Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 24

2015 | Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 5 (1): 227250

SPECIAL SECTION

Kinship, equality, and hierarchy


Sex distinction and values in comparative
perspective

Ccile Barraud, Centre Asie du Sud-Est, Centre


National de la Recherche Scientifique et cole des
Hautes tudes en Sciences Sociales, Paris

This article deals with the notion of equality in Louis Dumonts work, specifically relative
to ideology and sex distinction in kinship terminology. It provides a new reading of his
writings on kinship, analyzing his discussion of South Indian terminology and marriage,
the contrasting value of affinity and consanguinity in caste society, and equality of the sexes.
Dumonts works on kinship are used to open a comparative examination of sex distinction
in kinship terminology. This article seeks to extend this analysis of equality and hierarchy
in kinship to other societies and ideologies, in order to explore the applicability of this
approach to understanding of contemporary transformations in kinship relationships.
Keywords: value, Dumont, affinity, gender, comparison

Equality is a recurrent theme in discussions of Euro-American societies. It is both


an aspiration and an impossibility which stands in contradistinction to Euro-
American notions of power (Dumont 1986; Robbins 1994). As an aspiration, it
goes in tandem with the idea of liberty, both linked to the value of individualism,
which prevails in these societies. In his comparative works on ideologies, Louis
Dumont opposed equality to hierarchy through analysis of the Indian caste system.
He discussed the relationship between hierarchy and equality in nearly all his
texts, beginning with Homo hierarchicus (1980a). In his introduction to From
Mandeville to Marx, he contrasts hierarchy, as the paramount value of the caste sys-
tem, with equalitarianism, as one of the main values in modern societies (Dumont
1977: 3). He classifies these two systems as individualism and holism. Holism, he
explains, entails hierarchy while individualism entails equality, but this does not

 his work is licensed under the Creative Commons | Ccile Barraud.


T
ISSN 2049-1115 (Online). DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.14318/hau5.1.011
Ccile Barraud 228

indicate that all holistic societies stress hierarchy to the same degree, nor do all
individualistic societies stress equality to the same degree (ibid.: 4). Furthermore,
Dumont explains, equality and hierarchy must combine in some manner in any
social system (ibid.: 5). He claims that it is possible for equality to be valued...
without its being an entailment of individualism (ibid.: 5).
This essay grapples with this uncertain definition of equality. Is equality op-
posed to power, or to hierarchy? If, up to a certain point, equality is opposed to
power, is it the same notion of equality which can sometimes be present in a hierar-
chical ideology? And in the latter case, what is the meaning of this type of equality?
The surprising discovery of elements of equality within the hierarchal ideology of
the caste system, in Dumonts study of Dravidian kinship terminology, prompts
closer examination.
Dumonts contribution to kinship studies is substantially less known1 than his
work on ideology or caste hierarchy in India. This, however, has not always been
the case. His first published piece on kinship, in 1953, the provocative article The
Dravidian kinship terminology as an expression of marriage, elicited vivid com-
ments from A.R. Radcliffe-Brown (Dumont 1983: 1835). Since then, numerous
authors have engaged with Dumonts ideas on South Indian kinship. His approach
to kinship sparked significant debate among specialists of India and Indian kinship
regarding the nature and terminology of Dravidian kinship (see Trautmann 1981;
Rudner 1990; Parkin 1992; Pfeffer 1993; Busby 1997; Viveiros de Castro 1998). In
the piece Affinity as a value, published in English in 1983, Dumont responded to
his critics and put forth his principal arguments on affinity in an effort to end
years of contentious debate on topic (see Madan 1986 for a review).
Over the past twenty years, Dumonts ideas on kinship have resurfaced in
Amazonian anthropology. In the 1970s, Joanna Overing (1973, 1975) introduced
Dumonts Dravidian model of kinship to scholars in Amazonia. Three decades
later, Eduardo Viveiros de Castro (2001) argued for the relevance of Dumonts
arguments on equality between consanguinity and affinity in Amazonia, drawing
on Dumonts notion of affinity as a value to develop his theory of perspectivism.
His analysis diverges, however, from Dumonts model, in that Dumont argued that
equality between consanguinity and affinity gained its relevance within the hier-
archy of the caste system. Recent scholars (e.g., Gregory 2010, 2013) have again
turned their attention to the value question in India, renewing the debates on
affinity by approaching the value of other kin relations.
In this article, I examine a question largely overlooked in debates on affinity
as a value: that of the equality of the sexes in South Indian terminology, which
underlies Dumonts argument of the equivalent (equal) value of affinity and

1. Dumonts papers on kinship were often first published in English. Most of them have
been translated, including the most contentious article (Dumont 2006). This text pro-
vided a comparison between English and French kinship studies. Translation had to
face the different meanings attributed to key concepts in English and in French: the
meaning of kinship itself, and others such as descent, filiation, and so on. Parkins
Introduction (Parkin 2006) is very useful in this respect. See also my discussion at the
end of this article. Dumont himself was long opposed to a translation because of these
terminological issues.

2015 | Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 5 (1): 227250


229 Kinship, equality, and hierarchy

consanguinity. Dumont defined the notion of equality in opposition to the encom-


passing hierarchy of the caste system.2 I will examine this argument relative to his
later considerations of Western gender equality and kinship, which are relevant to
current debates on gender.
Following closely Dumonts analyses, in this text, I will make use of his own
written terms: equality between the sexes and sex distinction. In line with argu-
ments in the field of gender studies, it is first important to point out, however,
that the terms sex and gender always point to a social construct which is cul-
turally defined. While the notion of gender allows for the examination of diverse
social representations, symbols, social relationships, and so on, when used in the
context of kinship terminology, it is restricted to a category of classification, such
that sex is a more apt descriptor than gender. In this respect, the expression
sex distinction, like generation, affinity, collaterality distinctions, and so on, are
used as criteria of kinship terminological analysis. These criteria or distinctions
do not attribute any intrinsic value to kinship terms. Thus, the notion of equality
of the sexes in kinship terminology does not imply equal relations between the
genders. Following Dumont, I approach the question of equality from the narrow
perspective of kinship terminology and, as he does, deal almost exclusively with
kinship terminology rather than the kinship practices fundamental to gender stud-
ies (Busby 1997; Collier and Yanagisako 1987a). I employ the term sex distinc-
tion, as opposed to gender difference, to refer to relations between the sexes on a
strictly terminological level.
Debates in gender studies focused on kinship have yet to specifically exam-
ine kinship terminology, although the relationship between gender and kinship,
both dichotomous analytical domains, has been widely discussed and criticized
(MacCormack and Strathern 1980; Ortner and Whitehead 1981; Strathern 1987,
1988; Moore 1988; 1999; Atkinson and Errington 1990; del Valle 1993). Neither
gender nor kinship was capable of imposing the idea that all facts are cultural facts
and not natural or precultural givens. At the heart of kinship dichotomies is the an-
alytical division between domestic and politico-jural domains, which leads us
back to twentieth-century kinship theories, frequently discussed by early scholars
of gender studies. One of the notions that these scholars questioned is the biologi-
cal difference in male and female roles in sexual reproduction presumed to be at
the core of mens and womens relationships everywhere (Collier and Yanagisako
1987b: 7), such as Meyer Fortes (1949) discussion of procreation and child rear-
ing as natural facts (Yanagisako and Collier 1987: 31).3 As a social construct, the
notion of gender replaced the notion of sex and it became clear that what is meant
by gender did not refer to the biological difference between men and women. In
gender studies, sex is finally approached as one aspect of difference which in-
cludes other types of differences such as class, ethnicity, race, and religion. As nat-
ural biases and differences were progressively rejected, they have been replaced
by the study of culturally constructed social inequalities (ibid.: 15), leading to the

2. I use Dumonts definition of ideology as a configuration of ideas and values or a set of


ideas and values common to a society.
3. This question is still at the heart of kinship studies (Sahlins 2013).

