Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 23

Intellectuals, Sociology of

Robert J. Brym Department of Sociology University of Toronto 725 Spadina Avenue Toronto M5S 2J4 Canada rbrym@chass.utoronto.ca phone 416-787-0334 fax 416-787-0795

Keywords: intellectuals, intelligentsia, professions, politics, creativity, ideas

To be published in International Encyclopedia of the Social and Behavioral Sciences, 2nd ed., James D. Wright, ed. Oxford UK: Elsevier, 2015

Words: 4,776

Abstract

Intellectuals, sociology of This article first reviews the development of the term intellectual and the social and historical circumstances that led intellectuals to become a large, moderately well-defined, and occasionally self-conscious group. Particular attention is paid to the rise of commerce and industry since the late Middle Ages, the spread of literacy, the growth of markets, and the proliferation of social contexts for intellectual discussion and debate. The article then argues that three main traditions of analysis inform the sociological study of intellectuals: class theories, theories of classlessness, and theories of shifting social networks. It is argued that the third of these traditions is the most fruitful. Evidence to support this claim is drawn from analyses of the social conditions that lead intellectuals to assume various ideological and political positions. It is concluded that, to explain intellectuals allegiances, one must trace their paths of social mobility as they are shaped by the capacity of various social collectivities to expand the institutional milieus through which intellectuals pass. To the degree these milieus are imprinted with the interests of the social collectivities that control them, they circumscribe the interests reflected in intellectuals ideologies and political allegiances.

Definition Intellectuals are people who produce, evaluate, and distribute culture. Their role often involves some mixture of endorsing or criticizing the cultural objects of their attention. Following Michael Burawoy (2005), intellectual work may be said to vary along two dimensions: its intended audience (which may include academics, policy makers, various sections of the public, and the public as a whole) and the degree to which it makes instrumental versus normative claims (what is versus what ought to be). Individual intellectuals may specialize in one or more of the cells resulting from the crossclassification of the two dimensions. Similarly, particular academic disciplines, professions, schools of thought, regions, and historical periods may highlight one or more specializations (Brym and Nakhaie, 2009).

Origins The intellectual role has been performed in all societies. Even a nomadic tribe of fewer than 100 foragers could afford to employ a shaman to forecast the weather, predict the movement of animals, and tend to the ill. However, the Renaissance humanists (circa 13001600 CE) were the first influential group resembling todays intellectuals. Renaissance scholars thought they lived in a golden age of virtue and learning. To emphasize the point, they invented the term Middle Ages to refer to the dark gulf separating their era from the glories of the ancient world. Promoting the study of poetry, grammar, rhetoric, history, and moral philosophy, the humanists from Petrarch in the 14th century to More, Erasmus, and Rabelais in the 16th century influenced the Reformation, the scientific revolution, and the Age of Reason. 3

Only since about 1600, however, have intellectuals become a large, moderately welldefined, and occasionally self-conscious group. The chief factors that helped to distinguish them were the rise of commerce and industry since the late Middle Ages, the spread of literacy, the growth of markets, and the proliferation of social contexts for intellectual discussion and debate. Flourishing commerce and industry permitted the accumulation of economic surpluses. They were used to expand state and private institutions employing intellectuals. Public education and mass literacy increased demand for intellectual services. In turn, the evolution of markets for these services allowed intellectuals greater freedom to define their political allegiances. The interests of aristocratic and church patrons no longer tightly constrained them. Finally, a host of modern social settings ranging from universities to political movements, professional societies to coffee houses, academic journals to mass-circulation newspapers provided contexts within which intellectuals could formulate their social and political identities. It was not until the second half of the 19th century that intellectual and the kindred intelligentsia entered common parlance. The term intellectual was first employed on a wide scale in France. In 1898, Georges Clemenceau referred to the leaders of the anticlerical and antimilitary camp that opposed the conduct of the Dreyfus trial as les intellectuels. Soon the political right was deriding the self-proclaimed conscience of the French nation. Because of the resulting public debate, the term intellectual stuck. The term intelligentsia was popularized in Central and Eastern Europe a few decades earlier. It, too, denoted liberals, socialists, and other critics of authority. Only gradually since the end of the 19th century has the term intellectual gained widespread acceptance and succeeded in unwrapping itself from quotation marks. 4

