Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 511

The Bloomsbury

Companion to Heidegger
Bloomsbury Companions

The Bloomsbury Companions series is a major series of single volume companions to key
research fields in the humanities aimed at postgraduate students, scholars, and libraries.
Each companion offers a comprehensive reference resource giving an overview of key topics,
research areas, new directions, and a manageable guide to beginning or developing research in
the field. A distinctive feature of the series is that each companion provides practical guidance
on advanced study and research in the field, including research methods and subject-specific
resources.

Aesthetics, edited by Anna Christina Ribeiro Locke, edited by S.-J. Savonious-Wroth,


Analytic Philosophy, edited by Barry Paul Schuurman, and Jonathan Walmsley
Dainton and Howard Robinson Metaphysics, edited by Robert W. Barnard
Aristotle, edited by Claudia Baracchi and Neil A. Manson
Continental Philosophy, edited by Philosophical Logic, edited by Leon Horston
John Mullarkey and Beth Lord and Richard Pettigrew
Epistemology, edited by Andrew Cullison Philosophy of Language, edited by Manuel
Ethics, edited by Christian Miller Garcia-Carpintero and Max Kolbel
Existentialism, edited by Jack Reynolds, Philosophy of Mind, edited by James Garvey
Felicity Joseph, and Ashley Woodward Philosophy of Science, edited by
Hegel, edited by Allegra de Laurentiis and Steven French and Juha Saatsi
Jeffrey Edwards Plato, edited by Gerald A. Press
Hobbes, edited by S. A. Lloyd Political Philosophy, edited by Andrew Fiala
Hume, edited by Alan Bailey and and Matt Matravers
Dan OBrien Pragmatism, edited by Sami Pihlstrm
Kant, edited by Gary Banham, Socrates, edited by John Bussanich and
Dennis Schulting, and Nigel Hems Nicholas D. Smith
Leibniz, edited by Brandon C. Look Spinoza, edited by Wiep van Bunge
THE BLOOMSBURY
COMPANION TO HEIDEGGER

EDITED BY

Franois Raffoul
Eric S. Nelson

L ON DON N E W DE L H I N E W Y OR K SY DN EY
Bloomsbury Academic
An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc

50 Bedford Square 1385 Broadway


London New York
WC1B 3DP NY 10018
UK USA

www.bloomsbury.com

First published 2013

Franois Raffoul, Eric S. Nelson, and Contributors, 2013

All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or


transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including
photocopying, recording, or any information storage or retrieval system,
without prior permission in writing from the publishers.

No responsibility for loss caused to any individual or organization acting on or


refraining from action as a result of the material in this publication
can be accepted by Bloomsbury Academic or the authors.

British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data


A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library.

EISBN: 978-1-4411-7504-5

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data


The Bloomsbury companion to Heidegger / edited by Franois Raffoul and Eric S. Nelson.
pages cm. (Bloomsbury companions)
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 978-1-4411-9985-0 ISBN 978-1-4411-7504-5 (pdf) ISBN 978-1-4411-4161-3 (epub)
1. Heidegger, Martin, 1889-1976. I. Raffoul, Franois, 1960- editor of compilation.
B3279.H49B588 2013
193dc23
2013005645

Typeset by Newgen Imaging Systems Pvt Ltd, Chennai, India


CONTENTS

Acknowlcdgm<nts
List of Abbreviation.
"
N"t~. on Contributo ..
'"
ED ITO RS' INTRODUCTION
Fran,o;s Raff""/ a",/ Eric S. Nei$(}n

PA RT 1: LIFE AND CONTE XTS


1. II E!DEGGER AND TI l E QUEST ION OF B10GRA PI IY
TlMrx1lm K"i~1
2. T H E EAR LY H EIDEGGER
D"mo/ Moran
3. Tl IE TUI{N:ALl THRE E OfTHEM
Thom", Shuh""
4. II EIDEGGER [NTHE 1930" WHO ARE W E?
Richard Polt
5. H ElD EGGER. N IETZSCI-lE, NATIONAL SOCMUS)'l: THE PL\C E OF
l>I H Ar HYS1CS IN TI lE POLIT ICAL DEBATE OF T HE 1930. 47
Rob." Re"'MCO>"
6. TIl E LATER J IEIDEGGER: TI lE QUESTION OF Til E
OTII ER IIEGINN1NG OF T HINKING
Fmnfoi"" Dasrur

7. H EIDEGGER'S CORRES PONDENC E


Alfred D""ker

PART II: SOURC ES, IN FLUEN CES. AN D ENCOUNTERS


8. H [IDEGGER Al':D G REEK I'HILOS01'1 I Y n
Sean D. Kirk/"nJ
9. II EIDEGGER AND MEDIEVAL PHILOSOP HY
Ho/ge, Z,borow.ki
CO",'TENTS

10. lJEIDEGG ER AND DESCA RTES


Emilia Angcl()~a "
I I. H Ell)EGGER ,\Nl) " ,\NT, Tf IRH G IJIDI NG QUESTIONS '0;
fr""k Scbalow
12. II EIDEGGER AND GER~IAN !DEAUS.\I
reler Trawny '"
13. HEIDEGGER AND NIETZSCHE
Ullricb Haa", '"
14. HEIDE GGER AND DlLTl IEY, A DJJ' FERENCE IN 1l\,'TERPRETATION 129
Eric S. I>.'elmn
15. H EIDEGGER AND II USS ER L
Le,!;. MacA"""
H EiDEGGE R. NEO . K..\"''T I AN I S~l. AND CASSIRER
16.
!'eur E. Gordo" '"
17. H EIDEGGER AND CARNAP, DISAG RE U NG ,\BOUT NOTHIl'G! 151
Eric S. N et,on
I ~. H EI()EGG ER ,\N[) ARENln, HIE LAW FUL SPACE o r
WORLDLY Al'!'E.~RA"CE
r.g /hrmi"gham '"
19. IIEIDEGGER AND GADA1I.tER
Emilia Angelo,,", '"
20. H EIDEGGER AND 1I.t,\RCUSE: ON REIHCATION ANI)
COl'CRETE PH1LOSOP IIY
Andrew feen!>"'g

PART 111: KEY WR IT INGS


21. EARLY LECfURE CO URS ES
Scott M. c,mpbdl '"
22. HEIDEGGER, PERSUAS IO"",,A,,",D ARISTOTLE'S RHETORIC
r.
Ci>ri.lopber Smil" '"
ANDT I~l E
23. IIEING
Dem,i, J. .~cb",idt '"
24. TIl E ORIG IN OF TI IE WO RK O F ART
Gregory Sebu/mder '"
25. 1l>.' T RODUCTIONTO METAPHYS ICS 20'
Gregory fried
26. CONTRlBlJTlONS TO PI IILOSOPI IY
reurTrawny

.,
CONTE1'.'TS

27. TIlE 116LDERLl N LECTU RES 223


W/i1I, ~", McNejll

2~. TIlE "LETI'EK ON HU ~\ ..\1\' IS .\ l , EK SISTENCE. HEING.


AND L\NGlI,\GE
An(ire", J. Mi ,ch.1I
29. THE BRE MEN LECTURES
Andrew J. Milchell
30. LATER ESSAYS AND SEMIN ,\RS
Lu B,~<" " '"
I'A RT IV, T H EMES AND TOI'ICS

". m
Andreu, Bowi. '"
". BIRTH AI'D DEATlI
Ann, 0'8 Y'"' '"
,;. Ti lE BODY
KevmAho '"
". DASEIN
F"'"fOis Raffou l
m

35. EII. EIGNIS 283


D,mid.s Vallcg.s Ncl<
K ETIlICS
F"'"fOis Raffoul '"
". TH E FOURFOLD
Andrew J. Milch.1I '"
'". LAI'GUAG E
Jolm McCumber '"'
". THE NOTHI NG
Gregory Schu("jdcr '"
'". Ot-.'TOTIIEOLOGY
lain Thom son '"
.L RELIGION AND THEOLOGY m
Be~ Vedder

42. SCIENCE m
Tri,h GI..O"b",,,k
H. SPACE: TIlE OPEN IN Wlll e ll WE SOJO URN "5
Jolm Russon and Ki"u" Jacobson
CO",'TENTS

44. TECHNOLOGY
H"n' Rum
45. TRUHI
D,,"id O. O"h1"rom '"
PART V, RECEPTI ON AND INFLUENCE

". IIEIDEGG ER AND SARTR E, HISTORICITY, DESTINY, AI'D POLITICS


Robert Il ~rna.coni '"
". H EIDEGGER AND MERLEAUPONTY, TlIOUGHT IN Ti lE OPEN
I1Yay"e J. from""
m

'". IIEIDEGG ER AND ADORNO


lain Macdonald '"
". HEIDEGGER AND LEVINAS
Jil/ 51"4(,,
m

SO HEIDEGGER AND DERRJD;\


F",nfois Raffoul '"'
'L HEIDEGGER AND FOUCAULT
Leona,d Lawlor '"'
;>. H EIDEGGER AND DELEUz'E
A",/rca j""". Sho/lo ""'/ Leo"",d L"w/or '"
B. IIEIDE GGER'S ANGLO AME RICAN RECEPTION m
Le,/'. MacAIIOJI
H. H EIDEGGER AND ENVIRONMENTAL PHILOSOPIIY W
hi.h GI"o.ehwok
;;. IIElDEGG ER AND GEN DER, AN UNCANNY RETRIEVAL OF
IJEGEL'S ANTIGONE
Tina Chamer '"
,.. IIEIDEGGER AND POSTCARTESIAN PSYCHOANALYSIS
Robert D. Stolo. ou, '"
". HEIDE GGER AND AS IAN PHILOSOPHY
B,er W. Da"i, '"
". HEIDEGG ER AND LATIN A)o.!E RIC,\ N PHILOSOPHY
AI~ia"dm
A ,Iu"" Val/ega
m

InJcx m

VII'
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

Organizing an edited volume such as this requires the cooperation and assistance of many
individuals from family and friends to colleagues, contributors, editors, and external review-
ers. An anthology is the most social form of publishing and we are each thankful to all those
individualsfirst and foremost our contributorswho have directly and indirectly made its
publication possible. We would particularly like to express our gratitude to Iain Thomson
for suggesting that we pursue this volume and our editors at Continuum/Bloomsbury, David
Avital, Sarah Campbell and Rachel Eisenhauer. We thank them for their patience and con-
fidence. Our gratitude to Delbert Burkett, Seynaeve Professor of Biblical Studies and Chair
of the Department of Philosophy and Religious Studies at Louisiana State University, for his
advice and support. We also want to thank Alice Frye for her patient encouragement and
assistance as well as Meli Badilla for her generous support and lively spirit.

ix
LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS

GERMAN EDITION
(GA): Martin Heideggers Gesamtausgabe (Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann,
1978)
GA 1: Frhe Schriften, ed. Friedrich-Wilhelm von Herrmann, 1978
GA 2: Sein und Zeit (1927), ed. Friedrich Wilhelm von Herrmann, 1977
GA 3: Kant und das Problem der Metaphysik (1929), ed. Friedrich-Wilhelm von Herrmann,
2nd edn, 2010
GA 4: Erluterungen zu Hlderlins Dichtung (193668), ed. Friedrich-Wilhelm von
Herrmann, 1981
GA 5: Holzwege, ed. Friedrich-Wilhelm von Hermann, 1977
GA 6.1: Nietzsche I (19369), ed. Brigitte Schillbach, 1996
GA 6.2: Nietzsche II (193946), ed. Brigitte Schillbach, 1997
GA 7: Vortrge und Aufstze (193653), ed. Friedrich-Wilhelm von Herrmann, 2000
GA 8: Was heit Denken? (19512), ed. Paola-Ludovika Coriando, 2002
GA 9: Wegmarken, ed. Friedrich-Wilhelm von Hermann, 1976
GA 11: Identitt und Differenz (19557), ed. Friedrich-Wilhelm von Herrmann, 2006
GA 12: Unterwegs zur Sprache, ed. Friedrich-Wilhelm von Herrmann, 1985
GA 13: Aus der Erfahrung des Denkens, ed. Hermann Heidegger, 1983
GA 14: Zur Sache des Denkens, ed. Friedrich-Wilhelm von Herrmann, 1962
GA 15: Seminare, ed, Curd Ochwadt, 1981
GA 16: Reden und andere Zeugnisse eines Lebensweges, ed. Hermann Heidegger, 2000
GA 18: Grundbegriffe der aristotelischen Philosophie, ed. M. Michalski, 2002
GA 19: Platon: Sophistes, ed. Ingeborg Schler, 1992
GA 20: Geschichte des Zeitbegriffs. Prolegomena zur Phnomenologie von Geschichte und
Natur, ed. Petra Jaeger, 3rd edn, 1994
GA 21: Logik. Die Frage nach der Wahrheit, ed. Walter Biemel, 2nd edn, 1995
GA 22: Die Grundbegriffe der antiken Philosophie, ed. Franz-Karl Blust, 1993
GA 23: Geschichte der Philosophie von Thomas von Aquin bis Kant, ed. H. Vetter, 2006

x
LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS

GA 24: Die Grundprobleme der Phnomenologie, ed. Friedrich-Wilhelm von Hermann,


3rd edn, 1997
GA 25: Phnomenologische Interpretation von Kants Kritik der reinen Vernunft, ed.
I.Grland, 3rd edn, 1995
GA 26: Logik. Metaphysische Anfangsgrnde der Logik im Ausgang von Leibniz, ed.
Friedrich-Wilhelm von Herrmann, 1990
GA 27: Einleitung in die Philosophie, ed. O. Saame et I. Saame-Speidel, 2nd edn, 2001
GA 28: Der deutsche Idealismus (Fichte, Schelling, Hegel) und die philosophische
Problemlage der Gegenwart, Claudius Strube, 2nd edn, 2011
GA 29/30: Die Grundbegriffe der Metaphysik. WeltEndlichkeitEinsamkeit, ed. Friedrich-
Wilhelm von Herrmann, 3rd edn, 2004
GA 31: Vom Wesen der menschlichen Freiheit. Einleitung in die Philosophie, ed. H. Tietjen,
2nd edn, 1994
GA 32: Hegels Phnomenologie des Geistes, ed. I. Grland, 3rd edn, 1997
GA 33: Aristoteles, Metaphysik J 13. Von Wesen und Wirklichkeit der Kraft, ed. H. Hni,
3rd edn, 2006
GA 34: Vom Wesen der Wahrheit. Zu Platons Hhlengleichnis und Thetet, ed. Hermann
Mrchen, 1988
GA 35: Der Anfang der abendlndischen Philosophie: Auslegung des Anaximander und
Parmenides, ed. Peter Trawny, 2012
GA 36/37: Sein und Wahrheit, ed. H. Tietjen, 2001
GA 38: Logik als die Frage nach dem Wesen der Sprache, ed. G.Seubold, 1998
GA 39: Hlderlins Hymnen Germanien und Der Rhein, ed. Susanne Ziegler, 1980
GA 40: Einfhrung in die Metaphysik, ed. Petra Jaeger, 1983
GA 41: Die Frage nach dem Ding, ed. Petra Jaeger, 1984
GA 42: Schelling: Vom Wesen der menschlichen Freiheit, ed. Ingrid Schssler, 1988
GA 43: Nietzsche: Der Wille zur Macht als Kunst, ed. Bernd Heimbchel, 1985
GA 44: Nietzsches metaphysische Grundstellung im abendlndischen Denken: Die
ewige Wiederkehr des Gleichen, ed. Marion Heinz, 1986
GA 45: Grundfragen der Philosophie: Ausgewhlte Probleme der Logik, ed. Friedrich-
Wilhelm von Herrmann, 1984
GA 46: Zur Auslegung von Nietzsches II. Unzeitgemer Betrachtung Vom Nutzen und
Nachteil der Historie fr das Leben (193839). Ed. Hans-Joachim Friedrich,
2003
GA 47: Nietzsches Lehre vom Willen zur Macht als Erkenntnis, ed. E. Hanser, 1989
GA 48: Nietzsche: Der europasche Nihilismus, ed. Petra Jaeger, 1986
GA 49: Die Metaphysik des deutschen Idealismus. Zur erneuten Auslegung von Schelling:
Philosophische Untersuchungen ber das Wesen der menschlichen Freiheit und
die damit zusammenhngenden Gegenstnde (1809), ed. G. Seubold, 1991
GA 50: Nietzsches Metaphysik, ed. Petra Jaeger, 1990
GA 52: Hlderlins Hymne Andenken, ed. Curd Ochwadt, 1982
GA 53: Hlderlins Hynme Der Ister, ed. Walter Biemel, 1982
GA 54: Parmenides, ed. Manfred S. Frings, 1982

xi
LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS

GA 55: Heraklit, ed. Manfred S. Frings, 1994


GA 56/57: Zur Bestimmung der Philosophie, ed. Bern Heimbchel, 1987
GA 58: Grundprobleme der Phnomenologie, ed. Hans-Helmuth Gander, 1992
GA 59: Phnomenologie der Anschauung und des Ausdrucks. Theorie der philosophischen
Begriffsbildung, ed. C. Strube, 1993
GA 60: Phnomenologie des religisen Lebens, ed. Matthias Jung, Thomas Regehly, and
Claudius Strube, 1995
GA 61: Phnomenologische Interpretationen zu Aristoteles. Einfhrung in die phnome-
nologische Forschung, ed. Walter Brcker and Kte Brcker-Oltmanns, 2nd edn,
1994
GA 62: Phnomenologische Interpretation ausgewhlter Abhandlungen des Aristoteles
zu Ontologie und Logik, ed. G. Neumann, 2005
GA 63: Ontologie. Hermeneutik der Faktizitt, ed. K. Brcker-Oltmanns, 1988; 2nd
edn, 1995
GA 64: Der Begriff der Zeit (1924), ed. Friedrich-Wilhelm von Herrmann, 2004
GA 65: Beitrge zur Philosophie (vom Ereignis), ed. Friedrich-Wilhelm von Herrmann,
1989
GA 66: Besinnung, ed. Friedrich-Wilhelm von Herrmann, 1997
GA 67: Metaphysik und Nihilismus, ed. H.-J. Friedrich, 1999
GA 68: Hegel, ed. I. Schssler, 1993
GA 69: Gedachtes. Die Geschichte des Seyns, ed. Peter Trawny, 2012
GA 70: ber den Anfang (1941), ed. Friedrich-Wilhelm von Herrmann, 2005
GA 71: Das Ereignis, ed. Friedrich-Wilhelm von Herrmann, 2009
GA 72: Die Stege des Anfangs (1944), ed. Friedrich-Wilhelm von Herrmann, forthcoming
GA 73: Zum Ereignis-Denken, ed. Hans-Joachim Friedrich, forthcoming
GA 74: Zum Wesen der Sprache und Zur Frage nach der Kunst, 2010
GA 75: Zu Hlderlin / Griechenlandreisen, ed. C. Ochwadt, 2000
GA 77: Feldweg-Gesprche (1944/45), ed. Ingrid Schssler, 1995
GA 78: Der Spruch des Anaximander (1942), ed. Ingeborg Schler, 2010
GA 79: Bremer und Freiburger Vortrge, ed. P. Jaeger, 1994
GA 86: Seminare HegelSchelling, ed. Peter Trawny, 2011
GA 87: Seminare Nietzsche, ed. P. von Ruckteschell, 2004
GA 88: Seminare (bungen) 1937/8 und 1941/2:
1.Die metaphysischen Grundstellungen des abendlndischen Denkens, ed. Alfred
Denker, 2008;
2.Einbung in das philosophische Denken, ed. Alfred Denker, 2008
GA 89: Zollikoner Seminare, ed. Medard Boss, 2006
GA 90: Zu Ernst Jnger Der Arbeiter, ed. Peter Trawny, 2004

OTHER TEXTS
EM: Einfhrung in die Metaphysik, 5th edn (Tbingen: Max Niemeyer, 1987)
N1: Nietzsche. Erster Band, 5th edn (Pfullingen: Neske, 1989)
N2: Nietzsche. Zweiter Band, 5th edn (Pfullingen: Neske, 1989)

xii
LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS

SZ: Sein und Zeit (Tbingen: Max Niemeyer Verlag, 1953)


VA: Vortrge und Aufstze, 7th edn (Pfullingen: Neske, 1994)
WhD: Was heit Denken? 4th edn (Tbingen: Max Niemeyer, 1984)
Z: Zollikoner Seminare: ProtokolleZwiegesprcheBriefe (Frankfurt am Main:
Klostermann, 1997/2006)
ZSD: Zur Sache des Denkens, 3rd edn (Tbingen: Max Niemeyer, 1988)

English Translations
AM: Aristotles Metaphysics Theta 13 On the Essence and Actuality of Force, trans.
Walter Brogan and Peter Warnek (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1995)
BAT: Being and Truth, trans. Gregory Fried and Richard Polt (Bloomington: Indiana
University Press, 2010)
BCAP: Basic Concepts of Ancient Philosophy, trans. Richard Rojcewicz (Bloomington:
Indiana University Press, 2007)
BCAR: Basic Concepts of Aristotelian Philosophy, trans. Robert D. Metcalf and Mark B.
Tanzer (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2009)
BFL: Bremen and Freiburg Lectures: Insight into That Which Is and Basic Principles of
Thinking, trans. Andrew J. Mitchell (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2012)
BH: Becoming Heidegger: On the Trail of His Early Occasional Writings, 19101927,
ed. Theodore J Kisiel and Thomas Sheehan (Evanston: Northwestern University
Press, 2007)
BP: The Basic Problems of Phenomenology, trans. A. Hofstadter (Bloomington: Indiana
University Press, 1982; rev. edn, 1988)
BQP: Basic Questions of Philosophy: Selected Problems of Logic, trans. Richard
Rojcewicz and Andre Schuwer (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1994)
BT: Being and Time, trans. Joan Stambaugh. Revised and with a Foreword by Dennis J.
Schmidt (Albany: SUNY Press, 2010)
BTMR: Being and Time, trans. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson (New York: Harper,
1962)
BW: Basic Writings, rev. and exp. edn, ed. David Farrell Krell (San Francisco: Harper,
1993)
CP1: Contributions to Philosophy (From Enowning), trans. Parvis Emad and Kenneth
Maly (Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 1999)
CP2: Contributions to Philosophy: Of the Event, trans. Richard Rojcewicz and Daniela
Vallega-Neu (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2012)
CPC: Country Path Conversations, trans. Bret W. Davis (Bloomington, Indiana University
Press, 2010)
CT: The Concept of Time, trans. William McNeill (Oxford, Blackwell, 1992)
DT: Discourse on Thinking, trans. John M. Anderson and E. Hans Freund (New York:
Harper & Row, 1966)
EGT: Early Greek Thinking, trans. David F. Krell and Frank A. Capuzzi (New York:
Harper & Row, 1975)

xiii
LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS

EHF: The Essence of Human Freedom, trans. Ted Sadler (London: Continuum, 2002)
EHP: Elucidations of Hlderlins Poetry, trans. and introduction by Keith Hoeller
(Amherst, NY: Humanity Books, 2000)
ET: The Essence of Truth. On Platos Cave Allegory and Theaetatus, trans. Ted Sadler
(London Continuum, 2002)
FCM: The Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics: World, Finitude, Solitude, trans. William
McNeill and Nicholas Walker (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1995)
FS: Four Seminars, trans. Andrew Mitchell and Franois Raffoul (Bloomington:
Indiana University Press, 2003)
HCT: History of the Concept of Time: Prolegomena, trans. Theodore Kisiel (Bloomington:
Indiana University Press, 1985)
HHTI: Hlderlins Hymn The Ister, trans. William McNeill and Julia Davis
(Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1996)
HPS: Hegels Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. Parvis Emad and Kenneth Maly
(Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1988)
HR: The Heidegger Reader (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2009)
HS: Heraclitus Seminar, 1966/67 (Tuscaloosa, AL: University of Alabama Press, 1979)
ID: Identity and Difference, trans. Joan Stambaugh (New York: Harper & Row, 1969)
IM: Introduction to Metaphysics, trans. Gregory Fried and Richard Polt (New Haven,
CN: Yale University Press, 2000)
IPTP: Introduction to PhilosophyThinking and Poetizing, trans. Phillip Jacques
Braunstein (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2011)
KPM: Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics, trans. Richard Taft (Bloomington: Indiana
University Press, 1997)
LEL: Logic as the Question Concerning the Essence of Language, trans. Wanda Torres
Gregory and Yvonne Unna (Albany: SUNY Press, 2009)
MFL: The Metaphysical Foundations of Logic, trans. Michael Heim (Bloomington:
Indiana University Press, 1984)
NI: Nietzsche I: The Will to Power as Art, ed. and trans. David F. Krell (New York:
Harper & Row, 1979)
NII: Nietzsche II: The Eternal Recurrence of the Same, ed. and trans. David F. Krell
(New York: Harper & Row, 1984)
NIII: Nietzsche III: The Will to Power as Knowledge and Metaphysics, ed. David F. Krell,
trans. Joan Stambaugh (New York: Harper & Row, 1987)
NIV: Nietzsche IV: Nihilism, ed. David F. Krell, trans. Frank A. Capuzzi (New York,
Harper & Row, 1982)
OBT: Off The Beaten Track, ed. and trans. Julian Young and Kenneth Haynes (New York:
Cambridge University Press, 2002)
OHF: Ontology: The Hermeneutics of Facticity, trans. John van Buren (Bloomington:
Indiana University Press, 1999)
OWL: On the Way to Language (New York: Harper & Row, 1971)
P: Parmenides, trans. Andre Schuwer and Richard Rojcewicz (Bloomington: Indiana
University Press, 1992)

xiv
LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS

PA: Pathmarks, ed. William McNeill (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998)
PIA: Phenomenological Interpretations of Aristotle: Initiation into Phenomenological
Research, trans. Richard Rojcewicz (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2001)
PIA2: Phenomenological Interpretations in Connection with Aristotle: An Indication of
the Hermeneutical Situation, trans. John van Buren, in Heidegger, ed. John van
Buren, Supplements: From the Earliest Essays to Being and Time and Beyond (State
University of New York Press, 2002)
PICPR: Phenomenological Interpretation of Kants Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Parvis
Emad and Kenneth Maly (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1997)
PIE: Phenomenology of Intuition and Expression: Theory of Philosophical Concept
Formation, trans. Tracy Colony (London, Continuum, 2010)
PLT: Poetry, Language, Thought, trans. Albert Hofstadter (New York: Harper & Row,
1971)
PRL: The Phenomenology of Religious Life, trans. Matthias Fritsch and Jennifer Anna
Gosetti-Ferencei (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2004)
PS: Platos Sophist, trans. Richard Rojcewicz and Andre Schuwer (Bloomington:
Indiana University Press, 1997)
PT: The Piety of Thinking, trans. James G. Hart and John C. Maraldo (Bloomington,
Indiana University Press, 1976)
QCT: The Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays, trans. William Lovitt
(NewYork: Harper & Row, 1977)
S: Supplements, ed. John Van Buren (Albany: SUNY Press, 2002)
STEHF: Schellings Treatise on the Essence of Human Freedom, trans. Joan Stambaugh
(Athens, Ohio University Press, 1984)
TB: On Time and Being (New York: Harper & Row, 1972)
TDP: Towards the Definition of Philosophy, trans. Ted Sadler (London: Continuum,
2002)
WCT: What Is Called Thinking? trans. Fred D. Wieck and J. Glenn Gray (New York:
Harper & Row, 1968)
WIP: What Is Philosophy? trans. Jean T. Wilde and William Kluback (New Haven:
College and University Press, 1958)
WIT: What Is a Thing? trans. W. B. Barton, Jr. and Vera Deutsch (Chicago: Henry Regnery
Company, 1967)
ZS: Zollikon Seminars, ed. Medard Boss, trans. Franz K. Mayr and Richard R. Askay
(Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 2001)

xv
NOTES ON CONTRIBUTORS

Kevin Aho is Associate Professor of Philosophy at Florida Gulf Coast University. He has
published widely on Heidegger, phenomenology, and hermeneutics and is the author of
Heideggers Neglect of the Body (Albany: SUNY Press, 2009), coauthor (with James Aho)
of Body Matters: A Phenomenology of Sickness, Illness, and Disease (Lanham: Lexington
Books, 2008), and coeditor (with Charles Guignon) of a new edition of Dostoevskys Notes
from the Underground (Indianapolis: Hackett, 2009). He is currently completing a mono-
graph entitled Existentialism: An Introduction.

Emilia Angelova is Associate Professor of Philosophy at Trent University, Ontario, Canada,


and in 201213 is Visiting Scholar at Concordia University, Montreal. Her research is
in Twentieth-Century Continental Philosophy and Kant, including Nineteenth-Century
Continental Philosophy. Recent work has been directed to study of themes raised by Kant
and transformed by Heidegger, interpreting selfhood, temporality, freedom, and the imag-
ination. Her publications include articles in Idealistic Studies, Symposium, and Journal of
Contemporary Thought, and the forthcoming work: Hegel and Deleuze on Life, Sense
and Limit, in Hegel and Deleuze (Evanston: Northwestern University Press); and Times
Disquiet and Unrest: Affinity Between Heidegger and Levinas, in Between Heidegger and
Levinas (Albany: State University of New York Press). She is completing a book manuscript
on Heideggers reading of Kant from Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics and is the editor
of an anthology, Hegel, Freedom, and History (Toronto: University of Toronto Press).

Robert Bernasconi is Edwin Erle Sparks Professor Philosophy at Pennsylvania State


University. He is the author of The Question of Language in Heideggers History of Being
(Amherst: Humanity Books, 1985), Heidegger in Question (Atlantic Highlands: Humanities
Press, 1993), and How to Read Sartre (New York: W.W. Norton & Co., 2007). In addition
to his work on Heidegger and Sartre he has published extensively on Kant, Hegel, Levinas,
Derrida, Sartre, Fanon, and numerous topics on the critical philosophy of race. Together
with Paul Taylor and Kathryn Gines he is the editor of the journal Critical Philosophy of
Race.

xvi
NOTES ON CONTRIBUTORS

Peg Birmingham is Professor of Philosophy at DePaul University. She is the author of Hannah
Arendt and Human Rights (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2006) and coeditor (with
Philippe van Haute) of Dissensus Communis: Between Ethics and Politics (Kampen: Koros,
1995). She has published in journals such as Research in Phenomenology, Hypatia, and The
Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal on topics that include radical evil, human rights, and
the temporality of the political. She is currently working on a manuscript tentatively titled
Hannah Arendt and Political Glory: Bearing the Unbearable.

Andrew Bowie is Professor of Philosophy and German at Royal Holloway, University of


London. He has published very widely on modern philosophy, music, and literature, and is
a jazz saxophonist. His books are Aesthetics and Subjectivity: from Kant to Nietzsche (2nd
edn Manchester: Manchester University Press, 2003); Schelling and Modern European
Philosophy (London: Routledge, 2002); Introduction to, edition and translation of F.W.J.
von Schelling: On the History of Modern Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1994); From Romanticism to Critical Theory. The Philosophy of German Literary
Theory (London; New York: Routledge, 1997); Introduction to and Editor of Manfred Frank:
The Subject and the Text (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997); Introduction
to, edition and translation of F.D.E. Schleiermacher, Hermeneutics and Criticism and
Other Writings (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998); Introduction to German
Philosophy from Kant to Habermas (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2003); Music, Philosophy, and
Modernity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007); Philosophical Variations: Music
as Philosophical Language (Malm: NSU Press, 2010); and The Very Short Introduction to
German Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010). His Adorno and the Ends of
Philosophy will be published by Polity Press in September 2013.

Lee Braver is Associate Professor of Philosophy at the University of South Florida. He is


the author of A Thing of This World: A History of Continental Anti-Realism (Evanston:
Northwestern University Press, 2007), Heideggers Later Writings: A Readers Guide (London:
Continuum, 2009), and Groundless Grounds: A Study of Wittgenstein and Heidegger
(Cambridge: MIT Press, 2012), as well as number of articles and book chapters. He is pres-
ently working on two books: Heidegger: Thinking of Being, and Unthinkable.

Scott M. Campbell is Professor and Chair of the Philosophy Department at Nazareth College
in Rochester, New York. He has written on issues in education and communication, especially
as these relate to the notion of the practical in the early work of Martin Heidegger. He has
published The Early Heideggers Philosophy of Life (New York: Fordham University Press,
2012) and a translation of Heideggers Basic Problems of Phenomenology from the Winter
Semester of 1919/1920 (London: Continuum, 2012). Together with Paul W. Bruno, he has
coedited a volume of essays entitled The Science, Politics, and Ontology of Life-philosophy
(London: Continuum, 2013).

Tina Chanter is Professor of Philosophy at DePaul University. She is currently on a visit-


ing appointment at the University of West England, Bristol, UK. She is author of Whose

xvii
NOTES ON CONTRIBUTORS

Antigone? The Tragic Marginalization of Slavery (Albany: SUNY Press, 2011), The Picture of
Abjection: Film Fetish and the Nature of Difference (Bloomington: Indiana University Press,
2008), Gender (London: Continuum Press, 2006), Time, Death and the Feminine: Levinas
with Heidegger (Stanford University Press, 2001), Ethics of Eros: Irigarays Re-writing of the
Philosophers (London: Routledge, 1995). She is also the editor of Feminist Interpretations
of Emmanuel Levinas (University Park: Penn State University Press, 2001), and coeditor of
Revolt, Affect, Collectivity: The Unstable Boundaries of Kristevas Polis (Albany: SUNY Press,
2005), and of Sarah Kofmans Corpus (Albany: SUNY Press, 2008). In addition, she edits the
Gender Theory series at SUNY Press. Her current book, forthcoming with Continuum, is Art,
Politics and Rancire: Seeing Things Anew.

Daniel O. Dahlstrom is Professor of Philosophy at Boston University. In addition to trans-


lating Heideggers first Marburg lectures, Introduction to Phenomenological Research
(Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2005), he is the editor of Interpreting Heidegger:
Critical Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011) and the founding editor of
Gatherings, The Heidegger Circle Annual. His book-length publications on Heidegger include
Heideggers Conception of Truth (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001, 2009) and
The Heidegger Dictionary (London: Bloomsbury, 2013).

Franoise Dastur is an honorary professor of philosophy and attached to the Husserl Archives
of Paris (ENS Ulm). She taught at the University of Paris I (Sorbonne) from 1969 to 1995,
at the University of Paris XII (Crteil) from 1995 to 1999, and at the University of Nice
Sophia Antipolis from 1999 to 2003. She is the honorary President of the Ecole Franaise of
Daseinsanalyse, which she founded in 1993. She is the author of several books in French from
which three have been translated into English: Heidegger and the Question of Time (Amherst:
Humanity Books, 1998), Telling Time, Sketch of a Phenomenological Chronology (New
Brunswick: Athlone Press, 2000), and Death, An Essay on Finitude (New Brunswick: Athlone
Press, 1996). Her latest publications include Heidegger. La question du logos (Paris: Vrin,
2007), La mort. Essai sur la finitude (Expanded edition, Paris: PUF, 2007), Daseinsanalyse.
Phnomnologie et psychiatrie, coauthored with Ph. Cabestan (Paris: Vrin, 2011), and
Heidegger et la pense venir (Paris: Vrin, 2011).

Bret W. Davis is Associate Professor of Philosophy at Loyola University, Maryland. He


received his PhD in philosophy from Vanderbilt University and has spent 13 years studying
and teaching in Japan, during which time he completed the coursework for a second PhD in
Japanese philosophy at Kyoto University. He is the author of Heidegger and the Will: On the
Way to Gelassenheit (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 2007), translator of Martin
Heideggers Country Path Conversations (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2010),
editor of Martin Heidegger: Key Concepts (Durham: Acumen, 2010), coeditor of Japanese
and Continental Philosophy: Conversations with the Kyoto School (Bloomington: Indiana
University Press, 2011), and coeditor of Sekai no naka no Nihon no tetsugaku [Japanese
Philosophy in the World] (Kyto: Showado, 2005). He has also written more than 40articles

xviii
NOTES ON CONTRIBUTORS

in English and in Japanese. Among his current projects are two monographs on Zen and the
Kyoto School respectively, and The Oxford Handbook of Japanese Philosophy.

Alfred Denker is Director of the Martin-Heidegger-Archive and the Martin-Heidegger-Museum


in Messkirch, Baden-Wrttemberg, Germany. He has edited and coedited numerous antholo-
gies as well as works and letters of Heidegger, including the Heidegger-Jahrbuch (Freiburg:
Karl Alber, 2004ongoing) and the Martin-Heidegger-Briefausgabe (Freiburg: Karl Alber,
2010ongoing). His publications also include the recent book Unterwegs in Sein und Zeit.
Einfhrung in sein Leben und Werk (Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta, 2011).

Andrew Feenberg is Canada Research Chair in Philosophy of Technology in the School


of Communication, Simon Fraser University, Canada, where he directs the Applied
Communication and Technology Lab. His books include Heidegger and Marcuse: The
Catastrophe and Redemption of History (London: Routledge, 2005), Between Reason and
Experience: Essays in Technology and Modernity (Cambridge: MIT Press, 2010), and a coed-
ited collection entitled The Essential Marcuse (Boston: Beacon, 2007). A book on Feenbergs
philosophy of technology entitled Democratizing Technology appeared in 2006 with the
SUNY Press. His forthcoming book Realizing Philosophy: Marx, Lukcs and the Frankfurt
School will be published by Verso Press in 2014.

Gregory Fried received his BA from Harvard College and his MA and PhD from the University
of Chicago. He is the Chair of the Philosophy Department at Suffolk University, and he has
taught at the University of Chicago, Boston University, and UCLA. His research has focused
on defending the classical Enlightenment tradition against some of its most serious critics,
most particularly Martin Heidegger. He is the author of Heideggers Polemos: From Being to
Politics (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2000). With Richard Polt, he is also the transla-
tor of two of Heideggers works, Introduction to Metaphysics (New Haven: Yale University
Press, 2000) and Being and Truth (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2010); they have
a third Heidegger translation forthcoming in 2013: Nature, History, State. Together with his
father, Fried is the author of Because It Is Wrong: Torture, Privacy and Presidential Power in
the Age of Terror (New York: W.W. Norton & Co., 2010), an exploration of moral, legal, and
political questions in the post-9/11 world. Fried is also Director of The Mirror of Race Project
(www.mirrorofrace.org), an online, interdisciplinary project exploring the meaning of race in
Americas history.

Wayne J. Froman teaches philosophy at George Mason University where he served as


Department Chair from 1989 to 1999. In 19956 he held a Fulbright Research Professorship
at the Hegel Archive, Ruhr Universitt, Bochum. He has published numerous articles in
phenomenology and related topics. He has also edited and coedited a number of volumes,
including, most recently, Merleau-Ponty and the Possibilities of Philosophy: Transforming the
Tradition (Albany: State University of New York Press, 2009). He is currently working on a
comparative study of the thought of Franz Rosenzweig with that of Martin Heidegger.

xix
NOTES ON CONTRIBUTORS

Trish Glazebrook received a PhD in philosophy from the University of Toronto. She has
taught at Colgate University, Syracuse University, and Dalhousie University. She currently
chairs the Department of Philosophy & Religion Studies at the University of North Texas
and is a Research Fellow at Osun State University in Nigeria. She has published Heideggers
Philosophy of Science (New York: Fordham University Press, 2000), and edited Heidegger on
Science (Albany: State University of New York Press, 2012). She is coeditor of a 2012 issue of
Inflexions on the architecture of Arakawa and Gins, and has published numerous papers in
Heidegger studies, ecophenomenology, ancient philosophy, climate ethics, and international
development studies. Her current research addresses impacts of climate change on women
farmers in Ghana, and governance and policy issues in Ghanas oil industry.

Peter E. Gordon is Amabel B. James Professor of History and Harvard College Professor at
Harvard University. A faculty affiliate of the Minda de Gunzburg Center for European Studies,
Gordon is also cofounder of the Harvard Colloquium for Intellectual History. His books
include: Rosenzweig and Heidegger: Between Judaism and German Philosophy (Berkeley:
University of California Press, 2003); and Continental Divide: Heidegger, Cassirer, Davos
(Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2010). He is coeditor of several books, including: The
Cambridge Companion to Modern Jewish Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2007), The Modernist Imagination: Critical Theory and Intellectual History Essays in
Honor of Martin Jay (New York: Berghahn Books, 2009), and Weimar Thought: A Contested
Legacy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2013). He is the recipient of numerous fel-
lowships and awards, including the Jacques Barzun Prize from the American Philosophical
Society.

Ullrich Haase is Principal Lecturer and Head of Philosophy at the Manchester Metropolitan
University. He is also the editor of the Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology.
Over the last years his research has been turning around the relation between Heideggers
and Nietzsches thought in order to open an understanding of the question of modern sci-
ence in the twenty-first century. He has published various essays on these two authors as
well as on Hegel, Merleau-Ponty, Blanchot, and Bataille. In 2008 he published an introduc-
tion to the work of Friedrich Nietzsche with Continuum Publishers. He is currently working
on a translation of Heideggers lecture course on Nietzsches second Untimely Meditation
(GA 46).

Kirsten Jacobson is Associate Professor of Philosophy at the University of Maine. Her


research interests include the study of spatiality, existential psychology, and, more generally,
the philosophical significance and status of the phenomenological method. She has devel-
oped novel interpretations of spatial neglect, agoraphobia, hypochondria, and anorexia, and
explored the political significance of our spatial inhabitation. Her recent publications include
Embodied Domestics, Embodied Politics: Women, Home, and Agoraphobia (Human
Studies, 34, 1, 2011), The Experience of Home and the Space of Citizenship (The Southern
Journal of Philosophy, 48, 3, 2010), and A Developed Nature: A Phenomenological Account
of the Experience of Home (Continental Philosophy Review, 42, 2009). Currently, she is

xx
NOTES ON CONTRIBUTORS

developing a holistic view of health that is demanded, but not yet provided, by longstanding
efforts in phenomenology to overcome the dualism of self and world.

Sean D. Kirkland is Associate Professor in the Department of Philosophy at DePaul University.


He works in the areas of ancient Greek philosophy and contemporary continental philoso-
phy. He published a monograph with SUNY Press in 2012 entitled The Ontology of Socratic
Questioning in Platos Early Dialogues and he is currently finishing his second book, ten-
tatively titled Aristotle and the Ecstatic Present, which undertakes a study of temporality
in Aristotles Physics, Ethics, Politics, Rhetoric, and Poetics. He has written articles on sub-
jects ranging from Plato and Aristotle to Greek tragedy, from Heideggers phenomenological
thought to Nietzsches philosophy of history.

Theodore Kisiel is Distinguished Research Professor emeritus of philosophy at Northern


Illinois University, author of The Genesis of Heideggers Being and Time (Berkeley: University
of California Press, 1993), and coeditor, with Tom Sheehan, of Becoming Heidegger: On
the Trail of his Early Occasional Writings, 19101927 (Evanston: Northwestern University
Press, 2007), which has been published in a second revised edition as The New Yearbook for
Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy IX (Seattle: Noesis Press, 2009). He is
currently working on a sequel volume entitled The Demise and Destruction of Heideggers
Being and Time.

Leonard Lawlor is Edwin Erle Sparks Professor of Philosophy at Penn State University. He is
the author of seven books: Early Twentieth Century Continental Philosophy (Bloomington:
Indiana University Press, 2011); This is not Sufficient: An Essay on Animality in Derrida
(New York: Columbia University Press, 2007); The Implications of Immanence: Towards a
New Concept of Life (New York: Fordham University Press, 2006); Thinking Through French
Philosophy: The Being of the Question (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2003); The
Challenge of Bergsonism: Phenomenology, Ontology, Ethics (London: Continuum, 2003);
Derrida and Husserl: The Basic Problem of Phenomenology (Bloomington: Indiana University
Press, 2002); and Imagination and Chance: The Difference Between the Thought of Ricoeur
and Derrida (Albany: SUNY Press, 1992). He is one of the coeditors and cofounders of
Chiasmi International: Trilingual Studies Concerning the Thought of Merleau-Ponty. He has
translated Merleau-Ponty, Derrida, and Hyppolite into English. He has written dozens of arti-
cles on Derrida, Foucault, Deleuze, Bergson, and Merleau-Ponty. He is currently working on
two books: Is it Happening? (for Edinburgh University Press), and (coauthored with Vernon
Cisney) a Guide to Derridas Voice and Phenomenon (for Edinburgh University Press).

Leslie MacAvoy is Associate Professor of Philosophy and Chair of the Department of


Philosophy and Humanities at East Tennessee State University. She works on issues per-
taining to phenomenological conceptions of subjectivity and meaning. Her essays include
On the Unity of Intelligibility in Heidegger: Against Distinguishing the Practical and the
Discursive, Philosophy Today 55 (2011); Meaning, Categories, and Subjectivity in the Early
Heidegger, Philosophy and Social Criticism 31(1) (2005); The Other Side of Intentionality,

xxi
NOTES ON CONTRIBUTORS

in Addressing Levinas. Ethics, Phenomenology and the Judaic Tradition, eds Eric Nelson,
Antje Kapust, and Kent Still (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 2005); Thinking
through Singularity and Universality in Levinas, Philosophy Today 47(5) (2003), and
Overturning Cartesianism and the Hermeneutics of Suspicion: Rethinking Dreyfus on
Heidegger, Inquiry 44(4) (December 2001). She is currently doing research on the concept
of meaning and its relationship to temporality in the phenomenological work of Husserl,
Heidegger, and Levinas.

John McCumber is Professor of Germanic Languages at UCLA. His PhD is in Philosophy


and Greek from the University of Toronto, and he has taught in philosophy departments
there and at the University of Michigan-Dearborn, the Graduate Faculty of the New School
for Social Research, Northwestern University, UCLA, and John Carroll University. He has
also taught in the German Departments of Northwestern University and UCLA and in the
Classics and Political Science Departments at UCLA. He is the author of many books and
articles on the history of philosophy, including most recently Time and Philosophy: A History
of Continental Thought (Durham: Acumen, 2011) and On Philosophy: Notes from a Crisis
(Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2013). He is currently preparing a book on American
philosophy in the early Cold War.

Iain Macdonald is professeur agrg (Associate Professor) in the Department of Philosophy,


Universit de Montral, and president of the Canadian Society for Continental Philosophy. He
is the author of many articles in English and French on Hegel, Adorno, Heidegger, Nietzsche,
Terrence Malick, and Paul Celan, among othersin the areas of metaphysics, epistemology,
and aesthetics. He is coeditor of Adorno and Heidegger: Philosophical Questions (Stanford:
Stanford University Press, 2008) and of Les normes et le possible: hritage et perspectives
de lcole de Francfort (ditions de la maison des sciences de lhomme, forthcoming 2013).
His current work deals with the relation of possibility to actuality, especially in Hegel, Marx,
Critical Theory, and Heidegger.

William McNeill is Professor of Philosophy at DePaul University in Chicago. He is author of


The Glance of the Eye: Heidegger, Aristotle, and the Ends of Theory (Albany: SUNY Press,
1999) and The Time of Life: Heidegger and thos (Albany: SUNY Press, 2006). He has trans-
lated or cotranslated a number of Heideggers works, including (with Julia Davis) the lectures
on Hlderlins Hymn The Ister (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1996). He is cur-
rently completing the translation, together with Julia Ireland, of Heideggers first Hlderlin
lecture course, Hlderlins Hymns Germania and The Rhine (forthcoming with Indiana
University Press).

Andrew J. Mitchell is Assistant Professor at Emory University where he specializes in


nineteenth- and twentieth-century continental philosophy and the philosophy of literature.
He is the author of Heidegger Among the Sculptors: Body, Space, and the Art of Dwelling
(Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2010), translator of Martin Heideggers Bremen and
Freiburg Lectures (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2012), coeditor with Sam Slote of

xxii
NOTES ON CONTRIBUTORS

Derrida and Joyce: Texts and Contexts (Albany: SUNY Press, 2013), and is currently com-
pleting a manuscript on Heideggers conception of the fourfold.

Dermot Moran holds the Professorship of Philosophy (Metaphysics & Logic) at University
College Dublin and is a Member of the Royal Irish Academy. Prof. Moran has published
widely on medieval philosophy (especially Christian Neoplatonism) and contemporary
European philosophy (especially phenomenology). His books include: The Philosophy
of John Scottus Eriugena (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989; reissued
2004), Introduction to Phenomenology (Routledge, 2000), Edmund Husserl. Founder of
Phenomenology (Cambridge & Malden, MA: Polity, 2005), Husserls Crisis of the European
Sciences: An Introduction (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012), and, coauthored
with Joseph Cohen, The Husserl Dictionary (London: Continuum, 2012). He has edited
Husserls Logical Investigations, 2 vols. (London: Routledge, 2001), The Shorter Logical
Investigations, The Phenomenology Reader, coedited with Tim Mooney (London: Routledge,
2002), Phenomenology. Critical Concepts in Philosophy, 5 Volumes, coedited with Lester E.
Embree (London: Routledge, 2004), Eriugena, Berkeley and the Idealist Tradition, coedited
with Stephen Gersh (South Bend: University of Notre Dame Press, 2006), and The Routledge
Companion to Twentieth Century Philosophy (London: Routledge, 2008). Prof. Moran is
Founding Editor of The International Journal of Philosophical Studies. He is a Member of the
Steering Committee of the International Federation of Philosophical Studies, and is President
of the Programme Committee and of the Executive Committee organising the XXIII World
Congress of Philosophy to be held in Athens in August 2013.

Eric S. Nelson is Associate Professor of Philosophy at the University of Massachusetts, Lowell.


He is particularly interested in the encounter, interaction, and conflict among different forms
of life, systems of practice and belief, and styles of thought. His areas of research include
hermeneutics, ethics, and the philosophy of culture, nature, and religion. He has published
over 40 articles and book chapters on European and Asian philosophy, including many on
Heidegger. He is the coeditor, with Franois Raffoul, of Rethinking Facticity (Albany: SUNY
Press, 2008); with John Drabinski, of Between Levinas and Heidegger (Albany: SUNY Press,
forthcoming); with G. DAnna and H. Johach, of Anthropologie und Geschichte. Studien zu
Wilhelm Dilthey aus Anlass seines 100. Todestages (Wrzburg: Knigshausen & Neumann,
2013); and, with Antje Kapust and Kent Still, of Addressing Levinas (Evanston: Northwestern
University Press, 2005).

Anne OByrne is Associate Professor of Philosophy at Stony Brook University. Her work
is in political philosophy and ontology, and engages a number of thinkers in the twentieth
century and contemporary continental philosophyHeidegger, Arendt, Dilthey, Derrida,
and Jean-Luc Nancyon a range of issuesidentity, natality, embodiment, education, his-
tory, gender, and genocide. Publications include Natality and Finitude (Bloomington: Indiana
University Press, 2010), a variety of articles, and translations of Nancys Being Singular Plural
(translated with Robert Richardson, Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1996) and Corpus
II (New York: Fordham University Press, 2013).

xxiii
NOTES ON CONTRIBUTORS

Richard Polt is Professor of Philosophy at Xavier University in Cincinnati. He is the author


of Heidegger: An Introduction (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1999) and The Emergency
of Being: On Heideggers Contributions to Philosophy (Ithaca: Cornell University Press,
1999). With Gregory Fried, he has translated Heideggers Introduction to Metaphysics (New
Haven: Yale University Press, 2000) and Being and Truth (Bloomington: Indiana University
Press, 2010), and edited A Companion to Heideggers Introduction to Metaphysics (New
Haven: Yale University Press, 2001). Most recently, Fried and Polt have translated Heideggers
19334 seminar On the Essence and Concept of Nature, History, and State, which is to be
published together with essays about the text by several scholars.

Franois Raffoul is Professor of Philosophy at Louisiana State University. He is the author of


Heidegger and the Subject (Amherst: Prometheus Books, 1999), A Chaque fois Mien (Paris:
Galile, 2004), and The Origins of Responsibility (Bloomington: Indiana University Press,
2010). He is the coeditor of several volumes, Disseminating Lacan (Albany: SUNY Press,
1996), Heidegger and Practical Philosophy (Albany: SUNY Press, 2002), Rethinking Facticity
(Albany: SUNY Press, 2008), and French Interpretations of Heidegger (Albany: SUNY Press,
2008). Author of more than 45 articles, he has also cotranslated several French philoso-
phers, in particular Jean-Luc Nancy, The Title of the Letter (Albany: SUNY Press, 1992), The
Gravity of Thought (Albany: SUNY Press, 1998), The Creation of the World or Globalization
(Albany: SUNY Press, 2007) and Identity (forthcoming, New York: Fordham University
Press). He is the coeditor of a book series entitled Contemporary French Thought (Albany:
SUNY Press, ongoing) He is currently preparing a monograph on the question of the event in
contemporary philosophy.

Hans Ruin is Professor in Philosophy at Sdertrn University. He has published approximately


40 articles and chapters in peer-reviewed journals and books, mainly on Heidegger, phenom-
enology, and hermeneutics. Monographs include: Enigmatic Origins. Tracing the Theme of
Historicity through Heideggers Works (Stockholm: Almqvist & Wiksell, 1994), Herakleitos
Fragment (Lund : Propexus, 1997), Inledning till Heideggers Varat och tiden (2006), and
Frihet, ndlighet, historicitet. Esser om Heidegger filosofi (2012). Edited books include
Fenomenologiska Perspektiv (with A. Orlowski, Stockholm: Thales, 1997), Metaphysics,
Facticity, Interpretation. Phenomenology in the Nordic Countries (with D. Zahavi och
S.Heinmaa, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 2003), The Pasts Presence (with Marcia
Cavalcante, Huddinge: Sdertrns hgskola, 2006), Phenomenology and Religion: New
Frontiers (with Jonna Bornemark, Huddinge: Sdertrn University, 2010), Rethinking Time.
History, Memory and Representation (with Andrus Ers, Huddinge: Sdertrns hgskola, 2011),
Fenomenologi, Teknik och Medialitet (with Leif Dahlberg, Huddinge: Sdertrns hgskola,
2011), Ambiguity of the Sacred. Phenomenology, Aesthetics, Politics (with Jonna Bornemark,
Stockholm: Sdertrns hgskola, 2011). He translated into Swedish Derridas The Origin of
Geometry and Schibboleth for Paul Celan (with Aris Fioretos Stockholm: Symposion, 1990),
and the Heraclitean fragments from Greek (with Hkan Rehnberg, Lund: Propexus, 1997).

xxiv
NOTES ON CONTRIBUTORS

John Russon is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Guelph. He is the author of three
original works in the tradition of existential phenomenology: Human Experience: Philosophy,
Neurosis, and the Elements of Everyday Life (Albany: SUNY Press, 2003), Bearing Witness
to Epiphany: Persons, Things, and the Nature of Erotic Life (Albany: SUNY Press, 2009),
and Sites of Exposure: A Philosophical Essay on Politics, Art, and the Nature of Experience
(Bloomington: Indiana University Press, forthcoming). He is also the author of three books
on Hegel: The Self and Its Body in Hegels Phenomenology (Toronto: University of Toronto
Press, 1997), Reading Hegels Phenomenology (Bloomington: Indiana University Press,
2009), and Infinite Phenomenology: The Lessons of Hegels Science of Experience (Evanston:
Northwestern University Press, forthcoming). He is currently at work on a book entitled
Adult Life.

Frank Schalow is University Research Professor at the University of New Orleans. He has
published numerous books, including Departures: At the Crossroads between Heidegger and
Kant (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 2013), The Incarnality of Being: The Earth, Animals and the
Body in Heideggers Thought (Albany: SUNY Press, 2006), Heidegger and the Quest for the
Sacred: From Thought to the Sanctuary of Faith (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers,
2001), The Renewal of the Heidegger-Kant Dialogue (Albany: SUNY Press, 1992), along
with the edited volume Heidegger, Translation, and the Task of Thinking: Essays in Honor of
Parvis Emad (Dordrecht: Springer, 2011). Currently, he is coeditor of the international jour-
nal Heidegger Studies.

Dennis J. Schmidt is the Liberal Arts Professor of Philosophy, Comparative Literature, and
German. He has been a visiting professor of Classics and Philosophy at the Universitt
Freiburg (Germany) and a visiting professor of the humanities at the Universit Roma (La
Sapienza). Recently he authored Idiome der Wahrheit (Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann
Verlag, forthcoming 2013), Between Word and Image (Bloomington: Indiana University
Press, 2012), Lyrical and Ethical Subjects (Albany: SUNY Press, 2005), On Germans and
Other Greeks (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2001). He publishes in the areas of
Ancient Greek philosophy and tragedy, aesthetics, German Idealism and Romanticism, and
Contemporary Continental Philosophy.

Gregory Schufreider is Professor of Philosophy at Louisiana State University, where he was


the founding Director of the Program for the Study of the Audio-Visual Arts. His publica-
tions on Heidegger include Art and the Problem of Truth (Man and World, 13, 1, 1980);
Heidegger on Community (Man and World, 14, 1, 1981); Heideggers Contribution
to a Phenomenology of Culture (JBSP, 17, 2, 1986); Heideggers Hole: The Space of
Thinking (Research in Phenomenology, 31, 1, 2001); Sticking Heidegger with a Stela:
Lacoue-Labarthe, Art and Philosophy (in French Receptions of Heidegger, Albany: SUNY
Press, 2008); Re:Thinking Facticity (in Rethinking Facticity, Albany: SUNY Press, 2008) as
well as The Art of Truth (Research in Phenomenology, 40, 3, 2010). He is currently com-
pleting a two-volume study of Heidegger and Mondrian.

xxv
NOTES ON CONTRIBUTORS

Andrea Janae Sholtz is Assistant Professor of Philosophy at Alvernia University in Reading,


Pennsylvania. She completed her PhD in philosophy at University of Memphis and her MA in
philosophy at New School for Social Research. She researches primarily in Nineteenth- and
Twentieth-Century Continental Philosophy, Feminism, and Philosophy of Art. Dr. Sholtz is
writing a book entitled The Invention of A People Art and the Political in Heidegger and
Deleuze on the intersections between ontology, art, and the political in Martin Heidegger and
Gilles Deleuze, situating this discussion in the larger context of contemporary philosophical
conversation concerning community. She is a coauthor of What is Philosophy for Deleuze
and Foucault? (with Leonard Lawlor) to be published in Between Deleuze and Foucault and
published Reflections on Continental and Feminist Pedagogy: Heidegger and Anzaldua in
PhiloSOPHIA: A Journal of Continental Feminism, 2, 1 (2012).

Thomas Sheehan is Professor of Religious Studies and, by courtesy, Philosophy and German
at Stanford University and Professor Emeritus of Philosophy at Loyola University Chicago.
He is the author of The First Coming: How the Kingdom of God Became Christianity (New
York: Random House, 1986), Karl Rahner: The Philosophical Foundations (Athens: Ohio
University Press, 1987) and the editor and translator of Martin Heidegger, Logic: The Question
of Truth (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2010), Becoming Heidegger: On the Trail of
his Early Occasional Writings, 19101927 (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 2011),
Edmund Husserl, Psychological and Transcendental Phenomenology, and the Confrontation
with Heidegger (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1997) and Heidegger, the Man and
the Thinker (Chicago: Precedent, 1981), as well as the author and translator of numerous
works on Heidegger. He is currently at work on a book manuscript entitled Making Sense of
Heidegger: A Paradigm Shift.

P. Christopher Smith is Professor Emeritus of Philosophy at the University of Massachusetts,


Lowell. He has translated numerous books of Hans-Georg Gadamer and is the author of
Hermeneutics and Human Finitude: Toward a Theory of Ethical Understanding (New
York: Fordham University Press, 1991) and The Hermeneutics of Original Argument:
Demonstration, Dialectic, Rhetoric (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1998).

Jill Stauffer is Assistant Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Concentration in Peace,
Justice and Human Rights at Haverford College. Her edited volume (with Bettina Bergo),
Nietzsche and Levinas: After the Death of a Certain God, was published by Columbia
University Press in 2009. She has published articles in journals such as Law, Culture and the
Humanities, Theory and Event, Humanity, and Australian Feminist Law Journal. She is cur-
rently working on a book called Ethical Loneliness, using the work of Emmanuel Levinas and
Jean Amery to contemplate about the difficulties and possibilities of political reconciliation.

Robert D. Stolorow is a Founding Faculty Member at the Institute of Contemporary


Psychoanalysis, Los Angeles, and at the Institute for the Psychoanalytic Study of
Subjectivity, New York. Absorbed for more than three decades in the project of rethinking

xxvi
NOTES ON CONTRIBUTORS

psychoanalysis as a form of phenomenological inquiry, he is the author of World, Affectivity,


Trauma: Heidegger and Post-Cartesian Psychoanalysis (London: Routledge, 2011) and
Trauma and Human Existence: Autobiographical, Psychoanalytic, and Philosophical
Reflections (London: Routledge, 2007) and coauthor of eight other books. He received
his PhD in Clinical Psychology from Harvard in 1970 and his PhD in Philosophy from the
University of California at Riverside in 2007.

Iain Thomson is Professor of Philosophy at the University of New Mexico. He is the author
of two books, Heidegger on Ontotheology: Technology and the Politics of Education
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005) and Heidegger, Art, and Postmodernity
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011), as well as dozens of articles in philosophi-
cal journals, essay collections, and reference works. A recipient of the Gunter Starkey Award
for Teaching Excellence, Thomson is well-known for his ability to bring Heideggers difficult
ideas to life for contemporary readers. He is currently working on a philosophical biography
of Heidegger as well as on a book on the philosophical influence of Heideggers understand-
ing of death.

Peter Trawny studied Philosophy, Musicology, and History of Art in Bochum,


Freiburg, Basel, and Wuppertal. He taught at universities in Shanghai, Vienna, and
Stockholm. Today he teaches at the Bergische Universitt Wuppertal, where he is also
the director of the Martin-Heidegger-Institut. He is an editor of several volumes of the
Martin-Heidegger-Gesamtausgabe. His latest publications include Adyton. Heideggers esoter-
ische Philosophie (Berlin: Matthes & Seitz, 2010); Medium und Revolution (Berlin: Matthes
& Seitz, 2011); Ins Wasser geschrieben. Versuche ber die Intimitt and TechnikKapital
Medium is forthcoming.

Alejandro A. Vallega is Assistant Professor of Philosophy at the University of Oregon. He


is the author of Heidegger and the Issue of Space: Thinking On Exilic Grounds (American
and Continental Philosophy Series, University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press,
2003) and of Sense and Finitude: Encounters at the Limits of Art, Language, and the Political
(Contemporary Continental Philosophy Series, Albany: SUNY Press, 2009). He is head edi-
tor for the Latin America of the World Philosophies Series published by Indiana University
Press. His work focuses on aesthetics, Latin American philosophy, decolonial thought, and
Continental philosophy.

Daniela Vallega-Neu teaches at the University of Oregon. Among her book publications
are Heideggers Contributions to Philosophy: An Introduction (Bloomington: Indiana
University Press, 2004) and The Bodily Dimension in Thinking (Albany: SUNY Press, 2005).
She translated (together with) Martin Heideggers Contributions to Philosophy: Of the
Event (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2011) and coedited (with Charles E. Scott,
Susan Schoenbohm, and Alejandro Vallega) A Companion to Heideggers Contributions to
Philosophy (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2001). Her current research includes a

xxvii
NOTES ON CONTRIBUTORS

book project on Heideggers poietic writings from 193642, as well as investigations on


embodiment and time.

Ben Vedder studied Theology in Utrecht and Philosophy in Leuven. He wrote his dissertation
on Heidegger and Scheler. He was university teacher in Amsterdam and had a special chair
for philosophy at Wageningen University. He was full professor for Systematic Philosophy
at Tilburg University and, from 2002 onwards he serves as Professor of Metaphysics and
Philosophy of Religion at Radboud University Nijmegen. He published among others: Was
ist Hermeneutik? Ein Weg von der Textdeutung zur Interpretation der Wirklichkeit (What is
Hermeneutics? From Interpretation of Texts to Interpretation of Being, Stuttgart: Kohlhammer,
2000), De voorlopigheid van het denken, Over Heideggers hermeneutisering van de filosofie
(The Provisionality of Thinking, Dudley: Peeters Leuven, 2004.), and Heideggers Philosophy
of Religion, From God to the Gods (Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 2007). At present
he works on Paul in contemporary philosophy together with other colleagues, and is prepar-
ing a book on hermeneutics and religion.

Holger Zaborowski is professor of philosophy and philosophical ethics at


the Philosophisch-Theologische Hochschule Vallendar in Germany. He has edited sev-
eral volumes on Heidegger and is the author of Wie machbar ist der Mensch? (Mainz:
Matthias-Grnewald-Verlag, 2003), Spielraume der Freiheit: Zur Hermeneutik des
Menschseins (Freiburg: Alber, 2009), Robert Spaemanns Philosophy of the Human Person:
Nature, Freedom, and the Critique of Modernity (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010), and
Eine Frage von Irre und Schuld?: Martin Heidegger und der Nationalsozialismus (Frankfurt
am Main: Fischer Taschenbuch Verlag, 2010).

xxviii
EDITORS INTRODUCTION
Franois Raffoul and Eric S. Nelson

I It is the ambition of this volume to offer a


definitive reference guide to Heideggers path
The Bloomsbury Companion to Heidegger and thought by presenting 58 original essays
provides succinct and lucid essays intro- written for this volume by an international
ducing the thinking of Martin Heidegger group of prominent Heidegger scholars. This
(September 26, 1889May 26, 1976), one collection offers a detailed, extensive, and
of the twentieth centurys most striking, comprehensive resource for introductory
innovative, and controversial philosophers. and more advanced audiences to explore and
Heideggers groundbreaking works have further reflect on Heideggers thought, key
had a notable impact on twentieth- and writings, themes and topics, and reception
twenty-first-century thought through their and influence.
extensive reception, appropriation, critique,
and polemical rejection and condemna-
tion. Heideggers impact can be traced in
the responses of philosophers as diverse as II
Adorno, Arendt, Deleuze, Derrida, Foucault,
Gadamer, Levinas, Merleau-Ponty, Rorty, Heidegger was born on September 26, 1889
and Sartre, among others. in the small, provincial, conservative village
In addition to Heideggers formative role in of Mekirch. The young Heideggers ini-
intellectual movements such as phenomenol- tial intellectual development was shaped by
ogy, hermeneutics, existentialism, structural- the rhythms and rituals of everyday rural
ism and post-structuralism, deconstruction Catholic life and informed by his religious and
and postmodernism, he has had a trans- theological studies. After initially focusing on
formative effect on diverse areas of inquiry theology, Heidegger studied philosophy and
such as political theory and historiography, worked with the neo-Kantian philosopher
cultural studies and literary criticism, archi- Heinrich Rickert and the phenomenologist
tecture and art theory, theology and religious Edmund Husserl. Heidegger narrates later
studies, gender theory and feminism, and in life how his philosophical journey began
technology and environmental studies. with the question of being posed in Brentano

1
EDITORS INTRODUCTION

and Aristotle, a question to which he would lifeand the historical, immanent, and
repeatedly return. Despite his early interests already meaningful categories of life
in Catholic scholasticism, his philosophical from out of life itself, by realizing Husserls
training was in the modern epistemological demand of returning to the things themselves
traditions of German academic philosophy, and phenomenologically allowing each phe-
and his habilitation work on the philosophy nomenon to show itself from itself.
of Duns Scotus (1915) reflects the intersec- In this context, Heidegger formulated two
tion of both. objections to life-philosophy that would
During the First World War, and increas- motivate the modification of his thinking
ingly as it came to an end, Heidegger was through a sustained engagement with the
inspired not only by Husserls phenomeno- philosophical tradition, in particular Aristotle
logical method but by the existential and and Kant, in the mid-1920s. First, existential
life-philosophical crises and tendencies of his and life-philosophy is absorbed in the life
time. Unlike his teachers Rickert and Husserl, that it should clarify. Second, life-philosophy
who wrote polemically of these trends in was insufficient to address lifes basic disquiet
this period, the early Heidegger attempted (Unruhe, GA 60, 3054), that is, the inner ten-
to make life-philosophy philosophical while dencies of life toward its own self-ruination
at the same articulating philosophy imma- (GA 61, 2). Life is encountered not only in
nently from out of life. In contrast with the intuitive self-certainty and egotistical
prevalent popular or vulgar conceptions of security of the vulgar life-philosopher but as
life-philosophy, the early Heidegger focused dispersed and ruinated (103). Care (Sorge)
on the temporal event character of life (the emerges as a defining practicalas care for
es ereignet sich of 1919 in GA 56/57, 735) ones daily bread (90)and communica-
and increasingly the hermeneutical situation tiveas a vox media (GA 62, 357)lived
and historical intersection of meaning and category enacted in human existence.
life. Under Diltheys influence, among oth- In the lectures-courses of the mid-1920s
ers, life is understood as fundamentally and Being and Time, Heidegger developed
historical and interpretive rather than as an analytic of Dasein in which Dasein
biological life (whether mechanistically or (being-there) was defined as the site of an
vitalistically understood) or as intuitively understanding of being (Seinsverstndnis).
self-transparent life. This attention to the entity that we are
Heidegger perceived the philosophical led somenotably Husserlto accuse
significance of a life-philosophy that had Heidegger of developing a philosophical
failed to think through the issue of life radi- anthropology and falling back into subjec-
cally enough. This insight was unfolded in tivist metaphysics. Heidegger recognized this
Heideggers developing project of a herme- possibility when, evoking the interruption of
neutics of factical life, which foreshadowed the path opened by Sein und Zeit, he later
many of the concerns and strategies of Being admitted: The reason for the disruption is
and Time.1 The task is to articulate life in that the attempt and the path it chose con-
its questionability even more primordially front the danger of unwillingly becoming
than life-philosophy itself could (GA 60, merely another entrenchment of subjectiv-
50). This radicalization of life surpasses even ity (GA 6.2, 194/N III, 141). In the same
Dilthey, who inspired the task of articulating passage, Heidegger explained that far from

2
EDITORS INTRODUCTION

subjectivism or anthropology, Being and Time being, henceforth emphasizes the open-
was an ontological questioning of the human ness of being itself, rather than the open-
being, who was interrogated solely in terms ness of Dasein in regard to this openness
of its being; that is to say, in terms of being of being. This signifies the turn, in
which thinking always more decisively
itself. This interrogation occurs on the basis
turns to being as being. (FS, 41)
of the question concerning the truth of being
itself, as an attempt is made to determine the
essence of the human being solely in terms of In the later stage of his corpus, Heideggers
his relationship to Being (aus seinem Bezug thinking turned toward the truth of being as
zum Sein). That essence was described in a such (and no longer beingness), as it moved
firmly delineated sense as Da-sein (ibid.). from a thematic of the understanding of
The term Dasein is hyphenated as Da-sein in being to that of a happening of being. This
order to stress this sheer relatedness to being. opened the way to new directions in his
The understanding of being is not one work, which focused more on the various
property of humans among others, but it is modes of givenness of being in its happen-
that which defines the human being. This is ing, in its historical sendings and epochs.
why such understanding is not a human This led Heidegger, in a Seynsgeschichtliche
determination, but a characteristic of being. Denken or beyng-historical thinking, to
The privilege of Dasein is not ontic or stress the historicality of being itself, under-
anthropological, but ultimately ontological: stood as history of being.
Understanding of being is itself a determi- In this situation, Heidegger carried out
nation of being of Dasein [Seinsverstndnis a project of overcoming metaphysics in
is selbst eine Seinsbestimmtheit des Daseins]. dialogue with Nietzsche, returned to the
The ontic distinction of Dasein lies in the Greek dawn of philosophy, and engaged in
fact that it is ontological (SZ, 12/BT, 11). a dialogue with Hlderlin and other poets.
Humans are thus made possible by the In that historical meditation on the destiny
understanding of being and not the inverse: of the West (and its confrontation with the
Accordingly, the understanding of being is East, explored by Bret Davis in this volume),
the ground of the possibility of the essence Heidegger was able to further develop the
of the human being (GA 31, 125/EHF, 87, thematization of technology, of nihilism and
modified). To this extent, the understanding the Gestell, of the end of philosophy and
of being is not posited by us, much less by of the possibility of an other beginning. As
consciousness or the subject, but is an event Richard Polt reminds us, in contrast with the
in which we find ourselves among and in the first beginning of Western thought, which
midst of other beings. asks: what are beings? the other beginning
Therein lies the turn from a thinking would ask: How does beyng occur essen-
centered in Daseins openness to being to a tially? [Wie west das Seyn?] (GA 65, 75, 7/
thinking that meditates on the openness of CP2, 60, 8).
being to Dasein: The thinking of being, from the
Dasein-centered analyses of Being and
The thinking that proceeds from Being Time to the happening of being as such, led
and Time, in that it gives up the word Heidegger to a further reflection on the very
meaning of being in favor of truth of event of givenness of being, or Ereignis. This

3
EDITORS INTRODUCTION

reflection (Besinnung) on the event (Ereignis) Heidegger makes the important point
of being (Sein) that emerged in the 1930s, as that being is to be thought from Ereignis,
well as his support of National Socialism that in fact Being is appropriated through
and its disastrous consequences, informs the appropriative event [Sein ist durch das
his later lectures and writings on topics that Ereignis ereignet] (60, modified). We read
encompass architecture and art, animals a few lines further: The appropriative event
and humanism, the body and psychology, appropriates being [das Ereignis ereignet das
language and listening, letting, releasement Sein]. One of the most important contribu-
(Gelassenheit) and the thing, the poetic word tions of Heideggers later work is the way in
and technology, space and sense of place, which he distinguishes between Ereignis and
among others. being, showing how Ereignis exceeds being
In Heideggers later work, the emphasis and its economy. In On Time and Being,
shifts from a questioning of being to one that Heidegger went so far as to state, in a pro-
gestures toward the dimension from which vocative and enigmatic saying, that Being
being is given; that is, the event of given- vanishes in Ereignis (Sein verschwindet im
ness of being, or Ereignis. That focus on the Ereignis) (GA 14, 27/TB, 22). One should
es gibt of being led Heidegger to rethink thus not think Ereignis with the help of the
the meaning of being as letting (FS, 59). concepts of being or of the history of being.
Beginning from a reflection on the sense of Ereignis is said to exceed the ontological
Ereignis as an event of the givenness of pres- horizon, as it exceeds the Greek sending
ence, Heidegger states that it is a matter here in the history of being. It appears then that
of understanding that the deepest meaning of Heideggers thought is not contained within
being is letting [lassen] (ibid.). Being is not the horizon of ontology nor limited to the
the horizon of beings, nor the there is of thought of being. Heidegger in fact explains
beings. Rather, being means now: letting the that his thinking of the ontological differ-
being be (Das Seiende sein-lassen). This let- enceespecially in the period from 1927 to
ting is not a cause, for causality still depends 1936, which is taken to be the crux of this
on the logic of beings and their sufficient workwas a necessary impasse (Holzweg)
grounding. It is also not a doing, which (FS, 61).
draws from the philosophy of the acting sub- Furthermore, there is no destinal epoch of
ject. Letting is to be thought instead in the Ereignis. Ereignis is not an epoch of being,
context of giving. The giving here in ques- and nor is it the end of the history of being,
tion should not refer primarily to a present in the sense in which the history of being
being, or even to the presence of beings. The would have reached its end. Rather, the
giving should be separated from presence history of being is able to appear as history
itself; for the issue is to give thought to the of being from Ereignis. In fact, the histori-
es gibt, to giving, from an interpretation cal sendings of being are to be thought from
of letting itself. The es gibt is then the Ereignis. Sending is from the appropriative
gift of a giving as such, a giving that with- event [Das Schicken ist aus dem Ereignen]
draws in the very movement of its event: it (ibid.). Heideggers own summations of his
lets being (Es lt Sein). In this sense, release- path of thought shift us from the early focus
ment (Gelassenheit) is engaged from the on the meaning of being all the way to
question of Ereignis. his late notion of a topology of being and

4
EDITORS INTRODUCTION

tautological thinking. Heidegger also char- The part is structured according to the
acterized his final thinking as a phenome- defining periods of Heideggers intellectual
nology of the inapparent [Phnomenologie life. It begins with Kisiels reconsideration of
des Unscheinbaren] (80). the very notion of biography itself in terms
of Heideggers approach to the hermeneutic
character of life in its facticity; that is, the
fact that life interprets itself, explicates itself,
III and articulates itself; that is, that it has a
hermeneutic structure. In turn, the work
Part I: Life and Contexts of sense ultimately refers to factical life:
The very idea of facticity implies that only
This volume encompasses 5 parts viz. an authentic and proper [eigentliche] facticity
extensive list of entries on Heideggers life understood in the literal sense of the word:
and contexts (7 essays), his sources, influ- ones own [eigene] facticitythat is, the fac-
ences, encounters, and students (13 essays), ticity of ones own time and generation, is the
his key writings (10 essays), themes and genuine object of research (GA 62, 366/BH,
topics (15 essays), and his impact on philo- 167). In this sense, thinking leads us back
sophical movements and major contempo- to lifeto bio-graphy, understood as the
rary continental thinkers in Reception and concrete and hermeneutic existing of human
Influence (13 essays). Dasein.
The seven essays in the first part, Life Dermot Moran concentrates on Heideggers
and Contexts, examine Heideggers thought Freiburg and Marburg lecture courses to
with respect to the conditions of his life, Being and Time. Claiming that Heideggers
the trajectory of his work, and his career development was not as monolithic as pre-
as a whole, including his involvement with sented by Heidegger retrospectively, Moran
National-Socialist politics. As Theodore Kisiel unmasks a number of myths concerning
reminds us in Heidegger and the Question that period, myths presumably entertained
of Biography, Heidegger was skeptical of by Heidegger himself (for instance, Moran
biographies when it came to the work of stresses that the question of being was not
thought. He notably declared in an early lec- central in these early writings, and that
ture course, when introducing Aristotle, As Heidegger was instead occupied with facti-
for the personality of a philosopher, our only cal life and the nature of philosophy, as well
interest is that he was born at a certain time, as noting that Heidegger was never a student
that he worked, and that he died. The charac- of Husserl). Moran shows that in addition
ter of the philosopher, and issues of that sort, to a critique of the primacy of theoretical
will not be addressed here (GA18, 5/BCAR, knowledgethe primacy of the theoretical
4). However, what is salient is the history, (Primat des Theoretischen, GA 56/57, 87/
trajectory, andin a sensethe biography TDP, 73), the analysis of such factical life led
of the thinking itself; in other words, it is the Heidegger to understand it as a hermeneutic
story and history of Heideggers philosophi- notion comprising a world and a self. In such
cal development within his particular histor- a widening, Heidegger is envisaging that
ical and hermeneutical context that is the phenomenology must incorporate a new and
task of the first part to articulate. expanded kind of intuitionhermeneutic

5
EDITORS INTRODUCTION

intuition (die hermeneutische Intuition, The following two essays are devoted to
GA 56/57, 117/TDP, 98). Moran identi- Heidegger in the 1930s. Richard Polt investi-
fies Heideggers writings on the phenom- gates the problematic of Heideggers thinking
enology of religious life as prefiguring the of the people and the question who are
themes of his existential analytic. Indeed, the we? in this period. The 1930s are marked,
notion of a phenomenological destruction according to Polt, by Heideggers attempt
(Destruktion) originates in the early project to leap actively into a singular, transforma-
of a destruction of the metaphysical edifice tive event that would bring Germany into
encrusted on religious experience. Following its own. In this process, the question who
the Marburg years with its interpretations of are we? takes on a central role, and it can
Aristotle and Kant, among others, the road be taken as a guiding thread to understand
is paved for the appearance of Heideggers Heideggers thought during these years. Polt
magnum opus, Being and Time, in 1927. insists that Heideggers orientation toward
Thomas Sheehans essay focuses on the the question of the people includes a radical
scope and significance of the turn (die Kehre) critique of biologism. What matters is how
in Heideggers work. Beginning with the our own being is put into question and how,
claim that Heideggers main topic was not Our own proper Being is grounded in our
being, but initially meaning or significance belonging to the truth of Being itself (GA 65,
understood as the significance to us of what- 51/CP2, 42). This implies that the question
ever we meet in the world, Sheehan points of who we are remains as a question, the
out that not even significance was Heideggers question of human uncanniness. As Heidegger
key concern. Rather, Heideggers ultimate writes in Introduction to Metaphysics, The
purpose was . . . to move beyond such mean- determination of the essence of the human
ingfulness to the X that makes it possible. being is never an answer, but is essentially a
Sheehan contends that the turn includes at question (GA 40, 107/IM, 149).
least three distinct but interrelated senses: Robert Bernasconi examines Heideggers
the first, and primary, sense of the turn relation to Nietzsche and his troubled involve-
refers to what Heidegger calls the reciprocity ment with National-Socialism. He contends
(Gegenschwung) between human existence that Heideggers metaphysical concern was
(Dasein) and the clearing: Without human uppermost in his treatment of Nietzsches
being, there is no clearing, and without the relation to Darwinism and biologism and
clearing, there is no human being. The second that when it came to readings of Nietzsche,
sense of the turn, usually takenmistakenly, Heideggers resistance was directed prima-
according to Sheehanby Heideggerians rily against those among the Nazis whom he
as its proper signification, is the shift that suspected of promoting both the Darwinian
occurs from the 1930s, from the earlier ques- struggle for existence and a biologistic con-
tion on meaningfulness to the question of ception of race. Bernasconi shows how
the provenance of such meaningfulness. The the distinction between the biological and
third sense of the turn is the conversion, or the metaphysical, as well as the distinction
transformation, of the self-understanding of between the political and the metaphysical,
human Dasein, known in the Heideggerian was proving more fluid than Heidegger had
lexicon as resolve (Entschlossenheit) and at first suspected. With respect to Nietzsche,
releasement (Gelassenheit). Bernasconi states that Heidegger initially

6
EDITORS INTRODUCTION

defended Nietzsche against the charge of Georges Braque, Otto Dix, or Hans Kock).
biologism only subsequently to locate him Heideggers largest correspondence was with
within the history of Western metaphysics. his wife Elfride (over 1,100 letters). Since
However, in this account of Western meta- these letters provide clarifications of his own
physics as destiny, Heidegger deprived him- thinking, they can be taken as genuine addi-
self philosophically of a basis for a moral tions to Heideggers work.
condemnation of National Socialism.
Franoise Dastur examines Heideggers Part II: Sources, Influences, and
later thought and work. She consid- Encounters
ers Heideggers thought from the Bremen
Lectures after the war to the late seminars The second part investigates Heideggers
of The Thor in France in the late 1960s and sources, influences, students, and encounters
early 1970s by way of his various essays in 13 essays. Heidegger understood his own
on art, technology, and psychotherapy. Her work as a conversation with tradition. He
essay elaborates on the theme of the end of declared, in a response to a question about
philosophy that emerged in Heideggers lat- so-called Heideggerian philosophy: There
est writings, particularly in his 1964 lecture is no Heideggerian philosophy; and even if
on The End of Philosophy and the Task of it existed, I would not be interested in that
Thinking. philosophy . . . Rather, he characterized
In the last contribution to this part, Alfred his thought as being engaged in a dialogue
Denker explores an oft-neglected aspect of with the tradition.2 Heidegger insisted on
scholarship on Heidegger, his correspond- the historicity of the question of being, and
ence, which offers fascinating insights into his thought has been formed through rigor-
Heideggers private thoughts, his ties to his ous readings and bold interpretations of the
contemporaries, and with his own work. corpus of Western philosophy. This historical
Providing an overview of Heideggers cor- character of the question of being would be
respondence, which comprises an estimated further radicalized in his later thinking of the
10,000 letters, Denker reveals the extent of history of being and its sendings.
Heidegger correspondence: with philoso- This part explores such links with the phil-
phers (Heinrich Rickert, Edmund Husserl, osophical tradition with essays examining
Karl Jaspers, Karl Lwith, Hans-Georg Heideggers reading and responses to Greek
Gadamer, Hannah Arendt, Hans Jonas, and medieval philosophy (Sean Kirkland
Max Scheler, Jean-Paul Sartre, and Ernst and Holger Zaborowski), Descartes and
Tugendhat); scholars in the humanities Kant (Emilia Angelova and Frank Schalow),
(Kurt Bauch, Beda Allemann, and Emil Hegel, Schelling, and German Idealism
Staiger); scientists (Werner Heisenberg and (Peter Trawny), Nietzsche (Ulrich Haase),
Carl-Friedrich von Weizscker); psychiatrists Husserl (Leslie MacAvoy), Diltheys herme-
(Medard Boss and Ludwig Binswanger); neutics and Carnaps logical positivism (Eric
theologians (Conrad Grber, Karl Rahner, S. Nelson), his encounters and confronta-
and Johannes Baptist Lotz); authors and tions with philosophical movements such as
poets (Ren Char, Paul Celan, and Ernst and neo-Kantianism and Cassirer (Peter Gordon),
Friedrich-Georg Jnger), and artists (such as well as his reception by his early students
as Eduardo Chillida, Bernhard Heiliger, such as Arendt (Peg Birmingham), Gadamer

7
EDITORS INTRODUCTION

(Emilia Angelova), and Marcuse (Andrew Being and Time, Frank Schalow suggests that
Feenberg). Heideggers interpretation of Kant could shed
Sean Kirkland shows the necessity for light on the turn in his thinking. Essays on
Heidegger and for contemporary thought Heideggers responses to German Idealism
to engage Greek philosophy. Heideggers concentrating on Hegel and Schelling (Peter
attempt to reopen the question of being Trawny)and to Nietzsche (Ullrich Haase)
occurs in direct dialogue with the ancients, follow, giving a unique perspective on
as the opening paragraphs of Being and Heideggers treatment of post-Kantian and
Time testify. The entire project of Being nineteenth-century philosophy, and their
and Time can be said to unfold explic- role in his understanding of the history of
itly within a space opened up and deline- being. Eric Nelson considers the import of
ated by ancient Greek thought. Kirkland Heideggers understanding of Diltheys herme-
explores Heideggers relation with Greek neutical life-philosophy. This is followed
thought as provenance of our history, which by an essay by Leslie MacAvoy on Husserl
is not a simple return to the Greeks but and Heidegger in which she articulates their
indeed an engagement with the ancients respective conceptions of phenomenology.
unthought and unsaid as such. Holger Peter E. Gordon takes on Heideggers
Zaborowski explores the often-neglected relationship with neo-Kantianism by con-
relation of Heidegger to medieval philosophy. sidering the key themes of Kantian and
Heideggers response to medieval thought neo-Kantian philosophy that left their mark
and the scholastic tradition is closely tied up on Heideggers early thought. After Eric
with his relation to Christianity, and to that Nelsons chapter on Heidegger and Carnap,
extent was determinative of Heideggers early which contrasts their conceptions of noth-
work. Through these early works, Heidegger ingness, Peg Birmingham challenges the com-
made a considerable move towards . . . key mon understanding of the relation between
insights of his later hermeneutics of facticity, Heidegger and Arendt in terms of contrast (if
of his phenomenology of Dasein, and also of not opposition) and shows their proximity
his being-historical thinking. In her essay, with respect to the notions of world and com-
Heidegger and Descartes, Emilia Angelova munity. Emilia Angelova examines Gadamers
contrasts Heideggers early lecture courses exposition of philosophical hermeneutics
with the later period. Whereas in the early with Heideggers project of fundamental
period, the focus was on the ambiguity of ontology and clarifies how Gadamer dis-
Descartes problematic, the later writings tanced himself from the later Heidegger. In
(in particular in the Nietzsche courses, What the last chapter of Part II, Andrew Feenberg
is a Thing? The Age of the World Picture, engages Marcuse and Heidegger, discussing
and the final seminars) show a much more the various stages of Marcuses appraisal of
pronounced critical stance with respect to Heideggers thought, and confronting their
Descartes subjectivism. Angelova retraces respective conceptions of technology.
that trajectory and appraises its significance.
Reflecting on how Kants destructive- Part III: Key Writings
retrieval of transcendental philosophy illu-
minates the ostensible impasse surrounding The third part offers ten essays bearing
the unpublished, third division of part I of on Heideggers key writings, following a

8
EDITORS INTRODUCTION

chronological order and highlighting the only to Being and Time, and one of his more
most influential writings: the early lecture controversial works. Fried explains how
courses (Scott Campbell), the early lecture Introduction to Metaphysics occupies a tran-
courses on Aristotle (P. Christopher Smith), sitional position in Heideggers path, between
Being and Time (Dennis Schmidt), The Origin the fundamental ontology and the analytic
of the Work of Art (Gregory Schufreider), of Dasein in Being and Time and the efforts
Introduction to Metaphysics (Gregory Fried), in Contributions to Philosophy (193638),
Contributions to Philosophy (Peter Trawny), a volume considered in an entry by Peter
the Hlderlin lectures (William McNeill), Trawny. Trawny insists on the style of this
The Letter on Humanism (Andrew Mitchell), work, referring to the will and the style of
The Bremen Lectures (Andrew Mitchell) and thinking (CP1, 15), the style of inceptual
later essays and seminars (Lee Braver). thinking (24) and the reservedness evoked
Scott Campbell approaches Heideggers by Heidegger. The experimental character of
early writings in terms of three main foci: the Heideggers scripturality is stressed. William
meaningfulness of life; religious experience; McNeill provides an account of Heideggers
and language and the Greeks. P. Christopher relation to and dialogue with Hlderlin, elab-
Smith discusses what he calls the early orating on Heideggers Hlderlin lectures and
Heideggers revolutionary rehabilitation of their prominent place in his path of thinking.
rhetoric, showing how Heidegger consid- McNeill considers the first Hlderlin Lecture
ered human existence to be fundamentally Course, that is, The Hymns Germania and
rhetorical in a transformed sense. Dennis The Rhine (19345), the Remembrance
Schmidt considers that unique text that is lectures (19412), and the last Hlderlin
Being and Time, marking its irreducible char- Lecture Course: The Ister (1942).
acter with respect to the history in which it is Andrew J. Mitchell contextualizes the writ-
otherwise situated. Schmidt remarks that, In ing of Heideggers Letter on Humanism,
its efforts to set itself apart from philosophi- demonstrating that at the heart of the essay
cal traditions and languages, and to resist is a profound thinking of the interrelation
any easy appropriation into well-established between the human, being, and language.
contexts, Being and Time quietly announces This essay is followed by Mitchells text on
the radicality of its own intentions. It is that the 1949 Bremen Lectures, a volume that he
extraordinary originality of the work that recently translated into English. He considers
makes it a promise still to come. While not- these lectures to be a third, decisive mile-
ing that there are about half a dozen versions stone along Heideggers path of thought,
of the The Origin of the Work of Art, if not alongside the early Being and Time, and the
more if one takes into account the various mid-period Contributions to Philosophy. In
transcripts of the lectures taken by students the last contribution of Part III, Lee Braver
who attended them, Gregory Schufreider reflects on what distinguishes what is known
argues that Heideggers aim in turning his as the later Heidegger. In addition to
attention to the work of art in the 1930s is the question of style, Braver suggests that
to provide a new model of philosophy. Heidegger has added some new motifs, such
Gregory Fried notes that Introduction to as artworks and technology, for example,
Metaphysics is one of Martin Heideggers and what he calls things, which are very dif-
most widely read works, second perhaps ferent from objects.

9
EDITORS INTRODUCTION

Part IV: Themes and Topics understanding of a wide-range of domains


and topics.
The 15 essays of the fourth part focus on
key notions and themes found in Heideggers Part V: Reception and Influence
work. They enact and perform this task in
diverse ways by clarifying key notions and The fifth part consists of 13 essays that
questions in Heideggers corpus. In this part, investigate the influence of Heideggers
Franois Raffoul illuminates Heideggers thought on various thinkers and contempo-
conception of Dasein (being-there); rary philosophical movements. Heidegger
Daniela Vallega-Neu carefully explicates the has had a major impact on late modern and
complex fundamental notion of Ereignis postmodern philosophy. Just to mention
(the event); Andrew Mitchell reflects on the French example, one can list: Levinas
Heideggers meditations on the fourfold (das first commentaries on Heideggers early
Geviert); Hans Ruin inquires into the role of works (Levinas was the first one to intro-
technology in Heideggers thought; Daniel duce Heidegger in France); Sartres magiste-
Dahlstrom describes the event and structure rial (mis)appropriation of the key moments
of truth in Heideggers philosophy; Gregory and vocabulary of Being and Time in Being
Schufreider turns to the question of the and Nothingness; the fame, after the war,
Nothing (das Nichts); Anne OByrne inves- of existentialism and the celebrated Letter
tigates the elemental significance of both on Humanism addressed to Jean Beaufret,
birth and death in Heideggers works; Iain a key figure in the French reception of
Thomson elucidates Heideggers important Heidegger; Heideggers visit to France in
discussions of ontotheology; while Kevin the mid-1950s to attend the Cerisy meeting
Aho pursues the question of the extent to and his encounter with Lacan, his lecture
which Heidegger adequately addressed the at Aix-en-Provence in 1958; the seminars
thematic of the body. held in the 1960s in France, in Provence at
Other essays explore Heideggers relation the Thor, near the house of Ren Char; and
to various disciplines or domains of theory finally the reappropriation of Heideggers
and practice. These include Trish Glazebrooks Destruktion in the thought of Jacques
detailed analysis of Heideggers approach to Derrida and deconstruction, a work further
science; Andrew Bowies thoughtful com- pursued by Jean-Luc Nancy and Philippe
mentary on Heideggers relation to art and Lacoue-Labarthe.3
aesthetics; Franois Raffouls interrogation A number of essays review Heideggers
of Heideggers import for ethics; John Russon relation to these individual French thinkers,
and Kirsten Jacobsons examination of space whether Wayne Froman on Merleau-Ponty,
in Heideggers texts; Ben Vedders explica- Jill Stauffer on Emmanuel Levinas, Robert
tion of Heideggers thinking of religion and Bernasconi on Jean-Paul Sartre, Franois
theology; and John McCumbers clarifica- Raffoul on Jacques Derrida, Leonard Lawlor
tion of Heideggers meditations concerning and Janae Sholtz on Gilles Deleuze, and also
the question of language. The essays in this Leonard Lawlor on Michel Foucault. These
part serve to illuminate Heideggers think- detailed synthetic studies shed a unique light
ing by presenting Heideggers key technical on the ways in which Heidegger has helped
notions as well as his transformation of our shape twentieth-century French philosophy.

10
EDITORS INTRODUCTION

Beyond the French case, Iain Macdonalds In the time since Heideggers death on
essay focus on Adornos critical read- May26, 1976, his thought and life have con-
ing and diagnosis of Heideggers thought. tinued to inspire philosophical reflection and
Leslie MacAvoys incisive contribution con- argumentation as well as controversy and
centrates on Heideggers reception in the polemic. Our hope is that this volume, with
Anglo-American philosophical world, par- its 58 contributions from a range of notable
ticularly in Hubert Dreyfus, Mark Okrent, researchers of Heideggers thought and life
and Richard Rorty. Bret Daviss entry depicts from the United Kingdom, the United States,
the profound response to Heideggers work Germany, France, and Canada, will offer an
in Chinese, Indian, and Japanese philoso- expansive and detailed scope of analysis,
phy. Alejandro Vallegas chapter portrays the and serve as one of the most comprehensive
noteworthy reception of Heideggers think- guides available to approach and explore
ing in Latin American philosophy. Heideggers works. This is a work that is still
Moreover, Heideggers writings have to be discovered insofar as we do not cease
informed the formation of new discourses to confront the mysteryand wonderof
on the environment, gender, and psychology. being.
In further contributions, Trish Glazebrooke
measures and evaluates Heideggers impact
NOTES AND REFERENCES
on philosophical movements such as ecology
and environmental philosophy. Tina Chanter 1
On the notion of facticity and its role in
pursues the question of gender in Heidegger Heideggers early philosophy, see our intro-
via a discussion of Sophocles Antigone and duction to Rethinking Facticity, ed. Franois
Raffoul and Eric S. Nelson (Albany, NY: SUNY
its retrieval in Hegel, Heidegger, and femi- Press, 2008), 121.
nist philosophers such as Luce Irigaray and 2
In a session from August 31, 1955 in Cerisy,
Judith Butler. Robert D. Stolorow investi- cited in Dominique Janicaud. Heidegger in
gates Heideggers thought-provoking links France, vol. 1 (Paris: Albin Michel, 2001), 154.
with psychology and psychoanalysis and
3
On that reception of Heideggers thought in
France, in addition to Dominique Janicauds
new possibilities for thinking the psycho- magnum opus, see French Interpretations of
logical in existential, phenomenological, and Heidegger, ed. D. Pettigrew and F. Raffoul
post-Cartesian ways. (Albany, NY: SUNY Press, 2008).

11
1
HEIDEGGER AND THE QUESTION OF
BIOGRAPHY
Theodore Kisiel

In order to exemplify Heideggers dismissive then handed down to us as part and parcel of
attitude toward the role of biography in phi- the classical tradition of philosophy. Our
losophy, it has long been the custom to cite question of biography then becomes: what,
or paraphrase the remark he made on the if any, elements of biography, of the story of
opening day of his lecture course of Summer the life of a philosopher like Aristotle, enter
Semester 1924 on the Basic Concepts of into the story of his philosophical develop-
Aristotelian Philosophy: ment within his particular historical and
hermeneutical context.
As for the personality of a philosopher, Jaegers book was preceded by a set of
our only interest is that he was born at Studies toward the Entstehungsgeschichte
a certain time, that he worked, and that of Aristotles Metaphysics, a (hi)story of the
he died. The character of the philoso- origin (genesis, emergence, and development)
pher, and issues of that sort, will not be of his philosophy. In his course, Heidegger
addressed here. (GA 18, 5/BCAR, 4) accordingly embarks on a study of the forma-
tion of the basic concepts that shape and con-
To his students, Heidegger recommends textualize Aristotles philosophy. The most
instead a book on the (hi)story of Aristotles telling of his discoveries is that Aristotles
development by the classical philologist word for being, ousia, in the Greek language
Werner Jaeger that bears the title, Aristotle: ordinarily means property, possessions and
Fundamentals of the History of his goods, and real estate. This customary mean-
Development. In short, what is of inter- ing is constantly present and simultaneously
est to Heidegger is not so much the story accompanies its terminological meaning.
of Aristotles life as the story of the devel- And terminologically, ousia is a being in the
opment of his philosophy. In the terms of how of its being (GA 18, 24/BCAR, 19). As
the minimalist biography presented above, property and possessions, this how of being
the focus therefore falls on the fact/factic- is being in its being-available. This becomes
ity that he worked as a philosopher and the paradigm example of Aristotles way of
thinker at a certain time, and in the course philosophical concept-formation: drawing
of that lifetime produced works that were on an expression that was prevalent in the

15
HEIDEGGER AND THE QUESTION OF BIOGRAPHY

everyday language of his world, Aristotle have been thrown. In short, each and every
shapes it into his term for beings and their philosopher necessarily lives and works, in
being. In living in the native language that Heideggers terms, out of his very own herme-
imparts intelligibility to his world and all neutic situation in its already prepossessed,
that is experienced within it, he draws on previewed, and preconceptualized form. In
that natural intelligibility of experience to fact, at one point in his development of an
form his philosophical concepts that accord- ontology of being-here, Heidegger identifies
ingly remain indigenous (bodenstndig) ones own temporally particular hermeneutic
to that intelligible world wherein they are situation as the sole object of philosophi-
rooted and from which they are drawn. cal research of a time and a generation (BH,
A related concept that Heidegger draws 153). The very idea of facticity implies
from Aristotle and makes central is the that only authentic and proper [eigentliche]
concept of life, zoe, as drawn from the facticityunderstood in the literal sense of
Aristotelian definition of the human being as the word: ones own [eigene] facticitythat
zoon logon echon, the living being possess- is, the facticity of ones own time and gen-
ing, and possessed by, speech. Likewise here, eration, is the genuine object of research
zoe is a concept of being, a particular how (GA 62, 366/BH, 167). Resolved to speak
of being: radically to the worldto question and to
research (GA 18, 40/BCAR, 29), each gener-
Life refers to a mode of being, indeed ation of philosophers is called upon to radi-
a mode of being-in-a-world. . . . The cally retake its unique hermeneutic situation
being-in-the-world of the human being for its own time, to appropriate its own past
is defined in its ground through speak-
in order to recover its precedent possibilities
ing. The fundamental mode of being in
that are especially appropriate for its time
which the human being is in its world is
in speaking with it, about it, of it. (GA and generation. It is incumbent upon each
18, 18/BCAR14) Living, for the human generation of philosophers, by way of radical
being, means [heisst] speaking. (GA 18, questioning, to explicate and interpret that
21/BCAR, 16) situation for its own time. And by its very
nature, it is something that a time can never
We are not too far removed here from borrow from another time (GA 62, 348/BH,
Diltheys sense of the pan-hermeneutic char- 156). So identified are we with our particu-
acter of human life, expressed succinctly by lar historical time that Heidegger does in fact
Hans-Georg Gadamer: Das Leben selbst identify them, in existential assertions such
legt sich aus. Es hat selbst hermeneutische as I myself AM my time and We ourselves
Struktur. [Life itself lays itself out, interprets ARE history, to be sure, not an objectified
itself, explicates itself, articulates itself. Life history but rather a history-in-actualization
itself has a hermeneutic structure].1 This (Vollzugsgeschichte).
pan-hermeneutic dimension is especially Acknowledging ones own hermeneutic
relevant to the life of a philosopher, who situation as the proper matter of philosophy
in his conceptual labor naturally draws his and the proper arena of philosophical con-
concepts from the meaningful context of cept formation marks a considerable step
life-experience already articulated in the beyond ordinary unthinking life. It in fact
native language into which he happens to marks a transition into the more intense

16
HEIDEGGER AND THE QUESTION OF BIOGRAPHY

life of thought. The tradition of philosophy essential nature of being in each instantia-
has called it the transcendental move. But a tion mine (je meines), yours (je deines), and
flag of caution must now be quickly raised, ours (je unsriges). Finding ourselves situated
since we are dealing here with a uniquely in existence, thrown into an historical world
nontraditional domain of transcendence. that in fact is very much our own, we, each of
The young Heidegger is quick to rule out any us, are called upon to overtly own up to this
sort of transcendental ego or theoretical I situation as a whole and properly make it our
abstracted in Cartesian fashion from its vital very own. This call (solicitation, challenge, or
context, denouncing such an ego as thor- demand) elicited by the existential situation
oughly denuded of its world and therefore into which we find ourselves thrown is the
wholly devoid of concrete meaning, dehis- function of the formally indicative concepts
toricized, and, last but not least, thoroughly of philosophy. The meaning-content of these
devitalized. The phenomenological return concepts does not directly intend or express
back to our most original life-experience, what they refer to, but only gives an indica-
methodologically called a reduction, can per- tion, a pointer to the fact that anyone seeking
haps be better characterized as a movement to understand is called upon by this concep-
of transdescendance into our most original tual context to actualize [vollziehen] a trans-
concretion of experience. It is a return back formation of themselves into their Dasein
to our most original factic life experience, (GA 29/30, 430/FCM, 297, trans. modified).
where the very act of living spontaneously Because such conceptsHeideggers terse
articulates and contextures itself into the examples are death, resolute openness, his-
manifold of vitally concrete and meaning- tory, existencecan only convey the call
ful basic relations that constitute the fabric for such a transformation to us without
of human concerns that we call our histori- being able to bring about this transformation
cal life-world, which in turn constitutes the themselves, they are but indicative concepts.
tacit background context of meaningful- They, in each instance, point to Dasein itself,
ness within and against which all of factic which in each instantiation is my (your, our)
life necessarily takes place and is thereby Dasein, as the locus and potential agent of
understood. In explicating the implicit back- this transformation. Because in this indica-
ground of meaningfulness that underlies all tion they in each instance point to a concre-
of our experience, this move can be called the tion of the individual Dasein in the human
hermeneutic-phenomenological re-duction. being, yet never bring the content of this
But in this uniquely transcendental domain concretion with them, such concepts are for-
of meaningfulness in which the life of thought mally indicative (GA 29/30, 429/FCM, 296,
now operates, where, if at all, is there room trans. modified).
for the entry of anything like the biographical These formally indicative, properly philo-
elements of a life? The answer resides in our sophical concepts thus only evoke the Dasein
inescapable starting point from a temporally in human being, but do not actually bring
particular (je-weiligen) hermeneutic situation it about. There is something penultimate
unique to an historical individual and an his- about philosophizing in all of its conceptu-
torical generation, in the distinction made ality. Its questioning brings us to the very
above between a purely transcendental ego brink of the possibility of Dasein, just short
and an historically situated I, and in Daseins of restoring to Dasein its actuality, that is,

17
HEIDEGGER AND THE QUESTION OF BIOGRAPHY

its existence (GA 29/30, 257/FCM, 173). brings with itself certain elements of its ontic
There is a very fine line between philosophiz- background that it regards as indispensable
ing and actualizing over which the human and irrevocable to its very identity as a self.
being cannot merely slip across, but rather This can be readily exemplified through the
must overleap in order to dislodge its Dasein. testimony of Heidegger himself in a letter
Only individual action itself can dislodge to Karl Lwith in August 1921 in which he
us from this brink of possibility into actual- spells out the vital identity out of which he
ity, and this is the moment of decision and himself does his own philosophizing:
of holistic insight [into the concrete situation
of action and be-ing] (GA 29/30, 257/FCM, I work concretely and factically out
173, trans. modified). It is the protoaction of my I amout of my spiritual
and thoroughly factic provenance
(Urhandlung) of resolute openness to ones
[Herkunft], my milieu, my life contexts,
own concretely unique situation of be-ing,
and whatever is available to me from
of letting it be in its wholeness and ownness, these, as the vital experience in which I
in each instantiation concretely reenacted in live. This facticity, as existentiell, is no
accord with ones own unique situation and mere blind existencethis Dasein is
particular while of history that authenti- one with existence, which means that
cates our existence and properizes our phi- I live it, this I must of which no one
losophizing. It is in such originary action, speaks. The act of existing seethes with
repeatedly reenacted from one generation to this facticity of being-thus, it surges
the next, that ontology finds its ontic found- with the historical just as it iswhich
ing. Just as Aristotle (and so the metaphysical means that I live the inner obligations of
my facticity and do so as radically as I
tradition) founded his prote philosophia in
understand them. This facticity of mine
theologia, so Heidegger now founds his fun-
includesbriefly putthe fact that I am
damental ontology upon something ontic a Christian theologian. This implies
the Dasein (GA 24, 26/BP, 19). a certain radical self-concern, a certain
And it is this ontic founding that is actual- radical scientificity, a rigorous objectivity
ized by individual [proto]action that allows [Gegenstndlichkeit] in this facticity; it
for the entry of selected biographical elements includes the historical consciousness, the
at least at the threshold of the trans[des]cen- consciousness of the history of spirit.
dental level of philosophy. In the same vein, And I am all this in the life context of the
this individual protoaction brings in the university. (BH, 99100)
content of the concretion of the individual Ich bin christlicher Theologe. Such
Dasein in the human entity that is left unde- deeply personal declarations of who
cided because of the formal character of the I am are clear-cut statements of
indication. It is the individual Dasein itself, self-identity in which Heidegger is own-
which, as the being (Seiendes) that in its ing up to the deep Christian roots that
ineradicably belongs to his factic prov-
be-ing is concerned with this very be-ing, in
enance, and so an admission of where he
its very nature straddles the ontological dif-
is in fact coming from (Her-kunft) in his
ference between be-ing and beings, the onto- thinking. Eventually this provenance will
logical and the ontic, that in its transcending/ assume a note of necessity, of the inalter-
transforming move from the human being to ability and inescapability of a persons
its Dasein, from the ontic to the ontological, situation that cannot be denied without

18
HEIDEGGER AND THE QUESTION OF BIOGRAPHY

denying who I am, and so being untrue doctrine, and position,but we are
to oneself. I cannot do otherwise with- together in the one way in which humans
out rejecting myself and denying who I are able to be genuinely together: in
am (BH, 102). The note of possibility Existenz. (BH, 102)
comes into play in how one takes up this
inevitability and develops it further. I
What particularly distinguishes Heidegger
cannot make my I am into something
different, but can only take hold of it from Becker, the scientifically oriented
and be it in this or that way (BH, 101). philosopher, and Lwith, the existentielly
In confessing where he is in fact coming inclined thinker, in their respective factici-
from, Heidegger is at once translating ties (concrete backgrounds) is that the fact
the inner obligations of my facticity that I am a Christian theologian is a side
into must do tasks and projects, e.g., of Heidegger that neither one of them could
by assuming the self-confessed role of be expected to empathize with. Behind this
Christian theologian in his courses admission of identity lies an ontic-existentiell
on the phenomenology of religion and background experience that finds itself
on Augustine and Neoplatonism in
deeply embedded in a facticity of Christian
192021.
religiosity that developed into the (here left
unsaid and clearly ontic-existentiell) auto-
The letter continues with Heidegger contrast- biography of a former Catholic seminar-
ing himself with his two best students at the ian who had broken with the religion of
time, Lwith and Oskar Becker, first of all his youth to become a nondenominational
in regard to where each is coming from and free Christian and was now on the verge
how starkly divergent these concrete back- of proclaiming the atheism of philosophy
grounds are. It has always been clear to me in close conjunction with the rigorous fide-
that neither you nor Becker would accept the ism of Protestant theology. Thus the admis-
Christian side of me (BH, 100). But in spite sion implies a particular radical personal
of the disagreements and misunderstandings concern (Lwiths fort) and pathos that
that such radically divergent backgrounds are stems from this past life, but it also involves
bound to promote and the radically different a particular radical scientificity (Beckers
paths that may therefore be taken, Heidegger inclination) being cultivated by a university
nevertheless looks forward to a meeting of philosopher who had just completed two
minds provided that each comes to terms courses on the phenomenology of religion
with his temporally particular existential that had developed formal schemata that
situation in its ownness and wholeness in full prefigure the concrete historical actualization
propriety and authenticity. of Christian life (its Da-sein!) as it is depicted
respectively in Pauls letters and Augustines
Confessions.
Only one thing is decisive: that we
Heideggers admission provides the war-
understand each other well enough so
that each of us is radically devoted to the rant for further biographical probes into the
last to what and how each understands Heideggerian opus during this early phase.
the unum necessarium [one thing nec- And over the decades there has been a prolif-
essary (namely, our respective factici- eration of documents that have surfaced that
ties)]. We may be far apart in system, testify to the interplay of life and thought,

19
HEIDEGGER AND THE QUESTION OF BIOGRAPHY

biography and philosophy, in the early the extremes to which each by itself might be
period of Heideggers existentiell rootedness carried. Philosophy as a rationalistic system
in Christian religiosity. Let me venture one detached from life is impotent, mysticism as
such probe that brings out his deep Catholic an irrational experience is aimless (GA 1,
roots, the religion of my youth. 1915 is the 410/BH, 85).
year in which Heidegger writes his disserta- It should be noted that when Heidegger
tion on Duns Scotus, where its Introduction speaks of the vitality of the medieval world-
in its concluding lines first announces a view, he is speaking from the personal
major personal project of a hermeneutic phe- life-experience of his own boyhood in his
nomenology of religious life. hometown of Messkirch as a son of the sex-
tant of the nearby parish church. His later
For the decisive insight into [the nonpsy- reminiscences in a talk to a hometown crowd
chologistic character of scholastic psy- entitled The Mystery of the Bell Tower
chologys concept of intentionality], I recalls for them the daily medieval rhythm
regard the philosophical, more precisely, of the daily ringing of the Angelus and the
the phenomenological elaboration of the seasonal rhythms of the liturgical year that
mystical, moral-theological, and ascetic still defined daily life in his boyhood home
literature of medieval scholasticism to be at the turn of the century. [I myself experi-
of special urgency. (GA 1, 205) enced the same medieval rhythms still being
practiced as late as 1965 during an extended
In short, what is needed here is a phenom- stay in the Catholic village of St. Peter bei
enology of the full spectrum of religious Freiburg]. This nostalgia for a medieval
experience in the Middle Ages, in order to way of life and its worldview is only rein-
capture the living spirit of the medieval forced and amplified by the presence of the
worldview, a goal that Heidegger sets for Benedictine monastery at Beuron within hik-
himself in the penultimate lines of the 1916 ing distance of Messkirch. His hermeneutic
Conclusion of the Scotus dissertation: It is tour of the devotional manuals of the Middle
by such means that we shall first penetrate Ages by way of the phenomenological guide-
into the vital life of medieval scholasticism line of intentionality, while being philosophi-
and see how it decisively founded, vitalized, cal in intent, assumes in part the character
and strengthened a cultural epoch. For the of a personal itinerary, thus becoming both
medieval life-world, the form of its inner a personal and philosophical appreciation as
existence, is anchored in the transcendent well as confrontation of his boyhood faith,
primal relationship of the soul to Godan and be-ing.
inner existence that was alive in the Middle But by 1917, it becomes clear to Heidegger
Ages with rare concentration and intensity. that the excessive dogmatizing and theoriz-
The manifold of vital relations between God ing of medieval scholasticism drains all of the
and the soul, the world beyond and this vitality from religious life and that its ration-
world, varies according to the particular dis- alistic structures instigate a radical divorce
tance or proximity between them (GA 1, from life. In a note to himself in mid-1917
409/BH, 84). That is why scholasticism and out of the context of a neo-Kantian phi-
mysticism essentially belong together in the losophy of culture and religion nuanced by
medieval worldview and so mutually offset Schleiermachers experiential sense of the

20
HEIDEGGER AND THE QUESTION OF BIOGRAPHY

religious a priori, he writes in no uncertain totally excludes an original experience


terms that: of genuinely religious value... . This is
already implicit in the heavily scientific,
. . . dogmatic casuistic pseudo-philosophies, naturalistic, and theoretical metaphys-
which pose as philosophies of a par- ics of being of Aristotle and its radical
ticular system of religion (for instance exclusion and misconstrual of Platos
Catholicism) and presumably stand clos- problem of value, a metaphysics that is
est to religion and the religious, are the revived in medieval scholasticism and
least capable of promoting the vitality that sets its norm in the predominantly
of the problem [of the religious a priori]. theoretical. Accordingly, scholasti-
One is at a loss even to find the prob- cism, within the totality of the medieval
lem, since such [scholastic] philosophies Christian life-world, severely jeopard-
are not familiar with anything like a ized the immediacy of religious life and
philosophy of religion. For one thing, forgot religion for theology and dogma.
in the environment and context of such The theorizing and dogmatizing influ-
systems, the capacity to experience the ence was exercised by church authorities
different domains of value, in particular in their institutions and statutes already
religious value, stagnates, owing to the in the time of early Christianity. [In a sit-
complete absence of an original con- uation like this,] a phenomenon like that
sciousness of culture. For another, the of mysticism is to be understood as an
structure of the system has not grown elementary countermovement. (GA 60,
out of an organic cultural deed. Hence, 313f./PRL, 237f.)
the inherent worth of the religion, its
palpable sphere of meaning, must first be
experienced through a tangled, inorganic, NOTES AND REFERENCES
dogmatic hedgerow of propositions and
proofs that are left totally unclarified
Hans-Georg Gadamer, Wahrheit und Methode:
1
theoretically, which as an ecclesiastical Grundzge einer philosophischen Hermeneutik
and canonical statute backed by police (Tbingen: J.C.B. Mohr, 1965), 213. Revised
power in the end serves to overpower translation: Joel Weinsheimer and Donald
and repress the subject and to encum- G. Marshall Truth and Method (New York:
ber it in darkness. In the end, the system Continuum, 1994), 226.

21
2
THE EARLY HEIDEGGER
Dermot Moran

In this chapter I shall discuss the work of and collaboration for more than a decade
Martin Heidegger from 1912 to 1927, but I (191627), Heidegger was never a student of
shall concentrate especially on the Freiburg Husserls. Heidegger had already completed
and Marburg lecture courses leading up to both his doctorate and his Habilitation the-
Being and Time. sis before he first met Husserl in Freiburg
Heideggers intellectual origins are shortly after the latters arrival there in April
extremely important for his overall philo- 1916. Husserl himself had just lost his son in
sophical outlook but he also tended to a the war and it seems that, at least in Husserls
degree of self-mythologization in later ret- eyes, Heidegger gradually began to fit the role
rospective writings. Heideggers intellec- of Husserls adopted son. Heidegger himself
tual development was less monolithic and displayed less than filial loyalty in his public
focused that his later assertions to William and private evaluations of the old man.
Richardson1 and others might lead one to Largely because of the poverty of his par-
think. For instance, it is clear that the ques- ents, Heidegger had begun his studies as a
tion of Being (die Seinsfrage) is not the Catholic seminarian and theology student.
dominant theme of his early writings, which His 1914 doctoral thesis, an analysis of the
are more concerned in making precise his nature of judgment in which he criticized
understanding of the very nature of philoso- both Rickert and Lask, was entitled Die
phy and to articulate the nature of historical Lehre vom Urteil in Psychologismus (The
human existence (what he first called life Doctrine of Judgment in Psychologism, GA
and then Dasein) in facticity and finitude. 1, 59188),4 written under the direction
Secondly, contrary to his later 1963 account of Arthur Schneider, who held the Chair
in My Way to Phenomenology (TB, 74) it of Christian Philosophy in Freiburg. It is a
is not at all clear that Franz Brentanos On somewhat pedestrian critical discussion of
the Several Senses of Being in Aristotle,2 psychologism that shows few hints of his
the first philosophical text Heidegger read later genius.
while still in the Gymnasium, really did offer Heideggers Habilitation thesis was enti-
much of an inspiration.3 At best, it led him tled Die Kategorien- und Bedeutungslehre
to distinguish the existentialia of Dasein des Duns Scotus (The Categories and the
from the categories that apply to other enti- Doctrine of Meaning in Duns Scotus,
ties. Finally, despite their close friendship reprinted GA 1, 189412), under the

23
THE EARLY HEIDEGGER

direction of Heinrich Rickert. This thesis was philosophy and its relation to phenom-
on a text supposedly by Duns Scotus, but in enology (GA 567/TDP). The influence of
fact written by Thomas of Erfurt. Already Rickert is clearly visible. In this first course,
in his Habilitation (1915), Heidegger had his question is: what is involved in the very
claimed that philosophy had to be not just idea of philosophy? Or, as he puts it, he
about values but about the value of life wants to identify the essential elements
(Lebenswert). Furthermore, he maintained of the idea of philosophy (GA 56/57, 39/
that the formal study of Scholastic thought TDP, 32). Heidegger presents philosophy as
needed to be balanced by a phenomenologi- a scientific attitude that breaks through the
cal exploration of religious experience: natural attitude and heightens the sense of
life. Philosophy is presented as a primor-
I hold the philosophical, more exactly, dial science (Urwissenschaft) that should
the phenomenological handling of the not be allowed degenerate into a world-
mystical, moral-theological, and ascetic view (Weltanschauung). Phenomenology
writings of medieval scholasticism to be cannot be understood as a standpoint at all.
especially crucial in its decisive insight Philosophy is unique in that it contemplates
into this fundamental characteristic of itself through its history and in this way
Scholastic psychology. (GA 1, 205, my awakens to a higher spiritual life:
translation)

Every history and history of philosophy


In his efforts to gain an academic position, constitutes itself in life in and for itself,
Heidegger tailored his curriculum vitae life which is itself historical in an abso-
and interests. Thus he presented himself as lute sense. (GA 56/57, 21/ TDP, 18)
someone interested in the neo-Scholastic
revival of medieval philosophy. Later Karl It is clear that Heidegger is interested in a
Jaspers would record in his Autobiography way of capturing life, while still having sym-
that in conversation with Heidegger he pathy for it. Heidegger questions the man-
expressed his surprise that The dedication ner in which Rickert and other neo-Kantians
of Heideggers first book to Rickert, of his had misunderstood the nature of value and
second to Husserl, emphasizes a connection validity, but he is also critical of phenome-
with people of whom he had spoken to me nologysaying the concept of lived experi-
with contempt.5 Heidegger was certainly ence (Erlebnis) has now been devalued to
career oriented. the point of meaninglessness (GA 56/57, 66/
On January 21, 1919, benefitting greatly TDP, 55) but he is still trying to remain true
from the support of Husserl, Heidegger to the experience and attend to what is given
officially became a salaried member of the in it, filtering out all misinterpretation.
Freiburg philosophy seminar.6 Four days This first lecture course gives the impres-
later, on January25, the War Emergency sion of a young philosopher struggling to
Semester (Kriegnotsemester) commenced, articulate intuitions that are not yet clear to
and Heidegger offered his first lecture course, him. The primary sense is of someone resist-
The Idea of Philosophy and the Problem ing and attempting to throw off the existing
of Worldview, in which he explored his academic tradition in Germany, especially
own understanding of the true method of the neo-Kantian emphasis on epistemology

24
THE EARLY HEIDEGGER

and theory of science. There are foreshad- practical. We should not even say the envi-
owingswhen the circular nature of philo- ronment is given because givenness already
sophical understanding is mentioned, or the presupposes the theoretical. Thingliness
meaning of the questioning comportment [Dinghaftigkeit] marks out a quite original
(GA 56/57, 66/TDP, 56), the manner in which sphere distilled out the environmental (GA
humans always belong to an environing 56/57, 89/TDP, 75). Once we grasp things,
world (Umwelt), the way in which things their worldliness disappears. The expression
are always experienced as worldly, such that it worlds is supposed to convey the char-
one can say it worlds (es weltet, GA 56/57, acter of pre-theoretical experience. In this
73/TDP, 61). Perhaps most intriguingly, first lecture course, Heidegger is interested
Heidegger is already trying to distinguish in the manner in which the world as such is
between objective knowledge that involves presupposed in various kinds of encounters
distance from things and a kind of event of with things.
appropriation or happening (Ereignis) in Heidegger continued to lecture at Freiburg
which one is self-involved. Most importantly from 1919 to 1923 and his courses show him
Heidegger is envisaging that phenomenol- developing an independent critical perspective
ogy must incorporate a new and expanded on the then contemporary philosophical scene,
kind of intuitionhermeneutic intuition specifically neo-Kantian philosophy (particu-
(die hermeneutische Intuition, GA 56/57, larly Rickert, Natorp, Windelband, and Emil
117/TDP, 98). Already in 1919 Heidegger is Lask), phenomenology (Husserl and Scheler),
attempting to fuse hermeneutical interpret- hermeneutics, and life-philosophy (Dilthey
ing with phenomenological intuiting. and Simmel). No matter what the announced
One of the early Heideggers major con- course title was, Heidegger always used the
cerns is the meaning of realism. He diag- occasion to think deeply about the nature of
noses critical realism and critical idealism philosophy as such (What is it? What kind of
as both suffering from the same defectin science? How do we reach it?) and more spe-
believing our sense of world and of objects cifically to interrogate the meaning and value
are somehow constituted out of sense data of phenomenology as a mode of approach
(Sinnesdaten). Both idealism and realism pre- to the issues (and, in passing, treated in his
sume the primacy of theoretical knowledge lectures of issues such as the nature of phi-
the primacy of the theoretical (Primat des losophy as a science, the meaning of world-
Theoretischen, GA 56/57, 87/TDP, 73) and view, the externalities of the current study
assume its stance toward the world as being of philosophy in the university, the need for
simply the way things are. The problem is: university reform, and so on).
what is to be understood as the immediately Husserls own opinion of Heidegger at
given? (GA 56/57, 85/TDP, 71) Realism and that time is instructive. At first Husserl
idealism fail to grasp what being-in-the-world saw Heidegger as a confessionally bound
really means. Heidegger wants to understand Catholic, but he came to appreciate the seri-
how the environmental (das Umweltliche) ousness with which Heidegger appeared to
is experienced: how do I live and experi- have embraced Protestantism and regarded
ence the environmental? (GA 56/57, 88/ him as something of an expert on Martin
TDP, 74). Heidegger is already stressing Luther. For, on January 9, 1919, just prior
that our primary engagement with things is to taking up his post as Husserls assistant,

25
THE EARLY HEIDEGGER

Heidegger himself, in a letter to his former lecture to the Marburg Theological Society,
confessor Fr. Krebs, signaled his depar- Heidegger is much more detailed in terms of
ture from the system of Catholicism and explaining the relation between Dasein and
talks of his own phenomenological studies temporality, now deliberately employing his
in religion (S, 6970). Similarly, he wrote own technical jargon. Here he laments that
to his friend Elizabeth Blochmann in May previous Christian thinkers (paradigmatically
1919, stating that he was making prepara- Augustine) have always taken their orienta-
tions toward a phenomenology of religious tion from the eternity (aei) enjoyed by God
consciousness.7 In these early Freiburg and measured time in some respect as offset
lectures Heidegger constantly emphasizes against eternity, whereas he wants to clear the
that religion as a way of life has its own foreground by analyzing how time is lived in
entirely originary intentionality (ganz its everyday sense. Dasein itself is time (GA
originre Intentionalitt, GA 60, 322/PRL, 64/CT, 20E). Heidegger does recognize that
244), its own structural categoriesalready the distinctive claim of Christianity is that
described in his 1920/21 lecture course as time is in some sense fulfilled (e.g. St Paul,
existentialia (Existenzialien, GA 60, 232/ Gal. 4.4), but his own account concentrates
PRL, 173), its own worldliness and valu- on the manner the self disperses itself in the
ableness (Welt- und Werthaftigkeit, GA 60, everyday and flees from facing futurity, which
322/PRL, 244), and its own basic concep- is the real essence of human temporality.
tions on which philosophy must not try to Heideggers interest is to find a way to
impose its own conceptual schemes from understand life in and for itself (GA 56/57,
without: 125/TDP, 106) as he puts it in his 1919 lecture
course Phenomenology and Transcendental
Real philosophy arises not from pre- Philosophy of Value. In his 1919/1920 lecture
conceived concepts of philosophy and course Basic Problems of Phenomenology
religion. Rather the possibility of its (Grundprobleme der Phnomenologie, GA
philosophical understanding arises out
58), he speaks of an original exploration of
of a certain religiosity [Religiositt]for
life (Ursprungserforschung des Lebens, GA
us the Christian religiosity.. . . The task
is to gain a real and original relationship 58, 155). Heidegger suggests that phenome-
to history, which is to be explicated from nology has to describe the special kind of non-
out of our own historical situation and objectifying, nontheoretical self-awareness of
facticity. (GA 60, 1245/PRL, 89) original experience (GA 58, 1557; see also
2578). This nonreflective awareness belongs
Heidegger claims that no real religion allows to the immediate experience of life. This
itself to be captured philosophically (GA theme remainsself-reflection is not the best
60, 323/PRL, 244).8 Unfortunately, in this way to grasp the meaning of Dasein. Thus,
19201 courseas in the Freiburg lecture in his 1927 lecture course, Heidegger empha-
courses generallyHeidegger is somewhat sizes, against Husserlian phenomenology,
vague and promissory in his approach to that self-reflection is not the primary mode in
the kind of temporality enjoyed by Christian which Dasein is with itself or for itself:
life and how it orients itself to the eternal.
His confidence in describing temporality Dasein, as existing, is there for itself,
grows over the years such that, in his 1924 even when the ego does not expressly

26
THE EARLY HEIDEGGER

direct itself to itself in the manner of its Being and Time (1927). For example, it is
own peculiar turning around and turning in reflection on the existential structures of
back, which in phenomenology is called Christian living that Heidegger develops his
inner perception as contrasted with particular conceptions of everydayness
outer. The self is there for the Dasein
(Alltglichkeit), where time is experienced
itself without reflection and without
primarily as the present, and fallenness
inner perception, before all reflection.
Reflection, in the sense of a turning back, (Verfallen), the manner in which human life
is only a mode of self-apprehension, but finds itself captivated by the world.9 When
not the mode of primary self-disclosure. Heidegger writes that Christian experi-
(GA 24, 226/BP, 159) ence lives time itself (GA 60, 82/PRL, 57),
he seems to be suggesting that Christianity
In his 1920 lecture course Phenomenology has a certain stance toward life in its tempo-
of Intuition and Expression, Heidegger ral unfolding, one that emphasizes a future
presents one of the chief tasks of philoso- that has in some sense already arrived,
phy as the attempt to awaken and appreci- parousia, which in traditional Greek means
ate the sense of facticity (die Faktizitt): arrival (GA 60, 102/PRL, 71), and in the
Philosophy has the task of preserving the Old Testament signifies the arrival of the
facticity of life and strengthening the facticity Lord on the day or Judgment and, in Jewish
of Dasein (GA 59, 174/PIE, 133). In notes texts, refers to the arrival of the Messiah.
for this course, he writes: lifethe primary But, Heidegger claims that in Christianity
phenomenon! (Leben Urphnomen, GA it means the arriving again of the already
59, 176). Similarly, in his 19212 lecture appeared Messiah and hence its entire con-
course Phenomenological Interpretations ceptual structure has changed. Parousia is not
of Aristotle he writes: Factical life: life characterized by waiting or hope, rather
expresses a basic phenomenological cat- the issue is a question about the manner of
egory; it signifies a basic phenomenon carrying out ones life, the enactment of life
(Grundphnomen, GA 61, 80/PIA, 61). Life, itself (Vollzug des Lebens, GA 60, 104/PRL,
however, is also a vague and ambiguous con- 73). Living life constitutes different senses
cept. The key to life is its facticity: This of temporality. Similarly faith (pistis) is not
facticity is something life is, and whereby interpreted as a kind of believing, a taking
it is, in its highest authenticity (GA 61, to be true (Frwahrhalten, GA 60, 108/
87/ PIA, 66). Facticity is the basic sense of PRL, 76) but rather as a complex of enact-
the being of life (ibid.). Furthermore, phi- ment (Vollzugszusammenhang) of sense, a
losophy is historiological cognition of fac- way of experiencing capable of increase
tical life (GA 61, 1/PIA, 3). Life is also, or greater intensity and hence testifying to
Heidegger affirms, world-related (GA 61, something like authenticity. Christian hope,
85/PIA, 65). Thus, in his early lecture courses as Heidegger interprets it, is not about some
in Freiburg, Heidegger is concerned less with future event to come but rather about endur-
issues of Being (Sein) and more with the con- ing, coping, and resilience in relation to the
crete sense of factical human existence. insecurity of life (GA 60, 151/PRL, 107).
From 1920 to 1923 Heidegger identi- Heidegger is interpreting religious life not in
fies and explores the existential structures terms of its supposed transcendent meaning
that will receive full scale thematization in but in terms of an historically determined

27
THE EARLY HEIDEGGER

style of living in and through time, a way Alongside theses explorations of religious
of coping with the fundamental insecu- life, the early Heidegger was also deeply
rity. Christian life involves enactment immersed in Aristotles account of ethical liv-
(Vollzug); Christian facticity is enactment ing. He offered a course onPhenomenological
(GA 60, 121/PRL, 86). The challenge for Interpretations of Aristotle in 1921/1922
Christian factical life is to remain awake (GA 61/PIA) and also prepared a text with
and sober in relation to the enormous chal- a similar title that he submitted as a writing
lenge of life. sample to Paul Natorp for consideration for
For Heidegger, early Christian religious life a post in Marburg for which Husserl had
has already been Hellenized or Greecicized recommended him. This writing samplethe
(Heideggers word is Grzisierung) due to the so-called Natorp Berichtwas rediscovered
influence of the specifically Greek interpre- and published for the first time in 1989.11 It
tation of Dasein and through Greek concep- is a fascinating document that manyinclud-
tuality (GA 61, 6/PIA, 6). Heidegger here ing Hans-Georg Gadamersee as the first
explicitly speaks of the Greek worldview step toward Being and Time.12 Heidegger is
(die griechische Lebenswelt) and he is deeply now explicitly linking phenomenology to
awarein the spirit of Diltheyof the man- a kind of Aristotelian inquiry. He is seek-
ner in which worldviews wither away and ing the being of factical life (S, 121). The
are replaced by different worldviews. He object of research is factical human Dasein
wants then to uncover the meaning of histor- (115). Life has a tendency to make things
ical everyday existence before it is obscured easy for itself (113). It has a tendency for
by worldviewsthis is Daseinsanalyse. falling (117). Life is always experienced
It is a noteworthy feature of this period as having-been-interpreted (116). Life is
of Heideggers intellectual formation that always mired in inauthentic traditions and
the activity of removing the metaphysical customs of one sort or another (118). It is
edifice encrusted on religious experience is only when one brings ones own death into
referred to, already in 1920, as destruc- explicit focus that life as such becomes vis-
tion (Destruktion, also Zerstrung, GA60, ible (119). This is genuinely anticipatory
311/PRL, 236). Heideggers model here is of Being and Time in that Heidegger now
Martin Luthers reading of St. Paul.10 In speaks of a fundamental ontology (121) of
his 1920 lecture course he articulates the factical Dasein.
notion of phenomenological Destruktion In these years Heidegger is also elaborat-
(GA 59, 35) or phenomenological-critical ing on the meaning of hermeneutics. In his
destruction (GA 59, 30), which should 1921/22 course on Aristotle he is already
be thought of as not so much demo- speaking of phenomenological herme-
lition (Zertrmmern) but rather as neutics (GA 61, 187/PIA, 141; see also
de-structuring (Abbau, GA 59, 35). In his S, 122) and the fundamental intentional
Phenomenology of Religious Life lectures, movement of life as care (curare). By 1923,
he also speaks of the need to subject mod- he is characterizing hermeneutics not as any
ern history of religion to a phenomenolog- kind of interpretative method but rather as
ical destruction to allow the evidence of Daseins own wakefulness (Wachsein) with
its fore-conception to manifest itself (GA regard to its own existence; hermeneutics is
60, 78/PRL, 54). the self-interpretation of facticity (GA 63, 15/

28
THE EARLY HEIDEGGER

OHF, 12). As Heidegger writes in his Natorp and Time that he arrangedwith Husserls
Bericht: helpto have printed. Husserl himself even
visited Todtnauberg that Spring to assist
. . . philosophy is not an artificial occu- Heidegger with the proofreading.14 However,
pation that merely accompanies life and in December 1926, the Education Minister
deals with universals . . . but rather in Berlin declared the publication inadequate
is a knowing that questions, that is, as
and the Chair in Marburg was not offered to
research, simply the explicit and genu-
Heidegger. Heidegger then went on to pub-
ine actualizing of the tendency towards
interpretation that belongs to the basic lish the full text of Being and Time, Part I
movements of life in which what is at in Spring 1927 both as a separate book and
issue is this life itself and its being . . . as part of Husserls Jahrbuch.15 Heideggers
(S, 121) magnum opus had finally appeared in print,
an uneven work that manifests the enor-
In other words, humans live through self- mous efforts Heidegger had made to impose
interpretative engagement with their lives a system (transcendental phenomenological
and philosophy is that illumination of that ontology) and even an architectonic (see 8
self-interpreting historical living in facticity. Design of the Treatise, GA 2, 523/BTMR,
In Autumn 1923 Heidegger moved to 634) on what had been his diverse concrete
Marburg. Heidegger now comes into close explorations of human historical existence
contact with neo-Kantian philosophers (his preparatory fundamental analysis of
such as Nicolai Hartmann, distinguished Dasein, GA 2, 53/BTMR, 64) over the pre-
classicists such as Natorp, and theolo- ceding decade.
gians such as Rudolf Otto and Bultmann.13
But he himself seemed to find more affin-
NOTES AND REFERENCES
ity in the writings of Dilthey and Scheler.
In 1924, he offered Basic Concepts of 1
See Heideggers Letter to Richardson, in
Aristotelian Philosophy (Grundbegriffe der William J. Richardson, Heidegger: Through
aristotelischen Philosophie, GA 18), which Phenomenology to Thought (The Hague:
focused on the Nicomachean Ethics. The Nijhoff, 1963), viiixxiii.
theme is practical life. In 1925, Heidegger
2
Franz Brentano, Von der mannigfachen
Bedeutung des Seienden nach Aristoteles
was nominated by the Philosophy Faculty (Freiburg: Herder, 1862; reprinted, Darmstadt:
for the Chair at Marburg recently vacated Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1960),
by Hartmann. However, his nomination translated by Rolf George as On the Several
was turned down by the Education Ministry Senses of Being in Aristotle (Berkeley:
because of insufficient publications. To rem- University of California Press, 1975).
3
Theodore Kisiel, The Genesis of Being and
edy this gap, he was pressured by the Dean of Time (Berkeley: University of California Press,
the Marburg Faculty to hasten into print the 1993), 229, has rightly pointed out that both
still uncompleted manuscript of Being and My Way to Phenomenology and the letter to
Time. Heidegger promised to have the type- Richardson stress only Heideggers involvement
script to Niemeyer by April 1, 1926. Over with phenomenology and hence are not reliable
guides to his overall intellectual development.
the term break, from February to April 1926, 4
M. Heidegger, Die Lehre vom Urteil in
Heidegger retired to his hut in Todtnauberg Psychologismus. Eik kritisch-positiver Beitrag
and brought together some 240 pages of Being zur Logik (Leipzig: Barth, 1914).

29
THE EARLY HEIDEGGER

5
Quoted in Elizabeth Hirsch, Remembrances (neo-Kantian, phenomenological, hermeneutic,
of Martin Heidegger in Marburg, Philosophy life-philosophy) that were current in contem-
Today (Summer 1979), 1609. porary Germany. It is true, if a little odd, that
6
See Karl Schuhmann, Husserl-Chronik. Denk- Heidegger arrived in Marburg with a reputa-
und Lebensweg Edmund Husserls (The Hague: tion as an expert on Luther!
Nijhoff, 1977), 231. For the significance of 11
See M. Heidegger, Phnomenologische
Husserls achievement in gaining funding for Interpretationen zu Aristoteles. Anzeige
a paid assistantship, see Hugo Ott, Martin der hermeneutischen Situation,
Heidegger. A Political Life, trans. Allan Dilthey-Jahrbruch fr Philosophie und
Blunden (Oxford: Blackwell, 1993), 11516. Geschichte der Geisteswissenschaften 6 (1989),
Heidegger had been a Privatdozent but 23774; reprinted in Phnomenologische
Husserl secured funding for him. It is not clear Interpretationen zu Aristoteles. Ausarbeitung
that Heidegger was actually Husserls assistant fr die Marburger und die Gttinger Fakultt
in the formal sense. (1922) (Stuttgart: Reclam, 2003). There
7
See Martin Heidegger-Elizabeth Blochmann is a new English translation by John van
Briefe 19181969, hrsg. Joachim W. Buren Phenomenological Interpretations in
Storck (Marbach am Necker: Deutsches Connection with Aristotle. An Indication of the
Literatur-Archiv, 1989), 16; 2nd edn, 1990. Hermeneutical Situation (S, 11145).
8
Heidegger was not alone in wanting to free 12
Indeed Husserl had even planned to publish
religion from its philosophical superstructure. a version of it in Volume VII of his Jahrbuch
Ernst Troeltsch and Rudolf Bultmann were (1924/1925).
proposing something similar.
13
On Heideggers time in Marburg see Elisabeth
9
In his Letter on Humanism, Heidegger Hirsch, Remembrances of Martin Heidegger in
emphasizes that Verfallen does not signify the Marburg, Philosophy Today, 23(1979), 1609.
theological Fall of humanity but rather an 14
In the tradition of proofreading, it is custom-
essential relation of human being to Being, see, ary to read the text backward so that typo-
GA 9, 163/PA, 253. graphical errors are more visible as one is not
10
John van Buren, The Young Heidegger disrupted by the flow of the text. It is possibly
(Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1994), for this reason that Husserl did not at that
167, has suggested that Heideggers first use time realize how far Heidegger had departed
of the term destruction is in GA 58, 139, in from his own transcendental phenomenology
connection with Luthers attack on Aristotle until he sat down to read and comment on the
and Scholasticism. However, I believe van book in 1929.
Buren overstates the case when he claims: 15
In later years Heidegger recalled that Being
The young Heidegger saw himself at this time and Time was published in February 1927,
as a kind of philosophical Luther of Western whereas Theodore Kisiel, The Genesis of Being
metaphysics (ibid., 167). In fact, Heideggers and Time, 489, dates it to April 1927. On
tone in his lecture courses is still one of trying April8, 1926Husserls birthdayHeidegger
to come to terms with the meaning of the presented Husserl with a handwritten dedica-
various competing philosophical methods tion page for the book.

30
3
THE TURN: ALL THREE OF THEM
Thomas Sheehan

Heideggers main topic was not being between whatever we encounter and the cor-
and that for at least two reasons. First of responding human concerns and intentions.
all, when Heidegger uses the phrase the Which is to say that the early Heidegger con-
being of beings (das Sein des Seienden), he centrated on the significance to us of what-
understands the phrase as das Anwesen des ever we meet in the world.
Anwesenden, the meaningful presence of The second reason why being is not
things to human concerns. In other words, Heideggers main topic is the same reason
despite Heideggers employment of the sur- why meaningfulness (Anwesen) was not
passed ontological lexicon of being, there his final goal but only his initial concern.
is, underlying all of his work, a phenomeno- Heideggers ultimate purpose was not to
logical reduction of being to meaning. analyze the meaningfulness of things but to
In his mature work, in fact, Heidegger shied move beyond such meaningfulness to the
away from the word Sein. I no longer like to X that makes it possible. Using the tra-
use the word being, he said. ditions ontological lexicon, he named this
project the quest for the essence of being
Being remains only the provisional (das Wesen des Seins). This means not the
term. Consider that being was origi- definable whatness of being but, rather,
nally called presence [Anwesen] in the what brings being about. To state the mat-
sense of a things staying-here-before-us in ter more properly in phenomenological
unconcealment [i.e. in meaningfulness].1 terms, Heideggers sights were ultimately
set on what allows for or makes possible
Thus Heidegger does not read the phrase meaningfulness (das Anwesenlassen), that
the being of beings in terms of things exist- is, the source and provenance of meaning-
ing out there in the world, so to speak, fulness (die Herkunft des Anwesens).2 He
apart from human beings, as does classical called that enabling source the clearing
realist metaphysics. Rather, he understands (Lichtung), understood as the primal open-
the being of beings phenomenologically, as ing up of intelligibility at all (Verstehbarkeit)
referring to the meaningful presence of things that lets us make sense of whatever we
to our corresponding needs and interests, encounter.3
whether practical or theoretical. At least ini- These two moments of Heideggers proj
tially, Heidegger focused on the correlation ectthe analysis of the meaningfulness of

31
THE TURN: ALL THREE OF THEM

things and the discovery of the source of meaningfulness to his basic question about
that meaningfulnesscorrespond to what the X that makes meaningfulness possible.
we may distinguish as his lead-in question Most Heideggerians wrongly take this sec-
and his basic question. In turn we might ond and secondary meaning of the turn as
align those two moments with the earlier the proper sense of die Kehre. As against
(191929) and the later (193076) periods that, and in order to emphasize its secondary
of his philosophy. nature, I will call this reversal Kehre-2.
A third and analogous meaning of the
*** turn (Kehre-3) refers to the radical conver-
sion in ones self-understanding that ideally
Like many of Heideggers key terms, the follows from realizing that Kehre-1/reciproc-
turn (die Kehre) is analogical rather than ity is the basis of all meaningfulness and thus
univocal: it refers, by way of an analogy of of human existence itself.7 This personal
attribution ( ), to at least three dis- (existentiel) conversion in how one under-
tinct but interrelated issues in Heideggers stands and lives out ones life is discussed
thought. We may call them (1) reciprocity, (2) by the early Heidegger under the rubric of
reversal, and (3) resoluteness.4 resoluteness (Entschlossenheit) and by the
The first and primary issue that bears the later Heidegger under that of releasement
title the turn is what Heidegger calls the rec- (Gelassenheit), understood as taking the
iprocity (Gegenschwung)5 or back-and-forth turn into Ereignis.8 Both of these are under-
oscillation between human existence (Dasein) stood as the entre to what Heidegger called
and meaning. We can express that reciprocity authenticity in the sense of living in terms
in a chiasmic formula: Without human being, of ones true selfhood.
there is no meaning, and without meaning, Among these three analogical meanings of
there is no human being. This reciprocity of the word Kehrethe reciprocity of man and
need is the core of Heideggers thinking, what meaning, the reversal of perspective worked
he called the thing itself. Meaning needs us out in the 1930s, and the resoluteness that
if things are to be intelligible; and we need ideally follows from an awareness of the
meaning if we are to exist at all and as das finitude of reciprocityit is the first one, the
Da, the locus of all possible sense. Especially chiasm of man and meaning, that ultimately
in his Contributions to Philosophy (19368; controls the other two. On the one hand, the
published 1989), Heidegger declares that this reversal of perspective (Kehre-2) that was
reciprocity is in fact the proper sense of the planned for the unpublished part of Being
turn, the hidden ground of all other subor- and Time and that was de facto carried out
dinate turns. . . .6 It is the prime analogue in the mid-1930s, is only a means to arriving
that lends meaning to the other, subordinate at a clear understanding of the reciprocity
usages of the term Kehre. Therefore, let us of man and meaning: Kehre-1. On the other
call this reciprocity Kehre-1. hand, the resoluteness or releasement that
The second and quite distinct issue that can follow from insight into the reciproc-
also bears the title the turn is the reversal, ity is the way that we personally enact the
the de facto shift in focus that Heidegger car- consequences of that reciprocity in our own
ried out in his work from the 1930s onwards, lives. Thus, as is the case with the analogy of
a shift from his lead-in question about attribution, the second and third meanings of

32
THE TURN: ALL THREE OF THEM

the turn gather around and derive their sense space there could be no meaningfulness at
from the first and primary meaning, the all, whether practical (using this tool for that
prime analogue that is Kehre-1. In fact this task) or theoretical (taking Socrates as an
reciprocity of man and meaning is the core Athenian). The primary function of human
of Heideggers thought, the thing itself (die existence, its raison dtre, is to hold open
Sache selbst). that space and to belong to meaning. Or
We now take up the main characteristics to put it in terms of the second half of the
of each of these three turns. chiasm: meaning requires (braucht) human
existence to sustain the openness within
*** which meaning can occur.
Heidegger often speaks of meaning as
Kehre-1, reciprocity. Only with the posthu- such (being itself) as taking the initiative
mous publication of Heideggers Contributions of calling human existence to itself and as
to Philosophy did it become clear that the awaiting a response or correspondence
primary meaning of the turn was the chias- to that call.9 He will sometimes say that
mic reciprocity of human existences need of being itself throws itself forth to human
meaning and meanings need of human exist- existence while at the same time claiming
ence. The thesis underlying this position is that existence as its own property (Eigentum).10
the very nature of human being is to make dis- Such metaphors risk serious misunderstand-
cursive sense of things, that is, to understand ing, not only because they hypostasize being
their meaning (to deny this thesis is willy-nilly itself into an other that stands over against
to make sense of it and thus to confirm it). human existence but also because they
We do not first exist and only then, as an attribute anthropomorphic agency to mean-
add-on, make sense of things. Rather, we are ing (being itself), as if it had a mind and
pan-hermeneutical: sense-making is our very will of its own. The same anthropomorphiz-
existence. Even madness is a way of making ing hypostatization persists in Heideggers
sense. use of the faux reflexive voice when he speaks
To begin with the first moment of this of being hiding itself from and revealing
chiasmic reciprocity: Contributions speaks itself to human beings. The way to avoid
of human existence as necessarily belonging these gross misunderstandings is first of all to
(zugehrend) to meaning in the sense of sus- read being phenomenologically in terms of
taining the openness that is the condition of meaningfulness and its enabling source, and
all discursive intelligibility. Meaningfulness then to understand mans thrown nature
requires a spacea possibilizing dimen- (Geworfenheit) as the necessity of holding
sionwithin which we can perform the open the space for meaning.
twofold act of making sense of something, In Contributions to Philosophy, Heidegger
namely, distinguishing S and P (: equates such thrown-openness with what
keeping distinct a thing and its possible he calls the appropriation (Ereignis or
meanings) while taking S in terms of P Ereignetsein) of human being to sustaining
(: unifying the thing and its mean- the clearing. The term Ereignis/appropria-
ing). The primordial openness of the clearing tion means the same thing as thrownness
is what makes possible such distinguishing and has to do with human existence being
and synthesizing. Without that possibilizing brought into its own.11 Appropriation is

33
THE TURN: ALL THREE OF THEM

the later Heideggers preferred term for the out the full project of Being and Time. The
chiasmic reciprocity that is Kehre-1. Ones book remained a torso, and the reversal, at
appropriation to holding open the clearing least in the transcendental form in which
is ones thrown-openness (with emphasis on Heidegger had originally planned to carry it
the thrownness) as the clearing. Ereignis is out, remained a road not taken. Nonetheless,
thus the thing itself of Heideggers phi- still intent on carrying out the turn to mean-
losophy. It is the the opening of the open- ingfulness and its source, Heidegger in the
ness that allows for meaningful presence 1930s adopted a different approach to his
(Anwesenlassen) and thus answers the project, one that he characterized as seinsge-
question of how meaningfulness is given. schichtlich, which is best paraphrased as the
Heideggers key phrase Es gibt Sein (being giving-of-meaning approach.
is given) now translates as: Appropriation/ Thus from 1930 on, we notice a remark-
thrown-openness is what makes meaningful- able shift in Heideggers lectures and pub-
ness possible. lications. If his early work emphasized the
first half of the chiasmno human being =
*** no meaninghis later work shifted its focus
to the second half: no meaning = no human
Kehre-2, the reversal. Heideggers shift of being. The focus now in Kehre-2 was on
focus from meaningfulness to its source was how the clearing, which it is our very nature
already programmed into the 1927 outline of to hold open, makes possible the mean-
Being and Time. The book was projected in ing of all we encounter. But even with this
two parts, which we may abbreviate as BT shift, what remained constant throughout
I (fundamental ontology) and BT II (histori- the earlier and the later work was the core
cal deconstruction), but only BT I interests of Heideggers thought: the reciprocity of
us here. The first two divisions of part one need that we have called Kehre-1. In fact,
(= BT I.12) were focused on how human Kehre-2, the reversal, was only a means to
existence is thrown open as the locus of all spelling out Kehre-1, the reciprocity that
possible meaningfulness. The third division is the goal of Heideggers thought. So once
(= BT I.3) was then going to effect a shift in again we state the chiasmbut now in the
focus, a reversal (Kehre-2) from human reverse order: The clearing-for-meaning is
thrown-openness as the locus of meaning human existences raison dtre (in that sense
to the question of how meaningfulness is the clearing has priority over existence); and
given within the space of that openness. human existence is the sine qua non of the
Whereas BT I.12 concentrated on human clearing-for-meaning (in that sense, existence
existence, BT I.3 would reverse things and is the ground of the emergence of meaning).
concentrate on meaningfulness itself, with
special emphasis on its source. In that sense, ***
Kehre-2 was to be the reversal (William J.
Richardson) of the trajectory of BT I.12. Kehre-3, resoluteness. Above I said that
However, BT I.3 was never published, Kehre-1the reciprocity of need between man
partly because Heidegger found the tran- and meaningis the final goal of Heideggers
scendental approach, with human exist- thinking. But that is not exactly right. First of
ence as its centerpiece, inadequate to carry all, the final goal of his entire project is not

34
THE TURN: ALL THREE OF THEM

theoretical but practical: a transformation effective acceptance of the mystery of ones


in human being itself (eine Verwandlung des inexorable way of being, namely thrown-
Menschseins selbst).12 Secondly, an effective ness or appropriation for the sake of sustain-
and not merely theoretical understanding of ing the clearing for meaning. The point of
the reciprocity of man and meaning issues Heideggers exhortation is to love our fate,
in that very transformation. In the text cited that is, to take upon ourselves (= Kehre-3)
below, Heidegger speaks of the truth of our finite appropriation (= Kehre-1) and to
being, by which he means the opening for live in accord with it.
(or dis-closure of) meaningfulness, which Thus Kehre-3 or resoluteness not only
equates with the appropriated clearing as the depends on insight into Kehre-1 but also
source that enables all meaning. The phrase is related to it in three other ways. The
the meaning-process in the following text first deals with the threefold hiddenness of
translates the German Seyn. Note the relation Ereignis (hiddenness, too, is an analogical
between all three senses of the turn. term) and thus with the difficulty of person-
ally realizing ones thrownness as the basis of
We must insist over and over that what a possible conversion. The second concerns
is at stake in the question of the open- Heideggers so-called history of being,
ness [of the meaning-process] as raised which he presents under the rubric of appro-
here is . . . a transformation in human priation/thrown-openness as the giving of
being itself [Kehre-3: resoluteness]. . . . epochs of meaningfulness (die Geschicke
We are questioning human being in its des Seins). The third is the virtual oblitera-
relation to the meaning-process, or in the tion of all traces of Ereignis in the present
perspective of Kehre-2 [i.e. the reversal],
age. In what follows, I gather these three
the meaning-process and its openness in
issues together.
relation to human being. Determining
the essence of openness [Kehre-1] is The three analogical levels of the hidden-
accompanied by a necessary transforma- ness of appropriation, and thus of the clear-
tion of human being [Kehre-3]. Both are ing, are (1) their intrinsic hiddenness, (2) the
the same.13 overlooking of that hiddenness, and (3) the
present ages virtual obliteration of both
The whole of Heideggers work is a protrep- theintrinsic hiddenness and its overlooking.
tic to accept and become what one already is: The second level corresponds to the history
thrown open for the sake of meaningfulness. of metaphysics and the third to the current
This means taking the reciprocity, with all its age of techno-think (Technik).
finitude, upon oneself as the basis for a new, As regards the first level of hiddenness.
authentic way of living. Before the reversal Because our thrown-openness is the presup-
Being and Time culminated in an exhorta- position of all sense-making, it is opaque
tion to resoluteness, to becoming oneself by to any attempt to find out why that is the
taking over ones thrownness (bernahme case. Heidegger expresses this opacity as the
der Geworfenheit).14 After the reversal intrinsic hiddenness of the bond of man and
Heideggers work is an exhortation to meaning. Because that bond of appropriation
become oneself by taking over ones appro- is the presupposition of all sense-making,
priation (bernahme der Er-eignung).15 In one cannot make sense of itfor example,
both cases (which are coequal) the issue is an trace it back to a reason or causewithout

35
THE TURN: ALL THREE OF THEM

presupposing it and thus falling into circular thrown-openness. These individual forma-
reasoning. We can experience the fact that tionscalled epochs insofar as appropria-
thrown-openness-for-the-sake-of-meaning is tion and the clearing are under epochcan
as far back as we can go, but we are unable be distinguished by seeing how select Western
to peek over its edge to find out why thrown- philosophers, from Plato through Nietzsche,
ness/appropriation is the case. We can discern construed the basic sense of being/mean-
that but not why we are thrown into the need ingfulness: for example, in Plato,
to sustain the clearing-for-meaning. To try to in Aristotle, esse in Aquinas, and
make sense of this thrownness requires that so on. In all such historical casesas well as
we already use it as the basis of our effort to in individuals today who are unable to see
make sense of itwhich comes down to the through their fallenness to the thrown-open
logical fallacy called begging the question clearingthe intrinsic hiddenness of Ereignis
(petitio principii), that is, already assuming is doubled: Ereignis, the source of the clear-
and utilizing what we say we are trying to ing that allows for all meaningfulness, is not
explain.16 This complete opacity to questions only ineluctably hidden, but that hiddenness
about the what and why of thrown-openness is also overlooked and forgotten.
is what Heidegger means by the intrinsic hid- The result is that the ideal of traditional
denness of the man-meaning reciprocity. It is Western humanism is a conversion to a meta-
the prime analogue for the other two mean- physical understanding of man as the rational
ings of hiddenness. animal, capable of comprehending the mean-
Metaphysics and the second level of hid- ing of things and its ultimate entitative cause,
denness. Given its intrinsic hiddenness, the but blocked from an insight into, much less
reciprocal man-meaning bond is easily over- a conversion to, the mortal thrown-openness
looked and forgotten, and this constitutes the that is Kehre-1.
second level of hiddenness. For Heidegger, The present age and the third level of hid-
the history of Western philosophy is a his- denness. Heidegger holds that the current
tory of overlooking human thrownness and epoch of meaningfulness is characterized by
the open region of possible intelligibility that techno-think (Technik) and its compulsion to
it sustains. Metaphysics (1) has focused on construe everything, including human beings,
the meaningfulness (being) of whatever is as a resource to be exploited for capitaliza-
encountered within the clearing, while for- tion and consumption. The danger haunting
getting the clearing itself; and (2) has traced this age is that techno-think virtually blots
meaningfulness back to an ultimate ontic out all traces of both the intrinsic hiddenness
cause or reason, usually but not necessarily and the overlooking of Ereignis and thus
called god. leads to a tripling of the hiddenness of our
Thus for metaphysics the clearing is brack- appropriation. The age of techno-think and
eted out (is subject to an epoch), that is, the global exploitation is characterized by a vir-
fact of its intrinsic hiddenness is overlooked. tually complete obliteration (third level) of
Hence the history of meaning is parceled our overlooking and forgetting (second level)
out as a series of metaphysical formations of the intrinsic hiddenness of the reciprocity
of meaning. These formations are distinct (first level).
gifts (Geschicke) of the giving of mean- However, Heidegger sees a glimmer of
ing (Schenkung) that is made possible by hope that at least some people (the few)

36
THE TURN: ALL THREE OF THEM

could, at opportune moments, enjoy a brief of Being and Time. (3) Heideggers history of
glimpse into the mystery17a moment of philosophy reads all of Western metaphysics
epiphanyand even further, might turn as oblivious of the intrinsic hiddenness of the
into Ereignis. In his 1949 lecture Die reciprocity that is Kehre-1. While the present
Kehre, Heidegger held out the prospect that, age of techno-think harbors the danger of
in this age that virtually obliterates Ereignis, obliterating any trace even of our oblivious-
some might sense their profound alienation ness, Heidegger holds out the hope of a per-
from the source of meaning. In a moment of sonal insight into the source of meaning and
sudden but decisive epiphany (Blitz, Blick),18 human existence, and a corresponding turn
they might experience their mortal bonded- or transformation in how we lead our lives.
ness to meaning and thereby be drawn to a
transformation of themselves and of the cur-
NOTES AND REFERENCES
rent oppressive formation of meaning.
1
GA 15, 20.89/HS 8.345: Obwohl ich dieses
*** Wort nicht mehr gern gebrauche; and GA 7,
234.1317/EGT, 78.214: . . . her-vor-whren
In summary: (1) A proper, phenomenological in die Unverborgenheit.
understanding of the turn begins with the
2
GA 14, 45.2930/TB, 37.56: Anwesenlassen.
realization that Heideggers discourse about GA 6.2, 304.1011 = NIV, 201.1315:
Wesensherkunft, Herkunft von Anwesen.
being is to be understood as a discourse See GA 2, 53.345: Das Anwesen aus dieser
about meaningfulness, one that is ultimately Herkunft.
focused on the source of meaningfulness. The 3
GA 16, 424.1822: der Bereich
traditional and easily misunderstood onto- der Unverborgenheit oder Lichtung
logical terms for that source include being (Verstehbarkeit). See GA 9, 199.21/PA,
152.24: . . . ins Offene des Begreifens.
itself, the essence of being, and the truth 4
In this paper I put aside the hapaxlogomenon
of being. Phenomenologically that source of the metontological turn that leads to
is to be understood as the clearing, that metontology qua metaphysical ontics (GA
is, our appropriation or thrown-openness 26, 201.2835/MFL, 158.2935). As far as
for the sake of discursive meaningful- I can see, Heidegger never again mentions
this turn. I disagree with Theodore Kisiel
ness. (2) The reciprocity of needmeaning that the metontological turn is referenced in
requires us, and we require meaning, both Heideggers preparatory notes to GA 29/30:
moments at the service of our making sense See Bret Davis, (ed.), Martin Heidegger: Key
of thingsis what Heidegger calls the pri- Concepts (Durham: Acumen, 2009), 28.17.
mary turn at the heart of his thinking
5
GA 65, 251.24/CP2, 198.14; see ibid.,
261.26/206.3: gegenschwingende. The new
(Kehre-1), an effective insight into which translation of CP (CP2) uses oscillation for
would constitute a resolute conversion to Gegenschwung.
living an authentic life based on ones radi- 6
GA 65, 407.711/CP2, 322.324: der verbor-
cal finitude (Kehre-3). Heideggers change gene Grund aller anderen, nachgeordneten . . .
of perspective from human existence as the Kehren.
7
Heidegger speaks of the goal of his work as
locus of meaningfulness to the clearing as the the transformation of a person into Dasein,
locus of human existence (= Kehre-2) was that is, into accepting oneself as thrown-open
carried out in the 1930s and finally fulfilled as the clearing for the sake of meaning. This,
the project that was announced for part one he says, is the same as Kehre-1. Hence I

37
THE TURN: ALL THREE OF THEM

name this transformation Kehre-3. This turn 12


GA 45, 214.18/BQP, 181.78, italicized in the
is referred to in Heideggers lecture The original. See the next note.
Turn at GA 79, 76.34/BFL, 71.312: sich 13
GA 45, 214.1526/BQP, 181.515. Heideggers
ent-wirft, ent-spricht. emphasis.
8
GA 14, 50.23 and 51.33/TB, 41.24 and 42.30 14
GA 2, 431.13/BT, 226.1314.
1: das Einkehr in das Ereignis. 15
GA 65, 322.78/CP2, 169.14.
9
GA 9, 322.301/PA, 246.1516; Noch wartet 16
Aristotle, Prior Analytics II 16, 64b 2865a 9:
das Sein, da Es selbst dem Menschen denk- : On circular reasoning,
wrdig werde. ibid., II 5, 57b 1859b 1.
10
GA 65, 263.14/CP2 207.16. 17
GA 65, 11.21ff./CP2, 11.38ff: die Wenige. GA
11
GA 65, 239.5/CP2 188.25: . . . geworfener 9, 198.212/PA, 151.36: Der Ausblick in das
...d.h. er-eignet; ibid., 304.8/240.16: Dasein Geheimnis.
ist geworfen, ereignet; ibid., 34.9/29.7: die 18
See GA 79, 745/BFL, 701. Note the
Er-eignung, das Geworfenwerden in das eigentli- equivalence of Einblitz der Welt, Lichtblick
che Innestehen in der Wahrheit von der Kehre von Welt, Blitz der Wahrheit, and Blitz des
im Ereignis. Seyns.

38
4
HEIDEGGER IN THE 1930s:
WHO ARE WE?
Richard Polt

The decade of the 1930s is a distinctive and are marked by Heideggers attempt to leap
troubled period in Heideggers philosophical actively into a singular, transformative event
career, marked by a shift from the under- that would bring Germany into its own.
standing of Being to the happening of Being A detailed survey of this period would
(GA 40, 219). That is, instead of analyzing have to review Heideggers intricate interpre-
Daseins capacity to understand the meaning tations of a variety of thinkers, his passion-
of Being, as he intended to do in Being and ate but ambivalent connection to National
Time, Heidegger now looks to the happen- Socialism in thought and practice, and the
ing by virtue of which Dasein comes into its relationship of his academic lecture courses
own as the entity who stands in the truth of and seminars to his voluminous private texts.
Being. The emphasis is no longer on our own In this brief overview we can only scratch the
constitutionhuman nature, in traditional surface, but one recurring question can serve
termsbut on a transformative event that as our guiding thread: Who are we? For
seizes us and thrusts us into the condition of a time Heidegger believed that Hitler could
being-there. answer this question in practice, but with his
Such an event could involve the found- increasing distance from the Nazi party, he
ing of a new political orderand in fact, comes to see the question as a deeper and
the 1930s are notoriously the decade of more difficult one, requiring a philosophical
Heideggers overt political engagement, and poetic struggle that may never eventuate
including his 19334 tenure as Nazi rector in a solution.
of the University of Freiburg. For several
years, he is intensely concerned with action,
decision, and an authentic gathering of the
German Volk. By the end of the decade, how- THE PREDICAMENT OF WHO?
ever, Heideggers view of politics is consider-
ably jaundiced; in the 1940s he will develop Heidegger lays the basis for the question,
a philosophy of Gelassenheit or release- Who are we? in the 1920s, when he devel-
ment that lays aside power and will in order ops a conception of human temporality that
to await the gift of Being. The 1930s, then, culminates in the individuals choice of how

39
HEIDEGGER IN THE 1930s

to exist. Each of us is thrown into a concrete writes laconically, through communicating


heritage, inhabits a meaningful world, and and struggling (384).
projects possible ways to act in terms of some Heidegger begins to address the commu-
ultimate for-the-sake-of-whicha possi- nal dimension of identity more explicitly in
bility that provides the raison dtre for ones the 192930 lecture course The Fundamental
choices and in terms of which ones meaning- Concepts of Metaphysics. Here he carries
ful world is structured (SZ, 84). However, we out an exhaustive first-person-singular phe-
ordinarily forget and even avoid this ultimate nomenology of boredom, and then makes a
possibility; it is easier to sink into everyday surprising leap into the first person plural:
inauthenticity, and simply take ones world he identifies profound boredom as the
and ones identity for granted. defining mood of our time (GA 29/30,
Being and Time formalizes this human 23949/FCM, 1607). In this condition,
predicament by defining Dasein as the entity nothing seems urgent; the question of who
whose own Being is an issue for it (412). we are has not come alive for the commu-
That is, we are always, either deliberately or nity. Heideggers bold step into cultural
by default, taking a stand on our own Being critique anticipates the hazardous commit-
and deciding how to exist. We thus have a ments of the decade to come, when he will
relation to our own Being that other entities often refer to die Not der Notlosigkeit, the
seem to lack. But our relation to ourselves urgency of the lack of urgency (e.g. GA 45,
also affects our relation to all other enti- 183/BQP, 158).
ties: we exist by Being-in-the-world, and we The courses of the next few years evince
encounter other entities within the world, Heideggers desire to address the question of
so the question of how to exist marks our who we are on the basis of a concrete place,
interpretation of entities other than ourselves time, and community rather than in the name
(1213). In short, I care about the Being of all of an abstract humanity or Dasein.
beings in terms of how I care about my own In The Essence of Human Freedom (1930),
Being. What beings signify to me depends on Heidegger argues that the concepts of nega-
who I take myself to be. tive and positive freedom both invite reflec-
One can gain insight into ones own Being, tion on the general question of what it means
and ultimately into Being as such, only by to be (GA 31, 67, 301/EHF, 45, 223). But
lifting oneself out of everyday, anesthetized he does not subordinate the problem of free-
comfort and coming to grips with who one is. dom to the problem of Being: to the contrary,
Heidegger thus says that Dasein is a who, the question of Being itself is a problem of
not a what (45). A general definition of the freedom, not only theoretically but in a con-
human species fails to yield insight into how crete sense, since it requires one to become
any individual is existing; we must ask who essential in the actual willing of [ones] own
the person is, that is, which defining pos- essence (GA 31, 303/EHF, 205).1
sibility he or she is pursuing. Furthermore, The philosophical tradition, in Heideggers
because Dasein is always Being-with, we can view, has failed to engage the problems of free-
infer that the question Who am I? implies dom and Being deeply enough. He attempts
the further question, Who are we?a deci- to reveal what remained un-happened in
sion about the destiny of a people. Every gen- the tradition (GA 34, 322/ET, 228) through
eration must discover its destiny, Heidegger readings of key texts such as the Critique of

40
HEIDEGGER IN THE 1930s

Pure Reason (GA 31/PICPR; GA 41/WIT) find the liberating bond. According to Rector
and Book Theta of Aristotles Metaphysics, Heideggers inaugural address of May 1933,
which establishes the priority of actuality by taking its place in the new order, the uni-
over potentiality (GA 31, 107/EHF, 75; GA versity is performing an act of self-assertion.
33/AM). Heidegger, in contrast, affirms the This kind of self-assertion is not arbitrary
possible over the actual: it is only in terms of license, but positive commitment: labor serv-
possible ways to bewhich are always shad- ice, military service, and knowledge service
owed by the possibility of deaththat we (GA 16, 11314/HR, 11314).
can encounter any actualities (SZ, 262). At this time, Heidegger puts his own
Our own essence must be chosen from thought into the service of dictatorship.
finite possibilities. Accordingly, in his 19301 According to his 19334 seminar on Nature,
reading of the Phenomenology of Spirit, History, and State, the state is the very Being
Heidegger asks: are we, with Hegel, those of the people: in the state, the Volk finds its
who presume to possess absolute knowledge identity and endurance.2 The people natu-
(GA 32, 71/HPS, 501), or are knowledge rally feels eros for the state, just as every
and being not absolute, but finite (GA 32, individual wills to exist. And since the state
55, 145/HPS, 38, 1001)? If being is finite, essentially depends on the soaring will of
Heidegger implies that we must also recog- a born leader, it is ultimately the Fhrer who
nize our finitude by thinking and acting from decides who the German people is.3 The only
a unique historical situation. Accordingly, true alternative, as Heidegger sees it, is confu-
freedom is not the absence of limits, but the sion and collapse. A higher bond, such as
right kind of self-binding (GA 34, 59/ET, 44). a bond to the Volk, creates the highest free-
Even God, Heidegger suggests, must be finite, dom, whereas lack of commitment is nega-
not omnipotent (GA 33, 158/AM, 135). tive freedom. One has sometimes understood
Heideggers account of the history of political freedom in this latter sense, and thus
Western philosophy is deepened through misunderstood it.4
readings such as these and by the beginning The course On the Essence of Truth,
of his intense interest in pre-Socratic thought from the same semester, glorifies the darkest
(GA 35). The common thread in these inter- element of Nazism: glossing Heraclitus on
pretations is the need for a free but situated polemos or war, Heidegger proposes that in
decision that would reorient our own Being order to avoid losing its edge, a people must
and, in this way, establish a fresh relation to findor even fabricateits inner enemies
Being as such. and pursue them ruthlessly, to the point of
elimination (GA 36/37, 91/BAT, 73). One
way to answer the who question, in prac-
tice, is to annihilate those among us who
GERMAN DESTINY AND THE we are not.
POLITICS OF BEING The same course includes a vehement
attack on biological interpretations of
For Heidegger, the triumph of National Nazism. Heidegger insists that human beings
Socialism in 1933 seems to have provided, cannot be understood biologically precisely
for a while, an answer in practice to the ques- because they are a who. Only an entity
tion, Who are we? and the opportunity to whose own Being is at issue for it faces a

41
HEIDEGGER IN THE 1930s

destiny and is capable of freedom and sac- 1935 course Introduction to Metaphysics
rifice (GA 36/37, 21011, 21415/BAT, 161, (see Chapter 24 in this volume). As he puts
1634). it there, human beings struggle to affirm
Heideggers lectures on Logic as the Question their power in the face of the overpower-
Concerning the Essence of Language in 1934 ing violence of Being; in this way they take
unfold as a series of questions, with the who a stand on who they are and what differ-
question at the center (GA 38, 78, 97/LEL, ence it makes that there are beings instead
67, 812). What is logic? Logic is rooted in of nothing (IM, 16076). The Origin of the
language, so we must inquire into humans as Work of Art, also from 1935, presents the
the beings who have language. To be human artwork as the site of a revealing struggle
is to be a self, an entity that is thrown into the between the meaningful world of a people
questions, Who am I? and Who are we? and the opaque earth on which it rests (see
We are a peoplebut what is that? Belonging Chapter 23).
to the people is a matter of decision: we decide This violent imagery gradually fades as
to testify that We are here! and we affirm Heidegger tries to work through the meta-
the will of a state that wills that the people physical dimension of National Socialism
become its own master. Decision brings us by way of Nietzsche (GA 434, GA 468,
into historybut what is history? If history GA 87; see Chapter 5) and Ernst Jnger
is temporal, what is time? We must realize (GA 90). He concludes that Jngers con-
that we ourselves are times temporalizing cept of the worker as a new human type is
(GA 38, 120/LEL, 100). Heidegger concludes only a one-sided Nietzscheanism, and that
by pointing to the world-building power of Nietzsche himself is the last metaphysician
poetic language. (GA 47, 10/NIII,8).
It is to poetry that Heidegger turns in search Nietzsches struggle against traditional
of a deeper understanding of the German metaphysics ended up as a mere inverted
essence. His first lecture course (19345) on Platonism. His thoughts of eternal recur-
Hlderlin, the enigmatic poet who muses on rence and the will to power were the ultimate
Germanys relation to the Greeks and the metaphysical representation of beings as such
departed gods, emphasizes the difficulty of and as a whole, instead of an opening to the
the free use of the national, the challenge question of Being itself. By the late 1930s,
of discovering and even of asking who we Heideggers reflections on the will to power
are, and the enigma of the fatherland (GA as metaphysics will lead him to declare that
39, 4, 49, 2904). The riddle of national Being has nothing to do with either power or
identity calls for an elite who can participate powerlessness (GA 66, 83).5
in the poetic founding of a secret Germany.
Such themes will recur in further courses on
Hlderlin in 1941 and 1942 (GA 52, GA 53/
HHTI; see below, chapter 26). SELFHOOD AND APPROPRIATION
Poetic founding is not necessarily peace-
ful. At the same time as he is discovering These tumultuous thoughts and events begin
Hlderlin, Heidegger embraces the language to crystallize in a series of private texts
of power and conflict in a way that blends begun in 1936 (GA 6572), where Heidegger
politics with ontology. This is evident in the develops a new way of thought that circles

42
HEIDEGGER IN THE 1930s

around Ereignis. Interpretations of these enowning. Ereignis initiates us into self-


texts and of Ereignis itself vary considerably hood, allowing us to belong to a site and
(see also Chapters 25 and 35). For present time where beings can have significance.
purposes we will focus on the most clearly This brings us back to the who ques-
structured text and the first in the series, the tion. According to the Contributions, phi-
Contributions to Philosophy of 19368, pay- losophy necessarily involves a meditation
ing special attention to its treatment of the on the self, but not Cartesian self-certainty;
question, Who are we?6 the Cartesian ego is an underlying, thing-like
According to the Contributions, the first entity whose selfhood is not genuinely at
beginning of Western thought asks: what stake. Furthermore, the who question
are beings? The other beginning will ask, must be asked in the first-person-pluralbut
How does beyng occur essentially? [Wie Heidegger recognizes that the reference or
west das Seyn?] (GA 65, 75, 7/CP2, 60, 8). extension of we is problematic. Who gets to
One could take the old-fashioned spelling ask who are we in the first place? Which
Seyn as indicating the granting of significance ones do we mean in speaking of we? . . . do
and unconcealmenta granting that is more we mean the human being as such? Yet the
fundamental than any general representa- human being is unhistorical only as being
tions of what is. In other words, whereas the historical (GA 65, 48/CP2, 40). Human his-
philosophical tradition has sought principles toricity implies that our identity cannot be
and patterns that characterize all entities, some ahistorical abstraction; it also implies
Heidegger now wants to ask how we are that we are in constant danger of failing to
given any meaning of Being in the first place. exist in an authentically historical way.
The central proposal of the text is that One might affirm that we are the Volk,
beyng essentially occurs as Ereignis, the but Heidegger now insists on the problem-
appropriating event (GA 65, 260/CP2, 205). atic character of this concept: How is the
This proposal is not simply a statement of essence of a people determined? (GA 65, 48/
fact, but a new mode of thinking and existing CP2, 40). He rejects the supposition that we
into which we may shift. The Contributions should simply decide who we are by willfully
are structured around this transitional move- organizing the people; busy activity may or
ment (GA 65, 6/CP2, 7): we must feel the may not indicate genuine selfhood (GA 65,
shock of Beings abandonment and hear 4950/CP2, 401). Thought is essential: in
its echo in the history of the first beginning the absence of any meditation on who we
before making a leap into a new ground- are, we may even fail to be in the proper
ing of the thereled, perhaps, by the few sense at all (GA 65, 51/CP2, 41).
future ones who will follow the trace of It is this complacent self-certainty, devoid of
the Hlderlinian last god. In all this, our genuine selfhood, that Heidegger diagnoses as
own Being is put into question, or thrown the fatal trait of his time. The self-assured sub-
into a state of emergencyand only in this ject willfully plans and manipulates the world,
way can we enter genuine selfhood or the turning itself into the center of all meaning.
domain of what is proper (GA 65, 320/CP2, This (namely, such self-certainty) is the inner-
253). The word Ereignis deliberately echoes most essence of liberalism, which precisely
eigen, ownhence translations such as for that reason can apparently unfold freely
appropriation, appropriating event, or and march on in its unstoppable progress.

