Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 13

284 Robert Brain

not zeal, of the French state to arbitrate and guarantee its standards. In HANS-JORG RHEINBERGER
sense language policy corresponded closely with initiatives to pr<lffi<otg·
norms and standards in other spheres of practice-this was a raison
of the Third Republic. The spatial imperative oflong-distance
through telegraph systems gave way to the necessity of sustaining Experimental Systems,
in time, less by imparting influence than by creating, representing,
maintaining ritually shared beliefS. Linguistic values, like otl,crv.lue,,,h,,, Graphematic Spaces
to be arbitrary in order to remain robust, but natural in order to
valid. In this sense standards were semiotic and semiotics were standard

,reCeIl!)'e.,es, it has become fashionable among historians and philoso-


of science to turn their attention to the field of experimentation.
~re witnessing, after the Kuhnian move from continuity and verity of
knowledge to discontinuity and relativity, another turn-from
Kuhnian predilection for science as theory to post-Kuhnian engage-
with science as experiment., A philosophical landmark in this move
,been Ian Hacking's Representing and Intervening. Hacking reminded
rilosol,hers of science that experiments have a "life of their own."l
>:",uLJ.anofscience Peter Galison' has taken up this challenge and argued
history of experimentation that accords that activity the same depth
~fsl:ru,oture, quirks, breaks, continuities, and traditiom that we have come
from theory."3
A growing history and philosophy of science industry today is carry-
that move and amalgamating it with what has come to be labeled
as Practice and Culture."4 "SoCial construction of science" has
a shibboleth for those wishing to be members of the club. Actors,
politics, power, and authority have acquired the status of key
in a "strong program" to treat science on a par with any other
activity whatsoever. That Thomas Kuhn is "among those who
" , fonnd the claims of the strong program absurd: an example of de-
!P.SI:ru(ottcm gone mad,'" might not surprise, and might perhaps be put
, as a matter of taste. From a fundamental epistemological point of
, "_'. it is Bruno Latour who most explicitly and most radically has called
to an impasse of "science and society" studies from which there
to be no easy escape. 6 To put it crudely: What do we gain by
286 Hans-Jorg Rheinberger Graphematic Spaces 287

substituting "social conditions" for what has been taken as "natural condi~ , ducibly, as the experimental situation: in this situation, there are scientific
dons" of scientific activity?7 If, in the perspective of social construction, objects and the technical conditions of their existence, differential re-
we have lost the illusion of an ultimate reference called "nature," what do production of experimental systems, conjunctures of such systems, and
we gain by trying to compensate for this loss with the mirror image of graphematic representations. All of these are notions related to the practi-
"society" as a new and insurmountable reference? From where do we· cal process of producing what I shall call "epistemic things."
hope to derive its epistemic legitimacy? With the tetragonic opposition of Briefly, I argue along the following lines: First, experimental systems 13 \
theory and practice, nature and society, we remain, despite all rotation of are the working units a scientist or a group of scientists deals with. They
competences, within the confines of a conceptual framework that Jacques are simultaneously local, social, institutional, technical, instrumental, and
Derrida without doubt would qualitY as the logocentric legacy of occi- above all, epistemic units. My approach is biased towards this last aspect. 14
dental metaphysics.' ., Sec;ond, such systems must be capable of differential reproduction in
This essay does not claim to transcend these confmes with an encom- ,order to behave as a device for producing epistemic things whose pos-
passing gesture. Its purpose is more humble and modest. It sticks to the sibility is beyond our present knowledge, that is, to behave as a "generator
Derridean program of reworking such oppositions from within, of trying ofsurprises."15 "Differential reproduction" refers to the allowance, ifnot
to render their limits different/ deferent. It starts, therefore, from the more' . t~ the necessity of shifts and displacements within the investigative pro-
narrowly conceived Hacking and Galison move from theory to experi- in order to be productive, an experimental system has to be orga-
ment within the realm of scientific activity and develops a framework in: '. nized so that the generation of differences becomes the reproductive
which experimentation takes ~n meaning as a set of specific kinds of" ~ di:iving force of the whole experimental machinery.
epistemic practices. Nevertheless, this essay is ambitious: it tries to . Third, experimental systems are the units within which the signifters
ize those structures as hybrids that are recalcitrant to classification in qf science are generated. They display their dynamics in a space of repre-
realm, the natural or the social, the theoretical or the practical. sentation in which graphemes, material traces, are produced, are articu-
Experimental reasoning, then? Even this expression can easily be and disconnected, and are placed, displaced. and replaced. Science
understood. Its grammatical structure presupposes reasoning as the -uthinks" within its spaces of representation, within the hybrid context of
proximum, whose specific difference is to be guided by experiment. the available experimental systems. Graphemes are to be understood as
is at stake, however, is just the opposite. It is a kind of movement oriientecl the primary, material, significant units of the experimental game, and at
and reoriented by generating its own boundary conditions, in which rea- the same time, the units of reference. At the bench, the experimental
soning is swept offby tracing, a game of material entities. Gaston Scienljst engraves traces into a material space of representation; more
lard has spoken of instruments as "theories materialized"9 and has con':' 'prec:is':ly, the scientist creates a space of representation through graphema-
eluded: "Contemporary science thinks with! in its apparatuses."!O And he. concatenations that represent the epistemic thing as a kind of "writ-
has spoken about a "scientific real (Ie reel scientifique) whose noumeriiu' All this is to be understood as a. preliminary step toward a history of
contexture it is to be able to orient the axes of the experimental tJ,fst,emic things. 16 "There is a history of science, not only of scientists, and
ment."l1 In analogy to Wittgenstein's well-known expression, we is a history of things, not only ofscience."17
call this a tracing-game. Wittgenstein says: "I shall also call the whole, In ':)fder to exemplify my points, I shall draw upon some episodes in
sisting oflanguage and the actions into which it is woven, the 'la!lg1!age"; eXperimental history of the construction of an in vitro system for
game.' " And he continues: "Our mistake is to look for an expla.nation biosynthesis.
where we ought to look at what happens as a 'protophenomenon.'
is, where we ought to have said: this language game is played."!2 We
A Future-Making Machine
never able to get behind this weaving. Thus, I am not looking for
"logic" in the relationship between theory and experiment, or for a do I mean by the notion of "experimental system"? Traditionally,
behind experiment. Rather, I am grappling with what must be seen, . llj'prrilm;oF,hy of science, an experiment is seen as a singular instance, as a
288 Hans-Jorg Rheinberger Graphematic Spaces 289

