Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 14

Not Even Marxist: On Vivek Chibber's Polemic against Postcolonial Theory

[Note: I've added a response to Paul Heideman's critique at the bottom.] When Jacobin published Vivek Chibbers Marxist polemic against postcolonial theory, I wanted to write a counter-polemic. In fact, I did. As both a Marxist and a postcolonialist, I felt like Chibber was forcing me to choose sides where sides did not need to be chosen. After all, Chibber has to make several logical leaps in order to land his criticism of postcolonial theory; in a very real way, he has to invent it. The most obvious problem with Chibbers argument is the representativeness he ascribes to the South Asian Subaltern Studies collectivefor Chibber, they epitomize postcolonial theory in all its anti-Marxist glory. The second most obvious problem with Chibbers argument is his refusal to count as constitutive of postcolonial theory all anticolonial Marxist thinkers whose work was foundational for, or retroactively incorporated into, the postcolonial canon: George Padmore, Frantz Fanon, C.L.R. James, Mao, Ho Chi Minh, Kwame Nkrumah, Amilcar Cabral, Walter RodneyChibber is not unaware of this tradition. Indeed, in Postcolonial Theory and the Specter of Capital he recounts Robert Youngs lengthy attempt to place this Marxist tradition at the center of postcolonial theory, but only to discount it as spectacularly mistaken. Young is mistaken because Subaltern Studies and, by extension, postcolonial theory are either in tension with or simply reject what Chibber calls anticolonial socialism (290). In other words, after having presented a robust Marxist genealogy of postcolonial theory, Chibber rejects it because Subaltern Studies is postcolonial theory, Subaltern Studies is anti-Marxist, and therefore postcolonial theory cannot be Marxist. So, Chibber approaches his object with set terms that in fact constitute his object, and constitute it in such a way that Marxism is always exterior to it. This gets us to the biggest, but perhaps least obvious, problem with Chibbers Marxist assault on (what he calls) postcolonial theory: he does not approach this body of knowledge in a fulsomely Marxist fashion. Indeed, its unclear to me if Chibber, despite his vituperative polemic against anti-Marxist postcolonial studies, could in fact be described as a Marxist at all. At the level of method, Postcolonial Theory and the Specter of Capital is one of the least dialectical, most flatfooted Marxist texts that Ive read in some time. Chibbers Marxist criticism of postcolonial theory is that postcolonial theory is not Marxism. And, to be clear, it is a criticism, not a critique. Critique maintains an intimate relationship with the object it works over: it inhabits the objects terms, takes them as far as they can go, and in so doing recovers the potentials immanent to a field of thought even as it highlights the boundedness of that field. Critique becomes so intimate to its object that the critic risks being identified with it. Just think of Marx: he so affirmatively embraces political economy in his Kritik der politischen konomie that it is often assumed that Kapital is a political economy, that Marx is a political economist. No one, however, is going to mistake Chibber for a postcolonialist. This is not to say that Chibber does not cite postcolonial theoretical texts voluminously; he does. 85% of his citations are from three books. But he unpacks the arguments of three subalternists simply to show that a) they misread Marxism and b) they misunderstand capitalism and c) through their miscomprehension of Marx and capitalism they have come to articulate

an anti-Marxist theory, one that mystifies capitalist dynamics and reinscribes Orientalist claims about the difference of what Chibber is still somehow comfortable calling, without irony, the East. So, Chibber departs from a crucial aspect of Marxist epistemological and rhetorical protocolcritiquein order to defend Marxism. His very procedure assumes that Marxism exists in a position of exteriority to postcolonial theory. Indeed, it assumes that Marxism exists as a stable and coherent set of epistemological and political positions, positions that can be transformed into propositions that establish the non-identify of Marxism and postcolonial studies. So, postcolonial theory isnt Marxist, finebut what is Marxism for Chibber? Its kind of hard to say. Chibber does not expend anything like the same amount of time unpackingmuch less justifyinghis own Marxist normative and epistemological presuppositions as he does in showing that Guha, Chatterjee, and Chakrabarty are antiMarxist. In broad outlines, Chibbers Marxism depends on a defense of two universalisms, one pertaining to capital and the other to labor. More specifically, Chibbers Marxism is bound to the idea that the modern epoch is driven by the twin forces of, on the one side, capitals unrelenting drive to expand, to conquer new markets, and to impose its domination on the laboring classes [the first universalism], and, on the other side, the unceasing struggle by these classes to defend themselves, their well-being, against this onslaught [the second universalism] (208). So far, nothing objectionable: welcome to the Communist Manifesto. The problem emerges, however, when Chibber attempts moving from the universal to the particular, from the universality of capitalisms antagonism to the particular social zoning of its enactment. If postcolonial theorists want to hold onto the particularity of the particular, and engage the universal through it, Chibber uses these two universalisms to denude the particular, to remove the peculiarity of the particular in order to reduce it to the universal. Methodologically, Chibbers Marxism is pre-Hegelian. Indeed, his Marxism is the kind of monochrome formalism derided by Hegel, an epistemology for which the universal dominates the particular, one through which the living essence of the matter [is] stripped away or boxed up dead. The entirety of Postcolonial Theory and the Specter of Capital is staged as an antagonism between the champions of particularism (the Subaltern Studies people) and the champions of universalism (Marxists). Minus the first three or so, each of Chibbers chapters has the same form: the first section unpacks a subalternists methodological valorization of some form of particularity (Indian nationalism, peasant consciousness, Chakrabartys History 2) and the second section asserts a universalist counter -thesis, one that shows how the phenomena treated by the featured subalternist can actually become legible and explicable according to one of the two universalisms Chibber embraces. In other words, the chapters do not stage a dialectical tension between the particular and the universal. Rather, the chapters place particularist and universalist accounts side by side in a lifeless unity; indeed, the chapters keep the particular and the universal apart, positing an antinomic relation between them. The superior explanatory power of universalist accounts is not derived or deduced but asserted.

