Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 30

The Kin in the Gene The Medicalization of Family and Kinship in American Society

Author(s): Kaja Finkler


Source: Current Anthropology, Vol. 42, No. 2 (April 2001), pp. 235-263
Published by: The University of Chicago Press on behalf of Wenner-Gren Foundation for
Anthropological Research
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/320004
Accessed: 17-07-2016 13:41 UTC
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted
digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about
JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

The University of Chicago Press, Wenner-Gren Foundation for Anthropological


Research are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Current Anthropology

This content downloaded from 200.130.19.150 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 13:41:14 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

C u r r e n t A n t h r o p o l o g y Volume 42, Number 2, April 2001

2001 by The Wenner-Gren Foundation for Anthropological Research. All rights reserved 0011-3204/2001/4202-0003$3.00

The Kin in the Gene


The Medicalization of Family
and Kinship in American
Society1
by Kaja Finkler

In the past several decades there has been an explosion of research in genetics and on genetic inheritance. This new genetics
is part of contemporary biomedicine and forecasts great advances
in alleviating disease and prolonging human life. It also encompasses notions about biological family and kinship relations. I
propose that with the advent of the new genetics, family and
kinship are being medicalized. I explore the ways in which explanations of the inheritance of genetic disease influence peoples
understandings of family and kin and both reflect and conflict
with broader current sociocultural processes. The discussion includes a brief overview of the anthropological study of kinship,
the meaning of family and kinship in contemporary society, and
the concept of medicalization and its implications for peoples
lives as seen through narratives and concludes with an analysis
of the significance of the medicalization of family and kinship in
present-day society.
k a j a f i n k l e r is Professor of Anthropology at the University
of North Carolina, Chapel Hill (Chapel Hill, N.C. 27514, U.S.A.
[kxf9438@email.unc.edu]). She has taught at Eastern Michigan
University (197384) and has been a visiting scholar at the National Autonomous University of Mexico, the University of
Newcastle, and the University of Freiburg. Her publications include Spiritualist Healers in Mexico (Salem, Wis.: Sheffield,
1994), Women in Pain (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania
Press, 1994), Experiencing the New Genetics (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 2000), and Physicians at Work, Patients in Pain (Boulder: Westview Press, 2d edition, 2001). The
present paper was submitted 11 i 00 and accepted 21 viii 00.

1. I thank the four informants whose narratives enrich our understanding of the phenomena discussed in this paper for freely giving
me their time and receiving me with patience. I owe a special debt
to Cecile Skrzynia of the Division of Hematology and Oncology of
the School of Medicine at the University of North Carolina, Chapel
Hill, for introducing me to Eve and Maya (pseudonyms). I thank
Robin Miller for introducing me to the adoptees and Lynn Giddens
for assisting me in meeting Kristen and Eric (pseudonyms) and sharing with me the wealth of her experience as an advocate for adoptees. The entire project was supported by a fellowship from the
Institute of Arts and Humanities, University of North Carolina,
Chapel Hill, and by grants from the University of North Carolina
Research Council and from the University of North Carolina Graduate School. I especially thank Rick Ezell for giving the manuscript
a close reading and for his invaluable demand for clarity.

The past several decades have seen an explosion of research in genetics and on genetic inheritance.2 The new
genetics is part of contemporary biomedicine and promises great advances in alleviating disease and prolonging
human life, leading us into the medicine of the future.
The present perspective on genetic inheritance is a feature of the past four decades, although the hereditarian
concept of disease appeared in the mid-19th century (Rosenberg 1976, Strahan 1984[1902]), when the Darwinian
revolution of the 19th century and the Mendelian principles introduced in the early 20th gave rise to the discovery of the genetic assortment of individual traits
transmitted from generation to generation. The notion
of genetic inheritance as we know it today came into
existence in the mid-20th century with the blossoming
of molecular biology. As genetic inheritance increasingly
becomes the prevailing causal explanation of affliction
and of human behavior in general, it is appropriate to
ask how such explanations influence peoples understandings of family and kin and how they reflect and at
the same time conflict with broader social processes.
To address these issues, I will briefly describe anthropological debates about the meaning of kinship from
cross-cultural and historical perspectives and then examine current conceptualizations of family and kinship.
I will go on to discuss what I call the medicalization of
family and kinship, pointing out that this phenomenon
impacts individuals differently, depending on their experience, and illustrating this with narratives of healthy
individuals with a family history of breast cancer and
healthy adoptees who have searched for their birth parents. I will conclude with a discussion of the theoretical
and practical implications of the medicalization of family and kin. On the assumption that medical concepts
open a window to the understanding of a societys culture, I will suggest that contemporary conceptualizations
of hereditary transmission build on American cultural
conceptions of kinship and that the medicalization of
kinship reflects and promotes a traditional notion of family and kinship relations that is counter to the changing
patterns of the late 20th century and the new millennium.
2. The mass media are saturated with reports of this work. Television series such as Turning Point and Dateline feature issues
related to genetic inheritance. National Public Radios Fresh Air,
Morning Edition, and Talk of the Nation Science Friday have presented recent developments in genetic inheritance, as have the New
York Times (Jones 2000) and a multitude of other publications and
programs. All Things Considered on National Public Radio has
discussed the usefulness of mastectomies to save lives for women
whove seen their mothers or sisters die an early death from breast
cancer. While some reports question the new emphasis on genetic
inheritance, including Siebert (1995), Begley (1996, 1997), The Economist (1996), Marty (1996), and Turning Point (February 12, 1996),
the majority of these reports are enthusiastic about the achievements of the new genetics (Blakeslee 1997; Carey and Flynn 1997;
Elmer-Dewitt 1994; Freundlich 1997; Grady 1994; Jaroff 1989, 1994,
1996; Seligman 1994; Wade 1997; Glausiusz 1995a, b, 1996; Higgins
1997; Brownlee and Silberner 1991; Brownlee et al. 1994; Nash
1997; Sack 1997).

235
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.150 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 13:41:14 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

236 F c u r r e n t a n t h ro p o l o g y Volume 42, Number 2, April 2001

Anthropological Studies of Kinship


The study of family and kinship has been a major concern of anthropology since the disciplines formal inception in the 19th century. While kinship studies have
waned in the light of postmodern concerns, most anthropology textbooks usually include at least one chapter
on family and kinship beliefs and practices the world
over. With the invention of new reproductive technologies, the concepts of paternity, maternity, and siblingship are taking on new meanings, and a new language is
being developed to reflect this change (cf. Yoxen 1986,
Carsten 2000).3 New genetic categories of people are being created, and thus there has been renewed interest in
the meaning of family and kinship (Dolgin 1997; Franklin 1997; Strathern 1992a, b; 1995). In fact, a good argument could be made that the new reproductive technologies have done more than anything else to call into
question our traditional understanding of family and kinship (see Franklin 1993:128; Strathern 1995; see, for discussion, Dolgin 1997, 2000; Finkler 2000a). My concern,
however, is not with kinship and reproductive technologies but with the ways in which peoples experience of
family and kin is influenced by the widespread belief in
the new genetics that medicalizes family and kinship.
Early studies of family and kinship cross-culturally regarded biological relationships as a starting point for developing conceptions about kinship (Lowie 1948:57).
Schneider, however, in several ground-breaking works
(1965, 1972, 1984), called into question the basic assumption that family and kinship relations are universally established by reproduction and biological ties. He
argued persuasively that kinship is a Western construct
and that people the world over may not necessarily give
primacy to ties established through reproduction and
blood. Various scholars (Holy 1996, Keesing 1975, Peletz
1995, Scheffler 1991) have questioned Schneiders assertions. While I agree with him that people may not universally sort out family and kin on the basis of blood
ties, nevertheless they usually do identify what I call a
significant same group of people who are regarded as
family and kinwho perceive themselves as similar and
who consider themselves related on grounds of shared
material, be it land, blood, food, saliva, semen, or ideological or affective content. Most important, membership in a significant same group carries moral obligations and responsibilities.
In American society, the popular construal of this
group was based, at least until recently, on a belief in
biogenetic connections established by procreation. Thus,
according to Schneider (1980), consanguinity defines genealogical relations in the United States. Generally
speaking, in most societies that anthropologists have
3. Yoxen (1986:89) provides the example of an embryo created by
fertilization outside the womans body and donated by another couple and then transferred to the womb of an infertile womans sister,
who would carry the developing fetus to term. With this example
Yoxen shows that it is possible for a baby to have three fathers and
three mothers.

studied, kinship is established by the sharing of blood


(but see Weismantel 1995, Witherspoon 1975, and, of
course, Schneider 1965, 1972, 1984; for discussion see
Finkler 2000a). In fact, the role of family and kinship
has served to demarcate premodern from complex societies. Scholars have suggested that in premodern or
primitive societies all human endeavors are embedded
in kinship networks, including economic, political, and
religious activities (Fortes 1970; Giddens 1991; Sahlins
1968, 1976).4 For instance, according to Sahlins (1976),
primitive societies are defined by kinship, whereas contemporary bourgeois society is differentiated by its focus
on the economy and the production of goods and, most
recently, on the production and transfer of information.
In premodern societies, ones identity is defined by ones
family and kinship relationships; in complex societies
and especially modern ones, it is circumscribed by the
presence of a nation-state (Giddens 1991), by separate
economic, political, and religious institutions, and by the
diminished importance of kin relationships. Significantly, Giddens emphasizes that in premodern cultures
kinship provides a nexus of reliable social connections
which, in principle and very commonly in practice, form
an organizing medium of trust relations. Kin people can
usually be relied upon to meet a range of obligations
more or less regardless of whether they feel personally
sympathetic towards the specific individuals involved
(1990:101). In modern societies, these relationships of
trust have been replaced by friendship, sexual intimacy
as means of stabilizing social ties (p. 102). Strathern
(1992a) wisely observes that, however complicated the
kinship systems of non-Western peoples are, Westerners
understand them as inherently primitive. In nontraditional societies, individuals are separate entities divorced
from their kinship and family units (Strathern 1992a,
Finkler 1994).
Viewed cross-culturally, kinship-oriented societies
usually stress unilineal descent, emphasizing either the
maternal (matrilineal descent) or, more often, the paternal side (patrilineal descent). Descent defines how property, status, and social obligations are transmitted and
how marriage is contracted. Descent . . . confers credentials for status and, hence, for capacities, rights, and
duties, [and] . . . a specified parent is both a parent and
the repository, as it were, and transmitter, of structurally
significant ancestry (Fortes 1970:28182). In discussing
the Nuer, Tallensi, Tiv, ancient Romans, and Chinese,
Fortes declares that the paradigm of patrilineal descent
is not just a means of picturing their social structure; it
is their fundamental guide to conduct and belief in all
areas of social life (pp. 29091).
Even in societies that stress unilineal descent, arguably, people recognize that both mother and father contribute to the formation of the offspring, but that they
do so is less significant than the line of descent to which
4. Although Fortes (1970) would argue that kinship also played an
important role in ancient Rome, as it does among British royalty.

This content downloaded from 200.130.19.150 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 13:41:14 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

f i n k l e r The Kin in the Gene F 237

the offspring belongs.5 For example, among the Melpa,


the paternal substance is shared between males through
the patrilineal line (agnatically related). While the
mother provides the blood, the father supplies the
grease (i.e., semen) that gives strength to the sons (A.
Strathern 1972:13). Daughters inherit their strength from
the mother. Among the Baraya, the mother is not regarded as the parent whose substance forms the fetus
(Strathern 1992a:61). The Zande, as described by EvansPritchard (1962:247), hold similar beliefs: The spiritsoul [is] . . . what is derived from the father, in spite of
what is said about the mothers co-operation in its creation, and this is what makes all children, irrespective
of sex, members of their fathers clan. Thus, there is
a tendency to emphasize the fathers part in procreation
beyond that of the mother just as the fathers side of the
family is stressed socially to a greater extent than the
mothers side of the family (p. 248). By contrast, in matrilineal societies such as the Trobrianders, the father may
simply open the way for the child to be born (Parkin
1997:138). In fact, according to Malinowski the Trobrianders believe that children result from the return of
an ancestor through the body of a woman, largely ignoring the fathers contribution. Here rank, membership
in social groups, and the inheritance of possessions descend through the maternal line. In Malinowskis (1922:
71) words, The real kinship, the real identity of substance is considered to exist between a man and his
mothers relations.
In a minority of world societies, including most Western societies, bilateral descent is the norm, meaning that
people give equal weight to the mothers and the fathers
descent lines and that identity is derived from both parental lines. Bilateral kinship appeared in Europe with
the law of Emperor Justin in the 6th century a.d., changing the old pattern of emphasis on patrilineality (see
Finkler 2000a), although Galens theory that semen originated in the blood and also nourished the mother and
the fetus persisted until the 18th century (Singer 1997).
The new law decreed that consanguines included all
those related by birth in the paternal and the maternal
line up to the seventh degree; those related more closely
than the seventh degree were forbidden to marry. The
consanguinity category now fully included the matrilateral kin (Pomata 1996:59) and may even have privileged them.

Contemporary American society follows the pattern of


medieval Europe. However, whereas in England, as
Strathern (1992b:52) reports, reproducing ones own did
not literally mean ones genetic material: ones own flesh
and blood were family members and offspring legitimated through lawful marriage, in American cultural

conceptions kinship is biogenetic (Schneider 1980:25);


the child is made up of both the mothers and the fathers
material. Biogenetic substance is a symbol of oneness in
American culture (p. 52), and biological unity is the
symbol for all other kinds of unity including, most importantly, that of relationships of enduring diffuse solidarity (p. 53). According to Schneider, blood relationship is a relationship of identity (p. 25), and while
biological ties define identity, love gives them their diffuse solidarity. The family is the paradigm for how kinship relations are to be conducted and to what end and
specifies that relations between members of the family
are those of love (p. 50). Living in the same household
gives meaning to biological ties (p. 34); biologically related individuals who do not reside together may not be
regarded as family. In sum, bilaterality is the norm shared
by all Americans, but affect and choice define who precisely are kin. In contemporary American society, where
the ideology of choice rules, the notion of choice is extended to biogenetic ties and whom we regard as kinfolk
and family (Giddens 1992).
We saw earlier that complex societies are defined by
loosened kinship ties, a phenomenon that was also noted
by Tocqueville (1980[1840]). In fact, in contemporary
times, a lack of kinship attachments may even be a sign
of modernity. Excepting among elites (Bellah et al. 1985,
Domhoff 1983, Marcus and Hall 1992), strong kinship
and family ties are usually regarded as a mark of specific
ethnicity (Arensberg and Kimball 1965)6 and traditionalism. With the arguable exception of the nuclear family,
the mark of a modern individual is autonomy, independence, and detachment from kinship ties (Bellah et
al. 1985; Giddens 1990, 1991; Redfield 1941; Taylor
1989). Kinship has narrowed and the sphere of individual decisions has grown (Bellah et al. 1985:89). I expect,
however, that in practice loss of kinship ties is more
common in urban than in rural areas and varies by region, even though people everywhere may have become
dependent on other linkages established by friendship,
at work, at church, and through volunteer organizations,
support groups, and many other types of nonkin-related
associations.
During the 1960s family and kinship acquired new
meanings and ceased to organize peoples existence or
define their identity. The modern family of sociological
theory and historical conventionan intact nuclear
household unit composed of a male provider and a female
housekeeper and their children and established by procreation, consanguinity, and marriageno longer prevails in the United States (Dolgin 1997, Popenoe 1993,
Stacey 1990). Stacey (1990:6) notes that historians place
the emergence of the modern American family among
white middle class people in the late eighteenth century;
they depict its flowering in the nineteenth century and
chart its decline in the second half of the twentieth.
The postmodern family is characterized by uncertainty,
insecurity, and doubt; its arrangements are diverse, fluid,

5. This point has been vigorously debated in the anthropological


literature; see Leach (1961) and Malinowski (1962[1929]).

6. I have even heard social workers call Mexican-Americans close


kinship and family ties dysfunctional.

Family and Kinship in Contemporary


American Society

This content downloaded from 200.130.19.150 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 13:41:14 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

238 F c u r r e n t a n t h ro p o l o g y Volume 42, Number 2, April 2001

and unresolved, opening the way for an array of kinship


relations. Stacey observes that no longer is there a single
culturally dominant family pattern to which the majority of Americans conform and most of the rest aspire
(p. 17). The routinization of divorce and remarriage has
generated diverse patterns of family structure and conceptualizations of its meaning. Along with other scholars
(e.g., Gottlieb 1993, Thorne 1992), Stacey concludes that
the traditional family is no longer a viable unit because
it distorts the variety of kinship possibilities that are not
founded in blood bonds. Separation and divorce generate
a diversity of new kin connections that are ever-changing
and subject to negotiation. Today a family may be a group
established more on the basis of choice than on the basis
of biogenetic ties, including single-parent households
and blended, adoptive, and gay families. Gottlieb perhaps
sums it up best when she says that although it is impossible to overlook kinship as a force in peoples lives,
it is also impossible to pin it down (1993:200).7 What
is more, whereas in premodern American society people
inherited their status, rights and duties, property and
power, and poverty from their kin, today family and kinship relations are usually not expected to confer on people any particular status except among the very wealthy
(Marcus and Hall 1992). In fact, the majority of middleand lower-class families may have little to transmit to
their descendents other than ephemeral moral values
(Finkler 1994).
Notwithstanding the fact that connections with others
than kin define the modern or postmodern individual,
paradoxically, we also hear a wistful lament in American
society for the loss of kinship and family ties, and the
ideology of kinship and family bonds continues to carry
a powerful symbolic load. While politicians mourn the
decline of family values, the business world, arguably
the most dominant domain in modern life, has appropriated kinship, if only symbolically, in its incessant reference to companies as families. Investment vehicles
(such as mutual funds) designate groups of similar funds
as families of funds. We may still invoke kinship relations when in need, as in the song from the Depression,
Brother, Can You Spare a Dime? Unions refer to their
organizations as brotherhoods, and some religious
groups identify their members as siblings. Biomedicine,
yet another major institution in modern life (Foucault
1975, Freidson 1970), has also turned its gaze on family
and kinship, defining them in traditional ways based on
blood or genetic ties, contrary to contemporary changes.
7. Not all scholars agree that family and kinship relations have
become diluted in contemporary times (see, e.g., Shorter 1975 and
Segalen 1986). Segalen, examining European data, suggests that
family and kin ties may be more powerful than before. She sees
the family as powerful, a refuge and the special focus for our feeling (p. 2) and argues that relationships within the nuclear family
and among close kin have intensified. From Segalens perspective,
the crisis rests with society and not with the family. Finch and
Mason (1993) also regard family and kin relations as continuing to
be based on genealogical ties, perhaps reflecting somewhat different
patterns in Europe and America.

