Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 382

Neoconstructivism

This page intentionally left blank


Neoconstructivism
THE NEW SCIENCE OF COGNITIVE DEVELOPMENT

Edited by
SCOTT P. JOHNSON

1
2010
3
Oxford University Press, Inc., publishes works that further
Oxford University’s objective of excellence
in research, scholarship, and education.

Oxford New York


Auckland Cape Town Dar es Salaam Hong Kong Karachi
Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Nairobi
New Delhi Shanghai Taipei Toronto
With offices in
Argentina Austria Brazil Chile Czech Republic France Greece
Guatemala Hungary Italy Japan Poland Portugal Singapore
South Korea Switzerland Thailand Turkey Ukraine Vietnam

Copyright © 2010 by Scott P. Johnson

Published by Oxford University Press, Inc.


198 Madison Avenue, New York, New York 10016
www.oup.com

Oxford is a registered trademark of Oxford University Press.

All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced,


stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means,
electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise,
without the prior permission of Oxford University Press.

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data

Neoconstructivism : the new science of cognitive development / edited by Scott P. Johnson.


p. cm.
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 978-0-19-533105-9
1. Cognition in infants. 2. Attention in infants. 3. Perception in infants.
I. Johnson, Scott P., 1959–
BF720.C63N46 2009
155.4′13—dc22 2009007210

9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1
Printed in the United States of America
on acid-free paper.
FOREWORD

What is Neoconstructivism?
Nora S. Newcombe
Temple University

Piaget was supposed to have solved the problem is organized into modules that are not only neu-
of the origins of knowledge, to have bridged the rally specialized and present from the begin-
nativist–empiricist split. This goal was one of ning but that do not accept information from
his aims in beginning to study children’s cogni- each other. Indeed, nativists have argued that
tive development, and, at the end of his life, he evolution could not work to create human intel-
regarded this goal as accomplished (Chapman, ligence without such modular organization—
1988). Yet, even before his death, criticisms of there must be some thing for evolution to select
Piaget were mounting (Gelman & Baillargeon, or weed out (Cosmides & Tooby, 1994). And
1983). They now form a familiar litany: no clear nativism solved the second of Piaget’s main
evidence for stages and structuralism, insuf- problems (one that had shrunk to minuscule
ficient attention to the gradualisms and local- size by the hypothesized existence of so much
isms of cognitive progress, excessive emphasis innate knowledge) essentially by fiat—by pos-
on verbal justifications of judgments. Among tulating simple “triggers” that led children to
these limitations, two issues stand out: an overly select parameters or fi ll content into slots. More
lean delineation of the starting points for cog- recently, they have added the hypothesis that
nitive development, and a description of the change occurs when human language bridges
mechanism of cognitive change that was little the gap across modules of core knowledge
more than a re-naming of the phenomenon as (Spelke, 2003).
accommodation. None of these postulates of nativism are,
So, how do we characterize starting points however, supported by the evidence. Starting
and developmental change? These two ques- points are strong, but infants are not tiny adults
tions were addressed in a bold way by the with insufficient control over their arms and
resurgence of nativism, which came roaring legs. There is much more conceptual change
back on the intellectual scene in the 1950s with than nativists envision and strong evidence that
Chomsky’s (1959) critique of Skinner and which environmental input is integral to cognitive
had become the dominant paradigm for think- development in complex ways that go far beyond
ing about the origins of knowledge by 1980 or triggering (Newcombe, 2002). There is also good
so. Nativism solves the first of Piaget’s problems reason to think that language, while helpful to
by definition—by postulating the richest start- human thought, is not the sine qua non of cog-
ing points imaginable, ones that encompass all nitive flexibility (Newcombe & Ratliff, 2007). So,
the “core knowledge” required to understand what’s the alternative to nativism? Information-
the world. An important addition to this philo- processing theorists of the 1970s and 1980s
sophically classic position, appearing in force in retained lean starting points and used produc-
Fodor (1983), was the idea that the mind/brain tion system modeling to address the problem of

v
vi FOREWORD

change (Klahr & Wallace, 1976). However, there consider Piaget in a new light. Perhaps his
seems to be more initial competence than most life work did after all come close to his goal of
such modelers were willing to contemplate. In reconciling nativism and empiricism. He was
addition, these modeling efforts, like the con- wrong about many things—the viability of
nectionist modeling that succeeded produc- structuralism, the leanness of starting points,
tion systems, have often failed to use empirical the lack of a need for close study of input and
information about the kind and sequence of mechanism. He was also living at a time when
environmental information to constrain the he could not follow up thoroughly on his nods
models (Newcombe, 1998). Vygotsky has some- to social interaction, or to what might have
times been presented as an alternative to Piaget, been his fascination with the architecture
but his work concentrates too exclusively on and processes in the physical substrate (the
social and cultural interaction to seem to pro- brain that is the mind). Nevertheless, his fun-
vide a satisfying overall framework for many damental idea seems now to have been abso-
aspects of cognitive development (Newcombe & lutely right: that a biologically prepared mind
Huttenlocher, 2000). interacts in biologically evolved ways with
The need for new approaches to cogni- an expectable environment that nevertheless
tive development became increasingly evident includes significant variation. The chapters in
by 1990, and several books began to fi ll the this book collectively show us the promise of
need for nonnativist approaches to cognitive neoconstructivism.
development: Elman et al. (1996); Gopnik and Here are some tenets that I think unite the
Meltzoff (1997); Karmiloff-Smith (1992); Siegler neoconstructivist approach.
(1996); Thelen and Smith (1994). However, each
of these approaches also has some limitations, • Everyone is a Darwinist. That is, all theoriz-
for example, of scope or specificity. In addi- ing in cognitive development is situated in a
tion, they competed with each other, so that, for context in which we must consider the adap-
example, connectionism and dynamic systems tive value of thinking, and how it developed
theorists spent much time debating whether over evolutionary as well as developmental
their efforts were similar or different (Spencer, time. There is no need to cede the Darwinian
Thomas & McClelland, in press). The end result high ground to the modularity theorists or to
is that there is not, as yet, a dominant theoreti- the nativists in general.
cal framework within which to situate the large • Experience expectancy is a key concept.
volume of exciting recent empirical work on Keeping this valuable concept (delineated by
cognitive development—research that some- Greenough, Black, & Wallace, 1987) firmly
times seems to define theory better than debate in mind, we can see how nature’s solution to
that is self-consciously theoretical (Oakes, the problem of the construction of knowledge
Newcombe, & Plumert, in press). Research on could as easily—arguably more easily—have
cognitive development has gained steadily in been the selection of neural abilities that will
interest for several reasons—better techniques inevitably learn from their expectable input
and methods, established phenomena with what needs to be learned. There is no a priori
richly detailed data that allow for finely tuned need for specific content to be wired in—al-
competing explanations to be pitted against though of course some may be.
each other, and better and better contact with • The world is richly structured and well
insights and methods from cognitive science, equipped with perceptual redundancies and
neuroscience, computer science, and compara- correlations that support experience-expect-
tive psychology. But it is missing an “ism” to ant learning. This idea is a fundamentally
define it. Gibsonian one, although it acquires new reso-
Into this healthy and hopeful intellectual nance in contemporary theorizing, in which
ferment comes this book. It is forthrightly we can specify how the information is “picked
titled Neoconstructivism, returning us to up” rather than simply asserting that it is.
FOREWORD vii

• Humans (and perhaps other species as well) description (and “thick” description [see
bring to the task of learning about their world Geertz, 1973] comes close to being a cause);
a rich endowment in computing probabili- material cause is analogous to the neural
ties, lying at the heart of the work on statis- substrate; final cause is analogous to putting
tical learning discussed in this book, as well development in an evolutionary and adap-
as of Bayesian approaches to cognition and tive context; efficient cause is analogous to
its development. These abilities go a long way an analysis of the interactions of input with
to solve the problem of profligate association the neural substrate and the current cognitive
that nativism is fond of using to attack more state of the learner.
balanced approaches that include empiricist
elements. The chapters in this book cover many domains
• A richly structured world and a strong capac- (although not all) and more important, they
ity for probabilistic reasoning interact, within agree in many ways, subscribing either explic-
the experience-expectancy framework, to itly or implicitly to the list of key ideas listed
select among and/or to integrate the multiple above. But within the species of neoconstruc-
cues typically available to draw conclusions tivists, there are also dimensions of variation,
about causality, to remember spatial location, just as cats differ in their markings, eye color, or
and so forth. even in the possession versus absence of a tail.
• Action plays a key role in learning and devel- The two most important differences among the
opment, just as Piaget thought, not only chapter authors are the following:
because it creates the occasion for experi- • How strongly domain-general is human
ment but also because it allows for situations cognition and cognitive development? Some
that are more replete with information than investigators in the neoconstructivist tradi-
observation. tion embrace domain generality while oth-
• Development and learning are closely inter- ers clearly work within a domain-specific
twined concepts but not quite the same. framework. Note, however, that, importantly,
Development is learning as the learner domain specificity does not entail either
changes. For example, the learner acquires a nativism or modularity.
shape bias or the idea that words are reliable • How bottom-up versus top-down is human
cues to categories. As another and different cognition and cognitive development? Some
example, perceptual tuning, especially in the chapter authors seem to think that bot-
first year of life, works by pruning capacities tom-up approaches are necessary to avoid the
not by adding to capacity, to create a funda- extremes of nativism while others are more
mentally altered learner. comfortable with top-down influences—
• Developmental change can be quantitative, recognizing that those influences may them-
qualitative, or both at the same time, depend- selves be constructed.
ing on the granularity of observation. The
oft-cited dichotomy between quantitative Going back to the issue of a new “ism” to replace
and qualitative change that is supposed to nativism as the framework for thinking about
distinguish theories of developments should cognitive development—is neoconstructivism
be consigned to the dustbin of history; see just one more “ism” that can be added to the list
Thelen and Smith’s (1994) elegant discussion of contenders for a contemporary alternative?
of the “view from above” and the “view from Does it vie with connectionism, or dynamic
below.” systems thinking, or emergentism, or overlap-
• Analyses of the causes and mechanisms of ping wave theory, or small-p piagetianism, or
developmental change need to proceed on other terms or schools of thought? Very impor-
all four of Aristotle’s fronts—looking for tantly, I think the simple answer is No. The eight
formal, material, final, and efficient causes. tenets listed above establish a neoconstructivist
Formal cause is analogous to developmental big tent that can cover all of the specific schools
viii FOREWORD

of thought mentioned above and more. What Klahr, D., & Wallace, J. G. (1976). Cognitive devel-
can then ensue is the sorting out of the specific opment: An information-processing view.
issues in empirical description, theory making Oxford: Lawrence Erlbaum.
and modeling that are the normal business of a Newcombe, N. S. (1998). Defi ning the radical mid-
mature science. Piaget’s biggest idea, if not his dle. (Essay review of J. Elman et al., Rethinking
Innateness). Human Development, 41, 210–214.
many smaller ones, has turned out to be right
Newcombe, N. S. (2002). The nativist-empiricist
after all. controversy in the context of recent research
on spatial and quantitative development.
REFERENCES Psychological Science, 13, 395–401.
Newcombe, N. S., & Huttenlocher, J. (2000).
Chapman, M. (1988). Constructive evolution: Making space: The development of spatial rep-
Origins and development of Piaget’s thought. resentation and reasoning. Cambridge, MA:
New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. MIT Press.
Chomsky, N. (1959). A review of B. F. Skinner’s Newcombe, N. S., & Ratliff, K. R. (2007).
Verbal Behavior. Language, 35, 26–58. Explaining the development of spatial reori-
Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (1994). Origins of domain entation: Modularity-plus-language versus
specificity: The evolution of functional orga- the emergence of adaptive combination. In
nization. In L. A. Hirschfeld & S. A. Gelman J. Plumert & J. Spencer (Eds.), The emerging
(Eds), Mapping the mind: Domain specificity in spatial mind (pp. 53–76). Oxford University
cognition and culture. (pp. 85–116). New York: Press.
Cambridge University Press. Oakes, L. M., Newcombe, N. S., & Plumert,
Elman, J. L., Bates, E. A., Johnson, M. H., J. M. (2009). Are dynamic systems and con-
Karmiloff-Smith, A., Parisi, D., & Plunkett, K. nectionist approaches an alternative to “good
(1996). Rethinking innateness: A connectionist old-fashioned cognitive development”? In J.P.
perspective on development. Cambridge, MA: Spencer, M. Thomas & J. McClelland (Eds.),
MIT Press. Toward a new grand theory of development?
Fodor, J. A. (1983). The modularity of mind. Connectionism and dynamic systems theory
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. re-considered (pp. 268–284). Oxford: Oxford
Geertz, C. (1973). Th ick description: Toward University Press.
an interpretive theory of culture. In The Siegler, R. S. (1996). Emerging minds: The process of
Interpretation of Cultures: Selected Essays (pp. change in children’s thinking. New York: Oxford
3–30). New York: Basic Books. University Press.
Gelman, R., & Baillargeon, R. (1983). A review of Spelke, E. S. (2003). What makes us smart? Core
some Piagetian concepts. In J. H. Flavell and knowledge and natural language. In D. Gentner
E. Markman (Eds.), Cognitive development: and S. Goldin-Meadow (Eds.), Language in
Vol. 3, Handbook of child development (pp. mind: Advances in the investigation of language
167–230). New York: Wiley. and thought. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Gopnik, A., & Meltzoff, A. (1997). Words, thoughts Spencer, J. P., Thomas, M., & McClelland, J.
and theories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Eds.) (in press). Toward a new grand theory
Greenough, W. T., Black, J. E., &Wallace, C. S. of development? Connectionism and dynamic
(1987). Experience and brain development. systems theory re-considered. Oxford: Oxford
Child Development, 58, 539–559. University Press.
Karmiloff-Smith, A. (1992). Beyond modularity: Thelen, E., & Smith, L.B. (1994). A dynamic sys-
A developmental perspective on cognitive sci- tems approach to the development of cognition
ence. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. and action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
CONTENTS

Contributors xi
Introduction xiii
Scott P. Johnson

I. OBJECTS AND SPACE

1. Attention in the Brain and Early Infancy 3


John E. Richards
2. All Together Now: Learning through Multiple Sources 32
Natasha Kirkham
3. Perceptual Completion in Infancy 45
Scott P. Johnson
4. Numerical Identity and the Development of Object Permanence 61
M. Keith Moore and Andrew N. Meltzoff

II. WORDS, L ANGUAGE, AND MUSIC

5. Connectionist Explorations of Multiple-Cue Integration


in Syntax Acquisition 87
Morten H. Christiansen, Rick Dale, and Florencia Reali
6. Shape, Action, Symbolic Play, and Words: Overlapping Loops
of Cause and Consequence in Developmental Process 109
Linda B. Smith and Alfredo F. Pereira
7. Musical Enculturation: How Young Listeners Construct
Musical Knowledge through Perceptual Experience 132
Erin E. Hannon

ix
x CONTENTS

III. LEARNING MECHANISMS

8. Integrating Top-down and Bottom-up Approaches to Children’s


Causal Inference 159
David M. Sobel
9. What Is Statistical Learning, and What Statistical Learning Is Not 180
Jenny R. Saff ran
10. Processing Constraints on Learning 195
Rebecca Gómez
11. Mixing the Old with the New and the New with the Old:
Combining Prior and Current Knowledge in Conceptual Change 213
Denis Mareschal and Gert Westermann

IV. INDUCTION

12. Development of Inductive Inference in Infancy 233


David H. Rakison and Jessica B. Cicchino
13. The Acquisition of Expertise as a Model for the Growth
of Cognitive Structure 252
Paul C. Quinn
14. Similarity, Induction, Naming, and Categorization: A Bottom-up
Approach 274
Vladimir M. Sloutsky

V. FOUNDATIONS OF SOCIAL COGNITION

15. Building Intentional Action Knowledge with One’s Hands 295


Sarah Gerson and Amanda Woodward
16. A Neoconstructivistic Approach to the Emergence of a Face
Processing System 314
Francesca Simion and Irene Leo

VI. THE BIG PICTURE

17. A Bottom-up Approach to Infant Perception and Cognition: A


Summary of Evidence and Discussion of Issues 335
Leslie B. Cohen

Author Index 347


Subject Index 361
CONTRIBUTORS

Morten H. Christiansen Denis Mareschal


Department of Psychology Centre for Brain and Cognitive Development
Cornell University Birkbeck College, University of London
Jessica B. Cicchino Andrew N. Meltzoff
Department of Psychology Institute for Learning and Brain Sciences
Carnegie Mellon University University of Washington
Leslie B. Cohen M. Keith Moore
Department of Psychology Institute for Learning and Brain Sciences
University of Texas at Austin University of Washington
Rick Dale Nora S. Newcombe
Department of Psychology Department of Psychology
University of Memphis Temple University
Sarah Gerson Alfredo F. Pereira
Department of Psychology Department of Psychological and Brain Sciences
University of Maryland, College Park Indiana University—Bloomington
Rebecca Gómez Paul C. Quinn
Department of Psychology Department of Psychology
University of Arizona University of Delaware
Erin E. Hannon David H. Rakison
Department of Psychology Department of Psychology
University of Nevada, Las Vegas Carnegie Mellon University
Scott P. Johnson Florencia Reali
Department of Psychology Department of Psychology
University of California, Los Angeles University of California, Berkeley
Natasha Kirkham John E. Richards
Centre for Brain and Cognitive Development Department of Psychology
Birkbeck College, University of London University of South Carolina
Irene Leo Jenny R. Saffran
Department of Psychology Department of Psychology
University of Padova University of Wisconsin—Madison

xi
xii CONTRIBUTORS

Francesca Simion David M. Sobel


Department of Psychology Department of Cognitive and Linguistic
University of Padova Sciences
Brown University
Vladimir M. Sloutsky
Center for Cognitive Science Gert Westermann
Ohio State University Department of Psychology
Oxford Brookes University
Linda B. Smith
Department of Psychological and Brain Amanda Woodward
Sciences Department of Psychology
Indiana University—Bloomington University of Maryland, College Park
Introduction