2015 | Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 5 (1): 227250


Ccile Barraud 230

hypothesis that all social systems are systems of inequalities, kinship included. In
this context, it is all the more surprising that the analysis of terminologies was not
fully included in the effort to understand inequalities or differences between men
and women. Attributing a term to different types of social relationships, kinship
terminologies inevitably mark differences between relatives, more or less numer-
ous according to terminological systems, but at minimum distinguishing genera-
tion, age, and sex. What then, is the significance of these differences which are not
accounted for? Do they constitute inequalities? As modes of classification, kinship
terminologies inevitably inform the ways people are classified as relatives, without
distinguishing their roles or functions.
The examination of Dumonts works both on equality and on kinship terminol-
ogies is located at the interface of these questions. The first part of this article con-
siders Dumonts notion of equality, as presented in his comments on Tocquevilles
thoughts on egalitarian ideology and in his own writings on gender. Having clari-
fied the terms of the discussion, the central part of the article examines the inter-
section of caste hierarchy and kinship terminology. I analyze the status of affinity
and consanguinity, as well as the equality of the sexes in South Indian kinship ter-
minology. I then present my own ethnographic material from eastern Indonesia to
further explore Dumonts analysis of kinship terminology. Finally, I briefly address
Dumonts comparison of kinship terminologies in North India and Western societ-
ies, relative to ideology. In conclusion, I suggest some research directions concern-
ing the status of consanguinity and affinity in contemporary societies.

Dumonts comments on Tocquevilles notion of equality


Dumont only rarely alludes to questions of equality between men and women. One
such instance is found in his response to Tocquevilles definition of egalitarian ideol-
ogy (Dumont 1980a:13). What interests Dumont here is Tocquevilles comparative
approach. Tocqueville reflects on the American egalitarian mentality through the
eyes of a European, contrasting American ideology with what he perceived of the
hierarchical mentality in the France of the Ancien Rgime(ibid.: 15). Dumont claims
that this represents one of Tocquevillesvery important ideas, which concerns the
place of modern political ideology in relation to values as a whole (ibid.: 14).
Concerning equality, Dumont contends that for Tocqueville, The first feature
to emphasize is that the concept of the equality of men entails that of their similar-
ity (ibid.: 15). According to Tocqueville, equality thus abolishes differences, such
that all human being are alike. Dumontwrites,
So long as equality is only an ideal requirement expressing the transition
in values from man as a collective being to man as an individual, it does
not entail the denial of innate differences.4 ... But if equality is conceived
as rooted in mans very nature and denied only by an evil society, then,

4. Dumont further develops this idea in his essay On value (Dumont 1980b: 238). A
reprint of this article was published in Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory, Volume 3,
Issue 1, pp. 287315. Available here:
http://www.haujournal.org/index.php/hau/article/view/hau3.1.028

2015 | Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 5 (1): 227250


231 Kinship, equality, and hierarchy

as there are no longer any rightful differences in condition or estate, or


different sorts of men, they are all alike and even identical, as well as
equal. This is what Tocqueville says: where inequality reigns, there are
as many distinct humanities as there are social categories,... the reverse
being true in egalitarian society. (Dumont 1980a: 16)
Dumont then notes that Tocqueville seems to conflate the social form and the
natural or universal being (ibid.). He notes one exception, however, stating that
Tocqueville does make clear this distinction when he contrasts the way in which
the equality of man and woman is conceived in the United States and in France
(ibid.). Dumont then quotes this passage in Tocqueville but does not comment fur-
ther on the relationship between men and women until his discussion later in the
piece regarding hierarchical opposition.

Tocqueville and gender equality in America


Let us now turn to Tocquevilles discussion of equality (Tocqueville 1840: book 3).
Following chapters devoted to masters and servants and to kindred relations,
Tocqueville considers the education of young women and The young woman
in the character of a wife. Throughout these four chapters, he repeatedly praises
American women for their indomitable energy, the firmness of their reason, their
fearlessness, courage, and freedom of choice. In chapter XII, titled How the
Americans understand the equality of the sexes, Tocqueville juxtaposes several
dyadic relationships. He states, I believe that the social changes which bring nearer
to the same level the father and son, the master and servant, and superiors and infe-
riors generally speaking, will raise woman and make her more and more the equal
of man. As Franois Furet (1981: 32) has pointed out, for Tocqueville, equality of
conditions
does not mean that master and servant are really equal, but that they
can be, or that the provisional relationship of subordination does not
constitute a state that completely defines each, because, for example, it
can be reversed according to their mutual success. Since the servant can
become master, and aspires to become master, the servant is not different
from the master,
they hold the same rights, the servant a citizen like the master. It is important to
note here that these dyadic relationships are not equivalent: the servant may be-
come a master, but by nature the son cannot become his own father (see Dumonts
remark above regarding the conflation of the social form and the natural or uni-
versal being). But with regard to men and women, the question of equality and
similarity arises differently in Tocqueville. He criticizes those in Europe, who con-
founding together the different characteristics of the sexes, would make of man
and woman beings not only equal but alike (Tocqueville 1840: book 3, ch. XII).
He asserts that by thus attempting to make one sex equal to the other, both are
degraded; and from so preposterous a medley of the works of nature nothing
could ever result but weak men and disorderly women. He continues, explaining
that nature has appointed such wide differences between the physical and moral

2015 | Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 5 (1): 227250


Ccile Barraud 232

constitution of man and woman. Tocqueville asserted that there were natural au-
thorities in families and there was a natural head of the conjugal association.
This is clearly a question of gendered functions, duties, and rights in the marital
context, or marital power that should not be subverted. Tocqueville claims that,
In no country has such constant care been taken as in America to trace two clearly
distinct lines of action for the two sexes, and to make them keep pace one with the
other, but in two pathways which are always different (ibid.). And yet, Tocqueville
found that Americans held women in high esteem, noting their confidence in the
understanding of a wife, and profound respect for her freedom (ibid.).
Women pose a problem for Tocqueville, which points to issues still debated to
this day concerning equality, similarity, difference, and subordination.5 He con-
cludes chapter XII saying, Thus the Americans do not think that man and woman
have either the duty or the right to perform the same offices, but they show an
equal regard for both their respective parts; and though their lot is different, they
consider both of them as beings of equal value.
And yet, he asserts that whilst they have allowed the social inferiority of wom-
an to subsist, they have done all they could to raise her morally and intellectually
to the level of man. He finally claims that the singular prosperity and growing
strength of that people ought mainly to be attributed ... to the superiority of their
women (ibid.), offering no further comments on this assertion.
On the one hand, Tocqueville highlights a tension between the existence of
an egalitarian mentality and the dissimilarity of women and men, which reveals
the limits of this equality. On the other, he insists on the equal worth of men and
women, and, surprisingly, the superiority of women, which simultaneously contra-
dicts equality.
According to Tocqueville, mens and womens roles contrast specifically in the
context of marriage, their positions as husbands and wives. He views gender dif-
ferences as limited to their roles given by nature. He insists that there is comple-
mentarity, whatever their difference (dissimilarity), but finds that this feature does
not exclude a certain equality in social worth. This raises the question: Outside the
context of marriage and conjugal roles, what, then, prevents the equality of men
and women?
Scholars have suggested various interpretations of this passage. Furet (1981: 33)
contends that Tocqueville insists on equality of conditions as a constitutive princi-
ple of democratic social order ... a norm and not a fact. Marcel Gauchet (1980: 99)
states that equality as a principle and an ideal cannot account for the differences
that manifest themselves at another level; difference, especially the real division of
sexes, is not cancelled, but relegated to the background. He asserts that this is not
an ontological difference, but that this difference is at the same time deprived of
its substance and yet assumed so that its presence does not prevent any adult from
finding similarity with the other he dominates (ibid.). In contrast, Dumont, who
highlights Tocquevilles conflation of the social and the natural form, or universal

5. Debates since the 1980s (see, e.g., Ortner and Whitehead 1981; Collier and Yanagisako
1987a; Moore 1988) have addressed social systems of inequality, treating difference as
a social construction defined by each society. I have discussed these questions at length
in Barraud (2001) and in Als and Barraud (2001).

2015 | Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 5 (1): 227250


233 Kinship, equality, and hierarchy

being, commentsthat, In general, ... we may grasp here, in Tocqueville himself,


how the ideal is made immanent and reified, in the way characteristic of the mod-
ern democratic mentality. The fusion of equality and identity has become estab-
lished at the level of common sense (Dumont 1980a: 16).
Thus far, we have examined Dumonts discussion of the ideal of equality in com-
parison with Tocquevilles notion of (gender) equality and one of his very impor-
tant ideas, which concerns the place of modern political ideology in relation to
values as a whole (ibid.: 14). To summarize, Tocqueville views equality as rooted
in mans nature and claims that men are alike and thus equal. He distinguishes,
however, between men and women, whom he considers different by nature, but of
equal value. Dumont is critical of this notion of equality, which he suggests merges
equality and identity, reifying the democratic ideal.

