Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 45

Imagination

First published Mon Mar 14, 2011


To imagine something is to form a particular sort of mental representation of that thing.
Imagining is typically distinguished from mental states such
as perceiving, remembering and believing in that imagining S does not require (that the
subject consider) S to be or have been the case, whereas the contrasting states do. It is
distinguished from mental states such as desiring or anticipating in that imagining S does not
require that the subject wish or expect S to be the case, whereas the contrasting states do. It is
also sometimes distinguished from mental states such as conceiving andsupposing, on the
grounds that imagining S requires some sort of quasi-sensory or positive representation of S,
whereas the contrasting states do not.
Contemporary philosophical discussions of the imagination have been primarily focused on
three sets of topics. Work in philosophy of mind and philosophy of psychology has explored
a cluster of issues concerning the phenomenology and cognitive architecture of imagination,
examining the ways that imagination differs from and resembles other mental states both
phenomenologically and functionally, and investigating the roles that imagination may play
in the understanding of self and others, and in the representation of past, future and
counterfactual scenarios. Work in aesthetics has focused on issues related to imaginative
engagement with fictional characters and events, identifying and offering resolutions to a
number of (apparent) paradoxes. And work in modal epistemology has focused on the extent
to which imaginabilityand its cousin conceivabilitycan serve as guides to possibility.
Because of the breadth of the topic, this entry focuses exclusively on contemporary
discussions of imagination in the Anglo-American philosophical tradition. (For an overview
of historical discussions of imagination, see the sections on pre-twentieth century and early
twentieth centuryaccounts of mental imagery in the corresponding Stanford
Encyclopedia entry; for a more detailed and comprehensive historical survey, see Brann
1991. For a sophisticated and wide-ranging discussion of imagination in the
phenomenological tradition, see Casey 2000.)
1. Overview: Varieties of Imagination
2. Imagination and Other Mental States
o 2.1 Imagination and Mental Imagery
o 2.2 Imagination and Belief
o 2.3 Imagination and Desire

o 2.4 Imagination and Supposition


o 2.5 Imagination and Dreaming
o 2.6 Imagination and Pretense
3. Imagination: Norms and Violations
o 3.1 Mirroring and Quarantining
o 3.2 Disparity and Contagion
o 3.3 Explaining Contagion
4. Some Roles of Imagination
o 4.1 Imagination and Mindreading
o 4.2 Imagination, Fiction and Moral Understanding
o 4.3 Imagination and Reshaping Responses
o 4.4 Imagination and Counterfactual Reasoning
o 4.5 Imagination and Possibility
5. Imagination: Puzzles and Problems
o 5.1 Imagination and Fictionality
o 5.2 Imaginative Resistance
o 5.3 The Paradox of Fictional Emotions
o 5.4 The Paradox of Tragedy
o 5.5 The Puzzles of Iteration
o 5.6 Visualizing the Unseen (Berkeley's Puzzle)
6. Empirical Work on Imagination
o 6.1 Developmental Work on the Origins of Pretense

o 6.2 Imagination and Autism


o 6.3 Imagination and Delusions
o 6.4 Recent Cognitive and Social Psychological Work on Imagination
Bibliography
Academic Tools
Other Internet Resources
Related Entries

1. Overview: Varieties of Imagination


There is a general consensus among those who work on the topic that the term imagination is
used too broadly to permit simple taxonomy. Indeed, it is common for overview essays
(including this one) to begin with an invocation of P. F. Strawson's remarks in Imagination
and Perception (1970), where he writes:
The uses, and applications, of the terms image, imagine, imagination, and so forth make
up a very diverse and scattered family. Even this image of a family seems too definite. It
would be a matter of more than difficulty to identify and list the family's members, let alone
their relations of parenthood and cousinhood (Strawson 1970, 31; cf. McGinn 2009, 595).
These taxonomic challenges carry over into attempts at characterization. In the opening
chapter ofMimesis as Make-Believeperhaps the most influential contemporary book-length
treatment of imaginationKendall Walton (1990) throws up his hands at the prospect of
delineating the notion precisely. After enumerating and distinguishing a number of
paradigmatic instances of imagining, he asks:
What is it to imagine? We have examined a number of dimensions along which imaginings
can vary; shouldn't we now spell out what they have in common?Yes, if we can. But I
can't. (Walton 1990, 19)
The only recent attempt at a somewhat comprehensive inventory of the term's uses is due to
Leslie Stevenson (2003), who enumerates (without claiming exhaustiveness) twelve of the
most influential conceptions of imagination that can be found in recent discussions in
philosophy of mind, aesthetics, ethics, poetry and religion. These range from the
ability to think of something not presently perceived, but spatio-temporally real to the

ability to create works of art that express something deep about the meaning of life
(Stevenson 2003, 238).
In light of this unwieldiness, recent attempts at taxonomy have tended to eschew
comprehensiveness, focusing instead on identifying and classifying selected aspects of the
phenomenon. Kendall Walton (1990), for instance, distinguishes
between spontaneous anddeliberate imagining (acts of imagination that occur with or
without the subject's conscious direction), between occurrent and nonoccurrent
imaginings (acts of imagination that do or do not occupy the subject's explicit attention), and
between social and solitary imaginings (episodes of imagining that occur with or without the
joint participation of several subjects.)
Other taxonomies concentrate on carving out a particular aspect of the topic for further
discussion. Gregory Currie and Ian Ravenscroft (2002) begin their book-length work on
imagination by distinguishing among creative imagination (combining ideas in unexpected
and unconventional ways); sensory imagination (perception-like experiences in the absence
of appropriate stimuli); and what they call recreative imagination (an ability to experience or
think about the world from a perspective different from the one that experience presents),
focusing the remainder of their discussion largely on the third (recreative) sense, and setting
aside the first (creative) sense almost entirely. (Cf. also Strawson 1970, 31.) [Recent work on
the creative imagination has taken place largely within the context of empirical psychology
(see Boden 2003; Csikszentmihalyi 1997; Sternberg 1998), though there has been some
philosophical attention to the issue in recent years (see Carruthers 2007; Gaut & Livingston
2003).]
Yet other taxonomies classify varieties of imagination in terms of their structure and content.
Many philosophers distinguish between propositional imagination (imagining that P)
and non-propositional imagination, dividing the latter into objectual imagining (imagining
E) (Yablo 1993) and active imagining (imagining X-ing) (Walton 1990). (For a related
distinction, see the discussion of Thomas Nagel's (1974) distinction between sympathetic
imagining (imagining oneself undergoing a certain experience) and perceptual
imagining (imagining oneself perceiving a certain event or state of affairs) in section 4.5
below.) These notions are often spelled out by means of examples.
When a subject imagines propositionally, she represents to herself that something is the case.
So, for example, Juliet might imagine that Romeo is by her side. To imagine in this sense is
to stand in some mental relation to a particular proposition. (See propositional attitude
reports.)
When a subject imagines objectually, she represents to herself a real or make-believe entity
or situation. So, for example, Prospero might imagine an acorn or a nymph or the city of
Naples or a wedding feast. To imagine in this sense is to stand in some mental relation to a

representation of an (imaginary or real) entity or state of affairs. (Yablo 1993; see also Martin
2002; Noordhof 2002; O'Shaughnessy 2000.)
When a subject imagines X-ing, she simulatively represents to herself some sort of activity or
experience. So, for example, Ophelia might imagine seeing Hamlet or getting herself to a
nunnery. To imagine in this sense is to stand in a first-personal mental relation to some
(imaginary or real) behavior or perception.
A final way of thinking about imagination treats imagined as a decoupling or facsimile
or counterpart operator (cf. Leslie 1987; Goldman 2000; Budd 1989) that can, in principle,
be attached to any (mental) state. So, for example, one might speak of imagined perception
(or perception-like imagining), imagined belief (or belief-like imagining), imagined desire
(or desire-like imagining), imagined action (or action-like imagining), and so on. On this sort
of account, a taxonomy of imaginative attitudes would share whatever shape governs
experience more generally.
No particular taxonomy has gained general currency in recent discussions.

2. Imagination and Other Mental States


2.1 Imagination and Mental Imagery
To have a (merely) mental image is to have a perception-like experience triggered by
something other than the appropriate external stimulus; so, for example, one might have a
picture in the mind's eye or a tune running through one's head (Strawson 1970, 31) in the
absence of any corresponding visual or auditory object or event.
Although it is possible to form mental images in any of the sensory modalities, the bulk of
discussion both in psychological and philosophical contexts has focused on visual imagery.
The most prominent debate in this area concerns the representational format of visual mental
images, and, in particular, the question of whether visual mental images are picture-like in
the sense they can be mentally scanned in much the way that we can visually scan objects
that we see. The picture theory holds, roughly, that the mental representations we
experience in cases of visual imagining represent spatial relationships via representational
properties that are themselves inherently spatial (Kosslyn 1980, 1994; Kosslyn et al. 2006;
Shepard and Metzler 1971; Shepard and Cooper 1982). The alternative, propositional or
descriptive theory, holds that visual mental images are non-pictorial, language-like
representations of visual scenes (Pylyshyn 1973, 2002, 2003). (For a detailed presentation
and discussion of these issues, see the discussion of the analog-propositional debate in the
entry on mental imagery; cf. also Block ed. 1981; Tye 1991.)
A more general questionwhich has received less attention in philosophical discussions of
the imaginationconcerns the relation between mental imagery (or sensory imagination) and
imagination more generally. While most theorists of the imagination distinguish

between sensory imagination (forming a mental image) and cognitive


imagination (conceptually entertaining a possibility) (cf. McGinn 2009, following McGinn
2004), or between perception-like (sensory) andbelief-like (propositional) imaginings (Currie
and Ravenscroft 2002), questions such as whether sensory and propositional imagining are
related as perception is to belief have not been explored in detail. (For some speculative
thoughts about the ways in which sensory and cognitive imagination may be related, see
McGinn 2004, chapters 12 and 13; cf. also Kind 2001; for discussion of potential relations
between perceptual imagination and objectual imagination, see Chalmers 2002, 150151;
Yablo 1993.)
A detailed discussion of the topic of mental imagery and its attendant debates can be found in
theStanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy entry on mental imagery.

2.2 Imagination and Belief


As was noted in section 1, imagination, like belief, has a propositional use. When we say
something like: Macbeth believes that there is a dagger before him, we attribute to the
subject (Macbeth) an attitude (belief) towards a proposition (that there is a dagger before
him). In so doing, we areroughlysuggesting that he regards the proposition in question
as true. (See belief.)
Likewise, when we say something like: Juliet imagines that Romeo is standing beside her,
we again attribute to our subject (Juliet) an attitude (imagination) towards a proposition (that
Romeo is standing beside her). In so doing, we areroughlysuggesting that she regards
the proposition as, say, fictional or make-believe or pretend. (Cf. Currie 1990; Nichols and
Stich 2000; Walton 1990.)
To a reasonable approximation, then, to believe that P is to regard P as literally true (for
complications with this account, see Velleman 2000), whereas to imagine that P is to
regard P as fictional or make-believe or pretend, regardless of whether P actually obtains.
What does this characterization illuminate about the relation between the two attitudes?
It is widely accepted thatat least in their propositional usageimagination and belief
range over similar, though perhaps not identical, ranges of content. The caveats arise because
if one holds a view of imagination according to which imagination must be quasi-sensory,
then there are (abstract) propositions that can be believed but not imagined (though they can
presumably be conceived.) And if one holds a certain view of epistemic modality, there are
propositionsa posteriori necessary falsehoodsthat can be imagined but not believed.
Setting aside these exceptions, however, it appears that the in-principle domain over which
both belief and (propositional) imagination range is the same: roughly, the domain of all
understandable propositions.
But whereas what we believe is determined by (what we think) the actual world is like, what
we imagine is (to a large extent), up to us. The reason for this is straightforward. Since to

believe that Pis to take P to hold of the actual world, and since which world is the actual
world is (in the relevant sense) not up to us, belief's task is to conform to some pre-ordained
structureits direction of fit is mind-to-world. (For related discussion of direction of fit, see
the entry on speech acts.) By contrast, since to imagine P is to take P to hold of some
particular (set of) non-actual world(s), and since which worlds are imagined is (in the
relevant sense) up to us, imagining's task need not be to conform to some pre-ordained
structure. (A possible exception is guided imagination of the sort generated by stories and
works of art; for discussion of these issues, see section 5.1 below.)
This distinction is sometimes expressed by saying that whereas believing some content
involves taking the content to be true in the actual world, imagining that content involves
taking that content to be true-in-fiction, or make-believe-true, or pretend-true. (Discussion of
the relation between truthsimpliciter and truth-in-fiction goes beyond the scope of this entry.
For further discussion of some of these issues, see the Stanford Encyclopedia entries
on truth and fictionalism and Zalta 1992.)
On the basis of these sorts of considerations, a number of theorists have proposed cognitive
models on which belief and imagination (or pretense) involve distinct but structurally-similar
psychological mechanisms that act on similar sorts of representational content. The most
prominent of these is Nichols and Stich's (2000, 2003) cognitive theory of pretense,
according to which belief and imagination are psychological attitudes that operate on
propositional content stored in different mental boxesa Belief Box in the case of
beliefs, and a Possible World Box in the case of imaginingseach governed by
characteristic set of rules that regulate its relation to behavior and to other mental states.
For general discussions of the relation between imagination and belief, see Currie and
Ravenscroft 2002; Nichols and Stich 2000; Walton 1990; and Velleman 2000 as well as
essays collected in Lopes and Kieren eds. 2003 and Nichols ed. 2006.

