Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 319
TE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO IDE UNO THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO PAUL TILLICH'S PHILOSOPHY OF CULTURE SCIENCE, AND RELIGION A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE DIVINITY SCHOOL IN CANDIDACY FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY BY JAMES LUTHER ADAMS CHICAGO, ILLINOIS SEPTEMBER, 1945 TABLE OF CONTENTS Chapter Page I. HE NEED FOR A NEW LANGUAGE... ee ee eee ee 1 The Mortbund Character of Present-Day Protestant- ism and Its Language The Gulf between Church and People and between the Church and the World The Need for a New Understanding of Traditional Conceptions and for a New Turning toward the Re- alitios of Contemporary Life. The Inadequacy of the Method of Authority The Inadequacy of the Methods of the Psychology and the History of Religions ‘The Phenomenological Method: an Approach to That Which Ultimately Concerns Man II, TILLIGH'S BASIC CONCEPTS -.. +--+ +e eee 15 The Decisive Role of the Protestant Ethos The Concept of "the Present." "Existential" Thinking Decision: Man's Cleavage, Fate, Freedom, Perver- sion Depth The Boundary-Situation The Unconditioned Faith, Grace, and the Form of Grace Secularism: Protestant Secularism The Divine and the Demonic Autonomy, Heteronomy, and Theonomy Kairos and Logos ‘Thought, Belaes and Spirit Meaning Appendix: "Water"... eee ee ee eee BL III. THE THEOLOGY OF ART AND CULTURE... ....... 65 The Role of Art in Tillich's Early Development Art as a Revelation of Pure Being Basic Categories Derived from the Study of Art: Form and Import Art as a Phenomenon of the Border between Reli- gion and Culture The Outlines of a Theology of Culture The Relations between Culture and Religion: Form and Import Style and Metaphysics The Theologian of Culture and the Church-Theolo- gian ab Chapter Iv. Page Examples of Tillich's Application of the Theology of Culture to the Study of Art History An Interpretation and Typology of Technology The Relation between Technology and Art Domestic Architecture Theological interpretations of space and time Theological interpretations of support and threat Technology and Meaning The Technological City as a Symbol of Meaning and Frustration of Meaning Modern Art as a Revolt Against the Meaningless- ness of Technological Society Summary Statement of the Nature and Function of a Theology of Culture THE SYSTEM OF THE SCIENCES .. +. ++. + seee 18 Tillich's Relation to Idealism Philosophy as "Historical" "Meaning" as the Primary Concern of Contemporary Patlosophy Meaning as a System of Meanings The Nature of the Task of Constructing a Systen of the Sciences The Nature of Science The diversity of methods and objects The need for classification The ultimate frame of reference The Basic Significance of "the Idea of Knowledge" The Principle of Absolute Thought, of Absolute Being, and of Absolute Spirit The Tripartite Division of the Sciences The sciences of thought The sciences of being The concepts of law, sequence, and Gestalt The sciences of spirit: the cultural sciences The concept of spirit Spirit and meaning The Metalogical Method The nature and purpose of the method as re- vealed in a comparison and contrast of: Tillich and Troeltsch Tillich and Hegel Tillich and Kant Other important influences: Jacob Boohme, F. W. J. Schelling, and Neo-Platoniem The Creative and Normative Character of the Cul- tural Sciences The concept of meaning and its appropriate dis- ciplines The Classification of the Cultural Sciences Theoretical and practical Autonomous and theonomous: the supported and the supporting functions The Nature and Functions of Philosophy, Metaphys- ics, and Theology, and Their Relations to the Other Cultural Sciences Criticism and Evaluation of Tillich's System Aut Chapter Page V. THE PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION ....+.+ + see 186 The General Character of Tillich's Philosophy of Religion The Relations between Philosophy of Religion and the Other Disciplines The Method of the Philosophy of Religion Tillich's Conception of"Belief-ful Realism" The Concept of "the Unconditioned" ‘The Epistemology of Phenomenological Intuition The two traditions of European philosophy Logos and Kairos: space-thinking and time- ‘ing ‘The fundamental Protestant attitude "Existential" thinking: the role of decision Formal evidence, material probability, and the “third element" The dynamic conception of truth and meaning The overcoming of absolutism and relativism General characterization and criticism of Til- lich's epistemology Tillich's Construction of a Philosophy of Reli- gion in Terms of a Philosophy of Meaning The definition of the elements of meaning The definition of culture and religion in terms of a theory of the functions of meaning The structure of the functions of meaning; re- Ligion in its relation to the theoretical and the practical functions The advantage of the construction: the essence and the truth of religion are established si- mul taneously The symbolic character of religious truth ‘The Essential Elements of Religion and Their Re- lation to Other Phenomena Faith and unfaith God and the world The holy and the profane, the sacred and the secular; secularism The divine and the demonic; grace and "posses- sion’ The "Construction" of the History of Religion The theocratic, the sacramental, and the mys- tical tendencies Polytheism, monarchic and exclusive monotheism, the synthesis in the religion of paradox; Chris- tology Theology as the fulfilment of the goal of “con- struction" in a normative theory of meaning Analogies of the "Construction" in the History of Cuture The Special Categories of Religion The theoretical sphere: myth and revelation The practical sphere: cultus and community Criticism of the definition of these categories Summary and General Characterization of Tillich's Philésophy of Religion Criticiam and General Estimate iv Chapter Page VI. FROM PHILOSOPHY TO THEOLOGY... - 1... eee 266 The Functions of Philosophy of Religion and of Theology The Difficulty of Determining the Lines of Demar- cation in Tillich's Practice of These Disciplines The Principal Reasons for the Difficulty The Difficulty Increased by the Ambiguity and the Changes in the Meaning of the Concept ofthe Un- conditioned" The Concept of "the Unconditioned" as a Solvent Illustrations: Tillich's use of the concept in his treatment of culture, art, religion, Chris- tianity, and the theory of symbols. The Importation of Philosophy of Religion into Theology: the Doctrine of God, the Concept of Revelation, Christology The Influence of Christian Doctrine upon the T1l- lichian Philosophy of Religion: the Doctrines of Creation, of Justification by Faith, of Sin and Grace, and of God General Estimate of the Value and Significance of Tillich's Philosophy of Religion and Culture Tillich's New Language and Its Significance BIBLIOGRAPHY «6 ee ee ee eee et ee ee ee ee ee 2BT CHAPTER I THE W! FOR A NEW LANGUAGE Among contemporary European theologians there 1s no one who has more radically questioned the prevailing ideas and prac= tices of the Christian churches, and especially of Protestantism, than has Paul Tillich. In this respect, he would scarcely seem to be a typical theologian. The theologian is not usually thought of as areal disturber. When one hears the word "theologian" one is by habit predisposed to think of a professional journeyman who is comfortably ensconced within the securities of an ecclesiastical institution and who can, when he lays hands on him, dispose of any "@isturber." The theologian, it 1s generally thought, is one who by the very nature of his vocation attempts constantly to devise means whereby the "faithful" may be effectively exhorted simply to be more faithful to the tradition. He may think of himself as the disturber of Satan's cohorts, but he also considers himself as the defender of a "faith" which is in this world of sin always under attack or toward which the "faithful" are prone to be lukewarm. He 1s not expected to be a disturber within the church itself, a @isturber who attacks the practices of the churches as false or ir- relevant. And if he does give this appearance, he is expected to turn out in actuality to be merely a more subtle and more effective stimulus to institutional morale than his fellow exhorters. But the consequences of his labor are not viewed as a radical question- ing of the institution he serves. Paul Tillich sets forth his criticism of the church pre- cisely as a theologian. For him, protest 4s an ineradicable ele- ment in Protestantism as such and the first task of the theologian is to proclaim the protest. In his role as disturber within the church Tillich does not, of course, stand alone. Karl Barth, for example, especially in his earliest writings and in his attack upon the "German Christians" of the Third Reich, has secured a repute tion as such a disturber. But by the time his second major work was published Barth's disturbance quieted down into a return to 2 ecclesiasticism and confessionalism. Reinhold Niebuhr has deeply disturbed the social conscience of the churches and of other theo- logians, and it would be difficult to overestimate his significance in this respect, But the faith to which he summons his readers and Listeners is for the most part a faith that 1s couched in a tradi- tional theological language laden with the prickly pears of ambi- guity and with a certain odor of antiquarianism. Due to the inert social conservatism of the bulk of the clurches, he succeeds in eliciting within the churches more of renewed loyalty to tradition- al theological language than of daring protest and of commitment to new ways of living. Paul Tillich, on the other hand, 1s deeply disturbed by an awareness not only that present-day Protestantism is moribund but also that it 1s so-partially because the language of tradition can in our day have little effect upon the “believers” and still less upon those outside the churches. He holds that the Protes- tantism to which we are accustomed has almost exhausted itself by identifying itself with the dominant powers of the environment, that is, with a convulsive nationalism and with fat bourgeois in- terests. Hence, he believes that a radical protest against the churches is necessary if Protestantism is to fulfil its vocation for our time; indeed, he is convinced that for a long time to come protest must take priority.” This protest must include a protest against moribund terminology and it must issue in the creation of the word that speaks to our present condition, to the distressed condition of our particular time and of our particular churches. Emerson said that if one should cut Montaigne's words they would bleed. Tillich's view is that cutting into conventional religious language 1s almost like dissecting a corpse. He says that “we no longer have words in which the powerfulness of the word pulsates." But protest against dead words 1s not enough: Protestant protest must issue in Protestant realization, in the word that releases new vitality. New life demands new words first to sley death and then to summon daring novelty. The more encrusted the habits of the mass of churchmen and the more rigid the sense of authority attaching to conventional terminology, the more daring will the innovation seem. Innovation TReligiose Verwirklichung (Berlin: Purche, 1930), p. 44 and Note 2. Hereafter abbreviated, el. Verw. 3 with respect to religious language frequently elicits even a sense of shock among the faituful, with the consequence that little seri- ous attempt is made by them to understand new terms. Indeed, Til- lich confesses that in his own life "the immemorial experience of mankind that new knowledge can be won only through breaking a taboo and that all autonomous thinking 1s accompanied by a sense of guilt, has been a fundamental experience." The positive consequence of this sense of taboo has meant for Tillich that "every step in theo- logical, ethical, and political criticism encountered inhibitions which often could be overcome only after conflicts lasting for years. If Tillich's attitude toward the language of tradition is to be contrasted with the attitudes of Barth and Niebuhr, it of- fers striking comparison with that of the young Schleiermacher. When Schleiermachera century and a half ago summoned "the cultured despisors of religion" and undertook (in the Addresses) to show them its indispensability and inevitableness, he felt that he owed his audience an explanation for the fact that his language was not the language of the theologian. After "confessing" to his hearers that he belongs to the profession of theologian, he says, It 4s a willing confession, but my language would not have be- trayed me, nor should the 'eulogies' of my colleagues in the profession; what I desire lies so far out of their orbit and would little resomble what they wish to see and hear... . I am aware that in ell I have to say to you I fully disown my profession, and why should I not therefore confess it like any other misdemeanor. With greater cause than Schlelermacher, Tillich might well say this of his own language, for, as one of his European critics has ob- served, "his writings delight the reader in a remarkably untheologi- cal, profane way."