Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 31

Was Rome a Polis?

Author(s): Clifford Ando


Source: Classical Antiquity, Vol. 18, No. 1 (Apr., 1999), pp. 5-34
Published by: University of California Press
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/25011091
Accessed: 17-11-2015 20:21 UTC

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/
info/about/policies/terms.jsp
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content
in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship.
For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

University of California Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Classical Antiquity.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 99.72.109.133 on Tue, 17 Nov 2015 20:21:55 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

CLIFFORD ANDO

Was Rome a polis?

I. INTRODUCTION
Ancient models of cross-cultural contact under theRoman empire are notori
ously simplistic. The observations of Tacitus on Britain andFlorus on Spain-that
theRomans encouraged thenatives to live in cities on level ground, towear togas,
and to speakLatin-are typical of Roman reflection on the topic.' Both Romans
andGreeks asserted, however, thatRome's relationswith Greece took place on a
different level and that between them cultural influence flowed in the opposite
direction. Although philhellenism occasionally became controversial in political
life at Rome, especially in the second century B.C., it did so in part because the
dominant tendency was not to question the seductive sophistication of Greek
culture.2This dominant view was best expressed by Horace: "ConqueredGreece
conquers thewild victor and introduces her arts into rusticLatium."3
By asserting the superiority of Greek culture, advocates of this position
deflected attention away fromGreek subjugation to a foreign power; in so doing,
theymust have comforted Greeks unaccustomed to subservience to anyone other
than their fellow Greeks.4 Modem scholars have proved largely complicit in
thatproject, emphasizing the superiority of Hellenic culture as though thatwere
Earlier versions of thispaperwere delivered at Princeton University, York University, and theAnnual
Meeting of the APA. I thankmembers of the audiences on those occasions for their comments,
particularly Jonathan Edmondson and Peter Brown. For instruction on earlier drafts I am indebted
to Erich Gruen, Sabine MacCormack, Gary Miles, Jeremy Trevett, Phiroze Vasunia, and a reader
for this journal.
1. Tac. Agr. 21.1-2; Florus 2.33.59-60.
2. On the history of this problem in second-century Rome see Gruen 1990:158-92 and 1992.
3. Horace Epist. 2.1.156-57; cf. Cicero Brut. 73.254.
4. On Greek acceptance of the domination of powerful (Greek) states andmonarchs over other
less powerful cities, Greek and otherwise, see Austin 1986:454-56.

1999

BY THE

REGENTS

OF THE UNIVERSITY

OF CALIFORNIA.

ISSN0278-6656(p); Io67-8344 (e).


This content downloaded from 99.72.109.133 on Tue, 17 Nov 2015 20:21:55 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

CLASSICAL
ANTIQUITY

Volume 18/No. I/April 1999

sufficient compensation for the hegemony of Rome. Yet Hellenistic kings prior
to the second Macedonian war never regardedRoman conquest as inevitable:
indeed, one might argue thatmany Greeks of the late thirdcentury B.C. assumed
that they could defeat Rome precisely because of their superiority in all branches
of political and cultural endeavor. The conquest of the easternMediterranean
therefore demanded explanation, and all themore so for the astonishing speed
with which Rome accomplished it.The explanations for, and narratives of, Roman
conquest had ramifications that reached farbeyond the narrow confines of ancient
scholarly endeavor, whether in historiography or political philosophy. Political
circumstances and post-colonial angst have conspired to produce rigorous and
well-crafted studies on the geistige Widerstand gegen Rom;5Greek intellectual
and emotional accommodation toRoman rule, particularly in the late Republic
and age of Augustus, has received less attention.6 Yet that latter process must
have shaped contemporary narratives of the past: as Greeks grew willing to
direct their patriotism and nationalistic aspirations towardsRome, they required
an intellectual model of the empire that could exonerate, even justify, their
participation in its political institutions.
The basis of this intellectual accommodation calls for investigation not least
because research of the last century has so deepened our knowledge of life in
theGreek East at a religious, political, and institutional level. The last several
years have seen thepublication of largeand sophisticated regional surveys, but the
empiricism that informs theseworks seemingly constrains them to view and to de
scribe surviving data exclusively as the result of concrete actions.7The revolution
inGreek political consciousness that took place during this renaissance inGreek
urban culture has not received similarly detailed study.8Yet theGreeks' willing
ness to integrate particular instantiations of Roman power into civic institutions
and to accommodate imperial cult within their individual pantheons must have
been preceded by a conceptual model allowing such integration. Greek actions
following Roman conquest-seeking priesthoods in the imperial cult or Roman
citizenship or meeting with Roman officials, to say nothing of describing such

5. Fuchs 1938; cf. Gauger 1980 and Swain 1996. On the social trends inwhich these studies
participate seeMomigliano 1986:103-104.
6. Felicitous exceptions include Jones 1971:122-30; Gabba 1982 and 1984; Eckstein 1985,
1990, and 1995: 8-27 and 194-236; Stern 1987; Erksine 1990:181-204; Rogers 1991;Woolf 1993;
and Shaw 1995.
7. Sartre 1991,Millar 1993, Mitchell 1993, and Sartre 1995.
8. Swain 1996 is an important exception, but that work fundamentally misunderstands the
causal link-apparent even to contemporaries-between Greek classicism and Roman rule. See
Hidber 1996:75-81 and 117-23: Dionysius proposes Hellenic paideia as themeans to unite Greeks
and Romans culturally, while admitting that his ambition is capable of realization because of what
Augustus and theRomans had achieved politically. Similarly, the Panhellenion gave expression to
Hellenic identity, and gave rise to much research into classical history, but its focus was on the
relationship between theGreek people and theirRoman emperor.Greek in inspiration, its existence
and content were inconceivable without Rome: see Jones 1996 andBirley 1997:217-20.

This content downloaded from 99.72.109.133 on Tue, 17 Nov 2015 20:21:55 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

ANDO:Was Rome a polis?

deeds in the language of honorific decrees-presupposed amental geography that


assigned individuals and institutions their own place in the greaterwhole.
The creation of suchmaps ormodels must have been largely subconscious,
but they find expression in themetaphors throughwhich Greeks articulated their
understanding of the structure of the Roman state. But the language of Greek
historians seeking to understandRoman Italy is not merely, perhaps not even, a
reflection of the realities of life on the Italian peninsula. Rather, that language
springs from and can reveal theconceptual system thatordered reality and assessed
the boundaries of the possible for Greeks under Roman rule.9 Of course, the
Greeks did not share a single "conceptual system," nor could the parameters of
their systems

in a paper of this scope. This essay argues for amethod

be elucidated

of researchingGreek accommodation toRoman rule by investigating themodels


throughwhich they understood Rome, her empire, and theirplace within it.
Constructing a history of this process poses certainmethodological difficul
ties, for which I advance only tentative solutions. Intellectual history-in this
case, of Greek misunderstandings accomplished through flawed metaphorical
construal-does not proceed at the pace of political events, and is thus suscep
tible neither to the same periodization nor to similar narratives of causation. It
is easy enough to suggest thatGreeks of the second century B.C. viewed Rome
and her empire as two distinct entities, apolis thatconqueredmany territoriesand
an empire thatpossessed no more affective cohesion than aHellenistic kingdom.
Likewise, I can assert thatGreeks of the second century A.D. had come to view
the city and its empire

with Rome

as a unified whole,

as a single polis

embrac

ing innumerable fields and villages.'0 This shift was obviously profound. But the
fourhundredyears separating theseperiods display no simple progression. Indeed,
Greeks of the lateRepublic proposed several differentmodels of Rome andher em
pire, and the gradual consensus favoring the second of the views described above
resulted from a harmonious if accidental convergence of trends in the political
and intellectual

arenas. This essay

conceives

in three stages.

of this process

The exponents of the varied late-Republicanmodels shared a single method:


to assimilate

each sought

ence and then broadened


cal extension.

In doing

a Roman

institution

to a paradigm

the scope of this archetype


so, Greeks

from Hellenic

through a process

experi

of analogi

B.C. misapplied

of the second and first centuries

the terms and concepts of theirown political forms to those of Rome (Section II).
By using the existing vocabulary of Greek politics, thesemodels masked serious
disjunctures between Greek andRoman definitions of citizenship and community
that Greeks

had to negotiate,

articulating

it. As Mommsen

a form of

even
wrote

as their method
of Greek

LaotnoXLTeia, these approaches

were

attempts

rendered

them incapable

understandable

of

Latin

status as

enough,

but they

to construe

9. On reading metaphor and political language in these terms, see Lakoff and Turner 1980
and Bourdieu 1990:54-55.
10. See Dio 52.19.6, quoted at n. 115.

This content downloaded from 99.72.109.133 on Tue, 17 Nov 2015 20:21:55 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

CLASSICAL
ANTIQUITY

Volume 18/No. 1/April 1999

yielded results contrary toRoman conceptions of those same institutions.1'The


examples in this section concentrate on political terminology for two related rea
sons: they illuminate the gap that separatedGreek and Roman political theory,
even as they reveal the depth of Greek misinterpretation. The mapping of fa
miliar conceptual schemata onto the foreign thought-world of Rome, concretized
in term-for-term translations of Latin documents inGreek, was thus based on
false analogies. This is true in spite of the success of such translations, insofar
as the success of a reference-in this case, of applying Greek terminology to
Roman institutions-does not depend on the accuracywith which any given term
mapped the associative network of ideas on which the term and its referentwere
customarily predicated in their respective Greek andRoman contexts.12
Greek efforts to understand Rome were not mere intellectual games. They
possessed personal, political and moral dimensions. In the last decades of the
first century B.C., Augustan rhetoric to the provinces, exemplified in the fifth
Cyrene edict, possessed a universalizing dimension thatmany probably wanted
desperately or cynically to believe. In the same era, Greek historians studying
the integration of Italy after the Social War sought to understand and then to
describe the peninsula and, implicitly, the empire as a united community.Among
the conceptual models available to them, the only paradigm for a collectivity in
which individuals had equal rights and towardwhich they directed theirpatriotic
sentiments was thepolis. Prolonged engagement with, and repeated applications
of, polis-based understandings of Rome inducedGreeks tomake an ontological
commitment to theirmodels: they ceased to employ them as heuristic devices and
came to regard them existentially.13 Between theAugustan age and the second
century, the continuous application of Greek political terminology to institutions
that they did not literally describe forced a shift in the semantic field of the terms
themselves

(Section

"
111).

In the third stage of this process, Greeks' evolving understanding of Roman


institutions changed the interaction between the target and source domains in
thismetaphorical mapping, and ultimately changed the underlying conceptual
I1. Mommsen 1887-1888: vol. 3, part 1, 231 n. 1: "Das der Latiner zu den Romern betrachten
die Griechen vielmehr geradezu als Biirgerrecht (-noX-retLo,LnoXLteLoa),mit Rticksicht auf ihr
Stimmrecht; begreiflich genug, aber entgegen der r6mischen Auffassung."
12. On the success of references requiringmetaphorical construal, see Soskice 1985:50-55.
13. On this process and its dangers see Black 1962:220-42.
14. For a similar problem inRoman political thought, see Thomas 1996, amost elegant essay.
Thomas asks how the traditional idea of a patria could have been extended to such a large and
heterogeneous collectivity as the empire. Thomas begins with Roman juridical categories andwith
the overriding ancient tendency to see cities as both the basic unit of political life and the natural
object for patriotic sentiments. He then shows that innovations in religious and public law of the late
Republic and Augustan age, intendedmerely to extend earlier practice and based on antiquarian
research, in fact deconstructed the very foundations on which theywere intended to build. The result
was a fundamental shift in the notion of the "origin," a dissociating of theRoman people from any
particularized locality: this shift, in turn, allowed the creation of a shared patria, based on a legal
fiction, that transcended traditionalgeographic and ethnic boundaries.

