Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 37

Wittgenstein's Philosophy of Mathematics

First published Fri Feb 23, 2007; substantive revision Mon Mar 21, 2011
Ludwig Wittgenstein's Philosophy of Mathematics is undoubtedly the most unknown and underappreciated part of his philosophical opus. Indeed, more than half of Wittgenstein's writings from
1929 through 1944 are devoted to mathematics, a fact that Wittgenstein himself emphasized in
1944 by writing that his chief contribution has been in the philosophy of mathematics (Monk
1990, 466).
The core of Wittgenstein's conception of mathematics is very much set by the Tractatus LogicoPhilosophicus (1922; hereafter Tractatus), where his main aim is to work out the languagereality connection by determining what is required for language, or language usage, to be about
the world. Wittgenstein answers this question, in part, by asserting that the only genuine
propositions that we can use to make assertions about reality are contingent (empirical)
propositions, which are true if they agree with reality and false otherwise (4.022, 4.25, 4.062,
2.222). From this it follows that all other apparent propositions are pseudo-propositions of
various types and that all other uses of true and truth deviate markedly from the truth-bycorrespondence (or agreement) that contingent propositions have in relation to reality. Thus,
from the Tractatus to at least 1944, Wittgenstein maintains that mathematical propositions are
not real propositions and that mathematical truth is essentially non-referential and purely
syntactical in nature. On Wittgenstein's view, we invent mathematical calculi and we expand
mathematics by calculation and proof, and though we learn from a proof that a theorem can be
derived from axioms by means of certain rules in a particular way, it is not the case that this
proof-path pre-exists our construction of it.
As we shall see, Wittgenstein's Philosophy of Mathematics begins in a rudimentary way in the
Tractatus, develops into a finitistic constructivism in the middle period (Philosophical Remarks
(192930) and Philosophical Grammar (193133), respectively; hereafter PR and PG,
respectively), and is further developed in new and old directions in the MSS used for Remarks
on the Foundations of Mathematics (193744; hereafter RFM). As Wittgenstein's substantive
views on mathematics evolve from 1918 through 1944, his writing and philosophical styles
evolve from the assertoric, aphoristic style of the Tractatus to a clearer, argumentative style in
the middle period, to a dialectical, interlocutory style in RFM and the Philosophical
Investigations (hereafter PI).

1. Wittgenstein on Mathematics in the Tractatus

2. The Middle Wittgenstein's Finitistic Constructivism


o 2.1 Wittgenstein's Intermediate Constructive Formalism
o 2.2 Wittgenstein's Intermediate Finitism

o 2.3 Wittgenstein's Intermediate Finitism and Algorithmic Decidability


o 2.4 Wittgenstein's Intermediate Account of Mathematical Induction and
Algorithmic Decidability
o 2.5 Wittgenstein's Intermediate Account of Irrational Numbers
o 2.6 Wittgenstein's Intermediate Critique of Set Theory

3. The Later Wittgenstein on Mathematics: Some Preliminaries


o 3.1 Mathematics as a Human Invention
o 3.2 Wittgenstein's Later Finitistic Constructivism
o 3.3 The Later Wittgenstein on Decidability and Algorithmic Decidability
o 3.4 Wittgenstein's Later Critique of Set Theory: Non-Enumerability vs. NonDenumerability
o 3.5 Extra-Mathematical Application as a Necessary Condition of Mathematical
Meaningfulness
o 3.6 Wittgenstein on Gdel and Undecidable Mathematical Propositions

4. The Impact of Philosophy of Mathematics on Mathematics

Bibliography
o Wittgenstein's Writings
o Notes on Wittgenstein's Lectures and Recorded Conversations
o Secondary Sources and Relevant Primary Literature

Academic Tools

Other Internet Resources

Related Entries

1. Wittgenstein on Mathematics in the Tractatus

Wittgenstein's non-referential, formalist conception of mathematical propositions and terms


begins in the Tractatus.[1] Indeed, insofar as he sketches a rudimentary Philosophy of
Mathematics in the Tractatus, he does so by contrasting mathematics and mathematical
equations with genuine (contingent) propositions, sense, thought, propositional signs and their
constituent names, and truth-by-correspondence.
In the Tractatus, Wittgenstein claims that a genuine proposition, which rests upon conventions, is
used by us to assert that a state of affairs (i.e., an elementary or atomic fact; Sachverhalt) or fact
(i.e., multiple states of affairs; Tatsache) obtain(s) in the one and only real world. An
elementary proposition is isomorphic to the possible state of affairs it is used to represent: it must
contain as many names as there are objects in the possible state of affairs. An elementary
proposition is true iff its possible state of affairs (i.e., its sense; Sinn) obtains. Wittgenstein
clearly states this Correspondence Theory of Truth at (4.25): If an elementary proposition is
true, the state of affairs exists; if an elementary proposition is false, the state of affairs does not
exist. But propositions and their linguistic components are, in and of themselves, deada
proposition only has sense because we human beings have endowed it with a conventional sense
(5.473). Moreover, propositional signs may be used to do any number of things (e.g., insult,
catch someone's attention); in order to assert that a state of affairs obtains, a person must
project the proposition's senseits possible state of affairsby thinking of (e.g., picturing) its
sense as one speaks, writes or thinks the proposition (3.11). Wittgenstein connects use, sense,
correspondence, and truth by saying that a proposition is true if we use it to say that things
stand in a certain way, and they do (4.062; italics added).
The Tractarian conceptions of genuine (contingent) propositions and the (original and) core
concept of truth are used to construct theories of logical and mathematical propositions by
contrast. Stated boldly and bluntly, tautologies, contradictions and mathematical propositions
(i.e., mathematical equations) are neither true nor falsewe say that they are true or false, but in
doing so we use the words true and false in very different senses from the sense in which a
contingent proposition is true or false. Unlike genuine propositions, tautologies and
contradictions have no subject-matter (6.124), lack sense, and say nothing about the
world (4.461), and, analogously, mathematical equations are pseudo-propositions (6.2) which,
when true (correct; richtig (6.2321)), merely mark[] [the] equivalence of meaning [of
two expressions] (6.2323). Given that [t]autology and contradiction are the limiting cases
indeed the disintegrationof the combination of signs (4.466; italics added), where the
conditions of agreement with the worldthe representational relationscancel one another, so
that [they] do[] not stand in any representational relation to reality, tautologies and
contradictions do not picture reality or possible states of affairs and possible facts (4.462). Stated
differently, tautologies and contradictions do not have sense, which means we cannot use them to
make assertions, which means, in turn, that they cannot be either true or false. Analogously,
mathematical pseudo-propositions are equations, which indicate or show that two expressions are
equivalent in meaning and therefore are intersubstitutable. Indeed, we arrive at mathematical
equations by the method of substitution: starting from a number of equations, we advance to
new equations by substituting different expressions in accordance with the equations (6.24). We
prove mathematical propositions true (correct) by seeing that two expressions have the
same meaning, which must be manifest in the two expressions themselves (6.23), and by
substituting one expression for another with the same meaning. Just as one can recognize that

[logical propositions] are true from the symbol alone (6.113), the possibility of proving
mathematical propositions means that we can perceive their correctness without having to
compare what they express with facts (6.2321; cf. (RFM App. III, 4)).
The demarcation between contingent propositions, which can be used to correctly or incorrectly
represent parts of the world, and mathematical propositions, which can be decided in a purely
formal, syntactical manner, is maintained by Wittgenstein until his death in 1951 (Zettel 701,
1947; PI II, 2001 Ed., pp. 192193e, 1949). Given linguistic and symbolic conventions, the
truth-value of a contingent proposition is entirely a function of how the world is, whereas the
truth-value of a mathematical proposition is entirely a function of its constituent symbols and
the formal system of which it is a part. Thus, a second, closely related way of stating this
demarcation is to say that mathematical propositions are decidable by purely formal means (e.g.,
calculations), while contingent propositions, being about the external world, can only be
decided, if at all, by determining whether or not a particular fact obtains (i.e., something external
to the proposition and the language in which it resides) (2.223; 4.05).
The Tractarian formal theory of mathematics is, specifically, a theory of formal operations. Over
the past 10 years, Wittgenstein's theory of operations has received considerable examination
[(Frascolla 1994; 1997), (Marion 1998), (Potter 2000), and (Floyd 2002)], which has
interestingly connected it and the Tractarian equational theory of arithmetic with elements of
Alonzo Church's -calculus and with R. L. Goodstein's equational calculus (Marion 1998,
Chapters 1, 2, and 4). Very briefly stated, Wittgenstein presents:
a. the sign [a, x, Ox] for the general term of the series of forms a, Oa, OOa, .
(5.2522)
b. the general form of an operation () [as]
[, N()]() (= [, , N()]). (6.01)
c. the general form of a proposition (truth-function) [as] [p, , N()]. (6)
d. The general form of an integer [natural number] [as] [0, , + 1]. (6.03)
adding that [t]he concept of number is the general form of a number (6.022). As Frascolla
(and Marion after him) have pointed out, the general form of a proposition is a particular case
of the general form of an operation (Marion 1998, p. 21), and all three general forms (i.e., of
operation, proposition, and natural number) are modeled on the variable presented at (5.2522)
(Marion 1998, p. 22). Defining [a]n operation [as] the expression of a relation between the
structures of its result and of its bases (5.22), Wittgenstein states that whereas [a] function
cannot be its own argument, an operation can take one of its own results as its base (5.251).
On Wittgenstein's (5.2522) account of [a, x, Ox], the first term of the bracketed expression is
the beginning of the series of forms, the second is the form of a term x arbitrarily selected from
the series, and the third [Ox] is the form of the term that immediately follows x in the series.
Given that [t]he concept of successive applications of an operation is equivalent to the concept

and so on (5.2523), one can see how the natural numbers can be generated by repeated
iterations of the general form of a natural number, namely [0, , +1]. Similarly, truthfunctional propositions can be generated, as Russell says in the Introduction to the Tractatus (p.
xv), from the general form of a proposition [p, , N()] by taking any selection of atomic
propositions [where p stands for all atomic propositions; the bar over the variable indicates
that it is the representative of all its values (5.501)], negating them all, then taking any selection
of the set of propositions now obtained, together with any of the originals [where x stands for
any set of propositions]and so on indefinitely. On Frascolla's (1994, 3ff) account, a
numerical identity t = s is an arithmetical theorem if and only if the corresponding equation
tx = sx, which is framed in the language of the general theory of logical operations, can be
proven. By proving the equation 22x = 4x, which translates the arithmetic identity 2
2 = 4 into the operational language (6.241), Wittgenstein thereby outlines a translation of
numerical arithmetic into a sort of general theory of operations (Frascolla 1998, 135).
Despite the fact that Wittgenstein clearly does not attempt to reduce mathematics to logic in
either Russell's manner or Frege's manner, or to tautologies, and despite the fact that Wittgenstein
criticizes Russell's Logicism (e.g., the Theory of Types, 3.313.32; the Axiom of Reducibility,
6.1232, etc.) and Frege's Logicism (6.031, 4.1272, etc.),[2] quite a number of commentators, early
and recent, have interpreted Wittgenstein's Tractarian theory of mathematics as a variant of
Logicism [(Quine 1940 [1981, 55]), (Benacerraf and Putnam 1964, 14), (Black 1966, 340),
(Savitt 1979 [1986], 34), (Frascolla 1994, 37; 1997, 354, 35657, 361; 1998, 133), (Marion
1998, 26 & 29), and (Potter 2000, 164 and 182183)]. There are at least four reasons proffered
for this interpretation.
1. Wittgenstein says that [m]athematics is a method of logic (6.234).
2. Wittgenstein says that [t]he logic of the world, which is shown in tautologies by the
propositions of logic, is shown in equations by mathematics (6.22).
3. According to Wittgenstein, we ascertain the truth of both mathematical and logical
propositions by the symbol alone (i.e., by purely formal operations), without making any
(external, non-symbolic) observations of states of affairs or facts in the world.
4. Wittgenstein's iterative (inductive) interpretation of numerals as exponents of an
operation variable is a reduction of arithmetic to operation theory, where operation
is construed as a logical operation (italics added) (Frascolla 1994, 37), which shows
that the label no-classes logicism tallies with the Tractatus view of arithmetic
(Frascolla 1998, 133; 1997, 354).
Though at least three Logicist interpretations of the Tractatus have appeared within the last 8
years, the following considerations [(Rodych 1995), (Wrigley 1998)] indicate that none of these
reasons is particularly cogent.
For example, in saying that [m]athematics is a method of logic perhaps Wittgenstein is only
saying that since the general form of a natural number and the general form of a proposition are
both instances of the general form of a (purely formal) operation, just as truth-functional