2.3 Imagination and Desire


Like belief and imagination, desire has a propositional use. In this sense, we might say:
Hamlet desires that Claudius drink from the poisoned cup. When we say this, we attribute
to our subject (Hamlet) an attitude (desire) towards a proposition (that Claudius drink from
the poisoned cup). In so doing, we areroughlysuggesting that he regards the state of
affairs represented by the proposition as one to be brought about.
Unlike belief, desire does not have a mind-to-world fit. Desire is an attitude that
is conative rather than cognitive: it has a world-to-mind fit. To desire that P is, roughly, to
wish that it were or will be the case that P hold of the actual world.
In light of this, the question arises whetherin addition to there being an imaginative
analogue to beliefthere is also an imaginative analogue to desire. To imaginatively desire
(i-desire) that P, or to have a desire-like imagining, would be to wishin an imaginative

waythat it were or will be the case that P hold (in some fictional or make-believe or
pretend world.)
The notion of desire-like imagination (Currie 1990, 2002; Velleman 2000) or idesire (Doggett and Egan 2007) has been invoked to explain two phenomena: the generation
of behaviors in imaginary contexts, and the apparent existence of desires evoked by fictions.
According to such accounts, if I'm pretending to be Cleopatra, it is my desire-like imagining
that I be with Antony, in conjunction with my belief-like imagining that you are Antony, that
leads me to take actions such as embracing you. Relatedly, on such accounts, just as I may
imagine that Romeo and Juliet both die (and thus imagine something about them in a belieflike way), I may also want them to go on living (and thus imagine something about them in
a desire-like way.)
Objections to such accounts contend that the notion of desire-like imagination (or i-desire) is
unnecessary to explain the phenomena for which it is intended to account. On such views,
rather than desiring-in-imagination that Romeo and Juliet live, what I desire(-in-actuality) is
that in the fiction Romeo and Juliet live.
For further discussion of desire-in-imagination/i-desire, see (defenders) Currie 1990, ch.5;
Currie 2002; Currie and Ravenscroft 2002; Doggett and Egan 2007; Velleman 2000;
(dissenters) Carruthers 2003; Nichols and Stich 2000, 2003; Funkhouser and Spaulding 2009

2.4 Imagination and Supposition


A number of contemporary discussions of the imagination distinguish between mere
supposition on the one hand, and engaged or vivid imagination on the other. Roughly, mere
supposition is what is involved in simple cases of hypothetical reasoning, whereas vivid
imagination is what is involved in aesthetic participation, engaged pretense, or absorbing
games of make-believe.
A related distinction is made by Alvin Goldman (2006) between suppositional imagination
(s-imagination) on the one hand, and enactment imagination (e-imagination) on the other. Simagination involves supposing that particular content obtains (for example, supposing that I
am elated); e-imagination involves enacting, or trying to enact, elation itself. (Goldman
2006, 4748, italics omitted.) (Note that Goldman's notion of s-imagination is to be
distinguished from Peacocke's notion of the same name (see section 5.6 below.))
The distinction between mere supposition and vivid imagination is often invoked in
discussions of imaginative engagement. Richard Moran (1994), for example, distinguishes
between them on the grounds that vivid imagination tends to give rise to a wide range of
further mental states, including affective responses, whereas mere supposition does not. (See
section 5.3 below.) In a related vein, Tamar Gendler (2000) points out that while attempting
to vividly imagine something like that female infanticide is morally right seems to generate
imaginative resistance, merely supposing it does not. (For a characterization and discussion

of imaginative resistance, see section 5.2 below.) Gregory Currie and Ian Ravenscroft (2002)
contend that this difference arises because supposition involves belief-like imagining in the
absence of desire-like imagining, whereas engaged imagining involves both, Similarly, Tyler
Doggett and Andy Egan (2007) point out that vividly imagining tends to motivate actions in
the context of pretense, while merely supposing tends not to.
For additional discussion of the relation between supposition and vivid imagination, see
Currie & Ravenscroft 2002, Doggett and Egan 2007, Gendler 2000, Moran 1994, Nichols
2006, Weinberg & Meskin 2006.

2.5 Imagination and Dreaming


Dreaming is often characterized by appeal to the idea of imagination. Kendall Walton (1990),
for example, describes dreams as spontaneous, undeliberate imaginings, while
psychologist David Foulkes characterizes dreaming as the awareness of being in an
imagined world in which things happen (Foulkes 1999, 9).
As John Sutton (2009) notes, the topic of dreaming has been relatively neglected in recent
discussions in the philosophy of mind (for an exception, see Flanagan 2000)including the
literature on imagination. But there has been a recent flurry of discussion about the question
of whether dream contents are (experienced as) imagined or believed.
On what might be called the orthodox view of dreaming, if I dream that I'm falling, while
dreaming I have the belief that I'm falling. Perhaps the most famous adherent to the orthodox
view is Descartes, who uses the purported fact that we often believe what we dream to
motivate his skepticism.
More recently, Jonathan Ichikawa (2009) and Ernest Sosa (2005; 2007) have denied that
dreaming involves believing. Rather, they argue, dreaming is a form of imagining. Ichikawa,
expanding on work by Sosa, observes that the dream-analogues of beliefs do not behave like
normal beliefs: dream beliefs are not related to perceptual experience or to behavior in
ways that waking beliefs are; and dream beliefs are subject to radical shifts in ways that
waking beliefs are not. Thus, they contend, our relation to the contents of our dreams is one
of imagination, not belief. (See also Malcolm 1959; Dennett 1976.) Sosa claims (2005; 2007)
and Ichikawa denies (2008) that this reconstrual fully blunts the force of the Cartesian
dreaming argument.
In support of a version of the orthodox view, Colin McGinn (2004) has argued that, although
dreams do involve mental imagery rather than perceptual experiences, they may also involve
belief. He argues this partly on the grounds that dreams often involve a deep emotional
engagement that is absent from both imagination and daydreaming, yet characteristic of
belief (978). He proposes what he calls the fictional immersion theory of dreaming (1034),
according to which dreams are like fictions where we become so deeply engaged that we

lose ourselves and thereby form (admittedly atypical) beliefs. (For related discussion, see
5.3 below.)
For an overview of the range of philosophical issues raised by dreamingincluding a
number that relate directly to the issue of imaginationsee Sutton 2009, as well as the booklength treatment in Flanagan 2000. For an overview of recent empirical discussions of
dreaming see the anthologies edited by Barrett and McNamara eds. (2009), Ellman and
Antrobus eds. (1991), and Pace-Schott et al eds. (2003), or the book-length treatments by
Domhoff (2003) and Hobson (1988, 2002). For a review of recent empirical work on the
nature of daydreaming, see Klinger 2009.

2.6 Imagination and Pretense


Questions about the relation between imagination and pretense are to some extent
terminological. Some (following Ryle 1949) speak of imagination and pretense
interchangeably; others take imagination to be more mentalistic and pretense
more behavioral. On the latter reading, most philosophers agree that one could imagine
without pretending, and that one could pretend (that is, act-as-if) without imagining. (Cf.
Ryle 1949; Currie and Ravenscroft 2002.)
In the developmental psychology literature, there is debate over the underlying capacities
that facilitate pretense behavior in children, with three competing theoretical positions
predominating.Metarepresentational accounts maintain that pretense involves representing
the contents of the pretend episode as pretense, and thus holds that those who engage in
pretense behavior must possess a concept of pretense (Leslie 1987,
1994). Behaviorist accounts maintain, to the contrary, that pretending requires only the
ability to behave as if the content of the pretense were true (Harris 1994, 2000; Perner
1991; Nichols and Stich 2003). Intentionalist accounts maintain that what underlies the
ability to engage in pretense behavior is the ability to intend to pretend or to act as though the
contents of the pretense episode were true (Searle 1979; Rakoczy, Tomasello and Striano
2004).
A more detailed discussion of pretense in the context of early childhood development can be
found in section 6.1 below.

3. Imagination: Norms and Violations


3.1 Mirroring and Quarantining
Games of pretense in particular, and imaginative episodes in general, tend to share a pair of
features that have been dubbed mirroring and quarantining. (Gendler 2003; see also Leslie
1987; Perner 1991, Nichols and Stich 2000).

Mirroring is manifest to the extent that features of the imaginary situation that have not been
explicitly stipulated are derivable via features of their real-world analogues, or, more
generally, to the extent that imaginative content is taken to be governed by the same sorts of
restrictions that govern believed content. For example, in a widely-discussed experiment
conducted by Alan Leslie (1994), children are asked to engage in an imaginary tea party.
When an experimenter tips and spills one of the (empty) teacups, children consider the nontipped cup to be full (in the context of the pretense) and the tipped cup to be empty (both
within and outside of the context of the pretense). More generally, it appears that both games
of make-believe and more complicated engagements with fiction, cinema, and visual art are
governed by principles of generation, according to which particular prompts or props
generate or render make-believe particular fictional truths and that those principles tend to
be, for the most part, reality-oriented. (Walton 1990). (For further discussion, see Currie
2002; Gendler 2003; Harris 2000; Harris and Kavanaugh 1993; Leslie 1994; Lewis 1983b;
Nichols and Stich 2000. Related issues are discussed below in section 3.3 below.)
Quarantining, is manifest to the extent that events within the imagined or pretended episode
are taken to have effects only within a relevantly circumscribed domain. So, for example, the
child engaging in the make-believe tea party does not expect that spilling (imaginary) tea
will result in the table really being wet, nor does a person who imagines winning the lottery
expect that when she visits the ATM, her bank account will contain a million dollars. More
generally, quarantining is manifest to the extent that proto-beliefs and proto-attitudes
concerning the imagined state of affairs are not treated as beliefs and attitudes relevant to
guiding action in the actual world. (The failure to quarantine imaginary attitudes in certain
contexts is often taken to be a mark of mental illness; see section 6.3 below.)
Some (Nichols and Stich 2000, 2003; cf. Leslie 1987) have suggest that mirroring and
quarantining fall out naturally from the architecture of the imagination: mirroring is a
consequence of the ways in which imagination and belief share a single code and
quarantining is a consequence of the way in which imagination takes place off-line
(Nichols 2004; 2006.)

3.2 Disparity and Contagion


Though games of pretense and imaginative episodes are largely governed by mirroring and
quarantining, both may be violated in systematic ways. Mirroring gives way to disparity as a
result of the ways in which (the treatment of) imaginary content may differ from (that of)
believed content. Imagined content may be incomplete (e.g. there may be no fact of the
matter (in the pretense) just how much tea has spilled on the table) or incoherent (e.g. it
might be that the toaster serves (in the pretense) as a logical-truth inverter). And content that
is imagined may give rise todiscrepant responses, most strikingly in cases of discrepant
affect (where, for example, the imminent destruction of all human life is treated as amusing
rather than terrifying; cf. Nichols 2006, also Gendler 2003, 2006; see also section 5.2 below.)

