Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 9

XIII

494
XIV

political virtues (cf. 6, 154.19-20 ; 9, 155.27-29). This summarising


chapter. with its emphasis on Proclus' unsurpassed virtues. its claim
to have made his UOO.lfi.ovia the beginning, middle and end of the
work. and its concluding sentence recalling the Aristotelian concept
of cuoa.tfi.ovia which had been introduced at the start (66 ), now adding
t he words- Aristotle's (67 ) - xa.i iv {3i~ -.ElEi(f, serves to confirm, if ALEXANDER OF APHRODISIA$
any further confirmation were necessary, that the organization IN THE LATER GREEK COM?v1ENTARIES
according to the virtues controls the w hole arrangement of the ON ARISTOTLE'S DE ANIMA*
biography. Moreover. as we have argued, it also seems to have been
responsible, at the least. for a not insignificant reshuffling of the
Of the commentators on Aristotle whose works survive in other
actual events of Proclus career (68 ).
than partial or fragmentary form Alexander is unique in that he
worked before the new Platonism of Plotinus and his successors
came to dominate Greek philosophy: I use "successors" in the tem-
poral and therefore not necessarily philosophical sense. With the
exception of Themistius he is also alone in that he wrote more or
(66) See above pp. 472-473.
less unbiased commentaries on Aristotle, 1 commentaries that were
(67) Cf. EN. II 0 I a 16 : J.ll) TOY ruxovTa XPOVOV ilia n'AELOV Piov.
(68) An earlier version of this paper was read to a meeting of the seminar on o n the whole an honest, and generally successful- though this is
Christian and pagan biography, 4th to 7th centuries. held at the Institute of admittedly now controversial 2 - attempt to set out what A ristotle
Classical Studies, London in May 1983. I should like to thank its members for thought.J
their helpful comments.
Where no work is given references to the commentators arc to their commentaries
on the De anima.
1 For Themistius cf. my Themistius, the last Peripatl'tic commentator on Aristotle?,
in: Arktouros, Festschrift Knox (1979) 391-40J; fot another l'iew cf. 1:.. P.Maho
ney, 'eoplatonism, the Greek commentators, and Renais~ancc Aristote lian ism, in:
eoplatonism and Christian Thought, ed. D. J. O'Meara (Albany 1982) n.l, on
2.64-266.
1 Alexander himself, in hi~ De anima, claimed that, since Aristotle's views were supe-

rior to others', his task would be fulfilled if he set out Aristotle's opinions as clearly
as possible and added a few comments of his own: l:n15' W01t&(l i:v 1:0I~ iiM.ot~ Ta
'AQtOlOteA.ouc,; 1lQEOPEuo,.u:v CtAJlfi&OTEQa; ~yOUJl&Vot tat; im' <llJTOi> MQCt050
!.leva~ 06~at; t<iJV iiM.mt; El(lTH.Lf:V(!)V, QUl(!) oe a
i'.al tv t 'JlEQl \JIUXiit; OOYI.lCtll
q>QOVOV)JV, &otat ux tu
x.at<l 'tfiV 1lQ6i7Eotv -/)J,J.iV 1!CMJ1QWI.lf:va, iiv \m' txtvou
1lQi \JIUXi'Jt; CiQT]IJiva w; f:vMx.ttCtt oaq>GJc; EXi7WI.l~<l xat lOU xa>.~ exaotOV
a\m'l>v EiQiio6at tac; Oli'.Eiw;; naQaoxw,.u:t>o. naQal-lu6[ac; (2,4-9) . But acquain-
tance with the :"Jeoplatonists' frequent professions to be doing no more than
expounding Plato would suggest the need for caution in accepting such claims.
> Some modern scholarship has found Platonic elements in Alexander, cf. P. Merlan,
Monopsyschism, Mysticism, Metaconsciousness. Problem~ of the soul in the
Neoaristotelian and N eoplatonic trad ition, The Hague 1963, esp. 39 sqq.; P. L.
Donini, Tre studi sull'Aristotelismo nel Il secolo d. C., Turin 1974,5-59 passim; cf.
XIV XlV