* It is no doubt partially for thie reason that Tillich has been sometimes spoken of as an apostle to the Gentiles. One may here again note the contrast between Tillich and Barth. Although Barth repeatedly and rightly insists that the tru- ly religious outlook must affect all areas of life and although he says he would be "especially pleased" if his commentary, The Epistle 1, Interpretation of History (New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1936), p- 25 erica Kippers, "Zur Religionsphilosophie Paul Tillichs," Zwischen den Zeiten, IX (1931), 125. The passage from Schleier- macher, cited above, 1s quoted in this article. Translations from German writings, unless otherwise noted, are by the present writer. 4 to the Romans, should stray into the hands of some who are not theologians, he begs the indulgence of his untheological readers who may find his writings difficult to read. In response to his eritics who urge that "simplicity 1s the mark of divinity" he says, "Z could not make the book more easily intelligible than the usb- Ject itself allows. If I be not mistaken, we theologians serve the layman best when we refuse to have him especially in mind, and when we simply live of our own." Tillich may for some readers seem, like Schlefermacher, to owe an apology for his mode of expression which at times appears to be as esoteric as it 1s unconventional. But such a judgment would require qualification. Although Tillich does invent or adopt numerous terms which require extended explanation, these terms pos- sess an intriguing novelty coupled with a certain peculiar relevance to the mental climate of our time. Moreover, Tillich's range of interest and the variety of his forms of exposition provide mani- fold opportunities for him to win the attention of the reader. Out of the more than two hundred things he has written since the pub- lication of his earliest dissertations on Schelling, a majority have been addressed to the educated reader rather than merely to professional colleagues. Many of them deal explicitly and vividly with the common concerns of our time. Ultimately the explanation of the difference between Tillich and Barth 1s to be found in the former's conviction that the words of the theologian should be new words that speak to our time. In his view, the theologian must not be content with proclamation of the "Word of God" once delivered; he must accept the responsibility and challenge of apologetics. Strict adherence to an "established," "holy" language constitutes a "legalism of the word." Hence Tillich has in many of his writings made a deliberate effort to write in "an untheological, profane way." His Religious Situation and scores of his magazine articles published in Germany and America reveal the intent and the effectiveness of this effort. In Tillich's opinion, the traditional language of theology, despite any value 1t may possess for the expert, tends to create a gulf not only between the church and the world but also between the theologian and the layman. This traditional language often obscures lxarl Barth, Epistle to the Romans, trans. Edwyn C. Hoskyns (Oxford: Oxford Gaiversiey Pres 1933), Pe 5. 8 and even perverts the essential and relevant message of the church, whether it is directed to the churchman or to the outsider. Be- cause of it the characteristic doctrines of Christianity as well as the liturgy and preaching in the churches, are at present large- ly ineffective. The characteristic doctrines of the Reformation, for example, doctrines that "four centuries ago split the European continent asunder and aroused savage and bloody wars," are now "so strange to the modern man that there is scarcely any way available for making them intelligible." By trying again and again to 1m- Pose upon men as lew the religious language of earlier generations, the churches are defeating their own proper ends, Our intellectual and social situation is different from that out of which the words of the church proclamations were born. Our age has lost "the pre= suppositions which the Middle Ages and the Reformation had in com- mont those of the certainty of God, and with it the certainty of truth and meaning."® The modern man has experienced autonomy and he will not surrender it, at least not for long. This autonomy in+ volves also an autonomy with respect to modes of expression. Our intellectual and social situation is different also from the situations out of which the traditional lenguage of church liturgy came. Hence the liturgy of the churches has little to do with our contemporaneity, whether we think of the traditional lit- urgy or of that which has supposedly undergone "liturgical reform." If any attempt is to be made in the direction of giving the liturgy relevance to the conmon life, Tillich believes it "must be brought to light not with the ‘long arm! of the antiquarian but rather with the ‘cutting edget of contemporaneity."® It requires "a now under- standing of natural and everyday processes in their transcendent meaning." This same situation obtains with respect to "the word of the preacher, whether it be spoken in the church or out of it, and also for the hymns... ." Some preachers wrongly imagine that ecclesiastical and biblical language are devices that will of them- lRel. Verw., pp. 30-31. 2nRechtfertigung und Zweifel," Vortrage der Theologischen Konferenz zu Giessen, p. 59. Folge (Giessent Tépelmann, 1924), p 2.:COCOC~C~S~sts™S Rel. Verw., p. 85. 6 selves be sufficient. But Tillich, with his acute sense of the gulf between the church and the world, holds that "in so far as our understanding of the words of the Bible requires us to separate ourselves from the here and now, from our own contemporaneity, they are not the Word of God." The test of a realistic faith is the objectively powerful word.. Among the "faithful" the traditional language often serves to develop a mentality that is closed to criticism as well as to new light, a mentality that is unconcerned either about the irrele- vance or the ineffectiveness of the churches. Indeed, the indif- ference of "the world"--and even of the lukewarm within the church- es-~often elicits among churchmen only "a spirit of 111-tempered hybris." Instead of meeting the challenge to speak to the contemporary condition of their hearers, many representatives of the church prefer a sort of intoxicated renunciation of success or effec- tiveness, a renunciation that is in the end self-destructive. But even the message of the Bible can give no justifica- tio for repealing contemporaneity.! In this last-quoted passage Tillich is thinking especially of the Barthian opposition to any human attempt to give the Word of God contemporaneity, but the implications are also of general import. "The Word of God," he says, "is any reality by means of which the Eternal breaks with unconditioned power into our contemporaneity."2 It is not a question any longer of "a direct proclamation of the religious truths as they are given in the Bible and the tradition, for all of these things are torn down into the general chaos of doubt and questioning."® By ignoring these facts, the churches are actually accelerating and deepening the crisis of modern reli- gion and civilization.* They are arousing positive hostility to the message and work of the churches not only among the educated but also among the oppressed groups who are seeking a new meaning in life. "Until the appointed representatives of the Protestant message understand this, their work in the widest circles, and es- pecially among the working classes, will be utterly hopeless."> tipia., 2ro1a. Stpid., p. 38. 4Ipid., p. 198, Stpid., pp. 38 and 275, Note 20. Here contemporary liter- ature on the proletariat is cited to show the great distance in which the workers stand from the church. 7 Any attempt to proclaim a religious message without taking this situation into account, constitutes culpable blindness. Hence, Tillich concludes that we have here "the most urgent need of the church today in the proclaiming of its message: its language 1s remote from contemporary life and yet it makes a demand upon that 1ite."? the churches cannot reasonably expect to make any positive impact upon that life if they are ignorant of it or if they are out of direct touch with it. The chasm represented by the differences in languages is, of course, only the linguistic reflection of a chasm in life. The one chasm cannot be closed without closing the other, but we must first find the relevant words that "pulsate with the powerfulness of the word." The problem is more difficult when we remember that the co- hesion of a religious community demands continuity of linguistic usage along with novelty introduced for the sake of achieving con- temporaneity. In this connection, it should be emphasized that despite hie severely critical attitude toward traditional language, Tillich recognizes the significance of "objective constructions like the confessions of a Church the meaning of which transcend subjective belief or doubt, and which are thus able to support com munities in which all tendencies of doubt, criticism and certainty are admitted, provided only that the confessional foundation of the comunity is given general recognition."* Tillich's attitude toward the deficiencies of traditional language should, therefore, not be interpreted as favoring an abandonment of all church con= fessions or of the historic doctrines of the church. He does not propose that a general chaos of fresh thought and language be in- troduced into church life. As a theologian Tillich hopes rather to give new relevance to the basic faith of the church, to give its doctrines, wherever possible, the living meaning implicit and latent within them. He neither wishes nor expects that the new language of a particular theologian shall replace the more slowly changing language of the community. As a matter of fact, Tillich's attitude is similar to that of most creative theologians. They tipid., p. 85. 2Interpretation of History, pp. 18-19. These sentiments reflect Titishts orfontation to tho’ shuren situation in Burope. We do not know how he would interpret the American situation in this respect. 8 have spoken as it were in tongues, but they have not aimed to be- come ventriloquists for the community. We must bear these consid- erations in mind in this whole discussion of Tillich's criticiem of the traditional language of the churches. Otherwise, we shall fail to understand his true meaning and wrongly suppose that he wishes to replace a fetishism for traditional language with a fe- tishiom for novelty. Such a replacement would, of course, be im- possible of achievement. And even if it were possible to achieve, it would be psychologically and sociologically self-defeating. As Tillich puts 1t,"Realization in worship, sermon, and instruction assume forms that can be imparted. Ecclesiastical reality, the reality of the personal religious life, yes, even the prophetic word itself assumes a sacramental foundation, an abundance from which they live." the demand for novelty must not be interpreted as incompatible with these other aspects of a continuing church fellowship. On the other hand, these considerations must not blind one to the imperative character of the demand for novelty. The church in its rigid adherence to traditional language always appeals to divine inctions in order to justify itself. But however convincing these sanctions may be, the churches that employ them are actually ignoring the fact that the intellectual situation has changed. They are ignoring the fact also that lan- guage is a temporal, cultural creation, a vocabulary that in some different situation in the past served as an effective means of communication but that is now a strange idiom, a sort of fossil preserved because of the falsely pious notion that it 1s a sacro- sanct ark of the covenant to be touched by human hands only on pain of spiritual death. In its effect, this stubborn adherence to the language of the fathers brings about a degeneration into a quasi-priesthood of Scriptures and "sound doctrine." It may be added that this consequence virtually attaches also to much liberal reinterpretation of traditional language, for the reinterpretation often has as little effect as the original which is being reinter- preted. As a result, then, both the liberal and the orthodox churches communicate something that breeds death or false life. And in the outcome the traditional language, in its resistance to any disturbance of carrion comfort, must for its continuing via-~ bility depend upon an appeal to "conventional, mediocre theology tipid., p. 27. 9 as a protection against a better, though unconventional, theology."> It would be wrong to suppose that, in Tillich's view, the need for disturbance in the church arises merely from its predica- ment of being tongue-tied. The predicament is, as we have observed, only one aspect of @ larger embarrassment. This larger embarrass- ment is due to the fact that Protestantism in its present form is reaching its limit. In its contemporary realization Protestantism 1s not adequate for meeting the demands of the historical situation. The powerful motives that were effective in certain earlier periods of Christianity are no longer really functioning. It is to no pur- pose merely to repeat the old ideas in their frayed forms. Nor will it be possible to leap over the gulf between Protestantism and its lost provinces by simply resuming its connection with the Reformation or with some other period denominated as normative.” Protestantism by its very essence and through its inherit- ance of the substance of Christianity possesses a basis for coping with the situation. Before God Protestantism must protest against all false securities and undertake a new realization relevant to the present historical situation. If the churches wish to reach the men of today they must "discover anew the reality which was apprehended in earlier times and which is in essence the same today, and then present it in quite new terms." Only then can they "un- derstand that reality on the basis of what the old words Aintended."