The Medicalization of Family and Kinship


Medicalization (Freidson 1970, Illich 1976, Tomes 1990)
is, of course, not a recent phenomenon. With increasing
secularization in the 18th and 19th centuries, suicide and
homosexuality in England, for example, came to be
viewed as diseases rather than as moral transgressions
(Hansen 1992, MacDonald 1992). It is, however, difficult
to establish precisely when the term medicalization,
defined as the expansion of medical jurisdiction to cover
forms of deviant behavior that could alternatively be understood as sins, crimes, or moral faults (Estes 1988, Halpern 1985, Mayall 1990, Englehardt 1986), acquired cultural currency. Alcoholism, domestic violence, criminal
behavior, social problems, child abuse, certain undesirable personality characteristics, learning disabilities, and
even gambling, once considered religious, ethical, or
moral transgressions or matters of character, have been
reinterpreted as diseases (Gabe and Lipshitz-Phillips
1984, Rosenfield and Erchak 1988, Tiefer 1994). Bauman
(1992) suggests that even death has been medicalized, as
is evidenced by the search for its causes in defective
genes rather than a recognition of it as merely part of
the human condition.
Although men have not escaped the grip of medicalization, as with, for example, impotence and male pattern baldness (Tiefer 1994), it is women whose bodily
processes have been most subject to medicalization.
Menstruation, menopause, childbearing, and reproduction have all been brought under medical scrutiny (Gurevich 1995; Johnson 1987; Kaufer and Gilbert 1986; Kohler-Riessman 1983; Martin 1987; Markens 1996;
Ritenbaugh 1982; but cf. Bransen 1992). Women are
treated medically for even slight discomfort during menstruation, especially when such discomfort is labeled
Premenstrual Syndrome (PMS). Menopause and, of
course, childbearing require close medical supervision
(Davis-Floyd 1996, Johnson 1987, Kohler-Riessman 1983,
Martin 1987, Ritenbaugh 1982). Aesthetic sensibilities,
too, have been medicalized, the emphasis on a thin body
and a youthful appearance often requiring cosmetic surgery (Gilman 1999, Rodin 1992, Ritenbaugh 1982, Sullivan 1993). New technologies have extended the medical gaze to the fetus, making it visible, and with this
visualization through sonography even the unborn is
treated as a patient (Haraway 1997, Neustadter 1992, Petchesky 1987, Rapp 1999). Lastly, as Witzig (1996) points
out, race is medicalized when an association is made
between such groupings and specific diseases (see also
Wailoo 1996).
Medicalization, translating sets of problems into medical terms, changes peoples perspectives on reality, on
their being, and on how they experience the world (Englehardt 1986). When seen as medical problems, behaviors are usually characterized as circumstances that deviate from physiological or psychological norms
regarding proper levels of functioning, freedom from
pain, and achievement of expected human form. For example, discussing the medicalization of homosexuality

This content downloaded from 200.130.19.150 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 13:41:14 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

f i n k l e r The Kin in the Gene F 239

in the 19th century, Hansen (1992) points out that a new


type of person was created and a new core identity given
to such a person: now a homosexual might be regarded
as having a particular genetic makeup. Previously, homosexuality was viewed as a type of behavior, albeit an
aberrant one; with medicalization, the homosexual became a new species of person.
Medicalization restructures reality by intruding on the
world people take for granted. Aspects of behavior or the
body that are tacitly understood as normal are transformed into abnormal, disconcerting states, separating
the individual from others. Like all human actions, medicalization is a two-edged sword. While it may relieve
afflicted individuals of one set of devalued labels, it burdens them with another. When drug addiction, crime,
and alcoholism8 are converted from moral transgressions
to diseases, the persons affected are absolved of responsibility and blame, and this may provide them with a
sense of coherence and meaning (Broom and Woodward
1996, Englehardt 1986). A diagnosis of chronic fatigue
syndrome, for example, helps to provide a rational, discrete explanation for an incoherent and disorderly experience (see the case of Margarita in Finkler 1994). At
the same time, persons may be turned into deviants and
stigmatized in the process, and the underlying causes of
the problem (including the experience of a sense of meaningless in their lives) may be ignored. Again, with the
medicalization of womens reproduction, contraceptive
technologies have given women greater freedom by enabling them to control conception and relieving them of
the fear of unwanted pregnancy. Simultaneously, these
technologies have made women dependent on the medical profession and often adversely affected their health
(Bunkle 1993; Doyal 1979, 1995; Finkler 1994; Marieskind 1980; Yanoshik and Norsigian 1989).
Not everyone, of course, embraces the notion of medicalization (Finkler 2000a). Some scholars have questioned the degree to which the concept of medicalization
has penetrated popular consciousness, pointing to an apparent loss of dominance of the medical profession (Williams and Calnan 1996).9 Nevertheless, medicalization
is a powerful force. To the array of human experiences
that have become medicalized, I suggest that we must
now add the family and kinship. Understood as biogenetic, they have come under close medical inspection
through the prevailing biomedical understanding of disease etiology. Beyond issues associated with gender, family and kinship relations have been given a new dimension that stresses faulty genes rather than social status,
position, or even poverty. Cultural significance is given
to genetic transmission, for better or for worse.
Giddens (1992) has proposed the notion of toxic par8. But see Appleton (1995), who argues that alcoholism was medicalized not by biomedicine but by Alcoholics Anonymous. Which
institution first medicalized alcoholism is less relevant than the
fact that the culture is prone to regard any deviant condition in
medical terms. Arguably, in the 15th century alcoholism would not
have been considered a medical problem by anyone.
9. Approximately 33% of the U.S. population seek alternative therapy (Eisenberg et al. 1993; see also 1998).

ents, parents who harm their children by damaging


their sense of personal worth. Toxic parents are emotionally inadequate and either have abdicated their responsibilities to their children or insist on controlling
them. Alcoholic parents and verbal or physical child
abusers are examples. Although Giddens argues that
those who wish to rework their involvement with toxic
parents through therapy may come to recognize that
you are not responsible for what was done to you as a
defenseless child (p. 107), one cannot declare independence from ones genetic parents. As Bobinski (1996:80)
observes, information about genetic makeup is gotten
from examination of a persons medical record and analysis of his or her family genetic history. A family history
of a particular disorder, for example, would mean that
there was an elevated risk that the individual might be
a carrier who could pass the condition on to a new
generation.10
If Schneider is correct, love cements biogenetic kinship relations in American society and allows for a degree
of choice in deciding whom a person will love within
the family and kinship group. With the medicalization
of family and kinship, a connection must exist irrespective of love and choice. Biomedicine insists on uniting
those who may not choose to be connected. Family and
kin connections are framed in terms of genetic inheritance from parents, grandparents, and other relatives.
More than 5,000 medical conditions have been attributed
to genetic inheritance, and with the work of the Human
Genome Project we daily learn of another disorder that
is traceable to genetic transmission. The role of inheritance through our genes is widely accepted (Fox Keller
1992:283). Both the doctor-patient encounter and the
mass media tend to imprint on peoples consciousness
the emphasis on biological kinship and the notion that
families and kin pass on disease. People become conscious of their family and kinship connections and the
potential harm they may cause when their physicians
first ask for a family medical history.11 Taking a family
medical history reinforces the notion that there is an
association between kinship and health.12 Good medical
procedure requires physicians, in addition to doing a
physical examination, laboratory tests, and other tech10. Science (1993) describes how the BRC-1 gene for breast cancer
was discovered through the examination of blood samples and family histories from numerous extended families (see also Clark 1999).
11. On my first visit to a physician for a minor condition, for example, I was asked for a family medical history. I indicated that
one of my aunts had died of cancer. (I did not specify and the doctor
did not inquire about the precise genealogical tie; she was an aunt
by marriage.) Upon hearing this, the doctor insisted that I needed
a complex and costly examination because I was predisposed to
cancer and my condition could eventually develop into the disease
from which my aunt had died. Another poignant example is that
of a student who told me that her future might be in jeopardy
because alcoholism was part of her genetic heritage; both her parents were alcoholics, and she was convinced that it was inevitable
that she would suffer the same fate.
12. The doctor-patient encounter is an especially powerful means
by which societal ideologies are instilled in individuals consciousness, cutting across class, race, and gender lines (Finkler 1991, Phillips 1997, Waitzkin 1991).

This content downloaded from 200.130.19.150 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 13:41:14 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

240 F c u r r e n t a n t h ro p o l o g y Volume 42, Number 2, April 2001

nical diagnostic procedures, to take such a history (McAuliffe 1978, 1979). Thus, to resist the medicalization of
family and kinship one would have to reject biomedical
treatment.
The medicalization of family and kinship reverberates
in the mass media. A program presented on CNNs Your
Money on February 15, 1997, instructed viewers to track
down their family histories to acquire useful hereditary
information. The Chattanooga Times (December 12,
1996) reports that people are searching vigorously for
family trees to learn their ancestors causes of death to
clue them in on genetic diseases. Finch (1996:92) reports in Health that tracing your roots to learn your
familys health history may be the single most important
thing you ever do to bolster your well-being and instructs the reader on how to go about doing a family tree.
Daus (1999) shows how tracing your family medical
history can save your life (see also Adato 1995). Some
articles focus on adoptees seeking access to their genetic
history (Park 1997, Cool 1994) and advocate open adoptions and open medical records. A headline in the August
15, 1996, Wall Street Journal calls attention to One
Familys Search for a Faulty Gene, and another on the
same page announces that Doctors Recommend Every
Family Make Its Own Medical Tree (see Nelkin 1992).
Family magazines suggest that individuals work out genograms and family health pedigrees as a way of predicting
the future of their children. Some Mothers Day cards
remind the mother that its all in our genes (Siebert
1995).
References to peoples predisposition to inherited disease are made frequently on talk shows and in the print
media. Siebert (1995:74) writes, Genes are suddenly
thought to be responsible for everything from poverty to
privilege, from misdemeanors to murder. I seem to recall
watching television one night and seeing a man up on
homicide charges offer as a defense the presence of a
criminal gene, which he claimed ran in his family. He
reports that the Institute of Medicines Committee on
Assessing Genetic Risks recently concluded that multiplex genetic testing based upon a single blood or tissue
sample will become standard medical practice early in
the next century. Clearly, the day is not far off when a
doctors visit will yield personal genetic report cards,
indicating which disorders we may be destined for and
how to tailor our lives accordingly (p. 52).
The notion of the medicalization of family and kinship
would tend to predict such current phenomena as the
recent law enacted in Oregon that requires open adoption, meaning that adoptees can learn the names of their
birth parents and gain access to their medical records
without the need to resort to the courts.13 Not coincidentally, too, the search movement among adoptees
came into bloom in the 1960s, around the same time
13. The Oregon Adoptee Rights Initiative, passed by a vote of the
people of Oregon on November 3, 1998, restores the right of adopted
adults (age 21 and older) to request and receive a copy of their
original birth certificates with no amendments, no restrictions, and
no exceptions (see http://www.barysoftware.com/orelegl.htm).

that our collective consciousness concerning genetic inheritance came to the fore and notions about diseases as
genetically programmed began to take root in biomedicine. Moreover, the current intense interest in genealogies (see, e.g., Hornblower 1999, Mitchell 1999) is arguably connected with the necessity to provide the
family trees that are the basic technique of the clinical
geneticists (Richards 1996).

Experience of the Medicalization of Family


and Kinship
In my recent study of the issue based on interviews of
35 women who had experienced breast cancer or came
from families with a history of the disease and 15 adoptees who had been searching for their birth parents (see
Finkler 2000a), it became apparent that the medicalization of family and kinship significantly influenced peoples daily experience. Eve, for example, lives with anxiety because of her family medical history. A scientist
with a Ph.D. in biology, married and childless, she had
lost her 34-year-old mother to breast cancer when she
was a teenager. Her mothers 84-year-old sister had cancer. One of her two brothers had died of salivary gland
cancer and the other of prostate cancer. Her aging father
also had cancer. Both her paternal and maternal grandparents had died of heart disease, and Eve added, That
too is familial, and so its a double whammy, particularly since the predisposition to high cholesterol is
genetic.
Eve said, I am 59. My aunt and grandmother developed their cancer between 59 and 65, so now I am in
that age-range, and my sister, who is 54, is right behind
me. Neither she, her sister, nor her cousins had developed cancer, but Eve felt that she was sitting on a time
bomb because, she said, her family history placed her
at extremely high risk: an early onset of menses, no
children, and being the offspring of a parent that developed cancer, and thats where we fit. And we are Ashkenazy Jews. Because she regarded herself as at high
risk and firmly believed that cancer was inherited, she
lived in constant dread of falling ill. When she moved to
her current residence she immediately contacted and set
up a cancer team:
I am extremely anxious. I go for my mammograms
twice a year and I want to have a breast surgeon
that I am comfortable with, so I have a team. I do
everything now to monitor myself and knowing that
data, Id only be more anxious than I already am if it
came out to be that way. And if I ever needed insurance, I could be hard pressed to get it. You know,
theres this big computer in the sky and those data
seem to find their way into that. I am not going to
have a prophylactic mastectomy, which I have been
urged to do.

This content downloaded from 200.130.19.150 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 13:41:14 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

f i n k l e r The Kin in the Gene F 241

Eve noted that she felt closer to her sister and husband
and her father but had also become closer to her cousins:
Knowing that they share the same genes provides
the occasion for discussion. When I think I know
something thats useful, I pass it on to the others. So
basically the occasion for my cousins is a bar mitzvah we might all go to, but we are connected
through this exchange of information. Otherwise,
we have very different lives. The fact that they have
the same genes has created a close bond. We seem
to have a very clear and good and accepting understanding of who the family was. Let me just say that
this [disease] really has provided a lasting and a continuous bond.

The major theme of Eves narrative was her profound


fear of becoming afflicted. Despite the fact that she was
healthy and vibrant, she acted like a patient because of
her unwavering faith in the notion of the inheritance of
disease and the associated risk factors that she was convinced she possessed. Impelled by her understanding of
her family medical history, she acted on these fears by
having frequent mammograms and arranging for a cancer
team to stand ready for her eventual illness. Eve recognized a lasting bond with her blood kin because of a
shared genetic inheritance, although, reflecting the postmodern family pattern, she emphasized that she had very
little else in common with them. Furthermore, her beliefs about the adverse effects of genetic transmission
had influenced in part her decision not to have children.
Eve had not contemplated prophylactic breast removal,
but like the other women I interviewed she was what I
call a perpetual patient, someone who has entered the
medical stream despite the fact that she is healthy. Her
understanding that she might fall ill because of her family and kinship relations influenced her day-to-day
experience.
Maya had similar fears. She was a 50-year-old biologist,
born in South Asia, married with two children. Being of
dual cultural background, she had considered the possibility that the illnesses that had befallen her family
were due to witchcraft. She identified herself, however,
as an American and had internalized American values
of mastering the situation. Coming from a society in
which large extended families were the norm, she lived
in a nuclear family but remained in close contact with
her siblings in various parts of the United States. She
had sought genetic counseling because she wished to
undergo hormone replacement therapy but feared it
would increase her risk of ovarian cancer because her
mother and a 45-year-old sister had died of the disease
and her 22-year-old brother had recently succumbed to
colon cancer. She believed that colon and ovarian cancers
were closely associated but especially feared ovarian
cancer.
Maya said that, as a biologist, she could only think

that cancer was an inherited disease, unless of course it


was bewitchment of our family, a possibility she
quickly discounted. She volunteered that she had been
separated from her family in South Asia but had been
brought closer to them because of the possibility of their
sharing a disease. In fact, she wished to have her sisters
and oldest daughter tested, but they refused to take the
test. She believed that if one knew one was carrying the
gene, the disease could be prevented by a vegetarian diet.
Having her relatives genetically tested would have given
her some control over the future by knowing her risk of
inheriting the disease. We see here how genetic ideology
motivated her to seek genetic testing, requiring the cooperation of her family, to whom she became closer because of the fear of the disease. Seeking genetic testing
converted her and her family into patients. It is not surprising that Mayas relatives, who may have believed in
witchcraft, resisted the medicalization of their family
history by refusing to be tested, an option she did not
possess. As a biologist and a Westerner she could not
consciously sustain a view that would place her in the
category of the superstitious and uneducated, even
though, I suspect, she may still have maintained the belief at some level.
My interviews with adoptees who had searched for
their birth parents also reveal the power of the medicalization of genetic ties. The recurring reason they gave
for their searches was to obtain their natural families
medical histories. With one exception, all the adoptees
I interviewed indicated that they felt like aliens because of the lack of a biological family medical history.
Every time they went to a physician they were questioned about their family medical history, and they could
not provide one.
Kristen, 31 years old and married with three healthy
young children, had begun her search for her birth
mother when she was 21 years old and found the woman
about eight weeks prior to our meeting. She had started
searching shortly after her first child was born, primarily
to obtain a medical history but also to know from whom
she had inherited her personality and why she had been
given away. Kristen claimed that she was obsessed with
procuring her medical history because she suffered from
Raynauds disease, which she described as a circulatory
disorder characterized by muscle aches and weight gain
or loss. (She had gained 20 lb. in the past year.) In her
understanding, in at least 35% of cases Raynauds disease
was the precursor of lupus.14 Kristen commented, reflecting the sentiments of almost every adoptee I met, When
you go to the doctor you do not have a medical history
and you are not a person.
Kristen said that because she lacked a medical history
it had taken two years for her health insurance company
to approve her hysterectomy. She was being treated for
14. The cause of Raynauds disease is unknown. It is a condition
in which arterioles, usually in the fingers and toes, go into spasm,
often triggered by cold, causing the skin to become discolored. Sixty
to 90% of Raynauds disease cases occur in young women (Merck
Manual 1997:136).