91 Alexander of :\phrodisias in the later Greek commentaries

The first question that arises from these assertions is why this were these. First, there was the long process whereby Aristotelians,
should have been so -if indeed it is true. Why should not commenta- Platonists and Stoics came to adopt some of each others views, in a
tors who wrote during the long period of Neoplatonism's intellec- variety of mixtures according to a particular individual's philosoph-
tual ascendancy have been equally honest interpreters of Aristotle? ical orientation.6 The process begins in the 1st century B. C. 7 By the
In one sense one might admit that they were, but add immediately time of the great 5th and 6th century commentators it was more
that their powers of self-deception were considerably greater. And than merely acceptable tO find one philosopher's views in the writ-
here it is relevant th at, unlike Alexander himself, the later commen- ings of another. The most important result of this process was that
tators-such as Porphyry, Syrianus, Ammonius, Simplicius, Philopo- Aristotle became more and more close ly assimilated to Plato, a view
nus, O lympiodorus and Stephanus, were all, except a~ain Themis- of his pos ition that might be acceptable to certain. European scho-
tius, themselves practising Neoplatonists, a fact which has important lars,8 but is totally at variance with the normal reading of Aristotle
implications for their approach to the work of commenting on Aris- to-day. Moreover, by the time we are considering here, a course on
totle. Perhaps it would be as well to state at this stage that "Neopla- Aristotle was usually given as a preliminary, not to say prerequisite,
tonism" is not a description of a cut and dried set of doctrines, and to the study of Plato which meant, roughly, Plato's metaphysics. 9
that to apply the term "Neoplatonist" to a particular writer does not Give n this situation it was easier for Neoplatonic commentators
mean that he must believe all, and only, those t hings believed by than it wou ld otherwise have been to find their own views in the text
others so described. Thus these commentators will have held, and of an Aristotle whom they were inclined to see as an exponent of the
can be shown to have held, different views on the subjects treated in same Platonist truth to which they themselves subscribed. Here we
such Aristotelian works as they were discussing. And here we come come to the second factor, an open and conscious attempt to har-
to the implications of their Neoplatonism, for the mere fact that they monize the thought of Aristotle and Plato on most issues, or perhaps
held different views is more important th an it ought to have been. one should say the words in which that thought was expressed,
A~ this point I shou ld like to summarize some conclusions, for because it was by special interpretation of the words (Ak~u;) that the
which I have argued elsewhere, but which are basic to the matters "real meaning" of Aristotle's text could be shown to be compatible
under consideration here. 5 It is, of course, theoretically possible for a with Plato's philosophy (cf., e.g. Simplic. In Cat. 7,29-32}. The
philosopher to write scholarly commentary without introducing his
Mixtures should not be taken to imply fortuitous juxtapositions. For a recent pro-
own views: in practice things never turn out quite like that. But quite
test against the notion of eclecticism cf. J. M. Dillon, The Middle Platonists. A
apart from the general tendency for philosophers to see their own study of Pbtonism 80 B. C. to A. D. 220, London 1977, xiv-xv.
views at least adumbrated in the texts of earlier philosophers-Aris- 7
For this development up to the time of Plotinus, from a Platonist point of view, cf.
totle himself is, of course, a notorious example -two particular fac- Dill on, op. cit.; the Peripatetic perspective is of course to be found in Moraux's
tors operated in the case of the N eoplatonic commentators. They own Der Aristotelismus bei den Griechen von Andronikos bis Alexander von
Aphrodisias, Berlin-New York 1973-; for Plotinus him self cf. Porph., Vita Plot.
now too F. M. Schroeder, The analogy of the active intellect to light in the 'De 14.
anima' of Alexa nder of Aphrodisias, in: Hermes 109 ( 1981 ) 215-225; contra
1
One thinks in particular of the "To bingen school", cf. esp. H. J. Kramer, Der
P. Moraux, Le De anima dans Ia tradition grecque. Quelques aspects de l'interpn!- Ursprung der Geistmetaphysik, Amsterdam 1964, passim.
tation du traite, de Theop hraste aT hemistius, in: Aristotle on mind and the senses,
9
For Aristotle as an introduction to Plato cf. Marinus, Vita Procli 13, and for the
Proceedings of the seventh Symposium Aris totelicum, edd. G. E. R. Lloyd and G. o rde r of studying his works Simplic., In Cat. 5, 3- 6, 5; on the standard Plato course
E. LOwen, C ambridge 1978, 299-300; id. in: Gnomon SO (1978) 532-533, review- cf. L.G.Westerink, Anonymous Prolegomena to Platonic Philosophy, Amsterdam
ing Donini, and my review in: JHS 97 {1977) 195. 1962, xxxvii-xl; A. -J. Festugiere, L'ordre de lecture des dialogues de Pia ton aux
Cf. my Neoplatonic elements in the De anima commentaries, in: Phronesis 21 VeNTe siecles, in: MH 26 (1969) 281-296, and on the whole curriculum P. Hadot,
( 1976) 79-86, and Some Platonist readings of Aristotle, in: PC PhS n. s. 27 ( 1981) Les divisions de Ia philosophic dans l'antiquite, in: MH 36 { 1979) 219-221. Themis-
6-8, 12-13. tius again shows his independence by being interested in Plato as a political
5 For a fu ller discussion cf. Neoplatonic ele ments, 64-87. thinker, cf. my Themistius (see n.1 ) 393.
XIV XIV