Quarantining gives way to contagion when imagined content ends up playing a direct role in
actual attitudes and behavior. This is common in cases of affective transmission, where an
emotional response generated by an imagined situation may constrain subsequent behavior.
For example, imagining something fearful (such as a tiger in the kitchen) may give rise to
actual hesitation (such as reluctance to enter the room; cf. Harris et al 1991.) And it also
occurs in cases of cognitive transmission, where imagined content is thereby primed and
rendered more accessible in ways that go on to shape subsequent perception and experience.
For example, imagining some object (such as a sheep) may make one more likely to
perceive such objects in one's environment (such as mistaking a rock for a ram.) (For an
overview of such cases, cf. Gendler 2003; 2006.)

3.3 Explaining Contagion


A number of philosophers have proposed explanations for how imagining might give rise to
emotional and behavioral responses typically associated with belief, despite the imaginer's
explicit avowal that she does not take the imagined content to be real.
One recent explanation of this phenomenon makes appeal to what Tamar Gendler has
dubbed alief.(Gendler, 2008a, 2008b; see also Dennett and McKay 2009) To have an alief is
roughlyto have an innate or habitual propensity for a real or apparent stimulus to
automatically activate a particular affective and behavioral repertoire, where the behavioral
propensities to which an alief gives rise may be in tension with those that arise from one's
beliefs. So, for example, while a subject maybelieve that drinking out of a sterile bedpan is
completely safe, she may nonetheless show hesitation and disgust at the prospect of doing so
because the bedpan renders occurrent an alief with the content filthy object, disgusting, stay
away. Since aliefs, by their nature, are source-indifferent, imagined content may give rise to
alief-driven reactions. As a result, the notion of alief may explain how content that we
explicitly recognize to be purely imaginary may nonetheless produce powerful emotional and
cognitive responses. (Gendler 2008a, 2008b; see also section 5.3 below.)
Andy Egan (2001) explains similar phenomena in terms of what he calls bimagination, a
mental state that has some of the distinctive features of belief and some of imagination:
bimagination is both action-guiding (and hence belief-like) and inferentially highly
circumscribed (and hence imagination-like.) On Egan's view, this distinctive mental state can
be invoked to explain a number of cases that other philosophers have described as involving
imagined content that gives rise to belief-typical responses (particularly delusions, see
section 6.3 below.)
Further discussion of related issues can be found in Perner, Baker, and Hutton 1994;
Schwitzgebel 2001; and Zimmerman 2007. Additional discussion of contagion in the context
of fictional emotions can be found in section 5.3 below.

4. Some Roles of Imagination

Much of the contemporary discussion of imagination has centered around particular roles
that imagination is purported to play in various domains of human understanding and
activity. Five of the most widely-discussed are the role of imagination in the understanding
of other minds (Section 4.1), in the cultivation of moral understanding and sensibility
(Section 4.2), in the reconfiguration of responses (Section 4.3), in planning and
counterfactual reasoning (Section 4.4), and in providing knowledge of possibility (Section
4.5).

4.1 Imagination and Mindreading


Mindreading is the activity of attributing mental states to oneself and to others, and of
predicting and explaining behavior on the basis of those attributions.
Early discussions of mindreading were often framed as debates between the theory
theorywhich holds that the attribution of mental states to others is guided by the
application of some (tacit) folk psychological theoryand the simulation theorywhich
holds that the attribution of mental states is guided by a process of replicating or emulating
the target's (apparent) mental states, perhaps through mechanisms involving the imagination.
(Influential collections of papers on this debate include Carruthers and Smith, eds. 1996;
Davies and Stone, eds. 1995a, 1995b.) In recent years, proponents of both sides have
increasingly converged on common ground, allowing that both theory and simulation play
some role in the attribution of mental states to others (Cf. Carruthers 2003; Goldman 2006;
Nichols and Stich 2003; cf. also empirical work adverted to in section 6 below.) Many
such hybrid accounts include a role for imagination.
On theory theory views, mindreading involves the application of some (tacit) folk
psychological theory that allows the subject to make predictions and offer explanations of the
target's beliefs and behaviors. On pure versions of such accounts, imagination plays no
special role in the attribution of mental states to others. (For an overview of theory theory, cf.
the entry on folk psychology as a theory).
On simulation theory views, mindreading involves simulating the target's mental states so as
to exploit similarities between the subject's and target's processing capacities. It is this
simulation that allows the subject to make predictions and offer explanations of the target's
beliefs and behaviors. (For early papers, see Goldman 1989; Gordon 1986; Heal 1986; for
recent dissent, see, e.g., Carruthers 2009; Gallagher 2007; Saxe 2005, 2009; for an overview
of simulation theory, cf. the entry on folk psychology as mental simulation.)
Traditional versions of simulation theory typically describe simulation using expressions
such as imaginatively putting oneself in the other's place (Gordon 2004). How this
metaphor is understood depends on the specific account. (A collection of papers exploring
various versions of simulation theory can be found in Dokic and Proust, eds. 2002.) On many
accounts, the projection is assumed to involve the subject's imaginatively running mental

processes off-line that are directly analogous to those being run on-line by the target
(e.g. Goldman 1989). Recent empirical work in psychology has explored the accuracy of
such projections (Markman et al eds. 2009, section V; Saxe 2005, 2006, 2009.)
Though classic simulationist accounts have tended to assume that the simulation process is at
least in-principle accessible to consciousness, a number of recent simulation-style accounts
appeal to neuroscientific evidence suggesting that at least some simulative processes take
place completely unconsciously. On such accounts of mindreading, no special role is played
by conscious imagination. (For discussion, see Goldman 2009; Saxe 2009.)
Many contemporary views of mindreading are hybrid theory views according to which both
theorizing and simulation play a role in the understanding of others' mental states. Goldman
(2006), for example, argues that while mindreading is primarily the product of simulation,
theorizing plays a role in certain cases as well. Many recent discussions have endorsed
hybrid views of this sort, with more or less weight given to each of the components in
particular cases. (Cf. Carruthers 2003; Nichols and Stich 2003.)
A number of philosophers have suggested that the mechanisms underlying subjects' capacity
to engage in mindreading are those that enable engagement in pretense behavior (Currie and
Ravenscroft 2002; Goldman 2006; Nichols and Stich 2003; for an overview of recent
discussions, see Carruthers 2009.) According to such accounts, engaging in pretense involves
imaginatively taking up perspectives other than one's own, and the ability to do so skillfully
may rely onand contribute toone's ability to understand those alternate perspectives.
Partly in light of these considerations, the relative lack of spontaneous pretense in children
with autistic spectrum disorders is taken as evidence for a link between the skills of pretense
and empathy (see section 6.2.)

4.2 Imagination, Fiction and Moral


Understanding
Since ancient times, philosophers and others have argued that fiction can play a role in the
moral education of those who imaginatively engage with it through developing of their
abilities to think and act in morally desirable ways. One suggested mechanism for this
process is that fictions allow imaginative acquaintance with unfamiliar moral perspectives
and emotions, and cultivate existing moral understanding and capabilities by directing the
reader's attention in ways that allow that understanding to be applied. Theories along these
lines are endorsed by Carroll 2002, Currie 1995b, Jacobson 1996, Mullin 2004, Nussbaum
1990, and Robinson 2005, and explored throughout the works of Iris Murdoch passim.
Martha Nussbaum maintains that one of the central moral skills is the ability to discern
morally salient features of one's situation. This skill, she contends, is one that must be
developed, and one to which the engagement with literature might effectively contribute by
providing close and careful interpretative descriptions of imagined scenarios that enable

emotional involvement untainted by distorting self-interest (1990, 468). Hakemulder (2000)


reviews some empirical psychological evidence for this hypothesis.
Mark Johnson (1994, Ch. 8) holds a view on which our moral understanding and moral
development are both fundamentally tied to our imaginative abilities. On his account, our
abilities to imagine morally relevant situations and alternatives aids in our moral
understanding, and our moral education consists at least partly in the development of abilities
to imaginatively apply moral concepts to events in our everyday lives.

4.3 Imagination and Reshaping Responses


Another purported role for imagination is in reshaping innate or habitual patterns of
response. I might, for example, believe that snakes are harmless, yet nonetheless find myself
unable to tolerate their presence; or I might believe that male and female students are, on the
whole, equally capable academically, yet nonetheless read the papers of my female students
less charitably. Empirical evidence suggests that engaging in certain types of mental imagery
exercises can mitigate these sorts of unwanted automatic associations, that is, that
imagination, properly deployed, may be a resource for the regulation of behaviors that lie
beyond the range of our immediate rational control. (Historical discussions of this technique
can be found in the entry on Ancient, Medieval, and Renaissance theories of emotions and
on 17th and 18th century theories of emotions; for an overview of some recent work in this
domain, see Gendler 2008b.)
These issues have been explored extensively in work in sports psychology, where researchers
have demonstrated the efficacy of mental imagery practice in domains ranging from table
tennis and golf to kayaking and dart throwing. (For references to studies of the efficacy of
mental imagery in more than forty sports, see Kosslyn and Moulton 2009, 38.)
Mental imagery also plays a central role in a number of therapeutic practices, including
Cognitive Behavioral Therapy (cf. Beck 1993; Ellis 2001.) For further discussion, see
the Stanford Encyclopedia segment on the mental imagery revival.

4.4 Imagination and Counterfactual Reasoning


It has been argued that imagination plays a central role in figuring out what would happen
or what would have happenedhad things been different from how they in fact are or were.
Timothy Williamson, for example, suggests that When we work out what would have
happened if such-and-such had been the case, we frequently cannot do it without imagining
such-and-such to be the case and letting things run. (Williamson 2005, 19; cf. Williamson
2007). On this sort of account, if King Lear thinks to himself, If only I hadn't divided my
kingdom between Regan and Goneril, Cordelia would still be alive, it is Lear's imagining a
relevant situation in which he hadn't divided his kingdom between Regan and Goneril that
allows him to move from the antecedent to the consequent of the counterfactual conditional

that he entertains. Clearly, such contemplation gives access to a suitably circumscribed set of
worlds only if the imaginative exercise is somehow constrained with respect to what is held
constant.
The role of imagination in counterfactual thinkingand, in particular, the question of what
tends to be held constant when subjects contemplate counterfactual scenarioshas been
explored in detail in recent empirical psychological work. In her monograph-length
discussion of the role of imagination in counterfactual reasoning, Ruth Byrne (2005) presents
evidence showing that, when people reason using counterfactuals, what is imagined tends to
fall into certain typical categories. For example, people tend not to imagine worlds with
different natural laws, and they tend to imagine alternatives to more recent as opposed to
earlier events, alternatives to actions as opposed to inactions, and alternatives to events that
were within their control as opposed to events outside of it. (Additional influential work on
this topic can found in Byrne 2005; Johnson-Laird 1983, 2006; Markman et al. 2009, sect.
III; Roese and Olson 1995. )
Such issues may bear on other philosophical work that makes appeal to counterfactual
reasoning, for example, theories of causation, counterfactual conditionals and modality.