propositions can be constructed using the general form of a proposition, (true) mathematical
equations can be constructed using the general form of a natural number. Alternatively,
Wittgenstein may mean that mathematical inferences (i.e., not substitutions) are in accord with,
or make use of, logical inferences, and insofar as mathematical reasoning is logical reasoning,
mathematics is a method of logic.
Similarly, in saying that [t]he logic of the world is shown by tautologies and true mathematical
equations (i.e., #2), Wittgenstein may be saying that since mathematics was invented to help us
count and measure, insofar as it enables us to infer contingent proposition(s) from contingent
proposition(s) (see 6.211 below), it thereby reflects contingent facts and [t]he logic of the
world. Though logicwhich is inherent in natural (everyday) language (4.002, 4.003, 6.124)
and which has evolved to meet our communicative, exploratory, and survival needsis not
invented in the same way, a valid logical inference captures the relationship between possible
facts and a sound logical inference captures the relationship between existent facts.
As regards #3, Black, Savitt, and Frascolla have argued that, since we ascertain the truth of
tautologies and mathematical equations without any appeal to states of affairs or facts, true
mathematical equations and tautologies are so analogous that we can aptly describe the
philosophy of arithmetic of the Tractatus as a kind of logicism (Frascolla, 1994, 37). The
rejoinder to this is that the similarity that Frascolla, Black and Savitt recognize does not make
Wittgenstein's theory a kind of logicism in Frege's or Russell's sense, because Wittgenstein
does not define numbers logically in either Frege's way or Russell's way, and the similarity (or
analogy) between tautologies and true mathematical equations is neither an identity nor a relation
of reducibility.
Finally, critics argue that the problem with #4 is that there is no evidence for the claim that the
relevant operation is logical in Wittgenstein's or Russell's or Frege's sense of the termit seems
a purely formal, syntactical operation (Rodych 1995). Logical operations are performed with
propositions, arithmetical ones with numbers, says Wittgenstein (WVC 218); [t]he result of a
logical operation is a proposition, the result of an arithmetical one is a number. In sum, critics
of the Logicist interpretation of the Tractatus argue that ##14 do not individually or collectively
constitute cogent grounds for a Logicist interpretation of the Tractatus.
Another crucial aspect of the Tractarian theory of mathematics is captured in (6.211).
Indeed in real life a mathematical proposition is never what we want. Rather, we make use of
mathematical propositions only in inferences from propositions that do not belong to
mathematics to others that likewise do not belong to mathematics. (In philosophy the question,
What do we actually use this word or this proposition for? repeatedly leads to valuable
insights.)
Though mathematics and mathematical activity are purely formal and syntactical, in the
Tractatus Wittgenstein tacitly distinguishes between purely formal games with signs, which have
no application in contingent propositions, and mathematical propositions, which are used to
make inferences from contingent proposition(s) to contingent proposition(s). Wittgenstein does
not explicitly say, however, how mathematical equations, which are not genuine propositions, are

used in inferences from genuine proposition(s) to genuine proposition(s) [(Floyd 2002, 309),
(Kremer 2002, 29394)]. As we shall see in 3.5, the later Wittgenstein returns to the importance
of extra-mathematical application and uses it to distinguish a mere sign-game from a genuine,
mathematical language-game.
This, in brief, is Wittgenstein's Tractarian theory of mathematics. In the Introduction to the
Tractatus, Russell wrote that Wittgenstein's theory of number stands in need of greater
technical development, primarily because Wittgenstein had not shown how it could deal with
transfinite numbers (Wittgenstein 1922, xx). Similarly, in his review of the Tractatus, Frank
Ramsey wrote that Wittgenstein's account does not cover all of mathematics partly because
Wittgenstein's theory of equations cannot explain inequalities (Ramsey 1923, 475). Though it is
doubtful that, in 1923, Wittgenstein would have thought these issues problematic, it certainly is
true that the Tractarian theory of mathematics is essentially a sketch, especially in comparison
with what Wittgenstein begins to develop six years later.
After the completion of the Tractatus in 1918, Wittgenstein did virtually no philosophical work
until February 2, 1929, eleven months after attending a lecture by the Dutch mathematician
L.E.J. Brouwer.

2. The Middle Wittgenstein's Finitistic Constructivism


There is little doubt that Wittgenstein was invigorated by L.E.J. Brouwer's March 10, 1928
Vienna lecture Science, Mathematics, and Language (Brouwer 1929), which he attended with
F. Waismann and H. Feigl, but it is a gross overstatement to say that he returned to Philosophy
because of this lecture or that his intermediate interest in the Philosophy of Mathematics issued
primarily from Brouwer's influence. In fact, Wittgenstein's return to Philosophy and his
intermediate work on mathematics is also due to conversations with Ramsey and members of the
Vienna circle, to Wittgenstein's disagreement with Ramsey over identity, and several other
factors.
Though Wittgenstein seems not to have read any Hilbert or Brouwer prior to the completion of
the Tractatus, by early 1929 Wittgenstein had certainly read work by Brouwer, Weyl, Skolem,
Ramsey (and possibly Hilbert) and, apparently, he had had one or more private discussions with
Brouwer in 1928 [(Le Roy Finch 1977, 260), (Van Dalen 2005, 566567)]. Thus, the
rudimentary treatment of mathematics in the Tractatus, whose principal influences were Russell
and Frege, was succeeded by detailed work on mathematics in the middle period (19291933),
which was strongly influenced by the 1920s work of Brouwer, Weyl, Hilbert, and Skolem.

2.1 Wittgenstein's Intermediate Constructive Formalism


To best understand Wittgenstein's intermediate Philosophy of Mathematics, one must fully
appreciate his strong variant of formalism, according to which [w]e make mathematics (WVC
34, Ft. #1; PR 159) by inventing purely formal mathematical calculi, with stipulated axioms
(PR 202), syntactical rules of transformation, and decision procedures that enable us to invent
mathematical truth and mathematical falsity by algorithmically deciding so-called
mathematical propositions (PR 122, 162).

The core idea of Wittgenstein's formalism from 1929 (if not 1918) through 1944 is that
mathematics is essentially syntactical, devoid of reference and semantics. The most obvious
aspect of this view, which has been noted by numerous commentators who do not refer to
Wittgenstein as a formalist [(Kielkopf 1970, 36038), (Klenk 1976, 5, 8, 9), (Fogelin 1968,
267), (Frascolla 1994, 40), (Marion 1998, 1314)], is that, contra Platonism, the signs and
propositions of a mathematical calculus do not refer to anything. As Wittgenstein says at (WVC
34, Ft. #1), [n]umbers are not represented by proxies; numbers are there. This means not only
that numbers are there in the use, it means that the numerals are the numbers, for [a]rithmetic
doesn't talk about numbers, it works with numbers (PR 109).
What arithmetic is concerned with is the schema | | | |.But does arithmetic talk about the lines I
draw with pencil on paper?Arithmetic doesn't talk about the lines, it operates with them. (PG
333)
In a similar vein, Wittgenstein says that (WVC 106) mathematics is always a machine, a
calculus and [a] calculus is an abacus, a calculator, a calculating machine, which works by
means of strokes, numerals, etc. The justified side of formalism, according to Wittgenstein
(WVC 105), is that mathematical symbols lack a meaning (i.e., Bedeutung)they do not go
proxy for things which are their meaning[s].
You could say arithmetic is a kind of geometry; i.e. what in geometry are constructions on paper,
in arithmetic are calculations (on paper).You could say it is a more general kind of geometry.
(PR 109; PR 111)
This is the core of Wittgenstein's life-long formalism. When we prove a theorem or decide a
proposition, we operate in a purely formal, syntactical manner. In doing mathematics, we do not
discover pre-existing truths that were already there without one knowing (PG 481)we invent
mathematics, bit-by-little-bit. If you want to know what 2 + 2 = 4 means, says Wittgenstein,
you have to ask how we work it out, because we consider the process of calculation as the
essential thing (PG 333). Hence, the only meaning (i.e., sense) that a mathematical proposition
has is intra-systemic meaning, which is wholly determined by its syntactical relations to other
propositions of the calculus.
A second important aspect of the intermediate Wittgenstein's strong formalism is his view that
extra-mathematical application (and/or reference) is not a necessary condition of a mathematical
calculus. Mathematical calculi do not require extra-mathematical applications, Wittgenstein
argues, since we can develop arithmetic completely autonomously and its application takes care
of itself since wherever it's applicable we may also apply it (PR 109; cf. PG 308, WVC 104).
As we shall shortly see, the middle Wittgenstein is also drawn to strong formalism by a new
concern with questions of decidability. Undoubtedly influenced by the writings of Brouwer and
David Hilbert, Wittgenstein uses strong formalism to forge a new connection between
mathematical meaningfulness and algorithmic decidability.
An equation is a rule of syntax. Doesn't that explain why we cannot have questions in
mathematics that are in principle unanswerable? For if the rules of syntax cannot be grasped,

theyre of no use at all. [This] makes intelligible the attempts of the formalist to see
mathematics as a game with signs. (PR 121)
In Section 2.3, we shall see how Wittgenstein goes beyond both Hilbert and Brouwer by
maintaining the Law of the Excluded Middle in a way that restricts mathematical propositions to
expressions that are algorithmically decidable.

2.2 Wittgenstein's Intermediate Finitism


The single most important difference between the Early and Middle Wittgenstein is that, in the
middle period, Wittgenstein rejects quantification over an infinite mathematical domain, stating
that, contra his Tractarian view, such propositions are not infinite conjunctions and infinite
disjunctions simply because there are no such things.
Wittgenstein's principal reasons for developing a finitistic Philosophy of Mathematics are as
follows.
1. Mathematics as Human Invention: According to the middle Wittgenstein, we invent
mathematics, from which it follows that mathematics and so-called mathematical objects
do not exist independently of our inventions. Whatever is mathematical is fundamentally
a product of human activity.
2. Mathematical Calculi Consist Exclusively of Intensions and Extensions: Given that we
have invented only mathematical extensions (e.g., symbols, finite sets, finite sequences,
propositions, axioms) and mathematical intensions (e.g., rules of inference and
transformation, irrational numbers as rules), these extensions and intensions, and the
calculi in which they reside, constitute the entirety of mathematics. (It should be noted
that Wittgenstein's usage of extension and intension as regards mathematics differs
markedly from standard contemporary usage, wherein the extension of a predicate is the
set of entities that satisfy the predicate and the intension of a predicate is the meaning of,
or expressed by, the predicate. Put succinctly, Wittgenstein thinks that the extension of
this notion of concept-and-extension from the domain of existent (i.e., physical) objects
to the so-called domain of mathematical objects is based on a faulty analogy and
engenders conceptual confusion. See #1 just below.)
These two reasons have at least five immediate consequences for Wittgenstein's Philosophy of
Mathematics.
1. Rejection of Infinite Mathematical Extensions: Given that a mathematical extension is a
symbol (sign) or a finite concatenation of symbols extended in space, there is a
categorical difference between mathematical intensions and (finite) mathematical
extensions, from which it follows that the mathematical infinite resides only in
recursive rules (i.e., intensions). An infinite mathematical extension (i.e., a completed,
infinite mathematical extension) is a contradiction-in-terms

2. Rejection of Unbounded Quantification in Mathematics: Given that the mathematical


infinite can only be a recursive rule, and given that a mathematical proposition must have
sense, it follows that there cannot be an infinite mathematical proposition (i.e., an infinite
logical product or an infinite logical sum).
3. Algorithmic Decidability vs. Undecidability: If mathematical extensions of all kinds are
necessarily finite, then, in principle, all mathematical propositions are algorithmically
decidable, from which it follows that an undecidable mathematical proposition is a
contradiction-in-terms. Moreover, since mathematics is essentially what we have and
what we know, Wittgenstein restricts algorithmic decidability to knowing how to decide a
proposition with a known decision procedure.
4. Anti-Foundationalist Account of Real Numbers: Since there are no infinite mathematical
extensions, irrational numbers are rules, not extensions. Given that an infinite set is a
recursive rule (or an induction) and no such rule can generate all of the things
mathematicians call (or want to call) real numbers, it follows that there is no set of all
the real numbers and no such thing as the mathematical continuum.
5. Rejection of Different Infinite Cardinalities: Given the non-existence of infinite
mathematical extensions, Wittgenstein rejects the standard interpretation of Cantor's
diagonal proof as a proof of infinite sets of greater and lesser cardinalities.
Since we invent mathematics in its entirety, we do not discover pre-existing mathematical
objects or facts or that mathematical objects have certain properties, for one cannot discover
any connection between parts of mathematics or logic that was already there without one
knowing (PG 481). In examining mathematics as a purely human invention, Wittgenstein tries
to determine what exactly we have invented and why exactly, in his opinion, we erroneously
think that there are infinite mathematical extensions.
If, first, we examine what we have invented, we see that we have invented formal calculi
consisting of finite extensions and intensional rules. If, more importantly, we endeavour to
determine why we believe that infinite mathematical extensions exist (e.g., why we believe that
the actual infinite is intrinsic to mathematics), we find that we conflate mathematical intensions
and mathematical extensions, erroneously thinking that there is a dualism of the law and the
infinite series obeying it (PR 180). For instance, we think that because a real number
endlessly yields the places of a decimal fraction (PR 186), it is a totality (WVC 8182, Ft.
#1), when, in reality, [a]n irrational number isn't the extension of an infinite decimal fraction,
it's a law (PR 181) which yields extensions (PR 186). A law and a list are fundamentally
different; neither can give what the other gives (WVC 102103). Indeed, the mistake in the settheoretical approach consists time and again in treating laws and enumerations (lists) as
essentially the same kind of thing (PG 461).
Closely related with this conflation of intensions and extensions is the fact that we mistakenly act
as if the word infinite is a number word, because in ordinary discourse we answer the
question how many? with both (PG 463; cf. PR 142). But [i]nfinite is not a quantity,
Wittgenstein insists (WVC 228); the word infinite and a number word like five do not have the