The term neoconstructivism was generated by combining neo, taken from the Greek neos, meaning
“new,” and constructivism, taken from (among other sources) the pioneering theorist and researcher
Jean Piaget. Piaget’s constructivist theory holds that cognitive development is a continual process of
building knowledge on previous skills (e.g., perception, memory, and action repertoires) and existing
knowledge structures, from a foundation at birth consisting largely of reflexes and sensory impres-
sions. It seems to me a first principle of any theory of development that development happens—every
human being that ever existed or ever will started out as a fertilized egg and grew from there. This
is hardly an insightful observation, yet it is rarely mentioned in the literature, and consequently our
understanding of the “growth” of cognition is woefully incomplete. Piaget’s constructivism, and now
neoconstructivism, represent attempts to address this problem.
The origins of this book are rooted in an idea that came to me in 2003. The idea was motivated
by the following observations. Research on cognitive development, particularly in infancy, consists
largely of demonstration studies—experiments designed to show some cognitive skill at a partic-
ular age, often with little or no consideration of limitations characteristic of young infants’ per-
ceptual skills and cortical immaturity, and often with little or no consideration of development.
Demonstration studies can be contrasted with process studies—experiments designed to examine
mechanisms underlying performance or development that support the skill in question or bring it
about.
Back in 2003, I thought that the balance of the field was weighted heavily toward demonstration
studies, which tend to grab attention and headlines (“Infants Are Smarter Than You Think” and
such). These studies have an important place in the literature, and my colleagues and I have produced
a few ourselves. Yet progress in the field relies also on an understanding of process, in particular
developmental mechanisms, because an understanding of development is required for a complete
characterization of any psychological phenomenon. My idea in 2003 was to organize a symposium
focusing on process studies as a theme for a major developmental conference. I began attending
conferences in 1992 (the International Conference on Infant Studies, or ICIS, in Miami), and was
not aware of any such symposium having been organized previously. So I asked around, got agree-
ments from four principal researchers in the area (most of whom are represented by chapters in this
book), and submitted it to ICIS for the 2004 meeting in Chicago under the title “The Big Questions in
Infant Cognition: Trenchant Debate, Tentative Answers.” Talks were presented on object perception,
categorization, word learning, and dorsal/ventral visual processing.
The reviewers accepted the symposium, and the reception at the conference itself far exceeded
any of our expectations. The room was packed and overflowing; some audience members sat
on the floor, stood at the back, and stacked up deep outside the doors. At that time, I thought either

xiii
xiv INTRODUCTION

(a) we got lucky in terms of the conference schedule, (b) this is a fluke, or (c) there is pent-up demand
for discussion of developmental mechanisms at our conferences. To fi nd out, I tried it a second
time, submitting a symposium titled “Origins and Ontogenesis of Human Cognition” (all of whose
contributors have chapters in this book) to the 2007 meeting of the Society for Research in Child
Development in Boston. This time, the talks centered on memory development, grammar learning,
and social cognition. Again, the room, though substantially larger than the 2003 symposium, was
full to overflowing.
Finally, I organized a smaller meeting, held in November 2006 in New York City and generously
funded by the National Science Foundation, bringing together 12 of the 24 authors who appear in
this book. Participants in the meeting and authors in this book are all active researchers in cogni-
tive development whose work, though involving a wide range of methods and approaches, coheres
in a common framework: an explicit focus on developmental mechanisms of human cognition. The
meeting was productive, enlightening, and encouraging, and suggested to me (and, I think, the other
participants) that we are really onto something worthwhile.
I think the fields of developmental and cognitive science need this book and others like it. The
range of methods and approaches is not necessarily representative of relevant research as a whole,
but it is representative of some of the questions that are being asked and of some of the important
findings that have been yielded in the past several decades. I hope you find it useful.
I would like to thank the authors for their hard work; Catharine Carlin at Oxford University
Press for her enthusiasm and patience; the National Science Foundation for funding the meeting in
2006; the NSF, National Institute of Child Health and Human Development, Economic and Social
Research Council, and Nuffield Foundation for supporting my own work, and my family, in particu-
lar Kerri Johnson.

Scott P. Johnson
Los Angeles
PART I

Objects and Space


This page intentionally left blank
CHAP TER 1
Attention in the Brain and Early Infancy

John E. Richards

HYPOTHESIS: INFANT ATTENTION


covered by the myelin sheath. Myelin appears
DEVELOPMENT IS CONTROLLED
as “white” when viewed in the brain (fatty tis-
BY INFANT BRAIN DEVELOPMENT
sue reflects light). Thus, in autopsied brains,
Attention shows dramatic changes over the there are large areas called “white matter” that
period of infancy. At birth, there is little intrin- consist of long myelinated axons. Myelination
sic control of behavior and attention is affected is seen in magnetic resonance imaging (MRI)
mainly by salient physical characteristics of the T1-weighted scans as long channels of white
infant’s environment. By the age of 2 years, the matter surrounded on the edges by gray mat-
infants’ executive control systems are function- ter. Figure 1.1 shows MRIs from a newborn,
ing and infants voluntarily direct information 6-month-old infant, 15-month-old infant,
processing flow by allocating attention on the 10-year-old child, and an adult. The changes in
basis of well-defined goals and tasks. These the myelination appear to be rapid from birth
changes in attention affect a wide range of to the 15-month MRI scan, then slower after-
cognitive, social-emotional, and physiological wards. Myelination of the axon results in less
processes. noisy and quicker transmission, making the
The attention changes in young infants communication between neurons more effi-
occur simultaneously with substantial changes cient. It often is used an explanatory mechanism
in the brain. At birth, the structure, myelina- for how changes in the brain affect cognitive
tion, connectivity, and functional specialization development (e.g., Klingberg, 2008; Yakolev &
of the brain are relatively primitive. Much of the Lecours, 19672008). The changes in myelin have
brain’s structural development occurs between been documented in several publications, most
birth and 2 years. Many brain areas showing notably in the work of Yakolev and Lecours
these changes are closely linked in adult partici- (1967), Kinney and colleagues (Kinney, Brody,
pants to cognitive processes such as attention. Kloman, & Gilles, 1988; Kinney, Karthigasan,
A natural inclination is to hypothesize that the Borenshteyn, Flax, & Kirschner, 1994), and
changes in attention development are caused by Conel (1939 to 1967). (also see Johnson, 1997;
the changes in these brain areas. Klingberg, 2008; Sampaio & Truwit, 2001).
One example of the brain changes is the The relationship between brain development
axonal myelination of neurons. Myelin is a fatty and attention development has been hypothe-
substance that in adult brains covers the axons sized by several models. I recently reviewed my
of many neurons. Figure 1.1 shows a “typical” own view of the relationship between brain cen-
neuron with an unmyelinated portion (cell ters controlling eye movement, brain develop-
body, dendrites) and whose axon is completely ment in these areas, and developmental changes

3
4 OBJECTS AND SPACE

Dendrites

Cell body

Newborn 6 Months 15 Months

Axon

Myelin

Axon terminal 10 Years


Adult

Figure 1.1 The left figure is a cartoon drawing of a “typical” neuron with unmyelinated dendrites, cell
body, and axon terminal, and the myelin sheath covering the axon. The MRIs are T1-weighted slices
taken at the same anatomical level (anterior commisure) from participants from birth to adult. The
myelination of the long axons in the brain is seen as “white” matter in the adults and there are large
changes from the newborn to the adult period.

in attention (Richards, 2008). I will briefly (medial temporal, parietal), and show changes
summarize my observations here. beginning at 3 months and lasting throughout
There are three types of eye movements the period of infancy.
used to track visual stimuli and each eye move- There have been several models theoriz-
ment type is controlled by areas of the brain ing how the areas of the brain controlling the
that show different developmental trajectories. eye movement develop, and how these changes
“Reflexive saccadic” eye movements occur in affect attention-controlled eye movements,
response to the sudden onset of a peripheral including models by Bronson (1974, 1997),
stimulus, are controlled largely by subcortical Maurer and Lewis (1979, 1991, 1998), Johnson
brain areas, and are largely intact by 3 months and colleagues (Johnson, 1990, 1995; Johnson
of age. “Voluntary saccadic” eye movements are et al., 1991, 1998, 2003, 2007), Hood (Hood,
under voluntary or planned control, involve 1995; Hood, Atkinson, & Braddick, 1998), and
several parts of the cortex (occipital, fusiform Richards (Richards, 2002, 2008; Richards &
gyrus, parietal cortex, frontal eye fields), and Casey, 1992; Richards & Hunter, 1998). Iliescu
show rapid development from 3 to 9 months and Dannemiller (2008) review several per-
of age. “Smooth pursuit” eye movements occur tinent “neurodevelopmental” models. These
either voluntarily or involuntarily toward models hypothesize that change in the brain
smoothly moving objects, involve several cor- areas controlling the eye movements result
tical areas of the brain involved in voluntary in the overt changes in the eye movements.
saccadic eye movements and some areas not With respect to attention-directed eye move-
involved in voluntary saccadic eye movements ments, particularly in the first few months, the
ATTENTION IN THE BR AIN AND EARLY INFANCY 5

voluntary saccadic system is most relevant. It age and performing a brain dissection, or with
has been hypothesized that connections within invasive neuroscientific techniques such as
primarily visual areas of the cortex (e.g., pri- direct neural recording or lesions. These tech-
mary and secondary visual cortex) and myeli- niques may be applied to individuals who also
nation/connectivity to other areas of the cortex participate in tasks measuring behavioral per-
(e.g., parietal area PG) show growth spurts in formance and psychological processes. An
about 3 to 6 months. These brain changes are example of this approach is work on infant
accompanied by changes in the voluntary track- memory by Bachevalier (2008). She has shown
ing of objects in the visual field (Richards & that changes in memory in young monkeys are
Holley, 1999), changes in the attention-directed closely related to the development of the brain
eye movements toward peripheral visual targets areas that are the basis for this type of memory
(Hunter & Richards, 2003, submitted; Richards in adults. Lesioning these areas in the infant
& Hunter, 1997), and changes in the ability to monkey disrupts the onset or occurrence of this
shift attention “covertly” without making an eye type of memory. Bachevalier makes the parallel
movement (Richards, 2000a, 2000b, 2001, 2005, between the age-related monkey performance
2007b; also see Richards, 2004b, and the section and human infant performance on analog ver-
“Brain and Attention: Spatial Orienting”). sions of the visual preference procedure and
visual discrimination tasks. She concludes that
her experiment suggests that the basic neural
WHAT’S INSIDE A BABY’S HEAD?
systems underlying these memory tasks in mon-
The previous section presented the hypothesis keys and humans are parallel, and that studies
that brain changes in young infants are respon- of infant monkeys inform us about comparable
sible for the changes seen in psychological pro- memory development in infant humans.
cesses, with an emphasis on attention-directed There are several assumptions necessary
eye movements. There are many aspects of for the study of the study of infant nonhuman
infant cognitive development that have been animal to be relevant to human infants. First,
explained as a function of brain development; this study requires that a correlation can be
the field of “developmental cognitive neurosci- made between ages of the nonhuman animals
ence” uses this as a basic explanatory mecha- and human infants. For example, in a study
nism (Johnson, 1997; Nelson & Luciana, 2008). of changes in synaptogenesis in visual areas,
However, these models are severely limited in Bourgeois (1997) showed changes in rat, cat,
their description of what the actual brain is like macaque monkeys, and humans. Figure 1.2
for infants at a specific age or a specific infant shows comparable changes in the primary visual
at a specific age. They also are limited in their cortices of four different species. These changes
measurement of brain function (see the section show some similarity in the overall pattern of
“How to Measure Brain Activity in Infants”). change. However, the pattern of changes often is
I will review two ways in which brain develop- not isomorphic across species (e.g., compare the
ment has been modeled in past research. Then, prolonged decay in synaptic density in humans
I will assert that structural MRI techniques in Figure 1.2), and a comparison of development
should be used for this purpose. between species in one brain area might not be
The primary information about brain devel- the same for other brain areas. Second, one can
opment in infants comes from nonhuman ani- relate the changes in the brain in the nonhuman
mal models of brain development, primarily animals, the importance of these brain areas for
primates. For example, our knowledge of the a specific psychological process, and the changes
patterns of myelination, synaptogenesis, and in these psychological processes in human
neurochemical development comes primar- infants. This analysis presumes that there is
ily from study of normally developing non- an unequivocal relationship between the psy-
human animals. Nonhuman animals may be chological process and the brain area in devel-
studied by sacrificing the animal at a specific opment, which is a questionable assumption.
6 OBJECTS AND SPACE

Synaptogenesis in primary visual cortex


100%

BIRTH
RAT

PUBERTY

DEATH
3

0
100%
BIRTH

PUBERTY

DEATH
CAT

3
Density of synapses

LGN
V1
0
100%
BIRTH

MACAQUE
PUBERTY

DEATH
3
LGN
V1
0
100%
BIRTH

MAN
PUBERTY

DEATH
3
LGN
V1
0
10 102 103 104 105
Days after conception

Figure 1.2 Changes in the relative density of synapses in the primary visual cortex for four species.
The increase in synaptic density indicates synaptogenesis occurring, and the decline represents syn-
aptic pruning. Note the differences in the pattern of development relative to specific developmental
events (birth, puberty, death) in the four species. From Bourgeois (1997).

This type of analysis does not take into account of studies use analogical reasoning as a basis for
different developmental patterns for other brain nonhuman animal models being relevant for
areas and the influence of these brain areas on human infants. They cannot apply the invasive
human infant psychological activity. Third, this methods directly to human participants and
type of study assumes that brain–behavior rela- cannot inform us about the developmental sta-
tions in nonhuman animals are comparable to tus of the brain of individual infants.
those in humans. This assumption is doubtful A second way in which information about
due to the complexity of human behavior rela- human brain development has been obtained
tive to animals, the extremely large changes is from postmortem studies of young infants.
in brain size between nonhuman animals and Infants who die of neural-related causes and/
humans, and the relative size of brain areas in or other causes have been studied for a wide
humans and nonhuman animals (e.g., prefron- range of neuroanatomical, neurochemical, and
tal cortex; occipital cortex). Finally, these types cytoarchitectural processes (synaptogenesis
ATTENTION IN THE BR AIN AND EARLY INFANCY 7

# of myelinated fibers/0.005 mm2


30
Neuron # per 0.001 mm3

700 Layer VI (dotted lines)


Layer II (solid lines) 25
600
500
20
400 Layer I (dashed lines) Layer II (solid lines)
300 15
200
100 10
0 5
0 1 3 6 15 24 48 72
Postnatal age, months 0
0 1 3 6 15 24 48 72
Postnatal age, months

Newborn 1 Month 3 to 4 Months


1 1 1
2 2 2

3 3 3
4A 4A 4A
4B 4B 4B
4Cα 4Cα 4Cα

4Cp 4Cp 4Cp


5A 5A 5A
5B 5B 5B

6 6 6

M P P M S.C. B.G M P B.G. LGN S.C. M P B.G. LGN S.C. MT M MT V2, V3 etc
LGN LGN (P stream)
LGN LGN LGN

Figure 1.3 Work from Conel’s postmortem neuroanatomical studies (Conel, 1939 to 1967). The top
graphs show neural density in layers I and II (left figure) and the myelinated fiber density in layers II
and VI (right figure), both shown as a function of postnatal age (from Shankle et al., 1998). The bot-
tom figures show innervations of the layers in the primary visual cortex by different cell types at birth,
1 month, and 3 to 4 months of age.

in Huttenlocher, 1990, 1994; myelination in in more complex cortical functioning, shows


Kinney et al., 1988, 1994). The most well-known an extended time course for myelination. The
version of this kind of study is a series of stud- bottom figures show the types of neurons that
ies by Conel (1939–1967). Conel studied the innervate the cortical layers at different ages.
neuroanatomical and cytoarchitecture of the Conel’s work has been popular in develop-
layers of the human cerebral cortex in autop- mental cognitive neuroscience because of the
sied individuals. He measured six anatomical specificity of the information about the neu-
features, including cortical layer thickness, rophysiological processes being studied and its
cell density, numbers of cell types, and myeli- large age range. For example, Johnson (1990,
nated fiber density (Shankle, Romney, Landing, 1995; Johnson et al., 1991, 1998) posits that
& Hara, 1998). Figure 1.3 shows two types of development in the layers of the the primary
results from these studies. The top figures dis- visual cortex (e.g., Figure 1.3, bottom figures)
play neuron density and number of myelinated acts as a limiting factor for visual behavior and
fibers in two cortical layers as a function of age. visual attention controlled by brain systems.
Notice that the myelination of the layer 6, which Such developmental changes in the layers of the
receives input from noncortical areas and is primary cortex from birth to about 6 months
involved in simple cortical functioning, shows act as a gateway for the onset of these eye move-
myelination changes very early. Alternatively, ments in young infants.
layer 2, which has communications within lay- There are limitations of these postmor-
ers and with other cortical areas and is involved tem studies for developmental cognitive
8 OBJECTS AND SPACE

neuroscience. An implicit assumption is that been used to measure developmental changes


