Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 17

http://plato.stanford.

edu/entries/naturalism-mathematics/
Naturalism in the Philosophy of Mathematics
First published Sun Aug 24, 2008; substantive revision Tue Mar 26, 2013
Contemporary philosophy's three main naturalisms are methodological, ontological and
epistemological. Methodological naturalism states that the only authoritative standards are those of
science. Ontological and epistemological naturalism respectively state that all entities and all valid
methods of inquiry are in some sense natural. In philosophy of mathematics of the past few decades
methodological naturalism has received the lion's share of the attention, so we concentrate on this.
Ontological and epistemological naturalism in the philosophy of mathematics are discussed more
briefly in section 6.
1. Methodological Naturalism
Methodological naturalism has three principal and related senses in the philosophy of mathematics.
The first is that the only authoritative standards in the philosophy of mathematics are those of
natural science (physics, biology, etc.). The second is that the only authoritative standards in the
philosophy of mathematics are those of mathematics itself. The third, an amalgam of the first two,
is that the authoritative standards are those of natural science and mathematics. We refer to these
three naturalisms as scientific, mathematical, and mathematical-cum-scientific. Note that throughout
this entry science and cognate terms encompass only the natural sciences.
1.1 Mathematical Anti-Revisionism
Naturalismmethodological and in the philosophy of mathematics hereafter understood
seems to have anti-revisionary consequences for mathematics. The mathematician-philosopher
L.E.J. Brouwer developed intuitionistic mathematics, which sought to overthrow and replace
standard (classical) mathematics. Brouwer attempted to motivate intuitionistic mathematics
philosophically with an intuition-based account of mathematical truth. A more recent exponent of
intuitionistic mathematics is Michael Dummett, who has developed arguments from the philosophy
of language, in particular the theory of meaning, on its behalf. Yet scientific standards arguably
condone classical over intuitionistic mathematics: even if present-day science could be entirely
recast intuitionisticallya big ifit would be less simple and more cumbersome than its current
classically-based version. Mathematicians also tend to view intuitionistic mathematics as inferior to
classical mathematics if construed as a rival to it. Hence neither Brouwer nor Dummett's
intuitionism is apparently sanctioned by scientific or mathematical standards, so naturalism rules
them out of court. Indeed, for many of its adherents, that is precisely naturalism's point. Its point, it
is often thought, is to block fanciful attacks on established disciplines such as mathematics by
disciplines with less secure methodologies.
2. Recent History of Methodological Naturalism
2.1 Recent Background
Contemporary interest in naturalism stems from Quine, whose naturalism is prominent in his later
works. A representative quotation is that naturalism is the recognition that it is within science
itself, and not in some prior philosophy, that reality is to be identified and described (Quine 1981,
21). Another major influence is Hilary Putnam, who articulates his scientific naturalism as follows:
it is silly to agree that a reason for believing that p warrants accepting p in all scientific
circumstances, and then to add but even so it is not good enough. Such a judgement could only be
made if one accepted a trans-scientific method as superior to the scientific method; but this
philosopher, at least, has no interest in doing that. (Putnam 1971, 356)
Thus from this perspective mathematics is judged by scientific standards because everything is.
Moreover, Quine and Putnam maintain that these standards sanction platonist mathematics because
mathematics and its platonist construal are an indispensable part of our best scientific theories.
Although naturalism as a self-conscious position in the philosophy of mathematics emerges most
fully with Quine there are, as always, precursors. The empiricist tradition in its various guises
(logical positivism, Mill, Hume, etc.) is the most obvious precursor, though there are significant
differences between pre-Quinean empiricists and contemporary naturalists. The rise of scientific
naturalism in the philosophy of mathematics also coincides with a rise in a broader scientific
naturalism, also in part attributable to Quine, which sees all philosophynot just philosophy of
mathematicsas taking place within natural science. Naturalism also goes hand in hand with a now
generally prevalent pessimism about traditional philosophical modes of argumentation.
Some version of naturalism is attractive to virtually all philosophers today. That the methodologies
of mathematics and science are the best we have seems a platitude, which philosophy should try to
acknowledge and build on rather than ignore. The question is how exactly to do so.
2.2 Present context
The past couple of decades have seen a great surge of interest in naturalism. 1997 was an important
year in recent philosophy of mathematics, as it saw the publication of four books articulating the
positions of five leading philosophers of mathematics: John Burgess and Gideon Rosen's A Subject
with No Object, Penelope Maddy's Naturalism in Mathematics, Michael Resnik's Mathematics as
the Science of Patterns, and Stewart Shapiro's Philosophy of Mathematics. All four books are to
various degrees and amongst other things naturalistic: the first two are naturalist manifestos, the
third advocates a Quinean scientific naturalism, and the last, though mainly concerned with other
matters, is sympathetic to naturalism. John Burgess's naturalism, first set out in his (1983) and in the
past few years elaborated with his colleague Gideon Rosen (1997, 2005), is perhaps most naturally
construed as a version of mathematical-cum-scientific naturalism (1997, 211). Penelope Maddy's
naturalism is a heterogeneous form of naturalism which distinguishes between mathematics proper
and the philosophy of mathematics, embracing mathematical naturalism about the former and
scientific naturalism about the latter (section 5). Another position suggested by Maddy (1997) is a
thoroughgoing mathematical naturalism that takes mathematical standards as authoritative within
both mathematics and its philosophy.
Ignoring qualifications, the main contemporary versions of naturalism, with their representative
advocates, may be tabulated as follows:

Mathematics Proper Philosophy of Mathematics
Scientific
(Quine)
Scientific Scientific
Mathematical-Cum-Scientific
(Burgess)
Mathematical-cum-
Scientific
Mathematical-cum-
Scientific
Mathematical
(?)
Mathematical Mathematical
Heterogeneous
(Maddy 1997)
Mathematical Scientific
To illustrate the difference between statements in mathematics proper and the philosophy of
mathematics, consider as an example of the former the Green-Tao theorem, proved in 2004, which
states that the sequence of prime numbers contains arbitrarily long arithmetic progressions (but of
course no infinitely long one); as examples of the latter take the platonist claim that the number two
exists and is abstract or the claim that because mathematical entities are created rather than
discovered, impredicative definitions are not permissible. For any given philosopher, the Green-Tao
theorem and its proof are to be assessed by the standards of the first column. For example, Quine
accepts the theorem if and only if it is part of the best systematisation of science (which it is
assuming that the principles from which it is deduced and the logic by which it is deduced from
those principles are). Similarly, for any given philosopher, platonism and the stricture regarding
impredicativity are to be assessed by the standards of the second column. For example, Quine
accepts platonism because he takes it to be the scientifically sanctioned interpretation of
mathematics: in his view, the mathematics contained in the best systematisation of science is
platonic.