same syntax. The words finite and infinite do not function as adjectives on the words class or
set, (WVC 102), for the terms finite class and infinite class use class in completely
different ways (WVC 228). An infinite class is a recursive rule or an induction, whereas the
symbol for a finite class is a list or extension (PG 461). It is because an induction has much in
common with the multiplicity of a finite class that we erroneously call it an infinite class (PR
158).
In sum, because a mathematical extension is necessarily a finite sequence of symbols, an infinite
mathematical extension is a contradiction-in-terms. This is the foundation of Wittgenstein's
finitism. Thus, when we say, e.g., that there are infinitely many even numbers, we are not
saying there are an infinite number of even numbers in the same sense as we can say there are
27 people in this house; the infinite series of natural numbers is nothing but the infinite
possibility of finite series of numbers[i]t is senseless to speak of the whole infinite number
series, as if it, too, were an extension (PR 144). The infinite is understood rightly when it is
understood, not as a quantity, but as an infinite possibility (PR 138).
Given Wittgenstein's rejection of infinite mathematical extensions, he adopts finitistic,
constructive views on mathematical quantification, mathematical decidability, the nature of real
numbers, and Cantor's diagonal proof of the existence of infinite sets of greater cardinalities.
Since a mathematical set is a finite extension, we cannot meaningfully quantify over an infinite
mathematical domain, simply because there is no such thing as an infinite mathematical domain
(i.e., totality, set), and, derivatively, no such things as infinite conjunctions or disjunctions
[(Moore 1955, 23); cf. (AWL 6) and (PG 281)].
[I]t still looks now as if the quantifiers make no sense for numbers. I mean: you can't say (n)
n, precisely because all natural numbers isn't a bounded concept. But then neither should one
say a general proposition follows from a proposition about the nature of number.
But in that case it seems to me that we can't use generalityall, etc.in mathematics at all.
There's no such thing as all numbers, simply because there are infinitely many. (PR 126; PR
129)
Extensionalists who assert that (0).(1).(2) and so on is an infinite logical product (PG 452)
assume or assert that finite and infinite conjunctions are close cousinsthat the fact that we
cannot write down or enumerate all of the conjuncts contained in an infinite conjunction is only
a human weakness, for God could surely do so and God could surely survey such a
conjunction in a single glance and determine its truth-value. According to Wittgenstein, however,
this is not a matter of human limitation. Because we mistakenly think that an infinite
conjunction is similar to an enormous conjunction, we erroneously reason that just as we
cannot determine the truth-value of an enormous conjunction because we don't have enough
time, we similarly cannot, due to human limitations, determine the truth-value of an infinite
conjunction (or disjunction). But the difference here is not one of degree but of kind: in the
sense in which it is impossible to check an infinite number of propositions it is also impossible to
try to do so (PG 452). This applies, according to Wittgenstein, to human beings, but more
importantly, it applies also to God (i.e., an omniscient being), for even God cannot write down or

survey infinitely many propositions because for him too the series is never-ending or limitless
and hence the task is not a genuine task because it cannot, in principle, be done (i.e., infinitely
many is not a number word). As Wittgenstein says at (PR 128; cf. PG 479): Can God know all
the places of the expansion of ? would have been a good question for the schoolmen to ask,
for the question is strictly senseless. As we shall shortly see, on Wittgenstein's account, [a]
statement about all numbers is not represented by means of a proposition, but by means of
induction (WVC 82).
Similarly, there is no such thing as a mathematical proposition about some numberno such
thing as a mathematical proposition that existentially quantifies over an infinite domain (PR
173).
What is the meaning of such a mathematical proposition as (n) 4 + n = 7? It might be a
disjunction (4 + 0 = 7) (4 + 1 = 7) etc. ad inf. But what does that mean? I can
understand a proposition with a beginning and an end. But can one also understand a proposition
with no end? (PR 127)
We are particularly seduced by the feeling or belief that an infinite mathematical disjunction
makes good sense in the case where we can provide a recursive rule for generating each next
member of an infinite sequence. For example, when we say There exists an odd perfect
number we are asserting that, in the infinite sequence of odd numbers, there is (at least) one odd
number that is perfectwe are asserting (1) (3) (5) and so on and we know what
would make it true and what would make it false (PG 451). The mistake here made, according to
Wittgenstein (PG 451), is that we are implicitly comparing the proposition (n) with the
proposition There are two foreign words on this page, which doesn't provide the grammar
of the former proposition, but only indicates an analogy in their respective rules.
On Wittgenstein's intermediate finitism, an expression quantifying over an infinite domain is
never a meaningful proposition, not even when we have proved, for instance, that a particular
number n has a particular property.
The important point is that, even in the case where I am given that 32 + 42 = 52, I ought not to say
(x, y, z, n) (xn + yn = zn), since taken extensionally that's meaningless, and taken intensionally
this doesn't provide a proof of it. No, in this case I ought to express only the first equation. (PR
150)
Thus, Wittgenstein adopts the radical position that all expressions that quantify over an infinite
domain, whether conjectures (e.g., Goldbach's Conjecture, the Twin Prime Conjecture) or
proved general theorems (e.g., Euclid's Prime Number Theorem, the Fundamental Theorem
of Algebra), are meaningless (i.e., senseless; sinnlos) expressions as opposed to genuine
mathematical proposition[s] (PR 168). These expressions are not (meaningful) mathematical
propositions, according to Wittgenstein, because the Law of the Excluded Middle does not apply,
which means that we aren't dealing with propositions of mathematics (PR 151). The crucial
question why and in exactly what sense the Law of the Excluded Middle does not apply to such
expressions will be answered in the next section.

2.3 Wittgenstein's Intermediate Finitism and Algorithmic Decidability


The middle Wittgenstein has other grounds for rejecting unrestricted quantification in
mathematics, for on his idiosyncratic account, we must distinguish between four categories of
concatenations of mathematical symbols.
1. Proved mathematical propositions in a particular mathematical calculus (no need for
mathematical truth).
2. Refuted mathematical propositions in (or of) a particular mathematical calculus (no need
for mathematical falsity).
3. Mathematical propositions for which we know we have in hand an applicable and
effective decision procedure (i.e., we know how to decide them).
4. Concatenations of symbols that are not part of any mathematical calculus and which, for
that reason, are not mathematical propositions (i.e., are non-propositions).
In his (van Atten 2004, 18), Mark van Atten says that [i]ntuitionistically, there are four
[possibilities for a proposition with respect to truth]:
1. p has been experienced as true
2. p has been experienced as false
3. Neither 1 nor 2 has occurred yet, but we know a procedure to decide p (i.e., a procedure
that will prove p or prove p)
4. Neither 1 nor 2 has occurred yet, and we do not know a procedure to decide p.
What is immediately striking about Wittgenstein's ##13 and Brouwer's ##13 [(Brouwer 1955,
114), (Brouwer 1981, 92)] is the enormous similarity. And yet, for all of the agreement, the
disagreement in #4 is absolutely crucial.
As radical as the respective #3s are, Brouwer and Wittgenstein agree that an undecided is a
mathematical proposition (for Wittgenstein, of a particular mathematical calculus) if we know of
an applicable decision procedure. They also agree that until is decided, it is neither true nor
false (though, for Wittgenstein, true means no more than proved in calculus ). What they
disagree about is the status of an ordinary mathematical conjecture, such as Goldbach's
Conjecture. Brouwer admits it as a mathematical proposition, while Wittgenstein rejects it
because we do not know how to algorithmically decide it. Like Brouwer (1948 [1983, 90]),
Wittgenstein holds that there are no unknown truth[s] in mathematics, but unlike Brouwer he
denies the existence of undecidable propositions on the grounds that such a proposition
would have no sense, and the consequence of this is precisely that the propositions of logic
lose their validity for it (PR 173). In particular, if there are undecidable mathematical
propositions (as Brouwer maintains), then at least some mathematical propositions are not

propositions of any existent mathematical calculus. For Wittgenstein, however, it is a defining


feature of a mathematical proposition that it is either decided or decidable by a known decision
procedure in a mathematical calculus. As Wittgenstein says at (PR 151), where the law of the
excluded middle doesn't apply, no other law of logic applies either, because in that case we aren't
dealing with propositions of mathematics. (Against Weyl and Brouwer). The point here is not
that we need truth and falsity in mathematicswe don'tbut rather that every mathematical
proposition (including ones for which an applicable decision procedure is known) is known to be
part of a mathematical calculus.
To maintain this position, Wittgenstein distinguishes between (meaningful, genuine)
mathematical propositions, which have mathematical sense, and meaningless, senseless
(sinnlos) expressions by stipulating that an expression is a meaningful (genuine) proposition of
a mathematical calculus iff we know of a proof, a refutation, or an applicable decision procedure
[(PR 151), (PG 452), (PG 366), (AWL 199200)]. Only where there's a method of solution [a
logical method for finding a solution] is there a [mathematical] problem, he tells us (PR
149, 152; PG 393). We may only put a question in mathematics (or make a conjecture), he
adds (PR 151), where the answer runs: I must work it out.
At (PG 468), Wittgenstein emphasizes the importance of algorithmic decidability clearly and
emphatically: In mathematics everything is algorithm and nothing is meaning [Bedeutung];
even when it doesn't look like that because we seem to be using words to talk about
mathematical things. Even these words are used to construct an algorithm. When, therefore,
Wittgenstein says (PG 368) that if [the Law of the Excluded Middle] is supposed not to hold,
we have altered the concept of proposition, he means that an expression is only a meaningful
mathematical proposition if we know of an applicable decision procedure for deciding it (PG
400). If a genuine mathematical proposition is undecided, the Law of the Excluded Middle holds
in the sense that we know that we will prove or refute the proposition by applying an applicable
decision procedure (PG 379, 387).
For Wittgenstein, there simply is no distinction between syntax and semantics in mathematics:
everything is syntax. If we wish to demarcate between mathematical propositions versus
mathematical pseudo-propositions, as we do, then the only way to ensure that there is no such
thing as a meaningful, but undecidable (e.g., independent), proposition of a given calculus is to
stipulate that an expression is only a meaningful proposition in a given calculus (PR 153) if
either it has been decided or we know of an applicable decision procedure. In this manner,
Wittgenstein defines both a mathematical calculus and a mathematical proposition in epistemic
terms. A calculus is defined in terms of stipulations [(PR 202), (PG 369)], known rules of
operation, and known decision procedures, and an expression is only a mathematical proposition
in a given calculus (PR 155), and only if that calculus contains (PG 379) a known (and
applicable) decision procedure, for you cannot have a logical plan of search for a sense you
don't know (PR 148).
Thus, the middle Wittgenstein rejects undecidable mathematical propositions on two grounds.
First, number-theoretic expressions that quantify over an infinite domain are not algorithmically
decidable, and hence are not meaningful mathematical propositions.

If someone says (as Brouwer does) that for (x) f1x = f2x, there is, as well as yes and no, also the
case of undecidability, this implies that (x) is meant extensionally and we may talk of the
case in which all x happen to have a property. In truth, however, it's impossible to talk of such a
case at all and the (x) in arithmetic cannot be taken extensionally. (PR 174)
Undecidability, says Wittgenstein (PR 174) presupposes that the bridge cannot be made
with symbols, when, in fact, [a] connection between symbols which exists but cannot be
represented by symbolic transformations is a thought that cannot be thought, for [i]f the
connection is there, it must be possible to see it. Alluding to algorithmic decidability,
Wittgenstein stresses (PR 174) that [w]e can assert anything which can be checked in
practice, because it's a question of the possibility of checking [italics added].
Wittgenstein's second reason for rejecting an undecidable mathematical proposition is that it is a
contradiction-in-terms. There cannot be undecidable propositions, Wittgenstein argues (PR
173), because an expression that is not decidable in some actual calculus is simply not a
mathematical proposition, since every proposition in mathematics must belong to a calculus of
mathematics (PG 376).
This radical position on decidability results in various radical and counter-intuitive statements
about unrestricted mathematical quantification, mathematical induction, and, especially, the
sense of a newly proved mathematical proposition. In particular, Wittgenstein asserts that
uncontroversial mathematical conjectures, such as Goldbach's Conjecture (hereafter GC) and
the erstwhile conjecture Fermat's Last Theorem (hereafter FLT), have no sense (or, perhaps,
no determinate sense) and that the unsystematic proof of such a conjecture gives it a sense that it
didn't previously have (PG 374) because it's unintelligible that I should admit, when I've got the
proof, that it's a proof of precisely this proposition, or of the induction meant by this proposition
(PR 155).
Thus Fermat's [Last Theorem] makes no sense until I can search for a solution to the equation in
cardinal numbers. And search must always mean: search systematically. Meandering about in
infinite space on the look-out for a gold ring is no kind of search. (PR 150)
I say: the so-called Fermat's Last Theorem isn't a proposition. (Not even in the sense of a
proposition of arithmetic.) Rather, it corresponds to an induction. (PR 189)
To see how Fermat's Last Theorem isn't a proposition and how it might correspond to an
induction, we need to examine Wittgenstein's account of mathematical induction.