® only then can they break through the "academically petrified prob- lems" and achieve an immediate knowledge of essential reality. “Religious knowledge is knowledge of reality." It is "not prima- rily the unfolding of a tradition; it is rather a turning towards reality,"* "a penetrating in an ultimate sense into what happens day by day, in labor and industry, in marriage and friendship, in ordinary social intercourse and recreation, in meditation and quiet, and even in sleep."> 1 Protestantisches Prinzip und Proletarische Situation (Bonn: Friedrich Cohen, 193i), Pp. 24 2Rel. Verw., p. 47. Protestantism may not “on any point attribute a sort of classical status to the period of the Reforma- tion in a normative sense. It is of the essence of Protestantism that there can be no classical period for it." Srpia., p. Sl. 4tpid., p. 58. ®rpia., p. 61. 10 In this respect, certain secular philosophers of our day are exhibiting more nearly the right attitude than are some theo- logians. In fact, Tillich's own attempt to discover anew the pow- erful experiences that lay behind the old religious symbols that have now so largely lost their power is, in many ways, similar in purpose, for example, to the attempt of Martin Heidegger to discern the original experiences from which the leading conceptions of phi~ losophy have been created. Tillich says? Something very tragic tends to happen in all periods of man's spiritual life: truths, once deep and powerful, discov- ered by the great geniuses with profound suffering and in- credible labor, become shallow and superficial when used in daily conversation. How can this happen? It can happen and it unavoidably happens, because there is no depth without the way to depth. Truth without the way to truth is dead; and if it 1s still used, in detachment, it contributes only to the surface of things.! These words come very near to expressing the sentiments of the ex- Astential philosopher, Heidegger, though Tillich does not agree with Heidegger's atheistic position. Other secular philosophies and movements today exhibit this same desire to approach reality directly and to break through the encrustations of impotent traditional conceptions. Thus they "con- firm and strengthen what is really at issue in theology itself: a penetration unhampered by the restraints of traditional ways of posing problems and concepts . .. . Our attachment should be to the things themselves and not to mere authority."* They also dem- onstrate that no group of men holds a monopoly on the ability to penetrate reality. This fact leads Tillich to adopt a positive attitude toward secularism in so far as it uncovers depths of being and of history inaccessible to merely traditional ways of thinking and speaking. Theology must find a new approach to reality. The old method of authority, which appeals to Scripture or church doctrines, breaks down because unavoidable conflicts arise between dogmatic materials and scientific treatment, with the result that either science is mutilated by authority or authority 1s undermined by science. In face of this situation Tillich agrees with the modern man who believes that the days of authoritarianism and supernatu- lupepth," Christendom, IX (1944), 319. pel. Verw., p. 23. nn realism are numbered; science is here to stay. Since the time of Schleiermacher, an attempt has been made to devise a second approach by combining his psychological method with modern psychology, sociology, and history of religions. But however important its contributions, Tillich holds that this method is also to be criticized. It "remains enclosed in the subjectivity of religious consciousness and never attains an immediate grasp of the contents intended in the religious act, for it 1s impossible to derive the substance of the act from the act, instead of the 1 " act from the substance. This criticism of the second method suggests a third way of approaching reality, the path which T4llich wishes to follow. He calls this third method the immediate approach through "phenomenological intuition." In this approach, he says, "we turn neither to the authorities nor to religious consciousness, but im- mediately to the whole of reality, and endeavor to uncover that level of reality which is intended by the religious act."* This path is tobe distinguished especially from that of rationalism, for it 1s not possible to reach the substance of religion without experience of the religious act itself. Rationalism not only fails to penetrate the depth of the religious act; 1t also ends by negat~ ing the substance of religion. We shall have to return later to a discussion of these and other methodologies. Here we are centering attention upon the question of language. And, as we have already indicated, the sig- nificant thing to observe is that Tillich attempts in much of his writing to set forth his conception of religion and of reality without resort to the language of tradition. Indeed, in one of the most important expositions of his religious position, the essay en- titled "Belief-ful Realism," he sets forth his ideas without make ing use of conventional "religious" symbols at all.° The method of phenomenological intuition insists that the real basis of theo- logical thought 1s human existence itself and not certain sacro- sanct words that have been fixed by the crust of habit or by the linia., p. 128. 2ypia., p. 129. Scr, T4111ch's discussion of the ability of some posts to use words that "are both symbolic and precise" and that "neverthe- less penetrate into the deepest levels of existence." Cf. Rel. Verwe, p. 109 and Note 17. An example of this sort of poesis may Be seen in Hopkins' "God's Grandeur," quoted on the next page. 12 traditions of the schools. The methods of the schools derive con- cepts from concepts instead of from objects. Thus the paradox, the tension, the vitality, the depth and wonder of life are ration- alized and lost. Tillich believes that these methods can and must be put aside if the living, concrete, real power of religious sym- ols is to be allowed to spring forth. The new method must attempt to discover things directly without terminological prejudice. To be sure, there are perils that attend all attempts to clarify vision or to introduce new language into religious discus- sions, the perils of the eccentric and the esoteric. But the pres- ent theological situation demands that such riske be teken. "With- out daring, even frustrated daring, the impasse of the present theology cannot be resolved."+ ‘the spirit and the intention with which Tillich ventures to escape this impasse can best be indicated by his own characteristic words, words thet again reveal the undog- matic theologian: "This unusual method, in which scarcely a word of the religious tradition is used, and for which a painstaking and sensitive intuition of the things nearest to us, the most living things and therefore the most difficult to observe, is demanded,-- this method 1s intended only as an attempt which will be followed by other and better ones, so that we may see with our own eyes and name with our own words that which is not bound to any time or any eye or any word." What we must see and what we must name is, in the words of the poet, nothing less than "the grandeur of God," the living majes- ty in "the dearest freshness deep down things." This dearest fresh- ness deep down things has been seared with trade, bleared, smeared with toil and with the worn-out words which the generations have trod upon it. "The world is charged with the grandeur of God. It will flame out, like shining from shookfoil; It gathers to a greatness, like the ooze of ofl Crushed. Why do men then now not reck his rod? Generations have trod, have trod, have trod} And all is seared with trade; bleared, smeared with toil; And wears man's smudge and shares man's smell: the soil Is bare now, nor can foot feel, being shod. “and for all this, nature is never spent; There lives the dearest freshness deep down things; linterpretation of History, p. 284. Rel. Verw., p. 141. 13 And though the last lights off the black West wont Oh, morning, at the brown brink eastward, springs--~ Because the Holy Ghost over the bent 1 World broods with warm breast and with aht bright wings. Now, this demand for seeing and naming anew the grandeur of God would seem, at least at first blush, to be no cause for dis- turbance, in the churches, nor in the "world" either for that mat- ter. Have not the poets and the liturgies of the ages again and again seen anew and named the grandeur of God? The answer is that they have, but that all too often the seeing and naming anew have caused no disturbance and have brought no new vitality. If one proposes "to penetrate in an ultimate sense what happens day by day in labor and industry, in marriage and friendship" and in all the important concerns of the common life, one proposes to discover anew something that is seldom suggested, even to the average "be- liever," by the phrase, "the grandeur of God." In Tillich's view, to be sure, the embarrassment of present-day civilization and of present-day Christianity must be interpreted in the end as the re- sult of a loss of the sense of the majesty of God. But in order to interpret the embarrassment after that fashion, one would have to give the phrase a meaning it does not often possess in ordinary parlance. The word "God" has in many quarters lost its potency and has become a trivial breath of tepid air, suitable only for the hollow men of limbo. For many people, in fact, the word represents only a fantasy, a nonentity. For the “unbeliever" it suggests, and for many "believers" it provides, an escape from reality rather than a penetration of it. Somehow the "believers" (as well as the unbelievers) have failed to penetrate in an ultimate sense what happens day by day. Belief in the grandeur of God, as ordinarily understood, is not enough. These observations only give the greater plausibility to Tillich's claim that we need to discover and name something anew. It may well be that even the word "God" has been so much bleared and seared that it 1s, for wide circlos of men, not even potential with greatness. At least, Tillich's own writings would seem to indicate that he believes this is true, for he has been veritably an ascetic in his sparing use of the word. Indeed, certain theo- "God's Grandeur," Poems of Gerard Hopkins, Now First Pub- lished, with Notes by Robert Bridges (2d ed London: Humphrey Milford, 1931), p. 26. 14 logians in Germany some years ago charged him with being an atheist. Early in his career (in 1926) the clergy in Saxony protested against his appointment to the chair of philosophy in Dresden. This pro- test was made because of his prominent work among the religious so- cfalists and the unbelievers. The fact that he was known as a re- igious socialist convinced some conservative Christians that he is surely an atheist. And who would be so bold as to say that knowledge of the same fact would not elicit a similar reaction from many Christians and believers in God, in other countries? It would appear that for some people there are matters of much greater mo- ment than "God" or "the grandeur of God." If we could discover what these things are we would have discovered what God really is for these "believers." Evidently, the question is: Which God really has the grandeur? Now, TMillich's writings "delight the reader in a remarkably untheological, profane way," just because he wishes to get behind both religion and irreligion, behind theology and "anti-theology," to penetrate in an ultimate sense into what happens day by day in labor and industry, in war and "peace," in church and culture. For the fulfilment of this end he poses again and again the ques- tion: What is man's ultimate concern? Or rather, what should it be? As we have indicated, he believes that the actual ultimate concerns of men--and of churches--are to be discovered by penetrat- ing their very embarrassments; if one can discover what has caused the embarrassment one may discover what the ultimate concerns have been and also what they should be. In order to accomplish this purpose, he wishes to discover anew the dearest freshness deep down things and to remove again the blight that old and uncouth words have wrought upon it. CHAPTER II TILLICH'S BASIC CONCEPTS In order to name with his own words what he has seen, Til- lich, convinced of the present ineffectiveness of conventional re- ligious language, inevitably has had to devise a new vocabulary. Now, obviously other men have often made the same attempt. They too have "turned directly to reality" with the intention of grasp- ing it in some new and deeper fashion. They too have then returned to the cave with new and wingéd words. What, then, distinguishes Tillich's concepts from those of many other thinkers, and why should they make any special claim upon our attention? The answer is that in turning “directly to reality" Tillich has attempted to see it and name it in the spirit of a radical Protestantism. He does not sit down before reality like a child; nor does anyone else for that matter. He does not view it with the innocent eye. His apprehensions are decisively preconditioned by the Protestant ethos. What he sees with his own eyes and names with his own words--the concrete, dynamic, tensional, and tragic qualities, the intimate and the ultimate qualities of experience--he associates with a Prot- estant interpretation of the nature and meaning of life. In turn- ing directly to reality he wishes to test, and haply to confira, the validity of Protestant principles as he understands them. Hence there is in his method, as in all critical methods, a constant in- terplay between reality as inmediately experienced and reality as interpreted by historically inherited and tentatively held prin- ciples. Indeed, the tentative character of his approach aims to exhibit something of the spirit of science. Emerson once lamented that it was not possible for him to utter twenty-four sentences simultaneously. Anyone attempting to give an exposition of Tillich's thought might make the same lament. His philosophy is in its entirety extensive in range and his vocab- ulary is one that, because of its novelty and obscurity, demands close attention if it 1s to be understood. Hach of his concepts is related to all of the others. 