Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 26

An Analytical Theory

of Just Market Exchange





Ricardo Andrs Guzmn
Centro de Investigacin en Complejidad Social
and Facultad de Gobierno
Universidad de Desarrollo
rnguzma@udd.cl

Michael C. Munger
Departments of Economics
and Political Science
Duke University
munger@duke.edu




Prepared for presentation at the September School of Philosophy,
Economics, and Politics, September 5-9, 2012, Moeclu, Brasov,
sponsored by C.A.D.I., Bucharest, Romania. Draft: Please do not quote
without permission.
2
An analytical theory of just market exchange
Ricardo Andrs Guzmn
-
Michael C. Munger


September 1, 2012
Otto Toby Daviss believed that market exchange, and the institutions that foster market
exchange, were crucial to human development and flourishing. In two famous papers (Wu and Davis,
1999a and 1999b), Toby and his coauthor Wenbo Wu argued that economic freedom is
fundamental, and can precede political freedom on a growth path to development. But critics protested,
plausibly, that this aggregate result assumes too much about the justice of market exchanges between
particular individuals. If the disparity between market participants is too vast, if the access to the
benefits to markets are too restricted to those with market power, then the aggregate growth may
benefit the nation, but will exploit and damage those too weak to negotiate on fair terms. In this
paper, we take on the issue directly, investigating the moral obligations of individual participants in
market exchange. We are able to show that it is possible for market exchange to be just, even if it
may not be fair. Therefore, on both material consequentialist and moral justice grounds, market
freedoms can support the claims made by Davis and other advocates.
1 Introduction
Any plausible theory of just market exchange must balance two conflicting moral considerations:
euvoluntariness (true voluntariness) and Pareto efficiency. Voluntariness requires that neither party is
coerced into exchange by threat of violence or other form of direct harm. Euvoluntariness
imposes the additional requirement that neither party is coerced by the lack of a decent alternative
to a negotiated agreement. Pareto efficiency, on the other hand, requires that voluntary, mutually
beneficial exchanges should always be allowed, even if they are not euvoluntary.
The conflict between euvoluntariness and efficiency is illustrated by Michael Sandel, who
describes coercion by scarcity of alternatives.
The... objection [to the claim that an exchange is truly voluntary] is an argument
from coercion. It points to the injustice that can arise when people buy and sell things
under conditions of severe inequality or dire economic necessity. According to this

- Centro de Investigacin en Complejidad Social and Facultad de Gobierno, Universidad de Desarrollo.
Departments of Economics and Political Science, Duke University.
3
objection, market exchanges are not necessarily as voluntary as market enthusiasts
suggest. A peasant may agree to sell his kidney or cornea in order to feed his starving
family, but his agreement is not truly voluntary. He is coerced, in effect, by the
necessities of his situation (Sandel 1998).
Sandel notes that there are two conditions under which one party to an exchange might be
coerced by scarcity of alternatives: severe inequality or dire necessity. Severe inequality means
that the disparity in alternatives to the exchange is too large to be equitable. Dire necessity means
that for one party the alternative to exchange is disastrous. If at least one of these two conditions
is met the exchange is not euvoluntary.
However, it is not obvious that non-euvoluntary exchanges are morally objectionable, and even
less obvious that they should be prohibited. In Sandels example, the peasant would likely beg for a
chance to exchange, arguing that the loss of one kidney is better than having his family starve.
When viewed this way, denying him the right to sell his kidney appears to be a form of injustice.
The question naturally arises: Are non-euvoluntary market exchanges ever morally permissible? If
so, does justice impose any limits on the terms of exchange?
1

A sketch of an answer can be traced back to John Lockes essay Venditio, where he poses
the following moral dilemma:
A ship at sea that has an anchor to spare meets another which has lost all her
anchors. What here shall be the just price that she shall sell her anchor to the
distressed ship? To this I answer the same price that she would sell the same anchor to a ship that
was not in that distress. For that still is the market rate for which one would part with anything to
anybody who was not in distress and absolute want of it. And in this case the master of the
vessel must make his estimate by the length of his voyage, the season and seas he sails
in, and so what risk he shall run himself by parting with his [extra] anchor, which all
put together he would not part with it at any rate, but if he would, he must then take
no more for it from a ship in distress than he would from any other. (Locke,
1661/2005, Venditio, pp. 4456; emphasis added).
In a sense, Locke maintains that the safe ship must devise a fictitious negotiation in which the
distressed ship is not in distress, and behave in the actual negotiation as he would behave in the
fictitious one.
Inspired by all these ideas, we propose an analytical theory of just market exchange that guides
reasoned moral action in balancing euvoluntariness and efficiency. Our method is to postulate a
set of plausible moral axioms, and then use deductive logic to infer a series of moral imperatives

1
For our purposes, the validity of Sandels example depends on whether a kidney qualifies as transferable property or not
(Sandel himself would raise this objection). As this matter is the subject of another debate, we will refrain from taking a position.
In what follows, we will restrict the analysis to the exchange of conventional market goods and services.
4
with respect to two issues: the circumstances under which exchange is morally optional or
obligatory, and the just allocation of the gains from exchange.
The theory is operationalized through a fictitious negotiation model. Briefly, the fictitious
negotiation model is as follows:
1. Neither party is morally obliged to suffer harm by an act of market exchange.
2. The negotiation will be fair and exchange will be euvoluntary if and only if the disparity
between the parties outside options
2
does not exceed a certain threshold. The magnitude of
the disparity threshold depends on the abjectness of the weaker party. The direr the weaker
partys outside option, the lower the disparity threshold.
3. If the negotiation is fair, all non-supererogatory outcomes are just. A non-supererogatory
outcome is either a mutually beneficial agreement or the disagreement outcome, in which
the parties get their respective outside options.
4. If the negotiation is unfair, the stronger party must devise a fictitious negotiation, in which
the weaker party has an improved outside option. The outside option must be improved
until one of two things happens:
(a) The disparity in outside options is reduced until it is no longer unfair. This does not
require that all the disparity disappears; only that it equals the disparity threshold.
(b) The surplus of the fictitious negotiation is reduced to zero. This can happen because the
surplus of any negotiation decreases as the parties outside options improve.
We term condition (b) the non-worseness
3
clause of the fictitious negotiation.
5. The just agreements of the actual negotiation correspond to the non-supererogatory
outcomes of the fictitious negotiation that are implementable in practice.
The fictitious negotiation model is parametric. The free parameter is the observers revulsion
toward the imbalance in bargaining power, which is captured by the disparity threshold. Rather
than being a constant, the disparity threshold is a decreasing function of the direness of the weaker
partys outside option, but the particular shape of the threshold function varies from observer to
observer. Clusters of similar disparity threshold functions constitute a culture. A threshold
function that captures the essential features of a culture constitutes an ideology.

