who form a separate caste.7 The liberal professions, we learn, do not form part of the industrial army, and it is they alonedoctors, teachers, artists, men of letterswho, along with retired males over the age of forty-five, are eligible to vote. The industrial army itself is disenfranchisedas indeed are all women. In the case of women, of course, it may fairly be objected that Bellamy is merely reflecting the political realities of his day: women in late nineteenth-century North America did not have the vote, either. Nevertheless, as has already become evident, the features of his own society which the utopian writer chooses to preserve are no less significant than those he transforms. As with the Renaissance utopias maintenance of patriarchy, Bellamys relatively traditional conception of the role of women needs to be set against the sweeping transformations of society proposed elsewhere. For while, like Campanella, Bellamy seems at first sight to be proposing a radical extension of womens existing rights and freedoms, on closer examination a similar ambiguity becomes apparent. As does Campanella, Bellamy offers a freedom which proves increasingly illusory, undermined and contradicted as it is by other evidence in the text. While some recent critics have praised Bellamy for his commitment to feminism,8 his utopia is hardly less male-dominated than those of the Renaissance. For example, while women work in Bellamys Boston of the future, just as they do in the City of the Sun, the narratives initial assertion of equality in principle (women, as well as men, are members of the industrial army (p.142)) is subject to a series of progressively more disabling qualifications, whose ultimate effect is to restore women to a subordinate role. Just as in Campanellas utopia, the actual range of jobs open to women is restricted, due to their being inferior in strength, and further disqualified industrially in special ways (p.142): Under no circumstances is a woman permitted to follow any employment not perfectly adapted, both as to kind and degree of

78

NARRATING UTOPIA

labour, to her sex. Moreover, the hours of womens work are considerably shorter than those of mens, more frequent vacations are granted, and the most careful provision is made for rest when needed. The men of this day so well appreciate that they owe to the beauty and grace of women the chief zest of their lives and their main incentive to effort, that they permit them to work at all only because it is fully understood that a certain regular requirement of labour, of a sort adapted to their powers, is well for body and mind [pp.1423] What becomes clear, in effect, is that the power dynamic underlying Bellamys system of utopian gender relations is not radically different from that obtaining in the society to which his utopia proposes an alternative. While there are some real improvements in the lot of women, not least their liberation from most domestic labour by the institution of public kitchens, laundries, and facilities for clothes repair, the basic social structure remains clearly patriarchal. As Bammer argues, one way in which utopias of the period sought to allay anxieties aroused by the sweeping changes they imagined in societys public institutions was by their insistence that the structures of private life would remain reassuringly unchangedand that in particular gender would remain constant: a woman, no matter what else might change, would still remain every inch a woman. And a man, by implication, a man (p.30). Thus, in Looking Backward, while men permit women to work, it is only for health reasons: the principal value of their labour is that it renders them more desirable to the men. And the marginal status of womens labour is still further underscored when it transpires that women, notwithstanding Dr Leetes initial assertion, are not in fact part of the industrial army after all: they constitute rather an allied force than an integral part of the army of the men. They have a woman general-in-chief and are under exclusively feminine rgime (p.143).9 The motives for this segregation, however, are less puritanical than they might seem at first sight. Bellamys main concern, it would appear, is for the preservation of industrial discipline. Outside the workplace, relations between the sexes are not merely permitted, but actively encouraged: love, it turns out, is regarded as essential to the welfare of the state. In the course of yet another lengthy conversation with Dr Leete, the narrator learns that the independence of women has ensured that economic considerations no longer influence the womans choice of marital partner, with the result that there are nothing but matches of pure love (p.148). Yet while the narrator is appropriately impressed by this astonishing phenomenon, Dr Leete is more concerned to spell out its implications: It means that for the first time in human history the principle of

BELLAMY AND WELLS

79

sexual selection, with its tendency to preserve and transmit the better types of the race, and let the inferior types drop out, has unhindered operation. The necessities of poverty, the need of having a home, no longer tempt women to accept as the fathers of their children men whom they neither can love nor respect. Wealth and rank no longer divert attention from personal qualities. Gold no longer gilds the straitened forehead of the fool. The gifts of person, mind, and disposition; beauty, wit, eloquence, kindness, generosity, geniality, courage, are sure of transmission to posterity. Each generation is sifted through a little finer mesh than the last. [p.148] It is the effect of such untrammelled sexual selection as tending to race purification (pp.1489) that really matters. As in The City of the Sun, the sexual provisions of Looking Backward have selective breeding as their ultimate goal. Nevertheless, Bellamys is a distinctively nineteenth-century reworking of a longstanding utopian preoccupation: an end which Campanella seeks to attain by the imposition of rigorous state control, with appropriate medical and astrological supervision, is here left to the unhindered operation of the forces of the sexual free market. Yet purification of the race is not the only benefit, it turns out. In addition, Dr Leete reveals, the fact that merit alone inspires love also proves conducive to industrial efficiency, since the best (indeed virtually the only) way of demonstrating the desirable qualities Bellamy lists is by being a good worker: not all the encouragements and incentives of every sort which we have provided to develop industry, talent, genius, excellence of whatever kind, are comparable in their effect on our young men with the fact that our women sit aloft as judges of the race and reserve themselves to reward the winners. Of all the whips, and spurs, and baits, and prizes, there is none like the thought of the radiant faces which the laggards will find averted. [p.149] In the name of a saner, more rational organization of society, woman is still more nakedly reduced to the status not merely of consumer (Dr Leetes daughter, it will be recalled, is characterized as an indefatigable shopper), but of commoditythe prize awarded for success in the race of life. What Bellamy offers is not so much an alternative structure of gender relations, as an unmasking of the process whereby sexual gratification becomes a reward for economic success. Where the difference lies is that in his utopia there is no longer any mediation: the rewards for the productive capacity of the individual are now sexual instead of economic. While many of Looking Backwards most traditionally utopian provisionsthe abolition of money, state control of the means of production and distributionmight seem

80

NARRATING UTOPIA

antithetical to the values of late nineteenth-century capitalism, what is enacted, in effect, is the compensatory displacement of the economic into the realm of the sexual. In this instance, Bellamys underlying assumptions become only too overt; yet what he shows is perhaps less interesting than what he seeks to conceal. As in the Renaissance utopias, a relentless specificity of detail regarding the workings of the more perfect society is accompanied by an equally telling lack of detail concerning the process whereby it came into being. As Jean Pfaelzer remarks, despite the wealth of detail which Bellamy provides in other areas, he remains vague and imprecise about the transition to utopia (Immanence, p.53). Although he portrays late nineteenth-century America as being on the brink of anarchy, for example, it is significant that the utopian command economy of the year 2000 appears to have been established without any form of struggle or conflict whatsoever. Despite the competitive greed of the business community, and labour unrest so acute that it causes some observers to predict an impending social cataclysm (p.7), and to surmise that, having emerged from barbarism, the human race had attained the perihelion of civilization only to plunge downward once more to its nether goal in the regions of chaos (p.7),10 it transpires that the subsequent amalgamation of all businesses into a single nationwide corporation has been accomplished with none of the great bloodshed and terrible convulsions (p.29) that might reasonably have been expected. Instead, as Dr Leete is at pains to assure the narrator: there was absolutely no violence. The change had been long foreseen. Public opinion had become fully ripe for it, and the whole mass of people was behind it. There was no more possibility of opposing it by force than by argument. [p.29] And that is all we learn concerning the transition to a utopian society: it just happened, apparently inevitably. Brief as this is, however, it serves to emphasize the extent to which security, above all, remains the fundamental object of Bellamys utopian desire. The transition is not merely non-violent, but there is absolutely no violence (not a single landlord or capitalist forcibly resists dispossession, we must assume, nor does a single member of the proletariat resort to violence out of resentment or a desire for vengeance). Yet that is not all: not only is there no violencethere is not even any dialogue. Argument, like resistance, is futile in the face of the absolute, self-evident persuasive authority of the utopian ideal. Utopia is achieved, not by revolutionary struggle, but by consensusby a painless, automatic process which, for a late nineteenth-century middle-class liberal such as Bellamy was doubtless a profoundly consoling fiction. While Bellamy was

BELLAMY AND WELLS

81

frequently accused of being a socialist, it should be noted that he himself vehemently rejected the label, declaring the very word socialist to be a foreign word in itself, and equally foreign in all its suggestions. It smells to the average American of petroleum, suggests the red flag and all manner of sexual novelties, and an abusive tone about God and religion, which in this country we at least treat with decent respect. [Quoted in Bowman, p.31]11 This reluctance to deal with the process whereby utopia comes into being, however, is symptomatic of a broader pattern of evasion. What Bellamy seems to dislike, in fact, is explicitness about process of any kind. For example, while the predictive element in utopian fiction is not in itself of any great interest (witness the tedious journalistic debates in 1984 over how far Orwells fiction had come true), there is nevertheless a certain significance in what the futuristic details which Bellamy does get right have in common. Like More, for instance, Bellamy banishes money from his utopiabut instead of making his gold into chamberpots, he replaces it by credit cards. Piped music is the norm, live concerts having been replaced by a sort of musical telephone, on which one calls up a 24 hour concert servicethe narrator is woken one morning by a spirited reveille: the airs played during the waking hours of morning were always of the inspiring type (p.76). (In fact, what Bellamy calls the telephone more closely resembles the radioalthough it might equally be seen as fulfilling the Baconian dream of conveying sounds in trunks and pipes, in strange lines and distances.) Shops no longer exist, their place having been taken by central warehouses similar to the Argos or Consumers Distributing networks, the one difference being that, instead of consumers collecting their purchases, they are despatched directly to the consumers house via a subterranean system of pneumatic tubes! What all these details have in common is that they serve to mask the actual process involved. Money, itself a mere signifier of value, is replaced by a token of itself, thereby obscuring the commercial transaction involved; the producers of music have been rendered invisible, leaving only the product itselfthe actual music; while the pneumatic tube, for all its period charm, effectively serves the same purposeone never actually sees or touches the goods one buys: they simply arrive, as if by magic, in the home. Moreover, for all the extended discussion of how industrial production is organized, there is never any depiction of work as such: the narrator visits only places of consumption, never of production.12 Taking all this along with the fact that in the utopian household no-one cooks, meals being either provided in communal restaurants, or sent to the home, it begins to appear that for Bellamy the mechanisms of production are very much like

82

NARRATING UTOPIA

those of reproductionsomething to be kept decently veiled at all costs. This distaste for too much reality is further reflected in the odd extravagance of some of Bellamys language, and in particular in the often curious similes and analogies with which he seeks to emphasize the contrast between utopian perfection and the squalor of reality. For example, while Bellamys insistence on the fundamental importance of universal culture and education to the establishment of utopian society is in itself unremarkableindeed, very much in keeping with the norms of the Renaissance utopiahis justification for it is rather more idiosyncratic. As Dr Leete tells the narrator: we should not consider life worth living if we had to be surrounded by a population of ignorant, boorish, coarse, wholly uncultivated men and women, as was the plight of the few educated in your day. Is a man satisfied, merely because he is perfumed himself, to mingle with a malodorous crowd? Could he take more than a very limited satisfaction, even in a palatial apartment, if the windows on all four sides opened into stable yards? And yet just that was the situation of those considered most fortunate as to culture and refinement in your day. I know that the poor and ignorant envied the rich and cultured then; but to us the latter, living as they did, surrounded by squalor and brutishness, seem little better off than the former. The cultured man in your age was like one up to the neck in a nauseous bog solacing himself with a smelling bottle. [p.122] The principal benefit conferred by universal education and the availability of culture to all, in other words, is that it protects the cultivated from the unpleasant spectacle (not to mention smell) of ignorance. And, to judge by the terms in which the poor and ignorant are described (boorish, coarse, malodorous, etc.) , there can be little doubt that it is the plight of the rich and cultured for which Dr Leete feels most sympathy. Dr Leete and his family, in fact, provide an interesting perspective on the true nature of Bellamys utopian ideala perspective which, in part, emerges from one of the features of Looking Backward that renders it distinct from its predecessors. Whereas the Renaissance utopia contents itself with simply describing the more perfect society (Bacon is the only author to portray individual utopians, and then only in the most cursory fashion), Bellamy sets out both to describe and dramatize his utopia, to tell a story which will show the utopian society in action. Yet it is precisely here that a new contradiction emerges, a contradiction revealed by the significant gap between what is described and what is dramatized. While the emphasis of Bellamys description is heavily on work, on how it is organized, by whom it is performed, and so forth, his portrayal of how utopian life is

BELLAMY AND WELLS

83

lived shows only the utopians at leisure. As his sole representatives of utopian society, he chooses a retired couple and their daughter who, while she must surely be of working age (Dr Leete and his wife are both about sixty), never appears to work at all.13 The resultant picture of utopian society in operation portrays a lifestyle virtually indistinguishable from that of the wealthy middle-class of Bellamys own day. Dr Leete, with his wine and cigars, his novel-loving wife, and Edith, with her taste for classical music and fine muslin, would, one feels, be equally at home in the drawingrooms of 1887. The main benefit which utopia has brought them is precisely that freedom from the spectacle of squalor, brutishness, and ignorance to which Dr Leete refersa freedom which is, in essence, a freedom from guilt. In contrast to the acute discomfort which Julian West experiences when confronted by the disparity between his wealth and the poverty and suffering of the masses, the Leetes lead a placid existence, free from any such qualms. The elimination of poverty and injustice allows them to live the good life of the nineteenth-century bourgeoisie, only with a clear conscience. While Frye is no doubt correct in his assertion that utopias such as Bellamys were prompted in part by the distrust and dismay aroused by extreme laissez-faire versions of capitalism (Varieties, p.27), Bellamys utopian vision remains, in Kumars words, irretrievably bourgeois, depicting a world where leisure (and consumption) are still seen in relation, and opposition, to work (Utopia, p.163). What Looking Backward offers is in effect a middle-class fantasy of a classless society one created not by the transformation of society as a whole, but rather through the elimination of the lower orders by their absorption into the middle-class, whose values become the values of utopia. In this context, it becomes less surprising that the process of production is nowhere shown; while it may be described at great length, what is dramatized is very much the stuff of the traditional utopia: a life of leisure, plenty, innocence, and securitya life in many respects more paradisaical than any encountered in the utopias of the Renaissance. There remains the question of how the narrator gets to utopia. As we have seen, Looking Backward shares the reticence of the Renaissance utopia regarding the origins of utopian society; where it differs is in the nature of the compensatory elaboration which the text exhibits. Where the Renaissance utopia offers a wealth of often suggestive geographical detail in place of the historical specification which it evades, the basic narrative premise of Looking Backward renders this particular kind of displacement more difficult. Locating utopia elsewhere in time rather than in space clearly demands a little more by way of narrative explanation than is afforded by Mores prepositional phrase or Campanellas few impatient lines. Nevertheless, the account which Bellamy provides goes so far beyond

84

NARRATING UTOPIA

what might be seen as necessary to secure the readers willing suspension of disbelief, particularly when its lavish detail is contrasted to the perfunctory treatment given to utopias historical origins, that it is hard not to see it, again, as precisely a metaphor of transitiona narrative in which the psychological, rather than historical origins of utopia are encoded. To reach utopia, as we have seen, the narrator falls asleep, awakening in the year 2000 after a slumber of one hundred and thirteen yearsduring which time the construction of utopia has conveniently been taken care of. Nevertheless, this still leaves the cause of this spectacular case of oversleeping to be accounted for. In his former, non-utopian existence, it transpires that the narrator suffered from insomnia, a problem he sought to palliate by a number of precautions whose abnormality is not entirely concealed by the matter-of-fact tone in which they are related. Unable to sleep in an upstairs room due to the noise of the city, he has a sleeping chamber specially constructed beneath the foundations of his house: to this subterranean room no murmur from the upper world ever penetrated. When I had entered it and closed the door I was surrounded by the silence of the tomb. In order to prevent the dampness of the subsoil from penetrating the chamber, the walls had been laid in hydraulic cement and were very thick, and the floor was likewise protected. In order that the room might serve also as a vault equally proof against violence and flames, for the storage of valuables, I had roofed it with stone slabs hermetically sealed, and the outer door was of iron with a thick coating of asbestos. A small pipe, communicating with a windmill on the top of the house, insured the renewal of air. [p.10] Yet what is perhaps most striking about these quite obsessional provisions for a good nights sleepso reasonable in their every detail, so utterly bizarre when taken as a wholeis that they dont work! It might seem that the tenant of such a chamber ought to be able to command slumber, but it was rare that I slept well, even there, two nights in succession. So accustomed was I to wakefulness that I minded little the loss of one nights rest. A second night, however, spent in my reading chair instead of my bed, tired me out, and I never allowed myself to go longer than that without slumber If after two sleepless nights I found myself on the approach of the third without sensations of drowsiness, I called in Dr. Pillsbury. [p.10] Dr Pillsbury, it turns out, is a Professor of Animal Magnetismor in other words, a hypnotist.

BELLAMY AND WELLS

85

To cut a long story short, the narrator goes to visit his fiance, who, concerned at his having gone two nights without sleep, sends him home at nine oclock sharp, with strict orders to go to bed at once (p.9). Dr Pillsbury is summoned, and puts him into a hypnotic trance. During the night the house burns down (leaving, however, the cement-encased, hermetically sealed, asbestos-coated sleeping chamber unharmed), and the narrator remains entranced until the year 2000, when his subterranean refuge is finally excavated in preparation for the construction of, of all things, a laboratory. Considered in its purely functional aspect, as a plot mechanism for the transference of the narrator to the utopian future, it is a scenario which goes so far beyond the minimum demands of narrative plausibility as to prompt a number of questions as to its deeper significance. What are the implications of the narrators inability to sleep, for example? Or of the bizarre measures he takes to counter his insomnia? While Bellamys chief concern in Looking Backward is surely the exposition of a rational alternative to existing society, it seems curious to find this surrounded by narrative trappings more reminiscent of the world of Edgar Allan Poe. Here, as in Poe, we encounter hermetically sealed subterranean chambers: Julian Wests sleeping quarters seem like a lineal descendant of the coppersheathed vault that lies far beneath the bedroom of the narrator in The Fall of the House of Usher. There is the same fascination with hypnosis, with its capacity to render the individual passive, open to suggestion, deprived of agency. The distinction between dream and reality is deliberately blurred, as in so many of Poes tales: the utopia to which the narrator awakens seems at first like a dream, but proves a reality; while in a subsequent nightmare he returns to his own past, only to find that its hallucinatory vividness is mercifully an illusion. And there is even the same confusion of the roles of lover and mother. The narrators fiance sends him to bed early, like a little boy (and to a bedroom which seems more like a tomb), and her maternal role is promptly taken over in utopia by her great-granddaughter, who turns out to be Edith Leete. Nor is this the only feature of the narrators previous existence to reproduce itself in utopia. The hypnotist of 1887, Dr Pillsbury, finds a utopian equivalent in Dr Leete, whose medical treatment of the bewildered narrator consists largely of giving him sleeping draughts, and whose discourse holds him virtually mesmerized for the remainder of the book. While utopia is only a dream in 1887, by the year 2000 it is the past, as we have seen, that is a figment of the imagination. Even the process of the narrators emergence into utopia (as if the initial metaphor of transition were not enough) is re-enacted, not once, but twice. On the first occasion, Julian West, lonely and depressed despite all that utopia has to offer, returns

86

NARRATING UTOPIA

to his subterranean chamber: This, I muttered to myself, is the only home I have. Let me stay here, and not go forth any more (p.165). But he is rescued from this fit of self-pity by Edith, who appears at the door, having followed him there. He goes to meet her, and a short conversation discloses their mutual love. It turns out, in fact, that Edith had already known of the narrator, having read his love-letters to her greatgrandmother, and become fascinated by him. Discovering his identity from a locket of her great-grandmother which he had worn on his breast during his long sleep, she already feels a maternal solicitude for him before he awakesor is reborninto utopia. Now, on his second emergence from the womb-like chamber, it is to find mother and lover innocently united into one, his for the asking. Amid all the rational features of Bellamys utopia, its carefully thought-out legal, social, and economic provisions, there is the promise of guilt-free oedipal gratification.14 Yet even this is not the last occasion on which the transition to utopia is re-enacted. Shortly after, although enchanted by his new-found love, Julian West suffers a recurrence of his sleeping problems, and when he finally does fall asleep, it is only to suffer an extended nightmare of waking back in his old world. So vivid is the nightmare, in fact, that it is only with the utmost difficulty that he succeeds in arousing himself from it: Tears poured from my eyes. In my vehemence I became inarticulate. I panted, I sobbed, I groaned, and immediately afterward found myself sitting upright in my bed in my room in Dr. Leetes house, and the morning sun shining through the open window into my eyes. I was gasping. The tears were streaming down my face, and I quivered in every nerve. [p.185] While Bellamy asserts that the emergence of his more perfect society was smooth, inevitable, untroubled by violence or even opposition, it is clear that the transition to utopia is by no means as free from trauma as he might wish it to appear. In the narrators anguish and hysteria are surely signs that the birth pangs of the new society have been displaced and given a fictional embodiment elsewhere. It would appear, then, that Bellamys attempt to recast the traditional utopian paradigm in the light of more recent narrative practice causes at least as many problems as it resolves. In the gaps that emerge between the traditional description of the more perfect society and the more novelistic attempt to dramatize its workings, between what is told and what is shown, the familiar contradictions and disjunctures that characterize the Renaissance utopia become all the more apparent; while the narrative trappings that surround the outline of utopian societythe elements of futuristic fantasy, the gestures towards a fuller characterization of

BELLAMY AND WELLS

87

individualsonly serve to render more evident the psychological underpinnings of the utopian dream.15 At the same time, many of the features most typical of the Renaissance utopia persist. The womb-like topography of Utopia is reproduced in Bellamys description of the narrators sleeping quarters; there is the familiar reluctance to deal with utopias origins, or indeed with history in any form; and there is a similar rationalization of the essentially paradisaical dream of long life, leisure, freedom from guilt, and total security. Taking this along with the ambivalence of Bellamys presentation of the role of women, whose ostensibly enhanced freedom seems scarcely compatible with their effective status as commodities in a society no less male-dominated than the authors own, and it begins to appear that the constraints of the traditional narrative paradigm are more difficult to escape than might be imagined. Andrew Delbanco describes Looking Backward as both progressive in its politics and conservative in its artistic strategy (p.xi), yet not the least striking feature of Bellamys utopia is the extent to which it reproduces not simply the narrative form, but much of the authoritarian character of its Renaissance predecessors. Less, rather than more democratic than the society to which it proposes an alternative, its militaristic social organization is accompanied by the traditional emphasis on universal surveillance to ensure that utopian ideals are adhered to: one of the ways in which industrial efficiency is maintained, for instance, is through a system of quality control so stringent that any flaw in a specific product can be traced back to the individual worker responsible for it. Which raises anew the issue of the extent to which a works narrative form and ideological implications are in fact related. As we have seen, Bammer argues that as texts in which an oppositional impulse is embedded in an essentially conservative form, utopias are generically ambiguous (p.45) and in the case of Looking Backward that ambiguity prompts one to question whether progressive politics are in fact reconcilable with a conservative artistic strategy, or whether the authoritarian tendency of the Renaissance utopia is not actually inherent in the narrative paradigm in which it is embodied. Here the considerably more sophisticated narrative practice of H.G. Wellsto whom the progressive label is also often appliedis instructive. Unlike Bellamy, whose other fictional efforts are now largely forgotten,16 Wells reveals in his non-utopian fiction a mastery of a variety of narrative modes, ranging from realism, through social satire, to speculative fantasy. Well aware, as we have seen, of the problems which writing utopian fiction poses, his attempts to resolve them exhibit a correspondingly greater narrative resourcefulness. Thus, while the same basic narrative paradigm a journey, followed by a relation of the wonders of utopiastill lies at the

88

NARRATING UTOPIA

heart of A Modern Utopia (1905), In the Days of the Comet (1906), and Men Like Gods (1923), each represents a different approach to the problem of creating a utopia that is not static but kinetic (A Modern Utopia, p.5), and where the blood and warmth and reality of life (p.9) are no longer absent. H.G. Wells and Utopian Narrative Of the three examples under discussion, A Modern Utopia is the most ambitiousboth the most comprehensive in its outline of a more perfect society, and the most radical in its narrative experimentation. Rejecting both the form of the argumentative essay (p.xxxi) and the vulgar appetite for stark stories (p.xxxii), Wells creates instead a complex hybrid, in which both a fictional narrative and essayistic speculation are contained within multiple framing narratives in which, as in Mores Utopia, the voices of author and narrator are carefully distinguished. In the fictional narrative, the narrator (along with his travelling companion, the rather pathetic Botanist) is holidaying in the Swiss Alps, when the two are magically translated to another worldwhich turns out to be the utopian mirror image of our own; there then follows the familiar guided tour of the more perfect society. Yet while this, taken by itself, may seem little different from the traditional paradigm, the fictional narrative is interspersed with extended passages where the storyline is abandoned altogether in favour of something closer to a speculative treatise on the nature of utopia. Here, acknowledging the difficulty of successfully imagining a social order radically different from the one by which we have ourselves been conditioned, Wells attempts to present, not the traditional account of an already established utopia, but rather a carefully phrased and rather tentative exploration of the form it might take. Instead of the confident present tense in which the Renaissance utopia is described, Wells resorts to the uncertainties of the subjunctive mood or future tense. There is frequent recourse to formations such as Let us suppose, or In utopia we should , which further reinforce the works speculative character; while on occasions Wells deliberately employs frame-breaking devices apparently designed to undermine the fictional illusion altogether: The whole world will surely have a common language, that is quite elementarily Utopian, and since we are free of the trammels of convincing story-telling, we may suppose that language to be sufficiently our own to understand. [p.17] In Men Like Gods, the traditional paradigm is more clearly evident, with the central character, Mr Barnstaple, fulfilling the conventional role of the visitor to utopia. Driving off on his holidays, he is abruptly whisked into a

BELLAMY AND WELLS

89

parallel, utopian universeto whose wonders he is then introduced in the customary detail. Here Wells relies on a rather different kind of fictional sleight-of-hand, trusting to his skill as a satirist to distract attention from problems inherent in the depiction of a more perfect society. Mr Barnstaples fate, it turns out, is shared by a group of other motorists, which includes, among others, recognizable caricatures of Arthur Balfour, Lord Beaverbrook, and Winston Churchilland it is in contrast to their antics that the virtues of utopian society are allowed to appear. Given the way that the existing ruling class behave, Wells seems to be saying, is not even the almost inhuman calm of utopia preferable? In the Days of the Comet takes yet another tack, preparing the way for a relatively brief vision of utopia with a lengthy realistic account of the life of petty oppression and tormenting sexual jealousy experienced by the narrator prior to its advent (here occasioned by a passing comet, which releases a gas that transforms human nature). Whether any of these solutions is entirely successful, however, remains debatable. A Modern Utopia, in particular, has been widely praised for its success in avoiding many of the pitfalls of the traditional utopia,17 yet while Wells is clearly aware of the problematic character of utopian narrative, the paradigm embedded in each of the works under discussion is by no means the only traditional feature that is reproduced. Just as in Looking Backward, for example, the preoccupation with military attributes resurfaces even in a worldwide utopia without enemies. In Men Like Gods, such narrative suspense as exists resides in the armed conflict between the utopians and the party of the Churchillian Rupert Catskill, and Wells appears to derive considerable vicarious satisfaction from the spectacle of the latters helplessness in the face of the utopians vastly superior technological resources. In the Days of the Comet, while its final section sets out to depict the construction of the new utopian world-order, focuses as much on the vast exultant dust of house-breaking (p.200) which accompanies the wholesale destruction of London, Philadelphia, Chicago, and even Edinburgh that precedes itnot to mention the Year of Tents, when humanity lives in a vast encampment while demolishing the cities of the past and building those of the future. Yet it is A Modern Utopia, for all its attempts to circumvent the prescriptive character of the conventional utopia, that is perhaps most interesting in this regard. While Wells elsewhere describes his utopian ideal as a scientifically organized classless society,18 here there is envisaged a ruling lite called, tellingly, the samuraia name whose warlike connotations seem strangely at odds with the otherwise pacific tenor of the utopian society described in the text. The samurai are explicitly compared to Platos guardians, and are elsewhere referred to as a voluntary nobility (p.259). Becoming a member of this

90

NARRATING UTOPIA

lite involves passing a competitive examination, meditation, physical fitness, and a variety of rather oddly-assorted ascetic practices, which include bathing in cold water, and sleeping alone at least four nights in five (p.297). In return, they receive a number of privileges, including the right to wear a distinctive uniform, sole access to the careers of lawyer, doctor, and public administrator, and the right to votea right denied the rest of the population. There are also certain restrictions: members of the samurai class may not act on stage, perform menial tasks such as waiting, barbering, and so forth, and are forbidden either to play or watch competitive sportswhich Wells appears to regard as little more than ignoble spectacles for the degenerate masses. The bias of Wellss vision, in other words, is very much akin to that of Bellamys: once again, we find a utopian society substantially less democratic than that to which it offers an alternative, and (for all its talk of a voluntary nobility) representing an ideal that is fundamentallyas Wells himself admitted19that of the educated middle class, albeit a middle class not averse to strong government and firm treatment of undesirables. If poverty and oppression are to be eliminated, it is once again primarily because of the offence they give to societys cultured upper echelons. Even in the extreme case of slavery, we are told that the true objection is not that it is unjust to the inferior but that it corrupts the superior (p.337)! If inequality in society is to be remedied, it will be through a levelling-up process, ultimately brought about not so much by political or economic reform as by selective breeding. In Men Like Gods, as in Looking Backward, it would appear that the removal of barriers to the unhindered operation of love is sufficient to achieve the desired end. Socially undesirable qualities, such as indolence, are steadily being bred out of humanity, since their possessors will neither find lovers nor bear children, because no one in Utopia loves those who have neither energy nor distinction. There is much pride of the mate in Utopian love (p.64). In A Modern Utopia, however, the mechanisms of selective breeding are far more explicitly set out: in its initial stages, we are told, utopian society will retain a class systemthe difference being that it will be biologically based, rather than socially constructed.20 This will consist of four classes, labelled (with Fourier-like arbitrariness) the poietic, the kinetic, the base, and the dull: a structure which Frye describes as like an uncharitable version of the four Indian castes (1967, p.35).21 What is clear, however, is that the long-term goal of utopian eugenics is to move towards a classless society by the elimination of the latter twowhich will be achieved primarily by the provision that it will be necessary to reach certain pre-set earning levels in order to prove ones fitness to have children. Thus, while in the short term society will have to take into account the flaws and

BELLAMY AND WELLS

91

limitations of fallen humanity, in the long run the necessity for most laws, restrictions, and regulations will be eliminated by the evolution of a superior racethe cleaned and perfected humanity of Men Like Godsin comparison with whom even the best representatives of our world (Mr Barnstaple, for example, or the narrator of A Modern Utopia) will feel hopelessly inferior. Where Wells differs from Bellamy, at least at first sight (and still more so from the utopian writers of the Renaissance), is in his representation of the role of women in utopian society. While Bellamy, in direct contradiction of what he asserts to be the norms of his future society, only actually portrays women in stereotypically passive roles, Wells does not hesitate to show women in a markedly non-traditional light. We see women in A Modern Utopia as leaders and administrators, as scientists and inventors in Men Like Gods; while in In the Days of the Comet (where much the most complex and interesting character, Nettie, is female) it is a woman who most clearly articulates the sexual politics of the new utopia. Yet once again, there are some striking contradictions: as in Looking Backward, there is a telling gap between what we are told and what we are shownalthough in Wellss case it is the former that undermines the latter. In A Modern Utopia, for instance, the effect of Wellss attempt at a radical reassessment of societys sexual institutions is often to reinscribe, often more overtly, the assumptions that underlie them. As in his utopian revision of the class system, Wellss account of gender relations serves primarily to reinstate existing structures of domination by naturalizing themgiving them a biological, rather than socially constructed foundation. For example, in the context of what purports to be an argument in favour of liberating women from social discrimination, we are told that: It is a fact that almost every point in which a woman differs from a man is an economic disadvantage to her, her incapacity for great stresses of exertion, her frequent liability to slight illnesses, her weaker initiative, her inferior invention and resourcefulness, her relative incapacity for organization and combination, and the possibility of emotional complications whenever she is in economic dependence on men. [p.187] Nor does Wells end there: women with children in the modern utopia would be forbidden to work unless they are in a position to employ qualified efficient substitutes to take care of their offspring (p.188)child care apparently being naturally a womans taskwhile as the producers of children, who constitute the future of the species, they are subject to more severe moral restraints. Given that only the fittest are allowed to breed, we are told, logic dictates that one unavoidable condition of

92

NARRATING UTOPIA

the utopian marriage contract will be the chastity of the wife (p.194): Her infidelity being demonstrated, must at once terminate the marriage and release both her husband and the State from any liability for the support of her illegitimate offspring. That, at any rate, is beyond controversy It will be obvious that under Utopian conditions it is the State that will suffer injury by a wifes misconduct, and that a husband who condones anything of the sort will participate in her offence. A woman, therefore, who is divorced on this account will be divorced as a public offender, and not in the key of a personal quarrel; not as one who has inflicted a private and personal wrong. [p.194] Even in the non-utopian world, it would be hard to imagine a more explicit statement of the sexual double standardparticularly given the subsequent declaration that a reciprocal restraint on the part of the husband is clearly of no importance whatever (p.195). As in The City of the Sun, the project of total social transformation is undermined by a fundamental contradictionthe fact that it is an embodiment of specifically male desire. Wellss utopia not only frees men from sexual guilt regarding their own conduct: it also reassures them that womens sexual fidelity is an objective social requirement. Once again, the effect of utopian logic is to unmask the essential identity between its premises and those of the patriarchal order to which it proposes an ostensible alternative. Such contradictions, like those evident in the utopias of Campanella and Bellamy, are perhaps unsurprising in view of the tension inevitably inherent in the traditional utopian project of recreating maternal security through the imposition of a masculine order. In Wellss case, however, they are symptomatic of a broader ambivalencean ambivalence strongly reminiscent of that which Kolodny points to as characteristic of the discovery narrative. On the one hand, the utopian longing for maternal security is repeatedly reflected in passages which suggests a strong attraction to the idea of returning to a childlike passive dependence on the mother. In In the Days of the Comet, for example, the narrator, despairing over his loss of Nettie and the death of his mother, finds unexpected solace in the arms of Anna, who has nursed his mother through her final illness. A miserable attraction (p.243) draws him back for a last look at his mother, and he finds Anna at the bedside: Willie, she whispered, and eyes and body seemed incarnate pity. An unseen presence drew us together. My mothers face became resolute, commanding. I turned to Anna as a child may turn to its nurse. I put my hands on her strong shoulders, she folded me to her,

BELLAMY AND WELLS

93

and my heart gave way. I buried my face in her breast and clung to her weakly, and burst into a passion of weeping She held me with hungry arms. She whispered to me, There, there! as one whispers comfort to a child [p.244] As in Looking Backward, the line between mother and lover becomes blurred: they marry, and within a year she has borne him a son. Coming as it does in the midst of the turmoil of demolition and construction attending the birth of the new utopian order, the implications of the passage are hard to ignore. It is as though the birth pangs of the new society find a psychological equivalent in the narrators temporary return to infantile dependency, swiftly followed by the reassertion of male authority: the motherly Anna is given [him] in marriage (p.244) and bears him a son. A similar instance of temporary regression occurs in Men Like Gods, when Mr Barnstaple escapes from the castle where he has been immured with the other Earthlingseffectively choosing utopia in preference to their efforts to assert the old order. At the very moment that he sees the castle blasted out of existence, he collapses unconscious, awakening to find himself back among the utopians: Then people had stood about him and talked about him. He remembered their feet. He must have been lying on his face with his face very close to the ground. Then they had turned him over, and the light of the rising sun had been blinding in his eyes. Two gentle goddesses had given him some restorative in a gorge at the foot of high cliffs. He had been carried in a womans arms as a child is carried. [p.180] Yet while such passages speak powerfully of a yearning to be restored to the lost mother, to experience a form of rebirth in the arms of a stronger and more capable woman, Wells elsewhere seems to react strongly against this impulse. Underlying the passion for order which characterizes all Wellss utopian writings there is often evident a distaste for weakness which goes so far as to include a suspicion of any form of emotion which might soften the hard, clean lines of the utopian vision. In Men Like Gods, for instance, it is suggested that while the Utopians still experience love, it is no longer the same emotion as that experienced in our imperfect world: And they loved no doubtsubtly and deliciouslybut perhaps a little hardly. Perhaps in those distant plains there was not much pity nor tenderness. Bright and lovely beings they werein no way pitiful. There would be no need for those qualities [p.127] The stereotypically feminine qualities of pity and tenderness are disavowed, and due to their absence the terrestrial visitor finds himself

94

NARRATING UTOPIA

sadly neglected, since there is little about him to interest the superior beings who surround him. Yet when one Utopian, Lychnis, does take an interest in him after his spell of childlike dependence, Mr Barnstaple shies away from her sympathy. He begins to see her as a lingering romantic type, as one of Utopias failures (p.204), whose dark sacrificial disposition is surely evidence of some underlying racial taint something that Utopia was still breeding out (p.205). She represents the persistence of all that Utopia is seeking to outgrow: even after a short stay, Mr Barnstaple comes to the conclusion that he was a better Utopian than she was (p.205). All that is most motherly about her now seems to him distasteful, and as if to underscore the threat she represents to his aspirations to grow into someone worthy of utopia, Wells even provides the quite gratuitous detail that she was responsible for the deaths of her own two sons: She had had two children whom she had loved passionately. They were adorably fearless, and out of foolish pride she had urged them to swim out to sea and they had been taken by a current and drowned. Their father had been drowned in attempting their rescue and Lychnis had very nearly shared their fate. [p.204] The mother, whose allure is so powerfully portrayed elsewhere, is ultimately a danger to be resisted. In a particularly telling formulation, given the extent to which utopias may be seen as opening up space for the play of desire, she is described as filling more than her legitimate space in the Utopian spectacle. She lay across it like a shadow (p.205). In In the Days of the Comet the desire for the reassertion of male authority in the face of what is represented as female entrapment is still more apparent. Following the magical transformation of human nature by the vapours unleashed by a comet, the narrators personal transition from the old, imperfect world into the new, utopian one is significantly accompanied by the symbolic displacement of Nettie, the female who embodies all the disorder in his life (and whose name, one feels, is hardly coincidental), by Melmount (Male-mount?), the male epitome of order and control. His last memory before the comet descends is of pursuing Nettie, revolver in hand, through the thickening mist; when he awakens from the sleep into which the entire world has been plunged, the symbolically phallic pistol discarded,22 the first person he encounters is the famous politicianwhose appearance, he declares, he will remember to his dying day: I believe, for instance, I could match the fur upon the collar of his great motoring coat now, could paint the dull red tinge of his big cheek with his fair eyelashes just catching the light and showing beyond. His hat was off, his dome-shaped head, with its smooth hair

BELLAMY AND WELLS

95

between red and extreme fairness, was bent forward in scrutiny of his twisted foot. His back seemed enormous. And there was something about the mere massive sight of him that filled me with liking. [p.161] Yet there is more involved than simple liking: indeed, one of the very first new, utopian perceptions of which the narrator becomes aware is the fact that: without servility or any insincerity whatever, as if it were a first fruit of the Change, I found myself in the presence of a human being towards whom I perceived myself inferior and subordinate, before whom I stood without servility or any insincerity whatever, in an attitude of respect and attention. [p.165] While the longing for maternal security is always represented in an ambiguous light, as a desire to which surrender can never be more than temporary, no such reservations attend the acknowledgement of the authority of this archetypal father-figurewhich is further emphasized by the quasi-biblical language in which it is articulated.23 In A Modern Utopia, leaving aside the peculiarities of the Utopian marriage contract, the reaction against the feminine manifests itself rather differently, in a broader distaste for sexuality in general. The appeal of the samurais sexual abstinence is emphasized by the description of the narrators Utopian alter egothe person he would have been in Utopia: a samurai, unsurprisingly, his self-discipline is reflected in his appearance as taller, more youthful, sounder looking (p.247). Of course, his physical and mental superiority are not merely the product of his spending four out of five nights sleeping alone, but one feels that this is not the least of the facets of his life which the narrator enviesespecially given his earlier eulogy of the cleanliness of the Utopian bedroom, which contrasts starkly with the ftid disorder of many an earthly bedroom after a nights use (p.105). Physical, or indeed emotional involvement, insofar as it is portrayed at all, is seen as messy, self-indulgent: the bright, clean, unsentimental love of Men Like Gods is clearly foreshadowed. Indeed, part of the appeal of Utopia for the narrator is that it will clearly have no place for people like his travelling-companion, the Botanist, for whose love-affair he shows undisguised contempt. So far as the Botanist serves a narrative purpose, it is largely to illustrate most of the flaws which a utopian society will eliminateemotional indulgence clearly being one of them. Yet it is not merely the inadequacies of the Botanists love life that are significant: why, one wonders, of all possible professions, does Wells make the narrators travelling companion a botanist? A botanist is, in effect, a classifier of natureand as such represents the virtual antithesis of the

96

NARRATING UTOPIA

Wellsian attitude towards it, which involves not so much accepting and describing nature as it exists, but rather taking control of and transforming it. And it is this aggressive imposition of order on the natural world that is one of the most distinctive features of Wellss utopian vision. Where the Renaissance utopias describe societies sufficiently rationally organized as to offer their citizens a large measure of protection from natural disasters such as famine and disease, Wells proposes a far more radical policy of intervention.24 In part, of course, this is simply a reflection of the very different historical context in which he was writingof the fact that his was a world where the transformation of the natural environment by human technology was now an established fact. Nevertheless, it may be argued that, even by early twentieth century standards, Wellss vision of just how far human dominion over nature might be carried is an extravagant one.25 In Men Like Gods, for examplethe most extreme of Wellss utopian projectionsit appears that nature has been almost wholly domesticated. Human health and hygiene have been improved by the elimination of virtually all disease-carrying insects, all rats and mice, and even the untidier sorts of small bird (p.122). To be fair, most of the human pollution of the environment has been eliminated as well (a process vividly described in In the Days of the Comet), but this appears to be more a matter of human convenience than of environmental concern. In essence, Wellss utopian vision is of a natural environment entirely controlled by and at the service of humanity. Insects are largely eliminated, as are such big annoyances (p.73) as the wolf and hyena. Trees and plants have been hybridized: trained and bred to make new and unprecedented secretions, waxes, gums, essential oils and the like, of the most desirable quality (p.73). Indeed, one of the first and most striking indications of the extent to which the utopian society depicted in Men Like Gods differs is the appearance of a tame leopard (which subsequently dies of an infection it catches from Wellss fictional portrait of Winston Churchill), and it later becomes clear that this is merely one product of a much larger-scale befriending and taming of big animals (p.73): the larger carnivora, combed and cleaned, reduced to a milk dietary, emasculated in spirit and altogether becatted, were pets and ornaments in Utopia. The almost extinct elephant had increased again and Utopia had saved her giraffes. The brown bear had always been disposed to sweets and vegetarianism and had greatly improved in intelligence. The dog had given up barking and was comparatively rare. [pp.734] With its beautifully manicured landscapes, in which human and beast

BELLAMY AND WELLS

97

peacefully co-exist, the utopia described in Men Like Gods possesses a decidedly Edenic character. Yet it is, once again, very much an Eden recreated on rational principles, with man firmly in control, manipulating nature to suit his own convenience. And while Mr Barnstaple consciously alludes to that first garden, remarking that it was a good invention to say that man was created a gardener (p.74), he also describes the utopian reduction of wild animals to the status of harmless pets as a process of revision and editing (p.74)an intriguing metaphor, with its implicit comparison of nature to a provisional and still fluid draft which only utopia can transform into the static finality of the completed text. Nature, whose power over humanity the Renaissance utopia sought primarily to mitigate, is here transformed into the ultimate colony, entirely subject to human command. The desire to impose order on nature, however, constitutes only one aspect of a larger dream of order: Wellss utopias, like their predecessors, are in essence patterns for human existencefor the best, but also the most efficient mechanisms of social control. And in this respect, Wellss utopias are if possible still more regimented than Bellamys future Boston. While the measures outlined in Looking Backward to ensure individual adherence to the utopian ideal are far-reaching enough, Wells goes still further. Even in Men Like Gods, where formal government as such scarcely seems to exist, there is complete knowledge of the whereabouts of every soul upon the planet (p.193): everyone, we are told (in another literary metaphor) is indexed and noted (p.193). In A Modern Utopia the efficient functioning of utopian society relies heavily on the central card index which records the identity and whereabouts of every citizen of the world staterather as if its members were so many books in an enormous library. In this index are recorded the name, location, and thumbprint of each individual, while, in tribute to the distinctive qualities of the French intellect, the privilege of housing it is given to Paris. Yet while this may seem a bureaucratic nightmarethe kind of thing routinely parodied in any number of dystopian fictions, from Zamyatins We onthe detail of the thumbprint is revealing, given its implications concerning Wellss conception, not just of utopia, but of human nature. Utopia, for Wells, embodies an ideal, rational orderplanned, centralized, and secure from disruptive forcesand to maintain it, his utopian state seeks to control its citizens by the very fact of their individuality, the distinguishing characteristics that separate them from the rest of their fellows. To an even greater extent than in Bellamys utopia, there is a notable absence of structures which might mediate between the individual and the monolithic State: no unions or corporations, no parties, guilds, societies, or autonomous institutions of any kind. There is only the

98

NARRATING UTOPIA

individual and the State, and it is hardly coincidental that Wells should choose, as the distinctive hallmark of individuality, a featurethe thumbprintat the very time that fingerprinting was becoming established as a definitive method of determining the unique identity of the criminal. As in so many earlier utopias, the underlying implication is that humanity remains tainted by Original Sinand while this is explicitly denied in A Modern Utopia (p.299), the fact remains that Wellss vision is of a utopia that will curb and limit individual impulses, rather than allow individuals freedom to fulfill their desires. The overwhelming emphasis is on discipline, rather than freedom. A still more striking parallel between Wellss utopias and their Renaissance predecessors, however, is that (as in Looking Backward) there is almost no discussion of how the utopian society was createdan omission perhaps understandable in the Renaissance, but considerably less so in an era where there had been so many examples of radical social and political change. In A Modern Utopia, for instance, while its initial premise is that the society described is a utopian mirror-image of the narrators own that every man, woman, and child alive has a Utopian parallel (p.24)26this assertion is subsequently modified to the point of outright contradiction by the narrators admission that such a utopia could only have emerged from a wholly different utopian history. He then goes on to posit a world with a radically different history, in which a utopian tendency had always been apparent: a world in which Jesus Christ had been born into a liberal and progressive Roman Empire that spread from the Arctic Ocean to the Bight of Benin, and was to know no Decline and Fall, and Mahomet, instead of embodying the dense prejudices of Arab ignorance, opened his eyes upon an intellectual horizon already nearly as wide as the world. [p.260] For utopia to exist, in other words, it must already have existed: even while Wells attempts to imagine a society capable of change, he severs its link with the world which utopia proposes to alter for the betterhis own. In Men Like Gods, there is some talk of the utopian society having its roots in an Age of Confusion clearly akin to the world of Wellss own day, but once again (although an entire chapter is ostensibly devoted to it) there is a singular absence of detailed information regarding how utopia emerged from such chaotic origins. We learn that very slowly Utopia had evolved its present harmony of law and custom and education (p.190), and that as light grew and intelligence spread they [lawyers and politicians] became more and more evidently unnecessary (p.202)but the actual process involved is never discussed in any concrete detail. Much as in Bellamys

BELLAMY AND WELLS

99

utopia, history is a largely automatic affair, in which the truths of utopia become so self-evident that resistance to them is unthinkable: the old order simply withers away. Even in In the Days of the Comet, where the construction of utopia is portrayed, it is only made possible by the fantastic premise of a fundamental change in the nature of the human material of which utopia is comprised: after the descent of the comet, and the release of the green vapours, everyone suddenly sees reason, and nothing is ever the same again. Such fantastic narrative devices, like the mirror-image world of A Modern Utopia, or the parallel universe posited in Men Like Gods (not to mention the century-long sleep of Julian West in Looking Backward), are of course a reflection of the changed context in which Wells was writingone in which the traditional remote utopian locale, somewhere in the southern hemisphere, was no longer available. Yet even so, the fantastic methods whereby Wells effects the visitors transition to utopia have some curiously traditional features. As has already been remarked, both A Modern Utopia and Men Like Gods begin with the visitor going on holidayan activity which in a sense constitutes the modern version of the process of exploration described in the travel narratives on which the Renaissance utopia was modelled. Where in Mores time the traveller might well be an explorer, by Wellss day exploration has given way to vacationand in this respect the narrator of A Modern Utopia and Mr Barnstaple in Men Like Gods (even his name is that of a popular holiday destination in south-west England) may be seen as travellers just as representative of their age as were Hythloday and the Genoese mariner in the days of More or Campanella. (Even in In the Days of the Comet, the actual transition to utopia takes place while the narrator is at a seaside resort.) Nor do the echoes of the Renaissance discovery narrative and its utopian analogue end there. In Men Like Gods, Mr Barnstaple sets out on holiday, fleeing, not from the depredations of the Tartars, but rather from the tyranny of his wife and his employerand finds himself, despite his original intention of driving north to the Lake District, forced by roadworks to turn (in the best utopian tradition) south and west. A Modern Utopia likewise begins with a descent: seated at their picnic lunch high on the Piz Lucendro, gazing south at the landscape far below, the narrator and his companion are suddenly transported to their own worlds mirror-image, and then make their way down into the utopian counterpart of Switzerland. (Given Wellss passion for order and cleanliness, his choice of Switzerland as starting-point for a tour of utopia is hardly surprising.) There are even hazards associated with the process of transition: Arden and Greenlake, the pastorally named pioneers of contact between parallel universes in Men Like Gods, are both killed during their experiments, and there are numerous

100

NARRATING UTOPIA

fatalities during the universal sleep that precedes the worlds utopian awakening in In the Days of the Comet. In most respects, however, just as holidays are in general safer than voyages of exploration, the utopias of both Bellamy and Wells seem significantly tamer than those of their Renaissance predecessors. Indeed, judging by some of their salient features, it would appear that, if the travellers tale offered a narrative model for the Renaissance utopia, a more appropriate intertext to the utopias of Bellamy and Wells might be provided by the modern holiday brochure. Like the modern tourist, the utopian visitor of Bellamy and Wells is offered a guided tour of an unfamiliar world and, also like the modern tourist, generally adopts a passive, spectatorial role. Where the visitor is better off, however, is in that, unlike the average tourist, he has no complaints about the food or hygiene. Everything in utopia is clean, of good quality, and easily accessible by modern methods of transportation. Waiters are polite, the inhabitants are fit and sun-tanned, and everyone speaks perfect English. (In Men Like Gods this effect is produced by telepathic activation of the brains speech centres: when a utopian concept proves too advanced, the visitor suffers the temporary illusion that he has gone deaf.) Wells, in particular, makes much of the physical superiority of the Utopians to their terrestrial counterparts: in A Modern Utopia the more perfect society has succeeded in eliminating baldness; while in Men Like Gods, Mr Barnstaple discovers on his return home that he has grown nearly three inches during his utopian vacation. The image of perfect physical specimens disporting themselves in idealized surroundings, of course, is now a familiar one. As in life, so in the realm of the imagination: just as in the real world exploration paved the way for colonization, so the territory opened up by utopian imaginings has been seized upon with glee by the modern advertising industry. Part of the tourist brochures seductive allure lies in its implication that a utopian existence (if only for two weeks) is not only desirable, but possible. Utopian images, in other words, can be used not only to arouse the desire for things to be otherwise, but also to contain it: as Bloch suggests, the commercialization of such images still allows for dreams, yet it still rations them, even in more distant excursions to the over-blue coast of the travel agents and beyond: so that they do not explode the given world (1986, p.34). What Bammer refers to as commodified dreams become tools with which to keep deeper and politically more destabilizing dissatisfactions in check (p.44). The utopian dream, however radical its underlying impulse, is always in danger of being co-opted.27 Yet even when not in so debased a formin the form, that is, of utopian fictionit is clear that the utopian dream often ends up reinscribing many of the values of the society that it seeks to challenge. As we have seen, even given the most genuine desire for radical social change, for progressive

BELLAMY AND WELLS

101

values, for kinetic rather than static social formations, utopian fiction all too often presents an alternative order that remains static, authoritarian, and characterized by many of the most oppressive features of the writers own society. The precise extent to which this is determined by the narrative form in which the utopian vision is expressed is, of course, difficult to determine; nevertheless, it would seem clear that there are certain features inherent in the traditional narrative paradigm that are particularly conducive to the expression of that vision in authoritarian terms. To begin with, while the utopian narrative paradigm derives in part from the model of the classical dialogue, that model is, as Bakhtin observes, often profoundly un-dialogic. With the exception of Mores Utopia, where there is genuine debate and interaction between differing viewpoints, the tenor of most utopian dialogue is essentially monologic. The relation of the Knight Hospitaller to the Genoese mariner, of Julian West to Dr Leete, of Mr Barnstaple to a variety of utopian mentors, and even of the narrator in A Modern Utopia to his utopian alter ego is essentially similar: each involves the passive reception by the one of the authoritative utterance of the other. Even the questions that are asked, even such reservations as are expressed function primarily as rhetorical devices, designed to elicit a further flow of authoritative discourse. And in the eager passivity of the listener (Tell me more, I beg you, pleads Campanellas Knight, tell me more (p.29)) we may see figured the ideal reader of the utopian textone whose function is, above all, to be persuaded. The unequal relationship between speaker and listener is further reinforced by the inherent dynamics of the travellers tale. Having seen utopia, Hythloday and the mariners of Campanella and Bacon know it works; having lived there, Dr Leete and Wellss various utopians are even more certain: in the face of their superior knowledge, their practical experience, the assertion of contrary points of view can hardly have much authority. (Even where criticism of utopia is allowed to appearas voiced, for example, by the Botanist and the apostle of Nature in A Modern Utopia, its inadequacy is made glaringly self-evident.) As Bellamy puts it, utopia can no more be opposed by force than by argument (p.29). Resistance is futile, as is clear from the fate of Rupert Catskill and his companions in Men Like Gods. When asserted with such unshakeable authority, it is perhaps unsurprising that even the most progressive views are liable to seem fixed, static, and authoritarian in tendency. Equally, it may be argued that the retrogressive elements in the utopian vision are also related to the narrative implications inherent in the discovery narratives on which the traditional utopia is modelled. In its Renaissance formulation, as has been demonstrated, it is by its very nature ambiguous, given that the whole process of exploration and discovery was

102

NARRATING UTOPIA

by no means unequivocally oriented to a search for what was new. Informing the early voyages of discovery was the dream of re-establishing contact with the ancient civilizations of the East, even of attaining the mythical realms of Eden and El Dorado; discovery, it might be argued, was the incidental by-product of a far more ambiguous aspiration. Little wonder, then, that utopian narratives modelled on accounts of voyages of discovery should lend themselves so easily to expression of regressive fantasies of returning to the primal security of the womb, or to the protected world of early childhood. Moreover, if the motives for the process of exploration charted in the discovery narratives of the Renaissance were ambiguous, so too were its effects. While the voyages of discovery revealed a New world, they were soon followed by a process of colonization geared primarily to the reestablishment and consolidation of the values of the Old. The radically different cultures of the Americas were suppressed or erased; the hierarchies of the Old World were imposed; the resources of the New World were used to shore up the economies of Western Europe; while at the same time the New World functioned as a valuable safety valve, a refuge not only for surplus population, but also for dissidents and malcontents who might otherwise cause trouble at home.28 What the narrative of discovery enacts, therefore, is paradoxically a process whereby the new is disclosed, yet at the same time re-covered, its space filled and its novelty neutralized as a familiar order is imposed upon it. This process, as we have seen, is parallelled in the utopias of More and Campanella, both of which articulate fantasies of the conquest and subjection of the indigene. Yet it is also re-echoed in modern rewritings of the conventional utopian paradigm. While the geographically separate locale of the Renaissance utopia may have been replaced by the future, or by a parallel universe, what is still conceived of is essentially space to be filled. For such space to be available, however, it must first be emptyor, if there are local inhabitants, they must be easily enough moulded (like the subjects of King Utopus, or Peter Martyrs naked savages) to conform to a higher purpose. Thus, when Wells suggests that no less than a planet will serve the purpose of a modern Utopia (A Modern Utopia, p.11), it is partly on the grounds that the isolation of the Renaissance utopia is no longer possible under modern conditions, yet at the same time his rationale exhibits a colonialist distrust of the Otherof the epidemic, the breeding barbarian (p.11) lurking beyond the boundaries of anything other than a world state. What is at work here (and implicitly in Looking Backward, where nation states still exist, but have all followed the pioneering example of America) is a similar belief in the necessity of colonizing all available space: despite its global extent, there is little room for difference in the modern

BELLAMY AND WELLS

103

utopia: while there may be room for a few individual eccentrics, there is none for other value systems or forms of social organization. To be different, given the evident superiority of utopia, is to be inferior, and inferiority is something which utopia ultimately seeks to eliminategenerally by means of selective breeding. (Although Wells asserts, rather alarmingly, in the midst of what is generally an argument for racial tolerance, that there is only one sane and logical thing to be done with a really inferior race, and that is to exterminate it (A Modern Utopia, p.337).) Nor is this the only parallel: another recurrent feature of modern reworkings of the traditional utopian paradigm is the representation of the erasure of what was once there. Bellamys Boston of the future retains the familiar geographical features, but scarcely a vestige of the human structures that once accompanied them (the former inhabitants are, with the exception of the narrator, all dead). In William Morriss utopian rebuttal of Bellamy, News from Nowhere, one of the chief activities of his future society is the demolition of the ugly evidences of the old order; while in Wellss In the Days of the Comet, as we have seen, the transition to utopia is accompanied by a vast exultant dust of house-breaking (p.200) as the worlds cities are summarily levelled prior to the work of utopian reconstruction. The fate of Edinburgh, Philadelphia, Chicago, as imagined by Wells, is not dissimilar to that of the great City of Mexico at the hands of the conquistadores.29 Given the nature of its narrative models, then, it is not difficult to see why the utopian impulse towards radical change so often becomes redirected, turned back on itself. So long as the paradigm persists, it is unsurprising that even the most ambitious attempts to resolve the problems it poses by purely narrative means should never entirely succeed. In A Modern Utopia, for example, it is striking how often the speculative, tentative tone of voice which Wells strives to preserve slides into the prescriptive, authoritative utterance with which utopian narrative is so much more at home. The open-ended verbal formations already mentioned (Let us suppose, in Utopia we should ) repeatedly give way to far more authoritative assertions: there must be a competition in life of some sort to determine who are to be pushed to the edge, and who are to prevail and multiply (p.137); or that, at any rate, is beyond controversy (p.194)this last occurring, as we have seen, in the context of Wellss highly controversial discussion of women and marriage. When this is combined with the utopian tendency to determine things down to even the most apparently gratuitous detail, it is little wonder that the outlines of the utopian society which emerge despite Wellss attempts at narrative experimentation seem so familiar, so reminiscent of the utopian visions of an earlier era. Finally, it is clear that the gender dynamics of Bellamys and Wellss

104

NARRATING UTOPIA

utopian fictions differ surprisingly little from those of their Renaissance predecessors. In part, as Bammer suggests, this reflects the continued utopian privileging of the public sphere over the privateover the sphere of everyday life in which politics for women have most often been grounded (p.13)and the unspoken assumption that, however sweeping the social changes proposed, the structures of private life will remain comfortingly unaffected. Nevertheless, given not just the frequency, but the extent to which utopian narratives reassert patriarchal norms (even, as in the case of Bellamy and Wells, in the context of ostensible proposals for the enhancement of womens rights) it is worth asking whether the traditional utopian paradigm, following the narrative of discovery, does not itself inscribe the power dynamics of gender relations in the society of the time. The very processes of exploration, taking possession of territory repeatedly gendered as female, penetrating into its darkest unknown recesses, renaming it, guarding it against intruders, seem particularly susceptible to description in terms of metaphors of sexual possession. When this is set alongside the psychological implications of that paradigm, with its underlying fantasy of reconstituting maternal security through the institution of a masculine order, it is scarcely surprising to find the subordination of female to male so incessantly re-enacted in utopian fictionnot merely in the structures of the utopian society described, but even in the apparently gratuitous narrative flourishes that so often surround the description. To return, one last time, to Wellss Men Like Gods: when Mr Barnstaple finally returns to Earth, inspired by the wonders of utopia, it is with the determination to live his life differently, to live it in such a way as to work towards the realization of utopia upon Earth. He has all kinds of schemes in mind when he finally reaches home, but the only real difference we are shown (other than his gain in height and impressive sun-tan) is his new-found ability to assert effortless authority over his hitherto bossy wife.

