Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 14

JOURNAL OF VERBAL LEARNING AND VERBAL BEHAVIOR 11, 671-684 (1972)

Levels of Processing: A Framework for Memory Research 1

FERGUS I. M. CRAIK AND ROBERT S. LOCKHART


University of Toronto, Toronto 181, Ontario, Canada

This paper briefly reviewsthe evidence for multistore theories of memory and points out
some difficultieswith the approach. An alternative framework for human memory research
is then outlined in terms of depth or levels of processing. Some current data and arguments
are reexamined in the light of this alternative framework and implications for further
research considered.

Over the past decade, models of human store models, (b) question their adequacy, and
memory have been dominated by the concept (c) propose an alternative framework in terms
of stores and the transfer of information of levels of processing. We will argue that the
among them. One major criterion for distin- memory trace can be understood as a by-
guishing between stores has been their different product of perceptual analysis and that trace
retention characteristics. The temporal pro- persistence is a positive function of the depth
perties of stored information have, thus, to which the stimulus has been analyzed.
played a dual role: Besides constituting the Stimuli may also be retained over short inter-
basic phenomenon to be explained, they have vals by continued processing at a constant
also been used to generate the theoretical depth. These views offer a new way to interpret
constructs in terms o f which the explanation existing data and provide a heuristiciframe-
is formulated. The apparent circularity has work for further research.
been avoided by the specification of additional
properties of the stores (such as their capacity MULTISTORE MODELS
and coding characteristics) thereby character-
izing them independently of the phenomena The Case in Favor
to be explained. The constructs, thus formu- When man is viewed as a processor of in-
lated, have been used to account for data formation (Miller, 1956; Broadbent, 1958), it
across a variety of paradigms and experimental seems necessary to postulate holding mechan-
conditions. The essential concept underlying isms or memory stores at various points in the
such explanations is that of information being system. For example, on the basis of his
transferred from one store to another, and the dichotic listening studies, Broadbent (1958)
store-to-store transfer models may be distin- proposed that information must be held
guished, at least in terms of emphasis, from transiently before entering the limited-capacity
explanations which associate different reten- processing channel. Items could be held over
tion characteristics with qualitative changes the short term by recycling them, after
in the memory code. perception, through the same transient storage
In the present paper we will do three things: system. From there, information could be
(a) examine the reasons for proposing multi- transferred into and retained in a more
permanent long-term store. Broadbent's ideas
a This research was supported by Grants A8261 and have been developed and extended by Waugh
A0355 from the National Research Council of Canada
to the first and second author, respectively.We thank and Norman (1965), Peterson (1966), and
our colleagues who read a preliminary version of the Atkinson and Shiffrin (1968). According to
paper and made many helpful suggestions. the modal model (Murdock, 1967), it is now
671
"2opyright 1972 by Academic Press, Inc.
All rights o f reproduction in any form reserved.
672 CRAIK AND LOCKHART

widely accepted that memory can be classified guished from sensory memories by virtue of
into three levels of storage: sensory stores, its limited capacity (Miller, 1956; Broadbent,
short-term memory (STM) and long-term 1958), by the finding that information is lost
memory (LTM). Since there has been some principally by a process of displacement
ambiguity in the usage of terms in this area, (Waugh & Norman, 1965), and by the slower
we shall follow the convention of using STM rate of forgetting from STS: 5-20 seconds as
and LTM to refer to experimental situations, opposed to the 1-2-second estimates for
and the terms "short-term store" (STS) and sensory storage. While most research has
"long-term store" (LTS) to refer to the two concentrated on verbal STS, there is evidence
relevant storage systems. that more literal "representational" inform-
Stimuli can be entered into the sensory stores ation may also be held over the short term
regardless of whether or not the subject is (Posner, 1967), although the relationship
paying attention to that source; that is, between such modality-specific stores and the
sensory stores are "preattentive" (Neisser, verbal STS has not been made clear.
1967). The input is represented in a rather The distinctions between STS and LTS are
literal form and can be overwritten by further well-documented. Whereas STS has a limited
inputs in the same modality (Neisser, 1967; capacity, LTS has no known limit; verbal
Crowder & Morton, 1969). Further features items are usually coded phonemically in STS
which distinguish the sensory registers from but largely in terms of their semantic features
later st~bres are the modality-specific nature in LTS (Baddeley, 1966); forgetting from
and moderately large capacity of sensory STS is complete within 30 seconds or less
stores and the transience of their contents. while forgetting from LTS is either very slow
AtteOtion to the material in a sensoryregister or the material is not forgotten at all (Shiffrin
is equivalent to reading it out and transferring & Atkinson, 1969). In the free-recall paradigm,
it to STS. Here, verbal items are coded in it is generally believed that the last few items
some phonemic fashion (Shulman, 1971) or are retrieved from STS and prior items are
in auditory-verbal-linguistic terms (Atkinson retrieved from LTS; it is now known that
& Shiffrin, 1968). The STS is further distin- several variables affect one of these retrieval

TABLE 1
COMMONLY ACCEPTED DIFFERENCES BETWEEN THE THREE STAGES OF VERBAL MEMORY (SEE TEXT FOR SOURCES)

Feature Sensory registers Short-term store Long-term store

Entry of information Preattentive Requires attention Rehearsal


Maintenance of information Not possible Continued attention Repetition
Rehearsal Organization
Format of information Literal copy of input Phonemic Largely semantic
Probably visual Some auditory and visual
Possibly semantic
Capacity Large Small No known limit
Information loss Decay Displacement Possibly no loss
Possibly decay Loss of accessibility or
discriminabilityby inter-
ference
Trace duration k-2 Seconds Up to 30 seconds Minutes to years
Retrieval Readout Probably automatic Retrieval cues
Items in consciousness Possibly search process
Temporal/phonemic cues
LEVELS OF PROCESSING 673