This content downloaded from 99.72.109.133 on Tue, 17 Nov 2015 20:21:55 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

ANDO:Was Rome a polis?

archetype of the political collectivity. Greek cognition developed hand in hand


with Greek linguistic praxis.'5 Describing Rome as a polis eventually required
many Greeks-used to assuming a congruence between polis, patris, and po
liteia-to regardRome as thepolis of the empire (Section IV). For such people,
as for Aelian,

Rome

became

their city, and her laws the laws of their homeland."6

II. ROME FROM A DISTANCE:


SOMETHING STRANGE, FRIGHTFUL, AND MYSTERIOUS
There is every reason to think that the repeated failures of the Hellenistic
monarchs andGreek leagues in the face of Roman aggression were exceptionally
bitter. Greeks had long prided themselves on the power of a united Hellas, and
speakers throughout the text of Polybius urge their fellow Greeks to unite in order
toward off enslavement and depredation at the hands of the barbarians from the
West. 17Particularly notable are the repeatedexhortations by the representativesof
Greek cities urging that all Greeks, "holding hands likemen crossing a river,"
should rally behind theMacedonians, "people of the same race," "who spend their
whole lives fighting barbarians for the safety of theGreeks.""8The Greeks never
did present a united front against Rome, andGreek historians under the empire
repeatedly contrasted the single-minded progress of Rome with the internecine
strife of Greek poleis and of theHellenistic kingdoms.'9 Beginning at least from
the end of the first century
and to praise Roman
erupting

into war.

of this era, Greek

rule:

it alone

orators

this topos to justify

adapted

the rivalry of Greek

prevented

In the third and fourth centuries

a common

this became

from

cities

theme

not only in Jewish texts, but also among Christian authors seeking to findDivine
Providence atwork in the foundation of the empire.20
In blaming their ancestors for allowing their own subjugation, these authors
implicitly suggested that a united Greece might have been able to defend itself
15. See Lakoff and Turner 1989:60-67 and esp. Sweetser 1990:1-13 and 47-48. Sweetser
deploys her theoretical framework in historical inquiries, concerning, inter alia, metaphors for
epistemic processes, thatbrilliantly confirm themerit of that framework.
16.
oyA5ac

See Aelian
8tx0CLW

Hist.

2.38:

a&oycav,

i 8E oCUx aXv 'EtoT.LtLxcl


EL T&
Vv

Aoxp6v

xol

tov

'P0aicd&v

MaaaaXLw&tv

vo4ov;
xiL

t\

xaL

Tca

oCux

MLXkoLWv

&l&

tuTcxuoinovp'Loq &X6yo e'ac; See also 12.25 (8&cxptprL ,UOl


,uv#pirgs06i.niv, t& be
8e\
xotl toucwv [referring to ol.TEXXnveq], r'iye 'P&oVoZto6
e'LV)and 14.45.
17. E.g. Agelaus theAetolian atNaupactus in 217 (5.104), Lyciscus theAcarnanian in Sparta,
late in the spring of 210 (9.34-38), or the speech of an unnamed ambassador to theAetolians in
207 (11.5).
18. For theMacedonians as oyu'Aor, see 9.37.7.
19. E.g. Dion. Hal. Ant. Rom. 1.3.5 and 5.2; Appian Praef 8.30 and 10.42; cf. Polybius
5.106.3-5, referring only to the Peloponnesians.
20. E.g. Dio Chrys. Or 38-41, on which see Jones 1978:83-94; Pausanias 7.17.4, on which
see Jones 1971:17-18 andHabicht 1985:123; Cassius Dio 52.37.9-10; andHerodian 3.2.8. In later
literature see Augustine Civ. Dei 17.23; John Chrys. Homil. contra Iudaeos et Gentiles 3; and Sefer
Ha-Aggadah 5.92.

This content downloaded from 99.72.109.133 on Tue, 17 Nov 2015 20:21:55 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Volume 18/No. 1/April 1999

ANTIQUITY
CLASSICAL

10

againstRoman aggression. They therefore shared a conception of political life in


which solidarity based on ethnicity claimed second place only to one's loyalty to
thepolis. Between the city of one's origin and one's cultural identity,moreover,
there existed a natural bond. Hellenic solidarity ought, according to the logic
deployed by these admittedly later authors, to have requiredGreeks to give up
fighting each other in order to fight their common foe. That correlation was
so fundamental to classical and Hellenistic political thought thatGreek writers
never developed a vocabulary to describe the result of its breakdown.When, for
example, Posidonius attempted to describe the behavior of individuals during the
massacre of Italians inAsia instigated byMithridates, the narrative strained his
vocabulary: "Of the other Romans, some prostrate themselves before the images
of the gods, while the rest, changing into squared cloaks, identify themselves by
their original

na-tp(q once again."21

Justwhom does Posidonius here label as Roman? Strictly speaking, a person


was Roman
about

only

if he was

to be whipped
v, but only

TPcox,u

a Roman

in Jerusalem,
that he was

citizen.

Thus,

he did not have

for example,

when

Paul was

to say that he held noxeLtov

'P&,IcZtoq.22 Yet I very much

an av6ptnoq

doubt

thatPosidonius here observes such constitutional niceties. Inpractice, Greeks had


difficulty distinguishing Romans and Italians-they were equally un-Greek-and
no doubt many inAsia operated on the same principle as Posidonius: a person
was Roman if he assimilated toRoman customs.23How else could one change his
race by changing his clothes? On thatbasis, the "Romans" in this passage could
easily include Romanizing Greeks wearing togas.24Yet it is just as clear that
as a change

this metamorphosis

describing

violence

in notxpL' does considerable

to the conventional meaning of the term.


Traditional

Greek

categories

of ethnicity

did not aid attempts

to elevate

the

warriors of Rome to near-paritywith theirmore civilized subjects. Dividing the


population of the world into Greeks and others by labeling men as 6o,6?uXot
or aXXYpuXoL
did not tolerate any conceptual interstice in which to accommo
date a more

bellicose,

yet marginally

less civilized

Roman

between

Greek

and

Greeks were, of course, capable of distinguishing ethnic subdivisions


barbarian.25

21. Posidonius fr. 253 Kidd, 11.82-84 (Athenaeus 213B): t&v 8' BXXwv'P uai'v
Ek&V cyo(4XLcZGL lTpOcnTErG')xa7YLV,
apXnS

OL 8E XOlIOL VETU

Lec0qEVOL

TEXpYV

Oi vev

L.tlOCLt TC't

TtaCtpL8Ot T tXLV OVOVai'OUoL.

22. For the former phrase, see Euseb. Hist. Ecl. 5.1.47; for the latter see Acts 22:24-29.
23. This problem found expression, among other things, inGreek astonishment that PWVicLoL
see Kramer 1993.
spoke -i'v Acxtiv&v &&XEXTOV:
24. Cf. Seneca on the rhetorArgentarius, Controv. 9.3.13: illud tamen optima fide praestitit,
cum uterque Graecus esset, ut numquam declamaret, <et> illos semper admiraretur qui, non
[fuerunt] contenti unius linguae eloquentia, cum Latine declamaverant, toga posita sumpto pallio
quasi persona mutata rediebant et Graece declamabant. Argentarius derides this practice precisely
because the change in garb, from toga to pallium, could not alter those facets of one's character
thatwere, in fact, determined by one's patria.
25. On the development of this opposition in the classical period see Hall 1997:40-51.

This content downloaded from 99.72.109.133 on Tue, 17 Nov 2015 20:21:55 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

11

ANDO:Was Rome a polis?

within theGreek world, a process visible in classical andHellenistic diplomacy


and in the formation of fourth-century leagues.26And yet conversation about and
appeals to a unitaryGreek identity tended, after the fashion of all ideologically
charged discourse, to create and thenmaintain polarizing categories, of which the
most obvious was the reductive binarism of Greek and barbarian.27Under this
constraint, theonly route to reconciliationwith Roman rule on ethnic grounds was
that takenby Dionysius of Halicarnassus. Dionysius argued not only thatRomans
had descended from Greeks but thatRome had developed her most admirable
political institutions through the imitation of earlier,more virtuous Greeks.28 In
this he fought an uphill battle: he undertook the project, he said, because Greeks
remained ignorantof the history of thepolis of theRomans: they therefore con
tinued to complain thatTkXr had unjustly bestowed the blessings of theGreeks
upon the basest of barbarians.29
Iwill return toDionysius and his understanding of Roman institutions later,
but I note here three facts about his place in Greek historiography. First, we
must separate Greek scholarly interest in the origins of Rome and the racial
background of the Romans from any meticulous analysis of the structure of
the Roman state: the manipulation of the legendary past within ethnographic
literaturemay be understood as Greek antiquarian interest in the Greek past,
and not as interest

in Roman

history

for its own

sake.30 Earnest

attempts

to in

clude Roman affairswithin the contemporary history of theMediterranean (i.e.,


Greek) world began with Timaeus, whose interest inMagna Graecia naturally led
him to notice the growing power of Rome, and yet Rome fell within his orbit
largely because Rome's involvement in the first Punic War brought her firmly
into themainstream of Sicilian history.3' Second, althoughGreek historians from
Timaeus and Xenagoras throughPosidonius had devoted more and more space
toRoman affairs,Dionysius found his truestpredecessors among cultural histo
rians and grammarians likeHypsicratus of Amisus and Philoxenus of Alexandria,
both of whom attempted to demonstrate thatLatin derived from Greek.32Third,
Dionysius did not persuade anyone. Among other things, he clearly exposed
Hansen 1996b; Beck 1997:165-66.
Hartog 1988:212-30.
1.89.1-2; see Bowersock 1965:131-32 andGabba 1991:190-216.
Dionysius 1.4.2: xaXi o' yE xaXxo0oEsepot
xarTYopeVv cX0AWL , TUXr xauor TO
'
-r&
-cCv'EXXvvv
co?7
fxP3ap'pwv
TcOplvOpeVTayao .
Tcovi)pot&toLq
ycvep'v
30. On Greek ethnographic history the locus classicus is Bickerman 1952. See also Gruen
1992:6-51, and, toward a very different end, Wiseman 1995:43-62. Of course such legends
could serve political ends: Greek cities often manipulated themythical past to establish kinship
(GuyyEveLa)with other cities and in thatway established a racial justification forwholesale grants of
for the connections between these phenomena see Giovannini
honorary citizenship ('ioonoXLTeLot);
1993:277-79 and Curty 1995, who collects extant epigraphical evidence for appeals tomythical
founders in diplomacy of theHellenistic and Roman eras.
31. Momigliano 1966, esp. 44-51.
32. Hypsicrates: FGrH ii B 923. Philoxenus: Cicero Att. 13.8 and Suda b 394. Cf. Suda T
1 85, on Tyrannio the younger.
26.
27.
28.
29.

This content downloaded from 99.72.109.133 on Tue, 17 Nov 2015 20:21:55 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

12

CLASSICAL
ANTIQUITY

Volume 18/No. 1/April 1999

himself to the charge that he leveled against others, that of writing a false his
torywhich labeled his patrons as Greek and their enemies as barbarians.33 In
the long run, it was not the category "Greek" thatwould stretch to accommo
date the polyglot population of the empire, a sad fact thatDionysius himself
almost anticipated.34
Dionysius failed in part because he was too ambitious. He tried by a his
toriographical sleight of hand to reconcile Greeks and Romans. In so doing,
he dissented from a long-standing tradition that tied Rome to theGreek world
through the legend of Aeneas. That legend provided Roman and Greek with a
sharedmythological history, to be sure, but certainly not one that could read
ily unite them.35This tradition, as Amaldo Momigliano has shown, reached its
mature state during the Hellenistic period, to provide a historical background
to diplomatic contacts between Rome and the cities of the East.36Of course, it
remained possible for select cities to argue for a close connection with Rome on
thebasis of its putative Trojan past, but the language of ethnicity intrudes in those
cases, too, indeed, is fundamental to them. Thus, when Lampsakos sought an
alliance with Rome after Cynoscephelae, it cited its kinship (auyYEvrELC)
with
theRomans, grounding that claim on littlemore than its location in the Troad.37
Such negotiations over kinship thus treatedonly membership among theGreeks
as questionable and subject to inquiry,while leaving the categoryGreek ontologi
cally intact. If the practical result of manipulating themythological past was to
render the boundary between Greek and non-Greek quite permeable, thatperme
ability was not acknowledged: ideological stresswas rather laid on the existence
of the boundary.
More seriously andmore ambitiously, in aiming at reconciliation Dionysius
departed from the path blazed by his intellectual forbears, Polybius and Posido
nius, with whose
world.

narratives

Reconciliation,

a non-issue.

he intended

for a writer

The growth

of

of the Roman

to join his own in a tripartite history


pr,aX-LX'
empire,

'tL^op'Lasuch as Polybius,
like the evolution

of the
was

of the Roman

33. See Bowersock 1965:108 and Sacks 1990:135.


34. See below (at n. 86) on 2.17.1-2. Thus men did not become Greek merely by participating in
Hellenic culture, as Isocrates hadmaintained (Paneg. 50); rather, theywere discovered already to be
Greek through assimilation to pre-existing legendary genealogies.
35. Cf. Plutarch Flam. 11.4: The Greeks are astonished thatmen of another race (&Xo&(puXoL),
who were believed to have only insignificant traces of a shared ancestry (Evocxu6aaica,Lxpa X0l
.
aLXcoL)
yXLaxpa xoLvWV#,para
yevou; EXeLv8oxoCvte), would undertake such toils to free
Greece from despots and tyrants.See also SEG 30.1073, from 189/8 B.C.: theChians expressed their
friendship with Rome by erecting a monument depicting .iUOOL
np6g 80'aV 'Pca LoLv,namely
the story of Romulus and Remus and their descent from Ares, which was "justly to be regarded
as truebecause of themanly courage of theRomans."
36. Momigliano 1984a, and see the bibliography cited in n. 30.
37. L Lampsakos 4 = Curty 1995, no. 39. Lampsakos seems not to have noticed that its
simultaneous citing of its kinship with Massilia (they were both colonies of Phokaia) rendered its
blood kinship with Rome impossible. Attempts to resolve that contradiction have produced some
ingenious scholarship: see Curty 1995:81-82 and 251.