There are no clear exemplars of the view that mathematical standards should be authoritative in
philosophy of mathematics, hence the question mark. David Lewis flirted with this position in his
monograph on set theory (1991, viiiix, 54), but by the time of his (1993) had already repudiated it.
The position is suggested by remarks in Maddy (1997), though as we will see in section 5, Maddy
(1997) is more naturally interpreted as advancing a heterogeneous form of naturalism. Several other
philosophers of mathematics are also professed naturalists, notably Alan Baker (2001) and Mark
Colyvan (2001).
3. Elucidating Methodological Naturalism
Like many isms, naturalism is perhaps better thought of as an orientation with doctrinal
implications than as a doctrine per se. Nevertheless, we may attempt to elucidate it along several
dimensions.
3.1 Authoritative
How should we understand the claim that some set of standards ought to be authoritative in the
philosophy of mathematics? We may preserve generality by referring to X-standards, the instances
of interest to us being scientific, mathematical or scientific-cum-mathematical. Here are some
(non-exhaustive) readings of the authority claim:
1. Biconditional Naturalism: accept p iff p is sanctioned by X-standards
2. Trumping Naturalism: accept p if p is sanctioned by X-standards.
3. Emphasis Naturalism: In assessing whether p, give more emphasis to X-standards.
4. Compatibility Naturalism: do not accept p if p is incompatible with X-standards.
The biconditional reading is the strongest of the four. It expresses the thought that valid standards
just are X-standards. In contrast with biconditional naturalism, the trumping version apparently
allows that a statement in the philosophy of mathematics may be acceptable even if X-standards do
not sanction it. For instance, Burgess and Rosen express their naturalism as follows:
The naturalists' commitment is to the comparatively modest proposition that when science
[understood to include mathematics] speaks with a firm and unified voice, the philosopher is either
obliged to accept its conclusions or to offer what are recognizably scientific reasons for resisting
them (1997, 65).
This is naturally glossed as a trumping version of scientific-cum-mathematical naturalism. It seems
to allow that if mathematics and science do not speak with a firm voice on a question, we may
accept the verdict of some other discipline.
Emphasis Naturalism is a vaguer doctrine. Various versions arise depending on how much emphasis
is placed on X-standards. A modest version captures the position of naturalistically-inclined but not
outright naturalist philosophers. We recover biconditional naturalism when X-standards are
emphasised to the point where no others matter.
Compatibility naturalism is not as strong as trumping naturalism. If p is sanctioned by X-standards
then compatibility naturalism enjoins the non-acceptance of p but it does not necessarily enjoin the
acceptance of p. Non-acceptance of p falls short of acceptance of p since there is always the option
to suspend judgment on p. The compatibility view is generally accepted by most contemporary
philosophers. To take an example from outside the philosophy of mathematics, most philosophers
would reject a philosophy of time that clashes with the theory of relativity (in this case X = science).
Within the philosophy of mathematics, most philosophers would reject a philosophy of mathematics
that implies, for instance, that complex analysis should be jettisoned (in this case X could be
science, mathematics, or mathematics-cum-science).
Various weaker methodological theses are sometimes labelled naturalist, for instance the rejection
of Cartesian foundationalism, but here we understand the term more robustly. Which of the above
variants is the right way to develop naturalism depends of course on how naturalism is motivated
(section 4).
3.2 The boundary problem and the scientific method
Naturalism sets up an opposition between X-standards (scientific, mathematical or scientific-cum-
mathematical) and other types of standards, e.g., astrological, theological, or the standards of
common sense. Another example of standards that the naturalist sees as on the wrong side of the
tracks are fundamental philosophical ones. Goodman and Quine (in his pre-naturalist phase) once
began an article by declaring that the basis for their nominalism was a fundamental philosophical
intuition irreducible to scientific grounds (1947). Naturalists reject appeal to such standards.
An apparent problem with naturalism is that there do not seem to be sharp boundaries between
science and non-science and between mathematics and non-mathematics. For example, the
transition from physics to philosophy of physics to physics-heavy metaphysics to common-or-
garden metaphysics seems to be gradual. When a mathematician writes a research article, an
undergraduate textbook, a popular book on mathematics, a book expounding his personal
philosophy of mathematics and his psychological associations with various mathematical theories,
at what point exactly has he stopped doing mathematics? When research mathematicians get
together after the seminar and agree over coffee that the Riemann Hypothesis is the most important
outstanding problem in mathematics, is this a strictly mathematical claim or a personal judgement
recognised by mathematicians as outside the province of mathematics proper?
Many philosophers follow Quine by citing a standard cluster of principles putatively constitutive of
scientific standards: empirical adequacy, ontological economy, simplicity, fertility, and so on
(Quine 1955, 247; Quine and Ullian 1970, chapter 5). However, lists of this kind are unsatisfactory
for several reasons. For one thing, the principles come in different versions. Yet it is doubtful
whether the general versions are the scientifically sanctioned ones. Some writers claim, for
example, that scientific appeal to ontological parsimony does not extend to the postulation of
abstract objects (Burgess 1998). Others maintain that scientific appeals to simplicity are not best
captured by the utterly general slogan Prefer any theory T
1
to any less simple theory T
2
(in this
respect) (Paseau 2007). Moreover, lists of this kind do not tell us how to balance desiderata against
one another.
Since the explosion of science studies in the 1960s, more attention is now paid to the nuances of
scientific practice. Yet a more precise articulation of scientific standards and their weights remains
elusive. The existence of an algorithm encapsulating the scientific method is generally questioned
(though many human beings apparently manage to implement the scientific method, so if the
method is not algorithmic then neither are our minds). What is not questionable, however, is that its
exhibition currently escapes us.
Having said that, it is not clear how serious the boundary problem is for naturalists. Perhaps they
can argue that there is a fairly sharp boundary, though one that is hard to define. Perhaps
mathematicians implicitly know when something counts as a piece of mathematics and when it is a
non-mathematical commentary on mathematics. In any case, naturalism seems to survive the
absence of a sharp boundary. Naturalism can apparently rest its claims on a set of standards with
fuzzy boundaries.
3.3 Methodological unity?
What if there are no global scientific standards, but just the standards of this or that part of science
(e.g., physics or biology, or particle physics or fluid mechanics), or even just the standards of this or
that group of scientists? In that case, scientific naturalism would fragment into several versions
(e.g., physics-naturalism or biology-naturalism). If the motivation for scientific naturalism points to
one of these finer-grained naturalisms over the others (e.g., physics-naturalism), or if they all return
the same verdicts in the philosophy of mathematics, the potential fragmentation is not worrying. But
if not, the scientific naturalist is in trouble, as all these competing naturalisms are by assumption
equally valid. So far scientific naturalists have tended to assume that science operates with a single
set of standards. Plausible though that assumption is, a rigorous naturalist will want to shore it up
with detailed case studies. Similarly for mathematical naturalism and mathematical-cum-scientific
naturalism.