43
HEIDEGGER IN THE 1930s

The predominant racial ideology is nothing Heidegger never accepted liberal democ-
but biological liberalism (GA 65, 53/CP2, racy, and he may never have abandoned his
43), and Marxism is an equally thoughtless faith in the inner truth and greatness of
outgrowth of Judeo-Christian egalitarianism Nazism (IM, 213)the movements secret
(GA 65, 54/CP2, 44). Heidegger is coming to potential. However, his reflections on the dif-
see all the established political and religious ficulty of genuine selfhood and the question-
options as forms of bankrupt subjectivism, able character of the Volk did lead him to
whether on the individual, the national, or the reject the form that Nazism actually took. By
international scale. 1939, he is attacking Hitler by name in his
What is the alternative? Selfhood, writes private writings. When the Fhrer declares in
Heidegger, is a realm of occurrences, a a speech that every attitude must be judged
realm in which human beings are appro- by its utility for the whole, Heidegger asks:
priated to themselves only if they them- Why should only utility count? What is util-
selves reach the open time-space wherein an ity? And who is the whole? (GA 66, 122).
appropriation can occur. Our own proper The Nazis had never genuinely allowed them-
Being is grounded in our belonging to the selves to ask the question, Who are we?
truth of Being itself (GA 65, 51/CP2, 42). To In The Age of the World Picture (1938),
find ourselves, then, we have to look beyond Heidegger characterizes modernity as an age
any narrow and self-centered identity and that objectifies beings and represents them
turn to the gift of the meaning of Being, a in terms of willfully affirmed principles. The
gift that can be granted only in a distinctive modern subject blocks off the event that
site or situation: the time-space of the flight might call into question what it means to be
of the gods (GA 65, 52/CP2, 42, transla- and who we ourselves are. Heidegger appar-
tion modified). Absence, departure, denial, ently concluded that actual Nazism was
and longing thus point more genuinely to another form of modern subjectivity (GA 5,
our selfhood than any easily ascertainable, 923/HR, 220).7
present-at-hand characteristics. Here as Texts such as these indicate that Heidegger
elsewhere in the Contributions, Heidegger came to see his own political actions as rash,
points to the instability and problematic and that his thought cannot be reduced to a
character of all meaning: meaning depends rigid ideology. By the late 1930s, the urgency
on a mysterious event that cannot itself be of his questioning has won out over any fixed
understood in terms of the meaning that it answers. Even if we decide that we cannot
grants. Significance hovers over an abyssal forgive him for supporting Hitler, this is a
ground (Ab-grund: for example, GA 65, decision not only about Heidegger but about
379/CP2, 299). ourselvesand in this way it testifies that
Heidegger was at least correct to insist on the
importance of the question: Who are we?8

THE PERSISTENT QUESTION


NOTES AND REFERENCES
We can conclude with a few suggestions on
how we might judge the politics of this cru- 1
Similar claims are found in the 1930 essay On
cial decade. the Essence of Ground, in PA. Heidegger was

44
HEIDEGGER IN THE 1930s

to explore the question of freedom further in Emergency of Being: On Heideggers


his lectures on Schelling: GA 42 (1936) and GA Contributions to Philosophy (Ithaca: Cornell
49 (1941). University Press, 2006), 15680. Readers can
2
ber Wesen und Begriff von Natur, also find relatively accessible presentations of
Geschichte und Staat, in Alfred Denker some of the central ideas of the Contributions
and Holger Zaborowski (eds), Heidegger in GA 45/BQP.
und der Nationalsozialismus I: Dokumente, 7
There are discrepancies between the
Heidegger-Jahrbuch 4 (Freiburg/Munich: Karl 1938 manuscript of this text and its 1950
Alber, 2009), 76. A translation of this text by published version. In particular, the original
Gregory Fried and Richard Polt is forthcoming lacks a passage that describes the human
from Bloomsbury under the title Nature, self-conception as nation or people as a
History, State. type of subjectivity. See Sidonie Kellerer,
3
Ibid., 867. Heideggers Maske: Die Zeit des Weltbildes
4
Ibid., 88. Metamorphose eines Textes, Zeitschrift fr
5
See Fred Dallmayr, Heidegger on Macht and Ideengeschichte 5.2 (Summer 2011), 111.
Machenschaft, Continental Philosophy Review However, passages such as GA 65, 488 indicate
34 (2001), 24767; Richard Polt, Beyond that Heidegger was already critical of the
Struggle and Power: Heideggers Secret communal subject by the late 1930s.
Resistance, Interpretation 35.1 (Fall 2007), 8
For a good introduction to further secondary
1140. literature on this period of Heideggers career,
6
See Franois Raffoul, Rethinking Selfhood: see James Risser (ed.), Heidegger toward
From Enowning, Research in Phenomenology the Turn: Essays on the Work of the 1930s
37.1 (2007), 7594; Richard Polt, The (Albany: SUNY, 1999).

45
5
Heidegger, Nietzsche, National
Socialism: The Place of
Metaphysics in the Political
Debate of the 1930s
Robert Bernasconi

When in 1961 Heidegger presented his lec- students or add some clarificatory remarks
tures on Nietzsche in a two-volume edition in hindsight. Some scholars, such as Charles
running to over 1,100 pages, he insisted on Bambach, believe that in 1961 Heidegger
their centrality for an understanding of his had doctored the lectures to conceal com-
path of thought from 1930 to 1947 (GA 6.1, promising passages, whereas others, such as
xii/NI, xvi). It was an oblique reference to Tracy Colony, find another significance in
the Nazi period and its immediate aftermath, those same passages and argue that when
but what was not understood in 1961 was they impinge on political issues they express,
that in the course of editing the lectures for albeit very discreetly, his rejection of National
publication he had omitted a number of sig- Socialism.1 In any event, to the extent that the
nificant passages. It was only when these lec- secondary literature on Heideggers relation
tures were republished in the Gesamtausgabe to Nietzsche is still shaped by the version of
between 1985 and 1990, using Heideggers the Nietzsche lectures published in 1961, it is
own lecture notes as well as student tran- inadequate to the task of addressing the ques-
scripts, that this became clear. Many readers tion of Heideggers philosophical and political
were slow to recognize the significance of the development. And because the 1961 edition
differences between the lectures as Heidegger is the basis for the only English translations
delivered them and the versions published in of Heideggers writings on Nietzsche, it is
1961 (GA 43; GA 44; GA 47; GA 48; GA especially important to know the problems
50), just as they have been slow to recognize with that edition when passing judgment on
the invaluable assistance given by the recently Heideggers relation to National Socialism.
published notes from Heideggers seminars After the Second World War, Heidegger
in 1937, 19378, and 1944 (GA 46; GA 87). claimed that his lectures and seminars on
A careful comparison reveals that Heidegger Nietzsche from 1936 until 1940 constituted
did much more than simply omit passages in a form of intellectual or spiritual resist-
which he repeated himself for the sake of his ance to National Socialism (GA 16, 402).

47
HEIDEGGER, NIETZSCHE, NATIONAL SOCIALISM

But if there is a problem determining what breeding, and so on.4 Hrtles Nietzsche was
Heidegger meant when in 1935 he referred no doubt an extreme case, but it should not
to the inner truth and greatness of the be forgotten that in 1930 Nietzsche was
movement (GA 40, 208/IM, 213), it is even often seen throughout the world as an advo-
less clear what he was claiming to have cate of breeding programs and other forms
resisted. In order to address that question of eugenics.5 In 1920 Heinrich Rickert, one
we need to begin with the Nazi interpreta- of Heideggers early teachers, explicitly
tion of Nietzsche. Nevertheless, a problem denied that Nietzsche was a philosopher of
immediately presents itself: what is meant by the first rank and proposed that it would be
the Nazi conception of Nietzsche? For those better to consider him an influential biologist
within Nazi Germany who were sympathetic instead.6 Heidegger disagreed in his 19212
to Nietzsche, his name served almost as a sur- lecture course at Freiburg University (GA 61,
rogate for the National Socialist movement 80/PIA, 62), but it was not until the 1930s
itself, but that simply means that there was that the decisive shift in Nietzsches reputa-
no standard Nazi assessment of Nietzsche tion took place.7 Today Karl Jaspers is usu-
any more than there was a uniform under- ally given credit for establishing Nietzsches
standing of National Socialism.2 Ernst Krieck philosophical stature,8 but at that time
was an opponent of Nietzsche and, although Alfred Baeumler was a more influential
Alfred Rosenberg did not reject Nietzsche, he reader of Nietzsche. In 1931 he wrote a book
clearly favored Kant. To be sure, one major on Nietzsche with the intention of proving
reason for these differences was uncertainty that Nietzsche belonged alongside Descartes,
as to how to respond to the fact that the Leibniz, and Kant as a thinker of European
biology of race had undergone a decisive rank.9 When Heidegger put Nietzsche
shift since Nietzsches day. Heidegger had no in dialogue with Descartes, Leibniz, and
such uncertainty, albeit he only expressed his Kant, among others, he would have been
reservations in a manuscript that remained understood as following Baeumlers lead.
unpublished until 2004. Heidegger wrote: Heidegger was presumably thinking about
Race researchers play the part of admir- Baeumler when in 1932 he acknowledged
ers of the teacher of the will to power with- that there were a few German thinkers, albeit
out caring that Nietzsche, precisely at the only a few, who had begun to have a sense
time of his work on The Will to Power in that they were under an obligation to make
18867, wrote in his notebook: Maxim: Nietzsches destiny the fundamental event of
Deal with nobody who participates in the their innermost history (GA 35, 4556).10
fake race-swindle (GA 90, 254).3 This is indeed what Baeumler was attempt-
There was, it seems, an attempt to pro- ing, but his argument for Nietzsches philo-
duce the Nazi interpretation of Nietzsche sophical stature was based in large part on
when Heinrich Hrtles Nietzsche und der a political reading. Indeed in 1934 Baeumler
Nationalsozialismus was published under quoted Nietzsches call for the extinction
the imprint of the NSDAP. Hrtle attrib- of misfits, weaklings, and degenerates and
uted to Nietzsche a materialist biologism argued that he provided the foundation for
but largely limited himself to locating in a new policy that would ground the state
Nietzsches texts passages that reflected on race.11 At the end of this second essay,
Nazi positions on such topics as war, Jews, which was entitled Nietzsche and National

48
HEIDEGGER, NIETZSCHE, NATIONAL SOCIALISM

Socialism, Baeumler proclaimed that if certain way. Heidegger seems to have intended
today we shout Heil Hitler . . . at the same something more than this. Indeed, as Jaspers
time we are also hailing Nietzsche.12 noted in a letter to Heidegger, the Rectoral
Heidegger characterized his own inter- Address had Nietzschean resonances.16 That
pretation of Nietzsche as metaphysical and Heidegger himself read Nietzsche with an eye
dismissed Baeumler for being political (GA to politics is also clearly in evidence in his
6.1, 20/NI, 22). This was in the context of a seminar from the Winter semester 19389,
discussion of Baeumlers decision to ignore largely devoted to tracking the concept of
the doctrine of the eternal recurrence as of life in Nietzsches The Use and Abuse of
no consequence for Nietzsches system.13 History. He also used the opportunity to
Heideggerunlike Baeumler, Jaspers (G 6.1, explore the question of culture in the forma-
1920/NI, 22), and Ernst Bertram (GA 50, tion of German identity. Heideggers claim
99/IPTP, 9)placed the doctrine of eter- that in Nietzsche Volk was a metaphysi-
nal recurrence at the summit of Nietzsches cal concept far distant from Volkskunde was
reflections. And when Heidegger addressed part of his tendency to dismiss Volkskunde
Baeumlers 1931 book directly in 1939 in the as superficial (GA 46, 281). This is another
reworked version of the final lecture of The way in which his metaphysical reading of
Will to Power as Knowledge that was never Nietzsche, understood roughly as a reading
delivered as such, he praised Baeumlers that attended to the ontological status of the
essay for attempting to set the interpreta- concepts employed, bleeds into politics.
tion of Nietzsche free from a psychologiz- Heideggers metaphysical concern was
ing and existential misinterpretation of his uppermost in his treatment of Nietzsches
work, but complained that he had failed to relation to Darwinism and biologism. When
see the metaphysical essence of justice (GA it came to readings of Nietzsche, Heideggers
47, 297).14 Heidegger explained that it is resistance was directed primarily against
only with the insight into the essence of jus- those among the Nazis whom he suspected
tice as the essential ground of life that it can of promoting both the Darwinian struggle
be decided whether, how, and within what for existence and a biologistic conception of
limits Nietzsches thinking is biologistic, race. This was clearly stated in 1944 when
and this formulation was repeated almost Heidegger evoked Nietzsches account of
word for word in the final lecture (GA 6.1, the Germans and described it as reflecting
580/NIII, 145).15 In other words, Baeumler, a world for which Darwinism is the only
contrary to his own claim in Nietzsche, der philosophy with its doctrine of the struggle
Philosoph und Politiker, had failed to iden- for existence and the natural selection and
tify Nietzsches metaphysics, because, even choice of the stronger (GA 50, 120/IPTP, 28).
though he highlighted justice, he read it By this time the proper name Nietzsche had
politically and not metaphysically. become for Heidegger the name for an age:
But if Heidegger wanted his interpretation the epoch of the development and installation
to be understood as metaphysical, as opposed of the mastery of the human over the earth
to political, that would limit the degree to (GA 50, 84/IPTP, 645). However, Heidegger
which one could think of it as resisting had employed a different strategy earlier and
National Socialism as he claimed. It would this raises the question as to whether this ear-
simply amount to a refusal to read Nietzsche a lier approach was equally pointed politically.

49
HEIDEGGER, NIETZSCHE, NATIONAL SOCIALISM

It is clear that already in 1939 Heidegger Socialist racial policies, but things are more
directly challenged the dominant reading complicated. Some Nazis did adhere to biol-
of Nietzsche as a Darwinist. He claimed ogism, but this represented only one way of
that Darwin thought metaphysically-so- being a Nazi, albeit one to which Heidegger
ciologically, whereas Nietzsche thought was resolutely opposed.19 And it was possible
metaphysically-ontologically (GA 47, 91). to support most, if not all, of the Nazis racial
Initially Heideggers argument was that, in policies without accepting the biological the-
contrast to Darwins focus on self-preservation ories that some used in an attempt to justify
in the struggle for existence, Nietzsche them. Heideggers initial claim was that biol-
was concerned with the self-transcending ogism arose when the prevailing views about
enhancement of life (GA 6.1, 439/NIII, living beings are transferred from biology to
15). Heidegger at one time believed that other realms of being, for example, to history
Nietzsche had taken this point from the (GA 6.1, 472/NIII, 45). However, Heidegger
biologist Wilhelm Rolph who had opposed quickly dropped this argument borrowed
the notion of a struggle for the increase of from Rickert,20 choosing instead to issue
life to the Darwinian struggle for life (GA the modified claim that Nietzsche would
87, 193).17 But Heidegger subsequently was only have been guilty of biologism if he had
forced to acknowledge that the two terms adopted certain concepts and key proposi-
preservation and enhancementcould not be tions from biology without realizing that
separated in Nietzsche. The following semes- they already implied certain metaphysical
ter he referred to their necessary intercon- decisions. The proper defense against biolo-
nection (GA 6.2, 91/NIV, 65), and a couple gism was to be conducted in terms not of pro-
of years later, following aphorism 715 from tecting the borders between disciplines but in
The Will to Power, he insisted there should be terms of metaphysics: Biological thinking
no and between them, only a hyphen join- [. . .] can only be grounded and decided in
ing them (GA 6.2, 242/NIII, 196).18 By 1939 the metaphysical realm and can never justify
Heidegger conceded that Nietzsche thought itself scientifically (GA 6.1, 472/NIII, 45).
in a concretely biological way [...] without In a twenty-six page so-called Repetition that
misgivings (GA 6.1, 532/NIII, 101), but he was omitted by Heidegger from the first pub-
argued that Nietzsches apparently biologi- lication of The Will to Power as Knowledge
cal explanation of the categories moves into and as Metaphysics, he emphasized that the
the area of metaphysical thinking (GA 6.1, main thrust of his account was to displace
5356/NIII, 104). The distinction between from the realm of biology to that of meta-
the biological and the metaphysical, like physics (GA 47, 6893, esp. 85). At the time
the distinction between the political and the he clearly believed that this issued a chal-
metaphysical, was proving more fluid than lenge to contemporary readers of Nietzsche.
Heidegger had at first suspected. Indeed, he wrote that the many writers
Heidegger learned the same lesson when who whether consciously or unconsciously
he sought to use the term biologism as a expound and copy Nietzsches treatises
weapon. There has been a longstanding ten- invariably fall prey to a variety of biologism
dency for defenders of Heidegger to want to (GA 6.1, 474/NIII, 46).
believe that biologism was a code word for Nevertheless, Heidegger had earlier
National Socialism and especially National acknowledged a significant exception to

50
HEIDEGGER, NIETZSCHE, NATIONAL SOCIALISM

this account. In 1936 he judged Baeumler associated it specifically with Nietzsche (GA
to be among the few who rejected Klagess 65, 315/CP2, 249). The fact that Heidegger
psychological-biologistic interpretation of was more inclined to associate Nietzsche
Nietzsche (GA 6.1, 20/NI, 21). But whereas unambiguously with biologism in private
Heidegger declared Nietzsche innocent than in his public lectures could be used as an
of biologism, Baeumler in his 1931 study indication that the attempt to critique biolo-
had actually criticized Nietzsche for his gism in the course of a reading of Nietzsche
biologism, which he judged had its roots in was a way of being political, even if the
Darwin.21 According to Heidegger, in 1939, political work was limited to an attack on
biologism was ignorance of the fact that all only one group within the Nazi Party. But it
biology that is genuine and restricted to its was an attack only in the sense that he was
field points beyond itself (GA 6.1, 472/NIII, marking his own distance from biologism. It
45). Heidegger had said the same thing in a did not have a critical edge beyond that. In a
different idiom in 1927 when he maintained manuscript contemporary with the Nietzsche
that in the philosophy of life there was an lectures, Die Geschichte des Seyns, Heidegger
implicit tendency toward understanding conceded that all attempts to refute biolo-
the being of Dasein (SZ, 46). According to gism are worthless (GA 69, 71). By this
Baeumler, by contrast, biologism is the doc- time he no longer understood biologism as
trine that everything, including conscious- an error to be corrected but as something to
ness, can be traced back to life-processes.22 be traced back to its source in the Western
By excluding consciousness from this proc- metaphysical concept of life as developed
ess, he believed that he could avoid extreme especially by Leibniz, Hegel, and Nietzsche.
forms of biologism and so he argued that To relate Nietzsche to Descartes, Leibniz,
life in Nietzsche must be understood not and Kant now meant to circumscribe all of
empirically-physiologically but metaphysi- them together within the unity of Western
cally, that is to say, as a Dionysian or divine metaphysics. This constituted a second sense
phenomenon.23 in which Heidegger used the word meta-
In lectures from the late 1930s, Heidegger physics, one that came to dominate his use
maintained that the critique of biologism did of the term. Metaphysics as the history of
not apply to Nietzsche. He claimed that the Western metaphysics extending from Plato
latter recognized the metaphysical character to Nietzsche was to be overcome. Whereas
of the propositions in which he employed Heidegger had initially looked to National
biological concepts, concepts borrowed, as Socialism to assist in this task, at a certain
Heidegger well knew, from William Rolph, point, the precise date of which is hard to
Herbert Spencer, and Wilhelm Roux (GA determine, he came to see National Socialism
87, 1934. That at least is what Heidegger in its realization as a symptom of Western
said in public. In private, matters were differ- Metaphysics. In other words, he came to see
ent. In Contributions to Philosophy he not it as a symptom of the problem and not a
only complained that the fact that Nietzsche contribution to its solution.
stressed life was a clear indication of the lack There are clear indications of this shift
of originality of his questioning (GA 65, 326/ already in 1939. The governing thesis of
CP2, 258), but he also presented contempo- Heideggers The Will to Power as Knowledge
rary biologism in historical perspective and is not explicitly stated in the lecture course,

51
HEIDEGGER, NIETZSCHE, NATIONAL SOCIALISM

but is announced in a note included only in rather than biological (ibid. Compare GA
an appendix to the Gesamtausgabe version 50, 57). If one understands the two uses in
of the lecture course. The thesis was that this passage of the term metaphysical in
Nietzsche avoided mere biologism only by the positive sense of a thinking of the Being
virtue of the fact that his biologism was a of beings, then it might seem that Heidegger
necessary consequence of a metaphysical was legitimating a thinking in terms of
interpretation of beingness as will to power race, including eugenics or racial hygiene
(GA 47, 321). Metaphysical thinking as the (Rassenhygiene). But although this reading is
thinking of the Being of beings was thus the popular among Heideggers harshest critics,
prescribed way to avoid biologism, but at the it arises from a failure to see that he is speak-
same time, insofar Nietzsche was also meta- ing here of metaphysics as understood from
physical in the sense that his name stood for the history of Being understood as a destiny
the consummation of Western metaphysics (Geschick). Heideggers argument, as he
(GA 6.1, 429/NIII, 6), this was no longer a explained elsewhere, was that eugenics with
thinking to which Heidegger himself aspired. its project of racial breeding and race ranking
Nietzsche did not offer Heidegger a way of had to be seen as a manifestation of Western
resisting National Socialism, although it did metaphysics (GA 69, 701 and 223). Indeed,
offer him an opportunity to be critical of it was an inevitable consequence of Western
all those who sought to plunder Nietzsche metaphysics which is why he refers to it as
merely for the sake of some contemporary metaphysically necessary.
spiritual counterfeit (GA 6.1, 593/NIII, By initially defending Nietzsche against
157). Instead, he used Nietzsche to offer his the charge of biologism only subsequently
diagnosis of why one must look to the his- to locate him within the history of Western
tory of Western metaphysics to understand metaphysics, Heidegger in a double move-
the decline he saw everywhere he looked and ment elevated Nietzsche above his biologistic
not just in Nazi Germany. contemporaries the better to circumscribe him
This background is fundamental to under- more forcefully in another way. Heidegger
standing the much misunderstood passage rescued Nietzsche from a Darwinist read-
from Nietzsches Metaphysics where ing, including Baeumlers appropriation
Heidegger wrote: Only where the absolute of him, but only to associate him with the
subjectivity of will to power comes to be worst Nazi policies at a more fundamental
the truth of beings as a whole is the princi- level. This means that the sense in which
ple of a program of racial breeding possible; Heidegger could claim that his attempt to
possible, that is, not merely on the basis of save Nietzsche from biologism amounted to
naturally evolving races, but in terms of the a form of resistance to National Socialism is
self-conscious thought of race. That is to say, extremely limited. Heidegger offered a pow-
the principle is metaphysically necessary erful diagnosis of the ills of his time, but it left
(GA 6.2, 278/NIII, 231). The next sentence is little or no room for a political response that
missing from the manuscript written in 1940 was capable of combating it. By embracing
and so was presumably added only in 1961: an account of Western metaphysics as des-
Just as Nietzsches thought of will to power tiny Heidegger deprived himself philosophi-
was ontological rather than biological, even cally of a basis for a moral condemnation of
more was his racial thought metaphysical National Socialism.

52
HEIDEGGER, NIETZSCHE, NATIONAL SOCIALISM

NOTES AND REFERENCES a Nietzsche for whom biologism was not


central. Karl Jaspers, Nietzsche. Einfhrung in
1
Charles Bambach, Heideggers Roots, Nietzsche, das Verstndnis seines Philosophierens (Berlin:
National Socialism, and the Greeks (Ithaca: Walter de Gruyter, 1936); trans. by Charles
Cornell University Press, 2003), 26672 and F. Wallraff and Fredrick J. Smith, Nietzsche.
Tracy Colony, Heideggers Early Nietzsche An Introduction to the Understanding of His
Lecture Courses and the Question of Resistance, Philosophical Activity (Tucson: University of
Studia Phaenomenologica, 4 (2004), 15172. Arizona Press, 1965).
See also Tracy Colony, The Death of God and 9
Alfred Baeumler, Nietzsche der Philosoph und
the Life of Being: Heideggers Confrontation Politiker (Leipzig: Philipp Reclam, 1931), 5.
with Nietzsche, Interpreting Heidegger, ed.
10
Another possible candidate was Kurt
Daniel O. Dahlstrom (Cambridge: Cambridge Hildebrandt, a member of Stefan Georges circle.
University Press, 2011), 197216. See Nietzsche als Richter: Sein Schicksal in
2
Steven E. Aschheim, The Nietzsche Legacy in Ernst Gundolf and Kurt Hildebrandt, Nietzsche
Germany 18901990 (Berkeley: University of als Richter unsrer Zeit (Breslau: Ferdinand Hirt,
California Press, 1994), 255. See also Martha 1923), 63104.
Zapata Galindo, Triumph des Willens zur 11
Alfred Baeumler, Nietzsche und der
Macht. Zur Nietzsche-rezeption im NS-Staat Nationalsozialismus, in Studien zur deutschen
(Hamburg: Argument, 1995) and especially the Geistesgeschichte (Berlin: Junker und
list of courses on Nietzsche taught during the Dnnhaupt, 1937), 292.
Nazi period, pages 21018. 12
Baeumler, Nietzsche und der
3
The quotation from Nietzsche can now be Nationalsozialismus, 294.
found in Friedrich Nietzsche, Smtliche Werke. 13
Baeumler, Nietzsche der Philosoph und
Kritische Studienausgabe (Berlin: De Gruyter, Politiker, 80.
1980), vol. 12, 205. 14
Heidegger is referring to Baeumler, Nietzsche
4
Heinrich Hrtle, Nietzsche und der der Philosoph und Politiker, 778.
Nationalsozialismus (Munich: Zentralverlag 15
Heidegger explained in a passage that was
der NSDAP, 1937), 77. excised from the first publication that justice
5
For example, see Dan Stone, Breeding is the how in which the livingness of the living
Superman. Nietzsche, Race and Eugenics in holds itself (GA 47, 303).
Edwardian and Interwar Britain (Liverpool: 16
Karl Jaspers to Martin Heidegger, August 23,
Liverpool University Press, 2002). The French 1933, Briefwechsel 19201963 (Frankfurt:
reading of Nietzsche in this period was more Klostermann, 1990), 155.
antagonistic because of anti-German senti-
17
See W. H. Rolph, Biologische Probleme zugleich
ments. See Douglas Smith, Transvaluations: als Versuch zur Entwicklung einer rationellen
Nietzsche in France 18721972 (Oxford: Ethik (Leipzig: Engelmann, 1884), 97.
Oxford University Press, 1992), 5681. 18
For the original version of this text, see GA
6
Heinrich Rickert, Die Philosophie des Lebens. 50, 18.
Darstellung und Kritik der Philosophischen 19
Further on this topic, see Robert Bernasconi,
Modestromungen unserer Zeit (Tubingen: Heideggers Alleged Challenge to the
J.C.B. Mohr, 1920), 179n. and Heinrich Nazi Concepts of Race, in Appropriating
Rickert, Lebenswerte und Kulturwerte, Heidegger, eds James E. Faulconer and
Logos II.2 (1912), 136. Mark A. Wrathall (Cambridge: Cambridge
7
For a contemporary review of the German University Press, 2000), 5067.
literature on Nietzsche, see Karl Lwith, 20
Heinrich Rickert, Die Philosophie des Lebens.
Nietzsche, Smtliche Schriften 6 (Stuttgart: Darstellung und Kritik der Philosophischen
J.B. Metzler, 1987), 34580; trans. J. Harvey Modestromungen unserer Zeit (Tbingen:
Lomax, Nietzsches Philosophy of the Eternal J.C.B. Mohr, 1920), 75.
Recurrence of the Same (Berkeley: University 21
Baeumler, Nietzsche der Philosoph und
of California Press, 1997), 195225 Politiker, 28.
8
It might be true that Jaspers wrote the first 22
Ibid.
sanitized book on Nietzsche by describing 23
Ibid., 35.

53
6
The Later Heidegger:
The Question of the Other
Beginning of Thinking
Franoise Dastur

A long time before the lecture Heidegger path that had been cleared 2,000 years ago
gave in 1964 on The End of Philosophy by Plato and Aristotle, but on the contrary
and the Task of Thinking, the theme of requires the destruction of the history of
the end of philosophy had already emerged ontology in order to go back to the original
in some of the texts he had published. One experiences (SZ, 22), which are at the basis
of the notes he wrote between 1936 and of the meaning of the being concept that is
1946 that have been published under the still ours. In 1927 the question was never-
title Overcoming metaphysics says that, if theless to renew with the Greek beginning
with Nietzsches metaphysics, philosophy is from which it was necessary to bring back,
accomplished, which means that it has cov- to retrievethis is the proper meaning of the
ered up to the end the circle of its prescribed German word wiederholenwhat could give
possibilities, this end of philosophy is not a new life and future to a tradition that had
the end of thinking, which is going over to become sclerotic. Heideggers purpose was
another beginning (VA, 83). The transi- then to revive philosophy in rooting it again
tion from the Greek beginning to another in its true beginning. But in 1927 the Greek
beginning is Heideggers main concern in the beginning is understood in the light of what
middle of the 1930s, in a time when in his Heidegger will call later its initial end (EM,
manuscripts, and especially in Beitrge zur 137), that is, in the light of the gigantom-
Philosophie, Contributions to Philosophy, achia peri ts ousias, the battle of giants con-
written between 1936 and 1938, the word cerning being (SZ, 1), which defines Platos
Ereignis, which will become a key one for and Aristotles ontological investigation.
the last part of Heideggers work, appears Heidegger, taking up again the Aristotelian
for the first time. Until then, the question discovery of the nongeneric character of
had rather been, instead to begin in another Being was led to the idea of the ontological
manner, to begin again, that is, to repeat the difference, which was explicitly expounded
question of being as a question that is the in his 1927 lecture course on The Basic
leading question of philosophy. Such a rep- Problems of Phenomenology, but which con-
etition does not mean however to follow the stitutes already the implicit horizon of Being

55
THE LATER HEIDEGGER

and Time, where Being is defined as the itself, since existing means nothing else than
transcendens pure and simple (38). On the to perform the ontological difference, as
basis of the definition of ontology as tran- Heidegger explains in The Basic Problems
scendental science (GA 24, 460) Heidegger of Phenomenology (GA 24, 454). Philosophy
could therefore identify, as Kant already did, itself can therefore only be metaphysics get-
metaphysics and human nature in his 1929 ting under way (BW, 110), that is, an explicit
inaugural lecture on What is metaphysics? metaphysics that can be accomplished only
whose conclusion is : So long as man exists, through a leap bringing us outside of what
philosophizing of some sort occurs (BW, Heidegger names Verfallenheit, fallenness.
110). The concept of transcendence is still at For fallenness is what defines a way of exist-
that time the horizon into which metaphys- ing that is completely absorbed by the tasks
ics, according to the current meaning of the of the everyday, on the basis of which we have
expression meta ta physica, is defined as to open ourselves to what constitutes in the
inquiry beyond or over beings, which aims proper manner Dasein, which is Being in the
to recover them as such and as a whole for world as such. This is possible, as Heidegger
our grasp (107). But as a general question- showed in Being and Time and again in What
ing on beings, metaphysics does not think is metaphysics? only through the experience
the ontological difference, at least as long of this no-thing that is a world that takes
as it has not thematized in an explicit man- place in Angst, anxiety. Philosophy seems
ner Being and Nothingness as such, which is therefore to be the expression of authentic
the case of traditional metaphysics. It is only, Dasein, of a Dasein that exists on the modus
as Heidegger emphasizes, when nothingness of epekeina, that is, transcendence (GA 24,
becomes a problem that it awakens for the 425); and at that time it is precisely this
first time the proper formulation of the meta- transcendental essence of philosophy that
physical question concerning the Being of has to be renewed and accomplished, with-
beings (108), because the Being of beings is out questioning the Platonic origin of such a
truly questioned only when it is thought in his project. On the contrary, Heidegger declares
difference with the beings, that is, as what is in The Basic Problems of Phenomenology,
not a being, not a thing or in the literal sense that philosophy, in its cardinal question, has
of the word, as nothing. We have therefore to made no progress since Plato (399400),
deal with two concepts of metaphysics here so that when we ask the apparently abstract
that are opposed in the same manner as tra- question of the condition of possibility of the
ditional ontology and what Heidegger calls comprehension of Being, we want nothing
in Being and Time fundamental ontology, else than searching how to get out of the cave
that is, ontology of Dasein. The condition and find an access to light (404).
of possibility of metaphysics in its proper Heidegger has elaborated under the name
formulationin other words authen- of fundamental ontology this metaphysics
tic metaphysicsas explicit questioning of Dasein on the basis of which philosophy
can be found in human existence insofar as explicit metaphysics is founded. It is there-
as the human being can have a relationship fore not surprising to see him developing the
with beings only on the basis of a prelimi- project of a repetition of Kants foundation
nary openness to nothingness, that is, to the of metaphysics in his 1929 book on Kant.
Being of beings. Metaphysics is thus Dasein Kant is for Heidegger the first thinker after

56
THE LATER HEIDEGGER

Aristotle who has tried to give to traditional possibilities contained in the Greek begin-
metaphysics, to this metaphysica generalis ning (ibid.). Heidegger developed this idea
that is nothing else than Aristotles prote in his 1935 lecture course An Introduction
philosophia, the foundation of which it is to Metaphysics, when differentiating in the
deprived and which alone can make it pos- Greek beginning itself a beginning and an
sible, that is, the ontological difference as end: In order to overcome Greek philoso-
the modus of existence of the human being, phy as the beginning of Western philosophy,
that Heidegger calls transcendence. Kant it is necessary to grasp this beginning at the
has indeed seen the necessary connection same time in its initial end; for it is only this
between the Being-question and the finite end that became for the following times the
ontological constitution of man. But because beginning, a beginning which at the same
Kant remained prisoner of the Cartesian time concealed the initial beginning (EM,
way of thinking, in particular of the modern 137). Hegel has only brought to its end the
determination of man as subject, the question initial end of the great beginning, that is,
is for Heidegger to repeat in a more originary Platos and Aristotles philosophies, which
manner the Kantian foundation of metaphys- are the determination of physis as idea (144),
ics. To give a foundation to metaphysics does and not the thinking of Being as physis of the
not mean however only to add to the already so-called Presocratics. Thus, the possibility
existing metaphysical edifice the basis that is of a more originary repetition of the begin-
missing, but this implies on the contrary to ning is still preserved as our only chance
designing the plan of the future metaphysical to overcome Hegel and to give a future to
edifice.1 Heideggers purpose is consequently philosophy.2 But beginning anew in a more
to determine in a concrete manner the essence originary manner the beginning and not con-
of the metaphysics to come: this is the full sidering it as a thing of the past that it would
meaning of fundamental ontology, which be sufficient to imitate, this already means
aims at elaborating a new metaphysics. to transform it in another beginning (29).
It seems therefore that with the project of It is in fact not possible to limit oneself to
a repetition of the Being-question, a project the perpetuation of a beginning, because the
that guided Heideggers thought until 1929, beginning, by essence, and not only because
we are very far from the theme of the end of the incapacity of those who are watching
of philosophy. However this theme is not over it, can only decline and collapse, with-
completely absent during the 1920s, inso- out being ever able to conserve by itself the
far as Heidegger, in a very insistent manner, immediacy of its upheaval. It can be con-
situates his own philosophical project in con- served only if it is repeated in a more origi-
nection with Hegels philosophical accom- nary manner (1456). Heidegger develops
plishment. He writes in The Basic Problems this reflection on the notion of beginning,
of Phenomenology: With Hegel, philoso- which has to be put in connection with what
phy, i.e. antic philosophy, is in a way thought he called his political mistake in the same
to its end. Hegel was completely right when period, in the first version, written also in
he formulated this awareness of an accom- 1935, of The Origin of the Work of Art.
plishment (GA 24, 400). But if after Hegel a It is even possible to think that what charac-
new beginning is not only possible but neces- terizes the Greek beginning can reveal itself
sary, it is because he has not used up all the in a more essential manner in art, in Greek

57
THE LATER HEIDEGGER

tragedy and architecture, than in Heraclitus why repetition did not mean for Heidegger
and Parmenides thought, which are also, in in 1927 to become Aristotelian again, and
this same period, explicitly questioned. In did not mean so either ten years later, as
fact the Presocratics have never been absent Heidegger himself later underlined, to phi-
from Heideggers horizon of thought, and it losophize only in a Presocratic manner and
has to be recalled that one part of his very declare that all the rest is misunderstanding
first lecture course was dedicated in 191516 and decline (WhD, 175). The question is
to the Presocratics, and more particularly to rather to master the beginning of Western
Parmenides. His last seminar, in 1973, ends philosophy, which means to understand how
up in the same manner with a meditation on initial beginning and initial end are related
eon emmenai, Parmenides tautology. But if to each other in it. The question is precisely
the Presocratics are summoned to come in to situate Plato in regard to the thinkers of
the foreground after 1935 and if from now physis. This is the reason why Heidegger
on Platonism has to be situated in relation was led to speak of a mutation (Wandel)
to their thoughts, it is perhaps because what of the essence of truth in Platos Theory of
has been preserved in Heraclitus saying Trutha text published in 1942, but which
physis krypthestai philei and in Parmenides was already the subject of two lectures in
notion of aletheia reveals itself at first and 1930and, in a less explicit manner, in
in a privileged manner in the work of art. his 1935 lecture course An Introduction to
Hlderlin, to whom Heidegger dedicated a Metaphysics. If the word physis belongs to
first lecture course in 19345, was the one the same root as phs, light, according to the
from whom he learnt that tragedy is a way etymology invoked by Heidegger more than
in which truth occurs and the sacred opens once, for example, in his 1935 lecture course
itself. For the work of art gives a testimony and in the first version of The Origin of the
of what is really a beginning: a happening of Work of Art,3 the Platonic determination of
truth (BW, 162), which, because it lets appear being as idea, a word meaning look, aspect,
the antagonism of world and earth, of what becomes comprehensible. As Heidegger
opens itself and of what is secluded in itself, points out, the interpretation of Being as
can subsist only as a conflict maintained in a idea proceeds with an inescapable neces-
work. Heidegger declares however that the sity from the fact that Being has been experi-
work of art as the truth of being setting itself enced as physis, as the reign of what unfolds
in work is only one of the ways for truth to itself, as appearing, as what stands in light
happen: another way is questioning and say- (EM, 1389). The idea is not the appearing
ing (1867). But we can wonder whether this as such, but only the appearing insofar as it is
work of language that is thought possesses related to a look, so that it can remain stable
as much initiating power as this work of lan- and be understood as constant presence, that
guage that is poetry (EM, 146), especially in is, as ousia. The famous mutation of truth
regard to its capacity of grounding history that Heidegger attributes to Plato comes
(BW, 202). from the preeminence given to idea and idein
A beginning, because it happens suddenly, over physis and consists in submitting Being
can be maintained only if it is repeated, to noein, that is, to thinking and perception.
that is, begun anew. And beginning anew is Ideas, which are grasped by a non-sensible
always beginning in another manner. This is look, constitute the noetos topos, the domain

58
THE LATER HEIDEGGER

of the supersensible, into which the supreme of beings, not the truth of Being itself. But
idea, the idea tou agathou, the idea of the the expression truth of Being should not be
Good, is considered as the cause of all that misunderstood. It does not mean that Being
exists and therefore called to theion, the is true, but that Being is in itself truth in the
divine. Metaphysics that sees in the idea sense of altheia. In this 1949 Introduction,
the onts on, the true being, that is situated Heidegger, in opposition to what he said
beyond physis, which itself is reduced to the in Platos Theory of Truth, includes in the
level of a me on, a nonbeing, is essentially, in metaphysical epoch the Presocratics think-
the form of Platonism, an ideo-logy, a science ers themselves: The truth of Being remains
of the ideas and no longer a physio-logy, a concealed to metaphysics in the course of its
science of physis. As Heidegger points out: history from Anaximander to Nietzsche.7
Since being has been interpreted as idea, the All tentative of a rebirth of the Presocratic
thinking of the Being of beings is metaphys- thought is therefore definitively discredited,
ics, and metaphysics is theological.4 as Heidegger suggested already in Being
It is on the basis of this new definition of and Time when he declared that the phe-
metaphysics that the theme of the overcom- nomenon of world was passed over at the
ing of metaphysics can be developed, directly beginning of the ontological tradition deci-
taken up from Nietzsche and his project of sive for us, explicitly in Parmenides (SZ,
the reversal of Platonism that Heidegger 100). What remains to be understood is the
analyzed in the first lecture course he dedi- fact that the Presocratics did think only the
cated to Nietzsche in 19367 (N1, 231 f). truth of beings and not the truth of Being,
Metaphysics does not know that the clarity the altheia itself, in spite of the fact that
of the ideas comes from the light of Being. they named it. To experience aletheia and
This does not mean however that metaphys- to remain under its influence is not equiva-
ics, which has legitimately been named met- lent to mastering it by thinking. Aletheia is
aphysics of light insofar as the metaphor of for the Presocratics beyond all questions.
light is at the center of its self-interpretation, That the beginning cannot be mastered by
is totally blind to light, but it experiences thinking and opens the way to its possible
light only under the form of the lighting into future renewal belongs to the very essence of
which the enlightened beings stand, so that beginning. This is what Heidegger explained
the question it asks is only directed toward in 1933 in his Rectoral address that should
the state of clarity and the permanent source not be considered in this respect only as
of light and never toward the event of light having been required by the circumstances:
itself. This explains why Heidegger declares in The beginning is still. It does not lie behind
the Introduction he added in 1949 to What us as something long past, but it stands in
is metaphysics?: Wherever metaphysics front of us. The beginning has, as the greatest
represents beings, Being has (already) lit up.5 moment, in advance already passed over all
Metaphysics thinks only the being-lighted of that is coming and hence over us as well. The
beings, but not the lighting-process of Being beginning has fallen into our future, it stands
from which the clarity that illuminates being there as the distant decree that requires of us
proceeds: Being is not thought in its reveal- to recapture its greatness.8
ing coming-to-presence, i.e. in its truth.6
Metaphysics thinks therefore only the truth ***

59
THE LATER HEIDEGGER

To recapture the greatness of the begin- that Heidegger wrote with no intention of
ning, this can be accomplished only through immediate publishing, where he deals with
the transition to another beginning, which the transition from the first to the other begin-
opens itself as soon as the truth of Being ning, that is, from philosophy to thought,
is thought. This is clearly said in 19368 but still considers that he is thus contribut-
in Contributions to Philosophy dedicated ing to philosophy. At that time, philosophy
to the thinking of this transition. Here the is considered as including in itself a double
ambiguous status of the ontological differ- questioning: the question of the beingness of
ence becomes manifest, because, being linked beings, which refers to philosophy as it has
to a questioning dealing with the beings and existed up to now, and the question of the
beingness, it can be elaborated only through truth of Being, which refers to the philoso-
a going beyond of beings toward their Being. phy to come. This duality in the essence of
The question is now, as Heidegger declares, philosophy is linked to the difference of two
no to go beyond beings (transcendence), kinds of questioning: first of all, the ques-
but rather to leap over (berspringen) this tion of the relationship between being and
difference and question in a more initial thinking that characterizes the entire history
manner starting from Being and truth (GA of Western philosophy into which the lead-
65, 132, 250). Heidegger writes Seyn now ing thread of the Being-question is noein and
with a y, to indicate through this old spelling, legein, which implies the inevitable domi-
that the word Being now means truth and nation of logic upon ontology and its final
no longer the Being of beings, that is, their triumph in Hegels Science of Logic; and
ground. The ontological difference reveals secondly, the question of the relationship of
itself as at the same time necessary and fatal: Being and time, where time is, as Heidegger
necessary, as a first step in elucidating the stresses, the first indication of the truth of
Being-question and as springboard for the Being (GA 65, 91, 183). Here we have a
leap into the Ereignis; but fatal, because it good example of Heideggers retrospective
can succeed in helping us to get out of being- view on his own work that is the basis of
ness (this was the virtue of Aristotles nonge- his self-interpretation, a self-interpretation
neric concept of Being) only to immediately that was a way of presenting his thinking as
immerse us again into it, since in the onto- a path including different landmarks, as
logical difference Being is thought of only in shown in the title Wegmarken he choose in
relationship to beings. As such, the ontologi- 1967 for a collection of the most important
cal difference is the structure of the domain among the short texts he published between
of Western metaphysics that names Being 1929 and 1964. It seems that in Beitrge zur
but means the beings as beings, so that all Philosophie, Heidegger considers in a some-
what it says moves in a strange manner right what paradoxical manner that the other
from the start and until the end in a perma- beginning is the other beginning of philoso-
nent confusion between beings and Being.9 phy. However the other beginning has no
We can however wonder if in this transi- longer to do with philosophya word that
tion leading to this other beginning that is the is for Heidegger synonymous with meta-
truth of Being, we have not already gone out physicsand it is also no longer Greek, as
of philosophy. Here also, ambiguity remains, Heidegger explained some years later, when
as shown in the title of this big manuscript he began to see in Ereignis the unthought

60
THE LATER HEIDEGGER

element of the Greek thought, unthought whose subtitle is Vom Ereignis, the word
meaning not that which Greek thinking left is clearly understood on the basis of its incor-
aside, but what it preserved in itself as a gift rect popular etymology by which it is related
to future thinkers (WhD, 72). He said in 1954 to the verb eignen, meaning to make proper,
in his dialogue with Professor Tetzuka from to appropriate. But in later texts, Heidegger
Tokyo University that our thinking today recalled that its true etymology stems from
is charged with the task to think what the the word Auge, eye, so that er-ugen, which
Greek have thought in an even more Greek is the older form of ereignen, meant to catch
manner, adding that to enter into think- sight of, to see.12 It is in fact the combina-
ing this unthought element means: to pursue tion of these three meanings (event, appro-
more originally what the Greek have thought, priation, and sight) that renders this term
to see it in the source of its essence. To see it properly untranslatable. It means therefore
so is in its own way Greek, and yet in respect in Heideggers view the singular event that
to what it sees it is no longer, is never again allows the reciprocal propriation of Being
Greek (OWL, 39, tr. modified). In an even and man by making visible. As such, as he
more categorical manner, Heidegger declared explains in Identity and Difference, it names
in the last seminar he gave in Le Thor in the belonging together of Being and man.
France in 1969 But this belonging together is based on a self
de-propriation, Ent-eignis, of Ereignis itself,
Thinking Ereignis with the concepts of which comes from the fact that Ereignis can-
being and the history of being will not be not reveal itself completely as such and, as
successful; nor will it be with the assist- Heidegger explains, withdraws itself to the
ance of the Greek (which is precisely unlimited de-concealment (ZSD, 23). This is
something to go beyond). With being, precisely this concealed belonging together of
the ontological difference also vanishes. Being and man that the Greeks did not think,
Looking ahead, one would likewise
because for them Being had the meaning of
have to view the continual references
something subsistent, vorhanden, which
to the ontological difference from 1927
to 1936 as a necessary impasse or blind has no intrinsic relationship with the human
alley. With Ereignis, it is no longer an being.
issue of Greek thought at all. (FS, 601) But if the theme of the end of philosophy
could appear in the foreground in the last
The question arises here: how should we decades of Heideggers path of thinking,
understand what Heidegger names Ereignis, it was because metaphysics had been itself
if it is that which constitutes the unthought understood as the history of being, so that
element of Greek thought? Heidegger him- all tentative attempts to overcome it could
self declared in Identity and Difference that begin to appear as bound to fail. Such ten-
this word is as little translatable as the lead- tative attempts can lead nowhere, either in
ing Greek word logos and the Chinese word the Kantian form of the project of a meta
Tao.10 He also insisted on the fact that this physics of metaphysics (a project that
word should not be understood in the ordi- Heidegger tried in 1929 to take up again) or
nary sense of event, as it were an event in the form of the Nietzschean reversal of
among others, but that it is a singulare Platonism, which for Heidegger is only the
tantum.11 In Contributions to Philosophy, proof that thinking is definitively entangled

61
THE LATER HEIDEGGER

into metaphysics (VA, 79). In the fragments thought is not the difference between beings
collected under the title Overcoming of and being, but their double fold, Zwiefalt,
metaphysics, which are fragments from that at the same time holds them together
different manuscripts (including Beitrge) and separates them (ibid.). The ontological
written between 1936 and 1946, Heidegger difference was identified with the transcend-
immediately made clear that the expression ence of Dasein, it was then considered as a
berwindung der Metaphysik was used power of differentiation belonging to Dasein,
only as an expedient, because it does not whereas now it is Being that preserves in
allow to experience the ground of the history itself the difference of Being and beings, the
of Being, which is Ereignis (71). If metaphys- difference being sent to the human being by
ics does not think the truth of Being, it is not Being itself and no longer unfolded by him.
an omission or a mistake, and the forgotten- In Contributions to Philosophy, Heidegger
ness of Being that characterizes it is not in names this reversal die Kehre des Ereignisses
itself something negative, this forgottenness (GA 65, 255). Such a reversal inverts the
is on the contrary what is sent to us by Being, direction of the differentiating process: the
which, as the source of beings that are not human being is now the accomplishment of
itself a being of higher rank, has to stay in the differentiating process and no longer the
concealment for the sake of the unconceal- one that accomplishes it, because if it were
ment of beings.13 The question is neither the case, it could make us believe that this
therefore to suppress metaphysics and to accomplishment is his decision and the work
expel it from the horizon of culture nor to of a transcendental subject. Now the facticity
get rid of it as if it were a mere opinion,14 but and thrownness of the differentiation process
to recover from it, in what Heidegger calls no is no longer referred to Dasein, but to Being
longer Uberwindung, but Verwindung, itself; and as Heidegger says in the Letter on
a word that implies that metaphysics has Humanism, Being is illuminated for man in
been assimilated and is no longer something the ecstatic projection (Entwurf). But this
that can govern the movement of thinking. projection does not create Being. Moreover,
However, such a recovery does not depend the projection is essentially a thrown projec-
upon our decision, but, like the forgotten- tion. What throws in projection is not man,
ness of being, it is a sending, a destiny, which but Being itself, which sends man into the
allows us to experience forgottennness as ek-sistence of Dasein that is his essence
such. Such an experience can only be the (BW, 241). Dasein is therefore gebraucht,
experience of the identity of Lichtung und employed by the differentiation process
Verbergung, of clearing and concealing and stays in its service. But in order to make
Heidegger says precisely in The Origin of possible the thinking of the Zwiefalt, in order
the Work of Art that the clearing in which to let appear the double fold of being and the
beings stand is at the same time concealment beings, necessary for difference to properly
(BW, 178). In the experience of forgottenness happen, what is needed is the event of dif-
as forgottenness, the truth of being appears ference. This is precisely what takes place at
as that which has been concealed up to now, the end of metaphysics, in the last stadium
so that the forgottenness of Being can be of the accomplished metaphysics, when the
accepted and includedverwundenin forgottenness of Beings reaches its culmina-
Ereignis (VA, 79). What has now to be tion and when at the same time the decline of

62
THE LATER HEIDEGGER

beings begins, the becoming manifest of the presence, which have to be thought as hap-
beings having lost its exclusiveness. pening in a free succession and not, as
Hegel wanted, in a logical and dialectical
*** order. But this does not mean that they are
the results of the arbitrary views of each phi-
What does Heidegger mean under the expres- losopher, because, as Heidegger stressed in
sion the end of philosophy? We should his 1955 lecture What is philosophy? phi-
first of all leave aside the negative representa- losophers are only responding each time to
tions of the end as interruption or decadence. the claim of a new form of presence.15 But
It means rather accomplishment, comple- if the philosophies do not proceed in a dia-
tion, fulfillment of an assignment to which lectical order from each other, if no necessity
philosophy responds since the beginning of governs their development, in which sense is
its history and which requires that it thinks it possible to think of completion and fix a
the ground of beings, that is, the presence of limit to such a free succession? What could
what is present. Metaphysical or philosophi- allow us to see, after the determination of
cal thinking (this is the same in Heideggers presence as idea and ousia in Greek thought
view) is, as Heidegger says in his 1964 lec- and as objectivity in modern times, in its
ture on The End of Philosophy and the Task determination as Bestellbarkeit, as order-
of Thinking, a thinking that starting from ability, the ultimate phase of the history of
what is present, represents it in its presence philosophy? Is it not possible to imagine that
and thus exhibits it grounded by its ground future mutations of presence could appear
(432). The use of the terms representing after the one that is now? Heidegger explains
(Vorstellen) and exhibiting (darstellen) does that the mutation of presence that charac-
not mean that the metaphysics in question terizes our time determines the presence of
here is only the modern metaphysics of sub- what is present no longer on the basis of the
jectivity. Representation and exhibition are face to face of subject and object, but as a
not referred here to the activity of a subject, mere standing-reserve orderable by what
but to thinking itself when it is taken as the is no longer a subject, that is, by the indus-
leading thread of the interpretation of Being. trial society in its entirety, since it is itself
This is exactly what happened with Plato subjected to the challenging power of what
who gave the primacy to idein and noein, to Heidegger calls Ge-stell, the gathering of all
seeing and perceiving, and this is the reason modes of stellen, of framing and setting in
why in the period of its completion, philoso- order, which concentrates man upon order-
phy defines itself as die Wissenschaft, the ing the actual as standing-reserve (BW,
Science with Fichte and Hegel, ontology 324). But in spite of the special character of
having been thus completely dissolved into this mutation of presence, how can we be
logic. But if Platos thought determines the sure that this becoming-world of philoso-
entire history of philosophy, if indeed meta- phy that is for Heidegger modern technology
physics is Platonism, it takes various forms is really the ultimate form of philosophy?
corresponding to various waysof experienc- Is there really in this period something that
ing and interpreting the presence of what is goes beyond the limits of a thinking of pres-
present. For Heidegger, the history of phi- ence and ground? To such a legitimate ques-
losophy is the history of the mutations of tion, Heidegger answers that an insight into

63
THE LATER HEIDEGGER

what is today can perceive that the think- cannot understand such a simultaneity that
ing of ground does no longer govern modern constitutes the very structure of aletheia. For
science, which as operative mode of think- that it is necessary to see in lethe, the heart
ing, makes use of the old categories of cause of aletheia and not its opposite. It is not suf-
and ground in a pure instrumental manner. ficient either to bring to language their oppo-
Because the domination of operative think- sition as a contra-diction, ein Widerspruch,
ing is extended to the entire domain of the but it is necessary to see the conflict, die
beings and therefore also concerns man him- Widerstreit, into which clearing does not
self, who is thus employed (gebraucht) by appear only as the clearing of presence, but
Gestell, the relationship of the human being as the clearing of a presence that conceals
to presence takes a form in which presence itself (ZSD, 79).
as such becomes questionable. Philosophical This is the reason why Heidegger insists on
thinking does not question presence as such, the necessity of understanding the Lichtung,
but only what is present in its relation to the lighting-process or clearing, no longer
presence considered as its ground. The end out of the idea of light and brightness but
of philosophy is consequently double-faced, rather out of the idea of lightness, which is
as is also Gestell: it means on one side the the meaning of the German word lichten that
completion of the thinking of ground and corresponds to the adjective leicht meaning
presence, in the form of the thinking of light as opposed to heavy. As Heidegger
orderability, and on the other side, the task of explains in The End of Philosophy and the
questioning presence in the light of the think- Task of Thinking, to lighten something
ing of orderability. means to make it light, free and open and
But cannot such a questioning of presence the space thus originating is the clearing,
be already found in Greek thought? Plato so that light can stream into the clearing,
himself, when he defined the presence of into its openness, and let brightness play
what is present as idea, referred it at the same with darkness in it, but light never creates
time to light as what alone allows us to see. Is the clearing, rather it presupposes it (BW,
not Greek thinking characterized by the fact 441). But this openness (Offene) to which
that it thinks presence in relation to light, Heidegger gives the old name of Gegnet,
so that it can see in a being a phainomenon, country (in the literal meaning of what is
that is, something that appears in light and encountered),17 should not be identified
shines? It is only, as Heidegger explains in his with space alone. It should rather be put in
Letter in Humanism, in Roman thinking that relationship with what Heidegger called in
the emphasis was put unilaterally on see- Beitrge Zeitraum, time-space (GA 65,
ing, and no longer on appearing as such, so 238, 371 f.), which constitutes a more origi-
that the way was henceforth cleared for the nally mutual belonging of space and time
modern transposition of idea into perceptio. than their metaphysical juxtaposition. The
Plato however sees in light only the link, the openness of time-space, the clearing, is noth-
zugon, the yoke between seeing and what is ing else, as Heidegger said in his Letter on
to see,16 without thinking the event of light, Humanism (BW, 230), than the world itself
which happens as the simultaneity of clear- that cannot be understood on the basis of
ing and concealment. The metaphor of space, but is on the contrary that what is ein-
light, because it opposes light to darkness, rumend, that what gives space (BT, 24).

64
THE LATER HEIDEGGER

Thus with the thinking of Lichtung as clear- Heidegger suggested in his last 1973 semi-
ing and no longer of the Lichtung as light, we nar? (FS, 82). But what can we say about
have already left behind philosophy, because the inapparent? Heidegger already asked
as Heidegger says, philosophy does speak the question in Contributions to Philosophy
about the light of reason, but does not heed when he observed: We can never say Being
the clearing of Being (BW, 443). (Ereignis) immediately, and therefore also
This new definition of Lichtung makes never say it mediately in the sense of an
possible to measure the distance covered enhanced logic of dialectic. Every saying
since 1927. In opposition to Ereignis, which already speaks from within the truth of Being
appears as a key-word in Heideggers writings and can never immediately leap over Being
only in the mid-1930s, the word Lichtung is itself (GA 65, 38).
already a key-word in Being and Time, where This is the reason why he was favoring a
we can read in 28 that this being that is logic of silence, a sigetic (GA 65, 37) that
Dasein is itself the Lichtung (SZ, 133), in does not exclude, but on the contrary includes
the sense that it is in itself lighted, and not the logic of beingness and substance, which is
by another being, as it is said in the ontically always a predicative and foundative logic. For
figurative expression lumen naturale. It is what has to be done is not to remain silent,
therefore still in relation to the light of rea- but to give access to silence in language itself.
son that the disclosure of Dasein is defined in This is exactly what happens in the famous
1927. Going from the lighting that is Dasein tautologies or self predicative sentences such
for himself to the clearing that is Being itself as die Sprache ist die Sprache19 or Die Zeit
requires the leap in Ereignis that is ther- zeitigt, Der Raum rumt.20
malized in Contributions to Philosophy. This Heidegger often says that the thinking that
is what is acknowledged by Heidegger in one is no longer metaphysical is inferior in a way
of his last public lectures, in October 1965, to philosophy, precisely because it does not
where he declares: The analytic of Dasein raise itself to the level of a foundative way
does not reach to what is properly clearing of thinking. To the dream of an absolute
and absolutely not to the domain to which thinking, of this noesis noesos, the thinking
clearing for its part belongs.18 What is thus of thinking, that Hegel thought accessible for
implicitly acknowledged is the fact that the human being, Heidegger opposes the fini-
Heideggers path of thinking goes from tude of a thinking that is not self-centered,
what is in question in philosophy to what is and which in the poverty of its provisional
in question in thinking. essence (BW, 256) lets that before which it
Philosophy is therefore a question of light is led show itself (FS, 82). But there should
and seeing, as it has become manifest in its be no misunderstanding about the fundamen-
end, with Hegels speculative thinking and tally provisional character of the thinking
Husserls thought of the originary giving that is no longer philosophy. Vorlafigkeit,
intuition. Is there another mode of think- the provisional or preparatory character of
ing that could be neither immediate seeing thinking, as Heidegger stresses in the Letter
nor reflective mediation? A thinking that, on Humanism, is the essence of thinking,
going beyond Greek experienceber das that which constitutes thinking as such and
Griechiche hinaus (BW, 448)would be of which philosophy has remained unaware,
a phenomenology of the inapparent, as in spite of the fact that it acknowledged it in

65
THE LATER HEIDEGGER

its own way, since it forgets Being, remain- 6


Ibid.
ing thus in a negative way faithful to the
7
Ibid., 199.
8
M. Heidegger, Die Selbstbehauptung der
event of Being, which can give itself only by
deutschen Universitt, Reden und andere
concealing itself. Zeugnisse eines Lebensweges, GA 16, 110.
9
Heidegger, Wegmarken, 199.
10
M. Heidegger, Identitt und Differenz
(Pfullingen: Neske, 1957), 29.
NOTES AND REFERENCES 11
Ibid.
12
Ibid., 28. See also M. Heidegger, Unterwegs
1
M. Heidegger, Kant und das Problem der zur Sprache (Pfullingen: Neske, 1959), 260.
Metaphysik (Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann, 13
Heidegger, Wegmarken, 199.
1973), 2 14
Ibid., 72.
2
GA 24, 254: The overcoming of Hegel is the 15
M. Heidegger, Was ist dasdie Philosophie?
intrinsically necessary step in the development (Pfullingen: Neske, 1956), 29 and 31.
of Western philosophy which has to be accom- 16
Plato, Politeia, 508 a
plished if Western philosophy ought to stay 17
M. Heidegger, Gelassenheit (Pfullingen: Neske,
alive. 1979), 31.
3
EM, 54; GA 5, 28. 18
M. Heidegger, Zur Frage nach der Bestimmung
4
M. Heidegger, Platons Lehre von der der Sache des Denkens (St Gallen: Erker,
Wahrheit, in Wegmarken (Frankfurt am Main: 1984), 19.
Klostermann, 1967), 141. 19
Heidegger, Unterwegs zur Sprache, 15.
5
Heidegger, Wegmarken, 196. 20
Ibid., 213.

66
7
HEIDEGGERS CORRESPONDENCE
Alfred Denker

Martin Heidegger is probably the last of the Jean-Paul Sartre, and Ernst Tugendhat),
great letter writers in the history of philoso- scholars of the humanities (e.g. Kurt Bauch,
phy. He wrote an estimated 10,000 letters in Beda Allemann, and Emil Staiger), scientists
his life. If we add to this the sheer mass of (Werner Heisenberg and Carl-Friedrich von
his publications and other writingsthe col- Weizscker), psychiatrists (Medard Boss and
lected edition of his writings (Gesamtausgabe) Ludwig Binswanger) theologians (Conrad
contains approximately 100 volumesit is Grber, Karl Rahner, and Johannes Baptist
hard to imagine how he found time to do Lotz), authors and poets (Ren Char, Paul
other things than write. During his lifetime a Celan, and Ernst und Friedrich-Georg Jnger
number of interesting letters were published. to name a few), and artists (for instance
In this chapter I will present an overview Eduardao Chillida, Bernhard Heiliger,
of his correspondence. In the first section I Georges Braque, Otto Dix, and Hans Kock).
will discuss his letters in general. The second Many of Heideggers correspondences and
section is dedicated to the letters that were letters are voluminous. His largest corre-
published during his lifetime with his per- spondence with his wife Elfride contains over
mission and correspondences that have been 1,100 letters and we have to bear in mind that
published since his death. In the third sec- several hundred letters have been destroyed.
tion we will take a closer look at the planned The longest letter has over 50 manuscript
publication of almost all his letters in the pages. Heideggers letters are first and fore-
Martin-Heidegger-Briefausgabe. most important because of their biographical
and philosophical content. Heidegger often
presents and clarifies his thought in his let-
ters. Repeatedly he gives a far more detailed
Martin Heideggers account of his thought than elsewhere.
correspondence in general He is also very critical of himself and his
work. And of course the letters always show
Martin Heidegger corresponded with many glimpses of the background or context of his
important philosophers (among others thought that cannot be found anywhere else.
Heinrich Rickert, Edmund Husserl, Karl Without exaggerating we can claim that his
Jaspers, Karl Lwith, Hans-Georg Gadamer, letters are an important addition to his work
Hannah Arendt, Hans Jonas, Max Scheler, and lecture courses. We could describe his

67
HEIDEGGERS CORRESPONDENCE

correspondence as a work in its own right famous letter of them all is without doubt
alongside the Gesamtausgabe. his letter to Jean Beaufret that was written
The importance of his letters has been doc- in late 1946 and published in 1947 under the
umented by the few published correspond- title Brief ber den Humanismus [Letter on
ences. They are unique and irreplaceable Humanism] in a small volume that also con-
sources for any biographical, historical, or tained his Platons Lehre von der Wahrheit
philosophical interpretation of Heideggers [Platos Doctrine of Truth].1 Heideggers
life and work. Heideggers correspondence letter was an answer to a letter Beaufret had
with Karl Jaspers is for instance not only written to him on November 10, 1946.2 In
of great help in understanding Heideggers this letter Heidegger looked back on his path
relation to the university and his ideas of a of thought from Being and Time until 1946
reform of the Humboldt-University but also and positioned himself in the philosophical
of incomparable value for an understanding debate of the time. It is to a certain extent also
of the genesis of his main work Being and an answer to the famous essay by Jean-Paul
Time. His correspondence with Karl Lwith Sartre, Lexistentialisme est un humanisme
that will be published in 2013 is of similar that was published earlier in Paris in 1946.
importance. Heideggers correspondence Another important letter is Heideggers
with Hannah Arendt, Elisabeth Blochmann, letter to William J. Richardson, SJ, that
and his wife are of great value for biographi- was published as a preface in his magnus
cal and philosophical research. In these cor- opus: Heidegger. Through phenomenol-
respondences Heidegger shows himself in ogy to thought.3 Heideggers comments on
his role as philosophical mentor who not Richardsons interpretation of his thought
only clarifies his thought but also explains offers some valuable insights in the problem
his thought in its philosophical context and of the turning on his pathway of thought.
against the historical background. The letters This is not the place to take a closer
also contain numerous accounts of his trav- look at the contents of these letters. Instead
els and contacts for which we have no other I will provide the readers with a complete
sources. For the time immediately after the list of the letters that were published with
end of Second World War Heideggers cor- Heideggers permission during his lifetime. It
respondence with Max Mller is of utmost may be of interest to note that the last letter
importance. It offers many insights into the of this list is the last thing Heidegger wrote
Denazification-process, university politics, in his life.
and Heideggers role. Letter to Max Kommerell, published in:
Max Kommerell. Briefe und Aufzeichnungen
19191944. Freiburg 1967, 4045.
To a verse of Mrike. A correspondence
The letters published by with Martin Heidegger from Emil Staiger.
Heidegger and correspondences In: Trivium 9, Zrich 1954; reprinted in:
published after his death Martin Heidegger, Aus der Erfahrung des
Denkens, hrsg. von Hermann Heidegger,
Heidegger published or gave permission to Gesamtausgabe 13, Frankfurt am Main
publish letters during his lifetime. The most 1983, 93109.

68
HEIDEGGERS CORRESPONDENCE

Martin Heideggers letter on Einfhrung in Letter to Manfred S. Frings of October 20,


die Metaphysik. In: Die Zeit, Jhg. 8, Nr. 39. 1966 as greetings to the Heidegger-Symposium
15. September 1953. Reprinted in: Martin in Chicago, November 1112, 1966, pub-
Heidegger, Einfhrung in die Metaphysik, lished in: Manfred Frings (ed.), Heidegger
hrsg. von Petra Jaeger Gesamtausgabe 40, and the Quest for Truth. Chicago 1968;
Frankfurt am Main 1983, 2323. reprinted in: Gesamtausgabe 16, 6846.
Letter of April 1962 to William J. Letter to Franois Bondy from January 29,
Richardson, SJ, published as a preface in 1968, reprinted in: Critique. Revue gnrale
his Heidegger. Through phenomenology to des publications franaisses et trangers (24),
thought. The Hague 1963, viixxiii. 1968.
Letter to Takehiko Kojima written July 5, Letter to Roger Munier from July 31, 1969.
1963. In: Dino Larese (Hrsg.), Begegnung. In: Quest-ce que la mtaphysique?, prcd
Zeitschrift fr Literatur, bildende Kunst, dune lettre de lauteur. Trad. Roger Munier,
Musik und Wissenschaft 1, 1965, 27. published in: Le Nouveau Commerce, cahier
Letter of March 11, 1964 written for a 14, t-automne 1969, 556 ; reprinted in:
discussion at Drew University in Madison Martin Heidegger, Seminare, hrsg. von Curd
(USA) from April 9 to April 11, 1964. Einige Ochwadt, Gesamtausgabe 15, Frankfurt am
Hinweise auf Hauptgeschichtspunkte fr das Main 1983, 41416.
theologische Gesprch ber Das Problem Letter to Albert Borgmann from 29. October
eines nicht-objektivierenden Denkens und 39, 1969 as greetings and thanks to the par-
Sprechens in der heutigen Theologie, first ticipants of the Heidegger-Conference in
published in French translation in: Archives Honolulu, Hawaii 1721. November 1721,
de Philosophie (32) 1969, 396416. 1969, published in: Philosophy East and
Reprinted in: Martin Heidegger, Wegmarken, West 20, 1970; reprinted in Gesamtausgabe
hrsg. von Friedrich-Wilhelm von Herrmann 16, 7212.
Gesamtausgabe 9, Frankfurt am Main 1976, Letter to Jan Aler from November 1970,
6878, published in: Zeitschrift fr sthetik und
Readers letter to the editor in chief of the allgemeine Kunstwissenschaft 18, 1973;
Spiegel of February 22, 1966. In: Der Spiegel, reprinted in: Gesamtausgabe 16, 7234.
Jhg. 20, Nr. 7, 7. February 1966, 11012; Nr. Letter an Henri Mongis from June 7, 1972,
11, 7. Mrz 1966. 12. Reprinted in: Martin published in: H. Mongis. Heidegger et la
Heidegger, Reden und andere Zeugnisse eines Critique de la Notion de Valeur. The Hague
Lebensweges, hrsg. von Hermann Heidegger, 1976, vixi, reprinted in: Gesamtausgabe 16,
Gesamtausgabe 16, Frankfurt am Main 7279.
2000, 639. Greetings to the Symposium in Beirut
Letter to Arthur H. Schrynemakers of November 1974, in: Extasis. Cahiers de phi-
September 20, 1966 as greetings to the losophie et de littrature (8), Beirut 1981;
Symposium on Heideggers Philosophy at reprinted in Gesamtausgabe 19, 7423.
Dusquesne University, Pittsburgh October Letter from November 19, 1974 as con-
1516, 1966 published in: John Sallis (ed.), gratulations to the publishing of volume 500
Heidegger and the Path of Thinking. Pittsburgh of the journal Ris, published in: Ris, (500),
1970; reprinted in Gesamtausgabe 16, 6501.

69
HEIDEGGERS CORRESPONDENCE

January 1975; reprinted in: Gesamtausgabe for a reform of the Humboldt-University.


16, 7445. From the Heidegger-Jaspers correspond-
Greetings to Bernhard Welte and his home- ence we know that the necessity of a uni-
town Mekirch from late May 1976, pub- versity reform was one of the main topics
lished in: Stadt MekirchEhrenbrgerfeier of their discussions in Heidelberg in the
Professor Dr. Bernhard Welte. Mekirch early 1930s. (2) He was actively trying to
1978; reprinted in: Gesamtausgabe 13, 243. promote this proposal not only among the
In the last 25 years important corre- other professors but also in the Ministry of
spondences have been published. The most Education in both Karlsruhe and Berlin. (3)
famous correspondence is of course the let- Heideggers reform program was inspired
ter exchange with his onetime lover Hannah by Platonic philosophy. A small citation
Arendt. These publications have documented from a letter like the one above already
the different stages of Heideggers life and proves that Heideggers involvement with
work. Some of his earliest lettersthat offer National-Socialism and his ideas of univer-
insight into Heideggers philosophical devel- sity reform that he tried to put in place as
opment in his student yearswere published rector in 1933 cannot be separated from
in the Heidegger-Rickert correspondence. his thought. There are not only philosophi-
For the 1920s and the genesis of Being and cal reasons why Heidegger was attracted
Time the correspondences with Karl Jaspers to National-Socialism and the charismatic
and Karl Lwith are of great importance. leadership of Hitler but also philosophical
Heideggers relation to National-Socialism in reasons why he became ever more critical
the late 1930s and early 1940s can be found of National-Socialism. In the late 1930s he
in his letter exchange with Kurt Bauch. In his sees National-Socialism as the most extreme
second letter to Bauch from March 14, 1933 and terrible form of Nihilism and Hitler and
for instance Heidegger writes: his clique as the worst criminals in history.
For the convenience of the reader I have
In my opinion we can only try to avoid put together a list of the Heidegger cor-
mistakes and make people conscious of respondences that have been published so
the necessity of a total revolution that far.
cannot be achieved by so-called meas- Hannah Arendt/Martin Heidegger, Briefe
ures alone, but only by a clarification 1925 bis 1975 und andere Zeugnisse,
and determination of the will and the Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann,
mission of the young generation: In this
1998.
respect I have already presented a pro-
Martin Heidegger/Elisabeth Blochmann,
posal in the committee. If we dont want
our platonic program come to nothing, Briefwechsel 19181969, Marbach am
we need to know first what the govern- Neckar: Deutsches Literaturarchiv, 1989.
ment is planning.4 Martin Heidegger/Imma von Bodmershof,
Briefwechsel 19591976, Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta,
From this passage we can learn several 2000.
things: (1) Before Heidegger became rec- Martin Heidegger/Edmund Husserl, Brief
tor of Freiburg University on April 21, wechsel 19161933; in: Heidegger-Jahrbuch
1933 he had already formulated a program Bd. 6 (2012), 939.

70
HEIDEGGERS CORRESPONDENCE

Martin Heidegger/Karl Jaspers, Brief 8: HeideggerDenker in drftiger Zeit.


wechsel 19201963, Frankfurt am Main/ Stuttgart: Metzler, 1984.
Mnchen; Vittorio Klostermann/Piper, 1990. Heideggers Briefwechsel mit Paul Hberlin
Martin Heidegger/Erhart Kstner, Brief wurde verffentlicht in: Paul Hberlin/
wechsel 19531974, Frankfurt am Main: Ludwig Binswanger. Briefwechsel 1908
Insel Verlag, 1986. 1960. Herausgegeben von Jeannine Luczak.
Martin Heidegger/Heinrich Rickert, Briefe Basel: Schwabe, 1997.
19121933, Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Heideggers Briefwechsel mit Medard
Klostermann, 2002. Boss wurde teilweise verffentlicht in:
Rudolf Bultmann/Martin Heidegger, Brief Martin Heidegger, Zollikoner Seminare.
wechsel 19251975, Frankfurt am Main/ P r o t o ko l l e Z w i e g e s p r c h e B r i e f e .
Tbingen: Vittorio Klostermann/J.C.B. Mohr Herausgegeben von Medard Boss. Frankfurt
Verlag, 2009. am Main: Vittorio Klostermann,2 1994.
Martin Heidegger/Ludwig von Ficker, Brief
wechsel 19521967, Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta,
2004.
Ernst Jnger/Martin Heidegger, Briefe The
19491975, Frankfurt am Main/Stuttgart: Martin-Heidegger-Briefausgabe
Vittorio Klostermann/Klett-Cotta, 2008.
Martin Heidegger, Briefe an Max Mller The Martin-Heidegger-Briefausgabe has
und andere Dokumente, Freiburg/Mnchen: been published by Verlag Karl Alber in
Karl Alber Verlag, 2003. three divisions and edited by Alfred Denker
Martin Heidegger/Bernhard Welte, Briefe and Holger Zaborowski. Its aim is to pub-
und Begegnungen, Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta, lish Heideggers correspondences with phi-
2003. losophers, scientists, artists, writers, and
Martin Heidegger/Kurt Bauch, Briefwechsel other personalities as well as his private and
19321975 (Martin-Heidegger-Briefausgabe institutional correspondence with universi-
II.1), Freiburg: Verlag Karl Alber, 2011. ties, ministries, publishers, and academies.
Martin Heidegger/Erhart Kstner. Brief The series is divided into three divisions: I.
wechsel 19531974. Herausgegeben von Private correspondence, II. Scientific cor-
Heinrich W. Petzet. Frankfurt am Main: Insel respondence, and III. Correspondence with
Verlag, 1986. institutions and publishers. Approximately
Heideggers Briefwechsel mit Max 45 volumes are planned. A full list is pro-
Kommerell wurde teilweise verffentlicht in: vided below. In 2011 the first volume of
Max Kommerell, Briefe und Aufzeichnungen: the Martin-Heidegger-Briefausgabe was
19191944. Aus dem Nachla herausgege- published. It contains Heideggers corre-
ben von Inge Jens. Freiburg: Olten, 1967. spondence with his colleague and friend,
Karl Lwith verffentlichte Teile von the historian of art Kurt Bauch mentioned
seinem Briefwechsel mit Heidegger in: above.
Karl Lwith, Zu Heideggers Seinsfrage: Heideggers letters will continue to be of
Die Natur des Menschen und die Welt der utmost importance for the research into his
Natur; in seinen Smtlichen Schriften. Bd. life and thought.

71
HEIDEGGERS CORRESPONDENCE

Volume Correspondence Number of letters


(approx.)

I.1 Correspondence with his parents and sister 126


I.2 Correspondence with his wife Elfride 1,100
I.3 Correspondence with his brother Fritz 700
I.4 Correspondence with other family members (nephews, nieces, 300
grandchildren, parents-in-law, etc.)
I.5 Correspondence with his friends Bruno and Erika Leiner 200
I.6 Correspondence with his friends Ernst Laslowski, Fritz Blum, 200
and Theophil Reese
I.7 Correspondence with friends in Mekirch, Todtnauberg, and 150
Freiburg
I.8 Private correspondence 1,500
II.1 Correspondence with Kurt Bauch 144
II.2 Correspondence with Karl Lwith 115
II.3 Correspondence with Walter Brcker, Friedrich Gundolf, Werner 200
Jaeger, Gerhard Krger, Walter F. Otto, Wolfgang Schadewaldt,
Bruno Snell, and Julius Stenzel
II.4 Correspondence with Julius Ebbinghaus, Hildegard Feick, Georg 200
Misch, Hermann Mrchen, Hermann Nohl, and Manfred Schrter
II.5 Correspondence with Beda Allemann, Wolfgang Binder, Ivo 250
Braak, Max Kommerell, Paul Kremer, Paul Kuckhohn, Eduard
Lachmann, Emil Staiger, Ingeborg Strohschneider-Kohrs, Leopold
Ziegler, and Franz Zinkernagel
II.6 Correspondence with Max Mller, Gustav Siewerth, and Bernhard 200
Welte
II.7 Correspondence with Elisabeth Blochmann 112
II.8 Correspondence with Jean Beaufret 250
II.9 Correspondence with Romano Guardini, Engelbert Krebs, and 250
Karl Rahner
II.10 Correspondence with Medard Boss, Ludwig von Binswanger, and 350
Victor von Gebsattel
II.11 Correspondence with Erich Rothacker, Eugen Fink, Paul Hberlin, 200
Maria Scheler, Ludwig Langrebe, Paul Natorp, and Oskar Becker
II.12 Correspondence with Hans Kock, Bernhard Heiliger, George 100
Braque, Hans Wimmer, Otto Dix, and Carl Orff
II.13 Correspondence with Jean-Paul Sartre, Otto Pggeler, Hans Jonas, 250
Hartmut Buchner, Helene Wei, and Walter Biemel
II,14 Correspondence with Ernst Jnger, Friedrich Georg Jnger, Egon 120
Vietta, Paul Celan, and Andrea von Harbou
II.15 Correspondence with Kte Victorius, Walter Schulz, Wilhelm 100
Szilasi, and Gottfried Martin

72
HEIDEGGERS CORRESPONDENCE

Volume Correspondence Number of letters


(approx.)

II.16 Correspondence with Edmund Husserl, Heinrich Rickert, 150


and Jonas Cohn
II.17 Correspondence with philosophers and persons from Asia, 250
South America, the USA, and Canada
II.18 Correspondence with philosophers and persons from Asia, 300
South America, Canada and the USA
II.19 Correspondence with Heinrich Wiegand Petzet, Hans Jantzen, 250
Marilene Putscher, and Inge Krummer-Schroth
II.20 Correspondence with Ludwig von Ficker and Imma von 120
Bodmershof
II.21 Correspondence with Rudolf Bultmann 120
II.22 Correspondence with Clemens and Dorothea Podewils 350
II.23 Correspondence with Karl Jaspers 155
II.24 Correspondence with Hannah Arendt 169
II.25 Single letters I 300
II.26 Single letters II 300
II.27 Zusatzband 500
III.1 Correspondence with Gtnher Neske Verlag and others 300
III.2 Correspondence with Vittorio Klostermann Verlag 500
III.3 Correspondence with Academies in Berlin, Munich, and Heidelberg 400
III.4 Correspondence with universities 600
III.5 Correspondence with other institutions 250
III.6 Correspondence with the cities of Mekirch, Todtnuberg, Marburg, 150
and Freiburg

NOTES AND REFERENCES humanisme, transl. by Chris Bremmers (Budel:


Uitgeverij Damon, 2005), 915)
1
Martin Heidegger, Platons Lehre von der 3
William J. Richardson, SJ, Heidegger. Through
Wahrheit/Brief ber den Humanismus (Bern: Phenomenology to Thought (The Hague:
Verlag Francke, 1947). Martinus Nijhoff, 1963).
2
This letter is published in the Dutch transla- 4
Martin Heidegger/Kurt Bauch, Briefwechsel
tion of Brief ber den Humanismus. This 19321975, herausgegeben und kommentiert
volume contains both the Fench original and a von Almuth Heidegger (Freiburg/Mnchen:
Dutch translation (Martin Heidegger, Over het Karl Alber, 2010), 14.

73
8
HEIDEGGER AND GREEK PHILOSOPHY
Sean D. Kirkland

There is need (Es bedarf) of a thoughtful with Heidegger brings to light not what the
looking back into that which an ancient ancients themselves intended or had in mind,
(uralt) memory holds preserved for us, not the factual reality of a long dead Greek
into that which through all the things that culture, but what is preserved, although cur-
we think we know and possess nonethe-
rently inaccessible and unthinkable, in the
less remains distorted. We can after all
originally old (uralt) memory still some-
only seek that which is already known,
even if concealedly so (verhllterweise). how at work in our living present. Indeed,
(Auf., 2/Soj., 3, trans. modified) this passage indicates the motive for and
the method of Heideggers engagement with
Greek philosophy, both earlier and later in
The epigraph above has much to tell us his career.
about how Heidegger views our late-modern To be sure, Heideggers confrontations
or postmodern relationship to ancient with ancient Greek philosophy are numer-
Greek philosophy. It is taken from Sojourns: ous. Taking the published works and the
The Journey to Greece, a travel-book that lecture courses together, there are multiple
Heidegger composed on the occasion of his monograph-length studies of Heraclitus,
first visit to that country in 1962. We learn Parmenides, Plato, and Aristotle, to which
here that a thoughtful looking back to must be added the nearly countless embed-
the ancient Greeks is not merely a pleas- ded discussions of varying depth and detail
ant historical diversion from more pressing in which Heidegger takes up Greek thought
contemporary problems, not the sating of in general or a given Greek concept or term
an idle curiosity, and not merely a scholarly in particular. Anything like a comprehensive
exercise. Rather, Heidegger views this is as study of Heidegger and Greek philosophy
a Bedrfnis, a real necessitation or compul- would thus require volumes.1 However, even
sion for us. However, the ultimate destina- under the constraints within which this essay
tion toward which we find ourselves thus must operate, what we can address is the basic
compelled is not located in the past, but right why and the how of Heideggers deep and
here in our own present. That is, Heidegger persisting interest in ancient Greek philoso-
is calling for an ancient detour, by which we phy. That is, the aforementioned necessitation
would ultimately arrive at what we in a cer- and the way in which Heideggers herme-
tain sense already have; reading the Greeks neutic, by identifying a certain ambivalence

77
HEIDEGGER AND GREEK PHILOSOPHY

in the original texts of our inherited tradition, worthy of inquiryThis is where our ancient
aims to bring about a change in our experi- memory will have a role to play, meaning
ence of our world today. our persisting relation to ancient Greek philo-
sophical thinking and the texts that contain
the trace of what was experienced there. And
the compulsion to take up those ancient texts
The Necessity of Looking Back comes from a preliminary perplexity. That
to the Greeks is, from the simple strangeness of our being
incapable of asking the question of the mean-
The very first words of Heideggers Being ing of Being today despite this questions hav-
and Time are Platos. And the projected ing a certain undeniable priority with respect
final section of the work would have been to every other inquiry. Once this necessity
an extensive treatment of Aristotelian phys- (Notwendigkeit) for restating the question
ics and metaphysics. In an important sense, . . . becomes plain (SZ, 3/BTMR, 22), it is
then, the entire project unfolds explicitly unfolded into and imposes itself on us as
within a space opened up and delineated that twofold task (SZ, 15/BTMR, 36) that
by ancient Greek thought. Furthermore, the organizes the projected whole of Being and
central aim of all Heideggers thinkingthe Time into its two main parts.
recovery of the question of the meaning of Part one undertakes a Daseinsanalytik, a
Beingis introduced here as that same ques- phenomenological, hermeneutical analy-
tion that had provided a stimulus for the sis of Dasein, which is to say, of ourselves
researches of Plato and Aristotle, only to sub- as being there in the world in such a way
side from then on as a theme for actual inves- that we can ask or not ask the question of
tigation (SZ, 2/BTMR, 21). Why did this what it means to be (which ipso facto
question cease to be posed thereafter, such entails a certain pre-understanding of Being).
that it is initially impossible for us to pose it However, the fact that Being appears to us
again today? Because, ever since the original as initially unworthy of any investigation at
response to that question and on the basis of all indicates that Dasein has a tendency to
that response, Being has been and continues fall away from itself on this point. That is,
to be dismissed as a notion either universal we treat the question of what it means to
and self-evident or empty and indefinable. be as always already definitively answered
Even the posing of this question, there- in part because we reduce everything that is,
fore, requires preparation today, which is including ourselves, to the one mode of being
to say that Being must be first uncovered in that belongs to the things in the world with
its question-worthiness and made available which we are most closely and most con-
once again for consideration. In our epigraph stantly involvedBeing as being present
above, then, it is Being as worthy of our (presence here having a double valence
attention and inquiry to which Heidegger is of either Zuhandenheit, present and avail-
referring when he speaks of what our ancient able to be employed toward our ends, or
memory still preserves for us today, but as Vorhandenheit, present and available for
distorted and concealed. We might wonder contemplation, scrutiny, and understand-
how Being, as both inaccessible and neverthe- ing). Heidegger then goes on to show that
less somehow preserved, can emerge for us as we, as Dasein, actually have as our mode

78
HEIDEGGER AND GREEK PHILOSOPHY

of being a certain way of emerging out of With this insight into our own fundamental
a given past and stretching ourselves out way of being as Dasein, in order to respond
toward a future, thereby deciding our being properly to our newly awakened perplexity
each and every time. This fundamentally at our own inability to ask the most funda-
temporalizing structure Heidegger designates mental and most all-embracing question,
as Sorge or care. With this insight into our it is necessitated of us that we disrupt our
own mode of being as something other than traditional and inherited understanding of
mere presence, we should come to suffer Being. And this we can do only by tracing
anew the question of the meaning of Being our own basic ontological orientation back
tout simple. through the epochal moments of its develop-
Although never completed, Heidegger ment as charted by the outline of Being and
projects Part two as an absolutely necessary Times projected second half, through Kant
corollary to the analysis of Dasein. The tem- to Descartes, then looking back through the
poralizing movement that is Daseins mode of medieval thinkers all the way to Aristotle. It
being also entails an elemental historicality is the Greeks, most dramatically Aristotle but
(SZ, 20/BTMR, 41), a way of taking up a cer- perhaps already Parmenides (SZ, 26/BTMR,
tain tradition and projecting ourselves toward 48), who had confronted the question of the
possibilities delineated by that tradition. We meaning of Being to some extent and had
receive certain principles, concepts, and val- answered it, holding that to be is exclu-
ues from historical sources and we decide our sively to be present in the specific sense of
future actions accordingly. Indeed, Heidegger present and available to legein or speaking
traces the fallenness of our present condi- for Aristotle or to noein or thinking for
tion to two distinct tendencies in Daseins Parmenides. And this interpretation, the work
basic mode of being; As we remarked above, of Greek thinking about the world as they
Daseins tendency is inclined to fall back experienced it, was dogmatically passed along
upon its world . . . and interpret itself in as something self-evident, unworthy of ques-
terms of that world by its refracted light, tioning. By way of this destruction of our
but Dasein also simultaneously falls prey own tradition, what had seemed an absolute
(verfllt) to the tradition of which it has more and manifest truth would come to appear as
or less explicitly taken hold (SZ, 21/BTMR, a product of human interpretation, an histori-
42). Heidegger continues, cal artifact, and thus something that emerged
at a specific moment in our past. With this, we
Tradition takes what has come down to free up that ursprngliche Quelle or original
us and delivers it over to self-evidence; source from which the Greek interpretation
it blocks our access to those original of Being itself had originally arisen and we
sources (Zugang zu den ursprnglichen
become able to think in relation to it, pos-
Quellen) from which the categories and
ing once again the question of the meaning
concepts handed down to us have been in
part genuinely drawn. Indeed, the tradi- of Being for ourselves. We will return to this
tion makes us forget that they have had below, for it is the aim of excavating just this
such an origin. It teaches the needlessness source that determines Heideggers herme-
(Unbedrftigkeit) of even understanding neutic with respect to Greek texts.
the necessity (Notwendigkeit) of any such Having identified where the need or the
going back. (SZ, 21/BTMR, 43) necessity of looking back to the Greeks comes

79
HEIDEGGER AND GREEK PHILOSOPHY

from in Being and Time, we might now just Interesting here is the intimation that we find
note that the call for something like this in the texts of Aristotle evidence of an experi-
destruction actually appears much earlier ence of the world from which the interpre-
in Heideggers thinking. For example, in the tation of Being as presence arose as well as
1922 introduction to a never-executed book evidence that some aspect of that experience
project, Phenomenological Interpretations is being lost and put under pressure.
in Connection with Aristotle, the task of Again, as we shall see, it is precisely this kind
analyzing the basic structures of factical of ambivalence in the text that Heideggers
human Dasein (PIA2, 233/S, 114), that is, method of reading the Greeks attempts to
the phenomenological hermeneutic of our draw out.
own present existence carries out its tasks What necessitates our looking back to
only on the path of destruction (PIA2, the Greeks in Heideggers earlier period is
249/S, 124). Heidegger writes, thus an initial perplexity at our own lack of
perplexity, or at our own incapacity to be
In philosophical research, this destruc- provoked by the question of the meaning of
tive confrontation with its own history Being.2 Once our fundamentally historicizing
is not merely . . . an occasional overview mode of being is brought to light, this initial
of what others before us came up with perplexity compels us to trace our own pre-
. . . Rather, destruction is the authentic sumed understanding back through the tra-
path upon which the present needs to dition we inherit as our own, until we expose
encounter itself in its own basic move- its moment of origination in Greek thought.
ments. (ibid.) Whatever the precise meaning and signifi-
cance of the Kehre or turn that Heidegger
Already here in this text, we are compelled diagnosed in his own thinking, it must be
to push the destruction of our tradition back acknowledged that, with specific respect
to Aristotle, where Being was first firmly to the needfulness of looking back to the
equated with ousia or being, substance, Greeks, the change between the earlier and
here defined specifically as being made later periods is minor. Let us start with the
present or produced (PIA2, 272/S, 144). Contributions to Philosophy (Of the Event),
composed between 1936 and 1938, where
[T]his sense of being has its provenance the terminology and central themes of the
in the environing world as it is originally later period are introduced with startling
given in experience, but then, and this is intensity and compression.
found even in Aristotle himself, it lost Here Heidegger reaffirms his commitment
the sense of this provenance due to the to the question of the meaning of Being
pressure exerted by the kind of ontol- [It] is and remains my question, and is
ogy being worked out and refined. In the
my unique question (GA 65, 10/CP2, 11).
course of the subsequent development of
Indeed, it is the posing of just this question
ontological research, it fell into the aver-
ageness of having its vague traditional that should open the site for what Heidegger
meaning of reality or actuality and refers to as the other beginning, a think-
as such then provided the starting point ing that, recognizing the ontological differ-
for the problems of epistemology. (PIA2, ence, would not reduce Being to the presence
274/S, 145) of present beings. Instead, beings are to be

80
HEIDEGGER AND GREEK PHILOSOPHY

thought from out of Being, now spelled with and Times opening pages, that is, a perplex-
a y (Seyn) and identified with Ereignis or ity at our own incapacity to pose the ques-
event, the dynamic and always historically tion of Being and a dissatisfaction with our
situated emergence or unfolding of beings own claim to already enjoy adequate knowl-
into appearance, which precisely as such edge of Being. Now Heidegger has recourse
withdraws or remains inaccessible behind to a pre-epistemic register. He writes of, the
the very beings it allows to present them- fundamental attunement (Grundstimmung)
selves. This other beginning will only be pos- of thinking in the other beginning (GA 65,
sible, however, when it is held in an essential 14/CP2, 14, trans. modified), a certain way
relation to the first beginning, that is, the of being already opened up to, in contact
Greek interpretation of Being as presence. with, and disposed toward the world around
Heidegger calls for a thinking in the cross- us.3 The attunement of our historical present
ing from the first beginning to the other, is described as a combination of Erschrecken
in which the first beginning remains deci- or shock, Verhaltenheit or restraint, and
sive as the first and yet is indeed overcome Scheu or diffidence. It seems then that one
as beginning (GA 65, 56/CP2, 7). That is, is to take up the other beginning from out
understanding ourselves as the inheritors of of the nihilistic exhaustion of Western cul-
an ontological standpoint accomplished by ture today, just as philosophizing in the first
the Greeks, we come to inhabit the space beginning arose from out of the pathos of
of the crossing between our Greek past thaumazein or wonder. And this necessi-
and our present in such a way that we will tates our looking back to the Greeks in order
become decided for the futural possibility of to understand our late-modern moment as
thinking Being otherwise. the end of the historical development that
Although Heidegger is certainly still began with them. Indeed, by taking up the
affirming the necessity of looking back to first beginning, we will intensify and con-
the Greeks, his way of speaking of the source centrate our already fundamentally attuned
of that necessitation represents a departure condition until we are able to take the leap
from that of the earlier period. He writes, (see especially GA 65, 22789/CP2, 179
As unavoidable as is the confrontation with 227), which is how Heidegger describes the
the first beginning of the history of thought, transition into the other beginnings think-
just as certainly must questioning forget eve- ing Being otherwise than as the presence of
rything round about itself and merely think present beings.
about its own distress (Not) (GA 65, 10/ In the 1946 essay, The Anaximander Frag
CP2, 11, trans. modified). In order to open up ment, one finds this same necessitation at
this other way of thinking Being, Heidegger work. Heidegger begins by problematizing
again introduces a twofold task (SZ, 15/ his readers interest in this piece of antiquity.
BTMR, 36), described here as looking back He asks, Are we latecomers in a history now
to the Greek origin of our ontological com- racing towards its end, an end which in its
mitments while attending to the Not or dis- increasingly sterile order of uniformity brings
tress, needfulness that one should feel in our everything to an end? . . . Do we stand in the
present historical moment. very twilight of the most monstrous transfor-
This distress takes the place of the essen- mation our planet has ever undergone, the
tially epistemic perplexity provoked in Being twilight of that epoch in which the earth itself

81
HEIDEGGER AND GREEK PHILOSOPHY

hangs suspended? (EGT, 1617, GA 5, 300). have guided us ever since (SZ, 22/ BT, 44,
That is, Heidegger wants to evoke here the trans. modified). Throughout his career, what
disposition of the epigone, and then to inten- Heidegger hopes to bring to light in Greek
sify just that disposition with his question- texts is again and again this transitional or
ing, concentrating us on our present mood of liminal moment, in which the interpretation
nagging doubt or outright horror at the state of Being as presence is just emerging from an
of things in late modernity. Whether this original experience that, even while generat-
be the dehumanization associated with the ing that interpretation, nonetheless exceeds
exchangeability and reproducibility of eve- it. Early Heidegger reads the Greeks in order
rything or the terrifying prospect of nuclear to get access to those original sources
annihilation, Heidegger seems to wager that (Zugang zu den ursprnglichen Quellen)
his reader is experiencing at present a certain from which the categories and concepts
distress, which he then hopes will necessitate handed down to us have been in part genu-
attending to the Greek beginning of that very inely drawn (SZ, 21/BTMR, 43), and later
historical, philosophical development that on he hopes to access precisely what was in
we feel coming to a troubling end today. the first beginning sheltered (Verborgene),
the origin (Ursprung) that has not yet been
misused and driven on, the one that reaches
furthest ahead in constantly withdrawing
The Way of Looking Back to (GA 65, 57/CP2, 46). In both periods, how-
the Greeks ever, it is by confronting his readers with an
ambivalence or liminality in traditional texts
As was already clear from the epigraph that Heidegger hopes to reactivate that still
with which we began, in taking up the texts hidden Quelle or Urpsrung, that source or
of Greek philosophers, Heidegger is not origin, so that our thinking can attend to
concerned about accurately retrieving the it today and begin to think beings otherwise.
objective truth concerning events or atti- Over the course of his career, Heidegger
tudes belonging to that past reality. Rather, does seem to locate that ambivalence, that
throughout his career, Heidegger addresses limen or threshold, at an ever earlier
what our ancient memory holds preserved moment in Greek intellectual history. The
for us. The past we take up in order to younger Heidegger focused more attention
change our present is not the past itself but on the work of Aristotle, with a number of
our past, the past that is still vital and effec- lecture courses being devoted to him in the
tive in our experience of our world and years prior to Being and Time (and even the
ourselves today. But how does Heideggers course on Platos Sophist in 1924/1925 and
peculiar way of reading Greek texts accom- the more general Basic Concepts of Ancient
plish this? Philosophy from 1926 both take Aristotle as
In Being and Time, he says that our task is the central figure in accessing what is there
to destroy the traditional content of ancient for us in ancient Greek thought). In the mid-
ontology until we arrive at the original expe- dle period, we see Heidegger more deter-
riences (zu den ursprnglichen Erfahrungen) mined to find ambivalence in the Platonic
in which we achieved our first ways of deter- text, especially in the 1931 essay (revised in
mining the nature of Beingthe ways which 1940), Platos Doctrine of Truth, and in

82
HEIDEGGER AND GREEK PHILOSOPHY

the lecture course from 1931/1932, On the original notion of truth, which he associates
Essence of Truth: On the Allegory of the with the word altheia, to a notion much
Cave and the Theaetetus (not to mention more familiar to us, that of truth as corre-
Heideggers extremely deep and illuminating spondence. In Platos description of the more
treatments of the Republic and the Phaedrus orthots or correct relation to the eid or
in the 1936/1937 lecture course on Nietzsche Ideas, Heidegger sees a foreshadowing of
entitled The Will to Power as Art). Finally, truth as adequatio intellectus et rei. Truth
later still, Heideggers attention seemed to be in this sense would be located in the subject
drawn more and more to the Pre-Socratics, and would refer to the re-presentation in the
for example, 1942/1943s lecture course mind or in speech of the reality of present
on Parmenides and 1943s lecture course objects and their relations. The more original
on Heraclitus, as well as the essays from notion of truth is named by altheia, which
1943 to 1954 collected in the English vol- Heidegger understands as an abstract noun
ume, Early Greek Thinking, and finally the composed by adding the alpha privativum to
seminar Heidegger held with Eugen Fink in lth or forgetting, concealment and which
1966/1967. he thus translates as unconcealment. This
Let us now look for this hermeneutic of would precede and subtend the subject-object
ambivalence with respect to three of the most ordered relation the correspondence theory
fundamental and most frequently discussed seems to presuppose. Here, truth names the
themes in Heideggers readings of Greek phi- emergence of beings into presentation to us,
losophy, altheia, phusis, and logos. and is thus located not in the subject stand-
To be sure, Heidegger returns to the issue ing over against an object, but between us
of truth throughout his career, almost always and beings in their appearing to us (where
taking as his touchstone the Greek term our relation to such appearing beings is
altheia, commonly translated as truth. always already secured and inviolable).4 In
In the opening pages of Platos Doctrine of Platos discussion, thus, Heidegger reveals a
Truth, Heidegger indicates that his inter- moment of transition between these two con-
pretive approach will be quite unortho- ceptions of truth.
dox. He writes that the doctrine (Lehre) Heidegger finds a like liminality in
of a thinker is that which, within what is Aristotles thinking of phusis or, as it is
said, remains unsaid, that to which we are most often translated, nature. In On the
exposed so that we might expend ourselves Essence and Concept of Phusis in Aristotles
on it (GA 9, 109/PA, 155). What we seek in Physics B1, we uncover a moment where
analyzing Platos text is something inexplicit, the modern concept of nature is dramati-
but which we are nonetheless able to expe- cally emerging into view ready to accept its
rience in what is said through Heideggers opposition to civilization, spirit, history, or
interpretation. This unsaid to which we the supernatural, but where also there are
will be exposed is nothing other than a cer- some traces of a prior, more original expe-
tain change (Wendung) in what determines rience of the worlds unfolding as phusis,
the essence of truth (ibid.). Heidegger reads an experience of the encompassing site that
Platos Allegory of the Cave as a meditation precedes and invokes these later conceptual
on the process of paideia or education. oppositions. Heidegger challenges us in read-
There he finds a transition from a more ing Aristotles Physics with him, saying the

83
HEIDEGGER AND GREEK PHILOSOPHY

distinction between nature and history must produced or being present for articulation
be pushed back into the underlying area that and intellection and, on the other hand,
sustains the dichotomy, the area where nature Being as self-concealing revealing, phusis in
and history are (GA 9, 311/PA, 184). the original sense (GA 9, 371/PA, 230).
In Physics B1, Aristotle begins again with And finally, we find this same hermeneutic
his study of ta phusika or natural things, at work again in Heideggers treatment of
now opposing them to things produced by the Greek term logos, translated variously
techn or skill, insofar as the former have as language, speech, statement, argument,
their own arch or source of movement and reason, or logic. Let us focus on the piece
emergence within themselves while the latter entitled Logos (Heraclitus, Fragment 50),
have their moving source external themselves which Heidegger delivered first in the context
in the craftsperson who produces them. of a lecture course in 1944, then again as an
Heidegger focuses on Aristotles hylo- stand-alone lecture in 1951, and finally pub-
morphic conception of the individual being lished as a chapter of Vortrge und Aufstze
and his rejection in this text of the sophist in 1967.
Antiphons claim that it is the hul or mat- When we attempt to understand Heraclituss
ter of any given natural thing that must be claim that, Listening not to me but to the
its real phusis, its internal source of coming Logos, it is wise to say that all is one (DK
to be what it is. Aristotle ultimately seems 50), Heidegger notes that we presume to do
to reject this in favor of the things morph, so by means of logos or by letting reason
shape, or eidos, form, that is, the look be our guide, even though it is precisely the
that a thing presents us with whereby it nature of logos that is at stake in the frag-
enters into intelligibility and articulability as ment. In response to this perplexing situation,
what it is. Although it is this position that Heidegger invites us instead to meditate
is passed along in the substance metaphys- on the essential origin of reason and to let
ics that arises from Aristotle, the text offers [ourselves] into its advent . . . paying heed to
access to an experience of morph and phusis logos and following its initial unfolding (GA
as dichs or intrinsically twofold. If morph 7, 200/EGT, 60, trans. modified). We begin to
is understood as essentially bound to its hul, do so with Heidegger by relating logos back
then it is not the static intelligible form of the to its verbal root, legein, which surely means
natural thing that is its being, its phusis, but to speak, talk, but which also has a pro-
rather the dynamic emergence of the being foundly illuminating and original sense, that
into its form, a being-on-the-way according of laying out and gathering together.
to which each being that is pro-duced or put Heidegger insists that this gathering be heard
forth (excluding artifacts) is also put away, not as mere amassing, but, as with a har-
as the blossom is put away by the fruit (GA vest, as a kind of letting-lie-together-before
9, 367/PA, 227). Phusis would then be the of what comes into presence or appears to
movement according to which beings emerge us, and specifically in such a way that the
into appearance before us, leaving obscured gathering undertakes a sheltering and a
necessarily or withholding that movement as safe-keeping of what it gathers (GA 7,
the beings ultimate source. With this insight, 2034/EGT, 623). A profoundly different
an ambivalence emerges in Aristotles text conception of legein, thus, opens up here
between, on the one hand, Being as being beneath our own familiar conception of

84
HEIDEGGER AND GREEK PHILOSOPHY

speaking or language-usage, whereby logos in its later traditional sense arises from
this has been reduced to a mere juxtaposing this original sense, of which he writes,
of words that either successfully re-presents
or fails to re-present the objective state of Language would be the gathering
affairs to which it refers. By contrast, legein letting-lie-before of what is present in its
would now seem to have as its task the receiv- presencing. In fact, the Greeks dwelt in
ing of what is appearing in such a way that it this essential determination of language.
is allowed to lie together before oneself and But they never thought itHeraclitus
ones listener and is thus sheltered in its way included. (GA 7, 220/EGT, 77)
of being. Note that this legein is inseparable
from what it gathers together, unlike our Heideggers hermeneutic with respect to the
modern conception of language or speech, Greek text, as we have seen, is aimed at draw-
which always stands over against and is in ing out that unsaid or unthought, which
principle severed from the world of present precedes and motivates, without being taken
objects it strives to re-present. Once logos up in or articulated by the metaphysical
has been revealed in its essential relation thinking that follows, dominated and delim-
to this gathering, as a safe-keeping of what ited as it is by the identification of Being with
emerges into presence in its emergence, hear- presence. Having energized the tension of
ing becomes not fundamentally an acousti- this liminal, transitional moment, we come to
cal phenomenon, but a reception of just this experience the source or origin of the entire
gathering into appearance before us. tradition that emerged with the Greeks and
All of this, then, Heidegger brings to bear still joins us to them. This tradition and its
on the interpretation of the Heraclitus frag- ontology of presence having been shown to
ment. We are to listen not to Heraclitus but emerge from a source it leaves behind, we are
to the logos itself, for what is at stake is not a thereby placed in contact with that excessive
subject voicing his opinion, but the gathering source and become capable of questioning
of what is into appearance, which allows Being and thinking it otherwise.
it to emerge before us and present itself.
Listening in this way, it is wise to homolegein,
usually translated as to agree but meaning
more literally to legein the same, in the same Conclusion
way, or along with. And what is it that we
wisely say along with, gather, and shelter? It In his 1958 essay, Hegel and the Greeks,
is wise to say, All is One. Here Heidegger Heidegger begins by asserting that the con-
finds not a motto or a principle articulated junction that joins together the two subjects
in logos, but rather what logos itself accom- in his title represents not an arbitrary or
plishes. All is One, in the specific sense that accidental connection, but an essential and
everything that is, is by participating in the internal one. Our title here, Heidegger and
dynamic movement of emergence by which Greek philosophy, employs a no less essen-
beings are gathered together and present tial conjunction, but of an utterly different
themselves to us in a world. Heidegger thus kind. Indeed, Heidegger is linked to Greek
locates in Heraclituss fragment the transi- philosophy not by recovery or synthesis
tion between these two moments, where with respect to earlier historical moments

85
HEIDEGGER AND GREEK PHILOSOPHY

in the necessary unfolding of spirit, but by 2005). Heideggers interpretation of Plato is the
shared excess or openness. If Heidegger subject of Alain Boutots Heidegger et Platon:
Le probleme du nihilisme (Paris: Philosophie
tasks us with recovery, it is of the ancients
daujourdhui, 1987), of the collection
unthought and unsaid as such, and if he Heidegger and Plato: Toward Dialogue
tasks us with synthesis, it is only of that (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University, 2005),
which must remain inaccessible, withdrawn. edited by Catalin Partenie and Tom Rockmore,
Both earlier and later, Heidegger hopes to and of Francisco Gonzalez Heidegger and
Plato: A Question of Dialogue (State College:
expose thinking once again to that dynamic
Penn State University, 2009). Finally, on
and inevitably self-withdrawing source by Heidegger and the early Greek thinkers, we
which beings emerge into presence before us. have George Seidels early Martin Heidegger
This necessitates today a thoughtful look- and the Pre-Socratics (Lincoln: University of
ing back to what our ancient memory holds Nebraska, 1964), David Jacobs collection
of essays, The Presocratics after Heidegger
preserved for us. That is, it necessitates the
(Albany, NY: SUNY, 1999), as well as Ivo de
destruction of our tradition all the way back Gennaros LogosHeidegger Liest Heraclitus
to the Greeks and a reading of those ancient (Berlin: Duncker & Humblot, 2001).
texts that highlights their ambivalence and 2
This precise form of provocation is repeated
confronts us with a trace of the very source in the later period, in the lecture course from
19512 entitled What is Called Thinking? where
we are seeking.
Heidegger wants his listeners to wrestle with his
claim that, Most thought-provoking is that we
are still not thinking (GA 8, 2/WCT, 4).
3
It might be objected that the Stimmung or
NOTES AND REFERENCES
attunement of Angst or anxiety already
plays an important role in Being and Time.
1
Even excluding the hundreds of essays on Although that is no doubt the case, this mood
these subjects and limiting ourselves to books, is not presented as motivating the task of
previous scholarship on this subject would destruction.
include the first volume of Jean Beaufrets 4
Earlier, Heidegger seems to have placed some
Dialogue avec Heidegger series, Philosophie emphasis on the actual etymology of the
Grecque (Paris: ditions de minuit, 1973), term altheia as unconcealment, a claim
as well as the collection, Heidegger and the that was problematized by Paul Friedlnder
Greeks (Bloomington: Indiana University, (Platon, Bd.I, Berlin: De Gruyter, 1964,
2006), edited by Drew Hyland and John 23343), among others. Although Friedlnder
Panteleimon Manoussakis. On Heidegger and ultimately withdraws his original opposi-
Aristotle, there is Franco Volpis Heidegger e tion to Heideggers etymology, he does resist
Aristotele (Rome: Editori Laterza, 1984), Ted Heideggers claim that prior to Plato, truth was
Sadlers Heidegger and Aristotle: The Question understood as unconcealment rather than
of Being (London: Continuum, 2001), and correctness, and Heidegger himself seems to
Walter Brogans Heidegger and Aristotle: The grant as much later on, in his 1964 essay The
Twofoldness of Being (Albany, NY: SUNY, End of Philosophy and the Task of Thinking.

86
9
HEIDEGGER AND MEDIEVAL
PHILOSOPHY
Holger Zaborowski

A Forgetfulness of Medieval at least a marginal reference to it. And if it is


Thought? mentioned at all, Heidegger refers to it more
often than not in a stereotypical and foresee-
Heideggers reading of ancient philosophy able manner.
primarily of the pre-Socratics, Plato, and Medieval philosophy thus seems to share
Aristotleand of modern philosophy from the same fate as Roman philosophy in
Descartes to Husserl is much discussed by Heideggers texts: It is overlooked or simpli-
Heidegger scholars. It has also significantly fied and often not fully taken seriously as
influenced the common understanding of, philosophy. There is, however, one crucial
and research into, both ancient and modern difference: For Heideggers way of thought,
philosophy. With a few notable exceptions, medieval thought was much more impor-
however, scholars of medieval philosophy tant than the philosophy of Cicero, Seneca,
hardly take notice of Heideggers thought. or Marcus Aurelius. As is well known,
Furthermore, Heideggers reading of medi- Heidegger began his career as a promising
eval texts and its influence on his own think- scholar of scholastic philosophy.
ing, is not a common topic among students
of his thought.1
This does not come as a surprise. Medieval
philosophy does not play a very significant Christianity, Scholasticism,
role for Heidegger after 1919. The main and the Origins of Heideggers
focus of his philosophical attention lies with- Thinking
out any question at all on ancient and mod-
ern philosophy, that is, on, roughly speaking, It goes without saying that Heideggers rela-
the very beginning and the completion of tion to medieval thought and the scholastic
Western metaphysics. Because of his focus on tradition is closely tied up with his relation
the Greeks and, indeed, the Germans, who, to Christianity. For him, medieval thought is
for Heidegger, primarily shaped modern phi- by and large a form of Christian and, more
losophy, the medieval period is very often not specifically, Catholic thinking (Heidegger, to
even mentioned where a reader would expect be sure, did not show an interest in Jewish

87
HEIDEGGER AND MEDIEVAL PHILOSOPHY

and Arabic medieval thought; for scarce ref- written between 1909 and 1915 when he
erences to Arabic philosophy see GA 23, 44; was a student and then a young doctor of
GA 24, 113f.). This is why when Heidegger philosophy (see particularly GA 13, 17;
lost his Catholic faith, his philosophical GA 16, 336), show the great extent to
interests also changed significantly. which Heidegger was at some point influ-
Heideggers rereading of Aristotle as well enced by an anti-modernistic emphasis on
as his turn toward Protestant theologians and medieval theology and philosophy, common
figures such as St Paul and St Augustine (i.e. in early twentieth-century neo-Scholastic
toward a particular, rather Protestant read- Catholicism:3 While medieval thought was
ing of these figures), both beginning in the considered to be properly grounded in eter-
late 1910s, neatly show his self-distancing nal truth and thus to be capable of bringing
from Catholicism and its intellectual herit- together faith and reason, the bible and the
age and thus also from medieval thought. Greeks (primarily Aristotle, of course), mod-
For the Aristotle of the lecture courses that ern philosophy from Descartes and Kant up
Heidegger gave at the University of Freiburg to Nietzsche and early twentieth-century
between 1919 and 1922 is a distinctly non- thought was regarded to be characterized by
scholastic proto-phenomenological Aristotle. the principle of doubt, relativism, subjectiv-
And his understanding of Christianity in ism, historicism, and, eventually, nihilism.
this period of his way of thinking is one that However, Heideggers interest in (neo-)scho-
favors texts that belong to the very origins lasticism was characterized by a certain dis-
of Christianity such as the letters of St Paul satisfaction from the very beginning (see GA
over later sources that already show the 16, 37); he was, therefore, also quite critical
deteriorating effects, so Heidegger thought, of the narrow kind of neo-Scholasticism,
of the Hellenization of Christianity (see favored by the Catholic church of his time.
GA 60; GA 61, 6f.). From this perspective, His own anti-modernistic turn toward a
medieval thought appeared doubly unap- highly idealized medieval world was thus
pealing to Heidegger: not only as a betrayal rather short-lived. It was the product of a
of Christianity and its distinctly nonphilo- young and very gifted mind that had not yet
sophical character but also of philosophy found its own voice, but was eagerly looking
and its original impetus as disclosed in early for it.
Greek thought. In his doctoral dissertation The Doctrine
Heideggers turn away from medieval of Judgment in Psychologism,4 Heidegger
thought came as a surprise to many who con- critically discussed then contemporary psy-
sidered him a new voice in Catholic medieval chologist doctrines, using insights that he
studies. Heidegger first read Aquinas when found in Husserls phenomenology and
he still went to school,2 studied Aquinas, Rickerts neo-Kantianism to defend an
Bonaventure, and neo-Scholastic textbooks agenda that was at least partly motivated by
as a young student (GA 16, 37), and was his own religious persuasions: the critique of
introduced into early and high scholasti- a naturalization of consciousness (FRS, 5),
cism by his doctoral supervisor Arthur of a misconstrual of logic proper, and of a
Schneider and into medieval history by the relativization of the concept of truth. There
Catholic historian Heinrich Finke (42). is, therefore, an indirect relation between
Many of Heideggers earliest publications, the topic of his PhD thesis and his early

88
HEIDEGGER AND MEDIEVAL PHILOSOPHY

interest in medieval thought. It is, however, In his Habilitationsschrift, Heidegger did


important to note that Heidegger decided not intent to historicize the medieval period,
to write his PhD thesis on modern and not thus turning it into an object of merely his-
medieval philosophy. Furthermore, when torical research, nor did he dismiss modern
he decided to focus on a medieval thinker philosophy (even in the years prior to his
in his Habilitationsschrift, Heidegger chose Habilitation, he had shown a serious inter-
Duns Scotus (so he thought at least) and not est in figures such as Kant, Nietzsche, and
Aquinas.5 Even in the very early phase of his Husserl). Already Heideggers brief preface
philosophical career, Heidegger was neither a and introduction show that he follows a
Thomist nor a neo-Scholastic thinker in the specific agenda in this book: He explicitly
narrow and exclusive sense of the word and, thanks not only Heinrich Rickert but also
as we will see, was open to a serious engage- the neo-Kantian and neo-Fichtean Emil Lask
ment with modern thought. (whose influence on the early Heidegger
cannot be overestimated).7 The introduc-
tion stands under a citation from Hegel, that
is, his idea, that with respect to its inner
Heideggers Habilitation on essence, there are neither predecessors nor
Thomas of Erfurts De modis successors in philosophy (FRS, 135)as if
significandi Heidegger, focusing on philosophical prob-
lems rather than merely historical relations,
Heideggers Habilitationsschrift (FRS, 131 wanted to distance himself from an under-
354) was written under the guidance of his standing of the history of philosophy as a
neo-Kantian teacher Heinrich Rickert (to decline or, alternatively, as a progress from
whom the published book is dedicated in the medieval to the modern period.
most grateful admiration; 132) and is enti- Heidegger is, on this basis, interested in
tled Duns Scotus Doctrine of Categories rereading texts from the medieval period
and Meaning. In this book, Heidegger with respect to logical problems discussed by
focuses on the text De modis significandi then contemporary neo-Kantianism and phe-
that at the time was thought to be writ- nomenologyand also with respect to the
ten by Duns Scotus (it was, in fact, written history of German idealism and Protestant
by the Scotist logician Thomas of Erfurt, as theology. In 1922, he wrote retrospectively
Martin Grabmann showed a short time after about his interests after completing his PhD
Heidegger worked on this text6). Heideggers that his
study of this text is divided into two parts.
Following an introduction on the necessity initial intention inclined toward an
of a problem-historical (problemgeschich- investigation of late scholasticism, above
all Ockham, in order to obtain [. . .] a
tlich) examination of scholasticism, the first
concrete and broad infrastructure for the
part discusses the doctrine of categories as a
scientific understanding of the history of
systematic foundation of the understand- the genesis of Protestant theology and
ing of the doctrine of meaning; the second thereby of the central contexts of prob-
part focuses on the doctrine of meaning. lems of German idealism. My preoccu-
Heidegger concludes with a short reflection pation with Ockham made a return to
on the problem of categories. Duns Scotus urgent for me.8

89
HEIDEGGER AND MEDIEVAL PHILOSOPHY

Heidegger is, however, well aware of the modern character and his greater and finer
differences between the different periods proximity (haecceitas) to real life (FRS, 145)
of the history of philosophy. He notes, for and stresses his focus on the concrete individ-
example, that the medieval period lacks a ual as really existing: The individual is an
consciousness of methods, this strongly irreducible ultimate (194f.), so Heidegger
developed desire and courage to question, writes both commenting on Duns Scotus/
the permanent control of every step of think- Thomas of Erfurt and anticipating his own
ing (FRS, 140). According to Heideggers later phenomenology of Dasein.
interpretation, the idea of authority and The transitional and anticipatory charac-
the high esteem for all tradition are clear ter of the book perhaps becomes most appar-
signs for this. Unlike the medieval human ent in the afterword that Heidegger wrote in
being, Heidegger reasons, the modern per- 1916 for the publication of his book. It is
son is liberated from his or her background not only Hegel who plays an important role
(141; see also 206). These comments show in Heideggers concluding remarks but also
very nicely the transitional character of this Dilthey and the emphasis on life, history, and
book: While he criticized the modern lib- the irresolvable relation between philosophy
eration from tradition and authority quite and both life and history (see particularly
radically in his previous occasional writings, 352f.). Thus, particularly in concluding this
his approach to it is now positive; it is an book, Heidegger goes beyond the medieval
achievement. And what he now notes about world. His examination of a text by Duns
medieval thought in a rather concluding Scotus/Thomas of Erfurt was a stepping
manner will later become on object of his stone toward thinking about the problem of
severe criticism: its dependence on something the meaning of historical life/existence in its
that is not philosophy, that is, its doctrinal concrete individuality and temporality.
presuppositions.
It is, in the context of this discussion of the
transitional character of the book, important
to note that Heidegger makes a consider- After his Habilitation
able move toward (not more, of course) key toward Being and Time via the
insights of his later hermeneutics of facticity, Hermeneutics of Facticity
of his phenomenology of Dasein, and also
of his being-historical thinking (see GA 66, After his Habilitation, Heideggers main focus,
411f. for Heideggers retrospective interpre- both in his research and in his teaching, was
tation of this text and its focus) not some on other periods of the history of philoso-
years after the Habilitation, as some schol- phy than on the medieval period. Heidegger
ars have argued, but already in the published continues to be interested in Kant and, pri-
version of it (the version that he submitted to marily, Husserl, does extensive work in
the faculty is lost). If nothing else, the reader the area of modern philosophy of religion,
can find such a prelude to his later thought most notably on Schleiermacher in these
in Heideggers choice of topicthe doctrine years, and slowly rediscovers Aristotle as a
of categories and meaningas well as in his proto-phenomenologist. In 1916, Heidegger
choice of a text by Duns Scotus/Thomas of gave a lecture course on Kant and 19th
Erfurt: Heidegger explicitly emphasizes his century German philosophy and cotaught

90
HEIDEGGER AND MEDIEVAL PHILOSOPHY

a seminar with the Catholic priest and officiallyhave perceived the values that
scholar Engelbert Krebs about Aristotles the Catholic Middle Ages holds within
logical writings. He only once lectured on itself, values that we are still far from truly
medieval philosophy in the years follow- exploiting,11 he did not continue to exploit
ing his Habilitation. In the winter semester these values. In this letter, he further men-
1915/16, Heidegger gave a lecture course tions that his research into the phenomenol-
on The History of Ancient and Scholastic ogy of religion, which will draw heavily on
Philosophy (there are no written notes left the Middle Ages [. . .] should prove beyond
either from this course or from the Kant and dispute that, even though I have trans-
the Aristotle courses). In 1918 and 1919, formed my basic standpoint, I have refused
Heidegger prepared a lecture course on to be dragged into abandoning my objective
The Philosophical Foundation of Medieval high opinion and regard for the Catholic
Mysticism (GA 60, 30337); but he aban- lifeworld. This promise, however, should
doned the idea of delivering this lecture remain unfulfilled. After 1919, he left his
course. It seems that Heidegger was at some possible career not just as a Catholic phi-
point also preparing, or at least thinking losopher, but also as an expert in medieval
about, a comparative study of Aquinas and philosophy behind.
Scotus;9 but he must have dropped the idea Neither does his lecture courseIntroduction
of such a study relatively early, if he ever fol- into the Phenomenology of Religion, held in
lowed it seriously. the winter semester of 1920/21, seem heavily
One reason for Heideggers loss of interest indebted to the Middle Ages (quite the oppo-
in the medieval tradition may be the influ- site, one can argue, is the case; see GA 60,
ence of Husserl (and of his lack of interest for 3125, 12756). Nor did he not abandon his
the medieval tradition) on him, particularly high opinion and regard for the Catholic
since Husserl took over Rickerts chair at the lifeworld and thus for the medieval world.
University of Freiburg in 1916. There is, how- Under the particular influence of Luther and
ever, another reason that has already been other Protestant theologians, he now strongly
briefly mentioned: The focus of Heideggers emphasized the radical difference between
interest in the late 1910s and early 1920s Christian theology and philosophy and thus
is also closely related to Heideggers reli- also the intrinsic problems of medieval thought
gious crisis, his increasing distance to the as a distinctly Christian kind of thinking that
Catholicism of his youth and its philosophi- did not take this difference seriously. As a con-
cal underpinnings, and the eventual break sequence of this view, the medieval world dis-
with it. In a famous letter to Engelbert Krebs, appeared rapidly from his sight.
written on January 9, 1919, Heidegger There is, however, one important excep-
wrote that the system of Catholicism, that tion (if we disregard two seminars: the
is, particularly the neo-Scholastic system first on High Scholasticism and Aristotle.
of Catholicism, had become problematic Thomas, De ente et essentia, Cajetan, De
and unacceptable to me due to epistemo- nominum analogia, taught during the
logical insights that extend to the theory summer semester of 1924, and the second
of historical knowledge.10 Even though he on On the Ontology of the Middle Ages
confesses that he believe[s] that Iperhaps [Thomas, De ente et essentia, Summa contra
more than those who work on the subject gentiles], taught during the winter semester

91
HEIDEGGER AND MEDIEVAL PHILOSOPHY

of 1924/5; no written notes from these semi- Western philosophy is emphasized (this idea
nars are known). In the winter semester of stands clearly in the background of Being
1926/7, when he was finishing Being and and Time and its thesis of the forgetfulness of
Time, Heidegger gave a lecture course enti- the question of Being in Western philosophy
tled History of Philosophy from Thomas since its very beginning). Second, Heidegger
Aquinas to Kant (see GA 23; during this finds the center of Aquinas thought in the
semester, he offered a seminar on the same doctrine of creation (see 56). This implies, as
topic). The topic and content of this lecture he argues, that philosophy and theology are
course are rather unusual for Heidegger: He extremely closely intertwined in the Middle
discusses not only Aquinas and Descartes (he Ages (see 60f.). First philosophy is therefore
did not reach the goal of examining Kant at for Aquinas, as Heidegger points out, always
any length) but also Spinoza, Leibniz, Wolff, already theology and dependent on the dog-
and Crusius. A note that accompanied the matic presupposition of God (60). What
manuscript of this lecture course suggests was a problem for Aristotle, that is, the rela-
that the topic of the lecture course was due tion between first philosophy and theology,
to a teaching necessity (243), that is to Heidegger argues, is in Aquinas a dogma
say that Heidegger himself did not chose the (ibid.). Heidegger interprets Aquinas
very topic of this lecture course. Given these thought, particularly his concept of truth,
circumstances, it does not surprise that the therefore, as dependent on dogmatic presup-
manuscript of the lecture course shows the positions and thus as eventually falling back
lack of time and enthusiasm on Heideggers behind the ancient philosophy of Aristotle
side in preparing it. (see 63). His later comments on medieval
Nonetheless, this lecture course is an philosophy in general and on Aquinas in
important source for an understanding of particular are, as we will see, variations of
Heideggers view of medieval philosophy in this theme.
the late 1920s. Two important features can
be singled out for special attention: First,
Heidegger discusses Aquinas in the context
of his interest in the origins of modernity Medieval Thought in Being and
and in the development of Western meta- Time
physics. He criticizes the common reading
of Descartes as the first modern thinker and At first sight, medieval thought does not
argues instead that the foundations of moder- play a prominent role at all in Being and
nity were already laid in the medieval period. Time. Aquinas is explicitly mentioned
There is, then, not such a great gap between twice in the very beginning (see SZ, 3/
the medieval world and the modern period BT, 2, where Heidegger refers to Aquinas
as many readings of the history of philoso- Summa theologiae; SZ, 14/BT, 13, where
phy, both the Catholic anti-modernistic and he refers to Aquinas Quaestiones de ver-
the modernistic anti-Catholic, for example, itate and his De natura generis). He notes
suggest. Heidegger also highlights Aquinas that in Aquinas Quaestiones de veritate,
significance for an appropriation and trans- the priority of Dasein over and above all
formation of ancient philosophy so that from other beings, which emerges here without
this perspective the unity of the history of being ontologically clarified, obviously has

92
HEIDEGGER AND MEDIEVAL PHILOSOPHY

nothing in common with a vapid subjectiv- even though there are very important and
izing of the totality of beings (SZ, 14, BT, promising beginnings, more research into the
13).12 This is a rather important statement: Scotist dimension of Being and Time and its
Heidegger seems to read Aquinas as a kind relation to its other dimensions (particularly
of predecessor with respect to his own its Aristotelian, Augustinian, Husserlian, and
view of the ontico-ontological priority of Kantian dimensions) is needed.
Dasein. Heidegger, however, does not exam-
ine this historical link any further in Being
and Time, presumably because of the lack
of ontological clarification in Aquinas and After Being and Time:
also because of the very differences between Philosophy, Christian Faith,
Aquinas thought and the overarching inter- and the Metaphysical Impact
ests of Being and Time (and not the least of Medieval Thought
also because of the dogmatic character of
Aquinas thought). Duns Scotus and Meister In the period after Being and Time, Heidegger
Eckhart (or Thomas of Erfurt for that mat- mentions medieval thought in passing, if at
ter) are not mentioned at all in Being and all. The student of his writings misses a refer-
Time. It is almost as if the history of Western ence to medieval thought particularly in his
thinking between Augustine on the one hand frequent considerations about the course of
and Luther, Calvin, Zwingli, Cajetan, and Western metaphysics and the forgetfulness of
Scaliger (and then Descartes) on the other Being. It is fair to argue that he is now very
did not exist for Heidegger, when he wrote often fully ignorant of medieval thought.
his masterwork. In Introduction to Metaphysics (1935), we
There is, however, a little more to be said, find an explanation for this ignorance that
as there is clearly a Scotist dimension of stands in the tradition of some of his earlier
Being and Time (as there is such a dimen- comments on Aquinas (for this and the fol-
sion in his writings on the way to Being and lowing see EM, 5f., see also 147). It has to
Time). One can argue, for example, that do with his radical emphasis on the differ-
Heideggers fundamental ontology and his ence between theology and faith on the one
existential analysis of Dasein in Being and hand and philosophy on the other. There is,
Time shows an often striking similarity with according to Heidegger, Christian theology,
key ideas of the Scotist tradition such as the but no Christian philosophy (for this view
understanding of, and emphasis on, haeccei- see also NI, 14f.). Philosophy is according
tas (thisness), the priority of possibility over to Heidegger concerned with the ultimate
actuality, or the distinctio formalis. In many why question, the question why there is any-
cases, the Scotist dimension may be mediated thing at all and not rather nothing. However,
through later philosophies so that one has to the believer, as Heidegger argues, for whom
be very careful in determining the extent to the Bible is divine revelation and truth,
which medieval thought had a direct impact has already found an answer to the ultimate
on Being and Time. In other cases, Heidegger why question in the doctrine of creation:
significantly transformed the Scotist tradi- What is, insofar as it is not God himself, has
tion and conflated it with other traditions been created by him. Thus, the believer can-
or ideas. It needs to be said, though, that, not ask the ultimate why question without

93
HEIDEGGER AND MEDIEVAL PHILOSOPHY

abandoning himself as a believer. He is not deserves special attention for his insight in
only pursuing a totally different intellectual the nature of metaphysics. Furthermore, the
enterprise, but lives differently. Faith is there- metaphysical character of Aquinas thought
fore according to Heidegger an own way had in Heideggers view a lasting impact on
of standing in truth with its own safety the history of modern philosophy:
from which the philosopher needs to distance
himself (EM, 4). Thus, as one can conclude Having on the one hand reduced
on the basis of this and other texts, medieval to the ontic determination of
thought is for Heidegger either medieval the- actualitas, and, on the other hand, with
Aquinas, having identified the Summum
ology, substantially dependent on the doc-
Ens with the Ipsum esse, ontology sup-
trine of creation, and, because he no longer
presses every possibility for a question
shared the Christian faith, therefore unin- of being. The entirety of modern phi-
teresting to Heidegger and his concern with losophy is burdened by this ontic stamp
what he considered philosophy proper, or, if it inherited from Christian ontology of the
claims to be philosophy, a misunderstanding middle ages. (GA 15, 311/FS, 25)
of what philosophy ought to be and therefore
even more uninteresting. It remains surpris- This claim about Aquinas, taken as repre-
ing, though, that Heidegger even disregarded sentative of the medieval tradition, explains
medieval contributions to logic, for exam- why medieval thought does not play a role
ple, in his later works. For he did not only for Heidegger any longer. For he is now
know these contributions very well because mainly concerned with the question and the
of his earlier interest in them, they are also history of Being. Furthermore, he had to for-
not simply forms of Christian theology. But get medieval thought as a synthesis of Athens
Heidegger no longer makes the distinctions and both Jerusalem and Rome, as it were, in
that he could, and should, have made with order to save philosophy: To restore phi-
respect to the rich variety of medieval texts. losophy to its own essence means to purge
Even in his work of the 1950s and 1960s it of its Christian element, and to do this out
(when he gave up the radically anti-Christian of concern for the Greek elementnot for
position that characterized some of his writ- its own sake, but insofar as it is the origin of
ings of the 1930s), Heidegger would not philosophy (ibid.).
substantially revise his account of medieval His emphasis on a radical distinction
thought. In a seminar held in Le Thor in 1968, between philosophy and Christianity led
Heidegger discussed the ontological differ- Heidegger to overlook the possibility of an
ence and also examined medieval philosophy encounter with medieval thought from which
in this context. Heidegger emphasized that he may have benefitted. There is, however,
all metaphysics indeed moves within the one important exception: the medieval mys-
difference (this is constantly stressed, in par- tical tradition, most notably Master Eckhart.
ticular by Aquinas), but that no metaphys- In his Country Path, Meister Eckhart is
ics recognizes this difference as difference in the only thinker who is explicitly mentioned
the dimension that it unfolds (GA 15, 310/ (GA 13, 89). Already the Habilitationsschrift
FS, 24). For Heidegger, Aquinas, too, fully shows Heideggers interest in the German
remains in the metaphysical tradition and theologian and mystic (FRS, 160, 344); the
its forgetfulness of Being even though he published version of the public Habilitation

94
HEIDEGGER AND MEDIEVAL PHILOSOPHY

lecture The Concept of Time in the Science modern philosophy, one must pity the fact
of History (35575), stands under a cita- that, after his encounter with the medieval
tion from Meister Eckhart (358).13 There is world in his very early work, Heidegger
no question at all about the high esteem with did not continue to pay similar attention
which Heidegger treated Meister Eckhart to medieval philosophers, theologians, and
during his whole way of thinking (see also mystics. Some of Heideggers students, how-
GA 24, 127f.). In a letter to Bernhard Welte, ever, have reinterpreted the medieval tradi-
written on February 29, 1968, Heidegger tion in the light of his thought. They took
briefly compared Aquinas and Eckhart and Heideggers thought and its challenges seri-
found really a new step in Eckhart.14 ously while at the same time not sharing
According to Heidegger, Meister Eckhart has his very critical, if not even often dismiss-
a unique position because a sentence such ive attitude toward medieval thought. The
as Sed etiam Deus quod Deo non convenit group of these thinkers includes what one
esse nec est ens, sed est aliquid altius ente could call the Catholic Heidegger school of
[...] cannot be found anywhere else as far as notable figures such as Johannes B. Lotz,
I know.15 In arguing that God is something Gustav Siewerth, and, to a different degree,
higher than (a) being and that Being does Karl Rahner and Hans Urs von Balthasar.
not belong to him, nor is he a being, Meister Bernhard Welte, too, belongs to this group
Eckhart, not Aquinas (as Welte suggested16), of mediators between Heideggers thought
shows for Heidegger a hidden agenda that and the medieval tradition. Welte wrote
points beyond metaphysics, that is, to the not only an essay about Thomas Aquinas
possibility of an alternative to metaphysics. and Heideggers Idea of the History of
Heidegger therefore encouraged an exten- Being (this is one of many essays about
sive account of the problem of Being in Heideggers thought that he wrote), he
Thomas Aquinas and Meister Eckhart.17 also wrote a book-length study of Meister
All important differences notwithstand- Eckhart that clearly shows the influence of
ing, there is no doubt that Meister Eckhart Heidegger on his own thought and meth-
is one important (not the only) source of odological self-understanding.18 Many more
Heideggers own later discourse about scholars could be mentioned who have
letting-be as a way beyond the metaphysic continued the dialogue between the medi-
of the will to power (see particularly GA 16, eval world and Heideggers thought. In the
51729; see also GA 77). Heidegger did not, English-speaking context, John Caputos
however, examine Meister Eckharts writings early work on Heidegger and Aquinas and
with the kind of scrutiny that characterizes on Heidegger and mystical thinking may
his writings on other important thinkers. be singled out for special reference.19 More
work can, and should, be done along these
lines. The question of Heideggers relation to
medieval thought and of his legacy for our
Reading and discussing medieval reading of medieval texts not only remains
thoughtafter Heidegger open, it is one of the most challenging (even
though often unnoticed) questions both for
Given the significance of Heideggers inter- students of medieval thought and for stu-
pretation of the history of ancient and dents of Heideggers way of thinking.

95
HEIDEGGER AND MEDIEVAL PHILOSOPHY

NOTES AND REFERENCES Way of Thought. Critical and Interpretative


Signposts, ed. Alfred Denker and Marion Heinz
1
The number of secondary sources on Heideggers (New York/London: Continuum, 2002), 10136.
relation to medieval thought is limited. The 8
Martin Heidegger, Vita, in Theodore Kisiel and
following studies or collections of essays are Thomas Sheehan (eds), Becoming Heidegger.
particularly helpful (and contain further bib- On the Trail of His Early Occasional Writings,
liographical references to earlier works on this 19101927 (Evanston, IL: Northwestern
topic): Sean McGrath, The Early Heidegger and University Press, 2007), 1069, 107 (GA 16,
Medieval Philosophy. Phenomenology for the 415, 42). See also 79 (GA 16, 379).
Godforsaken (Washington, DC: The Catholic 9
See his letter to Martin Grabmann, written on
University of America Press, 2006); Constantino January 7, 1917, in Denker et al., Heidegger
Esposito (ed.), Heidegger e i medievali. Atti del und die Anfnge seines Denkens, 734, esp. 74.
colloquio internazionale, Cassino 10/13 maggio 10
Denker et al., Heidegger und die Anfnge
2000 (Turnhout: Brepols, 2001); Helmuth Vetter, seines Denkens, 67/Kisiel and Sheehan (eds),
Heidegger und das Mittelalter. Wiener Tagungen Becoming Heidegger, 96.
zur Phnomenologie 1997 (Frankfurt am Main: 11
Theodore Kisiel and Thomas Sheehan (eds),
Peter Lang, 1999). Becoming Heidegger, 96.
2
SZD, 8190, esp. 81Here and in the following, 12
For this see also Kisiel, The Genesis of
all translations, if not otherwise indicated, are Heideggers Being and Time, 426f.
my own. 13
For an English translation see Kisiel and
3
For the early Heideggers life and thought see Sheehan (eds), Becoming Heidegger, 6172.
particularly Alfred Denker, Hans-Helmuth 14
Martin Heidegger and Bernhard Welte, Briefe
Gander and Holger Zaborowski (eds), und Begegnungen. Mit einem Vorwort von
Heidegger und die Anfnge seines Denkens. Bernhard Casper, herausgegeben von Alfred
Heidegger-Jahrbuch 1 (Freiburg/Mnchen: Karl Denker und Holger Zaborowski (Stuttgart:
Alber, 2004). Klett-Cotta, 2003), 29
4
Martin Heidegger, Frhe Schriften (Frankfurt 15
Ibid.
am Main: Klosterman, 1972), 1129. Hereafter 16
In his Thomas von Aquin und Heideggers
cited as FRS, followed by page number. Gedanke von der Seinsgeschichte (1967), in
5
For the Scotist dimension of the early Bernhard Welte, Denken in Begegnung mit den
Heideggers thought see Theodore Kisiel, Denkern II. HegelNietzscheHeidegger,
The Genesis of Heideggers Being and Time eingefhrt und bearbeitet von Holger
(Berkeley: University of California Press, Zaborowski, Freiburg, Basel (Wien: Herder,
1995); Sean J. McGrath, The Early Heidegger 2007), 13955, particularly 145ff.
and Medieval Philosophy, 88119; Sean J. 17
Heidegger and Welte, Briefe und
McGrath, Die scotistische Phnomenologie Begegnungen, 30.
des jungen Heidegger, in Alfred Denker, 18
Bernhard Welte, Meister Eckhart. Gedanken
Hans-Helmuth Gander and Holger Zaborowski zu seinen Gedanken (2nd edition, 1992), in
(eds), Heidegger und die Anfnge seines Bernhard Welte, Denken in Begegnung mit
Denkens. Heidegger-Jahrbuch 1 (Freiburg/ den Denkern I. Meister EckhartThomas von
Mnchen: Karl Alber, 2004), 24358. AquinBonaventura, eingefhrt und bearbe-
6
See Martin Grabmann, Die Entwicklung der itet von Markus Enders, Freiburg, Basel (Wien:
mittelalterlichen Sprachlogik [Tractatus de Herder, 2007), 21215. Welte mentions that,
modis significandi], Philosophisches Jahrbuch when he last met Heidegger on January 14,
35 (1922), 12135, 199214 (for a revised 1976, a few months before Heidegger died, he
and expanded version see Martin Grabmann, and Heidegger spoke primarily and forcefully
Mittelalterliches Geistesleben. Abhandlungen about the thing of Meister Eckhart (21).
zur Geschichte der Scholastik und Mystik 19
John Caputo, The Mystical Element in
(Mnchen: Max Hber, 1926), 10446). Heideggers Thought (Athens: Ohio University
7
For an insightful discussion see Theodore Kisiel, Press, 1978); Heidegger and Aquinas. An Essay
Why Students of Heidegger Will Have to Read on Overcoming Metaphysics (New York:
Emil Lask, in Theodore Kisiel, Heideggers Fordham University Press, 1982).

96
10
Heidegger and Descartes
Emilia Angelova

Heidegger shifts between two contrasting manner in which the self and the subject is,
interpretations of Descartes. While discus- comports itself in the world: And this sum
sion around the time of the project of fun- is not taken in the ontological indifference
damental ontology emphasizes rather the in which Descartes and his successors took
unavoidable ambiguity of Descartes views, it, as the extantness of a thinking thing. Sum
the later texts (the courses on Nietzsche, here is the assertion of the basic constitution
What is a Thing?, The Age of the World of my being: I-am-in-the-world and therefore
Picture, the final seminars) more clearly I am capable of thinking it (ibid.).
express a critique of the extreme subjectiv- The modern epoch marks the conscious
ism of the Cartesian system and Cartesian reversion of the ego, an orientation that
method. Reception dates since the early determines the philosophical tradition,
lecture course 19212 in Freiburg1 and and beginning with Descartes, starts from
the Prolegomena from summer 1925 in the ego, the subject (GA 24, 1734/123).
Marburg, into the best known engagements Heidegger finds himself at odds with the
from Being and Time (esp. sections 6, 10, modern epochs return to the subject, since
18b21, 43) and in 1927, Basic Problems a critical appropriation will only show that
of Phenomenology (esp. sections 11, 12, and how Descartes leaped over the subject
13a,15a). (2201/155). The onset of a philosophical
From Prolegomena, Descartes figure revolution of modern philosophy in the end
looms large, symptomatic of the forgetting was not a revolution at all (175/124), caus-
of Being that marks the modern epoch itself: ing disappointment in two ways. One, taking
he is the example of the passing over of the over Descartes classical ontology is a chal-
phenomenon of the worldhood of the world lenge standing before Heidegger and his con-
(GA 20, 2301/171). The sum is the mode temporaries. Modern philosophy allegedly
of being, which as such orientates a turning revived, as the contemporaries claim, has only
around to the subject, and yet: It is not the been one-sidedly appropriated. So Heidegger
cogito sum which formulates a primary find- finds disturbing the historical construction
ing but rather sum cogito (296/216). As will of the Neo-Kantianism of recent decades,
be critically clarified, the sum cogito is dis- which heralds Descartes as the foundation
closive rather of Daseins being as a mode of with which a completely new epoch of phi-
interpretationit is a determination of the losophy begins. He cautions against a total

97
HEIDEGGER AND DESCARTES

turnabout centered on philosophy of the function for making possible an adequately


ego, including Husserl: through to contem- founded ontological inquiry in general). The
porary phenomenology in Husserls Ideen I, gleaned problematic of Being in Descartes
philosophy remains precisely one-sidedly hence undergoes a threefold reworking: the
subjectivist, in the form in which Descartes basic ways of being, which are the being of
expressed it: res cogitansres extensa (175 nature (res extensa); the being of mind (res
6/1245). Two, Descartes own relationship cogitans); and the subjects way of being,
to the predecessors is steeped in ambivalence. which now becomes an ontological prob-
Descartes works within the tradition, namely, lem (174/123). The findings give the clue
the ancient metaphysics of God, soul, and to the intentional structure of [Daseins]
nature, back to Plato, and basic ontological comportments and the understanding of
concepts, drawn directly from Suarez, Duns being at each time immanent in each com-
Scotus, and Thomas Aquinas. Heidegger portment, and as well, the question of the
praises the heightened sensitivity to the unity meaning of actuality, or of thingness and
of the subject that preserves continuity with actualityfor they enable the questioner
the metaphysics of substance (see discussion to ask about the constitution of the being
16573/11723): an ontology of nature to which in each instance the comportment
leads Descartes to conceive of the subject comports: the perceived of perception in its
for ancient ontology the ontologically exem- perceivedness, the product (producible) of
plary entity . . . is nature in the broadest sense production in its producedness (173/122).
(173/123). Still, modern philosophy works From Being and Time, Descartes opens
only on the ancient metaphysical problems, certain distinctive domains of Being: The
even the newly posed problems were posed ego cogito of Descartes, the subject, the I,
and treated on the foundation of the old and reason, spirit, person; even as he fails to
everything in principle remained as it was; determine the ontological foundation of
and yet, this inertia notwithstanding modern subjectivity and leaves uninterrogated,
philosophy nevertheless marked and accen- according to it, the categorial content
tuated the subject: shifting the distinction of substance (GA 2, 22/44). The project of
between subject and object in some way to fundamental ontology dictates but a new
the center, in conceiving with greater pen- reversion, one directed outside of the ego
etration the peculiar nature of subjectivity If the cogito sum is to serve as the point
(175/124). of departure for the existential analytic of
Heidegger engages Descartes on imma- Dasein, then it needs to be turned around:
nent critical grounds. In the 1920s Heidegger when it is turned around, the sum is then
takes over the fundamental-ontological ori- asserted first, and indeed in the sense that
entation to the subject, awakening the prob- I am in the world (211/254). Crucially,
lematic of the self and the modern subject, it is the mode of Being that determines the
and awakening philosophy itself: arriving existential structure of the entity of Dasein
at an understanding of Being, it neces- opening up the I am to more than thought:
sarily looks back to the Dasein (172/122). As such an entity, I am in the possibility
Recognizing Descartes primary findings of Being toward various ways of comport-
demands that Heidegger takes aim at a prob- ing myselfnamely, cogitationesas ways
lem of principle (i.e. Daseins distinctive of Being alongside entities within-the-world

98
HEIDEGGER AND DESCARTES

(ibid.). Descartes is a possible ally but only if structure of the ancient conception of Being
we recall that spatiality is manifestly one of (GA 2, 245/46; also see GA 24, 1513/108).
the constituents of entities-within-the-world, Heidegger here neglectspace Descartes
then in the end the Cartesian analysis of the and the medieval tradition debatethat
world can still be rescued (101/134). The since production means always producing
turn to the subject is to be rescued but something from something, material, the
one has to carry it through primarily out implied issue that remains is the assimilation
of fundamental-ontological motives, thus of creation to production. The homogeniza-
against Descartes analysis that cogitationes tion of the two domains (GA 24, 167/118)
are present-at-hand, and that in these the ego tracks back to the interpretation of Being:
is present-at-hand too as a worldless res cogi- Nevertheless, the question remains whether
tans (211/254). the whole universe [as Leibniz also asks] of
Strikingly Heidegger disengages Descartes beings is exhausted by the present-at-hand;
from the dogmatism of the Middle Ages and and [T]he Dasein, which in each instance we
Greek influence, on the issue of produced- ourselves are, is just that to which all under-
nessin what way are subject and object dis- standing of being-at-hand, actuality, must be
tinguished ontologically? Clearly, Descartes traced back (169/119).3 The medieval inter-
depends on the ancient-medieval classical pretation of Being, which orients Descartes
ontology, he posits the inherited concept of (the implantation of a baleful prejudice
realitas and this becomes a first and main (GA 2, 25/46)), is not radical enough: to
point of Heideggers distancing, as we note in take up reductively res cogitans as ens crea-
section 43: Care is the meaning of the real.2 tum just means to close off the subject and
But despite faithfulness to medieval thought, its ontology of production.4 A radicalized
Descartes novel foundation of idealism Descartes emerges out of this critique: All
strikes a kinship rather with the meaning entities other than God need to be produced
of just what Greek ontology already thinks in the widest sense and also to be sustained
in its deepest underlying presuppositions. (92/125).
Descartes understands what takes place in Being and Time infamously charges
Christianitys ex nihilo creation to be ideas Descartes with evasion of the question
inscribed in the Greek ontology of produc- of Being (94/126), a failure to master the
tion (see GA 24, 14975/10621). Descartes basic problem of Being and the ontologi-
gestures to the projective understanding of cal difference (94/127), above all targeting
existential life that is the subjects doing/ Descartes ambiguous reception of ancient
thinking; he grasps that projection is always ontology, it kept later generations from
already underway. And yet, while he agrees making any thematic ontological analytic
that the division into ens increatum and of the mind (25/46). And yet Heidegger
creatum is decisive (115/82), Heideggers will demonstrate that Being is included in
account of this division runs on very dif- each case in phenomenologically elaborat-
ferent reasons than Descartes seemingly ing expressions underlying Descartes utmost
new beginning and radical way: But concern, such as God is and the world
createdness [Geschaffenheit] in the widest is. As Heidegger claims, the clue to the
sense of somethings having been produced existential-ontological problematic tracks
[Hergestelltheit], was an essential item in the back but to the scholastic tradition, which

99
HEIDEGGER AND DESCARTES

first places beyond debate the positive sense From here to Heideggers existential analytic
in which Being signifies (93/126). Despite is a short distance: Existence, the Being of
problems lost, there remains in Descartes the entity which is Dasein, is the constitution
nevertheless an ontology of the world on whose basis Beings own interpretation
(89/122) and a characterization of the prob- appears. The substantiality of substance
lem of Being. He preserved the difference Heideggers expression for the Being of being
of Being, albeit in evasion, for he continued that is veiled in Descartes, and whose corre-
to enunciateto repeat, not to alteran late is the theory of preeminent attributes
equivocation: the meaning of is, existence, is able to be grasped only on the basis of
cannot be the same for God and for created definite characteristics of the entities under
things. consideration [seiende Bestimmtheiten des
In a large sense, Heidegger elaborates betreffenden Seienden]attributes (94/127).
Descartes question: How can the meaning This is why he says: the expression substan-
be the same for a created entity that is and tia functions sometimes with a signification
for God who also is? The emphasis is on which is ontological, sometimes with one
same, for Descartes shows that the eluci- which is ontical, but mostly with one which is
dation of substantiality applies to two kinds hazily ontico-ontological (94/ 127). Notably,
of thingsres cogitans or thinking things, Descartes ought to conceive of the being of
and res extensa or corporeal things. It even the subject, res cogitans, within the horizon
applies to three kinds of substancesof of substance:
God, too, we admit that he is (93/126). So
Heidegger reiterates: The name substance To determine the nature of the res corpo-
is not appropriate to God and to these uni- rea ontologically, we must explicate the
vocally, as they say in the schools; that is, no substance of this entity as a substance
that is, its substantiality. What makes up
signification of this name which would be
the authentic Being-in-itself [das eigentli-
common to both God and his creation can
che An-ihm-selbst-sein] of the res cor-
be distinctly understood (ibid.). It is here porea? How is it at all possible to grasp
that one must investigate into the holding off a substance as such, that is, to grasp its
of meaning: the withdrawal of the mean- substantiality? (90/123)
ing of Being which the idea of substantial-
ity embraces behind the entity (ibid.). The Descartes opposes res extensa to res cogi-
inaccessibility of substance that withholds tans, claiming that res cogitans is better
meaningsubstance is not clarified, it can- known, and even conceives of the Being of
not be clarifiedattests to the impossibility the subject, res cogitans, on the model of res
that substance be discovered merely from the extensa: On the contrary, [Descartes] takes
fact that it is a thing that exists. By itself the Being of Dasein (to whose basic con-
alone substance, as Descartes knows, does stitution Being-in-the-world belongs) in the
not affect us. very same way as he takes the Being of res
Heidegger thus aptly translates Descartes: extensanamely, as substance (98/131).
Being itself does not affect us, and therefore The model of res extensa is constitutive of
cannot be perceived (94/127). Focus shifts the substantiality of matter, res corporea.
to an infinite difference of Being (93/126) Taking over this reasoning critically (the
that separates finite being and infinite being. ancient ontology of Nature), Heidegger

100
HEIDEGGER AND DESCARTES

rescues the indispensable presupposition that a thing equates to an idea in which Being
res cogitans, the ego cogito, is disclosive but is equated with constant presence-at-hand
out of the basic principles of determination [stndige Vorhandenheit] (96/1289): this
of Worldhood (sections 19 and 20). The is how (anticipating Kant) Descartes firmly
promised phenomenological destruction of prescribes for the world its real Being.
the cogito sum, which was never published, In summary, Being and Time directs its criti-
will have justified this analysis.5 cisms against the ways in which the Being of
Descartes, then, positively prepares ways of the world remains covered over and veiled
the grounding of the interpretation of Being. in the concept of substantialityDescartes
(1) Sensible qualities, reduced in their ontical does not let what entities within-the-world
properties alone, are not sufficient to define the they themselves might have been permit-
substantiality of the res corporea (e.g. force, ted to present. The Cartesian circle (between
hardness, smell, coldness of bodies, as in the I am and God is) revisited, Heidegger
example of the piece of wax, as was discussed remarkably argues that res extensa emerge as
by the second meditation and Principles of a horizon of meaning already in the world:
Philosophy). Descartes is oriented ontologi- world founds existence upon Being, in the
cally by these principles: Sensatio (aisthe- same way in which entities of the present-to-
sis), as opposed to intellectio, still remains hand, Vorhandenheit, found upon the
possible as a way of access to entities by a Being-in-the-world of the I am.
beholding which is perceptual in character In the mid-1930s, starting with the lecture
(96/129). (2) The preeminent attribute of res courses on Nietzsche, Heidegger palpably
corporea (subsuming the substantial property shifts the tone, perhaps in recognition as well
that belongs most preeminently to the partic- of his own growing awareness of the diffi-
ular substance) is extension, but this means culty of twisting free from subjectivity. Not
that for the integrity of the body it is the prop- even a doubt is left that in Nietzsches doc-
erty that is presupposed by all else: For eve- trine of the Overman, Descartes celebrates
rything else that can be ascribed to the body his supreme triumph (Nietzsche, vol. IV:
presupposes extension. That is, extension is Nihilism, 28).6 And even so, in typical man-
positively distinct, remains intelligible, after ner, ambiguity remains:
everything else has been removed; the modes
of extension retained in this logic anticipate No matter how sharply Nietzsche pits
Kantian conditions of possibility (92/125). himself time and again against Descartes,
Res extensa constitute the substantiality of whose philosophy grounds modern met-
aphysics, he turns against Descartes only
the res corporea, providing to this entity the
because the latter still does not posit man
possibility of substantiality. (3) The intel-
as subiectum in a way that is complete
lect is the privileged mode of access to enti- and decisive enough. The representation
ties, on the model of mathematical-physical of the subiectum as ego, the I, thus the
knowledge. But in grasping the nature of egoistic interpretation of the subiec-
the body, of which only the understanding is tum, is still not subjectivist enough for
able, intellectio is mathematical knowledge: Nietzsche. (ibid., 28)
apprehending entities which can always
give assurance that their Being has been In Nietzschedespite attention, as Heidegger
securely grasped (95/128). Securely grasping continues to hold back, on a conception

101
HEIDEGGER AND DESCARTES

of anthropology as the metaphysics of Foundations of Logic, Heidegger recollects that


man, and the more essential content to be it attempted to come to terms with Leibniz
. . .; and also recollects that the course in
detected in referrals to cosmos, beings as
Marburg 19234 sought to adopt a corre-
a wholethe very essence of modern meta- sponding position with regard to Descartes;
physics becomes a psychology. It assigns this latter [position] that was then incorpo-
to man the basic character of being: in a rated into Sein und Zeit (sections 1921). As
definite preeminence man becomes the meas- Jean-Luc Marion, Bernasconi, and others note,
there may be a stronger and more sustained
ure and center of beings, and in this subjec-
discussion of Aristotle and Kant, but Descartes
tivist interpretation of subiectum man is at is no secondary figure for Heidegger, the
the bottom of all objectification and rep- reception Husserl-Descartes is a preoccupation
resentability (ibid.). Western history culmi- from the beginning, and to the very end. For
nates, or consummates the truth of Being Heidegger on Descartes, including in the Thor
Seminars (1969), the Zringen Seminar (1973),
in the doctrine of the will to power. To hear
and 1974 text Der Fehl heiliger Namen
transformatively the sending or Schickung (The lack of sacred names), see Marion
of Being, what now calls for thinking, need in Critical Heidegger, 6796. Marion offers
is to attend more carefully to how and that a more original interpretation of Descartes
the Cartesian Meditations on man as and Heidegger stressing the proximity with
Husserl (and Levinas) along alterity and
subiectum7 is the path to the fundamental
ethics: So Heidegger does not question the
problems of metaphysics implying nothing ego cogito with regard to the primacy of its
less than the way in which man is historical cognitive origin but rather the ontological
(ibid., 29)not an extrinsic form of commu- indeterminateness of the esse, that which it
nication, therefore, but a nihilism, inher- conceals from view rather than that which it
proclaims (69). Marions further explana-
ently viewed as a configuration of the will to
tion of why Descartes left undetermined and
power, as the occurrence in which man is his- undiscussed the meaning of Being, is found
torical (ibid., 28) (i.e. the question of the in: Sur le prisme metaphysique de Descartes
psychical what is living, in that particular (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1986),
sense of life that determines becoming as will 17780. Also see F.-W. Herrmann, Husserl und
die Meditationen des Descartes (Frankfurt,
to power (ibid.).8
Vittorio Klostermann,1971). Along similar
lines with Marion, but different, see Robert
Bernasconi, Heidegger in Question (New
NOTES AND REFERENCES Jersey: Humanities Press, 1993), 15070.
2
Of course as long as Dasein is (that is, only as
1
For Heideggers earliest engagement see, long as an understanding of Being is ontically
GA 61: Phenomenological Interpretations possible), is there Being [es gibt Sein] (GA2,
of Aristotle, English trans. Rojcewicz. 212/255). A footnote to this passage points out
This confrontation develops in Der that in Letter on Humanism Heidegger will
Beginn der Neuzeitlichen Philosophie (WS insist that es gibt here is used deliberately
19234)/Introduction to Modern Philosophy. [f]or the it which here gives is Being itself.
As Marion (68) observes, here for Heidegger, The gives, however, designates the essence of
Descartes already poses the question of Being . . .
the mode of being of the sum, precisely in 3
And even if creation out of nothing is nothing
overlooking it in favour of a question about identical with producing something out of a
the status and the power of the ego. Support material that is found already on hand, nev-
for this comes from Wegmarken, GA 9, 79: ertheless, this creating of the creation has the
about the course in SS 1928, The Metaphysical general ontological character of producing....

102
HEIDEGGER AND DESCARTES

as if ancient ontology in its foundations and F.-W. Herrmann, Kunst und Technik (Frankfurt:
basic concepts were cut to fit the Christian Klostermann, 1989), 10923.
world-view (GA 24, 168/11819). 7
Heideggers critique of Descartes is directed
4
Heidegger claims, Our Interpretation will not much more against the successors, the ones
only prove that Descartes had neglected the who have developed a metaphysics of subjectiv-
question of Being altogether; it will also show ity. See, for example, GA 24, 178/127, 217/153;
why he came to suppose that the absolute see Nietzsche vol. ii, 48; also Nietzsche vol. iv,
Being-Certain [Gewisssein] of the cogito 179, where the link with Leibniz is made clear:
exempted him from raising the question of the Descartes metaphysics is indeed a metaphys-
meaning of Being which this entity possesses ics of will to power (. . . Leibniz begins the
(GA 2, 24/46). interpretation of subiectum (substantia as
5
For more on Heideggers critique, appropriation monas)). From the late lecture on Kant, What
and interpretation of Descartes, see Franois is a Thing? of 19356, comes the verdict on
Raffoul, Heidegger and the Subject, trans. Descartes: at best it is only a bad novel, and
David Pettigrew and Gregory Recco (Amherst: anything but a story in which the movement of
Humanity Books, 1998), 5470; P. Ricoeur, Le Being becomes visibleciting from the revised
conflit des interprtations (Paris: Seuil, 1969), translation by David Farrell Krell, appearing in
22232; trans. The Conflict of Interpretations, BW, 298 ff.
ed. D. Ihde (Evanston: Northwestern, 1974), 8
From the early period onwards, Heidegger
22335. Also see Jean-Luc Nancy, Mundus est returns to Descartes as the one who initiates the
fabula, Ego sum (Paris: Flammarion, 1979), shift toward modern mathematical physics in
95127; trans. Daniel Brewer, Mundus est modern philosophy, which shift is continually
fabula, MLN 93.4, 1978, 63553. stressed everywhere; this return is even more
6
A sustained new reading of Descartes begins incessant in the later texts. Even so, what can-
here, to continue to the very end. This new not be stressed enough is that the ambiguity of
tone marks the lectures on European Nihilism, critique will remain, notably in QT, AWP
in Nietzsche volume iv, esp. in Sections 1321. (Holzwege, GA 5, 1089 (n. 9)), and to the very
Heidegger grows increasingly aware of this last texts. See also 193646, Verwindung der
need, as he himself sees Being and Time as Metaphysik, in Vortrge und Aufstze, I, 65.
more Cartesian and more bound to subjectivity This completes the remaking of Descartes as a
than he realized. See J. Taminiaux, Heidegger thinker (with Leibniz) in the subjectivist tradi-
lecteur de Descartes, in ed. W. Biemel and tion of cogito me cogitare (rem).

103
11
Heidegger and Kant: Three
Guiding Questions
Frank Schalow

Because the philosophies of Martin Heidegger mode of expression governing his exchange
and Immanuel Kant are of legendary com- with Kant. In his lecture-course on Heraclitus
plexity, unraveling the Auseinandersetzung (1943), Heidegger suggests that his radical
between them poses an enormous challenge. reinterpretation of transcendental philosophy
In Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics hinges on first translating the Critique (GA
(1929), Heidegger emphasizes the violence 55, 63). In other words, the reciprocal interest
of his interpretation of Kants Critique of Pure each thinker has in temporality will provide
Reason. Rather than provide an authoritative a crossing, allowing Heidegger to transpose
commentary of this work, Heidegger under- the key motifs of Kants thought within a
takes a destructive-retrieval of transcenden- broader, ontological context and thereby
tal philosophy, in order to elicit its unsaid amplify the question of being. Conversely,
ontological implications for re-asking the by appropriating Kants thinking in terms of
question of being (GA 3, 249/KPM, 175). He his own, Heidegger underscores the original-
thereby brings to fruition his earlier revela- ity of his project, and consequently recasts
tion that Kant opened my eyes to how tem- his hermeneutic inquiry of Being and Time
porality makes possible our understanding of within a wider historical orbit. The inaugu-
being and yields the idioms for its expression ral of three questions shaping Heideggers
(GA 25, 430/PICPR, 292). Yet, in order to exchange with Kant emerges into the fore-
develop parallels between Kants thinking and ground. First, what are the key steps by
his own, Heidegger must first cross a termi- which Heidegger transposes the Critique and
nological gulf separating them. The language allows it to become a sounding board to
that provides a common thread between echo the central themes of Being and Time?
these two thinkers develops, on the one hand, Second, why did Heidegger appeal to Kants
the reciprocal concern each places on human account of schematism, in order to develop
finitude, and, on the other, makes possible the unspoken connection between being and
beings disclosure through temporality. temporality? Third, how does Heidegger con-
In retrospect, Heidegger provides the key tinue to develop his conversation with Kant
to developing this language and thereby in light of the turning and the transition of
cracking the code of a complementary thinking to the other beginning?

