Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 4

Neurobiological Bases for Cognitive Schemas

The earliest clinical conceptions of schemas is evident in pioneering works of Pierre Janet, who posited the existence of schemas moderated by memory processes which acted as mental organizing systems. When acting smoothly and functionally, these schemas would incorporate new information into existing knowledge structures resulting in mental order and organization !avies, "##$%. Piaget "#$&% elaborated on these early concepts through his notions of accommodation andassimilation, theorizing that psychic trauma involved uncharacteristic events with a strong affective valence which could not be readily assimilated into the existing schema structures. Piaget sought to investigate some of the psychological functions which do the kind of information processing later ascribed to the schemas. Traditionally, cognitive theory has distinguished two 'levels( of cognitive phenomena) automatic thoughts, cognitive distortions, and schemas and named variously in the literature as 'schemata(%. *utomatic thoughts are described as 'a surface level of cognition that can be brought into awareness fairly readily( +ahoney, "##,, p. -&%. They represent spontaneous cognitive leaps which reflect the individual.s predisposition to interpret reality in a certain way. /n this sense automatic thoughts can be taken as 'symptoms( of the deeper schemas. 0re1uently2cited examples of automatic thoughts are the readiness with which depressed persons interpret events in such a way as to cast themselves as worthless or helpless, whereas anxious persons tend to experience automatic thoughts concerned with danger and threat. 3ognitive distortions are taken to be the epistemological interface between automatic thoughts and the more generalized schemas. True to the information2processing model so influential in cognitive theory, cognitive distortions have been defined by 4obins 5 6ayes "##,% this way) '3ognitive distortions are links between dysfunctional schemata and automatic thoughts. When new information or memories are cognitively processed, the information often is distorted or biased to fit a relevant schema. The result of this biased appraisal may then become accessible to consciousness in the form of automatic thoughts or images( p. -7%. !aca gandurile cognitive sunt fenomene de suprafata si distorisiunile cognitive sunt biasarile procesuale de nivel mediu care le genereaza, atunci schemele sunt motoarele generatoare ale intregului sistem cognitiv. /f automatic thoughts are the surface2level phenomenon and cognitive distortions the mid2level processing biases which generate them, then the schemas are the generative engines of the whole cognitive system. *aron 8eck defined a schema as 'a structure for screening, coding, and evaluating the stimuli that impinge upon an organism9 :n the basis of the matrix of schemas, the individual is able to orient himself in relation to time and space and to categorize an interpret experiences in a meaningful way( 8eck, "#$;, p. -"#%. There is, of course, no perfect unanimity in the operationalization of the construct, but in general schema are assumed to be 'working models( composed of thematically related belief systems which are assembled during the course of life experience. <ome models see below% emphasize early experience in the formation of schemas, but the practice of cognitive2oriented psychotherapy depends on the presumption that they may be modified at any time during life. The schema owed its integrity on the processing biases which they generate, which help to ensure that in the midst of everyday interpersonal experience, data which most closely fits the schema will be 'encoded( most 1uickly and efficiently. +ore recently, =oung has added to this paradigm an emphasis on a 'deeper( level of cognition, termed early maladaptive schemas. =oung defines these 'deep( schemas as 'broad, pervasive themes regarding oneself and one.s relationship to others, developed during childhood and elaborated throughout one.s lifetime, which are dysfunctional to a significant degree( =oung, "##-%. *ccording to =oung.s formulation, early schemas develop 'as the result of ongoing, dysfunctional experiences with parents, siblings, and peers during childhood and develop as children attempt to make sense of their experiences and to avoid further pain( +c>inn and =oung, "##$%. =oung.s conceptions of the early maladaptive schemas has received empirical support in <chmidt et al "##,%. These authors identified orthogonal factors corresponding to early maladaptive schemas ?+<s%, which are posited to rest 'at the core of the individual.s self concept( but which '@preventA realistic processing of schema2inconsistent information.(

