Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 6

Hedonism

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia


Jump to: navigation, search
For other uses, see Hedonism (disambiguation).
This article's introduction section may not adequately summarize its contents. To
comply with Wikipedia's lead section guidelines, please consider expanding the lead to
provide an accessible overview of the article's key points. (December 2009)
Hedonism is a school of ethics which argues that pleasure is the only intrinsic good.[1]

Contents
[hide]
• 1 Etymology
• 2 Basic concepts
• 3 Classic schools of antiquity
○ 3.1 Cārvāka
○ 3.2 The Cyrenaic school
○ 3.3 Epicureanism
• 4 Christian
• 5 Utilitarianism
○ 5.1 Mohism
○ 5.2 Anglo-Saxon utilitarianism
• 6 Egoism
• 7 Contemporary approaches
○ 7.1 Michel Onfray
○ 7.2 Abolitionism
• 8 Criticism
• 9 See also
• 10 References and notes
• 11 External links

[edit] Etymology
The name derives from the Greek word for "delight" (ἡδονισμός hēdonismos from ἡδονή
hēdonē "pleasure", a cognate of English sweet + suffix -ισμός -ismos "ism").
[edit] Basic concepts
The basic idea behind hedonistic thought is that pleasure is the only thing that is good for a
person. This is often used as a justification for evaluating actions in terms of how much pleasure
and how little pain (i.e. suffering) they produce. In very simple terms, a hedonist strives to
maximize this net pleasure (pleasure minus pain).
[edit] Classic schools of antiquity
Democritus seems to be the earliest philosopher on record to have categorically embraced a
hedonistic philosophy; he called the supreme goal of life "contentment" or "cheerfulness",
claiming that "joy and sorrow are the distinguishing mark of things beneficial and harmful" (DK
68 B 188).[2]
[edit] Cārvāka
Main article: Cārvāka
Cārvāka was an Indian hedonist school of thought that arose approximately about 600 BCE, and
died out in the 14th century CE. The Cārvākas maintained that the Hindu scriptures are false, that
the priests are liars, and that there is no afterlife, and that pleasure should be the aim of living.
Unlike other Indian schools of philosophy, the Cārvākas argued that there is nothing wrong with
sensual indulgence. They held a naturalistic worldview.
[edit] The Cyrenaic school
Main article: Cyrenaics

Aristippus of Cyrene
The Cyrenaics were an ultra-hedonist Greek school of philosophy founded in the 4th century BC,
supposedly by Aristippus of Cyrene, although many of the principles of the school are believed
to have been formalized by his grandson of the same name, Aristippus the Younger. The school
was so called after Cyrene, the birthplace of Aristippus. It was one of the earliest Socratic
schools. The Cyrenaics taught that the only intrinsic good is pleasure, which meant not just the
absence of pain, but positively enjoyable sensations. Of these, momentary pleasures, especially
physical ones, are stronger than those of anticipation or memory. They did, however, recognize
the value of social obligation, and that pleasure could be gained from altruism. The school died
out within a century, and was replaced by the more sophisticated philosophy of Epicureanism.
[edit] Epicureanism
Main articles: Epicureanism and Epicurus
Epicureanism is a system of philosophy based upon the teachings of Epicurus (c. 341–c. 270
BC), founded around 307 BC. Epicurus was an atomic materialist, following in the steps of
Democritus. His materialism led him to a general attack on superstition and divine intervention.
Following Aristippus—about whom very little is known—Epicurus believed that the greatest
good was to seek modest pleasures in order to attain a state of tranquility and freedom from fear
(ataraxia) as well as absence of bodily pain (aponia) through knowledge of the workings of the
world and the limits of our desires. The combination of these two states is supposed to constitute
happiness in its highest form. Although Epicureanism is a form of hedonism, insofar as it
declares pleasure as the sole intrinsic good, its conception of absence of pain as the greatest
pleasure and its advocacy of a simple life make it different from "hedonism" as it is commonly
understood.