105
HEIDEGGER AND KANT

I a common origin. By arising from this origin,


the categories acquire their power to signify
Ironically, the central philosophical issue that the universal determinations of any possible
Heidegger embraced, namely, the question object. If it can be shown that our tempo-
of being, assumed only peripheral impor- ral finitude constitutes this origin, then time
tance to Kant. When in 1929 Heidegger titles must also provide the key for understanding
his seminal work Kant and the Problem of and expressing what is first in universality,
Metaphysics, it is not metaphysics that consti- that is, being. A clue is then given to the hid-
tutes this problematic conventionally under- den reciprocity between being and temporal-
stood. In questioning metaphysics, Kant asks ity, such that the latter not only provides the
about its possibility, while emphasizing possibility for our understanding the former
that it is a natural predisposition of human but also yields the vocabulary for expressing
nature. Kants attempt to root the problem its meaning.
of metaphysics in human finitude provides The manner in which we can speak of
Heidegger with a springboard to his own being with words that exhibit a tempo-
methodological innovation, namely, that the ral character, simultaneously suggests that
inquiry into being is inextricably interwoven there is an inherent dynamic to being and its
with who raises it. Accordingly, that inquiry capacity for self-manifestation. Our under-
must proceed by examining the inquirers standing as well must also unfold within a
capacity to understand being, in such a way temporal arc, in order to project the horizon
that the crucial philosophical problematic upon-which (worhaufin) being can mani-
becomes: how is an understanding of being fest itself and thereby convey its meaning.
(Seinsverstndnis) possible? The concern for The universality of any concept of being must
possibility not only points back to the inti- be wedded to the singularity of its manifesta-
mate connection between metaphysics and tion, in order that its meaning can be trans-
human nature but also how our capac- mitted and disclosed through language. The
ity to understand is shaped, structured, and so-called problem of metaphysics, to which
developed by our temporal finitude. our finitude is central, transforms itself into
Kant coined the term Copernican revo- a hermeneutic concern in the most origi-
lution to describe his innovative approach nary way. That is, in its etymology herme-
to philosophy, which for Heidegger poses the neutics stems from Hermes, the messenger or
subsequent challenge of unfolding the circu- go-between. In this originary sense, herme-
lar dynamic of our understanding. For Kant, neutics renders meaningful what is otherwise
the Copernican revolution seeks in human arcane, elusive, and indeterminate, thereby
finitude a new axis to anchor the possibil- opening up a new horizon for finite, human
ity of human understanding/knowledge and understanding. Due to our finitude (and the
thereby delineate its preconditions (i.e. for fact that being withdraws from disclosure),
determining what can be known as a possible our understanding must be constructed on the
object). The centering of knowledge in this basis of this intermediary or go-between. In
way suggests (to Heidegger) that whatever undertaking a destructive-retrieval of Kants
the content of its categorial determinations transcendental philosophy, Heidegger unveils
may be, they (i.e. in Kantian terminology, the temporality as this basis, that is, as holding
pure concepts or categories) must derive from the key to the transmission of its meaning

106
HEIDEGGER AND KANT

and determination in words. In harmony a temporal or transcendental science (GA


with the dynamic of beings manifestation, 24, 466/BP, 327). With this statement, he
the meaning of being must be conveyed in brings Kants sense of the transcendental, as a
equally concrete terms, that is, through tem- way of considering the preconditions for the
poral idioms.1 knowers passing over to encounter what
Can we identify specific texts, in con- is knowable, in line with his own: the ecstatic
junction with his reading of Kant, by which trajectory of projecting forth the horizon for
Heidegger begins to develop this hermeneutic any understanding of being. In either case
breakthrough? In his 1925 lecture-course the movement of going beyond, or sur-
Platos Sophist, Heidegger provides an passing to, is propelled by the whereto of
important clue to the role that time plays temporality. As Heidegger illustrates in Basic
in formulating the question of being and Problems, the act of finite transcendence
in suggesting a vocabulary to express its equals temporality, that is, as the ecstatic
meaning. He characterizes being as a horizon upon-which to project (the under-
tense-word (Zeitwort), specifically point- standing of) being, and thereby formulate a
ing to the grammar of a distinctive linguis- logos in harmony with the singularity of its
tic practice, the declension of the verb to be disclosure. With this observation, Heideggers
(GA 19, 592/PS, 410). In The Basic Problems initial strategy for translating the Critique
of Phenomenology (1927), in which his of Pure Reason becomes evident: that is, ren-
interpretation of Kant begins to take center dering Kants transcendental philosophy (of
stage, Heidegger states that all proposi- knowledge) into a phenomenological ontol-
tions of ontology are temporal propositions ogy (of the possibility of understanding being
(GA 24 460/BP, 323). With this remark, he via the lens of temporality).
illustrates the double role that temporal- Throughout Kant and the Problem of
ity assumes both in shaping the possibility Metaphysics, Heidegger translates the key
of our understanding of being, and in dic- motifs of transcendental philosophy into
tating the grammar for its expression. This terms commensurate with his own inquiry
grammar must heed the verbal form to be, into being. In order to implement this strat-
that is, in a way that calls forth the unique egy, Heidegger reconstructs Kants account
temporal idioms that evoke the dynamic of of schematism or the procedure (Verfahren)
beings manifestation. Only when the inquiry for graphically depicting the meaning of the
into being reaches this level of concreteness, categories in temporal terms.2 As Heidegger
and develops a logos in concert with the states in Being and Time: Kant is the first
dynamics of beings manifestation, can an and only one who traversed a stretch of the
ontology or the science of being arise that is path toward investigating the dimension
truly phenomenological. Conversely, this of temporality [Temporalitt]or allowed
phenomenological ontology retains its tran- himself to be driven there by the compelling
scendental ancestry, precisely by accenting force of the phenomena themselves (GA
the temporal determinations or the lexicon 2, 32/BT, 22). With this directive, we then
of being, which incorporates human finitude proceed to the second question: why did
as its central problematic. Heidegger appeal to schematism in order to
As Heidegger states at the conclusion of establish the connection between being and
the Basic Problems, ontology is essentially temporality?

107
HEIDEGGER AND KANT

II possibility of understanding being in gen-


eral, and its origin in temporality. For Kant,
Heidegger recognized that while metaphys- the temporal character of our finitude yields
ics has persistently overlooked the question the common root for legitimately employ-
of being, the withdrawal of that concern ing the categories. The role of schematism
also preserves the possibility of renewing is to uncover this deeper temporal origin,
interest in it. For him, Kants transcenden- and thereby uproot reason in favor of a
tal philosophy harbored the vestige of such new form of creativity for engendering the
a point of departure, the opportunity for a nuances, distinctions, and determinations of
hermeneutic foothold in lieu of all other the categories, that is, the power of imagina-
foundations, for example, God, reason, the tion. Heidegger was attracted to schematism
I think, or even the consummation of all because of these radical implications, but
these metaphysical positions in the Hegelian most of all because of its tactical role in
absolute. Only given such a foothold would developing a new linguistic usage or gram-
it be possible to address the possibility of mar for the categories, which could elicit
metaphysics, and begin to map the histori- a common root of determination from a
cal landscape for re-asking the question of pre-predicative source, that is, the synthesis
being in terms of the dynamic of temporal- of time. In this regard, to follow the path of
ity (GA 25, 427/PICPR, 289). When viewed translating the Critique of Pure Reason
within this wider context, Heidegger turns is to reach the archway of a crossing, the
to Kantian schematism; for it is the first and trans-literating, iconic power of imagina-
foremost harbinger of this multidimensional tion (Einbildungskraft) through which time
dynamic of beings manifestation, the sign- emerges as the figure to transcribe pure con-
post along the way to its hidden reciprocity cepts into a distinctly ontological vocabu-
with temporality, such that there is being lary, that is, words capable of signifying (the
only insofar as there is time. In a retro- meaning) of being.
spective glance toward the end of his career, Accordingly, Kant calls this procedure
Heidegger offers an illuminating remark in schematism, which yields a new precedent
his seminar from 1973 that schematism is for the use of pure concepts by indexing
the Kantian way of discussing being and them to the conditions of our finitude and
time (GA 15, 3801/FS, 69). providing a nexus of interlocking patterns of
Given this context, Heidegger casts a signification. In its strategic role, tempo-
new spotlight on what is perhaps one of the rality provides the creative nexus for engen-
most nebulous of all philosophical doctrines, dering new distinctions, reconfiguring the
Kants schematism of the pure concepts of pure concepts so that (through their syn-
the understanding. Kant may have proceeded thetic unities) they can elicit precisely those
uncritically when he adopted the categories (transcendental) time-determinations to
from Aristotle. Indeed, from Heideggers per- define objects for us (GA 25, 431/PICPR,
spective, Kant did not fully appreciate how 292) Within the overall procedure of sche-
he also adopted Aristotles legacy that being matism, time serves as the proxy of our
can be spoken in many ways. For Heidegger, finitude, and, by bearing this insignia, pro-
however, the diversity of these ways must vides the common ancestry to shape the con-
be taken back into and adduced from the tent of each of the pure concepts. Through

108
HEIDEGGER AND KANT

the strategic role that time plays, however, Why, then, did Heidegger turn to Kantian
the formative power of imagination can schematism? He did so because the procedure
graphically exhibit a genre of distinctions of schematism yields temporal idioms capable
as etched through a temporal nexuswhich of signifying the meaning of being. Thus, our
prefaces the development of language in understanding must take a detour through
its predicative form. We appeal to this temporality, through the pre-orientation of
pre-predicative level to suggest a novelty the directionality of the horizonal schema,
of linguistic practice, which, by graphically in order to avail itself of the precise deter-
portraying each of the pure concepts through minations to express the meaning of being
images, simultaneously implicate the precise in conceptual terms. Once again, the basic
vocabulary for their expression. Time, then, thrust of Heideggers destructive-retrieval of
forms the universal character of the lexicon, transcendental philosophy is to extend the
because its chief idioms, for example, suc- hermeneutic arc of questioning and carry
cession, permanence, presence, cultivate that forward within this dynamic of translat-
an awareness that is common to all human ing the key message of the Critique. Insofar
beings, precisely because it is emblematic as the question of being is inherently histori-
of our finitude as such. cal, he broadens the arc of that inquiry in
By forming a new grammar of articulation, and through his Auseinandersetzung with
the prefixical character of the schemata his predecessors, most notably, Kant. Let us
sculptures or carves out in advance the finite proceed to our third question and ask how
horizon in which whatever can appear does Heideggers conversation continues to unfold
so in accord with precisely those temporal in light of the turning.
determinations. To clarify the ontological
import of this schematism, as outlining
the temporal backdrop for whatever can
manifest itself, Heidegger characterizes the III
ecstatic character of these schemata as hori-
zonal (GA 24, 436/BP, 307). As the impe- In all of Heideggers extensive writings on
tus and trajectory of finite transcendence, transcendental philosophy, there is one sec-
ecstatic-horizonal temporality projects-open tion of the Kant-book whose importance
the expanse of manifestation and thereby has been vastly underestimated: section 44
outlines the possibility of understanding of part IV. In his Notes to the Kant-book,
being. This understanding, however, is inti- later published in the Preface to the Fourth
mately tied to the grammar for expressing it, Edition (1973) of that work, Heidegger
that is, its meaning, in terms of the priority calls attention to Part IV, and its impor-
of the verbal form of the is. The horizonal tance in alleviating the misinterpretation
schemata outline the simplest form in which surrounding the so-called unpublished third
the temporalization of being can emerge into division (of part I) of Being and Time, as well
language via the idiom to be. That is, we as the task of Destruktion in part II, calling
return to the dynamism of the verbal form; special attention to the conclusion (part IV)
we do not say something is, but, in refer- of the Kant-book (GA 3, xiii/KPM, xvii). In
ring back to the hidden connection between alluding to the real question left open in the
being and time, say instead: es gibt. third division of the first part of Sein und Zeit,

109
HEIDEGGER AND KANT

Heidegger then concludes his personal reflec- impact the genesis of the traditional concept
tion with this enigmatic remark: Beitrge: of time? The problem with preconceiving
beginning to a new beginning (Anfang zu being as permanent presence is that it preju-
neuem Anfang) [GA 3, xiii/KPM, xvii]. As dices any subsequent view of time in terms
we will see, in Contributions to Philosophy of the single temporal ecstasies to which it
(From Enowning) [19368], he briefly reex- gives rise, for example, the present. The
amines his conversation with Kant. At issue is being of beings obviously is understood here
how Kants destructive-retrieval of transcen- as permanence and constancy [Bestndigkeit
dental philosophy illuminates the so-called und Stndigkeit] (GA 3, 240/KPM, 168).
impasse surrounding the unpublished, third On the basis of a preconception of being
division of part I of Being and Time, to be in terms of permanence, a controversy then
titled Time and Being. irrupts as to which temporal model can sal-
Whatever may have been the various sce- vage the priority of the present: the continu-
narios for addressing being at the inception ance of the present under the ideal of eternity,
of Western thought, relative to its influence or, in, recognition of the coming to be and
on the subsequent tradition, one approach passing away of nature, the opposite concept
in particular assumes prominence: Aristotles of transitoriness. Eternity and the immedi-
concept of ousia as permanent pres- ate and always present [gegenwrtigen] are
ence. And, while some scholars argue that two sides of the same coin (GA 3, 240/KPM,
Heidegger simply rejects Aristotles interpre- 168). As the flip side of this vision of eter-
tation of being, his criticism targets instead nity, a linear concept of time as a sequence
the ambiguity surrounding the birth of the of nows, which segments the movement
ancient concept of ousia. What exactly is this of time into before and after, is born.
ambiguity? In conceiving of being as perma- The philosophical tradition must then juggle
nent presence, the ancients implicitly allude two conflicting views of time, as permanence
to time, but they do not question why this and transitoriness, each of which, however,
linkage should be inevitable. But once the stems from the same derivative root of time
ancients forgo this initial line of questioning, that privileges the temporal dimension of the
the first level of neglect for the question of present. A double dissimulation occurs,
being arises. Given the lack of insight into in short, the traditions forgottenness of its
the inevitable conjunction of being and time, forgottenness.
the ancients then fall victim to a second In the occurrence of this forgottenness,
level of neglect when the occasion arises Heidegger locates the historical juncture
to address the constitution of temporality. where Western metaphysics arises. If meta-
Rather than make the concern for time the physics begins by inverting the projection
priority for any investigation into being, the of being upon time, falling prey to forgotten-
ancients proceed in an inverse way: they ness, then how can this inertia be counteracted
adopt an understanding of being that is through an alternative possibility of recollec-
already thematized through time, and then, tion? Through his Auseinandersetzung with
once being has been conceived as permanent Kant, Heidegger seizes upon this possibility
presence, redefine time, as if by an after- and rediscovers the origin of his own inquiry
thought, on the basis of this permanence. But through the turning (die Kehre), that is, the
how does this dissimulation subsequently turning around of the question from Being

110
HEIDEGGER AND KANT

and Time to time and being. In the turn- this term we understand not only a faculty
ing around of the question, the emphasis on of the soul and not only something transcen-
the conjunction and first comes to light dental (cf. Kant-book) but rather enowning
(GA 31, 126 /EHF, 87). For it is the grammar itself, where all transfiguration reverberates.
of this connective that redirects Heideggers Imagination as occurrence of the clearing
inquiry back to the giving of each, being/ itself (GA 65, 312/CP1, 219).
time, in reciprocity with one another, as enun-
ciated through the most primeval of all ges-
tures: there is/it gives (es gibt) being, and,
correlatively, there is/it gives (es gibt) time Conclusion
(GA 15, 3634/FS, 5960). These locutions
help to carry out the turning as Heidegger Heideggers Auseinandersetzung with Kant
describes it, by allowing an attunement to extends over the course of four decades,
language to intervene and introduce the basic carving out a Denkweg the many twists and
experience by which being can first become turns of which lead to the crossroads of the
understandable to us and we can partici- other beginning. Perhaps more than any phi-
pate in its openness. The Kantian legacy is losopher within the Western tradition, Kant
such that the conceptualization of being must offers Heidegger a blueprint for developing
always be linked to the experience thereof, his own fundamental ontology and thereby
with temporality serving as the go-between, the key for rediscovering the hidden connec-
the mid-point of intermediation. tion between being and time.
After the Kant-book, Heidegger would
periodically renew his Auseinandersetzung
with Kant. A brief remark from Contributions NOTES AND REFERENCES
to Philosophy offers a retrospective glance on
his own Kant-interpretation. In justifying his 1
For a discussion of this topic, in connection
initial attempt to use force against Kant in with schematism, see Frank Schalow,
order to work out the transcendental power Departures: At the Crossroads between
of imagination, Heidegger states: And so Heidegger and Kant (Berlin: de Gruyter, 2013),
pp. 4961. For a discussion of the role that
the Kant-book is necessarily ambiguous . . . translation, understood broadly, plays in
because Kant continues to be the only one transmitting the meaning of the most basic
since the Greeks who brings the interpreta- philosophical terms, see See Parvis Emad,
tion of beingness into a certain relation to Translation and Interpretation: Learning from
time. . . . (GA 65, 2534 /CP1, 1789). Beitrge, ed. F. Schalow (Bucharest: Zeta Books,
2012), 619.
Indeed: As thrown projecting-opening 2
See Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason,
grounding, Da-sein is the highest actuality in trans. Norman Kemp Smith (New York:
the domain of imagination, granted that by St.Martins Press, 1965), 182 (A 140 / B 179).

111
12
Heidegger and German Idealism
Peter Trawny

German Idealism is for Heidegger a certain Hegel and German Idealism


constellation and context of certain philoso-
phers and poets in the history of metaphys- In a later text Heidegger speaks of the super-
ics, that is, of being. The constellation and ficial talk of the breakdown of Hegelian
context of German Idealism are not always philosophy (GA 7, 74).2 This opinion is
the same, but they are ultimately stable. It is rejected, because in the 19th Century only
remarkable that Heidegger, with the excep- this philosophy has determined reality, and
tion of the lecture course German Idealism indeed it has as metaphysics. And then he
of summer semester 1929, ignores the canon- claims: Since Hegels death (1831) every-
ical accentuation in the study of German thing is only a countermovement, not only in
Idealism on the names of Fichte, Schelling, Germany, but also in Europe.
and Hegel.1 German Idealism for Heidegger is Heideggers engagement with Hegel begins
primarily the thinking of Hegel and Schelling, early and ends late. Heidegger dealt with no
its being-historical location is the Absolute other philosopher perhaps as continuously
in its relation to subjectivity. On the one as Hegel.3 When later he introduces certain
hand, it is set up by the philosophy of Kant, notations simply with Hegel | Heidegger
which is at the same time decidedly notable (GA 11, 1057), the proximity and distance
(GA 42, 62, 72; GA 86, 193). On the other is clearly marked. Heideggers philosophy is
hand, Hlderlins poetry, insofar as it in a also the attempt, by overcoming metaphys-
certain respect belongs to German Idealism, ics, to overcome that counter movement.
is dehistoricized (yet not understood as Already in his habilitation treatise, Duns
unhistorical), and its specific significance for Scotuss Doctrine of Categories and Meaning
the history of being beyond German Idealism (1916), Heidegger speaks of the great task
is emphasized (GA 65, 4212). of bringing about a thorough confronta-
We will accordingly consider German tion [Auseinandersetzung] with the abun-
Idealism in the following order: dance and depth, richness of experience and
conceptualization of the most powerful sys-
(1) Hegel and German Idealism tem, that is with Hegel (GA 1, 41011).
(2) Schelling and German Idealism This task, formulated under the influence of
(3) German Idealism in the history of meta- Dilthey, was realized in the coming decades
physics, that is, of being of Heideggers thinking.

113
HEIDEGGER AND GERMAN IDEALISM

This begins in summer 1923, in the lecture with absolute idealism and therefore with
course Ontology (Hermeneutics of Facticity), western metaphysics. It pushes in totally
where Heidegger separates phenomenol- concealed dimensions, which we primarily
ogy and dialectics in the Hegelian sense for have to obtain in a deep elaboration of the
the first time (GA 63, 437). If today it is problem of metaphysics. But still something
attempted to connect the authentic underly- different emerges. Heidegger in his readings
ing tendency of phenomenology with dialec- of Hegel will notably refer to the central
tics, then this is as if someone would like work of the Phenomenology of Spirit, but
to connect fire and water (42). Fire and also to the Science of Logic. He attempts
water build an antagonism resulting in the his first extended readings of Hegels
annihilation of each other. This demonstrates Phenomenology in the winter-semester
that phenomenology is not indifferent to 1930/31. It is abandoned in the interpre-
dialectics. tation of self-consciousness (GA 32, 215).
In Being and Time, Heidegger appears Everything should remain unsettled.
to distance himself from German Idealism. Heidegger taught a seminar four years
While Plato and Aristotle challenged him at later (1934/35) about Hegels Philosophy
the beginning of the 1920s to further his phil- of Right with the well-known theorist of
osophical development, Hegel still remains jurisprudence Erik Wolf at the university of
present. In the famous passage, where Freiburg. This seminar testifies to how the
Heidegger reminds us of the philosopher seeks to unfold a political phi-
, the question for the mean- losophy in recourse to Hegels thought. A
ing of being, which provided a stimulus concept of National-Socialism, and its coher-
for his researches of Plato and Aristotle, ence with political realities is questionable,
Heidegger also speaks of Hegel. For what serves as a pathmark. This attempt to answer
was achieved in this research, was to per- National-Socialism with Hegels Philosophy
sist through many alterations and retouch- of Right is not resumed. Hegels Elements of
ings down to the logic of Hegel (GA 2, 3). the Philosophy of Right remained the only
Hegels understanding of time then becomes classical work of political philosophy that
so important that Heidegger announces a Heidegger publically interpreted.
comparative lecture of Hegels Jena Logic At the end of the 1930s we see Heidegger
and Aristotles Physics and Metaphysics addressing Hegels understanding of nega-
(570). In the summer semester of 1927, he tivity, renewing the appeal for a philo-
ventured such an interpretation (in fact not sophical confrontation with Hegel (GA
on the Jena Logic, but on the Science of 68, 3). For Hegels philosophy stands
Logic (see GA 86)). definitively in the history of thinking, that
In the summer of 1929, Heidegger inter- is, of Beyng as a unique and still not
prets Hegel further in a lecture course on conceived demand. Every thinking that
German Idealism (GA 28, 195232). In this comes after Hegel, or also only prima-
lecture course, he returns to the confron- rily wants to arrange the presuppositions of
tation [Auseinandersetzung] with Hegel philosophy, cannot avoid this demand.
(214). Initial expressions of this confron- The uniqueness of Hegels philosophy
tation are crystallized, which remain in consists primarily in the fact that a higher
place. A confrontation with Hegel is one standpoint of the self-consciousness of spirit

114
HEIDEGGER AND GERMAN IDEALISM

beyond this philosophy is no longer possi- to its own inquiry (Prfung), it moves
ble. Therefore, there is no philosophy that out of its presence to arrive in this presence.
still could be superordinated on a higher Experience is the representation of the
level than Hegels systematics. But the appearance of the appearing knowledge.
standpoint of a necessary confrontation During this period, Hegels philosophy
with Hegels philosophy has nonetheless to found its place in the context of the history
cope with it, and thus to be superior in an of metaphysics. The desertification of the
essential aspect. This standpoint cannot earth (GA 7, 97) begins as a process which
be brought and convinced from outside, is willed, but unknown in its essence, and
but must be found in Hegels philosophy also not knowable at the time, where the
as an essentially inaccessible and indiffer- essence of truth is projected as certainty.
ent ground for it. A true critique of a phi- It is Hegel who conceives this moment of
losophy has to confront its main ideas. An the history of metaphysics as the moment in
external interpretation of Hegels philoso- which absolute self-consciousness becomes
phy remains shallow. the principle of thinking.
The second presupposition of a philo- Heidegger confirmed this idea immediately
sophical confrontation with Hegel chal- after the war. In his Letter on Humanism
lenges the systematic standard of his (1946) Hegels thinking appears in the his-
thinking. As the principle of his philoso- tory of beyng (GA 9, 335, 360), the key to
phy (45) conceives the whole of beings, Heideggers later philosophy. Those who
thus that philosophy has to dispose of the wish to understand the accomplishment of
principle that shows itself in the whole modernity with its far-reaching consequences
of beings because it is the actual. A basic in the twentieth century cannot avoid a con-
confrontation with Hegel can only succeed frontation with Hegels philosophy.
if it fulfills at the same time and consistently Hegels thinking is furthermore the start-
both demands (6). In the introduction of the ing point for the interpretation of the
notes of 1938/39, Heidegger begins to deal onto-theo-logical constitution of metaphys-
with Hegels fundamental determination ics(1957).Thephilosophical confrontation
of negativity. has become a thinking dialogue about the
The 1942 summer term seminar represents matter of thinking (GA 11, 55). If we want
a further intense interpretation of Hegels to enter into such a dialogue with Hegel,
Phenomenology of Spirit. This turned out we not only have to talk with him about the
to be a very fertile exploration. The out- same matter, but to talk with him about the
come of this seminar was the essay Hegels same matter in the same way. Hegel thinks
Concept of Experience (GA 5, 115208) the being of beings in a speculative-historical
and Elucidation of the Introduction of the way (spekulative-geschichtlich). Heidegger
Phenomenology of Spirit (GA 68). Hegels responds to this way of thinking by
Concept of Experience, published in Off the being-historical thinking.
Beaten Track (1950), belongs to the context The outcome of this correspondence is
of examining the problem of experience in differences that Heidegger roughly contrasts:
general. For Hegel, experience concerns the For Hegel (56) the matter of thinking is
present in its presence (GA 5, 186). Insofar being in reference of the being-thought in
as consciousness exists by exposing itself absolute thinking and as absolute thinking.

115
HEIDEGGER AND GERMAN IDEALISM

In contrast for us the matter of thinking is of being and thinking is really an equiva-
the same, thus being, but being in reference lence (59). Therefore, it does not come to a
to its difference to beings. Heidegger then question of being. Furthermore, the human
adds: For Hegel, the matter of thinking is being is interpreted as a coming-to-itself of
the idea as the absolute concept. For us, for- the Absolute, what leads to a sublation
mulated in a preliminary fashion, the matter of the finitude of the human being. In the
of thinking is difference as difference. thinking of Heidegger the finitude of the
Heideggers exhortation to speak with human being is what comes to view.
Hegel about the same matter in the same In the Le Thor seminars (1968/69),
way continues in a lecture given in 1958 Heidegger attempts to formulate the great
in Heidelberg and Aix-en-Provence with task of a philosophical confrontation
the title Hegel and the Greeks. In this text with Hegel. Heidegger thinks the finitude
Heidegger interrogates the originality of of being (GA 15, 3701). Being can not be
Hegels philosophy of history insofar as he is absolutely for itself. Even if Hegel says that
also concerned with philosophy in the total- the Absolute is not without us, he says
ity of its historical destiny (GA 9, 429). The this in reference to the Christian God, who in
question is whether Hegel is able to recog- a certain sense is reliant on the human being.
nize the enigma of in his consid- But for Heidegger being is not without its
eration of truth (442). For with relation to Dasein and Nothing is further
our thinking is addressed by something; away from Hegel and all idealism.
what before the beginning of philosophy
and through the whole course of its history
has already drawn thought to itself (444).
The relation Hegel | Heidegger was so Schelling and German Idealism
precarious that Heidegger, at the instigation
of Jean Beaufret in 1962, accepted the neces- Heidegger became acquainted with Schelling
sity of distinguishing his thinking from Hegel at the same time as Hegel (GA 1, 56), in the
with even more emphasis. It is stated in the years before the First World War. This might
Protocol of a Seminar about Time and not be a coincidence. Heidegger always
Being: Thus in France the impression was read Schelling with Hegel and Hegel with
widely predominant that Heideggers think- Schelling; Hegel and Schelling build the
ing was a recapitulationas a deepening and essential constellation and core of German
an expansionof Hegels philosophy (GA Idealism.
14, 57). From Hegels point of view (59), Heidegger offered a seminar about Hegels
one could say that Being and Time gets logic in the summer semester of 1927. He
caught in being, because it is not developed taught Schellings Philosophical Inquiries
to the concept. On the other hand, one into the Nature of Human Freedom for
could ask from the perspective of Being and the first time in the winter of 1927/28. The
Time, why Hegel considers being as inde- notations as they are handed down to us do
terminate immediacy, just to place it from not reveal a special interest, but the discus-
the very beginning in relation to determina- sion of love of evil reveal a change in
tion and mediation. For Hegel, the identity Heideggers interpretation of Hegel.

116
HEIDEGGER AND GERMAN IDEALISM

In the lecture course German Idealism in Mindfulness. Schelling has projected the
from the summer of 1929, Heidegger dis- deepest form of the spirit within the history
cussed Schelling rather briefly. He is inter- of German metaphysics. Indeed, the spirit
preted as a critic of Fichte, and Heidegger and the Absolute remain Subjectum; but
refers more or less superficially to Schellings if it [spirit] has its essence in freedom, thus in
philosophy of nature. Heidegger claims that this freedom a determination of the capabil-
Schelling primarily in a countermovement ity of good and evil is present, which says
[Gegenspiel] to Hegels phenomenology came something more essential than Hegels abso-
to himself (GA 28, 197). Nonetheless, some- lute concept (GA 66, 264).
body different has brought him to himself, It is plain that Schelling transcends
i.e., has freed the whole of philosophizing in German Idealism, because he is able to
him, namely Caroline4 (193). She has by confront Hegel with an own understand-
the impact [Wucht] of her existence, which ing of spirit and the Absolute. Heidegger
took place beyond convention, moralism, elucidates this event in the history of being
and prevailing taste and the dwarfishness of in an explanation entitled The Difference
everyday life, accomplished her great life. of Hegels and Schellings System. The phi-
This was undoubtedly an opportunity for losopher emphasizes immediately that this
Heidegger to identify himself with Schelling. difference builds an aspect of the history
A half-dozen years later Heidegger of being. The difference between Hegel
returns to Schelling. In the context of the and Schelling lies in the determination of
being-historical lecture courses Heidegger being (GA 86, 212). It is only possible to
now allows Schelling a special meaning. In speak of a difference, when in advance una-
the Schelling-lecture course (summer 1936), nimity in the essential is given. This is the
Schelling has freed himself of his dependency case insofar as for Hegel and Schelling being
on Hegel. He is now the real creative and is subjectivityreasonspirit.
farthest reaching thinker of this whole era For Schelling and Hegel, spirit is abso-
of German philosophy, that is, of German lutethat is it unifies everything in himself.
Idealism. He is this thinker to such an If this is true, then the non-spiritual or the
extent that he drives German Idealism from sensuous belongs to it. Here, in the determi-
within right past its own fundamental posi- nation of the relation between the sensuous
tion (GA 42, 6). It is difficult to say what and reason, lies the difference. For Hegel,
this means. the sensuous is the one-sidedabstract.
Heidegger offers an initial clue when he It is not negated, but considered irrational.
emphasizes that the innermost center of Schelling in contrast understands the sensu-
Schellings thinking is the essence of human ous emerging from will and appetite. This
freedom, that is, the question for free- is also recognized by Hegel, but the unity
dom (ibid.). Hegel did not see that just as unity of ground (base) and existence is
this single thing, freedom, was not isolated nevertheless different; Schellings idea of
for Schelling, but was thought and developed identity and un-ground as in-difference is
as the essential foundation of the whole, as more original within the absolute meta-
a new foundation for a whole philosophy physics of subjectivity, but only within.
(21). Heidegger becomes even more definite Schelling consequently does not project a

117
HEIDEGGER AND GERMAN IDEALISM

thinking that crosses German Idealisms his- speculative idealism, Schelling has recon-
torical borders. structed it in the difference of negative and
This is articulated again in another con- positive philosophy. In the identity of iden-
text. The fundamental movement to the pos- tity and difference, ontological difference
itive (GA 88, 149) is decisive for Schelling. has disappeared yet is not overcome, as it
Heidegger calls this Schellings . The returns again in the difference of negative
positive consists: (1) in the fact that it is and positive philosophy.
not able to be content with the negative of
the Fichtian non-I, but that it has to conceive
nature out of itself as the visible spirit; (2)
that it does not integrate the identity of The German Idealism in the
intelligence and nature in a mutual dia- History of Metaphysics and
lectics of both, but that it goes back in a Being
ground of both, their absolute indiffer-
ence; and (3) the fundamental movement Heidegger considered German Idealism
into existence as first testifies that the to be an era in the history of being. In
freedom and the will as such is the first, Contributions to Philosophy, he allocated
what comes forward from itself and thus it its own place in the third joining of
becomes beings. With this Schelling reaches Playing-Forth. Localizing an era in the his-
the highest stage of his philosophy and tory of being requires that its descent from
perhaps of western metaphysics in general the first beginning be made visible.
(141). Of course, the fundamental move- This descent consists in the fact that ideal-
ment to the existing unfolds in a final, ism interprets the as , and that is
highly Christian-theological restorative way. understood as being-seen, re-presentedness
The growing antagonism to Hegel renders and of course re-presented[ness of]
Schelling more and more dependent on him, and (GA 65, 202). Hence idealism goes
and makes the positive more and more rude back to its Platonic genesis, where the idea is
and backwards oriented. Therefore, the thought as the general and the eternal. The
real exciting moment of Schellings thinking idea is re-presented already in Plato. Thus
lies not in his late philosophy. Especially Platos idealism became an anticipation of
in this philosophy, Schelling reveals less of the interpretation of beings as ob-jects for
what is necessary for the overcoming of real representation.
rationalism. This place in the history of being is the
The status of Schellings late philosophy is beginning of the modern age. Here the repre-
consequently evident.Thedifference between sentation is ego percipio, the representedness
the negative and positive philosophy is the as such for the I think. This representation
reflection of the onto-theological essence of is at the same time an I think myself, which
metaphysicswithin absolute idealism (GA means that the I gains certainty. But this
86, 520). But the onto-theological essence certainty is apparently not a consequence of
of metaphysics has its basis in the onto- representation, but the origin of the priority
logical difference (517). Whereas Hegel has of the ego that lies in the will to certainty
dissolved the ontological difference in to be certain of itself.

118
HEIDEGGER AND GERMAN IDEALISM

But this place in the history of being is still and becomes the certainty that unfolds
not the place of German Idealism. For this into an unconditioned trust in spirit and
first self-representation still remains in the thus unfolds first as spirit in its absolute-
particularity of precisely each particular I. ness. Now beings are completely dis-
In this sense, this version of idealism does placed into objectness. What Heidegger
not even reach Platonic idealism for what has in mind with this unusual interpreta-
is thus represented is not yet and tion becomes more evident in his reference
. Therefore, the self-representation has to machination. For machination as the
to become a self-knowing in the absolute basic character of beingness becomes a
sense. This absolute self-knowing knows subject-object-dialectics, which, as abso-
the necessity of the relation of the object to lute, plays out and arranges together all pos-
the I and of the I to the object. It has freed sibilities of all familiar domains of beings [in
itself from the one-sidedness of Cartesian the system].
philosophy. From this position there is no bridge
This absolute knowledge in German to the other beginning. Nevertheless it is
Idealism is connected with divine knowing important to know particularly this think-
of the Christian God. It can look back on a ing of German Idealism; for here the
tradition in which St. Augustine has already machinational power of beingness comes
determined what is represented in the rep- into its utmost, unconditioned unfolding.
resentation of God, that is, as ideas. Hence the end is prepared.
Nevertheless, Heidegger insists that such The end of metaphysics is prepared in this
idealism, which can invoke the whole history way that the self-evidence of being, that is,
of metaphysics since Plato, was developed the neglect of the question of being, is now
only since Descartes. systematically extended to the richness of the
German Idealism (202) is this ideal- historicity of spirit and its forms (2034).
ism, which was delineated in advance in It is Hegels system appearing as one end
Leibniz, and attempts to conceive the ego of philosophy or metaphysics. Schellings
cogito on the basis of Kants transcendental treatise on freedom attested to individual
step beyond Descartes at the same time as thrusts, but it nevertheless does not lead to
it moves in direction of Christian dogma. any decision (204). Hegel and Schelling are
The aberrance (203) of German Idealism nearly codified, as German Idealism remains
therefore lies in the combination of modern in its richness a location of the history of
Dasein and Christianity, which finally hin- metaphysics.
dered its thinking of the question of being.
In this sense, German Idealism was too
true-to-life and produced countermove- NOTES AND REFERENCES
ments like positivism, which now celebrates
its biologistic triumphs.
1
Daniel O. Dahlstrom places more empha-
In the context of German Idealisms sis on Heideggers reading of Fichte in
Dahlstrom, Heidegger and German Idealism.
allocation in the history of metaphysics, In: A Companion to Heidegger, ed. Hubert L.
the following can be understood: Truth as Dreyfus and Mark A. Wrathall (Malden, MA:
being is thought differently in metaphysics Blackwell Publishers, 2005), 6579.

119
HEIDEGGER AND GERMAN IDEALISM

2
The quotations are related to the (Amherst: New York, 2000), 13). This judgment
Gesamtausgabe (GA), but, if possible, oriented is based on many hermeneutic presuppositions.
to existing English translations. Perhaps the most problematic one lies in this
3
Rockmore writes about Heideggers reading question: what does it mean to understand
of Hegel: Although he prepared a number Hegels position as a whole?
of texts on aspects of Hegels thought, he 4
Caroline Michaelis (17631809), since 1803
seems finally not to have made much progress married to Schelling, formerly married to
toward understanding Hegels position as a August Wilhelm Schlegel, was a woman with a
whole (Heidegger, German Idealism, and very unusual biography in the early nineteenth
Neo-Kantianism, ed. by Tom Rockmore century.

120
13
Heidegger and Nietzsche
Ullrich Haase

One cannot underestimate the influence that European Nihilism, Heidegger sees the over-
Nietzsche had on Heidegger from his early coming of the metaphysics of presence by
to the very end of his career. While readers means of the temporal dimension of the exis-
often stress the extensive thematic interpre- tential understanding of the human being.
tation of Nietzsche from the mid-1930s to Where Nietzsche thinks the Overhuman as
the mid-1940s, one should be careful not the historical potential of human life after
to overlook that Heideggers reading of the end of the Platonic understanding of
Nietzsche in the early years of the twenti- human being, Heidegger thinks the possibil-
eth century have influenced the very begin- ity of an insertion into Dasein as its historical
ning of his philosophical development and potentiality.
that it does so even and especially where One might say that as Heidegger has
Nietzsche is not explicitly mentioned. From taught many of us to think, so Nietzsche
the question of metaphysics, to the question has taught Heidegger to think, whatever
of the meaning of being, to his reflections on other influences there might have been in
art and nihilism, right down to the fact that the form of Husserlian Phenomenology,
when asking What is Called Thinking in the nineteenth-century neo-Kantianism, or the
years 1951 and 1952, Heidegger very quickly extensive interpretations of Hlderlins poetry,
turns toward a reflection on the thought of among others. This makes reading Heidegger
Friedrich Nietzsche, the latters philosophi- on Nietzsche for us about as difficult as it was
cal influence is ubiquitous in Heideggers for him. In the end, thinking thematically
writings. Where Nietzsche said that there about a thought that has given rise to ones
are no truths, there are only interpretations own, always means thinking against oneself;
and interpretations of interpretations, it means putting into question the very foun-
Heidegger, already in Being and Time, devel- dation of ones own thinking. As Heidegger
ops the essentially hermeneutic essence of said himself, Nietzsche is the thinker who is
truth. Where Nietzsche speaks of the death closest to him and the whole of Heideggers
of God, Heidegger demands the complete career is characterized variously by medita-
extrication of Christian theology from the tions on Nietzsches thought or the attempt
philosophical problematic. Where Nietzsche to distance himself from it.
thinks of the potential of the doctrine of the But the relation between these thinkers is
Eternal Return of the Same to overcome not only complicated by way of Heideggers

121
HEIDEGGER AND NIETZSCHE

personal philosophical development. Rather, beyond the limits of metaphysical thought.


the reason for which Heidegger puts so much Such an interpretive strategy is supported
emphasis on Nietzsches philosophy is not by Heideggers own stance, which some-
only in this sense personal, but rests on the times involves Nietzsches thought with the
conviction that Nietzsches thought consti- utmost affirmation, while then turning to
tutes the historical fulfillment and exhaus- its clearest condemnation. It is this ambiva-
tion of metaphysical thought as it has reigned lence that confuses many readers, especially
over two millennia of European history. Or, if they are looking for a critical judgment on
rather, it is metaphysics which by means of a thinker. What is it now? Is Nietzsche the
Nietzsche deprives itself in a specific way of last metaphysician, oriented backwardly by
its own essential potentialities [HW, 193]. being lost in his reversal of Platonism? Or is
To be able to understand Nietzsche is thus Nietzsche the thinker who still waits for us
not only a philological endeavor but the in our future (NI, 340)? In any case, if trying
attempt at making a historical difference. to understand the philosophical stakes in the
As Heidegger says in a lecture course on confrontation of Nietzsche and Heidegger,
Schelling: one needs to avoid the rather meaningless
escape route of claiming that the contradic-
Nietzsche . . ., has been ruined over his tions in Heideggers statements concerning
main work, the Will to Power. Whoever Nietzsches philosophy are due to him chang-
would truly come to understand the rea- ing his mind a few times. Great philosophers
son for this failure would have to become as they are, neither Nietzsche nor Heidegger
the founder of a new beginning of occi- ever change their minds.
dental philosophy. (GA 42, 4) Indeed, Heideggers own approach has
often followed this ambiguous strategy. It
As this was precisely Heideggers aim as a could be useful here to pick up Rita Casales
philosopher, everything for him depended distinction between the time of Heideggers
on such an essential understanding of encounter with Nietzsches philosophy from
Nietzsches philosophy and, consequently, 1910 to 1928, his unthematic critical disen-
his ability finally to separate his thinking gagement [Auseinandersetzung] from 1929
from Nietzsches. to 1935 and his thematic, critical disengage-
Thus to understand Heideggers philoso- ment from 1936 to 1946,1 as long as one adds
phy it is necessary to follow two alterna- Heideggers later work to this distinction. One
tive and contradictory moments in which will have to bear in mind, though, that these
Nietzsche and Heidegger, first, are made are just strategic differences, which do not
to say the same thing, if in rather different allow for a very precise differentiation of his
wordsa method complicated by the fact work. Thus, for example, the lecture course
that especially Nietzsche makes his readers from 1938/39, Towards an Interpretation of
aware of the question of style in the presenta- Nietzsches 2nd Untimely Meditation, while
tion of philosophical thinkingin order then certainly thematic, belongs more to the elab-
to move from here to make the difference orations of Heideggers philosophy closer
between Nietzsche and Heidegger, in such to Being and Time, than to the contempo-
a way that Heidegger comes to say, not the raneous Nietzsche Lectures. Yet in all these
opposite of Nietzsche, but something new cases the aim of reading Nietzsche is not to

122
HEIDEGGER AND NIETZSCHE

ascertain an abstract philological truth of To understand this rather exalted place that
Nietzsches text. Indeed, philologically speak- Nietzsche finds in Heideggers universe, one
ing, Heideggers approach might sometimes needs to make an attempt to understand the
appear violent if not even unjust. As many essentially historical [geschichtliche] nature
interpreters have tried to object: can one not of Nietzsches and Heideggers understand-
find more in Nietzsches text? Could one not ing of philosophy.
read him with more hermeneutic generosity?
And yet, for Heidegger, Nietzsche is certainly ***
too great a thinker to be in need of such
generosity, while his greatness is reflected in When Heidegger spoke above of the great-
his value for our openness to the future. As ness of Hegels and Nietzsches thought, then
Heidegger puts this, locating the Nietzsche this has to be understood on account of both
lectures within the context of his wider his- of these realizing the essential nature of his-
torical lectures: Nietzsche: to dare the crit- tory as to philosophical thought. Where
ical dis-engagement [Auseinandersetzung] Hegel had ended in the claim that the his-
with him who is closest to us and to realize tory of philosophy is identical to the phi-
that he is furthest away from the question of losophy of history, Nietzsches maybe most
being. To understand Nietzsche as the end pivotal reflection came in the 2nd Untimely
of metaphysics is the historical approach to Meditation,2 when considering the essentially
the future of occidental thought (GA 65, historical nature of all thinking. In this text
176). In such an engagement with Nietzsche, Nietzsche does not merely ponder the nature
one should never fall for the impression that of history, but wonders about the possibility
Heidegger assumes the chair of the judge who of historical intervention, that is, the crea-
can or should condemn Nietzsches thought tion of the new, the conservation of the given
from above, and this not only because of the and the destruction of the old. But more than
greatness of Nietzsches thinking but also that, Nietzsche asks in this text for the his-
because of the historical nature of philo- torical task that philosophy is allotted in our
sophical thought: age, and, therefore, he also asks for the very
possibility of his own thinking. At the end of
We too have to take a previous thought this text he sketches out a historical meth-
into view and interpret it from the per- odology of philosophical thinking, which
spective of our own thinking. As little as attempts to deal with the historical reality of
Nietzsche and as little as Hegel are we thought after the death of God, that is, once
able to posit ourselves outside of his- it has been demonstrated to the philosopher
tory and of time and to pretend to an that he cannot take up a position in a purely
absolute position from which to regard logical domain outside of historical reality.
that which has been, as if independent
Philosophical thinking, itself a part of this
from a determined and therefore neces-
world, has to address the essentially tempo-
sarily one-sided optic. This holds for us
as much as for Nietzsche and Hegel; but ral dimension of thought and, therefore, has
also this: that the horizon of our thinking to address this in its methodological founda-
might not even have the essentiality and tions. When he speaks in subsequent texts
certainly not the greatness of the ques- about the destruction of Idealism he really
tion posed by these thinkers. (NI, 115) has in mind any philosophical stance that

123
HEIDEGGER AND NIETZSCHE

presents itself in a theoretical fashion, that and nihilism can thus only be engaged by a
is, that adheres to the traditional notion of more active nihilism.
truth as a thought correctly representing a As thought is to be understood as an action
state of affairs, or, as the philosophers say, as within the historical world, or as Heidegger
adequatio intellectus et rei. Consequently, the will later say, as philosophizing is a handi-
question is no longer which one of a set of craft, it can no longer appear in the form
competing theories is the true one, but what of a theory representing a present state of
is truth itself? For there to be any promise affairs. Nietzsche therefore does not present
of a future, Nietzsche says, knowledge must theories of the Eternal Return of the Same or
turn its sting against itself, that is, the philos- the Will to Power, but sees these as doctrines
opher has to ask what knowledge is good for or teachings [Lehre]. Such a doctrine, as
and how an answer to this question might Nietzsche says, has more than one face. It,
change our very understanding of what truth on the one hand, has to look backwards in
is. From here stems Heideggers insight into order to comprehend the present, while, on
the fact that philosophers have for too long the other hand, it has to make a difference
taken the meaning of truth for granted and with respect to the future. A teaching like
from here also follows the famous discussion the Eternal Return of the Same thus incor-
of truth in 44 of Being and Time. porates a movement from critique to crea-
But what has Nietzsche in mind when he tion. This is especially clear in the famous
speaks of a historical method by means of passage from the Zarathustra, Of the Face
which history itself must solve the problem and the Riddle, in which Nietzsche dem-
of history? In the second half of the text, onstrates the modern nature of the thought
Nietzsche makes clear that of the three forms as arising from the development of modern
of history, the monumental, the antiquarian physics and the philosophical discourse from
and the critical; we live in an age character- Leibniz to German Idealism, while trying to
ized by a one-sided prevalence of critique, draw the consequences from such a thought
that is, in an age of essential change that, in its in order to transform it into a promise of the
inception, is purely negative, that is, destruc- future. In such a process the thought changes
tive. This idea of a historical malady will as does the thinker, while the thinker who
later become Nietzsches thought of nihilism does not change with thinking the thought is
as the truth of European history. It is here in left behind, failing to understand anything.
the 2nd Untimely Meditation that Nietzsche Thus the tripartite methodology of
outlines the phases of his work as it is to be Nietzsches text, separating the moments of
developed over the next decades, from the creation, preservation, and destruction in
radicalization of critical philosophy in what history, becomes in Heideggers work the
has come to be called his critical phase, up to sequence of the destruction [Destruktion] of
the later writings beginning with Thus Spoke metaphysics in Being and Time and the criti-
Zarathustra. The critique of critical history cal disengagement [Auseinandersetzung] not
cannot for Nietzsche lead to an affirmation only from Nietzsche, but throughout the his-
of its opposite, as thought has to engage with torical lecture courses and always in unison
what is given, which is to say, derive itself with the critical disengagement from meta
from the given. The critical age can thus only physics itself, as Heidegger develops these
be overcome by a radicalization of critique between Being and Time and the mid-1940s,

124
HEIDEGGER AND NIETZSCHE

especially in the three books, Contributions away from which the transition moves
to Philosophy (GA 65), Meditation (GA 66), towards the other side. (GA 8, 21)
and The History of Beyng (GA 69), but also
later on in the question concerning technol- As we have seen above, it is this methodo-
ogy. This is how Heidegger characterizes the logical demand that legitimates the violence
idea of an Auseinandersetzung: of Heideggers reading of Nietzsche.
Being and Time, the repetition of meta-
The historial critical disengagement physics with the intent of its destruction,
[Auseinandersetzung] . . . moves us as Heidegger describes it, attempts to bring
into those fundamental attunements out the historical foundation of contem-
[Grundstimmungen], in which and porary ontology. In this respect it reflects,
from out of which the thinkers are for example, on the true foundation of our
no longer mutually intelligible [ver- understanding of truth. It is for this reason
stndigt], where agreement is essen- that many commentators are much happier
tially declined, because no agreement
with the period of Being and Time than with
of opinions within the same are able to
the later work, as they often do not quite see
bear whatever truth... . For this reason
an Auseinandersetzung never concerns a the sense of the destruction of metaphysi-
calculation of the correctness and incor- cal ontology as intended by Heidegger. In a
rectness of doctrines or opinions; the similar way as the initial step of the doctrine
ideas of a schoolmaster, thinking about of the Eternal Return of the Same is to make
the mistakes which a thinker might the nihilism of our contemporary age palpa-
have made and which are to be eradi- ble and to do so especially where there seems
cated, might have a place in the setting not to be any explicit nihilism at stake, Being
of a school, but not in the history of and Time demonstrates an age that drifts
being and never in the conversation along the path toward the loss of history
between thinkers. (GA 66, 69)
[Geschichtslosigkeit] as which Heidegger
understands the Nietzschean notion of nihil-
I have translated Auseinandersetzung here as ism in his famous dictum that the desert
a critical disengagement, in order to bring grows. Such Geschichtslosigkeit is, therefore,
out the methodological idea of Heidegger, Ver-wstung, that is, desertification. History
insofar as this word, otherwise translated proper exists therefore not where there is a
as confrontation, literally refers to the set- high value placed on historical science, but
ting oneself apart from, and it is for this only where there is a passing down of deci-
reason that as to the thematic interpretation sions and of resoluteness (see GA 66, 167).
of Nietzsche in the famous lecture courses It is, then, first with the famous Turning
Heidegger insists that, insofar as Nietzsches of Heidegger, that he attempts to move
thought marks an historical transition, toward the understanding of a new think-
ing, which would no longer be metaphysical.
only a dialogue whose own path prepares The development from asking the question
for a transition can be commensurate of the meaning of being toward that of the
to it. Yet in terms of such a transition, history of Beyng does not accidentally fall
Nietzsches thought will need to be into the time in which Heidegger begins his
brought to stand wholly on that side critical engagement with Nietzsche in quite

125
HEIDEGGER AND NIETZSCHE

an explicit form, namely by a sustained set of Thus it is by means of science itself that
lecture courses lasting from the mid-1930s to the essential relation of true knowledge
the mid-1940s.. to beings is destroyed and, insofar as the
true, essential knowledge is the ground
of all science, the modern sciences cre-
***
ate themselves the menace to their being
by means of a ground- and unfound-
From Being and Time onwards, the underly- edness [Grund und Bodenlosigkeit].
ing thread of Heideggers work can be seen (Bedrohung., 8)
as a critique of science, culminating in his
later question of technology. This question,
as he makes clear in a text on the Bedrohung This Grund und Bodenlosigkeit is explained
der Wissenschaft3 has become possible and by the prevalence of method and its con-
necessary with Nietzsches meditation on sci- solidation as technology, an analysis that
ence as it started with the Birth of Tragedy. Heidegger quotes verbatim from Nietzsche
It is first with the end of metaphysics that who said in 466 of the Will to Power that
we can understand the question of science it is not the victory of science which char-
properly and as this has been opened with acterizes our 19th century, but the victory of
Nietzsches work, Heidegger can claim that scientific methods over the sciences. While
Nietzsche does not use the word technology
the fact that Nietzsche left the university to clarify his critique of science, Heidegger can
[of Basel] is the sharpest decision of those thus still build his case on Nietzsches insight.
days against its science. Seen from this In these few pages I cannot do this ques-
perspective any contemporary reflection tion of the destiny of the modern natural
on science is only a more or less ade- sciences and their reflection by Nietzsche
quate and modified renewal of the task and Heidegger any justice at all. So all I will
assigned to us by Nietzsche. (ibid. 7) do here is to point to Nietzsches reflection,
especially in the Antichrist as a preparation
Still in 1943, in a text on Nietzsches Word for Heideggers critique of technology and
God is Dead, Heidegger understands the quickly to circumscribe Heideggers argu-
essentially important task set by Nietzsches ment that finally Nietzsches critique remains
work as enabling us to think in the midst of wholly on the side of metaphysics. To do so,
the sciences, to pass by them without dis- let us see if we can find a short quotation
daining them (GA 5, 207). Heidegger thus clarifying what Heidegger expects from a
again credits Nietzsche with the insight that historical reflection on science if it then is to
the interpretation of nihilism necessarily overcome the metaphysical delimitation of
leads us to a critique of science in the appear- philosophy, thereby putting the critique of
ance of modern technology. The sciences Nietzsche into perspective:
here are always thought of in the more essen-
tial sense of Wissenschaft, rather than only in The normative delimitation of the essence
terms of the more narrow idea of the natu- of place and of time for all metaphysics is
ral sciences. found in a physics. Roughly speaking,
this entails that place and time are not

126
HEIDEGGER AND NIETZSCHE

conceived in terms of their relation to nihilism remains short of enabling us to


history or to human beings as historical, experience its metaphysical essence (NII,
but rather are thought with respect to 336). Nietzsche says that nihilism holds sway
mere processes of movement in general. when the highest values devalue themselves.
As such, the places and sequences of
While the introduction of the notion of val-
events in human history also fall into
ues seems to place the question of science
dimensions, that is, into those realms
in which space and time can be measured on a ground independent from the presum-
numerically. The representations of space ably value-free methodology of the sciences,
and time that have held reign for almost thereby opening up a critique of science that,
two and a half thousand years are of a as Nietzsche argued, needs to locate the
metaphysical kind. (GA 53, 65f) problem of science outside of its own terri-
tory (BT, 5), on closer inspection these values
This, for Heidegger, is the essential delinea- seem themselves derived from the fundamen-
tion of metaphysics as instituted by Aristotles tally physical foundation of the doctrines
Physics, and he claims that this idea of phys- of Eternal Recurrence and Will to Power.
ics determining metaphysics holds equally In other words, Nietzsche understands val-
for Thomas Aquinas doctrine of the actus ues generally with respect to a so much, to
purus, of Hegels absolute notion, as of quantum and number, as Heidegger argues
Nietzsches thinking of Eternal Recurrence in Nietzsches Word: God is Dead (GA 5,
and Will to Power (GA 40, 14), especially as 223). In the same way as Nietzsches main
both have been developed from the funda- doctrines are derived from the foundation of
mental essence of our understanding of the modern physics, Nietzsche argues that one
physical universe since Leibniz and Newton. would have to make an attempt to base a
While Heidegger grants that this is not what scientific order of values on a numerical scale
Nietzsche has intended (NI, 134), he claims of measures of forces . . .allother values
that it was using the language of physiol- are prejudices, naiveties, misunderstand-
ogy and biology, which hold him back in the ings . . .they are always reducible to that
metaphysical context of his time. Already numerical scale of measures of forces.4
the central reflection of Nietzsche under the It is on this account that Heidegger claims
title of the physiology of art would therefore that Nietzsche does not exceed the experience
condemn him to biologism (NI, 109), in such of modern metaphysics. Or, the misunder-
a way that all further reflections concern- standing of the origin of values is the rea-
ing possibility and necessity would reduce son for which he fails to reach into the true
these to modes of the real (GA 66, 187). Yet essence of philosophy (GA 40, 152). And this
this thinking from out of reality is what not reaching, according to Heidegger, is philo-
Heidegger conceives of as the forgetting of sophically due to his self-proclaimed aim of
the question of being as separate from beings, reversing Platonism. While Nietzsche was
while Nietzsche, even in his later work still the first thinker properly to have understood
affirms, as Heidegger claims, the primacy of the importance of Plato in the history of
beings (NI, 477). philosophy, more so than even Hegel, who
According to Heidegger, it is for the same understood his philosophy as the realization
reason that Nietzsches understanding of of Platonic logos-philosophy, it is exactly

127
HEIDEGGER AND NIETZSCHE

for this reason that he cannot proceed to makes Heidegger say that only a God can
overcome Platonism. Accordingly, insofar save us (GA 16, 671).
as Nietzsches thought is and was always a As we have seen by means of the above
consistent but also ambiguous dialogue with confusion of arguments, Heidegger, after dec-
Plato (NII, 221), he interprets pre-Socratic ades of reflection on Nietzsches philosophical
thought from a Platonic perspective (GA 65, thought, a thought that lies at the foundation
219). of his own, will never quite come to a deci-
The difference between the thought of sion concerning its location in the history of
Nietzsche and Heidegger, then, essentially European thought. Thus we are still wonder-
goes back to the fundamental estimation ing whether Nietzsche is the last metaphysi-
of the role of philosophical thinking. While cian or whether, in his last steps, Nietzsche
Nietzsche keeps himself within the philo- has left metaphysics behind (NI, 618). Finally,
sophical tradition that since Aristotle sees thus, Nietzsche remains, even after Heideggers
truth as a determination and a result of extensive meditation on his thought, the phi-
thinking (362), Heidegger argues that from losopher who is still to come (340).
all the above follows Nietzsches misunder-
standing of the role of philosophy. Indeed,
as Heidegger claims, no doctrine will ever NOTES AND REFERENCES
be able to change the fate of our existence.
Rather any change has to arise from Dasein 1
Rita Casale, Heideggers Nietzsche: Geschichte
itself (GA 54, 81). This explains the rather einer Obsession (Bielefeld, Transcript Verlag,
contrary understanding that Nietzsche 2010), 21.
and Heidegger have concerning the role of
2
Friedrich Nietzsche, On the Uses and
Disadvantages of History for Life, in Untimely
philosophy. While Nietzsche thinks of the Meditations (Cambridge: CUP, 1997), ed.
philosopher as the author of history, and Daniel Breazeale, 57144.
therefore as the most active individual 3
Martin Heidegger, Die Bedrohung der
following the major outlines of Platonic and Wissenschaft, in: Zur philosophischen
Leibnizean thoughtin Heideggers under- Aktualitt Heideggers, vol I, edited by Dietrich
Papenfuss und Otto Pggeler, Frankfurt
standing the philosopher has a much more a.M.:Klostermann 1991.
modest role to play. It is breaking with the 4
Friedrich Nietzsche, Der Wille zur Macht,
identity of Being and Thinking that finally Krner Verlag: Stuttgart 1964, 710.

128
14
Heidegger and Dilthey:
A Difference in Interpretation
Eric S. Nelson

Introduction hermeneutical and life-philosophical themes.2


Nonetheless, Heidegger did not disregard
It is arguable how extensively the histori- Dilthey in Being and Time as he continued
cally and hermeneutically oriented life- to draw on concepts and strategies from
philosophy (Lebensphilosophie) of Wilhelm Diltheys writings. Heideggers conclusion
Dilthey (18331911) influenced Heideggers that the preparatory existential and tem-
intellectual development between the end poral analytic of Dasein is resolved to culti-
of the First World War and the publica- vate the spirit of Count Yorck in the service
tion of Being and Time. There is a strong of Diltheys work (SZ, 404; BT, 369) indi-
thesis maintaining that there was a whole cates both a critical spiritual distance from
period in the early and/or mid-1920s and Dilthey as well as a concern with continu-
even a draft of Being and Time inspired ing, in some sense, Diltheys project, which
by Dilthey.1 A more minimalistic interpre- Dilthey portrayed as a critique of historical
tation supports the claim that the scope reason.
and depth of Diltheys impact is exagger-
ated, highlighting instead an intellectual
formation shaped by modern German
Scholasticism, neo-Kantianism, Husserls Life-Philosophy and Historical
phenomenology, and the general existential Life
and life-philosophical intellectual climate of
the postwar years. Dilthey is credited with motivating the intro-
Others, like Hans-Georg Gadamer, empha- duction of the language of hermeneutics
size the importance for Heidegger of Count into Heideggers early thought. Yet, in
Paul Yorck von Wartenburg (183597), addition to hermeneutics and historicity,
Diltheys more politically conservative, phil- Heidegger stresses in his earliest remarks
osophically speculative, and theologically concerning Dilthey the priority of the ques-
oriented friend and correspondent (1835 tion of life, and particularly the being and
97) over Diltheys more humanistic, liberal, reality of the life that poses this question and
and scientifically oriented articulation of he continues this theme in Wilhelm Diltheys

129
HEIDEGGER AND DILTHEY

Research and the Struggle for a Historical thought. In 1925, Heidegger claimed that
Worldview (1925). Heidegger describes Dilthey penetrated into that reality, namely,
here how this question of life and human life human Dasein which, in the authentic sense,
reflects a crisis in knowledge and life that has is in the sense of historical being. He suc-
shaken the sciences and ordinary life itself ceeded in bringing this reality to givenness,
and created the conditions of a struggle for defining it as living, free, and historical
a historical world view (S, 148). (S,159). This is not pure life, however, as
What distinguished Diltheys conception Heidegger notes how Dilthey elucidates the
of life from other conceptions, and intrigued structures of the primary vital unity of
the early Heidegger, was the threefold artic- life itself (156). What Heidegger gestures
ulation of life in Diltheys mature magnum to here is Diltheys articulation of the cat-
opus The Formation of the Historical World egories of life (such as selfsameness, doing
in the Human Sciences (1910) as (1) expe- and undergoing, and essentiality) that are
rientially lived (Erlebnis), (2) structured dynamically given in reality and constituted
through and embodied in its expressions and and enacted in the interpretive processes of
objectifications (Ausdruck), and (3) inter- life itself rather than grasped as abstract and
pretively enacted and understood (verste- fixed categories or forms of the understand-
hen). All three modalities are fundamentally ing (Verstand). Diltheys model of an imma-
historical insofar as they encompass rela- nent, self-generative, and worldly formation
tions of resistance, conflict, and the fullness of sense and meaning informed Heideggers
of a greater life-context or connectedness rethinking of categories as existentiell and
(Lebenszusammenhang). existenzial structures.
Heidegger differentiated Diltheys inter-
pretation of life as historically mediated from
the immediacy of both biologicalwhether
mechanistic and vitalisticconceptions of The Ontic and the Ontological
life as well as appeals to the self-intuitive cer-
tainty or introspective transparency of life or According to Dilthey, a specifically mod-
consciousness to itself in early lecture courses ernistic conception of life-philosophy calls
such as the Phenomenology of Intuition and for interpreting life from out of itself.3
Expression (PIE, 129/GA 59). Diltheys life Dilthey confronted the idealization of the
is consequently fundamentally that of the nonconceptual with the unavoidability of
historian (S, 152); that is, a kind of external, conceptual mediation and self-reflection.4
formal, ultimately aesthetic construction of However, despite Diltheys hermeneutical
life even if it is does not attain that presumed approach to the categories of life and the
objectivity of the natural scientist (PIE, 128). generation of meaning, Heidegger rejects
Despite Heideggers suspicions throughout the modernistic epistemological focus of
the 1920s of the exteriority and distance of Diltheys writings while also contending that
life to itself in Dilthey, which is indeed what Diltheyeven if coming closest, but failing
makes human life intrinsically interpretive like all life-philosophy in the enddid not
and hermeneutical for Dilthey, Heidegger adequately attain the categorical-conceptual
recognized at the same time the primor- clarity and ontological character of the
diality of the question of life in Diltheys self-articulation of life (GA 21, 216; SZ, 46).

130
HEIDEGGER AND DILTHEY

Whereas the turn toward the imma- the world as world; it does not first ontically
nence of life led to empirical and interpre- observe and inquire, as Diltheys hermeneuti-
tive work in psychology, anthropology, and cal experientialism suggests.
human scientific inquiry in Diltheys thought, The lack of unity, the inductive incom-
Heidegger demanded a more radical dis- pleteness, and the danger of relativity that
tinction between ontic inquiry into entities Heidegger criticizes in Dilthey is a conse-
(whether in the human or natural sciences) quence of Diltheys pre-phenomenological
and the ontological task of phenomenology methodology. Heidegger noted that Dilthey
and philosophy. Accordingly, Heidegger con- prefigured phenomenology and was one of
cludes that Dilthey did not pose the ques- the first to appreciate the radical nature of
tion of historicity itself, the question of the Husserls project. Nonetheless, Heidegger
sense of being, i.e., concerning the being of consistently maintained throughout his
beings. It is only since the development of active reception of Diltheys work from 1918
phenomenology that we are in a position to to 1927 that we are indebted to him for
pose this question clearly (S, 159). valuable intuitions, which, however, do not
Heidegger repeats the charge in Being and reach down to ultimate and primordial prin-
Time as he credits Yorck with prefiguring the ciples and to radical purity and novelty of
ontological difference by distinguishing,in con- method; that is, the self-evidence of things
trast with Dilthey, the historical-ontological disclosed only by phenomenology (TDP, 140;
and the historiological-ontic (SZ, 399400).5 S, 160).
This distinction is not entirely absent in
Dilthey, where it entails the unbreakable rela-
tion between history as science and history as
facticity. For Heidegger, it constitutes the dif- RESISTANCE AND FACTICAL LIFE7
ference between the ontic science of history
or historiography (Historie) and history as According to Dilthey, the phenomenon of
ontological enactment, occurrence, and event resistance is what enables the formation of a
(Geschichte). Heidegger separates Historie worldly self; that is, a self that cannot purely
from Geschichte, a tendency that culminated be itself to the extent that it is always thrown
in his history of being (Seinsgeschichte), and entangled in relations with others and
whereas Dilthey emphasized the mediated objects. Self and resistant world are neither
intertwinement of historical lived-experience independent nor derivative of the other, they
(the lived history that we are) and historical are co-given or equiprimordial. It is accord-
research (the academic history that we study) ingly a kind of difference that is the condi-
through self-reflection and interpretation. tion of self-identity. Resistance is a primary
Heidegger revisits this issue once again feature of Diltheys thought for the early
when he argues that in Diltheys orientation Heidegger. Its significance is to some extent
toward the sciences and worldviews, being underestimated in the reception of Heidegger
(Sein) is lost in beings (Seiende), the world due to his critique of reality as resisting in
vanishes in a plurality of worlds, and the Being and Time (SZ, 209). In that context,
ontological difference disappears in unending Heidegger rejected resistance as proving the
ontic differences (GA 27, 3678, 38290).6 externality of the world, arguing that resist-
Dasein primordially understands and intuits ance already presupposes world. Despite his

131
HEIDEGGER AND DILTHEY

suspicion of an epistemological and ontic resistance in Being and Time (GA 61, 1301;
conception of resistance, which he associated SZ, 20911). Magda King notes how resist-
with Dilthey, resistance arguably remains ance characterizes beings within the world,
operative at various levels of Heideggers and by no means explains the phenomenon
thinkingfrom the resistance of things in of the world.8 Resistance occurs from out of
the breakdown of their instrumental and the world rather than being the how or way
pragmatic purposiveness to the resistance of in which the world can be grasped as world.
existence to human projects and understand- It is significant though that Heidegger pro-
ing in the impossibility of mastering and vides an ontological basis for resistance while
appropriating ones own death. rejecting its apparent ontic and empirical
Worldly resistance continues to inform character in Dilthey: Resistance gives a fac-
Heideggers early hermeneutics of factical life, tical existence to understand his exposedness
as experience is still related to the resistant to and dependence upon a world of things
insofar as experience is both passive and active which, in spite of all technical progress, he
and implies a differentiating setting-apart-with can never master.9
(Sich-Auseinander-setzen-mit) and the Heidegger perceived in his Kassel lectures
self-assertion of what is experienced (GA that the epistemological and methodologi-
60, 9). The origin and goal of philosophy is cal aspects of Diltheys thinking need to be
factical life understanding and articulating considered in light of the centrality of the
itself, as thinking springs from its facticity in question and conception of life. Historical
order to return to it (8, 15). The resistance of knowledge is self-reflexive, and thus turns
facticity not only opens access to the world on the self relating to itself as well as to its
through differentiation, it equally resists and worldly context. The life that reflects upon
blocks access to itself in its everyday indiffer- itself is confronted by its own historicity and
ence (12, 1516). conditionality in attempting to know itself.
Heidegger further transformed Diltheys Accordingly, the self is a world to itself along
conception of resistance as the ruination, with an environing world and a world of oth-
counter-movedness, and transversal of life ers. For Heidegger, this self-world in factical
(GA 61, 185). The there in and from which life is neither a thing nor an ego in the episte-
the I occurs is primordially resistant and mological sense, rather it has the character
ruinating (ibid.). Thus, despite Heideggers of a definite significance, that of possibility
suspicion of resistance as an argument for (GA 58, 232; GA 61, 94). The self-world is
the self-existence of the external world, not a denial of others, it indicates how the
Diltheys notion of resistance is appropriated I is always referred to others and the world
and transformed in Heideggers thinking of in the equiprimordiality of the self-world,
lifes facticity. with-world, and environing world (GA 61,
In contrast to this account of resistance 95). These three overlapping co-constitutive
as (1) the key to individuation and (2) the worlds make up the life-world such that
counter-movement of life, which is imma- they cannot be separated from each other
nent to life insofar as it is life itself that or interpreted as self-sufficient (96). Hence,
presents us with its own ruination and ques- despite the constitutive but cogiven signifi-
tionability, we can compare (3) Heideggers cance of the self-world in these early lec-
critical interpretation of Diltheys account of ture courses, Heidegger problematized the

132
HEIDEGGER AND DILTHEY

primacy of the subject as separate from life. affective, historical, and worldly (GA 20,
Life can neither be understood as merely an 161).13 Diltheys project was, however, a
object or a subject (GA 58, 236). flawed anti-naturalist personalism and a
Diltheys primary concern is with the his- failed phenomenology that gave the natu-
torically embedded self and its potential for ralistic and scientistic perspective too much
self-knowledge in which the being who ques- authority (ibid.). Diltheys works are con-
tions is at the same time addressed by and sequently an ambiguous source for the new
included in the question of who it is. Life phenomenology. Heideggers criticisms of
confronts me as personal in being my own Dilthey did not go unanswered, as some of
life to live even as the subject of that life Heideggers earliest critics were former stu-
is inevitably differentiated from itself by liv- dents of Dilthey, such as Georg Misch (1878
ing in a historical and worldly context (GS 1965), or scholars who were in part inspired
19, 3467).10 Life is then not only the ground by his philosophical project, such as Helmuth
of knowledge, it resists it and is thus in the Plessner (18921985). Georg Mischs
last instance unknowable. The facticity of Lebensphilosophie und Phnomenologie:
life is the last ground of knowledge, such Eine Auseinandersetzung der Diltheyschen
that knowledge cannot penetrate behind its Richtung mit Heidegger und Husserl
own facticity.11 Life endeavors to understand (1929/1930) is one of the first sustained cri-
itself while remaining non-transparent and tiques of Heidegger, which he responded to
ineffable to itself; human life is consequently in his lecture-courses and correspondence.
necessarily interpretive or hermeneutical. Based on Misch and Plessners arguments,
Such alterity, excess, and remainder that rest- it could well be argued that Diltheys full
lessly pulls life out of itself is a concern in hermeneutical legacy only partially resonates
Heideggers early thinking from the singular in the ontologically oriented hermeneutics of
thisness (haecceitas) of his early work on Heidegger and Gadamer, as neither of them
Duns Scotus to the thisness and mineness further articulated the emergence and individ-
(Jemeinigkeit) of my existence in Being and uation of the biographical human individual
Time. As Dilthey explicated lived-experience immanently from the mediating contexts of a
as an exposure to lifes facticity in its singular- natural-biological and social-historical life. In
ity and contingency, he should be considered contrast to Diltheys historical-anthropological
a primary source for interpreting Heideggers approach to human life, Heidegger asserts the
early philosophical project of a hermeneutics dignity of the ontological and the transcend-
of factical, or resistant, life (GS 19, 348). ent over against the complex mediations of
life that call for continuing empirical inquiry
and interpretive understanding.
From Diltheys perspective, as Misch
Divergent Legacies: HEIDEGGER, argued, Heidegger marginalized the dis-
mISCH, AND PLESSNER12 courses of the natural and human sciences as
ontic from the tasks of a fundamental ontol-
Heidegger was less influenced by Diltheys ogy. Heidegger did not recognize or allow for
personalist interpretive psychology, even the basic role that Dilthey gave the particu-
as he appreciated Dilthey as a thinker of lar sciences in interdisciplinary research and
human life as immanently self-interpretive, critical self-reflection. According to Misch,

133
HEIDEGGER AND DILTHEY

the dispersion in ontic multiplicity that Erste Hlfte (Gttingen: Vandenhoeck und
Heidegger criticizes in Diltheys thought is Ruprecht, 1957), 370.
4
I develop this point in Eric S. Nelson,
not the negation of the essence and dignity
Self-Reflection, Interpretation, and Historical
of philosophy, if it is the arena in which phi- Life in Dilthey, in ed. H.-U. Lessing, R. A.
losophy takes place as an event and enact- Makkreel, und R. Pozzo, Recent Contributions
ment not of impersonal being and neutral to Diltheys Philosophy of the Human Sciences
Daseina formal neutrality that is derived (Stuttgart: Frommann-holzboog, 2011),
10534.
after the fact from the partiality and

5
See Eric S. Nelson, The World Picture and its
perspectivality of historical life in Mischs Conflict in Dilthey and Heidegger, Humana.
estimationbut, extending Diltheys inter- Mente: Journal of Philosophical Studies, 18
pretive individualism, of individual and per- (2011), 33.
sonal biographical life.14
6
See Eric S. Nelson, History as Decision and
Event in Heidegger, Arhe, IV.8 (2007), 1024.
It was not in Heideggers phenomenology

7
This section draws on Nelson, The World
then, but in the bio-hermeneutical anthro- Picture and its Conflict in Dilthey and
pology of Plessner and hermeneutical logic Heidegger.
of Misch that the historically mediated char-
8
Magda King, A Guide to Heideggers Being
acter of nature and spirit continues to be and Time (New York: SUNY Press, 2001), 261.

9
Ibid., 261.
analyzed. Echoing Diltheys elucidation of 10
Wilhelm Dilthey, Gesammelte Schriften19:
an individuated self in the midst of the con- Grundlegung der Wissenschaften vom
ditions and forces of natural and historical Menschen, der Gesellschaft und der
life, Plessner corrected the partiality of natu- Geschichte Ausarbeitungen und Entwrfe
ralism and an anti-naturalistic personalism zum zweiten Band der Einleitung in die
Geisteswissenschaften (ca. 187095), edited by
by clarifying their immanent consistency in
Helmut Johach & Frithjof Rodi (Gttingen:
the formation of a relational self: that is, the Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1982), 3467.
naturally eccentric and artificial constructive 11
Wilhelm Dilthey, Leben Schleiermachers: Auf
animal called human occurring in the midst Grund des Textes der 1. Auflage von 1870 und
of historical life. der Zustze aus dem Nachla, ed. M. Redeker
(Gttingen: Vandenhoeck und Ruprecht,
1970), 53.
12
I examine this issue further in Eric S. Nelson,
NOTES AND REFERENCES Between Nature and Spirit: Naturalism and
Anti-Naturalism in Dilthey, in G. DAnna,
1
Compare Theodore Kisiel, The Genesis H. Johach, and E. S. Nelson, Anthropologie
of Heideggers Being and Time (Berkeley: und Geschichte. Studien zu Wilhelm Dilthey
University of California Press, 1993), 313; aus Anlass seines 100. Todestages (Wrzburg:
Otto Pggeler, Historicity in Heideggers Late Knigshausen & Neumann, 2013).
Work, ed. J. N. Mohanty and R. W Shahan, 13
Compare E. von Aster, Die Philosophie der
Thinking about Being: Aspects of Heideggers Gegenwart (Leiden: A. W. Sijthoff, 1935),
Thought (Norman: University of Oklahoma 149, 155.
Press, 1984), 56. 14
Georg Misch, Lebensphilosophie und
2
Hans-Georg Gadamer, Martin Heideggers Phanomenologie (Leipzig: Teubner, 1931), 47;
One Path, ed. Theodore Kisiel and John van on Mischs pluralistic and life-immanent per-
Buren, Reading Heidegger from the Start: sonalism, in contrast with Heideggers history
Essays in His Earliest Thought (Albany: SUNY of being, see Eric S. Nelson, Heidegger,
Press, 1994), 23. Misch, and the Origins of Philosophy, Journal
3
Wilhelm Dilthey, GS 5, Die Geistige Welt: of Chinese Philosophy, 39, Supplement
Einleitung in die Philosophie des Lebens. (2012).

134
15
Heidegger and Husserl
Leslie MacAvoy

Although Martin Heidegger engaged with apparent to Husserl until about 1927 when
a great many thinkers and philosophical Being and Time was published and when
positions in the early part of his career, his he invited Heidegger to collaborate with
relationship to Husserls phenomenology him on an article on phenomenology for
occupies a place of special importance. In the Encyclopedia Brittanica. In the course
1916 Edmund Husserl came to the University of this (failed) collaboration, the extent
of Freiburg, where Heidegger was a lecturer, of Heideggers departure from Husserls
to occupy the senior chair in philosophy. approach became evident.2 Husserl was dis-
Heidegger had become interested in Husserls appointed by the direction Heideggers work
phenomenology several years earlier and was was taking, and their philosophical relation-
already familiar with Logical Investigations, ship deteriorated after 1928 and was broken
and within the next couple of years, a philo- irremediably when Heidegger became rector
sophical friendship developed between them. of the university and joined the National
In time Husserl came to view Heidegger as Socialist party in 1933.
one of his most talented and promising stu- Although Husserl thought that Heidegger
dents, and expected him to play an important had drifted away from phenomenology,
role in his phenomenological research pro- Heidegger understood himself to be engag-
gram. Indeed, Husserl thought so highly of ing with important philosophical questions
Heidegger that he exerted considerable effort using its approach. This is evident through-
in advancing the young philosophers career. out much of his work during the 1910s and
He made Heidegger his assistant in 1919 and 1920s. While direct discussion of Husserls
supported him for an associate professor- work rarely appears in Heideggers texts,
ship at Marburg. Most significantly, Husserl the 1925 lecture course The History of the
advocated for Heidegger to succeed him in Concept of Time is a particularly impor-
the philosophy chair at Freiburg when he tant exception. This essay will consider
retired in 1928.1 Heideggers claims about the contributions of
Husserl and Heidegger were very close for phenomenology and the way he appropriates
about a decade, but signs that Heidegger was these contributions to develop his existential
drifting further from orthodox phenome- phenomenology and fundamental ontol-
nology became apparent during the Marburg ogy. Though clearly influenced by Husserls
years, though it may not have become phenomenology, Heidegger is also critical

135
HEIDEGGER AND HUSSERL

of it, and a clear understanding of how he particularly important for responding to the
responds to Husserl can facilitate a deeper psychologism objection, involves bracketing
understanding of his own philosophy. the empirical ego in order to direct the inten-
For Husserl phenomenology is a method tional analysis away from the psychological
for studying phenomena by analyzing the states of the particular person and toward
intentional acts of which they are corre- the meaning content of the experience as it
lates and through which they are given. belongs to a transcendental ego. This ideal
This intentional analysis is meant to yield meaning content can then be analyzed with
a logic of experience that can then be used regard to its structure.
to ground the sciences and epistemology. Although Husserl understands phenom-
In Logical Investigations the project is to enology as contributing to epistemology,
uncover the a priori logical principles that Heidegger argues that phenomenology is
guide thought, which turn out to be princi- instead a method for doing ontology. He
ples for the constitution of objects.3 These justifies this claim through an etymologi-
objects are validly formed wholes exhibiting cal analysis of the term phenomenology.5
a propositional structure. Thus, Husserl lik- Phenomenon means that which shows
ens these logical principles, derived through itself in itself or that which shows itself as
an analysis focused on the structure of inten- what it is while logos means what lets
tional acts and their objects, to an a priori something be seen. This yields a definition
logical grammar. of phenomenology as a discourse that lets
Husserl argues against a psychologistic things be seen as what they are. It is, to put
approach to logic in Logical Investigations, it in Husserls terms, a way of going to the
and he attempts to distinguish his position things themselves. But since to see some-
from psychologism by arguing that the objects thing as what it is is to see it in its being,
and content of intentional acts are ideal. Heidegger claims that phenomenology aims
However, critics of Logical Investigations to unpack the being of something and thus is
argued that his approach, which he charac- a method for doing ontology.
terized as a descriptive psychology, results In History of the Concept of Time
in its own kind of psychologism. It is gen- Heidegger maintains that the three most
erally thought that Husserl introduces the important contributions of phenomenology
phenomenological reduction in Ideas in are intentionality, categorial intuition, and
order to respond to these objections.4 The a particular view of the a priori. While this
reduction functions to suspend the empirical claim signals the importance of Husserls
components of an intentional act in order to work, particularly Logical Investigations, for
arrive at its ideal content. The first moment Heidegger, closer examination of his discus-
suspends the natural attitude to enable the sion of each of these three items reveals that
assumption of the phenomenological atti- he is already radicalizing Husserls concepts.
tude. In the natural attitude, we simply live The first concept that Heidegger
through our intentional relations and focus emphasizes is intentionality. In Logical
on the objects with which we are absorbed. Investigations, Husserl holds that intention-
By suspending this attitude, we can focus on ality is the structure of consciousness and
the acts through which these objects are given. indicates that consciousness always has an
A second moment of the reduction, which is object, though that object need not be an

136
HEIDEGGER AND HUSSERL

actual object. Rather, consciousness is always practical comportment. The chair, he says,
of something, and what it is conscious of is can be taken as one kind of thing or another
the intentional object. Further, Husserl notes based upon different intentional orienta-
that a given object might be intended in dif- tions. For instance, the chair can be taken as
ferent ways, and so he draws a distinction an environmental thing, as something to
between the object that is intended and the sit in, or it can be taken as a natural thing
object as it is intended, or between the inten- that is simply made of wood (GA 20, 4950/
tional object strictly speaking and its inten- HCT, 378). The idea of intentional sense,
tional sense. For instance, Napoleon might that is, how or as what an object is intended,
be intended either as victor at Jena or as van- develops here in the direction of the herme-
quished at Waterloo.6 Examples of this sort neutic as, which plays such an important
suggest that how something is intended is a role in Heideggers analysis of the reference
function of the predication that is performed and significance of equipment that shows up
in a judgment. as something to be used for some purpose
Heideggers discussion of intentionality is or another in the course of Daseins activ-
consistent with Husserls treatment up to a ity (GA 2, 149, 1578/BT, 1445, 1523).
point. He stresses that intentionality is the For instance, when in the kitchen making a
structure of lived experience (GA 20, 36/ cup of coffee, the kettle shows up as equip-
HCT, 29), and like Husserl he rejects the ment for boiling water. Items of equipment
view that intentionality is a kind of psychic ordinarily show up in terms of their usual
directedness toward a physical object. On meanings (e.g. that a kettle is for boiling
such a view an act is only intentional if it is water) because they are generally disclosed
in fact directed toward a real object, and this in relation to equipmental contexts that
would yield the result that false perceptions reflect established practices and the norms
or hallucinations would not be intentional. that govern them. However, Daseins pro-
Heidegger dismisses such objections as based jection of a goal is also determinative of
on a misunderstanding of intentionality and how an item of equipment is disclosed. So,
argues that false perceptions and hallucina- for example, if no kettle for boiling water
tions still contain a directedness toward an is available, a small pot might be disclosed
object. If I think I see a pink elephant, and for the purpose. Alternatively, if one needs
subsequently realize that I was hallucinat- to keep a cookbook open to a particular
ing, my hallucination was still directed at an page, the kettle might show up as handy for
object; it was still of something, namely a use as a paperweight. Thus, how the object
pink elephant. Any comportment whatsoever is taken is a function of ones comportment
has a directing-itself-toward as its struc- toward it based on ones project and ones
ture (GA 20, 3940/HCT, 31). background understanding of the situational
In other respects, however, Heidegger context. Regardless of whether one takes
departs from Husserl. In discussing the the kettle as a utensil for boiling water or
different ways an object can be intended, as a paperweight, one takes it as ready-to-
Heidegger uses the example of a chair in a hand in a sort of practical intentionality. For
manner that foreshadows his more devel- Heidegger, this taking-as is pre-predicative,
oped account of how things are disclosed and thus, in contrast to Husserl, the object
as equipment in worldly contexts through as it is intended is given, not in judgment,

137
HEIDEGGER AND HUSSERL

but in a pre-judgmental intentionality upon For Heidegger categorial intuition has


which judgment can subsequently be based. an additional significance, namely that it
The second Husserlian notion that apprehends being. That is, it is owing to cat-
Heidegger discusses is categorial intuition, egorial intuition that we can apprehend the
which as the term suggests refers to an intui- books being on the table (GA 20, 7181/
tion that apprehends the categorial structure HCT, 5360). Thus, it can be argued that
of objects (GA 20, 64/HCT, 48). In introduc- categorial intuition is crucial to Heideggers
ing this idea, Husserl draws the distinction view that phenomenology is a method for
between empty intentions that merely sig- ontology (GA 20, 98/HCT 72). Indeed,
nify their objects and intuitions that fulfill many years later in the Zhringen seminar
those intentions by giving the objects that in 1973, Heidegger refers to the importance
were previously only emptily meant. For of categorial intuition for his position (FS,
instance, if one says that the book is on the 67). Husserls abandoning of this important
table, a state of affairs, namely the books notion in Ideas may be one more reason
being on the table, is emptily intended. This why Heidegger, in his footnotes to Being and
same state of affairs can be given in an intui- Time, tends to be rather more approving of
tion that fulfills this intention, and such a Logical Investigations.
fulfillment might occur in a perception in Because of categorial intuition and the
which one sees the book on the table. If the access it gives us to being, Heidegger sur-
intuition fulfills the empty intention, then mises that phenomenology provides us with
that means that the intentional object, in a more original sense of the a priori than the
this case a state of affairs, is meant in the one inherited from the tradition, which tends
first case and given in the second. This raises to conceive of it in Kantian terms as a struc-
the question of whether the state of affairs ture of subjectivity that serves as a condi-
is given in simple perception strictly speak- tion of the possibility of knowledge (GA 20,
ing. Husserl claims, and Heidegger agrees, 99103/HCT, 725). Against this, Heidegger
that while certain elements of the state of thinks that there are a priori structures of the
affairs are given, for example, the book and being of entities, and that these can be drawn
the table, there are other elements that are out through categorial intuition. Here the
not, such as the definite article, the preposi- differences between Husserl and Heidegger
tion, and the copula is. Yet, if the state of come into sharper relief. For Husserl, cat-
affairs is given in intuition, which it is, then egorial intuition was important because it
these elements that are part of the state of was a way to help us extract the categorial
affairs must also be given, and so Husserl structure of objects with an eye toward iden-
concludes that there must be a categorial tifying the a priori logical principles of their
intuition.7 One reason this is significant for formation or constitution. For Heidegger,
both Husserl and Heidegger is that it chal- on the other hand, the goal is to disclose the
lenges those readings of Kant that hold that structure of being by identifying ontological
categories are added by subjectivity to what categories. Thus, for Heidegger phenomenol-
is given in intuition (Hua XIX/2, 1824; ogy provides a method for arriving at a new
GA 20, 79/HCT 59). Here the view is that sense of the ontological a priori.
objects are given in intuition as already cat- Thus, Heideggers discussion of the three
egorially formed. fundamental contributions of phenomenology

138
HEIDEGGER AND HUSSERL

is not simply an account of its past accom- view that this entity is consciousness is, for
plishments, but is instead a sketch of its Heidegger, to beg the question on this point.
future direction toward ontology. He writes: Heideggers second objection is to the
We have thus determined that intentional- phenomenological reduction, which he also
ity gives us the proper field of subject matter, thinks distorts the investigation of intention-
the a priori gives us the regard under which ality. Both moments of the reduction noted
the structures of intentionality are consid- above are problematic. The first moment of
ered, and categorial intuition as the originary the reduction involves suspending the natural
way of apprehending these structures repre- attitude, which Husserl thought would bring
sents the mode of treatment, the method of the intentional into focus. But Heidegger
this research (GA 20, 109/HCT, 80). That thinks that the reduction brackets the real-
is, phenomenology is a method for analyzing ity of the intentional and thus takes us away
being because being is given as the a priori from the phenomenon that should be investi-
element in intentional objects, and catego- gated. He writes:
rial intuition gives us a way of isolating this
a priori element. The challenge will be to see we start from the real consciousness in
how Heidegger intends to make good on this the factually existing human, but this
sketch of the direction for future phenom- takes place only in order finally to disre-
gard it and to dismiss the reality of con-
enological research.
sciousness as such. In its methodological
To do that, it is necessary to consider
sense as a disregarding, then, the reduc-
what Heidegger takes to be the limitation of tion is in principle inappropriate for
Husserls phenomenology. There are two pri- determining the being of consciousness
mary objections to mention, both of which positively. The sense of the reduction
are articulated in History of the Concept of involves precisely giving up the ground
Time. The first and more important objec- upon which alone the question of the
tion is that Husserl fails to explore the being being of the intentional could be based.
of intentionality because of his uncritical (GA 20, 150/HCT, 109)
appropriation of the traditions notion of
consciousness, which Heidegger thinks is not Heidegger also objects to the second moment
drawn from the things themselves (GA 20, of the reduction, in which the particularity
1402, 147/HCT, 1023, 107). Thus, Husserl of the ego is suspended in favor of the tran-
is not true to his own phenomenological scendental ego. This, too, transforms the
method when it comes to consciousness, and character of intentionality from something
the result is a distorted view of intentionality that is necessarily individuated and mine to
modeled on the theoretical attitude, namely, something that in principle belongs to any-
a detached stance wherein intentional objects one. Heidegger thinks that both moments
are construed as presented to consciousness of the reduction focus on the what of the
in judgments. Heidegger questions the prior- intentional experience and ignore the how
ity that Husserl gives to the theoretical atti- of that experience and thus fail to capture
tude in his theory of intentionality and claims something important about intentionality.
that to understand the being of intentional- This leads Heidegger to conclude that if the
ity, it is necessary to understand the entity intentional is to be interrogated regarding
that is intentional. To accept the traditional its manner of being, then the entity which is

139
HEIDEGGER AND HUSSERL

intentional must be originally given, that is, it involved-in [care]. (GA 20, 420/HCT,
must be originally experienced in its manner 3034)
of being (GA 20, 152/HCT, 110). In other
words, to explore intentionality, we need a This suggests that Husserls view of inten-
phenomenological analysis of the being who tionality is partial and covers over some
is intentional. more primordial intentionality indicated
That being is Dasein, and Heidegger by Daseins Being as care. One might take
develops extensive analyses of Dasein and this to mean that care represents a kind of
its being in Being and Time. Where Husserl practical intentionality that is more primor-
focuses on intentionality as a feature of dial than the intentionality exemplified by
consciousness that can be thought about in the theoretical attitude found in Husserl.
abstraction from its existence, Heidegger However, in Being and Time Heidegger
emphasizes that Dasein is an entity whose writes that as a primordial structural
essence lies in its existence and whose exist- totality, care lies before every factical atti-
ence is always individuated and personal tude and position of Dasein, that is, it is
(GA 2, 412/BT, 412). Intentionality, as always already in them as an existential a
Husserl claimed and Heidegger averred, is priori. Thus this phenomenon by no means
the structure of lived experience, but the expresses a priority of practical over theo-
structure of Daseins lived experience is retical behavior (GA 2, 193/BT, 187). Thus,
shown by Heideggers analyses to consist the priority of care does not amount to
in Being-in-the-world. Daseins intentional reversing the order of priority that Husserl
relations are expressed in its practical com- gives to the theoretical over the practical.
portment in the world, which is in turn While it is true that Heidegger does want to
possible on the basis of the disclosedness focus more on practical comportment and
of the being of the world and of the enti- that he does seem to think of it as a kind of
ties within it. Thus, Daseins dealings in the intentionality, the point here is largerit is
world are the site of its intentionality. But in that care is the ground of any intentionality
the end, Daseins being is not to be under- at all. Care is not a comportment; it is what
stood as coextensive with this comport- makes comportment possible. Daseins Being
ment. By the end of Division I of Being and as care opens up the world as a sphere of
Time, Heidegger comes to the conclusion intelligibility that serves as a horizon for the
that Daseins Being is care. In History of the encounter of entities and, through this prior
Concept of Time, Heidegger writes that: disclosedness, makes comportment toward
entities possible. The analysis of Daseins
It could be shown from the phenomenon being as care and Being-in-the-world is the
of care as the basic structure of Dasein analysis of the entity who is intentional that
that what phenomenology took to be Heidegger thinks is missing from Husserls
intentionality and how it took it is frag-
phenomenology.
mentary, a phenomenon regarded merely
Husserl himself thought that Heideggers
from the outside. But what is meant by
intentionalitythe bare and isolated work was unrecognizable as phenomenology
directing-itself-towardsmust still be set and believed that Heidegger had misunder-
back into the unified basic structure of stood it in drawing it away from epistemol-
being-ahead-of-itself-in-already-being- ogy and toward ontology. However, one

140
HEIDEGGER AND HUSSERL

can readily see that Heidegger was deeply at the Encyclopedia Britannica Article, in
engaged not only with Husserls work but Husserl, Heidegger, and the Space of Meaning
(Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press,
with what he took to be the task of phe-
2001), 16781.
nomenology. Heidegger arrives at the posi- 3
Edmund Husserl, Logische Untersuchungen,
tion that phenomenology is ontology and hrsg. Elmar Holenstein, Husserliana: Band
requires an analysis of Dasein in part by XVIIIXIX (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff,
thinking through Husserls work with the 1975, 1984); Logical Investigations, trans.
J.N.Findlay (New York: Routledge, 1970).
aim of extending and radicalizing it. There
(Hua VIII, XIX/1, XIX/2).
can be no doubt that Husserls philosophy 4
Edmund Husserl, Ideen zu einer reinen
exerted a deep influence on the development Phnomenologie und phnomenologischen
of Heideggers thought. Philosophie: Erster Teil, hrsg. Karl Schuhmann,
Husserliana: Band III (The Hague: Martinus
Nijhoff, 1950; rev. edn 1976); Ideas
Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and a
NOTES AND REFERENCES Phenomenological Philosophy: Book One,
trans. Fred Kersten (The Hague: Martinus
1
For biographical information, see Hugo Ott, Nijhoff, 1983).
Martin Heidegger: A Political Life (London: 5
See GA 2, 2839/BT, 2637, and GA 20,
Harper Collins, 1993). 11021/HCT, 808.
2
See Steven Galt Crowell, Husserl, Heidegger, 6
Hua XIX/1, Investigation I.
and Transcendental Philosophy: Another Look 7
Hua XIX/2, Investigation VI.

141
16
Heidegger, Neo-Kantianism,
and Cassirer
Peter E. Gordon

Of the many contemporary philosophical philosophy of its metaphysical obscurities and


schools of the early twentieth century that restoring it to its proper task as a critique of
aroused Heideggers interest, the neo-Kantian knowledge. In his early work, Kants Theory
school provoked greatest ambivalence. On of Experience (1871), the German-Jewish
the one hand, neo-Kantianism appears, espe- philosopher Hermann Cohen laid down
cially in Heideggers early work, as a para- the movements guiding insight that Kant
digmatic philosophy of modernity: It is was best understood as an epistemologist
understood to be afflicted by some of the car- and a theorist of scientific method. During
dinal errors of the modern worldsubjectiv- his tenure as Professor of Philosophy at the
ism, scientism, and the forgetting of Being Philipps-Universitt in Marburg, Cohen,
(Seinsvergessenheit). On the other hand, in alliance with his colleague Paul Natorp,
Heidegger trained with the neo-Kantian became a charismatic leader of the so-called
Heinrich Rickert, and key themes of Kantian Marburg school where many of the leading
and neo-Kantian philosophy left their mark philosophers of the early twentieth century
on Heideggers early thought. Especially dur- were to receive their training. Equally influ-
ing the 1920s, Heidegger made frequent and ential was the Southwestern, or Baden
largely negative reference to neo-Kantianism. School of neo-Kantianism at Heidelberg and
His criticism of the philosopher Ernst Freiburg, which took shape under the guid-
Cassirer was particularly intense and culmi- ance of Wilhelm Windelband, and later Emil
nated in the dramatic 1929 confrontation Lask and Heinrich Rickert. Whereas the
between the two philosophers in Davos, Marburg School focused chiefly on themes
Switzerland.1 in Kantian epistemology, the Southwestern
The neo-Kantian movement in Germany neo-Kantians paid greater attention to the
first arose in the later nineteenth century philosophy of value and sought to theorize
in opposition to dominant trends in both the epistemological distinction between the
Hegelian and Schopenhauerian philosophy. natural sciences and human sciences, includ-
Following Otto Liebmanns exhortation, ing history.2
back to Kant, a diverse group of schol- Building upon the Kantian idea of a strong
ars united in the twofold effort of purging divide between theoretical and practical

143
HEIDEGGER, NEO-KANTIANISM, AND CASSIRER

reason, the Southwestern neo-Kantians argued between two ways of knowing, historical
that the law-like (or nomothetic) character and natural-scientific, became in Heideggers
of explanation in the natural sciences was philosophy an ontological and normative
ill-suited to the understanding of uniquely distinction between authentic and inauthen-
meaning-laden events in the human sci- tic modes of existence.3
ences. The human realm possessed its own Heideggers attitude toward the Marburg
idiographic method suitable for understand- School was more conflicted. His ambivalence
ing unique occurrences rather than law-like was due chiefly to an acknowledged affinity
regularities. Rickerts theories concerning the in philosophical doctrine, between transcen-
distinctive character of concept-formation in dental idealism and Heideggers own view
historical understanding (as presented in his of Dasein as the existential condition for the
1902 book, The Limits of Concept-Formation disclosure of the world. According to Kant,
in Natural Science) left a deep imprint on the world owes its order and fundamen-
Heideggers own theories of history. The tal intelligibility to the rules and forms (the
early Heidegger saw the human understand- categories and the pure forms of intui-
ing of history as grounded in a deeper phe- tion) that are an essential endowment of the
nomenon of human historical existence. He human mind. Insofar as it is only in virtue
contrasted human historicity with what he of these rules and forms that things appear
called the time-free realm of nature (HCT, as a well-ordered world, we can say that the
230). This project comes most to the fore in world of possible experience just is the world
Being and Time where Heidegger seeks to of appearances governed by the mind. This
show how Daseins own world owes its very doctrine of transcendental idealism impor-
intelligibility to an underlying temporal pro- tantly resembles the doctrine of existential
jection, or historicity (Geschichtlichkeit), conditions Heideggers lays down in Being
without which our everyday understanding and Time: Dasein, Heidegger argues, is the
of historical events would not be possible. only being endowed with an understanding of
This strong view regarding the primor- Being (or Seinsverstndnis). This understand-
dial or ontological constitution of historical ing of Being is itself embedded in Daseins
experience reinforces Heideggers view that very own manner of being-in-the-world, or
situated cultural-historical understanding is existence, whose structure Heidegger anato-
prior to (and deeper than) natural-scientific mizes in the existential analytic. This anal-
understanding. The latter is demoted to a ysis reveals the basic modes of existence, or
species of merely technological reason that existentials that serve as the conditions for
requires a decontextualization or deworld- the possibility of Daseins world. The note-
ing (Entweltlichung) of Daseins care-laden worthy resemblance between transcendental
world (SZ, 112/ BT, 147). This distinction idealism (Kant) and the existential analytic
contributed to Heideggers well-known (Heidegger) is due to the fact that both doc-
view that, due to the dominance of technol- trines aim to show that the only world of
ogy and the natural sciences, modernity is relevance to the human being is the world as
prone to misrecognize or forget its proper it shows up in virtue of certain endowments
(eigentlich) manner of temporal being. What that are peculiar to human understanding or
had been for the Southwestern neo-Kantians existence. These endowments are therefore
an essentially methodological distinction transcendental conditions in the Kantian

144
HEIDEGGER, NEO-KANTIANISM, AND CASSIRER

sense. The strong dissimilarity is that, while abandoned: the Kantian faculty of sensi-
Kant sees these conditions as grounded in bility (and space and time as the two pure
the mind, Heidegger sees them as grounded forms of intuition) could no longer be seen as
in existence. making an equal contribution, alongside the
That Heidegger appreciated his philo- understanding, to the constitution of knowl-
sophical debts to Kants doctrine of transcen- edge. Instead, Cohen saw space and time as
dental idealism is obvious. In Being and Time conceptual in nature and he understood the
he writes that Being is the transcendens pure thing-in-itself as an object having its origin in
and simple. In a later chapter he suggests thought alone. Cohen modeled this idea, the
that Being is in the consciousness, and principle of origins (or Ursprungsprinzip)
he endorses the transcendental premises of after the calculus, where, on Cohens inter-
Kants critical turn: If what the term ideal- pretation, an infinitesimally small magnitude
ism says, amounts to the understanding that is generated from logical procedure. The
Being can never be explained by entities but principle of origins distinguishes Cohens
is already that which is transcendental for revisionist interpretation of Kantianism as
every entity, then idealism affords the only strongly intellectualist and anti-metaphysical
correct possibility for a philosophical prob- in character, and it is precisely this revision
lematic (SZ, 3/ BT, 22; and SZ, 2078/BT, that Heidegger found most objectionable.
251). But notwithstanding the transcendental In his Freiburg inaugural address, What
character of his project, Heidegger harbored is Metaphysics, Heidegger went so far as
fundamental objections to what he consid- to suggest that Cohens principle of origins
ered the metaphysical premises of Kants misunderstood the priority of thought to
philosophy.4 Most of all, he rejected the existence. The revelation of Daseins non-
intellectualist premise that the transcenden- foundational condition was the primary phe-
tal conditions for possible experience are pri- nomenon of the nothing out of which was
marily conceptual rather than intuitive and born negation as a logical function: The
embedded in worldly existence. The attempt nothing is the origin of negation, not vice
to overturn the priority of concepts in the versa. If the power of the intellect in the field
constitution of a priori synthetic knowledge of inquiry into the nothing and into Being is
is among the major tasks of Heideggers Kant thus shattered, then the fate of the reign of
and the Problem of Metaphysics. logic in philosophy is thereby decided. The
The desire to overturn the priority of idea of logic itself disintegrates in the turbu-
concepts over intuitions may also explain lence of a more original questioning.5
Heideggers objection to the revisionist Heideggers largely negative assessment of
interpretation of Kantianism articulated the neo-Kantian legacy also extended Cohens
by Hermann Cohen in The Logic of Pure disciples. Ernst Cassirer (18741945) was a
Knowledge (1902). On Cohens view Kants German philosopher of Jewish descent who
adherence to the metaphysical independence taught at the University of Hamburg during
of the thing-in-itself (Ding an sich) repre- the era of the Weimar Republic (191933).
sented an embarrassing concession to the With the Nazi seizure of power he was forced
nave empiricism of precritical philosophy. into exile and spent the 1930s in transit (stay-
A properly critical perspective demanded ing in Vienna, Oxford, and Sweden) before
that this metaphysical independence be arriving in the United States in 1941. Early in

145
HEIDEGGER, NEO-KANTIANISM, AND CASSIRER

his career Cassirer authored important stud- a footnote to Being and Time Heidegger
ies on the history and philosophy of science, recalls that in 1923 he had met Cassirer at
Substance and Function, Einsteins Theory of a Hamburg meeting of the Kant-Society and
Relativity, and The Problem of Knowledge, that we agreed in demanding an existential
works that reflect his neo-Kantian training analytic.6
at Marburg. In the 1920s Cassirer made By the later 1920s, however, Heidegger
a well-known shiftfrom the critique of had come to believe that Cassirer exempli-
reason to the critique of culture: Drawing fied the cardinal errors of modern philoso-
inspiration from Aby Warburgs library in phy. Heideggers essential complaint is that
Hamburg, Cassirer laid out a broad theory Cassirer could not surrender the dogma of
of culture in a monumental three-volume transcendental spontaneity, or uncondi-
study entitled The Philosophy of Symbolic tioned consciousness, that he had inher-
Forms, the first volume on language (1923), ited from his Kantian antecedents. In The
the second on mythical thought (1925), and Philosophy of Symbolic Forms, volume two,
the third, entitled The Phenomenology of Cassirer characterized primitive myth as a
Knowledge, on the rise of the natural sciences fabric of meaning generated by spontaneous
(1929). In his last years Cassirer authored a acts of human consciousness. But in Being
work in political theory entitled The Myth of and Time Heidegger expresses skepticism
the State (published posthumously in 1946), regarding the Kantian principles supporting
which concludes with critical remarks on this characterization: It remains an open
Nazism and specifically mentions Heidegger question, Heidegger notes, whether . . . the
as a philosopher who contributed to what architectonics and . . . systematic content of
Cassirer calls the return of fatalism in Kants Critique of Pure Reason can provide
modern politics. a possible design for such a task, or whether
Heideggers opinions of Cassirer were a new and more primordial approach may
complex. Although Cassirer is not univer- not here be needed.7 In Heideggers eyes
sally acknowledged today as a philosopher this means that Cassirer had failed to grasp
of the first rank, during the later 1920s his the true significance of myth as an instruc-
contemporaries ranked him among the most tive model for the way human beings always
consequential philosophers in all of Germany. find themselves in thrall to rather than as the
Indeed, Heidegger and Cassirer were often transcendental authors of cultural meaning.
finalists for the most prestigious positions, Mythic Dasein, Heidegger argues, finds
including the Ernst Troeltsch Chair in phi- itself delivered up to the world in such a
losophy at the University of Berlin (which way that it is overwhelmed by that to which
was ultimately offered in 1930 to Heidegger, it is delivered up.8 Heidegger concludes
who declined it). Because Cassirer had that mythic Dasein was in this sense com-
moved beyond the Marburg neo-Kantian parable to human existence per se insofar
emphasis on the epistemology of the natural as mythic Dasein is primarily determined
sciences to embrace the broader domain of by thrownness [Geworfenheit].9 Myth, in
human culture, it was plausible that at first other words, is a welcome phenomenon for
Heidegger saw Cassirer as a potential ally for existential analysis insofar as it provided an
overcoming the science-focused and intellec- illustration of Dasein in its mode of average
tualist tendencies of modern philosophy. In everydayness, where human existence finds

146
HEIDEGGER, NEO-KANTIANISM, AND CASSIRER

itself always-already embedded in a context strongest terms: It implied the destruction


of engaged understanding and concern. of the former foundation of Western meta-
Heideggers basic objection to Cassirers physics (spirit, logos, reason). In the 1929
neo-Kantian premise of mental sponta- book on Kant, Heidegger added a further
neity came to the fore in the spring of (and quite controversial) claim, that Kant
1929 during their public conversation in first recognized the destructive implica-
Davos, Switzerland. Before their exchange, tions of his own argument but drew back
Heidegger offered a series of independent in fear. Kant subsequently revised his argu-
lectures on Kants Critique of Pure Reason ment for the Critiques second edition so as
as a Groundlaying for Metaphysics, a to preserve reasons sovereignty. Heideggers
presentation that offered a preview of the own interpretation brought to the surface
argumentation of his book, Kant and the the unthought thought in Kants philoso-
Problem of Metaphysics, published later that phy, that is, an understanding of the human
same year. To understand the stakes of the being as a creature of insuperable finitude
exchange with Cassirer it is helpful to recall (Endlichkeit) whose innermost temporal
the arguments of the book. Heideggers read- constitution also determines the temporal
ing of Kant was highly controversial and character of all worldly knowledge.
explicitly dissented from the then-dominant In their debate at Davos Cassirer offered
interpretation of the Marburg School. a series of challenges to this interpretation.
Against the Marburg reading of the first Heideggers antipathies to the neo-Kantian
Critique as a theory of knowledge in service school were surprising, Cassirer said, since
to the natural sciences, Heidegger saw the one might have thought Heideggers philoso-
first Critique as a groundlaying for meta- phy itself bore the imprint of neo-Kantianism.
physics, that is, a preparatory inquiry into Furthermore, Heideggers interpretation of
the ontological constitution of human being. Kants first Critique could not account for
In contrast to Cohens emphatically intellec- the minds capacity to grasp forms of knowl-
tualist reading of synthetic a priori knowl- edge that were nonrelative to the finitude of
edge as conditioned primarily by the pure the human being. Such objectivity was evi-
categories of the understanding, Heidegger dent both in natural scientific knowledge and
insisted that the understanding could not be in the objectivity of moral truths as theorized
assigned the primary role in the constitution in Kants practical philosophy. Heideggers
of experience. He claimed instead that both philosophy disallowed this species of objec-
the understanding and sensibility (the two tivity and thus implied that truth is rela-
basic stems of human knowledge accord- tive to Dasein. Cassirer further objected to
ing to Kant) were grounded in the faculty Heideggers portrait of the human being as a
of transcendental imagination as their com- creature bound in its innermost constitution
mon root. But according to Heidegger the to anxiety. Cassirer confessed that he wished
imagination was itself grounded in primor- to remain faithful to Kant, and that his own
dial temporality. Within Kants own phi- philosophy of symbolic forms bore witness to
losophy, in other words, there lay a hidden the human capacity to transcend anxiety and
challenge to the supremacy of the rational to achieve a mode of objectivity through the
mind. In his independent lectures at Davos medium of form. Cassirers overall assessment
Heidegger stated this conclusion in the of Heideggers philosophy is summarized in

147
HEIDEGGER, NEO-KANTIANISM, AND CASSIRER

two extensive footnotes that can be found interpretation to transform Kants text beyond
in The Phenomenology of Knowledge, the recognition. This was especially the case for
third volume of The Philosophy of Symbolic Heideggers highly original reading of the
Forms, where Cassirer expresses admiration transcendental imagination as a common
for Heideggers existential analytic but insists root beneath the understanding and sen-
that its portrait of Dasein remains valid only sibility, a reading that distorted Kants own
for the world as it is grasped in the mode of view of unconditioned mental spontaneity in
the ready-to-hand. According to Cassirer, the the constitution of experience. Heideggers
difficulty is that Heideggers analysis stops at emphasis on the essential finitude of human
the stage of existential spatiality and tempo- knowledge encouraged paradoxical-sounding
rality and fails to appreciate the transition to language such as the characterization of our
a state of being that lies beyond the exis- knowledge as a purely receptive spontane-
tentiality of being-there.10 For Cassirer, in ity (a phrase Cassirer compared to wooden
other words, Heidegger remained an impor- iron). Heideggers interpretation of Kant as
tant theorist of Dasein in the mode of average a theorist of unqualified finitude and anxi-
everydayness but he could not appreciate the ety belonged to the world of Kierkegaard
nonsubjective status of scientific and ethical and little to do with Kant himself, who
knowledge. remained in Cassirers phrase a thinker of
Rumor and anecdote have left the impres- the Enlightenment.11
sion that the Davos encounter represents a Heideggers critique of Cassirers phi-
dramatic turning point in Continental phi- losophy was equally sharp and occasionally
losophy. While the truth is more complex, verged on polemic. In his winter 192930
Cassirer was clearly less charismatic than seminar on The Fundamental Concepts of
his interlocutor. Heidegger impressed many Metaphysics, Heidegger complained that It
participants, especially students, as a thinker is a widespread opinion today that both cul-
alert to philosophys more urgent concerns. ture and man in culture can only be properly
Cassirers own criticism of Heidegger grew comprehended through the idea of expres-
more pronounced in the years following sion or symbol. We have today a philosophy
their debate. In an extensive 1931 review of culture concerned with expression, with
of Heideggers Kant and the Problem of symbol, with symbolic forms. [. . .] Yet we
Metaphysics, Cassirer offered a penetrating must as anew: Is this view of man an essen-
critique of Heideggers work. According to tial one? The philosophy of symbolic forms
Cassirer, Heideggers desire to read Kant as a was according to Heidegger not only inca-
partisan for the renewal of metaphysics rather pable of grasping the fundamental condition
than a critic of metaphysics resulted in wilful of Dasein, it actually obstructed any under-
distortion: Heidegger speaks no longer as standing of this condition: This philosophy
a commentator but as a usurper, Cassirer of culture at most sets out what is contempo-
wrote, who intrudes as it were on the rary about our situation, but it does not take
Kantian system with force of arms to subject hold of us, Heidegger explained. What is
it and make it serve his [own] problematic. more, not only does it not succeed in grasp-
The key difficulty in Heideggers interpreta- ing us, but it unties us from ourselves [. . .]
tion on Cassirers view was that it deployed Our flight and disorientation, the illusion and
(in Heideggers words) a strategy of violent lostness become more acute.12 This negative

148
HEIDEGGER, NEO-KANTIANISM, AND CASSIRER

verdict on Cassirer and neo-Kantianism is Rudolph (eds), Cassirer-Heidegger. 70 Jahre


grounded in Heideggers basic view that phi- Davoser Disputation, Cassirer-Forschungen 9
(Hamburg: Felix Meiner, 2002).
losophy both reflects and reinforces broader 2
For an overall history of the neo-Kantian
facets of the human condition: The general movement, see Klaus Khnke, The Rise
neo-Kantian emphasis on the natural sci- of Neo-Kantianism: German Academic
ences was thus understood as symptomatic Philosophy between Idealism and Positivism,
of technological modernity, while Cassirers trans. R. J. Hollingdale (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1991); and also
specific interest in the cultural sciences was
Thomas Willey, Back to Kant: The Revival of
deemed an evasion of the more primordial Kantianism in German Social and Historical
questions attending the human condition. Thought, 18601914 (Detroit: Wayne State
Still more troubling was Heideggers readi- University Press, 1978).
ness to criticize the neo-Kantian school as a
3
For a summary of Heideggers views on
Rickert and the Southwestern neo-Kantian
leveling philosophy that was tailor-made
school especially as regards the status of his-
for liberalism whose influence could only tory, see Charles Bambach, Heidegger, Dilthey,
be fought with native-born teachers.13 and the Crisis of Historicism (Ithaca, NY:
Heidegger also warned a colleague that Cornell University Press, 1995).
we are faced with a choice, either to pro-
4
On this theme see Steven Crowell and Jeff
Malpas (eds), Transcendental Heidegger
vide our German intellectual life once more
(Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2007).
with real talents and educations rooted in 5
What is Metaphysics? in PA, 92
our own soil, or to hand over that intel- 6
SZ, Div. I, chap. 1, n.xi/BT, Dvis. I, chap. 1,
lectual life once and for all to the growing n.xi, 490.
Jewification [Verjudung] in the broad and
7
SZ, 51, n. 1/BT, ch. 1, 490, n. xi.
8
Heidegger, Review of Cassirer, The Philosophy
narrow sense.14 Such remarks tend to vali-
of Symbolic Forms, Volume 2: Mythic
date Cassirers complaint during the Davos Thought, in PT, 3245; quote from 43.
debate that Neo-Kantianism has become
9
Heidegger, PT, 43.
the scapegoat of the newer philosophy.15 10
Ernst Cassirer, The Philosophy of Symbolic
Whatever our ultimate verdict on the signifi- Forms, Volume III: The Phenomenology of
Knowledge (New Haven, Yale University Press,
cance of Heideggers political prejudices, it is
1957) 163, n. 2.
clear that Heidegger saw in neo-Kantianism 11
Cassirer, Review of Heidegger, Kant und das
a philosophical school aligned with those Problem der Metaphysik, Kantstudien, 36
features of the modern world for which he (1931), 126; quote from 24.
felt little sympathy.
12
FCM, 77.
13
These remarks come from an official letter
Heidegger wrote as rector at Freiburg:
Heidegger, Hnigswald aus der Schule des
Neukantianismus (June 25, 1933), in GA 16,
NOTES AND REFERENCES
1323.
14
For an historical summary of this 1929 letter,
1
On the Davos encounter, see Peter E. see Ulrich Sieg, Die Verjudung des deut-
Gordon, Continental Divide: Heidegger, schen Geistes, Die Zeit, December 22, 1989,
Cassirer, Davos (Cambridge, MA: Harvard Feuilleton, 52.
University Press, 2010); also see Michael 15
KPM, Appendix IV, 193207; quote at
Friedman, A Parting of the Ways: Carnap, 193, where the resonant term scapegoat
Cassirer, and Heidegger (Chicago: Open (Sndenbock) is mistranslated as whipping
Court, 2000); and Dominic Kaegi and Enno boy.

149
17
Heidegger and Carnap:
Disagreeing about Nothing?
Eric S. Nelson

OVERLAPPING ORIGINS natural sciences and perhaps his progressive


cultural ideas and social democratic politics,
The differences between Heidegger and the Carnap emerged as one of Heideggers ear-
prominent Vienna Circle logical positiv- liest critics. In Overcoming Metaphysics
ist Rudolf Carnap (18911970) are fre- through the Logical Analysis of Language,
quently interpreted as an historical source based on an earlier lecture (1929) and first
of the division between a more specula- published in Erkenntnis, 2, 1931/32, Carnap
tively and stylistically oriented Continental critiqued Heideggers depiction of the noth-
philosophy and a more scientific and ing in What is Metaphysics? as a conceptu-
logically oriented Analytic philosophy. ally nonmeaningful confusion that involves
Nonetheless, Heidegger and Carnap shared the substantializing of the logical operation
a common intellectual context informed of negation that senselessly posits and rei-
by the Southwest or Baden School of fies nothing as an object by taking it as a
neo-Kantianism, Husserls phenomenology, noun.
the life-philosophy of Dilthey and Nietzsche, Metaphysical propositions, as well as
the projects of experiential, linguistic and utterances concerning moral and aesthetic
Gestalt-psychological holism, an antagonism values and norms, are neither false nor uncer-
toward traditional metaphysics as a reifica- tain. They are also not hypotheses or conjec-
tion of life and lived-experience, a suspi- tures that might be eventually empirically
cion of overly theoretical epistemological verified. According to Carnaps emotivist or
and abstract ethical discourses, and also the non-cognitivist interpretation of such utter-
German youth movement of the years fol- ances, they are merely expressions of affec-
lowing the First World War.1 tive moods and emotional states disguised as
Because of Carnaps emphasis on applying theoretical and empirically verifiable proposi-
the new formal logic pioneered by Gottlob tions. If cognitively valid meaning rests in the
Frege and Bertrand Russell to philosophical possibility of empirical verification, then met-
questions, his commitment to creating a new aphysics consists of pseudo-propositions
more logically rigorous form of empiricism, that are cognitively and epistemically, if
as well as his advocacy of the priority of the not affectively or expressively, senseless.2

151
HEIDEGGER AND CARNAP

Accordingly, Carnaps and Heideggers phi- and performative condition of the negativity
losophy diverges over three central issues: the that makes human thoughtincluding logi-
significance of nothing, the role of mood in cal negation and consequently all logic and
disclosure and philosophical reflection, and sciencepossible.4 Contrary to Carnaps
the proper task of overcoming metaphysics argumentation, it is the encounter with
in contemporary thought. elementary forms of negativity that makes
the conceptual positivity of thought and
the positivism of scientific inquiry think-
able.5 Logical negation cannot be primary,
METAPHYSICS AND THE NOTHING since it is rooted in a more originary exis-
tential encounter with the negativity of the
In his critique of Heideggers thinking of abyss and lack of ground of the nothingness
the nothing as the metaphysical question, disclosed in disorienting experiences such as
Carnap argued that the nothing is deriva- those of radical anxiety, profound boredom,
tive of the logical operation of negation. and the anticipation or premonition of ones
Negation is merely the reversal of an existen- own death. As dispositionally and affectively
tial proposition, and thus cannot be treated rooted in human existence, the apparent
as affirming existence, reality, or an object.3 neutral and indifferent conceptualization of
Negation immanently and derivatively denies logical negation presupposes the interrup-
the factual and logical propositions that it tive encounter with our own groundlessness
depends on for its significance. It is noth- in lack, loss, frustration, denial, and suffer-
ing but parasitical on positivity and has no ing rather than, as Carnap maintained, the
further cognitive meaning. Carnap upholds opposite. Rather than the nothing being
that Heideggers proposition that nothing meaningless, the disclosure of nothingness
nothings (das Nichts nichtet) has no genu- is in Heideggers phenomenological analysis
ine cognitive content that can be thematized the very condition of meaning.
and validated even as it elicits feelings akin Carnap concluded from his critical lin-
to those evoked in poetry while senselessly guistic analysis of Heideggers interpreta-
ascribing conceptual validity, which consists tion of the nothing and of more traditional
of empirical verifiability and logical validity, metaphysical thinkers that metaphysical
to them. utterances senselessly reify logical opera-
In Heideggers thinking, Nichts nichtet tions in making substantive assertions about
does not substantialize but brings out the being and nothing. Carnap contends that
verbal character (nichtet) of the nothing Heideggers thinking of being exploits and
(Nichts). Nothing is neither the affirmation hides the ambiguity of the verb to be as
of existence nor a thingand thus not the copula and the assertion of existence.6
reification criticized by Carnapnor is it a The published version of Overcoming
meaningless null. Nothing is not so much Metaphysics retains echoes of Carnaps
a substantive idea, as it is a formally indica- earlier lectures in which metaphysics was
tive or hermeneutical concept for the early critiqued through logical analysis and
Heidegger. Nothing is a formal indica- through a genealogical or genetic tracing of
tion (formale Anzeige) that interpretively the history of words from meaningfulness to
anticipates and opens up the experiential meaninglessness.7 Primary examples of this

152
HEIDEGGER AND CARNAP

transformation and loss of meaningfulness and speculative systems are consequently lost
can be traced in words such as soul and God discourses alienated from the needs of genu-
as well as ordinary words such as life, exist- ine feeling and theory as well as the demands
ence, and being when these are understood of practical life. They are at worst reaction-
metaphysically.8 Their continuing authority ary obscurantism and at best impoverished
rests in their lingering earlier senses and in replacements for art, literature, and music in
their affective aura. They have an ideological expressing the feeling of life.9
and obscurantist as opposed to a clarifying Carnap concludes that metaphysicians
and enlightening function. Logical analysis are musicians without musical ability.10
is not purely theoretical in this lecture, as in They dress their lack of expressive talent
Carnaps later analysis of language, since it in the garb of pseudo-theoretical language.
serves an emancipatory function for scientific He notes in the spirit of Schopenhauer,
thought and practical life by therapeutically Nietzsche, and Dilthey that music is perhaps
breaking the absorption in the magic and the purest expression of the feeling of life
mania of reified words and the reified sys- (Lebensgefhl); whereas the dogmatic and
tems of thought they support. To this extent, unverifiable systems of metaphysics confuse
Carnaps earlier project of overcoming meta- feelings with concepts, conflating affective
physics shares affinities with Heideggers life moods and practical situations and deci-
own early project of destructuring meta- sions with theoretically valid propositions.11
physics and they could be said perhaps to This life-feeling or basic orienting mood is
offer two different strategies for returning neither a mystical nor an elemental force, it is
to lived experience through the critical and affective and expressive. Carnap, much like
emancipatory overcoming of its traditional Dilthey, distinguishes the immanent articula-
reification. tion of the feeling and expressiveness of life
from positing one metaphysical or vitalistic
force that externally grounds or underlies
life.
LIFE, MOOD, AND MUSIC While Heidegger stresses the role of affec-
tive mood in the constitution of all cognition
In addition to skeptically applying argumen- and experience, including the neutral objec-
tative strategies from the new formal logic to tivating or theoretical mood that he argues is
Heideggers claims about nothingness, section the basis of the perspective of logic and sci-
seven of Overcoming Metaphysics illus- ence in What is Metaphysics? Carnap radi-
trates Carnaps debt to the anti-metaphysical cally distinguishes and separates an emotivist
and interpretively-oriented life-philosophies realm encompassing expressions of mood
of Nietzsche and Dilthey. Carnap deploys and feeling in the context of artistic and
here Diltheys argument that metaphysics is practical situations from cognitively valid
a transitional stage lacking both theoretical propositions. Propositions are either analyti-
validity and contemporary practical neces- cally valid, as in logic and mathematics, or
sity. Metaphysics is no longer myth and it empirically warranted. These latter nonlogi-
is not yet art, even if it expresses an emo- cal synthetic terms consist of observational
tive state or mood without its non-cognitive empirical statements, nonobservational the-
character being acknowledged. Metaphysical oretical statements, and statements of their

153
HEIDEGGER AND CARNAP

translation through the use of correspond- strategically and methodologically justified


ence rules that contain both kinds of terms. materialist) interpretation (Deutung) of sci-
Despite this apparent duality between the entific inquiry.14
subjective and the objective, Carnap recog- In Heideggers being-historical think-
nized as much as Heidegger the affective ing (seinsgeschichtliches Denken) of the
grounds of the pursuit of science. He noted, 1930s, the logical positivist overcoming
in the context of the growing irrational- of metaphysics in logistics remains a tacit
ism and obscurantism of the late Weimar metaphysics that continues to supress the
Republic, that the scientific spirit of dispas- fundamental question of the meaning of
sionate impartiality is also a mood and an being (Sein) and signals the fulfilment and
ethos: culmination of the history of metaphysics in
instrumental calculation.15 It could be noted
We too, have emotional needs that Heidegger answered Carnap indirectly
[Bedrfnisse des Gemts] in philosophy, by modifying his approach to the nothing,
but they are filled by clarity of concepts, including adjustments in his later additions
precision of methods, responsible the-
to his criticized essay What is Metaphysics?
ses, achievement through cooperation in
and in polemical remarks expressed in 1935.
which each individual plays his part.12
Heidegger linked the logical positivism of
the Vienna Circle and the essay published in
the circles journal Erkenntnis, Overcoming
Metaphysics, whose author he does not
A TALE OF TWO TURNS explicitly name, with various symptoms of
modernity such as Russian communism,
Little would endure of Carnaps and Americanism, the uprooting and levelling
Heideggers early overlapping points of of thinking in reductive instrumental cal-
departure in their later thought. In contrast culation, and the technological destruction
with Heideggers shift to a more poetic dis- of nature.16 The connection between these
course of being and a radicalized critique of apparently unconnected and diverse phe-
modernity, science, and technology, Carnaps nomena is, Heidegger repeatedly states, no
turn in the early 1930s involved a transi- accident.17 They are unified through the
tion to a pragmatic-semantic approach to seemingly merely linguistic question of the
language governed by a meta-theoretical verb is and in being indications of the
and pluralistic principle of tolerance in fateful forgetting of being that culminates
which metaphysical and ontological ques- in the pathologies of the rationalized and
tions are bracketed in favour of questions of profaned world of modernity. Of course,
logical syntax.13 At the same time, Carnap Heidegger linked in this politically troubling
moved from the more phenomenological passage the logical positivism of the Vienna
and phenomenalist explication of concrete Circle with modernist cultural and political
Gestalt-like lived experience (Erlebnis) as developments that Carnap, and other mem-
the generative and reductive basis of scien- bers of the so-called left-wing of the Vienna
tific explanation in The Logical Formation Circle such as in particular Otto Neurath,
of the World (Der logische Aufbau der Welt, stressed in the 1920s and 1930s. Heidegger
1928) to a more purely physicalist (i.e. a diagnosed positivism as yet another symptom

154
HEIDEGGER AND CARNAP

of the massification of humans, flight of the 5


GA 9, 116.
gods, darkening of the skies, and dominion
6
Carnap, berwindung der Metaphysik durch
logische Analyse der Sprache, 99.
of science and technology over nature char- 7
Ibid., 83, 88.
acteristic of occidental modernity.18 8
Ibid., 87, 89.
9
Ibid., 1067.
10
Ibid., 107.
11
Carnap maintained this distinction between
NOTES AND REFERENCES cognitive validity and emotively informed
practice for the sake of both theory and
1
On the extensive range of cultural and practice in the context of the rise of National
philosophical influences on the early Carnap, Socialism in his essay Theoretische Fragen
see Gottfried Gabriel, Introduction: Carnap und praktische Entscheidungen, Natur und
Brought Home, in ed. S. Awodey and C. Geist, 9 (1934), 25760.
Klein, Carnap Brought Home: The View from 12
Rudolf Carnap, Der logische Aufbau der
Jena (Chicago: Open Court, 2004), 323, Welt (Berlin: Weltkreis, 1928), xv; Rudolf
and Eric S. Nelson, Dilthey and Carnap: Carnap, The Logical Structure of the World,
Empiricism, Life-Philosophy, and Overcoming trans. R. A. George (Berkeley, University of
Metaphysics, Pli: Warwick Journal of California Press, 1967), xvii. Compare Gabriel,
Philosophy, 23 (2012), 2049; on the signifi- Introduction: Carnap Brought Home, 11.
cance of Husserls phenomenology for the early 13
Rudolf Carnap, Logische Syntax der Sprache
Carnap, see Guillermo E. Rosado Haddock, (Wien: Springer, 1934).
The young Carnaps unknown master: Husserls 14
On the relation between eliminating
influence on Der Raum and Der Logische metaphysics and the principle of tolerance,
Aufbau der Welt (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2008). see Gottfried Gabriel, Carnaps Elimination
2
Rudolf Carnap, berwindung der Metaphysik of Metaphysics through Logical Analysis of
durch logische Analyse der Sprache, in Language. A Retrospective Consideration
Scheinprobleme in der Philosophie und andere of the Relationship between Continental
metaphysikkritische Schriften (Hamburg: and Analytic Philosophy, in ed. P. Parrini,
Meiner, 2004), 81, 103. W. C. Salmon, and M. H. Salmon, Logical
3
Ibid., 95. Empiricism: Historical and Contemporary
4
I examine nothingness as disorienting interrup- Perspectives (Pittsburgh: University of
tion, existential enactment, formal indication, Pittsburgh Press, 2003), 37.
and fundamental openness in Eric S. Nelson, 15
See ibid., 38.
Language and Emptiness in Chan Buddhism 16
GA 40, 2278.
and the Early Heidegger, Journal of Chinese 17
Ibid., 228; compare Michael Friedmans
Philosophy, 37.3 (2010), 47292; and Eric S. discussion of this passage in A Parting of
Nelson, Demystifying Experience: Nothingness the Ways: Carnap, Cassirer, and Heidegger
and Sacredness in Heidegger and Chan (Chicago: Open Court, 2000), 22.
Buddhism, Angelaki, 17.3 (2012), 6574. 18
GA 40, 29, 34.

155
18
Heidegger and Arendt:
The Lawful Space of Worldly
Appearance
Peg Birmingham

When considering Heideggers and Arendts Heidegger. This note is not Arendts last
respective thought, all too often the famil- word on the debt she owes Heidegger. In
iar narrative is one of contrast. The story 1971, at the conclusion of the second vol-
often told is one in which Heidegger is the ume of Life of the Mind, a book she now
thinker of mortality and being toward death, dedicates to Heidegger (we may con-
while Arendt is the thinker of natality and clude that there now exists a between),
our capacity for beginning something new Arendt turns to Heideggers Anaximander
through speech and action. Yet, a note Arendt Fragment claiming that Heideggers essay
sends Heidegger on the occasion of the pub- serves as the basis of her understanding
lication of Vita Activa, the German edition of worldly appearance that for her is the
of The Human Condition, suggests that this condition for the public space and politi-
often-repeated narrative is misleading and in cal action. In what follows, I first exam-
need of retelling. Arendt writes: ine Heideggers essay, The Anaximander
Fragment, focusing on his account of the
You will see that the book does not con- gathering that constitutes lawful worldly
tain a dedication. Had things worked appearance, which he names the law of the
out properly between usand I mean possible. I then turn to Arendts reading of
between, that is, neither you nor meI Heideggers essay, examining how it serves
would have asked you if I might dedicate as the basis for her understanding of a com-
it to you; it came directly out of the first mon world, the world of the between,
Freiburg days and hence owes practically which she claims is possible because it has as
everything to you in every respect.1 its condition worldly appearance as such. In
conclusion, I argue that Heideggers account
Important here is Arendts self-understanding of the lawful space of worldly appearing has
that everything in her book devoted to the significant importance for Arendts political
question of action came directly out of the thought, specifically, providing the founda-
first Freiburg days and hence owes practi- tion for Arendts claim of a right to have
cally everything . . . in every respect to rights.

157
HEIDEGGER AND ARENDT

Heideggers The Anaximander quiet power of the possible . . . I mean Being


Fragment which in its favoring presides over thinking
and hence over the essence of humanity, and
If there is a continuous preoccupation that that means over its relation to Being. To
marks Heideggers thought from its earliest enable something here means to preserve it is
beginnings in Being and Time to the later in its element, to maintain it in its element.2
essays on technology, it is the question of This enabling element is the decisive essence
the will to power. Certainly this is the cen- of action [understood] as accomplishment,3
tral focus of his essay, The Anaximander that is, that which enables something to
Fragment. Heidegger begins the essay by unfold in its being. As just noted, Heideggers
noting that he is following Nietzsches trans- focus in The Anaximander Fragment is to
lation of the fragment: When things have think the decisive essence of action, which
their origin, there they must also pass away I suggest is the key reason why Arendt will
according to necessity; for they must pay turn to this essay when thinking the condi-
penalty and be judged for their injustice, tions for political action.
according to the ordinance of time (GA 5, For Heidegger, the essence of action is
296/EGT, 13). It is significant that Heidegger rooted in the worldly appearance taking place
compares this earliest of Greek fragments between the arrival and departure of Being.
to a later fragment in Western thinking, In other words, the possibility of action is
namely, Nietzsches aphorism: To stamp accomplished in beings appearing and linger-
Becoming with the character of beingthat ing between two absences. Heidegger calls
is the highest will to power (GA 5, 306/EGT, this lingering between two absences, tran-
22). Both Anaximander and Nietzsche speak siency. The worldly appearance of beings is
of a fundamental power that comes to be. transient, finite, and contingent. Heidegger
However, according to Heidegger, Nietzsche states: Accordingly . . . presently means as
does not think the being of this power nor much as having arrived to linger awhile in
does he connect it to the question of justice the expanse of unconcealment . . . Such a
and injustice. For Heidegger, this is precisely coming is proper arrival, the presencing of
what the Anaximander fragment accom- what is properly present.. . .4 At the same
plishes. Heidegger states: What is Greek is time, Heidegger warns that the transiency
the dawn of that destiny in which Being illu- off beings must not be set off from the per-
minates itself in beings and so propounds a manence of Being. The unfolding power of
certain essence of man; that essence unfolds Being never appears as one present being
historically as something fateful, preserved in among others; instead, it remains concealed
Being and dispensed by Being, without ever in its luminous letting-presence of beings.
being separated from Being (GA 5, 310/ Thus, Being is not the absolute actuality
EGT, 25). of the unconditioned will. Instead, the power
Thinking the original unfolding of Being, of Being is the letting-presence that holds
Heidegger is thinking the original power itself back in its giving. Rather than abso-
that allows for lawful worldly appearance. lute actuality, Being is potentiality, as that
In Letter on Humanism, Heidegger names which can never be taken up into actuality; it
this original power the enabling power is that which escapes or refuses all uncondi-
of being. He states: When I speak of the tional will to power.

158
HEIDEGGER AND ARENDT

Going further, Heidegger argues that the paying the penalty of injustice (a-Dike). To
giving of Being, is not only giving-away; commit injustice is to overstep the bounda-
originally giving has the sense of acceding or ries of ones finitude. I shall return to this
giving-to. Such giving lets something belong momentarily.
to one another which properly belongs to it. To better understand how beings could
Heidegger names this belonging the join- commit injustice, we need to further grasp
ture (Dike) of being. The giving of Being that for Heidegger the enabling power of
allows for a fundamental belonging or join- being allows for the uniqueness of the self.
ture among beings. In other words, the com- Heidegger argues that necessity gives each
mon world has at its condition the giving of being its own essence, while preserving it in a
being that holds things together and allows protective hold of belonging. The self there-
being to belong together. Heidegger calls this fore is both singular and plural, both unique
jointure order. At the same time, this join- and in a relation of belonging-together in
ture (Dike) can also be out of joint; this can being-with. Thus, in giving, Dike both gives
also be because there is a disjunction between and preserves the singularity or uniqueness of
the giving of Being and the beings who linger each individual being in its being-with others.
in this givenness: Everything that lingers Yet, the self, always conditioned and thrown
awhile stands in disjunction. To the presenc- into the overpowering order of Dike without
ing of what is present, to the eov of eovta, any hope of autonomy, is absolutely account-
doika belongs (GA 5, 328/EGT, 42). able for that which happens in the worldly
Heidegger then introduces another word to expanse of appearance. Human beings must
describe the giving of appearance: brauch respect this order: If what is present grants
or need. Brauch, he points out, comes from order, it happens in this manner: as beings
the Latin frui, meaning to brook or to hand linger awhile they give reck [respect] to one
something over to its own essence and keep it another. The surmounting of disorder prop-
in hand, preserving it as something present erly occurs through the letting-belong of reck
(GA 5, 337/EGT, 52). Need or necessity [respect] (GA 5, 333/EGT, 47). In respect for
does not mean scarcity, but abundance as the lawful order of belonging-together, the
the overflowing that needs (frui) to give. self is given as a responsible and accountable
Heidegger goes on to name this abundance self. Here Heidegger is challenging Kant. For
of giving, Dike. Dike is the law of belong- Kant, freedom and responsibility are located
ing; it is that which compels adaptation and in the autonomous subject who is both leg-
compliance. Dike enjoins order and respect, islator and subject in a sovereign community
demanding that beings linger, but not per- of ends. Rather than the Kantian transcend-
sist, in their appearance: Enjoining order ent law that addresses the sovereign subject,
... [Being] delivers to each present being the Heidegger gives us the law of the possible
while into which it is released. But accompa- that addresses a thrown and exposed self
nying this process is the constant danger that that finds itself belonging to and in a com-
lingering will petrify into mere persistence mon world with others. This law, Heidegger
(GA 5, 33940/EGT, 54). This persistence is claims, cannot be violated by a will to power
another name for the unconditional will to that seeks to actualize possibility by impos-
power. Beings therefore appear within lawful ing ultimate meanings or determinations
bounds that cannot be transgressed without upon it.

159
HEIDEGGER AND ARENDT

Recently, Giorgio Agamben has shown from our privately owned place in it . . . It is
the problematic relation of possibility and related . . . to the human artifact, the fabri-
actuality, particularly its relation to national cation of human hands, as well as to affairs
identity and sovereignty: which go on among those who inhabit the
man-made world together.7 Prior to and dis-
Assuming my being-such, my manner tinguished from the publicity of a common
of being, is not assuming this or that world, there is worldly appearing as such,
quality, this or that character, virtue or although not yet a common, political appear-
vice, wealth or poverty. My qualities and
ance, the latter being for Arendt constituted
my being-thus are not qualifications of
through the common interests, the inter-esse,
a substance (of a subject) that remains
behind them and that I would truly be. of a plurality of human beings.
I am never this or that, but always such, Although Arendt suggests that the sec-
thus. Eccum sic: absolutely. Not posses- ond sense of publicity, the common world
sion but limit, not presupposition but of making and acting, has as it condition
exposure.5 the first sense of publicity, she spends no
time in The Human Condition consider-
Agamben learns from Heidegger that worldly ing this first sense. Only in her reading of
appearance is first of all an unqualified expo- Heideggers The Anaximander Fragment
sure to the world; it is a limited and lawful does she return to it, arguing that our activ-
exposure that can never be made fully actu- ity in the common world with a plurality of
alized in terms of a sovereign will to power others depends upon our belonging to the
that seeks to understand the self as a set of givenness of worldly appearance as such.
qualifications or determinations, whether Indeed, she makes explicit in her reading
that be at the individual or political level. of Heideggers essay that the givenness of
worldly appearance is precisely what allows
for the unpredictability of action as our
capacity for beginning something new. In
Arendt: On the Givenness of her reading of this fragment, she is particu-
Worldly Appearance larly interested in Heideggers understanding
of physis as unconcealment:
While Arendt never mentions Heidegger
in The Human Condition, nevertheless she . . . it belongs to the beings that they
reveals her debt to him at the very beginning arrive from and depart into a hidden
of her analysis of the vita activa by making a being. What can hardly have caused
distinction between two senses of publicity. but certainly facilitated this reversal is
Publicity, she argues, means first of all worldly the fact that the Greeks, especially the
pre-Socratics, often thought of Being as
appearance as such: For us, appearance
physis (nature), whose original mean-
something that is seen and heard by others
ing is derived from phyein (to grow),
as well as by ourselvesconstitutes reality.6 that is, to come to light out of darkness.
The second sense of publicity, she argues, Anaximander, says Heidegger, thought
denotes a common world: Second, the term of genesis [becoming] and phthora [pass-
public signifies the world itself, insofar as ing away] in terms of physis, as ways of
it is common to all of us and distinguished luminous rising and declining.8

160
HEIDEGGER AND ARENDT

Physis is genesis, an unpredictable appearing. becoming remains its law while it lasts.11
Indeed, she understands this genesis in terms Genesis estin contains its own law; it is the
of a contingent causality in which the law of becoming that holds sway over the
aitia are the unpredictable causes of appear- abandonment of existence to itself. Following
ance. She then emphasizes the next sentence, Heidegger on this point, Arendt argues that
...as it reveals itself in beings, Being with- as finite, we are set adrift in the domain of
draws. Arendts emphasis here is on the coming-to-be: In the beginning, Being dis-
original abandonment of appearing itself. closes itself in being, and the disclosure
More precisely, physis is abandonment. Here starts two opposite movements: Being with-
she is describing how the aitia, the constitut- draws into itself, and beings are set adrift
ing powers of appearing, is in an entirely dif- to constitute the realm (in the sense of the
ferent ontological relation to what appears. princes realm) of error.12 Again, following
Or to put it more radically: there is no onto- Heidegger, Arendt argues that human exist-
logical relation between the potentializing ence is irreparable in the sense of being
power of being and its actual appearance. unjustifiable and without cause. Cut off and
More precisely, the emergence of physis is not adrift from any sovereign constituting power
a relation of potentiality and actuality. Again or foundation, we are not, however, without
following Heidegger, she argues the coming law. The law of becoming (physis) is the law
and going, appearing and disappearing, of or rule of givenness.
beings always begins with a disclosure that is To better understand this law, Arendt
an ent-bergen, the loss of the original shelter returns to an insight that inaugurates her
(bergen) that had been granted by Being.9 reflections on appearance in the first vol-
This loss is not the suspension of Being, nor ume of Life of the Mind: the instinct for
is it the abandonment of Being to itself. To self-preservation is not fundamental to
think physis (coming-to-be of appearance) our appearance. The law of becoming that
without any relation to Being in the form of holds sway in givenness is not the law of
potentiality that is then actualized is to think self-preservation with its accompanying
the letting-be of appearance as such. This is desire for persistence, but instead, it is the
the radical sense of givenness: there is no law of givenness with its accompanying grat-
relation to BeingBeing itself is the rela- itude and sense of delight. Here she agrees
tion. Arendt cites Heidegger: Presumably, with Heideggers critique of the sovereign
Anaximander spoke of genesis and phthora will, which in its desire for self-preservation
[generation and decline] . . . [that is] genesis and persistence breaks with the law of
estin (which is the way I should like to read becoming: The Will as destroyer appears
it) and phthora ginetai, coming-to-be is, and here, too, though not by name; it is the crav-
passing-away comes to be.10 Genesis estin: ing to persist, to hang on, the inordinate
which is the way both Arendt and Heidegger appetite men have to cling to themselves.
read it. Physis as genesis estin is the taking In this way they do more than just err.13
place of appearance as such. Following Heidegger, Arendt insists that to
Arendt then formulates a law of unquali- persist is . . . an insurrection on behalf of
fied givenness: . . . everything we know sheer endurance. She understands this to
has become, has emerged from some previ- mean that . . . the insurrection is directed
ous darkness into the light of day, and this against order (dike); it creates the disorder

161
HEIDEGGER AND ARENDT

(adikia) permeating the realm of errancy.14 the right to belong to a political community
Disorder is the willful rebellion against the or what she names a right to have rights.
order of becoming in favor of some sort of She states, We become aware of the exist-
sovereign endurance. Adikia is the rebellion ence of a right to have rights . . . and a right
against the lawful appearance of givenness to belong to some kind of organized commu-
in favor of an insurrectionary sovereign will nity, only when millions of people emerged
that seeks to impose itself. Order or the law- who had lost and could not regain these
fulness of worldly appearance is restored by rights because of the new global and political
our ability to say Yes to the genesis estin. situation.17 But on what basis do we have a
Arendt argues that there is no higher affirma- right to have rights? What is the normative
tion than to say, Amo: volo ut sis, I love foundation for declaring that human beings
you, I want you to beand not I want to have a right to belong?
have you or I want to rule you.15 At the I suggest that Heideggers law of the
very heart of our capacity to act, therefore, possible provides this normative founda-
is the unconditional affirmation of the given: tion. Recall that for Heidegger the law of
Amovolo ut sis. the possible emerges through the givenness
of appearance that allows for an originary
belonging together of all beings. This origi-
nary belongingness constitutes what can be
Heidegger and Arendt: A Right called rightful appearance as such. In other
to Belong or a Right to have words, an originary belonging to worldly
Rights appearance as such provides the normative
foundation for a right to belong to a political
In the Origins of Totalitarianism, Arendt, space. Still further, on the basis of the right-
reflecting on her status of a refugee fleeing ful appearance of the human being as such,
Nazi Germany and for whom the universal the mutual recognition and granting of equal
declaration of human rights proved to be rights is a political imperative. While I can-
entirely illusory and without any political not develop it here, Heideggers understand-
effect, states: ing of the lawful givenness of being provides
a way to rethink radically the modern prob-
The fundamental deprivation of human lem of political sovereignty. We saw above
rights is manifested first and above all in that originary givenness thwarts any claim to
the deprivation of a place in the world sovereignty (particularly state sovereignty),
which makes opinion significant and
because it is that which is always outside any
actions effective. Something much more
identity (including national identity) that
fundamental than freedom and justice,
which are the rights of citizens, is at state could argue for hegemony over unqualified
when belonging to the community into existence. Thus, the basis of the right to
which one is born is no longer a matter have rights emerges: the right of givenness,
of course and not belonging no longer a unqualified mere existence, to appear and to
matter of choice.. . .16 belong to a political space.
The right of givenness is Arendts debt
Arendt goes on to formulate a right more fun- to Heidegger. As she herself recognizes in
damental than the rights of citizens, namely, the note she sends him on the publication

162
HEIDEGGER AND ARENDT

of the Vita Activa, her political thought (Frankfurt Am Main: Vittorio Klostermann,
owes almost everything in every respect to 1967), 314. English translation: Letter on
Humanism, translated by Frank Capuzzi, in
Heidegger because he first made her aware
Basic Writings, ed. David Krell (New York:
of the lawful space of worldly appearance, Harper and Row, 1977), 1967.
an originary space of belonging that allows 3
Ibid., 311/193.
for the common world of political praxis. 4
Martin Heidegger, Der Sprauch das
As Arendts note and subsequent dedica- Anaxamander, GA 5, 320/34.
5
Georgio Agamben, The Coming Community,
tion tell us, while the common world of the
trans. Michael Hardt (Minneapolis: University
between can at times be out of joint, it of Minnesota Press, 1993), 96.
can be regained and built anew because it is 6
Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition
sustained by the givenness of being-with and (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
belonging-together, that is, the lawful space 1958), 50.
7
Ibid., 52.
of worldly appearance as such. 8
Hannah Arendt, Life of the Mind, vol. 2 (New
York: Harcourt Brace Janovich, 1978), 190.
9
Ibid.
NOTES AND REFERENCES 10
Ibid.
11
Ibid., 191, emphasis mine.
1
Letters 19251975, Hannah Arendt and 12
Ibid., 192.
Martin Heidegger, ed. Ursula Ludz. Translated 13
Ibid., 193.
from the German by Andrew Shields (New 14
Ibid.
York: Harcourt, 2004), 124. (Translation 15
Ibid., 104.
modified). Letter dated October 28, 1960. 16
Hannah Arendt, Origins of Totalitarianism
2
Martin Heidegger, Brief uber den (New York: HBJ, 1951), 296.
Humanismus (1946) in Wegmarken 17
Ibid., 297.

163
19
Heidegger and Gadamer
Emilia Angelova

On Heideggers invitation in 1960, Gadamer the prejudice of Kantian subjectivity, has a


writes an indispensable text, the introduc- foundation rather in that which precedes and
tion for the Reclam edition of Heideggers makes possible modern science, and does
mid-1930s lectures on the work of art. In not limit itself to consciousness or method
the same year the first edition of Gadamers (including that of historicism of the verstehe-
Truth and Method is published, with the last nde Geisteswissenschaften) or a given mode
words in the introduction outlining the debt of behaviour. (TM, xvii)1 The term herme-
to Heidegger. Again, in 1965, in the foreword neutics as used by Gadamer denotes the
to the second edition of Truth and Method, basic being-in-motion of There-being which
Gadamer recognizes deep kinship and affin- constitutes its finiteness and historicity, and
ity with Heidegger, even as he notes several hence includes the whole of its experience
points of difference. This chronology is worth of the world. (2) In an ontological herme-
recounting for by 1960 close to 30 years of neutics, then, Gadamer follows Heidegger
silence separate the two thinkers. With the that it is the nature of the thing itself that
silence broken in the 1960s, Gadamer, one of makes the movement of understanding com-
Heideggers most outstanding students, will prehensive and universal. This is based on
stay close to his teacher to the end of his life Heideggers temporal analytic of human
and beyond. existence (Dasein), which has shown con-
Gadamers exposition of philosophical vincingly that understanding is not just one
hermeneutics has roots in Heideggers project of the various possible behaviours of the sub-
of fundamental ontology and revolves on ject, but the mode of being of There-being
these points: (1) The objectives of knowledge itself (xviii). (3) Unifying ontological with
(how far is modern science possible?) bring historical hermeneutics, Gadamer claims
to the fore a difference that methodologi- that the universality of the hermeneutic
cal dispute has long served to conceal and viewpoint does not admit to an abso-
neglect dating back at least to Kants phi- lute validity arrived at by mere contrasting
losophy of subjectivity. The task of herme- between historical and dogmatic method.
neutics exceeds a Kantian distinction based Hermeneutical consciousness exists only
solely on method between human sciences under specific historical conditions (the
(Geisteswissenschaften) and modern natural principle of effective-history raised to general
science. Unconcealment and revealment of structural element of understanding) without

165
HEIDEGGER AND GADAMER

committing to historical relativity; this is so of understanding, even if he risks becom-


since in all understanding of historical tra- ing, as Habermas calls this, a three way
dition effective-history is itself operative bridge-builder between Heidegger and the
(historical consciousness as living precisely discourse of the contemporaries.4 What is
involves a fundamental distance between the secret of Heideggers enduring presence?
the present and all historical transmission) asks Gadamer. To begin with, there is much
(xxi).2 Against a certain ambiguity deline- at stake in this early word for secret, for
ated in the received concept of historical con- Gadamer, as was mentioned, will not write on
sciousness (against claims about ineffability, his teacher for decades; and Gadamer unam-
and Droysens historicism and Diltheys con- biguously defends Heidegger through both
ceptually weak conclusion about the culmi- debates with Habermas. Today, Gadamers
nation of all history in intellectual history), own work in philosophical hermeneutics
philosophical hermeneutics is hence to show gains new momentum as the early lecture
itself in agreement with Heideggers state- courses by Heidegger are made available and
ment that being that can be understood is there is increasingly more scholarship engag-
language (xxiii). ing hermeneutics and the sciences.
But Gadamer distances himself clearly In the 15 essays (written since 1960 and
where the question of the end of metaphys- over 25 years) from Heideggers Ways,5
ics as a science (the cosmic night and the Gadamer breaks the silence that he had
forgetfulness of being (xxv)) is concerned. imposed upon himself during the intense
He distances himself from the later Heidegger debate and discussion that surrounded
(1) on the question that for Gadamer, the Heidegger in the period after the Second
analyses of hermeneutic play (concealment World War. As Dennis Schmidt notes, far
and unconcealment) and of language are from forgetting his teacher, Gadamer found
intended in a purely phenomenological the requisite distance needed if he was to
sense (this puts language still in the realms of write about Heidegger (HW, xvii). In for-
phenomenological demonstration since what mulating his own hermeneutics after receiv-
is described is the experience of the subject) ing a philosophical impetus from Heideggers
(xxiv); and as well, (2) on assimilating the early hermeneutics of facticity (since 1922,
tradition (against Heidegger, I have empha- attending the first Freiburg lecture course6),
sized the element of the assimilation of what and in carrying out his own philosophical
is past and handed down (xxv)). Gadamer projectthinking through the Greek texts,
claims proximity rather with Hegels task Aristotle, Plato, and beyondGadamers
of the infinite relation (Hegels specula- own work is clearly driven by an ethical and
tive dialectic remains close to us (xxiv)),3 he political concern for history, and for the life
insists that the task is one about maintaining of culture and peoples. Gadamers distance
hermeneutic consciousness of the continuity from his teacher is creative, measured by his-
of the subject and the tradition, which must tory, and perhaps also moral. Gadamers
be awakened and kept awake (xxv). philosophical hermeneutics preserves a deep
Through the end of the 1960s, a period fidelity to the project of thinking as interro-
that is intensified as well by his debate gation, continually elaborating possibilities
with Habermas, Gadamer continues his opened up by Heidegger. For Gadamer, it is
efforts of thinking through the finitude unquestionable that Heidegger takes up with

166
HEIDEGGER AND GADAMER

radicality and boldness the crisis of the from the Letter on Humanism: the theme
roots of the inherited forms of thinking, in of ethics (HW, 11). What is alive and what
the age of closure that is occidental techno- is dead in the thinking of Martin Heidegger,
logical reason (193). Yet points of departure as Gadamers phrasing runs, is a question
and disputation between the two thinkers decided by the great thinkers ability to
remain, and this concerns mostly the later overcome, by virtue of what they have to
Heidegger, the thesis of the end of metaphys- say, the stylistic resistance and stylistic dis-
ics and the other beginning. tance that separates them from the present.
Surely, Gadamer does not understand him- By this measure alone Heidegger can pro-
self as a metaphysical thinker. But contra the ceed beyond and overcome the existen-
thesis of the end of philosophy, his point tialist phase in philosophy, to be a partner
of departure is thoroughly marked by com- among philosophers included in a philosoph-
mitment to the unity and continuity of the ical conversation that will continue through
subject through history. This takes the shape tomorrow (13). Gadamer makes this point
of a decisive persistence on attending to the in recalling the opening lines of the letter:
experience of the limits of language and of For some time now we have not considered
metaphysics, an attentiveness rather to the the nature of action decisively enough. This
hermeneutic play of finite truth: in art (and its is a point worth reiterating for us also. That
relation to truth); in language (and the claims is, Heideggers critique, unlike present days
of metaphysics and the positive sciences); and cultural criticism (16) was much more
in history (and the open dialogue with the tra- ambiguousand this holds of the earli-
dition and its texts). To this deep fidelity, yet est beginnings, of the sharp and vehement
difference, speaks the acknowledgment from critique of the they, of curiosity and idle
the preface to Truth and Method: Heidegger, talk (ibid.). The same leveling and flat-
like many of my critics, might see in this a tening with which the critiques of contem-
lack of ultimate radicality in the drawing of porary culture accuse the technological
conclusions (TM, xxv). To this anticipated culture of repressing freedom, is also what
objection from the teacher, there is offered takes hold of every aspect of our lives. Since
also the response that [T]he finite nature of Being and Time this necessary concomi-
understanding is the manner in which reality, tance of authenticity with inauthenticity,
resistance, the absurd, and the unintelligible of the essential [Wesen] with the inessential
assert themselves. If one takes this finiteness [Unwesen], of truth with error [Irre] (17)
seriously, then one must also take the reality defines Heideggers task of revealment: not in
of history seriously (xxiii). any irrational way and pathos of existence,
It remains essential to Gadamers philo- but instead in that it allows for understand-
sophical hermeneutics that a deep continu- ing his work as posed to the present.
ity with the unity of the subject must be Gadamers hermeneutics avoids a romantic
preserved. Preserving this unity (recognition, criticism of both technology and logical posi-
and dialogue) is the task of thinking and tivism, much in debt to Heideggers ways (not
interpretation. In this spirit Gadamer defends works) of thinking. Today for us Heideggers
Heidegger (in 1981), giving important guid- question is posed by the manifestation in
ance to what the French readers missed in philosophy of a growing trend toward logi-
Heidegger (starting with Jean-Paul Sartre), cal clarity, exactness, and verifiability of all

167
HEIDEGGER AND GADAMER

assertions, and once again, as Gadamer turbulence marking one called to thinking
diagnosed, science is adorned with uncon- as the mission of life: In a whirl of radical
ditional faith. Renewed hermeneutic effort questionsquestions that Heidegger posed,
calls on the present, that todays situation that posed themselves to Heidegger, that he
has much to learn from Heideggers unique- posed to himselfthe chasm that had devel-
ness among all of the philosophical teach- oped in the course of the last century between
ers of our time; for Heideggers example academic philosophy and the need for a
lies in approaching the same <thing> from world-view seems to close (19). Gadamer
themost diverse perspectives, thus giving the says that after Being and Time (in which
conceptual description the character of the a single question is posed and explored)
plastic arts, that is, the three-dimensionality none of Heideggers later works operate on
of tangible reality (ibid.). Todays phi- a single, unified plane; they belong to differ-
losopher, too, needs a warning that where ent planes (20). This diagnosis echoes rather
[t]he entire conceptual analysis is presented the experience of radically bearing witness to
as an argued progression from one concept a thinking in search of a new language, one
to another (ibid.), one in turn demands of better suited to new insights. Gadamer him-
philosophy a justification of its very exist- self locates in Heideggers own preparatory
ence (16). effort of thinking in the 1920s the justifica-
The last point sums up well the reasoning tion for a continuity between the thinking
that Gadamer presents when he argues that of Being and the so-called turn (Kehre):
there is room for holding off on Heideggers Heidegger does not so much pose the ques-
late talk of the end of metaphysics. It is tion of Being in Being and Time as prepare
important to resist this talk, since Heideggers for it (21):
work is not to be understood merely from
a historical perspective; this latter would What is happening there [da], what hap-
render it irrelevant to the present, a slow pens as a Da, is what Heidegger later
movement of thinking from the recent past calls the clearing of Being [Lichtung des
Seins]. A clearing is that which one enters
that grows ever more strange as it develops
after walking endlessly in the darkness of
(ibid.). For Gadamer, the shift claimed by
a forest when, suddenly, there is an open-
Heidegger can be rendered in clear language: ing in the trees letting in the light of the
an awareness of this shift [to talk of end of sununtil one has walked through the
metaphysics] allows for an understanding clearing as well and the darkness envel-
of his work: namely, a visionary, a thinker ops one anew. (23)7
who sees (17).
As we ponder this insistence on the pow- In short, Gadamer remains committed to
ers of understanding and dialogue, we that which unifies the various formula-
should remember that Gadamers own early tions of the question of the thinker, as truly
years as a student in Freiburg in 19212 obsessed with his own affairs [Sache] as
and onwards were shaken by the burning Heidegger was. The unmistakable intensity
questions of a generationthe horrors of and disclosive power of his encounters and
the First World War. For he was no stranger identificationsincluding the interpretations
to the sense of distress expressed in the of Hlderlin (a type of freeing his tongue),
lectures by the young Heidegger, a sense of and concomitant with these interpretations,

168
HEIDEGGER AND GADAMER

Heidegger finding his own new tone in the P.Christopher Smith (New Haven and London:
lectures The Origin of the Work of Art (in Yale University Press, 1976).
4
See Habermas laudatio for Gadamer in
1936)suggest only that the changes, far
1979 on the occasion of Gadamers receipt
from inserting a break, showed but stages: of the Hegel-Prize titled The Urbanization
The use of the word earth [in the Origin of of the Heideggerian Province. For the
Work of Art lectures] gave the Being of the debate see J. Habermas, Zur Logik der
work of art a conceptual characterization Sozialwissenschaften, Philosophische
Rundschau 14, Beiheft 5, 196667. Translation
that showed that Heideggers Hlderlin inter-
of the section on Gadamer is found in A Review
pretations (and these lectures) were stages on of Gadamers Truth and Method, appear-
his own way of thinking (22).8 ing in Understanding and Social Inquiry, ed.
Fred Dallmayr and T. McCarthy (Notre Dame:
University of Notre Dame Press, 1977), 33563.
5
Hans-Georg Gadamer, Heideggers Ways,
NOTES AND REFERENCES trans. John W. Stanley, intr. Dennis J. Schmidt
(Albany: SUNY, 1994). Hereafter cited as HW.
1
Hans-Georg Gadamer, Wahrheit und Methode
6
In HW 556; 1267; 1312. See also
(Mohr: Tbingen, 1965)/Truth and Method, Heideggers One Path, trans. P. Christopher
trans. Sheed and Ward Ltd. (1975), ed. Garrett Smith, in ed. Theodore Kisiel and John van
Barden and John Cumming (New York: Buren, Reading Heidegger from the Start,
Crossroad, 1986). Hereafter cited as TM. (Albany: SUNY, 1994), 1935.
See on this Robert Bernasconi, Heidegger
7
For a different reading of darkness, the clear-
in Question (New Jersey: Humanities Press, ing, and the experience of oblivion of being in
1993), 17090. Heidegger, see Robert Bernasconi, Heidegger
2
The universality of the hermeneutic aspect in Question (New Jersey: Humanities Press,
and what is elicited in language embraces the 1993), 89. Also see Eric S. Nelson, History as
pre-hermeneutic consciousness as well as the Decision and Event in Heidegger, Arhe, IV.8
modes of hermeneutic consciousness. But this (2007), 97114.
is not relativism. Even the nave appropriation
8
Heideggers series of the essay from the 1936
of tradition is a retelling, although it ought not lectures in Frankfurt, which Gadamer attended,
to be described as a fusion of horizons (for first appeared in German in 1950, in the collec-
the latter concept see TM, 486ff). tion Holzwege. See also commentary by David
3
For more see Hans-Georg Gadamer, Hegels Farrell Krell, BW, 24 ff.
Dialectic. Five Hermeneutical Studies, trans.