components without affecting the other


Capacity
(Glanzer, 1972). Further persuasive evidence
for the STS/LTS dichotomy comes from Although limited capacity has been a major
clinical studies (Milner, 1970; Warrington, feature of the information flow approach,
1971). The distinguishing features of the three and especially a feature of STS in multistore
storage levels are summarized in Table I. models, the exact nature of the capacity
The attractiveness of the "box" approach limitation is somewhat obscure. In particular,
is not difficult to understand. Such multistore it has been unclear whether the limitation is
models are apparently specific and concrete; one of processing capacity, storage capacity,
information flows in well-regulated paths or is meant to apply to some interaction be-
between stores whose characteristics have tween the two. In terms of the computer
intuitive appeal; their properties may be analogy on which information flow models
elicited by experiment and described either are based, the issue is whether the limitation
behaviorally or mathematically. All that refers to the storage capacity of a memory
remains, it seems, is to specify the properties register or to the rate at which the processor
of each component more precisely and to work can perform certain operations. The notion of
out the transfer functions more accurately. a limited-capacity channel (Broadbent, 1958)
Despite all these points in their favor, when appears to emphasize the second interpreta-
the evidence for multistore models is examined tion while later models of memory, such as
in greater detail, the stores become less that of Waugh and Norman (1965), appear to
tangible. One warning sign is the progressively favor the storage interpretation. Both inter-
greater part played by "control processes" in pretations are present in Miller (1956) but the
more recent formulations (for example, relationship between the two is not explicitly
Atkinson & Shiffrin, 1971). In the next section worked out.
we consider the adequacy ofmultistore notions Attempts to measure the capacity of STS
more critically. have leant towards the storage interpretation,
and considered number of items to be the
appropriate scale of measurement. Such
The Case Against attempts have provided quite a range of
The multistore approach has not been values. For example, recent estimates of
without its general critics (Melton, 1963; primary memory size (Baddeley, 1970; Mur-
Murdock, 1972). Other workers have objected dock, 1972) have yielded values between two
to certain aspects of the formulation. For and four words. However, measures of
example, Tulving and Patterson (1968) argued memory span (which have been said to reflect
against the notion of information being the limited capacity of the STM box) are
transferred from one store to another. typically between five and nine items, depend-
Similarly, Shallice and Warrington (1970) ing on whether the items in question are words,
presented evidence against the idea that letters or digits (Crannell & Parrish, 1957).
information must necessarily "pass through" Finally, if the words in a span test form a
STS to enter LTS. sentence, young subjects can accurately
In our view, the criteria listed in the previous reproduce strings of up to 20 words (Craik &
section do not provide satisfactory grounds Masani, 1969). Thus, if capacity is a critical
for distinguishing between separate stores. feature of STM operation, a box model has to
The adequacy of the evidence will be con- account for this very wide range of capacity
sidered with reference to the concepts of estimates.
capacity, coding, and finally, the retention The most widely accepted explanation of
function itself. this variation is that capacity is limited in
674 CRAIK AND LOCKHART

terms of chunks, and that few or many items an important characteristic by which one store
can be recoded into a chunk depending on the is distinguished from another.
meaningfulness of the material. Apart from We will argue that the coding question is
the difficultyof defining a chunk independently more appropriately formulated in terms of the
from its memorial consequences, this view processing demands imposed by the experi-
entails a rather flexible notion of STS as a mental paradigm and the material to be
storage compartment which can accept a remembered. In some paradigms and with
variety of codes from simple physical features certain material, acoustic coding may be
to complex semantic ones. either adequate or all that is possible. In
From the standpoint of the present paper, other circumstances processing to a semantic
the concept of capacity is to be understood in level may be both possible and advantageous.
terms of a limitation on processing; limitations
of storage are held to be a direct consequence Forgetting Characteristics
of this more fundamental limitation. If memory stores are to be distinguished in
terms of their forgetting characteristics, a
Coding minimal requirement would seem to be that
Working with verbal material, Conrad the retention function should be invariant
(1964) and Baddeley (1966) provided one across different paradigms and experimental
plausible basis for distinguishing STS and conditions. While this invariance has not been
LTS. They concluded that information in STS rigorously tested, there are cases where it
was coded acoustically and that coding was clearly breaks down. We will give two
predominantly semantic in LTS. Further examples. First, in the finite-state models of
research has blurred this distinction, how- paired-associate learning, the state commonly
ever. First, it has been shown that STS coding identified as STS shows forgetting character-
can be either acoustic or articulatory (Levy, istics which are different from those established
1971; Peterson & Johnson, 1971). Second, for STS in other paradigms (Kintsch, 1970,
recent papers by Kroll and his colleagues p. 206). In the former case, STS retention
(Kroll et al., 1970) have demonstrated that extends over as many as 20 intervening items
even with verbal material, STS can sometimes while in the free-recall and probe paradigms
be visual. Apparently STS can accept a variety (Waugh & Norman, 1965), STS information
of physical codes. is lost much more rapidly. As a second
Can STS also hold semantic information? example, the durability of the memory trace for
The persistence of contradictory evidence visual stimuli appears to depend on the mat-
suggests either that the question has been erial and the paradigm. According to Neisser
inappropriately formulated or that the answer (1967), the icon lasts 1 second or less, Posner
depends on the paradigm used. When tradi- (1969) and his colleagues have found evidence
tional STM paradigms are considered, the for visual persistence of up to 1.5 seconds,
answer seems to be "no" (Kintsch & Buschke, while other recent studies by Murdock (1971),
1969; Craik & Levy, 1970), although Shulman Phillips and Baddeley (1971) and by Kroll et
(1970, 1972) has recently presented persuasive al. (1970) have yielded estimates of 6, 10, and
evidence in favor of a semantic STS. While 25 seconds, respectively. Estimates are even
type of coding may originally have seemed a longer in recognRion memory for pictures
good basis for the distinction between short- (Shepard, 1967; Haber, 1970). Given that we
term and long-term memory, the distinction recognize pictures, faces, tunes, and voices
no longer appears satisfactory. A defender of after long periods of time, it is clear that we
the multistore notion might argue that STS have long-term memory for relatively literal
coding is flexible, but this position removes nonverbal information. Thus, it is difficult to
LEVELS OF PROCESSING 675