dramatized trial (tribunal en scene) organized and performed in order rather to start with a "practical" approach and "take advantage of (
corroborate or refute theories. is Quite some time. ago, Ludwik Fleck " :whatever new opportunities became available, in the hope that a definite
drew our attention to scientific-especially biomedical-research practice': '. , turned up in any corner of the field."23
and argued that, in contrast to what philosophers of science might as"' " The "practical approach" consisted in the introduction of radioactive
sume, the experimentalist does not deal with single experiments. "Every , Carbon-labeled amino acids as "tracers" for following the incorporation of
experimental scientist knows just how little a single experiment can ' , amino acids into proteins. They were synthesized by Robert Loftfield,
or convince. To establish proof, an entire system of experiments who then was a research associate at the Radioactivity Center of MIT .24
controls is needed." 19 According to Fleck, in research we do not have to Loftfield had succeeded in producing carbon-labeled alanine and glycine
deal with single experiments in'relation to a clearly defined theory, but ih- 'amounts suitable for biochemical research. What a few years later
with a complex experimental arrangement designed to produce lrumrl- ,: 'proved to be one of the most potent technical tools for tracing protein
edge that we do not yet have. Even more important, we deal with systems' '~metabolism. was itself part of the res~arch program at the beginning. At \
of experiments that usually do not provide clear answers. "If a research the outset, It was not at all clear which one of the different amino acids
experiment were well defmed, it would be altogether unnecessary to should be used for the incorporation reaction, and what should be done
perform it. For the experimental arrangements to be well defmed, the ",'" order to circumvent the possible tracing of metabolic processes other
outcome must be known in advance; otherwise the procedure cannot be than protein synthesis because of the prior metabolism of amino acids.
limited and purposeful."20 Workers in the field were confronted with-and indeed constantly
Like Fleck, I consider an experimental system to be a unit of research;' haunted by-the possibility that what they observed as "uptake" or "in-
designed to give answers to questions we are not yet able to ask clearly. In < corporation" of radioactive amino acids might turn out to be a side
the rypical case, it is, as Fran,ois Jacob has put it, "a machine for making reaction with respect to the protein synthetic activity within the cell. But
the future,"21 It is a device that not only generates answers; at the same " how proteins were made there was precisely the unknown process. Be-
time, and as a prerequisite, it shapes the questions to be answered. cause usually no more than I percent of the radioactivity added to the
experimental system is a device to materialize questions. It cogenerates; "~system became "incorporated," there was not only a, realistic chance of
SO to speak, the phenomena or material entities and the concepts bonding other than regular alpha-peptide bonding-known to be
come to embody, A single experiment as a sharp test of a properly , characteristic for proteins-but also the possibility of a rather unspecific
(
ated conception is not the simple, elementary unit of experimental :' """adSol,ptiOll'" Not only was it unclear what "uptake" or "incorporation"
ence, but rather the degeneration of an elementarily complex sittlati:on."', .ofradioactivity meant, uncertainty also remained for years as to whether
One of the first in vitro systems of protein biosynthesis COlnstltucted the'same process was being observed in different experimental systems
from components of a rat liver cell sap may provide an illustration for at protein synthesis and derived from different tissues. 25
experimental system, In its outlines, it was established between 1947 and Uncertainty was also a given with respect to the choice of the specific
1952 at the Collis P. Huntington Memorial Hospital of Harvard Univer.' . system itself. Should one stick to injecting radioactive
siry at the Massa,chusetts General Hospital, in the laboratory of acids into living animals, thus taking advantage of their regular
Zarnecnik. In 1947, the Harvard group had set out to look at '·mlet2lbo.lic turnover? This rendered the measurements difficult, and it
deregulation in malignant tissue-a classical biomedical research pr<>je¢\.,' 'h'qulir"dlots of radioactive material. Should one trv to avoid these short-
in a hospital that, under the directorship of Joseph Aub, had long "ctlminl,s and work with liver slices in the test tube'? But this could cause
devoted to cancer research. Because growth could be assumed to "fu,eta.boli'c distortions of an unknown order of magnitude. Should one
closely related to the making of proteins, protein biosynthesis was with so-called "model systems" involving proteolytic enzymes?
the possible targets of the neoplastic behavior of cancer cells. Little ''FIllS inlplied a theoretical assumption-protein synthesis as a reversal of
known about the factors involved in carcinogenesis at that time: 'prot"olysis--thatwas current; but by no means substantiated. Should one
Zamecnik decided not to consider "a single avenue of biochemical to homogenate the tissue or even take the cell sap apart by means of
290 Hans-Jorg Rheinberger Graphematic Spaces 291