Dumont on the relationship between men and women: A hierarchical


opposition
In this section, I examine Dumonts theories on malefemale relationships relative
to equality and hierarchy. I base my analysis on his discussion of kinship terminol-
ogy and refrain from making claims regarding gendered social practices in con-
temporary India.
First, when mentioning status (which he also refers to as value), Dumont
distinguishes equistatutory oppositions from what he calls hierarchical opposi-
tion. He developed this contrast over the course of his career, drawing on Harold
Conklins notion of paradigm (Dumont 1979, 1980b: 21314, 1983: 2628). In
equistatutory oppositions, neither status is superior to the other. Dumont contrasts
this relationship to hierarchical oppositions, which he illustrates using the example
of the right and left hands (Dumont 1979: 807). Right vs. left is a common binary
opposition that organizes ideas and representations in a great number of societies
(see Hertz 1973 and Needham 1973, for example). For Dumont, the right and left
hands do not occupy the same status or position relative to the rest of the body.
They exist thus in a nonequistatutory relation, a hierarchal opposition in which
egalitarianism is not in place (Dumont 1979: 806). Although right and left do not,
therefore, have the same value, this does not suggest the universal superiority of
one over the other. This hierarchal relationship may be reversed, but is constitutive
of both hands and their relationship to the body.
Dumont draws a parallel between the right and left opposition and the way
men and women are distinguished in the Old Testament story of the creation of
Eve from a part of Adams body (Dumont 1980a: 23940, 1980b: 225). Adam is the
prototypical Man, who represents mankind, which includes both men and women
who are identical as human beings. On another level, however, Adam is opposed to
Eve, as male is to female and man to woman. Unity on one level thus coexists with
opposition on a second level. Dumont (1980a: 240) argues that these two relations
characterize the hierarchical relation which exists, between a whole (or a set)
and an element of this whole (or set): the element belongs to the set and is in this
sense consubstantial or identical with it; at the same time, the element is distinct
from the set or stands in opposition to it. He contends that by subordinating one

2015 | Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 5 (1): 227250


Ccile Barraud 234

element to another, the hierarchical principle introduces a multiplicity of levels,


which allows for the reversal of status. With regard to the hierarchical unit of male/
female couples and the possible reversal of position at different levels, he says: The
mother of the family (an Indian family, for example)inferior though she may be
made by her sex in some respectsnonetheless dominates the relationships within
the family (ibid.: 24041). To illustrate this type of reversal, Dumont mentions
that in India, while the priest is superior to the king in matters of religion, ...
the priest must obey the king in matters of public order, which he characterizes
as subordinated matters (Dumont 1980b: 225). He follows with this surprising
comment: One might say, from an egalitarian viewpoint, that traditional societies
are made bearable by these reversals (Dumont 1980a: 241).
Dumonts approach to male/female relations contrasts with Tocquevilles. Rather
than directly addressing the question of equality (which he introduces only later), in
this context he theorizes distinctions which lead to the reversal of status positions.
Focusing on the reversal of levels allows Dumont to avoid Tocquevilles conflation
of equality and identity. Tocquevilles response to the tension between his claims of
equality and empirical dissimilarities between men and women (wide differences
in roles, functions, and destinies) was to introduce the notion of womens moral
value and women and mens equal worth.
Dumont deals with the relationship between men and women from the point of
view of the unity of the couple as a whole. In the postface of Homo hierarchicus, he
states clearly: You may well declare both sexes equal, but the more you manage to
make them equal, the more you will destroy the unity between them (in the couple
or family) because the principle of this unit is outside them and because, as such, it
necessarily hierarchizes them with respect to one another (ibid.: 24041, emphasis
in original).6
In other passages, Dumont refers explicitly to womens lower status overall in
the Indian context, saying that woman is in general considered inferior to the
man (ibid.: 117). He also describes this lower-status position in his discussion of
marriage, in reference to endogamy (marriage within the caste) and hypergamy
(marriage of a woman of a slightly inferior status with a man of a slightly superior
status from which the womans family draws prestige). Following Dumont, I now
turn my attention to the question of endogamy in India and hierarchy, in an ef-
fort to address questions of status in relation to marriage and to the malefemale
relationship.

Kinship in India and hierarchy


In the previous section, I introduced questions of female subordination, as ana-
lyzed in Dumonts work on India, and explored the ways he analyzed hierarchical
distinction, both at the logical level (Adam and Eve) and regarding relationships
and status within the caste system. I shift now to the question of kinship criteria,

6. A French philosopher, Vincent Descombes (1999), analyzed and developed these


aspects of equality in a comment on Dumonts discourse pronounced when he was
awarded the Tocqueville Prize in 1987.

2015 | Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 5 (1): 227250


235 Kinship, equality, and hierarchy

including sex distinctions, within the framework of caste, in an effort to offer a new
perspective on questions of hierarchy and equality.
Endogamy is one of the principles underlying the separation of castes, which, by
definition, appears to exclude hierarchy within the caste itself. The nature of caste
hierarchies has been long debated in scholarship on India. Dumont (1980a: 43)
sees the separation of castes as reducible to a single true principle, namely the
opposition of the pure and the impure. This opposition underlies hierarchy, which
is the superiority of the pure to the impure, underlies separation because the pure
and the impure must be kept separated, and underlies the division of labor because
pure and impure occupations must likewise be kept separate. How, then, might we
grapple with differences of status within endogamous castes or subcastes? If castes
are separate owing to their differences in status, it would seem that a given status
would be extended throughout a given caste. This is where Dumont begins his
study of marriage.
Dumont addresses several aspects of hierarchy in his discussion of marriage in
India. First, he considers the relationship between castes and kinship (including
affinity), examining to what extent the ideology of hierarchy influences the field
of kinship (ibid.: 11213). A second aspect, related to the first, is whether or not
kinship configurations, specifically kinship terminologya circumscribed do-
maincomprise hierarchical oppositions. Dumonts aim here is to shed light on
the relationship between the ideology of caste hierarchy and domains which are
not directly determined by it. His writings on kinship introduce theories that he
developed more fully later on, concerning hierarchy, comparison, the need to de-
part from our own ways of thinking in kinship analysis, the limits of generalization,
and the importance of reconsidering ones own analyses in response to discussion
and critique.
I will begin with Dumonts famous article Hierarchy and marriage alliance in
South Indian kinship (1957).7 This title makes clear Dumonts attempt to grapple
with the relationship between ideological hierarchy and forms of marriage. I draw
on this text to highlight his treatment of sex distinction in the limited but influen-
tial domain of kinship terminology (as subsystems of kinship in general) (Dumont
1983: 23). To justify his approach, Dumont often insists on the specificity of kinship
terminology, as a clearly bounded, simply patterned, indigenous system of catego-
ries (ibid., emphasis in original). He asserts that in kinship terminology one finds
the terms in which the people actually think their kinship relationships, and they
are for us more important ... because the terms in which the people actually think
are more important than what they say ... about the terms in which they think that
they are thinking (ibid.: 2324).
In this article Dumont first seeks to establish the common character among
subcastes close to one another in the caste hierarchy, who nonetheless diverge in
terms of kinship characteristics (descent, residence, marriage rules, etc.) (ibid.: 36).
Dumonts second goal was to find, within the internal constitution of the caste
group, something of the principles that govern its [hierarchal] external rela-
tions (ibid.: 37). He examined whether caste hierarchy was also present in kinship

7. Hierarchy and marriage alliance in South Indian kinship was published in French in
1975 (Dumont 1975a) and reprinted in Affinity as a value (Dumont 1983).