draw a line between "sensory memory" and with matching the input against stored abstrac-
"representational" or "pictorial" memory. tions from past learning; that is, later stages
We will argue that retention depends upon are concerned with pattern recognition and
such aspects of the paradigm as study time, the extraction of meaning. This conception
amount of material presented and mode of of a series or hierarchy of processing stages is
test; also upon the extent to which the subject often referred to as "depth of processing"
has developed systems to analyze and enrich where greater "depth" implies a greater degree
particular types of stimuli; that is, the familiar-
of semantic or cognitive analysis. After the
ity, compatibility, and meaningfulness of the stimulus has been recognized, it may undergo
material. further processing by enrichment or elabor-
Although we believe that the multistore ation. For example, after a word is recognized,
formulation is unsatisfactory in terms of its it may trigger associations, images or stories
capacity, coding, and forgetting character- on the basis of the subject's past experience
istics, obviously there are some basic findings with the word. Such "elaboration coding"
which any model must accommodate. It seems (Tulving & Madigan, 1970) is not restricted to
certain that stimuli are encoded in different verbal material. We would argue that similar
ways within the memory system: A word may levels of processing exist in the perceptual
be encoded at various times in terms of its analysis of sounds, sights, smells and so on.
visual, phonemic, or semantic features, its Analysis proceeds through a series of sensory
verbal associates, or an image. Differently stages to levels associated with matching or
encoded representations apparently persist for pattern recognition and finally to semantic-
different lengths of time. The phenomenon of associative stages of stimulus enrichment.
limited capacity at some points in the system One of the results of this perceptual analysis
seems real enough and, thus, should also be is the memory trace. Such features of the trace
taken into consideration. Finally, the roles as its coding characteristics and its persistence
of perceptual, attentional, and rehearsal thus arise essentially as byproducts of percep-
processes should also be noted. tual processing (Morton, 1970). Specifically,
One way of coping with the kinds of in- we suggest that trace persistence is a function
consistencies we have described is to postulate of depth of analysis, with deeper levels of
additional stores (see, Morton, 1970; Sperling, analysis associated with more elaborate,
1970). However, we think it is more useful to longer lasting, and stronger traces. Since the
focus on the encoding operations themselves organism is normally concerned only with
and to consider the proposal that rates of the extraction &meaning from the stimuli, it is
forgetting are a function of the type and depth advantageous to store the products of such
of encoding. This view is developed in the deep analyses, but there is usually no need to
next section. store the products of preliminary analyses.
It is perfectly possible to draw a box around
early analyses and call it sensory memory and
LEVELS OF PROCESSING
a box around intermediate analyses called
Many theorists now agree that perception short-term memory, but that procedure both
involves the rapid analysis of stimuli at a oversimplifies matters and evades the more
number of levels or stages (Selfridge & Neisser, significant issues.
1960; Treisman, 1964; Sutherland, 1968). Although certain analytic operations must
Preliminary stages are concerned with the precede others, much recent evidence suggests
analysis of such physical or sensory features that we perceive at meaningful, deeper levels
as lines, angles, brightness, pitch, and loud- before we perceive the results of logically
ness, while later stages are more concerned prior analyses (Macnamara, 1972; Savin &
676 CRAIK AND LOCKHART

Bever, 1970). Further elaborative coding does limited-capacity central processor which may
not exist in a hierarchy of necessary steps be deployed in a number of different ways.
and this seems especially true of later pro- If this processing capacity is used to maintain
cessing stages. In this sense, "spread" of information at one level, the phenomena of
encoding might be a more accurate descrip- short-term memory will appear. The processor
tion, but the term "depth" will be retained as itself is neutral with regard to coding char-
it conveys the flavor of our argument. acteristics: The observed PM code will depend
Highly familiar, meaningful stimuli are on the processing modality within which the
compatible, by definition, with existing cogni- processor is operating. Further, while limited
tive structures. Such stimuli (for example, capacity is a function of the processor itself,
pictures and sentences) will be processed to a the number of items held will depend upon the
deep level more rapidly than less meaningful level at which the processor is operating. At
stimuli and will be well-retained. Thus, speed deeper levels the subject can make greater use
of analysis does not necessarily predict reten- of learned rules and past knowledge; thus,
tion. Retention is a function of depth, and material can be more efficiently handled and
various factors, such as the amount of atten- more can be retained. There is apparently
tion devoted to a stimulus, its compatibility great variability in the ease with which inform-
with the analyzing structures, and the pro- ation at different levels can be maintained
cessing time available, will determine the depth in PM. Some types of information (for
to which it is processed. example, phonemic features of words) are
Thus, we prefer to think of memory tied to particularly easy to maintain while the main-
levels of perceptual processing. Although these tenance of others (such as early visual analyses
levels may be grouped into stages (sensory --the "icon") is apparently impossible.
analyses, pattern recognition, and stimulus The essential feature of PM retention is
elaboration, for example) processing levels that aspects of the material are still being
may be more usefully envisaged as a con- processed or attended to. Our notion of PM is,
tinuum of analysis. Thus, memory, too, is thus, synonymous with that of James (1890)
viewed as a continuum from the transient in that PM items are still in consciousness.
products of sensory analyses to the highly When attention is diverted from the item,
durable products of semantic-associative information will be lost at the rate appropriate
operations. However, superimposed on this to its level of processing--slower rates for
basic memory system there is a second way in deeper levels. While PM retention is, thus,
which stimuli can be retained--by reeirculat- equivalent to continued processing, this type
ing information at one level of processing. In of processing merely prolongs an item's high
our view, such descriptions as "continued accessibility without leading to formation of
attention to certain aspects of the stimulus," a more permanent memory trace. This Type I
"keeping the items in consciousness," "hold- processing, that is, repetition of analyses
ing the items in the rehearsal buffer," and which have already been carried out, may be
"retention of the items in primary memory" contrasted with Type II processing which
all refer to the same concept of maintaining involves deeper analysis of the stimulus. Only
information at one level of processing. To this second type of rehearsal should lead to
preserve some measure of continuity with improved memory performance. To the extent
existing terminology, we will use the term that the su~ect utilizes Type II processing,
primary memory (PM) to refer to this oper- memory will improve with total study time,
ation, although it should be noted that our but when he engages in Type I processing, the
usage is more restricted than the usual one. "total time hypothesis" (see Cooper & Pantle,
We endorse Moray's (1967) notion of a 1967) will break down. Stoff and Eagle (1971)
LEVELS OF PROCESSING 677