differential centrifugation? This promised to identify the com,lon.enltS" . thought centered On a tiny fragment of the universe, on a 'system' one
involved in the process, hut a cell homogenate was qualified "at present to turns over and over to view from every angle? How, above all, does one
be a biochemical bog in which much effort is being expended to reach . recapture the sense of a maze with no way out, the incessant quest for a
ftrm ground."26 solution, without referring to what later proved to be the solution in all its
Ifwe take a closer look at the laboratory process between 1947 and dazzling obviousness?"29 An experimental system can be compared to a to 'K?
195 I, we see that all of these possibilities were explored, that this explora. labyrinth whose walls, in the course of being erected, simultaneously \ '\
tion was centered around the use of radioactive tracing, and that initially it blind and gnide the experimenter. The construction principle of a laby-
was organized from what could be called a "significant difference." The rinth consists in that the existing walls limit the space and the direction of
significant difference was that malignant tissue appeared to take up comi' walls to be added. It cannot be planned. It forces one to move by
siderably more radioactivity than did normal tissue. But experimentally: means of checking out, of groping, of tatonnement. 30
1
this difference turned out to be silent, for it did not tell what to do next'
Above all, it did not tell which of the systemic alternatives should be
The coherence over time of an experimental system is granted by the
reproduction of its components. The development of such a system de-
pursued. In this situation, a differential signal, quite surprisingly, came o pends upon eliciting differences without destroying its reproductive co-
from a control. A particular substance called dinitrophenol (DNP), whicli herence. Together, this makes up its differential reproduction. The artic-
Fritz Lipmann had found to inhibit the process of prlosph-o'lTlatiOIlp7"': ulation, dislocation, and reorientation of an e~perimental system appears
inhibited the "incorporation" of radioactivity in the rat liver-slice governed by a kind of movement that has been described as a play of
toO.28 This could mean that phosphorylated compounds like adenosine possibilities (jeu des possibles)." With Derrida, we might also speak of a
triphosphate (A TP) might be inyolved in protein synthesis. That initiated . "game" of difference.'2 It is precisely the characteristic of "fall(ing) prey
a change in the research perspective. The medical point of view gradually· to its own work" that brings the scientific enterprise to what Derrida calls
became replaced by a biochemical perspective. To find out whether :i "the enterprise of deconstruction."33 On the part of the experimenter, it
high-energy intermediate was involved in protein synthesis was no longer requires acquired intuition (Erfohrenheit) in order to play the game. 34 Ex-
a question of the differential behavior of normal and malignant tissue. The periencedness is not experience. Experience is an intellectual quality;
DNP event also clarified the options. In order to get the system on eXperiencedness is a form of practice.
biochemical track, the cells had to be homogenized. Conditions had to be . [ would like to add a few remarks with respect to the differential
found under which the protein synthesis activity could be checked against reproduction of experimental systems. The first is that one never knows
compounds such as ATP or similar phosphorylated substances. The tech" exactly where it leads. As soon as one knows exactly whatit produces, itis
nical objective at this point became to separate the cellular components ifr .n:o longer a research system. An experimental system in which a scientific
such a way that the cellular compartments produdng energized gathers contours and becomes stabilized, at the same time must
( pounds could be distingnished from the cellular structures that used windows for the emergence of unprecedented events. While be-
,!eaming stabilized in a certain respect, it must be destabilized in another.
arriving at new "results," the system must be destabilized-and with-
The "Logic" of the Process
previously stabilized system there will he no "results." Stabilization
A scientific object or epistemic perspective in the framework of such destabilization imply each other. If a system becomes too rigid, it is
experimental system is as inherently open as the system itself with longer a machine for making the future; it becomes a testing device, in
to its technical potentials. An epistemic thing may not even be i',magrnled' sense of producing standards or replicas. It loses its function as a
when an experimental arrangement is in the course of being eSI:ablisl,e,l:: "'Besean:h tool. It may, however, he integrated as a stable subsystem into
But once a surprising result has emerged and has been sufficiendy 'iinoth,,,, still growing experimental system, and help to produce unprece-
bilized, it is difficult to avoid the illusion of a logic of thought and a
}'H,ent:ed events within larger field. This transformation offormer research
a teleology of the experimental process, "How does one re-·mlate,'" "SYstems into stable, technical subsystems of other research arrangements is
292 Hans-Jorg Rheinberger Graphematic Spaces 293

what confers its own kind of material information storage on the or,oc"ss Tissue
of experimentation. But by the same mechanism, it generates a historical _ homogenization
burden. Most new objects, therefore, are first shaped by old tools. Onth,,·· .
other hand, scientific objects are continually transformed into
devices, and in the long run become replaced by devices that err,be,dy the
' 1 blender

(I) Cell Homogenate


centrifugation
current, stabilized knowledge in a more suitable way. The hi:;torian·,JQf.
[10.8) (5,000 X g)
science usually looks at a "museum of abandoned systems."
In order to remain a research system, therefore, such machinery Supernatant
be operated differentially. If it is organized in a way such that the p[(lduc":' ,?'(mlel"i, cell debris) centrifugation
tion of differences becomes the organizing principle ofits ref,roducti,)n; iii I (12,000 X g)

~supernatant
\ can be said to be governed by or to create that kind of subversive
displacing movement Jacques Derrida has called the "differance."35 (3) Sediment
ferance" operates at the basis of what has become known as deco:nstru,o" (mitochondria) centrifugation
tions, as Derrida prefers to say in the plural: "a certain dislocation wincH"
[1.3) I (45,000 X g, 60 minutes

repeats itself regularly ... in every 'text,' in the general sense I W<JWU "M
to attach to that name, that is, in experience as such, in social, hi,;to,rie,t/;
(4) Sediment ~(5) Supernatant
(microsomes) (enzymes)
economic; technical, military reality."36 [1.0) [0.4)
How differential reproduction operates on the level of expeJrirrlen.clF
systems can be seen if we pursue the work of the Hllnl'in:gtc,n orot,oiIi ~ecorlSti'",",d activity:

synthesis group. Besides radioactive tracing, a new technique ofreFJre"en"


tation was introduced at the time of the DNP-induced reorientation.
},'::::~~::::::
~i:;
+ microsomes
+ enzymes
4.2
6.6
mechanical disintegration of the liver tissue, the resulting cell sap rni'toch0l1dr.ia + microsomes + enzymes 9.8
10·5
differentially fractionated by means of a laboratory centrifuge. Differ:enltial"
centrifugation of liver-cell homogenates was not in itself a new 13· I. Fractionation diagram. The numbers give the activity of the frac-
deavor." The problem was that the whole fractionation process in counts per minute {cpm] per milligram of protein. Reconstructed from
made sense if the "incorporation" activity that had been observed in Siekevitz, "Uptake of Radioactive Alanine in Vitro into the Proteins of
experiments with animals and with tissue slices could be preserved ,~" k.t m Fractions;' Journal of Biological Chemistry r 9 5 (1952): 549-65.

the shape of the system was completely changed from in vivo to in .


does not come as a surprise, therefore, that the first detailed report been the driving force for "going in vitro." The essential point was
such a fractionated incorporation system appeared only in 1952.38 the crudely structured partition of the cell sap created an interface
report is remarkable in several respects. It reflects how, in the or·oc",,·O betV{"en two techniques of representation: that of radioactive tracing, and
the establishment of a cell-free protein synthesis system, the backl.round' of differential centrifugation of the cytoplasm, metabolic function,
complexity alluded to as "biochemical bog" was dealt with. At that . topology,
ical stage, the fractionated incorporation signal still was too "dirty" to In Figure 13. I, we see how representational devices and scientific
unequivocal, but already sufficiently "clean" to produce some counts that are, to use the words of Michael Lynch and Steve Woolgar, "inex-
allowed one to regard the fractionated system as a successor to the interconnected."39 The content of the liver cells was unpacked
vious in vivo studies. On the other hand, the experiments yielded different fractions. The fractions were operationally defined in terms
information with respect to the energy dependence of the process at different centrifugal ford~s by means of which lighter and heavier
There was an answer, but again, it was not an answer to the question tprnp,)n',nts could be separated. Some of the fractions contained cellular
294 Hans-Jorg Rheinberger Graphematic Spaces 295