169
20
Heidegger and Marcuse:
On Reification and Concrete
Philosophy
1

Andrew Feenberg

Introduction Edmund Husserl, with whom Marcuse also


studied, contacted Max Horkheimer on
Herbert Marcuse (18981979) completed Marcuses behalf. In 1933 Marcuse joined
his doctorate in 1922 but decided not to pur- the Frankfurt Institute for Social Research
sue the habilitation that would have quali- Institute in exile.
fied him for an academic career. Instead, he Marcuses most detailed discussion of his
returned to Berlin where he established an early relation to Heidegger is in a 1972 inter-
antiquarian bookstore with a partner. When view with Frederick Olafson. He observes
he read Being and Time shortly after its pub- that he and Heideggers other students were
lication in 1927, he reconsidered his options. surprised by their teachers sudden adher-
He believed that unlike the philosophy he ence to Nazism. But he also claims that the
had studied previously, Heideggers phi- gloominess of Being and Time already sug-
losophy was concrete, relevant to life. He gests a joyless, repressive concept of exist-
later said, We saw in Heidegger what we ence not incompatible with Nazism. There is
had first seen in Husserl, a new beginning, one further comment in this interview that
the first radical attempt to put philosophy illustrates the unreliability of philosophers
on really concrete foundationsphilosophy self-interpretations. Marcuse says that he had
concerned with human existence, the human few reservations about Heideggers thought
condition, and not with merely abstract ideas during this period, which implies that he was
and principles.2 a loyal disciple. We will see that this is far
In 1928 Marcuse became Heideggers stu- from being the case.
dent and in 1930 he delivered a brilliant thesis In 1934 Marcuse settled accounts publicly
entitled Hegels Ontology and the Theory of with his Heideggerian past in an essay enti-
Historicity. It is not clear whether Heidegger tled The Struggle against Liberalism in the
rejected the work but in any case it would Totalitarian State.4 This essay argues that
soon be impossible for a Jew like Marcuse Heidegger and other Nazi sympathizers such
to find employment in a German university.3 as Carl Schmitt abandoned the fundamental

171
HEIDEGGER AND MARCUSE

concepts and norms of the philosophical during the 1919 revolution that followed
tradition. The existentialists attempted to the First World War and remained true to the
concretize the abstract categories of philoso- socialist ideal to the end. Thus his interest in
phy but ended up producing new and still Heideggers philosophy may seem surprising.
more empty abstractions that cancelled the In fact he found in Heidegger the basis for a
ethical implications of the traditional ones response to the crisis of Marxism.
and surrendered thought to power. With the defeat of the wave of revolu-
In 1947 Marcuse met Heidegger at his hut tionary offensives that followed the First
near Freiberg and came away dissatisfied: World War, the mechanistic and econo-
Heidegger apparently admitted his political mistic Marxism of the prewar period was
errors but declined to make a public apology. discredited theoretically. It could neither
In the following months, in an exchange of account for the one successful revolution in
letters, Heidegger asserted the moral equiva- Russiaa backward countrynor the failed
lence of Nazi crimes and the hardships suf- revolutions that occurred in advanced ones
fered by Germans during and after the war. with low proletarian participation. Marxist
This was the last straw for Marcuse who theorists such as Georg Lukcs argued for
denounced his former teacher in a final let- a theory of class consciousness to explain
ter that broke off all relations.5 Nevertheless, the actions of the proletariat, both its revo-
Heideggers thought had a continuing influ- lutionary enthusiasms and its disappointing
ence on him. acquiescence. Lukcs introduced the concept
Marcuses appropriation of Heideggerian of reification to describe the objectivistic and
themes divides into two periods. The first instrumentalist culture that blocked revolu-
phase has been called Heidegger-Marxismus. It tionary aspirations in capitalist society.
focuses on the existential problematic of revolu- This is where Heidegger comes in. One
tionary action as a form of authentic existence. could read his theory of inauthenticity and
This phase is cut short not only by historical authenticity as an implied critique of reifica-
contingencies but by Marcuses discovery tion and a call to historical participation in
in 1932 of Marxs Economic-Philosophical a radical project of social transformation.6
Manuscripts. The Manuscripts offered him a This was roughly how Heidegger himself
Marxist language and conceptual framework understood his theory in 1933, with dis-
in which to pursue many of the themes of his astrous consequences. Marcuse appropri-
Heideggerian phase. Much later, in the 1960s, ated the same theory for a diametrically
Marcuse focuses on the critique of science and opposed politics. Such different interpreta-
technology. In this period Heidegger again tions were possible because of what Marcuse
appears as a significant interlocutor, although would later call the phony concreteness of
there are few explicit references. Heideggers thought. However, at the time
Marcuse believed Marxism could grant it
truly concrete meaning.
Marcuse develops what I call a
Heidegger-Marxismus meta-critique of the Heideggerian con-
cepts. On the one hand, he draws on Hegel
Marcuse was a Marxist all his life. He par- and Marx to provide a social content to
ticipated in the soldiers councils in Berlin Heideggers ontological claims. On the other

172
HEIDEGGER AND MARCUSE

hand, the Marxist concept of labor is onto- relations. Class now enters the ontological
logically grounded in the Heideggerian con- domain described by Heidegger. Marcuse
cept of being-in-the-world. Heideggers Being asks,
and Time was thus transformed into a politi-
cal theory with a normative foundation.7 . . . is the world the same even for all
Marcuse argues that subject and object are forms of Dasein present within a con-
related most fundamentally, ontologically, crete historical situation? Obviously
not through consciousness or knowledge not. It is not only that the world of
but through labor. Being-in-the-world is now significance varies among particular
understood as the objectification of the self in contemporary cultural regions and
groups, but also that, within any one of
the appropriation of thinghood. The relation
these, abysses of meaning may open up
between this rather forced interpretation and
between different worlds. Precisely in the
Heideggers analysis of readiness-to-hand most existentially essential behaviour, no
was apparent to Heidegger himself. In his understanding exists between the world
only recorded comment on Marcuse, he says of the high-capitalist bourgeois and that
that Marcuse saw a parallel between Marxs of the small farmer or proletarian. Here
claim that being has precedence over con- the examination is forced to confront
sciousness and his own rejection of the prior- the question of the material constitu-
ity of consciousness in Being and Time.8 tion of historicity, a breakthrough that
Marcuse reinterpreted the concept of Heidegger neither achieves nor even ges-
Dasein on these terms. Heideggers concept tures toward.9
already represents a concretization of the
philosophical concept of the subject. He From a Heideggerian standpoint this seems
is influenced by Dilthey in identifying this a mere substitution of sociology for ontol-
concrete subject with the living individual ogy. Is there not a more fundamental onto-
as opposed to a pure cognitive function. logical level shared by all these various types
Marcuse agrees with the general approach, of Dasein? Marcuse would agree, but he
but argues that the material needs of the argues that that fundamental level can only
individual are not merely an ontic complica- be described starting out from the concrete
tion but belong to its essential nature. The human situation that is characterized by the
temporality of Dasein is now concretized struggle for the necessities of life.
through the notion of labor. Dasein must Marcuses politics then follow from his
project itself, not in the abstract but con- concretization of the concepts of inau-
cretely through the transformation of nature. thenticity or fallenness and authenticity.
Its fundamental relation to the world, its Inauthenticity is no longer identified with
being-in is now explained not just by the absorption into the anonymity of das Man
individual relationship to ready-to-hand but is due to the reification or alienation of
tools, but by the social conditions of labor. labor. Inauthentic objectivism is now iden-
This ties its ontologically fundamental rela- tified with the reduction of possibility to
tion to the future to its social relations with actuality in the reified world of the capitalist
the others alongside whom it labors. economy. Authentic action, which Heidegger
This radical revision of Heideggers con- describes as precisely the disclosive projec-
cepts situates the individual in antagonistic tion and determination of what is factically

173
HEIDEGGER AND MARCUSE

possible at the time, that is, the response between man and nature. Heidegger
called for by the situation, is now redescribed stressed that the project of an instru-
as the revolutionary act in which the sit- mental world precedes (and should pre-
uationreificationcalls for a transforma- cede) the creation of those technologies
which serve as the instrument of this
tion of the conditions of labor.10 Marcuse
ensemble (technicity) before attempting
writes, Knowledge of ones own historicity
to act upon it as a technician. In fact,
and concrete historical existence becomes such transcendental knowledge pos-
possible at the moment when existence itself sesses a material base in the needs of
breaks through reification.11 society and in the incapacity of society
The existentiale Heidegger introduces to either satisfy or develop them. I would
appear arbitrary or excessively abstract in the like to insist on the fact that the abolition
light of Marcuses meta-critique. But given of anxiety, the pacification of life, and
the collapse of the idea of proletarian revo- enjoyment are the essential needs. From
lution, Marcuses early attempts at concre- the beginning, the technical project con-
tization appear as arbitrary as Heideggers. tains the requirements of these needs....
If one considers the existential character
Nevertheless, the meta-critical structure of
of technicity, one can speak of a final
his Marxist argument will continue to rule
technological cause and the repression
his later much less orthodox writings. He will of this cause through the social develop-
continue to transform philosophical abstrac- ment of technology.13
tions into ontologized historical categories.
The concept of reason is subjected to this
treatment in the later critique of technology. This passage translates Heideggers transcen-
dental analysis of worldhood as a system
of instrumentalities based on a generalized
concept of care into the historically spe-
Technology and Rationality cific concept of technicity as the system of
technology. Heideggers care has become
In 1960 Marcuse published a short article the orientation toward human needs that
entitled De lOntologie la Technologie: is intrinsic to instrumental action as such,
Les Tendances de la Societ Industrielle.12 including modern technology. But service to
This article promises a forthcoming book human needs has been blocked by capitalism.
that will be One-Dimensional Man. The arti- Thus what Heidegger thought of as an ontol-
cle contains a significant reference to Being ogy of instrumental action unifying human
and Time. Once again Heideggers text is being and world in terms of an unspeci-
meta-critically interpreted. fied possible end has become a normative
account of the failure of technology to realize
its quite definite proper end. Marcuse sets up
A machine, a technical instrument, can
the contrast between a truncated technologi-
be considered as neutral, as pure matter.
But the machine, the instrument, does not cal a priori aimed exclusively at domina-
exist outside an ensemble, a technologi- tion and an alternative a priori that would
cal totality; it exists only as an element fulfill the telos of technology in the creation
of technicity. This form of technicity is of a harmonious society reconciled with
a state of the world, a way of existing nature. Technology is not neutral, but rather

174
HEIDEGGER AND MARCUSE

it is ambivalent, available for two different The world, now stripped of any valua-
developmental paths. tive features and disaggregated, is exposed
In 1964 Marcuse finally published to unrestrained instrumental control. Within
One-Dimensional Man. Chapters 5 and 6 can the framework of scientific research this
be seen as an implicit response to Heideggers instrumentalism is innocent enough. Science
The Question Concerning Technology. The learns by manipulating its objects in experi-
problem Marcuse poses is how to explain the ments. But the innocence of science is lost
connection between capitalism as a system of when the possibilities of instrumental con-
domination and scientific-technical rational- trol opened by the a priori of science are
ity. Chapter 5 corresponds to Heideggers exploited on a much larger scale by technol-
discussion of Aristotle and contrasts premod- ogy. This is the inner connection between sci-
ern ontology with modern science. Chapter 6 ence and technology. It reveals the inherently
then explores the science-technology connec- technological nature of science hidden in
tion and concludes with a discussion of their the cloister of the lab. Thus Marcuse writes,
political role under capitalism. The science of nature develops under the
Marcuses history of rationality can be technological a priori which projects nature
read as an alternative to Heideggers history as potential instrumentality, stuff of control
of being. Marcuse explains that in its ancient and organization.14
Greek form, reason encountered a world of In support of this view Marcuse cites sev-
substantial things. For the Greeks, exempli- eral passages from Heideggers writings on
fied by Aristotle, things are not composed science and technology. Heidegger explains
of functional units awaiting transformation that the essence of technicsMarcuses
and recombination, but rather they are sub- a prioriis the basis of mechanization.
stances with an essence that lays out their Modern man takes the entirety of Being
form and purpose. Is and ought are har- as raw material for production and subjects
monized in the potentialities that belong to the entirety of the object-world to the sweep
the essence. The Greek conception is realized and order of production. . . . the use of
practically in techn, the knowledge associ- machinery and the production of machines
ated with craft production and artistic crea- is not technics itself but merely an adequate
tion, which actualizes essence in a material. instrument for the realization of the essence
This Greek conception of rationality is of technics in its objective raw materials.15
superseded in modern times by the scientific Marcuse diverges from Heidegger in argu-
mode of experiencing and understanding the ing that the congruence of science, technol-
world. The new a priori has two essential ogy, and society is ultimately rooted in the
features, quantification and instrumentali- social requirements of capitalism and the
zation. Science does not address experience world it projects. As such science and tech-
in its immediacy but transforms everything nology cannot transcend that world. Rather,
it encounters into quantities. This stance they are destined to reproduce it by their
eliminates purpose and hence also potential- very structure. They are thus inherently con-
ity from the world. This is the basis of the servative, not because they are ideological in
value-neutrality of science, its indifference to the usual sense of the term, or because their
the good and the beautiful in the interests of understanding of nature is false. Marcuse
the true. never calls into question the cognitive value

175
HEIDEGGER AND MARCUSE

of science and technology. Rather, they Herbert Marcuse, Heideggerian Marxism,


2

are conservative because they are intrinsi- ed. R. Wolin and J. Abromeit (Lincoln and
London: University Nebraska Press, 2005),
cally adjusted to serving a social order that
1656.
views being as the stuff of domination. Thus 3
Douglas Kellner, Herbert Marcuse and the
Technology has become the great vehicle of Crisis of Marxism (Berkeley: University of
reification.16 California Press, 1984), 406, n. 1.
On this account capitalism is more than
4
Herbert Marcuse, Negations, trans. J. Shapiro
(Boston: Beacon, 1968).
an economic system; it is a world in the phe- 5
Richard Wolin, The Heidegger Controversy: A
nomenological sense of the term. This world Critical Reader (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1993),
is the historical project of a specific historical 15264.
subject, that is, it is only one possible world 6
Lucien Goldmann, Lukcs et Heidegger (Paris:
among those that have arisen in the course Denoel/Gonthier, 1973).
7
For a full account of these transformations,
of time. The subject of this world, capital-
see Andrew Feenberg, Heidegger and Marcuse:
ism, can be displaced by another subject. The The Catastrophe and Redemption of History
question of the future is thus raised. (New York: Routledge, 2005).
The progressive alternative Marcuse imag- 8
Martin Heidegger, Four Seminars, trans.
ines would have a different mode of experi- A. Mitchell and F. Raffoul (Bloomington
and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press,
ence, of seeing, from the prevailing one. The
2003),52.
leap from the rationality of domination to the 9
Herbert Marcuse, Heideggerian Marxism,
realm of freedom demands the concrete tran- ed. R.Wolin and J. Abromeit, (Lincoln and
scendence beyond this rationality, it demands London: University of Nebraska Press,
new ways of seeing, hearing, feeling, touching 2005),16.
10
Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, trans.
things, a new mode of experience correspond-
J.Macquarrie and E. Robinson (New York:
ing to the needs of men and women who can Harper and Row, 1962), 345.
and must fight for a free society.17 11
Herbert Marcuse, Heideggerian Marxism,
Marcuse develops this idea in An Essay on ed. R. Wolin and J. Abromeit (Lincoln and
Liberation with his theory of the new sensibil- London: University of Nebraska Press,
2005),32.
ity.18 The new sensibility projects an aesthetic 12
Herbert Marcuse, De lOntologie la
lifeworld oriented toward needs rather than Technologie: Les Tendances de la Societ
domination. It would be technological but in Industrielle, Arguments, 4.8 (1960)
a different way, respectful of the potentialities 13
Herbert Marcuse, From Ontology to
of its objects, both human and natural. Is there Technology: Fundamental Tendencies of
Industrial Society, in ed. D. Kellner and
a hint here of a response to Heideggers sug-
C. Pierce, Herbert Marcuse: Philosophy,
gestion that someday art might find the power Psychoanalysis and Emancipation (New York:
to again shape worlds? Perhaps so, but by the Routledge, 2011), 1367.
time Marcuse writes this text Heidegger has 14
Herbert Marcuse, One-Dimensional Man
disappeared as a reference. (Boston: Beacon Press, 1964), 153.
15
Quoted in Ibid., 1534.
16
Ibid., 108.
17
Herbert Marcuse, Beyond One-Dimensional
NOTES AND REFERENCES
Man, ed. D. Kellner, Herbert Marcuse:
Towards a Critical theory of Society (London
1
This chapter is drawn from my book Realizing and New York: Routledge, 2001), 11718.
Philosophy: Marx, Lukcs and the Frankfurt 18
Herbert Marcuse, An Essay on Liberation
School (Verso Press, forthcoming 2014). (Boston: Beacon, 1969).

176
21
Early Lecture Courses
Scott M. Campbell

What are often referred to as Heideggers the early lecture courses are intellectually
Early Lecture Courses generally consist of rich and exciting to read in their own right,
those courses that span the period between not just because of the way in which they
1919 and the publication of BT in 1927. He point toward BT.
delivered these courses while he was Husserls It would be impossible to summarize all
assistant at the University of Freiburg (1919 of Heideggers early lecture courses in this
23) and then an associate professor at the brief synopsis. My goal here will be to iso-
University of Marburg (19238). Much of late three key themes from those courses:
the scholarship on the early Heidegger has (1) the meaningfulness of life, (2) religious
focused on how these courses and other experience, and (3) language and the Greeks.
texts from that time period develop into his Early on, Heidegger was trying to develop
magnum opus, BT, the text that established an approach to philosophy that would grasp
Heideggers reputation around the world. the immediacy of life-experience in its mean-
One who is familiar with BT will find ingfulness. Along the way, he engages in an
many of the main ideas from that text sprin- analysis of life-experience in early Christian
kled throughout the early lecture courses, communities, an interpretation that is pivotal
but there are other, less familiar, ideas in to his understanding of temporality. Once
these courses, and while Heidegger eventu- he goes to Marburg in 1923, he embarks
ally abandons some of them, the early lec- upon a number of extraordinary analyses of
ture courses are philosophically interesting Plato and Aristotle, with particular emphasis
in themselves. It is important to remember on Greek logos. In all of these early lecture
that these courses are not finished products courses, he wants to show how human beings
written for publication but, indeed, lecture understand themselves from within the con-
courses that were spoken out loud to stu- texts of their own lives, making his early
dents. In them, Heidegger is thinking through project a hermeneutics of factical, everyday
ideas and explicating philosophical texts, life. Looking at these themes, we will see that
sometimes extemporaneously as many of the in his early lecture courses, Heidegger was
texts of these courses are drawn from student trying to synthesize existential ideas about the
notes. Reading these courses, one often has contextual meaningfulness of life with onto-
the sense of being a student in them. Thus, logical concerns about the nature of being.

179
EARLY LECTURE COURSES

The Meaningfulness of Life Philosophy and the Problem of Worldview


from TDP. In that lecture course, he dis-
In the early lecture courses, one can see why cusses the historical-I, which is the human
Heidegger was initially thought to be an self understood not according to an arrange-
existentialist. In many of these courses, he ment of concepts (e.g. as rational animal,
is explicitly interested in exploring with his defined by a genus and a specific difference),
students the intensity of average, everyday but rather according to the increasing inten-
life-experience and the philosophical import sity of historical experience, what he calls
of that experience. Accordingly, Heidegger is phenomenological life in its ever-growing
developing a method of doing philosophy so self-intensification (GA 56/57, 110/TDP,
as to grasp human life without turning it into 84). This concept of the historical-I is the first
a theoretical or objectified object, in other incarnation of what will later become Dasein.
words, to investigate The Being of life as its Its explicit historicality, the sense of intensity
facticity (GA 61, 114/PIA, 85). During these that it maintains and its connectedness to fac-
early years, the young Heidegger employed tical life, conveys a sense of vitality that the
the method of phenomenology. In both GA more antiseptic term Dasein lacks. In GA
56/57 and GA 58, he examines the extent to 58, he explicitly distinguishes scientific expe-
which phenomenology is a primordial sci- rience (the way a botanist studies flowers,
ence, but in these and other courses he also the way an art historian looks at Rembrandt
questions whether any science can adequately paintings, the way that a theologian analyzes
interpret the phenomenon of life. Science, he a liturgy) from factical life-experience (as one
says, is not able to gain access to the factical walks through a meadow enjoying the flow-
life-worlds in which we exist (GA 58, 77). He ers, visits a museum to look at works of art,
even says, the idea of a science of life is an or attends a mass on Sunday) (GA 58, 65).
absurdity (80). Thus, on the one hand, the Indeed, this lecture course in particular con-
young Heidegger recognizes that Husserls tains a variety of everyday examples, which
phenomenological method advances beyond show that factical life, even trivialities, are
neo-Kantianism by showing things as they the stuff of philosophical analysis (104). We
appear and not strictly according to the cannot take a theoretical or epistemological
logical laws of thought. On the other hand, view of life, but rather view it factically in its
Heidegger does not think that Husserlian meaningful character. He says:
phenomenology can adequately grasp the
meaningfulness of factical life. The object of Drinking tea, I take my cup in my hand.
phenomenology, for Husserl, was a domain In conversation I have my cup standing
of objects (GA 63, 71/OHF, 56). The object before me. It is not the case that I grasp
something colorful or even that in myself
of phenomenology for Heidegger was facti-
I grasp data of perception as a thing, and
cal life-experience in its meaningfulness.
this thing as a cup, which is determined
In BT, Heidegger describes Dasein as in time and space, something that gives
being-in-the-world, where the world is under- itself in perceptual succession, something
stood as a context of meaningful relation- that could also eventually not exist. My
ships. One can trace this theme through the cup, out of which I drinkits reality
early lecture courses, starting with the War fulfills itself in meaningfulness, the cup
Emergency Semester of 1919, The Idea of is meaningfulness itself. I live factically

180
EARLY LECTURE COURSES

always caught in meaningfulness, and identifies itself with these care-worlds so


every meaningfulness has its encircle- completely that it entirely loses a sense of
ment of new meaningfulnesses . . . I live itself. These categories are all modes of facti-
in the factical as in a wholly particular cal lifes ruinance. Inclination shows factical
context of meaningfulnesses, which are
lifes self-sufficiency (Selbstgengsamkeit)
continually permeating one another, i.e.
within those worlds. In its caring movement,
every meaningfulness is meaningfulness
for and in a context of tendency and a life is inclined toward the world and bears
context of expectation, which constructs its heaviness. The world and its distractions
itself ever anew in factical life. (1045) weigh life down. There is a distance between
life and the world, but factical life destroys
that distance or, rather, transposes that dis-
There is a particular concentration of worlds tance into the world itself, and then becomes
within the self-world, what he calls the inten- a search for worldly measure: rank, success,
sifying concentration (Zugespitztheit) of the position in life (world), catching-up, advan-
life-worlds in the self-world, and Heidegger tage, calculation, bustle, noise, style . . . (GA
describes here the layers of manifestation 61, 103/PIA, 77). The distance between life
permeating each other that can be explicated and world becomes exclusively a worldly
from ones own self-life (545). Indeed, one phenomenon. Weighed down by the heavi-
must go further than brute experience and ness of the world and seeking after worldly
see that Heidegger is trying to grasp that success, factical life is still there, but it is
primal, hidden domain that is the source or blocking-off access to itself (GA 61, 107 /PIA,
origin of the immediacy of life in its meaning- 80). There is an elliptical movement whereby
fulness. In OHF from 1923, the last lecture life circles itself without ever finding itself.
course that Heidegger delivers in Freiburg Heidegger develops these categories from
as Husserls assistant, he claims, emphati- Aristotles claim in the Nicomachean Ethics
cally, that Dasein [factical life] is being in a that virtue is difficult and vice is easy, and
world (GA 63, 80/OHF, 62). Thus, in OHF, so the fourth and final category of factical
we see that it is being itself that underlies life is effectively the ground for the other
factical life and constitutes the primal source three. Human beings are always trying to
of lifes engagement or encounter with the make things easier for themselves such that
world. lifes caring movement into the world mani-
In GA 61, Heideggers notion of factical life fests as a kind of carelessness.
changes to show that while human beings do In these early lecture courses, we find
live within rich and varied contexts of expe- Heidegger making a realistic portrayal of
rience, they can also be so absorbed in the human life. We live within rich contexts
world that they misinterpret themselves. In of meaningful relationships, which consist
this course, he outlines four categories of fac- of the connections and relations we have
tical life: inclination, distance, blocking-off, to other people, to objects, to the outside
and making things easy. These categories world, and to ourselves (the with-world,
are based on how life manifests a tempo- the environing-world, and the self-world).
ral, caring movement into the self-world, But the worlds in which we live can also be
the with-world, and the environing-world. deceiving. We can be so taken in by them that
They indicate the various ways in which life we fail to see ourselves, identifying human

181
EARLY LECTURE COURSES

life completely with the world in which we the historical here: the first is Platonic, the
live. When Heidegger describes authenticity second is pragmatic, and third is based on
in BT, we find this same confluence of revela- life-philosophy. The Platonic approach,
tion and deception, so that Dasein is always he says, renounces history. According to
both in the truth and in untruth (SZ, 222/ Heidegger, the approaches found in both
BT, 265). Note, too, that although Heidegger pragmatism and life-philosophy are episte-
will not thematize the structure of aletheia as mological and objectify the historical, sub-
a simultaneous revelation and concealment/ jecting it to human manipulation. Thus, none
errancy until much later, it is tacitly operative of these approaches adequately captures the
here in the early lecture courses. genuine historical movement of life.
It is possible that Heidegger would have
spent the entire lecture course on these meth-
odological ruminations, but at one point
Religious Experience during the semester students in the course
complained to the Dean of the University of
During the winter semester of 19201 and Freiburg that this class actually contained
the summer semester of 1921, Heidegger no religious content. Immediately, Heidegger
presents a fascinating series of lecture courses shifted gears and engaged upon a phenom-
on religious life. In the first of these courses, enological analysis of the letters of Paul.
Introduction to the Phenomenology of In these interpretations Heidegger is try-
Religion, he is trying to grasp the intensity ing to grasp the temporal immediacy of the
and immediacy of life-experience in the pri- lives of the early Christians, who believed
mal Christian communities. This is consist- that Jesus return was imminent and so the
ent with his approach to factical life during world could end at any moment. There is a
this period. His analysis in this course is of profound sense of urgency in Pauls letters
a particular community of people, and con- as he exhorts them to become Christians
sequently it is less abstract than some of his (GA 60, 100/PRL, 70). Their factical lives
analysis in BT. The course divides into two as Christians are thus structured by faith,
main parts. The first part is a general medi- knowledge, and the parousia (the second
tation on the method of formal indication. coming of Christ), and these structures are
The second part uses the letters of St. Paul grounded in the temporality of their own
to capture the factical immediacy of life in lives. When the early Christians asked Paul
the early Christian communities. Heidegger when Jesus will return, Paul turns the ques-
shows how categories of life can be applied tion back on them, forcing them to make
to the factical lives of religious people. a critical decision about who they are and
His meditation on formal indication in what kind of life they want to lead. While
this lecture course on religious life is particu- they do not know exactly when Jesus will
larly instructive. It is clear from this course return, they are called upon to understand
that the primary goal of formal indication themselves as Christians: it is essential that
is to develop a method, grounded in phe- the word (Verkndigung) always remains
nomenology, which can sustain the tempo- there with you in a vital (lebendig) way (GA
ral and historical movement of human life. 60, 117/PRL, 84). Heideggers conclusion is
He looks at three different approaches to that the early Christians lived time. As he

182
EARLY LECTURE COURSES

says, Christian experience lives time itself which he provides an analysis of Aristotles
(GA 60, 82/PRL, 57). Who they are (present) Rhetoric. Many of the commentators on
depends on having become a Christian (past) these early lecture courses have remarked
as they await the second coming of Christ that in the early courses Heidegger is more
(future). interested in Aristotles practical works, the
Ethics and the Rhetoric, than he is in the
theoretical works, such as the Physics and
Metaphysics. Indeed, he is attempting to
Language and the Greeks interpret theoretical concepts out of the con-
text of the factical life-world from which they
In 1923, Heidegger traveled to Marburg to derived. This is similar to his approach in the
become an assistant professor at the univer- courses on religious life, where he tries to
sity. His lecture courses on the Greek thinkers retrieve the factical life of the early Christian
during this time are extraordinary analyses of communities prior to the interpolation of
the texts of Plato and Aristotle, often line-by- philosophical concepts into religion and
line explications sustained throughout the the subsequent development of theological
semester. One marvels at how these close dogma. His analysis of GA 18 is consistent
readings illuminate the facticity of Greek life. with this approach. He uses Aristotles analy-
He does not focus on Aristotles ontological sis of the ordinary ways of speaking, arguing,
system or on Platos theory of forms. Instead, refuting, debating, and discussing evident in
Heidegger was interested in bringing to life the Rhetoric in order to grasp the basic ori-
the Greek world from which the concepts of entation of human beings in the world. As he
Plato and Aristotle developed, what we might emphasizes, The Rhetoric is nothing other
call the factical conceptuality of ancient than the interpretation of concrete Dasein,
Greek philosophical concepts. For example, the hermeneutic of Dasein itself (GA 18,
Heidegger accepts Aristotles definition of 110/BCAR, 75). The main idea of this course
the human being as a zoon logon echon. This is that logos or speaking is the fundamental
is normally translated as rational animal. way in which human beings orient themselves
Looking at the factical conceptuality of these in the world (GA 18, 18/BCAR, 1415). With
concepts, however, Heidegger claims that this approach, he explores ideas of authentic
in the Greek world, zoon did not just mean speaking, being-in-the-polis (or city), and
animal, it meant life, and logos did not even ethical excellence.
just mean reason or rationality, it meant In the winter semester of 19245, Heidegger
speaking. The human being thus is a zoon continues his exploration of logos by analyz-
logon echon, but not a rational animal. The ing Platos Sophist. He actually begins with
human, rather, is a living being in dialogi- an extended treatment of Aristotle, follow-
cal (speaking) relationships in a community ing the hermeneutic principle that Aristotle
with others, and this can be discerned within understood Plato better than Plato under-
Aristotles own definition when it is read stood himself. Although Heidegger is critical
from within the context of the factical world of Platonic dialectic because, he says, its goal
in which he lived. is a pure seeing of the Ideas (which are beings
One of the most extraordinary of and not being itself), he believes that Plato had
Heideggers early lecture courses is GA 18, in a deeper and more original understanding of

183
EARLY LECTURE COURSES

being and logos than modern thinkers. In a the environing-world, the with-world, and the
remarkable analysis at the end of this course, self-world, and there is a kind of intensifying
he connects logos to deloun to show that the concentration of permeating layers of meaning
primary way in which human beings are in embedded within the self-world. The second
the world is through a way of speaking that vector of experience is temporal and histori-
reveals or discloses phenomenal contexts cal. Heidegger often refers to ancient texts in
through manifolds of words (GA 19, 594/PS, order to retrieve original meanings, but there is
411). In his interpretation of Greek Dasein, simultaneously a propulsion forward, toward
he presents deloun as a kind of nontheoreti- the future, into new ways of thinking. Taking
cal disclosure that is operative in both speak- up these two directions of experience, we try
ing and attentive listening. to make sense of our own lives. As he says in
It is worthy of note that many of the basic GA 58, We are standing in our factical life,
ideas in Heideggers reading of Greek logos and we speak and understand in the circle of
from his Marburg periodabout authentic our understandability (98). In other words,
language, speaking, and listening to others in we try to become understandable to ourselves
a community, and revealing structural mani- from within these various contexts as we look
folds of words in discourseeither do not through the past and toward the future, which
make their way into BT or are underdeveloped is why a hermeneutics of factical experience is
in that text. Reading the early lecture courses, running through these early lecture courses.
we see that Heidegger was using the texts of In GA 63, he describes hermeneutics as pursu-
Plato and Aristotle to develop ways of think- ing our own self-alienation, but always within
ing about the complex relationships among the contexts of our own unique and particular
speaking, being, and factical human life. lives. From within our own life-contexts, our
There are a variety of ways to interpret own experiences, our own historical epochs,
Heideggers early lecture courses, but any and thus our own time, we try to understand
approach would have to take account of the who we are. Similar to Descartes, Heidegger
relationship between factical human existence starts philosophizing with the I am, but
and the meaning of being that he was explor- whereas Descartes emphasizes the I or cog-
ing during this time period. Throughout all ito, Heidegger emphasizes the am, that is,
of these courses, Heidegger does not repeat the being of factical human life (GA 61, 174/
himself. There are similar themes, but he PIA, 131).
does not rehash the same material over and It is interesting, yet perhaps somewhat
over again or reuse his lecture notes from puzzling, that the main topic of BT is neither
semester to semester. Each of the published being nor time but rather Dasein. BT attempts
courses contains new and original insights, to lay bare hermeneutically the ontological
and yet running through these courses is a structures of Dasein, which is the human
restless quest to synthesize human existence being insofar as it is concerned about its own
with an understanding of who we are in our being. In this structure, we find the whole
factical, everyday lives. project of the early lecture courses coming
There are two primary vectors of experi- together. The effort to synthesize ontologi-
ence that we find in these early courses. The cal ideas about who the human being is with
first is contextual. We live within contexts of existential ideas about human life crystallizes
meaning structured by the various life-worlds: in the notion of Dasein.

184
22
Heidegger, Persuasion, and
Aristotles Rhetoric
P. Christopher Smith

In treating Heideggers 1924 lectures, direction from the one Heidegger had in
Grundbegriffe der Aristotelischen Philosophie mind.1 As his 1927 Sein und Zeit (Being and
(Basic Concepts of Aristotelian Philosophy, Time) will make clear, Aristotles exposi-
GA 18), this chapter explores the early tion of the path or affects in the Rhetoric
Heideggers revolutionary rehabilitation is of interest to Heidegger primarily because
of rhetoric. We will be concerned with two of the opening it provides for him to pur-
issues here. First, we want to see how, in sue the concomitance of human existences
developing a hermeneutics of facticity, thrusting of itself toward future possibilities
Heidegger finds one of the most basic ways (Sich-Entwerfen) and its inescapable experi-
we are originally, there in the factual ence of always having already been thrust
world to be precisely in our speaking to each (geworfen) into a certain mood, frame of
other to take care of things. We want to see, in mind or, literally, way in which it finds itself
other words, how he considers human exist- feeling (sich befindet).2 The exposition of
ence to be fundamentally rhetorical. Second, this concomitance in Being and Time paves
we wish to show how, more radically, within the way for a discussion of Angst as the par-
this rhetorical dimension of his herme- ticular mood in which the meaningfulness
neutics of facticity Heidegger uses a strategy of things is annihilated and in which, conse-
of Destruktion to overthrow our standard quently, the self, having forfeited itself to the
ideas about reasoning and display that at its public world of what everybody thinks and
Grund or ground any rhetorical communica- does, is abruptly summoned back to its genu-
tion is inextricably embedded in an affective ine being.3 If one is seeking authenticity, as
setting and conditioned by it. This will clarify Heidegger is, the talk in the public realm, die
why Aristotles treatment of pathos as a basic ffentlichkeit, the realm of rhetoric, is thus
component of rhetorical persuasion receives viewed as mere talk, Gerede, that not only
Heideggers particular attention. falsifies the real nature of the things talked
It may well be, however, that in reading about but absorbs the self and hides it from
Heideggers Basic Concepts of Aristotelian itself. Accordingly, instead of countering the
Philosophy as a rehabilitation of rhetoric, critique of rhetoric found in Platos Gorgias
we are forcing this text in a very different and Republic, Heidegger is developing his

185
HEIDEGGER, PERSUASION, AND ARISTOTLES RHETORIC

own version of it: the everybody that bab- refutation and disputation (ibid.). Moreover,
bles on vacuously is Platos hoi polloi, and a validation of rhetoric is clearly evident in
the task is to know yourself by retrieving the three theses that Heidegger will make
yourself from the received opinions (endoxa) basic for his interpretation of Aristotles
being bantered about. Rhetoric: (1) the being of the human being
In the Basic Concepts of Aristotelian is being in a world, (2) this being in a world
Philosophy, however, this trajectory has not is characterized by logos, (3) this speaking
yet been fully set and, remarkably, we still itself is the way taking care of things [in the
find there many rich and seminal passages world] is carried out (GA 18, 66). What
on how communication originally takes is more Heidegger titles his chapter III An
place among human beings engaged in tak- exposition (Auslegung) of human existence
ing care of things in the everyday world. And (Dasein) in regard to the ground and basic
for the purposes of a philosophical reha- possibility of speaking with one another,
bilitation of rhetoric it is striking that quite using the Rhetoric as a guide (103). As he
unlike the Heidegger of Being and Time who says there,
condemns die ffentlichkeit or the public
realm of discourse as degenerate (see SZ, The human being is a living thing that
27), the Heidegger of the Basic Concepts, has its real existence in conversation
takes Aristotles characterization of the and talk. . . . This constitutive ground
human being in the Politics (1252b30) as (Grundverfassung) of Greek existence
the zion logon echon, the live being having is where one should look for the soil
speech, to be proof that for Aristotle there (Boden) from which this [Greek] defini-
tion of the human being grows. (108)
is contained in the very being of the human
being the ground and basic existential pos-
sibility of being in the polis; Aristotle, Accordingly, the issue for a philosophy of
he says, takes being-in-the-polis to be the rhetoricand this is my concern hereis
life proper to human beings (das eigentliche what one could achieve if one developed
Leben der Menschen) (GA 18, 467; my from Heideggers revolutionary beginnings
emphasis). Our speaking, he concludes, is the a rhetorical theory that stays with the pri-
very essence of our being together with each ority of the being spoken to over speaking,
other, or as Aristotle puts this, our koin- and that consequently establishes, beneath
nia, our community (ibid., 47). Thus even if all derivative abstractions, the ground and
early on in the Basic Concepts we seem to be basis of human community in my hearing
diverted from expositing a theory of how we what is said to me by someone else. If this is
speak and listen to each other publicly, rheto- so, my speaking to myself becomes entirely
ricians can at least point out that Heidegger derivative.
has argued here that in this determination, Approaching the matter this way would
logon echon, a fundamental characteristic have two advantages. First, it heads off
of human existence becomes visible: being Heideggers turn inward and the residual
with one another, and this, to be sure, not in Cartesianism that this turn implies. Listening
the sense of merely being placed next to each to oneself, after all, is merely a modification
other, but in the sense of being involved in of Descartes cogito me cogitare, I think
speaking to each otherin communication, myself thinking, from which he deduces his

186
HEIDEGGER, PERSUASION, AND ARISTOTLES RHETORIC

cogito ergo sum, I think, therefore I am. at first takes even rhetorical speech as dis-
The priority of hearing what another has closure of something we can see rather
said to me would force the restatement of than as exhortation we either do or do not
this with something like mihi loquoris ergo hear. Indeed, he will argue that the rhetori-
loquor, you speak to me, therefore I speak. cal logos has the basic, ground function of
In this way Aristotles koinnia or commu- making plain (dloun) that [world] which
nity, with which Heidegger begins, would be being-in-a-world resides in (GA 18, 139).
recovered. And self-evidently I am not the For him rhetorical speech brings something
condition of the possibility of the language into view for onlookers who will see it in
I speak to others in my community, rather a certain way, and the pathos and frame of
they are: I can only say things in response to mind, diathesis, of these onlookers is of inter-
what I have first heard from others. Second, est because it determines the view or Ansicht
in stressing the priority of what I have heard they will have of it.
from another we could finally escape the If krisis, is taken as decision, however,
mythology of speech acts as performances the pathos and frame of mind of an audi-
of some fictional agent self. ence determines whether they hear and obey
This, of course is not the route Heidegger (hupakouein) what the speaker is exhorting
takes. To be sure, in treating Aristotles three them to do. (If a parent says to a child, Do
pisteis, or persuaders, namely logos, thos, you hear me? I see what you mean is not
and pathos, or the speakers reasoning, their the response expected!) To be sure, Aristotle
character, or the way they come across, and himself has the very same ocular tendencies
the feeling or disposition (diathesis) they wish as Heidegger does, and krisis, as he uses the
to bring about in their audience, Heideggers word, could often mean judgment and the
primary focus is on pathos and, with that, related krinein, to pass judgmentbut
his attention shifts from what the speakers clearly not always. If, unlike Heidegger, we
say to what is going on in their hearers. To are to appropriate Aristotles rhetoric for
be specific, Heidegger follows Aristotle in persuasion (peith) rather than for exposi-
asserting that it is pathos that determines the tion of a state of affairs, we would need a
krisis of the audience (see GA 18, 120 and phenomenology of the experience of hearing,
Rhet. 1356a 1416). The problem for us, of what is done to us and with us when we
however, those of us who might anticipate are spoken to, such that we are changed, not
an account of their acoustical experience, in our Ansichten or views of things, but in
is that Heideggers translates krisis, not as what we are willed to do.
Entschlu, or decision, but as Ansicht, that Despite his very different intent, however,
is, a view or opinion that the audience there is much in Heideggers interpretations
comes to hold as a result of what the speaker that still can help us in this regard. That kri-
has said to them. We have here a first indi- sis is more than coming to an opinion or view
cation of the overriding, ocular, rather than about some subject matter (Sache; see 122),
acoustical, concern that defines Heideggers and more even than passing judgment as an
appropriation of Aristotles Rhetoric: though impartial onlooker (theros; see 1245), is
Entschloenheit, decisiveness or better, made clear in Heideggers recounting of the
resolve, will figure prominently in Being and double purpose of sumbouleutik or delib-
Time, here in the Basic Concepts Heidegger erative rhetoric, which, as Heidegger puts it,

187
HEIDEGGER, PERSUASION, AND ARISTOTLES RHETORIC

gives counsel regarding a course of action. really is, about which there exists some opin-
For as protrop or apotrop, this form of ion or view (Ansicht) (ibid.).
speech would literally either turn someone What is sumpheron or the advantageous,
toward or turn someone away from an as opposed to what is blaberon or harmful,
action (125). We are, in other words, talking is, of course, precisely the issue in sumbeu-
about a visceral change in volition here and leutik or deliberative rhetoric (see Rhet.
not just an intellectual change in opinion. 1358b 22). We note, accordingly, that what
And if, for the time being, Heidegger seems we have here, stated in an exposition of the
to overlook the physical, somatic basis for Ethics and not the Rhetoric, is the very dis-
such a change in will, he does at least in pass- tinction we had been looking for between
ing call to our attention the word thumos, the purposes of argument in deliberative
heart or breast, contained in the name for the rhetoric and argument in demonstration:
rhetorical syllogism, the enthumma, by say- Unlike demonstrative argument, deliberative
ing that the rhetorical argument is meant be rhetoricand this is rhetorics most basic
taken to heart (133). formdoes not aim primarily at commu-
As a matter of fact Heidegger will become nicating an opinion or view (Ansicht) after
more explicit on this visceral, volitional all. Its concern, instead, is to bring its audi-
dimension of krisis via a detour through the ence to a decision, an Entschlu, whether
Ethics account of prohairesis or choice. For an action is to be undertaken or not. To be
krisis, at least in sumbouleutik or delibera- sure, this decision is not merely a matter of
tive rhetoric, means, as it turns out, virtu- epithumia and thumos, desire and the heart
ally the same thing as choice. In the Basic or spirit, which lack the clarity of a trans-
Concepts, 143 ff., Heideggers immediate parent decision (Entschlu) (GA 18, 143).
concern in treating prohairesis is precisely to It will have an intellectual component, for,
differentiate between doxa, on the one hand, as the name sumbeuleutik makes evident, it
which Heidegger defines as the opinion or comes at the end of joint consultation and
view (Ansicht) one has of something, and pro- deliberation (bouleuesthai). Still, there is a
hairesis, on the other, which he renders with lot more involved here than simply thinking
the German Entschlossensein, meaning to things over. Since to decide on something is
have resolved or decided upon something. A more a matter of volition rather than cogni-
prohairesis, he says, is concerned with the tion, one must be made to feel like doing it.
prakton [an action to be done], that which is Not, I see, but, I hear you and I will, is
decisive for taking care (Besorgen) of some- the response sought, and no logos without
thing at the moment (145). Prohairesis, pathos will bring this about.
committing oneself to, and deciding for For clarification that Heidegger sees the
something (sich entschlieen zu etwas), aims role of pathos in moving an audience to a
at the sumpheron, namely something which, decision, we can turn to a crucial passage in
if undertaken, will be to my advantage in the Rhetoric, cited by Heidegger in the Greek
taking care, Besorgen, of some matter that (170):
I might take in hand (147). Doxa, in con-
trast, is concerned with what is althes and
pseudes, what is true or false: With doxa . (Rhet.
the concern to comprehend what something 1378a 20)

188
HEIDEGGER, PERSUASION, AND ARISTOTLES RHETORIC

Piecing together the fragments of Heideggers The point for us, who are pursuing the
reading of this, we get something like the fol- implications for rhetoric of this Destruktion
lowing translation: of the listeners self-possessed reason, is that
Heidegger has uncovered the physiological,
It is, however, the path by which, in our somatic ground and basis of supposedly
sudden conversion from one to another, rational thought in the conversion of the
we differ in the decisions [we make].4 listeners hexis and diathesis brought on by
a shift in the path. What takes place here
Precisely in turning to the phenomenology is a sudden conversion in my whole psycho-
of hearing that we have been looking for, somatic being from one underlying state or
Heidegger seizes upon the di hosa metabal- habitude to another, and it is this conversion,
lontes here, which he glosses as, in regard not the logos or argument of what is said to
to which a sudden conversion (Umschlag) me, that ultimately determines my krisis or
occurs in ourselves (GA 18, 170), and decision. Remarkably, Heidegger argues that
with that, he moves to a most radical and far from being firm, steady, unmoved, we are
astonishing break with philosophys tradi- metaballontes, that is, in Heideggers words,
tional emphasis on Socratic composure and we are reeling from one state and attitude
self-control. He sees the Umschlag or sudden (Fassung) into another, and, he continues,
conversion as taking place in our, the listen- the defining feature of this transition is not
ers, hexis, which he renders as Verfassung, the new state we arrive at, but our being
namely, the constitution, condition, state, in motion, underway, between states, its
habitude, we happen to find ourselves in. peculiar Unruhe, disquietude, unsettled-
Such Umschlagen in eine andere Verfassung, ness, perturbation. In the case of phobos or
or sudden conversion into another state fear, this condition can even be character-
can even take the form, he says, of being ized as tarach, confusion, getting mixed
seized or being waylaid (Ergriffenwerden, up (Verwirrung, Durcheinandergeraten)
berfallenwerden) and, playing on the (183) (so much for Epicurean ataraxia or
Fassung or composure stem of Verfassung, imperturbability!).
Heidegger adds that in this case the sud- This demolition of the listeners fictive
den conversion from one state to another disembodied, self-contained, rational detach-
amounts to Aus-der-Fassung-Kommen, ment goes hand in hand with Heideggers
meaning to lose it or come unhinged hermeneutics of facticity and its empha-
(171). Of course I can make myself ready sis on our original being-in-the world. We
for this, (Gefatsein dafr); indeed, my are ec-static, out there, so to speak, and
hexis or state determines the authentic- thereby exposed physically, corporeally, to
ity (Eigentlichkeit) of human existence in a what comes over us even as we are overcome
moment of being ready for and accepting by it. The states of mind corresponding to
of something (des Gefatseins fr etwas), these experiences are derivative epiphenom-
which takes the form of Here I am come ena that are grounded in what is happen-
what may (176). Still, I must acknowledge ing to the body. It follows that pathos, from
the possibility that within my being, some- paschein, meaning literally to undergo, is
thing comes over me that throws me (aus to be understood as Mitgenommenwerden
der Fassung bringt) (ibid.). des menschlichen Daseins in seinem vollen

189
HEIDEGGER, PERSUASION, AND ARISTOTLES RHETORIC

leiblichen In-der-Welt-sein (human existence actually are. The self-evident answer is by


being carried along in its complete bodily voice and gesture, which is to say, music
being-in-the-world), and For this reason, and dance. For the vibrations of voice with
he explains, the path are not psychological its variations in tone, volume, timbre, pitch
events, not in consciousness (197). The as well as in tempo, rhythm, meter, and the
so called bodily conditions (Leibeszustnde) correlative expressive motions of the body
experienced with anxiety, joy and the like are impact the audience immediately, and it is
no mere accompaniment to the phenomena, the bodily experience of these in the audience
rather they belong to the characteristic being that invoke the reversed hexis or diathesis,
of the human being (198). the Verfassung or psychosomatic condition
The conclusion Heidegger draws from our and disposition, that underlies not only our
ground in bodily feeling is stunning: volitional decisions but in fact our cognitive
views of things too. But Heidegger, of course,
Insofar as the path (feelings) are not just does not go so far as to say this.
an appendix of psychological events but
the soil and ground from which speech
NOTES AND REFERENCES
grows and into which what has been said
grows back, the path, for their part, pro- 1
As the title of his lectures makes clear, Basic
vide the ground and basic range of affec- Concepts of Aristotelian Philosophy, Aristotles
tive possibilities that human existence is Rhetoric per se is by no means the exclusive
predisposed to feel, and within which it concern of Heideggers investigations, and in
orients itself about itself. Its primary way his exploration of concepts basic to Aristotelian
of orienting itself, of clarifying its being philosophy he will range over many other texts,
in the world, is no form of knowing among them, the Metaphysics, On the Soul, the
but a way one finds oneself feeling.. .. Nicomachean Ethics, the Politics, the Physics,
The possibility of speaking about things and On Interpretation.
2
See SZ, 29, 31, 40 on the gleichursprnglich
[authentically] is only given once these
or equally basic Entwurf (ones thrust of oneself
have been stripped of the appearance forward, or projection), Geworfenheit (the con-
[of objectivity] they have when we first dition of having been thrust), and Befindlichkeit
begin to deal with them and we grasp (the frame of mind that one always already
them within an affective predisposition finds oneself thrust into).
or feeling characterized as such. (262) 3
See SZ 567 on Angst and the Ruf des
Gewissens (call of conscience).
4
I would translate, It is the path whose
The question for a philosophy of rhetoric, conversions from one to another alter the
then, is just how speakers communicate on decisions [we make]. At issue is the subject of
this ground and basic level, just how they metaballontes and diapherousi. I take this to be
can induce the prerequisite metabol, the path, but Heidegger takes it to be we (wir),
reading the third person plural diapherousi as a
Umschlag or sudden conversion of affect in first person plural in German. This is stand-
the inherently unstable psychosomatic unity ard Greek usage, and right or wrong, it leads
that, beneath all fictions of pure reason, we Heidegger in a most compelling direction.

190
23
Being and Time
Dennis J. Schmidt

The philosophical project that unfolds in the power of the most elemental words in
Being and Time resists any simple defini- which Dasein expresses itself (GA 2, 220/
tion and any reduction to a position. None BT, 211). Even the key terms of Husserls
of the usual interpretive techniques seem phenomenologya philosopher and a meth-
to help one approach this unusual text, odology to which Heidegger pays explicit
even the effort to situate it in the context homageare largely abandoned in Being
of a larger tradition and other texts is dif- and Time. So, in the Introductionwhen
ficult. At the outset however, one might get one is searching for an orientation or context
the impression that Being and Time can be with which one might approach this text
located in a long and well-defined meta- one finds an unsettled and quite complicated
physical tradition: it opens with its dedica- sense of just how one is to enter into the phil-
tion to Heideggers teacher, Husserl, moves osophical project of Being and Time. From
to a citation from Platos Sophist, and then, the beginning Being and Time seems deter-
in the Introduction, mention is made of a mined to disorient its readers. In its efforts to
wide range of philosophers including Plato, set itself apart from philosophical traditions
Aristotle, Suarez, Aquinas, Descartes, Pascal, and languages, and to resist any easy appro-
Kant, Hegel, Bergson, and Husserl. While priation into well-established contexts, Being
it might seem that by doing this Heidegger and Time quietly announces the radicality of
locates his own work with reference to its own intentions.1
other works that have come to define a sort The first readers of Being and Time recog-
of orthodox philosophical canon, one soon nized this and so the first reviews spoke of
learns that these references provide almost the experience of reading this book as like
no help in situating the project of Being and an electric shock and a lightning strike,
Time. Adding to the sense that all of the and its young (37-year-old) author, Martin
markers that might orient the reader of this Heidegger, was described as philosophi-
text offer no help whatsoever, one finds that cally brilliant and a genius. Of course,
the abundance of neologisms populating not every reviewer was so positive and Being
Being and Time constantly remind one that and Time, and its author, rapidly became the
Heidegger finds the language of philosophy center of controversies that continue even
that he has inherited insufficient for the into our time. It is now 85 years since the
business of philosophy [namely] to preserve publication of Being and Time and during

191
Being and Time

that period it seems as if Being and Time that being [Seiende] who asks the question of
has become a work in the very same canon being [Sein]. This being who asks the ques-
that it sought to disrupt. While the contro- tion of what it means to beand not to be
versies surrounding Heidegger and his work Heidegger calls Dasein. The character of
have continued, what seems to have been lost this being will only gradually become clear
today that the first readers of this remarkable through analyses of how Dasein is in the
text recognized is the sense of disorientation world and it is important that the reader
that comes as soon as one engages this book. of Being and Time not quickly seek to find
However, to lose sight of this disorientation traditional philosophical notionssuch as
is to lose sight of the real access that opens subject, human being, consciousnessthat
up Being and Time since the first task it sets can serve as substitutes for the difficult task
for itself is to reawaken a special perplex- of understanding the being of Dasein, of the
ity, namely the perplexity that opens up the way being is in-the-world. If one needs to find
question of the meaning of being. Heidegger a preliminary definition of Dasein, then it
argues that the chief task of Being and Time is best to say simply that it is that being who
is to unfold a question that must come to be is defined and distinguished by always asking
understood as inherently elusive. In order to the question of being. Asking this question
bring this question forward, it is necessary to is the fundamental drive and preoccupa-
begin with what is inherent to it: its difficulty, tion of Daseineven when it is forgotten
elusivity, resistance, and disorienting charac- and even when it remains unthematized it
ter. It is quite significant then that the first remains definitive for the being and defini-
words of Being and Time note that the ques- tion of Daseinand the way Dasein is, is at
tion of being has today been forgotten (GA each moment defined by this preoccupation
2, 2/BT, 1) and that the first aim of Being and with the question of what it means to be.
Time is to rekindle and explicitly retrieve Heidegger calls this way of being of Dasein in
the question of being. It is this question of which it perpetually faces itself as a question
being, which is the fundamental ontologi- factical life and he argues that the recovery
cal question, that guides the philosophical of the question of being is first made possi-
project of Being and Time. And yet, it is pre- ble by means of an analysismore precisely,
cisely this question that we have forgotten. by the hermeneuticsof the factical life of
From the outset, Heidegger makes clear that Dasein: Thus fundamental ontology . . .
this forgetting of the question of being is not must be sought in the existential analysis of
simply a mistake or an error that could Dasein (GA 2, 13/BT, 12).
be easily corrected: one does not forget the In the final section of the Introduction
question of being the way one forgets ones Heidegger outlines the entire project of
keys, nor can one ask this question in the Being and Time. He announces that it will be
form that most questions take. Its obscurity divided into two parts and that each part will
and difficulty, its tendency to be forgotten, be divided into three divisions. Part one is to
are not accidental, but belong intimately to lay out the interpretation of Dasein and then
the very question of being itself. It is a ques- the explication of time as the horizon for ask-
tion that, initially at least, disorients. ing the question of being. Part two is to carry
In order to recover this question, Heidegger out a phenomenological destruction of the
undertakes a phenomenological analysis of history of ontology in order to clear the way

192
Being and Time

to a more radical formulation of the question that drives and guides the project of Being
of being. For reasons that have more to do and Time, is never fully broached in text that
with job security and the well-known pub- we have.
lish or perish problem of the academic world
(though he was, as his recently published lec-
ture courses make clear, a powerful teacher
of renown and originality, Heidegger had Division One
not published anything in the decade prior
to publishing Being and Time), Heidegger The preliminary analysis of Dasein begins
elected to publish the first two completed by asserting two key features of this being
divisions before the remaining four divisions who asks the question of being: first, that
were complete. And, for more complicated it is always mine (GA 2, 41/BT, 41) and
and philosophically very interesting rea- second that the essence of this being lies
sons, Heidegger never publishedat least in its to be. . . . its existence (GA 2, 42/
as the continuation of Being and Timethe BT, 41). In other words, Dasein is inalien-
remaining four divisions.2 It was not until ably singular and so must be understood in
the seventh edition of Being and Time (1953) its concreteness, and it is always unfinished
that Heidegger would drop the designation and underway, that is, it is always a matter
First Half that had stood as a reminder of possibilities that it is to be or not to be and
that the published text of Being and Time thus it is more than simply something actual.3
was unfinished. With that edition Heidegger In other words, from the outset Dasein is
acknowledged that the second half could no sharply distinguished from other kinds of
longer be added without the first being pre- beings that are defined by their actuality
sented anew, unfortunately by removing the and simple presence. This is why Heidegger
reminder that the published text is the torso refers to the analytic of Dasein as an existen-
of its own intentions, Heidegger quietly hides tial analytic, that is, as an inquiry into how
the best reminder that the book that we have Dasein comes to exist as it does rather than
does not carry out its own project. We never as seeking to define what Dasein is.4 To this
fully arrive at the question of Being (and end, Heideggers analysis seeks to expose the
Time), but remain largely concerned with structures that make a being such as Dasein
the question of the analytic of Dasein that possible. Heidegger calls these structures
culminates in the presentation of Dasein and existentials.
temporality. That some of the first interpret- It is not possible to even pretend to do
ers of Being and Time mistook it as a work justice to the careful and probing phenom-
of existentialism (Sartre) or of philosophical enological analysis of Dasein that constitutes
anthropology (Husserl) can be accounted for the bulk of division one of part one of Being
by remembering what both of those com- and Time (strictly speaking, the preliminary
monplace interpretations forget: that the analytic of Dasein is found in sections 1242;
published text of Being and Time is unfin- GA 2, 52200/BT, 53193). One finds there
ished. The best readings of Being and Time discussions of the meaning of a world, of
always bear in mind that this self-rewriting things and tools, of signs and significance,
text is incomplete and that the question of of meaning and intelligibility, of space and
being, the fundamental question of ontology spatiality, of everydayness and the self, of

193
Being and Time

mood, anxiety, and fear, of understanding, Heidegger puts the point this way: Dasein
language, and propositions, of curiosity, gos- is its disclosedness (GA 2, 133/BT, 129).
sip, of others, and of thrownness, of solici- Second, although Heidegger examines these
tude and careamong other themes. In the structures of Daseins factical way of being
course of these analyses, we find a critique as largely distinct matters, it must be stressed
of Cartesian ontology (sections 1921; GA that Dasein is, and always understands itself,
2, 89101/BT, 8799) that is introduced in as a whole. Heidegger makes this clear when
order to provide a sharp contrast with the he says that all of the existential structures
sense of a world and the being of Dasein are equiprimordial, that is, none of them
Heidegger is presenting. After concluding the has priority over any of the others. This
analytic of Dasein and before beginning its means that the structures defining Dasein
repetition in division two Heidegger provides cannot be regarded as grounds upon
another set of contrasts between what his which other structures rest; rather, the being
analysis of Dasein has demonstrated and tra- of Dasein is much more appropriately char-
ditional, metaphysical assumptions. In these acterized as the event in which all of these
final sections of division one, Heidegger structures open Dasein to its world and thus
addresses the notions of reality and of truth to itself. This wholenessthis eventof
(sections 434; GA 2, 22030/BT, 193220). Dasein is what Heidegger describes as care
Kant and Aristotle are frequently invoked in [Sorge]. Care names the structural wholeness
these sections, but it would be incorrect to of Dasein in which Dasein always finds itself
suggest that Heidegger is providing a careful already in a world, with others, and among
treatment of either figure in these sections; things in such a way that Dasein must be
they serve more as foils for what Heidegger understood as ahead of itself. Its being
takes to be positions he is attempting to matters to Dasein because it remains always
overcome. a question for itself, it exists as this question
In order to make sense of the analytic of of the to be: a constant unfinished quality
Dasein two overarching points need to be thus lies in the essence of the basic constitu-
kept in mind. First, that the existential struc- tion of Dasein (GA 2, 236/BT, 227).
tures exposed by this phenomenological anal- The preliminary analysis of Dasein found
ysis describe the various ways in which the in part one, division one exposes the equipri-
factical life of Dasein unfolds in the world. mordially fundamental structures that artic-
They indicate the ways in which Dasein ulate and give shape to the way that Dasein
articulates itself, exists in the world, and is in the world and the way in which it finds
so discloses itself to itself. It is important to itself there. This analysis is, as Heidegger
emphasize that this self-disclosure of Dasein reminds his reader, preparatory and can-
as it is in the world is not a cognitive matter, not lay claim to primordiality (GA 2, 233/
that is, it is not a form of self-knowledge or BT, 223) since the wholeness of the being
self-reflection as it has long been discussed of Dasein that is characterized there as care
in the history of philosophy.5 Strictly speak- only shows Dasein as still outstanding and
ing, Dasein exists in and as these structures, as not yet whole. The task of division two
these existentials, and the way in which is to press upon this question of the authentic
they unfold concretely thereby disclosing wholeness of Dasein by addressing the ques-
Dasein and the world in which it finds itself. tion of the end of Dasein. The analysis of

194
Being and Time

Dasein laid out in division one will then need the question and character of its own being.
to be rewritten in light of the real meaning In an earlier lecture course Heidegger had
of the wholeness of Dasein. Before turning expressed this doubled situation of the facti-
to division two there is one further comment cal life of Dasein by saying that Das Leben
that should be made about the results of the ist diesig, es nebelt sich immer wieder ein
analysis in division one. [life is misty, it always and again shrouds
One way of characterizing the largest itself in fog]. Among the many important
result of this analysis is to say that the exis- consequences of this insight into the doubled
tential structures articulate the various ways situation of Dasein as itself a movement of
that Dasein discloses itself. This disclosure is truth/untruth, one consequence needs to be
the way Dasein is in the world. Heidegger mentioned as especially significant for the
puts the point this way: project of Being and Time. It is simply that
in exposing this structural and constitutive
Insofar as Dasein essentially is its dis- tendency of Dasein to close itself off from
closedness, and, as disclosed, it discloses the questions that define it, Heidegger gives
and discovers, it is essentially true. an account of the forgetfulness that defines
Dasein is in the truth. This statement
the question of being for us and that forms
has an ontological meaning. It does not
the opening remark of Being and Time. This
mean that Dasein is ontically always, or
even only at times, inducted into every forgetfulness is not an accident, not an error
truth, but that the disclosedness of its that could be evaded or avoided. It is rather
ownmost being belongs to its existential the forgetfulness, the concealing of its own
constitution. (GA 2, 221/BT, 212) being, that belongs to the factical life of
Dasein in the same way as that life articulates
However, saying that Dasein is in the truth an opening and unfolding of its own being.
is only one way of speaking of the way it
means to say that Dasein is its disclosed-
ness (GA 2, 133/BT, 129). Since the factical
being of Dasein, the existentials that struc- Division Two
ture its existence, include the ways in which
Dasein hides from itself and loses itself in Although these remarks on the doubled life of
the they or becomes entangled in things Daseinthe way that closure and disclosure
and everydayness, it must also be said that that are woven together in the very structure
Dasein is in untruth. This means that of Daseinare among the final comments
being closed off and covered over belong in division one, Heidegger does not explic-
to the facticity of Dasein. The full existential itly pursue this point. Rather, division two
and ontological meaning of the statement opens by asking once again the question of
Dasein is in the truth also says equiprimor- the wholeness of Dasein and by asserting
dially that Dasein is in untruth (GA 2, 222/ that the existential analytic of Dasein up
BT, 213). In short, the same structures that to now cannot lay claim to primordiality. Its
open Dasein to its world and to the ques- fore-having never included more than the
tion that it is for itselfthe question of hav- inauthentic being of Dasein, of Dasein as less
ing to beequally and at the same time than whole (GA 2, 233/BT, 223). The prob-
close Dasein off from its world and obscure lem is that as long as Dasein is, something is

195
Being and Time

always outstanding: what it can and will be voice, the call of conscience does not reach
(GA 2, 233/BT, 224). This outstanding poten- words, but speaks solely and constantly in
tial, this having to be, only ceases with the the mode of silence (GA 2, 273/BT, 263). It
death of Dasein. In its death, Dasein reaches is in and as this silent call of conscience that
its wholeness. That is why division two opens Dasein reminds itself of its ownmost, inalien-
with a discussion of The possible being-a- able possibilitydeath, as that which defines
whole of Dasein and Being-toward-death the mineness and wholeness of Dasein, and
(GA 2, 23567/BT, 22755). as that which defines the ultimate sense of
Heidegger is quick to point out that what it means that Dasein has to be, that its
strictly speaking no phenomenology of death being is futural. This is the point at which
is possible: I do not experience my own death one begins to see how the analytic of Dasein
and in experiencing the death of the other I begins to open up the question of being, the
never really experience death so much as the fundamental question of ontology.
peculiar heartbreak of my own survival. Any The presentation of the notion of con-
attestation of death will necessarily need science, of this call of Dasein from itself to
to be of a distinct character precisely because back to itself, marks a sort of summit of the
it eludes any and all direct experience. This phenomenological analysis of the existential
paradox of deaththat it is a possibility not constitution of Dasein. By means of unpack-
to be evaded, that it is impossible to grasp ing the possibility of this call of conscience,
phenomenallycan only be answered inso- Heidegger takes the next step in the project
far as the existential meaning of death, that of Being and Time, that is, he moves from
is the lived meaning of death as such a possi- the analysis of Dasein in its wholeness to
bility, is unfolded. How, in other words, does the phenomenal exposition of temporality
death announce itself in advance of its actual (GA 2, 301/BT, 289). In other words, after
appearance and what does this announce- the analysis of conscience Being and Time
ment mean for Dasein? moves to the preliminary consideration of
The most radical and penetrating announce time as the horizon shaping the question of
ment of the existential meaning of death, being. With this move begins the process that
of its reality as a possibility that cannot be is to eventually lead to division three of part
evaded, appears in what Heidegger refers to one in which Heidegger takes up the topic of
as the call of conscience. Conscience is one Time and Being. This new step begins with
of the central and most significant notions a repetition of the preliminary phenomeno-
developed in Being and Time, but it is also logical analysis of Dasein in which the exis-
one of the least understood and most misrep- tential structures exposed by that analysis
resented. Despite Heideggers clear argument are now shown to be modes of temporality.
that conscience should not be interpreted as Demonstrating that the movement of time
a moral phenomenon, the impulse toward is the ground of the being of Dasein and
such an interpretation is often not resisted. thus makes possible the question of being the
Conscience gives something to be under- asking of which defines Dasein as the being
stood, it discloses (GA 2, 269/BT, 259). It that it is, is the final step in the published
is a strange call that interrupts the flatness portion of Being and Time. To be sure, more
of everyday life and summons Dasein back themes do emerge in these final sections: for
to itself. Nonetheless, though it is a sort of instance, the movement of time is shown as

196
Being and Time

opening up the historical character of Dasein, NOTES AND REFERENCES


its relationality beyond its immediate world
1
Of course, Being and Time did not suddenly
and its present moment; likewise, Heidegger
appear ab novo and without any context or
recognizes the conception of time that forms debts that can help one understand and interpret
the real unity and ground of Dasein needs to it. It was, however, only in the past two or three
be clearly distinguished from the traditional decades that we have had access to the most sig-
(Heidegger calls it vulgar) sense of time as nificant works that can shed light on Being and
Time itself. Here I am referring to Heideggers
the linear movement of nows that succeed
own lecture courses from the years immediately
one another. The final sections of Being and prior to the publication of Being and Time.
Time are devoted to this task of contrasting Heideggers students during these years
the temporality that grounds Dasein with among them Hannah Arendt and Hans-Georg
the metaphysical conception of time that has Gadamerwere able to follow the evolution
of Heideggers thought that would culminate
shaped philosophy from Aristotles Physics
in Being and Time. Many of the key issues that
up to Hegel. would be published in a more condensed form in
It would be wrong to say that Being and that text were developed by Heidegger in lecture
Time has a clear conclusion. The final sec- courses such as Prolegomena zur Geschichte
tions are devoted to highlighting the way des Zeitbegriffs (1925) and Die Grundprobleme
der Phnomenologie (1927). In a similar
in which the insights and project of Being
fashion, later workshere one thinks above
and Time stands apart from traditional phi- all of Beitrge zur Philosophie (19368)offer
losophy. The conclusion comes in the brief insight into Heideggers own self-critique and
final section (GA 2, 4367/BT, 41315) in self-understanding of his achievement in Being
which Heidegger reminds his readers of the and Time.
2
One can argue, rightly, that several of the works
larger project that guides Being and Time
of the late 1920s and early 1930sfor instance,
and how it is that what has been achieved Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics (1929),
thus far in the first two of the six planned do represent at least sketches of those promised,
divisions still needs to be understood in that but never published, sections of Being and Time.
context of the largest question of being. To
3
That is why Heidegger says that higher than
actuality stands possibility (GA 2, 38/BT, 36).
this end, the final words of Being and Time 4
As examples of disciplines that seek this what
are more dedicated to raising questions than and that are to be distinguished from the Dasein
to offering conclusions. Almost one half of analytic, Heidegger refers to anthropology, psy-
the final section is composed of questions chology, and biology (GA 2, 4550/BT, 449).
that Heidegger reminds his reader remain
5
In this regard, Section 14 (GA 2, 5962/BT,
5962) is especially significant. In that section
open precisely as a result of the phenome-
Heidegger clearly distinguishes the forms of
nological analysis of Dasein completed thus disclosure outlined by the existentials from any
far. Bearing these questions in mind, return- form of cognition. Knowing, in all of its forms,
ing to the original plan of Being and Time is he argues a founded, not an original, way
that is laid out in the introduction but never in which the world and the self is discovered:
in knowing, Dasein gains a new perspective
completed, one is led to ask just how far
of being toward the world always already
the project of fundamental ontology that is discovered in Dasein.. . . Knowing is a mode of
developed in Being and Time can be carried Dasein which is founded in being-in-the-world
out as it promises. (GA 2, 62/BT, 62).

197
24
The Origin of the Work of Art
Gregory Schufreider

Der Ursprung des Kunstwerkes designates 1956, was then added to the revised edition
both a topic and a text. And just as there of the text that appeared in 1960. Finally,
are multiple versions of the text, there are a there is the Gesamtausgabe version, which
number of topics at issue, over and above the includes Heideggers marginal comments
question of the origin of artwork. In fact, one to the earlier editions, marking yet another
might argue that Heideggers aim in turning incarnation of the text.
his attention to the work of art in the 1930s In what follows, we will be drawing our
is to provide a new model of philosophy; account primarily from this final version,
although seeing this would require an appre- noting differences from other versions only
ciation of the precise way in which the topic when unavoidable. In this respect, there
of art is treated in a philosophical text that is are two worth mentioning from the start,
designed to initiate a poetic thinking. namely, in connection with the First Version
To complicate matters, there are at least a of the essay; for its stunning formulation that
half a dozen versions of the essay, and more truth is essentially earthy (erdhaft) is omit-
if we take into consideration the variations ted from later versions, as is its claim that only
in the transcripts of the lectures taken by art works. Given this distinctive emphasis,
students who attended them. What has come we begin with a discussion of work, before
to be designated as the First Version is the turning our attention to the Earth.
draft of a lecture that was never delivered.
The text was published (in Heidegger Studies)
in 1989, after an unauthorized version of a Originating Art
lecture that was first delivered in Freiburg
in 1935 appeared in France (in 1987). These As necessarily as the artist is the origin
differ significantly from one another as well of the work in a different way than the
as from the official version of the essay that work is the origin of the artist, so it is
was published in Holzwege in1950. That text equally certain that, in a still different
was based on the typescript of three lectures way, art is the origin of both artist and
work. (GA 5, 1/PLT, 17)
delivered in Frankfort in1936, although not
without alteration in the later publication,
including an Epilogue that was, at least in While modern thought may take it for granted
part, written later. An Addendum, written in that the artist is the origin of the work of art,

199
THE ORIGIN OF THE WORK OF ART

on Heideggers view, this cannot be true, at Pieta of Michelangelo or an inverted urinal


least not unambiguously. For the work is the signed R. Mutt.
origin of the artist, assuming that someone We mention Duchamps Fountain, which
only becomes an artist by creating a success- Heidegger does not (although it was cre-
ful work of art. The event that Heidegger ated in 1917), because it helps to raise the
calls art is not the work of a single individ- question of the origin of the work of art,
ual but must be thought collectively: in terms neither in the predictable procedure of a
of a community that is constituted histori- technical production nor through the inex-
cally in a complex dynamic between artists, plicable genius of an artistic creation, at least
works, and what he calls preservers. At the not one that operates by generating new
same time, while Heidegger undermines the beings metaphysically. Instead, what would
modern emphasis on genius, he also rejects otherwise appear as an item of gear (when
the ancient failure to distinguish art from mounted on the wall in a washroom) or
craft, such that techne refers to a set of even as an object (on display at a plumbing
productive principles through which a work showroom) presents itself as a work of art,
is created by following the rules; even if he virtually without ontical alteration, except
would agree that art is a distinctive way of in its signature presentationunless we also
coming into being (genesis). count its change of location (to a gallery)
It may appear that what we have here and inversion, which renders it dysfunctional
are two opposed models of the origin of (as gear) but self-standing (as a work of art).
artwork: a production model, in which a Similarly, when it comes to the traditional
product is produced by executing a set of art that is mimicked here, it should be clear
procedural techniques, in contrast to a that the work may appear as an object
model of creation that emphasizes the free (in aesthetic appreciation) or as an item of
imagination of an artistic genius, which gear (in interior decoration), not to men-
cannot be duplicated in its operation. tion as a product (of a creative operation)
Both, however, offer causal accountsthe or even as a commodity (in an economic
first based on Aristotles four causes, and calculation). Assuming that these ontologi-
the second by elevating what the classical cal categories designate different ways in
account had relegated to the role of an effi- which the same being can appear, the ques-
cient cause. In either case, art is thought in tion remains: what constitutes the workly
terms of metaphysical genesis: as an origin character of the work of art, if not the work
through which beings come into being in that the artist does in making it? What work,
what Heidegger would regard as their onti- in other words, does the work itself do, such
cal creation. By contrast, he would have us that, when it works, it creates an artist? And
approach art ontologically, in a phenome- under what conditions does a being appear
nological ontology that thinks of being in (in its being) as artwork, including the
terms of the different ways in which a being readymade, which (as its nickname indicates)
can appear. In that event, works of art are abandons metaphysical creation in favor of
not simply ontical creations but involve an an ontological originality that takes place
ontological determination; which is to say right before our very eyes, in the event that
that artwork designates a specific way in what would otherwise appear as an item of
which a being may appear, whether it is the gear presents itself as a work of art?

200
THE ORIGIN OF THE WORK OF ART

Unearthing a World riddle of art, which entails an appreciation


of the way in which art works both onti-
When a work is created, brought forth cally and ontologically. In that event, the task
out of this or that work-materialstone, (of philosophy), we are told, is not to solve
wood, metal, color, language, tonewe the riddle (of art) but to see it: to clarify how
say that it is made, set forth out of it. an ontical creativity may be riddled with an
(GA 5, 31/PLT, 45) ontological originality, such that the origin
(Ursprung) of art is seen to operate in rela-
In attending to the question of what makes tion to a primal leap (Ur-sprung) that is sus-
something art, we would, no doubt, have to pended in a breach between world and Earth
face the institutional determination of the that is created by the work itself.
work, and not just in the museum (as an In that case, we face a circle that may well
institution in which it may be displayedto be puzzling, given that artwork must cre-
appeal to another ontological categoryas ate its own origin: instigate a rift between
an artifact) but insofar as a community is world and Earth whose resolution renders
involved in setting the historical conditions, the design of a veritable fault line as an
including for the advent of the readymade. outline of truth in the making through the
To oversimplify, we might say that the onto- struggle of creation. If what Heidegger calls
logical dimension of the work of art will be the world is an historical structure, then the
thought in terms of what Heidegger calls the Earth is a prehistoric ground: an Ur- as well
world, as an historical structure that is cre- as an Ab-grund; which is to say that, as both
ated collectively, while the insistence on its a primal and abysmal ground, it is as likely
ontical determination will involve a relation to undermine a world as to allow one to be
to the Earth as a prehistoric base of opera- founded on it. For the ground is not a foun-
tions. This oversimplification will have to be dation but, in this case, an abysmal source on
corrected when we arrive at the most origi- which a world must be founded through the
nal thought in the essay on art, namely, of a work of art. This does not make the Earth a
rift-design that is created through a con- resource (which is another way in which it
flict that is yet to be defined. can appear, ontologically speaking, under the
If we have appealed to the readymade, it is auspices of modern technology), any more
not to suggest that Heidegger overlooks the than the work is to be thought of as an object
ontical aspect of artwork, given his insistence or an item of gear, let alone as a product or
on its relation to the Earth as the source of a commodity. Instead, a world must be created
concrete creation. Even Duchamps Fountain and supported through work that has accom-
presents itself with a certain ontical origi- modated itself to both world and Earth: is set
nality, not in a material creation but in its between world and Earth or, to be precise,
presentation as an anomaly that isolates the sets up (aufstellen) a world by setting forth
ontological dimension of the work, highlight- (herstellen) the Earth through a settlement
ing the question of what makes something of their inherent strife. In so doing, the work
art. The answer, for Heidegger, is not that art is set back (zurckstellen) on an Earth that
is whatever artists say it is. On the contrary, secures (feststellen) a world, however tenu-
his claim is that the successful work must ously, given the struggle through which it
be thought in terms of what he dubs as the originates.

201
THE ORIGIN OF THE WORK OF ART

While it may to be obvious that, in art, an that maintains its self-enclosure in a sublime
earth-material is worked into an historical seclusion. This is not a matter of isolation
structure, in Heidegger the result cannot be but of an integrity that keeps to itself in an
thought in terms of a static (let alone an eter- indifference that must be thought in rela-
nal) form that dominates its matter, but in tion to a duality that is complicated by its
the configuration (Gestalt) of a framework simplicity, namely, thatworld and Earth are
(Gestell) that is clearly designated as a gath- not two different things. For while there is
ering of opposition in the linguistic operation an inherent asymmetry in their relation inso-
of the above-mentioned set of stellens. To far as the Earth is indifferent to a world that
appreciate the dynamic nature of the resolu- depends upon it, there is a far more essential
tion of the conflict between world and Earth, in-difference between them insofar as their
we would have to add another piece to the difference is not ontical but ontological. The
puzzle by insisting that, for Heidegger, what Earth is not just indifferent to the world but
is distinctive about such work is that, in set- in-different from it insofar as the world is
ting up a world, the Earth is revealed as a the Earth disclosed historically. In that event,
self-concealing source: set forth in its con- the ontological (in)difference between world
cealment as an abysmal support that must and Earth is not just instigated by and secured
be unearthed in a dual sense. Not only through but exhibited in the work of art as it
must the Earth be disclosed in a world, displays its origin in its presentation.
but if it is to be exposed in the integrity of In so doing, what art shows is that a world
its self-determination, it must be worked is not imposed upon beings (as the paradigm
against itself: be literally un-earthed as of the object may suggest) but unearthed in
the Earth in a world that does not violate its their midst through the creation (and instal-
self-concealment. Instead, in the respect that lation) of specific beings, namely, works
is shown for it in its revelation, the Earth of art, that literally make a world out of the
appears as the self-contained basis for a Earth. If we take art as our model, it is clear
world to which it is indifferently opposed. that a world happens as a concrete site for
If the world of a people directs us to an human habitation when the Earth appears
historical dimension of phenomena, while within the confines of an historical struc-
the Earth marks the facticity of a prehis- ture. Moreover, if these works are to provide
toric givenness, then artwork makes it clear a foundation for the world, then they must
that a world is not simply projected on but be designed in and as a configuration of the
protected by the Earth insofar as it is cre- conflict, such that, in the unearthing of a
ated out of it. If the Earth is to be rendered world through artwork, it becomes apparent
suitable for historical habitation, it must be that truth is essentially earthy.
un-earthed, however ambiguously, even as a
world is unearthed on the basis of it insofar
as the configuration of the work is worked
out in a conflict that stems from a profound Designing a Rift
indifference. While the Earth is disclosed in
a world that must work with and against Truth establishes itself as a strife within
its inclination for concealment, the world a being that is to be brought forth only
is stabilized by being set back on an Earth in such a way that the conflict opens up

202
THE ORIGIN OF THE WORK OF ART

in this being, that is, this being is itself the clash of their alignment. This dynamic
brought into the rift-design. (GA 5, 51/ rift is thought linguistically in terms of a
PLT, 63) complex design: in relation to the sketch
or layout (Auf-ri) of a ground plan or out-
If what Heidegger once referred to as our line (Grund-ri), in this case, taken liter-
being-in-the-world must now be thought ally as a ripping open of the ground. Such
in relation to a being-on-the-Earth, then this a rift-design, in other words, is rendered
is to insist that the world, as a meaningful in a rent that rips through (Durch-ri) the
whole, is founded on a massive insignificance ground, breaking it open in such a way that
that both precedes and exceeds wherever the breach defines the contour (Um-ri) of
sense can be made of human existence. In a concrete design. It is as if the ground must
that event, we must admit that all historical be ground down, if it is to take shape in a
significance is instituted through and submit- structure that is created as the configuration
ted to a formation that is faulty, if we may of a conflict between world and Earth that is
take the term geologically: is full of faults, etched into the work insofar as the work has
not as defects or mistakes but as cracks or been (sk)etched out of it. In this respect, the
breaks in the foundation. In this respect, it work of art is torn between the two, given its
is the self-concealing operation of the Earth commitment to let the self-concealing Earth
that keeps a world open: interrupts our incli- appear in a world that is clearly grounded
nation for totalization in an enclosure of on it.
sense as a framework of significance. Not If artwork is to found a world on the
only does the Earth inevitably disrupt our Earth, it must submit to both by creating a
meaning, given its indifference, but a sublime concrete relation between them: instigate a
insignificance may be glimpsed in the beauty strife that is defined by the configuration of
of the breach that is created by works of art in a rift-design in a dynamic event of uncon-
the breakdowns as well as the breakthroughs cealment. Not only does the Earth appear
that constitute a continuous history of cre- in the unearthing of a world, but the work
ative struggle. For the Earth remains intact presents itself in its own originality: appears
in its integrity throughout the fluctuations in as an unprecedented revelation of the rela-
world-history, which is to say that there is tion between world and Earth, and in an
only one Earth (which is why we capitalize origination that is apparent in the appear-
it as a proper name) but many worlds. ance of the work of art. In this respect, art
While it should come as no surprise if the involves an exhibition of truth in the beauty
key term that unlocks the structure of the of the breach, assuming that what we see
work of art has geological overtones, what on display in the work is the creation of an
is referred to as the rift (Ri) is designed historic opening between world and Earth: a
to describe the structure of the strife between time-space, to be exact, that arranges for the
world and Earth as a breach in which each disclosure, not just of the work (as an onti-
is related to the other in the concrete deter- cal creation) but of all beings in the historical
mination of a dynamic configuration. The dimension of their appearance, thanks to the
crack or split between world and Earth cre- installation of art in their midst. This is to
ates a figurative fault line, which defines an insist that art is in a position to set a standard
opening between them that is configured in for unconcealment, ontologically speaking:

203
THE ORIGIN OF THE WORK OF ART

to create a measure of being that the work time in a clearing that is designed to keep the
brings with it in its own creation insofar as conflict between world and Earth happening
its appearance happens through a primal by refining it in a dynamic design.
conflict that art is designed keep open, as if This refinement of the rift, as both a clari-
in the riptide of an historical momentum that fication and a condensation of conflict, takes
does not subside in the meeting of its oppos- place in the beauty of a concrete configu-
ing currents. On the contrary, art accelerates ration that must be thought of not only as
history, setting its pace by intensifying the an open structure but as a structured open-
flow of time through the operation of a free ness. In structuring the strife, the work of
creation that takes place spatially as well as art shows a certain restraint that displays
temporally. the contention of the clearing in such a way
as to keep its originality in play, working to
disclose the struggle for beings in their his-
torical being. Needless to say, the creation
A Moving Beauty of what we might think of as a true beauty,
given its relation to unconcealment, connects
History is the transporting of a people a world to the Earth more directly than a tra-
into its appointed task as entrance into ditional sense of truth. In the end, it is the
that peoples endowment. (GA 5, 65/ earthy dimension of truth that links it to
PLT, 77) the beauty of the work of art insofar as onto-
logical truth must be installed (einrichten)
If art involves an ontological determina- or executed (verrichten) ontically in order to
tion, then this is to insist that a time-space create a concrete opening for an historical
of unconcealment is not only opened up in existence. The disclosure of a free time-space
the conflict between world and Earth but must be arranged (richten) with an exactness
that what Heidegger designates as the truth (Richtigkeit) that is not a matter of correct-
of being happens historically in ontical ness, or even of a mere precision, but of a
creations that are stationed in the midst of literal accuracy in setting the directions from
beings to set a standard for their appearance which a community may take its orientation
as phenomena. In facing what he dubs as the (Richtung), in the case of art, through the
clearing (Lichtung), in the case in point, erecting (errichten) of concrete sites of truth
as an historical opening that takes place (Wahrheit) whose breakthroughs must be
through creative work, we come to the preserved (verwahren) collectively in order to
heart of Heideggers thinking, and not only sustain the momentum of a peoples history.
about the origin of art. On the contrary, it is Such a moving beauty will itself be thought
his thought about the clearing of a time-space in four movements, once again expressed in
for the appearance of phenomena that gives terms of a root that is pulled in different
to art a specifically Heideggerian look. As an directions. This time the term rcken will
historic event, what he calls the open is rid- be deployed to define a linguistic complex
dled with openingswhich is what a work that is designed to track an elusive beauty
of art is, and not only insofar as great in its dynamic operation. Through entrance-
art creates a breach in history, but in that ment (bercken), engagement (einrcken),
the work generates a free and open space and transport (entrcken), and derangement

204
THE ORIGIN OF THE WORK OF ART

(verrcken), the work of art attracts an audi- displays the Earth in its entry into unconceal-
ence that is drawn to it thanks to a capti- ment, assuming that we agree not only with
vation that engages them in an historical Heideggers view of Cezannes many render-
movement insofar as they are transported to ings of Mont Sainte-Victoire, but appreciate
another world, as old standards are struck that they are created out of paint.
down and new ones are erected, which only
take effect if preservers are willing to submit
to them: are committed to protect the truth
that is happening through the work as a Poetic Thinking
standard-setting event of unconcealment. In
submitting to an ontological derangement, Does the clearing happen through lan-
not as the madness of the insane but in the guage or does this appropriative event of
ecstatic opening that is involved in resetting clearing first grant articulation and renun-
the range of the horizons of world-history, ciation and so language? Language and
the audience participates in the beauty of body (speech and writing). (GA 5, 62)
art, whose origin, as we have insisted from
the start, must be thought of as a collective Given the word-play that we have seen on
creation. display, it should come as no surprise that a
In Heideggers view, art takes part in the text on the origin of art would inevitably lead
creation of a truth that is coming true histori- to the thought of linguistic work in its own
cally, in work that sets the standards for the originality as well as to a (re)consideration
appearance of phenomena through its beauty. of philosophy as a work of the word in its
For beauty happens when ontological truth kinship with poetry. This is not a matter of
appears ontically: in its installation through art yielding to philosophy, as in Hegel, and
the origination of specific beings that oper- certainly not of poetry giving way to prose.
ate to set a standard of being in their own On the contrary, the point, we would insist,
appearance. Such a measure-setting event, in is to recreate philosophy in the face of art;
the case of art, involves the self-evidence of its even if Heidegger will do so by insisting upon
own creation, in which a being appears to set the priority of a poetic thinking.
the standard for its own appearance, not to While we cannot deny that the overall
have one imposed upon it, and least of all by structure of The Origin of the Work of Art
us insofar as we submit to it. Consequently, involves the plotting of what would appear
Heidegger will claim, following Hlderlin, to be a strategy of betrayal in its ultimate
that beauty is the most apparent appear- commitment to poetry, the tactics of the text
ance, as an appearance in which appear- would suggest otherwise. Admittedly, the
ance itself becomes apparent and, as such, movement of thinking begins by appealing
strikes us with an amazement that is aston- to a model drawn from the plastic arts, in
ishing, if not awe-inspiring. In appreciating which the appearance of the Earth is evident,
the unprecedented presence of the work of only to end by rendering them secondary to
art in its originality, we are struck by the fact poetry, based on Heideggers claims about
that it is at alland not in the debilitation the priority of languagewhich hardly
of anxiety but in the elation of a beauty that seems to qualify as an earth-material, even
moves mountains into history insofar as it though he includes it in the list, along with

205
THE ORIGIN OF THE WORK OF ART

stone and paint. And while he also includes as a plastic operation. Here we would have
a disclaimer, distinguishing poetry proper to appreciate the text not only in its con-
from the poetic nature of all art, his insist- figuration of opposing roots (stellen, reissen,
ence on the centrality of linguistic creativity richten, rcken) but in its rendering of each
remains problematic. through a complex prefixing that operates
It would appear, however, that sometime through hyphenation: by inserting a rift in
after 1960 Heidegger had second-thoughts, the word as a plastic act designed to break it
questioning the priority that he had attrib- open, and not just in the exposure of a root
uted to language in the determination of the meaning but in a reconfiguration of the sight
clearing, or at least wondering what it means and sound of language insofar as a moment
to say that the other arts operate in an open- of silence has been inserted into the word
ing that has already happened unnoticed in through its punctuation. In so doing, words
language. And without addressing this in presents themselves with an unprecedented
detail, we would insist that the tactics of the significance, such that we literally sense
text already suggest a different approach: not language as an original event, breaking the
an eclipsing of the plastic by the poetic arts silence through which meaning comes into
but the presentation of a linguistic creation being.

206
25
Introduction to Metaphysics
Gregory Fried

Since its publication in 1953, Introduction Dasein in Being and Time and the efforts in
to Metaphysics has been one of Martin Contributions to Philosophy (19368) and
Heideggers most widely read works, second later works to find language for a new kind
perhaps only to Being and Time (1927). It was of thinking. In this period Heidegger first
the first book by Heidegger to be translated begins exploring the poet Hlderlin, and we
into English, in 1959, before even Being and find here the same incipient attempt to engen-
Time (1962). Heidegger himself signaled the der a poetizing thinking (GA 40, 153/IM,
books importance in his Authors Preface to 154) that would break past the nihilism of
the seventh edition of Being and Time: For traditional metaphysics.
the elucidation of this question [of Being] the
reader may refer to my Einfhrung in die
Metaphysik, which is appearing simultane-
ously with this reprinting (SZ, viii/BTRM, Introducing Metaphysics
17). Based on lectures delivered in 1935, at
the height of Heideggers ardent embrace of The first obstacle for a reader new to
National Socialism, it has also been one of Heidegger is the deceptively ordinary title,
his most controversial works, with debates Introduction to Metaphysics. This makes
breaking out from its first appearance in it sounds like a conventional primer on a
1953.1 We will return to the vexed question shop-worn field in academic philosophy. At
of Heideggers politics, but it is also worth first, Heidegger seems close to the traditional
pointing out what has made this book attrac- understanding of metaphysics when he begins
tive to readers: its accessibility, at least com- his course by asking, Why are there beings
pared to some of Heideggers more obscure at all rather than nothing? This certainly
works; the sweep of its themes, ranging across does not seem like a question that a science
2,500 years of Western philosophy; its pow- like physics could answer. It reaches all the
erful interpretation of classic works of litera- way back, then, to what Aristotle would have
ture, most prominently, the Ode to Man called first philosophy, which he treated in a
in Sophocles Antigone. Developmentally, body of works later referred to as his meta
Introduction to Metaphysics occupies a tran- ta phusika, those texts that come after the
sitional position in Heideggers path, between physics and therefore inquire beyond the
the fundamental ontology and the analytic of physical (see GA 36/37, 201/BAT, 1719).

207
INTRODUCTION TO METAPHYSICS

The most pressing metaphysical question IM, 19). But then what is Being? That is the
asks why something, anything, should go to question, and one Heidegger is in no hurry
the bother of existing at all. As Heidegger to answer.
says, this metaphysical question par excel- Heidegger quite emphatically means his
lence is not allowed to dwell on this or that introduction to metaphysics in a literal
domain of natureinanimate bodies, plants, sense as a leading-in of his listeners into what
animalsbut must go on beyond ta physica is at stake in how the history of metaphysics
(GA 40, 19/IM, 18). The question is not sim- has obscured the question of Being:
ply asking about what happens to be the sub-
stance and structure of this or that being or Introduction [Einfhrung] to meta-
even of reality in general, but beyond this, physics accordingly means: leading
why reality should have this substance and into [Hineinfhrung] the asking of
structure in the first place, what its most the fundamental question. . . . Leading
fundamental and essential cause is. Hence [Fhrung] is a questioning going-ahead,
Heidegger writes: The question we have a questioning-ahead. This is a leadership
identified as first in rankWhy are there that essentially has no following. (GA
beings at all instead of nothing?is thus 40, 22/IM, 21)
the fundamental question of metaphys-
ics. Metaphysics stands as the name for the Heidegger seeks to awaken the question
center and core that determines all philoso- of Being by showing how metaphysics has
phy (GA 40, 1920/IM, 19). resulted in a dead end in the two millennia
The novice reader might well misunder- after Plato. At the end of this long history of
stand Heidegger to mean that he agrees that metaphysics, Nietzsche most prominently,
metaphysics should be central to philosophy. but the West more broadly, has repudiated
This would be a fatal mistake. Heidegger Being as something no longer worth asking
often spells out at great length a position he about: The word Being is then finally just
will ultimately bring to a dead end and declare an empty word. It means nothing actual, tan-
inadequate, even if he might have seemed gible, real. Its meaning is an unreal vapor
sympathetic to it along the way. Heidegger (GA 40, 39/IM, 38). But precisely this expe-
emphatically distinguishes between the onto- rience of Being as an empty word, a mere
logical question about Being as such and the vapor, is what Heidegger wants to ques-
metaphysical question about beings (GA tion, and from there to reawaken a renewed
40, 20/IM, 19). By asking exclusively about understanding of Being, yet without simply
beings, their origin, and substance, Heidegger slipping back into metaphysics.
holds that metaphysics forgets the question It cannot be an accident for a thinker so
of Being by treating it as another version of careful about language to speak so deliber-
the question of beings. But as Heidegger has ately of Fhrung in 1935. Here we have an
argued in Being and Time (SZ, 4/BTMR, 23), example of Heidegger attempting to appro-
there is a difference between Being (Sein) priate Nazi terminology for his own use and
and beings (das Seiende): Being is not itself a to construe leadership not as a blind follow-
being, some metaphysical ground for every- ing but as an incitement to ones own appro-
thing that is, even if the metaphysical tradi- priation of what is essential. We see this
tion interprets Being in this way (GA 40, 20/ when Heidegger rejects Nietzsche and asks,

208
INTRODUCTION TO METAPHYSICS

Is Being a mere word and its meaning a because they are identical but because each
vapor, or is it the spiritual fate of the West? in its way understands the world metaphysi-
(GA 40, 40/IM, 40) For Heidegger, this ques- cally. Both have forgotten the question of
tion is a question about our people, the Being. So he proclaims, To ask: how does it
Germans: stand with Being?this means nothing less
than to repeat and retrieve the inception of
We lie in the pincers. Our people, as our historical-spiritual Dasein, in order to
standing in the center, suffers the most transform it into the other inception (GA
intense pressureour people, the people 40, 42/IM, 41).
richest in neighbors and hence the most
It would be hard to exaggerate the ambi-
endangered people, and for all that, the
tion couched in this declaration. Heidegger
metaphysical people. We are sure of this
vocation; but this people will gain a fate takes the reawakening of the question of
from its vocation only when it creates in Being as a decisive event in the spiritual fate
itself a resonance, a possibility of reso- of the West, because how we understand
nance for this vocation, and grasps its what it means to be is the departure for the
tradition creatively. (GA 40, 41/IM, 41) understanding of our entire existence. By
inception (Anfang), Heidegger means not
It seems strange that Heidegger calls the a mere chronological beginning point, but
Germans the metaphysical people, given his rather that which gives an historical epoch its
attack on metaphysics, but this must be heard trajectory. The inception to be reanimated, in
in the overall spirit of the lecture course: that this moment of national revolution, is the
confronting the historical meaning of meta- ancient Greek one, but not through rank
physics is an inescapable task, that doing this imitation; Heideggers notion of repetitive
is the vocation of the Germans as part of the retrieval (Wieder-holung) does not mean
restoration of the question of Being. This is duplicating facts or institutions; it means
why Heidegger makes one of the most star- reawakening lost and neglected possibilities
tling pronouncements in this course: of Being inherent to that first, ancient incep-
tionthe one before the incipient nihilism
This Europe, in its unholy blindness of Platos idealism took holdand making
always on the point of cutting its own it a fertile ground for bringing on this other
throat, lies today in the great pin- inception, a new departure for the West, led
cers between Russia on the one side
by Germany.
and America on the other. Russia and
America, seen metaphysically, are both
the same: the same hopeless frenzy of
unchained technology and of the root-
less organization of the average man. Retrieving the Greeks
(GA 40, 401/IM, 40)
Chapter 2, On the Grammar and Etymology
For Heidegger, Germany lies in the pincers of the Word Being, engages in a
because the metaphysical understanding of Heideggerian destruction of the history
the world underlies nations and political sys- of Western grammar in order to show how
tems as diverse as Russias communism and the meaning of Being, as a decisive ques-
Americas liberalism; they are the same not tion, has been obscured by developments in

209
INTRODUCTION TO METAPHYSICS

language and schools of grammar. Without IM, 76). He understands this meaning even
going into the technical details,2 Heideggers more primordially as coming-to-presence
point here is that the transition from the (An-wesen), or presencing (GA 40, 656/IM,
Greek to the Latin grammarians distorted 64), which does not mean Being is an object
the sense of what a verb is, so that what eternally present to us, but rather that Being
we now call the infinitive, from the Latin unfolds a world of meaning in which beings
modus infinitivus, is taken to be the most come in and go out of presence for us. To use
abstract, least meaningful, and emptiest language not too alien to Heidegger, what is
form of the verb (GA 40, 74/IM, 73). On at issue in the question of Being is the tem-
this already attenuated basis of the infini- poral whiling of meaning that makes a his-
tive, Indo-European languages have formed torical world accessible.
verbal substantives, such as das Sein from Heidegger now introduces one of the
sein. While English constructs substantives Presocratic fragments that is of the great-
from the gerund rather than from the infini- est significance for him in this period, frag-
tive, the result, such as Being, is then an ment 53 of Heraclitus about war (polemos),
even further intensification of this general- which he renders as follow: Confrontation
ity. Furthermore, this making a substan- is indeed for all (that comes to presence) the
tive, a noun, out of the verb, leads to the sire (who lets emerge), but (also) for all the
most baleful distortion of all for Heidegger, preserver that holds sway. For it lets some
namely, the confusion of Being with beings: appear as gods, others as human beings,
some it produces (sets forth) as slaves, but
The substantive das Sein [Being] implies others as the free (GA 40, 66/IM, 65).3
that what is so named, itself is. Being Polemos as struggle (Kampf) or confron-
now itself becomes something that is, tation (Auseinandersetzung) is the process
whereas obviously only beings are, and through which beings become meaningful
it is not the case that Being also is. (GA to us, and so through which Being itself is
40, 73/IM, 73) manifested, by allowing things to take on
clear boundaries as discernible, separate
The way to understand the question of entities, each of which can take on a name
Being is to ask what it means to be, not what in language: Confrontation does not divide
makes up the attributes of some noun-like, unity, much less destroy it. It builds unity; it
big-B Being, a being like all other beings is the gathering (logos). Polemos and logos
except that it somehow causes or explains are the same (ibid.). Language is not a
all the rest of them. What it means to be consequence of experience or a secondary
is verbal, or temporal, and for this reason feature of human understanding; language
finite, historical, and situated in a context. assembles the world as it divides it up into
This is why, when Heidegger looks at the intelligible parts that can come into presence
conglomeration of Indo-European roots that for us (GA 40, 93/IM, 912). Where strug-
make up the morphology of the verb to be gle ceases, beings indeed do not disappear,
(e.g. I am, you are, it is, they were, I have but world turns away (GA 40, 67/IM, 65):
been, etc.), he discerns the unifying meaning a meaningful world requires the struggle
of living, emerging, abiding (GA 40, 767/ over the interpretation of what things are.

210
INTRODUCTION TO METAPHYSICS

Breaking Restrictions to, mere seeming. At the same time,


Being as idea was elevated to a supersen-
This emphasis on language as the heart sory realm. The chasm, khorismos, was
of a hermeneutical struggle helps explain torn open between the merely apparent
beings here below and the real Being
why Heidegger turns to Greek poetry and
somewhere up there. Christian doctrine
the Presocratics in this work. Here we see
then established itself in this chasm,
Heidegger attempting to develop a new while at the same time reinterpreting
vocabulary to articulate the recovered ques- the Below as the created and the Above
tion of Being. Chapter 4, The Restriction of as the Creator, and with weapons thus
Being, encompasses the remaining and larg- reforged, it set itself against antiquity
est portion of the book. Heidegger examines [as paganism] and distorted it. And so
four ways in which Western thought has Nietzsche is right to say that Christianity
sought to delimit Being: Being and becom- is Platonism for the people. (GA 40, 113/
ing, Being and seeming, Being and think- IM, 111; Heideggers brackets)
ing, and Being and the ought. The key is
that Heidegger is attempting to deconstruct It is against this nihilistic metaphysics inher-
and reappropriate these formulaic opposi- ited from Plato that Heidegger seeks a revo-
tions so that they no longer serve as restric- lutionary retrieval of the possibilities covered
tions of Being (GA 40, 1002/IM, 98100). over in the pre-Socratic origins.
For example, in a conventional reading of Heidegger devotes the most attention to
Parmenides we are used to thinking of Being Being and thinking. He starts with the mod-
as perdurance of the constant, as opposed ern understanding of thinking that represents
to the Heraclitean panta rhei (everything Being as an object (GA 40, 124/IM, 123). But
flows) of becoming (GA 40, 104/IM, 102), if thinking represents Being in its reality, then
but Heidegger calls this conventional oppo- is not logic, the science of thinking, what
sition into question. Similarly, we are used we are after here (GA 40, 128/IM, 126)? But
to thinking of Being as opposed to seeming, Heidegger rejects logic as the final arbiter for
the genuine versus the ungenuine (GA 40, thinking and the representation of reality,
1056/IM, 103). But Heidegger insists that because Being as unconcealment . . . is pre-
Being essentially unfolds as appearing cisely what was lost due to logic (GA 40,
(GA 40, 108/IM, 107). He argues that Being 129/IM, 127). Logic assumes that the asser-
unfolds as what manifests itself, as what tion is the locus of truth, but Heidegger holds
appears, as the phenomenon that emerges that truth as altheia, as unconcealment,
into the truth as unconcealment (altheia) must transpire prior to any assertions and
(GA 40, 109/IM, 107). Truth as correctness representations we make. Hence Heideggers
is derivative to truth as appearing: only if focus on logos in Greek not as language,
beings are manifest to us as somehow mean- discourse, or reason, but as something more
ingful can we then determine their reality. primordial than all of these: gathering (GA
But the history of the West has subsequently 40, 132/IM, 131). Drawing on the fragments
condemned seeming as mere seeming: of Heraclitus, Heidegger argues that Logos
is constant gathering, the gatheredness of
Only with the sophists and Plato was beings that stands in itself, that is, Being
seeming explained as, and thus reduced (GA 40, 139/IM, 138). Given that polemos

211
INTRODUCTION TO METAPHYSICS

and logos are the same, this means that the deinon has two faces: the overwhelming sway
world as we think it is a world assembled in a of Being as dik, the justice that constantly
meaningful way, with differentiations giving threatens to submerge us, and the violence of
things the intelligibility that can be articu- the creators, who strive to make something
lated in words and everyday discourseand that will endure through their techn (GA 40,
ultimately in logical assertions. 169/IM, 171). Being requires the violence of
Now Heidegger turns to Parmenides to these creative figures so that it may have a site
address what thinking itself means, other than in which to appear. This is Beings polemical
the rules of logic that allows us, as subject, to necessity (GA 40, 1712/IM, 1734); other-
make accurate sense of Being as an external wise, the world sinks into the self-evident,
object (GA 40, 144/IM, 144). Fragment 5 of and all meaning gets taken for granted.
Parmenides reads to gar auto noein estin te Therefore the violencedoer knows no kind-
kai einai, conventionally rendered but think- ness and conciliation (in the ordinary sense),
ing and Being are the same (GA 40, 145/ no appeasement and mollification by success
IM, 145). Noein, Heidegger insists, must be or prestige and by their confirmation (GA
understood as apprehension, the way we take 40, 172/IM, 174)again we see Heideggers
in the gathered meaning of the world (GA rejection of anything resembling Christian
40, 1467/IM, 1467). Heidegger asserts that norms or secular moralism.
Parmenides has been so obscured by the his- Heideggers claim now is that the belong-
tory that has made him seem self-evident that ingtogether of noein (apprehension) and
it would help to take a detour through the einai (Being), which is said in the saying of
Ode to Man choral passage in Sophocles Parmenides, is nothing but this reciprocal
Antigone (GA 40, 1535/IM, 1546). The relation of dik and techn (GA 40, 174/
passage begins Manifold is the uncanny, IM, 176). It cannot be exaggerated how far
yet nothing/uncannier than manbestirs itself removed Heideggers sense of justice (dik)
. . . ( GA 40, 155/IM, 156). The key is the is from a moraljuridical one; he means
Greek to deinon, the uncanny, the terrible; it in a radically ontological sense as how
human beings are the uncanniest, the most Being gives the world its fit, its sense of an
terrible, because as those who do violence, articulated, structured whole that neverthe-
they overstep the limits of the homely, pre- less always threatens to exceed us and leave
cisely in the direction of the uncanny in the us destitute and at a loss for understanding.
sense of the overwhelming (GA 40, 160/ As such, dik beckons human creative techn
IM, 161). Only those whose daring (tolma; but also suspends these efforts over disas-
GA 40, 170/IM 172) undertakes the risk of ter as the deepest and broadest Yes to the
this uncanny violence rise high in historical overwhelming (GA 40, 172/IM, 174), for
Being as creators, as doers (GA 40, 162/IM, our works can never get out past Being and
163). Against what Heidegger calls the over- produce an everlasting dispensation that will
whelming sway of Being itself, its capacity bring the becoming of Being to an end. And
to unseat all human endeavors with mortal- so: apprehension, in its belonging-together
ity and finitude, the creators oppose the vio- with Being (dik), is such that it uses violence,
lence of their techn, their skillful knowing, and as doing violence is an urgency, and as an
in poetry, in statecraft, or in thought (GA 40/ urgency is undergone only in the necessity of
IM, 169, 168; also GA 40, 66/IM, 65). The a struggle [in the sense of polemos and eris]

212
INTRODUCTION TO METAPHYSICS

(GA 40, 176/IM, 178; Heideggers brackets). this is where Heidegger makes his infamous
If thinking is apprehension, in this sense of claim, when, condemning the theories of hack
engaging the meaning of Being in a creative Nazi Party intellectuals, he writes that, what
polemos, an interpretive confrontation over is peddled about nowadays as the philosophy
the constitution of the world, then Being and of National Socialism, but which has not the
thinking belong together in a manner prior least to do with the inner truth and great-
to logic or to representational thinking. But ness of this movement [namely, the encoun-
through Plato emerged a form of thinking ter between global technology and modern
that reduces apprehension to the apprehen- humanity] is fishing in these troubled waters
sion of an idea (GA 40, 18990/IM, 192), of values and totalities (GA 40, 208/IM,
and so the inception with Parmenides and 213; Heideggers brackets). At this point,
Heraclitus collapses: Consequently, what the reader must decide how far to go with
really is, is what always is, aei on. What is Heidegger in this Introduction: Is the ques-
continuously coming to presence is what tion of Being more than an empty word-play,
we must go back to, in advance, in all com- and if it is, does it really imply the intellectual
prehending and producing of anything: the and political deconstruction of the West that
model, the idea (GA 40, 201/IM, 206). Logic Heidegger demands? Or does the Western
and representational thinking are grounded tradition retain resources that exceed
upon an interpretation of Being as what is Heideggers apocalyptic confrontation?
always in the supersensory otherworld.
We know the final opposition, Being
and the ought, well enough: Being, what
NOTES AND REFERENCES
is, may well be opposed to what ought to
be. Heidegger again sees the root of this in 1
See Herbert Marcuse and Martin Heidegger,
Platos ideas: As Being itself becomes fixed An Exchange of Letters and Jrgen
in its character as idea, it also tends to make Habermas, Martin Heidegger: On the
up for the ensuing degradation of Being. But Publication of the Letters of 1935, in ed.
by now, this can occur only by setting some- Richard Wolin, The Heidegger Controversy
(Cambridge: MIT Press, 1993).
thing above Being that Being never yet is, but 2
See Gregory Fried, Whats in a Word?
always ought to be (GA 40, 206/IM, 211). Heideggers Grammar and Etymology of
Heidegger deems this a nihilism that mani- Being, in ed. R. Polt and G. Fried, A
fests the oblivion of Being (GA 40, 21112/ Companion to Heideggers Introduction to
IM, 217), for it has laid the foundation for Metaphysics (New Haven: Yale University
Press, 2001).
value-thinking: values become the ground for 3
For more on this theme, see Gregory Fried,
the ought as what negate Being and set some- Heideggers Polemos: From Being to Politics
thing up in its stead as what ought to be. And (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2000).

213
26
CONTRIBUTIONS TO PHILOSOPHY
Peter Trawny

When in 1989 the Contributions to Philosophy transformed his ways of thinking into dif-
(From Enowning) was published, the aca- ferent ways of writing, then this decision
demic community was surprised by a presents a philosophical problem. What
manuscript, a text, which was immediately Heideggers texts distinguished so uniquely
compared and connected with Being and can be characterized as the scriptuality
Time. Scholars spoke of a first and a sec- (Schriftlichkeit) of his philosophy. This char-
ond master-piece,1 although in the history acterization is of course in itself problematic,
of philosophy there is hardly another phi- because it suggests that there is a form for
losopher who has written texts as different the thinking representing itself, that is, the
as these two books. Indeed the texts are not writing, and the content, that is, the think-
connected, except of course by the fact that ing itself. This difference is based on the idea
Heidegger in the Contributions refers back that everything can be said in different ways.
to Being and Time and claims a dependency Following this idea we would fall into the
on the fundament of the thing itself. crevasses of the metaphysical differentiation
The diversity of Heideggers texts exceeds between form and matter.
the exemplar in the comparison of the But in the Letter on Humanism Heidegger
Contributions with Being and Time. Before speaks of the now rare handicraft of writ-
the lecture courses, articles, and public lec- ing (GA 9, 174/PA, 262). This expression of
tures Heidegger had earlier written poems, course could refer only to handwriting, that
and later intense meditations, which he is, to the fact that Heidegger wrote every-
himself called What has been Thought thing with a pen. This does not need to be
(Gedachtes). He wrote dialogues and a wrong. But it is possible that the philosopher
three-way conversation, not to mention intends something else: The handicraft of
the very different correspondences with fam- writing is a knowledge, an intimacy with
ily members, friends, colleagues, and lovers. the different ways of writing. Thus the writ-
The Contributions are internally related to ing itself has importance and meaning. And
other being-historical manuscripts such as the scriptularity of Heideggers philosophy
Mindfulness and The History of Be-ing, etc. then would be the significance of writing,
Such a plurality of ways of writing cannot and writings for and in this philosophy.
be accidental for a philosopher. It must have The scriptularity of this philosophy would
a meaning. If it is the case that Heidegger have its own extension and abundance, its

215
CONTRIBUTIONS TO PHILOSOPHY

austereness and immense openness. From pages of the text. The title Contributions to
here on a new access to this philosophy Philosophy gives the impression, that they
would be possible. are concerned with the promotion of science.
In the Contributions Heidegger sublated But this is only the appearance. For philoso-
the difference of form and matter. In his own phy cannot appear in public in any other way,
words the Contributions are no work of since all fundamental words have been used
the style heretofore (CP1, 3). The concept of up and the genuine relation to the word has
style as stilus stems from the manual way been destroyed (3). In other words: one who
of writing. Style is therefore a way to write. still wants to address a philosophical text to
Where the concept actually adheres to the dif- the public sphere has unavoidably to use triv-
ference of form and matter (of medium and ial titles. For the public sphere is dominated
informationa banal difference), Heidegger by a discourse, which has lost the genuine
uses it to overcome this difference. A letter relation to the word.
to Ernst Jnger reads: The question of style In contrast the proper heading of the
is in the same time a secret of workshop and book is From Enowning. It does not inform
profession (Berufung). It cannot be discussed what is reported by the text, but rather
in public. But it stays the most necessary the following is what is at stake: [. . .] a
and distressful for us. Style belongs to the thinking-saying which is en-owned by enown-
thing itself. Style is not the thing itself, but ing and belongs to be-ing and to be-ings
it belongs to it. This means that the thing word. The thinking of the Contributions is
primarily becomes the thing itself, because a correspondence or response to this, that
the style renders it in this way. which Heidegger calls the enowning. If
The style plays not a minor role in the this thinking was able to inscribe itself in this
Contributions. Heidegger speaks of the text, it is assigned to the enowning itself.
will and the style of thinking (CP1, 15), Only because the enowning en-owns, that
which as style of inceptual thinking (24) is, because it transfers thinking to a respon-
in reservedness is elucidated. Considered sive relation to itself (to enowning), could
in this way the style is distanced from the the Contributions emerge.
form/matter-difference. The style, with and With the distinction between a public title
in which the Contributions are written, is and a proper heading the Contributions
basically the way, inceptual thinking is immediately state a difference that deter-
realizing itself. This style is given only in mines the whole work and its thinking. This
this thinking and this thinking only in this difference for Heidegger consists of that
style. Thus a hint to interpret the style of the between a public discourse of science and
Contributions is indicated. For an inceptual the specific presuppositions of an original
thinking must necessarily distance itself (more or less still missed) philosophic lan-
from the thinking that follows or precedes it. guage unfolding itself from enowning. This
Or it must generally be distinguished from presumably is the difference, with which in
all other kinds of thinking. If each thinking different forms Heideggers thinking is strug-
has its own style, then the style of inceptual gling everywhere.
thinking must be uniquely different. A possible interpretation of this difference
This situation, namely that the Contributions is one between an exoteric discourse of the
are a beginning, is unfolded on the first public sphere (in which Heidegger himself

216
CONTRIBUTIONS TO PHILOSOPHY

participates, for instance, with lecture courses period Heidegger worked at the first lecture
or public lectures, that is, with an academic course on Schelling in the summer of 1936,
mode of his philosophy) and an esoteric phi- at both lecture courses on Nietzsche in the
losophy, which appears For the Few and winter of 1936/37 and the summer of 1937.
for the Rare (9).2 This difference can be This was followed by a lecture course quite
explicated in many utterances of Heidegger. close to the Contributions about the Basic
Thus, he claims of philosophy that what is Questions of Philosophy in the winter
essentialafter it, almost hidden, has gone to seminar of 1937/38. Furthermore in 1936
the foremust retreat and become inaccessi- Heidegger gave two public lectures in Rome,
ble (for the many), for this essential is unsur- at first Hlderlin and the Essence of Poetry,
passable and therefore must withdraw into the then Europe and the German Philosophy.
enabling of the beginning (13). Or perhaps Nor is this an exhaustive account of
he illuminates the difference more acutely, his work during this time. The editor of
when he argues that making itself intelligi- the Contributions Friedrich-Wilhelm von
ble is the suicide for philosophy (307). Herrmann calls attention to the fact that
In my eyes Heidegger does not inscribe Heidegger was also working on other, as yet
himself in a conservative or pessimistic move- unpublished manuscripts such as Current
ment of European thinking, which is refer- Comments on Being and Time (1936),
ring to a deep difference between the many The . The Remembrance into the
( ) and the best ( ). Rather First Beginning and Disempowerment of
he takes up the question: to what extent does the (both 1937). It is assumed that
philosophy need a language that cannot be the genesis of Mindfulness (1938/39)
subordinated to the general category of pub- coincided with the accomplishment of the
licity (Kant). If we consider the argument Contributions. Such a confluence of the
as one of these criteria, Heidegger could only concurrent genesis of totally heterogeneous
accept this as a form of one specific mode texts demonstrates in what dimension the
of thinking, but not as one of philosophy as question for the scriptuality of Heideggers
a whole. And indeed, if taken as an essen- thinking is relevant.
tial criterion, the argument is effective as In the middle of 1934 Heidegger declared
a selection and clean(s)ing. The majority of his resignation from the rectorate of the uni-
philosophy becomes mere literature. versity of Freiburg. This resignation some-
times has been interrelated to the resolution
to write manuscripts apart from the public
sphere. In this sense the specific character
The Historical Context of the Contributions could be reduced to
a political disappointment. This idea is not
The Contributions to Philosophy were supported by Heideggers continued assent
generated between 1936 and 1938, whereas during this period to defend the new state
the Preview and the six following parts, in seminars (for instance in the seminar on
named by Heidegger as joinings, were Hegels Philosophy of Right in winter
written between 1936 and 1937, and the last 1934/35), lecture courses, and public lectures.
part of the actual version of the text The Furthermore, for quite some time before
Be-ing emerged in 1938. During the same 1933 Heidegger wrote texts (for instance

217
CONTRIBUTIONS TO PHILOSOPHY

poems), which could not be understood as it is unlikely that Heidegger thought of this
academic. meaning of the word.
When the work on the manuscript was com- Rather he relied on two other meanings.
pleted in 1938, Fritz Heidegger, the brother At first the jointure is the gap of the space
of the philosopher, made a typewritten-copy, between two parts of a construction. In this
which in 1939 Martin Heidegger compared sense Heidegger calls the structure of the
with the original. Well before the publication Contributions also Gefge (jointure), that
of the Contributions this typewritten-copy is, an expedient adjustment. But, besides this
was distributed to certain students and the philosopher also refers to the meaning
friends of the philosopher. It is part of the of Fuge as Verfgung (conjointure), that
history of the Contributions, that a distinct is, a binding, sometimes fateful decision.3
circle of persons outside the public sphere Both are characterized as an endowment
knew the strange text. (Fgung) of be-ing itself, of the hint and
The manuscript copy of the Contributions withdrawal of its truth.
to Philosophy in the German Archive for An expedient adjustment is also a sys-
Literature in Marbach contains a dedication, tem. But the Fuge is something essen-
which was not carried over into the publica- tially different. For Heidegger the system
tion. For Christmas 1957 Heidegger had is a form of metaphysics moving toward its
dedicated the manuscript to Dory Vietta, end. It is only possible as a consequence of
the wife of Egon Vietta, who in 1950 pub- the mastery of mathematical thinking (in its
lished The Question of Being by Martin widest sense) (45). Heidegger is thinking
Heidegger. The dedication consists of a of the most geometrical prestructuring, the
handwritten copy of an ode of Pindar in deductive organization of the system.
the Greek original as well as in Hlderlins The six parts of the text, which are
translation. It includes erotic references. introduced by a Preview, read: Echo,
The question, whether the addition of this Playing-Forth, Leap, Grounding, The
dedication to the manuscript has philo- Ones to Come, and The Last God. They
sophical meaning, is debatable. But that the are called the six joinings of the jointure,
dedication belongs to its history, cannot be attempting always to say the same of the
doubted. same (57). The onefold of these joinings
can only be sustained from within theinabid-
ing in Da-sein, which distinguishes the being
of those who are to come. Thus the relation
The Structure of the Text to the addressee is emphasized.
A special problem of the edition of the text
Heidegger marks the structure of the represents its end, wherein the actual form
Contributions as a jointure (Fuge) (CP1, of the book the joining Be-ing is to be
56, 81) of the inceptual thinking. The word found. Obviously Heidegger initially planned
has many connotations. Certainly it brings to integrate it as Section II [Part II] (365),
to mindin the sense of the Latin fuga but then he declared in handwriting that it
the musical principle of composing, which was not correctly arranged. This note led
Johann Sebastian Bach in the first half of the the editor to move that part to the end of
eighteenth century brought to its acme. But the text. This resolution is clearly legitimate.

218
CONTRIBUTIONS TO PHILOSOPHY

But it is also clear that Heidegger originally dependency of the university addicted to a
designed it as the second joining. It is evi- technically organized public sphere that lets
dent that reflections about philosophy, the Heidegger preserve a defined place for philos-
ontological difference, and language ophy. In the Contributions the public sphere
altogether contained by Be-ingcould be without a doubt is understood as an ele-
placed at the beginning of the Fuge. Finally ment of machination. But already in Being
a (dis-)closure of the book with the Last and Time Heidegger interpreted the public
God would correspond to the character of sphere as the real dictatorship of the they
Gefge and Verfgung. (BTMR, 164). In the light of the public
sphere everything gets obscured, and what
has thus been covered up gets passed off as
something familiar and accessible to every-
The Method of the one (165). What is what has been covered
Contributions up (das Verdeckte)? It is what belongs to
the phenomenon in the full sense; the phe-
For the understanding or interpretation of nomenon, which is always the clearing for
the Contributions to Philosophy the dif- self-sheltering-concealing (CP1, 237). The
ference between a public and scientific dis- using up of the language Heidegger is speak-
course and a specifically philosophical or, ing of at the beginning of the Contributions
better, a being-historical language is pre- is realizing itself in a mass-media-instituted
supposed. Heidegger takes this difference as public sphere, which begins to provide the
a fact. This is shown by the Propositions technical and economical and, that is, the
about Science (10010). In these propo- discursive standards for the university.
sitions Heidegger refers to the academic Therefore philosophy has no place
innovation of newspaper science (106). (108) in the university. It has no such place
This science was an ancestor of communi- at all, unless it be that place that philosophy
cation science along with radio science itself grounds. But from an established
(Rundfunkkunde, see GA 78, 1889) in institution there is immediately no way
possession of an institute at the university to philosophy. Hence seen in the authentic
of Freiburg between 1922 and 1943. The perspective of philosophy there is only the
newspaper science, was absolutely not a a-topic community of those who question
mere polemical idea of Heidegger. It was in (10) (die Fragenden), who cannot accept
fact incorporated into academic study at a normative-discursive presuppositions, for
university, where the objective and method- there are primarily these presuppositions,
ical difference between the natural and the which are called into question. An institution
human sciences [i.e. philosophy] will recede declaring it discourse for binding is, what-
more and more (CP1, 107). ever it looks like, unphilosophical.
The character of this academic institution The language of philosophy cannot be
for Heidegger consists in the event that the taken from the scientific discourse. Indeed
present lived-experience will continually it cannot continue to emerge from the
be interpreted historically [historisch] and in same area from which scientific discourse
this interpretation will be conveyed the pub- is emerging. This area for Heidegger is the
lication for everyone (ibid.). Hence it is the language of metaphysics. In metaphysics

219
CONTRIBUTIONS TO PHILOSOPHY

language represents the asserting of beings force (54). This is definitely not ordinary
(350). But is there a new language for language. More likely it is the language of
be-ing (54)? Heidegger answers in the nega- poetry and in the Contributions the language
tive, even if this abnegation is not as evident of Hlderlin (2978). HoweverHeidegger
as the philosopher declares (here and there points this out several times (14, 42, but also
he attempted to speak (or to write) such a 50)it has to be a language of thinking as
language). This problem marks the place distinct from a language of poetry. Hence the
where Heidegger encounters the method of demand for this language remains open.
the Contributions. The method of the Contributions consists
The saying of be-ing is happening in of a decision for a certain usage of the word.
words and namings which are understand- This usage can be determined as an esoteric
able in the direction of everyday references one, for it is preceded by a turning away from
to beings (58). But if they are thought the language of metaphysics and science. The
exclusively in this direction, they are mis- approach of the Contributions addresses
construable as the utterance of be-ing. The itself ab initio only to those who are will-
word itself discloses something (familiar) ing to approve or even to respect this turn-
and thus hides that which has to be brought ing away, or at least to understand its idea.
into the open through thinking-saying. This To approve is the institutionalizing of a dis-
difficulty demands a specific approach course, which with its criteria is inhibiting the
(Verfahren). possibility of philosophy. This turning away
This approach must within certain and the responding esoteric initiative charac-
limits extend to ordinary understanding terizes the whole thinking of Heidegger since
and must go a certain stretch of the way the 1930s. This thinking is refusing to subject
with it, only to exact a turning in think- itself to a discourse except its own. This is its
ing at the right moment, but only under freedom and its problem.
the power of the same word. Heidegger
names examples. One of these is the word
machination, which at first means a way
of human comportment. But suddenly and Problems of Reception
properly there emerges the reverse: what
is ownmost (or precisely not ownmost) to The reception of the works of Heideggers
be-ing, from where primarily the possibility thinking stands under particular conditions.
of this comportment is originating. This If in art or in music it happens quite often
reverse is not a trick to alter the mean- that artists or composers provide comments
ing into mere words but rather transforma- or even interpretations of their works, in phi-
tion of man himself. In the approach of losophy it is rare. This is not only because the
the Contributions the human being itself is concept of the work in philosophy cannot
determined to leave the space and the time lay claim to the same (for instance aesthetic)
of metaphysics. meaning as in art. More than around works
This language of the Contributions is not philosophy seems to circle around argu-
the one of metaphysics or of science stem- ments. Nonetheless, perhaps like no other
ming from metaphysics, but the most nobly philosopher, Heidegger has criticized and
formed language in its simplicity and essential interpreted his own works.

220
CONTRIBUTIONS TO PHILOSOPHY

From the six remarks on the Contributions (Heideggerian) philosophical language (as
to Philosophy from the later text Das was emphasized at the beginning). Thus
Ereignis (1941/42) only two are mentioned. the Contributions are integrated into
In the Contributions the question for academic Heidegger-research (as if they
being is still seized in the style of meta- would be an academic text), realizing
physics, instead of thought in the way of the addressee-related-writing of the text
the already conceived history of being (4). in a strange way. Just because there is no
Moreover the idea of the last God is still hermeneutic respect for Heideggers denial
unthinkable (5). of the academic and scientific way of writ-
If in the aesthetic context of the recep- ing, just because there is no mindfulness of
tion of artworks, the difference between the esoteric and always more esoteric ges-
the reflections of the artist and the artwork ture of Heideggers thinking, a specific, and
itself is so deep that the artists reflection perhaps the whole research of Heideggers
can be considered merely another interpre- philosophy is separated from an open-
tation of the artwork, the problem is more ness of thinking, that we can learn from
complex in philosophy. For a philosophical Heidegger himself. Thus sects and cliques
text does not define its limits and borders as and groups are defining their territories and
strictly as an artwork. A text can be touched choking the philosophical dialogue. Only if
and sometimes seems to transform itself we are critically aware of Heideggers eso-
into its interpretations. Heidegger does not teric initiative, only if we are free enough to
comment on that which is separate from acknowledge the philosophical dimension
him. Again and again he inscribes himself of this initiative, which includes indeed the
in his own works, or he even picks up the great majority of Heideggers texts, and
thread repeatedly. This is why Heideggers only if we are open-minded enough to see
critique of his own writingsrightly or the possible failure of this initiative, will
notclaims a privileged meaning. But this the reading of Heidegger take the necessary
is not the only problem of the reception of next step.
the Contributions.
In general the text is considered as the
second major work of Martin Heidegger NOTES AND REFERENCES
(after Being and Time). Such an estimation
seems to orientate toward Heideggers own 1
See Friedrich-Wilhelm von Herrmann, Wege
understanding of the work. Otherwise it is ins Ereignis. Zu Heideggers Beitrgen
zur Philosophie (Frankfurt am Main:
contrasted by the philosopher himself, when
Klostermann, 1994), 6. See also Emad and
he chose the motto for the Gesamtausgabe Maly in their Translators Foreword, xv.
Waysnot works. This motto, if taken 2
See Peter Trawny, Adyton. Heideggers esoter-
seriously, would open up a totally different ische Philosophie (Berlin: Matthes & Seitz,
access to the writings of this philosopher. The 2011), or Richard F. Polt, The Emergency
of Being: On Heideggers Contributions to
experimental character of Heideggers scrip-
Philosophy (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University
tuality is yet to be discovered. Press, 2006), 1122. Also consider Hans
The reception of the Contributions has Ruin, Contributions to Philosophy, in, ed.
mostly ignored the difference between a Hubert L. Dreyfus and Mark A. Wrathall,
public-scientific discourse and an authentic A Companion to Heidegger (Malden, MA:

221
CONTRIBUTIONS TO PHILOSOPHY

Blackwell Publishers, 2005), 35873, and publication (xv). Maybe the publication of
Daniela Vallega-Neu, Heideggers Contributions the text was not in sight, but there is an impor-
to Philosophy: An Introduction (Bloomington: tant difference between Heideggers esoteric ini-
Indiana University Press, 2003), finally tiative and private ponderings. Philosophical
Companion to Heideggers Contributions to thinking is never private pondering. This is a
Philosophy, ed. Charles E. Scott (Bloomington: real misunderstanding even of the style of the
Indiana University Press, 2001). As given in Contributions.
the translators introduction of Rojcevicz and 3
Emad and Maly translate Verfgung with
Vallega-Neu: At issue in the Contributions are the neologistic conjointure and access. One
indeed private ponderings not composed for would have to find another solution.

222
27
THE HLDERLIN LECTURES
William McNeill

Contexts and Nietzsche. Of these two, it is Nietzsche


who has received by far the greatest atten-
Heidegger scholarship generally has read- tion from scholars, and indeed for reasons
ily acknowledged that a decisive shiftthe that are quite understandable. Nietzsches
so-called turningtakes place in Heideggers project of overcoming Platonismthat
thought during the 1930s: a shift away from is, the fundamental structure of occiden-
the hermeneutic phenomenological ontol- tal metaphysics that institutes a difference
ogy of the Being and Time period (an ontol- between being and beings, between truth
ogy imbued with scientific and objectifying and appearances, positing a true world
aspirations) and toward an overcoming of of ideas beyond and governing the realm of
ontology (now viewed more historically sensuous becomingparallels Heideggers
as metaphysics) that entails a turning of own concern to overcome metaphysics and
thought toward art and poetizing as well to recover an other commencement for
as a sustained critique of science and tech- Western-European thinking, one that might
nicity, themselves outgrowths of occidental transform the human beings relation to
metaphysics. This shift in Heideggers think- being and to the Earth from a power-hungry
ing during the 1930s is to this day not well relation of technological mastery to a more
understood, and this is due not only to the finite and responsive manner of dwelling
sheer volume of Heideggers work during this with and upon the Earth, one mindful of the
period but also to its richness and complex- finitude of its own temporality and mortality.
ity, not to mention the politics involved Heideggers thoughtful yet critical encounters
before, during, and after Heideggers notori- with Nietzsche in the mid- to late 1930s and
ous assumption of the Rectorship of Freiburg early 1940s (essentially, up to 1941) indeed
university in 1933 and his failed attempt to show a breadth and depth of engagement
engage National Socialism for his own politi- that appear second to none. That engage-
cal ends. ment begins with three major lecture courses:
If one surveys Heideggers work of the The Will to Power as Art (19367), The
1930s with a view to the multiple dimensions Eternal Recurrence of the Same (1937), and
at stake in this shift in his thinking, then it The Will to Power as Knowledge (1939),
is readily apparent that Heidegger has two and continues with the essays and notes from
main interlocutors during this time: Hlderlin 193941 (including the essay on European

223
THE HLDERLIN LECTURES

Nihilism from 1940) that are collected in interpretation has made of this in all its
volume II of the original German edition of orientations. (GA 39, 2934)
Heideggers Nietzsche.
Nevertheless, the significance of this sus- Heideggers Nietzsche lectures would thus
tained and critical encounter with Nietzsche not only face the task of liberating Nietzsches
notwithstanding, it needs to be recognized thought from all of these fateful entanglements
that this encounter occurs within the greater and misguided interpretations, exposing
context of a dialogue with Hlderlin.1 the fundamental significance of Nietzsches
The Nietzsche lectures are both preceded thinking as lying in its relation to the first
and followed by major lecture courses commencement of occidental metaphysics
on Hlderlin, which also give rise to sev- and the light it sheds upon the essence of
eral published essays. In the winter semes- historical Dasein, it would also free the path
ter of 19345, following his resignation for a return to the purity and simplicity of
from the Rectorship, Heidegger lectures on Hlderlins poetizinga purity and simplic-
Hlderlins hymns Germania and The ity that, admittedly, also demand the work
Rhine. In winter semester 19412, directly of interpretation in order to be heard. In his
following his sustained engagement with lecture from the following semester, summer
Nietzsche, Heidegger returns to Hlderlins semester 1935, Heidegger again signals what,
poetry, presenting a second lecture course, even prior to the Nietzsche lectures, appears
this one on the hymn Remembrance. In to have already been decided: the superior-
summer semester 1942 he gives the last of ity of Hlderlin over Nietzsche, the latters
his lecture courses on Hlderlin, an interpre- greatness notwithstanding. Nietzsches meta-
tation (or more precisely, as he insists, a set physics, he remarks, did not find its way to
of remarks) focusing on the hymn The the decisive question, even though he under-
Ister.2 This return to Hlderlins poetry was, stood the age of the great commencement of
it seems, entirely anticipated by Heidegger the entire Greek Dasein in a manner that was
toward the end of the first Hlderlin course. surpassed only by Hlderlin.4
There, speaking of Hlderlins famous 1801 The importance of Heideggers Hlderlin
letter to his friend Bhlendorff, he remarked lectures (and especially of the first lecture
that: course) for understanding Heideggers work
of the mid- to late 1930s, and indeed all of
What Hlderlin here sees as the essence his subsequent thought, can hardly be over-
of historical Dasein, the conflictual inti- stated. Here, we may recall briefly just a few
macy of endowment and task, was discov- external indications of this (there are many
ered again by Nietzsche under the titles
more that could be cited):
of the Dionysian and the Apollonian,
but not with such purity and simplic-
ity as in Hlderlin; for in the meantime (1) The seminal essay on The Origin of
Nietzsche had to make his way through the Work of Art was completed in its mature
all those fateful steps signaled by the and final version in 1936. Yet Heidegger had
names Schopenhauer, Darwin, Wagner, already begun to work on the initial drafts of
Grnderjahre.3 Not to mention the most the essay in 19345, that is, during exactly
fateful thing of all, namely, what sub- the same period that he was delivering the
sequent and contemporary Nietzsche first Hlderlin course. Not only does the

224
THE HLDERLIN LECTURES

essay conclude by recalling the infallible Hlderlins fragments for The Titans con-
sign of Hlderlin, the poet, whose work cerning the question of the right time, the
still confronts the Germans as a test to be opportune moment (Augenblick) or kairos,
stood, and by citing lines from the hymn now seen from the historical perspective of
The Journey (Reluctantly that which / being setting itself to work.
Dwells near the origin abandons the locale); (4) Heideggers major manuscript of the
it should be apparent to anyone familiar with 1930s, the Contributions to Philosophy:
Heideggers work of this period that both the Of Ereignis, is suffused with Hlderlinian
monumental theme of the Eartha motif motifs and resonances, most prominently
clearly adopted from Hlderlinand the the theme of the Earth mentioned above,
claim that all art, and indeed language itself, but also the question of the divine, of the
is in essence poetizing (Dichtung) cannot flight of the gods poetized in the hymn
be adequately understood without an appre- Germania and the motif of the last god.
ciation of the first Hlderlin course. Hlderlin, Heidegger here announces, is the
(2) The crucially important and roughly most futural poet, as the one who experi-
contemporaneous essay Hlderlin and the ences the flight of the gods of old and awaits
Essence of Poetry, first delivered as a lecture the arrival of the gods to come, the one who
in Rome in 1936 and subsequently to become stands within the time-space of this transition
the first published essay of Heideggers that, as the site of the historical moment of
on Hlderlin, is in all essential respects beings disclosure, opens the possibility of an
excerpted from the 19345 course. The much other commencement. The word Ereignis
longer essay Remembrance, published in itself, referring to the appropriative event of
1943, is likewise essentially drawn from the beings happening, indeed may well be taken
19412 lecture course on the same hymn. from Hlderlin.5
Both are contained in the volume of essays (5) The seminal essay The Age of the
Elucidations of Hlderlins Poetry. World Picture from 1938, Heideggers first
(3) The 1935 lecture course Introduction systematic critique of science and represen-
to Metaphysics, in which we find the remark tation, likewise ends by raising the question
noted above concerning the superiority of of the historical moment and by citing
Hlderlins understanding of the first com- Hlderlins poem To the Germans, con-
mencement over that of Nietzsche, is also cerning the untimely time into which the
conducted under the shadow of the 19345 poet-thinker is transported.
Hlderlin course. Here, Heidegger attempts (6) Heideggers last lecture course, What
to retrieve the poetizing thinking of is Called Thinking?, from 19512, draws
Greek tragedy, recalling Hlderlins charac- heavily on Hlderlin, particularly in its
terization of Oedipus as having an eye too opening phase, where Heidegger recalls the
many, and venturing a first interpretation lines from the hymn Mnemosyne con-
of the famous ode to man from Sophocles cerning man as a sign that is not read,
Antigonea choral ode that is absolutely and also appeals to the lines from the poem
central to Hlderlins poetic thinking, and Socrates and Alcibiades that run He who
that Heidegger would return to in his later has thought most deeply, loves what is most
course on Hlderlins The Ister. The alive in order to insist on thinking as a form
1935 course ends with a quotation from of love.

225
THE HLDERLIN LECTURES

(7) Finally, the roughly contempora- one whose poetizing remains in proximity to
neous essay The Question Concerning thinking, to a supremely thoughtful saying
Technology, formulated between 1949 of beyng in the poetic word. Thereby, think-
and 1953, notoriously ends with an appeal ing itself demands to be experienced differ-
to Hlderlins word . . . where danger is, ently, not as philosophical conceptuality, but
there / Grows the saving power also, and as it is configured poetically, in and through
to Hlderlins claim that . . . poetically man the poetizing itself. Hlderlin is indeed,
dwells upon this Earth.6 Heidegger insists, our most futural thinker,
because he is our greatest poet (6), and by
this formulation also signals that the issue of
the manifestation of beyng in this poetizing
The First Hlderlin Lecture will prove inseparable from the question of
Course: The Hymns Germania the we, of the German peoplea question
and The Rhine (19345) to which he will shortly turn more explic-
itly. This claim, furthermore, points to the
The first Hlderlin lecture course falls almost proximity and belonging together (though
exactly into two halves, the first half devoted not the identity) of thinking and poetizing,
to articulating the initial approach to where thinking is something other than
Germania, and the second to an interpre- traditional philosophy and is implicitly
tation of The Rhine that then, in its clos- attuned to the poetic.
ing stages, returns to Germania in order to The phenomenon of attunement, indeed
display the inner unity of the two hymns and of what Heidegger terms a fundamental
expose what Heidegger calls the metaphysi- attunement, will prove crucial here. Our task
cal locale of Hlderlins poetizing. in experiencing Hlderlins poetizing is not
The first half of the lecture course is espe- to distill from it some spiritual content or
cially important, for Heidegger here devotes symbolic meaning, some abstract truth, but
considerable effort to gaining a preliminary rather, in resisting our everyday and com-
understanding of what poetizing (Dichtung) monplace view of poetry, to experience the
is, its essence and its linguistic character. The power of the poetic word in exposing our-
essence being sought, however, is not some selves to its saying or telling (Sagen), to
universal essence of poetizing in general, the overarching sweep and configuration of
but the essence of this, Hlderlins, poet- its resonance and oscillation, and to do so in
izing: the essence that is poetized in and letting ourselves be torn away by the poetic
through this singular poetizing. It is thus word in its very telling. For contrary to our
not to be imposed from the outside, as it everyday understanding, Heidegger explains,
were, through the philosophical applica- language is not reducible to a means of
tion of a concept of poetizing to this par- expression that articulates some spiritual
ticular instance. Rather, it must be gleaned meaning; it is not at all what it appears to be,
by experiencing the power of the poetizing something present at hand that we have,
itself that is in question, through a thought- just as we would have some piece of prop-
ful encounter with the manifestation of erty. Rather, as he forcefully puts it, It is not
beyng that is achieved in this poetizing (GA we who have language, rather language has
39, 6).7 Hlderlin is the poet of poets (30), us (23).

226
THE HLDERLIN LECTURES

As Hlderlins poetizing itself articulates it, Germania itselfwith particular atten-


poetizing is, first, a telling in the manner of a tiveness to the time of this we; and second,
making manifest that points. In the poem As to unfolding the fundamental attunement
when on feast day . . ., Hlderlin writes: of the hymn Germania, which proves to be
that of a holy mourning with the waters of
Yet us it behooves, under Gods the homeland. The homeland, Heidegger
thunderstorms, insists, does not here mean a mere birth-
You poets! to stand with naked heads,
place or geographical region, but rather the
To grasp the Fathers ray, itself
power of the Earth upon which the human
With our own hands and shrouded in
the song being, in his or her historical Dasein, poeti-
To pass on to the people the heavenly cally dwells (88). The mourning is holy:
gift. not just any mourning, but a mourning aris-
ing out of the experience of the flight of
The poet, in Heideggers words, thus har- the gods enunciated in the opening lines of
nesses the lightning flashes of the God, com- Germania. As such, however, this mourn-
pelling them into the word, and places this ing, as a plaint and distress arising from
lightning-charged word into the language of the necessity of renouncing the gods of old,
his people (30). In exposing himself to the is not merely a preserving of the gods that
overwhelming power of beyng, the poet has have been, but simultaneously a readiness
the task of receiving the beckonings of the and awaiting of the future and of that which
gods and passing them on to the people, and is to come. The poetic attunement unfolds
in so doing his poetizing is, in the words of precisely as this power of temporality in
the last line of the hymn Remembrance, a which we are torn in these two directions,
founding (Stiften) of that which remains, and it is in inhabiting this time that tears,
a founding of beyng, as Heidegger puts it, to use Hlderlins words, that the time of
one that first grounds the historical Dasein a historical people is first temporalized in
of a people. Although from an everyday per- and as a poetic attunement (109). This time
spective it appears, in Hlderlins words, to of the we, of a historical people, is, how-
be this most innocent of occupations (33), ever, uncertain and unknown; it remains
poetizing is anything but one meritorious concealed from us, Heidegger insists, and
cultural activity among others. Rather, as may at most be intimated by the poet whose
Hlderlin elsewhere tells, it configures and soul, in the words of Hlderlins poem To
founds the human beings dwelling upon this the Germans, is transported beyond its
Earth: own time. Seeking the true time for his
own time, remarks Heidegger, the poet is
Full of merit, yet poetically dwell necessarily removed from the time of the
Human beings upon this Earth. present day (50); he must inhabit the peaks
of time (52), and his dwelling on the peaks
Following this initial situating of the lan- of time, as a creator, is a persistent waiting
guage of Hlderlins poetizing, Heidegger and awaiting the event [Ereignis], a mak-
turns first to the question of the we of a his- ing ready for the true that shall once come
torical peoplea question he develops from to pass [sich ereignen] (56). The word
the turbulence of the telling of the hymn Ereignis, which becomes the keyword of

227
THE HLDERLIN LECTURES

Heideggers thinking from the mid-1930s out and around into the thinking of his own
on, is here appropriated from Hlderlins homeland (171). The destiny (Schicksal)
hymn Mnemosyne, which speaks of the that comes toward him in this pondering is
sich ereignen, the coming to pass, of the indeed the key word of his poetizing, it is
true: the name for the beyng of the demigods
(172).
. . . Lang ist In the poetizing of the Rhine as a destiny,
Die Zeit, es ereignet sich aber
destiny does not mean any kind of fatal-
Das Wahre. ism or predestination. It names, rather, the
. . . Long is being and becoming of the river itself in its
The time, yet what is true very flow. The river Rhine is a destiny, and
Comes to pass. destiny comes to be only in the history of
this river (196). This flowing of the river,
In the second half of the lecture course, however, is determined by its relation to its
Heidegger turns his attention to one of the origin. In the remaining part of the course,
aforementioned waters of the homeland, Heidegger ponders above all what is at stake
specifically the river poetized in Hlderlins in the enigma of this relation, for it is that
hymn The Rhine. Keeping in mind a enigma that is poetized in and as the hymn
remark from one of Hlderlins fragments itself, according to lines 46f.:
on Pindar, that the river is that which vio-
lently creates paths and limits upon the orig- Enigma is that which has purely sprung
inarily pathless Earth (923), Heidegger forth. Even
identifies as the pivot of the entire hymn The song may scarcely unveil it.
the first line of strophe X, Demigods now I
think. The river Rhine itself is poetized as a The poet dwells close to the origin
demigod, that is, as something that is at once (Ursprung). According to the second strophe,
more than the human and yet less than the he hears the river in its origin, in the coldest
gods. It does not merely occupy an existing abyss, as yet to spring forth; mere mortals,
space between humans and gods, however, by contrast, have fled the locale. Yet the
but first creates and opens up this very space task of this poetizing is not to unveil the ori-
in which the essence of both humans and gin as such, but the river in its having purely
gods can be asked about. The poet thinks sprung forth (Entsprungensein), and to do
the demigods when, as the opening line of so in a veiled saying that scarcely unveils
the hymn puts it, he is sitting at the portal the entire enigma. And this can be accom-
of the woods, that is, at the threshold of plished only through a poetic thinking of the
the poets homeland. The poet, Heidegger entire course of the river, as determined by
comments, sits at the threshold of the its relation to the origin, a relation that will
Earth of the homeland, there he thinks the prove to be intrinsically discordant. Whereas
demigods (16970); and this thinking is, mortals flee from the origin and attend only
according to the first strophe, an unsus- to what has already sprung forth, without
pecting apprehending of a destiny: the poet giving thought to its having sprung forth (or,
is, from out of his pondering that which is if they think the origin, they think it only in
distant and has been, unsuspectingly torn terms of what has already sprung forth, that

228
THE HLDERLIN LECTURES

is, metaphysically), the task of Hlderlins The poetizing of this poet is thus nothing
poetizing is different: other than nature coming into beingtelling
of itself and founding its being in such telling:
Yet just as the origin that has merely
sprung forth is not the origin, neither Because the poets are not directed toward
is the merely fettered origin. Rather, the nature as an object, for instance; because,
entire essence of the origin is the fet- rather, nature as beyng founds itself
tered origin in its springing forth. Yet in saying, the saying of the poets as the
the springing forth itself first comes to self-saying of nature is of the same essence
be what it is as the river runs its entire as the latter. This is why it is said of the
course; it is not limited to the begin- poets: they intimate always. (258)
ning of its course. The entire course of
the river itself belongs to the origin. The
origin is fully apprehended only as the Nature here is thus not an entity, but
fettered origin in its springing forth as a word for beyng itself. Yet the nature or
having sprung forth. (202) beyng in question here is not indeterminate,
for the poets task is to found, through his
Yet something decisive happens in the course poetizing, the historical dwelling of a people
of the Rhines flowing. Although originally upon this Earth, to found the land as land
driven toward Asiawhich Heidegger, and as homeland of the people (259). The
drawing on another hymn, takes to include question of this peopleof the we and of
Greecethis original directionality is sud- the historical time of the we, the historical
denly broken off, and the river turns north, momentis, as we have indicated, central
toward Germany, a turning indicative of a to Heideggers concern here. The question
counter-will to the original will of the ori- of the we is the question of the Germans;
gin. We cannot here convey the entire detail Hlderlin is not only the poet of poets and
and subtlety of Heideggers ensuing analy- of poetizing, he is the poet of the Germans,
sis, and we shall have to come back to The one who must become a power or force in
Rhine in our remarks on The Ister. It the history of our people. The issue con-
must suffice here to indicate that Heidegger cerns politics in the highest and authentic
proceeds to interpret this counter-will as a sense, so much so that whoever accomplishes
strife and blessed enmity within beyng, a something here has no need to talk about the
counter-turning that is still a unity (blessed- political (214). For the political in the
ness), and to unfold this enigma in terms of narrower sense of the affairs of state first
what Hlderlin names intimacy, Innigkeit. arises from poetizing: [. . .] the historical
Intimacy does not, for Hlderlin, mean any Dasein of the peoples . . . springs from poet-
kind of human relationship: it is his word izing, and from the latter springs authentic
for that originary unity of the enmity of the knowing in the sense of philosophy, and from
powers of what has purely sprung forth. It is both the effecting of the Dasein of a peo-
the mystery belonging to such beyng (250). ple as a people through the statepolitics
Innigkeit is Hlderlins word for the being (51). Toward the end of the lectures on The
of nature itself, a being that, in the poem As Rhine Heidegger returns to this question of
when on feast day . . ., is said to be intima- the historical moment, of the moment named
tive (ahnend)as are the poets themselves. in Germania as the middle of time, as

229
THE HLDERLIN LECTURES

that historical Dasein in which and as which The Titans, Mnemosyne, and Ripe,
the essence of this land finds itself and com- bathed in fire . . .; of these, however, only
pletes itself (289). This middle of time, how- the first two received extensive attention:
ever, first arises from having-been (the flight Remembrance in winter semester 19412,
of the gods) and future (to be founded in and The Ister the following semester.
poetizing), and as such, is nothing given, but The interpretation of Remembrance
an identity that must first be attained in and is remarkable with regard to a number of
through struggle. Heidegger here appeals, in themes, which we can only indicate briefly
closing, to Hlderlins letter to Bhlendorff here. First, the interpretation of greeting,
from 1801 (the same year as the two hymns which Heidegger at once links to the phenom-
were written), which insists that the struggle enon of remembrance and, by way of anticipa-
of historical existence is always to transform tion, to the flow of the river poetized in The
what is given one as an endowment (ones Ister. The hymn opens with the lines:
own, the national) into what is given one
as a task (the free use of the national). The Northeasterly blows,
For the Germans, endowed with the gift of Most beloved of the winds to me
conceptual clarity, ordering, and planning, For it promises fiery spirit
And good voyage to those at sea.
this means learning to be struck by beyng,
But go now, and greet
and this is the opposite of the situation faced
The beautiful Garonne,
by the Greeks, who were struck by the fire And the gardens of Bordeaux
from the heavens (the violence of beyng, ...
as Heidegger translates it) and had to har-
ness this excess in bringing it to a stand in The single line But go now, and greet,
the work. This reversal of historical predica- Heidegger insists, conceals the entire mystery
ment is also, for Heidegger, indicative of the of what is called remembrance (GA 52, 49;
special relationship between the German 55). Remembrance, Andenken, is poetized as
and the Greek: In fighting the battle of the a greeting; as a greeting, it is a thoughtful turn-
Greeks, but on the reverse front, we become ing toward that which is greeted. Heidegger
not Greeks, but Germans (293).8 unfolds the structure of greeting from a med-
itation on the opening lines that poetize the
blowing of the wind, in an intricate analysis
that we cannot reproduce here.9 Genuine
Hlderlin Revisited: The greeting, as an address (Zuspruch) turned
Lectures on Remembrance toward the one greeted, is recognition: the
(19412) recognition that recognizes the one greeted in
the nobility of their essence and through
In the winter semester of 19412, follow- such recognition lets them be what they are.
ing a seven year hiatus marked by his criti- Greeting is thus a letting be of things and
cal encounters with Nietzsche, Heidegger of human beings (50). In the structure of
returned to lecture on Hlderlin. At the begin- greeting poetized in Remembrance, that
ning of the lecture course he announced that which is to be greeted, however, itself inclines
the course would be concerned with five dif- toward the poet, approaches him in his very
ferent poems: Remembrance, The Ister, thinkingsomething the poet poetizes in the

230
THE HLDERLIN LECTURES

striking line Still it seems to think of me of the south of France (line 18) represent, he
(Noch denket das mir wohl), which opens insists, the Greek world and the festival of
the second stropheand this mysterious humans and gods once celebrated there (80);
turning or reversal of direction indeed char- the golden dreams (line 23) likewise refer
acterizes the very structure of remembrance, to the Greeks and to the Greek world (113,
and perhaps of thought itself. It is as though, 122); the land of southern France depicted
Heidegger remarks, a river that runs out and in the poem stands poetically for Greece
goes into the sea suddenly flowed backward (184); indeed, the hymn Remembrance,
in the opposite direction, toward the source, ostensibly about France, is in fact, by virtue
here alluding already to the hymn The of its poetizing of the relation of Greece to
Ister, in which the river is said almost to Germany, claimed to be the most German
flow backward (54). of all German poems (119). Heideggers
A second major theme of the 19412 interpretive move here is aware of appearing
course, one that takes up and develops arbitrary, but justifies itself by appeal, on the
the structure of greeting and that subse- one hand, to a second letter of Hlderlins to
quently dominates the entire course, is the Bhlendorff, from 1802, following his return
question of festival and festivity. While we from Bordeaux, where the poet writes explic-
must again forego a detailed interpreta- itly of experiencing the fire from the heav-
tion here, we may simply note the striking ens thereattributed to the Greeks in the
claims made by Heidegger, first, that festival earlier, 1801 letterand of being struck by
(which for Hlderlin means the bridal fes- Apollo (224; 184); and on the other hand,
tival of humans and gods, poetized in The to the lines in Remembrance that read
Rhine) comprises the incipient greeting But now to Indians / The men have gone,
in which humans and gods are greeted by that is, as Heidegger reads it, beyond France
the holy, and that this originary greeting (which allegedly stands for Greece) and to
is the concealed essence of history. It is, Asia, to the Indus, from which, according to
says Heidegger, the Ereignis, the commence- the poem The Eagle, the German ances-
ment (70). Correspondingly, the holy tors once arrived. The sweep of Hlderlins
comprises an attunement more incipient poetic vision would thus exceed the more
and more originary than every other human proximate remembrance of Bordeaux in
attunement.10 relating the origins of the Germania to the
Third, Heidegger returns in this lecture more distant and remote lands of Greece and
course to the question of the free use of ones Asia. Still, the sidelining of Bordeaux and the
own, the question with which he had con- heavy emphasis on the German cannot but
cluded the first Hlderlin course. The poet of appear troubling.11
Remembrance, composed after Hlderlins
return from Bordeaux in France, of course
sends his greeting from his homeland, from
Germania. Yet it is arguably the least con- The Last Hlderlin Lecture
vincing, most reductive move in Heideggers Course: The Ister (1942)
entire interpretation when he essentially
translates Bordeaux into Greece and the The course on Remembrance, in its conclud-
ancient Greek world: the brown women ing phase, already situated its interpretation

231
THE HLDERLIN LECTURES

of that hymn with a view to the hymn that prepares for the festivalthe festival
The Ister (the Greek name for the lower that, in the case of Hlderlins river hymns,
Danube12), which poetizes a return from the will prove to be the bridal festival of humans
Indus to the homeland on the part of those in and gods. Yet the course is no less attuned
search of what is fitting (i.e. ones own, by the first line of the hymn, Now come,
which Heidegger interprets as the holy). It fire!, a call enunciated by those who are
thus explicitly anticipated and prepared the already called upon, who are of a calling,
ground for the course of the following semes- eager . . . to see the day, as the hymn con-
ter on The Ister, identifying the latter as the tinues. The emphatic Now with which the
authentic river of the homeland of this poet hymn opens, though seeming to speak from
(GA 52, 185). The final Hlderlin lecture the present into a future to come, speaks in
course is indeed entirely articulated around the first instance into what has already hap-
the question of the homeland, more precisely: pened; as such, it names an appropriative
of what it means to come to be at home event [Ereignis] (9), one that has appro-
or homely (heimisch) in ones own. The priated those who have been called upon,
course is remarkable not only for the way in brought them into this moment of poetic
which it seeks to integrate these later courses saying. This emphatic Now, Heidegger
on Remembrance and The Ister with the insists, gives the entire poem its proper and
earlier interpretations of Germania and singular tone (8). Yet the Ister, as a river, is
The Rhine, poems to which it returns in not just a Now, a moment of time, but, as
its concluding phase, but also for the exten- Hlderlin indicates in the poem Voice of the
sive interpretation of the first choral ode People, the rivers simultaneously intimate
from Sophocless Antigone, an interpretation what is to come and vanish into what has
thatquite unexpectedlyoccupies almost been: they are intimative and vanishing,
half the entire lecture course.13 and as such, are themselves time, remarks
The 1942 course falls into three parts: an Heidegger. While they do not take the path of
initial, introductory part, rejecting a meta- human beings, according to the same poem,
physical or symbolic reading of Hlderlins there is nevertheless a love of them, a belong-
poetry and reflecting on the essence of the ing to them, a going along with the rivers on
river hymns; the second, intermediary part the part of human beings.
containing the lengthy commentary on the Yet the first strophe of The Ister
Antigone chorus; and the third, concluding names not only a now but also a here:
part, reflecting on the essence of the poet Here, however, we wish to build (line 15).
as sign, and on the divergent relation to the Although in its flowing or journeying
origin poetized in the Ister and Rhine the river always occupies another here, it
hymns. marks the site of dwelling for human beings,
Antigone, admittedly, attunes the entire which Heidegger goes on to call the local-
1942 lecture course. Heidegger indeed opens ity for human dwelling upon the Earth, the
the course by prefacing his reading of The site where they can come into their own (das
Ister with some remarks on the meaning of Eigene) and be at home (heimisch). Yet
hymn, in which he appeals to the words precisely this, dwelling within ones own, is
of Antigone at lines 806f. and interprets the that which comes last, and is seldom suc-
meaning of humnos as a celebratory song cessful, and always remains what is most

232
THE HLDERLIN LECTURES

difficult (24). Humans thus have the task Gewaltttigkeit) in which the earlier inter-
of first coming to be at home, of coming to pretation was couched. The human being, in
be at home in and through the poetizing that the word of the chorus, is to deinon, which
the river itself is, through the journeying of Heidegger again renders as the uncanny
the locality of human dwelling, a journeying das Unheimliche, in the sense of not being
that is historical: The river is the journey- at home among beings. Uncanniness marks
ing of the coming to be at home of historical the very being of the human being: it is not
human beings upon this Earth (378). a state or predicament to be overcome, nor
That human beings must first come to be does it first arise as a consequence of human
at home in what is their own, however, entails existence. Humankind, rather emerges from
that they are at first and for a long time, and uncanniness and remains within itlooms out
sometimes forever, not at home; coming to of it and stirs within it (89). Far from being
be at home thus entails a passage through something to be overcome, such not being at
the foreign (60). For Hlderlin, ones own home is something that has to be taken on,
names the fatherland of the Germans; the assumed as the very essence, the abode or
finding of this forbidden fruit14 must entail dwelling place of the human being, an abode
a passing through and encounter with the that prevails amid change and becoming,
foreign. Yet the foreign is not any arbi- journeying and flowing. And precisely this,
trary foreign, but one that is intrinsically according to Heideggers interpretation, is,
related to ones own, the foreign of ones in her own words, the essence of Antigone:
own, the foreign that is already within ones pathein to deinon touto, to take up into
own: for the poet Hlderlin, the Greek poets my own essence the uncanny that here and
Pindar and above all, Sophocles. The foreign now appears (127). Coming to be at home
in question thus belongs to ones own: it is thus means, not overcoming our not being
the provenance of the return home, for the at home, but appropriating it as our essence,
Germans, the Greek world (67). Heideggers coming to dwell within it, coming to be at
claim that throughout Hlderlins poetic tell- home in not being at home. Antigone herself,
ing of the human beings coming to be at Heidegger writes, is the poem of coming to
home there repeatedly resonates a singular be at home in not being at home (151).
poetic work of a singular poet, namely the When Heidegger returns to Hlderlin in
first choral ode of Sophocless Antigone, now the extremely rich and compressed closing
becomes the occasion for an extended inter- part of the lecture course, it is on the one
pretation of the ode (63). This interpretation hand to contrast the different relation to
is not only much more extensive than that the origin that is poetized in the Ister and
offered previously in Heideggers 1935 course Rhine hymns. Whereas The Rhine tells
Introduction to Metaphysics; it also differs in of a violent relation to the origin, in which the
significant respects. Heidegger now not only river attempts to rush with violence to the
integrates his commentary into the context heart of the mother, to the Earth of the home-
of Hlderlins poetizing and the question of land, and is rejected into an unknown destiny
translation (both his own translation of the (201),15 The Ister, in its seeming almost to
choral ode, and Hlderlins translations of flow backward, comes from the encounter
Pindar and Sophocles) but also largely retracts with the foreign back to a more intimative
the entire discourse of violence (Gewalt and dwelling close to the source. Yet the foreign

233
THE HLDERLIN LECTURES

is not thereby abandoned or left behind, but Heideggers encounters with Hlderlin are
remains determinative for the journeying crucial for understanding the turn to lan-
and flow of the river. The Ister has invited guage that characterizes his later work, as
the Greek demigod Hercules from the land of well as his meditations on art, technicity, and
the heavenly fire as a guest, as the presence poetic dwelling. They are also crucially inter-
of the unhomely in the homely; the return woven with issues of politics and history,
to the home is never a simple appropriation interpretation and translation, attunement
of ones own, insists Heidegger: The appro- and memory. In particular, they offer rich
priation of ones own is only as the encounter resources for pursuing questions of national
and guest-like dialogue with the foreign. [...] identity, linguistic identity, and the histori-
The relation to the foreign is never a mere cal constitution of traditions, questions that
taking over of the Other (177, 179). The today appear more pressing than ever.
source that is poetized in Hlderlins hymn
is thus not a metaphysical source or pure ori-
gin, but must be thought in terms of the des- NOTES AND REFERENCES
tining of a historical vocation that occurs as
the unfolding of a dialogue with the foreign: 1
Furthermore, Heideggers dialogue with
The Ister is that river in which the foreign Hlderlin needs to be understood in the
is already present as a guest at its source, context of existing Hlderlin scholarship at
that river in whose flowing there constantly the time. For an overview, with particular
reference to the hymn Remembrance, see
speaks the dialogue between ones own and Robert Bernasconi, Poets as Prophets and
the foreign (182). Heideggers own remarks as Painters: Heideggers Turn to Language
break off, not with an assured conclusion as and the Hlderlinian Turn in Context, in
to the historical vocation of the Germans in ed. Jeffrey Powell, Heidegger and Language,
relation to the Greeks, but with an insistence (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2013).
2
In addition to the three major lecture courses
on the need to think through the as yet con- on Hlderlin (published as GA 39, GA 52,
cealed law at work in the relations between and GA 53), and to the collection of essays
The Rhine, The Ister, and Germania. published by Heidegger (GA 4), we also possess
Indeed, the Ister hymn itself breaks off, as a a substantial collection of notes and drafts (GA
sign that makes manifest, yet in such a way 75). Audio recordings of Heidegger reading
Hlderlin are also available (Martin Heidegger
that it simultaneously conceals (202)as Liest Hlderlin, ISBN-10: 3608910484), as is a
a sign that, in the words of Mnemosyne, recording of his 1960 lecture Hlderlins Earth
with which Heidegger concludes the course, and Heaven (Hlderlins Erde und Himmel,
is not read, of a we who have almost ISBN-10: 3608910492). The present essay
lost our tongue in foreign parts. confines itself to providing an overview of the
three lecture courses.
3
The term Grnderjahre, founders years,
refers to the period of rapid industrial expan-
sion in Germany from 18713, following the
Concluding Remarks Franco-Prussian war of 1870.
4
Einfhrung in die Metaphysik (Tbingen:
Niemeyer, 1987), 97. On Nietzsche and
One can readily make the case that Hlderlin Hlderlin, see also Heideggers later remarks in
is Heideggers most important and persist- the 19412 course on Remembrance, GA 52,
ent interlocutor from the mid-1930s on. 789.

234
THE HLDERLIN LECTURES

5
See the remarks below on the first Hlderlin 10
For more on this, see my remarks in An
course. Attunement More Primordial Than Every
6
See also Heideggers essay of the same title, Other Human Attunement: Inaugural Time
... Poetically Man Dwells . . ., delivered in Heidegger and Hlderlin. Paper delivered
as a lecture in 1951 (GA 7, 189208/PLT, at the 2004 meeting of the Heidegger Circle,
21129). hosted by The University of New Orleans and
7
Heidegger in this lecture course generally Louisiana State University. Available to mem-
uses the German Seyn, an archaic form of bers in the conference Proceedings via www.
Sein (being) that was used by Hlderlin, heideggercircle.org.
although his appropriation of this archaic 11
Heidegger goes so far as to situate the brown
spelling is not completely consistent and women of Remembrance in relation to the
Heidegger occasionally reverts to Sein. Seyn German women referred to in Hlderlins
has here been rendered as beyng, which hap- Song to the Germans (GA 52, 7980). An
pens to be an archaic form of the English outraged Adorno complains that Heidegger
being. drags the German women in by the hair. For
8
It is on account of this special relation- a commentary, see David Farrell Krell, The
ship that Heidegger earlier refers to Swaying Skiff of Sea: A Note on Heideggers
the Greek-German dispensation, der and HlderlinsAndenken. Paper delivered
griechisch-deutschen Sendung, out of which at the 2010 meeting of the Heidegger Circle,
thinking must enter its originary dialogue Stony Brook University, Manhattan, New
with poetizing (GA 39, 151). On the centrality York. Available to members in the conference
of the Bhlendorff letter of December 4, 1801 Proceedings via www.heideggercircle.org.
for all three lecture courses on Hlderlin, 12
Heidegger notes that Hlderlin uses the
see Julia A. Ireland, Learning in Dialogue: Greco-Roman name for the lower Danube (in
The Letter to Bhlendorff and Hlderlins German, the Donau) to designate the upper
Conception of History. Paper presented at course of the river, as if the lower Donau had
the 2010 meeting of the Heidegger Circle, returned to the upper, and thus turned back to
Stony Brook University, Manhattan, New its source (GA 53, 10).
York. Available to members in the conference 13
Heideggers course on The Ister has,
Proceedings via www.heideggercircle.org. moreover, inspired a film under the same title,
9
For more details see my remarks in Buried produced and directed by David Barison and
Treasure: Greeting and the Temporality of Daniel Ross. Details can be found at www.
Remembrance in Heideggers Lectures on theister.com.
Andenken. Paper delivered at the 2010 14
Hlderlins words from a late fragment,
meeting of the Heidegger Circle, Stony Brook cited by Heidegger at the outset of the first
University, Manhattan, New York. Available Hlderlin course (GA 39, 4).
to members in the conference Proceedings via 15
Heidegger here refers to lines 94ff. of the hymn
www.heideggercircle.org. The Journey (Die Wanderung).

235
28
The Letter on Humanism:
Ek-sistence, Being, and Language
Andrew J. Mitchell

The famed Letter on Humanism was a letter has provided new avenues for appreciat-
response to French philosopher Jean Beaufret, ing Heideggers thinking, whether by connect-
who wrote to Heidegger on November 10, ing it back to the Renaissance (as per the work
1946 posing a number of questions relating to of Grassi) or running ahead to deconstruc-
the issue of humanism and asking what role, tion (where it figures in Derridas essay The
if any, remains for humanism in Heideggers Ends of Man). It is likewise noteworthy for
thinking. The response, initially entitled On the relation it articulates between ethics and
Humanism: Letter to Jean Beaufret, Paris, ontology, for its considerations of animality,
was Heideggers first publication after the and for its provocative remarks on the holy
Second World War.1 Given that its author was and the divine.
under a teaching ban imposed by the French Granting the importance of these moments
Denazification committee at this time, it could of context and consequence in and for the
be said to be the first public appearance of the Letter, at its heart it is a thorough state-
man Heidegger as well. As such, the Letter ment of the interrelation between the human,
provides Heidegger with a forum for present- being, and language, and it is to this interrela-
ing himself and his thinking anew, something tion that the following will attend. Indeed, the
of which Heidegger takes full advantage. The three are brought together on the very first
letter is at great pains to read Heideggers page, where Heidegger tells us: Language
current thoughts as continuous with what is the house of being. In its accommodation
has gone before. As such, it is a central docu- dwells the human (GA 9, 313/239, tm).
ment in what has been called Heideggers Only by thinking through this constellation
self-interpretation.2 It also provides a forum of human, being, and language can any ques-
for him to publicly demonstrate his ties with tions concerning humanism be addressed.
French philosophy and his lack of animosity in The letter begins by reflecting on thinking
this regard.3 The topic of humanism likewise and its inextricable connection to language
allows him surreptitiously to distance himself (GA 9, 31319/PA, 23944). As thinking and
from a Nazi regime that was roundly con- language have been considered distinctive of
demned as barbarous and inhuman.4 Along the human, the Letter then turns to the issue
with these personal and political contexts, the of humanism, tracing its history through the

237
THE LETTER ON HUMANISM

Renaissance adoption of the Roman appro- or possibility. As Heidegger explains, The


priation of the late-Greek concept of . statement: The human ek-sists is not an
This history is complemented by considera- answer to the question of whether the human
tion of humanisms prevailing at the time, spe- actually is or not; rather, it responds to the
cifically, those of Marxism, existentialism, question concerning the essence of the
and Christianity (GA 9, 31923/PA, 2447). human (GA 9, 327/PA, 249, tm). To address
As all of these address the nature of human Beaufrets question concerning humanism
existence, whether wittingly or not, the next thus requires thinking further into the essence
section of the letter turns to Heideggers own of the human, that is, ek-sistence.
notion of existence (GA 9, 3239/PA, 247 The term itself, ek-sistence, is hyphenated
51). Since this notion of existence relates to so as to emphasize the prefix ek-, and the
beingis, in fact, a relation to beingwhat exteriorization that it entails. Ek-sistence is
follows is a presentation of Heideggers cur- outside of itself. It is ecstatic, as Heidegger
rent understanding of being (GA 9, 32937/ had already observed in Being and Time. And
PA, 2517), including discussion of the for- as that text shows, Dasein has its being to be,
getting of being and the homelessness that it is always already ahead of itself, always
this entails (GA 9, 33744/PA, 25762). After futural. This futural nature of Dasein is coin-
this treatment of human existence and being, cident with its own thrownness. Dasein is
the letter returns to the question of human- thrown into the world, with its being to be,
ism, responding to possible objections to the and in the midst of its thrownness projects its
view (GA 9, 34452/PA, 2628), expounding existence. This way of being is a way of being
some of the ethical consequences of the posi- outside of itself, no longer one condemned
tion reached (GA 9, 35261/PA, 26874), and to the prison house of the ego. It is an ecstatic
concluding as it began with further reflec- existence.
tions on the nature of thinking (GA 9, 3614/ What the Letter proposes, however, is that
PA, 2746). What comes into focus across all we understand this ecstatic ek-sistence now in
of this is a new interrelation between human terms of a standing in. As Heidegger makes
existence, being, and language. plain in the letter, Such standing in the clear-
For Heidegger, humanism has always been a ing of being I call the ek-sistence of the human
concern that the human should remain human, (GA 9, 3234/PA, 247, tm). The human is out-
that is to say, that it keep to its humanity and side of itself, but this does not place it in some
not become inhuman. Humanism is thus a kind of void. Instead, the human that stands
matter of the human retaining its humanity, or out (ek-stasis) is standing in (in-herence) the
rather, its essence: in what does the human- truth of being: the way that the human in
ity of the human being consist? It lies in his his proper essence presences to being is ecstatic
essence (GA 9, 319/PA, 244). And yet pre- inherence [Innestehen] in the truth of being
cisely this essence is what has been distorted (GA 9, 330/PA, 251, tm). We will return to this
by the history of metaphysics, for, according notion of a truth of being presently, for now,
to Heidegger, the essence of the human, let us simply note that to be out is to be in.
lies in its ek-sistence [Ek-sistenz] (GA 9, Indeed, that only by being outside of oneself,
325/PA, 247) and this ek-sistence has been that is, by being no longer encapsulated in an
mischaracterized traditionally as existentia, ego, can one really be exposed to anything at
or the actuality of a subtending essentia, all. Only when the refuge of the ego shell is

238
THE LETTER ON HUMANISM

abandoned, can our ecstatic, exposed exist- Heidegger identifies being in the text as this
ence be permeated by being and stand in it: openness, he [the human] stands out in the
Ek-sisting, he [the human] stands in [steht . . . open of being, which is being itself (GA 9,
in] the dispensation [Geschick] of being (GA 350/PA, 266, tm), or, again, as clearing, the
9, 336/PA, 256, tm). Inherence is another clearing itself is being (GA 9, 332/PA, 253).
name for exposure. Being is the open and the clearing. In this con-
But Dasein would not ecstatically stand in text, truth is equally a term of expansion,
anything at all, if being were not receptive to that is, the truth of being is the breadth of
that stance. Dasein has its being outside of being, hence locutions such as the dimen-
itself, it is inherently ecstatic. But all this is sion of the truth of being, the house of the
so much as to say that the outside in ques- truth of being, and the element of the truth
tion is nothing empty. There is a there there of being, merely to name a few.
(Da-sein). It is the there of being. The ecstatic We might take what Heidegger says at the
existence of Dasein is an entrance into outset of the letter in regards to the element
being. For lack of a better word, being is the as bearing on this entire list of expansive
medium for this ecstatic appearance. And names for being. Heidegger explains that, the
to be sure, one of the most intriguing aspects element is authentically that which enables:
of the Letter is the variety of ways in which the enabling (GA 9, 316/PA, 241, tm). Being
it presents this medial nature of being itself. as element enables beings. It makes them
Being is thought here expansively. Heidegger possible (mglich). But the relation here
alternately speaks of the house of being, the must be more carefully understood, instead
nearness of being, the clearing of being, of a making crudely construed, it is more of
the light of being, the open of being, and a letting be, it lets beings essence, using the
being as the element (in the sense of ones word as a verb. Being as element is what lets
fitting environs). In all these senses, what is at beings be what they are and lets them be this
stake is not something contained, but instead essentially. This sense of essence is a way
a realm, an arena, a field of appearance. In of being of these beings. It is a way of being
what follows, I will refer to being in this sense that affiliates (mgen) them to the medium,
as a medium for appearing, though the to being. In so doing, beings exhibit a certain
term will require some elaboration to defend relationality. When beings are construed as
against understanding it as simply a space objects situated in a void and standing apart
between otherwise present entities. from a subject, there is no relation, only
Given this expansive, medial character, encapsulation. Heidegger notes in the text
Heidegger can write, being is essentially how the dominance of subjectivity leads
broader [weiter] than all beings and is equally to the metaphysically conditioned establish-
nearer to the human than any being (GA 9, ment and authorization of the openness of
331/PA, 252, tm), adding later so is being beings in the unconditional objectification of
essentially broader [weiter] than all beings, everything (GA 9, 317/PA, 242). And never-
because it is the clearing itself (GA 9, 337/ theless, what something is in its being is not
PA, 256). The breadth of being is its expan- exhausted by its being an object (GA 9, 349/
sive character. Being is not a being. But it is PA, 265, tm). There is more to the being of
also not without relation to beings. Being things than objectivity. This surplus is its rela-
is an expanse for appearance, a medium. tion or affiliation to being, its belonging to its

239
THE LETTER ON HUMANISM

element. This relationality is prior to objecti- the dispensed. What is dispensed, however,
fication. It occurs within the openness [die is being. Now every giving, every dispensa-
Offenheit] of being, within the open region tion, is a testament to the distance traversed.
[Offene] that first clears the between within We are reached by what is given both despite
which a relation of subject to object can and on account of that distance. Thus every
be (GA 9, 350/PA, 266, tm). giving requires that something be held back,
In this thinking of the element of being, the such that this distance may be marked. In
element that makes beings possible, Heidegger the words of the letter: Being comes to its
recasts the notion of a condition of possibil- dispensation in that It, being, gives itself.
ity in terms of a letting be whereby the par- But this says, thought dispensationally: It
ticular being is affiliated to the medium in gives itself and refuses itself simultaneously
which it appears. Such a condition of possi- (GA 9, 335/PA, 255, tm). Only through such
bility is not indifferent to that which appears a refusal can it reach us at all. It reaches us
within it. Being and beings are affiliated and without ever becoming entirely present. It
held in a relation to one another (this is the comes extended in this way, spaced from us.
importance of the etymological connection It comes, in short, as a clearing: This dispen-
between medium as enabling, vermgen, sation takes place as the clearing of being
the possible, das Mgliche, and affiliation, (GA 9, 337/PA, 257, tm). Put more elabo-
mgen). Ek-sistence does not stand in a void, rately: only so long as the clearing of being
but participates in a medium. That medium takes place does being convey itself to human
is being. But it is not a medium in the sense beings. But the fact that the Da, the clearing
of an independent, indifferent third thing (or as the truth of being itself, takes place is the
void) that would intervene between two oth- sending [Schickung] of being itself. This is
erwise present entities. Instead, the medium the dispensation [Geschick] of the clearing
likes what appears in it, lets it essence. (GA 9, 336/PA, 257, tm).
But it is not enough to construe being as The dispensation is also thought by
a medium in this way. Being might still Heidegger in terms of a claim (Anspruch),
seem a container for ek-sistence. Indeed, for something that metaphysics in its objectifying
the ecstaticity of ek-sistence, being can be no tendencies is unable to hear: Metaphysics
void, but it can likewise be no plenum either. excludes the simple essential condition that
If ek-sistence is exposed and permeated by the human only essences in its essence in
being, then that being cannot be stagnant, it that it is addressed [angesprochen] by being.
must be always arriving. Heidegger thinks Only from out of this claim [Anspruch]
this in terms of a sending, whereby being is has he found that wherein his essence
given or sent to us, not so as to have already resides (GA 9, 323/PA, 247, tm). Ecstatic
arrived in full, but as being underway, arriv- Ek-sistence resides in a medium always
ing at us. His term for this is Geschick, which addressing it, encroaching on it, pouring
is typically rendered fate or destiny, both in on it. Ek-sistence is immersion, properly
fitting terms, but terms that tend to obscure understood. The coming of being can like-
the connection with sending (schicken). wise be cast in terms of an arriving (being as
Thus, in what follows, Geschick shall be ren- das Ankommende), with Heidegger observ-
dered dispensation with the understanding ing that thinking is related to being as to
that ones fate lies in an accommodation to what arrives (lavenant) (GA 9, 363/PA,

240
THE LETTER ON HUMANISM

275). Indeed, thinking is nothing other than traditional construal as language of a subject
exposing oneself to this arrival and letting (understood on the basis of the animal ration-
oneself be marked (claimed) by it. The mark ale, see GA 9, 333/PA, 254). They do not insist
of the claim is attested in language. on language as means of expediting informa-
Language names the interface between tion transfer, but allow it to trace the contour
ek-sistence and the coming of being. of eksistence and being, to be shaped by that
Heideggers concern in the Letter with juncture and announce that contact. They are
thinking is ultimately a concern with lan- the guardians of the house, as Heidegger
guage. Thinking, the metaphysical privilege explains, Those who think and poetize are
of the human, is an exposing of oneself to the guardians [Wchter] of this accommoda-
the dispensation, claim, and arriving of being tion. Their guardianship [Wachen] accom-
such that this advent be brought to language. plishes [Vollbringen] the openness of being,
Heidegger could not be more clear: To bring insofar as they bring this to language through
to language ever and again this arriving of their saying and preserve it [aufbewahren] in
being [Ankunft des Seins] . . . is the sole matter language (GA 9, 313/PA, 239, tm).
of thinking (GA 9, 363/PA, 275, tm). Indeed, By guarding (wahren) and preserving (auf-
for being to arrive at all, for there to be a bewahren), a protected space (a house and
sending, it must be remarked. Otherwise there accommodation) is created. Within the space
would be oblivion. Language is thus more of this protectionotherwise known as
than an ex post facto testament to the arrival truth (Wahrheit)what appears does so as
of being, it is that arriving itself: Language is protected. The true (das Wahre) is protected
the clearing-concealing arriving [Ankunft] of (bewahrt). The claim of being that reaches
being itself (GA 9, 326/PA, 249, tm). the human, the call of being, is a call to par-
If language is the efflorescence of this ticipate in such protection, the truth of being.
contact between ecstatic ek-sistence and the The question of humanism and human
dispensation of being, the effulgence of the dignity must be reoriented around this fact.
interface between these two movements, The human becomes shepherd: The human
all language becomes testimony. Language is the shepherd of being . . . whose dignity
is the preservation of this event. As such, it consists in being called by being itself into
entails a sheltering function, as in the famous the guardianship of its truth [Wahrnis seiner
claim from the very first page of the letter: Wahrheit] (GA 9, 342/PA, 260, tm). To hear
Language is the house [Haus] of being. In the call is to let oneself be addressed by the
its accommodation [Behausung] dwells the claim of being and thus to attest to the ecsta-
human (GA 9, 313/PA, 239, tm). ticity of ek-sistence. To hear the call is to be
But what language preserves of this event struck by it and as a human this means to
must itself be protected. For under the reign bring it into language.
of subjectivity, language falls into the serv- In all we have said, being has marked itself
ice of expediting communication along routes in language. At the close of the letter, however,
where objectificationthe uniform accessibil- Heidegger suggests a reciprocal movement
ity of everything to everyonebranches out whereby thinking sets its mark in language,
and disregards all limits (GA 9, 317/PA, 242). too: With its saying, thinking lays incon-
Thinkers and poets are the ones who attend spicuous furrows in language. They are still
to language in a way that breaks with its more inconspicuous than the furrows that

241
THE LETTER ON HUMANISM

the farmer, slow of step, draws through the its second billing in the volume (the title page
field (GA 9, 364/PA, 276). Language attests identifies the volume as Platos Doctrine of Truth
with a Letter on Humanism), is actually much
to the belonging together of the human and
longer than the essay it follows (66 pages for the
being. Any humanism must begin from this. letter vs. 47 for the essay).
2
The Letter is a strongly retrospective affair,
with Heidegger referencing all of his pub-
NOTES AND REFERENCES lished works from Being and Time to date.
Indeed, he cites Being and Time no less than
It was first published in the 1947 volume Platos
1
30 times in the course of the essay, along
Doctrine of Truth (Bern: Verlag A. Francke, with Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics,
1947), as something of an appendix behind What Is Metaphysics? On the Essence of
a reprinting of the title essay on Plato from Reason, and On the Essence of Truth. On
1942. A headnote to the volume states: The equal footing with these works he also cites
attached letter is to Jean Beaufret (Paris) as all four of the Hlderlin essays he had pub-
a response to questions posed in his letter of lished up to this point. Indeed, the only major
November 10, 1946. The questions arose from publication that is not cited is the infamous
the French translation of the lecture [Platos Rectoral address, The Self-Assertion of the
Doctrine of Truth] prepared by Josef Rovan German University, though critical refer-
(Platons Lehre, 4). Beaufrets letter to Heidegger ence is made in the letter to collectivism as
is printed in Franois Fdier, LHumanisme en completing the unconditional self-assertion
Question: Pour aborder la lecture de la Lettre [Selbstbehauptung] of individualism (GA 9,
sur lhumanisme de Martin Heidegger (Paris: 3412). On Heideggers self-interpretation as
Les ditions du Cerf, 2012), 1415. Platos a whole, see Friedrich Wilhelm von Herrmann,
Doctrine of Truth was a volume in the series Die Selbstinterpretation Martin Heideggers
berlieferung und Auftrag (Tradition and (Meisenheim am Glan: Anton Hain, 1964).
Mission) edited by Ernesto Grassi and Wilhelm 3
The French connection is well documented. The
Szilasi. Grassi had previously published the Plato seminal work in this is Dominique Janicaud,
essay in the second issue of his journal Geistige Heidegger en France, 2 vols. (Paris: Hachette
berlieferung (Spiritual Tradition). Nevertheless, Littratures, 2005). A key text is also Frdric
due to the circumstances of the war, a reprint- de Towarnicki, la rencontre de Heidegger:
ing of the essay was in order. Heidegger himself Souvenirs dun messager de la Fort-Noire
pointed to the treatment of this essay as evidence (Paris: Gallimard, 1993). Details surround-
of the antagonism between him and the National ing the Letter can also be found in Fdier,
Socialist party. In a November 11, 1945 letter Lhumanisme en question.
to the rectoral committee of his university, 4
There is not much to be directly gleaned
Heidegger cites a National Socialist directive about his relation to National Socialism in the
that states: The essay by Martin Heidegger, Letter. He makes critical comment of the
Platos Doctrine of Truth, in the Journal for self-assertion (Selbstbehauptung) of individu-
Spiritual Tradition, shortly to appear with alism, which could be seen as a retort to his
Helmut Kpper Publishers, Berlin, shall be nei- own Rectoral Address, The Self-Assertion of
ther reviewed nor named. Heideggers participa- the German University (see GA 9, 3412/PA,
tion in this second volume of the journal, which 260), and he closes the letter with words that
otherwise can be thoroughly discussed, is not to could apply to his own silence regarding the
be mentioned (GA 16, 403). The headnote to events of the war. The fittingness of thought-
the 1947 volume repeats these claims, mention ful saying, he writes, requires that we ponder
in the press and review was forbidden, publica- whether what is to be thought is to be saidto
tion as a separate printing was likewise denied what extent, at what moment of the history of
(Platons Lehre, 4). Grassi thus had some reason being, in what sort of dialogue with this history,
to see to a second publication of the essay five and on the basis of what claim, it ought to be
years after its first appearance. The letter, despite said (GA 9, 363/PA, 276).