have reported findings in line with this experimenter has a control over the processing
suggestion. the subject applies to the material that he does
To summarize, it is suggested that the not have when the subject is merely instructed
memory trace is better described in terms to learn and uses an unknown coding strategy.
of depth of processing or degree of stimulus We will consider several examples which
elaboration. Deeper analysis leads to a more illustrate this point. Tresselt and Mayzner
persistent trace. While information may be (1960) tested free recall after incidental learn-
held in PM, such maintenance will not in itself ing under three different orienting tasks:
improve subsequent retention; when attention crossing out vowels, copying the words, and
is diverted, information is lost at a rate which judging the degree to which the word was an
depends essentially on the level of analysis. instance of the concept "economic". Under
the last condition, the number of words re-
EXISTING DATA REEXAMINED called was four times higher than that of the
first and twice that of the second condition.
Incidental Learning Similar results using the free-recall paradigm
When memory traces are viewed as the have been obtained by Hyde and Jenkins
product of a particular form of processing, (1969), and Johnston and Jenkins (1971).
much of the incidental learning literature The experiments by Jenkins and his colleagues
acquires a new significance. There are several showed that with lists of highly associated
reviews of this literature (Postman, 1964; word pairs, free recall and organization
McLaughlin, 1965), and we will make no resulting from an orienting task which required
attempt to be comprehensive. An important the use of the word as a semantic unit, was
characteristic of the incidental learning para- equivalent to that of an intentional control
digm is that the subject processes the material group with no incidental task, but both were
in a way compatible with or determined by substantially superior to an incidental group
the orienting task. The comparison of whose task involved treating the word
retention across different orienting tasks, structurally (checking for certain letters or
therefore, provides a relatively pure measure estimating the number of letters in the word).
of the memorial consequences of different These results are consistent with those of
processing activities. According to the view of Mandler (1967) who showed that incidental
the present paper, and in agreement with learning during categorization of words
Postman (1964), the instruction to learn yielded a similar recall level to that of a group
facilitates performance only insofar as it leads who performed the same activity but who
the subject to process the material in a manner knew that their recall would be tested.
which is more effective than the processing Experiments involving the incidental learn-
induced by the orienting task in the incidental ing of sentences (Bobrow & Bower, 1969;
condition. Thus, it is possible, that with an Rosenberg & Schiller, 1971) have shown that
appropriate orienting task and an inappro- recall after an orienting task that required
priate intentional strategy, learning under processing the sentence to a semantic level was
incidental conditions could be superior to that substantially superior to recall of words from
under intentional conditions. equivalently exposed sentences which were
From the point of view of this paper, then, processed nonsemantically.
the interesting thing to do is to systematically Schulman (1971) had subjects scan a list
study retention following different orienting of words for targets defined either structurally
tasks within the incidental condition, rather (such as words containing the letter A) or
than to compare incidental with intentional semantically (such as words denoting living
learning. Under incidental conditions, the things). After the scanning task, subjects were
678 CRAIK AND LOCKHART

given an unexpected test of recognition degree. When the orienting task involved the
memory. Performance in the semantically production of mediating responses, perform-
defined target conditions was significantly ance was equal to that of unhindered inten-
better than that in the structurally defined tional learning and superior to when the
conditions although scanning time per word orienting task was rating words for pleasant-
was approximately the same in most cases. ness. In single-trial free recall, this latter
These results support the general conclusion orienting task produces performance equal to
that memory performance is a positive func- that of intentional learning (Hyde & Jenkins,
tion of the level of processing required by the 1969). Identical orienting tasks do not seem to
orienting task. However, beyond a certain have equivalent effects across different para-
stage, the form of processing which will prove digms. The interaction between initial en-
optimal depends on the retrieval or trace coding and subsequent retrieval operations is
utilization requirements of the subsequent worth emphasizing. Although the distinction
memory test. There is clear evidence in the between availability and accessibility (Tulving
incidental learning literature that the relative & Pearlstone, 1966) is a useful one, the
value of different orienting tasks is not the effectiveness of a retrieval cue depends on its
same for all tests of memory. compatibility with the item's initial encoding
This conclusion is supported by compari- or, more generally, the extent to which the
sons of the differential effects of orienting retrieval situation reinstates the learning
tasks on recognition and recall. Eagle and context.
Leiter (1964) found that whereas free recall
in an unhindered intentional condition was Selective Attention and Sensory Storage
superior to that of an incidental group and Moray (1959) showed that words presented
to a second intentional group who had also to to the nonattended channel in a dichotic
perform the orienting task, these latter two listening test were not recognized in a later
conditions showed superior recognition per- memory test. Similarly, Neisser (1964) has
formance. Such a result poses no: difficulty shown that nontarget items in a visual search
provided it is assumed that optimal processing task left no recognizable trace. Thus, if stimuli
does not take the same form for both memory are only partially analyzed, or processed only
tests. In the Eagle and Leiter (1964) experi- to peripheral levels, their record in memory
ment, the orienting task, while almost is extremely fleeting. This point was neatly
certainly involving some degree of semantic demonstrated by Treisman (1964). When the
analysis, might have served to prevent the same prose passage was played to both ears
kind of elaborative processing necessary for dichotically, but staggered in time with the
later access to the stored information. On the unattended ear leading, the lag between
other hand, such elaborative coding might messages had to be reduced to 1.5 seconds
hinder subsequent discrimination between before the subject realized that the messages
target words and the associatively related were identical. When the attended (shadowed)
distractors used in this experiment. Results ear was leading, however, subjects noticed the
consistent with this kind of analysis have also similarity at a mean lag of 4.5 seconds. Thus,
been reported by Dornbush and Winnick although the subjects were not trying to
(1967) and Estes and DaPolito (1967). remember the material in either case, the
While the orienting tasks used by Wicker further processing necessitated by shadowing
and Bernstein (1969) in their study of in- was sufficient to treble the durability of the
cidental paired-associate learning all required memory trace. Treisman also found that
analysis to a semantic level, they did not meaningfulness of the material (reversed
facilitate subsequent performance to the same speech versus normal speech, and random
LEVELS OF PROCESSING 679