2
In the jargon of game theory, the parties outside options are their best alternatives to a negotiated agreement.
3
Non-worseness is a potential constraint on moral action, on consequentialist grounds. Suppose that, in order for the
stronger party to act morally, the weaker party must actually be harmed in some material sense. Non-worseness is described by
Zwolinski (2008, 2009) interpreting Wertheimer (1996), this way: In cases where A has a right not to transact with B, and where
transacting with B is not worse for B than not transacting with B at all, then it cannot be seriously wrong for A to engage in this
transaction, even if its terms are judged to be unfair by some external standard. (p. 357).
5
Several moral imperatives follow logically from the fictitious negotiation model. The most
important are:
1. If the negotiation is unfair but has a positive surplus, the stronger party is morally obliged
to exchange with the weaker party. He cannot refuse to exchange by invoking his property
rights, or by claiming that the exchange would not be euvoluntary.
2. Moreover, the stronger party must negotiate as if the weaker party had a better outside
option.
(a) This fictitious outside option should eliminate all the unfair disparity, provided this does
not rule out the possibility of a mutually beneficial exchange.
(b) Otherwise, the stronger party must give the entire surplus to the weaker party, and
content himself with a payoff equal to his outside option.
These logical implications of the model are imperatives because they will necessarily trigger
when the weaker partys outside option is sufficiently dire. The particular disparity threshold just
specifies the meaning of sufficiently dire. For some observers, even small disparities are sufficient
to trigger the obligation to give away the entire surplus. For other observers, who find property
rights and ownership paramount, the obligation may only trigger at very large disparities. But the
obligation to give away the surplus is always triggered, at the limit of infinite direness, even on the
eye of the least disparity-averse beholder.
The theory of just exchange is a coherent alternative to radical egalitarianism and radical
libertarianism. When they are carried to their logical conclusions, both moral philosophies produce
untenable moral judgments. This indicates that these philosophies are founded on flawed sets of
premises. In contrast to the radical moral philosophies, our theory of just exchange produces
perfectly intuitive moral judgments. Importantly, these judgments are logical consequences of the
premises of the theory. There is no need to patch the theory with a long list of exceptions. Below
we provide two brief examples (the detailed workings of the fictitious negotiations will be
presented in the following sections).
Radical egalitarians consider that voluntary exchange is unjust if the resulting allocation is
unequal, despite being beneficial to both parties. For example, radical egalitarians firmly oppose
sweatshops, even if the workers themselves prefer the low-paid factory jobs to starvation in the
fields.
4
In contrast, our theory entails that it is unjust to let the workers starve. Moreover, the
factory owner is obliged to hire them and pay substantially more than they would earn in the field,
but he is not obliged to incur an economic loss (i.e., he must recover at least his opportunity cost
of capital).

4
See, for example, Sample 2003, and SASL 2001.
6
Radical libertarians condone exchanges that violate even the most basic notions of human
dignity and mutual obligation. For example, a man lost in the desert is on the verge of dying of
thirst. Out of nowhere appears another man carrying plenty of water. From the point of view of a
radical, logically consistent libertarian, the passerby has the right to sell his water at any price he
chooses, even if that price is exorbitant and patently abusive. And what is more absurd, the
passerby is entitled to refuse the sale and let the lost man die of thirst. Our theory entails it is
unjust to deny water to a thirsty man. The passerby is obliged to sell his water, but he is not
obliged to give it away. He must offer the lowest price that covers the full cost of the water,
including the purchase price, transport costs, and opportunity costs of possibly needing the water
himself.
The paper is organized in six sections. In Section 2 we define the notion of euvoluntary
exchange. In Section 3 we present an analytical negotiation model and formalize the notions of
fairness and euvoluntariness. In Section 4 we develop the fictitious negotiation model and our
analytical theory of just market exchange, which makes a distinction between equitable and just
negotiated agreements. In Section 5 we apply the fictitious negotiation model to four hypothetical
examples, each an abstract version of a real life moral dilemma. The examples are: Lockes anchor
problem, competitive market exchange, price-gouging, and sharecropping contracts. In Section 6
we offer some conclusions. Importantly, we argue that all reasonable moral theories must be
parametrical, rather than strictly deductive ( la Kant) or sentimentalist ( la Hume). Our analytic
theory of just market exchange is an example of a parametric theory, because its axioms are
modulated by a free parameter: the disparity threshold function.
Before we proceed, a clarification must be made. In this paper, we do not advance a
comprehensive theory of justice, or even a theory of just exchange. Our theory is only concerned
with market exchange. Any other form of exchange is outside the theorys domain of application.
Market exchange takes place within a particular structure of social norms and legal constrains.
Practices of negotiation and bargaining that are perfectly acceptable in market exchange might be
considered distasteful, offensive, or plainly immoral in other contexts, such as romance, the family,
military service, politics, the school, sports, or religious worship. Furthermore, the law or social
custom may prohibit the commerce of certain goods (e.g., recreational drugs). But even if the
commerce of a good is socially accepted and legal, the good may be degraded or corrupted by
market exchange; sexual intercourse being a favorite example of this phenomenon (Sandel 1998).
This means that some goods are inherently non-marketable (e.g., friendship).
The fictitious negotiation model applies to the exchange of marketable goods, provided the
exchange is socially accepted and legal. In many cases, there will be little dissent in this regard. For
example, most people would agree that trade in food, clothing, housing, and labor are legitimate
businesses, and that these particular goods are not degraded or corrupted by market exchange. At
other times, dissent will be profound, as in the cases of prostitution and organ trade. For this
reason, we remain agnostic, and leave to readers the task of agreeing on the boundaries of markets.
7
2 Euvoluntary exchange
For a market exchange to be considered euvoluntary (truly voluntary) six conditions must be met
(Munger, 2011):
1. The parties own the objects being exchanged, according to the conventional interpretation
of ownership.
2. The parties have the capacity to transfer the ownership of these objects.
3. There is no fraud in the exchange, and no psychological compulsions such as addiction or
neuropathy.
4. The exchange does not produce large-scale uncompensated non-pecuniary externalities, and
does not impose costs on third parties without their express euvoluntary consent.
5. Neither party is coerced in the sense of being forced to exchange by threat of violence or
other form of direct harm.
6. Neither party is coerced in the alternative sense of being harmed by the dire consequences
of failing to exchange.
Conditions 16 are standard requirements for a valid contract in the common law. Conditions 5
and 6 could be summarized as no duress. An exchange will be voluntary if and only if conditions
15 are satisfied, but the exchange will not be euvoluntary unless condition 6 is satisfied as well.
As stated by condition 5, an exchange is not voluntary if a party exercises its power to force an
agreement that benefits him. Here, power is understood in its colloquial sense, as the ability to
impose ones will on others through the threat of violence or other form of direct harm.
In negotiations, power has a different meaning. Bargaining power is the ability to cause harm
indirectly by refusing to exchange. Condition 6 states that euvoluntariness requires that no party
has excessive bargaining power over the other. Note that condition 6 says nothing about the
exercise of bargaining power during the negotiation, only that the parties are close in power. The
balance in bargaining power makes a negotiation fair, in the similar sense that weight classes make
boxing matches fair. The boxers need not weigh the same, but fairness requires that the disparity
in weight must be within a reasonable range.
For example, most of us have a sense that monopoly is not only economically inefficient, but
fundamentally unfair. It is true that the monopolist does not hold a gun to the consumers head
and shouts buy! But if the product is desperately needed, a consumers decision to buy cannot
be said to be truly voluntary. Put another way, the sale is essentially an armed robbery.
David Hume gives another example of coercion by scarcity of alternatives:
8
A man, dangerously wounded, who promises a competent sum to a surgeon to
cure him, woud certainly be bound to performance; tho the case be not so much
different from that of one, who promises a sum to a robber. (Hume, 2000, Book III,
Pt. II, Page 11)
The surgeon has a tremendous bargaining power because the injured man is about to die and does
not have the time to call another doctor. Humes view on this case coincides with that of most
people: the exercise of bargaining power by the surgeon is a form of extortion.
3 A two-parties negotiation model
3.1 Definitions
Define a two-party negotiation as a three-tuple
2 1
, , d d v P = , where 0 > v is the total value to be
divided between the parties, and
1
d and
2
d are the parties outside options. The (potential)
surplus of the negotiation is thus
.
2 1
d d v = (1)
We will assume that the surplus is nonnegative, so
2 1
d d v + > . Otherwise, any exchange would
necessarily harm one of the parties. A negotiation with a positive surplus is profitable. A
negotiation with zero surplus is unprofitable.
We will also assume that the negotiation satisfies conditions 15 from the previous section.
These were, briefly, that ownership is exclusive and transferrable, there is no fraud or
psychological compulsion, there are no uncompensated non-pecuniary externalities, and no party
can force the other to accept a particular allocation.
Let
1
x and
2
x be the payoffs to party 1 and party 2, respectively. A negotiation outcome is
an allocation X x x e ) , (
2 1
, where