4. Dystopia: The Dream as Nightmare


Today, examining the utopias of Bellamy and Wells with all the benefits conferred by hindsight, their regimentation appears more than a little alarming. While the subjection of individual conduct to incessant public scrutiny, the subordination of private freedoms to the interests of public welfare, are equally characteristic of the Renaissance utopia, the eagerness of Bellamy and Wells to use the resources of modern technology in the service of an imposed, centralized social order now seems decidedly suspect. To be fair, neither writer had any real experience of what a modern, centralized, totalitarian state could be likebut such innocence of the consequences of seeking to impose order on humanity in its own best interests soon becomes impossible. Where the utopian dream of order appears later in the twentieth century (with the exception of such maverick productions as B.F. Skinners Walden Two), it is most strikingly in the form of parodic inversionin the nightmare visions of Zamyatin, Huxley, Orwell, and more recently, Atwood. Challenges to the utopian ideal, of coursewhether in the form of direct rebuttal or of parodyare hardly an exclusively modern phenomenon. Examples of the former range from Aristotles strictures on Plato, through J. Lesleys attack on James Harrington, A Slap on the Snout of the Republican Swine that rooteth up monarchy,1 to the numerous abusive reviews of Walden Two; while in the latter category one might include Jonathan Swifts grotesque send-up of the Baconian scientific ideal in Book III of Gullivers Travels, as well as his far more disturbing portrait of the perfect society of the cold, rational, genocidal Houhyhnhnms in Book IV. Bellamys Looking Backward inspired a veritable rash of parodic responses,2 primarily designed to show what his utopian ideal would lead to in practiceperhaps the most noteworthy being A.D. Vintons Looking Further Backward, which portrays a future United States in which individual initiative has been so far sapped by the abandonment of the capitalist competitive ethic that it easily falls prey to a Chinese invasion. Yet it is only in the twentieth century that dystopian fiction, combining a parodic inversion of the traditional utopia with satire on contemporary society, begins to take on the kind of mythic resonance that underlies the appeal of the traditional utopia from the time of More on. Indeed, many of the very factors that undermine the appeal of the utopian dream of order in the modern era also serve to heighten the relevance of the dystopian parodic inversion. Where utopian fictions gave expression to humanitys

106

NARRATING UTOPIA

growing sense of mastery over both social conditions and the natural world, the works of writers such as Zamyatin, Huxley, and Orwell speak to an audience increasingly disillusioned by the consequences of such controlling aspirations. Where Bellamys belief in the virtues of an industrial army and Wellss vision of a world where nature is groomed and manipulated to suit human convenience now seem disturbingly nave, the totalitarian nightmares of Zamyatin and Orwell, or Huxleys portrait of a society dominated by mindless consumerism, seem hardly less apposite now than when they were written. There are several reasons for this. The first and most obviousas has already been suggestedis the modern experience of totalitarian governments whose conduct has called into question the traditional utopian premise that strong, centralized authority would act in the best interests of the citizen. Implicit in Vintons parody of Bellamy, however, is a second concernthat, even were the institution of a benevolent utopian state possible, the consequent resolution of social problems would deprive its citizens of the challenges necessary to sustain progress, and that they would consequently lapse into a state of decadence that would render them easy prey to more vigorous, if less perfect societies. Vinton, in fact, was tapping into an anxiety, current in both America and Britain during the later nineteenth century, that progress had already rendered such decadence a real dangeran anxiety reflected in a whole series of invasion narratives.3 Perhaps the most memorable of these is Wellss science fictional reworking of the theme in The War of the Worlds, yet it is in his earlier The Time Machine that he points most clearly to what he fears might be the inherent weakness of a future utopia. Arriving in the distant future, Wellss Time Traveller finds a beautiful, apparently peaceful, pastoral worldyet one whose inhabitants have degenerated into either effete lethargy or mindless cannibalism, and he reflects on the bitter irony that, having achieved its goal of comfort and ease, a balanced society with security and permanence as its watchword (p.97)a perfect world with no unemployed problem, no social question left unresolved (p.97) humanity had removed all incentive for further development: It is the law of nature we overlook, that intellectual versatility is the compensation for change, danger, and trouble Nature never appeals to intelligence until habit and instinct are useless. There is no intelligence where there is no change and no need of change. Only those animals partake of intelligence that have to meet a huge variety of needs and dangers. [p.97] Implicit in such evolutionary pessimism, however, is not simply the mournful conclusion that resolving our current problems would merely

DYSTOPIA

107

create others, probably much worse, but also what is surely at the root of the dystopian distrust of utopia: the fear that we are simply creatures of our societythat what we take to be our essential identity is in fact socially constructed, and hence susceptible to radical change under different social circumstances. While utopias, as Levitas argues, are seen by their opponents as totalitarian because they visibly shape needs and match them with available satisfactions, thus moulding the individual to the system (Concept of Utopia, pp.1845), they also imply, perhaps more alarmingly, that we are already products of our social environment, and that it is only the unpredictable outcome of competing conditioning influences that creates the illusion of individual freedom and essential identity. Not the least of the reasons for the continuing appeal of dystopian fiction is that it addresses this fear, but at the same time mobilizes against it the reassuring notion that there is, after all, some essential and invariant human nature that is in the last analysis immune to such conditioning influences. In addition, unlike the traditional utopia, dystopian fiction posits a society whichhowever outlandishis clearly extrapolated from that which exists. Where utopian fiction stresses the difference of the society it depicts, often obscures the connection between the real world and its alternative, and rarely indicates how such an alternative might be created, the dystopian writer presents the nightmare future as a possible destination of present society, as if dystopia were no more than a logical conclusion derived from the premises of the existing order, and implies that it might very well come about unless something is done to stop it. Thus Zamyatin, in We, while depicting a society of the far future, clearly takes as his starting point Lenins Socialist Order, and the contemporary artistic fascination with the aesthetic of the machine, to project a world where that order is now absolute, and where the only beauty is mechanical. Not the least impressive of Zamyatins achievements, in fact, is his ability to convey not only the horror and cruelty of his future society, but also something of the terrible appeal of the dream of order which underlies itthe appeal of sensing oneself part of something far greater than the mere sum of its parts. Although We charts the process whereby an individual comes to rebel against the authority of the One State, we are given a powerful sense of the difficulty he experiences in breaking away from beliefs and assumptions he has held all his life. Until the seeds of doubt are sown in his mind, D-503 is not merely a good citizen, giving unquestioned allegiance to authority; he is also the designer of the spaceship Integral, with which the One State proposes to conquer the universea man genuinely committed to the ideas and values of his society. Part of the power of Zamyatins narrative lies in the vividness with which he dramatizes not just the struggle between the individual and the State, but also the internal struggle which precedes it.

108

NARRATING UTOPIA

Huxley, by contrast, takes the consumer society of modern capitalism as the starting point for his satiric extrapolation. While the names of some of the characters in Brave New WorldLenina Crowne, Benito Hoover, Morgana Rothschild, Helmholz Watson, and so forthsuggest a plagueon-all-your-houses approach, with capitalism, communism, fascism, modern science, all featuring as ancestors of the society of the future, it is Henry Ford who is its presiding deity. Huxley not only takes the production line that Ford pioneered several steps further, applying its principles to the creation of human beings as well as motor vehicles, he also works out the implications of Fords wage policies, in part designed to assist in creating a market for his own products, and comes up with a vision of a consumer society based on an ethos of endless self-sustaining economic growth which bears a disquieting resemblance to the western society of today. Indeed, there are striking parallels between Huxleys depiction of a world where citizens acquiesce in their own conditioning, where ostensible sexual liberation is instrumental in sustaining oppression, and where solitude is almost impossible, and Marcuses analysis of postwar American society as one where people are conditioned by a process of repressive desublimation to acquiesce in their own enslavement, and where solitude, the very condition which sustained the individual against and beyond his society, has become technically impossible (One-Dimensional Man, p.71). Orwells Nineteen Eighty-Four returns to communism, this time of the Stalin era, for its inspiration. Although the ambience of Orwells future society, with its rationing, appalling food, and general seediness is very much that of post-war Britain, there can be little doubt as to who is the model for the mustachioed Big Brother, whose face gazes down from innumerable posters. While certain features of Airstrip One, as Britain has been renamed (such as the use of children to spy on their parents) appear to have been derived from the example of Nazi Germany, the bulk of the parallelsbetween Goldstein and Trotsky, for exampleare clearly with the Soviet Union. Certainly, there is no doubt as to what Pravda saw as the main target of Orwells satire. There, Orwell is described as: slobbering with poisonous spittle he imputes every evil to the people It is clear that Orwells filthy book is in the spirit of such a vital organ of American propaganda as the Readers Digest which published the work. [Quoted in Chilton and Aubrey, p.11] In the United States, the message appears to have been equally clear. Isaac Deutscher describes being recommended the book by a New York newsvendor with the words: Have you read this book? You must read it, sir. Then you will know why we must drop the atom bomb on the Bolshies (p.265)!

DYSTOPIA

109

Dystopian fiction, then, for all that it is set in futures of varying degrees of remoteness, reasserts the connection between the actual and the imagined which the traditional utopia so often obscures. In its parodic inversion, the essential identity between many features of utopia and those of the world to which it proposes an alternative re-emerges. Where utopian satire on the existing order (such as Bellamys parable of the coach) stresses the disparity between the real world and its utopian alternative, that difference constituting the measure of the formers deficiencies, dystopian fiction highlights the resemblances between our own world and the projected society of the future. Dystopia, in effect, satirizes both society as it exists, and the utopian aspiration to transform it. From the dystopian perspective, it is by very reason of its roots in existing society that utopia is unable to transcend it: conditioned by what exists, utopia can only offer more of the same, on a larger scale. Utopias apparently noble dream of creating a better world is seen as arrogant and presumptuousthe reflection of an unquestioning belief in mankinds right to control and manipulate both humanity and nature. Dystopian Narrative In terms of narrative impact, this altered relationship between the actual and the imagined carries with it a number of benefits. In parodically inverting the utopian model, the dystopian text succeeds in establishing a dialectic between existing society and the projected alternative which, while to some extent present in Mores Utopia, is generally lacking in the work of his more literal-minded successors. While the traditional utopia seeks to forestall critical judgement of the alternative society, utopia constituting the standard by which our own world is judged and found wanting, dystopian fiction positively demands that readers judge the projected society by the standards of their own. Confronted by a world where everyone lives in glass boxes, as in We, under the constant surveillance of telescreens, as in Nineteen Eighty-Four, or under the inescapable influence of both pre- and post-natal conditioning, as in Brave New World, it is almost impossible not to conclude that the dystopian projection is less desirable than the world as it stands. Yet at the same time, the evident resemblances between dystopian and existing society encourage a parallel process, whereby readers are encouraged to judge their own society by the extent to which it embodies dystopian features. In its parody of the traditional utopia, the dystopian text at the same time satirizes many features of existing societyand, in the grotesque distorting mirror which it holds up to reality, the reader is enabled to see, in some respects more clearly, the extent to which society manifests the dystopian

110

NARRATING UTOPIA

characteristics of mindless conformity and acceptance of authoritarian control. Rather than being embedded in the static portrait of a more perfect society, the values implicit in the dystopian text emerge from an active interplay between the readers critical judgements of both actual and imaginary worlds. This is not to say, however, that dystopian fiction is any less manipulative of the reader than is its utopian counterpart. While the reader of a dystopian text may well experience a greater freedom in passing judgement, that freedom is clearly constrained and determined by the terms in which the comparison between the two worlds is set up. When Huxley, in Brave New World, portrays babies being given electric shock treatment to encourage an aversion to books and flowers, followed by an official sermon from the Director of Hatcheries and Conditioning on the benefits of replacing a taste for the simple pleasures of literature and nature by a desire for far more technologically sophisticatedand accordingly expensiveartifacts and pursuits, the readers response is not hard to predict: initial revulsion, followed by recognition of the obvious parallels between Huxleys dystopia and modern consumer society. Such crude, though undeniably effective, satire is in essence just as clear in its designs on the reader as the standard scene in traditional utopian fiction, where a depiction of utopias positive aspects is closely followed by a parallel scene in the real world, in which health, cleanliness, and happiness are mirrored by decrepitude, squalor, and misery.4 The only real difference is that it works better. Where utopian narrative ostensibly juxtaposes two different viewpoints, the utopian and the non-utopian, it is clear that, as Bakhtin puts it: This is not a clash of two ultimate semantic authorities, but rather an objectified (plotted) clash of two represented positions, subordinated wholly to the higher, ultimate authority of the author. The monologic context, under these circumstances, is neither broken nor weakened. [Problems, p.188] In dystopian parody, by contrast, the monologic authority of the utopian voice (for example, that of the Director of Hatcheries and Conditioning) is undermined by the parodic context in which it is placed. What is introduced, by implication, is, as Bakhtin suggests, a second voice with a semantic intention that is directly opposed to the original one (p.193) and in the light of which it is impossible to accept the first voice as authoritative. Where the monologic character and schematic oppositions of utopian narrative are liable to create resistance on the part of the reader (this is what I am supposed to think), their dystopian parodic counterparts are a far more effective rhetorical device for securing the readers assent to the authors point of view. In addition, because the dystopian text tends

DYSTOPIA

111

to dramatize both the similarities and differences between the real and imagined, rather than spelling them out, the reader is also spared the presence of the usually uncritical narrator or visitor, whose opinions the reader of the traditional utopia is so clearly intended to share. In effect, dystopian fiction demonstrates a greater readiness to trust both the readers intelligence and the writers own technical skill. This is perhaps most clearly evident when the first person narratives of such utopian texts as Looking Backward or A Modern Utopia are compared with the equivalent use of the device in dystopian fiction. Bellamys and Wellss narrators, as we have seen, speak with the conviction of the converted: to them, the virtues of utopia are self-evident, and in representing them as desirable they speak with confidence and authority; yet at the same time, they exhibit a curious passivity. Bellamys Julian West, in the face of the still more authoritative utterance of Dr Leete; Wellss narrator (at any rate during the overtly fictional sections of the text) when confronted by his utopian alter ego: each displays an uncritical acceptance of what he is told, and in doing so, as has been suggested, offers an implicit model for the reader. The narrators in Zamyatins We, or indeed Atwoods The Handmaids Tale are more active, by contrast, yet at the same time less confident. D-503 and Offred are hesitant, reluctant to pass judgement, sometimes even confused, and their narratives reveal, not minds already made up, but rather minds in the process of being made up. D-503 reveals himself as engaged in an internal struggle over what to think, over whether to accept or reject the values of the One State, while Offred, although clearly opposed to the fundamentalist values of Gilead, is occupied throughout the book with the question as to what she can or should do about her situation. The narrative, in other words, embodies a process, is to use Wellss termsnot static but kinetic, and as a result offers the reader a very different model with which to identify. In its parodic inversion of the traditional utopia, dystopian fiction portrays a society whose undesirability is far more clearly self-evident than is the desirability of its utopian counterpart, while at the same time it presents a protagonist whose actively critical attitude towards it is far easier to endorse. Dystopian fiction, then, would seemat least at first sightto be free from many of the narrative limitations of the traditional utopia. Gone are the ponderous narrative mechanisms used to account for the visitors transfer to utopia: the fictions of Zamyatin, Huxley, Orwell, Atwood all begin in medias res, often with arresting narrative devices calculated at once to stimulate curiosity and alert the reader to the difference of the world being described: A squat grey building of only thirty-four stories. Over the main

112
CENTRE ,

NARRATING UTOPIA

entrance, the words, CENTRAL LONDON HATCHERY AND CONDITIONING and in a shield, the World States motto, COMMUNITY , IDENTITY , STABILITY . [Brave New World, p.15]

It was a bright cold day in April, and the clocks were striking thirteen. [Nineteen Eighty-Four, p.7] What then follows is an account of life in the different society filtered through the consciousness, not of the admiring tourist, but of the inhabitant, living with it day-in, day-out, and lacking any other standards by which to judge itunless one counts the rapidly fading memories of Offred and Winston Smith. The only visitor to dystopia, as such, is Huxleys Savage, whose background is almost as alien to our own reality as the society he visits. Hence the details of dystopian society emerge, not in the course of the traditional guided tour, but in the process of an inherently far more dramatic narrative of oppositional struggle; while, as we have seen, where there are expository set pieces, such as the Directory of Hatchery and Conditionings pompous lecture on the history of conditioning techniques in Brave New World, their effect is radically different, inviting ridicule rather than acceptance. Nevertheless, for all these differences in narrative strategy, dystopian fiction continues to reproduce many features of the traditional utopia and not always just parodically. While extrapolated from the very different value systems of Soviet communism, consumer capitalism, and fundamentalist Christianity, the dystopias of Zamyatin and Orwell, Huxley, and Atwood all display a family resemblance whose source is not difficult to divine.5 All constitute parodic reworkings of the traditional utopian paradigm, but while the primary function of parody is of course to expose the limitations of the original, the very closeness of its relationship to the original often means that these limitations are also to some extent reproduced. Given the degree to which the utopian paradigm is characterized by tension and contradiction, it is perhaps unsurprising that these should also inform dystopian parody. As will be seen, some of the most characteristic features of the traditional paradigm resurfacein sometimes unexpected formseven in a parodic context. In terms of what dystopian fiction exposes, perhaps the most immediately striking feature of all the works under discussion is their common emphasis on the extraordinarily public character of life in the societies they project. Like the traditional utopia, dystopia portrays a society which is regimented and hierarchicaland also one where adherence to the societal ideal is ensured by an almost obsessive concern with surveillance, with the subjection of the individual to public scrutiny. Not only do its citizens conform to the standards of the monolithic statethey must be seen to

DYSTOPIA

113

conform, and it is this visible conformity which is seen as essential to the preservation of stability and order in utopia and dystopia alike. More, in Utopia, sees the elimination of privacy as the key to ensuring individual virtue: no one is likely to do wrong because they live in full view of all (p.49). Dystopian fiction simply takes this one step further, exposing it as a fundamental principle of both utopian and dystopian order: ultimately, the only way to be certain that societys norms are consistently observed is by watching everyone, all the time. Accordingly in dystopia all the resources of modern technology are employed to ensure that privacy is kept to an absolute minimum. The glass bedrooms of We, the telescreens of Nineteen Eighty-Four (precursors of the video cameras which grace todays banks, stores, public buildings, and even mens washrooms), the spies and hidden microphones of The Handmaids Tale all serve the same essential purpose as do the social provisions of Mores Utopia. Brave New World, indeed, resembles Utopia still more closely, in that the element of overt coercion present in other dystopias, where the consequences of being seen to act antisocially are made abundantly clear, is replaced by a benign confidence in the powers of conditioning. The citizens of Brave New World are conditioned to want to spend all their time in the full view of all; such privacy as they preserve is devoted to such harmless (and in societys terms, respectable) practices as sleep, recreational sex, and the consumption of stupefying drugs. Conformity is assured, and so too is uniformityin the most literal sense. The citizens of all four dystopias wear uniforms, reinforcing the sense that (as in so much utopian narrative) people are types rather than distinct individuals. (Huxley and Atwood make their uniforms colour coded, like electrical wiring, further enhancing the sense that the individual is merely part of the social machine.) In We, everyone does everything at the same time, while all four future societies have communal rituals in which individual identity is submerged in that of the group, ranging from public executions, in Zamyatin and Atwood, through Orwells Two Minutes Hate, to the group sex of Huxleys Brave New World. Even this last may be seen as having its roots in the provisions of the traditional utopia, with its characteristic blurring of the lines between the public and private spheres, which is nowhere more apparent than in its treatment of sexual relations. Campanella, as we have seen, organizes sexual intimacy under the supervision of astrologers, physicians, and matrons, with not only the choice of sexual partner but the exact time of intercourse dictated by the state. Yet this, while extreme, is scarcely an aberration. Implicit in both Bellamys substitution of sexual for economic rewards, with women providing the ultimate incentive for male productive efficiency, Wellss depiction of marital relations as ultimately the concern

114

NARRATING UTOPIA

of the state, rather than of the individuals involved, is the same impulse to subordinate all aspects of individual experience to the needs of society. Again, dystopian fiction simply takes this one stage further: Zamyatins sex-vouchers, the universal promiscuity in Brave New World, where everyone belongs to everyone else, the reduction of women to mere mechanisms for procreation in The Handmaids Tale, all serve to expose the implications inherent in the sexual provisions of utopia. Ultimately, whether in utopia or dystopia, the message is the same: that individual agency cannot be trusted, even in the most intimate sphere of personal relations; in the end, the overriding interests of the state must prevail. In taking the utopian emphasis on the virtues of conformity and the need for supervision of every aspect of individual behaviour to its logical conclusion, dystopian fiction makes explicit the extent to which the utopian ideal is premised on the suppression of any distinct individual identity. Such identity is acquired only gradually, in the process of growing up, as individuals begin to make choices and take responsibility for their actions: in effectively removing responsibility and choice from the individual sphere, utopian society minimizes the opportunities for such identity to emergewhich in part explains why attempts to incorporate elements of novelistic characterization into the traditional utopian narrative are so seldom successful. Dystopian fiction, however, portrays a process which renders the implications still clearer: in suppressing the emergence of individual identity in the interests of stability, security, conformity, the dystopian state clearly seeks to discourage the development of any kind of mature, adult awarenessof any form of consciousness sophisticated enough to perceive and articulate the societys limitations. There is in consequence a distinct childishness evident in the behaviourial norms of dystopian society, suggesting that the regressive aspect of the utopian idealits desire for a return to womb-like securityhas been correctly intuited. It is Huxley who exposes these implications most clearly. As well as providing an abundance of food, diversion, and guilt-free sexual gratification, his future society reduces work to an undemanding minimum (as the same time conditioning the individual to enjoy it), and leaves the responsibility for running things to a ruling lite of World Controllers. It is a world which is not merely innocent, but quite explicitly infantile: infantile behaviour constitutes the socially approved norm. When Bernard Marx talks to Lenina Crowne of wanting to act like an adult, her response is one of simple incomprehension, and Bernard is later reprimanded for his lapse from a proper standard of infantile decorum (p.85). For welladjusted citizens, by contrast, the ideal state is one of blissful unconsciousnessthe symbolic implications of which are made only too

DYSTOPIA

115

clear. When Lenina and Henry Foster conclude their evening out with a trip to the Westminster Abbey Cabaret (featuring the music of Calvin Stopes and his Sixteen Sexophonists), their last, drug-enhanced dance together is described in unmistakable terms: Lenina and Henry had what they wanted They were inside, here and nowsafely inside with the fine weather, the perennially blue sky. And when, exhausted, the Sixteen had laid by their sexophones and the Synthetic Music apparatus was producing the very latest in slow Malthusian Blues, they might have been twin embryos gently rocking together on the waves of a bottled ocean of blood-surrogate. [pp.6970] In the more hostile environments depicted in other dystopian fictions, particularly Nineteen Eighty-Four, this aspect is less overt. Nevertheless, the elimination of individual responsibility, the enforced conformity, the endless organized activities in which the citizens of both Orwells and Zamyatins future societies are obliged to participate all serve to suggest a pattern almost as regressive. If womb-like security is the ideal of the citizens of Brave New World, the ambience of We and Nineteen Eighty-Four is more akin to that of a gigantic boarding-school, governed by routine, ritual, and arbitrary acts of authority. And in all three works, as in The Handmaids Tale, any indication of an adult tendency to independent thought or action is the ultimate heresy. The parallels between the childlike, infantile, or even foetal dependence fostered by dystopian society and the underlying pattern of the traditional utopia are clear enough, but the resemblance does not end there. In each case the regressive dependence of the individual is secured by essentially similar meansby the imposition of a distinctively patriarchal order. In We, it is the larger-than-life figure of The Benefactor who rules the One State which protects its citizens from the terrors of the unexpected and the dangers that might accompany the savage state of freedom (p.19). In fact, The Benefactor is merely a man: a bald-headed, a Socratically bald-headed man (p.205), perhaps modelled on Lenin; but he is normally described in terms that suggest he is giganticrather as a father might appear to a small child. In an interview with D-503, The Benefactor, concerned by his involvement with the rebels, significantly invites him to talk as grownups do when the children have gone off to bed (p.204), much as the privileged eldest son might be invited to join with his father in man-toman conversation.6 Equally significantly, it is a woman who represents the disruptive force which tempts D-503 to taste the forbidden delights of freedomand it is a woman whose destruction is essential to the preservation of the stability of the patriarchal state. It is the womans,

116

NARRATING UTOPIA

E-330s,7 attempt to take possession of the Integral, the phallic spaceship with which the patriarchal One State seeks to penetrate the heavens, that constitutes the ultimate, unforgivable act of rebellion; when it is thwarted by the intervention of the male Guardians, order is thereby restored. In Nineteen Eighty-Four an almost identical scenario unfolds itself; indeed, the parallel is so close that it is clear that Orwell must have been indebted to Zamyatin for the inspiration. Here it is another woman, Julia, who arouses the protagonist, Winston Smith, to go beyond mere sullen resentment of the Stalin-like Big Brother and take action against authority. Once again, however, the woman proves no match for the patriarchal state: tortured and brainwashed, Winston disowns Julia, and ends up in ginsodden adulation of Big Brother. Here, however, the power of the patriarchal ruler is mediated by the presence of another male authority figure, OBrien, for whom Winston feels much the same instinctive regard as does the narrator in Wellss In the Days of the Comet for the politician, Melmountalthough here the homoerotic implications are even clearer. Larger and stronger than Winston, OBrien treats himeven while torturing himwith an almost indecent intimacy. All the while Winston is being subjected to the most unspeakable agonies, OBrien is there, hand on his shoulder, to reassure him that it is all for his own good, and, (as Gerald Fiderer points out) there is a distinctly masochistic element in Winstons response: At sight of the heavy, lined face, so ugly and so intelligent, his heart seemed to turn over. If he could have moved he would have stretched out a hand and laid it on OBriens arm. He had never loved him so deeply as at this moment It made no difference. In some sense that went deeper than friendship, they were intimates. [p.217] OBrien even invades Winstons dreams, which had hitherto been primarily about his mother, and on this unconscious plane re-enacts the triumphant suppression of the female by the male. By the end, Winston has betrayed and forgotten not only his lover, but also his motherboth have been replaced by males. Amid the rampant heterosexual promiscuity of Huxleys World State, the element of patriarchal dominance is less immediately apparent (although the confrontation between the rebels and the World Controller, Mustapha Mond, replicates the power dynamics of the equivalent scenes in We and Nineteen Eighty-Fourindeed, faced by Monds unassailable authority, Bernard Marx reverts completely to the status of a child: he bursts into tears, and has to be put to bed). None the less, while men and women apparently enjoy an equal degree of sexual freedom (or lack of it, given that promiscuity is more or less compulsory), it soon becomes clear

DYSTOPIA

117

that equality ends there. Henry Ford, rather than Lenin or Stalin, is the presiding male deity, in whose name the (apparently all male) World Controllers rule the acquiescent masses. And while humanity is segregated into genetically predetermined castes, which are conditioned to have as little as possible to do with one another, there appears to be an exception which allows for sexual relationships between Alpha males and Beta females. It is a revealing contradiction, indicative of the extent to which Huxleys futuristic extrapolation remains governed by the assumptions of his own time: despite imagining a world whose sexual morality is radically different, Huxley uncritically reproduces the gender relations of his own era. Significantly, the only members of the Alpha lite we encounter are male, with the exception of the Headmistress of Eton, who is a freemartina female who has been rendered sterile by prenatal doses of male sex hormones. (The status of the central female character, Lenina, is left ambiguous: although Theodor Adorno describes herrather oddly as a well-groomed and polished American career woman (p.105), her occupation points to a Beta, rather than an Alpha classification.) In a world whose only sexual taboos are against celibacy and monogamy, and where pregnancy and childbirth have been superseded by mechanical reproductive technology, the word Mother is the ultimate obscenity. (Father is only mildly smutty by comparison.) Although there is no counterpart to the subversive females of Zamyatin and Orwell, it is noteworthy that the main opponent of the dystopian societythe Savageis devoted to his mother. The work ends, once again, with the destruction of the central female characterin this case the hapless Leninaand the death, rather than the acquiescence of the defeated rebel. While there may be less overt glorification of male power in Brave New World than in We or Nineteen Eighty-Four, in removing womens reproductive power, and replacing it with a male inventionthe production lineHuxley takes the utopian dream of a male-dominated order still further. At the same time, he takes to its logical conclusion the longstanding utopian preoccupation with selective breeding: in Brave New World, humanity is quite literally designed to fit the demands of the state. The conformity which in the dystopias of Zamyatin and Orwell is secured by such relatively clumsy means as brain surgery or torture is painlessly ensured in Huxleys World State by the technologies of mass production: One hundred and seven heat-conditioned Epsilon Senegalese were working in the foundry. Thirty-three Delta females, long-headed, sandy, with narrow pelvises, and all within 20 millimetres of 1 metre 69 centimetres tall, were cutting screws. In the assembling room, the dynamos were being put together by two sets of Gamma-plus dwarfs.

118

NARRATING UTOPIA

The two long work-tables faced one another; between them crawled the conveyor with its load of separate parts; forty-seven blond heads were confronted by forty-seven brown ones. Forty-seven snubs by forty-seven hooks; forty-seven receding by forty-seven prognathous chins. The completed mechanisms were inspected by eighteen identical curly auburn girls in Gamma green, packed in crates by thirty-four short-legged, left-handed male Delta-minuses, and loaded into the waiting trucks and lorries by sixty-three blue-eyed, flaxen and freckled Epsilon Semi-Morons. [pp.1301]8 To such visions of the future, in which human beings seem hardly less mechanical than the machines they use, it is hard to respond without a degree of revulsionand part of the narrative appeal of dystopian fiction stems from the writers ability to exploit the readers reaction against the society portrayed. Whereas it is often difficult to share the visitor to utopias uncritical enthusiasm for the wonders of utopian society, the horrors of dystopia guarantee a sympathetic reaction on the readers part to anyone who stands out against the mindless conformity imposed by the monolithic state. On occasions, such sympathy is still further exploited for ironic effect, as when Huxley, having first established Bernard Marx as a sympathetic figure by making him a cogentindeed, almost the onlycritic of the appalling world he lives in, then proceeds to undercut the readers natural tendency to identify with such a character by showing him succumbing all too readily to the lures of success. But this is a comparative rarity: while none of D-503, Winston Smith, the Savage, or Offred are by any stretch of the imagination idealized portrayals, they are so much preferable to the worlds they live in that the actual nature of their opposition to dystopian society may easily escape critical examinationgiven that in such a society any opposition seems better than none at all. The forms which opposition to dystopia takes, however, are worth looking at more closely, for it is here that the extent to which dystopian fiction shares the limitations of the original it parodies begins to become apparent. There is in fact a family resemblance, not only between the patterns of the various dystopian societies, but also between the modes of rebellion against them. Thus, for example, the first form which resistance takes is invariably the repudiation of the demand that life be lived primarily in public. At E-330s behest, D-503 finds himself conniving in the use of the hours of privacy sanctioned only for sexual purposes for other, more subversive purposes. Secret knowledge, secret behaviour are seen as in themselves subversive, almost irrespective of the nature of the secrets involved. Bernard Marx establishes himself as suspicious simply by virtue of his desire to spend time by himself, rather than in the mindless

DYSTOPIA

119

gregariousness which is seen as normal. And Winston Smith, for all his terror of the states power of physical coercion, deliberately risks his safety in his pursuit of privacy:9 at first timidly, in the tiny alcove out of sight of the telescreen, where he keeps his journal; and later more boldly, with his illicit liaison with Julia in their secret meeting place above a junk shop. What is significant, however, is the consistency with which this reassertion of the desire for privacy is associated with the past. The early meetings of D-503 and E-330 take place at the House of Antiquity, a relic of the past preserved for instructional purposes; Winston and Julia pursue their liaison in a room above a shop that sells antiques. Both E-330 and Julia shock and entice their lovers by wearing old-fashioned clothing, while Winston Smith records his subversive thoughts in a ladys keepsake album which is attractive partly because of its age, writing with an old-fashioned pen-nib on beautiful creamy paper (p.11) which is no longer manufactured. And the past, in its turn, becomes the main source of the values in comparison with which dystopian society is judged and found wanting. In Brave New World, the energy and verbal richness of the Savages beloved Shakespeare is used to highlight the clichs and emotional poverty of dystopia; while such ancient texts as the Bible and the writings of William James and Maine de Biran are seen as so subversive that they are kept securely locked away in the safe of the World Controller, Mustapha Mond. At first sight, the subversive import of such survivals from the past would seem to be largely symbolic. Certainly there are relics of the past whose political relevance is immediately evident, as when Winston Smith comes across a newspaper photograph of three party members who officially no longer existor indeed ever existed. Here there is objective evidence that the authorities are lyingyet in terms of its impact, the actual use that can be made of the information, there appears to be little effective difference between the photograph and the keepsake album in which Winston keeps his diary. Ultimately, the subversiveness of an interest in the past lies not in the implications of any specific piece of information, but rather in the fact that there was a past at all. Dystopian society, like that of most traditional utopias, has as its ideal a condition of eternal and static stability. Once perfection (of whatever kind) is achieved, change automatically becomes a threatand the problem with the past is that, simply by showing that things were once different, it demonstrates that change is at least possible. The very existence of the past where things were different implies that society is not static but kinetic, and dystopian societies uniformly go out of their way to obliterate its memory. In Nineteen Eighty-Four, history is systematically rewritten to conform to the changing necessities of the present: even so dramatic an event as the replacement of Eurasia by Eastasia as Oceanias

120

NARRATING UTOPIA

enemy in the endless world war is so effectively glossed over that within a matter of days the fiction that Oceania and Eastasia have always been at war is almost universally accepted as fact. To show an interest in what the past was really like is almost certain evidence of thoughtcrime, punishable by anything from twenty-five years imprisonment to death. In We, the past possesses a certain exotic fascination, but it is generally viewed as hopelessly primitive, infinitely remote from the present: a wild epoch (p.34), peopled by brutes, apes, whose behaviour is repeatedly described as laughable and incredible, and whose art is referred to as wild, unorganized, insane epileptically distorted (p.41). Although the World State in Brave New World preserves an enclave of tribal society on the New Mexico Reservation, its squalor, and the queer behaviour of its inhabitants serve primarily as an object lesson to visitors of the horrors from which the World State has liberated them; otherwise, the prevailing view of the past is summed up by the celebrated dictum of the Godlike Ford: History is Bunk. Yet despite its satiric exaggeration, the dystopian attitude towards the past is little more than the logical development of a tendency implicit in the traditional utopia. In A Modern Utopia, history proves as malleable as in Nineteen Eighty-Four: to render utopia possible, the entire course of human history is blithely rewritten in less than a page. In Men Like Gods, the allegedly intellectual curious Utopians show singularly little interest in the more primitive culture of the Earthlings: a single brief conference serves to tell them all they need to know, and they show scarcely any curiosity thereafter. Even in Looking Backward, where the arrival of a visitor from the past does arouse considerable interest, his account of the past serves only to confirm existing assumptions. The general attitude of Bellamys utopians to their past is one of self-congratulation for having escaped from it so easily: the old musty books (p.166) that talk of the past hold little fascination, while in their celebrations of the year 2000 we are told that the almost universal theme has been the future rather than the past, not the advance that has been made, but the progress that shall be made, ever onward and upward (p.xxii). Skinners Walden Two is hardly exceptional in its explicit assertion that the ideal society would deliberately set out to discourage any sense of history (p.235). Rebellion in dystopia, then, expresses itself through a series of binary oppositions. It opposes the public with the private, and counters the dystopian aspiration to permanence and stability with the destabilizing evidence of history and tradition. In addition, the rebel finds in the rural, pastoral world beyond the confines of dystopian society a space and freedom otherwise denied. Dystopia shares with the traditional utopia a predominantly urban emphasis, and here again rebellion takes the form

DYSTOPIA

121

of simple antithesis. Freedom from the One State in We lies beyond the Green Wall, among the more natural, primitive humans who refuse to be conscripted into the conformist world ruled by The Benefactor. It is in the countryside that the Savage seeks refuge from the horrors of Brave New World, and it is in the countryside, too, that Winston and Julia first share the liberation of sexual ecstasy. Where the Wellsian utopia offers a vision of humanity in control of nature, in dystopia the natural world offers virtually the last refuge from the tyranny of the state. Once again, dystopia makes absolute what in utopia is only implicit. Where even Wells allows nature at least some role, however subordinate, dystopia draws the lines more starkly: the natural, organic character of the rural world is inalterably opposed to the controlling human design of dystopian society. In opposing this controlling impulse, the dystopian rebel inevitably challenges the prevailing ethic of infantile or childlike dependence fostered by the patriarchal state. Not only privacy and tradition, but adult behaviour of any kind are seen by the state as inherently subversive. Thus, when E330 upholds the value of independent individual initiative, or the Savage argues for the benefits of deferred, rather than immediate gratification, it is primarily their defiance of the regressive norms of their society that constitutes a threat. Yet for all this, the form such defiance takes often seems curiously limited in scope: only We, for example, portrays any kind of effective political challenge to the State. For the most part, resistance manifests itself more in the sexual than the political realmand then most often in the form of the reassertion of more traditional sexual values. In We, where the Lex Sexualis states that Every number has the right of availability, as a sexual product, to any other member (p.37), securing the sexual services of anyone one desires is a simple matter of applying to the authorities for the appropriate pink coupons, which entitle one to have sex during the private sexual hours. And it is this indiscriminate, yet regulated gratification of desire that E-330 resists, both by engaging in sexual activity outside the designated hours, and refraining from it during them. Sexuality is restored to the individuals control, and with it responsibility for the consequences of her actions. Yet it is here that the implications of E-330s challenge to the One States sexual norms become more equivocal. On D-503s first trip with her to the House of Antiquity, she exchanges her androgynous uniform for more traditional garb: She had on a black hat, a short, antiquated, glaringly yellow dress, black stockings. The dress was of light silk: I could clearly see that the stockings were very long, reaching considerably above her knees, while the neckline was low, revealing that shadow between her [p.43]

122

NARRATING UTOPIA

And here D-503 breaks off, as though barely able to control himselfas he does again on a subsequent occasion, where the nature of the costumes allure is made even more explicit: She was in a saffron-yellow dress of an ancient cut. This was a thousandfold more wicked than if she had had absolutely nothing on. Two sharp points, glowing roseately through the thin tissue: two embers smouldering among ashes. Two tenderly rounded knees [p.65] Clearly, the utopian project of stripping sexuality of guilt has been less than successful, given the immediacy of D-503s response to this traditional stereotype of female sexuality, teasingly provocative in its simultaneous offer and refusal of gratification. This, Zamyatin seems to be implying, is what human beings (or, more precisely, men) really want, as opposed to the bureaucratically regulated permissiveness of the One State. Yet in opposing one form of objectification to another, in presenting the socially constructed sexual stereotypes of his own day as more natural than the more overtly regulated sexuality of his future society, Zamyatin effectively does little more than reinscribe his own societys norms. While We posits a future society with a radically different sexual ethic, the implications of this are never really thought through: in a world where everyone is sexually available to everyone else, We reproduces the familiar scenario of a traditional bourgeois narrative of adulterous love. D-503 has an officially approved partner, O-90, who is short and chubby, talks faster than she thinks, and goes on rather tiresomely about wanting to have a baby; he deserts her in favour of E-330, whose sharp white teeth, exotic taste in clothing, and bodyslender, hard, wilfully pliant as a whiplash (p.24) clearly have a rather different kind of appeal; and the result is disaster. In the world of the far future, not a great deal seems to have changed. In Nineteen Eighty-Four, where the prevailing sexual ethic is repressive rather than permissive (there is even a State-sponsored organization called the Anti-Sex League), the form rebellion takes is still strikingly similar. Once again, any form of sexual activity other than that sanctioned by authority is seen as inherently subversive. As Winston reflects: The sexual act, successfully performed, was rebellion. Desire was thoughtcrime (p.62). It is the instinctual, spontaneous, uncontrollable quality of sexual desire that makes it a threat to officially imposed conformity, and indeed part of Julias appeal to Winston lies precisely in her promiscuity, which he sees as representing a breach in the wall of virtue which the state has tried to erect: His heart leapt. Scores of times she had done it: he wished it had

DYSTOPIA

123

been hundredsthousands. Anything that hinted at corruption always filled him with wild hope. Who knew, perhaps the Party was rotten under the surface, its cult of strenuousness and self-denial simply a shame concealing iniquity. If he could have infected the whole lot of them with leprosy or syphilis, how gladly he would have done so! Anything to rot, to weaken, to undermine! [p.111] Here, at the outset, there is an almost carnivalesque quality to Orwells depiction of sexuality: even in corruption and disease there is the spark of life, the hope of renewal. Simple undifferentiated desire (p.112) is a force that the official values of society can never wholly contain or repress: that was the force that would tear the Party to pieces (p.112). And Winston is quite clear as to the implications of his desire: Their embrace had been a battle, the climax a victory. It was a blow struck against the Party. It was a political act. [p.112] Yet as the relationship between Winston and Julia develops, this anarchic, carnivalesque celebration of desire soon gives way to something far more conventional. Defiance of the official sexual morality increasingly takes the form, as it does in We, of a reinscription of traditional stereotypes. Julia speaks of her desire to wear a real womans frock rather than trousers, to wear silk stockings and high-heeled shoesto be a woman, not a Party comrade (p.127). In a scene clearly influenced by Zamyatins example, Julia enhances her allure, not only with old-fashioned clothing, but even make-up: Her lips were deeply reddened, her cheeks rouged, her nose powdered; there was even a touch of something under the eyes to make them brighter. It was not very skillfully done, but Winstons standards in such matters were not high. He had never before seen or imagined a woman of the Party with cosmetics on her face. The improvement in her appearance was startling. With just a few dabs of colour in the right places she had become not only very much prettier, but, above all, far more feminine. Her short hair and boyish overalls merely added to the effect. [p.126] While it is her animal instinct (p.112) that Winston finds attractive at first, it is paradoxically the old-fashioned artifice of make-up10 that reveals her true femininity. Moreover, although it is Julia who first takes the lead in their relationship, she soon reveals more stereotypically feminine qualities. Unlike Winstons, her opposition to the Party proves to be instinctual, rather than intellectual: she has little interest in political ideas, falls asleep when he reads her the subversive writings of Goldstein, and regards any kind of organized revolt against the Party as stupid (p.117).