242
29
The Bremen Lectures
Andrew J. Mitchell

Heideggers 1949 Bremen lecture cycle, separating the juvenilia from the works of
Insight into That Which Is, stands along- fundamental ontology, for example, or the
side the early Being and Time (1927), and rectoral texts from the esoteric notebooks
the mid-period Contributions to Philosophy and the exoteric lecture courses of the late
(19368), as a third, decisive milestone along 1930s and early1940s, or, lastly, distinguish-
Heideggers path of thought. Comprised of ing the work of the 1960s, that is, the home-
four lecturesThe Thing, Positionality, land speeches and aesthetic investigations
The Danger, and The TurnInsight (signally, of sculpture) from the immedi-
into That Which Is combines provoca- ately postwar period of the fourfold running
tive flair with an unflinching assessment of through the 1950s. Nevertheless, the heuris-
the times. While situating Insight into That tic benefits of such a rough division warrants
Which Is alongside Being and Time and the this simplified, tripartitioned approach to
Contributions to Philosophy might first Heideggers remarkable path of thought.
appear hyperbolic, Heidegger himself puts The Bremen lectures are Heideggers first
great stock in these lectures.1 Indeed, as lecture appearance after the Second World
Heideggers first public appearance after the War, held while he was under a teaching
war, the Bremen lectures inaugurate his later ban imposed by the French authorities in the
thinking. wake of the war. As such, they were held at
In saying that the Bremen lectures are no university, but instead at the private Club
the inauguration of Heideggers late zu Bremen, which, as one contemporary put
thought, I have a rough tripartite periodi- it, was made up of big businessmen, spe-
zation of Heideggers work in mind: early cialists in overseas commerce, and directors
(191232, culminating in Being and Time, of shipping lines and dockyards.2 To this
1927), middle (193344, centering around audience, then, Heidegger delivered what an
the Contributions to Philosophy, 19368), attending reviewer called the boldest state-
and late or postwar (194576, taking its ment of his thinking.3 To be sure, while
orientation from Insight Into That Which Is, Heidegger already had published something
1949). While these are not arbitrary catego- after the war, the Letter on Humanism of
rizations, their bounds are not rigidly fixed 1947, this text was largely retrospective (see
either. Indeed, good cases could be made the entry on the Letter elsewhere in this
for further dividing each of these periods: volume) and, as Heidegger himself says in an

243
THE BREMEN LECTURES

opening note to the letter, the letter contin- Heidegger this world is one that has been
ues to speak in the language of metaphysics, claimed by technology.
and does so knowingly (GA 9, 313 n. a/P The second lecture in the cycle,
239 n. a). As we have seen, with The Thing Positionality, details the nature of a world
(and the Bremen lectures more generally), so claimed. He first coins the term position-
Heidegger announces his thinking on its ality (das Ge-Stell) in this lecture as naming
own terms. It is also worth noting that the the very essence of technology. Positionality
Letter makes no overt mention of the war, institutes the regime of requisitioning (das
whereas the Bremen lectures address the war Bestellen), whereby all that is becomes trans-
at its most horrifying, with Heidegger infa- formed into so much standing reserve (das
mously discussing the concentration camps Bestand), replaceable commodities utterly
themselves. Despite the (merely) chrono- available for ordering and delivery along
logical precedence of the Letter, then, it is supply routes of unending circulation. The
Insight into That Which Is that stands as the standing reserve is the mode of presence
inauguration of Heideggers postwar or for all that exists under the dominance of
late thinking. contemporary technology and it is the only
In the Bremen lectures, Heidegger offers permissible mode: In positionality, the pres-
a concrete ontology of existence within a encing of all that presences becomes standing
world given over to contemporary technol- reserve (GA 79, 32/BF 31). What circulates
ogy. It is here, in the opening lecture The under the aegis of positionality is no longer
Thing that Heidegger first introduces the object, but instead the standing reserve.
the term fourfold (das Geviert), which Heidegger could not be more clear on this
is the key to his new understanding of the point: Nature is no longer even an object
thing (see the entry under fourfold in [Gegen-stand] (GA 79, 44/BF 41). The
this volume). Understanding the thing as object, as Gegenstand, requires an over and
arising from a gathering of the fourfold against (a gegen) in which to stand. This
means understanding the thing as noth- space of the gegen, for its part, names a dis-
ing self-enclosed or encapsulated. Rather, tance between subject and object, the space
the thing is now understood as opened and of representation. But it is precisely this dis-
spilling over into relations with what lies tance that is put in question by positionality.
beyond it. Things are defined relationally Instead of a space between subject and object,
and in sustaining these relations and being there is now a suffusion into that space and a
sustained by them in turn; things are singu- smothering of the difference between subject
lar, unique. What makes a thing the unique and object in the general transformation into
thing it is, is its place within this network standing reserve. No space is unclaimed or
of mutually supportive relations. The thing off limits. Nearly 25 years later in the 1973
is nothing self-same and self-present but seminar in Zhringen, Heidegger remains
essentially defined by what lies outside of it. true to this insight, describing how the human
Things are contextual, open. But this same has gone from the epoch of objectivity
openness that singularizes the thing and by [Gegenstndlichkeit] to that of orderability
which the thing relates to what lies beyond it [Bestellbarkeit]. . . . Strictly speaking, there
also entails that what lies beyond the thing, are no longer objects (GA 15, 388/FS, 74).
the world, now relates back to it. And for In the words of the Bremen lectures where

244
THE BREMEN LECTURES

the idea is first forged: Where the standing claim that beyng is unqualifiedly in itself,
reserve comes into power, even the object from itself, for itself, the danger (GA 79,
crumbles as characteristic of what presences 54/BF, 51). This self-diremption within being
(GA 79, 26/BF, 25). has been broached by Heidegger before. It
That the fourfold would be thought in was the most secretive thing that Hlderlin
conjunction with technology is nothing could say in the first Hlderlin lecture course
accidental. Indeed, for Heidegger it is the of 1934, the innermost contrariety in beings
fourfold that grants the thing its relational as a whole . . . the highest questionability in
character, a relationality that likewise singu- the essence of beyng (GA 39, 269). In the
larizes the thing. When each thing is opened 1946 essay on Anaximander, it was cast in
to the world around it, stands in contextu- terms of an insurrection on the part of
alizing relations with this world, and when beings themselves (GA 5, 356/OBT, 268,
those relations are essential to the thing tm). Despite these precursors, however, noth-
itself, then the place of the thing within this ing could prepare the listener for the griz-
world becomes irreplaceable. Or rather, the zly reckoning with the times that Heidegger
relational thing is specified and singularized would now detail:
through these relations. Things are unique.
But Heidegger now sees the essence of tech- Hundreds of thousands die in masses.
nology to lie in the circulation of standing Do they die? They perish. They are put
reserve (das Bestand), wherein one piece of down. Do they die? They become pieces
of inventory of a standing reserve for the
standing reserve is replaceable by another.
fabrication of corpses. Do they die? They
And it is the essence of technology to drive
are unobtrusively liquidated in annihila-
for its own expansion. Thus an essential ten- tion camps. And even apart from such as
sion exists between the singularity of the thesemillions now in China abjectly
thing and the replaceability of the standing end in starvation. (GA 79, 56/BF, 53)
reserve.
The third lecture, The Danger, locates These stand as Heideggers first words on
this tension within beyng itself. The conflict the aftermath of the war, startling words
of singularity and replacement is no acciden- that have garnered Heidegger condemnation
tal misfortune that has befallen our world. since long before their first publication in
Rather, the technological challenge to things German in 1994. When it is even acknowl-
is effected by being itself. Along with requi- edged that Heidegger is here drawing out the
sitioning (Bestellen), then, Heidegger identi- full consequences of the self-pursuit of being,
fies pursuit (Nachstellen) as determinative of of a world given over to technological com-
contemporary existence, the pursuit whereby modification, Heideggers claim is taken as
beyng pursues itself with its own forgetting. cold and indifferent. The careful phrasing
This forgetting is a mistaking of the thing as and rhetorical force of the passage says oth-
something immediately available, as without erwise. These are not the words of a business
the medium through which its relations might report, they are shocking and unsettling and
stream, as apart from the medium of truth are so intended. An insight into that which is
(Wahrheit), as suffering an ontological kind demands it.
of neglect or unguarding (Verwahrlosung). The last lecture, The Turn, shows that
Heidegger can thus make the provocative the source of the technological danger in

245
THE BREMEN LECTURES

being means that a relation to technology is a fresh start. It would leave metaphysics
a relation to being. The turn is from a false behind. There would be a new fully present
belief in the annihilation of being by technol- order separated by a gap of pure absence
ogy to an understanding of existence as never from a now outdated order that is com-
so pinioned between the false alternatives of pletely left behind. That is to say, this think-
presence or absence. The turn effects a think- ing of sequentiality reiterates the very motifs
ing of nonpresence, of the trace, we might say of metaphysics, specifically the oppositional
(to take up a vocabulary Heidegger employs thinking of presence and absence, that it
in the 1946 text What Are Poets For? as seeks to escape. Heideggers name for this
well as his earlier Hlderlin readings). It is failed and ultimately metaphysical project is
in these pages that Heidegger first brings overcoming (berwindung). He contrasts
Hlderlin into conversation with contem- it with converting (Verwindung), a term
porary technology, famously citing the cou- that likewise makes its first public appear-
plet: But where the danger is, there grows/ ance in Heideggers work with the Bremen
also what saves (cited at GA 79, 72/BF, 68). lecture The Turn. Through conversion
The insight proclaimed in the lecture cycles metaphysics is not left behind, but instead
title is this very insight into the transitional, taken to its limit, shown that it has a limit,
relational, and endangered existence of all that all supposed closure is really an expo-
that is. Where an appendix to The Thing sure, that the same line that encloses like-
informed us that things have never yet been wise exposes, that closure is impossible, that
as things (GA 79, 23/BF, 22), we now see we dwell in this between.
the reason for this. The thing is nothing To understand how this configuration
apart from the threat of its replacement. of singularity and replacement marks the
Singularity demands this. Relationality can- Bremen lectures as inaugurating Heideggers
not remove itself from the world, but must later thought, a brief look at the situation
engage with it at its most essential level. Only in his middle period is revealing. We will
in so doing can there be things at all, things take the Contributions to Philosophy (Of the
that are nothing present and self-evident, but Event) and the essay The Age of the World
things that are always ever not yet things. Picture as representative here. Simply stated,
The insight into that which is is an insight Heideggers middle period is a thinking of,
into that which is not yet. Heidegger thinks and worry over, modernist objectification.
the belonging together of technology and the With the Bremen lectures, Heidegger achieves
fourfold, standing reserve and thing. a position of postmodern commodification
What this means is that the thing is (replaceability).
always endangered, always further com- In this middle period of the mid- to late
modifiable and assailable. But it also entails 1930s, Heidegger first comes to understand
that this process can never be completed. being (beyng) as essentially defined by with-
Were it to be so we would be relieved of all drawal. Beings, for their part, are understood
responsibility. Heideggers refusal to think in as concomitantly abandoned, where aban-
such black and white alternatives means we donment names a way of essencing that
always remain a part of the world, open to is not entirely present (what is abandoned
its appeal. Were the thing simply to thing, maintains a relation to something outside
it would be a new order, a new beginning, of it that it essentially does not possess, its

246
THE BREMEN LECTURES

abandoner, we might provisionally say). The danger for the human in this is accord-
Against this understanding of a withdrawn ingly that of understanding oneself in terms
and abandoning beyng, however, against this of objectified lived experience (Erlebnis).
strange and newly framed essencing of beyng, Under the reign of machination, experience
Heidegger poses the object, objectification. itself is objectified. The human is delivered
The antagonist of the middle period, in over to a sham world of objectified experi-
other words, the great danger facing us, is ences that may be hoarded and possessed.
that of objectification. For this reason the They are available for the taking by the
Contributions can be said to remain within intrepid adventurer. As he notes, The being
a modernist framework. counts first as extant, insofar as and to the
In the Contributions, Heidegger observes extent that it is included in and related back
that beings are abandoned to the world, and to this life, i.e., is experienced in life [er-lebt]
this means they are abandoned into machina- and becomes lived experience [Erlebnis] (GA
tion, which many would see as a proto form of 5, 94/OBT, 71, tm). Heideggers vitriol in the
Heideggers thinking of technology. Nothing Contributions over movies and trips to the
could be further from the truth. In regard to beach should be understood in this regard
abandoned beings, the Contributions make (GA 65, 139/CP, 109). The Contributions is
clear that, as so abandoned, the being a thinking of objectification.
then appears thus, it shows itself as object With the Bremen lectures, all this changes.
and present-at-hand, as if beyng did not The Second World War provided Heidegger
essence (GA 65, 115/CP, 91, tm, empha- with insight into the consumption of all
sis modified). Machination thus names the beings in the service of what Ernst Jnger
constellation of forces that struggle for the termed a total mobilization. The human,
objectification and presence of the world at too, was now enrolled in cycles of consump-
the time of the Contributions. Beings are rep- tion like any other raw material, as the
resentationally objective in that text, as per war made gruesomely clear. This experience
Heideggers understanding of machination undergirds Heideggers later writing, start-
there as machination, that interpretation ing with the Bremen lectures. It is in these
of beings as re-presentable and re-presented that the war is first registered in his lectures
[Vor-stellbaren und Vor-Gestellten] (GA or publications.4 The insight that agricul-
65, 1089/CP, 86). The essay The Age of ture is now a mechanized food industry,
the World Picture makes the connection in essence the same as the production of
explicit: This objectification of beings is corpses in the gas chambers and extermi-
accomplished in a setting-before, a repre- nation camps is light years away from a
senting [Vor-stellen], aimed at bringing each worry over people visiting the beach (GA
being before it in such a way that the person 79, 27/BF, 27). The Bremen lectures conse-
who calculates can be sure, and that means quently inaugurate Heideggers late work
be certain, of the being (GA 5, 87/OBT, 66, as explicitly postwar, and the thinking of
tm). Indeed, representation so dominates the replacement that he undertakes in these, as
age that only what is represented is admit- opposed to modernist objectification, makes
ted as true or extant, so construed, only them postmodern as well.
what becomes an object is, that is, counts as Heideggers genius in the Bremen lectures
extant (GA 5, 87/OBT, 66, tm). is to refuse to separate the two economies of

247
THE BREMEN LECTURES

singularity (the thing) and replacement (the NOTES AND REFERENCES


standing reserve) as two separate orders of
being. The thing does not come after the 1
See the letter to Sinn, cited in the entry to The
standing reserve. There is no epoch of the Fourfold elsewhere in this volume, where
Heidegger notes that The Thing is the only
thing that would follow upon that of techno- time he published his thinking as expressed on
logical positionality and in which we would its own terms. As The Thing opens the cycle
finally be at-home. Instead, Heidegger Insight into That Which Is and indeed depicts
insists on the tension between the two, the necessary counter force to technological
between the thing and the standing reserve, replaceability as detailed in the second and
third lectures of the cycle, it would seem that
positionality and the fourfold, Gestell und the Bremen lectures as a whole would most
Geviert, the danger and what saves. In sum, fully express Heideggers thinking on its own
it is not that there is something salvatory terms.
somewhere apart from an external danger 2
The businessman F. W. Oezle, cited in Heinrich
that we happen to have fallen into. Rather Wiegand Petzet, Auf einen Stern zugehen:
Begegnungen mit Martin Heidegger 1929 bis
Heidegger thinks the danger and the saving 1976 (Frankfurt am Main: Societts Verlag,
together. A proper appreciation of this means 1983), 59. English translation: Encounters&
thinking from the between, thinking in terms Dialogues with Martin Heidegger, trans.
of traces. This is the way of thinking that is Parvis Emad and Kenneth Maly (Chicago: The
truly postmodern for Heidegger, a thinking University of Chicago Press, 1993), 53.
3
Egon Vietta, cited in Petzet, Auf einen Stern
of the between (and not simply the simulta- zugehen, 62/56.
neity of oppositions, each internally coherent 4
To be sure, the war plays a role in the Evening
in itself, in a kind of duck-rabbit coupling). Conversation of 1945 in the Country
It is neither an either/or nor a both/and as Path Conversations, but this text remained
there are no longer present-at-hand relata unpublished until its appearance in the
Gesamtausgabe in 1995. Another 1945 text,
standing outside the relation to be brought Poverty, also addresses the war, but this was
together or separated apart in a manner that an extremely private lecture spoken before a
never compromises their self-identity. There handful of people in no official context. The
is instead relationality. The Bremen lectures Bremen lectures are the first public declaration.
present Heideggers fullest account of such The first mention in print will be in his contri-
bution to the exhibition catalog of the sculptor
an existence and one that remains determi- Ernst Barlach in 1951 (subsequently included
native for the rest of the way along his path as section 24 of Overcoming Metaphysics in
of thought. the 1954 volume Vortrge und Aufstze).

248
30
Later Essays and Seminars
Lee Braver

Heidegger changed his mind; that is why modulates it into other keys or even crosses
we speak of a later Heidegger. The simple it out in favor of other terms. But that is one
division between an early and a later phase of the strange things about Being and Time
the arrangement that initially structured there is far more time in it than being. He tells
Heidegger studiesis now generally seen as us from the outset that he wants to reawaken
too stark. For one thing, over his 80 years the question of being rather than provide an
of thinking Heidegger changed his mind a answer, to revive a long-dormant puzzlement
lot, not just once. Almost every decade of rather than settle it, and in this aim he has
his career a new topic surfaces as the central surely succeeded. The part that was to have
idea that gets retrospectively read back into dealt directly with beingdivision III of part
not just his own previous work but into the onewas never published, making it impos-
history of Western civilization. However, the sible to construct a substantive continuity
turning that took place around 1930 is between his early and late work on his views
sharper and deeper than the later transitions. about being.
Nor need we exaggerate this change into While the continuities are vague and
a complete break that repudiates his early sketchy, we find ideas in the later work that
work. Of course there are continuities. Later are either absent from or that even directly
and early Heidegger are both recognizably, conflict with the early. I want to lay out here,
indeed unmistakably, Heidegger. But these as clearly and directly as I canas becomes
continuities are incomplete. Being and Time a good companionthe main topics of
contains an important discussion of truth, Heideggers later work and, more briefly,
for example, which already makes the cru- how they differ from his earlier views.
cial move of defining it as unconcealment.
But these 20-odd pages are a far cry from
the extensive, complex, historically informed
discussions of the topic in the 1930s, and Style
throughout the rest of his career.
Of course, the primary continuitythe Perhaps the first thing that strikes the reader
primary fact about Heideggers thought in about the later works is how hard they are.
generalis the question of being. He never This may be the second and third thing too
strays far from this home key, even when he and, all too often, the last thing as well.

249
LATER ESSAYS AND SEMINARS

Hard does not do them justicemore them. People, for example, have a very differ-
than impenetrable, they seem to actively ent way of being than chairs, which is why we
resist comprehension, like a hermeneutically talk to and ask permission of the former but
repulsive magnetic field. Being and Time sit on the latter (Kant made this distinction
is difficultyou have to master a whole between persons and objects central to his
vocabulary in order to read itbut it is rec- ethics). Perhaps the main point of the book as
ognizably philosophical in form and con- we have it is that we inappropriately tend to
tent. With the proper background, the book interpret both of these kinds of beings in the
becomes a bit of an Easter egg hunt for ideas manner of a third typebare inert objects.
plucked from predecessors: one spies a bit of Now Heidegger maintains this framework
Kierkegaard here mixed in with a splash of in his later work, although he adds more
Hegel there, with a sprinkle of Aristotle over modes of being: artworks and technology,
the lotand that is just one chapter! for example, and what he calls things,
When one reads the later work, on the which are very different from objects. But he
other hand, it is hard to know where to also adds to the ontological difference a third
beginor to middle or end. Here too, master- layer that barely appears in Being and Time,
ing the vocabulary helps immensely although which he sometimes calls being itself or the
his favorite words keep evolving. Perhaps truth of being. This means the manifestation
the single best advice to reading Heidegger of beings to us, the fact that we can become
is to take him at his word, that being is the aware at all. This clearing was the defining
skeleton key to all philosophy, especially his. feature of Dasein in the early work, but there
Unlike Being and Time, which the reader can he explains our awareness by appealing to
get quite a bit out of without paying much our nature, the way philosophers like Kant
attention to being, it is hard to advance a and Husserl do. It is because we are the kinds
single step in the later volumes without a of creatures that we are and because we do
solid grasp of it. With a graspwell, it is still the kinds of things that we do that beings
tough going, but progress can be had, so let show up for us at all, and in the specific ways
us turn to being. that they do. The later work turns this for-
mulation around: it is because beings show
up for us and in the specific ways that they
do that we are the kinds of creatures that we
Being are and do the kinds of things that we do.
Being is something that happens to us rather
Being and Time teaches us the ontological than something we do, even autonomically.
distinction between beings and being, which This, along with the dynamic connotation, is
is more straightforward than it sounds. why he comes to use the term Ereignis: being
Beings are just what you think they arethe manifesting itself is an event in which we are
various entities that populate our livesand caught up rather than an act we perform.
being means the kind of entities that they are. This changes everything. Being and Time
It is quite close to the traditional notion of works out fundamental ontology, which
essence, though more dynamic: things actively founds the study of being on a grasp of our-
are or, in a sense, behave in certain ways that selves since being, in a Kantian way, is a pro-
determine what is appropriate to do with jection of our nature. It is our use of tools that

250
LATER ESSAYS AND SEMINARS

structures them as ready-to-hand; they change dismantles this emphasis, even its coherence, as
over to presence-at-hand when we stop to he comes to see it as a symptom of our age that
study them. The later work reverses funda- he associates with Nietzsche and technology.
mental ontology into an ontological founda- Heidegger studies many thinkers exten-
tion: everything must be understood in light sively, but Nietzsche ranks as one of the most
of the fact and way that being appears to us. important. Heidegger spent four years teach-
The later work as a whole can be described ing him and left 1,200 pages of surprisingly
as working out the consequences of this one readable lecture notes. He argues that after the
insight, which is why he says that, the pri- pre-Socratics, for whom he has a great affin-
mal mystery for all thinking is concealed in ity, Plato instituted a fundamental distinction
Parmenides phrase, for there is Being (BW, between appearing and being, between how
238). Heidegger patiently, doggedly, takes up we experience reality and what it is really
one topic after another and works out new like. This distinction instigates metaphysics
understandings of them in light of this idea. as the search for true reality beyond mere
Let us examine a few of the most important. appearance, and while this project has gone
through many forms, it has always remained
true to this basic approach. What counts as
appearance and what counts as real and how
The Will, Nietzsche, and we distinguish the two has fluctuated consid-
Technology erably, but the formal distinction and the goal
have stayed the same throughout.
There are debates about how to read Nietzsche represents the other bookend to
Heideggers early view of authenticity and the the history of metaphysics, bringing it to a
will, as there are debates about most of his close by ringing the final variation on Platos
positions, but I read him as basically an exis- appearance-being duality. His is the final vari-
tentialist voluntarist. This means that, largely ation because it directly reverses Plato, mak-
inspired by Kierkegaard, he believed that we ing the empirical, changing world the one that
passively drift through our lives, acquiescing is really real and the intellectual, eternally
unquestioningly in our societys values until stable Ideas mere whiffs of smoke, dreamed
something shakes us from this complacency. up to render the mob more governable. This
This interruption can be a mid-life crisis, a reversal draws metaphysics to a close, allowing
bout of depression, or just the vivid dawn- us to pursue fundamentally different forms of
ing of ones mortality, but afterwards one can thought while keeping Nietzsche himself stuck
explicitly decide upon how to live ones life within it, insofar as just reversing appearance
rather than just doing what one does. and reality still retains the distinction.
This ethics obviously places great empha- Nietzsche believes that traditional values
sis on the making of explicit decisions. While have been supported by superstition, religion,
Heidegger rejects the possibility of a transcend- and metaphysics (among which he sees little
ent perspective that could validate particular difference) and, with their demise, the old val-
ways of living as objectively or absolutely right, ues are fading as well. We can no longer believe
he does praise choosing to choose (GA 2, in objective values; we project them onto the
270/BT, 314) as the right way to approach the world much the way Kant has us injecting cat-
problem. Much of his later work, however, egories like time or causality into experience.

251
LATER ESSAYS AND SEMINARS

Nietzsche thinks we have always been the and ourselves is incoherent. Thought for
creators of meaning but now that we realize it, Heidegger is essentially a response to what
we can take control of this process and delib- solicits it.1 We think about what attracts our
erately forge more life-affirming values. attention, what calls out for thoughta
This is to treat values as a kind of technology, different translation of the title usually ren-
broadly understood. Heideggers analysis of dered as What Is Called Thinking. We dream
technology is more concerned with an attitude of self-creation. Descartes complained bitterly
or mentality than the proliferation of gadgets. of the way he had unquestioningly accepted
These are just a symptom of a deeper under- beliefs as a child. He never really thought
lying mindset that treats all inconveniences or about them so, in a way, he did not believe
obstacles as things to be taken care of. If some- them; he just ran across them in his head as
thing keeps us from getting what we want, he rummaged around. He must empty his
then we should roll up our sleeves and come head of these merely found elements in order
up with a way to remove it. Fixing problems to reconstitute his belief system under his
often involves making devices, which is why control, with his express consent, and those
electronic tools share the name, but the essence beliefs will truly be his. The self that is made
of technology goes much deeper and pervades of them will truly be him. Nietzsche seeks an
virtually all aspects of our lives. Descartes, amor fati that will reconcile himself to the
for example, was an arch-technologist even fact that he did not will his own past.
though he lived before modern devices. He But what beliefs does Descartes accept into
saw that Medieval ways of thinking were that epistemologically sterile operating room?
not getting the job, were not getting us good Those that he finds so persuasive that he sim-
medicine or machinery, so he set about con- ply cannot doubt. Clear and distinct percep-
structing a new way of thinking. He correctly tions are those whose siren song he cannot
intuited that before we could start making new resist, those he cannot help but believe (the
inventions we needed new rules for the direc- attempt to prove them via divine veracity, of
tion of the mind, a new instruction manual course, argues in a circle by employing ideas
for the brain. Nietzsche similarly urges us to legitimated through clear and distinct percep-
erect axiological structures that will enhance tion). Heidegger does not criticize Descartes
our well-being. Ultimately, these ideas all cir- for this, but for thinking that he could do
cle around autonomy, the attempt to decide anything else. No matter what kind of test
our own fate, which is the organizing ideal Descartes uses on his beliefs, it ultimately
of the Enlightenment. In epistemology, we do comes down to his passively finding which
not rely on authorities but find out the truth beliefs pass it. Moreover, the choice of the test
for ourselves; in ethics, we do not accept any itself cannot be tested on pain of circularity or
tablet of values handed down but give ones to infinite regress, so that selection is made on
ourselves; in gadgetry, we do not rest with the the basis of which one appears best to him.
limitations evolution has saddled us with, but Nietzsche wants to decide which values are
create our own tools and habitat. best without relying on those he has been
Heidegger sees a paradox at the heart of socialized into accepting, but he needs some
this quest for autonomy that has structured basis on which to judge, a basis that itself can-
much of the intellectual history of the last not have been chosen. Choices can only occur
400 years. Absolute control over the world on the basis of something that has not been

252
LATER ESSAYS AND SEMINARS

chosen. Every decision, however, bases itself Nietzsche thinks that we face nihilism or the
on something not mastered . . . else it would loss of all values because the death of God
never be a decision (BW, 180). This does not their former supportpulls them down with
make them not our choices, however, because Him. Nietzsches solution is to invent new
there is no other way to act. A being with values to pump meaning back into our rap-
no previous preferences whatsoever would idly deflating lives. Heidegger argues that this
be impotent, not free, unable to select from solution actually poses a greater danger.
among options that made no appeal to him. Besides being conceptually impossible, as
Although this analysis applies to all actions, described above, the attempt to throw off the
it has particularly devastating consequences ballast of tradition leaves the individual naked
when applied to the technological attitude. and alone. The kinds of standards or principles
We moderns organize the world around us so we come up with on our own are paltry things,
that it serves our needs and desires with max- lacking the authority to command assent and
imum efficiency, making everything serve us the gravitas to order a life. No one dies for
from the sun and wind to the ways we think mere values (OBT, 77). Instead, according
and value. We seek more and more control, to our human experience and history, every-
but we did not in fact decide to see the world thing essential and great has arisen solely out
as to-be-controlled; rather, problems simply of the fact that humans had a home and were
appear to us as to-be-solved-by-our-efforts, rooted in a tradition (HR, 325). Nietzsche
the way chocolate ice cream shows up as argues that because we live in an unprecedent-
should-be-eaten. Technological activity . . . edly godless time, we lack values and so must
always merely responds to the challenge of create them for ourselves. Heidegger believes
enframing, but it never comprises enfram- that we live in a time of nihilism or cosmic
ing itself or brings it about (326). Thus if homelessness precisely because we are trying
we fully understand our drive to control, we to create values for ourselves. Refusing exter-
realize that we are not in control of it. This is nal authority robs us of the sense of worthi-
how Heidegger reads Hlderlins lines: pre- ness, the unity of those paths and relations in
cisely the essence of technology must harbor which birth and death, disaster and blessing,
in itself the growth of the saving power. But victory and disgrace, endurance and decline
in that case, might not an adequate look into acquire the shape of destiny for human being
what enframing is, as a destining of revealing, (BW, 167), that orient the kind of world that
bring the upsurgence of the saving power into makes a home for a people.
appearance? (334). Properly understanding The question as to what we ought to do
the nature of the essence of technology limits about this situation is tricky, in that trying
this essence by showing us that we neither to do anything perpetuates the technologi-
created nor control it. cal attitude by implying that it is up to us to
take control of our fate. Instead, everything
depends on our inhering in this clearing that
is propriated by Being itselfnever made or
Nihilism and Gelassenheit conjured by ourselves. We must overcome the
compulsion to lay our hands on everything
In fact, it is worse than simply a paradox; (NIII, 181). As opposed to his early notion
feeding the will this way prevents a good life. of resoluteness, we do not choose our lives,

253
LATER ESSAYS AND SEMINARS

even after soul-shattering moments; we are when one is struck by a work of art. All sense
thrown into them, given the particular tastes of control over the situation ebbs away, leav-
and traditions that guide all decisions. We do ing one captivated, part of an experience
not so much make decisions, as much as we that is not the grasping of an idea. The art-
are made by them, as we respond to the call work unfolds as the eye or ear attends to it,
of the world. showing more depth and detail, ultimately
The right attitude is not to resent this as making one alive to the simple fact of see-
a foreign imposition upon our natural integ- ing and hearing. Artworks make unconceal-
rity, for there is nothing to be imposed upon ment as such happen in regard to beings as a
prior to this formation. Rather, we should be whole.. . . That is how self-concealing Being
immensely grateful for the fact that we can be is cleared (BW, 181).
aware of anything at all. As far as we know, This happens in thinking when we think
we are the lone flickering of consciousness in about the fact that experience is given to us.
all of existence. In this vast universe, all takes We did not create it, we do not control it, and
place in darkness, unknown and unexperi- we should be tremendously grateful for the gift.
enced, except in this clearing where things Thanking, Heidegger writes in a rare wordplay
are lit up. Here there is a spark, the halo of a that comes through in English, is thinking. We
small, fragile light in which reality comes to should truly use this capacity to think, and we
know itself through us. should think about the fact that we can think.
This is the tremendous adventure of con- Whereas the poet is the one who truly hears
sciousness. We, perhaps alone in all of exist- words instead of passing them back and forth
ence, have been given the ability to see and like coins with their faces worn off by over-use;
know and think and feel. What Hegel called it is necessary for thinking to become explic-
a highway of despair Heidegger considers the itly aware of the matter here called clearing
blessing of destiny. We are absurdly, ridicu- (442). This is, for Heidegger, the logical cul-
lously fortunate, and yet what do we do with mination of phenomenology, phenomenology
this ur-gift that enables all presence? We who squared if you will, as the study of awareness
can know, ignore 99 percent of the world; becomes the awareness of awareness itself.
we can become aware but we let all fade into The phenomenological attitude is not limited
inconspicuous background, drifting through to a specialized activity one does in ones study
the oblivious passing of our lives (BP, 297) but should infuse ones entire life with a higher
on auto-pilot. We can express this awareness attentiveness, a more sensitive attunedness to
in words, but rely on easy clichs. the luminosity of the world.
A grateful life would be one lived in appre-
ciation of this cosmic gift, this extraordinary
NOTES AND REFERENCES
chance that has somehow been granted to
us. Heidegger encourages the attitude of 1
For more on this topic, see my Never Mind:
Gelassenheit, a releasement or letting-be that Thinking of Subjectivity in the Dreyfus-
dwells with and on our experience, a patient McDowell Debate, in ed. Julian Schear,
attending to the way things show themselves Mind, Reason and Being-in-the-World: The
McDowell-Dreyfus Debate (New York:
to us the way one cares for and nurtures a Routledge, 2013), and chapter four of
plant. A paradigm of this attitude would be, Groundless Grounds: A Study of Wittgenstein
I think, Zen satori, but also what happens and Heidegger (Cambridge: MIT Press, 2012).

254
31
ART
Andrew Bowie

Heideggers assessment of specific works the concern is too often with tedious, and
of art is largely based on quite traditional largely vacuous classificatory ontology. In
assumptions. He sometimes pays signifi- such cases what matters about art disappears
cant attention, for example, to not par- because of the concern to analyze the object
ticularly outstanding poetry, such as that of art in conceptual terms. The importance
Conrad Ferdinand Meyer, and his criticisms of Heideggers approaches to art lies, in con-
of Wagner are largely copied from the later trast, in how they help us to see why philoso-
Nietzsches pseudo-classicist rejection of phy may sometimes have more to learn from
the supposed excesses in Wagners music. art than vice versa.
Heidegger is also famously mistaken in The Heideggers earlier philosophy, before
Origin of the Work of Art about Van Goghs the essay The Origin of the Work of Art
painting of shoes, which he sees as those of (1935), does not address art in any substan-
a peasant woman, but which seem to have tial way, so why does art become a crucial
been Van Goghs own. Like Kant, who was point of orientation for his work from this
famously limited in his awareness of sig- time onwards? Being and Time, as Mark
nificant art, Heideggers relationship to art Okrent, Charles Taylor, Richard Rorty,
tends generally not to be important for what and others have suggested, has an essen-
he says about major works of art. However, tially pragmatist dimension, in which the
again like Kant, Heidegger also helps to open understanding of being is dependent on the
up a whole new way of thinking about the ways in which Dasein responds in practi-
significance of art both for modern phi- cal terms. The hammer that changes status
losophy and in more general terms, whose from zuhanden to vorhanden when it breaks
implications are still being understood. This shows up its significance in terms of a world
mismatch between engagement with works of practical action that is determined by the
of art in the manner of critics and other art- needs and desires of Dasein. This version of
ists, and philosophical insight into art might the understanding of being can, though, seem
suggest that Kant and Heidegger are impos- to depend on an idealist projection of signifi-
ing on art ways of thinking that are actually cance onto the world by the subject. There is
alien to it. Indeed, this kind of imposition is much more to Heideggers phenomenological
easy to show in many versions of the philoso- ontology than this, but ways in which under-
phy of art in the analytical tradition, where standing of the world must also derive from

257
ART

the world itself can be inadequately articu- an approach goes counter to the apparently
lated in certain kinds of pragmatist perspec- obvious view that what philosophy needs to
tive. If, as Heidegger seeks to do, one wishes do in relation to art is to explain how nonaes-
to get out of a subject/object philosophical thetic objects become works of art. This view
model that separates two aspects and then starts with the assumption of an objective
has to account for the fact that they cannot world of physics and chemistry as the foun-
be wholly separate, one needs ways of doing dational reality, which leads to the puzzle of
this that do not reproduce the original prob- what makes physical and chemical objects be
lem despite themselves. It is this situation able to be art. In contrast, what happens in
that leads Heidegger toward art. art is seen by Heidegger as prior to the objec-
Is art, then, the object that shows how tifications that enable the explanatory and
the subject/object model can be circum- predictive success of the sciences.
vented? The point, of course, is that art is Art has to do with how the world makes
not an object: the object Beethovens Ninth sense at all, where the fact that it can be
Symphony or Van Goghs painting of shoes explained in terms of natural laws is, how-
consists of what can be said about them that ever important that undoubtedly is, a deriva-
is subsumable within objective conceptual tive way of relating to being (see The Age
terms: a mass of frequencies and durations, in of the World Picture). In the contemporary
the case of the Beethoven (or a pile of printed world the assumption has increasingly come
paper, a digitally encoded set of sounds, etc.), to dominate that, in the long run, everything
and a chemical and physical object display- will ultimately become explicable via the
ing colored properties, or whatever, in the growing reach of explanations derived from
case of Van Gogh. If one begins with their physics, chemistry, and biology. Recent books
status as objects, the fact that these are works using evolutionary psychology to account
of art would then appear to consist either in for art are a characteristic offshoot of this
their supposedly possessing a further prop- metaphysical assumption. Heidegger, and the
erty not possessed by objects that are not art, hermeneutic, phenomenological, and Critical
or in the fact that they are taken to be art by Theory traditions deriving from Kant and
their listeners and viewers, which is a further German Idealism, show that the idea that all
example of the projection of significance by other forms of understanding will eventually
the subject. It is this approach that Heidegger be explained by scientific objectification is
rejects as failing to grasp what is at issue in unsustainable. A challenge to the objectifying
art, and this rejection has considerable philo- model that dominates much Western philos-
sophical consequences. ophy already formed the core of Being and
Heideggers alternative is, as Manfred Time, and Heideggers move to focusing on
Frank has suggested, encapsulated by Paul art relates to other changes associated with
Klees remark that art renders reality visible, the turn. In the turn the role of Dasein
rather than representing it. In Heideggers becomes less dominant because of what is
terms, then, art has to do with unconceal- encapsulated in the idea of language as the
ment, world-disclosure, and the question house of being, in which things make sense
is why this becomes so significant both for by the way in which they are expressed in
Heideggers philosophical project and for language. There is a connection here between
decisive issues in modern philosophy. Such the way language is understood and the way

258
ART

art is understood. In both cases, it is not sub- central social role it did, for example, in the
jective projection that makes sense of things, Athenian polis is clearly true. Hegel infers
but rather the existence of forms of articula- from this that: The science of art is thus in
tion and expression that are prior to individ- our time much more necessary than in times
ual subjects, and which those subjects come in which art for itself as art provided com-
to inhabit. Whether this obscures the role plete satisfaction.3 However, he means by
of subjective initiative in both language use this that philosophy takes the central role,
and the creation of art is a complex subject. which is just as unconvincing today as the
In the present context what matters, though, idea that art plays a central role in contem-
is how Heidegger shows that art is not some- porary society. The counter to the Hegelian
thing that can be adequately understood understanding of art that Heidegger helps to
either just from the side of the subject, or just articulate becomes apparent if one questions
from the side of the world as described in the scope of the notion of art.
objective terms. Much debate in discussion of modern art
The importance of these issues is evident in particular concerns the criteria for deciding
in the contrast between the role of art in the whether something is art or not. The obvious
analytical, and in the European traditions of lack of agreed criteria is itself the clue to how
philosophy. The former is often critical of to respond to the question. If we see art in
an apparent overestimation of the signifi- terms of ways in which sense is made, there
cance of art in the latter, which they rightly can be no general criteria for deciding whether
observe does not play a determining role for something is art or not, in the same way as
many people in many areas of modern life. there are no universal criteria for deciding
Ernst Tugendhat suggests the reasons for this on all cases of what makes sense. Clearly
kind of objection as follows, in relation to much depends here on how one understands
his interpretation of the tradition to which the notion of making sense. Within an
Heidegger belongs: it may be correct that established discipline or practice, criteria of
art has something to do with truth, but this sense will often be norms that have become
can hardly be demonstrated by pointing out regarded as legitimate by those involved in
that a work of art has the function of show- the discipline or practice: playing too many
ing something.1 Tugendhat assumes that notes outside diatonic harmony in certain
truth has to be analyzed in semantic terms kinds of diatonic music makes no sense, for
before one can begin to argue about the example. However, it is easy to think of con-
truth conveyed by art, but the question he texts in which playing wrong notes would
does not adequately address is what makes make sense, and the development of Western
the semantic approach itself possible at all, music has often involved just this. It is pre-
which is what Heidegger tries to understand cisely the way in which, by stepping outside of
in terms of unconcealment.2 A further objec- some of the norms that constitute a practice,
tion here is that if the importance of art in new sense can be made that is philosophically
the European tradition were just based on crucial, because this is part of what follows
contemporary artistic production and recep- from Heideggers idea of unconcealment.
tion, the emphasis art receives might well Schleiermacher already saw art as that
be said to be based on a misapprehension. for which there admittedly are rules, but the
Hegels judgment that art no longer plays the combinatory application of these rules cannot

259
ART

in turn be rule-bound, on pain of a regress what there is up to now via causal contexts of
of rules for rules, which would make mak- interaction. The effect of the work does not
ing sense impossible.4 Language involves this consist in an effecting. It resides in a trans-
art, as understanding anothers utterances formation, which happens from out of the
cannot be achieved just in terms of pregiven work, of the un-hiddenness of beings and that
norms: the awareness of which norms should means: of being (GA 5, 58). What this means
be relevant in a context cannot be generated becomes clearer from Heideggers examples.
by another norm. As such, sense depends on Even though Heideggers Van Gogh exam-
contexts of understanding and action that ple is factually probably mistaken, what it
cannot be wholly established in advance, and suggests can still be used as a model of how
which can be changed by new articulations. art is world-disclosing. The painting is not
This idea relates to what Heidegger discusses essentially a representation of shoes, which
in terms of the idea of world in the Origin can be better achieved with a photograph, it
of the Work of Art. is rather the opening up of that which the
Heideggers questioning of what becomes material, the pair of peasant shoes is in truth.
the dominant analytical perspective lies, then, This entity steps out into the unhiddenness
in the fact that any objectifying form of expla- of its being so that there is a happening
nation depends on the constitution of a con- of truth at work in the painting (21). The
text of inquiry. This constitution depends in crucial idea is that the world of which the
turn on the emergence of sense in ways that material is an integral part emerges via the
Heidegger comes to think are to be under- way the shoes make sense of their context,
stood by what happens in art, and cannot even though the context itself is not what
themselves all be objectively explained. What is represented. Similarly, Beethovens Eroica
we have said so far should enable us to grasp Symphony can be described, for example, in
the sometimes rather cryptic way Heidegger terms of melodic, rhythmic, and harmonic
talks about arts importance for philosophy. ideas. The happening of truth through the
In On the Essence of Truth the hidden- symphony lies, though, in the specific sense
ness of being as a whole, Heidegger claims, that the music makes by evoking a world
never results after the fact as a consequence that combines a new expansive freedom with
of the always piecemeal cognition of entities. new forms of order. The happening of truth
The hiddenness of being as a whole, the real cannot be without the work, but it is the way
un-truth, is older than every openness of this that the world is made manifest in new ways
and that entity.5 The alternative model to the that constitutes the works truth.
analytical perspective is summarized by the Heideggers example of the Greek temple
claim in the art essay that science is not an is particularly resonant, and has had signifi-
original happening of truth but in each case cant effects on how some architects regard
the extension of a realm of truth which is what they are doing. Once again, there is
already open.6 The question is how to think an inversion of the received way of thinking
about the way realms of truth become open, about what is at issue. The assumption would
and this is what the artwork is supposed to normally be that first there is nature, then
enable us to grasp. This does not happen via there is the temple. In one sense this is obvi-
an explanation, but instead by a transforma- ously true, but the point of Heideggers idea
tion of the world: the work in no way affects of unconcealment is that what is manifest

260
ART

is what is brought to light by the work, not also sees in terms of contractive and expan-
something that is always already present: sive forces. If the former dominates, there can
be no world, but a world of pure expansion
In standing there the building [Bauwerk, would just dissipate into formlessness. There
which contains the sense of work as is therefore a constant tension in how the
in art work] stands up to the storm world is manifest, between the need for some
which rages over it and in this way first
kind of ground to make it intelligible at all
shows the storm in its power. The splen-
and the realization that seeking to make the
dor and the glowing of the stone, appar-
ently itself dependent on the blessing of ground totally intelligible renders it devoid of
the sun, first renders the lightness of the sense. Sense in Schellings On the Essence of
day, the breadth of the sky, the darkness Human Freedom and his later philosophy
of the night manifest. (27) therefore depends on freedom, and freedom
demands that from which we liberate our-
It is the making manifest of something that selves, upon how we transcend the ground
otherwise remains hidden by establishing a without seeking completely to overcome it.7
context of significance that is decisive in this With respect to art, one can get an under-
conception. The philosophical importance of standing of what this implies via the idea
this approach lies precisely in the reminder that great music is grounded in what can
that however much we expand our explana- destroy sense: transience, loss, longing, and
tory cognitive reach, what enables the world pain are essential aspects of the ground of the
to make sense is not exhausted by this. Indeed, greatest music, which makes a world out of
such expansion can itself lead to things being this ground that at least temporarily makes
hidden. Sense here consists in what connects sense. In a related manner, Heidegger sees the
us to the world, makes us devote ourselves to earth via the example of a stone, whose
it, rather than making it an object of manipu- weight rejects . . . any penetration into it. If
lation. The historically shifting line between we try to do this by breaking up the cliff, then
knowing about the world and the world mak- it never shows an inside, something revealed,
ing sense became a vital philosophical issue in its pieces (GA 5, 32). The earth constitu-
via what Max Weber termed the disenchant- tively involves hiddenness, but at the same
ment of the world in modern science and time, it is the ground of what can become
bureaucracy, and Heidegger offers resources manifest: the sculptor who uses the stone
for responding to disenchantment that do not can liberate significance that the attempt to
rely on an illusory reenchantment. penetrate and analyze the stone can destroy.
The inversion from a perspective that seeks The creation of the work also destroys
to ground itself on what can be objectively some aspect of the earth: But this use does
known is characterized in the Heideggers not use up and abuse the earth as a material
essay in terms of the relationship between (Stoff) but rather first frees it to itself, by
earth and world. Heidegger derives this constituting the truth in the form (Gestalt)
contrast (with no real acknowledgment) (50). World and earth are essentially differ-
from the work of Schelling, which he was ent and yet never separated.. . . The opposi-
studying at the time he wrote the essay on art. tion of world and earth is a conflict (34) via
Schelling thinks in terms of the relationship which the truth of being arises in a manner
between ground and existence, which he that is both revealing and concealing.8

261
ART

Heideggers approach in the essay is in patient, which unlocks a truth for the per-
some respects weighed down by his tradi- son that enables them to cope with what has
tionalism, and by a rhetoric that echoes the been tormenting them for years.
Rektoratsrede. He talks of Dichtung The core philosophical issue with respect
which has the sense of Poesie, crea- to Heidegger and art is, then, what can be
tive making in Romantic thoughtnow developed from his best ideas for a reorien-
becoming a saying [Sage, with the impli- tation of philosophy toward the question of
cations of saga], so that: In such a say- making sense of the world,9 rather than con-
ing the concepts of the essence of a historical tinuing to seek a ground for epistemology, of
Volk are pre-formed for it, i.e. its belonging the kind that history shows is not what actu-
to world-history [Welt-Geschichte, which ally results from philosophical reflection. If
implies the sense of history as being sent] we are concerned about the future of phi-
(60). It is therefore important to separate the losophy as part of modern culture, it will be
interpretative issue of how The Origin of as a resource for making sense, rather than
the Work of Art relates to the philosophical as an adjunct for the natural sciences, that
and other history of which it is a question- philosophy will prosper.10
able part, from the philosophical question
of the texts own bringing to light of truth
about art in contemporary discussion. The
NOTES AND REFERENCES
focus on the notion of work can, for
example, hide the fact that the happening 1
E. Tugendhat, Philosophische Aufstze
of art is not dependent on art being in the (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1992), 430.
form of a work: revelatory jazz perform- 2
See M. Wrathall, Heidegger and Unconcealment
ances, of the kind that helped constitute (Cambridge: Cambridge University
the world of Civil Rights by establishing Press, 2011) for a convincing rejection of
Tugendhats critique of Heidegger on truth and
new forms of cultural identity, are not best
world-disclosure.
seen as works of the kind Heidegger uses 3
G. W. F. Hegel, sthetik, Vols 1 and 2, ed.
as examples. Indeed, Martin Luther Kings Bassenge (Berlin, Weimar: Aufbau, 1965),
I have a dream speech can be seen in this Vol.1, 21.
context as a happening of truth of the kind
4
F. D. E. Schleiermacher, Hermeneutics and
Criticism, trans. A. Bowie (Cambridge:
Heidegger is concerned with: it does not suc-
Cambridge University Press, 1998), 229.
ceed predominantly on the basis of proposi- 5
GA 9, 191.
tional claims, but rather by helping form a 6
GA 5, 48.
new world vision with rhythms of language 7
See A. Bowie, Schelling and Modern European
derived from the tradition of gospel singing. Philosophy (London: Routledge, 1993).
8
For more on this, see A. Bowie, From
When Heidegger says language first brings
Romanticism to Critical Theory. The
the entity as an entity into the open (ins Philosophy of German Literary Theory
Offene) (59), we can extend the conception (London: Routledge, 1997).
beyond the kind of medium size dry goods 9
On this see the outstanding A. W. Moore, The
to which he refers, to anything that becomes Evolution of Modern Metaphysics. Making
Sense of Things (Cambridge: Cambridge
unconcealed by language that makes truth
University Press, 2012).
happen. This can, for instance, be a thera- 10
See A. Bowie, Adorno and the Ends of
pist using an apparently banal locution to a Philosophy (Cambridge: Polity, 2013).

262
32
BIRTH AND DEATH
Anne OByrne

Even if Dasein is assured in its belief leaving it, and, moreover, to talk of them in
about its whither, or if, in rational the same breath? After all, this is the condi-
enlightenment, it supposes itself to know tion of finitude. We are finite by virtue of
about its whence, all this counts for having an end and a beginning.
nothing as against the phenomenal facts
What interested Heidegger was never the
of the case: for the mood brings Dasein
phenomenon of death or of birth but, rather
before the that it is of its there,
which, as such, stares it in the face with what death and eventually birth had to do
the inexorability of an enigma. (BTMR, with the sort of beings we are. That is to say,
H. 136) death and birth happen, and they are the
object of empirical study by biologists and
anthropologists who assign them meaning
Death is everywhere in Being and Time, and it in specific physical and cultural contexts,
would be difficult to understand Heideggers but they have no being and are not beings.
work or make any claim about his thinking Neither ever is. From the point of view of
without having undergone that text and its ontology, birth and death are relevant only
unrelenting confrontation with our mortal as the concrete instantiation of our natal and
finitude. Our being is being-toward-death, mortal mode of being. In Being and Times
and our mode of being in time is essentially existential analytic, the being under consid-
futural as we project ourselves on the cer- eration is each time mine and mortality or
tainty of our own deaths. For Heidegger, being-toward-death shows the futural char-
famously, death is our ownmost, nonrela- acter of my temporal being. Yet I have argued
tional possibility that is certain and not to be elsewhere that natality or being-toward-birth
outstripped (BTMR, H. 264). Much has been complicates that temporality and also points
written about this and anything that has been to our being-with others, making the being
written about birth in Heideggers work has in question essentially plural.2 It is a matter
had to take this overwhelming emphasis into of our being. Then, when we turn to think-
account.1 Yet what happens if, now, we take ing mortality and natality together, the and
birth and death together, and take seriously shows us stretching along between birth and
the and that holds them in relation and that death, not as though strung between discrete
requires us to talk of coming to be and pass- points that mark the ends of our finite exist-
ing away, of emergence into the world and ence, but as actively stretching along, making

263
BIRTH AND DEATH

us open to the most intimate extremities of is predominantly futural as we project our-


existence. It is not a matter of adopting an selves upon our possibilities of being. This is
open stance or attitude, or of deliberately howvery briefly putdeath permeates our
taking up a more or less open mode of liv- existence. The future orients our existence;
ing; rather, Dasein is being-open. Thomas death, mortality, and futuricity dominate the
Sheehan has argued that Heideggers theme, work.
late and early, is our finitude as opening up Yet, throughout division one, the place
the world/clearing/open that we essentially of birth and natality is held open by the
are.3 If so, our birth, growth, and death thought of thrownness. Heidegger writes:
show how we are essentially open beings. Thrownness is neither a fact-that-is-finished
Pursuing this thought through and beyond nor a Fact that is settled (H. 179). Far from
Being and Time means following a series of it. We are thrown into the world and this
displacements. Jemeinigkeitthe mine-ness not deathis the source of our constantly
of the being that is at the center of the investi- disruptive existential anxiety. Anxiety is
gation of Beingis set in place in the opening anxious about naked Dasein as something
lines of S.9 of Being and Time: We are our- that has been thrown into uncanniness
selves the entities to be analyzed. The being [Unheimlichkeit]. It brings one back to the
of any such entity is each time mine (H. 41). pure that-it-is of ones ownmost individual-
The initial aim of the work is to make us per- ized thrownness (H. 343). Reading this in
plexed about Being, and the seat of that per- natal terms allows us to make concrete and
plexity will be the being that is a question for explicit what otherwise remains hidden in the
itself, the being we have long thought that folds of the text. First, in our natal thrown-
we know best of all. The first task is to dis- ness we come face to face with the fact that
place that familiarity, and pushing aside the we once were-not-yet, and with the contin-
terms subject, self, human, rational animal, gency of our having come to be at all. There
etc. in favor of Dasein is Heideggers opening is every reason to be anxious about naked,
move. In the course of division one of Being thrown Dasein because there is no reason for
and Time he goes on to reorder our under- its having been thrown. We could very eas-
standing of time such that we may no longer ily have never come to be. Second, we arrive
think of ourselves as moving through a series new into a world that is already old, and our
of presents away from the past into the arrival is a moment of possibility and renewal
future, from birth to death. He writes: [t]he but also, inevitably, disruption.4 Thus, third,
non-relational character of death understood making the world our world is a task, and it
in anticipation individualizes Dasein down will turn out to be a shared task. Put another
to itself (H. 263); when Dasein exists, it way, we receive the historical task of making
is already thrown into this possibility (H. the past our past despite its being irrevocably
251); authentic being-toward-death is a gone and thoroughly inappropriable.5
project in that Dasein projects itself upon it How does this come to be a shared task?
as an eminent possibility of its own (S, 53); What does birth have to do with opening
the authentic future is the toward-oneself Dasein to plural being? For most of Being
. . . existing as the possibility of a nul- and Time Heidegger holds off the first per-
lity not-to-be-bypassed (BTMR, H. 330). son plural. Dasein is singular, and both its
Indeed, he argues that Daseins temporality death and birth are presented as above all

264
BIRTH AND DEATH

having to do with its individuality. While he to be finite is to lack perfection and find
does attend to Mitsein [being-with] and even oneself subject to limitations. If we follow
acknowledges that Dasein and Mitsein are Heideggers lead in setting aside this oppo-
co-originary, the problem of plural Dasein sition, finite being emerges instead as being
emerges fully only once birth is explicitly in the mode of openness and dis-closure.
addressed for the first time in division two. Death and birth are limits toward which we
The context is Heideggers approach to the are. Concretely, natal, mortal being means
historical (and eventually political) character we encounter ourselves in specific contexts
of our being.6 He writes in Section 72: at specific points in lives that are marked by
growth, development, and deep transforma-
The question [of the wholeness of tion.7 This is what is signaled by the and of
Dasein] itself may . . . have been answered birth and death.
with regard to being-toward-the-end. At this point in his opus, in the late sec-
However, death is, after all, only the
tions of Being and Time where the pursuit of
end of Dasein and formally speaking,
a complete account of Dasein is once again
it is just one of the ends that embraces the
totality of Dasein. But the other end is derailed, Heidegger does not pursue these
the beginning, birth. Only the being indications and the account of historicity
between birth and death presents the famously passes from individual Dasein to
whole we are looking for. (H. 373) the being of a people [Volk]. Yet there are
signs that he understood it early on. In his
The wholeness of Dasein will continue to lectures of the War Emergency Semester of
elude Heidegger precisely because of the 1919 Towards the Definition of Philosophy
unpredictable, disruptive newness that he can (TDP, GA 56/57, 6376 (German), 5364
no longer ignore once he opens up the ques- (English)) he urged his students to take up
tion of birth. Birth cannot be accounted for formal indication as a means of philoso-
using terms borrowed from the characteri- phizing in a way grounded in life, specifi-
zations of death, nor even thrownness. Thus cally ones own life. In 1926, life and change
Heideggers own schema is displaced. Rather become explicit concerns as he broaches the
than nonrelational, birth is ur-relational, ontology of life and Dasein in terms of the
since no one is born alone. Birth is not our Aristotelian concepts of dunamis and ener-
ownmost, since it is an event and an expe- geia (BCAP, GA 22). Yet in the period of
rience for othersnotably our mothers Being and Time he broadly sets aside the
before we can call it our own. It does not concern by distancing himself from anthro-
mark us as futural so much as subject to a pology and the tradition of life philosophy,
syncopated temporality where we can only and by establishing the ontological differ-
catch up with our birth after the fact. We ence. Not only that, but soon after Being and
only ever encounter ourselves as having Time both these strategies begin to break
always already been born, and we are always down. The 1928/29 lectures Einleitung in der
already with others. Philosophie show him sketching a phenom-
Such displacements are inevitable once we enology of childhood and human develop-
grasp the dynamic character of Daseins lived ment (GA 27, 12349) and thinking through
existence. According to the metaphysical Daseins disclosedness [Erschlossenheit]
opposition between the finite and the infinite, alongside Daseins being-with [Mitsein]. In

265
BIRTH AND DEATH

the 1928 lecture course The Metaphysical central to his later thinking, whether or not
Foundations of Logic, he acknowledges that we agree with Heideggers own assessment of
the struggle to prevent ontological enquiry that thinking as post-metaphysical. Thomas
slipping back into the realm of merely ontic Sheehan makes one version of this argument
observations has become difficult to sustain, based on Contributions to Philosophy: From
indeed, so difficult that he suggests aban- Enowning, where he sees Heideggers deep-
doning the ontological difference in favor of est interest in dehypostasized being emerge
what he names metontology. He writes: as an interest in our being open, together. He
writes:
[W]e need a special problematic which
has for its proper theme beings as a Human openness is always co-openness
whole. This new investigation resides in (Mitdasein). Our socialityco-extensive
the essence of ontology itself and is the with finitude, and its first giftis what
result of its overturning, its makes it possible and necessary to take-as
[metabole]. I designate this set of ques- and to understand is. Our sociality is
tions metontology. And here also, in the die Sache selbst. (Sheehan, 199)
domain of metontological-existentiell
questioning, is the domain of the meta-
physics of existence (here the question of Peter Sloterdijk makes another version
an ethics may properly be raised for the based on the Letter on Humanism (1949)
first time). (MFL, 157; GA 26, 199)8 and in his essay Domestikation des Seins:
die Verdeutlichung der Lichtung [The
Metontology disappears from Heideggers Domestication of Being: The Clearing up of
work after this lecture course, but it marks a Clearing].9 Focusing on the use of Lichtung
stage on his way to a transformed philosophy (which could be translated as clearing, light-
that comes together in the mid-1930s and ing, or lightening), he avoids the interpreta-
comes most clearly to light in the publication tion that understands it as a clearing into
of The Origin of the Work of Art in 1950. which a being might step and instead argues in
By this point, any metaphysics of existence frankly anthropological and biological terms
seems to have been definitively left behind, for an natal understanding of Lichtung as an
and Dasein, mineness, ourness, and birth and open-ended Menschenwerdung [becoming-
death are displaced. He writes in the same human]. The dwelling is the place of becoming-
period, in Contributions to Philosophy (from human; our bodies are the site of Lichtung
Enowning), that the shift in his vocabulary and; brains are the Lichtungsorgane par
from Sein [being] to Seyn [be-ing] is meant excellence (Nicht gerettet: Versuche nach
to indicate that Sein is no longer thought Heidegger, 1956). Thanks to our neotenie
metaphysically. the fact that we are born prematurely and in
Yet, as I mentioned earlier, Heideggers need of years of careour becoming-human
concern was never with the phenomena of happens in a plural context.10
birth and death but, at least for a period, Birth and death, then, can show us a new
with the natal, mortal, living mode of being. version of Heidegger, but it is one that part
Studying birth and death has led us to finitude of us may find disappointing. Is everything
and the openness of finite being, and there that is radical about Heideggers work now
are good reasons to think that this remains in danger of being domesticated? Will all the

266
BIRTH AND DEATH

shattering insights of fundamental ontology 2


See OByrne, Natality and Finitude.
and beyond be retrieved not as metaphysics
3
Thomas Sheehan, A Paradigm Shift in
Heidegger Research, Continental Philosophy
but as anthropology? This is a real worry
Review 34.2 (2001), 183202.
only if we insist on an opposition between 4
See Felix Murchadha, Future or Future
domesticity and radicality. If we regret the Past: Temporality between Praxis and Poiesis
radicality of Heideggers work it may be in Heideggers Being and Time, Philosophy
that what we miss is the high loneliness and Today 42.3 (October 1998), 2629.
5
See Franoise Dastur, Death: An Essay on
existential courage that comes with broach-
Finitude, trans. John Llewelyn (London:
ing Being, or the feeling of purity that is the Athlone Press, 1996).
reward for resolutely pursuing the question 6
Karl Lwith is reported to have once asked
past all theological, scientific, and quotidian Heidegger about the link between his philoso-
distractions.11 When it turns out that the root phy and his politics and was told in reply that
the link was historicity.
of us all and of each one of us is in the domos, 7
See David Wood, Reading Heidegger
the oikos that is the scene of our first com- Responsibly: Glimpses of Being in Daseins
ing to be and that is our first world, we fear Development, in ed. Franois Raffoul and
that existential courage might look less like David Pettigrew, Heidegger and Practical
standing out into the gathering storm and Philosophy (Albany: SUNY Press, 2002),
21936.
more like standing up to ones parents. Yet 8
As both William McNeill and Steven
there is high art thereperhaps less Caspar Galt Crowell argue, metontology does
David Friedrich and more Jan Vermeerand not ever happen, but is a provocative,
poetry, and philosophy too. revealing attempt. See William McNeill,
Metaphysics, Fundamental Ontology,
Metontology, 192535, Heidegger Studies
8 (1992), 6381 and Steven Galt Crowell,
NOTES AND REFERENCES Metaphysics, Metontology, and the
End of Being and Time, Philosophy and
1
On birth in Heidegger, see Artur Boelderl, Von Phenomenological Research, 60.2 (March
Geburts wegen: unterwegs zu einer philoso- 2000), 30731.
phischen Natologie (Wurzburg: Koenigshausen 9
Peter Sloterdijk, Domestication des Seins:
and Neumann, 2007); Lisa Guenther, die Verdeutlichung der Lichtung, in Nicht
Being-from-others: Reading Heidegger after gerettet: Versuche nach Heidegger (Berlin:
Cavarero, Hypatia 23.1 (Winter 2008), Suhrkamp, 2001), 142234. My thanks to
99118; Leslie MacAvoy, The Heideggerian Nathan Van Camp for this reference.
Bias Toward Death: A Critique of the Role 10
A third version, less focused on a specific text
of Being-Towards-Death in the Disclosure of of Heideggers, is Jean-Luc Nancys Being
Human Finitude, Metaphilosophy 27.12 Singular Plural, trans. Robert Richardson and
(January 1996), 6377; Anne OByrne, Natality Anne OByrne (Stanford: Stanford University
and Finitude (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2000).
Press, 2011); Christina Sches, Philosophie des 11
See Sheehan, A Paradigm Shift in Heidegger
Geborenseins (Freiburg: Alber, 2008). Research.

267
33
THE BODY
Kevin Aho

One of the most significant contributions of beings live or embody this understanding as
Heideggers Being and Time (1927) is the dis- Dasein, a colloquial German expression that
mantling of an embedded assumption in the can mean ordinary human existence.
Western philosophical tradition that privi- Dasein is not to be understood as a thing or
leges the cognizing mind and the standpoint substance, an autonomous mind, a casually
of theoretical detachment. On this view, it is determined body, or some combination of the
only by means of adopting a disinterested and two. (GA 2/BT, 910) Dasein, rather, refers
disembodied attitude that the philosopher to the situated activity of being human, where
can be genuinely objective and acquire clear human is understood not as a being but as
and distinct knowledge about various aspects a self-interpreting, self-understanding way of
of reality. As Plato says in the Phaedo, If we being. The word is meant to capture the way
are ever to have pure knowledge of anything, that human beings are already there (Da),
we must escape from the body, and con- that is, bound up and involved in a context
template things by themselves with the soul of sociohistorical meanings that they already
itself (66e). In Being and Time, Heidegger vaguely understand. Thus, to exist, says
famously reverses this position, arguing that Heidegger, is essentially . . . to understand
the standpoint of theoretical detachment (GA 24, 391/BP, 276, my emphasis), and
is actually derivative and parasitic on the understanding is not mental or cognitive.
embodied and situated practices of everyday It is informed, rather, by how we are situ-
life. According to Heidegger, humans already ated or thrown (geworfen) into the world,
embody a kind of tacit understanding or and our situatedness (Befindlichkeit) is
familiarity with things that has nothing to do revealed to us in terms of particular moods
with mental processes. As we go about our that make it possible for thingslike our
daily liveshandling equipment and engag- jobs, relationships, possessions, and personal
ing in various social practicesthe things identitiesto emotionally matter to us in
that we encounter already make sense to us the ways that they do. (GA 2, 137/BT, 176)
in ways that can never be made theoretically But if it is true that Dasein already embodies
explicit. Heidegger calls this vague, precogni- this noncognitive, affective understanding of
tive familiarity with things the understand- Being, critics have long been puzzled as to
ing of Being (GA 2, 5/BT, 25), and he will why Being and Time offers no account of the
refer to the practical way in which human bodys role in this understanding. Is it not my

269
THE BODY

body after all that represents the situated site that serves me as a means of all perception
of this understanding?1 stands in my way in the perception of itself
To address this criticism we have to and is a remarkably incompletely constituted
first get clear about what we mean by the thing.3 Indeed, in the seamless flow of my
body. Edmund Husserls work in Ideas everyday life, I am altogether unaware of my
II and, later, in The Crisis of European body because I am already existing or living
Sciences and Transcendental Philosophy is through it. As Merleau-Ponty will later write,
especially important because he articulates I am not in front of my body. I am in it or
the crucial distinction between two senses rather I am it.4
of the body in the German language, the But a systematic treatment of the sens-
quantifiable physical body (Krper) and ing, orienting, and kinesthetic aspects of the
the lived-body (Leib).2 The conception lived-body is precisely what is missing in
of Krper is largely informed by Cartesian Heideggers account of everyday existence in
and Newtonian science where bodies are Being and Time. As French critic Alphonse
defined in terms of first, having a material de Waelhens famously quipped, [Heidegger]
composition that is measurable; second, already presupposes that the subject of daily
having determinate boundaries and causal existence raises his arm, since he hammers
interaction; third, occupying a specific spa- and builds; that he orients himself, since he
tiotemporal location; and finally, being con- drives an automobile . . . In Being and Time
figured as an object that is separate from one does not find thirty lines concerning the
and represented by the cognizing subject. problem of perception; one does not find ten
In this sense, any physical objecta rock, concerning that of the body.5 What are we
tree, cultural artifact, or human beingis to make of this omission?
an instance of Krper, but this definition First, critics have to recognize that Being
does not help us understand the body as it and Time is by no means a complete manu-
is lived, felt, or experienced. Related to the script. Heidegger only completed the first
words for life (Leben) and experience two divisions of part one of the book. The
(Erlebnis), the lived-body (Leib) is not an third division of part one, entitled time and
object or thing that we have and that can Being and the whole of part two, which was
be viewed from a standpoint of theoretical also to consist of three divisions, were never
detachment. It is, rather, a reference to the completed (GA 2, 3940/BT, 64). Thus, the
experience of my own body, and this expe- fact that Heidegger does not treat the body
rience is not encapsulated or self-contained; in Being and Time has to be understood
it is fundamentally bound up and entwined within the context of a fundamentally unfin-
in the life-world (Lebenswelt) that I am ished manuscript. And if we look at the lec-
involved in. This sensual intertwining makes tures immediately preceding and following
it impossible for me to perceive my body as the publication of Being and Time we see
a discrete object because I am already per- Heidegger already addressing a number of
ceptually situated and oriented in the world different aspects of embodiment. For instance,
on the basis of my body. Husserl explains: his early Freiburg lecture courses offer exten-
I do not have the possibility of distancing sive critical treatments of the phenomena
myself from my body (Leib), or my body of life (Leben) and lived-experience
from me. This is because The same body (Erlebnis) (e.g. GA 567/TDP, 20; GA 60/

270
THE BODY

PRL, 12, 17; GA 61/PIA, 3; GA 63/OHF, and I was unable to say more at the time
56). In his 1928 lecture course on Leibniz, (GA 89, 292/ZS, 231).8 These remarks seem
Heidegger acknowledges that Dasein is to indicate that a thematic treatment of the
among other things in each case dispersed in body would have been important in fleshing
a body and goes on to discuss the problem out the account of Dasein in Being and Time
of a sexed or gendered incarnation of Dasein but that Heidegger may have been unsure
(GA 26, 173/MFL, 137), a theme he returns about how to go about it.
to in the winter semester course of 1928/29 Finally, critics have to recognize that
(GA 27, 20).6 And, in his 1929/30 course Heidegger does, in fact, offer an analy-
The Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics, sis of Dasein from the perspective of the
Heidegger offers a lengthy treatment of Krper/Leib distinction. Although there are
sense organs, moods, and of Dasein as a some indications in earlier texts and lectures
unique world-forming (weltbildend) ani- (e.g. GA 20/HCT, 18; GA 24/BP, 13; GA
mal that is fundamentally different from the 2/BT, 910), one of the clearest articula-
impoverished or world-poor (weltarm) tions is found in his 1936/37 winter semes-
nature of nonhuman animals (GA 2930/ ter course on Nietzsche, The Will to Power
FCM, 46, 4963). Heidegger will go on to as Art, when Heidegger writes, We do not
address aspects of Daseins animal-nature in have a body in the way we carry a knife in
a number of other writings and lectures from sheath. Neither is the body a natural body
his middle and later period (e.g. GA 7/BW; that merely accompanies us and which we
GA 8/WCT; GA 5/BW; GA 12/OWL). can establish, expressly or not, as being also
Second, we need to acknowledge that at hand. We do not have a body; rather,
Heidegger appeared to be genuinely per- we are bodily . . . we are somebody who
plexed about how to interpret Dasein from is alive (GA 6.1/N1, 99). This description
the perspective of embodiment. In Being and sets the stage for Heideggers most sustained
Time (23), for example, he recognizes that and systematic treatment of the body in a
Daseins bodily-nature (Leiblichkeit) plays series of seminars with psychiatrists and
a significant role in spatially orienting us in medical students that took place in Zollikon,
the world in terms of our experiences of dis- Switzerland from 195969.
tance and directionality, but does not explain In the Zollikon Seminars Heidegger suc-
how the body does this. Indeed, he appears cessfully fills out the account of embodiment
to dismiss the problem altogether when he that is missing in Being and Time, and this
writes in a parenthetical remark that Daseins helps to clarify why Dasein should not be
bodily nature hides a whole problematic understood as a bounded, biochemical thing
of its own though we shall not treat it here that is physically present (krperhaft). In
(GA 2, 108/BT, 143).7 Later, in his 19667 these seminars, Heidegger makes it clear
Heraclitus seminar, he will refer to Daseins that prior to any scientific or naturalistic
bodily nature as the most difficult problem account that explains what I am as a cor-
(GA 15/HS, 147), and in 1972 he admits that poreal object, I am already existing or bod-
he was unable to respond to earlier criticisms ying forth (Leiben) as a situated, affective,
of Being and Time regarding his neglect of and motile way of being-in-the-world. The
the body because the bodily [das Leibliche] body, from this perspective, is in each case
is the most difficult [problem to understand] my body, and it is not here, like a table

271
THE BODY

or chair, occupying a determinate time and For Heidegger, moods are not to be under-
place (GA 89, 113/ZS, 86). Unlike Krper, stood as discrete sensations or states of
my body is not a self-contained thing; it does mind that take place inside of us (GA
not stop with the skin because it is already 2, 1367/BT, 176). As an embodied way
out there, stretching beyond the corpo- of being-in-the-world, there is no distinc-
real into a shared world as it moves through tion between inner or outer because
its environment, handles equipment, and our emotional lives are already bound up in
engages with others (GA 89, 112/ZS, 86). the world, already situated and entwined in
My body, in this regard, already orients me in public contexts of meaning. In fact, it is this
the world, constituting a perceptual range embodied intertwining that makes it possible
or horizon within which things can be for us to be in a mood in the first place, that
encountered. is, to be in situations where things meaning-
Echoing the earlier accounts of Husserl fully affect as dull, frightening, embarrass-
and Merleau-Ponty, Heidegger refers to the ing, or confusing. This means moods are
body in terms of the spontaneous mediating always working behind our backs prior to
activity that I cannot get behind or objectify any mental intentions, already providing
because it is already opening up the percep- a background sense of what counts and
tual horizon that I exist in. The limit of matters to us in particular situations.9
bodying forth, says Heidegger, is the hori- When, for instance, Heidegger notices Dr.
zon of being within which I sojourn (GA K rubbing his temples at the seminar table,
89, 113/ZS, 87). This mediating activity he immediately senses the meaning of this act
reveals the extent to which my body already because he is already attuned to the situated
possesses a kind of unitary, sensory grip on mannerisms and gestures that are unique to
its surroundings. It is already perceptually the academic world. This particular gesture
directed toward things and understands how reveals that Dr. K. was puzzled and was
to move through its environment; it already thinking of something difficult (GA 89, 115/
encounters things in terms of directions of ZS, 88). Heideggers example reveals that in
right and left and front and back, and tac- bodying-forth, we are affectively open and
itly senses where things are in terms of dis- responsive to specific contexts of meaning,
tance and location (GA 89, 2934/ZS, 232). and this receptivity or world-openness to
Here, direction, distance, and location are the significance of things suggests that we are
not grasped thematically in terms of objects always already in a mood (GA 89, 292/ZS,
in geometric space. I do not, for instance, ini- 231). In this sense, says Heidegger, moods
tially experience my cell phone as an object are like an atmosphere in which we first
that is five meters from the couch. The phone immerse ourselves in each case and which
is already understood in terms of my embod- then attunes us through and through (GA
ied familiarity with a particular living space 2930, 100/FCM, 67).
as something handy, close by, or too far In giving an account of how Daseins
away. This familiarity reveals the seamless bodily nature situates and orients us in the
kinesthetic bond between my body and the world, the Zollikon Seminars provide a
world and it also helps us to get clear about critical supplement to Being and Time and
the bodys role in Heideggers account of help to explain why Heidegger says that all
emotions or moods. existing, our comportment, is necessarily a

272
THE BODY

bodily (leiblich) comportment . . . (GA 89, Time. See, for instance, K. Aho, Heideggers
258/ZS, 206) and that bodying-forth as Neglect of the Body (Albany, NY: SUNY Press,
2009); R. Askay, Heidegger, the Body, and the
such belongs to being-in-the-world (GA
French Philosophers, Continental Philosophy
89, 248/ZS, 200). But it is also important Review, 32 (1999), 2935; D. Cerbone,
to note that the primary aim of Heideggers Heidegger and Daseins Bodily-Nature: What
project is not simply to critique the tradition is the Hidden Problematic? International
of disembodied theorizing as parasitic on the Journal of Philosophical Studies 33 (2000),
20930; M. Haar, The Song of the Earth:
situated and embodied practices of everyday
Heidegger and the Grounds of the History
life. Heideggers aim, rather, is to address the of Being, trans. R. Lilly. (Bloomington, IN:
question of the meaning of Being in gen- Indiana University Press, 1993); T. Kessel,
eral. In this regard, the analysis of every- Phnomenologie des Lebendigen: Heideggers
dayness (Alltglichkeit) in Being and Time Kritik an den Leitbegriffen der neuzeitli-
chen Biologie (Freiburg und Mnchen:
is merely provisional or preparatory (GA
Karl Alber, 2011); D. F. Krell, Daimon Life:
2, 17/BT, 38). Heideggers core concern is Heidegger and Life-Philosophy (Bloomington,
giving an account of how we are appropri- IN: Indiana University Press, 1992); D. M.
ated by and belong to the unfolding histori- Levin, The Bodys Recollection of Being:
cal event (Ereignis) of meaning itself, an Phenomenological Psychology and the
Deconstruction of Nihilism (New York:
impersonal event that opens up a disclosive
Routledge, 1990); F. Schalow, The Incarnality
space or there (Da) prior to my own bod- of Being: The Earth, Animals, and the Body in
ily emergence on the scene. This space con- Heideggers Thought (Albany, NY: SUNY Press,
stitutes all of the possible ways that I, as an 2006); D. Vallega-Neu, The Bodily Dimension
embodied way of being, can understand and in Thinking (Albany, NY: SUNY Press, 2005).
2
For an analysis of the distinction between
make sense of things, including myself. This
Krper and Leib in Husserl see 3542 of
is why Heidegger says that the concept of Ideen zu einer reinen Phnomenologie und
Dasein in Being and Time is often misunder- phnomenologischen Philosophie. Zweites
stood as a reference to ones own individual Buch: Phnomenologische Untersuchungen
existence. The emphasis, for Heidegger, is not zur Konstitution, ed. M. Biemel (The Hague:
Martinus Nijhoff, 1952). English translation:
on the individual but on the Da, on the open
Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology
region or space of meaning that is already and to Phenomenological Philosophy, Second
there. The Da in Being and Time does Book, trans. R. Rojcewicz and A. Schuwer
not mean the statement of a place for a being (Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer, 1989).
but rather it should designate the openness Also see 28 and 62 of Die Krisis der
europischen Wissenschaften und die transzen-
where beings can be present for the human
dentale Phnomenologie: Eine Einleitung in die
being, and the human being also for himself phnomenologische Philosophie, ed. W. Biemel
(GA 89, 156/ZS, 120). (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1954). English
translation: The Crisis of European Sciences
and Transcendental Philosophy, trans. D. Caar
(Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press,
NOTES AND REFERENCES 1970).
3
Husserl, Ideas Pertaining to a Pure
1
There have been a number of commentaries in Phenomenology, Second Book, 167.
recent years that engage Heideggers thought 4
Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology
from the perspective of embodiment as well of Perception, trans. C. Smith (London:
as his failure to address the body in Being and Routledge, 1962), 150, my emphasis. The

273
THE BODY

influence of Husserls account of the body on and Time. See Krells Daimon Life, 3363, esp.
Merleau-Pontys philosophy is well known. 325, n. 17.
Merleau-Ponty described his studies of 6
As of this writing, GA 27, Introduction to
Husserls manuscripts at the Archives in Leuven Philosophy (Einleitung in die Philosophie) has
as une exprience presque voluptueuse. See yet to be translated.
R. Rojcewicz and A. Schuwer, Translators 7
Heidegger should have been aware of Husserls
Introduction to Husserls Ideas II, xvi. For an reflections on the body in Ideas II as he was
excellent comparative analysis of the concep- writing Being and Time. Husserl sent a copy of
tions of embodiment in Edmund Husserl the manuscript to Heidegger in 1925 while he
and Maurice Merleau-Ponty, see T. Carman, was lecturing at Marburg, and one cannot help
The Body in Husserl and Merleau-Ponty, but notice certain similarities regarding their
Philosophical Topics, 27.2 (1999), 20526. accounts of spatial orientation. See Ideas II,
5
Alphonse de Waelhens, The Philosophy of the 412 and Being and Time, 23.
Ambiguous, in Maurice Merleau-Ponty, The 8
See K. Aho, Heideggers Neglect of the Body, 4.
Structure of Behavior, trans. A. Fisher (Boston: 9
See C. Guignon, Moods in Heideggers Being
Beacon Press, 1963), xix. David Krell offers and Time, in eds C. Calhoun and R. Solomon,
a much more accurate accounting of all the What is an Emotion: Classical Readings in
places that Heidegger uses the terms Leib and Philosophical Psychology (Oxford, UK: Oxford
Krper and their various cognates in Being University Press, 1984), 22939.

274
34
Dasein
Franois Raffoul

When Heidegger introduced the term questionableness (Fraglichkeit) is unfolded,


Dasein, as a terminological choice, in Being it includes us in an essential way. Heidegger
and Time, it was in the perspective of pro- presents this implication in What is
viding an access (Zugang) to the question Metaphysics? in the following way: First,
of the meaning of being. An analysis of the every metaphysical question always encom-
being of Dasein (the very task of Being and passes the whole range of metaphysical
Time) must, in the final analysis, allow for problems. Each question is itself always the
the interpretation of that which is asked whole [das Ganze]. Therefore, second, every
about (das Gefragte) in the questioning, metaphysical question can be asked only in
namely the meaning of being, and in fact such a way that the questioner as such is also
presupposes it. The analysis of Dasein is ulti- there within the question, that is, is placed in
mately subordinated to the elaboration of question (GA 9, 103/PA, 82). This betrays
the question of being, Heidegger speaking of that the human being must essentially remain
the provisional (vorbereitenden) character a question, that our essence is question-
of the analysis of Dasein. At the same time, able. As Heidegger writes in Introduction
the term Dasein, which ordinarily means to Metaphysics, The determination of
existence in German, is said to designate the essence of the human being is never an
the being of human being (SZ, 25/BT, 24) answer, but is essentially a question (GA 40,
and the being which we ourselves in each 107/IM, 149). To that extent, it is a matter
case are (SZ, 7/BT, 7). Thus, from the out- of rendering the essence of the human being
set, the problematic of Dasein combines the uncanny, if not dangerous, if it is the case
question of the meaning of being with the that, The human being is to deinotaton, the
most extreme individuation. The question uncanniest of the uncanny (GA 40, 114/IM,
of the meaning of being is the most universal 159). Here one glimpses the intimate relation
and the emptiest. But at the same time the between the questionableness (Fraglichkeit)
possibility inheres of its most acute individu- of Dasein in Being and Time with the dan-
alization in each particular Dasein (SZ, 39/ gerousness (Gefhrlichkeit) of the human
BT, 37). being in the Contributions. Just as Dasein
In the early writings, Dasein arises out of was accessed in Being and Time in terms of
the opening of being in and as a question. the questionableness of being, later the dan-
The question of being is such that, once its gerousness of the question who are we? is

275
DASEIN

the only way for us to come to ourselves missed in their mistranslation of Dasein as
(GA 65, 54/CP2, 44). ralit humaine, or human reality. In fact,
At the time of Being and Time, Daseins the very terminological choice inherent in
implication in the general question of the the notion of Dasein was motivated by the
meaning of being is analyzed as Daseins project to liberate the determination of the
privilege or priority (Vorrang). Dasein has a human essence from subjectivity, but also
privilege in the ontological inquiry because from the definition of animal rationale
it hasand isan understanding of being. (GA 9, 368/PA, 2823). Heidegger indeed
Dasein emerges as what is interrogated stressed in Being and Time that the thinking
(das Befragte) in the question on the mean- of Daseinthat is, the beings that we our-
ing of being because it is that being who can selves aremust avoid terms such as sub-
understand the question of what it means to ject, soul, consciousness, spirit, person, and
be. Further, Dasein does not simply occur even life [Leben] and man [Mensch] (SZ,
among other beings, but rather is con- 46/BT, 45).
cerned about its very being (SZ, 12/BT, 10). With the term Dasein, Heidegger under-
Only a being that can have a relationship to took an ontological questioning on the
other beings and who at the same time has human being, interrogated solely in terms
the possibility of questioning, that is, a being of its being, that is to say, in terms of being
that does not simply appear among other itself. This is what Heidegger clarified in Der
beings, but whose constitution of being is to europische Nihilismus, explaining that in
have in its very being, a relation of being to Being and Time, on the basis of the ques-
this being (SZ, 12/BT, 10), should be inter tion no longer concerning the truth of beings
rogated in its being. Dasein has thus proven but the truth of being itself, an attempt
itself to be that which, before all other beings, is made to determine the essence of man
is ontologically the primary being to be inter- solely in terms of his relationship to Being
rogated (SZ, 13/BT, 12). (aus seinem Bezug zum Sein). That essence
The problematic of an analysis of Dasein was described in a firmly delineated sense
must therefore be situated in the Seinsver as Da-sein (GA 6.2, 194/NIII, 141). The
stndnis, which Heidegger presents, quite term Dasein then became oftentimes hyphen-
simply, as a fact (Faktum) (SZ, 5/BT, 4). ated as Da-sein, in order to stress this sheer
Such understanding is not a human deter- relatedness to being. The term Da-sein, as
mination, but a characteristic of being. This Heidegger specified in his 1949 introduction
is why the privilege of Dasein is not ontic or added to What is Metaphysics? designates in
anthropological, but ultimately ontological. the same stroke the human beings relation
Understanding of being is itself a determi (opening) to being and beings relation to the
nation of being of Dasein [Seinsverstndnis human being: To characterize with a single
is selbst eine Seinsbestimmtheit des Daseins]. term both the relation of Being to the essence
The ontic distinction of Dasein lies in the fact of the human being and the essential relation
that it is ontological (SZ, 12/BT, 11). Dasein of the human being to the openness (there,
is thus the ontological name of the human [Da]) of Being [Sein] as such, the name of
being, and constitutes a radical break with the Dasein [there-being] was chosen for the
traditions of anthropology and subjectivity, a essential realm in which humans stand as
break that Sartre and the early existentialists humans (GA 9, 372/PA, 283, tr. modified).

276
DASEIN

Dasein in the Turn the entire anthropological problematic


is kept at a distance, that the normative
As we saw, the understanding of being is not issue is emphatically and solely the expe-
a property of humans among others, but that rience of Da-sein with a constant eye to
the Being-questionfor it to become
which defines the human being. Humans are
strikingly clear that the Being into
made possible by the understanding of being
which Being and Time inquired cannot
and not the inverse. Accordingly, the under long remain something that the human
standing of being is the ground of the pos subject posits.
sibility of the essence of the human being
(GA 31, 125/EHF, 87, tr. modified). To this
extent, it is not posited by us, but is an event The turn was thus already present in Being
in which we find ourselves among all other and Time, insofar as the thinking of Dasein
beings. With the existence of human beings already exceeded the problematic of sub-
there occurs an irruption into the totality of jectivity: It is rather Being, stamped as
beings, so that now the being in itself first Presence by its time-character, [that] makes
becomes manifest (GA 3, 228/KPM, 160). the approach to Da-sein. As a result, even in
One moves from a thematic of the under- the initial steps of the Being-question in Being
standing of being to that of a happening and Time thought is called upon to undergo
of being. Dasein has its origin in the event a change whose movement corresponds with
[Ereignis]. Therein lies the turn (Kehre) in the reversal [Kehre].1
Heideggers work, from a thinking centered Heideggers thinking thus increasingly
on Daseins openness to being to a think- turned toward the truth of be-ing as such (and
ing that meditates the openness of being to no longer beingness), and inquired into the
Dasein: truth of be-ing out of be-ing itself. Heidegger
considers that his earlier work was still too
The thinking that proceeds from Being attachedreactively or defensivelyto
and Time, in that it gives up the word the metaphysical subjectivistic way of think-
meaning of being in favor of truth of ing, and attempts to think the truth of be-ing
being, henceforth emphasizes the open-
out of itself. The very first task, however,
ness of being itself, rather than the open-
is precisely to discontinue postulating the
ness of Dasein in regard to this openness
of being. This signifies the turn, in which human being as a subject and to grasp this
thinking always more decisively turns to being primarily and exclusively on the basis
being as being. (FS, 41) of the question of being, and only in this way
(GA 65, 489/CP2, 385). Heidegger explained
Heidegger returned to the significance of further the shift in his thinking by stressing
the turn in his letter to William Richardson that, In Being and Time, Da-sein still has an
(1962), to explain that the problematic of appearance that is anthropological, subjec-
Dasein corresponded to a moving away from tivistic, individualistic, etc. (GA 65, 295/
the language of subjectivity, CP2, 233). But, Da-sein, as the overcom-
ing (berwindung) of all subjectivity, itself
One need only observe the simple fact that arises out of the essential occurrence of being
in Being and Time the problem is set up [Wesung des Seyns] (GA 65, 303/CP2, 240),
outside the sphere of subjectivismthat and is now approached from the key word

277
DASEIN

in his thought, Ereignis, that is, from the Heidegger grasps this implication in
happening of the truth of be-ing. Heidegger terms of a certain need: Dasein is required,
explains that the relation between Da-sein implicated in, needed, in the event of be-ing:
and beyng was first grasped in Being and Beyng needs humans [Das Seyn braucht den
Time as an understanding of being, where Menschen] in order to occur essentially;
understanding is meant in the sense of pro- and in turn, humans belong to Beyng [der
jection and that in turn as thrown, i.e., as Mensch gehort dem Seyn] so that they might
belonging to appropriation by beyng itself fulfill their ultimate destiny as Da-sein
(GA 65, 252/CP2, 199, tr. slightly modified). (GA 65, 251/CP2, 198). Further, Heidegger
clarifies that, Beyng is nothing human in
the sense of a human dominion, and yet the
essential occurrence of beyng needs [braucht]
From Dasein to Da-sein: Da-sein and hence also needs the steadfastness
The Between of the human being (GA 65, 265/CP2, 209,
tr. slightly modified). One could not empha-
Thinking from the truth of being itself does size enough the importance of such a needi-
not mean that the reference to the human ness for a redefinition of the human being as
being is abandoned, but rather that there is Dasein, as well as for the determination of
a sort of dislodging of humans into a dimen- the essence of be-ing itself, Heidegger going
sion, which Heidegger calls the between, so far as to state that needing (Brauchen)
from which they become for the first time constitutes the essence of be-ing: being needs
themselves. In the history of the truth of Dasein for its manifestation, and Dasein
being, Da-sein is the essential intervening is needy due to its thrownness. This need
incidence, i.e., the in-cident of that between reveals the co-belonging between humans
into which humans must be dis-lodged in and be-ing. Be-ing needs us because only on
order to first be themselves again (GA 65, the ground of Da-sein . . . does being enter
317/CP2, 251). If the human being is to into truth (GA 65, 293/CP2, 231). To that
become Da-sein, this implies a transforma- extent, the essential occurrence of beyng
tion, the transformation of human beings requires the grounding of the truth of be-ing
themselves (GA 65, 84/CP2, 67), from the and that this grounding must be carried out
anthropological enclosure to the belonging as Da-sein (GA 65, 176/CP2, 138).
to the truth of be-ing (Da-sein). Through this As such, this represents what Heidegger calls
displacing, humans will come to stand in the the counter-resonance (Gegenschwung)
event and remain steadfast there in the truth of needing and belonging, or the counter-
of beyng (GA 65, 26/CP2, 23). What this play between call and belonging (GA 65,
situation reveals is that Dasein is necessarily 311/CP2, 246), a between approached in
in play in the event of be-ing, and that the the Contributions under the expression of
human being, and then again not the human domain of the proper (das Eigentum). It is
being, and indeed in each case in a reaching in this perspective that Heidegger insists that
out and a dislodging, is somehow in play in Da-sein is to be thought as the between, a
the grounding of the truth of beyng. Precisely between clearly marked in the new writing
what is thus question-worthy is what I call of Dasein with a hyphen, as Da-sein. That
Da-sein (GA 65, 313/CP2, 314). between, explicitly contrasted with his

278
DASEIN

earlier vocabulary of transcendence, is the 384). The problematic is therefore neither


play between the enowning throwing call of restricted to nor aimed at the figure of the
be-ing and the belonging of Dasein as stand- people, here relegated to both subjectivism
ing in. Being only holds sway where and when and biologism.
there is Dasein, and in turn Da-sein is only One might ask, then, how is the question,
where and when there is be-ing. Da-sein is who are we, to be taken? And what does
itself by standing in be-ing and is exhausted we mean, or, as Heidegger puts it: which
in such a between. Dasein now designates the ones do we mean in speaking of we? (GA
belonging-together of the human being and 65, 48/CP2, 39). First, Heidegger clarifies, the
Being. Who are we? We are the ones called we is not some given present people, for the
by be-ing, needed by be-ing to sustain its question remains of how what is ownmost
essential sway. to a people is to be determined. Only on
the basis of Da-sein is it possible to grasp the
essence of a people, which means at the same
time to know that a people can never be a
Who are we? goal and a purpose. (GA 65, 319/CP2, 252).
The we thus does not refer to an ontic pres-
A clarification is needed concerning the sense ence or to an actual people or community, but
and role of that we, which might be mis- must be aligned with beyng itself: the ques-
construed, superficially, as the collective form tion of who are we must remain purely and
of the people as opposed to the individual fully incorporated into the asking of the basic
I or singular mine of Being and Time. In question: how does beyng essentially occur?
fact, Heidegger clarifies from the outset that (GA 65, 54/CP2, 44). In the question who
neither the I nor the weunderstood within are we, what is inquired about is not some
the opposition of the individual to the col- given us but rather what is proper to being
lectiveare adequate to determine Dasein. ourselves, that is, to being a self. This is why
In Introduction to Metaphysics, Heidegger any question concerning the we presup-
explained that the selfhood of humanity poses the question of the who. In the question
does not mean that humanity is primarily who are we? the emphasis is on the who:
an I and an individual. Humanity is not this asking about who we are already contains
any more than it is a We and a community a decision about the Who (GA 65, 48/CP2,
(GA 40, 152/IM, 153). One therefore needs 34). Heidegger sees in this circle of the we and
to be careful when attempting too quickly to the who the very reverberation of the turning
interpret the presence of the we as the sign (Widerschein der Kehre). The question who
of the passage from an individualistic prob- are we? aims at a dimension that is said to
lematic to a communal one. Both the indi- be more originary than any I or we. Selfhood
vidualistic and the communal orientations is more originary (ursprnglicher) than any I
are for Heidegger nothing but two variants and you and we. These are as such first gath-
of the traditional metaphysics of subjectivity, ered as such in the self and thereby become
and this is why there is no room at all here each respective self (GA 65, 320/CP2, 253).
for the interpretation of the human being as Dasein names original selfhood, in whose
subject, whether in the sense of the egologi- domain we, you and I, in each case come to
cal or communal subject (GA 65, 488/CP2, our selves (GA 65, 67/CP2, 54).

279
DASEIN

Dasein as Ek-static Standing-in as the open (Z, 282/ZS, 225). This is


Being why he explained that: This being-in-
an-open-expanse is what Being and Time
In late writings and seminars, Heidegger called (Heidegger even adds: very awk-
continued to posit the distinctive role of the wardly and in an unhelpful way) Dasein
human being in the event of being. And how (FS, 69).3 Dasein itself comes to designates
could it be otherwise, if, as he explains in the openness. Dasein must be understood as
Zollikon seminars, there cannot be the being being-the-clearing. The Da is namely the
of beings at all without the human being word for the open expanse (ibid.). The
(Z, 221/ZS, 176)? For the manifestedness of very notion of an understanding of being,
being, Heidegger stresses, what is needed is which had defined Dasein in the early writ-
the [ecstatic] standing-in [Innestehen] of the ings, is reinterpreted as openness: But since
human being in the Da [there] (Z, 221/ZS, the human being can only be human by
176). Now, as we have seen, Daseins being understanding beingthat is, insofar as he
does not lie in subjectivity but indeed in the is standing in the openness of beingbeing
dimension of being itself, especially since in human, as such, is distinguished by the fact
the determination of the humanity of the that to be, in its own unique way, is to be in
human being as ek-sistence what is essen- this openness (Z, 157/ZS, 121).
tial is not the human being but beingas
the dimension of the ecstasis of ek-sistence
(GA 9, 3334/PA, 254). This means that
ecstasis is related to being, and not simply Conclusion: Dasein as
to the reversal of immanent subjectivity. Topological Revolution
The ecstatic essence of existence is therefore
still understood inadequately as long as one Heidegger often states that a leap is needed
thinks of it as merely a standing out, while to access our proper being, a leap from the
interpreting the out as meaning away from subject to Da-sein. Heideggers thinking of
the interior of an immanence of conscious- Dasein leads us to a topological revolution
ness or spirit (GA 9, 374/PA, 284). The through which the human being is dis-placed
out should be taken instead as the open- from the ego cogito and resituated within
ness of being itself, Heidegger proposing the the event of the truth of be-ing. Here lies the
term Instndigkeit to designate this standing topological revolution of the understand-
in the Da of being.2 Today, Heidegger adds, ing of the human being, now conceived of
I would formulate this relation differently. I as the ek-static place for beings coming to
would no longer speak simply of ek-stasis, presence. In his 1949 introduction to What
but of instancy in clearing [Instndigkeit in is Metaphysics? Heidegger rejected the inter-
der Lichtung] (FS, 71). Da-sein is rethought pretation that considered that in place of
as standing-in the truth of being. the term Bewusstsein he substituted Dasein.
Ek-statis is ultimately to be taken as open Any attempt at thoughtfulness is therefore
ness. As Heidegger clarified in the Zollikon thwarted as long as one is satisfied that in
seminars, In Being and Time, being-open Being and Time the term Dasein is used in
(Da-sein) means being-open (Da-sein). place of consciousness. As if this were sim-
The Da [of Da-sein] is determined here ply a matter of using different words! (GA

280
DASEIN

9, 373/PA, 283). With the choice of the term NOTES AND REFERENCES
Dasein, it was not a question of a simple sub-
stitution of terms that would leave the place 1
Martin Heidegger, Preface to William
assigned to the human being undisturbed, J. Richardson, Heidegger. Through
but a revolution in the place of the essence of Phenomenology to Thought (New York, NY:
Fordham University Press, 2003), xviii, modified.
the human being. This is why 2
What is meant by existence in the context
of a thinking that is prompted by, and directed
the term Dasein neither takes the place toward, the truth of Being, could be most
of the term consciousness, nor does felicitously designated by the word instancy
the matter designated as Dasein [Instndigkeit] (GA 9, 374/PA, 284, modified).
take the place of what we represent to 3
In a letter to Roger Munier from 1973,
ourselves when we speak of conscious- Heidegger also explains that his thinking
ness. Rather, Dasein names that places the very one who is questioning, and
which is first of all to be experienced, thus the Da-sein of the human, into question.
He then adds: It is important to experience
and subsequently thought of accord-
Da-sein in the sense that man himself is the
ingly, as a place (Stelle)namely, as Da, i.e., the openness of being for him, in that
the locality of the truth of Being (die he undertakes to preserve this and, in preserv-
Ortschaft der Wahreit des Seins). (GA 9, ing it, to unfold it (FS, 88).
373/PA, 283)4 4
As Heidegger also wrote in Nietzsche II: The
locale of the place of being as such is being
It is in this sense that Dasein is the index of itself. . . This locale, however, is the essence of
man (Die Ortschaft des Ortes des Seins als
a topological revolution of the original being solchen ist das Sein selber. Diese Ortschaft aber
of humans. It is to such a revolution that ist das Wesen des Menschen) (GA 6.2, 357/
Heideggers thinking of Dasein invites us. NIII, 217).

281
35
EREIGNIS
Daniela Vallega-Neu

Since 1936, the year Heidegger began to EREIGNIS (APPROPRIATING EVENT)


write Contributions to Philosophy (Of the AND THE TURNING (KEHRE) IN THE
Event), Ereignis names the very core of how EVENT
Heidegger attempts to think the truth of
being in its historicality.1 Contributions to To think and speak out of the truth of beyng
Philosophy is the work in which Heidegger is possible only if thinking attempts to stay
lays out his thought of Ereignis for the first attuned to an authentic mode of being in
time, but Heidegger develops it further in which the thinker finds himself/herself dis-
volumes following Contributions2 and also placed (Heidegger speaks of a leap) from
in the last period of his writings. both everyday and theoretical modes of being
Heideggers thought of the truth of being in and thrown into the groundless openness of
terms of Ereignis begins with the abandonment being as such. The truth of beyng needs to be
of the transcendental-horizontal approach to sustained in order to occur as truth, and this
the question of being (which marked his ear- is why thinking needs to be (-sein) there
lier fundamental ontology of Being and Time) (da-) in that groundless openness. It is then
in the attempt to speak more inceptually, more that thinking may find itself ereignet, appro-
originally, from within an authentic experi- priated by beyng and beyng in its truth may
ence of being. In the project of Being and Time be experienced and thought as Ereignis, as
being as such is questioned through Daseins appropriating event.3 In other words, out
transcendence. Dasein always already tran- of the experience of being thrown into being,
scends particular beings (Seiendes) such that we experience a disclosing event in which we
in Daseins being-in-the-world the being (Sein) first find also our own being; we experience
of other beings also and thus being as such our being as er-eignet, appropriated in the
is disclosed. The itinerary of Being and Time event thatin turnfirst discloses in this
leads toward the discovery of a temporal hori- appropriation.4
zon out of which being discloses as presence; The appropriating event cannot be repre-
however the path of questioning still goes sented in terms of a linear process such that
toward the temporal horizon of being. In some being appropriates another being,
Contributions, the task is to think out of the namely Da-sein, but instead oscillates between
temporal horizon of being as such, a temporal the truth of beyng and Da-sein, such that
horizon that since the 1930s Heidegger calls both occur simultaneously. Heidegger speaks
the truth of beyng. in this context of the Kehre im Ereignis,

283
EREIGNIS

the turning in the appropriating event.5 He marks our era, such that this lack is sus-
articulates this turning as well in terms of tained in Da-sein.8 Thus the truth of beyng
an oscillation between the appropriating finds an open site. This truth occurs as hesi-
call (Zuruf) and a belonging (zugehren).6 tant withdrawal such that in this hesitation,
The truth of beyng as event discloses only in unconcealment of the concealment occurs.
Da-sein, in the moment of appropriation and The preservation of this unconcealed conceal-
belonging. Furthermore, Da-sein (now writ- ment becomes more and more important in
ten with a hyphen) does no longer designate Heideggers thinking of the event in the vol-
a human entity at all, nor does it designate umes following Contributions. The conceal-
simply human being, although it does require ment belonging to beyng is precisely what
humans as the ones who are (-sein) the there remains concealed and thus forgotten in meta-
(Da), the open site of a historical time-space. physics (the first beginning).9 Thinking,
as it finds itself appropriated and responds
to the appropriating call, is dis-lodged into
an untimely situation. It enters a realm
Ereignis, Attunement, and in-between where it is no longer forgetful of
History the truth of beyng, and yet, in the sense of the
history of a people, the event of appropriation
The appropriating event (Ereignis) is not does not occur, and people remain disposed
something one may willfully engage, but by machination and lived experience. The
there are fundamental attunements or dis- moment in which Ereignis would hold sway
positions (Grundstimmungen, like Angst in historically, would mark an other beginning
Being and Time) that dispose thinking such of history. In Contributions, we need, then, to
that it undergoes the experience of the event. distinguish Ereignis in an epochal sense from
In Contributions, the basic dispositions that Ereignis in so far as it is intimated by the few
transpose into the event of the truth of beyng future ones and sustained in the thinking and
are those of an epoch rather than those of a saying of a single thinker or poet. This single
singular human being. Heidegger mentions thinkers and poets are transposed (appropri-
especially shock (Erschrecken), restraint ated) into the transition into the other begin-
(Verhaltenheit), and diffidence (Scheu). ning and in this transition their thinking and
Disposed by shock, one realizes that in our saying is inceptive (anfnglich).10
epoch being does not occur as an appro-
priating event but rather as a withdrawal
(Verweigerung or Versagung).7 This relates to
the realization that the way beings appear is Ent-eignung (Dis-appropriation)
determined by machination (Machenschaft, and Ent-eignis (ex-propriation)
the dominion of the makeability) and lived
experience (Erlebnis) such that beings are In our epoch of the utmost abandonment of
abandoned by beyng and beyng in its truth beings by beyng, beyng at first is experienced
remains completely forgotten. Restraint as withdrawal, that is, not as appropriation
(which comprises shock and diffidence) dis- but as dis-appropriation, as Ent-eignung.11
poses thinking to remain turned toward the Ent-eignung in this sense has a negative
withdrawal of beyng, toward the lack that connotation; it indicates that in our epoch

284
EREIGNIS

Er-eignis does not (yet) occur and the truth by being and the twisting free of being into
of beyng (especially the concealment belong- the beginning.16 One may interpret this as
ing to it) remains concealed. This is not due a preliminary form of the differentiation he
to a human fault but rather is rooted in the makes in Time and Being (1962) between,
way beyng itself unfolds in the first begin- on the one hand, the appropriating event
ning, namely as presence. as the giving of historical determinations
Later, in The Thing (1950), Heidegger of being (such that this giving is not itself a
speaks of enteignen in a positive sense as a form of history), and, on the other hand, the
letting go in to the proper and in Time historically determined epochs.
and Being (1962), Heidegger speaks of
Ent-eignisagain positivelyin terms of
the originary concealment that belongs to
the truth of beyng even when it occurs as The full expanse of Ereignis:
Er-eignis.12 Da-sein, Gods and Humans
(Zueignung and bereignung),
World and Earth, Beings

Ereignis as Inception In Contributions, besides the relation between


the truth of beyng, being-t/here (Da-sein), and
In ber den Anfang and Das Ereignis humans, Ereignis has other essential dimen-
(19412) Heideggers thinking of the event sions belonging to it. The full expanse of the
moves further into the concealed dimension appropriating event comprises gods and
belonging to Ereignis while venturing to be humans, world and earth, as well as beings; and
more inceptive. Even with previous acquaint- Heidegger thinks Da-sein (being-there) as the
ance with Heideggers Contributions, the vol- in-between of these multiple dimensions.17
ume Das Ereignis remains extremely difficult In Da-seinwhen the appropriating event
to access because of an even more radical occursour being is appropriated in rela-
attempt to speak out of an experiencing of the tion to the gods such that we are assigned
event. Heidegger now characterizes the move- (Zueignung) to the gods and the gods are con-
ment of thinking as departure and down- signed (bereignung) to us. For Heidegger, the
going into the beginning. Downgoing is gods lack being; they are not and need humans
inception of the beginning in its inceptiveness as the ones who sustain the open site of truth
[Der Untergang ist Anfngnis the Anfangs in such that a grounding of Da-sein occurs.18
seiner Anfnglichkeit].13 The event [now] This moment would mark the other begin-
names the inception of the beginning that ning of history; Heidegger calls it a moment of
properly clears itself.14 In ber den Anfang decision; it comprises the passing of the last
he writes: Beginning is the taking into safe god. This moment does not result in a pres-
keeping of the departure [Abschied] into encing of gods (as if they were beings); rather
the abyss.15 Heidegger begins to articulate the gods remain tied to the essential conceal-
the relation between the inceptive thinking ment belonging to the event. This is why gods
and the epochal dis-appropriation of beings and humans emerge in the event both in their
in terms of the passing [Vorbeigang] by separation (Geschiedenheit) as well as in their
each other of the abandonment of beings assigned/appropriated encounter.

285
EREIGNIS

It is within this encounter between gods foreshadows Heideggers thinking of the


and humans that the strife of world and fourfold (Geviert) of gods and humans,
earth as well as the relation to beings are sky and earth. Viewed from the horizon
situated in the thought of Contributions.19 of Contributions, essays like The Thing
With the appropriation of Da-sein is dis- (1950) and Building, Dwelling, Thinking
closed the strife of world and earth20 that (1951) think ahead into an occurrence of
is related to what Heidegger calls the shel- Ereignis such that a sheltering of truth in
tering (Bergung) of the truth of beyng into beings takes places and thus beings gather
beings. The truth of beyng occurs as Ereignis the event of appropriation. Yet whereas in
only when world and earth find an open Contributions Heidegger speaks of the strife
site by virtue of beings, that is, works of art, of world and earth, in the later writings he
deeds, things, and above all and first of all speaks of the relation between sky and earth;
words.21 (Otherwise beings remain ent-eignet, all four elements of the fourfold are said to
that is, dis-appropriated by beyng, as said constitute the worlding (Welten) of the
above.) Thus Ereignis, as the moment of an world. When speaking of the fourfold in the
other beginning of history, occurs only in the essay The Thing, Heidegger thinks that
assignment of the gods to humans and the Ereignis occurs through the appropriating
consignment of humans to gods, in which mirror-play of the fourfold such that each of
Da-sein is grounded such that in Da-sein, the four mirrors in its own way the presence
the strife of world and earth is sheltered in a of the other. Each therewith reflects itself in
being. This would also be the moment of the its own way into its own, within the unity
passing by of the last god. of the four.24 In this context, Heidegger
In the grounding of the truth of beyng, uses the term Vereignung: The mirroring
beyng and beings are transformed into their appropriates [ereignet]by clearing each of
simultaneity.22 Yet this simultaneity does not the fourtheir own essence into the simple
abolish all difference between beyng and appropriation [Vereignung] to each other.25
beings. According to what Heidegger thinks The prefix ver has (in this context) the
during the time he is writing Contributions, sense of an achievement; we may thus trans-
the strife of world and earth functions as a late Vereignung as achieving appropria-
form of medium between the truth of beyng tion. The essay The Thing also contains
and beings. He says that the truth of beyng a different use of the term enteignen than
cannot be directly sheltered in beings but in Contributions. When speaking of the four-
first needs to be transformed into the strife fold, Heidegger will play with a more posi-
of world and earth.23 tive meaning of the prefix ent; this time,
he stresses the sense of letting go or let-
ting free that the term contains (whereas
in Contributions he emphasized the sense
Ereignis as the mirror play of of privation). He writes: Each is expropri-
the fourfold (enteignende ated [enteignet], within their mutual appro-
Vereignung) priation [Vereignung], into its own being.
Heidegger sums up: This expropriative
The relation between gods and humans appropriating [dieses enteignende Ereignen]
and world and earth in Contributions, is the mirror-play of the fourfold.26

286
EREIGNIS

Ge-stell as a preliminary form through the event of appropriationif we


of Ereignis explicitly enter into this relation.

Heideggers meditations on the mirror play


of the fourfold are one way into thinking
the event of appropriation. Another one is Ereignis and Geschick (the
his meditations on Ge-stell, (framework sending of history)
or enframing).27 Through the notion of
Ge-stell, Heidegger reflects further on what In Contributions it remains somewhat ambig-
in Contributions he calls the domination of uous whether Ereignis only names how beyng
machination, calculation, and lived expe- occurs initially, in the moment of decision of
rience. An experience of the truth of beyng the other beginning, or whether Heidegger
as appropriating event first requires that we thinks of the possibility of a whole epoch
experience and acknowledge the abandon- in which appropriation occurs more fully.
ment of beings by beyng. This abandonment Later, in Time and Being, Heidegger makes a
is rooted in beyngs withdrawal that, in meta- clearer differentiation between Ereignis and
physics, issues a technological disclosure the history of being in its epochal forms.31
of beings, which covers over the essential Here, Heidegger thinks of Ereignis in terms
concealment belonging to the truth of beyng. of the sending of epochs and calls the history
A meditation on the essence of technology of being that is sent in the sending Geschick
leads precisely to this essential concealment (destiny):
of beyng out of which may arise an intima-
tion of the truth of beyng as Ereignis. It is In the sending of the destiny of Being,
thus that Heidegger can speak of Ge-stell as in the extending of time, there becomes
a preliminary form of Ereignis.28 manifest a dedication [Zueignen], a
delivering over [bereignen] into what
In Identity and Difference (1957) Heidegger
is their own [Eigenes], namely of being
writes that we need to pay attention to the
as presence and of time as the realm of
claim that speaks in the essence of technol- the open. What determines both, time
ogy: Our whole being everywhere finds and being, in their own, that is, in their
itself challenged [. . .] to devote itself to belonging together, we shall call: Ereignis,
planning and calculating everything. [. . .] the event of appropriation.32
The name for the gathering of this challenge
which places man and being towards each The event of appropriation is nothing
other [einander zu-stellt] in such a way that behind being and time but rather names
they challenge each other is the framework their appropriation, the event of their coming
[das Ge-stell]29 The belonging together of into their own and in relation to each other.
man and beyng through this mutual chal- Heidegger points out that the appropriating
lenging reveals that and how man is appro- conceals itself as it gives time and it gives
priated over [vereignet] to being, and being is being. In the German sentence Es gibt Zeit
appropriated [zugeeignet] to human being.30 (it gives time) the es has a similar func-
Thus, realizing how we are challenged into tion as in the sentence it rains. There is no
the planning and calculating of everything thing that rains. Similarly, there is no thing
reveals our relation to beyng as occurring that gives time or gives being; appropriation

287
EREIGNIS

occurs as the giving, but in such a way that as during Heideggers lifetime explicitly deal with
it gives, it conceals itself. Ereignis. In On Time and Being Heidegger
names the Letter on Humanism, four lectures
As the sending of time and being, the event
given in 1949 to which belong The Thing,
of appropriation is not itself a form of being; Enframing, Danger, and The Turn,
it is unhistorical while it determines the his- the lecture on technology, and Identity and
tory (or histories) of being. Accordingly, for Difference. (TB, 36) We should add to these
a thinking that turns into the event of appro- texts the said lecture and seminar on Time on
Being as well as Four Seminars (FS).
priation as a sending that withdraws or con- 3
Ereignis in German usually means event,
ceals itself (here is where Heidegger speaks of but, like in many other instances, Heidegger
die Enteignis or expropriation in the more likes to play with a wider semantic field that
original sense) the history of Being as what opens up once we hear the word more liter-
is to be thought is at an end.33 In one of the ally by breaking it up into its two semantic
components er- and -eignis. The prefix
seminars held in Le Thor in 1969 Heidegger
er- carries the sense of a beginning motion
again draws the differentiation between or of an achievement, whereas -eignis refers
Ereignis and the history of being: There is to the word eigen, which in German usually
no destinal epoch of enowning [Ereignen].34 means own, but which is also at play in a
Heidegger also specifies in enowning, the word that is familiar to us from Heideggers
Being and Time, namely eigentlich, in
history of being has not so much reached
English proper or authentic. This has lead
its end, as that it now appears as history scholars to translate Ereignis not simply with
of being. In summary, in his later thought, event but also with the neologism enown-
Heidegger understood Ereignis to be the ing, or with appropriation, or, the event of
event of appropriation out of which epochs appropriation.
4
See GA 65, 239/CP2, 188, section 122.
of being occur.35 The event of appropriation
Compare also sections 1336.
itself remains concealed in the way being dis- 5
See GA 65/CP2, sections 140, 141, and 191; in
closes in each epoch, unless thinking enters section 217, for instance, this turning is articu-
the event of appropriation and finds itself as lated as oscillation between appropriating call
appropriated thinking of the event. and belonging.
6
GA 65/CP2, section 217. Zugehren con-
tains the root meaning hren, to hear.
7
See Contributions, the fugue titled Anklang
NOTES AND REFERENCES (translated as Resonating, or Echo) section
50 and following (GA 65, 107ff./CP2, 85ff.).
1
See Heideggers indication of this in ZSD, 46/
8
This relates to being-towards-death as
TB, 43. For earlier uses of the term Ereignis Heidegger elaborates it in Being and Time.
by Heidegger, see William Koch, Richard Only in resolute anticipation of the possibility
Capobianco: Engaging Heidegger, Human of the impossibility of being does being as such
Studies 34 (2011), 2316; and Daniela disclose out of its temporal horizon.
Vallega-Neu, Ereignis: the event of appropria-
9
Compare The Essence of Truth. BW, 130f.
tion, in ed. Bret Davis, Martin Heidegger (Key
10
See the sections on the future ones in
Concepts) (Durham: Acumen, 2010), 141f. Contributions.
2
All these volumes attempt to think being in
11
GA 65, 120/CP2, 95. Heidegger does not use
its historicality out of an experience of being the substantive Ent-eignis in Contributions
as event. They comprise GA 65 (19368), but uses the verbal form: beings remain
GA 66 (19389), GA 69 (193840), GA 70 dis-appropriated (ent-eignet) by beyng.
(1941), GA 71 (19412), GA 72 (1944), and
12
Expropriation [Ent-eignis] belongs to
GA 73 Only a few texts (lectures) published appropriation as such. By this expropriation,

288
EREIGNIS

appropriation does not abandon itself 25


VA, 172. My translation.
rather, it preserves what is its proper [sein 26
VA, 172/PLT, 177. For the relation between
Eigentum], ZSD, 23/TB: 22f. the Ereignis as the mirror-play of the fourfold
13
GA 70, 142. and Heideggers thought of Gelassenheit see
14
GA 71, 147. Bret Davis, Heidegger and the Will (Evanston,
15
GA 70, 11. IL: Northwestern University Press, 2007)
16
GA 71, 84. 2318.
17
GA 65, 310f./CP2, 146f.; sections 190 and 191. 27
ZSD, 38f/TB, 36.
18
GA 65, 470. 28
TB, 53/ZSD, 57.
19
See section 190 of Contributions (GA 65, 310/ 29
Martin Heidegger, ID, 22f/34f. Translation
CP2, 246) where Heidegger even diagrams this slightly altered.
relation. 30
ID, 24/36.
20
Compare Heideggers essay The Origin of the 31
Heideggers meditations especially in ber den
Work if Art. BW, 143212. Anfang (GA 70) and Das Ereignis (GA 71)
21
See The Origin of the Work of Art, where pave the way toward that differentiation.
Heidegger speaks of poetry in a larger sense 32
TB, 19/ZSD, 20.
as encompassing all creation and preserving 33
TB, 41/ZSD, 44.
of a work (BW, 199). For the relation between 34
FS, 61.
language and Ereignis see Vallega-Neu, 35
These epochs are usually equated with the
Poetic Saying, in Companion to Heideggers epochs of Western thought, namely the Greeks,
Contributions to Philosophy; and Dastur, the Middle Ages, Modern Though, and the
Language and Ereignis, in Reading current epoch of technology. But all these
Heidegger, 35569. epochs belong to metaphysics and metaphys-
22
GA 65, 14/CP2, 14. ics may be seen as one large epoch in relation
23
GA 65, 391/CP2, 308. to which Heidegger thinks the possibility of
24
VA, 172/PLT, 177. another beginning of history.

289
36
ETHICS
Franois Raffoul

Introduction and stubborn refusal, despite the increasingly


desperate attempts by his interlocutor, to
Heideggers thought of ethics needs to be state how philosophy can be a guide for con-
approached, from the outset, in terms of what crete affairs in the world. For, as he explains,
he called, in the Letter on Humanism, an only a God can save us, and humans can
originary ethics (ursprngliche Ethik). The only ready themselves . . . to be ready for
first significant aspect of such an expression such an arrival, something that might take,
is that it seeks to capture ethics in relation to we are told, at least 300 years.1 Whatever
being itself, for it is precisely the thinking of the reasons advanced, Heideggers thought,
being that is defined as an originary ethics. it has been concluded, cannot contribute to
Heidegger explains that the thinking which ethics.
thinks the truth of being as the primordial It is true that Heidegger did not propose
element of the human being . . . is in itself the a system of morality, a body of prescriptive
originary ethics (GA 9, 356/PA, 271). This norms or values. It is also well-known that he
already indicates that Heideggers under- took issue with ethics as a discipline (GA 9,
standing of ethics unfolds in terms of being 354/PA 269). Rather, he attempted to rethink
itself, the adjective originary also indica- the very site of ethics, what Derrida, follow-
tive that it will not be an issue of ethics as an ing Levinas, called the ethicality of ethics.
applied discipline, or even normative, which This ethicality lies, as we mentioned, in rela-
would then be applied, but of an originary tion to the very event of being. Heidegger
phenomenon. brackets out the metaphysical understand-
Nonetheless, Heidegger has often been ing of ethics as a system of moral norms and
reproached for his alleged neglect of ethical instead conceives of the ethical in terms of
issues, specifically his inability to provide our relation to being: not some theoretical
or articulate an ethics, or even a perspec- principles to apply, but as the very unfold-
tive for practical engagement in the world. ing of human existence. For instance, when
The simple fact that he never wrote an eth- Heidegger takes issue with ethics as a met-
ics, as he himself admits in his Letter on aphysical discipline, it is with the intent of
Humanism, seems an eloquent fact in this uncovering a more originary sense of ethics
regard. One also thinks here of the famed as authentic dwelling and standing-in the
Spiegel interview, and Heideggers persistent truth of being. When in Being and Time he

291
ETHICS

took issue with the distinction between good This ontological ethicality of Dasein is
and evil, characterized as ontic and deriva- factical through and through. Heideggers
tive, it was in order to retrieve an original critique of traditional ethics was, first,
guilt (Schuldigsein) that is said to be more a critique of its abstract character. As
originary than good-and-evil morality and early as 19212, during the winter semes-
that provides an ontological foundation for ter course at the University of Freiburg
morality (SZ, 286/BT, 264). When Heidegger on Phenomenological Interpretations of
criticized the theme of empathy (SZ, 1245/ Aristotle, Heidegger opposed the belief in
BT, 117), it was not in order to condemn an absolute system of morality, a system
an ethical motif as such but to show how of ethical value and value-relations that are
the problematics of empathy are still too valid in themselves. Instead, he writes of
dependent on Cartesianism and ego-based a concrete factical ethics, which he refers
philosophies. Instead, Heidegger provides to as a living morality (GA 61, 164/PIA,
an ontological analysis of being-with, that 124). Dasein has no predicates but in each
is, the originary being-with-others of Dasein case it is its possibilities. Because Dasein is
that renders moot the question of accessing a way of being, a how and not a what,
another mind through empathy. it can modify or modalize itself into authen-
Ultimately, for Heidegger, as he states in tic and inauthentic modes. The ethical for
the Letter on Humanism, the thinking of Heidegger is situated in factical existence
being is an originary ethics because being is itself, in its specific motion and oscilla-
not some substantial ground but an event tion between the proper and the improper.
that calls for a responsible engagement. Now, in the authentic mode of existing,
we do not go off to some other plane dis-
tinct from factical existence. Authenticity
has no other content than that of everyday
Dasein as an Ethical Notion existance; it is but a modified form of it.
Authenticity is only a modification but not
It could be argued that the concern for a total obliteration of inauthenticity (GA
ethics has been constant in Heideggers 24, 243/BPP, 171). Heidegger clarified that
thought, to the extent that being displays its no values, no ideal norms, float above
own ethicality. This appears clearly in the factical existence. When one considers the
very notion of Dasein, which as concern, Eigentlichkeit/Uneigentlichkeit alternative
care, and responsibility, is defined in ethical in Being and Time, one sees that it is a mat-
terms. Dasein is delivered over to its being, ter of an existence coming into its own, the
entrusted with being or charged with the immanent movement of a radically finite
responsibility for its being: We are our- and open event, and not the application of
selves the entities to be analyzed. The being rules, from above, to a previously an-ethical
of any such entity is each time mine. These realm. Existence thus displays its own ethi-
entities, in their being, comport themselves cality, is ethical through and through, and
towards their Being. As beings with such for that reason does not need to be ethi-
being, they are charged with the responsi- cized from above. In a sense, for Heidegger,
bility [berantwortet] for their own Being ethics is ontology itself; there is no need to
(SZ, 412/BT, 41, tr. modified). add an ethics to an ontology that would

292
ETHICS

have been presupposed as unethical. This is is not that which causes an effect, nor is it
why, as J-L. Nancy writes, Original ethics governed by the value of utility. In fact, in
is the more appropriate name for funda- the Beitrge, Heidegger makes the claim that
mental ontology. Ethics properly is what is genuine thinking is powerless, in the sense
fundamental in fundamental ontology.2 that the inventive thinking [Er-denken]
of the truth of be-ing tolerates no immedi-
ate determination and evaluation, especially
since this power must transpose thinking
Ethics and the Useless into being and bring into play the whole
strangeness of beyng. Accordingly, the power
Heidegger points to this originary dimen- of thinking can never depend on its having
sion of ethics when he takes issue with objective results in beings (GA 65, 47/CP2,
the motif of application. For instance, in 39). This is all the more the case since as we
Introduction to Metaphysics, Heidegger know any calculation of effects produced
stresses the untimely nature of philosophy quickly proves incalculable. Hence the site
(GA 40, 10/IM, 9), as he would still do in of originary ethics is not a subjective agency
the Spiegel interview, and claims that philos- but instead requires the most radical loss of
ophy is in a certain essential sense useless self, and it is in this madness that, properly
(Nutzlos) (ibid.). Indeed, philosophy is attuned, one is drawn toward, opened to, the
not a kind of knowledge which one could gift of Being (VP, 147).
acquire directly, like vocational and tech-
nical expertise, and which, like economic
and professional knowledge in general, one
could apply directly and evaluate accord- Desubjectivizing Ethics:
ing to its usefulness in each case (GA 40, On Decision
10/IM, 9). It is due to its originary dimen-
sion that philosophy is not an applied dis- Another key feature of this original ethics,
cipline, that it cannot be instrumentalized. apart from its uselessness, is thus its radi-
We might add that it is foreign to ethics as cally nonsubjective nature. Ethics is no longer
well, for as we saw above, ethics is not the tied to the subject, but to the event of being: it
application to an an-ethical realm of theo- is not the active manipulation of entities, but
retical principles, but the very motion of an the enactment of being itself. Such an enact-
existence coming into its own. According to ment is not the act of a subjectivity, because,
Heidegger, asking for philosophy to have a as Heidegger says of projection (Entwurf), it
result or a use is actually a demand of tech- is always thrown (Geworfen), and therefore
nological thinking, of what he calls machi- before the subject. This radically nonsub-
nation, Machenschaft. jectivistic approach appears in the motif of
Originary ethics cannot be measured in decision.
terms of results, or production of effects. The Decision is traditionally assigned to a
useless opens the space of ethics, while instru- willful subject and an agent who decides,
mentality closes it. The essence of thinking to such an extent that decision in the end
as originary ethics, Heidegger writes in the becomes only about such a subject. The
very first lines of Letter on Humanism, stress is always on who decides, who has

293
ETHICS

the power to decide, who leads and who the from the enclosure of subjectivity, this
deciders are. In such a context, decision would be one of the main features of the
is identified with subjectivity, and the power ethicality of being.
of such subjectivity. In contrast, Heidegger
attempts to remove decision from the hori-
zon of subjectivity. In the Contributions, he
states clearly that ordinarily, when we speak Ethics as Responsibility
of de-cision (Ent-scheidung), we think of for being
a human act, something carried out, a pro-
cedure. However, decision is not a power Being is thus a matter of a decision, of what
or a human faculty: What is essential here, we might call a responsible decision. For as
however, is neither the humanness of the act there is a decision for being, there also is a
nor the procedural quality (GA 65, 87/CP2, responsibility for being.3 In fact, Heidegger
69). Rather, decision is related to the truth defined Dasein in terms of responsibility in
of being, not only related to it but rather at least three respects: responsibility defines
determined by it alone (GA 65, 100/CP2, the essence of Dasein as a care and concern
79, my emphasis). Decision is no longer for being; Dasein comes to itself in a respon-
about the glorified subject, displaced from siveness to a call; responsibility names the
a subject-based thinking to a thinking that is human beings relationship to being, that
concerned with what the decision is about, is, the cobelonging of being and the human
the decisive. being.
Emphasizing the decisive and the First, the very concept of Dasein means:
decidedness (Entschiedenheit) in deci- to be a responsibility of and for oneself, as
sion (Entscheidung) suggests that in deci- Dasein designates that entity in which being
sion the matter is not already settled, not is at issue. Being is given in such a way that I
already decided. Rather, the matter is to be have to take it over and be responsible for it.
decided. This undecidedness points toward Care, concern, solicitude, anxiety, authentic-
the decidedness of any decision, and is its ity, being-guilty, all are different names for
proper site. As Heidegger puts it, decision such originary responsibility: Dasein is con-
(Entscheidung) thereby is already decid- cerned about its own being, or about being
edness (Entschiendenheit) (GA 65, 102/ as each time its own. This determination of
CP2, 80). De-cision is not a choice between Dasein from the outset defines it as a respon-
given ontic possibilities, but is the essence sibility of being.
of being itself, and in fact truth itself is Second, Dasein is not a pre-given sub-
already that which is to be decided per se ject, but is instead approached in terms of
(GA 65, 102/CP2, 81). Heidegger speaks a response to an event that is also a call,
of a decision for be-ing (Entscheidung fr thematized in Being and Time as the call of
das Seyn) (GA 65, 91/CP2, 93, tr. slightly conscience and in later writings as the call or
modified). Being is what is at issue or to address (Anspruch) of being. Responsibility
be decided in the decision, and decision is is not based on subjectness (accountabil-
about nothing but being. Being as the deci- ity) but constitutes Dasein as the called one
sive, being as the matter of decision, away (responsiveness). There lies the hidden

294
ETHICS

source and resource of responsibility: to be responsibility in Ereignis, the taking-over of


responsible means, before anything else, to a being-appropriated as the way in which
respond, respondere. Playing on the prox- Dasein in its being-with-itself essentially
imity between Verantwortung and Antwort, occurs. Heidegger writes of the taking over
Heidegger explains in the 1934 summer of the belonging to the truth of being, leaping
semester course on Logik als die Frage into the there (bernahme der Zugehrigkeit
nach dem Wesen der Sprache that the deci- in die Wahrheit des Seins, Einsprung in das
sion for being alluded to above is about a Da) (GA 65, 320/CP2, 253, tr. modified).
kind of answering (Antworten) in which we Responsibility then means: appropriated by
take over an answering . . . it is about an the truth of be-ing, and owning up to such
answering for (Verantworten). Responsibility appropriation by sustaining it, enduring and
(Verantwortung) should thus not be under- taking-over the exposure to it.
stood in its moral or religious sense, as respon- Heidegger is very careful to stress that
sibility before the moral law or before God, the projection of the essence of beying is
but is to be understood philosophically as a merely an answer to the call (GA 65, 56/
distinctive kind of answering (GA 38, 121/ CP2, 45), and one sees here how the realm of
LEL, 101). This response or attunement to the ethicalof originary ethicsis located in
the call of being is an original responsibility. the space of a certain call, a call to which a
Thirdly, after Being and Time, Dasein was response always corresponds. Such an origi-
referred to more and more as the called nal responsibility cannot even be character-
one, der Gerufene, having to answer for the ized as human, following Heideggers claim
very openness and givenness of being and be that in the determination of the humanity of
its guardian. To be responsible here means the human being as ek-sistence what is essen-
to have been struck, always already, by the tial is not the human being but being (GA
event of being. Responsibility refers to that 9, 3334/PA, 254). In fact, for Heidegger
event by which being enowns humans, and responsibility is not a human characteristic,
represents human beings very belonging to but instead a phenomenon that belongs to
being as well as their essence as humans. The being itself. It is not I who is the subject
response to the call becomes rethought as of the event of being: on the contrary, I am
belonging to the call, and ultimately as cor- thrown into itthat is, appropriatedby
respondence to being. be-ing, in be-ing, and for the sake of be-ing,
The event of being thus engages an insofar as be-ing is my ownmost, Heidegger
original responsibility, a responsibility for insisting that care is uniquely a care for
being. One notes such original responsi- the sake of beyngnot of the beyng of the
bility in what is called in the Beitrge the human being but of the beyng of beings as
taking-over (ber-nahme) by Dasein of its a whole (GA 65, 16/CP2, 15, modified).
belonging to the truth of be-ing in which In his thinking of ethics and responsibility,
it is thrown (thrown, that is to sayonce Heidegger thus breaks with a subject-based
rethought from be-ing-historical thinking thinking, breaks from the tradition of auton-
appropriated). In paragraph 198 of the omous subject, and with an anthropological
Beitrge, Heidegger would speak of the way of thinking. The entirety of ethics is to be
ber-nahme der Er-eignung, a sort of original recast in terms of being itself, and no longer

295
ETHICS

based on the human subject. Responsibility NOTES AND REFERENCES


names the cobelonging of being and Dasein
(a cobelonging not posited by the human 1
Only a God Can Save Us in T. Sheehan (ed.),
being but rather one in which the human is Heidegger: The Man and the Thinker (Chicago,
thrown). It is in that dimension that we are IL: Precedent Publishing, 1981), 60.
to situate the thinking of ethics, or original 2
Jean-Luc Nancy, Heideggers Original Ethics,
ethics, in Heideggers work. As he put it in in eds Franois Raffoul and David Pettigrew,
Heidegger and Practical Philosophy (Albany,
the Zollikon seminars, To stand under the NY: SUNY Press, 2002), 78.
claim of presence is the greatest claim made 3
See my The Origins of Responsibility
upon the human being. It is ethics (Z, 273/ (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press,
ZS, 217). 2010), chapter 7.

296
37
THE FOURFOLD
Andrew J. Mitchell

Heideggers thinking of the fourfold (das rather have presented it always only in such
Geviert) is a thinking of the relationality of a manner whereby, as a first attempt, I have
things. It names the gathering of earth, sky, sought to make my thinking understandable
divinities, and mortals that Heidegger views in terms of the tradition.1 The fourfold is
as constitutive of the thing. The thing so con- Heideggers thinking on its own terms.
stituted, however, is one that is resolutely
finite and opened to the world beyond it. As
such, the thing can no longer be considered
an object in the sense of a self-contained, The Fourfold
encapsulated, discrete entity that would stand
ever only over and against a subject. Instead, Given this remark of Heideggers, it should
the thing exists relationally, in engagement come as no surprise that the presentation
with the world, and the fourfold is what of the fourfold found in The Thing is not
makes this relational existence possible. stated in the staid language of traditional
The term fourfold first emerges in the philosophy, but veers toward the poetic (the
1949 lecture cycle Insight into That Which same holds for the subsequent presentation
Is held at the private Club zu Bremen while of the fourfold in the 1951 lecture Building
Heidegger was under a teaching ban from the Dwelling Thinking). We read:
French authorities in the wake of the Second
World War. This lecture cyclecomprised of The earth is the building bearer, what
the lectures The Thing,Positionality,The nourishingly fructifies, tending waters
Danger, and The Turnis Heideggers and stones, plants and animals. [. . .]
first lecture appearance after the war and it The sky is the path of the sun, the course
marks the debut of a new configuration of his of the moon, the gleam of the stars, the
thinking, one centered on things. It is thus a seasons of the year, the light and twilight
major step along his path of thought. Indeed, of day, the dark and bright of the night,
in a 1964 letter, Heidegger states in no uncer- the favor and inclemency of the weather,
tain terms that, Apart from the thing lecture, drifting clouds, and blue depths of the
I have never once presented my own think- ether. [. . .]
ing purely on its own terms in publications, The divinities are the hinting messengers
however far it has come in the meantime, but of godhood. From the concealed reign of

297
THE FOURFOLD

these there appears the god in his essence, What this means is that there ultimately
withdrawing him from every comparison is no ground, or no ultimate ground. The
with what is present. [. . .] only traction that we find in this world is
The mortals are the humans. They are through a reciprocal relation of holding each
called the mortals because they are able other afloat. We bear each other, we bear the
to die. Dying means: to be capable of world, but those same others and that same
death as death. (GA 79, 17/BFL, 1617) world bears us up in turn.
With such a flimsy support of thingly exist-
These four elements of the fourfold are what ence, it is no wonder that the earth can be
join together to constitute the relational nothing substantive. Instead what the earth
thing. Each warrants comment in turn. bears is called a fructifying (Fruchtende).
What the earth bears comes to fruition, it
The Earth blossoms into appearance. The earth bears the
sensuous appearance of things. And it is only
The earth is perhaps the most familiar of the in this sense that it can be the material of
four components of the fourfold. The earth things. The earth as sensuous gleam (Glanz)
is materiality. The earth is the material out is what things are composed of. Things do
of which things are composed. But we go not exist materially, they exist phenomenally.
wrong to think this material quality of the They are composed not of inert, dead matter,
earth as anything substantial or stable. To but of shining, phenomenal radiance. They
understand this earth, we must rid ourselves make up a world that reaches out to us, radi-
of such substantialist prejudices. This is just ates to us.
what Heideggers emphasis on the earth as The nature that Heidegger lists in his
a bearer (Tragende) is meant to do. In the depiction of the earthstone, water, plants,
fourfold the earth names the way that things and animalsall make appearances in his
exist as sensuously and materially apparent. work of the late 1940s and 1950s. Each is
Heideggers name for this is bearing. rethought in terms of just this manner of
Bearing is not to be confused with existing, a nonsubstantive bearing relation.
ground (Grund) or grounding. In the Nothing is simply inert, stones speak, rivers
typical grounding scenario, that which is poetize, and both plants and animals move
grounded, the object, is traced back to a sub- past any presumed encapsulation in an envi-
stantive, eternal basis, its essence, for exam- ronment (Umwelt) or disinhibiting ring
ple. What is grounded is dependent upon the (Enthemmungsring).
ground and follows from it. With bearing,
Heidegger indicates instead a cobelonging. The Sky
What is borne (das Getragene) requires its
bearer (der Trger), but it likewise consti- If the earth is the phenomenal appearance of
tutes that bearer through the state of being things, then it needs some space in which to
borne. In a similar sense, we might say that appear. The sky is this space. The ungrounded
a parent is only a parent thanks to the child. earthly appearing that gleams in an unteth-
While the parent bears the child, it is only ered radiance can only do so through a
through the child that the adult first becomes medium capable of receiving it. The sky is
a parent. that medium. Without the sky, there would

298
THE FOURFOLD

be no earth. The two together form the To think the relationality of things, this
dimension, are united in a marriage (GA notion of medium is crucial. If things are to
7, 198/PLT, 218; GA 79, 11/BFL, 10). For the be understood as relational, they are outside
sky to be able to do this, however, it cannot of themselves. This means they must enter
be a mere void. A void would be the correlate a space that is capable of receiving them, a
to the modern object, the absence correlate space suited to them. The sky is this space.
to objective full presence. With the abandon- And what appears under the sky is affected by
ment of a thinking of objective presence, appearing there. Because the sky is not empty
however, we likewise abandon the thought of space or a void, it has an effect upon all that
sheer absence; we abandon the thought of a appears within it. What appears is weathered
void. And the sky is no void. Instead, it is a by the sky. What exists blanches and wears
complex and varied medium, an ether, as away. Whatever appears cannot last for long.
Heidegger says.
The sky is a space of movement and change. Divinities
The change of the sky yields a particular kind
of time, the natural time of heavenly altera- The divinities are messengers, hinting mes-
tion. Day passes into night, the sun recedes sengers of godhood and each of these terms
before the moon and stars. These changes of is crucial for understanding their function in
the day are part of a larger cycle of changes the constitution of a relational thing. By writ-
of the year. The seasons change. These tempo- ing this messengerial role into the thinging
ral shifts are accompanied by changes of the of the thing, Heidegger moves into a new
light. Thanks to the sky, things appear under paradigm of meaning for his later work. As
different lightings, show themselves differ- the researcher in the Dialogue on Language
ently at different times. The color of the sky is (1953) remarks, it would scarcely have
blue, that is to say, neither pitch black nor escaped you that in my later writings the
bright white, but a color between these two, names hermeneutics and hermeneutical
the color of the between and mediation. are no longer employed (GA 12, 94/OWL,
No void, the sky is a textured space. As an 12, tm). In place of this, we find a thinking of
ether, there is a viscosity to it. The density the message. The divinities are the inaugural
of the sky varies and it undulates in accord- moment of this new (nonhermeneutical) the-
ance with the things and relations that run matic of the message.
through it. This nonhomogeneity of the sky Since Heideggers first Hlderlin reading,
is amplified by passing patches of opacity the hint (Wink) has named the way of pres-
(clouds) that appear throughout it. Still more, encing of that which is not simply present.
large swaths of the medium are subject to Hlderlins notion of a flight of the gods
occasional seizures of great violence (storms), is understood as itself a hint. The hint names
releasing untold destructive powers. But that the presence of what is no longer present, it
same sky is capable of matching our mood, announces an absence. But in announcing
of cheering us up (Aufheitern) and elating us. an absence, it is no longer utterly absent. It
It provides a space of relief from our mun- is remarked. The hint thus troubles the very
dane preoccupations, where we might look opposition between presence and absence.
up from our labor (Aufschauen) and open Even more, the hint is understood in
ourselves to change. terms of the trace. Heideggers thinking of

299
THE FOURFOLD

godhood here (first broached in two texts strange nonpresence of death. On the one
from 1946, the Letter on Humanism and hand, death is most our own in that no one
What Are Poets For?) makes this abun- can die our deaths for us, but on the other,
dantly clear. Godhood is the medium of death is nothing we possess, when it is here,
the godly (of the gods), but only insofar as we are gone, and when we are here, it is not.
the element of this godhood is found in the Existence was thus defined by this nonpos-
holy (das Heilige), itself the medium for session of ones own. What is most our own is
the appearance of the hale (das Heile). The no possession and this frustrates the attempts
hale for its part is a mode of presencing that of the ego to seclude itself in isolation, to
resists the total availability of the standing have itself. To be mortal is to be defined by
reserve. Technology would make everything dispossession, by a death we can never have.
unconcealed, yet the hale (das Heile) keeps a What is most my own remains outside of me,
concealment. But it would appear that today and this fact cracks me open, and is thus my
all is standing reserve (Bestand), that there is fundamental opening to world.
nothing hale. As Heidegger explains, today In his later thinking, Heidegger takes this
not only does the holy remain hidden as the notion of death a step further. Now death is
trace of godhood, but even what is hale, the understood as something of which the mor-
trace of the holy, appears to be extinguished tals are capable (vermgen). But this is a
(GA 5, 295/OBT, 221; tm). But it only technical term for Heidegger. The Letter on
appears to be extinguished, it is not yet so. Humanism explained what is most ena-
There still remains a glimmer of concealment bling in this regard as an element, that is, a
and this is what the divinities signal to us, medium: The element is what properly ena-
why there is meaning, and why they can only bles [das Vermgende]: it is the enabling [das
hint at it. Vermgen] (GA 9, 316/PA, 241). The death
The divinities are messengers of this, that the mortal does not possess, but which
between origin and destination and defined by enables the mortal to be mortal, is a death
a meaning they do not possess as their own. that opens them to the outside. Mortals are
They ensure that we remain between presence outside in their death. Death is the medium
and absence, that metaphysical closure yet of mortality.
entails an outside, and that the exposure Consequently, mortals names those beings
to this outside is meaningful. They promise defined by exposure and openness to the
a space of meaning, the space of a message. world. The essential plurality of the name
The things themselves are messaged to us, points to their communal nature. As Building
that is, are meaningful. And this without the Dwelling Thinking explains, mortals dwell
imposition of a meaning structure on the part insofar as, by their own essence, namely,
of the human, a hermeneutic circle in which that they are capable of death as death, they
only Dasein is meaningful. Heideggers later accompany [others] in the use of this capa-
thinking of meaning begins from this. bility so that there may be a good death
(GA 7, 152/PLT, 148; tm). This is dwelling,
Mortals an exposed, relational existence upon the
earth, under the sky, before the divinities,
Death is constitutive for the mortals. In and with others, with the things. Mortals
Being and Time, Heidegger explored the are no longer world-building Dasein, but so

300
THE FOURFOLD

thoroughly members of a community as to depiction of this relationship is somewhat


forego such privilege by participating in the obscure, but this obscurity should not belie
fourfolds play of thing and world. the profundity that is at stake. Heidegger
The presence of mortals within the thing- presents the thinging of the thing, the gath-
ing of the thing does not entail that things ering of the fourfold, as a kind of play, more
only exist for the mortal or that the mortal particularly, a mirror-play (Spiegel-Spiel;
is somehow the source of things. Rather, if GA 79, 19/BFL, 18).
things are understood to be relational, then
those relations must be ones that reach out Each of the four in its way mirrors the
to us. There could not be a relational world essence of the remaining others again.
of things that remained indifferent to us. Each is thus reflected in its way back
into what is its own within the single
Relationality must be absolute or it is noth-
fold [Einfalt] of the four. This mirroring
ing. And this means that we are always
is no presentation of an image. Lighting
already claimed by the world, appealed to by up each of the four, this mirroring
things. This responsibility is the gift of mor- appropriates the essence of each to the
tality. It lets there be a good death. others in a simple bringing into own-
ership [einfltige Vereignung]. In this
appropriating-lighting way, each of the
four reflectively plays with each of the
The Mirror-Play of Things remaining others. (GA 79, 18/BFL, 17)

Earth, sky, divinities, and mortals join Here Heidegger is thinking of the way in
together in creating the finite, relational which the four belong together. We have
thing. But it is not enough to arrange the four proposed understanding the four as consti-
alongside each other. As Heidegger notes, tuting the finite thing. The earth composed
the united four are already suffocated in of its phenomenal radiance. This required
their essence when one represents them only a medium through which to move, the sky.
as individuated actualities that are grounded That mediated appearing was inherently
through one another and are to be explained meaningful, constituted as a message sent to
in terms of each other (GA 79, 19/BFL, us via the divinities, and directly appealed to
18). Instead, we must understand them in us as exposed mortals. The four mirror each
their fouring (Vierung), in their belonging other in that none of them is anything stable
together. or self-identical, but instead are ungrounded,
The thing is a gathering of the fourfold shifting, sent, and dying. The same structure
and this concentration of the four enables of mediated appearance appears in each of
the thinging of the thing. Without this them. Each of the four can thus be said to
gathering, there would be no things. So let us mirror the others.
make no mistake, when Heidegger speaks of But Heidegger goes further than this. To
the coming together of the four, he is speak- understand the thing as relational, the core
ing of the very core or heart of things. itself must be nothing self-same. As Heidegger
He is telling us what transpires in the very explains it, each of the four belongs to the
make up of a thing at its most basic level. others. Mirroring appropriates the essence
Thus it should come as no surprise that his of each to the others. Each is sent out to the

301
THE FOURFOLD

others, reflected over to them, but only in within any of these mirrors. Rather the play
order to be reflected back to itself. Indeed, occurs outside all of them, between them, in
what it itself is, is nothing other than the middle (Mitte) of them. This is the expro-
this originary reflection. Otherwise put, the priative heart of finitude.
four do not have distinct identities that can The fourfold is thus Heideggers attempt
be aligned alongside each other. Each is so to think the utter relationality of things. To
intricately involved with the others that each do so requires breaking with all objectivist
receives whatever identity it has from that presuppositions and prejudices. It requires
relationship. To think the four as mirroring that we no longer see the thing as constrained
is to think them as bouncing past their own from without or even self-contained from
limits. It is to think the identity of the thing within. We think things now relationally
as nothing present. The language of appro- and this means contextually, appearing at a
priation here should not lead us astray. What place and being affected by that placement.
is appropriated is only the constitution of a Because of this, we would go wrong to think
self that partakes in this fourfold, and does of the fourfold and the thing as a new order
so from out of a prior reflection, a prior of being or as opening up a world beyond our
expropriation (Enteignung) as Heidegger current one. Instead the utter relationality of
explains: the thing entails that it is completely given
over to our world, the world dominated by
None of the four insists on its separate contemporary technology. The singular rela-
particularity. Each of the four within this tional structure of the thing is essentially
bringing into ownership [Vereignung] threatened by technological replacement
is much more expropriated [enteignet]
and a transformation into standing reserve
to what is its own. This expropriative
(Bestand). The thing can never abolish this
bringing into ownership [enteignende
Vereignen] is the mirror-play of the four- and still remain the relational thing that it
fold. From it is entrusted the single fold is. Heidegger will ultimately insist that we
of the four. (GA 79, 18/BFL, 1718) think these two together, thing and stand-
ing reserve. And for this reason he can write,
Mirroring thinks the expropriation at the things have not yet ever been able to appear
heart of appropriation and belonging. At the as things at all (GA 79, 9/BFL, 9). Such is
center of the thing is no thing. Or better, at the the condition of finite relationality that the
center of the thing is the middle or medium fourfold presents, to be between, not yet one
(Mitte) through which the radiance of the thing, no longer another.
four passes. The members of the fourfold at
the middle of the thing each give themselves
to and receive themselves from each other. NOTES AND REFERENCES
They appropriate their existence from out
of an original expropriation. In this relation,
1
Letter to Dieter Sinn of August 24, 1964,
cited in Dieter Sinn, Ereignis und Nirwana:
no member of the four remains within itself. HeideggerBuddhismusMythosMystik.
The mirror play takes place beyond the plane Zur Archotypik des Denkens (Bonn: Bouvier
of the mirror. The play does not take place Verlag, 1991), 172, emphasis modified.

302
38
LANGUAGE
John McCumber

Martin Heideggers views on language are senseless. But in spite of that we do run
not only important in themselves, but the up against the limits of language.1
changes in them provide an index to his
philosophical developments and provide a It is not clear whether Wittgenstein is refer-
pathway for relating it to other approaches ring to Being and Time itself or to the lec-
in philosophy, particularly the linguistic ture Introduction to Metaphysics, both of
turn in twentieth-century analytical phi- which had appeared by this time. In either
losophy. The main landmarks for charting case, however, Wittgensteins remark is acute,
Heideggers views on language are Being because at this time Heidegger himself had
and Time (1927), The Origin of the Work not seen the intimate connection between his
of Art (1935), and Remembrance (1943), reawakening of the question of being and the
all of which were published during his topic of language. Only in 1936, with The
lifetime. Origin of the Work of Art, does language
begin to assume fundamental significance
for Heideggera significance that it retains
throughout his later thought.
Early Views: Being and Time In 7 of Being and Time (BT, 2739),
Heidegger approaches language in terms of
In his 1929 fragment On Heidegger, the phenomenological philosophy of con-
Ludwig Wittgenstein makes an observation sciousness he has inherited from Husserl
about the early Heidegger: and reinterpreted via Greek thought (prima-
rily Aristotle). Thus, in allegiance to Husserl,
I can understand quite well (ich kann mir Heidegger conceives language in relation to
wohl denken) what Heidegger means by appearances, not facts or states of affairs;
Being and Angst. The human being
but he develops this understanding via a
has the drive to run up against the limits
reflection on the Greek word logos, which
of language. Consider for example the
astonishment that anything exists. This he understands in terms of the Greek dloun,
astonishment cannot be expressed in the to make clear. Logos is thus primarily a way
form of a question, and there is also no of making appearances clear. It provides
answer to it at all. Everything which we a direct showing of phenomena, rather
might want to say can a priori only be than the conveyance of thoughts or beliefs

303
LANGUAGE

residing in the mind of a speaker to the mind Language is thus introduced, at Being and
of a hearer: Time 7, as a phenomenological tool for
making appearances clear. When Heidegger
communication is never anything like a extends his analysis of language beyond this,
conveying of experiences, for example language remains a tool: it is seen in terms
opinions or wishes, from the inside of of how language helps us Be-in-the-world
one subject to the inside of another.. . .
(150). In such Being, we primarily relate to
Being-with is explicitly shared in dis-
things by using them (6272). In order to
course: that is to say, it already is, only
unshared as something not grasped and use something, I must have what Heidegger
appropriated. (152) calls a context of signification, or what I
will call a script, for dealing with it. Such
scripts can be quite simple: in the case of
The sentence Martin Heidegger was a phi- a knife, for example, they include holding it
losopher, for example, does not function to by the handle rather than the blade, bringing
express a speakers belief about Heidegger; it into contact with something I want to cut,
it brings us to an encounter with Heidegger and so on. Also part of the script is the point
himself. Nor, however, does it express a fact of the whole endeavor: I am cutting cloth
about Heidegger: in contrast to logic-based to make a dress, or cutting a steak in order
approaches to language, Heidegger does not to eat it, and so on. Our everyday life, for
accord priority to propositions. The primary Heidegger, amounts to a movement through
units of language are not truth-bearers cor- such preestablished contexts or scripts.
related to facts, such as sentences of propo- Words clearly play important roles in this.
sitions, but can include anything that helps I am able to identify something as belonging
someone get a clearer view of a phenomenon. to a particular script, for example, when I
This flexibility is in turn derived from have a word for that thing: if I could not call
Heideggers Husserlian view of truth. For something a knife, I would not be able to rec-
Husserl, truth is a matter of the fulfill- ognize it as a knife and could not use it. This
ment of intentions over time: an intentional identity-providing function of language is thus
object (i.e. object of awareness) is true if it a condition of my use of toolsand my use
confirms, or fills in, what was only vaguely of words as well. It is for Heidegger a deeper
present in previous experiences.2 To be true level of language than spoken speech, one
is thus to be part of a temporal process: if, in that he calls discourse (Rede).4 Discourse,
Heideggers example (217) I stand with my the existential-ontological foundation of lan-
back to the wall and say that the picture is guage (150) is thus language insofar as it is
hanging askew, to say that this sentence is viewed, not as a vehicle of communication, but
true means, among other things, that if I turn as the medium in which a human being makes
around I will see that the picture is indeed sense of the world. As such, it is the articu-
askew. If I turn around and see it hanging lation of being-in-the-world itself, and is the
straight, the sentence was false: as Husserl field of encounter of Daseins other two basic
puts it, instead of the [originally] intended properties or Existenziale: understanding,
itself a different thing comes forth, at which which articulates our current situation with
the [original] positing of the intended fails and respect to the future, and state-of-mind, which
it takes on the character of nothingness.3 articulates with respect to the past (3201).

304
LANGUAGE

Not all languages, however, have the same wordless Schweigen, a keeping-silent, which
repertoire of names; we have already seen is indefinite and outside the worldly artic-
Heidegger allude to this when he recurred ulations of both discourse and understanding
to the Greek dloun to clarify the nature of (2523, 273, 296).
language. German does not have that word,
and so is unable to articulate its own nature
as language. The words available in a lan-
guage thus limit the scripts that speakers of The Origin of the Work of Art
that language can follow, and so the under-
standings they can have. My understanding Language moves to center stage for
of something is inevitably conditioned by Heidegger in the 1936 Origin of the Work
the words available to me, and so is always of Art (1935), and it does so at the same
interpretive or hermeneutical. This means time world is demoted from its primordial
that predication is a sort of illusion: S is status as the source of all meaning. Seeking
P, which suggests that entity S simply has to understand the nature of things in gen-
the property P, is really a matter of x as y: eral via an understanding of the nature of
here is how we, given our current language, works of art, Heidegger argues that to every
should take this entity. The traditional view work of art there belongs a material, not
of predication results from an artificially in the traditional Aristotelian sense of a qui-
theoretical frame of mind (13940). escent matter into which the artistic form is
The availability of words, finally, is a func- projected (see OBT, 910), but in the sense
tion of the world. This is because scripts, to of something that is dynamic and configurat-
begin with, are not freestanding: one script ing. Heidegger calls this earth (BT, 212,
can be an ingredient in a more complex script, 237).
and can have simpler scripts as its own ingre- We can begin to understand the role of earth
dients. The scripts available to Dasein, and in the constitution of a thing by recurring
so the words available to it, are thus inter- to an example that Heidegger himself men-
woven; and the totality of interwoven scripts tions (OBT, 43): Albrecht Drers claim that
for a particular Dasein constitutes its world. he did not put the forms of his woodcuts
World is thus the enabling horizon of partic- into the wood from which they were made,
ular scripts, or contexts of signification, and but wrested themout of the grains, stress
the words we actually use grow up to these: lines, and fractures of that particular piece of
words accrue to significations (151). wood. From this we can see, first, that earth
The account of language in this reputedly is pre-human, so that the term conveys the
existential work thus exhibits none of the dynamism of the natural world: the work
individualism so often associated with exis- of art thus originates from the natural sig-
tentialism. Rather, language itself is grounded nificance of the earth (245). Second, earth
on the preestablished significations of the needs to be made clearer, its shifting grains
world. It is the homogenized product of pre- brought out into the open where we can
vious speakers, and is inadequate to express experience them. It is then inherently undis-
my own authentic individuality. Thus the closed, and as such is self-secluding (25).
call of conscience, which summons Dasein The opening-up of earth so that its dynamic
to its ownmost possibility, death, is a traits can be experienced is accomplished by

305
LANGUAGE

humans (whom Heidegger now calls mor- enough to be marked. Only when it is marked
tals) in many ways, but language occupies in that way does H2O become water.
a major place in all of them. Consider water. Prior to somethings being named, then,
Water can obviously be present to a stone it exists in an earthly, dispersed state: its
lying on the bottom of a stream: the water various modes and roles are not explicitly
touches the stone, moves it along down- brought together so it can be experienced
river, gradually grinds it into an ellipsoid, as what unifies them. It is via a things name
and so forth. But the water is not present to that, in Heideggers term, it is first pro-
the stone as water, for there are many other jected onto the various scripts or contexts
dimensions to water as we encounter it: it of signification in which it can subsequently
runs in other streams, falls from the sky, and recur. Speech that does this originary project-
nourishes plants; it can be drunk or bathed ing is what Heidegger calls poetic: poetic
in, used in religious ceremonies, and so on. naming places an earthly, and so natural,
These different occurrences of water con- being into a new set of contexts of significa-
stitute it as the phenomenon that it is for tion, and so into a new world (OBT, 456).
human beings; but they remain unknown to Language, as poetic, no longer is conditioned
the stone. by world; it opens it up (224).
They also remain hidden from essentialist
philosophical accounts of water, such as Saul
Kripkes, according to which water necessar-
ily is H2O.5 The first Heideggerean response Later Heidegger: Poets and
to Kripke is not that he is wrong, that things Thinkers
have no necessary features (that point would
come later), but that this account of water is It is perhaps past time to question the
oversimplified: it subtracts from water all the premise of this article: does not an article on
ways in which we interact with it, relegating Heidegger and Language presuppose that
them to the status of mere appearances. As there is such a thing as language? And is such
Husserl taught, appearances are important. a presupposition consonant with Heideggers
The watery phenomena listed above are thought?
very different from one another. There is no If the fundamental vehicle of language is
reason why what runs through rivers must fall the poetic name, and if the poetic name func-
out of the sky, or that it should also nourish tions as a work of art, then it would appear
plants and humans. It is quite possible, in a that overall discussions of language are
Wittgensteinian spirit, to imagine a tribe who beside the point. For work of art is not
thought that those phenomena in fact had a universal essence that could be under-
nothing to do with one another. One thing we stood apart from encounters with individ-
can see immediately about that tribe is that ual works of art; each such work is unique,
it would have no word for water: no word and its uniqueness is essential to its charac-
that covers the disparate phenomena that our ter as an artwork (37, 3940). True to this,
word covers. The reason we have that word Heideggers later writings on language are
is that our linguistic forebears not only rec- generally keyed to concrete cases of poetic
ognized the role of H2O in those disparate namingthat is, to actual poems or state-
contexts, but thought that role was important ments of great philosophers.