This content downloaded from 200.130.19.150 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 13:41:14 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

242 F c u r r e n t a n t h ro p o l o g y Volume 42, Number 2, April 2001

endometriosis, and her doctor wished to perform a hysterectomy, but the company would not authorize the
procedure. She maintained that had she had a medical
history she would have received the procedure immediately.15 Furthermore, she observed that it was very important to have a family medical history so that she
would know what she was passing on to her children.
She said, You dont know what I could have given them
that would hurt them.
Kristen had contacted the agency that had handled her
adoption to advise them of her Raynauds condition and
to request her medical history. The staff member who
found her file said, Well, do you know that your maternal grandmother died of lupus? Kristen continued,
And I was like, what? whoa, wait a minute, youre sitting on this information, you never told me. I got very
upset.When she told her doctor that she was adopted
and that her maternal grandmother had suffered from
lupus, the doctor got real quiet, and said, You need to
find your family. You need to be getting physical documents about your family history. The doctor also told
her that there is a strong maternal genetic link between
Raynauds disease and lupus. All on the same branch
of diseases, said Kristen. After I found out I was like
a demon. I was not only dealing with my childrens
health, my curiosity, but I was dealing with my health.
She was on a one-year recall visit schedule for blood tests
for lupus because of the information she had gathered
about her genetic background.
Having found her birth mother, Kristen had learned
that her maternal grandfather had died of a heart attack
when he was 34 years old. She commented,
When I found my birth mother, shes opened her entire life to me, her medical records, my grandmothers medical records, my great-grandmother,
whos 93 and still alive, had gotten her doctor to get
up stuff for me. And my great-aunt Lois has done
the same. And the whole family is riddled with arthritis, my grandmother died of lupus, my mother
has connective-tissue muscle disorder, and so I was
able to call my doctor back and say, This is what
Ive got in my background. And the doctor started
laughing, saying, God, no wonder youre gonna test
positive for lupus, youre always gonna test positive
for lupus.
The doctor, a rheumatologist, told Kristen that with her
background and genetic makeup, Youre asking for a lot
of problems. The doctor told her that she would become
afflicted with arthritis later on and that the Raynauds
disease would get worse. Kristen continued, I was
started on medication for that. I was also told, You will
have to watch yourself, because of the genetic background there. She was convinced that she had inherited
15. According to the head of an adoption search chapter, if an adoptee lacks a medical history the doctor will often refuse to order
various procedures because the insurance companies claim a lack
of documentation to justify them.

all these disorders from her birth mother, and she had
become a perpetual patient.
She lamented that she had not learned sooner that she
originated from a family with lupus, because it would
have explained her circulatory problems, such as her cold
fingers and toes, especially in wintertime. Had she
known that this condition was part of her family heritage, she said, she would have been assured sooner that
she was not crazy; the doctors had not taken her symptoms seriously until she was able to show that others in
her family had suffered from the disorder. The medical
history not only recounted for Kristen her family history
but also, significantly, affirmed her sanity. She had also
discovered that she had a half-sister with cerebral palsy,
and she wished that she had known that before she had
children. She observed, I would have at least been tested
when I was pregnant. It wouldnt have changed anything,
but I would have been prepared emotionally.
Kristens biomedical understanding of genetic inheritance required her to be on an annual recall schedule of
medical visits and to take certain medications. More important, her medical history linked her with those who
shared her genetic heritage rather than with those who
had raised and educated her. Her emphasis on medical
history anchored her identity in her patienthood and also
tied her to a world of relatives in the past. For Kristen,
as for the other adoptees, kinship meant biological connectionvalidated by the medical history that firmly
established her continuity with the past and presentwith her birth mother and her family. The medical
history, by recapitulating genetic inheritance, turned
into a kinship history and a mental map of the past.
Importantly, too, having her biological familys medical
history affirmed her sanity for Kristen. Only when she
could demonstrate a genetic history did her doctors take
her symptoms seriously and acknowledge that her ills
were not in her head.16
Eric was 51 years old, married with two children, a
college graduate, and employed in a managerial position.17 He had begun the search for his birth mother eight
months prior to our meeting, shortly after the death of
both his adoptive parents, to whom he had felt very close.
I found Erics narrative especially poignant because,
sadly for him, the woman he was certain was his birth
mother had not responded to his several letters of introduction. He wanted to meet her primarily because he
wished to obtain his medical history so that he might
16. It is especially common for women to be told that their symptoms are in their heads if their condition cannot be assessed
biomedically (see Finkler 1994).
17. The ratio of women to men seeking their birth parents is 9:1
(head of the search support group, personal communication). The
reasons for the disparity are not clear. The head of the support group
attributes it to the fact that women are more sensitive to birth
and pregnancy issues than men and mens lesser abilities to connect to the birth process. There may be other reasons, including
the fact that since women seek treatment more often than men
(Finkler 1994, Verbrugge 1990) they are more exposed to medicalization. This interesting disparity requires further exploration, but
with the ongoing medicalization of family and kinship it is likely
to disappear.

This content downloaded from 200.130.19.150 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 13:41:14 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

f i n k l e r The Kin in the Gene F 243

learn what health problems to anticipate for himself and


his children. Eric said,
The one thing that a lot of adoptees who are looking
say when they go to the doctors office and they
take a medical history, and they are asked, Has
there been any history of high blood pressure or
heart disease or diabetes or glaucoma or whatever in
your family? And, of course, I, like they, always
have had to say I have no idea, because I was
adopted, I have no medical background, and heredity plays such a big part. I mean I think its become
more evident every year as to how much heredity affects your genes, and DNA and all that affects your
well-being throughout your whole life and what
kind of diseases or whatever you are prone to possibly get. So, it was important for me from that perspective, the medical perspective, but not just for
me, but for my children, because they have the
same missing pieces in their medical background because I have them and Im half of what they are.
And as I matured and as I got older and, of course,
the older you get, the more likely you are to come
down with something or have something develop,
whether its your eyesight or whatever it is. And Ive
never liked doctors. I try to stay away as frequently
as possible, not go, but the older I get the more I realize that its an important thing that I need to be
aware of and plan for the future and my children
need it. And when and if they have children, thatll
be something thatif I had that missing piece of the
puzzle, or at least part of the missing piece of the
puzzle that I would be able to pass along to them,
the knowledge that, yes, your maternal grandmother
was prone to this problem or that or your greatgrandmother or whatever.
Eric was also curious about his birth mother because, he
said,
Its a part of me that I dont know where it came
from. I think the other part [apart from the medical]
is just probably as much of a driving force in my
search for beginning; it was just natural curiosity. I
like to know, so many people compare, I mean, how
many times have you gone and seen a new baby and
heard people say, Oh, she looks just like so-and-so
or He looks just like his dad or whatever. And I
dont look like either one of my [adoptive] parents.

have, more than likely, a high probability of having


the correct information about the birth mother.
Whether or not the birth father information is correct is much less likely.
Eric believed not only that he would recapitulate his
birth mothers medical history but that he inherited from
his birth parents certain characteristics that he had not
shared with his adoptive parents. He reported,
I used to amaze my parents with my ability to, or
inquisitiveness about taking things apart, figuring
out how they work, and putting them back together.
Two of the things that I did a lot of as I was growing
up and even into adulthood that my father would
never do, my adoptive father, is if something broke,
Id try to fix it. Hed call a repairman. One of the
things that I have oftentimes said, halfway in jest
and halfway in reality, is I wish I could turn the
clock back and say to hell with going to a university
for four years. I would have been a lot happier person, I think, if I had gone and taken six months
worth of community college courses in plumbing
and another six months in electricians and learned,
because I admire very much the ability of someone
to do things like that, to actually be able . . . not to
just have to write a check and say, Come fix it.
And I get a real feeling of satisfaction about replacing the brakes on my car or repairing the television,
not that I can repair televisions. The other thing
that was so much different was my enjoyment of
the outdoors from a sports standpoint. I love to fish,
and I did hunt a little bit. I havent in years, but to
the best of my knowledge my father never hunted,
and about the only time he ever went fishing was
when he took me out to a pond somewhere and
watched me fish. And actually I went fishing with
my mothers only brother, my uncle, on several occasions. I even camped out with him and went canoeing on the river down near my mothers hometown. I went deer hunting with him, and Ive been
on the river with him before, and thats just not
something my father ever had any interest in. I
think an awful lot of what a person is comes from
their parents. From their birth parents, yeah. From
the genes and the DNA and all of that; thats what
made them up.
For Eric kinship relations implied

He wanted to find his birth father as well, but, in his


words,
I am a novice in searching and it has consumed
enormous amounts of time on the Internet reading
other peoples thoughts and emotions and anger and
guilt. Its probably as important as my mother to
learn about my father; its just that my mother
would be the easiest one to find. Its a beginning
point because anybodys birth certificate is going to

friendship as part of the relationship, of enjoying the


same things but also biological unity. Kinship is a
feeling of togetherness or bonding or being part of.
. . . You know you enjoy the same things that I do,
you love the same things that I love, whether it be
the ocean or animals orI think that, to me, thats
something else that you may have inherited. I mean
your love of animals or your dislike for animals, you
know. I love cats. My wife loves animals. My par-

This content downloaded from 200.130.19.150 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 13:41:14 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

244 F c u r r e n t a n t h ro p o l o g y Volume 42, Number 2, April 2001

ents could have cared less. They always allowed me


to have animals, but they neverI never perceived
any real affection to my dogs and my cats from
them. I think you can be related by way of kinship
and not be biologically related.
He conflated shared interest with blood ties, as most of
the adoptees did, arguably reflecting both the postmodern notion of kinship based on shared behavioral characteristics and the biomedical notion of biogenetic ties.
As it was for Kristen, the medical history was the chief
reason Eric had initiated the search for his birth mother,
but he had other reasons as well. This calculus reflected
his confusion about whether his real family was the people for whom he felt affection and with whom he shared
experiences or the people with whom he shared a genetic
inheritance that embodied medical and genealogical
memory.

Consequences of the Medicalization of Family


and Kinship
We can envision myriad effects of the medicalization of
family and kinship, but what is most important is that
it differentially influences peoples lives depending on
their experience. The dissimilar effects of medicalization
on peoples daily existence can be gleaned even from only
four narratives. Generally speaking, the foreseeable consequence of the medicalization of kinship for all of us is
that people may no longer need to present complaints
to be regarded as sick. They may be considered sick simply because they come from families with particular diseases. Those who have relatives who have suffered from
breast cancer, colon cancer, Alzheimers disease, or one
of the many other diseases believed to be transmitted by
inheritance will be assumed to have inherited it in an
autosomal dominant fashion. Jonsen (1996:89)18 suggests that
persons could be designated patients in an anticipatory sense. Some with monogenic disorders will be
patients without symptoms, but sure to have them
in the future. Others, with the genetic patterns associated with polygenic or multifactorial disorders,
will be known as a schizophrenic or cardiac or cancer patient long before any illness is felt or any pathology damages the organism; indeed, they may
never be affected at all, yet still be marked. Persons
will become patients before their time: They will be
described in disease terms but feel fine and be
fine for years, perhaps always.
The notion of genetic risk for a disease has now become
almost a disease in itself, as has the notion of predisposition (Nelkin 1996), despite the fact that scholars
18. See also Hubbard and Wald (1997), who speak of the healthy
ill.

here and abroad (Hoedemaekers and ten Have 1999) recognize that predisposition does not necessarily lead to
disease.19 The concept of the inheritance of a predisposition extends the medicalization of family and kinship
to encompass almost everyone, converting most people
into potential perpetual patients. Peoples realities will
encompass a future that is incessantly punctuated by
worry. Indeed, the medicalization of family and kinship
alters peoples perceptions from if I get breast or colon
cancer to when I get breast or colon cancer or any
one of the many diseases believed to be inherited.
Moreover, the medicalization of family and kinship
creates a new dynamic within the family. Some have
suggested that it may lead to guilt for parents and resentment for their offspring (Serban 1989, Richards
1996). Healthy members of a family or kin group may
resent being told that they are potentially at high risk
for developing a disease (Green, Murton, and Statham
1993). Lynch, Lynch, and Lynch (1979:223) found that
family members manifest anxiety, fatalism, denial and
even accusation directed toward the spouse, parents, or
other family members who have caused the disease among us. But Wexler (1979:207), discussing
Huntingtons disease,20 observes that remarkably few
interviewees expressed conscious anger toward the parent who had given them this legacy. Compassion and
grief were by far the most common feelings. It was considered in particularly bad taste to harbor hostility toward a parent who was already broken and ill. Wexler
(1992) was surprised, as was I (Finkler 2000a), that people
failed to express anger with their families for having
passed down a lethal disease.
Most important, with the medicalization of kinship
the individual is no longer the sole patient. We read that
genetic counselors are beginning to ask questions such
as who is the patientthe individual? The familythe
spouse, the sister, the brother, or the child? (Nelkin
1992:180). In contrast to the broader societal process, in
which individualism and freedom of choice are emphasized, the medicalization of kinship creates a tension
between individualism and choice and an orientation to
family and kin. As I noted earlier, individualism insists
on an autonomous person, standing outside any one socially defined unit and selecting his/her life course,
whereas kinship relationships based on genetic inheritance call for connectedness and circumscription of
choice. If Edwards and Strathern (2000) are right, forgetfulness plays an important role in delineating kin beyond
the nuclear family. But the medicalization of family and
kinship unites people wittingly or perhaps unwittingly
and jolts their memories. Whereas in modern society
individuals may choose their kin on the basis of affective
ties, paradoxically, the new genetics prescribes ones kin
19. See, e.g., the work of Lisbeth Sachs in Sweden (1995, 1996) and
Adelsward and Sachss (1996) work on the ways in which biomedicines assignment of numerical values to risk creates in people a
state of being neither healthy nor diseased.
20. Huntingtons disease is caused by a single dominant gene, and
the odds are 5050 that the individual will inherit the disease,
which becomes manifest at 3540.

This content downloaded from 200.130.19.150 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 13:41:14 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

f i n k l e r The Kin in the Gene F 245

relations on the basis of birth. The medicalization of


kinship thus subverts both the ideology of choice and
the new family patterns based on factors other than
blood.21 In an interesting contradiction, with the medicalization of family and kinship freedom and choice, so
profoundly embedded in American consciousness, must
confront genetic determinism.
It can even be said that the medicine of the future will
be the medicine not of the individual but of the family.
The traditional biomedical model is based on a physician/patient dyad. With the medicalization of kinship,
the individual may no longer make medical decisions
independent of his/her family. Family members must
cooperate in order for a physician and geneticist to assess
the patients condition, especially within the domain of
genetic testing for disease. Family and kin of different
generations must be drawn into the diagnostic process
(Jonsen 1996, Wexler 1992). Wexler goes so far as to say
(p. 228) that
anybody in a family with a genetic diseasethis
probably includes everybodyshould think about
storing samples of DNA from relatives whose genotype would be essential to know for a diagnostic
testing. The most important relatives to you are
those in the family with the illness and those
clearly unaffected, parents of these individuals and
your own parents. If you have a genetic disorder,
banking your own DNA could be critical for your
descendants. Each family might have its own genetic variation, its own genetic fingerprinting of
the gene in question, and it is best to preserve a
sample of the particular gene that plagues your family rather than extrapolate from the genes from
other families.
Tests are currently being prepared for breast cancer, colon cancer, heart disease, Alzheimers, manic-depressive
disorder, and schizophrenia (Wexler 1992).22
The medicalization of family and kinship may not affect all people adversely. Undoubtedly it reassures some
people to know that, if no one in the family past or
present has suffered from a particular disease, they, too,
are protected from becoming afflicted. Moreover, medicalization offers a sense of mastery; knowing a family
medical history allows one to do something about it. It
may furnish the person with a feeling of security, albeit
perhaps illusory, and it makes it possible to take preventive measures, such as mammograms (but see Kaufert
and Gilbert 1996) and blood tests, in anticipation of potentially falling ill. Significantly, in contrast to most biomedical explanations, the medicalization of family and
kinship explains not only the how but the why of a dis21. It is interesting that medicine has moved from the visible to
the invisible, from blood to the gene, arguably promoting greater
awe.
22. Given the medicalization of family and kinship, it can be predicted that one family member will eventually sue another for unlawful disclosure of a medical condition.

ease. The answer to the question Why me? rests in


ones family medical history.
What is more, medicalization may even lead to reestablishing relationships among family members,23 who
may become closer to one another not only because they
share a disease but also because they have developed a
new sense of sharing a genetic heritage. In fact, family
and kin become closer not only to the living but also to
the dead, whom they must recall to account for their
genetic heritage; this may promote a sense of continuity
with the past, even if it is based on adversity.
The family medical history recapitulates their kinship
history for people whose kinship memories may lack
depth. In present-day American society, where memory
is shallow, DNA becomes a central repository of human
memory by assuming agency and true ontological status
with its alleged capacity to remember peoples ancestors in ways that their living memories may have forgotten. The medicalization of family and kinship binds
people to the past as well as to the future and propels
them to search for ancestors and anticipate future afflicted descendents. Arguably, human beings are the only
animals that contemplate a past and a future, and our
genetic conceptualizations emphasize that aspect of our
humanity. DNA engenders a dialectic between anticipation of the future and remembrance of the past. It is
devoid of morality or affect, a hallmark of family and
kinship relations (see Finch and Mason 1993, Witherspoon 1975); it is inherently impersonal and does not
impose, express, or insist on responsibilities, obligations,
or love other than requiring living relatives to furnish
blood samples in order to establish genetic markers on
chromosomes;24 yet it stands in for our past and future
family and kin, our personhood, and our being. The family medical history is mindful that the body remembers.
Connerton (1989:87) observes that ceremonies of the
body, such as are exemplified in court etiquette at Versailles, remind performers of a system of honor and hereditary transmission as the organizing principle of social
classification. Blood relations are signs cognitively
known and recalled through the visibly elaborate display
of privileges and avocations which make sense only by
constant reference to that principle. In contemporary
times, the ceremonies of the body have been reduced to
blood tests, nucleic acid, and molecules, ignorant of
honor and social classifications, connecting us with kin
in the past.
What is most intriguing is that at the level of the individual, the medicalization of family and kinship impacts people in profoundly different ways. As we have
seen from the narratives, for healthy women from fam23. Organ transplantation will also promote a strengthening of biological kinship ties among persons who may have been alienated.
In fact, a few of the adoptees I interviewed noted their desire to
find their blood kin for that purpose as well. The relationship between transplantation and the medicalization of kinship requires
exploration.
24. The metaphor to give ones blood for someone, denoting devotion, is here concretized as the one act a family member may
perform for another.

This content downloaded from 200.130.19.150 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 13:41:14 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

246 F c u r r e n t a n t h ro p o l o g y Volume 42, Number 2, April 2001

ilies with a history of cancer, the concept of genetic inheritance at once created fear of the future and provided
some meaning for their fears and potential suffering,
sometimes even moving them to action to avoid becoming ill. These women tended to believe that, knowing
their predisposition to inheritance of a disorder, they
could do something, if only by avoiding identified risk
factors, to prevent the inevitable.25 For the adoptees,
in contrast, the medicalization of family and kin produced fragmentation, internal conflict, and turmoil, creating special dilemmas that do not affect individuals who
have been raised by blood kin. Adoptees were impelled
to search for their birth parents by the very consciousness of genetic inheritance and in large part by the need
for a family medical history, and they came to question
the fiction of living as if they were related by blood to
their adoptive families. The power of the medicalization
of family and kinship, pitted against their experience of
love and solidarity within their adoptive families, had
led them to search for their birth parents, placing them
in profound contradiction. Most of the adoptees I studied
had difficulty reconciling the belief in genetic inheritance with their experience of being a member of an
adopted family, frequently a loving one, with whom they
lacked blood ties and whom they did not resemble physically. What is more, it is significant, if also puzzling,
that the adoptees who had found their birth parents had
taken on new personas, created a past with new ancestors, and become transformed by their newly formed
relationships.
Curiously, in contrast to patients or potential patients,
who sometimes found answers to basic existential questions associated with their affliction, the adoptees tended
not to discover answers for their issues of abandonment
and rejectionthe question Why was I given away?
that may have been the deepest reason for searching for
their biological families. Their cultural comprehension
of kinship in biological terms did, however, allow them
to attempt to deal with these issues by reestablishing
contact with their birth parents and creating histories,
if only medical ones. By becoming reunited with their
birth families, the fragmented adoptees, torn between
cultural ideologies and lived experience, became, in the
words of many, whole, arguably masking the fragmentation people may feel more generally in contemporary capitalist society. But at the same time they confronted new issues and conflict that tore them apart.
Bartholet (1993:166) argues that in American society biological origins are central to our destiny and that it
is only genetically linked parents who are truly entitled
to possess their children and to whom children truly
belong (p. 167). Along with others (e.g., Andersen 1993)
25. Of course, the medicalization of family and kinship may also
reassure healthy people that they come from healthy stock. People
may take pride in the fact that their ancestors gave them positive
features such as blue eyes or lanky bodies. Although these may be
offset by unfavorable characteristics such as heavy thighs or other
deprecated physical attributes, these attributes do not draw the
individual into the medical domain in the same way as conceptualizations of genetic inheritance of disease.

she observes that the assumption of the search movement is that adoptees must forever suffer the loss of
their birth parents and the related loss of genetic continuity with the past and that they are prone to genealogical bewilderment as they struggle to live a life
cut off from their genetic origins (p. 172). In short, in
this literature adoptees are in pursuit of a genetic inheritance that is taken to be equivalent to their true
family, their significant same. According to Bartholet,
adoptees suffer when they are cut off from their biological links and generational continuity is destroyed. She
observes that sperm donors, their offspring, and birth
mothers in surrogacy arrangements increasingly voice
complaints of the pain they suffer from being cut off from
genetic forebears or descendants (pp. 22728),26 although she rightly claims that parenting cannot be
equated with procreation. She wisely observes that a
sense of immortality comes not from passing on ones
genes but from the parental relationship and how it
shapes the child. She concludes, All adoptions require
parents to transcend the conditioning that defines parenthood in terms of procreation and genetic connection
(p. 113).27

Summary and Conclusion


My concern is not with the truth or falsity of the science
of genetic inheritance. There is an extensive literature
that argues that biomedicine and the scientific enterprise
to which it is wedded are socially, culturally, and historically molded. For instance, according to Bowler
(1989:12), without denying the important factual consequences that have flowed from the development of genetics, the history of the field will show that the new
science was invented to serve human purposesit did
not grow automatically as a consequence of factual observations. Thus theories are invented rather than discovered (p. 13). From Bowlers vantage point, genetic
models are constructed to reflect the values of the social
groups whose interests are best served by the promotion
of these particular models (p. 17).
Fujimura (1996) is but one of a number of scholars to
26. Dolgin (1997) in fact reports that donor-inseminated offspring
seek their genetic fathers.
27. The majority of adoptees do not search for their birth parents.
According to the head of the support group 1.9 out of 4 adoptees
do so. The remaining adoptees may decline to do so, she suggested,
because of denial of their real feelings, loyalty to their adoptive
parents, lack of interest, or lack of mental energy. In her words,
You have to have some form of stability to be able to even undergo
the process. Dysfunctional people would certainly find it difficult
to start and finish, because it is an emotional and time-consuming
process. It seems to be people that are comfortablemost of the
people who I see search are comfortable with themselves and they
want their answer to finish formulating their image of themselves
and their past and their background. People who are very unhappy
with themselves normally dont search, from what I see. The argument is that such people are too busy trying to survive the consequences of that. People search at considerable emotional and financial cost. The emotional search is draining, and also there is an
ambivalence of not wishing to hurt the adoptive familys feelings.