15 16 Hence if we should immediately undertake a comprehensive exposition of his thought, the first part of the exposition would not achieve its full meaning until the end. In order to assist the reader to appreciate the meaning and significance of the mat- ters to be treated as the exposition unfolds, we shall therefore, at the risk of repetitiousness and oversimplification, first list and define briefly his major concepts. Then later on, we shall examine these concepts in greater detail as occasion demands. Prominent among these concepts is the idea that we have already mentioned, an idea that runs through all of Tillich's life and thought, namely, the concept of the Present. This emphasis corresponds to his conviction that Protestantism should in both its protest and its positive realizations be concrete and contem- poraneous. It corresponds also to his conviction that the exis- tential element in philosophy involves not only the individual but also the total social situation. Thus religious knowledge includes Imowledge of the present. Protestant protest and realization are protest and realization in the present. Only through concern with the present can concern with the future lead to fulfilment. With- out this concern for the present, irrelevance, disillusionment, futility, and even self-destruction ensue. With it, the ultimate seriousness of a divinely sponsored adventure appears. Hence re- form of any kind, whether it be in theology, in liturgy, in reli- gious education, or in social action, must keep its eye on the present total situation if it is worthy of being taken seriously as possessing positive significance. Reform that aims merely to restore lost or forgotten treasures of the past is bound to lose contact with the present. Neither Protestant protest nor Prote: tant realization finds relevant expression in antiquarian restora- tion, for the demand of history is that of "transforming the past into the future." The demand is that we allow our past and our present to be grasped by and imbued with the creative and re-crea- tive power which has worked hitherto and which awaits new reception or release. The Christian gospel is not a gospel proclaiming merely good advice; it is a gospel of good news. "The kingdom of heaven is at hand," it is coming, it is drawing near. But even conceptions so powerful as those of the New Testa- lin order to assist the reader in identifying the major con- cepts here discussed, key words will be underlined. 1 ment may also degenerate into mere antiquarian fossils; or, to use the figure of Schleiermacher, they may become a monument showing that "a great spirit was once there but is there no longer." One of the paths leading to this sort of impotence is that of abstrac- tionism, Abstractions are indispensable if man is to grasp clearly his situation, but abstractions can deprive him of a vital relation to the contemporary. Like Hartmann, Tillich believes that they may substitute static forms for creative thought (dynamisches Schopfung- denken). They can serve as a path of escape from reality. A spe- clalized and isolated concern with abstractions may prevent one from taking time and history seriously. By its ascetic attitude toward the concrete present, this specialized concern with abstrac- tions virtually spatializes the ultimately meaningful by sending it into exile. It 4s, as Schopenhawrwould put it, a way of giving the polite congé to God. This attitude assumes a great variety of forms. It may take the form of identifying religion with mystical experience above time and space; here the desire for unity leads away fron the present and the concrete, the present becomes a vale of illusion. It may take the form of undue regard for abstract philosophic contemplation; again the present is missed and concern with essences (as, e.g., in Husserlian phenomenology) rather than with existence predominates. Or it may take the form of a prefer- ence for the "purely spiritual" religion that wishes to avoid con- troversy concerning "materialistic," this-worldly things; here we have a capital instance of spatialization, the limiting of the re- ligious to one sphere, an abstract sphere of "spirit." This type of spatialization 1s a part of the progeny of the old dichotomy that divorces the secular from the sacred. Or again, it may take the form of devotion to a "Word of God" that relates man only to the past or to the "wholly Other." None of these forms of spatial- ization helps transform the past into a more meaningful future; in their avowed aloofness from the present they only offer a covert way of permitting the rest of the world to go by and of going com- fortably along with it. Indeed, certain of these forms of non- contemporaneity are accompanied by a very practical and un-abstract trafficking with the contemporary. Tillich's strictures against abstractionism are by no means confined to the mysticism that "communes with God" merely by mani- curing the soul, nor to ivory-tower intellectualism and spiritual- istic liberalism. In coming to terms with "the present" European 18 Protestantism, he has confronted Barthianism, and in so far as it involves an abstractionist escape from reality and a subterranean support of the social status quo, he has decisively rejected it. "The repudiation of ethics by dialectical theology," he says, "is the consequence of the view that the universal 1s necessarily ab- stract and non-contemporary."! ‘This deficiency in Barthianism is, he believes, due partially to the large influence of Kantianisn upon it. Kant's categorical imperative is abstract and un-timely, and it gives little direct stimulus to face the concrete present. Speaking of the social implications of Barth's love for the non- contemporary, Tillich has again and again pointed out the disas- trous consequences of Barthian "neutrality" with respect to immedi- ate social and political issues. He says: Karl Barth's pessimistic supernaturalism helped to destroy the Religious-Socialist attempts in pre-Hitler Germany to stop Nazism by creating a better social order on the basis of Chris- tian principles. And even when Barth became a fanatical anti- Nazi he showed in his letter to the British Christians that it was not the common fight of people of all religions and creeds against the National-Socialist distortion of humanity that in- terested him, but the defense of the Church as the finger pointing only to heaven and not to earth... . He, like all pessimistic supra-naturalists, 1s not interested in history,as such nor in social transformation for the sake of humanity.? We see what a distance there is between Tillich and the outlooks just characterized whei we read, "The task of Protestantism is at any given time set by the immediate present; and here ‘the present! is viewed as the central concept that integrates all the tensions characteristic of a certain epoch."> But if Protestantien is to fulfil its proper task at any given time it must in an ultimate sense penetrate "the present" not merely as a concept but also as a reality. It must penetrate the concrete present. It must be practical in the sense that it must deal with the present as 1t concerns us in the very depth of our being. But the word "practical" should not be interpreted as "“anti-theoretical." Since the influence of Ritschl has been such as to give the word "practical" this anti-theoretical connotation Rel» Verw., p. 78. 2unrends in Religious Thought That Affect Social Outlook," in Religion and the World Order, ed. F. Ernest Johnson (New York: Harper and Brothers, 1944), pp. 24-25. Rel. Verw., p. 54. 19 it is better to use Kierkegaard's word “existential.” "Existential is what characterizes our real existence in ell its concreteness, in all its accidental elements, in its freedom and separation from its true and essential meaning." Always for Tillich religious concern must be a concern about the meaning of life for us in our total existence. The spec- tator attitude 1s not areligious attitude. Our whole being, in mind and body and spirit, in external relations as well as in the inner life, must be brought face to face with the threat and the support of existence. The fact that Barth, through his supernatu- ralism and his static confessionaliom, has set himself against every theology of existence and its shaping, is for Tillich "the most painful and downright disastrous event in recent Protestant theology."* Henee Protestantism must come to terms with the char- acteristic cultural realities of the time, with the arts and the pedagogy, with the sciences, with the social and economic and po- litical institutions and trends. Only in and through these con- crete manifestations can it make contact with the present and only through these concrete manifestations can it penetrate in an ulti- mate sense the characteristic spirit of the age. When it has done this, it may be able to see not only the way in which it is itself entangled in the age but also what manner of protest and realiza- tion it must attempt in order to transform the past into the future; and withal, it may also be able to discover the secular forces of protest and realization with which 1t may in some way join its ef- forts. It may be able to understand the union of the present with what has gone before, its affirmations and denials of the past, its creative forces pregnant with the future; and most important of all, it may be prepared to discern within and beyond this growth and decay the unconditioned meaning and depth of past, present, and future.® In other words, it may be able to see how "the uncondi- tionally powerful breaks in, revealing itself in the present, in Philosophy and Theology," Religion in Life, X (1941), 8 Here we should observe Tillich's characteristically "existential" preoccupation with the concrete as it affects even his Begriffs- bildung. This concern of Tillich's is one of the reasons for his Gissatisfaction with phenomenology. ?Rel. Verw., pp. 20=21. She Religious Situation, trans, H. Richard Niebuhr (New York, 1088} pEe i? 20 the power of being which appears in the here and now."? (Some of the expressions just quoted we shall deal with later.) This con- corn of Tillich with the concrete present must be remembered as we continue our survey of the central concepts by means of which he approaches reality and by which he approaches the age. Otherwise, the exposition of the concepts will itself seem to be merely an- other illustration of the escape from contemporaneity into abstrac- tions. Since this concept of the present and its connection with the existential attitude is so fundamental for Tillich's outlook 1t may be well to indicate here the intellectual ancestry of these ideas. Kierkegaard is, of course, the principal ancestor of con- temporary existential philosophy, and especially significant is his resistance to Hegel's abstract logiem and his love of the complete system. But Kierkegaard's principal concern was with the individ- ual's "existential" confrontation with ultimate reality. Tillich shares this concern, but he is also interested in other metaphysi- eal aspects of the reaction against Hegel and in the social aspects of the reaction against Hegelianiem. The metaphysical aspect of this reaction is to be seen in his great interest in Schelling's overcoming of idealism in the direction of realism--the replacement of a negative philosophy of mere possibilities by a positive phi- losophy--as well as in Schelling's qualification of a philosophy of identity in terms of a self-seeking, self-isolating freedom is- suing in the consciousness of guilt. (Tillich's first two disser- tations dealt with Schelling.) Schopenhauer's analysis of the in- dividual life process represents for Tillich also a reaction against Hegelian logism and an anticipation of the interpretation of exist- ence as life (in the later Lebensphilosophie). The social aspects of the reaction against Hegelianism may be symbolized by the names of Feuerbach and Marx. "“Feuerbach's materialism," he says, "is an- other expression of the emphasis on existence--a word used by him against Hegol."