124

NARRATING UTOPIA

It is Winston who initiates their joining what he takes to be the resistance, at which point the formerly promiscuous Julia declares that, even in the interests of overthrowing the Party, the one thing she will not countenance is their separation. Her resourcefulness, so striking at the outset, soon becomes largely confined to finding black market food for them to consume in the rented room that is almost a home (p.133), where they meet to make love and g[i]ve themselves up to daydreams of escape (p.134). In the end, what is opposed to the massive tyranny of the state is little more than a bourgeois domestic idyll, a brief, fragile dream of quasi-marital bliss. Like Zamyatin, Orwell opposes to the monstrous sexual conformity of the dystopian state a purportedly natural sexuality which is in fact no less socially constructed. Brave New World also creates an opposition between the sexual norms of dystopian society and more traditional valuesbut here the contrast is less uncritical. Huxley portrays a society more permissive even than Zamyatins, where everyone has not merely the right, but the duty to have sex with as many partners as possible, both privately and in communal sex-orgies. Extrapolated as it is from the realities of capitalist society, there is no bureaucratic regulation of the operations of the sexual free market which is probably just as well, given that the volume of pink coupons required would most likely have exceeded the capacity of the World States paper production. In such a world, about the only possible subversive form of sexual activity is to refrain from it, which is precisely what the various rebels attempt to do: Helmholz Watson, though once an indefatigable lover (p.62) with a track record of six hundred and forty sexual conquests in less than four years, gives up sex altogether in the hope that the energy thus saved will enable him to think more clearly, while Bernard and the Savage justify their aversion to immediate sexual gratification by imagining they are in love. Yet while this might seem to suggest a yearning for authenticity, for something more real than state-sanctioned promiscuity, the fact that in the case of both Bernard and the Savage the object of their desire is the vacuous Lenina rather undercuts the effect of their romantic idealism. The old-fashioned male ideal of chivalric love, rather than being held up as a contrasting positive, is exposed as mere fantasy projection (onto a singularly blank screen), quite as ludicrous as the mindless sexual indulgence to which it is opposedand for that matter, quite as clearly socially constructed. Nevertheless, this is not to say that Huxley altogether avoids the trap of merely reversing the utopian equation, and judging the alternative society by the standards of todays, rather than vice versa. While the search for authenticity in the form of true love may be represented as bogus, it is clear that Huxley does imply some absolute standards whereby the values

DYSTOPIA

125

of Brave New World can be judged as specious and inauthentic. As Adorno points out, although Huxley satirizes conventional morality, showing a world where promiscuity is just as moral as sexual decorum used to be, the ideological bias of his own critique is hardly less conventional: In its proclamation of the bourgeois nature of what claims to be unbourgeois, [Huxleys] thesis itself becomes ensnared in bourgeois habits Like that of many emancipated Englishmen, his consciousness is preformed by the very Puritanism he abjures. He fails to distinguish between the liberation of sexuality and its debasement. [p.103] For Huxley, what is most repellent about Brave New World is not so much its oppression of its citizens (in any event, he is only really concerned with the problems of the Alpha lite), as the vulgarity of its mass culture. Of the rebels, the only one who is not also the object of satire is Helmholz, the creative artist who is unable to find an audience in a world of mindless conformitya world where even Shakespeare is no longer relevant. What Huxley proposes as sources of absolute value by which dystopia is judged and found wanting are Art, and still more so, Religionit is instructive to discover what the really forbidden books are that Mustapha Mond keeps locked up in the safe in his office: the Bible, The Imitation of Christ, William Jamess The Varieties of Religious Experience, works by Cardinal Newman and Maine de Biran. These, it is implied, represent the objective, transcendent reality lost sight of in Brave New Worlds pursuit of subjective happinessa reality whose ideological character Huxley never acknowledges.11 Despite such variations in approach, however, the pattern of resistance in dystopian fiction remains remarkably consistent: the reassertion of traditional and individual values is accompanied in each case by the displacement of political resistance into the sexual realm. While D-503 and E-330, Bernard, Helmholz, and the Savage, Winston and Julia all desire the destruction of the State, at any rate in theory, what is actually dramatized is more their sexual than political unorthodoxy. Yet perhaps the most striking similarity of all lies in the fact that, in every case, rebellion is shown as doomed to defeat. Although in We the battle goes on, E-330 is executed, and the lobotomized D-503 renews his allegiance to The Benefactor; Helmholz and Bernard are exiled, while the Savage commits suicide; and Winston and Julia betray both themselves and each other. For all its parodic inversion of the utopian ideal, one feature which dystopia reproduces virtually unchanged is the myth that resistance is futile. Indeed, there is a curious inevitability to the process whereby the individual takes on the might of the monolithic State, and is ultimately destroyed by it

126

NARRATING UTOPIA

an inevitability which perhaps stems from the terms in which the confrontation is set up. To begin with, the dualistic opposition between the values of the individual and those of society ultimately places the individual in a situation where defeat can scarcely be avoided. While secrecy and privacy are appealing in the context of the invasive surveillance practiced by the dystopian state, they remain essentially defensive strategies; collecting obsolete artifacts, wearing old-fashioned clothing, and engaging in anachronistic sexual behaviour offer only symbolic resistance to the power of the State, while the individual, alone and isolated, can realistically do little to challenge the collective might and technological resources which society can deploy. As in the traditional utopia, there is very little by way of collective organization to mediate between the individual and centralized authority. Significantly, Zamyatins dystopia is the one where resistance is shown as coming closest to success. It is hardly coincidental that it is the only one where resistance is shown as collective and organized, rather than merely an individual gesture of defiance. Yet the oppositional struggle that dystopian fiction dramatizes is not simply that of the individual against society. In its parodic inversion of the utopian dream of order, dystopian fiction effectively rewrites its underlying fantasy of the patriarchal appropriation of the powers of the mother, focusing instead on the dream of the sons unsuccessful rebellion against the father. It is noteworthy, to begin with, that all the male rebels against patriarchal authority (with the lone exception of Helmholz) feel themselves to be in some way inadequate: D-503 feels his hairiness is somehow primitive; Bernard is sensitive about his height; the Savages insecurity goes back to his lonely, fatherless childhood; and Winston is painfully aware of his physical frailty. Yet they all take on an authority symbolized by a larger-than-life male figure who has all the confidence and power that they lack. D-503 is clearly intimidated by The Benefactor: although at one point, briefly, he laughs at his baldness, it is rather guilty laughter, and for the most part the emphasis is on The Benefactors almost superhuman power. Bernard is intimidated, and the Savage outargued by the sleekly self-confident World Controller, Mustapha Mond, and the symbolic authority of Big Brother is given concrete expression in OBriens physical dominationmost glaringly in the scene where he actually pulls out one of Winstons teeth with his bare hands. The outcome of such a confrontation is predictable enoughto the extent, indeed, that the actual conclusions of We, Brave New World, and Nineteen Eighty-Four are strikingly similar. All three end with the defeat of the rebellious male, the triumph of paternal authority, and the incidental destruction of the female who has been presumptuous enough to usurp the love which the father-figure sees as rightfully his. In We, the conclusion

DYSTOPIA

127

is particularly disturbing, with the now acquiescent D-503 sitting alongside The Benefactor as E-330 is tortured: Then she was led in under the Gas Bell Glass. Her face became very white, and since her eyes were dark and large, this created an extremely beautiful effect. When they started pumping the air out of the Gas Bell Glass she threw her head back, half closing her eyes and compressing her lips: this reminded me of something This was gone through three times [p.221] The sexual overtones of D-503s description are unmistakable, and it is clear that the triple repetition of this quasi-orgasm is not merely an arbitrary exercise in cruelty, but also a manifestation of superior potency: only The Benefactor could induce such symptoms three times in rapid succession. The conclusion of Nineteen Eighty-Four is equally indecent, as Winston is alternately tortured and comforted by the muscular OBrien. When he encounters Julia again, after his release, she arouses no feeling in him other than a vague distaste, and he leaves her to return to the caf, where he can indulge in loving thoughts of Big Brotherand in an almost voluptuous longing for the bullet which will penetrate the back of his neck: He was walking down the white-tiled corridor, with the feeling of walking in sunlight, and an armed guard at his back. The long hopedfor bullet was entering his brain. He gazed up at the enormous face. Forty years it had taken him to learn what kind of smile was hidden beneath the dark moustache. O cruel, needless misunderstanding! O stubborn, self-willed exile from the loving breast! Two gin-sodden tears trickled down the sides of his nose. But it was all right, everything was all right, the struggle was finished. He had won the victory over himself. He loved Big Brother. [p.256] Even in Brave New World, where the homoerotic overtones are less overt, the scenario concludes in a similar fashion. The Savages mother dies, Lenina is killed (whether actually or only ritually is never made quite clear), and the Savage expiates his sexual guilt for having succumbed to heterosexual desire by hanging himself in, of all things, a lighthouse which continues to point to the sky as the Savage dangles dead at its base, in yet another symbol of triumphant phallic authority. Thus, while dystopian parody of the utopian ideal exposes many of its underlying implications, the very closeness of the relationship between parody and original results in the reproduction of some of the latters most problematic features. While designed as an attack on the utopian dream of a static, all-embracing order, dystopian fiction nevertheless accepts

128

NARRATING UTOPIA

utopias underlying premise: that its ideal of a synchronous total system is the only viable alternative to the chaos and flux of history in process. All that differs in dystopias parodic inversion is that the utopian ideal is presented as undesirable, the corollary being that a return to the world as it is now becomes the goal. As a counter to the threat of a utopian future, the dystopian writer often ends up merely reasserting the values of the past.12 In its own way, in fact, the basic impulse of dystopian fantasy is just as regressive as that of the traditional utopia, and for all its success in transcending some of the latters narrative limitations, it may be seen that the underlying structure of the traditional utopian paradigm still persists. Although, as we have seen, dystopian narrative begins in medias res, rather than with the customary journey to utopia, this is not to say that the journey motif is altogether dispensed with. Where the utopian narrative starts in the everyday world, moves to utopia, then returns, what dystopian fiction enacts is the same process, only in reverse. Here the narrative begins and ends in the dystopian future, but frames a symbolic return to the past. D503s first irrational act is to accompany E-330 to the House of Antiquity; Bernard and Lenina travel to the tribal Reservation; and Winstons first illicit assignation with Julia takes the form of a trip out to the unspoilt countryside. And while these symbolic journeys may be seen in the light of dystopian fictions overall opposition of the values of the past to those of the nightmare dystopian future, their underlying psychological implications prove on closer examination to be strikingly similar to those of their utopian counterparts. In We, D-503 and E-330 are greeted at the House of Antiquity by an old crone, whose mouth consist[ing] solely of pleats and folds seems grown over, somehow (p.40). When she opens this vaginal aperture, much to D-503s astonishmentit seemed altogether unbelievable that she would break into speech (p.40)it is to invite them into her house. They ascend a wide dark staircase (p.40) into an apartment whose gorgeous organic chaos could not be reconciled in any equations whatsoever (p.41), and D-503 finds himself unaccountably reminded of the sexual act. Bernard and Lenina, in Brave New World, ascend to the reservation by way of a channel between precipitous banks; after rounding a projection, they then enter a water-worn ravine (p.92), accompanied all the while by the sound of drums as though the whole air had come alive and were pulsing, pulsing with the indefatigable movement of blood (p.92). On finally reaching their destination they encounter the ultimate object of disgusta real, live biological mother, Linda, whose previous employment just happens to have been in the Fertilizing Room. And in Nineteen Eighty-Four a similar pattern is evident: Winston and Julia make their way along a narrow track into the woods:

DYSTOPIA

129

They came to the fallen tree that she had spoken of. The girl hopped over and forced apart the bushes, in which there did not seem to be an opening. When Winston followed her, he found that they were in a natural clearing, a tiny grassy knoll surrounded by tall saplings that shut it in completely. [p.106] Here they proceed to make love, but before doing so, Winston actually sees the landscape which has been recurring in his dreamsa landscape invariably associated with his mother. As in the traditional utopia, the underlying dream is of finding refuge in the security of the maternal womb. In addition, albeit from a different perspective, dystopian fiction reenacts the triumph of an essentially masculine dream of order. As we have seen, at the conclusion of dystopia and utopia alike (with the partial exception of We, where resistance continues despite the defeat of E-330 and D-503) patriarchal authority is shown as reigning supreme.13 While this may be undesirable, it nevertheless indicates an implicit acceptance of the premise of the traditional utopiathat the establishment of a permanent, static order is at any rate practicable.14 Writing in 1939, Orwell declared that: The terrifying thing about the modern dictatorships is that they are something entirely unprecedented. Their end cannot be foreseen. In the past every tyranny was sooner or later overthrown, or at least resisted, because of human nature, which as a matter of course desired liberty. But we cannot be at all certain that human nature is constant. It may be just as possible to produce a breed of men who do not wish for liberty as to produce a breed of hornless cows. The Inquisition failed, but then the Inquisition had not the resources of the modern state. The radio, press censorship, standardized education and the secret police have altered everything. Mass suggestion is a science of the last twenty years, and we do not yet know how successful it will be. [Essays, Journalism, Letters, Volume 1, p.419] Paradoxically, while the concept of some kind of essential, invariant human nature lies at the root of dystopias critique of the traditional utopia, what dystopia dramatizes is the possibility of that nature being altereda horrifying possibility which can only be avoided by a return to the past. Thus, while the traditional utopia may be characterized as a narrative in which an oppositional impulse is embedded in an essentially conservative form (Bammer, p.45), dystopian fiction, as Jean Pfaelzer argues, is formally and historically, structurally and contextually, a conservative genre (Parody and Satire, p.61)one in which even the oppositional impulse leads back to the status quo. Nevertheless, there are alternatives to the depiction of order

130

NARRATING UTOPIA

triumphant: despite the defeatist tendency of much dystopian fictionits despairing acknowledgment that the worst may very well happensuch defeatism is not necessarily an inherent feature of the genre. Although the result of the struggle between the all-too-human individual and virtually superhuman authority is predictable enough, the outcome of a struggle depends not only on the relative strengths of the opponents, but also to some extent on the terms of the contest. As in real life, to confront a more powerful opponent directly is to court defeat, however gallantto opt for failure, however heroic. D-503 in the presence of The Benefactor, Bernard and the Savage in that of Mustapha Mond, Winston in the hands of OBrien, have already lost before they even meet their opponents. The transaction is a foregone conclusion. Yet it remains to be seen whether there are not other strategiesthe fictional equivalent of guerilla tactics, perhaps, where the weaker side chooses the conditions of battle, and may ultimately triumph, even over a stronger opponent. Rewriting Dystopia: Atwood, The Handmaids Tale In this context, Atwoods The Handmaids Tale is worth looking at more closely. Although, as has been suggested, Atwoods text is in very much the same tradition as its dystopian predecessors, it also reveals some interesting departures from the norm. Gilead, Atwoods vision of a theocratic dictatorship set in the United States of the not-very-distant future, in many ways closely resembles the worlds portrayed by Zamyatin and Orwell: it, too, is an authoritarian, patriarchal state (authority being wielded in the name of that ultimate patriarch, God the Father), and is once again a primarily urban society, which relies on extensive surveillance to enforce both political and sexual orthodoxy. At first sight, indeed, it would appear that the individual is equally powerless in the face of authority. Offred, the protagonist, is as helpless a victim as any of her fictional predecessors. Even the religious basis of Atwoods dystopia makes relatively little difference to the essential nature of the society described. While Gileads values may differ ostensibly from those of Zamyatins One State or Orwells Oceania, the basic principle of insisting on universal conformity remains constant. Despite abolishing the worship of God, in fact, Zamyatins, Orwells, and indeed Huxleys dystopias all effectively replace it with quasi-religious cults centred on a patriarchal authority figure. Religion serves, as it does in Atwoods Gilead, as an effective instrument of control; if it figures more largely in her dystopia, the difference is primarily one of emphasis. Where Atwoods fiction differs most obviously is in the gender of its protagonist, which radically alters the underlying scenario of conflict

DYSTOPIA

131

between father and son, in which the average male confronts the omnipotent authority or the supermale patriarch, and is doomed to defeat. This is not to say, of course, that Offred does any more by way of effectively challenging authority: at best, she is a witness to the challenges of others her mothers, her friend Moiras, her companion Ofglens, all of which end in varieties of defeat. Even her attempts at escape are orchestrated by othersby her husband, Luke, or by Nick, her lover. Indeed, in many ways she is the most passive of all the rebels against dystopia. Yet for all her passivity, Offred is by no means simply a victim of the all-powerful state. Although she is humiliated, forced against her will into what is tantamount to slavery, separated from her friends, husband, childeven stripped of her nameshe never concedes defeat, as do D-503, the Savage, or Winston Smith. In sheerly practical terms she may do even less than they by way of actively challenging authority, but what differs is the way in which her resistance is represented. Far more exclusively than any other dystopian writer, Atwood chooses to focus on the private consciousness of her protagoniston the one realm that the State cannot successfully invade. Whether this is in fact the case is, of course, arguable: as we have seen, a central premise of the earlier dystopias is that, in the last analysis, the State can control individual consciousnessthat the human mind is simply another territory that can be colonized. Lobotomized, D-503 renews his allegiance to The Benefactor and the One State; tortured and brainwashed, Winston Smith lapses into maudlin adoration of Big Brother. Huxleys World State, more confident of its power, sees independent thought as so little of a threat that such radical procedures are not even needed: the small minority of dissidents can easily be contained on the margins of society, in penal colonies in places like the Falkland Islands; only the Savage, lacking the benefit of proper conditioning, tries to lead an existence wholly independent of the Statebut ends up killing himself. Yet while this might seem the ultimate admission of defeat, suicide is presented in The Handmaids Tale in a different light, as a radical refusal of the States authority. Both Ofglen and Offreds predecessor as the Commanders handmaid take that route, and are to an extent honoured for doing so: while self-destructive, suicide is seen as a gesture of defiance, rather than surrendera willed removal of oneself from the sphere of the States coercive power. It is not Offreds solution, however: she sets as her goal survival, which in turn involves compromise, though not surrender. What The Handmaids Tale charts is the process whereby Offred, even though a prisoner of the dystopian state, attempts the precarious task of preserving both her life and her integrity. In focusing on this, Atwood resorts, like Zamyatin, to first person narration. Whereas the narrative perspective of Brave New World and

132

NARRATING UTOPIA

Nineteen Eighty-Four, showing the individual in society, serves to heighten the sense of his helplessness and vulnerability, Atwoods narration shows the State through the subjective perspective of the individual. The effect, however, is very different from that created by Zamyatins use of the same device. While everything is filtered through D-503s consciousness, his narrative utterance is permeated by the controlling discourse of the State. Even as he is led by E-330 into increasingly active resistance, he engages in an incessant inner dialogue as he tries to explain and justify his conduct in the light of the official values which he has so thoroughly internalized. In effect, it is his subjective consciousness that constitutes the main battleground for the tension between the conflicting ideologies of the State and the dissidents, whose challenge to assumptions long taken for granted causes him such acute discomfort. D-503 is already a product of the State: the very language he uses reflects the extent to which its values are a part of him, and when he finally undergoes the Grand Operation to cure him of fantasythat is, the power of independent thinkingone senses a certain feeling of relief on his part that the tormenting inner dialogue has finally been stilled, that things have been made simple once again. In Offreds case, however, the values of Gilead have never been part of her consciousness: she is a creature of her own past, and while this does not automatically transform her into an active opponent of the new order, there is little doubt as to her contempt for it. There is no battle between competing discourses to be fought out within her mind, since she is already clear which side she is on. Although her thoughts are about all she does have left her, the privacy of her mind remains inviolable. For all the elaboration of the States surveillance mechanisms, it cannot prevent her from committing treason in her own mind, from thoughtcrime, to use Orwells terminologyremembering with affection those whom the State has sought to destroy, judging the system and its representatives and finding them wanting. Admittedly, much the same could be said of Winston Smith, prior to his arrestbut again, the difference of perspective is crucial. By focusing so exclusively on Offreds subjective consciousness, Atwood privileges her perceptions to a far greater degree. While she is scarcely in a position to take effective action against authority, that authority is seen only through her eyesa context in which its pretensions become more than a little ridiculous. Context is all (p.136), Offred remarks at one point, and her narrative goes a long way towards demonstrating the truth of this. In the context of Offreds narrative, for example, patriarchal authority no longer looms as large: in place of the superhuman, machine-like Benefactor, the Godlike Ford, the all-seeing Big Brother, isa void. Nominally, Gilead is a society dedicated to the great glory of God the Father, but from Offreds point of view His is not a presence, but an absence: in

DYSTOPIA

133

His place there are merely rather pathetic surrogatesthe Commanders. Unlike the representatives of authority elsewhere (the suave Mustapha Mond, the brutal OBrien) the Commanders almost invariably appear in contexts which render them ridiculous. Offreds own Commander, with his desire for the forbidden delights of Scrabble, his furtive glee over the schoolboy obscenities scrawled in his Latin textbook, his excitement at a trip to a brothel where sexual allure is provided by old cheerleaders outfits and secondhand Bunny costumes, is merely ludicrous. Even his real power, his power over life and death, is undermined by being presented in the context of Offreds accompanying awareness of his confusion and incompetence. He appears genuinely puzzled by the course of events, surprised by Offreds dislike of her role, as if dimly aware that the perfect order that has been created is not quite working as it should. And as a representative of God the Father, he is conspicuously lacking in the sexual vitality of the Old Testament patriarchs, being both probably sterile (as even his wife concedes) and sexually inept: Ive had him, Moira remarks offhandedly, hes the pits (p.228). Unlike Mond or OBrien, Offreds Commander appears vulnerable: at the end he is shown as worried and helpless (p.276), visibly shrinking as he sees himself being dragged down by Offreds apparent disgracethe victim, in effect, of his failure to control someone he had regarded as a mere possession. Nor do the other male figures fare much better. In her earlier fictions, Atwoods virtuosity in evoking sexual disgust is already apparent: in Life Before Man, for instance, a woman describes a sexual encounter with a particularly bland civil servant as like being in bed with a large and fairly active slab of Philadelphia cream cheese (p.213)and in The Handmaids Tale she allows that virtuosity full rein. At the Prayvaganza, Offred reflects that while the presiding Commander, with his uniform and decorations, may appear impressive enough, she has the power to imagine him otherwise: in bed with his Wife and Handmaid, fertilizing away like mad, like a rutting salmon (p.204). And at the mass wedding ceremony for military heroes newly returned from the front, Offred again imagines the reality of their sexual lives: .... momentous grunts and sweating, damp furry encounters; or better, ignominious failures, cocks like three-week-old carrots, anguished fumblings upon flesh cold and unresponding as uncooked fish. [p.209] Laughter becomes a powerful weapon in The Handmaids Tale. It does so do good. It does, insists Moira (p.208) when Offred (repressing her impulse to giggle) protests at her crude but vivid fantasy of one of the trainees engaging in oral sex with the redoubtable Aunt Lydia. In its

134

NARRATING UTOPIA

carnivalesque reassertion of the physicality of the body, such laughter implies the hollowness of the rgimes official faade of reason and spirituality. Laughter asserts the humanity of the person who laughs, while at the same time undermining the authority of those who are laughed at. For all its limitations as a practical political tool (although satire and ridicule have never been particularly welcome to those in power), in the context of a fictional narrative it decisively affects the impression made by the representatives of the dystopian state. While Zamyatin, too, sees laughter as a liberating force, it works only sporadically: although D-503 may laugh at the bald-headed man who is the reality behind the cast-iron image of The Benefactor, his power is too real to be laughed at for long. Mustapha Mond and OBrien are not laughed at at all. In The Handmaids Tale, however, mirth rhymes with birth (p.138): laughter provides a way out of the all-embracing security which the State seeks to impose on the individuals whom it is striving to mould in its own image. Where the dystopian dissidents of Zamyatin, Huxley, and Orwell seek refuge from the States authority in the womb-like security of the past, Atwood presents liberation as a process of going forward, into the unknown. In addition, laughter represents the assertion of alternative perspectives on reality; it speaks a different language, one which challenges the official discourse of the State. Beneath its surface frivolity lies something more serious: while the schoolboy dog-LatinNolite te bastardes carborundorum scrawled on the floor of Offreds cupboard may be merely a furtive joke to the Commander, for Offred it is a coded inscription, a gesture of defiance from a woman whose death has put her beyond the reach of the States authority. While, as Orwell perceived, the standardization and impoverishment of language is an essential of the States control of individual thought, Atwoods rebels exploit the richness and ambiguity of a linguistic realm over which the State has no jurisdiction. (It is significant that Offreds interactions with the Commander, outside the sphere of their official relations, involve their playing a competitive word game.) In the end, the States attempt to impose the authority of its own official, monologic discourse is thwarted by the sheer variety of associations which language derives from contexts beyond its control. The very codeword of the resistanceMaydayis fraught with complex and ambiguous associations wholly alien to the simplistic fundamentalism of the dystopian state: Mayday is a call for help in a foreign language, a carnival reminder of pagan fertility rituals, and the chief festival of international socialism. In the context of the book, it is also a declaration of independence. In Atwoods hands, then, opposition becomes both more complex and more far-reaching than in the earlier dystopias: what she grasps is the paradox that the farther the State attempts to extend its power, the more

DYSTOPIA

135

arenas it creates where resistance is possible. As Barthes argues in his discussion of Fourier, the utopian impulse to determine everything down to the last detail ultimately deconstructs itself, establishing a system so complex that it inevitably breaks down. Thus, the more that is forbidden, the greater the number of potentially subversive actions becomes. And while Offred makes no effort to conceal her weaknesses, her defeats, her failures in courage, her passivity, her shameful dependence on her lover, her opposition to the monolithic authority of the State is in fact a good deal more effective than she realizes. However passive her resistance, she provides an audience for the resistance of others, a space in which the implications of their actions can resonate. The point that Atwood stresses is that no matter how powerless, how often defeated, the rebel is not alone. When Moira escapes from the Re-Education Centre, after overpowering Aunt Lydia in the washroom, hers is not merely a personal bid for freedom; at the same time she exposes the limitations of authority: Moira was our fantasy. We hugged her to us, she was with us in secret, a giggle; she was the lava beneath the crust of daily life. In the light of Moira, the Aunts were less fearsome and more absurd. Their power had a flaw to it. They could be shanghaied in toilets. [p.125] It is, indeed, in Bakhtins terms, a classic example of the carnivalesque uncrowning of official authority. Aunt Elizabeth, the symbol not only of authority, but of female purity, is overpowered in a lavatory overflowing with excrement; she is led downstairs to the basement, where she is stripped of her clothing, and dressed in the red garments of the Handmaid, while Moira now dons the robes of authority. In one action the official hierarchy of dystopian society is completely reversed. Thus, despite the extent of the States attempt to impose the authority of an all-embracing static system, the result is merely to increase the potential scope of opposition. Even something so apparently trivial as gossip becomes subversive: when Offred asks the Commander to tell her whats going on, her choice of language implies a process, a continuous dynamic which may at any moment result in change. The necessity of imposing control implies the continued existence of something that has to be controlled. The television news, though rigorously censored by the authorities, implies by its self-evident selectivity the fact of other events, which are not reported. The more absolute the authority the State seeks to wield, the more precarious it becomes. This is not to say, of course, that this renders the collapse of authority inevitable. As Stuart Hall observes: The multiplication of new points of antagonism characteristic of

136

NARRATING UTOPIA

our emerging post-industrial societies, while making available new potential sites of intervention, further fragments the political field, dispersing rather than unifying the different social constituencies. [Quoted in Levitas, Concept of Utopia, p.197] Like Orwell and Huxley, and to a lesser extent Zamyatin, Atwood chooses not to address the question of how effective resistance to the all-powerful state may be mounted (an evasion which clearly echoes the utopian reluctance to specify how the more perfect society might be created): at best, she shows more clearly the points at which it is vulnerable. Nevertheless, it is clear that Atwood effectively transforms both the main terms in the classic dystopian equation, creating a protagonist whose passive resistance and satiric eye produce a very different impact than do the direct challenges to authority presented by the male rebels of earlier dystopian fiction, while at the same time stripping patriarchal authority of much of its aura of invulnerability. In addition, she is more sceptical of the basic premise of utopia and dystopia alike, that the creation of an enduring total system is actually possible. Unlike Zamyatins One State, Huxleys World State, or Orwells Oceania, Gilead has clearly indicated limits, both spatial and temporal. There are other places to which escape is possible, and it is apparent that, as a social experiment, it has only a finite existence.15 In the epilogue, Gilead becomes the focus of a twenty-second century academic symposium, from which it becomes clear that its existence was merely a transient historical phenomenonalbeit one which provided an abundance of research opportunities. Unlike the earlier dystopias, whose terror lies partly in the threat of their being eternal, Gilead is ephemeral, deprived of an eternal future in part because of its inability to sever itself from the past. The connection with contemporary reality, which utopian fiction seeks to obscure, and dystopian society to obliterate, is here clearly manifest. Gileads fatal weakness lies in its inability to cut itself off from history: Atwood demonstrates what is one of the principal limitations of all revolutions, whether for good or ill: the fact that they are made by those who have been conditioned by the values of the society which the revolution seeks to overthrow. It is the States belief, of course, that this limitation can be overcome. The aunts repeatedly assure their sceptical charges that, while they may find it difficult to adjust to the new order, it will be easier for generations to come: You are a transitional generation, said Aunt Lydia. It is the hardest for you. We know the sacrifices you are being expected to make. It is hard when men revile you. For the ones who come after you, it will be easier. They will accept their duties with willing hearts.

DYSTOPIA

137

She did not say: Because they will have no memories, of any other way. [p.111] Until that time, however, memory, with the different perspectives it provides, remains a potent threat to the authority of the State. Offred is just one of innumerable individuals who remember how things were before, who remember the outrages perpetrated in the name of the new order, who can contrast now with then, and consider the implications of the difference. Nor are the rulers themselves immune to the power of memory, to the influence of the past: unable to control their previously socialized lust for women as sex-objects, they recreate the brothels which their puritan revolution was meant to abolish. Between the hypocrisy of the rulers and the mocking laughter of the ruled, it is clear that the new order is constructed on shaky foundations. In both its narrative approach, then, and in its presentation of the nature of the authoritarian states limitations, The Handmaids Tale represents a radical extension of the dystopian critique of the traditional utopia. Nor is it only the limitations of utopian idealism or authoritarian trends in contemporary society that Atwood seeks to expose; in places, it is clear that The Handmaids Tale is also addressing the flawed assumptions underlying specific aspects of earlier dystopian fiction. In particular, Atwood challenges Zamyatins and Orwells stereotypical depiction of traditional images of female sexuality as more natural than, and hence subversive of the States sexual norms. As we have seen, both Zamyatins E-330 and Orwells Julia resort to old-fashioned methods of sexual allure by way of defying the official sexual ethic of the State, and by doing so render themselves far more attractive than the state-approved partner with whom the protagonist has previously been involved. In The Handmaids Tale, however, the equivalent scene, in which Offred sheds her nun-like uniform and puts on make-up, high heels, and a revealing outfit largely comprised of feathers, is designed to illustrate, not the subversive power of natural female sexuality, but rather the extent to which such stereotypes are merely the obverse of the male fear of female sexuality which informs Gileads puritanism. While Gileads stringent moral code is ostensibly designed to protect women from predatory male sexuality, its designers continue to dream of the old stereotypes, and find their sexual outlets at that archetypal locale of male fantasy, the brothel. Perhaps the most ludicrous aspect of Offreds trip to the brothel with her Commander is his pathetic belief that the trip is somehow exciting for her. Where Offred defies the States sexual norms is not in overt displays of male-approved traditional femininity, but in her illicit encounters with the Commanders chauffeur, which take place in the darkness, and which she never really

138

NARRATING UTOPIA

finds words to describe. The subversiveness of such sexual conduct lies, familiarly enough, in its privacysomething which her monthly couplings in the Commanders marriage bed signally lacksyet even so, Offred remains dubious as to just how far this too constitutes a form of compromise with male authority. Where Winston Smith sees his sexual relations with Julia as a battle, the climax a victory a blow struck against the Party a political act (p.112), for Offred, so simplistic an opposition of natural sexuality to official authority is impossible. Having experienced the unequal sexual power relations not only of Gilead, but of the society that preceded it, she cannot help but be aware the sexual arena is one where, while rebellion may be possible, it remains fraught with complicity. Thus, The Handmaids Tale presents a dystopia where the lines of battle are far more ambiguously drawn. Offreds challenges to the States authority are not always uncritically presented as positive, and while her memory constitutes an alternative perspective by which the State can be judged, there is far less of the nostalgia that characterizes both We and Nineteen Eighty-Four, where the past is portrayed as somehow more authentic, more real than the present. By contrast, Offreds recollections of contemporary America, with its pornography, its sex industry, its continual threat of rape and violent assault, hardly offer a glittering alternative to the new morality of Gilead. Indeed, it becomes abundantly clear in the course of the narrative that many of her survival skills, her capacity for secrecy and passive resistance, were learned from her experience as a woman in the society which Gilead replaced. Indeed, while Gilead evidently collapses at last, it is clear that the world of the future that succeeds its fall is far from ideal either. The academic discussion of Gilead, with its sexist jokes, its smug refusal to take any kind of moral stance in its discussion of what happened, indicates much the same kind of intellectual elitism and abdication of responsibility that was presumably one of the preconditions for the establishment of Gilead in the first place. This sense of the force of historical continuity, of the overlap between past, present, and future, enables Atwood to avoid the often simplistic, polarized alternatives of earlier dystopian fiction. The dualistic opposition between future and pastthe one associated with totalitarian conformity, the other with a vaguely liberal conception of freedomis replaced by an altogether more complex sense of their interrelationship. The result is a vision which is critical, not only of utopia, or of the society to which utopia proposes an alternative, but also of the dystopian response itself. It is this criticaland indeed, self-criticalimpulse which may be seen to underlie a series of attempts to likewise transform the nature of the utopian vision.

DREAMS OF FREEDOM

5. Libertarian Alternatives: Morris, News from Nowhere; Bogdanov, Red Star; Huxley, Island
The basic premise of dystopian fiction, of course, is rooted in the assumption that the utopian ideal is inherently repressivethat the establishment of the machinery of State repression nevertheless has its origins in a genuinely utopian impulse. Not the least disturbing aspect of We, Brave New World, and The Handmaids Tale, in fact, is the apparent sincerity of the belief of those in authority that they are actually doing good. Only in Nineteen EightyFour, where OBrien brazenly admits that power is its own reward, is the rationale that authority is wielded in the best interests of society as a whole abandonedbut this is very much the exception rather than the rule. The patriarchal authority figures of the other dystopian narrativesThe Benefactor, Mustapha Mond, even the Commandersshare with Wellss Samurai, the officers of Bellamys industrial army, and the priest-rulers of the City of the Sun, the conviction that authority is a duty rather than a matter of self-interest. Whatever the effect of their exercise of that authority, the underlying aspiration remains in keeping with the traditional utopian ideal: the creation of a better, more rational social order, from whose allembracing security the citizen cannot help but benefit. Yet a distaste for the generally repressive and authoritarian tenor of the traditional utopia, such as that which activates the dystopian critique of the utopian ideal, can also be combined with very different approaches approaches which do not necessarily presuppose the utopian aspiration to be flawed in itself. In News from Nowhere (1890), for example, William Morris is among the first to call into question the premises of the traditional utopia by proposing an alternative embodying radically different values: libertarian and decentralist, rather than repressive and authoritarian. Morriss vision is of a Communist far future in which the state has withered away, and in this he is followed by Alexander Bogdanov, whose Red Star (1908), written in the aftermath of the abortive Russian revolution of 1905, envisages an equally decentralized (although noticeably less pastoral) Communist societyremoved in space rather than time, however, being set on the planet Mars. Nor is this the only ideological perspective from which the traditional utopia has been reimagined: Aldous Huxleys Island (1962) offers another libertarian vision, but one whose emphasis on spiritual values seems explicitly designed to counter the materialist bias of the Wellsian utopia. Whether, however, such conscious challenges to the

142

NARRATING UTOPIA

values and political assumptions of the traditional utopia are any more successful a recipe for resolving the problematic implications of the traditional narrative paradigm than, say, Wellss primarily narrative experimentation, remains to be seen. While all three works indicate a clear awareness of the tradition of utopian narrative, it is those of Morris and Huxley that most directly address its limitations. Indeed, both News from Nowhere and Island were conceived of in direct response to what each perceived as the problematic character of specific works in the utopian tradition. News from Nowhere was quite deliberately designed as a rebuttal of Bellamys Looking Backward, which Morris had already reviewed in extremely hostile terms in The Commonweal, the paper of the Socialist League. First published in serial form in the pages of The Commonweal, its polemic intent is quite clear: to offer what Morris saw as a genuinely Socialist alternative to the stifling conformity of Bellamys utopia. Huxley likewise set out, in Island, to remedy the deficiencies of an earlier workin this case his own dystopia, Brave New Worldwhich he had criticized in a subsequent Foreword (1946) for its lack of any positive alternative to the insanity of Utopia on the one hand and the lunacy of the Savage on the other (Brave New World, p.7). Island represents the working out of that positive alternative, whose outlines are first suggested in the Foreword. News from Nowhere It is not difficult to see why Morris so disliked Looking Backward: almost every aspect of Bellamys utopia, from its regimentation to the crass vulgarity of its authors conception of the role of culture, represented the virtual antithesis of everything Morris stood for.1 Nevertheless, it is worth examining in more detail some of the specific objections which Morris raised in his highly critical review, particularly given the light which they shed on the nature of the countervailing ideals which he sought to embody in News from Nowhere. To begin with, Morris accurately perceived that, while Looking Backward purported to offer a vision of a society in which class conflict had been resolved, its values were exclusively those of the middle class: The only ideal of life which such a man can see is that of the industrious professional middle-class men of today purified from their crime of complicity with the monopolist class, and become independent instead of being, as they now are, parasitical.2 As we have already seen, Dr Leetes sympathy for the plight of the few educated in the late nineteenth century, living in a society largely

LIBERTARIAN ALTERNATIVES

143

comprised of ignorant, boorish, coarse, wholly uncultivated men and women (Looking Backward, p.122), to say nothing of his singular view that the rich and cultured of the period were little better off than the poor (p.122) gives a fair idea of Bellamys class bias. To Morris, Bellamys utopian ideal represents, not radical social reform, but rather the maintenance of existing privilege: an ideal utopian only in its abolition of guilt. Where Bellamy offers the vision of a world in which a bourgeois lifestyle is available to all, Morris sees its maintenance as incompatible with the existence of social and economic justice. Culture, for Morris, is an integral aspect of society, a superstructural expression of its economic foundations: the transformation of societys economic basis and political institutions must necessarily transform its cultural values and the forms in which they are expressed. What he thought of Bellamys attempt to preserve unchanged the values of the late nineteenth century bourgeoisie in a radically different socioeconomic context may be divined from his comment, in a letter to Bruce Glasier: I wouldnt care to live in such a cockney paradise (Glasier, p.198). Nevertheless, it was on the organization of Bellamys utopia, and the assumptions underlying it, that Morris concentrated most of his fire. The elaborate structure of Bellamys industrial army, and the complex system of incentives to productive labour, ranging from early retirement to the prospect of a more attractive marital partner, struck him as merely laughable: Mr Bellamy worries himself unnecessarily in the seeking (with obvious failure) some incentive to labour to replace the fear of starvation, which is at present our only one, whereas it cannot too often be repeated that the true incentive to useful and happy labour is and must be pleasure of the work itself. [p.506] The provision of early retirement, in particularBellamys utopian equivalent of the paradisiacal dream of idlenesswas something which, in Morriss view, wholly missed the point: ....everybody is to begin the serious work of production at the age of twenty-one, work three years as a labourer, and then choose his skilled occupation and work till he is forty-five, when he is to knock off his work and amuse himself (improve his mind, if he has one left him). Heavens! think of a man of forty-five changing his habits suddenly and by compulsion! [p.505] In Looking Backward, work is a necessary evil, its rigours palliated by an elaborate system of honours and rewards, but still sufficiently arduous as to require both strict discipline and a complex supervisory process to ensure

144

NARRATING UTOPIA

it gets donethe whole being coordinated by the industrial equivalent of a military high command. Conformity is enforced, while individual responsibility is minimizedvery much, in fact, as it is in the earlier utopias of More and Campanellaand to this Morris vigorously objected: It is necessary to point out that there are some socialists who do not think that the problem of the organization of life and necessary labour can be dealt with by a huge centralization, worked by a kind of magic for which no one feels himself responsible; that on the contrary it will be necessary for the unit of administration to be small enough for every citizen to feel himself responsible for its details, and be interested in them; that the individual man cannot shuffle off the business of life onto the shoulders of an abstraction called the State, but must deal with it in conscious association with each other; that variety of life is as much the aim of a true Communism as equality of condition, and that nothing but a union of these two will bring about real freedom [pp.5067] Morris also took exception to what he saw as Bellamys uncritical enthusiasm for technology (which, as we have already seen, serves in Looking Backward largely to conceal the processes of production), and still more so to his assumption that the transition to a utopian society could be a painless, automatic process, devoid of conflict. Nevertheless, it was clearly the centralization of Bellamys utopia, the States authoritarian assumption of responsibility and denial of individual agency, that he saw as most pernicious. One can only imagine, given the vehemence of Bellamys response to being labelled a socialist, how he must have reacted to Morriss dismissal of his utopia as State Communism. It is Communism of a very different cast, however, that underlies Morriss counterblast,3 News from Nowhereand that Morris, writing in 1890, consciously conceived of his utopia as Communist is worth emphasizing. While the old-fashioned view of Morris as only incidentally (if indeed at all) a Marxist has been comprehensively demolished by the studies of Paul Meier and E.P. Thompson,4 a lingering tendency to see Morriss utopia as a work of only vaguely radical sympathies persists. Engels description of Morris as a very rich art enthusiast but untalented politician,5 and as a sentimental socialist,6 perhaps encourages such a viewas indeed do such attempts to conscript News from Nowhere for the anarchist cause as Peter Kropotkins description of it as perhaps the most thoroughly and deeply anarchist conception of the future society that has ever been written (quoted in Meier, Volume 1, p.xxxviii). Morris, however, was in no doubt as to the character of the society he was describing. His own struggles with the anarchists within the Socialist

LIBERTARIAN ALTERNATIVES

145

League had given him a keen sense of the distinction between Anarchism and Communism, and in News from Nowhere the form of social organization is explicitly described as being the latter (p.76). While there is no longer formal government as suchdecisions being for the most part taken at the local, communal levelthis is in keeping with the withering away of the State envisaged in Marxist theory as characterizing Communisms final phase.7 And while there is of course a millenarian element in such a vision, a static quality very much akin to that of the traditional utopia, where Morris differs is in his refusal to gloss over the process of reaching the desired goal. Unlike Bellamy, whose utopia comes into being with smooth inevitability, by consensus, and with absolutely no violence, Morris emphasizes the sheer difficulty involved in the creation of a more perfect society. In marked contrast to the perfunctory accounts of utopias origins which characterize the traditional narrative paradigm, Morris devotes an entire chapterthe longest in the bookto describing the brutal class conflict from which his utopian society emerged, and the arduous process of reconstruction which was involved. Throughout the narrative, in fact, Morris consistently calls attention to what other utopian fictions seek to conceal: the problematic nature of the connection between reality and its utopian alternative. Rather than creating elaborate rational explanations to account for the narrators passage into utopia, Morris deliberately emphasizes the precarious, dreamlike quality of his presence in the society of the future. Both William Guest (as he chooses to call himself, without any pretence that it is his real name) and the utopians show an awareness that his account of himself does not really make sense, and both his embarrassment when their questions become too awkward and their courteous, but at the same time clearly evident avoidance of angles of inquiry that may expose the improbability of his story serve to call attention to the narratives fictional characterrather as Wells was to do later in A Modern Utopia. Often, and especially when the most disturbing aspects of the past are conjured up, the dream seems to fray at the edgesso that even the utopians become half aware of the reality by which the narrator is haunted. Following his long discussion of the past with Old Hammond, Dick (who acts as the narrators utopian guide) remarks: I am glad to have you again, and to find you and my kinsman have not quite talked yourselves into another world; I was half suspecting ... that you would be vanishing away from us, and began to picture my kinsman sitting in the hall staring at nothing and finding that he had been talking a while past to nobody. [p.115] Clara, Dicks lover, likewise seems aware that something is amiss:

146

NARRATING UTOPIA

I dont like this: something or another troubles me, and I feel as if something untoward were going to happen. You have been talking of past miseries to the guest, and have been living in past unhappy times, and it is in the air all round us, and makes us feel as if we were longing for something that we cannot have. [p.116] Morris rarely allows the establishment of a comfortable suspension of disbelief: the very precariousness of the dream constantly calls attention to the reality which it only barely veils. As E.P. Thompson suggests: [Morris] allows an ambiguity to hang over the narrator throughout: he is troubled to understand how he is there himself; the other characters sense him as someone different, and this is a disturbing influence on their relationship; he has premonitions that he must return [pp.6945] Rather as Wells was to do in A Modern Utopia, Morris deliberately draws attention to the fictional character of his utopian vision, and in this Thompson argues that his aim is to make it clear that what is being offered is not so much a blueprint, as a vision of utopian possibility. Rather than setting out in detail the mechanisms of an alternative social order, Morris may be seen as engaged in what Bloch was later to propose as the main goal of utopian speculationthe education of desire (Thompson, p.791).8 Other critics have gone still further, taking this, along with Morriss conscious references to his own actual political involvements, as prefiguring the self-referential practice of more recent fiction.9 Yet while it is undoubtedly true that Morriss focus on the problematic nature of the relationship between utopia and reality is relatively unusual, it by no means enables him to avoid entirely the problems inherent in the traditional narrative paradigm. Despite the perceptiveness of his critique of the political shortcomings of Bellamys utopia, Morris seems less aware of its narrative limitationsmany of which News from Nowhere reproduces. Suvin argues that whereas Bellamys political stance is reflected in a closed and often oppressive narrative structure (Metamorphoses, p.189), Morris succeeds in creating an open and airier structure homologous to his warmer, nonregimenting politics (p.189), yet this is surely to understate the extent of the narrative parallels between the two works. For example, while the narrators interactions with the utopianswith Old Hammond, with Ellen, with Dick and Claracommunicate more of a sense of genuine dialogue than do Julian Wests with Dr Leete and his daughter, the essential passivity of the narrator, which the convention of the visit to utopia imposes, remains. While the transmission of information concerning the utopian society is more deftly handled than in Looking Backward (even the garrulous Old Hammond is considerably more succinct than Dr Leete), the

LIBERTARIAN ALTERNATIVES

147

narrator is still condemned by his ignorance of the nature of utopian society to be the passive recipient of information, to rely on guides to show him what he ought to see. And while Morriss utopians do exhibit slightly more curiosity concerning their visitors past experience, his first-hand knowledge of the past serves largely (as is the case in Looking Backward) to confirm their existing preconceptions as to how awful it was. Morris may be, as Thompson argues, more alive to the political realities involved in the transformation of society than other utopian writers of the period, yet he experiences similar difficulties in translating theory into narrative practice. Although his utopia posits a far more radical departure from the ideological assumptions of his own society than do the utopias of Bellamy and Wells, whose values are in essence those of the contemporary bourgeoisie, translated into a context where they can be perpetuated without the inconvenience of guilt about those less well off, this greater radicalism often seems at odds with the implications of his utopian narrative. Indeed, for a utopia purportedly grounded in Marxist theory, News from Nowhere seems curiously backward looking. Even granted that, as Thompson points out, it must not be, and was never intended to be, read as a literal picture of Communist society (p.696), the degree to which it is permeated by a sense of nostalgia for a world that has been lost is striking.10 From the moment of the narrators first plunge into the cleansed and cleansing waters of a River Thames in which the salmon swim once more, the overwhelming emphasis of Morriss description of the utopian future is on restoration rather than innovation. Ugly factories and jerry-built housing have been torn down, and much of the urban wasteland of the late nineteenth century has been reclaimed by fields and woodland, the big murky centres of manufacture (p.58) having been replaced by a decentralized network of workshops. Although we are told that all work which would be irksome to do by hand is done by immensely improved machinery (p.82), the work that is actually describedbe it harvesting, construction, or manufactureis almost invariably manual labour. While the rags of the Victorian poor and the stiff formal attire of the ruling class have been replaced by elegant costumes of a decidedly mediaeval cast, both these and the artifacts which Morris describes in such loving detailthe glassware, crockery, pipes, furnitureare evidently the work of individual craftsmen. Indeed, so far as what we are actually shown, there is little sign of any form of modern technology in Morriss utopia, other than the force barges used to transport goods by water. The railway, we learn, has disappeared, and in the world of the future the only other methods of transport we encounter are rowing boat and horse and carriage. All this, together with the pastoral setting of the latter part of the narrative, lends an almost Arcadian quality

148

NARRATING UTOPIA

to Morriss utopia: in places, his vision of a Communist future reads more like an evocation of some vanished golden age. What begins to emerge, in fact, is a gap between Morriss imaginative response to the all too evident squalor and suffering which attended the rapid industrialization of a hitherto predominantly rural Britain, and the theoretical stance which informs both his critique of Bellamy and much of Old Hammonds outline of utopian society. While, as a Marxist, Morris acknowledges the necessity of Capitalism as a phase in the development of society, an inescapable precondition for the transition to Socialism, his distaste for it is often couched in terms more suggestive of the romanticism of his earlier years. When he talks elsewhere of the need to be our own Goths, and at whatever cost break up again the new tyrannous Empire of Capitalism (quoted in Meier, Volume 1, p.255), his choice of terminology is surely significant, suggestive not merely of the fascination with barbarian culture so often reflected in his other writings, but of an attitude towards existing society whose impulse is primarily destructive. In 1888, in a lecture entitled The Society of the Future, Morris declared that my special leading motive as a Socialist is hatred of civilization; my ideal of the new society would not be satisfied unless that Society destroyed civilization (quoted in May Morris, Volume 2, p.457)and in that emphasis on the destruction, the erasure of the existing order, he seems closer to the spirit of the conservative Romantic critique of modern industrialism than to the Marxist view of Capitalism as a necessary phase in the dialectical process of history.11 While it is possible to argue that the pastoral character of News from Nowhere is in keeping with Engels insistence on the necessity of the abolition of the antithesis between town and country (p.331),12 it is at the same time no coincidence that Morris was a great admirer of Richard Jefferies After London, a novel which charts with extraordinary vividness the disappearance of virtually every trace of modern civilization, as a resurgent Nature obliterates roads, houses, towns, cities, under a tangle of undergrowth and rampant vegetation. While Morriss vision, in News from Nowhere, is one of humanity living in harmony with the natural world, rather than struggling to survive, there are clear echoes of Jefferies in his description of a future London where much of Victorian suburbia has been re-covered by woodland which stretches from Kensington northward and west right over Paddington and a little way down Notting Hill: thence it runs north-east to Primrose Hill, and so on; rather a narrow strip of it gets through Kingsland to Stoke-Newington and Clapton, where it spreads out along the heights above the Lea marshes; on the other side of which is Epping Forest holding out a hand to it. [p.22]13

LIBERTARIAN ALTERNATIVES

149

To an even greater extent than Wells, who cheerfully demolishes the worlds major cities in preparation for the establishment of utopia in In the Days of the Comet, Morris celebrates the erasure of his own society as a necessary precondition for the creation of a better future:14 much of the narrative fascination of the latter part of the book, which charts the narrators voyage up the Thames, lies in its insistent emphasis on what is no longer there. Where the often obsessive specificity of detail which characterizes the traditional utopian paradigm suggests a colonialist desire to fill the space into which utopia can be imagined, Morriss concern seems rather to make it empty againor perhaps, more accurately, to render visible once more the outline of an ideal order that is already there. Thus, while the lack of regimentation in Morriss society, its emphasis on freely chosen cooperation rather than imposed conformity, sharply differentiates it from virtually all previous utopian fictions, it remains fraught with contradictions. In part, this can be ascribed to Morriss adherence to a narrative strategy that differs little from that of the traditional utopia. As we have seen, the standard format of the visit to utopia produces the same essential passivity on the part of the narrator, whose interactions with the utopians, while somewhat livelier than is normally the case, are scarcely more inherently dialogic. William Guest has already assented in advance to the desirability of utopia; the utopians have already determined their attitude towards the past which he representsand it is clear that, as in most such exchanges, the values of the utopians are to be accepted as authoritative. As Morson argues, what is involved is not so much a dialectical interaction between competing value systems, from which a new truth emerges, but ratheras in the traditional utopian paradigma final determination of value, different in character from any that preceded it: News from nowhere differs from all other news in that it will never be outdated. Thus, when the citizens of Morris pastoral paradise condemn nineteenth-century urban architecture, they are not simply expressing the opinion of one period and civilization about another. They are, rather, voicing a final determination of aesthetic value, one which, unlike any of our evaluations, will never become but one chapter in the history of taste. Utopia anachronizes anachronism. [p.121] As a result, all that really emerges from the exchanges in News from Nowhere is the traditional linear and episodic narrative in which the distinctive excellences of utopia are revealed. Once again, however, as in the utopias of Bellamy and Wells, a gap emerges between what the narrator is told, and what he is shown.