the individuals measured at different ages are in myelination (Sampaio & Truwit, 2001), dis-
representative of that age and provide knowl- tribution of white and gray matter in the cor-
edge about the brain status of specific individu- tex (O’Hare & Sowell, 2008), and biochemical
als of that age. It is likely true that the changes characteristics of the developing brain (Sajja &
across age are large enough that groups of Narayana, 2008). An interesting use of the MRI
infants at one age will have neuroanatomic and is the application of “diff usion tensor imaging,”
cytoarchectural similarities differentially from which details the connectivity of axons between
groups at different ages. However the develop- different areas in the brain (Wozniak, Mueller,
mental status of the brain of an individual are & Lim, 2008).
likely to show idiosyncratic individual differ- The use of structural MRI for determining
ences in brain development between individuals brain developmental status is relatively new but
at the same age. Second, these studies typically well underway. The most comprehensive study
are limited to small samples (single individual of brain structural development with MRI is
at each age) and restricted to infants who died. currently ongoing. The “NIH MRI Study of
If the reasons for the death are related to the Normal Brain Development” (Almli, Rivkin, &
characteristics being studied, the results will McKinstry, 2007; Evans, 2006; NIH, 1998) is a
not be applicable to a wide range of participants. multicenter research project sponsored by the
Without some independent verification of the National Institutes of Health to perform ana-
generality of the findings, these surely cannot tomical scans of about 800 children ranging in
be applied to determine the status of individual age from birth to 18 years. This study uses 1.5T
participants. These studies typically have used scanners to get T1- and T2-weighted images,
extremely limited samples for young infants proton density excitation, DTI, and other scans.
and children. An interesting aspect of this study is the collec-
One technique that may be used to examine tion of a large battery of neuropsychological and
the brains of individual infants is MRI. MRI developmental tests. This will allow the correla-
has been described in several publications (e.g., tion of psychological processes, neuropsycho-
Huettel, Song, & McCarthy, 2004; Thomas & logical status, and developmental level with
Tseng, 2008) and I will provide a brief overview the brain status of individual participants. The
emphasizing its use for studying the brain. MRI study will provide individual MRIs to research-
applies a very large magnetic field to the head. ers interested in these aspects, and likely will
The head’s media (skull, cerebrospinal fluid provide standardized or stereotaxic scans in
[CSF], brain) have magnetic properties such that the “MNI” framework (Montreal Neurological
the magnetic field aligns spinning protons in the Institute brain atlas, Mazziotta, Toga, Evans,
same direction as the field. Radiofrequency (RF) Fox, & Lancaster, 1995; Evans, Collins, & Milner,
energy pulses cause disruption of the magnetic 1992; Evans et al., 1993) or Talairach space
fields and disrupt the alignment of the protons. (Talairach &Tournoux, 1988; also see Talairach
MRI measures the disruption in alignment due Atlas Database Daemon, Fox & Uecker, 2005;
to the RF pulse and return of the alignment to Lancaster, Summerlin, Rainey, Freitas, & Fox,
the strong magnetic field. Different body tissue 1997; Lancaster et al., 2000). Currently (late
types have differing times to return to align- 2007) MRIs are available for children ranging
ment, and these differing times (or different in ages from 4 to 18 years. Most of the MRIs for
resonance frequencies and/or differing on/off the infant participants have been collected but
durations of the RF pulses) may be used to iden- are undergoing quality control.
tify where different types of media are located A second approach I am using in my current
in the head. This allows the identification and work is to acquire structural MRIs on infant
visualization of skull, skin, CSF, white and gray participants who also participate in studies
matter, myelin, vascularization, and other com- of attention, and relate the information found
ponents in the head. MRI measurement has about specific individual’s brain developmental
ATTENTION IN THE BR AIN AND EARLY INFANCY 9

status to performance in attention tasks. Parents nonsedated infants with success rates that range
of infants are contacted in the normal course of from 66% to 90% (Almli et al., 2007; Dehaene-
our contact system for psychological experi- Lambertz, Dehaene, & Hertz-Pannier, 2002;
ments. The parents who agree to participate in Evans, 2006; Gilmore et al., 2004; Paterson,
the MRI have several visits. First, the parent(s) Badridze, Flax, Liu, & Benasich, 2004; Sury,
and infant come to the MRI center located at Harker, Begent, & Chong, 2005). We have had
a local community/teaching hospital. The par- 100% success after the infant is sleeping; sev-
ent is shown the equipment and the process is eral infants have not been able to get to sleep.
described. Second, the parents return to the The parent is in the scanner room during the
MRI center for the scan. The procedures for the scan, along with a pediatric nurse. Finally, the
MRI recording use infants during sleep (Almli, infant and parent then come to a psychophysi-
Rivkin, & McKinstry, 2007; Evans, 2006; NIH, ological laboratory for studies of attention (see
1998). The infant and parent come to the MRI the section “Brain and Infant Attention: Spatial
center in the evening at the infant’s normal bed- Orienting”).
time. The infant and parent go into the dark- Several procedures are followed to insure
ened room with the MRI and the infant is put the infant’s safety, obtain a good recording, and
to sleep. Then the infant is placed on the MRI minimize the amount of time in the scanner.
table, earplugs and headphones put on, and Potential risks of MRI recording include scan-
then the recording is done. Figure 1.4 shows an ner noise, the magnetic fields, and magnetic
infant lying on the MRI bed—the headphones gradients. We use earplugs and earphones to
and cloths surrounding the infant can be seen. minimize scanner noise. The scans in our 3T
When the infant is in the MRI tube, a research magnet are optimized for the lowest sound lev-
assistant reaches in and has a hand on the infant els and fastest recording. The infants are placed
to see if the baby moves or wakens. Getting the on the bed on “memory foam,” covered snugly
baby to sleep usually takes about 45 to 60 min, with sheets, and have rolled washcloths around
and the MRI recording itself has scan sequences the head for restricting head movement com-
lasting in total about 20 min. Previous stud- fortably. The U.S. FDA considers MRI record-
ies from several laboratories have described ing in infants to be a “nonsignificant” risk when
procedures for performing MRI recording of used within FDA-specified parameters (USFDA,
2003, 2006). This assessment is based on over 20
years of MRI recording in neonate and infants
(e.g., Barkovich, Kjos, Jackson, & Norman,
1988; Rivkin, 1998) with no reports of del-
eterious long-term effects. Outcome studies of
such effects show that the magnetic field or the
magnetic gradients do not threaten the concur-
rent physiological stability of the infant during
scanning (Battin, Maalouf, Counsell, Herlihy,
& Hall, 1998; Taber, Hayman, Northrup, &
Maturi, 1998; Stokowski, 2005) and there are
several studies showing no short-term or long-
term effects from this type of recording (Baker,
Figure 1.4 An infant lying on the MRI bed going
Johnson, Harvey, Gowland, & Mansfield, 1994;
into the MRI tunnel. The infant is covered with
Clements, Duncan, Fielding, Gowland, Johnson,
a sheet and has a restraining strap lightly placed
across its body. The headphones and cloths sur- & Baker, 2000; Kangarlu, Burgess, & Zu, 1999;
rounding the infant can be seen in this picture. Kok, de Vries, Heerschap, & van den Berg,
A research assistant (left side of picture) and the 2004; Myers, Duncan, Gowland, Johnson, &
parent (right side of picture) are close to the baby Baker, 1998; Schenck, 2000). These risks are dis-
during the scan. cussed in detail in several sources (Barkovich,
10 OBJECTS AND SPACE

2005; Dehaene-Lambertz, 2001; Evans, 2006; attention and how they affect specific corti-
Stokowski, 2005). cal/cognitive processes. Neural activity pro-
Three scans are done on each infant. First, duces electrical currents that pass through the
we do a localizer sequence (45 s) to orient the media of the head and can be recorded on the
subsequent high-resolution slices. Th is orients surface of the scalp. This electrical activity is
the longitudinal fissure parallel with the sag- the electroencephalogram (EEG). We use the
gital plane, perpendicular to the coronal and EEG for cortical source analysis. One aspect of
axial planes, and the line between the anterior this analysis is the necessity to have a realistic
commisure (AC) and posterior commisure (PC) head model for the quantification. We obtain
is on the center MRI slice. This will orient the this from the MRI. Figure 1.5 shows the MRI
scan so that the MRI may be oriented relative recorded from the infant pictured in Figure 1.4.
to the origin for the stereotaxic space defined The middle section shows the media identified
by Talairach (Talairach & Tournoux, 1988). inside this baby’s head (i.e., gray matter, white
Second, the localizer scan is followed by a 3D matter, CSF, skull). The right section shows
MPRAGE T1-weighted scan. The T1-weighted a tetrahedral wireframe model of the identi-
(T1W) scan results in an MRI volume that fied sections. This wireframe model is used in
shows maximal distinction between gray mat- computer program such as BESA, EMSE, and
ter and white matter. The MPRAGE employs a my own computer program (Richards, 2006,
TI of 960 ms, a delay of 3000 ms between shots submitted) to identify the current sources of the
and an 8º flip angle, with a very short TE (4.9 EEG on the head. I will describe the details of
ms). Using this sequence, we can collect a 1 mm the EEG analysis in the next section (section on
isotropic (150 × 256 × 256 mm FOV) in about “How to Measure Brain Function”) and some
9 min. The gray matter, white matter, and CSF results from the study in a following section
can be segmented from the T1W scan, but a (section on “Brain and Infant Attention: Spatial
subsequent T2-weighted (T2W) scan helps to Orienting”). Whereas our use of these MRIs is
discriminate white matter and CSF with auto- primarily as an adjunct to current source analy-
matic segmenting routines. The T2W scan sis of EEG signals, specific aspects of the MRI
emphasizes liquid in the brain, so CSF is very can be used such as amount of myelination in
bright (high voxel values) relative to other brain brain areas, structure of brain areas, and per-
matter. This is acquired as a dual contrast pro- haps connectivity between brain areas.
ton density and T2-weighted sequence with Why is this approach important? The first
a dual echo fast spin echo sequence. The dual and perhaps obvious answer is that “cognitive
echo acquisition takes 4 min to acquire (256 neuroscience” requires measurement of both
× 256 matrix with rectangular FOV, 1 × 1mm the cognitive and the neural aspects of cogni-
pixel size, 2 mm slice thickness, no slice gap, tive neuroscience. A developmental cognitive
50 saggital slices in two interleaved packages, neuroscience study without measures of brain
echo train length of 10, first TE=13 ms, second development will be extremely limited. Second,
TE=101 ms, TR=4640 ms, parallel imaging fac- the structural MRI of individual infants is nec-
tor = 2). Any of the sequences may be repeated essary to relate the findings for particular par-
if degraded by motion artifacts; however, all ticipants to the functional data of particular
infants we have tested have been sleeping and infants. This is especially important given the
still during the entire scanning protocol. If only wide range of topographical changes over this
the T1W scan is available, some automatic clas- age, and the possibility that large individual
sification/segmentation routines are substituted differences might occur in infant brains. An
with manual segmentation routines of the T1W example of this problem is shown in Figure 1.6.
scan. This shows MRIs at a common stereotaxic posi-
What are the MRI scans used for? Briefly, tion (axial level of anterior commisure) across
the purpose of the attention studies is to iden- a wide range of ages. The wide range of head
tify areas of the brain involved in sustained sizes across this age, and some variability within
Figure 1.5 The MRI from the infant shown in Figure 1.4. The left scan is a saggital view of the
T1-weighted scan, with the cross-hairs indicating the position of the anterior commisure. The middle
figure is the brain segmented into skin and muscle (white), gray matter (red), white matter (green),
CSF (cerebralspinal fluid, yellow), dura (pink), skull (blue), and nasal cavity (purple). The right figure
is a representation of the tetrahedral wireframe used in EEG source analysis programs.

Newborn (3.0T), 1 & 3 Months (1.5T), 3.5 & 4.5 Months (3.0T)

6 & 6.5 Months (3.0T), 12 Months (1.5T), 12 Years (3.0T)

Figure 1.6 Axial T1-weighted MRI scans for participants ranging from birth to 12 years. Each scan
is presented at the axial level of the anterior commisure (blue cross-hairs). Note the large change in
shape and size, differences in the type of brain underlying similar skull locations, and the changes in
myelination across these ages.

11
12 OBJECTS AND SPACE

ages, is clear in these examples. Additionally, the have been identified for the MNI brain. For
exact type of brain media under the same skull example, Figure 1.7 (bottom right panel) shows
location differs across the infants. It is important various anatomical structures that have been
for the study of brain development to have struc- identified on the MNI brain. The MNI brain
tural information on particular infants. and associated brain areas may be used as a ste-
A third reason why this approach is impor- reotaxic atlas to identify structures in children
tant is that this allows specific comparisons at younger ages. The bottom part of the figure
across age in related structures. Figure 1.7 shows the structure identified on the MNI brain
shows brains of infants at 3 and 6 months, (bottom right panel), which is then transformed
and a 10-year-old child. The MNI brain is also to the head size and shape of the participants at
shown (Montreal Neurological Institute brain the other ages (three bottom panels on left). This
atlas, Mazziotta et al., 1995; Evans et al., 1992, may allow the direct comparison of the develop-
1993). The MNI brain consists of the average of ment of specific brain areas across a wide range
152 college-age participants. Several brain areas of participants.

3 Months 6 Months 10 Years MNI

Figure 1.7 Axial T1-weighted MRI scans for participants at 3 and 6 months, 10 years, and the “MNI”
brain, located on the axial level of the anterior commisure (cross-hairs). The bottom right MRI has
the anatomical locations overlaid in color derived from the MNI brain, and structures such as the pre-
frontal cortex (blue), temporal (red) and occipital (green) cortex, and several subcortical structures
may be seen. The three figures on the bottom left are the single participant brains with the stereotaxic
anatomical areas translated from the MNI brain to the individual participant.
ATTENTION IN THE BR AIN AND EARLY INFANCY 13

not tell us about the developmental status of the


HOW TO MEASURE BRAIN ACTIVITY
brain for an individual participant. With proper
IN INFANTS
caution, marker tasks and psychophysiological
There are multiple aspects of brain development measures allow inferences to be made about
that might be important in the development of brain development and help to inform a devel-
cognitive processes. The previous section gave opmental cognitive neuroscience approach to
some illustrative examples of the development attention.
of brain anatomy (brain structure). The field I have been using the EEG and scalp-
of cognitive neuroscience is interested in the recorded event-related potentials (ERP) as mea-
functioning the relationship between the brain, sures of brain activity. The EEG is electrical
and cognitive and psychological processes. The activity located on the scalp that is generated by
development of brain functioning is as impor- neural activity occurring in cell bodies or extra-
tant for developmental cognitive neuroscience cellular neural tissue. ERP are EEG activity that
as is the development of brain structure. is time-locked either to experimental events or
The measurement of brain activity during to cognitive events. Recently I have been advo-
psychological tasks in infant participants has cating the use of these measures with “cortical
been as difficult as the measure of brain struc- source analysis” (Reynolds & Richards, 2007,
ture. Most of the neurodevelopmental models 2009; Richards, 2003b, 2005, 2006, 2007a,
of infant attention mentioned in section 1 were 2007b, submitted). Cortical source analysis uses
based on the brain function of nonhuman ani- high-density EEG recording (Johnson et al.,
mals, so-called “marker tasks,” or speculative 2001; Reynolds & Richards, 2009; Tucker, 1993;
relations between overt behavioral measures Tucker, Liotti, Potts, Russell, & Posner, 1994)
and putative brain markers. I will briefly review to hypothesize cortical sources of the electrical
the older measurement techniques and then activity and identifies the location of the brain
comment on three new techniques. areas generating the EEG or ERP (Huizenga
Most neurodevelopmental models have & Molenaar, 1994; Michel et al., 2004; Nunez,
relied either on measurement of brain function 1990; Scherg, 1990, 1992; Scherg & Picton, 1991;
in animal models, or the measurement of overt Swick, Kutas, & Neville, 1994). The activity of
behavior putatively linked to brain activity. these cortical sources may be directly linked
Johnson (1997) calls the latter measures “marker to ongoing behavioral manipulations or psy-
tasks.” Marker tasks are behavioral activities chological processes. This results in a descrip-
that can be measured overtly but which are tion of the functional significance of the brain
thought to be controlled by specific brain areas. activity, i.e., functional cognitive neuroscience.
Johnson proposes that such tasks may be used Greg Reynolds and I have been using this tech-
in infants with the understanding that devel- nique to study infant recognition memory in
opment in these tasks implies brain develop- the paired-comparison visual-preference pro-
ment in the associated areas. I have discussed cedure (Reynolds, Courage, & Richards, 2006;
this proposal previously (Richards, 2002, 2008; Reynolds & Richards, 2005) and have recently
Richards & Hunter, 2002). Similarly, there are a reviewed our use of this technique (Reynolds &
wide range of studies using physiological indices Richards, 2009). I will present a brief introduc-
in the infant in psychological tasks (Richards, tion to this work but we have reviewed it else-
2004c; Reynolds and Richards, 2007). These where (Reynolds & Richards, 2007, 2009).
psychophysiological measures (e.g., heart rate, The basic outlines of this technique are as
EEG) have known physiological processes that follows. Recording of electrical activity on the
cause their activity and thus may show changes head (EEG, ERP) is made. The cortical source
in these processes linked to experimental analysis hypothesizes electrical dipoles gener-
manipulations or cognitive processing. Like the ating current inside the head as the sources of
marker tasks, psychophysiological measures the EEG (ERP) changes measured on the scalp.
are indirect measures of brain function and do The source analysis estimates the location and
14 OBJECTS AND SPACE

amplitude of the dipole. Figure 1.8 (top left MRI events. Figure 1.8 (bottom figures) shows the
slices) shows the dipoles for an ERP compo- activity of these dipoles for stimuli that were
nent known as the “Nc” that occurs in young novel or familiar, and which elicited atten-
infants in response to brief familiar and novel tion or did not. The activity of the dipoles dis-
stimuli (from Reynolds & Richards, 2005; also tinguishes the type of stimuli (experimental
see Reynolds et al., 2006, and Richards, 2003a). manipulation), the attention state of the infant
The spatial resolution of EEG for localizing (psychological process), and the temporal
brain activity is typically believed to be about 5 unfolding of the brain activity. Since neural
cm (Huettel et al., 2004), whereas source analy- activity is generating the EEG, the temporal
sis with realistic models has spatial resolutions resolution of this procedure is on the same time
closer to 1 cm (Richards, 2006). course of neural activity (1 ms). Our conclusion
The activity of the dipoles can be estimated from this analysis is that we have identified the
over time and in relation to psychological brain areas that generate the scalp-recorded

10 Prefrontal 10
Attention Prefrontal
Inattention
μV

μV

0 0
1000 ms 1000 ms

–10 –10

Figure 1.8 The sequence of MRI slides shows the dipole locations (yellow circles) for an ERP compo-
nent known as the Nc (topographical scalp potential maps on upper right figures). The activity of the
dipoles is shown in the bottom figures as a function of experiment condition (familiar stimuli on left ,
novel on right), psychological process (attentive dark line, inattentive solid line), and temporal pattern
(0 to 1000 ms following stimulus onset).
ATTENTION IN THE BR AIN AND EARLY INFANCY 15