Epicurus
In the Epicurean view, the highest pleasure (tranquility and freedom from fear) was obtained by
knowledge, friendship and living a virtuous and temperate life. He lauded the enjoyment of
simple pleasures, by which he meant abstaining from bodily desires, such as sex and appetites,
verging on asceticism. He argued that when eating, one should not eat too richly, for it could lead
to dissatisfaction later, such as the grim realization that one could not afford such delicacies in
the future. Likewise, sex could lead to increased lust and dissatisfaction with the sexual partner.
Epicurus did not articulate a broad system of social ethics that has survived.
Epicureanism was originally a challenge to Platonism, though later it became the main opponent
of Stoicism. Epicurus and his followers shunned politics. After the death of Epicurus, his school
was headed by Hermarchus; later many Epicurean societies flourished in the Late Hellenistic era
and during the Roman era (such as those in Antiochia, Alexandria, Rhodes and Ercolano). The
poet Lucretius is its most known Roman proponent. By the end of the Roman Empire, having
undergone Christian attack and repression, Epicureanism had all but died out, and would be
resurrected in the 17th century by the atomist Pierre Gassendi, who adapted it to the Christian
doctrine.
Some writings by Epicurus have survived. Some scholars consider the epic poem On the Nature
of Things by Lucretius to present in one unified work the core arguments and theories of
Epicureanism. Many of the papyrus scrolls unearthed at the Villa of the Papyri at Herculaneum
are Epicurean texts. At least some are thought to have belonged to the Epicurean Philodemus.
[edit] Christian
Main article: Christian hedonism
Christian hedonism is a controversial Christian doctrine current in some evangelical circles,
particularly those of the Reformed tradition. The term was coined by Reformed Baptist pastor
John Piper in his 1986 book Desiring God. Piper summarizes this philosophy of the Christian life
as "God is most glorified in us when we are most satisfied in Him."[3] Christian Hedonism may
anachronistically describe the theology of Jonathan Edwards. In the 17th century the atomist
Pierre Gassendi, adapted Epicureanism to the Christian doctrine.
[edit] Utilitarianism
[edit] Mohism
Main article: Mohism
Mohism was a philosophical school of thought founded by Mozi in the 5th century BCE. It
parallelled the utilitarianism later developed by the Anglo-Saxon thinkers. As Confucianism
became the preferred philosophy of later Chinese dynasties, Mohism and other non-Confucian
philosophical schools of thought were supressed.
[edit] Anglo-Saxon utilitarianism
The nineteenth-century British philosophers John Stuart Mill and Jeremy Bentham defended the
ethical theory of utilitarianism, according to which we should perform whichever action
maximizes the aggregate good. Conjoining hedonism, as a view as to what is good for people, to
utilitarianism has the result that all action should be directed toward achieving the greatest total
amount of happiness (Hedonic Calculus). Though consistent in their pursuit of happiness,
Bentham and Mill’s versions of hedonism differ. There are two somewhat basic schools of
thought on hedonism:[1]
• One school, grouped around Jeremy Bentham, defends a quantitative approach. Bentham
believed that the value of a pleasure could be quantitatively understood. Essentially, he
believed the value of pleasure to be its intensity multiplied by its duration - so it was not
just the number of pleasures, but their intensity and how long they lasted that must be
taken into account.
• Other proponents, like John Stuart Mill, argue a qualitative approach. Mill believed that
there can be different levels of pleasure - higher quality pleasure is better than lower
quality pleasure. Mill also argues that simpler beings (he often refers to pigs) have an
easier access to the simpler pleasures; since they do not see other aspects of life, they can
simply indulge in their lower pleasures. The more elaborate beings tend to spend more
thought on other matters and hence lessen the time for simple pleasure. It is therefore
more difficult for them to indulge in such "simple pleasures" in the same manner.
Critics of the quantitative approach assert that, generally, "pleasures" do not necessarily share
common traits besides the fact that they can be seen as "pleasurable."[citation needed] Critics of the
qualitative approach argue that whether one pleasure is higher than another depends on factors