4.5 Imagination and Possibility


On one widely-discussed view of the epistemology of modality, conceivability is taken to be
a (prima facie) guide to possibility. (For discussion, see Yablo 1993,). On the simplest
version of this account (which, for reasons discussed below, no one holds), whatever can be
conceived is possible (sometimes called the C-P thesis) and whatever is possible can be
conceived (sometimes called theP-C thesis).,
Possibility in this context is generally understood as metaphysical possibility, where a
proposition is metaphysically possible iff it describes some way things might have been. (Cf.
Gendler & Hawthorne 2002; Fine 2002). Conceivability here is generally taken in a broad
sense, where conceiving is something like the capacity that enables us to represent scenarios
to ourselves using words or concepts or sensory images, scenarios that purport to involve
actual or non-actual things in actual or non-actual configurations (Gendler & Hawthorne
2002, 1; for an overview of some of the distinctions that this characterization brushes over,
see Yablo 1993).
Given these clarifications, it is clear that the P-C thesis is a non-starter, at least without heavy
idealization: the range of metaphysical possibilities certainly outruns the range of
propositions that we ordinary humans can represent to ourselves. But versions of the C-P
thesis, according to which the fact that we can represent P to ourselves provides
(probabilifying or decisive) evidence in favor of P's metaphysical possibility, have played a
central role in a number of traditional and contemporary discussions, particularly in the

context of mind-body dualism (for details, see relevant sections in the SEP entries
on zombies and dualism.)
Descartes famously offered one such modal argument in the Sixth Meditation (CSM II, 54),
reasoning from the fact that he could clearly and distinctly conceive of his mind and body as
distinct to the real distinctness between them. Contemporary advocates of related arguments
details of which can be found in relevant sections in the SEP entries
on zombies and dualisminclude Saul Kripke (1972/80), W.D. Hart (1988), and David
Chalmers (1996, 2002). One form of such argument takes as a premise something implying
or implied by the following:
Zombie-conceivability: It is conceivable that there could be an exact physical duplicate of me
who lacked consciousness.
And, relying on some suitably strong C-P-style principle, concludes from this that:
Zombie-possibility: It is possible that there could be an exact physical duplicate of me who
lacked consciousness.
Both defenders and critics of such modal arguments have suggested that appeal to the notion
ofimaginingas distinct from mere conceivingmay play a role in such arguments'
soundness.
On the defenders' side, David Chalmers has argued that even those who hold that there are
propositions that are not epistemically accessible on the basis of a complete qualitative
description of the world should still accept that what he calls ideal primary positive
conceivability entails what he calls primary possibility. Primary (as opposed
to secondary) possibility concerns the question of whether there is some world W that
makes P true when W is considered as actual. (For a discussion of the relation between this
notion and the notion of metaphysical possibility, see Chalmers 2002.) Ideal (as opposed to
mere prima facie) conceivability concerns the question of whether P is conceivable on ideal
rational reflection. And positive (as opposed to negative) conceivability concerns the
question of whether P is imaginable: to positively conceive of a situation is to in some sense
imagine a specific configuration of objects and properties (Chalmers 2002). According to
Chalmers, then, a certain sort of C-P thesis holds for states of affairs that are conceivable on
reflection in the positive sensethat is, for states of affairs that are, on reflection,
imaginable. (For discussion, see Byrne 2007; Levin 2008; Stoljar 2007; Stalnaker 2002;
Yablo 2002.)
On the critical side, Christopher Hill (Hill 1997; Hill & McLaughlin 1999), following a
suggestion of Thomas Nagel (Nagel 1974, footnote 11), has argued that if we distinguish
properly betweensympathetic imaginingwherein one imagines oneself undergoing a certain
experienceandperceptual imaginingwherein one imagines oneself perceiving a certain
event or state of affairs, then Descartes/Kripke/Chalmers-style modal arguments fail. He

contends that in the Zombie argument, the exact physical duplicate is imagined in one way,
whereas the lacking consciousness is imagined in another: the conceiving that goes on with
respect to the relevant physical features involves perceptual imagination, whereas the
conceiving that goes on with respect to the relevant phenomenal features
involves sympathetic imagination. As a result, the relation between the physical and
phenomenal features will appear contingent even if it is necessary, because of the
independence of the disparate types of imagination (Nagel 1974, footnote 11). So the
argument cannot get off the ground. (Chalmers' response can be found in Chalmers 1999.)
For a comprehensive discussion of the major philosophical positions concerning the relations
among imagination, conceivability and possibility, see the entry on the epistemology of
modality; for related discussion, see relevant sections in the entries on zombies and dualism.
A detailed introduction to the issues in question can be found in Gendler & Hawthorne 2002b
or Evnine 2008; recent papers on this topic can be found at PhilPapers Conceivability,
Imagination and Possibility. See especially Byrne 2007 and Stoljar 2007.

5. Imagination: Puzzles and Problems


Much of the most sophisticated discussion of imagination in recent years has taken place in
the context of the relation between imagination and aesthetic experienceoften focusing on
issues of imaginative engagement with fictional content through literature, theater and
cinema, and visual art.
The subsections below present some of the main issues that have emerged in these
discussions by looking at six sets of puzzles and problems around which a great deal of
discussion has been focused.

5.1 Imagination and Fictionality


When we engage with a fiction, by watching a play or reading a book or viewing a work of
visual art or playing a game of make-believe, we take certain things to be fictional, or true in
that fiction. One way to understand this is to explain what is fictional in terms of what we
imagine or are directed or supposed or intended to imagine.
Influential accounts by Kendall Walton (1990) and Gregory Currie (1990), for instance,
contend that there is an intimate connection between imagination and fictionality. On
Walton's view, what is fictional is what is to be imagined given the conventions governing
the game of make-believe or the world of the story. If you and I are putting on a production
of Twelfth Night and we decide that I'll play Viola and you'll play Sebastian, then we will
have established a convention by which what I say and do is what, in the fiction, Viola says
and does, and what you say and do is what Sebastian says and does. On Walton's account,
this will be the case regardless of whether the members of our audience do in fact imagine

that what I'm saying is what Viola says; what is important is that it isprescribed, by the
conventions of our production, to be imagined that what I say is what Viola says.
On Currie's account, which is similar to Walton's, what is fictional is defined as that which
the author (or actor, or creator) intends the audience to make-believe or imagine. Related
discussion in the context of literature can be found in Lamarque and Olson (1996).
The intimate relationship between imagination and fictionality is illustrated by the puzzle of
imaginative resistance (see Section 5.2). When we resist imagining something, we also tend
to resist accepting it as fictional. And conversely, what we imagine is often (particularly in
the context of art and games of make-believe) what we take to be fictional.
For related considerations in the context of film, see the entry on film. For empirical work in
this area, see the writings of Ed Tan passim (under Other Internet Resources).

5.2 Imaginative Resistance


Imaginative resistance occurs when a subject finds it difficult or problematic to engage in
some sort of prompted imaginative activity. Suppose, for example, that you were confronted
with a variation of Macbeth where the facts of [Duncan's] murder remain as they are in fact
presented in the play, but it is prescribed in this alternate fiction that this was unfortunate
only for having interfered with Macbeth's sleep (Moran 1994). If you found it difficult to
imagine this, even though the author had done everything authors usually do to make such a
story fictionally true, then you would be experiencing imaginative resistance.
While early discussions of imaginative resistance tended to focus on examples (like the one
above) involving morally deviant worlds, it is now widely agreed that this initial
characterization was too restrictive (for partial dissent, see Gendler 2006). In more recent
literature, the term is typically applied to any sort of case where subjects find it unexpectedly
difficult to (bring themselves to) imagine what an author describes, or to accept such a claim
as being true in the story. So, for example, Brian Weatherson (2004) has argued that
resistance puzzles arise not only for normative concepts (including thick and thin moral
concepts, aesthetic judgments, and epistemic evaluations), but also for attributions of mental
states, attributions of content, and claims involving constitution or ontological status.
As Kendall Walton (2006) notes, the questions addressed under the rubric of imaginative
resistance turn out to be a tangled nest of importantly distinct but easily confused puzzles.
Indeed, it has been argued (Weatherson 2004) that there are at least four such puzzles: those
of aesthetic value, phenomenology, fictionality, and imaginability.
In its most general form, the aesthetic value puzzle is the puzzle of why texts that evoke
imaginative resistance are often aesthetically compromised thereby; this puzzle is typically
discussed specifically in the context of morality. (See, for example, Bermdez & Gardner
2003, Gaut 2003, Walton 2006.) The phenomenological puzzle is the puzzle of why passages

that evoke resistance tend to involve a particular phenomenology, described by Gendler as


doubling of the narrator or pop-out (Gendler 2000, 2006). The fictionality puzzle is the
puzzle of why, in certain cases, the default position of authorial authority appears to break
down, so that mere authorial say-so is insufficient to make it the case that something is true
in a story. And the imaginability puzzle is the puzzle of why, in certain cases, readers display
a reluctance or inability to engage in some mandated act of imagining, so that typical
invitations to make-believe are insufficient to bring about the requisite response on the part
of the reader.
The bulk of philosophical discussion has been devotedoften without distinguishing
between themto the puzzles of fictionality and imaginability, with accounts of the
phenomena falling into two main categories.
The first groupsometimes called can't theories (Gendler 2006)trace the puzzles to
features of the fictional world: they maintain that readers are unable to follow the author's
lead because of some problem with the world the author has tried to describe.
Simple can't theories often embrace some sort of impossibility hypothesis, suggesting that
propositions that evoke imaginative resistance are impossible in the context of the stories
where they appear, and that this explains why readers fail to imagine them as true in the
fiction. (For discussion and criticism, see Gendler 2000; Stock 2005; Walton 1994.) Brian
Weatherson (2004) offers a more sophisticated version of a can't theory, suggesting that
resistance puzzles arise in the face of a certain type of impossibility: they arise in cases
where the lower-level facts of the story and the higher-level claims of the author exhibit a
particular kind of incoherence. (See also Yablo 2002.)
The second groupsometimes called won't theoriestrace the puzzles to features of the
actual world: they maintain that readers are unwilling to follow the author's lead because
doing so might lead them to look at the (actual) world in a way that they prefer to avoid
(Gendler 2000, 2006). Advocates of such views tend to stress the distinctive role
of imagination in imaginative resistance, focusing on ways that imagination may implicate
the subject's actual beliefs and desires. (For discussions see Currie 2002; Doggett & Egan
2007; Matravers 2003; Nichols 2006; Stokes 2006.)
A number of recent discussions of resistance-related phenomena draw on work in cognitive
and social psychology, naturalizing the puzzle in ways that partially finesse the can't/won't
distinction. According to architectural accounts, imaginative resistance emerges because
imagination and belief make use of the same cognitive structures, so resistance to
imagining P is to be expected in certain of the cases where we would be resistant to
believing P. (Cf. Nichols (2004); Weinberg and Meskin (2006).)
Other recent work has explored the connections between imaginative resistance, moral
evaluation, moral psychology and moral realism (Driver 2008; Levy 2005; Stokes 2006;
Todd 2009).

5.3 The Paradox of Fictional Emotions


The paradox of fictional emotions arises because certain reactions to fictional scenarios seem
to systematically violate the norm of quarantining (see section 3.1 above), in that subjects
regularly exhibit apparently genuine emotional responses to characters and situations that
they explicitly represent as being merely imaginary. The paradox is typically formulated
using something like the following three conditions (cf. Radford 1975; Gendler &
Kovakovich 2006). Regarding certain fictional characters (and situations) F, it appears to be
simultaneously true that:
a. Response Condition: Subjects experience genuine emotional responses (e.g. pleasure,
fear, pity, sadness) towards F
b. Belief Condition: Subjects believe that F is purely fictional or merely imaginary
c. Coordination Condition: In order to have genuine emotional responses towards a
character (or situation), one must not believe that the character (or situation) is purely
fictional or merely imaginary
Solutions to the paradox generally deny one of the three claims while maintaining the other
two, and are typically classified into three families on the basis of which condition they
reject.
The first family of solutions rejects the Response Condition (a) by denying that subjects have
emotional responses towards imaginary characters and situations. They do so either by
denying that the responses in question are genuine emotions, or by denying that the targets of
these responses are imaginary characters and situations.
The most prominent view in the first subgroup is Walton's (1990) quasi-emotion theory,
according to which what appear to be genuine emotions are, in the context of engagement
with imagined content, nothing more than quasi pretend or fictional emotions. Quasiemotions differ from their actual counterparts both in their source (they are generated by
beliefs about what is fictionally rather than actually true), and, typically, in their behavioral
consequences (though we may pity Ophelia, we make no effort to console her in her sorrow.)
Views in the second subgroup maintain that when we engage with fiction, our emotional
responses are directed not towards the characters or events within the imaginary context, but
rather towards appropriate real-world surrogates for or counterparts of those characters and
events. So, for example, we don't feel sadness for Romeo and Juliet, but rather for people in
the actual world who have led relevantly similar lives. (Cf. Charlton 1984)
A second family of response rejects the Belief Condition (b), denying that the situations and
characters to which subjects have emotional responses are situations and characters that they
believe to be fictional or merely imaginary. Advocates of

such confusionist or illusionist or belief-suspension views maintain that when we engage