words versus prose) affected the lag necessary term retention as well. We would also suggest
for recognition, but only when the attended that it is processing level, rather than inform-
channel was leading. If the message was ation content, which determines the rate of
rejected after early analyses, meaningfulness decay.
played no part; but when the message was
attended, more meaningful material could be The STS/LTS Distinction
processed further and was, thus, retained The phenomenon of a limited-capacity
longer. The three estimates of memory per- holding mechanism in memory (Miller, 1956;
sistence in these experiments (1.5 seconds for Broadbent, 1958) is handled in the present
all nonattended material, 3 seconds for attend- framework by assuming that a flexible central
ed reversed speech and attended strings processor can be deployed to one of several
of random words, and 5 seconds for attended levels in one of several encoding dimensions,
prose) can be attributed to the functioning of and that this central processor can only deal
different stores, but it is more reasonable, in with a limited number of items at a given time.
our view, to postulate that persistence is a That is, items are kept in consciousness or in
function of processing level. primary memory by continuing to rehearse
While further studies will not be reviewed in them at a fixed level of processing. The nature
such detail, it may be noted that the findings of the items will depend upon the encoding
and conclusions of many other workers in the dimension and the level within that dimen-
area of sensory memory can also be accom- sion. At deeper levels the subject can make
modated in the present framework. Neisser more use of learned cognitive structures so
(1967, p. 33) concluded that "longer exposures that the item will become more complex and
lead to longer-lasting icons." Studies by semantic. The depth at which primary
Norman (1969), Glucksberg and Cowen memory operates will depend both upon the
(1970), and Peterson and Kroener (1964) may usefulness to the subject of continuing to
all be interpreted as showing that non- process at that level and also upon the amen-
attended verbal material is lost within a few ability of the material to deeper processing.
seconds. Thus, if the subject's task is merely to repro-
Massaro (1970) suggested that memory for duce a few words seconds after hearing them,
an item is directly related to the amount of he need not hold them at a level deeper than
perceptual processing of the item, a statement phonemic analysis. If the words form a
which is obviously in line with the present meaningful sentence, however, they are
proposals, although his later arguments compatible with deeper learned structures
(Massaro, 1972), that echoic memory inevit- and larger units may be dealt with. It seems
ably lasts only 250 milliseconds, are probably that primary memory deals at any level with
overgeneralizations. Shaffer and Shiffrin con- units or "chunks" rather than with inform-
cluded from an experiment on picture recogni- ation (see Kintsch, 1970, pp. 175-181). That
tion that "it might prove more fruitful to is, we rehearse a sound, a letter, a word, an
consider the more parsimonious view that idea, or an image in the same way that we
there is just a single short-term visual memory. perceive objects and not constellations of
This short-term visual memory would decay attributes.
quickly when the information content of the As pointed out earlier, a common distinc-
visual field was high and more slowly when the tion between memory stores is their different
information content was greatly reduced" coding characteristics; STS is said to be
(Shaffer & Shiffrin, 1972, p. 295). Plainly this predominantly acoustic (or articulatory) while
view is similar to our own, although we would LTS is largely semantic. According to the
argue that the continuum extends to long- present argument, acoustic errors will pre-
680 CRAIK AND LOCKHART

dominate only insofar as analysis has not


proceeded to a semantic level. There are at least The Serial Position Curve
three sources of the failure of processing to Serial-position effects have been a major
reach this level; the nature of the material, source of evidence for the STS/LTS distinction
limited available processing capacity, and (see Broadbent, 1971, pp. 354-361; Kintsch,
task demands. Much of the data on acoustic 1970, pp. 153-162). In free recall, the recency
confusions in short-term memory is based on effect is held to reflect output from STS while
material such as letters and digits which have previous items are retrieved from LTS
relatively little semantic content. The nature (Glanzer & Cunitz, 1966). Several theoretical
of this material itself tends to constrain pro- accounts of the primacy effect have been
cessing to a structural level of analysis and it given, but perhaps the most plausible is that
should be no surprise, therefore, that errors initial items receive more rehearsals and are,
of a structural nature result. Such errors can thus, better registered in LTS (Atkinson &
also occur with meaningful material if process- Shiffrin, 1968; Bruce & Papay, 1970). We
ing capacity is diverted to an irrelevant task agree with these conclusions. Since the
(Eagle & Ortoff, 1967). subject knows he must stop attending to
A further set of results relevant to the initial items in order to perceive and rehearse
STS/LTS distinction are those that show that subsequent items, he subjects these first items
in free recall, variables such as presentation to Type II processing; that is, deeper semantic
rate and word frequency, affect long-term but processing. Final list items can survive on
not short-term retention (Glanzer, 1972). Our phonemic encoding, however, which gives rise
interpretation of these findings is that in- to excellent immediate recall (since they are
creasing presentation rate, or using unfamiliar still being processed in primary memory)
words, inhibits or prevents processing to those but is wiped out by the necessity to process
levels necessary to support long-term reten- interpolated material. In fact, if terminal
tion, but does not affect coding operations of items have been less deeply processed than
the kind that are adequate for short-term initial items, the levels of processing formula-
retention. It follows from this interpretation tion would predict that in a subsequent recall
that diverting processing capacity as in the attempt, final items should be recalled least
Eagle and Ortoff (1967) experiments should well of all list items. The finding of negative
result in a greater decrement in long-term recency (Craik, 1970) supports this prediction.
than in short-term retention and, indeed, An alternative explanation of negative recency
there is good evidence that such is the case could be that recency items were rehearsed
(Murdock, 1965; Silverstein & Glanzer, fewer times than earlier items (Rundus, 1971).
1971). However, recent studies by Jacoby and Bartz
Conversely, manipulations that influence (1972), Watkins (1972), and Craik (1972) have
processing at a structural level should have shown that it is the type rather than the amount
transitory, but no long-term, effects. Modality of processing which determines the subse-
differences (Murdock, 1966) provide a clear quent recall of the last few items in a list.
example. Finally, long-term recall should be In serial recall, subjects must retain the
facilitated by manipulations which induce first few items so that they can at least com-
deeper or more elaborative processing. We mence their recall correctly. The greatly
suggest that the encoding variability hypo- enhanced primacy effect is thus probably
thesis as it has been used to account for the attributable, in part at least, to primary-
spacing effect in free recall (Madigan, 1969; memory retention. The degree to which
Melton, 1970) is to be understood in these subjects also encode initial items at a deeper
terms. level is likely to depend on the material and
LEVELS OF PROCESSING 681