{ }
{ }. : ) , (
), , (
,
2 1 2 1
2 1
v x x x x A
d d d
d A X
= + =
=
=
(2)
Allocation d is the disagreement outcome, in which both parties obtain their outside options.
The allocations in set A are called (potential) agreements. The set of agreements can also be
written as follows,
{ }, : ) , (
2 1 2 1 2 1
d d x x x x A + + = + = (3)
since .
2 1
d d v =
9
As an example, consider the following negotiation. Ada has carved a sculpture which she
values at $1,000. The rest of her wealth amounts to $1,000,000. Bob, a collector, is interested in
the sculpture, which he values at $1,200. Before the negotiation, his wealth amounts to $1,500,000.
The surplus equals the difference in valuations; that is, $200. Formally,

. 200 $ 000 , 1 $ 200 , 1 $
, 000 , 500 , 1 $
000 , 001 , 1 $ 000 , 000 , 1 $ 000 , 1 $
Bob
Ada
= =
=
= + =
d
, d
(4)
If Ada and Bob reach an agreement, then

, , , $ p x
, , , $ p x
000 500 1 200 , 1 $
000 000 1
Bob
Ada
+ =
+ =
(5)
where p is the price agreed by the parties. Thus, the disagreement outcome, the set of
agreements, and the set of all possible outcomes are
{ }
{ } { }. ) 000 , 500 , 1 $ , 000 , 001 , 1 ($ 200 $ : ) , (
, 200 , 501 , 2 $ : ) , (
), 000 , 500 , 1 $ , 000 , 001 , 1 ($ ) , (
Bob Ada Bob Ada
Bob Ada Bob Ada
Bob Ada
= + =
= + =
=
x x x x X
x x x x A
d d
(6)
An agreement is mutually beneficial (i.e., Pareto-improving or neutral) if and only if
1 1
d x >
and
2 2
d x > . This condition is strong if both inequalities are strict, and weak if at least one of
the constraints is met with equality (i.e., that party is not strictly benefitted, but is indifferent
between exchanging and not exchanging). The set of mutually beneficial agreements is thus
}. , , : ) , {(
2 2 1 1 2 1 2 1 2 1
d x d x d d x x x x M > > + + = + = (7)
In what follows, we will assume that all mutually beneficial agreements are achievable through
negotiation, although this may not always be the case in reality. It may be that a potential surplus
exists, but that it cannot be divided between the parties; for instance, if it happens that one of the
parties lacks sufficient liquidity and cannot borrow.
For example, Andrew is broke, homeless, and starving. Beatrice is a prosperous baker. He
enters Beatrices bakery and begs her for bread, which would save him from starvation. There is a
very large surplus at stake, since the value of a human life is much higher than the cost of
producing a loaf of bread. However, there are only two possible negotiation outcomes, neither of
which is mutually beneficial: Beatrice ignores Andrew and he starves, or she gives him a loaf of
bread for free (losing the opportunity cost) and he survives. Since a mutually beneficial agreement
is not achievable, this negotiation is not a true case of standard market exchange. Thus, our model
is silent about its moral content.
10
In principle, any non-mutually beneficial agreement could be achieved with the voluntary
consent of both parties. In our model, an agreement in which one party sacrifices itself to benefit
the other is considered supererogatory. There are two sets of supererogatory agreements,
depending on which party makes the sacrifice:
{ } . 2 , 1 for , , : ) , (
2 1 2 1
= < = + = i d x v x x x x S
i i i
(8)
Note that
2 1
S M S X = , where
1
S , M , and
2
S are disjoint sets.
The set of non-supererogatory negotiation outcomes contains all mutually beneficial
agreements and also the disagreement outcome:
{ }. ) , (
2 1 2 1
d d M S S X NS = = (9)
The sets M and { } ) , (
2 1
d d need not be disjoint. If M d d e ) , (
2 1
, then the negotiation has zero
surplus, and vice versa.
3.2 Euvoluntary exchange and the disparity threshold
Without loss of generality, let us assume that
2 1
d d < . The fact that the outside option for party 1
is worse means that party 1 is the weaker party to the negotiation and that party 2 is the stronger
party. Euvoluntariness does not require that there be zero disparity in outside options, but only
that the disparity not be too large. The specific meaning of too large depends on the
observers revulsion toward the imbalance in bargaining power.
An observed disparity in outside options is fair if and only if it does not exceed the disparity
threshold function ; that is, if and only if d d s
1 2
, where 0 > . The smaller is , the less
likely that any given exchange will be euvoluntary. To quantify the magnitude of the unfairness, we
define the (degree of) unfair disparity:
( ) { } 0 , max
1 2
d d = (10)
We distinguish between a negotiation, which is the process of reaching an agreement or a
disagreement, and an exchange, which is the act of consummating an agreement. If there is no
unfair disparity (i.e., if 0 = ), the negotiation is fair. Any exchange between the parties will be
considered euvoluntary. If there is an unfair disparity, the negotiation is unfair. Any exchange
between the parties will be considered non-euvoluntary.
We will assume that the disparity threshold is a non-decreasing function of the weaker partys
outside option:
, : ) (
1
D d 9 (11)
11
where
0 >
9 _ D . Intuitively, the disparity threshold function should increase with the weaker
partys outside option (in absolute terms, not in relation to the other partys outside option). The
reason is that an imbalance of bargaining power strikes most people as more unfair when the
weaker party is desperate.
Figure 1 shows what may be considered a reasonable disparity threshold function. As
1
d
grows smaller, the value of ) (
1
d asymptotically approaches zero. Consequently, all negotiations
will violate the unfair disparity threshold, because even the smallest differences between
1
d and
2
d
will be larger than ) (
1
d . But for larger values of
1
d , the value of ) (
1
d might rise very quickly,
implying that even exchanges with significant disparity in outside options will be euvoluntary.
Radical egalitarianism and radical libertarianism can be modeled as particular cases of the
threshold function. On the side of radical egalitarians, Olsaretti (2003)
5
would argue that ) (
1
d
should be close to zero for all values of
1
d . This implies that an exchange can only be euvoluntary
if the difference in outside options is negligible. On the side of radical libertarians, Robert Nozick
(1974) (worried about preventing capitalist acts between consenting adults) would advocate for
an infinite disparity threshold, regardless how low the value of
1
d . This is to say that voluntary
and euvoluntary exchanges are two names for the same thing. In Nozicks worldview, there is no
such thing as coercion by scarcity of alternatives.
To summarize, in this section we posited a specific condition under which negotiations are fair
and exchanges are euvoluntary:
{ } . 0 0 ), ( ) ( max disparity unfair
1 1 2
= = d d d (12)