But Marxism is not a flatfootedly universalist epistemology. No theory indebted to a dialectical philosophy could be. In order to transform the relationship between the particular and the universal into an antinomic allergy, in order to assert the superior explanatory and political value of a universalist analytic, Chibber first needs to contort Marxism into something it never was. Im now going to work through both of Chibbers universalisms, reading them alongside moments in Marxist theory. Its going t o get kind of techy, so, if Marxian scholasticism isnt your jam, feel free to skip down or click away. The Universalism of Capital Consider Chibbers discussion of the universalization of capital. Chibber accuses the subalternists of arguing that capital abandoned its universalizing mission in the colonial world, a putative abandonment that has theoretical/historiographical effects. For Chibber, subalternists use the claim that colonial capitalism abandoned its universalizing mission as a means to assert that theories of capital that presuppose capitals universality are not applicable to the colonial world. (Its always, for Chibber, a question of application, of imposing abstract, superordinate terms onto the ordinary worlds of the particular.) Chibbers response is that, well, capitalism did continue its universalizing mission. But what does Chibber even mean by capitals universalization? Simply put, its globalization, its forc[ing] producers to submit to the competitive pressures of the market (138). He continues, This drive to continually intensify surplus extraction and continually lower production costs is what is universalized in capitalism. Capitalism thus produces abstract labor, which Chibber rightly notes is not homogenous labor but is rather a social fiction produced by the market: the emergence of abstract labor is specific to capitalism because [it] creates a social mechanism that takes the dispersed, disparate laboring activities of producers, and forces them onto a common metric (140). Chibber is making a crucial point: the universalization of capital involves the implantation of particular mechanisms of distribution (the market) and the formation of a quotidian social epistemology derived from the market (abstract labor). The one implies the other. But is this so? According to Marx, the simple articulation of a society to a capitalist market does not immediately yield abstract labor as its social precipitate. In what is now the appendix to volume 1 of Capital, Marx distinguishes between the formal and the real subsumption of societies into capital. In conditions of formal subsumption, capital subsumes the labor process as it finds it, that is to say, it takes over an existing labor process, developed by different and more archaic modes of production (1021). In conditions of real subsumption, capital backforms the labor process, taking over it directly. Formally subsumed societies produce capital for capital, but capital has not reconstituted the entirety of the social. Rather, capital gloms onto given forms of production and simply extracts surplus: formally subsumed societies produce absolute surplus value, not relative surplus value. Chibber is aware of this distinction, sort of; he marks the fact that in the formally-subsumed colonial world, the reliance on producing absolute surplus made capitalism highly coercive and violent, whereas in the advanced world [sic] the dominance of relative surplus value caused a switch to less personalized and less violent modes of value creation and extraction (113). Aware that