93 .'\lexander of Aphrodisias in the later Greek commentaries 94

usual approach was to say that if one paid attention to the meaning to find the content of the commentaries influenced by the philo-
behind the text, and not to the superficial impression created by the sophical opinions of authors who thought that Aristotle and Piato
mere expression of it, one would find that what appeared to be were both trying to say the same thing, though they might some-
attacks by Aristotle on Plato were nothing of the kind. An interest- times disagree on what that was. In fact one must go further and
ing example may be found in a passage of Simplicius' De caelo com- accept that much of what is in the commentaries is primarily an
mentary where Alexander is criticized for attacking Plato because he expression of the commentators' own thought. For they seem to
had failed to understand the purpose of Aristotle's arguments (In have been so convinced of the unity of what we should distinguish
Cael. 388, 20-34). Thus it was possible for Simplicius, in the preface as Platonism, Aristotelianism and Neoplatonism that they were pre-
to his De anima commentary,l0 to state it as his intention to discover pared to take as exposition of Aristotle views that were originally
and set out Aristotle's internal consistency and his essential harmony put forward as an individual's own philosophical position. T he most
with the truth-as seen by P latonists - and for both him and Philopo- striking case of this comes in the interpretation of De ani ma III 5: I
nus to argue over and over again that apparent differences between shall not discuss this at length here, but shall briefly set out the main
P lato and Aristotle were not in fact such. 1 1 Given the comb ination of points which emerge, as they provide a clear illustration of the atti-
such open statements of t heir intentions with the basic view that tudes and approaches involved. 12
Aristotle and P lato were both expounding one truth, it would be In the pseudo-Philoponus commentary on Book III -the real
unreasonab le not to be suspicious about the commentators' pure author is Stephan us- we have a list of opinions on the meaning of
scholarship. O u r suspicions might well be increased by statements active intellect (535, 4-16). The opinions are those of Alexander,
like that of Simplicius that he intended to explain the De anima in Plotinus, Plutarch (of Athens) and Marinus. Alexander's is rejected
accordance with the truth and the views of Iamblichus (In An. in the first place because his explanation, that intellect in act is the
l, 18-20). supreme cause of all things, that is Aristotle's unmoved mover,
Given all this one might after all expect something other than would fall outside the scope of the De anima as seen by the Neopla-
straightforward commentary. In particular it would not be surprising tonists, namely soul and vo()~ in us,u a difference between them and
Alexander to which we must return.u Plotinus, we are told, states
10
for convenience I continue to call the author of thi s commentary Simplicius, as I that Aristotle means by intellect in act our vo()~ which is perma-
think he was. The anribution has been contested by F. Bossier and C. Steel, Priscia- nently engaged in intellection. This is the key case, for we know
nu s Lydus en de In De anima van Pseudo(?) Simplicius, in: Tijdsch. voor Filos. 34
both that Plotinus did not write commentaries on Aristotle-we have
(1972) 76 1-822, with french summary on 821-822, who attribute the work to Pris-
cian. I. Hadot, while accepting that they may be right about the authorship argues
a complete list of his works prepared by his pupil, editor and biogra-
that the doctrines in it are the same as those in Simplicius' other works, cf. Le pro- pher, Porphyry IS- and also that the view here given as his view on
bleme du neop latonisme alexandrin . H ierocles et Simplicius, Paris 1968, 193-202. Aristotle is identical with his own position in a Platonist controversy
H that is correct, the question of authors hi p may be largel y prosopographical. Cf. about whether or not the highest part of the human soul descended
further L Hadot, La doctrine de Simplicius sur l'ame raisonnable humaine dans le with the rest of the individual soul to form the compound that
commentaire sur le manuel d'Epictt!te, in: Soul and the Structure of Being in late
Neoplatoni srn . Syria nus, Prod us and Simplicius, ed d. H.]. Blumenthal and A. C.
makes a person, or remained above, and therefore in a state of unim-
Lloyd, Liverpool 1963, 46- 71, and my Th e psycho lo gy of(?) Simplicius' commen- peded intellection, in the intelligible world. 16 Plutarch's v1ew may
taty on the o~ anima, ibid. 73-93 with the discussio n, 93-94. The commentary is
11
treated as Priscian's by Steel in his The chan gi ng self. A study of the soul in later Cf. Neoplatonic elements (n.4) 72-82.
13 Cf. [Philop.], In An. 536,2-4; 537, 18-24.
Neoplatonism: lamblichus and Priscianus, Brussels 1978, cf. csp. 123-160
14
(- Vcrh.Kon.Ac.\Xict. Lett. etc. Belg. 40 [1978] n.85). See below pp. I 04-105.
'1 Quite apa rt from lesser disagreements exception must always be made of the notor- IS Porph., Vita Plot. 24-26: all these works, of course, survive.

ious dispute about the eternity of the world and the nature of the heavens, cf. esp. Cf. esp. Plot., Enn. IV 8. 8, 1-3; on the later history of the question cf. Prod us, In
Simplic., In Phys. 1156,28-11 82,39. Tim.III 333,28sqq.; Hermias, In Phaedr. 160,1-4; Simplic., In An. 6,12- 17.
XIV XIV