3.4 Degree of sanction
Scientific standards sanction propositions to a certain degree rather than outright. The latest
hypothesis at the research coalface adopted tentatively by a few experts does not have the same
standing as a long-entrenched theory. Thus the black-or-white notion of scientific standards
sanctioning or not sanctioning p will not do. (This is an idea which Bayesian confirmation theory
takes seriously.) It might also be argued that this is also true for mathematical standards, for
example by considering non-deductive grounds for belief in mathematical propositions. It seems
reasonable to see Goldbach's Conjecture, the claim that every even number greater than 4 is the sum
of two primes, as supported to a high degree by the non-deductive evidence currently available for
it. In the absence of a proof of Goldbach's Conjecture, however, this degree falls short of 1. A more
precise statement of the naturalist's creed must therefore issue guidelines for apportioning credence
in p in line with the degree and type of commitment to p scientific or mathematical standards
recommend.
3.5 Standards and practitioners
It would be wrong to equate what X-standards sanction with what X-practitioners believe (for X =
science or mathematics or more generally). For one thing, X-practitioners may not have given a
particular question any thought. For another, X-practitioners might all be mistaken. Moreover, X-
practitioners might self-consciously maintain the opposite of or at any rate something distinct from
what X-standards sanction. For instance, a scientist may believe p, perhaps on the basis of a gut
feeling or on account of some overriding religious convictions or for whatever non-scientific
reason, whilst still recognising that scientific standards support not-p. Or a mathematician may
believe that the number 7 has mystical properties but not believe it qua mathematician. A tighter
connection between practitioners and standards, then, might be this: what X-standards sanction is
what X-practitioners are disposed to correctly believe qua X-practitioners. (This is not intended as a
reductive analysis.)
Having said that, it takes special pleading to attribute widespread error to the community of X-
practitioners regarding what X-standards sanction. Thus what X-practitioners in fact believe usually
serves as good, though defeasible, evidence for what X-standards sanction.
3.6 Broader naturalisms
Scientific naturalism as here defined encompasses only natural science (and likewise for scientific-
cum-mathematical naturalism). Broader naturalisms take in not just traditional natural science but
also some of the other sciences: perhaps all of social science, perhaps only some of it, perhaps
linguistics, perhaps cognitive science. Note that in later writings Quine himself adopts a broad
version of naturalism (1995, 49). Penelope Maddy has more recently made it clear that the form of
scientific naturalism she espousesSecond Philosophy as she now prefers to call itis very
broad indeed, taking in not only the natural sciences but also psychology, linguistics, sociology, etc.
(2007, 2).
Broadening scientific or scientific-cum-mathematical naturalism to include these disciplines has
potentially significant consequences for the philosophy of mathematics. For instance, if semantics
falls under the naturalist umbrella it may provide a naturalistic sanction for mathematical realism or
platonism, as the face value semantics for mathematics seems to assimilate it to the
uncontroversially literal parts of languagea point famously made in Benacerraf (1973).
Whether to construe naturalism broadly or narrowly depends on its motivation. The attractions of
scientific or mathematical or scientific-cum-mathematical naturalism lie in the disciplines'
incomparable success (on some understanding of what this success comes tosee section 4). At
this point in time, however, the non-natural sciences are less successful than the natural sciences.
The less successful one deems the non-natural sciences compared to the natural ones, the less
attractive a broader scientific or scientific-cum-mathematical naturalism becomes in comparison
with a strictly natural-scientific one.
All naturalists, especially those of the broader variety, have to balance potentially competing
standards. A broad naturalist might decide, say, to give the natural sciences 2/3-weighting and
semantics 1/3-weighting. Or she might hold that a proposition in the philosophy of mathematics is
acceptable if (or even: if and only if) all the sciences, natural or non-natural, sanction itthat is to
say, when all the sciences speak with one voice. These balancing questions have unfortunately not
been much addressed by naturalists. Perhaps that is because questions of this kind arise for
everyone: whichever justificatory standards one accepts, the problem of how to adjudicate between
them arises. But to the extent that naturalism is prescriptive and cannot rely on an implicit
procedure that is already in place, it owes us an articulation of how to balance different sets of
standards.
The balancing issue is particularly pressing for mathematical-cum-scientific naturalists. A scientific
naturalist is in principle happy to say that if a mathematical theory M is scientifically superior but
mathematically inferior to another mathematical theory M
*
then M should be preferred to M
*
(the
next paragraph contains an example). Mathematical-cum-scientific naturalists, however, may come
down on either side, depending on the details of the particular theories: it all depends on whether
M's scientific advantages compared to M
*
are outweighed by its mathematical disadvantages. Now
the philosophy of mathematics does not have an established tradition of weighing mathematical
theories' scientific and mathematical pros and cons against one another; nor does any other
discipline. So the problem of how to balance mathematical and scientific standards is particularly
pressing for the mathematical-cum-scientific naturalist.
To illustrate this problem, suppose, as many philosophers maintain, that the general principle of
ontological economyposit as few entities as possibleis a scientific standard. Suppose also, as
Penelope Maddy maintains, that a set-theoretic version of ontological profligacyposit as many
sets as possibleis a mathematical standard (this is one way of cashing out the set-theoretic maxim
Maddy calls MAXIMIZE). These two standards clash, as Maddy recognises (1997, 131). Thus given
these assumptions a predicativist set theory which posits a relatively small number of sets, say of
the kind developed in Hermann Weyl's Das Kontinuum, might be scientifically superior to ZFC,
which posits more sets. Yet ZFC is generally thought to be mathematically superior to a
predicativist set theory. Perhaps the right diagnosis is that the clash is only superficial, since the
correct scientific version of ontological economy is posit as few concrete entities as possible and
the correct mathematical version of ontological profligacy is posit as many abstract entities as
possible. However that may be in this instance, the mathematical-cum-scientific naturalist has to
come up with a general policy for dealing with potential clashes, or argue that no such clashes are
possible.
4. Motivating Naturalism
One may simply adopt naturalism without providing an argument or motivation for it. But
motivations for naturalism buttress it, making it internally stronger, and give it dialectical strength,
increasing its appeal to non-naturalists. They answer the fundamental question: why exactly those
standards?
(The same goes for naturalisms primarily conceived as approaches or stances rather than doctrines.
Since the publication of her 1997 book, Penelope Maddy has clarified that her version of naturalism
is a stance (Maddy 2001) or a piecemeal approach/method of inquiry (2007, see e.g., p. 19 fn. 15, p.