2015 | Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 5 (1): 227250


Ccile Barraud 236

terminology. He finds that while kinship institutions(i.e., internal relationships)


show differences, caste hierarchy (i.e., external relationships) reveals closeness in
a common social pattern (ibid.: 36). Dumont then asks how kinship and caste
might be related. He suggests that the relationship is organized at two distinct lev-
els, irrelevant to each other, on which the interconnection of features could be
studied, namely the caste system on the one hand, and the endogamous group on
the other (ibid.: 52).
Dumont questions the notion that status unity exists within endogamous castes
or subcastes. His study focuses on the gradation of status within subcastes ac-
cording to subdivisions in terms of territorial units, lineage, and exogamous units
(ibid.: 48). These distinctions illustrate a tendency toward internal hierarchization,
founded on and manifest in forms of marriage. He suggests that intracaste hierar-
chy may be found, for instance, in primary or secondary unions, irregular unions
of seniors, marriage of leaders, and of men of high-status subcastes. These exam-
ples illustrate how, in South India, the tendency to graded statuses does not stop
at the boundary of the endogamous group, but enters it and finally pervades the
whole sphere of kinship, so that in South India kinship cannot be severed from the
caste system (ibid.: 42). Dumont qualifies this statement: in South India the kin-
ship system is (relatively) isolated from caste (there is an overlap or two systems
of conceptions (ibid.: 42 n. 3, emphasis in original). This is not the case in North
India, where there is a closer relationship between kinship and caste. Nor is this the
case in kinship terminology, as we will see in the following section.

Marriage and affinity


After examining the common characteristics of these groups, Dumont analyzes
kinship features in each (succession, inheritance, residence, descent, and marriage
rule), which he then groups in a comparative table. Despite the differences between
the subcastes, he observes common characteristics of kinship throughout. Beyond
a paternal or maternal principle (patri- or matrifiliation), there is a combination of
paternal or maternal features, which, he suggests, do not constitute a second de-
scent principle (as argued by many Dravidian kinship studies). Dumont therefore
seeks to understand the nature of this combination or additional feature, which
appears to him to be related to intermarriage and affinity.
Dumont uses the term affinity to designate the kinship link created by mar-
riage (parent par alliance in French; see Needhams 1960 discussion on this topic).
Unlike the notion of kinship in English, in its common usage the French term
parent (kinship) includes both affinity and consanguinity (see Dumont 1971 in
Parkin 2006). For comparative purposes, Dumont defines blood relatives as all
those who are not affines (in contrast with French law, which designates only pa-
ternal kin as such). In this respect, consanguinity is not biologically determined,
but depends on social recognition (Dumont 1971: 15, in Parkin 2006: 4).
One then must consider marriage not as a secondary product of other insti-
tutions such as descent ... (residence, etc.), [for] there is rather an interrelation
(Dumont 1983: 71). To this end, Dumont argues that the study of South Indian
kinship must simultaneously consider both the marriage rules and the features of the

2015 | Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 5 (1): 227250


237 Kinship, equality, and hierarchy

kinship vocabulary revealed by the analysis. If one expresses a rule as marriage with
the mothers brothers daughter, Dumont explains, it appears as a rule for deriving
a mans marriage from a relationship excluding any idea of marriage of affinity, i.e.
from a relationship of consanguinity (ibid.). However, if the rule is interpreted as a
feature of affinity, it takes on another meaning. It then expresses a condition ... to
maintain a certain form of intermarriage8 (ibid.: 72). He thus claims that the rule is
not an instrument allowing one to deduce a secondary category (a marriage) from
a primary category (a consanguinity relationship) (ibid.: 71). Rather, this regula-
tion determines ones marriage by reference to ones ascendants marriage, which
means reproducing the marriage of ones father (or ones grandfather according to
the form of marriage) if the rule is maintained (ibid.: 72). The consequence of the
rule in the case of South India is that affinity (kinship through marriage) is trans-
mitted from one generation to the other. It thus acquires a diachronic dimension,
which Western systems only attribute to consanguinity.9
On the contrary, in Western systems, while the relationship of a man to his
brother-in-law is an affinity relation, the relation between their children is a con-
sanguinity relation, described by the kinship term cousins. Dumont easily dem-
onstrates that it is not true in South India, where both children inherit the affinity
relation of their fathers. Children are linked to each other by affinity, a relation
transmitted from generation to generation, such that cousins in Western terms
are brothers-in-law or potential brothers-in-law.

Kinship vocabulary and sex distinction


Having identified the diachronic character of affinity, Dumont claims that one
must take into account the interrelationship between marriage rules and kinship
terminology in order to understand the role played by the sex distinction. In all the
subgroups Dumont studied in South India, kinship terminologies are character-
ized by an absolute distinction of the sexes in the three central generations and/
or in age groups. More importantly, these terminologies do not comprise specific
terms characteristic of affinity, like father-in-law and mother-in-law. There is a sin-
gle term for both the maternal uncle (mothers brother) and the father-in-law, who
are one and the same person in unions which follow the rule of preferential mar-
riage, in which a man should ideally marry the daughter of his mothers brother.
In the same manner, there is a single term for the paternal aunt (fathers sister)
and the mother-in-law (treating the fathers sister as an affine, in this way, has been

8. The French version adds: of a certain type of affinity (Dumont 1975a: 48).
9. Whenever I use the expressions with us, our systems, we Westerners, our/their,
and so on, or whenever I quote Dumont using these expressions, it must be recalled
that Dumont, since his earliest analyses, always advocated the analysis of the subject
studied (caste, kinship, hierarchy, ideology, etc.) with the anthropologists own society,
culture, ideology, and so on (see, e.g., his introduction to Homo hierarchicus). He as-
serts that anthropology has the aim of putting modern society in perspective in rela-
tion to the societies which have preceded it or which co-exist with it, and of making in
this way a direct and central contribution to our general education (Dumont 1980a: 2).

2015 | Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 5 (1): 227250


Ccile Barraud 238

considered highly controversial, see, e.g., Dumonts 1983 response to Radcliffe-


Brown). Dumonts analysis shows that in the three central generations and/or in
age groups, kinship terminology distinguishes two categories of parents of each
sex: on the one hand, parents connected to the referent or ego of each sex by con-
sanguinity; on the other, parents of each sex connected to ego by affinity. Thus,
there is a term for a male egos fathers, on the one hand, and a term for fathers male
affines, on the other (but not maternal uncles). There is one term for brothers and
another for brothers-in law (but not cousins). Similarly for women, there is a term
for female egos mothers on one side and a term for mothers female affines on the
other (but not paternal aunts), one term for sisters and another for sisters-in law
(but not cousins).
Dumont thus proposes that in these three generations, each sex has its own set
of kinship terms for consanguines and affines. He asserts, There is likely to be an
affinal content in terms which are generally considered to connote consanguinity,
or genealogical relationships (such as mothers brother, etc.). This is obviously so
when there are no special terms for affines, for otherwise we should have to admit
that in such cases affinity is not expressed at all10 (Dumont 1957: 25, 1983: 73).
In these South Indian terminologies, at the central generations, when there
are two male terms that indicate affinity, the two female terms are completely
distinct. One sees that the distinction of sex and the alliance distinction go to-
gether (Dumont 1957: 26, 1975a: 51, 1983: 74). Where there is no sex distinc-
tion, as is the case beyond the third generation, there is no affinity distinction
either. Thus it is the combination of sex and affinity distinctions that orders the
terminology in these central generations or age groups. Strictly speaking, affinity
relationships exist exclusively between persons of the same sex. Dumont insists
several times on this feature of the Dravidian terminology, arguing that sex dis-
tinction is absolute.
From this, he draws the unexpected conclusion that the perfect symmetry be-
tween the sexes, which he claims one might call a superb invention, transcribes
in terms of equality the segregation of the sexes in social life (1983: 24). Regard-
ing caste, he adds, South Indian kinship presents us with a contrast of that sort:
something like an island of equality in an ocean of caste (ibid.: 167), again mak-
ing reference to Conklins distinction between a paradigm (equistatutory opposi-
tion) and a hierarchy comprised of successive levels of inclusion. He specifies later,
saying,
The grid of categories is determined by a specific conjunction of the
consanguines/affines opposition with the absolute distinction of (equal)
sexes. In other words, the alliance relationship provides the backbone of
the classification of relatives. Here is the island of equality, even though
the ocean of hierarchy invades it here and there, with the effect of adding
status within the framework. (Dumont 1983: 168)
This leads Dumont back to the hypothesis he introduced in Hierarchy and marriage
Alliance (1975a, 1983) regarding his attempt to understand whether caste hierarchy

10. The French version (Dumont 1975a: 50) adds, in the vocabulary while marriage rules
specifically emphasize its importance.