95 Alexande r of Aphrodisias in the later Greek com mentaries 96

have been contained in a commentary on the De anima, but can also am no longer sure that such an agreement was ever rnade.2o The
be shown to relate to this controversy. He thought we have a single Ale.xandrians did not stop teac~ing Plato, and other reasons might
intellect which sometimes thinks and sometimes does not, and his be mvolved, such as the predomtnance of At hens in Platonic studies.
view can be paralleled fro m Proclus, his pupil, who gave it in his own To read Aristotle un-Piatonically was to all the late commenta-
independent work, Elements of Theology (2 11 ) as well as in his tors a sign of perversity, and we find accusations made against Alex-
commentaries on PlatoY Similarly Marinus, whom we do not other- ander that he interprets Aristotle perversely to make Aristotle's views
wise know to have written a commentary on the De anima, is cred- conform to his own, from our point of view a strange accusation
ited with a view that Aristotle means by intellect in act some dem- coming as it does from those who were themselves guilty of that
onic or angelic intellect: this too can be explained by reference to very charge. They could make this complaint while continuing to
Proclus, his teacher, this time to Proclus' Timaeus commentary, honour Alexander as the interpreter of .'\ristotle par excellence. Sim-
where such minds form part of a triad mediating higher intellect to plicius more than once calls him simply t he commentator on Aris-
our world (III 165,7- 22) . totle (In Phys.707, 33) or jusr 6 t{.T)Yll't~t;. the commentator (ibid.
All this should make it clear that we are likely to find the 1170,2 and 13). 21 Even when he has bee n attacking an interpretatio n
Neoplatonists' personal positions masquerading as explanation of of the Eleatics offered by Alexander, he will describe him as 6
Aristotle. O ne reason may have been that the commentators and YVTJOul>'teQOt; 'tWV 'AQlO'tOt/~.out; e~T)YT)'tWV, and explain the length
their contemporaries were, on at least some, not to say many, ques- of his own discussion by the inadequacy of Alexander's (In Phys.
tions no longer able to tell the difference. When we consider their 80, 15- 17). Similarly in the De anima commentary he can refer to
attitudes to Alexander we must not be surprised if they disagree with Alexander as 6 toO 'AQtO't:OteA.out; t~T)YT)'t~~ while disagreeing ;ith
him when his view is closer than theirs to what we would take to be his understanding of Aristotle (52, 26-30).22 As we shall see, there
Aristotle's meaning, while they interpret him in a Platonic way. In were certain respects in which such honorific refe rences were not
fact they will occasionally state that that is why they do not accept merely lip service. We shou ld note that other Neoplatonists were
Alexander's interpretation. One further factor shou ld be born in treated in the same way. Plotin us and Iamblichus are always spoken
mind, an external one. This is that in Alexandria, for whatever rea- of in terms of the greatest respect- Iamblichu s is frequently referred
son, the delivery of lectures on Aristotle and the publication of com- to as 6 {}gi:ot;- but their opinions are not necessari ly accepted. One
ments on his treatises, often derived from those lectures, became the need only think of the references to 6 ~yat; m.
ro't:i:vot; and 6 {}gTot;
standard means of philosophical expression for the Neoplatonists
there. 18 This will inevitably have encouraged the insertion of Platon- one of the conditions, cf. Le chretien Jean Philopon et Ia suni"ance de ('ecole
ism into the exposition of Aristotle. There would have been a special d'A iexandric au Vle sieclc, in: REG 67 (1954) 400-401; cf. also Alan Ca meron, The
stimulus if the reason for this concentration on Aristotle was, as has last days of the Academ y at Athens, in: PCPhS n.s . l 5 ( 1969) 9; and L.G.Westc-
rink, Anonymous Prolego men a (see n. 9) xi-xii, who thinks there was an agree-
sometimes been suggested, that Ammonius made an agreement with
ment bu t that it did not entail dropping lectures o n P lato.
the ecclesiastical authorities at Alexandria not to teach Plato/ 9 but I 10
The case rests almost entirely on Damasc., Vita ls1d. fr. 316 Zintzen- Photius,
Cod. 242, 292, wh ich does not say that this is what happened. I shall discuss this
17
Cf. Prod us, In Tim. ibid.; In Parm. 948, 18-38 . matter further in a treatment of Philoponus as an Alexandrian Platonist.
21
18
By contrast some, if not all, of Simplicius' commentaries were produced as schol- The reference is quite clear: Alexander is named at 1169, 33, cf. also In Phys.
arly works, for readers, in the first place, cf. K. Praech ter, Art. Simplicius ( 10), in: 1176,32, with 11 75,13.
12
RE III A I (1 927) 205 . A passage in an Athenian source, Syrian us, In Metaph. 100, 1-13, which has some-
1
' That some agreement was made on the basis that Ammon ius took Christian pupils times been taken to refer to Alexa nder as 6 v&rotCQOc; 'AQlOtO"TEAT)<; can not do so,
in exchange for official subventions was arg ued by P.Tannery, Sur Ia periode as the views attributed to that person are incompatible with those reported for
finale de Ia phiiosophie grecque, in: RPhilos. 42 (1896) 275-276, and accepted by Alex ander in the same passage, cf. Meraux, Aristoteles, der Leh rer A lex anders von
H.-D. Saffrey, who suggested that abandoning the teaching of Plato may have been Aphrodisias, in: AGPh 49 (1967) 179-182.
XIV XIV