403). However, stances and approaches to inquiry are attractive to the extent that they are well
motivated.)
4.1 Naturalism is Revolutionary in some Respects
Naturalism is often thought to be a conservative philosophy of mathematics, as we suggested in
section 1. But actually things are more complicated. Each of the three naturalisms of interest is
revolutionary in some respect.
Our default view is that mathematical standards decide questions in mathematics proper, for
example questions such as whether Fermat's Last Theorem or the Axiom of Choice is true.
Scientific standards are thought not to affect this: when Andrew Wiles proved Fermat's Last
Theorem in the mid-1990s, he was not particularly concerned with how his proof would go down in
physics departments, or more generally its impact on empirical science. Similarly, the claim that if
some large cardinal axiom is not scientifically sanctioned (perhaps because it leads to no new
empirical consequences) then there is no good reason to accept it is, as Maddy points out, out of
step with the actual practice of set theory (1997, 132), and indeed out of step with the actual
practice of much philosophy. We usually do not judge large cardinal axioms by scientific standards;
we judge them by mathematical standards. Quine was self-consciously going against the grain when
he rejected the higher flights of set theory on scientific grounds (1986, 400).
Scientific naturalism about mathematics proper is thus a philosophically revolutionary view, since it
advocates a different set of standards with which to judge mathematics (scientific ones) from the
traditional ones (mathematical). It is also potentially revolutionary about mathematics itself, as it
might lead to a revision of mathematics. (Notice that even if scientific naturalism does not entail a
revision of mathematics, it still counts as philosophically revolutionary: advocating the replacement
of Y-standards with X-standards as the proper arbiters in some domain is philosophically
revolutionary even if the Y-standards and X-standards happen to endorse the same claims in that
domain.) Having said that, recent scientific naturalists have tended to be mathematically
conservative in temperament and have advocated little or no revision of mathematics.
These morals also apply to mathematical-cum-scientific naturalism, but to a lesser extent, as the
latter gives some weight to mathematical standards in mathematical justification.
The third of the three naturalisms of interest, mathematical naturalism, is philosophically but not
mathematically revolutionary. Mathematically, it is as conservative as can be: no standards other
than mathematical ones are relevant to the assessment of mathematical claims. Thus no accepted
mathematics is overturned from without. Yet mathematical naturalism is a revolutionary stance in
the philosophy of mathematics. To see this, suppose that platonism is part of standard, accepted
mathematical practice. In that case, mathematical naturalism entails that there is no further question
of its truth. Loosely put, simply because mathematicians (qua mathematicians) are platonists,
platonism is the correct philosophy of mathematics. This is clearly out of step with philosophical
practice: philosophers look to mathematicians' views (qua mathematicians) as defeasible data for
the philosophy of mathematics, not its conclusion. Thus we see that the simple characterisation of
mathematical naturalism as conservative is not quite right: though mathematically conservative, it is
philosophically revolutionary.
In sum, scientific, mathematical, and mathematical-cum-scientific naturalism are each revolutionary
in some respect and face a corresponding burden of proof. We may now appreciate the sense in
which the general claim, expressed in section 1, that naturalism is anti-revisionary is true and the
sense in which it is not.
This also shows that contemporary naturalism is different from the latter Wittgenstein's
superficially similar metaphilosophy. Wittgenstein's anti-philosophy, like naturalism, bars
philosophy from changing mathematics: Philosophy may in no way interfere with the actual use of
languageIt leaves everything as it is. It also leaves mathematics as it is (1953, 163).
Naturalism's revolutionary tenor, however, means that it does not leave everything as it is.
4.2 Dearth of Arguments in the Literature
Arguments for naturalism are lacking in the literature. Most naturalists simply posit their naturalism
and work downstream from it, hoping that its consequences will prove attractive to the susceptible
(Maddy 2007, 3). Naturalism thus effectively becomes a personal credo with little direct attempt to
bring anyone else on board: I accept only X-standards in some domain because I find them more
credible than others. Now perhaps at the end of the day one cannot do better. But we shouldn't
assume that at the outset. That is all the more important given naturalism's revolutionary features, as
explained earlier. A conservative theory of justification might sanction naturalism given a broadly
naturalist starting point; but our starting point, as we have seen, is not that of trumping naturalism: it
is at most compatibility naturalism. So an argument for anything more than the mildest version of
naturalism would be welcome.
4.3 Current Success
Naturalists are motivated by the thought that scientific or mathematical standards are the most
successful standards we possess. But what does success come to? Very roughly, the following could
be taken to be a mark of a discipline's success: (i) among its practitioners, there is a widely shared
conception of the discipline's guiding questions and permissible methodology; and (ii) there is
progress within the discipline in addressing its guiding questions. One may then try to argue along
these lines that physics is more successful than metaphysics, that psychology is more successful
than parapsychology, and that astronomy is more successful than astrology.
An approach of this kind faces a twofold problem. If anything goes when it comes to methodology,
all sorts of disciplines can achieve success without thereby achieving credibility. Consider Guru-
ology, the discipline that takes its guiding questions to be those enunciated by some guru, and lays
down as its methodology that acceptable answers are all and only the guru's pronouncements
(perhaps assuming consistencyso let us assume for good measure that the guru is consistent and
more generally probabilistically coherent). These answers could be as fanciful as you like: we leave
it to the reader's imagination to devise examples of outlandish claims made by the guru. If we
suppose that the guru answers each of the questions that he raises, Guru-ology is therefore
progressiveit answers all the questions it raisesand it is therefore successful. But its success
speaks nothing of its credibility.
In general, if the success of any given set of standards S is gauged on its own terms, i.e., by using S-
standards, several self-supporting but intuitively unacceptable sets of standards count as successful.
This relativism is clearly not what the naturalist wants. Likewise for the thought that success is to be
determined by how well the standards help us to cope with reality; several non-scientific and non-
mathematical naturalisms likewise self-vindicate under this criterion. Perhaps success should
instead be measured by how well the standards explain and predict natural phenomena, i.e., with
how they cope with the subject matter of natural science. But adopting our usual view of how to
judge success in this respect would be question-begging in favour of scientific naturalism, since
scientific standards are precisely the standards we have developed to cope with this portion of
reality. Compare an astrological naturalism motivated by the idea that success is to be measured by
how well the standards explain and predict astrological phenomena, understood as the astrologers
do. So if a naturalist argument based on success is to succeed, some other naturalistically acceptable
but non-question begging understanding of success must be found.
The second problem with a success argument is that success in one sphere is no indication of
success in another. Biology is rather successful at explaining and predicting biological phenomena.