capitalism maintains and (re)produces forms of production it finds to hand, Chibber critiques the subalternists for refusing to realize that capitalism does just that, suggesting that their anti-Marxism derives from their assumption that capitalism only takes the form it takes in societies where relative surplus production reigns. But he refuses to mark the gap between societies producing absolute and societies producing relative surplus value as indexical of a fissure between formal and real subsumption. This is key, insofar as Marxs theorization of this gap shows that capital a) doesnt universalize whole hog, all at once and that b) the quotidian social epistemology called abstract labor that the market disseminates is a territorialized phenomenon. Indeed, Marx describes at length in volume 3 of Capital how certain modes of bookkeeping only become available within conditions of real subsumption. In my own research on plantation accountancy, Ive uncovered a bunch of planters who desperately want to be capitalist, but cant be: the markets uneven territorialization and subsumption of the globe inhibits some tryhard capitalists from adopting the common metric of abstract labor. Even as capital globalizes, it auto-delimits its universality (cf. all of world systems theory). It is not mystification to suggest that abstract labor is an improper analytic for the relation between capital and laborers in a given zone of the world-system when the abstraction of those diverse labors into calculable values takes place beyond the boundary of an epistemic divide. For most plantations or farms producing colonial exports, abstraction was a retroaction, a fact that inhibited capital accounting, prevented the optimal disposal of variable capital, and led to crazy crises of overproduction. Abstraction happened in another time and placein London or Glasgow, say, months after the produce had been harvested and shippedand colonial capitalists could only reckon with their production through abstraction months after their produce had been monetized and realized on the market. The one thing most colonial capitalists knew is that they could not operate like the ideal-typical firm that undergirds Chibbers analysis. To suggest, as Chibber does, that the universalization of capital consists simply in a drive to intensify surplus extraction reduces the material differentiation between forms of surplus extraction to a contingent accident, and thus discounts the way in which the capacity of this drive to realize itself is preformed by structuralmaterial conditions. Instead of a Marxian account, in other words, we get a Weberian one. If capital universalizes, this universalization is an uneven tendency, not an accomplished fact. This point has extremely important practical and theoretical effects. On one hand, as suggested, it means that capitalist rationality materially transforms depending on a societys mode of articulation to capital. The globalization of capit al implies not its universalization but its striationthis is a Marxist, and indeed Marxs, thesis. On the other hand, this striation of capitals globality impacts the labor process, labors relation to capital, and the modes through which resistance can take place. Formally subsumed societies contain a great deal of socialities that are defective for capitalism. Their modes of resistance are not reducible to capital and, indeed, what the underclasses of such societies resist is not necessarily structurally or phenomenologically identical to it. As Marx recognized as early as the Grundrisse (in his brief discussion of post-emancipation Jamaica) and as late as his writings on Russian

peasant communities, these forms-of-life can be seized by underclasses and potentiated as sites of resistance to capital. But this is already pointing us in the direction of a critique of Chibbers second universalism, that of labor. The Universalism of Labor Chibbers most useful, genuinely Marxist claim is that emergent bourge oisies have no interest in extending or disseminating democratic freedoms to working classes. The extension of bourgeois rights is not the act of a revolutionary bourgeoisie; there is, in fact, no such thing as a revolutionary bourgeoisie. Rather, as Chibber discusses in his overview of the historiography of the English and French Revolutions, working classes pushed the revolution into directions it would not go, producing and seizing the bourgeois freedoms that Whiggish histories wish to see as a gift bestowed by antifeudal capitalists. (This was, of course, CLR James take on the Haitian Revolution in The Black Jacobins, a text and an historical example that Chibber does not and cannot cite.) According to Chibber, the subalternists misrecognize the ordinary relation of capitalism to the political (i.e., capitalisms desire to restrict the zone of state rights and freedoms to the few) and so consider the dynamics of Indian postcoloniality (where a condition of dominance without hegemony, or capitalism without an extension of rights, reigns) to be a refutation of the general dynamics posited by Marxist theory. More importantly, by pegging the extension of rights and freedoms to an emergent bourgeoisie, the subalternists analytic gaze fixates on that bourgeo isie, on its successes and failures, and ignores the self-activity of the subaltern classes. Most importantly, by pegging capitalism to a regime of rights and by asserting that Indian capitalists failed to extend these rights to subalterns, the subalternists were able to posit the existence of a separation between the idioms of bourgeois politics (with its investment in rights, freedoms, and interests) and that of subaltern politics. According to Chibber, subalternists mobilized this separation notsimply to urge us to recognize and respect the political content of insurgencies but also to call for a displacement of the foundational concepts for political analyses (157). The subalternists, in other words, stick too close to the particularist content of subaltern politics and, in so doing, attempt to complicate (or displace, for Chibber) the universalist concepts proposed by Western theories of politics (157). Once again, then, Chibbers criticism functions by demoting a particularist content to th e status of a contingent accident and by reasserting the explanatory power of a formal, universalist concept. Chibber is indeed allergic to thinking from the particular, resistant to the kind of close hermeneutic engagement it necessitates. (This allergy to close reading bleeds into his own reading practice of the subalternists. In a block quote of Chatterjee on 158, he gives a snarky [sic] after encountering a There in the text, as if Chatterjee should have written Their. The anaphor of the term in question is the consciousness of a rebellious peasantry, a term in the singular that is marking out an analytic space and thus, in fact, to be referenced with There. A will to criticize makes one a bad reader indeed) To the particularist, hermeneutically sensitive accounts of collective peasant consciousness offered by Chatterjee, or factory worker consciousness offered by Chakrabarty, Chibber opposes the idea, central to the Enlightenment tradition of interests, of common interests that are superor dinate to the