5
See also Colburn 2008, and Gaus 2007.
Figure 1: A reasonable disparity threshold function
(d1)
d1
12
This condition would be true if the parties have similar bargaining power (i.e.,
1
d and
2
d are close
in magnitude), but the condition could also be true if the disparity threshold is so large that we do
not care that the weaker party lacks a decent alternative to a negotiated agreement. We allow the
disparity threshold to increase with the value of the weaker partys outside option, which captures
the intuition that disparity in outside options is more unfair when the weaker party is desperate.
4 The fictitious negotiation model of just market exchange
Formally, a fictitious negotiation is a three-tuple
2 1
, , d d q P ' = ' . Its only difference with the
actual negotiation P is that P' assigns an improved fictitious outside option
1
d ' to the weaker
party. The fictitious outside option is defined as follows:
{ }, , min
1 1
+ = ' d d (13)
where is the unfair disparity of the actual negotiation, and is its surplus.
Properties of the fictitious negotiation
1. If the actual negotiation is fair, then the actual and the fictitious negotiations are identical.
. 0 P P ' = = (14)
2. If the actual negotiation is unfair and has zero surplus, then the actual and the fictitious
negotiations are identical. Both have a unique mutually beneficial agreement, which
coincides with the actual disagreement outcome.
{ }. 0 0 d M M P P = ' = . ' = = . > (15)
3. If the actual negotiation is unfair but potentially profitable, and the unfair disparity does not
exceed the surplus, then the fictitious negotiation completely eliminates the unfair disparity
and is potentially profitable. The fictitious negotiation has infinitely many mutually
beneficial agreements, which constitute a proper subset of the actual mutually beneficial
agreements. The actual disagreement outcome is not a feasible outcome of the fictitious
negotiation.
. c 0 0 0 X d M M M ' e . c ' . = . > ' . = ' s < (16)
4. If the actual negotiation is unfair but potentially profitable, and the unfair disparity exceeds
the surplus, then the fictitious negotiation reduces the unfair disparity but does not
eliminate it. The fictitious negotiation is unfair, but less unfair than the actual negotiation.
The surplus of the fictitious negotiation is reduced to zero. The fictitious negotiation has a
13
unique mutually beneficial agreement, which corresponds to the fictitious disagreement
outcome. This outcome assigns the entire surplus to the weaker party. The actual
disagreement outcome is not a feasible outcome of the fictitious negotiation.
{ } . ) , ( 0 0 0
2 1
X d d d d d M ' e . + = ' . ' = ' . = ' . < ' < < < (17)
Proofs to these properties are provided in Appendix A.1
A negotiation outcome can be either equitable or inequitable. Three requirements must be
met for an outcome to be equitable. First, it must be feasible (i.e., it bust belong to X ) Second,
the outcome must be a non-supererogatory outcome of

the fictitious negotiation. Third, the
fictitious negotiation must completely eliminate the unfair disparity.
In formal terms, the set of equitable outcomes is

> ' C
= ' '
=
. 0 if
, 0 if S N X
E (18)
The inequitable outcomes, on the other hand, correspond to the non-supererogatory outcomes
that are not equitable:
E NS IE = (19)
The sets of equitable and inequitable outcomes are decomposed in Table 1.
Properties of the equitable outcomes
1. If the actual negotiation is fair, then all non-supererogatory outcomes are equitable
(including the disagreement outcome).
{ }. 0 d M NS E = = = (20)
Table 1: Decomposition of the sets of equitable, inequitable, just, and unjust outcomes
Case
Equitable
outcomes
Inequitable
outcomes
Just outcomes Unjust outcomes