emotionally with fictional characters and situations, we temporarily cease to represent them
as imaginary, instead representing them (as the result of some confusion, or an illusion, or a
suspension of disbelief) to be real and mind-independent. Such views have few adherents
among contemporary philosophers (a possible historical advocate is Coleridge 1817) and are
generally discussed only to be subsequently dismissed (cf. Currie 1990; Radford 1975;
Walton 1978; for partial exception in the case of dreaming, see McGinn 2004).
The most popular family to responses rejects the Coordination Condition (c), allowing that it
is possible or permissible to have emotional responses towards a character (or situation) that
one believes to be purely fictional or merely imaginary.
Such non-coordination theories take a number of different forms. Advocates of socalled thought theories argue that it is false to think that, in general, our emotional responses
are directed only towards things that we take to be real. Versions of this sort of theory have
been advanced by, among others, Nol Carroll (1990), Susan Feagin (1996), Peter Lamarque
(1981; 1996), and Richard Moran (1994); objections to the thought theory are explored in
Walton 1990. A recent version of this sort of account makes appeal to the notion
of alief (Gendler 2008a, 2008b, see section 3.3 above), according to which emotional
responses to fictional characters are the result of cognitive mechanisms that are indifferent
between content that is represented as real or as merely imaginary.
A second family of anti-coordination views rejects (c) on empirical grounds. Gendler and
Kovakovich 2005, following Harris 2000 suggest that work done by cognitive
neuroscientists (Damasio 1997, 1999) has shown that emotional engagement with imagined
scenarios is integral to human practical reasoning. Potential decisions are tested out in the
imagination, and are accepted or rejected partly on the basis of emotional reactions to
imagined outcomes. Thus, it is argued, if we could not have genuine emotional responses to
imagined scenariosand by extension fully developed fictionwe would not be able to
engage in practical reasoning. (Related views are explored in Weinberg and Meskin 2006;
Currie 1997.)
Finally, according to irrationalist accounts, although subjects tacitly endorse all three of (a),
(b) and (c) as normative constraints, as a descriptive matter, they violate (c): they have
genuine emotional reactions to fictional characters and events that they believe to be purely
imaginary, while (tacitly) holding that they should have genuine emotional reactions only to
characters and events that they believe to be real. These reactions are thus irrational. (cf.
Radford 1975).
Influential anthologies on the fictional paradoxes include Bermdez & Gardner, eds. 2003;
Hjort & Laver, eds. 1997; Kieran & Lopes, eds. 2003; Nichols, ed. 2006; collections of
essays include Currie 2004; Levinson 1998. Book-length treatments include Carroll 1990;
Currie 1990, 1995a; Feagin 1996; Robinson 2005; Scruton 1974; Walton 1990; see also

Brann 1991. Discussion in this section is indebted to the thorough review found in Neill
2005, as well as in Levinson 1997 and Schneider 2006.

5.4 The Paradox of Tragedy


The paradox of tragedy is closely related to the paradox of fiction. But whereas the former
focuses on an unexpected similarity between our reactions to fiction and reality, the latter
focuses, in additional, on an unexpected difference between them. The paradox of tragedy
takes notice not only of the fact that we seem to experience negative emotions in response to
tragedy in fiction, but also that, while we tend in general to avoid things that evoke negative
emotions in us, we do not tend to avoid fictional tragedies.
Like the paradox of fiction, the paradox of tragedy can be formulated as a conflict among
three mutually inconsistent propositions:
d. Negative Emotion Condition: Tragedy evokes negative emotion in subjects.
e. Negative Avoidance Condition: If something evokes negative emotion in a subject,
then the subject tends to avoid it.
f. Non-Avoidance Condition: Subjects do not tend to avoid tragedy.
There seem to be few grounds for the rejection of the Non-Avoidance Condition (f); it is
undeniable that, at least in some cases, people seek out tragedy. So we will restrict our
discussion to solutions that reject the Negative Emotion (d) or Negative Avoidance (e)
Condition.
Anti-Negative Emotion Condition responses deny thatproperly understoodthe emotion
that tragedy evokes in us is negative. Conversionary explanations suggest that in the context
of an engagement with art, negative emotional responses are convertedas a matter of fact
about how human psychological mechanisms operateinto something positive and pleasant.
This sort of view can be found in Hume's Of Tragedy. Deflationary explanations deny that
we in fact have negative emotional responses to art. One version of such an account is
Walton's (1990) theory of quasi-emotions (see section 5.3 above), according to which artistic
representations do not give rise to genuine emotions.
Anti-Negative Avoidance Condition responses deny that if something evokes negative
emotion in us, we tend to avoid it. These responses take a number of forms. The most blunt
form simply denies (e) outright. Such revisionary explanations argue that, in fact, it is simply
not true that in general we tend to avoid things that induce negative emotional responses in
us (cf. Walton 1990.)Compensatory explanations stress that, although engagement with
tragedy may bring unpleasantness, the reward gleaned from that experience outweighs the
cost of the negative emotional experience. (Cf. Aristotle's Poetics; Carroll 1990.) Closely
related are rich experience explanations, according to which art that is ultimately painful

may nevertheless be valuable because of the richness of experience that it provides (Smuts
2007).
A view that can be understood either as an anti-avoidance view or an anti-negative emotion
view is the control theory explanation (Morreall 1985.) Advocates of such views argue what
explains our relative desire to engage with fictional tragedies is that we have more control
over our experience of fictionswe can get up and leave any time we wantthan we do
over real life. (For criticism, see Yanal 1999.)
For a comprehensive recent overview of responses to the paradox of tragedy, see Smuts
2009.

5.5 The Puzzles of Iteration


An iterated fiction (or pretense) is one that has a fiction (or pretense) embedded within it.
Following Nichols (2003), it is common to speak of two puzzles of iterated fiction,
the puzzle of preserved iteration (also known as the Flash Stockman puzzle (Lewis 1983a))
and the puzzle of collapsed iteration (Currie 1995c). A successful theory of pretense or
imagination must simultaneously account for both puzzles.

The Puzzle of Preserved Iteration


The puzzle of preserved iteration is the puzzle of how it is possible for pretending to pretend
(or imagining that one is imagining) to differ from merely pretending (or imagining).
Suppose, for example, that you are playing one of the rude mechanicals in A Midsummer
Night's Dream, who themselves stage a performance of Pyramus and Thisbe as a play
within a play. In order to do so, you need to pretend to be a character in A Midsummer
Night's Dream pretending to be a character inPyramus and Thisbewithout your pretense
collapsing into your simply pretending to be a character in Pyramus and Thisbe.
David Lewis (1983a), who brought the puzzle to the attention of the Anglo-American
philosophical community (with the story of a singer who pretends to be a lying stockman
pretending to tell the truth) offers no solution to it. Peter Lamarque (1987) has suggested that
a solution can be found in the nature of pretense itself: pretense has particular features, which
are mimicked in cases of pretending to pretend. Shaun Nichols (2003) contends that this
solution is insufficiently general, since there are parallel cases of iteration that do not involve
pretense: I might imagine imagining that I see a dagger, and this is different from imagining
that I see a dagger.
Nichols suggests instead that the phenomenon can be accounted for by appeal to the
cognitive theory of pretense advanced in Nichols and Stich (2000). On this account, our
mental architecture contains not only a belief box in which believed content is storedit
also contains a pretense box for holding imagined or pretended content. Nichols maintains
that the pretence box account provides a general solution to the puzzle of preserved

iteration. To imagine about imaginings is to have a representation in one's pretence box that
attributes imagining (Nichols 2003).

The Puzzle of Collapsed Iteration


The puzzle of collapsed iteration is the puzzle of how it is possible for pretending to pretend
tocollapse into merely pretending.
Consider The Taming of the Shrew which, for almost the entirety of the main plot, is framed
as a performance for a drunkard. Here, audiences will typically watch the play, not as a play
within a play, but as having one level of pretense, and those playing Bianca and Katherina
will (typically) be pretending to be Bianca and Katherina, not pretending to be actors
pretending to be Bianca and Katherina.
Greg Currie (1995c) who raises the puzzle, suggests that collapsed iteration may result from
limitations in our cognitive resources; on his account, imagining imagining requires a
simulation of a simulationa capacity that human beings may simply lack. Nichols (2003)
counters that such an account makes it difficult to explain how, in some cases (as above),
iteration is preserved. Instead, he suggests, in some cases of imagining we relocate
ourselves into the position of another person, imagining what they imagine (resulting in
collapsed iteration), while in others, we do not engage in such relocation (resulting in
preserved iteration.)
The puzzle of collapsed iteration provides a useful foil for thinking about the relation
between imagination and belief. While in imagining that you imagine something I might end
up thereby imagining what you imagine, I will not come to believe what you believe simply
by coming to believe that you believe it. (Cf. Currie 1995c, 161)

5.6 Visualizing the Unseen (Berkeley's Puzzle)


In its original form, Berkeley's Puzzle is presented as a puzzle about the possibility of
conceiving of something neither perceived nor thought of, or, as Winkler (1989) suggests, as
a puzzle of how it could be that an idea in the mind represents the mind-independence of
what is represented. In the context of imagination, attention has been given to a special case
of the puzzle, namely, whether it is possible to visualize the unseen.
The original puzzle, often referred to as the Master Argument, is found in both
Berkeley'sPrinciples (sect. 23) and his Three Dialogues. In the Dialogues Hylas, challenged
by Philonous to conceive of the unperceived, finds that he is unable to do so:
Hylas: [] As I was thinking of a tree in a solitary place, where no one was present to see it,
methought that was to conceive a tree as existing unperceived or unthought of, not
considering that I myself conceived it all the while. But now I plainly see, that all I can do is
to frame ideas in my own mind. I may indeed conceive in my own thoughts the idea of a tree,

or a house, or a mountain, but that is all. And this is far from proving, that I can conceive
them existing out of the minds of all spirits. (First Dialogue between Hylas and Philonous)
The notion of conception assumed here seems tied closely to mental imagery: it appears that
what Hylas sets out to do is to visually imagine an unperceived tree; in so doing, he
constructs a visual image of a tree, thereby rendering it conceived. A number of philosophers,
including Bernard Williams (1973), have dismissed the argument as incapable of achieving
its stated goal on the grounds that it fails to distinguish between conceiving of something and
visually imagining it. John Campbell points out that one can, for example, describe in writing
an unseen tree (Campbell 2002, 128; contra Williams, Campbell argues that there is
something importantly correct in Berkeley's challenge with respect to conceivability).
According to Williams, the more interesting challenge raised by Berkeley's puzzle concerns
whether one can visualize the unseen. It might seem that, almost trivially, one cannot
visualize an unseen object, in virtue of the apparent fact that to visualize, say, a tree is to
think of oneself as seeing a tree, and I can hardly think of myself as seeing a tree that is
unseen. Against this view Williams argues that even if to visualize a tree is to think of myself
as seeing a tree, nevertheless I need not include my seeing in what is visualized. In cinema
and theater, it need not be true in the fiction that the camera or audience sees what the scene
contains, so too, Williams argues, even though I can visualize my seeing a tree such that my
seeing is part of what is visualized, I can also visualize a tree without doing so, and therefore
can visualize an unseen tree (Williams 1973).
Against Williams' arguments, Christopher Peacocke has defended the view that one cannot
visually imagine the unperceived, on the grounds that the content of what one imagines may
contain more than what is depicted in the image (Peacocke 1985). To make this point
Peacocke introduces the notion of S-imagination, with the S standing for supposition
(25). S-imagined content is supposed to account for the difference between visually
imagining, say, a briefcase, and visually imagining a cat that is wholly obscured by a
briefcase; though they share imagistic content, they differ in S-imagined content. Peacocke
acknowledges that in visually imagining a tree it may not be part of what is visualized that it
is being seen, but, he argues, that the tree is seen will inescapably be part of what is Simagined. (Note that Peacocke's use of the term S-imagine differs from Goldman's notion
of the same name (see Section 2.4 above.))
For additional discussions of Berkeley's puzzle, see Walton 1990, 2379; cf. also Szab
2005. Further discussion of Berkeley's master argument and its role in his philosophical
program can be found in the entry on Berkeley (sect. 2.2.1).