2015 | Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 5 (1): 227250


239 Kinship, equality, and hierarchy

penetrates all social domains (kinship, marriage, etc.).11 He asserts that, within
kinship proper, i.e. within the domain defined through the system of kinship cat-
egories, hierarchy plays its role within a framework it does not determine, and is
thus conceptually subordinate to kinship (Dumont 1983: 168).
The suggestion that equality in India manifests itself through the absolute dis-
tinction of (equal) sexes is surprising in light of Dumonts acknowledgment that
sex distinctions are inherently hierarchical (the hierarchical opposition between
man and womansupra Adam and Eve). For Dumont, the hierarchical distinction
applies to a particular type of unit (the couple) or relationship (between husband
and wife). It must thus be conceptually differentiated from the perfect equality of
the sexes in South Indian terminology. The latter is an analytical and conceptual
equality that exists within kinship terminology. Gender equality in kinship termi-
nology does not entail equity of social relations between men and women. Nor is
it the type of equality Dumont discussed in the context of individualism. Here he
defines equality as perfect symmetry between the sexes, which he opposes to
the segregation of the sexes in social life (ibid.: 24). I suggest, however, that this is
an equality that exists solely outside of any social relation. This type of equality, like
that in individualism, separates each individual from the others, given that the two
sexes are separated in the South Indian affinity terminology.
As is often the case in Dumonts theories, these matters are not black or white.
Here equality is present without it being an entailment of individualism. Equality
of the sexes, or the perfect similitude in the treatment of sexes, in conjunction with
the axial distinction ibid.: 28), is emphasized in that affinity has equal status with
consanguinity, or a value equal to it (ibid.: vii, emphasis in original). At this point,
the kinship terminology does not hierarchize the sexes.
Dumont insists on the perfect equivalence and the equal status of consanguinity
and affinity in this system (ibid.: vii and 170). Values are, by definition, consid-
ered durable. While Western affinity is ephemeral (see above Dumont 1971: 15,
in Parkin 2006: 4), South Indian affinity is permanent, possessing a value equal to
that of consanguinity (Dumont 1983: vii). In India, although hierarchy penetrates
subcaste endogamy (seen in the different statuses within the subcaste itself), in kin-
ship terminologies, equality of the sexes and of affinity and consanguinity prevails.
Returning to Conklins paradigm once more and to the equistatutory opposition,
Dumont (1983: 26) states that it is a configuration in which no hierarchical dis-
tinction of levels is found.12
Dumont concludes, Let me state again that this analysis claims to deal only
with the basic level of distinction in the vocabularyequal status of consanguinity
and affinityand to thus deliver the basic cognitive grid through which the people
think their kinship relationships. It is incomplete in the sense that secondary levels
of distinction are not explored (ibid.: 35).

11. In another passage, Dumont (1983: 169) expresses this idea in simple terms: with
regard to our problem of the relation between caste and kinship, or hierarchy and
equality, in South India.
12. I diverge from Dumont on this point, prefering the formulation equality of the sexes
to equality between the sexes. The latter could be interpreted as equality between men
and women, whereas the analysis at hand focuses solely on the terminological level.

2015 | Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 5 (1): 227250


Ccile Barraud 240

The last section of this article discusses the importance of affinity relationships
in other contexts, such as the roles and functions of affines in matters of inheri-
tance that illustrate the central role played by marriage, including gifts, wedding
and mourning prestations, the ceremonial role of the maternal uncle, and so on.
In summary, in South India, and within the hierarchical caste system, kinship
terminology is organized by a simple distinctive opposition (which Dumont de-
scribes as a paradigm) which establishes the equal value of consanguinity and
affinity, in conjunction with the marriage rule, as well as the perfect symmetry
between and equality of the sexes.
These conclusions lead me to reflect upon sex distinctions and the relationship
between consanguinity and affinity when it is not a structural opposition, in other
kinship systems and terminologies.

Affinity and the sex distinction in another configuration


I will briefly present the example of Kei society, in the Southeast Moluccas
of Indonesia, where I conducted fieldwork (Barraud 1979, 1990). Unlike the
Dravidian terminology, the kinship terminology here does not show a structur-
al opposition between consanguinity and affinity. Affinity vocabulary is lacking;
most of its terms are made from compound consanguinity terms (like the English
term father-in-law, constructed from the term father). In Kei, like South India,
there is preferential marriage, but the term father-in-law is different from that of
mothers brother. Affinity is not a significant opposition in ordering the kinship
terminology (each sex treated separately, as in the case of South India, two terms
opposing consanguine and affinal relatives in three generations or age classes). In
Kei, affinity, unlike consanguinity, is only loosely present in kinship terminology.
This does not mean that marriage is unimportant; on the contrary. Rather, it is
conditioned by another type of transmitted relationship: that between a brother
and a sister. Marriage ties two social units (houses), which are then called ances-
tors of the brother, on the one hand, and children of the sister on the other, a
relation that cannot be reversed. For generations, the houses continue giving and
receiving different types of prestations in all kinds of ceremonies (birth, marriages,
funerals, building of boats and houses, etc.; see Barraud 1979, 1990), according to
their position relative to the husband or wife in previous marriages. Thus, what we
usually call affine relations, in Kei, is expressed in terms of the relation between
the descendants of the wifes brother house and the sisters husband house, that is,
through the brothersister relationship.
The distinction that orders the terminology is the sex distinction, in its rela-
tive modality (contrary to Dravidian terminology, where sex distinctions are ab-
solute, each sex being called by a distinct term). It manifests itself in the terms used
respectively between siblings and husbands and wives (the same term is used by a
woman or a man to designate a person of the other sex). These terms do not oppose
male and female, whereas in Dravidian terminology each sex is absolutely distin-
guished in the three central generations.
However, a disjunction appears analytically between this absence of opposi-
tion in the use of kinship terms and a hierarchy within the sex distinction itself.

2015 | Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 5 (1): 227250


241 Kinship, equality, and hierarchy

This hierarchy is contained in the distinction that encompasses both sexes (there
is a single relative sex term for brothersister and a single relative sex term for
husbandwife), thus attributing them a different status with regard to the distinc-
tion (Dumonts principle of the unit: 1980a: 24041).13
What is striking is that this analytical disjunction emerges between actual mar-
riage partners and in the subsequent relationships between their houses for at least
two generations after a marriage. The hierarchy inherent in the sex distinction takes
the form of different statuses given to the wifes and the husbands houses: the wifes
brothers ancestors being attributed a higher status than the sisters descendants, who
are considered helpers of the former.14 The kinship terminology presents a sort of
formal synchronic symmetry of the sexes in the central generation. However, any
marriage creates a diachronic dissymmetry of the sexes for the descendants of this
marriage (who have different statuses). This is one of the main features of the societies
where the brothersister relationship is central in the analysis of kin terminologies.
Kei society thus presents a contrasting configuration, in which affinity nearly
disappears. It is a configuration where a marriage induces a change of status, es-
tablishing higher- or lower-ranked relationships between intermarried houses. In
other words, although there is no distinction of sex in the use of kinship terms, in
the social relations between brothers and sisters, and husbands and wives, a sex
distinction does exist. Within this distinction, there is a hierarchy, which exists in
tandem with differential statuses of marriage relationships.
For further comparison with South India, we can briefly underline a point con-
cerning Kei ideology (Barraud 1990; Als and Barraud 2001). In South India, while
trying to understand the relationship between ideology (the pure and the impure,
caste and hierarchy) and kinship features, Dumont finds in kinship terminology
what he calls equality of the sexes and equal status between consanguinity and af-
finity. At the same time, he discovers that differences of status (hierarchy) enter the
caste through marriage. In Kei, by contrast, values are defined in reference to two
sets of ideas, which, for simplicity, may be described as the internal organization of
the society (subordinate level) and the relationship with the world beyond society
(superior level). Marriage must be considered at both levels. Maternal affines (the
mothers brother and their ancestors) have a higher status at the subordinate level
of ideology. Sisters destined to marry outside the house are called women strang-
ers from birth. These out-married sisters, their husbands and descendants, are as-
sociated with the superior level of the world beyond society. In this case, marriage
and sex distinction have a dual status.
In Dumonts terms, equality would be an inappropriate description of this
configuration. South India displays in its kinship terminology an equistatutory op-
position between affines and consanguines for each sex. South Indian kinship ter-
minology includes distinct words for each sex, which receive equal treatment. This
is not the case in the Keiese terminology, where a single term designates both sexes.
The sex distinction here is manifested through the relation.