14
2. If the actual negotiation is unfair and has zero surplus, then no outcome is equitable.
. 0 0 C = = . > E (21)
3. If the actual negotiation is unfair but potentially profitable, and the unfair disparity does not
exceed the surplus, then the negotiation has infinitely many equitable outcomes. These
correspond to the fictitious mutually beneficial agreements. These agreements constitute a
proper subset of actual mutually beneficial agreements. The actual disagreement outcome is
inequitable.
{ } . c 0 UE d M M E E e . c ' = . = s < (22)
4. If the actual negotiation is unfair but potentially profitable, and the unfair disparity exceeds
the surplus, then no outcome is equitable.
. 0 C = < < E (23)
Proofs to these properties are provided in Appendix A.2.
It may seem natural that a negotiation outcome must be equitable to be considered just. But
this requirement is too stringent to be reasonable, as it would prohibit inequitable mutually
beneficial agreements when no equitable agreement is available (property 4). Worse yet, the
prohibition will take effect precisely when the weaker party more desperately needs to exchange.
This is because the disparity in outside options is more unfair when the weaker partys outside
option is more disastrous.
We propose a less stringent definition of justice that avoids this problem. We affirm that the
just outcomes correspond to the implementable non-supererogatory outcomes of

the fictitious
negotiation. These are the outcomes that two self-interested and rational parties could reach
euvoluntarily if the fictitious negotiation actually took place.
In formal terms, the set of just outcomes is
S N X J ' = (24)
The unjust outcomes, on the other hand, correspond to the non-supererogatory outcomes that
are not just:
. J NS UJ = (25)
The sets of just and unjust outcomes are decomposed in Table 1.
15
Properties of the just outcomes
1. If the actual negotiation is fair, then all non-supererogatory outcomes are both equitable
and just (including the disagreement outcome). Therefore, exchange is morally optional.
{ }. 0 d M NS E J = = = = (26)
2. If the actual negotiation is unfair and has zero surplus, the disagreement outcome is just,
although it is not equitable. This outcome coincides with the unique mutually beneficial
agreement of the actual negotiation, which is also just. Therefore, exchange is morally
optional.
{ } . 0 0 UF d M d J e . = = = . > (27)
3. If the actual negotiation is unfair but potentially profitable, and the unfair disparity does not
exceed the surplus, then the negotiation has infinitely many just outcomes. Just and
equitable outcomes are the same, and correspond to the fictitious mutually beneficial
agreements, which constitute a proper subset of actual mutually beneficial agreements. The
actual disagreement outcome is unjust. Therefore, the stronger party is morally obliged to
exchange with the weaker party.
. c 0 UJ d M M E J J e . c ' = = . = s < (28)
4. If the actual negotiation is unfair but potentially profitable, and the unfair disparity exceeds
the surplus, then the fictitious disagreement outcome is the only just outcome, although it is
inequitable. The just outcome assigns the entire surplus of the actual negotiation to the
weaker party, so the stronger party is left indifferent between exchanging and not
exchanging. The actual disagreement outcome is unjust. Therefore, the stronger party is
morally obliged to exchange with the weaker party.
{ } . ) , ( 0
2 1
UJ d d d d UE d d M J e . + = ' . e ' . ' = ' = < < (29)
Proofs to these properties are provided in Appendix A.3.
As a corollary to these properties, we have:
1. All negotiations have at least one just outcome.
2. All equitable outcomes are just.
3. If a negotiation has at least one equitable outcome, then the just and equitable outcomes
coincide.
16
4. If a negotiation does not have an equitable outcome, then it has a unique just outcome,
which assigns the entire surplus to the weaker party.
5. If the negotiation is unfair but potentially profitable, then a disagreement is unjust.
5 Examples
5.1 A ship without an anchor
A ship at sea that has an anchor to spare meets another which has lost all her
anchors. What here shall be the just price that she shall sell her anchor to the
distressed ship? (Locke, 1661/2005, Venditio, p.p. 4456)
Denote by 0
1
> u the use value of a first anchor, and by 0
2
> u the use value of a spare. Since
the lack of an anchor is dangerous, the use value of a main anchor is quite high, approaching the
value of the ship plus the value of its cargo and a value for the lives of the passengers and crews.
A spare anchor is inessential, but provides valuable insurance against the accidental loss of the first
anchor. Hence,
2 1
u u > . At port, anchors are bought and sold at 0
mkt
> p .
The ships outside options correspond to the status quo:

, 2
, 0
mkt 2 1 2
1
p u u d
d
+ + =
=
(30)
where ship 1 is the distressed ship, and ship 2 is the rescuer. The outside option of the rescuer ship
includes the market price of her anchors, because at the end of her voyage the ship will sell them
at the port. Or, what amounts to the same thing, the ship could sell the anchors to herself at the
market price to use again on a future voyage.
The distressed ship values the anchor at
mkt 1
p u + , while the rescuer ship values it in
mkt 2
p u + . The surplus of the negotiation is equal to the difference in valuations:
. 0
2 1
> = u u (31)
Following Locke, we will assume that the prospect of a shipwreck is so dire that the unfair
disparity is greater than zero:
. 0 ) 0 ( 2
mkt 2 1
> + + = p u u (32)
Locke argues in his Venditio that the only just price for the spare anchor is its market price plus
its use value for the rescuer ship. At that price, the rescuer is indifferent between selling and not
selling. Locke claims that the rescuer is not obliged to perform a supererogatory act and simply
17
give away the anchor. But at the same time he claims that the rescuer ship may not profit from the
distress of the other ship, recognizing that profit in this case means taking a price above the
price required to make the rescuer ship indifferent between selling and not selling.
Under reasonable parameterizations, a fictitious negotiation would lead to the same conclusion
reached by Locke. Recall that the non-worseness clause is activated if the unfair disparity is larger
than the surplus. In the case at hand, this condition reduces to
( ) . 0 ) 0 ( 2
mkt 2
> + = p u (33)
Most people would agree that the value of human life is so high that the disparity threshold in this
case must be extremely low, probably close to zero. This implies that the previous condition is
met. As Locke intuited, the rescuer ship has a duty to hand over the entire surplus to the distressed
ship, but not a penny more. Moreover, and contrary to Lockes intuition
6
, the rescuer boat is
morally obliged to exchange with the distressed ship. The rescuer cannot argue that property rights
allow her to refuse the sale.
5.2 Competitive market exchange
Is it just to charge high prices for an essential commodity? We argue that the answer is yes,
provided the market for the commodity is competitive. All competitive market exchanges are just,
because they do not generate a surplus. We show this below.
A producer and a consumer are bargaining over the price of a certain commodity, which is also
traded in a competitive market. Let 0 > c be the cost of producing the commodity, and let u be its
use value for the consumer. The parties alternative to the exchange is trading with someone else in
the market. Denote by
mkt
p the market price of the good, and assume that u p c < <
mkt
. Let
prod
w be the wealth of the producer, and let
cons
w be the wealth of the consumer. It follows that
the outside options are

.
,
cons mkt cons
prod mkt prod
w p u d
w c p d
+ =
+ =
(34)
Also, if an agreement is reached, then

,
,
cons cons
prod prod
w p u x
w c p x
+ =
+ =
(35)