6. Empirical Work on Imagination

6.1 Developmental Work on the Origins of


Pretense
By the age of 15 months, typically developing children are capable of engaging in primitive
games of make-believeacting, for instance, as if a piece of cloth or coat collar were their
special bedtime pillow. (Instances of unconscious symbolic representation may occur much
earliersee Piaget 1945/1962, 96 and chapters 6 and 7.) By 18 months, many children show
signs of tracking rather elaborate games of pretense initiated by othersfor instance, being
able to identify which of two dolls that have been washed by an adult experimenter is still
wet and engaging in the requisite drying activity (Walker-Andrews and Kahana-Kelman
1997). By 22 months, these skills become quite widespread (Harris 2000, chapter 2; Harris
and Kavanaugh 1993), and by 2428 months, most children are able to participate fully in
such gamesfor example, pouring tea for a stuffed cow from an empty plastic teapot,
feeding a toy pig some cereal from an empty bowl, giving a toy monkey a banana when
there are no (real) bananas in sight, and so on (Harris 1994; Harris 2000, chapter 2; WalkerAndrews and Kahana-Kelman 1997).
Around this same age (2428 months), children show themselves readily able to generalize
on the basis of others's pretend stipulationsif they are told, for instance, that a particular
yellow block represents a banana and a particular red block represents a cookie, they require
no further prompting to engage in a pretense where yellow blocks in general represent
bananas, and red blocks in general represent cookies (Harris 2000, chapter 2 reporting Harris
& Kavanaugh 1993; Walton 1990). They show themselves readily able to suspend such
stipulations as soon as a new episode of pretense beginsthe bricks that represent bananas
or sandwiches in one game can without difficulty come to represent bars of soap or pillows
in the next game. (Skolnick and Bloom 2006a, 2006b) They show themselves ready to credit
imaginary objects with causal powers much like those of their real-world analoguesif
Teddy eats one of the (wooden brick) bananas, he will no longer be hungry; if he is bathed in
a (cardboard-box) bathtub, he will emerge wet (Harris 2000). And they are ready to describe
situations from the perspective of the imaginary worldwhen asked to express what
happened after (literally) an experimenter holds a stuffed animal in such a way that the
animal's paws grip an empty plastic teapot and hold the teapot above the head of some other
stuffed animal, children are happy to report the event as: Teddy poured tea on Monkey's
head or Monkey's all wethe's got tea on his head (cf. Harris 2000).
During the year that follows, most children develop the capacity to engage in complex
coordinated games of joint pretense with others (Perner et al 1994, 264). And well before the
age of four, they have figured out how to keep track of different individuals simultaneously
engaging in different games of pretenserecognizing, for instance, that if you pretend the
pebbles are pears and I pretend the pebbles are cherries, you will be baking a pear cake while
I bake a cherry cake (Perner at al 1994, 264).

These capacities are accompanied by a parallel conscious capacity to keep track of what is
pretend, and what is not. Even children as young as 15 months show few signs of what Alan
Leslie has termed representational abuse, that is, there is little indication that the child
comes overtly to believe that actual-world objects have or will come to have features of the
pretend objects that they serve to represent (Leslie 1987). By the age of 3, children are able
to articulate explicitly a number of the differences between real and pretendnoting, for
instance, that a child with a real dog will be able to see and pet the dog, whereas a child with
a pretend dog will not (Estes, Wellman and Wooley 1989; Harris 2000, chapters 2 and 4;
Wellman and Estes 1986; see also Bouldin and Pratt 2001 and references therein).
In recent years, there has been intense debate among psychologists concerning exactly what
this capacity for pretense amounts to, in light of the fact that children of this age are (a)
generally incapable of solving standard (Smarties-box) false-belief tasks (though see
Onishi and Baillargeon 2005); (b) fairly limited in their capacity to distinguish apparent from
real identity in the case of visually deceptive objects; and (c) generally willing to attribute the
behavior pretending to be an X to an individual unaware of the existence of Xs. For further
discussion, see Harris 2000, chapter 3 and the papers collected in Goswami ed. 2002; Lewis
and Mitchell ed. 1994; Mitchell ed. 2003.

6.2 Imagination and Autism


Individuals with autism typically display a trio of impairments often referred to as Wing's
triad: problems in social competence, communication, and imagination (Happ 1994; Wing
and Gould 1979).
Imagination: Children with autism do not engage in spontaneous pretend play in the ways
that typically-developing children do, engaging instead in repetitive and sometimes
obsessional activities. Adults with autism often show little interest in fiction. (Carpenter,
Tomasello, and Striano 2005; Happ 1994; Rogers, Cook, and Meryl 2005; Wing and Gould
1979).
Communication: Autism is often characterized by a delay or lack of development in speech, a
failure to respond to the speech of others and to initiate or sustain normal conversation, a
tendency towards pronoun reversal (I for you), and abnormalities in prosody and nonverbal communication.(Happ 1994).
Social Competence: Children with autism often display an inability to share and direct
attention, to engage in imitation, and to recognize affect (Happ 1994). Autistic individuals
often display difficulty in understanding and interpreting the mental states of others (BaronCohen et al. 1985) and in collaborating with others on shared intentions and goals
(Tomasello et al. 2005). For these reasons, autism is often understood as involving a deficit
in subjects' theory of mind or mindreading skill. (See section 4.1, above).

While the degree to which theory of mind enlists imaginative faculties is a matter of
considerable debate, as is the matter of what autistic spectrum disorders can tell us about that
debate, some have suggested that autism's characteristic deficits might provide evidence for
the simulation theory of mind reading (e.g. Goldman 2006; for dissent see Carruthers 2009
and discussion therein.) More radically, Currie and Ravenscroft (2002) have suggested that
autism is itself a disorder of the imagination, arguing that an inability to engage in
imaginative activities could uniformly explain the constellation of Wing's deficits.

6.3 Imagination and Delusions


Delusions can be characterized, roughly, as belief-like mental representations that manifest
an unusual degree of disconnectedness from reality, and cover a range of phenomena.
Particularly striking examples would include Capgras and Cotard delusions. In the former,
the sufferer takes her friends and family to have been replaced by imposters; in the latter, the
sufferer takes himself to be dead. More mundane examples might include cases that are
closer to what would typically be called self-deceitthinking of oneself as a great friend or a
great beauty, when all evidence points to the contrary.
A natural way to characterize delusions is as beliefs that are in some way dysfunctional,
either in their content or formation. (For a representative collection of papers that present and
criticize this perspective, see Coltheart and Davies ed. 2000). Currie and Ravenscroft (2002:
170175), however, have argued that delusions are often disorders of the imagination.
Specifically, they argue that delusions are imaginings that are misidentified by the subject as
the result of an inability to keep track of the sources of one's thoughts. A delusion, on this
view, is an imagined representation that is misidentified by the subject as a belief.
A different theory, but also one on which delusions and self-deceptions are the result of
imagination or pretense, has been offered by Gendler (2007). In contrast to Currie and
Ravenscroft, Gendler argues not that the self-deceived subject misidentifies imaginings as
beliefs, but that, in certain cases, imaginings can come to play a role in one's cognitive
economy similar to that typically played by beliefs. This view emphasizes the ways in which
the line between imagination and belief may be difficult to discern in some cases.
Andy Egan (2008) likewise argues that delusions should be understood as bimaginations,
that is, as something in between belief and imagination. Like Currie and Ravenscroft and
Gendler, Egan focuses on the fact that delusions are similar in certain ways to both
imaginings and to beliefs, in that, like beliefs, they guide certain aspects of a person's
behavior and inferences, but, like imaginings, their range is circumscribed. (Cf. section 2.2).
Schizophrenia is a complex pathology that may involve, among its many signs and
symptoms, severe delusions and hallucinations. Although the nature and causes of the
disorder are a matter of controversy (see Harrison 2005 for a review of the neurological data;
cf. also Frith 1992; for representative philosophical discussion, see Campbell 1999;

Carruthers 2009; Gallagher 2004; Langdon, Davies and Coltheart 2002; Zahavi ed. 2000). It
has been suggested by Currie (2000) and Currie and Ravenscroft (2002, 170) that
schizophrenia and its attendant hallucinations might be understood as fundamentally
involving a deficit in the subject's ability to distinguish between what is real and what is
merely imagined.

6.4 Recent Cognitive and Social Psychological


Work on Imagination
Recent empirical work on imagination and mental simulation has been focused in four main
areas: (1) the relation between imagination and memory, with particular attention to the topic
of false memory; (2) the role of imagination in the mental simulation of action and
behavior; (3) the role of imagination in enabling empathy and perspective taking; and (4) the
role of imagination in counterfactual reasoning, and in planning for the future.
Regarding the first (the relation between imagination and memory), a sizable literature has
been devoted to the phenomenon of imagination inflation (Garry et al. 1996; Goff and
Roediger 1998), whereby imagining an event can cause a subject to remember having
experienced it. (For a more general discussion of intrusion errors of this kind, see Loftus
1979 and Fiedler et al. 1996). An overview of recent discussions of this topic can be found in
Bernstein et al 2009.
Regarding the second (the role of imagination in the mental simulation of action and
behavior), work by Jean Decety (Decety and Stevens 2009), Marc Jeannerod (Jeannerod
2006, 1997), and others suggests that simulated or imagined action activates the same
cortical structures that are responsible for motor execution (Markman et al. 2009, viii). The
implications of this overlap have been a central topic in discussions of, among others,
implicit memory and learning (Kosslyn and Moulton 2009), imitation (Hurley and Chater,
eds. 2005; Meltzoff and Prinz, eds. 2002), and social understanding (Decety and Stevens
2009; Goldman 2006; Rizzolatti and Sinigaglia 2008).
Regarding the third (the role of imagination in enabling empathy and perspective taking), in
addition to the work just mentioned, a sizable research program has been devoted to
exploring the general issue of the role played by imagination in empathy, perspective taking,
and the theory of mind. An overview of some of this work can be found in the essays that
appear in Markman 2009, section V.
Regarding the fourth (the role of imagination in counterfactual reasoning and planning for
the future), systematic treatments have been offered of the general structures that appear to
govern human counterfactual thinking; the influence of past-directed counterfactual thinking
on creativity, emotion, problem-solving and motivation; and the role of simulation in
planning and preparing for future contingencies. (For an overview of these issues, see the
essays collected in Markman 2009, sections III and VI, and references therein.)

Bibliography

Aristotle, Poetics, in The Complete Works of Aristotle, Volumes I and II, J. Barnes
(ed.), Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984.

Baron-Cohen, S., 1997, Mindblindness: An Essay on Autism and Theory of Mind,


Cambridge: MIT Press.

Baron-Cohen, S., A. Leslie, and U. Frith, 1985, Does the Autistic Child Have a
Theory of Mind? Cognition, 21: 3746.

Beck, A., 1993, Cognitive Therapy and the Emotional Disorders, New York: Penguin.

Berkeley, G., 1712, Of The Principles of Human Knowledge: Part I, in The Works of
George Berkeley, Bishop of Cloyne, vol. 2, A. A. Luce and T. E. Jessop (eds.), pp. 41113,
19481957.

, 1713, Three Dialogues Between Hylas and Philonous, in The Works of Georger
Berkeley, Bishop of Cloyne, vol. 2, A. A. Luce and T. E. Jessop (eds.), pp. 163263, 1948
1957.

Bermdez , J. L., and S. Gardner (eds.), 2003, Art and Morality, London: Routledge.

Bernstein, D. M., R. D. Godfrey, and E. F. Loftus, 2009, False Memories: The Role
of Plausibility and Autobiographical Belief, in Markman et al. 2009, 89102.

Block, N. (ed.), 1981, Imagery, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.


Block, N. and Stalnaker, R. 1999. Conceptual Analysis, Dualism, and the
Explanatory Gap,Philosophical Review, 108: 146.
Boden, M., 2003, The Creative Mind: Myths and Mechanisms, London: Routledge.
Bouldin, P., and C. Pratt, 2001, The Ability of Children with Imaginary Companions
to Differentiate between Fantasy and Reality, British Journal of Developmental Psychology,
19: 99114.

Brann, E. T. H., 1991, The World of the Imagination, Rowman & Littlefield.

Budd, M., 1989, Wittgenstein's Philosophy of Psychology, London: Routledge.

Byrne, A., 2007, Possibility and Imagination. Philosophical Perspectives, 21


(1):125144.

Byrne, R., 2005, The Rational Imagination, MIT Press.


Campbell, J., 1999, Schizophrenia, The Space of Reasons, and Thinking as a Motor
Process,Monist, 82: 60925.

Campbell, J., 2002, Berkeley's Puzzle, in Gendler and Hawthorne 2002, pp. 127
44.