particularist contents through which they are worked out. He will also call them universal interests. Lets ignore the fact that, at least since Spinoza, the common has been distinguished from the universal. Lets look instead at the polemical work to which these universal/common interests are put. Chibber first asserts the importance of these universal interests through his criticism of Chatterjees work on peasant consciousness. According to Chibber, Chatterjee valorizes the collective, communal consciousness of peasants, for whom community attains a foundational status in peasant psychology (157). [I]n cases of peasant action, Chibber glosses, interests are replaced by duty and obligation; the sovereign individual of Western theories are replaced by the community (160). For Chibber, this assertion simply reinscribes, in Orientalist fashion, the essentialist difference posited between (again) East and West: The West is the site of the bounded individual, while the East is the repository of Community (161). Chibbers solution is to deny the possibility of any form of difference and simply assert the universal reign of the bounded individual, one who struggles to realize his best interests. Let the pope remain, as Marx might say, but make everybody pope. Chibber then reveals that all peasant political activity can be deduced through individual peasant interests. A Marxist will have three problems with Chibbers claims. First, Chibber for some reason simply assumes and asserts that Marxism is an Enlightenment philosophya claim which sits oddly beside, say, On the Jewish Question or Notebook M of the Grundrisse. Marxism is a critique of the Enlightenment: it moves through it to open it up in new ways, ways that point beyond it. Second, Chibber for some reason thinks that Marxism offers a transhistorical, transgeographic analytic of the political premised on individuals interests, entirely ignoring Marxs fulminations against the Robinsonade of Enlightenment philosophy. There is, really truly, no theory of individual action derivable from Marxs texts. He was a Ricardian, not a marginalist; a critic of the Enlightenments sovereign individual, not its culminating thinker. The interests that Marx discusses are always class interests. Third, Chibber wants to collapse the distinction between individual as unit of analysis and individual as one person, body, and interest. Its only in this way that he can read Chatterjee as if the latter claims that all peasants are stupid and blind to their interests. But even if we think that interest is a meaningful analytic through which to come to grips with peasant rebellion, it is by no means clear that the individual who has actionable interests is identical to a single human being. Chayanovian approaches to peasant economies have long suggested that the household is the proper individual of the economic world of peasants, and thus the proper unit of economic analysis for peasant economies. This isnt to deny that the individual human beings composing this household do not have dreams, ideas, desires, and something that might be legible as interests to us; it is to claim that such dreams, desires, and interests become thinkable and actionable through the material, econonomic, and political unit of the household. Chibber wants to get rid of this complexity and reduce the individual unit of analysis to an embodied individual so as to reduce political interest to need, to physical well being (202). Everyone you know has a body, after all. Ergo, it is the universal

fundament of political interest; indeed, politics begins through an assault on the body, when capitalist domination generates palpable harm to workers physical integrity (203). Chibber then defines physical well-being as freedom from dangerous working conditions, poverty-level wages, high mortality, ill health, environmental hazards, and so on (203). One wonders what the so on covers. Im willing to bet, though, that if we drew a portrait of this universal body of the worker, he might look a lot like me: a white male with the normal bodily capacities ascribed to human beings. But the universality of the body is fractured by material particularismsby race, by gender, by disability that cannot be subsumed into a formal, superordinate set of real needs. To take the racialization or gendering of bodies seriously is not simply to respect difference, in some multiculti way; rather, it is to grasp the fact that differential bodily materializations yield new and particular needs that produce new modes of thinking and accessing universality. What I hear in Chibbers work is the old refrain used to silence feminists, queers, and race radicals: After the revolution, well fix that right up. Undeterred, feminists, queers, and race radicals began their own revolutions, they thought freedom from the way in which their particularized bodies were articulated to social structure, and did far more radical work (in the States, at least) than 2938 Stalinist sects. The radical Marxiststhe real materialiststook note. (There was, of course, significant overlap between these populations.) Political rationalities and their idioms shift according to the modes by which a social formation is articulated to capital. These idioms are not accidental, contingent, or reducible to mere content; rather, they materially express an insurgent relation to capital, even when they do not jive with the grammar of rational interest that primes some anti-capitalist politics. To not pay attention to the specificity of these idioms to reduce them to a universalism or to transcode them into Enlightenment talkis to court disaster. Im not going to go into his criticisms of Chakrabarty; Ive already been going on for too long. They follow the same line. Chibber wants to save Marxism from postcolonialisms assault; he ends up transforming Marxism into an abstract, formalist, anti-materialist hot mess of Enlightenment jibber-jabber. Why? Why? Why? If youre like me, youre wondering: Why was this even written? After all, Chibbers story is a twice (or thrice) told tale. When have Marxists not assailed postcolonial studies for not being Marxist enough? Moreover, his dramatic intervention is a bit belated. He invests postcolonial theory with an institutional clout it has not possessed for some years. Within the U.S. intellectual scene, myriad conferences, special issues of journals, and books have declared the demise of postcolonial studies; in literature departments across the nation, hiring lines that once would have been postcolonial positions have increasingly become Anglophone or Global English jobs. (Perhaps things are different in Chibbers field of sociology, but I doubt it.) I myself dont identify as a postcolonialistnot just because, period-wise, Im more properly described as a colonialist, but because I identify primarily as a Caribbeanist. (This might have