6
As Locke put it: And in this case the master of the vessel must make his estimate by the length of his voyage, the season
and seas he sails in, and so what risk he shall run himself by parting with his [extra] anchor, which all put together he would not part with
it at any rate, but if he would, he must then take no more for it from a ship in distress than he would from any other. In other
words, there is no obligation to sell the extra anchor, though the value of the first anchor to the distress ship is clearly higher than
the second anchor to the other ship.
18
where p is the price agreed between the parties. Therefore, the surplus created by the exchange is
given by
( ) ( ) ( ) ( )
, 0

cons mkt prod mkt cons prod


cons prod cons prod
=
+ + + + + =
+ =
w p u w c p w p u w c p
d d x x
(36)
since all terms are cancelled in the subtraction. Because the surplus of the negotiation is zero, the
unique just agreement is equivalent to the disagreement outcome. Also, the disagreement outcome
and the unique mutually beneficial agreement coincide. Hence, exchange is morally optional.
The above reasoning is valid even in scenarios of extreme shortage of basic necessities. Locke
provides the following example.
[L]et us suppose a merchant of Danzig sends two ships laden with corn, whereof
the one puts into Dunkirk, where there is almost a famine for want of corn, and there
he sells his wheat for 20s a bushel, whilst the other ship sells his at Ostend just by for
5s. Here it will be demanded whether it be not oppression and injustice to make such
an advantage of their necessity at Dunkirk as to sell them the same commodity at 20s
per bushel which he sells for a quarter the price but twenty miles off? (Locke,
1661/2005, Venditio, p. 444)
In this example, the market price is 20s a bushel, while the production cost is 5s, because the
cost of producing a bushel of corn is the alternative cost of not selling it for 5s at Ostend.
Despite the great sales margin, the corn market is competitive in Dunkirk. This is evidenced by the
fact that the merchant is a mere price taker. It follows that corn sales yield zero surplus, which in
turn implies that the market price is just.
Locke reaches the same conclusion, although his makes a slightly different argument. His
argument is based on the concepts of price discrimination and arbitrage:
[The merchant commits no injustice], because he sells at the market rate at the
place where he is [Dunkirk], but he sells there no dearer to Thomas as he would to
Richard. And if there he should sell for less than his corn would yield, he would only
throws his profit into other mens hands, who buying of him under the market rate
would sell it again to others at the full rate it would yield. (Locke, op. cit., p. 444.)
5.3 Price gouging in Dunkirk
Consider the alternative scenario in which our merchant is the first to arrive at Dunkirk. This gives
the merchant an enormous bargaining power: If the people do not accept his prices, the merchant
can take his business to Ostend, while they go hungry waiting for the arrival of more supplies. At
19
the same time, the intense hunger of the people of Dunkirk, combined with the low cost of corn,
results in a huge negotiation surplus. Given these circumstances, the analytical theory of just
market exchange stipulates that the merchant must sell his corn at a low price, perhaps even at
cost.
Suppose that Thomas desperately needs corn for his own consumption, but he also detects a
business opportunity: Richard, his neighbor, is unaware of the arrival of the merchant. So the
cunning Thomas goes to the just merchants shop and asks for two bushels of corn, with the
secret intention of keeping one bushel for himself and selling the other to Richard at a higher
price.
The merchant feels obliged to sell the bushels to Thomas at a low price. But the merchant,
who is not a fool, anticipates Thomas intentions. The merchant knows that Thomas will resell one
bushel at an abusively high price, to someone who also has a desperate need of corn. What shall
the merchant do? This contradiction between two imperatives, make a just exchange and prevent
an abusive exchange, appears to invalidate our theory.
But the contradiction is only apparent. It arises from the violation of a simplifying assumption
of the fictitious negotiation model, not from an incoherence of its moral premises. The fictitious
negotiation model assumes the existence of only two agents, and rules out externalities. This
assumption ceases to be valid in scenarios in which the exchange may unjustly harm third parties.
In Lockes example, that third party is Richard.
Nevertheless, the logic of the theory of just market exchange extends naturally to the multi-
agent case, as illustrated by the following argument. Given his privileged position, the merchant is
morally obliged to sell corn to Thomas at a discount price, but he has the same obligation toward
every famished person in Dunkirk. Therefore, if Thomas resold one of his bushels at a high price,
the merchant wound fail in his duty to an anonymous buyer, who is as desperate as Thomas. To
fulfill his duty, all that the merchant needs to do is sell a single bushel to each costumer. In times
of famine, price caps and rationing are the moral market strategy.
5.4 Sharecropping
The harvest has just ended and the hacendado and his inquilino renegotiate their sharecropping
agreement. What agreement would be just?
Suppose that the parties expect that the value of the next harvest will be 0 > h . If an agreement
is reached between the parties, the inquilino will have to incur a cost of 0 > c (this includes food,
effort, etc.), while the hacendado will have to invest to invest a total of 0 > i (these includes seeds,
fertilizers, etc.). The value of the crop is enough to cover all the costs of production: i c h + > .
Thus, the set of potential agreements is given by
{ }, : ) , (
H I H I
i c h x x x x A = + = (37)
20
where subscript i identifies the inquilino and subscript H identifies the hacendado.
If the hacendado and his inquilino fail to reach an agreement, the inquilino may move out from
the hacienda and seek work elsewhere as a day laborer. The hacendado, on the other hand, is free to
evict the inquilino and hire day laborers at market wage w . However, the harvest would suffer due
to the day laborers lack of skills and lower effort. It is expected that the harvest will fall from h to
h . The outside options are thus,