* But Marx goes even further in his reaction against Hegel, in effect transferring the Kierkegaardian concern with in- ward tensions of the individual to a concern with the outward ten- sions of social process. Accordingly, with Tillich the interest in the present is combined with the existential outlook through a 4Rel. Verw., p. 81. "Kierkegaard in English," The American-Scandinavian Re~ Niew, XxX (1942), 256. a1 passionate concern with the total social situation in its present erisis. Tillich believes that despite the vaunted claims of Ameri- can empiricism and positivism to provide as it were a corrective to Hegelian abatractionism, these "characteristically American" philosophies in their turn need also the correction of a genuine existentialism that takes individual “ultimate concern" and social actualities seriously. This aspect of Tillich's emphasis on Ex- istenz and the Present has such a direct bearing upon his attitude toward Anglo-American thought, that we should quote at length Til- lich's views on the latter: Although the empiristic and positivistic trend of the Anglo- Saxon mind has prevented the domination of a speculative sys- tem, the question of existential and objective truth is by no means solved by them. American theology still . . . . confuses systems of ethical abstractions or metaphysical possibilities with the ethical and religious existence before God. It has not yet accepted existential materialism as the great correc- tive to the Christian-bourgeois idealism. And contemporary philosophy has either--as logical positivism--extinguished every trace of existential passion and interest within philo- sophical thought--or it has--as metaphysical naturalism--re- moved the individual "existenting" man who stands between the infinite and the finite and never can be understood as a part of the whole of natural objectivity. And even pragmatism which is more closely related to existential thinking than the two other groups--because it acknowledges the fragmentary and dy- namic character of truth--has surrendered itself as 'instrumen- talism! to the objective process of nature and society, produc- ing means for ends which are finite and, consequently, not a matter of infinite, passionate concern. This paragraph introduces ideas that are not directly germane to our discussion at this point, ideas that will have to be dealt with later, but the context and implications of Tillichts concern with Existenz and the Present are brought sharply into relief by the whole passage. If the concept of "the present" is the central concept that integrates the tensions characteristic of an epoch, the concept of decision is the idea that integrates the tensions of an individual or a group as it confronts the present. The manner in which the gor an extensive survey of the main stages and themes in the development of existential philosophy, see Tillich's essay, “Existential Philosophy," Journal of the History of Ideas, V (1944), 44-70. 2nKsorkegaard in English," The American-Scandinavian Re- view, 1K (1942), 256-57. ee 22 past 1s transformed into the future depends upon the kind of deci- sion with which man meets the present. And if that decision is to take time by the forelock it must be daring decision, for there are in this world no guarantees of success in man's rendezvous with time. "The act of daring is an act that pushes ahead into the un- certain, an act that renounces securities and risks secure posses- sions." This leap into the uncertain future is unavoidable. The difference between men appears when they make decision. “There are those who dare really, who aim the bow sharply and shoot the arrow of their deed into dark distances; and there are those who aim too short, in the secret hope of being able to remain on the firm ground of the secure path."* To be sure, man faces always the pos- sibility of going amiss; and he has a sense of guilt when he does go amiss. Yet the very possibility of making daring decision be- longs to man alone. No other creature can miss the mark through the violation of universal norms. Existence is given to other creatures immediately, but man is not something merely identical with his inmediate existence. The very fact that in man existence rises above itself is the occasion for peril and opportunity. It is the ground for what Pascal calls the misery and the greatness of man. And it is the ground for decision. Let us examine more closely the nature of decision. In his immediate existence man is in a state of cleavage. That he is in this state of cleavage or of inner contradiction, is shown by two things.® First, every man raises a question about his existence. He asks: Is it true existence? In doing so, he implies that he does not possess the thing he raises the question about. Moreover, by raising the question he shows that he is in some fashion free from existence. On the other hand, in seeking an answer to the question, he can miss getting the answer. And whatever answer he gets, he will remain in a state of cleavage. This suggests the second consideration. Every man makes a demand upon existence. In making this demand, the presupposition is that the thing demanded Inppedigt zum Semesterschluss vor der Theologenschaft der Universitat Marburg," Neuwerk, VIII (1927), 469. 2rpid., p. 470. 3me following analysis of decision end its relation to "the present" is based primarily upon the article, "Gegenwart und Religion," Neuwerk, XI (1929), 2-11, and upon Rel. Verw., chap. 1. 23 1s not present: there exists a contradiction between existence as it 1s and as it should be. In man life rises above itself, the immediacy of the life-process is broken through the fact that free- dom enters on the stage. Ina sense, man is unfree in possessing freedom, for to rise above the imuediacy of existence ia to lose it; and he cannot regain it. Any attempt to return to the mere life-process 1s an attempt which contradicts the fate of man. He cannot return to the subhuman level. By way of summary then: Man must raise the question as to the character of true existence, and he must make a demand. "He cannot escape this fate, the fate of being man. If he did not wish to raise a question, his not doing it would itself be an answer to a question. If he did not choose to make a demand, his not making it would be obedience to a demand. Man always acts even when inaction is the burden of his action." He must dare to make decisions, and this necessity brings anxiety, the anxiety that may pervert his freedom. We must turn then to a description of man's freedom and of his perversion of that freedom. Man is a living subject, "a Gestalt, a totality of inter- dependent relations in which no part can be isolated as long as the living process goes on."* Within himself he is the dynamic unity of reason ana power, of intellectual universality and vital indi- viduality. On the other hand, he "has a world which is at once unitary and infinite," a world "set over against himself, from which he is separated and to which he belongs at the same time... . Being between himself and his world, man 1s free from both of them even while he is bound to both of them."> In the relations between this living subject, thie Gestalt, and its world, there are various levels and degrees of freedom. Man can transcend any given situation; and thus he can imagine and realize something new. He has the moral freedom to transcend him- self "in the direction of complete unity of universality and indi- viduality." This 1s the freedom "to receive unconditional demands," and 4t 1s a freedom fraught with high seriousness. He has cultural tRel. Verw., p. 52. 2nmme Conception of Man in Existential Philosophy," Jour- nal of Religion, XIX (1959), 202. Cf. also Rel. Verw., p. 168. Ste Conception of Man in Existential Philosophy," op. cits, p. 205. 24 freedom, the freedom to create with purpose, to represent the world and himself with symbols. And he has freedom from his own freedom, the freedom to play. This freedom is the "playful" counterpart of the seriousness of moral freedom. But man's power of self-determination is not unlimited. "The new which 1s created by man is dependent on the given which he finds--on himself as well as on his world. Man does not exist by himself alone nor does his world."? Although he possesses a freedom from himself and his world, he participates in the primary creativity on which both he and his world depend. When he uses his freedom to act against freedom, he decides against his essential nature, and thus he perverts his freedom into servitude, it is transformed and becomes tragic and sinful. “Freedom can maintain itself only in so far as it chooses the content, the norms, and the values in which our essential nature, including our freedom, ex- presses itself."* The possibility of the surrender of freedom rises not out of necessity but out of the freedom to forget that one is finite. Nor 4s 1t the result of reversion to the animal level; it comes from "stepping too high." This is the tragic perversion of freedom, the attempt of man to make his finiteness infinite. "The individ- ual thinking to make himself universal instead of subjecting him- self to the universal is the tragic Andividual."> This tragic servitude to the infinite desires of the self often has actually the opposite effect from that intended: it sepa~ rates the self from "the infinity of universality," and it leads to the destruction of the self and its world. Thus man is brought into the realm of necessity, a necessity that 1s both transcendent and immanent. It would be wrong, however, to suppose that neces- sity operates only after the perversion of freedom. Necessity is present even in the exercise of freedom, for man lives in history, and the forms and limits of freedom are partially determined by the human past, by material factors, and by the social environment. The creature that ie free stands under the fate of unfreedom. Nev- ertheless, his freedom remains undestroyed. The creativity is al- ways primary, for everything depends upon it. This is true even though the outcome of tragic servitude is a destructive one. In= deed, the destructive tendency may itself prepare the way for new apia., p. 209. *rpta., p. 208. *rp4a., p. 210. 25 creation. The possibilities of the perversion of freedom exist on all levels of freedom, and no change in the social environment can secure man against the realization of these possibilities. Only the complete loss of freedom can do that. For this reason human freedom will always be human peril. The ability to transcend any given situation implies the possibility of losing one's self in the infinity of transcend- ing one's self. Technical freedom may become technical servi- tude if the means become ends in themselves. Moral freedom may become moral servitude if the individual self, in order to preserve itself, resists the demand coming from the other and loses personality and community. Cultural freedom can become cultural servitude if it finds expression in the will to power or the will to draw the totality of one's world into the lim- itations of one's individual self. Freedom to play may become the surrender of,one's own freedom, thus wasting one's self and one's world. Just because human freedom 1s human peril, man character- lstically suffers anxiety, the anxiety of "not actualizing all pos- sibilities and the anxiety of leaping from possibility into actu- ality. Man 4s afraid not to use this freedom and yet he is afraid to use it." This anxiety gives rise to temptation, which appears on all levels of freedom. Here again decision, and daring decision, is demanded. The human situation with respect to freedom and necessity can be described also in terms of freedom and fate. Freedom is al- ways entangled in fate. Fate involves three things. First, it is related to freedom: where there is no freedom there is no fate, and where there is no fate there 1s no freedom. A merely physical ob- Ject that is conditioned in all ways, is entirely without fate be- cause it is wholly bound to necessity. On the other hand, anyone whose freedom is absolute, whose freedom is not jeopardized by an ever intruding necessity, has no fate. Secondly, every free being is entangled in fate: no being has unconditional power over itself; and when it acts as though it did have it, it is driven by inex- haustible desire from one illusion to another until it encounters resistance and penalty. Thirdly, freedom and fate do not appear separately and by alternation, but rather they interpenetrate each other in every event: every man's character and every civilization's character is the result of creative freedom but it 1s also "condi- tioned by events that in their origin go back to past generations, Typia., p. 208. 26 back to much earlier manifestations of the continuing and living fabric of humanity." Thus it is, as we have already indicated, conditioned by national, economic, and geographic factors, and also by unconscious vitalities and tensions. These factors always af- fect philosophy and theology as well as other human endeavors. Man is thrown into existence at a particular time and place in uni- ty with all other beings. Yet he feels himself responsible for his existence in the context of his unity with and differentiation from all other beings. Hence human existence is always comprised of both the fated (or given) fact and the responsible act; freedom and necessity, fate and guilt presuppose each other and they cannot be separated.