something to do with the old, old tendency to put South Asian theory and history at the center of postcolonial theory, as Chibber does.) So, whats at stake? In part, I think that Marxism versus postcolonial theory is simply running interference for a set of disciplinary battles over methodological and theoretical orientation. The antinomy that Chibber continually establishes is one between a realist sociology (with an investment in abstract structures that prime and cause human action) and hermeneutically inclined fields of anthropology, history, and literary studies. (Dont mention literary studies to Chibber. He doesnt seem to like it very much.) In each of Chibbers chapters, the explanatory triumph of universalist accounts over particularist accounts can be read as the triumph of a certain form of sociological reason over its others. More importantly, I think that Chibber is desperate for the resurgence of a particular kind of Marxism, one that was displaced not by postcolonial theorists but by anticolonial Marxists like Fanon, James, and so on. Thats why he cant incorporate them into his account of postcolonial theory: they are Marxists who mount critiques of formalist universalisms by keeping close to the particular, by maintaining the tension that obtains between economic structure and lived phenomenology, between structuralist accounts of the world and hermeneutic investigations into worlds. I have no idea why one would wish to return to the days of CP sloganeering. (I cant be the only one who heard echoes of black and white, unite and fight! in his book.) But the desire is there, and it shapes the way he constructs postcolonial theory. Chibbers fantasy that an anti -Marxist postcolonial theory reigns hegemonic in the academy enables him to maintain the fantasy that the once and future king of Marxism might some day be restored to rule. But, in order to elaborate this fantasy, he needs to transform a tension internal to postcolonial theory (between Marxist accounts of structure and hermeneutic approaches to the particularwhich can still be, of course, Marxist) into a struggle exterior to it. But if Marxism regains a position of prominence in the US academyand I hope it doesit no doubt not be Chibbers brand of Marxism. Chibber rightly locates the conditions of possibility for a Marxist resurgence in the academy in social movements beyond its walls. As he notes in his interview, until we get the kind of movements that buoyed Marxism in the early years after World War I, or in the late 1960s and early 1970s, you wont see a change. He ignores the fact, however, that a vibrant U.S. social movement did just take place in the form of Occupya diffuse movement that drew on the idioms of anarchism, liberalism, and certain forms of Marxism. Yet, because this movement did not limit itself to the kinds of things that Marxists used to talk about in the good old days, Chibber doesnt mention it: it is not functional for buoying a rigorously restrictive Marxism. In good vanguardist fashion, he notes the effectivity of such social movements only to dismiss them: the social movements adopt an idiom of anti-oppression that he claims is incompatible with a consideration of class exploitation. It takes a Marxist of a special kind to discount the radical potentials immanent to a movement from the bottom, a special kind of Marxist who wants to pulverize the textured phenomenology of social life into the universality of class. Indeed, Chibbers