components that could be identified by microscopic inspection \W._... , .'·~~~~t~~~';~;~~ gathered did stimulate the incorporation process. Not-
mitochondria)-yet another layer of representation. This did not mean, ," ,",1 the whole system worked only if external energy resources
however, that the fractions were defined by these components. Rather; : added. However, A TP as such a resource failed to do this job. And
the centrifugation velocity determined the fractions, and the partition . .' ,·:0'_.11_. the reconstitution signal itself was on the borderline of resolution.
turn determined the provisional structure of the scientific object. Soon', then, had been achieved? The centrifugal representation did not
the language in which the experimental handling ofprotein synthesis 'desbroy any essential component required for the incorporation reaction.
captured also came to reflect the intimate packing of technical conditions , The promise was nothing else than the further differential reproduction of \\
and scientific object. The laboratory began to speak of protein synthesis the system. Two events, one small, one big, became crucial for the next
in terms of centrifugal velocities and of sedimentation properties.' of affairs: a modified homogenization method, 40 and a higher frac-
"45,000 X gsupernatants," and '~I2,OOO X gsediments" appeared. -n"",,'; resolution by the introduction of an ultracentrifuge. 41
entities represented a new kind of experimental reasoning. . Along the way, the research problem of the first period had silently
Another interesting aspect of this early fractionation work is the disappeared from the scene: the work was no longer directed toward the
lishment of meticulous procedures for washing, isolation, and Idenltlt1ca- of cancer cells., The other research problem had become
tion of radioactive protein. They were to ensure that the radioactivity traruifo.rmled into a powerful technological device: the incorporation of
could be recovered from the samples was indeed "incorporated" via ra,:tioactive amino acids into protein was now fairly well established. And
tide bonds. These procedures provided, on the one hand, a framc:wc>rktor althcm,;h the search for the role of ATP had not led to any appreciable
sorting out one specific metabolic event: peptide-bond formation. with respect to that question, it had led to a readily manipulable
on the other hand, they did not simply filter this single metabolic .fiiactional representation of the liver celi-to chopping it into several
out of a tremendous background of "contamination." They were '''COtllp<)nI,nt, necessary for the amino acid incorporation reaction.
trivial conditions-not merely to be granted in order to obtain
producible" results. They interfered with the metabolic signals of
Graphematic Spaces
experimental system: they destroyed what was "not wanted," and
prevented access to things unknown and beyond the acmal a research system, and given its formal dynamics as a machine for
investigation. To make the formation of srable peptide bonds a "hard "rrlakiin" the future, how does it organize what I have called, preliminarily,
meant to do away with any labile amino acid-bonding to other "tracing-game"? This is a question of representation. 42 What does
stances. The rigorous procedures for product analysis de"m.ed nece,;saIy"~: ;'h",rese,ntati,on mean? If we speak. of tracing, are we allowed to speak of
order to ensure the identity of the scientific object in its product at all? Mter all, the term representation implies the exis- \
prevented access to the conditions of its formation. The as,;urnption of a reference. But if we conceive of a scientiftc object investigated
derlying the construction of an in vitro protein synthesis sy';telm--n.anlel'y;, '!lI1ou,gn an experimental system as, deployed and articulated within a ~
that the "incorporation" of amino acids had to be accounted for in of material representation-such as radioactive tracing and centrifu-
of alpha-peptide bond formation-took the form of a destruction' .fractionation-the traditional meaning of "representation" is erased.
everything else that was not alpha-peptide bonding. . :We certainly miss the specificity of the procedure if we consider
These experiments provided a first glimpse of a reconstituted arrlinl,:i'o« l"1l!eSerltation simply as a "theoretical" reflection of some kind of "real-
incorporation activity. None of the fractions was fully active per se; In the research process, what goes on practically and on a primary level
when they were recombined, the initial activity of the homogenate . :. ·the articulation of traces with the help of technical devices that can
restored. On the other hand, this was the oruy unequivocal result. mems"lv,,, be considered and manipulated as sufficiently stable embodi-
the main fractions could defmitely be sorted out in order to narrow of concepts or theo.ries. Trace-articulations are what I call epi-
the synthetic activiry. Especially, there was no hint that the m.Jlto,:h(mCIr1 things. Once srabilized, they can be transformed into technical
might be dispensed with; on the contrary. The fraction in which th"vv."" that allow researchers to produce new research objects. They
296 Hans-Jorg Rheinberger Graphematic Spaces 297

become implemented into the process of realizing further unprece,ienlted of presentation/ absentation" going on. For every grapheme is the
events. su]pplression of another one. Trying to show or enhance a particular trace
Representation: What goes on when the experimentalist produces inevitably means trying to suppress another one. It is as in a game with
chromatogram, a protein sequence, an array of tubes, to which pieces wedges. If you drive in one, you drive out the other. In an ongoing
filter paper are correlated, on which, in turn, counts per minute of radio''': research endeavor one usually does not know which of the possible traces
active decay are superimposed? All these epistemic procedures are the' " be suppressed and which should be made more prominent. So, at
objects of an ongoing process of materialized interpretation. They repre:':: " least for shorter spans of time, the game of presentation/ absentation has
sent certain aspects of the scientific object in a form that is manipulable in' ," ':; tobe conducted as reversibly as possible. In other words, the epistemic ~l
the laboratory. The arrangement of these graphernatic traces or graph" " thing must be allowed to oscillate between different interpretations/ VI
emes and the possibility of their being articulated in a particular space
representation constitute the experimental "writing-game." Out of these . Experimental systems create spaces of representation for things that
units the experimenter composes what he calls his "model." .: otherwise cannot be grasped as scientific objects. A biochemical represen-
What is the status of graphematic articulations? A polyacrylamide gel tation in particular creates an extracellular space for processes assumed to
in a biochemical laboratory, for instance, is an analytical tool to separate run in the cell under regular conditions. The laboratory language speaks
macromolecules; at the same time, it is a graphematic display of com.:.: ',. of model reactions here. Models of what? Models ofwhat is going on "out
pounds visualized as stained, fluorescent, absorbent, or radioactive spotS; , I there in nature." Thus, "in vitro systems" would be models for "in vivo
The represented scientifIc object, the embodied model, then is colnpared situations." But what goes on "within the cell"? The only way to know it
to other models, to gther representations. Thus, the comparison .' ls to have a model for it. Thus, "nature itself" only becomes "real," in \\\