306
LANGUAGE

His later procedure is illustrated by his 1943 which seems fit only for poetic decoration,
essay on Hlderlins poem Andenken,an Heidegger declares, is an [essentially dis-
essay, which, tellingly, carries the exact same closing] word . . . (124). In the course of
title as the poem. Heidegger begins from a his essay, as Emil Staiger notes with some
traditional view of what a poem is: a bounded wonderment, Heidegger actually does dis-
whole of words structured by a single theme, cuss every single word of Hlderlins 59-line
that of remembrance; produced by an author, poem.6
Hlderlin, out of certain circumstances in his As Heidegger views it, the path of the poem
life, and aimed at being clearly understood is the following. The first five lines introduce
by the reader. He begins, in other words, with the basic relationship between Hlderlin,
the poem understood in terms of Aristotles Being (the Northeaster that blows), and
material, formal, efficient, and final causes. the future poets of Germania, the seafar-
This traditional view of the poem begins to ers (10911). The rest of the first stanza and
fail, however, when Heidegger points out that the second stanza describe the poets own
the poems original title (Der Ister) names the trip to France (107). The third stanza shows
Danube and alludes to the Rhine. These are the poet back in his native land, engaged in
the two rivers that flow through Hlderlins dialogue with others there; the fourth begins
native Swabia, nourishing it and relating it to poetize his solitude in his native country,
to the rest of the world (EHP, 106). The ori- and does so by showing how his dwelling in
gin of the poem is thus displaced from the his native land is a nearness to the source
poet to the Swabian earth and its two rivers. (which, presumably, is Being; 15960). The
Another problem with the ordinary fifth and final stanza continues these themes,
understanding of the poem concerns its title. restating the necessity for travel to foreign
Andenken in German usually means remem- lands and the nature of the voyage, culminat-
brance or souvenir. But the poem, in its crucial ing in two different visions of Andenken.
center (the first line of the third stanza) asks One of these, a wandering over the sea, is
a question: where are [the poets] friends? a constant running-toward-the-foreign that
(Wo aber sind die Freunde?) This question is awakens, and consistently forgets again,
about their present location, and so cannot what is ones own. The other is the steady
be answered by memory. And the last line loving gaze backwards to the Source. Neither
of the poem refers to poets as founding of these, Heidegger argues, is the primordial
somethingan act that clearly bears refer- type of Andenken, (1635). There is thus a
ence, not to the past, but to the future. The third type of Andenken, the truest form of
remembrance of the title is then uncanny remembrance for Heidegger, which in dwell-
indeed: it is a remembrance of something ing by the Source does not simply leave the
that is not in the past but (perhaps) in the sea voyage behind but rather makes it into its
future; the rest of the poem, Heidegger says, own authentically disclosed object:
expands on the meanings of such remem-
brance (1079). Remembrance thinks of the location of
True to Heideggers later emphasis on the place of origin in thinking of the
concreteness, the bulk of his essay presents journey of the voyage through the for-
a close reading of the poem: Even the eign. Remembrance thinks of the source
most inconspicuous word and every image because of its reflecting on the sea that

307
LANGUAGE

was traversed, into which the source and perspectivechanges along thematics
flowed out as the river. (171) that are as different from one another as the
watery phenomena mentioned above, but
Through all of this, Heideggers basic proce- which are ultimately unified by the irreduc-
dure is simple. He takes each word or phrase ible ambiguity of the poems title.
of the poem and thinks it through in terms of The three meanings of Andenken, again,
its significance to poetry as Andenken, in the have no clear relationship to one another:
three senses of that word. The seafarers thus wandering and retrieval, leading back to a
become the poets themselves. The braune source, and founding something still futural
Frauen of Bordeaux become participants at cannot be derived either from one of their
the wedding festival of mortals and immor- number or from some more general concept.
tals that gives birth to poetry (12531). The Heideggers main gesture in this essay is thus
dark light of the wineglass becomes the to highlight irreducible ambiguities in the
mortal thoughts through which is expressed meanings of this and its other terms, and to
what the poet has seen, and so on (1413). show how such ambiguity is itself the basic
The poem thus is read as unified, not by a unifying force in the poem. This confronts
determinate theme or message, but by the the ordinary way of understanding the poem
equiprimordial interplay of the different with its own limits. For if we are going to
meanings of the word Andenken. approach words in the usual Western way,
The essay Andenken thus continues as sensible signs of supersensible meanings,
the dimension of language first explored each single word should have a unique mean-
in the Husserlian framework of Being and ing. Heidegger can shatter that usual under-
Time: it does not present, but is the gradual standing by pointing out that the meanings
coming-to-clarity of a single word, Andenken. of some of the words employed by Hlderlin,
In contrast to the graduality of Husserlian or another poet or philosopher, have, rather
versions of intentional fulfillment, however, than a single general meaning, an irreducible
the essay does not progress by establish- plurality of specific ones.
ing and moving along syntactic or semantic In all this the word Andenken functions
connections among the poems component for Heidegger not only in but as a work of
terms. Rather, it interprets the poems move- art. The earth on which it is grounded
ment as one of jerks and contrasts. Thus, is first its own previous existence on the
Heideggers final statement on Hlderlins German language (as remembrance of things
poem is that it is a single articulated struc- past), against which it must fight in the
ture of aberbut or however (172). The poem; a second dimension to its earthiness
German aber, which on Heideggers analysis is the diverse phenomena that come together
is the key on which the poem is structured, in is final ambiguity. The open clarity into
serves to indicate not a smooth development which these mobile elements are brought is
from what has gone before and still less a furnished by the whole of words that is the
logical inference, but precisely the intro- poem itself, structured on the single word
duction of something new and unexpected. aber. The result is that each word on the
And indeed, on Heideggers treatment of the poem is put together with the other words in
poem, both the poem itself and his own dis- ways that have not happened before, so that
cussion of it contain abrupt changes of theme every word meaning in the poem is a new

308
LANGUAGE

one. In this way, language itself founds new 2


Edmund Husserl Cartesian Meditations, trans.
words; and when we take them to heart, we Dorion Cairns (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1970),
934.
can found new ways of life and new worlds. 3
Ibid., 93.
4
See John Sallis, Language and Reversal,
Southern Journal of Philosophy, 8 (1970),
NOTES AND REFERENCES 38198.
5
Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity (Cambridge,
1
B. F. McGuinness (ed.), Luqwig Wittgenstein MA: Harvard University Press, 1980), 116.
und der Wiener Kreis (Oxford: Blackwell, 6
Emil Staiger, Hlderlin-Forschung Whrend
1967), 68. This remark is discussed in detail by des Krieges, Trivium, IV (1946), 215. Also
Michael Murray in his Heidegger and Modern see on this Beda Alleman, Hlderlin et
Philosophy (New Haven, CT: Yale Uiversity Heidegger, trans. Francois Fedier (Paris: Presses
Press, 1977), 803. Universitaires de France, 1959), 1515.

309
39
THE NOTHING
Gregory Schufreider

. . . is it so obvious that every not signi- the question of being can only be properly
fies something negative in the sense of a addressed by thinking nothing.
lack? (SZ, 2856/BTMR, 3312) It goes without saying that nothing is an
elusive topic. Rather than try to pin it down,
The thought of nothing spans virtually the we propose to approach the question from
entirety of Heideggers career, not to men- different directions, in effect, distinguish-
tion the history of Western philosophy. ing five different ways of thinking nothing,
Rather than attempting to provide a survey which are not mutually exclusive. On the
of either, let alone of both, we would like to contrary, we would hope to see the first four
take advantage of a text that is expanded movements, if not converging then at least
across Heidegger career. For the 1929 lec- verging on the fifth.
ture What Is Metaphysics?, (in)famous for
its pronouncement that nothing nothings,
had a Postscript added to it in 1943 and
an Introduction in 1949, entitled The THINKING NOTHING EXISTENTIALLY
Way Back into the Ground of Metaphysics.
Following these developments in Heideggers The nothing with which anxiety brings
thinking will allow us to see his view of noth- us face to face, unveils the nullity by
ing in relation to the tradition of metaphys- which Dasein, in its very basis, is defined
ics while, at the same time, emphasizing ... as thrownness into death. (SZ, 308/
the revisions of his own approach, and not BTMR, 356)
only insofar as he (re)sets the original text
between an introduction and a postscript but What Is Metaphysics? is designed to con-
in that we intend to place all three between tinue a discussion that is pivotal in Being and
the bookends of SZ (1927) and a letter that Time, even if the later will approach the topic
was eventually published under the title Zur of anxietyas a way to get at nothingfrom
Seinsfrage (1955). In this respect, we will a different direction. If the aim of SZ is to
be prefacing our own remarks to What is reawaken the question of being, its strategy is
Metaphysics? with a discussion of nothing to revitalize our sense of being existentially:
in Being and Time and following them with through an analysis of human existence that
an epigraph designed to make it clear that is designed to strike questioners directly by

311
THE NOTHING

raising the question of their own being as a its relation to nothing. On the contrary, that
concrete being. In that case, nothing will Dasein can be invaded by a sense of its own
not be thought as an abstract concept (any nothingness in the experience of anxiety
more than being will) but in terms of what shows an openness to nothing that directs
the text will designate as the facticity of an us to the ontological source of negativity.
individual(ized) Dasein. Anxiety over death not only individuates
Ironically, the fact of Daseins being Dasein but discloses it as the being that it is:
determines it to be a being whose being is a being not only pervaded by a sense of its
pervaded by a negativity that is woven into own nothingness but one that, to be such,
the complexity of its open structure. Not must be exposed to nullitywhich is to say
only in its being-towards-death is Dasein that Dasein must be free to relate both to
shown to be a being that is bound to and for what is and to what is not, and not just with
nothing, but its self-determination requires it respect to its own being.
to become the basis of a nullity insofar as it
must assume responsibility for what it is not,
namely, its thrown facticity. And it must do
so on the basis of a self that it is not (yet): THINKING NOTHING
through the appeal of a call (of conscience) PHENOMENOLOGICALLY
that issues from what amounts to the silent
voice of a missing person. The nothing itself nihilates. (GA 9, 114/
More importantly, when it comes to a PA, 90)
structural negativity, and in direct connec-
tion to SZs scenario of selfhood, death is While SZ had raised the question of the
the ultimate in thrown facticity. This is not source of negativity, its analysis of the not
just a matter of the fact that my life will end itself is postponed in favor of an approach to
but of the facticity of a concrete existence nothing that stresses the facticity of Daseins
that is pervaded by nothing. In thematizing being-towards-death as an existential struc-
a thrownness into death, it must be clear ture of its being. By contrast, in What Is
that Daseins being-towards-death is not a Metaphysics? death will not be mentioned
matter of externalities but designates a struc- insofar as its account of anxiety is developed
tural determination. What we might dub as along the trajectory of Daseins transcend-
an immanent death is not the coincidence of ence, in its freedom to project beyond beings
my eventual demise but is meant to suggest a into nothing.
relation to (my own) nothing(ness) that per- The account of nothing in the 1929 lecture
vades my being existentially. To claim that begins from what one might think of as the
death is immanent is not to say that it can traditional metaphysical approach, which
happen at any time, ontically speaking, but interprets nothing as not-something.
to insist that an ontological relation to noth- This, of course, is to think of nothing in
ing pertains to the temporal structure of my terms of negation; which is to say that such
being as Dasein. an approach aims to show that nothing can-
In that event, the existential character of not be thought in itself but strictly in terms
being-towards-death, as a distinguishing of the negation of something. On the one
feature of human being, does not exhaust hand, this is consistent with the most ancient

312
THE NOTHING

ontology, which claims that nothing cannot Instead, beings withdraw into a whole that
be thought, while, on the other hand, it sup- can neither be grasped intellectually nor
ports the metaphysical aim of showing that instrumentally. In this respect, Dasein may
when we are thinking nothing, we are not be said to face the void that is left insofar as
thinking about something but, on the con- beings have slipped away in(to) a profound
trary, thinking not-something. meaninglessness: present themselves with
Taken to its extreme, however, this a pervasive sense of utter insignificance, in
not-something can be thought more gen- what amounts to a dysfunctional indifference,
erally in terms of the negation of all beings: given the dis-integration, dis-orientation,
of a metaphysical nothingness that may be and dis-sociation that Dasein experiences in
regarded as the annihilation of what is. In anxiety. In the nihilation of these existential
that case, nothing is thought to designate structuresdisrupting our integration into
what Heidegger characterizes as the nega- the midst of beings and the spatial orienta-
tion of beings as a whole. In his view, this tion that goes with it by neutralizing social
will constitute an ontical approach to noth- relationsDasein is faced with nothing, not
ing, not one that understands it ontologically; with any particular being; which is to say
even if it operates more universally: not just that nothing appears along with beings
in terms of the negation of a specific being insofar as they are withdrawing as a whole.
but as the total annihilation of what is. As Heidegger would put it: nothing is there
In contrast to this metaphysical sense of (da) with (mit) beings, not in the nothingness
nothing, arrived at through the theoretical of my being-towards-death but insofar as
operation of a universal negation, Heidegger they appear neither as items of gear nor as
will propose a phenomenological approach objects but as beings pure and simple.
based on a nihilation of beings that takes While withdrawing as a whole, beings
place in anxiety as an experience of nothing nonetheless press in on us in anxiety: oppress
and that is captured in his claim that noth- as well as impress us insofar as we are over-
ing nothings. Instead, that is, of thinking of whelmed by the fact that they are. We are,
nothing as a noun that refers to a universal in other words, struck by the wonder of their
state of nonbeing, he verbalizes the term, sug- being, and precisely in the face of the fact
gesting that we would have to think nothing that they are not nothingwhich is to say
in its operation as the source of negation, not that what is appears insofar as it is, and is
the other way around. In this respect, it is not not nothing. In that event, nothing is thought
just a question of nothing as no-thing but ontologically: not as if it were a being (or, for
of a noth-ing that must be thought of as an that matter, a non-being) but as making an
original event. appearance in a specific way in which beings
In anxiety, Dasein experiences an onto- appear. Moreover, this experience makes it
logical nullification in relation to beings, not clear that all appearances (of beings as phe-
as their ontical annihilation but in relation nomena) are possible only on the basis of
to a nothing that appears at one with nothing: insofar as Dasein must be free from
them in this key mood: in a neutralization an ontical captivity if it is to relate to beings
that renders our ordinary relation to beings in different ways, ontologically speaking. In
null and void, given our inability to engage this respect, the experience of anxiety dem-
with them, either theoretically or practically. onstrates that we are free not only to relate

313
THE NOTHING

to beings but to transcend them in a projec- but struck by the wonder that they are. And
tion into nothing, disclosing an ontological it is in response to this ontological experi-
condition that reveals Dasein in its freedom ence that metaphysics is said to formulate
to relate to their being. its central question, as the why is forced
to our lips insofar as Dasein is exposed to
the nihilation of what is: such that nothing
is revealed as a void into which beings as a
THINKING NOTHING whole are dis-appearing phenomenologi-
METAPHYSICALLY cally and through which the mystery of their
being is disclosed.
[N]othing . . . is the veil of being. (GA 9, In this respect, Heidegger is subjecting
312/PA, 238) metaphysics to a phenomenological de(con)
struction, tracing the (metaphysical) thought
In its way, the 1929 lecture on anxiety still of nothing back to its (phenomenologi-
thinks of nothing in relation to Dasein, cal) roots in the clear night of anxiety, in
albeit in stressing its transcendence (pro- which beings are cleared out of the way in
jecting beyond beings) instead of its factic- order to make room for nothing as a veil
ity (being-towards-death). The approach through which we may catch a glimpse of
will be different in 1943, when Heidegger being. In his view, traditional metaphysics
appends a postscript to the text that links the remains in thrall to beings (as does modern
thought of nothing to the history of Western science) insofar as it thinks of being in terms
metaphysics. of beings: of beings as such and, there-
What must be clear from the start, namely, fore, not of being itself; just as, in limiting
from the title of the lecture, is that the point its thinking to beings, it is bound to inter-
of What Is Metaphysics? is not to conceive pret nothing as not-something, if not as a
of nothing metaphysically but, on the con- non-being. At the same time, while being
trary, to see how thinking nothing phenom- has been repressed in the tradition, a trace
enologically may direct our response to the of it is nonetheless expressed in the formal
question of the essence of Western metaphys- structure of the fundamental question of
ics. In contrast to a traditionally metaphysical Western metaphysics: Why are there beings
approach to nothing, the claim that nothing and not rather nothing? For while the ques-
nothings is designed to describe an event tion here is clearly about beings, a veiled
that happens in a key mood and is thought reference to being may be detected in what
to unlock the essence of metaphysics in its would appear to be a supplementary addi-
relation to nothing, although not in its inter- tion, in the concluding mention of nothing,
pretation as not-something. Unlike fear, albeit in its own negation.
not only is anxiety an experience without While metaphysics concentrates on the
an objectand therefore over nothingbut question of why beings are, Heidegger would
Dasein experiences a nihilation of beings have us face the question of how nothing
insofar as they slip away as a whole into operates in relation to being, in the case of
insignificance, given that we are not taken metaphysics, as a veil or mask that inevita-
up by their practical utility (instrumentality) bly reveals what has been concealed in its
or their theoretical intelligibility (objectivity) history. In effect, nothing holds the place

314
THE NOTHING

of being insofar as it has been forgotten, the mistake of taking it to be a problem of


if not forsaken by Western metaphysics: it value and, as such, fail to see it in relation
operates as a memento of what is missing to the question of being. Put, perhaps, too
in the abandonment of being in the history simplistically, if nothing must be thought
of philosophy. This historic oversight will be ontologically, then being must be thought
emphasized in the Postscript to What Is nihilistically: in terms of a true nihilism,
Metaphysics?. By that time, Heidegger will which thinks through the relation between
be thinking in terms of a history of being being and nothing such that philosophy is in
and the need to overcome metaphysics, if a position to part the veil that has been cov-
we are, once again, and along the lines of ering being, and precisely in an opening to
yet another strategy, to feel the force (this nothing. In this respect, addressing the ques-
time historically) of ontological questioning. tion of being historically will require the for-
Here it will be critical that, while our sense mulation of a nihilistic ontology, in contrast
of being has gotten lost in the tradition in its to what Heidegger would have us think of as
reduction to a question about beings, a trace an onto-theo-logical metaphysics.
of being remains in a reference to nothing
from which we would presumably need to
take our lead, if Western philosophy is to get
back on track. While the 1929 lecture ends THINKING NOTHING
(quoting Plato) by claiming that metaphys- ONTOLOGICALLY
ics belongs to the nature of human being, its
1943 Postscript will be emphasizing the need How does it come about that beings take
to overcome it, just as Heideggers view of precedence everywhere and lay claim
nothing will have undergone further refine- to every is, while that which is not a
ment in what amounts to the Introduction to beingnamely, the nothing thus under-
his Introduction to Metaphysics. stood as being itselfremains forgotten?
(GA 9, 382/PA, 290)
As if to indicate (if only formally) that this
difference is not the same as other differ-
ences, that 1935 lecture course will explic- In 1949, Heidegger will expand the text
itly set the discussion of the relation between of What Is Metaphysics? by adding
being and nothing apart from the other an Introduction to the lecture and its
delimitations of being in Greek philosophy, Postscript. There he will indicate that, to
namely, in its determination through the dis- regroup historically, we need to find The
tinctions between being and appearing, being Way Back into the Ground of Metaphysics,
and becoming, being and thinking, and being in a text that takes its directions from a
and valuing. It is the latter relation (between reconsideration of the Cartesian image of the
being and the good) that Heidegger will find tree of knowledge, whose trunk is physics,
most problematic, as it is introduced in the and branches the various sciences, but whose
work of later Greek philosophy, specifically, roots are metaphysics. And while Heidegger
in Plato, and is said to run through the his- would like to extend the metaphor by attend-
tory of metaphysics, right up to its final vic- ing to the soil in which the tree is rooted,
tim, namely, Nietzsche. For while raising namely, being, a nihilistic ontology would
the specter of nihilism, Nietzsche will make also have to expose the hole in the ground

315
THE NOTHING

through which the roots are free to take root, scarcely know. And while, in the mid-1930s,
and which would be obvious were the pro- he tried to separate an ontological from a
verbial tree to fall, roots and all. For if meta- metaphysical tradition in Western philoso-
physics is rooted in ontology, then the tree phy, hoping to distinguish the branch that
of philosophy would have to be uprooted if runs from Plato to Nietzsche from its roots
we are to face the opening in which Western in early Greek thinking, especially, Heraclitus
thought originates. and Parmenides, by the late 1940s Heidegger
In overcoming metaphysics, and its sub- is having his doubts about ontology, which
sequent forgetfulness, a history of being we take to be indicated by his development
would take us back to its original naming of a mythopoetic alternative to the tradi-
in Greek philosophy. In so doing, however, tional vocabulary of philosophy.
we would face an equally original nihila- As insightful as the thought of the onto-
tion, not just of beings but of being itself logical difference may be, it requires a prior-
insofar as it is thought in relation to noth- ity of being that obstructs a proper access to
ing. Needless to say, the question of the nothing; for while it may not literally bar the
relation between being and nothing is not way (as in Parmenides), ontology represses
only decided in the founding of ontology in nothing (in its captivation with being) as
Parmenides but their association is clear in surely as metaphysics forgets being (in its
Heideggers thinking of the ontological dif- captivity to beings). Not only, then, would
ference. The distinction between being and we have to trace the roots of metaphysics to
beings is not an ontical difference, like the the ontological soil in which it thrives, but
difference between different beings, but is we would have to step back into the open-
designed to indicate the different ways in ing in which the ground of being is prepared.
which the same being can appear ontologi- While metaphysics may well think of beings
cally: as an item of gear or an object, a with respect to their being, such that being is
work of art or a being pure and simple. thought in relation to beings (not as being
In that case, the failure to think through the itself), not even the ontological difference
ontological difference in metaphysics leads will allow us to think of being without beings,
to its confusion about nothing, just as its even if it is not thought theologically. Instead,
failure to think of nothing properly has led we would have to appeal to a pre-ontological
to a confusion about being. If beings are all difference, in which being is thought in rela-
that is, then being will not only be thought tion to nothing: a nihilistic difference that,
of as a being but, at best, as the supreme from the start, was seen to be different from
being insofar as it is thought to be the causal all other differencesas if nothing makes no
ground of other beings. difference at all and, as such, makes all the
The onto-theo-logical confusion (of being difference.
with a being) that riddles metaphysics is Insofar as the original distinctiveness of
presumably corrected in Heideggers phe- being is determined in its difference from
nomenological ontology, in which being is nothing, it is based on the claim that, unlike
associated with a clearing that takes place other differences, being does not have an
in the midst of beings: a time-space opening opposite, so long as we are clear that nothing
for the appearance of phenomena, which is is nothing. In that case, while this may set
said to be more like the nothing that we ontology in motion and initiate the singular

316
THE NOTHING

priority of being in Western philosophy, it is In the end, we must think of nothing not
actually nothing that makes the difference just as an opening to being (when the veil is
here, albeit in its nihilation: makes the dif- parted) or even as an opening in it (as a hole
ference between being and nothing different in the ground) but as an opening through
from those differences in which different which being happens (as an event) in an
elements are opposed to one another (hot original nihilation. The nihilistic operation
to cold, moist to dry, etc.). If nothing can- that is at work in the naming of being in
not be thought of as the opposite of being, Western philosophy is graphically marked in
it is because nothing nihilates itself and, in the marginal comments that Heidegger will
so doing, creates an opening in which being later make to the Introduction to What Is
is determined, seemingly without opposition. Metaphysics?, presumably included after
In that event, what we face in the creation his writing of a letter addressed To the
of ontology is the original nihilation of noth- Question of Being and published in 1955.
ing in the name of being: in a difference that As infamous as the claim that nothing
nihilates itself insofar as it is drawn through nothings, Heideggers revolutionary cross-
its denial as a difference. ing out of being is directed to an abysmal
If ontology represses nothing as surely connection that is opened up through the ,
as metaphysics forgets being, then how in what amounts to a graphic description of
are we to retrace nothing in a nihilation the relation between being and nothing. As
that takes place in the face of being: in its an editorial indication of the nihilation of
self-effacement, given that we would expect a word, the is to be read as an epigraph of
nothing less of nothing? If nothing holds nothing, marked by what would otherwise
the place of being as a sign that stands (in) operate as a self-deleting sign. In this case,
for it, ironically (even if appropriately) des- however, the is left in the text, and not
ignating what is missing in the metaphysi- simply as a sign of deletion but in a nihila-
cal tradition, then how are we, at the end of tion of being that is performed in the act
philosophy, to mark what has been repressed of writing. In that (historic) event, noth-
in the name of being from the start, assum- ing is not thought verbally but through an
ing that the founding of Western ontology inscription that de-scribes being in a nihil-
entails an original exploitation of nothings istic epigraphy that marks the withdrawal
nihilation? of what Heidegger has taken to be the key
word of Western philosophy.
In the graphic depiction of being, the ing
out of being is not a mere negation, even
THINKING NOTHING if it brings the history of both metaphysics
EPIGRAPHICALLY and ontology to an end. Instead, the is
designed to operate as the sign of a cross-
ing (over and out) that points the way to
[T]he essence of nihilism points us toward
a realm that demands a different vocabu- Heideggers Fourfold of earth, sky, divinities,
lary . . . Accordingly, a thoughtful look and mortals. As such, it marks an opening
ahead into this realm can write being between ontological and mythopoetic vocab-
only in the following way: being. (GA9, ularies in what has become a bi-textual cor-
40111/PA, 310) pus. Consequently, if the depletion of being

317
THE NOTHING

completes its history through an inscription a destruction of the history of ontology


of nothing that points to its departing into by remarking on the way in which noth-
the Geviert, then the reference to mortals ing might be (re)inscribed into the text. For
should remind us that, even in the Fourfold, by ing out every sign of being in a radical
death will operate as the shrine of noth- revision of SZ, we would inevitably have to
ing. In the end, then, we might return to the describe our own being as Dasein in a signa-
beginning of SZ, executing its promise for ture act of nihilation.

318
40
ONTOTHEOLOGY
Iain Thomson

Understanding ontotheology, I have long understanding of beingthat is, our most


argued, provides a skeleton key to Heideggers basic sense of what it means for anything
later thinking, unlocking the door to that to begets disclosed, focused, transmitted,
work in a way that shows it to be much more and transformed over time. The history of
unified, coherent, and defensible than previ- being thus presupposes the (initially ver-
ously recognized.1 Simplifying that story here, tigo and so resistance inducing) thesis I call
I briefly explain how Heideggers understand- ontological historicity. Ontological histo-
ing of Western metaphysics as ontotheology ricity is simply the insight that humanitys
emerges as one of the deepest lessons of his basic sense of reality changes with time.
longstanding deconstruction of the history of As Heidegger puts it, what one takes to be
being (section 1) and how it justifies his onto- the real is something that comes to be only
logical critique of the nihilistic spread of our on the basis of the essential history of being
late-modern technological understanding of itself (NII, 376/NIV, 232). Heidegger takes
being (section 2). I then show how this criti- this insight into historicity over from Hegel
cal understanding of ontotheology as the dual (who similarly sought to chart humanitys
core of the tradition of Western metaphys- unfolding shapes of spirit), but purges
ics in generaland as the basis of our own the idea of Hegels implicit teleology and
nihilistic epoch of late-modern technologi- refocuses it to fit his own understanding of
zation in particularmotivates Heideggers Western philosophy as concerned centrally
own positive vision of a genuinely meaningful (albeit unknowingly) to understand what it
postmodernity (section 3), and conclude by means to be.
addressing a cluster of common misunder- The fundamental historical changes in
standings of his view (section 4). humanitys understanding of being are
accomplished by the metaphysical tradi-
tion.2 Heideggers critique of the nihilism
(or meaninglessness) that Western metaphys-
Ontotheology as the dual core ics increasingly generates, however, tends to
of Western metaphysics obscure the pride of place he in fact assigns to
metaphysics in establishing and transform-
The later Heideggers famous history of ing our basic sense of being: Metaphysics
being focuses on the way Western humanitys grounds an age in that, through a specific

319
ONTOTHEOLOGY

interpretation of what is . . ., it gives the and reshaped by the ontotheological tradi-


age the ground of its essential form (GA tion running from Plato to Nietzsche.
5, 75/QCT, 115/OBT, 57). Here Heidegger The best way to see this is to reconstruct
advances the thesis I call ontological holism: the historical emergence of the ontotheologi-
Because everything intelligible is in some cal core of metaphysics (a task we can only
way, if you change our historical concep- briefly summarize here).3 The ontological
tion of what isness itself is, you thereby and theological paths of Western metaphysics
set in motion a transformation in our sense begin when Thales and Anaximander under-
of everything. Hence: Western humanity, in stand the same questionnamely, What is
all its comportment toward entities, and that the final ground (arch) of reality?in
means also toward itself, is in every respect diametrically different ways by seeking this
sustained and guided by metaphysics (GA ground in realitys innermost core and out-
6.2, 309/NIV, 205). By focusing Western ermost horizon, respectively. By understand-
humanitys historically unfolding under- ing the ground of reality as water, Thales
standing of what is-ness is, metaphysics is the Wests first ontologist. Thales teaches
plays a foundational role in establishing and us to look within what-is in order to dis-
transforming our very sense of the intelligi- cover, at its deepest core, that final ground
bility of all things, ourselves included. How out of which everything else is composed,
exactly does Western metaphysics accom- and so to understand being in terms of this
plish this task? final underlying ground (the method our
In a word, ontotheologies are what focus physicists still pursue). Taking the opposite
and disseminate Western humanitys basic approach (which we might now call cos-
sense of what it means to be. What, then, is mological), Anaximander seeks to grasp
an ontotheology, and how does it allow the ground of all things by getting outside
metaphysics to focus and transform our his- them to that ultimate source from which
torically shifting understanding of being? An they finally derive. Taking up this Gods eye
ontotheology is basically a double answer to perspective, Anaximander seeks to vindicate
the question, what (and how) is an entity? the meaningfulness of the cosmic order as a
To put it as simply as possible, if you think wholewhich he does, but only by denying
of reality as a beach ball (like Parmenides that finite existence is intrinsically meaning-
well-rounded sphere), then an ontothe- ful (to exist as a discrete entity is to violate
ology is an attempt to grasp the beach ball the undifferentiated source of all individual
from the inside-out and the outside-in at the things, to which we thus justly return by
same time. Ontotheologies doubly ground ceasing to be). Proclaiming his nihilistic
the entire intelligible order by uncovering cosmodicy from the Gods eye perspective,
both its innermost ontological core and its Anaximander becomes, in Heideggers terms,
outermost theological expression, linking the first theologian.
these antipodal perspectives together so as It took a thinker as great as Plato,
to ground an historical ages sense of real- Heideggers first metaphysician, to give us
ity from the inside-out and the outside-in the first unified ontotheology. Plato implic-
simultaneously. In this way, our changing itly combines Thales and Anaximanders
understanding of the being of entities (i.e. opposite ways of grasping the ground of
of what and how all entities are) get shaped what-is in his own doctrine of the forms,

320
ONTOTHEOLOGY

which explains both the underlying unity of Heideggers controversial reading (which is
all entities and their highest fulfillment out- undeniably reductive but also, I have argued,
side the finite world. The form of beauty in deeply revealing), Nietzsche both completes
the Symposium, for example, explains what and destroys the metaphysical tradition of
unifies all the different kinds of beautiful ontotheological foundationalism when he
things; they are all imperfect instantiations conceives the totality of entities as such
of the perfect form of beauty. As this sug- as essentially will-to-power existing in an
gests, it also explains the highest fulfillment endless cycle of eternal recurrence.5 As
of beauty: the perfect form of beauty itself, Heidegger writes:
an eternal form compared to which noth-
ing in this imperfect, temporal world can The mode in which entities (whose
ever measure up. By again condemning the essentia is the will to power) in their
finite world of human experience by com- entirety exist, their existentia, is the
eternal return of the same. The two
paring it to a standard unrealizable in this
fundamental terms of Nietzsches meta-
life, Plato deeply embeds Anaximanders
physics, will to power and eternal
otherworldly nihilism into the theologi- return of the same, determine entities
cal perspective (Christianity later takes over in their being in accordance with the
Platos transcendence-valorizing, finitude- perspective that has led metaphysics
denigrating perspectivefor example, by since antiquity, the ens qua ens in the
condemning this world as a vale of tears sense of essentia and existentia. (GA 5,
compared to the heavenly afterlifethereby 2378/OBT, 177)
becoming Platonism for the people, as
Nietzsche famously observed. Yet, even In sum, metaphysics understands being (ens
Nietzsche himself inadvertently falls victim qua ens, being as being) in terms of the being
to this nihilism of otherworldliness when he of entities (and thereby misses being as such,
suggests that existence cannot be affirmed a crucial point to which we will return), and
without the unknowable doctrine of eter- it understands the being of entities ontotheo-
nal recurrence).4 logically by grasping entities in terms of both
The ontotheological duality implicit their essence and their existence, that is, both
in Platos forms becomes explicit when ontologically (from the inside-out) and theo-
Aristotle makes it into his conception of logically (from the outside-in). In this way,
primary and secondary substance, or that- metaphysics grasps reality floor-to-ceiling,
ness and whatness (influentially reversing microscopically and telescopically, or, in a
the priority Plato assigned the rational idea word, ontotheologically.
over its empirical embodiment). The medi- Ontotheologies determine entities in
eval scholastics transform Aristotles con- their being (as Heidegger puts it in the pas-
ception into existentia and essentia, thereby sage above) when they doubly anchor an
inscribing this fundamental ontotheologi- epochs historical understanding of being.
cal distinction between the existence and Ontotheologies do this only when they suc-
the essence of entities into the very core ceed in grasping reality from both extremes at
of the metaphysical tradition of conceiving once, temporarily establishing both the micro-
being. This basic metaphysical duality then scopic depths and ultimate telescopic expres-
continues all the way until Nietzsche. In sion of what-is. Successful ontotheologies

321
ONTOTHEOLOGY

uncover and link the deepest and broadest Our late-modern


ways of understanding what and how enti- ontotheology as the engine of
ties are, thereby doubly grounding the under- nihilistic technologization
standing of being that an age finds itself
unable to get beneath or beyond for a time With this background sketch in place, we can
(the time of an epoch). Ontotheologies now understand the most pressing problem
thus supply neither the unshakeable and to which the metaphysical tradition has led
so unchanging foundation (Grund) they us, namely, the growing nihilism of our cur-
seek, nor merely offer us the endless flux rent, technological understanding of being.
of a groundless abyss (Ab-grund); instead, One of Heideggers deepest but most often
they yield a perhaps necessary appearance overlooked insights is that our late-modern,
[Schein] of ground (Un-grund) (GA 40, 5/ Nietzschean ontotheology generates the
IM, 3) for each historical age. nihilistic technologization in whose currents
As a result, historical intelligibility takes we remain caught.
shape neither as a chaotic Heraclitean Our late-modern age is what Heidegger
flux (pace Derrida) nor as an unbroken calls enframing (Gestell), and (like all other
Parmenidean unity (pace Rorty).6 Instead, ages in the history of being) it is unified by
according to Heideggers punctuated equilib- its underlying understanding of being. Our
rium view of historicity (a view I call ontolog- technological understanding of being fol-
ical epochality), our changing understanding lows directly from our Nietzschean ontothe-
of being takes shape as a series of three dras- ology; we tend to understand the being of all
tically different but internally unified and entities as eternally recurring will to power
relatively coherent, overlapping historical that is, as an unending disaggregation and
epochs: the ancient, the medieval, and the reaggregation of forces with no end beyond
modern. (In the end, Heidegger subdivides the perpetuation of force itself. (If I press you
the ancient epoch into the Presocratic and on what this table is, for example, you will
the Platonic, and the modern into the early probably end up saying that it is an arrange-
modern and the late modern, for a total of ment of subatomic particles moving so fast
five ages in the Western history of being, that the table appears solid, when in fact it is
five overlapping historical constellations just a rather temporary and empty form that
of intelligibility.) In each of these epochs, these underlying forces have taken.) Insofar
the overwhelming floodwaters of being are as we implicitly understand what-is through
temporarily dammed (epoch, as readers of this ontotheological framework, not only
Husserl know, comes from the Greek word do we dissolve being into becoming, but we
for to hold backor, as Derrida liked to tend to relate to and so transform all entities
say, to put in parentheses) so that an island into mere resources (Bestand), intrinsically
of historical intelligibility can arise out of the meaningless stuff standing by to be opti-
river of historicity. Ontotheologies are what mized, ordered, and enhanced with maximal
build, undermine, and rebuild these dams, efficiency.
or (if you prefer) what put the parentheses As this Nietzschean, technological
around an epoch, temporarily shielding its ontotheology becomes more entrenched, this
unifying sense of being from the corrosive historical transformation of beings into mere
sands of time. resources becomes more pervasive, and so

322
ONTOTHEOLOGY

(according to the first law of phenomenology, there is somethingwhich is not a thing, not
the distance of the near) it increasingly eludes an entitythat lends itself to and yet also
our critical notice. Indeed, we late-moderns exceeds every metaphysical conception of
come to treat ourselves in the very same terms the being of entitiesconstitutes the sine
that underlie our technological reframing of qua non of the later Heidegger (and the
the world. No longer modern subjects seeking core of the so-called turn). Heidegger strug-
to master an objective world, we are turning gled throughout his life to clarify this crucial
the techniques developed for controlling the phenomenological insight, continually seek-
objective world back on ourselves, and this ing new names with which to attune us to this
objectification of the subject is transform- dynamic and never finally circumscribable
ing us into just another intrinsically mean- ontological excessiveness, this inexhaustible
ingless resource to be optimized, ordered, abundance that, as he nicely put it, gives
and enhanced with maximal efficiency itself and refuses itself simultaneously (GA
whether cosmetically, psychopharmacologi- 9, 335/PA, 255).8
cally, genetically, aesthetically, educationally, What, then, is the difference between
or otherwise technologically.7 The deep- our late-modern technological understand-
est problem with this technologization ing of being and the genuinely postmodern
of reality is the nihilistic understanding of understanding of being for which Heidegger
being that underlies and drives it: Nietzsches calls? A truly postmodern understanding of
ontotheology dissolves being into nothing being needs to push through and beyond
but sovereign becoming, an endless circula- the late-modern understanding of entities as
tion of forces, and in so doing, it denies that nothing but forces caught in an endless proc-
things have any inherent nature, any genuine ess of becoming. For Heidegger, we do that
meaning capable of resisting this slide into when we come to see this nothing not as
nihilism (any qualitative worth, for example, nothing at all but, instead, as the noth-ing of
that cannot be quantified and represented in the nothingthat is, as the way in which we
terms of mere values). post-Nietzscheans first encounter that inher-
ently pluralistic phenomenological excess
that makes intelligibility possible. The cru-
cial differenceindeed, the very difference
Beyond ontotheology: between the danger of nihilistic technolo-
A genuinely meaningful gization and the promise of a meaningful
postmodernity postmodernityis that, whereas Nietzsche
dissolves being into nothing but becoming,
Every previous historical understanding of Heidegger sees this nothing not as empty
being understands being reductively as only of meaning but as the not-yet-a-thing, the
the being of entities, and thereby for- phenomenological noth-ing whereby the
gets being as such, a dynamic ontological abundance of being offers us its inchoate
excess that both informs and partly escapes hints of meaningful possibilities. Rather than
all the ontotheologies (indeed, all the con- preconceiving reality as an inherently mean-
cepts) that attempt to fix it in place once and ingless conglomeration of forces ready to be
for all. I have argued that this insight into reshaped to fit our preconceived ideas or to
being as suchthat is, the recognition that receive whatever values we project onto it,

323
ONTOTHEOLOGY

Heidegger thought that we need instead to texture of the texts all around us (and can
learn to recognize and begin to do justice to even threaten to render us oblivious to it
the ways be-ing continues to offer these most plausibly, if genetic enhancement inad-
meaningful possibilities to us. vertently eliminates our defining capacity for
In other words, a truly postmodern under- creative world-disclosure).9 But Heidegger is
standing requires us to recognize that, when clear that once we recognize this technologi-
approached with a poetic openness and cal current, we can learn to resist it, and so
respect, things push back against us, making develop a free relation to technology in
subtle but undeniable claims on us. We need which it becomes possible to thoughtfully
to acknowledge and respond creatively and use technologies against nihilistic technolo-
responsibly to these claims if we do not want gization, as we do when we use a camera,
to deny the source of genuine meaning in the microscope, telescope, or even glasses in
world. For, only meanings that are at least order to creatively help bring out something
partly independent of us and so not entirely there in the world that we might not other-
within our controlmeanings not simply wise have seen, a synthesizer or computer
up to us to bestow and rescind at will to make a new kind of music that helps us
can provide us with the kind of touchstones develop our sense of what genuinely matters
around which we can build meaningful lives to us, or when we use a word processor to
and loves. Heidegger sometimes describes bring out our sense of what is really there
our encounter with such genuine mean- in the issues and texts that most concern us,
ings as an event of enowning (Ereignis), and so on.
a significant event in which we come into
our own as world-disclosers by creatively
enabling things come into their own, just as
Michelangelo came into his own as a sculp- God and Postmodernity
tor by creatively responding to the veins and beyond the fatalistic
fissures in a particularly rich piece of marble misreading
in order to bring forth his David, just as a
woodworker comes into her own as a wood- Let me briefly address a common misun-
worker by learning to respond to the subtle derstanding of the view outlined here. That
weight and grain of an individual piece of Heidegger thinks metaphysics pervasively
wood, or as teachers comes into their own as shapes historical intelligibility does not mean
teachers by learning to recognize, cultivate, that he thinks there is no way to get beyond
and so help develop the particular talents metaphysics (or that nothing escapes its
and capacities of individual students. reach), so that we are doomed to be its help-
This poetic openness to that which pushes less victims and unwitting perpetrators.10 On
back in reality is what we could call a sen- the contrary, once we learn to discern the
sitivity to the texture of the text, which is specific metaphysical currents in which our
all around us (GA 77, 227/CPC, 147). late-modern age remains caught (by recog-
(This is the seditious way I would like to re- nizing the ontotheology that continues to
Heideggerize Derridas famous aperu, there drive these currents), it becomes possible to
is nothing outside the text.) The current of attend to the crucial phenomena that resist
technologization tend to sweep right past the the nihilistic metaphysics of late-modernity,

324
ONTOTHEOLOGY

phenomena that can thus help lead us into a his philosophical terms of art. Heidegger him-
genuinely meaningful postmodernity.11 self equates the last God with a postmodern
According to Heideggers history of being, understanding of being, for example, when
our basic understanding of the being of enti- he poses the question as to whether being
ties changes drastically over time and yet is will once more be capable of a God, [that
neither a constantly shifting medium we can is,] as to whether the essence of the truth
alter at will nor an unchanging monolith over of being will make a more primordial claim
which we exert no influence. The role human upon the essence of humanity (GA 5, 112/
beings play in the disclosure and transforma- OBT, 85).13 Here Heidegger asks whether
tion of our basic sense of reality occupies a our current understanding of being is capa-
middle ground between these poles of volun- ble of being led beyond itself, by giving rise
taristic constructivism and quietistic fatalism. to other world-disclosive events that would
Heidegger is primarily concerned to combat allow human beings to understand the being
the former, subjectivistic errorthat is, the of entities neither as modern objects to be
error of thinking that human subjects are mastered and controlled nor as late-modern,
the sole source of intelligibility and so can inherently meaningless resources standing
reshape our understanding of being at will by for optimization but, instead, as things
because that is the dangerous error toward that always mean more than we are capa-
which our modern and late-modern ways ble of expressing conceptually (and so fixing
of understanding being increasingly incline once and for all in an ontotheology).14
us. As a result, his rhetorical exaggerations Such exemplary disclosive events are
often lead readers mistakenly to conclude what Heidegger calls an Ereignis or event
that he makes the converse error of fatalistic of enowning. In such events, entities, the
quietism himself (and thus that he thinks being of entities, and Dasein all come into
humanity is completely passive with respect their own by disclosing being as such. For
to our fundamental metaphysical positions example, Van Goghs painting of A Pair
concerning the truth of entities as such and of Shoes (1886) allows Van Gogh to come
as a whole, at best able to prepare for some into his own as a painter by bringing paint-
vague postmodern understanding of being ing into its own (as Derrida saw, Heideggers
whose contours we cannot yet anticipate). Van Gogh paints the truth of painting itself
That, however, is a superficial misreading of by painting the a-ltheiac or earth-worlding
his view. disclosure that painting is), and the art-
Indeed, Heideggers oft-quoted line from work also discloses the being of entities in
his famous Der Spiegel interview, Only its ownmost by allowing us to understand
another God can save us, is probably the being not simply as equipmentality (as in
most widely misunderstood sentence in his division 1 of Being and Time) but, instead,
entire work. By another God, Heidegger to recognize even the understanding of
does not mean some otherworldly crea- being as equipment as a partial understand-
tor or transcendental agent but, instead, ing of being made possible by a deeper phe-
another understanding of being.12 He means, nomenon it does not exhaust, namely, being
quite specifically, a post-metaphysical, as such.15 In other words, Heidegger thinks
post-epochal understanding of the being of that only an understanding of being as
entities in terms of being as such, to use both informing and exceeding (yielding and

325
ONTOTHEOLOGY

overflowing, lending itself to and withdraw- 2011), so I refer to the relevant chapters of
ing from) all those efforts, practical and the- those books below.

2
Heidegger thinks great poetry and other
oretical, by which we disclose our historical
world-disclosive artworks first embody the
worlds can move us beyond the nihilism understanding of being than a metaphysician
of modern subjectivism and late-modern universalizes in a successful, epoch-grounding
enframing into a genuinely meaningful ontotheology (see Thomson, Heidegger, Art,
postmodernity. and Postmodernity, chs 12).

3
On the historical emergence of metaphysics
Rather than despairing of the possibility
as ontotheology, see Thomson, Heidegger
of such an inherently pluralistic, postmodern on Ontotheology, ch. 1. On the links that
understanding of being ever arriving, moreo- join ontology and theology, see Thomson,
ver, Heidegger thought it was already here Heidegger, Art, and Postmodernity, ch. 1.
(as suggested earlier, historical ages overlap),
4
See Friedrich Nietzsche, Beyond Good and
Evil, trans. W. Kaufmann (New York: Vintage,
embodied in the futural artwork of artists
1966), 3. On how Nietzsche falls victim to
like Hlderlin and Van Gogh, simply needing the very otherworldly nihilism he diagnosed
to be cultivated and disseminated in myriad (and for a partial defense of Heideggers
forms (clearly not limited to the domain of controversial interpretation of Nietzsche), see
art, pace Badiou) in order to save the onto- Thomson, Heidegger, Art, and Postmodernity,
ch. 1; and Iain Thomson, Transcendence and
logically abundant earth (with its inex-
the Problem of Otherworldly Nihilism: Taylor,
haustible plurality of enduringly meaningful Heidegger, Nietzsche, Inquiry, 54.2 (2011),
possibilities) from the devastation of tech- 14059.
nological obliviousness, thereby leading us
5
Nietzsche ended the dual foundationalism of
beyond many of the deepest problems we now ontotheology by postulating that reality is
nothing but forces struggling against other
face. When Heidegger stresses that thinking
forces so as to maximally perpetuate force
is at best preparatory (Vorbereiten), what itself, and that reality exists (seen from the
he means is that great thinkers and poets go Gods eye view) as an endless cycle of cosmic
ahead and make ready (im Voraus bereiten), becoming. That Nietzsche thus cuts the strings
that is, that they are ambassadors, emissar- of foundationalism does not stop his ontothe-
ology from becoming the groundless ground
ies, or envoys of the future, first postmodern
for our own late-modern age.
arrivals who, like Van Gogh, disseminate and 6
See, for example, Jacques Derrida, Whos
so prepare for this postmodern future with Afraid of Philosophy? Right to Philosophy 1,
the unobtrusive sowing of sowers (GA 5, trans. J. Plug (Stanford: Stanford University
21011/OBT, 158).16 Press, 2002), 123. Whereas Derrida was
skeptical of Heideggerian epochality because
he thought the unity it claims to read off
history was in fact a distorting philosophi-
cal projection, Rorty made it clear (in a
NOTES AND REFERENCES personal conversation) that he was skeptical
of historicity, since he did not believe human
1
Space constraints require this chapter to beings had changed much in the last 2,700
simplify views developed in Iain Thomson, years. Rorty said that if you time-travelled
Heidegger on Ontotheology: Technology back to ancient Greece and could speak the
and the Politics of Education (Cambridge: language, everyone would be pretty much like
Cambridge University Press, 2005) and Iain us. By contrast, Derrida sometimes suggests
Thomson, Heidegger, Art, and Postmodernity that even among contemporaries, indi-
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, vidual idiolects are so pervasive that genuine

326
ONTOTHEOLOGY

understanding, if it occurs, is an amazing creative thinking.) Yet, Heidegger also though


accomplishment. See, for example, Jacques that as this danger grows, so does the promise
Derrida, Monolingualism of the Other; or, of a postmodern understanding of being. On
The Prosthesis of Origin, trans. P. Mensah the noth-ing, see Thomson, Heidegger, Art,
(Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1998). and Postmodernity, ch. 3, and see ch. 7 for
7
On this crucial difference between moder- the relation of this nothing to the greatest
nity and late-modernity and its dangerous danger and the saving power. On Heideggers
technological consequences, see Thomson, critique of technologization, see Thomson,
Heidegger on Ontotheology, ch. 2 and Heidegger on Ontotheology, ch. 2. See the
Thomson, Heidegger, Art, and Postmodernity, fatalistic misreading in, for example, Dana
chs 2 and 7. Belu and Andrew Feenberg, Heideggers
8
The later Heideggers search for names with Aporetic Ontology of Technology, Inquiry,
which to convey being as such yielded a 53.1 (2010), 119.
long succession of different terms of art for 11
See Thomson, Heidegger, Art, and
this be-ing that gives itself to intelligibil- Postmodernity, chs 3 and 7.
ity (the nothing, earth, be-ing, being 12
Heidegger writes: The Last God: Wholly other
written under a cross-wise striking-through, than the past ones and especially other than the
the it of there is/it gives [es gibt]) as well Christian one (GA 65, 403/CP2, 319).
as for the way it gives itself (the noth-ing 13
Here the truth of being is shorthand for
of the nothing, altheia or dis-closedness, the way an understanding of the being of
the presencing of presence, the difference, entities (i.e. a metaphysical understanding
the fourfold, even the event of enowning of the truth concerning entities as such and
[Ereignis]). With such poetic names Heidegger as a whole or, in a word, an ontotheology)
tries to neither separate nor hypostatize this works to anchor and shape the unfolding of
be-ing and its giving (by privileging presence an historical constellation of intelligibility.
over presencing, for example, or by treating Its essence is that inexhaustible source of
intelligibility as the gift of a given entity, such historical intelligibility the later Heidegger
as an ontotheological creator God). In so calls being as such, an actively a-ltheiac (i.e.
doing, he seeks to get behind the ontotheologi- ontologically dis-closive) Ur-phenomenon
cal tradition to recover an encounter with that metaphysics eclipses with its ontotheological
inexhaustibly pluralistic non-identical same fixation on finally determining the being of
that metaphysics sought to bifurcate and deter- entities. (That being as such lends itself to
mine once and for all (see Thomson, Heidegger a series of different historical understandings
on Ontotheology, ch. 1). of the being of entities rightly suggests that
9
See note 10. it exceeds every ontotheological understand-
10
My ambiguous parenthetical might be a bit ing of the being of entities.) The essence
misleading because Heidegger thinks that the of humanity refers to Daseins definitive
nothingthat is, the active nothing of the world-disclosive ability to give being as such
nothing, the subtle and inconspicuous hints of a place to be (to happen or take place);
that which is not (yet) a thingdoes escape it refers, that is, to the poietic and maieutic
the reach of modern metaphysics and so can activities by which human beings creatively
help lead us beyond it. That the reach of our disclose the inconspicuous and inchoate hints
late-modern ontotheology could become total offered us by the earth and so help bring
is what Heidegger calls the greatest danger, genuine meanings into the light of the world.
and it is likely to happen only if, in our 14
That the God needed to save us is a
ongoing quest for genetic optimization, we postmodern understanding of being is one of
unintentionally engineer away our essential the central theses of Thomson, Heidegger, Art,
capacity for world-disclosure. (Heideggers and Postmodernity (see esp. chs 1, 3, 6, 7, and
dystopian vision is lent some support by the 8). On Heideggers view of God and religion,
recent spate of reports suggesting that intel- see also Thomson, Transcendence and the
lectual performance enhancing drugs diminish Problem of Otherworldly Nihilism.

327
ONTOTHEOLOGY

15
See Jacques Derrida, The Truth in Painting particularly receptive thinkers pick up on
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987), broader tendencies happening independ-
discussed in Thomson, Heidegger, Art, and ently of their own wills (in the world around
Postmodernity, ch. 3. them or at the margins of their cultures,
16
As this suggests, historical ages are not for example) and then make these insights
simply dispensed by some superhuman central through their artworks and philoso-
agent to a passively awaiting human- phies (see Thomson, Heidegger, Art, and
ity. Rather, actively vigilant artists and Postmodernity, chs 13).

328
41
RELIGION AND THEOLOGY
Ben Vedder

During his whole live Heidegger has been in proper context one must refer to his Letter
discussion with religion and theology. But on Humanism, wherein religion is located
the way he did it is not easy to make under- in the neighborhood of the thinking of being
standable from a classic philosophical point (PA, 23976). Yet religion maintains its own
of view, because Heidegger criticizes the clas- tension with regard to both sides: if we grasp
sic metaphysical philosophy, as we all know. religion completely from a (ontotheologi-
A dominant tendency of a philosophical cal) philosophical point of view we tend to
understanding of religion is to make religion neutralize it; on the other hand, if we con-
itself into a part of philosophy. This is par- ceive it simply as poetic expression, we
ticularly apparent where all forms of religion tend to be philosophically indifferent to it.
get absorbed into an ontotheological phi- These tensions urge us to take up the ques-
losophy. In such cases religion is understood tion of Heideggers position. It turns out that
from a concept of God, which is, as a philo- Heideggers thinking is, in the end, a theologi-
sophical idea, the beginning and the end of cal thinking of a specific kind. It is a theology
philosophical rationality. Hegels philosophy in which he avoids every connection to an
is perhaps the clearest example of this ten- ontotheological concept of God. His think-
dency. When ontotheology is taken up in this ing of being tends toward a poetic theology
way, however, certain possibilities for under- of naming the gods, which is both a prais-
standing religion are foreclosed. But regard- ing and an invocation of them. According to
ing Heidegger it is a question whether he Heidegger the thinking of being is a movement
speaks as a philosopher or as a theologian. no longer in accordance with the thinking of
This problem is most clear in Heideggers faith or of divinity (Gottheit). Each of these
exclamation: Only a God can save us!1 is heterogeneous in relation to the other. The
How can a philosopher exclaim that experience of the thinking of being manifests
only a God can save us? It is my view that itself rather as a topological disposition, that
Heideggers thinking on religion occupies a is, as an indication of a place characterized
place between the forms of poetic and philo- by availability. It is a topological disposition
sophical speaking. To understand the poetic for waiting for, though not expecting, the
aspect of Heideggers language, one must turn reception of being, as a place for the happen-
to his interpretations of Hlderlin (EHP). ing of being. Therefore Heidegger states that
And to give his philosophical expression its he does not know God; he can only describe

329
RELIGION AND THEOLOGY

Gods absence. His atheistic philosophy (in religion (especially if it makes no reference
the sense of an ontotheology) maintains an to the facticity of the human being) is pure
openness toward the possible reception of nonsense.3 Such nonsense evolves out of
religious gods. a lack of piety, that is, a merely theoretical
The young Heidegger grew up as a semi- approach that fails to attune itself to the fac-
narian in a ahistorical neoscholasticism. ticity of life. Thus, Heideggers endeavors to
Only later, after he stopped studying theol- destruct ontotheology have their roots in his
ogy, he became more interested in the his- experience that theistic and theoretical con-
toricity of religion through his reading of ceptuality is not appropriate to understand
Friedrich Schleiermacher. He started to reject the facticity of life.
a theoretical approach to religion while nev- Through his explication of the notion of
ertheless endeavoring to preserve the piety historicity, Heidegger was able to find a path
of philosophyincluding the piety of the leading out of the closed religious world in
philosophy of religion. In a certain sense one which he was raised. This rupture takes place
could call this the prehistorical Heidegger.2 with his encounter with Schleiermacher.
The term prehistorical refers to the timeless Through Schleiermachers thinking,
character of scholastic and neo-scholastic Heidegger was offered the possibility of iso-
Catholicism, the intellectual environment lating the religious as the absolute; and in so
out of which Heidegger emerged, and the doing, he was led away from both theology
period prior to his adoption of a historical and theoretical philosophy in his thinking.
perspective. But at the same time he devel- Out of this engagement, Heidegger was able
ops a persistent questioning toward the to conclude that the religious is none other
ontological and temporal as the earlier than the historical, due to the fact that the
and prior. This persistent questioning he radicality of a personal position is only to be
understands as piety. uncovered within history.
After Heidegger had finished his stud- Heidegger directed his philosophy toward
ies in theology and philosophy he became the facticity of human being, which will be
more interested in phenomenology. Where developed as the historicality of Dasein. The
the object of phenomenology is concerned, attempt to think facticity was his guiding inter-
he attempts to remain radically atheistic, yet est during this early period, and it is from the
on the other hand, he seeks to be pious and standpoint of this interest that his approach
devoted when it comes to this same object. to religion must be understood. As the win-
The pious person here is the devoted ascetic ter semester approached in 1920, Heidegger
who understands his object as it demands to announced his upcoming lecture course, enti-
be understood, that is, from out of its fac- tled Introduction to the Phenomenology of
tical character. Only when philosophy has Religion (PRL). Heidegger asks whether the
become fundamentally atheistic can it deci- kairological moment, which is important in
sively choose life in its very facticity, and early Christianity, can be preserved within
thereby make this an object for itself. Because the history of the actualization of life and
philosophy is concerned with the facticity the unpredictability of the eschaton. It could
of life, the philosophy of religion must be potentially be understood as a possibility that
understood from that same perspective. For we ourselves have or something that is under
Heidegger the very idea of philosophy of our control, so that the future that withdraws

330
RELIGION AND THEOLOGY

from us becomes part of our own planning. put into perspective, where one can see how
Yet, if it were to be understood thus, the spe- it opposes the understanding of facticity.
cific character of the kairos would then be Heidegger seeks an atheistic philosophy, or
lost in a totalizing form of calculation. The at the very least, a philosophy without an a
future would then be conceived in the end priori concept of God.
as a horizon of consciousness out of which Heidegger understands faith as the natural
experiences evolve in a certain order. For enemy of philosophy (PA, 53).
what takes place with regard to the content Faith appears as a possibility of existence,
in the moment of the kairos can itself never yet one that implies death for the possibil-
be deduced. ity of the existence of philosophy. The fun-
Heideggers interpretation of Saint Paul damental opposition of two possibilities of
and of Augustine is an elucidation of this. existence cannot be realized by one person
Heideggers quest for truth is no longer in one and the same moment. Yet neither
devoted to the highest being, as was the case excludes a factical and existentiell taking
during his early studies in Freiburg. Rather, seriously of the other. This does not mean
Christian religion has to be understood out that the scientists in each respective field
of its own situation and out of the presuppo- must behave like enemies. The existentiell
sitions contained within it. It should not be opposition between faith, on the one hand,
taken up from a philosophical framework, as and philosophical self-understanding, on the
if from the standpoint of some highest being, other, must be effective in its scientific design
precisely because the philosophical idea of a and in its explications. And this must be
highest being hinders our understanding of done in such a way that each meets the other
facticity, and with this, religion as an expres- with mutual respect. This can be undertaken
sion of facticity. In Heideggers thinking, the more easily where one sees more sharply the
orientation toward the highest is instead different points of departure. Christian phi-
reformulated as a historical orientation. We losophy, therefore, is in Heideggers view a
see this change actualized in Heideggers ear- square circle.
liest writings, and it involves as well the philo- Nevertheless, one can thoughtfully ques-
sophical paradigm with which he approaches tion and work through the world of Christian
religion. What we are left with, then, is a reli- experience, the world of faith. This would be,
gion that is an expression of historicity. then, theology. Heidegger sees in theologys
Heidegger looks for a better philosophy, dependence on philosophy a lack of great-
but not for a new faith that would be a faith ness in theology itself. Only ages that really
without philosophy. In his complete devotion no longer believe in the true greatness of
to philosophy, he distances himself from reli- the task of theology arrive at the pernicious
gious philosophical approaches, in which a opinion that, through a supposed refurbish-
religious a priori is supposed. He distances ment with the help of philosophy, a theology
himself as well from a conciliation of faith can be gained or even replaced, and can be
and reason that would reduce faith to rea- made more palatable to the need of the age.
son, as in the philosophies of Kant and Hegel. Philosophy for originally Christian faith is
Nor does he assume the harmony of faith foolishness (IM, 8). If Heidegger rejects the
and reason at which Thomistic philosophy philosophical paradigm with which reli-
aims. Instead, the metaphysical paradigm is gion is usually approached, the question of

331
RELIGION AND THEOLOGY

from where stems the ontotheological philo- without a theology for Heidegger is, however,
sophical approach of religion arises. This no longer a question within the domain of
ontotheological approach is at work even philosophy and metaphysics. He determines
today. Heidegger sees its origin in Aristotles metaphysical philosophy as ontotheology.
philosophy. For Heidegger, Greek philosophy The question of being as a question is forgot-
reaches its climax in Aristotle and is deci- ten in philosophy. Rather, it is within what he
sive for the whole of Western philosophy. calls the domain of thinking. The motive
Therefore, Aristotles thinking is a normative of philosophy, strictly speaking, has disap-
point from which the philosophical tradi- peared from philosophy, but it has been pre-
tion can be determined more precisely. The served in the thinking of being. This domain
well-thought-out way in which Aristotle fol- of thinking is, in a sense, a counter paradigm
lows the motive of philosophy marks at the to philosophy in which the question of being
same time the limit of the whole tradition, is not answered with an entity that represents
which becomes visible now as a finite possi- the highest way of being, the whole of being
bility for thinking and as a temporary answer and the cause of being.4
to the question of being. Heideggers criticism with regard to the
Already, in his earliest writings, Heidegger metaphysical concept of God is especially
emphasizes the relation between ontology directed toward the concept of God as cause.
and theology in Aristotles first philosophy. In the wake of Aristotle, being is understood
Heidegger sees the metaphysical tradition as actualitas. The highest representation of
as an ontotheological tradition that follows actualitas is an entity, which as a determin-
from the tendency for philosophy to forget its ing characteristic has this actualitas in the
original motive. This tendency is due to the purest way. This means that it is actus purus.
fact that understanding has its concrete pos- Being in the first and the purest way is proper
sibility for being actualized in being free from to God. Such a metaphysics does not tran-
daily concerns, which places the possibility of scend the level of entities, because it does not
theorizing against the background of the fac- understand the difference between being and
ticity of life. Theorein is the purest movement entity (ontological difference). On the one
that life has available to it. Because of this, it hand, it speaks about being as a characteris-
is something God-like. But for Aristotle the tic of entities and is only understood as this
idea of the divine did not arise in the expli- characteristic (actualitas as determination of
cation of something objective that was made the dominant understanding of an entity). On
accessible in a basic religious experience; the the other hand, it sets as the ground of enti-
theion is rather the expression for the highest ties another entity, which possesses the crite-
being-character that arises in the ontological rion for being an entity in the most perfect
radicalization of the idea of being. way. In a certain sense, God is an exemplary
Being is understood from a normative instance of being as actualitas, of something
perspective, from the perspective of the high- that actualizes completely. This idea of actu-
est way of being. Connected with this is the alization is also present in the modern ideal
highest way of moving, which is pure think- of the self-actualization of the human being.
ing. This also determines the way Christianity But Heidegger does not understand human
speaks about the highest being of God. being from the perspective of self-actualization.
The question of whether there is ontology The quest for meaning is a quest for the whole

332
RELIGION AND THEOLOGY

space in which man can exist. This whole can- fear. With the appearance of godlessness, he
not become a fixed property. In the end, we must remain near to the Gods absence.
are not that which makes us possible, for it In Heideggers view, what happens in our
is earlier than and prior to us. Man is under- time is that the ontotheological temple of
stood by Heidegger as an entity that cannot metaphysics is crumbling; the death of God is
appropriate the whole of his conditions of a symptom if this crumbling of metaphysics.
possibility, because he cannot appropriate his According to Heidegger and Nietzsche, the
temporality that is always earlier. death of God is a historical event, which means
The implications of the ontotheological a history (Geschichte), a story. It is an event
structure of metaphysics are worked out on that makes history. The nature of this history
the basis of Heideggers interpretation of can be continued, be it the history of a God or
Nietzsche. Heidegger considers Nietzsche, a hero, but it is a history next to other histo-
just like all great thinkers in philosophy since ries. This history is the history of the bereave-
Plato, to be an ontotheological philosopher. ment of a God. This does not mean that this
Entities are only entities out of the unifying history itself has a God, for God is also sub-
principle of the Will to Power according to jected to the destinies of history (Geschick). It
Nietzsche. Therefore, Nietzsches metaphys- is a history that makes history. In Heideggers
ics is, as ontology, at the same time a theology. view, historicity is connected with the histori-
This metaphysical theology is a specific kind cality of Dasein. This historicality is still there
of negative theology, its negativity shown in when God is dead, and even when the human
the pronouncement God is dead. (QCT, being, as causa sui, is dead.
53112). Nevertheless it remains metaphys- As a counter-paradigm to the metaphysical
ics, be the God living or dead. idea of God, Heidegger introduces the diffi-
Where God is dead, he is absent. This is cult notion of a last God (CP1, 28593). The
something different from the denial of God in last God is totally other to the Christian God,
atheism, which remains tributary to ontothe- it is a passing God. This presupposes that this
ology. The loss of God, however, is not thought God is not explicable from the perspective of
within metaphysics, that is, as ontotheol- entities, whether the entity be anthropologi-
ogy. Heidegger thinks this experience of the cal or ontological. Understanding the divine
absence of God as an experience of the poets. from a perspective or framework in which
Metaphysics cannot experience the loss of God is the fulfillment of a maladjusted human
God because it is theologically structured. For need for certainty goes against the possibility
the poet, on the other hand, the absence of of experiencing the last God. The last God
God is not a lack; it is not an empty space is without a reference or presupposition of
that needs completion. Nor is it necessary to something eternal and unchangeable. This
appeal to the God that one is used to. It is points to a theology that is completely
about presenting and holding out the absence historical, because its subject is historical: a
of God. The poet can live in a domain of deci- passing God. But Heidegger would never call
sion where ontology is not necessarily theo- this theology, because all (metaphysical)
logically structured, since in poetry the poet theology presupposes the theos, the God as
has to seek, but not into the divine. In poetry an eternally present entity; and it does this so
there is no a priori divine entity. It is the poets certainly that everywhere where (metaphysi-
care to face up to the lack of God without cal) theology arises, the God already flies.

333
RELIGION AND THEOLOGY

It is not sufficient to say in the era of nihil- presencing of Being. But this is something of
ism that God is dead or that transcendental which man as causa sui is not capable.
values pass away; rather, one must learn to From the perspective of man in the near-
think a Gods being, as well as its truth, as ness of the fourfold, Heidegger prefers to
passing-by. It is no longer the God of meta- keep silent with regard to theology insofar as
physics or the theistic God of Christianity. It it is dominated by a subjectivistic anthropol-
is the metaphysical conceptuality that hin- ogy. Someone who has experienced theology
ders to think the passing-by God. in his own roots, both the theology of the
As said before the Letter on Humanism Christian faith and that of philosophy, would
plays a crucial role with regard to Heideggers today rather remain silent about God when
position toward the way he considers notions he is speaking in the realm of thinking (ID,
like the gods and the holy. Here he asks how 545). With these words, Heidegger points
the thinking of being makes possible the out that when one keeps silent it is not only
thinking of the divine. It is no accident that due to a lack of knowledge but to dissociate
Heidegger rejects the reproach of atheism oneself from ontotheology and its fusion with
with regard to his thinking. With the exis- Christian theology. Whether there is a place
tential determination of the essence of the here for negative theology is very doubtful,
human being, nothing is decided about the because negative theology remains paradig-
existence of God or his non-being any matically connected with ontotheology.
more than about the possibility or impossi- It is also important to ask which role
bility of gods. He does not speak out about the holy plays in Heideggers view of the
the existence of a God or godhead, but this divine. It seems that there is no direct con-
is because he thinks about the possibility and nection between naming the holy and think-
framework within which something like a ing of being. In the postscript to What is
God has to be thought. Metaphysics? Heidegger writes that think-
With regard to the framework of the highest ing, obedient to the voice of being, seeks from
entity and the self-actualized human being, the being the word through which the truth of
subjectivistic and anthropological interpreta- being comes to language. Of like provenance
tion of humanity is most radically rejected in is the naming of the poet (PA, 237).5 Because
Heideggers notion of the fourfold (Geviert). poetizing and thinking are most purely alike
The fourfold indicates the unity of earth and in their care of the word, they are at the same
sky, divinities and mortals. The divinities are time farthest separated in their essence. The
the beckoning messengers of the godhead. thinker says being. The poet names the holy.
Out of the hidden sway of the divinities, the This kinship and difference make further
God emerges as what he is, which removes examination of the relation between being
him from any comparison with beings that are and the holy more urgent.
present. The mortals are the human beings. Heidegger links the experience of the holy
But human beings are not mortal because of to the experience of being as wholesomeness.
the finitude of life; they are mortals because Ontotheology is an understanding of being
they can die. To die means to be capable of in which God and the gods do not have a
death as death. And this means to experience place. As long as there is a forgottenness of
death as the shrine of Nothing. As the shrine being in ontotheology, there is also a for-
of Nothing, death harbors within itself the gottenness of the historicality of the gods.

334
RELIGION AND THEOLOGY

It is important in understanding religions places the theological element of think-


and their gods to understand them histori- ing in the poetical work of the poet.
cally. Such a time needs the poets to get an Heideggers philosophy thus has its own
entrance to the holy. theology within the thinking of being.
The holy has to appear as that in which Theologos, theologia mean at this point
human being can find its wholeness. The holy the mytho-poetic utterance about the gods
is not God, the godhead, the highest entity (ID, 54). The saying of the poet is only pos-
of metaphysics, or the divine grace. It is an sible when he listens to the word. The poet
ontological phenomenon, expressed in the knows that he or she is called by the gods
thinking of being, that can be the entrance in order to praise their name. This implies
to the religious. Without understanding the that the poet at first has to be a listener, to
holy, we behave with respect to it like tour- know how to receive and to get the word
ists and visitors to a museum. Therefore an like a gift and an endowment. Theologia
understanding of it from the perspective of in this respect is at first instance a prais-
the historicality of being is an entrance to ing that springs from the experience that it
understanding religion and the religions, is called, without a connection to a dogma
God and the gods. or a church. This poetical theologia does
It is important to see that Heidegger not ask for the first cause or the totality of
approaches gods and religion as histori- entities. This theologia is the song that is
cal. Theology, as part of metaphysics, is not sung by the poet.
something that has a place in the historicity
of the event of being, according to Heidegger.
Counter to this, Heidegger develops the par-
NOTES AND REFERENCES
adigm of the fourfold. The counter-paradigm
of the fourfold no longer implies a subjectiv- 1
M. Heidegger, Only a God Can Save Us: Der
istic or ontotheological relation to the divine Spiegels Interview with Martin Heidegger,
and the holy. However, this does not mean Philosophy Today, 20 (1976), 26784.
that mortals or human beings, as understood
2
See for this and other parts of this article:
from within the fourfold, have no relation B.Vedder, Heideggers Philosophy of Religion,
From God to the Gods (Pittsburgh: Duquesne
with the gods. In a certain sense, they have a University Press, 2000), 1133; B. Vedder,
theology when they sing and praise the gods. APhilosophical Understanding of Heideggers
We can see this especially in what Heidegger Notion of the Holy, Epoche, a journal for
says about the poet, particularly Hlderlin. the history of philosophy, 10 (2005), 14154;
In Heideggers view it is the poet who can B.Vedder, Heideggers Explication of
Religious Phenomena in the Letters of Saint
wait and long for the coming; he is, based on Paul, Bijdragen, International Journal in
this longing, capable of naming the holy. In Philosophy and Theology, 70 (2009), 15267.
naming the holy, the poet creates a holy place 3
M. Heidegger, Phenomenological
to prepare an abode for gods and mortals. Interpretations with Respect to Aristotle, trans.
Mortals dwell in that they await the divini- Michael Baur, Man and World, 25 (1992), 393.
4
B. Vedder, Heideggers Philosophy of Religion,
ties as divinities. In hope they hold up to the From God to the Gods (Pittsburgh: Duquesne
divinities what is unhoped for. University Press, 2007), 93112.
Heideggers interpretation of the poetic 5
About the difference between the poetic and the
word has a theological element in it. He thinking experience, see OWL, 6970.

335
42
SCIENCE
Trish Glazebrook

The first generation of Heidegger schol- leads Heidegger to the conclusion that sci-
ars in North America was quite clear that ence necessarily entails nihilism. Finally,
Heidegger never developed a systematic Heideggers long-standing engagement with
philosophy of science.1 Nonetheless, his Aristotle opens the possibility of a new
engagement with science begins as early as dwelling that does not reduce thinking to
1912 and continues until his death in 1976. representation and being to objectivity. This
In the earliest text, Das Realittsproblem in is not to say that there would no longer be
der Modernen Philosophie (GA 1, 115), he science. Rather, the mathematical projection
articulates what is later call instrumental of nature would no longer one-sidedly deter-
realism: scientists (unlike philosophers) are mine the human experience of modernity as
not plagued by metaphysical doubt; daz- global conquest.
zling results (3) encourage scientists to take
for granted the reality of objects of research.
From that beginning, his thinking can be
understood as ongoing development of the Specialization
thesis that science is the mathematical pro-
jection of nature. Accordingly, his analysis of R. Crease calls for analyses of specialized sci-
science is the lynchpin for a lifelong engage- ences and scientific practice in Heideggerian
ment with the question of how understand- philosophy of science.2 Applications of
ing can be projective without thereby being Heideggers critique of science to specific
hermeneutically violent. scientific disciplines have indeed burgeoned
His answer is a call for a new beginning in recent years. Sciences addressed include
that is precisely alternative to the modern, quantum physics,3 biology,4 psychology and
scientific, representational, and calculat- psychoanalysis,5 and artificial intelligence
ing thinking that overruns the earth as the and cognitive science.6 Babich argues, how-
essence of technology through the exploita- ever, that the real significance of Heideggers
tion of nature. This movement in Heideggers analysis is his call for rigorous, critical analy-
thinking can be traced through three themes. sis of science.7 Such analysis reveals that sci-
First, reflection on disciplinary specializa- ence determines modernity, yet the sciences
tion reveals that sciences have no access to are incapable of self-critique concerning this
their own essence. Secondly, phenomenology historical role.

337
SCIENCE

Until Heidegger stops doing fundamental died back. Heidegger argues that the only
ontology, his account of science is entangled meaningful source of unity for the sciences
with his claim that philosophy is a science.8 is provided by the practical establishment
At first, he holds merely that projection of goals by each discipline (GA 9, 104/
functions in knowledge to determine disci- BW, 94), and in the Rektoratsrede some four
plinary specialization. In Der Zeitbegriff in years later, he argues that questioning under-
der Geschichtswissenschaft in 1916, he dis- stood as the highest form of knowing shat-
tinguishes history from physics by means ters the division of the sciences into rigidly
of projection of their time concept. In Basic separated specialties . . . and exposes science
Problems of Phenomenology, he grounds the once again to the fertility and the blessing
regional ontologies of the sciences in philoso- bestowed by all the world-shaping powers
phy as fundamental ontology. That is, the sci- of human-historical Dasein.9 Some 20 years
ences carve off some realm of being to take later, he emphasizes the inconspicuous state
as their object, while ontology is the science of affairs (VA, 63/QCT, 179) concealed in
of being. Thus he says in the Beitrge that the sciences as the river lies in its source
there is no science, but rather science is (idem.). Around the same time, in What Is
only a formal title whose essential under- Called Thinking?, he argues that the sci-
standing requires that the breakdown into ences come out of philosophy . . . [and] they
disciplines, into individual and separate sci- can never again, by their own power as sci-
ences, be thought along (GA 65, 145/CP1, ences, make the leap back into the source
101). In Being and Time, he claims that sci- from which they have sprung (GA 8, 52/
ences specialize through projection of basic WCT, 18). He never gives up the claim that
concepts and suffer crisis when these con- the reflection necessary for such critical anal-
cepts undergo revision (SZ, 9/BTMR, 29). ysis of science cannot itself be scientific.
In 1929, in the Antrittsrede, Heidegger The latter lecture course, What Is Called
explicitly argues that Our existencein Thinking?, is notorious for its claim through-
the community of researchers, teachers, and out that Science does not think (GA 8, 4/
studentsis determined by science (GA 9, WCT, 8), but Heidegger also asserts through-
103/BW, 94), and he poses the question of out the lectures that most thought-provoking
metaphysics as the question of What hap- of all is that we are still not thinking (GA 8,
pens to us essentially, in the grounds of our 2/WCT, 4). The lectures are aimed at show-
existence, when science becomes our pas- ing how representational thinking is impov-
sion? (idem.). He comments on the division erished philosophically as it gains access to
of the sciences into specialized disciplines beings but cannot ask the question of being.
and their consolidation into the university, The sciences do in fact decide what of the
and argues that the rootedness of the sci- tree in bloom may or may not be consid-
ences in their essential ground has atrophied ered valid reality (GA 8, 18/WHD, 43),
[abgestorben] (GA 9, 104/BW, 94). That is, Heidegger notes, but the sciences themselves
fundamental ontology can no longer ground cannot question this decision. Accordingly,
the sciences because the relation between the relation between philosophy and science
beings and being is abgestorben, which in is now clear. Philosophy must be unscientific
medicine means necrotized and, keeping precisely to make possible thinking of the
with the root metaphor, in botany means question of the relation between being and

338
SCIENCE

beings, the thinking Heidegger later calls in phenomenology. In 69(b), this conception
the 1950s Besinnung, translated in Science is developed for the first time (SZ, 357/
and Reflection as reflection, and in GA 66 BTMR, 357) in the search for the existen-
as mindfulness. tial conception of science. Heidegger can-
Philosophical reflection on the sciences not provide a fully adequate existential
reveals that modernity is determined by Interpretation of science (idem.) until he has
an extremely narrow conception of reality clarified the meaning of Being and the con-
derived from the sciences. Heideggers cri- nection between Being and truth . . . in terms
tique of technology has received much more of the temporality of existence (idem.), that
attention than his critique of science; but it is is, the central problem of Being and Time.
science, not technology, that for Heidegger is His subsequent deliberations on science are,
the theory of the real (VA, 42/QCT, 157; he says, preparatory to that central issue.
et passim). By the time Heidegger argues this Science is thus more fundamental to Being
point, he holds the sciences no longer capable and Time than has been typically thought.13
of self-transparencythe crisis of science is Yet the inquiry in 69 does not show that
that the sciences cannot see their own essence the sciences are phenomenological in the
(VA, 62/QCT, 179). sense of getting at the things themselves. In
The issue of specialization thus disrupts the theoretical attitude, the circumspective
Heideggers commitment to philosophy as concern of the natural attitude is not just
science. Only from outside science can the stripped away; rather, the understanding of
thinking pose the question at the root of the Being . . . has changed over (SZ, 361/BTMR,
sciences that Heidegger articulates in a lecture 412). Readiness-to-hand, is replaced by
to the Faculty of Medicine at the University another interpretive projection, presence-at-
of Freiberg in 1937 of what is worth know- hand. The sciences are thus hermeneutic.14
ing.10 Thus it is less surprising than it initially What is decisive for them is the way in
seems that Heidegger chooses the question which Nature herself (sic) is mathematically
of the essence of science in The Age of the projected (SZ, 362/BTMR, 4134). This
World Picture to lay bare the entire essence is the first indication of the mathematical
of the modern age (GA 5, 76/QCT, 117).11 projection of nature that Heidegger traces
Philosophy cannot ground the sciences, but in Die Frage nach dem Ding to the ground-
anyone thinking philosophically, including ing function of transcendental subjectivity in
scientists, can question the role of science in Cartesian and Kantian idealism.
human experience. In Being and Time, he notes that this
projection discloses something a priori (SZ,
362/BTMR, 414), and in Die Frage nach dem
Ding he defines the mathematical exactly as
Phenomenology12 what is a priori rather than being found in
experience, of which the numerical is the
That science is the mathematical projection most obvious example (GA 41, 737/BW,
of nature is a central thesis in Heideggers 2758). Hence the sciences may not describe
phenomenology. In 7(c), he borrows anything beyond the imaginative projections
Husserls maxim, To the things themselves! of transcendental subjectivity. Heidegger
to delimit his preliminary conception of remains caught in the problem he articulated

339
SCIENCE

in 1912 that in modern philosophy even 9, 18990/BW, 126).15 Nature is more than
the mere positing of an external world inde- the objects of science; it is what presences of
pendent of consciousness is inadmissible and its own accord.
impossible (GA 1, 3), yet scientists take it Thus physis is indeed poisis in the high-
for granted that they have access to reality. est sense (VA, 15/QCT, 10) in the technol-
In Being and Time, he is thus caught in the ogy essay, and in the Beitrge, physis is the
seemingly contradictory claims that entities measure and is earlier than, source, origin.
are, quite independently of the experience The earliest, what comes to presence first,
by which they are disclosed while Being presencing is physis itself (GA 65, 222/CP1,
is only in [Daseins] understanding (SZ, 155), immediately covered over by Platos
183/BTMR, 228), repeated in 1928 in The idea. Accordingly, the a priori, what is first,
Metaphysical Foundation of Logic (GA 26, is no longer upsurgent presence, but the idea
1945 and 216/MFL, 153 and 169). So how that in modernity belongs to the ego cogitans
is it possible for sciences to gain knowledge and is projected onto beings as the meaning
of independent entities rather than just syn- of being. Hence modern science, as the math-
thesizing imagined objects? There must be ematical projection of nature rather than
something onto which to project. mindful attentiveness, is a bastardized form
In What is Metaphysics? in 1929, he of what Aristotle called techn, the projec-
argues that That with which the scientific tion of form onto matter, and modern science
confrontation . . . occurs are beings them- can never, in Heideggers analysis, simply let
selvesand beyond that nothing (GA 9, beings be. Thus in the last text Heidegger
105/BW, 95). Moreover, the sciences are composed prior to his death, he simply asks:
only possible because Dasein is transcendent,
that is, holding itself out into the nothing Is modern natural science the founda-
(GA 9, 115/BW, 103), yet science wants to tion of technologyas is supposedor
know nothing of the nothing (GA 9, 106/ is it for its part, already the basic form of
BW, 96). Introduction to Metaphysics picks technological thinking, the determining
up where What Is Metaphysics? leaves off, fore-conception and incessant incursion
with the question, Why are there beings at of technological representation into the
all, and not rather nothing? (GA 9, 122/ realized and organized machinations of
BW, 110). Heidegger argues that phys- technology?16
ics determines the essence and the history
of metaphysics from the inception onward Technology can conquer nature as standing-
and metaphysics steadfastly remains phys- reserve because modern science already projects
ics (GA 40, 20/IM, 19). This is because, as nature mathematically as object.
he noted in 1930, when human beings first That narrow conception, essential to sci-
asked what beings are, that is, at the ori- ence, is objectivity, articulated clearly in
gin of philosophy in ancient Greece, being The Question Concerning Technology
as a whole reveals itself as physis, nature, as the projection of nature as a coherence
which here does not yet mean a particular of forces calculable in advance (VA, 25/
sphere of beings but rather beings as such as QCT, 21). At issue there, however, is not the
a whole, specifically in the sense of upsur- essence of science but the essence of technol-
gent presence [aufgehendes Anwesens] (GA ogy: Ge-stell, translated as Enframing. In

340
SCIENCE

fact, in Heideggers analysis, Enframing as in which accidents inhere. Heidegger had


standing-reserve [Bestand] is only possible been given a copy of Brentanos On the
because prior to domination of the essence Several Senses of Being in Aristotle for
of technology, the essence of modern science his eighteenth birthday, and later said this
holds sway as objectivity. Heidegger argues book drove him to write Being and Time.17
in What Is Called Thinking? that Modern In 19212, Heideggers lecture provides a
science is grounded in the nature [Wesen] of phenomenological reading of Aristotle that
technology (GA 8, 155/WCT, 135), imply- is preoccupied with making sense of the
ing that the essence of technology is prior. givenness of world in factical life, and the
But a short time later, in the technology essay, accepted reading of the analogy of being by
he argues instead that the modern physical way of the categories is not put into question.
theory of nature prepares the way first not In the analogy, however, Aristotle details
simply for technology but for the essence at Metaphysics 5.7 that being can also be
of modern technology (VA, 25/QCT, 23). understood as accidental, true or false, and
That is, the essence of technology drives the by way of actuality (entelecheia) or potenti-
organized global conquest of the earth (GA ality (dunamis). In 1931, Heidegger gives a
6.2, 358/NIV, 248) because science deter- lecture course on Aristotles Metaphysics 9,
mines modernity but has at its core what 13 in which he treats actuality and potenti-
for Aristotle belonged to techn: represen- ality in detail. He suggests that Brentano has
tational thinking. The relation between the a tendency to recognize actuality and poten-
essence of science and the essence of technol- tiality as categories (GA 33, 45) but does not
ogy began historically, in Heideggers view, himself articulate fully a different reading
with Aristotle; and it is only by going back to until the 1939 lectures on the Physics, where
that originary account of physis that physis he reads the analogy of being by way of
can be the counter-ground [Gegengrund] actuality and potentiality in their own right
by which to understand the transformation rather than reducing them to categories.
[Umbildung] of techn into technicity In those lectures, Heidegger details the
[Technik] (GA 66, 368). distinction between production (techn)
and nature (physis) for Aristotle: production
entails a conception of what is to be pro-
duced in the mind of the artist prior to pro-
Dwelling duction. If nature required such a paradigm,
says Heidegger, an animal could not repro-
In 1939, Heidegger lectures on Aristotles duce itself without mastering the science of
Physics B, 1. He has already considered its own zoology (GA 9, 290/PA, 222). In
Aristotles account of techn in The Origin art, then, form is imposed onto matter by the
of the Work of Art where he resisted under- artistexactly the account of art Heidegger
standing art as the imposition of form onto rejected in the 1935 lecture, The Origin of
matter. This resistance is a long-standing the Work of Art where he argued instead that
thinking that goes back to Brentanos read- art is itself world-opening origin. In 1939,
ing of Aristotles analogy of being by way he argues that nature cannot be understood
of the categories, that is, that being can be by analogy to artifacts, as if natural entities
understood first and foremost as substance are matter on which form has been imposed

341
SCIENCE

by, for example, a divine craftsperson in the In 40 in Being and Time, Heidegger con-
Judeo-Christian account. Such an analogy, he nects anxiety (Angst) with Unheimlichkeit,
argues, fails from every conceivable point usually translated as uncanniness but mean-
of view. This means: we must understand the ing literally un-home-iness. He implies, since
essence of physis entirely from out of itself it is a basic kind of Being-in-the-World (SZ,
(GA 9, 292/PA, 223). That is to say, the sci- 188/BTMR, 233), that it pervades the human
ences, if they are to understand nature, must condition. He does not connect this home-
be phenomenological. Rather than coming to lessness to the sciences in Being and Time, but
natural entities with an a priori conception, soon thereafter, however, Heidegger under-
that is, a projected representation under the stands that such homelessness is distinctively
model that Aristotle noted best belongs to modern and a consequence of the scientific
production, sciences gain knowledge by let- projection of nature. By the mid-1930s, for
ting being be. example, he argues that Anxiety [Angst] in
In 1930, Heidegger argued in the truth the face of be-ing has never been greater than
essay that freedom is not a property of human today (GA 65, 139/CP1, 97), and that nihil-
being, but reveals itself as letting beings be ism is an abandonment of being (GA 65,
[das Seinlassen von Seiendem] . . . to engage 52 et passim) that is essentially co-decided
oneself with the open region and its openness by modern science . . . insofar as modern sci-
in which every being comes to stand, bringing ence claims to be one or even the decisive
that openness, as it were, along with itself knowing (GA 65, 141/CP1, 98) such that
(GA 9, 188/BW, 125). Likewise, the 1955 lec- any attempt to find the echo of be-ing in the
ture, Gelassenheit, retains this notion of let- abandonment of being cannot avoid being
ting (lassen) as a releasement toward beings mindful of modern science (idem.). For only
that is attentive and meditative, in contrast through reflection, thinking that is not the
precisely to the calculative thinking [rech- representation and calculative thinking of
nende Denken]18 that characterizes the sci- the sciences, can human being be at home in
ences. The calculative function of the sciences nature in the dwelling alluded to in the 1951
is explicit in the 19356 lectures, Die Frage lectures Building, Dwelling, Thinking and
nach dem Ding, where Heidegger argues that . . . Poetically Man Dwells.. . .
calculation is the most familiar form of the
mathematical, but that ta mathemata meant
more broadly for the Greeks, things inso- NOTES AND REFERENCES
far as we take cognizance of them as what
we already know them to be in advance, the
1
J. J. Kockelmans The Era of the
body as bodily, the plant-like of the plant, the World-as-Picture in eds J. J. Kockelmans
and T. J. Kisiel, Phenomenology and the
animal-like of the animal, the thingness of Natural Sciences (Evanston, IL: Northwestern
the thing, and so on (GA 41, 73/BW, 275). University Press, 1970), 184201, 184. See
Modern science cannot, however, let beings also W. J. Richardson, Heideggers Critique
be in order to experience the Greek sense of of Science, New Scholasticism, 42.4 (1968),
self-unfolding presencing [sich entfaltende 51136, 511. See P. Heelans response
to this paper, Heideggers Longest Day:
(ffnende) Anwesung] (GA 66, 87). Modern Twenty-Five Years Later in B. E. Babich
human being is thus alienated from nature (ed.), From Phenomenology to Thought,
in science. Errancy, and Desire: Essays In Honor of

342
SCIENCE

William J.Richardson (Dordrecht: Kluwer, M.Ratcliffe rejected Heideggerian cognitive


1995), 57987. See T. Glazebrook, Heideggers science (www.philosophy.ed.ac.uk/events/
Philosophy of Science (New York: Fordham heideggerworkshop.html).
University Press, 2000) for arguments that 7
B. Babich The Problem of Science in
Heidegger did in fact have a philosophy of Nietzsche and Heidegger, Research Resources.
science. Paper 7. http://fordham.bepress.com/phil_
2
R. Crease, Heidegger and the Empirical Turn research/7 (Accessed May 12, 2012).
in Continental Philosophy of Science in ed. 8
See J. J. Kockelmans, Heidegger on
T. Glazebrook, Heidegger on Science (Albany, the Essential Difference and Necessary
NY: SUNY Press, 2012), 22537, uses formal Relationship between Philosophy and Science,
indication as an example of a Heideggerian in J. J. Kockelmans and T. J. Kisiel (eds),
concept that can be adapted for understand- Phenomenology and the Natural Sciences
ing scientific practice; he gave a related paper (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press,
on formal indicators in Heidegger at the 1970), 14766 and T. J. Kisiel, Science,
forty-third Annual Meeting of the Heidegger Phenomenology, and the Thinking of Being,
Circle in Cincinnati in 2009. 16783, in the same volume, on the relation
3
See J. R. Watson and E. Richter on quan- between philosophy and science.
tum physics in T. Glazebrook, Heidegger on 9
Martin Heidegger, Die Selbstbehauptung der
Science (Albany, NY: SUNY Press, 2012), Deutschen Universitt (Frankfurt am Main:
4765 and 6790. Vittorio Klostermann, 1983), 13; Martin
4
See L. Hatab on biology in Glazebrook, Heidegger, The Self-Assertion of the German
Heidegger on Science, 93111. University: Address Delivered on the Solemn
5
Contributions on psychology and psychoa- Assumption of the Rectorate of the University
nalysis have been emerging since Heideggers of Freiberg; The Rectorate 1933/34: Facts and
exchanges with Medard Boss that began in Thoughts, trans. Kirsten Harries, Review of
1947 (M. Boss (ed.) Zollikoner Seminare, Metaphysics, 38 (1985), 46752, 474.
ProtokolleGesprcheBriefe (Frankfurt 10
Martin Heidegger, Die Bedrohung der
am Main: Vittorio Klostermann, 1987)). Wissenschaft, Zur philosophischen Aktualitt
H. Dreyfus has written on Heidegger and Heideggers, Band 1, ed. Dietrich Papenfuss
psychology since his 1980 Daseins Revenge: und Otto Pggler (Frankfurt: Vittorio
Methodological Solipsism as Unsuccessful Klostermann, 1991), 527; see T. Glazebrook,
Escape Strategy in Psychology (Behavioral Heideggers Philosophy of Science (Albany,
and Brain Sciences, 3.1, 789). NY: State University of New York Press,
6
Dreyfus has also written on cybernetics and 2000), 14852.
artificial intelligence (e.g. Why Heideggerian 11
See J. J. Kockelmans, The Era of the
AI Failed and How Fixing It Would Require World-as-Picture, in eds Kockelmans and
Making it More Heideggerian, Philosophical Kisiel, Phenomenology and the Natural
Psychology, 20.2 (2007), 24768). Both Sciences (Evanston, IL: Northwestern
analyses have their conceptual origins University Press, 1970), 184201 for a detailed
of his reading of being-in-the-world as reading of this lecture concerning science.
coping (H.Dreyfus, Being-in-the-World: 12
See J. J. Kockelmans, Heidegger and Science
A Commentary on Heideggers Being and (Washington, DC: University Press of America,
Time, Division I (Cambridge, MA: MIT 1985) for a thorough reading of the influence
Press, 1991), and see his responses to his of the phenomenological tradition on
critics in M. Wrathall and J. Malpas (eds), Heideggers critique of science.
Heidegger, Coping and Cognitive Science: 13
J. D. Caputo, Heideggers Philosophy of
Essays in Honor of Hubert L. Dreyfus, Vol.2 Science: The Two Essences of Science, in eds
(Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2000). On J. Margolis, M. Krausz, and R. M. Burian,
October 7, 2010, the University of Edinburgh Rationality, Relativism and the Human
hosted a workshop on Heidegger and Sciences (Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff, 1986),
cognitive science; M. Wheeler defended and 4360, 43 argues in fact that even the later

343
SCIENCE

Heidegger himself neglected his own earlier Phenomenology 7 (1977), 14, with translation
reflections on science. by J. Sallis.
14
P. Heelan, who began as a physicist, has been 17
F. Brentano, On the Several Sense of Being
providing critical analyses of science as herme- in Aristotle, trans. R. George (Berkeley:
neutic practice since the 1970s. He engages University of California Press, 1975).
Heidegger throughout, but also explicitly Heidegger confirms that this text drove
states at the After Postmodernism Conference him to write Being and Time in M.
at the University of Chicago, November Heidegger, The Understanding of Time in
1416, 1997 that Hermeneutic philosophy Phenomenology and in the Thinking of the
refers mostly to M. Heideggers (www.focus- Being-Question, trans. T. Sheehan and F.
ing.org/apm_papers/heelan.html (Accessed July Elliston, Southwest Journal of Philosophy,
17, 2012)). 10.2 (1979), 199201, 201, and in his
15
See W. Marx, Heidegger and the Tradition, inaugural address to the Heidelberg Academy
trans. T. Kisiel and M. Greene (Evanston, IL: of Science, noted in H. Siegfried, Martin
Northwestern University Press, 1971), 13943 Heidegger: A Recollection, Man and World,
on physis and Anwesen. 3.1 (1970), 34, 4.
16
M. Heidegger, Neuzeitliche Naturwissenschaft 18
M. Heidegger, Gelassenheit (Pfullingen: Verlag
und moderne Technik, Research in Gnther Neske, 1992), 12 et passim.

344
43
SPACE: THE OPEN IN WHICH
WE SOJOURN
John Russon and Kirsten Jacobson

We have a basic experience of there. in his career (1969), in his Zollikon seminars,
There is opposed to here, to be sure, but Heidegger remarks:
more basically there is somewhere, a pri-
mordial situating that precedes, makes pos- In Being and Time, being-open (Da-sein)
sible and contains the opposition of here means being-open (Da-sein). The Da is
and there: there is reality, it takes determined here as the open. This open-
ness has the character of space. Spatiality
place. This taking place has the dual sense
belongs to the clearing [Lichtung]. It
of happening and occupying a determi-
belongs to the open in which we sojourn
nate location vis--vis others in the universal as existing beings. (GA 89, 283/ZS,
arena of appearing: there is both the sin- 225)1
gular fact of the global happening of reality,
and it is the always local specificity of things
situated with respect to other things and We are Da-sein, which is to say we are open to
to ourselves. This there is the Da with a reality that is open to us, and that is a real-
which Heideggers investigations throughout ity in which things open onto other things.
his career are preoccupied. We are intrinsi- Before engaging in any technical reflections
cally engaged with that Da: we are Dasein, on space, we must first push ourselves to
there-being. noticeand notice the mysterious wonder
The Da, the there, is space, but say- ofthis fact of the open: we should notice
ing the word space does not suddenly that there is a there is for us. We live as the
make transparent the sense of the Da; on witnessing of a clearing in which it is given
the contrary, reflecting on the phenomenon to us to notice, it is given to us that there is
of there draws our attention to the fun- something to notice.
damental enigma of space, the enigmatic Heideggers philosophy is fundamentally a
way that we find ourselves in the midst of phenomenology, that is, it is a description of
things, thrown into a world that presents experience as it is lived. To respond mean-
itself simultaneously as embracing us and as ingfully to his philosophyto understand
spread away from us into the distance. Late itwe must first engage ourselves in the

345
SPACE

project of reflecting upon the character of our world, and thus this world that provides the
own experience: we must begin by reflect- context and background for our lives is the
ing on this, our fundamental experience of most basic phenomenon of our experience:
being there. Having attuned ourselves to it is what most basically appears, what is
the mysterious character of the happening there.3 We are Daseinbeing there
of our experience, we can follow Heideggers first in this sense that our very existence is
ever-deepening reflections on the nature of this being stretched out into the things that
spacethe nature of the Dathroughout make our home.4
his writing. This existing as stretched out into things
is our spatiality, our being spatial. Space is
not first a characteristic of the object of our
experience but is the very character of how
Lived-space we exist.5 The close and the distant are not
primarily matters of the quantity of separa-
Heideggers first and most revolutionary tion between objects, but are matters of our
contribution, and the one that provides the comfortable absorption in or our alienated
context for all his subsequent reflections on unfamiliarity with our world. What is near
space, is the emphasis in Being and Time on is near because we have turned ourselves
the primacy of the ready [zuhanden] char- toward it and taken the thing up into our
acter of the world.2 Though we are intelli- care. What is far is far because we are not
gently, meaningfully, and discriminatingly focusing our attention on it or because it
related to the very specific features of our lies out of reach of a project we undertake.
surrounding environment, in our everyday Space, first, is the proximity to or distance
experience we integrate ourselves with them from our world that we live.
without making them the explicit objects of It is this lived spatiality that Heidegger
our attention. While one is walking, reaching studies in Being and Time.6 In accordance
into a pocket or grabbing for the telephone, with its Being-in-the-world, Heidegger
one will typically be talking with a friend writes, Dasein always has space presented
about the plans for the evening or some other as already discovered, though not themati-
topic. The explicit, conspicuous object of cally (GA 2, 112/BT, 147): even when space
attention is the evenings events, while the as such has not yet become an explicit object
surrounding world of ground, limbs, pocket, of focal concern for us, we already know
and telephone whose support we gather up space in that we are oriented in our irremov-
in our behavior is inconspicuousnon- able involvement with the world in terms of
thematic in, though utterly essential to, our our felt proximities and the ways in which
experience. we are oriented from this home to what is
This nonthematic involvement with the distant. Heidegger studies these character-
determinacies of our environment is not an istics of our spatiality under the headings
optional or secondary aspect of our experi- de-severance [Ent-fernung] and direc-
ence, but is our primary way of existing. First tionality [Ausrichtung].7
and foremost, we dwell in the world, which De-severance is the way in which our
means we always experience from a network being is always characterized by finding things
of involvements, a lived inhabitation of the at a distance, by having things presented to

346
SPACE

us in their separation from us.8 As I launch The world of our experience is not at root
upon a project of writing, the things not con- an alienated assemblage of isolated things set
nected with this writing slip away and I bring off against each other and against an isolated
near those that enable my writing. The pen- knowing subject in space as a uniform and
cil, for example, emerges as a relevant option empty container, but is, rather, the hetero-
and takes its place in the heterogeneous net- geneous fabric of availability upon which
work of papers, surfaces, lights, and limbs we draw to carry out our practices of every-
that, in their separation from me, are the day life, a fabric meaningfully articulated in
possibility of my writing. In engaging with determinate regions that provide the context
the region of writing, these differentiated to which things themselves belong. The sub-
options become simultaneously close and ject as an isolated consciousness, things as
distant: as de-severing, we are always doing isolated individuals and the empty space in
away with the farness between things and which we imagine them to be contained are
us precisely in allowing them to exist for us derivative realities that emerge from within
as relevant differences/distances.9 This mak- this primordial, lived spatiality, rather than
ing close that is de-severing is not reducing being the original terms of reality.11
of the quantity of bodily separation between
my body and some thing, but is rather let-
ting any entity be encountered close by as
the entity which it is (GA 2, 105/BT, 139). Earth and Time-Space
De-severance is the way in which things are
only ever far from us on the basis of their The phenomenological descriptions of
being close to us. world in Being and Time challenged our
In this description of de-severance, we see typical understanding of the world by com-
as well our directionality. Every bringing- pelling us to notice a realm of lived space,
close, Heidegger writes, has already taken beneath, so to speak, the objective real-
in advance a direction towards a region out ity of discrete objects situated in empty
of which what is de-severed brings itself space. In The Origin of the Work of Art,
close (GA 2, 143/BT, 108). We exist as Heidegger compels us to shift our atten-
directional insofar as we are always bring- tion from the world of availability to the
ing things close to us from out of a region to earth that is the originary matrix that
which these things belong, which is to say, we is the very possibility of world. Heidegger
do not indifferently relate to the things of the describes phenomenologically the experience
world, but we are instead always oriented of an ancient Greek temple, noting how the
toward the world in some meaningful way or temple, rather than presenting itself as an
other. We experience the world as regional, object, in fact articulates a world, shaping
as having locationsthe relevant, oriented for us a perspective on ourselves and nature:
domains of our involvementin which cer- the temple, in its standing there, first gives
tain things are gathered together through to things their look and to men their outlook
our projects and, more generally, our care, on themselves (GA 7, 28/PLT, 42). The art-
and we experience things as belonging to work is the gesture by which a community
regions, as coming out of a place to which carves out for itself a Weltanschauunga
they belong.10 worldviewbut this world is itself the

347
SPACE

taking up of possibility that, qua possibility, all being-in-the-world, is earth showing


does not itself have the form of world. itselfor, more exactly, earth as such with-
This possibility of world is the earth. drawing from appearance such that a world
Whatever appears co-arises with a per- might appear.12 With earth we have the very
spective upon it, and, as thus inherently for possibility of the there is, that which in its
a perspective, is meaningful: it has Sinn withdrawal gives there to be the meaningful
sense or directionas we saw already in space of our lives.
our discussion of Daseins directionality. The Heideggers discussion of earth thus
basic phenomenon of meaningful appear- draws our attention to the enabling power
ance, Being and Time argued, is the world, that precedes our experience of the meaning-
that is, we do not first encounter discrete ful articulation of space.13 This notion is fur-
things and discrete other subjects and then ther developed in the concept of time-space,
gradually build up to an experience of real- [Zeit-Raum] in Contributions to Philosophy
ity as a whole but, on the contrary, we begin (1938). Heidegger writes:
with an experience of a meaningful world
as a whole, within which or out of which One must first generally attempt to think
discrete figures emerge. Qua perspectival, what is ownmost to time so originarily
however, any situation of appearingany (in times ecstasis) that time becomes
graspable as the possible truth for be-ing
being-in-the-worldis always selective and
[Seyn] as such. But already thinking time
one-sided. The world is always a culturally
through in this way brings time, in its
and historically specific way of apprehending relatedness to the Da of Da-sein, into an
the possibilities of appearing, of apprehend- essential relationship with the spatial-
ing what it is to be, of encountering the ity of Da-sein and thus with space. . . .
there. Other ways of being-in-the-world But measured against their ordinary
other worldshowever, are also possible. A representations, time and space are here
world, as a specific way of appearing, shows more originary; and ultimately, they are
itself, but through itself it is also manifest- time-space [Zeit-Raum], which is not
ing the possibility of appearing. The pos- a coupling of time and space but what
sible, always failing to appear as suchas is more originary in their belonging
together. (GA 65, 189/CP1, 132)
possiblenonetheless always appears as the
actual. This possibility of world, realized in
and as the world, but not reducible to it, is Being and Time took temporality as its clue
earth. for investigating the nature of being: the
If we now return to our initial phenom- articulation and realization of our care in
enological project of describing experience the experience of lived time is our funda-
and thus ask, What is appearing? or What mental hold on the relationship of what is,
is there? we can advance beyond our earlier what was, and what will be, and is thus the
answer. Earlier, we recognized that, through fundamental fabric of the meaningfulness
the temple, for example, a world appears. the Sinnof our experience.14 Yet, Being and
Now we can deepen our description further Time revealed, this, our meaningful grasp
and say that, through the temple, earth is of the world, is not a matter of intellectual
appearing as world. Indeed, earth is appear- representation, but is a matter, as we saw
ing as appearance. All appearing, hence above, of lived spatiality, an inhabitation of

348
SPACE

a world.15 This inseparability of time and Zeit-Raum, the possibility of meaningful


spaceof meaning and extension, so to space and meaningful time, is neither a spa-
speakinvites us to recognize a source for tially separate existent nor a temporally ante-
each that precedes their apparent separabil- cedent reality; indeed, it does not exist in any
ity. This is the time-space [Zeit-Raum] of way other than as space and time. There is
Contributions to Philosophy. only the event [Ereignis] that is the appropri-
As earth is that of which world is the reali- ating of the possibility of being in the happen-
zation, Zeit-Raum is that of which the space ing of a meaningful world.20 The event is the
and the time that we live are realizations. co-occurrence of Zeit-Raum and of space and
As what makes possible space and time, time, but it is precisely the event of their sepa-
Zeit-Raum is not properly graspable in the ration from each other: they each exist only
terms of space and time. Such terms, however, in and as this constitutive strife.21 Similarly,
are the terms of meaning for us. Zeit-Raum, in our inhabitation of a familiar world
then, as the ground of meaning, is itself our existence as Daseinthere always lurks
outside the domain of meaning: it is pre- Da-sein, our constitutive homelessness that
cisely meaningless. In this sense, Zeit-Raum carries within it a call to recognize that we are
is ground in the sense of Abgrund thus exposed to the abyss; and, equally, our
abyss.16 The recognition of Zeit-Raum is the homeless Da-sein can exist in no way other
recognition that meaning as such cannot be than as making a home in being, appropriat-
the last word, so to speak, but as mean- ing being in one way or another. What is ulti-
ing precisely points to its own rootedness in mately at stake in our spatiality is the how
a kind of absence of meaning. of our appropriation: specifically, what is at
Recognizing this absence of meaning is stake is whether we live our Dasein in a way
neither a theoretical matter, nor a matter of that acknowledges this, its inherent Da-sein.
nihilism, but is, as Heidegger already antic-
ipated in his study of anxiety in Being and
Time, precisely a lived realization of ones
own exposure to an outside that, as such, Machination and Dwelling
can never be brought within the confines of
comfortable experience: an outside in which Da-sein, according to Contributions to
we can never be at home.17 The experience Philosophy, is the site for the moment of
of space is always the experience of being the grounding of the truth of be-ing (GA 65,
exposed to our limits, and here, in this engage- 323/CP1, 227).22 We exist as the site as which
ment with the deepest sense (or absence of the event of being as the strife of earth and
sense) of space, we similarly engage this expo- world is enacted, and recognizing this is rec-
sure at it most extreme level.18 Dasein under- ognizing the fundamental responsibility that
stood as our lived spatiality of being-at-home defines us. Indeed, our spatiality is ultimately
itself depends on Da-sein understood as an a grappling with what matters most deeply
originary homelessness that is our relation to and originally.
space as Zeit-Raum.19 Contributions to Philosophy emphasizes
Da-sein, the site of our homeless expo- the contemporary political and social prob-
sure to Zeit-Raum, is not simply other than lem of what Heidegger there calls machina-
Dasein, our being-at-home in the world. tion [Machenschaft]. We saw in our initial

349
SPACE

study of lived space the problem of confus- earth, is Buan, dwelling.. . . The old word
ing the mathematically measurable empty bauen, which says that man is insofar as
space of our objective relation to the world he dwells, this word bauen however also
with the original spatiality of our dwelling. means at the same time to cherish and
protect, to preserve and care for. (GA 7,
Machination is the carrying out at a global
149/PLT, 147)
level of this misapprehension of our inher-
ent spatiality: with machination, we inhabit
space in a way that denies the nature of spatial How we establish our habitationhow we
inhabitationwe dwell in a way that betrays buildis how we shelter [bergen] what
dwellingand the res extensa as which space Heidegger in Building, Dwelling, Thinking
appears when we confront the world as an calls the fourfold, which he there iden-
object becomes an exploitative inhabiting tifies as the essential character of being:
of the world that actively transforms the Dwelling, as preserving [als Shonen], keeps
world into a desert.23 Hence the concern of the fourfold in that with which mortals stay:
Contributions to Philosophy: We need to in things (GA 7, 153/PLT, 151).24 What this
show how it happens that space and time means, in short, is that building is not simply
become framing representation .. . for math- instrumental shelter for us from the natu-
ematical calculation and why these concepts ral elements; it is, on the contrary, how we
of space and time dominate all thinking shelter all that is of value in the world, how
(GA 65, 373/CP1, 260). The reorientation in we shelter the possibilities for being. Though
our understanding of space that Heideggers our study of space recognized the priority of
philosophy offers is itself crucial to resisting Zeit-Raum, the weight of this recognition
the inherently destructive way in which we is the acknowledgment that it is only in our
currently inhabit our world. actual dwelling that this enabling power is
The analysis of dwelling [Wohnen] housed. As the site for the moment of the
in Building, Dwelling, Thinking (1951) grounding of the truth of be-ing, our exist-
offers resources for a significantly differ- ence inherently puts upon us the capacity to
ent approach to our inhabitation of our shape how the possibilities of being will be
places from that enacted in machination. realized, a capacity that involves the danger
The description of the Greek temple in The that we will live in destructive denial of the
Origin of the Work of Art, revealed that how very fabric of meaning but a capacity that is
we build is how we articulate space, which, equally the possibility of sheltering the giving
indeed, is how we open a world. Space is not power.25
a given empty container and building is not This emphasis on the concreteness and
merely instrumental; rather, how we build existential intimacy of space is brought to
our architectural spaces is how we disclose a powerful conclusion in Heideggers stud-
space as a place for dwelling. Our building ies of sculpture from the 1960s. Art and
simultaneously releases to us how the world Space, (1969), is a meditation on how
can be inhabited and, correlatively, is expres- the sculptural work releases the nature of
sive of how we are: space to our experience. It is only in our
actual dwelling that the possibility of space
The way in which you are and I am, the exists, and sculpture brings to appearance
manner in which we humans are on the this dependence of space upon the places

350
SPACE

of which it is the possibility: Place is not very possibility of meaning in an acknowl-


located in a pre-given space, after the man- edgment of our homelessness. How we heed
ner of physical-technological space. The lat- this call will be decisive in this technological
ter unfolds itself only through the reigning world that is premised upon the denial of our
of places of a region (Art and Space 11). essential reality.
And, just as space is not an indifferent con-
tainer of indifferent places, so is place not
an indifferent container for an indifferent
NOTES AND REFERENCES
thing: We would have to learn to recognize
that things themselves are places and do not 1
See Thomas Sheehan, A Paradigm Shift in
merely belong to a place (ibid.). This line of Heidegger Research, Continental Philosophy
thinking is completed in the closely related Review, 32 (2001), 120.
Remarks on Art-Sculpture-Space, where 2
GA 2, 63113/BT 91148, division 1, chapter3,
Heidegger identifies the crucial role of the The Worldhood of the World. The concept
body in relation to space: of world is also discussed extensively in the
1927 lecture course, Die Grundprobleme der
Phnomenologie, GA 24, 23041 and 41229/
The human has no body and is no body, BP, 16270 and 291302, and in earlier courses
but rather it lives its body [Leib]. The such as the 1925 course, Prolegomena zur
human lives in that it bodies [leibt], and Geschichte des Zeitbegriffs, GA 20 210325/
thus is it admitted into the open of space, HCT 156236, division 1, chapter 3, sections
and through this self-admittance it holds 1925. For the idea that Heideggers later phi-
itself already from the outset in a rela- losophy of space represents a fundamental shift
tion to its fellow humans and things.26 in position, see Andrew J. Mitchell, Heidegger
among the Sculptors: Body, Space and the Art
of Dwelling (Stanford: Stanford University
Press, 2010); for a powerful criticism of this
We began by noting that our being is Da-sein,
position, see Franois Raffoul, The Event
which is being-open. Sculpture reveals that of Space, Gatherings: The Heidegger Circle
this being-open is enacting only as our bod- Annual, 2 (2012), 89106.
ying. It is ultimately in and as the concrete- 3
For dwelling, see GA 2, 54/BT, 7980; for
ness of our bodily engagement with things involvements, see section 18, GA 2, 84/BT,
that there is.27 116, and to compare the notion of equipmen-
tal totality, see GA 2, 68/BT, 97.
4
See GA 2, 1115 and 529/BT, 325 and
7886. See Kirsten Jacobson, A Developed
Nature: A Phenomenological Account of the
Conclusion Experience of Home, Continental Philosophy
Review, 42 (2009), 35573. Initially, Heidegger
presented Dasein as a word without
What is there? We will never exhaust the hyphenation; later, he hyphenated the word
description of this, and so we will never Da-sein. In discussing Being and Time, we
exhaust our account of space, the enigmatic use the term without hyphenation; the relation
possibility and actuality of the world that between the earlier and later uses is considered
constitutes the context and fabric of our in the second section of this chapter.
5
GA 2, 138/BT, 104: To encounter the ready-to-
lives. Space is where we live in the comfort- hand in its environmental space remains
able familiarity of being-at-home, and also ontically possible only because Dasein itself is
where we encounter the call to shelter the spatial with regard to its Being-in-the-world.

351
SPACE

6
Sections 224, The Spatiality [Rumlichkeit] primal phenomena at the awareness of which
of Dasein. See Yoko Arisaka, On Heideggers men are overcome, as Goethe says, by an awe
Theory of Space: A Critique of Dreyfus, to the point of anxiety? . . . For behind space, so
Inquiry 38 (1995), 45567; Jing Long, The it will appear, nothing more is given to which
Body and the Worldhood of the World, it could be traced back. Before space there is
Journal of Philosophical Research, 31 (2006), no retreat to something else. See Stuart Elden,
295308. Contributions to Geography? The Spaces of
7
See also GA 20 30625/HCT 22336, section 25. Heideggers Beitrge, Environment and Planning
8
See Hubert Dreyfus, Being-in-the-World: A D: Society and Space, 23 (2005), 81127.
Commentary on Heideggers Being and Time, 17
See especially GA 2, 186/BT, 180.
Division I (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1991), 18
See Mitchell, Heidegger among the
132; Jeffrey Malpas, Heideggers Topology, Sculptors, 52.
(Cambridge: MIT Press, 2006), 91, 376; 19
Heidegger takes up our homeless or
Peg Birmingham, Heidegger and Arendt: unhomely character in Being and Time (e.g.
The Birth of Political Action and Speech, in GA 2, 189/BT, 183). It is a central theme of the
eds Franois Raffoul and David Pettigrew, 1942 lecture course, Hlderlins Hymne der
Heideggers Practical Philosophy (Albany: Ister, GA 53.
SUNY Press, 2002), chapter 12, 197. 20
Zeit-Raum is originally the site for the
9
For regions, see GA 2, 103/BT, 1367. moment of enowning [Augenblicks-Sttte des
10
See Edward S. Casey, The Fate of Place: A Ereignisses]. (GA 65, 30/CP1, 22)
Philosophical History (Berkeley: University of 21
See GA 65, 29/CP1, 21: Time-space [is] the
California Press, 1997), 24756. site for the moment of strife.. . . Strife [is]
11
Heideggers phenomenological description of the strife of earth and world, because truth of
lived experience also challenges the mutual be-ing [takes place] only in sheltering, shelter-
isolation that we typically presume to exist ing as grounding the between in beings: the
between subjects; see Being and Time, division tug of earth and world.
1, chapter 4. 22
See John Sallis, Grounders of the Abyss,
12
Compare Heideggers remarks on a phenom- in eds Charles Scott, Susan Schoenbohm,
enology of the inapparent, GA 15, 135/FS, 80. Daniela Vallega-Neu, and Allejandro Vallega,
13
See Thomas Sheehan, Kehre and Ereignis: Companion to Heideggers Contributions to
A Prolegomenon to Introduction to Philosophy (Bloomington: Indiana University
Metaphysics, in eds Richard Polt and Press, 2001), 18197.
Gregory Fried, A Companion to Heideggers 23
See Elden, Contributions to Geography? 819.
Introduction to Metaphysics (New Haven and 24
In Contributions to Philosophy, similarly,
London: Yale University Press, 2000), 316, Heidegger identifies the hidden essence
26374, especially 7. of Zeit-Raum as nearness and remoteness,
14
The meaning [Sinn] of Dasein is temporality, emptiness and gifting, fervor and dawdling, in
GA 2, 331/BT, 380. contrast to quantitative measurability we com-
15
See GA 2, 3679/BT, 41821 for Heideggers monly take to be definitive of objective space
discussion of the relation of space and time in and time (GA 65, 372/CP1, 260).
Being and Time. 25
Compare GA 7, 2936/BW, 33341.
16
GA 65, 37188/CP1, 25971: Der 26
Bemerkungen zu KunstPlastikRaum, ed.
Zeit-Raum als der Ab-grund. On this Hermann Heidegger (St. Gallen, Switzerland:
theme, see Friedrich-Wilhelm von Herrmann, Erker Verlag, 1996), 13; quoted in Mitchell,
Wahrheit-Zeit-Raum, in ed. Ewald Richter, Die Heidegger among the Sculptors, 40.
Frage Nach der Wahrheit (Frankfurt am Main: 27
On the concreteness of space see Jeffrey
Klostermann, 1997). Compare Heidegger, Der Malpas, Heidegger and the Thinking of
Kunst und der Raum (St. Gallen, Switzerland: Place: Explorations in the Topology of Being
Erker Verlag, 1969), translated by Charles (Cambridge MA: MIT Press, 2012) and the
H.Siebert as Art and Space, Man and World, review of this book by Franois Raffoul, Notre
6 (1973), 38, 7: Spacedoes it belong to the Dame Philosophical Reviews, July 19, 2012.

352
44
TECHNOLOGY
Hans Ruin

Up until the mid-nineteenth century, the technology as the defining issue of our time.
question and problem of technology was not Ortega y Gasset in Spain, Nikolai Berdjajev
seen as an issue of great philosophical inter- in Russia (and France), Oswald Spengler,
est. It is in the social philosophy of Marx and Ernst Jnger, and Ernst Cassirer in Germany,
other left Hegelians that one can first see a and many others take part in the discussion
genuine shift among philosophers in this of the meaning and consequences of the tech-
respect. The modes of production and thus nologizing of culture. The culmination of the
the very technical means of life are now seen Second World War brought the whole mat-
as cultural forces in their own right, and thus ter to yet another level. The atomic bomb
as influencing the thoughts, experiences, and marked a new step in both the technological
self-understanding of a society. In 1877 Ernst and the spiritual evolution of humankind. It
Kapp, a philosopher and a contemporary of now had the ability to abolish life on earth
Marx, publishes the first book with the title as such. With the parallel discovery of the
Outline for a Philosophy of technology human genome, humanity appeared to have
(Grundlinien einer Philosophie der Technik), fulfilled the ancient phantasies of a demi-
where he launches the idea of the tool as an urge that in his hands had the power and the
organ-extension of man. techne to create and destroy life.
With the First World War the question The first phase of this discussion takes
takes on another urgency. The war was not place when Heidegger is developing his own
only a human and cultural disaster of previ- version of phenomenology as existential
ously unseen dimensions. It was also an expe- ontology. Yet, in his early published works,
rience of how the machinery of war somehow including Being and Time, the question of
seemed to have taken over the lives of men, technology does not stand forth as a funda-
and made them into its servants rather than mental concern. It is not until the early 1950s
its masters. Together with the rapid and con- that he explicitly and publicly takes on the
vulsive industrialization of the West it contrib- question of technology as a philosophical
uted to bringing the question of technology to theme in its own right. He then gives several
the forefront of the cultural and philosophi- public lectures on this theme, which are then
cal debates in postwar Europe. edited into the immensely influential essay
In the 1920s many European philosophers The Question Concerning Technology
and intellectuals turn their interest toward in 1954. Here he describes the essence of

353
TECHNOLOGY

technology as enframing (Ge-stell) and as and development of his phenomenological


the defining characteristic of our age. Techne ontology and its inner tensions that one can
in its double legacy, as both technology and make better sense of it, and also that one can
as art, is here presented as the source of the formulate relevant criticisms.
greatest danger but also as a potentially sav- As a short historical background it is
ing power, as both Gefahr and Rettung. To helpful to rehearse a few basic points from
contemplate (besinnen) this situation is a Aristotle, who remained the main reference
crucial task for philosophy, perhaps even its for Heidegger on this issue throughout his life.
greatest responsibility in the present. In his In book six of Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle
last words to his colleagues and friends in provides the first known philosophical defini-
America in 1976, the year of his death, he tion of techne: A techne is a rational quality
writes that contemplating technology is the concerned with making, that reasons truly
most important task if we are to counter the (1140a). The translation of techne is here a
forgetfulness of being. philosophical problem in itself. The stand-
For a long time it was believed that the ard Latin translation of techne was always
problem of technology was something that ars, and following this it was rendered in the
belonged only to Heideggers later work. But modern Latinized European languages as
with the publication of his lectures from the art, and in the Germanic languages as Kunst
1920s onward it has become clear that his (where the etymology points back toward a
interest in and perspective on this problem verb for knowledge and ability, kunna). In
must be seen in a new light. First of all, he some translations of Aristotle we find the
was greatly influenced by the earlier cultural extended translation art or technical skill,
and philosophical debate about the role and to mark the difference from art in the more
meaning of technology, in particular by the modern aesthetic sense. But it is important
writings of Ernst Jnger. Also, the problem of to note that Aristotle and the Greeks did not
the technical and its effect on language and clearly distinguish between what we think of
thinking is something that guides his criti- as technology on the one hand and the fine
cal assessment of the history of metaphysics arts on the other. Techne was essentially the
from the very earliest writings onward. name for a creative and productive form of
Heideggers essay on the question of tech- knowledge, an intellectual virtue comparable
nology is today the single most quoted paper to other intellectual virtues, notably scien-
in the field of Science and Technology Studies. tific knowledge and wisdom. As such it also
One reason that it has become so influential had something to do with truth. In another
is that it seeks to capture the problem of the famous and somewhat enigmatic passage
technical on such an extremely general level, from the same text, Aristotle writes: There
both philosophically and historically, con- are five ways in which the soul achieves
necting it with the meaning and development truth (aletheuein), namely through techne,
of the metaphysical and philosophical tradi- scientific knowledge, prudence, wisdom, and
tion as such. Yet, because of how intricately intelligence (1139b).
it is folded into his overall philosophical The meaning of this statement has been the
problematic, it is often poorly understood. It source of much debate. Whatever Aristotle
is only by locating its analyses and conclu- meant, its importance for Heideggers
sions in the broader context of the emergence understanding of technology can hardly be

354
TECHNOLOGY

overestimated. The relation between techne one according to which Greek metaphysics
and truth and the disclosure of being is a built its fundamental conceptual structure.
question that guides his attempts to think Only by becoming critically aware of what
technology philosophically from the very we could thus call a certain technical bias in
earliest lectures. Throughout this trajectory, the very construction of metaphysical lan-
the double legacy of techne, as both art and guage, can we also engage in an exploration
technology, will also generate shifting con- directed toward other, complementary, and
stellations. We will come back to it as we supposedly also more fundamental senses of
proceed, but with this background in mind I being.
now turn to how the problem of technology This conclusion is not simply a descrip-
first appears in his work. tive hypothesis that concerns the first emer-
In 1922, Heidegger composed a survey gence of a metaphysical conceptuality. It also
article to summarize the interpretations of holds a critical potential. For in questioning
Aristotle on which he had been working the validity of the original conceptual con-
for several years (PIA). The dense text can figuration it also opens up a space for criti-
be read as a condensed outline of Being and cal reflection on the inherited understanding
Time five years before its publication. It also and meaning of being that will continue to
contains some very important remarks on the direct his critical questioning of inherited
technical that anticipates his later thinking. metaphysics.
He stresses here the importance of analyzing When Heidegger publishes Being and Time
how the vocabulary of early Greek meta- five years later, the core of its argument is the
physics is created, and what its guiding mod- critique of a substance metaphysics, which
els and motives are. As an example he turns understands being along the line of what is
to how Aristotle conceptualizes substance, present-at-hand (Vorhandenheit). The con-
Greek ousia. When designating the most nection to the earlier analysis of the tech-
fundamental nature of being by this term, nical roots of metaphysics is not, however,
Aristotle has been guided, Heidegger argues, obvious at first glance. In Being and Time,
by an understanding of being as something the explicit theme of technology and techne
created in poiesis, as a Hergestelltsein, a is hardly mentioned. It is clear from some
being-fabricated. The German word is remarks in passing that he attaches a some-
important here, for it marks the first in a long what negative sense to the technical. When
sequence of concepts forged around the root discussing the phenomenological method, he
verb stellen, to place or put, at the extension emphasizes, for example, that it should not
of which he eventually coins that of Ge-stell. be understood along the lines of a techni-
In Greek metaphysics being is thought in cal device (GA 2, 27/BT, 26). And in a later
its general essence as something produced passage from the book he makes a distinc-
that is then grasped in language through its tion between what he calls a genuine reflec-
eidos, its visibility. This way of making being tion on method from empty discussions of
appear and stand forth, and thus to be true, technology (GA 2, 303/BT, 290). In order
Heidegger continues, is the way of techne or to ground this vaguely negative conception
technics. So the technological understand- of the technical we need to see it in the con-
ing of being is in fact what we could call the text of the larger project in BT, its criticism
basic model of understanding being, and the of modern Cartesian substance ontology,

355
TECHNOLOGY

and how it carries on the basic connection distanced and objectifying modern Cartesian
between a technical approach to being and understanding of nature in modernity. This is
metaphysical language. what permits him to speak of readiness-to-
In Being and Time the critique of sub- hand, Zuhandenheit, as a more original
stance ontology does not, unlike the earlier manifestation of being than present-at-hand,
draft, take its starting point in a Greek tech- Vorhandenheit.
nical sense of being. Instead it points to From one perspective the ontology
Cartesian metaphysics as the root of seeing developed in Being and Time could thus
being as a pure extension in space. Heidegger be described as a pragmatist ontology of
uses Descartes famous example of a piece the artifact and the tool, since the being of
of wax to demonstrate his point. By reduc- readiness-to-hand is argued to be more fun-
ing the object to its pure extension in space, damental than the secondary and theoreti-
Descartes has abstracted it from its immedi- cally mediated present-at-hand of the simply
ate surroundings, in order to visualize it only contemplated object of nature. It has also
as a calculable material extension. been interpreted in this way, especially by
In order to destruct this understanding some of Heideggers American readers.
of thingness, Heidegger turns to the Greek Even though the rationale behind his
word for thing, which is pragmata, signify- analysis was to critically reflect on the form
ing etymologically that with which we are of objectification of nature that emerges
concerned. These entities are not meaningless with modern science and its metaphysics, its
extensions in space, but always contextually implications nevertheless remain problem-
meaningful in terms of a surrounding world atic, not least for Heidegger himself. For if
of concerns. They are, he says, readiness-to- nature is understood along the model of a
hand, Zuhandenheit. Their understanding useful thing or readiness-to-hand, then the
and meaningfulness presupposes precisely phenomenological analysis would seem to
that they are not objectified, but rather lived reinstall a subjectivist and anthropocentric
in their spontaneous referential context. determination of the world that it sought to
From this perspective it is possible for him to transcend. If we read Being and Time from
develop his analysis of world as something this angle we can also sense why he subse-
more than simply a constellation of material quently adopted a critical distance toward
entities. The primary phenomenon of world its analyses.
is a lived, meaningful referential context, into This is the case in particular in the essay
which we are always already thrown. Origin of the Work of Art from 1935.This
From the viewpoint of the earlier critique is his most important statement on Art, but
of substance metaphysics this is a bit confus- as such it is also an important statement on
ing. Through his interpretations of Aristotle the technical, since art or Kunst goes back to
he had reached the conclusion that Greek the same Greek word techne. Readers often
instrumental and technical understanding fail to fully appreciate the interconnected-
of being accounts for a kind of elementary ness of the question of art and technology
forgetfulness in the history of metaphysics. in Heideggers work. But here, in the art-
But now the artifact, tool or equipment, work essay, he literally builds his argument
as in Greek pragmata, is instead presented by pitting the two senses of ancient techne
as a critical contrast in relation to a more against one another. In seeking to expand

356
TECHNOLOGY

his earlier critique of substance ontology, he metaphysics as the matrix for thinking being
states that the true being of an artwork can- as a disconnected entity, in a way that comes
not be grasped along the model of objective to the fore in modernity, where the truth or
present-at-hand entities, as Vorhandenheit. event of being is covered over and domesti-
However, neither can it be understood along cated in a representational and objectifying
the model of the useful tool or readiness-to- (technical) understanding. At the same time,
hand, as Zuhandenheit. Nor indeed can techne as art emerges as a unique avenue
nature be understood along any of these toward thinking the event of truth, in a way
models. For natural being is rather charac- that does not objectify being, but rather per-
terized by an elusive way of self-containment mits it to prevail in its own essence, in its dual
(Eigenwuchsig), a kind of auto-emergence. nature as presence and absence at once. As
When we turn to the artwork, however, we shall see shortly, the 1953 essay on tech-
it turns out that it in fact differs from all nology brings this confrontation between the
of these three types of being. Instead it is a two forms of techne to an even higher level.
special way of bringing together and letting In the years that follow upon the Artwork
appear the being of nature, not consuming it essay, from the mid-1930s onward, Heidegger
as a raw material for the purpose of its own embarks on a huge undertaking, to reassess
utility, but rather by letting it appear and the entire movement and inner motivation
come to presence. It is in this sense that the of German idealism and its legacy, including
artwork can be a happening of truth. Nietzsche. From an initial positive appre-
In contrast to the analysis in Being and ciation of both Schelling and Nietzsche as
Time, the mode of equipment or usefulness attempts to escape from the confines of met-
is thus here what lies in the way of grasp- aphysics in its traditional form, he gradually
ing the genuine phenomenon of nature. On reaches the conclusion that not only all of
the other hand, this truth can be discerned German idealism, but also Nietzsche himself,
through the event of the artwork. As a work are ultimately symptoms of a more encom-
of truth, the artwork is what reveals the passing metaphysical development. The true
deeper meaning of nature that is concealed legacy of metaphysics is a will to power and
as long as nature is interpreted only through domination that brings everything under
the traditionaltechnologically oriented its yoke, and that finds its concretization in
matrix of matter and form. So in the place of modern technology, especially in its relation
techne as artifact, the essay opts for techne as to nature.
artwork. From the viewpoint of the Artwork His own radicalized attempt to abandon
essay, there is thus also a positive possibility the confines of Western thinking is mani-
emanating from the Greek techne, not as the fested most dramatically in his writings
instrument of immediate life concerns, but as from the mid-1930s onward, notably in
the poetic bringing forth of something into Contributions to Philosophy and Besinnung
its presence. (GA 65 and GA 66). In these posthumously
At this stage in Heideggers thinking the published works we find the first steps in his
two conflicting modes of techne thus begin critical assessment of technology as a world
to structure his thinking in a cross-wise, chi- shaping power, a power that is about to
astic way. Techne in the sense of the fabri- transform the sense of nature, leading to a
cated artifact functions from the inception of forgetfulness of being (GA 65, 277). Here he

357
TECHNOLOGY

also tries to develop new modes of thought, command nature, herausgefordert die Natur
as well as a series of new concepts. Central herauszufrdern (VA, 21/BW, 320). This is
for the former attempt is to shape a mode the concentrated formulation behind the idea
of thinking that avoids the objectification of Ge-stell as the essence of technology. It
of conceptual thought, by including its own manifests itself as a demand inherent in man
belonging to that which is thought. In himself and as a consequence of his freedom,
these experimental works, written mostly in and through which he takes control over
under the years of dictatorship, Heidegger nature and over himself. It is a destiny, but
elaborates many of the thoughts that will not in the sense of being ordained by a supe-
eventually surface in his postwar lectures and rior power, but as a way in which humans
writings. It is a question of saying things so encounter nature and themselves.
as to call forth the attention of the listener to As such a destiny it is not given once and
how she has already been claimed by what for all, but rather as something toward which
she is trying to think. we can seek to establish a more free rela-
In the 1953 lecture on technology this tion. By listening to its claim or its demand
strategy and therapy is at the heart of its (Anspruch), and by permitting it to resonate
argument and style. Unlike the common as such, it can also become a freeing claim
approach to the philosophical question of (VA, 29/BW, 331). For this reason the Ge-stell
technology, Heidegger holds that the essence constitutes a fundamentally ambiguous situ-
of something is not simply the answer to its ation. From a superficial perspective the con-
fundamental what. In the case of technol- cept and diagnosis itself may appear only
ogy the standard answer is that technol- as an anti-modernist and even reactionary
ogy is a means to an end, an instrument assessment of the present. But Heideggers
for action, or as in the earlier theorists an point is that it also contains new possibilities
organ-projection. But against this stand- of experiencing this very modernity, if we are
ard response, he suggests that we look able to listen to the way that it speaks in and
instead for how technology brings about its through us.
truth. Then we do not only ask for the truth The danger inherent in the Ge-stell also
about technology, but rather for the truth of holds a saving potential. In his later writ-
and through technology. ings, Heidegger would often quote the lines
At this stage he also recalls the passage from Hlderlins Patmos, But where dan-
from the Nicomachean Ethics referred to ger is, grows the saving power also. In the
above, according to which techne is a way essay on technology this quotation holds a
of making true. He uses it to convey the very special place, for it summarizes the way
point that techne has to do with bringing in which he wants the Ge-stell to be under-
about the true, in the sense of letting some- stood, namely as an ambiguous situation
thing come into its appearance, and thus of of danger and saving at once. The latter pos-
disclosing it. The primary way in which tech- sibility rests, however, on the condition that
nology discloses nature is as exploitation, man can reach a thoughtful and reflective
or a commanding, as Herausfordern. It dis- relation to that which is, as it is disclosed in
closes nature as that which can and should the Ge-stell.
be commanded. But not only that, it also At the very end of the essay he explic-
discloses man to himself as commanded to itly takes up this ambiguity in terms of the

358
TECHNOLOGY

aforementioned double inheritance of the which were known by the Greeks also as
Greek techne. Once, he says, techne also techne. But this is only possible on the condi-
meant the bringing forth of the true into the tion that philosophy thinks the technological
beautiful (VA, 38/BW, 339). To the hope of condition to its end. So at the end of it all it is
technology belongs this possibility of bring- as if techne comes forward to reveal a liber-
ing it back to a sense of a poietic disclosure, ating perspective on that which is, liberating
first carried and made possible in the arts, it, as it were, from itself.

359
45
TRUTH
Daniel O. Dahlstrom

When someone protests that a certain depic- forms of representation is no reason to give
tion of events is not a true picture of what up on them. They call for interpretation and
happened, the expression a true picture revision, but their very possibility turns on
is typically metaphorical. Yet the metaphor a capacity at least to approximate the truth.
captures a common enough experience. Nor do we have any other access tothe truth
Accounts and representations of things, than that provided by them. Even if the
relations, or events often leave out or sig- skeptical claim (representation) that repre-
nificantly distort what is, within a particular sentations generally fall short of the things
context, essential to them and to the recogni- themselves is not self-refuting (though per-
tion of them. Obviously even a picture (from haps regressive), the claim gets any traction
snapshots to computed tomography scans or it possesses from the presumption of the dis-
MRIs) can be less than accurate, and mov- closiveness of at least some representations.
ing pictures no less so. Nevertheless, we fre- Yet the skeptic is on to something on which
quently picture things to facilitate our ways Heidegger repeatedly insists, namely, the fact
of talking about things and getting closer that access to the truth is not the same as
to the truth of a matter.1 And the reverse is the truth itself. Truth is the disclosure of the
also true. Consider the animated discussions presence (being) of beings to us. The differ-
of the Zapruder film capturing Kennedys ence between disclosure and presence here is
assassination or of the images of the recently slight, underscoring the metonymy of truth
discovered streaks on Martian slopes. and being for Heidegger. However, while
In a sense, recourse to the interaction we can conceive a presence not present to
between picturing and discussing, far from someone or perhaps anyone, the same does
boosting our confidence in them, may seem not hold for a disclosure. Moreover, in order
to underscore their feebleness. A picture may for the presence of something to be disclosed
be worth a thousand words but at a time to us, we have to represent it. That is to say,
when a thousand is hardly enough. If a picto- there is no truth without our representa-
rial representation contributes to a linguistic tion as an ingredient part of the truth.2 But
representation or vice versa, the fact remains that representation, while necessary, is by
that they are representations and, as such, a no means sufficient for the disclosure of the
skeptic may insist, always fall short of the presence of beings to us. Nor can we directly
things themselves. Yet the feebleness of these represent that disclosure itself in the ordinary

361
TRUTH

ways that we discursively represent objects or judgment.4 The prejudice is logical in the
(though we can indirectly represent, that is, sense that logic, as the study of inference,
think it).3 presupposes the possibility of properly for-
Tarskis rendition of the correspondence mulated propositions that are thus capable
theory of truth can be read as illustrating of being true or false and of being premises
Heideggers point. The snow is white is or conclusions of inferences. The compo-
true if and only if the snow is white. The nents of propositions are not true or false
clause predicated as true is equivalent to the themselves. Thus, the sunlike shines
unquoted clause because the latter refers to sun theis neither true nor false, but the
snow presenting itself as white. On some sun shines can be. Inference is a relation
interpretations, the equivalence implies that between propositions that need not be true.
the truth-predicate is redundant, superfluous, However, adherence to the rules of inference
or perhaps merely an expression of assertive guarantees that if the premises of the infer-
force. This implication reinforces Heideggers ence are true, so is the conclusion. If it is true
point that truth as correspondence cannot be that the sun shines and that whatever
the end of the story. It presupposes the dis- shines, shines on something, then it is true
closure of that to which the true assertion that the sun shines on something. Hence, it
corresponds. is the assertions or statements making up the
Meanwhile, neither the predicate true premises and conclusion that are the bearers
nor the unquoted statement in the Tarskian of truth. These truth-bearers are thus alleg-
formula directly represent that disclosure in edly the site of truth.
the way that we take terms like snow and Heidegger explicitly exposes and reverses
white to represent an object and its prop- this logical prejudice. The assertion is not the
erties respectively. The disclosure of the pres- site (place, Ort) of truth but rather truth is
ence of white snow is neither white nor snowy. the site of the assertion (SZ, 214/BT, 206).
The correspondence theory of truthin That is to say, we make assertions and they
classical terms, the conformity of the under- have their distinctive referential, predicative,
standing to the thing (adaequatio intellectus and communicative functions because they
ad rem)necessarily supposes that things can be truthful, that is, they can be helpful
present themselves of themselves in accord- and, in some cases, are even necessary for dis-
ance with the way they are understood. Not closing how things are (the presence of things
unlike skeptics such as Hume and Kant in this to us).5 But we do not disclose how things are
regard, Heidegger stresses that the proposi- for the purpose of making assertions.6
tion or understanding (intellectus) involved Mention was made earlier of the fact
is not by itself sufficient to demonstrate as that talk of truth can only be indirect and
much. What it supposes, in other words, is the metaphorical, at least relative to ordinary
disclosure of the presence (being) of things to ways of speaking in a seemingly straight-
the understanding. Heideggerwith Husserl forward and literal manner. What passes for
and in contrast to his skeptical predecessors straightforward and literal, however, is rela-
accordingly understands this disclosure as the tive to a world defined by human concerns
primordial phenomenon of truth. and interests. Contemporary science is a
It is a long-standing logical prejudice that techno-science that marshals those ordinary
truth is a property of a proposition, assertion, ways of speaking into ever more canonical

362
TRUTH

forms that define the universe of discourse. what correspond to logical structures and
In these contexts of everyday common sense judgments but are not reducible to the latter.
and scientific research, there is accordingly The objects of categorial intuitions include
no placethere are no wordsfor the truth states of affairs (corresponding to the logi-
as the disclosure of the presence of things. cal structure Fx or S is P), ideas (corre-
What passes for truth in common sense sponding to universals, such as whiteness),
and science is what the world presents to and, notably, being (corresponding in todays
confirm human mastery of it. terms to existential quantification, x(Fx)).
Truth in Heideggers sense is both sup- The categorial objects of these intuitions do
posed by yet hidden from standard ways of not correspond to those of straightforward,
relativizing truth to the representation of it. It sensory perceptions, though categorial intui-
is supposed since the way the world presents tions build upon the latter. For example, in a
itself (e.g. as capable of being mastered) is straightforward sense I see the snow, I may
not itself the doing of human beings. Once even see in a way the white of the snow, but
again this basic point cuts across the every- in neither of these ways do I see the being of
day world and the world of science. If I go the snow (i.e. that it exists). Still, I see cat-
into the woods searching for edible mush- egorially, as it were, that the snow is there,
rooms, I am only able to find them if they thanks in no small part to the sensory per-
present themselves as such. If someone asks ception. Similarly, the truth of the representa-
me how to tell the nonpoisonous from the tion of the snow as existing is not the same as
poisonous mushrooms, I may describe some the snow itself or the white of the snow. Yet I
identifying feature or even show them a pic- see categorially the truth of the assertion that
ture. But the description or picture are true the snow exists. In relation to any straightfor-
only if the mushrooms present themselves ward, sensory perception, what corresponds
as so described or picturedand that is not to being or to truth is hidden.
something that follows automatically from Perhaps more important to Heideggers
the description or picture. So, too, whatever understanding of truth as the hidden dis-
is true about the discovery and harnessing of closing of the presence of beings to us is his
electricity is not the product of the discovery interpretation of the Greek word tradition-
and harnessing itself. At the same time, what ally translated as truth, namely, aletheia. The
the discovery and the harnessing in question emphasis that Heidegger places on this inter-
represent is electricity, not the disclosure of pretation for the history of philosophy and,
its presence, that is, the very disclosure that indeed, the state of the contemporary world in
makes the discovery and harnessing possible. the grip of technology can scarcely be under-
Insofar as everyday and scientific representa- estimated. Key to Heideggers interpretation
tions are confined to beings (mushrooms, elec- is the fact that the Greek word is built from a
tricity), truth as that fundamental, underlying root (lethe) meaning hiddenness and from its
disclosure of their being remains hidden. privation in the form of the prefix (the alpha
In terms of Heideggers intellectual biog- a). In other words, a-letheia means, quite
raphy, his appreciation of the hiddenness of literally, un-hiddenness. The early Greeks
truth stems in part from his understanding (Anaximander, Heraclitus, and Parmenides)
of Husserls theory of categorial intuition. appreciated the hiddenness of beings gener-
Categorial intuitions are discernments of allyalbeit without fully thinking it through

363
TRUTH

(GA 54, 95/P, 64). As Heraclitus in particu- unhiddenness that not incidentally abets the
lar recognized, nature (physis) loves to hide use and production of things), they disregard
and a-letheia is a restless gathering (logos) the sense of hiddenness that underlies truth
and conflict (polemos) of hiddenness and as unhiddenness. This disregard brings in its
un-hiddenness as the primordial opposites. wake a progressive obliviousness to the root
As the disclosure (unhiddenness) of the pres- significance of aletheia, that is, that struggle
ence (being) of things, truth presupposes their between hiddenness and unhiddenness that
foregoing closure (hiddenness). At the same also sustains them and their relationship.
time un-hiddenness is something wondrous As a result, in modernity, not only the hid-
that happens, a movement of dis-closing and denness of things is forgotten; so, too, is the
emergence into presence, that is the funda- unhiddenness itself, as the focus shifts from
mental sense of physis, the term that captures things insofar as they are unhidden to objects
the most basic Greek understanding of being. insofar as they can be represented, produced,
This unhiddenness is captivating and human and managed.9
beings are themselves caught up in the natural The center of gravity of Heideggers
processand uncanny violenceof wresting account of truth in the 1920s shifts after
this unhiddenness from the primordial hid- 1930. Yet echoes of the medieval doctrine of
denness of things.7 the convertibility of being and truth (as tran-
With the beginnings of metaphysics (i.e. scendentals) reverberate in both accounts.
the work of Plato and Aristotle), the notion of Before 1930 Heidegger pursues fundamental
hiddenness is increasingly submerged in favor ontology, a clarification of the sense of being
of a concern with the unhiddenness of beings. that is presupposed for ontology generally,
So taken were these thinkers by the wonder through existential analysis, that is, analy-
of the sheer unhiddenness of things that they sis of the sense of being of those who exist.
equated aletheia, conceived simply as unhid- What distinguishes existence or being-here
denness, with being. The truth (aletheia) is (Da-sein) is the fact that it isof itselfthe
understood as the unhidden look of things clearing in terms of which what is at hand
(Platos ideas) or what is always already is accessible in the light and hidden in the
unhidden and finished in things (Aristotles dark. In other words, Dasein is its disclos-
to ti en einai and energeia). In a controver- edness and, as such, the most basic sense in
sial interpretation of the Cave Allegory of which truth is (SZ, 133/BT, 129). Truth in
Book VI of the Republic, Heidegger contends the most primordial sense is the disclosedness
that Platos yoking (sugon) of aletheia to the of being-here, to which the un-coveredness
manifest way things look in the light marks of inner-worldly entities belongs (SZ, 223/
a key moment in the devolution of truth as BT, 214). In other words, our being-here fun-
unhiddenness into truth as correctness and damentally coincidesis fundamentally con-
correspondence.8 vertible, as it were,with our truthfulness,
Neither Plato nor Aristotle construed that is, the way we disclose the presence of
truth (aletheia) as something fabricated or beings. As Heidegger himself puts it, being
derivative of human representation and and truth >>are<< equiprimordially (SZ, 230/
production. Yet they set the stage for this BT, 220). At the same time the dis-closedness
modern development. In their preoccupa- (truth) of being-here (genitivus appositivus)
tion with the unhiddenness of things (an presupposes being closed-off from things as

364
TRUTH

well, in the sense that they are hidden from not mean the superseding [Aufhebung] of the
us, distorted, or disguised, sometimes even hidden and setting it free and transforming
by their own doing (think of chameleons). it into something unhidden but precisely the
Hence, being-here is equiprimordially in the grounding of the abyssal ground for the con-
truth and un-truth (SZ, 223/BT, 214). This cealing (GA 65, 352/CP1, 246).
un-truth, it bears emphasizing, is not in the One form of this grounding is art. In the
first instance falsehood. It corresponds instead work [of art] the happening of truth is at work
to the fact that beings are never fully present (GA 5, 45, 59, 65/BW, 183, 196, 202). Truth
to us and, indeed, not primarily because of us, happens as an openness in the midst of beings
but because of the character of their presence that is characterized by the strife between
itself.10 Just as truth entails un-truth, so being earth and world, at once inseparable and
as presence entails absence. essentially different from one another (GA 5,
In the course of the 1930s, historical being 35/BW, 174). The earth constantly closes itself
(Seyn) replaces being-here as the locus of off from the familiar world that affords things
truth.11 The notion of truth as a clearing con- their proximity and distance, the same world
tinues to hold center stage but Heidegger no where decision, measure, and a peoples fate
longer identifies it with being-here. Instead hang historically in the balanceon earth.
being-here is a necessary part of the event The truth that places itself in the artwork is
(Ereignis) of that clearing or disclosure of the strife between clearing and concealment
historical being (Seyn) that conceals itself in in the opposition of world and earth to one
the process. As noted above, it is not only another (GA 5, 50/BW, 187).
the presence (being) of beings and thus the In 1964 Heidegger makes some significant
disclosure (truth) of that presence that are qualifications, if not retractions regarding his
incomplete and fraught with absence. The previous handling of the question of truth
very disclosure of that presence conceals itself in terms of aletheia. He acknowledges that
as well. This self-concealingbeings with- the natural concept of truth does not sig-
drawal or epocheis the event that under- nify un-hiddenness and that the question of
lies the ways in which beings historically are aletheia, un-hiddenness, is thus not the ques-
present to us. Sometimes Heidegger employs tion of truth as such. He also concedes that
being (Sein)in contrast to historical the claim that an essential change took place
being to signify the way beings are conceived in regard to truth, namely, from un-hiddenness
metaphysically within a particular historical to correctness, is untenable. Such a claim
epoch. Historical being is the groundless, leaves the false impression that the early
grounding event in terms of which beings Greeks did not already use aletheia in the sense
are rendered present to being-here, allow- of correspondence or agreement (homoiosis).
ing beings and being-here alike to come into Moreover, the identification of aletheia with
their own. Against this backdrop Heidegger truth naively overlooks the weight of the tra-
characterizes truth as the clearing for the ditional understanding of truth as veritas, a
self-concealing, the self-concealing of his- major historical obstacle to appreciating the
torical being in the clearing of the here full significance of un-hiddenness. Construing
[da], where the truth-bearer is the appro- aletheia as truth also confuses the possibility
priating event (GA 65, 344, 346/CP1, 240, of truth with any sort of actual verification
242). The clearing of the concealment does (GA 14, 85ff./ID, 6972).

365
TRUTH

However, whatever the weight of these the assertion or statement (Aussage) as the site
qualifications, they do not constitute a of truth, other times the judgment (Urteil) or
even the proposition or sentence (Satz); see SZ,
retraction of Heideggers basic contentions:
214/BT, 206.
that there is no un-hiddenness (truth in the 5
Heidegger elaborates these three functions
primordial sense as a-letheia) and thus no of assertions (that they are about or refer to
truth in any sense, without hiddenness; that something by way of determining it through
what it means to be (or, equivalently, the predication and that they are means of com-
munication) in 33 of SZ.
truth of historical being as the appropriating 6
Heidegger notably defends Aristotle from the
event) coincides with the struggle by which charge of buying into the logical prejudice.
the un-hiddenness of things is wrested from Aristotle defines assertions in terms of truth
their hiddenness; that the meaning, future, rather than vice versa and he plainly recog-
and liberation of human existence consist nizes a nonpropositional access to truth; see
SZ, 226/BT, 216f.
fundamentally in resolutely owning up to 7
Heidegger finds a telling account of the Greek
this struggle over all others.12 understanding of the violence of this wrest-
ing in the song of the chorus in Sophocles
Antigone; see GA 40, 12032/IM, 16783.
8
GA 9, 2234/PA, 17180; GA 34, 21112/ET,
NOTES AND REFERENCES 1781; GA 65, 3315/CP1, 2325.
9
Crucial to the eventual loss of the primor-
1
Aristotle, De anima, III (431a16): the soul dial senses of hiddenness and un-hiddenness
never thinks without an image; see, too, ibid., entailed by aletheia is its Latin translation
432a89. as veritas. Instead of being itself a privative
2
SZ, 226/BT, 217: Newtons laws, the law term, supposing an underlying hiddenness
of contradiction, and any truth whatso- as something positive, veritas in the sense of
ever, are true only as long as Dasein is; imperial Roman and Ecclesial rightness or
GA 65, 356/CP1, 249: 229. Truth and correctness becomes basic and its privation is
Being-here [Da-sein]. The clearing for the no longer hiddenness, but something negative,
self-concealing illumines itself in the projec- namely, falsitas. For an extended account of
tion. The throwing of the projection occurs this development, culminating in truth as the
as Da-sein . . . (see, too, GA 65, 329/CP1, judiciousness (Gerechtigkeit) of the will to
231). To put the point more prosaically, power, see GA 54, 4286/P, 2858.
truth supposes the very opposite of inactivity 10
On the various modes of hiddenness, see GA
on our part even though it is not the product 54, 86130/P, 5887.
simply of anything we do. 11
In 35. Ein Hinweis auf die Wahrheitsfrage
3
At this juncture the mill-run skeptic and in Besinnung, Heidegger lists nine key places
Heidegger probably part ways. If the skeptic between 1930 and 1940 where he explic-
insists on the direct representation of things, itly addresses the question of truth (GA 66,
the assertion that truth cannot be directly rep- 107/M, 89f.). This list supports his retrospec-
resented appears to the skeptic as a confirma- tive in 1969 where he charts the course of his
tion of the skeptical contention. For Heidegger, thinking as proceeding from the question of
by contrast, it signals the limits of representa- the sense of being to that of the truth of being
tional thinking in this sense. and, finally, that of the place of being. Notably
4
Longstanding debates about the truth-bearers he emphasizes that he understands truth in the
often turn on differences between propositions second question not as the correctness of an
and sentences, statements and judgments, and assertion but as unhiddenness or clearing
the like. While not eschewing such differences, (GA 15, 344f./FS, 46f.).
Heideggers criticism of the logical prejudice 12
On resoluteness as the authentic truth, see
does not discriminate accordingly. So, some- GA 5, 55/BW, 192; GA 13, 63f.; GA 65, 87/
times he speaks of the prejudice of construing CP1, 60f.

366
46
HEIDEGGER AND SARTRE:
HISTORICITY, DESTINY, AND POLITICS
Robert Bernasconi

In 1946 in Letter on Humanism Heidegger time for him. But in Letter on Humanism
presented what is sometimes thought of as Heidegger gave no hint that he had read
a devastating critique of Sartre, but only a any of Being and Nothingness. He focused
year earlier in a note to himself he endorsed only on Existentialism is a Humanism, the
Sartres reading of Being and Time. Heidegger transcript of an occasional lecture delivered
wrote in relation to Corbins translation of late in 1945 and intended for the general
What is Metaphysics?: Decisive effect on public rather than an academic audience.
Sartre: from there Being and Time under- Sartres lecture was itself more conciliatory
stood for the first time (GA 3, 251/KPM, in tone toward Heidegger than Being and
176). Indeed on October 28, 1945 Heidegger Nothingness had been, but Heidegger would
wrote to Sartre, not only acknowledging that not have appreciated this work of popu-
in Being and Nothingness Sartre had shown larization in which Sartre seemed to present
a level of understanding of Being and Time the two of them as if they were members of
that he had not found elsewhere, but also the same branch of atheistic existentialism.2
recognizing him as an independent thinker They did not meet until 1952 after which
in his own right.1 Acting completely out Heidegger spoke more favorably of their
of character, Heidegger told Sartre that he 90-minute conversation than did Sartre.3
accepted Sartres critique of the account of In Existentialism is a Humanism Sartre had
Mitsein in Being and Time and he acknowl- little to say about Heidegger in the essay but
edged the legitimacy of Sartres insistence on he did attribute to atheistic existentialism the
being-for-others. At the same time Heidegger conviction that the human being first mate-
told Sartre that he himself had meanwhile rializes in the world, encounters himself, and
moved on and that what was most impor- only afterward defines himself.4 This is how
tant to him now was establishing an original Sartre explained the formulation existence
relation with the beginning of Western his- precedes essence. In Letter on Humanism
tory. It was a remarkably conciliatory letter, Heidegger sought to distance himself from
even if one cannot avoid the suspicion that this formula by objecting that Sartre was still
Heidegger was soliciting Sartres help during using the terms existence and essence accord-
what after Germanys defeat was a difficult ing to their metaphysical meaning and that

369
HEIDEGGER AND SARTRE

by merely reversing the terms he remained was a difference between these two destinies,
within Western metaphysics: The differenti- Heideggers and his own, but, as I shall show,
ation of essentia (essentiality) and existentia the precise sense he gave them changed.
(actuality) completely dominates the destiny Heideggers polemic against Sartre did
of Western history and of all history deter- not constitute a major part of the Letter on
mined by Europe (GA 9, 329/P, 250). For Humanism. This essays philosophical sig-
Heidegger it was not as a result of a simple nificance lies rather in seeing how Heidegger,
failure of human thinking that Western meta- after being largely silent, chose to introduce
physics had failed to ask the question about his readers to his thinking of the history of
the destiny of being, but it belonged to that being. But it was also a somewhat cynical
destiny itself. This notion of destiny is one attempt on his part to rehabilitate his dam-
of the keys to understanding what separated aged reputation after the war.7 In addition to
Sartre from Heidegger. dismissing nationalism, Heidegger presented
Sartres specific criticisms of Heidegger in his thought as open to a productive dialogue
Being and Nothingness are now no longer with Marxism in a way that he alleged that
generally considered to be as incisive as Sartre was not (GA 9, 340/P, 259). Heidegger
Heidegger suggested in his letter. Sartre him- seems to have been playing it safe given the
self went back on some of them as his own proximity of the Soviet army, but the philo-
thinking developed and his appreciation of sophical basis of this claim was that, accord-
Heideggers early thinking deepened as a ing to what he had read of him, Sartre did
result. Sartre had bought a copy of Being not recognize the essential importance of
and Time at the end of 1933, but he did not the historical in being (ibid.).
begin to read it seriously until the summer Heidegger scholars have formulated the
of 1939. He explained the delay in terms of criticisms that they believe Heidegger should
his fondness for Husserl and when he wrote have leveled against Sartres Being and
Being and Nothingness he was still closer to Nothingness. Most notably, Michel Harr
Husserl than Heidegger. Nevertheless, in his accused Sartre of preserving the fundamental
War Diaries for February 1940, at a time structures of metaphysics, when, for exam-
when he was teaching Heideggers philoso- ple, he described the presence of conscious-
phy to his fellow inmates in a prison of war ness to itself as an act of self-foundation
camp, he judged his discovery of Heidegger and the origin of all meaning.8 Even when
to be providential because it taught him Sartre tried to follow Heidegger, as when he
the meaning of authenticity and historicity at took up section 13 of Being and Time and
the very time when the war had made these attempted to break with Husserl by treating
notions indispensable to him.5 In order to knowledge as a founded mode of being in the
understand how this external influence on world, he allegedly ended up reaffirming the
him could be made sense of within his philos- preeminence of knowledge by linking under-
ophy of freedom, Sartre wrote I can redis- standing with consciousness.9 One might
cover Heideggers assumption of his destiny respond that Sartre insisted that already in
as a German, in that wretched Germany of Being and Nothingness Consciousness is not
the postwar years, in order to help assume knowledge but existence.10 But ultimately
my destiny as a Frenchman in the France of for a Heideggerian it is Sartres retention of
40.6 Sartre never lost his sense that there the language of consciousness that assigns

370
HEIDEGGER AND SARTRE

him irretrievably to the Western metaphysi- precedes existence if one understands it,
cal tradition. as Sartre did, in terms of the human beings
Whether Being and Nothingness is as encounter with the world. In any event, to
Cartesian as is usually maintained should be correct this Sartre introduced into Critique
questioned. It is true that Sartre insists on the of Dialectical Reason the notion of the
cogito as his point of departure but he adds practico-inert. The practico-inert is Simply
that it leads us only on condition that we the activity of others in so far as it is sus-
get out of it.11 Heideggerian critics of Sartre tained and diverted by inorganic inertia.17
who accuse him of dualism seem to be as That is to say, it is the level where alienated
mesmerized byto use Simone de Beauvoirs praxis and worked inertia are equivalent.18
phrasea pseudo-Sartrianism, just as Whereas the upshot of the discussion of free-
Merleau-Ponty was.12 They treat Sartres dom in Being and Nothingness was that even
for-itself and in-itself as if they had the onto- a slave is free because the slave can choose
logical status of subject and object, whereas him- or herself on the ground of slavery, in
even in Being and Nothingness Sartre recog- the Critique Sartre protested that it is not the
nized them as abstractions. Against dualism case that all men are free in all situations, I
he wrote: the For-Itself and the In-itself are mean the exact opposite: all men are slaves in
reunited by a synthetic connection which so far as their life unfolds in the practico-in-
is nothing other than the For-itself itself.13 ert field and in so far as this field is always
To be sure, Sartres reading of Heidegger conditioned by scarcity.19
in Being and Nothingness is inadequate by The justification of this notion of scarcity
todays standards.14 But increasingly it is the lies in concrete history, but the idea is absent
Critique of Dialectical Reason from 1960 from Being and Nothingness and there is
that is recognized as Sartres masterpiece and some indication that it finds its way into
it is to this work, which has inspired philoso- Sartres philosophy as he tried to explore
phers from the Third World who recognized more deeply the basis of his distance from
its powerful resources for identifying sys- Heidegger. Sartre never responded publicly
temic oppression as a prelude to resisting it, to Heideggers Letter on Humanism, and
that we should now turn.15 with the possible exception of a remark in
In Letter on Humanism, Heidegger Notebooks for an Ethics, where he dismissed
reinterpreted his earlier thinking in the light both Husserl and Heidegger as small-time
of what came later, and this enabled him philosophers in contrast with Hegel and
to exaggerate Sartres misunderstanding of even Marx, there is no indication that Sartre
Being and Time. By contrast, Sartres inclina- was offended by Heideggers criticisms.20
tion was often to be dismissive of his own However, in the unpublished manuscript
earlier ideas. This was especially true of some Truth and Existence, written only one year
of his more brazen pronouncements about after the Letter appeared, and more focused
human freedom. They are significant in this on Heideggers essay Essence of Truth that
context because they can be understood as had only recently appeared in French transla-
having arisen from overemphasizing the tion, there was not a point by point rebut-
project within Heideggers account of the tal, but at least some clear indications of
thrown project.16 Arguably this is also what how Sartre would have responded to Letter
went wrong with the formulation essence on Humanism. One sees this, for example, in

371
HEIDEGGER AND SARTRE

his comments on the idea of historical com- Sartres definition of praxis as an organising
placency that arises from the acceptance of project which transcends material conditions
destiny, Sartre writes: As for this Being itself, towards an end and inscribes itself, though
it is conceived in the inauthentic (happiness labor, in organic matter as a rearrangement
or the harmonious society), because it is first of the practical field and a reunification of
of all posited by needs (hunger, revolt against means in the light of the end.25 And the
slavery, etc.).21 Indeed, he already anticipates proximity to Heidegger is even clearer when
in this text what he says in the Critique, that Sartre insists on knowing as a moment of
need is concretized in scarcity and that scarcity praxis.26 But what gives new depth to this
is the material condition of antagonism.22 account is the extent to which it is tied to a
When Haar reads how Sartre in Search for new appreciation of material circumstances.
a Method dismissed the philosophy of Karl As one commentator describes it, in the
Jaspers but judged the case of Heidegger too Critique Sartre renders the cogito dialectical
complex to discuss, he concluded that this and thus acknowledges that consciousness
was an evasion of the philosophical prob- and materiality are indissolubly connected.27
lems.23 In my account, by contrast, these lines Sartre liked to borrow a phrase from Engels
reflect Sartres new appreciation for the phi- to make the same point: Men themselves
losophy of Being and Time. This interpreta- make their history but in a given environ-
tion is supported by Pietro Chiodi who argued ment that conditions them.28
that the Critique is a straightforward return Sartre was clearly well aware of his prox-
to the Heideggerian position after the attack imity to Heidegger and the evidence is in the
on it in Being and Nothingness.24 The basis text. The evidence for this emerges when we
for this claim is the recognition that by the juxtapose the accusations leveled against
time he wrote Critique of Dialectical Reason Sartre by the Heideggerians that he did not
Sartre had come to a richer understanding of understand Heidegger, with Sartres comment
what Heidegger had meant by the thrown in Search for a Method that Lukcs has the
project. The rapprochement does not extend instruments to understand Heidegger, but
to all other aspects of the book, such as the he will not understand him.29 Lukcs had
so-called phenomenological destruction, nor attacked not only Sartre in Existentialisme ou
to the late Heidegger. Furthermore, one has Marxisme? but also albeit to a lesser extent
to differentiate how Heidegger seems to have Heidegger, Jaspers, and Merleau-Ponty.30 In
understood the thrown project in Being and the course of defending himself, Sartre chose
Time and how Heidegger had reinterpreted also to come to Heideggers defense. After
it in Letter on Humanism where the thrown saying that Lukcs does not understand
project is no longer thrown by Dasein but by Heidegger, Sartre added: And there is no
being itself (GA 9, 337/P, 257). Sartre had no longer any Marxist, to my knowledge, who
reason to accept Heideggers attempt to tie is still capable of doing so.31 By implica-
the thrown project to the thinking of destiny tion, Sartre was saying that he alone among
such that Da-sein . . . unfolds essentially Marxists understood Heidegger, and anyone
in the throw of being as a destinal sending who wants to understand Sartre also needs
(GA 9, 327/P, 249). to understand Heidegger. It was hardly the
Nevertheless, we can recognize the thrown most tactful way to introduce a volume
project of Being and Time in the Critique in designed to convince Marxists of Marxisms

372
HEIDEGGER AND SARTRE

compatibility with existentialism, but it of them is hatred of man in the sense that
shows the depth of his appreciation of his they are not only victims of alienation but its
debt to the early Heidegger. accomplices too.34
Sartres relation to the late Heidegger is This does not end the harsh things Sartre
very different. Although most of the refer- was willing to say about those aspects of
ences to Heidegger in Critique of Dialectical Heideggers philosophy from which he
Reason are to the early Heidegger and, wanted to distance himself. In an interview
moreover, are in Search for a Method and in May 1975, when told that some students
so are outside the main body of the book, wondered if they could take a philosopher
one passage in the Critique proper develops seriously who at one point was a Nazi, Sartre
a powerful rejection of the late Heidegger sided with them, but not because of his
for not being faithful to Being and Time and Nazism. I would reproach him, but rather
in ways that return to the themes raised by for a lack of seriousness. His attitude showed
Letter on Humanism. Sartre writes: The a compliance with the regime in power in
reason why Heidegger payed tribute to order to continue teaching his courses more
Marxism is that he saw Marxist philoso- than an awareness of any value that Nazism
phy as a way of showing, as Waelhens says claimed to have.35 Sartre was willing to con-
(speaking of Heideggerian existentialism), demn Heidegger for his Nazism, but he was
that Being is Other in me . . . (and that) equally willing to condemn him in the face
man . . . is himself only through Being, of any attempt to excuse him on the grounds
which is not him.32 Sartre is clearly refer- that politics was of no importance to him.
encing the passage in Letter on Humanism According to Sartre, there was a time when
where Heidegger alleged that Sartre was philosophy could be separated from poli-
without the means to enter into a produc- tics, but that time had passed. It is on that
tive dialogue with Marxism. Furthermore, question, rather than the issue of whether
in referencing Heideggers existentialism Heidegger had understood Sartre, or Sartre
he was also reiterating the characterization had understood Heidegger, that the destiny
to which Heidegger in the same essay had of the proper names Heidegger and Sartre
objected. Sartre continued: But any philoso- will ultimately be decided. It will be deter-
phy which subordinates the human to what mined not by the circumstances that Sartre
is Other than man, whether it be an existen- evoked when he referred to their different
tialist or Marxist idealism has hatred of man nationalities, but by whether one believes
as both its basis and its consequence: History one can separate philosophy from politics,
has proved this in both cases.33 That is to which since 1933 has been the overriding
say, history has given us National Socialism question no reader of Heidegger can afford
and Stalinism and the former is reflected to ignore.
in Heideggers decision to conceive of the
human being as the bearer of the opening of
Being as the latter is reflected in the exter- NOTES AND REFERENCES
nal materialist dialectic. Both Heidegger and
the Marxist idealists oppose the human to 1
The letter is published in French in Frdric de
what is Other than man. Sartre in his inimi- Towarnicki, la rencontre de Heidegger (Paris:
Gallimard, 1993), 835.
table way insisted that what underlies both

373
HEIDEGGER AND SARTRE

2
Jean-Paul Sartre, Lexistentialisme est and Sartre, in ed. Steven Crowell, Cambridge
un humanisme (Paris: Nagel, 1946), 17; Companion to Existentialism (Cambridge:
trans. Carol Macomber, Existentialism is a Cambridge University Press, 2012), 34260.
Humanism (New Haven: Yale University Press, 16
See Robert Bernasconi, How to Read Sartre
2007), 20. (London: Granta, 2006), 4352.
3
Towarnicki, la rencontre, 856. 17
Jean-Paul Sartre, Critique de la raison
4
Sartre, Lexistentialisme est un humanisme, dialectique (Paris: Gallimard, 1960), 547; trans.
21; trans. Macomber, Existentialism is a Alan Sheridan-Smith, Critique of Dialectical
Humanism, 22. (London: New Left Books, 1976), 556.
5
Jean-Paul Sartre, Carnets de la drle de 18
Sartre, Critique de la raison dialectique, 154;
guerre (Paris: Gallimard, 1995), 403; trans. trans. Sheridan-Smith, Critique of Dialectical
Quintin Hoare, War Diaries (London: Verso, Reason, 67.
1984), 182. 19
Sartre, Ltre et le nant, 635; trans. Barnes,
6
Sartre, Carnets, 4089; trans. Hoare, War Being and Nothingness, 550. Sartre,
Diaries, 187. Critique de la raison dialectique, 369; trans.
7
See Ethan Kleinberg, The Letter on Sheridan-Smith, Critique of Dialectical
Humanism. Reading Heidegger in France, in Reason, 331. To be sure, on closer examina-
eds Jonathan Judaken and Robert Bernasconi, tion there is a passage already in Being and
Situating Existentialism (New York: Columbia Nothingness that comes closer to what he says
University Press, 2012), 386413. in the Critique than some commentators are
8
Michel Haar, Sartre and Heidegger, in eds willing to concede. The difference is that in
Hugh J. Silverman and Frederick A. Elliston, Being and Nothingness the Other limits my
Jean-Paul Sartre. Contemporary Approaches freedom, whereas in the Critique it is the mate-
to his Philosophy (Pittsburgh: Duquesne rial conditions. Sartre, Ltre et le nant, 326;
University Press, 1980), 168. trans. Barnes, Being and Nothingness, 267.
9
Haar, Sartre and Heidegger, 1701. 20
Jean-Paul Sartre, Cahiers pour une morale
10
Jean-Paul Sartre, Vrit et existence (Paris: (Paris: Gaillimard, 1983), 67; trans. David
Gallimard, 1989), 18; trans. Adrian van Pellauer, Notebooks for an Ethics (Chicago:
den Hoven, Truth and Existence (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992), 61.
University of Chicago Press, 1992), 4. 21
Sartre, Vrit et existence, 12; trans. Hoven,
11
Jean-Paul Sartre, Ltre et le nant (Paris: Truth and Existence, 12.
Gallimard, 1943), 116; trans. Hazel E. Barnes, 22
Sartre, Critique de la raison dialectique, 192;
Being and Nothingness (London: Methuen, trans. Sheridan-Smith, Critique of Dialectical
1957), 734. Reason, 113. Compare Sartre, Vrit et
12
Robert Bernasconi, Sartres Response to existence, 84; trans. Hoven, Truth and
Merleau-Pontys Charge of Subjectivism, Existence, 44n.
Philosophy Today, 50 (Supplement 2006), 23
Haar, Sartre and Heidegger, 169. Jean-Paul
11325. Sartre, Critique de la raison dialectique, 21n;
13
Sartre, Ltre et le nant, 711; trans. Barnes, trans. Hazel E. Barnes, Search for a Method
Being and Nothingness, 617. (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1963), 15n.
14
Nevertheless, for an example of how Sartre 24
Pietro Chiodi, Sartre and Marxism, trans. Kate
might still be defended, see Steve Martinot, Soper (Hassocks: Harvester Press, 1976), 8.
Sartres being-for-Heidegger; Heideggers 25
Sartre, Critique de la raison dialectique, 687;
being-for-Sartre, Man and World, 24.1 trans. Sheridan-Smith, Critique of Dialectical
(1991), 6374. Reason, 734.
15
For example, Frantz Fanon, Les damns 26
Sartre, Critique de la raison dialectique, 63;
de la terre (Paris: Maspero, 1961); trans. trans. Barnes, Search for a Method, 91.
Richard Philcox, The Wretched of the Earth 27
Leo Fretz, Individuality in Sartres
(New York: Grove Press, 2004). See Robert Philosophy, in ed. Christina Howells, The
Bernasconi, Racism is a System: How Cambridge Companion to Sartre (Cambridge:
Existentialism became Dialectial in Fanon Cambridge University Press, 1992), 80, 89.