150

NARRATING UTOPIA

For example, while News from Nowhere contains numerous vivid descriptions of the look of thingsutensils, clothes, furnishingsthe process whereby they are produced (for all Morriss emphasis on the virtues of unalienated labour) is hardly more evident than is the case in Looking Backward. Harvesting and construction work are fleetingly glimpsed at as the narrator and his utopian companions make their leisurely way up the Thames, but the latter part of the narrative is, significantly enough, an extended account of going to work, but one where the goal is never actually reached: the dream breaks off before the actual process of working can be experienced. Nor, for that matter, is there any more direct evidence of the processes whereby society is governed. While Old Hammond offers the narrator a brief account of the participatory democracy obtaining at the local level, the only interactions we are actually shown are purely social: the pleasant and courteous exchanges that occur over the rituals of hospitality. Indeed, for an avowedly Communist utopia, the lack of political emphasis is striking. Even Old Hammonds account focuses more on what has disappeared than on what exists. Laws have disappeared, as has moneythe absence of the latter rendering the former redundantand shopkeeping has become, quite literally, childs play. Morriss future society is one where the Houses of Parliament are preserved only as an archaeological curiosity, and as a storehouse for horse manurean amusing reflection of the anti-parliamentarian stance of Morris and the Socialist League at the timeand when the narrator inquires as to the nature of utopian politics, he is told that utopia has none. Any discussion of politics, Old Hammond tells him, would resemble the chapter in Niels Horrebows Natural History of Iceland, entitled Concerning Snakes, which reads in its entirety: No snakes of any kind are to be met with throughout the whole island (p.72). As Suvin argues overcompensating for Bellamys state apparatus and clear lines of power, News from Nowhere omits all machinery for determining priorities between communes or any other basic units. Yet all production, including very much an automated one, requiresas long as it is not simply magicalcoordination and a (however truly participatory) system of vertical decision making News from Nowhere sacrifices human productivity in order to get rid of Statism and technocracy. [Metamorphoses, p.182]15 The markedly apolitical character of Morriss future society in its turn highlights a further contradictionthe fact that, for all Morriss keen awareness of the historical process, his is a utopia in many ways hardly less static than those of his predecessors. The world he portrays, reflecting

LIBERTARIAN ALTERNATIVES

151

as it does that most utopian element in Communist ideology, the belief in the ultimate withering away of the State, is one where the dialectic of class struggle has run its courseand where history has, in effect, come to an end. In subtitling News from Nowhere An Epoch of Rest, Morris even highlights this aspectthe fact that his utopia, though the result of a dynamic process, has reached stasis: the present rest and happiness of complete Communism (p.160). It is scarcely surprising in consequence to find that the resultant chronotope differs little from that of the traditional utopia. Extension in space, the journey in the course of which utopia is revealed, fails to conceal the blurring of time so characteristic of the utopian vision. In the eternal summer which Morriss future appears to enjoy, where all that changes from day to day is location, time has little more meaning than it does in Looking Backward, where a week is all it takes for the otherwise bemused Julian West to secure the hand of Edith Leete in marriage, despite her being some hundred years his junior. Under utopian conditions, the ageing process has been radically affected: although the spectacular longevity of the City of the Sun, where a lifespan of two hundred years in not unknown, may not have been attained, the biblical norm of three score years and ten has certainly been surpassed. Old Hammond, for instance, is over a hundred and five, yet the narrator is reminded, on seeing him, of his own face in the mirror. Age, rather than signalling the passage of time, often suggests that its normal operations have been suspended: the narrator mistakes a woman of forty-two for a twenty year old, while he, though only fifty-five,16 is taken for a man in his eighties. Clara, in fact, goes so far as to suggest that prolonged exposure to utopia might even reverse the ageing process: I think in a few months we shall make him look younger; and I should like to see what he was like with the wrinkles smoothed out of his face. Dont you think he will look younger after a little time with us? [p.116] Such dislocations of the normal temporal process are not uncommon in the traditional utopia, where, as Bloch suggests, longevity is often offered as a rationalized substitute for the more fantastic dream of immortality which characterizes visions of paradise or the millennium. Yet this is by no means the only feature which News from Nowhere shares with more traditional utopian dreams of order; indeed, in some respects, it resembles the Renaissance utopia still more closely than do the visions of Bellamy and Wells. While universal co-operation between nations is the norm, thus obviating the need for the ruthless defensive precautions described in Mores Utopia, or The New Atlantiss concern with maintaining complete secrecy regarding the location of Bensalem, News from Nowhere is none the

152

NARRATING UTOPIA

less yet another island utopia (the island in this case being Britain), and one characterized by much the same qualities of abundance and freedom from care so typical of paradisiacal fantasyindeed, Suvin goes so far as to propose that, generically, the work should be classified as an Earthly Paradise, rather than as a utopia per se (Metamorphoses, pp.1823). Nevertheless, like earlier utopias, Morriss offers a radical simplification of the complexities of living, a rational approach to the problems and anxieties of everyday existence having caused them virtually to disappear. Thus, as we have seen, while Morris fully acknowledges the necessity of labour, its irksomeness is removed, not by reducing working hours or providing for early retirement, but rather simply by making it enjoyableindistinguishable, in the delight it affords, from any other form of recreation. Commercial problems and financial complexities have disappeared along with money itself, with trade largely being conducted by children; and while sexual tensions still persist, they are minimized by the removal of legal constraints on human relationships. Nevertheless, it is curious that this should be the sole area which Morris chooses to show as remaining problematicto the extent, indeed, that despite the otherwise pacific tenor of his utopia, we learn of no fewer than four murders occasioned by sexual jealousy. While Old Hammond tells the narrator that laws have been rendered superfluous by the abolition of all those features of the capitalist economic system which provided incentives to crime, this persistence of violence suggests that, as in Looking Backward, the economic imperatives of existing society have been displaced, in utopia, into the sexual sphere. Significantly, when the question of economic incentives to labour is raised, Morris explicitly equates production and reproduction. When the narrator asks what makes people work in the absence of any financial reward, Old Hammond responds that work is its own reward: Plenty of reward, said hethe reward of creation. The wages which God gets, as people might have said time agone. If you are going to ask to be paid for the pleasure of creation, which is what excellence in work means, the next thing we shall hear of will be a bill sent in for the begetting of children. [p.77] With this exception, however, Morriss utopia is one where innocence has largely been restored, and while his emphasis is on individual freedom, rather than order, the underlying zeal for simplification is very similar to that embodied in the traditional utopian paradigm. Even Morriss unusually concrete depiction of the process involved in the creation of a more perfect society has only a localized impact, casting a shadow of past unhappy times over the sunlit world of his utopian dream. While his

LIBERTARIAN ALTERNATIVES

153

recognition of the cost, in terms of lives lost and human suffering, of radical social change is in marked contrast to the evasion or glossing over of the connection with reality which constitutes the utopian norm, the transitional metaphor in News from Nowhere, the account of the process whereby the narrator reaches utopia, is no less suggestive than is the case in fictions where it fulfils a clearly compensatory function. Like Julian West, Morriss narrator falls asleep in his own world and wakes in the utopian future, and while there is none of the preposterous apparatus of subterranean chambers and hypnosis whereby Bellamy accounts for the mystery of his narrators reawakening, Morriss narrative is not without its own curiosities. Prior to waking in utopia, Morriss narrator undergoes a rather less eccentric subterranean ritual, travelling home by underground railway (or, as it was already becoming known in Morriss time, by tube) a journey during which he stews discontentedly with his fellow travellers in a vapour bath of hurried and discontented humanity (p.1). On arriving home, he goes to bed and falls into a troubled sleep from which he finally awakes to find the early winter of reality transformed into the midsummer of the utopian future. His first act, on emerging from this symbolic gestation period, is to go for a baptismal swimhe takes on a new name shortly thereafterand is then taken under the protective wing of Dick the boatman who, along with Clara, displays an almost parental solicitude for his charge, educating him in the ways of the new world in which he finds himself. Yet here further ambiguities emerge: while to the narrator it is a new world, much of its novelty consists in its restoration of an older one. The utopian future is several times described as a world enjoying a second childhoodan ambiguous phrase in which youth and age become merged into onewhich further heightens the sense that Morriss Communist utopia is as much as anything a paradise regained. While the narrator encounters much that is unfamiliar, he finds the experience far less unsettling than does Julian West on his first exposure to the new Boston a reflection, perhaps of the extent to which Morriss utopia represents a return to an old, organic harmony between humanity and nature, rather than the imposition of a new, man-made order. Certainly, the emphasis of News from Nowhere, describing as it does a world that has been brought to its second birth (p.112), is on the innocence and freedom which might be associated with childhood, rather than on the security, allied of course with individual helplessness, of the womb, but the underlying impulse is none the less a regressive one. The very direction of the journey that occupies the latter part of the book is in itself significant: it is a voyage upstream, against the current, back towards the source. Although, in ideological terms, News from Nowhere may be seen as representing a radical

154

NARRATING UTOPIA

break with utopian tradition, it remains limited by its adherence to a narrative model evolved in a very different historical context, and to express a very different political ideal. For all the forcefulness of Morriss critique of Bellamys utopia, his own is equally one which might be described as Looking Backward. Red Star If Morriss disgust with Looking Backward provided the initial inspiration for News from Nowhere, Bogdanovs motivation for writing Red Star appears to have been more directly propagandistic. As a leading Bolshevik (although one on the verge of an irreparable breach with Lenin),17 he saw the function of his utopia as both educational and inspirational, not only providing its audience with an instructive portrait of a society operating in accordance with Marxist principles, but also offering an enabling vision of revolutionary possibility, designed to counteract the prevailing defeatism and despair following the failure of the 1905 revolution. Perhaps as a result, Bogdanov appears to pay little attention to the narrative problems of utopia as such, making few significant modifications to the traditional paradigm of the visit to and guided tour of a utopian society. Nevertheless, while this in turn creates some familiar problems, his acute awareness of the political implications of some of the resultant contradictions enables him to address directly issues that earlier utopian writers ignore. Set in Russia in the immediate aftermath of the 1905 revolution, Red Star begins with an encounter between Leonid, a seasoned party worker with marital problems, and a mysterious envoy from the South, whose code name is Menniand who later turns out to be from Mars. Having first pointed out the ideological basis of the tensions between Leonid and his wife to such good effect that she promptly leaves him, Menni then invites Leonid to accompany him to Mars, where it turns out a fully-fledged Communist society already exists, one both politically and technologically far more advanced than any on Earth. Seeing in this the opportunity for the acquisition of knowledge and skills that will render him more useful to the revolutionary cause, Leonid agrees, and the trip to utopia begins. For all its science fictional character, however, it turns out to be journey with a number of familiar features: Leonid and Menni leave the latters apartment in a small flying machine, and travel through the night until they reach the etheronepha massive spaceship, whose form is described as almost spherical, being flattened at the lower end rather like Columbuss egg (p.35). Although there is no visible means of entry, part of the metal cover of the structure slowly moved to one side, and our craft sailed into the black opening (p.33); within, they pass through the by now almost

LIBERTARIAN ALTERNATIVES

155

standard utopian terrain of elongated rooms and dimly lit corridors (p.33), until Leonid reaches his cabin, where he falls asleep, his brain overpowered by oppressive visions: I had a series of dreams which ended in a terrible nightmare. I was standing on the brink of an enormous black abyss. Stars shone at the bottom, and Menni was irresistibly dragging me down into it, telling me that there was no reason to fear the force of gravity and that in a few hundred thousand years we would reach the nearest star. I moaned in my final agonizing struggle and awoke. [p.33] Awakening from his nightmare, he finds himself in the reassuring presence of the ships doctor, Netti, who (in a manner reminiscent of the equivalent scene in Looking Backward) soothes him back to sleep with a combination of soft lights and hypnotic suggestion. The following morning they depart. Although the nuclear-powered etheroneph is technologically extremely advanced, the journey to Mars is still a lengthy one, and Leonid takes the opportunity to learn the Martian language, which turns out to be of great simplicity (p.47), so regular that its rules have no exceptions whatever (p.48), and entirely lacking in gender distinctionsindeed, the only thing he finds confusing is that the names of all objects and qualities are declined according to their temporal status (p.48). This evidence of a concern with the passage of time is also reflected in the fact that (in marked contrast to the utopian norm) Leonid is given a good deal of information concerning Martian history18including, as in News from Nowhere, an extended account of how the revolution came about. Only once is the otherwise uneventful journey disrupted, whenfor reasons that never become apparentan elderly scientist chooses to conduct in Leonids presence what turns out to be a highly dangerous experiment, resulting in an explosion that blasts a hole in the ships hull. Disaster seems inevitable, until the scientist heroically plugs the hole with his own body, saving Leonids life, but killing himself in the process. Once he has arrived on Mars, what follows is very much the standard utopian guided tour. As K.M. Jensen points out, its familiar features include: plenty, uniform standard of living, stable planned economy, free labour, complete satisfaction of needs, personal security and happiness, absence of politics and state, high level of social consciousness, an environment conducive to individual creativity, universal education, scientific efficiency, functional architecture and effective population distribution, urban society, high technology and automation. [p.17]

156

NARRATING UTOPIA

Like Morriss, Bogdanovs Communist utopia is one where the state has withered away, although, in marked contrast to News from Nowhere, Red Star provides a great deal of information concerning the mechanisms of social organization. Leonid visits (and later works in) a factory where automation has reduced the average working day to the equivalent of between four to six Earth hours, and learns that the elimination of mindless drudgery, together with the high level of Martian education, has rendered each individual perfectly free to choose his own occupation (p.67). He visits a Childrens Colony, where Martian children are raised and educated, not only by adults, but also by one another, in an environment free of the tensions and traumas of conventional family life, and then tours a museum where he is introduced to Martian art and architecture, and reflects on the role and character of art in a socialist society (a discussion of particular interest, given Bogdanovs later status as one of the leading theoreticians of the Proletcult movement).19 This is followed by a visit to a hospital, where he learns of the advanced medical technology which, along with the practice of mutual blood transfusions,20 has resulted in a dramatically increased lifespan, and by trips to public meetings and the theatre. After several weeks of this strenuous rgime, however, Leonid suffers a complete nervous breakdownapparently the result of information overloadand is put to bed under Nettis care, which, besides reducing him to the childlike dependency so characteristic of the traditional visitor to utopia, also serves to introduce a love interest strongly reminiscent of the relationship between Julian West and Edith Leete in Looking Backward. Netti, to whom he has already found himself strangely attracted, turns out not to be a man after all, but a womanand one moreover, whose passion for all things terrestrial has already predisposed her to return his evident affection: Simply and generously, she yielded to my unbridled impulses. When I recovered from my joyous insanity I again kissed her hands with involuntary tears of gratitude in my eyes. My crying, of course, was due to weakness caused by my illness. Netti said with her sweet smile: You know, it seemed to me just now that I was holding your whole youthful world in my arms. Its despotism, its egotism, its desperate hunger for happinessI felt all that in your caresses. Your love is like murder. But I love you, Lenni. [p.93] As in Looking Backward, the visitor arrives in utopia to be rewarded by the effortless fulfilment of sexual desire. Yet, as in Wellss utopias, such desire also turns out to be disturbingly conflated with maternal affection: prior

LIBERTARIAN ALTERNATIVES

157

to leaving on yet another interplanetary expedition, this time to Venus, Netti leaves him a letter in which she declares: I love you not only as a wife, I love you as a mother who guides her child into a new and strange life full of trials and dangers. This love is the strongest bond that can exist between two people. For that reason my promise requires no sacrifice of me. Goodbye my darling, my beloved child [p.106] So far, it would appear, so familiar. Despite some often acute political analysis, Bogdanovs utopian narrative repeatedly lapses into a fantasy of infantile dependence. Not the least significant aspect of Nettis letter is that despite the fact that free love is the norm on Mars (and something to which Leonid also claims to be committed), she goes out of her way to reassure him that There will never be anyone else (p.106): what is offered is the utopian promise of absolute security, free from the complications of adult existence. Indeed, even where Bogdanov is at his strongestas in his commitment to address the process whereby the utopian society is createdthere are still indications of a regressive simplifying impulse, an underlying desire to evade complexity and difficulty. Revolution on Mars, it transpires, was a far simpler affair than is the case on Earth. Smaller, and with better communications (there being fewer seas to divide people and less gravity to slow them up), Mars had already evolved into a world state with a single language long before the revolutionand as a result there were no national rivalries to interfere with the revolutionary process. While the major industrial crisis that followed the completion of the Great Project (the digging of Marss canals) was accompanied by strikes and uprisings, there wasas in Looking Backwardalmost no violence: The result was a social revolution, but once again the course of events was relatively peaceful The owners retreated step by step before the inevitable, and even when the government fell into the hands of the workers party, the vanquished did not attempt to assert their interests by force. [p.56] For an active Bolshevik, who had personally witnessed the brutal suppression of the 1905 uprising, it is a remarkable compensatory fantasy. In addition, Red Star displaysif possible, to an even greater extent the displacement of tension and conflict from the public (political and economic) arena into the private, sexual realm, which has already been observed both in the traditional utopian paradigm and its dystopian parody. At the outset, as we have seen, Leonid is married to a woman with whom he has profound differencesdifferences which, as Menni points out, have a clearly ideological basis. Nevertheless, despite the importance of the

158

NARRATING UTOPIA

revolutionary struggle in which both are engaged, their political character (Leonid is a Bolshevik, Anna Nikolaevna a Menshevik) is mentioned only in passing, whereas their differences over questions of sexual morality are discussed at considerable length: According to Anna Nikolaevna, in socialist society the class ethics of the proletariat would necessarily become the universal moral code, while I believed that the proletariat was already moving toward the destruction of all morals and that the comradely feeling uniting people in labour, joy, and suffering would not develop fully until it had cast off the fetishistic husk of morality She thought that love implied certain obligationsconcessions, sacrifices, and, above all, fidelity for the duration of the union. In actual fact I had no intention whatever of entering into other liaisons, but I was unable to recognize fidelity as an obligation. I even believed that polygamy was in principle superior to monogamy, since it provided for both a richer private life and a greater variety of genetic combinations. In my opinion, it was only the contradictions of the bourgeois order which for the time being made polygamy either simply unfeasible or merely the privilege of the exploiters and parasites, who were all befouled by their own decadent psychology Anna Nikolaevna deeply resented such views, in which she perceived an attempt to mask a coarsely sensual outlook with intellectual phrases. [p.25] Nevertheless, despite this stance, Leonids reaction on discovering the nature of Nettis sexual history is far from philosophical. Having recovered from one breakdown, he almost suffers another on learning that her past partners include Lettathe scientist who saved Leonids life at the cost of his ownand Sterni, another member of the expedition which brought him to Mars, and also an advocate of the colonization of Earth. Ostensibly concerned over the fate of the human race (Sterni argues that colonizing Earth would necessarily involve first exterminating its inhabitants) but really motivated by sexual jealousy, he seeks out Sterni, and bludgeons him to death. (When Netti describes his love as being like murder, she clearly speaks more accurately than she knows: not content with her assurances of sexual fidelity in the future, he effectively erases her sexual past.) As in News from Nowhere, the only violence in utopia is caused by sexual jealousy, while to an even greater extent than in the case of Bellamy and Wells, the visitors experience of the more rational utopian world is accompanied by symptoms of extreme psychological disturbance: Leonids last days on Mars prior to his return to Earth are spent in a mental hospital. At the same time, however, there are some significant differences. While the process of the Martian revolution may be radically simplified and

LIBERTARIAN ALTERNATIVES

159

smoothed over, the achievement of a utopian society takes on a very different resonance in the light of its connection with Bogdanovs vivid depiction of the revolutionary struggle on Earth. Indeed, whenever the two planets histories are compared, the far greater scale of the problems of achieving social justice on Earth is repeatedly stressedyet always with the accompanying assurance that the much greater energy required to overcome such obstacles will ultimately lead to a correspondingly higher pinnacle of achievement. To return to Earth is to return to the realm of difficulty, to the necessity of struggle, and in juxtaposing the situations of the two planets Bogdanov creates a dynamic that to some extent anticipates the narrative strategies of later writers such as Piercy and Le Guin. Despite feeling that he has disgraced himself by his conduct on Mars, Leonid returns determined to continue fighting for a better society on Earth: in the Epilogue, he is critically wounded while leading a commando attack on the government forces. In addition, while Red Star exhibits the familiar displacement of political tensions and contradictions into the sexual realm, there is at the same time evidence of some critical awareness of the resultant implications. While at the outset Leonid is able to reflect on his differences with Anna Nikolaevna in an apparently objective fashion, his encounter with a society where his theories are common practice force him painfully to confront the contradictions arising from his own socialization. On learning not only that Netti had been involved with Letta and Sterni, but that for a time the relationships had overlapped, Leonid reflects: there are no words to describe how I felt. Why? No reason in particular. Netti was a free person and behaved like a free person. What of it if Letta was her husband? I had always respected him and would have liked him very much even if he had not sacrificed his life for me. Netti was married to two of her comrades at the same time? So what? I have always believed that monogamy among us is due exclusively to our economic conditions, which limit and enslave man at every step. The conditions on Mars were quite different and in no way inhibited personal feelings and relationships. Why then this agitated bewilderment, this incomprehensible pain that made me want to scream and laugh at the same time? Or was it that I did not know how to feel as I thought? [pp.1045] Where both the traditional utopian narrative and its dystopian parody comfortably reinscribe the unequal gender relations of existing society, Bogdanovs emphasis on Leonids discomfort when faced with womens sexual freedom highlights the extent to which, as a male, he has unconsciously assumed the inequity from which he has hitherto benefited

160

NARRATING UTOPIA

to be the normalthough the effect of this acknowledgement is somewhat undermined when Netti returns at the end, monogamous and maternal, to whisk him back to utopia. As well, Leonid is forced to acknowledge the contradictions of his class status: while, as a revolutionary intellectual, he is committed to the workers cause, he often experiences the genuinely co-operative culture of Mars as a threat to his own identity. When his fellow-workers at the factory help him out when he makes mistakes, for example, he assumes that it reflects badly on his competence, and that they are constantly keeping an eye on himwhereas in fact such mutual assistance is the norm. At the end, reflecting on his bouts of mental instability during his exposure to genuine social equality, he wonders whether it was not partly the result of his background as an intellectual who nine-tenths of the time had worked either alone or in a one-sided unequal relationship to his comrades and fellow workers (p.135): Perhaps it would be easier for an uneducated worker to become integrated into a new and higher order, for although he would have to learn much more at first, he would not be forced to relearn as much, and that, after all, is the most difficult problem Perhaps the contradiction would have proved less acute for a man who had instead spent nine-tenths of his working life in an environment that may have been primitive and uncultivated but was nonetheless pervaded by a spirit of comradeship. An environment in which equality was real [p.135] Where Bellamy and Wells imagine utopias in which middle-class values have become universal, and even dystopian parody for the most part implicitly appeals to those values as normative, Bogdanov stresses the extent to which a more equal society imposes the imperative to change. (Although, at the same time, it is significant that despite his dawning awareness of the contradictions of his own gender position, Leonid never wonders if a woman might not also find the experience of utopia less problematicgiven that she might be liable to find gender equality rather less of a threat.) Finally, while much of the dialogue in Red Star functions as little more than an expository device, there is one episode which features genuine debate. For there is debate on Marsin part because, for all its utopian features, it is not a world where all problems have been resolved: although at the level of social interaction this may be the case, the struggle with the forces of nature still continues. Despite the Great Project, the massive engineering works that have irrigated the Martian desert, natural resources are in increasingly short supply, and as one Martian remarks: the tighter our humanity closes ranks to conquer nature, the tighter the elements

LIBERTARIAN ALTERNATIVES

161

close theirs to avenge the victory (p.79). Since checking population growth would be tantamount to capitulating to the elements (pp.7980), Martian society is faced with only one solution: the colonization of other planets and it is this that constitutes the focus of the central debate. As we have already seen, one recurrent feature of utopian narrative is its rehearsal of the process of colonization so inextricably linked with the narratives of discovery on which it is partly modelled. From Mores Utopia, where the indigenous inhabitants are remoulded in the image of their conqueror, and then proceed to impose their norms on the nations that surround them, to Morriss and Wellss celebration of the destruction of the architecture and culture that preceded the establishment of utopia, the utopian dream is in part a fantasy of finding space in which a new order can be constructedand if that space should happen to be occupied, the only logical conclusion is that it will have to be made empty. In terms of utopian narrative, this can be effected in a fairly painless and guilt-free fashion simply by projecting utopia into the future, by which time all those inhabitants of the utopian space not committed to utopian values will have died, without the inconvenience of having to either massacre or re-educate them, leaving only their buildings to be demolished (as they almost invariably are). In the case of Red Star, however, Bogdanov chooses not to evade the issue of the connection between the process of colonization and the utopian aspiration to create a better world, but instead makes it a central focus of his narrative. As Bogdanov structures it, the debate focuses on two alternativesthe colonization of Venus, a hostile environment, though rich in natural resources, and the colonization of Earthand in the view of the astronomer, Sterni, that effectively leaves only one option. Given the dangers of Venusthunderstorms and winds which can destroy aircraft and demolish buildings, monsters, bacteria, diseases, earthquakes, volcanic eruptions, tidal wavesEarth is the only realistic alternative. However, this presents problems of its own: Sterni maintains that the primitive character of Earths society renders it impossible to live among them nationalist propensities meaning that humans are liable to band together against a common enemy. Echoing the discovery narratives demonization of the indigene as a rationale for what is almost invariably represented as retaliatory violence, he argues that humanitys reliance on brute strength and violence will force us to adopt the same attitude toward them (p.111). An enclave of Martian civilization is unthinkable, given the constant struggle that would be involved, since Socialism is still a long way off, even with Martian assistanceand even if achieved, its character would likely be warped by the violent struggle to attain it. (Sterni at this point offers an eerily prescient vision of the likely consequences of the

162

NARRATING UTOPIA

establishment of socialism in one country.21) Given the clear superiority of Martian civilization, extermination is the only answer. Two of Wellss pronouncements in A Modern Utopiathat no less than a planet will serve the purpose of a modern Utopia (p.11) and that there is only one sane and logical thing to be done with a really inferior race, and that is to exterminate it (p.337)here take on a particularly sinister overtone. It is Netti who counters these arguments in favour of conquest and genocide with what is essentially a plea in favour of differenceregarding which, as we have seen, traditional utopian narrative remains highly ambivalent. While Martian civilization is unquestionably more advanced than that of Earth, this does not in Nettis view argue a fundamental superiority: If they were identical with us in all respects save their level of development, then one might be able to agree with Sterni: a lower stage is worth sacrificing for the sake of a higher one, the weak must yield to the strong. But the Earthlings are not the same as we. They and their civilization are not simply lower and weaker than ours they are different. If we eliminate them we will not replace them in the process of universal evolution but will merely fill in mechanically the vacuum we have created in the world of life forms. [p.117] Ultimately, she argues, the greater variety and energy of life on Earth, its diversity of language and culture, while it may render the process of uniting humanity longer and more arduous, will give birth to a socialism in many ways richer and more sophisticated than that of Marswhich is not to say, however, that Mars cannot help it on its way. What Bogdanov dramatizes in this exchange, in effect, is the relation between utopia and the world as it exists: not only may one learn from the example of the utopia that lies beyond and above the limitations of the here and now, but by doing so it becomes possible to transcend the regularity and simplification which is utopias limitation. What is also significant, however, is the way in which Bogdanov genders the debate. It is Sterni, not merely a male, but an unusually large and powerful one, who expresses the colonialist desire for the suppression and expropriation of the Other, and for the imposition of a single, harmonious order; whereas it is the woman, Netti, who speaks for diversity and the right to self-determination. Where Sterni describes the human race as masters of the planet (p.110), who can simply be replaced by more powerful masters, Netti refers to them as though they are an organic part of itas a stormy but beautiful ocean of life (p.119)whose loss would be irreparable. This is not to say that Nettis position is entirely unproblematic: if Sterni embodies the male dream of conquest and

LIBERTARIAN ALTERNATIVES

163

possession of nature, Netti at points seems to associate herself with the maternal passivity which Kolodny sees as its polar opposite, while in her emphasis on the organic character of human development she often comes close to suggesting that the achievement of socialism is itself not only a natural, but an inevitable process. Nevertheless, set in the context of subsequent challenges to the largely male-authored traditional utopian dream of order by feminist writers who seek to incorporate freedom and multiplicity into the utopian dream, Bogdanovs treatment of the issue may be seen as a decisive step forward. Only one detail serves to darken the picture. In order to obtain access to the records of the meeting at which the debate took place, Leonid has to resort to subterfuge, since the librarian at colonial archives denies such records exist: slipping past him while he is otherwise engaged, he proceeds to the audio-recording section, where he is careful to make his request for information sufficiently general not to cause alarm. Only then does he discover the audio-recording of the debate. While Martian society is otherwise represented in a uniformly favourable light, secrecy and bureaucratic obstructionism are apparently no strangers to the utopian state. Island Nearly forty years later, in the 1946 Foreword to Brave New World, Aldous Huxley also offered, in outline, a vision of what might constitute the basis of a libertarian utopia. While Brave New World set out to expose what for Huxley were the nightmarish implications of the Wellsian utopia, its weakness, as he saw it, lay in its failure to see beyond the polarized alternatives it presentedbetween the irrational brutality of a natural life in a primitive community, on the one hand, and the mindless conformity of a rationally planned utopia on the other. As a possible solution, he suggested a third alternative (p.8)the possibility of sanity which might be embodied in a community of exiles and refugees from the utopian World State: In this community economics would be decentralist and HenryGeorgian, politics Kropotkinesque and co-operative. Science and technology would be used as though, like the Sabbath, they had been made for man, not (as at present and still more so in Brave New World) as though man were to be adapted and enslaved to them. Religion would be the conscious and intelligent pursuit of mans Final End, the unitive knowledge of the immanent Tao or Logos, the transcendent Godhead or Brahman. [pp.89] Given that, with only minor modifications, this is very much the ideal

164

NARRATING UTOPIA

which forms the basis for the fully worked-out utopian society depicted in Island, it is worth examining Huxleys recipe for a positive alternative to dystopia more closely. Most immediately striking, perhaps, is its spiritual emphasis, which, given the predominantly secular and materialist concerns of most earlier writers (including even the devoutly Christian More), would seem to indicate a significant change of focus. It is no coincidence that, while lacking the spectacular religious special effects of Bacons The New Atlantis, Island is concerned above all to demonstrate the crucial importance of spiritual awareness as a precondition for the establishment of any truly desirable form of social organization. Even the subordination of technology to human needs, which the Foreword advocates, and Island illustrates, is only made possible by a sense of purpose which Huxley sees as ultimately religious in character. And while the utopia portrayed in Island is predominantly Buddhist, rather than based on the somewhat eclectic mix advocated in the Foreword, its underlying emphasis remains much the same. For Huxley, the ultimate horror of his dystopian future, and indeed of the contemporary society from which it was extrapolated, lay in its mindlessness, its lack of awareness of any goal other than that of immediate gratification. It is this which his utopia, with its focus on the central necessity of spiritual awareness, seeks to counter. Huxleys evident intuition of the regressive element inherent in the utopian impulse is, of course, reflected in Brave New World, whose infantile behavioural norms render explicit an aspect that remains latent in the utopian tradition he parodies. There, as we have seen, Huxley implies that spiritual awareness is the antithesis of such infantilism, and in his utopian society of Pala the religious exercises and rituals that are practised from childhood on are represented as crucial to the development of an independent, adult consciousness, in which the individual is able to perceive her or his own needs in relation to the wider horizons of society, as well as to the Final End referred to in the Foreword. Palanese religion works in tandem with its educational system to encourage a strong sense of distinct personal identity, based on the exploration of ones individual potential, while at the same time emphasizing the individuals responsibility to control any anti-social impulses to which s/he is particularly susceptible. Children learn at an early age to deal with personal problems, to resolve family conflicts within a network of extended families, and to take a mature and responsible attitude towards sexual relationshipsin other words, to grow up both faster and more fully. Children are deliberately exposed to all aspects of human experience: all the important and significant things that human beings do and suffer working, playing, loving, getting old, being sick, dying.... (p.93), and Attention, a slogan insistently repeated by Palas talking birds, is perhaps

LIBERTARIAN ALTERNATIVES

165

the fundamental motto of Huxleys utopia. Active attention is encouraged to everything: the food one eats, the experience of sexual intercourse, the controversial moksha-medicine (the psychedelic drug which certain of Huxleys less perceptive critics have sought speciously to equate with the narcotics consumed in vast quantities in Brave New World)22the ultimate goal being to promote awareness, complete and constant awareness (p.152) of the infinite variety of the world one inhabits. When this is combined with the active encouragement of a sceptical attitude towards conventional beliefs and received assumptions, it becomes clear that Huxleys utopia is explicitly designed to ensure that its citizens cannot be manipulated by the centralized authority so characteristic of the traditional utopia. The primary purpose of Palas social, political, and religious institutions is to create a framework that allows for the maximum possible individual freedom: rather than a structure to be imposed on its citizens in their own best interests, utopia here is the sum of the experience of the individuals who compose it. Interestingly enough, the sharpest contrasts between the virtues of utopia and the deficiencies of the real world are provided by the example of the individual products of the different societies. Opposed to the balance and maturity of Dr Robert and Susila, or even the young lovers Radha and Ranga, is the sulky petulance of the mother-dominated Murugan, or the example of the two distinguished westerners cited by the Palanese UnderSecretary of Education: I was thinking of two people I met last time I was in England. At Cambridge. One of them was an atomic physicist, the other was a philosopher. Both extremely eminent. But one had a mental age, outside the laboratory, of about eleven and the other was a compulsive eater with a weight problem that he refused to face. [p.214] For Huxley, the superiority of utopia resides not so much in the perfection of its social and political structures, as in the extent to which such structures promote growth and maturity: many of the problems of his own society are represented as rooted in the relative immaturity of those who comprise it. When the mentality of the playground is allowed to persist into adulthood, the consequences can be disastrousthe most spectacular example offered being that of Adolf Hitler, who is significantly described as a Peter Pan: a classic case of arrested development leading to psychopathic behaviour. In Pala, by contrast, the compulsions that create a Hitler, like the gullibility that caused people to respond to his primitive appeal, are something that can be outgrown. Even at the level of metaphor the adult quality of utopian society is

166

NARRATING UTOPIA

evident. Palanese medicine, for example, stresses the importance of allowing the bodys own self-healing mechanisms to do their work: to prevent the conscious mind interfering in this process, patients are often put into a hypnotic trance. The conscious self is like a little boy who, though only too anxious to help, has to be sent to play in the garden so that the grown-ups can do their work in peace (p.94). When Dr Robert justifies Palas refusal to import luxuries, such as the expensive foreign cars for which Murugan yearns, it is on the grounds that We cant import toys only essentials (p.146). In such a context, it is perhaps hardly coincidental that the only mode of transport available to the Rani, who embodies the bogus spirituality so prevalent outside utopia, should be a Baby Austin. Nevertheless, however refreshing Huxleys stress on the virtues of maturity, of individual freedom and responsibility may beparticularly in a utopian context, familiar problems arise when it comes to translating theory into narrative practice. Island is, yet again, a narrative which adheres to the basic format of a guided tour provided for the visitor to utopiaand one whose didactic intent is no less overt than is the case in the utopias of Bellamy and Wells. Thus, while few would quarrel with the old Raja of Palas realistic assessment that a certain amount of pain and sorrow is an inescapable part of the human condition (even in utopia), Islands narrative format often makes Huxleys representations of human sorrow seem merely propagandistic. Even the movingly described death of Dr Roberts wife, Lakshmi (itself clearly based on the death of Huxleys first wife, Maria23) is surrounded by episodes clearly designed to show how well the Palanese deal with it; indeed, as though anxious lest the point be missed, Huxley also provides graphic descriptions of how badly death is dealt with elsewhere. In contrast to Lakshmi, the visitor to utopia, Will Farnaby, cites the case of his Aunt Mary, whose death from cancer was marked by nothing but terror and degradation; his own helpless guilt and horror over the death of his wife is set against the strength and dignity with which Susila deals with the death of her husband. Such schematic contrasts, of course, exemplifying as they do the problematic double encoding of utopian narrative as both fiction and some other mode with very different designs on the reader, are only too typical of the traditional utopian paradigm. In the case of Island, however, their effect is particularly unfortunate, working as they do against the basic premises of the utopia which it proposes. While the free exercise of individual judgement by the Palanese may be approved, Huxley is evidently reluctant to allow a similar privilege to the reader. As in so many more authoritarian utopias, it is less the inherent implausibility of the society depicted that constitutes the problem (witness the cheerful suspension of disbelief with which readers greet the far more extravagant

LIBERTARIAN ALTERNATIVES

167

inventions of much science fiction), than the authorial insistence on spelling everything out, on specifying each detail of the utopian vision. Island is yet another utopia whose dialogue is essentially monologic, calculated as it is to assert the authority of a single utterance. Huxley himself was obviously aware of the problems inherent in the creation of an effective utopian fiction. Writing to his son during the early stages of composition, he described himself as: wrestling with the problem of getting an enormous amount of diversified material into the book without becoming merely expository or didactic. It may be that the job is one which cannot be accomplished with complete success. In point of fact, it hasnt been accomplished in the past. For most Utopian books have been exceedingly didactic and expository. I am trying to lighten up the exposition by putting it into dialogue form, which I make as lively as possible. But meanwhile I am always haunted by the feeling that, if I only had enough talent, I could somehow poetize and dramatize all the intellectual material and create a work which would be simultaneously funny, tragic, lyrical and profound. Alas, I dont possess the necessary talent [Letters, pp.8756] Coming from the author of Brave New World, it is a telling admission, indicative of the much greater compositional problems inherent in utopian narrative as opposed to dystopian parody. Adhering as he does so closely to the traditional utopian narrative model, Huxley is little more successful in transcending its limitations: his attempts at lively dialogue rarely succeed in disguising its fundamentally didactic intentthe fact that once again it is little more than exposition distributed among a range of speakers. Where Huxley does extend the conventions of the traditional narrative paradigm, it is by the inclusion of novelistic elementsin this case, a subplot designed, like that in Wellss Men Like Gods, to supplement the somewhat limited narrative appeal of the standard utopian visit. Will Farnaby, it transpires, is not just a journalist: he is also the agent of the newspaper proprietor and oil magnate, Joe Aldehyde, who is keenly interested in getting his hands on Palas substantial oil resourceswhich the Palanese themselves refuse to develop for other than their own needs. Even as, in the course of his guided tour, he becomes increasingly attracted to the Palanese way of life, Will is simultaneously engaged in underhand negotiations with various parties also interested in Palas oil reserves including the ambassador of the neighbouring dictatorship. And while this is clearly likely to undermine the independence which is the precondition for Palas remaining a utopian society, he initially justifies his actions on the grounds that the commission he will earn will enable him to abandon

168

NARRATING UTOPIA

journalism for the pursuit of Art. As time goes by, however, he grows increasingly unhappy about the compromises he is being forced to make and in this Huxley is doubtless trying to dramatize the connection between individual practice and the existence of utopian society, and to create a visitor to utopia who is more than simply a passive presence. The only problem is that the subplot is so transparently just that: a subplot and no more. In the end, it doesnt really matter what Will does: Palas fate depends, not on his negotiations, but on the actions of Murugan, heir apparent to the Palanese throne, his mother, the Rani, and Colonel Dipa, the neighbouring dictator. Which brings us to the question of the political structure of Huxleys utopia. In the Foreword to Brave New World, it will be recalled, Huxley envisaged a more perfect society whose economics would be decentralist and HenryGeorgian, politics Kropotkinesque and co-operative (p.8). The economic principles of the bourgeois prophet of land reform, Henry George, are seen, in other words, as wholly compatible with political structures based on entirely different premisesa yoking which shows little sign of awareness of their essential incompatibility.24 Huxleys tendency towards a sort of mix-and-match political eclecticism is of course already apparent in Brave New World, where capitalism, communism, fascism, and modern science are lumped together as joint progenitors of his dystopian future. Yet while this presents comparatively few difficulties in the context of Huxleys freeranging satiric attack on almost every aspect of modern society (with its highly conservative underlying premise that almost all change is for the worse, and should be avoided), such patent lack of discrimination becomes considerably more problematic when it comes to devising the basis for a more perfectand radically differentsocial order.25 In Island, the contradictions implicit in the Foreword to Brave New World become glaringly evidentto the point that, in places, it begins to seem that Huxley himself is not entirely clear as to how his utopian society is run. At the outset, it would appear that the Palanese utopia was to all intents and purposes established by fiat, in the context of a political structure best described as benevolent despotism. It is the creation of two men: the Raja of Pala and Dr Andrew MacPhail, the Scottish surgeon who, after first saving the Rajas life, becomes his chief adviserPrime Minister in all but name. While their recipe for a more perfect societyin essence a fusion of Western scientific and technological know-how with the wisdom and spiritual awareness of the Eastmay differ radically in character from those of More and Bacon, their mode of putting it into effect differs little from that of King Utopus or King Solamona. While the Raja and Dr MacPhail go to great pains to win the Palanese over to their new ideas, there is no doubt that in the first instance it is the existence of an inherently

LIBERTARIAN ALTERNATIVES

169

authoritarian political structure that enables them to impose their will. By the time Will Farnaby reaches utopia, however, Pala appears to have movedat least to some extentwith the times. Pala has become a constitutional monarchy (p.40): there is a Cabinet, a Privy Council, a House of Representatives. Elsewhere Dr Robert boasts: we have no omnipotent politicians or bureaucrats. Palas a federation of self-governing units, professional units, economic unitsso theres plenty of scope for small-scale initiative and democratic leaders, but no place for any kind of dictator at the head of a centralized government the eloquent rabble-rouser, like Hitler, or our neighbour across the Strait, Colonel Dipa, just doesnt have a chance here in Pala. [p.149] Yet here, once again, as in so many utopias, what we are told is at odds with what we are shown. The virtues of Palanese society are unfortunately lost on the heir apparent, Murugan, who appears to be the lone Palanese not to have benefited from its educational system. Instead, he has been brought up by his mother, the Rani, on quite different principles: the result is a sulky, gay playboy, whose favourite reading is the Sears-Roebuck catalogue. With a mother eager to use Palas oil resources to finance a religious crusade reminiscent of Moral Re-Armament, and a lover who just happens to be the same Colonel Dipa from across the strait, Murugan has rather different priorities from those of his subjects. On his coming-of-age, the constitutional aspect of his monarchy is conveniently forgotten: Colonel Dipas troops arrive to assist in establishing the new order, and Pala reverts to being part of the all too imperfect real world. Huxleys decision to make his utopia, of all things, a monarchy particularly given that it is precisely this feature that ensures its destructionis surely a curious one, more in keeping with the political norms of the Renaissance than those of the mid-twentieth century. It does, however, serve to highlight the contradiction inherent in Huxleys account of his utopias origins: the fact that it is a libertarian society created by essentially authoritarian means. It is this contradiction which resurfaces at the end of Island, when it becomes clear that the whole libertarian panoply of independent initiative and self-determination can be erased as easily as it was created. Once again, it would appear that the persistence of the traditional narrative paradigm serves to undermine the authors attempts to transcend its limitations. Even as Huxley strives to demystify the question of utopias origins, he exposes the essential similarities between his vision of a utopia based on freedom and the authoritarian models that precede it. Nor do the resemblances end there: as its title suggests, Island also represents a return to the traditional location of earlier

170

NARRATING UTOPIA

utopian narrativean island in some unspecified southern sea. Rather than embracing the whole world, as do the utopias of Bellamy and Wells, Huxleys isolates itself from itan isolation rather unconvincingly explained as being due to its lack of a natural harbour. This, in its turn, has some interesting consequences, for, unlike its neighbour, Rendang, Pala is thus spared the ill-effects of successive waves of colonization: Rendang has a magnificent harbour. That brought them an Arab invasion in the Middle Ages. We have no harbour, so the Arabs left us alone and were still Buddhists or Shivaitesthat is, when were not Tantrik agnostics After the Arabs, it got the Portuguese. We didnt. No harbour, no Portuguese. Therefore no Catholic minority, no blasphemous nonsense about it being Gods will that people should breed themselves into subhuman misery, no organized resistance to birth control. And that isnt the only blessing. After a hundred and twenty years of the Portuguese, Ceylon and Rendang got the Dutch. And after the Dutch came the English. We escaped both those infestations. No Dutch, no English, and therefore no planters, no coolie labour, no cash crops for export, no systematic exhaustion of our soil. Also no whisky, no Calvinism, no syphilis, no foreign administrators. We were left to go our own way and take responsibility for our own affairs. [pp.801] What Pala has escaped, in other words, is almost the entire course of modern history. Like Wells in A Modern Utopia, Huxley effectively severs utopia from existing reality: utopia can only emerge from a context that is already different from that obtaining in the present. In addition, like Bacons The New Atlantis, Island offers a scenario in which communication between utopia and the rest of the world is essentially one-way. Utopians from both societies go out into the world to learn from it, but contamination by visitors is discouraged. Given this self-imposed isolation, of course, it becomes necessary to offer some form of narrative explanation for the visitors presenceand once again this takes the by now sufficiently familiar form of a highly suggestive rite of passage. Shipwrecked on the coast of Pala after sailing alone beyond the safe confines of Rendang harbour, Will Farnaby miraculously ends up on the only sandy beach in all those miles of Palas rockbound coast (p.6). At the head of the little cove in which he finds himself there is a kind of headlong ravine where a little stream came down in a succession of filmy waterfalls, and there were trees and bushes growing between the walls of grey limestone (p.6), and he proceeds to climb. The ascent, however, becomes increasingly nightmarish: the narrow path into Eden, it turns out, is infested with snakes, and after nearly stepping on

LIBERTARIAN ALTERNATIVES

171

one, he falls, badly injuring his leg. The light begins to fail, and even when he finally reaches the top, the nightmare continues. As he lies in a woodland glade in a state of semi-delirium, a series of painful memories return to haunt him. He recalls his wife, Molly, dying in the hospital after a car crash; he remembers his guilt-wracked sexual encounters with the woman for whom he left her, nights of mingled ecstasy and degradation in a room which the light of the neon gin advertisement outside periodically transforms into a womb of mud (p.3); and finally, with something like revulsion, he recalls his mother. Only after being taken through the trauma of his climb (and fall) by a ten-year-old girl does he escape from his nightmare and find release in a fit of hysterical crying. As in Bellamys Looking Backward, the entry to utopia is accompanied by tears. What follows is among the most paradisiacal of all utopias, rife with the symbols of Eden. On his recovery from his perilous ascent he finds himself lying at the foot of a tree; the girl he first encounters gives him fruit which he eats (although, to be fair, it is not an apple, but a banana); and the psychotherapy which she then proceeds to practice on him involves, significantly enough, curing him of his fear of snakes. Pala seems very much a paradise regained, with its birds that talk, its luxuriant but wellgroomed tropical landscape, and its securitywhich is in the first instance provided by a number of comforting adult presences. Unable to walk, Will is first treated for his injuries by the wise and fatherly Dr Robert (shades of Dr Leete), then carried off to bed, where he is soothed to sleep by an attractive yet motherly woman, Susila. For all the emphasis of Huxleys utopia on the virtues of adult responsibility and independence, its opening sequence, with its tears, its helplessness, its reassuring parental presences, reads very much like an account of a return to infancy. After Will sinks into his trance-like slumber, Susila notes that his face seemed suddenly very young, childlike in its perfect serenity (p.29): once again the reversal of the direction of time, that most fantastic of all utopian aspirations, is made to seem almost possible. Pala is, in addition, yet another world where innocence has been in large measure restored: such powerful potential inducers of guilt as religion, sexuality, and the family have been rationalized in order to minimize the problems to which they normally give rise. This in turn is symptomatic of a more general impulse towards simplification and demystification, which also manifests itself in such dubious panaceas as a return to the gold standard, which is touted as a solution to the complex problems of modern financealthough it may equally be seen as exemplifying the utopian desire to eliminate the gap between appearance and reality so strikingly evident in The City of the Sun. As so often, utopia is a world where what you see is what you get. Death, as we have seen, is

172

NARRATING UTOPIA

dealt with with far more openness, courage, and understanding than is the case elsewhere, and if its terror cannot be eliminated altogether, nor the pain of bereavement abolished, Huxleys utopia is yet another where the minimizing of the causes of pain and confusion acts as a figure for their erasure. In keeping with Bacons belief that humanity, by its own efforts, could at least in some part repair the consequences of the Fall, Huxley creates another rationalized Edena world in which the Fall was an exploded doctrine (p.219). Where Island departs most strikingly from the traditional narrative paradigm, in fact, is in its conclusion, where the utopian dream is decisively shattered, not merely by the visitors awakening, as in News from Nowhere, but by the actual destruction of utopia by the invading armies of Rendang. What emerges, however, is a pattern almost identical to that of the dystopias of Zamyatin, Orwell, and Huxley himself. At the end, a woman (Lakshmi) lies dead, the male representative of positive values (Dr Robert) is destroyed, and a more powerful male authority (Colonel Dipa) is triumphant. As in both We and Nineteen Eighty-Four, a heterosexual interaction involving the relationship of a fallible male to a stronger and more resourceful womanhere the dawning attraction between Will and Susilais swept aside by a very different kind of partnership, which in this case in quite explicit in its homo-eroticism. Yet while the unholy alliance of Murugan and Colonel Dipa signals the end of utopia, it also highlights the fact that the original utopian dream was also the product of a male union. For all its emphasis on free, equal relations between the sexes, and its portrayal of strong, independent women, Island nevertheless depicts a society which is the brainchild of two men. Palas utopian society is quite explicitly presented as the fruits of a marriage between the best aspects of Eastern and Western civilizations, the one represented by the Raja of Pala, the other by Dr MacPhail. And while the villainsMurugan, Dipa, Mr Bahu, Joe Aldehydeare also men, it is significant that the strongest expressions of contempt are reserved for the Rani, the embodiment both of False Spirituality and of Motherhood. Underlying Huxleys utopian vision is much the same tacit assumption of male dominance as informs the traditional utopian dream of order. Despite a theoretical commitment to a greater degree of freedom and independence for women, Huxley only shows them playing relatively conventional rolesnursing, teaching, nurturingwhile it is males who continue to take the lead. While there is one brief passage towards the end which seems to acknowledge the extent to which conventional images of women are merely male projections, when Will, under the influence of moksha, sees Susila in quick succession as Mater Dolorosa, a dark Circean goddess (p.289), a laughing girl with a weakness for kisses (p.290), and a cross between Juliana of

LIBERTARIAN ALTERNATIVES

173

Norwich and Catherine of Genoa, at the very end the traditional order is restored. Although throughout the narrative Susila has been depicted as stronger and wiser than Will, the narrative ends with her sobbing in Wills comforting arms, as the troops of Colonel Dipa move in to take control. Gender and Utopian Narrative Huxley, however, is hardly alone in his reinscription of the power structures of existing gender relations. Morris, in fact, reproduces still more glaringly his own societys assumptions as to the natural role of women. As Levitas points out, in her otherwise positive assessment of News from Nowhere, one thing it shares with Bellamys Looking Backward is its failure to give any serious attention to the questions of the position of women or the care of children (Concept of Utopia, p.109). For all his emphasis on freedom, as opposed to the regimentation of Bellamys utopia, Morriss vision of freedom remains very much that of a Victorian male, eating excellent food and drinking fine wine, while waited on by beautiful women. Indeed, when William Guest expresses surprise at finding that women still do all the housework, he is greeted by Old Hammond with the nearest he comes to scorn: perhaps you think housekeeping an unimportant occupation, not deserving of respect. I believe that was the opinion of the advanced women of the nineteenth century, and their male backers. If it is yours, I recommend to your notice an old Norwegian folk-lore tale called How the Man minded the House the result of which minding was that, after various tribulations, the man and the family cow balanced each other at the end of a rope, the man hanging half-way up the chimney, the cow dangling from the roof. [pp.501] Having thus naturalized the apparent male incapacity for domestic labour by appealing to the authority of a tale rooted in the cultural assumptions of an entirely different social formation, Old Hammond goes on to ask: dont you know that it is a great pleasure to a clever woman to manage a house skilfully, and to do it so that all the house-mates about her look pleased, and are grateful to her? And then, you know, everybody likes to be ordered about by a pretty woman: why, it is one of the pleasantest forms of flirtation. [p.51] As the everybody makes clear, News from Nowhere is once again a utopian vision in which the marginal status of women is reinscribed. In the final chapters, indeed, the extent to which it embodies specifically male desire becomes still clearer, as the narrators unconsummated love for the

174

NARRATING UTOPIA

beautiful Ellen is made to act as a figure for the ungraspability of utopia. The bitter-sweet melancholy that suffuses the conclusion stems as much from thwarted sexual yearning as from the loss of utopia as a whole. Even Bogdanov, as we have seen, although he goes further than either Morris or Huxley in foregrounding the contradictions between his narrators theoretical commitment to sexual equality and the effects of his social conditioning, falls into some of the same traps. As in Island, for all the insistence on the unimportance of gender distinctions (women and men are physically more difficult to tell apart, while the Martian language, as has been noted, has no gender distinctions) women are only shown in traditional nurturing roles. Of the three the main female characters, Netti is a doctor, Nella, her mother, works at the Childrens Colony (in fact, the only people we actually see involved in child care are all women), while Enno, although an astronomer, is only shown in the roles of teacher, lover, and an unhappy wife who nearly commits suicide when she is unable to have a child by the man she loves. Thus, while the utopian premise that humans will behave differently under different social circumstances implies acceptance of the socially constructed character of human identity, in all three cases the notion of an essential, natural femininity persists. Taken in conjunction with the obstinate survival of an archaic narrative paradigm, this repeated reinscription of conventional patterns of gender relations even in the context of radical modifications of the social structure as a whole poses the question whether what is most problematic about utopian narrative is not so much the basic premise of imagining a more perfect society per se, as the extent to which it embodies a specifically male fantasy of establishing a familiar security. If its narrative problems seem largely associated with an inability to break away from an increasingly anachronistic narrative model, the aspects of existing social relations that it seems most consistently unable to reimagine are those to do with gender. However, not all narratives with roots in the past are necessarily regressive in their implications: while Morriss Old Hammond may appeal to the example of the Norwegian folktale of How the Man Minded the House to naturalize existing modes of gender inequity, the example of another folktale, Hansel and Gretel might be helpful in establishing a context for examining ways in which utopian narrative may be rewritten from a different gender perspective. In the early stages of the tale, the initiative is taken by the male, while the womans role remains marginalyet at the same time, Hansels initiative consists solely in devising means of finding the way home, of returning to a situation that is familiar; it is only when the prospect of return is denied the children, and they find themselves confronted with the dangers of the altogether new, that Gretel takes the lead. When, having

LIBERTARIAN ALTERNATIVES

175

outwitted the Witch, she leads her brother back home, it is not by the old path but by an entirely new oneone which involves crossing water, symbolically marking their break with the pastand when they do return, it is no longer to the old pattern of a hierarchy in which they are subordinate. Instead, they arrive back older, wiser, and independent. As Bloch argues, the utopian desire for a world where one is truly at home is by no means the same as a desire to return to the way things once were although it is always possible for the former to be contaminated by the latter. Without drawing too crude an analogy between Hansel and Gretel and the history of utopian narrative as a whole (to see women writers as necessarily displaying Gretel-like resourcefulness in dealing with the problems involved is to lapse into another kind of essentialism), what does become clear from at least some feminist rewritings of utopia is that the introduction of a different gender perspective can result in fundamental changes to the narrative paradigm we have so far seen at work. It is with these that the final two chapters will deal.