Theories Many normative or moralistic treatments of the problem of intellectuals may be found in the literature. They criticize what intellectuals do and make a case for what they ought to do. Julian Benda (1969 [1928]), Noam Chomsky (1969), and others have written important works in this tradition. In contrast, this article focuses on the analytical literature, which seeks to explain why intellectuals do what they do. Three main analytical traditions inform the sociological study of intellectuals. Sociologists have regarded intellectuals as (1) members of a class or as a class in their own right; (2) relatively classless; and (3) embedded in a shifting network of class and other group affiliations (Brym, 2010 [1980]; Kurzman and Owens, 2002).

Class Theory Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels (1972 [1848]) regarded intellectuals as members of the petite bourgeoisie who would be precipitated into the proletariat as capitalism developed. They believed that, under socialism, classes would disappear, so one could be a farmer in the morning, a laborer in the afternoon, and a philosopher in the evening (1972 [1845-6]). In contrast, anarchists Mikhail Bakunin (1872) and Jan Wacaw Machajski (Shatz, 1989) chief among them asserted that intellectuals aspired to form a dominant class. In making this claim, they anticipated the ideas of many 20th century social thinkers. By the 1950s, the middle of the class structure had expanded enormously in both capitalist and self-proclaimed socialist societies. People with university degrees filled many of the intermediate ranks. Reflecting on this change, a growing number of social thinkers 5

argued that intellectuals constitute a class that enjoys increasing power. Alvin Gouldner (1979) held that intellectuals comprise a new emancipatory class. Barbara and John Ehrenreich (1979) maintained that intellectuals form part of a new professionalmanagerial class. Irving Kristol (1972) called intellectuals the new class of knowledge workers. Defining intellectuals broadly to include economists, technocrats, administrators, police bureaucrats, ideologists, scientists, and artists, Georg Konrad and Ivn Szelnyi (1979) went so far as to claim that Eastern European intellectuals had assumed class power. These and other scholars, including James Burnham (1941), Milovan Djilas (1957), and John Kenneth Galbraith (1967), disagreed about much, but they shared the view that intellectuals form a large, ideologically quite homogeneous, and rising or dominant class. Steven Brints research exemplifies one important criticism of the view that intellectuals form a class. Using American data from a series of General Social Surveys, he demonstrated considerable ideological heterogeneity and strong cohort effects among intellectuals. Intellectuals, it turns out, are as numerous on the right as they are on the left, with the two camps tending to cluster in different occupational niches. Moreover, their ideological predispositions depend partly on the Zeitgeist of the historical period during which they reach late adolescence and early adulthood (Brint, 1984). Consequently, the ideological cohesiveness and presumed teleological movement of intellectuals toward class power seems greatly exaggerated. The second main criticism of the argument that intellectuals form a rising or dominant class is that, typically, they are demonstrably subservient to other economic and/or political classes. The Communist Party of the Soviet Union always sought to ensure that universities, research institutes, and the nomenklatura were populated by loyalists. In 6

