Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 5

HOME

BOOKSTORE
ESSAYS
VIDEOS
PHOTOS
BLOG

GODTUBE
YOUTUBE
PANORAMIO
FAQ
LINKS
GENESIS WEEK

JOHN PHILOPONUS,
ARISTOTLE'S EARLY CREATIONIST CRITIC
Author: Dan Graves
Subject: History
Date: 6/24/1998
Article adapted from the Dan Graves' book, Scientists of Faith
The first to present his case seems right until another comes forward and questions
him. Proverbs 18:17.
The power of the creationist view can be better seen at the very outset of Western science
in the person of John Philoponus.
Aristotle (384-322 B.C.), the ancient Greek philosopher and scientist whose views still
reverberate today, did more than perhaps any other thinker to shape pre-Christian science.
But his theories, while innovative for his day, often combined brilliant insights with a
good deal of nonsense-nonsense that opposed several fundamental tenets of first Judaism
and then Christianity.
Significantly, Aristotle's most serious critic in the first seven hundred years was John
Philoponus, an Alexandrian Christian. In response to Aristotalian error, Philoponus
forged a sustained attack against Aristotle's chief proponent during the seventh century
A.D., a Greek philosopher named Simplicius. Fortunately for modern science, Simplicius
often responded to those attacks with long quotations from Philoponus, inadvertantly
preserving his opponent's work for posterity.
Philoponus's application of Christian theology to physics prefigured a new era in science.
The Alexandrian scholar was the first to combine scientific cosmology (the study of the
nature of the universe) with monotheism and the Christian doctrine of creation. In doing
so, Philoponus anticipated not only the findings but also the methods of modern science.
He controlled his observations in the manner of genuine research, although it is not
certain he ever progressed beyond thought experiments-that is, experiments carefully
thought out, but not actually performed.

Three fundamental beliefs dominated Philoponus' thinking:


The universe is the single creation of a single God and not eternal
The heaven we see has the same physical properties as the earth
Stars are not divine
Simple ideas these were, but they had profound implications as to the origin and duration
of the universe, its constitution, and its physical forces. If the universe was created, it is
not infinite in duration. Aristotle taught that it is. If the universe was created, the
heavenly bodies can reasonably be assumed to be of the same material as the rest of
creation. Aristotle taught that the stars are made of a special celestial stuff. If the
heavenly bodies are material, they must be moving in a void; otherwise resistance to their
passage would create impossible friction. Aristotle taught that a void is impossible. If
stars are created, they are subject to physical laws of motion. Aristotle taught that divine
spirits move the stars.
Simplicius countered Philoponus with a number of arguments. How could star stuff be
like earth stuff? Would not the duration of a fall tend toward zero as the density of a
medium decreases? If space were a vacuum, Simplicius contended, objects such as stars
would have infinite speed.
Philoponus' replies anticipated the great Renaissance scientists Galileo (1564-1642) and
Simon Stevin (1548-1620). He correctly argued that the velocity of a body's fall is not
proportional to its weight. A millenium before Galileo, he proposed dropping two bodies
of unlike weight from a tower and postulated that the time of the fall would differ little
between the two objects.
He also speculated that any object dropped in a vacuum would require finite time to fall.
And, contrary to Aristotle, he asserted that a vacuum is possible and saw no absurdity in
supposing that motion can occur in such a void.
Having declared the stars to be of the same material as earth, Philoponus was forced to
explain their movement. Aristotle attributed celestial movements to spirits. But his
seventh-century critic suggested that the Creator had impressed movement upon the
original universe. Inertial motion is a kind of "rest", Philoponus argued. That is, once
motion was imparted, an object in a void kept going because of inertia, without a further
push. This impetus theory was revived in the thirteenth century by Peter John Olivi (c.
1248-1298) and has been incorporated into modern physics as momentum or kinetic
energy theory.
This conception cut straight to the heart of another Aristotalian error. Aristotle had taught
that air closing in behind a moving projectile propelled it. Philoponus disagreed, teaching
instead that a medium such as air that resists the motion of a projectile cannot also propel
that projectile. A stone moves because force is impressed onto it. Eventually it ceases to

move because of counteracting resistance. If we throw a stone, it flies a distance. If we