6. A World of Ones Own: Separatist Utopias


If the patriarchal character of the traditional utopian narrative paradigm is reflected not only in the social and political provisions of the Renaissance utopia, but also in the distinctively masculine character of the fantasy which underlies them, it is scarcely surprising that where the influence of this paradigm persists, its doubly patriarchal bias should be so hard to escape. As we have seen, the conscious attempts of writers such as Bellamy, Wells, and Huxley to provide for a greater degree of sexual equality are undermined by the contradictions that emerge within the narrative which perhaps indicates the extent to which the paradigm itself serves to potentiate the latent assumptions of male dominance rooted in the culture which utopia seeks to transcend. Even dystopian attacks on the premises of the traditional utopia rarely avoid a reinscription of the utopian suppression of the female: except in Atwoods The Handmaids Tale, dystopian narrative enacts an erasure of the feminine no less striking than that embodied in Bacons The New Atlantis. It would seem to follow, therefore, that a successful challenge to the inherently patriarchal assumptions of the traditional utopia might be likely to have more far-reaching narrative repercussions than those produced by Wellss primarily narrative experimentation, by libertarian reworkings of the traditional utopias authoritarian premises, or even dystopian parody. Such a challenge is clearly the goal of a number of writers who have envisaged societies not merely no longer dominated by men, but wholly exclusive of them. And while some of these (those of Monique Wittig, Joanna Russ, or Suzy McKee Charnas, for example) are only tangentially utopian,1 othersnotably Charlotte Perkins Gilmans Herland (1915) and Sally Miller Gearharts The Wanderground (1979)offer fully developed accounts of a more perfect society whose most fundamental premise is the absence of men. Herland Of the two, Herland seems, at least at first sight, far closer to the traditional paradigm. Whereas Bellamy, Morris, and Wells had already acknowledged the implications of the end of the age of discovery by either projecting their utopias into the future, or else positing such science fictional scenarios as the existence of a parallel universe, Gilman adheres to the time-honoured convention of the geographical utopia, lying in some unspecified

A WORLD OF ONES OWN

177

southland, inaccessible and undiscovered. Like Mores Utopia and Bacons Bensalem, it once had links to the outside world, but these were decisively severedalthough not, in this instance, by the conscious decision of a male authority figure. Where King Utopus decreed the cutting of the isthmus connecting Utopia to the mainland, and King Solamona took the political decision to isolate his kingdom from the rest of the world, Herlands isolation came about as the result of a natural catastrophe. At one time, we learn, the plateau on which Herland is located was inhabited by what is referred to as a bi-sexual race (p.54), which formerly possessed all the accoutrements of a patriarchal society: ships, commerce, an army, a king (p.54)not to mention slaves. However, like Campanellas Solarians, they are forced by the depredations of more warlike races to retreat to the security of an impregnable strongholdin this case, a mountain fastness connected to the outside world only by a single pass. It is while their army is off defending the pass that a volcanic eruption takes place, completely blocking itand leaving the army on the wrong side of the impenetrable obstruction. Very few men are left behind, and those who are are promptly wiped out by a slave uprising, followed in turn by a desperate struggle in the course of which the surviving women kill all the male slaves. In the end, we learn, There was literally no one left on this beautiful high garden land but a bunch of hysterical girls and some older slave women (p.55). With the closure of the pass it would appear that the women are doomed not merely to isolation, but to inevitable extinction, deprived both symbolically and literally of access by the impregnating male presence. It is at this point, however, that they are rescued from racial oblivion by one of their number (described as a wonder-woman) developing the capacity for parthenogenesis. This proves to be an inherited trait: each of the five daughters she bears produces five daughters in her turn, and they, with characteristically utopian symmetry, give birth to a further five daughters each, and so on. From the first Queen-Priestess-Mother a new race of ultra-women (p.57) is born. In what is almost a precise mirror-inversion of the male utopian fantasy of masculine appropriation of the womb, Gilman imagines a womb-like environment from which the male is forever excluded. In contrast to the Baconian dream (and Huxleian nightmare) of rendering women superfluous to the reproductive process, Gilman posits a scenario where it is men who are redundant. In most other respects, however, Gilmans all-female society conforms closely to the traditional utopian pattern. There is the familiar emphasis on peace and security: Herlands inhabitants are notable for their confidence and self-assurance, which is born of their having nothing to fear. Nature has been domesticated with an almost Wellsian singlemindedness: wild animals have been eliminated, and while there is a

178

NARRATING UTOPIA

profusion of cats (which have been trained not to eat birds), there are no dogs to foul the pathways of what is repeatedly described as like a gigantic park or gardeneven the trees are under as careful cultivation as so many cabbages (p.14). Indeed, at times it almost seems that it is only in the gender of its inhabitants that Gilmans utopia differs significantly from the traditional norm. It, too, provides the womb-like security and untroubled, innocent happiness of the typical rational Edenalthough it is significant that Gilman does depart from the island location so beloved of male authors of utopian fiction, isolating her utopia instead by perching it on top of a piece of geography [which] stands up like a basalt column (p.38). Gilmans major innovation, in fact, has less to do with the structure of her utopia as such, than with her handling of that most traditional feature of utopian narrative, the visit (with its attendant guided tour). Here the issue of gender becomes crucial, for Gilman chooses to problematize the relationship between visitor and utopia by making the visitors (three in number) to her all-female utopia male. This, in its turn, has a number of consequences. As we have seen, in its traditional formulation, the visit to utopia tends to impose passivity on the visitor: inevitably ignorant of how things work, of the basic facts concerning utopian societyits customs, its history, and so forthhe has therefore to be told or shown everything of importance by the more knowledgeable inhabitants. What results is a scenario which, while ostensibly dialogic in format, is actually monologic in effect: the visitor fills the role of passive and acquiescent audience, whose primary function is to elicit and be persuaded by the authoritative utterance of his utopian mentor. In Herland, however, the situation is radically different: the interactions between Gilmans explorers and the utopians who act as their captors, instructors, and even partners have little in common with the cosy camaraderie which exists between Julian West and Dr Leete, or William Guest and Old Hammond; nor, for that matter, is there much sign of the schoolmasterly indulgence with which Dr Robert treats Will Farnaby, let alone the self-abasing reverence of Bacons narrator in the presence of the representative of the House of Salomon. There is, to begin with, a marked difference in emphasis. Gilman devotes far less space than usual to direct disquisitions on the wonders of utopia, and far more to the reactions of the visitors to what they experience, while at the same time exploiting the difference in gender to sharpen the contrast between their perspective and that of the inhabitants. Although the dynamic of the relations between visitors and utopians remains in keeping with utopian tradition, the effect could hardly be more dissimilar: in Herland, it is women who have the knowledge and power, the men who have to adjust to the values and expectations of the society in which they find themselvesand by enacting this reversal of conventional gender roles, Gilman calls

A WORLD OF ONES OWN

179

attention to the situation of the visitor in a way that most utopian fictions do not. In place of the uncritical transmission of information which the visitor normally provides, as if his sole purpose were to provide the reader with the most faithful and unmediated account possible of the merits of utopia, Gilmans visitors respond to their new situation in a manner which is often confused, reluctant, or even frankly hostile. Rather than trying to close the gap in perception between the utopians and their visitor/s as fast as possible, Gilman stresses its existence, at the same time encouraging the reader to judge the judgements of the visitors. Herland, in other words, encourages what most utopian fictions seek to suppress: an active critical participation on the part of the reader. Nor is this the only change in emphasis. Inaccessible though Herland isto the extent that it has gone undiscovered for two thousand years one of the most striking features of the opening sequence is the relative ease with which the visitors get there. While the physical barriers unscalable cliffs, waterfalls, mountain ranges, and so forthwhich isolate Herland from the rest of the world may seem formidable enough at first sight, surmounting the challenge which they represent involves none of the pain, hardship, or trauma so apparent in works such as Looking Backward or Island. Faced by such apparently insuperable geographical obstacles, Gilmans narrator and his companions avoid the normal arduous rite of transition by resorting to the aid of modern technology: they simply fly there. The enormous wealth of Terry (the most traditionally male of the three) provides a steam yacht to cover the first part of the journey, a motorboat to enable them to penetrate the upper reaches of the river above which Herland rises, and an aeroplane to ferry them to the plateau itself. Of all journeys to utopia, it is by far the most comfortable and bestequipped; in marked contrast to the normal utopian pattern, the visitors problems begin only after they get there. Almost from the moment of their arrival, Gilmans visitors encounter difficultieswhich in itself distinguishes them from the majority of their fellow explorers, for whom acceptance into utopia is normally a relatively uncomplicated process. At most, there may be a few minor bureaucratic problems, as in A Modern Utopia, or a seeking of preliminary assurances, as in Bacons The New Atlantis, but in general utopian societies are notable for the trust and hospitality with which they welcome strangers. While Julian West may initially be somewhat overwhelmed by the shock of finding himself in a new world, his utopian hosts are quick to put him at his ease, offering him wine, food, tobacco, and the hand of their daughter in marriage; and the periodic unease of Morriss William Guest or Wellss Mr Barnstaple is largely attributable to their sense that utopia is almost too good to be true. Even in Men Like Gods, where almost the first action of the

180

NARRATING UTOPIA

visitors is to kill someone with their motor car, the first reaction of the godlike utopians is one of benevolent curiosity: the visitors actually have to shoot two of them before they finally take action. In Herland, however, the situation is markedly different. Not only are the inhabitants considerably more wary of strangers, but the visitors also show themselves to be more than usually aggressive: almost their first action on arriving is to attempt to take one of the inhabitants captive. As a direct consequence, they find themselves forcibly confinedand while they are well treated, things are by no means made easy for them. It is they who have to learn the local language, there being no comfortable fiction that utopia is naturally English-speaking, and it is their masculine assumptions that have to be radically revised in the face of an exclusively female society that evidently works considerably better than their own. (It takes them some time, in fact, finally to abandon their conviction that there must be some men in charge, somewhere, given that everything runs so smoothly.) In response to such unaccustomed hardships, the three make an early attempt to escape, to reassert their freedom of actiononly to find themselves recaptured with humiliating ease. Nor is this by any means the only humiliation they experience: in many fields of endeavour which they have been conditioned to view as exclusively male preserves, the utopian women prove themselves to be decisively superior; in a world where the natural superiority of the male is not assumed, their attempts somehow to demonstrate it are repeatedly frustrated. The result is a growing sense of unease: even as early as their first confrontation with the women of utopia, the narrator confesses to the funniest feelinga very early feelinga feeling that I traced back and back in memory until I caught up with it at last. It was that sense of being hopelessly in the wrong that I had so often felt in early youth when my short legs utmost effort failed to overcome the fact that I was late to school We felt like small boys, very small boys, caught doing mischief in same gracious ladys house. [p.19] It is an image which recursand one which highlights one of the most traditionally utopian aspects of the narrative, namely, the state of childlike dependence to which the visitors are reduced. While the narrative starts out with all the trappings of a tale of conventional male derring-do, in the tradition of Rider Haggards She or Conan Doyles The Lost World, it soon takes a very different direction. On their arrival they are physically overpowered: Each of us was seized by five women, each holding arm or leg or head; we were lifted like children, straddling helpless children, and borne onward, wriggling indeed, but most ineffectually. [p.23]

A WORLD OF ONES OWN

181

Struggling manfully, but held secure most womanfully (p.23), they are carried inside, anaesthetized, undressed, washed, and put to bed, as even the macho Terry ruefully acknowledges, like so many yearling babies (p.25)and whereas in most utopian fictions such imposed passivity seems to constitute an important part of utopias appeal, in Gilmans case it is exploited for comic and satiric effect. While for Julian West or Will Farnaby being tucked up in bed and put to sleep may be an unmixed blessinga welcome return to the blissful security of childhoodfor Gilmans intrepid explorers it is an unending source of embarrassment. Their evident resentment at their subordinate status in a world run by women becomes a consistent source of humour. A rarity among utopias, Herland is (among other things) genuinely funny. Part of the humour, of course, lies in the conspicuous gap between the visitors expectations and the reality they encounter. Terry, we are told, has visions of a sort of sublimated summer resortjust Girls and Girls and Girls (p.7) and talksonly half-jokinglyof becoming a latter-day King Solomon. The situation in which he in fact finds himselfa prisoner, guarded and watched over by the all-too-capable women of Herlandis a source of acute discomfiture. In addition to finding it hard to come to terms with the nature of the society in which they find themselves, however, the visitors find equally unnerving the utopians sharp eye for the gaps and contradictions that emerge from their own somewhat selective account of the world they have come from. Despite what Van, the narrator, describes as a tacit endeavour to conceal much of the social status at home (p.80) the visitors frequently find themselves revealing the most discreditable features of their own society as they struggle to answer the awkward questions they are so often posed: such ... questions as might have intimidated a university professor (p.65). Much to the visitors alarm, Herlands women prove singularly adept at drawing deductions not only from what they are told, but also from the things we palpably avoided saying (p.80) and reveal a disconcerting ability to put two and two together in such a way as to expose the falsity of many of their claims. Terrys comforting fiction that women enjoy a privileged position in a maledominated society, for example, soon falls apart in the face of questioning: Tell uswhat is the work of the world, that men dowhich we have not here? Oh, everything, Terry said grandly. The men do everything, with us. He squared his broad shoulders and lifted his chest. We do not allow women to work. Women are lovedidolizedhonoredkept in the home to care for the children. Zava begged: Tell me first, do no women work, really?

182

NARRATING UTOPIA

Why, yes, Terry admitted. Some have to, of the poorer sort. About how manyin your country? About seven or eight million, said Jeff [pp.601] Even from quite minor detailscasual remarks about the treatment of cats and dogs in the visitors worldthe utopians are able to draw much larger inferences as to the questionable nature of the assumptions informing their society as a whole. Innocent though they may be in many respects, the utopians are far from nave. As the narrator comments: just as a clear-eyed, intelligent, perfectly honest, and well-meaning child will frequently jar ones self-esteem by innocent questions, so did these women, without the slightest appearance of malice or satire, continually bring up points of discussion which we spent our best efforts in evading. [p.62] As a satiric device, of course, this is hardly new: Swift achieves much the same kind of effect in Gullivers Travels, when the King of Brobdingnag interrogates the boastful Gulliver, and accurately intuits from his replies the unsavoury reality underlying his guests account of European society.2 Gilmans focus is rather narrower, her main concern being to expose the inherent contradictions of her own societys sexual politics, rather than to offer Swifts blanket condemnation of hypocrisy, injustice, cruelty, corruptionof all that renders civilization, in his view, an organized lie yet the device itself is similar. Where the real difference lies is in the presence of such satire in a utopian contextfor Gilmans purpose is not merely satiric. Damaging though her critique of male values undoubtedly is, there is nevertheless a sense of genuine dialogue at places in the text: not only do the visitors undergo a painful process of learning to acknowledge the virtues of utopia (as opposed to accepting them uncritically from the outset, as is so often the case), the utopians themselves reveal an unusual degree of openness to change. Although only too aware of the shortcomings of the visitors world, they remain eager not only to learn about it, but to learn, if possible, from it. While Gilmans intent is no less didactic than that of earlier utopian writers, there are far fewer of the ponderous, one-sided set pieces that characterize traditional utopian narrative: dialogue, instead, becomes an interaction in which actual communication takes place, rather than merely serving to mask the unidirectional and monologic transmission of information. One side-effect of this is that the actual character of the visitor takes on a significance seldom encountered in the traditional utopia. While Gilmans visitors often make fools of themselves, what they say actually matters, in a way that is rarely the case in narratives where the visitors main function

A WORLD OF ONES OWN

183

is merely to be persuaded by what he is told, and to act as a medium for the communication of the utopian message. Normally, as we have seen, such individualizing traits as the visitor may possessthe impatience of Campanellas sea-captain, the weariness of Morriss narrator, or the mawkish sentimentality of Julian Westare rarely more than vestigial. Even the Botanist in A Modern Utopia, whose main function appears to be to provide some variety in terms of characterization, rapidly becomes a rather tiresome distraction from what is clearly Wellss main concernthe theorizing of a more perfect form of social organization. In Gilmans hands, however, the characterization of the visitors, although certainly schematized, has a genuine function. Whereas the character traits of most visitors to utopia are more or less interchangeableit would make little difference to the actual narrative if it were Will Farnaby who arrived in Bellamys future Boston, or Julian West who landed in Palain Herland they make a difference, representing as they do radically different possible interactions between the values of utopia and those of the outside world. Thus, while the narrator himself may be seen as conforming fairly closely to the traditional norm, inasmuch as he is quickly persuaded of the superiority of the utopian way, he is flanked by two companions whose long-held assumptions prove less susceptible to alteration by exposure to the utopian ideal. The more immediately striking example of this, of course, is Terry, the ultra-masculine leader of the expedition, whose only real interest in women is as objects of sexual desire. When the reality proves to be conspicuously different than his anticipations, it is he who prompts their unsuccessful escape bid, who shows the clearest frustration at the constraints imposed upon them, and who is most consistently critical of utopian society. Yet here again Gilmans focus is less on the perfections of utopia, than on the glaring inadequacies of the visitors response. Brave, resourceful, charismatic, a mans man (p.9), Terry seems at first sight the archetypal explorer of (male-authored) romance. Yet in the context of Herlands value system his manliness often seems indistinguishable from childish petulance. His evident resentment of women who do not conform to his expectations regarding appropriate female behaviour expresses itself at first in rather schoolboyish attempts at humour: he makes digs at the Colonels or Grandmas, as he characterizes their captors, and contrives extremely forced puns on the names of the tutors assigned to them. But his hostility does not end there: instead, his frustration at the old-maid impudence (p.33) that prevents him mixing with the real girls, together with his conviction that There never was a woman yet that did not enjoy being mastered (p.131), culminates in an attempted rape. Despite the example of an entire society of women controlling their own destiny and

184

NARRATING UTOPIA

being happy doing so, he continues to cling to his fixed belief that what a woman really wants is to be forced to submit to the superior power of the man. Not even the dismal failure of his attempt at a practical demonstration seems to move him: while the response of his intended victim (a powerful kick in the testicles) would seem to constitute a convincing refutation of his thesis, he remains unpersuaded: Id give a year of my life to have her alone again, he said slowly, his hands clenched till the knuckles were white (p.143). By itself, this might seem perilously close to caricaturewhich is not to say that a great deal of conventional male behaviour might not also be described in the same termsbut Terrys crude attempts at asserting male superiority are only one aspect of Gilmans representation of male responses to the threatening reversal of gender expectations which Herland represents. In addition to Terry and the narrator, the party has a third memberJeff, the doctorwhose views differ markedly from those of either of his companions. Jeff, we are told, idealized women in the best Southern style. He was full of chivalry and sentiment, and all that. And he was a good boy; he lived up to his ideals (p.9). As a result, it is Jeff who is by far the most enthusiastic about the matriarchal society they encounterto the extent, indeed, that his companions begin to regard him as something of a traitorhe so often flopped over and took their side of things (p.51). Yet Jeff also has his limitations: while he displays none of the closed-minded opposition which Terry exhibits, neither does he seem in any way changed by his experiences, as the narrator is. Where the narrator is shown as becoming increasingly sympathetic to the society in which he finds himself, Jeff seems almost a parody of the passive, uncritical observer of the traditional utopia (a device which has the side-effect of making the actual narrator seem more objective, and hence reliable). He has always idealized women, and seen them as other than they arethe narrator complains of his tendency to put rose-colored halos (p.9) on themwith the result that when he encounters women who differ markedly from those he is used to, his attitude remains virtually unchanged: the irony that in Herland womens superiority is practical rather than theoretical is one that appears to elude him. Significantly, Jeff is the only one of the three who appears unperturbed when the marriages they contract in Herland turn out not to include sexual relations other than for strictly procreational purposes. Unlike Terry, who attempts to rape his wife, or the narrator, whose resultant emotional difficulties are rendered in some detail, Jeff apparently finds the absence of sex quite as natural as do the utopiansfor whom sexuality had ceased to be an issue some two thousand years before. In seeking to illustrate the gap between the expectations of the male

A WORLD OF ONES OWN

185

visitors, which are rooted in the sexual politics of their own society, and those of their utopian wives, Gilman provides a curious analogy: imagine a devoted and impassioned man trying to set up housekeeping with a lady angel, a real wings-and-harp-and-halo angel, accustomed to fulfilling divine missions all over interstellar space. This angel might love the man with an affection quite beyond his power of return or even of appreciation, but her ideas of service and duty would be on a very different scale from his. Of course, if she was a stray angel in a country of men, he might have had his way with her; but if he was a stray man among angels! [p.123] While hardly the most fortunate of comparisons, it does serve to suggest the extent of what Gilman terms the gulfs of difference (p.94) between the utopians and their visitors. Of course, given the absence not only of sexual relations, but of any equivalent to either home or family in Herland, the fact that the utopians should consider contracting marriages with their visitors at all remains something of an unresolved contradiction. Nevertheless, the marriages do highlight what in many utopias is passed overthe fact that the inhabitants of a society radically different from our own are themselves liable to be radically different. Unlike Bellamys Leete family, who differ hardly at all from the middle-class norms of the late nineteenth century, Gilmans utopians are differentdespite which Jeff accepts their unorthodox views on marriage without as much as a flicker of surprise: He accepted the angel theory, swallowed it whole, tried to force it on uswith varying effect. He so worshipped not only Celis, but what she represented; he had become so deeply convinced of the almost supernatural advantages of this country and people, that he took his medicine like aI cannot say like a man, but more as if he wasnt one. [p.123] As with so many visitors to utopia, Jeff, while uncritically approving of utopias superiority, seems oddly immune to any sense of its otherness. Utopia is betterbut it is not strange. Like Julian West, William Guest, Mr Barnstaple, Jeff is already a convert: no process of persuasion is necessary for him. Yet while Gilmans often satiric presentation of the interactions between the utopians and their visitors effects an unsettling reversal and defamiliarization of conventional sexual assumptions, the actual picture of utopian society that emerges mirrors many of the most familiar features of the conventional utopia. The cult of supreme male authority, implicit in the traditional utopia, seized upon and made explicit in its dystopian

186

NARRATING UTOPIA

inversion, is here replaced by an idealization of the feminine no less pronounced. With its Altar of Motherhood, its great ruling Over Mother, its repeated references to super-, ultra-, and wonder-women, Herland offers merely a reversal, rather than any radical transcendence of the conventional narrative paradigm.3 Although at first sight its matriarchal society could hardly seem further removed from the patriarchal norms of utopian tradition, this reversal of one of utopian narratives major premises in fact leaves many of its dynamics unaffected. As Susan Gubar points out, Gilmans strategy of reversal [often] threatens to invalidate her feminism by defining it in precisely the terms set up by the misogynists it would repudiate (p.198). While the feminine values which Herland endorses are represented as a positive alternative to the abuses of the patriarchal society of the three explorers, they nevertheless reflect a conception of femininity which is very much the creation of precisely that male-dominated society whose values Gilman rejects. In what amounts to its fetishization of the virtues of Motherhood, its emphasis on the sacred duties of child care, and its repeated stress on the purity and virtue of the utopian women, Herland reveals what Bammer terms an unsettling convergence between a vision of what women, under utopian conditions, could be, and the normative definition of what a woman, according to the prevailing ideology should be (p.31).4 As has often been pointed out, Herland is a utopia in which womans sphere remains the home; the only difference is that here the home has expanded to embrace the entire community. When Terry sneers that [t]here isnt a home in the whole pitiful place (p.98), Jeff retorts that [t]here isnt anything else, and you know it (p.98). Herland is a country which has been entirely domesticated: there are no wild areaseven the forests have been groomed and petted (p.13) to be useful as well as beautiful; the entire country has been purged of pests and mess-creating animals; and overall, we learn, their country was as neat as a Dutch kitchen (p.53). Despite two thousand years of separate development, Herlands women manifest precisely those idealized qualities ascribed to them by the patriarchal ideology of early twentieth-century North America. In thus effectively naturalizing her own societys socially constructed gender roles, Gilman endorses a view of woman which, as Bammer argues, is revalued, but not redefined (p.93), and which ultimately serves to reaffirm the very ideology of separate gender spheres on which the suppression of women had been based (p.35).5 Nevertheless, while Gilmans vision of a utopia which is essentially the private sphere writ large enshrines the concept of domestic virtues prevailing at the time, its emphasis on order is also wholly in keeping with the visions of utopia offered by male writers. From Mores Utopia, where even the cities are both

A WORLD OF ONES OWN

187

identical and equidistant, to Wellss Men Like Gods, which shares Gilmans passion for cleanliness to the point of eliminating not only all pavementfouling animals, but even the untidier sorts of small birds (p.122), utopian narratives repeatedly represent worlds where everything is in its place, known and accounted for. As in the best run homes, utopia provides an environment where nothing ever goes wrongindeed, where nothing ever happens. Process and changeanything that is liable to disturb order are normally conspicuous in utopia only by their absence. Herland is no exception in this regard. As in so many utopias, the actual course of utopian history is vague and in places even contradictory: from a developmental level described as being equivalent to that of Ancient Egypt or Greece (p.67) they have apparently advanced to the point where electric cars travel along their modern roadways, but very little appears to have happened in the interim. The utopians, we are told, are agreed on most of the basic principles of their life; and not only agreed in principle, but accustomed for these sixty-odd generations to act on those principles (p.122), yet despite this continuity, they exhibit little interest in the past. When the narrator asks his wife-to-be Have you no respect for the past? For what was thought and believed by your foremothers? she replies simply: Why, no Why should we? They are all gone. They knew less than we do. The women of Herland, he reflects, had ignored their past and built daringly for the future (p.111). And this characteristically utopian vagueness concerning history has its counterpart, at the level of narrative, in a consistent vagueness with regard to the passage of time: the weeks ran into months (p.33) is a typical formulation, and while we learn at the end that the visitors stay has lasted more than a year (p.137) there is virtually no specific indication of when anything takes place during that period. Given the opening words of the bookThis is written from memory, unfortunately (p.1)it would appear that this is a deliberate narrative strategy. Yet what is perhaps most problematic in Herland is not so much the lack of action as (as a number of critics have pointed out) the absence of desire, which has apparently disappeared along with the men: the sexual tensions which trouble even so idyllic a world as that of News from Nowhere have simply vanished. Herlands citizens are women whose great life-view had no shady places; they had a high sense of personal decorum, but no shameno knowledge of anything to be ashamed of (p.101). As Van, the narrator, later remarks: No wonder this whole nation of women was peaceful and sweet in expressionthey had no horrible ideas (p.111). Free from even such pleasant vices (p.98) as drinking and smoking, it is a world which, in the more acid words of Terry, is like a perpetual Sunday school (p.99). Yet while this clearly reflects contemporary stereotypes of

188

NARRATING UTOPIA

feminine virtue, it isonce againalso very much in keeping with utopian tradition. Like its Renaissance predecessors, Herland exhibits the characteristic utopian impulse towards simplification: problems are not so much resolved, as avoided by the elimination of their source. As in Mores Utopia, it is difficult to get into trouble, primarily because there is so little trouble to get intobut in some ways Gilman goes even farther. Where earlier utopias sought the restoration of innocence through the control of desire (as for example in The City of the Sun, where intercourse is supervised by a team of gym instructors, matrons, doctors, and astrologers), Gilman eliminates it altogether. One of the resultant problems, however, is that in doing so Gilman ends up reinstating the infantilization of the visitor which she began by satirizing. Whereas the reduction of the explorers on their arrival to the state of helpless children, undressed and put to bed, offers an effective parody of the customary passivity of the traditional visitor to utopia, it is harder to discern any such complicating irony in Gilmans later representation of the marriages contracted between the explorers and three of the inhabitants. Part of Gilmans purpose, of course, in putting forward the notion of marriages which include neither cohabitation nor sexual relations, is to focus attention on the assumptions of the male explorers, whose horror at the absence of what they had hitherto taken for granted is rendered in some detail. (Or rather, to be more precise, the horror of two of them: as we have seen, the idealistic Jeff does not appear to notice that there is anything unusual about the arrangements.) Yet while this serves to expose the realities underlying so much male rhetoric regarding the sanctity of marriage, Gilmans actual descriptions of Herlands unconventional marital arrangements contain some curiously revealing analogies. When his wife refuses to accept sexual relations as a natural part of marriage, Van first tries to rationalize this by quite literally, and apparently uncritically comparing her to an angel (p.123), and then praises her successgreat superwoman that she was (p.130)in distracting him from his sexual preoccupations: no child, stormily demanding a cookie between meals, was ever more subtly diverted into an interest in house-building than was I when I found an apparently imperative demand had disappeared without my noticing it. [p.128] Here the process of infantilization, elsewhere reinforced by his wifes use of such epithets as you blessed child (p.110), is represented in a largely positive lightas is also the case when Van finally renounces his sexual desires in favour of his wifes purer ideal of gender relations. Indeed, the abject submissiveness with which he acknowledges her superior

A WORLD OF ONES OWN

189

judgement, in addition to reproducing the blurring of the distinction between wife and mother so strikingly apparent in the utopias of Wells and Bellamy, almost seems to prefigure the dystopian abasement of D-503 and Winston Smith in the face of the larger-than-life representative of the dominant ideology: After I got over the jar to my pride I found that loving up was a very good sensation after all. It gave me a queer feeling, way down deep, as of the stirring of some ancient prehistoric consciousness, a feeling that they were right somehowthat this was the way to feel. It was likecoming home to mother. [pp.1412] While the power relations envisaged in Herland may differ radically from those of the traditional male utopian fantasy, inasmuch as what is imagined is not the male recovery of prenatal security, but rather the restoration of some lost world of prehistoric matriarchy, the regressive character of the utopian dream remains very much in evidence. One of Herlands most puzzling features, however, involves what would seem at first sight to be a clear departure from the utopian norm. Given that the traditional utopia so often represents a state of perfection or nearperfection, it follows that any change is likely to be for the worse, and the majority of male-authored utopias, as we have seen, include provisions to prevent such an eventualitywhether by the maintenance of formidable armies (although only, of course, for purposes of self-defence), keeping its location concealed, or extending its compass to include the entire world, thereby eliminating external enemies. In Herland, however, despite its inhabitants evident satisfaction with things as they are, and in the face of all they have been able to deduce regarding the evils of the world outside, the women seem astonishingly open to the possibility of renewed relations with menand in an attempt to render this plausible, Gilman stresses the possibility that the interaction of the male visitors with the strong, independent women of Herland may lead not only to the re-education of the former, but also to a fuller range of experience for the latter. Vans future wife, for example, declares: We are only half a people. We have our woman-ways and they have their man-ways and their both-ways. We have worked out a system of living which is, of course, limited. They must have a broader, richer, better one. [pp.978] Yet despite repeated assertions that a bi-sexual society must necessarily be much more stirring with new possibilities of growth (p.135), their effect is undercut by the force of Gilmans own satire. Such optimism hardly seems compatible with the bleak picture which the utopians have deduced

190

NARRATING UTOPIA

from their visitors account of the outside worldand while this does, of course, open the way for a sequel (duly provided in With Her in Ourland, in which Van and his wife undertake a tour of his world), one of the least convincing features of Herlands decidedly abrupt conclusion is the utopians apparent readiness to accept their visitors word of honour as gentlemen not in any way to betray the location of this country (p.145). Although Terry, angry and humiliated following his unsuccessful rape attempt, immediately protests (in language strongly reminiscent of colonialist fantasies of the land as a female body awaiting penetration) that [t]he first thing Ill do is to get an expedition fixed up to force an entrance into Maland (p.146), the women are apparently quite content to rely on the entirely alien concept of a gentlemans word6to the extent that a mere six lines later his promise has been accepted, and their departure ensues.7 This tacit acceptance of the values of the society to which Herland offers an alternative, however, is hard to reconcile with Gilmans repeated emphasis on the incompatibility between Herland and its visitors (a relationship which differs radically from that obtaining in the traditional utopia). Simply by reason of their being male, they represent both a threat and a challenge to the utopian order in a way that the traditional visitor does not. Although Morriss narrator may be unable to sustain his utopian dream, and while Wellss Mr Barnstaple may consent to return to his own world, there is normally no inherent incompatibility between the visitor and utopia. Once converted to the utopian way, there is no reason why the visitor should not be co-opted and absorbed by the more perfect society (as is Julian West, for example). In Herland, by contrast, the visitors impose on utopia the imperative to change: unless the visitors are deported, imprisoned, or done away with,8 their mere presence implies that utopia will ultimately have to adapt to new and potentially disruptive forms of human relationship. While the focus is primarily on the ways in which the visitors are forced to adjust, it is clear that utopia, too, will be changed by their continued residence. This, in its turn, is a reflection of the fact that Gilmans utopian society is one whose basis is biologically, as well as socially determinedand while this is in part responsible for the more dynamic character of the relations between utopia and its visitors, it is clear that it also creates certain problems. Whereas the traditional utopia posits a society structured in such a way as to promote more desirable conduct on its members part, Gilmans makes inherited characteristicsnamely sexual differenceequally, if not more fundamental: the basis of her more perfect society is genetic as well as environmental. As a result, the male visitor becomes an alien, differing from the utopians not merely in terms of values, but in terms of his very being. The superiority of the utopians is, implicitly, innate, rather than

A WORLD OF ONES OWN

191

being something to which the visitor, given sufficient exposure to a utopian environment, might aspire. While in theory, Gilmans separatist utopia may be seen as offering a model from which the rest of the world might well learn, the problems inherent in the notion of a society whose superiority has, even in part, a genetic basis remain unresolved. If sexual difference can provide such a basis, one might well ask, then why not race? Gilmans own racist tendencies have been commented on,9 and it is scarcely reassuring to learn that Herlands inhabitants are most likely of Aryan stock, and were once in contact with the best civilization of the old world (p.54). We are also informed that They were white, but somewhat darker than our northern races because of their constant exposure to sun and air (p.54). And while such overt statements are very much the exception in Herland,10 the unsettling implications remain: Gilmans is yet another in which some of the least appealing features of the dominant ideology of the time are still more starkly reproduced. The Wanderground Where such implications can lead may be seen more clearly in Sally Miller Gearharts The Wanderground, in which womens superiority, rather than emerging from the confrontation of a female utopian society with the crass assumptions of males from the outside world, becomes a givena fact to be celebrated. Written from the perspective of a feminism far more radical than Gilmans, it portrays a world in which sexual difference is likewise far more polarized. While the women of the Wanderground possess (as we shall see) quite literally supernatural powers, which are used not only for their own protection, but for that of the planet, the men of the City are described as Driven in their own madness to destroy themselves and us and any living thing (p.3). Men and women are adversaries, between whom the dialogue which is so striking a feature of Herland is no longer even an option:11 We once had hope for them, but even that hope they snuffed out (p.2), laments one of the Hill Women. Even with the gentlesthe small minority of men who, knowing that maleness touched women only with the accumulated hatred of centuries, touched no women at all (p.2)communication is a precarious affair, fraught with hostility and suspicion. Yet it is not merely the patriarchal ideology of the traditional utopia that Gearhart challenges: The Wanderground also representsat least at first sightan equally radical break with the traditional narrative paradigm. It is a utopia without visitors (the only contacts with outsiders take place beyond its borders), without compensatory metaphors of transition, and without even any real linear, connected narrative. In its place are a series

192

NARRATING UTOPIA

of loosely overlapping episodes concerning the lives of the Hill Women, in which only a handful of characters recur, yet from which there nevertheless emerges a comprehensive picture of how Gearharts utopians deal with the realities of love, death, danger, religious experience, and interaction with the natural world. They are portrayed in conference on questions of policy, engaging in defence duty, andmost unusuallymaking concerted efforts to preserve the memory of the past from which their utopia emerged: as in News from Nowhere, the section dealing with the past is by far the longest in the book. In addition, The Wanderground is a work in which the element of fantasy is far more crucial than in any of the utopias so far discussed. As we have seen, despite such episodes as the miraculous apparition of an advance copy of the Bible in The New Atlantis, it is noteworthy that the majority of traditionally conceived utopias content themselves with relatively modest extrapolations from the realities of their time. The contrast between Wellss exuberant exploration of the possibilities of weightlessness, invisibility, time travel, and interplanetary travel in his science fiction, for example, and the modesty of invention evident in his utopias could scarcely be more marked. Gearhart, by contrast, shows little regard for the constraints of relative plausibility, which lay something of a dead hand on the inventiveness of so many earlier utopian works. Whereas the traditional utopia tends to rely as little as possible on exceeding the limits of existing human or technological possibilities (leaving aside whatever bizarre elaborations may surround the process of getting there), The Wanderground makes no pretence at realism. Like News from Nowhere, only to a far greater degree, Gearharts utopia offers, not so much a potential blueprint for a more perfect society, as a prefigurative vision of future possibilitiespresumably designed, like those of Morris and Bogdanov, to energize and inspire a readership already engaged in various forms of political and personal struggle towards goals to which utopian fiction is able to give a more concrete image than any provided by contemporary society. Set at an unspecified point in the future, The Wanderground posits a world in which the total destruction of the environment by a male-dominated society has only been forestalled by what is termed the Revolt of the Mother (p.158)the Earths refusal to consent any longer to its violation. No explanation is offered as to the cause of this, but its effects are dramatic. Machines and weapons suddenly cease to function; animals refuse to be ridden by males; and men lose their sexual potency outside the urban enclaves within which most of them live. Nevertheless, the threat that men may one day recover both their sexual and technological power remains, and it is the prevention of such a disaster that constitutes one of the main priorities of the Hill Women, who represent Gearharts vision of an all-

A WORLD OF ONES OWN

193

female utopian society. Like the inhabitants of Herland, the Hill Women have developed the capacity for parthenogenesis, but whereas that was virtually the sole element of the marvellous in Gilmans utopia, in Gearharts it is merely one wonder among many. Over the years, the Hill Women have developed their psychic powers to the point where their abilities are, quite literally, supernaturala premise which also allows Gearhart to bypass some of the more problematic aspects of womens situation in existing society. Thus, in response to the growing feminist awareness during the 1970s that women were the prisoners (or even the creation) of linguistic as well as social structures, Gearhart fantasizes a world beyond language altogether: although the discipline of speaking aloud is sometimes practiced for the refining of present images and the generation of new ones (p.60), communication between the Hill Women is otherwise almost exclusively telepathic.12 In addition, having learned to channel their mental energies, they have developed the capacity to fly (windriding), lift enormous weights (toting), swim for long distances underwater, engage in psychic healing, and participate in energy exchanges with trees. As well as being able to communicate with cats, dogs, birds, snakes, horses, and fish, they enjoy empathic communion not only with the Earth and the Moon, but even with such unlikely objects as holes in the ground and cakes of dried tuna. Indeed, in one scene, a pair of lovers even use their combined psychic powers for the rather prosaic purpose of making tea: The early morning ritual of beginning together proceeded that day along familiar lines: in mutual mind effort from across the room they enfolded the tea water, requesting it to boil, aiding it, with its consent, in doing so. [p.20] More commonly, however, their powers are employed for less mundane ends: as well as maintaining a constant telepathic watch along the border that separates the Wanderground from the Dangerlandbeyond which lies the male-dominated Citythe Hill Women also maintain a presence in the City itself. Disguised as men, and assisted by the gentles, a network of strong, psychically powerful women use their powers to prevent the male energy of the City extending beyond its confines. The necessity for this is confirmed by the consequences reported when the rotation of the Hill Women in the City is temporarily disrupted: Several years ago when three hill women were caught and killed in the City whole parties of celebrating men and their women poured into the countryside. They revved up deserted farm machinery and hauled truckloads of copulating couples around a field all night long.

194

NARRATING UTOPIA

Things stopped rather suddenly, a cessation that corresponded precisely to the arrival in the City of the hill womens replacements Last year when some crisis called four women home without warning, some would-be hunters holding rifles that had not fired for generations found that live ammunition worked. There were several rapes at that time, toocountry men of their wives or of women living alone who thought they were safe. When the hill women returned or were replaced the effect took hold again. No shots. No rapes. [p.175] Except for the gentles, who are accorded a distinctly wary and qualified respect, men are presented exclusively as would-be rapists, wholly responsible for the ills that have befallen the planet. In contrast to the flat rage that often surfaces, expressing itself in visions of manslaying, of manmangling (p.128), Gilmans satire seems positively genial.13 Like Gilmans, however, Gearharts is a utopia of which the fundamental premise is basically a reversal of the traditional utopian pattern: patriarchal authority is once again replaced by an exclusively female system of social organization. Yet while Gearhart makes this the starting point for a far more radical imagining of the resultant possibilities, a curiously familiar picture begins to appear when one examines the work in detail. Again, as in Herland, what emerges is less a departure from the utopian norm, than its mirror inversionin which many of the same contradictions are apparent. For all its narrative innovation, in fact, The Wanderground shares a surprising number of the characteristic features of the traditional utopia. While the existence of the Hill Women is anything but the comfortable, problem-free idyll depicted in Looking Backward or News from Nowhere, their almost obsessive (though understandable) defensive precautions have much in common with those of Mores Utopians or Campanellas Solarians. As in Utopia and The City of the Sun, the more perfect society is only made possible by the exclusion of the outside world. Likewise, although Gearharts emphasis on the virtue of privacy (violation of anothers privacy is referred to as mans crime) may seem something of an anomaly in a utopian context, the pervasiveness of telepathic communication among the Hill Women creates an atmosphere as oppressively public as anything to be found in the work of More or Wells. As in A Modern Utopia and Men Like Gods, everyones location is known, and while the intent of the following passage is presumably to suggest the power of womens solidarity, its portrayal of the submersion of individual identity in that of the group conjures up echoes of the dystopian visions of Zamyatin and Huxley: Hot bodies surrounded her: Judas head to her left at waist level, Tolatilitas to her right; Yva and Rhoda prone on each of her legs;

A WORLD OF ONES OWN

195

Lyssa and Phtha hovering over her own head. They wiped her face, her body, with sharp-smelling leaves. The incantations swirled around and over her, words circling her head, her body, words sliding over her skin, drooping around her ribs and over her brow, under her fingernails and through the curling forest of the mountain slopes and planes; words leapt and pounded in the sockets of her spine; words bent and broke in the crevice of her brain. A thousand hands now moved on her flesh, a thousand eyes now peered at the window of her soul, a thousand lips caressed at the door of her deepest self. [p.51] Elsewhere, following the Gatherstretcha telepathic conference involving most of the Hill Womenone of the children awakens and comes downstairs to find the exhausted adults lying in a tangle which she describes as like a kitten pile (p.132), and this is merely one of many scenes in which security is provided by physical contact. Womb imagery abounds, here overt and explicit, rather than oblique and indirect, as is so often the case in male-authored utopias: indeed, the image of organic, nurturing enclosure is central to the work itself, reflected in the Hill Womens nestlike dwellings; in the subterranean passages of the Remember Rooms, where they recall the past; in the tunnels of the Deep Cella, where the rite of impregnation is enacted; and even in their characteristic mode of telepathic communication, often referred to as enfoldment. Nor is the geography of The Wanderground, for all its inversion of the traditional utopian pattern, any less suggestive. Whereas the majority of utopias are located in the mythical southland of male fantasy, the territory of the Hill Women is in the north, above the regions inhabited by men. (Herland, likewise, is portrayed as rising above the surrounding region.) The Hill Women themselves live mainly in the twin ensconcements, the breast-like curves of whose borders overlook the Dangerlanda disputed area over which neither women nor men have established hegemony beyond which lies the City, the enclave where male sexuality still functions. In the map which prefaces the text, the implications are still harder to ignore: within a geographical configuration that strikingly resembles a womans body, the male-dominated City occupies the space where the genitalia would be. What Gearharts utopia unquestioningly accepts, in other words, is the traditional utopian identification of the land as female the difference being that it is no longer territory available to be colonized by the male, but rather a domain to be reclaimed by the formerly colonized female.14 In effect, The Wanderground embodies a fantasy of returning to a state of being that formerly existed, before the damage was done. As Bammer argues: the unpredictable and contradictory dynamics of change are finally

196

NARRATING UTOPIA

collapsed into an almost mystical vision of harmony defined as the restoration of natural order. Gearharts utopian vision is in the end based not on an estranged view of history, but on the attempt to transcend it. [p.89] While the kind of past that Gearhart seeks to recover may differ radically from that imagined in the traditional, male-authored utopia, the regressive character of the underlying fantasy is no less apparent. The principle of reversal extends still further, however: where the traditional utopia seeks to re-establish the security of the womb by the imposition of a distinctively masculine order, The Wanderground depicts a world in which many aspects of that order are recreatedonly by means which Gearhart represents as essentially female. While the Hill Women are, for example, adamantly opposed to any form of technology (which they see as merely a tool of male domination), it is clear that their refusal of technology goes hand-in-hand with a conscious decision to pursue many of its goals by other means. And here again contradictions begin to emerge. On the one hand, we are told that women could have built whats been called western civilization; we knew how to do all of it but rejected most such ideas as unnecessary or destructive (p.145). Yet at the same time it becomes apparent that, by pursuing the development of their own psychic powers, the Hill Women have in fact become capable of achieving everything that technology once made possible: We can do anything that the old machines could do. And with a good deal less effort (p.145). With their rituals, incantations, telepathy, intuition, and psychic strength, the Hill Women have effectively realized virtually the entire technological programme first adumbrated in Bacons The New Atlantis: flight, underwater exploration, long-range communicationsnot to mention the ability to create life without resorting to conventional methods of reproduction all are there. Bacons longstanding dream of regaining the dominion over creation lost by the Fall has all but come true: although the Hill Women would no doubt reject the terms in which it is expressed as overly suggestive of the male desire for mastery over nature, the Wanderground is nevertheless a world where nature does their bidding. Indeed, as Bammer points out, the science-fictional neologisms that Gearhart coins to describe the Hill Womens powers evoke an image of power more congruent with the high-tech potential of an age of radars, lasers, and micro-computers than with the forces of nature [they are] meant to signify (pp.912); although she attempts to go outside existing language to find terminology to describe the Hill Womens utopian reality, the result ultimately subverts the binary opposition she seeks to establish between woman/nature on the one hand and man/power on the other.15 While the Hill Women are,

A WORLD OF ONES OWN

197

of course, justifiably proud of their refusal to reproduce many of the negative features of technology, such as bombs, nerve gas, and so forth this satisfaction begins to seem more than a little complacent when it becomes apparent that what they have developed is a potentially genocidal superweapon of their own. In the Gatherstretch, it would appear, the combined psychic energies of hundreds of Hill Women generate a channeled power which could prove literally lethaland it is a power which a sizeable faction seem eager to use for destructive ends: Let us wipe the City out now. One directed gatherstretch (p.129) The implications are, to put it mildly, alarmingnot least in that the enemy is genetically determined. Men, it is claimed, are no longer of the same species (p.115), while the Hill Women, for their part, disclaim all responsibility for the evils that have befallen the Earth. In their incantations in the concluding section, all blame is laid squarely at the door of Man: The Crown of Creation. He is the slayer. His is the litany. We are the slain [p.193] His crimes are enumerated, womens freedom from complicity in them is celebrated, and after the briefest possible expression of remorse for such part as women might have played in aiding Mans enormities, the ceremony moves on to imagine the final death of Man through his own destructive impulses, leading to the affirmation: With water and blood we can wash away the slayer. / With water and blood we can wash away the race. It is in many respects a characteristic utopian fantasyone of being able to remain as one is (in this case, true to an ahistorically conceived essential femininity), but without guilt.16 There are some qualifications, certainly: that women have occasionally collaborated with the male oppressor is reluctantly conceded, while elsewhere it is even acknowledged that It is too simple to condemn them all or to praise all of us (p.2). Yet this concession is promptly undermined by the qualification that immediately follows it: But for the sake of earth and all she holds, that simplicity must be our creed (p.2). There may be menthe gentles, for instancewho are not all bad, but for the sake of a higher cause the simplifying fiction must be upheld, even in the face of evidence to the contrary. It is a logic with which Goebbels would certainly have been familiar. An unfair comparison? Perhapsalthough it is hardly one that The Wanderground does a great deal to discourage. As Bammer points out, the uncomplicated ascription of woman to the realm of nature was also a central feature of Nazi ideologyas was the appeal to a glorified mythic past (although not, as in Gearharts case, a matriarchal one) whose recovery

198

NARRATING UTOPIA

becomes a central goal. If Mores and Campanellas visions of a rational social order have been seen (whether justifiably or not) as prefiguring the communist dream of an end to human exploitation, Gearharts emphasis on the mystic properties of the blood, the unlimited powers of the human will, the appeal of group ritual, and above all the simplistic attribution of all ills to a genetically determined Other, suggests a rather different parallel. Part of the appeal of fascism, as Bloch has argued, lies in its awareness of the utopian allure of the simple solution. To blame economic crisis on the Jews, or mass unemployment on foreign immigrants is simpler than seeking the source of such problems in the complexities of modern capitalism; at the same time, by identifying the Other as responsible for whatever has gone wrong, fascist ideology absolves of guilt all those to whom it appeals. And, so long as problems persist, it takes only a small step to identify the simple, not to mention the final solutionthe elimination of those who are to blame: Jews, immigrants, or, in Gearharts case, mentaking care first, of course, to deny their essential humanity. Once the other has been identified as an inferior race, or no longer of the same species (p.115) there is likely to be only one outcome: to return once more to Wellss declaration in A Modern Utopia[t]here is only one sane and logical thing to be done with a really inferior race, and that is to exterminate it (p.337). What lies beyond the final solution is, of course, utopia: a world where the natural order has been restored, and where guilt and evil have been banished along with those who were their source. Even as it seeks to challenge and subvert the norms of the traditional male utopia, The Wanderground shows all too clearly how the utopian impulse to pursue premises to their logical conclusion often serves to unmask their more alarming implications. At the same time, it is clear that much of the dynamism of Gearharts narrativethe sense it communicates (highly unusual in utopian fiction) of people having experiences that actually matteris dependent on the very fact of the existence of the hated Other. The violent and disturbing struggle between the two lovers, Seja and Alaka, stems from Sejas uncontrollable rage over another womans rape; the anxiety, tension, anger that surfaces during the Gatherstretch are occasioned by the proposal that the Hill Women meet with men officially (only gentle, but men none the less); even the Hill Womens highly un-utopian preoccupation with the past is rooted in their need to maintain awareness of the dangers they have escaped. However much they may deny their connection with the men of the City, it is against the men that they define themselves; from the Other that they derive part of their own identity.17 In this it is hard not to see both a reflection of the political realities of Gearharts own society, and at the same time yet another example of the curious utopian tendency

A WORLD OF ONES OWN

199

to displace those realities into the realm of sexual politics. In Looking Backward, as we have seen, Bellamy replaces the economic incentives of the late nineteenth century free market by sexual ones, while not even Morris, who envisages a far more radical transcendence of the realities of contemporary society, can imagine the total disappearance of the desire for possession, which translates itself into the violent sexual jealousy which constitutes the lone disruptive element in his idyllic future. Likewise, in the polarized oppositions of The Wanderground, what we encounter is surely a reinscription of the simplistic dualism of the Cold War: In God We Trust versus The Evil Empire; us versus them; women versus men. Gearharts is yet another utopia which reproduces, albeit on a different plane, the limitations of the reality which it seeks to transcend. Gender and Utopian Narrative (part two) While both The Wanderground and Herland offer a direct challenge to the patriarchal assumptions of the traditional utopia, what becomes clear is the extent to which even this leaves some familiar problems unresolved. Although Gearhart and Gilman avoid some of the narrative pitfalls inherent in the traditional paradigm, their strategy of simply reversing the terms of the conventional utopia resultsas is so often the case in dystopian narrativein the reproduction, rather than resolution of many of its most problematic features. What is perhaps most striking, however, is the degree to which both writers share the traditional utopian tendency to accept as natural a conception of essential femininity that itself derives from the gender relations of their own society. Clearly, neither Gilman nor Gearhart share Campanellas assumption of womens weakness, which undermines the apparently enlightened vision of gender equality which his utopia proposes, or Bellamys conviction that womens true role is to provide the incentive for male industrial productivity. Nevertheless, their ahistorical ascription to women of precisely those qualities traditionally associated with them by patriarchal society creates problems which are by no means resolved simply by presenting such qualities in a more positive light. Gilmans utopians may well be stronger and more athletic than their counterparts in the real world, but they continue to manifest the virtues of purity, goodness, and maternal kindness to children which constitute the ideal of femininity in the patriarchal society of her own era; and while the Hill Women are still more spectacularly accomplished, they are again represented as loving, nurturing, spiritually aware, and closely associated with Nature. What this fails to conceal, however, is the extent to which these essential qualities are in fact relational. Although Gilmans fantasy of a

200

NARRATING UTOPIA

natural femininity grown strong enough to withstand male oppression differs in emphasis from Gearharts vision of out-and-out separatism, each depends on the existence of an Other to which such essentialized femininity can be opposed. Both, in effect, are fantasies of redemption: the one a liberal feminist vision of bringing peace and harmony to existing society through the influence of values which are themselves a product of that society; the other a radical feminist dream of rescuing the Earth from the demonized Other, and being rewarded by the restoration of an untroubled symbiotic union with Nature. Nevertheless, as Thrmer-Rohr argues: We cannot simply say: Patriarchy has turned out to be a form of society whose predominant members, men, saw as valuable something that turned out not to be valuable. Therefore we women are finally taking our different morality out of the closet, setting the priorities ourselves, replacing and occupying the empty spaces. I see this fine challenge as an ahistorical illusion. We are not bounding into unoccupied territory; such territory doesnt exist. Besides, we have nothing in our possession, or not enough, with which to occupy this no place in our own waya completely different, brand-new way. [p.104] Although the gender basis of Gilmans and Gearharts utopias serves to heighten the sense of their difference from existing society, they are in many ways as hampered by the baggage of the past as their male-authored counterparts. Once again, the connection between utopia and real world may be obscured, but it cannot be altogether concealed. In another sense, however, the separation between reality and utopia becomes more pronounced. While it may be argued that the narrative premises of Herland and The Wanderground are not in themselves any more fantastic than the positing of hundred-year sleeps, parallel universes, or life on Mars by earlier authors, there is a crucial difference in terms of what Levitas terms the perceived possibility (Concept of Utopia, p.194) of the utopian society envisaged. While none of the utopias so far discussed are concerned with the actual prediction of the nature of a future society, there can be little doubt that works such as Looking Backward, A Modern Utopia, or Red Star are based on the assumption that a society something like that imagined by the writer would be both possible and desirable. With Herland and The Wanderground, however, this is clearly not the case. For all her emphasis on womens strength, and on the inequities of existing society, there is never a sense that Gilman is actually advocating separatism as a solutionas is clear from the rather unsatisfactory conclusion; and while Gearhart might well see her imaginary society as desirable, it is clearly not her intent to represent features such as human flight, parthenogenesis, or

A WORLD OF ONES OWN

201

telepathic tea-making as possible in the same sense as, say, Bogdanovs representation of Martian child care arrangements. There are, of course, certain benefits in such an approach, particularly in narrative terms. As Levitas remarks, [w]here utopia is not expected to be realised, one is constrained only by what it is possible to imagine, not by what it is possible to imagine as possible (Concept of Utopia, p.193): one side-effect of the greater imaginative freedom made possible by the abandonment of the criterion of perceived possibility is that both Herland and The Wanderground exhibit a narrative dynamism far removed from that of the traditional ponderous utopian guided tour. At the same time, however, there is a cost involved. While, as we have seen, the traditional utopia is often evasive about the process whereby a more desirable society might be created, the retreat from the notion of utopia as at least possible results in a still further diminished sense of agency. In the case of The Wanderground in particular, the reliance on quasi-divine interventionthe Revolt of the Motheras the premise for the establishment of a utopian society has a decidedly millennialist flavour, somewhat reminiscent of the native American Ghost Dancers belief in the great wave of earth that would cross the continent, obliterating the white man as it passed. Yet, as Levitas goes on to argue, millennial fantasies of divine intervention are most frequent among groups which perceive themselves, often correctly, as unable to exert control over the course of history (p.194). While they may provide the incentive to acts of opposition (usually doomed), they may equally reflect a fatalism which she suggests is the key issue (p.195) when it comes to the writing of utopias: Where it is no longer assumed that social organisation is inherently controllable by human agents, or where it is no longer believed that the agents who are in control can themselves be made accountable to the rest of us, much of the motive for the construction of utopias as goals is lost. They cease to be images of a hoped-for future and become again expressions of desire. The role of fantasy increases and utopia is less and less intended as a literal goal, and less bound by constraints of literal plausibility. [pp.1956] In the case of The Wanderground in particular, for all its undeniable narrative benefits, this removal of hope to the realm of fantasy and myth, as Bammer puts it, leads inevitably to a utopia which presents a separation from reality rather than a process of intervention (p.89). Whether this represents a step forward is a question that will be addressed in the final chapter.