Marxism will never regain its position of hegemony because Marxism has already beyond the narrow horizon by which he bounds it. The Marxism fashionable both inside and outside the academy today is that Marxism which has learned to meet people where they are, that has learned that a caring approach to particularity and a concern to foster difference is not opposed to the universal but is, rather, one way of producing new universals, of realizing freer modes of being in common. Indeed, the Marxism fashionable today is that Marxism which has taken postcolonial theory as a serious incitement, as a spur to think critically about its own deficits but also as a challenge to uncover its hidden possibilities. It is a Marxism that has foregone the fantasy-laden drama of polemic in favor of the open rhythm of critique and auto-critique. As Gayatri Spivak once wrote, Marx keeps moving for a Marxist as the world moves (67). Through the work of writers such as Spivak, postcolonial theory has moved with Marx, and Marxism too has kept up. Its only the Marxists who have fallen behind. [EDIT: My response to Paul Heideman's criticisms of me. I'm keeping it here so as to limit the amount of posts and to refrain from the drama of response / counter-response etc. Fight capitalism not each other and all that.] --> Hi Paul, thank you for taking the time to respond to my post, especially because, as you say, it deserves none of the attention it has received. I was raised Catholic, so being informed that Im not deserving of anyones regard is nothing too newit only amplifies my gratitude to my readers and to you. I admire the passion behind your words, Paul, but I fear youve fundamentally misread me. I also fear that you fail to respond to my primary question: If Chibber offers a Marxist criticism of subaltern studies, what kind of Marxism provides Chibber the epistemological and political foundation of his attack? My aim, then, was not to defend the subalternists from Chibber. Partha Chatterjee, Dipesh Charkrabarty, and all the rest are more than competent to do that themselves. My aim was to defend Marxism from being, once more, defined as a universalist theory that reduces particularity to an accident, a contingency, or something to strip away so that the pure body of universality might appear. My silence on aspects of Chibbers arguments against the subalternists in no way amounts to a concession, any more than your silence on many substantive aspects of my reply amounts to one. So, point by point: I turned to Marxs analytic of formal and real subsumption in order to demonstrate that, for Marx, capital constitutively zones its universality. Particularity does not simply befall it as an accident or as something it picks up, makes due with, or reproduces as an effect of its universalizing drive. This, to you, might sound like Chibbers argument that labor is not homogenousa claim that I marked in the text as correct. I was interested, however, in pegging the heterogeneity of labor to the striated way in which capital itself globalizes. The blocking of capitals globalization is a moment immanent to capital itself: capital blocks itself and blocks itself off, zones itself into regions of the world-system. It was not a question for me, then, of showing that abstract labor is always concreted and concretely differentiated, a specific and particular body riven by

forms of difference, as Chibber argues and as I agree. Making that claim is already to look at labor from the vantage of real subsumption. My aim was to show that Marx creates space to think about particularity from the horizon of an abstraction that has not happened, or that only happens in an epistemic elsewhere. I was arguing that it is simply misleading to say that capital universalizes when the apparent unity of the unit is a territorialized perception and a territorially differentiated structure. For me, capitalism is globalization without universalization. Ill engage your third point next and quickly. You, quite simply, chastise me for laying out the architecture of a theoretical framework and than extrapolating consequences from that theoretical position. I was not imagining what Chibber might write, I wasnt trying to get into his head. I wouldnt presume, and Im sure there are lovely thoughts in there. I was simply extending the consequences of a theoretical position, demonstrating what this position makes thinkable and unthinkable, seeing what is possible to think from the perspective of this position. Thats what critical thinking is: unpacking assumptions an argument makes and determining their theoretical effects. Besidesand to address your second pointits somewhat contradictory for you to excoriate me for seeing something in a text that isnt explicitly there while simultaneously congratulating Chibber for his indifference to Marxs own theoretical text in favor of some amorphous but certain version of the Marxist tradition, a tradition that forms the epistemic foundation for his argument. Well talk about that in a second. But, Paul, you criticize me for saying Chibber criticizes the subalternists for not being Marxist enough, only to suggest that he in fact criticizes them for reject[ing] this legacy of Marxist thought. In short, I said he criticizes them for not being Marxist enough; you say he criticizes them for not being Marxist at all. Fair enough. All of which returns me to my main point: What Marxism primes Chibbers criticism? Its not, by your own admission and Chibbers, one derived from Marx. Its some vague but certain tradition. Like I said, I was raised Catholic, and I think that escaping the magisterium of the church has turned me into a kind of sola scriptura guyI cant take the authoritative claims to the authority of a tradition as meaning anything. So, please, just name the tradition. As I argued, I dont think you can. Chibbers Marxist tradition is standing in for two other traditions: the Enlightenment (but which one?) and a certain kind of Weberian sociology. All of that is fine, I guess. Just stop trying to seize the sign of Marxism to pass off theoretical positions that are decidedly not Marxist. Stop using the sign of Marxism to castigate a field of knowledge that, while decidedly possessing its own problems, can in fact enrich and thicken Marxism and Marxist, anti-capitalist politics. Thanks again!