Nc ERP component. The effects of attention on differentially absorbed/reflected by oxygenated


this brain activity are to enhance the ampli- and deoxygenated hemoglobin. The reflected
tude of the brain activity and make it occur light can be measured with a detector placed
more quickly to novel stimuli. Th is technique near the emitter, and the time course of the
offers a noninvasive tool for the measurement oxygenated and deoxygenated blood flow can
of brain activity, with spatial resolution suf- be measured. Th is procedure is being applied to
ficient to locate anatomical areas in the brain infant participants routinely (Mehler, Gervain,
and temporal resolution occurring on the same Endress, & Shukla, 2008).
time frame as activity in neurons (Reynolds & Both techniques have been applied to infant
Richards, 2009; Richards, 2006). participants. The recording of fMRI was done
I will mention two other techniques that in young infants of 2–3 months of age to study
might be useful to measure brain activity in speech perception (Dehaene-Lambertz et al.,
young infants. Both measure the change in 2002). Infants were presented with speech and
blood flow that occurs following neural activ- backward speech in 20 s blocks, alternating
ity. Neural activity occurring in a localized with 20 s periods of silence. MRI sequences
area of the brain results in changes in brain tis- were recorded about every 2 s (usually done in
sue resulting from the neural activity (e.g., neu- 3 mm slices). The fMRI technique examines the
rotransmitter release, ionic exchange between blood flow in the brain during the presenta-
neuron and surrounding media). These local tion of the sounds, subtracting the blood flow
changes affect arterial capillaries and arteries measurements during the periods of silence.
to effect the transport of oxygen and nutrients Figure 1.9 shows where in the brain these
to the area. Some of these changes occur over changes occurred. The MRI slices on the top
wide areas of the brain whereas some are lim- left are from three different levels. Brain activ-
ited to the area in which the neural activity ity during speech was larger than during the
occurred. silent periods in the colored areas on the MRI
Two techniques have been used in adult slices. This occurred over a wide range of areas
participants in cognitive neuroscience to mea- in the left temporal cortex. The time course of
sure these blood flow changes. The most famil- this activity is shown in Figure 1.9 (top left fig-
iar is “functional MRI” (fMRI; Huettel et al., ure). There was a gradual increase in blood flow
2004; Thomas & Tseng, 2008). Oxygenated and to these areas that peaked about 6 to 7 s after
deoxygenated blood have differing magnetic sound onset, continued during the presentation
properties that may be distinguished in MRI of the sound, and lasted for nearly 10 s into the
recording. When the blood flow (and resulting silent period.
oxygenation) change occurs immediately after The NIRS procedure has been used to study
neural activity, the MRI may be used to local- functional brain activity in newborns and young
ize these areas and show their time course. Th is infants (Mehler et al., 2008). For example, one
signal may then be related to the experimen- study investigated language perception in new-
tal manipulations or cognitive processes, i.e., borns (Peña et al., 2003). Figure 1.9 (bottom left
functional neuroimaging. Th is procedure has figure) shows the location on the scalp on which
been used extensively in young children and the emitters and detectors were placed. The
adolescents (Thomas & Tseng, 2008), but has numbers indicate the area on the scalp under
been applied only rarely in infant participants. which the blood flow is reflected. The middle
The less-familiar technique for measuring figure shows the same locations overlaid on the
activity-dependent blood flow is near-infrared brain. This study presented newborn infants
optical spectroscopy (NIRS) or optical topog- with forward and backward speech, with 15 s
raphy (OT). An infrared emitter placed on the stimulus periods and 25 to 35 s silent periods.
skull can send an infrared signal that pen- The bottom left figure shows the changes in the
etrates several millimeters (2 to 3 cm) into the total blood flow as a function of time for the 12
skull. Infrared light of differing wavelengths is recording locations. The blood flow changes for
16 OBJECTS AND SPACE

t(19 d.f.) % Signal change


6 1

4 0

2 –1

0 –2
2 4 6 8 10 12
Scans

1 2

0.3
3 4 5
1 2
3 4 5 6 7
6 7
8 9
11 10 8 9 10
12
11 12

Figure 1.9 Blood-flow-based neuroimaging techniques in infant participants. The upper figures show
the fMRI activations for activity at three levels of the temporal cortex, and the time course of this
activity is seen in the upper right figure (about 6 scans per 10 s). The bottom left figure shows the posi-
tioning of the NIRS detector (blue) and emitter (red) probes, and the lines and numbers between the
probes are the location of the scalp under which blood flow is measured. The middle figure shows the
putative brain locations being measured, and the right figure shows the time course of total hemoglo-
bin activity for forward speech (red), backward speech (green) and silent periods (blue).

the forward speech (red lines) were different measure of brain structure and function since
in the recordings over the left temporal cortex the procedure is directly measuring blood flow
than those for backward speech (green) or silent in the location of the cortical activity. The EEG
periods (blue). Comparable regions on the right source analysis procedure uses quantitative
temporal cortex (not shown) were not different inferential techniques to estimate such loca-
for forward, backward, and silent periods. The tions. The NIRS is limited to the analysis of the
onset of the maximal peak was 10 to 15 s follow- scalp-recorded optical changes. Th is restricts
ing stimulus onset and the blood flow changes its value for localizing brain activity. The exact
lasted 10–15 s after sound offset. These results type of brain material under the same skull
show that infants are sensitive to the properties location differs across infants at the same age
of speech at birth. Areas of the brain similar to and across ages (Figure 1.6). Second, the NIRS
those in older infants (i.e., Figure 1.9. top MRI and fMRI have a slower temporal resolution
figures) respond differentially to forward and than EEG/source analysis. The underlying
backward speech. measurement phenomenon in the former are
I will comment briefly on the relative advan- changes in blood flow, which occur over sec-
tages of these three techniques (EEG source onds (6–7 s for fMRI, 10–15 s for NIRS, Figure
localization, fMRI, NIRS) for the measurement 1.9) and continues to respond for several
of brain function in infant participants. First, seconds after stimulation. Alternatively, the
the fMRI technique provides the most direct EEG changes are caused by neural electrical
ATTENTION IN THE BR AIN AND EARLY INFANCY 17

activity occurring around the time of the


BRAIN AND INFANT ATTENTION:
synaptic potential changes of the neuron and
SPATIAL ORIENTING
are responsive to short-latency changes in this
neural activity (e.g., 100–200 ms in Figure 1.8). The previous sections have outlined the proposal
Th ird, the spatial resolutions of the three tech- that brain development and attention develop-
niques vary. MRI recording has <1 mm resolu- ment were closely related (section “Hypothesis:
tion for structural scans, and fMRI uses 3 mm Infant Attention Development is Controlled
slices and needs to perform averaging over a by Infant Brain Development), and elaborated
wide area. Motion artifacts may also degrade on methods used to measure brain structure
the spatial resolution of fMRI, especially for (section “What’s Inside a Baby’s Head?”) and
infant participants. The EEG techniques typi- function (“How to Measure Brain Function in
cally have resolution in the 5 cm range, though Infants”). The current section details a type of
EEG source analysis with realistic head models attention, “covert attention” or “covert orient-
probably lowers this to about 1 cm (10 mm). ing” that has been studied behaviorally, psy-
The NIRS technique has the poorest spatial chophysiologically, and with the functional
resolution, since its measurement technique brain measurement described in the previous
demands that emitter/detector distance be two sections.
about 2–3 cm. It also may have its resolution Studies with adult participants have shown
blurred by larger arterial vascular changes that attention may be moved around our envi-
occurring on the surface of the cortex carrying ronment flexibly. This is shown by the volun-
blood to intracortical capillaries. Fourth, the tary movement of the eyes from one location
three techniques vary in “ease of use.” The NIRS to another, which requires disengaging fi xation
and EEG recordings are noninvasive and can (and attention) at one location, moving fi xation
be done easily on infant participants behaving (attention) to another location, and engaging
in relatively unrestrained situations. The fMRI attention in the new location. The flexibility of
recording is extremely sensitive to motion arti- spatial attention is shown most dramatically in
facts and is best done in sleeping infants. Th is “covert attention” or “covert orienting.” Michael
restricts its use for the study of a wide range of Posner first studied this type of flexibility with
psychological processes in infant participants. the spatial cueing procedure (Posner, 1980;
The NIRS has the fewest quantitative require- Posner & Cohen, 1984). In this procedure, a par-
ments; EEG source analysis and fMRI requires ticipant is directed to pay attention to a location
extensive and sophisticated modeling with in space where a target will occur. The target
computer programs. The most used measure of identifies some action needed to be done by the
the three for infant cognitive neuroscience is participant. The target occurs in the periphery
EEG, and NIRS is beginning to be used. The and target identification is done without moving
fMRI technique has rarely been used. Whereas the eyes to the location, either during the target
I prefer the EEG source analysis technique as or in the time preceding target onset. The partici-
a temporally relevant and spatially appropriate pant’s response to the target is affected by several
method for infant cognitive neuroscience, the factors, which show that attention may be moved
three techniques offer complementary infor- about in space covertly. The cueing procedure
mation about infants’ developmental cogni- can use a cue in the same location as the target,
tive neuroscience. They provide measurement in which case the psychological process is called
of brain activity (and structure) in individual “covert orienting.” Alternatively, when a cue in
participants, rather than relying on brain mea- a different location than the target, or cues are
surement in other participants (i.e., nonhu- based on simple directions to “pay attention to
man animals, postmortem or autopsy studies) the right side,” the resulting psychological pro-
or on techniques, which at best only indirectly cesses are called “covert attention.”
measure brain activity (marker tasks, indirect Behavioral studies of this type of spatial ori-
psychophysiological recording). enting have been done in infant participants.
18 OBJECTS AND SPACE

The spatial cueing procedure developed by common variant is to present the peripheral pat-
Posner was first adapted by Hood (1995) to tern when the central stimulus is present, then
study covert orienting in infant participants. turn both stimuli off, then present a pattern,
Hood presented 3- to 6-month-old infants with functioning as a target, to which an eye move-
an interesting (color and movement) pattern on ment will be made. The target can be presented
the center of a video monitor. When the infant on the same side as the cue (“valid trials”), on
began to fi xate on this pattern, a stimulus was the opposite side (“invalid trials”), not presented
presented on the right or left side of the center; (“no-target control”), or can be presented on
the center pattern remained on. Infants at this a trial without the cue being presented (“neu-
age will not shift fi xation from a center pattern tral”). A number of studies show that in 2- and
that is engaging fi xation to the peripheral pat- 3-month-old infants, the time to move the eyes
tern. Thus, any differential response to the side from the center location to the target is faster
on which the cue was presented, or the cue on when the cue and target are on the same side
the side, would indicate that the infant was able (valid trials) than when no cue was presented or
to covertly orient toward the peripheral pattern the cue and target were on opposite sides (Hood,
in the absence of overt eye movements. Note 1993, 1995; Hood & Atkinson, 1992; Johnson
that this procedure differs from the typical & Tucker, 1996; Richards, 2000a, 2000b, 2001,
Posner-type spatial cueing procedure in which 2004a, 2004b, 2006, 2007). Figure 1.10 shows
verbal instructions are given to the participant this finding for 14-, 20-, and 26-week-old
to keep fi xation oriented toward the center of infants (Richards, 2000a). The left-hand figures
the display. show the time to move the eyes from the center
There are a number of behavioral findings location to the target when the stimulus-onset
for infants in this spatial cueing procedure. A asynchrony (SOA) was 350 ms. This time was

1200
Valid cue
Inhibition of return
Inhibition of return

Invalid cue &


1000 no-cue control
Facilitation

Inhibition of return

Inhibition of return
Facilitation
Facilitation

800
Msec

600

400

200

0
Age 14 20 26 14 20 26 14 20 26
SOA 450 875 1300

Figure 1.10 Reaction time in the spatial cueing procedure for infants at 14, 20, and 26 weeks of age, as
a function of stimulus onset asynchrony (SOA) and cueing type. The short SOA shows faster response
times for the valid cued trials than the invalid and neutral trials for the three testing ages, whereas
the medium and long SOA show inhibition of return only for the 20 and 26 week old infants. From
Richards (2000a).
ATTENTION IN THE BR AIN AND EARLY INFANCY 19

shorter on the valid trials for the three testing linking these ERP changes with fMRI recording
ages. This facilitation shows that the presence (Martinez et al., 1999). For example, in response
of the cue registered in the infant’s cognitive to a target occurring in one part of the visual
system even though fi xation continued on the space, there is an enhanced ERP component
central stimulus; i.e., covert orienting. labeled “N1” that occurs on the posterior scalp
An additional finding comes from the 20- on the contralateral side, i.e., where the occipital
and 26-week-old (4.5 and 6 months) infants. On brain areas for the opposite visual field are. This
trials when the time between the cue and tar- enhanced N1 seems to be caused by areas in the
get was relatively brief (e.g., 350 ms in Richards, extrastriate occipital cortex and the fusiform
2000a), infants showed the facilitation of the gyrus (Martinez et al., 1999). The inhibition of
response to valid targets. Alternatively, if the return effect is thought to be mediated by the
SOA was large enough (e.g., 700 to 1000 ms), superior colliculus (Posner, Rafal, Choate, &
the opposite occurred. The movement of the Vaughan, 1985; Rafal, 1998; Rafal, Calabresi,
eye from the center position to the target was Brennan, & Sciolto, 1989). It is thought that the
longer on the valid trials than on either the activation of pathways in the superior colliculus
invalid trials or neutral trials with no cue stim- responsible for fi xation shifts, and the inhibi-
ulus. This longer response time may be seen tion of those pathways during the spatial cueing
in Figure 1.10 for the middle and right sets of procedure, results in inhibition of return.
bars. The 20- and 26-week-old infants showed Researchers studying infants in the spatial
lengthened reaction times for the valid tri- cueing procedure have adopted this neurophysi-
als at the 750 and 1300 ms SOA in this figure. ological perspective (Hood, 1993, 1995; Johnson
Posner labeled this slowing of the response at & Tucker, 1996; Richards, 2000a, 2000b, 2001,
intermediate SOA levels “inhibition of return.” 2004b, 2005, 2007b; Richards & Hunter, 2002).
Interestingly, the inhibition of return occurs at The spatial cueing effects have three putative
late ages only for “covert orienting.” If the cue developmental phases for infants. First, the
is shown and fi xation is moved to the cue, and superior colliculus is relatively mature at birth
then back to the center pattern, “overt orient- and should support inhibition of return. One can
ing,” young infants and newborns take longer find in newborns, using the procedure in which
and are less likely to move fi xation back to the there are overt shifts of fi xations, examples of
cued location (Butcher, Kalverboer, & Gueze, inhibition of return (Simion et al., 1995; Valenza
1999; Clohessy, Posner, Rothbart, & Vecera, et al., 1994). Second, the facilitation of response
1991; Simion, Valenza, Umilta, & Barba, 1995; times at short SOAs must occur in cortical areas
Valenza, Simion, & Umilta, 1994). supporting visual processing. Only by 3 or 4.5
The effects showing covert shifts of atten- months is this area mature enough to support
tion (covert orienting, covert attention) in adult such response facilitation; thus the emergence
participants have been studied with methods to of shortened response times to valid targets
determine the brain bases of these responses. occurs by about 3 months of age (Richards,
Study methods have included fMRI, ERP, 2000a, 2000b, 2001, 2005, 2007b). Finally, the
study of pathological populations, and invasive emergence of inhibition of return following
studies in animal preparations. The response covert attention shifts by 4.5 or 6 months of age
facilitation that occurs at short SOAs is hypoth- must be due to the increasing influence of cor-
esized to be due to the enhancement of sensory tical systems on fi xation in this task. Perhaps
processing of information occurring in the these cortical systems inhibit fi xation to the
attended portion of visual space (Hillyard, Luck, peripheral stimulus during the presentation of
& Mangun, 1994; Hillyard, Mangun, Woldroff, the cue, leading to an inhibition of return of the
& Luck, 1995). This has been shown with ERP attention system to the cued area. The changes
studies that find enhanced amplitude of the in covert attention shifts found between 3 and 6
early components of the ERP elicited by the tar- months of age must therefore be due to cortical
get (Hillyard et al., 1994, 1995), and by studies changes in areas such as the parietal cortex and
20 OBJECTS AND SPACE

frontal eye fields involving saccadic planning 2000b, 2001, 2005, 2007b). The spatial cueing
and attention shift ing. This interpretation is procedure adapted for infants was used and
consistent with the general view that that there the ERP was measured at the beginning of tar-
is an increase in the first 6 months of life of get onset or immediately before saccade onset.
cortical control over eye movements that occur Figure 1.11 shows the ERP changes occurring at
during attention and increasing cortical con- target onset for the occipital electrode that was
trol over general processes involved in atten- contralateral to the target (Richards, 2000a).
tion shift ing (e.g., Hood, 1995; Richards, 2008; This contralateral occipital electrode is interest-
Richards & Hunter, 1998, 2002). ing because visual information from the eye first
I have studied the areas of the brain involved reaches the cortex in the contralateral occipital
in covert orienting effects in infants using ERPs cortex, which is just underneath the scalp near
and cortical source analysis. I briefly presented this electrode. A large positive deflection in the
the use of scalp-recorded EEG for the measure ERP occurred about 135 ms following target
of brain activity (section “How to Measure Brain onset. This potential was the same size for the
Activity in Infants”). An EEG recording is made 14-week-old infants for the valid and other con-
of the electrical activity occurring on the scalp. ditions, slightly larger for the valid condition for
The EEG is generated by neural activity occur- the 20-week-old infants, and largest for the valid
ring in neural tissue inside the head. The infant condition for the 26-week-old infants. This ERP
is placed in the experimental situation with the component occurred about the same time and
spatial cueing procedure and changes in EEG has similar morphology to the “P1” ERP com-
are measured that are linked in time to the ponent often found in adults. This enhanced
experimental presentations, i.e., ERP. The ERP P1 is often found in response to a valid target
thus is a measure of brain activity, recorded in adult participants, and has been labeled the
on the scalp, which is synchronized with the “P1 validity effect” (Hillyard et al., 1994, 1995).
experimental manipulations or the psychologi- The study suggests that areas of the brain that
cal processes occurring in the spatial cueing control this response are developing over this
procedure. The link between the scalp-recorded age range. Presumably this brain development
activity and the experimental manipulations is is related to the behavioral changes occurring in
therefore a functional neuroscience method. response facilitation or inhibition of return.
The studies I have done have tested infants at The cortical locations that generate the
14, 20, and 26 weeks of age (e.g., Richards, 2000a, P1 validity effect was further examined with