13. The sex distinction, and particularly its relative sex modality in different societies, is
central to Als and Barrauds Sexe relatif ou sexe absolu? (2001).
14. This feature is well known as being a characteristic of Eastern Indonesia societies.

2015 | Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 5 (1): 227250


Ccile Barraud 242

North Indian vocabulary


This point may be illustrated through a comparison Dumont (1962) highlighted
between North and South India. Unlike Southern Indian kinship terminology, a
strict central opposition does not characterize kinship vocabulary in Northern
India. There is here no positive marriage rule, but only marriage prohibitions.
Upon analysis, only one feature appears systematically: the relationship between
siblings of the opposite sex. Dumont further develops these points in an article
comparing North India and South India (Dumont 1966). He notes the empirical
importance of relationships between affines, manifest in the relatively large num-
ber of affinal terms, the difference in status between marriage partners, and (like
in the South) the important ceremonial functions of some affines (ibid.: 114). His
central argument is that the affinity arrangements depend largely on status and are
not directly linked to kinship terminology, which, he claims, has a more modest
place in the whole (ibid.:114). Dumont argues that the ordering of affinal rela-
tives is ... at any rate, largely a function of status, i.e. of caste, instead of a function
of kinship (ibid.). He goes so far as to say that there is thus no kinship system in a
strict sense, as an extraneous principle pervades the kinship field and deprives it of
its internal consistency in favour of a more complex arrangement (ibid.). Dumont
contends that this also reduce[s] the function of kinship in social life (ibid.: 110).
To his regret, he acknowledges: We must own up to yet another unpleasant rec-
ognition: the ordering of affinal relatives is, in [Uttar Pradesh] at any rate, largely a
function of status, i.e. of caste, instead of a function of kinship (ibid.: 114).
Dumont is, as ever, cautious, limiting the comparison to the logical arrange-
ment of the kinship terms in each context.
Hence one hypothesis: the center of gravity of a kinship system lies in
the terminology only when it is simple and quite systematic, the outright
expression of a largely non-conscious construction of the mind. There
are other cases where the link between terminology and behavior is
much looser, signaled by the relatively unsystematic character of the
terminology, and where the center of gravity of the kinship system is to
be sought elsewhere. (Dumont 1966: 103)

Kinship terminologies in French and English


Dumonts comparison once again goes further. Indeed, in order to clarify his analy-
sis of this very complex and confusing North Indian kinship terminology, he relies
on a brief comparison with French kinship vocabulary, drawn from common lan-
guage. He searches for its axis, or a principle that orders the system, with respect
to the arrangement of the three elementary kinship relationships (descent, sibling
relationships, and marriage/affinity) in comparison with the South Indian vocabu-
lary (Dumont 1962: 3236, particularly n. 16).15

15. To understand the situation, we may perhaps recall the more extreme case of our own,
Western, societies in which kinship does not, as in simpler societies, order directly or
indirectly the whole of social life (Dumont 1966: 110, emphasis in original).

2015 | Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 5 (1): 227250


243 Kinship, equality, and hierarchy

In the French system, he says, there are, strictly speaking, only two affinity terms,
gendre (son-in-law) and bru (daughter-in-law). Other affinal terms are compound
words, composed of consanguine terms like pre (father) or frre (brother) and a
prefix marking affinity. In French, beau-pre (father-in-law), beau-frre (brother-
in-law), and so on, do not constitute distinct categories with respect to father and
brother. Dumont thus asserts that among modern Westerners, affinity is subor-
dinated to consanguinity, for my brother-in-lawan affine[]becomes an uncle,
a consanguine relative, for my children. In other words, affinity is ephemeral, it
merges into consanguinity in the next generation (Dumont 1983: vii). There are no
positive marriage rules, there is no repetition of the marriage relations in successive
generations. And sexes are equal in the ideology, both ideally and in terminology.
Note that in English, the vocabulary is even more limited: son-in-law is com-
posed of son, daughter-in-law of daughter, while French has gendre and bru.
Whereas French still has special terms in certain cases, English only has second-
ary determinants. Comparatively ... the dichotomy in English usage corresponds
to a sort of apotheosis of consanguinity and a concomitant devaluation of affinity
(Dumont 1971: 14, in Parker 2006: 4).
However, Dumont sees in this system a sort of central distinction, between di-
rect line and collateral line within descent: the terminology distinguishes father
and uncle, brother and cousin, son and nephew, and so on ... and also the sexes
(Dumont 1962: 35). This does not organize in any way the status of affinity, which is
residual. Thus kinship consists of consanguinity only and introduces, says Dumont,
an opposition within a substance, descent (ibid.) between direct and indirect line.
***
In summary, in South India, in the context of caste hierarchy, kinship terminology
exhibits an equal treatment of the sexes in conjunction with the axial distinction,
equivalence in value of consanguinity and affinity, with respect to the marriage rule.
In Kei society, the axial distinction is the sex distinction; there is a sort of sym-
metry between the positions of both sexes at egos generation (brothersister) and
a dissymmetry of the brothersister relation, which is revealed at the next genera-
tion after a marriage occurs. There is dissymmetry and hierarchy in the relation
between two generations in conjunction with marriage; this is a hierarchy, which is
reversed at the superior level of ideology.
In North India, the hierarchy of the caste enters the field of kinship, particularly
in affinity relations, such that the two sexes are not equal or equivalent in this re-
gard. There is no strict opposition in the terminology and no axis, but the sibling
relationship serves as a guiding principle, which organizes kinship.
In Western systems, where egalitarian ideology dominates, there is no strict
central opposition in the kinship terminology. At this level, sex distinction is clear
in the non equivalence of consanguinity and reduced affinity. Taking into account
the fact that kinship in Western societies nowadays does not order the whole of
social life, one can say, however, that with regard to value and permanence, only
consanguinity is transmitted and affinity is not valued.16

16. An anonymous reviewer of this article rightly underlined the great influence of the
church in defining Western kinship and affinity and property transmission. There is

2015 | Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 5 (1): 227250


Ccile Barraud 244

And finally Dumont remarks:


The irony of the situation is that, in this matter, we Westerners,
egalitarians as we are, practice subordinationthe relation between
consanguinity and affinity is exactly what I have defined elsewhere
as a hierarchical relationwhile South Indian people, who live in a
hierarchical society, look at the two entities with equanimity, and make
a simple, straightforward, symmetrical distinction between them, where
we maintain a hierarchical distinction. (Dumont 1983: vii, emphasis in
original)

Concluding remarks
In Western societies, where equality is an ideal, if not a reality, hierarchy is largely
unsuspected and underestimated. I am not an expert on French kinship or marriage,
but it seems to me that their relation to ideology engenders three conclusive remarks.
First, the devaluation of affinity in kinship terminology must be examined with
regard to the contemporary desire to give both sexes equal treatment. Empirical-
ly, there are today a growing and infinitely expandable number of affinity terms
used in contexts where affinity is no longer present. I am thinking of terms which
designate the spouse of egos mother or father, in French beau-pre (stepfather)
and belle-mre (stepmother), or the children of egos spouse: beau-fils (stepson),
belle-fille (stepdaughter), who are neither affines nor consanguine relatives for the
children but who take the place of kin.17 Given the valorization of consanguinity
relative to affinity, could the use of affinity terms (beau-pre, belle-mre) by chil-
dren (parentchild relationship, a filiation relationship) lead to the confusion of
relations and a further devaluation of affinity? Furthermore, does consanguinity
itself not lose its value, becoming a kind of second-rate consanguinity? To follow
Dumonts questioning, one can ask what causes this ordering of affinal relatives
and the devaluation of affinity in Western societies (Dumont 1966: 110).
My second point is a comment on filiation (Dumont 1962: n. 13) in France. Does
speaking of filiation (in French) produce confusion between its two meanings? On
the one hand, the parentchild bilinear relationship (filiation in English), and,
on the other, filiation as descent, that is, understood as transmission of mem-
bership in an exogamous group, unilineal and even patrilineal in many Western
societies, connected to a genealogical arrangement tracing a relation back to ascen-
dants. This confusion is also reported by Agns Fine regarding the parentchild

indeed a historical context to take into account to explain the contemporary devalua-
tion of affinity, which I did not include in the comparison of English and French termi-
nologies. I am grateful to this reviewer for this important observation.
17. See the recent French Report (Thry and Leroyer 2014) on the question of access
to origins, and the familial place of beaux-parents (stepparents); and a reflexion on
filiation, to account for the evolutions of contemporary family. If the discussion of
marriage is central in this interesting report, nowhere are the statuses of affinity or the
question of the affinal terms used in the context of filiation examined.