374
HEIDEGGER AND SARTRE

28
Friedrich Engels to Borgius, January 25, 1894. passage concerns the early Heidegger. Sartre
In Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, Werke, also cites Walter Biemels book, which has more
vol.39 (Berlin: Dietz, 1984), 206. Quoted to say about the later Heidegger: Le concept de
Sartre, Critique de la raison dialectique, 60; monde chez Heidegger (Paris: Vrin, 1950).
trans. Barnes, Search for a Method, 85. 33
Sartre, Critique de la raison dialectique, 248;
29
Sartre, Critique de la raison dialectique, 345; trans. Sheridan-Smith, Critique of Dialectical
trans. Barnes, Search for a Method, 38. Reason, 181.
30
Georg Lukacs, Existentialisme ou Marxisme? 34
Ibid.
(Paris: Nagel, 1948). 35
Jean-Paul Sartre, An Interview with Jean-
31
Sartre, Critique de la raison dialectique, 345; Paul Sartre, in ed. Paul Arthur Schilpp, The
trans. Barnes, Search for a Method, 38. Philosophy of Jean-Paul Sartre (La Salle, IL:
32
Sartre, Critique de la raison dialectique, 248; Open Court, 1981), 32. It should also be
trans. Sheridan-Smith, Critique of Dialectical recalled that in Occupied France after the
Reason, 181. The quotation is from Alphonse publication of Being and Nothingness Sartre
de Waelhens, Phnomnologie et Vrit. Essai was criticized for his interest in a Nazi philoso-
sur lvolution de lide de verit chez Husserl pher like Heidegger. Kenneth and Margaret
et Heidegger (Paris: PUF, 1953), 160. It should Thompson, Sartre. Life and Works (New York:
be noted that this book and specifically this Facts on File, 1984), 50.

375
47
HEIDEGGER AND MERLEAU-PONTY:
THOUGHT IN THE OPEN
Wayne J. Froman

Merleau-Pontys Notes de Cours 1959 sense-complex that comes about by way


1961,1 from his lectures at the Collge de of the historicizing of our lived experience.
France, published in 1996, provide back- Philosophys task, as Heidegger understands
ground for the significant appearance in his it here, is the primordial carrying out of this
The Visible and the Invisible: Followed by movement, and with this sense of primordial-
Working Notes,2 unfinished at the time of his ity, Heidegger takes up the issue of constitu-
death and published posthumously in 1964, tion, which figures in phenomenology as, so
of Heideggerian terminology.3 The publica- to speak, an ultimate dynamic. The coming
tion of Heideggers early lectures, including, about of this sense-complex by way of the
from the summer of 1920, Phenomenology of initial self-obscuring or movement away that
Intuition and Expression (GA 59/PIE), which pertains to facticity marks the occurrence or
will be particularly helpful here, provide the event of world, and along with that, as
important background for Being and Time Heidegger will accentuate in Being and Time,
(GA 2/BTMR, BT), and at the same time are how we are always already in-the-world by
of help in understanding the pertinence of way of a structure where the unity is Care
Merleau-Pontys thought to Heideggers. The (Sorge).
issue in these lectures is facticity, and along Importantly, the falling away of factic-
with it, historicity. Facticity, the very fact that ity, its self-obscuring, always comes first. It
we are and must be, tends to obscure itself is not after the fact. Thus, there is no initial
and this marks movement away or distanc- coincidence, and this is the significance of
ing from facticity. This is a historicizing the word complex in reference to facticity.
intrinsic to lived experience and it opens us We are always already in-the-world. In Being
to cultural and historical factors. In that fac- and Time, Heidegger will characterize factic-
ticity is the fact that we are and must be, in ity as a thrown projection. The point to
one way or another, there is a movement of the effect that there is no initial coincidence
return. This movement amounts to our liv- is what makes Heideggers phenomenologi-
ing out, what Heidegger calls a vollziehen, cal analysis here a de-struction of both
an enactment, a carrying out, or perhaps, intuition and expression. Intuition,
execution, of what Heidegger here calls a associated by Husserl with an end-point of

377
HEIDEGGER AND MERLEAU-PONTY

phenomenological reduction, where the con- In Being and Time, Heidegger proceeds
tent of awareness is apprehended apodicti- with phenomenological analysis of that
cally in its self-givenness or self-evidence, entity we are, Dasein, that is, the entity char-
would amount to an immediate and direct acterized by ex-istence, by our always already
apprehension of what is there to be appre- being-in-the-world, which is the mark of our
hended, but by virtue of the fact that the facticity. Dasein is characterized, in effect,
obscuring of facticity and the movement by a running ahead of itself (vorlaufen).
away comes first, there is no such coincidence In Division I, Preparatory Fundamental
in the first place to be recovered or regained. Analysis of Dasein, of Part I, the only
The sense of a direct and immediate appre- part to ever see the light of day, Heidegger
hension of what is there to be apprehended specifies three existentialia, structural
is bound up with the Cartesian Cogito, the I features of the existential constitution
think, which is characterized by direct and of the there (the da) of Dasein whereby
immediate access to its content, providing Dasein gets disclosed: Befindlichkeit, mood
a certainty that would have to be included, (or attunement, or disposition), Verstehen,
somehow, in any knowing. understanding, and Rede, discourse. Mood,
When Heidegger then examines two com- which Heidegger analyzes first, is disclosive
peting philosophical trajectories at the time, of being-in-the-world as a whole (BTMR,
that of Paul Natorp and that of Wilhelm 176). Mood always involves a moving away
Dilthey, he finds them both lacking, in dif- and a moving toward. For example, fear
ferent ways, and to different degrees, with involves that of which one is fearful, and it
regard to the issue of facticity. Natorp advo- involves that for which one is fearful. What
cated a methodological reconstruction of distinguishes the mood of anxiety, which
Platonic truths and in doing so took as a start- Heidegger characterizes as a rare mood
ing point a vantage point already sufficiently that can precede an individuals being in the
distanced from the fact that we are and must Moment (Augenblick), is that what one is
be as to preclude the sense of facticity and anxious about and that for the sake of which
a return to the context of lived experience. one is anxious are the same, namely, ones
Dilthey, in understanding the subject matter very being-in-the-world.
of the historical sciences as self-expressions After the analyses of the three structural
of life that can be understood by means of features of our being-in-the-world, no one
hermeneutics, rather than by means of the of which lies deeper than or accounts for
explanatory methodology of the natural sci- the others, which is to say that they are
ences that is bound up with a Cartesian sense equi-primordial, and after the specifica-
of the Cogito, was surely closer to facticity tion that the unity of these features lies in
and historicity. But Diltheys far-reaching Care (Sorge), Heidegger asks about the pos-
insights notwithstanding, what Heidegger sibility of bringing Dasein as a whole within
finds is: Dilthey did not see that only a radi- our grasp. This would guard against the pos-
calism that makes all concepts questionable sibility of an undermining of the analysis.
can lead further. The entire conceptual mate- Heidegger finds possible means for bringing
rial must be newly determined in primordial Dasein as a whole within our grasp, which
apprehension. That is the particular tendency is to say, in effect, thinking Dasein from one
of phenomenology (PIE, 129). end to the other, in Daseins being toward a

378
HEIDEGGER AND MERLEAU-PONTY

distinctive end, namely, death or mortality. From the initial characterization of our
This suggests the possibility of an authentic facticity in terms of Daseins running ahead
mode of existence that amounts to the how of itself, the sense in which Dasein is always
of being in the Moment (Augenblick), which already in-the-world, to the appearance late
is to say, the authentic present. This authentic in the text of the question of history, what
present lies in the alignment of extremities of is undermined is the direct and immediate
future and past, where the former is under- access to its own content of the Cartesian
stood in terms of Daseins running ahead of Cogito. This direct and immediate access to
itself unto death or mortality, and the latter its own content is indicative of the classical
is understood in terms of a resolute return, in sense of substance that goes back to the man-
effect, to facticity, a return that is prompted ner in which Aristotle takes the culmination
by the call of conscience. The analysis of the of Greek philosophy in Platos thought to
possibility of an authentic mode of exist- its farthest reaches. What is at stake in that
ence then becomes the point of departure for culmination of Greek philosophy is the iden-
a preliminary reinterpretation of Daseins tification of Being with presentness, which
existential structure in terms of the tempo- means with ongoing presence. That identifi-
ralizing of Dasein. cation will define philosophical thought since
After that preliminary reinterpretation the Greeks. Descartes unquestioningly adopts
of Daseins existential structure, Heidegger the sense of substance. In modern thinking,
observes that a deeper rethinking of the Kants transcendental philosophizing, for all
character of Dasein would have to take into its radicality, will nonetheless sustain that
account the other end of Dasein, in addi- sense of substance in its analysis of reflection.
tion to death or mortality, namely, birth. In Heideggers understanding, the longstand-
Now, in the next to last chapter of what was ing model, in effect, for what becomes the
to be part I of a two-part Being and Time, standard ontology, is found in the concep-
Heidegger explicitly brings up the issue of tion of perception as a bringing together of a
history. Here Heidegger characterizes his concept with a sensory manifold, a making
thinking as hermeneutical in a manner that present that amounts, in effect, to a subjec-
takes up the work of Count Von Yorck in tivizing of perception in a manner consistent
the service of Diltheys insights. Count Von with a tendency in Greek thought, and which
Yorck had emphasized the historicity of the reinforces an unquestioned identification of
practitioner of hermeneutics, so to speak, in Being with ongoing presence. What drops
distinction from the historicity of the herme- out is any sense of facticitys self-obscuring
neutical subject matter, so to speak. What and the movement away or forgetting that
Heidegger specifies here is that the possibility precedes a living out, in one way or another,
for understanding historicity lies in under- an enactment of the sense-complex that takes
standing the temporalizing of Dasein. While shape with this historicizing. In Heideggers
Heideggers discussion here of historicizing The Basic Problems of Phenomenology, a
is brief, it is clear from his earlier lectures, lecture course from the same year as the pub-
and in particular from his Phenomenology of lication of Being and Time, 1927, he writes:
Intuition and Expression, that this is hardly
a tacked-on afterthought. It is, in fact, the When Kant says, therefore, that exist-
destination of his thinking here. encethat is, for us, extantness, being

379
HEIDEGGER AND MERLEAU-PONTY

on or at handis perception, this thesis a stroke. The point here is that there can be
is extremely rough and misleading; all no data until the perception takes place.5
the same it points to the correct direction Merleau-Ponty next distinguishes between
of the problem. On our interpretation, our body as objectivistically conceived, which
being is perception now means: being
is to say conceived subjectivistically, and our
is an intentional comportment of a pecu-
body as lived, the phenomenal body, or ones
liar sort, namely, enpresenting; it is an
ecstasis in the unity of temporality with own body (le corps propre), or the lived body
a schema of its own, praesens. Being (le corps vcu). Here Merleau-Ponty explores
equals perception, when interpreted the spatiality of the body and motility, the
in original phenomenological terms, synthesis of the body understood as ec-static
means: being equals presence, praesens. by way of the living of the body, the sexual
At the same time, it thus turns out that schema of the body, and the body as expres-
Kant interprets being and being-existent sion and speech. All of this is prior to our
exactly as ancient philosophy does, for body as objectivisitically conceived, which is
which that which is is the hupokeime- to say, conceived subjectivistically. None of
non, which has the character of ousia
this can be understood by way of an objectiv-
(substance). In Aristotles time ousia in
istic analysis, which relies on a subjectivistic
its everyday, pre-philosophical sense is
still equivalent to property, estate, but as point of departure.
a philosophical term it signifies presence. In part II of the text, Merleau-Ponty
(BP, 315) explores the world as perceived. He pro-
ceeds by way of sensory experience where
the synthesis is again prior to objectification
In Phenomenology of Perception, published by a subjectivity. Having begun from the
in 1945, Merleau-Ponty carries out a lived body, and proceeding by way of sen-
de-struction of perception.4 He first dis- sory experience, Merleau-Ponty reaches the
tinguishes theoretical accounts of perception other pole, so to speak, of this trajectory,
that are empiricist in character from theoreti- the world as perceived, which includes
cal accounts of perception that are intellec- the things and the natural world as well
tualist in character. According to the former, as others and the human world. Along the
perceptions content comes about basically way, there are indications of how all this may
by way of an automatic physiological proc- actually be perceived in a manner that is not
ess. According to the latter, perceptual con- bound up with objectification.
tent comes about by way of an intervention, In part III of the text, the final part,
such as attention or judgment, by the intel- Merleau-Ponty addresses the Cogito, tempo-
lect. Merleau-Ponty then points out that rality and freedom. Importantly, with each
both types of theoretical accounts employ step into a subjectivity, Merleau-Ponty dis-
the notion of sense data or bare units of covers our being-in-the-world. In the chap-
sensation. Furthermore, we never encoun- ter devoted to the Cogito, Merleau-Ponty
ter such units in our awareness. These are suggests a tacit cogito that is prior to
purely constructs employed in contrived Descartess articulated Cogito and that lies in
theoretical depictions of perception. At one the context of existence, the context of our
point, Merleau-Ponty characterizes percep- being-in-the-world. Importantly, by the time
tion as just that act that creates its data at Merleau-Ponty begins work on The Visible

380
HEIDEGGER AND MERLEAU-PONTY

and the Invisible, we find in the Working one to the context of reflection remains itself
Notes for the text published along with it unjustified and facticity is simply lost from
that he had found the tacit cogito unten- sight. With regard to dialectical philosophiz-
able insofar as it would imply an adequation ing, which reaches its culmination in Hegels
at the level of existence or being-in-the-world. work, an ultimately auto-critical dimen-
He also indicates in a Working Note that sion would be needed in order that facticity
the analysis of the Cogito should have been not drop out in the course of the dialectical
related explicitly to the analysis, earlier in ascent. This is not provided by Sartres trun-
Phenomenology of Perception, of the body cated dialectic in Being and Nothingness
as expression and speech. That analysis is, insofar as the theoretical diremption between
in effect, the high point of Merleau-Pontys Being and Nothingness with which it begins
exploration of the body as lived where he disallows any sense of the precedence of a
finds that speech, despite all the complexities movement away as it pertains to facticity.
of language as spoken, comes about by means Finally, with regard to philosophies of intui-
of a gesture, which is to say, on the basis of tion, Merleau-Ponty first addresses Husserls
the living of the body. If we take into account appeal to intuition, and in particular, the
the fact that the subject matter of history has so-called Wesenschau, or intuition of an
long and for the most part been specified as essence. Merleau-Ponty observes that the
res gestae, in distinction from the Cartesian question of Being remains an issue behind
domains of res cogitans and res extensa, we any attempt to determine an essence, as it
find, despite what may seem to be the case does where questions of fact are concerned,
at first sight, that we are not that far from and along these lines, he finds that there is
Heideggers crucial concern with historiciz- a certain interchangeability between the two
ing in his work up through and including questions. Merleau-Ponty also observes that
Being and Time, and which he would eventu- Husserl never reached a presumed intuition
ally understand in its pertinence to the char- of an essence that he did not find it neces-
acter of aletheia. sary to reexamine. Where all this leads,
In one of the Working Notes for The Visible Merleau-Ponty concludes, is in the direction
and the Invisible, Merleau-Ponty observes of Heideggers eventual understanding of
that while his analyses in Phenomenology the verbal sense of the German word das
of Perception may be taken as psychologi- Wesen, essence. Merleau-Ponty writes:
cal in character, his findings there must be
understood in terms of their ontological There is no emplacement of space and
import. In The Visible and the Invisible, time that would not be a variant of the
which was to have been the next major text, others, as they are of it; there is no indi-
vidual that would not be representative
Merleau-Ponty takes up those findings in a
of a species or of a family of beings,
more primordial manner. What he does first
would not have, would not be a certain
is to analyze three primary modes of philoso- style, a certain manner of managing the
phizing: philosophy that proceeds in terms of domain, of radiating about a wholly vir-
reflection, philosophy that proceeds in terms tual centerin short, a certain manner
of dialectic, and philosophy that proceeds in of being, in the active sense, a certain
terms of intuition. With regard to philoso- Wesen, in the sense that, says Heidegger,
phies of reflection, the initial step that takes this word has when it is used as a verb.6

381
HEIDEGGER AND MERLEAU-PONTY

In a footnote to this passage, Merleau-Ponty to the visible, in order for the visible there
cites Heidegger: The high school building, to become my own landscape, realizing
for us who return to it, thirty years later, as (as it is said) the miraculous promotion of
for those who occupy it today, is not so much Being to consciousness, or (as we pre-
fer to say) the segregation of the within
an object which it would be useful or possi-
and the without; so also.. . .11
ble to describe by its characteristics, as it is a
certain odor, a certain affective texture which
holds sway over a certain vicinity of space.7 In the chapter Interrogation and Intuition
After this, Merleau-Ponty turns, more we find the following: . . . the world and I
briefly, to Bergsons appeal to intuition. are within one another, and there is no ante-
While affirming Bergsons sense of the type riority of the percipere to the percipi, there
of language required of the philosopher,8 is simultaneity or even retardation.12 It is
Merleau-Ponty finds, nevertheless, that on the basis of this simultaneity, or this
what Bergson lacks is the double reference, retardation (which accounts for a sense
the identity of the retiring into oneself with that the percipere is anterior), or this defer-
the leaving of oneself, of the lived through ral (to adopt a term of Derridian prov-
with this distance.9 This cart, this diver- enance), that we might understand better
gence, this reversal, this differentiation why Merleau-Ponty observes in one of the
that Merleau-Ponty finds at the heart of Working Notes that it is by understanding
intuition decisively rules out the adequa- perception that we will be able to respond to
tion of the Cogito (although Merleau-Ponty the questions that pertain to history.13
allows for a possibility that Descartes must Another term whereby Merleau-Ponty
have been aware of what precedes a theoreti- refers to the cart, the divergence, the differ-
cal diremption of the empirical and reflec- entiation, the reversal, is openness, or sim-
tions context) and it returns us directly to ply, the open. It is here where exteriority
Heideggers crucial concern with historiciz- and interiority reverse into one another, here
ing as this shows up early on in the course of where the world worlds, that Heideggers
his de-struction of intuition, and then again, thought seeks a dwelling. His discussion of
near the close of Being and Time. The impor- the time-space of the Moment (der Zeitraum
tance of this finding for Merleau-Ponty can des Augenblicks) in the mid-1930s unfinished
be gauged in terms of the following two pas- text Beitrge zur Philosophie: Vom Ereignis
sages. The first is from a Working Note: The (first published in 1989) (GA 65, CP2),
true philosophy = apprehend what makes where the themes of his later thought come
the leaving of oneself be a retiring into one- into view, points in this direction. Prompted
self, and vice versa. Grasp this chiasm, this by Hlderlin, Heidegger would address the
reversal. That is the mind.10 In other words, open in later texts in terms of a gathering
it marks what is distinctive to who we are. of the Fourfold or the Quadrate (Geviert) of
The other passage is found in the chapter earth, heavens, mortals, and divinity, which
Interrogation and Intuition: separates while bringing together. Where
Heidegger takes up this thought of the near-
As my body, which is one of the visibles, ing of the Fourfold at the close of his lec-
sees itself also and thereby makes itself ture The Turning, (die Kehre) from 1949,
the natural light opening its own interior we find what may well be the one point in

382
HEIDEGGER AND MERLEAU-PONTY

Heideggers writings where what he says takes 2


Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Le Visible et linvisible
the form of prayer: May world in its world- ed. Claude Lefort (Paris: Gallimard, 1964); The
Visible and the Invisible: Followed by Working
ing be the nearest of all nearing that nears,
Notes, trans. Alphonso Lingus (Evanston, IL:
as it brings the truth of Being near to mans Northwestern University Press, 1968).
essence, and so gives man to belong to the dis- 3
For a reading of the pertinent Notes de cours
closing bringing-to-pass that is a bringing into lectures, see my Merleau-Pontys 1959
its own (QCT, 49). By way of a philosophi- Heidegger Lectures: The Task of Thinking and
the Possibility of Philosophy Today, in ed.
cal gesture of interrogation prompted by the
David Pettigrew and Franois Raffoul, French
enigma that perception gives us access to the Interpretations of Heidegger: An Exceptional
things even while it removes us to a margin Reception (Albany, NY: SUNY Press, 2008).
of the world, a gesture of eliciting a response 4
Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Phnomnologie
from that mute or reticent interlocutor that de la perception (Paris: Gallimard, 1945);
Phenomenology of Perception, trans. Colin
is Being, Merleau-Ponty, in the last chapter
Smith (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul,
he wrote for The Visible and the Invisible, 1962); 2nd edn, 2002.
begins to take his bearings in the Open, and 5
This parallels Merleau-Pontys finding in his
he observes here how having entered it, one previous book, La structure du comporte-
does not see how there could be any ques- ment (Paris: Gallimard, 1942); 2nd edn,
2006; The Structure of Behavior, trans. Alden
tion of leaving it.14 This is a mark of the
Fisher (Boston: Beacon Press, 1963), where
primordial or the originary character of what he observes that the linear model of the arc of
Merleau-Ponty calls this strange domain.15 stimulus-response breaks down once one real-
This primordiality is a first indication of das izes that there can be no stimulus until the
Ereignis, the event of world, as addressed by response takes place.
6
Merleau-Ponty, The Visible and the Invisible,
Heidegger in his later work, an event that is
11415.
not epochal and that cannot be recaptured 7
Martin Heidegger, Introduction to
by the Greek metaphysics of presence. Both Metaphysics, trans. Ralph Manheim
Merleau-Ponty and Heidegger caught sight of (GardenCity, NY: Anchor Books, 1961), 278
this in the strange precedence of the move- cited in Merleau-Ponty, The Visible and the
Invisible, 115.
ment away, the forgetting, or the withdrawal 8
See Merleau-Ponty, The Visible and the
that characterizes our being-in-the-world. Invisible, 125.
9
Ibid., 124.
10
Ibid., 199.
NOTES AND REFERENCES
11
Ibid., 118.
12
Ibid., 123.
13
Ibid., 196.
1
Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Notes de cours: 14
Ibid., 152.
19591961 (Paris: Gallimard, 1996). 15
Ibid.

383
48
HEIDEGGER AND ADORNO
Iain Macdonald

A random sampling of Adornos many refer- quite varied in tone and substance. In general,
ences to Heidegger will likely leave the reader three layers of criticism may be discerned in
with a strong impression of his view. Yet it his writings. His position becomes clearer as
would be wrong to infer from the severity and we peel back these layers.
unrelenting nature of his objections that his The first layer provides the rhetori-
opposition to Heidegger is thoughtless or mali- cal shell of the critique. Here, we find the
cious. On the contrary, although it is harsh and remarks that openly mock or pour scorn on
persistent, it is philosophical at its core. Heideggers language and approach. Adorno
The critique of Heidegger spans the refers, for example, to Heideggers agrarian-
entirety of Adornos career, beginning in 1931 ism1 and his homely murmuring, calling
with his inaugural address, The Actuality attention to a resemblance of some of his
of Philosophy, and returning in numerous writings to trusty folk art.2 Adorno also
texts, right up until his death in 1969. The compares Heideggers attempts to think
core theses of the critique are laid out in detail being without beings (GA 14, 29/TB, 24)
in Jargon of Authenticity (1964) and in part to the behavior of the obsessive compulsive,
one of Negative Dialectics (1966). The lec- who must constantly wash his hands to keep
ture course entitled Ontologie und Dialektik from getting them dirty (OD, 1023).3 We
[Ontology and Dialectics], from 19601, is should also include under this heading the
also of direct relevance. Other texts contain particular derision that Adorno reserves for
material of interest as well, such as the 1932 Heideggerians who mimic their masters way
lecture on The Idea of Natural-History and of speaking and thereby lapse into perfor-
the lecture course entitled Philosophische mative contradiction. This is the jargon of
Terminologie [Philosophical Terminology], authenticity at its most pernicious and the
from 19623. There are scattered remarks in critique is correspondingly unforgiving: the
many other works. stereotypes of the jargon seem to guarantee
that one is not doing what, in fact, one is
doing, namely, bleating with the herd; they
Layers of Critique seem to guarantee that one has achieved it
all oneself as an unmistakably free person.
Part of the difficulty of getting at the heart The formal gesture of autonomy replaces the
of Adornos critique of Heidegger is that it is content of autonomy (GS 6, 425/JA, 18). In

385
HEIDEGGER AND ADORNO

other words, the question of whether or not Adornos reading of Heidegger: the legitimate
one is free and authentic cannot be decided need to which Heideggers thought responds,
by the use of catchwords. This, however, is and the kind of thinking that should arise
merely the first layer of criticism. from the disappointment of that need.
The second layer concerns fascism It may seem strange at first that abstraction
and Nazism. Adorno was well aware of should be one of Adornos central criticisms.
Heideggers involvement with the Nazi After all, in Being and Time, Heidegger argues
party and cites Karl Lwith in this connec- explicitly that Dasein must be analyzed in its
tion.4 Moreover, he suggests that Heideggers concreteness, that is, in its everydayness and
philosophy promotes emotional invest- according to its facticity and Jemeinigkeit
ment in something like the National its concrete mineness. It was this approach
Socialist Volk-community (GS 6, 463/JA, that more or less briefly impressed Adornos
76). Likewise, Adorno refers to Heidegger future colleagues, Herbert Marcuse and,
as belonging to a group of Blubo friends astonishingly, Max Horkheimer.6 As Adorno
(i.e. Blut und Boden or blood and soil puts it in Jargon of Authenticity: around
comrades) and Heideggerian jargon is said to 1925 there was a perceptible need for a phi-
be the philosophical continuation of blood losophy that responded to the concretion
and soil rhetoric (GS 6, 449, 480/JA, 55, of experience, thought, and comportment
100). Elsewhere, he refers to Heidegger in the midst of a total situation that served
as an alter Kmpfer, or member of the old an abstraction: exchange (GS 6, 475/JA,
guard, a phrase that implies a commitment 92). This ontological need, as he calls it,
to National Socialism prior to 1933 (OD, was quite real and valid: the new ontologys
74). Perhaps most damningly, Adorno claims enthusiastic reception would be unintelligi-
that Heideggers philosophy is fascist to its ble if it did not meet an emphatic need, if it
innermost cells (GS 19, 638). Some com- were not a sign of something missed (GS 6,
mentators take such references to be deter- 69/ND, 61). Heidegger seemed to meet that
mining, subsuming Adornos critique of need by offering, for example, a critique of
Heidegger under his critique of fascism.5 But inauthentic and impersonal social relations,
this would be to stop short of the real sub- as well as a philosophical approach, appar-
stance of Adornos view, not least because ently interested in historicality, that might
such remarks are relatively marginal in the serve to ground social philosophy. However,
context of the overall critique. for Adorno, Heideggers treatment of rel-
evant things relapsed into abstraction (GS
6, 71/ND, 63).
This relapse is perhaps most evident in
The Critique of Abstraction Heideggers approach to history and the
philosophical tradition, as outlined, for
The third and final layer of Adornos critique example, in his so-called deconstructive
of Heidegger is composed of more substantial readings of Western metaphysics. In the
philosophical challenges to the thinking of 1920s, Heidegger at first called for a recur-
being. Among these, the critique of abstrac- sion (Rckgang) to the tradition that would
tion is perhaps the most important because it appropriate the relation to being concealed
is tied to two other essential components of within it (GA 24, 31/BP, 23). In later years,

386
HEIDEGGER AND ADORNO

this recursion undergoes a transformation that Marxs call to transform the world tac-
into the step back (der Schritt zurck), itly depends upon the possibility of an ade-
by which the engagement with the tradi- quate interpretation not of existing actuality,
tion aims not at something that has already but of what a world is in generalthe hid-
been thought but rather at something that den possibility of world, as opposed to social
has not been thought, from which thought relations among things in the world.7
receives its essential space (GA 11, 57/ID, If Heideggers thought was appealing in
48). As Heidegger puts it, the step back goes the 1920s because it seemed concrete and
from what is unthought [vom Ungedachten], developed a critique of inauthenticity that
from the difference [between being and was rooted in Daseins everydayness, then
beings], into what remains to be thought [in increasingly it shed the appearance of this
das zu-Denkende] (GA 11, 59/ID, 50). concretion and everydayness for a history of
The step back is therefore not merely a being that openly rejected as insufficiently
critical-interpretive gesture. At root, it is thoughtful the social and practical problems
a step away from any thinking that prima- of alienation and the historical relations
rily treats of beings or of being in terms of of productionwhence the relapse into
beings. But it is also a step toward a new way abstraction. For Heidegger the only history
of thinking, one that addresses being itself that philosophy can legitimately concern
as event (Ereignis). Of course, thought must itself with is one that does not consist in the
prepare for the step back in view of happenings and deeds of the world, nor in
beings as they are now, that is, as technologi- the cultural achievements of human beings
cally determined and reduced to mere func- (GA 13, 612/DT, 79), all of which take
tionality (GA 11, 60/ID, 51). Nevertheless, place only as a mere mode of , of
the step back is most essentially a step out rendering beings manifest (GA 9, 340/PA,
of technology and technological description 259). Strictly speaking, thinking must pen-
and interpretation of the age, into the essence etrate beyond history, into historicality and
of modern technology, which remains to be its temporal conditions, that is, into the very
thought (GA 11, 61/ID, 52). Hence, for possibility of metaphysical questioningand
Heidegger, the step back cannot be directly ultimately into , that is, the play of
critical of social and scientific etiolations of concealment and unconcealment itself.
experience, which are at best mere symp- Thus, in Adornos view, Heidegger is more
toms and incitements. It is the openness of concerned with primordial possibility than
being in its relation to the human being that with the real possibility of emancipation,
must be graspednot the sociohistorical which is suppressed by existing conditions.
arrangements of beings that occur within Moreover, it seems clear that for Heidegger
that openness. the possibility of an other beginning for
Consequently, the task of thinking being thinking remains indefinitely blocked by
cannot surrender to the dialectical media- metaphysical prejudices that we cannot seem
tion of the movement of absolute spirit and to escape: The age of the systems has past.
of the historical process of production (GA The age that would elaborate the essential
14, 70/TB, 56), that is, Hegel, Marx, and the form of beings from out of the truth of beyng
sociohistorical interests motivating their phi- [Seyn] has not yet come (GA 65, 5/CP2, 6).
losophies. Indeed, Heidegger will even say Consequently, the retreat into primordiality

387
HEIDEGGER AND ADORNO

entails a projection of the corrective to met- socially determined (e.g. Marx names surplus
aphysical prejudice onto a distant future, value as the hidden origin of exploitation
effectively detached from the present. For and the objective impetus to emancipation).
Heidegger, we can only strive to awaken a By contrast, Heidegger blurs the distinction
readiness in man for a possibility whose con- between the more for which language gropes
tour remains obscure, whose coming remains and the being-in-itself of this more (GS 6,
uncertain, all the while living in equal uncer- 421/JA, 12). In other words, Heidegger treats
tainty about whether world civilization will this more not as a contextually determined
soon be abruptly destroyed or whether it will social problemwhereby an emancipatory
be stabilized for a long time [in a monoto- potential is suppressed by existing mate-
nous sequence of changing fashions] (GA rial and historical relationsbut rather as
14, 75/TB, 60). inherent to being itself beyond any particu-
To this sort of talk, Adorno responds with lar historical organization of things (e.g. the
a charge of willful indifference to existing refusal, withdrawal, etc. proper to being).
suffering: A new beginning [Neubeginn] at Thus for Adorno, emancipatory potential
an alleged zero point is the mask of intense requires the rigorous determination of exist-
forgettingsympathy with barbarism is ing conditions and, ultimately, a refinement
not extrinsic to it (GS 6, 79/ND, 71). The of the entwinement of subject and object in
question is this: is the uncertain promise of concrete society, whereas Heidegger seeks
a transition to a new age not tantamount to hold on to the pointing-beyond-itself,
to allowing the existing world to follow and to leave behind, as rubble, that beyond
its wicked course untrammeled, perhaps to which it points [i.e. beings] (GS 6, 109/ND,
catastrophe? The more we look to the pri- 102). Essentially, what Heidegger forgets is
mordial origin or to the uncertain future, the the fact that all thinking is bound to beings
more we turn a blind eye to contemporary (GS 6, 110n/ND, 103n). To the extent that
barbarism. But what is this intense forgetting the concreteness of the more is forgotten
of which Adorno speaks? This question can in the thinking of being, the world is left to
be answered in two parts. its viceswhile awaiting, perhaps forever,
First, Adorno acknowledgeseven appre- a reorganization of beings from out of the
ciates, to some extentthat being (Sein) truth of beyng.
refers to an insufficiency of beings, that is, Second, the accusation of an intense for-
that the current organization of beings is getting of beings is reinforced by Adorno
false, and that another way of thinking is not in the claim that Heidegger ontologizes the
only logically possible, but indicated by the ontic and thereby reifies states of affairs that
existing order, however faintly or negatively. cannot be reified. For example, he castigates
Indeed, Adorno will even say that the being Heidegger for normalizing anxiety (Angst):
of beings reminds us of an essential fact: categories such as anxietyof which, at
that any being whatever is more than it is the very least, we cannot stipulate that they
(GS 6, 109/ND, 102), and that it is the proper must be everlastingare transfigured into
task of language to name this nonidentical constituents of being (GS 6, 125/ND, 119).
more or hidden potentiality in things. But Similarly, thrownness (Geworfenheit) and the
for Adorno this potentiality is precisely in structures of Dasein more generally drown
things, which means: in the way things are out intimations of objective negativity [i.e. of

388
HEIDEGGER AND ADORNO

an emancipatory more] through the message of relevant things beyond the academicism
of an implicit and essential order of things and formalism of traditional metaphysics,
[Ordnung an sich], up to the most abstract while quite legitimate, is disappointed by
order, that of the structures of being (GS 6, Heideggers thought, which demands of us
96/ND, 89). The problem, put succinctly, is that we look away from the specific prob-
that the categories of the jargon [i.e. prima- lems that assail us, toward the general possi-
rily the existentiales of Being and Time] are bility of the openness of being. The charge of
happily put on display, as though they were abstraction thereby rests on four interrelated
not abstracted from generated and transi- points: history is eclipsed by historicality and
tory situations, but rather belonged to the temporality; the talk of hidden origins and
essence of the human being as inalienable of overcoming metaphysics disregards the
possibility. The human being is the ideology pressing problems of today; the more of
of dehumanization (GS 6, 452/JA, 59). That the being of beings is hypostatized; and the
is, what is socially constructed and ought structures of Dasein unduly fix and normal-
to be surmountable is instead presented as ize aspects of existence.
fundamental and ineluctable (e.g. anxiety, By contrast, for Adorno, the ontological
curiosity, idle talk, and even death, insofar need is to be met by determining and naming
as one is defined by such terms). As such, the more that is implied by the systematic,
suffering, evil, and death are to be accepted, socially constructed features of wrong life. It
not to be changed. The public is being made is in this sense that dialectics is the ontology
to rehearse a balancing act: they are being of the wrong state of things (GS 6, 22/ND,
prepared to see their nothingness as being; to 11): the only true ontology would be one
revere avoidable or at least corrigible distress that describes not what is, but rather what
as what is most human in the image of the ought not to be and the real possibility of its
human; to respect authority on the basis of overcoming.
innate human insufficiency (GS 6, 4567/
JA, 67). Here again, the criticism is that
Heidegger has gone to great lengths to forget
beings and the suffering of the human being Heideggers Response
in particular. He renders fixed that which is
fluid, and natural that which is socialand Heidegger never responded directly to
thereby robs us of the possibility of chang- Adornos critiques. However, in a 1969
ing our sorry lot by projecting this possibility interview with Richard Wisser (just a few
onto an uncertain and unclear other begin- weeks after Adornos death), he answers the
ning beyond metaphysical prejudices, from charge that his thought was unconcerned
which, for the foreseeable future, we can with concrete society and all its various
only prepare to break free. responsibilities and worries, troubles and
Thus the main line of the critique of hopes (MHIG, 69). He must certainly have
Heidegger amounts to this: the jargon had Adorno in mind. His response, which is
wants to be immediately concrete without very brief, is that such critiques are simple
sliding into mere facticity and is thereby misunderstandings: the openness of being
forced into secret abstraction (GS 6, 475/ needs human beings and, inversely, . . . the
JA, 923). The ontological need to speak human being is human only insofar as he

389
HEIDEGGER AND ADORNO

stands in the openness of being (ibid.). The and substantially modified his approach
social aspect of Wissers question is passed after Being and Time. However, he does
over in silence. But in off-the-record remarks note the shifts from Dasein to being (Sein),
to Wisser, Heidegger was more directand and from being to beyng (Seyn) and to the
severe. To the question whether philosophy typographical crossing out of the word being
has a social mission, he replied, somewhat (OD, 712).
curtly: No! I see none!8 Further prompting Second, Adorno fails to follow up on
by Wisser was met with great reserve. In the specific points of intersection between
same informal discussion, he also wondered his thought and Heideggers, even to dis-
aloud about the kind of man who would pel the illusion of compatibility; rather, he
seek to bring him down as he thought flatly denies all compatibility (GS 19, 638).
Adorno had (FI, 283).9 Nevertheless, certain points of intersection
Heideggers correspondence with Ernst do suggest themselves: for example, their spe-
Jnger shows that Adornos name and cial appreciation of the poet Paul Celan and
views were known to him at least as early their interest in defending the priority of pos-
as 1966 and quite possibly long before.10 As sibility over actuality (against a longstanding
to whether he had read Adorno or whether metaphysical tradition). More generally, it
the critique had merely been reported to him, is a pity that Adorno did not pursue reflec-
there is one crystal clear indication, again tions such as the following, from a 1949 let-
recorded by Wisser in 1969: I have read ter to Horkheimer: Ive been thinking a lot
nothing by him. Hermann Mrchen once about Heidegger and will send you . . . a few
tried to talk me into reading him. I never did more notes. In the meantime, his Holzwege
(2834). Nevertheless, Heidegger questions [Off the Beaten Track] has appeared (he is
Adornos credentials and suggests to Wisser in favor of occasional paths [Holzwege] in a
that he was merely a sociologist, not a phi- way thats not very different from our own),
losopher (284). but Ive not quite got around to it, am too
deep into Kant and Aristotle.11

Limitations of Adornos NOTES AND REFERENCES


Critique
1
For example, see Theodor W. Adorno,
Although Adornos critique of Heidegger Philosophische Terminologie, 2 vols (Frankfurt
am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 1973), 1, 15464.
takes on many aspects of his thought, at least 2
Theodor W. Adorno, Gesammelte Schriften,
two important limitations should be men- ed. Rolf Tiedemann, 20 vols (Frankfurt am
tioned here. Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 1997), 6, 44, hereafter
First, Adornos critique nearly always cited as GS/Theodor W. Adorno, The Jargon
focuses on Being and Time or the stakes of of Authenticity, trans. Knut Tarnowski and
Frederic Will (London/Evanston: Routledge
fundamental ontology (he had a first edi-
and Kegan Paul/Northwestern University Press,
tion of Being and Time that he annotated 1973), 53, hereafter cited as JA. Please note
quite heavily in places). He does not pay that translations from the German have been
careful attention to the fact that Heidegger tacitly emended where necessary throughout
dropped the term fundamental ontology this article.

390
HEIDEGGER AND ADORNO

3
I sometimes quote writings of Heideggers that Wiggershaus, The Frankfurt School, trans.
Adorno may not or could not have known Michael Robertson (Cambridge: Polity Press,
when these contain succinct formulations of 1994), 1024 and 45, respectively.
the themes that are the objects of his criti- 7
Richard Wisser (ed.), Martin Heidegger im
cisms. In any case, any reconstruction of the Gesprch (Freiburg und Mnchen: Verlag Karl
main line of the critique requires reference Alber,1970), 689, herafter cited as MHIG.
to passages and contexts other than those 8
Richard Wisser, Das Fernseh-Interview, in
Adorno cites directly. ed. Gnther Neske, Erinnerung an Martin
4
Adorno, GS 6, 135136n/Theodor W. Adorno, Heidegger (Pfullingen: Verlag Gnther Neske,
Negative Dialectics, trans. E. B. Ashton 1977), 260, hereafter cited as FI.
(London: Routledge, 1973), 130n, hereafter 9
Worthy of note is that Heidegger openly laid
cited as ND. claim to Siegfried Landshut, editor of the first
5
See Fredric Jameson, Late Marxism: Adorno, German edition of Marxs early writings, as
or the Persistence of the Dialectic (London: a pupil of his (FI, 276). The evidence suggests
Verso, 1990), 9. that Heidegger knew these writings very well.
6
Horkheimer met Heidegger while on a study 10
Ernst Jnger and Martin Heidegger, Briefe
trip to Freiburg in 1921, when Heidegger was 19491975, ed. Gnter Figal and Simone
still Edmund Husserls assistant. Marcuse Maier (Stuttgart/Frankfurt am Main:
went to Freiburg in 1928 in order to study Klett-Cotta/Vittorio Klostermann, 2008), 58.
with Heidegger, but abandoned this plan in 11
Theodor W. Adorno and Max Horkheimer,
1932 due to a lack of support from Heidegger Briefwechsel, 4 vols (Frankfurt am Main:
and the darkening political context. See Rolf Suhrkamp Verlag, 20036), 3, 351.

391
49
HEIDEGGER AND LEVINAS
Jill Stauffer

These lines, and those that follow, owe philosophy cannot, when confronted by
much to Heidegger. Deformed and Heideggers work, fail to recognize how
ill-understood? Perhaps. At least this the originality and force of his achieve-
deformation will not have been a way of ments . . . are combined with an atten-
denying the debt. Nor this debt a reason tive, painstaking, and close working-out
to forget.. . .1Emmanuel Levinas of the argument.2

Perhaps most readers of Levinas are not Levinas omitted that passage when he
looking to him for a balanced reading of revised the essay for publication in 1949.3 In
Heideggerand that is fortunate, since they Existence and Existents, published in 1947
will not find it in Levinas works. For that but written largely while he was in held in a
reason, perhaps most readers of Heidegger, forced labor camp during the Second World
when they venture into Levinas pages, are War, Levinas wrote:
confused by the version of Heidegger they
find there. Levinas is not known for his faith- If at the beginning our reflections are in
ful readings of other philosophers works: large measure inspired by the philosophy
Sartre, Hegel, Husserl, and Bergson are also of Martin Heidegger, where we find the
concept of ontology and of the relation-
interpreted creatively. Of course, creative
ship which man sustains with Being, they
reading of the philosophical tradition is
are also governed by a profound need
a skill (or liberty) one could as easily learn to leave the climate of that philosophy,
from Heidegger as Levinas. But that should and by the conviction that we cannot
not absolve us of the need to puzzle out some leave it for a philosophy that would be
of the lines of influence and resistance in the pre-Heideggerian.4
relation of Levinas thought to Heideggers.
In the 1920s, Levinas studied with both Levinas reconsidered Heideggers thought
Heidegger and Husserl. In 1932 Levinas in the wake of the calamity of the Second
published the essay Martin Heidegger and World War. That explains this essays epi-
Ontology, wherein he wrote: graphical quote from Levinas: he owes
much to Heideggers thinking; his reading
For once, Fame has picked one who of Heidegger is deformed but does not
deserves it.. . . Anyone who has studied deny its debt to that work; but the debt and

393
HEIDEGGER AND LEVINAS

the work do not override the responsibility ways with regard to its relation to others, the
Levinas felt to distance himself from that passing of time, and formation of its self. One
philosophyto leave its climate. could say the same of Heideggers subject:
Heidegger modified Husserls phenom- Daseins thrownness stands for its position in
enological method to suit his own choice of a world that predates it, etc. Later concepts
focuswhich he described as Western meta- such as Gelassenheit, Lichtung, and Ereignis
physics neglect of the question of Being, also describe a subjects passivity with regard
emphasizing the ontological difference to world (though Levinas seems to limit
between Being and beings. For Heidegger his thinking about Heidegger to Being and
that means, put roughly, that the Being of Time). But passivity ends up placing differ-
beings is not a beingthat there is some- ent constraints on the existence of an exist-
thing beyond the existence of an existent. ent in the two thinkers thoughtsand that
However, in Levinas reading, Heidegger changes how we define the kind of being a
sets out to recover Being from a tradition human being is. In a larger work it would
that has obscured it, and in doing so plants be possible to trace more explicitly the lim-
Western philosophy more squarely than ever its of the overlap between the two thinkers.
in a tradition that subordinatesand always But if it is true that Levinas left the climate
has subordinatedthe relation of human of Heideggers thought, the more interesting
beings to other human beings to the rela- question may be what that means. It comes
tion between Dasein and Being.5 Heidegger down to a difference of emphasis rather than
worries about beings forgetfulness of Being. a reversal or outright refusal of Heideggers
Levinas worries about human beings forget- phenomenology.
fulness of other human beings. Heidegger considers himself to have
One might on first glance suspect reversed the philosophical traditions prior-
that Levinas aims to reverse the order of ity of epistemology over ontology by situat-
Heideggers thought. But the relation is not ing knowledge within a being always already
so straightforward. When Levinas says he in a world and defined by moods or modes
wants to escape the climate of Heideggers of comportment toward that world, while
philosophy or get beyond being, he means Levinas takes Heidegger to be involved in
he seeks to get outside of ontology, for the reducing everything that is other to what
sake of ethicsbut not in an ontic direc- is the same, which amounts to a violence
tion. Heidegger describes to us a temporal- against the othera forgetting of the other.
ized subject for whom much is always yet to In arguing that, Levinas seems to forget
be decided; he offers an analysis of authentic that Heidegger defines Dasein as Mitsein,
and inauthentic ways of dwelling for that being-with:
creature, where all hangs on the relation of
beings to Being. Levinas, like Heidegger, gives Da-sein is essentially being-with. The
phenomenological statement that
us a temporalized subject for whom dwelling
Da-sein is essentially being-with has an
alongside others is a necessity rather than
existential-ontological meaning. It does
a choice, but emphasizes human passivity not intend to ascertain ontically that
in relation to other human beings over the I am factically not objectively present
capacity for resolute choosing of ones own alone, rather that others of my kind also
fate. Levinas subject is passive in important are.6

394
HEIDEGGER AND LEVINAS

It is a structure of Daseins being that it exists temporalization itself. The primordial and
alongside othersand not just in an empiri- authentic future is the towards-oneself
cal (or ontic) sense. Mitsein is a condition (to oneself!), existing as the possibility of
prior to any freedom. Dasein just is the kind nullity, the possibility which is not to be
outstripped.11
of being that lives in a world with others.
Here is where Levinas wants more infor-
mation. Is Dasein responsible for those oth- It is not only that someday one will cease
ers? Are there limits on what Dasein may do to exist, and one knows this because one
with other Daseins? (Is Dasein ever plural?) observes that death happens. The reminder
But those are not Heideggers questions,7 and of lifes finitude turns Dasein back on itself,
that bothered Levinas, especially in the wake calling on it to take up its own life authenti-
of Heideggers membership in the Nazi party. cally rather than falling into the they, living
This is the nodal point of the difference in inauthentically, never taking the trouble to
emphasis. Heidegger chooses Being. Levinas be its own basis. The possibility of impossi-
chooses human beings. bilitynullity, deathindividualizes Dasein
The divergence comes to the fore when if Dasein heeds it as a call to authenticity.
we consider the role death plays in their Levinas might want to argue that the
respective philosophies.8 For Heidegger emphasis on authenticity assumes a form
being-toward-death is how Dasein grasps the of freedom or volition blind to the sub-
potentiality of its own ability to be: jects passivity. But, as we have seen, that
would ignore the passivity inherent in the
Care is Being-towards-death. We have structure of care that Heidegger identifies
defined anticipatory resoluteness with Being-toward-death, where the phe-
as authentic Being towards the pos- nomenon of care in its totality is essentially
sibility which we have characterized
something that cannot be torn asunder; so
as Daseins utter impossibility. In such
any attempts to trace it back to special acts
Being-towards-its-end, Dasein exists in a
way which is authentically whole as that or drives like willing or wishing or urge or
entity which it can be when thrown into addiction, or to construct it out of these,
death.9 will be unsuccessful.12 Instead, the key fac-
tor differentiating Heidegger from Levinas
It is easy enough to exist lightly, to float on on death is its singularity, that death is
the surface of things, and deny ones own in every case mine.13 If Dasein as care is
finitude. But if one is to grasp ones own always ahead of itself (projecting itself for-
potential, Heidegger suggests, one needs ward even in inauthenticity) because there is
a sense of that finitude, and its relation to always something still outstanding that has
temporality.10 Just as Mitsein does not mean not yet become actual for Dasein, then one
that one empirically stands next to others can never experience ones life as a whole.
in the world, being-toward-death does not Only death makes of life a whole, and death
mean that one simply needs to know that is not an event that Dasein can experience.
one will die: Dasein does experience being left behind by
those who die and thus comes to understand
[Daseins] finitude does not amount pri- something of death. But that is an empirical
marily to a stopping, but is characteristic of concern, sometimes a psychological reality,

395
HEIDEGGER AND LEVINAS

but not the existential meaning of death. others individualizes the self as responsible,
Death is in every case mine because no such that the necessity of being in the world
one can take the Others dying away from with others carries a different meaning.
him.14 One can die for another, but that is Not only the death but the life of oth-
a concrete sacrifice that does not take away ers individualizes me. For Levinas, a self is
the Others death, even if it prolongs her life. formed responsively, in a ceaseless oscillation
Levinas gives that truth a different sense. between the selfs innate capacity to enjoy its
According to Levinas, death is, for Heidegger, own lifeits conatusand its prevolitional
the most proper, the most untransfer- responsiveness to other human beings, who
able, and the most inalienable possibility of have always already invaded the self, plac-
Dasein15it is the meaning of jemeinigkeit. ing its conatus in question.18 Individuation
But Levinas argues: comes not from anticipatory resoluteness but
from being called by an other as irreplace-
Sympathy and compassion, to suffer for able. It is I who am called and not someone
the other or to die a thousand deaths else.19 I cannot shrug off the responsibility by
for the other, have as their condition of generalizing the call in accord with an idea of
possibility a more radical substitution
formal equality.
for an other. This would be a responsi-
Of course, the Levinasian idea of guilt in
bility for another in bearing his misfor-
tune or his end as if one were guilty of some ways parallels Heideggers reminder
causing it.16 that the ontological guilt Dasein bears
when conscience calls on it to be responsi-
That one can die for another is more than an ble for its Beingis not to be understood as
empirical truth. The as if of guilt is impor- information about the self, is not ontic.20
tant here: responsibility is not tied to acts Rather, it is existential, a call directed only to
and intentions but rather is constitutive of Dasein, a summons to take up its own poten-
human subjectivity as a form of responsive- tial. As Heidegger puts it:
ness against which no one is free to choose.
That might echo Heideggers thrownness, The summons to Being-guilty signifies
but the overlap is not perfect. To bear the a calling-forth to that potentiality-for-Be-
misfortune of an other as if one were guilty ing which in each case I as Dasein am
of it is to remain indifferent to a discourse of already. Dasein need not first load a
authenticity: guilt upon itself through its failures
or omissions; it must only be guilty
authenticallyguilty in the way in
In this sense, the sacrifice for another
which it is.21
would create an other relation with the
death of the other: a responsibility that
would perhaps answer the question of If you hear the call to conscience in the right
why we can die. . . . The death of the way, you will be able both to embrace the
other is not only a moment of the mine- potentiality of your own being and to free
ness of my ontological function.17
yourself to hear the call. You will have cho-
sen your authentic self.
Rather than the selfs own death individual- Both descriptions assign to human beings
izing the self as properly its own, the death of forms of passivity and guilt that are not

396
HEIDEGGER AND LEVINAS

empirical.22 The why? attached to death respond, to protect lives beyond our own.
is, for Levinas, about what we owe to others Those are not his questions.
whereas for Heidegger it is about the selfs For Levinas, evil is tied to suffering. Those
resolute attention to its own authenticity. It is who suffer are overwhelmed by an evil that
possible to make an ethical judgment about rends their humanity in a way that transcends
which approach is better, but it is not the active/passive distinction. They are over-
absolutely necessary that we do so. We gain come otherwise than by non-freedom, in
important, and importantly different, insight a manner more cruel than the negation that
from each. characterizes being rendered unable to act
A related difference of emphasis emerges freely.29 As such, what matters for Levinas
in the two thinkers discussions of the prob- about evil is not chiefly whether or not
lem of evil. For Heidegger evil is an onto- one acts freely or authentically, as it is not
logical category, interesting only insomuch through passivity that evil is described, but
as it helps clarify the selfs existential sta- through evil that suffering is understood.30
tus. Similarly the Good does not have any We may be free to do good or evil, but that
moral meaning.23 Heideggers conception does not capture all of what matters about
of evil comes largely from Schelling. What evil. According to Levinas, suffering is use-
Heidegger likes about Schellings description less. It is for nothing. The pain of cancer, of
of evil is that it moves beyond questions of torture, abuse or oppression, of chronic dis-
morality into the ground of freedom, which easethese are evils and none of them do
includes freedom for good or evil.24 That anything useful, nor are they easily modified
insight allows Heidegger to compare, struc- by the bodys consciousness, its anxiety, or
turally, the relation of Being and beings to its psychological states. Even the most reso-
that of evil and good. Both are about choices lute decision is hard-pressed to evade severe
one might make against a backdrop of what sufferings invasion of consciousness. Nor
is unchosen.25 would we want to find pain useful, as that
For Heidegger, evil at times describes might amount to a theodicy, where we use
something that Dasein fears (We do not redemptive narratives to explain pain by
first ascertain a future evil and then fear finding it justified or beneficial. It is never
it but rather we feel fear because we have right to justify another human beings pain.
already discovered something fearsome26); The only useful thing pain may do is open
it can also describe death (as something we up the interhuman channel of communica-
do not desire, and probably fear).27 When tion, whereby anothers groan or a call for
Dasein fears, it fears for itself (That which aid brings out in me a duty to help.31
fear fears about is that very entity which is For Heidegger evil is part of a story about
afraidDasein. Only an entity for which in freedom and authenticity. For Levinas it is
its Being this very Being is an issue, can be tied to the exigency of human responsibility
afraid.28). For Heidegger, evil is something for other human beings. This passage from
that fear fears, and fear opens up anxiety Levinas illuminates much of the substance of
about nothingness, forestalling Daseins the difference:
embrace of its own authenticity. There is
no mention of evil inflicted on others, nor There is a radical difference between suf-
concern about whether evil calls on us to fering in the other . . . and suffering in me,

397
HEIDEGGER AND LEVINAS

my own experience of suffering whose Reversal would preserve the underlying


constitutional or congenital uselessness logic. Levinas goal was to range beyond it.
can take on meaning, the only one of He takes up various of the themes Heidegger
which suffering is capable, in becoming explored and uses them, even deforms them,
a suffering for the suffering (inexorable
in order to advance a rival theory of the sub-
though it may be) of someone else. This
ject, one concerned with the self but centered
attention [to the suffering of others] and
this action [to alleviate it] are so imperi- on the other despite itself, in such a way
ously and directly incumbent on human that authenticity and deathto be or not to
beings that it makes awaiting them from beare not the main questions animating
an all-powerful God impossible without the kind of being a human being is. When
lowering ourselves.32 Levinas chooses to leave the climate of
Heideggers philosophy, but not for a phi-
Here Levinas seems to suggest that, in the losophy that would be pre-Heideggerian,
face of twentieth-century experiments in cru- he is both giving credit where it is due and
elty, one cannot say that only a god can save asserting the need he felt to make a decisively
us now and retain ones humanity.33 Evil is different philosophical move.
implicated in suffering, and suffering is use-
lessunless it is my own suffering on behalf
NOTES AND REFERENCES
of someone else. Heidegger would likely
say that such sacrifice does not take away 1
Emmanuel Levinas, Otherwise than Being or
anothers deathand that is surely true. For Beyond Essence, (OB) tr. by Alphonso Lingis
Levinas, it misses the point. He asks: (Pittsburg, PA: Duquesne University Press,
1998), 189, n. 28.
But is it so certain, after all, that the 2
Emmanuel Levinas, Martin Heidegger and
essence of death, which is fulfilled in Ontology, Diacritics, 26.1 (Spring 1996),
anxiety, must be thought, according to 11, as quoted in Michael Smith, Toward the
the description of Sein und Zeit, as noth- Outside: Concepts and Themes in Emmanuel
ingness? Is the secret about death not Levinas (Pittsburg, PA: Duquesne University
Press, 2005), 127.
phenomenologically inherent in death 3
Michael Smith points this out in Toward the
and the anxiety of dying? Is it not a Outside, 127.
modality, or the anticipated sharpness, 4
Emmanuel Levinas, Existence and Existents,
of sufferingand not the solution of the trans. Alphonso Lingis (Pittsburg, PA:
dilemma: to be or not to be?34 Duquesne University Press, 2001), 4.
5
Emmanuel Levinas, Totality and Infinity: An
Death is about more than ones own exist- Essay on Exteriority, trans. Alphonso Lingis
ence; it is a modality of suffering, part of the (Pittsburg, PA: Duquesne University Press,
1969), 46.
interhuman relationship. It calls on me to be 6
BT, 120.
responsible. 7
But see, for instance, Lawrence Vogel,
It might be tempting to say that Levinas, The Fragile We: Ethical Implications of
discontented with Heideggers philosophy Heideggers Being and Time (Evanston, Il:
or even with his political choices, aimed to Northwestern University Press, 1994). One
could also read the work of Arendt, Sartre,
reverse Heideggers phenomenology, choosing Beauvoir, Lacan, Taylor, Derrida, Vattimo,
beings over Being. But the relation between Agamben, and others as framing ethical (and
the two lines of thought is more complex. other) questions in a Heideggerian vein.

398
HEIDEGGER AND LEVINAS

8
See Tina Chanter, Time, Death and the 23
ET, 77.
Feminine: Levinas with Heidegger (Stanford, 24
See STEHF, 98f.
CA: Stanford University Press, 2001) for 25
See STEHF. See also Drew Dalton, Otherwise
an in-depth consideration of Levinas and than Nothing: Heidegger, Levinas and the
Heidegger on death, time, and responsibility. Phenomenology of Evil, Philosophy and
9
BT, 32930. Theology, 21.12, 10528, 2009.
10
See Peter Gratton, Heidegger and Levinas 26
BT, 141.
on the Question of Temporality, Journal of 27
Ibid., 248.
Philosophical Research, 30 (2005), 15768 28
Ibid., 141.
for a deeper analysis of how the two thinkers 29
Emmanuel Levinas, Useless Suffering, (US)
conceptualize temporality. in trans. Michael Smith and Barbara Harshaw,
11
BT, 330. Entre Nous: Thinking of the Other (New
12
BT, 1934. York: Columbia University Press, 1998), 92.
13
BT, 240. 30
Ibid.
14
Ibid. 31
See Levinas, US.
15
Emmanuel Levinas, God, Death and Time, 32
Levinas, US, 92.
(GDT) trans. Bettina Bergo (Stanford, CA: 33
See Only a God Can Save Us Now: Der
Stanford University Press, 2000), 3940. Spiegels Interview with Martin Heidegger on
16
GDT, 39. September 23, 1966, trans. Maria P. Alter and
17
Ibid. John D. Caputo, Philosophy Today 20 (1976),
18
See Levinas OB, Substitution, 99129. pp. 26785. A related point: Levinas argues
19
See OB, 144ff. that technology is not only will to power, but
20
BT, 287. rather is also perhaps only the price that must
21
Ibid. sometimes be paid by the high-mindedness of
22
Wayne Froman argues, along these lines, that the a civilization called upon to feed human beings
two thinkers are at cross-purposes in Levinas and lighten their sufferings (Levinas, US, 94).
and Heidegger: A Strange Conversation in 34
Emmanuel Levinas, Transcendence and Evil,
ed. Daniel Dahlstrom, Interpreting Heidegger: in trans. Bettina Bergo, Of God Who Comes to
Critical Essays, (New York: Cambridge Mind (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press,
University Press, 2011), 25672. 1998), 129, translation modified.

399
50
HEIDEGGER AND DERRIDA
Franois Raffoul

Derridas relation to Heidegger can be other thinker, neither in this century nor in
described as marked by a deep ambivalence. general, with whom I have had, with whom I
While he has always recognized his debt still have a relationship of admiration that is
toward Heidegger, although he went so far as contradictory and as uneasy (ibid.). The
as to state that, What I have attempted to reader is often faced with this ambivalence
do would not have been possible without in Derridas writings, which offer, on the one
the opening of Heideggers questions,1 hand, uncannily precise and insightful, and
Derrida has also nevertheless consistently indeed faithful readings of Heideggers text
expressed reservations or differences with with, on the other hand, less than generous
that thought.2 In a late interview from 1999 interpretations. This situation accounts in
with Dominique Janicaud, he described his any case for how Derrida perceived his own
ambivalence toward Heidegger in this way: position, which he described thusly: I found
In any case, it is [a relation] of admiration, myself, I still find myself, with others, in the
respect, recognition, and at the same time a situation of a non-devotee who, at the same
relation of profound allergy and of irony.3 time, cannot stand the anti-Heideggerians.
Derrida further elaborated on this profound We are caught in the cross-fire. I am as aller-
allergy toward Heideggeran allergy that gic to the Heidegger devotees as I am to the
is not without recalling Levinas famed run-of-the-mill anti-Heideggerians.5
remark on the profound need to leave the With respect to the debt that Derrida rec-
climate of Heideggers philosophy4by ognized toward Heidegger, we could mention
comparing Heidegger to a sort of severe here what Derrida said in a 1987 interview,
father, a kind of suspicious superego that Heidegger, the Philosophers Hell, regard-
constantly has Derrida under surveillance: ing the importance of Heideggers thought:
For me, he is something like a watch- For more than a half century, no rigorous
man [veilleur], a thinking that always keeps philosopher has been able to avoid a debate
watch over mean overseer [surveillant] with [explication avec] Heidegger, a think-
who is always watching over me, a think- ing that is also multiple and that, for a
ing through which I constantly feel that I am long time to come, will remain provocative,
under surveillance (HF, 103). Nonetheless, enigmatic, still to be read.6 Even through
Derrida presents his relation to Heidegger as the criticisms, reservations, and explica-
unique, if not incomparable: I know of no tions, Derrida still refers to Heidegger as an

401
HEIDEGGER AND DERRIDA

indispensable resource for future thought. not (HF, 101). For Derrida, deconstruction
Indeed, from the moment one is having it is above all the deconstruction of presence,
out with [sexplique avec] Heidegger in a whereas for Heidegger Destruktion seeks to
critical or deconstructive fashion, must one unveil the original meaning of being as pres-
not continue to recognize a certain necessity ence (Anwesenheit).8
of his thinking, its character, which is inaugu- Some biographical information that may
ral in so many respects, and especially what not be widely known about Derridas first
remains to come for us in its deciphering? exposure to Heideggers thought, and how he
(Points, 1834). In any case, he explains, an forged his own problematic of deconstruc-
endless Auseinandersetzung with Heidegger tion, might be useful here. In his interview
was engaged and set forth in all my texts with Janicaud, Derrida returned to his intel-
(HF II, 101). lectual formation, stressing how prominently
What is at stake in this Auseinander Heidegger already figures. He mentions hav-
setzung? Derrida considered that for all of ing first heard of the name Heidegger as
its advances, Heideggers thought remained early as hypokhgne, in the year 19489;
in several key moments caught in the very he recalls having read, in the University of
metaphysics it attempted to overcome: Algiers library, texts by Sartre containing
despite this debt to Heideggers thought, numerous references to Heidegger, as well as
or rather because of it, I attempt to locate the texts from Heidegger that were collected
in Heideggers text . . . the signs of belong- and translated by Henry Corbin, namely,
ing to metaphysics, or to what he calls fragments from Sein und Zeit, and Was
onto-theology (Positions, 8). In particular, ist Metaphysik? As early as 19489, then,
Heideggers determination of difference as Derrida recounts, I was also very aware
ontological difference seems to me still held of him, because of classes and because of
back in a strange way within metaphysics. the role that I saw him play in the French
In contrast, Derrida seeks to open a thought intellectual landscapewith Sartre notably,
of differance that is no longer determined, and more distantly Merleau-Ponty (HF,
in the language of the West, as the differ- 89). Significantly, Derrida describes how
ence between Being and beings (Positions, he felt so much closer to Heidegger than to
910). Derrida thus marks a distance with Husserl (he insists on the fact that he stud-
Heidegger around this motif of presence, ied Husserl only after he had been work-
going so far as to state that, I sometimes ing on Heidegger) and how he resonated
have the feeling that the Heideggerian prob- with the pathos of Heideggers questions.
lematic is the most profound and power- The question of anxiety, of the experi-
ful defense of what I attempt to put into ence of nothingness before negation, corre-
question under the rubric of the thought of sponded well to my personal pathos, much
presence (55). This question of presence is more so than the cold Husserlian discipline,
without a doubt the veritable knot between to which I came only later (HF, 90). Then,
Derrida and Heidegger,7 as Derrida recog- in the early 1950s, after having entered the
nized in his interview with Janicaud. With cole Normale Suprieure, Derrida attended
respect to the question of presence, indeed, the lectures of Jean Beaufret, the recipient of
I found a knot there, which at bottom I The Letter on Humanism. One must also
always thought was there, whether rightly or mention here the several courses that Derrida

402
HEIDEGGER AND DERRIDA

devoted to Heidegger in the early 1960s to articulate the positive intent of the term
when he was teaching as an assistant at the Destruktion by appealing to the word
Sorbonne: for instance in 19601 in a course Ab-bau (Derrida explained also that he
on the present; in 19612 on the notion of chose the word dconstruction in order
world in Heidegger; in 19634 on error and to avoid the negative connotation of the
errancy in Heidegger; in 19645 on the ques- term destruction to render Destruktion).
tion of being and history in Heidegger.9 In 1968, the French translator of that essay,
The debate around the senses to give to Grard Granel, a close friend of Derrida since
deconstruction constitutes the very core of their years together at the cole Normale
Derridas relation to Heidegger: my endless Suprieure, rendered Abbau (described
debate with Heidegger concerns the mean- as a dismantling, a sort of taking things
ing to be given to deconstruction, the usage apart, senses that would become central in
of this word. What concept corresponds to Derridas understanding of deconstruction as
this word? This is an endless explication the opening of a differance, a gap or a spac-
(HF, 105). Let us stress from the outset that ing) as D-construction.13 The term appeared
the very word dconstruction originated in in Derridas writings at the same time, and
a translation of Heideggers own text, as it is highly probable that Derrida discov-
Derrida recognized in the 1983 Letter to ered or rediscovered the term in his friends
a Japanese Friend. In that essay, Derrida translation.14 That term thus first entered
begins by recalling how even in the French the intellectual world in France as a trans-
language, the word dconstruction mobi- lation of Heidegger. Curiously, although he
lizes the question of translation within ones recognized that debt in the passage just cited
language: the term dconstruction is not a from Letter to a Japanese Friend (1983),
master-word or a transcendental signified in his late interview with Janicaud, Derrida
but always already caught in a context no longer recalled exactly when he heard the
and in a metonymic chain of signifiers, term:
enjoying no particular privilege there. The
word deconstruction, like all other words, It makes me sad, but I am not able to
acquires its value only from its inscription reconstitute this evolution and this trans-
in a chain of possible substitutions, in what formation for myself, in other words,
the moment I arrived at the schema of
is too blithely called a context.10 Derrida
deconstruction (the word Destruktion,
then narrates how that term, dconstruction,
for example, I dont rememberbut
was chosen as a rendering of Heideggers is my memory reliable?having paid
Destruktion: When I chose this word, or attention to it thematically during those
when it imposed itself upon meI think it years). I think it is later. I wouldnt swear
was in Of GrammatologyI little thought it to it. (HF, 95)
would be credited with such a central role in
the discourse that interested me at the time. The term dconstruction was is any case
Among other things I wished to translate taken up by Derrida in his own thought of
and adopt to my own ends the Heideggerian diffrance, and if deconstruction has become
word Destruktion or Abbau.11 Heidegger identified with the name and the thought of
had attempted (among other places, in the Jacques Derrida, its provenance was decid-
1955 essay, On the Question of Being12) edly Heideggerian.

403
HEIDEGGER AND DERRIDA

As we saw above, for Heidegger manifesting the impossibility of the proper,


Destruktion seeks to unveil the original leading us to an aporia or impossible.
meaning of being as Anwesenheit. This is Thus, although Derrida certainly shares
where Derrida seeks to introduce a break with Heidegger the conviction that decon-
with Heidegger. For what does deconstruc- struction has a positive or affirmative
tion give access to? Not to some original sense,18 it nonetheless remains an experience
givenness of being, as Derrida believes of the impossible. To the extent that decon-
Heidegger may have hoped, not to some struction reveals the faults of the system,
transcendental signified escaping the play the places where the system does not work,
of diffrance, but rather to an unsubstantial this affirmative sense of deconstruction as
gap or spacing, to the a of differance, that openness must always be associated with,
is, to a nothing with no substantiality of its as Derrida put it, the privilege I constantly
own. It is not the access to another domain, grant to aporetic thought.19 Deconstruction
but simply the differential gap of the con as such, Derrida tells us, needs to be under-
struction. In this sense, Derrida clarifies, the stood as aporetic thinking, and he still evoked
undoing, decomposing, and desedimenting in a late text all the aporias or the impossi-
of structures . . . was not a negative opera- bles with which deconstruction is concerned
tion. Rather than destroying, it was also (toutes les apories ou les im-possibles qui
necessary to understand how an ensemble occupent la deconstruction).20 In a later
was constituted and to reconstruct it to this text on the secret, Derrida writes that the
end.15 Any construction supposes a gap system is impossible.21 With deconstruc-
within it, and that gap draws the contours tion, he continues, it has been a question of
of the construction, while marking its lim- showing that the system does not work (TS,
its, its exposure to the void, and already its 4, my emphasis). Deconstruction thus will
self-deconstruction. And we know that for not lead to the reappropriation of the proper,
Derrida deconstruction must be understood but to the impropriety of the proper, to the
first and foremost as a self-deconstruction. im-possible.
In the Letter to a Japanese Friend, he thus Derrida takes issue with Heideggers
explained: Deconstruction takes place, it is alleged privileging of the proper. Indeed,
an event that does not await the deliberation, Derrida seeks to break with the very distinc-
consciousness, or organization of a subject, tion between the proper (eigentlich) and the
or even of modernity. It deconstructs itself improper (uneigentlich), a distinction that
[a se dconstruit].16 It deconstructs itself for Derrida is metaphysical.22 In Ousia
because, Deconstruction is something which and Gramm, Derrida claimed that for
happens and which happens inside; there is a Heidegger, the Primordial, the authentic
deconstruction at work within Platos work, are determined as the proper (eigentlich),
for instance.17 It deconstructs itself because that is, as the near (proper, proprius), the
the construction harbors a fault or an apo- present in the proximity of self-presence
ria within it. Deconstruction for Derrida will (Margins, 64, n. 39). This can be seen for
not be the return to and appropriation of Derrida at the very beginning of Being and
some original element of being. This is why, Time, namely in the decision to ask the
for Derrida, is not a question of reappropri- question of the meaning of Being on the
ating the proper of human existence, but of basis of an existential analytic of Dasein

404
HEIDEGGER AND DERRIDA

(ibid.). That privilege given to the propriety existence, is, Being . . . are all names of the
and proximity of self-presence can propa- impossible and of self-incompatibility.25
gate its movement to include all the concepts Now, we should note that with respect
implying the value of the proper, Derrida to this charge of a privilege of the proper in
adding in a parenthesis a list (not included Heidegger, Derrida has wavered somewhat. In
in the English translation) that includes Philosophy in a Time of Terror, for instance,
all derivations of the motif of the proper Derrida states that the Heideggerian thought
in Heideggers thought: (Eigen, eigens, of being as event, as Ereignis, involves a cer-
ereignen, Ereignis, eigentmlich, Eignen, tain expropriation. Going against the grain of
etc.) (ibid.). The dominance of the motif of his previous interpretations, Derrida claims
the proper in Heideggers thinking can then that the thought of Ereignis in Heidegger
be found in the relation established between would be turned not only toward the appro
being and the human Dasein, Derrida asso- priation of the proper [eigen] but toward a
ciating the proper (le propre) with the certain expropriation that Heidegger him-
near (le proche): The near is the proper; self names [Enteignis].26 He thus explicitly
the proper is the nearest (prope, proprius). links the Heideggerian thought of the event
Man is the proper of Being, which right to the inappropriable and the impossible:
near to him whispers in his ear; Being is the The undergoing [lpreuve] of the event,
proper of man, such is the truth that speaks, that which in the undergoing or in the ordeal
such is the proposition that gives the there at once opens itself up to and resists experi-
of the truth of Being and the truth of man ence, is, it seems to me, a certain inappro-
(Margins, 133). Gesturing to an outside priability of what comes or happens [ce qui
that would come to threaten this circularity, arrive].27 There is thus inappropriable in the
Derrida suggests that it is that very security very happening of the event, and Derrida rec-
of the near that is trembling today, and it ognizes the presence of an inappropriable in
is that privilege of the proper that he seeks to Heideggers thought of being as event.
destabilize and undo. This appears in fact in Heideggers under-
For Derrida seeks to claim the impossi- standing of the phenomenological method.
bility of appropriation and the primacy of For the very concept of phenomenology,
expropriation. In On TouchingJean-Luc insofar as it is defined as a letting something
Nancy, Derrida cites a passage from The be seen (sehen lassen), a legein, a bringing
Gravity of Thought where Nancy wrote to light, necessarily implies the withdrawal
that existence is the appropriation of of the phenomenon. The original phenom-
the inappropriable.23 Derrida reads that enon, precisely as that which is to be made
expression by insisting on the expropria- phenomenologically visible, does not show
tion of the proper, which he calls exappro- itself:
priation. Ex-appropriation designates that
interminable appropriation of an irreduc- What is it that phenomenology is to
ible nonproper that limits every and any let be seen? What is it that is to be
appropriation process at the same time.24 called a phenomenon in a distinctive
From this thinking of the inappropriable in sense? What is it that by its very essence
existence, Derrida introduces the motif of becomes the necessary theme when we
the impossible: Another way of saying that indicate something explicitly? Manifestly,

405
HEIDEGGER AND DERRIDA

it is something that does not show itself to an inappropriable. Indeed, the event of
initially and for the most part, something appropriation that Ereignis is said to desig-
that is concealed [verborgen] in contrast nate includes eminently the expropriation
to what initially and for the most part of Enteignis. As Heidegger explained in On
does show itself. (SZ, 35/BT, 33)
Time and Being:

Phenomenology, in its very essence, is thus Appropriating makes manifest what is


a phenomenology of what does not appear, proper to it, that Appropriation with-
a phenomenology of the inapparent, as draws what is most fully its own from
boundless unconcealment. Thought in
Heidegger described it in the 1973 Zhringen
terms of Appropriating, this means: in
seminar (FS, 80). Destruktion in Heideggers
that sense it expropriates itself of itself.
sense thus manifests a struggle with the con- Expropriation [Enteignis] belongs to
cealment of phenomena, engaging what he Appropriation [Ereignis] as such. By
called in his course on Platos Sophist a con- this expropriation, Appropriation does
stant struggle against the tendency to cover not abandon itselfrather it preserves
over residing at the heart of Dasein (GA 19, what is its own. (GA 14, 278/TB, 223,
52/PS, 367). This betrays that Heideggers translation slightly modified)
Destruktion has to do with a certain expe-
rience of or negotiation with the secret, the And it may well be around this motif of the
inappropriable, and indeed perhaps is an inappropriable at the heart of appropriation,
experience of the impossible, as Derrida that is, ex-appropriation, that Derrida may
attempted to think it in his own aporetic be closest to Heidegger, closer than it would
thinking. seem, that is, than Derrida would have liked.
In fact, as Derrida had to admit, there is
in Heideggers thinking of being the pres-
ence of an irreducible expropriation. Being NOTES AND REFERENCES
is the withdrawal, and it calls us from this
withdrawing. One notes the presence of such 1
Jacques Derrida, Positions, trans. Alan Bass
inappropriable in all stages of Heideggers (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981), 9.
2
The reverse is not the case: in his interview with
thought: in the ruinance of factical life
Dominique Janicaud (In Heidegger in France, II.
in the early writings and lecture courses; in Interviews [Paris: Albin Michel, 2001, hereafter
the Uneigentlichkeit of existence and the cited as HF II]41), Walter Biemel indicates that
Schuldigsein of conscience in Being and Heidegger did in fact follow Derridas work,
Time; in the thrownness and facticity felt and, still according to Biemel, that he looked
upon it favorably, as we can also gather from
in moods, in the weight of a responsibility
two letters that Heidegger wrote to Lucien Braun
assigned to an inappropriable finitude; in (the first from September 29, 1967 and the other
an untruth co-primordial with truth; in the from May 16, 1973), regarding the possibility
concealment that not only accompanies but of a meeting with Derrida, which Derrida had
is indeed harbored in unconcealment; in the suggested. See Lucien Brauns report in Penser
Strasbourg (Paris: Galile, 2004), 216.
withdrawal in the sendings of being; and 3
In HF, II, 103.
finally in the presence of Enteignis within 4
Emmanuel Levinas, Existence and Existents,
Ereignis. Each time and throughout, one trans. Alphonso Lingis (Pittsburg, PA:
finds in Heidegger this motif of an exposure Duquesne University Press, 2001), 4.

406
HEIDEGGER AND DERRIDA

5
HS. Interestingly, this late statement echoes, 8
In Four Seminars, in the 1969 Thor seminar
almost word for word, a passage one finds in a (FS, 42), we thus read: The previous session
footnote from Ousia and Gramm, in which concluded with a recollection upon how the
Derrida already denounced the complicity question of being was first raised in Being
which gathers together, in the same refusal to and Time.. . . [Heidegger] begins by naming
read, in the same denegation of the question, of the authentic name of the method followed:
the text, and of the question of the text, in the destructionthis must be understood in
same repetitions [redite], or in the same blind the strong sense as de-struere, dis-mantling
silence, the camp of Heideggerian devotion and [ab-bauen], and not as devastation . . . But
the camp of anti-Heideggerianism. Jacques what is dismantled? Answer: that which cov-
Derrida. Margins of Philosophy, trans. Alan ers over the meaning of being, the structures
Bass (Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press, amassed upon one another that make the
1982), 62, n. 37, translation modified. meaning of being unrecognizable . . . Further,
6
Jacques Derrida, Points . . . Interviews, destruction strives to free the original meaning
19741995, trans. Peggy Kamuf and Others of being (Anwesenheit).
(Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1992), 9
Regarding these courses, see the list established
1823, translation modified. in the Derrida Seminars Translation Projects
7
Although by no means the only difference website: http://derridaseminars.org/seminars.
or disagreement between them. In that same html
1987 interview, Derrida gives a long list of his 10
Letter to a Japanese Friend, in Derrida
disagreements with Heidegger. They include: and Differance, eds David Wood and Robert
the questions of the proper, the near [proche], Bernasconi (Evanston, IL: Northwestern
and the fatherland (Heimat) [patrie], the point University Press, 1988), 4.
of departure of Being and Time, technics 11
Letter to a Japanese Friend, in Derrida and
and science, animality, or sexual difference, Differance, 1. My emphasis.
the voice, the hand, language, the epoch, 12
Martin Heidegger, On the Question of Being,
and especially, this is the subtitle of my book in ed. William McNeill, Pathmarks (New York:
[Of Spirit. Heidegger and the Question], the Cambridge University Press, 1998), 315.
question of the question, which is almost 13
Martin Heidegger, Contribution la ques
constantly privileged by Heidegger as the tion de ltre (1955), in Questions I (Paris:
piety of thinking (Points, 182). As readers Gallimard, 1968), 240.
of Derrida reading Heidegger, we could add 14
As Francoise Dastur observes, if in Being
to that list: Derridas critique of Heideggers and Time it is a question of Destruktion, the
alleged anthropomorphism, from The Ends term abbau, deconstruction, which is also
of Man to The Animal that Therefore I Am present in Husserl, appears on page 315 in
and beyond, the hierarchies of Being and Martin Heidegger, On the Question of Being
Time (such as the subordination of regional . . . where Derrida probably found it. The
ontologies to fundamental ontology or the Reception and Nonreception of Heidegger in
distinction between existential analytic and France, in eds David Pettigrew and Franois
biology and anthropology, between existence Raffoul, French Interpretations of Heidegger
and life), the motif of the as such in the exis- (Albany, NY: SUNY Press, 2008), 288, n.26,
tential analytic, the prioritization of death as my emphasis.
some transcendental ground of existence, the 15
Letter to a Japanese Friend, in Derrida and
critique of a certain solipsism of the existential Differance, 3.
analysis excluding the death of the other from 16
Letter to a Japanese Friend, in Derrida and
its domain, the notions of truth of being Differance, 4, translation slightly modified.
and ontological difference, the privileg- 17
Deconstruction in a Nutshell: A Conversation
ing of the gathering (Versammlung), which with Jacques Derrida (NY: Fordham University
suppresses otherness, the problematic of truth Press, 1997), 9.
and truth-keeping, the unity of the history of 18
Derrida clarified this affirmative sense in
being, etc. the 2004 Humanit interview, in terms of

407
HEIDEGGER AND DERRIDA

an openness toward what comes: A slogan, quest for an archia in general, no matter with
nonetheless, of deconstruction: being open to what precautions one surrounds the concept,
what comes, to the to-come, to the other. still the essential operation of metaphysics?

19
Jacques Derrida, Rogues. Two Essays on asks Derrida (Margins, 63).
Reason, trans. Pascale-Anne Brault and 23
Jacques Derrida, On TouchingJean-Luc
Michael Naas (Stanford, CA: Stanford Nancy, trans. Christine Irizzary (Stanford,
University Press, 2005), 174, n. 3. CA: Stanford University Press, 2000), 299. See

20
Jacques Derrida and Elisabeth Roudinesco, For also Jean-Luc Nancy, The Gravity of Thought,
What Tomorrow . . ., trans. Jeff Fort (Stanford, trans. Franois Raffoul and Gregory Recco
CA: Stanford University Press, 2004), 48, (Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press,
translation modified 1997).

21
Jacques Derrida and Maurizio Ferraris, A 24
Derrida, On TouchingJean-Luc Nancy, 1812.
Taste for the Secret, ed. G. Donis and D. Webb 25
Ibid.
(Malden, MA: Polity Press, 2001), 4, my 26
Giovanna Borradori, Philosophy in a Time
emphasis. Hereafter cited as TS, followed by of Terror: Dialogues with Jrgen Habermas
page number. and Jacques Derrida (Chicago: University of

22
Now, is not the opposition of the primordial Chicago Press, 2003), 90.
to the derivative still metaphysical? Is not the 27
Ibid, translation modified.

408
51
HEIDEGGER AND FOUCAULT
Leonard Lawlor

In his final interview, Foucault famously recommencement, to that strange, sta-


says, For me, Heidegger has always been the tionary disquietude which forces upon
essential philosopher. My whole philosophi- it the duty of repeating repetition. Thus
cal development was determined by my read- from Hegel to Marx and Spengler we
find the developing theme of a thought
ing of Heidegger.1 There is no question that
which, through the movement in which
this quotation means that Heidegger had a
it accomplishes itself . . ., curves over
tremendous influence on Foucaults think- upon itself . . . [and] achieves its circle.
ing. One is hard-pressed, however, to under- In opposition to this return . . ., we find
stand the nature and scope of the influence the experience of Hlderlin, Nietzsche,
since Foucault never wrote a text devoted to and Heidegger, in which the return is
Heidegger. Lacking a book or even an arti- given only in the extreme retreat of the
cle on Heidegger, one ends up searching for origin.4
comments by Foucault that seem to allude to
Heidegger.2 For example and most obviously, This single occurrence of the name Heidegger
it seems impossible not to think of Heidegger indicates that Foucaults relation to Heidegger
when one sees the title of Foucaults last pub- centers on the task or even the duty of rep-
lished book, The Care of the Self. Yet, the etition or retrieval (rptition in French,
situation is really worse. Not only do we not Wiederholung, in German).5 Although
have a book or article written by Foucault Foucault forms an opposition between the
on Heidegger, Heideggers name does not two conceptions of returnHeidegger in the
even appear in the books Foucault published company of Hlderlin and Nietzsche, and
during his lifetimeexcept once.3 The only opposed to Hegel, Marx, and Spengler
occurrence of Heideggers name appears in both, he says, prescribe something like the
chapter nine, Man and his Doublesin a Same (OT, 334). As we know from the title
section called The Retreat and Return of the of the chapter, Man and his Doubles, it
Originin Foucaults 1966 The Order of seems that Foucault thinks that Heideggers
Things. Here is the occurrence: task of a retrieval of the question of being
retrieves only what is the same as mans
This is why modern thought is devoted, being. Therefore, if Foucaults thought goes
from top to bottom, to its great preoc- beyond Heideggersat least beyond the
cupation with return, to its concern with Heidegger that this comment impliesthen

409
HEIDEGGER AND FOUCAULT

Foucaults task of retrieval seems to con- us examine Man and his Doubles in order
cern whether there is a repetition that is not to determine more fully this one occurrence
restricted to the same, whether there is a rep- and thereby understand the trajectory of
etition or retrieval of something other than Foucaults thought in general.
the being of man. As we shall see, Foucaults It is well known that, like all of Foucaults
task lies in the retrieval of the question of the histories (up until the 1984 Use of Pleasure,
being of language. which concerns the ancient Greeks), The
This claim about the retrieval of lan- Order of Things examines a discontinuity
guage defining Foucaults thinking might between the Classical Age (the seventeenth
seem controversial since, after The Order and eigteenth centuries) and the Modern Age
of Things and after The Archeology of (the nineteenth and twentieth centuries). The
Knowledge, Foucaults thinking takes up the discontinuity occurs at the moment of the
problem of power. Yet, we must not forget Enlightenment and the French Revolution.
that at a crucial juncture in The Archeology Prior to the Enlightenment, in the Classical
of Knowledge (he has just referred to The Age, words or language in general had a
Order of Things through the phrase les function of representing things. Thanks to
mots et les choses, the actual French title this function, humans were able to charac-
of The Order of Things), Foucault insists terize and classify, make equivalencies and
that he is interested, not in the sign, but in exchanges, establish identities and differ-
what he calls the more of discourse.6 It is ences among things. The function of lan-
this more that leads Foucault, at the end guage thenin the Classical Age, words are
of his career, on the other side of his power thought to be transparentallowed humans
studies such as Discipline and Punish and to set up a table, as Foucault says, of rep-
The History of Sexuality 1, to consider the resentations, by means of which one was
ancient notion of parrsia (franc-parler, fear- able to understand the world. Importantly,
less speech, outspokenness). The more this grid of representations, made possible
of discourse allows one to speak out and by language in its transparency, was an order
speak freely, and in this way discourse is external to the things themselves (OT, 311).
able to intervene in arrangements of power. Now, at the threshold of the nineteenth cen-
Therefore, it is possible to say that the task tury, according to Foucault, the Classical
of the retrieval (la rptition) of the being order of words and things dissolves. During
of language determines the entire trajectory the time of the French Revolution and after,
of Foucaults work in general. We can make certain thinkers (Cuvier, for example) work-
this claim in another way if we recognize, as ing in the areas of knowledge called natural
Heidegger did, that there can be no thought history, exchange, and grammar demand
without language. Then the repetition of the that life, labor, and language define them-
being of language determines the most gen- selves (312). In other words, they demanded
eral task of Foucaults thinkingeven when that life, labor, and language be understood
it concerns powersince his thinking aims in terms of conditions of possibility inter-
to produce histories of thought. Of course, nal to life, labor, and language themselves.
characterizing Foucaults work as the history Although Foucault will alternate among
of thought reinforces the importance of the these three areas throughout Man and his
one occurrence of Heideggers name.7 So, let Doubles, he privileges language since the

410
HEIDEGGER AND FOUCAULT

unmaking of the Classical order was due to he speaks. Using Kantian terminology, we
language losing its transparency function. can say that man does not have intellectual
When things withdraw into themselves, intuition. Thus, mans being is ambiguously
language acquires its own being. doubled between a finitude that is the same
The end of the Classical order, for as itself since the same body, the same desire,
Foucault, is not merely negative or destruc- the same language are known and conditions
tive. When this withdrawal of things into knowledge, and a finitude that is radically
themselves occurs, life, labour, and language other, since the finite conditions of knowl-
become phenomena. Here we can see the edge indicate a fundamental finitude that
impact of Enlightenment thinking and in seems not to depend on man having a his-
particular Kant. As phenomena, things are tory or a language. The fundamental finitude
given. As given, they take up an external depends only on its own fact (315).
relation not with an orderthe order is Foucaults introduction of man in this
internal to the things, in the noumena behind way in The Order of Things is well-known.
the phenomenabut with the human being, It refers not to a shift in our physical
who has the power of representation and make-up, but in the way we think of our-
self-representation. When this shift occurs selves. Undoubtedly, Heideggers publica-
in the human being, when we start to think tion of Being and Time had a transformative
of ourselves no longer as having a human effect on how we think about our exist-
nature (which is opposed term by term to ence. Thanks to Heidegger (and probably
nature (309)), when we start to think of our- thanks to the popularization of his ideas by
selves as spectators of phenomena, then, for the French Existentialists), we think of our-
Foucault, man is invented. In other words, selves as finite. And, if we want to be precise
man is required when things become phe- about our finitude, we must think of our-
nomena since he is the one to whom the selves as finite in the double way in which
phenomena are given. Moreover, since man Foucault describes it: a positive finitude and
is the one who lives, who labours, and who a fundamental finitude. Thus, due to this
speaks, he seems to have a privileged posi- Heideggerian inheritance, Foucault speaks
tion among other animals who live, do of an obligation to ascend or descend to an
things, and express themselves in sounds, a analytic of finitude (ibid.). The allusion to
privileged position in these areas of knowl- Heideggers Dasein analytic in Being and
edge, called in the Modern Age, biology, Time is obvious. But, the phrase the ana-
economics, and philology. However, lytic of finitude especially resembles cer-
as Foucault says, this imperious designa- tain phrases Heidegger uses in Kant and the
tion is ambiguous (313). On the one hand, Problem of Metaphysics, where Heideggers
the positive content of biology, economics, project consists in a retrieval of human
and philology tells man that he is finite; the finitude.8 For Foucault, as for Heidegger, the
givens or phenomena of mans being analytic of finitude concerns mans mode of
are corporeality, desires, and language. On being. Most importantly, however, Foucault
the other hand, the knowledge of life, labor, states that mans primary characteristic is
and language is itself determined as finite, entirely that of repetition (ibid.). Defining
since man knows through his body, in rela- the primary characteristic of mans being as
tion to his desires, and in the language that repetition means, for Foucault, that mans

411
HEIDEGGER AND FOUCAULT

being is defined as the same; the death it from the historicity of things as it is con-
that gnaws at mans life and the death that is ceived in the Modern Age. In the Modern
fundamental are the same. As Foucault says, Age, the historicity of things seems to resem-
From one end of experience to the other, ble a cone, whose summit is a point of iden-
finitude answers itself; it is the identity and tity; then history seems to evolve from that
difference of the positivities, and of their identity, resulting in dispersion and diversity,
foundation, within the figure of the Same in becoming other (32930). In contrast, the
(ibid.; Foucaults emphasis and upper-casing). origin, for man in Modern thought, is a kind
In the Modern Age, human finitude comes to of otherness since his origin is a past on which
be thought no longer in a negative relation man cannot locate himself: the already
to the infinite (as a fallen existence); it is begun (330). Man always finds himself alive
defined entirely in terms of itself (316). against the background of life that began
Having defined mans primary charac- long ago, his labor finds itself within institu-
teristic as repetition (the repetition of the tions already established, and he speaks from
positive and the fundamental), Foucault then a language he did not invent. Foucault calls
extends the analytic of finitude into three mans relation to this already begun the
other doubles that define man: the tran- originary (ibid.). Foucaults introduction
scendental repeats the empirical, the cogito of this word alludes to Heidegger, since the
repeats the unthought, the return of the French originaire translates Heideggers
origin repeats its retreat (317). The repeti- German Ursprnglichkeit, as it is found,
tion of the same in the transcendental and for example, in Being and Time and in Kant
the empirical alludes to phenomenology and the Problem of Metaphysics.10 As in
since Foucault speaks of the discourse of Heidegger, Foucault describes the originary
lived-experience (vcu), lived-experience as that which is closest to man since he
being a central phenomenological con- lives, labours, and speaks, and yet it is what
cept (321).9 The repetition of the same in is distant since life, labour, and language
the cogito and the unthought alludes more belong to a time that has neither the same
clearly to Heidegger. In fact, the repetition of standards of measurement nor the same
The Cogito and the Unthought seems to foundations as him (ibid.). The originary
allude to Heideggers idea of an originary is what connects man to what is not con-
ethics, since Foucault speaks of an impera- temporaneous with him (331). Because of
tive of thought, an imperative on the basis this non-contemporaneity, it is not possible
of which thought must think mans other, to attribute, according to Foucault, an ori-
thereby making it the same as himself (328). gin to man. Yet, because man seems to have
However, as we have already noted, it is in no origin, to be virtually outside of time, he
this fourth and last repetition, the retreat and also appears to be that being from which all
return of the origin, that Foucault mentions the chronologies of life, labour, and language
Heidegger by name. have derived. Therefore, Foucault concludes
Foucault calls the fourth repetition that that there is a double retreat of the origin: the
defines mans mode of being the relation origin of things always withdraws to a begin-
to the origin (ibid.). He distinguishes this ning earlier than man, while man withdraws
origin from the ideal genesis imagined in from things as that from which all the dura-
Classical thought, but he also distinguishes tions of things can begin.

412
HEIDEGGER AND FOUCAULT

This double retreat, however, makes pos- Doubles or in The Order of Things, nor
sible, according to Foucault, a third retreat anywhere in his corpus.11 A clue seems to
(332). Because man seems to be the source appear, however, when he says in Man and
for all the chronologies, a task arises for his Doubles that [the origin] is promised
thought in the Modern Age (ibid.). Thought to [man] in an imminence that will perhaps
calls into question everything that pertains to be forever snatched from him (3345, see
time. It contests the origin of things in order also 332). The clue seems to be this: it is dif-
to discover the origin without either origin ficult to conceive promising in any other way
or beginning. Foucault calls this origin- than as something to be kept; as something
less origin the rip (the French word is to be kept, a promise must be fulfilled. Then
dchirure, which probably is intended to as something to be fulfilled, it seems that
render Heideggers idea of a Riss) from promising must always be based in a lack.
which, itself having no chronology or history, The same dominates this retrieval or return
time has issued forth (ibid.). Time then would or repetition because the promising, to which
be, as it were, suspended in thoughtin the Foucault seems to be referring, is conceived
sense that making this timeless origin be vis- as a deficiency (342). The withdrawal of the
ible thought would seem to have made time origin produces a deficiency, but the defi-
stand still. And yet, thought itself would not ciency, it seems, produces something like an
be able to escape from time because it is not outline or a figure in relief that the future fills
contemporary with the originless origin of in. In other words, what is to come is deter-
time. In the Modern Age, thought can never mined as what is going to fill in this lack. The
be contemporary with the origin. However, still coming future will be the same as what
as Foucault stresses, the suspension of time was outlined with the withdrawal of the
in thought is able to make the relation of origin into the past. There seems, however,
thought and origin flip over. Previously, the for Foucault, another and stronger step in
origin withdrew from thought into the past; this argument, if we understand it correctly.
now, however, it withdraws from thought Foucault speaks of the insurmountable rela-
going out into the future. In other words, tion of mans being to time (335). Thus it
after finding itself coming too late for the seems that the lack is a lack in mans own
origin, thought now projects the origin out in being (ibid.), which means that the return of
front as what is still to be thought (ibid.). It the originpromised and not yet fulfilledis
is at this moment in Man and his Doubles a fulfilment of mans being. Man is the figure
that Foucault mentions Heideggers name. in relief made by the withdrawal. The return
Although Foucault does not say this, the task of the origin therefore is a return of the same
for thinking that aims at suspending time being as us. The circle of withdrawal and
amounts to Heideggers task of a retrieval of return closes and encloses us.
the meaning of being as time. Is there a way to break out of this circle of
According to Foucault, however, this man, this eschatological return? In Man and
retrieval (Wiederholung), as we saw at the his Doubles, Foucault suggests that we must
beginning, is a retrieval of the same. Why ask this question: Does man truly exist
is the Heideggerian task a retrieval of the (322, my emphasis)? This question, with the
same? Foucault does not really answer this emphasis on the exist, makes us question
question anywhere, not in Man and his beyond mans being. What lies beyond mans

413
HEIDEGGER AND FOUCAULT

being? At least at the time of The Order of conceive language in terms of promising
Things, the answer to the question of what and in this way we confirm our opening the-
lies beyond mans being is the being of lan- sis about the most general task of Foucaults
guage. In The Order of Things, the being of thinkingbecause Foucault argues late in
language seems for be, for Foucault, opposed his career, in The Government of Self and
to the being of man. What is the being of lan- Others that parrsia is not a performative
guage for Foucault? We recall that, accord- utterance. Parrsia is always something
ing to Foucault, language in the Classical Age more than a performative. As examples of
had a function. It transparently represented performative utterances, Foucault speaks of
things, which allowed the things to be ordered I baptize you and I apologize, but he
in a table of representations. In other words, could just as well have spoken of I prom-
through this function, it occupied the middle ise. In contrast to performative utterances
between things and order. This conception of such as I promise, there is, Foucault
language also implies that language stands in says, parrsia at the moment when the
the middle as a transparent medium between statement of [the] of truth constitutes an
a speaker who intends to say something and irruptive event opening up an undefined
a hearer who understands the transported or poorly defined risk for the subject who
meaning. Language in this conception has speaks.13 Involving a nondefined or badly
no other being than transitivity. Language defined, indeed an unforeseeable risk for
as transitivity dissolves at the time of the the speaker, this kind of eventperhaps this
Enlightenment. As in Mallarms poetry event is really what Heidegger has in mind
Mallarm is Foucaults example, along with with the Ereignis?is not promising. With
Nietzschelanguage then takes on a new parrsia, there is no outline of what is com-
density since it no longer occupies the middle. ing. In fact, we do not know what is coming,
Therefore it no longer functions transitively. and thereby the circle of man is unwound.
It no longer has a destination, an end or telos Indeed, it seems for Foucault that only the
or eschaton. Then language no longer folds event of parrsia opens up what he calls
back over itself into a circle. The being of lan- early in his career the play of masks, and
guage in Foucault is radical intransitivity. late in his career the indefinite work of free-
Through radical intransitivity, language is dom.14 Or, we could say, echoing Heidegger,
liberated from its finitude, allowing it to take that parrsia answers the question of what
on an indefinite potentiality (300). calls for thinking.
Of course, the later Heidegger of On the
Way to Language defines the being of lan-
guage no longer in terms of its communi- NOTES AND REFERENCES
cative function. Indeed, he seeks the being
of language within poetry, just as Foucault 1
Michel Foucault, Le retour de la morale,
seems to do in The Order of Things. Yet, in Dits et crits, IV, 19801988, dition
tablie sous la direction de Daniel Defert
in the Language essay in particular,
et Franois Ewald (Paris: NRF Gallimard,
Heidegger conceives language as a promise, 1994), 703; English translation by Thomas
which seems to restrict the potentiality of Levin and Isabelle Lorenz as The Return
language to a circular return, even to a return of Morality, in ed. Lawrence D. Kritzman,
of man.12 We know that Foucault does not Michel Foucault. Politics, Philosophy, Culture:

414
HEIDEGGER AND FOUCAULT

Interview and other Writings, 19771984 Wiederholung is a fundamental feature of


5

(New York: Routledge, 1988), 250, transla- Heideggers thinking at the time of Being and
tion modified. For Foucaults early studies, see Time. See GA 2, 2/BT, 1 and GA 2, 385/BT,
Didier Eribon, Michel Foucault, trans. Betsy 367. It organizes as well Heideggers 1929
Wing (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics. See GA
Press, 1991), 301. David Macey, The Lives 3, 204/KPM, 143.
of Michel Foucault (New York: Vintage, 6
Michel Foucault, Larchologie du savoir (Paris:
1993), 34. The quotation with which I began NRF Gallimard, 1969), 67; English translation
is often cited. See Alan Milchman and Alan by A. M. Sheridan Smith as The Archeology of
Rosenberg, Foucault and Heidegger: Critical Knowledge (New York: Pantheon, 1972), 49.
Encounters (Minneapolis: University of 7
Deleuze claims that Heideggers question
Minnesota Press, 2003). Batrice Hans essay in of what calls for thinking haunts all of
this volume is particularly interesting. Batrice Foucaults thinking. Gilles Deleuze, Foucault
Han, Foucault and Heidegger on Kant and (Paris: Minuit, 1986), 124; English transla-
Finitude, in Foucault and Heidegger, 12762. tion by Sen Hand as Foucault (Minneapolis:
See also Jean Zoungrana, Michel Foucault. Un University of Minnesota Press, 1988), 116.
parcours crois: Lvi-Strauss, Heidegger (Paris: 8
See, in particular, GA 3, 88/KPM, 62: the
LHarmattan, 1998). task of an analytic of transcendence, i.e., of a
2
Heideggers name appears often in Foucaults pure phenomenology of the subjectivity of the
interviews and occasionally in his courses. subject, namely, as a finite subject.
Michel Foucault, Mthodologie pour une 9
The English translation renders vcu as
connaissance du monde: comment se dbar- actual experience. Vcu however is the
rasser du marxisme, in Dits et crits, III, standard French translation for the German
19761979, dition tablie sous la direction de Erlebnis, which is usually rendered into
Daniel Defert et Franois Ewald (Paris: NRF English as lived-experience. Here Foucault
Gallimard, 1994), 6045. Michel Foucault, seems to allude to Husserl and probably the
Leon sur la volont de savoir. Cour au Collge early Merleau-Ponty.
de France. 19701971. Suivi de Le savoir 10
See GA 2, 151/BT, 146 and GA 3, 126/KPM,
ddipe (Paris: Hautes tudes Gallimard 89. Ursprnglichkeit is also rendered into
Seuil, 2011), 206. Finally, see Paul Veyne, The English as primordiality. The originary is a
Final Foucault and his Ethics, in ed. ArnoldI. primary concern of Foucaults Introduction
Davidson, Foucault and his Interlocutors, to Kants Anthropology. And later in 1971, he
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1997), expresses suspicion of the concept of origin.
231n.1. See Michel Foucault, Nietzsche, la gnealo-
3
This claim is not quite correct since Foucault gie, lhistoire, in Dits et crits. Volume I
mentions Heidegger by name in his 1954 intro- 19541975, dition tablie sous la direction
duction to Binswangers Le rve et lexistence. de Daniel Defert et Franois Ewald, avec la
Yet, here, Foucault seems merely to brush any collaboration de Jacques Lagrange(Paris:
concern with Heidegger aside. See Ludwig Quarto Gallimard, 2001), 1008; English trans-
Binswanger, Le rve et lexistence (Paris: lation by Donald F. Brouchard and Sherry
Descle de Brouwer, 1954), 1314; English Simon as Nietzsche, Genealogy, History,
edited by Keith Holler as Dream and Existence in ed. James D. Faubion, Essential Works of
(Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press, Foucault. Volume 2: Aesthetics, Method and
1993), 323. Epistemology (New York: New Press, 1998),
4
Michel Foucault, Les mots et les choses 373.
(Paris: Tel Gallimard, 1966), 345; English 11
In Ariane sest pendue, Foucault says that
translation by A. M. Sheridan Smith as The [To think intensity] is to reject finally the
Order of Things (New York: Vintage, 1970), great figure of the Same, which, from Plato to
334. Hereafter cited with the abbreviation Heidegger, has not stopped locking Western
OT. I have frequently modified the English metaphysics into its circle (my transla-
translation. tion). But here too, Foucault provides no

415
HEIDEGGER AND FOUCAULT

explanation. See Michel Foucault, Ariane 13


Michel Foucault, Le gouvernement de soi
sest pendue, in Dits et crits. Volume I et des autres. Cours au Collge de France.
19541975, dition tablie sous la direction de 19821983 (Paris: Seuil, 2008), 61; English
Daniel Defert et Franois Ewald, avec la col- translation by Graham Burchell as The
laboration de Jacques Lagrange (Paris: Quarto Government of Self and Others. Lectures at
Gallimard, 2001), 798. the Collge de France, 19821983 (London:
12
Heidegger, GA 12, 12/PLT, 190: Language Palgrave MacMillan, 2010), 63.
brings about and produces [er-gibt] man, 14
For masks, see OT, 385, and Sheridan, The
and so thought, man would be one promise Archeology of Knowledge, 131, and Brouchard
[ein Versprechen] of language. Heidegger and Simon, Nietzsche, Genealogy, History,
hyphenates er-gibt here so that it indi- 386. For the indefinite work of freedom, see
cates that language has given man over, as Michel Foucault, What is Enlightenment?
if he were a gift, instead of man producing (Quest-ce que les Lumires?), in Dits et
language. Instead of language being one of crits, IV. 19801988, dition tablie sous la
mans activities, man is one of languages direction de Daniel Defert et Franois Ewald
products or even promises (Versprechen). (Paris: NRF Gallimard, 1994), 574; English
For Heidegger, it seems that humans keep translation by Catherine Porter as What is
the promisecome into their ownby Enlightenment? in The Essential Works of
co-responding to the call that defines lan- Foucault, Volume I: Ethics, Subjectivity and
guage (see GA 12, 170/OWL, 76). Truth (New York: New Press, 1997), 31516.

416
52
HEIDEGGER AND DELEUZE 1

Andrea Janae Sholtz and Leonard Lawlor

It is difficult to determine the exact rela- not be conceived as a middle; there must be
tion Deleuze has with Heideggers work no continuity. For Deleuze, the between
since Deleuze never wrote an extensive text must be conceived through an image that
on Heidegger.2 Nevertheless, on the basis of differs from the neat alignment of the fold:
Deleuzes numerous mentions of and allu- it must be conceived as a struggle or even as
sions to Heidegger,3 we are able to determine chaos that breaks, stretches, or unhinges the
two points of intersection.4 First and most fold, the asymmetry of a zigzag.5 The sec-
importantly, there is the issue of difference ond issue in which Deleuze and Heidegger
or even the difference, that is, the difference intersect is thinking. The second issue flows
between being and beings (between Sein and out of the first since for both Deleuze and
Seiende, in German; between ltre and ltant, Heidegger the problem is once again that of
in French), but also the difference between the between, the between of thinking and
thinking and being, between subject and what is to be thought. Heidegger seems to
object, between words and things, between conceive this relation on the basis of a rep-
things said and things seen, and between state- etition of the original sense of philosophy, as
ments and visibilities. Here the issue is how philia, while Deleuze conceives this relation
to conceive the between of these doubles. transforming philosophy into misosophyas
Both Deleuze and Heidegger recognize one violence. Only the violence of an encounter
fundamental requirement for conceiving the makes thinking be creative. As we can see
between: the between must not be con- already, the problem in both of these issues is
ceived as a separation; there must be no dual- that of the foundation: sameness and original
ism. Therefore, both Deleuze and Heidegger sense function as the foundation, while strug-
make use of the image of the fold. This image gle and violence are the nonfoundational.6
suggests no separation, since folding one sheet Now we can see these two points of intersec-
of paper over itself does not tear the sheet tion most clearly in one of Deleuze most sus-
into two separate pieces. Yet, what Deleuze tained discussions of Heidegger, his Note on
sees in the Heideggerian fold is a sameness Heideggers Philosophy of Difference found
between being and the beings, between all the in chapter one of his 1968 Difference and
doubles. So what distinguishes Deleuze from Repetition (DR, 8991/646).
Heidegger is a second requirement for con- Chapter one of Difference and Repetition
ceiving the between: the between must brings us directly to the issue of difference (and

417
HEIDEGGER AND DELEUZE

the between) since it is called Difference reversal of Platonism (82/59). However,


in itself. Here, Deleuze brings to light the and not so well-known, echoing Heidegger,
various ways in which the Western metaphys- Deleuze also calls for a destruction of
ical tradition has made difference come to be Platonism (91/66). Indeed, it is precisely in
reconciled with the demands of the concept the center of this destruction that we find
in general. The concept in general demands Deleuzes five-point summary of Heideggers
that difference be represented. Converted to Philosophy of Difference (8991/646).
a representation (a mental representation in Here are the five points. Since Platonism
the human subject), difference becomes a dif- defines difference as the negation of the
ference between two determinable things. As foundation, Deleuze starts with the not in
a between two, it comes to be defined as Heidegger.7 More specifically, he starts here
resemblance, and then resemblance is able to because Hegelian dialectic, as we just sug-
be transformed into the identity of an abstract gested and as Deleuze had shown earlier in
or general concept. The concept is the third or the chapter, had tried to explain negation in
middle term through which the two determi- propositions by putting nonbeing right into
nable objects are compared and made equal, being; this nonbeing within being would be
in a word, mediated. As representation, dif- the negative; but the negative would have no
ference is subordinated to identity and media- other function, according to Deleuze, than to
tion, it is subordinated to dialectic in either its be itself negated, and therefore difference, as
ancient or modern form (445/29). Thus dif- in Platonism, would be returned to identity
ference comes to be conceived only for or in (64/45, 78/55, 889/63). So, in the first point,
relation to something that serves as its foun- Deleuze says that, in Heidegger, the not does
dation or ground. Indeed, difference becomes not express the negativeHeidegger is not
nothing but the negation of the foundation, a Hegelrather the not expresses the differ-
negation that, when it is itself negated, returns ence between being and beings. In the second
difference to the foundation from which it point, Deleuze says that the difference between
derived (we shall turn to this idea of return being and beings is not the between in the
in a moment, but we can see already that in ordinary sense.8 Instead, it must be understood
the representational concept of difference, as the fold, the Zwiefalt. For Deleuze, the fold
difference is nothing but a bare repetition of image means that being constitutes the being
the foundation; the dialectic is always circu- in the double movement of unconcealment
lar). Clearly, in this conceptiondifference (or clearing) and concealment. Difference
(or differences) relates negatively back to a understood as the fold is constitutive of being.
foundation, which is the abstract identity of In other words, being, in Heidegger, differenti-
the concept (the third term of mediation) ates the being off from a sort of background
difference is no longer conceived in terms of obscurity. In this way, Deleuze gives a new
of itself or in itself. Although he analyzes sense to Heideggers expression ontologi-
Aristotle (ancient dialectic) and Hegel (mod- cal difference: being is the active differen-
ern dialectic), Deleuze orients the entire chap- ciator of beings (90/65; see also 154/117).9
ter toward one overarching movement in Like the first two points, the third takes up
Western metaphysics: Platonism (91/66). As a well-known aspect of Heideggers thought:
is well-known, in this chapter, Deleuze defines the question of being.10 Deleuze says that
the task of contemporary philosophy as the ontological difference corresponds to the

418
HEIDEGGER AND DELEUZE

question. In other words, through the cor- Deleuzes five points aim to outline a more
respondence, Deleuze makes an equivalency accurate reading of the Heideggerian not:
between being and questioning. He makes the Heideggerian NOT refers not to the
this equivalency not only because it seems to negative in being, but to being as difference;
be faithful to Heideggers thinking but also it refers not to negation but to the question
because Deleuze had already suggested that (Deleuzes capitalization of not). Deleuzes
Plato (not Platonism) had transformed being defense of Heidegger is so strong here that
itself into questions and problems by means he says that he considers the Heideggerian
of his mythological accounts of origins. correspondence between difference and the
For instance, the oracular saying at Delphi question, between the ontological difference
explains Socrates origin, but the saying itself and the being of the question, fundamen-
raises problems and questions for Socrates tal. Despite this attachment to Heideggers
(88/63). Through this paradoxical origin, thought, Deleuze suggests that Heideggers
Deleuze is arguing, one is able to insert nonbe- own formulas for the not might be to blame
ing into being but not in a way that nonbeing for the misunderstandings of his later work.
exists simply to be itself negated and thereby Indeed, through a series of questions, Deleuze
returned (as in a circle, again) to the identity distances himself from Heideggers think-
of being. As equivalent to a question, being ing. In particular, Deleuze is not certain that
actively constitutes beings as differences, as speaking of the Same (gathering), rather than
if they were so many different answers to a Identity, is really enough to think original dif-
question that remains open and consequently ference (see also 154/117).12 Deleuze asks, Is
unanswerable. As a kind of nonbeing, dif- Sameness enough to disconnect difference
ference (or the question)fourth pointis from all mediation? This question implies,
not, as Deleuze says (our emphasis of not), as we shall see, that the fold, for Deleuze,
an object of representation.11 The turn must not be a homology between being and
beyond metaphysics, in Deleuzes interpre- beings. The distance, however, that Deleuze
tation of Heidegger, amounts to insisting takes from Heideggers thought really comes
that metaphysics cannot think difference in down to the status of the being (Seiende or
itself. The Heideggerian turn, for Deleuze, ltant), not the status of being (not Sein or
is a resistance to conceiving difference as a ltre). The question for Deleuze is the fol-
third term between being and beings, it is lowing: Does Heidegger make the conver-
a stubborn resistance to mediation. Finally, sion by means of which being [ltre] must be
the fifth point: Difference cannot, therefore, said only of difference and in this way being
be subordinated to the Identical or the Equal, [ltre] revolves around the being [ltant]?
but must be thought as the Same, in the Same (translation modified). In other words, Does
(Deleuzes capitalizations). Through the Same Heidegger conceive the being [ltant] in such
(le Mme in French, die Selbe in German), a manner that the being [ltant] is removed
Heidegger is trying to think a gathering that from all subordination in relation to the iden-
is not reducible to empty indifferent oneness. tity of representation? Deleuze concludes,
Deleuze intends these five point to show It seems not, given [Heideggers] interpreta-
how certain readings of the later Heidegger tion of Nietzsches eternal return (91/66).13
(Deleuze probably has Sartre in mind) are Whether or not Deleuzes claim about
really misunderstandings. In particular, Heideggers interpretation of Nietzsches

419
HEIDEGGER AND DELEUZE

eternal return doctrinein Difference and event such as the writing of Hamlet was based
Repetition (but already in the 1962 Nietzsche in no determinate model, no exact founda-
and Philosophy [see NP, 211n1/220n31]), it is tion, and no self-identical origin; therefore its
clear that Deleuze thinks that Heidegger does subsequent theatre productions, while repeti-
not understand the eternal return doctrineis tions, all are able to be different. Undoubtedly,
correct, it tells us a lot about how Deleuze with this description of recommencement
conceives his own thinking in relation to that (creative repetition14), Deleuze seems to be
of Heidegger. When Heidegger interprets the very close to Heideggers own reflections on
eternal return doctrine as being metaphysi- the artwork, on the Abgrund (the foundation-
cal, Deleuze thinks that Heidegger is claim- less), on the Ereignis (the event of propria-
ing that the return of the eternal return is a tion), and on another beginning. Indeed, the
founded repetition. That is, it is the repeti- French word recommencement could be
tion of an identity that predetermines all the rendered in English as another beginning.
answers to the question, as if for Nietzsche Yet, insofar as Deleuze thinks that Heidegger
the repetition was a repetition of permanence, does not understand Nietzsches eternal return
as if for Nietzsche repetition did not pro- doctrine, he thinks the real issue between his
duce a multiplicity of new answers, as if for own thinking and that of Heidegger is the
Nietzsche therefore there was no true becom- idea of foundation: founded repetition ver-
ing. In contrast, what Deleuze sees in the eter- sus unfounded repetition. It is a question,
nal return doctrine is a very specific kind of as Deleuze would say in his later works, of
repetition, one that, as he says, makes a dif- becoming and deterritorialization.15
ference (DR, 85/60). The repetition to which The question of foundation is at work as
the eternal return refers, in Deleuzes interpre- well in the issue of thinking. In Difference
tation of Nietzsche, is a repetition that repeats and Repetition, Deleuze refers several times
no identity. It is a foundationless repetition. to Heideggers famous question of what
It is foundationless insofar as it repeats the calls for thinking (in particular, 188/144; but
being (ltant), but the beingan individual also 2523/1956, 259/200, 353/275).16 Of
thingis not conceived as copy of an origi- course, Deleuze recognizes that this question
nal or of a model. The being is conceived as means that it is possible for humans to think.
a singularity or as an event. A singular event, But, he also recognizes that for Heidegger that
for Deleuze, is a true commencement so possibility does not mean that we are think-
that the repetition of the eternal return is a ing or even capable of thinking. In short, for
recommencement. Being based in a com- Heideggerand Deleuze completely agrees
mencement, in an event, the recommencement with Heideggerthought thinks only in the
is not determined. Therefore the recommence- presence of what is to be thought. And what is
mentthe return of the eternal returnhas to be thought is not only what gives food for
the potential to produce more differences, thought but also and especially the unthink-
more events, more novelties, more answers to able or the nonthought, that is, the fact that
the question (25861/2002). The repetition we are not yet thinking (188; here Deleuze is
is creative. This formula seems to be contra- quoting Heideggers What is called Thinking?;
dictory since repetitions repeat and therefore the passage from Difference and Repetition
cannot be creative. Yet, one can understand that we are paraphrasing here from 188/144
the formula if one thinks of the artwork. An is untranslated in the English translation). Yet,

420
HEIDEGGER AND DELEUZE

for Deleuze what is at issue is how Heidegger everything begins with misosophy (DR,
conceives the relation between thought and 182/139).
what is to be thought. Deleuze claims (in a The question of philosophy is the one that
footnote, which reinforces what we saw in Deleuze asks in his last book (coauthored
The Five Points) that the later Heidegger with Flix Guattari): What is Philosophy?
(the Heidegger of What is Called Thinking?) In fact, this question brings us to what must
remains attached to the primacy of Same count as a third point of intersection between
(Deleuzes capitalization of the word the Deleuze and Heidegger: the fact that philoso-
Same, le Mme). The primacy of the same phy historically begins in Greece. Of course, it
means that Heidegger, according to Deleuze, is not controversial to claim that Heideggers
conceives the relation between thought philosophy revolves around some sort of
and what is to be thought as a homology retrieval of the original Greek inspiration
(188n1/321n11). Thus, the homology between for philosophy. Deleuze, however, explains
thought and what is to be thought, according Heideggers impulse to retrieve the Greeks as
to Deleuze, turns the Heideggerian fold into a particularly modern (nineteenth and twenti-
a kind of benevolent desire; it bears a strong eth century) endeavor, and, even more, a par-
resemblance to the philia of philo-sophy. In ticularly German endeavor (QPh, 97/101).
short, Heidegger seems to conceive the fold as Generally, according to Deleuze, German phi-
an interlacing, or even a chiasm. For Deleuze, losophy (Deleuze mentions Kant, Hegel, and
however, the fold must be understood as a Heidegger) wants to reconquer the Greek
fold between two kinds of forms, as if being philosophical territory (that seemingly has
and beings, thought and the object of thought, been given over to barbarians, nomads, and
and between things said and things seen, as anarchy [100/10419]). In order to reconquer
if all of the doubles are formalized. These the Greek territory, German philosophy must
two forms are not homologous but hetero- constantly clear and consolidate the soil, that
geneous and different from one another; the is, it must found [fonder] (ibid.). Once again,
fold is in fact a non-relation (F, 117/109).17 we see how the issue of foundation organizes
Yet, although different, they encounter one all of Deleuzes reflections on Heideggers
another across an element that is not the thought. But more specifically, Heidegger,
form of either of the doubles. The element according to Deleuze, conceives the Greeks as
must be conceived as formless or informal. the Autochthon: philosophy arises naturally
This negationin-formalimplies that out of the Greek soil. It is not imported from
prior to the fold, there is an unfold.18 The elsewhere; it does not come from another ter-
unfold is not an interlacing but a strangle- ritory. Thus, according to Deleuze, Greece is
hold (119/112). For Deleuze, therefore, and for Heidegger an origin (91/95). As the word
unlike for Heidegger, the fold between being autochthonous suggests, origin means
and beings, between things seen and things something like an internal necessity between
said, between words and things, subject and the Greeks and philosophy (89/93), as if phi-
object, etc., the between of all of these dif- losophy could not have appeared elsewhere,
ferences is conceived as violence or a struggle. as if from this origin the history of philosophy,
Indeed, without the violent relation, without which Heidegger calls the history of being,
an encounter, it is not clear why humans develops according to a kind of analytic
would ever start to think. As Deleuze says, and necessary principle (90/94). Because the

421
HEIDEGGER AND DELEUZE

Greeks are the origin, and despite the fact that have known that the people called forth by
the Greeks do not articulate their relation to philosophy (and art) is not one that claims
being, in Heidegger, Deleuze says, there is to be pure, but rather an oppressed, bastard,
no question of going farther than the Greeks; lower, anarchical, nomadic, and irremediably
it is enough to resume their movement in an minor race (1045/109). Earlier we said that
initiating, recommencing repetition (91/95, for Deleuze everything begins with misoso-
translation modified). Deleuze is arguing that phy. Now we can see that, for Deleuze, eve-
since the history of being is necessarily con- rything begins with nonphilosophy, with the
nected to a repetition of the Greek origin, nonphilosophers, the artists, the barbarians,
Heideggers idea of another beginning the anarchists, the nomads, with the ones
the initiating, recommencing repetitionis who contaminate us, who make the violence
a founded repetition. Heideggers repetition of the encounter. They are the ones who make
congeals at and around the Greek origin as us think; they are the ones who call for think-
if what the Greeks did is valid once and for ing. Yet, Deleuze knows that we would not
all (92/96). have the question of what calls for thinking
The congealed repetition of the Greeks without Heidegger. This is why he says, We
brings Deleuze to Heideggers so-called politi- must not refuse to take Heidegger seriously
cal mistake, his association with Nazism in (F, 118/111).
1933. In fact, what Deleuze is doing here is
providing an explanation of the so-called
mistake. Deleuze says, Heidegger wanted to NOTES AND REFERENCES
rejoin the Greeks through the Germans at the
worst moment of their history (104/108). 1
The following abbreviations are used here
At the worst moment of their history: to refer to Deleuzes works: DR: Diffrence
et rptition (Paris: Presses Universitaires de
this occurred when the Germans conceived
France, 1968). English: Paul Patton, Difference
themselves as a pure race. The mistake is and Repetition (New York: Columbia
that Heidegger takes the Germans, the pure University Press, 1994); NP: Nietzsche et la phi-
race, for the Greeks, the origin of philosophy. losophie (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France,
Although Deleuze wonders if Heideggers phil- 1962). English: Hugh Tomlinson, Nietzsche and
Philosophy (New York: Columbia University
osophical concepts are therefore not intrin-
Press, 1983); F: Foucault (Paris: ditions de
sically sullied, he admits that Heidegger may Minuit, 1986). English: Sen Hand, Foucault
have just been confused, that he lost his way, (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press,
that his eyes got tired. Nevertheless, it seems 1988); QPh: with Flix Guattari: Quest-ce
that, for Deleuze, Heideggers confusion had que la philosophie? (Paris: ditions de Minuit,
1991). English: Hugh Tomlinson and Graham
its source in the concept of the Greeks as an
Burchell, What is Philosophy? (New York:
autochthonous origina virtually pure ori- Columbia University Press, 1994).
gin of virtually pure philosophy could only 2
There is evidence that early in his career, during
call forth a pure people. In contrast, for the 1950s, Deleuze studied Heidegger. See Gilles
Deleuze, the Greeks were not an origin and Deleuze, Quest-ce que fonder?, accessed on
December 6, 2011, www.webdeleuze.com. This
they were not pure: philosophy was brought
text is the transcription of Deleuzes 19567
[to Greece] by immigrants (89/93). If cours hypokhgne, at Lyce Louis le Grand.
Heidegger had understood philosophy on In the context of a discussion of foundation in
the basis of this migratory event, he would Kant, he refers several times to Heideggers Kant

422
HEIDEGGER AND DELEUZE

and the Problem of Metaphysics. Also, in 1953 Graham Jones and Jon Roffe (eds) Deleuzes
he wrote book reviews on Rgis Jolivets Le Philosophical Lineage (Edinburgh: Edinburgh
problme de la mort chez M. Heidegger et J.-P. University Press, 2009), 32138); Miguel de
Sartre and K. E. Lgstrups Kierkegaard und Beistegui draws them together as thinkers
Heideggers Existenzanalyse und ihr Verhltnis of different sides of Being, ultimately irrec-
zur Verkndigung. oncilable (Truth and Genesis: Philosophy as
3
For references to Heidegger, see: NP 445/39, Differential Ontology (Bloomington: Indiana
123/108, 174/151, 194/169, 194n4/203n30, University Press, 2004). Claire Parnet identi-
174n/215n3, 211n1/220n31; DR xvixvii, 1/ fies a correlation in their occupation with the
xix, 52/35, 8991/646, 154/117, 169/129, nonthought within thought, yet admits in her
188/144, 2523/1956, 260/2001, 353/275, conversation with Deleuze that You [Deleuze]
384/301 and 333n11, 188n1/321n.11, are not a Heideggerian in Gilles Deleuze and
391/334; ID: Lle dserte et autres texts. David Claire Parnet, Dialogues (Paris: Flammarion,
Lapoujade (ed.) (Paris: Editions de Minuit, 1976). English: Dialogues II (New York:
2002). English: Mike Taormina, Desert Islands: Columbia University Press, 1977), 31/23.
and Other Texts, 195374, David Lapoujade Janae Sholtz claims Deleuze radicalizes the
(ed.) (New York: Semiotext(e), 2004), Heideggerian relation between the aesthetic and
106/75, 110/77, 112/79, 219/157, 222/159, a people-to-come (The Transformative Potential
225/161, 363/260, 156/301n14; D (Dialogues) of Art: Creating a People in Heidegger and
1819/1213; MP (A Thousand Plateaus) Deleuze. Dissertation (University of Memphis,
156/125, 5012n78/561n.85; C1 (Cinema 2009)). Also see: Dronsfield, Jonathan
1) 20n1/219n15; C2 (Cinema 2) 204/156, Between Deleuze and Heidegger There Never
218/167, 218n23/310n23; F (Foucault) is Any Difference, in David Pettigrew and
578/50, 66/59, 959/8993, 102/95, 115 Franois Raffoul (eds), French Interpretations
121/10713, 1218/11420, 107n16/146n16, of Heidegger: An Exceptional Reception. Suny
115n33/148n33, 118n36/148n36, Series in Contemporary French Thought (New
119n38/149n38, 121n41/149n41; TF (The York: SUNY Press, 2008), 15166; Keith
Fold. Leibniz and the Baroque)16/10, 36/26, Robinson, Towards a Political Ontology of
42/30, 5051/3536, 71, 36n27/154n14; the Fold: Deleuze, Heidegger, Whitehead and
QPh 43/40, 55/55, 56/56, 89100/93104, the Fourfold Event in Sjoerd van Tuinen
1045/1089, 88n5/223n5, 140n10/228n10, and Niamh McDonnell (eds.) Deleuze and the
169n17/231n17; N (Negotiations) 47/31, Fold: A Critical Reader (New York: Palgrave
1303/957, 1445/107, 1523/11213; Macmillan, 2009), 184202.
TRM (Two Regimes of Madness) 129/141, 5
The zigzag is imaged repeatedly by Deleuze:
226/241, 239/256, 356/380; CDG (semi- as undermining totality, a crack, asymmetrical
nars at the Universit Paris VIII Vincennes (MP, 263/216, 341/278); an extremely sinuous
and Vincennes St. Denis 197187, accessed fold . . . a primal tie that cannot be located
on February 3, 2012, www.webdeleuze. (TF, 162/120); something which passes or
com) IMAGE MOUVEMENT IMAGE happens between two as though under a
TEMPS: VincennesSt Denis00/00/1982, potential difference and a broken line . . .
01/00/1982; KANT: VincennesMarch that slips between (Dialogues, 13/6, 41/32);
21, 1978, March 28, 1978, April 4, 1978; . . . cest ptt le mouvement lmentaire, cest
LEIBNIZ: Vincennes May 20, 1980, ptt le mouvement qui a prsid la cration
00/00/1987, VincennesSt Denis20/01/1987. du monde . . . (LAbcdaire de Gilles Deleuze,
4
Alain Badiou argues for their proximity based filmed by Pierre-Andr Boutang in 19889).
on the univocity of Being (The Clamor of Being 6
We have simplified Deleuzes distinction
(Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, between foundation and nonfoundation. In
2000) (orig. pub. 1997)); Constantin Boundas fact, in Difference and Repetition, what is
views Deleuzes Difference and Repetition as at issue is to found or ground (fonder) and
a response to Heideggers Being and Time but begin (commencer). Yet, for Deleuze a genuine
claims the lines of divergence ultimately out- founding must metamorphose; however to
weigh those of proximity (Martin Heidegger, have a genuine founding what is founded must

423
HEIDEGGER AND DELEUZE

be related to a without ground (sans-fond) important definition of the plane of imma-


(DR, 200/154). Thus to ground in Deleuze is nence appears in What is Philosophy? See
never a repetition of the same. QPh, 50/489.
7
Deleuze cites Heideggers On the Essence of 18
Deleuze speaks of the unfold (dpli) in TF
Ground, and What is Metaphysics, both (P, 501/356). The word unfold, however,
in Martin Heidegger. Pathmarks edited by really comes from Foucault. See Foucault,
William McNeil (USA: Cambridge University Les mots et les choses, 353; The Order of
Press, 1998), 97135 and 8296. Things, 342. In our discussion of the fold in
8
Deleuze cites Heideggers Overcoming Deleuze, we have inserted some comments
Metaphysics, in trans. Joan Stambaugh, The from Deleuzes Foucault. Near the end of
End of Philosophy (USA: Harper & Row, this book, Deleuze compares Foucaults
1973). thought to that of Heidegger (and to that of
9
See also TF where Deleuze late in his career Merleau-Ponty) (F, 11520/10813). This is
(1988) takes up again Heideggers language of an important and truly illuminating compari-
the Zwiefalt (TF 42/30). son. Indeed, there can be no question that
10
Deleuze cites again On the Essence of Ground. Deleuzes Foucault is one of the best books
11
Deleuze cites again Overcoming ever written on Foucaults thinking. Yet, as
Metaphysics. But here in the fourth point, he some have claimed, Foucault appears to be as
also cites Jean Beaufrets Introduction une much a book about Deleuzes thinking itself
lecture du Pome de Parmnide (Paris: Presses as is it about Foucaults. See Thomas Flynn,
Universitaires de France, 1955), and Beda Sartre, Foucault, and Historical Reason,
Alleman, Hlderlin et Heidegger (Paris: Presses Volume Two (Chicago: University of Chicago
Universitaires de France, 1954). Press, 2005), 350n22: . . . [Deleuzes] impor-
12
By focusing on the same (gathering), Deleuzes tant book on Foucault . . . is an original
criticism of Heidegger is virtually identical attempt to think his own thought through
to that of Foucault and that of Derrida. See that of Foucault. It is possible therefore that
Michel Foucault, Les mots et les choses (Paris: Deleuze is presenting his own thinking under
Tel Gallimard, 1966), 345; anonymous English the proper name Foucault. Yet, Deleuze
translation as The Order of Things (New York: does not put the name Foucault between
Vintage, 1970), 334. See Jacques Derrida, scare quotes and he claims unequivocally
Mmoires pour Paul de Man (Paris: Galile, that he is presenting Foucaults thinking as
1988), 136; English translation by Cecile such in his book. The possibility, however,
Lindsay, Jonathan Culler, and Eduardo Cadava that Foucault is actually Deleuze presents
as Memoires for Paul de Man (New York: a serious interpretative problem for anyone
Columbia University Press, 1986), 1412. who wants to incorporate Foucault into
13
Here Deleuze cites Heideggers interpretation an exposition of Deleuzes thinking. This
of Nietzsche in What is Called Thinking? problem explains why we have used Foucault
14
In Difference and Repetition, Deleuze calls sparingly in our exposition. No matter what,
what we are calling a creative repetition a however, we think Foucault is one of the
clothed or disguised repetition. See DR, most important philosophy books written
114/84. in the twentieth century. For instance, what
15
Deleuze develops the concepts of becom- Deleuze says about dualism in Foucault
ing and deterritorialization in MP. See MP, specifically and about dualism generally is
305/249 for becoming; see MP, 211/172. extraordinarily illuminating (F, 89/83).
16
See also F, 124/116: In truth, one thing haunts 19
In this comment, Deleuze cites the Preface to
Foucaultthought. The question what does the First Edition of Kants Critique of Pure
thinking mean? What do we call thinking? Reason (see Allen W. Wood, editor, Basic
is the arrow first fired by Heidegger . . . the Writings of Kant (New York: The Modern
arrow par excellence (translation modified). Library, 2001), 36), where Kant speaks of
17
The fold in Deleuze is equivalent to what the land of metaphysics being given over to
he calls a plane of immanence. The most barbarians, nomads, and anarchy.

424
53
HEIDEGGERS ANGLO-AMERICAN
RECEPTION
Leslie MacAvoy

Heideggers work has been best received context. He characterizes Heideggers posi-
within Anglo-American philosophy by phi- tion as a transcendental pragmatism.
losophers interested in pragmatism, and, While Okrent does not directly address rep-
indeed, reference is often made to the prag- resentationalism, the verificationist thesis for
matist reading at least when discussing texts which he argues has anti-representationalist
like Being and Time. This essay shall explore consequences. Finally, Rorty sees affinities
three prominent pragmatist interpretations between Heideggers position and pragmatist
of Heidegger. All of them share as a common approaches in the philosophy of language
theme a critique of representationalism, but insofar as both are critical of metaphysics
each elaborates this critique in very different and representationalism. His position could
ways. For this reason, it makes sense to think be considered pragmatist in the further sense
of pragmatism as functioning as a kind of that he is more concerned with a philoso-
family resemblance concept. phys usefulness than he is with its truth, and
The three positions to be explored here this informs his appropriation of Heideggers
are put forward by Hubert Dreyfus, Mark thought.
Okrent, and Richard Rorty. Dreyfus offers a The locus classicus for pragmatist readings
pragmatist reading of Heidegger, particularly of Heidegger is the analysis of Daseins eve-
of Being and Time, insofar as he emphasizes ryday Being-in-the-world in Being and Time.
the place of practices in Heideggers phi- Heidegger indicates that his project is to
losophy and the priority given to the prac- arrive at some philosophical understanding
tical over the theoretical. He is particularly of being and thus to do fundamental ontol-
interested in using Heideggers phenomeno- ogy. But, as he also says in the introduction,
logical account of subjectivity to challenge the point of access for investigating this ques-
positions within the philosophy of mind tion is an analysis of Dasein because Dasein
that give priority to mental representations. is that entity that has an understanding of
Okrent focuses less on practices as such and being (GA 2, 1213/BT, 1112). Though
more on purposive, practical activity itself this understanding of being is not explic-
and how epistemic conditions may be articu- itly grasped, it operates in the background
lated in connection with this more pragmatic in everything that Dasein does, so to bring

425
HEIDEGGERS ANGLO-AMERICAN RECEPTION

it to philosophical awareness, an analysis instance, the writer uses the pen to write,
of Dasein in its way of being is required. but to understand the pen as something to
That way of being is existence, or Being-in- be used for writing indicates a more general
the-world, and the objective of much of the familiarity with the practice of writing, the
first division of Being and Time is to offer a other items of equipment that are bound up
phenomenological analysis of it. with the pen in such activities, etc. These
In developing this position, Heidegger equipmental contexts are bound together
directly opposes the more traditional for Heidegger by a set of references through
Cartesian view that a relation to the world which each item in the context points to and
is extrinsic to what it is to be a subject. The thus signifies the others. Thus, the under-
first important point, then, is that the subject, standing operative in practical comportment
Dasein, is necessarily related to the world. is holistic, and the things we encounter make
Furthermore, Heidegger explicitly rejects sense and are intelligible because they are
the notion that to be in the world can be disclosed to us as situated within worlds.
understood in terms of contingent, external, Such worlds are to be conceived as struc-
spatial, or locative relations such as are indi- tured spaces of meaning.
cated by expressions such as the water is in Heideggers rich analysis of Being-in-
the glass (GA 2, 54/BT, 545). By contrast, the-world has provided many resources to
the sense of Being in that he seeks concerns supply various pragmatist accounts. Dreyfus,
dwelling within or inhabiting the world. Thus, in his well-known book Being-in-the-World
as Heidegger begins his investigation into highlights the role of the practical in Being
Being-in-the-world, he focuses on practical and Time.1 He argues that the practical com-
activity and practical comportment, which portment Heidegger describes in chapter 3 of
he calls dealings (Umgang) (GA 2, 66/BT, Division I of Being and Time depends upon
66). The second important point, then, is that a familiarity with meanings that are tied to
the relation to the world is one of practical practices, and that practices by their very
involvement. This move challenges the prior- nature must be shared and social. This inter-
ity typically given to the theoretical attitude pretation emphasizes the role of the they
over the practical attitude as a perspective and Mitsein in Daseins Being-in-the-world.
from which to grasp what things are. That is, for Dasein the world is always a
A significant feature of Heideggers analy- world that it shares with others, and which
sis pertains to the way practical understand- it discloses on the basis of structures of intel-
ing operates by situating particular objects ligibility that are also shared.2
or items of equipment within broader equip- Dreyfuss reading of Heidegger is domi-
mental contexts or totalities of significance nated by a focus on the critique of two
that function as horizons in relation to which related forms of Cartesianism. The first
something becomes intelligible. Thus, Dasein form is an epistemological Cartesianism
demonstrates not only an understanding according to which subjects are character-
of an item of equipment by using it but a ized primarily as knowers who come to
familiarity with a whole range of equipment know objects by contemplating them. This
to which this particular item belongs and view construes the relation between sub-
a grasp of how all of it might be mobilized ject and object in terms of detachment, and
toward the completion of a project. So, for Dreyfus associates it with the theoretical

426
HEIDEGGERS ANGLO-AMERICAN RECEPTION

attitude. The second form is an ontological apophantic as involves a subtracting of


Cartesianism according to which objects to the reference relations in virtue of which, in
be known are conceived of as present-at- practical contexts, something can be taken
hand or occurrent [vorhanden]. Against as something or other (GA 2, 158/BT, 153).
the theoretical attitude and the ontological Thus, the apophantic as is derivative of the
priority given to presence-at-hand connected hermeneutic as, and assertion is derivative
with it, Dreyfus argues that Heidegger gives of interpretation.
priority to the practical attitude. He glosses Heideggers position here lends support
Heideggers account of dealings with equip- to Dreyfuss view regarding the priority of
ment as skilled coping, and he empha- the practical, and also serves as the basis
sizes Heideggers point that things show up for his claim that the knowing how associ-
for Dasein as ready-to-hand in this sort of ated with understanding and interpretation
comportment. is nonpropositional and nonconceptual.
This theme of the priority of the practical Dreyfus holds that propositional form is
attitude over the theoretical attitude, and in introduced into meaning in the move from
general the view that the theoretical attitude interpretation to assertion. He claims that
is somehow derivative of the practical atti- while assertions clearly have propositional
tude and achieved through a kind of disen- form and involve concepts, interpretation,
gagement from it, runs throughout Dreyfuss which occurs purely in practical activity, has
interpretation and underlies his characteriza- no such form and thus knowing how entails
tion of Heideggers account of understand- an understanding of nonpropositional, non-
ing as a knowing how to be contrasted with conceptual meaning. Dreyfuss commitment
the knowing that associated with the theo- to this position comes clearly into view in
retical attitude.3 It is further reinforced by his debate with McDowell about whether
Heideggers claim that assertion is a deriva- there is any sort of experience that is non-
tive form of interpretation. For Heidegger, conceptual but nonetheless meaningful or
interpretation is a development of under- whether, as McDowell maintains, experience
standing that involves an articulation of what must be conceptual all the way out.4 This
the understanding understands, and there is sheds important light on Dreyfuss interest in
an argument to be made that this interpreta- Heideggers critique of Cartesianism, namely
tion occurs in practical activity itself. That is, that what is perhaps most important about
when Dasein deals with equipment, it takes it for him is that it entails a critique of rep-
each item as something or other, that is, as resentationalism because practical comport-
a table or a door (GA 2, 149/BT, 1445). ment represents a kind of intentionality that
Heidegger calls this the hermeneutic as. In is not directed at mental representations.5
discussing assertions, Heidegger notes that it Dreyfuss reading of Heidegger might be
too contains an as-structure, but the as considered pragmatist in several ways. First,
in this case is an apophantic as, which is he emphasizes the theme of practical com-
bound up with the structure of predication portment in Heidegger, and stresses that the
(GA 2, 1545/BT, 14950). Thus, in the source of meaning that makes up the world
assertion the paper is white, the paper is as a structure of significance is shared social
asserted as being white. For Heidegger the practices. Second, Dreyfus not only gives pri-
transformation of the hermeneutic to the ority to the practical over the theoretical, he

427
HEIDEGGERS ANGLO-AMERICAN RECEPTION

renders the practical in some degree ineffable would count in favor of its truth or success.7
in relation to the theoretical. In his view, the- An act is successful if it brings about the state
oretical understanding, bound up as it is with of affairs intended by the action, and so we
what can be represented conceptually and can verify whether an act counts as being
propositionally, is impoverished relative to an act of a certain kind (or having a certain
what is understood in practical understand- meaning) by judging whether it is successful,
ing, which cannot be fully or adequately or has a reasonable chance of success, with
translated into this theoretical idiom. This regard to its goal. For instance, something
leads to a philosophical stance in opposition counts as an act of hammering if it succeeds
to representationalism. in achieving the goal that acts of hammering
Okrent also characterizes Heideggers have, that is, of pounding nails into boards.
position in pragmatist terms and, at least for Someone who uses a shoe to perform this
a significant portion of his book Heideggers action might be said to be performing an act
Pragmatism, shares Dreyfuss focus on of hammering just as much as someone who
Heideggers work during the period of Being uses a hammer, provided that there is success
and Time.6 Okrent considers Heideggers or a reasonable chance thereof. On the other
philosophy to be pragmatist for several rea- hand, someone who picks up a wet noodle to
sons. First, it is anti-essentialist. Second, his perform the same action could not be said to
entire account is about the primacy of a kind be performing an act of hammering because
of practical understanding that is rooted in the aimed for state of affairs will never be
shared practices about how to do things to achieved through this act. So Okrent says that
achieve some end. Third, this focus leads to the specific meaning of an act of interpreta-
a kind of pragmatist metaphysics insofar tion, then, is fixed by the conditions which
as Heidegger ends up holding the view that the act is to bring about, and this in turn is
the meaning of being is a function of Daseins the state of affairs which the agent of the act
understanding of being. would take as evidence for the truth of the
Okrent is primarily interested in the epis- act.8 Okrent continues: for Heidegger, the
temological consequences of this pragmatism fundamental notion of evidence is tied to the
and in bringing Heidegger into conversation way in which purposeful, practical activity
with the Anglo-American tradition of episte- must be recognizable as successful or unsuc-
mology. He argues that Heideggers position cessful if the activity is to count as purposeful
amounts to a kind of pragmatist recasting at all.9
of a more standard verificationist position. This amounts to an extension of pragma-
Verificationism holds that the meaning of a tist considerations to a verificationist account
sentence is a function of what would count insofar as verificationism is extended from
as evidence for its truth. Heideggers position sentences to acts. Acts can have meaning,
is not primarily about the meaning of sen- and that meaning is determined relative to
tences, but about the meaning of acts, given what would count as evidence of the actions
the priority granted the practical sphere. success. But for Okrent, Heideggers prag-
Okrent argues that the form of verification- matism goes even further because he holds
ism found in Heideggers work is the view that the meaning of the being of something is
that the meaning of any act, intention, or tied to Daseins understanding of being. This
assertion is a function of the evidence that claim is particularly important for Okrents

428
HEIDEGGERS ANGLO-AMERICAN RECEPTION

view that Heidegger is a transcendental prag- is not too bothered about whether he gets the
matist. To be a transcendentalist in Okrents thinkers he reads right. He simply uses them
sense is to be concerned with the necessary for accomplishing a purpose, and this con-
conditions for something, in this case, for tributes to the sort of playfulness one finds
intentionality. In this view, then, Heideggers in his reading of Heidegger and other phi-
philosophy is transcendental in that it is losophers. This playfulness is decidedly not
concerned with the necessary conditions for a feature of the other pragmatist interpreta-
intentionality, and Heidegger finds those con- tions considered here.
ditions to be rooted in Daseins being, which Rorty is motivated to adopt a pragmatist
for Okrent has to do with purposive, practi- position mainly by a critique of representa-
cal activity. So, the transcendental ground for tionalism. His objection to representational-
intentionality turns out to be practical, and ism is that it purports to make the truth of
so Heidegger is a pragmatist on transcenden- sentences depend upon their correspondence
tal grounds, which makes him a transcen- to the world. Such a view holds that there is a
dental pragmatist.10 Although Okrent does truth to the world, and that sentences, or lan-
not address representationalism directly, as guage, are only derivatively true in relation
Dreyfus does, the verificationist position that to the degree to which they copy this truth.
he emphasizes is anti-representationalist. Rorty rejects this. He claims that there is no
Representationalist theories are typically truth to the world; truth is only a property
conceptually related to correspondence of sentences, and sentences are descriptions
notions of truth, that is, that for some idea of the world.11 He suggests that however
or proposition to be true, it must accurately plausible the notion that language repre-
represent reality. Verificationism focuses sents the world may seem to be, it is much
instead on the evidence that justifies a belief, less tenable when we shift our consideration
claim, or action where that evidence might from sentences to vocabularies in general,
be coherence with other beliefs or actions, where it seems fairly clear that the criteria
and so, by contrast, is often associated with a that determine which words one should use
coherentist theory of truth. are actually set by language games, not cor-
Rortys approach to pragmatism and respondence relations with the world. To
consequently to Heidegger is somewhat dif- a large degree this aspect of Rortys prag-
ferent. Rortys pragmatism entails the view matism is rooted in a Wittgensteinian view
that truth is a function of the coherence of about language, namely that language is
discourses and the usefulness of those dis- based on language games that are essentially
courses for accomplishing certain ends. practices. In this regard, signs are just linguis-
Since philosophical discourse is just another tic tools for achieving certain ends, and how
discourse, there can be no sense in which it they are to be used is set by the norms that
is true except in the pragmatic sense, so a function as rules within some particular lan-
philosophical discourse will only be true to guage game. Language games and all prac-
the extent that it is useful for accomplishing tices are, in the end, contingent, meaning that
some end. This stance leads Rorty to con- although we have a set of words that we use
clude that the pragmatist should also be an to talk about the world, we might have had
ironist toward philosophical discourse, and a different set of words.12 This realization
his writing conveys the general sense that he should lead us to oppose essentialism as well

429
HEIDEGGERS ANGLO-AMERICAN RECEPTION

as representationalism, and thus one can see critique of the metaphysical tradition. Thus,
that Rortys pragmatism does indeed draw Rorty appropriates Heidegger for his pur-
attention to the primacy of practices. poses because he thinks he is useful, but also
It is also clear that this view contributes to because he thinks that Heideggers critique of
the ironist stance. Rorty thinks that beliefs metaphysics overlaps in important ways with
and desires are related to one another in the the pragmatist critique as one finds it in a fig-
sense that a belief can be said to be true or ure such as Dewey. First, both Heidegger and
false partly because of how useful it is for the pragmatist identify pseudo-problems
helping us achieve our desires. This leads to that arise from a sort of sedimented way of
the view already mentioned that philosophy thinking inherited from the tradition, and
should be viewed as a tool, as something second, both distrust the theoretical attitude
that is useful for something, and the use to as a kind of view from nowhere that can
which Rorty thinks philosophy should be be used for apprehending truth.14
put is overcoming representationalism and In conclusion, one can see that the prag-
the idea that there are any things in them- matist approach to Heidegger encompasses
selves that we can know with certainty.13 a fairly wide variety of interpretations, and
He associates this way of thinking with the though they may all be loosely grouped
Cartesian-Kantian tradition, which has gen- together as concerned with a critique of rep-
erated all sorts of philosophical problems resentationalism, the way this critique is elab-
that are in fact pseudo-problems. Following orated varies quite a bit. Dreyfus is mainly
Wittgenstein, Rorty thinks we need to show interested to engage positions in philosophy
the fly the way out of the bottle, and he looks of mind, Okrent in epistemology, Rorty in
to a wide variety of philosophers to assist philosophy of language and metaphysics. All
with this project. share an interest in illustrating the relevance
Rortys reading of Heidegger is moti- of Heideggers thought to a wider philo-
vated by this interest, and he thinks that sophical audience, and in this regard these
Heideggers philosophy can be useful for his philosophers have done much to help close
anti-representationalist goals. On the one the perceived gap between continental and
hand, Rorty agrees with Dreyfus, Okrent, analytic philosophy.
and others and for the same reasons that
Heidegger is a pragmatist in Being and Time.
Dasein discloses the world in relation to its NOTES AND REFERENCES
projects, and these are contingent, fragile,
and could have been otherwise. Thus, Rorty
1
Hubert L. Dreyfus, Being-in-the-World: A
sees Heidegger as sharing the pragmatist view Commentary on Heideggers Being and Time,
Division I (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1991).
about contingency. On the other hand, Rorty 2
This view is also put forward by Robert
claims that by the 1930s Heidegger moves Brandom in his influential essay, Heideggers
away from this pragmatism as he under- Categories in Being and Time, The Monist, 66
takes the history of being in the Nietzsche (1983), 387409.
lectures. Interestingly enough, however, it is
3
Dreyfus, Being-in-the-World, 184. In various
places, Heidegger seems to suggest that the
this period of Heideggers philosophy upon opposition between the theoretical and the
which Rorty himself seems far more inter- practical might not be a straightforward as
ested in drawing because of its more overt Dreyfus suggests. See GA 2, 3578/BT, 3401.

430
HEIDEGGERS ANGLO-AMERICAN RECEPTION

4
See John McDowell, Mind and World Metaphysics (Ithaca: Cornell University Press,
(Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1988).
1996). For Dreyfuss critique of McDowell, 7
Ibid., 5.
see Hubert L. Dreyfus, Overcoming the 8
Ibid., 127.
Myth of the Mental: How Philosophers Can 9
Ibid., 128.
Profit from the Phenomenology of Everyday 10
Continuing in the same vein, Okrent holds
Expertise, Proceedings and Addresses of the that Heidegger is also a kind of metaphysical
American Philosophical Association, 79.2 pragmatist because he turns to a pragmatic
(November 2005), 4765; Hubert L. Dreyfus, account to address metaphysical questions,
Overcoming the Myth of the Mental, Topoi, and Okrent says that any position asserting
25.12 (2006), 439. For the debate that that all metaphysical questions can legitimately
ensues between McDowell and Dreyfus, see be answered only pragmatically is pragmatic
Hubert L. Dreyfus, The Return of the Myth (ibid., 10).
of the Mental, Inquiry, 50.4 (August 2007), 11
Richard Rorty, Contingency, Irony, Solidarity
35265, and John McDowell, What Myth? (New York: Cambridge University Press,
Inquiry, 50.4 (August 2007), 33851. 1989).
5
That Dreyfus is critical of this view is evident 12
Rorty, Contingency, Irony, Solidarity, 9f.
throughout his commentary on Heidegger, 13
Richard Rorty, Essays on Heidegger and
especially as he formulates the opposition Others: Philosophical Papers Volume 2
between Husserl and Heidegger. It also sur- (NewYork: Cambridge University Press,
faces repeatedly in his debates with Searle. 1991), 45.
6
Mark Okrent, Heideggers Pragmatism: 14
Rorty, Essays on Heidegger and Others,
Understanding, Being, and the Critique of 1011.

431
54
HEIDEGGER AND ENVIRONMENTAL
PHILOSOPHY
Trish Glazebrook

Heidegger never had an environmental phi- It took some time, however, for environ-
losophy as such. Environmental philosophy mentalism to gain ground in Heideggerian
was only just emerging when he passed away scholarship. The 1980s saw a disparate col-
in 1976.1 Nonetheless, he had a robust phi- lection of almost entirely unrelated papers. In
losophy of nature. Hwa Yol and Petee Jung 1982, Cave used Heideggers notion of care
made the first contribution to Heideggerian (Sorge) to argue against utilitarian arithme-
ecophenomenology in 1975 with To Save tic and for a higher qualitative good that
the Earth that they alternatively called To justifies animals right to life.4 Zimmerman
Dwell Rightly on Earth, and described as was the most influential of Heideggers envi-
a phenomenological reflection on the eco- ronmentalist interpreters. He argued in 1983
logic conscience . . . following Heideggers that Heideggers thinking supports radi-
path.2 They argue that what Heidegger calls cal environmentalism.5 In 1984, Foltz used
care (Sorge), when misconstrued individual- Heideggers historical analysis of Western
istically, becomes careless thought in mans metaphysics to locate the conceptual roots
domination or will to power over nature of contemporary environmental crisis in
and the earth (Jung and Jung, To Save the the very texture of Western thinking.6 In
Earth, 111). As an alternative, they explore 1985, Westra, quoting Zimmerman (1983),
Heideggers later work on poetic dwelling and used care in support of intergenerational
letting beings be. This interpretation of him environmental justice by arguing that leav-
was radically novel for its time and its cen- ing beings free to be what they are does not
tral theme remains throughout Heideggerian exploit them instrumentally for their value
ecophenomenology: the intellectual history in the future.7 In 1986, Zimmerman argued
of the West began with the Greek interpreta- further that Heideggers thinking has much
tion of nature and culminates in the essence in common with deep ecology.8 Deep ecolo-
of technology. Equally novel, Seidel (1979) gists Devall and Sessions were influenced by
mined Heidegger for resources for ecolo- Zimmermans reading of Heidegger to sup-
gists, a direction explored ten years later by port their arguments that the intellectual
Padrutt at the conference noted below, and history of the West is anthropocentric, that
again ten years later by Holland.3 Heideggerian letting beings be provides an

433
HEIDEGGER AND ENVIRONMENTAL PHILOSOPHY

Eastern alternative, and that authentic dwell- other animals. Since the beginning of ani-
ing is possible on its basis.9 mal rights debates, philosophers have argued
The decade culminated in 1989 with there is no basis to distinguish humans from
a conference at Truman State University, other animals that might justify not giv-
Heidegger and the Earth, that resulted ing animals the same ethical consideration
in a collection of essays on earth, world, as people. Heidegger is in a unique posi-
and dwelling interpreting and extend- tion with respect to this debate, because he
ing Heideggers thinking.10 These echoed takes transcendence, whether articulated in
the first papers from the 1970s by expli- terms of being-in-the-world, ek-sistence, or
cating Heideggers critique of the logic of the ek-stases of temporality, as definitive of
ecodestruction in the intellectual history Dasein yet does not insist that Dasein is nec-
of the West, and possibilities for a more essarily human, and he is strongly critical of
harmonious relation to nature. Extending the commitment to transcendental subjectiv-
Heidegger beyond philosophy, Pradutt con- ity that characterizes post-Cartesian philoso-
nected Heideggers work with ecology, and phy. In the lectures on Leibniz and logic, he
Skocz used him to assess the conceptual explicitly states that he has deliberately cho-
foundations of GIS (geographical informa- sen Dasein and not man . . . for that being
tion systems), an analysis he later applied to which is the theme of the analysis (GA 26,
reconcile wild animals lived space and the 172/MFL, 136), and that Dasein is not the
techno-human space of environmental man- egocentric individual (GA 26, 173/MFL,
agement. There has never been another con- 137). Thus his discussion in the Fundamental
ference dedicated entirely to Heidegger and Concepts of Metaphysics brings him directly
environment, though in 1997, Bruce Foltz to the question of animal cognition as he
and Robert Frodeman, both Heideggerians, inquires into the metaphysical foundations
founded the International Association for of thinking. His response is to argue that
Environmental Philosophy that has hosted animals are poor in world while humans
many Heideggerian ecophenomenologists. are world-forming (GA 29/30, 263/FCM,
In 1993, Zimmerman recanted, claiming 177). As recently as 2012, Hatab notes that
that Heideggers involvement with National the issue of transcendence that Heidegger
Socialism tends him toward ecofascism, has engaged since the 1920s remains an open
of which deep ecologists had already been problem in evolutionary biology.13 Scientists
accused.11 In 1995, Zimmerman had his final simply cannot explain consciousness, that is,
word on Heideggers saving power versus how brain events carry meaningthey dis-
threat by arguing that Heideggerian tran- miss this question as the hard problem.14
scendence supports the will to domination So for Heidegger, animals are (somewhat
as much as it does benevolence.12 The ques- vaguely) more worlded than rocks, but less
tion of transcendence figures prominently in so than Dasein.
Heideggerian approaches to animal issues, Glendinning (1996) argues that Heidegger
but also concerning deeper questions sur- is anthropocentric in that his focus on lan-
rounding Heideggers conception of human guage privileges humans.15 Being anthro-
being as critics assess whether transcendence, pocentric (human-centered) is a common
language, and freedom commit Heidegger to criticism in environmental philosophy that
a radical distinction between humans and accompanies the charge of speciesism,16

434
HEIDEGGER AND ENVIRONMENTAL PHILOSOPHY

that is, the unjustified privileging of the in terms of societies or social groups rather
human over other species, analogous to rac- than the species.21 Others defend anthropo-
ism, sexism, and other -isms of domina- centrism. Schalow (2002) argues that the
tion. Anthropocentrism reduces nature to its capacity for language obliges humans to
instrumental value for meeting human needs, speak on animals behalf,22 but this looks
while biocentrics (who are life-centered) and like an instance of the naturalist fallacy in
ecocentrics recognize the intrinsic value of which is is taken to imply ought, or in
all living beings and take human beings as this case can implies should. More inter-
members rather than overlords of the biotic estingly, Van Burens (1995) critical environ-
community. These terms come from deep mental hermeneutics argues that Heideggers
ecologists, who defend threatened life-forms, account of communicative discourse makes
species, and/or ecosystems, but have been room for radical heterogeneity and local-
accused of ecofascism, that is, militant dis- ism in environmental narratives . . . and
regard for human welfare, because their espouses coexistence, communication, com-
biocentrism promotes an egalitarianism in promise, cooperation, and consensus.23 In
which, for example, the malaria-carrying this reading, Heideggers account of language
Anopheles mosquito has as much right to life accordingly precludes ecofascism and instead
as anything else. grounds democratic exchange across disa-
In Derridas 1997 lectures, Heideggers greements and diverse needs and interests.
question of the animal (Derridas phrase) is Given that mainstream environmental phi-
permeated by the issue of language and took losophy stalled over the anthropocentric/eco-
a metaphysical turn that Calarco (2008) crit- centric debate, Heideggers real contribution
icizes as anthropocentric.17 Since Derrida is to ecophenomenology may be not what he
interested in the animal that therefore [he] brings to specific issues, but how he makes
is, his account could not possibly be non- possible new approaches. For example,
anthropocentric insofar as it is intentionally Swanton (2010) reads Heidegger on dwelling
Derrida-centric. Yet Derrida is not blind to and truth to develop an environmental virtue
the limitations of the metaphysics of moder- ethics that avoids both anthropocentric spe-
nity, and regularly follows Heidegger back to ciesism and biocentric egalitarianism.24 She
the Greeks. Indeed, Elden (2006) had already claims thereby to escape metaphysical dilem-
argued that Heideggers zoon logon ekhon is mas in the analytic philosophical tradition of
not the animal rationale of metaphysics.18 ethics. Ecophenomenology may thus make
Dombrowski before him in 1994 had also possible broader Heideggerian contribution
argued for an anti-anthropocentric reading to ethics heretofore impeded by his Nazi
of Heidegger,19 and McNeill (1999) used involvement, and his preference for meta-
Heideggers historical critique of moder- physics. Such ethics are articulated in dwell-
nity to demonstrate that he should not be ing, Heideggers alternative to culmination
regarded as another essentialist or human- of the intellectual history of the West in the
ist concerning animals.20 So is Heidegger essence of technology.
anthropocentric or biocentric? Manoussakis says Heidegger had one
Thiele (1995) offers a Heideggerian cri- single thought, Being, as it first appeared
tique of both biocentrism and sociocentrism, in the Greek beginning of philosophy,25
a more nuanced form of anthropocentrism that is, as physis, nature. Reading Aristotle,

435
HEIDEGGER AND ENVIRONMENTAL PHILOSOPHY

Heidegger confirms that the word nature poisis in the highest sense (VA, 15/QCT,
. . . contains an interpretation of beings as 10). For as Aristotle knew, physis has the
a whole (GA 9, 240/PA, 184), and accord- bringing-forth . . . in itself (ibid.)nature
ingly that meta-physics is physics, i.e., appears with no artist.
knowledge of physis (GA 9, 241/PA, 185). Heidegger is not thereby claiming, how-
He had been coming up against the relation ever, that nature is like art; rather, art is like
between earth and world, the physical and nature. Production is a derivative version
the metaphysical, for some time, for exam- of the generative power of physis. Thus he
ple, in the 1929/30 lectures on metaphys- argues in 1939 that attempt to clarify the
ics (GA 29/30) and the 1935/36 lectures on essence of physis by way of an analogy with
art. In 1939, reading Physics B, 1, he locates techn fails . . . from every conceivable point of
the crucial event determining the history of view (GA 9, 292/PA, 223). Historically, the
metaphysics in Aristotles double concept of medieval account understands natural enti-
physis (GA 9, 273/PA, 209): physis, nature, ties as divine artifactsan idea in the mind
is a way that beings come to be (192b8); but of God that shapes matterbut modern sci-
ta physika, natural entities, are substances, ence makes the divine redundant. Glazebrook
that is, formed matter. The former is the (2000) explicates how in Heideggers account,
last echo of the original (and thus supreme) once nature has neither Aristotelian teleology
thoughtful projection of the essence of phy- nor divine, Judeo-Christian purpose, noth-
sis of the pre-Socratics (GA 9, 242/PA, 186); ing stops the organized global conquest of
the latter is the first interpretation of nature the earth (GA 6.2, 358/NIV, 248) by the
by analogy with production. Definitive of essence of technology, a mechanistic, materi-
production, techn, for Aristotle is the artists alist way of revealing (VA, 16/QCT, 12) that
conception of the work prior to its produc- sets upon . . . unlocks and exposes (VA,
tion (640a32; 1140a13). In production, the 189/QCT, 15) nature so it can be stock-
artist imposes that form onto the material. piled into standing-reserve (VA, 20/QCT,
Heidegger criticized that account in 1935/36 17).26 Plumwood notes likewise that a
because art is a bringing forth of beings mechanistically conceived nature lies open
(GA 5, 48/BW, 184) that is only possible in to, indeed invites the imposition of human
the midst of the being that surges upward, purposes and treatment as an instrument for
growing of its own accord, physis (ibid.). the achievement of human satisfactions.27
That is, production is only possible because But nature is not mere matter passively
natural materials are already available of standing by for appropriation into human
their own accord for appropriation into art. projects. Heidegger names the interpretation
By the mid-1930s, Heidegger already holds of being that turns self-revealing physis into
that the history of metaphysics following the standing-reserve of nature: Ge-stell (VA,
Aristotle interprets art reductively as form 23/QCT, 19); ecofeminists call it the logic of
imposed on matter. Rather, he argues, art domination.28
is truthaltheia, a world-opening event, Heidegger argues that Ge-stell, drives out
unconcealment of beingsthat can only arise every other possibility of revealing (VA, 31/
on the ground of earth (GA 5, 31/BW, 168). QCT, 27). Ecofeminists argue likewise that
The creative act is poisis, and Heidegger will logics of domination privilege the environ-
say almost 30 years later, physis is indeed mentally destructive knowledge practices

436
HEIDEGGER AND ENVIRONMENTAL PHILOSOPHY

of modern science over traditional ecologi- Greeks called bios thertikos, the con-
cal knowledge-systems.29 In the Beitrge, templative life. But it has none of the aloof-
Heidegger argues that insofar as modern ness and restraint of objectivity; rather, it is
science claims to be one or even the decisive the highest doing (VA, 48/QCT, 164). The
knowing (GA 65, 141/CP1, 98), it deter- pre-Socratics did not experience physis as
mines the abandonment of being, experi- a collection of objects, but as self-revealing
enced in anxiety that has never been greater provocation to the question, Why are there
than today (GA 65, 139/CP1, 97; see GA 9, beings at all, and not rather nothing? that
33741/BW, 2414). The idea of anxiety goes ends What is Metaphysics? and begins
back to Being and Time where it is explained Introduction to Metaphysics.
as Unheimlichkeit, a not-being-at-home Heidegger identifies the power of the
(SZ, 188/BTMR, 233). But only reading earth as a home (GA 39, 88). When the
Aristotles Physics on being as physis leads Chipko movement began in India in 1973,
Heidegger to the insight that the abandon- the women proclaimed, The forest is our
ment of being is not the existential human home!32 Environment has indeed been
condition as in Being and Time, but the famously redefined in the environmental
not-being-at-home in nature assessed in the justice movement as where we live, work
Beitrge. Warren likewise describes experi- and play.33 Heidegger calls earth the build-
ence of environmental crisis as longing for ing bearer, nourishing with its fruits, tending
home . . . a troubling, nagging, uncomfort- water and rock, plant and animal (VA, 170/
able feeling.30 Both Warren and Heidegger PLT, 178), the serving bearer, blossoming
envision an alternative conception of nature and fruiting, spreading out in rock and water,
as a home in which human beings dwell. rising up into plant and animal (VA, 143/BW,
In the same way that the concept of 351). Glazebrook (2004) argues from experi-
nature is a historically degraded conception ence backpacking in the Canadian Rockies
of physis derivative from Aristotles concep- that Nature gives me all I need to survive,
tion of techn, sciencethe theory of the even thrive, but is at the same time an indif-
real (VA, 42/QCT, 157 et passim)is for ferent death trap.34 Crucial to survival is
Heidegger a degraded experience of theo- paying close attention (Glazebrook 2004,
ria. In contrast to the objective indifference 89). Heideggers depiction of earth as nur-
of scientific theory, humans can encounter turer is not mere idealization, but a warning
natural phenomena with a sense of wonder. that nature is where humans dwell, on which
For example, Babich, whose first degree is in they depend, and should not be thoughtlessly
biology, describes waterbears as fascinating, destroyed. He aims, like ecofeminists, to
even fun, but little understood to this day ... honor, cherish, and respect the value of earth
alien-seeming, fascinating, and intriguingly as our home.35
intractable.31 Heidegger argues that etymo- For Heidegger, humans dwell in that they
logically, theorizing means to look atten- save the earth . . . To save properly means
tively on the outward appearance wherein to set something free into its own essence
what presences becomes visible and, through . . . Saving the earth does not master the
such sightseeingto linger with it (VA, earth and does not subjugate it (VA, 150/
48/QCT, 163). Heidegger identifies such BW, 352). McNeill (1999) explains that
attentive, thoughtful practice with what the Dwelling means . . . saving the earth and

437
HEIDEGGER AND ENVIRONMENTAL PHILOSOPHY

heavens in letting them be.36 Letting beings not dwell; dwelling needs community. The
be was first hinted at in Being and Times situatedness Heidegger identifies as historical
maxim of phenomenology: To the things is also cultural (once Eurocentric blinders are
themselves! In 1930, Heidegger argues that removed). Every culture is an event of being.
freedom belongs to truth not as a property Heideggers one single thought is of dwell-
of human subjects, but as letting beings be ing together in nature through cultivating
(GA 9, 188/BW, 125). In 1942, the hospita- and caring (VA, 185/PLT, 217). His ecophe-
ble host lets the guest be the one he is (GA nomenology is not the wilderness ethics of
53, 1756). In 1951, to free actually means the deep ecologist, but an agrarian ethics of
to spare (VA, 143/BW, 351), and sparing care.40
is the fundamental character of dwelling
(ibid.). Reading Hlderlin a few months
later, . . . poetically man dwells . . . when NOTES AND REFERENCES
the environment is managed through a tak-
ing of measure (VA, 196/PLT, 227) that lets 1
Three foundational texts appeared in 1973:
the earth be as earth (VA, 195/PLT, 227), R. Sylvan, Is there a Need for a New, an
Environmental, Ethic? Proceedings of
in contrast to our unpoetic dwelling [that]
the XV World Congress of Philosophy, 1,
derives from a curious excess of frantic meas- 20510; P.Singer, Animal Liberation, New
uring and calculating (VA, 197/PLT, 228). York Review of Books, 20 (5); and A. Naess,
In 1955, Gelassenheit, retains the notion of The Shallow and the Deep, Long-range
letting as attentive and meditative release- Ecology Movement, Inquiry, 16, 95100.
F.dEaubonne, Le fminisme ou la mort (Paris:
ment that frees beings from the calculative
Pierre Horay, 1974), the founding text of
thinking37 that reduces them to stockpilable ecofeminism, appeared the following year.
resources. Haar (1993) and Bate (2000) hear 2
H. W. Jung and P. Jung, To Save the Earth,
song in such ecopoetic listening.38 Philosophy Today, 19.2 (1975), 10817, 108.
Llewelyn (1991) reads letting beings
3
G. J. Seidel, Heidegger: Philosopher for
Ecologists, Man and World, 4 (1979), 939;
be through the middle voicea technical
N.J. Holland, Rethinking Ecology in the
term in verb conjugation especially chal- Western Philosophical Tradition: Heidegger
lenging to Anglophones knowing only active and/on Aristotle, Continental Philosophy
and passive voiceto disrupt domination Review, 32.4 (1999), 40920.
of subject over object, and ground ecologi-
4
G. S. Cave, Animals, Heidegger, and the Right
to Life, Environmental Ethics, 4.3 (1982),
cal conscience.39 Heideggers talk of care in
24954.
Being and Time, with which Heideggerian 5
M. E. Zimmerman, Toward a Heideggerian
environmental philosophy began, focuses Ethos for Radical Environmentalism,
on how care unifies consciousness (SZ, 193/ Environmental Ethics, 5.2 (1983), 99131.
BTMR, 238). He is still caught in the meta-
6
B. V. Foltz, On Heidegger and the
Interpretation of Environmental Crisis,
physics of subjectivity, despite his protests
Environmental Ethics, 6.4 (1984), 32642; 338.
against it. Conscience is the call of care (SZ, 7
L. Westra, Let it Be: Heidegger and Future
277/BTMR, 322), but that call comes from Generations, Environmental Ethics, 7.4
not-being-at-home (Unheimlichkeit) (SZ, (1985), 34150.
281/BTMR, 325). In dwelling, the thinker
8
M. E. Zimmerman, Implications of
Heideggers Thought for Deep Ecology, The
experiences not anxiety and homelessness,
Modern Schoolman, 64 (1986), 1943.
but wonder. Transcendental subjectivities do

438
HEIDEGGER AND ENVIRONMENTAL PHILOSOPHY

9
B. Devall and G. Sessions, Deep Ecology: 20
W. McNeill, Life Beyond the Organism:
Living as if Nature Mattered (Layton, UT: Animal Being in Heideggers Freiburg Lectures,
Peregrine Smith Press, 1985); see S. P. James, 192930, in ed. H. P. Stevens, Animal Others:
Thing-centered Holism in Buddhism, On ethics, Ontology, and Animal Life (Albany:
Heidegger, and Deep Ecology, Environmental SUNY Press, 1999), 197248, 198, follow-
Ethics, 22.4 (2000), 35975. ing his Heidegger: Visions of Animals, Others
10
The essays are collected in L. McWhorter, and the Divine (Coventry, UK: University of
Heidegger and the Earth: Essays in Warwick Press, 1993).
Environmental Philosophy (Kirksville, 21
P. T. Thiele, Nature and Freedom: A
MO: Truman State University Press, Heideggerian Critique of Biocentric
1992); expanded and reprinted, edited by and Sociocentric Environmentalism,
L.McWhorter and G. Stenstad, in 2009 by Environmental Ethics, 17.2 (1995), 17190.
University of Toronto Press. 22
F. Schalow, Who Speaks for the Animals?
11
M. E. Zimmerman, Rethinking the Heidegger Heidegger and the Question of Animal
Deep Ecology Relationship, Environmental Welfare? Environmental Ethics, 22.3 (2002),
Ethics, 15.3 (1993), 195224. See argu- 25972.
ments that ecofeminist readings of Heidegger 23
J. Van Buren, Critical Environmental
preclude fascism in T. Glazebrook, Heidegger Hermeneutics, Environmental Ethics, 17.3
and Ecofeminism, in eds Nancy Holland (1995), 25975, 275.
and Patricia Huntington, Re-Reading the 24
C. Swanton, Heideggerian Environmental
Canon: Feminist Interpretations of Heidegger Virtue Ethics, Journal of Agricultural and
(University Park, PA: The Pennsylvania State Environmental Ethics 23.102 (2010), 14566.
University Press, 2001), 22151. See S. P. James, Heidegger and Environmental
12
M. E. Zimmerman, Ontical Craving versus Ethics. Doctoral thesis, Durham University,
Ontological Desire, in ed. B. Babich, From 2001 and Heidegger and the Role of the Body
Phenomenology to Thought: Errancy and in Environmental Virtue, The Trumpeter, 181
Desire (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1995), 50123. (2002), 19.
13
L. J. Hatab, From Animal to Dasein: 25
J. P. Manoussakis, The Sojourn in the Light,
Heidegger and Evolutionary Biology, in ed. in eds D. A. Hyland and J. P. Manoussakis,
T. Glazebrook, Heidegger on Science (Albany, Heidegger and the Greeks (Bloomington:
NY: SUNY Press, 2012), 93111. Indiana University Press, 2006), 18, 2.
14
The term was introduced by D. Chalmers, 26
From physis to nature, techn to technol-
Facing up to the Problem of Consciousness, ogy: T. Glazebrook, Heidegger on Aristotle,
Journal of Consciousness Studies, 2.3 (1995), Galileo and Newton, The Southern Journal of
20019. Philosophy, 38.1 (2000), 95118.
15
S. Glendinning, Heidegger and the Question 27
Val Plumwood, Feminism and the Mastery of
of Animality, International Journal of Nature (New York: Routledge, 1993), 11011.
Philosophical Studies, 4.1 (1996), 7582. 28
K. Warren, The Power and Promise of
16
Peter Singers term from All Animals are Equal, Ecological Feminism, Environmental Ethics,
Philosophic Exchange, 1.5 (1974), 24357. 12.2 (1990), 12546, 128; see V. Plumwood,
17
J. Derrida, The Animal that Therefore I Feminism and the Mastery of Nature (London:
am, ed. Marie-Louise Mallet (New York: Routledge, 1993).
Fordham University Press, 2008); M. Calarco, 29
V. Shiva, Reductionist Science as
Zoographies: The Question of the Animal Epistemological Violence, in ed. Ashis Nandy,
from Heidegger to Derrida (New York: Science, Hegemony and Violence: A Requiem
Columbia University Press, 2008). for Modernity (New Delhi: Oxford University
18
S. Elden, Heideggers Animals, Continental Press, 1988), 23256; Staying Alive: Women,
Philosophy Review, 39.3 (2006), 27391. Ecology, and Development (London: Zed
19
D. A. Dombrowski, Heideggers Books, 1988), 26; M. Mies, and V. Shiva (eds),
Anti-anthropocentrism, Between the Species, Ecofeminism (Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Zed
10.1 (1994), 2638. Books, 1993) 23; See D. Curtin, Recognizing

439
HEIDEGGER AND ENVIRONMENTAL PHILOSOPHY

Womens Environmental Expertise, in 37


M. Heidegger, Gelassenheit (Pfullingen: Verlag
D. Curtin, Chinnagrounders Challenge: Gnther Neske, 1992), 12 et passim.
The Question of Ecological Citizenship 38
M. Haar, The Song of the Earth: Heidegger
(Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1999). and the Grounds of the History of Being

30
K. J. Warren, Ecofeminism and the Longing trans. Reginald Lilly (Bloomington: Indiana
for Home, in ed. L. S. Rouner, The Longing University Press, 1993); J. Bate, The Song of
for Home (Notre Dame, IN: University of the Earth (London: Picador, 2000).
Notre Dame Press, 1996), 227. 39
J. Llewelyn, The Middle Voice of Ecological

31
B. Babich, Towards a Critical Philosophy of Conscience (New York: St. Martins Press,
Science: Continental Beginnings and Bugbears, 1991).
Whigs, and Waterbears, International Studies 40
See P. B. Thompson, The Agrarian Vision:
in the Philosophy of Science, 24.4 (2010), Sustainability and Environmental Ethics
34391, 375. (Lexington: University Press of Kentucky,

32
Chipko movement. Uttarakhand Encyclopedia. 2010) on agrarian ethics. See M. Kheel, The
Available online at www.apnauttarakhand. Liberation of Nature: A Circular Affair,
com/chipko-movement/ (Accessed October 12, Environmental Ethics 6.4 (1985), 33945;
2012). Warren, The Power and Promise of Ecological

33
See P. Novotny, Where we Live, Work and Feminism;; and, D. Curtin, Toward an
Play: The Environmental Justice Movement Ecological Ethic of Care, in ed. Karen Warren,
and the Struggle for a New Environmentalism Ecological Feminist Philosophies (Bloomington:
(Santa Barbara, CA: Praeger, 2000). Indiana University Press, 1996), 6681 on

34
T. Glazebrook, Toward an Ecofeminist ecofeminist ethics of care. See T. Glazebrook,
Phenomenology of Nature. Every grain of Heidegger and International Development,
sand: Canadian perspectives on ecology and in eds Georgakis Tziovanis and Paul Ennis,
environment (Waterloo, ON: Wilfrid Laurier Heidegger in the Twenty-First Century (New
University Press, 2004), 87100, 88. York: Springer, 2012); and, V. R. Rao, Women

35
Warren, Ecofeminism and the Longing for Farmers of Indias Deccan Plateau: Ecofeminists
Home, 226. Challenge World Elites, in eds David Schmidtz

36
W. McNeill, Heimat: Heidegger on the and Elizabeth Willott, Environmental Ethics:
Threshold. Heidegger toward the Turn: Essays What Really Matters, What Really Works (New
on the Work of the 1930s, ed. James Risser York: Oxford University Press, 2002), 25562
(Albany: SUNY Press, 1999), 31949, 326. on ecofeminist agrarian ethics.