7: Dreams of Freedom: Piercy, Le Guin, and the Future of Utopia


What begins to emerge in both the libertarian visions of Morris, Bogdanov, and Huxley, and the separatist utopias of Gilman and Gearhart, is an increasing sense that the relationship between utopia and reality is one in which conflict is inherent. In News from Nowhere, as we have seen, the transition to utopia is marked by violence and bloodshed, while the memory of the squalor and brutality of the narrators own time repeatedly threatens the precarious fabric of the utopian dream, ultimately overwhelming it altogether. Red Star not only begins and ends in the midst of revolutionary struggle, but also includes serious consideration by the utopians of a possible war of extermination against the human race followed by the murder of its chief proponent by the visitor from Earth; while in Island, utopia is quite literally overwhelmed by a hostile outside world. In Herland, likewise, it is clear that the utopians wariness of their visitors from outside is amply justified: in the light of their initial attempt to capture one of the local inhabitants, not to mention Terrys subsequent attempted rape, or his threat to organize an expedition to force an entrance into Ma-land (p.146), the decision to imprison them until tamed and trained to a degree they considered safe (p.72) seems eminently reasonable. The visitors from our reality have, so to speak, to be utopianized before being allowed their freedom. And in The Wanderground, of course, relations between the utopian Hill Women and what remains of modern civilization are marked by outright hostility. It may be objected, however, that such antagonism is already implicit in the Renaissance utopia. The ruthless defence policy of Mores Utopians, the massive fortifications of the City of the Sun, and the precautions which Bacons Bensalemites observe to prevent the discovery of their land hardly suggest that congenial relations with the rest of the world are seen as likely. Nevertheless, there is a difference: in each case, utopias strength is sufficient to render it secure: such is the military might of the Utopians and Solarians, not to mention the technological superiority of the Bensalemites, that there is never the slightest suggestion that the outside world represents a threat to their stability. Conversely, their remoteness renders them models which may safely be admiredat a comfortable distance. Even where More explicitly contrasts the virtues of Utopia to the shortcomings of his own society, there is little sense that the more perfect

DREAMS OF FREEDOM

203

order imposes anything so threatening as an imperative to change. As the narrator himself remarks in conclusion: I confess there are many things in the Commonwealth of Utopia which I wish our own country would imitatethough I dont really expect it will (p.91). In the utopias of Bellamy and Wells, of course, even the implication that utopia and reality are inimical all but vanishes. In Looking Backward, as we have seen, utopia supersedes the old order without so much as a hint of opposition; while In the Days of the Comet depicts humanity emerging from its slumber unanimously committed to the construction of a better world. More speculative in tone, A Modern Utopia allows that some of the details of the more perfect society may be open to debate, but the desirability of a utopia along the general lines suggested remains a given. Only in Men Like Gods is there active opposition to the utopian ideal, in the shape of Rupert Catskill and his companions, but even this intrusion from the past represents little real challenge: once they become too troublesome, they are swept aside like so many irritating insects. The utopian truths are selfevident to all but a benighted few, who will soon be left behind by the inevitable course of history. Utopia, worldwide and unchallenged, is in each case represented as a form of manifest destiny. Morris is thus perhaps the first writer seriously to challenge the comforting fiction that the transition to utopia would be painless, injurious to no ones vested interestsand it is no coincidence that his is among the first utopias to stress the precariousness of the utopian vision, not to mention the fact that even the capacity to dream requires some degree of liberation from the bare necessities of life. Yet even while Morris acknowledges the necessity of struggle, and the sheer difficulty of creating a better world, his actual representation of conflict remains marginal to the utopia he depicts. Although the chapter entitled How the Change Came is the longest in the book, the account it offers remains self-contained, isolated from the main body of the text. For most of the utopians, such conflict is a thing of the past: the struggles whereby the world was brought to its second birth (p.112) are hardly more than a dream. It is not until much later that we encounter utopian fictions in which the conflict between utopia and reality which Morris recognizes becomes more centralintegral to the depiction of an alternative social order in which utopia is neither a static alternative, remote from reality, nor the inevitable destination of a linear historical process, but rather a disputed territory, to be fought for in the here and now. It is this focus on change and conflict that Moylan identifies as central to what he terms the critical utopiawhich he sees as distinguished by an awareness of the limitations of the utopian tradition [rejecting] utopia as blueprint while preserving it as dream (Demand the Impossible,

204

NARRATING UTOPIA

p.10), by its concern with the conflict between the originary world and the utopian society opposed to it so that the process of social change is more directly articulated (p.10), and by a focus on the continuing presence of difference and imperfection within utopian society itself (pp.1011). In addition, the apparently unified, illusionary, and representational text of the more traditional utopia (p.46) is replaced by a more fragmented and self-reflexive narrative, in which the single, authoritative vision of the traditional paradigm is never allowed to establish itself. As examples, Moylan cites works by Russ, Le Guin, Piercy, and Delanyand given that he sees these as in large measure resolving the problems, both narrative and ideological, inherent in earlier utopian writing, it is to a consideration of these that we will now turn. In two of Moylans examples, in fact, Russs The Female Man and Delanys Triton, utopia is stripped altogether of its privileged position as the central focus of the text, coexisting instead with other, non-utopian (or even frankly dystopian) portrayals of societythe effect being to create a multiplicity of perspectives, in which the utopian is seen as only one of a variety of possibilities. In The Female Man, for example, the action shifts back and forth between four different settings, only one of which is utopian, and in the process we are offered fragmentary glimpses, rather than a comprehensive vision of the utopian world of Whileawayan all-female society in which extremely advanced technology and minimal government combine to maximize individual freedom. In Triton, the hapless protagonist moves through a range of worlds, some desirable, some quite the reverse, at home in none of themthe crowning irony being his inability to take advantage of utopian possibilities even when they present themselves. Yet while both fictions go some way to resolving many of the problems which have been identified as characteristic of traditional utopian narrative, they do so at a certain cost. In each, the notion of utopia as perceived possibility, whose coexistence with the opposing notion of utopia as an unattainable ideal creates such a fertile and life-giving tension in so many earlier fictions, again gives wayas in Herland and The Wandergroundto what is more in the nature of a thought-experiment, where utopia becomes primarily a device for defamiliarizing and calling into question the assumptions which we bring to reality. It is significant that in both The Female Man and Triton the utopian society itself remains a given, made possible largely by means of the sort of technological fix so beloved of earlier writers. In Russs Whileaway the problem of labour has been all but eliminated by means of the induction helmet, which allows for direct mental control of machinery; while on Triton, one of the moons of Neptune, Delany depicts a society where a whole battery of standard science fictional devices gravity shields, cybernetic technology, advanced surgical and

DREAMS OF FREEDOM

205

psychotherapeutic techniquesmake possible not only universal abundance, but also overnight changes in both gender and sexual orientation. What each offers, in effect, is another form of simplification by exclusion: the solution of certain problems is taken as read, thereby making it possible to focus more exclusively on others. For both Russ and Delany, the elimination of basic economic problems by technology allows them to focus primarily on questions of sexual politics (a displacement which, as we have seen, is by no means atypical of traditional utopian narrative) in which they are clearly far more interested. Yet while both Russ and Delany succeed in avoiding some of the most characteristic weaknesses of the traditional utopiaits ponderous didacticism, its imposition on the reader of a specific (and often authoritarian) vision, its unquestioning reproduction of existing patterns of gender relationsthey abandon in the process much of what renders utopian fiction utopian. Russ offers only a fragmentary vision of the more perfect society, while Delanys Triton, as we have seen, refuses the title of utopia altogether. And while this may be no bad thing (indeed, commentators such as Bammer argue that it is only in such fragmentary glimpses or partial visions that genuinely utopian alternatives can be advanced), the question remains whether or not it is possible to create a fiction in which the outline of an at least plausible social ideal continues to be central, yet which at the same time resolves some of the perennial narrative and ideological problems inherent in the genre. In this regard perhaps the most interesting experiments are provided by two of Moylans other examples, Piercys Woman on the Edge of Time and Le Guins The Dispossessed, and also by Le Guins later Always Coming Home, all of which offer detailed visions of utopian society, only no longer in isolation, linked to reality only by the presence of the visitor. In both Woman on the Edge of Time and The Dispossessed, utopias troubled, precarious, yet at the same time life-giving relationship with reality emerges from a pattern of alternating episodes, in which events in utopia are counterpointed to those in the real world. And while Always Coming Home represents a utopia far removed in time from the world of our own day, the sense of the relationship between the two remains strong: if utopia is haunted by the nightmare of our reality, equally our reality is permeated by a saving awareness of the utopian dream. Like Russ and Delany, both Piercy and Le Guin use the conventions of science fiction to provide the vehicle for their utopian extrapolations: the more perfect societies of Woman on the Edge of Time and Always Coming Home are displaced into the far future, while that depicted in The Dispossessed is remote in space, located on one of a pair of planets in the system of Tau Ceti. Yet for all that, futuristic technology is far less central to the actual

206

NARRATING UTOPIA

workings of the societies presented than is the case in either Triton or The Female Man. Indeed, in both Woman on the Edge of Time and Always Coming Home (the latter representing an almost exclusively agrarian society) the utopias depicted seem hardly less Arcadian in some of their aspects than the future imagined in News from Nowhere. In Woman on the Edge of Time, for example, although there is no lack of advanced technology, its uses are relatively unobtrusiveto the extent that when Connie Ramos, the twentieth-century visitor to the future, arrives in the year 2137, she is at first struck by how primitive everything seems, and even wonders whether she has not travelled back in time instead. The inhabitants of Piercys utopia wear small portable computers which are used both for purposes of communication and as actual extensions of human memory; sophisticated weaponry is deployed in the ongoing struggle with the last vestiges of the old military-industrial complex; and, most notoriously, there is the brooderwhere human embryos are now grown, thus liberating women from the disabling effects of pregnancy and reproduction. Yet none of this alters the fact that Piercys is a largely agrarian utopia, consisting of a network of largely selfsupporting village communities. There is an elaborate system of trade and communication between them, as well as provision for a decision-making process to deal with broader issues concerning more than one community, but as one of the utopians tells Connie, they are all peasants (p.70). Everyone, no matter how technically skilled, is obliged to engage in manual labour, since machines are for the most part used only when there is a clearly demonstrated needas in the case of dangerous, or boring and repetitive work. We learn that mining is performed entirely by machines, and we are given a brief glimpse of a fully automated pillow factory, but in general, as in News from Nowhere, the narrative emphasis is less on innovation than on restoration, on the need to repair the damage done to the environment by urban industrialism. Connies puzzled comment, Forward, into the past? (p.70) captures perfectly the ambiguous temporal direction which Piercys utopia shares with that of Morris. Indeed, if one were to take Piercys representation of utopian society by itself, it might well seem, for all the distinctiveness of many of its details, conventional enough in general outline. While the peace and harmony of Piercys utopia do not depend on the regimented order envisaged by More or Campanella, its inhabitants share with the Utopians and Solarians an uncompromising commitment to their societys defence: virtually everyone takes turns at military service, and indeed in the course of the narrative one of the main characters, Jackrabbit, is killed in combat. There are the familiar utopian benefits of abundance (although a cautionary note is sounded regarding the need to ration such comparatively wasteful

DREAMS OF FREEDOM

207

luxuries as coffee and tea), health, and (marginally) longer life. As in so many earlier utopias, possessiveness has vanished along with private property, and once again sexuality has been rendered guilt-free. Most of the sources of injustice, oppression, pain and suffering have been eliminatedwith predictable consequences in terms of human behaviour. Less cynical and repressed, more openly and freely expressive of their feelings than their twentieth-century counterparts, Piercys utopians seem both more innocent and more childlike as a result. Indeed, it is precisely this quality that strikes Connie most powerfully on her first visit: Like a child! She could not imagine any woman of the age they must share saying in El Barrio or any place else she had lived, Me myself, I drum magnificently! Indeed, they were like children, all in unisex rompers, sitting at their long kindergarten tables eating big plates full of food and making jokes. [p.75] Piercy is clearly aware of the problems this can cause: to Connie, the utopians seem in consequence simply that much less real. Contrasting her dead lover, Claud, with the utopian, Bee (who strongly resembles him), she reflects: Pain had honed Claud keen. This man was a child by comparison (p.104). It is Clauds sufferingin large measure due to his being a black man in a racist class societythat gives him much of his identity: to imagine him in a world from which racism and class oppression have been eliminated is more than she can manage. As her sarcastic response suggests You saying theres no racism left? Paradise on earth, all Gods children are equal? (p.104)utopia seems to her quite literally too good to be true. This is, of course, a familiar problem in utopian narrativesbut Piercys attempted solution goes beyond the mere acknowledgement that it exists. To begin with, like Morris, Piercy seeks to avoid mere idealized abstraction in her evocation of the utopian future. Even more so than in News from Nowhere, there are unusually concrete descriptions of the look and feel of things: of what people eat and what they wear, of their utensils and furnishings, their music and their visual art. And while, like Morris, she emphasizes the pleasure that work can involve (rather than merely reducing the hours), she not only shows it in process, but makes it clear that even under the most utopian conditions it is far from an unmixed blessing; in particular, Piercy does not shirk representing the often exhausting rounds of meetings and negotiations involved in communal and inter-communal decision making. Moreover, in the search for utopian solutions, Piercy tries so far as possible to avoid the utopian tendency toward oversimplification. In the area of sexuality, for example, there are neither the restrictive exclusions

208

NARRATING UTOPIA

of Campanella, who outlaws sodomy, nor Gearhart, who represents heterosexuality as solely a form of male oppression, nor the somewhat nave faith of Morris (and to a lesser extent Huxley) that the simple removal of legal and social constraints will take care of things. Nor, for that matter, does Piercy fall into the familiar trap of merely reproducing (as natural) her own societys patterns of gender relations: in Woman on the Edge of Time homosexuality, heterosexuality, bisexuality, celibacy, promiscuity, and even juvenile sexual experimentation are all represented as perfectly acceptableyet at the same time there is no pretence that the absence of a single restrictive norm does more than alleviate the problems inherent in human relationships. While her utopians are no longer troubled by sexual guilt, the problems of jealousy, pain, loss remainon occasions becoming so disruptive that action at the communal level is required in order to deal with them. While possessiveness and dependence are countered by strong communal ties, by the separation of sexuality and parenthood (there is no longer a biological relation between parents and children), and by the provision of specific social mechanisms to deal with jealousy, or the grief caused by loss and separation, there is no suggestion that all problems are thereby resolved. As the rivalry between two of Jackrabbits lovers, Luciente and Bolivar, shows, the confrontation of jealousy and personal antagonism remains a painful process; while the reactions to Jackrabbits subsequent death on military service reveal that even the provision of rituals allowing for the expression of grief and coming to terms with loss can only mitigate, not remove the pain involved. What Piercy emphasizes, in effect, is the process of problem-solving. Hers is not a utopia in which all the major problems have already been dealt with. Instead, to an even greater extent than Bogdanov, she represents a world where decisions are still in the process of being taken. A war is still being fought, both in time and space; there are constant negotiations to resolve disputes between communities; and there is also what is referred to as the shaping controversya worldwide debate over the ethical issues involved in using genetic manipulation to increase human ability. More than most utopias, Piercys is one where change still appears to be taking place, and as a result, for all the childlike characteristics which the utopians exhibit, the element of regressive fantasy is far less apparent. There is freedom, but not freedom from responsibility; security, but only as a result of unceasing struggle. Where Woman on the Edge of Time departs most strikingly from the traditional utopian narrative paradigm, however, is not so much in the way the society is portrayed (Connie is, after all, given the standard guided tour) as in the surrounding narrative context. Were it merely a narrative of Connies visit to utopia, Piercys blend of socialist feminism, ecological

DREAMS OF FREEDOM

209

consciousness, and do-it-yourself psychotherapy might seem little more than a 1970s update of the traditional model, in much the same way that Island, with its free love, eastern mysticism, and sacramental use of psychedelic drugs, might be seen as reflecting the spirit of the preceding decade, or Wellss utopias that of the early years of the century. What makes Piercys utopia radically different in its effect is its juxtaposition of the traditional visit to utopia with a narrative which serves to highlight the troubled relationship between utopia and reality. The narrative begins, in fact, not with the arrival of the visitor in utopia, but rather with the intrusion of utopia into the all-too-squalid reality of modern-day New York. At the outset, Connie is troubled by disturbing glimpses of a stranger, who claims to come from the futureglimpses which cause her, not unreasonably, to doubt her own sanity. In fact, shortly after her first extended conversation with the stranger she finds herself incarcerated in a mental hospitalalthough not because she is thought to be suffering from utopian delusions. Instead, her committal is the result of her breaking the nose of her nieces pimp with a wine jug, after he has beaten up the niece for refusing to have an abortion. In the non-utopian world of twentieth-century America, the pimps false testimony, together with a past history of mental problems, proves more than enough to get her locked up. In the hospital she is again visited by the stranger, who proves able to transport her telepathically to a utopian future, and there then ensues a sequence of alternating episodes, juxtaposing scenes in utopia with the contemporary reality of the mental hospital. The effect of this narrative strategy is to foreground both the connection between utopia and reality, and the essential conflict between them. To begin with, Piercys vivid representation of the glaring abuses present in her own society makes the need for alternatives seem that much more pressing, and in consequence her utopian imaginings appear less arbitrary than is often the case. Set against the description of Connies suffering as a child, a lover, a parent in a world which makes a decent life for the poor and disadvantaged a virtual impossibility, even the more extreme of Piercys utopian inventionsthe severing of the biological links between parent and child, the provision of three, rather than two parents for each childseem a good deal more persuasive than they might if taken in isolation. And while Piercys attempt to imagine language appropriate to a genuinely utopian future (with per as a non-sexist replacement for the possessives his and her, and a studied avoidance of expletives rooted in sexual taboos) often seems awkward, too obviously invented and unnatural,1 that very awkwardnessthe fact that it is hard not to notice makes all the more effective the contrast with such natural verbal formulations as the pimp Geraldos greeting to Connie: Caca de puta. Old

210

NARRATING UTOPIA

Bitch. Get your fat and worthless ass out of my way (p.13)or indeed his still more charmless Hey, cunt, stop blubbering to a woman he has just beaten up. Juxtaposed, the representations of the real and the utopia encourage a reexamination of the assumptions which the reader brings to each: utopian artifice becomes a device for exposing the limitations of the real. This is not to say that Piercys narrative approach is altogether new. Mores Utopia, after all, owes much of its force to its juxtaposition of Hythlodays indictment of the injustices and abuses current in contemporary England with his subsequent account of Utopian society, and the somewhat schematized counterpointing of utopian perfection to the squalor of reality is, as we have seen, a recurrent feature in many of its successors. Yet in no case is there the degree of interaction, the dialectic between the real and the utopian which Piercy succeeds in establishing. Utopia is presented not merely as a more desirable alternative to reality, but as a possibility which implies the necessity for reality to change. Like other utopias, Woman on the Edge of Time is of course a product of the society to which it proposes an alternative, but it is also shown to be the embodiment of an ideal which changes as the nature of that society changes. While the utopian future is the product of past decisions, past struggles, it is not therefore fixed and static. Instead, it is actively engaged not only in a continuing military struggle with what remains of the old order, but also in taking decisions that affect both the future and the past. The telepathic experiment which brings Connie to the utopian future is part of a battle to ensure that contemporary reality does give birth to a better future; the utopian is not the only possible future, for as Piercy also shows, there are other, much less desirable futures also struggling to be born. For the utopia she depicts to come into being, reality has to change in ways which powerful interest groups in society will fight to the death to prevent; for such groups to gain their ends in the here and now will be finally to eliminate utopia as a real possibility. In Woman on the Edge of Time the space opened up by utopian imagining is not an empty oneit is disputed territory, over which the battle is already being fought. Thus, while a number of features of Piercys utopia might be seen as conventional in themselves, the context in which they appear radically changes their impact. What is stressed is not peace and securitythe simplified bliss of a utopia to which one might dream of escapingbut rather the lessons to be learned from a utopia which is more than merely a dream or an abstraction. Connie, the visitor to utopia, is described by the utopians as a catcher: someone unusually open to telepathic suggestion from the utopian futurebut what is also clear is that she is more than usually alive to the utopian potential even of her own deprived existence.

DREAMS OF FREEDOM

211

In the ultimate deprivation of the mental hospital, she sees her everyday life as in a sense utopian, as representing something more: No more Thorazine and sleeping pills, the brief high and the endless sluggish depths. Nights of sleep with real dreams. She would go hungry for a week for the pleasure of eating a real orange, an avocado. All day long nobody would tell her what to do. Miraculously she would walk through the streets without an attendant. She would breathe the beautiful living filthy air Her life that had felt so threadbare now spread out like a full velvet rosethe rose that Claud had once brought her, loving it for its silkiness, its fragrance, and not knowing it was dark red. Her ordinary penny-pinching life appeared to her full beyond the possibility of savouring every moment. [p.28] Mattapoisett in the year 2137, however, goes as far beyond the possibilities of her everyday life as that life goes beyond the possibilities of her existence in the mental hospitalto the extent that, once she has overcome her initial scepticism, it almost seems as though it were the fulfilment of a dream. In utopia she finds herself free again, sexually attractive, valued for herself, yet the true power of the dream ultimately derives from what it reveals concerning the possibilities of individual human beingspossibilities which her own society denies. In utopia, Connie encounters the utopian embodiment of what her lover, her first husbandboth deadand her child, taken from her for adoption, might have become; while in Luciente, the stranger from the future, a woman so formidable and self-assured that she initially mistakes her for a man, Connie sees an image of what she herself could bea fighter for the good of others, rather than a helpless victim of society. Far more than most visitors to utopia, Connie is actually changed by her experiences. Indeed, it is Connies education, her development, that constitute the main focus of the narrative. In a sense, Woman on the Edge of Time might be seen as a utopian bildungsroman, an account of an individuals growth toward becoming fully a person, the climax coming when Connie realizes that utopia is not in fact the ideal, self-evident, automatically-arrived-at solution to societys ills typical of so many earlier utopian narratives, but rather a state whose very existence depends on decisions taken by individuals in the here and now. As her own plight worsens (she becomes one of the subjects in an experimental programme involving electronic brain implants), she has glimpses of other futuresnightmarish projections of other possible directions society might take, if those with power over her continue to have their way. Instead of passively accepting the security provided by a more perfect society, she learns to fight for utopia in this one. In what amounts to a declaration of war on the society that has stripped her of even the little she has, she

212

NARRATING UTOPIA

effectively puts an end to the brain implant programme by fatally poisoning four of the team responsible with pesticide stolen from her brothers greenhouse. Far from being static, Piercys is a utopia that is kinetic with a vengeance, concerned less with demonstrating the superiority of a utopian social structure than with highlighting the urgency of utopian desireof the need for things to be changed. Always Coming Home The utopian society that Piercy actually envisages, consisting as it does of a cooperative network of self-supporting, predominantly agrarian communities, is in some respects not dissimilar to that imagined in Le Guins Always Coming Home. But whereas Woman on the Edge of Time stresses the mutually transformative relationship between utopia and reality, it would appearat least at first sightthat Le Guins intention is to demonstrate their remoteness from one another. Where Piercys utopia is projected a mere century and a half into the future, Le Guins is set in a future just as conditional, but far more distantas is apparent from the opening words: The people in this book might be going to have lived a long, long time from now in Northern California (p.ix). Even the apparent familiarity of the spatial location soon proves illusory: it transpires that earthquakes and volcanic action have completely altered the regions geography, submerging most of the old coastline, and raising other areas above sea-level. The Kesh, the people whose culture is described in great detail in the text, live in a valley near the Inland Sea, beneath which San Francisco apparently lies buried. In addition, Le Guin provides very few clues as to the nature of the events separating the utopian future from contemporary reality. There are indications that large areas of the planet have been rendered desolate by radioactivity or toxic chemicals, but no specific details are given as to the cause of this. The present era is remembered, if at all, mainly in the form of myths, of which Le Guin provides a number of examples, all suggestive of a time when humanity was radically out of touch with the rest of the natural world, and also with most of the values that are central to the culture of the future utopia. So far as the Kesh conceptualize our time, they do so in terms of a spatial, rather than a temporal metaphor: Civilisation, as we know it, appeared in Valley thought as a remote region, set apart from the community and continuity of human/animal/earthly existencea sort of peninsula sticking out from the mainland, very thickly built upon, very heavily populated, very obscure, and very far away. [p.160]

DREAMS OF FREEDOM

213

In the tales of the Kesh, the people of our era are generally referred to almost as an alien speciesas having their heads on backward, or as living outside the world (p.160), rather than inside it, as do the Kesh and other peoples of the utopian future. Otherwise, few vestiges of the historical period, the era of human existence that followed the Neolithic era for some thousands of years in various parts of the earth (p.160), surviveunless one includes the various degenerative diseases caused by genetic impairment due to chemicals and radioactivity, from which the Kesh continue to suffer. Yet while such separation of utopia from history might seem familiar enough, it is presented from a perspective that is in many respects a reversal of the traditional pattern: where Mores Utopia was once a peninsula, not an island, joined to the outside world by an isthmus which King Utopus severs as a prelude to the creation of Utopia, here it is our world that is the peninsula. Utopia becomes the norm, our reality the exception. And while Le Guin, unlike Piercy, seems concerned to stress the tenuousness of the connection between utopia and reality, the nature of the relationship between them emerges in a rather different fashion. In the person of Pandora, who constitutes a quasi-authorial presence in the text, Le Guin makes often comical attempts to find out what happened, to discover how utopia came into beingonly to be thwarted by the Keshs apparent inability to understand her questions, or indeed the reasoning processes that underlie them. The Kesh, whose economy is based on a combination of hunting-andgathering and small-scale agriculture, live in intimate relationship with the natural world, and their cultural values have much in common with those of the aboriginal peoples of North America. Hence, to their way of thinking, Pandoras questions often appear quite literally meaningless: her preoccupation with when things happened, her desire for precise answers formulated in terms of an abstract, linear concept of time, seem to them barely comprehensible. When Pandora asks the inhabitants of the Valley about the origins of their society, their answers are often oblique, as though couched in the terms of an altogether different frame of reference: How long have your people lived in the Valley? All along. But she looks puzzled, a little uncertain of the answers, because the question is strange. You wouldnt ask, How long have fish lived in the river? How long has the grass grown on the hills? and expect an exact answer, a date, a number of years [p.171] Instead of the precise information she craves, Pandora is given a number of colourful creation myths, which the Kesh no doubt regard as conveying a truth at least as valid as any schedule of dates and times. In the end, asked

214

NARRATING UTOPIA

to define what she means by history, Pandora suggests that it is the study of Man in Time (p.181): There is a silence. You arent Man and you dont live in Time, I say bitterly. You live in the Dream Time. Always, says the Archivist of Wakwaha. Right through Civilisation, we have lived in the Dream Time. And her voice is not bitter, but full of grief, bitter grief. [pp.1812] What emerges, in effect, is a conception of utopia as dreambut a dream that is more than simply prefigurative (as is the case, say, in News from Nowhere). Instead, it holds much the same significance that dream possesses in many aboriginal cultures: not so much wish fulfilment, or an exploration of possibility, as an alternate way of perceiving reality. The society of the Kesh is portrayed not only as a future possibility, but as, in a sense, a separate reality whose chronotope is coexistent with that of contemporary reality: what utopia proposes is another way of seeing: It is very difficult to be sure of meanings when dealing with a language and way of thought in which no distinction is made between human and natural history or between objective and subjective fact and perception, in which neither chronological nor causal sequence is considered an adequate reflection of reality, and in which time and space are so muddled together that one is never sure whether they are talking about an era or an area. [p.160] Such blurring of the categories of space and time is of course not uncommon in utopian fiction, where, as we have seen, the erasure of time often involves a compensatory extension of the spatial. What is clear in Always Coming Home, however, is that the ambiguity is deliberate. While the society depicted appears to be relatively static, its stasis is used as a device to interrogate our own conceptions of timeand in particular the ways in which modern society tends automatically to conceptualize change over time as representing progress. What Le Guin seeks to embody, in the often fragmentary and overlapping narratives which comprise the work, is a sense that the two different temporal frameworksthat of utopia, and that of contemporary realityare not in fact exclusive of one another. Our own reality is depicted as permeated by utopian time, by the perennial dream of things being otherwise; while the utopian future is still haunted by the vestiges of our own timenot only in the form of the persistent effect of the environmental damage wrought in our era, but also in the resurfacing of patterns of thought and action clearly rooted in our ways of perceiving the world.

DREAMS OF FREEDOM

215

For all its apparent temporal remoteness, Le Guins utopia reveals its connection with reality in a number of ways. While, like Morriss, it is in many respects a paradise restored, rather than a new and improved version of the society at present existing, the overall effect is very different. In contrast to the somewhat idealized medievalism of Morriss utopia, Le Guins has its roots in a past ostensibly more primitivethat represented by the cultures of the native American societies that predate European settlement of the New World. Which, in a sense, represents another kind of return to utopian roots, since it was precisely the example of such societies that inspired More to conceive his own image of a society without money or private property. Le Guins future harks back to the era when the New World still represented a dream of infinite possibility, before its space was explored, colonized, recreated in the image of the Old World to which it had once offered the dream of an alternative. At the same time, however, the memory of our society is by no means erased. What Le Guin presents instead is a world which, rather than offering mere security, protection from the forces that render our own society less than utopian, is characterized by an underlying balance and harmony that is able to contain disruptive forces. Always Coming Home provides examples of violence and conflict at almost every level from the personal upwhile the longest narrative in the book, the story of Stone Telling, deals with the attempt of a warrior people, the Condor, to impose their authority over the surrounding region. In every case, however, violence proves primarily selfdestructive, largely because the society as a whole lives by a logic which does not allow conflict to gather momentum. The case of the Condor, in fact, is particularly instructive. Their culture monotheistic, hierarchical, militaristichas clear parallels in our own world, yet their dreams of military conquest are ultimately thwarted (as those of Colonel Dipa in Island are not) by the prevailing social and economic context. To begin with, it is clear that the role of technology in the utopian future is far from conducive to large-scale military enterprise. While humans have access to the City of Minda self-sustaining network of computers and cybernetic devicesand there is exchange of information between the City and the human communities across the planet, it is clear that technology is no longer central to the functioning of society as a whole: Thoughtful and educated people in the Valley recognised the incalculable treasure put at their disposal by the City of Mind; but they were not disposed to regard human existence either as information or as communication, nor intelligent mortality as a means to the ends of immortal intelligence. In their view, the two species had diverged to the extent that competition between them

216

NARRATING UTOPIA

was nonexistent, cooperation limited, and the question of superiority and inferiority bootless. [p.159] The Kesh utilize certain forms of what might be described as modern technology: electricity, steam locomotives, guns, long-range communicationsbut very little else. The information exists as to how to construct devices far more sophisticated than anything the Kesh employ up to and including nuclear weaponsbut in the absence of the industrial base necessary for their production, they remain purely theoretical concepts. While the Condor actually succeed in constructing a tank, and later several aeroplanes, the cost and effort involved virtually cripples their economy. In addition, their centralized, urban society proves less and less viable in a non-industrial world: forced to range further and further afield in search of food and supplies, they become increasingly vulnerable to retaliation by the communities that surround them. After doing a considerable amount of damage, their society finally disintegrates, torn apart by its own contradictions. Nevertheless, Le Guin does not present their destruction as a simple matterlet alone an inevitable one. Warrior societies grow up in many of the surrounding communities, ostensibly to fight back against the Condor, but also in imitation of many of their waysand these cause almost as much disruption as the Condor themselves. Describing the eventual dissolution of one such society, one of the Kesh reflects: I have come to think that the sickness of Man is like the mutating viruses and the toxins: there will always be some form of it about, or brought in from elsewhere by people moving and travelling, and there will always be the risk of infection. What those sick with it said is true: It is a sickness of our being human, a fearful one. It would be unwise in us to forget the Warriors lest it need all be done and said again. [p.411] Le Guins utopia is not one where the past is ignored, or forgotten; nor is it a paradise from which Original Sin has been banished: the human capacity to do evil remainsutopia is the provision of a context which is as conducive as possible to doing otherwise. Our own era is not merely a bad dream: it must be remembered, lest it recur; conversely, in our own era, utopia is not merely a dream, eitherit must be worked toward, lest our own era continue. Underlying Le Guins representation of utopia as almost unimaginably remote from our own world, then, is a vigorous polemic directed against the values by which modern society lives. There is a connection between the two, but its nature is suggested by what Le Guin makes the central metaphor of her text: the heyiya, or hingemost commonly depicted as a

DREAMS OF FREEDOM

217

pair of interlocking spirals. This constitutes a common decorative motif, the basis for their town design (houses in one spiral, communal buildings in the other), and a metaphor for any kind of link between opposing states: life and death, dream and waking, earth and sky. It implies both a connection and a separation, a link which also involves some form of dislocation. As a metaphor for the complex relationship between utopia and reality, its implications are very different from those of the painful transitions depicted elsewhere, suggestive of both return to and reemergence from the womb. The hinge, joining surfaces which move in different directions, is the mechanism whereby doors are opened, disclosing gaps in the wall, and revealing new spaces into which movement is possible. The complex implications of this central metaphor, simultaneously suggesting both difference and relationship, are further reinforced by Le Guins narrative strategy, which represents a departure from the utopian norm even more radical than Gearharts The Wanderground. Always Coming Home contains a number of sequential narratives varying in length from less than a page to the three-part story of Stone Telling, which is practically a novella in its own right; there are examples of Kesh biography, history, fiction, poetry and myth, interspersed with accounts of their customs, rituals, architecture, medical practice, and religious beliefs. And while it is a reflection of the non-utopian character of our own society that the accompanying tape cassette of utopian music is available only to those who can afford the hardback edition, the utopian recipes contained in the section helpfully labelled The Back of the Book can be made by anyone.2 How all this is readhow much, and in what orderis left up to the reader, and it becomes clear that part of Le Guins purpose is to avoid the creation of a utopia which is complete, self-contained, and separate from the reality of writer and reader alike. In the words of the quasi-authorial Pandora: Pandora doesnt want to look into the big end of the telescope and see, jewel-bright, distinct, tiny, and entire, the Valley. She shuts her eyes, doesnt want to see, she knows what she will see: Everything Under Control. The dolls house. The dolls country. [p.56] What is offered instead, disparate yet connected, is Bits, chunks, fragments, Shards, Pieces of the Valley, lifesizealong with the advice: Let the heart complete the pattern (p.56). As a challenge to the often authoritarian narrative practice of the traditional utopia, Le Guins experiment could scarcely be more thoroughgoing. From the bits, chunks, fragments, shards there emerges a picture of life lived under possible utopian conditions which has a concreteness far removed from the abstraction which characterizes many

218

NARRATING UTOPIA

earlier utopias; yet at the same time, there is little of the relentless specificity of detail typical of the traditional paradigm. Always Coming Home does not seek to fill the space opened up by utopian imagining, but rather to suggest its extent: even within the relatively limited geographical confines of Le Guins future Northern California a good deal of variety is evident, and while we are told that the rest of the world was not a matter of very urgent concern to most people of the Valley (p.483), they are clearly aware that their own is only one of an infinite variety of ways of beingdistinct, yet not unrelated. Beyond the mountains to the East that constitute the boundary of their immediate geographical world, the lands go on and on to the sea again, you know and so on round till you come back to the Valley (p.483). In addition, while no less serious than its predecessors, Always Coming Home is singularly free of the earnestness that so often attends utopian speculation: like More, whose example in this regard has only infrequently been followed, Le Guin is alive to the element of game, of play, even of self-indulgence inherent in the utopian projectand she engages, particularly in the Pandora sequences, in a considerable amount of self-mockery. While her utopia offers serious criticism of our own society, a more than usually concrete delineation of possible alternatives, and a range of sophisticated narrative experiment, it is also, in the words of the Archivist of Wakwaha: a mere dream dreamed in a bad time, an Up Yours to the people who ride snowmobiles, make nuclear weapons, and run prison camps by a middle-aged housewife, a critique of civilisation possible only to the civilised, an affirmation pretending to be a rejection, a glass of milk for the soul ulcered by acid rain, a peace of pacifist jeanjacquerie, and a cannibal dance among the savages in the ungodly garden of the farthest West. [p.336] For Le Guin, at least, the ambiguity, the potential multiple significations of utopian fiction are clearly something to be celebrated. As an attempt to resolve the problems inherent in the extended depiction of a coherently developed utopian ideal, Always Coming Home clearly differs radically from Woman on the Edge of Time, even while addressing many of the same issues. Both works, however, suggest new directions in terms of the relation between ideology and narrative practice. In Piercys utopia, there is clear evidence of a commitment both to feminism and to a revolutionary socialism whose somewhat eclectic character is suggested by the names of some of the people and places in her utopian societythere are characters called Red Star, Bolivar, Sacco-Vanzetti, and Luxembourg, not to mention a greenhouse named after Amilcar Cabral. Le Guins leanings are equally clearly anarchist (as is likewise apparent in

DREAMS OF FREEDOM

219

The Dispossessed); elsewhere, she defines her anarchism as not the socialDarwinist economic libertarianism of the far-right; but anarchism, as prefigured in early Taoist thought, and expounded by Shelley and Kropotkin, Goldman and Goodman (Winds Twelve Quarters, p.285). In contrast to Morriss Marxism, however, or the vaguer and more confused radicalism of Huxley, the political beliefs of Piercy and Le Guin do appear to find a reflection in their respective narrative practice. It is hardly coincidental, for example, that Piercy chooses not only to make the central focus of her narrative a womans oppression, but also to structure the narrative around the dialectic which she establishes between contemporary reality and the utopian future: a dialectic in which utopian ideals can be seen as both a product of and a commentary on the political actualities of the present. Equally, Le Guins abandonment of an ordered, linear narrative may be seen as motivated by a desire to return to the individual reader a measure of control over the way in which the text itself is constituted, and to resist so far as possible the imposition on the reader of a single, predetermined vision. Even so, it is necessary to guard against too rigid or facile an equation of ideology and narrative strategy: as has already been seen, an authoritarian, centralist utopian vision need not exclude radical narrative experiment, nor a libertarian one the retention of the traditional narrative paradigm. While Piercy and Le Guin do succeed in avoiding many of the narrative pitfalls evident in earlier utopias, it is clear that resolving the problems inherent in utopian narrative is more than a simple matter of adopting a libertarian stance and then adopting a narrative schema to reflect it. Indeed, it is significant in this context that Le Guins earlier utopia, The Dispossessed, whose narrative strategy closely resembles that of Woman on the Edge of Time, with a structure of alternating episodes which once again seeks to establish a dialectic between the real and the utopian, has nevertheless been subjected to a veritable barrage of criticism directed at its alleged political shortcomings. The Dispossessed The Dispossessed, which Moylan sees as the most problematic of the critical utopias he discusses, has been found fault with on a number of grounds. Nadia Khouri, for instance, criticizes it precisely for what she sees as its failure to embody a dynamic interaction between utopia and realityfor its reduction of the dialectic to binary oppositions, with points of gravity congealed into static equilibrium (p.51).3 Despite the recurrent contrasts between the utopian world of Anarres and its twin planet, Urrasclearly analogous to our ownKhouri argues that nothing in fact changes in The

220

NARRATING UTOPIA

Dispossessed except that an individuals awareness has acquired a sounder perception of truth (p.53). The individual in question has also come in for his share of criticism. Shevek, the utopian physicist and mathematician, whose return to Urras constitutes the narrative link between utopia and the analogue of our own reality, is viewed by a number of critics as little more than a classic stereotype: the Great Scientist (male, of course), who leads humanity forward by both his discoveries and his example.4 Worse, he is also a heterosexual male who, in a society where there is no marriage, nor any social taboos against multiple relationships, deliberately chooses to live in a monogamous partnership. While other modes of sexuality are positively portrayedBedap, for example, easily the most politically astute character in the book, is gaythis is dismissed as sheer tokenism.5 In addition, the relative lack of positive portrayals of women is seen as problematic, indicative of a privileging of traditional sex roles and familial structures.6 Overall, while her utopia may radically question many of the norms of existing society, Le Guin is viewed as ultimately reinscribing one of its most fundamental basesnamely, patriarchal authority: like so many utopias before it, The Dispossessed reinscribes the very norms of gender relations that it purports to challenge. Such criticisms, however, imply certain normative assumptions of their own as to what utopian fiction should be like. Taken collectively, they suggest a preference for a utopia in which change is inherent (not static, but kinetic), connected to reality, yet as far removed from it as possible in terms of its sexual politicsideally, Moylan suggests, one where the more collective heroes of social transformation are presented off-center and usually as characters who are not dominant, white heterosexual, chauvinist males but female, gay, non-white, and generally operating collectively. [Demand the Impossible, p.45] What is preferred, in other words, is a utopia not unlike Piercys. Yet even granting the validity of at least some of the criticisms cited above, it is troubling, to say the least, to find the prescriptive character it has taken writers of utopian narrative so long to escape resurfacing in the form of a new orthodoxy among commentators on such narrative. While perspectives such as those which Moylan lists obviously provide a valuable, even essential corrective to the comfortable white, middle-class, male assumptions of a Bellamy or a Wells, it is simplistic to conclude that works that do not embody them automatically reinscribe the norms of existing society. As Terry Eagleton remarks: Simply to counterpose difference to identity, plurality to unity, the marginal to the central, is to lapse back into binary opposition, as the

DREAMS OF FREEDOM

221

more subtle deconstructors are perfectly aware. It is pure formalism to imagine that otherness, heterogeneity and marginality are unqualified political benefits regardless of their concrete social content. [Ideology, p.128] What Le Guins narrative choices reflect is not so much an unthinking reproduction of her own societys normative gender ideology, nor indeed the stasis of the traditional utopia, but rather the fact that she is engaged in a rather different interrogation of the utopian project than that provided by Russ, Delany, and to a lesser extent by Piercy. Perhaps in this context it might be helpful to cite the words of one of Piercys own characters, Sojourner, during a debate over the issue of art and political correctness: Every piece of art cant contain everything everybody would like to say! Ive seen this mistake for sixty years. Our culture as a whole must speak the whole truth. But every object cant! Thats the slogan mentality at work, as if there were certain holy words that must always be named. [pp.21011) While it is true that the utopia Le Guin depicts perpetuates certain of the norms of her own society, the question of the relationship between what changes in utopia and what remains the same, already addressed in the context of the discussion of earlier works, here becomes more than usually ambiguous. For example, while Sheveks relationship with his partner, Takver, conforms to the conventions of twentieth-century Western society, it is clear that the pattern which it represents is hardly fundamental to Le Guins utopia in the way that, say, Mores or Bacons representation of the patriarchal family is central to the societies depicted in Utopia or The New Atlantis. Heterosexual monogamy on Anarres is a choiceone among manyrather than the model to which economic and social pressures encourage the individual to conform. As in Piercys society of the future, there is no reason to be anythingcelibate, promiscuous, monogamous; homo-, bi-, or heterosexualunless it is the individuals wish. Obviously, Le Guins privileging of monogamous heterosexual partnership as the central relationship in the book, notwithstanding the absence of the economic and social structures that sustain it as the norm in our own society, may be seen as tacitly suggesting that such relationships are natural, as opposed to socially constructed; yet at the same time it is apparent that Sheveks normality in this regard serves a narrative function that goes beyond the mere reinscription of conventional values in a utopian context. Certainly, it is true that Le Guin does not address, or addresses only in passing, many of the questions of sexual politics, sexual identity, sexual practice that are central concerns in the work of writers such as Delany and Russ; however, it might be argued that, just as Russs and

222

NARRATING UTOPIA

Delanys reliance on the convenient fiction that economic problems are resolvable by technological advances frees them to focus on questions of sexual politics, so Le Guin uses Sheveks apparent conformity to conventional sexual values as a means of exposing other forms of difference. For Shevek is far more than the mere conventional hero to which Le Guins critics reduce him: in his role as a visitor, not to, but from utopia, his inability to be persuaded by the values of the society he encounters (the reverse of the traditional visitor to utopias almost immediate conversion) serves to unmask many of its limitations. It is clear, for example, that it is precisely Sheveks surface normality that enables him to be accepted on Urras in a way that someone more threatening to its patriarchal normsan independent woman, a gay man, or (heaven forbid) a lesbianwould not. (The Urrasti scientists are shocked, and indeed rather put out to discover that Sheveks teacher, Gvarab, was a woman.) Instead of the overt rejection, not to say persecution, which such alternative visitors might have experienced, Shevek encounters welcome, acceptance, attempted co-option, and as a result gains a more immediate insight into the insidiousness of Urrasti culture than would be possible for a more obvious outsider. Indeed, rather as in Herland the unguarded comments of the visitors enable the innocent utopians to deduce the realities that underlie them, so Sheveks equally innocent questioning often serves to expose the real state of affairs. While he is told by an Urrasti scientist (in terms reminiscent of Terry in Herland) that a beautiful, virtuous woman is an inspiration to usthe most precious thing on earth (p.60), this proves hard to reconcile with the response to his innocent question after attending a gathering of dignitaries who are nearly all male: Where are other women?which his Urrasti hosts automatically interpret as a request for some form of hired sex. Unwillingor perhaps unableto accept that someone from a radically different society might be fundamentally different from themselves, the Urrasti accept him as someone from whom it is unnecessary to conceal their assumptions. Yet while Sheveks personal life may appear conventional enough, he is in other respects exceptional. His acceptance on Urras may be a reflection of his apparent normality, but the main reason for his welcome is the fact that he is the foremost physicist on either planet, the pioneer of a theory of time which may render possible instantaneous communication across the galaxy. To criticize Le Guin for making Shevek a stereotypical Great Scientist, however, is surely to miss the pointfor in the context she creates, what Moylan reads as the privileging of male, intellectual, solitary heroics (Demand the Impossible, p.110) in fact raises as many questions about the nature of utopia as his acceptance on Urras raises about our own

DREAMS OF FREEDOM

223

reality. The problem is that, on Anarres, Shevek is out of the ordinary: Le Guins utopia is not one characterized by Fourieresque profusion, with thirty-seven million mathematicians the equal of NewtonShevek is very much one of a kind, and as such he represents a threat to certain tendencies within utopia, namely those toward stasis and conformity. Just as in a capitalist society such as Le Guins own North America (or its Urrasti analogue, A-Io), which trumpets the virtues of individualism, it is solidarity and collective action that pose the greatest threat, so in the collective society of Anarres it is visible individuality that causes the most problems. In her portrayal of Anarres, Le Guin offers not merely a representation, but also a critique of utopia, and in showing the difficulties occasioned by Sheveks individuality, she dramatizes one of the chief dangers inherent in a utopian society: the possibility that collective solidarity may degenerate into mere conformity (a very real one, judging by the number of utopias that provide specific, and often draconian penalties for dissidence). Even a society run on the most libertarian principles cannot guarantee freedom, and what Le Guin sets out to explore is the extent to which, in a society based on collective co-operation, freedom is measured by the ability to accept difference (always provided such difference is not actively antisocial). While fully accepting that his duty to society involves performing arduous physical labour, as well as simply thinking great thoughts, Shevek at the same time insists on his freedom, his right as an individual to do his own work as welland in doing so becomes part of a larger struggle to keep utopia utopian, not by striving to preserve it as it is, but by forcing it to continue changing. The outcome of an earlier revolution on Urras, the utopia on Anarres is in danger of stagnation, having cut itself off from its roots: Sheveks return represents the reestablishment of a connection between the real and the utopian of which both are in desperate need. The corrupt and increasingly repressive world of Urras needs the hope that utopia represents in order to bring about revolutionary change; Anarres needs the threat which Urras represents to oblige it to keep changing. Arguing for his right to make the trip back to the world Anarress anarchist revolutionaries had left generations before, Shevek stresses the need to avoid the dangers of pursuing security at all costs: what were after is to remind ourselves that we didnt come to Anarres for safety, but for freedom. If we must all agree, all work together, were no better than a machine. If an individual cant work in solidarity with his fellows, its his duty to work alone. His duty and his right. We have been denying people that right. Weve been saying, more and more often, you must work with the others, you must accept the rule of the majority. But any rule is tyranny. The duty

224

NARRATING UTOPIA

of the individual is to accept no rule, to be the initiator of his own acts, to be responsible. Only if he does so will the society live, and change, and adapt, and survive. We are not subjects of a State founded upon law, but members of a society founded upon Revolution. Revolution is our obligation: our hope of evolution. The Revolution is in the individual spirit, or it is nowhere. It is for all, or it is nothing. If it is seen as having any end, it will never truly begin. [pp.2889] The clear message of The Dispossessed is that the only real revolution is permanent revolutiona continuing process, not something to be achieved once and for all.7 On Urras, however, it is Sheveks failure to be merely exceptional that proves disconcerting to his hosts. The Great Scientist they can cope with; the fact that, for all his difficulties on Anarres, he remains a utopian is more difficult to comprehend. While they would like to treat him simply as a dissident genius, gratefully embracing the offer of freedom, the Urrasti gradually learn that they cannot seduce, bribe, or intimidate him into accepting their values. Nor are they able to obtain his secret, the new and revolutionary temporal theory, since he does not perceive it as a possession. Their efforts to co-opt him ultimately fail, as do their attempts to cast him in the role of as genius unappreciated by his society, in which his unique gifts are merely part of his identity, rather than something that makes him better than others. If he fights for his own freedom, it is at the same time for a freedom to which everyone should be entitled. It is this, more than anything, that the Urrasti ruling class are unable to understand. On Anarres, Sheveks struggles serve to expose some of the problems inherent in a utopian society; on Urras, by contrast, it is the virtues of utopia that become apparent. For it is not Sheveks brilliance as a scientist that enables him to see so clearly what is wrong with a society based on greed and injusticeit is the perspective he has gained from his socialization while growing up in utopia. For Le Guins utopia is not simply a society that provides an equitable distribution of resources, where nobody goes hungry while another eats (p.229)although that is of course the essential precondition for all its other qualitiesit is also a world, unlike our own, that provides for its members the possibility of growing to something like their full potential. What Le Guin attempts to imagine is what it might be like to be a utopian. Shevek is not a Dr Leete, who is simply a prosperous nineteenth-century professional living in more congenial surroundings; nor even a Dr Robert, the well-balanced antithesis to Huxleys eminent atomic physicist with a mental age, outside the laboratory, of about eleven (Island, p.214): rather, he represents Le Guins vision of what it might be like to be an exceptionally gifted individual growing up in a society which

DREAMS OF FREEDOM

225

does not seek to co-opt those gifts and make them serve the interests of existing power structures. Nevertheless, the extent to which Shevek is a product of utopia, rather than merely a stereotypical Great Scientist, only becomes fully apparent when he is placed in the context of Le Guins analogue of the real world and here, as elsewhere, it is clear that much of the impact of The Dispossessed is due to its narrative strategy. Out of the different contexts provided by the twin worlds of Urras and Anarres, separate, yet related, there emerges a larger perspective that embraces both. Taken in isolation, Le Guins depiction of utopian society shows it in an almost dystopian light; it is through the contrast with Urras that the splendour of the utopian dream is restored. As in Woman on the Edge of Time, it is the focus on the relationship between the real and the utopian that gives to the latter the sense of urgency, that utopia is worth fighting for, so singularly lacking in most earlier utopian fictions. Like Piercys utopia, The Dispossessed begins with a reversal of the traditional arrival of the visitor in utopia: it is Shevek, the utopian, who sets out for the counterpart of our own reality. Nor does the parallel end there: just as Luciente comes from a utopian future whose roots lie in our own present, Shevek is likewise returning to his past, to the world from which his ancestors emigrated, seeking refuge from the injustice which on Urras still persists. The gap in space which Shevek crosses is also, in a sense, a gap in time. Where there is a difference of perspective, however, is in the controlling point of view from which both utopia and reality are portrayed. Here Piercys is closer to the traditional approach, focusing on the consciousness of Connie, the visitor to utopia, who assesses utopia in the context of her own oppression in the here and now. Le Guin, by contrast, makes the utopian the norm by which reality is judgedwhich in turn lends a more overtly satirical edge to the narrative. Rather as earlier satirists used the insights of the innocent outsiderthe Noble Savage, the Persian traveller to expose the follies and corruption of European civilization, Le Guin employs Sheveks innocent utopian eye to unmask the absurdity of a number of aspects of Urrasti (and of course our own) society. Unfamiliar with Urrasti norms, Shevek requires explanations for much that his hosts take for granted: the capitalist economic system, the hierarchical military structures used to defend it, the role and status of women, and even the oddities of the university grading system.8 Like Gilmans utopians, Shevek has a well-developed propensity for asking awkward questions. Nevertheless, as in Herland, the satire is of secondary importance in comparison to the focus on the individuals changing experience of a new society. Le Guins main emphasis is on Sheveks own struggles as he confronts the contradictions and complexities of a world other than his

226

NARRATING UTOPIA

own, with its own distinctive assumptions as to the nature of reality. At first he is excited by its richness and diversity, by what initially seem to be its wider horizons, by the apparently greater personal freedom he enjoys; even the evident injustice and visible oppression seem at first like discords in a larger, richer harmony. But gradually his enthusiasm, stimulated by the newness of his experience, gives way to disillusion. The surface splendour and richness of Urras seem less inspiring when it becomes clear that they are available only to a privileged minority. Frustrated on Anarres because of the difficulties he experiences in doing his own work, he begins to realize that on Urras he is denied the freedom to do anything else. If Anarres places restrictions on his individual freedom, Urras refuses him the right to participate with others in struggling for larger, collective freedoms: on both worlds there is the need for rebellion, resistance, change. And yet there remains a difference: whereas on Anarres nonconformity arouses the threat of violencewhen Shevek leaves for Urras there is a fracas in which rocks are thrown, and one person is killedthere is no equivalent for the organized violence of the Urrasti state. It is only after witnessing helicopter gunships firing on an unarmed demonstration that Shevek finally understands that there is a reason for military hierarchy after allthat it is not merely a coercive mechanism of extraordinary inefficiency (p.245): he now understood why the army was organized as it was. It was indeed quite necessary. No rational form of organization would serve the purpose. He simply had not understood that the purpose was to enable men with machine guns to kill unarmed men and women easily and in large quantities when told to do so. [p.245] As in Woman on the Edge of Time, it is only in the course of the narrative that Shevek comes to realize, like Connie, why utopia is so urgently necessary. At the same time, Sheveks relation to the utopian world of Anarres undergoes an equally significant process of growth and change. Interwoven with the sequence of chapters dealing with his experiences on Urras is a parallel account of Sheveks life on Anarres, beginning with infancy, and ending at the point where he departs for Urras. The Shevek of the Anarres chapters is younger, just as Anarres itself is the younger society, but the impression created by the young Shevek is constantly modified by its juxtaposition to the sequences which portray the adult he has become. Similarly, the actions of the older man, his responses to the world of Urras, can be seen to be in many respects determined by his past experience on Anarres. The different stages in Sheveks development, in other words, are presented in such a way that the child, the youth, the young man, the

DREAMS OF FREEDOM

227

mature adult can be seen as part of a whole being, existing in both space and time: human character is no more static than human society; the changes which the one undergoes are reflected in the other. Indeed, Le Guins presentation of the individual, Shevek, in many ways parallels her depiction of utopian society as a whole. For Anarres, too, changes as the narrative unfolds: it likewise faces many of the problems that confront the individualthe dangers of stagnation, conformity, sterile compromise, ceasing to grow; Sheveks avoidance of them also enacts that of his society. For while all these dangers suggest a society on the brink of lapsing into the stasis of the traditional utopia, or even a dystopian enforced conformity, it is clear that such a fate is not inevitable. Anarres is not perfect, not static: it is a utopia, but one shown to be the product of unceasing human effort, not created once and for all, but rather perpetually recreated. Its very precariousness, in fact, is what gives it life, and lends urgency to the efforts of the individuals who comprise it. Even its limitations shed light on the nature of its twin world, the reality to which it is both linked and opposed. Significantly, it is Urras, the analogue of our own reality, which is portrayed as richer and more fertile, more colourful, various, and alive; Anarres, by contrast, is arid, barren, devoid of any life forms other than scrubby vegetation and the humans who have colonized it. There are no animals on Anarres: like any utopia, it is purely a human creation and in its inhabitants ceaseless struggle to make fertile their barren world, Le Guin provides a richly suggestive metaphor for the process of trying to breathe life into and give substance to a political abstraction. Like any ideal, utopia can only be made real through human action. By contrast, Urras realityfor all its fertility, is a world full of fear, suffering, oppression, death: it needs the ideal which Anarres represents to give it hope and direction, just as Anarres needs the life giving energy which Urras embodies. The two, real and ideal, are inseparably linked, for all the attempts that have been made to maintain a separation between them. The Urrasti effort to preserve the status quo by licensing the departure of the revolutionary element to Anarres has proved a failure; so too has the Anarresti attempt to preserve the purity of the utopian ideal by cutting themselves off from Urras: in isolation, the one society is in danger of stagnating, the other of falling apart. On Urras, the inequalities and injustice that once prompted revolution are getting worse in the absence of the revolutionary forces who chose exile over continuing struggle;9 while on Anarres, cut off from the world which prompted their revolution, the Anarresti find themselves slipping into the sterile conformity so typical of the traditional utopia. In opting for isolation, they have opted out of the dialectic of the real and the ideal, choosing instead a solution that is utopian in the worst sense. Like Woman on the Edge of Time, The Dispossessed is