the task. Using a relatively slow (2.5 seconds) trace or merely postpones forgetting depends
presentation rate and words as visually on what the subject is doing with his rehearsal.
presented stimuli, Palmer and Ornstein (1971) Only deeper processing will lead to an
found that an interpolated task only partially improvement in memory.
eliminated the primacy effect. However,
Baddeley (1968) presented digits auditorily
CONCLUDING COMMENTS
at a 1-second rate and found that primacy was
entirely eliminated by the necessity to perform Our account of memory in terms of levels
a further task. of processing has much in common with a
number of other recent formulations. Cermak
Repetition and Rehearsal Effects (1972), for example, has outlined a theoretical
One suggestion in the present formulation framework very similar to our own. Per-
is that Type I processing does nothing to ceptually oriented attribute-encoding theories
enhance memory for the stimulus; once such as those of Bower (1967) and Norman and
attention is diverted, the trace is lost at the Rumelhart (1970) have a close affinity with the
rate appropriate to its deepest analyzed level. present approach as does that of Posner (1969)
Thus, the concept of processing has been split who advocates stages of processing with
into Type I or same-level processing and Type different characteristics associated with each
II processing which involves further, deeper stage.
analysis of the stimulus and leads to a more If the memory trace is viewed as the by-
durable trace. Similarly, the effects of repeated product of perceptual analysis, an important
presentation depend on whether the repeated goal of future research will be to specify the
stimulus is merely processed to the same level memorial consequences of various types of
or encoded differently on its further present- perceptual operations. We have suggested
ations. There is evidence, both in audition the comparison of orienting tasks within the
(Moray, 1959; Norman, 1969), and in vision incidental learning paradigm as one method
(Turvey, 1967), that repetition of an item by which the experimenter can have more
encoded only at a sensory level, does not lead direct control over the encoding operations
to an improvement in memory performance. that subjects perform. Since deeper analysis
Tulving (1966) has also shown that repeti- will usually involve longer processing time,
tion without intention to learn does not it will be extremely important to disentangle
facilitate learning. Tulving's explanation of the such variables as study time and amount of
absence of learning in terms of interitem effort from depth as such. For example, time
organization cannot easily be distinguished may be a correlate of memory to the extent that
from an explanation in terms of levels of time is necessary for processing to some level,
processing. Similarly, Glanzer and Meinzer but it is possible that further time spent in
(1967) have shown that overt repetition of merely recycling the information after this
items in free recall is a less effective strategy optimal level will not predict trace durability.
than that normally used by subjects. Although Our approach does not constitute a theory
both Waugh and Norman (1965), and Atkin- of memory. Rather, it provides a conceptual
son and Shiffrin (1968) have suggested that framework--a set of orienting attitudes--
rehearsal has the dual function of maintaining within which memory research might proceed.
information in primary memory and trans- While multistore models have played a useful
ferring it to secondary memory, the experi- role, we suggest that they are often taken too
ments by Tulving (1966) and by Glanzer and literally and that more fruitful questions are
Meinzer (1967) show that this is not necessarily generated by the present formulation. Our
so. Thus, whether rehearsal strengthens the position is obviously speculative and far from
682 CRAIK AND LOCKHART

complete. W e have looked at m e m o r y purely COOPER,E. H., & PANTLE,A. J. The total-time hypo-
from the i n p u t or encoding end; no a t t e m p t thesis in verbal learning. Psychological Bulletin,
1967, 68, 221-234.
has been m a d e to specify either how items are
CRAIK, F. I. M. The fate of primary memory items in
differentiated from one another, are grouped free recall. Journal of Verbal Learning and
together a n d organized, or how they are Verbal Behavior, 1970, 9, 143-148.
retrieved from the system. While our position CRAIK,F. I. M. A 'levels of analysis' view of memory.
does n o t imply a n y specific view of these Paper presented at the 2nd Erindale Symposium
on Communication and Affect, March, 1972.
processes, it does provide a n appropriate
CRAIK,F. I. M., & LEVY,B. A. Semantic and acoustic
framework within which they can be information in primary memory. Journal of
understood. Experimental Psychology, 1970, 86, 77-82.
CRAm, F. I. M., & MASANI,P. A. Age and intelligence
differences in coding and retrieval of word lists.
British Journal of Psychology, 1969, 60, 315-319.
REFERENCES CRANNELL,C. W., & PARRISH,J. M. A comparison of
ATKINSON,R. C., & SHIFFRIN,R. M. Human memory: immediate memory span for digits, letters, and
A proposed system and its control processes. In words. Journal of Psychology, 1957, 44, 319-
327.
K. W. Spence and J. T. Spence (Eds.) Thepsycho-
logy of learning and motivation: Advances in CROWDER, R. G., & MORTON, J. Precategorical
research and theory, Vol. II. New York: Academic acoustic storage. Perception and Psychophysics,
1969, 5, 365-373.
Press, 1968. Pp. 89-195.
ATKINSON,R. C., & SHIFFRIN,R. M. The control of DORNBUSH, R. L., & WlNNICIC, W. A. Short-term
short-term memory. Scientific American, I971, intentional and incidental learning. Journal of
Experimental Psychology, 1967, 73, 608-611.
224, 82-89.
BADDELEY, A. D. Short-term memory for word EAGLE, M., & LEITER, E. Recall and recognition
sequences as a function of acoustic, semantic, and in intentional and incidental learning. Journal
formal similarity. Quarterly Journal of Experi- of Experimental Psychology, 1964, 68, 58-63.
mental Psychology, 1966, 18, 362-365. EAGLE,M., & ORTOEF,E. The effect of leve/of attention
BADDELEY, A. D. How does acoustic similarity upon "phonetic" recognition errors. Journal of
influence short-term memory? Quarterly Jour- Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 1967, 6, 226-
231.
nal of Experimental Psychology, 1968, 20, 249-
264. ESTES,W. K., & DAPOLITO,F. Independent variation
BADDELEY,A. D. Estimating the short-term component of information storage and retrieval processes
in free recall. British Journal of Psychology, 1970, in paired-associate learning. Journal of Experi-
61, 13-15. mental Psychology, 1967, 75, 18-26.
BOBROW,S. A., & BOWER,G. H. Comprehension and GLANZER, M. Storage mechanisms in recall. In G. H.
recall of sentences. JournalofExperimentalPsych- Bower (Ed.) The psychology o f learning and
ology, 1969, 80, 455-461. motivation: Advances in research and theory.
BOWER, G. H. A multicomponent theory of the Vol. 5. New York: Academic Press, 1972. Pp.
memory trace. In K. W. Spence and J. T. Spence 129-193.
(Eds.) The psychology of learning and motivation: GLANZER,M., & CUNITZ,A. R. Two storage mechan-
Advances in research and theory, Vol. 1. New isms in free recall. Journal of Verbal Learning and
York: Academic Press, 1967. Pp. 230-325. Verbal Behavior, 1966, 5, 351-360.
BROADBENT, D. E. Perception and communication. GLANZER,M., & MEINZER,A. The effects of intralist
New York: Pergamon Press, 1958. activity on free recall. Journal of Verbal Learning
BROADBENT, D. E. Decision and stress. New York: and Verbal Behavior, 967, 6, 928-935.
Academic Press, 1971. GLUCKSBERG, S., & COWEN, G. N. Memory for
BRUCE,D., & PAPAY,J. P. Primacy effect in single-trial nonattended auditory material. Cognitive Psycho-
free recall. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal logy, 1970, 1, 149-156.
Behavior, 1970, 9, 473-486. HABER,R. N. How we remember what we see. Scientific
CERMAK,L. S. Human memory. Research and theory. American, 1970, 222, 104-112.
New York: Ronald, 1972. HYDE,T. S., & JENKINS,J. J. The differential effects of
CONRAD, R. Acoustic confusions in immediate incidental tasks on the organization of recall of a
memory. British Journal of Psychology, 1964, list of highly associated words. Journal of Experi-
55, 75-84. mental Psychology, 1969, 82, 472-481.
LEVELS OF PROCESSING 683