*s <chmidt et al noted, =oung.s concept of the ?+< is theoretically consistent with more classical formulations of schemas 8eck, "#$;B <egal, "#CC% with a significant exception) =oung.s ?+<s are unconditional '/ am unlovable(% while 8eck.s conception of the schema was conditional '/f / can please others all the time, / will be loved(%. This distinction does not replace or invalidate 8eck.s conceptualization of schemas, but rather suggests that there are hierarchical 'layers( of schemas which may be reduced to the most basic, fundamental, unconditional, and presumably unconscious, presumptions. Parallel neuropsychological analysis of such theoretical structures has been hampered by limitations on the development of techni1ue and methodology. Dntil very recently, neuropsychological research has tended to focus upon 'lower2order,( more directly observable or representable brain processes. *t the same time, cognitive theory has continued along the more theoretical and postulative track, generating plausible models first and then checking for experimental and, more rarely, neuropsychological viability. Piaget, along with his moralist counterpart Eawrence Fohlberg, set out to describe mental representations within a general epistemological frameworkB that is to say, he saw a place for a scientific conceptualization of the mental representation as a new and different way of characterizing psychological processes. 0lanagan "#C#% proposed that what Piaget and Fohlberg% had in mind was to 'chart their way between the <cylla of naGve empiricism and the 3harybdis of extreme nativism and arrive at some empirically and philosophically safe port( p. ""#%. /n this sense, Piaget sought to chart a middle passage between the hard behaviorists and their vision of the mind as tabula rasa on one hand, and the nativists who saw human nature as determined by heredity on the other hand. That is to say, Piaget and others have sought to derive models which make sense at the behavioral level, but which also demonstrate viable 'biological( substrates. The constructivists comprise a sort of 'post2modern( movement within the cognitive school. >rowing out of the literatures of evolutionary epistemology, constructivism seeks to shift focus away from the traditional analysis of beliefs and perceptions and back to the individual.s own activity as the basic mediator of experience. the constructivists presume that individual organisms actively explore their environments and organize experience around pro2active, creative, and, significantly, tacit expectations, hypotheses, and theories see Weimer, "#;,%. The term constructivism itself implies 'form2giving,( which in turn suggests that the individual becomes the architect of her experiences and the world2models she bases on themB this conceptualization significantly differs from the passive receptacle described by the traditional associationist paradigm. 3onstructivism may represent an attempt to fulfill Piaget.s incomplete attempts to divine underlying mechanisms for the categorization of experience. +ahoney et al. "##,% outline three essential features of the constructivist approach) the proactive nature of the cognitive process, nuclear morphogenic structure, and self2organizing development. 3onstructive theory invokes the proactive nature of the cognitive process in arguing that the individual constructs reality not merely on the basis of data supplied by the five senses, but 'in formare, that which is formed from within( p. "H,%. +ahoney et al. note that radical constructivism goes so far as to assume that 'all experienced order is self2generated and organismically recursive( p."H,%. 3learly then, what makes for radicalism in one model would 1ualify for old2school traditionalism in anotherI :nce again the constructivists seem to be 'circling back( towards nativism, which is far from a radical new, maverick hypothesis but rather the long2standing other side of the e1uation long since neglected by traditional associationists in the cognitive2behavioral school. *nother very significant aspect of the proposed proactive nature of cognitive processes challenges the associationist tradition of obJectivism) cognitive2behaviorist theory presumes that there must be an obJective veracity to interpersonal reality against which the various schemas may be assessed in order to determine their relative degree of 'reality distortion.( 3onstructivism, in high post modernist style, argues that since there is no 'obJective reality,( it doesn.t make sense to talk about 'distortions( of reality. There are no cognitive distortions, Just more or less viable hypotheses. +ahoney et al. posit a second feature centering upon 'nuclear morphogenic structure.( This construct implies a central core of processes which are protected from undue change from without, and which in turn limit the flexibility of the peripheral assumptions associated with them. The third proposed aspect of constructivist conceptualization involves self2organizing development of the