97 Alexander of Aphrodisils in the later Greek commentaries 98

'I6.jl~ALXO~ in the opemng section of Simplicius' Categories com- formity with himself, pretended to comment on this treatise. So
mentary (2, 3.9). showing his perverse understanding from the start, he produced a
Let us start with the accusations of perversity, since they provide perverse exposition of the beginning" (21, 20-25). A similar com-
a motivation for the kind of differences we do find. Immediately we plaint, this time without reference to Plutarch, but using the same
are faced with the difficulty that we cannot always tell whether or word, ooyxm:aondv, may be found a few pages earlier, at 10, I-3,
not Alexander himself has been misrepresented. The references to where Alexander is mentioned as one of those who think the whole
him in the De anima commentaries of Philoponus, Simplicius and soul is inseparable and therefore mortal. From a compleTely differ-
Stepha nus seem nearly all to be to Alexander's own lost commentary ent context we might compare Simplicius' complaint in the Physics
on the De anima, and the only control we have is whether or not commentary (77, 9-10) that Alexander's own preoccupations caused
these views on Aristotle conform with what are probably Alexander's him to oppose those who said being is one.
own opinions as found in his treatise OeQi \!IUXii<;, a treatise which is Stephanus, discussing 434 b 4-5, on whether or nor. heavenly
still often, but nonetheless incorrectly, treated as if it were a para- bodies are endowed with sense perception, quotes the views of both
phrastic commentary of the type later written by T hemistius. The- Plutarch and Alexander. Here we have a mixture of philological and
mistius fo r one will not have regarded it as such, for he claimed to philosophical differences. Alexander, Stephanus tells u s, read the
have invented the paraphrase-type exposition, modestly claiming in text as Su:x -ct yaQ ~et; "why should <the heavenly bodies> have
the introduction to his paraphrase of the Posterior Analytics that he <sense perception>?", and explain ed it as an open question o:cQOHll!lO.-
was not proposing to compete with the many and excell ent full com- ux.<'i>~). P lutarch went the opposite way, took it with a negative, and
mentaries that had already been produced : that would be a pointless wrote Ota d yaQ t:a ouQ6.vw. oux c~ct a'(o&l,otv; "why ~ hould not
quest to e nhance one's own reputation (In An. Post. 1, 1-7).2.1 Phi- the heavenly bodies have sense-perception?" Stephanus tells us that
loponus himself refers to Alexander's treatise as a separate work at both chose their reading to conform with the answer they wished to
In An.t59, 18. find in Aristotle, a negati ve one in Alexander's case, a po~itive one in
fortunately, we may learn something about the later treatment of Plutarch's (595, 37-596, 36). He next concedes that one can show
Alexander from questions which do not depend on the accuracy with from Aristotle's writings that the heavenly bodies do not share in
which he is reported. In his comments on the opening words of the sense-perception, but immediately goes on to say that such a demon-
De anima Philoponus cites Plutarch for the opinion that Alexander's stration may be refuted from the writings of the Platonists, a refuta-
commentary on Aristotle was really a facade for the display of his tion which he then proceeds to produce (596, 36-598, 7) . Unfortun-
own doctrines, an opinion with which Philoponus clearly concurs, as ately he does not identify the nt..a-rwvtx.o(, but it is clear that it
he goes on to use the point to criticize Alexander's comment on the is their reading, rather than the more Aristotelian one. which he
opening words of the treatise: 6 ~v ouv 'AM~av8Qo<;, &~ <PllOlV 6 prefers. Simplicius, on the other hand, in discussing the preceding
m..out:CLQXO~, x8cotv 'tWV t8lwv OOyjlCt'tWV notT,oao~Ul ~OUAO words - in some texts-&A.A.a jl~V o65e 6.yVll<Ov, prefers Alexan-
~evo~ XCtl ouyxet1Ct01tUOCtl tmn(i> XCtl TTJV 'AQ LO't01EAO\l~ 1tQOOe- der's understanding of these words to Plutarch's on the grounds that
notf,oa'tO U1t0jlV1lj.1Ct'tLsclV 'tUU'tllV TT]v TlQCLY~Ctt:dav. ex
1tQOOljllWV Alexander does not attribute a'(o~oL~ to heavenly bodies, a thing
oov 'tTJV etu"t00 evOLUO'tQO<pOV yvw~TlV OclXVO<; a6t:6 'tO 1tQOOljllOV Aristotle nowhere does, whereas P lutarch's explanation causes him
OlUOtQ6q>w~ t~TlYiloat:o "Alexander, as Plutarch says, wishing to to do so (320,28-38).
expound his own doctrines and forcib ly to drag Aristotle into con- Nevertheless Simplicius gives an extreme Athenian-type interpre-
tation of Aristotle's psychology. It depends on splitting the soul into
as many layers as w ill enable him to deal with ambiguities, real and
n On Thcmistius' purpose in writing paraphrase see my Photius on Themisrius
(Cod.74): did Themistius write commentaries on Aristotle?, in: Hermes 107 ( 1979) imagined, by transforming each of two possible interpretations of a
175-176. text into separate entities, making both sides of the ambiguity true in
XIV XIV