Russia, the collapse of communism witnessed the ascent not of intellectuals but of people with strong connections to the state security apparatus and organized crime. Lawrence King and Ivn Szelnyi (2004) anticipate that, in capitalist societies, intellectuals will come to dominate an increasingly autonomous state. However, this eventuality seems increasingly unlikely in an era when giant global corporations have influenced governments to eliminate trade barriers and give up sovereign rights to pro-free market transnational organizations such as the World Bank and the International Monetary Fund. State autonomy has decreased in recent decades and there can be little doubt which socioeconomic strata are chiefly responsible for this development. For a time, intellectuals were politically ascendant in some parts of the world. For instance, as Charles Kurzman (2008) has shown, between 1905 and 1911, more than a quarter of the worlds population (in China, Iran, Mexico, the countries of the Ottoman Empire, Portugal, and Russia) was caught up in democratic revolutions led largely by selfidentified intellectuals. Many workers, peasants, members of the bourgeoisie, and in some cases even landlords deferred to them. Within a few years, however, their ascent was checked. Russian workers wanted more than just elections and a constitution. Chinese intellectuals lost power to the army because of widespread social disorder. When their commercial interests were threatened, the great powers turned against new, democratic regimes. Among the countries listed earlier, only Portugals democratic constitution survived, and then only until 1926.

Theories of Classlessness Karl Mannheim (1955 [1929]) held that modern intellectuals form neither a class nor part of a class. Instead, they are members of a relatively classless stratum which is not too firmly embedded in the social order. Mannheim acknowledged that intellectuals are typically recruited from various classes. However, he also held that, because intellectuals participate in a common educational milieu, their class differences, and the variations in outlook normally associated with them, tend to be suppressed. Many scholars echoed Mannheims conclusions. Talcott Parsons (1963) asserted that intellectuals put cultural considerations before social ones. Everett Ladd and Seymour Martin Lipset (1975) wrote that the capacity of intellectuals for social criticism, creativity, innovation, and attention to facts enables them to overcome their class socialization and, for that matter, the socializing influence of many other social collectivities to which they belong. A recent and more nuanced variant of the classlessness thesis has been proposed by Neil Gross (2002; 2008). Gross does not regard intellectuals as entirely removed from the sway of social forces but nonetheless emphasizes that ideological and intellectual choices are largely a function of which ideas resonate with intellectuals self-conceptions. However, this approach begs the question of how self-conceptions are rooted in social experience. Categories such as class, ethnicity, and gender are admittedly too broad and static to capture the range of social forces that influence intellectuals political and other choices, but acknowledging this fact does not necessitate a retreat to an explanatory framework that emphasizes coincidence or a voluntaristic phenomenology of self. Instead, it suggests the importance of discovering more precise and dynamic social variables that influence intellectual choice. 8

Theories of Shifting Social Networks Both class theories and theories of classlessness ignore crucial issues. Notably, intellectuals may be found at all points on the political spectrum. Class theories may briefly note ideological heterogeneity but tend to dismiss it as an uninteresting side issue, leaving it unexplained. Meanwhile, theories of classlessness minimize the significance of social influences on the shaping of ideas, thereby deflecting attention from the very issue that the sociology of intellectuals is mandated to analyze. A third approach seeks to overcome both these problems by focusing on the intellectuals web of shifting group affiliations. According to Pierre Bourdieu (1984 [1979]; Bourdieu and Wacquant, 1992), cultural fields tie individual and organizational actors together in various social institutions. These cultural fields are structured as social networks. Different positions in a social network are associated with different endowments of economic, social, cultural, and intellectual capital. Network position is also associated with cognitive structure. Thus, intellectuals in similar network positions share tastes, ideas, and values (Anheier, Gerhards, and Romo, 1995; Lamont, 1987). Randall Collinss magnificent analysis of philosophical schools takes this argument a step farther by showing how intellectuals gain reputations by successfully competing for attention, fame, and influence in intellectual networks. Collins demonstrates that intellectual creativity flows through chains of personal contacts. It moves by structured rivalries between intellectual networks. And it flowers when rival circles intersect in cultural metropoles. Because intellectual attention space is limited, no more than six, and often as few as three, creative schools manage to propagate their ideas across generations 9