~
nitely does not take place between ('nature" and its "model," but rather ~, 's'Cientific and technical perspective, as a model. And so in vivo experi-
between the different graphematic traces that can be produced ments, too, are model systems. In an in vitro system, any intact cell
particula'r spaces of representation. It is their matching, not the '; behaves, as Zamecnik once said, as a "whole cell artifact."45 Paradoxically
between representation and nature, that gives us the sense of ,'reality" , ~e are faced with the notion of a natural artifact. There is no external and
ascribe to the scientifIC object under study.43 The "scientific real" is" ' : final point of reference for anything that becomes involved in the game of
world of traces. Bruno Latour and Steve Woolgar have distinguish"d, scientific representation. The necessity of representation as intervention)
between machines that "transform matter between one state and !mplies that any possibility of immediate evidence is foreclosed. ~
other," and apparatuses or "inscription devices" that "transform pieces , What, then, do scientists do practically when engaged in the produc-
matter into written documents."44 This separation often fails to be of epistemic things? They continuously subvert the opposition be-
in a clearcut manner. What is a polyacrylamide gel? It transforms m'"tter..... ,',, •• ,, representation in the traditional sense of the word and reality,
it separates molecules-and it produces an inscription-blue spots, betw,eell IllO,ieland nature. scientific
\ instance, on its vertical axis. We have to go a step further and look at
ensemble of the experimental arrangement, including both types of treat representatIOn not as something of another order,
chines, as a graphematic activity. A written table or a printed curve the condition of the possibility of knowing things, but as the
only the last step in a series of transformations of a previous gr:.plmnalj( of the Further-
disposition of pieces of matter, which is given by the experimental representation as and they re-
rangement itself. in the sense of a rep.etition, an iterative act. Any intervention in
The production of "inscriptions" is neither an arbitrary process of a scientific Nature cannot be
which anything goes, nor is it completely determined by the techni,ca this activity. It is experimental nature only inso-
conditions and the instrumental equipment of the respective 'it is always already representation, insofar as it is always already an
the differential reproduction of experimental systems there is a oerrrlanerr ,leillient, however marginal, of the garne. With that representation is
Hans-Jorg Rheinberger Graphematic Spaces 299

always already the representati~n of a representation. As Hacking puts jrt


the real, as a problenl, comes into existence "as an attribute of representa-
tions."46 The same goes for the model. The model is part of what is
modeled, and what is modeled itself is always already a model. Jean
Baudrillard speaks of a "precession of the model": "Facts no longer have
any trajectory of their own, they arise at the intersection of the models."47- -;
Instead of conc~iving ~he epistemic activi~ of ~epresenting or ~odeling,
as an asymmetnc relatIOn, we should consIder It to be syrmnetnc: both
[ terms of the relation are representations or models of each other. 48
I will try to exemplifY this with another episode from the history of
the in vitro protein synthesis system. The episode refers to the "microso"'''
mal fraction" of that system. In 1952, it was considered to stimulate the
incorporation reaction. Two years later, it had acquired the status of one
of the essential fractions. In order to sediment this material quantitatively;
the cell homogenate had to be centrifuged at high speed and for a longer
time. This could not be done until an ultracentifuge had become available
at the Huntington Laboratories in 1953, and it would have made no sense'
to do before it had become possible to obtain more active homogenates. 49
In order to examine this high-speed sediment with respect to -its'
particulate appearance, another technique of representation had to be
introduced into the system: the electron microscope. The untreated'
cytoplasmic fraction looked heterogeneous and appeared to be composed
of large, irregular chunks of intracellular membrane vesicles, and
electron-dense particles of a somewhat more regular size. Using deox": .' ".c '~ ,

ycholate as a detergent,50 the membrane vesicles obviously dissolved and: ;L;~i


the electron-dense particles could be recovered from a 105,000 X g .'
13·2. Electron micrographs of microsome fractions: (I) micrograph of
mentation run (see Fig. IJ.2). These particles, although still v"cv;,win C particles from a microsome fraction, magnification
size, exhibited an average diameter of about twenty nanometers, and X; (2) micrograph of an untreated microsome fraction, magnification
RN A to protein content was nearly equivalent, whereas in the Orl~lIliIJ" X. Reproduced from John W. Littlefield, Elizabeth B. Keller, Jerome
microsome fraction the respective ratio was approximately 1:8. and Paul C. Zamecnik, "Studies on Cytoplasmic Ribonucleoprotein Par-
sounds quite straightforward, yet there were, once again, nontrivial from the Liver of the Rat," Journal of Biological ChcmistlY 2I7 (1955): III-
culties with the technique of representation: what was re':o',er'ed fix)m
detergent-~nsoluble sediment in terms of RNA-rich "rib(lmlcleopn)teini',(',
in its RNA/protein composition largely depended upon the conoentra" . situation, alternative spaces of representation had to be opened in
tion of the solubilizer. So the representation, or "definition" of the to ustabilize" the particle by way of a triangulation or calibration
cle was a matter of the preparative operations performed on it, and
cause the solubilization procedure brought all subsequent i',OcoJr!'Ol:atiiiii c:: of these representatipns operated on size and shape. Because the
activity in the test tube to a halt, there was no representational correlat",tcH had a dimension of only some twenty nanometers, the procedure
the preparative, operational definition in terms of biochemical fi1l1ctioriLii: , bound to the use of electron microscopic visualization. Yet the use of
300 Hans-Jorg Rheinberger Graphematic Spaces JOI

this technique brought with it serious operational problems of another


order: that of specimen preparation for inspection. Because electron mi- ~ 100.t\_ _ _........
croscopy is based on the physical interaction of an electron beam with the w
object to be visualized, the specimen is prone both to destruction by the :2
is 80 RNA
beam and! or to deformation by the addition of electron-dense heavy w
(J)
metal solutions used to "stain" and ftx the biological material. Because of
Z
preparation differences, Zamecnik's particles measured between 19 and 60
>-
33 nanometers, quite a considerable variation, whereas Palade's osmium- a:
w
treated particles were only 10 to 15 nanometers in diameter. 51 Were the 6
u
40 PROTEIN
particles homogenous and small, or were they heterogenous and larger? w
The problem could not be solved within the representational space of a:
f- 20
electron microscopy. zw
A further technique of representation brought into play was the sedic Cl