But why should that give it authority over questions in mathematics or the philosophy of
mathematics? Likewise for other natural sciences. As we shall see, this point generalises.
4.4 Agreement
Traditional philosophy, a naturalist might say, leads to endless disagreement. Science and
mathematics, on the other hand, usually reach broad agreementoften consensuson questions
within their domain. Hence scientific or mathematical standards are to be preferred to others. (Such
arguments from disagreement and lack of convergence in opinion have featured prominently in
other areas of philosophy, notably meta-ethics.)
However, the moral that the naturalist wishes to draw from patterns of agreement and disagreement
seems unwarranted. Agreement or disagreement in a community is a contingent matter. A
totalitarian state could achieve community-wide agreement with chilling efficacy by imposing some
preferred set of standards on its subjects. In general, there are countless non-epistemic reasons for
agreement or disagreement. It is therefore not agreement that matters, but rather the explanation of
why agreement obtains.
A more sophisticated version of this argument might therefore be based on the tractability of
disagreement rather than on its mere presence. Disagreement is rife in both philosophy and science,
but only in the latter, it might be said, is disagreement tractable. At the very least, progress can be
made and perhaps agreement can in principle always be reached. Actual patterns of agreement and
disagreement might then be cited as evidence for the respective tractability or intractability of
debates umpired by, say, scientific and non-scientific philosophical standards.
It is beyond the scope of this entry to assess this more sophisticated version of the argument, which
in one form or another has recently garnered considerable attention outside the philosophy of
mathematics. However, note a couple of prima facie difficulties.
In order to abstract from the contingencies of our epistemic situation, arguments about tractability
usually proceed by considering highly idealised subjects, in particular subjects whose factual,
logical, etc. knowledge far exceeds ours. But the problem with such idealisations is that they seem
question-begging. For example, a theological anti-naturalist would maintain that factually highly-
informed subjects will be apprised of facts about supernatural reality. Our grip on idealised subjects
and how disagreement between them is likely to resolve itself may therefore be too loose to draw
any substantive morals from such thought experiments. Either that or such arguments are likely to
be question-begging.
Second, we may grant that considerations of tractability reveal that scientific and mathematical
standards are more truth-conducive in their respective spheres. Yet that does not seem to provide a
warrant for thinking that they will be successful in other spheres. (This is the same point we made
in connection with the argument from success.)
4.5 Historical Success
Perhaps the most promising argument for naturalism is based on historical success. Scientific and
mathematical standards have a better track record than others; therefore scientific and mathematical
standards should be taken as authoritative, in the philosophy of mathematics and elsewhere.
Observe that like the previous two arguments, this argument for naturalism in the philosophy of
mathematics is an argument for global naturalism.
Some naturalists have explicitly relied on this motivation. For example, Lewis uses it to reject
structuralism as the correct philosophy of set theory in Parts of Classes (1991, 589) even if he
disclaims it as an argument; see also Colyvan (2001, 33), Shapiro (1997, 30) and Burgess (1998,
197). There is much to say about the argument, explored in Paseau (2005). Here we content
ourselves with two critical observations.
Since philosophers deploy apparently different standards, it is not clear what it means to say that
philosophy as a whole has a poor historical track record. Consider the early Popper (1935), who
held that no amount of evidence can make an unfalsified theory probable (or at least no more
probable than any other unfalsified theory). This is the kind of example David Lewis wields to poke
fun at philosophy: surelysurelythe standards that led to this conclusion are not trustworthy. The
theory of relativity is undoubtedly more probable than the as yet unfalsified hypothesis that the
world will end in the year 2525. Yet if I do not share Popper's 1935 standards, the fact that his then
philosophy of science is from my point of view manifestly wrong does nothing to shake my faith in
my own philosophical standards. Similarly, take Thomas Aquinas, whose philosophical standards
included consonance with the Bible and more generally with the tenets of the Christian faith. If I am
not a Christian, the fact that Aquinas' philosophical theology is from my point of view wrong does
nothing to shake my faith in my philosophical standards. Thus, that Sir Karl or St Thomas'
standards were, as I see it, no good does not tend to undermine my faith in my own.
I may therefore agree with the naturalist that philosophy has a worse track record than science and
mathematics. But it does not follow that the (non-scientific or non-mathematical) standards that I
use have a poor track record. If philosophers have consistently assumed a more or less uniform set
of standards over the course of history, and if I too follow in that tradition by accepting them as
mine, and furthermore if these standards demonstrably have a poorer track record than scientific or
mathematical standards, that would be a reason for me to turn naturalist. But the first assumption is
at least questionable, and it is not clear what remains of the argument from history if my standards'
antecedents do not have a poor track record.
A second problem with the argument has to do with its application to philosophical questions. Let
us agree that scientific standards have a good track record when it comes to answering scientific
questions, that mathematical standards have a good track record when it comes to answering
mathematical questions, and moreover that these track records are better than philosophical
standards' track record in answering philosophical questions. These facts, however, do not seem to
be relevant to the issue of which standards should be treated as authoritative when it comes to
philosophical questions. A good track record in one sphere is not in itself evidence for truth-
conduciveness in another.
This by now familiar objection may be illustrated by considering the debate between platonists and
structuralists in the philosophy of mathematics. Platonists interpret 1 + 2 = 3 as a claim about
abstract objects. Structuralists on the other hand interpret 1 + 2 = 3 as a claim about what is the
case in any structure that satisfies the axioms of arithmetic. (Here we are thinking of structuralism
as the type of view often labelled eliminative structuralism following Charles Parsons, and whose
most sophisticated book-lengthand modalversion may be found in Hellman (1989).)
Naturalists claim that mathematical standards have been more successful in the past and hence
should be trusted on this issue. But it is by no means clear that this is the type of question
concerning which mathematical standards have a better track record than philosophical ones.
Mathematical standards have a good track record when it comes to questions such as whether 1 + 2
is equal to 3, or what the series 1 + 1/4 + 1/9 + 1/16 + converges to, or whether the Poincar
Conjecture (concerning the classification of 3-manifolds) is true; but they do not have a proven
track record when it comes to questions such as whether these truths are platonist or structuralist. (A
related objection to the argument is that scientific standards do not speak to questions of
interpretation, such as the question of which of platonism or structuralism to prefer. Cf. Paseau
(2007).)
In sum, the need for naturalists to develop these arguments or to produce better ones remains
pressing.
5. Heterogeneous Naturalism
So far we have considered three uniform types of methodological naturalism relating to
mathematics: scientific, mathematical, and mathematical-cum-scientific. Consider now a
heterogeneous methodological naturalism that accepts mathematical standards when it comes to
mathematics proper but adopts scientific standards for the philosophy of mathematics and for
philosophy more generally. Heterogeneous naturalism has been advanced by Penelope Maddy
(1997), whose rich contributions have animated and incomparably influenced the debate on
naturalism in the philosophy of mathematics over the past twenty years. (Maddy now prefers to call
her naturalism Second Philosophy, as in the title of her 2007 book, but here we maintain the label
naturalism in keeping with the rest of the entry.)