2.4 Wittgenstein's Intermediate Account of Mathematical Induction and


Algorithmic Decidability
Given that one cannot quantify over an infinite mathematical domain, the question arises: What,
if anything, does any number-theoretic proof by mathematical induction actually prove?
On the standard view, a proof by mathematical induction has the following paradigmatic form.

Inductive Base:
Inductive Step:
Conclusion:

(1)
n((n) (n + 1))
n(n)

If, however, n(n) is not a meaningful (genuine) mathematical proposition, what are we to
make of this proof?
Wittgenstein's initial answer to this question is decidedly enigmatic. An induction is the
expression for arithmetical generality, but induction isn't itself a proposition (PR 129).
We are not saying that when f(1) holds and when f(c + 1) follows from f(c), the proposition f(x) is
therefore true of all cardinal numbers: but: the proposition f(x) holds for all cardinal numbers
means it holds for x = 1, and f(c + 1) follows from f(c). (PG 406)
In a proof by mathematical induction, we do no actually prove the proposition [e.g., n(n)]
that is customarily construed as the conclusion of the proof (PG 406, 374; PR 164), rather this
pseudo-proposition or statement stands proxy for the infinite possibility (i.e., the
induction) that we come to see by means of the proof (WVC 135). I want to say,
Wittgenstein concludes, that once youve got the induction, it's all over (PG 407). Thus, on
Wittgenstein's account, a particular proof by mathematical induction should be understood in the
following way.
Inductive Base:
Inductive Step:
Proxy Statement:

(1)
(n) (n + 1)
(m)

Here the conclusion of an inductive proof [i.e., what is to be proved (PR 164)] uses m
rather than n to indicate that m stands for any particular number, while n stands for any
arbitrary number. For Wittgenstein, the proxy statement (m) is not a mathematical
proposition that assert[s] its generality (PR 168), it is an eliminable pseudo-proposition
standing proxy for the proved inductive base and inductive step. Though an inductive proof
cannot prove the infinite possibility of application (PR 163), it enables us to perceive that a
direct proof of any particular proposition can be constructed (PR 165). For example, once we
have proved (1) and (n) (n + 1), we need not reiterate modus ponens m 1 times to
prove the particular proposition (m) (PR 164). The direct proof of, say, (714) (i.e.,
without 713 iterations of modus ponens) cannot have a still better proof, say, by my carrying out
the derivation as far as this proposition itself (PR 165).
A second, very important impetus for Wittgenstein's radically constructivist position on
mathematical induction is his rejection of an undecidable mathematical proposition.
In discussions of the provability of mathematical propositions it is sometimes said that there are
substantial propositions of mathematics whose truth or falsehood must remain undecided. What
the people who say that don't realize is that such propositions, if we can use them and want to
call them propositions, are not at all the same as what are called propositions in other cases;
because a proof alters the grammar of a proposition. (PG 367)

In this passage, Wittgenstein is alluding to Brouwer, who, as early as 1907 and 1908, states, first,
that the question of the validity of the principium tertii exclusi is equivalent to the question
whether unsolvable mathematical problems exist, second, that [t]here is not a shred of a proof
for the conviction that there exist no unsolvable mathematical problems, and, third, that there
are meaningful propositions/questions, such as Do there occur in the decimal expansion of
infinitely many pairs of consecutive equal digits?, to which the Law of the Excluded Middle
does not apply because it must be considered as uncertain whether problems like [this] are
solvable (Brouwer, 1908 [1975, 109110]). A fortiori it is not certain that any mathematical
problem can either be solved or proved to be unsolvable, Brouwer says (1907 [1975, 79]),
though HILBERT, in Mathematische Probleme, believes that every mathematician is deeply
convinced of it.
Wittgenstein takes the same data and, in a way, draws the opposite conclusion. If, as Brouwer
says, we are uncertain whether all or some mathematical problems are solvable, then we know
that we do not have in hand an applicable decision procedure, which means that the alleged
mathematical propositions are not decidable, here and now. What mathematical questions
share with genuine questions, Wittgenstein says (PR 151), is simply that they can be
answered. This means that if we do not know how to decide an expression, then we do not
know how to make it either proved (true) or refuted (false), which means that the Law of the
Excluded Middle doesn't apply and, therefore, that our expression is not a mathematical
proposition.
Together, Wittgenstein's finitism and his criterion of algorithmic decidability shed considerable
light on his highly controversial remarks about putatively meaningful conjectures such as FLT
and GC. GC is not a mathematical proposition because we do not know how to decide it, and if
someone like G. H. Hardy says that he believes GC is true (PG 381; LFM 123; PI 578), we
must answer that s/he only has a hunch about the possibilities of extension of the present
system (LFM 139)that one can only believe such an expression is correct if one knows how
to prove it. The only sense in which GC (or FLT) can be proved is that it can correspond to a
proof by induction, which means that the unproved inductive step (e.g., G(n) G(n + 1)) and
the expression nG(n) are not mathematical propositions because we have no algorithmic
means of looking for an induction (PG 367). A general proposition is senseless prior to an
inductive proof because the question would only have made sense if a general method of
decision had been known before the particular proof was discovered (PG 402). Unproved
inductions or inductive steps are not meaningful propositions because the Law of the Excluded
Middle does not hold in the sense that we do not know of a decision procedure by means of
which we can prove or refute the expression (PG 400; WVC 82).
This position, however, seems to rob us of any reason to search for a decision of a meaningless
expression such as GC. The intermediate Wittgenstein says only that [a] mathematician is
guided by certain analogies with the previous system and that there is nothing wrong or
illegitimate if anyone concerns himself with Fermat's Last Theorem (WVC 144).
If e.g. I have a method for looking at integers that satisfy the equation x2 + y2 = z2, then the
formula xn + yn = zn may stimulate me. I may let a formula stimulate me. Thus I shall say, Here

there is a stimulusbut not a question. Mathematical problems are always such stimuli. (WVC
144, Jan. 1, 1931)
More specifically, a mathematician may let a senseless conjecture such as FLT stimulate her/him
if s/he wishes to know whether a calculus can be extended without altering its axioms or rules
(LFM 139).
What is here going [o]n [in an attempt to decide GC] is an unsystematic attempt at constructing a
calculus. If the attempt is successful, I shall again have a calculus in front of me, only a different
one from the calculus I have been using so far. [italics added] (WVC 17475; Sept. 21, 1931)
If, e.g., we succeed in proving GC by mathematical induction (i.e., we prove G(1) and G(n)
G(n + 1)), we will then have a proof of the inductive step, but since the inductive step was
not algorithmically decidable beforehand [(PR 148, 155, 157), (PG 380)], in constructing the
proof we have constructed a new calculus, a new calculating machine (WVC 106) in which we
now know how to use this new machine-part (RFM VI, 13) (i.e., the unsystematically proved
inductive step). Before the proof, the inductive step is not a mathematical proposition with sense
(in a particular calculus), whereas after the proof the inductive step is a mathematical
proposition, with a new, determinate sense, in a newly created calculus. This demarcation of
expressions without mathematical sense and proved or refuted propositions, each with a
determinate sense in a particular calculus, is a view that Wittgenstein articulates in myriad
different ways from 1929 through 1944.
Whether or not it is ultimately defensibleand this is an absolutely crucial question for
Wittgenstein's Philosophy of Mathematicsthis strongly counter-intuitive aspect of
Wittgenstein's account of algorithmic decidability, proof, and the sense of a mathematical
proposition is a piece with his rejection of predeterminacy in mathematics. Even in the case
where we algorithmically decide a mathematical proposition, the connections thereby made do
not pre-exist the algorithmic decision, which means that even when we have a mathematical
question that we decide by decision procedure, the expression only has a determinate sense qua
proposition when it is decided. On Wittgenstein's account, both middle and later, [a] new proof
gives the proposition a place in a new system (RFM VI, 13), it locates it in the whole system
of calculations, though it does not mention, certainly does not describe, the whole system of
calculation that stands behind the proposition and gives it sense (RFM VI, 11).
Wittgenstein's unorthodox position here is a type of structuralism that partially results from his
rejection of mathematical semantics. We erroneously think, e.g., that GC has a fully determinate
sense because, given the misleading way in which the mode of expression of word-language
represents the sense of mathematical propositions (PG 375), we call to mind false pictures and
mistaken, referential conceptions of mathematical propositions whereby GC is about a
mathematical reality and so has just a determinate sense as There exist intelligent beings
elsewhere in the universe (i.e., a proposition that is determinately true or false, whether or not
we ever know its truth-value). Wittgenstein breaks with this tradition, in all of its forms, stressing
that, in mathematics, unlike the realm of contingent (or empirical) propositions, if I am to know
what a proposition like Fermat's last theorem says, I must know its criterion of truth. Unlike the
criterion of truth for an empirical proposition, which can be known before the proposition is

decided, we cannot know the criterion of truth for an undecided mathematical proposition,
though we are acquainted with criteria for the truth of similar propositions (RFM VI, 13).

2.5 Wittgenstein's Intermediate Account of Irrational Numbers


The intermediate Wittgenstein spends a great deal of time wrestling with real and irrational
numbers. There are two distinct reasons for this.
First, the real reason many of us are unwilling to abandon the notion of the actual infinite in
mathematics is the prevalent conception of an irrational number as a necessarily infinite
extension. The confusion in the concept of the actual infinite arises [italics added], says
Wittgenstein (PG 471), from the unclear concept of irrational number, that is, from the fact that
logically very different things are called irrational numbers without any clear limit being given
to the concept.
Second, and more fundamentally, the intermediate Wittgenstein wrestles with irrationals in such
detail because he opposes foundationalism and especially its concept of a gapless mathematical
continuum, its concept of a comprehensive theory of the real numbers (Han 2010), and set
theoretical conceptions and proofs as a foundation for arithmetic, real number theory, and
mathematics as a whole. Indeed, Wittgenstein's discussion of irrationals is one with his critique
of set theory, for, as he says, [m]athematics is ridden through and through with the pernicious
idioms of set theory, such as the way people speak of a line as composed of points, when, in
fact, [a] line is a law and isn't composed of anything at all [(PR 173), (PR 181, 183, &
191), (PG 373, 460, 461, & 473)].
2.5.1 Wittgenstein's Anti-Foundationalism and Genuine Irrational Numbers
Since, on Wittgenstein's terms, mathematics consists exclusively of extensions and intensions
(i.e., rules or laws), an irrational is only an extension insofar as it is a sign (i.e., a numeral,
such as 2 or ). Given that there is no such thing as an infinite mathematical extension, it
follows that an irrational number is not a unique infinite expansion, but rather a unique recursive
rule or law (PR 181) that yields rational numbers (PR 186; PR 180).
The rule for working out places of 2 is itself the numeral for the irrational number; and the
reason I here speak of a number is that I can calculate with these signs (certain rules for the
construction of rational numbers) just as I can with rational numbers themselves. (PG 484)
Due, however, to his anti-foundationalism, Wittgenstein takes the radical position that not all
recursive real numbers (i.e., computable numbers) are genuine real numbersa position that
distinguishes his view from even Brouwer's.
The problem, as Wittgenstein sees it, is that mathematicians, especially foundationalists (e.g., set
theorists), have sought to accommodate physical continuity by a theory that describes the
mathematical continuum (PR 171). When, for example, we think of continuous motion and the
(mere) density of the rationals, we reason that if an object moves continuously from A to B, and
it travels only the distances marked by rational points, then it must skip some distances