in a given culture at a given time. Creativity dries up when a single orthodoxy dominates. Contrariwise, intellectuals create new schools of thought in response to political and economic changes that shift the distribution of material resources needed to support their work. The stars of intellectual life tend to be people who are involved in, or close to, such organizational transformations. Leading innovators are as likely to be conservatives as radicals (Collins, 1998; Gross and Frickel, 2005). Bourdieus and Collinss mesolevel theories are compatible with Robert Bryms approach, which, however, focuses on political allegiance rather than intellectual creativity and influence. Developing themes in Antonio Gramscis essay on intellectuals (Gramsci, 1971 [1929-35]), Brym argues that the ideologies and political allegiances of intellectuals depend on their social origins and the structure of opportunities for education, employment, and political involvement they face during their careers. These opportunity structures are, in turn, shaped by the relative power of major classes and other social collectivities. Accordingly, to explain intellectuals ideologies and political allegiances, one must trace their paths of social mobility as they are shaped by the capacity of classes, ethnic groups, religious orders, and other social collectivities to expand the institutional milieus through which intellectuals pass. To the degree these milieus are imprinted with the interests of the collectivities that control them, they circumscribe the collective interests reflected in intellectuals ideological and political allegiances. From this point of view, it is an oversimplification to say that intellectuals form a class, are members of a class or are classless. They are embedded in social networks whose ties to various classes and other collectivities shift over time and help account for their ideologies and political

10

allegiances (Brym, 1978; 2010 [1980]). This theme has also been taken up by Jerome Karabel (1996). The remainder of this article illustrates it.

Social Origins and Institutional Opportunities Social Origins In Weimar Germany, professors were largely antirepublican and right-wing. Mostly, their fathers were military officers, state bureaucrats, and academics: members or handmaidens of the aristocracy. In contrast, nonacademic intellectuals were inclined to the left. They tended to be children of successful participants in the industrial revolution: members of the upstart German bourgeoisie. Similarly, in the middle of the nineteenth century, Russias conservative and politically moderate intellectuals were recruited overwhelmingly from the aristocracy. On the other hand, the first generation of truly radical Russian intellectuals dates from the 1860s, and it contained in its ranks a large mixture of commoners. Their fathers were merchants, peasants, and petty officials. These examples illustrate that support for the traditional social order is common among intellectuals who have been reared in upper-class families that are threatened by social change. Being born into a less advantaged class has usually been associated with greater potential for intellectual radicalism. But not always. In North America, it seems that rates of upward social mobility have historically been higher than in Europe, and class has been a less important social distinction. As a result, class origin has less bearing on the ideologies and political allegiances of North American than European intellectuals. Especially in the United States, ethnic and racial origin, educational background, field of expertise, professional and 11

institutional status, and generational experience matter more. Accordingly, American surveys show that professors in small provincial universities are more likely to be politically conservative than professors in prestigious Ivy League universities. AfricanAmerican and Jewish intellectuals are usually more left-wing than are non-Jewish white intellectuals. Young intellectuals who work in the social sciences and cultural fields are more likely to be left-wing than are older intellectuals with business affiliations (Ladd and Lipset, 1975).

Economic Opportunities As intellectuals reach adulthood and enter the job market, the structure of markets for intellectuals skills can modify their early political socialization. An abundance of secure jobs that allow free expression can dampen intellectuals early radical impulses. A lack of such jobs can exert a radicalizing effect. Some intellectuals may continue to express radical political sentiments after they have taken jobs that suit them professionally. Still, the rate and intensity of radicalism are generally greater when the number of such jobs is fewer. For example, the Quebec educational system began to produce substantial numbers of highly educated French-speaking graduates in the 1960s. The new graduates found that an English-speaking minority controlled the larger and more efficient businesses in the private sector of the economy. Many highly educated Qubcois were shut out of good jobs. This, among other factors, encouraged some of them to develop the idea that to become masters in their own house Quebec must become a sovereign state. Surveys show that intellectuals became separatists in disproportionately large numbers and were a driving force leading to the election of separatist governments in 1976 and 1994. 12