To begin with, a representative quotation from Maddy:
Where Quine holds that science is not answerable to any supra-scientific tribunal, and not in need
of any justification beyond observation and the hypothetico-deductive method , the
mathematical naturalist adds that mathematics is not answerable to any extra-mathematical tribunal
and not in need of any justification beyond proof and the axiomatic method (1997, 184).
In our terminology, Maddy's heterogeneous naturalism is a trumping thesis. As she puts it, if our
philosophical account of mathematics comes into conflict with successful mathematical practice, it
is the philosophy that must give (1997, 161). Neither philosophy nor science can overturn
mathematics' methodological verdicts (2007, 361), since they are both extra-mathematical
tribunals. However, Maddy takes the philosophy of mathematics as opposed to mathematics proper
to be a branch of natural science, as she explains in the following passage:
So naturalistic philosophy of mathematics takes place within natural science, like naturalistic
philosophy of science, but unlike naturalistic philosophy of science, it takes a hands-off attitude
toward the naturalized model of mathematical practice (1997, 202).
These and similar passages (especially 1997, 200203) indicate that Maddy takes the philosophy of
mathematics to be answerable to (natural-) scientific standards.
The distinctiveness of heterogeneous naturalism is thus that it recommends one set of standards
(mathematical) for settling some questions about mathematicsmathematical ones, such as which
axioms to chooseand another set of standards (scientific) for settling other questions about
mathematics left open by the practice itselfphilosophical ones, such as how to interpret
mathematics. This is in contrast to uniform naturalisms in the philosophy of mathematics, for
example Quinean scientific naturalism, or Burgessian mathematical-cum-scientific naturalism, or a
uniformly mathematical naturalism (also suggested by Maddy (1997) but in our view ultimately not
advocated there).
To explain how this bivalent attitude might work in practice, take Maddy's favourite example: set
theory. Suppose that ZFC + LCA is our current accepted set theory, where LCA is some collection
of large cardinal axioms. Given mathematical naturalism about mathematics proper, there is no
question of rejecting ZFC + LCA in favour of, say, ZFC + the axiom that there are no inaccessibles,
or some other set theory, say Quine's New Foundations. Mathematical standards sanction ZFC +
LCA, so that is the set theory we must accept. But how should we interpret ZFC + LCA?
Platonistically, structurally or in some other way? That is a philosophical question, so given
scientific naturalism about the philosophy of mathematics (and philosophy more generally) its
correct answer is that sanctioned by scientific standards. For example, if an overriding scientific
criterion of simplicity favours platonism over all other interpretations, that must be the correct
interpretation of ZFC+LCA.
Maddy motivates her naturalism by appeal to the fundamental spirit that underlies all naturalism:
the conviction that a successful enterprise, be it science or mathematics, should be understood or
evaluated on its own terms, that such an enterprise should not be subject to criticism from, and does
not stand in need of support from, some external, supposedly higher point of view (1997, 184).
One strained reading of this sentence is that naturalism's fundamental conviction by definition
applies only to natural science and mathematics. A more natural reading is that it applies to any
successful science whatsoever. Maddy then claims that as a matter of fact non-mathematical
grounds have not impinged on mathematics. We can express this as the thesis that mathematics is
autonomous.
The assessment of Maddy's heterogeneous naturalism consists principally in the assessment of the
autonomy thesis regarding mathematics and its implications. One question is whether the thesis is
true. Another is whether, if true, the thesis supports heterogeneous naturalism.
5.1 Is Mathematics Methodologically Autonomous?
Maddy claims that the correct model of mathematical justification will vindicate the hypothesis that
traditionally scientific or philosophical arguments do not enter into the justification of mathematical
statements. For example, the French analysts Baire, Borel and Lebesgue criticised the Axiom of
Choice on the basis of a definabilist methodology, according to which the existence of an object
depends on its definability: functions should be definable rules, membership of a set should given in
a definable way, etc. But definabilism ended up having no influence on the practice of mathematics,
and its sympathisers were silenced or gave up on it when its mathematically undesirable features
became clear. For example, the Axiom of Choice allows the taking of maximal ideals in rings and
other structures; it entails the kinds of maximality principles that even the analysts were already
using; it simplifies transfinite arithmetic; and despite its suspicious abstractness it turns out to be
equivalent to concrete and mathematical statements such as the claim that every vector space has
a basis. The reasons for accepting the Axiom of Choice were in the end purely mathematical.
Maddy also offers an admirably detailed account of the kinds of mathematical reasons that militate
against the Axiom of Constructibility, V = L, in particular the fact that its adoption goes against
the set-theoretical maxim MAXIMIZE, which enjoins that the universe of sets should be as
expansive as possible (by containing as many isomorphism types as possible).
Most commentators have let the descriptive component of Maddy's naturalism, the autonomy thesis,
pass, focusing criticism instead on its normative implications. Yet the autonomy thesis is very
radical. The usual picture of the interaction between mathematics and philosophy is of a two-way
street. In particular, it is usually thought that philosophy impinges to some degree on mathematical
practice. Intuitionists for example take the dependence to be profound: they think that all of
mathematical practice rests on a false philosophical foundation and that once that foundation is
removed, mathematics totters.
Maddy willingly concedes that philosophical doctrines such as definabilism or realism are
important inspirations for mathematical development even if they fall short of justifications (1997,
192). And she accepts that theories of mathematical truth or existence or knowledge do in fact
appear in most mathematical debates over proper methods, alongside more typically mathematical
considerations (2007, 348). But she maintains that such theories have not in the end played an
instrumental role (2007, 359), and that they have racked up a track record of irrelevance (2007,
366) in the development of mathematics.
So do philosophical (or more generally non-mathematical) considerations always fall on the side of
inspiration rather than justification? Well, philosophical considerations are hardly ever advanced in
mathematical journals or books. And whenever they are Maddy sees them as amounting, when one
scratches the surface, to intra-mathematical arguments (1997, 193), of which a naturalized model
of the practice would be purified, because of their methodological irrelevance (1997, 197). If she
is right, this reply generalises from this particular, rather restricted, type of context to all
mathematical contexts.