personality. >uidano "#C;% describes the idea in the following way) 'The essential feature of this perspective considers the self2organizing ability of a human knowing system as a basic evolutionary constraint9.The availability of this stable and structured self2identity permits continuous and coherent self2perception and self2evaluation in the face of temporal becoming and mutable reality( p. 7%. /n characterizing the constructivist take on self2organization, +ahoney et al. invoke the concept of autopoieses, involving spontaneously self2ordering complex phenomena. The authors recall the work of +anfred ?igen, who described autocatalytic 'hypercycles( intended to bridge biological systems and patterns of thinking see ?igen 5 <chuster, "#;#%. The hypercycles are described by +ahoney et al. "##,% as 'certain dynamic patterns of energy exchange @whichA afford the emergence of self2 perpetuating structures which form the basis for higher2order life support processes in organic systems( p. ""H%. ?igen.s conceptualization is Just one way of operationalizing the emergence of stable knowledge systems from 'random energy dynamics.( /lya Prigogine "#CH% approached the same problem from a somewhat different perspective by introducing 'dissipative structures,( which resembles modern chaos theory in that functional disorganization at a fundamental level serves to effect deep structural reorganization of knowledge systems. <ince theoretical work on schemas has come about 1uite separately from actual neurological or neuropsychological research, it becomes necessary to seek out parallels between the former and the latter in order to postulate a neuropsychological substrate for the schemas. Piaget was one of the first to do this, and set out to describe mental representations within a general epistemological frameworkB that is to say, he saw a place for a scientific conceptualization of the mental representation as a new and different way of characterizing psychological processes. 0lanagan "#C#% proposed that what Piaget and Fohlberg% had in mind was to 'chart their way between the <cylla of naGve empiricism and the 3harybdis of extreme nativism and arrive at some empirically and philosophically safe port( p. ""#%. /n this sense, Piaget sought to chart a middle passage between the hard behaviorists and their vision of the mind as tabula rasa on one hand, and the nativists who saw human nature as determined by heredity on the other hand. :f course, Piaget.s was not the first attempt in the history of human thought to reconcile these apparently opposite polesB the philosophical feud between the followers of Fant, with their promotion of the absolute, and the relativistic followers of +ill provides one historical example. /t could be argued that Piaget and 8eck were not even the first cognitive psychologists96ume anticipated their models when he enumerated the three structural principles of the mind, called 'laws of association() resemblance, contiguity, and cause2and2effect. 6ume.s prescription resembles modern attempts on the part of cognitive psychologists to identify the orthogonal organizing principles of human thought. <uch discrete organizing principles even have their place in theoretical physics in the form of 'strange attractors( which seem to bind both matter and energy. 6owever, Piaget appears to have attempted one of the earliest formulations within modern psychology to reconcile nativist and empiricist approaches, in the creation of the nascent field of cognitive2 developmental constructivism. Piaget sought to circumnavigate the 'excesses( of pure behaviorism by elaborating on the complexity of learned behaviors, and attempting to take into account observed neuropsychological functions. 6e achieved this end by postulating the unfolding development of developmental capacities which result not Just in new experiences, but in 1ualitatively different experiences. That is to say, far from being the inert 'storehouse of ideas( as Eocke originally hypothesized, the mind is e1uipped to impose some kind of order on new experience, sorting them in a new way9via the schemas. Piaget counters nativism by highlighting the sensitivity of the developing mind to environmental conditions and to its apparent development of completely novel cognitive strategies for interacting with the environment. 0lanagan "#C#% summarized the argument this way) 'The thinking of an intelligent eighteen2year2old differs from the thinking of an intelligent one2year2old not only in content 2 for example, in thinking about sex, music and geometry as opposes to blocks, the sandbox, and the mother.s breast2 but in form as well. The eighteen2year old is able to represent things to herself linguistically, to rotate geometrical figures mentally, to deploy deductive proof procedures, to make reliable inductive references, and to utilize unconsciously and unerringly the principles of conservation and transivity9( p. "&&%