This content downloaded from 200.130.19.150 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 13:41:14 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

f i n k l e r The Kin in the Gene F 247

have shown that scientific knowledge, including biomedical knowledge, is socially produced. She makes a
compelling case that genetic knowledge is constructed
when she demonstrates that in the late 1980s the view
of cancer changed from a set of heterogeneous diseases
marked by the common property of uncontrolled cell
growth to a disease of human genes (p. 1). This change
was brought about not by new discoveries or new epistemic advances but by negotiated social processes (Latour 1987). Haraway (1991:184), in a more critical mode,
describes the social constructionist approach best when
she states that no insiders perspective is privileged,
because all drawings of inside-outside boundaries in
knowledge are theorized as power moves, not moves towards truth.
In keeping with these scholars perspective, we have
come to acknowledge that biomedicine is a cultural system (Hahn and Kleinman 1983, Finkler 1991, Ingleby
1982, Krieger and Fee 1994, Lock 1980, Lock and Gordon
1988, Martin 1997, Wright and Treacher 1982, Young
1981)28 and that, like science itself (Brandt 1997, Fujimura 1996, Haraway 1991, Hess 1997, Latour and Woolgar 1979, Martin 1997, Richter 1972, and, on genetics,
Bowler 1989), is an intellectual endeavour that has
emerged at a particular historical moment in the social
formation of Western society. Like all other knowledge
systems, biomedicine is socially and culturally constructed, reflecting the themes of the society and culture
of which it is part while imposing these themes on cultural conceptualizations. For example, biomedicines
model of the human body as a standardized machine and
illness as the breaking down of its component parts (Berliner 1975, Martin 1987, Osherson and Amara Singham
1981, Turner 1992) mirrors the predominance of technology and machines in modern society while at the
same time imprinting on peoples consciousness a mechanistic view of themselves.29 An extensive body of literature shows persuasively how medical concepts are
socially constructed (Finkler 1991; Wright and Treacher
1982; Turner 1987, 1992), reflecting broader cultural
themes including gender differences (Johnson 1987, Martin 1997, Petchesky 1987, Ritenbaugh 1982, Rodin 1992,
Yanagisako and Collier 1990). Current hereditarian concepts are not, however, confined to any one gender (see
Granner 1988, Nelkin 1992, Nelkin and Lindee 1995).30
Recognizing the contingent nature of biomedical conceptualizations, even the most ardent critic of genetic
determinism will acknowledge the incontrovertible evidence that a handful of diseases are inherited (Hubbard
28. And see Fleck (1979[1935]:35), who, prior to most contemporary
scholars, said, In science, just as in art and in life, only that which
is true to culture is true to nature.
29. See especially Douglas (1992[1970]) on how our comprehension
of the body reflects broader societal themes.
30. My study dealt with women with family histories of breast
cancer, but my argument applies equally to men and women and
to the numerous diseases currently construed as hereditary. (I hasten to add that specific diseases may also have other consequences
not encountered among women with breast cancer.) The full impact
of the medicalization of family and kinship must continue to be
an empirical question.

and Wald 1993). We need to ask, however, why family


and kinship have been medicalized as we enter the 21st
century. The medicalization of family and kin is facilitated by American conceptualizations of kinship. In fact,
attributing disorders to genetic inheritance not only addresses ultimate causality but also builds on American
cultural understandings of kinship in biogenetic terms.
Schneider (1984:193) remarked that kinship has been
defined by European social scientists, and European social scientists use their own folk culture as the source
of many, if not all, of their ways of formulating and understanding the world about them. He recognized that
anthropological studies had imposed their folk knowledge on non-Western kinship, but he seems to have failed
to discern that scientific claims frequently follow a similar pattern (see Finkler 1991 on physicians cultural beliefs and biomedical understandings). I suggest that the
emphasis placed on genetic transmission elaborates on
the American folk category of bilateral kinship. Not surprisingly, then, the fact that American kinship builds on
a biogenetic template facilitates the wide popular acceptance of the belief in genetic inheritance and also explains, along with the powerful authority that science
possesses in contemporary society, the lack of resistance
to and even ready acceptance of the medicalization of
family and kinship. Folk notions of family as a biogenetic
entity allow for an effortless embrace of the scientific
and biomedical notion of genetic determinism precisely
because it mimics cultural conceptualizations of the biogenetic foundations of kinship.
The medicalization of family and kinship weaves into
a mantle of science the historical and cultural grasp of
kinship and reaffirms family and kinship cohesion that
has been lost in the lived world. As we have seen, Schneider viewed biological unity as the symbol for relationships of enduring diffuse solidarity, but whatever solidarity may exist rests in genetic unity. The American
family has not disappeared, but, arguably, it lacks unifying forces, a phenomenon that even Tocqueville had
recognized when he stated in the mid-19th century that
not only does democracy make men forget their ancestors but also it clouds their view of their descendants
and isolates them from their contemporaries
(1980[1840]). People have tended to become separated
from kin, if not from their immediate families, and family and kinship have taken on an amorphous cast. No
single explanation for diminished kinship ties in modern
society suffices. The most obvious cause may be geographic dispersal associated with social and economic
mobility, but the organization of work and the glorification of individualism that nourishes the market economy may also have played a role.
I suggest that biomedicine defines the family in precise
terms by uniting individuals with their families and kin.
The more social processes tend to distance people from
family and kin, the more biomedicine tends to move
them closer to consanguinity, creating new forms of interaction that may be embedded in the very absence of
interaction. People are compelled to recognize consanguinity even when in the lived world they define family

This content downloaded from 200.130.19.150 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 13:41:14 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

248 F c u r r e n t a n t h ro p o l o g y Volume 42, Number 2, April 2001

by a sense of sameness that may be grounded in friendship or sharing of affect and interest rather than in genes.
With the belief in genetic inheritance and the medicalization of kinship, interaction with family and kin may
no longer be required for people to recognize relatedness
and connection.
In the past, peoples existence was embedded in family
and kinship relations. A human being was defined as a
social person, inheriting from family status, power,
goods, blood, and honor. Normally, families bequeathed
to their offspring everything that was positive and negative in human existence. At present, family and kinship
relations may be defined more by the inheritance of disorders and pain than by the inheritance of status and
social attributes. Peoples kinship is sustained by the
DNA that mediates memory of their ancestors by the
relentless transmission from generation to generation of
its encoded material. DNA, as our proxy, records and
remembers our ancestors better than our fragile memories do. It establishes continuity with the dead, a continuity of particles that lack the moral responsibilities
associated with relatedness.
Memories are usually embedded in sounds, smells, affect, and tales of past ancestors and kinship ties. But we
recall our ancestors not for these characteristics or for
their achievements, for their beliefs, for the numerous
dimensions of their being, for their quirks, but for their
physicality.31 Although through DNA we establish continuity with the dead, it is a continuity comprised of
hollow particles that may lack any of the affect that is
normally associated with memories. Even if people wish
to forget their antecedents and reinvent themselves, the
physician will remind them of their true biological
ancestors. The family medical history is part of the persons identity and memory. Within the biomedical domain, the medical history and biological antecedents determine personhood, and knowing ones genetic ties is
sometimes raised to a spiritual state, a transcendent experience (Finkler 2000a).32
Yet, phenomenologically there is a distinction between experiencing oneself as a member of a significant
same group that feels a sense of solidarity and relatedness associated with shared experiences from the beginning of life and experiencing oneself as a member of
a family, or group, that shares DNA molecules. Once
adoptees find their birth mothers and medical histories,
they tend to create new fictions for themselves by establishing presumably loving relationships with those
people. And while they may, as most of the people I
interviewed reported, find a new wholeness, experi31. However, in the 19th century certain diseases were considered
prestigious; tuberculosis, for example, served as a metaphor for an
artistic personality (see Sontag 1978). Hemophilia may have been
a mark of nobility, and obesity was a mark of wealth. Sickle-cell
anemia is an indicator of race associated with African-American
descent (see Wailoo 1996).
32. In a lecture entitled Genetics and Faith, Francis Collins
(1999b), head of the Human Genome Project, has advanced the
notion that there is no conflict between religion and genetics and
that uncovering the genome is a religious experience.

entially it masks a sense of fragmentation as they continue to exist between two worlds: one rooted in the
fiction of as if by blood and the other in shared experience and affective ties.
The notion of shared experience suggests being in the
world and interacting with others, whereas being part of
the same DNA circle requires no social interaction. Bauman (1992:42) points out what Merleau-Ponty knew, that
the only way we can comprehend ourselves and know
that we are alive is by being with others and being anchored in a moral order. Levinas observes that humans
are beings with meaning and that meaning comes out of
our responsibility for others; being reduced to the is
without the ought equals solitude (quoted by Bauman
1992:42). As I have argued elsewhere (Finkler 1994), to
be human is to be a moral being, to insist on the ought
and the should against all odds, and the sense of responsibility to others that arises out of the ought is
initially experienced in ones significant same group.
To sense that one is part of a family chiefly because one
shares the same genes, requiring no social participation
or sense of responsibility to those who are related except
to provide blood samples for testing purposes, removes
the moral context of family relations and being in the
world. Relations between family and kin, however defined, are governed by a special morality arising out of
the recognition of commonality (Finch and Mason 1993,
Freeman 1968, Witherspoon 1975), whereas relations established on the basis of the new genetics lack moral
imperatives.
Paradoxically, genes are both amoral and moral. On
the one hand, people do not hold their ancestors responsible for transmitting faulty genes. On the other hand,
the medicalization of family and kinship gives meaning
to the randomness inherent in geneticsto the luck of
the drawby supplying a reason for suffering and thus
making it more bearable. Belief in genetic inheritance
carries a moral load in that it may even bring people
back to the religious notion of original sin and the sins
of the fathers, embodying the notion of predestination
(see Finkler 2000a). Ironically, the contemporary solitary,
independent, and autonomous individual becomes
united with genetic family and kin by sharing asocial
and amoral DNA. Bauman (1992:198) correctly observes
that the sociality of the postmodern community does
not require sociability. Its togetherness does not require
interaction. Its unity does not require integration. Thus,
the individual can enjoy traditional kinship and family
relations without moral obligation, responsibility, or sociability. At the same time, medicalization expands the
recognition of family and kin and gives them new importance for the individual that they may have lacked
before. Paradoxically, molecular biology and the genetic
model of family and kinship bridge the essentialism of
modern science with postmodern ideologies and experience. It could even be said that the ideology of genetic
inheritance promises contemporary humans immortality within the flux of the postmodern world. The individual exists in a transient world but is fastened biolog-

This content downloaded from 200.130.19.150 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 13:41:14 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

f i n k l e r The Kin in the Gene F 249

ically to the past and to the future because DNA codes


the past and the future.
Concepts about genetic inheritance do the work for
memories lost. Kinship is not only a relationship of the
present. Kinship relations are repositories of and connections with the past, sustained in the genealogical
memories of ones forebears. The memory represented
by DNA never forgets; it is embedded in the absence of
experience and feelings. DNA remembers what has long
been forgotten. It does not permit reinvention of the self
or the embellishment of ancestors: it records only the
forerunners physicality. People cannot invent or appropriate ancestors, because a DNA test will reveal the
truth.
Tocqueville noted that in a democracy those who
have gone before are easily forgotten (1980[1840]:507).
Indeed, in postmodern times, more than ever, memory
may be depthless, but genetic inheritance establishes
depth and continuity with previous generations and unifies people with their past. It reinforces or, arguably, reintroduces the experience of chronology, of time passing.
But, in characteristic postmodern fashion, as time and
space become compressed, memory is reduced to the exquisite simplicity of DNA molecules. While the postmodern individual may chiefly know the present, the
medicalization of family and kinship reminds people
that there was a past to which they are connected, defining an intergenerational space. In day-to-day experience, aunts, uncles, and even grandparents may not be
recalled, but they must be remembered when one is
asked for a family medical history.
Building on biologism, the medicalization of family
and kinship reinforces contemporary humans physicality by assigning shared identities to people, past and present, who may have little in common. It adds a new
dimension to memory while distancing people from their
being by erasing the complexity of living, if not of life.
Drawing on phenomenology, I introduce the notion of
lifes lesions, the adversity and the moral contradictions that become inscribed on the body and are expressed in non-life-threatening symptomatologies (see
Finkler 1991, 1994). With the medicalization of kinship,
peoples lives and experience become irrelevant to their
disorder, diminishing the work of memory. The chemical
construction of the gene is registered on the body of family and kin, overlooking lifes lesions.
The medicalization of family and kinship compels us
to remember the relatives and ancestors who bewitched
us by giving us bad genes. In fact, it engages us in a
profound contradiction. We have lost our right to exercise choice in selecting our relatives. The medicalization
of family and kinship forces us to establish a connectedness with kin in the wake of the weakening of family
ties, whether we choose it or not.
In sum, the medicalization of family and kinship is
but an extension of the ongoing process of the expansion
of the medical gaze to include our most profound relationships, building on the cultural template of bilateral
and biogenetic kinship that forms part of American beliefs and practices. It recasts our dispersed and loose kin-

ship ties as inexorable genetic ones and reestablishes our


continuity with family and kin. Once uprooted, we have
been reunited by the medicalization of family and kinship. Willingly or not, we must recognize our connectedness, albeit by our dysfunction and disorders. DNA
joins the compartmentalized, fragmented postmodern
individual to his or her ancestors.
The medicalization of family and kinship raises numerous research questions. Future studies of the diffusion of biomedicine (cf. Finkler 2000b) need to focus on
the phenomenology of the medicalization of family and
kinshiphow biomedical beliefs, especially about genetic inheritance of disease, are interpreted in Western
developed and non-Western societies. Although it is recognized that very little research has been done on genetic disorders, or the use of genetic services, from a
family perspective (Richards 1996:250), Richardss work
in England raises various important considerations concerning the intersection between the new genetics and
kinship, as does, for example, the work by Sachs (1996)
on more general notions of the concept of risk. It is also
necessary, however, to turn to Third World societies. For
instance, in Mexico, where the family and not the individual is still the primary unit of existence (Finkler
1991, 1994), the notion that ones family is detrimental
to ones health is disorienting. While there have been a
few clinical studies on how people respond to genetic
counseling in non-Western society (e.g., Dumars and
Chea 1989), it will be especially important for both academic and practical reasons to examine how people in
kinship-oriented societies, such as those in Africa, Melanesia, the Middle East, and India, respond to the medicalization of family and kin.33 Moreover, while my study
focused on people who, with a few exceptions, are part
of the giant American middle class, we need field studies
of how the medicalization of family and kinship is experienced among the working poor and among the elite.
Because people of all classes in the United States are
exposed in varying degrees to biomedical treatment and
thus to the taking of family medical histories, as well as
to the mass media, I hypothesize that the medicalization
of kinship will be widely accepted in American society
across classes. The degree to which these ideas have penetrated throughout American society and the Western
world remains an empirical question that requires future
investigation. Finally, given the increasing consciousness of genetic inheritance, it will be important to learn
to what degree it affects marriage and procreation
choices.

33. Dumars and Chea (1989:164) describe the genetic diseases


among the Cham (an ethnic group originating in Southeast Asia),
including a high frequency of alpha and beta thalassemia and E
hemoglobin. Here, although medical personnel explained the reasons for the disease that resulted in many newborn deaths, this
did not alter their reproductive behavior (p. 165).