Not Even Marxist? Paul M. Heideman examines Chris Taylor's critique of Vivek Chibber
By Huw Lemmey / 02 May 2013

In his recent blogpost Not Even Marxist: On Vivek Chibber's Polemic against Postcolonial Theory, Chris Taylor takes exception to the arguments raised in Chibber's new book, Postcolonial Theory and the Specter of Capital. In this special blog, academic Paul M. Heideman responds to Taylor's attack directly, addressing the continuing debate around Chibber's influential new reading of Postcolonial Theory. Chris Taylor's post (Not Even Marxist: On Vivek Chibber's Polemic against Postcolonial Theory) presents what purports to be a quite sharp critique of Postcolonial Theory and the Spectre of Capital. He takes the book to task for being un-dialectical, for orthodoxy-mongering, and a host of other theoretical sins. As the most extensive response to the book yet published, it has garnered a good deal of positive attention from those uncomfortable with Chibber's promotion of a frankly universalistic theory and his attacks on the fetishization of particularism. Unfortunately, Taylor's article deserves none of the attention it has received. It exemplifies the kind of evasiveness and non-engagement which typifies the culture of the academic left. What are presented as incisive blows against the intellectual architecture of the book are in fact a series of passages that, at their best, do not even contradict the arguments made in the book and, at their worst, descend into mere name-calling. Three examples: His argument about real and formal subsumption doesn't actually contradict anything Chibber argues in his book. What is presented as a criticism of Chibber actually works as an extension (or at most, a small modification) of his argument. Chibber argues, contra Lowe, Roediger, and Esch, that abstract labor does not mean homogenized labor. He also argues that Guha is wrong to say that capital didn't universalize in India, because the things Guha says it failed to do there are also things it failed to do in Europe, where no one would argue it failed to universalize. Taylor responds that Chibber doesn't see the importance of the difference between formal and real subsumption of labor, and that abstract labor is produced only when the latter has been accomplished. He also says in the colonies that formal subsumption tended to predominate, which means that the universalization of capital took place unevenly.

But as should be plain from this summary, what Taylor is saying doesn't actually contradict Chibber's argument. First of all, it's an entirely different account from Guha's, which is centered on the colonial/national bourgeoisie's failure to confront the landed classes in the way the Western European bourgeoisie supposedly did. So Taylor effectively concedes Vivek's critique of Guha. More importantly, however, it doesn't contradict the key theoretical point Chibber is making: capitalist universalization doesn't imply homogenization, but is perfectly capable of generating difference based on the concrete history of its universalization. To say that as capitalism spreads it relies on the formal or real subsumption of labor in different places, and that this looks quite different, is a very different argument from one that says the only way you can explain the difference between how things look in the metropole and in the colonies is by positing that capital's universalization has been blocked in the latter. Taylor's account actually implies precisely the key theoretical point Chibber is insisting upon. Though Taylor attempts to load a

critique into this point, tendentiously suggesting that Chibber refuses to see the way the material histories of different spaces condition the development of capitalism within them, there is still nothing here that contradicts the argument that capital's universalization, properly understood as the universalization of market dependence, happens differently in different places, and produces different histories. Second, it is actually a very bad misreading of the book to argue that Chibber is criticizing the subalternists for not being Marxist enough. Nowhere does he make that claim. Rather, he argues that Marxism has a rich legacy of thinking about what the development of capitalism outside of Europe looks like, and that the subalternists have tended to reject this legacy on the basis of critiques which are not very persuasive theoretically or empirically. Chibber's response to Partha Chatterjee at the final plenary of Historical Materialism New York after Chatterjee accused him of having a different theory of abstract labor than Marx is indicative of this point: I don't care. Chibber isn't trying to out-Marx the subalternists here, he is simply arguing that a certain version of the Marxist tradition is capable of explaining the historical phenomenon that their own theories fail to. This is a very different claim, and one that it is much harder to dismiss as orthodoxy-mongering. Finally, and, I think, most egregiously, there is this: Chibber then defines physical well-being as freedom from dangerous working conditions, poverty-level wages, high mortality, ill health, environmental hazards, and so on... (203). One wonders what the so on covers. I'm willing to bet, though, that if we drew a portrait of this universal body of the worker, he might look a lot like me: a white male with the normal bodily capacities ascribed to human beings. Here, we have Taylor, quite literally, attacking Vivek not for what he wrote, but for what Taylor imagines he might write. What is there to reply to this? No, Chibber wouldn't have written that? We have descended into the realm of the absurd here, though I think that it is telling that Taylor chooses to have a go at the book not for what is written in it, but what he imagines might be in Chibber's head. Any reasonable standard of intellectual exchange should rule out this sort of ridiculous analytic maneuver. At the end of the day, Taylor's post exemplifies an intellectual laziness that I think is far too common on the academic left. Chibber's book can be criticized in all sorts of ways. So it saddens me that a post that fails to make even one substantive criticism of an argument made in the book, and instead relies primarily on name-calling (neener-neener you're not dialectical!!) and conjecture is being taken as a real critique. Paul M. Heideman is a Ph D candidate in American Studies at Rutgers-Newark. His dissertation examines the place of the Russian Revolution in New Negro thought. Hi Paul, thank you for taking the time to respond to my post, especially because, as you say, it deserves none of the attention it has received. I was raised Catholic, so being informed that Im not deserving of anyones regard is nothing too newit only amplifies my gratitude to my readers and to you. I admire the passion behind your words, Paul, but I fear youve fundamentally misread me. I also fear that you fail to respond to my primary question: If Chibber offers a Marxist criticism of subaltern studies, what kind of Marxism provides Chibber the epistemological and political foundation of his attack? My aim, then, was not to defend the