This content downloaded from 99.72.109.133 on Tue, 17 Nov 2015 20:21:55 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

ANDO:Was Rome a polis?

13

constitution, had takenplace xacx yuaLv, according to nature.38It simply didn't


matter whether one likedRoman rule: thewise statesman, however, would want
to know why it had come about.39
Polybius grounded his explanation forRoman expansion in theparticular form
of theRoman constitution, towhose explication he devoted the sixth book of his
history.40Polybius has risen steadily in the estimation of his readers over the last
several decades: we want to recognize in his sociological inquiry a sophisticated
attempt to escape the cult of personality that so dominated ancient historiography.
Yet his work both stands outside the mainstream of Greek thought and falls
just short of its goal: the "mixed constitution" might have preserved Rome's
internal stability, but it certainly cannot explain the growth of the empire. Nor
do theHistories anywhere address, at least in the extant fragments, the peculiar
permeability of theRoman citizen body that so aroused the curiosity of Polybius'
countrymen. To adapt the comments of Momigliano when he reflected upon the
inadequacy of Polybius as a guide to Greek encounters with Roman culture,
Polybius failed to see Rome "from a distance-as something strange,mysterious
in language and religion, frightful in rituals and formidable inwarfare."'" This
blindness arose, according toMomigliano, because Polybius wished too strongly
to view Rome as amember of the civilized community of theGreek world.42
Momigliano directs our attention to another question that the scope of Alien
Wisdom did not allow him to explore. Given thatPolybius explicitly addressed a
Greek audience, what conceptual categories were available tohim for the analysis
and articulation of his topic?We must answer thatquestion before we consider the
consequences of Polybius' decision within its culturally-determined parameters.
The next section explores Greek attempts to understandRome on analogy with
empires, leagues, and city-states. At a theoretical level, however, the belief that
Rome

can be explained

through

an analysis

of her constitution,

her ntoxt-sea,

in

itself presumes that she is a polis, with institutions and thereforementalities at


some

to Greek

level analogous

of settlements
of meaning,

as poleis
nor did

does

it prevent

cities.43 That Greeks


not require
theoretical

referred

the conclusion
reflection

to a broad

that polis

on the nature

was

range
devoid

of the polis

itself. On the contrary,designating a community as apolis gave it status, implied


38. Polybius 6.9.12-13.
39. On Polybius and Rome, amidst a huge bibliography, seeWalbank 1965, Derow 1979, and
Eckstein 1985.
40. See esp. 1.1.5, 3.2.6, and 6.9.
41. Momigliano 1975:37 and 1942:119-20.
42. Momigliano 1975:37.
43. That Latin had no equivalent for noXtlteLx is well known: see Cicero Att. 7.8.4. Cicero
himself had to employ various circumlocutions to surmount this problem: see Rep. 1.41 (omnis ergo
populus, qui est talis coetus multitudinis qualem exposui, omnis civitas, quae est constitutio populi.
omnis res publica, quae ut dixi populi res est, consilio quodam regenda est, ut diuturna sit) and
Leg. 1.15 (Atqui si quaeris ego quid expectem, quoniam scriptum est a te de optimo rei publicae
statu, consequens esse videtur ut scribas tu idem de legibus).

This content downloaded from 99.72.109.133 on Tue, 17 Nov 2015 20:21:55 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

14

CLASSICAL
ANTIQUITY

Volume 18/No. 1/April 1999

its political autonomy, and pointed to a citizen body with a shared commitment
to particular criteria of membership.' But Rome did not resemble any notional
idea of thepolis, neither in its attitude towardmembership, nor in its eagerness
to assimilate conquered populations, nor in its control and use of its colonies.
Polybius was, of course, not alone in seeking and ultimately positing an illusory
similarity between Greeks and Romans. But themanifest superficiality of this
presumptionmasks itsmore serious consequences, both positive and negative. As
a handicap it crippled Polybius in his attempt to explain Roman rule even before
he began; at the same time, it provided a conceptual frameworkwithin which
Greeks could justify theirwholesale participation in imperial culture and political
life.Ultimately itwould also forceGreeks to choose, consciously or not, between
theirpolis of origin and thepolis of their empire.
In their efforts to understand the Roman constitution, Hellenistic Greeks
faced a series of conceptual obstacles logically prior to any attempt to construe
its operation on analogy with Hellenistic models. I focus on two issues and the
terms throughwhich Romans, and subsequentlyGreeks, articulated them, namely,
citizenship and popular sovereignty. In each case, describing the errors committed
by Greeks requires understanding the difference that separatedGreek andRoman
thought on these topics.
We may begin by acknowledging thatGreeks no less thanmodern scholars
wrestled with Latin political terminology.The fact thatGreeks crafted translations
of Roman documents should not be allowed tomask the considerable conceptual
disjunction between their respective political traditions:did Greeks really under
stand thedifference betweenpopulus Romanus and 6o8i,uoq 'Pw iatv? According
toCicero, "the res publica is the respopuli, but a populus is not every crowd of
men,

gathered

for any reason, but a crowd bound by consensual

commitment

to a

particular normative order and by common interest."45The populus Romanus was


thus notionally permeable, open to thosewilling to participate in this consensus,
and yet that consensus constructed the Roman people, in its corporate identity,
as a singular

and homogeneous

collective.46

A Greek

8n,oq,

by contrast, was

an

44. On poleis see Hansen 1996a: 14-34. See also Gauthier 1981:168-72, together with the
review of Hansen's collection by A. Chaniotis and Hansen's reply to that review (BMCR 97.7.16
and BMCR 98.2.7, respectively).
45. Cicero Rep. 1.39.1: "Est igitur" inquitAfricanus "res publica res populi, populus autem
non omnis hominum coetus quoquo modo congregatus, sed coetus multitudinis iuris consensu et
utilitatis communione sociatus." On this passage see Zetzel 1995 ad loc., as well as Brunt 1988:2
and 326.
46. See, for example, Cicero Mur. 5 1, construing thepopulus as a corpus, orAteius Capito, cited
by Gellius 10.20.5: Plebem autem Capito in eadem definitione seorsum a populo divisit, quoniam in
populo omnis pars civitatis omnesque eius ordines contineantur, plebes vero ea dicatur, inqua gentes
civium patriciae non insunt. To Justinian belongs a particularly concise formulation: appellatione
populi universi cives significantur (Inst. 1.2.4). For the contexts inwhich Romans made explicit
reference to consensus, see Ruggiero, Diz. Epigr. s.v. Instinky 1940 is notable particularly for its
discussion of texts inwhich the ideology of consensus is operative without being explicitly raised.
More recently, see Nicolet 1979:332-39.

This content downloaded from 99.72.109.133 on Tue, 17 Nov 2015 20:21:55 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

ANDO:Was Rome a polis?

15

agglomeration of citizens defined ultimately and almost exclusively by descent.47


The genitive-populus Romanorum?-makes all the difference.
The Greeks thereforedid not understandhow thepopulus could havemaiestas.
Translating

maiestas

as OE:L&rT or occe3PeLo is understandable

under

the empire

because of Augustus (Eep3aaTo6)and all that his name represented, but under
the Republic doing so would have reflected a profoundly mistaken idea of the
relationship between the individualRoman and his populus.48Nor did there exist
aGreek equivalent for respublica: the official Greek translationof theRes Gestae
of Augustus uses four different phrases to cover that term'sbroad semantic field.49
Polybius' narrative of thenegotiations between theAetolians andManius Acilius
Glabrio is paradigmatic of the linguistic pitfalls that confronted Greeks in their
early encounters with Roman magistrates. In 191 B.C. theAetolians decided to
ask the consul Glabrio for his pardon and resolved to commit themselves "to the
faith of the Roman

people"

(?t5 -rV Pwiczcov

KLaTLv), not knowing,

as Polybius

writes, the import (8&vcxciLq)


of the phrase. In fact, aRoman understood surrender
infidem as unconditional; theAetolians, Polybius explains, were deceived by the
word "faith" intobelieving that theiractionwould obtain amore complete pardon
TOOTO TE?XLOT6pOU YLoYLvEXeou; 07povcoq).
(W? aV 8L&&

After

granting

the

Aetolians an audience, Glabrio began to dictate the termsunderwhich they could


act in the future.

The Aetolians

cried

out

in surprise:

"What you demand

is

not Greek (EXXrXvLx6v)."


Glabrio responded coldly: "Are you still going to run
around acting Greek
yourselves

(E':L yOp V ?LX ?XXvoxo1trE:),

s15 tnv Tctaatv? Iwill

even after you have given

throw you all in chains

if Iwant

to."50

Such broad disparities between the semantic fields of superficially synony


mous terms can reveal even more substantial differences between Hellenistic
47. See M. Humbert 1978:85-143, Gauthier 1981, andMeier 1996. On the importanceof ethnics
see also Hansen 1996b: 194: "All three types of ethnic were used as a kind of hereditary surname but
in contradistinction to all other western peoples the Greeks used them primarily as an indication
of political status rather than as habitation names, i.e. names indicating where a person was born
or lived."Other recent essays contrasting Greek andRoman conceptions of citizenship include Eder
1990, concentrating on the differential hierarchies between individual citizens and the citizen body
inGreek andRoman thought, andEder 1996. For the role of legal theory in theAthenian andRoman
traditions, see Nippel 1996.
48. The earliest use of 0et6tj,; is on an inscription from Aphrodisias: Reynolds 1980:73-74,
no. 2 = Reynolds 1982, no. 54. For &Olae La see Philo Flacc. 128.
49. Res Gestae 1.1 (rem publicam = tos xoLv&aitpay,aiot), 1.4 (triumvirum rei publicae
constituendae

= x v

npoyVa-&cv),

2 (bellum

x&v tpL&)V &VAP&V


reipublicae
inferentis

i'XOVta
= no6XeVov

eTYL -Cl XCl-tatCrL


'L(EpoV

T)oV 8TVOGL&V
-Ca L TC-orLptLL),and 34.1 (rem

publicam is subsumed, in theGreek, in natvtCovxxv npotyV6Cuv).Many other renderingswere also


employed (see Mason 1974 s.v.). On "the ideology of theGreek 'ResGestae'" seeWigtil 1982,
and on translating respublica in particular see Judge 1974:280-85. See also Drexler 1957, 1958. and
Stark 1967.
50. Polybius 20.9-10. The accounts of this episode have generated an enormous bibliography
that is not immediately relevant tomy purposes here, since I cite this episode merely as an example of
a larger phenomenon that is not itself in doubt. Gruen 1982 provides references, and I have seen
nothing since then that represents a significant advance.