This content downloaded from 200.130.19.150 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 13:41:14 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

250 F c u r r e n t a n t h ro p o l o g y Volume 42, Number 2, April 2001

Comments
janet dolgin
Hofstra Law School, Hempstead, N.Y. 11550, U.S.A.
(lawjld@mail1.hofstra.edu). 14 xi 00
Many aspects of Finklers insightful analysis in The Kin
in the Gene, as well as in her recent book Experiencing
the New Genetics (2000a), deserve praise and scholarly
notice. This brief note, however, comments on only one
issue.
Finkler suggests that the new genetics and the attendant ideology of genetic inheritance usher in an unprecedented notion of patient. She explains that with the
medicalization of kinship the individual is no longer the
sole patient and that genetic counselors are beginning
to ask questions such as who is the patientthe individual? The familythe spouse, the sister, the brother,
or the child? (Nelkin 1992:180) and suggests that the
medicine of the future will be the medicine not of the
individual but of the family. Some implications of this
insight are evident in a set of legal and institutional responses to the use of genetic information, especially in
familial contexts. The most remarkable of these is a
court case decided by a New Jersey appellate court in
1996. That case, Safer v. Pack,1 was initiated by Donna
Safer, who was diagnosed with a hereditary form of colon
cancer at age 36. Twenty-six years earlier Donnas father,
Robert Batkin, had died of the same illness.2 Donna sued
Dr. George Pack, who had treated Batkin during his final
illness.3 Donna and her husband, Robert Safer, argued
that Dr. Pack had had a duty to warn those at risk (including Donna) that his patients condition was hereditary so that they might have the benefits of early examination, monitoring, detection and treatment.4 The
court agreed. Judge Kestin, who wrote the courts decision, defined a broad duty to warn: It is appropriate . . .
that the duty be seen as owed not only to the patient
himself but that it also extends beyond the interests of
a patient to members of the immediate family of the
patient who may be adversely affected by a breach of
that duty.5
1. Safer v. Pack, 677 A.2d 1188 (N.J. Super. Ct. App. Div. 1996).
2. Robert Batkin was diagnosed with adenocarcinoma. A pathology
report prepared in 1956, after Robert Batkin first underwent surgery
for colon cancer, noted the existence of diffuse intestinal polyposis.
The condition is hereditary. I am grateful to Gary Maher, attorney
for Donna Safer and her husband, Robert Safer, for sending the
Safers complaint to the Hofstra Law Library.
3. Dr. Pack had died in 1969. Thus, the suit was actually commenced against George Packs estate (677 A.2d at 1190).
4. 677 A.2d at 1190.
5. 677 A.2d at 1992, citing Schroder v. Perkel, 432 A.2d 843 (N.J.
1981). Soon after the decision in Safer, the New Jersey legislature
rejected the opinions more far-reaching implications. The state
legislature provided that health-care workers are permitted to warn
relatives of patients suffering from genetic disorders only if the
patient has either consented to the revelation or died (Genetic Privacy Act, N.J. Stat. Ann., Sec. 17B:30-12 [West 1998]).

The basic message of Safer is reflected as well in a


1998 statement of the American Society of Human Genetics (ASHG),6 which suggested that health-care workers be allowed to reveal confidential information about
a patient to at risk relatives (p. 474).
Both Safer and the ASHG statement suggest a broad
redefinition of family privacy. Both assume a genetic
family, delimited exclusively through reference to shared
DNA. Within that family, each person is presumed to
mirror each other person and the larger whole. The implications are startling. As Finkler suggests, this construction of familyand presumably of other groups
that society identifies through reference to a genomereplaces the notion of autonomous individuality
with a notion of a larger group, defined through the metaphor of the individual but within which each person is
indistinguishable from each other and from the genetic
group.
This construction of group subordinates the interests
of the individual to those of a larger social whole. Louis
Dumont described that possibility as resulting from the
attempt, in a society where individualism is deeply
rooted and predominant, to subordinate it to the primacy
of the society as a whole (Dumont 1977:12). That redefinition displaces the autonomous individual with a
group, itself viewed as an undifferentiated, autonomous
whole. Moreover, that redefinitionwhich might affect
ethnic and racial groups as much as familiescould ultimately exclude as Other all those defined as genetically different from the so-called human genome.7

sarah franklin
Department of Sociology, Lancaster University,
Lancaster LA1 4YL, U.K. (s.franklin@lancaster.ac.uk).
3 xii 00
Finklers contribution to the literature on kinship in the
context of the new genetics makes a far-reaching and
original claim about the extent to which the gene acts
as an asocial repository of kin ties and indeed helps to
restore them, paradoxically, because the DNA records
and remembers our ancestors better than our fragile
memories do. Moreover, while she notes that negative
effects of geneticization include the perpetual patient
situation of a healthy person predisposed to an illnessyet-to-be, she contrasts this aspect of geneticization with
some of its more positive aspects, such as bringing people
closer together through both practical aspects of collecting and sharing genetic information and a sense of
solidarity in confronting actual or possible genetic ill6. The Society limited this right to cases in which the patient had
first been encouraged to inform identifiable at risk relatives but
had failed to do so, the harm is likely to occur and is serious and
foreseeable, and the harm that may result from failure to disclose is deemed to outweigh the harm that may result from disclosure (ASHG 1998:474).
7. The implications of this brief comment are considered in greater
depth in my article Personhood, Discrimination, and the New
Genetics (n.d.).

This content downloaded from 200.130.19.150 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 13:41:14 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

f i n k l e r The Kin in the Gene F 251

ness. These arguments are used to make a broader set of


claims about the extent to which contemporary American society remains kin- and family-based and the extent to which geneticization furthers very strongly established models of blood-based bilateralism and even to
suggest that DNA anchors individuals relationship to
the past and future differently. This is a very helpful
article both because it makes some very bold assertions
and because it does so in relation to a very clearly presented interpretation of some of the major sociological
questions about modernity, kinship, and embodiment
raised by the new genetics.
In contrast to recent ethnographers who consider kinship in the context of new reproductive and genetic technologies (Rapp 1999, Edwards 2000), emphasizing the variety, creativity, and constraints in the ways existing
kinship knowledges are deployed in relation to the new
genetics, Finkler wants to be able to draw some broad
formal conclusions that extend and contribute to existing models of modernity, medicalization, and kinship.
This leads her to spend quite a bit of time at the outset
reviewing the literature on the way in which modernization diminished the reliance on kin ties in favour of
market-based individualism, medicalization produced a
new form of modern subject for whom pathology became
identity, and new blended parenting arrangements gave
us the postmodern, flexible family. Because she wants
to add to this picture with her data, using specific cases
of the conflicts and resolutions individuals from a range
of backgrounds found in pursuit of more genetic information to illustrate new shifts in the story of contemporary American kinship where it meets the new genetics, she returns to these very broad themes at the end,
arguing that, in a sense, the new genetics is forcing us
to return to a more traditional definition of family
tiesthat is, consanguinity rather than choice. It is not
so much that Finkler wants the analytical categories she
is using to stand still as that she wants them to be reordered in what might be described as very consistent
patterns. In sum, she wants to tell us how geneticization
fits into or refigures the models of modernization and
medicalization we already know, but with a new twist.
This analytical goal distinguishes her work from that of
many other scholars working in this field and in particular from the work on kinship by Marilyn Strathern and
a host of other scholars who want to use the new technologies as a defamiliarizing lens, to add new reflexivity to the questions that are being asked about how
anthropological knowledge produces its objects and to
point out that this process cannot be separated from
other questions we are asking. This is why much of the
work on kinship in the context of new reproductive and
genetic technologies has overlapped with science studies, cultural studies, and feminist theory.
As Dorothy Nelkin and Susan Lindee (1995) have demonstrated, DNA is not simply a set of physical molecules
but a powerful set of cultural representations. To use
Donna Haraways phrase, DNA is a material semiotic
entity at the dense interface between biology and information, which is doing a great deal of representational

work both in changing scientific and medical accounts


of bodies, health, and illness and in the myriad cultural
settings, from advertisements to contemporary art, in
which it has become an iconic signifier. For me this is
one of the reasons that it is hard to know exactly what
Finkler means when she says that DNA remembers the
past and at the same time describes it as amoral and
asocial. I read her as being very literal in these claims,
but I find them difficult to reconcile with how polyliterate DNA and genes have become in contemporary society. Attributing memory to DNA seems to me
evidence of the way in which DNA is being socialized.
Holding a biological or chemical definition of DNA as
somehow objectively separate from the social relations which make DNA visible or active in very particular ways returns to a nature-culture dualism of which
a great deal of recent scholarly work in this field has
been explicitly critical.
Finklers thesis that DNA reties the blood tie is undoubtedly true in certain cases and demonstrates the
contradictory nature of geneticization. The exercise of
rethinking the relationship between modernity, medicalization, and kinship is also highly appropriate in the
context of the new genetics, which is rapidly reshaping
basic elements of how health will be defined in the future
and much else besides. It is unlikely, however, that the
social and cultural dimensions of the new genetics will
be analysed in much depth without a corresponding degree of theoretical innovation that moves beyond established binarisms of the individual and society, nature and
culture, or ideological and scientific. In fact, DNA is
itself a very good place to look for the ways in which
all of these categories are being very explicitly
reprogrammed.
hugh gusterson
Anthropology Program, MIT, Cambridge, Mass. 02139,
U.S.A. (guster@mit.edu). 27 xi 00
Evans-Pritchard (1937) told us that illness can provoke
a sense that the world is out of joint until the identity
of those causing it has been divined. For the Azande,
they were witches; for modern Americans they are increasingly likely to be ancestors who have passed on bad
genes.
This is not a bad thing for the medical profession. Finkler shows that those who believe themselves to be genetically predisposed to certain illnesses become perpetual patients. By analogy with the permanent war
economy (Melman 1974) of the cold war era, we might
say that this situation offers the medical-industrial complex the prospect of a permanent sickness economy
in which patients pay for medical help before, or without, getting sick.
Finkler, however, is not so interested in the political
economy of this situation as in the ways in which it is
remaking our sense of self. After the atrophy of the family in the postindustrial United States, some feel a new,
and discomfiting, sense of connection to the parents and

This content downloaded from 200.130.19.150 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 13:41:14 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

252 F c u r r e n t a n t h ro p o l o g y Volume 42, Number 2, April 2001

grandparents who bequeathed them their genes; those


given up for adoption may feel that, without their biological familys medical history, they are missing a key
part of their identity, and perpetual patients, subject
to the new micropanoptical technologies of genetic testing, increasingly see themselves as prisoners of their
genes.
Finklers compassionate and insightful article is particularly good at dramatizing the ways in which people
are reimagining their life histories and prospects in the
era of genetic testing and the new kinds of pain and
meaning this is generating. We might push the analysis
a little farther by probing the political functioning and
consequences of the discourse she anatomizes. As this
discourse circulates, the probabilistic language used by
experts in academic journals morphs in the minds of
ordinary citizens into a deterministic language of genetic
reductionism. It would be interesting to know how it
thrives when it is at odds with the complex, multicausal
models of our leading biomedical thinkers (Fox Keller
2000) and to what degree doctors and those sectors of
the medical-industrial complex that will benefit from
genetic testing and gene therapy are implicated in this.
It also bears pointing out that looking for the cause of
our cancer in our mothers genes rather than in the water
we drink and the air we breathe has political consequences that work to the benefit of powerful institutions
that deposit carcinogens in the environment. Instead of
looking for cancer clusters around industrial plants and
laboratories, we learn to look at our familiesthose who
care for us when we are sickas the source of our ills.
This is a way of seeing (Berger 1995) the world that needs
to be looked into more deeply.
Finkler asks how this geneticized way of seeing will
change the American family. One can imagine that, as
Silver (1998) has suggested, it will do so in part by providing new axes of inequality and stratification. Bourdieu
(1984) has argued that, in the industrial era, privileged
families learned to use the educational system to convert
one generations financial capital into the cultural capital of the next, which then converted it back to economic wealth. We can expect an increasing interchangeability of financial and genetic capital as affluent families
use genetic screening and embryo selection to give their
children the best possible start in life. Those who cannot
afford to access these technologies may find themselves
disadvantaged in the job market, the medical insurance
market, and so on. Thus, we may see a return to the
kinds of ideologies about family breeding that characterized 18th- and 19th-century Europeexcept that
this breeding will now be technologically mediated.
If I have one quibble with Finkler, it is in her use of
the term medicalizationa word that is not adequate
to convey the novelty and power of the processes she
analyzes. I would suggest that we speak not of the medicalization of the family but of its geneticization. Homosexuality was medicalized when it ceased to be a sin
and became instead a disease. It became geneticized
more recently when Dean Hamer (Hamer and Copeland
1996) claimed to have found a gay gene that made it

not a disease but a genetically determined variation in


the population. The family was medicalized, as Foucault
and his intellectual heirs have argued, when we learned
to look for the origin of our behavioral problems in our
parents relationships, when the state began to send social workers into the families of the poor, and when a
massive literature emerged on normal and deviant families. What Finkler describes goes beyond this as we learn
to reconstrue the family not in terms of social pathologies but in terms of the deterministic force of vectors
of gene transmission. She is documenting the emergence
of a new way of seeing that has profound implications
for us all.
nortin m. hadler and james p. evans
Department of Medicine, University of North
Carolina, Chapel Hill, N.C. 27599-7280, U.S.A.
(nmh@med.unc.edu). 28 x 00
Finklers conceptualization of the medicalization of kinship is compelling. Of course, the driving force for this
medicalization is the return to prominence of genetic
determinism among medical doctrines. To the extent
that this doctrine is flawed, the medicalization of kinship
is likely to be misguided, if not iatrogenic. Likewise, to
the extent that the doctrine is flawed, the recrudescence
of social iatrogenesis is facilitated. It is our intent, in this
brief commentary, to demonstrate that the doctrine is
seriously flawed indeed.
This is not to say that science is flawed or that a social
constructionist view of genetics is in any way valid.
However, the relevance of the new insights to the human
predicament is far more limited than is widely appreciated and far more circumscribed than the assertions of
august bodies and leading scientists cited by Finkler. Unbridled promise and enthusiasm is symbiotic with the
growth of the biotechnology industrial sector. All of this
permeates the hallowed halls of the medical academies,
persuades continuing medical education, and bears the
promise of profit for many in the know. In remonstrating
that the science supports Finklers thesis far more than
the creed of the genome, we are iconoclasts.
Genetic determinism offers clinical promise when diseases are consequent to discrete gene defects with high
penetrance. In such circumstances, genotyping is informative. For example, MEN-2 is a rare familial endocrinopathy with regard to which foreknowledge mandates
removal of the precancerous thyroid as early as infancy.
We may hope that, in our lifetime, foreknowledge based
on genotyping will afford palliation if not cure for individuals marked with a high likelihood of developing
hemophilia, sickle cell disease, cystic fibrosis, Fanconis
anemia, and more. For example, in certain cases, genetic
testing to ascertain risk of colon cancer may allow intensive screening by colonoscopy to be appropriately targeted to high-risk individuals. However, in the case of
the BRCA genes, which predispose to early onset of
breast and ovarian cancer, surveillance is imperfect and
the pharmaceutical and surgical options anything but

This content downloaded from 200.130.19.150 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 13:41:14 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

f i n k l e r The Kin in the Gene F 253

optimal. Until effective and acceptable preventative


measures exist for women at high risk of these cancers,
prognostic genetic testing is fraught with problems.
What likelihood would a particular person consider so
compelling as to call for prophylactic mastectomies and
oophorectomies? For someone such as Eve in Finklers
paper, disabuse, not genotyping, is in order.
Indeed, for most common diseases, prognostic genetic
testing is seldom more than marginally informative and
presents personal dilemmas for the patient and moral
dilemmas for the clinicians. The choice to pursue even
highly informative genetic testing rests on many individual factors and is rarely an unmixed blessing. The
genetics community was surprised to find that after introduction of a test for Huntingtons disease, few at-risk
individuals chose to pursue this option. When properly
informed and educated, individuals are quite capable of
determining whether such information is likely to be of
benefit to them; patients will vote with their feet. The
medical establishment must eschew hubris and educate
the public (as well as itself) so that our burgeoning arsenal of genetic tests can be used in an informed and
responsible manner.
The promise of genetic determinism relates to pauciallelic genetic diseases. This promise will be realized and
will be a triumph. However, genotyping is no match for
all that is multifactorial. A genetic influence has been
demonstrated for the susceptibility to and even the
course of many disease states. The crucial word is influence. For example, it has been possible to demonstrate that a segment of the population is more likely to
develop lupus, but the likelihood in that segment still
leaves lupus a rare disease. Kirsten also needs to be disabused; lupus is not a familial disease in spite of a demonstrable genetic influence on predisposition. This is
also true for most of the highly prevalent diseases, particularly those that are prevalent in the last decades of
life.
In our deterministic fervor, we often forget that
whether one develops any disease has less to do with
nature or nurture than with chance. Random stochastic mechanisms are the most important determinant
of disease occurrence and progression. It is a fools hope
(or perhaps blessing) to believe that we will be able to
sort out the interactions of environment, 100,000 human
genes, and the role of chance to provide a crystal ball
that is anything but murky. Uncertainty prevails. Is it
meaningful that someone is a bit more likely to suffer
dementia and a bit less likely to suffer coronary artery
disease? For the informed clinician, patient, or person,
the question is rhetorical.
What price the medicalization of kinship?
marit melhuus
Department of Social Anthropology, University of
Oslo. P.B. 1091 Blindern, 0317 Oslo, Norway
(marit.melhuus@sai.uio.no). 29 xi 00
Finklers article is both disturbing and thought-provokingdisturbing in that it presents yet another empirical

case of the grip that biogenetic models have on the (Anglo-European) grasp of specific social relations, thoughtprovoking in that the material it presents exemplifies
practices that seem specifically North American and
thus invite cross-cultural comparison.
Finkler posits that the medicalization of kin and family relationships at once concurs with an American
model of biogenetic kinship and serves to link people
who might otherwise have no wish (or need) to be connected, thus defying an ideology of individual free
choice. Leaving aside the problematic notion of American, Finklers empirical findingthat people hold contradictory values and draw on them variouslymirrors
social realties more generally. Indeed, the contrary would
be exceptional. Of greater interest are the ways in which
such contradictory values are articulated and practiced.
Research among the involuntarily childless in Norway
and their practices of assisted conception (be it through
new reproductive technologies or by transnational adoption) indicates that people hold both cultural and biological models and shift between them according to context. Although this tension between indigenous models
of nature and nurture runs through much of Norwegian
society, there is no doubt that biogenetic models are gaining ground. This is, for instance, reflected in laws pertaining to the rights of adopted children to know their
biological origins and the renewed debates on artificial
donor insemination, where there is a movement to repeal
the current law of donor anonymity. In both cases the
arguments are grounded in notions of knowing ones
identity, and identity is unproblematically assumed to
be the same as biogenetic origins. However, laws based
on such knowledge do not deter people from adopting
children from abroad. Local ideas of identity are more
complex; origins and belonging are not necessarily perceived as the same thing.
Issues of identity are also immanent in Finklers discussion of medical histories. Finkler states that the family medical history is part of the persons identity and
memory. It is through the need to establish medical
histories that people begin their quest for unknown kin.
This need, moreover, is irrespective of whether one is ill
or not; it is the possibility of becoming ill that is a driving
force. Medical histories, if they can be established, give
one a semblance of control over the future by unraveling
particular facts about the past. Thus they are more than
just a record of individual health cycles; they are a mnemonic device structuring individual perceptions of significant relationships. DNA is the key that unlocks
memory, inscribing ancestry into (or onto) related bodies
in the present and future. DNA is not only a matter of
time; viewed as a fact (devoid of morality), it contradicts
the values people attach to it.
Medical histories surface as documents certifying who
one is. Yet, the necessity of possessing one seems to rest
on the demands of health insurance companies, and thus
the family medical history is a type of identity document
that not only has personal valuein the sense of giving
a person a sense of beingbut may in fact be crucial in
obtaining medical treatment. In Western democratic-

This content downloaded from 200.130.19.150 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 13:41:14 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