228

NARRATING UTOPIA

concerned with the relationship between the real and the utopian: for Le Guin, the utopian ideal can neither replace reality nor exist in isolation from it. Instead, the two are inextricably linkedalthough not in the static, binary opposition that Khouri suggests; rather, what is portrayed is a symbiotic relationship in which each gives the other what it lacksthe reason to go on changing. In conversation with an alien diplomat from Earth (which is represented as having undergone an environmental catastrophe of such magnitude that it makes Urras seem a paradise by comparison) Shevek reflects on the connection between the real and the ideal, the past and the future: You dont understand what time is You say that the past is gone, the future is not real, there is no change, no hope. You think Anarres is a future that cannot be reached, as your past cannot be changed. So there is nothing but the present, this Urras, the rich, real, stable present, the moment now. And you think that is something which can be possessed! You envy it a little. You think it is something you would like to have. But it is not real, you know. It is not stable, not solidnothing is. Things change, change. You cannot have anything And least of all can you have the present, unless you accept with it the past and the future. Not only the past but also the future, not only the future but also the past! Because they are real: only their reality makes the present real. You will not achieve or even understand Urras unless you accept the reality, the enduring reality, of Anarres we are the key. [pp.2801] Utopia is a future, but one constantly changing in response to both past and present, whose nature it also shapes. Like Piercy, Le Guin succeeds in creating what Wells only talks ofa utopia that is not static, but kinetic. It is here that the real significance of Sheveks vocation becomes apparent. As a physicist and mathematician, he is engaged throughout the course of the narrative in an attempt to find a theory that will reconcile the concept of time as linear and sequential with what are termed the Principles of Simultaneitya conceptual model in which all moments are seen as, in a sense, present. This exploration of the nature of time becomes, in its turn, another of the works central metaphors, reflecting as it does a narrative structure which, while linear, also juxtaposes and shows the links between different moments in time. Sheveks experiences in the present reality of Urras are not merely counterpointed to, but moulded by his past experiences in a utopia which at the same time constitutes an embodiment of a possible future. The Dispossessed is a utopia which might also be termed a chronotopia. Given this dynamic conception of the nature of utopia, it is hardly

DREAMS OF FREEDOM

229

coincidental that The Dispossessed, like Woman on the Edge of Time, shows little sign of the traditional utopias tendency toward a regressive simplification of the complexities of adult experience. While money has been abolished on Anarres, as in so many other utopias, this does not affect the economic realities of trying to grow enough to feed the inhabitants of a singularly unforgiving physical environment. Sexuality is not complicated by irrational taboos and legal constraints, but it remains problematic, a human relationship which resists both systematization and easy solutions. And while labour is rendered more rewarding by its having a demonstrably useful purposethe furthering of the common good, rather than the enrichment of an employerLe Guin provides none of the traditional rational substitutes (very early retirement, very short working days) which so often mask the essentially fantastic dream of paradisaical idleness. Still less is there the pretence that work can be transformed into a form of creative play, as tends to be the case in News from Nowhere: not all work is good for the health, or offers the aesthetic satisfactions of mediaeval craftsmanship. John Fekete, in fact, criticizes Le Guin for her choice of a scarcity and necessity-dominated environment (p.135) rather than dealing with the more interesting range of speculative questions, having to do with permanent revolution and the forms of freedom in a libertarian post-scarcity society (p.135).10 For Le Guin, however, it is clear that there is a utopian aspect to the overcoming of difficulty, the sharing of hardship. The utopian ideal present in The Dispossessed is not the recovery of childhood, but the achievement of brotherhood, sisterhooda solidarity which begins, in Sheveks words, in shared pain (50). While, like all utopias, Le Guins is a human construct, a simplification which can never fully match the richness and complexity of reality, it remains one in which the human element is not a limitation, but a strength. While attending a party at the luxurious home of a wealthy Urrasti, Shevek makes this very point, contrasting the richness of Urras to the poverty of Anarres: Anarres is all dust and dry hills. All meager, all dry The towns are very small and dull, they are dreary. No palaces. Life is dull, and hard work. You cant always have what you want, or even what you need, because there isnt enough. You Urrasti have enough. Enough air, enough rain, grass, oceans, food, music, buildings, factories, machines, books, clothes, history. You are rich, you own. We are poor, we lack. You have, we do not have. Everything is beautiful, here. Only not the faces. On Anarres nothing is beautiful, nothing but the faces. The other faces, the men and women. Here you see the jewels, there you see the eyes. And in the eyes you see the splendor, the splendor of the human spirit. Because our men and

230

NARRATING UTOPIA

women are freepossessing nothing, they are free. And you the possessors are possessed. You are all in jail. Each alone, solitary, with a heap of what he owns. You live in prison, die in prison. It is all I can see in your eyes [p.184] Following which, having indulged for the first time in the Urrasti custom of drinking alcohol (another of Anarres many lacks), he proceeds to vomit copiously over an elaborate tray of canapes. Yet even here we see a metaphor of the relationship between utopia and reality. The gross physical act whereby Shevek renders the delicate, expensive pastries repulsive and inedible is itself, to use Bakhtinian terminology, a form of carnival uncrowning, unmasking the reality that underlies the official version: from a utopian perspective such displays of conspicuous consumption in the midst of poverty and starvation are inherently disgustingSheveks gross physical action merely makes this apparent. Although concerned with ideals, Le Guin does not therefore idealize those who uphold them: her Great Scientist is also a fallible human being with stinking breath and a bad hangover the following morningan apt enough representative of the utopia which produced him. Le Guins utopia is one which acknowledges reality, rather than seeking to escape it, not least because it presents its ideological concerns within a narrative framework which serves to foreground the relationship between utopia and the reality from which it stems, yet to which it proposes an alternative. Like Piercys, it is a utopia which shows the future as conditional, rather than perfect. The Future of Utopia In the introductory chapter it was suggested that critical responses to utopian narrative are themselves a form of narrativemost often of a journey away from the monolithic ideal of the traditional utopia, and toward a variety of destinations. For some commentators it is a narrative with an at least potentially happy ending, as in the case of readings where the fragmentation of the monolith into a variety of partial visions, of multiform and self-reflexive narratives, is seen as a positive development, enabling a renewed engagement with the problematics of oppositional struggle under the conditions of late capitalism; or where the stasis and authoritarianism of the traditional utopia are seen as being made open to dialogue by the active reading strategies of reader-response theory. For others, the narrative is more problematic: while such new developments (not to mention the critical interest in them) may be taken as a welcome indication that utopian hope is still alive, they also serve to highlight the difficulties of finding ways of acting on that hope under the conditions obtaining in contemporary societydifficulties which have led some critics

DREAMS OF FREEDOM

231

to the more pessimistic conclusion that the relevance of utopia has been exhausted, and that the journey is one that merely leads to a dead-end. In the case of the present discussion, it might seem that the narrative is of the more optimistic variety, tracing as it does a movement toward the resolution of many of the narrative problems on which earlier chapters focused. Yet at the same time it is clear that this has not been achieved without cost. While the utopias of Piercy and Le Guin delineate societies far removed from the regimented visions of the past, and do so in ways that resolve many of the formal and aesthetic difficulties apparent in traditional utopian narrative, it remains unclear whether this renders them any more effective in promoting social transformation than their predecessors. As Levitas reminds us, while both the form and content of utopia are of central importance, there is also the question of function and it would seem that in this regard the movement away from the norms of the traditional utopia has also involved a retreat from the notion of utopia as representing a coherent possible alternative to existing society. What has become clear, in effect, is that the role of utopia has changed: the purpose of utopian narrative has become less the advocacy of specific alternative sociopolitical formations, and more the stimulus and education of desire. Clearly, the issue of the education of desire is a crucially important one particularly given the existence of a vast capitalist dream machine dedicated to colonizing the imagination in the interests of the maintenance of the status quo. As Bammer argues, ours is a society which also seeks to educate desire, but in the service of far from utopian goals: to the extent that consumer economies are based on the principle of perpetual increase, a systemic effort is made to commodify desire as a need that can be satisfied through the acquisition of objects. Desire is thus (re)constructed in material terms and directed to become profitable within the sphere of production and exchange. As visions of the good life (romance, adventure, wealth, and power) are marketed as lucrative diversions from the stress and tedium of everyday routines, commodified dreams become tools with which to keep deeper and politically more destabilizing dissatisfactions in check. Seduced by our own desires as we see them reflected in the promises for fulfilment on display, we buy into fantasies that prevent us from acknowledging (much less pursuing) what might be more authentic needs. [p.44] Not the least insidious aspect of this process is its transformation of desire from a potential engine of change to a tool of social control. Indeed, part of the ideological legitimacy of late capitalism rests on its success in making

232

NARRATING UTOPIA

us believe that our desires are being met, or that if not they can be met or, failing that, that if not, the fault lies with the individual rather than the system: that this is the way things are, and that change is neither possible nor desirable. Obviously, for change to be possible, it is necessary for people to be able to imagine change as both possible and desirable, and given the extent of what Kenneth Roemer refers to as speculative illiteracy in modern society, the need for powerful images of alternative possibilities is all the more pressing. In a society where utopia has become a brand name for soft drinks and canned tomatoes, and where even highly educated young students, to use Roemers example, asked to imagine a utopian transformation of their own environment, with unlimited resources available to accomplish the task, are unable to conceive of anything more than better parking facilities and a winning season for the local baseball team (Utopian Literature p.394), the need for the educative potential of utopia scarcely needs to be argued.11 Nevertheless, while utopian literature offers a potential mechanism for the education of desire in new directions, an awareness of the importance of the task can lead to an overestimation of the success with which it is being carried out. Thus, while Moylan, for example, argues that [f]rom Gerard [sic] Winstanleys designs of a democratic and just society in the seventeenth century to the elaborate systems of the utopian socialists in the nineteenth, great alternate systems in print did little to generate fundamental social change (p.5), this sober assessment of the limitations of the traditional utopia gives way to an almost messianic zeal when he turns to the critical utopia of his own time: The critical utopias have restored the utopian impulse to the general oppositional movement. Therein radically hopeful figurations can become part of the collective, participatory, and nonhierarchical project of tearing down the present dominant system and meeting the historical, material, and situationally specific needs of all people rather than of the few who benefit from the current structure The critical utopias help achieve a breach in the ideological and cultural structures that surround us and thus help create that oppositional public sphere in which the play of alternatives can be elaborated. In their self-reflexive and deconstructive questioning of utopian discourse they free the utopian impulse for the ongoing task of social change. [pp.21213] This, however, begs a number of questions. Leaving aside the question of how far the utopianism of Winstanley and others was in fact effective in informing the radical oppositional consciousness of earlier eras, Moylans claims for the much greater effectiveness of what are after all a relatively

DREAMS OF FREEDOM

233

small number of utopian fictions, written in a single country during a relatively brief period of time, do seem to indicate an exaggerated sense of the importance of cultural production to the larger sphere of oppositional strugglewhich in Levitass view can be attributed in part to what she describes as an alarming if increasingly common misconception of Gramsci, claiming that Gramsci identified the terrain of ideology and culture as the [rather than a] major site for contesting the dominant power (Concept of Utopia, p.174). Yet while it is not uncommon for those engaged in intellectual and cultural production to overestimate the importance of their own sphere of endeavour, such underlying assumptions can lead on occasion to flagrant absurdity, as for example when Moylan cites Stanley Aronowitzs assertion that: the struggle over culture, rather than the struggle for economic advantage, is connected to the problematic of historical change, since under late capitalist conditions economic struggles no longer retain their subversive content. [Quoted in Moylan, p.208] Quite what would happen if one were to inform striking workers, fighting for their jobs against the corporate agenda of transnational capitalism, that they would be better deployed writing postmodern utopian fiction is perhaps better left to the imaginationand, indeed, it might equally be questioned whether the freedom fighters of East Timor, fighting against a rgime that continues to enjoy close ties with the North American academic establishment that also supports the expanding study of utopianism, would identify their struggle as primarily a cultural one. While the task of generating images of alternative possibilities is an important one, there is little to be gained from exaggerating its significance. Yet while Moylan is clearly aware of the continued necessity of utopian alternatives, the same can hardly be said of Peter Ruppert, who, while also writing in the aftermath of the wave of utopian writing hailed by Moylan as a breakthrough, takes an almost antithetical view of its continuing relevance. According to Ruppert: The essence of utopian thinking has always been a desire for a thorough restructuring of social relations and a radical transformation of social life. Such a restructuring implies the possibility of a perspective outside of and in opposition to the status quo. In a homogeneous society such as our own, so completely standardized, systematized, and programmed by mass culture, such a perspective is more and more difficult to achieve. There are simply fewer areas of discontent and fewer remaining dissatisfactions in a society that delivers the goods and provides so many distractions.

234

NARRATING UTOPIA

The net result is that many forms of utopian expression surviving today seem vacuous and lacking in genuine utopian content. [pp.1645] With statements like this, it is hard to know where to begin: delivers the goods to whom? To the US prison population, one of the largest per capita in the world? To the inhabitants of its urban ghettoes? To the Third World? Were the Los Angeles riots in the aftermath of the Rodney King beating merely one of the fewer areas of discontent in a homogeneous society? Nevertheless, depressing though this, the revelation that it is possible to write an entire book on utopian literature and still ask whether we have not reached precisely the kind of well-being and happiness that those old utopian dreamers dreamt about (p.164) does suggest that the effectiveness of utopia in challenging the dominant ideology may be rather less than Moylan claims. In thus universalizing the experience peculiar only to his own class and culture, Ruppert betrays a parochialism which is, however, not unfamiliar in a utopian context: the world in which Ruppert imagines he lives is in fact not far removed from that of Bellamys Dr Leetea comfortable, middle-class reality whose norms are supposed to be universally shared. And while Moylan is not guilty of such crassness, his inflated assessment of the oppositional utility of the critical utopia is in some respects hardly less ahistorical than Rupperts suggestion that utopia may finally have arrived. Whereas Ruppert appears to believe that we have finally arrived at a state hardly distinguishable from Fukuyamas End of History, where utopian alternatives are redundant, Moylans exuberant claim that the critical utopia has at last overcome the irrelevance of its predecessors, and unlocked a range of entirely new oppositional strategies strikes an almost equally millennial note. What does seem to be the case is that even as utopian writing has resolved many of its narrative problems, it has lost some of its immediate relevance. In the face of the more extreme claims made for the importance of contemporary utopian writing, it is worth bearing in mind Kumars reminder that no recent utopia has succeeded in stimulating anything like as much public debate as did works such as Looking Backward or A Modern Utopia (Utopia, p.420). Kumar sees this as being due in part to formal considerations, arguing that the more limited appeal of works such as The Dispossessed is a direct result of its use of a science fiction format, rendering it difficult to break out of its specialized literary ghetto (p.420)and while this may be somewhat overstated, it offers a useful corrective to the tendency, fostered by the expanding study of science fiction in the academy, to overestimate the universality of its appeal. In addition, as

DREAMS OF FREEDOM

235

Levitas points out, the self-conscious, self-reflexive ambiguity of much recent utopian writing, for all its artistic and intellectual appeal is not merely exploratory and open, it is also disillusioned and unconfident The presentation of alternative futures, multiple possibilities and fragmented images of time reflects a lack of confidence about whether and how a better world can be reached. [Concept of Utopia, p.196] Perhaps as a result, the wave of new utopian writing, however exciting its implications, has proved to be a relatively short-lived phenomenon indeed, it might be argued that the expansion of the academic study of utopias during the last decade has been in inverse proportion to their continued production. At the same time, a more sober assessment of the role and significance of utopian writing need not necessarily entail a pessimistic view of its future, still less an acceptance of the complacent assumption that utopia is no longer necessary in the homogeneous and supposedly eternal world of late capitalism. What utopian writing is still capable of doing is highlighting the socially constructed, and hence potentially transformable character of existing reality, and also of providing images of the utopian momentglimpses of the almost infinite possibilities that are opened up at the moment of revolutionary social transformation. Such glimpses occur in real life, as well as imaginative literature: witness the testimony of observers of the early days of the Russian and Chinese Revolutions, such as John Reeds Ten Days That Shook the World, or William Hintons Fanshen or more recently the Portuguese Revolution where, in the immediate aftermath of the fall of Caetano, it was at least briefly possible to erect a sign in Lisbons central railway station reading We are trying to create a better societyplease help us by paying your fare and actually be taken seriously. Perhaps one of the continuing functions of utopian writing is to remind us that such moments need not be merely a thing of the past. What happens after such moments, of course, is often disillusioning: the past all too often resurfaces in an only slightly different guise. In the Soviet Union there soon emerged a leader as brutal and authoritarian as any Tsar; in China one as self-aggrandizing as any Emperor; while in Portugal there now exists a capitalist state little different from any other in Europe. Perhaps one of the functions of the study of utopia is to encourage reflection on the causes of this recurrent tendency of even the most hopeful social developments to collapse back into the semblance of the very thing to which they were opposed. For utopia, as we have seen, constantly reproduces featuresoften the most troubling and problematic ones both of its predecessors, and of the society to which it proposes an

236

NARRATING UTOPIA

alternative; it, too, repeatedly falls short of what it might be; in looking to the future, it all too often re-enacts the past. And yet at the same time, it is still capable of pointing the way, however hesitantly, toward something new. In looking at its failures, we may perhaps learn more about our own tendency to repeat the past, whether that tendency is rooted in personal psychology, our broader socialization, or simply the narratives in which we find ourselves taking part. To recognize a narrative is the first step toward deciding whether or not we wish to participate in it, and then looking for ways to be part of another storyand in this context utopia provides innumerable examples from which we may learn. While utopia may tell the same story over and over again, one of its lessons is that it does not always have to be repeated.

Notes
Preface
1. For a more detailed discussion of these questions, see Levitas (1997). 2. Reader-response criticism goes still further, suggesting that all utopian fiction canor even shouldbe read in such a way. Ruppert provides perhaps the most sustained example of this approach. 3. For a helpful discussion of the state of contemporary utopian studies, which includes a critique of Moylans concept of the critical utopia, see Levitas (1990), pp.156200. For Moylans response, see Moylan (1992), pp.8994.

Chapter 1. Introduction
1. See Morson pp.16475. Morson argues, in fact, that editorial decisions regarding the inclusion of this material as part of the text often reflect the editors assumptions as to the works nature: It appears that those who either view Utopia as an unambiguous endorsement of a particular ideology or regard the distinction between literary and tractarian works as unimportant tend to offer shorter versions than those who read it as an ironic, playful, and ambiguous literary work (p.166). 2. Suvin, Metamorphoses, pp.3762; also Morson, pp.702 and 1735, on the dangers of regarding utopian narrative as merely the literary mould into which utopian political theory is poured. 3. See for example Ruppert, who examines utopian fiction in the light of reader-response theory. More broadly, there is a growing body of criticism which seeks to re-read earlier utopian fiction in the light of more recent fictional practice, as exemplified by works such as Russ, The Female Man (1975), Delany, Triton (1976), or, more recently, Le Guin, Always Coming Home (1986). For a discussion of what he terms the critical utopia, see Moylan, Demand the Impossible. 4. Although see Morson, who suggests that utopian visions are designed, in short, not to be convincing, but to convince, i.e. that aesthetic success, rather than being an end in itself, nevertheless remains secondary to the persuasive intent. 5. The remark is attributed to Marx in Sorel, p.150. 6. Kumar likewise suggests that [a]s so often, the teacher came to be the enemy of the artist. Like Wells, Huxley grew impatient with purely literary form, and came to see the message as infinitely more important than the medium (Utopia, p.226). 7. See Levitas (1990), pp.3558 for a more extensive discussion of the views of Marx and Engels on utopianism; see also Geoghegan, pp.2234. Both Levitas (1990), pp.83105, and Geoghegan, pp.8797, also provide valuable discussions of the work of Ernst Bloch. See also Levitas (1997). 8. See Geoghegan, pp.98139 for an examination of how this insight has been developed by a range of more recent Marxist or neo-Marxist thinkers. See also Bammer, pp.4853.

238

NARRATING UTOPIA

9. See note 2, above. 10. For a discussion of the distinctions between various types of utopian fantasy, see Davis, pp.1241. For a discussion of the essential differences between millennial and utopian fantasy, see Olson. 11. Suvin argues that while science fiction is collaterally descended from utopia... if not a daughter, yet a niece of utopia (Metamorphoses, p.61), its subsequent expansion has led to an englobing of utopia (p.61). It is thus in retrospect that utopia can be seen as the sociopolitical subgenre of science fiction (p.61). For a spectacular misreading of this argument see Ruppert, who asserts that in extending the boundaries of utopia to include [italics mine] science fiction, Suvin is attempting to gain greater recognition and acceptance of the latter by associating it more closely with the utopian tradition. This is somewhat ironic since utopian literature is itself not highly regarded as literature, although it apparently has achieved greater recognition and regard than the science fiction texts Suvin is seeking to justify (p.39). This in a study published in 1986when the study of science fiction can hardly be said to have been in its infancy. 12. See also Levitas (1990), pp.934, for a more recent overview, in which she argues that working definitions of utopia, rather than resulting from the consistent application of identifiable criteria are in fact the outcome of habitual assumptions (p.11). 13. In his more recent (1997) discussion of the problematics of defining utopia, Suvin concedes that his earlier formula was perhaps too narrowly focused (p.135), and suggests that, for all his reservations concerning what he terms Ernst Blochs pan-utopianism (p.132), Blochs broader conception of the utopian as a category offers a way out of the definitional impasse. This discussion also provides an illuminating examination of the relation between the utopian text and its reader. 14. This would also appear to be Richard Gerbers position in Utopian Fantasy, where he appears to argue that the most successful utopian narratives are those which most closely approximate to the norms of the realist novel, and suggests that the evolution of utopian narrative is in fact towards the novel: The development towards the novel is part of the logical evolution of the myth-creating utopian imagination, which impatiently proceeds from the general idea to ever greater actualization (p.120). See Morson, pp.724 for a critique of this position. 15. Kumar takes a similar view of Le Guins The Dispossessed, which he suggests so qualified its optimism as to appear to many readers to be offering merely the material for contemplation, rather than endorsing a new order (Utopia, p.420). However, he also argues that its failure to fulfill the persuasive function of the traditional utopia is also a reflection of generic considerations: Presented in science fiction guise, it tended in any case to find it difficult to break out of its specialized literary ghetto (p.420). 16. For Ruppert, this process is evident even in a hostile reading, such as William Morriss response to Bellamys Looking Backward. Ruppert argues that [w]hat remains incomplete in Bellamys vision has been spelled out in great detail in William Morriss dialectical reading of Bellamys text Morriss critical response to Bellamy, in other words, attempted to complete Bellamys fragmented and inconclusive vision (pp.767). 17. Jameson, however, argues that the plot devices of traditional utopian

NOTES

239

narrative are in fact so perfunctory that the relative absence of plot and character creates a kind of estrangement effect, undermining the readers expectations, conditioned by more conventional fictional narrative, and jar[ring] the mind into some heightened but unconceptualizable consciousness of its own powers, functions, aims and structural limits (Islands and Trenches, p.11). See Bammer, pp.1521, for a critique of this position. 18. Such proposals for a radically reduced working day are a continuing feature of utopian speculationand not merely by authors of utopian fiction: witness, for example, August Bebels suggestion, in Woman Under Socialism (1879), that the working day might be reduced to two-and-a-half hours. 19. Les utopies apparaissent comme bien plus ralisables quon ne le croyait autrefois. Et nous nous trouvons actuellement devant une question bien autrement angoissante: Comment viter leur ralisation dfinitive? Les utopies sont ralisables. La vie marche vers les utopies. Et peut-tre un sicle nouveau commence-t-il, un sicle ou les intellectuels et la classe cultive reveront aux moyens dviter les utopies et de retourner une socit non utopique, moins parfaite et plus libre. Not the least interesting aspect of Berdiaeffs statement is its clear implication that utopian dreaming is essentially only the business of the cultivated literather than the lower orders who might actually benefit from the transformation of the existing order. 20. Other examples include L.P. Hartleys Facial Justice, Kurt Vonneguts Player Piano, Anthony Burgesss A Clockwork Orange, and Ira Levins (admittedly rather derivative) This Perfect Daywhile dystopian futures are a staple feature of modern science fiction. Kumar, however, argues that more recent dystopian writing suffers from the same malaise that he detects in utopian writing: Antiutopia shares in the fate of utopia. As utopia loses it [sic] vitality, so too does anti-utopia (Utopia, p.422). He also suggests that No anti-utopia since Nineteen Eighty-Four has truly captured the popular imagination or become the centre of public debate (p.422). 21. See for example Lefanu, pp.13046. Also Khouri, pp.4960. 22. See Jameson, The Political Unconscious, in which he argues that a study of the ideology of form serves not merely to reveal the active presence within the text of a number of discontinuous and heterogeneous formal processes but makes it possible to grasp such formal processes as sedimented content in their own right, as carrying ideological messages of their own, distinct from the ostensible or manifest content of the works (p.99). 23. To counteract the impression of total conformity, some writers (William Morris, H.G. Wells in A Modern Utopia) do include a token dissenter, but it is fair to say that this transparently schematic device seldom creates the impression of there being any genuine debate in utopia. 24. See for example Morson, pp.14655; also Ruppert, pp.12330. 25. A comparable utopian prevision of humanity transformed by radical changes in social organization may be found in Trotskys Literature and Revolution, where he suggests that Social construction and psycho-physical self-education will become two aspects of one and the same process Man will become immeasurably stronger, wiser and subtler; his body will become more harmonized, his movements more rhythmic, his voice more musical. The forms of life will become dynamically dramatic. The average human type will rise to the heights of an Aristotle, a Goethe, or a Marx. And above this ridge new peaks will rise (p.256).

240

NARRATING UTOPIA

26. Bloch argues that the bourgeois imagination, while much given to dreams, still rations them, even in more distant excursions to the over-blue coast of the travel agents and beyond: so that they do not explode the given world. People with wishes of this kind live beyond their own means, but never beyond the generally existing means (Principle of Hope, p.34).This, of course, becomes less of a problem for writers whose utopian fictions are conceived of within the generic conventions of Science FictionRuss and Delany being cases in point.

Chapter 2. The Utopian Dream of Order


1. Frye argues, in fact, that utopian romance does not present society as governed by reason; it presents it as governed by ritual habit, or prescribed social behavior, which is explained rationally (Varieties, p.27). 2. Yates, Giordano Bruno and the Hermetic Tradition, p.119. 3. See Yates (Bruno, pp.2059); also McNulty, pp.3005. 4. See Webster, pp.631. 5. The publication in 1989 of the long-missing Letter to the Sovereigns announcing the Discovery has made this clearly apparent: through the divine grace of Him who is the origin of all good and virtuous things, who favours and gives victory to all those who walk in His path, in seven years from today I will be able to pay Your Highnesses for five thousand cavalry and fifty thousand foot soldiers for the war and conquest of Jerusalem, for which purpose this enterprise was undertaken (Zamora, p.7). See Zamora for a translation of the letter, and a discussion of its implications. 6. Columbuss theories as to the location of the earthly paradise are contained in his account of his third voyage. See Jane, Volume 2, pp.2838. 7. See A.E. Morgan, Nowhere Was Somewhere. 8. Vespuccis were by no means the only discovery narratives whose authenticity was questioned: Walter Raleghs The Discoverie of the large, rich, and beautifull Empire of Guiana (1596) was published in part to refute accusations that, far from exploring Guiana, he had hidden in Cornewall (p.273), and that the gold samples he brought back had in fact been purchased in Barbary (p.278). 9. So vague is Mores description, indeed, that one otherwise perceptive critic locates Utopia somewhere in the South Atlantic (Kumar, Utopia, p.71)! 10. For a more detailed discussion of the search for the earthly paradise and its implications, see Bloch (Principle of Hope, pp.77281); also Sanford, pp.3645. Vespucci also declared that if the terrestrial paradise be in any part of this earth, I esteem that it is not far distant from these parts (Letters, p.48), although this is in a letter widely held to be spurious. 11. The text of this letter, and the following one cited, are translated by Robert Adams, and are included in his edition of Utopiaalthough their textual status is rendered somewhat equivocal by their being separated from what is labelled The Text of Utopia, and included instead in an appendix which also contains selections from earlier writers and subsequent critical discussions. 12. In actual fact, this view is attributed to Simon Magus by a hostile critic, St Hippolytus, in The Refutation of all Heresies. See Manuel and Manuel, p.43. 13. See Bakhtin, Rabelais, p.11. 14. See The Principle of Hope, pp.5177. Bloch argues that conscious dreams,

NOTES

241

whatever their unconscious basis, are all dreams of a better life. No doubt there are among them base, dubious, dismal, merely enervating escapist dreams full of substitution, as is well-known. This kind of escape from reality has often been combined with approval and support of the status quo; as is revealed most strongly in the empty promises of a better hereafter. But how many other wishful daydreams have sustained men with courage and hope, not by looking away from the real, but, on the contrary, by looking into its progress, into its horizon. How many have reaffirmed their refusal to renounce, in the course of anticipation, of venturing beyond and its images. The amount of venturing beyond that takes place in daydreams thus indicates nothing repressed, even psychologically, nothing that has simply sunk down out of consciousness that already existed, nor any atavistic state which was simply left over from or breaks out of primeval man. The venturer beyond does not occupy a shaft in the ground beneath existing consciousness, with a single exit either into the familiar daylight world of today, as in Freud, or into a romanticized diluvium, as in C.G. Jung and Klages. What hovers ahead of the self-extension drive forwards is rather a Not-Yet Conscious, one that has never been conscious and has never existed in the past, therefore itself a forward dawning, into the New (pp.767). 15. Kolodny provides an extensive examination of this aspect of the discovery narrative. For more recent discussions, see Parker, pp.12654, and Montrose. 16. For a detailed discussion of the gender implications of the narratives of Ralegh and Keymis, see Montrose. 17. For an extended critique of the assumptions underlying such essentialist views of what constitutes the feminine, see Thrmer-Rohr. 18. Bammer argues that utopian fantasies in fact reinscribe a whole range of the inequities to which utopia purports to offer an alternative: as we look more closely at the visions of supposedly ideal worlds from Platos Republic to contemporary science fictions, we find that hierarchies of class and caste and inequalities of race and gender are everywhere reinstated. Indeed many of the most virulent prejudices of the time and place in which a given utopia was written are likely to reappear, alive and flourishing, in the new world that purports to present an alternative (p.19). Yet while this is undoubtedly true of some utopias (existing class prejudices, for example, are strongly evident in the utopias of Bellamy and Wells), it is by no means true of all of them. What this study argues is that existing gender hierarchies and assumptions regarding gender relations are far more consistently reproduced (at any rate, in maleauthored utopias) than any of the other inequalities to which Bammer refers. 19. There are clear parallels here with Raleghs later Discoverie, in which he represents the indigenous inhabitants of the lands bordering on Guiana as desperately eager for English rule, given that only the English appear able to defeat the hated Spaniardsalthough in order to sustain this eagerness, whether real or imagined, Ralegh is at pains to conceal that Spaniards and English alike came both for one errant, and that both sought but to sacke & spoile them (p.335). 20. In Montroses view, the renaming process exemplifies an emergent colonialist discourse that works to justify and, symbolically, to effect the expropriation of what it discovers. Typically, this discourse denies the natural right of possession to indigenous peoples by confirming them to be heathens,

242

NARRATING UTOPIA

savages, and/or foragers who neither cultivate the land nor conceptualize it as real property; or it may symbolically efface the very existence of those indigenous peoples from the places its speakers intend to exploit (p.184). 21. J.C. Davis, however, cites a number of authorities who argue that The New Atlantis was in fact left by Bacon in the form in which he had intended its publication. See Davis, pp.1214. 22. See Gilison, p.24. 23. See Yates, Bruno, p.375. 24. See Morley, p.vi. As Richard Stites points out in his edition of Bogdanovs Red Star, this is by no means the only such expurgation: a recent Soviet edition of Bogdanovs novel saw fit to omit Leonids ruminations on marriage and sex (p.9). 25. This is only one of a number of details that suggests the influence of Diodorus Siculuss account of the Isles of the Blessed, written in the second century BC, which Cohn describes as typical of the kind of egalitarian phantasy which the ancient world was to bequeath to the Middle Ages (p.189), and which was repeatedly translated during the Renaissance. It too depicts a society of sun-worshippersthe Heliopolitans, among whom private property, marriage, and the family are all unknown, and whose lifespan is a hundred and fifty years. 26. This claim is echoed, some three hundred years later, by H.G. Wells, in a lecture entitled The Discovery of the Future, in which he declares: In the past century there was more change in the conditions of human life than there had been in the previous thousand years (quoted in Kumar, Utopia, p.173). See also Kumar, p.437 for a discussion of the possible sources of this remark. 27. See Kumar, Utopia, pp.2936. While Kumar suggests that The New Atlantis provided the model of the dynamic utopia which was at the same time feltat least by his followersto be a realizable project (p.34), he also points to the problematic character of the link between science and utopia: the dynamism of science was bound to press against the finished, perfect order of utopia (p.30). 28. Despite its explicitly Christian character, Kumar, rather oddly, describes The New Atlantis as of all the seventeenth-century utopias the one least obviously indebted to Christian conceptions (Utopia, p.19), although he does go on to point out that the House of Saloman is modelled fairly clearly on the monastery (p.19).

Chapter 3. Bellamy and Wells


1. Frye, for instance, argues that because technology is progressive, getting to the utopia has tended increasingly to be a journey in time rather than space, a vision of the future and not of a society located in some isolated spot on the globe (or outside it (Varieties, p.28). Moylan, similarly, suggests that in late nineteenth-century utopias, subversive visions were relocated in a future time when the process of revolutionary, historical change brought about the utopian society. At this point in the development of the genre, history more directly entered the texts, and utopian novels more regularly provided accounts of the required transition from the present to utopia (Demand the Impossible, p.6). Yet in fact, with the honourable exception of Morriss News from Nowhere,

NOTES

243

it is striking how seldom such transitions are described in anything other than the most perfunctory detail: the evasion of the connection with existing society remains a recurrent feature of utopian narrative until well into the twentieth century. 2. In fact, this narrative device first appears as early as 1771, in LouisSebastien Merciers LAn 2440, which Clarke describes as the first influential story of the future in world literature (p.23). 3. Leacock farcically restages the scene where Julian West is taken to a rooftop by Dr Leete and shown a vista of the utopian Boston of the future: Great Heavens! Was this the city I had known! Whither had gone the tall skyscrapers reaching to the clouds? Where was the long reach of the wide Hudson, the vast suspension bridge hung like an aerial web from shore to shore? Where was it all gone, or how had it changed to this? I turned to Dr. Oom, who stood beside me, quietly smiling at my evident and utter astonishment. Can this, I said, pointing to the vision around me, can this be New York? New York? said Oom, no, of course not. This is London. The exhilaration which had kindled in his face died out of it. In fact he looked rather crestfallen What made you think it New York? Why, I fell asleep in New York, I said. I believe thats right, said Dr. Oom, reflecting, you did, very likely. There was a sort of patriotic exchange of hundred-year sleepers between England and America and you must have come over in that lot. In fact, now I think of it, you did. (p.13). 4. For a more extensive discussion of Bellamys influence, see Bowman. 5. While this is one of the most universally criticized features of Bellamys utopia, Bellamy was hardly alone in proposing such solutions. See for example Trotskys argument, in Terrorism and Communism, that the militarization of labour was essential to solve the economic problems facing the new Soviet Unionat least on a temporary basisalthough he was at the same time careful to distinguish between the structures of Soviet-style military organization and those of conventional armies (pp.13357). 6. Bleich suggests, rather unkindly, that the otherwise pacific Bellamys preoccupation with such militaristic analogies might be rooted in his youthful failure to gain admission to West Point (p.52). 7. Kumar suggests a different parallel, arguing that the structure of Bellamys utopian society comes very close to the actual Saint-Simonian proposal of a triumvirate of industrialists, scientists, and artists as the directing agency of the socialist society. As with Saint-Simon, the specific organization of the free professions introduces a much-needed liberal and pluralist element in an otherwise highly co-ordinated and integrated structure based on industry (Utopia, p.158). 8. See for example Jean Pfaelzer, Immanence, p.53. 9. As Kumar remarks, Such a rgime of sexual apartheid might please some of the radical feminists of today. But it can scarcely satisfy socialists, and seems to owe more to Bellamys Victorian patriarchalism than to any anticipation of feminine separatism (Utopia, p.164). 10. Morson points out that such apocalyptic imagery is a recurrent feature in Looking Backward (p.121). In a subsequent discussion with Dr Leete, Julian West suggests that this is indeed the new heavens and the new earth wherein dwelleth righteousness, which the prophet foretold (p.112)a view which he is informed is shared by a number of the citizens of the future, including,

244

NARRATING UTOPIA

it would appear, the preacher towards the end of the book, who declares that in the world of AD 2000 For the first time since the creation every man stood up straight before God (p.159). 11. The comment actually occurs in a letter to William D. Howells, written 17 June 1888. 12. See Milton Cantor, The Backward Look of Bellamys Socialism in Patai (Looking Backward, pp.2136) for a discussion of this aspect of Bellamys utopia. See also Kumar, pp.15863. 13. A further gap between what is described and what is dramatized becomes apparent when one considers that, as Kumar observes: Julian never meets anyone outside the nuclear family circle of Dr Leete, nor is anyone else even mentioned as a neighbour, colleague or friend (Utopia, p.164). This despite the fact that a whole range of communal social structures have been created which render the role of the family in many respects redundant. 14. Not the least remarkable feature of this curious love-scene is the extent to which it reaffirms the narrators passivity. Far from having to win Ediths love, he arrives in utopia to find that she is already in love with himalthough she is at the same time anxious to forestall any thoughts he might have that she was over quick to fall in love After you know who I am, you will be found to confess that it was nothing less than my duty to fall in love with you at first sight, and that no girl of proper feeling in my place could do otherwise (p.167). 15. A radically different reading of Bellamys text is offered by Rosemont, who sees the romance between Julian West and Edith Leete as centrally important, rather than merely novelistic window-dressing: Looking Backward is, among other things, a love story, telling of a love that conquers, symbolically at least, not only time but death itself. This marvellous erotic triumph exemplifies another essential feature of Bellamys revolutionary project: the supersession of time (p.150). This must rank as one of the rare occasions when the imaginative powers of the critic outstrip those of the author under discussion. See also Pfaelzer, who argues that the representation of Julian West has the richness, intimation, and ambiguity of the symbolic, and it is through the heros developing consciousness that we adhere to the latent potential for a redeemed society within industrial capitalism (Immanence, p.56). 16. Some of Bellamys fiction none the less remains of interest in a utopian context. Given the ambiguous relation of utopia to its own past, it is worth noting that in his novel Dr Heidenhoffs Process (1880) Bellamy imagines a procedure whereby memory can be erased; while in his short story The Blindmans World (1898) he portrays a society in which precognition is the rule, memory the exception. 17. See for example Kumar, pp.190205, who argues that [t]he attractiveness and originality of the form is undoubtedly one reason for the books popularity and success. Unlike most utopias [it] evokes a vision as much as, and perhaps rather more than, it proclaims a programme (p.190). For a discussion of A Modern Utopia as meta-utopia, see Morson, pp.14655. See also Ruppert, pp.12330, who discusses the work in the light of reader-response theory. 18. See note 19, below. 19. In his Experiment in Autobiography Wells declares that while his thinking

NOTES

245

has run very close to communist lines my conception of a scientifically organized classless society is essentially of an expanded middle-class which has incorporated both the aristocrat and plutocrat above and the peasant, proletarian and pauper below (Volume 1, p.94). 20. The naturalizing of class distinctions by giving them a biological, rather than social basis is a recurrent feature in Wellss fictionmost glaringly in The Time Machine (1895), where the aristocracy have degenerated into the effete Eloi, and the working class into the subhuman Morlocks. In this scenario, the vigorous and resourceful Time Traveller is able to fulfill a range of middle-class fantasies by sleeping with a representative of the former, and massacring the latter in large numbers. 21. Frye regards Wellss fourfold division of humanity as particularly uncharitable considering that the only essential doctrine in Wellss utopian religion is the rejection of original sin. Wellss writing in general illustrates the common principle that the belief that man is by nature good does not lead to a very good-natured view of man (p.35). Hence, perhaps, Wellss insistence on the need to transform humanitys biological nature; despite his rejection of the doctrine of original sin, he continues to assume the existence of innate flaws which need to be bred out, as opposed to being modified by social conditioning. 22. As if to underscore the Edenic quality of the world into which the narrator awakens, when he does discover his discarded revolver, it is described, rather curiously, as a blue-black thing, like a dead snake at my feet (p.155). 23. Cf. 1 Corinthians 15:20. But now is Christ risen from the dead, and become the first fruits of them that slept. Here Wells echoes a passage descriptive of the Resurrection, and the final and irrevocable establishment of the authority of the Father. 24. Certainly both Campanella and Bacon imagine the possibility of scientific inventions extending human mastery over nature, but in neither case does the possibility really influence the character of the utopian society they imaginewhereas in Wellss utopias the possibility is vividly dramatized. Wells, however, does refer approvingly to the dynamic character of The New Atlantis, and on one occasion asserted that the Utopia of Bacons [sic] has produced more in the way of real consequences than any other Utopia that was ever written (quoted in Kumar, Utopia, p.198). 25. See Kumar, Utopia, pp.23042, however, for a discussion of the wildly ambitious speculations of contemporary scientists such as J.B.S Haldane and J.D. Bernal, who envisaged a future in which the human physique would be radically transformed (a possibility already considered by Wells in works such as The Man of the Year Million (1893) and The War of the Worlds (1898)), and where energy would be provided by the transformation of the stars into efficient heat engines (quoted in Kumar, p.234). Wellss vision of the extent of the possible transformation of nature by human agency is also rivalled by Bogdanov, in his descriptions of the colossal engineering projects of the Martians in Red Star and Engineer Menni, and even surpassed by Trotsky, whose Literature and Revolution (published the year after Men Like Gods) looks forward to a future in which the present distribution of mountains and rivers, of fields, of meadows, of steppes, of forests, and of seashores, cannot be considered final (p.251), and where Man will learn how to move rivers and mountains, how to build peoples palaces on the peaks of Mont Blanc and at the bottom

246

NARRATING UTOPIA

of the Atlantic (p.254). 26. The narrator continues: From now onward, of course, the fates of these two planets will diverge, men will die whom wisdom will save there, and perhaps conversely here we shall save men; children will be born to them and not to us, to us and not to them, but this, this moment of reading, is the starting moment, and for the first and last occasion the populations of our planets are abreast (pp.245). There is, however, no explanation of how this is to be reconciled with the radically different human history that Wells goes on to imagine. 27. Utopia, of course, is hardly the only form of radical expression to be thus co-opted: witness the use of Bob Dylans 1960s protest song The Times They Are A-Changing in a recent Bank of Montreal TV commercial, or the Vodafone ads featuring models wearing clothes, and striking poses, clearly borrowed from Soviet revolutionary postersall in the cause of celebrating the freedom provided by a cellular phone. 28. Ralegh, for example, in his Discoverie, uses as an important argument for his proposed colonization of Guiana the fact that Her Majestie may in this enterprize employ all those souldiers and gentlemen that are younger brethren, and all captaines and chieftaines that want employment, and the charge will be onely the first setting out in victualling and arming them (p.349). 29. Even where less than a global utopia is imagined, colonialist aspirations still resurface: witness Skinners Walden Two, which at first sight appears to propose the relatively modest possibility of the establishment of a single utopian community. Later on, however, we discover that in addition to Walden Two, there are also Waldens Three, Four, Five, and Sixand that Walden Twos founder imagines the possibility of their growing and subdividing once every two years. Then in ten years Waldens Two and Six will give birth to some sixtyodd communities In thirty years we could absorb the whole country many times over (p.228).

Chapter 4. Dystopia
1. See Blitzer, pp.34. 2. These include Conrad Wilbrandt, Mr Easts Experiences in Mr Bellamys World (1891), and J.W. Roberts, Looking Within (1893). Like Vintons Looking Further Backward, they offer farcical visions of what Bellamys future would really be like: Wilbrandt imagines a world where chronic inefficiency, combined with overspending induced by the use of credit cards, obliges everyone to work until the age of 65; Roberts envisages a society where uniformity has gone so far that everyone actually looks the same, wearing specially moulded masks. 3. Examples of such narratives include Sir George Chesney, The Battle of Dorking (1871), Sir William Butler, The Invasion of England (1882), William Le Queux, The Great War in England in 1897 (1894), M.P. Shiel, The Yellow Danger (1898). 4. Such scenes appear in the concluding sections of Looking Backward, News from Nowhere, A Modern Utopia, and Walden Twoto name but a few. 5. It has often been suggested that this family resemblance is in fact a reflection of the dystopian genres debt to Zamyatin. Ruppert, for instance, declares that We has achieved the status of an exemplary work whose influence

NOTES

247

can be seen in numerous imitations: Huxleys Brave New World, Orwells Nineteen Eighty-Four, Goldings Lord of the Flies and many others (p.105). However, there are a number of problems with this. While Nineteen EightyFour is clearly indebted to the example of We (in places almost to the point of plagiarism), Huxley explicitly denied ever having read it (Collins, p.351), and, as Kumar argues, such resemblances as exist between Brave New World and We can readily be explained by their common acquaintance with Wellss utopias (Utopia, pp.225, 462), and their both using the Legend of the Grand Inquisitor from The Brothers Karamazov as inspiration for the set piece debate between the rebels and authority (pp.1223). In addition, the extent of Zamyatins own originality is open to question: as Stites points out, N. Fedorov published a science fiction novel in 1906, entitled An Evening in the Year 2217, which features numbered citizens, monstrous conformity, abolition of marriage and family, sex by appointment, and a lifeless socialist urban milieu of glass and stone a virtual prototype for Zamyatins We (p.5). 6. As Morson points out, the scene in which the ruler acknowledges the falsehood to a rebel who has detected it (p.126) is a recurrent feature in dystopian fiction, and one which parodies those numerous utopian exchanges in which the delineator reveals the truth. The climax of these dystopias, in other words, is the Revelation of the Lie (p.126). As Kumar points out, however, such scenes are less parodies of utopia, than reworkings of Dostoevsky (p.122). 7. This is the transliteration used in Guerneys translation; in other translations the character often appears as I-330. 8. While Fords production line is the most obvious inspiration for Huxleys fantasy of a world whose citizens are both mentally and physically moulded to fit the needs of the State, Kumar points out that another possible model is Wellss The First Men in the Moon, with its portrait of the ant-like civilization of the Selenites anticipating in detail the purported anti-Wellsian critique of Brave New World (Utopia, p.178). 9. Fiderer comments on a number of aspects of this scene: its emphasis on the erotic quality of the creamy paper, the immaturity of the scrawl with which he covers it, the almost deliberate courting of disaster by leaving the book openall of which he sees as lending credence to his thesis that the novel is in part a masochistic fantasy of erotic submission to the power of a superior male, all leading up to the climactic admission that He loved Big Brother. 10. While it may be hard to see the use of make-up as particularly subversive, it is worth bearing in mind that in the utopian context of Campanellas The City of the Sun using cosmetics is a capital offence. 11. For Adorno, it is this opposition that constitutes Brave New Worlds major weakness: The crude alternative of objective meaning and subjective happiness, conceived as mutually exclusive, is the philosophical basis for the reactionary character of the novel (p.112). 12. The extent to which dystopian fiction is inherently reactionary remains the subject of debate. Jameson argues, for example, that Utopia is a transparent synonym for socialism itself, and the enemies of Utopia sooner or later turn out to be the enemies of socialism (Islands and Trenches, p.3). Ruppert, on the other hand, suggests that The enemy of both utopia and anti-utopia is the status quo, which both seek to transform (p.104), and that anti-utopias compel the reader to the same dialogue, to the attempt to answer the same

248

NARRATING UTOPIA

questions inspired by utopias (p.103). This is, however, difficult to reconcile with his later claim that anti-utopias are also inherently reductive, leaving us with a single menacing vision of society, a vision, moreover, which may have the unproductive effect of affirming the status quo (p.122). 13. Atwood argues that in the case of Nineteen Eighty-Four the States apparent triumph is undermined by the concluding Appendix (The Principles of Newspeak): he ended it with the note on Newspeak, which is written in the past tense in standard English which means that he didnt think Nineteen-Eighty-Four was going to last forever. And you rarely see that point made, except by me (quoted in Alaton, C1). 14. Zamyatin is more sceptical than Huxley or Orwell in this regard: witness his assertion all truths are mistaken; the dialectical process is precisely that todays truths become tomorrows errors; there is no last number (quoted in Morson, p.120)although he elsewhere suggests that stasis might be reached by a process equivalent to entropy.Revolution is everywhere, in everything. It is infinite. There is no final revolution, no final number It is a cosmic, universal law, like the laws of conservation of energy and of the dissipation of energy (entropy) When the flaming, seething sphere (in science, religion, social life, art) cools, the fiery magma becomes coated with dogmaa rigid, ossified, motionless crust. Dogmatization in science, religion, social life, or art is the entropy of thought. What has become dogma no longer burns; it only gives off warmthit is tepid, it is cool (A Soviet Heretic, pp.1078). In any event, We is unlike Brave New World and Nineteen Eighty-Four in representing the rebellion as continuing. 15. See Alaton, where Atwood acknowledges that this is partly influenced by her reading of Nineteen Eight-Four, as indicated in note 13, above.

Chapter 5. Libertarian Alternatives


1. For a fuller account of Morriss reaction to Looking Backward, see Meier, Volume 1, pp.7393. 2. Morriss review of Looking Backward appeared in The Commonweal, 22 June 1889. It is reprinted in May Morris, Volume 2, pp.5017. 3. While it seems clear that Morris, having undertaken the demolition of Looking Backward in his review, intended News from Nowhere as an alternative vision of utopian possibility, Ruppert argues that Morris, in his response to Bellamy, attempted to complete Bellamys fragmented and inconclusive vision; Morris tried to reveal the exclusions that a dialectical reading of Bellamys text uncovers and intensifies (pp.767). This view of the text as completed by the reader is a recurrent feature of Rupperts application of readerresponse theory to utopian narrative (rather as though reader and text come together to form the seamless monad which traditional utopian narrative can only aspire to create). However, to see Morris as trying to complete Bellamys visionas opposed to blasting it off the face of the earthseems somewhat extraordinary. 4. There are, however, important differences between their readings of Morris; indeed, in the second, revised edition of his work on Morris, Thompson is sharply critical of Meiers representation of Morris as an orthodox Marxist. For Thompson, Morriss utopianism has its roots as much in the Romantic critique of capitalism as in Marxist theory, and has as its goal the education

NOTES

249

of desire (p.791), rather than a literal depiction of what a future Communist state would look like. Levitas provides a useful overview of this debate, situating it in the broader context of Marxist discussions of the relationship between Marxism and utopianism (Concept of Utopia, pp.10630). 5. Letter to Karl Kautsky, 22 June 1884. quoted in Meier, Volume 1, p.230. 6. Letter to Frederick Sorge, 29 April 1886. quoted in Meier, Volume 1, p.234. 7. For a critique of this view of News from Nowhere, see Buick, p.20. 8. Blochs own attitude to what he termed Morriss Gothic socialism (Principle of Hope, p.551) was by no means unsympathetic. While he describes News from Nowhere as a backward-looking utopia reminiscent of the longings at the time of the Restoration, of the Romantic infatuation with the Middle Ages and the wish to see it approaching again from the future (p.614), he also concedes that the conservative political brief which the Romantics had over a hundred years before is missing Morris backward utopia was not intended in a politically reactionary way. It wanted progress from the standpoint of an abandoned position, agrarian-artisan reaction for the sake of a revolutionary new beginning (pp.61415). 9. See for example Wilding, p.90. 10. Beilharz, for instance, describes News from Nowhere as an idyll anticipating Wind in the Willows [sic] (p.5). 11. Kumar argues that News from Nowhere might be read more as a powerful indictment of a large-scale mechanical civilization than as a utopian portrait of a future society. It would be more akin, that is, to something like Rousseaus Discourse on the Origin of Inequality, with its similar ambivalence between a primitivist utopian and an anti-utopian critique of the writers own society (Utopia, pp.1267). He also draws attention to the influence on Morris of After London, a work whose depiction of savagery and brutality mark[s] it out clearly as an anti-utopia (p.127). 12. See for example Levitas, Concept of Utopia, pp.405, 10630. 13. For a differing view of the relation of News from Nowhere to After London see Suvin, Metamorphoses pp.18793. While acknowledging Morriss debt to Jefferies, Suvin argues that News from Nowhere in fact charts a third way between the visions of Looking Backward and After London, transcending the opposition between Bellamys ethicoreligious pacification and Jefferiess politicogeological devolution (Metamorphoses, p.188). 14. Despite the wholesale demolition, a few exceptions are made: for example, the British Museum is preserved, on the grounds that it is not a bad thing to have some record of what our forefathers thought a handsome buildingalthough at the same time many people have wanted to pull it down and rebuild it (p.43). In fact, bearing in mind Morriss own tastes, its survival is most probably due to its being a repository of all kinds of antiquities, besides an enormous library with many exceedingly beautiful books in it (p.43). 15. It is largely on the basis of this absence of sociopolitical organization (Metamorphoses, p.182) that Suvin denies News from Nowhere the formal status of a utopia. 16. When asked his age, the narrator describes himself as hard on fiftysix (p.14)which was Morriss own age when News from Nowhere began appearing in serial form in The Commonweal in January 1890.