14 Weeks 20 Weeks 26 Weeks


+20 +20 +20
P1
Oc Oc Oc P1
P1
mv
mv

0
500 ms

–20 –20 –20

Figure 1.11 The ERP changes occurring at target onset in the occipital electrode contralateral to the
target side. The valid (solid), invalid (dotted), and neutral (dashed) targets produced the same ERP
response in the 14-week-old infants. The P1 ERP component was larger for the valid trials in the 20-
and 26-week-old infants. From Richards (2000a).
ATTENTION IN THE BR AIN AND EARLY INFANCY 21

cortical source analysis (Richards, 2005, 2007b). I first will discuss the change over time occur-
The section “How to Measure Brain Activity in ring in several locations. Cortical sources for
Infants” introduced cortical source analysis. In ERP recording were found in several areas of the
this analysis, electrical dipoles that can gener- cortex, including the posterior occipital cortex,
ate the current resulting in the ERP component extrastriate occipital cortex (including fusiform
may be identified. The dipoles represent the gyrus), and temporal cortex. Figure 1.12 shows the
location of the source of the cortical activity activity of these areas over time. A significant dif-
that is related to the experimental manipula- ference between the valid and the invalid/neu-
tions or psychological processes, i.e., function- tral trials is highlighted with the hatched bars.
ally localized brain sources. Activity in these The posterior occipital cortex and the temporal
dipoles changes over time so that cortical activ- cortex showed a large negative activity (brain
ity that generates the temporal characteristics of activity resulting in negative scalp recordings),
the ERP can be shown. whereas the extrastriate occipital cortical areas

10 μV Ipsilateral temporal Contralateral temporal


Target
Onset

Valid

300 ms

Invalid
Neutral Early Neg
–10 μV

Ipsilateral extrastriate occipital Contralateral extrastriate occipital


P1

Occipital-parietal

N1

Figure 1.12 The time course of activity for the dipoles located with cortical source analysis. The valid
trials (solid line) produced a significantly larger response in the posterior occipital cortex, extrastriate
occipital (including lateral occipital, lateral-medial occipital, fusiform gyrus), and temporal regions
(hatched areas). The cortical source analysis identifies only “activity” of the sources, and the direction
of the source is determined from the direction of the ERP occurring in these locations.
22 OBJECTS AND SPACE

showed the positive activity. This latter activity occurring in this area of the cortex underlie the
was similar in time course and electrical cur- P1 validity effect changes and perhaps some of
rent direction to the P1 ERP component. the behavioral changes occurring in this task.
The activity for the contralateral extrastri- An interesting comparison can be made
ate occipital areas will be examined further. between the findings that areas of the contral-
Figure 1.13 (top left figures) shows a topograph- ateral extrastriate occipital cortex are the brain
ical scalp potential map for the ERP activity sources for the P1 validity effect in infants and a
occurring in this area. The cortical sources for combined ERP/fMRI study in adults (Martinez
this brain area may be seen in the figure on the et al., 1999). The Martinez study used a spatial
top right. These sources occurred in middle cueing procedure in which participants were
and superior occipital areas (Brodmann areas instructed to direct fixation to either the right or
18, 19) and in the fusiform gyrus. These areas left side, and then targets were presented in either
are pathways that lead from the primary visual the attended or the unattended side. This proce-
area to the object identification areas in the dure was done separately in a psychophysiologi-
temporal cortex (“ventral processing stream”). cal session using ERP and in a functional MRI
Figure 1.13 also shows these activations in a session. They found the typical P1 validity effects
bar graph separately for 14- and 20-week-old in the ERP and localized the cortical sources to
infants, and separately for the valid, invalid, extrastriate occipital areas. These areas showed
and neutral conditions. The largest response enhanced blood oxygen level–dependent (BOLD)
was for the 20-week-old infants. This parallels activity in the fMRI experiment when attention
the earlier fi nding of the gradual increase in was directed to the contralateral visual field.
the P1 validity effect over this age (Figure 1.11; Alternatively, areas of the primary visual cortex
Richards, 2000a). Th is implies that changes did not show the ERP validity effect.

ECD Cluster, –26, –84, –7, mid & sup occipital g, fusiform g, (18,19)

Valid
Invalid
Neutral
Mean activations Activations for ECD cluster
20 50 to 150 ms Post-target
P1
15
μV Change

10
300 ms
5

0
14 20
Testing age (weeks)

Figure 1.13 Topographical scalp potential maps for the contralateral extrastriate occipital areas (top
left) and the cortical sources located in the brain (top right). The activity in this area was largest for the
20-week-olds in the valid cueing condition (bottom left figure).
ATTENTION IN THE BR AIN AND EARLY INFANCY 23

Figure 1.14 compares the findings from the The Martinez et al. (1999) and the Richards
Martinez et al. (1999) study to the Richards (2005) results are compared further in Figure
(2005) results. Figure 1.14 shows the fMRI areas 1.15. The average MRI from several infants in the
in the Martinez et al. study (upper left corner) range from 3 to 6 months is shown as the MRI
and the cortical sources plotted on MRI slices in Figure 1.15. Superimposed upon the MRI
from the Richards (2005) study. The green and in the cross-hatched area are the middle and
red arrows point from the fMRI areas where an superior occipital cortex (top figures) or lateral-
attention effect was observed to the comparable occipital cortex/occipital-fusiform gyrus (bot-
areas in the cortical sources of Richards, repre- tom figures). These areas were identified from
senting the contralateral extrastriate occipital the relevant anatomical areas derived from the
areas that was the basis for the infant P1 validity MNI brain (Figure 1.7). The small yellow circles
effect. These areas are very similar in both stud- represent individual source dipoles from the
ies. The yellow arrows point to the areas in the cortical sources found in Richards (2005), both
primary visual cortex in the studies of Martinez areas which show a P1 validity effect in their
et al. (1999) and Richards (2005) where no valid- activation. The larger fi lled circles are the aver-
ity effects occurred. age Talairach locations for the superior occipital

25, –86, –5,


B

0, –92, –4

Figure 1.14 Comparison of results from a study of adults with fMRI (Martinez et al., 1999) and infants
with source analysis of ERP (Richards, 2005). The upper left panels show the sources that were active
in the fMRI study. The green lines are areas in the lateral occipital cortex and fusiform gyrus that were
more active when attention was shifted to the contralateral side (fMRI) and the lateral occipital and
fusiform gyrus locations that showed a P1 validity effect (infant ERP). The red arrows point to middle
and superior occipital areas showing attention effects in both studies. The yellow areas are occipital
cortex areas representing the primary visual cortex, showing attention effects in the adult fMRI but
not in the infant ERP.
24 OBJECTS AND SPACE

Middle occipital from fMRI

Ventral fusiform from fMRI

Figure 1.15 The distribution of cortical sources in Richards (2005) which were the cortical sources
for the P1 validity effect in the ERP (yellow circles), compared with the cortical source locations found
with adult ERP for this effect (large circles). The light purple hatched areas represent the anatomical
locations of these areas translated from the MNI stereotaxic atlas (Figure 1.7) to an average of infant
MRIs from 3 to 6 months of age.

and fusiform gyrus locations identified in the neuroscience” for infant participants. Second,
Martinez et al. study as showing the P1 validity the brain changes found in the P1 validity effect
effect in the ERP. Figure 1.15 shows how similar (Figures 1.11 and 1.13) parallel those findings of
are the locations of the cortical source analysis the inhibition of return rather than those of the
found in these two studies. response facilitation (Figure 1.10). This suggests
There are two implications of the work show- that the development of the inhibition of return
ing the ERP components accompanying covert may be linked to the enhanced processing of
orienting in young infants and their cortical stimuli occurring initially in the sensory sys-
bases. The first implication is that the brain areas tems. I have argued that cortical areas involved
involved in the control of sensory processing with saccade planning (presaccadic ERP; fron-
and the effects of attention on these brain areas tal eye fields; see Richards, 2000a, 2001, 2005,
may form the basis for the changes in attention 2007b) may be more closely related to the
to peripheral stimuli in young infants. These inhibition of return effect. This may occur as
techniques may be useful in showing how brain attention-based saccade planning and fi xation
changes in these areas parallel developmental control comes to inhibit the movement of the
changes in the behavioral components of these eyes from the center to the cued location. These
tasks. The use of scalp-recorded ERP and the areas are likely in prefrontal cortex rather than
source analysis allow a “functional cognitive posterior regions.
ATTENTION IN THE BR AIN AND EARLY INFANCY 25

approach would be to first identify aspects of


BRAIN AND INFANT ATTENTION: FUTURE
brain development in individual participants
DIRECTIONS
and relate those aspects to that infant’s behav-
This chapter reviewed the hypothesis that ioral performance. For example, perhaps extent
changes in brain areas controlling attention of myelination (Figure 1.1) of the occipital areas
strongly influence the development of attention (Figures 1.13 to 1.15) in an infant would be
in infant participants. A considerable portion related to the existence of response facilitation
of the chapter examined the methodological but not inhibition of return for that infant, and
advances in imaging showing what is inside the the inhibition of return would be closely related
infant’s head and how to measure brain activ- to the size of the P1 validity effect. Alternatively,
ity in infant participants. I have focused on my myelination in frontal areas occurring in this
work using cortical source analysis of ERP in the age range may be closely related to ERP changes
spatial cueing procedure as an example of how indicating attention-directed saccade plan-
this might be done. The goal of research in this ning and the presence of inhibition of return.
area is to link measures of infant brain develop- Such analyses would show directly the rela-
ment and measures of attention development. tion between brain development and attention
There are aspects of this work that require development. An example of this kind of work
further advances. Greg Reynolds and I is that of Klingberg (2008) showing in children
(Reynolds & Richards, 2009) describe in more and adolescents a close relation between myeli-
detail the application of cortical source analysis nation characteristics and cognitive and lin-
to infant participants. One limitation we note is guistic status.
that the cortical source analysis has been based Finally, I am working on several improve-
on parameters for use with adult participants. ments to the spatial cueing procedure to make
The forward solution used impedance values for it more amenable to EEG and ERP analysis.
the matter inside the head (gray matter, white One advance I have made is to create a testing
matter, CSF, skull) that are derived from adult protocol that results in a large number of pre-
participants. We know these are incorrect— sentations. In prior studies (Richards, 2000a,
adult skin has higher impedance than infant 2000b, 2001, 2005), the infants were presented
skin because of the accumulation of dead skin with a single presentation of center stimulus,
cells in adults, and infant skulls are less dense cue, target, and reaction time, interspersed with
and thinner than adult skulls so that adult intertrial intervals with no stimulus present.
skulls have higher impedance than infants. This took from 5 to 15 s and resulted in 20 to 40
This is being addressed by taking individual trials per participant. This allowed us to obtain
participant MRIs (section “What’s Inside a numbers of trials sufficient for ERP analysis, but
Baby’s Head?”) from infants and using source not optimal for relating individual performance
analysis based on that infants head topogra- with brain areas active in the task. Currently, I
phy and infant-based values of the impedance am using a procedure that presents a variegated
of head materials (Reynolds & Richards, 2009; background with continuous presentation of a
Richards, 2006, 2007a, submitted). stimulus that is foveated, cue, target, response,
A second aspect of this work that requires and then continued presentations. Between 75
advancement is the association of specific cor- and 200 trials can be obtained with this proce-
tical changes with specific behavior changes in dure and the infants are very cooperative. This
individual infant participants. The work dis- allows for more manipulations in a single partic-
cussed in the previous section (section “Brain ipant, larger numbers of trials for ERP averages,
and Infant Attention: Spatial Orienting”) relied and examination of the relation between ERP
on average change in the group on the measures characteristics, brain source activation, and dif-
of behavior (Figure 1.10), ERP validity effect ferent behavior patterns on a trial-by-trial basis.
(Figure 1.11), and source activation and brain I have presented some results from this proce-
change (Figures 1.12 to 1.15). An individual dure (Richards, 2007b) and am continuing with
26 OBJECTS AND SPACE

other studies using this procedure. We also are Butcher, P. R., Kalverboer, A. F., & Gueze, R. H.
using this procedure to test individual par- (1999). Inhibition of return in very young
ticipants who have had anatomical MRIs. This infants: A longitudinal study. Infant Behavior
allows the correlation between the structural and Development, 22, 303–319.
characteristics of the individual infant’s brain Clements, H., Duncan, K. R., Fielding, K.,
Gowland, P.A., Johnson, I. R., & Baker, P. N.
and its performance in the task.
(2000). Infants exposed to MRI in utero have
a normal paediatric assessment at 9 months of
ACKNOWLEDGMENT age. British Journal of Radiology, 73, 190–194.
Clohessy, A. B., Posner, M. I., Rothbart, M. K., &
This research was supported by grants from the Vecera, S. P. (1991). The development of inhi-
National Institute of Child Health and Human bition of return in early infancy. Journal of
Development, R01-HD18942. Cognitive Neuroscience, 3, 345–350.
Conel, J. L. (1939). Postnatal development of
the human cerebral cortex: The cortex of the
REFERENCES newborn (Vol. 1). Cambridge, MA: Harvard
Almli, C. R., Rivkin, M. J., & McKinstry, R. C. University Press.
(2007). The NIH MRI study of normal brain Conel, J. L. (1941). Postnatal development of
development (Objective-2): Newborns, infants, the human cerebral cortex: The cortex of the
toddlers, and preschoolers. Neuromage, 35, one-month infant (Vol. 2). Cambridge, MA:
308–325. Harvard University Press.
Bachevalier, J. (2008). Non-human models of pri- Conel, J. L. (1947). Postnatal development of
mate memory development. In C.A. Nelson the human cerebral cortex: The cortex of the
& M. Luciana (Eds.), Developmental cognitive three-month infant (Vol. 3). Cambridge, MA:
neuroscience (pp. 499–508). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
MIT Press. Conel, J. L. (1951). Postnatal development of
Baker, P. N., Johnson, I. R., Harvey, p. R., Gowland, the human cerebral cortex: The cortex of the
P. A., & Mansfield, P. (1994). A three-year six-month infant (Vol. 4). Cambridge, MA:
follow-up of children imaged in utero with Harvard University Press.
echo-planar magnetic resonance. American Conel, J. L. (1955). Postnatal development of
Journal of Obstetrics and Gynecology, 170, 32–33. the human cerebral cortex: The cortex of the
Barkovich, A. J. (2005). Pediatric neuroimag- fifteen-month infant (Vol. 5). Cambridge, MA:
ing. Philadelphia, PA: Lippincott Williams & Harvard University Press.
Wilkins. Conel, J. L. (1959). Postnatal development of
Barkovich, A.J., Kjos, B.O., Jackson, D.E., & the human cerebral cortex: The cortex of the
Norman, D. (1988) Normal maturation of the twenty-four-month infant (Vol. 6). Cambridge,
neonatal and infant brain: MR imaging at 1.5 MA: Harvard University Press.
T. Radiology, 166, 173 Philadelphia, PA 180. Conel, J. L. (1963). Postnatal development of the
Battin, M., Maalouf, E.F., Counsell, S., Herlihy, A., human cerebral cortex: The cortex of the forty-
& Hall A. (1998). Physiologic stability of pre- eight-month infant (Vol. 7). Cambridge, MA:
term infants during magnetic resonance imag- Harvard University Press.
ing. Early Human Development, 52, 101–110. Conel, J. L. (1967). Postnatal development of the
Bourgeois, J. P. (1997). Synaptogenesis, heterochrony human cerebral cortex: The cortex of the sev-
and epigenesis in the mammalian neocortex. enty-two-month infant (Vol. 8). Cambridge,
Acta Paediatrica Supplement, 422, 27–33. MA: Harvard University Press.
Bronson, G. W. (1974). The postnatal growth Dehaene-Lambertz, G. (2001). Practical and
of visual capacity. Child Development, 45, ethical aspects of neuroimaging research in
873–890. infants http://www.unicog.org/main/pages.
Bronson, G. W. (1997). The growth of visual capac- php?page=InfantEthics. Accessed 2009.
ity: Evidence from infant scanning patterns. Dehaene-Lambertz, G., Dahaene, S., & Hertz-
In C. Rovee-Collier & L.P. Lipsitt, Advances Pannier, L. (2002). Functional neuroimaging
in infancy research (Vol. 11, pp. 109–141). of speech perception in infants. Science, 298,
Greenwich, CT: Ablex. 2013–2015.
ATTENTION IN THE BR AIN AND EARLY INFANCY 27