254 F c u r r e n t a n t h ro p o l o g y Volume 42, Number 2, April 2001

type societies, we associate identity papers (and the right


to issue them) with state institutions (e.g., birth certificates, passports, identity cards) and certain forms of governmentality. They are related to notions of citizenship
as well as to control and power. Not only do we assume
that we have a right to these documents but we believe
that they confer on us certain rights (e.g., mobility, the
vote, schooling, and in some countries, health care). In
a recent study from Peru, Lund (2001) shows how being
indocumentado, without documents (which is the case
for approximately 30% of Perus population), causes
problems not only for individuals (limiting their access
to basic institutions) but also for the state. In her case
it is, among other things, a problem of matching peoples
and territory and establishing boundaries.
Identity documents are powerful and visible mechanisms of inclusion and exclusion. Although family medical histories appear to be of a different order from identity papers, they seem to work in the same way. Both
documents are invested with certifying authority the absence of which has marked repercussions on peoples
lives. Whereas identity papers are official documents regulated by the state, family medical histories work as
insidious gatekeepers, not open to public contestation.
The cultural meanings of biogenetic models can perhaps
be better apprehended by examining the social practices
through which they are enacted. This may enhance our
understandings of the apparent ease with which biogenetics is accepted as configuring realties.
d o ro t h y n e l k i n
Department of Sociology, New York University, New
York, N.Y. 10003, U.S.A. (dorothy.nelkin@nyu.edu).
31 x 00
Why are genetic explanations so powerful? As Susan Lindee and I observed in The DNA Mystique (1995), they
are particularly appealing in a society reacting with anxiety to the ambiguities of new families. The family
seems to be besieged, threatened by feminism, divorce,
gay rights, the ability of children to sue their parents,
the complex arrangements enabled by new reproductive technologies, and other social changes. Families
grounded in emotional ties appear to be chronically unstable, fragile, and insecure. Genetics, in contrast, seem
to ground family relationships in a stable and well-defined unitthe geneproviding the individual with indisputable roots that are more reliable than the
ephemeral ties of love, friendship, or shared values. Furthermore, as Finkler notes, we readily accept this medicalization of kinship because it mimics conceptualizations of the biogenetic foundation of kinship. In
effect, medicalization reinforces traditional family
values.
I would like to add a further reason for the influence
of genetic explanations. They suit our commercial culture. They have not only medicalized but commodified
kinship. Let me provide some examples. Belief in genetic
determinism has led to the remarkable expansion of the

reproductive technology industry. Women willing to undergo difficult and often dehumanizing procedures spend
more than $1 billion annually on infertility services. The
discourse on reproduction is pervaded by images of
banks, deposits, property, products, and possessions. Articles in family magazines have such titles as Babies to
Order and Shopping for Mr. Good Genes. Sperm donor profiles read like personal ads, providing detailed information about the donors favorite colors, ability to
carry a tune, and serious hobbies. Donor eggs from
women with carefully specified education and talents are
advertised on the Internet for as much as $50,000whatever the traffic will bear. Eggs and sperm are consumer
products evaluated according to their genetic worth, and,
like other commodities, they have been subject to theft.
They are part of the commodification of kin.
Commercial enterprises have proliferated to service
the family in the age of genetics. Genetic testing is big
business, and companies are identifying not only criminals but also kin. Highway billboards and New York
City taxicabs carry advertisements: Call 1-800-DNAType. Unregulated firms provide identity tests by mail.
Dads use their services to avoid child support and moms
to claim their right to child support through paternity
identification. Meanwhile children become property
on the basis of biological criteria, and their ongoing family relationships may be disrupted.
As biological ties assume growing importance, new
business enterprises form. Search firms are in the business of finding biological parents for adoptees seeking
roots. An international registry affiliated with 450
groups worldwide is available for people looking for relativesif, of course, they can pay. Genealogy is also a
growing business, and companies have proliferated to
help people trace their genetic origins so as to avoid genealogical bewilderment. And disinterment services
are available for people who want to document, through
DNA tests, their genetic connections with a dead relativeoften to validate inheritance claims.
Family anxieties about inherited disease also have
commercial implications. Assumptions about the origins of disease or behavioral conditions imply preferred
treatments. If a condition is defined in social terms, one
looks to changes in the family or social environment for
solutions. If a condition is believed to follow from genetic endowment, the preferred treatment is drugs or
medication. Genetic explanations have contributed to
the sale of psycho-stimulants, antipsychotic agents, antidepressants, antianxiety agents, and sedatives. The pharmaceutical industry has much to gain from medicalizing
the family.
Meanwhile, the family defined by genetic predisposition may face economic problems. If a woman is predisposed to a genetic disease, her children and siblings
may also be at risk, and they all may be subject to employment or insurance discrimination. Defining the family in terms of genetic predisposition may also encourage
family decisions based on a commercial calculus. An odd
example was the mother who knew that she was a carrier
of the Huntingtons gene and that her two daughters had

This content downloaded from 200.130.19.150 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 13:41:14 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

f i n k l e r The Kin in the Gene F 255

a 50% chance of inheriting the gene. She brought the


girls to a clinic to be tested for the gene because she
could only pay tuition for one child and wanted to decide
which one to send to college.
But technological optimism persists. The new genetics
offer medicalized families a hope of buying solutionseven perfectionthrough gene enhancement.
Emerging technologies offer the possibility of diagnosing
genetic disease in the embryo and the hope of in vitro
therapy prior to implantation. Gene therapies are leading
to gene manipulationperhaps, in the future, for cosmetic purposes. Heredity may yet be overcome.
Relationships in the commodity culture of the United
States are increasingly based less on moral understandings than on market exchange. Aggressive commercialization is invading nearly every sector of human life. Not
surprisingly, the new genetics is fostering not only the
medicalization but also the commodification of kinship
and family life in contemporary American society.
martin richards
Centre for Family Research, University of Cambridge,
Cambridge CB2 3RF, U.K. (mpmr@cam.ac.uk).
21 xi 00
Finklers paper is to be welcomed as an addition to the
disappointingly small numbers of studies of family and
kinship in relation to the new genetic technologies. Finkler raises important points about the ways in which inherited disease may colour family histories and remembrances and influence family attitudes and relationships.
However, she also makes a number of generalizations
which are difficult to sustain.
She suggests that family and kinship are being medicalized by the advent of the new genetics. While she
summarizes a number of studies which show the medicalization of social and moral conditions, she provides
little evidence that medicalization stems from the new
human genetics. She states that more than 5,000 medical conditions have been attributed to genetic inheritance, and with the work of the Human Genome Project,
we daily learn of another disorder that is traceable to
genetic transmission. While it is true that there are
some 5,000 Mendelian disorders which have dominant,
recessive, or sex-linked patterns of inheritance, this is
knowledge that in many cases is a century old and owes
nothing to the Human Genome Project. These are disorders which have their characteristic patterns of inheritance across generations. What new genetic research has
done is to provide tests that can predict which individuals within the families at risk are likely to develop those
diseases which develop in adulthood and who has or is
a carrier of the recessively inherited conditions. It is not
true that the Human Genome Project demonstrates genetic transmission where this has not been previously
recognized. Similarly, the taking of family medical histories is a basic technique in Western medicine which
can be traced back to the 19th century, when there was
much concern about inherited disease. More evidence is

needed to substantiate the claim that the new molecular


genetics has medicalized understanding of kinship and
family relationships or that genetic inheritance has become the prevailing causal explanation of afflictions and
of human behaviour more generally.
As the four respondents she quotes demonstrate, there
are those for whom family medical histories are particularly salient, and it may well be the case that current
concerns with genetics have increased such salience and
perhaps, for some, provided new narratives for discussion
of family relationships. However, our own interviews
with women at risk from the inherited forms of breast
cancer (see Richards 1999) show that, in some cases at
least, the knowledge that the disease runs in the family long pre-dates molecular genetics. Indeed, some
members of the present generation of such families may
be relieved to discover that their family knowledge is
now accepted by the medical profession and that they
can be given risk information and, for those who want
it, predictive genetic testing.
In a discussion of the medicalization of kinship, it is
surprising that Finkler does not consider the possible
consequences of easily available DNA paternity testing
or the use of such techniques in matters such as the
assessment of liability for child support payments. These
pose new situations for families.
Finkler suggests that kinship no longer plays a significant role in our lives. While there have been major
changes in families, the evidence suggests that kinship
remains important for identity and social position in the
U.S.A. (Johnson 2000) and the U.K. (Finch and Mason
1993, Edwards 2000). New reproductive technologies
may pose new situations for conventional notions of kinship, but they are also used and perceived through concepts of kinship. So, for example, extrafamilial providers
of gametes may either be included in families as friends,
aunts, or godparents or have their existence hidden by
secrecy (Richards 2001). In this context it would be helpful to explore the parallels between adoption and the use
of new reproductive technologies (see Haimes 1988). For
example, to what extent is there an association between
the development of open adoption and openness within
families about the use of donated eggs and sperm? Finkler provides striking narratives from adopted individuals
who have sought to find their birth parents, but such
searches are probably as old as adoption. What is needed
to support her thesis is evidence that the narratives of
searches have changed in the era of molecular genetics.
Finkler may not be concerned with the truth or falsity
of the science of genetic inheritance but her arguments
need to be closely informed about the metaphors and
images provided for the public by biomedical scientists
(Nelkin 1997, Fox Keller 1995) and the ways in which
these are perceived and by which biomedical technologies may influence families. Her view of the ways in
which notions of genetic science and its technological
practices influence family relations and histories needs
to be developed further because, as she states, genetic
diseases are the concern of families, not individuals. But
in doing this we need to distinguish what follows from

This content downloaded from 200.130.19.150 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 13:41:14 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

256 F c u r r e n t a n t h ro p o l o g y Volume 42, Number 2, April 2001

modern developments and what is part of a much older


understanding of diseases that may run in the family
(Richards 1996).
lisbeth sachs
Department of Communication Studies, Linkoping
University, Linkoping, Sweden (lisbeth.sachs@
swipnet.se). 30 x 00
It is very satisfying to discover that the study of kinship
in anthropology is entering a new era because of research
in genetics and the genetic inheritance of disease. Finkler
explores the impact of this biomedical research on todays fragmented, postmodern way of dealing with family and kinship with great engagement and intelligence.
Her focus is on American society, but her descriptions
and arguments are valid for the European world as well.
She has a way of dealing with her ethnography that is
intriguing and much appreciated in the Nordic countries.
Some surprising discoveries stand out. The fact that
some adopted persons begin searching for their roots and
their families mainly for the sake of their medical histories, rather than for the psychological reasons (e.g., the
question Why did you leave me to somebody else?)
that are so common in earlier descriptions of adoptees
problems, strikes me as one of the major implications of
the medicalization of kinship.
Being familiar with Finklers earlier work, I find it
somewhat surprising that she is not tempted in this article to take up the discussion of causality and life experience in relation to heredity in her interview material.
Surely the persons she has been talking to have their
doubts about genes being the only cause of disease and
try to explain familial disease and suffering in other
ways.
It also strikes me that there is no information here
about how people have become aware of their predisposition to or risk of cancer. In our research in Sweden
there is a big difference between the experience of risk
that one gets from presymptomatic diagnostic information based on genealogical mapping and the information that one gets from genetic testing. It is not yet
possible to test for all diseases. The interactive process
in a clinical situation in which the individuals risk is
calculated either from a medical history or from a DNA
test is very important for the management of risk over
time. There is also an important difference in the kinds
of knowledge generated by these two procedures.
Finkler adopts the perspective that biomedicine is socially and culturally constructed. I wish she had taken
this a step farther by relating some of the biomedical
facts in her study to the ongoing discussion. This would
have extended the earlier work in the field of medical
anthropology (e.g., Good 1994) in the direction of a truly
interdisciplinary discussion of knowledge and beliefs related to her ethnographic material. In my view we have
carried postmodernist social constructivism too far in
discussions of diseases such as AIDS and cancer. These
diseases do exist, as does the body, and we have to deal

with both in relation to our more culturally created notions and interpretations of medical facts. Social scientists ought to be able to discuss etiology and causality
with a more open mind and relate their research based
on fieldwork to biomedical knowledge. This kind of
problematization is among the most fruitful aspects of
Finklers earlier research in Mexico. Even though she is
dealing with mainstream Americans here, the problem
is the same.
One last comment is on the notion of personal/emotional and molecular memory in Finklers article. In my
own research in clinical situations of presymptomatic
diagnosis, it is obvious that memory is related to the
importance of remembering. If you are depending on the
medical history for information about your own risk or
that of your children, your memory may be sharper than
it is with regard to distant kin that you ought to inform
about the familys risk. Here there is also a difference
between those who have a diagnosis based on genealogical mapping and those whose diagnosis comes from a
genetic test. But the main argument here is that a persons memory is the only material there is on which
to base a presymptomatic risk diagnosis, and DNA can
only confirm from the tests that have been taken
whether people carry the same mutation on a gene. The
power in genetic research is with the informant, the person who exposes his or her family and kin by mentioning
them as potential carriers of a predisposition. Finklers
statement that DNA remembers what has long been forgotten is of course valid only when you can check
whether people are trying to invent ancestors. Family
members who are not visualized by the memories of
their kin do not exist even for the memory of DNA.

Reply
kaja finkler
Chapel Hill, N.C., U.S.A. 13 xii 00
The various responses to this paper are gratifying in that
they stimulate so many exciting new ideas and broaden
the perspectives for the study of family and kinship in
the context of beliefs about genetic inheritance. They
also testify to the tensions between the two theoretical
approaches in anthropology that this paper straddlessocial constructivism, advanced by Franklin, Gusterson, and Nelkin, and positivism, advocated by Hadler
and Evans, Richards, and Sachs. I hasten to add that these
tensions exist also in other academic disciplines, including philosophy (between nominalism and realism).
I thank all the commentators for the time and careful
consideration they gave to this paper and Dolgin for calling attention to my 2000a book, which would probably
answer some of the concerns raised by Nelkin, Richards,
and Sachs. In this reply, I will first address the individual
commentators observations and then move on to some

This content downloaded from 200.130.19.150 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 13:41:14 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

f i n k l e r The Kin in the Gene F 257

thoughts on the conflict between the two theoretical


perspectives.
Research on family and kinship and the new reproductive technologies has been greatly advanced by various scholars, notably Dolgin, Franklin, Strathern, and
others, but the examination of the ideology of genetic
inheritance in the context of family and kinship is in its
infancy. Unquestionably, reproductive technologies raise
many political, economic, social, and ethical issues, but,
as I have said and as Franklin recognizes, my concern
here is not with these technologies. The new reproductive technologies and the new genetics are closely intertwined, but they must not be conflated as they seem
to be by Richards and Nelkin. There is a great deal of
difference between an embryo created by in vitro fertilization and people who come from families with breast
cancer. While the ideology of genetic inheritance may
guide both, they must not be confused.
Dolgin addresses the legal consequences of the medicalization of family and kinship, which call attention
to the cracks in what is normally accepted as unproblematic biomedical truth about the inheritance of disease. Safer v. Pack is a superb example of a consequence
that I have not explored, namely, the violation of privacy
(but see n. 22). Arguably, privacy is sacred in American
society, and it is being sacrificed with the medicalization
of family and kinship because a group rather than an
individual is the patient. For better or for worse, the autonomous individual will no longer stand alone or suffer
in isolation but will also no longer be able to choose his
or her family, having become subordinate to a biogenetically defined group. Dolgin and Melhuus foresee a disturbing future in which individuals may be excluded and
marked as Other because their genomes do not conform
to the normal profile. At the same time, as Gusterson
suggests, some may acquire genetic capital and become a separate class with special privileges.
Nelkins observations adumbrate issues of the commodification of genetics that Gusterson discusses and
Hadler and Evans allude to as well. The business of genetics, including the Human Genome Project (HGP), has
opened new frontiers for the medical and pharmaceutical
industries.
Elsewhere (2000a) I present various theories that attempt to explain the prevalence of the ideology of genetic
inheritance in mid-20th century. I point out that the
political economy of the medicalization of family and
kinship helps to answer this question only in part. Nevertheless, Nelkins observations are extremely pertinent,
and she provides us with stunning support for my assertion that people desire to establish connection with
ancestors through DNA testing to the extent that they
seek disinterment services. The mother with the
Huntingtons gene who sought a genetic test for her children to help her decide which child merited a college
education is an especially striking instance of Gustersons idea of parents attempting to ensure their childrens accumulation of both educational and genetic
capital.
Franklins work in the field of kinship and reproduc-

tive technologies has been exemplary, and she has also


captured beautifully the major point of my argument. I
see DNA as a reality to which we give agency and attribute memory every time a genetic counselor and a
physician ask for a family medical history. Franklin is
needlessly puzzled by my use of DNA as a marker of
remembrance. The fact that an amoral and asocial DNA
is represented and molded by our culture underscores
my conviction that culture and nature cannot be separated and that DNA is configured as culture. But perhaps
I have not sufficiently emphasized my view that the two
are inextricably intertwined. DNA is at once a molecule
that leaves traces from generation to generation and a
proxy for memory. It is also, in Melhuuss words, a mnemonic device structuring individual perceptions of significant relationships. We cannot escape from the reality that can only be known culturally and that makes
sense only because human beings give it meanings. A
material semiotic entity is still a material reality that
bites.
Gustersons comments are thought-provoking in suggesting various ramifications of the medicalization of
family and kinship. I am particularly intrigued by his
application of Bourdieus theory of capital to genetic capital and by his notion of a permanent-sickness economy
to accommodate perpetual patients. Although I regard
the political-economy approach as powerful, Gusterson
is correct that my focus here is on peoples experience
of the medicalization of family and kinship and the advantages, dilemmas, and contradictions it creates for
them in contemporary society. He takes the analysis in
yet another direction when he raises the question of the
degree to which doctors and the medical industrial complex contribute to genetic reductionism. I have elsewhere (2000a) discussed his point that the medicalization of family and kinship relieves the state of the
responsibility to deal with the deposition of carcinogens
in the environment and in foods that may be the chief
cause of cancer. It is easier to blame families and ancestors, who lack lobbies in Congress, than for the state to
consider and deal with the extrasomatic factors that may
produce sickness.
Indeed, Gusterson and Dolgin point out that the medicalization of family and kin could lead to creating a new
Other, deepening inequalities and producing a new social
stratum based on the possession of genetic capital. This
issue is of particular concern to ethicists in the face of
the new technologies that may encourage attempts to
invent perfect embryos and rests at the intersection
between the new reproductive technologies and the new
genetics.
I appreciate Gustersons quibble over my use of the
notion of medicalization. Actually, as I explain elsewhere (2000a), I prefer to use the concept of the hegemony of the gene instead of geneticization because the
Gramscian construct of hegemony encompasses the concept of the power of dominant institutions to impose an
ideology by their very authority, which permeates the
social and cultural fabric of daily life, without the use
of force. I do not find geneticization a similarly com-

This content downloaded from 200.130.19.150 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 13:41:14 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