other than how pleasurable it is.[citation needed] For example, some people may see the pleasure of
satanism as a more base pleasure because it is morally unpalatable to them, and not because it is
lacking in pleasure.
In the medical sciences, the inability to derive pleasure from experiences that are typically
considered pleasurable is referred to as anhedonia.
[edit] Egoism
Hedonism can be conjoined with psychological egoism - the theory that humans are motivated
only by their self interest - to make psychological hedonism: a purely descriptive claim which
states that agents naturally seek pleasure. Hedonism can also be combined with ethical egoism -
the claim that individuals should seek their own good - to make ethical hedonism the claim that
we should act so as to produce our own pleasure.
However, hedonism is not necessarily related to egoism. The utilitarianism of John Stuart Mill is
sometimes classified as a type of hedonism, as it judges the morality of actions by their
consequent contributions to the greater good and happiness of all. This is altruistic hedonism.
Whereas some hedonistic doctrines propose doing whatever makes an individual happiest (over
the long run), Mill promotes actions which make everyone happy. Compare individualism and
collectivism.
It is true that Epicurus recommends for us to pursue our own pleasure, but he never suggests we
should live a selfish life which impedes others from getting to that same objective.
Some of Sigmund Freud's theories of human motivation have been called psychological
hedonism[citation needed]; his "life instinct" is essentially the observation that people will pursue
pleasure. However, he introduces extra complexities with various other mechanisms, such as the
"death instinct". The death instinct, Thanatos, can be equated to the desire for silence and peace,
for calm and darkness, which causes them another form of happiness. It is also a death instinct,
thus it can also be the desire for death. Psychoanalysis has developed greatly since Freud but his
ideas remain influential and contentious.
[edit] Contemporary approaches
A modern proponent of hedonism with an ethical touch is the Swedish philosopher Torbjörn
Tännsjö[4].
[edit] Michel Onfray
Main article: Michel Onfray
A dedicated contemporary hedonist philosopher and on the history of hedonistic thought is the
French Michel Onfray. He defines hedonism "as an introspective attitude to life based on taking
pleasure yourself and pleasuring others, without harming yourself or anyone else."[5] "Onfray's
philosophical project is to define an ethical hedonism, a joyous utilitarianism, and a generalized
aesthetic of sensual materialism that explores how to use the brain's and the body's capacities to
their fullest extent -- while restoring philosophy to a useful role in art, politics, and everyday life
and decisions."[6]
Onfray's works "have explored the philosophical resonances and components of (and challenges
to) science, painting, gastronomy, sex and sensuality, bioethics, wine, and writing. His most
ambitious project is his projected six-volume Counter-history of Philosophy,"[7] of which three
have been published. For him "In opposition to the ascetic ideal advocated by the dominant
school of thought, hedonism suggests identifying the highest good with your own pleasure and
that of others; the one must never be indulged at the expense of sacrificing the other. Obtaining
this balance – my pleasure at the same time as the pleasure of others – presumes that we
approach the subject from different angles – political, ethical, aesthetic, erotic, bioethical,
pedagogical, historiographical…."
For this he has "written books on each of these facets of the same world view."[8]His philosophy
aims "for "micro-revolutions, " or revolutions of the individual and small groups of like-minded
people who live by his hedonistic, libertarian values."[9]
[edit] Abolitionism
Main article: Abolitionism (bioethics)
One modern group that is hedonistic is the Abolitionist Society. They are also a part of the
transhumanistic movement. They propose that all suffering should be abolished, and the
prospects for happiness be increased, through biotechnology at a major scale.
[edit] Criticism
Hedonism has been criticized by a number of modern philosophers.
Robert Nozick argued that we do not only want the pleasure from our activities, but actually
want to do them for their own sake as well.
G.E Moore argued that hedonists commit the naturalistic fallacy.

Вам также может понравиться