Evans, A. C. (2006). The NIH MRI study of normal potentials in the brain. Multivariate Behavioral
brain development. NeuroImage, 30, 184–202. Research, 29, 237–262.
Evans, A. C., Collins, D. L., & Milner, B. (1992). Hunter, S. K., & Richards, J. E. (2003). Peripheral
An MRI-based stereotactic atlas from 250 stimulus localization by 5- to 14-week-old
young normal subjects. Journal of the Society infants during phases of attention. Infancy, 4,
for Neuroscience Abstracts, 18, 408. 1–25.
Evans, A. C., Collins, D. L., Mills, S. L., Brown, Hunter, S. K., & Richards, J. E. Characteristics
E. D., Kelly, R. L., & Peters, T. M. (1993). 3D of eye movements to a “Sesame Street” movie
statistical neuroanatomical models from 305 from 8 to 26 weeks of age, Manuscript submit-
MRI volumes. Proceedings of the IEEE-Nuclear ted for publication.
Science Symposium and Medical Imaging Huttenlocher, P. R. (1990). Morphometric study
Conference, 1813–1817. of human cerebral cortex development.
Fox, M. & Uecker, A. (2005). Talairach daemon Neuropsychologia, 28, 517–527.
client. University of Texas Health Sciences Huttenlocher, P. R. (1994). Synaptogenesis, syn-
Center, San Antonio, TX http://ric.uthscsa.edu/ apse elimination, and neural plasticity in
projects/talairachdaemon.html. Accessed 2005. human cerebral cortex. In C.A. Nelson (Ed.),
Gilmore, J. H., Zhai, G., Wilber, K., Smith, J. K., Threats to optimal development, the Minnesota
Lin, W., & Gerig, G. (2004) 3 Tesla magnetic Symposia on Child Psychology (Vol. 27,
resonance imaging of the brain in newborns. pp. 35–54). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Neuroimaging, 132, 81–85. Iliescu, B. F., & Dannemiller, J. L. (2008).
Hillyard, S. A., Luck, S. J., & Mangun, G. R. Brain–behavior relationships in early visual
(1994). The cueing of attention to visual field development. In C. A. Nelson & M. Luciana
locations: Analysis with ERP recordings. In (Eds.), Developmental cognitive neuroscience
H. J. Heinze, T. F. Munte, & G. R. Mangun (pp. 127–146) Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
(Eds.), Cognitive electrophysiology (pp. 1–25). Johnson, M. H. (1990). Cortical maturation and the
Botson: Birkhauser. development of visual attention in early infancy.
Hillyard, S. A., Mangun, G. R., Woldroff, M. G., Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 2, 81–95.
& Luck, S. J. (1995). Neural systems mediat- Johnson, M. H. (1995). The development of visual
ing selective attention. In M. S. Gazzaniga attention: A cognitive neuroscience perspec-
(Ed.), Cognitive neurosciences (pp. 665–682). tive. In M. S. Gazzaniga (Eds.), The cognitive
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. neurosciences (pp. 735–747). Cambridge, MA:
Hood, B. M. (1993). Inhibition of return produced MIT Press.
by covert shifts of visual attention in 6-month- Johnson, M. H. (1997). Developmental cognitive
old infants. Infant Behavior and Development, neuroscience. London: Blackwell.
16, 245–254. Johnson, M. H., de Haan, M., Oliver, A., Smith,
Hood, B. M. (1995). Shifts of visual attention in W., Hatzakis, H., Tucker, L. A., et al. (2001).
the human infant: A neuroscientific approach. Recording and analyzing high-density
Advances in Infancy Research, 10, 163–216. event-related potentials with infants using
Hood, B. M., & Atkinson, J. (1991). Shift ing covert the Geodesic Sensor Net. Developmental
attention in infants. Paper presented at the Neuropsychology, 19, 295–323.
meeting of the Society for Research in Child Johnson, M. H., Gilmore, R. O., & Csibra, G.
Development, Seattle, WA, April, 1990. (1998). Toward a computational model of
Hood, B. M., Atkinson, J., & Braddick, O. J. (1998). the development of saccade planning. In
Selection-for-action and the development of J.E. Richards (Ed.), Cognitive neuroscience of
orienting and visual attention. In J. E. Richards attention: A developmental perspective (pp. 103–
(Ed.), Cognitive neuroscience of attention: 130). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Press.
A developmental perspective (pp. 219–250). Johnson, M. H., Posner, M. I., & Rothbart, M. K.
Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Press. (1991). Components of visual orienting in early
Huettel, S.A., Song, A.W., & McCarthy, G. (2004). infancy: Contingency learning, anticipatory
Functional magnetic resonance imaging. looking and disengaging. Journal of Cognitive
Sunderland, MA: Sinauer Press. Neuroscience, 3, 335–344.
Huizenga, H. M., & Molenaar, P. C. M. (1994). Johnson, M. H., Posner, M. I., & Rothbart,
Estimating and testing the sources of evoked M. K. (1994). Facilitation of saccades toward
28 OBJECTS AND SPACE

a covertly attended location in early infancy. Maurer, D., & Lewis, T. L. (1998). Overt orienting
Psychological Science, 90–93. toward peripheral stimuli: Normal develop-
Johnson, M. H., & Tucker, L. A. (1996). The devel- ment and underlying mechanisms. In J. E.
opment and temporal dynamics of spatial Richards (Ed.), Cognitive neuroscience of atten-
orienting in infants. Journal of Experimental tion: A developmental perspective (pp. 51–102).
Child Psychology, 63, 171–188. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Kangarlu, A., Burgess, R. E., & Zu, H. (1998). Mazziotta, J. C., Toga, A. W., Evans, A., Fox, P.,
Cognitive, cardiac and physiological studies in & Lancaster, J. (1995). A probablistic atlas of
ultra high field magnetic resonance imaging. the human brain: Theory and rationale for its
Magnetic Resonance Imaging, 17, 1407–1416. development. NeuroImage, 2, 89–101.
Kinney, H., Brody, B., Kloman, A., & Gilles, F. Mehler, J., Gervain, J., Endress, A., & Shukla, M.
(1988). Sequence of central nervous myelina- (2008). Mechanisms of language acquisition:
tion in human infancy: Pattern of myelination imaging and behavioral evidence. In C. A.
in autopsied infants. Journal of Neuropathology Nelson & M. Luciana (Eds.), Developmental cog-
and Experimental Neurology, 47, 217–234. nitive neuroscience (pp. 325–336). Cambridge,
Kinney, H., Karthigasan, J., Borenshteyn, N., Flax, MA: MIT Press.
J., & Kirschner, D. (1994). Myelination in the Michel, C. M., Murray, M. M., Lantz, G., Gonzalez,
developing human brain: Biochemical corre- S., Spinelli, L., & Grave de Peraltz, R. (2004).
lates. Neurochemistry Research, 19, 983–996. EEG source imaging. Clinical Neurophysiology,
Klingberg, T. (2008). Development of white mat- 115, 2195–2222.
ter as a basis for cognitive development dur- Myers, C., Duncan, K. R., Gowland, P. A.,
ing childhood. In C.A. Nelson & M. Luciana Johnson, I. R., & Baker, P. N. (1998). Failure to
(Eds.), Developmental cognitive neuroscience detect intrauterine growth restriction follow-
(pp. 237–244). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. ing in utero exposure to MRI. British Journal
Kok, R. D., de Vries, M. M., Heerschap, A., & van of Radiology, 71, 549–551.
den Berg, P. P. (2004). Absence of harmful Nelson, C.A., & Luciana, M. (2008). Developmental
effects of magnetic resonance exposure at 1.5 cognitive neuroscience. Cambridge, MA: MIT
T in utero during the third trimester of preg- Press.
nancy: A follow-up study. Magnetic Resonance NIH (1998). Pediatric study centers (PSC) for
Imaging, 22, 851–854. a MRI study of normal brain development.
Lancaster, J. L., Summerlin, J. L., Rainey, L., NIH RFP NIHNINDS-98–13, sponsored by
Freitas, C. S., & Fox, P. T. (1997), The Talairach National Institute of Neurological Disorders
Daemon, a database server for Talairach Atlas and Stroke, National Institute of Mental
Labels. Neuroimage, 5, S633. Health, National Institute of Child Health and
Lancaster, J. L., Woldorff, M. G., Parsons, L. M., Human Development.
Liotti, M., Freitas, C. S., Rainey, L., et al. (2000). Nunez, P. L. (1990). Localization of brain activ-
Automated Talairach Atlas labels for func- ity with electroencephalography. Advances in
tional brain mapping. Human Brain Mapping Neurology, 54, 39–65.
10, 120–131. O’Hare, E. D. & Sowell, E. R. (2008). Imaging
Martinez, A., Anllo-Vento, L., Sereno, M. I., developmental changes in grey and white mat-
Frank, L. R., Buxton, R. B., Dubowitz, D. J., et ter in the human brain. In C. A. Nelson & M.
al. (1999). Involvement of striate and extrastri- Luciana (Eds.), Developmental cognitive neu-
ate visual cortical areas in spatial attention. roscience (pp. 23–38). Cambridge, MA: MIT
Nature Neuroscience, 2, 364–369. Press.
Maurer, D. & Lewis, T. L. (1979). A physiological Paterson, S. J., Badridze, N., Flax, J. F., Liu, W.-C.,
explanation of infants’ early visual development. & Benasich, A. A. (2004). A method for struc-
Canadian Journal of Psychology, 33, 232–252. tural MRI scanning of non-sedated infants.
Maurer, D., & Lewis, T. L. (1991). The develop- Chicago: International Conference for Infancy
ment of peripheral vision and its physiologi- Studies.
cal underpinnings. In M. J. S. Weiss & P. R. Peña, M., Maki, A., Kovacic, D., Dehaene-
Zelazo (Eds.), Newborn attention: Biological Lambertz, G., Koizumi, H., Bouquet, F., et al.
constraints and the influence of experience (pp. (2003). Sounds and silence: An optical topog-
218–255). Norwood, NJ: Ablex. raphy study of language recognition at birth.
ATTENTION IN THE BR AIN AND EARLY INFANCY 29

Proceedings of the National Academy Sciences, Richards, J. E. (2001). Cortical indices of sac-
100, 11702–11705. cade planning following covert orienting in
Posner, M. I. (1980). Orienting of attention. 20-week-old infants. Infancy, 2, 135–157.
Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, Richards, J. E. (2002). Development of attentional
32, 3–25. systems. In M. De Haan & M. H. Johnson
Posner, M. I., & Cohen, Y. (1984). Components (Eds.), The cognitive neuroscience of develop-
of visual orienting. In H. Bouma & D. G. ment. East Sussex, UK: Psychology Press.
Bouwhis (Eds.), Attention and performance X Richards, J. E. (2003a). Attention affects the rec-
(pp. 531–556). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. ognition of briefly presented visual stimuli in
Posner, M. I., Rafal, R. D., Choate, L. S., & infants: An ERP study. Developmental Science,
Vaughan, J. (1985). Inhibition of return: Neural 6, 312–328.
basis and function. Cognitive Neuropsychology, Richards, J.E. (2003b). Cortical sources of event-
2, 211–228. related-potentials in the prosaccade and anti-
Rafal, R. D. (1998). The neurology of visual ori- saccade task. Psychophysiology. 40, 878–894.
enting: A pathological disintegration of devel- Richards, J.E. (2004a). Recovering cortical dipole
opment. In J. E. Richards (Ed.), Cognitive sources from scalp-recorded event-related-
neuroscience of attention: A developmental per- potentials using component analysis: Principal
spective (pp. 181–218). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence component analysis and independent com-
Erlbaum. ponent analysis. International Journal of
Rafal, R. D., Calabresi, P. A., Brennan, C. W., & Psychophysiology, 54, 201–220.
Sciolto, T. K. (1989). Saccade preparation inhib- Richards, J. E. (2004b). Development of covert
its reorienting to recently attended locations. orienting in young infants. In L. Itti, G. Rees,
Journal of Experimental Psychology Human & J. Tsotsos (Eds.), Neurobiology of atten-
Perception and Performance, 15, 673–685. tion (Chap. 14, pp. 82–88). London: Academic
Reynolds, G. D., Courage, M., & Richards, J. E. Press/Elsevier.
(2006). Infant visual preferences within the Richards, J. E. (2004c). The development of sus-
modified-oddball ERP paradigm. Poster pre- tained attention in infants. In M. I. Posner
sented at the International Conference on (Ed.), Cognitive neuroscience of attention
Infant Studies, Kyoto, Japan. (Chap. 25, pp. 342–356). Guilford Press.
Reynolds, G. D., & Richards, J. E. (2005). Richards, J. E. (2005). Localizing cortical sources
Familiarization, attention, and recogni- of event-related potentials in infants’ covert
tion memory in infancy: An ERP and corti- orienting. Developmental Science, 8, 255–278.
cal source localization study. Developmental Richards, J. E. (2006). Realistic cortical source
Psychology, 41, 598–615. models of ERP. Unpublished manuscript.
Reynolds, G. D., & Richards, J. E. (2007). Infant http://jerlab.psych.sc.edu./PDF%20Files/
heart rate: A developmental psychophysi- RealisticSourceModels.pdf. Accessed 2009.
ological perspective. In L. A. Schmidt & S. J. Richards, J. E. (2007a). Realistic head models for
Segalowitz (Eds.), Developmental psychophysi- cortical source analysis in infant participants.
ology (pp. 106–117). Cambridge: Cambridge Society for Research in Child Development,
University Press. Boston.
Reynolds, G. D., & Richards, J. E. (2009). Richards, J. E. (2007b). Infant sustained attention
Cortical source analysis of infant cognition, affects brain areas controlling covert orienting.
Developmental Neuropsychology,34,312–329. Society for Research in Child Development,
Richards, J. E. (2000a). Localizing the development Boston.
of covert attention in infants using scalp event- Richards, J. E. (2008). Attention in young
related-potentials. Developmental Psychology, infants: A developmental psychophysiologi-
36, 91–108. cal perspective. In C. A. Nelson & M. Luciana
Richards, J. E. (2000b). The development of covert (Eds.), Developmental cognitive neuroscience
attention to peripheral targets and its relation (pp. 479–497) Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
to attention to central visual stimuli. Paper Richards, J. E.(2009) Cortical sources of ERP in
presented at the International Conference the prosaccade and antisaccade task using real-
for Infancy Studies, Brighton, England, July istic source models based on individual MRIs.
2000. Manuscript submitted for publication.
30 OBJECTS AND SPACE

Richards, J. E., & Casey, B. J. (1992). Development M. N. (Eds.), Event-related brain research
of sustained visual attention in the human (pp. 24–37). Amsterdam: Elsevier Science.
infant. In B. A. Campbell, H. Hayne, R. Shankle, W. R., Romney, A. K., Landing, B. H., &
Richardson (Eds.), Attention and information Hara, J. (1998). Developmental patterns in the
processing in infants and adults: Perspectives cytoarchitecture of the human cerebral cortex
from human and animal research (pp. 30–60). from birth to 6 years examined by correspon-
Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. dence analysis. Proceedings of the National
Richards, J. E., & Holley, F. B. (1999) Infant atten- Academy of Sciences, 95, 4023–4028.
tion and the development of smooth pur- Simion, F., Valenza, E., Umilta, C., & Barba, B.
suit tracking. Developmental Psychology, 35, D. (1995). Inhibition of return in newborns is
856–867. temporo-nasal asymmetrical. Infant Behavior
Richards, J. E., & Hunter, S. K. (1997). Peripheral and Development, 18, 189–194.
stimulus localization by infants with eye and Stokowski, L. A. (2005). Ensuring safety for
head movements during visual attention. infants undergoing magnetic resonance imag-
Vision Research, 37, 3021–3035. ing. Advances in Neonatal Care, 5, 14–27.
Richards, J. E. & Hunter, S. K. (1998). Attention Sury, J., Harker, H., Begent, J., & Chong, W. K.
and eye movement in young infants: Neural (2005) The management of infants and chil-
control and development. In J. E. Richards dren for painless imaging. Clinical Radiology,
(Ed.), Cognitive neuroscience of attention: 60, 731–741.
A developmental perspective (pp. 131–162). Swick, D., Kutas, M., & Neville, H. J. (1994).
Mahway, NJ: Erlbaum. Localizing the neural generators of event-
Richards, J. E., & Hunter, S. K. (2002). Testing related brain potentials. In A. Kertesz (Ed.),
neural models of the development of infant Localization and neuroimaging in neuropsy-
visual attention. Developmental Psychobiology, chology. Foundations of neuropsychology (pp.
40, 226–236. 73–121). San Diego: Academic Press.
Rivkin, M. J. (1998). Developmental neuroimag- Taber, K. H., Hayman, L. A., Northrup, S. R., &
ing of children using magnetic resonance tech- Maturi, L. (1998). Vital sign changes dur-
niques. Mental Retardation and Developmental ing infant magnetic resonance examinations.
Disabilities Research Reviews, 6, 68–80. Journal of Magnetic Resonance Imaging, 8,
Sajja, B. R., & Narayana, P. A. (2008). Magnetic 1252–1256.
resonance spectroscopy of developing Talairach, J., & Tournoux, P. (1988). Co-planar ste-
brain. In C.A. Nelson & M. Luciana (Eds.), reotaxic atals of the human brain. New York:
Developmental cognitive neuroscience (pp. 337– Thieme Medical Publishers.
350). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Thomas, K. M., & Tseng, A. (2008). Functional
Sampaio, R. C., & Truwit, C. L. (2001). Myelination MRI methods in developmental cognitive neu-
in the developing human brain. In C. A. Nelson roscience. In C.A. Nelson & M. Luciana (Eds.),
& M. Luciana (Eds.), Developmental cogni- Developmental cognitive neuroscience (pp. 311–
tive neuroscience (pp. 35–44) Cambridge, MA: 324). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
MIT Press. Tucker, D. M. (1993). Spatial sampling of
Schenck, J. F. (2000). Safety of strong, static mag- head electrical fields: the geodesic sensor
netic fields. Journal of Magnetic Resonance net. Electroencephalography and Clinical
Imaging, 12, 2–19. Neurophysiology, 87, 154–163.
Scherg, M. (1990). Fundamentals of dipole source Tucker, D. M., Liotti, M., Potts, G. F., Russell,
potential analysis. In F. Grandori, M. Hoke, & G. S., & Posner, M. I. (1994). Spatiotemporal
G. L. Romani (Eds.), Auditory evoked magnetic analysis of brain electrical fields. Human Brain
fields and potentials (pp. 40–69). Basel: Karger. Mapping, 1, 134–152.
Scherg, M. (1992). Functional imaging and local- U. S. Food and Drug Administration (2003).
ization of electromagnetic brain activity. Brain Criteria for significant risk investigations of
Topography, 5, 103–111. magnetic resonance diagnostic devices. http://
Scherg, M., & Picton, T. W. (1991). Separation and w w w.fda.gov/cdrh/ode/guidance/793.pdf.
identification of event-related potential com- Accessed 2009.
ponents by brain electrical source analysis. U.S. Food and Drug Administration (2006).
In Brunia, C. H. M., Mulder, G., & Verbaten, Information Sheet Guidance For IRBs, Clinical
ATTENTION IN THE BR AIN AND EARLY INFANCY 31

Investigators, and Sponsors Significant Risk M. Luciana (Eds.), Developmental cognitive


and Nonsignificant Risk Medical Device neuroscience (pp. 301–310). Cambridge, MA:
Studies. http://www.fda.gov/oc/ohrt/irbs/devr- MIT Press.
isk.pdf. Accessed 2009. Yakolev, P. I., & Lecours, A. R. (1967). The
Valenza, E., Simion, F., & Umilta, C. (1994). myelogenetic cycles of regional maturation of
Inhibition of return in newborn infants. Infant the brain. In A. Mankowski (Ed.), Regional
Behavior and Development, 17, 293–302. development of the brain in early life (pp. 3–69).
Wozniak, J.R., Mueller, B.A., & Lim, K.O. (2009). Philadelphia: Davis.
Diff usion tensor imaging. In C.A. Nelson &
CHAP TER 2
All Together Now: Learning through
Multiple Sources