258 F c u r r e n t a n t h ro p o l o g y Volume 42, Number 2, April 2001

pelling term, although I agree with Gusterson that medicalization is a more general and geneticization a
more specific term for the phenomenon at hand.
Melhuus too takes the notion of the medicalization of
family and kinship in a new direction, especially in likening the family medical history to an identity document that has the power to include and to exclude. I
consider Melhuuss notion that identity documents are
issued by the state and family medical histories are insidious gatekeepers highly original. Indeed, one already
hears predictions that soon we will carry on our bodies
chips encoding our DNA that can be used for multiple
purposes in the public and private domains.
I am indebted to Sachs for noting that my analysis is
applicable to Nordic Europe as well. Along with Melhuus, I hope that studies will be done cross-culturally
to address the extent to which the medicalization of family and kinship takes place in different Western and nonWestern settings. I too was surprised by my findings
about adoptees. Although it would be incorrect to reduce
the reasons for their searches to purely medical ones, all
the adoptees I interviewed but one identified the need
for a family medical record as one major reason for
searching for their biological families.
Sachs notes and Melhuus too has found that people
may have their doubts about the ideology of genetic inheritance. This is clear from narratives of women with
breast cancer (Finkler 2000a). It is fascinating, however,
that while people contemplate alternative explanations
for their affliction, including exposure to environmental
toxins, most reject them in favor of genetic inheritance
because the ideology of genetic inheritance has become
naturalized.
Sachs calls attention to an important distinction between the ways in which people become conscious of
the ideology of genetic inheritancewhether through
the taking of a medical history or through DNA testing.
However, this distinction fails to account for healthy
adoptees determination to find their birth mothers, inasmuch as they have not been exposed to genetic counseling. The adoptees have, however, been exposed to biomedicine, to the media, and to the zeitgeist. Arguably,
there are cultural differences between Europe and the
United States that may also influence the ways in which
people become conscious of beliefs about genetic inheritance. Nelkin and Lindee (1995) show that in the United
States we are constantly bombarded by reports on genetic
inheritance in the print and visual media. Judging by
Melhuuss observations, what Hornblower (1999) has described as roots mania has not yet reached Norway.
Aside from the mass media and genetic counseling,
however, another dimension to the medicalization of
family and kinship that influences peoples perceptions
of genetic inheritance is the pervasive scientific ethos
that insists on evidence for any claim. A familial medical
history supplies such evidence. People may discount alternative explanations, such as the possibility that the
entire family was exposed to similar toxins that might
have produced the disease or, as in Mayas case, that her
family was bewitched. Moreover, as many adoptees have

pointed out and as we have seen in Kristens case, physicians depend on a familys medical history to make the
diagnosis that the disease is familial (Richards 1996).
Even so, Sachss concern about the ways in which people
learn about the belief in genetic inheritance should alert
future investigators of medicalization to address this
question.
Finally, Sachss point about DNA as memory seems
to suggest that humans beings have a choice about what
they remember. Of course, as Freud recognized long ago,
memory of any kind is selective. However, the medicalization of family and kinship requires people to remember; it makes memory of kin important.
Richards incorrectly asserts that I attribute medicalization to the new genetics. In fact, I recognize that medicalization is not new, and nowhere do I suggest that the
Human Genome Project is responsible for it. The HGP
assumes that identifying the genes will open the door to
the understanding of disease. For example, according to
the web site of the National Human Genome Research
Institute, Our genes orchestrate the development of a
single-celled egg into a fully formed adult. Genes influence not only what we look like but also what diseases
we may eventually get. The HGP also promises to usher
in an era of molecular medicine, with precise new approaches to the diagnosis, treatment, and prevention of
disease (www.ornl.gov/hgmis/faq/faqs1.html4/20). Furthermore, Francis Collins (1999), director of the National
Human Genome Research Institute, has hailed the project as the book of life that will be opened by the year
2002 and will explain, cure, and predict nearly all human
diseases.
Richards points out that the family medical history
was adopted by biomedicine in the 19th century, at a
time when there was also great concern about inherited
diseases, albeit understood more in Lamarckian than in
Mendelian and Weismannian terms. His remark supports my point that the taking of medical histories is
linked with hereditarian views. His report that knowing
that a disease is familial often relieves the patient of
responsibility for it is a point that emerges from many
narratives (Finkler 2000a). We can sense Kristens relief
that she is sane on learning that Raynauds disease is
rooted in her heredity. As has Richards, I have found that
knowing that a disease is inherited also gave informants
a sense of control. What is more, I have found that for
some the notion of surviving a familial history of affliction is evidence of the strength of the family rather than
its weakness.
Richards is correct that the new paternity testing for
child support will raise new issues, adding yet another
dimension to the medicalization of family and kinship.
As Daniels (1997) demonstrates, the fathers genetic contribution to his offsprings health state is invisible, disease in the child usually being attributed to the gestational mother. With the medicalization of family and
kinship the fathers role in his offsprings health will
become more visible and he will need to accept responsibility in many new ways.
Richards may have overlooked my n. 7, in which I cite

This content downloaded from 200.130.19.150 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 13:41:14 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

f i n k l e r The Kin in the Gene F 259

Finch and Masons work and indicate that there seems


to be some difference between the U.K., France, and the
United States regarding the role of the postmodern family in peoples lives. His assertion that there is a similarity between open adoption and the use of donated eggs
is very interesting, but, as Bartholet (1993) observes, the
two must not be equated. His comment that adoptees
searching for their birth parents is probably as old as
adoption is an assertion that he fails to substantiate. As
I note, searches may have existed, but the rise of an
extensive search movement among adoptees corresponds
to the time when the ideology of genetic inheritance
came to the forefront in the 1960s (see Bartholet 1993,
Belkin 1999, Finkler 2000a, Modell 1994).
I concur with Richards that we need to see what is
new and what is not. Indeed, I have traced the history
of the concept of heredity elsewhere (2000a). Introduced
into the English medical literature between 1860 and
1870, it no longer was simply a descriptive term that
denoted the transmission of property or physical and
moral qualities but became a self-sufficient cause (Lopez-Beltran 1994; see also Rosenberg 1976).
I especially value Hadler and Evanss response because,
as physicians and geneticists, they bring a biomedical
perspective to the analysis. It is rewarding to find ones
conclusions corroborated when one is treading on anothers territory. Hadler and Evans stress, as I do, the
incontrovertible evidence that certain diseases are inherited genetically, and they have identified better than
I have which diseases follow a predictably inherited pattern. Yet, they, too, lament the genetic determinism that
is manifested in the medicalization of family and kinship. For example, they call attention to the flaws of
medical surveillance of ovarian and breast cancer and
the dubiousness of genetic testing. Their observation
that whether one develops any disease has less to do
with nature or nurture than with chance is especially
insightful.
But to accept the notion of chance is to be willing to
live with uncertainty to which human beings cannot
easily submit. To be human is to impose order and meaning on the reality of chaos. This has been the work of
religion (Berger 1969) and now is also the work of biomedicine. As many of the afflicted recognize, humans
reject the notion of randomness, a roll of the dice. In
fact, one of the reasons that sacred healing attracts so
many people is the quest for certainty (Finkler 1994).
Genetic determinism promotes a sense of certainty, and
with this certitude comes a sense of control. Eve is able
to do something about the certainty that she will become afflicted. Paradoxically, people in her situation
may also contemplate the idea of predestination that is
embedded in genetic determinism in the same way as,
as Melhuus points out, people may hold both cultural
and biological models at the same time. One of the
women I interviewed had a prophylactic mastectomy in
an attempt to control the risk of getting cancer owing
to her family medical history and was dismayed and morally indignant when she nevertheless became afflicted
with breast cancer (Finkler 2000a).

Hadler and Evans are not social constructivists; it is


precisely because they are scientists that they can see
the flaws in genetic determinism. The ideology of genetic inheritance bridges positivism with postmodernism, and so, I believe, does my work. As Sachs intimates,
I have attempted to steer clear of the culture wars. In
my long experience as an anthropologist, my theoretical
approach has been pragmatic. By this I mean that my
starting point has always been a question about human
life for which I seek answers in ethnographic work and
empirical data. Whatever theoretical approach illuminated that question was the one I would use. A quantitative, more positivistic approach may be useful for
some questions but not for others (see Finkler 1991).
Thus, in much of my work I have combined positivistic,
social constructivist, and political-economic approaches
without feeling a traitor to any one of these. For example,
as I show in another place (Finkler 2000b; also 1991),
biomedicine becomes constructed in United States and
reconstructed in another cultural venue, such as Mexico,
but, I argue, we must nevertheless question what exactly
is being constructed and what remains invariant in diverse cultural settings.
While I do not doubt for a moment that kinship reckoning and family structure are social and cultural constructs, can we say the same for genetic inheritance?
Whereas extreme social constructivism may even say
that there is no objective reality, cancer is palpable today
as it was for ancient Egyptians and Greeks, who described it and their understanding of its causes (Finkler
2000a). Breast cancer is no more socially constructed
than tuberculosis or amoebiasis, but the explanation for
its occurrence, its etiology, and the meaning we give it
are socially constructed. In seeking explanations for their
suffering, human beings the world over have developed
etiological theories of diseasewhether witchcraft, invasion by evil spirits, punishment by a deity, ancestral
ghosts, and an inimical environment or, in Western biomedicine, the failure of body parts, invasion by pathogens, contagion, trauma, stress, aging, and heredity. To
make sense of human beliefs and practices, I have drawn
upon a modified social constructivist perspective that I
believe has always been intrinsic to anthropological discourse by the very nature of its preoccupation with the
concept of culture. I depart from the strict constructivist
view, however, in believing that there is a reality independent of our cultural productions. Genetic transmission is not purely a social construction, as any victim,
of, say, Huntingtons disease will attest. I consider the
presence of a reality, say, of DNA molecules, which, paradoxically, cannot exist without being culturally interpreted. In this manner, we can avoid the dualism that
rightly concerns Franklin and retain the realism that
Sachs insists on. Sachs is correct in saying that postmodernism and social constructivism must be approached with caution, as I have tried to do here. However, in the instance of the ideology of genetic
inheritance, the issue may not be the binarism of nature
vs. culture but, as Hadler and Evans assert, the random-

This content downloaded from 200.130.19.150 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 13:41:14 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

260 F c u r r e n t a n t h ro p o l o g y Volume 42, Number 2, April 2001

ness of genesunless, of course, one wishes to reduce


the notion of randomness to a social construction.
In the end, whether cultural beliefs and practices are
socially constructed or rooted in an objective reality may
arguably be less significant than how the individual, as
agent, experiences and negotiates them. To assess this,
we cannot simply theorize but must meticulously observe and carefully listen to the culture bearers. This is
why I said that I do not question the truth or falsity of
the ideology of genetic inheritance.
This meditation on the conflict between constructivism and positivism is my attempt to deal with a dilemma
that is difficult to resolve for oneself, let alone for human
experience. Arguably, this is just one step in that
direction.

References Cited
a d a t o , a l l i s o n . 1995. Living in legacy. Life 18(4):60.
a d e l s w a r d , v. , a n d l . s a c h s . 1996. The meaning of 6.8:
Numeracy and normality in health information. Social Science
and Medicine 43:117987.
a m e r i c a n s o c i e t y o f h u m a n g e n e t i c s . 1998. ASHG
statement: Professional disclosure of familial genetic information. American Journal of Human Genetics 62:474. [jd]
a n d e r s e n , r o b e r t . 1993. Second choice: Growing up
adopted. Chesterfield, Mo.: Badger Hill Press.
a p p l e t o n , l . 1995. Rethinking medicalization: Alcoholism
and anomalies, in Images of issues. Edited by Joel Best, pp.
5980. New York: Aldine de Gruyter.
a r e n s b e r g , c o n r a d , a n d s o l o n k i m b a l l . 1965. Culture and community. New York: Harcourt, Brace and World.
b a r t h o l e t , e l i z a b e t h . 1993. Family bonds. New York:
Houghton Mifflin.
b a u m a n , z y g m u n t . 1992. Mortality, immortality, and other
life strategies. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
b e g l e y, s h a r o n . 1996. Holes in those genes: Not even DNA
can live up to all the hyped claims. Newsweek, January 15, p.
57.
. 1997. Infidelity and the science of cheating. Newsweek,
December 30/January 6, pp. 5759.
b e l k i n , l i s a . 1999. What the Jumans didnt know about Michael. New York Times Magazine, March 14, pp. 4249.
b e l l a h , r . , r . m a d s e n , w. , s u l l i v a n , a . , s w i d l e r ,
a n d s . m . t i p t o n . 1985. Habits of the heart. Berkeley:
University of California Press.
b e r g e r , j o h n . 1995. Ways of seeing. New York: Viking. [hg]
b e r l i n e r , h o w a r d . 1975. A larger perspective on the Flexner Report. International Journal of Health Services 5:57391.
b l a k e s l e e , s a n d r a . 1997. Accounting for taste. New York
Times, February 23.
b o b i n s k i , m . 1996. Genetics and reproductive decision making, in The Human Genome Project and the future of health
care. Edited by Thomas H. Murray, Mark A. Rothstein, and
Robert F. Murray Jr., pp. 79112. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
b o u r d i e u , p i e r r e . 1984. Distinction: A social critique of
the judgement of taste. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
[hg]
b o w l e r , p e t e r , j . 1989. The Mendelian revolution. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
b r a n d t , a l l a n , m . 1997. Behavior, disease, and health in
the twentieth-century United States: The moral valence of individual risk, in Morality and health. Edited by Allan M.
Brandt and Paul Rozin, pp. 5379. New York: Routledge.

b r a n s e n , e . 1992. Has menstruation been medicalized? Or


will it never happen? Sociology of Health and Illness 14:
98110.
b r o o m , d . , a n d r . w o o d w a r d . 1996. Medicalization reconsidered: Toward a collaborative approach to care. Journal of
Health and Illness 18:35778.
b ro w n l e e , s h a n n o n , g a r e t h , g . c o o k , a n d v i v a
h a r d i g g . 1994. Tinkering with destiny. U.S. News and
World Report 117(8):58.
b r o w n l e e , s h a n n o n , a n d j o a n n e s i l b e r n e r . 1991.
The age of genes. U.S. News and World Report 111(19):64.
b u n k l e , p . 1993. Calling the shots? The international politics
of Depo-Provera, in Racial economy of science. Edited by
Sandra Harding, pp. 287302. Bloomington: Indiana University
Press.
c a r e y, j o h n , n a o m i f r e u n d l i c h , j u l i a fl y n n , a n d
n e i l g r o s s . 1997. The biotech century. Business Week,
March 10, pp. 7890.
c a r s t e n , j a n e t . 2000. Introduction: Cultures and relatedness, in Cultures of relatedness. Edited by Janet Carsten, pp.
137. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
c l a r k e , a n g u s . 1999. The genetic dissection of complex
traits, in Genes and morality. Edited by Veikko Launis, Juhani Peitarinen, and Juha Raikka, pp. 10320. Amsterdam:
Rodopi.
c o l l i n s , f r a n c i s . 1999. Genetics and faith. Lecture, Christian Physicians Association of North Carolina, University of
North Carolina at Chapel Hill, April 16.
c o n n e r t o n , p . 1989. How societies remember. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
c o o l , l i s a c o l l i e r . 1994. Finding my parents saved my
life! Good Housekeeping 219:62.
d a n i e l s , c y n t h i a . 1997. Between fathers and fetuses: The
social construction of male reproduction and the politics of fetal harm. Sings 22:579616.
d a u s , c a r o l . 1999. Past imperfect: How tracing your family
medical history can save your life. Santa Monica: Santa Monica Press.
d a v i s - f l o y d , r . 1996. The technocratic body and the organic body: Hegemony and heresy in womens birth choices,
in Gender and health. Edited by C. Sargent and C. Brettell, pp.
12326. Upper Saddle River: Prentice-Hall.
d o l g i n , j a n e t . 1997. Defining the family: Law, technology,
and reproduction in an uneasy age. New York: New York University Press.
. 2000. Choice, tradition, and the New Genetics: The fragmentation of the ideology of family. Connecticut Law Review
32:52366.
. n.d. Personhood, discrimination, and the new genetics.
Brooklyn Law Review. In press [jd]
d o m h o f f , w i l l i a m . 1983. Who rules America? Englewood
Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.
d o u g l a s , m a r y. 1992. Natural symbols. New York: Vintage
Books.
d o y a l , l e s l i e . 1979. The political economy of health. Boston: South End Press.
. 1995. What makes women sick? New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press.
d u m a r s , k . , a n d c . c h e a . 1989. The Cham: A population
isolate, in Genetic disease: The unwanted inheritance. Edited
by Rainer et al., pp. 15368. New York: Haworth Press.
d u m o n t , l o u i s . 1977. From Mandeville to Marx. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press. [jd]
Economist. 1995. Biotechnology and genetics: Breaking natures
limits. 334(7903):318.
e d w a r d s , j e a n e t t e . 2000. Born and bred. Oxford: Oxford
University Press. [mr]
e d w a r d s , j e a n e t t e , a n d m a r i l y n s t r a t h e r n . 2000.
Including our own, in Cultures of relatedness, pp. 14966.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
eisenberg, david, r. davis, s. ettner, s. appel, s.
w i l k e y, m . v a n r o m p a y, a n d r . c . k e s s l e r . 1998.
Trends in alternative medicine use in the United States,

This content downloaded from 200.130.19.150 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 13:41:14 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

f i n k l e r The Kin in the Gene F 261

19901997. Journal of the American Medical Association, November 11.


eisenberg, david, r. c. kessler, f. foster, d. norl o c k , j . c a l k i n s , a n d t . d e l b a n c o . 1993. Unconventional medicine in the United States. New England Journal of
Medicine, January 28, pp. 24683.
e l m e r - d e w i t t , p h i l i p . 1994. The genetic revolution. Time
143(3):46.
e n g l e h a r d t , t . 1986. The foundations of bioethics. New
York: Oxford University Press.
e s t e s , c . 1988. The biomedicalization of aging: Dangers and
dilemmas. American Sociological Association, Association Paper 88S20430.
e v a n s - p r i t c h a r d , e d w a r d . 1937. Witchcraft, oracles, and
magic among the Azande. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
[hg]
. 1962. Heredity and gestation as the Azande see them,
in Social anthropology and other essays, pp. 24356. New
York: Free Press.
f i n c h , s t e v e n . 1996. To see your future look into your past.
Health 10(6):92.
f i n c h , j . , a n d j . m a s o n . 1993. Negotiating family responsibilities. London: Routledge.
f i n k l e r , k . 1991. Physicians at work, patients in pain. Boulder: Westview Press.
. 1994. Women in pain. Pittsburgh: University of Pennsylvania Press.
. 2000a. Experiencing the new genetics: Family and kinship on the medical frontier. Pittsburgh: University of Pennsylvania Press.
. 2000b. Diffusion reconsidered: The case of the cross-cultural transformation of biomedical practice. Medical Anthropology 19(1):139.
f l e c k , l u d w i k . 1979 (1935). Genesis and development of scientific fact. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
f o r t e s , m . 1970. Kinship and the social order. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
f o u c a u l t , m . 1975. The birth of the clinic. New York: Vintage Books.
f o x k e l l e r , e v e l y n . 1986. Making gender visible in the
pursuit of natures secrets, in Feminist studies/Critical studies. Edited by Teresa de Laurentis, pp. 6777. Milwaukee: University of Wisconsin Press.
. 1995. Refiguring life: Metaphors of twentieth-century biology. New York: Columbia University Press. [mr]
. 2000. The century of the gene. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [hg]
f r a n k l i n , s . 1993. Making representations: The parliamentary debate on the Human Fertilization and Embryology Act,
in Technologies of procreation: Kinship in the age of assisted
conception. Edited by Jeanette Edwards, Sarah Franklin, Eric
Hirsch, Frances Price, and Marilyn Strathern, pp. 96131. Manchester: Manchester University Press.
. 1997. Embodied progress. New York: Routledge.
f r e e m a n , j . d . 1968. On the concept of the kindred, in
Kinship and social organization. Edited by Paul Bohannan and
John Middleton, pp. 25572. Garden City: Natural History
Press.
f r e i d s o n , e . 1970. Profession of medicine. New York: Harper
and Row.
f r e u n d l i c h , n a o m i . 1997. Finding a cure in DNA? Business Week, March 10, pp. 9092.
f u j i m u r a , j o a n . 1996. Crafting science. Cambridge: Harvard
University Press.
g a b e , j . , a n d s . l i p s h i t z - p h i l l i p s . 1984. Tranquilizers
as social control. Sociological Review 32:52447.
g i d d e n s , a . 1990. The consequences of modernity. Stanford:
Stanford University Press.
. 1991. Modernity and self identity. Stanford: Stanford
University Press.
. 1992. The transformation of intimacy. Stanford: Stanford
University Press.

