Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 4

Published on Philosophy (https://philosophy.tamucc.

edu)
Home > Printer-friendly PDF > Printer-friendly PDF

Foundations of Professional Ethics


Submitted by Stefan Sencerz on Mon, 02/02/2015 - 15:16
Course Home [1]

Monday, 02-02-15: Natural Law Theory


Synopsis:

Texts: C. E. Harris, The Ethics of Natural Law [2]


[http://falcon.tamucc.edu/~sencerz/Harris_Nat_Law.htm]
ASSUMPTIONS OF THE NATURAL LAW THEORY
The Teleological World View (TWV)
The world, and all things in the world, have a function (purpose, end, goal (gr. telos)). (Variants of
this theory assume only that humans and other living creatures have telos).
A Christian Philosopher, and the Doctor of Church, St. Thomas Aquinas (1225?74) attempted to
provide interpretation of the Holy Scripture in light of philosophical insights of the great Greek
philosopher, Aristotle (383?322 B.C.). Both Aristotle and Aquinas assume that (TWV) is true. To
support this view Aquinas assumes that world is both intelligently designed and created in
accordance with the Divine Plan.
It is an open question whether an atheist can also assume that the Teleological World View is
true. Many physicalists and materialists (students of Newton, Kepler, and Galileo) would reject
TWV. They argue that since everything is a result of purely physical causes, nothing has telos.
Suppose, however, that at least living creatures, especially humans, have telos a proper
purpose. Given this assumption, we can develop an ethical theory.

Positive (human) Law vs. Natural Law


Augustine distinguishes two kinds of law, the one eternal, the other temporal, which he calls
human... These particular determinations, devised by human reason, are called human laws,
provided that the other essential conditions of law be observed... (Aquinas, Q91, art 3)
To wit, human (positive) law is what we design to guide our action. Aquinas notices that, since
our intellects are limited, our laws are imperfect in many respects. For example, human laws
sometimes fail to proscribe all bad things (Q91, art. 4).
Aquinas thinks also that, for each human being, our destiny (goal) is to flourish and be fully
happy. But he observes also that our natural abilities are insufficient to bring about our destiny,
we have insufficient skills to guarantee that we will be happy. As he observes:
man is ordained to an end of eternal happiness which exceeds man's natural ability, . . .
therefore it was necessary that, in addition to the natural and the human law, man should
be directed to his end by a law given by God. (ibid.)
Aquinas calls this God's law the Natural Law. NL is a set of principles that guide the behavior of
all rational beings in accordance with our proper function. Those principles are independent of
any human law and depend only on the nature of humans (in other words, on our essence or
proper function).
BASIC PRINCIPLES OF THE NATURAL LAW THEORY (NLT)
NLT1: An action, A, is morally right iff A is consistent with the nature (essence) of a human
(or a living) being.
The nature (essence) of a human being encompasses all of our relevant proper purposes.
Hence, there is another way to state the main principle of NLT:
NLT2:An action, A, is morally right iff A is consistent with all relevant proper purposes of a
human (or a living) being.
Aquinas accepts an Aristotelian concept of a human being as a rational animal. That is, our
essence (nature), consists in the fact that we are both rational and biological beings. This fact
points to two different sets of requirements that we must fulfill. First, Aquinas thinks that all
actions that develop us as rational beings of intellectual nature are morally right. As he observes:
"the rational soul is the proper form of man, there is in every man a natural inclination to act
according to reason; and this is to act according to virtue. Consequently, considered thus,
all the acts of the virtues are prescribed by the natural law, since each one's reason
naturally dictates to him to act virtuously. ... For many things are done virtuously, to which
nature does not primarily incline, but which, through the inquiry of reason, have been found
by men to be conducive to well?living...." (Q93, art. 3)
All actions that harm our rational nature (or are contrary to it in some other way) are morally

wrong.
In addition, actions that sustain us as biological organisms are also morally right. By extension,
actions that harm us as biological organism are wrong. As he observes:
Temperance is about the natural concupiscences of food, drink and sexual matters, which
are indeed ordained to the common good of nature, just as other matters of law are
ordained to the moral common good. (Q93, art. 3)
Aquinas and many NL theorists assume that we are created in God's image. We must remember
that they assume also that God is maximally (or all?)good, maximally powerfull, and all?knowing.
These assumptions have profound implications. Most fundamentally, God never creates anything
bad, and never aims at anything bad. At most, God allows for bad things to happen and only if
there is a sufficient reason for it. (Notice what we earlier said about the argument from evil and
the superfluous evil.)
SUPLEMENTARY PRINCIPLES: Can we ever take a life of a person. Traditional versions of
(NLT) tried to solve the problem by the means of one of the folowing principles:
The Principle of Forfeiture (PF): If X threatens an innocent human life (i.e., violates the
principle concerning the protection of life), X forfeits his (her) right to life. Thus, killing in
necessary self?defense is morally permissible.
Many contemporary proponents of NLT reject (PF). They think that this principle cannot be
reconcile with the doctrine of the sacnctity of human life. Notice, just like it is not in God's nature
to directly bring about something bad (for God is all good), it is not in our nature (essence) to aim
at anything bad. At most, we can allow that bad things happen and only if there is a sufficient
reason for that. This is known as
The Principle of Double Effect (PDE): A person may lawfully perform an action from
which two effects will follow, one bad, and the other good when four conditions obtain:
1. The act itself must be morally good or at least indifferent.
2. The agent may not positively will the bad effect but may merely permit it. If he could
attain the good effect without the bad effect, he should do so.
3. The good effect must flow from the action at least as immediately (in the order of
causality, though not necessarily in the order of time) as the bad effect.
4. The good effect must be sufficiently desirable to compensate for the allowing of the bad
effect. [Adopted from the New Catholic Encyclopedia]

LOGIC ETHICS HISTORY METAPHYSICS EPISTEMOLOGY MIND VALUE


LANGUAGE

Source URL: https://philosophy.tamucc.edu/content/foundations-professional-ethics


Links:
[1] ../https://ethics.tamucc.edu/
[2] http://falcon.tamucc.edu/~sencerz/Harris_Nat_Law.htm

Вам также может понравиться