Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 1

# Set theory odds and ends

One fact that's important for some lemmas in topology is this: Given $A$, $B$ ar
e subsets of $X$, then $A \subseteq X - B$ iff $B \subseteq X - A$. There are tw
o ways to see this:
1. First we need the following lemma: $A \subseteq B$ iff $X-B \subseteq X-A$.
This is easily proved via taking the contrapositive. You can also think pictoria
lly: if $A$ is just a section of $B$, then inverting $A$ and $B$ results in the
inversion of $B$ being just a section of the inversion of $A$.
With this lemma, it is straightforward to prove. $A \subseteq X-B$ implies $
X - (X - B) \subseteq X - A$, and $X - (X - B) = B$.
2. For $x \in X$, $A \subseteq X - B$ really means that $x \in A$ implies that
$x \notin B$. Take the contrapositive: $x \in B$ implies $x \notin A$, or $B \s
ubseteq X - A$. The other way obviously works too.
This fact is especially important for reasoning about closed sets, since our def
initions are in terms of open sets and complements of closed sets are open.
---
If $A \subseteq B$ and $X$ intersects $A$, then $X$ intersects $B$. Kind of obvi
ous, but there you go.
---
$f(f^{pre}(S) ) = S$, but $f^{pre}(f(S))$ could be a strict superset of $S$. One
way to get equality is if $f$ is injective, but there's actually a weaker condi
tion that works: we just need $S$ to be the only points that map into $f(S)$ (i.
e. the restriction of $f$ to $S$ must be injective). The LHS of the first is the
image of all the points that map into S, which is obviously still S. The LHS of
the second is the set of all points that map into the same points that S maps i
nto, which could be more than just S.
---
If $f: X \rightarrow Y$ is a function, $S \subseteq X$ and $\mathcal{U}$ is a co
llection of subsets in $Y$, then let $\mathcal{P} := \{f^{pre}(A) : A \in \mathc
al{U}\}$ ($\mathcal{P}$ is the collection of preimages of sets in $\mathcal{U}$.
) Then we have the following true:
If $\mathcal{U}$ covers $f(S)$, then $\mathcal{P}$ covers $S$. *Proof:* for $x \
in S$, $f(x) \in f(S)$, so it's in one $A_x \in \mathcal{U}$, and hence $f^{pre}
(A_x)$ is in $\mathcal{P}$. $x$ is in $f^{pre}(A_x)$ for obvious reasons.
---
You can use this in the proof that the image of a continuous function on a compa
ct metric space is compact: $f^{pre}(\bigcup \mathcal{F}) = \bigcup \{ f^{pre}(A
) : A \in \mathcal{F}\}$. The idea is that $f(x) \in \bigcup \mathcal{F}$ iff $f
(x) \in A$ for some $A \in \mathcal{F}$.
---
$(A \times B) \cap (X \times Y) = (A \cap X) \times (B \cap Y)$, but the same do
es not hold for union.

Вам также может понравиться