Political Opportunities The patterns of political opportunities intellectuals face also profoundly affect their ideas and loyalties. At the level of social organization, political opportunities are structured by the availability of historical agents: workers, peasants, ethnic collectivities, and other groups that intellectuals may demarcate as the chief instruments of social change. Whether intellectuals become, say, socialists, populists or nationalists is determined partly by which historical agents are mobilized for political action and which are relatively politically dormant in intellectuals milieus at a given time. At the level of the political system, the capacity of party organizations to absorb new talent is also important in shaping intellectuals allegiances. For example, before the 1920s, the German Social Democratic Party had attracted most of the countrys radical intellectuals. By the 1920s, however, it became (to use the then-current catchwords) bossified, ossified, and bourgeoisified. Old men remained incumbents in the German Social Democratic Party for many years. Young men had little hope of rising in its ranks. Young women were even less likely to ascend to prominence, hindered as they were by the institutionalized inequality and sexism that, as Dale Spender (1982) documents, has dominated intellectual life for centuries. Lack of opportunity was one reason the young generation of radicals turned in large numbers to the Communist Party of Germany. If historical agents are largely unmobilized and no party organization is available to sustain the intellectuals beliefs, a process of political disillusionment is likely to set in. The

13

lack of an historical agent combined with the presence of a party organization, however, is likely to lead to intellectual elitism.

Intellectual Elitism Ever since Plato envisaged a society ruled by philosopher-kings, some intellectuals have been motivated by the conviction that they are better suited than are nonintellectuals to create and maintain ideal social arrangements. For example, in 1816 Hegel referred to Prussia as the state of the intelligentsia. Both he and Comte characterized historical epochs as accomplishments of the human mind, which they saw as the driving force of history. In their judgment, the intellectual was the human minds personification. Reinforcing this elitist view was the late-19th and early 20th century conception of scientists and other highly educated experts as a sort of ascetic priesthood whose dispassionate approach to their subject matter allowed them to perform extraordinary cognitive feats promoting the progress of humanity. Lewis Feuers studies did much to dispel the supposed ascetic roots of modern science, emphasized by Max Weber and Robert Merton, and demonstrate the antiauthoritarian, hedonistic, and individualistic mindset that typically accompanies creative scientific work (Feuer, 1963; Merton, 1936; Weber, 1958 [1905]). In recent decades, scholars working in the hybrid field known as social studies of science have succeeded in bringing intellectual creativity even more firmly down to earth by demonstrating how (to quote Steven Shapin) science is produced by people with bodies, situated in time, space, culture, and society, and struggling for credibility and authority (Shapin, 2010; Johnson, 2008) 14

Turning to politics, the degree of elitism expressed by intellectuals varies independently of their position on the left-right dimension. One finds democrats and elitists on both the left and the right. Two sets of circumstances promote intellectual elitism: weak participatory demands by the masses and lack of competition from other elites. The history of Latin America illustrates how weak mass demand for political participation encourages intellectual elitism. For example, in the 1950s, Cuban revolutionary intellectuals were faced with a small and reformist working class and a politically inert peasantry. Consequently, they took matters into their own hands, forming guerilla bands in the countryside to seize state power. The low level of popular political participation in, and mass control over, the Cuban revolutionary party diminished the likelihood of subsequent democratic development. The history of socialism and communism in Russia reveals a similar pattern. However, the Russian case is also instructive because it illustrates the opposite tendency. Even apparently unyielding elitists can democratize if they are pressured from below. Thus, when ties between workers and Russian Marxist intellectuals were dense during the strike wave of the 1890s, the 1905 revolution, and the period of labor militance in 1912-14 most intellectuals wanted their parties to operate according to democratic principles. In contrast, when working class political participation fell due to labor quiescence caused by troughs in the business cycle, strong government and police reaction to radical activities, and enormous losses in World War I intellectuals returned to elitist principles of party organization.