Natasha Kirkham

The exciting promise of developmental In this chapter, I shall discuss the impor-
psychology is that it can produce coherent tance and the usefulness of such cross-modal
explanations of development instead of merely integration in learning about basic structure,
describing behavior. It is, therefore, our business suggesting that it provides the foundations for
as developmental psychologists to find mecha- more complex knowledge, and outline a theory
nistic explanations, which can be traced back to of multiple cue integration. Data from a variety
their origins, as opposed to delineating behavior of paradigms will show the effect that richer,
at only one time slice. We must account for how more numerous, and cross-modal cues have on
infants and children build complex representa- infants’ ability to learn visual sequences and
tions and acquire sophisticated knowledge, and events. As the infant develops, her tolerance for
then how they go on to use that knowledge to coherence between these cues changes, as she is
define and modulate their behavior. And we able to acquire more sophisticated representa-
must show how all this occurs in real time. This tions for a narrower set of cues. It may be that
is a daunting task, which requires analyzing the rich scenery, with the many cues available that
cognitive system from the bottom up, as learn- highlight environmental structure, is processed
ing occurs over time. more efficiently by infants than a scene contain-
Such a study of learning is, in part, a study of ing sparser features. If this is so, then emergent
perception, since the building blocks of complex sensitivities to probabilistic spatiotemporal
knowledge must presumably be extracted from information might require more contextual
the world. Fortunately for the infant, the world support in order to glean structure from the
is rich with perceptual redundancies that help environment.
guide attention (e.g., Bahrick & Lickliter, 2000; In order for humans to effectively use proba-
Lewkowicz, 2000). The same information, such bilistic information (i.e., to draw conclusions
as the location of an event or the number of an about the likelihood of potential events), they
event’s occurrences, can be conveyed simulta- must be sensitive to the relative frequencies of
neously in visual, auditory, and tactile cues: We various events. Indeed, there is much evidence
hear the voice of our partner coming from the to suggest that humans are very sensitive to
direction of our front door, we see his face come frequencies of occurrence (and co-occurrence;
through the doorway, and we reach out to greet Jonides & Jones, 1992; Jonides & Naveh-
him. The ability to integrate perceptual infor- Benjamin, 1987). Some examples include the
mation across different modalities (as well as ability to accurately judge the relative frequencies
within them) is a key element in learning about of encounters with other people (e.g., Saegert,
events and objects. Swap, & Zajonc, 1972), the ability to judge the

32
LEARNING THROUGH MULTIPLE SOURCES 33

frequency of lethal events (e.g., Lichenstein, information across different senses (e.g., Ernst,
Slovic, Fischoff, Layman, & Combs, 1978), and Banks, & Bülthoff, 2000). Research on depth
in the language domain, judgments of the fre- perception has shown the benefit of differen-
quency of words (e.g., Shapiro, 1969), syllables tial visual cues such as binocular disparity
(e.g., Rubin, 1974), letters (e.g., Attneave, 1953), (e.g., Mayhew & Frisby, 1980), texture gradients
and position of letters (e.g., Sedmeier, Hertwig, (e.g., Todd & Akerstrom, 1987), and motion
& Gigerenzer, 1998). Zajonc (1968) showed that (e.g., Sperling, Landy, Dosher, & Perkins, 1989).
this sensitivity to frequency can implicitly bias Object motion, binocular disparity, occlusion
judgments of liking, the “mere exposure” effect and texture gradients, to name a few, are inte-
that has been used widely by experimental psy- grated to produce coherent visual percepts of
chologists across numerous fields. objects, surface layout, and scenes (e.g., Bruno &
Infants are sensitive not just to frequency Cutting, 1988; Mayhew & Frisby, 1980; Sperling
of events, but also their probabilistic structure. et al., 1989; Todd & Akerstrom, 1987). In the
As I shall discuss below, it has become evident adult vision literature, theories of multiple cue
that infants and young children have access to integration, or weighted sum models, have been
a powerful domain-general learning device. In offered as explanations for how observers com-
laboratory experiments they can quickly learn bine stimulus property cues (e.g., Kinchla, 1977;
statistically defined (or probabilistic) patterns Landy et al., 1995; Massaro, 1999).
in both auditory and visual domains (Fiser & In the cognitive domain too, multiple cues
Aslin, 2003; Kirkham, Slemmer, & Johnson, are often integrated in complex decision mak-
2002; Saff ran, Aslin, & Newport, 1996). Young ing, such as medical diagnosis (Brehmer &
children, as well, are quickly capable of under- Qvarnstrom, 1976). A doctor uses all the pieces
standing probabilistic information implicitly of information available to her, not just one.
(Meulemans, Van der Linden, & Perruchet, The information will be weighted differentially
1998) or with explicit feedback (Kirkham depending on the context and the nature of
& Shohamy, 2007). I posit that this learn- the information, but each bit will be used. This
ing device, coupled with a rich and accessible instance is an example of a complex cognitive
environment, provides the building blocks for problem, but multiple cue use is evident in
mature knowledge. the simplest, most mundane situations. When
you decide to go to a restaurant for dinner, for
example, there are a great many bits of infor-
MULTIPLE CUES
mation that will help produce a decision of the
What happens when there are multiple probabi- specific restaurant: What kind of food do you
listic information sources available? From basic want to eat? Who else is going, and what food
vision to language acquisition, multiple percep- do they want to eat? Who is paying? Are either
tual cues have been cited as providing important time spent at or distance from the restaurant
information to the system. How these cues are issues for anyone attending the dinner? No one
weighted, and what parameters determine dif- bit will be the conclusive bit, but a combination
ferential weighting, has been of great interest in of all of them will get you to the correct deci-
the perception literature. Weighted sum models sion. And these cue weightings are done in a
of perception have been proffered as explana- matter of minutes, or even seconds.
tions for how adults perform many different So, given that multiple sources of informa-
tasks, including detecting an auditory signal tion are available to solve problems in both per-
with two frequency components that activate ception and cognition, and that these sources
different auditory channels (e.g., Green, 1958), tend to be probabilistic in nature, reliance on
combining redundant stimulus properties in multiple cues should therefore produce greater
complex figures (e.g., Kinchla, 1977), combin- success than reliance on any one individual cue.
ing multiple depth cues (e.g., Landy, Maloney, Furthermore, since many problem domains
Johnston, & Young, 1995), and combining are characterized by probabilistic solutions,
34 OBJECTS AND SPACE

sensitivity to variables such as frequency and extent that they expect the sound to move with
correlation should be a domain-general ability, the associated object (Morrongiello, Fenwick, &
and perhaps a fundamental characteristic of the Chance, 1998). Lewkowicz and Turkewitz (1980)
developing mind. In order for infants to make showed that very young infants (3 weeks of age)
use of this information available in the envi- bind sound and vision together by attending to
ronment, she must be sensitive to probabilistic the intensity of the stimuli. By 4 months of age,
patterns. This sensitivity then creates the foun- infants can not only perceive the bimodal nature
dation upon which higher-order knowledge is of objects (Spelke, 1979, 1981), but they can also
based. perceive speech bimodally (Kuhl and Meltzoff,
1982; Rosenblum, Schmuckler, & Johnson,
1997). Infants of 5 months, when habituated
INFANTSENSITIVITY TO MULTIMODAL
to a bimodal presentation of rhythm (e.g., an
REGULARITIES
audiovisual movie of a hammer tapping out a
Infants show great sensitivity to multimodal rhythm), dishabituated to a unimodal presenta-
regularities. Similar to adults, infants use mul- tion of a novel rhythm (e.g., just the visual of
tiple cues to organize their visual perception: a hammer tapping, without the sound; Bahrick
For example, when making decisions about an & Lickliter, 2000). By 5–7 months, infants can
occluded object, infants may exploit such cues match faces with voices based on the age, gen-
as edge alignment, synchronous motion, and der, and affective expression of the speaker
depth to support perception of unity (Johnson, (Bahrick, Netto, & Hernandez-Reif, 1998).
1997; Smith, Johnson, & Spelke, 2003). In addi-
tion, investigations of language acquisition have
MULTIPLE CUE INTEGRATION THEORY
led Christiansen and colleagues (Christiansen,
Allen, & Seidenberg, 1998; Christiansen & Dale, It seems clear from the evidence presented in the
2001; Christiansen & Monaghan, 2006; see also earlier section that infant learning in the natu-
the chapter in this volume by Christiansen, ral environment would exploit multiple cues
Dale, & Reali) to put forward a multiple cue across different modalities. Certainly, infants’
hypothesis. They propose that the mecha- sensitivity to cross-modal information stands in
nism underlying language acquisition has the contrast to the sparse, unimodal presentations
capacity to extract and store various statistical of many laboratory experiments. If laboratory
properties of language, and integrate different studies do not fully exploit the cross-modal sen-
sources of information. They go on to suggest sitivity of infants, then perhaps they risk under-
that it might be the conjunctions of these cues estimating the full capacity of their learning
that provide evidence about aspects of linguistic abilities. For example, Bahrick and Lickliter and
structure that is not available from any single colleagues have presented beautiful evidence
source of information. that “intersensory redundancy,” the overlap of
A great deal of our perceptual understand- information provided by amodal stimuli, drives
ing (as well as a great many of our responses selective attention (e.g., Bahrick & Lickliter,
to the environment) requires correctly corre- 2000; Bahrick, Lickliter, & Flom, 2004). Thus, it
lating events across modalities. Gibson (1969) seems to follow nicely that intersensory redun-
suggested that the responsiveness to invari- dancy should also drive basic perceptual learn-
ant intersensory relations is a necessary part ing. Broadly speaking, this theory predicts that
of the development of perception and learn- there are three factors that will affect an infant’s
ing. Indeed, during the first 6 months of life, ability to learn a particular sequence or set of
infants develop many intersensory capacities, events: (1) the availability of multiple cues, (2)
which allow them to perceive correlations the coherence of the cues presented, and (3) the
across modalities (Lewkowicz, 2000; see also age of the infant. Thus, learning of basic visu-
Richardson & Kirkham, 2004). Newborns bind a ospatial patterns or events should be facilitated
visual stimulus with an auditory stimulus to the if the same information is present in multiple
LEARNING THROUGH MULTIPLE SOURCES 35

cues within or across modalities. For example, as to the joint and conditional probabilities of
infants will be better able to learn the statisti- successive shape pairs.
cal structure of a sequence of events when that Are infants also sensitive to the statisti-
pattern is conveyed by the shape, color, posi- cal structure of events? Research concerned
tion, and sound of the events, rather than one of with the development of sequence learning has
those cues alone. Cues can interfere with learn- revealed a capacity to pick up temporal patterns
ing when they do not coherently co-occur. So if under many conditions. Saff ran, Aslin, and col-
particular sounds are associated with particular leagues found that 8-month-old infants parse a
locations, but the visual features that appear in stream of auditory stimuli based solely on the
that location are random or constant, learning transitional probabilities within and between
will suffer. At younger ages, infants will require the syllables (Aslin, Saff ran, & Newport, 1998;
a higher number of cues and a higher degree of Saff ran et al., 1996; see also Gomez’s and
coherence between them. At later ages, infants Saff ran’s chapters in this book for more dis-
will be able to learn statistical structure from cussion of infant auditory sequence learning).
a smaller set of cues and be able to tolerate a Gomez and Gerken (1999) exposed 12-month-
degree of incoherence between multiple cues. olds to a subset of strings produced by one of
two artificial grammars and then tested the
infants on their ability to discriminate new
SEQUENCE LEARNING
strings from both the familiar and the unfa-
Both adults and infants are sensitive to the miliar grammar. Infants preferred to listen to
statistical structure of perceptual events. Adults new strings from their training set relative to
are extremely competent at exploiting complex strings from the novel grammar. These gram-
spatiotemporal sequences in order to guide mars differed only in terms of the ordering of
behavior (Chun & Jiang, 1998; Howard, Mutter, word pairs: Individual words in the two sets,
& Howard, 1993). In serial reaction time stud- and the starting and ending words, were always
ies, for example, adult observers view a single the same. The only cues to provide recognition,
repetitive stimulus presented sequentially at therefore, were contained in word order, imply-
different locations and respond to each position ing that the infants encoded the temporal pat-
by pressing a corresponding key (e.g., Nissen terns of word co-occurrences. Infants’ ability
& Bullemer, 1987). Stimulus locations follow a to extract regularities in sequential input does
particular spatial and temporal pattern that a not seem to be a language-specific mechanism,
participant may be unable to describe explicitly, but exists broadly across audition. Infants parse
yet reaction times typically decrease reliably auditory streams based on statistical probabili-
across trials (Cohen, Ivry, & Keele, 1990; Curran ties even when the stimuli are tones (Saff ran,
& Keele, 1993; Nissen & Bullemer, 1987). There Johnson, Aslin, & Newport, 1999), and at least
is evidence that such learning is independent one species of nonhuman primates, cotton-
of the specific motor response: Observation top tamarins (which never develop humanlike
of a sequential pattern can also lead to knowl- language skills), learns statistically structured
edge of serial order (Howard et al., 1993), and sounds (Hauser, Newport, & Aslin, 2001).
there appears to be no special benefit to learn- There is evidence from other paradigms,
ing imparted by manual responses, relative to however, that infants show some sensitivity to
oculomotor responses (Heyes & Foster, 2002). visual spatial relations among repetitive events
Perception of scenes can be guided by statisti- under certain conditions. For example, young
cal information (Chun, 2000). Fiser and Aslin infants learn simple (two-location), predictable
(2001, 2002) presented adults with probabilisti- spatial sequences in the visual expectation par-
cally structured sequences of single shapes and adigm, which uses oculomotor anticipation as
shape arrays and found that observers were sen- the index of learning (Haith, 1993). Infants also
sitive to the statistical correlations among mul- show sensitivity to spatial contingency in tem-
tipart objects presented simultaneously, as well poral sequences: Wentworth, Haith, and Hood
36 OBJECTS AND SPACE

(2002) presented 3-month-old infants with a p = 1.0


spatiotemporal sequence in which a stimulus
appeared on the left, in the center, or on the
right of a computer monitor. Infants viewed p = 1.0
either a fi xed or a random pattern of locations,
and in some cases, there was a contingent rela- p = 1.0
tion between the identity of the central stimulus
and the location of the next peripheral picture. p = .33
The fi xed sequence of three locations resulted
in more eye movement anticipations, and there
were more anticipatory saccades to the cor- p = .33 Time
rect location when there was a contingent rela-
tion between central and peripheral events. In
displays of greater complexity than the simple
two- and three-location events described previ-
Figure 2.1. Schematic of Kirkham et al. (2002):
ously, infants are still responsive to statistical
An example of the visual sequence shown to the
structure. Upon exposure to a sequence of static
infants (NB. In the actual experiment, the shapes
multielement scenes, for example, 9-month- were different colors and not black-and-white).
olds appeared to acquire the underlying sta-
tistical structure of the scene layout, attending
longer following habituation to isolated ele- the first shape in a pair reliably predicted the sec-
ment pairs that had co-occurred with a higher ond, but the next shape to appear could be any
frequency within the familiar scenes (Fiser & of the first members of a pair. Following habitu-
Aslin, 2003). ation, infants viewed six test displays alternating
between familiar sequences, composed of the
same three pairs of shapes, and novel sequences,
VISUALSTATISTICAL LEARNING: COLOR
produced by randomly ordering the same
AND SHAPE
shapes. The only difference between familiar
There is clear and compelling evidence that and novel sequences was the transitional prob-
infants are sensitive to patterns of events. Much abilities between the shapes. We hypothesized
of the work discussed has focused on the types that visual statistical learning would be evinced
of abstract statistical structure that infants are by a consistent preference for the random post-
capable (and not capable) of learning at specific habituation sequence (i.e., a novelty preference).
ages. This leaves open the question of the effect Our prediction was supported: Infants in all
of the range and type of stimuli that infants three age-groups exhibited a reliable preference
are exposed to in such learning paradigms. For for the random (novel) sequence. Indeed, there
example, in earlier work, my colleagues and were no statistically significant age differences
I tested the hypothesis that infants’ ability to in the strength of novelty preferences, indicating
learn the statistical structure of event sequences that statistical learning under these conditions is
was not limited to the auditory domain. available even to very young infants.
We examined visual statistical learning In the Kirkham et al. (2002) study, sequence
in infants using a habituation/dishabituation information was contained in two cues, shape
technique (Kirkham et al., 2002). Two-, 5-, and and color. Although the information conveyed
8-month-olds were familiarized with a series of by the cues was completely redundant, a multiple
six discrete colored shapes that loomed from the cue integration theory would suggest that such
center of a display monitor. Presentation order a redundancy supports learning. In the first test
was defined in part by statistical regularities: The of a multiple cue integration theory, this predic-
shapes were organized into pairs, and the pairs tion was supported by several experiments in
were ordered randomly (see Figure 2.1). That is, which infants of ages 5 and 8 months failed to
LEARNING THROUGH MULTIPLE SOURCES 37

learn the same sequences when they consisted A


of either monochrome looming shapes or dif-
ferent colors of the same shape (Kirkham &
A1 A2 B2
Wagner, in preparation).