99 Alexande~ of Aphrodisia.s in the later Greek coinment:J.ries 100

one way if not another. 24 Such an approach, though common to all later commentators. Plutarch has sometimes been characterised as a
later Neoplatonists, is more marked in the Athenian Neoplatonism sane and respectable commentator, a reliable interpreter of Aristotle
best represented by Prod us, whose ideas- or the Iamblichean ideas free from the wilder tendencies of later Neoplatonism. 29 If this were
which come to us in Proclus' writings-clearly influenced Simplicius, so we should expect to find, leaving aside other evidence as to his
notwithstanding his training at Alexandria.H He later studied under views both on the soul and other matters, that Plutarch and Alexan-
Damascius 26 at Athens and worked with him thereY der agreed more often than not, at least in their basic approach. Yet,
Thus Simplicius, commenting on 407 b 23-26, complains that as we have already seen, it is in relation to their approach that they
other interpreters, among whom he includes Alexander, made mis- are liable to be opposed. We must of course allow the possibility that
takes because they failed to distinguish between the form of life both are cited only in cases such as those we have considered, where
-and life is for him roughly equivalent to soul - which uses body as they disagree, or when the commentator who cites them disagrees
an instrument, 1TJV roc; OQy6.v(!> XQW!J.VT]V, and that which forms the with them both,30 while for most of their commentaries they will
instrument and makes it such as it is, 1ft<; 10 OQYO.VOV roc; OQya.vov have agreed with each other, and their views will have been accept-
eioonOlOUOT]<;. In consequence Alexander thought that soul does not able to their successors. Now that may have been the case, but if so it
use body as an instrument (52, 22-30). In other words, Alexander, is not necessarily important that it was so, for the simple reason that
having failed to make a Neoplatonic distinction, and an extreme one large sections of the De anima will have been uncontroversial in any
at that, fails to misinterpret Aristotle's basic concept of the soul in case.
such a way as to make it, in at least one sense, a separable entity such That statement perhaps requires justification. How, when the
as the Platonist concept, which all the late commentators shared, basis of Neoplatonic psychology is Platonic, in so far as there is no
required. 28 question about the soul's separat e and independent existence, can
The mention of P lutarch in conj unction with Alexander in two any considerable part of a treatise which starts from the opposite
of these passages is interesting and significant. These two are the assumption have remained uncontroversial? Briefly, the answer is
only commentators referred to with any frequency- Plutarch more this. From Plotinus on the Neoplatonists accepted the main outlines
often in Book III, to which any full commentary he wrote may have of Aristotle's psychology in so far as it related to the soul's functions
been confined-and in almost every case where their views are at var- rather than its nature. 31 Thus controversy was centred on the points
iance P lu tarch's is preferred to Alexander's. That this should be so is where the soul might or might not have been separable from the
only to be expected in view of the Neoplatonic orientation of the body, the lower part for the Neoplatonists and the higher for Aris-
totle. The whole central section of the soul, with its various func-
l Cf. my The psycho logy of(?) Simplicius (n. I 0) 78-82. tions, nutrition, reproduction, perception, memory and even, to an
u That there were such differences does not mean that Alexandrian and Athen ian extent, discursive thought, operated for the Neoplatonists in more or
Neoplatonism were based on a radically difFerent view of the structure and extent less the way described by Aristotle-while being for the N eoplaton-
of the intelligible, as was maintained by Pracchter, Richtungcn und Schulen im
ists separable like a Platonic soul. In this area the main problems for
Neuplatonismus. in: Genethliakon C. Robert, Berlin 1910, I 05-155, summarised on
155- 156, reprinted in: Kleine Schriften, ed. H.D6rrie, Hildesheim - New York the Neoplatonists arose over the demarcation of the boundary
1973, 165- 216, summary 215- 216; also in articles, Hierocles (1 8) in: RE III ( 1913)
19
1479-1482 and Simplicius (see n. 18) 204- 213. For a c ritique of Praechtel"s views Cf. Praechter, Art. Syria nos ( I) in: R I V A 2 (1932) 1737, and R. Beutler, Art. Plut-
cf. I. Hadot, Le probleme ( n. I 0) 47-65. archos (3) in: RE XXI I ( 1951 ) 963-964; contra H.-D. Saffrey and L. G . Weste-
z Cf. e. g. Simplic., In Phys. 642, 17 . rink, edd. Proclus, Th eo logie P latonicienne I, Paris 1968, xlvii.
21 If the author of Simplicius' De anima commentary is after al l Priscia n the point >o Cf. Simplic., In An. 50,36-37; 259,38-260,2; [Philop.), In An. 465,22-27;
about the Athenian milieu still stands. 529, 17- 26.
21 For furt her discussion of Simplicius' interpretation cf. Some Platonist readings ,, C f. my Plotinus' Psychology. His doctrines of the embodied soul, T he H ague 1971 ,
( n.4)6. 134-140.
XIV XIV