This content downloaded from 99.72.109.133 on Tue, 17 Nov 2015 20:21:55 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

16

CLASSICAL
ANTIQUITY

Volume 18/No. 1/April 1999

and Republican political ideologies. Thus, for example, a Hellenistic monarch


was the state: Greeks did not address Antigonus or Ptolemy or Antiochus as
"King of theGreeks," or "King of Egypt," or even "King of theGreeks who live
in Asia":

it was

characteristically

Roman

to insist

that a king must

be king of

something.51Compare, for example, Livy's description of thosewho signed the


peace of Phoenice with Polybius' narrativeof thedebate before theAchaean synod
in 188/7 B.C.Livy identifies both kings andmagistrates by thepeoples whom they
represented-"Amynander, king of theAthamanians, and other magistrates of
the Epirotes and Acarnanians"-while Polybius identifies kings by name and
private individuals by nationality-"King Ptolemy" and "King Eumenes," but
"Nicodemos of Elaea" and "Apollonidas of Sicyon."52
The reasons behind thisdeserve examination. Romans conceived of thepower
of amagistrate or legitimatemonarch as something transferredto that individual
by thepeople, and itwas thepopulus Romanus in its corporate identity thatretained
the right to choose thebearers of its authority.The briefest formulationbelongs to
Ulpian: "Thewishes of theprinceps have the force of law because thepopulus
transfers to him and into him its power of command (imperium) and its powers of
jurisdiction (potestas) by that lex regiawhich is passed concerning the imperium
of the princeps."53 The office towhich Ulpian refersmay be anachronistic, but
the reasoning is not: when Cicero argues thatnothing so harmonizes with justice
and

the laws of nature

as imperium,

he

intends

by

that phrase

the legitimate

exercise of power by a magistrate. The magistrate should command "justly,


beneficially, and inaccordancewith the laws"; the law thusprescribesmagistrates'
power

of command

in specific

ways,

even

as it urges

the citizen

to obey

that

power in its legitimate domain.54Greek political vocabulary did not connote the
same limitations and tended to describe instead theRoman magistrate's control
over, and governance by, coercive force; not understanding the termprovincia
in its non-geographical sense, Greeks were unable to reconcile the seemingly
limitless powers granted to holders of imperiumwith theultimate and unqualified
sovereignty of thepopulus Romanus.55
As a consequence of his subordination to the populus, a Roman magistrate
could justify his actions by appealing to his patriotic sentiment, his studium rei
publicae,

but a Hellenistic

monarch,

who

had similar-indeed,

often

inferior

coercive force at his disposal, accepted no such constitutional link between


51. On the lack of ideological import behind the rare, and exceptional, usage "king of the
Macedonians," see F.W. Walbank in CAH2 VII.1 64-66.
52. Livy 29.12.12-14; Polybius 22.7-8.
53. Dig. 1.4.1 .pr On theRepublican origins of Augustan construals of imperium see Beranger
1977.
54. Cicero Leg. 3.2-5.
55. See Magie 1905 s.v. orMason 1974:132-34. Of course, theRomans hadmaintained that the
consuls' potestas was genere ipso ac iure regia (Cicero Rep. 2.56). See Livy 2.1.7-8 and 2.7.7:
The iinperium of the consuls was more limited than regia potestas only in duration, and yet the
people appreciated that itsmaiestas visque were greater than those of the suspect consul Valerius.

This content downloaded from 99.72.109.133 on Tue, 17 Nov 2015 20:21:55 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

17

ANDO:Was Rome a polis?

himself and any community.56This generalization oversimplifies the range of


ideologies governing the eastern monarchies of the third and second centuries,
but I concentrate here on themuch vaster gulf that separates them from Rome.
On the rare occasions on which Hellenistic kings referred to their =TopL8eq,
they signified only an emotive link to the city of their origin.57 Indeed, this is
precisely the period when themeanings of ta-tp'Ldiverge, separating the notion
of "birthplace" from "the object of one's patriotic sentiment and nationalistic
aspirations." Similarly, loyalty toward a king, expressed through the titulature
of his "Friends,"was a personal relationship, not grounded in theirmutual love of
a shared native land or community.58
Polybius in the second century had already understood something of the
obstacle facing Hellenistic Greeks in their encounters with Rome. According
to him, someone with a limited perspective might easily extrapolate from the
functional power of magistrates or the senate or thepeople atRome to an erroneous
assessment of theRoman government asmonarchical, aristocratic, or democratic
in turn.The language of Polybius stresses that this fictive observer was just that,
an observer,who would errwhile watching themagistrate in action or viewing the
senate while the consuls were absent.59To rewrite Polybius in the terms of the
present inquiry, these individuals interpreted the exercise of authority at Rome
using theparadigms provided by Hellenistic political thought.Polybius corrected
these individuals by asserting thatHellenistic paradigms provided only a partial
model forRome, by yielding exemplars for each branch of themixed constitution.
Extrapolation through analogical extension from any one of these exemplars was
thus doomed to failure.
Given

thus to misconstrue

of Greeks

the tendency

the exercise

of authority,

suspect thataLatin source-Cornelius Sisenna?-rather thanaccounts derivative


from the ambassadors
revealed

Mithridates,

sent to Rome
to Appian

of Bithynia

by Prusias

that the urban praetor,

on the eve of war with


o 'P&otiocdLWv
GTpWC-yo

Ev QCTcEL,
deliberately delayed introducing them to the Senate. In comparison,
the description
baffling. Rumor

of Rome
reported

in the first book of Maccabees


they make

to help

and to make

depose,

and they have been greatly

kings,

kings;

exalted.

seems

at once astute and

that "those whom

to Judas Maccabeus

and those whom

the Romans
they wish

wish
they

Yet for all this not one of them has

56. E.g. Memmius at Sallust Iug. 31. 1.


57. See Welles 1934, no. 45 (= IGLS 3.2.1183), 11.4-5, no. 67 (= OGIS 331 IV), 11.5-6, or
no. 71 (OGIS 257), 11.15-16. Indeed, the ability of Antiochus VIII to display both "piety" and
"generosity" to Seleucia, his 7out-p'L,signifies the break: "piety" signifies his emotive obligations,
but "generosity" reveals thatwealth and privilege are his to give, and to take away.
58. On the institutionalization of "friendship," see Habicht 1958. For a broader treatmentof the
phenomenon, considering the changing perception of such "friendships" amongGreeks, seeHerman
1980/81.
6.12.9
;trMlv av, &r" TLg El
59. Polybius
(65oa' elxO6&;
X
aOlXLXO'xVEGtL 'c6
6LOTlVOVOCPLXOXV 0C7)&)( Xcl
TOoX[TruVa),
6?1L8T)V ORnl '7 frCXOpVTO, Ut0ctTOU.. .), and cf. 6.14.12.

rCv 4SpEL8(,
T(XUtTV C'7OPAxELr
6.13.8
(?t Ov T&XLV &OiOIT .Lr

This content downloaded from 99.72.109.133 on Tue, 17 Nov 2015 20:21:55 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

18

CLASSICAL
ANTIQUITY

put on a crown

or clothed

Volume 18/No. 1/April 1999


in purple

himself

as a mark

of pride. And

they have

built a council-chamber for themselves, and each day three hundred and twenty
men take counsel, deliberating concerning the people, to govern themwell. They
trust one man

each year

to rule over

them and to control

all their land; they all

obey one man and there is no envy or jealousy among them."'Without Appian's
narrative, Iwould leap to the conclusion that these Jews, desiring to interpret the
exercise of power at Rome in terms familiar fromHellenistic monarchies, have
here described a consul and assumed that therewas only one of them. But in
light of Appian's story,we should perhaps leave open the possibility thatearnest
ambassadors mistook for a king-like magistrate themere praetor who ordered
them about.6'

III. THE DEVELOPMENT OF A MODEL


BETWEEN POLYBIUS AND DIODORUS
Let us now connect two problems already raised: the identityof theRomans in
thenarrativeof Posidonius and the size of theRoman citizen body. It is impossible
to know precisely whom Mithridates targeted for extermination in the cities of
Asia early in 88 B.C.62Two contemporary letters byMithridates survive, which
and do not address the extermination as such, leaving us
refer only toWPuIaXoL,
with the same difficulty thatwe encountered in the textof Posidonius.A Posidonius
believed thatMithridates received embassies from Carthage and the peoples of
Italy, seeking his aid in the destruction of Rome.64 Appian, on the other hand,
attributed toMithridates the knowledge thatRome was preoccupied with a civil
war against the Italians but nevertheless argued that he included both Romans
and Italians

in his plot.65 Cicero,

speaking,

to be sure, before

a Roman

audience,

lamented only themassacre of cives Romanos.66 Even if, as seems probable,


Mithridates wished only citizens to die, many Greeks throughoutAsia clearly
did not differentiate

between

the Romans

who

ruled the empire

and the Italian

publicani who profited from it.67

60. IMacc. 8:13-16.


61. Cf. Shaw 1995:378-80, arguing that Josephus under the Principate, as opposed to Polybius
and the author of IMaccabees, felt little need to explain the structureof Roman government because
he could interpret the Principate as "a form of personal power" "much like thatwhich typified his
own world."
62. The sources are canvassed byMagie 1950, vol. 2:1103 n. 36; Brunt 1987:223-27; andmore
briefly by J. G. F. Hind in CAH2 IX 149 n. 67. For the chronology of events between 91 and 87,
Badian 1976 remains fundamental.
63. Welles 1934 nos. 73 and 74, from theChaeremon dossier, fromNysa on theMaeander.
64. Fr. 253 Kidd, 11.87-92.
65. Appian Mith. 22.83.
66. Leg. Man. 3.7 and 5.1 1; cf. Livy Per. 78.
67. Appian Mith. 23.91.

This content downloaded from 99.72.109.133 on Tue, 17 Nov 2015 20:21:55 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

ANDO:Was Rome a polis?

19

If many easterners drew no distinction between Romans and Italians, ac


cording to what political structure did they imagine the Italian peninsula to be
arranged?That is to say, throughwhat paradigm could they envision a political
collectivity uniting cities throughout Italy in the shared task of world conquest?
For what surprisedGreeks was not the size of the Roman army: anyone with
enough money could hire an equivalent number of mercenaries. Rather, Rome
fielded enormous armies of citizens and allied Italians, all of whom had something
patriotic, and not just pecuniary, at stake in theoutcome of thebattle. Surely some
understanding of thatproblem, correct or not, underlies the famous letterof Philip
V toLarisa fromAugust 215, inwhich he commended theRomans for extending
the franchise to freedmen. "In thatway," he wrote, "they have sent out colonies to
nearly seventy places."68And surely forGreeks so inclined, an appreciation of the
unity of Italy could provide a paradigm for theirown gradual assimilation into the
corridors of power within theRoman government.
We should be chary of holding Greeks to an unreasonable standard.Romans
had themselves aspired tounite Italy at an emotive level only in the lateRepublic,
and they did not all share in that objective

even

then.69 Nor

did Romans

develop

a helpful vocabulary to describe relations between Rome and the cities of Italy
under such a plan. Livy, for example, described Servius Tullius as wanting to
unify the cities of Latium under Roman leadership, in which case the city of
Rome would become the caput rerum-not the stuff of catchy political slogans.70
In attempting to express what such a unity would constitute, Romans of the
middle Republic no less thanGreeks were hampered by traditionaldefinitions of
patria

and of citizenship.

Put simply,

a patria was

the place whence

one's

family

sprang, and in thatcommunity one held citizenship: political rights in some far-off
polity were, through sheer impracticality, regarded and explicitly labeled as such,
as though not

intended

to be exercised.

As we have

seen,

the Romans

defined

citizenship through intersecting legal, emotive, and participatory criteria, while


Greeks allowed that citizenship followed blood. Insofar as citizenship inGreek
states did not depend

on an individual's

actions,

it could conceivably

be bestowed

on an individualwho would not exercise its rights or fulfill its obligations.7'

68. SIG 543, from August 215: seeWalbank 1972:156 n. 151 and the literature cited there.
Compare the astonishment of Pyrrhus at the rebirth of the army of Valerius Laevinus: he remarked
that the legions of theRomans, like a hydra, when cut down grew whole again (Cass. Dio 9 fr. 28).
69. Augustus' claim that tota Italia swore an oath of loyalty to him (ResGestae 25.2) illustrates
the vast changes which had taken place since the state of Italia rose against Rome in 90/89; it also
looks back to the enormous propaganda campaign thatAugustus had waged precisely to unite Italy
against the victor ab Aurorae populis et litore rubro. See Gabba 1978. For up-to-date summaries of
evidence, concentrating more on process than on cause, see David 1994 andM. Crawford, CAH2
X 414-33 and 979-89. On the integration of Italy as an intellectual problem in late Republican
literature, see Habinek 1998:88-102.
70. 1.45.3.
71. See at notes 39-43, with the literaturecited there.