(intervals, or points) not marked by rational numbers. But if an object in continuous motion
travels distances that cannot be commensurately measured by rationals alone, there must be
gaps between the rationals (PG 460), and so we must fill them, first, with recursive irrationals,
and then, because the set of all recursive irrationals still leaves gaps, with lawless irrationals.
[T]he enigma of the continuum arises because language misleads us into applying to it a picture
that doesn't fit. Set theory preserves the inappropriate picture of something discontinuous, but
makes statements about it that contradict the picture, under the impression that it is breaking with
prejudices; whereas what should really have been done is to point out that the picture just doesn't
fit (PG 471)
We add nothing that is needed to the differential and integral calculi by completing a theory of
real numbers with pseudo-irrationals and lawless irrationals, first because there are no gaps on
the number line [(PR 181, 183, & 191), (PG 373, 460, 461, & 473), (WVC 35)] and, second,
because these alleged irrational numbers are not needed for a theory of the continuum simply
because there is no mathematical continuum. As the later Wittgenstein says (RFM V, 32), [t]he
picture of the number line is an absolutely natural one up to a certain point; that is to say so long
as it is not used for a general theory of real numbers. We have gone awry by misconstruing the
nature of the geometrical line as a continuous collection of points, each with an associated real
number, which has taken us well beyond the natural picture of the number line in search of a
general theory of real numbers (Han 2010).
Thus, the principal reason Wittgenstein rejects certain constructive (computable) numbers is that
they are unnecessary creations which engender conceptual confusions in mathematics (especially
set theory). One of Wittgenstein's main aims in his lengthy discussions of rational numbers and
pseudo-irrationals is to show that pseudo-irrationals, which are allegedly needed for the
mathematical continuum, are not needed at all.
To this end, Wittgenstein demands (a) that a real number must be compar[able] with any
rational number taken at random (i.e., it can be established whether it is greater than, less than,
or equal to a rational number (PR 191)) and (b) that [a] number must measure in and of itself
and if a number leaves it to the rationals, we have no need of it (PR 191) [(Frascolla 1980,
242243); (Shanker 1987, 186192); (Da Silva 1993, 9394); (Marion 1995a, 162, 164);
(Rodych 1999b, 281291); (Lampert 2009)].
To demonstrate that some recursive (computable) reals are not genuine real numbers because
they fail to satisfy (a) and (b), Wittgenstein defines the putative recursive real number
53
2
as the rule Construct the decimal expansion for 2, replacing every occurrence of a 5 with a
3 (PR 182); he similarly defines as
73

(PR 186) and, in a later work, redefines as


777 000

(PG 475).
Although a pseudo-irrational such as (on either definition) is as unambiguous as or 2
(PG 476), it is homeless according to Wittgenstein because, instead of using the idioms of
arithmetic (PR 186), it is dependent upon the particular incidental notation of a particular
system (i.e., in some particular base) [(PR 188), (PR 182), and (PG 475)]. If we speak of
various base-notational systems, we might say that belongs to all systems, while belongs
only to one, which shows that is not a genuine irrational because there can't be irrational
numbers of different types (PR 180). Furthermore, pseudo-irrationals do not measure because
they are homeless, artificial constructions parasitic upon numbers which have a natural place in a
calculus that can be used to measure. We simply do not need these aberrations, because they are
not sufficiently comparable to rationals and genuine irrationals. They are not irrational numbers
according to Wittgenstein's criteria, which define, Wittgenstein interestingly asserts, precisely
what has been meant or looked for under the name irrational number (PR 191).
For exactly the same reason, if we define a lawless irrational as either (a) a non-rule-governed,
non-periodic, infinite expansion in some base, or (b) a free-choice sequence, Wittgenstein
rejects lawless irrationals because, insofar as they are not rule-governed, they are not
comparable to rationals (or irrationals) and they are not needed. [W]e cannot say that the
decimal fractions developed in accordance with a law still need supplementing by an infinite set
of irregular infinite decimal fractions that would be brushed under the carpet if we were to
restrict ourselves to those generated by a law, Wittgenstein argues, for [w]here is there such an
infinite decimal that is generated by no law [a]nd how would we notice that it was missing?
(PR 181; cf. PG 473, 48384). Similarly, a free-choice sequence, like a recipe for endless
bisection or endless dicing, is not an infinitely complicated mathematical law (or rule), but
rather no law at all, for after each individual throw of a coin, the point remains infinitely
indeterminate (PR 186). For closely related reasons, Wittgenstein ridicules the Multiplicative
Axiom (Axiom of Choice) both in the middle period (PR 146) and in the latter period (RFM V,
25; VII, 33).
2.5.2 Wittgenstein's Real Number Essentialism and the Dangers of Set Theory
Superficially, at least, it seems as if Wittgenstein is offering an essentialist argument for the
conclusion that real number arithmetic should not be extended in such-and-such a way. Such an
essentialist account of real and irrational numbers seems to conflict with the actual freedom
mathematicians have to extend and invent, with Wittgenstein's intermediate claim (PG 334) that
[f]or [him] one calculus is as good as another, and with Wittgenstein's acceptance of complex
and imaginary numbers. Wittgenstein's foundationalist critic (e.g., set theorist) will undoubtedly
say that we have extended the term irrational number to lawless and pseudo-irrationals because
they are needed for the mathematical continuum and because such conceivable numbers are
much more like rule-governed irrationals than rationals.

Though Wittgenstein stresses differences where others see similarities (LFM 15), in his
intermediate attacks on pseudo-irrationals and foundationalism, he is not just emphasizing
differences, he is attacking set theory's pernicious idioms (PR 173) and its crudest
imaginable misinterpretation of its own calculus (PG 46970) in an attempt to dissolve
misunderstandings without which [set theory] would never have been invented, since it is of
no other use (LFM 1617). Complex and imaginary numbers have grown organically within
mathematics, and they have proved their mettle in scientific applications, but pseudo-irrationals
are inorganic creations invented solely for the sake of mistaken foundationalist aims.
Wittgenstein's main point is not that we cannot create further recursive real numbersindeed,
we can create as many as we wanthis point is that we can only really speak of different
systems (sets) of real numbers (RFM II, 33) that are enumerable by a rule, and any attempt to
speak of the set of all real numbers or any piecemeal attempt to add or consider new recursive
reals (e.g., diagonal numbers) is a useless and/or futile endeavour based on foundational
misconceptions. Indeed, in 1930 MS and TS passages on irrationals and Cantor's diagonal, which
were not included in PR or PG, Wittgenstein says: The concept irrational number is a
dangerous pseudo-concept (MS 108, 176; 1930; TS 210, 29; 1930). As we shall see in the next
section, on Wittgenstein's account, if we do not understand irrationals rightly, we cannot but
engender the mistakes that constitute set theory.

2.6 Wittgenstein's Intermediate Critique of Set Theory


Wittgenstein's critique of set theory begins somewhat benignly in the Tractatus, where he
denounces Logicism and says (6.031) that [t]he theory of classes is completely superfluous in
mathematics because, at least in part, the generality required in mathematics is not accidental
generality. In his middle period, Wittgenstein begins a full-out assault on set theory that never
abates. Set theory, he says, is utter nonsense (PR 145, 174; WVC 102; PG 464, 470),
wrong (PR 174), and laughable (PG 464); its pernicious idioms (PR 173) mislead us and
the crudest possible misinterpretation is the very impetus of its invention (Hintikka 1993, 24,
27).
Wittgenstein's intermediate critique of transfinite set theory (hereafter set theory) has two main
components: (1) his discussion of the intension-extension distinction, and (2) his criticism of
non-denumerability as cardinality. Late in the middle period, Wittgenstein seems to become
more aware of the unbearable conflict between his strong formalism (PG 334) and his
denigration of set theory as a purely formal, non-mathematical calculus (Rodych 1997, 217-219),
which, as we shall see in Section 3.5, leads to the use of an extra-mathematical application
criterion to demarcate transfinite set theory (and other purely formal sign-games) from
mathematical calculi.
2.6.1 Intensions, Extensions, and the Fictitious Symbolism of Set Theory
The search for a comprehensive theory of the real numbers and mathematical continuity has led
to a fictitious symbolism (PR 174).
Set theory attempts to grasp the infinite at a more general level than the investigation of the laws
of the real numbers. It says that you can't grasp the actual infinite by means of mathematical

symbolism at all and therefore it can only be described and not represented. One might say of
this theory that it buys a pig in a poke. Let the infinite accommodate itself in this box as best it
can. (PG 468; cf. PR 170)
As Wittgenstein puts it at (PG 461), the mistake in the set-theoretical approach consists time
and again in treating laws and enumerations (lists) as essentially the same kind of thing and
arranging them in parallel series so that one fills in gaps left by the other. This is a mistake
because it is nonsense to say we cannot enumerate all the numbers of a set, but we can give a
description, for [t]he one is not a substitute for the other (WVC 102; June 19, 1930); there
isn't a dualism [of] the law and the infinite series obeying it (PR 180).
Set theory is wrong and nonsensical (PR 174), says Wittgenstein, because it presupposes a
fictitious symbolism of infinite signs (PG 469) instead of an actual symbolism with finite signs.
The grand intimation of set theory, which begins with Dirichlet's concept of a function (WVC
10203), is that we can in principle represent an infinite set by an enumeration, but because of
human or physical limitations, we will instead describe it intensionally. But, says Wittgenstein,
[t]here can't be possibility and actuality in mathematics, for mathematics is an actual calculus,
which is concerned only with the signs with which it actually operates (PG 469). As
Wittgenstein puts it at (PR 159), the fact that we can't describe mathematics, we can only do
it in and of itself abolishes every set theory.
Perhaps the best example of this phenomenon is Dedekind, who in giving his definition of an
infinite class as a class which is similar to a proper subclass of itself (PG 464), tried to
describe an infinite class (PG 463). If, however, we try to apply this definition to a particular
class in order to ascertain whether it is finite or infinite, the attempt is laughable if we apply it
to a finite class, such as a certain row of trees, and it is nonsense if we apply it to an infinite
class, for we cannot even attempt to co-ordinate it (PG 464), because the relation m = 2n
[does not] correlate the class of all numbers with one of its subclasses (PR 141), it is an
infinite process which correlates any arbitrary number with another. So, although we can
use m = 2n on the rule for generating the naturals (i.e., our domain) and thereby construct the
pairs (2,1), (4,2), (6,3), (8,4), etc., in doing so we do not correlate two infinite sets or extensions
(WVC 103). If we try to apply Dedekind's definition as a criterion for determining whether a
given set is infinite by establishing a 11 correspondence between two inductive rules for
generating infinite extensions, one of which is an extensional subset of the other, we can't
possibly learn anything we didn't already know when we applied the criterion to two inductive
rules. If Dedekind or anyone else insists on calling an inductive rule an infinite set, he and we
must still mark the categorical difference between such a set and a finite set with a determinate,
finite cardinality.
Indeed, on Wittgenstein's account, the failure to properly distinguish mathematical extensions
and intensions is the root cause of the mistaken interpretation of Cantor's diagonal proof as a
proof of the existence of infinite sets of lesser and greater cardinality.
2.6.2 Against Non-Denumerability

Wittgenstein's criticism of non-denumerability is primarily implicit during the middle period.


Only after 1937 does he provide concrete arguments purporting to show, e.g., that Cantor's
diagonal cannot prove that some infinite sets have greater multiplicity than others.
Nonetheless, the intermediate Wittgenstein clearly rejects the notion that a non-denumerably
infinite set is greater in cardinality than a denumerably infinite set.
When people say The set of all transcendental numbers is greater than that of algebraic
numbers, that's nonsense. The set is of a different kind. It isn't no longer denumerable, it's
simply not denumerable! (PR 174)
As with his intermediate views on genuine irrationals and the Multiplicative Axiom, Wittgenstein
here looks at the diagonal proof of the non-denumerability of the set of transcendental numbers
as one that shows only that transcendental numbers cannot be recursively enumerated. It is
nonsense, he says, to go from the warranted conclusion that these numbers are not, in principle,
enumerable to the conclusion that the set of transcendental numbers is greater in cardinality than
the set of algebraic numbers, which is recursively enumerable. What we have here are two very
different conceptions of a number-type. In the case of algebraic numbers, we have a decision
procedure for determining of any given number whether or not it is algebraic, and we have a
method of enumerating the algebraic numbers such that we can see that each algebraic number
will be enumerated. In the case of transcendental numbers, on the other hand, we have proofs
that some numbers are transcendental (i.e., non-algebraic), and we have a proof that we cannot
recursively enumerate each and every thing we would call a transcendental number.
At (PG 461), Wittgenstein similarly speaks of set theory's mathematical pseudo-concepts
leading to a fundamental difficulty, which begins when we unconsciously presuppose that there
is sense to the idea of ordering the rationals by sizethat the attempt is thinkableand
culminates in similarly thinking that it is possible to enumerate the real numbers, which we then
discover is impossible.
Though the intermediate Wittgenstein certainly seems highly critical of the alleged proof that
some infinite sets (e.g., the reals) are greater in cardinality than other infinite sets, and though he
discusses the diagonal procedure in February 1929 and in June 1930 (MS 106, 266; MS 108,
180), along with a diagonal diagram, these and other early-middle ruminations did not make it
into the typescripts for either PR or PG. As we shall see in Section 3.4, the later Wittgenstein
analyzes Cantor's diagonal and claims of non-denumerability in some detail.