+ In the teeth of this tension or polarity between freedom and fate, between fate and guilt, between spirituality and vitality, between reason and the will to power and pleasure, man must make decision, But, as Tillich understands it, decision is not merely decision between surface alternatives of existence. It possesses a dimension of depth. To speak of depth, of the depths, of the ground, the abyss, is for Tillich highly characteristic. Instead of looking up and away from reality he prefers to look down through it. In his view the metaphors of height, so widely familiar in religious usage, are today unconvincing. They suggest what Henry Churchill King used to call "the seeming unreality of the spiritual life." This seeming unreality attaches to any religion that makes a business of looking to the heights and of averting the eye from the ground and abyss underneath. Although depth is a dimension of space, it 1s employed as a symbol for a spiritual quality.” Like most of our religious sym- bols, it reminds us of our finitude and our bondage to things that are visible. We are and we remain sense-beings even when we deal with things spiritual. But in religious usage, the word has also Jmnis paragraph 1s based upon the formulations set forth in "Philosophie und Schicksal," KantStudien, XXXIV (1929), 502 ff., and also upon certain theses in the mimeographed outlines of "Sys- tematic Theology," Third Part, a preliminary draft for the private use of students only. 2mne following paragraphs are based primarily on the ar- ticle, "Depth," Christendom, IX (Summer, 1944), 317-25. Many of the phrases used are Tillich's. As with the theosophical writers upon whom Tillich depends, "depth" is not tobe interpreted in a spatial sense. It symbolizes rather, the inmost character of real- ity. 27 another connotation, as is suggested by the familiar texts: "The Spirit searcheth all things, even the deep things of Gode. . . « Out of the depth have I cried unto thee, 0 God." There are two meanings of "depth" when considered in the religious sense. It is either the opposite of shallow, or it is the opposite of high. "Truth is deep and not shallow. Suffering is depth and not height. Both are deep, the light of truth and the darkness of suffering. There is depth in God and there is a depth out of which the psalmist cried to God." We think of truth as deep and we think of suffering as deep. We use the same spatial symbol for both of them, because the search for truth and the experiences of disappointment and suffering drive us to dig deeper than the surface of things. Science makes its great contributions when it penetrates the surfaces. This penetration into the depth of things has let loose earthquakes in the history of science; as, for example, when Copernicus questioned the appearance that the sun revolves around a stationary earth or when Einstein questioned the assumption that there is an absolute point from which the observer can look at the motion of things. The early Greek philosophers likewise penetrated beneath the surfaces when they questioned "being" itself, asking why "there is something and not nothing." “Depth psychology" has led us from the surfaces of con- sciousness into the subconscious depths. Here again an earthquake has ensued, and men have not yet been able to regain equilibrium, for, deep as these probings have been, "depth psychology" cannot alone strike a supporting depth. "It can help us to find the way into our depth, although it can not give the final help because it cannot guide into the deepest ground of our being and of all being, the depth of life itself." All of these questionings have been daring ventures. And so must our questionings be if we wish to penetrate beneath the surface of ourselves and of the opinions we take for granted. This is a painful process. Usually we prefer to wait and let the depths erupt beneath us. We are not prone to search in the depths unless an earthquake brings us disillusion concerning the surfaces. Then self-Imowledge is itself shaken and disrupted. The only substitute for an earthquake is that we travel steadily and voluntarily the road into the depth of being and into the depth of our own being. This 1s a hard road. 28 But we have to penetrate to the depths not only of self and being. Depth must be seen in "the present." There are depths in the common life, there is a depth in history. Here again earth- quakes occur when men look beneath the surface. Marx let loose an earthquake in social life and thought when he questioned whether there is an intellectual and moral history independent of its eco- nomic and social basis. A sociology of depth arose, showing us the support and especially the eruption from below. But earth- quakes are necessary in the social life also before most of us can see the depths. In history we live as much on the surface as we do in our individual lives. The noise of shallow waters prevents us from listening to the sounds out of the depth, to the sounds of what really happens at the base of our social structure, in the longing hunger and oppression of the masses. "We have believed that we were living in a period of unavoidable progress to greater humanity. But in the depth of our social structure the forces of destruction have already gathered strength." We have become weak in our strength; the improved means and tools of life have been turned into the means and tools of self-destruction. Therefore, within the community a rebellion against the surface has started. An earthquake is now upon us. Yet many people still want to return to the "normalcy" of the old surfaces. They want to escape from the depth of the present into the shelter of an illusory security. It 1s natural that men should shun the depths. In the depths of being and history they find a threat to human existence and to accepted values. They find suffering there. In these depths we discover not only the depth of emptiness, as Thomas Muenzer called it, or the depth of humanity, as Marx called it. We find also the chthonic depths, the depth which in religious lan- guage is often called the dwelling place of the evil forces, of the demonic powers, of death and hell. It is through these depths that men must go if they are to find the depth of truth and of be- ing. The German people have been "possessed" by these morbid and destructive depths. They are the prime example in modern history of a people that did not know how to plumb to the depths that would lead, through suffering, to hope and joy; they did not know how to plumb through the surfaces of nationality into the creative depths. TAllich raises the question as to why the German people were thus caught by the evil, the demonic depths of destruction. His 29 answer to the question should be quoted at length, for it bears not only upon the contemporary "German probleu" but also upon the contemporary religious problem (and the problem of language) with which he is concerned. In answering the question, he reminds us of a beautiful ancient myth: When the soul leaves the body it has to traverse many spheres where demonic forces rule. And only the soul which knows the right and powerful word can continue its way to the ultimate depth of the divine ground. No soul can avoid these tests. If we look at the struggle of the saints of all times, of the prophets and reformers, of the great creators in all realms, We recognize that the myth tells the truth. Bverybody has to face the deep things in life. Danger is no excuse. He has to conquer the danger. He has to know the liberating word. The German people and many people in all nations have not known this word, and so they were caught by the evil forces of the depth and missed the ultimate, saving depth. Nowhere in Tillich's writings do we find a more illuminating dis- cussion of the relation between the Word and the penetration into the depths of the human condition. Here we find expressed the great significance of the task of discovering "the dearest fresh~ ness deep down things" and of naming the saving word that pulsates with the powerfulness of the depths. ‘This significance resides in the fact that willy-nilly our every pattern of decision possesses a dimension of depth. Decision involves not merely a choice between surface alternatives. To be sure, it may be made with reference to surfaces alone, but those surfaces only thinly conceal the supporting and disrupting powers, the ground and abyss of the depths. The disrupting powers have be- come a darkness visible in the convulsions of the twentieth century, as they break open the surfaces. Fate and decision have wrought Us woe, Today we see the disruptive depths of decision not only in the German parade of death down into the demonic depths. All over the planet modern capitalism, nationalism, and racism have been taking the same path. These depths are the abyss of destruc- tion. But those who know the depth of what has happened should not rest on this level where all seems hopeless. Here there is danger of despair and cynicism. We must needs dig deeper. We must dig into the ground of our historical life to the ultimate depth of history, to the depth of the supporting creative powers. This Tipia., p. 323. 30 depth Tillich calls "the infinite and inexhaustible ground of being." This is the depth that is the ground of hope. It is the dynamic source of all creative decision, The way to it leads beyond woe to joy, for the end of the way to the depth is joy. Nietzsche, the depth philosopher, knew this even though he was "a man who in his passionate striving for the depth was caught by destructive forces and did not know the word to conquer them." Nietzsche, the philos- opher of joyous suffering, glimpsed the deepest depth, the dearest freshness deep down things, when he wrote: "The world is deep, and deeper than the day could read. Deep is its woe. Joy deeper still than grief can be. Woe says: Hence, Gol But joys all want eternity. Want deep, profound eternity." Commenting on these words Tillich says: This 1s the message of all religions: the Kingdom of God is peace and joy. This is the message of Christianity... . But eternal joy is not to be reached by living on the surface. It is reached by breaking through the surface, by penetrating into the deep things of ourselves, our world, and God. At every moment in which we reach the last depth of our lives we can experience the joy that has eternity in it, the hope which cannot be destroyed and the truth on which life and the world are built. We see, then, that we find in the depths of being and his- tory not only the threat to human existence and to human values. We find not only suffering there; we find also the purifying fire through which we pass in order to reach the depth of truth. Til- lich is, then, a philosopher of tragedy, but he ie also a philoso- pher of joy; and for him the "deeper" of these is joy. This fact must be borne in mind when Tillich speaks of the creative and de- structive depths as the infinite and inexhaustible ground and abyss of all being. We see now what is meant by the assertion that decision possesses a dimension of depth. It means that true decision pos- sesses the depth of a spiritual attitude orientated to the ultimate, the infinite and inexhaustible ground and abyss, the dynamically supporting and threatening Apeiron.” The perversion of freedom ‘ipia., p. 525. 2y— use the word of Anaximander here in order to bring into relief both the infinitely creative and the tragically destructive aspects of T4llich's conception of ground and abyss, the absolute Something and the sbsolute Nothing. "Abyss" carries a double con- notation: inexhaustible, restless, positive dynamic and threatening, disruptive dynamic. These connotations are given poetic expression in Tilifch's essay on "Water," appended at the end of this chapter. 