mentati~n pattern and sedimentation coefficient of the particles derived a:


w
Q. 0.2 04 06 0.8 10
and calculated from analytical ultracentrifugation. Zamecnik's particles .
appeared as a major "47S peak" in the optical record (see Fig. 13.3). This NA DEOXYCHOLATE IN PER CENT
peak resembled the main macromolecular component already described :' ,Figure I3·4· Effect of sodium deoxycholate concentration on the recovery of
for rat liver by Mary Petermann and her coworkers. 52 A broader ,. and protein from a roS,ooo X g microsomal sediment. Reproduced from
running ahead of the 47S particle disappeared upon treatment of the. Lit:rle.fiel.d" Keller, Gross, and Zamecnik.
material with 0.5 percent of the detergent. But there was also a smlaw",
peak running behind the 47S particle, which did not disappear upon 'same treatment. Was the ribonucleoprotein portion of the microsomal
fraction itself heterogenous after all? Again, the question could not be
answered within the framework of this representational technique alone .
4 MIN. 18 MIN. .r," Still another representation of "ribonucleoprotein particles" was the

~u
r ':.ha.ra';teristic change of their biochemical composition as a function of
a. increasing solubilizer concentration. This was a typical biochemical
,·repre:serltatiO!l. Raising the level of detergent caused the nonsolubilized
pr""t,ein remaining on the particles to decrease more or less monotonically,
wJllereas for RNA, a clearly definable boundary showed up (see Fig. 13.4).
b.
LJu 0·5 percent deoxycholate, virtually all RNA of the fraction re-
'1hium,d in the unsoluble material. Beyond this value, however, the RNA
c;w,as ~~ra,ju;illy lost to completion. This biphasic behavior of the RN A with
·''''':;I>e.ct to the solubilizer could be taken to point to an edge at which the
.bi!~dlenllcal representation indicated a qualitative change in the cohesion
!he]l1aviot of the particle.
Figure 13.3. Ultracentrifugal analysis of microsomes after four and eiE~",en'
For all representational techniques, there was no conceivable external
minutes at 37,020 rpm in a Spineo model centrifuge. The sedimentation
cion is indicated by the arrows. Reproduced from Littlefield, Keller, Grossi
rejten,nc:e concerning the shape and composition of the scientific object
'. preparation. Its shape could not simply be derived by comparison
l:: Zamecnik.
'I "model" particle with a "real" particle; it gradually took some shape
~:
302 Hans-Jorg Rheinberger
Graphematic Spaces 303
from a correlation of representations constructed from different biophysi- to change the identity of its components, and it fails to do so by its very
cal and biochemical techniques. 53 And because the material was no longer presence as a supplement. This is because a supplement, by definition,
active in the test tube with respect to 'amino acid incorporation after the tends to be supplemented by "another" one. A model is a model in the
different isolation procedures, there was no functional reference for com- perspective of something at which it fails to arrive. It functions preCisely
parison. The experimental representations partially matched each other in the sense of a Rotmanian "xenotext." I quote from Signifying Nothing:
and partially interfered. The "deoxycholate particle" entered the field of "Wha,t it [the xenotext] signifies is its capacity to filrther signify. Its value
in vitro protein synthesis around 1953. and around 1956 it disappeared is determined by its ability to liring readings of itself into being. A
again from the scene because no ways were found to render it functionally xenotext thus has no ultimate 'meaning,' no single, canonical, definitive,
active. Nevertheless, it had a transitory function quite generally charac- or final 'interpretation': it has a signifIed only to the extent that it can be
I teristic for the production of epistemic things. It was a tentative inven-
tion. It was a step on the laborious path of trying to bring the fractional
made to engage in the process of creating an interpretive future for itself.
I representation of the cell sap into resonance with some functional sutures
It 'means' what its interpreters cannot prevent it trom meaning." 55

il of protein synthesis-in the present case, amino acid incorporation into.,:


proteins. Ribonucleoprotein particles that were active in vitro becam,e, ,'i
,1\, only available some years later in the course of a process that involved the ,
recomposition of the ionic composition of the buffer system, the ex",,:
change of the solubilizing material, and the switch to another cellular
source for the particles.

Xenotext
In the construction of scientific objects, I see a process in which differ·enr'·
representations are made to bear upon each other. Insofar as this pH)CeSS;
as a research process, has no predictable outcome, I am inclined to put
constructivist vocabulary in brackets and declare: If there is
specific for scientific representation, it is to deconstruct itself Within
continuum between epistemic things and technical things, what we
ally call a "model" occupies a kind of middle position. As a rule,
epistemic things, models are already sufliciently established to be re,:anled
as promising areas of research and therefore to function as research
tors. On the other hand, they are not yet sufliciently standardized in
to serve as unproblematic subroutines in the differential re]m)dllctiorl'o.lli
other experimental systems. Thus, an experimental model
j, always something of the character of a supplement in the sense D,:rriclli',
{,I confers on the notion. 54 It stands for something only the absence
J'I allows it to become effective. If the supplement presents itself as a
i addition, it has nevertheless the potential to direct the differential
ment of the whole system. The subversion ofan experimental system
f
supplement shows both aspects characteristic for that movement: it
~,
Notes to Pages 280-85 425