Carpenter, M., M. Tomasello, and T. Striano, 2005, Role Reversal Imitation and
Language in Typically-Developing Infants and Children with Autism, Infancy, 8: 25378.
Carroll, N., 1990, The Philosophy of Horror, New York: Routledge.

, 2002, The Wheel of Virtue: Art, Narrative and Moral Knowledge, Journal of
Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 60(1): 326.

Carruthers, P., 2003. Review of Recreative Minds, by G. Currie and I.


Ravenscroft, Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews, 11 (12). [Available online]

, 2007, The Creative-Action Theory of Creativity, in The Innate Mind:


Foundations and the Future, P. Carruthers, S. Lawrence, and S. Stich (eds.), Oxford: Oxford
University Press.

, 2009, How We Know our Own Minds: The Relationship between Mindreading
and Metacognition, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 32(2): 12138.

Carruthers, P. and P. K. Smith (eds.), 1996, Theories of Theories of Mind, Cambridge:


Cambridge University Press.

Casey, E., 2000, Imagining: A Phenomenological Study, 2nd ed., Bloomington: Indiana
University Press.

Chalmers, D., 1996, The Conscious Mind, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

, 1999. Materialism and the metaphysics of modality. Philosophy and


Phenomenological Research 59:47396.

, 2002, Does Conceivability Entail Possibility? in Gendler and Hawthorne (eds.)


2002, pp. 145200.

Charlton, W., 1970, Aesthetics, London: Hutchinson University Library.

, 1984, Feeling for the Fictitious, British Journal of Aesthetics, 24(3): 20616.

Coleridge, S. T., 1907, Biographia Literaria, J. Shawcross (ed.), Oxford: Oxford


University Press.

Coltheart, M., and M. Davies (eds.), 2000, Pathologies of Belief, Wiley-Blackwell.

Csikszentmihalyi, M., 1997, Creativity: Flow and the Psychology of Discovery and
Invention, Perennial Books.

Currie, G., 1990, The Nature of Fiction, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

,1995a, Image and Mind: Film, Philosophy and Cognitive Science, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.

, 1995b, The Moral Psychology of Fiction, Australasian Journal of Philosophy,


(73)2: 250259.

, 1995c, Imagination as Simulation: Aesthetics Meets Cognitive Science, in


Davies and Stone 1995b.

, 2000, Imagination, Delusion, and Hallucinations, in Coltheart and Davies


2000, pp.167182.

, 2002, Desire in Imagination, in Gendler and Hawthorne 2002, pp. 201221.

, 2004, Arts and Minds, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Currie, G., and I. Ravenscroft, 2002, Recreative Minds: Imagination in Philosophy


and Psychology, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Damasio, A. R., 1997, Descartes' Error, New York: Grosset/Putnam.

, 1999, The Feeling of What Happens, New York: Harcourt.

Davies, M. and T. Stone (eds.), 1995a, Folk Psychology: The Theory of Mind Debate,
Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
(eds.), 1995b, Mental Simulation, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

Decety, J., and J. A. Stevens, 2009, Action Representation and Its Role in Social
Interaction, in Markman et al. 2009, pp. 320.

Dennett, D., and R. McKay, 2009, The Evolution of Misbelief, Behavioral and
Brain Sciences, 32: 493510.

Doggett, T., and A. Egan, 2007, Wanting Things You Don't Want: The Case for an
Imaginative Analogue of Desire, Philosophers' Imprint, 7(9). [Available online].

Dokic, J. and J. Proust (eds.), 2002, Simulation and Knowledge of Action, (Series:
Advances in Consciousness Research, Volume 45), John Benjamins.

Driver, J., 2008, Imaginative Resistance and Psychological Necessity, Social


Philosophy and Policy, 25(1): 301313.

Egan, A., 2008, Imagination, Delusion, and Self-Deception, in Delusion and SelfDeception: Affective Influences on Belief-formation, Bayne and Fernandez (eds.),
Psychology Press, pp.263280.

Ellis, A., 2001, Overcoming Destructive Beliefs, Feelings, and Behaviors: New
Directions for Rational Emotive Behavior Therapy, Prometheus Books.

Ellman, S. J., and J. S. Antrobus, The Mind in Sleep: Psychology and


Psychophysiology, 2nd ed., Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley & Sons.

Estes, D., H. Wellman, and J. Wooley, 1989, Children's Understanding of Mental


Phenomena, in Reese 1989, pp. 4187.

Evnine, S., 2008, Modal Epistemology: Our Knowledge of Necessity and


Possibility, Philosophy Compass, 3/4 (2008): 664684, 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2008.00147.x

Farah, M., 1999, The Cognitive Neuroscience of Vision, Basil Blackwell.

Feagin, S., 1996, Reading With Feeling: The Aesthetics of Appreciation, Ithaca:
Cornell University Press.

Fiedler, K., E. Walther, T. Armbruster, D. Fay, and U. Naumann, 1996, Do You


Really Know What You Have Seen? Intrusion Errors and Pressuposition Effects on
Constructive Memory,Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 32(5): 484511.

Fine, K., 2002. The Varieties of Necessity in Gendler and Hawthorne 2002a: 253
281.Fodor, J., 1975, The Language of Thought, Cambridge: Harvard.

Flavell, J.H. 1999, Cognitive Development: Children's Knowledge About the


Mind, Annual Review of Psychology, 50: 2145.

Frith, C. D., 1992, The Cognitive Neuropsychology of Schizophrenia, Hillsdale:


Erlbaum.

Frith, U., 1992, Autism: Explaining the Enigma, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

Funkhouser, E., and S. Spaulding, 2009, Imagination and Other


Scripts, Philosophical Studies, 143(3): 291314.

Gallagher, S., 2004, Neurocognitive Models of Schizophrenia: A


Neurophenomenological Critique, Psychopathology, 37: 819.

Gallagher, S., 2007, Simulation Trouble, Social Neuroscience, 2(34): 35365.

Garry, M., C. G. Manning, E. F. Loftus, and S. J. Sherman, 1996, Imagination


Inflation: Imagining a Childhood Event Inflates Confidence That It Occurred, Psychonomic
Bulletin & Review, 3(2): 20814.

Gaut, B. and P. Livingston (eds.), 2003, The Creation of Art, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.

Gendler, T. S., 2000, The Puzzle of Imaginative Resistance, Journal of Philosophy,


97(2): 5581.

, 2003, On the Relation between Pretence and Belief, in Kieran and Lopes 2003,
pp. 12541.

, 2006. Imaginative Resistance Revisited, Nichols 2006, pp. 149173.

, 2007, Self-Deception as Pretense, Philosophical Perspectives: Philosophy of


Mind.

, 2008a, Alief and Belief, Journal of Philosophy, 105(10).

, 2008b, Alief in Action (and Reaction), Mind and Language, 23(5): 55285.

, 2009, Imaginative Resistance, in A Companion to Aesthetics (2nd ed.), S.


Davies, K. Higgins, R. Hopkins, and B. Stecker (eds.), John Wiley and Sons.

Gendler, T. S., and J. Hawthorne (eds.), 2002a, Conceivability and Possibility, New
York: Oxford University Press.

, 2002b. Introduction, in Gendler and Hawthorne 2002a.

Gendler, T. S., and K. Kovakovich, 2006, Genuine Rational Fictional Emotions, in


Kieran 2006, pp. 24153.

Goff, L. M., and H. L. Roediger, III, 1998, Imagination Inflation for Action Events:
Repeated Imaginings Lead to Illusory Recollections, Memory and Cognition, 26(1): 2033.

Goldman, A., 1989, Interpretation Psychologized, Mind and Language, 4: 161185;


reprinted in Davies and Stone 1995a.

, 2000, The Mentalizing Folk, in D. Sperber (ed.), Metarepresentation,


Vancouver Series in Cognitive Science, New York: Oxford University Press.

, 2006, Simulating Minds, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

, 2009, Prcis of Simulating Minds: The Philosophy, Psychology, and


Neuroscience of Mindreading, Philosophical Studies, 144(3): 431434.

Gordon, R., 1986. Folk Psychology as Simulation, Mind and Language, 1: 158
171; reprinted in Davies and Stone 1995a.

, 2004, Folk Psychology as Mental Simulation, The Stanford Encyclopedia of


Philosophy (Fall 2004 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL =
<http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/folkpsych-simulation/>.

Hakemulder, F. J., 2000, The Moral Laboratory: Experiments Examining The effects
of Reading Literature on Social Perception and Moral Self-knowledge, Amsterdam:
Benjamins.

Happ, F., 1994, Autism: An Introduction to Psychological Theory, London: UCL


Press.

Harris, P. L., 1994, Understanding Pretense, in Lewis and Mitchell 1994, pp. 235
59.

, 2000, The Work of the Imagination, Oxford: Blackwell.

Harris, P. L., and R. D. Kavanaugh, 1993, Young Children's Understanding of


Pretense,Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development, 58(1): serial no.
231.

Harris, P. L., A. Lillard, and J. Perner, 1994, Commentary: Triangulating Pretence


and Belief, in Lewis and Mitchell 1994, pp. 287293.

Harrison, P. J., 2005, Neuropathology of Schizophrenia, Psychiatry, 4(10): 1821.

Hart, W. D., 1988, The Engines of the Soul, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Heal, J., 1986, Replication and Functionalism, in Language, Mind, and Logic, J.
Butterfield (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; reprinted in Davies and Stone
1995a.

2003, Mind, Reason and Imagination: Selected Essays in Philosophy of Mind and
Language, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Hill, C. S. 1997. Imaginability, Conceivability, Possibility and the Mind-Body


Problem,Philosophical Studies, 87: 6185.

Hill, C. S. and McLaughlin, B. P. 1999. There are Fewer Things in Reality Than are
Dreamt of in Chalmers's Philosophy, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 59: 445
454.

Hjort, M., and S. Laver (eds.), 1997, Emotion and the Arts, Oxford: Oxford
Unviersity Press.

Hume, D., 18741875, Of Tragedy, in The Philosophical Workds of David Hume,


vol. 3, T. H. Green and T. H. Gross (eds.), London: Longman, Green.

Hurley, S. L., and N. Chater (eds.), 2005, Perspectives on Imitation: From


Neuroscience to Social Science, Cambridge: MIT Press.

Ichikawa, J., 2008, Skepticism and the imagination model of


dreaming, Philosophical Quarterly, 58(232): 519527.

Ichikawa, J., 2009, Dreaming and Imagination, Mind and Language, 24(1): 10321.
Jacobson, D., 1996, Sir Philip Sydney's Dilemma: On the Ethical Function of
Narrative Art, The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 54: 32736.

Jeannerod, M., 1997, The Cognitive Neuroscience of Action, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

, 2006, Motor Cognition: What Actions Tell to the Self, Oxford: Oxford University
Press.

Johnson, M., 1994, Moral Imagination: Implications of Cognitive Science for Ethics,
University of Chicago Press.

Johnson-Laird, P.N., 1983, Mental Models, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

, 2006, How We Reason, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Kieran, M. (ed.), 2006, Contemporary Debates in Aesthetics and the Philosophy of


Art, Oxford: Blackwell.

Kieran, M., and D.M. Lopes (eds.), 2003, Imagination, Philosophy, and the Arts,
London: Routledge.

Kind, A. 2001. Putting the Image Back in Imagination, Philosophy and


Phenomenological Research, 62: 85109.

Klinger, E., 2009, Daydreaming and Fantasizing: Thought Flow and Motivation, in
Markman et al. 2009, pp. 22540.

Kosslyn, S.M., 1980, Image and Mind, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Kosslyn, S. M., 1994, Image and Brain: The Resolution of the Imagery Debate,
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Kosslyn, S. M., and S. T. Moulton, 2009, Mental Imagery and Implicit Memory, in
Markman et al. 2009, pp. 3552.

Kosslyn, S.M., W. L. Thompson, and G. Ganis, 2006, The Case for Mental Imagery,
Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Kripke, S., 1972/1980, Naming and Necessity, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Lamarque, P., 1981, How Can We Fear and Pity Fictions? British Journal of
Aesthetics, 21(4): 291304.

, 1987, The Puzzle of the Flash Stockman: A Reply to David Lewis, Analysis,
47(2): 9395.