31 ensues when decision involves only decision for the infinity of one's own desire; when vital power is made to predominate over rational mutuality; when man attempts to place himself at the depth or the center of being rather than relate himself to 1t; when man, who is dependent upon the primal "given" creativity of being, sets up his own creaturely and conditioned character as unconditioned. It appears, in short, when he tries to make his own finiteness in- finite. This is to court disaster in the jaws of the abyss, it is to incur the wrath of the abyss, to invite demonic possession. Thus the depth dimension of decision may be the tragic dimension. But that is not all, for there is an alternative. It is decision in the true dimension of depth, decision for the Unconditioned. This brings us to the central concept of Tillich's philos- ophy of religion, a concept which also bears upon his whole social philosophy and his interpretation of Protestantism. But before turning to the consideration of this difficult concept, a further word should be said concerning the idea of depth as it appears in Tillich's life and thought. Some further consideration must also be given to the setting in which the concept of" the Unconditioned” appears. It 1s reported by Tillich's colleagues that one of his fa~ vorite retreats has always been a seat on the rocks above the edge of the ocean. No doubt, the reason for this attraction is, so to speak, philosophical. For him the ocean possesses a metaphysical frisson. Here in the waves can be seen the motion of the depths disturbing the face of the waters. Here is the symbol of the in- finite bordering on the finite and of the infinite depths touching the finite surfaces. In Tillich's own autobiographical sketch, these and other aspects of the dimension of depth are referred to in a felicitous, Personal way. After mentioning his early love of nature, of “great memories and strong longings interlaced with landscapes, with the soil and the weather, with corn fields and the smell of autumnal potato foliage, with the forms of clouds, with wind, flowers, and woods," he writes Most important, however, was the fact that from my eighth year onward annually I spent some weeks, later even months, by the seaside. The experience of the infinite bordering upon the finite, as one has it by the sea, responded to my tendency toward the border and supplied my imagination with a symbol from which feeling could win substance and thinking productiv- ity. It 1s likely that my development of the theory of the 32 human border-situation in Religiése Verwirklichung ("Religious Realization") and tts more anthropological formulation in lec- tures at Yale University, might not have turned out as it did without that experience of nature. But there is also another element in the contemplation of the sea: the dynamic, the ag- gression upon the land in its tranquil finiteness, the ecstatic quality of gales and waves. Thus the theory of the "Dynamic Mass" in my essay 'Masse und Geist’ ("The Mass and the Spirit") was conceived under the immediate impression of the agitated sea. Also for the doctrine of the Unconditioned as both ground and abyss of dynamic truth, and of the religious essence as the eruption of the eternal into finiteness, the sea supplied the imaginative element needed for these thoughts. It was Nietzsche who said that no idea could be true unless it was thought in the open air. Obedient to the saying, many of my ideas have been conceived in the open and even mich of my writing has been done among trees or on the seaside.) In this passage certain of the motifs we have already dis- cussed are evident, but here the dynamic, tensional character of Tillich's life and thought is especially brought to the fore through his use of the concept of the border. In his autobiograph- i1eal sketch Tillich speaks of living on the boundary between vari- ous possibilities of existence.” Now the notion of the border- situation is given a different turn, a "deeper" metaphysical inter- pretation, and it is related to the central Tillichian concept of the Unconditioned. Before giving even a general definition of these concepts we should make note of their bearing on two corresponding problems of philosophy and religion, namely, the problems posed on the one hand by ecclesiastical or political absolutism and on the other by historical and ethical relativism. Our exposition will seem to "take the longest way home," but it is only by this way that we can see the problem situation out of which the concepts emerge. Martin Luther once said that humanity is like a drunken sailor riding horseback. At one moment the sailor jogs up and comes linterpretation of History, pp. 7-8. Since a number of the themes of the present discussion are imaginatively expressed in it, the author's "meditation" on water is appended at the end of the chapter. This "meditation" shows that the references to water in the passage quoted above are by no means accidental. Interpretation of History, pp. 3-73. Tillich speaks of his life as being lived on the boundaries between city and coun- try, between social classes, between reality and imagination, theory and practice, heteronomy and autonomy, theology and philoso- phy, church and society, religion and culture, Lutheranism and so- cdalism, idealism and Marxism, home and alien land. 33 down almost falling off the horse on one side; at the next moment he jogs up and comes down almost falling into the mud on the other side. This sort of drunkenness has frequently been displayed in modern times as men have recovered themselves from the tyranny of absolutism only at the next jog of history to fall into the slough of relativism. At the one extreme, men absolutize a particular point of view, endowing it with final validity; at the other they question whether any position has a validity beyond the fact that it satisfies desire. We need not here enter a detailed discussion of the tangled problems suggested by the corollary terms "relative-absolute." It will suffice if we say that Tillich found satisfaction in neither of the main solutions with which he was presented. On the one hand, he saw in the inflated claims of the churches to possess the abso- lute, something as unacceptable as the equally inflated claims of the prevailing economic and political philosophies of "liberal" capitalism. All such boisterous complacency must, in his view, be punctured. In their varying ways they all claimed to have domesti- cated the absolute. In short, they claimed to have salvation firm- ly in their possession. Science, or rather scientism, was itself making similarly self-regarding ordinances. On the other Hand, complete relativism could not be accepted. If it were, all claims to truth or value could only be adjudged as illusory along with the vaunted claims of absolutism. In either case, the meaning of human existence was in question. In the face of this spiritual and philosophical enbarrass- nent, German idealism had ventured a solution, It had claimed that its "system of meaningful categories portrays reality as a whole" and thus provides the next step beyond religion and other mytho- logical fumblings. According to it, reality is the appearance of essence refracted dialectically but fulfilled in cultural synthesis reaching ever greater richness. This optimistic philosophy evi- dently made strong appeal to Tillich in his youth, though the later Schelling's departure from idealism had already impressed him as early as 1910. Tillich came to hold, with Schelling, Kierkegaard, and Marx, that idealism itself represented "a definite and limited relation to reality" and that reality 1s a contradiction of essence. This fact was especially evident in the imminent breakdown of the social system idealism had supported or condoned. Idealistic syn- thesis has no place for real evil and destruction. It sought only 34 the support of existence and ignored the threat, the abyss of being and meaning. Moreover, its subjection of everything to the purely rational form deprived it of a sense of the positive vitality and dynamic of reality. Hence it degenerated into formalism, and its view of the basic meaning of life became a relative, conditioned meaning. Tillich therefore felt the demand for a transcendent mean- dng that would invade and break through the system of pure forms. He came to view the idealistic synthesis as a forn of spatializa- tion of the infinite, as an imprisonment of the infinite in the fi- niteness of a static self-assured understanding which served as a sanction for a crumbling social system. Such a spatialization,he decided, failed to recognize the depth of our being, the infinite and inexhaustible ground and abyss of meaning. It failed also to recognize the socially and historically conditioned character of human thinking. Tillich's concepts of the boundary-situation and of the Unconditioned cannot be understood apart from a recognition of the necessity that lay within him of overcoming the idealistic synthe- sis which provided a comfortable cushion not only for formalistic rationalism but also for those who were terribly at ease in Zion, for those who did not see the guilt of the human condition, for those who found in idealistic metaphysics a divine sanction for ac cepting conservative and decaying bourgeois ethics and for inter- preting evil as merely a dialectical necessity and therefore as good. The reasons for his turning against idealism in these re= spects, are set forth succinctly in the following passage: The catastrophe which idealism had suffered in the nine~ teenth century had been too terrible for any one to invite its recurrence... + It cannot see the true religious situation, the situation of time in the presence of eternity, it seeks to evade the Judgment under which the temporal stands before the eternal. Its forms, to be sure, are open to the reception of living content, it restores to the state and even to logic their primordial and essential holiness, but it rests content then with these sanctified forms; it does not penetrate to the absolutely transcendent, to that which lies beyond even the most sacred form, whether it be called the church or state; it does not see the abyss which opens before every time and every present . . . . War and revolution have revealed depths of re- ality which idealism cannot master. In the light of his view, then, that both absolutism and idealism made unwarranted claims for themselves and ended by becom- Jahe Religious Situation, pp. 43-44. 35 ing illustrations of historical relativism, and in the light of his view that relativism could not be overcome without a more ade- quate apprehension of something standing beyond the relative, we must understand his conceptions of the boundary-situation and of the Unconditioned. ‘he one provides a limiting principle, the other a supporting principle. The two would seem to lead in oppo- site directions. Yet they actually aim at the same goal. "The one is the way of most radical apprehension of the Protestant prin- ciple as a proclamation of the 'human boundary-situation,' the oth- er is that of decided affirmation of the presence of the Uncondi- tioned-Beyond, the ‘speaking! or expression of a 'form of grace.t"> The metaphysical concept of the "human boundary-situation" as the limit of human possibility--in distinction from the idea of the border as a line between contrasting possibilities of exist- ence--has been used by a nunber of other theologians and also by secular philosophers, especially by Kierkegaard, Barth, and Jas- pers. It is also anticipated after a fashion by Nietzsche's idea of the self-surpassing character of human nature. In general, we may say that its use is the trade-mark of existential philosophy and theology. The concept of the Unconditioned, as the ultimate that is presupposed by all meaning, being and value (conditioning and sup- porting them), is a composite concept. In Tillich's usage it draws upon and modifies the ontological and axiological concepts of Greek and modern thought, from Anaximander and Parmenides to Spinoza and Kant, though in its modified form it aims to give expression to the Jewish-Christian idea of the majesty and unspeakable richness of the divine. These concepts of the boundary-situation and of the Uncon- ditioned are proposed as demand and expectation--demand in face of the Eternal, in face of the infinite and inexhaustible ground and abyss of being, and expectation in the sense of anticipating the possible realization of the true meaning of life. The boundary-situation is encountered as an aspect of both this demand and this expectation. On the one hand, man finds sup- port in the human and cosmic situation; on the other, he confronts a threat to meaningful existence. In short, he finds himself sus- Pended over the "depth" of the infinite and inexhaustible ground tRel. Verw., p. 15. 36 and abyss of being. The boundary-situation is the boundary between support and threat. Or as Tillich puts it, "The boundary of human activity is encountered when human possibility reaches its absolute Lmit, when human existence is confronted by unconditional threat + ++ + This border-situation of man is possible because man stands above his mere existence, because he 1s in his immediate existence in a state of cleavage." Thus man, in transcending mere existence, possesses a freedom to say Yes or No to existence. But this very freedom becomes the occasion for a radical threat to his existence. The fate of having to make decision is the profoundest disturbance of our existence. This inescapable freedom is a threat to us be- cause of the consequences that follow from our decisions, especially when these decisions are seen in the pattern of the totality and meaning of the human situation, When his decisions are seen in their relation to this pattern, man knows that he does not fulfil the demand for the right existence, and that he possesses no guar- antee of fulfilment. "Wherever this situation 1s experienced in its unconditioned and inescapable character, the human border-situ- ation 1s encountered. The point at which nothingness threatens us unconditionally, is the boundary line of all human activity, the human boundary-situation."