3. The Later Wittgenstein on Mathematics: Some


Preliminaries
The first and most important thing to note about Wittgenstein's later Philosophy of Mathematics
is that RFM, first published in 1956, consists of selections taken from a number of MSS (1937
1944), most of one large typescript (1938), and three short typescripts (1938), each of which
constitutes an Appendix to (RFM I). For this reason and because some MSS containing much
material on mathematics (e.g., (MS 123)) were not used at all for RFM, philosophers have not

been able to read Wittgenstein's later remarks on mathematics as they were written in the MSS
used for RFM and they have not had access (until the 20002001 release of the Nachlass on CDROM) to much of Wittgenstein's later work on mathematics. It must be emphasized, therefore,
that this Encyclopedia article is being written during a transitional period. Until philosophers
have used the Nachlass to build a comprehensive picture of Wittgenstein's complete and
evolving Philosophy of Mathematics, we will not be able to say definitively which views the
later Wittgenstein retained, which he changed, and which he dropped. In the interim, this article
will outline Wittgenstein's later Philosophy of Mathematics, drawing primarily on RFM, to a
much lesser extent LFM (1939 Cambridge lectures), and, where possible, previously unpublished
material in Wittgenstein's Nachlass.
It should also be noted at the outset that commentators disagree about the continuity of
Wittgenstein's middle and later Philosophies of Mathematics. Some argue that the later views are
significantly different from the intermediate views [(Frascolla 1994), (Gerrard 1991, 127, 131
32), (Floyd 2005, 105106)], while others argue that, for the most part, Wittgenstein's
Philosophy of Mathematics evolves from the middle to the later period without significant
changes or renunciations [(Wrigley 1993), (Marion 1998), (Rodych 1997, 2000a, 2000b)]. The
remainder of this article adopts the second interpretation, explicating Wittgenstein's later
Philosophy of Mathematics as largely continuous with his intermediate views, except for the
important introduction of an extra-mathematical application criterion.

3.1 Mathematics as a Human Invention


Perhaps the most important constant in Wittgenstein's Philosophy of Mathematics, middle and
late, is that he consistently maintains that mathematics is our, human invention, and that, indeed,
everything in mathematics is invented. Just as the middle Wittgenstein says that [w]e make
mathematics, the later Wittgenstein says that we invent mathematics (RFM I, 168; II, 38; V,
5, 9 and 11; PG 46970) and that the mathematician is not a discoverer: he is an inventor
(RFM, Appendix II, 2; (LFM 22, 82). Nothing exists mathematically unless and until we have
invented it.
In arguing against mathematical discovery, Wittgenstein is not just rejecting Platonism, he is also
rejecting a rather standard philosophical view according to which human beings invent
mathematical calculi, but once a calculus has been invented, we thereafter discover finitely many
of its infinitely many provable and true theorems. As Wittgenstein himself asks (RFM IV, 48),
might it not be said that the rules lead this way, even if no one went it? If someone produced
a proof [of Goldbach's theorem], [c]ouldn't one say, Wittgenstein asks (LFM 144), that the
possibility of this proof was a fact in the realms of mathematical realitythat [i]n order [to]
find it, it must in some sense be there[i]t must be a possible structure?
Unlike many or most philosophers of mathematics, Wittgenstein resists the Yes answer that we
discover truths about a mathematical calculus that come into existence the moment we invent the
calculus [(PR 141), (PG 283, 466), (LFM 139)]. Wittgenstein rejects the modal reification of
possibility as actualitythat provability and constructibility are (actual) factsby arguing that it
is at the very least wrong-headed to say with the Platonist that because a straight line can be
drawn between any two points, the line already exists even if no one has drawn itto say

[w]hat in the ordinary world we call a possibility is in the geometrical world a reality (LFM
144; RFM I, 21). One might as well say, Wittgenstein suggests (PG 374), that chess only had
to be discovered, it was always there!
At (MS 122, 3v; Oct. 18, 1939), Wittgenstein once again emphasizes the difference between
illusory mathematical discovery and genuine mathematical invention.
I want to get away from the formulation: I now know more about the calculus, and replace it
with I now have a different calculus. The sense of this is always to keep before one's eyes the
full scale of the gulf between a mathematical knowing and non-mathematical knowing.[3]
And as with the middle period, the later Wittgenstein similarly says (MS 121, 27r; May 27,
1938) that [i]t helps if one says: the proof of the Fermat proposition is not to be discovered, but
to be invented.
The difference between the anthropological and the mathematical account is that in the first we
are not tempted to speak of mathematical facts, but rather that in this account the facts are never
mathematical ones, never make mathematical propositions true or false. (MS 117, 263; March
15, 1940)
There are no mathematical facts just as there are no (genuine) mathematical propositions.
Repeating his intermediate view, the later Wittgenstein says (MS 121, 71v; 27 Dec., 1938):
Mathematics consists of [calculi | calculations], not of propositions. This radical constructivist
conception of mathematics prompts Wittgenstein to make notorious remarksremarks that
virtually no one else would makesuch as the infamous (RFM V, 9): However queer it
sounds, the further expansion of an irrational number is a further expansion of mathematics.
3.1.1 Wittgenstein's Later Anti-Platonism: The Natural History of Numbers and the
Vacuity of Platonism
As in the middle period, the later Wittgenstein maintains that mathematics is essentially
syntactical and non-referential, which, in and of itself, makes Wittgenstein's philosophy of
mathematics anti-Platonist insofar as Platonism is the view that mathematical terms and
propositions refer to objects and/or facts and that mathematical propositions are true by virtue of
agreeing with mathematical facts.
The later Wittgenstein, however, wishes to warn us that our thinking is saturated with the idea
of [a]rithmetic as the natural history (mineralogy) of numbers (RFM IV, 11). When, for
instance, Wittgenstein discusses the claim that fractions cannot be ordered by magnitude, he says
that this sounds remarkable in a way that a mundane proposition of the differential calculus
does not, for the latter proposition is associated with an application in physics, whereas this
proposition seems to [solely] concern the natural history of mathematical objects
themselves (RFM II, 40). Wittgenstein stresses that he is trying to warn us against this
aspectthe idea that the foregoing proposition about fractions introduces us to the mysteries
of the mathematical world, which exists somewhere as a completed totality, awaiting our
prodding and our discoveries. The fact that we regard mathematical propositions as being about

mathematical objects and mathematical investigation as the exploration of these objects is


already mathematical alchemy, claims Wittgenstein (RFM V, 16), since it is not possible to
appeal to the meaning [Bedeutung] of the signs in mathematics, because it is only
mathematics that gives them their meaning [Bedeutung]. Platonism is dangerously
misleading, according to Wittgenstein, because it suggests a picture of pre-existence,
predetermination and discovery that is completely at odds with what we find if we actually
examine and describe mathematics and mathematical activity. I should like to be able to
describe, says Wittgenstein (RFM IV, 13), how it comes about that mathematics appears to us
now as the natural history of the domain of numbers, now again as a collection of rules.
Wittgenstein, however, does not endeavour to refute Platonism. His aim, instead, is to clarify
what Platonism is and what it says, implicitly and explicitly (including variants of Platonism that
claim, e.g., that if a proposition is provable in an axiom system, then there already exists a path
[i.e., a proof] from the axioms to that proposition [(RFM I, 21); (Marion 1998, 1314, 226),
(Rodych 1997; 2000b, 267280), (Steiner 2000, 334)]). Platonism is either a mere truism
(LFM 239), Wittgenstein says, or it is a picture consisting of an infinity of shadowy worlds
(LFM 145), which, as such, lacks utility (cf. PI 254) because it explains nothing and it
misleads at every turn.

3.2 Wittgenstein's Later Finitistic Constructivism


Though commentators and critics do not agree as to whether the later Wittgenstein is still a
finitist and whether, if he is, his finitism is as radical as his intermediate rejection of unbounded
mathematical quantification (Maddy 1986, 300301, 310), the overwhelming evidence indicates
that the later Wittgenstein still rejects the actual infinite (RFM V, 21; Zettel 274, 1947) and
infinite mathematical extensions.
The first, and perhaps most definitive, indication that the later Wittgenstein maintains his finitism
is his continued and consistent insistence that irrational numbers are rules for constructing finite
expansions, not infinite mathematical extensions. The concepts of infinite decimals in
mathematical propositions are not concepts of series, says Wittgenstein (RFM V, 19), but of
the unlimited technique of expansion of series. We are misled by [t]he extensional definitions
of functions, of real numbers etc. (RFM V, 35), but once we recognize the Dedekind cut as an
extensional image, we see that we are not led to 2 by way of the concept of a cut (RFM V,
34). On the later Wittgenstein's account, there simply is no property, no rule, no systematic
means of defining each and every irrational number intensionally, which means there is no
criterion for the irrational numbers being complete (PR 181).
As in his intermediate position, the later Wittgenstein claims that 0 and infinite series get
their mathematical uses from the use of infinity in ordinary language (RFM II, 60). Although,
in ordinary language, we often use infinite and infinitely many as answers to the question
how many?, and though we associate infinity with the enormously large, the principal use we
make of infinite and infinity is to speak of the unlimited (RFM V, 14) and unlimited
techniques (RFM II, 45; PI 218). This fact is brought out by the fact that the technique of
learning 0 numerals is different from the technique of learning 100,000 numerals (LFM 31).
When we say, e.g., that there are an infinite number of even numbers we mean that we have a

mathematical technique or rule for generating even numbers which is limitless, which is
markedly different from a limited technique or rule for generating a finite number of numbers,
such as 1100,000,000. We learn an endless technique, says Wittgenstein (RFM V, 19), but
what is in question here is not some gigantic extension.
An infinite sequence, for example, is not a gigantic extension because it is not an extension, and
0 is not a cardinal number, for how is this picture connected with the calculus, given that
its connexion is not that of the picture | | | | with 4 (i.e., given that 0 is not connected to a
(finite) extension)? This shows, says Wittgenstein (RFM II, 58), that we ought to avoid the
word infinite in mathematics wherever it seems to give a meaning to the calculus, rather than
acquiring its meaning from the calculus and its use in the calculus. Once we see that the calculus
contains nothing infinite, we should not be disappointed (RFM II, 60), but simply note (RFM
II, 59) that it is not really necessary to conjure up the picture of the infinite (of the
enormously big).
A second strong indication that the later Wittgenstein maintains his finitism is his continued and
consistent treatment of propositions of the type There are three consecutive 7s in the decimal
expansion of (hereafter PIC).[4] In the middle period, PIC (and its putative negation, PIC,
namely, It is not the case that there are three consecutive 7s in the decimal expansion of ) is
not a meaningful mathematical statement at all (WVC 8182: Footnote #1). On Wittgenstein's
intermediate view, PIClike FLT, GC, and the Fundamental Theorem of Algebrais not a
mathematical proposition because we do not have in hand an applicable decision procedure by
which we can decide it in a particular calculus. For this reason, we can only meaningfully state
finitistic propositions regarding the expansion of , such as There exist three consecutive 7s in
the first 10,000 places of the expansion of (WVC 71; 8182, Footnote #1).
The later Wittgenstein maintains this position in various passages in RFM (Bernays 1959 [1986,
176]). For example, to someone who says that since the rule of expansion determine[s] the
series completely, it must implicitly determine all questions about the structure of the series,
Wittgenstein replies: Here you are thinking of finite series (RFM V, 11). If PIC were a
mathematical question (or problem)if it were finitistically restrictedit would be
algorithmically decidable, which it is not [(RFM V, 21), (LFM 3132, 111, 170), (WVC 102
03)]. As Wittgenstein says at (RFM V, 9): The question changes its status, when it becomes
decidable, [f]or a connexion is made then, which formerly was not there. And if, moreover,
one invokes the Law of the Excluded Middle to establish that PIC is a mathematical proposition
i.e., by saying that one of these two pictures must correspond to the fact (RFM V, 10)
one simply begs the question (RFM V, 12), for if we have doubts about the mathematical status
of PIC, we will not be swayed by a person who asserts PIC PIC (RFM VII, 41; V, 13).
Wittgenstein's finitism, constructivism, and conception of mathematical decidability are
interestingly connected at (RFM VII, 41, par. 25).
What harm is done e.g. by saying that God knows all irrational numbers? Or: that they are
already there, even though we only know certain of them? Why are these pictures not harmless?
For one thing, they hide certain problems. (MS 124, p. 139; March 16, 1944)

Suppose that people go on and on calculating the expansion of . So God, who knows
everything, knows whether they will have reached 777 by the end of the world. But can his
omniscience decide whether they would have reached it after the end of the world? It cannot. I
want to say: Even God can determine something mathematical only by mathematics. Even for
him the mere rule of expansion cannot decide anything that it does not decide for us.
We might put it like this: if the rule for the expansion has been given us, a calculation can tell us
that there is a 2 at the fifth place. Could God have known this, without the calculation, purely
from the rule of expansion? I want to say: No. (MS 124, pp. 175176; March 2324, 1944)
What Wittgenstein means here is that God's omniscience might, by calculation, find that 777
occurs at the interval [n,n+2], but, on the other hand, God might go on calculating forever
without 777 ever turning up. Since is not a completed infinite extension that can be
completely surveyed by an omniscient being (i.e., it is not a fact that can be known by an
omniscient mind), even God has only the rule, and so God's omniscience is no advantage in this
case [(LFM 10304); cf. (Weyl, 1921 [1998, 97])]. Like us, with our modest minds, an
omniscient mind (i.e., God) can only calculate the expansion of to some nth decimal place
where our n is minute and God's n is (relatively) enormousand at no nth decimal place could
any mind rightly conclude that because 777 has not turned up, it, therefore, will never turn up.