2015 | Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 5 (1): 227250


245 Kinship, equality, and hierarchy

relationship (specifically parenthood) and the English filiation. When the term
is used in the first sense (parentchild relation) and in the contexts described in
the first point (beaux-parents, terms which in French connote affinity), there is
a collusion of meanings between affinity and consanguinity. The term parents in
French, meaning relatives in English, becomes a catch-all term in which no dis-
tinctions are made. The second notion tends to cover the first, which means that
the parentchild link tends to occupy all that contains filiation (Fine 2001: 46). It
also contributes simultaneously to a confusion with affinity, owing to the use of the
same terms in second marriages. Affinity is recognized only through a preference
for consanguinity (parentchild relationship) at the same time as consanguinity is
reduced to the parentchild relationship (parenthood).18
Finally, my third point is that in all examples of kinship terminologies presented
here, except the French one, the sex distinction operates in conjunction with an-
other principle to organize the kinship vocabulary relative to marriage and affinity.
On the other hand, in Western kinship terminologies, sex distinction, although
present, is not able to organize a consanguinityaffinity relation, since affinity is an
attribute of consanguinity and does not significantly oppose it. The sexes are ideo-
logically equal (if not in reality), but sex distinction has no effect in the construc-
tion of elementary kinship oppositions. One could say that marriage and affinity
in Western systems do not have much to do with la parent (kinship in English,
in its broadest definition), on the restricted level of the construction of elementary
kinship oppositions. Their status on the ideological level is also unclear (an issue
which preoccupies contemporary debates regarding marriage, if not affinity strictly
speakingsee footnote 17which, at this point, is beyond the scope of my own
research).
And again I give the floor to Dumont, on comparison.
While with us, only consanguinity is inherited, in South India affinity
is transmitted also from one generation to another, making it an exact
counterpart of consanguinity. In saying this, we conceptually move from
our own conceptual system to the one that is studied, and our comparison
is complete. We subsumed under a formula our conception and their
conception ... we have not achieved the universal, but only a step toward
it, because there is in the world a wide variety of kinship systems based
on other principles. (Dumont 1992: 244, emphasis in original)

18. See Parkins (translation of Dumonts Introduction to two theories, for his discussion
of the translation of French filiation: Dumont also addresses the double meaning of
French filiation (meaning both descent and the parentchild links which descent con-
sists of: though it is relatively rare in English, the same word is used there in the latter
sense only (Parkin 2006: xii). And again, in his discussion of Radcliffe-Browns defini-
tion of kin and of siblingship, I quote Parkins translation of Dumont: Siblingship is left
aside, consanguinity thus being linked only to the relation of filiation (elementary) or
descent (multiple), a nuance to be noted in the way the French term filiation is used.
And in the translators note 1: In other words, French filiation is used to translate
both filiation (ties between parents and children) and descent (the extension of such
ties backwards in time from the perspective of the present) from English (Parkin in
Dumont 2006: 6).

2015 | Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 5 (1): 227250


Ccile Barraud 246

After rejecting dichotomies, and natural differences, the editors of Gender and
kinship propose a premise that social systems are systems of social inequalities.
This follows the question of how attributes and characteristics of people are cul-
turally recognized and differentially evaluated and its corollary: what are a soci-
etys cultural values? (Yanagisako and Collier 1987: 3940). The key phrase here,
however, is values entail evaluation, meaning that all things and actions are not
equal in a system of social relationships, and values create inequalities (ibid.).
This is where the advantage of Dumonts theory of hierarchy becomes clear.
As we have seen, hierarchy does not create inequalities but distinguishes levels
in which the values attributed to elements can be reversed. The logic of equality
excludes anything that is not of equal value, whereas hierarchy includes multiple
levels of elements of different values, without exclusion. The separation of sexes
in kinship terminology does not attribute a priori a value to one sex or the other.
Similarly, the affinityconsanguinity distinction, as criteria of analysis, does not
attribute a value to one or the other. Only the analysis of the entire terminological
system allows for the attribution of status. The combination of a limited number of
terms in a terminology does not account for natural differences and even seems
to erase them, as we have seen with the term relative sex in the Keiese terminol-
ogy. Equality is not in place, according to Dumonts use of the term (in his discus-
sion of the equality of sexes in South Indian terminology), which points exclusively
and significantly to an equal treatment of the sexes as a formal kinship category by
contrast with the caste hierarchy.
Once more, Dumonts comparative method is at work here (see also Dumont
1975b: 15657). The notion of equality has been presented first in comparison
with Tocquevilles idea that equality abolishes differences and implies similarity
except in the case of men and women: dissimilarity of women but equal value with
men, in the egalitarian mentality. Dumont argued that Tocqueville confused equal-
ity and identity, which the latter locates in human nature. In contrast, Dumonts
approach to hierarchy distinguishes equality, identity, and difference, distinctions
that remain at the heart of contemporary discussions of gender as a social con-
struct. In this respect, a closer reading of Dumonts work can shed light on ques-
tions of equality and gender relations. This was my aim in this essay through the
examination of kinship terminology. This analysis limits the scope of the question,
illustrating the place of notions of equality within the hierarchical context of the
caste system. The challenge we now face is to determine to what extent and in
what contexts a reversal is feasible. The present analysis has revealed the presence
of equality within hierarchy, leading to the question: How might hierarchy be con-
ceivable within egalitarian contexts?
In 1988, in her book Feminism and anthropology, the British anthropologist
Henrietta L. Moore wrote, The different theoretical positions within feminist
anthropology are best demonstrated through a consideration of the debate which
dominates the subject: is sexual asymmetry universal or not? In other words, are
women always subordinate to men? (Moore 1988: 13).
In this article, I have proposed an answer to these questions. Yes, there is always
sexual asymmetry. No, women are not always subordinate to men. And the value
subordination (not to be confounded with the either/or implied in formulations
of equality vs. domination) that takes place in the social manifestation of the sex

2015 | Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 5 (1): 227250


247 Kinship, equality, and hierarchy

distinction is not uniform, but rather unfolds in diverse ways, which include rever-
sals of hierarchal relations.

Acknowledgments
This article has benefited from long discussions with my colleagues Ismal Moya
and Andr Iteanu. The English version was greatly improved with the assistance of
Chelsie Yount-Andr, to whom I am deeply grateful.

References
Als, Catherine, and Ccile Barraud, eds. 2001. Sexe relatif ou sexe absolu? De la distinction
de sexe dans les socits. Paris: ditions de la Maison des Sciences de lHomme.
Atkinson, Jane Monnig and Shelly Errington, eds. 1990. Power and difference: Gender in
Island Southeast Asia. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Barraud, Ccile. 1979. Tanebar-Evav: Une socit de maisons tourne vers le large. Paris:
ditions de la Maison des Sciences de lHomme.
. 1990. Wife-givers as ancestors and ultimate values in the Kei Islands. Bijdragen tot
de Taal-, Land- en Volkenkunde 146: 23.
. 2001. La distinction de sexe dans les socits: Un point de vue relationnel. Esprit
273 (marsavril): 10529.
Busby, Cecilia. 1997. Of marriage and marriageability: Gender and Dravidian kinship.
Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute (N.S.) 3(1): 2142.
Collier, Jane Fishburne, and Sylvia Junko Yanagisako, eds. 1987a. Gender and kinship: Essays
toward a unified analysis. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
.1987b. Introduction. In Gender and kinship: Essays toward a unified analysis, edited
by Jane Fisburne Collier and Sylvia Junko Yanagisako, 113. Stanford: Stanford Univer-
sity Press.
del Valle, Teresa, ed. 1993. Gendered anthropology. London: Routledge.
Descombes, Vincent. 1999. Louis Dumont et les outils de la tolrance. Esprit 253 (juin):
6582.
Dumont, Louis.1957. Hierarchy and marriage alliance in South Indian kinship. Occasional
Papers 12. London: Royal Anthropological Institute of Great Britain and Ireland.
. 1962. Le vocabulaire de parent en Inde du Nord. LHomme 2 (2): 548.
. 1966. Marriage in India, the present state of the question: III. North India in rela-
tion to South India. Contributions to Indian Sociology (O.S.) 9: 90114.
. 1971. Introduction deux thories danthropologie sociale. Paris: Mouton EHESS.
. 1975a. Dravidien et Kariera: Lalliance de mariage dans lInde du sud et en Australie.
Paris: Mouton.