126. Ferdinand de Saussure, Course in General Linguistics, trans. Roy Harris


Duckworth, 1983). All references to Saussure's text are to this edition.
127· Ibid., p. 33.
128. Ibid., p. II8.
129. Ibid., p. 120 .
. 130. Rousselot made this argument in his "La methode graphique appliquee
a ",dler<;he des transformations inconscientes du langage," Comptes rendus du
sdentifique internationale des Catholiques (1891), sect. S, pp. 109-12. See
SO..Mich;lelHagner's very fine accounts of Broca's and Wernicke's work on the
localization of language functions, an important component of Saus-
concept: Michael Hagner, "Vom Stottern des Menschen zum Stocken der
lase:hille;" in Im Zug der Schrift, ed. Norbert Haas, Rainer Nagele, and Hans-
·Rheinberger (Munich: Wilhelm Fink, 1994), pp. 26-31; and Hagner,
fiirnbi"dc:r: Cerebrale Representationen im 19. und 20. Jahrhundert" (paper
at the 1994 Berlin Summer Academy).
3I. See Harris, pp. 204- I 8.
32. Saussure, Course, pp. 110-20. See also Samuel Weber, "Saussure and the
JPaJ:itic)U ofLangnage: The Critical Perspective," MLN 9 I (1976): 9 13 -3 8.
3'3. Saussure, Course, p. lI6. 134. Ibid., p. 13·
Ibid. 136. Ibid.
. Emile Durkheim, The Rules of Sodological Method, trans. W. D. Halls
Macmillan, 1982), p. 51.
138 .. French engineers since the 1830S had spoken of graphic inscriptions in
terms, referring to them as monnaie mecanique. See J.-V Poncelet, Cours de
appliquee aux machines (Paris: Gauthier-Villars, 1874), p. 2.
139. Saussure, Course, p. 110.
- 140. Brbl, "Science of Language," p. 133.
, . 141. Saussure, Course, p. lIS. 142. Ibid.
Ibid., p. II7. 144. Ibid., p. 115·
,, . Harry Collins, Artificial Experts: Sodal Knowledge and Intelligent Machines
;).mlbridg;e, Mass.: MIT Press, 1990), pp. 22-29.
146. Saussure, Course, p. 18.
147. Ibid., p. 10.
148. See Derrida, "Linguistic Circle"; and- OJ Grammatology, trans. Gayatri
(Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1974).

13. Rheinberger, Graphematic Spaces

This essay was presented at the Summer Academy of the Rathenau Program
[·Hist,)[v of Science on "Writing Science," Berlin, July 1991. The essay partly
on material published in 'Hans-J6rg Rheinberger, "Experiment, Differ-
and Writing: I. Tracing Protein Synthesis," and "II. The Laboratory Pro-
426 Notes to Pages 285-87 Notes to Pages 287-89 427

duction of Transfer RNA," Studies in the History and Philosophy <if Science on research in biomedicine, bioche:nristry, biology, and molecular biol-
(1992): 3QS-3I, 389-422. I thank an anonymous reviewer for challenging and draws upon the use made of it in the everyday language of the scientist.
encouraging comments. among many references, FranyoisJacob, The Statue Within (New York: Basic
I. Ian Hacking, Representing and Intervening (Cambridge, Eng.: Camllricigi 1988), p. 234. Only very recently have historians of science started to
University Press, 1983), pp. 149-50. k.ro,~. aware of the historiographic potential of the idea of the experimental
2. Peter Galison, How Experiments End (Chicago: University of Robert Kohler, in dealing with Drosophila, Neurospora, and the rise of
Press, 1987). 'biiocloernical genetics~ speaks of "systems of production." See Robert Kohler,
3. Peter Galison, "History, Philosophy, and the Central Metaphor," Scien"dli' '''Systems of Production: Drosophila, Neurospora, and Biochemical Genetics,"
Context 2 (1988): 197-212, quoted from p. 211. Historical Studies in the Physical and Biological Sciences 22 (1991): 87-130; RobertE.
4. Andrew Pickering, ed., Science as Practice and Culture (Chicago: U1UV,,,slltV , Lords of the Fly (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994). David
of Chicago Press, 1992). See also, from varying perspectives, Kactirl Knorr t:etiill:i 1\mlb'lll and Terry Stokes use the notion of "manipulable systems" in their
The Manufocture of Knowledge (Oxford: Pergamon Press, 1981); Harry M.
Changing Order (London: Sage Publications, 1985); Steven Shapin and
Schaffer, Leviathan lmd the Air-Pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the E''PeJ·jm.ent"H'1fi

;\,
of malaria research at the Walter and Eliza Hall Institute of Medical
~~::~:'~h in Melbourne. See David Turnbull and Terry Stokes, "Manipulable
and Laboratory Strategies in a Biomedical Institute," in Le Grand,
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1985); Allan Franklin, The 16 7-92.
Experiment (Cambridge, Eng.: Cambridge University Press, 1986); Bruno 14. There is a simple reason for this restriction: We cannot claim that all
and Steve Woolgar, Laboratory Life (Princeton: Princeton University Press, scien,tific activity is locally constrained without accepting that this holds for our
David Gooding, Trevor Pinch, and Simon Schaffer, eds., The Uses ojExpeni/tl/;t uw." a',,,,'''y, too.
(Cambridge, Eng.: Cambridge University Press, 1989); David Gooding, 15. Mahlon Hoagland, Toward the Habit oj Truth (New York: W. W. Norton,
ment and the Making ojMeaning (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1990); Homer E. Le p. xvii. Hoagland speaks of the "selection ofa good system" as one key to
ed., Experimental Inquiries (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1990); Allan Franklin, E':peJ;m"nt success on the "itinerary into the unknown" (p. xvi).
Right or Wrong (Cambridge, Eng.: Cambridge University Press, 1990). 16. George Kubler has labeled his thoughts about the temporal forms of aids-
5. Thomas Kuhn, The Trouble with the Historical Philosophy oj Science ,. oic pm,iu(:tic>D as "Remarks on the History of Things." Under the aspect of formal
bridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1992), p. 90. ':'s,eqllen.ces of works of art, experiments, tools, and technical constructs, Kubler
6. Bruno Latour, "One More Turn After the Social Turn: Easing "The value ofany rapprochement between the history ofart and the history
Studies into the Non-Modern World," in The Social Dimensions of Science, , .- of science is to display the cormnon traits ofinvention, change, and obsolescence
Ernan McMullin (Notre Dame: Notre Dame University Press, 1992), pp. "; that the material works of artists and scientists both share in time." See George
94· The Shape of Time (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1962), p. ro.
7. Bruno Latour, Science in Action (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard 17. Bruno Latour, "The Force and the Reason ofExperiment," in Le Grand,
Press, 1987), pp. IJ2-J4. emphasis added.
8. Jacques Derrida, "Structure, Sign, and Play in the Discourse of the 18. See, e.g., Karl Popper, The Logic of Scientific Discovery (New York: Harper
Sciences," in Writing and Difference (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, &Row, 1968), p. 107.
PP·27 8-9J. 19. Ludwik Fleck, Genesis and Development oj a Sdentijic Fact (Chicago: Uni-
9. Gaston Bachelard, The New Scientific Spirit (1934; Boston: Beacon of Chicago Press, 1979), p. 96.
1984), p. IJ. 20. Ibid., p. 86.
10. Gaston Bachelard, L'Activite rationaliste de la physique contemporaine 21. Jacob, Statue Within, p. 9.
Presses Universitaires de France, 1951), p. 84. 22. Bachelard, New Scientific Spirit, p. 139.
11. Bachelard, New Scientific Spirit, p. 6; the translation has been 23. Paul C. Zamecnik, "The Use of Labeled Amino Acids in the Study of the
·,.
slightly. Metabolism of Normal and Malignant Tissues: A Review," Cancer Re-
12. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations (Oxford: Basil 10 (1950): 659-67, quoted from p. 659.
well, 195J), § 7, § 654· 24. Robert Loftfield, "Preparation of C14-Labeled Hydrogen Cyanide, Al-
13. The notion of "experimental system," as it is introduced here, and Glycine," Nucleonics I (1947): 54-57.
428 Notes to Pages 289-96 Notes to Pages 296-303