subalternists from Chibber. Partha Chatterjee, Dipesh Charkrabarty, and all the rest are more than competent to do that themselves. My aim was to defend Marxism from being, once more, defined as a universalist theory that reduces particularity to an accident, a contingency, or something to strip away so that the pure body of universality might appear. My silence on aspects of Chibbers arguments against the subalternists in no way amounts to a concession, any more than your silence on many substantive aspects of my reply amounts to one. So, point by point: I turned to Marxs analytic of formal and real subsumption in order to demonstrate that, for Marx, capital constitutively zones its universality. Particularity does not simply befall it as an accident or as something it picks up, makes due with, or reproduces as an effect of its universalizing drive. This, to you, might sound like Chibbers argument that labor is not homogenousa claim that I marked in the text as correct. I was interested, however, in pegging the heterogeneity of labor to the striated way in which capital itself globalizes. The blocking of capitals globalization is a moment immanent to capital itself: capital blocks itself and blocks itself off, zones itself into regions of the world-system. It was not a question for me, then, of showing that abstract labor is always concreted and concretely differentiated, a specific and particular body riven by forms of difference, as Chibber argues and as I agree. Making that claim is already to look at labor from the vantage of real subsumption. My aim was to show that Marx creates space to think about particularity from the horizon of an abstraction that has not happened, or that only happens in an epistemic elsewhere. I was arguing that it is simply misleading to say that capital universalizes when the apparent unity of the unit is a territorialized perception and a territorially differentiated structure. For me, capitalism is globalization without universalization. Ill engage your third point next and quickly. You, quite simply, chastise me for laying out the architecture of a theoretical framework and than extrapolating consequences from that theoretical position. I was not imagining what Chibber might write, I wasnt trying to get into his head. I wouldnt presume, and Im sure there are lovely thoughts in there. I was simply extending the consequences of a theoretical position, demonstrating what this position makes thinkable and unthinkable, seeing what is possible to think from the perspective of this position. Thats what critical thinking is: unpacking assumptions an argument makes and determining their theoretical effects. Besidesand to address your second pointits somewhat contradictory for you to excoriate me for seeing something in a text that isnt explicitly there while simultaneously congratulating Chibber for his indifference to Marxs own theoretical text in favor of some amorphous but certain version of the Marxist tradition, a tradition that forms the epistemic foundation for his argument. Well talk about that in a second. But, Paul, you criticize me for saying Chibber criticizes the subalternists for not being Marxist enough, only to suggest that he in fact criticizes them for reject[ing] this legacy of Marxist thought. In short, I said he criticizes them for not being Marxist enough; you say he criticizes them for not being Marxist at all. Fair enough. All of which returns me to my main point: What Marxism primes Chibbers criticism? Its not, by your own admission and Chibbers, one derived from Marx. Its some vague but certain tradition. Like I said, I was raised Catholic, and I think that escaping the magisterium of the church has

turned me into a kind of sola scriptura guyI cant take the authoritative claims to the authority of a tradition as meaning anything. So, please, just name the tradition. As I argued, I dont think you can. Chibbers Marxist tradition is standing in for two other traditions: the Enlightenment (but which one?) and a certain kind of Weberian sociology. All of that is fine, I guess. Just stop trying to seize the sign of Marxism to pass off theoretical positions that are decidedly not Marxist. Stop using the sign of Marxism to castigate a field of knowledge that, while decidedly possessing its own problems, can in fact enrich and thicken Marxism and Marxist, anti-capitalist politics. Thanks again!
Taylor

Вам также может понравиться