This content downloaded from 99.72.109.133 on Tue, 17 Nov 2015 20:21:55 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

20

Volume 18/No. 1/April 1999

CLASSICAL
ANTIQUITY

Thus, for example, those who regard hospitium publicum as a status that
brought "all the private rights and privileges of Roman citizenship" without "its
burdens and obligations" seem, tome at least, to have misunderstood its import.72
Hospitium publicum was explicitly not a form of citizenship and was, on the
contrary, ideologically distinct from it.73Consider, for example, Cicero's defense
of Lucius Cornelius Balbus: it does not matter for us today, as it did not matter
for Cicero, whether Balbus might, as amatter of law, hold citizenship inGades
and Rome simultaneously.74Before the juryCicero emphasized not thatBalbus
had conformed to any existing statute, but rather thathe had formally renounced
his status as a Gaditanus once he moved his domicile toRome: Cicero insisted
thatBalbus now dealt with his former countrymen through pacts of hospitium,
precisely because hospitium did not imply shared patriotic sentiment. Honorary
citizenship among Greeks, not unlike dual citizenship between a polis and a
league, concretized very different attitudes toward the exclusivity of a patria's
emotive, political, and legal demands.75
municipal Italians aspired
Again, unlike Greeks holding tao- or ouItnoXLtEia,
to full participation in Roman life, and it was themuniceps Cicero who best
articulated an Italian ideal.76In the conversation thatopens the second book of De
legibus,Cicero referred to the land inwhich theywalked as his patria; this elicited
a question fromAtticus: "Have you then twopatriae? Or is our communispatria
the only one? Unless,

that is, you think that Cato's

fatherland was not Rome,

but

Tusculum?" To which Cicero responded: "Absolutely I think that both he and


all othermunicipal nien have twopatriae: one by birth, and one by citizenship....
Thus we consider
by which

we

as our patria

are adopted.

But

both the place where we were


that patria

must

born, and that place

be preeminent

in our affection,

inwhich the name of the res publica signifies the common citizenship of us all.
For her it is our duty
her altar we ought

to die;

to place

to her we ought

and to dedicate,

to give

as it were,

our entire

selves,

and on

all that we possess."77

Cicero thus urged that political loyalties need not stand in conflict with
each other. Although the next sentence evidently emerged badly mutilated in
the archetype of all surviving witnesses to the Leiden corpus,78 it seems clear
thatCicero concluded this section by urging that loyalty to the communis patria
must

take precedence

over

that to any other political

collectivity.

In the hierarchy

of allegiances outlined by Cicero, loyalty towardRome occupies a superordinate


72. E.g. Cornell 1995:321.
73. So, rightly,Humbert 1978:139-43 and Brunt 1987:515-16.
74. See Balb. 28-30, 42-43, and Caec. 100, and cf. Brunt 1982, Rawson 1985, and Errington
1988:153. Contra: Sherwin-White 1973:302-304.
75. See Gawantka 1975 and Beck 1997:174-85.
76. Roman patriotism received exemplary treatment in Bonjour 1975. I believe that she has
supplied a proper framework for approaching the topic, although I do not always sympathize with
her reading of individual texts.
77. Leg. 2.5.
78. Schmidt 1974.

This content downloaded from 99.72.109.133 on Tue, 17 Nov 2015 20:21:55 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

21

ANDO:Was Rome a polis?

position: her laws and her culture provide thenormative fabric thatwill, to borrow
the phrase of Rutilius Namatianus, "create from distinct and separate nations a
single fatherland."79
InDe legibus Cicero could ignore the Social War. Appian could not. His
narrative of the political machinations leading up to the Social War participates
in two important trends in Hellenistic thought. First, Appian played the race
card. According to him, Gaius Gracchus reasoned that the Senate could not
refuse to grant full citizenship to the Latins because they were "of the same
race."80Second, he acknowledged the complaint by Italians thatcitizenship could
not be held piecemeal: the Italians desired citizenship "so that theymight be
Whatever its provenance, Appian's
partners in the empire, rather than subjects."'81
history of these years recognizes two categories-ruler and ruled-and these are
distinguished in the first instance along ethnic lines.
Dionysius of Halicarnassus approached relations between Rome and her
Italian allies in a very different fashion and, given his declared desire to educate
his fellow

Greeks,

we would

be remiss

if we

failed

to read his narrative

as a

polemic with contemporary relevance. As Livy did in the same era, Dionysius
connected the legal details of Rome's relationswith her Latin allies to the reign of
Servius, althoughDionysius posited a source for Servius in thatking's admiration
forAmphictyon and theAmphictyonic council.82But Dionysius brought to the
entire issue a Hellenistic sense of wonder at the sheer size and structureof the
Roman state, one directly continuous with the remarksof Philip V.83More so than
his Roman counterparts, Dionysius attributed the fundamental rules of Roman
government toRomulus.84 The most significant of these rules by far, he argued,
established Roman policy on citizenship. Romulus extended citizenship to all free
men, including select members of conquered cities, and he started thepractice of
sending

colonies,

&.toLxoua., to occupy

some portion

of the land in any conquered

territory.By thismeasure he increased the citizen body and stretched the tentacles
of Roman power throughoutLatium.85
Dionysius explicitly contrasted this practice with that of contemporary
Greeks. Taking up the comparison of constitutions, he declared allGreek states in
79. Rut. Namat. 1.63.
80.

BCiv.

1.23.99:

xal

TOuR Aa-cLvouv

Erl

Taivo

aPoiXc,(v,
ex&CXEL t&

S OCux EUTpET1J)5

tr( f3ouXi( (V-CLOtT)VaL


UyYYEVEAL
8uvocievr). P.A. Brunt is quite right to describe his analysis
of "the concept of Italian unity" in the context of the Social War as concerned with Romanization:
Brunt 1988:111-20, esp. 112-13.
81. BCiv. 1.34.152.
82. Livy 1.45; Dion. Hal. Ant. Rom. 4.23-25.
83. Cf. Gabba 1991:19-20.
84. Although Gabba 1991:162-63 remains unconvinced, I follow Balsdon 1971 in seeing the
"constitution of Romulus" as a fully Dionysian product. See also Poma 1989 at 201-203, as well
asMiles 1995:124-25.
85. Dion. Hal. Ant. Rom. 2.16. On Dionysius' understanding of Roman citizenship and the
contrasts he drew with theGreek world see Humbert 1978:85-143 but esp. 86-99, as well as Poma
1989.

This content downloaded from 99.72.109.133 on Tue, 17 Nov 2015 20:21:55 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

22

CLASSICAL
ANTIQUITY

Volume 18/No. 1/April 1999

this respect as failures: the Spartans, Athenians, and Thebans jealously guarded
their birthrights and granted citizenship to no one. As a consequence, each lost
their hegemony after a single defeat.86 Dionysius credited both Romulus and
Servius with a desire for world conquest; believing that the size of the Roman
state had been an important factor in her success, he attributed to both kings a
desire to increase the body of citizen-soldiers. He articulated the goals of this
policy most eloquently in his version of a speech delivered by Appius Claudius
during thewar with Coriolanus: "For all the Latins, towhom we recently gave
equal rights of citizenship, will standby us, fighting for thispolis as if theirpatria,
and themany good cities colonized from here will protect Rome, regarding it as
imperative that theirmetropolis be saved."87
I highlight two features of this remarkable passage. First, Dionysius has
followed Cicero and crossed the emotive boundaries of Hellenistic forms of dual
citizenship. The Latins ought tovalue Rome as apatria, above and beyond the city
of theirbirth. Second, Dionysius no less thanPhilip attributedan ideal strength to
the bonds between Rome and her colonies. Despite his assiduous and arduous
reading of Thucydides, Dionysius clearly had not learned that citizens of Greek
colonies did not automatically esteem theirmetropolis as theirpreeminent ntxTpL.
Indeed, itmay well be thatGreek cities of the second century petitioning Rome
for the status of a Roman colony transliterated the Latin colonia because they
recognized, even if they never quite articulated, that the semantic field of &7COLXLca
did not match the purely emotive attachment that their requestwas intended to
convey.88

The history of Greek politics did offer one potentialmodel for the integration
of several

communities

into a single

state, and that was

the xotLV6V, or league.89

Yet understandingRome on strict analogy with Hellenistic leagues remained an


illusory fantasy. For example, Polybius gave eloquent testimony to the glories
of

the Achaean

league.

"While many

about because

each made

for the acquisition

in bygone

to bring

the

able

to bring

this

the effort not for the sake of the common

freedom

but

into a state of common

Peloponnese

of personal

power.

advantage,
Yet

times

attempted

no one was

in my

time this object

has been

so

completely realized that there exists among them not only an allied and friendly
but they use the same

community,

laws and weights

and measures

and coinage,

86. Dion. Hal. Ant. Rom. 2.17.1-2; theargument is repeatedby Tacitus' Claudius (Ann. 11.24.4),
though not in this form by Claudius himself-perhaps a satirical reference throughDionsyius to
Claudius' Greek learning.
87. Dion.
8E8cw,tv,

Hal.

oL T' EVOEV86

Ant.

Rom.

v l

aTOO0l,

7.53.5:

-re yap

TTjv LotLOXJL;CEliV
otg vEWCr
tCXavCEq,
"
t
Trz Tc ccp
TiT98E
aY KVL6XsC
8i1pn
XOLXL9OSELOOCLTtO6XeLSTOXXoXLxcXt &yaC'L TCEP'L
TXVTOc TCOLOUlE4V0L CYW'E{79OXl

GU
ovu

"Aocttvo'l

Ti) VUycp7tO-AOXLV 0t1UVOU5LV aOj."

88. For petitions toRome for colony status seeMillar 1993:143-44, 147, 150, 155. and 257-58.
For the use of xoXwv(e)Lot, see Millar 1990:9-10.
89. Greek terminology for confederate states and their institutions is notoriously vague: see
Larsen 1955:24-25, 87-92, and Beck 1997:10-19.

This content downloaded from 99.72.109.133 on Tue, 17 Nov 2015 20:21:55 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

ANDO:Was Rome a polis?

23

as well as the same magistrates, councils, and courts: the entire Peloponnese
falls short of having the arrangement of a single polis in this respect alone, that
its inhabitants are not enclosed by a single wall, but in other respects-both in
common and city by city-conditions are nearly identical."90This formulation
of the achievement of theAchaean league maps the parameters within which
Polybius, as aHellenistic writer, could conceive of a community in its corporate
identity.Thus, inmatters thatconcern othermember cities, individualpoleis must
cease to command the specific loyalties of their citizens; at the same time, the
xolvov
was

itself did not become

a political

ideal

in its own

right:

the ideal xoiv6v

a polis.

In contrast to Polybius, theAugustan writers Dionysius and Diodorus each


display-albeit in different fashions-the influence of Roman conceptions of
community. It is not that they coined new words, or transliteratedLatin; on
the contrary, they employed the terminology of Polybius. Yet we may detect
in their usage subtle shifts in the meanings of the terms themselves, as they
stretched to embrace the institutions to which they were now applied. When
Dionysius described the foundationof theLatin league underServius, he attributed
that king's inspiration to the paradigm provided by the Amphictyonic league.
According toDionysius, the cities in that league had laws common to the league
and laws unique to themselves.9"Dionysius did not draw attention to Servius'
departure from that plan, but, like Livy, he argued both that Servius assigned
leadership in the league to Rome and also that the Latin communities assented
to that plan.92 Although

Dionysius

had argued

that the Latins

formed

a natural

unity because of their sharedGreek descent, Diodorus understood that the Italians
who

against Rome

rebelled

in the Social War came from many

different

cities and

peoples.93 In his narrative they came together, however, as Italians. As Italians


they fortified
established

Corfinum
a common

rule their patria

as their xowVj

toXUL,and it was

senate of five hundred men,

and those capable

in that city

from whom

that "they

those worthy

of taking thought for the common

to

safety would

be chosen."94Diodorus has here successfully envisioned, through an analysis of


Italians imitatingRomans, a political union inwhich individuals abandon their
partisan

loyalties

and communis

to race and polis

and direct

them instead

toward a single polis

patria.

the key clause


being xcOo6Xou
be -coit
,oivo
90. 2.37.9-11,
8tLoXXa&CeLV tou VuvLoij
'
elBk
AU,lOCVa
tC
0V InV
x tv cXUt6 v EepLf3oXov
tcv Ga[
IkXrt6vvr)ao
OZvy)(YOVI
8lO'COelLV 'eXELVO6v
axe
, ZlnTVajo
lO)XeW(;
Te
'
A 0
tOl, XOtOLXOuaLV aUrT)V, TCXXaX
LVOXL
XXd XOLVj XAl XOCtl LO6XEL;EX&aGTOL5 -CuO
U7TCXPXELV

xci

potpa7txYaCLOC.
91. Dion. Hal. Ant. Rom. 4.25.3.
92. Dion. Hal. Ant. Rom. 4.26.1-2.
93. Diodorus 37.1.6: .csxva-rr&vv
94.