2015 | Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 5 (1): 227250


Ccile Barraud 248

. 1975b. On the comparative understanding of non-modern civilizations. Daedalus


104(2): 15372.
. 1977. From Mandeville to Marx: The genesis and triumph of economic ideology.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
. 1979. The anthropological community and ideology. Social Science Information
18(6): 785817.
. 1980a. Homo hierarchicus: The caste system and its implications. Translated by Mark
Sainsbury, Louis Dumont, and Basia Gulati. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
. 1980b. On value: The RadcliffeBrown Lecture in Social Anthropology. Proceed-
ings of the British Academy 66: 20741.
. 1983. Affinity as a value: Marriage alliance in South India, with comparative essays on
Australia. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
. 1986. Essays on individualism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
. 1992. Rtrospection. Lenseignement de lInde: le tout et les parties. Religio, Bulzone
Editore (remise du prix europen Amalfi): 23951.
. 2006. Introduction to two theories of social anthropology: Descent groups and mar-
riage alliance. Translated and edited by Robert Parkin. New York: Berghahn.
Fine, Agns. 2001. Vers une reconnaissance de la pluriparentalit. Esprit (marsavril):
4052.
Fortes, Meyer. 1949. The web of kinship among the Tallensi. London: Oxford University
Press.
Furet, Franois. 1981. Prface. In De la Dmocratie en Amrique, Alexis de Tocqueville,
771. Paris: Garnier-Flammarion.
Gauchet, Marcel. 1980. Tocqueville, lAmrique et nous. Libre 7: 43120.
Gregory, Christopher A. 2010. Siblingship as a value in Middle India. In The anthropology
of values: Essays in honour of Georg Pfeffer, edited by Peter Berger, Roland Hardenberg,
Ellen Kattner, and Michael Prager, 318. Delhi: Dorling Kindersley.
. 2013. The value question in India: Ethnographic reflections on an ongoing debate.
Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 3 (1): 11639.
Hertz, Robert. 1973. The Pre-eminence of the right hand: A study in religious polarity. In
Right and left: Essays on dual symbolic classification, edited by Rodney Needham, 331.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
MacCormack, Carol, and Marilyn Strathern, eds. 1980. Nature, culture and gender. Cam-
bridge: Cambridge University Press.
Madan, T. N. 1986. Reviewed work: Affinity as a value: Marriage alliance in South India,
with comparative essays on Australia, by Louis Dumont. American Journal of Sociology
91(4): 101618.
Moore, Henrietta L. 1988. Feminism and anthropology. Cambridge: Polity.

2015 | Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 5 (1): 227250


249 Kinship, equality, and hierarchy

. 1999. Whatever happened to women and men? Gender and other crises in an-
thropology. In Anthropological theory today, edited by Henrietta L. Moore, 15171.
Cambridge: Polity.
Needham, Rodney. 1960. Descent systems and ideal language. Philosophy of Science
27(1): 96101.
, ed. 1973. Right and left: Essays on dual symbolic classification. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
Overing, Joanna. 1973. Endogamy and the marriage alliance: A note on continuity in kin-
dred-based groups. Man (N.S.) 8(4): 55570.
. 1975. The Piaroa, a people of the Orinoco Basin: A study of kinship and marriage.
Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Ortner, Sherry B., and Harriet Whitehead, eds. 1981. Sexual meanings: The cultural con-
struction of gender and sexuality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Parkin, Robert. 1992. Dispersed alliance and terminological change in South Asia. Journal
of the Anthropological Society of Oxford 23 (3): 25362.
. 2006. Introduction. In Two theories of social anthropology: Descent groups and
marriage alliance, Louis Dumont, viixxvii. Translated and edited by Robert Parkin.
New York: Berghahn.
Pfeffer, Georg. 1993. Comments: Dispersed alliance, terminological change and evidence.
Journal of the Anthropological Society of Oxford 24 (1): 4963.
Robbins, Joel. 1994. Equality as a value: Ideology in Dumont, Melanesia and the West.
Social Analysis 36: 2170.
Rudner, David. 1990. Inquest on Dravidian kinship: Louis Dumont and the essence of
marriage alliance. Contributions to Indian Sociology (N.S.) 24(2): 15374.
Sahlins, Marshall. 2013. What kinship isand is not. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Strathern, Marilyn, ed. 1987. Dealing with inequality: Analysing gender relations in Melanesia
and beyond. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
. 1988. The gender of the gift: Problems with women and problems with society in Mela-
nesia. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Thry, Irne, and AnneMarie Leroyer. 2014. Filiation, origines, parentalit: Le droit face
aux nouvelles valeurs de responsabilit gnrationnelle. Paris: Ministre de la Famille.
Tocqueville, Alexis de. 1840. Democracy in America. Vol. 2. Translated by Henry Reeve.
http://www.gutenberg.org/files/816/816-h/816-h.htm.
Trautmann, Thomas R. 1981. Dravidian kinship. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Viveiros de Castro, Eduardo. 1998. Dravidian and related kinship systems. In Transforma-
tions of kinship, edited by Maurice Godelier, Thomas R. Trautmann, and Franklin Tjon
Sie Fat, 33285. Washington, DC: Smithsonian Institution Press.
. 2001. GUT feelings about Amazonia: Potential affinity and the construction of
sociality. In Beyond the visible and the material: The Amerindianization of society in the
work of Peter Rivire, edited by Laura M. Rival and Neil L. Whitehead, 1943. Oxford:
Oxford UniversityPress.

2015 | Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 5 (1): 227250


Ccile Barraud 250

Yanagisako, Sylvia Junko, and Jane Fishburne Collier. 1987. Toward a unified analysis of
gender and kinship. In Gender and kinship: Essays toward a unified analysis, edited by
Jane Fishburne Collier and Sylvia Junko Yanagisako, 1450. Stanford: Stanford Univer-
sity Press.

Parent, galit, hirarchie: distinction de sexe et valeurs dans une


perspective comparative
Rsum : Cet article traite de la notion dgalit dans loeuvre de Louis Dumont,
plus particulirement en relation avec la distinction de sexe et lidologie. Cet exer-
cice de lecture des textes de Dumont sur la parent revisite son analyse de la ter-
minologie et du mariage en Inde du Sud, qui le conduit discuter la valeur gale
de laffinit et de la consanguinit dans la socit hirarchique des castes, et lgalit
des sexes. Ses travaux sont ici utiliss pour ouvrir une perspective comparative sur
la distinction de sexe. Larticle propose dtendre ce type danalyse dautres socits
et dautres idologies, pour tenter de mieux comprendre les changements contem-
porains dans les relations de parent.

Ccile Barraud is a Senior Researcher Emeritus at the National Center for Scien-
tific Research (CNRS, France). She has conducted extensive fieldwork in Southeast
Moluccas, Eastern Indonesia, since 1971. Her research focused initially on under-
standing houses as social groups. She is the author of Tanebar-Evav: Une socit de
maisons tourne vers le large (ditions de la Maison des Sciences de lHomme, 1979),
Sexe relatif ou sexe absolu (with Catherine Als, ditions de la Maison des Sciences
de lHomme, 2001), and of an essay on the notion of property in Austronesian lan-
guages and in the Indo-Pacific area (in Andr Iteanu, ed., La cohrence des socits:
Mlanges en hommage Daniel de Coppet, Maison des Sciences de lHomme, 2001).
She is currently engaged in a cooperative GermanFrench program on the theme
Encountering religions in Southeast Asia and beyond.
 Ccile Barraud
 Centre Asie du Sud-Est
 Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique
 cole des Hautes tudes en Sciences Sociales
Paris
France
barraud@msh-paris.fr

2015 | Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 5 (1): 227250

Вам также может понравиться