JACOBY, L. L., & BARTZ, W. H. Encoding processes MORAY, N. Attention in dichotic listening: affective
and the negative recency effect. Journal of Verbal cues and the influence of instructions. Quarterly
Learning and Verbal Behavior, 1972, 11, 561-565. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 1959, 9,
JAMES, W. Principles of psychology. New York: Holt, 56-60.
1890. MORAY,N. Where is capacity limited ? A survey and a
JOHNSTON,C. D., & JENKINS,J. J. Two more incidental model. In A. Sanders (Ed.) Attention and perform-
tasks that differentially affect associative clustering ante. Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1967.
in recall. Journal of Experimental Psychology, MORTON, J. A functional model of memory. In D. A.
1971, 89, 92-95. Norman (Ed.) Models of human memory. New
KINTSCH, W. Learning, memory, and conceptual York: Academic Press, 1970. Pp. 203-254.
processes. New York: Wiley, 1970. MURDOCK, B. 13. JR. Effects of a subsidiary task on
KdNTSCH, W., & 13tJSCHKE, H. Homophones and short-term memory. British Journal of Psychology,
synonyms in short-term memory. Journal of 1965, 56, 413-419.
Experimental Psychology, 1969, 80, 403-407. MURDOCK, B. B. JR. Visual and auditory stores in
KROLL,N. E. A., PARKS,T., PARKINSON,S. R., 13IEBER, short-term memory. QuarterlyJournalofExperi-
S. L., & JOr~NSON,A. L. Short-term memory while mental Psychology, 1966, 18, 206-211.
shadowing. Recall of visually and aurally pre- MURDOCK, B. B. JR. Recent developments in short-
sented letters. Journal of Experimental Psychology, term memory. British Journal of Psychology, 1967,
1970, 85, 220-224. 58, 421-433.
LEvv, B. A. Role of articulation in auditory and visual MtJRDOCK,]3. B. JR. Four channel effects in short-term
short-term memory. Journal of Verbal Learning memory. Psychonomic Science, 1971, 24, 197-
and Verbal Behavior, 1971, 10, 123-132. 198.
MACNAMARA,J. Cognitive basis of language learningin MVRDOCK, B. B. JR. Short-term memory. In G. H.
infants. Psychological Review, 1972, 79, 1-13. Bower (Ed.) Psychology of learn#Tgand motivation,
MADIGAN, S. A. Intraserial repetition and coding Vol. 5. New York: Academic Press, 1972. Pp.
processes in free recall. Journal of Verbal Learning 67-27.
and Verbal Behavior, 1969, 8, 828-835. NEISSER, U. Visual search. Scientific American, 1964,
MANDLER, G. Organization and Memory. In K. W. 210, 94-102.
Spence and J. T. Spence (Eds.) The psychology of NEISSER, U. Cognitive psychology. New York: Apple-
learning and motivation: Advances in research and ton-Century-Crofts, 1967.
theory, Vol. 1. New York: Academic Press, 1967. NORMAN, D. A. Memory while shadowing. Quarterly
Pp. 328-372. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 1969, 21,
MASSARO,D. W. Perceptual processes and forgetting 85-93.
in memory tasks. Psychological Review, 1970, 77, NORMAN, D. A., & RVraELHART,D. E. A system for
557-567. perception and memory. In D. A. Norman (Ed.)
MASSARO, D. W. Preperceptual images, processing Models of human memory. New York: Academic
time, and perceptual units in auditory perception. Press, 1970. Pp 21-64.
Psychological Review, 1972, 79, 124-145. PALMER, S. E., & ORNSTEIN,P. A. Role of rehearsal
McLAUGHEIN, B. "Intentional" and "incidental" strategy in serial probed recall. Journal of Experi-
learning in human subjects: The role of instruc- mental Psychology, 1971, 88, 60-66.
tions to learn and motivation. Psychological PETERSON, L. R. Short-term verbal memory and
Bulletin, 1965, 63, 359-376. learning. Psychological Review, 1966, 73, 193-
MELTON, A. W. Implications of short-term memory 207.
for a general theory of memory. Journal of Verbal PETrRSON, L. R., & JOHNSON, S. T. Some effects of
Learning and Verbal Behavior, 1963, 2, 1-21. minimizing articulation on short-term retention.
MELTON,A. W. The situation with respect to the spac- Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior,
ing of repetitions and memory. Journal of Verbal 1971, 10, 346-354.
Learning and Verbal Behavior, 1970, 9, 596-606. PETERSON,L. R., & KROENER,S. Dichotic stimulation
MILLER, G. A. The magical number seven, plus or and retention. Journal of ExperimentalPsychology,
minus two: Some limits on our capacity for 1964, 68, 125-130.
processing information. Psychological Review, PmLLIVS, W. A., & BADDELEY,A. D. Reaction time
1956, 63, 81-97. and short-term visual memory. Psychonomic
MILNER,13. Memory and the medial temporal regions Science, 1971, 22, 73-74.
of the brain. In K. H. Pribram and D. E. Broad- POSNER, M. I. Short-term memory systems in human
bent (Eds.) Biology of memory. New York: information processing. Acta Psychologica, 1967,
Academic Press, 1970. Pp. 29-50. 27, 267-284.
684 CRAIK AND LOCKHART