440
55
HEIDEGGER AND GENDER:
AN UNCANNY RETRIEVAL OF
HEGELS ANTIGONE
Tina Chanter

terror is in all cases whatsoever, either suggestion, I construe Heideggers return


more openly or latently, the ruling prin- to Antigone as, in its turn, a useful model
ciple of the sublime. Several languages for feminist intersectional analysis, in the
bear a strong testimony to the affinity of sense that gender needs to be construed in
these ideas. They frequently use the same
a relationship of fluidity with other politi-
word to signify indifferently the modes
cal questions, including citizenship and
of astonishment or admiration and those
of terror.. . . [Greek: deinos] is terrible or slavery, a fluidity thatmuch like the ques-
respectable. Edmund Burke tion of Being according to Heideggerhas
been obfuscated by the rigid oppositions of
metaphysical categories. This is not to sug-
In order to tackle the question of Martin gest that Heideggers apparent disregard for
Heidegger and gender I approach his phi- gender is unproblematic. At the same time,
losophy through the general problematic I utilize feminist intersectional analyses to
of art, with specific reference to Sophocles complicate Heideggers not entirely suc-
Antigone. I read Heidegger against the cessful effort to overcome Hegel, an effort
backdrop of G. W. F. Hegel, arguing that that nonetheless, paradoxically, returns us
Heideggers understanding of the uncanny to Greek poetry in such a way as to prove
sublimates Hegels rigorously sexualized, Heideggers interpretation of Antigone ulti-
representationalist account of Antigones and mately more fruitful for contemporary femi-
Creons mutually exclusive ethical stances. nist thought than Hegelseven if Heidegger
My approach to Heideggers reading of might not (and, I would say, does not) intend
Antigone is also informed by an intersec- such fruitfulness.
tional, feminist analysis. Intersectional analyses problematize the
I suggest that feminist responses to Hegels relative isolation in terms of which feminist
reading of Antigone stand in need of com- theory initially broached the concept of gen-
plication, because they remain attached to der, insisting that, in order for feminists not
an understanding of sexual difference that to replicate the white, middle class, heter-
is still too metaphysical. In developing this onormative bias of masculinist, patriarchal

441
HEIDEGGER AND GENDER

thinking, specific attention has to be paid For Hegel, the tragic form of art presents
to race, class, sexuality, and other sexually an early, culturally embedded practice that
salient differences, conceived as intersecting embodies values that he takes the modern
with gender. When Luce Irigaray and Judith era to have moved beyond, while the ancient
Butler, for example, in their very different Greece out of which the tragic form arose
ways, effect what they intend to be an over- also provides crucial clues for problematiz-
turning or interrogation of the terms in which ing the legalistic/Kantian direction in which
Hegel approaches Antigone, they nonetheless ethics was developed within a metaphysical
preserve sexual difference as their central cat- framework that both Hegel and Heidegger,
egory of analysis. By contrast, intersectional in different ways, put into question. Hegels
theory insists on construing gender as part of progressive, developmental account of phi-
a complex field, striated with a network of losophy as having surpassed, or sublated the
social forces. By taking up such analyses and Spirit that expresses itself in a less mediated
applying them to the ancient Greece out of form in Greek tragedy assumes a relationship
which Antigone emerges, and with which the between art and philosophy that Heidegger
play engages, I argue that the themes of fam- wants to challenge, but to which he remains
ily, kinship, and sexual difference need to be inadvertently committed, such that he allows
thought in relation torather than treated the figure of Antigone to continue to perform
in abstraction fromthemes of citizen- a preparatory role to philosophys allegedly
ship, slavery, and foreigners/outsiders, and more sophisticated conception of the truth of
that while the play is not typically analyzed art.2 Hegels ambivalent attitude toward the
in these terms, precisely such an interroga- Greeks is taken up as a model for Heideggers
tion of these interlocking themes permeates retrieval of the question of Being.
Sophocles Antigone. For Hegel, the Greeks serve to provide
Taking my cue from an intersectional a lost ideal in some respects, while in other
feminist analysis, I suggest that sexual dif- ways they are required to stand for a lack
ference, which remains the dominant vector of development. The return to the Greeks
in both Hegels reading and in feminist/queer effected by both Hegel and Heidegger is a
efforts to overturn the naturalized basis in maneuver that is burdened with the meta-
terms of which Hegel interprets ethical life physical elaborations that have taken place
(Sittlichkeit), needs to be complicated. Recent, since the Greeks, and at the same time
pivotal feminist reclamations of Hegels figu- enriched by those very elaborations, even
ration of Antigone remain, then, I argue, as metaphysics has led philosophy into cer-
overdetermined by Hegels oppositional tain impasses, which, as they see it, it is up
reading of the play, and as such, even as they to Hegel and Heidegger themselves to unset-
attempt to overturn his reading they adhere tle, elucidate, or overcome. Thus when Hegel
to its terms, remaining at the same time com- suggests that art for us is not what it was for
mitted to the hierarchical relationship Hegel the Greeks, his judgment harbors an admi-
establishes between art and philosophy in ration for the way in which tragic perform-
some of its aspects, a hierarchy from which ances at the theatre of Dionysos constituted
Heideggers understanding of metaphysics part of the cultural fabric of the Athenian
seeks to depart, but in relation to which it polis.3 Tragedy, for Hegel, depicts heroes
also remains captive to some extent.1 who understand and take up their ethical

442
HEIDEGGER AND GENDER

duty not as fully autonomous, individualized conception of morality, one in which con-
moral actors, who choose among an array of science, freedom, reflection, individuation,
moral choices that they are free to embody and choice can play significant roles, it must
or discard; rather their stance is assigned to also be observed that the subject of moral-
them according to socially prescribed roles, ity (Moralitt) into which the custom-based
values that proceed from duties embedded ethics on which Hegel takes Antigone to be
and enshrined in culture. Antigones role as based devolves, is a morality that is identi-
a woman assigns her to the family, to the fied with a public sphere that is thoroughly
care of dead, and to the old order of the permeated with masculinist assumptions.4
gods, while Creons and Polynicess roles as Women do not count as legal persons (neither
men assign them to the state, the preserva- for the Greeks nor for Hegel). Womens per-
tion of which Creon understands Polynices sonhood is subsumed by their husbands (and
to have threatened, and to the new order of before that, by their fathers), who, as heads
the gods. of households, guide families, into which the
While the tension between Antigones and personhood of women disappears. Women
Creons ethical stances takes center stage for do not have any legal personhood in their
Hegel, the tensions created by his own differ- own right, and have little, if any, significance
ential and naturalized assignation of gender outside their familial roles; Hegel considers
remain unexplored by him; sexual difference it womens duty to marry.5 The peculiar, both
naturally apportions the female sex to the quasi-transcendental and abject status that
sphere of the familial, and the male sex to the family plays in Hegels thought, as both
the sphere of the political. The ethics embod- facilitating, yet itself resistant to, dialectical
ied by women are necessary to the state, synthesis is explored by Derrida, as is the
in providing care for the family (care that peculiar status Hegel accords to the sister, to
not only extends to care of the dead, but in Antigone, whose father, at the beginning of
Hegels reading is epitomized by such care), Antigone, is dead, and who will never mar-
yet women are themselves not represented in ry.6 In refusing to marry Haemon, Antigone
any political capacity by the state. It is left defies Creon, who is not only her king but
to feminist interpretations to pursue the ten- who, on Oedipuss death, becomes her famil-
sions and difficulties this view entails. ial guardian (kurios). Antigone, however,
Hegels admiration of the heroes of Greek acts as if she is without a guardian; she is
tragedy, and of Antigone in particular, is tem- akyron.
pered by his progressive, developmental view The term genos, like the term Geschlecht
of history, a history in which the individu- (as Derrida points out) includes among its
alization of moral agents has introduced a significations not only family/generation
more sophisticated moral compass into the but also race, and as such provides textual
arena of ethics. If the ethical life (Sittlichkeit) evidence for Sophocles consideration in
for which Hegel makes Antigone and Creon Antigone of a complex and interconnected
representative in ways that are inevitably constellation of concerns, among them the
partial, since he assigns them to separate, difference between slaves and freemen,
and mutually opposing spheres, according that characterize the signifying field that
to a naturalized understanding of sexual dif- Sophocles is exploring.7 Yet this complex
ference, stands in need of a more variegated network of concerns has been oversimplified

443
HEIDEGGER AND GENDER

in the reception of Antigone, not least due case of Antigone, a mythical figure, defined
to the overdetermining influence of Hegels by her incestuous birth and her decision to
opposition of family/state, which circum- take on her fate in the form of suicideis
scribes the range of connotations genos has achieved at the expense of writing nameless
by limiting its reference to a narrow concep- others out of the history of Being.
tion of family or kinship. Heidegger emphaticallyperhaps a little
In addition to the polyvalent connotations too emphaticallydistances himself from
of genos, which Hegelian and post-Hegelian Hegels reading of Antigone, rejecting the
analyses tends to understand restrictively religion/state opposition in terms of which
as family/kinship, once one starts to look, Hegel reads the play.11 Yet, in the refusal with
textual and contextual evidence abounds which Heidegger greets these Hegelian terms
for Sophocles central, but neglected, con- can be read a resounding silence regarding
cern with citizenship/foreignness/slavery not other decisive terms that Hegel opposes to one
merely in Antigone but in the Oedipus cycle another in his understanding of Antigones
as a whole.8 I restrict myself here to citing conflict with Creon, which proceeds not just
only one further detail, a detail, however, in terms of the opposition between religion
that I take to be decisive. Antigone differenti- and state, but also in terms of the opposi-
ates Polynices from a slave, maintaining that tional claims of genos and state, of feminin-
she would not have violated the law in order ity and masculinity. Hegels interpretation of
to bury Polynices had he been a slave.9 While Antigone is rigorously sexualized, but, while
much ink has been spilled on the issue of irre- Heidegger distances himself from the notion
placeability vis--vis brother and husband, an of state, insisting that the term polis is not to
astounding silence has surrounded Antigones be equated with state, thereby implicitly con-
distinction of Polynices from a slave, a differ- testing one side of this Hegelian dichotomy,
entiation that grants her brother humanity, Heideggers only response to the question
while relegating slaves to the murky region of genos and sexual difference is silence.12
of the less than human, or the not quite How is this silence to be read? I suggest that
human.10 In differentiating Polynices from a Heideggers highlighting of the notion of
slave, Antigone differentiates her family from uncanny (unheimlich, deinon) in Antigone
those whose kin should not be honored in can be read as a sublimation of the question
death. She thus appeals to a distinction that of sexual difference, a sublimation in which
sets her familial, generational line, her genos, can also be read the trace of race.
her race, apart from those who would not If, at least at the level of his overt inter-
have deserved a burial that violates Creons pretation, Heidegger would appear to reject
law, those who are thus marked as less than Hegels reading of Antigone entirely, there is
human, those who are deracinated from their one important respect in which his approach
families: slaves, who, in ancient Athens, not to tragedy remains clearly continuous
coincidentally, are, for the most part bar- with Hegels; like Hegel, Heidegger makes
barians (nonGreeks). It turns out, then, that Antigone, rather than Oedipus, the privileged
any success Antigone might be said to have hero of his analysis of the Greek tragic form.
in inscribing her brothers humanity, and her By construing Antigone as sublime, Hegel
own existence as an ethical subjectto the had challenged Aristotles attribution of
extent that we can speak of success in the pride of place, when it comes to Greek tragic

444
HEIDEGGER AND GENDER

heroes, to Oedipuswith whom Aristotles political opposition, that between family


Poetics associates the finest recognition and state, while Oedipus Rex is privileged
(anagnorisis), which occurs simultaneously by Aristotle because the recognition that its
with reversal (peripeteia).13 Hegels admira- plot reversal affords is the most dramatic
tion for Antigone, which tends to conflate and complete: we come to know ourselves,
the empirical category of Athenian women, paradoxically, only by confronting our
for which Antigone serves as a symbol, with failure to know, our ignorance. Aristotle is
the mythical, fictional, Theban character of responding to Platos Socratic formulation
a play written by a male playwright of aris- of knowledge that comes from knowing one
tocratic origins, is beset with a series of ten- does not know, a response that champions
sions. Not the least of these, I would argue, the self-reflective capacity of an individual,
is the tension embodied in Hegels effort to while Hegels figuring of tragedy under-
discipline and contain what he construes as stands it as a more collective, civic endeavor,
Antigones ethical purity within a (Christian) reflecting the pulse of a polity, its performa-
religious piety at precisely the time at which tive enactment embodying the tensions of a
feminism is beginning to make its demands people.16
felt.14 Yet insofar as Hegel makes Antigone Although Heidegger follows Hegel in
an ethical heroine (albeit one that he does all attributing to Antigone, rather than Oedipus,
he can to purify, containing her within the pride of place in the pantheon of ancient
space of domesticity), Hegel implicitly chal- Greek tragic, mythical heroes, he follows
lenges Aristotles more disparaging attitude Aristotle both in depoliticizing Antigone in
to women, which prohibits women from the wake of Hegels challenge to Aristotle,
qualifying as fully rounded ethical subjects, and I would conjecture, in highlighting the
and in consonance with this declines to ana- quality that defines Antigone.17 I do not
lyze Antigones significance as a tragic hero, think it is too rash to trace, if not a direct
except through omission, neglect, and by causal link, at least some kind of continu-
intimating her inappropriateness. The sense ity (though not one without reconfigura-
in which Hegel recognizes Antigones ethi- tion) between an observation that Aristotle
cal capacity (even as he limits it, excluding makes in his Poetics, and Heideggers read-
it from the political), embraces a more com- ing of Antigone. Aristotle suggests that it
plex conception of the role of Greek tragedy is inappropriate for women to be coura-
than Aristotles, one that anticipates in some geous or clever (deinen).18 The remark is of
ways Jean-Pierre Vernants assessment of it. a piece with the views on women expressed
Precisely by construing Antigone as an ethi- throughout the Aristotelian corpus, and its
cal subject, Hegel departs from Aristotles influence reverberates in a series of refer-
exclusion of women from ethics, and in ences that come to punctuate, not to say
doing so construes Antigone as contesting determine, a constellation of interpretations
the socially prescribed roles Athens man- of Antigone, including Heideggers and
dated for women.15 Hegel thereby also gives Lacans.19 It also demonstrates that there is
the significance of tragedy a more political a dimension of Aristotles Poetics that fits
inflection than Aristotle; Antigone is the in seamlessly with his efforts elsewhere to
noblest tragedy for Hegel because it explores keep women and slaves in their ethical and
what Hegel considers to be the most salient political place.

445
HEIDEGGER AND GENDER

What would it mean, then, for Aristotle, an effort to contain women within the pri-
who is surely familiar with the use Sophocles vate, familial, domestic sphere, to keep them
makes of the word deinos and its deriva- in the home, out of which feminism threat-
tives in Antigone, to proclaim that it is inap- ens to break them? How should Heideggers
propriate for women to be deinen, and for apparent neutralization of the question of
Heidegger to seize upon precisely this term sexual difference be read? And how might
as the lynchpin of his interpretation?20 Is the determination Heidegger shows in Being
Heideggers championing of Antigone as and Time to maintain Daseins neutrality
the most uncanny (to deinotaton) a celebra- with regard to sexual differencea neutral-
tion of sexual difference, or a taming of it?21 ity that Derrida has suggested in his con-
Is he condoning Aristotles implication of sideration of Geschlecht (a term connoting
Antigones inappropriateness? Is he challeng- not just sexual difference but also racial
ing Aristotles judgment that it is inappropri- difference), rather than closing down the
ate for tragic poetry to characterize women question of sexuality, productively opens it
as courageous or clever? Is he championing uptranslate into Heideggers discussion of
Sophocles over Aristotle precisely because Antigone?22
Antigone crosses the boundaries, mixes up For Heidegger, Antigones dying is a
the categories of men and women, public becoming homely (HHTI, 104) that is
and private? How does Hegels interpreta- unhomely in the proper way, that is, out
tion, which had accorded Antigone an ethical of a belonging to being rather than a being
privilege that Aristotle had implicitly denied unhomely in the improper way, by being
her, play into Heideggers reading of the driven about amid beings without any way
play? In short, why is Antigone so important out (118). By taking on, enduring suffer-
in Heideggers understanding of the play, and ing (see 103) Antigone becomes supremely
what remains of her import as uncanny once uncanny (see 104), she makes the uncanny
it is (at least overtly) shorn of the connota- fitting, that is, she is at home with being
tions of sexual difference with which Hegel unhomely (121). As such, for Heidegger, she
fuses Antigones significance? embodies the truly human, which is to make
If Aristotle is surely aware of the use of herself at home in that in which one is not
the term deinos in Sophocles Antigone, at home, the not-human in the sense of that
Heidegger is just as surely aware of Aristotles which is of no avail (101). In champion-
use of the term in the Poetics. How then ing Antigones uncanniness, her way of abid-
should Heideggers focus on deinos be read ing in the uncanny, Heidegger recognizes her
in the light of Aristotles judgment? And extraordinariness, yet is too quick to convert
how should Heideggers interpretation of this into an exemplary trait of humanity. For
Antigone be read in the light of Hegels rigor- Heidegger to elide the difference between
ously sexualized interpretation of Antigone, the way in which Antigone is not at home
an interpretation that, while glorifying in the polis, and the ways others are not at
Antigone for embodying in the purest way home, short-circuits the question of sexual
the ethics of her sex, at the same time circum- difference and ignores Antigones radical
scribes her in a gesture that I read as a dis- exclusion from the polis, ignores that she is
ciplining mechanism, as an effort to contain not at home in the way that free men are,
Antigone within religious, Christian piety, since they are citizens. Heidegger eclipses

446
HEIDEGGER AND GENDER

this difference, and with it sexual/racial dif- uncanny than that which Heidegger and oth-
ference, by making Antigones uncanniness ers demand that she inhabit.
representative of humans uncanniness in If Hegel makes the issue of sexual dif-
general. ference decisive for his understanding of
Moreover, if, as on Heideggers reading, Antigone, Heidegger obliquely takes up and,
Antigone brings out the unfamiliarity at the despite himself, transforms the issue into a
heart of what it might mean to be human, the question that brings him into closer proxim-
limited inscription she achieves for herself as ity with how I am suggesting the nexus of
a finite being is accomplished only through connotations surrounding genos resonates
the banishment of others to the impossibil- in the text of Antigone, and how this signi-
ity of ever being at home. Not only does fying nexus might have functioned for the
Heidegger ignore the sense in which Antigone variously constituted, ancient Athenian audi-
writes herself into the political, from which ence of Antigone. While Heidegger himself
the polis excludes her, and thereby contests does not prove to be invested in pursuing as
the parameters of what constitutes the politi- problematic the politics at stake in how the
cal, he also neglects (along with an entire tra- discrimination between slaves and freemen
dition) Antigones endorsing of the inhuman takes place, his interpretation of Antigone
status of those who, in her effort to inscribe nonetheless, albeit inadvertently, makes more
herself as a political subject, she stipulates as available for interrogation than does Hegels
unworthy of burial, when she differentiates the neglected Sophoclean themes of citizen-
Polynices from a slave. Perhaps, then, it is ship, slavery, and freedom that intersect
in the deracination of slaves, their defamil- with those of sexual difference in Antigone.
iarization, their uprootedness from families In tragedy, Heidegger tells us, in a reference
they can call their own, that we should look that cannot help but conjure up Antigone, as
for a neglected resonance of the meaning of well as fragment 53 of Heraclitus to which
uncanny, since it is in their forced removal Heidegger explicitly refers,
from their families in life, that they are also
deprived of any possibility of being honored the battle of the new gods against the
by family members in their death. And in this old is being fought. The linguistic work,
failure to be honored, they become displaced originating in the speech of the people,
does not refer to this battle; it transforms
souls, not quite recognizably human, not quite
the peoples saying so that now every liv-
at home in a world that nonetheless they help
ing word fights the battle and puts up for
to make a world in which others feel quite at decision what is holy and what unholy,
home, a world in which others can comfort- what great and small, what brave and
ably qualify as human, and can even safely what cowardly, what lofty and what
explore the intricacies of what it might mean flighty, what master and what slave. (GA
philosophically to be wrenched from being 5, 29/PLT, 42)23
at home, wrenched from the secure position
of having been at home, yet able to return In Heideggers reading, there might not be
home. To the extent that Antigone makes her- a privileging of sexual difference, of who
self at home in the world, reconciles herself is male and who is female, but in question
to that which is of no avail, it is only by rather is who is free and who is not, who is
relegating slaves to an uncanniness still more master and who slave.

447
HEIDEGGER AND GENDER

NOTES AND REFERENCES in which the relation is figured differently. See


G. W. F. Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit, trans.
1
Brilliant as they are, in their different ways, A. V. Miller (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979);
Butlers and Irigarays interpretations of Phnomenologie des Geistes, ed. J. Hoffmeister
Antigone might remain too Hegelian in certain (Hamburg: Felix Meiner, 1952). See also
respects, but they have also paved the way for Hegel, Philosophy of Right, trans. with notes
going beyond Hegel in crucial regards. While T. M. Knox (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
Butler gestures in the direction of expanding 1967).
kinship in a more racially inflected direc-
5
Hegel, Philosophy of Right.
tion than Irigaray (and while she certainly
6
See Jacques Derrida, Glas, trans. John P.
engages race productively in other works), she Leavey and Richard Rand (Lincoln: University
only addresses it minimally in her discussion of Nebraska Press, 1986). As many have
of Antigone. See Butler, Antigones Claim: pointed out, the temporality of beginning and
Kinship between Life and Death (New York: ends I invoke here is in fact complicated by the
Columbia University Press, 2000) and Luce order in which Sophocles wrote the Oedipus
Irigaray, Speculum of the Other Woman, trans. cycle.
Gillian C. Gill (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University
7
Jacques Derrida, Geschlecht II: Heideggers
Press, 1985); Speculum de lautre femme Hand, trans. John P. Leavey, Jr. in ed. John
(Paris: Minuit, 1974). Sallis, Deconstruction and Philosophy: The
2
Heidegger understands Antigone as poetic, but Texts of Philosophy (Chicago: Chicago
thinks it falls to him to unpack the philosophi- University Press, 1987).
cal meaning of the poetic that she embodies
8
I develop this argument in Whose Antigone?
in Sophocles. Antigone herself is the poem The Tragic Marginalization of Slavery (Albany:
of being unhomely in the proper and supreme SUNY, 2011).
sense and the rendering poetic the potential
9
Elizabeth Wyckoff translates It was a brother,
of human beings for being homely is the not a slave [doulos] who died Antigone
highest vocation of the poet, which Sophocles says to Creon in Sophocles Antigone (1954,
realizes in Antigone. Yet deinon, understood as line 517). See Elizabeth Wyckoff (trans.),
unhomeliness, which is only through human Antigone, in ed. David Grene, Sophocles
beings in general being homely in being I (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press,
is thus named poetically, without being 1991). David Grene and Richmond Lattimore
thoughtfully unfolded (HHTI, 91). This (ed.), The Complete Greek Tragedies (Chicago:
latter task, to unfold the poetic thoughtfully, University of Chicago Press, 1954).
is the philosophers, Heideggers. In this way,
10
F. Storr translates the line The slain man
although Heidegger might appear to privi- was no villain but a brother (353), while
lege the poetic/art, he reinstalls the authority Reginald Gibbons has It was no slaveit
of philosophy over art, making (the female/ was my brother who died. See F.Storr (trans.),
feminine) Antigone encapsulate the mysterious Sophocles in Two Volumes, vol. 1. The Loeb
enigma that the (masculine/male) philosopher Classical Library (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
must articulate theoretically. University Press, 1981). See also Reginald
3
In fact, there is a sense in which tragedy, Gibbons and Charles Segal, Antigone, The
according to Hegel, did not constitute art at all Greek Tragedy in New Translations, eds Peter
for the Greeks, if we bear in mind that art was Burian and Alan Shapiro (Oxford: Oxford
not constituted as occupying an autonomous University Press, 2003).
sphere of its own, as it will come to do so from
11
See HHTI, 118.
the point of view of the modern regime of
12
See ibid., 85.
aesthetics.
13
Aristotle Poetics, Bk. 11, 312, ed. and
4
The relation between ethics (Sittlichkeit) and trans. Stephen Halliwell (Cambridge, MA:
morality (Moralitt) referred to here assumes Harvard University Press, 1995). Longinus
Hegels understanding in the Phenomenology on the Sublime, trans. W. H. Fyfe, revised by
of Spirit rather than the Philosophy of Right, Donald Russell; Demetrius on Style, trans.

448
HEIDEGGER AND GENDER

Doreen C. Innes, based on W. Rhys Roberts. Bringing Antigone Home? Comparative


Loeb Classical Library, Aristotle, vol. 23 Literature Studies, 45.3 (2008), 31640.
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 18
In maintaining that the characters in tragedy
1995). See also G. W. F. Hegels Aesthetics: should be good, and having conceded that
Lectures on Fine Art, trans. T. M. Knox, women and slaves can be good, Aristotle under-
2 vols (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1988), cuts his concession immediately by adding that
vol. I: 464; Vorlesungen ber die sthetik. women are of an inferior class and slaves are
Suhrkamp Taschenbuch Wissenschaft, b. wholly paltry, and then says characters should
1315 (Suhrkamp: Frankfurt am Main, be appropriate, and it is inappropriate for a
1970), b. II: 60. woman to be courageous or clever (andreion e
14
Antigones attachment to the older order of deinen einai) (1995, Bk. 15, 234).
Greek, chthonic gods is thus doubly purified, 19
See Jacques Lacan, The Ethics of
first, as it is made to give way to a new order Psychoanalysis 19591960: The Seminar
of Olympian gods, with whom Creon is associ- of Jacques Lacan, ed. Jacques-Alain Miller,
ated, then by the way in which Greek polythe- Book VII, trans. Dennis Porter (New York:
ism is made to play the role of precursor to Tavistock/Routledge, 1992). It would be worth
Hegels Christianity, a religion that provides asking how Freuds reflections on the uncanny
the Trinitarian structure of Hegels system of might play into Lacans consideration, and
thought. even how those reflections constitute a cultural
15
As critics such as Jean-Pierre Vernant have (if repudiated) background for Heideggers
suggested, putting a slightly different twist on discussions. But that is another paper.
Hegels point by seeing tragedy as a critical 20
Shortly before Aristotle proclaims it inappro-
inflection of norms, tragic performances were priate for women to be characterized as coura-
one of the mechanisms by which the Athenian geous, in the only direct reference to Antigone
polis put itself on trial and was able to under- of the Poetics (though he refers to the play
take a critical examination of its tensions. elsewhere), he discusses what incidents are ter-
See Jean-Pierre Vernant, Myth and Society in rible or pitiable (1995, 75), using the plot of
Ancient Greece, trans. Janet Lloyd (New York: Antigone as an example of the worst kind of
Zone Books, 1990). plot, where a character is about to act know-
16
Hence, for Hegel, Oedipus Rex, which is more ingly, yet does not do so (77). The reference
concerned with self-reflective knowledge, is is to Haemon and Creon, specifically, in the
almost a modern tragedy, while Antigone is words of the editor, Henderson, to Haemons
more reflective of Greek ethical customs. abortive attempt to kill his father (ibid.).

17
While Heidegger discusses politics in his con- 21
See GA 40, 114/IM, 159.
sideration of Antigone, the gesture is only to 22
Derrida, Geschlecht II: Heideggers Hand.
distance himself from the idea that everything 23
Thomson also draws a connection between
is political, and to inflect the notion of the polis PLT and Heideggers discussion of death in
in the direction of the hearth (see HHTI, 104). Antigones the choral ode in the Introduction
As Valerie Reed points out, despite his preoc- of Metaphysics (IM, 756). See Iain D.
cupation with the senses in which Antigone Thomson, Heidegger, Art, and Postmodernity
is both at home and not at home, Heideggers (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
discussion betrays a conspicuous lack of atten- 2001). See also Heideggers discussion of the
tion to the notion of oikos. See Valerie Reed, uncanny in PLT.

449
56
HEIDEGGER AND POST-CARTESIAN
PSYCHOANALYSIS
Robert D. Stolorow

The aim of this chapter is to show how and to illuminate the phenomenology of the
Heideggers1 existential philosophy enriches psychoanalytic process itself. Our dedication
post-Cartesian psychoanalysis and vice versa. to phenomenological inquiry, in turn, led us
Binswanger and Boss were two early pioneers to a contextualist theoretical perspective, for
who saw the value of Heideggers analysis of which we subsequently found philosophical
existence for psychotherapy and psychoa- support in Heideggers existential analytic.
nalysis. They both proceeded from the top
downthat is, they started with Heideggers
philosophical delineation of essential exis-
tential structures and applied these to clini- Investigative Method
cal phenomena and the therapeutic situation.
Although Binswangers existential analysis Post-Cartesian psychoanalytic method is
produced some brilliant phenomenological characterized by three closely interrelated
descriptions of the world-designs2 under- features. It is phenomenologicalits focus
lying various forms of psychopathology, and is on worlds of emotional experience. It is
Bosss3 Dasein analysis freed the psycho- hermeneuticit seeks interpretively to illu-
analytic theory of therapy from the dehu- minate the structures of meaning that prere-
manizing causal-mechanistic assumptions flectively organize such worlds of emotional
of Freudian metapsychology, neither effort experience. And it is contextualit grasps
brought about a radicalization of psychoana- emotional experience and its horizons as
lytic practice itself or of the psychoanalytic being constituted within formative relational
process. contexts. Heideggers investigative method
The evolution of what my collaborators in Being and Time is also a unique blend-
and I call post-Cartesian psychoanalysis,4 by ing of phenomenology, hermeneutics, and
contrast, proceeded from the bottom up. contextualism and thus holds great potential
Born of our studies of the subjective origins of for providing a philosophical grounding for
psychoanalytic theories,5 it developed out of post-Cartesian psychoanalysis.
our concurrent efforts to rethink psychoanal- What enables Heidegger to investigate his
ysis as a form of phenomenological inquiry subject matter, the question of the meaning

451
HEIDEGGER AND POST-CARTESIAN PSYCHOANALYSIS

of Being,6 phenomenologically? In my read- or thematizing its as-structure9for


ing, it is his choice of the inquirer, Dasein, as example, our intelligibility to ourselves as
the right entity to be interrogated as to its the human beings we are. Against Husserl,
Beingthat is, as to its intelligibility to itself Heidegger insists, All interpretation . . .
as a human beingthat enables him to do operates in the fore-structure,10 the system
so. And this is so because: of presuppositions that make up the interpre-
tive perspective the interpreter brings to the
Dasein . . . is ontically distinguished by act of interpreting.
the fact that, in its very Being, that Being I see Heideggers own interpretive perspec-
is an issue for it.. . . [Thus] there is some tive as a contextualist one, crystallizing con-
way in which Dasein understands itself
trapuntally from his ongoing dialogue with
in its Being.7
the philosophers of traditional metaphys-
ics and epistemologymost prominently,
Because this human kind of Being (existence) Descartes. This feature of Heideggers thought
comports itself understandingly toward that is of central importance for post-Cartesian
Being,8 and an unthematized, pre-ontological psychoanalysis.
understanding of our Being is constitutive of
our kind of Being, we humans can investigate
our own kind of Being by investigating our
understanding (and lack of understanding) Contextualism: From
of that Being. Accordingly, it follows that Mind to World
Heideggers investigative method is to be a
phenomenological one, aimed at illuminat- In Descartes11 metaphysical dualism, mind
ing the fundamental structures of our under- is ontologically isolated from the world in
standing of our Being. which it dwells, just as the world is purged of
Heidegger points out, however, that the all human significance, and both are beheld
search for phenomenological access to our in their bare thinghood. Traditional Freudian
kind of Being in our understanding of that theory is pervaded by the Cartesian myth
Being is a complicated one because, in both of the isolated mind,12 which bifurcates
our traditional philosophical and our aver- the experiential world into inner and outer
age everyday understanding of Being, Being regions, severs both mind from body and cog-
can be extensively covered up and disguised. nition from affect, reifies and absolutizes the
Therefore, our Being that is covered up in resulting divisions, and pictures the mind as
our understanding of it must be laid bare an objective entity that takes its place among
by means of interpretation of that under- other objects, a thinking thing that has an
standing. Accordingly, Heideggers analytic inside with contents and that looks out on an
of Dasein is a hermeneutic phenomenology external world from which it is essentially
aimed at disclosing or unconcealing the basic estranged. Freuds psychoanalysis greatly
structures of our kind of Being, its existen- expanded the Cartesian mind to include a
tiality, which lie hidden within our under- vast unconscious realm. Nevertheless, the
standing of it. Freudian psyche remained a Cartesian mind,
For Heidegger, interpreting what is under- a self-enclosed mental apparatus containing
stood means explicitly articulating, unveiling, and working over mental contents, a thinking

452
HEIDEGGER AND POST-CARTESIAN PSYCHOANALYSIS

thing that, precisely because it is a thing, is significance. In light of this fundamental con-
ontologically decontextualized, fundamen- textualization, Heideggers consideration of
tally separated from its world. Post-Cartesian affectivity is especially noteworthy.
psychoanalysis, by contrast, is a phenomeno-
logical contextualism that investigates and
illuminates emotional experience as it takes
form within constitutive relational contexts. From Drive to Affectivity
From a post-Cartesian perspective, all the
phenomena that have been the focus of psy- Heideggers term for the existential ground
choanalytic investigation are grasped not as of affectivity (feelings and moods) is
products of isolated intrapsychic mechanisms Befindlichkeit. Literally, the word might be
but as forming within systems constituted by translated as howonefinds-oneselfness.
interacting worlds of emotional experience. As Gendlin15 has pointed out, Heideggers
This phenomenological contextualism finds word for the structure of affectivity denotes
solid philosophical grounding in Heideggers both how one feels and the situation within
ontological contextualism. which one is feeling, a felt sense of oneself
In his hermeneutic of Dasein, Heidegger in a situation, prior to a Cartesian split
seeks interpretively to refind the unity of our between inside and outside. Befindlichkeit
Being, split asunder in the Cartesian bifurca- is disclosive of our always already hav-
tion. His contextualism is formally indicated ing been delivered over to the situatedness
early on, in his designation of the human in which we find ourselves. The concept of
being as Dasein, to-be-there or to-be-situated, Befindlichkeitdisclosive affectivityunder-
a term that already points to the unity of the scores the exquisite context-dependence and
human kind of Being and its context. This context-sensitivity of emotional experience,
initially indicated contextualization is further a context-embeddedness that takes on enor-
fleshed out as Heidegger focuses his inquiry mous importance in view of post-Cartesian
on our average everyday understanding of psychoanalysis placing of affectivity at the
our kind of Being. His aim is to lay bare motivational center of human psychological
a fundamental structure in Dasein: Being-in- life.
the-world,13 Daseins constitutive state.14 It is a central tenet of post-Cartesian psy-
With the hyphens unifying the expres- choanalysis that a shift in psychoanalytic
sion Being-in-the-world (In-der-Welt-sein), thinking from the motivational primacy of
Heidegger indicates that in his interpretation instinctual drive to the motivational primacy
of Dasein the traditional ontological gap of affectivity moves psychoanalysis toward
between our Being and our world is to be a phenomenological contextualism and a
definitively closed and that, in their indissol- central focus on dynamic relational systems.
uble unity, our Being and our world always Unlike drives, which in Freudian psychoanal-
already contextualize one another. His ana- ysis were claimed to originate deep within the
lytic of Dasein unveils the basic structure of interior of a Cartesian isolated mind, affec-
our human kind of Being as a rich contex- tivity is something that from birth onward
tual whole, in which human Being is satu- is co-constituted within ongoing relational
rated with the world in which we dwell, and systems. Therefore, locating affect at their
the world we inhabit is drenched in human motivational center automatically entails

453
HEIDEGGER AND POST-CARTESIAN PSYCHOANALYSIS

a radical contextualization of virtually all us that entities within-the-world are not rel-
aspects of human psychological life and of evant at all. . . . [The world] collapses into
the psychoanalytic process. Nowhere is this itself [and] has the character of completely
contextualization seen more clearly than in lacking significance.20 Heidegger makes
the understanding of emotional trauma. clear that it is the significance of the average
everyday world, the world as constituted by
the public interpretedness of the they (das
Man), whose collapse is disclosed in anxiety.
Trauma, Anxiety, Finitude Furthermore, insofar as the utter insignifi-
cance21 of the everyday world is disclosed in
From a post-Cartesian perspective, develop- anxiety, anxiety includes a feeling of uncan-
mental trauma is viewed, not as an instinc- niness, in the sense of not-being-at-home.22
tual flooding of an ill-equipped Cartesian In anxiety, the experience of Being-at-home
container, as Freud16 would have it, but as an [in ones tranquilized] everyday familiarity23
experience of unbearable affect. Furthermore, with the publicly interpreted world collapses,
the intolerability of affect states can be fully and Being-in enters into the existential
grasped only in terms of the relational sys- mode of. . . uncanniness.24
tems in which they are felt. Developmental In Heideggers ontological account of
trauma originates within a formative rela- anxiety, the central features of its phe-
tional context whose central feature is malat- nomenologythe collapse of everyday
tunement to painful affectthe absence of significance and the resulting feeling of
a context of human understanding in which uncanninessare claimed to be grounded in
that pain can be held and endured. Without what he calls authentic (nonevasively owned)
such a relational home for the childs emo- Being-toward-death. Existentially, death is
tional pain, it can only be felt as unbear- not simply an event that has not yet occurred
able, overwhelming, disorganizing. Painful or that happens to others, as das Man would
or frightening affect becomes lastingly trau- have it. Rather, it is a distinctive possibil-
matic when the attunement that the child ity that is constitutive of our existenceof
needs to assist in its tolerance and integration our intelligibility to ourselves in our futurity
is profoundly absent. and our finitude. It is the possibility of the
In addition to providing ontological ground- impossibility of any existence at all,25 which,
ing for traumas context-embeddedness, because it is both certain and indefinite as to
Heideggers existential philosophyin par- its when, always impends as a constant
ticular, his existential analysis of anxiety threat, robbing us of the tranquilizing illu-
enables us to grasp traumas existential sions that characterize our absorption in the
significance. Like Freud, Heidegger makes a everyday world, nullifying its significance for
sharp distinction between fear and anxiety. us. The appearance of anxiety indicates that
Whereas, according to Heidegger, that in the the fundamental defensive purpose (flee-
face of which one fears is a definite entity ing) of average everydayness has failed and
within-the-world,17 that in the face of which that authentic Being-toward-death has bro-
one is anxious is completely indefinite18 ken through the evasions that conceal it. Torn
and turns out to be Being-in-the-world as from the sheltering illusions of das Man, we
such.19 The indefiniteness of anxiety tells feel uncannyno longer safely at home.

454
HEIDEGGER AND POST-CARTESIAN PSYCHOANALYSIS

I have contended26 that emotional trauma we meet each other as brothers and sisters
produces an affective state whose features in the same dark night,27 deeply connected
bear a close similarity to the central ele- with one another in virtue of our common
ments in Heideggers existential interpreta- finitude. Thus, although the possibility of
tion of anxiety and that it accomplishes this emotional trauma is ever present, so too
by plunging the traumatized person into is the possibility of forming bonds of deep
a form of authentic Being-toward-death. emotional attunement within which devas-
Trauma shatters the illusions of everyday life tating emotional pain can be held, endured,
that evade and cover up the finitude, contin- and eventually integrated. Our existential
gency, and embeddedness of our existence kinship-in-the-same-darkness is the condi-
and the indefiniteness of its certain extinc- tion for the possibility both of the profound
tion. Such shattering exposes what had been contextuality of emotional trauma and of the
heretofore concealed, thereby plunging the mutative power of human understanding.
traumatized person into a form of authentic Critchley points the way toward a second,
Being-toward-death and into the anxiety essential dimension of the relationality of
the loss of significance, the uncanniness finitude:
through which authentic Being-toward-death
is disclosed. Trauma, like death, individual- I would want to [emphasize] the funda-
izes us, in a manner that invariably manifests mentally relational character of finitude,
in an excruciating sense of singularity and namely that death is first and foremost
experienced as a relation to the death
solitude.
or dying of the other and others, in
Being-with the dying in a caring way,
and in grieving after they are dead.. . .
[O]ne watches the person one loves . . . die
The Relationality of Finitude and become a lifeless material thing . . .
[T]here is a thinga corpseat the heart
It is implicit in Heideggers ontological of the experience of finitude.. . . [which
account that authentic existing presupposes is] fundamentally relational.28
a capacity to dwell in the emotional pain
the existential anxietythat accompanies Authentic Being-toward-death entails own-
a nonevasive owning up to human fini- ing up not only to ones own finitude but
tude. It follows from my claims about the also to the finitude of all those we love.
context-embeddedness of emotional trauma Hence, authentic Being-toward-death always
that this capacity entails that such pain can includes Being-toward-loss as a central con-
find a relational home in which it can be stituent. Just as, existentially, we are always
held. What makes such dwelling and holding dying already,29 so too are we always
possible? already grieving. Death and loss are exis-
Vogel provides a compelling answer to tentially equiprimordial. Existential anxiety
this question by elaborating what he claims anticipates both death and loss.
to be a relational dimension of the experi- Support for my claim about the equipri-
ence of finitude. Just as finitude is funda- mordiality of death and loss can be found
mental to our existential constitution, so in the work of Derrida,30 who contends
too is it constitutive of our existence that that every friendship is structured from its

455
HEIDEGGER AND POST-CARTESIAN PSYCHOANALYSIS

beginning, a priori, by the possibility that it. So if we are to leap ahead33 of the other,
one of the two friends will die first and that freeing him or her for his or her ownmost
the surviving friend will be left to mourn: possibilities, we must also free him or her
To have a friend, to look at him, to follow for an authentic Being-toward-death and
him with your eyes, . . . is to know in a more for a readiness for the anxiety that discloses
intense way, already injured, . . . that one of it. Therefore, according to my claims about
the two of you will inevitably see the other the contextuality of emotional life, we must
die.31 Finitude and the possibility of mourn- Be-withthat is, attune tothe others exis-
ing are constitutive of every friendship. tential anxiety and other painful affect states
In loss, all possibilities for Being in rela- disclosive of his or her finitude, thereby pro-
tion to the lost loved one are extinguished. viding these feelings with a relational home in
Traumatic loss shatters ones emotional which they can be held, so that he or she can
world, and, insofar as one dwells in the seize upon his or her ownmost possibilities
region of such loss, one feels eradicated. As in the face of them. Authentic solicitudea
Derrida claims, [D]eath takes from us not central component of friendship, love, and a
only some particular life within the world therapeutic attitudecan be shown to entail
[but] someone through whom the world, one of the constitutive dimensions of deep
and first of all our own world, will have human bonding, in which we value the alter-
opened up.32 ity of the other as it is manifested in his or
her own distinctive affectivity.

Expanding Heideggers
Conception of Relationality Conclusions: The Ontical and
the Ontological
Authentic relationality or Being-with
(Mitsein) is largely restricted in Heideggers Post-Cartesian psychoanalysis and Heideggers
philosophy to a form of solicitude existential philosophy are both forms of
(Frsorge) that welcomes and encourages phenomenological inquiry. Post-Cartesian
the others individualized selfhood. Here I psychoanalysis is an ontical discipline; it
wish to expand Heideggers conception of investigates and illuminates the struc-
authentic solicitude by showing that it entails tures that prereflectively organize the lived
the existential kinship-in-finitude that I, emotional worlds of actual particular per-
along with Vogel, claim is constitutive of our sons, along with the specific relational
Being-with one another. contexts in which these structures take
Authentic solicitude, in Heideggers form. Heideggers existential analytic is an
account, frees the other to exist authentically, ontological inquiry; it lays bare the neces-
for the sake of his or her ownmost possibili- sary and universal structures (existentiales)
ties of Being. But recall that, for Heidegger, that, a priori, constitute the human kind of
being free for ones ownmost possibilities Being (existence)our intelligibility to our-
also always means being free for ones utter- selves as human beings. I have shown that
most possibilitythe possibility of death a psychoanalytic phenomenological con-
and for the existential anxiety that discloses textualism finds philosophical grounding

456
HEIDEGGER AND POST-CARTESIAN PSYCHOANALYSIS

in Heideggers ontological contextualism In the lecture course, Heidegger discusses a


and that the psychoanalytic understand- number of such ground moods that make
ing of emotional trauma is greatly enriched philosophizing possible: anxiety, homesick-
by an encounter with Heideggers elucida- ness, turbulence, boredom, melancholy. In
tion of the structures of authentic existing. later works he emphasizes other ontologi-
How did Heidegger view the role of ontical cally revelatory ground moods, such as awe,
phenomena in the illumination of ontologi- wonder, and astonishment.41
cal or existential structures, and how can I cannot recall ever encountering a refer-
grasping the interplay of the ontical and ence to the mood of shame in Heideggers
the ontological contribute to an enrichment philosophical work. It is my view that, just
of Heideggers existential philosophy by as existential anxiety is disclosive of authen-
post-Cartesian psychoanalysis? tic existing, it is shame that most clearly dis-
Answers to these questions can be found closes inauthentic or unowned existing. In
in the central role that Heidegger gives to feeling ashamed, we feel exposed as deficient
moods (affectivity) in the disclosure of our or defective before the gaze of the other.42
Being-in-the-world: [O]ntologically mood In shame, we are held hostage by the eyes
is a primordial kind of Being for Dasein, in of others, belonging not to ourselves but to
which Dasein is disclosed to itself prior to them. Thus, a move toward greater authen-
all cognition and volition.34 Mood discloses ticity, toward a taking ownership of ones
Daseins thrownness . . . into its there;35 it existing, is often accompanied by an emo-
discloses Being-in-the-world as a whole;36 tional shift from being dominated by shame
and it discloses how what [Dasein] encoun- to an embracing of existential guilt, anxiety,
ters within-the-world can matter to it.37 and anticipatory grief. This is a shift from a
Elkholy emphasizes that, for Heidegger, preoccupation with how one is seen by oth-
[M]ood, especially the mood of Angst, has ers to a pursuit of what really matters to one
the power to reveal the . . . whole of how one as an individual, including the quality of
is in the world and the whole of the world at ones relatedness to others.
large.38 Thus for Heidegger, ontical experi- It is precisely here that an encounter with
ences of certain moods are ontologically rev- post-Cartesian psychoanalysis has the poten-
elatory. Anxiety, in particular, is grasped as tial of enriching Heideggers existential phi-
a bridge to the truth of Being39from the losophy, in that post-Cartesian psychoanalysis
ontical or psychological to the ontological. gives an account of the relational contexts that
In his 192930 lecture course, Heidegger make it possible for one to dwell in and bear
makes a truly remarkable claim regarding the painful emotional experiences, the ground
ontologically revelatory moods, which he moods, that are revelatory of authentic exist-
calls ground moods (Grundstimmungen) or ing. Experiencing our kinship-in-finitude
fundamental attunements: with one another, thereby finding a relational
home or context of human understanding
Philosophy in each case happens in a fun- in which the traumatizing emotional impact
damental attunement. Conceptual philo- of our finitude and the finitude of those we
sophical comprehension is grounded in love can be held, brought into dialogue, and
our being gripped, and this is grounded integrated, helps make authentic existen-
in a fundamental attunement.40 tial philosophizing possible. Post-Cartesian

457
HEIDEGGER AND POST-CARTESIAN PSYCHOANALYSIS

psychoanalysis illuminates the rich relation- 17


BTMR, 231.
ality of authentic existing.
18
Ibid.
19
Ibid., 230.
20
Ibid., 231.
21
Ibid.
NOTES AND REFERENCES 22
Ibid., 233.
23
Ibid.
1
BTMR.
24
Ibid.
2
L. Binswanger, The Existential Analysis School
25
Ibid., 307.
of Thought, trans. E. Angel, in eds R.May,
26
R, Stolorow, Trauma and Human Existence:
E.Angel, and H. Ellenberger, Existence: A New Autobiographical, Psychoanalytic, and
Dimension in Psychiatry and Psychology (New Philosophical Reflections (New York:
York: Basic Books, 1958), 195. Routledge, 2007).
3
M. Boss, Psychoanalysis and Daseinanalysis,
27
L. Vogel, The Fragile We: Ethical
trans. L. Lefebre (New York: Basic Books, 1963). Implications of Heideggers Being and Time
4
R. Stolorow, World, Affectivity, Trauma: (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press,
Heidegger and Post-Cartesian Psychoanalysis 1994), 97.
(New York: Routledge, 2011).
28
S. Critchley, Enigma Variations: An
5
R. Stolorow and G. Atwood, Faces in a Cloud: Interpretation of Heideggers Sein und Zeit,
Subjectivity in Personality Theory (Northvale, Ratio, 15 (2002), 16970.
NJ: Jason Aronson, 1979).
29
BTMR, 298.
6
BTMR, 19.
30
J. Derrida, Politics of Friendship, trans. G.
7
Ibid., 32. Collins (New York: Verso, 1997).
8
Ibid., 78.
31
J. Derrida, The Work of Mourning, ed. P.-A.
9
Ibid., 190. Brault and M. Naas (Chicago: University of
10
Ibid., 194. Chicago Press, 2001), 107.
11
R. Descartes, Meditations (Buffalo, NY:
32
Ibid.
Prometheus Books, 1989).
33
BTMR, 158.
12
R. Stolorow and G. Atwood, Contexts of
34
Ibid., 175.
Being: The Intersubjective Foundations of
35
Ibid., 174.
Psychological Life (Hillsdale, NJ: Analytic
36
Ibid., 176.
Press, 1992), 7.
37
Ibid.
13
BTMR, 65.
38
S. Elkholy, Heidegger and a Metaphysics
14
Ibid., 78. of Feeling: Angst and the Finitude of Being
15
E. Gendlin, Befindlichkeit: Heidegger and the (London and New York: Continuum,
Philosophy of Psychology, in ed. K. Hoeller, 2008),4.
Heidegger and Psychology (Seattle, WA:
39
Ibid., 7.
Review of Existential Psychology & Psychiatry,
40
FCM, 7.
1988), 4371.
41
R. Capobianco, Engaging Heidegger (Toronto:
16
S. Freud, Inhibitions, Symptoms, and Anxiety, University of Toronto Press, 2010).
standard edn, vol. 20 (London: Hogarth Press,
42
J.-P. Sartre, Being and Nothingness, trans.
1959). H.Barnes (New York: Citadel Press, 2001).

458
HEIDEGGER AND ASIAN PHILOSOPHY

Heidegger-Jahrbuch 7: Heidegger und das Nishitani Keiji] (Tokyo: Sbunsha, 1998),


ostasiatische Denken (Freiburg/Munich: Alber 18990, 201. Note that Chinese and Japanese
Verlag, forthcoming). names will generally be written in the order
4
Rolf Elberfeld, Heidegger und das ostasia- of family name first, except in cases where the
tische Denken: Annherungen zwischen frem- Western order has been used for publications
den Welten, in ed. Dieter Thom, Heidegger in Western languages.
Handbuch: Leben-Werk-Wirkung (Stuttgart: 10
Tomonobu Imamichi, In Search of Wisdom:
Metzler, 2003), 469. Unless otherwise noted, One Philosophers Journey (Tokyo: LTCB
all translations in this chapter are my own. I International Library, 2004), 123.
have marked tm where I have modified exist- 11
Okakura Tenshin, Cha no hon/The Book
ing translations. of Tea (a bilingual edition), trans. Asano
5
From Gadamers personal correspondence with Akira (Tokyo: Kodansha, 1998), 923; see
Graham Parkes, as related in the introduction also Dennis Hirota, Okakura Tenshins
to Graham Parkes (ed.), Heidegger and Asian Conception of Being in the World, Rykoku
Thought (Honolulu: University of Hawaii Daigaku Ronsh, 478 (2011), 11, 31. I will
Press, 1987), 5, 7. This landmark collection cite the Daodejing and the Zhuangzi by chap-
will hereafter be cited as HAT. ter number. Reliable translations include The
6
Nagley, Introduction to the symposium and Daodejing of Laozi, trans. Philip J. Ivanhoe
reading of a letter from Martin Heidegger, (Indianapolis: Hackett, 2003) and Zhuangzi:
221. See also GA 9, 424/PA, 321, as well as The Essential Writings, trans. Brook Ziporyn
Heideggers statement quoted in Willfred (Indianapolis: Hackett, 2009).
Hartig, Die Lehre des Buddha und Heidegger: 12
Heinrich Wiegand Petzet, Encounters &
Beitrge zum Ost-West-Dialog des Denkens Dialogues with Martin Heidegger 19291976,
im 20. Jahrhundert (Konstanz: Universitt trans. Parvis Emad and Kenneth Maly (Chicago:
Konstanz, 1997), 1516. Hartigs book, which University of Chicago Press, 1993), 18.
collects much of Heideggers correspondence 13
See the final section of my Heideggers
and reported statements regarding Asian phi- Orientations.
losophy, will hereafter be cited as LBH. 14
See the chapter by Yasuo Yuasa in HAT; the
7
The most important collections are Heidegger chapter by Rysuke hashi in JH; Parkess
and Eastern Thought, Philosophy East and Rising Sun over Black Forest; and Mine
West 20.3 (1970); HAT; Hartmut Buchner Hideki, Haidegg to nihon no tetsugaku:
(ed.), Japan und Heidegger (Sigmaringen: Watsuji Tetsur, Kuki Shz, Tanabe Hajime
Thorbecke, 1989); LBH; and Denker (ed.), [Heidegger and Japanese Philosophy: Watsuji
Heidegger-Jahrbuch 7: Heidegger und das osta- Tetsur, Kuki Shz, Tanabe Hajime] (Kyoto:
siatische Denken. Buchners collection, which Minerva, 2002). While the most prevalent
includes significant texts by Japanese philoso- and sustained Asian responses to Heideggers
phers as well as correspondence and dialogues thought have been in Japan, there have also
with Heidegger, will hereafter be abbreviated been important responses made by philoso-
as JH. phers from India (such as J. L. Mehta), China
8
Above all Reinhard May, Heideggers Hidden (such as Chang Chung-yuan), and Korea (such
Sources: East Asian Influences on His Work, as Park Chong-Hong, Ha Ki-Rak, and Cho
trans. with a complementary essay by Graham Kah Kyung).
Parkes (New York: Routledge, 1996); and 15
Watsuji Tetsur, Watsuji Tetsurs Rinrigaku:
Graham Parkes, Rising Sun over Black Ethics in Japan, trans. Yamamoto Seisaku and
Forest: Heideggers Japanese Connections, in Robert Carter (Albany: SUNY Press, 1996).
Reinhard May, Heideggers Hidden Sources: 16
Watsuji Tetsuro, Climate and Culture: A
East Asian Influences on His Work (New York: Philosophical Study, trans. Geoffry Bownas
Routledge, 1996), 79117. This volume will (New York: Greenwood Press, 1988).
hereafter be cited as HHS. 17
See Mine, Haidegg to nihon no tetsugaku, 43,
9
Ban Kazunori, Kaky kara hanarezu: Nishitani 14852, 250, 331.
Keiji sensei tokubetsu kgi [Without Departing 18
Graham Parkes, Heidegger and Japanese
from Home: Special Lectures of Professor Thought: How Much Did He Know and When

469
HEIDEGGER AND ASIAN PHILOSOPHY

Did He Know It? in ed. Christopher McCann, 25


Quoted in Ma, Heidegger on East-West
Martin Heidegger: Critical Assessments (New Dialogue, 238. See also JH, 166.
York: Routledge 1992), vol. 4, 394. 26
Petzet, Encounters & Dialogues with Martin

19
See hashi Rysuke, Nishida-tetsugaku no Heidegger, 180; see also GA 16, 592.
sekai [The World of Nishidas Philosophy] 27
William Barret, Introduction to Selected
(Tokyo: Chikumashob, 1995), 17998; Elmar Writings of D. T. Suzuki (New York:
Weinmayr, Thinking in Transition: Nishida Doubleday, 1996), xi.
Kitar and Martin Heidegger, trans. John W. 28
Hseki Shinichi Hisamatsu, Die Flle des
M. Krummel, Philosophy East and West, 55.2 Nichts: Vom Wesen des Zen, trans. Takashi
(2005), 23256; and John W. M. Krummel, Hirata and Johanna Fischer (Stuttgart: Neske,
The Originary Wherein: Heidegger and 1994).
Nishida on the Sacred and the Religious, 29
See Bret W. Davis, Forms of Emptiness in
Research in Phenomenology, 40 (2010), Zen, in ed. Steven Emmanuel, A Companion
378407. to Buddhist Philosophy (Hoboken:

20
HHS, 323; see also Gnter Wohlfart, Der Wiley-Blackwell, 2013), 190213.
Philosophische Daoismus: Philosophische 30
Zenkei Shibayama, The Gateless Barrier:
Untersuchungen zu Grundbegriffen und Zen Comments on the Mumonkan (Boston:
komparative Studien mit besonderer Shambhala, 2000), 1920.
Bercksichtigung des Laozi (Lao-tse) (Kln: 31
See Bret W. Davis, Heidegger and the Will:
edition chra, 2001), 66. On the Way to Gelassenheit (Evanston:

21
Mori Hideki, Dka ni okeru mu no Northwestern University Press, 2007), 569.
tetsugaku [The Philosophy of Nothingness 32
Nishitani Keiji, Shky to wa nanika [What
in Daoist Thinkers], Nihon no tetsugaku is Religion?], Nishitani Keiji chosakush
[Japanese Philosophy], 5 (2004), 356. [Collected Works of Nishitani Keiji] (Tokyo:

22
Already in Being and Time (1927) Heidegger Sbunsha, 1987), vol. 10, 108; Nishitani Keiji,
writes of Angst as bringing Dasein face to Religion and Nothingness, trans. Jan Van
face with the nothingness of [death as] the Bragt (Berkeley: University of California Press,
possible impossibility of its existence and 1982), 96 tm.
of the nothingness of the world especially 33
Ueda Shizuteru, Basho: Nij-sekai-nai-sonzai
when it has sunk into insignificance (SZ, [Place: Being-in-the-Twofold-World] (Tokyo:
265, 343; see also 187, 308). Shortly thereaf- Kbund, 1992), 59; see also Davis, Heidegger
ter, in 1928, Heidegger writes more positively and the Will, 57.
of the world as a nihil originarium, that 34
See Bret W. Davis, The Step Back Through
is, as the nothing which temporalizes itself Nihilism: The Radical Orientation of
primordially (GA 26, 272/MFL, 210). In later Nishitani Keijis Philosophy of Zen, Synthesis
texts, it remains for Heidegger our mortal- Philosophica, 37 (2004), 13959.
ity that opens us up to being as the nothing. 35
JH, 15965; Kichi Tsujimura, Martin
The nothing, as other than beings, is the veil Heideggers Thinking and Japanese
of being (GA 9, 312/PA, 238); and death is Philosophy, trans. Richard Capobianco and
the shrine of the nothing (VA, 171/PLT, 176) Marie Gbel, Epoch, 12.2 (2008), 34957.
insofar as our experience of mortality frees 36
Tsujimura Kichi, Haidegg ronk [Heidegger
us from our fallenness in running around Studies] (Tokyo: Sbunsha, 1971), 905; see
amidst beings (GA 9, 116/PA, 92) and opens also Davis, Heidegger and the Will, 358, 315
us up to the no-thing of being. Death is the n. 14.
purest nearness of the human to being (and 37
Tsujimura, Haidegg ronk, 445; Kichi
therefore to the nothing) (GA 71, 194). Tsujimura, Die Wahrheit des Seins und das

23
Note that the etymology of Nichts is similar to absolute Nichts, trans. Daisuke Shimizu and
that of no-thing; see NIV, 1819. Ursula Baatz, in ed. Rysuke hashi, Die

24
See Wohlfart, Der Philosophische Daoismus, Philosophie der Kyto-Schule, 2nd edition
chapter 2. (Freiburg/Munich: Alber Verlag, 2010), 414.

470
HEIDEGGER AND ASIAN PHILOSOPHY

38
Tsujimura Kichi, Haidegg no shisaku 41
Nishitani, Shky to wa nanika, 1701, 178,
[Heideggers Thought] (Tokyo: Sbunsha, 186; Nishitani, Religion and Nothingness,
1991), 203. 1512, 158, 166.
39
Tsujimura, Haidegg ronk, 448; Tsujimura, 42
Nishida Kitar zensh [Complete Works of
Die Wahrheit des Seins und das absolute Nishida Kitar] (Tokyo: Iwanami: 19879),
Nichts, 41318; see also Tsujimura, Haidegg vol. 11, 418, 433, 445.
no shisaku, 35960. 43
Ibid., 399.
40
Kichi Tsujimura, Ereignis und Shki: 44
JH, 165; Tsujimura, Martin Heideggers
Zur bersetzung eines heideggerschen Thinking and Japanese Philosophy, 355; also
Grundwortes ins Japanische, in JH, 82. Tsujimura, Haidegg ronk, 53; Tsujimura,

471
57
HEIDEGGER AND ASIAN PHILOSOPHY
Bret W. Davis

On the Way to the Inevitable Yet, despite the profound interest in


Dialogue Daoism and Zen he often revealed to col-
leagues and visitors, Heideggers published
Again and again it has seemed urgent references to Asian philosophies are frus-
to me that a dialogue take place with tratingly few. Gadamer, who has said that
the thinkers of what is to us the Eastern Heidegger studies would do well to pur-
world. Heidegger wrote these lines in sue seriously comparisons of his work with
1969 in a letter to Albert Borgmann,
Asian philosophies, tells us that one reason
the director of a conference held at the
may be that Heidegger was hesitant to refer
University of Hawaii on the theme of
Heidegger and Eastern Thought.1 Since to a thought he could not read in the origi-
that time, Heideggers relation to Asian nal language.5 Heidegger himself stated in his
philosophies, and to Daoism and Zen in letter to Borgmann that, despite the urgency
particular, has been the subject of much for dialogue with the East, the greatest dif-
commentary and controversy. While ficulty in this enterprise always lies, as far
some have contended that Heidegger as I can see, in the fact that with few excep-
was an inveterate Eurocentrist,2 oth- tions there is no command of the Eastern
ers have extolled his efforts to clear a languages either in Europe or in the United
pathway toward what he called the States.6 Heidegger frequently expressed such
inevitable dialogue with the East Asian
caution and concern about hisand our
world (VA, 43/QCT, 158), a dialogue
ability to understand Asian languages well
which would enable the development
of a radically intertraditional discourse enough to engage in a dialogue with Asian
of planetary thinking (GA 9, 424/PA, philosophies. The alterity of East Asian lan-
321).3 In fact, Heidegger demonstrated guages in particular was largely responsible
a lifelong interest in engaging in such both for his attraction to East Asian thought
dialogue. It is not without justification as harboring possible alternatives to Western
that Rolf Elberfeld claims: Heidegger metaphysics, and for his wariness regarding
is the first great European thinker . . . our ability to understand it without assimi-
whose entire path of thought has been lating it into Western concepts (GA 12, 85,
accompanied by dialogues with Asian 98/OWL, 4, 15; GA 79, 1456; LBH, 29).
philosophers.4
Indeed, Heidegger would be suspicious
of the very title of this chapter, given that he

459
HEIDEGGER AND ASIAN PHILOSOPHY

stated, on more than one occasion, that there prosecutorial manner) by Reinhard May,
is no such thing as Asian philosophy since there exists the following type of anecdotal
philosophy, properly speaking, is quintes- testimony from the eminent Kyoto School
sentially Western (GA 55, 3; WhD, 136/WCT, philosopher, Nishitani Keiji. When Nishitani
224; WIP, 31). However, it is important to was studying in Freiburg between 1937 and
note that his reasons for saying this are very 1939, he presented Heidegger with a copy
different from those who, even today, arro- of the first volume of D. T. Suzukis Essays
gantly and ignorantly presume that only in Zen Buddhism. It turned out Heidegger
Westerners have thought deeply and rigor- had already read and was eager to discuss
ously about fundamental questions. When this book. Nishitani recounted to Graham
Heidegger says that there is no Asian phi- Parkes how Heidegger had given him a
losophy, and that Western philosophy is a standing invitation to come to his house
tautology, he is equating philosophy with on Saturday afternoons to talk about Zen
Western metaphysics, which Heidegger (HHS, 100). He also told Ban Kazunori that
himself is trying to overcome or recover he had often been invited to the Heidegger
from. Hence, he speaks of the end of philos- residence, where he explained quite a lot
ophy and the task of thinking (ZSD, 6180/ about the standpoint of Zen to Heidegger.
BW, 43149), and writes: The thinking that Nishitani even said that, after taking meticu-
is to come is no longer philosophy because it lous notes, Heidegger would himself repeat
thinks more originally than metaphysicsa these ideas in his lectures, only without men-
name identical to philosophy (GA 9, 364/ tioning Zen!9
PA, 276). While one can take issue with his The ex oriente lux may indeed go back
restrictive definition of philosophy, one much further. The term In-der-Welt-sein
can hardly doubt Heideggers interest in and (being-in-the-world), for example, was first
respect for Asian thinking. coined not by Heidegger but rather in the
German translation of Okakura Tenshins
The Book of Tea, a copy of which Heidegger
reportedly received in 1919.10 Okakuras
Indications of Influence on expression being in the world, which
the Way (Dao) appears in a chapter entitled Taoism and
Zennism, was presumably a translation of
While many scholars have pursued fortui- the term chushi (Japanese: shosei) from the
tous parallels and resonances (as well as dif- Zhuangzi (e.g. chapter 9).11 Heidegger was
ferences and dissonances),7 some have more certainly familiar with Martin Bubers 1910
recently argued that the development of edition of the Zhuangzi, at least by 1930,
Heideggers thought itself was profoundly when he refers to chapter 17 of it to eluci-
influenced by his contact with Asian philos- date our being-with others.12 He concludes
ophies.8 While too offhandedly dismissed by his 19445 Country Path Conversations with
some and too eagerly exaggerated by others, a reflection on a passage from chapter 26 of
it would be difficult to deny some degree of the Zhuangzi on the necessity of the unnec-
influence, even if its depth and significance essary (GA 77, 239/CPC, 1567).
remains debatable. Along with the tex- In 1946 Heidegger proposed to cotranslate
tual evidence assembled (albeit in a rather the Daodejing with Paul Shih-yi Hsiao, and,

460
HEIDEGGER AND ASIAN PHILOSOPHY

even though the project was abandoned after for a shared attunement to an originary
eight chapters, this work seems to have left a silence (GA 12, 144 /OWL, 523). Radical
lasting impact on Heidegger (HAT, 93103). crosscultural dialogue would, it is suggested,
In a text from the 1950s, Heidegger went so need to be accompanied by an even more
far as to write: radical diasigetics, a conversing through
silence.13
The Dao could thus be the Way that
moves everything [der alles be-wgende
Weg], that from which we might first be
able to think what reason, mind, mean-
Heideggers Preparation and
ing, logos properlyi.e., from their own
Japanese Engagement
essencemean to say.. . . [M]ethods . . .
are after all merely the runoff of a great
hidden stream, of the Way that moves Heideggers Dialogue on Language was
everything, of the Way that draws every- rather loosely based on actual conversations
thing onto its path. All is Way. (GA 12, he had with Tezuka Tomio and other Japanese
187/OWL 92 tm) visitors. In general, however, Heidegger
remained more committed to preparing for
Eventually giving his own Collected Edition the inevitable dialogue with East Asian
the motto waysnot works, Heidegger thought than to venturing to engage in it him-
must have been intrigued by the fact that self. A dialogue with the Greek thinkers and
dao can mean both way and to say. For their language, he wrote, remains for us the
Heidegger, being comes to appear ever again precondition of the inevitable dialogue with
through the saying (Sagen) in which lan- the East Asian world (VA, 43/QCT, 158).
guage speaks (die Sprache spricht) (GA 12, According to Heidegger, Westerners, that is
30/PLT, 207). Moreover, the ultimate source to say, those whose language and thinking
of this saying remains, for Heidegger as for are determined by the Western sending of
Daoism, unspoken. The Way (dao) that being, are not yet prepared for this encoun-
can be said (ke dao) is not the abiding Way ter. On one occasion he even suggested that
(Daodejing, chapter 1). Heidegger: Perhaps this preparation may take another 300 years
there is concealed in the word Way, dao, the (LBH, 269)!
mystery of all mysteries of thoughtful Saying, Given the swift pace of what Heidegger
if only we let these names return to that in calls the Europeanization of human
them which is unspoken (GA 12, 187/OWL, being and of the earth, which is said to
92 tm). devour the wellsprings of everything
In Heideggers most sustained engage- essential (GA 12, 99/OWL 16), centuries
ment with Asian philosophy, his Dialogue of preparation is not a luxury afforded to
on Language between a Japanese and an Easterners themselves. In his Dialogue
Inquirer (dated 19534, first published on Language Heidegger admonishes the
in 1959), he tentatively suggests that the Japanese to attend to the venerable begin-
entirely different Western and East Asian nings of [their] own thinking rather than
linguistic houses of being may ultimately chasing after the latest news in European
well up from a single source (GA 12, 85, philosophy (GA 12, 124/OWL, 37). Yet,
89/OWL, 5, 8). The dialogue ends by calling in the Spiegel interview of 1966 he claims

461
HEIDEGGER AND ASIAN PHILOSOPHY

that a reversal can be prepared only in beings (Watsuji draws here on the fact that
the same location in the world where the the Japanese word for human being, nin-
modern technological world arose, and ... gen, literally signifies the betweeness of
cannot happen by means of an adoption persons).15 On the other hand, spatial-
of Zen Buddhism or other Eastern expe- ity also indicated for Watsuji our originary
riences of the world (GA 16, 679). Does interconnectedness with the natural environ-
this mean that Easterners should attend ment (in this case he draws on a Japanese
only to their own traditions, even when word, fdo, which implies both climate
these cannot help save the world from the and culture).16 In their own ways, Tanabe
problem of technology? Fortunately, this is and Kuki also criticized Heideggers early
not all Heidegger had to say on the matter. emphasis on temporality at the expense of
Indeed, in the Spiegel interview Heidegger spatiality.17
had already stated: And who of us can As it turns out, Heidegger later recanted
decide whether one day in Russia and in his earlier attempt to derive existential
China ancient traditions of a thinking spatiality from temporality (ZSD, 24/TB,
will awaken which will help enable human 23), and came to think of time and space
being to have a free relationship to the tech- as equiprimordially given in an originary
nical world (GA 16, 677). In a foreword appropriating-event (Ereignis). Moreover,
written for the Japanese translation of one Heideggers stress on the temporality and
of his essays in 1968, Heidegger reaffirmed historicity of being is increasingly accom-
that the Auseinandersetzung of Western and panied by the spatial language of the
Eastern thinking can assist in the endeavor clearing (Lichtung) and the place or
to save the essence of the human from the locality (Ort, Ortschaft, Ortlichkeit) of
threat of an extreme technical calcula- being, such that he comes to characterize
tion and manipulation of human Dasein his thought as a topology of being (GA
(JH,230). 15, 335/FS, 41).
The Japanese, for their part, have been All this invites comparison with Japans
ardently engaging with Heideggers thought most famous modern philosopher, Nishida
since the 1920s, when several of Japans Kitar, who spoke of the self-determination
leading young philosophers studied with of the place of absolute nothingness. Parkes
Heidegger.14 Indeed, the first article on has gone so far as to write that Heideggers
Heideggers thought was written by Tanabe Lichtung may be seen as the German ver-
Hajime in 1924 (89108), and the first book sion of Nishidas mu no basho, or topos of
on Heidegger was published by Kuki Shz nothingness.18 Yet Heidegger apparently
in 1933. Moreover, arguably the first sub- considered Nishida too Western (JH,
stantial critique was undertaken by Watsuji 170), while Nishida, for his part, did not
Tetsur beginning in 1928. Watsuji criticized think much of Heideggers (early) thought.
Heideggers early emphasis on temporality And so, unfortunately, the potentially his-
at the expense of spatiality. By spatiality toric East-West dialogue between these two
Watsuji meant, on the one hand, a more great figures of twentieth-century philoso-
radical notion of what Heidegger calls phy was not to beor rather, it is a task they
being-with (Mitsein): the originary social- left to those of us who inherit their paths of
ity or betweenness (aidagara) of human thought.19

462
HEIDEGGER AND ASIAN PHILOSOPHY

Being: Nothing: The Same vein Heidegger writes: Even if we mean it


only in the sense of the complete negation
Even if it were not influenced by Nishidas of anything present, the nothing belongs,
conception of the place of nothingness, in its absencing [ab-wesend], to presencing
Heideggers thought of the clearing may per- [Anwesen] as one of its possibilities (GA 9,
haps have been influenced by the Chinese 41314/PA, 31213 tm). Yet for Heidegger,
graph for nothing (wu, pronounced mu in as for Daoism and Zen, the nothing means
Japanese). One interpretation of this graph much more than merely a negation or priva-
entails, to quote a text by Len Wieger to tion of what is present.
which Heidegger may have had access, A Dramatically in his 1929 lecture What is
multitude . . . of men acting upon a forest, Metaphysics?22 and consistently in numer-
felling the trees, clearing of wood a tract of ous texts up through the 19669 Le Thor
land. In the old form [the graph] stated that seminars, Heidegger links being with the
the wood had vanished.20 Not only does this nothing (das Nichts) (GA 9, 10522, 123,
resemble Heideggers later explanations of 360, 3823, 41020/PA, 8496, 97, 273,
the clearing (see ZSD, 72/BW, 441), already 28990, 30918; GA 5, 113/QCT 154; GA
in his 1936 essay, The Origin of the Work 65, 1289, 145; GA 66, 27, 74, 778,
of Art, we read: In the midst of beings as a 845; GA 67, 5961; GA 69, 109; GA 70,
whole an open place occurs. There is a clear- 4850; GA 71, 121, 124, 1323, 148, 194,
ing [. . . which . . .] encircles all that is, like 208, 21920, 223; GA 15, 3469, 3602/FS,
the nothing, which we scarcely know (GA 4850, 568). According to the ontologi-
5, 40/BW, 178). A few years later he sharpens cal difference, the being [Sein] of beings
the point: This emptiness of the clearing is is itself not a being [ein Seiendes] (SZ, 6/
the inceptual nothing (GA 71, 208). BT, 5); hence, being, in contrast to all
Although scholars today tend to favor a beings, is no being and is in this sense a
different etymological account of wu/mu, nothing (JH, 166). In other words, being
according to which it is related to the graph is no-thing.23 Or, to put it the other way
for dance (in this case perhaps a rain around: The nothing itself, however, is
dance) and may also depict a person disap- being (GA 71, 121).
pearing behind thick vegetation, this inter- Heidegger repeatedly dismisses nihilistic
pretation too can be understood to carry misunderstandings of what he means by the
strikingly Heideggerian connotations of an nothing. On the contrary, he retorts, perhaps
interrelation between revealing and conceal- the essence of nihilism consists in not taking
ing. One Japanese scholar recently writes the question of the nothing seriously (N2,
(without reference to Heidegger): Precisely 53/NIV, 21; see also EM, 155/IM, 21718).
because nothingness (wu/mu) is a hardly The nothing is not a nihilistic privation of
perceptible indeterminacy, it contains the being, but rather the essential trembling of
idea of anticipating the possible appearance beyng itself and therefore is more than any
of something. . . . Nothingness contains being (GA 65, 256/CP2, 209).
the etymological ambiguity of being going In his most terse formulation, Heidegger
out of being (Entwerden) on the one hand writes: Being: Nothing: The Same (GA
and non-being harboring the possibility of 15, 363/FS, 58; see also GA 9, 115, 421/
being on the other.21 In a complementary PA 91, 318; GA 66, 294). He sometimes

463
HEIDEGGER AND ASIAN PHILOSOPHY

explicates this sameness as an essential inter- The Nothing and Mu:


play of being and the nothing, such that that Resonances
each employs itself for the other in a kin-
ship whose essential fullness we have as yet In a letter to Kojima Takehiko in 1963,
scarcely pondered (GA 9, 419/PA, 317). Heidegger wrote:
Although he does not explicitly cite chap-
ter 11 of the Daodejing, Heidegger clearly The lecture [What is Metaphysics?]
draws an insight from it when he speaks of was translated into Japanese as early as
the emptiness or nothingness of the jug as 1930 and was immediately understood in
your country, in contrast to the nihilistic
the ungraspable yet essential element of its
misunderstanding of the terms it intro-
being (GA 77, 1301/CPC, 842; VA, 161/
duced which remains prevalent in Europe
PLT, 167).24 The Daodejing speaks of noth- to this day. What is called the nothing
ingness (wu) both as the essential counter- [das Nichts] in this lecture means that
part of being (you) (chapter 2) and as the which, in regard to beings [das Seiende],
origin of being (chapter 40). For Heidegger, is never any one of these beings [niemals
the presencing of being is inseparable from etwas Seiendes], and which is thus
the absencing or nihilating of the nothing. the nothing, and yet which nevertheless
In Contributions to Philosophy, Heidegger determines beings as such and thus is
refers to the nothing as the abyssal char- called being [das Sein]. (JH, 225)
acter of being (or beyng), as the high-
est gift of its self-withdrawal and refusal In 1969 he wrote to Roger Munier: In the
(Verweigerung); for it is on account of this far East, with the nothing properly under-
negativity of beyng itself that nothingness stood, one found in it the word for being.25
is full of that assigning power the endur- In his Dialogue on Language Heidegger
ing of which is the origin of all creating had already expressed his appreciation for
(GA 65, 1289/CP2, 1934; see also GA the ability of the Japanese to understand his
66, 267, 845; GA 71, 124; GA 5, 113/ notion of the nothing, and had his Japanese
QCT, 154). interlocutor proclaim: For us, emptiness is
For Heidegger, it could be said, the noth- the loftiest name for what you mean to say
ing is the concealedness that always accom- with the word being (GA 12, 103/OWL,
panies the unconcealedness of being. The 19 tm).
nothing is the essentially self-withdrawing Heinrich Petzet relates the following 1963
and self-concealing dimension of being; it encounter with Bhikkhu Mani, a Theravada
is the lethe of aletheia, the expropriation Buddhist monk from Thailand.
(Enteignis) involved in the appropriating
event (Ereignis), the mystery (Geheimnis) Heidegger had spoken of releasement
of the forest that surrounds any bounded and openness to the mystery, so the
openness of the clearing. It is not a priva- nature of meditation is finally discussed.
What does meditation mean for Eastern
tion or vacuity, but rather the fullness of the
humanity? The monks response is quite
undelimited open-region (Gegnet) in which
simple: Meditation means to gather
this or that delimited sense of beingthis oneself. The more humanity succeeds
or that horizon of meaningcomes to be in gathering itself and concentrating,
formed. without exertion of the will, the more it

464
HEIDEGGER AND ASIAN PHILOSOPHY

lets go of itself. The I dissolves, until Mu and the Nothing:


in the end only one thing remains: the Differences
Nothing. But this Nothing is not noth-
ing; it is just the oppositefullness. No At the same time, Heidegger was also under-
one can name this. But it is nothing and
standably concerned about the differences
everythingfullness. Heidegger under-
between his thought and Buddhism. These
stands this and says, This is what I
have been saying throughout my whole differences may even undermine some appar-
life.26 ent similarities. At one point in Contributions
to Philosophy (19368) he writes: The less
that humans are beings, the less that they
At various other times Heidegger expressed adhere obstinately to the beings they find
similar enthusiasm about the resonances themselves to be, all the nearer do they come
between his own thought and that of to being (Not a Buddhism! Just the oppo-
Buddhism. He is reported to have exclaimed site) (GA 65, 170/CP2, 134). However,
upon reading a book on Zen by D. T. Suzuki: Heidegger is here presumably following
If I understand this man correctly, this Schopenhauers and Nietzsches misinterpre-
is what I have been trying to say in all my tations of Buddhism, as he does later when
writings!27 Suzuki visited Heidegger in he speaks of Schopenhauer and Buddhism as
1953 (see JH, 16972). Some years later, both involving a redemption from the will
Heidegger spoke to C. F. Weizcker of the [that] would amount to redemption from
deep impression left on him by a visit from being, hence to a collapse into vacuous noth-
a renowned Japanese Zen Buddhist, who ingness (VA, 113/NIV, 225). With regard to
spoke of what is decisive in an entirely this passage, Heidegger subsequently admit-
unmetaphysical manner; it was as if here a ted to Hellmuth Hecker that he was speak-
door had been opened for Heidegger (LBH, ing from the perspective of Nietzsche, and
29). Heidegger may have had in mind a visit that Buddhism, and no less Chinese and
from Hisamatsu Shinichi, a book of whose Japanese thought, were in need of an entirely
was later translated into German as Die Flle different interpretation (LBH, 58).
des Nichts.28 In 1958 Heidegger concluded a Even so, important differences between
discussion with Hisamatsu by stating: It has Heideggers thought and Buddhism remain. In
become clear that, with our ideas . . . we can conversation with Bhikkhu Mani Heidegger
hardly get to where the Japanese already are stated: In contrast, I believe, to Buddhist
(JH, 215). teachings, in Western thinking an essential
How close is Heideggers thought of the distinction is made between human being
nothing to that of Buddhism? While an and other living beings, [namely] plants and
examination of the various interrelated animals. Human being is distinguished by
yet also distinct senses of emptiness and having language, that is, by the fact that he
nothingness in Buddhism and Daoism is stands in a relationship of knowing to being
beyond the scope of this chapter,29 some of (GA 16, 590). Heidegger writes elsewhere:
these senses do indeed resonate with aspects The human being: the placeholder of the
of Heideggers thinking, and his enthusi- nothing [GA 9, 118, 419/PA, 93, 316; GA
asm for pointing these resonances out is not 15, 370/FS, 63] and the human being: the
unfounded. shepherd (not the master) of being [GA 9,

465
HEIDEGGER AND ASIAN PHILOSOPHY

342/PA, 260] . . . say the Same (JH, 225). Yet Heidegger is still right to point out
Following Medard Bosss claim that Indian a difference from Buddhism regarding his
thought does not require a guardian for the conception of the linguistic relation between
clearing, Heidegger remarked: In contrast, human being and being. For Heidegger, the
it is very important to me that the human essential trait of human being is a responding
being is a human being. In Indian thought, (Entsprechen) or answering (Antworten) to
the point is a giving up of being human the claim (Anspruch) or address (Zuspruch)
[Entmenschlichung] in the sense of Da-seins or call (Gehei) of being (GA 77, 235/
self-transformation into the pure luminosity CPC, 1516; GA 12, 2930/PLT 2067;
[of being] (ZS, 178). WIP, 6877; WhD, 80, 152/WCT, 11415,
In response to these statements, it should 124). For Heidegger, the sameness (das
first of all be pointed out that in most schools Selbe) of Dasein and Sein, human being and
of Hinduism and Buddhism, despite the fact being, the self and the nothing, thinking and
humans are seen as sharing the cycle of being, is never a distinctionless identity but
rebirth in samsara with other living beings, rather the belonging together (ID, 302;
they are also placed in a unique and privi- WhD, 74/WCT, 79; GA 9, 4078/PA, 3089)
leged position: only in the form of a human of this call and response. While Heidegger
being can one attain enlightenment or nir- does think being as the nothing, he says that
vana. Moreover, some distinctions need to human being is held out into the nothing or
be made, not only between various Hindu is the placeholder of the nothing; he never
schools of thought and Buddhism but also goes so far as to identify the nothing with the
between the Theravada Buddhism repre- true self. Zen, on the other hand, urges one
sented by Bhikkhu Mani and Mahayana to go beyond not only nihilistic and dualistic
Buddhist schools such as Zen, which pro- interpretations of Mu (nothingness) but also
claim a non-abiding nirvana and even the beyond all linguistic and intellectual discrim-
nonduality of samsara and nirvana. In Zen, inations and, by means a holistic practice of
when the I as an illusory reified and egois- seated meditation (zazen), to concentrate one-
tic sense of self is dissolved into the nothing, self with ones 360 bones and 84,000 pores
the true self emerges as a self-expression into this Mu and be Mu.30 Only then can
of this creatively self-delimiting nothingness one undergo the great death and come back
or emptying of emptiness. In other words, to life in a freely creative engagement with
while a false or inauthentic sense of self is to things and selflessly compassionate relation
be radically negated in Zen, by way of this with others. Despite some significant reso-
great death a true or authentic sense of self nances with Heideggers thoughts on death,31
is born or awakened. From the perspective of we do find here a significant difference
the East Asian Mahayana Buddhist school of between his meditative or commemorative
Zen, so-called Hinayana schools of Buddhism, thinking (Besinnung, Andenken) as a corre-
such as Theravada, along with schools of spondence with being, and the Zen practice
Hinduism such as Advaita Vedanta, do not of meditation, which involves a more radi-
sufficiently reaffirm the world of multiplicity cally nondualistic descent into nothingness
and interconnected individuality after negat- by way of a non-thinking (hi-shiry) that
ing the illusory ego and its dualistic and rei- underlies both thinking and not-thinking
fying discriminations. (fu-shiry).

466
HEIDEGGER AND ASIAN PHILOSOPHY

It is just such a difference that Nishitani Heidegger: Schritt zurck), for Heidegger
has in mind when he criticizes Heideggers the step steps back before, gains distance
statement: Da-sein means: being held out from that which is about to arrive (ZSD, 32/
into the nothing [Hineingehaltenheit in das TB, 30). From the perspective of Nishitanis
Nichts] (GA 9, 115, 120/PA, 91, 95; see philosophy of Zen, Heideggers being main-
also KPM, 162). According to Nishitani, tains an element of externality or tran-
insofar as Heidegger thought of the noth- scendence that would needed to be broken
ing as an abyss into which Dasein is thrust through on the path of a more radical step
in a state of anxiety (Angst), traces of the back or trans-descendence to the absolute
representation of the nothing as some thing near-side, that is, to the field of emptiness
[which threatens Dasein from without] still that is none other than ones own original
remain.32 Nishitanis main successor in the face.34
Kyoto School, Ueda Shizuteru, traces the Tsujimura Kichi was another Zen adept
development of Heideggers own under- and student of Nishitanis; he was also a lead-
standing of the relation to the nothing, and ing Heidegger scholar in Japan and principal
suggests that the experience of releasing editor of the Japanese edition of Heideggers
oneself [Sichloslassen] into the nothing, inti- Gesamtausgabe. After his stay in Freiburg in
mated at the end of What is Metaphysics? 19568, Heidegger held him in high regard,
(GA 9, 122/PA, 96), is radicalized in the and he was asked to speak at Heideggers
later Heideggers thought into the notion of eightieth birthday celebration in 1969.35
Gelassenheit.33 Following Uedas indica- Tsujimura has also led the way in plumbing
tions we could say that, were one to thor- the resonances between Heideggers thought
oughly release oneself into the nothing, it and Zen. And yet, not only is he critical of the
would no longer be experienced as the hor- fundamental attunement of Angst and what
ror of the abyss (GA 9, 3067/PA, 2334), he sees as the transcendental will opera-
or as the anxiety springing from pain, anxi- tive in Heideggers early thought,36 he also
ety as experience of the nothing (GA 71, indicates some crucial differences between
220). Rather, in a fundamental attunement of Heideggers later thought and Zen. In par-
Gelassenheit rather than Angst, the nothing ticular, he contends that the truth of Zen is
would be experienced as the essentially con- the absolute nothingness that cannot be
cealed dimension of being in its profoundest reached by any kind of thought and cannot
sense of giving or letting be (Seinlassen) be brought to speech as such with any kind
(GA 15, 363/FS, 59). of language. . . . By contrast, [Heideggers]
Nevertheless, Gelassenheit, for all truth of being is a truth that is established
its resonances with the Daoist and Zen thoroughly on the basis of thinking and
idea of non-doing (wuwei, mu-i), for language.37 The leap into the truth of
Heidegger names a relation to being that being that Heidegger speaks of, accord-
entails a coming-into-nearness to the far, ing to Tsujimura, does not reach the origin
a going-into-nearness that also preserves (Ursprung) of thought, which is itself no
an essential distance from being (GA 77, longerand not yetthought. It is for this
116, 1527/CPC, 75, 99103). Although reason that Heidegger speaks of a last god
both Zen and Heidegger speak of the need (GA 65, 40617) or, in the Spiegel interview,
to take a radical step back (Dgen: taiho, of a god who is needed to save us (GA 16,

467
HEIDEGGER AND ASIAN PHILOSOPHY

671); these are the unthinkable origin of absolutely contradictory self-identity of


thought as it is reflected in the dimension of the self and this immanently transcendent
thought.38 Tsujimura is careful to point out Buddha (i.e. absolute nothingness), Nishida
that Heideggers thought is not simply con- quotes Zen master Dait Kokushis famous
fined within the horizon of thought, since it saying: For countless eons separated from
responds to the call of that which is beyond one another, yet not divided for a moment;
thought, to that which Heidegger names, standing opposite one another all day long,
adopting a term from Schelling, the unpre- yet not opposed for an instant.43
thinkable (das Unvordenkliche) (GA 77, We may nevertheless conclude with Tsujim
146, 231/CPC, 95, 150). The difference is ura that, while Heideggers thought can help
thus that Heideggers thinking takes place in Zen develop its insights into a historical and
the in-between of thinking and the unthink- critical thinking,44 Zen can lead Heideggerian
able origin of thought, whereas Zen practice thinkers beyond or beneath the limits of
is aimed at becoming that origin itself and thought and language to a more direct expe-
speaking from there. Tsujimura concludes: rience of their silent origin.45
The truth of being is the truth of Zen inso-
far as the latter is, as the prior to thought,
reflected in thought. The truth of being is, as NOTES AND REFERENCES
it were, the shadow of the truth of Zen and
not the truth of Zen itself.39
1
Winfield E. Nagley, Introduction to the sym-
posium and reading of a letter from Martin
In short, according to Heidegger, the Heidegger, Philosophy East and West 20.3
authentic self and being or the nothing (1970), 221.
belong together in a linguistic relation of 2
Especially Lin Ma, Heidegger on East-West
call and response. The nothing is not only a Dialogue: Anticipating the Event (New
name for being in its difference from beings, York: Routledge, 2008). See also my
review in Journal of the British Society for
it is also the veil separating the concealed or Phenomenology 41.3 (2010), 3279.
withdrawn dimension of being from human 3
Especially Florian Vetsch, Martin Heideggers
being. Human being is held out into the noth- Angang der interkulturellen Auseinandersetzung
ing, is the placeholder of the nothing, but is (Wrzburg: Knigshausen& Neumann, 1992);
not the nothing itself. In Zen, by contrast, the also Reiner Thurnher, Der Rckgang in den
Grund des Eigenen als Bedingung fr ein
nothing is the original face of the true self; as Verstehen des Anderen im Denken Heideggers,
Tsujimura puts it: This nothing . . . is this, in ed. Hans-Helmut Gander, Europa und die
what we ourselves are.40 Philosophie (Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio
To be sure, many Zen masters and Kyoto Klostermann, 1993). For my own examination
School philosophers suggest that the self is of this issue, see Bret W.Davis, Heideggers
Orientations: The Step Back on the Way
in truth always a twofold self: a being and to Dialogue with the East, in eds Alfred
the nothing. The self is both a finite being Denker, Holger Zaborowski, Georg Stenger,
standing in relation to other finite beings and Rysuke Ohashi, and Shunsuke Kadowaki,
the field of emptiness in which these relations Heidegger-Jahrbuch 7: Heidegger und das
take place.41 According to Nishida, the self ostasiatische Denken (Freiburg/Munich: Alber
Verlag, forthcoming).
is fundamentally a self-contradiction, inso- 4
Rolf Elberfeld, Heidegger und das ostasia-
far as that which transcends the self is found tische Denken: Annherungen zwischen frem-
within the self as its own basis.42 On the den Welten, in ed. Dieter Thom, Heidegger

468
HEIDEGGER AND ASIAN PHILOSOPHY

Handbuch: Leben-Werk-Wirkung (Stuttgart: 10


Tomonobu Imamichi, In Search of Wisdom:
Metzler, 2003), 469. Unless otherwise noted, One Philosophers Journey (Tokyo: LTCB
all translations in this chapter are my own. I International Library, 2004), 123.
have marked tm where I have modified exist- 11
Okakura Tenshin, Cha no hon/The Book
ing translations. of Tea (a bilingual edition), trans. Asano
5
From Gadamers personal correspondence with Akira (Tokyo: Kodansha, 1998), 923; see
Graham Parkes, as related in the introduction also Dennis Hirota, Okakura Tenshins
to Graham Parkes (ed.), Heidegger and Asian Conception of Being in the World, Rykoku
Thought (Honolulu: University of Hawaii Daigaku Ronsh, 478 (2011), 11, 31. I will
Press, 1987), 5, 7. This landmark collection cite the Daodejing and the Zhuangzi by chap-
will hereafter be cited as HAT. ter number. Reliable translations include The
6
Nagley, Introduction to the symposium and Daodejing of Laozi, trans. Philip J. Ivanhoe
reading of a letter from Martin Heidegger, (Indianapolis: Hackett, 2003) and Zhuangzi:
221. See also GA 9, 424/PA, 321, as well as The Essential Writings, trans. Brook Ziporyn
Heideggers statement quoted in Willfred (Indianapolis: Hackett, 2009).
Hartig, Die Lehre des Buddha und Heidegger: 12
Heinrich Wiegand Petzet, Encounters &
Beitrge zum Ost-West-Dialog des Denkens Dialogues with Martin Heidegger 19291976,
im 20. Jahrhundert (Konstanz: Universitt trans. Parvis Emad and Kenneth Maly (Chicago:
Konstanz, 1997), 1516. Hartigs book, which University of Chicago Press, 1993), 18.
collects much of Heideggers correspondence 13
See the final section of my Heideggers
and reported statements regarding Asian phi- Orientations.
losophy, will hereafter be cited as LBH. 14
See the chapter by Yasuo Yuasa in HAT; the
7
The most important collections are Heidegger chapter by Rysuke hashi in JH; Parkess
and Eastern Thought, Philosophy East and Rising Sun over Black Forest; and Mine
West 20.3 (1970); HAT; Hartmut Buchner Hideki, Haidegg to nihon no tetsugaku:
(ed.), Japan und Heidegger (Sigmaringen: Watsuji Tetsur, Kuki Shz, Tanabe Hajime
Thorbecke, 1989); LBH; and Denker (ed.), [Heidegger and Japanese Philosophy: Watsuji
Heidegger-Jahrbuch 7: Heidegger und das osta- Tetsur, Kuki Shz, Tanabe Hajime] (Kyoto:
siatische Denken. Buchners collection, which Minerva, 2002). While the most prevalent
includes significant texts by Japanese philoso- and sustained Asian responses to Heideggers
phers as well as correspondence and dialogues thought have been in Japan, there have also
with Heidegger, will hereafter be abbreviated been important responses made by philoso-
as JH. phers from India (such as J. L. Mehta), China
8
Above all Reinhard May, Heideggers Hidden (such as Chang Chung-yuan), and Korea (such
Sources: East Asian Influences on His Work, as Park Chong-Hong, Ha Ki-Rak, and Cho
trans. with a complementary essay by Graham Kah Kyung).
Parkes (New York: Routledge, 1996); and 15
Watsuji Tetsur, Watsuji Tetsurs Rinrigaku:
Graham Parkes, Rising Sun over Black Ethics in Japan, trans. Yamamoto Seisaku and
Forest: Heideggers Japanese Connections, in Robert Carter (Albany: SUNY Press, 1996).
Reinhard May, Heideggers Hidden Sources: 16
Watsuji Tetsuro, Climate and Culture: A
East Asian Influences on His Work (New York: Philosophical Study, trans. Geoffry Bownas
Routledge, 1996), 79117. This volume will (New York: Greenwood Press, 1988).
hereafter be cited as HHS. 17
See Mine, Haidegg to nihon no tetsugaku, 43,
9
Ban Kazunori, Kaky kara hanarezu: Nishitani 14852, 250, 331.
Keiji sensei tokubetsu kgi [Without Departing 18
Graham Parkes, Heidegger and Japanese
from Home: Special Lectures of Professor Thought: How Much Did He Know and When
Nishitani Keiji] (Tokyo: Sbunsha, 1998), Did He Know It? in ed. Christopher McCann,
18990, 201. Note that Chinese and Japanese Martin Heidegger: Critical Assessments (New
names will generally be written in the order York: Routledge 1992), vol. 4, 394.
of family name first, except in cases where the 19
See hashi Rysuke, Nishida-tetsugaku no
Western order has been used for publications sekai [The World of Nishidas Philosophy]
in Western languages. (Tokyo: Chikumashob, 1995), 17998; Elmar

469
HEIDEGGER AND ASIAN PHILOSOPHY

Weinmayr, Thinking in Transition: Nishida 28


Hseki Shinichi Hisamatsu, Die Flle des
Kitar and Martin Heidegger, trans. John W. Nichts: Vom Wesen des Zen, trans. Takashi
M. Krummel, Philosophy East and West, 55.2 Hirata and Johanna Fischer (Stuttgart: Neske,
(2005), 23256; and John W. M. Krummel, 1994).
The Originary Wherein: Heidegger and 29
See Bret W. Davis, Forms of Emptiness in
Nishida on the Sacred and the Religious, Zen, in ed. Steven Emmanuel, A Companion
Research in Phenomenology, 40 (2010), to Buddhist Philosophy (Hoboken:
378407. Wiley-Blackwell, 2013), 190213.

20
HHS, 323; see also Gnter Wohlfart, Der 30
Zenkei Shibayama, The Gateless Barrier:
Philosophische Daoismus: Philosophische Zen Comments on the Mumonkan (Boston:
Untersuchungen zu Grundbegriffen und Shambhala, 2000), 1920.
komparative Studien mit besonderer 31
See Bret W. Davis, Heidegger and the Will:
Bercksichtigung des Laozi (Lao-tse) (Kln: On the Way to Gelassenheit (Evanston:
edition chra, 2001), 66. Northwestern University Press, 2007), 569.

21
Mori Hideki, Dka ni okeru mu no 32
Nishitani Keiji, Shky to wa nanika [What
tetsugaku [The Philosophy of Nothingness is Religion?], Nishitani Keiji chosakush
in Daoist Thinkers], Nihon no tetsugaku [Collected Works of Nishitani Keiji] (Tokyo:
[Japanese Philosophy], 5 (2004), 356. Sbunsha, 1987), vol. 10, 108; Nishitani Keiji,

22
Already in Being and Time (1927) Heidegger Religion and Nothingness, trans. Jan Van
writes of Angst as bringing Dasein face to Bragt (Berkeley: University of California Press,
face with the nothingness of [death as] the 1982), 96 tm.
possible impossibility of its existence and 33
Ueda Shizuteru, Basho: Nij-sekai-nai-sonzai
of the nothingness of the world especially [Place: Being-in-the-Twofold-World] (Tokyo:
when it has sunk into insignificance (SZ, Kbund, 1992), 59; see also Davis, Heidegger
265, 343; see also 187, 308). Shortly thereaf- and the Will, 57.
ter, in 1928, Heidegger writes more positively 34
See Bret W. Davis, The Step Back Through
of the world as a nihil originarium, that Nihilism: The Radical Orientation of
is, as the nothing which temporalizes itself Nishitani Keijis Philosophy of Zen, Synthesis
primordially (GA 26, 272/MFL, 210). In later Philosophica, 37 (2004), 13959.
texts, it remains for Heidegger our mortal- 35
JH, 15965; Kichi Tsujimura, Martin
ity that opens us up to being as the nothing. Heideggers Thinking and Japanese
The nothing, as other than beings, is the veil Philosophy, trans. Richard Capobianco and
of being (GA 9, 312/PA, 238); and death is Marie Gbel, Epoch, 12.2 (2008), 34957.
the shrine of the nothing (VA, 171/PLT, 176) 36
Tsujimura Kichi, Haidegg ronk
insofar as our experience of mortality frees [Heidegger Studies] (Tokyo: Sbunsha, 1971),
us from our fallenness in running around 905; see also Davis, Heidegger and the Will,
amidst beings (GA 9, 116/PA, 92) and opens 358, 315 n. 14.
us up to the no-thing of being. Death is the 37
Tsujimura, Haidegg ronk, 445; Kichi
purest nearness of the human to being (and Tsujimura, Die Wahrheit des Seins und das
therefore to the nothing) (GA 71, 194). absolute Nichts, trans. Daisuke Shimizu and

23
Note that the etymology of Nichts is similar to Ursula Baatz, in ed. Rysuke hashi, Die
that of no-thing; see NIV, 1819. Philosophie der Kyto-Schule, 2nd edition

24
See Wohlfart, Der Philosophische Daoismus, (Freiburg/Munich: Alber Verlag, 2010), 414.
chapter 2. 38
Tsujimura Kichi, Haidegg no shisaku

25
Quoted in Ma, Heidegger on East-West [Heideggers Thought] (Tokyo: Sbunsha,
Dialogue, 238. See also JH, 166. 1991), 203.

26
Petzet, Encounters & Dialogues with Martin 39
Tsujimura, Haidegg ronk, 448; Tsujimura,
Heidegger, 180; see also GA 16, 592. Die Wahrheit des Seins und das absolute

27
William Barret, Introduction to Selected Nichts, 41318; see also Tsujimura, Haidegg
Writings of D. T. Suzuki (New York: no shisaku, 35960.
Doubleday, 1996), xi.

470
HEIDEGGER AND ASIAN PHILOSOPHY

40
Kichi Tsujimura, Ereignis und Shki: 44
JH, 165; Tsujimura, Martin Heideggers
Zur bersetzung eines heideggerschen Thinking and Japanese Philosophy, 355; also
Grundwortes ins Japanische, in JH, 82. Tsujimura, Haidegg ronk, 53; Tsujimura,
41
Nishitani, Shky to wa nanika, 1701, 178, Die Wahrheit des Seins und das absolute
186; Nishitani, Religion and Nothingness, Nichts, 425.
1512, 158, 166. 45
Tsujimura, Haidegg ronk, 478; Tsujimura,
42
Nishida Kitar zensh [Complete Works of Die Wahrheit des Seins und das absolute
Nishida Kitar] (Tokyo: Iwanami: 19879), Nichts, 41718. On the silent origin of lan-
vol. 11, 418, 433, 445. guage, see GA 65, 36, 79; GA 12, 144, 2412/
43
Ibid., 399. OWL, 523, 122.

471
58
HEIDEGGER AND LATIN AMERICAN
PHILOSOPHY
Alejandro Arturo Vallega

The reception of Heideggers thought in nineteenth century that culminated with the
Latin America is inseparable from the independence of most of the Americas from
unfolding of Latin American philosophy.1 Spain and with the founding of new nations.
In order to understand the influence of the These movements were philosophically
German philosopher in this development founded on the positivism of such figures as
a few historical remarks will serve as a fit- Comte and Spencer. Their ideal of progress
ting introduction. With the arrival of the through rationalist calculation and growth is
conquistadors to the Americas follows the well captured in the motto that still appears
colonization of indigenous cultures and their on the Brazilian flag Order and Progress.
understanding of existence, through geno- By the beginning of the twentieth century
cide, violence, and exclusion of their thought. positivism had proven to be a failure in Latin
At the same time, with the colonization of America, and a new generation of intellec-
the Americas and the invention of its other tuals appeared who rose against positivism
appears the modern European mind. Thus, and with the aim to developing a thinking
modern rationality and colonialism appear grounded on the concrete reality of the Latin
as inseparable aspects of a single project, American situation. This group of intellectu-
the modern revolution or the enlightenment, als known as the founders were influenced
that is, the development of a single system of at first by Bergsons ideas concerning vital-
economic trade and of production and con- ism, by Schopenhauer, Hegel, and later by
trol of knowledge throughout the world. In Ortega y Gasset and Max Scheler. Following
light of this entanglement, to speak of Latin the emphasis on life and existentialism, they
American philosophy, and the reception of and the following generation then took up
Heidegger within it, is nothing other than the thought of Husserl, Dilthey, Hartmann,
to engage the complex relation of Western and Martin Heidegger.
thought and Latin American thought in their Heideggers influence becomes directly
mutual and yet distinct development. While apparent from the 1930s on, through the
the Americas participated actively in the work of some of the main figures in the devel-
development of the enlightenment, the very opment of a situated Latin American thought,
thought of freedom led to movements in the whose work was inspired by phenomenology,

473
HEIDEGGER AND LATIN AMERICAN PHILOSOPHY

existentialism, and Heideggers fundamen- humanismo, existencialismo (Una aproxi-


tal ontology, and who went to study with macion a Heidegger) (Being, Humanism,
Heidegger. This turn had been prepared and Existentialism (an engagement with
and introduced to a great extent by Ortega Heidegger)).6 In 1948, in the first issue of
y Gassets lectures on phenomenology and the journal Cuadernos de Filosofa, appears
eventually on Heideggers fundamental ontol- Astradas translation of The Essence of
ogy during his visits to Argentina in 1916 and Truth,7 and in 1952/53 in the same journal
in 1928, and by the founding of his famous appears his translation of Platos Doctrine
journal Revista de Occidente in 1923. of Truth.8 These works are followed by
Furthermore, the Spanish philosopher Javier two essays: La etapa actual del ltimo
Xubiri, who had been a student of Ortega Heidegger: Que significa pensar? (The cur-
y Gasset and of Heidegger in 1929, would rent stage of the latest Heidegger: What does
publish in 1932 in one of the first issues of Thinking Mean?) and Hlderlin los dioses:
Victoria Ocampos historical journal SUR, un paralelo con Heidegger y el humanismo
the first translation of Heideggers work to (Hlderlin the Gods: a Parallel with
appear in Spanish, Heideggers What is Heidegger and Humanism).9 In 1963 appears
Metaphysics?2 another direct encounter with Heideggers
Both Carlos Astrada and Alberto Wagner thought in his book Existencialismo y cri-
de Reyna studied with Heidegger at the end sis de la filosofa (Existentialism and The
of the 1920s and in the early 1930s. Carlos Crisis of Philosophy).10 In 1968 Astrada
Astrada returned to Argentina in 1932 dedicates his book Dilogos (Dialogues) to
and in 1933 published El juego existencial Heidegger.11 His proximity to Heidegger is
(The Existential Game), followed in 1936 also evidenced by Heideggers invitation of
by Idealismo fenomenolgico y metafsica Astrada to his seminar in 1970 to deliver a
existencial (Phenomenological Idealism and lecture titled: Concerning the Possibility of
Existential Metaphysics).3 Astrada follows an historical-existential praxis.12 In spite
Heideggers existential-analytic of Dasein in of his turn from existentialism to Marxism,
his work, but he criticizes Heideggers empha- Astradas engagement with his teachers work
sis on the question of being rather than on continues to the year of the Argentine philos-
Daseins concrete situation. This marks his ophers death in Buenos Aires, with the pub-
turn towards Marxism: Astrada develops a lication in 1970 of Martin Heidegger: de la
synthesis of the thinkers in which he recog- analtica ontolgica a la dimensin dialctica
nizes the praxis that situates Dasein without (Martin Heidegger: From the Ontological
abandoning Heideggers existential insight. Analytic to the Dialectic Dimension).13
This synthesis finds its strongest form in El Alberto Wagner Reyna studied with
mito Gaucho (The Gaucho Myth).4 Astrada Heidegger in 1935/36, and then went
will continue throughout his career his dia- on to complete his dissertation in Peru:
logue with Heideggers works and their dis- Heideggers Fundamental Ontology, which
semination in the Spanish-speaking world. appeared in book form the following year
In 1943 appears his book Temporalidad under the title La ontologia fundamen-
(Temporality).5 In 1949 he publishes the col- tal de Heidegger: su motivo y significacin
lection of essays Martin Heideggers Einfluss (Heideggers Fundamental Ontology: Its
auf die Wissenschaften (Bern, 1949), and Ser, Themes and Significance).14 Out of his

474
HEIDEGGER AND LATIN AMERICAN PHILOSOPHY

analysis of Heideggers thought Wagner Heideggers Hlderlin and the Essence of


Reyna went on to publish La filosofa en Poetry (1936) and The Origin of the Work
Iberoamrica, in which the Peruvian philoso- of Art (19346).21
pher sought to engage the Latin American Another major figure in the reception of
situation on its grounding difficulties.15 Heidegger in Latin America is the Spanish
In 1954 he published his important work philosopher Jos Gaos, who in 1938 immi-
Destino y vocacin de Iberoamrica (Destiny grated to Mexico escaping Francos regime
and Vocation of Iberoamerica).16 In 1958 and became a leading figure in the develop-
Wagner Reyna publishes his translation of ment of Mexican and Latin American philos-
Die Zeit des Weltbildes under the title La ophy as a professor at the UNAM in Mexico
poca de la imagen del mundo (The Epoch City. His courses were the inspiration for the
of the World-Image). His work on Heidegger next generation of Latin American philoso-
will continue to his final days, with the pub- phers. Among his courses is his legendary
lication of Ensayos en torno a Heidegger seminar on Being and Time, which he led for
(Essays on Heidegger) in 2000.17 As another ten years, from 1942 to 1952, and in which
major figure in Heideggers reception in participated many of those who would
Latin America has pointed out to the present become major figures in Latin American
author, the Venezuelan philosopher Ernesto thought, including Leopoldo Zea. In 1945
Mayz Vallenilla, Wagner Reyna (as Astrada) Gaos published 2 exclusivas del hombre, la
was a major force that brought many others mano y el tiempo (Mans Two Exclusives, the
to Heideggers thought. Walter Reyna recog- Hand and Time).22 And in 1951 he would
nized the opening provided by Heideggers publish his famous translation of Being and
work on the ontological sense of historicity Time,23 accompanied by his close interpreta-
(Geschichtlichkeit) and a hermeneutics that tion of it, titled Introduccon al Ser y Tiempo
could lead to a meta-politics that would give de Heidegger (Introduction to Heideggers
articulation to Latin American existence in Being and Time).24 Also worth mentioning
its specific senses of being. It would be out is his essay Heidegger 1956 y 1957.25 As
of his engagement with the work of Walter Enrique Dussel has pointed out, the pub-
Reyna and other interpreters of Heidegger lication of Heideggers Being and Time in
that Leopoldo Zea, one of the most impor- Spanish was itself a major turning point for
tant philosophers in the history of Latin the development of a philosophy situated
American philosophy, would come to call for in Latin American experience and history.
a Latin American philosophy and no more Along with his teaching and interpretation
(una filosofa latinoamericana sin ms).18 In of Heideggers thought, Gaos would launch
terms of this thematic, one must also con- a project for a Latin American thought born
sider the important work of the Mexican from the Latin American situation. Already
philosopher Samuel Ramos in his famous in 1941 Gaos taught a seminar at the UNAM
work El perfl del hombre y la cultura de titled, America en los origenes del mundo
Mxico (The Profile of Man and Culture moderno y los llamados historiadores de
of Mexico).19 Thereafter Ramos turns to las Indias (America in the Origins of the
the question of aesthetics. In 1950 he pub- Modern World and the So-called Historians
lishes Filosofa de la vida artstica,20 and the of the Indias), and in 1952 he would publish
year of his death appear his translations of En torno a la filosofa mexicana.26 Ultimately

475
HEIDEGGER AND LATIN AMERICAN PHILOSOPHY

it was Gaos interest in Latin American phi- Art) (1956); and Esttica operatoria en sus
losophy that spurred many of the impor- tres direcciones III. Promocin y requerim-
tant figures in the next generation of Latin iento de la obra de arte (Operatory Esthetics
American thinkers to seek the articulation of in its Three Directions: Promotion and
its distinct characteristics. Appropriation of the Work of Art) (1967).30
The Argentine philosopher Luis Juan Guerreros works on esthetics are developed
Guerrero closed his studies with Heidegger out of Heideggers sense of the work of art and
in 1927 with a dissertation titled Die go further to engage Merleau-Pontys esthetic
Entstehung einer allgemeinen Wertlehre in thought. Throughout his work Guerrero is
der Philosophie der Gegenwart (Marburg, clear about the dangers and possibilities for
1927). Following his studies Guerrero ethics inherent in esthetic experience, and the
takes a phenomenological and existentialist phenomenological and existential paths that
approach to philosophy that will eventually is required for taking up such issues.
lead him to his major work on aesthetics. Danilo Cruz Vlez studied with Heidegger
In 1939 he publishes Psicologa.27 In 1942, in1951, and upon his return to his native
together with Francisco Romero, he pub- country, Colombia, founded a landmark
lishes a collection of text from German phi- group of studies on Being and Time, that
losophy aimed to renew the interpretation of eventually went on to work on Heideggers
German philosophy in the new generation of The Essence of Ground and The Essence
Latin American thinkers: Filosofa alemana of Truth. From these years of study results
traducida al espaol (German Philosophy one of his most important books: Filosofa
in a Spanish Translation) (Buenos Aires, sin supuestos: From Husserl to Heidegger.31
1942). In 1945 in order to become a profes- In this work the Colombian philosopher
sor in Buenos Aires he publishes Tres temas interprets Heideggers thought as a radicali-
de filosofa en las entraas del Facundo zation of Husserls understanding of the phe-
(Three Philosophical Themes in the Guts of nomenological constitution of the knower
Facundo).28 In 1949 he presented at the first and the known. For Cruz Vlez, as for many
national congress of philosophy in Argentina Latin American interpreters of Heideggers
two works that mark his future path: Escenas thought, the key moment that happens as
de la vida esttica (Scenes of Esthetic Life) thinking is situated in its living context rather
and Torso de la vida esttica actual (The than on ideal structures. In 1989 appeared
Figure of Contemporary Esthetic Life).29 The his El mito del rey filsofo: Platn, Marx
years that follow will see the publication of Heidegger (The Myth of the Philosopher
his major works: Que es la Belleza? (What is King: Plato, Marx, Heidegger).32 His con-
Beauty?) (1954); tica (1955); Esttica oper- cern with the Latin American situation and
atoria en sus tres direcciones I. Revelacin y with the development of a new humanism
acogimiento de la obra de arte (Operatory appears clearly in Ortega y Gasset y el des-
Esthetics in its Three Directions: Revelation tino de Amrica Latina (Ortega y Gasset and
and Reception of the Work of Art) (1956); the Destiny of Latin America). 33
Esttica operatoria en sus tres direcciones The concern with the being of Latin
II. Creacin y ejecucin de la obra de arte Americans, technology and technique, is
(Operatory Esthetics in its Three Directions: the central spurring point for the work
Creation and Execution of the Work of of the Venezuelan philosopher Ernesto

476
HEIDEGGER AND LATIN AMERICAN PHILOSOPHY

Mayz Vallenilla. Mayz Vallenilla studied titled: Lecciones de introduccin a la filos-


in Gottingen and Freiburg and was closely ofa, de antropologa filosfica.41 The course
acquainted with his teacher Martin Heidegger, gives a close reading of Being and Times
who he first met in 1950 and later on visited Dasein analysis as the basis for the unfolding
in the Black Forest. Mayz Vallenilla founded of what will become Dussels philosophy of
his work on the analysis of Dasein and on liberation, putting emphasis on the idea of a
the problem of technology as developed by philosophy that arises from Daseins concrete
Heidegger. His first work along these themes being-in-the-world. In other words, in this
was El problema de Amrica: Apuntes course Dussel interprets Heideggers work
para una filosofa americana (The Problem as an anthropological fundamental ontology.
of America: Notes for a Latin American He writes: Man is called by his vocation
Philosophy).34 This work is a phenomenolog- (vocare means to call), by his own pro-ject.
ical analysis of the being of Latin American This vocation is but the way in which man
Dasein in its distinct temporality (given the comprehends himself in the world. . . .42
historical origination of his/her consciousness Later he explains, It is here that in our case
in the arrival of the conquistadors). He then philosophy appears, anthropological phi-
went on to publish in 1960 Ontologia del losophy. This requires that we overcome the
conocimiento (Ontology of Knowledge).35 naivete of accepting our very being in the
Again, taking on Heideggers work he pub- world as something obvious, all of it from
lished El problema de la Nada en Kant (Kant the essence of man to the axioms of science
and the Problem of Nothingness).36 His con- . . . philosophy will accomplish a more fun-
cern with the Latin American situation and damental position . . . a hermeneutical posi-
the role of technology and the possibility tion. It is here that Heideggers proposition
of a new humanism in light of Heideggers is situated.43 Then he concludes:
thought as a path for interpreting these issues
marks his lengthy career, and is apparent in What we call philosophical anthropol-
such works as: Del hombre y su alienacin ogy is a fundamental ontological con-
(Of Man and his Alienation);37 Tcnica y sideration of man. That is, the sciences
will arrive at their unity (as well as the
humanismo (Technique and Humanism);38
university), not by a synthesis more or
Latinoamrica en la encrucijada de la tc-
less composed accidentally (that is a pos-
nica (Latin America at the Crossing of teriori), but through its foundation, from
Technique).39 His most important later work the root from which they emerge (that is a
is Fundamentos de la meta-tcnica (The priori). The root from which the sciences
Foundations of Meta-technics).40 arise is man-already-in the-world.44
Martin Heideggers work has a founding
role for the first philosophy to be distinctly Dussel will radicalize Heideggers insight by
identified with Latin America as its origin turning to Paul Ricoeur and to Levinas cri-
and sense, namely the philosophy of lib- tique of Heidegger. Thus, Daseins being-in-
eration. This movement begins in Argentina the-world will become the being-in-the-world
in the early 1970s, but already in 1968 its of one who tells stories and makes sense of
most widely known founding figure, Enrique the world, and this being is understood not
Dussel, offers a course on Heidegger in from the view of Western thought but with
Mendoza, Argentina. The famous course was Levinas insight, as the other, the excluded,

477
HEIDEGGER AND LATIN AMERICAN PHILOSOPHY

the poor, the exploited. However, Heideggers The contemporary figures in Latin
insight, the situating of philosophical thought American philosophy that have contin-
in its originary living situation is a basic pil- ued the legacy of those who studied with
lar for the development of Dussels work, and Heidegger and brought his thought to bear
for the philosophy of liberation as well. on the unfolding of Latin American phi-
Another figure present at the very begin- losophy are as many and bring forth as
nings of the philosophy of liberation was many complicated issues and new open-
Rodolfo Kusch.45 Kuschs thought arises ings for development as is the case with the
in departure from Heideggers Dasein German philosophers reception in Europe
analysis and he is very critical of the or North America. Some salient figures
German philosophers later thought. He must be at least named. The Argentine phi-
sees Heideggers later thought as a turn losopher Dina V. Picotti C. in departure from
toward ontological rather than following Heideggers later thought in Contributions
an anthropological-philosophical path. By to Philosophy has developed a thinking
contrast, Kuschs own path leads him to that engages issues of race and identity in
think phenomenologically the anthropologi- Argentina and Latin America. This unique
cal reality of indigenous Americans. Indeed, and powerful work in contemporary philos-
he turns to a concrete analysis that aims to ophy follows her crucial contribution to the
articulate the being of the excluded, forgot- reception of Heidegger in Latin America, her
ten lives of deep America, as the title of his precise and clear translation of Heideggers
famous book Amrica profunda indicates.46 Contribution to Philosophy into Spanish,
Kusch thinks out of the estar (the concrete as well as her translation of Besinnung.50 At
existence of the indigenous ways of being in the same time contemporary interpreters of
the world) rather than from seeking a gen- Heideggers have not failed to recognize and
eral sense of ser (being) in light of which an problematize his involvement with national
understanding of their existence may occur.47 socialism. This was already an issue that
His work has begun to gain the attention Pablo Neruda would emphasize in his pro-
of North American philosophers, particu- tests about the publication of Heideggers
larly with the translation into English of one works in the famous journal SUR.51 In 1987
of his major works, El pensamiento ind- appeared Heidegger et le nazisme by the
gena y popular en Amrica under the title exiled Chilean philosopher Victor Faras.
Indigenous and Popular Thinking in America This work will open a world-wide discussion
(Latin America Otherwise).48 We must also concerning the issue.52 Pablo Feinmann, the
mention along with Kusch another major Argentine philosopher and writer published
figure in the development of the philosophy his novel La sombra de Heidegger in 2005,
of liberation Juan Carlos Escannone, and his another work that invited much discussion
critique of Heidegger out of the perspective concerning Heideggers figure in relationship
of the Theology of Liberation, always point- to Latin American thought.53 The question
ing to Heideggers turn away from a think- of the relationship of Heideggers thought
ing out of concrete singularity and difference and National Socialism is distinctly acute
the German philosopher makes possible with in Latin America given the identification in
his work. Scannone develops in his work a Latin America of his thought as a whole with
hermeneutical theology of liberation.49 nationalist populist governments and fascist

478
HEIDEGGER AND LATIN AMERICAN PHILOSOPHY

military regimes. At the same time, as already his little book from 2005 Entre Heidegger
noted above, Heideggers thought for a situ- y Celan (Between Heidegger and Celan), in
ated thinking invites for the developments which through the tension of reading Celans
of antifascist and diversifying movements poetry and Heideggers work at the limit of
like that of the philosophy of liberation. language and sense he explores philosophi-
Moreover, with the end of many military dic- cally the depth and difficulty that affords us
tatorships in the 1990s the question of the the work of Martin Heidegger.57
role of history in the development of national
identities, communities, and subjects becomes
central. Again appears existentialism and NOTES AND REFERENCES
among the main figures Heidegger in the
development of Latin American thought, this 1
My discussion will not cover Heideggers
time as the call for a hermeneutics that rec- reception in Brazil, which is entirely another
fecund field for investigation. Also, I have
ognizes history and thinks through it, rather
covered only the principal figures of a history
than attempting to ignore the violence, that is too extensive and that reaches to the
exclusion, and destruction of society in the present in its reception of Heideggers work.
name of focusing on a projection of develop- I have based this essay on a previous article:
ment and economic growth that must look Alejandro Vallega, Die Heidegger-Rezeption
in Sdamerika, Heidegger-Jahrbuch
ahead and forget the past as the only path
(Heidegger and Nietzsche), vol. 3 (2006),
for the future of Latin America. As a result Verlag Karl Alber Freiburg, Germany.
Heidegger becomes an important figure for 2
Along with the translation appeared an
rethinking the Latin American situation in essay entitled, Martin Heidegger before the
light of its hard and dark history of fascist Shadow of Dostoiewsky by the poet Benjamn
Fondane.
capitalist and neoliberal regimes.54 3
Carlos Astrada, El juego existencial (Buenos
Among later philosophers working on Aires: Babel, 1933); Idealismo fenomenolgico
Heidegger appears another crucial figure, the y metafsica existencial (Buenos Aires: UBA,
Chilean Eduardo Rivera, a student of Hans 1936). Throughout this chapter I will provide
Georg-Gadamer and Zubiri, who published English translation citations when available.
The reader should note that almost all of the
a new translation of Being and Time in 1997.
works on Heidegger from Latin America have
Thereafter he has followed with an extensive never been translated into English.
two-volume commentary.55 The work being 4
Carlos Astrada, El mito gaucho (Buenos Aires:
done on Heidegger today is too extensive to Ediciones Cruz Azul, 1948. Second edition,
begin to cover it, but I must mention, although 1964).
5
Carlos Astrada, Temporalidad (Buenos Aires:
of previous generations, Jorge Acevedo
Cultura Viva, 1943).
Guerras work on Heidegger and Ortega in 6
Carlos Astrada, Ser, humanismo, existencial-
Chile as well as his later work on Heidegger ismo. Una aproximacin a Heidegger (Buenos
and Technology and, the Venezuelan Alberto Aires: Kairs, 1949).
Rosales and his work on the ontological dif-
7
Carlos Astrada, De la esencia de la verdad,
Cuadernos de Filosofa, Numero Uno, Buenos
ference.56 Finally I close by mentioning the
Aires, 1948. Cuadernos de Filosofa was
work of the philosopher Pablo Oyarzn, who founded by Carlos Astrada and is now in its
has made a fine contribution to the reception third epoch (Obras de Martin Heidegger: segn
of Heidegger in Latin America with respect el plan de la Gesamtausgabe, available online
to the political issues mentioned above with at: www.heideggeriana.com.ar/bibiliografia/

479
HEIDEGGER AND LATIN AMERICAN PHILOSOPHY

gesamtausgabe_1.htm) One of the best sites 20


Samuel Ramos, Filosofa de la vida artstica
for information concerning the translations (Buenos Aires: Espasa-Calpe, 1950).
of Heideggers works into Spanish and for 21
The translation appeared as a book titled
information about Heidegger in Latin America Arte y Poesia (Buenos Aires: Fondo de cultura
is Heidegger en Castellano, a website kept by econmica, 1958).
Jaime Potel: www.heideggeriana.com.ar/ 22
Jos Gaos, 2 exclusivas del hombre: la mano
8
Carlos Astrada, La doctrina de Platn a cerca y el tiempo (Mexico: Universidad de Nuevo
de la verdad, Cuadernos de Filosofa, 10, 11, Leon, 1945).
12, Buenos Aires, 19523. 23
Martin Heidegger, El Ser y el Tiempo, trans.
9
Carlos Astrada, La etapa actual del Jos Gaos (Buenos Aires: Fondo de cultura
ltimo Heidegger: Que significa pensar? econmica, 1951).
in Cuadernos de Filofofa (Buenos Aires), 24
Jos Gaos, Introduccin a El Ser y El Tiempo
Numbers 79 (1952). Hlderlin los dioses: (Madrid: Fondo de cultura econmica, 1951).
un paralelo con Heidegger y el humanismo in 25
Heidegger 1956 y 1957, Dianoia, 4 (1958),
Aletheia, Ao 1, nmeros 45 (1957). 35468.
10
Carlos Astrada, Existencialismo y crisis de 26
Jos Gaos, En torno a una filosofa mexi-
la filosofa (Buenos Aires: Editorial Devenir, cana (Mxico: Porra y Obregn, 1952).
1963). Republished in 1980.
11
Carlos Astrada, Dilogos (Universidad de 27
L. J. Guerrero, Psicologa, (Buenos Aires:
Puerto Rico) ao V, nmeros 1112 (abril Losada, 1939).
septiembre, 1968). 28
L. J. Guerrero, Tres temas de filosofa en las
12
Original Spanish title: Sobre la posibilidad de entraas del Facundo (La Plata: Universidad
una prctica histrico-existencial. Nacional de La Plata, 1945/Buenos Aires:
13
Carlos Astrada, Martin Heidegger: de la Docencia, 1981).
analtica ontolgica a la dimensin dialctica 29
L. J. Guerrero, Escenas de la vida esttica,
(Buenos Aires: Editor Juarez S.A., 1970). en Actas del Primer Congreso Nacional de
14
Alberto Wagner Reyna, La ontologia funda- Filosofa, UN Cuyo, Mendoza, 1 (1949)
mental de Heidegger: su motivo y significacin 22141; Torso de la vida esttica actual, en
(Buenos Aires: Losada, 1939). The significance en Actas del Primer Congreso Nacional de
of this work for the reception of Heidegger Filosofa, UN Cuyo, Mendoza, 3, 146674.
in Latin America is evidenced by its second 30
L. J. Guerrero,Qu es la belleza?, (Buenos
and third editions in 1945 and in Brazil Dois Aires: Columba, 1954). L. J. Guerrero, tica
problemas na filosofia de Heidegger (Rio de (Mimeo, Buenos Aires, 1955). L. J. Guerrero,
Janeiro: Imprensa Nacional, 1945). Esttica operatoria en sus tres direcciones
15
La filosofa de Iberoamrica (Lima: Soc. I. Revelacin y acogimiento de la obra de
Peruana de Filosofa, 1949). arte (Buenos Aires: Losada, 1956). Esttica
16
Alberto Wagner Reyna, Destino y vocacin operatoria en sus tres direcciones II. Creacin
de Iberoamrica (Madrid: Inst. De Cultura y ejecucin de la obra de arte (Buenos Aires:
Hispnica, 1954). Losada, 1956). Esttica operatoria en sus tres
17
Alberto Wagner Reyna, Ensayos en torno a direcciones III. Promocin y requerimiento
Heidegger (Lima: PUCP-FCE, 2000). de la obra de arte (Buenos Aires: Losada,
18
Leopoldo Zea, La Filosofa Americana como 1967).
Filosofa Sin Ms (Mexico: Siglo XXI Editores, 31
D. Cruz Vlez, Filosofa sin supuestos.
2010) El pensamiento filosfico latinoameri- De Husserl a Heidegge (Buenos Aires:
cano, del Caribe y latino [13002000] ed. Sudamericana, 1970).
Enrique Dussel, Eduardo Mendieta, Carmen 32
D. Cruz Vlez, El mito del rey filsofo (Bogot:
Bohrquez (DF, Mexico: Siglo XXI Editores, Planeta, 1989).
2009), 839. 33
D. Cruz Vlez, Ortega y Gasset y el destino
19
Samuel Ramos in his famous work El perfl de Amrica Latina (Buenos Aires: Fundacin
del hombre y la cultura de Mxico, 2nd edn Banco de Boston, Institucin Ortega y Gasset,
(Buenos Aires: Espasa-Calpe, 1952). 1983).

480
HEIDEGGER AND LATIN AMERICAN PHILOSOPHY

34
Ernesto Mayz Vallenilla, El problema de the Universidad del Salvador, San Miguel,
Amrica: Apuntes para una filosofa americana 19703). My following observations about
(Caracas: Universidad Central de Venezuela, Kusch are founded in part on the fine research
1957). El problema de Amrica (Caracas: done by the contemporary Argentine phi-
Universidad Central de Venezuela, 1959/ losopher Dina V. Picotti C. (see her article on
Caracas: Universidad Central de Venezuela, Kusch titled, Rodolfo Kusch: aportes de una
1969/Caracas: Equinoccio (Universidad Simn antropologa americana, El pensamiento
Bolvar), 1992). latinoamericano del siglo XX ante la condicin
35
Ernesto Mayz Vallenilla, Ontologia del cono- humana (2003 Coordinador General Pablo
cimiento (Caracas: Universidad Central de Guadarrama Gonzlez. Coordinador General
Venezuela, 1960). para Argentina, Hugo Biagini. El pensamiento
36
Ernesto Mayz Vallenilla, El problema de la latinoamericano del siglo XX ante la condicin
Nada en Kant (Madrid: Editorial Revista humana. Versin digital, iniciada en junio de
de Occidente, 1965/Caracas: Monte vila 2004, a cargo de Jos Luis Gmez-Martnez).
Editores Latinoamericana, 1992; in German: www.ensayistas.org/critica/generales/C H/
Pfllingen: Verlag Gnther Neske, 1974; in argentina/kusch.htm
French: Paris: LHarmattan, 2000). 46
Rodolfo Kusch, Amrica profunda, 1st edn
37
Ernesto Mayz Vallenilla, Del hombre y su (Buenos Aires: Hachette, 1962); 2nd edn
alienacin (Caracas: Instituto Nacional de (Buenos Aires: Bonum, 1975); and 3rd edn
Cultura y Bellas Artes, 1966/Caracas: Monte (Buenos Aires: Bonum,1986).
vila Editores, 1969) 47
Among the many books and writings by Kusch
38
Ernesto Mayz Vallenilla, Tcnica y humanismo appear his principle works: La seduccin de
(Caracas: Universidad Simn Bolvar, 1972). la barbarie-Anlisis hertico de un continente
39
Ernesto Mayz Vallenilla, Latinoamrica en la mestizo (Rosario, Argentina: Edit. Fundacin
encrucijada de la tcnica (Caracas: Universidad Ross, with Prlogues for the 1st and 2nd
Simn Bolvar, 1976). edn by F. J. Solero and C. Cullen, 1983). El
40
Ernesto Mayz Vallenilla, Fundamentos de la pensamiento indgena y popular en Amrica
meta-tcnica (Caracas: Monte vila Editores, (3rd edn, Buenos Aires: Hachette, 1977). La
1990/Barcelona: Gedisa, 1993; in Italian: negacin en el pensamiento popular (Buenos
Naples: Istituto per gli Studi Filosofici, 1994; Aires: Cimarrn, 1975). Geocultura del
in French: Paris: LHarmattan, 1997; in hombre americano, (Buenos Aires: F.Garca
German: Berlin: Verlag Peter Lang, 2002; in Cambeiro, 1976). Indios, porteos y dioses
Portuguese: Lisbon: Edies Colibri, 2004) (1st edn, Buenos Aires: Stilcograff, 1966; 2nd
Published in English under the title, The edn, 1994). Esbozo de una antropologa filos-
Foundations of Meta-technics, trans. Carl fica americana (S.Antonio dePadua: Castaeda,
Mitcham (Maryland: University Press of 1978).
America, 2004). 48
Rodolfo Kusch, El pensamiento indgena
41
Enrique Dussel, Lecciones de introduccin a la y popular en Amrica (3rd edn, Buenos
filosofa, de antropologa filosfica (unpub- Aires: Hachette, 1977). Indigenous and
lished text, Consejo Nacional de Ciencias Popular Thinking in America (Latin America
Sociales, 19962001). From here on sited as Otherwise), trans. Maria Lugones and Joshua
LAF, followed by page number. Price (Durham: Duke University Press, 2010).
42
LAF, 38. My translation. 49
Among his works are Religion y nuevo pen-
43
Ibid., 49. My translation. samiento: Hacia una filosofa de la religion
44
Ibid., 50. My translation. para nuestro teimpo desde American Latina
45
He is present and active in the first meetings (Mexico: Anthropos, 2005); Discernimiento
that give rise to the philosophical movement filosfico de la accin y pasin histrica
(at the II Congreso Nacional de Filosofa en (Mexico: Anthropos, 2009).
Alta Gracia, Crdoba in 1971, and par- 50
Martin Heidegger, Aportes a la Filosofa
ticipated in the academic week concerning Acerca del Evento, trans. Dina V. Picotti
Latin American thought that took place at C. (Buenos Aires: Editorial Biblos, 2003).

481
HEIDEGGER AND LATIN AMERICAN PHILOSOPHY

Testimony to the excellence of her work is Heideggers opening for other ways of thinking
that her translation was one of the few works and then turns to Levinas and Fanon.
at times consulted during the translation 55
Martin Heidegger, Ser y Tiempo, trans. Jorge
of Heideggers work into English (Martin Eduardo Rivera (Santiago, Chile: Editorial
Heidegger, Contributions to Philosophy (of the Universitaria, 1997). Jorge Eduardo Rivera
Event.), trans. Richard Rojcewicz and Daniela y Mara Teresa Stuven, Comentario a Ser
Vallega-Neu (Bloomington: Indiana University y Tiempo de Martin Heidegger, vol. 1,
Press, 2012). Besinnung (GA 66) appeared as Introduccin (Santiago, Chile: Ediciones
Meditaciones (Buenos Aires: Biblos, 2006). de la Universidad Catlica de Chile, 2008).

51
This America of Ours: The Letters of Gabriela Jorge Eduardo Rivera y Mara Teresa Stuven,
Mistral and Victoria Ocampo, trans. Elisabeth Comentario a Ser y Tiempo de Martin
Horan and Doris Meyer (Austine: University Heidegger, vol. 2, Primera Seccin (Santiago,
of Texas Press, 2003), 2246. Chile: Ediciones de la Universidad Catlica de

52
Victor Faras, Heidegger et le nazisme (Paris: Chile, 2010).
Editions verdier, 1987), then translated into 56
Jorge Acevedo Guerra, Heidegger y la
German under the title Heidegger und der poca tcnica (Santiago, Chile: Editorial
Nationalsozialismus (Frankfurt am Main: Universitaria, 1999). Alberto Rosales,
Fischer Verlag, 1989), and into English as Transzendenz und Differenz (Den Haag,
Heidegger and Nazism (Philadelphia: Temple Holanda: Phaenomenologica vol.33, Martinus
University Press, 1989). Nijhoff, 1970)

53
Pablo Feinmann, La sombra de Heidegger 57
Pablo Oyarzun Robles, Entre Heidegger y
(Buenos Aires: Seix Barral, 2005). Celan (Santiago, Chile: Metales Pesados,

54
The place of Heideggers thought in con- 2005). On the question of the limits of
temporary Latin American philosophy has language and sense see the article by Juan
also been complicated by the fine work on Manuel Garrido Una pisca de sentido:
decolonial philosophy by the Puerto Rican acerca de Entre Celan y Heidegger de Pablo
thinker Nelson Maldonado-Torres. See Nelson Oyarzn, in Revista de Filosofa, 64 (2008),
Maldonado-Torres, On the Coloniality of 7988 (Facultad de Filosofa y Humanidades,
Being: Contributions to the Development of Universidad de Chile.) For further reading
a Concept, Cultural Studies, 21.23 (March/ in more detail see Crnica de la recepcin
May 2007), 24070. In a move similar de Heidegger en hispanoamrica, Revista
to Dussels Maldonado-Torres recognizes Santander, 1 (2006), 10225.

482
Index

abandonment 43, 161, 2845, 287, 315, 342, Augustine 1819, 26, 88, 93, 119, 331
437 authenticity 19, 27, 32, 167, 1723, 182, 185,
of Being to itself 161, 2467 189, 251, 292, 294, 370, 385, 3958, 457
of beings by being 287 Jargon of, The 3856, 390n. 2
address (Zuspruch) 230, 294, 466 as a modification but not a total obliteration of
Adorno, Theodor W. 235n. 11, 262n. 10, inauthenticity 292
38591
Agamben, Giorgio 160, 398n. 7 Baeumler, Alfred 489, 512
Anaximander 59, 158, 1601, 320, 363 Basic Concepts of Aristotelian Philosophy 15, 29,
Anaximander Fragment, The 81, 157, 15860 1856, 190n. 1
anthropology 102, 131, 134, 193, 197n. 4, 265, Basic Problems of Phenomenology, The 557,
267, 276, 334, 407n. 7, 477 107, 379
anxiety (Angst) 56, 86n. 3, 1478, 152, 174, 190, Beaufret, Jean 68, 116, 2378, 402
194, 205, 264, 294, 31114, 342, 349, 352n. Becker, Oskar 19, 72
16, 378, 3889, 3978, 402, 4378, 4547, becoming 102, 158, 1602, 21112, 223, 228,
467 233, 315, 322, 420
apophantic as 427 as becoming human 266
Aquinas, Thomas 36, 889, 914, 98, 127, 191 and deterritorialization 420, 424n. 15
arche 84, 320 oneself 35
Arendt, Hannah 678, 70, 73, 15763, 197n. 1, as sovereign becoming 323
398n. 7 beginning 55, 58, 110, 285
Aristotle 1516, 18, 21, 28, 36, 55, 57, 7780, another 55, 57, 60, 105, 286, 289n. 35, 387,
824, 86n. 1, 878, 902, 108, 114, 128, 420, 422
166, 175, 179, 1834, 1867, 191, 194, 207, first 43, 812, 118, 217, 2845
250, 292, 303, 321, 332, 335, 337, 3402, Greek 55, 57, 82, 435
3546, 364, 366n. 6, 379, 390, 418, 4356, being-historical thinking (seinsgeschichtliches
4456, 449nn. 18, 20 Denken) 90, 115, 154
art 25760 being-in-the-world 16, 25, 40, 1001, 140, 144,
artwork, the 42, 199206, 221, 254, 260, 306, 173, 180, 190, 197n. 5, 2713, 283, 304,
3256, 347, 3567, 365, 420 342, 346, 348, 378, 3801, 383, 4256, 434,
attunement 81, 111, 226 4534, 457, 460, 477
as fundamental attunement and being-on-the-Earth 203
(Grundstimmung) 81, 227 being-towards-death 31214, 395
poetic 227, 231, 234, 284, 295, 378, 4545, and the non-relational character of
457, 461 death 264

483
Index

being-with 40, 159, 163, 263, 265, 292, 295, configuration (Gestalt) 2024, 206
304, 3945, 4556, 460, 462 conscience (Gewissen) 190n. 3, 196, 396, 406,
Bergson, Henri 191, 382, 393, 473 438, 443
between, the 240, 248, 2789 call of 196, 294, 305, 312, 379
Binswanger, Ludwig 67, 71, 72, 415n. 3, 451, ecologic 433, 438
458n. 2 consciousness 18, 51, 136, 13940, 1456, 190,
biography 1521, 363 192, 254, 276, 2801, 303, 331, 340, 347,
biologism 4852, 217, 279 370, 372, 382, 434, 438, 477
critique of 51 bodys 397
birth 253, 2637 hermeneutical 1656, 169, 1723
as ur-relational 265 naturalization of 88
Blochmann, Elizabeth 26, 68, 70, 72 phenomenology of religious 26
body, the 101, 18990, 26974, 342, 3801 and self-consciousness 11415, 130, 136
lived-body (Leib) 270 of something 136
as physical body (Krper) 270 Contributions to Philosophy 323, 43, 51, 55,
and space 351 602, 65, 80, 11011, 125, 207, 21521, 243,
boredom 40, 152, 457 246, 266, 283, 34850, 357, 364, 465, 478
phenomenology of 40 creation, ex nihilo 99
Boss, Medard 67, 71, 72, 343n. 5, 451, 458n. 3,
466 Dao/Tao () 64, 4601
Butler, Judith 442, 448n. 1 Darwin 501, 224
Darwinism 49
call, the 17, 80, 254, 396, 416n. 12, 438, 468, Death of God, the 121, 123, 253, 333
479 decision 3942, 44, 49, 62, 119, 1879, 215, 218,
of being 241 220, 253, 279, 2935, 333, 338, 365, 404, 447
of conscience 196, 2945, 379 and decidedness (Entschiedenheit) 294
capitalism 1726, 479 as a decision for be-ing (Entscheidung fr das
care (Sorge) 28, 79, 99, 140, 174, 194, 292, 294, Seyn) 294
334, 3468, 3778, 395, 433, 438 moment of 18, 285, 287
as care for the sake of being 295 deconstruction 34, 213, 237, 319, 4024
of the dead 443 as aporetic thinking 404
ethics of 438 as self-deconstruction 404
as structural wholeness of Dasein 194 Deleuze, Gilles 41724
Carnap, Rudolf 1515 Derrida, Jacques 291, 322, 325, 4018, 435, 443,
Cassirer, Ernst 1439, 353 446, 4556
Celan, Paul 67, 72, 390, 479, 482n. 57 Descartes, Ren 48, 51, 79, 878, 92, 97
Christianity 21, 267, 879, 94, 119, 211, 238, de-severance (Ent-fernung) 3467
321, 330, 332, 334 destiny 402, 48, 52, 62, 116, 158, 228, 233,
theistic God of 334 240, 2534, 278, 287, 358, 36970, 3723,
claim, the (Anspruch) 2401, 466 4756
of presence 296 destruction (Destruktion) 28, 7980, 109, 124,
clearing, the (Lichtung) 31, 337, 62, 645, 111, 185, 189, 4024, 406
2046, 23841, 250, 2534, 264, 266, 280, as experience of the impossible 406
286, 345, 3645, 418, 4624, 466 of the history of ontology 55
of being 168 diffrance 4024
Cohen, Hermann 143, 145 Dilthey, Wilhelm 25, 289, 90, 113, 12934, 151,
common, world 157, 15960, 163 153, 173, 378, 473
community 40, 159, 162, 1824, 1867, 2001, directionality (Ausrichtung) 271, 3478
204, 279, 301, 338, 347, 386, 4378 disclosure 27, 65, 1057, 144, 152, 161, 184,
concealment 612, 64, 83, 166, 182, 202, 2845, 187, 1945, 2034, 225, 258, 287, 3245,
287, 300, 385, 387, 406, 418 355, 359, 3615, 457

484
Index

discourse (Rede) 3045, 378 facticity 1516, 1819, 23, 267, 29, 62, 166,
divinity (Gottheit) 329 180, 185, 189, 195, 202, 312, 314, 3302,
Dreyfus, Hubert 42530 3779, 381, 386, 389, 406
Duns Scotus 20, 234, 8990, 93, 98, 133 Christian 28
dwelling 223, 229, 2324, 266, 291, 300, 307, of life 1313
337, 3412, 34951, 382, 394, 426, 4335, self-interpretation of 28
4378, 455 faith 20, 27, 88, 934, 168, 329, 334
upon the Earth 223, 227, 232 as the natural enemy of philosophy 331
as a possibility of existence 331
earth, the 49, 58, 81, 115, 169, 2016, 223, fallenness (Verfallenheit) 27, 36, 56, 79,
2259, 2323, 261, 2856, 297301, 3058, 173
317, 3256, 334, 337, 341, 34750, 353, Fichte, Johann Gottlieb 63, 113, 117
365, 382, 4334, 4368 finitude 23, 32, 35, 37, 41, 65, 1059, 109, 147,
as indifferent to the world 202 159, 166, 212, 223, 2634, 266, 302, 321,
opaque 42 334, 395, 41112, 4547
power of 227 of being 116
as self-concealing source 202 human 106, 116, 148
Eckhart, Meister 935 inappropriable 406
ego, the 26, 979, 101, 118, 139, 238, 280, 300, insuperable 147
340, 434
foreign, the 2334, 307
as transcendental ego 17, 136, 139
journeying in 233
eidos 84, 355
forgetting, of Being 36, 83, 97, 127, 143, 154,
ek-sistence (Ek-sistenz) 62, 2378, 241, 280, 295,
192, 238, 245, 379
434
of beings 388
empathy 292
of our being-in-the-world 383
enactment 278, 131, 134, 377, 379, 395
formal indication (formale Anzeige) 152, 155n. 4,
of being 293
182, 265, 343n. 2
Ent-eignis (ex-propriation) 61, 2845, 288,
Foucault, Michel 40916, 424nn.12, 16, 18
288nn.11, 12, 302, 4056, 464
fourfold, the (das Geviert) 2436, 248, 2867,
environing world (Umwelt) 25, 80, 132, 181,
184 297302, 31718, 3345, 350, 382
Ereignis (event of appropriation) 34, 25, 327, freedom 402, 45, 11719, 159, 162, 167, 176,
43, 55, 602, 65, 81, 221, 225, 227, 2312, 220, 2601, 312, 314, 342, 358, 3701,
250, 273, 2778, 2839, 295, 3245, 349, 380, 395, 397, 414, 434, 438, 443, 447,
365, 3823, 387, 394, 4056, 414, 420, 462, 473
464 Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics, The 40,
Essence of Human Freedom, The 40, 261 148, 271, 434
essentia 238, 321, 370
ethics 102, 167, 237, 2502, 266, 2906, 394, Gadamer, Hans-Georg 16, 28, 67, 129, 133,
435, 438, 4423, 4456, 476 1659, 459, 479
of care 438 Gestalt 151, 154, 261
as originary ethics (ursprngliche as configuration 2024, 206
Ethik) 290, 412 Ge-stell, Gestell 634, 202, 2434, 248, 287,
recast in terms of being itself 295 297, 322, 340, 3545, 358, 436
everydayness (Alltglichkeit) 27, 146, 148, God, the last 43
193, 195, 273, 3867, 454 good, the 59, 175, 315, 397
evil 11617, 292, 389, 3978 and evil 117, 292, 397
as an ontological category 397 in a non-moral sense 397
as useless suffering 3978 Granel, Grard 403
existentialism 193, 238, 305, 367, 369, 373, guarding (wahren) 241
4734, 479 and unguarding (Verwahrlosung) 245

485
Index

Haar, Michel 273n. 1, 372, 438 imagination, power of (Einbildungskraft) 1089,


Habermas, Jrgen 166 111
happening 25, 59, 63, 168, 2045, 220, 262, 278, inauthenticity 40, 167, 1723, 292, 387, 395
3456, 349, 405 intentionality 20, 13640, 427, 429
of being 39, 225, 227, 329 originary (originre Intentionalitt) 26
of truth 58, 260, 262, 357, 365 intimacy (Innigkeit) 229
Hartmann, Nicolai 29, 473 Introduction to Metaphysics 42, 578, 93,
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 41, 51, 57, 60, 20713, 225, 233, 275, 279, 293, 303, 315,
63, 65, 8990, 108, 11319, 123, 127, 143, 340, 437
166, 172, 191, 197, 205, 217, 250, 254, 259, intuition 245, 65, 131, 137, 377, 3812, 411
319, 329, 331, 353, 371, 381, 387, 393, 409, categorial 136, 1389, 363
418, 421, 4419 hermeneutic 25
Heraclitus 41, 58, 77, 835, 105, 21011, 213, pure forms of 144
316, 3634, 447 inventive thinking (Er-denken) 293
hermeneutics 25, 28, 99, 106, 129, 1657, 184, Irigaray, Luce 442, 448n. 1
378, 435, 451, 475, 479
of facticity 90, 114, 1323, 185, 189, 192 Jaeger, Werner 15, 72
historicity (Geschichtlichkeit) 43, 119, 129, Janicaud, Dominique 11n. 2, 242n. 3, 4013,
1312, 144, 165, 1734, 265, 319, 322, 406n. 2
3301, 333, 335, 36970, 3779, 412, 475 Jaspers, Karl 24, 489, 53n. 8, 678, 70, 73, 372
history 42, 124 Jonas, Hans 67, 72
of being 35, 52, 612, 945, 113, 11719, 125, Jnger, Ernst 42, 712, 216, 247, 3534, 390
131, 175, 221, 2878, 315, 319, 322, 325,
370, 387, 4212, 430, 444 Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1057
as event (Geschichte) 131 Kassel lectures, the 132, 1478, 41112
as historicality 283 Kierkegaard, Sren 148, 2501
as historiography (Historie) 131
History of the Concept of Time 1356, 13940 labor 16, 41, 1734, 299, 372, 41012
Hlderlin, Friedrich 423, 58, 113, 121, 1689, Marxist concept of 173
205, 207, 21718, 220, 2235, 2456, 253, language 85, 226
299, 3078, 326, 329, 335, 358, 382, 409, as the belonging together of the human and
438, 4745 Being 242
holy, the 2312, 237, 300, 3345 as the house of being 237, 241
home, at 2323, 248, 349, 351, 437, 4467, 454 retrieval of 410
and not at-home 438, 446, 449n. 17, 454 Lask, Emil 23, 25, 89, 96n. 7, 143
homeland, the 2279, 2313, 243 Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm 48, 51, 92, 99, 119,
homelessness 238, 253, 342, 349, 351, 438 124, 1278, 271, 434
Horkheimer, Max 171, 386, 390, 391n. 6 Letter on Humanism 62, 645, 68, 115, 158,
Hule 84 167, 215, 23742, 266, 2913, 36973,
Human Condition, The 157, 160 402
humanism 36, 23742, 369, 474, 4767 Levinas, Emmanuel 291, 3939, 401, 477
Husserl, Edmund 23, 245, 29, 67, 70, 73, 87, life 1617, 24, 26
8991, 98, 13541, 171, 180, 191, 193, 250, as factical 278, 1313, 184
270, 272, 3034, 306, 322, 362, 3701, 381, and life-philosophy (Lebensphilosophie) 128,
393, 402, 452, 473, 476 130
and the lived-body (Leib) 2701, 273n.2,
idealism 25, 99, 11819, 123, 209, 339, 373 274n. 5, 351
absolute 118 and lived experience (Erlebnis) 24, 130, 154,
German 89, 11320, 124, 258, 357 247, 270
transcendental 1445 metaphysical concept of 51
Identity and Difference 61, 287, 288n. 2 as original factic life experience 17

486
Index

as the primary phenomenon (Leben need (Brauch) 323, 62, 64, 77, 79, 81, 159,
Urphnomen) 27 27880, 283, 285, 389
religious 27, 183 reciprocity of 324, 367
and zoe 16 Neurath, Otto 154
Logical Investigations 1356, 138 nihilism 70, 88, 102, 121, 124, 1257, 207, 209,
Logos 83 213, 2534, 315, 317, 319, 3213, 326, 334,
Lwith, Karl 7, 1819, 53n. 7, 678, 702, 337, 342, 349, 463
267n.6, 386 active 124
Lukcs, Georg 172, 372 otherworldly 321, 326n. 4, 327n. 14
Luther, Martin 25, 30n. 10, 91, 93 Nishida, Kitar 4623, 468
Nishitani, Keiji 460, 467
machination (Machenschaft) 119, 21920, nothing, the 1512, 154, 31118, 323, 340,
247, 284, 287, 294, 34950 4638
Marburg School, the 1434, 147 as origin of negation 145
Marcuse, Herbert 1716, 213n.1, 391n. 6
Marx, Karl 1723, 353, 371, 387, 388, 391n. 9, Okrent, Mark 257, 425, 42830, 431n. 10
409 ontological difference, the 18, 557, 602, 80,
Marxism 44, 172, 238, 370, 3723, 474 94, 99, 118, 131, 219, 250, 2656, 316, 332,
meaning, of being 34, 39, 434, 7880, 100, 394, 402, 41819, 463, 479
107, 109, 114, 121, 125, 184, 192, 209, 213, ontotheology 31928, 32934
openness 1718, 30, 336, 56, 64, 86, 111, 204,
273, 2757, 33940, 355, 402, 404, 413, 428
216, 2401, 244, 260, 2656, 2723, 2767,
meaningfulness 17, 317, 1523, 179, 185, 320,
280, 283, 295, 300, 312, 342, 345, 365, 382,
348, 356
387, 38990, 404, 464
of life 1801
of finite being 266
meaninglessness 25, 152, 313, 319
thrown 337
Merleau-Ponty, Maurice 270, 272, 3712,
orderability (Bestellbarkeit) 634, 244
37783, 402, 476
Origin of the Work of Art, The 42, 578, 62,
Metaphysical Foundations of Logic, The 102n.1,
169, 199206, 224, 257, 262, 266, 303,
266
3056, 341, 347, 350, 463, 475
Metontology 37n. 4, 266, 267n. 8
Ortega y Gasset, Jos 353, 4734
mineness (Jemeinigkeit) 133, 196, 264, 266, 386, ousia 15, 55, 58, 63, 80, 110, 355, 380, 404
396
Misch, Georg 72, 1334 Parmenides 589, 79, 83, 21113, 251, 316, 320,
moods 82, 1514, 185, 194, 263, 269, 2712, 363
299, 31314, 378, 394, 406, 453, 457 Parousia 27, 182
morality 2912, 397, 443, 448n. 4 people, the 6, 413, 209, 211, 227, 229, 232,
mortals, the 2978, 3001, 306, 308, 31718, 279, 321, 422, 447
3345, 350, 382 phenomenology, of the inapparent
mourning 227, 456 (Phnomenologie des Unscheinbaren) 5,
holy 227 165, 339, 406
mystery, the (Geheimnis) 11, 35, 37, 230, 251, Phenomenology of Intuition and Expression 27,
314, 461, 464 130, 377, 379
glimpse into 37 Pindar 218, 228, 233
mythic Dasein 146 Plato 21, 36, 51, 558, 634, 778, 87, 98, 114,
11819, 1278, 166, 179, 1834, 191, 208,
National Socialism 4, 39, 412, 44, 47, 4852, 211, 213, 251, 269, 31516, 3201, 333,
70, 114, 1456, 155n. 11, 162, 1712, 364, 406, 419, 476
2078, 213, 223, 237, 242n. 2, 373, 386, Platonism 42, 589, 61, 63, 128, 211, 223, 321,
395, 422, 434, 435, 478 41819
Natorp, Paul 25, 289, 72, 143, 378 reversal of 59, 122, 127

487
Index

Plessner, Helmuth 1334 Rorty, Richard 257, 322, 326n. 6, 425, 42930
poetizing (Dichtung) 207, 2231, 233, 334 ruinance 181, 406
Polemos 41, 21013, 364
power 39, 42, 58, 63, 119, 1589, 161, 168, 172, Sartre, Jean-Paul 678, 72, 167, 193, 276,
227, 229, 245, 2934, 358, 410, 455, 457, 36975, 393, 402, 419
464 Scheler, Max 7, 25, 29, 67, 473
of the earth 437 Schelling, Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph 113, 11619,
enabling 1589, 348, 350 122, 217, 261, 357, 397, 468
saving 226, 253, 354, 358, 434 Schleiermacher, Friedrich 90, 259, 330
of thinking 293 Schopenhauer, Arthur 143, 153, 224, 465, 473
will to 48, 52, 95, 102, 15860, 3212, 333, self, the 267, 43, 978, 132, 15960, 173, 185,
357, 433 252, 279, 396, 398, 466, 468
Presocratics, the 579, 211 as self-world 132, 181, 184, 193
primordial science (Urwissenschaft) 24, 180 selfhood 32, 424, 45n. 6, 279, 312, 456
publicity 160 Seneca 87
of a common world 160, 217 sheltering (Bergung) 82, 845, 161, 219, 241,
286, 3501
race 48, 52, 422, 4424, 478 shock (Erschrecken) 43, 81, 284
biology of 489 Simmel, Georg 25
realism 25, 337 situatedness (Befindlichkeit) 269, 438, 453
reciprocity (Gegenschwung) 327 sociality 266, 462
Rectoral address, the 49, 59, 242n. 4 Sojourns: The Journey to Greece 77
reduction, the 17, 136, 139 Sophocles
phenomenological 139, 378 Antigone 207, 212, 225, 2323, 4419
reification 1513, 1714, 176 spatiality 99, 148, 193, 34550
relationality 197, 23940, 2456, 248, 301, 456 of the body 380, 462
of finitude 4556 Spencer, Herbert 51, 473
of things 297, 299, 302 Spengler, Oswald 353, 409
releasement (Gelassenheit) 4, 6, 32, 39, 254, 342, standing reserve (das Bestand) 63, 2446, 248,
438, 464 300, 302, 341, 436
remembrance 217, 2247, 2302, 303, 3078 step back, the 387, 468n. 3, 470n. 34
requisitioning (das Bestellen) 244, 245 struggle for existence, the 6, 4950
res cogitans 98101, 381 subjectivity 44, 52, 63, 98, 101, 113, 117, 138,
res extensa 98, 1001, 350, 381 165, 239, 241, 2767, 27980, 2934, 339,
resistance 1302, 167, 192 380, 396, 425, 434, 438
and factical life 1313 Kantian 165
resoluteness (Entschlossenheit) 32, 345, 125, overcoming of 277
253, 366n. 12, 3956
responsibility 159, 246, 292, 294 techne 84, 175, 200, 212, 3401, 3539
for being 2946 technology 63, 1256, 144, 1545, 158, 167,
as the cobelonging of being and Dasein 296 172, 1746, 201, 209, 213, 226, 2447,
restraint (Verhaltenheit) 81, 284 2503, 287, 300, 302, 324, 337, 33941,
reversal, the 32, 345, 62, 160, 231, 277 3539, 363, 387, 433, 4356, 462, 4767,
Richardson, William 23, 34, 689, 277 479
Rickert, Heinrich 12, 7, 235, 48, 50, 67, 70, and technicity 174
89, 143, 149n. 3 telos of 174
rift (Ri) 2024 thaumazein (wonder) 81
between world and earth 201 They, the (das man) 173, 195, 395, 426, 454
and rift-design 201 thing, the 32, 145, 21516, 2436, 248, 297,
right 114, 160 299, 3012, 342, 346, 362
and the right to have rights 157, 1623 as thing-in-itself (Ding an sich) 145

488
Index

thrownness (Geworfenheit) 336, 62, 146, 194, understanding (verstehen) 130, 165, 378
238, 2645, 278, 31112, 388, 394, 396, understanding of Being (Seinsverstndnis) 23,
406, 457 39, 789, 989, 1057, 110, 144, 208, 238,
time-space (Zeitraum) 44, 64, 2034, 225, 284, 257, 269, 2768, 280, 31920, 3223,
316, 3479, 382 3256, 334, 339, 3556, 364, 369, 425, 428,
Towards the Definition of Philosophy 265 452
transcendence 17, 567, 60, 62, 107, 109, 176, as the ground of the possibility of the essence
279, 283, 312, 314, 321, 434, 467 of the human being 277
transcendental idealism 1445 useless, the 293
truth 58, 83, 3617
as adequatio intellectus et rei 83, 124 Van Gogh, Vincent 2578, 260, 3256
as aletheia 589, 64, 83, 182, 211, 3635, 381, Volk, the 39, 41, 434, 49, 262, 265
464 Vorhandenheit 78, 101, 3557
of being 3, 6, 35, 37, 39, 44, 5860, 62, 65,
102, 204, 23841, 250, 261, 2768, 2801, Welte, Bernhard 702, 95, 96n. 18
283, 291, 2945, 325, 334, 364, 383, 405, What is Called Thinking? 86n. 2, 121, 225, 252,
457, 4678 338, 341, 4201
of beyng 278, 2837, 3878 What Is Metaphysics? 56, 151, 1534, 275,
as essentially earthy (erdhaft) 199 31112, 314, 340, 437, 463, 467, 474
and untruth 182, 195, 406 Who are we? 3945, 279
Truth and Method 165, 167, 169nn. 1, 4 will to power 42, 48, 52, 95, 102, 103n. 7, 158,
Tsujimura, Kichi 4678 160, 3212, 357, 366n. 9, 399n. 33, 433
turn, the (die Kehre) 6, 318, 80, 234, 246, unconditional 159
2778 Will to Power, The 48, 50, 122, 124, 126, 333
Windelband, Wilhelm 25, 143
uncanniness 6, 233, 264, 342, 4467, 4545 Wittgenstein, Ludwig 303, 430
uncanny, the (das Unheimliche) 212, 233, 275, worldview (Weltanschauung) 245, 130, 180,
307, 364, 441, 444, 4467, 454 347
unconcealment 31, 43, 62, 83, 158, 160, 1656, Greek 28
203, 205, 211, 249, 254, 25860, 387, 406, medieval 20
418, 436
of the concealment 284 zoon logon echon 16, 183

489

Вам также может понравиться