250

NARRATING UTOPIA

17. The differences of opinion between Lenin and Bogdanov were both philosophical and tactical. It was shortly after the publication of Red Star, in fact, that Lenin produced the extended polemic, Materialism and EmpirioCriticism (1908), in which he denounced what he saw as the pernicious revisionism of Bogdanov and others, whom he accused of lapsing (among other things) into Berkeleian idealism. In addition, Lenin disagreed with Bogdanov over the latters insistence that a successful armed insurrection remained a realistic possibility in the aftermath of 1905. Both Jensen and Stites provide useful background on the political context for the composition of Red Star; for a discussion of the philosophical differences between Bogdanov and Lenin, see Ballestrem (although the latters bias may be deduced from his description of Materialism and Empirio-Criticism as a philosophical catastrophe (p.283)). 18. A good deal more information is provided in Bogdanovs next novel Engineer Menni (1913), which deals with the period of the Great Project, the building of the Martian canals some time prior to the Martian revolution, centering on the father/son conflict between Menni, the great capitalist engineer who conceives the project, and Netti (who this time really is a man), the committed unionist who succeeds him. 19. While for the most part Bogdanov sees art as reflecting the changing economic and political circumstances of the society that produces it, there is one point where Bogdanov tries to hold up traditional artistic conventions as natural, rather than socially constructed. When Leonid expresses surprise that Martian poetry still uses strict meter and rhyme, asserting that it is commonly thought among us that such form was generated by the tastes of the ruling classes of our society, and that it reflects their fastidiousness and predilection for conventions which restrict the freedom of artistic expression (p.78), he is firmly corrected: Nothing could be further from the truth Regular rhythmicality seems beautiful to us not at all because of any liking for conventions, but because it is in profound harmony with the rhythmical regularity of our processes of life and thought. As for rhyme, which resolves a series of dissimilarities in uniform final chords, it is intimately related to that vital bond between people which crowns their inherent diversity with the unity of the delights of love, the unity that comes from a rational goal in work, and the unity of feeling in a work of art. Without rhythm there is no artistic form at all (p.78). 20. Bogdanov was not only an economist, philosopher, novelist, and revolutionary: he was also a physician, and a pioneer of theat that time imperfectly understood process of blood transfusion. He in fact died as the result of an experiment in which he exchanged blood with a patient desperately ill with malaria and tuberculosis (Graham, p.252). 21. Sterni argues that the uneven development of different nation states means that in some it is possible that the cause of socialism will be frustrated for decades (p.113). In such an event the individual advanced countries in which socialism triumphs will be like islands in a hostile capitalist and even to some extent precapitalist sea. Anxious about their own power, the upper classes of the nonsocialist countries will continue to concentrate all their efforts on destroying these islands. They will constantly be organizing military expeditions against them, and from among the ranks of the former large and small property-holders in the socialist nations themselves they will be able to find plenty of allies willing to commit treason. It is difficult to foresee the

NOTES

251

outcome of these conflicts, but even in those instances where socialism prevails and triumphs, its character will be perverted deeply and for a long time to come by years of encirclement, unavoidable terror and militarism, and the barbarian patriotism that is their inevitable consequence. This socialism will be a far cry from our own (pp.11314). 22. Kermode, for example, remarks that The soma which was once anathematized as a cheap escape from the ardours of reality is now essential to social health (p.472); see also Birnbaum: A freedom induced by a drug extracted from mushrooms seems hardly different from the euphoria induced by soma in Brave New World (p.174). In fact, even the most cursory comparison of Brave New World and Island reveals that the two drugs have dramatically different effects. For a discussion of Huxleys views on, and use of psychedelic drugs, see Ferns (pp.193212). 23. Huxley describes Marias death in a letter to Humphry Osmond, 21 February, 1955 (Letters, pp.7347). Not only is the process of hypnotic suggestion described in Island almost identical to that used during Marias final days, but some of Dr Roberts words to Lakshmi are taken verbatim from Huxleys own. 24. William Morris, it should be said, was in no doubt as to the gap between Georges position and that of the anarchists. It was Georges disowning of the Chicago anarchists, four of whom were executed on trumped-up charges, that prompted him to write in The Commonweal: Henry George approves of this murder; do not let anybody waste many words to qualify this wretchs conduct. One word will include all the restTRAITOR!! (quoted in Thompson, 1955, p.593) 25. For a more detailed discussion of Huxleys shortcomings as a political thinker, see Ferns, pp.2354; a more sympathetic account of Huxleys political views is provided by Firchow, pp.77116.

Chapter 6. A World of Ones Own


1. Wittig, Les Guerillres (1969); Russ, The Female Man (1975); Charnas, Motherlines (1978). 2. For a more detailed discussion of the parallels between Herland and Gullivers Travels, see Keyser, who argues that Herland can more profitably be read as a satire than as a utopia per se. 3. While it is argued here that the utopian narrative paradigm itself is at the root of the more problematic features of Gilmans narrative, other critics have seen these as having more specifically ideological causes. Mary Hill, for example, argues that some of Herlands shortcomings stem in part from the influence on Gilman of Bellamys Nationalist Movement: like most Nationalists [Gilman] was more effective in describing conditions which deprive human life of dignity and meaning than she was in projecting viable solutions (p.173). 4. In an illuminating discussion of the historical context from which Herland emerges Bammer argues that this is characteristic, not only of Herland, but of a number of womens utopias written in America during the preceding century (pp.2847); she also suggests that the dangerously romanticizing adulation of woman as the embodiment of virtue and goodness (p.35) is one of the chief weaknesses of the mainstream feminism of the period.

252

NARRATING UTOPIA

5. See also Thrmer-Rohr, pp.13252, for a critique of idealized conceptions of an essential femininity. As she points out: [t]hose qualities ascribed to femaleness, the fantasy images of women, display astonishing consistency over a hundred and fifty years. This is not without its comic side, if you can still find any of this comical. The extraordinary nature of the feminine, which is situated beyond the masculine order of progress, exploitation, and expansion in a disorderly realm devoid of developmental logic, is still celebrated for its creatively liberating qualities : emotionality, sensuality, surrender, imagination, sensibility, receptivity, empathy, harmony, patience, gentleness, understanding, and above all the capacity to love, to sacrifice, and to be selfless (pp.1345). 6. Gilman is by no means alone in attaching such exaggerated importance to a gentlemans word of honour. Bellamy, in fact, (whose work Gilman much admired) goes still further: in Looking Backward, Dr Leete informs his visitor from the nineteenth century that the world has outgrown lying (p.153); when the latter expresses surprise, he then goes on to make the astonishing claim that Falsehood, even in your day, was not common between gentlemen and ladies, social equals Because we are now social equals the contempt of falsehood is so universal that it is rarely that even a criminal in other respects will be found willing to lie (p.153). 7. Still more curious, perhaps, is the fact that it is Terryof all people who gives the country its name: Herland is represented as his invention, not that of the inhabitants (whose name for their country we never learn). In more ways than one, Gilmans utopia is reliant on the word of a gentleman. 8. A more logical (not to mention more disturbing) exploration of these options is provided in James Tiptrees Houston, Houston, Do You Read? 9. See for example Ann J. Lanes discussion of the issue in her introduction to Herland (pp.xviixviii). For a different perspective, see Mary Jo Deegans introduction to With Her in Ourland (pp.157). 10. They prove more prevalent, regrettably, in Gilmans sequel, With Her in Ourland (1916), which contains an analysis of anti-semitism almost as antisemitic as the views it analyses, as well as fears of Americas racial contamination by crowding injections of alien blood, by vast hordes of lowgrade laborers (p.106). Deegan, however, argues that these represent a few (and it really is only a few) ethnocentric lapses (p.6), which are balanced by Gilmans denunciation of Western colonialism and theories of racial superiority elsewhere in the book. 11. The possibility of dialogue is still further diminished by the fact that (with the partial exception of the gentles) men are incapable of the telepathy which constitutes the Hill Womens main mode of communication. 12. Whether a reality external to language is even possible, let alone desirable, is another question. For a valuable critique of the concept of a prediscursive reality, and in particular its association with notions of the maternal as a category prior to the institution of a patriarchal culture, see Butler. 13. This seems to present problems for some male readers of the work. To respond objectively (that is, if one assumes an objective response to utopian fiction to be possible, or even desirable) is clearly more difficult for readers who find themselves identified as belonging to a different speciesand, possibly as a result, male critical accounts of Gearharts utopia often leave a good deal to be desired. Kingsley Widmer, for example, although styling himself

NOTES

253

a feminist fellow traveller, dismisses the work as mere coterie writing, an assertion backed up by out-of-context quotation and a derisive summary which at points descends into mere abuse (pp.624). 14. While The Wanderground is by no means alone in drawing the analogy between women and the colonized, Bammer argues that Gearharts literalminded equation of colonialism with patriarchy, and her unproblematic identification of women with the land constitute a disturbingly dehistoricized appropriation of the colonial critique (p.85)based, among other things, on the construction of woman as victim, free of complicity in the historical process which has led to the nightmare from which the Hill Women seek to escape. 15. For a more detailed discussion of the problems inherent in Gearharts attempt to imagine a reality outside the patriarchal structures of existing language, see Bammer, pp.7992: while Gearhart realizes that in order to write she must position herself within language; simply put, she must use words The Wanderground discursively counters its own premise that woman can be written outside of culture by reinscribing her within it (pp.912). 16. For a forceful critique of the belief in womens freedom from complicity with the structures of patriarchy, see Thrmer-Rohr, pp.3963. 17. Such disjunctive binarism, Butler argues, paradoxically, institutes precisely the relation of radical dependency it seeks to overcome: Lesbianism would then require heterosexuality. Lesbianism that defines itself in radical exclusion from heterosexuality deprives itself of the capacity to resignify the very heterosexual constructs by which it is partially and inevitably constituted. As a result, that lesbian strategy would consolidate compulsory heterosexuality in its oppressive forms (p.128). Rather than troubling (to use Butlers term) straight societys structures of gender relations, Gearharts fantasy of their disappearance ultimately leaves them intact.

Chapter 7. Dreams of Freedom


1. Lefanu takes a different view of this, describing Piercys utopian discourse as vivid, racy, and economical; in particular, she suggests that it is remarkable how quickly, as a reader, one becomes accustomed to its lack of gendered pronouns and begins to enjoy this (p.63). 2. They are disappointing: perhaps the quality of the ingredients is better in utopia. 3. Khouri argues that Le Guins Taoist-based philosophy embodies a stasis incompatible with the rendering of a genuinely dialectical process. Although by the end of the novel the contradictions inherent in the societies of both Urras and Anarres (and indeed the relations between them) seem on the brink of producing far-reaching transformations in each, this is discounted, as is also the case in Lefanus discussion of the work: At the end of The Dispossessed differences are resolved without conflict or change (p.142). Khouri also criticizes Le Guin for being forced to resort to a contrived and non-functional endinga deus ex machinathe incarnation of the authors narrative superego in the form of the unexpected appearance of the Hainish at the end of the novel (p.53). (The Hainish are the galaxys oldest known human civilization; a Hainish cosmonaut elects to accompany Shevek on his return to Anarres.) It is difficult to reconcile this assertion with anything the text actually contains. For a more perceptive discussion of the relation between Le Guins Taoism and

254

NARRATING UTOPIA

the dialectical process, see Suvin, Parables, pp.26574; see also Blochs more general discussion of the relationship between Taoist philosophy and dialectic in Principle of Hope, pp.122530. 4. See Moylan, Demand the Impossible, pp.91120; also Delany, Jewel-Hinged Jaw, pp.239308. Delanys critique is in many respects a persuasive one, although he sometimes appears to get carried away by his polemic intent, as for example when he compares the narrative structure of The Dispossessed to that of Edgar Rice Burroughs Tarzan novels! 5. See Moylan, pp.10910; Lefanu, p.141; Delany passim. While Delany, as suggested above, makes a plausible case in this regard, the same can hardly be said of Lefanu, whose assertion that homosexuality is tolerated as adolescent experimentation but nothing more (p.141) is certainly not borne out by the text. In fact, when Shevek and Bedap renew the homosexual relations they had briefly engaged in during adolescence they discuss the matter first, recognizing that adult sexuality is a more complicated affair (Dispossessed, p.139). 6. Lefanu goes furthest in this regard, denouncing Le Guin for her failure to provide any positive portrayals of women other than Poor old Takver, the token strong woman, [who] keeps the home fires burning while Shevek is off changing the future of mankind (Presumably the fact that Anarres was the product of a revolution led by a woman does not count.) Takver, a marine biologist who engages in the apparently unforgivable sin of child care, seems to cause Lefanu particular irritation. Elsewhere she refers to her simply as Takver. Oh dear, Takver (p.133). 7. For an opposing view, see Fekete, pp.12943. 8. Although The Dispossessed was published in 1974, Le Guins critique is strongly reminiscent of that of the student activists of the late 1960s. Shevek, we learn, was appalled by the examination system, when it was explained to him; he could not imagine a greater deterrent to the natural wish to learn than this pattern of cramming information and disgorging it at demand. At first he refused to give any tests or grades, but this upset the University administrators so badly that, not wishing to be discourteous to his hosts, he gave in. He asked his students to write a paper on any problem in physics that interested them, and told them that he would give them all the highest mark, so that the bureaucrats would have something to write on their forms and lists. To his surprise a good many students came to him to complain. They wanted him to set the problems, to ask the right questions; they did not want to think about questions, but to write down the answers they had learned. And some of them objected strongly to his giving everyone the same mark. How could the diligent students be distinguished from the dull ones? What was the good in working hard? If no competitive distinctions were to be made, one might as well do nothing. Well, of course, Shevek said, troubled. If you do not want to do the work, you should not do it (p.103). 9. Le Guins representation of the consequences of the mass emigration of the revolutionary elements in Urrasti society echo Marxs concerns, as expressed in Citizen Cabets Plea for Emigration, published in La Revue Communiste 1 (1858): If those honest people who struggle for a better future leave, they will leave the arena completely open to the obscurantists and the rogues. Europe would certainly fall. Europe is that part of the world where communal wealth can be put forward first and most easily, simply for statistical

NOTES

255

and economic reasons. Instead, fire and brimstone will descend upon suffering humanity for centuries to come (quoted in Marin, pp.2719). 10. Leaving aside the fact that permanent revolution is precisely what The Dispossessed is about, Feketes clear preference for Delanys comforting fiction that such a society can be achieved through continuing technological progress may itself be seen as reflecting certain prevailing ideological assumptions which were already being questioned in the late 1970s. Two decades later, his dismissal of the problems flowing out of scarcity and having to do with distributive justice as less interesting than those posed by the notion of a post-scarcity society (leaving aside its irrelevance to anyone outside the more well-to-do lite of advanced capitalist societies) is beginning to seem more than a little dated. 11. Roemers experience is hardly an uncommon one. In my own classes I have sometimes conducted a similar exercise, based on the folk-tale, The Three Wishes, which Bloch cites as a paradigm of the problematics of utopian desire. As an imaginative exercise, the students were asked to suppose their instructor temporarily gifted with magical powers capable of granting any three wishes they might haveonly provided that they were able to write them down within the space of three minutes. Although a number of students came up with honourable abstractions such as World Peace, or such clearly desirable goals as A Cure for Cancer, what was striking was the poverty of their personal visions, which would often take the shape of the desire to marry my boyfriend, get an A on the course, or even get a job at Mount Saint Vincent University. Perhaps the closest to the banality which Roemer records was the student who wished for a sports-carit was only a Mazdaalthough even this outstrips the student whose capacity for utopian desire was limited to the acquisition of a forest-green Jetta.

Bibliography
Adams, Percy G. Travel Literature and the Evolution of the Novel. Lexington: University of Kentucky Press, 1983. Adorno, Theodor W. Prisms. Trans. Samuel and Shierry Weber. London: Neville Spearman, 1967. Alaton, Salem. A Tale in the Making. The Globe and Mail. 13 May 1989. C1. Albinski, Nan Bowman. Womens Utopias in British and American Fiction. London: Routledge, 1988. Armitt, Lucie, ed. Where No Man Has Gone Before: Women and Science Fiction. London: Routledge, 1991. Atwood, Margaret. The Handmaids Tale. Toronto: Seal Books, 1986. . Life Before Man. Toronto: Seal, 1979. Bacon, Francis. The Philosophical Works of Francis Bacon, Ed. J.M. Robertson. London: Routledge, 1905. Bakhtin, M.M. The Dialogic Imagination. Ed. Michael Holquist. Trans. Caryl Emerson and Michael Holquist. Austin: University of Texas Press, 1981. . Problems of Dostoevskys Poetics. Ed. and Trans. Caryl Emerson. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1984. . Rabelais and His World. Trans. Hlne Iswolsky. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1984. and P.N. Medvedev. The Formal Method in Literary Scholarship. Trans. Albert J. Wehrle. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1991. Ballestrem, Karl G. Lenin and Bogdanov. Studies in Soviet Thought 9.4 (1969), pp.283310. Bammer, Angelika. Partial Visions: Feminism and Utopianism in the 1970s. London: Routledge, 1991. Barr, Marlene S. Ed. Future Females: A Critical Anthology. Bowling Green: Bowling Green State University Press, 1981. . Alien to Femininity: Speculative Fiction and Feminist Theory. Westport: Greenwood, 1987. Barthes, Roland. Sade, Fourier, Loyola. New York: Hill and Wang, 1976. Bartkowski, Frances. Feminist Utopias. Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1989. Baruch, Elaine Hoffman. A Natural and Necessary Monster: Women in Utopia. Alternative Futures 2.1 (1979), pp.2949. Baxandall, Lee and Stephan Morowski, Eds. Marx and Engels on Literature and Art. New York: International General, 1974. Beilharz, Peter. Labours Utopias: Bolshevism, Fabianism, Social Democracy. London: Routledge, 1992. Bellamy, Edward. Looking Backward 20001887. New York: Bantam, 1983. Benjamin, Walter. Illuminations. New York: Harcourt, 1968. Bennett, Tony. Formalism and Marxism. London: Methuen, 1979. Bergonzi, Bernard. The Early H.G. Wells. Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1961. Berneri, Marie Louise. Journey Through Utopia. New York: Schocken, 1971.

BIBLIOGRAPHY

257

Bierman, Judah. Ambiguity in Utopia: The Dispossessed. Science Fiction Studies 7 (1975), pp.24956. . Science and Society in the New Atlantis and other Renaissance Utopias. PMLA 78.4.1 (1963), pp.492500. Birnbaum, Milton. Aldous Huxleys Quest for Values. Knoxville: University of Tennessee Press, 1971. Bleich, David. Utopia: the Psychology of a Cultural Fantasy. Ann Arbor: UMI Research Press, 1984. Blitzer, Charles. An Immortal Commonwealth: The Political Thought of James Harrington. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1960. Bloch, Ernst. The Principle of Hope. 3 vols. Trans. Neville Plaice, Stephen Plaice, and Paul Knight. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1986. . The Utopian Function of Art and Literature. Trans. Jack Zipes and Frank Mecklenburg. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1988. Bogdanov, Alexander. Red Star: The First Bolshevik Utopia. Ed. Loren Graham and Richard Stites. Trans. Charles Rougle. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1984. Bonansea, Bernardino. Tomasso Campanella: Renaissance Pioneer of Modern Thought. Washington: Catholic University of America Press, 1969. Booker, M. Keith. The Dystopian Impulse in Modern Literature: Fiction as Social Criticism. Westport: Greenwood, 1994. . Dystopian Literature: A Theory and Research Guide. Westport: Greenwood, 1994. Booth, Wayne C. Yes, But Are They Really Novels? Yale Review 51 (1962), pp.6301. Borges, Jorge Luis. Death and the Compass. Labyrinths. Ed. Donald A. Yates and James E. Irby. New York: New Directions, 1964, pp.7687. Bowman, Sylvia E. Edward Bellamy Abroad: An American Prophets Influence. New York: Twayne, 1962. Buick, Adam. William Morris and incomplete Communism: a critique of Paul Meiers thesis. Journal of the William Morris Society 3.2 (1976), pp.1632. Butler, Judith. Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Identity. New York: Routledge, 1990. Callenbach, Ernest. Ecotopia. Berkeley: Banyan Tree, 1975. Callinicos, Alex. Against Postmodernism: A Marxist Critique. Cambridge: Polity, 1989. . Theories and Narratives: Reflections on the Philosophy of History. Cambridge. Polity, 1995. Campanella, Tomasso. The City of the Sun: A Poetical Dialogue. Trans. Daniel J. Donno. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1981. Charnas, Suzy McKee. Motherlines. New York: Berkley, 1979. Chilton, Paul and Crispin Aubrey, Eds. Nineteen Eighty-Four in 1984: Autonomy, Control and Communication. London: Comedia, 1983. Clarke, I.F. The Pattern of Expectation 16642001. New York: Basic, 1979. Cohn, Norman. The Pursuit of the Millennium: Revolutionary Millenarians and Mystical Anarchists of the Middle Ages. London: Paladin, 1970. Columbus, Christopher. The Journal of Christopher Columbus. Trans. Cecil Jane. London: Anthony Blond, 1960. Cranny-Francis, Anne. Feminist Fiction: Feminist Uses of Generic Fiction. New York: St Martins, 1990.

258

NARRATING UTOPIA

Daniel, Jamie Owen and Tom Moylan, Eds. Not Yet: Reconsidering Ernst Bloch. London: Verso, 1997. Davis, J.C. Utopia and the Ideal Society. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981. De Bolt, Joseph. Ed. Ursula Le Guin: Voyager to Inner Lands and to Outer Space. Port Washington: Kennikat, 1978. de Certeau, Michel. The Writing of History. Trans. Tom Conley. New York: Columbia University Press, 1988. Delany, Samuel R. The Jewel-Hinged Jaw: Notes on the Language of Science Fiction. Elizabethtown: Dragon, 1977. . Triton. New York: Bantam, 1976. Delbanco, Andrew. Introduction. Looking Backward. By Edward Bellamy. New York: Bantam, 1983, pp.ixxix. Deutscher, Isaac. Russia in Transition. New York: Grove, 1960. Donawerth, Jane L. And Carol A. Kolmerten. Eds. Utopian and Science Fiction by Women. Syracuse: Syracuse University Press, 1994. Eagleton, Terry. Criticism and Ideology. London: New Left Books, 1976. . Ideology: An Introduction. London: Verso, 1991. . The Illusions of Postmodernism. Oxford: Blackwell, 1996. Elliott, R.C. The Shape of Utopia: Studies in a Literary Genre. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970. Eliade, Mircea. Paradise and Utopia: Mythical Geography and Eschatology. Utopias and Utopian Thought. Ed. Frank E. Manuel. Boston: Beacon, 1967, pp.26080. Eliav-Feldon, Miriam. Realistic Utopias. Oxford: Clarendon, 1982. Engels, Friedrich. Herr Eugen Duhrings Revolution in Science. Chicago: Charles H. Kerr, 1935. Fekete, John. The Dispossessed and Triton: Act and System in Utopian Science Fiction. Science-Fiction Studies 18 (1979), pp.12943. Ferns, C.S. Aldous Huxley: Novelist. London: Athlone, 1980. Fiderer, Gerald. Masochism as Literary Strategy: Orwells Psychological Novels. Literature and Psychology 20 (1970), pp.321. Firchow, Peter. The End of Utopia: A Study of Aldous Huxleys Brave New World. Lewisburg: Bucknell University Press, 1984. Firestone, Shulamith. The Dialectic of Sex: The Case for Feminist Revolution. New York: Bantam, 1970. Fitting, Peter. Impulse or Genre or Neither? Science-Fiction Studies 66 (1995), pp.27281. Fisher, Judith L. Trouble in Paradise: The Twentieth-Century Utopian Ideal. Extrapolation 24. 4 (1983), pp.32939. Foucault, Michel. The Archaeology of Knowledge. London: Tavistock, 1972. . The History of Sexuality. New York: Pantheon, 1978. Frye, Northrop. Anatomy of Criticism. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1957. . Varieties of Literary Utopias. Utopias and Utopian Thought. Ed. Frank E. Manuel. Boston: Beacon, 1967, pp.26080. Fukuyama, Francis. The End of History and the Last Man. New York: Free Press, 1992. Garvey, Brian. The Utopian Imagination. Science-Fiction Studies 45 (1988), pp.2445.

BIBLIOGRAPHY

259

Gearhart, Sally Miller. The Wanderground. Boston: Alyson, 1984. Geoghegan, Vincent. Utopianism and Marxism. London: Methuen, 1987. Gerber, Richard. Utopian Fantasy: A Study of English Utopian Fiction Since the End of the Nineteenth Century. London: Routledge, 1955. Gilison, Jerome M. The Soviet Image of Utopia. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1975. Gilman, Charlotte Perkins. The Charlotte Perkins Gilman Reader. Ed. Ann J. Lane. London: The Womens Press, 1981. . Herland. London: The Womens Press, 1979. . With Her in Ourland: Sequel to Herland. Ed. Mary Jo Deegan and Michael R. Hill. Westport: Praeger, 1997. Glasier, J. Bruce. William Morris and the Early Days of the Socialist Movement. London: Longmans, 1921. Goodwin, Barbara and Keith Taylor. The Politics of Utopia: a Study in Theory and Practice. New York: St Martins, 1982. Gove, Philip B. The Imaginary Voyage in Prose Fiction. London: Holland, 1961. Graham, Loren R. Bogdanovs Inner Message. Red Star: The First Bolshevik Utopia. By Alexander Bogdanov. Ed. Loren Graham and Richard Stites. Trans. Charles Rougle. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1984, pp.24153. Gramsci, Antonio. Selections from the Prison Notebooks. New York: International, 1971. Greenblatt, Stephen. Marvelous Possessions: The Wonder of the New World. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1991. Gubar, Susan. She in Herland: Feminism as Fantasy. Charlotte Perkins Gilman: The Woman and Her Work. Ed. Sheryl L. Meyering. Ann Arbor: UMI Research Press, 1989, pp.191202. Helgerson, Richard. Forms of Nationhood: The Elizabethan Writing of England. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992. Hertzler, Joyce Oramel. The History of Utopian Thought. New York: Macmillan, 1923. Hexter, J.H. The Vision of Politics on the Eve of the Reformation. New York: Basic, 1973. Hill, Eugene D. The Place of the Future: Louis Marin and his Utopiques. ScienceFiction Studies 27 (1982), pp.16779. Hill, Mary A. Charlotte Perkins Gilman: The Making of a Radical Feminist. Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1980. Hillegas, Mark. The Future as Nightmare: H.G. Wells and the Anti-Utopians. Carbondale: University of Illinois Press, 1974. Hutcheon, Linda. The Politics of Postmodernism. London: Routledge, 1989. Huxley, Aldous. Brave New World. London: Granada, 1977. . Island. New York: Harper, 1972. . Letters of Aldous Huxley. Ed. Grover M. Smith. London: Chatto, 1969. Irigaray, Luce. This Sex Which is Not One. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1985. Jackson, Rosemary. Fantasy: The Literature of Subversion. London: Methuen, 1981. Jameson, Fredric. Marxism and Form: Twentieth Century Dialectical Theories of Literature. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1971. . Of Islands and Trenches: Neutralization and the Production of Utopian Discourse. Diacritics 7.2 (1977), pp.222.

260

NARRATING UTOPIA

. The Political Unconscious: Narrative as a Socially Symbolic Act. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1981. . Postmodernism, or, The Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism. London: Verso, 1991. . Progress Versus Utopia; Or, Can We Imagine the Future? ScienceFiction Studies 27 (1982), pp.14759. . World Reduction in Le Guin: The Emergence of Utopian Narrative. Science-Fiction Studies 7 (1975), pp.22131. Jane, Cecil. Ed. Select Documents Illustrating the Four Voyages of Columbus. 2 vols. London: Hakluyt Society, 1930, 1932. Jensen, K.M. Red Star: Bogdanov Builds a Utopia. Studies in Soviet Thought. 23.1 (1982), pp.134. Jones, Libby Falk and Sarah Webster Goodwin, Eds. Feminism, Utopia, and Narrative. Knoxville: University of Tennessee Press, 1990. Kalin, Martin G. Utopian Flight From Unhappiness: Freud Against Marx on Social Progress. Totoway: Littlefield, 1975. Kateb, George. Utopia and its Enemies. New York: Free Press, 1963. Kautsky, Karl. Thomas More and his Utopia. London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1979. Kermode, Frank. Fiction Chronicle. Partisan Review 29 (1962), pp.4723. Kessler, Carol Farley. Charlotte Perkins Gilman: Her Progress Toward Utopia, with Selected Writings. Syracuse: Syracuse University Press, 1995. . Daring to Dream: Utopian Fiction by United States Women Before 1950. Syracuse: Syracuse University Press, 1995. . Woman on the Edge of Time: A Novel To Be of Use. Extrapolation 28.4 (1987), pp.31018. Keulen, Margarete. Radical Imagination: Feminist Conceptions of the Future in Ursula Le Guin, Marge Piercy, and Sally Miller Gearhart. Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang, 1991. Keymis, Laurence. The second voyage of Guiana performed and written in the yeere 1596, by Laurence Keymis gentleman. The Principall Navigations of the English Nation. By Richard Hakluyt. Vol 7. London: Dent, 1907, pp.35893. Keyser, Elizabeth. Looking Backward: From Herland to Gullivers Travels. Critical Essays on Charlotte Perkins Gilman. Ed. Joanne B. Karpinski. New York: Hall, 1992, pp.15972. Khouri, Nadia. The Dialectics of Power: Utopia in the Science Fiction of Le Guin, Jeury, and Piercy. Science-Fiction Studies 20 (1980), pp.4961. Kolodny, Annette. The Lay of the Land: Metaphor as Experience and History in American Life and Letters. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1975. Kumar, Krishan. Utopia and Anti-Utopia in Modern Times. Oxford: Blackwell, 1987. . Utopianism. Milton Keynes: Open University Press, 1991. Lane, Ann J. Ed. The Charlotte Perkins Gilman Reader. London: Womens Press, 1981. . Introduction. Herland. By Charlotte Perkins Gilman. London: The Womens Press, 1979, pp.vxxiv. . To Herland and Beyond: The Life and Work of Charlotte Perkins Gilman. New York: Pantheon, 1990. Lasky, Melvin J. Utopia and Revolution. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1976.

BIBLIOGRAPHY

261

Leacock, Stephen. Afternoons in Utopia: Tales of the New Time. London: Bodley Head, 1932. Lefanu, Sarah. In the Chinks of the World Machine: Feminism and Science Fiction. London: Womens Press, 1988. Le Guin, Ursula K. Always Coming Home. New York: Bantam, 1986. . The Dispossessed. New York: Avon, 1975. . The Language of the Night. London: Womens Press, 1989. Lem, Stanislaw. The Chain of Chance. Trans. Louis Iribarne. Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1981. Lenin, V.I. Materialism and Empirio-Criticism: Critical Comments on a Reactionary Philosophy. Moscow: Foreign Languages Publishing House, 1952. . What Is To Be Done? Peking: Foreign Languages Press, 1975. Levitas, Ruth. The Concept of Utopia. Syracuse: Syracuse University Press, 1990. . Educated Hope: Ernst Bloch on Abstract and Concrete Utopia. Not Yet: Reconsidering Ernst Bloch. Ed. Jamie Owen Daniel and Tom Moylan. London: Verso, 1997, pp.6579. Lukcs, Georg. History and Class Consciousness. Trans. Rodney Livingstone. London: Merlin, 1971. . The Theory of the Novel. London: Merlin, 1971. Macherey, Pierre. A Theory of Literary Production. Trans. Geoffrey Wall. London: Routledge, 1978. Mannheim, Karl. Ideology and Utopia: An Introduction to the Sociology of Knowledge. New York: Harcourt, 1936. Manuel, Frank E. Ed. Utopias and Utopian Thought. Boston: Beacon, 1966. ., and Fritzie P. Manuel. Utopian Thought in the Western World. Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap, 1979. Marcuse, Herbert. Eros and Civilization. Boston: Beacon, 1955. . Marxism and Feminism. Womens Studies 2, 3 (1974), pp.27989. . One-Dimensional Man. Boston: Beacon, 1964. Marin, Louis. Utopics: Spatial Play. Trans. Robert A. Vollrath. New Jersey: Humanities, 1986. McNulty, Robert. Bruno at Oxford. Renaissance News 13 (1960), pp.3005. Meier, Paul. William Morris: The Marxist Dreamer. Brighton: Harvester, 1978. Mellor. Anne K. On Feminist Utopias. Womens Studies 9 (1982), pp.24162. Meyering, Sheryl L. Ed. Charlotte Perkins Gilman: The Woman and Her Work. Ann Arbor: UMI Research Press, 1989. Montrose, Louis. The Work of Gender in the Discourse of Discovery. New World Encounters. Ed. Stephen Greenblatt. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993, pp.177217. More, Sir Thomas. Utopia. Ed. and Trans. Robert M. Adams. New York: Norton, 1975. Morgan, A.E. Nowhere Was Somewhere. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1946. Morris, May. William Morris: Artist, Writer, Socialist. 2 vols. New York: Russell & Russell, 1966. Morris, William. News from Nowhere. Ed. James Redmond. London: Routledge, 1970. Morley, Henry. Ed. Ideal Commonwealths. London: Routledge, 1885. Morson, Gary Saul. The Boundaries of Genre: Dostoevskys Diary of a Writer and the Traditions of Literary Utopia. Austin: University of Texas Press, 1981.

262

NARRATING UTOPIA

Morton, A.L. The English Utopia. London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1952. Moylan, Tom. Demand the Impossible: Science Fiction and the Utopian Imagination. London; Methuen: 1986. . Utopian Studies: Sharpening the Debate. Science-Fiction Studies 19 (1992), pp.8994. Negley, Glenn. Utopian Literature: A Bibliography. Lawrence: Regents Press of Kansas, 1977. Norris, Christopher. The Truth About Postmodernism. Oxford: Blackwell, 1993. Olander, Joseph D. And Martin Greenberg. Ursula K. Le Guin. New York: Taplinger, 1979. Olson, Theodore. Millennialism, utopianism, and progress. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1982. Orwell, George. Nineteen Eighty-Four. Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1983. . The Collected Essays, Journalism and Letters of George Orwell (4 vols). Ed. Sonia Orwell and Ian Angus. Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1970. Parker, Patricia. Literary Fat Ladies: Rhetoric, Gender, Property. London: Methuen, 1987. Parrinder, Patrick. Imagining the Future: Zamyatin and Wells. Science-Fiction Studies 1 (1973), pp.3741. Patai, Daphne. Ed. Looking Backward, 1988-1888: Essays on Edward Bellamy. Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1988. . The Orwell Mystique: A Study in Male Ideology. Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1984. Pfaelzer, Jean. Immanence, Indeterminance, and the Utopian Pun in Looking Backward. Looking Backward, 19881888: Essays on Edward Bellamy. Ed. Daphne Patai. Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1988, pp.5167. . Parody and Satire in American Dystopian Fiction of the Nineteenth Century. Science-Fiction Studies 7 (1980), pp.6171. . A State of Ones Own: Feminism as Ideology in American Utopias, 1880-1915. Extrapolation 24 (1983), pp.31128. . The Utopian Novel in America 18861896: The Politics of Form. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, 1984. Piercy, Marge. Woman on the Edge of Time. London: Womens Press, 1979. Rabkin, Eric. The Fantastic in Literature. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1976. ., Martin H. Greenberg and Joseph D. Olander. No Place Else: Explorations in Utopian and Dystopian Fiction. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1983. Ralegh, Sir Walter. The Discoverie of the large, rich, and beautifull Empire of Guiana, with a relation of the great and golden citie of Manoa (which the Spaniards call El Dorado) Performed in the yeere 1595 by Sir Walter Ralegh. The Principall Navigations of the English Nation. By Richard Hakluyt. Volume 7. London: Dent, 1907, pp.272350. Roemer, Kenneth M. The Obsolete Necessity: America in Utopian Writings, 18881900. Kent: Kent State University Press, 1976. . Prescription for Readers (and Writers) of Utopias. Science-Fiction Studies 44 (1988), pp.8893. . Utopian Literature, Empowering Students, and Gender Awareness. Science-Fiction Studies 23 (1996), pp.393405.

BIBLIOGRAPHY

263

Rosemont, Franklin. Bellamys Radicalism Reclaimed. Looking Backward, 19881888: Essays on Edward Bellamy. Ed. Daphne Patai. Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1988, pp.147209. Rosinsky, Natalie. Feminist Futures: Contemporary Womens Speculative Fiction. Ann Arbor: UMI Research Press, 1984. Rowbotham, Sheila, Lynne Segal and Hilary Wainwright. Beyond the Fragments. London: Merlin, 1979. Ruppert, Peter. Reader in a Strange Land: The Activity of Reading Literary Utopias. Athens: University of Georgia Press, 1986. Russ, Joanna. The Female Man. New York: Bantam, 1975. . To Write Like a Woman: Essays in Feminism and Science-Fiction. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1995. Sanford, Charles L. The Quest for Paradise: Europe and the American Moral Imagination. Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1961. Sargent, Lyman Tower. British and American Utopian Literature, 15161985: An Annotated Chronological Bibliography. New York: Garland, 1988. Scholes, Robert. Structural Fabulation: An Essay on the Fiction of the Future. South Bend: Notre Dame University Press, 1975. ., and Eric Rabkin. Science Fiction: History, Science, Vision. New York: Oxford University Press, 1977. Skinner, B.F. Walden Two. New York: Macmillan, 1962. Somay, Bulent. Towards an Open-Ended Utopia. Science-Fiction Studies 32 (1984), pp.2538. Sorel, Georges. Reflections on Violence. Trans. T.E. Hulme. New York: Peter Smith, 1941. Stites, Richard. Fantasy and Revolution: Alexander Bogdanov and the Origins of Bolshevik Science Fiction. Red Star: The First Bolshevik Utopia. By Alexander Bogdanov. Ed. Loren Graham and Richard Stites. Trans. Charles Rougle. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1984, pp.116. Suvin, Darko. Locus, Horizon, and Orientation: The Concept of Possible Worlds as a Key to Utopian Studies. Not Yet: Reconsidering Ernst Bloch. Ed. Jamie Owen Daniel and Tom Moylan. London: Verso, 1997, pp.12237. . Metamorphoses of Science Fiction. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1979. . Parables of De-Alienation: Le Guins Widdershins Dance. ScienceFiction Studies 7 (1975), pp.26574. . Positions and Presuppositions in Science Fiction. London: Macmillan, 1988. Thompson, E.P. The Poverty of Theory and Other Essays. New York: Monthly Review, 1978. . William Morris: Romantic to Revolutionary. London: Merlin, 1977. Thrmer-Rohr, Christina. Vagabonding: Feminist Thinking Cut Loose. Trans. Lise Weil. Boston: Beacon, 1991. Tiptree Jr., James. Houston, Houston, Do You Read? Star Songs of an Old Primate. New York: Ballantine, 1978, pp.164226. Trotsky, Leon. Literature and Revolution. New York: Russell & Russell, 1957. . Terrorism and Communism. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1961. Unamuno, Miguel de. The Tragic Sense of Life. New York: Dover, 1954. Vespucci, Amerigo. The First Four Voyages of Amerigo Vespucci. London: Bernard Quaritch, 1893.

264

NARRATING UTOPIA

. The Letters of Amerigo Vespucci. Ed. Clements R. Markham. London; Hakluyt Society, 1894. Volosinov, V.N. Freudianism: A Marxist Critique. Trans. I.R. Titunik. New York: Academic, 1976. . Marxism and the Philosophy of Language. Trans. Ladislav Matejka and I.R. Titunik. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1986. Walker, D.P. Spiritual and Demonic Magic From Ficino to Campanella. London: Warburg Institute, 1958. Walsh, Chad. From Utopia to Nightmare. Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1964. Webb, Sidney. Socialism in England. London: Swan Sonnenschein, 1890. Webster, Charles. The Great Instauration. London: Duckworth, 1975. Wells, H.G. Experiment in Autobiography. 2 vols. London: Cape, 1969. . In the Days of the Comet. London: Hogarth, 1985. . Men Like Gods. Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1987. . A Modern Utopia. Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1967. . The Time Machine. New York: Bantam, 1976. Widmer, Kingsley. Counterings: Utopian Dialectics in Contemporary Contexts. Ann Arbor: UMI Research Press, 1988. Wilding, Michael. Political Fictions. London: Routledge, 1980. Williams, Raymond. Culture and Society. Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1958. . The Long Revolution. Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1975. . Marxism and Literature. London: Oxford University Press, 1977. . Problems in Materialism and Culture. London: Verso, 1980. . Utopia and Science Fiction. Science-Fiction Studies 16 (1978), pp.20314. Winstanley, Gerrard. The Law of Freedom and Other Writings. Ed. Christopher Hill. Harmondsworth: Pelican, 1973. Wytenbroek, J.R. Always Coming Home: Pacifism and Anarchy in Le Guins Latest Utopia. Extrapolation 28.4 (1987), pp.3309. Yates, Frances. Giordano Bruno and the Hermetic Tradition. London: Routledge, 1964. . The Rosicrucian Enlightenment. London: Routledge, 1972. Zamora, Margarita. Christopher Columbuss Letter to the Sovereigns: Announcing the Discovery. New World Encounters. Ed. Stephen Greenblatt. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993. 111. Zamyatin, Yevgeny. A Soviet Heretic: Essays by Yevgeny Zamyatin. Ed. and Trans. Mirra Ginsburg. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970. . We. Trans. Bernard Guilbert Guerney. Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1983.
v

Index
Adams, Robert, 38, 240n Adorno, Theodor, 117, 125, 247n anarchism, 1445, 2189, 251n Aristotle, 105, 239n Aronowitz, Stanley, 233 Atwood, Margaret, 105, 1113, 248n The Handmaids Tale, 15, 17, 1145, 130138, 141, 176 Life Before Man, 133 Aubrey, Crispin, 108 Bacon, Francis, 2, 4, 15, 24, 36, 38, 46, 5051, 64, 71, 82, 101, 151, 172, 177, 202 New Atlantis, xi, 32, 49, 50, 5963, 164, 170, 176, 179, 192, 196, 221, 242n, 245n Bakhtin, Mikhail, 21, 24, 66, 110, 135, 230, 240n Balfour, Arthur, 89 Ballestrem, Karl G., 250n Bammer, Angelika, x, 8, 9, 13, 24, 41, 45, 78, 87, 100, 129, 186, 1956, 197, 200, 205, 231, 237n, 239n, 241n, 251n, 253n Barthes, Roland, 25, 135 Beard, Charles, 74 Beaverbrook, Lord, 89 Bebel, August, 239n Beilharz, Peter, 70, 249 Bellamy, Edward, xii, 6, 56, 66, 6887, 902, 1001, 103, 1056, 109, 120, 141, 148, 149, 160, 170, 176, 183, 185, 189, 220, 251n Dr Heidenhoffs Process, 244n Looking Backward, 3, 11, 15, 20, 21, 26, 69, 7487, 90, 97, 99, 1426, 151, 1557, 173, 179, 194, 199200, 203, 234, 239n, 243n, 244n, 246n, 248n, 252n Berdiaeff, Nicolas, 15, 239n Bergonzi, Bernard, 6 Bernal, J.D., 245n Bierman, Judah, 59 de Biran, Maine, 119, 125 Birnbaum, Milton, 251n Bloch, Ernst, x, 1, 4, 7, 16, 25, 43, 47, 61, 64, 146, 151, 175, 198, 237n, 239n, 2401n, 249n Bleich, David, 5, 243n Bogdanov, Alexander, 192 Engineer Menni, 245n, 250n Red Star, xii, 141, 154163, 174, 200, 202, 242n, 245n, 250n, Bonansea, Bernardino, 50 Booth, Wayne C., 9 Borges, Jorge Luis, 18 Bowman, Sylvia E., 81, 243n Bruno, Giordano, 35 Buick, Adam, 249n Burgess, Anthony, 239n Burroughs, Edgar Rice, 254n Butler, Judith, 252n, 253n Butler, William, 246n Busleyden, Jerome, 40 Cabral, Amlcar, 218 Caetano, Marcelo, 235 Callenbach, Ernest Ecotopia, 2, 13 Campanella, Tomasso, 14, 16, 19, 36, 38, 46, 61, 635, 689, 71, 77, 83, 99, 101, 113, 144, 183, 1989, 206, 208, 245n The City of the Sun, xi, 2, 3, 4, 23, 24, 32, 49, 5060, 64, 79, 92, 171, 188, 194, 202, 247n Cantor, Milton, 244n capitalism, 7, 18, 67, 745, 80, 83, 108, 112, 124, 148, 152, 168, 198, 223, 225, 2301, 233, 244n, 249n, 255n Catherine of Genoa, 173 de Certeau, Michel, 49 Charnas, Suzy McKee, 176, 251n Chesney, George, 246n Chilton, Paul, 108 chronotope, 212, 27, 65, 151, 214, 228 Churchill, Winston, 89, 96 classical dialogue, 13, 16, 234, 656, 101 colonization, 12, 479, 58, 1023,

266

NARRATING UTOPIA
1034, 1301, 159 60, 1623, 1725, 178, 1867, 199201, 205, 2201, 241n, 252n Geoghegan, Vincent, 7, 237n George, Henry, 163, 168, 251n Giles, Peter, 39, 40 Gilison, Jerome M. , 37, 242n Gilman, Charlotte Perkins, xii, 1934, 199 Herland, 2, 11, 70, 176191, 2001, 204, 222, 225, 251n, 252n With Her in Ourland, 252n Glasier, Bruce, 143 Goebbels, Josef, 197 Goethe, Johann Wolfgang von, 239n Golding, William , 247n Goldman, Emma, 219 Goodman, Paul, 219 Goodwin, Barbara, 13 Gramsci, Antonio, 233 Greenblatt, Stephen, 489 Gubar, Susan, 187 Haggard, H. Rider, 180 Haldane, J.B.S., 245n Hall, Stuart, 1356 Halliday, Thomas, 56 Hansel and Gretel, (folktale), 1745 Harrington, James, 105 Oceana, 25 Hartley, L.P, 239n Hermes Trismegistus, 35 Hexter, J.H., 46 Hill, Mary, 251n Hinton, William, 235 Hitler, Adolf, 165 Homer, 25 Horrebow, Niels, 150 How the Man Minded the House (folktale), 1734 Huxley, Aldous, xii, 11, 24, 1056, 1767, 194, 219, 237n, 248n Brave New World, 5, 14, 15, 22, 109121, 124130, 1412, 1635, 1678, 247n, 251n Island, 2, 6, 9, 13, 16, 20, 26, 70, 1412, 163174, 202, 209, 215, 224 Huxley, Maria, 166, 251n James, William, 119, 125 Jameson, Fredric, 19, 24, 71, 74, 2389n, 2478n Jefferies, Richard, 148, 249n

149, 1613, 2412n, 246n, 252n, 253n Columbus, Christopher, 36, 38, 44, 45, 47, 49, 240n communism, 37, 50, 108, 1445, 147, 14950, 154, 156, 168, 198, 243n, 245n, 249n Copernicus, Nicolaus, 35, 51 critical utopia, x, 12, 14, 2035, 237n Davis, J.C., 59, 60, 238n, 242n Deegan, Mary Jo, 252n Delany, Samuel R., 2212, 240n, 255n The Jewel-Hinged Jaw, 254n Triton, 11, 12, 2046, 237n Delbanco, Andrew, 87 Deutscher, Isaac, 108 Dewey, John, 74 Diodorus Siculus, 242n discovery narratives, ix, 13, 16, 19, 23, 34, 3839, 445, 71, 73, 1002, 104, 161, 240n, 241n Dostoevsky, Fyodor, 247n Doyle, Arthur Conan , 18, 180 Dylan, Bob, 246n dystopia, xii, 1516, 22, 10538, 1634, 167, 176, 239n, 247n Eagleton, Terry, 2201 Eden, Garden of, 32, 413, 73, 97, 102, 1702, 178, 245n Engels, Friedrich, 5, 7, 148 fascism, 108, 168, 198 Fedorov, N., 247n Fekete, John, 229, 254n, 255n Ferns, Chris, 251n Ficino, Marcilio, 35 Fiderer, Gerald, 247n Firchow, Peter, 251n Foucault, Michel, 12 Fourier, Charles, 25, 90, 135, 223 Ford, Henry, 108, 117, 120,132, 247n Freud, Sigmund, 41, 43, 241n Frye, Northrop, xi, 6, 13, 21, 32, 74, 83, 90, 240n, 242n, 245n Fukuyama, Francis, 234 Galileo Galilei, 51 Gearhart, Sally Miller, xii, 11, 208 The Wanderground, 176, 191201, 204, 217, 253n gender and utopian narrative, 27, 457, 546, 63, 7780, 915,

INDEX
Jensen, K.M., 155 Juliana of Norwich, 1723 Jung, Carl, 44, 241n Kautsky, Karl, 249n Kermode, Frank, 6, 9, 251n Keymis, Laurence, 45, 241n Keyser, Elizabeth, 251n Khouri, Nadia, 21920, 228, 239n, 253n Khruschev, Nikita, 37 King, Rodney, 234 Klages, Ludwig, 241n Kolodny, Annette, 45, 92, 241n Kropotkin, Peter, 144, 163, 168, 219 Kumar, Krishan, 1, 6, 69, 83, 234, 237n, 238n, 242n, 243n, 244n, 247n, 249n Lane, Ann J., 252n Leacock, Stephen, 70, 243n Lefanu, Sarah, 239n, 253n, 254n Le Guin, Ursula, xii, 11, 15, 16, 231 Always Coming Home, 2, 205, 212219, 237n The Dispossessed, 11, 205, 219230, 238n, 253n, 254n, 255n The Winds Twelve Quarters, 219 Lem, Stanislaw, 18 Le Queux, William, 246n Lenin, V.I., 107, 115, 117, 154, 250n Lesley, J., 105 Levin, Ira, 239n Levitas, Ruth, 7, 10, 107, 136, 173, 2001, 231, 233, 235, 237n, 248n, 249n Macherey, Pierre, xi, 16, 26, 73 Magus, Simon, 41, 240n Manuel, F.E and F.P, 1, 4, 19, 25, 41, 240n Marcuse, Herbert, 45, 108 Martyr, Peter, 49, 102 Marx, Karl, 5, 7, 50, 74, 237n, 239n, 254n de Medici, Cosimo, 35 Meier, Paul, 144, 148, 248n, 249n Mercier, Louis-Sebastien, 243n metaphors of transition, 27, 846, 99100, 1289, 153, 1545, 1701, 191 meta-utopia, x, 9, 244n Molire (Jean Baptiste Poquelin), 25 Moltke, Helmuth Karl Bernhard von, 76

267

Montrose, Louis, 241n More, Thomas, 2, 14, 19, 23, 24, 45, 5052, 57, 635, 71, 81, 83, 99, 144, 164, 177, 198, 202, 206, 215, 218, 240n Utopia, xi, 3, 9, 23, 31, 3249, 54, 57, 62, 645, 75, 87, 101, 113, 151, 161, 186, 188, 194, 210, 213, 221, 237n Morley, Henry, 242n Morris, William, xii, 3, 11, 15, 24, 1424, 161, 179, 183, 190, 203, 219, 238n, 239n, 248n News From Nowhere, 14, 16, 26, 103, 1412, 144156, 158, 173, 187, 192, 194, 202, 2068, 2145, 229, 248n, 249n, 250 Morson, Gary Saul, x, 3, 9, 12, 17, 31, 712, 149, 237n, 239n, 243n, 244n, 247n Moylan, Tom, x, 8, 9, 2035, 220, 222, 232234, 237n, 2423n, 254n Newman, Cardinal, 125 Newton, Isaac, 25, 223 Olson, Theodore, 238n Orwell, George, 81, 1056, 111, 129, 134,1368, Nineteen Eighty-Four, 14, 15, 1089, 11232, 141, 172, 247n, 248n Osmond, Humphrey, 251n paradise, 36, 38, 415, 62, 143, 149, 151, 1523, 171, 207 Parker, Patricia, 241n patriarchy, 457, 54, 115, 1303, 136, 141, 176, 186, 191, 194, 220 Pfaelzer, Jean, 80, 129, 243n Pico della Mirandola, Giovanni, 35 Piercy, Marge, xii, 15, 2301, 253n Woman on the Edge of Time, 2, 14, 205212, 2189, 2259 Plato, xi, 14, 32, 34, 35, 89, 105, 241n Poe, Edgar Allan, 18, 85 Ponce de Len, Juan, 38 Rabkin, Eric, 40 Ralegh, Walter, 45, 49, 240n, 241n, 246n reader-response theory, 9, 12, 237n Reed, John, 235 Roberts, J.W, 246n

268

NARRATING UTOPIA
191, 199, 204, 208, 2189, 231, 251n utopia, sexual relations in, 556, 7880, 902, 95, 1137, 1214, 1378, 152, 15760, 1845, 2078, 2212, 242n, 243n, 254n Vespucci, Amerigo, 34, 38, 240n Vinton, A.D., 1056, 246n Vonnegut, Kurt, 239n Walker, D.P., 50, Webb, Sidney, 68 Webster, Charles, 36, 240n Wells, H.G., xii, 6, 11, 15, 19, 20, 24, 26, 56, 656, 6874, 87104, 105 6, 141, 149, 160, 161, 1767, 18990, 209, 220, 237n, 242n Experiment in Autobiography, 245n The First Men in the Moon, 247n In the Days of the Comet, 3, 22, 23, 88100, 103, 116, 149, 203 Men Like Gods, 7, 22, 23, 69, 88101, 104, 120, 167, 179, 187, 194, 203 A Modern Utopia, 4, 9, 22, 23, 8892, 95103, 120, 146, 162, 170, 179 183, 194, 198, 200, 203, 234, 239n, 244n, 246n The Time Machine, 6, 70, 106, 245n The War in the Air, 70 The War of the Worlds, 6, 70, 106, 245n When the Sleeper Wakes, 70 Widmer, Kingsley, 253n Wilbrandt, Conrad, 246n Wilding, Michael, 249n The Wind in the Willows, 249n Winstanley, Gerrard, 9, 44, 232 Wittig, Monique, 176, 251n Yates, Frances, 60, 240n, 242n Zamora, Margarita, 240n Zamyatin, Yevgeny, 1056, 134, 1367, 194, 248n We, 15, 97, 107,109, 111123, 125132, 141, 172, 247n

Roemer, Kenneth, 232, 255n Rosemont, Franklin, 244n Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 249n Ruppert, Peter, 9, 12, 23, 2334, 237n, 238n, 244n, 247n, 248n Russ, Joanna, 176 The Female Man, 12, 2046, 237n, 251n Sanford, Charles L., 240n Shakespeare, William, 119, 125 Shelley, Percy Bysshe, 219 Shiels, M.P., 246n Skinner, B.F. Walden Two, 3, 105, 120, 246n socialism, 7, 15, 50, 81, 107, 134, 142, 1445, 148, 156, 1613, 218, 232, 243n, 244n, 247n, 249n, 250n Sorel, Georges, 237n Sorge, Frederick, 249n Stalin, Joseph, 108, 117 Stites, Richard, 242n, 247n Suvin, Darko, x, 3 10, 11, 12, 146, 152, 237n, 238n, 249n, 254n Swift, Jonathan Gullivers Travels, 6, 105, 182 Thompson, E.P., 144, 1467, 248n The Three Wishes (folktale), 255n Thrmer-Rohr, Christina, 47, 200, 241n, 252n, 253n Tiptree, James (Alice B. Sheldon), 252n travellers tale, see discovery narratives Trotsky, Leon, 108, 239n, 243n, 2456n Unamuno, Miguel de, 44 Urban VIII, Pope, 50 utopia, definitions of, 912, 152, 238n, 249n utopian geography, 27, 34, 3940, 6970, 83, 1779, 195, 2123 utopian impulse, 5, 8, 12, 245, 27, 32, 64, 67, 100, 103, 135, 138, 141, 164, 188, 198 utopian narrative paradigm, xxii, 1214, 1618, 24, 312, 646, 70, 724, 879, 112, 128, 149, 154, 157, 167, 175, 176, 186,

Вам также может понравиться