g i l m a n , s a n d e r l . 1999. Making the body beautiful. Princeton: Princeton University Press.


g l a u s i u s z , j o s i e . 1995a. A gene for breast cancer. Discover,
January, pp. 99100.
. 1995b. Anastasia, nyet. Discover, January p. 99.
. 1996. The genes of 1995. Discover, January, pp. 3233.
g o o d , b y r o n . 1994. Medicine, rationality, and experience:
An anthropological perspective. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press [ls]
g o t t l i e b , b . 1993. The family in the Western world from the
Black Death to the industrial age. New York: Oxford University Press.
g r a d y, d e n i s e . 1994. The new way to predict your future
health. Redbook 183:32.
g r a n n e r , d a r y l . 1988. Nucleic acid structure and function, in Harpers biochemistry 22nd edition, pp. 36682. Norwalk, Conn.: Appleton and Lange.
g r e e n , j . , f . m u r t o n , a n d h . s t a t h a m . 1993. Psychosocial issues raised by a familial ovarian cancer register. Journal of Medical Genetics 30:57579.
g u r e v i c h , m . 1995. Rethinking the label: Who benefits from
the PMS construct? Women and Health 23:6798.
h a h n , r o b e r t , a n d a r t h u r k l e i n m a n . 1983. Biomedical practice and anthropological theory: Frameworks and directions. Annual Review of Anthropology 12:30533.
h a i m e s , e r i c a . 1988. Secrecy: What can artificial reproduction learn from adoption? International Journal of Law and the
Family 2:4661. [mr]
h a l p e r n , s . 1985. Medicalization through specialization. Society for the Study of Social Problems Association Paper
85S16990.
h a m e r , d e a n , a n d p e t e r c o p e l a n d . 1996. The science
of desire: The search for the gay gene and the biology of behavior. New York: Touchstone Books. [hg]
h a n s e n , b . 1992. American physicians discovery of homosexuals, 18801900: A new diagnosis in a changing society, in
Framing disease. Edited by C. Rosenberg and J. Golden, pp.
10413. New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press.
h a r a w a y, d o n n a , j . 1991. Simians, cyborgs, and women.
New York: Routledge.
. 1997. Modest_witness@second_millennium. New York:
Routledge.
h e s s , d a v i d . 1997. Science studies. New York: New York
University Press.
h i g g i n s , e a n . 1997. Study links mens bad behaviour to
whats in their genes. The Australian, June 14, p. 12.
h o e d e m a e k e r s , r o g e e r , a n d h e n k t e n h a v e . 1999.
Genetic health and genetic disease, in Genes and morality.
Edited by Veikko Launis, Juhani Pietarine, and Juha Raikka,
pp. 12144. Amsterdam: Rodopi.
h o l y, l . 1996. Anthropological perspectives on kinship. Chicago: Pluto Press.
h o r n b l o w e r , m a r g o t . 1999. Roots mania. Time 153:
5458.
h u b b a r d , r . , a n d e . w a l d . 1997. Exploding the gene
myth. Boston: Beacon Press.
i l l i c h , i . 1975. Medical nemesis. London: Marion Boyars.
i n g l e b y, d a v i d . 1982. The social construction of mental
illness, in The problem of medical knowledge. Edited by P.
Wright and A. Treacher, pp. 12343. Edinburgh: Edinburgh
University Press.
j a r o f f , l e o n . 1989. The gene hunt: Scientists launch a $3
billion project to map the chromosomes and decipher the complete instructions for making a human being. Science, March
20, p. 62.
. 1994. Battler for gene therapy. Time 143(3):56.
. 1996. Keys to the kingdom. Time 148(14):2429.
j o h n s o n , c o l l e e n . 2000. Perspectives on American kinship
in the later 1990s. Journal of Marriage and the Family 62:
62339. [mr]
j o h n s o n , t h o m a s . 1987. Premenstrual syndrome as a Western culture-specific disorder. Culture, Medicine, and Psychiatry 11:33756.

This content downloaded from 200.130.19.150 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 13:41:14 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

262 F c u r r e n t a n t h ro p o l o g y Volume 42, Number 2, April 2001

j o n e s , m a g g i e . 2000. The genetic report card. New York


Times Magazine, June 11.
j o n s e n , a . 1996. The impact of mapping the human genome
on the patientphysician relationship, in The Human Genome Project and the future of health care. Edited by Thomas
H. Murray, Mark A. Rothstein, and Robert F. Murray Jr., pp.
120. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
k a u f e r t , p . , a n d p . g i l b e r t . 1986. Women, menopause,
and medicalization. Culture, Medicine, and Psychiatry 10:
721.
k e e s i n g , r . 1975. Kin groups and social structure. New York:
Holt, Rinehart and Winston.
k o h l e r - r i e s s m a n , c . 1983. Women and medicalization A
new perspective. Social Policy, Summer, pp. 318.
k r i e g e r , n a n c y , a n d e l i z a b e t h f e e . 1994. Man-made
medicine and womens health: The biopolitics of sex/gender
and race/ethnicity. International Journal of Health Services 24:
26583.
l a t o u r , b r u n o . 1987. Science in action. Cambridge: Harvard
University Press.
l a t o u r , b r u n o , a n d s . w o o l g a r . 1979. Laboratory life:
The social construction of scientific facts. Beverly Hills: Sage.
l e a c h , e . r . 1961. Rethinking anthropology. London: Athlone
Press.
l o c k , m a r g a r e t . 1980. East Asian medicine in urban Japan.
Berkeley: University of California Press.
l o c k , m a r g a r e t , a n d d e b r a h g o r d o n . 1988. Biomedicine examined. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
l o p e z b e l t r a n , c a r l o s . 1994. Forging heredity: From metaphor to cause, a reification story. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 25:21135.
l o w i e , r . 1948. Social organization. New York: Rinehart.
l u n d , s a r a h . 2001. Bequeathing and quest: Processing personal identification documents in bureaucratic space (Cuzco,
Peru). Social Anthropology 9(1):324. [mm]
l y n c h , h . t . , p . l y n c h , a n d j . l y n c h . 1979. Genetic
counseling and cancer, in Genetic counseling. Edited by S.
Kessler, pp. 22142. New York: Academic Press.
m c a u l i f f e , w . 1978. Studies of process-outcome: Correlations in medical care evaluations, a critique. Medical Care 26:
90730.
. 1979. Measuring the quality of medical care: Process versus outcome. Milbank Memorial Fund Quarterly/Health and
Society 57:11852.
m a c d o n a l d , m . 1992. The medicalization of suicide in
England: Laymen, physicians, and cultural change, 15001870,
in Framing disease. Edited by C. Rosenberg and J. Golden, pp.
85103. New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press.
m a l i n o w s k i , b . 1922. Argonauts of the Western Pacific. New
York: E. P. Dutton.
. 1962 (1929). The sexual life of savages. New York: Harcourt, Brace and World.
m a r c u s , g . , w i t h p . h a l l . 1992. Lives in trust: The fortunes of dynastic families in late twentieth-century America.
Boulder: Westview Press.
m a r i e s k i n d , h . 1980. Impact of technology on womens
health care, in Women in the health system: Patients, providers and programs. Edited by H. Marieskind, pp. 23582. St.
Louis: C. V. Mosby.
m a r k e n s , s . 1996. The problematic of experience A political and cultural critique of PMS. Gender and Society 10:4258.
m a r t i n , e m i l y. 1987. The woman in the body. Boston: Beacon Press.
. 1997. The egg and the sperm, in Situated lives. Edited
by L. Lamphere, H. Ragone, and P. Zavella, pp. 8598. New
York: Routledge.
m a r t y, m a r t i n e . 1996. Slightly extraordinary genes. Christian Century, February 7, p. 183.
m a y a l l , b . 1990. Childcare and childhood. Children and Society 4:37485.
Merck manual of medical information, home edition. 1997.
Whitehouse Station, N.J.: Merck Research Laboratories.
m e l m a n , s e y m o u r . 1974. The permanent war economy:

American capitalism in decline. New York: Touchstone Books.


[hg]
m i t c h e l l , e m i l y. 1999. Growing your family tree. Time 153:
67.
m o d e l l , j u d i t h . 1994. Kinship with strangers. Berkeley:
University of California Press.
n a s h , m a d e l e i n e . 1997. Addicted: Why do people get
hooked? Mounting evidence points to powerful brain chemical
called dopamine. Time 149:6875.
n e l k i n , d o r o t h y. 1992. The social power of genetic information, in The code of codes. Edited by Daniel J. Kevles and
Leroy Hood, pp. 17790. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
. 1996. The politics of predisposition: The social meaning
of predictive biology, in Biopolitics: The politics of body,
race, and nature. Edited by A. Heller and S. P. Reikmann.
Brookfield, Vt.: Avebury.
. 1997. Selling science: How the press covers science and
technology. New York: Freeman. [mr]
n e l k i n , d . , a n d s . l i n d e e . 1995. The DNA mystique.
New York: W. H. Freeman.
n e u s t a d t e r , r o g e r . 1992. Squatters rights in the ovum:
The unborn as patient. Free Inquiry in Creative Sociology 20:
199204.
osherson, samuel, and lorna amara singham.
1981. The machine metaphor in medicine, in Social contexts of health, illness, and patient care. Edited by Elliot G.
Mishler et al., pp. 21849. London: Cambridge University
Press.
p a r k , a n d r e w. 1997. Adoptees seek access to genetic history.
The News & Observer June 20.
p a r k i n , r o b e r t . 1997. Kinship: An introduction to basic
concepts. Oxford: Blackwell.
p e l e t z , m . 1995. Kinship studies in late twentieth-century anthropology. Annual Review of Anthropology 24:34372.
p e t c h e s k y, r o s a l i n d . 1987. Fetal images: The power of
visual culture in the politics of reproduction, in Reproductive
technologies: Gender, motherhood, and medicine. Edited by
Michelle Stanworth, pp. 5779. Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press.
p h i l l i p s , s u s a n . 1997. Problem-based learning in medicine:
New curriculum, old stereotypes. Social Science and Medicine
45:49799.
p o m a t a , g i a n n a . 1996. Blood ties and semen ties: Consanguinity and agnation in Roman law, in Gender, kinship,
power. Edited by M. J. Maynes, A. Waltner, B. Soland, and U.
Strasser, pp. 4366. New York: Routledge.
p o p e n o e , d a v i d . 1993. American family decline, 19601990:
A review and appraisal. Journal of Marriage and the Family 55:
52755.
r a p p , r a y n a . 1999. Testing women, testing the fetus. New
York: Routledge.
r e d f i e l d , r o b e r t . 1941. The folk culture of Yucatan. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
r i c h a r d s , m a r t i n . 1996. Families, kinship, and genetics,
in The troubled helix. Edited by Theresa Marteau and Martin
Richards, pp. 24973. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
. 1999. Genetic counseling for those with a family history
of breast or ovarian cancer. Acta Oncologica 38:55965. [mr]
. 2001. Future bodies: Making babies in the biotech century, in Body lore and laws. Edited by A. Bainham, S. Day
Sclater, and M. P. M. Richards. Oxford: Hart. In press. [mr]
r i c h t e r , m a u r i c e , j r . 1972. Science as a cultural process.
Cambridge: Schenkman.
r i t e n b a u g h , c h e r y l . 1982. Obesity as a culture-bound syndrome. Culture, Medicine, and Psychiatry 6:34761.
r o d i n , m . 1992. The social construction of premenstrual syndrome. Social Science and Medicine 35:4956.
r o s e n b e r g , c h a r l e s . 1976. No other gods. Baltimore: Johns
Hopkins University Press.
r o s e n f i e l d , r . , a n d g . e r c h a k . 1988. Learning disabilities, dyslexia, and the medicalization of the classroom. Society for the Study of Social Problems Association Paper
88S20306.

This content downloaded from 200.130.19.150 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 13:41:14 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

f i n k l e r The Kin in the Gene F 263

s a c h s , l i s b e t h . 1995. Is there a pathology of prevention? Implications of making the invisible visible in screening programs. Culture, Medicine, and Psychiatry 19:50325.
. 1996. Causality, responsibility, and blame: Core issues in
the cultural construction and subtext of prevention. Sociology
of Health and Illness 18:63252.
s a c k , c a t h e r i n e . 1997. Washington diarist: Tropic of cancer.
New Republic 216:46.
s a h l i n s , m a r s h a l l . 1968. Tribesmen. Englewood Cliffs:
Prentice-Hall.
. 1976. Culture and practical reason. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
s c h e f fl e r , h . 1991. Sexism and naturalism in the study of
kinship, in Gender at the crossroads of knowledge. Edited by
Micaela di Leonardo, pp. 36182. Berkeley: University of California Press.
s c h n e i d e r , d a v i d . 1965. Kinship and biology, in Aspects
of the analysis of family structure. Edited by A. Coale, L. Fallers, M. Levy, D. Schneider, and S. Tomkins, pp. 83101.
Princeton: Princeton University Press.
. 1972. What is kinship all about? in Kinship studies in
the Morgan centennial year. Edited by P. Reining, pp. 3263.
Washington, D.C.: Anthropological Society of Washington.
. 1980. 2d edition. American kinship: A cultural account.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
. 1984. A critique of the study of kinship. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.
Science. 1993. Zeroing in on a breast cancer susceptibility gene.
259(January 29):62223.
s e g a l e n , m . 1986. Historical anthropology of the family.
Translated by J. C. Whitehouse and S. Matthews. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
s e l i g m a n , d i a n e . 1994. A substantial inheritance. National
Review 46(19):5660.
s e r b a n , g . 1989. Unwanted inheritance: The psychosocial
care of progressive genetic illnesses, in Genetic disease: The
unwanted inheritance. Edited by Rainer et al. pp. 199202.
New York: Haworth Press.
s h o r t e r , e d w a r d . 1975. The making of the modern family.
New York: Basic Books.
s i e b e r t , c . 1995. The DNA weve been dealt. New York
Times Magazine, September 17, pp. 50104.
s i l v e r , l e e . 1998. Remaking Eden: How genetic engineering
and cloning will transform the American family. New York:
Avon Books. [hg]
s i n g e r , p . n . 1997. Galen: Selected works. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
s o n t a g , s u s a n . 1978. Illness as metaphor. New York: Farrar,
Straus and Giroux.
s t a c e y, j . 1990. Brave new families: Stories of domestic upheaval in late twentieth-century America. New York: Basic
Books.
s t r a h a n , s . a . k . 1984(1902). Marriage and disease. London:
Garland.
s t r a t h e r n , a . 1972. One father, one blood. Canberra: Australian National University Press.
s t r a t h e r n , m a r i l y n . 1992a. After nature: English kinship
in the late twentieth century. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
. 1992b. Reproducing the future. New York: Routledge.
. 1995. Displacing knowledge: Technology and the consequences for kinship, in Conceiving the New World Order. Edited by F. Ginsburgh and R. Rapp, pp. 34664. Berkeley: University of California Press.

s u l l i v a n , d . 1993. Cosmetic surgery: Market dynamics and


medicalization research. Sociology of Health Care 10:97115.
t a y l o r , c h a r l e s . 1989. Sources of the self. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
t h o r n e , b . 1992. Feminism and the family: Two decades of
thought, in Rethinking the family. Edited by B. Thorne with
M. Yalom, pp. 330. Boston: Northeastern University Press.
t i e f e r , l . 1994. The medicalization of impotence: Normalizing phallocentrism. Gender and Society 8:36377.
t o c q u e v i l l e . a . d e . 1980(1840). Democracy in America. Pt.
2. Edited by Phillips Bradley. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.
t o m e s , n a n c y. 1990. Historical perspectives on women and
mental illness, in Women, health, and medicine in America.
Edited by R. Apple. New York: Garland.
t u r n e r , b r y a n , s . 1987. Medical power and social knowledge. London: Sage.
. 1992. Regulating bodies. London: Routledge.
Turning Point. 1996. Race for a miracle: The Brad and Vicki Margus story. Transcript #152, February 12.
v e r b r u g g e , l o i s . 1990. Pathways of health and death, in
Women, health, and medicine in America. Edited by R. Apple.
New York: Garland.
w a d e , n . 1997. Testing genes to save a life without costing
you a job. New York Times, September 14.
w a i l o o , k e i t h . 1996. Genetic marker of segregation: Sickle
cell anemia, thalassemia, and racial ideology in American
medical writing 19201950. History and Philosophy of the Life
Sciences 18:30520.
w a i t z k i n , h . 1991. The politics of medical encounters: How
patients and doctors deal with social problems. New Haven:
Yale University Press.
w e i s m a n t e l , m a r y. 1995. Making kin: Kinship theory and
Zumbagua adoptions. American Ethnologist 22:685709.
w e x l e r , n a n c y. 1979. Genetic Russian roulette: The experience of being at risk for Huntingtons disease, in Genetic
counseling. Edited by S. Kessler, pp. 199220. New York: Academic Press.
. 1992. Clairvoyance and caution: Repercussions from the
Human Genome Project, in The code of codes. Edited by D.
Kevles and L. Hood, pp. 21143. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
w i l l i a m s , s i m o n j . , a n d m . c a l n a n . 1996. The limits
of medicalization? Modern medicine and the lay populace in
late modernity. Social Science and Medicine 42:160920.
w i t h e r s p o o n , g . 1975. Navajo kinship and marriage. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
w i t z i g , r . 1996. The medicalization of race: Scientific legitimization of a flawed social construct. Annals of Internal Medicine 125:67579.
w r i g h t , p e t e r , a n d a n d r e w t r e a c h e r . 1982. The
problem of medical knowledge. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
y a n a g i s a k o , s y l v i a , j . , a n d j a n e f . c o l l i e r . 1990.
The mode of reproduction in anthropology, in Therapeutic
perspectives on sexual difference. Edited by Deborah L. Rhode,
pp. 13144. New Haven: Yale University Press.
y a n o s h i k , k . , a n d j . n o r s i g i a n . 1989. Contraception,
control, and choice: International perspectives, in Healing
technology. Edited by K. S. Ratcliff, pp. 6192. Ann Arbor:
University of Michigan Press.
y o u n g , a l a n . 1981. The creation of medical knowledge:
Some problems in interpretation. Social Science and Medicine
15B:37986.
y o x e n , e d w a r d . 1986. Unnatural selection? Coming to
terms with the new genetics. London: Heinemann.

This content downloaded from 200.130.19.150 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 13:41:14 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Вам также может понравиться