, 1996, Fictional Points of View, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

Lamarque, P. and S. H. Olsen, (repr. 1996), Truth, Fiction, and Literature: A


Philosophical Perspective, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Langdon, R., M. Davies, and M. Coltheart, 2002, Understanding Minds and


Understanding Communicated Meanings in Schizophrenia, Mind and Language, 17(12):
68104.

Lee-Chiong, T. L., 2006, Sleep: A Comprehensive Handbook, Hoboken, NJ: John


Wiley & Sons.

Leslie, A., 1987, Pretense and Representation: The Origins of Theory of


Mind, Psychological Review, 94(4): 41226.

, 1994, Pretending and Believing: Issues in the Theory of ToMM, Cognition,


50(13): 21138.

Levinson, J., 1997, Emotions in Response to Art: A Survey of the Terrain, in Hjort
and Laver 1997.

, 1998, Aesthetics and Ethics: Essays at the Intersection, Cambridge University


Press.

Levin, J. 2008, Taking Type-B Materialism Seriously. Mind & Language, 23 (4):
402425.

Levy, N., 2005, Imaginative Resistance and the Moral/Conventional


Distinction, Philosophical Psychology, 18(2): 231241.

Lewis, D., 1983a, Postscript to Truth In Fiction, in Philosophical Papers, v.1, pp.
27980.

, 1983b, Truth in Fiction, in Philosophical Papers, v.1, pp. 26180.

Lewis, C., and P. Mitchell (eds.), 1994, Children's Early Understanding of Mind,
Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.

Lillard, A., 1993, Young Children's Conceptualization of Pretend: Action or Mental


Representation State? Child Development, 64: 37286.

, 1994, Making Sense of Pretence, in Lewis and Mitchell 1994, 21134.

Loftus, E., 1979, Eyewitness Testimony, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Lopes, D., and M. Kieran (eds.), 2003, Imagination, Philosophy, and the Arts,
London: Routledge.

Markman, K.D., W.M.P. Klein, and J.A. Suhr (eds.), 2009, Handbook of Imagination
and Mental Simulation, New York: Taylor & Francis.

Martin, M. G. F., 2002, The Transparency of Experience, Mind and Language, 4(4):
376425.

Matravers, D., 2003, Fictional Assent and the (So-Called) Puzzle of Imaginative
Resistance, in Kieran and Lopes 2003, pp. 91106.

, 2006, The Challenge of Irrationalism, and How Not to Meet It, in Kieran
2006, pp. 25464.

McGinn, C., 2004, Mindsight: Image, Dream, Meaning. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.

Meltzoff, A. N., and W. Prinz (eds.), 2002, The Imitative Mind: Development,
Evolution, and Brain Bases, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Moran, R., 1994, The Expression of Feeling in Imagination, Philosophical Review,


103(1): 75106.

Morreall, J., 1985, Enjoying Negative Emotions in Fiction, Philosophy and


Literature, 9(1): 95103.

Mullin, A., 2004, Moral Defects, Aesthetic Defects, and the Imagination, Journal of
Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 62(3): 24961.

Nagel, T. 1974. What Is It Like To Be A Bat? Philosophical Review, 83: 43550.

Neill, A., 1993, Fiction and the Emotions, American Philosophical Quarterly,
30(1): 113.

, 2005, Art and Emotion, in The Oxford Handbook of Aesthetics, J. Levinson


(ed.), New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 421435.

Nichols, S., 2003, Imagination and the Puzzles of Iteration, Analysis, 63(3): 182
87.

, 2004, Imagining and Believing: The Promise of a Single Code, The Journal of
Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 62(2): 129139.

, 2006, Just the Imagination: Why Imagining Doesn't Behave Like


Believing, Mind & Language, 21: 459474.

(ed.), 2006, The Architecture of the Imagination: New Essays on Pretense,


Possibility, and Fiction, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Nichols S., and S. Stich, 2000, A Cognitive Theory of Pretense, Cognition, 74(2):
115147.

, 2003, Mindreading: An Integrated Account of Pretense, Self-awareness and


Understanding Other Minds, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Noordhof, P., 2002, Imagining Objects and Imagining Experiences, Mind and
Language, 17(4): 42655.

Nussbaum, M., 1990. Love's Knowledge, Oxford: Oxford University Press.


O'Brien, L., 2005, Imagination and the Motivational Role of Belief, Analysis,
65(285): 5562.

O'Shaughnessy, Brian, 2000, Consciousness and the World, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Peacocke, C., 1985, Imagination, Experience, and Possibility, in Essays on
Berkeley, J. Foster and H. Robinson (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Perner, J, 1991, Understanding the Representational Mind, Cambridge: MIT Press.

Perner, J., S. Baker, and D. Hutton, 1994, Prelief: The Conceptual Origins of Belief
and Pretense, in Lewis and Mitchell 1994, pp. 261286.

Piaget, J., 1945/1962, Play, Dreams, and Imitation in Childhood, C. Gattegno and F.
M. Hodgson (trans.), New York: Norton.

Putnam, H., 1981, Reason, Truth and History, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.

Pylyshyn, Z.W., 1973, What the Mind's Eye Tells the Mind's Brain: A Critique of
Mental Imagery, Psychological Bulletin, 80: 125.

Pylyshyn, Z.W., 2002, Mental Imagery: In search of a theory, Behavioral and Brain
Sciences, 25: 157182.
Pylyshyn, Z.W., 2003, Seeing and Visualizing, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Radford, C., 1975, How Can We Be Moved by the Fate of Anna


Karenina? Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, supp. vol. 49: 6780.

Rakoczy, H., M. Tomasello, and T. Striano, 2004 Young children know that trying is
not pretending: a test of the behaving-as-if construal of children's understanding of
pretense,Developmental Psychology, 40: 388399.

Reese, H. W. (ed.), 1989, Advances in Child Development and Behavior, vol. 22, San
Diego: Academic Press.

Reisberg, D. (ed.), 1992, Auditory Imagery, Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum Associates.

Rizzolatti, G., and C. Sinigaglia, 2006, Mirrors in the Brain: How Our Minds Share
Actions and Emotions, F. Anderson (tr.), New York: Oxford University Press.

Robinson, J., 2005, Deeper Than Reason: Emotion And Its Role In Literature, Music,
And Art, Oxford University Press.

Roese, N.J., and J.M. Olson (eds.), 1995, What Might Have Been: The Social
Psychology of Counterfactual Thinking, Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.

Rogers, S., I. Cook, and A. Meryl, 2005, Imitation and Play in Autism,
in Handbook of Autism and Pervasive Developmental Disorders, 3rd ed., F. R. Volkmar, R.
Paul, A. Klin, and D. Cohen (eds.), John Wiley and Sons, pp. 382405.

Saxe, R., 2005, Against Simulation: The Argument From Error, Trends in Cognitive
Sciences, 9(4): 174179.

, 2006, Why and How to Study Theory of Mind with fMRI, Brain Research,
1079(1): 5765.

, 2009, The Neural Evidence for Simulation is Weaker Than I Think You Think It
Is,Philosophical Studies, 144: 447456.

Schneider, S., 2006, The Paradox of Fiction, in The Internet Encyclopedia of


Philosophy, URL = <http://www.iep.utm.edu/f/fict-par.htm>.

Schwitzgebel, E., 2001, In-between Believing, Philosophical Quarterly, 51: 7682.

Scruton, R., 1974, Art and Imagination, South Bend, IN: St. Augustine's Press.

Searle, J.R., 1979, Expression and Meaning: Studies in the Theory of Speech Acts,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Shepard, R., 1982, Mental Images and their Transformations, Cambridge: Bradford
Books.

Skolnick, D., and P. Bloom, 2006a, What Does Batman Think about SpongeBob?
Children's Understanding of the Fantasy/Fantasy Distinction, Cognition, 101: B9-B18.

, 2006b, The Intuitive Cosmology of Fictional Worlds, in Nichols 2006, pp. 73


86.

Smuts, A., 2007, The Paradox of Painful Art, Journal of Aesthetic Education, 41(3):
5977.

, 2009, Art and Negative Affect, Philosophy Compass, 4(1): 3955.

Sosa, E., 2005, Dreams and Philosophy, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society,
79(2): 718.

, 2007, A Virtue Epistemology, v.1, New York: Oxford University Press.

Stalnaker, R., 2002, What is it Like to Be a Zombie?, in Gendler and Hawthorne,


eds. 2002a: 385400.

Sternberg, R., 1998, The Handbook of Creativity, Cambridge University Press.

Stevenson, L., 2003, Twelve Conceptions of Imagination, British Journal of


Aesthetics, 43(3): 238259.

Stock, K., 2005, Resisting Imaginative Resistance, Philosophical Quarterly,


55(221): 607624.

Stokes, D., 2006, The Evaluative Character of Imaginative Resistance, British


Journal of Aesthetics, 46: 347405.

Stoljar, D., 2007. Two Conceivability Arguments Compared, Proceedings of the


Aristotelian Society Vol CVII, Part 1, pp. 2744

Szab, Z. G., 2005, Sententialism and Berkeley's Master Argument, Philosophical


Quarterly, 55: 462474.

Strawson, P. F., 1970, Imagination and Perception, in Experience and Theory, L.


Foster and J. W. Swanson (eds.), Amherst, MA: University of Massachusetts Press, pp. 31
54.

Todd, C.S., 2009, Imaginability, Morality, and Fictional Truth: Dissolving the Puzzle
of Imaginative Resistance, Philosophical Studies, 143(2): 187211.

Tomasello, M., M. Carpenter, J. Call, T. Behne, and H. Moll, 2005, Understanding


and Sharing Intentions: The Origins of Cultural Cognition, Behavioral and Brain Sciences,
28(5): 67591.

Tye, M., 1991, (repr. 2000), The Imagery Debate, Cambridge, MA: MIT.

Velleman, D., 2000, The Aim of Belief, in The Possibility of Practical Reason.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Walker-Andrews, A. S., and R. Kahana-Kelman, 1997, The Understanding of


Pretense Across the Second Year of Life, British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 17:
52336.

Walton, K., 1978, Fearing Fictions, The Journal of Philosophy, 75(1): 527.

, 1990, Mimesis as Make-Believe, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

, 1994, Morals in Fiction and Fictional Morality, Proceedings of the Aristotelian


Society, suppl. vol. 68: 2750.

, 2006. On the (So-Called) Puzzle of Imaginative Resistance, in Nichols 2006,


pp. 137148.

Weatherson, Brian, 2004. Morality, Fiction, and Possibility, Philosophers' Imprint,


4(3). [Available online].

Weinberg, J., and A. Meskin, 2006, Puzzling Over the Imagination: Philosophical
Problems, Architectural Solutions, in Nichols 2006.

Wellman, H., and D. Estes, 1986, Early Understanding of Mental Entities: a


Reexamination of Childhood Realism, Child Development, 57: 910923.

Williams, B., 1973, Problems of the Self: Philosophical Papers 19561972,


Cambridge University Press.

Williamson, T., 2005, Armchair Philosophy, Metaphysical Modality, and


Counterfactual Thinking, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 105: 123.

, 2007, The Philosophy of Philosophy, Oxford: Blackwell.


Wing, L., and J. Gould, 1979, Severe Impairments of Social Interaction and
Associated Abnormalities in Children: Epidemeology and Classification, Journal of Autism
and Developmental Disorders, 9(1): 1129.

Winkler, K. P., 1989, Berkeley: An Interpretation, Oxford: Oxford University Press.


Yablo, S., 1993, Is Conceivability a Guide to Possibility? Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research, 53(1): 142.

, 2002, Coulda, Woulda, Shoulda, in Gendler and Hawthorne, eds. 2002a:441


92.

Yanal, R. J., 1999, Paradoxes of Emotion and Fiction, University Park, PA:
Pennsylvania State University Press.

Zahavi, D. (ed.), 2000, Exploring the Self: Philosophical and Psychopathological


Perspectives on Self-Experience, Amsterdam: Benjamins.

Zalta, E., 1992, Fictional Truth, Objects, and Characters, in Blackwell Companion
to Metaphysics, J. Kim and E. Sosa (eds.), Oxford: Blackwell.

Zimmerman, A., 2007, The Nature of Belief, Journal of Consciousness Studies,


14(11): 6182.
How to cite this entry: Gendler, Tamar, "Imagination", The Stanford Encyclopedia
of Philosophy (Fall 2013 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL =
<http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2013/entries/imagination/>.

Вам также может понравиться