101 Alexander of Aphrodisias in the later Greek commentaries 102

between higher, rational, and lower, irrational, soul, a problem combine (2 : 3). The figures are of course far too small to have any
hinted at in Aristotle's treatise (432 a 22-26), but not of primary con- statistical significance; they merely indicate a trend. This is unfortun-
cern to him, and then over their constant anxiety to stress the active ate, as the same proportions apply to the philological issues in Sim-
and independent n ature of the soul's part in any activity involving plicius: on the combined questions disagreements outnumber agree-
both body and sout.n Thus there is a prima facie likelihood that ments by 6: 1. In the case of the genuine Philoponus commentary on
arguments against Alexander should be preponderantly, if by no Book III, available only for chapters 4-9 in Moerbeke's translation,
means entirely, related to his views about the unity of body and soul there are no agreements, arguably because no purely philological
and the nature of the intellect. points are at issue. Moreover, that part of the De anima is of course
There is one further area where one would not expect the late more "Neoplatonica.lly sensitive" than the rest in so far as it deals
commentators to disagree consistently with Alexander. That is in with intellect, which may also in part explain the greater divergence
matters of pure scholarship, reading, textual interpretations, the con- between Stephanus and Alexander. Only in part, because the differ-
struction of sentences or even their meaning-in the primary as ence holds also for those parts of Book III whose subject is more
opposed to the philosophical sense. Inevitably there will be some dif- neutral - the discussions of imagination, locomotion and the
fere nces even on the former, such as simple disagreements about arrangement and distribution of the faculties. An important point
cross-references, or points of grammar.33 In the last instance, of that emerges from these adm ittedly scant figures is that Alexander is
course, the boundaries between straight philological comment and not only cited on those occasions when the commentators feel that
active philosophical interpretation are-we have already seen a case his view must be disposed of or at least corrected.
of this- 34 likely to be blurred, notwithstanding the efforts o f the So far we have said nearly nothing about Themistius. Themistius
latest generation of commentators - Stephanus rather than Philopo- is a useful control since he wrote non-Platonic commentary at a
nus or Simplicius, though the procedure can be traced back to Pro- time, the mid-fourth century,36 when Platonism was already the pre-
clus-to separate formally their discussion of thought and lan- vailing philosophy, even if it had not yet been so for some three cen-
guage.H In fact Stephanus is, if anything, less good than the others, turies. Thus, unlike Simplicius and Philoponus, he is to be found on
who do not make the formal distinction in their work, at keeping the the same side as Alexander in his account of Aristotle's defini-
two apart in those cases which pertain to Alexander's interpretations. tion of the soul, and even closer to Aristotle- arguably of course-
And in all the cases where he presents Alexander's interpretation by than Alexander himself on the question of the active intellect, which
name he rejects it: this applies also to his citations of Alexander on Themistius took as internal to the individual human soul
philosophical points, a situation whose explanation we have already (102,30sqq.). These two cases alone suffice to show both that it was
touched on. The genuine Philoponus, on the other hand, in the com- not necessary to write Platonic commentary after the rise of Neopla-
mentary on Books I and II agrees with Alexander on purely philo- tonism, and also that a commentator's views could still, on crucial
logical points half as often again as he disagrees (6: 4), with the issues, reflect his own judgement rather than a prevailing school line.
reverse ratio applying where philological and philosophical points As in modern times the place where a man worked may have
affected his views: Themistius was at Constantinople, not at Athens
u Cf. ibid. 69 sqq., a11d Proclus on perception, in: BICS 29 ( 1982) 6-8. or Alexandria. It may of course be argued that the method Themis-
u Cf. e.g. Simplicius' complaint about Alexander's criticism of a double negative at tius used restricted his scope for unorthodoxy, but it will not be
Phys.ll 4, 196 a 8- 10 at In Phys. 329,14-20, or the simple disagreement about a
entirely outrageous to suggest that Aristotle's text leaves plenty of
cross referen ce at Simplic., In An. 50,36-37.
) Cf. the differences between Plutarch and Alexander on HI 12, discussed above,
p.98. >< The commentaries were written at an early stage in Themistius' career, cf. A. H. M.
)S Cf. festug iere, Modes de composition des commentaires de Proclus, in: M H 20 Jones, J. R. Martindale, J. Morris, Prosopography of the Later Roman Empire I,
(1963) 77- 100. Cambridge 1971, 88"9.
XIV XIV