hang a stone from a light string and then stir the air with any device we choose, the stone
barely moves. The cause of movement, once a stone leaves the throwing hand, resides in
the stone itself.
A widespread religion of Philoponus's time was pantheism, a belief system that sees God
as equivalent to nature. In his rejection of this, Philoponus argued that the Creator
transcends nature rather than being within it. He taught that God created matter ex nihilo
(out of nothing) and endowed it with fundamental physical properties, possessing the
capacity to develop according to natural laws from chaos to its present state. Having been
created, nature exists without constant intervention by God. This radical conception
shocked the pagans who believed the gods were imbedded within the material universe.
If Simplicius had difficulty with Philoponus's refutations of Aristotle, he certainly did not
know how to take his opponent's even bolder assertion that this world is to be recreated
by God.
Philoponus's brilliance also burned brightly in his astronomical theories. Since, in his
cosmology, the heavenly bodies are made of the same stuff as the earth, it follows that
sun and stars are fiery. His everyday experience with burning substances told him that the
color of anything, and therefore of a star, depends on the nature of its fuel. Differences in
stellar magnitude and brightness are a function of different fuels.
He also claimed that celestial bodies are just as subject to change and decay as earthly
bodies. Such changes are not observed in the stars because of their large masses, he
reasoned, noting that even on earth we observe that the greater the mass of a body, the
slower its decay.
Today we know that his guesses were shrewd beyond his time. While the color of a star is
largely a function of its mass which determines its temperature, stars do produce
characteristic spectra according to the elements of their composition. Remarkably,
Philoponus arrived at his conclusions unaided by even the most primitive telescope.
The astute Alexandrian also tackled Aristotle's ideas about the origins of the Milky Way.
Aristotle had attributed the Milky Way and comets to gaseous exhalations rising from the
earth. How can this be? asked Philoponus. Unlike comets, the Milky Way never changes
in position or size. It doesn't dim the moon. It is not subject to changes like the weather.
The number of distinguishable stars behind it doesn't affect its brightness. Yet he failed to
recognize it as a blurred host of stars, placing it instead in the realm of things knowable
only to God.
Philoponus rejected still other Aristotalian errors. In Aristotle's thought, things move
toward their affines, that is, toward objects possessing similar properties. Phrased more
practically, this means air tends to rise. Earth will fall to rest with earth. Celestial objects
are in an etheric class all their own. Nonsense, said John. Lift a shovelful of dirt and air
rushes into the hole.

Philoponus taught that light is a directional phenomenon. Rays are not projected from our
eyes to the object, but they move from the object to our eyes. This now seems obvious,
but to early thinkers, attempting to explain the conic spread of light, it did not.
While almost all early religions and philosphers believed in either an eternal universe or
one that emerged from an earlier substance (the body of a murdered god, for example)
Philoponus argued strongly against the notions of infinite space and time. Since the world
is a creation, it cannot be infinite, he hypotheized. His reasoning made use of infinite
cardinal numbers and pointed out the logical problems found in infinite series. For
example, if the amount of all numbers is infinite, and if the amount of all even numbers is
infinite, there must be a one to one correspondence between all numbers and the even
numbers. Commonsense says there should be twice as many odd and even numbers as
there are even numbers. Since it seemed absurd to suppose there really are, infinities of
any countable sort of thing are an absurdity, said Philoponus. He is the first person
known to have made this argument.
His use of infinities anticipated modern concepts by thirteen hundred years. Current
theory now takes us where Philoponus thought we could not go. But today's cosmology
also has mathematical and material proof that time and the universe are finite. Again and
again Philoponus's theology led him to insights surprisingly close to modern science. All
these ideas were the outcome of working out the logical implications of creation and
time.
John Philoponus is believed to have lived an extraordinary long and productive life. His
reputation for hard work earned him the name, "Lover of Labor." He was also a lover of
books. According to legend, he was still alive when the Islamic armies under Amrou
sacked Alexandria (c. 642-646). Muslims were not generally offended by Philoponus's
Christian writings because of his monophysite leanings. He supposedly discoursed on
theology with the learned Amrou and pled that the Library of Alexandria be spared the
torch. But acting on orders from home, Amrou burned the library anyway. Whether the
legend is rooted in fact is unclear, but we do know that his own writings were taken by
the Arab conquerors and lost to the West. Still, Islamic science seems to have been
positively influenced through them.
Philoponus successfully challenged Simplicius and the fundamental errors of Aristotalian
theory. His originality and keen insight helped pave the way for many of the discoveries
of modern science. Reading him centuries later, Galileo praised Philoponus. But the
Alexandrian's greatest contribution is his demonstration that acceptance of the
fundamental assertions of Scripture, especially the fact of creation, will direct us toward
the truth. It is the clearest path to scientific enlightenment.
References:
Canfora, Lucius. The Vanished Library: A Wonder of the Ancient World. Berkeley and
Los Angeles: UCLA Press, 1987.

Edwards, Paul, ed. The Encyclopedia of Philosophy. New York: Macmillan and free
Press, 1967.
Gillispie, Charles Coulston, ed. Dictionary of Scientific Biography. New York:
Scribner's, 1970.
Jaki, Stanley L. The Milky Way; An Elusive Road for Science. New York: Science
History Publications, 1973.
Pedersen, Olaf. Early Physics and Astronomy. Cambridge: cambridge university, 1993.
Taton, Rene. Ancient and Medieval Science; From the Beginnings to 1450. History of
Science. New York: Basic Books, 1963.
Philoponus. Corollaries on Place and Void. Trans. David Furley. Ithaca, NY: Cornell
University, 1991.
Philoponus. Against Aristotle on the Eternity of the World. Trans. Christian Wildberg.
Ithaca, NY: Cornell, 1987.
Sorabji, Richard. Philoponus and the Rejection of Aristotalian Science. Ithaca, NY:
Cornell, 1987.

Вам также может понравиться