.
,
H
I
w i h d
c w d
=
=
(38)
Both outside options are positive.
The surplus of the negotiation is given by
.
H I
h h d d v = = (39)
This surplus is small but not negligible, because day laborers are imperfect substitutes for the
inquilino.
As is usual in the countryside, the hacendado is the stronger party to the negotiation, and the
negotiation is unfair. That is,
. 0 ) ( 2 ) (
I I I H
> = = d w i c h d d d (40)
The unfair disparity is positive but not dramatically high, because the inquilino has a poor but
relatively decent outside option.
What is the minimum payoff to the inquilino that would satisfy the requirements of justice?
According to our theory, the answer is his fictitious outside option.
{ } { }. , min , min
I I
+ = + = ' c w d d (41)
This fictitious outside option may or may not eliminate the unfair disparity, depending on whether
or not s . Both scenarios are plausible, since is positive but not dramatically high, and
is small but not negligible.
Let
I
w be the implicit wage that the inquilino would earn if he stayed at the hacienda. The
payoff to the inquilino would be his wage minus the costs he incurs. That is, c w x =
I I
. We also
know that, the minimum just payoff to the inquilino is his outside option
I
d ' . Hence, a just
implicit wage satisfies:
{ }. , min
I I
+ = + ' > w c d w (42)
21
This means that the hacendado is not only morally forbidden to evict the inquilino from his
hacienda. He is also obliged to pay the inquilino a higher salary than he would earn working as a
day laborer. In the extreme case that > , the inquilino must earn exactly
,
I
h h w w w + = + = (43)
That is, the wage of a day laborer plus the harvest that would be lost if the inquilino moved out
from the hacienda. The payoff to the hacendado would thus be
.
H
w i h w i h x
H
= = (44)
In words, the hacendado must content with the same profit that he would obtain if he hired day
laborers instead of keeping the inquilino.
6 Concluding remarks
The main modern theories of justice commit themselves to a strictly deductive approach ( la
Kant). The theorist first dictates a finite set of universal moral axioms, which are self-evident and
therefore must be accepted by every morally-sane person. The axiomatic theory is supposed to
work as an automated reasoning machine that receives as an input a moral dilemma and produces
as an output a moral judgment. Many times, perhaps most of the time, the moral judgments appear
to be reasonable, or at least defensible, as general propositions. But inevitably, the machine will
face a confounding moral dilemma, of the sort in which philosophers delight. At this point, instead
of delivering an obvious or intuitively sensible result, the axiom machine will deliver a judgment so
repugnant that the axioms are rendered untenable. And so the machine is scrapped, thrown into a
pile with all the other broken axiomatic systems.
Confronted with this predicament, the theorist takes one of two ways out. The first is to stick
to the logical consequence of his theory, no matter how absurd. This was Kants gallant reaction
when posed with the following dilemma: would you tell the truth to a murderer that knocks on
your door, and asks you if his victim is hiding inside your house? Kant (1797) maintained that he
would not lie, because not to lie is a categorical imperative. Instead, he would give an ambiguous
answer to the murderer: I do not know if he is. Needless to say, few people consider this to be a
rightful answer in such a situation.
The second way out for the theorist is to patch his theory with a list of exceptions. Consider
the libertarian traditional justification of private property rights. In Lockes words,
Though the earth, and all inferior creatures, be common to all men, yet every man
has a property in his own person: this no body has any right to but himself. The
labour of his body, and the work of his hands, we may say, are properly his.
22
Whatsoever then he removes out of the state that nature hath provided, and left it in,
he hath mixed his labour with, and joined to it something that is his own, and thereby
makes it his property. It being by him removed from the common state nature hath
placed it in, it hath by this labour something annexed to it, that excludes the common
right of other men: for this labour being the unquestionable property of the labourer,
no man but he can have a right to what that is once joined to, at least where there is
enough, and as good, left in common for others. [Locke, 1661/2005, Second Treatise of
Government, Chapter V, Sec. 27; emphasis added).]
Nozick (1974) calls Lockes final qualification the Lockean proviso. This can be summarized as
follows: homesteading private property by mixing labor with natural resources is legitimate only
where there is enough for everyone.
In his own libertarian manifesto, Nozick applies the Lockean proviso to the following
examples:
Once it is known that someones ownership runs afoul of the Lockean proviso,
there are stringent limits on what he may do with (what it is difficult any longer
unreservedly to call) his property. Thus a person may not appropriate the only water
hole in a desert and charge what he will. Nor may he charge what he will if he
possesses one, and unfortunately it happens that all the water holes in the desert dry
up, except for his. This unfortunate circumstance, admittedly no fault of his, brings
into operation the Lockean proviso and limits his property rights. Similarly, an
owners property right in the only island in an area does not allow him to order a
castaway from a shipwreck off his island as a trespasser, for this would violate the
Lockean proviso. (Locke, 1974, p. 180)
In other words, Nozick backs himself into a corner, and then invokes to his defense a deux ex
machina. Property rights are absolute, unless they are not. No one is obliged to share a glass of
water, except that one may be obliged under some circumstances to do just that.
The fundamental flaw with Nozicks line of argument is that the specific meaning of
sufficient is subjective, casting down the claim to universality of the libertarian axioms. It can
even be argued, as economists do, that resources are always scarce (Robbins 1939). In this limiting
case, the libertarian justification of property rights collapses into one big exception that ironically
precludes all private property.
The natural alternative to strict moral deductivism is sentimentalism, a moral philosophy that
posits that moral judgments are based on feelings rather than universal moral principles. One of
the foremost sentimentalists is David Hume
7
(2000, p. 325), who wrote:

7
Humes sentimentalist beliefs were shared by his friend Adam Smith (Smith, 1759), and both friends were influenced by the
earlier writings of Anthony Ashley Cooper (Cooper, 1737), and Francis Hutcheson (Hutcheson, 1728).
23
Morals excite passions, and produce or prevent actions. Reason itself is utterly
impotent in this particular. The rules of morality, therefore, are not conclusions of our
reason.

Sentimentalism is the ultimate version of moral relativism: anything is right, as long as you feel
it is right. For its refusal to deliver judgments, sentimentalism is useless as a moral philosophy. But
this is a minor flaw compared to its absolute empirical failure. Systematic observation of human
behavior falsifies the sentimentalist claim that in matters of moral values, anything goes (Rachels
1995). Certainly, moral values vary broadly across people and cultures, but they do not vary
haphazardly. There is a structure to values (Rachels 1995, Brown 1991).
We argue that moral universals exist, but not in the form of a minimal list of principles shared
by all cultures, as suggested by Rachels (1999) and others. Moral universals are not principles but
logical structures that constrain the set of plausible moral theories. The scope of disagreement is
tightly limited to the specific values of parameters that modulate a set of moral axioms. Therefore,
this approach to moral philosophy is neither strictly deductive nor sentimentalist, but parametric.
To be more precise, universals are captured by parametric meta-theories of morality. Depending
on the values taken by its parameters, a meta-theory produces a particular, concrete moral theory.
The analytical theory of just market exchange is an example of a parametric meta-theory. The
free parameter of the theory is the disparity threshold function, which quantifies the observers
revulsion toward unfairness. The fictitious negotiation model provides the logical scaffolding.
The analogy between the analytical theory of just market exchange and the utility theory
clarifies the parametric approach. Preferences can vary broadly among people, but utility theory
requires four conditions for rationality: completeness, reflexivity, transitivity, and continuity. Many
nonsensical preference rankings are ruled out by these axioms.
For example: Carlos cannot prefer simultaneously an apple to an orange, an orange to a
banana, and a banana to an apple. The utility theory then dictates that a rational person must
maximize utility subject to his budget constraint. Every rational person must obey this dictation,
regardless of his particular utility function. Otherwise, he would not be rational. In a similar
fashion, the analytical theory of just market exchange admits that aversion to unfairness (e.g., to
disparity in outside options) can vary broadly among people. But the theory also establishes that all
disagreements in aversion to unfairness are captured by differences in the non-decreasing disparity
threshold functions .
The theory then dictates that a just person is obliged to use the fictitious negotiation model to
judge the morality of a market exchange. Every just person must obey this imperative, regardless of
his particular disparity threshold function.
24
The fictitious negotiation model produces logical consequences that are morally intuitive. This
is appealing, if the theory unifies conflicting commonsense principles under a single framework.
8