103 Aleunder of Aphrodisias in the later Greek commentaries 104

scope fo r more than one paraphrase. Unfortunately Themistius' w hether soul is the entelechy of the body as a sailor is of a ship"
views are no t discussed sufficiently often in the other De anima (413 a 8-9). For Simplicius (96, 3-15) these remarks present a diffi-
commentaries for any useful conclusions to be drawn from such dis- culty because for him it is perfectly clear that the soul is an entelechy
cussions as we do find. In his De anima commentary Simplicius men- of that kind, that is, detachable: he does not discuss, or even men-
tions him only once ( 151, 14). Philoponus in one discussion mentions tion, Alexander's view that Aristotle appears to be in doubt. Philo-
him to object to his views on the problem at De anima 422 b 17 sqq. ponus does but, of course, rejects it because for him there can be
about whether or not a single sense is involved in the perception of no doubt on this point (225, 20-31 ). But Alexander, like some mod-
different kinds of objects of touch (408, 25-411 , 1), a question suffi- ern interpreters, raises the possibi lity that Aristotle is talking about
ciently difficult for disagreement not necessarily to be significant, t he intellect. As Philoponus puts it Alexander is forced to say that
and on another occasion to disagree about whether or not flesh is a Aristotle may be referring w the intellect: ngot:rov xcti oe
Tii~ uno
sense organ (418, 25-26). Stephan us refers to him three times, once Ae~eW<; ~lCt~O!!f.VO~ tpT]Otv Otl. tOtXB 8e 1tBQl voo Aiystv on eon
on the number of senses, where he accepts Themistius' opinion XWQlOt6<; (ibid. 25-26).
( 490, 9-19) but suggests that a Platonic explanation would be prefer- Yet Philoponus himself does not think that Ari3totle can be dis-
able (ibid . 27-34), and twice on the definition of imagination: here cussing a completely separate intellect anywhere in this work, a point
he dispu tes a view which he seems to have carelessly misrepresented that comes up at several places where the possibility arises that Aris-
(508, 19-21; 5 14,29-31) ! 7 None of these points depends on a differ- totle could be talking about a fully transcendent intellect (413 b
ence between a P latonic and non-Platonic reading of an Aristotelian 24-27, 415 a 11- 12). In discussing these passages Philoponus brings
text. to bear a principle of interpretation which excludes certain possibili-
It is, as we have already indicated, on just such points that Alex- ties right from the start, namely that all works of Plato and Aristotle
ander is criticised . We have mentio ned how Simplicius complains had one particular philosophical purpose. How misleading this
about his view of the body soul relatio n.l 8 P hilopon us makes some could be is perh aps best shown by the fact that lamblichus, who
attempt to come to terms with Aristotle's definition (215,4-216,25), seems to have been respons ib le for this system, decided that the
and so does not attack Alexander on this point, though in the course Sophist was a theological work dealing with the sub lunary demi-
of the discussion he does take issue with him on another matter. He urge.41 Under this rule the De anima was a work about A.oytxl)
does, however, object no less than Simplicius to Alexander's treat- ljiVXTJ, the rational soul, that is the human soul as attached to an
ment of those passages where Aristotle suggests that perhaps some individual and separate from the transcendent intelligible world (cf.
part of the soul is separable after all .J 9 These of course more often e.g. Simp lic. 4,29- 31) . This arbitrary limitation of the scope of the
relate to the intellect, but the different approaches of Alexander and De anima is produced as an argument here and elsewhere, most
his Neoplatonic successors emerge just as clearly over the still unre- notably in the discussions of III 5 by Stephanus, to which we have
solved problem passage where Aristotle, having argued that the soul already referred, 2 and also by Simplicius (cf. 240,2-5) 4 ) to show
must be the inseparable entelechy of the body, allows the possibility that Aristotle could not have been talking about what Neoplatonists
that some parts may be separable just because they are not the called divine (fisto<;) or unparticipated (al!EfiEX"TO~) intellect, and so
body's entelechy, and then continues en
8E a o, A.ov ~::t oihw~ tv-cst.- not about the supreme cause, as Alexander maintained.
xsw. -coO OW!!CX.to~ ~ \j/UX~ wonsQ nf..w't~Q nA.o(ou,40 "it is unclear 41
Cf. the scholi on o n Plat., Soph.116 a, p. 445 Greene; also in Plato, ed. Hermann VI,
l1 See further my Neoplatonic interpretations of Aristotle on phantasia, in: RMcta 31 249.
2
(1977) 253-254. ' See above pp. 94-95.
> Cf. p . 99 above. " Cf. also [Philop.), In An. 518, 36-519, 2 where Ammonius is reported to have com-
" See pp. 104-105 below. plained that both Alexander and Plutarch failed to see that the treatise is not about
c Simplicius' lemma reads 'tOU o6>1J.tl"t6~ eonv &o m:g but the sense is not affected. 6 66Qa{h:v voil<;.
XJV
XIV
lOS
Alexander of Aphrodisias in th e later Greek commentaries 106
Just as Philoponus had refused to accept that Aristotle shows any
doubt about the separability of soul, so Simplicius, discussing 413 b account of this passage. 4 s As we indicated, Stephanus there quotes
15-16, where Aristotle says there is a problem about separability, Alexander only to disagree with him, and here we have at least o ne
writes that we must not follow Alexander in thinking the remark is piece of evidence to show that Neoplatonist commentators could
occasioned by intellect: the difficulty is about the senses, which use take a different view of the same passage. If we h ad more examples
separate o rgans (101 , 18-32). At 413 b 24-26 Aristotle says nothing of texts where Alexander's views of the De anima were discussed by
is yet clear about the power of thought, but it seems to be a different more than o ne of his successors, we shou ld be able to form a clearer
kind of soul and the only one that can be separable. Simplicius, like picture of how far the different commentators were prepared to
Philoponus, maintains that Aristotle's difficulty is not about the accept them, and thus incidentally o f the precise differences between
separability of intellect. When Alexander suggests that Aristotle's these commentators themselves on the points at issue.46
"seems" (cnxe) leaves open two possibilities, Simplicius asserts that
"seems" must mean "is apparendy" (nQEJtet or cpa(ve-rat), and argues 4
j Cf. above p. 98.
46
that the rational soul is certainly separate - a good example of how An earlier version of this paper was given to a joint session of the Classical Associa-
the Neoplatonists read their philosophical presuppositions into an tion of Canada and the Canadian Philosophical Association at Laval University,
and w:~s wrinen durin g the tenure of :1 Junior Fellowship at the Center for Hellenic
ostensibly philological discussion ( 102,27- 103, 8). In discussing the Studies, and a Leve rhulme Research Fellowship.
same text Philoponus, as we have just seen, uses his view that the
divine intellect must be separable to exclude Alexander's suggestion
that that is the subject of Aristotle's doubt (241, 28-242, 5; cf. also
194, 12- 13). And when at 415 a 11-12 Aristotle, talking about lower
faculties being entailed by higher ones, says that the intellect that
thinks is another subject, Philoponus rejects Alexander's explanation
that the reference is to the divine intellect on the grounds that that is
not Aristotle's s ubject here (261, 10-262, 4).
These are a few examples of how the Neoplatonist commenta-
tors confronted Alexander on matters where differe nces could
hardly fail to arise. What happens is dear enough. But it would be
wrong to think that these principles of interpretation are not applied
at other points in the work. Let us take an apparently innocuous
issue like the section where Aristotle discusses locomotion under the
stimulus of the appetitive faculty (433 b 8 sqq.). Alexander, giving a
clearly Aristotelian explanation, said that the faculty was moved
accidentally. Plutarch differed, and said that the activity of the
appetitive faculty is movement: this Simplicius describes as a Pla-
tonic explanation, and prefers it (302, 23-30). 44 On the other hand, a
few pages below Simplicius prefers Alexander to Plutarch on the
question whether moving but ungenerated entities h ave sense-per-
ception (320, 33- 34): we have already looked at his and Stephanus'

On th is text see further Sollle Plato nist read ings (n.4) 12.

Вам также может понравиться