25. For a retrospective review, see Robert Loftfield, "The Bi'DS)'llthe:;;', riIe"pioic constraints operating upon competing local representations." N. Kath-
Protein," Progress in Biophysics and Biophysical Chemistry 8 (1957): 348-86. Hayles, "Constrained Constructivism: Locating Scientific Inquiry in the
26. Zamecnik, p. 663. of Representation," in Levine, pp. 27-43, quotation on p. 33·
27. W. E Loomis and Fritz Lipmann, "Reversible Inhibition of the C(lUlilitlg' 44. Latour and Woolgar, p. 51; see also Latour, Science ill Action, pp. 64-70.
Between Phosphorylation and Oxidation," Journal of Biological Chemistry 45. Marvin Lamborg and Paul C. Zamecnik, "Amino Acid Incorporation
('948): 807-8. Protein by Extracts ofE. Coli," Biochimica et Biophysica Acta 42 (1960): 206-
28. Ivan D. Frantz, Jr., Paul C. Zamecnik, John W. Reese, and M,,,,,,r;'.'
Stephenson, "The Effect of Dinitrophenol on the Incorporation of 46. Hacking, p. '36.
Labeled with Radioactive Carbon into the Proteins of Slices of Normal 47.JeanBaudrillard, Simulations (New York: Semiotext(e), 1983), pp. 31-32.
Malignant Rat Liver," Journal ifBiological Chemistry 174 (1948): 773-74. 48. Harry Collins has described this situation lucidly. But because he still
29·Jacob, Statue W'ithin, p. 274. . to break the circle of the "experimenter's regress," he gives "society" the
30. Ibid., p. 255. to do so. See Collins.
3 I. Frao/i=ois Jacob, The Possible and the Actual (Seattle: University 49. Compare notes 40 and 41. The first fractionations by ultracentrifugation
ington Press, 1982). The French title is Lejeu des possibles. this laboratory were reported in Elizabeth B. Keller and Paul C. Zamecnik,
]2. Jacques Derrida, OJ Grammatology, trans. Gayatri Spivak (B't!tilnoi~: :'~4~:~~~s~Incorporation of C14-Amino Acids into Protein in Cell-Free Liver
Johns Hopkins University Press, 1974), pp. 23-24, and elsewhere. "! " Federation Proceedings 13 (1954): 239-40. Compare also Paul C.
33. Ibid., p. 24· ?;amecni~ and Elizabeth B. Keller, "Relation Between Phosphate Energy Do-
34. Fleck, p. 96. Incorporation ofLabeled Amino Acids into Protein," Journal of Biological
35. Derrida, Grammatology, p. 23. ]heJnistry 20 9 ('954): 337-54·
36. Jacques Derrida, "Une 'folie' doit veiller sur la pensee: Interview 50. In 1952, Strittmatter and Ball from the Harvard Medical School had
Fram;ois Ewald," Magazine litteraire (Mars 1991): 18-30, see pp. 26-27;' that deoxycholate rapidly clarified a microsome suspension-it solubilized
translation. fgg:rej,.ted material, presumably the lipoproteins. Cornelius F. Strittmatter and
37. For a contemporary overview, see Albert Claude, "Studies on G. Ball, "A Hemochromogen Component of Liver Microsomes," Proceed~
Morphology, Chemical Constitution, and Distribution of Biochemical of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 38 (1952): 19-
tion," Harvey Lectures 43 (1950): 121-64. Initially, deoxycholate had been used for disrupting bacterial cells and for
38. Philip Siekevitz, "Uptake of Radioactive Alanine in Vitro into "omlCtimg macromolecular components. Avery, MacLeod, and McCarty had
teins of Rat Liver Fractions," Journal of Biological Chemistry 195 (1952): it for isolating their "transforming agent."
39. "Our position is that representations and objects are in"xtricahlyirite 5 I. George E. Palade, «A Small Particulate Component of the Cytoplasm,"
connected; that objects can only be 'known through representation.' " qfBiophysieal and Biochemical Cytology' ('955): 59-68.
Lynch and Steve Woolgar, eds., Representation in Scientific Practice (Cll11bri:dg" 52. Mary L. Petermann, Nancy A. Mizen, and Mary G. Hamilton, "The
Mass.: MIT Press, 1990), p. 13. .MatI:onoo'lecu]'" Particles of Normal and Regenerating R..'1t Liver," Cancer Re-
40. The recipe came from a neighboring lab of the Huntington Mem,6!:i>, 13 (1953): 372-75; Mary L. Petermann,·Mary G. Hamilton, and Nancy A.
Hospital and had been developed for quite a different purpose. Nancy . "Electrophoretic Analysis of the Macromolecular Nucleoprotein Parti-
Bucher, "The Formation of Radioactive Cholesterol and Fatty Acids ~ of Mammalian Cytoplasm," Cancer Research 14 (1954): 360-66 .
C14-Labeled Acetate by Rat Liver Homogenates," Journal of the American . :, 53. In paraphrasing the adequation theory of truth, Latour has called this
Sodety 75 ('953): 498. . in his wonderful Kitchen Latin, adaequatio la/Joratorii et laboratorii.
41. The instrument was introduced into the system in 1953. Latour, The Pasteurization of France (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Univer-
42. There is a growing body of literature on the pn)bIeITI oj' rep,,:sellta'~."\ '988), p. 227·
science. For an overview, see Lynch and WQolgar. See also George 54. Derrida, Grammatology, p. 145·
Realism and Representation (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1993)." 55. Brian Rotman, Signifying Nothing: The Semiotics of Zero (New York: St.
43. "We cannot see reality in its positivity. We can only feel it thrOtlgill;! Press, 1987), p. 102.

Вам также может понравиться