Diodorus

XEVItVOL, NwXavoL,
nEvTaLxocatv
OtLTpoPou

rev90otL

yap tCOvXaxT&T)v'ICxXv

e,ovcv ....

Il
Ee PwLcx'LOL; EaUV-aL,
Aaxo)cwvoL',
Aeuxavot,
XOLVTv
XaL ETepRt TO'XEL(xai eOviq .... EuvEa-Cj%OvCrO 8E xat cuYxX7nyov
(Ej O'L e tT) T(XrpL8O;
E,~ xv
APXSLV C'LOL TXpOaeCFO0a
6VEXXOV XoI

37.2.4-5:

'EnoX4Eouv

8UVcXI.ELVOLrTEpiLCY XOLVT) O-T)PLO;.

This content downloaded from 99.72.109.133 on Tue, 17 Nov 2015 20:21:55 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

24

CLASSICAL
ANTIQUITY

Volume 18/No. 1/April 1999

We can observe the development and exploitation of this language in that


most Hellenistic of historical genres, universal history. Given some anecdotes
connecting Ephorus to Isocrates, scholarly imaginations have naturally assumed
that the first universal history culminated in a paean to the unification of the
world under a united Hellas.95 But if it was first the dream of an Alexander,
and thenAlexander himself who made universal history possible,96 itwas Rome
thatmade universal history meaningful. Polybius gave voice to this view in his
preface, after judging the achievements of previous empires to be lacking: none
of them had truly conquered theworld. But since the start of the second Punic
war, "history became like an organicwhole" inwhich the events of East andWest
tended toward a single t?Xoq.97Yet for Polybius the Roman empire remained
the natural culmination of man's natural tendency towards imperialism: he felt
no need to disguise its coercive force. Although he continued his history from
167 to 146 specifically to understandwhether Rome governed her territorieswith
the same intelligence with which she had conquered them, he did not expect the
empire to be anything other than an agglomeration of conquered territories: itwas
a 8uvaa-m(a,

and the Romans

were

Eyxpocre6;

or xpaxouvrEq.

They

ruled over

others because they had the power to do so.98


Of the universal histories written in the age of Augustus, thatof Diodorus is
themost complete. Dionysius, aswe have seen, intendedhis narrative to endwhere
Polybius began, though itwas no less politically charged for itspreoccupationwith
ancient history. Diodorus carried this political program a step further, not least
in his integrationof Stoic political philosophy with universal history.99Diodorus
understood universal history in precisely the terms outlined above; in fact, he
opened

his work

a review

with

of

the political

power

wielded

by authors

of

universal histories. "Furthermore,these authors have aspired to gather allmen


who

share with each other ties of kinship

beneath

one and the same narrative

and yet are separated

structure,

as if they were

in time and place


the agents of divine

Providence. For Providence, assembling the order of the visible stars and the
natures of men into a common relation, continually directs all things for eternity,
to each

distributing

thing the lot cast for it by fate; similarly

those writing

up the

95. E.g. Fornara 1983:42-46. Momigliano 1984 implicitly argues against such simplistic,
'rhetorical"models. Cf. K. Sacks 1990:36.
96. See Tarn 1948, vol. 2:399-449. Badian 1958may have successfully denied the relevance of
"cosmopolitanism" to the study of Alexander, but his work does nothing to disprove the effect of
Alexander's conquests on theGreek political imagination.
97.

Polybius

3UVEf3tLVE; Tk

1.3.3-5:
T7(

ev

lIbv

O'LXOUie;Vi5

ouiv

TOl5

TpO' EL;,

UT
Tp6OTOU6TWV XpOVOlq 6r, aEv
EIVOU
1topab&X
TO\
OaS 7tnLOXO),(q 8E
xat
8\ca TO XXL XXa\
E`C

OuvTEXELO(
Ocu`v O6qOl(&8e;xOCxczta toC\ t6itoU<;&yineXCLV
iexxcracctxv nenpczyVESvx. aci.o
8E TOUTCOVT&V Xalp&OV O'LOV Et 06

Ea'Itc)Xixa

xcx3.ALvx&

Titp6r i'v YLIVe(YOCLt6?,Xo(

aTOCL87 aUIPcxLVeL yiVEGOaL T V LOTopiav,

-cp\,el to

-Ci\v &Vayopopv

ouVnXe6aXOL

TC oua& xcv AOL'ov xcd Talg 'EXrnVLxO(ZXcoct

&ot&vtrcov.

98. Walbank 1965 and 1972:173-81; cf. Eckstein 1985.


99. See Pavan 1991 and Camoux and Bertrac 1993:xviii-xxii.

This content downloaded from 99.72.109.133 on Tue, 17 Nov 2015 20:21:55 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

ANDO:
Was
Rome
apolis?

25

common history of theworld as though of a single zT6XiL


have produced in their
treatises a unified narrative and common storehouse of historical knowledge."'00
Diodorus latercontrasted the four great empires of world history, as the rules
of his genre demanded. But he clearly saw theRoman empire as a very different
entity than any which had preceded it. Rome's uniqueness did not stem from
her control over the entire oixouue'vr. Diodorus understood thatmen derived a
common kinship from their shared humanity, but he also understood that that
had not been and was not in itself sufficient to unite them. Diodorus could not,
therefore, articulate theRoman achievement using oLxou,evr)-it was, for him,
simply a geographical term-nor could he use the vocabulary of empires. To
speak of empires was to invoke a dichotomy of ruler and ruled. Rome had done
far more

than conquer men.

Rather,

Rome

had united

all men

no less than the

universal historianswho connected them through theirauv-r&TELq.


Rome therefore
crowned the succession of world empires precisely because itwas not an empire:
itwas apolis. On thisunderstanding, even the choice of genre becomes a political
decision: "writing the common history of theworld as though of a single not6Xi"
construes narrative not merely as the representation, but as the construction of
a political reality.ForDiodorus, theRoman empirewas thenatural culmination of
man's desire to gather in themost natural form of political collectivity.
Authors of theSecond Sophistic display their allegiance to this understanding
of the empire in various ways. Lucian, for example, referred toRome repeatedly
as "The City."'01

In this period,

too, authors

to describe

began

as a city

Rome

whose countryside was the empire. Aelius Aristides delivered themost famous
development of this theme in his panegyric toRome, inwhich he added the detail
that the armies

on the borders were

of a single,

like the walls

great

city.'02 At

one level suchmetaphors and themodels they represented arose from theGreek
tendency to divide theworld between Greeks and barbarians,'03and on that level
theirusage must reflect aGreek desire to lump themselves togetherwith Romans
as common participants in a single ethnic and political reality.Yet thesemetaphors
accomplished thatdesire throughawholly Greek attempt to envision the residents
of the empire

as the inhabitants

of a single

city. On

these

terms,

the erroneous

definition of pomerium given in theSuda-"Pomerium: aminiature representation


of a city wall"-may
the pomerium
of a wall

be unraveled."'4

to be some

around

a city

To be sure, the compiler

sort of wall.

But why

could have thought

use a miniature

that had a real one? Perhaps

because

representation

the wall which

the

100. Diodorus 1.1.3. On the strands of thought intersecting in this passage, andDiodorus' role in
bringing them together, see Sacks 1990:10-11, 36, and 64. Among earlier literature, see esp. Burton
1972:35-38.
101. See, e.g., Nigrinos 2, 16, 29, 34, and cf. Jones 1986:85 n. 31. Elsewhere see Philostratus Vit.
Soph. 488 and 534.
102. Or. 26.80-81.
103. Palm 1959:56-62, 75-76, and 82-83; J.Vogt 1967:8-9 and Brunt 1990:473-77.
104.

Suda

[I 2178:

fI&un5ptov

-o

tou

LeLXouq sExo6vLaGcX.

This content downloaded from 99.72.109.133 on Tue, 17 Nov 2015 20:21:55 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

26

CLASSICAL
ANTIQUITY

Volume 18/No. 1/April 1999

pomerium representedwas the imaginarywall around the borders of the empire,


throughwhich the community of theempire became coextensive with the territory
of itspolis.
IV.COMPLICATIONS
The

author of

the first book

AND CONSEQUENCES

of Maccabees

was

not alone

in his desire

to

see power exercised at Rome by a single, all-powerful magistrate, whom the


Romans entrusted "to rule over them and to control all their land." Scattered
inscriptions and papyri describing embassies to the triumvirs suggest thatGreeks
throughout the East not only welcomed the existence of de facto monarchs
with whom to negotiate, but that they particularly appreciated that access to
thesemen was controlled by others, like somany qlXOLof a Hellenistic king.105
These embassies, which continued unabated for the next four centuries, were
themselves directly continuous with the Greek practice of using embassies to
congratulate a new monarch on his accession while receiving assurances that
the city's status with the central government remained unchanged.'" To these
Greeks, the outcome of the civil wars seemed perfectly natural. In the words
of Appian, "Thus, from its varied internal disorders the Roman state resolved
to harmony andmonarchy."'07Both he and Cassius Dio remarkedupon Roman
reticence

to call a spade a spade: the principate

was,

for them, amonarchy

cloaked

in fancy dress.'08
That fancy dress was the res publica. Imperial ideology continued for cen
turies

to suggest

quarreled

that the emperor

with maiestas

the state:

thus Tacitus

they had no legal justification

that he was

was

trials because

the servant

of

prepared to recognize. He would not have objected, I suspect, to trials based


on the emperor's tribunician sacrosanctity.The application of maiestas, however,
implied that thedignitas of theemperorwas somehow coextensive with thatof the
Roman people, and thatTacitus found intolerable, not least because it conflicted
with the publicly professed ideology of the Principate. A Greek steeped inHel
lenistic political thought could not understand theobjections of aTacitus because,
to put it bluntly, Hellenistic thought had developed a philosophy of kingship but
never one of empire.Nothing inHellenistic rhetoric resembled theuniversalizing
105. On knowledge in the Greek East regarding men's status as amici Caesaris, see Millar
1977:116. Cf. Shaw 1995:378-80, paraphrased in n. 61.
106. Millar 1984.
'

107.
xCa

Appian

,ovapXLctv
108. Appian
s
r

BCiv.

1.6.24:

68e

,uv

?x caO?@t(YV TtOLXLX&V

T0oXL'teLCXPTN0L0Lool

praef
t

6.23: xad 1aicv


t s
ws

r t
"bePiX;
s
*~T)

T)

iUCv
I'XPL VUV
o

E'L
;V. XpXOVtl oU,
t
*

&Vto V) VOVLG), lQOV


OpXOVMCltOUl.eLVOL
l OU XeyOUl,V,
l;OVntEXcXL,
a'utoxp
o XaL t(O3V
tat 8e ppy( t 1tVT
TtpoCxaip&v atpa7y&v ovo,u
OvoIICoucQLv,
See also Cassius Dio 53.17-18 and JohnLydusMag. 1.4 (o`m nxpd
%aiC px
TPWV.EZOL, otov

opvotxv

7CEpLeG-U.

CL npw,TT)V xeyaXpc0v

ti(

7TorS

noXLt-cebx)

and 2.2.

On Greek

fXcOLXErc,

topcX e
l
ea& av

names

Roman emperor, seeWifstrand 1939.

This content downloaded from 99.72.109.133 on Tue, 17 Nov 2015 20:21:55 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

for

the

ANDO:Was Rome a polis?