3.3 The Later Wittgenstein on Decidability and Algorithmic Decidability


On one fairly standard interpretation, the later Wittgenstein says that true in calculus is
identical to provable in calculus and, therefore, that a mathematical proposition of calculus
is a concatenation of signs that is either provable (in principle) or refutable (in principle) in
calculus [(Goodstein 1972, 279, 282), (Anderson 1958, 487), (Klenk 1976, 13), (Frascolla
1994, 59)]. On this interpretation, the later Wittgenstein precludes undecidable mathematical
propositions, but he allows that some undecided expressions are propositions of a calculus
because they are decidable in principle (i.e., in the absence of a known, applicable decision
procedure).
There is considerable evidence, however, that the later Wittgenstein maintains his intermediate
position that an expression is a meaningful mathematical proposition only within a given
calculus and iff we knowingly have in hand an applicable and effective decision procedure by
means of which we can decide it. For example, though Wittgenstein vacillates between provable
in PM and proved in PM at (RFM App. III, 6, 8), he does so in order to use the former to
consider the alleged conclusion of Gdel's proof (i.e., that there exist true but unprovable
mathematical propositions), which he then rebuts with his own identification of true in calculus
with proved in calculus (i.e., not with provable in calculus ) [(Wang 1991, 253),
(Rodych 1999a, 177)]. This construal is corroborated by numerous passages in which
Wittgenstein rejects the received view that a provable but unproved proposition is true, as he
does when he asserts that (RFM III, 31, 1939) a proof makes new connexions, [i]t does not
establish that they are there because they do not exist until it makes them, and when he says
(RFM VII, 10, 1941) that [a] new proof gives the proposition a place in a new system.
Furthermore, as we have just seen, Wittgenstein rejects PIC as a non-proposition on the grounds

that it is not algorithmically decidable, while admitting finitistic versions of PIC because they are
algorithmically decidable.
Perhaps the most compelling evidence that the later Wittgenstein maintains algorithmic
decidability as his criterion for a mathematical proposition lies in the fact that, at (RFM V, 9,
1942), he says in two distinct ways that a mathematical question can become decidable and that
when this happens, a new connexion is made which previously did not exist. Indeed,
Wittgenstein cautions us against appearances by saying that it looks as if a ground for the
decision were already there, when, in fact, it has yet to be invented. These passages strongly
militate against the claim that the later Wittgenstein grants that proposition is decidable in
calculus iff it is provable or refutable in principle. Moreover, if Wittgenstein held this position,
he would claim, contra (RFM V, 9), that a question or proposition does not become decidable
since it simply (always) is decidable. If it is provable, and we simply don't yet know this to be
the case, there already is a connection between, say, our axioms and rules and the proposition in
question. What Wittgenstein says, however, is that the modalities provable and refutable are
shadowy forms of realitythat possibility is not actuality in mathematics [(PR 141, 144, 172),
(PG 281, 283, 299, 371, 466, 469)], (LFM 139)]. Thus, the later Wittgenstein agrees with the
intermediate Wittgenstein that the only sense in which an undecided mathematical proposition
(RFM VII, 40, 1944) can be decidable is in the sense that we know how to decide it by means of
an applicable decision procedure.

3.4 Wittgenstein's Later Critique of Set Theory: Non-Enumerability vs. NonDenumerability


Largely a product of his anti-foundationalism and his criticism of the extension-intension
conflation, Wittgenstein's later critique of set theory is highly consonant with his intermediate
critique [(PR 109, 168), (PG 334, 369, 469), (LFM 172, 224, 229), and (RFM III, 43, 46, 85,
90; VII, 16)]. Given that mathematics is a MOTLEY of techniques of proof (RFM III, 46), it
does not require a foundation (RFM VII, 16) and it cannot be given a self-evident foundation
[(PR 160), (WVC 34 & 62), (RFM IV, 3)]. Since set theory was invented to provide
mathematics with a foundation, it is, minimally, unnecessary.
Even if set theory is unnecessary, it still might constitute a solid foundation for mathematics. In
his core criticism of set theory, however, the later Wittgenstein denies this, saying that the
diagonal proof does not prove non-denumerability, for [i]t means nothing to say: Therefore the
X numbers are not denumerable (RFM II, 10). When the diagonal is construed as a proof of
greater and lesser infinite sets it is a puffed-up proof, which, as Poincar argued (1913b, 61
62), purports to prove or show more than its means allow it (RFM II, 21).
If it were said: Consideration of the diagonal procedure shews you that the concept real
number has much less analogy with the concept cardinal number than we, being misled by
certain analogies, are inclined to believe, that would have a good and honest sense. But just the
opposite happens: one pretends to compare the set of real numbers in magnitude with that of
cardinal numbers. The difference in kind between the two conceptions is represented, by a skew
form of expression, as difference of extension. I believe, and hope, that a future generation will
laugh at this hocus pocus. (RFM II, 22)

The sickness of a time is cured by an alteration in the mode of life of human beings (RFM II,
23)
The hocus pocus of the diagonal proof rests, as always for Wittgenstein, on a conflation of
extension and intension, on the failure to properly distinguish sets as rules for generating
extensions and (finite) extensions. By way of this confusion a difference in kind (i.e.,
unlimited rule vs. finite extension) is represented by a skew form of expression, namely as a
difference in the cardinality of two infinite extensions. Not only can the diagonal not prove that
one infinite set is greater in cardinality than another infinite set, according to Wittgenstein,
nothing could prove this, simply because infinite sets are not extensions, and hence not infinite
extensions. But instead of interpreting Cantor's diagonal proof honestly, we take the proof to
show there are numbers bigger than the infinite, which sets the whole mind in a whirl, and
gives the pleasant feeling of paradox (LFM 1617)a giddiness attacks us when we think of
certain theorems in set theorywhen we are performing a piece of logical sleight-of-hand
(PI 412; 426; 1945). This giddiness and pleasant feeling of paradox, says Wittgenstein (LFM
16), may be the chief reason [set theory] was invented.
Though Cantor's diagonal is not a proof of non-denumerability, when it is expressed in a
constructive manner, as Wittgenstein himself expresses it at (RFM II, 1), it gives sense to the
mathematical proposition that the number so-and-so is different from all those of the system
(RFM II, 29). That is, the proof proves non-enumerability: it proves that for any given definite
real number concept (e.g., recursive real), one cannot enumerate all such numbers because one
can always construct a diagonal number, which falls under the same concept and is not in the
enumeration. One might say, Wittgenstein says, I call number-concept X non-denumerable if
it has been stipulated that, whatever numbers falling under this concept you arrange in a series,
the diagonal number of this series is also to fall under that concept (RFM II, 10; cf. II, 30,
31, 13).
One lesson to be learned from this, according to Wittgenstein (RFM II, 33), is that there are
diverse systems of irrational points to be found in the number line, each of which can be given
by a recursive rule, but no system of irrational numbers, and also no super-system, no set of
irrational numbers of higher-order infinity. Cantor has shown that we can construct infinitely
many diverse systems of irrational numbers, but we cannot construct an exhaustive system of
all the irrational numbers (RFM II, 29). As Wittgenstein says at (MS 121, 71r; Dec. 27, 1938),
three pages after the passage used for (RFM II, 57): If you now call the Cantorian procedure
one for producing a new real number, you will now no longer be inclined to speak of a system of
all real numbers (italics added). From Cantor's proof, however, set theorists erroneously
conclude that the set of irrational numbers is greater in multiplicity than any enumeration of
irrationals (or the set of rationals), when the only conclusion to draw is that there is no such thing
as the set of all the irrational numbers. The truly dangerous aspect to propositions such as The
real numbers cannot be arranged in a series and The set is not denumerable is that they
make concept formation [i.e., our invention] look like a fact of nature (i.e., something we
discover) (RFM II 16, 37). At best, we have a vague idea of the concept of real number, but
only if we restrict this idea to recursive real number and only if we recognize that having the
concept does not mean having a set of all recursive real numbers.

3.5 Extra-Mathematical Application as a Necessary Condition of Mathematical


Meaningfulness
The principal and most significant change from the middle to later writings on mathematics is
Wittgenstein's (re-)introduction of an extra-mathematical application criterion, which is used to
distinguish mere sign-games from mathematical language-games. [I]t is essential to
mathematics that its signs are also employed in mufti, Wittgenstein states, for [i]t is the use
outside mathematics, and so the meaning [Bedeutung] of the signs, that makes the sign-game
into mathematics (i.e., a mathematical language-game) [(RFM V, 2, 1942), (LFM 140141,
16970)]. As Wittgenstein says at (RFM V, 41, 1943), [c]oncepts which occur in necessary
propositions must also occur and have a meaning [Bedeutung] in non-necessary ones [italics
added]. If two proofs prove the same proposition, says Wittgenstein, this means that both
demonstrate it as a suitable instrument for the same purpose, which is an allusion to something
outside mathematics (RFM VII, 10, 1941; italics added).
As we have seen, this criterion was present in the Tractatus (6.211), but noticeably absent in the
middle period. The reason for this absence is probably that the intermediate Wittgenstein wanted
to stress that in mathematics everything is syntax and nothing is meaning. Hence, in his
criticisms of Hilbert's contentual mathematics (Hilbert 1925) and Brouwer's reliance upon
intuition to determine the meaningful content of (especially undecidable) mathematical
propositions, Wittgenstein couched his finitistic constructivism in strong formalism, emphasizing
that a mathematical calculus does not need an extra-mathematical application (PR 109; WVC
105).
There seem to be two reasons why the later Wittgenstein reintroduces extra-mathematical
application as a necessary condition of a mathematical language-game. First, the later
Wittgenstein has an even greater interest in the use of natural and formal languages in diverse
forms of life (PI 23), which prompts him to emphasize that, in many cases, a mathematical
proposition functions as if it were an empirical proposition hardened into a rule (RFM VI,
23) and that mathematics plays diverse applied roles in many forms of human activity (e.g.,
science, technology, predictions). Second, the extra-mathematical application criterion relieves
the tension between Wittgenstein's intermediate critique of set theory and his strong formalism
according to which one calculus is as good as another (PG 334). By demarcating mathematical
language-games from non-mathematical sign-games, Wittgenstein can now claim that, for the
time being, set theory is merely a formal sign-game.
These considerations may lead us to say that 20 > 0.
That is to say: we can make the considerations lead us to that.
Or: we can say this and give this as our reason.
But if we do say itwhat are we to do next? In what practice is this proposition anchored? It is
for the time being a piece of mathematical architecture which hangs in the air, and looks as if it
were, let us say, an architrave, but not supported by anything and supporting nothing. (RFM II,
35)

It is not that Wittgenstein's later criticisms of set theory change, it is, rather, that once we see that
set theory has no extra-mathematical application, we will focus on its calculations, proofs, and
prose and subject the interest of the calculations to a test (RFM II, 62). By means of
Wittgenstein's immensely important investigation (LFM 103), we will find, Wittgenstein
expects, that set theory is uninteresting (e.g., that the non-enumerability of the reals is
uninteresting and useless) and that our entire interest in it lies in the charm of the mistaken
prose interpretation of its proofs (LFM 16). More importantly, though there is a solid core to all
[its] glistening concept-formations (RFM V, 16), once we see it as as a mistake of ideas, we
will see that propositions such as 20 > 0 are not anchored in an extra-mathematical practice,
that Cantor's paradise is not a paradise, and we will then leave of [our] own accord (LFM
103).
It must be emphasized, however, that the later Wittgenstein still maintains that the operations
within a mathematical calculus are purely formal, syntactical operations governed by rules of
syntax (i.e., the solid core of formalism).
It is of course clear that the mathematician, in so far as he really is playing a game[is] acting
in accordance with certain rules. (RFM V, 1)
To say mathematics is a game is supposed to mean: in proving, we need never appeal to the
meaning [Bedeutung] of the signs, that is to their extra-mathematical application. (RFM V, 4)
Where, during the middle period, Wittgenstein speaks of arithmetic [as] a kind of geometry at
(PR 109 & 111), the later Wittgenstein similarly speaks of the geometry of proofs (RFM I,
App. III, 14), the geometrical cogency of proofs (RFM III, 43), and a geometrical
application according to which the transformation of signs in accordance with
transformation-rules (RFM VI, 2, 1941) shows that when mathematics is divested of all
content, it would remain that certain signs can be constructed from others according to certain
rules (RFM III, 38). Hence, the question whether a concatenation of signs is a proposition of a
given mathematical calculus (i.e., a calculus with an extra-mathematical application) is still an
internal, syntactical question, which we can answer with knowledge of the proofs and decision
procedures of the calculus.