Of course, consistency is not necessary for acceptance; existing moral intuitions do not constitute
an empirical test of an axiomatic theory. In fact, axiomatic theories can re-educate intuition by
means of persuasion. They can also guide action when several moral principles come into conflict
and none seems to dominate over the others. In fact, this is precisely why we need moral
philosophy on the first place: the need to assist intuition in the hard cases afforded to us by
moral dilemmas.
9

For its parametric character, our theory can be considered part of the market democracy
research program initiated by Tomasi:
I propose we treat justice as fairnessas a living research program. The general
definition of justice as fairness leaves room for a significant (but bounded) range of
disagreement about the requirements of liberal justice. These ambiguities and tensions
are fundamental features of justice as fairness. They spring from the complex nature
of the bedrock liberal idea that citizens are free and equal moral beings. (Tomasi 2012;
p. 179).
In this spirit, we recognize that there are substantial discrepancies about what makes a fair
negotiation and a just market exchange. But these differences are bounded by the seemingly
universal moral sentiment that all persons posses an essential dignity. In market interactions, the
prohibition of voluntary exchanges tramples this dignity, as does the arbitrary imposition of terms
of exchange by an enlightened third party. In the market, human dignity is honored by respecting
the liberty of others, and by refraining from abusing power and from harming others, either by act
or omission.
These are the axioms that constitute our theory.


8
As Kamm (1993, p. 26) explains: [One] philosophical method (there may others) begins with responses to
cases This procedure is attractive because it permits recognition of new factors that may be morally relevant in
certain cases, factors emphasized by no theory yet developed. Philosophers using this method try to unearth the
reasons for particular responses to a case and to construct more general principles from these data. They then
evaluate these principles in three ways: Do they fit the intuitive responses? Are their basic concepts coherent and
distinct from one another? Are the principles or basic concepts in them morally plausible and significant, or even
rationally demanded? The attempt to determine whether the concepts and the principles are morally significant and
even required by reason is necessary in order to understand why the principles derived from cases should be
endorsed.
9
Insofar as they are truly hard. Kants murderer dilemma, for example, is not really a dilemma, but a
provocation.
25
References
Brown, Donald. E. 1991. Human Universals. McGraw-Hill.
Colburn, Ben. 2008. The Concept of Voluntariness. Journal of Political Philosophy. 16: 101-111.
Cooper, Anthony Ashley (3
rd
Earl of Shaftesbury). 1737 / 2001. An Inquiry Concerning Virture
and Merit. In Characteristicks of Men, Manners, Opinions, Times, ed. Douglas den Uyl
(Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 2001). Vol. 2.
Giberson, Michael. 2011. "The Problem with Price Gouging Laws: Is optimal pricing during an
emergency unethical?" Regulation. Spring: 48-53.
Gaus, G. F. (2007). Social Complexity and Evolved Moral Principles. In P. McNamara (Ed.),
Liberalism
Gaus, G. F. (2009). Is the Public Incompetent? Compared to Whom? About What? Critical Review:
A Journal of Politics and Society, vol. 20 (2009): 291-311.

Hutcheson, Francis. 1728 / 2003. An Essay on the Nature and Conduct of the Passions and Affections,
with Illustrations on the Moral Sense. Kund Haadonssen and Aaron Garrett (eds.). Indianapolis:
Liberty Fund.
Hume, David. 2000. A treatise of human nature: being an attempt to introduce the experimental method of
reasoning into moral subjects. David Norton and Mary Norton (eds), Oxford University
Press.
Kamm, Frances M. 1993. Morality, Mortality: Volume I: Death and Whom to Save From It.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kant, Immanuel. 1797 / 1976. "On A Supposed Right to Lie From Altruistic Motives." In
Critique of Practical Reason and Other Writings in Moral Philosophy. L. B. White (ed.), Garland
Press.
Locke, John. 1661 / 2004. Venditio. Locke: Political Writings (ed. By David Wooton). Hackett
Publishing.
Munger, Michael. 2011. Euvoluntary or Not, Exchange is Just. Social Philosophy and Policy 28(2):
19211.
Nozick, Robert. 1974. Anarchy, State, and Utopia. Basic Books.
Olsaretti, Serena. 2004. Liberty, Desert, and the Market. Campbridge University Press.
Rachels, James. 1999, The Challenge of Cultural Relativism, The Elements of Moral Philosophy,
3rd ed., New York: Random House, 2036.
26
Robbins, Lionel. 1939. The Economic Causes of War. London: Jonathan Cape.
Sample, R. 2003. Exploitation: What it is and why it's wrong. New York: Rowman and Littlefield.
SASL. 2001. Scholars Against Sweatshop Labor Statement. Available at
http://www.peri.umass.edu/SASL-Statement.253.0.html . Accessed September 12, 2006.
Sandel, Michael. 1998. "What Money Can't Buy: The Moral Limits of Markets." The Tanner
Lectures on Human Values, Delivered at Brasenose College, Oxford, May 11 and 12.
Reprinted in Hedgehog Review, Summer 2003.
Smith, Adam. 1759 / 1982. The Theory of Moral Sentiments, D.D. Raphael and A.L. Macfie, eds,
vol. I of the Glasgow Edition of the Works and Correspondence of Adam Smith Indianapolis:
Liberty Fund.
Tomasi, John. 2012. Free Market Fairness. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Wertheimer, A. 1996. Exploitation. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Wu, Wenbo, and Otto Davis. 1999a. The Two Freedoms, Economic Growth and
Development: An Empirical Study. Public Choice. 100: 39-64.
Wu, Wenbo, and Otto Davis. 1999b. The two freedoms in a growth model. Journal of Private
Enterprise. 14: 11543.
Zwolinski, Matthew. 2008. "The Ethics of Price-Gouging." Business Ethics Quarterly. 18(3): 347-373.
Zwolinski, Matthew. 2009. "Price Gouging, Non-worseness, and Distributive Justice." Business
Ethics Quarterly, 19(2): 295-306.

Вам также может понравиться