27

tendencies or the rationalism inherent in the fifthCyrene edict, in its concern for
non-citizen provincials and its allusions to a hierarchical appeals process; nothing
in the ideology of Hellenistic monarchies suggested thatkings were not sovereign
within their territories.When in Roman political oratory the goddess Roma or
thegenius publicus addressed the emperor, the author simultaneously honored his
emperor and yet also suggested thatRome herself was the ultimate repository of
authoritywithin the state. The prosopopoeia of Dea Roma or the genius publi
cus inGreek oratory, which became prevalent only in the fourth century A.D.,
thus represented the penetration of a purely Roman imperial ideology intoGreek
thought, andByzantine legislation retained for the next two centuries this explicit
subordination of emperor to state.109
The breakdown of traditional links between citizenship, city, and fatherland
required considerable negotiation to resolve, nor was its outcome predetermined.
To adapt

the phrase

of Appian,

it was

not necessary

for Rome

to invite

all her

subjects to become equal participants in the empire. Yet in the end theRomans
themselves played no small role in this process. Polybius himself had remarked
that theRomans had thecapacity-which theydid not always act upon-to govern
their subjects wisely.110 As Cicero saw, themore the Romans subordinated the
coercive aspect of their rule, and themore they governed for the good of their
subjects, the greater would be the good realized by both ruler and ruled. For
that reason he urged that a properly governed empire not be called an empire, an
imperium,but a protectorate, apatrocinium. l' Greeks acknowledged this rhetoric
regarding theuniversalization of thebenefits of Roman rule in the age of Augustus,
at which

time the empire

largely ceased

to be a&uvaa-erLo or a xpacioq

and became

an apXt)

Some inscriptions fromAsia Minor in the same period exhibit similar sensi
tivity to the finerpoints of diction. Late in the rule of Augustus themember-cities
of the koinon of Asia erected a series of inscriptions recording honors voted to
the emperor.They named the emperor using his official titulature, translated into
Greek, with one minor but importantaddition. They render the titlepater patriae
as narTp
norpL'8og xai toO a,u'4TEcvtoE Txv oiv6pxTv
yEvou~: "Father of
his fatherland and of the entire human race.""12 At one level, this represents a

perfectly natural adaptation of royal honors from theHellenistic period: kings


at that time were
intrusion

always

of that phrase

benefactors
into several

or saviors

of the human

lines of Latin nomenclature

race. And
must

yet the

have been

109. E.g. N. Maj. 1. Though [Aristides] does not personify Rome or the state, he does describe
the emperor as useful to the empire, implying the priority of the latter (Or. 35.12): ... rov[tEv ,eya
O(prXO(
I 10.

T?) PaGLtXSL
10.36.2,

XtL

iTplV ELS X6T)'V

XxtaoTi(Vxl.

and cf. 3.4. 1.

111. Off 2.8.27: itaque illud patrocinium orbis terrae verius quam imperiumpoterat nominari.
Cf. Erskine 1990:202-203 andDyck 1996 ad loc.
112. Texts collected in Buckler 1935. See IGRR IV 1410.6-7; IGRR IV 1611 (= OGIS 470),
tabletB.6-8; IGRR IV 1756, section X, 11.101-102; and IBM 894.

This content downloaded from 99.72.109.133 on Tue, 17 Nov 2015 20:21:55 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

28

CLASSICAL
ANTIQUITY

Volume 18/No. 1/April 1999

intended, at least in part, to claim Augustus as their father, too. These Greeks
began to share the empire, by first sharing the emperor.
Citizenship remained a contentious issue, of course. But long before the
universal extension of the franchiseGreeks began to use first-person possessive
adjectives to refer to Roman institutions.113In the words of Aelius Aristides:
"You, again, have best proven the common maxim that the earth is themother
and communis

patria

of all. Now

at last it is possible

or non-Greek,

for a Greek

travelingwith orwithout his possessions, to pass wheresoever he wills, as easily


as if traveling from country to country.The Cilician Gates do not cause fear,nor do
the narrow, sandy roads fromArabia toEgypt, nor impassablemountains nor the
endless lengths of rivers nor the savage tribes of barbarians: for safety it suffices
to be a Roman or, rather, simply one of those under your rule."'14We should,
I believe, read the last sentence as a prescriptive slip of the tongue: realizing
that "Roman," strictly construed, meant "Roman citizen," his correction urged
the extension of the franchise by thanking theRomans for extending the benefits
of empire to all.
Aristides does not envision an empire whose residents link their identity
as Romans to some abstract political community, which has a capital but is
nevertheless defined by the geographic and imaginative dispersal of its citizens.
On

the contrary:

as we

have

seen, Aristides

lacked

and a term for a

a model

national state.He has rather succumbed to that reasoning which, with the benefit
of hindsight, Cassius Dio put in themouth of Maecenas in the fateful debate
of 29 B.C.: by giving his subjects a share in their governance, Augustus could
bring it about that they "believe themselves equal participants in the politeia
and thus become
of us all,

our faithful

regarding

allies,

as though

in some unified

they dwelt

and their cities

as truly their own,

this polis

city

as its fields

and villages."'15 Dio's clumsy expression in this climactic phrase divulges the
poverty

of his political

his selection

vocabulary

of Rome

over Nicaea

even as it discloses
as the primary

the model

object

that exonerated

of his loyalties

and the

beneficiary of his talents. Libanius participated in the same mentality as Dio,


albeit with
polis

different

of their origin

attitude, when

he argued

and "the polis

founded

that men must


by a certain

choose

emperor"

between

the

that drained

the city-councils of theEast."'6


Greeks did not universally subscribe to the binarism that forced Libanius to
choose between Antioch andConstantinople. Career inscriptions throughout the
East celebratemen likeTiberius Claudius Diogenes of Aphrodisias, andwe should
note

that the council

and people

of Aphrodisias

listed

first in their dedication,

13.
I
Instances catalogued by Palm 1959 passim.
114. Or. 26.100.
115. Cassius

Dio

)CFTLEpXOlVLV [cV
(7(p Tepa &ypouc

52.19.6:
t

xai

xiVcr

CUVVLXoL U6lV WYLoV,


cotc6
'LOOVtLpO CVtErRlGtO.
e 8
-OtUTV 4EV OVT
TtOXLVta
nOtXLV OLXOU5VrE, XXl

. .. 'Lxvoxot

)V ICpEE V

VoViLoVtEg

etVal.

116. Libanius Or. 49.2.

This content downloaded from 99.72.109.133 on Tue, 17 Nov 2015 20:21:55 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

29

ANDO:Was Rome a polis?

in positions of priority, Diogenes' priesthoods in the imperial cult."7 Yet their


perspective, like thatof Plutarch, urgedmen likeDiogenes to use their influence
with imperial officials for the benefits of their local cities: the binarism is there, if
it is not destructive."8 Romans did not subscribe to the necessity of this choice.
Cicero's achievement inDe legibus had been toprivilege a legal abstraction as the
basis for a largercommunity. Other Romans may not have been as sophisticated
inmatters of political theory as Cicero, yet neither Virgil nor Ovid nor Tacitus
felt the need to sacrificeMantua or Sulmo or Gallia Narbonensis to the claims
of Rome.
What about those provincials who did feel loyal toward Rome and who,
well before theConstitutio Antoniniana formally embraced them, felt their safety
ensured by Rome's success? What was to stop a non-citizen provincial from
identifying himself as Roman, in order to celebrate his love of his country
and his membership in her community? To return to the language of Paul,
I believe

it was

necessary

in the era of

the martyrs

of Lyons

to specify

that

some of those Christians held Roman citizenship-and not simply to identify


them as Roman-precisely because so many non-citizens had begun identifying
themselves as Roman."'' Insofar as this revolution in provincial self-definition
was aided by the universalizing themes of imperial rhetoric and by long-standing
awareness of Rome's willingness to extend its franchise, itwas for similar reasons
that the term "peregrine" disappeared in legal texts of the later empire. The
ConstitutioAntoniniana obviously rendered it irrelevantwithin theempire, but the
government did not subsequently classify those outside theempire as "peregrine":
to do so would have implied that those outside the empire possessed a character
equivalent to the recently enfranchised within. Legal texts of the later empire
thereforedivide humanity between Roman and barbarian.
The rapid spread of citizenship and the dissolution of the category "Roman"
was not altogether to Rome's liking. It could have promoted egalitarianism,
a distinctly un-Roman concept. Sporadic claims of citizenship in legal contexts
remindus that some benefits continued to accrue to citizens, especially in criminal
courts.

But

even

as these appeals went

on,

the government

began

to recognize

a very different division of the population, into honestiores and humiliores. No


extant text defines

these terms, but two facts emerge

from those texts that recognize

the categories: first, appeal to these categories becomes markedly more frequent
from themiddle of the second century on and, second, "thehonestiores/humiliores
distinction cut across the citizen/alien one: therewere citizens and aliens on both
sides of thedividing line."'20The vast expansion of the semantic field of Romanus,
coupled

with

the increasingly

rapid extension

of

the franchise,

thus had as its

117. Reynolds 1981:321 no. 4.


118. See PlutarchMoralia (Praec. ger. reip.) 814C, togetherwith Jones 1971:113-16.
1 19. See

the texts cited

in n. 22.

120. Garnsey 1970:266.

This content downloaded from 99.72.109.133 on Tue, 17 Nov 2015 20:21:55 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

30

CLASSICAL
ANTIQUITY

Volume 18/No. 1/April 1999

inevitable consequence the development of new categories of status, categories,


most importantly, thatwere not determined by the language of ethnicity.
IfGreeks slowly shifted their conceptions of homeland and of city to accom
modate their participation in imperial government and ultimately to justify their
loyalty to the imperial city, what became of the classical city? In his narrative of
events inAthens during theMithridatic war, Posidonius put a speech in themouth
of the demagogue Athenion, inwhich that self-appointed philosopher urged the
Athenians to "tolerate no longer the anarchywhich the senate of theRomans has
allowed to continue, until it should see fit todecide how we are to be governed."'2'
Athenion and his followers chafed at the disjunction between Roman rhetoric an
nouncing the freedom of Greek poleis and the realities of Roman rule.More than
a century later,Plutarch still felt called upon to comment on this feature of Roman
rule: "Being yourself governed, you govern a city managed by proconsuls, the
procurators of Caesar."'22Given the technological constraints on transportation
and communication in the ancient world, Rome had little choice but to govern
throughcities, and theempire consequently brought urbanizationof all areas of the
Mediterranean to new heights. Did these cities, the new and the refurbished, laid
out on Roman models and decorated with Roman monuments, ultimately inspire
the sort of partisan loyalty found in classical poleis? I do not think so. Rather,
each new

forum was

a mirror

for that other

forum; each city a representation

of

The City. The improvements in quality of life brought by these urban centers thus
reflected toRome's credit. The slow desertion of the classical city in late antiquity
may have been due, in part, to Christian

withdrawal

from this world

and, in part, it

was a response to the financial and personal duties incumbent on the curial class.
But Rome, ironically, made that desertion possible by lowering the place such
cities held

in the hearts of men.

For Rome

had finally become,

in the words

of the

Syrian Greek andRoman juristModestinus, "the communispatria of us all."'23


University of Southern California
cando@usc.edu
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Austin, M. M. 1986. "Hellenistic kings, war and the economy." CQ 36: 450-66.
Badian, E. 1958. "Alexander the Great and the unity of mankind." Historia 7: 425-44.
. 1976. "Rome, Athens, and Mithridates."
In D. M. Pippidi, ed., Assimilation
et resistance a la culture greco-romaine dans lemonde ancien, 501-21. Paris.
Balsdon, J. P. V. D. 1971. "Dionysius on Romulus." JRS 61: 18-27.

121. Fragment 253 Kidd, 11.94-97.


122. Moralia (Praec. ger. reip.) 813E:
UTWCtOLq, EnvLponOtg

C
.px6VuEvo aPXeL4
U7o0nETCyCvr)q7t6XeXo &vO

KocLacapo,.

123. Modestinus ad Dig. 50.1.33: Roma communis nostra patria est.

This content downloaded from 99.72.109.133 on Tue, 17 Nov 2015 20:21:55 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

ANDO:Was Rome a polis?