15

A second precondition of democratic practice among intellectuals is vigorous elite competition. Aristotle argued that justice can be maximized not if philosopher-kings rule, but if constitutions are divided against themselves if, in other words, there exists what is now called a separation of powers between the various branches of government. Following Aristotle, scholars now commonly believe that tyranny and arbitrary rule by an elite can be prevented if the branches of government hold each other in check. One may invoke a broadly similar principle in analyzing intellectual elitism. Nonintellectual elites need to keep intellectuals in check if they are to prevent the political and social dangers that can result from intellectuals taking Plato to heart. The most compelling case for the benefits of elite competition derives from the history of communism, the epitome of intellectual tyranny in the twentieth century. Yet the dangers of intellectual elitism have hardly subsided now that the communist era has virtually ended. In much of the world, intellectuals are making bolder claims than ever about their ability to forecast and plan social and scientific change. Governments are respecting those claims by seeking the advice of intellectuals, awarding them research contracts, and employing them by the legion. Emboldened by their growing numbers and prestige, some intellectuals, particularly in the United States and Eastern Europe, have proclaimed themselves the ruling class of the future, the real holders of power in an era when knowledge allegedly means more than capital in determining status. One should not take intellectuals claims about their accomplishments too seriously. For example, as Eva Etziony-Halevy (1985) documents, economists, the hardest of the social scientists, have generally failed to forecast and regulate economic trends. Natural

16

scientists have arguably helped to create nearly as many social problems as they have solved. On the other hand, the dangers of too much intellectual influence on political life should be carefully heeded. Individual intellectuals have proved to be exemplary political leaders, but when intellectuals are in a position to impose their blueprints on society they often do more harm than good. The shock therapy advocated by the academics who formed the core of the Russian government late in 1991 caused tremendous social dislocation and political reaction that undermined reform in that country. This is only one example of what can happen when intellectuals rule. It seems reasonable to conclude that the practice of politics is much too serious a matter to be left only to the intellectuals.

17

References

Anheier, Helmut K., Jrgen Gerhards, and Frank P. Romo. 1995. Forms of Capital and Social Structure in Cultural Fields: Examining Bourdieus Social Topography. American Journal of Sociology 100, 4: 859-903.

Bakunin, Mikhail. 1872. On the International Workingmens Association and Karl Marx. http://www.marxists.org/reference/archive/bakunin/works/1872/karl-marx.htm (retrieved 3 July 2012).

Benda, Julien. 1969 [1928]. The Treason of the Intellectuals, Richard Aldington, trans. New York: Norton.

Burawoy, Michael. 2005. For Public Sociology. American Sociological Review 70, 1: 428.

Bourdieu, Pierre. 1984 [1979]. Distinction: A Social Critique of the Judgment of Taste, Richard Nice, trans. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.

__________ and Loic J. D. Wacquant. 1992. An Invitation to Reflexive Sociology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Brint, Stephen. 1984. New Class and Cumulative Trend Explanations of the Liberal Political Attitudes of Professionals. American Journal of Sociology 90, 1: 30-71 18

Brym, Robert J. 1978. The Jewish Intelligentsia and Russian Marxism: A Sociological Study of Intellectual Radicalism and Ideological Divergence. London: Macmillan.

__________. 2010 [1980]. Intellectuals and Politics. London: Routledge.

Brym, Robert J. and M. Reza Nakhaie. 2009. Professional, Critical, Policy, and Public Academics in Canada. Canadian Journal of Sociology 34, 3: 655-69.

Burnham, James. 1941. The Managerial Revolution. New York: John Day.

Chomsky, Noam. 1969. American Power and the New Mandarins. New York: Vintage.

Collins, Randall. 1998. The Sociology of Philosophies: A Global Theory of Intellectual Change. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.

Djilas, Milovan. 1957. The New Class: An Analysis of the Communist System. New York: Praeger.