3.6 Wittgenstein on Gdel and Undecidable Mathematical Propositions


RFM is perhaps most (in)famous for Wittgenstein's (RFM App. III) treatment of true but
unprovable mathematical propositions. Early reviewers said that [t]he arguments are wild
(Kreisel 1958, 153), that the passages on Gdel's theorem are of poor quality or contain
definite errors (Dummett 1959, 324), and that (RFM App. III) throws no light on Gdel's
work (Goodstein 1957, 551). Wittgenstein seems to want to legislate [[q]uestions about
completeness] out of existence, Anderson said, (1958, 48687) when, in fact, he certainly
cannot dispose of Gdel's demonstrations by confusing truth with provability. Additionally,
Bernays, Anderson (1958, 486), and Kreisel (1958, 15354) claimed that Wittgenstein failed to
appreciate Gdel's quite explicit premiss of the consistency of the considered formal system
(Bernays 1959, 15), thereby failing to appreciate the conditional nature of Gdel's First
Incompleteness Theorem. On the reading of these four early expert reviewers, Wittgenstein

failed to understand Gdel's Theorem because he failed to understand the mechanics of Gdel's
proof and he erroneously thought he could refute or undermine Gdel's proof simply by
identifying true in PM (i.e., Principia Mathematica) with proved/provable in PM.
Interestingly, we now have two pieces of evidence [(Kreisel 1998, 119); (Rodych 2003, 282,
307)] that Wittgenstein wrote (RFM App. III) in 193738 after reading only the informal, casual
(MS 126, 126127; Dec. 13, 1942) introduction of (Gdel 1931) and that, therefore, his use of a
self-referential proposition as the true but unprovable proposition may be based on Gdel's
introductory, informal statements, namely that the undecidable proposition [R(q);q] states that
[R(q);q] is not provable (1931, 598) and that [R(q);q] says about itself that it is not provable
(1931, 599). Perplexingly, only two of the four famous reviewers even mentioned Wittgenstein's
(RFM VII, 19, 2122, 1941)) explicit remarks on Gdel's First Incompleteness Theorem
[(Bernays 1959, 2), (Anderson 1958, 487)], which, though flawed, capture the number-theoretic
nature of the Gdelian proposition and the functioning of Gdel-numbering, probably because
Wittgenstein had by then read or skimmed the body of Gdel's 1931 paper (Rodych 2003, 304
07).
The first thing to note, therefore, about (RFM App. III) is that Wittgenstein mistakenly thinks
again, perhaps because Wittgenstein had read only Gdel's Introduction(a) that Gdel proves
that there are true but unprovable propositions of PM (when, in fact, Gdel syntactically proves
that if PM is -consistent, the Gdelian proposition is undecidable in PM) and (b) that Gdel's
proof uses a self-referential proposition to semantically show that there are true but unprovable
propositions of PM.
For this reason, Wittgenstein has two main aims in (RFM App. III): (1) to refute or undermine,
on its own terms, the alleged Gdel proof of true but unprovable propositions of PM, and (2) to
show that, on his own terms, where true in calculus is identified with proved in calculus ,
the very idea of a true but unprovable proposition of calculus is meaningless.
Thus, at (RFM App. III, 8) (hereafter simply 8), Wittgenstein begins his presentation of what
he takes to be Gdel's proof by having someone say: I have constructed a proposition (I will use
P to designate it) in Russell's symbolism, and by means of certain definitions and
transformations it can be so interpreted that it says: P is not provable in Russell's system. That
is, Wittgenstein's Gdelian constructs a proposition that is semantically self-referential and which
specifically says of itself that it is not provable in PM. With this erroneous, self-referential
proposition P [used also at (10), (11), (17), (18)], Wittgenstein presents a proof-sketch very
similar to Gdel's own informal semantic proof sketch in the Introduction of his famous paper
(1931, 598).
Must I not say that this proposition on the one hand is true, and on the other hand is unprovable?
For suppose it were false; then it is true that it is provable. And that surely cannot be! And if it is
proved, then it is proved that it is not provable. Thus it can only be true, but unprovable. (8)
The reasoning here is a double reductio. Assume (a) that P must either be true or false in
Russell's system, and (b) that P must either be provable or unprovable in Russell's system. If (a),
P must be true, for if we suppose that P is false, since P says of itself that it is unprovable, it is

true that it is provable, and if it is provable, it must be true (which is a contradiction), and
hence, given what P means or says, it is true that P is unprovable (which is a contradiction).
Second, if (b), P must be unprovable, for if P is proved, then it is proved that it is not provable,
which is a contradiction (i.e., P is provable and not provable in PM). It follows that P can only
be true, but unprovable.
To refute or undermine this proof, Wittgenstein says that if you have proved P, you have
proved that P is provable (i.e., since you have proved that it is not the case that P is not provable
in Russell's system), and you will now presumably give up the interpretation that it is
unprovable (i.e., P is not provable in Russell's system), since the contradiction is only proved
if we use or retain this self-referential interpretation (8). On the other hand, Wittgenstein argues
(8), [i]f you assume that the proposition is provable in Russell's system, that means it is true in
the Russell sense, and the interpretation P is not provable again has to be given up, because,
once again, it is only the self-referential interpretation that engenders a contradiction. Thus,
Wittgenstein's refutation of Gdel's proof consists in showing that no contradiction arises if
we do not interpret P as P is not provable in Russell's systemindeed, without this
interpretation, a proof of P does not yield a proof of P and a proof of P does not yield a proof
of P. In other words, the mistake in the proof is the mistaken assumption that a mathematical
proposition P can be so interpreted that it says: P is not provable in Russell's system. As
Wittgenstein says at (11), [t]hat is what comes of making up such sentences.
This refutation of Gdel's proof is perfectly consistent with Wittgenstein's syntactical
conception of mathematics (i.e., wherein mathematical propositions have no meaning and hence
cannot have the requisite self-referential meaning) and with what he says before and after (8),
where his main aim is to show (2) that, on his own terms, since true in calculus is identical
with proved in calculus , the very idea of a true but unprovable proposition of calculus is a
contradiction-in-terms.
To show (2), Wittgenstein begins by asking (5), what he takes to be, the central question,
namely, Are there true propositions in Russell's system, which cannot be proved in his
system?. To address this question, he asks What is called a true proposition in Russell's
system?, which he succinctly answers (6): p is true = p. Wittgenstein then clarifies this
answer by reformulating the second question of (5) as Under what circumstances is a
proposition asserted in Russell's game [i.e., system]?, which he then answers by saying: the
answer is: at the end of one of his proofs, or as a fundamental law (Pp.) (6). This, in a
nutshell, is Wittgenstein's conception of mathematical truth: a true proposition of PM is an
axiom or a proved proposition, which means that true in PM is identical with, and therefore
can be supplanted by, proved in PM.
Having explicated, to his satisfaction at least, the only real, non-illusory notion of true in PM,
Wittgenstein answers the (8) question Must I not say that this proposition is true, and
unprovable? negatively by (re)stating his own (56) conception of true in PM as
proved/provable in PM: True in Russell's system means, as was said: proved in Russell's
system; and false in Russell's system means: the opposite has been proved in Russell's system.
This answer is given in a slightly different way at (7) where Wittgenstein asks may there not
be true propositions which are written in this [Russell's] symbolism, but are not provable in

Russell's system?, and then answers True propositions, hence propositions which are true in
another system, i.e. can rightly be asserted in another game. In light of what he says in (5, 6,
and 8), Wittgenstein's (7) point is that if a proposition is written in Russell's symbolism and
it is true, it must be proved/provable in another system, since that is what mathematical truth is.
Analogously (8), if the proposition is supposed to be false in some other than the Russell
sense, then it does not contradict this for it to be proved in Russell's sense, for [w]hat is called
losing in chess may constitute winning in another game. This textual evidence certainly
suggests, as Anderson almost said, that Wittgenstein rejects a true but unprovable mathematical
proposition as a contradiction-in-terms on the grounds that true in calculus means nothing
more (and nothing less) than proved in calculus .
On this (natural) interpretation of (RFM App. III), the early reviewers conclusion that
Wittgenstein fails to understand the mechanics of Gdel's argument seems reasonable. First,
Wittgenstein erroneously thinks that Gdel's proof is essentially semantical and that it uses and
requires a self-referential proposition. Second, Wittgenstein says (14) that [a] contradiction is
unusable for a prediction that that such-and-such construction is impossible (i.e., that P is
unprovable in PM), which, superficially at least (Rodych 1999a, 19091), seems to indicate that
Wittgenstein fails to appreciate the consistency assumption of Gdel's proof (Kreisel, Bernays,
Anderson).
If, in fact, Wittgenstein did not read and/or failed to understand Gdel's proof through at least
1941, how would he have responded if and when he understood it as (at least) a proof of the
undecidability of P in PM on the assumption of PM's consistency? Given his syntactical
conception of mathematics, even with the extra-mathematical application criterion, he would
simply say that P, qua expression syntactically independent of PM, is not a proposition of PM,
and if it is syntactically independent of all existent mathematical language-games, it is not a
mathematical proposition. Moreover, there seem to be no compelling non-semantical reasons
either intra-systemic or extra-mathematicalfor Wittgenstein to accommodate P by including it
in PM or by adopting a non-syntactical conception of mathematical truth (such as Tarski-truth
(Steiner 2000)). Indeed, Wittgenstein questions the intra-systemic and extra-mathematical
usability of P in various discussions of Gdel in the Nachlass (Rodych 2002, 2003) and, at (19),
he emphatically says that one cannot make the truth of the assertion [P or Therefore P]
plausible to me, since you can make no use of it except to do these bits of legerdemain.
After the initial, scathing reviews of RFM, very little attention was paid to Wittgenstein's (RFM
App. III) and (RFM VII, 2122) discussions of Gdel's First Incompleteness Theorem (Klenk
1976, 13) until Shanker's sympathetic (1988b). In the last 11 years, however, commentators and
critics have offered various interpretations of Wittgenstein's remarks on Gdel, some being
largely sympathetic (Floyd 1995, 2001) and others offering a more mixed appraisal [(Rodych
1999a, 2002, 2003), (Steiner 2001), (Priest 2004), (Berto 2009a)]. Recently, and perhaps most
interestingly, (Floyd & Putnam 2000) and (Steiner 2001) have evoked new and interesting
discussions of Wittgenstein's ruminations on undecidability, mathematical truth, and Gdel's
First Incompleteness Theorem [(Rodych 2003, 2006), (Bays 2004), (Sayward 2005), and (Floyd
& Putnam 2006)].

4. The Impact of Philosophy of Mathematics on


Mathematics
Though it is doubtful that all commentators will agree [(Wrigley 1977, 51), (Baker and Hacker
1985, 345), (Floyd 1991, 145, 143; 1995, 376; 2005, 80), (Maddy 1993, 55), (Steiner 1996, 202
204)], the following passage seems to capture Wittgenstein's attitude to the Philosophy of
Mathematics and, in large part, the way in which he viewed his own work on mathematics.
What will distinguish the mathematicians of the future from those of today will really be a
greater sensitivity, and that willas it wereprune mathematics; since people will then be more
intent on absolute clarity than on the discovery of new games.
Philosophical clarity will have the same effect on the growth of mathematics as sunlight has on
the growth of potato shoots. (In a dark cellar they grow yards long.)
A mathematician is bound to be horrified by my mathematical comments, since he has always
been trained to avoid indulging in thoughts and doubts of the kind I develop. He has learned to
regard them as something contemptible and he has acquired a revulsion from them as infantile.
That is to say, I trot out all the problems that a child learning arithmetic, etc., finds difficult, the
problems that education represses without solving. I say to those repressed doubts: you are quite
correct, go on asking, demand clarification! (PG 381, 1932)
In his middle and later periods, Wittgenstein believes he is providing philosophical clarity on
aspects and parts of mathematics, on mathematical conceptions, and on philosophical
conceptions of mathematics. Lacking such clarity and not aiming for absolute clarity,
mathematicians construct new games, sometimes because of a misconception of the meaning of
their mathematical propositions and mathematical terms. Education and especially advanced
education in mathematics does not encourage clarity but rather represses itquestions that
deserve answers are either not asked or are dismissed. Mathematicians of the future, however,
will be more sensitive and this will (repeatedly) prune mathematical extensions and inventions,
since mathematicians will come to recognize that new extensions and creations (e.g.,
propositions of transfinite cardinal arithmetic) are not well-connected with the solid core of
mathematics or with real-world applications. Philosophical clarity will, eventually, enable
mathematicians and philosophers to get down to brass tacks (PG 467).

Вам также может понравиться