POSNER, M. I. Abstraction and the process of recogni- ation. In A. Young and D. B. Lindsley (Eds.)
tion. In G. H. Bower and J. T. Spence (Eds.) Early experience and visual information processing
The psychology of learning and motivation: in perceptual and reading disorders. Washington:
Advances in research and theory, Vol. III. New National Academy of Sciences, 1970. Pp. 198-215.
York: McGraw-Hill, 1969. Pp. 152-179. STorr, M., & EAGLE, M. N. The relationship among
POSTMAN, L. Short-term memory and incidental reported strategies, presentation rate, and verbal
learning. In A. W. Melton (Ed.) Categories of ability and their effects on free recall learning.
human learning. New York: Academic Press, 1964. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 1971, 87,
Pp. 145-201. 423-428.
ROSENBERG,S., & SCHILLER,W. J. Semantic coding and SUTHERLAND, N. S. Outlines of a theory of visual
incidental sentence recall. Journal of Experimental pattern recognition in animals and man. Proceed-
Psychology, 1971, 90, 345-346. ings of the Royal Society. Series B, 1968, 171,
RUNDUS, D. Analysis of rehearsal processes in free 297-317.
recall. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 1971, TREISMAN, A. Monitoring and storage of irrelevant
89, 63-77. messages in selective attention. Journal of Verbal
SAVlN, H. B., & BEVER, T. G. The nonperceptual Learning and Verbal Behavior, 1964, 3, 449-459.
reality of the phoneme. Journal of Verbal Learning TRESSELT,M. E., & MAYZYER,M. S. A study of inci-
and Verbal Behavior, 1970, 9, 295-302. dental learning. Journal of Psychology, 1960, 50,
SCHULMAN,A. I. Recognition memory for targets from 339-347.
a scanned word list. British Journal of Psychology, TULVINC, E. Subjective organization and effects of
1971, 62, 335-346. repetition in multi-trial free-recall learning.
SELFRIDGE,O. G., & NEISSER,U, Pattern recognition Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior,
by machine. Scientific American, 1960, 203, 60-68. 1966, 5, 193-197.
SHAFFER, W. O., & SHIFFRIN,R. M. Rehearsal and TULVING,E., & MADIGAN,S. A. Memory and verbal
storage of visual information. Journal of Experi- learning. Annual Review of Psychology, 1970, 21,
mental Psychology, 1972, 92, 292-296. 437-484.
SHALLICE, T., & WARRINGTON, E. K. Independent TULVIN6,E., & PATTERSON,R. D. Functionalunits and
functioning of verbal memory stores: A neuro- retrieval processes in free recall. Journal of
psychological study. Quarterly Journal of Experi- Experimental Psychology, 1968, 77, 239-248.
mentalPsychology, 1970, 22, 261-273. TULVIN6, E., & PEARLSTONE,Z. Availability versus
SHEPARD, R. N. Recognition memory for words, accessibility of information in memory for words.
sentences, and pictures. Journal of VerbalLearning Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior,
and Verbal Behavior, 1967, 6, 156-163. 1966, 5, 381-391.
SHIFFRIN, R. M., & ATKINSON, R. C. Storage and TURVEY, M. T. Repetition and the preperceptual
retrieval processes in long-term memory. Psycho- information store, Journal of Experimental
logical Review, 1967, 76, 179-193. Psychology, 1967, 74, 289-293.
SHULMAN,H. G. Encoding and retention of semantic WARRINGTON, E. K. Neurological disorders of
and phonemic information in short-term memory. memory. British Medical Bulletin, 1971, 27
Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 243-247.
1970, 9, 499-508. WATKINS, M. J. The characteristics and functions of
SHULMAN, H. G. Similarity effects in short-term primary memory. Unpublished Ph.D. thesis,
memory. PsyehologicalBulletin, 1971,75, 399~15. University of London, 1972.
SrlULMAN, H. G. Semantic confusion errors in short- WAUCH, N. C., & NORMAN,D. A. Primary memory.
term memory. Journal of Verbal Learning and Psychological Review, t965, 72, 89-104.
Verbal Behavior, 1972, 11, 221-227. WICKER,F. W., & BERYSTEIN,A. L. Association value
SILVERSTEIN,C., & GLANZER, M. Concurrent task in and orienting task in incidental and intentional
free recall: Differential effects of LTS and STS. paired-associate learning. Journal of Experimental
Psychonomic Science, 1971, 22, 367-368. Psychology, 1969, 81, 308-311.
SPERLING,G. Short-term memory, long-term memory,
and scanning in the processing of visual inform- (Received June 3, 1972)

Вам также может понравиться