Ehrenreich, Barbara and John Ehrenreich. 1979. The Professional-Managerial Class. Pp. 545 in Pat Walker, ed. Between Labor and Capital. Montreal: Black Rose Books.

19

Etzioni-Halevy, Eva. 1985. The Knowledge Elite and the Failure of Prophecy. London: George Allen and Unwin.

Feuer, Lewis S. 1963. The Scientific Intellectual: The Psychological and Sociological Origins of Modern Science. New York: Basic.

Galbraith, John Kenneth. 1967. The New Industrial State. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

Gouldner, Alvin. 1979. The Future of Intellectuals and the Rise of the New Class: A Frame of Reference, Theses, Conjectures. New York: Seabury.

Gramsci, Antonio. 1971 [1929-35]. The Intellectuals. Pp. 5-23 in Selections from the Prison Notebooks, Quentin Hoare and Geoffrey Nowell Smith, eds. and trans. New York: International Publishers.

Gross, Neil. 2008. Richard Rorty: The Making of an American Philosopher. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Gross, Neil and Scott Frickel. 2005. A General Theory of Scientific/Intellectual Movements. American Sociological Review 70, 2: 204-232.

Gross, Neil. 2002. Becoming a Pragmatist Philosopher: Status, Self-Concept, and Intellectual Choice. American Sociological Review 67, 1: 52-76. 20

Johnson, Steven. 2008. The Invention of Air: A Story of Science, Faith, Revolution, and the Birth of America. New York: Riverhead Books.

Karabel, Jerome. 1996. Towards a Theory of Intellectuals and Politics. Theory and Society 25, 2: 205-33.

King, Lawrence Peter and Ivn Szelnyi. 2004. Theories of the New Class: Intellectuals and Power. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

Konrad, Georg and Ivn Szelnyi. 1979. The Intellectuals on the Road to Class Power: A Sociological Study of the Role of the Intelligentsia in Socialism. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.

Kristol, Irving. 1972. About Equality. Commentary 54: 41-7.

Kurzman, Charles. 2008. Democracy Denied, 1905-1915: Intellectuals and the Fate of Democracy. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.

Kurzman, Charles and Lynn Owens. 2002. The Sociology of Intellectuals. Annual Review of Sociology 28: 63-90.

21

Ladd, Everett Cyrill and Seymour Martin Lipset. 1975. The Divided Academy: Professors and Politics. New York: McGraw-Hill.

Lamont, Michelle. 1987. How to Become a Dominant French Philosopher: The Case of Jacques Derrida. American Journal of Sociology 93, 3: 584-622.

Mannheim, Karl.1955 [1929]. Ideology and Utopia. Louis Wirth and Edward Shils, trans. New York: Harvest.

Marx, Karl. The German Ideology: Part One. 1972 [1845-6]. Pp. 147-200 in Robert Tucker, ed. The Marx-Engels Reader. New York: Norton.

Marx, Karl and Friedrich Engels. 1972 [1848]. Manifesto of the Communist Party. Pp. 33162 in Robert Tucker, ed. The Marx-Engels Reader. New York: Norton.

Merton, Robert. 1936. Puritanism, Pietism and Science. The Sociological Review 28, 1: 130.

Parsons, Talcott. 1963. The Intellectual: A Social Role Category. Pp. 3-24 in Paul Rieff, ed. On Intellectuals. Garden City NJ: Anchor.

22

Shapin, Steven. 2010. Never Pure: Historical Studies of Science as if It Was Produced by People with Bodies, Situated in Time, Space, Culture, and Society, and Struggling for Credibility and Authority. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

Shatz, Marshall. 1989. Jan Wacaw Machajski:A Radical Critic of the Russian Intelligentsia and Socialism. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

Spender, Dale. 1982. Women of Ideas and What Men Have Done to Them: From Aphra Behn to Adrienne Rich. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

Weber, Max. 1958 [1905]. The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism, Talcott Parsons, trans. New York: Scribner.

23

Вам также может понравиться