31

Beck, H. 1997. Polis und koinon. Untersuchungen


zur Geschichte und Struktur der
griechischen Bundesstaaten
im 4. Jahrhundert v. Chr Stuttgart.
Beranger, J. 1977. "'Imperium,' expression du pouvoir imp6rial." REL 55: 325-44.
Bickerman, E. J. 1952. "Origines gentium." CP 47: 65-81.
Birley, A. R. 1997. Hadrian: The restless emperor. London.
Black, M. 1962. Models and Metaphors.
Ithaca.
Bonjour, M. 1975. Terre natale. Etudes sur une composante affective de patriotisme
romain. Paris.
Bourdieu, P. 1990. The Logic of Practice. Stanford.
Bowersock, G. W. 1965. Augustus and the Greek World. Oxford.
Brunt, P. A. 1982. "The legal issue in Cicero, pro Balbo." CQ 32: 136-47.
1987. Italian Manpower. 2nd. edition. Oxford.
1988. The Fall of the Roman Republic and Related Essays. Oxford.
1990. Roman Imperial Themes. Oxford.
Buckler, W. H. 1935. "Auguste, Zeus Patroos." RPhil. 9: 177-88.
Burton, A. 1972. Diodorus Siculus, Book 1. A Commentary. Leiden.
Camoux, F., and P. Bertrac, eds. 1993. Diodore de Sicile, Bibliotheque Historique. Livre
I. Paris.
Cornell, T. J. 1995. The Beginnings of Rome. London.
Curty, 0. 1995. Les parentes legendaires entre les cites grecques. Geneva.
David, J.M. 1994. La romanisation de l'Italie. Paris.
Derow, P. S. 1979. "Polybius, Rome, and the East." JRS 69: 1-15.
Drexler, H. 1957. "Res publica." Maia 9: 247-81.
. 1958. "Res publica." Maia 10: 3-37.
Dyck, A. R. 1996. A Commentary on Cicero, De Officiis. Ann Arbor.
Eckstein, A. M. 1985. "Polybius, Syracuse, and the politics of accommodation." GRBS
26: 265-82.
. 1990. "Josephus and Polybius: A reconsideration." ClAnt 9: 175-208.
. 1995. Moral Vision in The Histories of Polybius. Berkeley.
Eder, W. 1990. "Der Burger und sein Staat-der
Staat und seine Burger." InW. Eder, ed.,
Staat und Staatlichkeit in derfruhen romischen Republik, 12-32. Stuttgart.
. 1996. "Rechtsentwicklung
in Athen und Rom. Meth
und Verfassungskrise
oden und Moglichkeiten
einer vergleichenden Untersuchung."
In E. Schmidt, ed.,
Griechenland und Rom, 131-51. Thilissi.
Errington, R. M. 1988. "Aspects of Roman acculturation in the East under the Republic."
Festschrift K. Christ, 140-57. Darmstadt.
Erskine, A. 1990. The Hellenistic Stoa. Ithaca.
Fornara, C. W. 1983. The Nature of History inAncient Greece and Rome. Berkeley.
Fuchs, H. 1938. Der geistige Widerstand gegen Rom in der antiken Welt. Berlin.
Gabba, E. 1978. "II problema dell"unita' dell'Italia Romana." La cultura Italica, 11-27.
Pisa.
. 1982. "Political and cultural aspects of the classicistic revival in the Augustan
age." ClAnt 1: 43-65.
. 1984. "The historians and Augustus." In F. Millar and E. Segal, eds., Caesar
Augustus, 61-88. Oxford.
. 1991. Dionysius and theHistory of Archaic Rome. Berkeley.
Garnsey, P. 1970. Social Status and Legal Privilege in the Roman Empire. Oxford.

This content downloaded from 99.72.109.133 on Tue, 17 Nov 2015 20:21:55 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

32

CLASSICAL
ANTIQUITY

Volume 18/No. 1/April 1999

Gauger, J. D. 1980. "Phlegon von Tralleis, Mirab. III. Zu einem Dokument geistigen
Widerstandes gegen Rom." Chiron 10: 223-61.
Gauthier, Ph. 1981. "La citoyennete en Gr6ce et a Rome: Participation et integration."
Ktema 6:167-79.
Gawantka, W. 1975.
Isopolitie. Ein Beitrag zur Geschichte der zwischenstaatlichen
Beziehungen
in der griechischen Antike. Munich.
Giovannini, A. 1993. "Greek cities and Greek commonwealth." InA. Bulloch et al., eds.,
Images and Ideologies, 265-86. Berkeley.
Gruen, E. S. 1982. "Greek Hflat L and Roman Fides." Athenaeum 60: 50-68.
1990. Studies inGreek Culture and Roman Policy. Leiden.
1992. Culture and National Identity inRepublican Rome. Ithaca.
Habicht, C. 1958. "Die herrschende Gesellschaft
in den hellenistischen Monarchien."
Sozial- und Wirtschaftsgeschichte
45: 1-16.
Vierteljahrschriftfiir
. 1985. Pausanias' Guide toAncient Greece. Berkeley.
Habinek, T. N. 1998. The Politics of Latin Literature: Writing, Identity, and Empire in
Ancient Rome. Princeton.
Hall, J.M. 1997. Ethnic Identity inGreek Antiquity. Cambridge.
Hansen, M. H. 1996a. "lToXX0aCX6
no'XiLX6eye-to (Arist. Pol. 1276a23). The Copenhagen
inventory of poleis and the Lex Hafniensis de civitate." In M. H. Hansen, ed.,
Introduction to an inventory of poleis. Symposium August 23-26, 1995, 7-72.

Copenhagen.
. 1996b. "City-ethnics as evidence for polis identity." InM. H. Hansen and K.
Raaflaub, eds., 96-169. More studies in the ancient Greek polis. Stuttgart.
Hartog, F. 1988. The mirror of Herodotus. Trans. J. Lloyd. Berkeley.
"The 'friends' of the early Hellenistic
Herman, G. 1980/1981.
rulers: servants or
officials?" Talanta 12/13: 103-49.
Hidber, R. 1996. Das klassizistische Manifest des Dionys von Halikarnass. Die Praefatio
zu De oratoribus veteribus. Stuttgart.
Humbert, M. 1978. Municipium et civitas sine suffragio. L'organisation de la conquete
jusqu'a' la guerre sociale. Rome.
Instinky, H. U. 1940. "Consensus Universorum." Hermes 75: 265-78.
Jones, C. P. 1971. Plutarch and Rome. Oxford.
1978. The Roman World of Dio Chrysostom. Cambridge.
1986. Culture and Society in Lucian. Cambridge.
-. 1996. "The Panhellenion." Chiron 26: 28-56.
Judge, E. A. 1974. "'Res publica restituta' A modem illusion?" In J. A. S. Evans, ed.,
Polis and Imperium. Studies inHonour of Edward Togo Salmon, 279-31 1. Toronto.
und AwrZvoL." In G. W. Most et al., eds., Philanthropia kai
Kramer, J. 1993. "TPWuCiXot
Eusebeia. Festschrift fur Albre,cht Dihle, 234-47. Gottingen.
Lakoff, G., and M. Turner. 1980. Metaphors We Live By. Chicago.
. 1989. More than Cool Reason: A Field Guide to Poetic Metaphor. Chicago.
-in Greek and Roman History.
Larsen, J. A. 0. 1955. Representative Government
Berkeley.
Magie, D. 1905. De Romanorumjuris publici sacrique vocabulis sollemnibus in graecum
sermonem conversis. Leipzig.
-.
1950. Roman Rule inAsia Minor. Princeton.
Mason, H. J. 1974. Greek Terms for Roman Institutions. Toronto.

This content downloaded from 99.72.109.133 on Tue, 17 Nov 2015 20:21:55 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

ANDO:Was Rome a polis?

33

Meier,

C. 1996.
"Der griechische und der romische Burger. Gemeinsamkeiten
und
im Ensemble gesellschaftlicher
Unterschiede
Bedingungen."
In E. Schmidt, ed.,
Griechenland und Rom, 41-66. Tbilissi.
Miles, G. 1995. Livy. Reconstructing Early Rome. Ithaca.
Millar, F. 1977. The Emperor in the Roman World. Ithaca.
. 1984. "State and subject: The impact of monarchy." In F.Millar and E. Segal,
eds., Caesar Augustus. Seven aspects, 37-60. Oxford.
. 1990. "The Roman coloniae of the Near East: A study of cultural relations." In
H. Solin and M. Kajava, eds., Roman Eastern Policy and Other Studies in Roman
History, 7-58. Helsinki.
1993. The Roman Near East. Cambridge.
Mitchell, S. 1993. Anatolia. Oxford.
Momigliano, A. 1942. "Camillus and Concord." CQ 36: 111-20.
. 1966. "Atene nel III secolo a.c. e la scoperta di Roma nelle storie di Timeo
di Tauromenio." Terzo contributo, 1: 23-53. Rome.
1975. Alien Wisdom. Cambridge.
1984a. "How to reconcile Greeks and Trojans." Settimo contributo, 437-62.

Rome.
1984b. "The origins of universal history." Settimo contributo, 77-103. Rome.
1986. "Some preliminary remarks on the 'religious opposition' to the Roman
empire." EntrHardt 32: 103-29.
Romisches Staatsrecht. Leipzig.
Mommsen, T. 1887-1888.
Nicolet, C. 1979. Rome et la conque^te du monde Meoditerraneen. Vol. 1: Les structures de
l'Italie romaine. Paris.
Nippel, W. 1996. "Recht und Gesetz. Bemerkungen zur Funktion rechtstheoretischer
Reflexion inAthen und Rom." In E. Schmidt, ed., Griechenland und Rom, 152-59.
Tbilissi.
Palm, J. 1959. Rom, Romertum und Imperium in der griechischen Literature der
Kaiserzeit. Lund.
Pavan, M. 1991. "Osservazioni su Diodoro, Polibio e la storiografia ellenistica." In E.
Galvagno and C. Mole Ventura, eds., Mito Storia Tradizione. Diodorus Siculo e la
storiografia classica, 5-16. Rome.
Poma, G. 1989. "Dionigi d'Alicarnasso e la cittadinanza Romana." MEFRA 101: 187

205.
Rawson, E. 1985. "Cicero and theAreopagus." Athenaeum 63: 44-46.
Reynolds, J. 1980. "The origins and beginning of imperial cult at Aphrodisias." PCPhS
26: 70-84.
. 1981. "New evidence for the imperial cult in Julio-Claudian Aphrodisias." ZPE
43: 317-27.
. 1982. Aphrodisias and Rome. London.
Rogers, G. M. 1991. The Sacred Identity of Ephesos. London.
Sacks, K. 1990. Diodorus Siculus and the First Century. Princeton.
Sartre, M. 1991. L'Orient romain: Provinces et societe's provinciales en Me'diterranee
orientale d'Auguste aux Se've'res. Paris.
. 1995. L'Asie Mineure et l'Antatolie d'Alexandre a Diocletien. Paris.
Schmidt, P. L. 1974. Die Uberlieferung von Ciceros Schrift 'De legibus' inMittelalter
und Renaissance. Munich.
Shaw, B. 1995. "Josephus: Roman power and responses to it."Athenaeum 83: 357-90.

This content downloaded from 99.72.109.133 on Tue, 17 Nov 2015 20:21:55 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

34

CLASSICAL
ANTIQUITY

Volume
18/No.1/April1999

Sherwin-White, A. N. 1973. Roman Citizenship. 2nd ed. Oxford.


Soskice, J.M. 1985. Metaphor and Religious Language. Oxford.
Stark, R. 1967. "Res publica." In H. Oppermann, ed., Romische Wertbegriffe, 42-110.
Darmstadt.
Stem, M. 1987. "Josephus and the Roman Empire as reflected in The Jewish War." L.
H. Feldman and G. Hata eds. Josephus, Judaism, and Christianity. Detroit. 71-80.
Swain, S. 1996. Hellenism and Empire. Language, Classicism, and Power in the Greek
World (A.D. 50-250). Oxford.
Sweetser, E. 1990. From Etymology to Pragmatics: Metaphorical
and Cultural Aspects
of Semantic Structure. Cambridge.
Tam, W. W. 1948. Alexander the Great. Cambridge.
Thomas, Y. 1996. "Origine" et "commune patrie." Etude de droit public romain (89
av. J.-C. - 212 ap. J.-C.). Rome.
Vogt, J. 1967. "Kulturwelt und Barbaren: Zum Menschheitsbild
der spatantiken Gesell
schaft." AbhMainz 1967, No. 1.
Walbank, F.W. 1965. "Political morality and the friends of Scipio." JRS 55: 1-16.
. 1972. Polybius. Berkeley.
Welles, C. B. 1934. Royal Correspondence
in theHellenistic Period. New Haven.
Wifstrand, A. 1939. "Autokrator, Kaisar, Basileus. Bemerkungen zu den griechischen
... dedicatum,
Benennungen der romischen Kaiser." DRAGMA Martino P. Nilsson

529-39. Lund.
Wigtil, D. N. 1982. "The ideology of the Greek 'Res Gestae.' "ANRW 2.30.1: 624-38.
Wiseman, T. P. 1995. Remus. A Roman Myth. Cambridge.
Woolf, G. 1993. "Becoming Roman, staying Greek: Culture, identity and the civilizing
process in the Roman East." PCPhS 40: 116-43.
Zetzel, J. E. G., ed. 1995. Cicero: De re publica. Cambridge.

This content downloaded from 99.72.109.133 on Tue, 17 Nov 2015 20:21:55 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Вам также может понравиться