+ Protestantism had its very origin in the proclamation of this boundary-situation, and accordingly it de~ nies security to all human possessions including religion and the church. This recognition of the limit and of the threat which at- tach to religion itself, is a necessary implication of the Reforma- tion doctrine of justification by faith. Men are, then, confronted with the questions: "Where does one find the threat to human existence?” "And where does one find its support?" ‘The major differences between men, that is, between their ultimate orientations, depend upon the differences between kel. Verw., p. 52. For a telling presentation of the un- conditional seriousness of the boundary-situation, see Kierkegaard's parable of the King's coachman in Judge for Yourself, reported by W. Lowrie, Kierkegaard (London: Oxford University Press, 1938), pp. 480 ff. Gompere these typical sentences from Karl Barth: "The ua~ ture and well-balanced man, standing firmly with both feet on the earth, who has never been lamed and broken and half-blinded by the scandal of his life, is as such the existentially godless man" (op. git., p. 235). "The frontier of religion is the line of death which separates flesh from spirit, time from eternity, human possibility from the possibility of God" (op. cit., p. 238). These sentences show Barth's conception of the boundary. As we shall see presently, Tillich does not draw the border line in precisely this way. 37 the answers they give to these questions. TAillich holds that the fate of unfreedom arises out of the opposition between freedom and existence, but that the ultimate support comes from something beyond this opposition. The support depends upon something we do not produce at all; it is the power of being that is the core of all creativity. This primary creativi- ty is expressed even in the threat to human existence. Anything that exists must in some fashion participate in the basic "given" creativity, and anything that completely violates the conditions of creativity will not exist at all. There are two principal forms of expression which threat and support may take, those that aim to be absolutely nothing other than an expression of threat and support, and those indirect forms Which have no explicit sense of ultimate threat and support. The first are religious forms, the second are cultural. This does not mean that religious forms are not a part of the culture. It means rather that the religious forms are by intention religious, and the cultural forms are not so by intention though they are so in actual- ity (or in substance). Every expression is, then, an explicit or tacit expression of the human situation in its ultimate dimension. Now there are sundry and devious methods whereby man at- tempts to conceal from himself the disturbance and the insecurity of all forms, whether religious or cultural. The ambiguous charac~ ter of the human situation "can be covered over or weakened by our relying upon truth that we have already achieved or upon demands already fulfilled, thus evading the unconditioned threat. Tais is @ possibility that 1s always present; and in one way or another all of us try to make this escape." Depth psychologists have revealed the devious processes of rationalization whereby men conceal from themselves their own inse= curity and attempt to compensate by projecting a false security. Depth sociology has disclosed analogous concealments in social life, rationalizations that take the form of ideology, smoke screens that conceal the actual situation of being confronted by demand and threat. One finds similar attempts at concealment in "religion.' Indeed, most religions may be classified according to their modes of concealment. Hence religion may be a deception and a snare. Tillich would agree with the young Barth before he retreated into the concealments of confessionalism, the Barth who said, "Religion, 1Rel. Verw., ps 32. 38 then, so far from dissolving men existentially, so far from rolling them and pressing them against the wall, so far from overwhelming them and transforming them, acts upon them like a drug which has been extremely skilfully administered." At least, he would agree if this Barthian protest against "religion" did not lead to a new form of concealment in supernaturaliem.” Another forn of conceal- ment is to be discerned, as we have seen, in philosophical idealism. Absolute seriousness with respect to the boundary-situation 4s found only where men scorn the possibility of escape, only where men renounce the illusory possibility of escape by submergence in the life-process, in intellectual or cultural activity, in mysti- ciom and asceticism, in strenuous works of piety, in the guarantees of the church, of "sound" doctrine, and of the "Word of God," in the sacraments of the nation, the tribe, or the economic and social system. The modern man believes he has in principle made these re- nunciations. As a matter of fact, however, he has in wide areas of life either explicitly or tacitly renounced the renunciation and has attempted to "escape from freedom" into one or another guaran- teed temporal security. In so far as the modern man takes seriously the border- situation he is able to understand the radical element in Protes- tantism, its doctrine of justification by faith and its prophetic protest. On the other hand, in so far as Protestantism forgets that it stands in the boundery-situation it forfeits its own char- acter and becomes a weakened imitation of Catholicism. As a conse- quence it elicits protest from those in religious and secular groups who are aware of the boundary. In the moment when it no longer holds itself in question, it is brought into question by those who have understood and in some fashion have accepted its original principle. Iparta, op. cit., p. 236. ®comenting on Barth's early assertion that Tillich's struggle against "The Grand Inquisitor" of guaranteed and enforced securities is no longer necessary today, the latter observed in 1935 that "the development of the German confessional Church in the last two years has proved that it is necessary. The Grand Inquis- itor is about to enter the Confessional Church, and strictly speak- ing with a strong but tight-fighting armor of Barthian supranatu- ralism" (Interpretation of History, p. 26). From Tillich's point of view, Berthtanten tse Toma of concealment of the doundary-situ- ation comparable to that provided by Roman Catholicism. 39 But if Protestantism, in recognizing the boundary-situation, only insists upon the ambiguity of all human securities and of all human (and "religious") forms, it serves only to relativize all Imowledge and conduct. Its message becomes only a stentorian "No" to all human endeavor, a proclamation only of the threat to human existence. The doctrine of the majesty of God becomes the basis for a complete devaluation of his creatures. In this fashion the boundary is really dissolved, for one confronts only a No; the Yes to concrete decision is not heard. This sort of interpretation creates a spiritual vacuum so far as active participation in the contemporary life of society and culture is concerned. Barth himself helped to create such a vacuum vy restricting attention to the demand that the church resist the attempt of the National Socialist state to subject 1t to state policy. Only after the advent of World War II and the German inva- sion of Czechoslovakia did he deign to make a political decision; and even then the decision was made only in the name of the church's right to proclaim the Gospel. Into the spiritual vacuum created by this asceticism to con- crete social and political decision the German Christians rushed with their idol of German Christianity. Indeed, Huanuel Hirsch perverted Tillichian doctrine into obedience to "the sovereign of history" speaking through Adolph Hitler. Here again the boundary was dissolved; the German Christian could hear only the Yes. In order to avoid these errors of interpretation the con- cept of the boundary-situation must be understood in relation to the concept of the Unconditioned and its corollaries, the ideas of "the form of grace" and the Kairos. Tillich has nowhere written a systematic essay on the con- cept of the Unconditioned. This is unfortunate, for his many and scattered references to it make for great difficulty in securing @ consistent and synoptic view of it. This difficulty is increased by the fact that Tillich's language is obscure in the extreme and by the fact also that Tillich has not remained consistent in his definitions. Here we shall adumbrate only its main features, bas- ing the synthetic definition upon formulations drawn from various Periods in his developments The concept is variously referred to as the unconditioned transcendent, the unconditionally real, the unconditionally power- ful, the unconditionally personal, the unconditionally perfect, 40 the inaccessible Holy, the Eternal, the unconditional demand, the unconditional meaning, and simply the Unconditioned. In Tillich's view, “it would not be worthwhile to speak at all of the fact that all sorts of things, ideas or feelings or deeds, move out of the past into the future... . if all this were nothing but a moving, a flowing, a becoming and decaying with- out ultimate meaning or final importance." 411 of this is really worthy of serious concern and decision only if something transcends the process of mere becoming, the mere transition from past to fu- ture. There must be something that "supports the times but is not subject to them." The direction of consciousness toward this unconditioned meaning is a necessary function which constitutes the reality of meaning. The prius of every individual apprehension of meaning 1s the unconditioned meaning itself, the prius of every meaning-form is the direction toward the unconditioned form, and the prius of every meaning-content 1s the unconditioned import. It is senseless to ask if there is an unconditioned meaning, for the very question presupposes an ultimate meaning. It is also senseless to ask if the Unconditioned "exists," for if it were something established in the temporal order it would no longer be the Unconditioned; more= over, it would be some object the "existence" of which it would be impossible to prove. The Unconditioned cannot be proved, it can only be demonstrated as the meaning that is the foundation of all meaning- fulfilment.” The above formulations appear relatively early in Tillich's writings (1923). Almost twenty years later, he says that direction toward the Unconditioned is a matter of decision and faith, of ori- entating ourselves to a creative reality, a transcendent order which informs but which also contradicts the order to which we belong. It involves receiving this transcendent reality as a gift, an un~ conditional power that grasps us and gives to the passing fact and decision an unconditional seriousness and meening.® It confronts lane Religious Situation, p. 7 2pes System der Wissenschaften (Gottingen: Vandenhoeck und Ruprecht, 1983), p. 130. The unconditioned meaning should not be interpreted as being some ethereal or purely spiritual thing. As will be indicated later, it is inherent in the nature of being to strive for meaning-fulfilment. Hence the term "meaning" involves something ontological as well as axiological. SuiPaith! in the Jewish-Christian tradition," Christendom, VII (1942), 525-26. 41 us as the depth of our life, as the source of our being, as our ultimate concern. We take it seriously and without reservation. Only the person who can in complete seriousness say that there is nothing to be taken seriously and without reservation is lacking in faith; only such a person is a real atheist. And anyone who at= tempts to take seriously the mere surface appearances possesses no prineiple of selection; if he possesses a principle of selection he has already questioned the surfaces and is started on the path into the depths. In the path leading to the depths one will, as we have seen, be driven either to the demonic depths and their threat or to the deeper depth--the infinite and inexhaustible ground and abyss. The person who has been grasped by the experience of the unconditioned meaning of life is a man of faith, whether he calls himself atheist or not. And conversely, the person who has not known this depth of life is an atheist, whether he calls him- self theist or not. It must not be supposed that religion is “the only phenomenon which bears witness to the ultimate." "In some periods it is not even the most important of the witnesses or the most effective in expression and symbolism." In every time there is something within it which drives it beyond itself to a re- ality, a meaning that lies beneath all time and all existent forms. In every time there is also a taking of the unconditioned meaning up (paradoxically) into the forms of time. "That which is not ex- istential form becomes an existing form." There are therefore with- in every time two tendencies moving in opposite directions, the one toward that which is not in time but beyond it and beneath it; the other a tendency to give a name and a local habitation to this depth which is beneath time. We find self-transcendence in every time, openness to the eter- nal, a hallowing of time; but upon the other hand we see the appropriation of the eternal, the self-sufficiency of time, the secularization of the holy. There 1s a movement to and fro be~ tween self-transcendence and self-sufficiency, between the de- sire to be a mere vessel and the desire to be the content, be- tween turning toward the eternal and the turning towards the self. In this action and reaction we discern the religious situation of every present at its profoundest level.® Hence in a general sense we may say that every period has an uncon- scious, self-evident faith which lies at a deeper level than the apparent antithesis of belief and unbelief both of which arise out line Religious Situation, p. 9. "Zbid., p. 11.

Вам также может понравиться