One of the implications of this view is that the kinds of maxims Maddy sees as purely internal to
mathematics, such as MAXIMIZE or UNIFY, are never themselves underlain by philosophical
beliefs. UNIFY is a methodological consequence of set theory's foundational ambition of providing
a single system in which all objects and structures of mathematics can be modelled or instantiated
(1997, 2089). Yet perhaps UNIFY and set theory's foundational ambitionthe fact that as Maddy
correctly observes, set theory is (at least partly) designed to provide a foundation for classical
mathematics (2007, 355)are themselves in some small way, perhaps to some slight degree,
underpinned by set-theoretic realism, i.e., the view that set theory is about a single universe of sets.
Likewise for the Axiom of Choice, which on the surface owes its place in the set-theoretic canon
partlyperhaps only to a small degreeto an ingrained realism about set theory. Several set
theorists are on record as making claims to that effect, so the burden of proof is on Maddy to
explain away these remarks.
Maddy also employs the following problematic style of argument. She thinks that the fact that
philosophical debates (e.g., about realism) are wide open but that mathematics has developed in a
particular way (e.g., to allow impredicative methods) shows that philosophical debates have not
affected the outcome of modern mathematics (e.g., 2007, 348). But the fact that a debate about
realism is wide open in philosophy does not mean that it is wide open in mathematics. Perhaps
mathematicians have implicitly taken a realist stance, which in part underlies their acceptance of
impredicativity, even as philosophers continue to debate the correctness of realism as a philosophy
of mathematics. Mathematics may be philosophically parti pris, which is why it has developed the
way it has.
These points against the autonomy thesis are hardly conclusive. To evaluate it, greater clarity is
required on where the boundary between justification and inspiration lies and what exactly it means
to say that something falls on one side or the other. And of course we then need to identify more
precisely which of the factors in the evolution of mathematics are justificationally operative and
which idle. However, even if the autonomy thesis is not true, perhaps it is almost true. And perhaps
nothing quite as strong as an autonomy thesis is required to support trumping as opposed to
biconditional naturalism.
5.2 If Mathematics is Methodologically Autonomous, does that establish Maddy's
Naturalism?
That a statement-issuing practice is as a matter of fact autonomous does not entail that its statements
are thereby acceptable. Practices may be hermetically sealed from outside influence (e.g., astrology,
dogmatic theology), but that does not in itself make their claims acceptable. What makes
mathematics different?
Maddy recognises this problem for her position (1997, 2035; 2005, 449; 2007, 3467), which
reviews and discussions of her work have seized upon (e.g., Dieterle 1999, Rosen 1999, Roland
2007; only Tappenden (2001) is more sympathetic). She addresses it by making a distinction
between pure and applied disciplines. Taking astrology as a foil, she notes that applied astrology
may be construed as making claims about the empirical world. Using her ordinary scientific
standards, the scientific naturalist appreciates that applied astrology is false (as it diverges from the
accepted scientific story). Hence applied astrology does not deserve the naturalist's respect. Pure
astrology in contrast is astrology interpreted as treating of certain supernatural vibrations that don't
interact causally with ordinary physical phenomena (1997, 204). However, there is no reason to
believe in pure astrology, since it does not feature in our best scientific theory of the world. On
either interpretation, then, astrology is disanalogous to mathematics.
Maddy seems to want to have her cake and eat it. The reason for mathematics' credibility is
supposed to be its application in science. But why should the fact that mathematics features in our
best science be a reason for believing mathematicians' utterancesthat is, a reason for taking them
to be true? The suspicion is that if featuring in best science is the mark of credibility, it should be
scientific standards that ultimately determine mathematical theories' acceptability. Maddy has
indeed cited a feature distinguishing mathematics from pure astrology, as she points out (2007,
390); but what still remains unclear is why this feature should make mathematics rather than
science authoritative with respect to questions in mathematics proper. Thus it seems that she has not
explained how one can consistently be a mathematical naturalist about mathematical theories but a
scientific naturalist about everything else, including the truth and nature of mathematics. More
generally, given that a practice issues in truth-evaluable statements, it seems that one cannot
advocate X-standards as the arbiters of these statements' acceptability while simultaneously
advocating a different set of standards, the Y-standards, as arbiters of whether or not the statements
should be taken as true, how they should be interpreted, etc. Notice that this is a problem faced
exclusively by heterogeneous as opposed to uniform naturalism.
The only way to avoid this apparent inconsistency is to suppose that to accept a statement
sanctioned by mathematical practicea statement to which the autonomous practice of
mathematics gives the thumbs-updoes not amount to taking it as true. Although suggested by a
couple of passages in Maddy (1997), this interpretation is not one that can seriously be put on her
book. Besides, it is tantamount to scientific naturalism in all but name. It amounts to the claim that
whatever mathematicians spend their time saying, doing, and publishing should not be interfered
with, but that we should be mindful only to believe those mathematical claims sanctioned on
scientific grounds, whether or not they are given the thumbs-up in mathematicians' language-game.
This picture has recently been complicated by Maddy's claims that what she calls Arealismnot
taking set theory and more generally mathematics to be truemay be just as scientifically
respectable as Thin Realismroughly, the view that sets have only the properties ascribed to them
by set theory (2007, IV.4). This entry does not have space to do justice to this twist in Maddy's
metaphilosophy. Suffice it to note the following. The issues just discussed seem to arise for the
Thin Realist just as much as any other kind of realist. And the Arealist construal seems to transform
Maddy's position into something quite different from the heterogeneous naturalism under
consideration here.
6. Ontological Naturalism
Turning away from methodological naturalism, consider now ontological naturalism, the view that
all entities are natural. One way to read this is that only the entities posited by the natural sciences
exist. A second and perhaps more natural reading is that only spatiotemporal entities exist. We
address both readings briefly in this final section, and take in epistemological naturalism briefly in
6.3.
6.1 Natural Science as the Arbiter of Ontology
On its first reading, ontological naturalism in the philosophy of mathematics is a straightforward
consequence of methodological scientific naturalism. It states that the ontology of mathematics is
the mathematical ontology of our best natural science. Scientific platonists claim, following Quine
and Putnam, that this ontology is platonist, as do mathematical-cum-scientific platonists (e.g.,
Burgess and Rosen (1997)). Resistance to scientific platonism and the associated indispensability
argument has been mounted on several fronts (e.g., Field 1980, Sober 1993, Maddy 1997, ch. II.6,
Paseau 2007). Consult Colyvan (2011) for a detailed discussion.
6.2 All Entities are Spatiotemporal
The second reading of ontological naturalism, according to which all entities are spatiotemporal,
amounts to a version of anti-platonism in the philosophy of mathematics.