* nativist response to the cognitive2developmental caveat is articulated by 0odor in 0lanagan, "#C#%) 'it is never possible to learn a richer logic on the basis of a weaker logic, if what you mean by learning is hypothesis formation and confirmation( p. "7C%. That is to say, it does not appear likely that the mind would be able to make up 1uantum2leap advancements in spatial perception out of whole cloth, without the ingredients for such an advancement already being present in some fashion in the construction of the developing brain. This counter2argument suggests that the more complex and refined cognitive processes vaunted by Piaget are somehow 'already there( in a nascent state, ready to be accessed in the right way by a developing mind that already knows everything it is ever going to know. The existence of such 'already there( elements has been labeled preformation. /n supporting preformation, 0odor, of course, champions the nativist cause, along with his colleague Koam 3homsky. 3homsky.s debate with Piaget on the nature and origin of psychological functions such as speech% is one of the better2known arenas of contention within this area, and reflect the epistemological importance of the 1uestion see 3homsky, "#CH%. 3homsky, 0odor, and the nativists respond to the associationist by repeating the classical formula) ex nihil nihil fit, nothing comes of nothing. The possibility of preformation, ore indeed any evidence of preformation, will naturally lead to a search for neuropsychological substrates which may account for such inborn facilities. Luite apart from theoretical schemes designed to locate cognitive structures anatomically, recent work has attempted to investigate orthogonal factors determining interpersonal and social behavior via schemas and related constructs. <uch cognitive mediators have included locus of control 4otter, "#$$%, attributional style *nderson, 6orowitz, 5 0rench, "#C7%, individual sensemaking 6arris, "##-%, social categorization +oskowitz, "##7%, chronically accessible constructs <orrentino 5 <hort, "#C$%, and many others. This diverse body of research has convincingly indicated the pervasive power of schema and their network of assumptions and presumptions, from word choice in everyday speech ?dwards 5 Pearce, "##-% to parenting styles 8ugental , 8rown, 5 4eiss, "##$%. There have been some neuropsychological findings which have to some extent gone beyond the limits encountered by Piaget, due to the development of new diagnostic and exploratory technology and methodology. These newer sorts of studies show 'up2close( neuropsychological mechanisms which may well be implicated in the formation and maintenance of cognitive schemas. 6owever, current understanding of the neurological substrate for intentionality, motivation, and consciousness suggest that such high2level cognitive processes are not seated in any singly area of the brain but instead seem to arise from complex feedback2loops based on neural pathways linking numerous neuropsychological functions. This kind of system allows a perceptually2driven field of consciousness, in which input from the sensorium is selectively attended by attentional resources, based on feedback originating in complex motivational systems. <uch mechanisms may play a part in the formation of schemas based on patterned tendencies built into the brain. <everal recent studies have implicated the cingulate gyrus in determining hierarchical relationships in cognitive processing, especially in the top2down organizational scheme which is evident in priming tasks *ston2Jones at al, "###%. <uch discoveries encourage the hypothesis that the mind functions largely categorically, with 'nested( subroutines based on deeper and more fundamental systems. Phelps et al "##C% examined the role of the amygdala in emotional memory, comparing a ,-2year old female with bilateral amygdala damage to controls. 4esults indicated deficits in fear conditioning and recognition memory for arousing stimuli, but only when episodic memory is marked by an arousal state not when the memory itself contained an emotional valence%. The authors postulate that the amygdala may contribute to the formation of episodic memories through the organization of 'an organizing principle such as a schema or category( p. ,7$%. This finding tends to lend credence to the formation of schemas around a nodal point of affectively charged experience, with the participation of the amygdala. <everal models of schema development count on the input of emotional experience in the formation of enduring associative complexes see Winter 5 Fuiper, "##;%.

Вам также может понравиться