The position subdivides. On a reductionist view, mathematics is taken at logico-grammatical face
value but its objects (numbers, functions, sets, etc.) are taken to be spatiotemporal. This view is
advocated for sets in Armstrong (1991) and more generally in Bigelow (1988). Non-reductionist
views are manifold. They include taking mathematics as meaningless symbol-manipulation
(formalism), or as the exploration of what is true in all structures obeying the axioms
(structuralism), or as the exploration of what is true in all possible structures obeying the axioms
(modal-structuralism). Bueno (forthcoming) discusses various nominalisms, i.e., views which
countenance only spatiotemporal entities. Since many of these nominalisms are compatible with
non-naturalist as well as ontologically naturalist motivations, we do not discuss them here. We
concentrate on a handful of issues relating mainly to reductionist versions of ontological realism.
Reductionist ontological naturalism and non-modal structuralism about set theory face an
immediate problem: there are apparently far fewer entities in spacetime than there are sets. Even on
the most liberal assumptions (spacetime points and arbitrary regions thereof exist, some smallish
infinity of entities may be collocated at any of these points or regions), the size of spacetime and the
objects in it is a relatively low infinite cardinality (surely no more than

even that is generous).


Thus there are not enough spatiotemporal entities to interpret set theory literally nor to make a
structural interpretation of set theory non-vacuously true, and hence to ensure that set-theoretic
falsehoods come out false rather than true. See Paseau (2008) for discussion of this and other
problems for set-theoretic reductionism.
Another problem is that even if spacetime were large enough to provide either a model for a literal
interpretation of set theory or an instance for its structural interpretation, this would be a contingent
fact about our universe. Set theory would be true but contingent. Since we typically think of
mathematics as necessary, however, this is an untoward consequence for a philosophy of
mathematics. Some might even call it a reductio.
Versions of these problems also affect Mill's empiricism (1843). For Mill, mathematics and logic
are natural sciences, and their principles are laws of nature. Arithmetic, for instance, is the theory of
aggregates, i.e., the theory of collections of concrete entities. Geometry is the theory of idealised
limits of concrete entitieslines, points, planes and so onwhose principles are real facts with
some of their circumstances exaggerated or omitted (Mill 1843, vol. 1, bk. II, ch.v). Millian
philosophy of mathematics is susceptible to the cardinality problem just given. (Of course this is an
anachronistic criticism, since infinitary set theory had yet to be developed in Mill's time.) As for the
contingency of mathematics, Mill bit the bullet and accepted it.
A related problem for a Millian view, which arises even for the mathematics of Mill's day, is a
dilemma concerning the existence of aggregates of aggregates, aggregates of aggregates of
aggregates. Higher-order aggregates, if they exist, can only be abstractwhat else? But if they
do not existif there are only first-order aggregatesthen in particular there are no numbers of
numbers, for instance it is meaningless or false to say that there are two primes between 20 and 30.
Kitcher (1983) is an attempt to resuscitate Mill's philosophy of mathematics by modalising it. It
accounts for mathematical truth in terms of the operations of a possible but non-actual ideal agent,
and thus falls under the heading of modalist philosophies of mathematics. (Though Kitcher himself
is not fond of the label (1983, 1212).)
Other apparent problems for reductionist ontological naturalism include the problem of arbitrariness
and the fact that it goes profoundly against mathematical method. Suppose arithmetic is the study of
some particular spatiotemporal entities. Very well; but which ones? Surely it is arbitrary which
spatiotemporal entity is chosen as the number zero. This criticism is a version of a general anti-
reductionist argument presented in Benacerraf (1965). The response to it is usually that
reductionism does not seek to uncover the meaning of number terms but instead proposes a
theoretical identification (Paseau 2009). The charge of contradicting mathematical method is a
serious one too. If mathematical objects are spatiotemporal, why do mathematicians not perform
experiments to discover their properties? If mathematics were genuinely concerned with the
spatiotemporal, surely its methodology would be more empirical.
Ontological naturalist views of the type discussed are for these and related reasons seen as
problematic, and are consequently unpopular.
6.3 Naturalist Anti-Platonism and Epistemological Naturalism
Whatever their motivation, ontological naturalists are by definition (on this second reading of the
doctrine) agreed that platonism is false. Sometimes ontological naturalism is motivated by
metaphysical doctrines, for instance by the principle that everything that exists has causal powers.
Subscribers to this principle include Armstrong (1997) who calls it the Eleatic Principle; for
criticism, see Colyvan (2001 ch. 3) and Papineau (2009).
The most popular argument for ontological naturalism is epistemological, and consequently
ontological naturalism is often allied with epistemological naturalism. If there are abstract entities
then it seems we cannot know nor form reliable beliefs about them (Benacerraf 1973, Field 1989),
because of their causal isolation from us. Most philosophers take this to be the main problem
afflicting platonism. Note that the argument typically leads to agnosticism rather than denial of
abstract mathematical objects' existence. This is not the place to engage with the argumentfor
more details, see Balaguer (2009)save to sketch how a platonist who is also a scientific or
mathematical-cum-scientific naturaliste.g., Quineresponds to it.
The naturalist-platonist response is two-pronged (Burgess and Rosen 1997, 2005; for criticism, see
Linnebo 2006, Chihara 2006). The first prong is that no simple criterion for knowledge (or reliable
belief or justified belief) has ever been devised that succeeds in ruling out knowledge of the abstract
without thereby ruling out types of knowledge most naturalists would accept (Steiner 1975). A
couple of examples: (i) the condition that p is a cause of the belief that p is too strong, as it rules out
knowledge of the future; (ii) as the naturalist-platonist sees it, that abstract mathematical reality is
thus-and-so is in fact part of the best explanation for the belief that p; hence an explanatory
condition of this kind turns out to be compatible with platonism. Moreover, naturalist-platonists
complain that even if a criterion were found that draws the line where the nominalist wishes it to be
drawn, it would beg the question against platonism.
Secondly, naturalist-platonists run a standard Quinean line by construing any challenge to the
reliability of our beliefs about platonic mathematical objects as a general challenge to the scientific
method's reliability. (This is from the point of view of the scientific naturalist; the scientific-cum-
mathematical naturalist can run the same line with corresponding adjustments.) However, by our
best lightsaccording to our best theory of the world, i.e., natural science, which posits abstract
mathematical objectsbelief in abstract mathematical entities is arrived at by a reliable method,
namely the scientific method. This is not simply self-vindication, since the scientific method is here
being used to explain the reliability of mathematical beliefs, albeit holistically. But of course if the
reliability of the scientific method itself is put into question, the naturalist has no choice but to use
the scientific method itself to explain its own reliability. The naturalist-platonist may add that we
can do no better, and that anyone who questions the scientific method's reliability has thereby
abandoned the naturalist camp. From this perspective, then, there is no epistemological problem for
platonism once it is settled that platonist mathematics is part of best science.
Copyright 2013 by
Alexander Paseau <alexander.paseau@philosophy.ox.ac.uk>

Вам также может понравиться