SPATIOTEMPORAL STATISTICAL LEARNING:


COLOR, SHAPE, AND LOCATION B1 C2 C1

The world will only seem coherent if one can pro-


cess an object’s spatial location and understand
what its present location might predict about B
future events. Acquisition of this type of knowl-
edge is essential for motion perception and for A1 A2 B2
the production of action sequences, because one
has to learn not only which actions are appro-
priate, but also where and when they should be
performed. In recognition of the importance B1 C2 C1
of location information, Kirkham, Slemmer,
Richardson, and Johnson (2007) adapted the
Kirkham et al. (2002) visual statistical learning Figure 2.2 (A) Experiment 1 in Kirkham et al.
paradigm to examine spatiotemporal statistical (2007): An example of the location statistics.
learning. Multiple cue integration theory was (B) Experiment 2 in Kirkham et al. (2007): An
tested by isolating location from visual feature example of the location statistics
cues and examining learning with the support
of different cue combinations across the first
year of life. Could infants extract purely spa- the 11-month-olds had. Experiment 3 suggested
tiotemporal correlations, and if so, at what age that perhaps 5-month-olds were simply not
and under what conditions? able to encode spatiotemporal information suf-
Infants were familiarized to stimuli appear- ficiently, since they showed renewed interest in
ing in one of six different locations on a grid and the novel sequence when the sequence of loca-
then were shown the familiar spatial pattern tions but not the sequence of color/shape pair-
alternating with a novel spatial sequence. These ings was held constant in the test trials.
spatial patterns mirrored the structure of the There is an alternative explanation for
randomized shape pairs used by Kirkham et al. 8-month-olds’ performance in Experiment 2. It
(2002). In Experiment 1, a red circle appeared is possible that the infants were not sensitive to
in a statistically defined spatial pattern, and a probabilistic pattern of location changes: They
11-month-olds, but not 8-month-olds, exhibited merely picked up on individual shape–location
significantly greater interest in the novel spatial pairings and showed a novelty preference when
sequence (Figure 2.2A). In Experiment 2, six those pairings were violated. To rule out this
different color/shape stimuli were presented explanation, Experiment 4 used an “on-line
(Figure 2.2B). There was a statistical structure to learning” paradigm, in which 8-month-olds’ eye
both the features and the locations of the stimuli, movements were recorded as they watched the
but crucially, only the spatial sequence was vio- habituation sequence employed in Experiment
lated during the test phase. Eight-month-olds, 2. Saccadic latencies to the newly appearing
but not 5-month-olds, showed a novelty prefer- shapes were recorded as a measure of sequence
ence for an altered spatial sequence. Although learning. After exposure to the sequence, laten-
they provided only redundant information, cies to the first shape in a pair were longer on
these multiple visual cues allowed 8-month- average than latencies to the second shape in a
olds to learn the spatiotemporal sequence as pair. This is because the second shape in a pair
38 OBJECTS AND SPACE

could be predicted once the first had appeared. events, track the locations as they move, and
If, as the alternative explanation holds, the later, look back to the correct location when
8-month-olds in Experiment 2 only learnt asso- a particular event is relevant (Richardson &
ciations between a particular shape and a partic- Kirkham, 2004). This behavior has been shown
ular location, they would have no information in adult subjects. For example, in Experiment
about how one location can predict the next and 1 of Richardson and Kirkham (2004), adult
should not show any saccade latency decrease participants looked at a spinning cross that
in this experiment. In contrast, the decrease in appeared in two squares ports on a computer
anticipatory saccades that was found revealed screen. While the cross span, adults heard a
the role multiple cue integration can play in piece of factual information. After two facts, the
generating expectations about the world. ports moved around the screen. Participants
These four experiments present evidence then answered a question relating to one of
concerning a fundamental cognitive skill in the facts. While answering, they looked at the
infancy—the ability to learn probabilistic event empty port that had previously been associated
sequences across space and time. Evidence was with the fact (see also, Richardson & Spivey,
also obtained of an important developmental 2000). We hypothesized that a propensity for
limitation in learning: Only the oldest infants dynamic spatial indexing is not just a feature of
observed (11-month-olds) responded solely on the mature adult visual system, but emerges by
the basis of location statistics, showing a post- 6 months along with some of the first uses of
habituation novelty preference to a display adult-like spatial reference frames. At that age,
in which the positions of stimulus elements infants are still learning to orientate their atten-
were randomly placed. The youngest infants tion properly (Colombo, 2001) and are only
(5-month-olds), in contrast, appeared largely beginning to represent spatial locations egocen-
insensitive to location statistics, although they trically (Gilmore & Johnson, 1997).
were able to detect probabilistic sequences based
on a combination of color and shape. Infants at Consistent Visual Cues
an intermediate age (8 months) provided evi-
In Experiment 2 (Richardson & Kirkham,
dence of learning location statistics only when
2004), infants saw movies of two brightly col-
color and shape contributed additional (redun-
ored toys that moved in time to two different
dant) cues for the spatiotemporal sequence.
sounds (see Figure 2.3). The toys appeared in
This suggests that temporal order statistics that
square ports on a computer screen. Test phases
involve spatial relations may become available
consisted of the two empty ports and the audi-
to infants over the course of the first year after
tory element of one of the movies. We found that
birth and that integrating multiple cues can
infants looked longer at the empty port that had
bolster such learning.
previously been associated with the toy, even
when the ports had moved round the screen
SPATIALINDEXING: COLOR, SHAPE, in between the presentation and test phases
LOCATION, AND SOUND (Experiment 3). We argued that the ability to
At a certain stage of their development, infants spatially index under these challenging circum-
can learn spatiotemporal sequences by exploit- stances was supported by the rich, multimodal
ing redundant information of multiple cues. The nature of the events. So, how does the relative
cues used in Kirkham et al. (2007), however, coherence of these three types of cues (visual
were all visual. Infants do not live in a silent features, location, and sound) affect dynamic
world, as a trip to any toy store will show. Do the spatial indexing?
sounds of particular objects act as redundant,
Uninformative Visual Cues
cross-modal cues that can help infants to learn?
Dynamic spatial indexing is defined as the The multiple cue integration theory pre-
ability to encode the locations of multimodal dicts that even though the visual features
LEARNING THROUGH MULTIPLE SOURCES 39

Boing..! Boing..!
Boing..!

Brring!!!
Brring!!!
Brring!!!
2
×

Boing..! Boing..!
3
=
6

Boing..!
fa
m
ila
r is
at
io
n
tra
ils

2
×
te
s
tt
r ia
ls

Figure 2.3. An example of what was presented to infants in Experiment 2 of Richardson and Kirkham
(2004) with crosshair showing fi xation. Note: In Experiment 3, the location of the ports during the
familiarization phase was at the top and bottom of the screen; during test the empty ports translated
to the horizontal positions.

provide information that is redundant for spatial seemed to be reliably associated with two
indexing, their presence will support the infants’ locations. In every case, on test trials, only the
behavior. In contrast, it has been argued that auditory element was presented, and infants’
infants below 9 months of age have an “object looking times to empty frames were measured.
concept” governed by spatial–temporal conti- Infants of 6 and 10 months were run in the
nuity and that changes in visual features can go three conditions. Three-month-olds were run
unnoticed (e.g., Xu & Carey, 1996). This account only in the original condition. The original
predicts that visual features would be irrelevant dynamic spatial indexing finding (informa-
to dynamic spatial indexing. tive cue) was replicated in all three age groups;
Kirkham, Richardson, Johnson, and Wu (in even the 3-month-olds performed well. Infants
preparation) tested these predictions in a series looked longer at the empty port previously asso-
of experiments that modified Richardson and ciated with the toy after the ports had moved
Kirkham’s (2004) paradigm (see Figure 2.3). In around the screen. The behavior is different,
the inconstant visual cues condition, the infants however, in the inconstant and constant visual
saw a different object on each presentation trial. cues conditions. Six-month-old infants failed to
In the constant visual cues condition, infants look significantly longer at either port in both the
saw the same object on every presentation trial. inconstant and constant visual cues conditions.
In other words, the same auditory stimulus and Changing the visual features of the multimodal
the same synchronized motion were always events on each presentation, or keeping them
associated with a certain location, but the visual the same, reduced the infants’ ability to dis-
features either changed on every trial (incon- criminate locations during the test trial. When
stant cues) or stayed the same (constant cues). we presented 10-month-old infants with the
To replicate the original finding, an informative same stimuli, however, they successfully looked
cue condition was included where two objects at the critical location in both conditions. As
40 OBJECTS AND SPACE

predicted by a multiple cue integration theory, understanding of the object’s trajectory is


without the support of reliable and informative determined by number of anticipatory saccades
(though still redundant) multiple cues, younger directed toward the emerging ball. The typical
infants find it harder to learn about their world. results are that 4-month-olds appear to con-
Older infants, however, are capable of learning strue partly occluded trajectory events in terms
these associations from a narrower set of reli- of disconnected trajectories on either side of the
able cues. occluder (suggesting that they are not expecting
its reemergence), whereas by 6 months of age,
infants are beginning to perceive the continuity
OBJECTTRAJECTORY: OBJECTS, MOTION,
of the trajectory behind the occluder (Johnson
AND SOUND
et al., 2003). This skill is not on a fi xed path,
So far in this chapter, I have discussed the however: Johnson, Amso, and Slemmer (2003)
usefulness of multiple cues on various forms showed that 4-month-old infants, who are right
of pattern detection. I would like to intro- at the beginning of a transition toward success
duce the idea that multiple cues are useful in at perceptual completion in the ball-and-box
supporting more complex representations. display, benefit greatly from “training.” When
This can be shown in investigations of young exposed to an unoccluded trajectory prior to
infants’ understanding of objects as enduring viewing an occluded trajectory, 4-month-olds
across space and time, regardless of tempo- showed a reliable increase in anticipatory sac-
rary occlusion. In most experimental settings, cades (relative to a control group of untrained
this experiment is unimodal: Infants watch a 4-month-olds). This visual experience with the
ball move across a screen, disappearing briefly object’s complete trajectory facilitated a repre-
behind a rectangular occluder. Accompanying sentation of the persistent motion of the object
sound tends to be stationary, coming at the even when interrupted by occlusion. Given that
infant from both sides of the screen that is outside of the laboratory infants have more than
used to keep the infants focused. Successful just visual experience of moving objects, perhaps

Figure 2.4. An example of one of the trajectories presented to the babies in Kirkham, Johnson, and
Wagner (in preparation).
LEARNING THROUGH MULTIPLE SOURCES 41

the addition of another source of information cross-modal perception perspectives and ascer-
would help. Kirkham, Johnson, and Wagner (in tain the capabilities of infants’ hypothesized
preparation) incorporated a continuous moving statistical learning mechanism.
sound into the ball-and-box paradigm, such that
the sound traveled with the object from one side
of the occluder to the other side (see Figure 2.4). ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
Results from this study showed that 4-month- The research discussed in this chapter was sup-
olds integrate multiple auditory and visual cues ported, in part, by Grant RO3 HD050613–01 from
to infer a continuous trajectory. Control con- the National Institute of Health. I would like to
ditions examining whether static lateralized thank all the parents and children who came to
sounds would help or whether a sound moving our laboratory and participated in our research.
in the opposite direction of the object would I would also like to thank Daniel Richardson for
produce anticipations in the opposite direction helpful comments on this chapter.
support the initial finding. Four-month-olds
show more anticipations only when the sound REFERENCES
travels with the object. Indeed, when given these
multiple, cross-modal cues, 4-month-old infants Aslin, R. N., Saff ran, J. R., & Newport, E. L. (1998).
appear to be anticipating trajectories as well as Computation of conditional probability sta-
6-month-olds in the unimodal condition. tistics by 8-month-old infants. Psychological
Science, 9, 321–324.
Attneave, F. (1953). Psychological probability as a
CONCLUSION function of experienced frequency. Journal of
Experimental Psychology, 46, 81–86.
In this chapter, I have tried to describe a the- Bahrick, L. E., & Lickliter, R. (2000). Intersensory
ory of multiple cue integration, supporting the redundancy guides attentional selectivity and
acquisition of complex knowledge. As we now perceptual learning in infancy. Developmental
know, the “great blooming, buzzing confusion” Psychology, 36, 190–201.
(James, 1890, p. 462) of the perceptual world Bahrick, L. E., Lickliter, R., & Flom, R. (2004).
actually holds a wealth of information for an Intersensory redundancy guides the develop-
infant in the form of statistical structure and ment of selective attention, perception, and
cross-modal regularities. It also contains many cognition in infancy. Current Directions in
Psychological Science, 13, 99–102.
distractions, in terms of noise and extraneous
Bahrick, L. E., Netto, D., & Hernandez-Reif,
information. When learning about the world,
M. (1998). Intermodal perception of adult
how do infants pay attention to the right set and child faces and voices by infants. Child
of multiple cues at the right time? This theory Development, 69, 1263–1275.
posits a developmental trajectory out of this Brehmer, B., & Qvarnstrom, G. (1976). Information
problem: At early ages, infants rely on multiple, integration and subjective weights in multiple-
cross-modal cues in learning about sequences cue judgments. Organizational Behavior &
and locations; later on, they are better able to Human Performance, 17, 118–126.
ignore unhelpful information and learn from a Bruno, N., & Cutting, J. E. (1988). Minimodularity
narrower set of cues. and the perception of layout. Journal of
In conclusion, I would like to suggest that Experimental Psychology: General, 117, 161–170.
Christiansen, M. H., Allen, J., & Seidenberg, M. S.
the impact of multiple cue integration on
(1998). Learning to segment speech using mul-
infant learning in a probabilistic environment
tiple cues: A connectionist model. Language
remains largely unexplored. How does multiple and Cognitive Processes, 13, 221–268.
cue integration interact with statistical learn- Christiansen, M. H., & Dale, R. A. C. (2001).
ing? What kinds of expectations about objects Integrating distributional, prosodic and pho-
can be supported by this type of learning? The nological information in a connectionist model
theory outlined in this chapter is an attempt of language acquisition. Proceedings of the 23rd
to unify research from statistical learning and Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science
42 OBJECTS AND SPACE

Society (pp. 220–225). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Green, D. M. (1958). Detection of multiple
Erlbaum. component signals in noise. Journal of the
Christiansen, M. H., & Monaghan, P. (2006). Acoustical Society of America, 30, 904–911.
Discovering verbs through multiple-cue inte- Haith, M. M. (1993). Future-oriented processes
gration. In K. Hirsh-Pasek & R.M. Golinkoff in infancy: The case of visual expectations. In.
(Eds.), Action meets words: How children C. Granrud (Ed.), Visual perception and cog-
learn verbs (pp. 88–107). New York: Oxford nition in infancy (pp. 235–264). Hillsdale, NJ:
University Press. Erlbaum.
Chun, M. M. (2000). Contextual cueing of visual Hauser, M. D., Newport, E. L., & Aslin, R. N.
attention. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 4, (2001). Segmentation of the speech stream in
170–178. a non-human primate: Statistical learning in
Chun, M. M., & Jiang, Y. (1998). Contextual cue- cotton-top tamarins. Cognition, 78, B53–B64.
ing: Implicit learning and memory of visual Heyes, C. M., & Foster, C. L. (2002). Motor learn-
context guides spatial attention. Cognitive ing by observation: Evidence from a serial
Psychology, 36, 28–71. reaction time task. The Quarterly Journal of
Cohen, A., Ivry, R. I., & Keele, S. W. (1990). Experimental Psychology, 55A, 593–607.
Attention and structure in sequence learning. Howard, J. H., Mutter, S. A., & Howard, D. V. (1993).
Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Serial pattern learning by event observation.
Memory, and Cognition, 16, 17–30. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning,
Colombo, J. (2001). The development of visual Memory, and Cognition, 18, 1029–1039.
attention in infancy. Annual Review of James, W. (1890/1981). The principles of psychology.
Psychology, 52, 337–367. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Curran, T., & Keele, S. W. (1993). Attentional and Johnson, S. P. (1997). Young infants’ perception
nonattentional forms of sequence learning. of object unity: Implications for development
Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, of attentional and cognitive skills. Current
Memory, and Cognition, 19, 189–202. Directions in Psychological Science, 6, 5–11.
Ernst, M. O., Banks, M. S., & Bülthoff, H. H. Johnson, S. P., Amso, D., & Slemmer, J. A. (2003).
(2000). Touch can change visual slant percep- Development of object concepts in infancy:
tion. Nature Neuroscience 3, 69–73. Evidence for early learning in an eye tracking
Fiser, J., & Aslin, R. N. (2001). Unsupervised sta- paradigm. Proceedings of the National Academy
tistical learning of higher-order spatial struc- of Sciences USA, 100, 10568–10573.
tures from visual scenes. Psychological Science, Johnson, S. P., Bremner, J. G., Slater, A., Mason,
12, 499– 504. U., Foster, K., & Cheshire, A. (2003). Infants’
Fiser, J. & Aslin, R. N. (2002). Statistical learning perception of object trajectories. Child
of higher-order temporal structure from visual Development, 74, 94–108.
shape sequences. Journal of Experimental Jonides, J., & Jones, C. M. (1992). Direct cod-
Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, ing of frequency of occurrence. Journal of
28, 458–467. Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory,
Fiser, J., & Aslin, R. N. (2003). Statistical learning and Cognition, 18, 368–378.
of new visual feature combinations by infants. Jonides, J. M., & Naveh-Benjamin, M. (1987).
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of Estimating frequency of occurrence. Journal of
The United States of America, 99, 15822–15826. Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory,
Gibson, E. J. (1969). Principles of perceptual learn- and Cognition, 13, 230–240.
ing and development. New York: Appleton Kinchla, R. A. (1977). The role of structural
Century Crofts. redundancy in the perception of visual targets.
Gilmore, R. O., & Johnson, M. H. (1997). Egocentric Perception and Psychophysics, 22, 19–30.
action in early infancy: Spatial frames of ref- Kirkham, N. Z., Johnson, S. P., & Wagner, J. Moving
erence for saccades. Psychological Science, 8, sounds: The role of inter-modal perception in
224–230. solving the problem of occlusion. Manuscript in
Gomez, R. L., & Gerken, L. (1999). Artificial preparation.
grammar learning by 1-year-olds leads to spe- Kirkham, N.Z., & Shohamy, D (2007). Feedback
cific and abstract knowledge. Cognition, 70, modulation of probabilistic learning: A devel-
109–135. opmental perspective. Poster presented at the
LEARNING THROUGH MULTIPLE SOURCES 43

Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Neurosciences Eye movements of adults and 6-month-olds
Society, May 2007. reveal dynamic spatial indexing. Journal
Kirkham, N. Z., Richardson, D. C., & Johnson, S. P., of Experimental Psychology: General, 133,
& Wu, R. The importance of ‘what’ The usefulness 46–62.
of multiple redundant cues across the first year of Richardson, D. C., & Spivey, M. J. (2000).
life. Manuscript in preparation. Representation, space, and Hollywood Squares:
Kirkham, N. Z., Slemmer, J. A., & Johnson, S. P. Looking at things that aren’t there anymore.
(2002). Visual statistical learning in infancy. Cognition, 76, 269–295.
Cognition, 83, B35–B42. Rosenblum, L. D., Schmuckler, M. A., & Johnson,
Kirkham, N. Z., Slemmer, J. A., Richardson, D. C., J. A. (1997). The McGurk effect in infants.
& Johnson, S. P. (2007). Location, location, loca- Perception & Psychophysics, 59, 347–357.
tion: Development of spatiotemporal sequence Rubin, D. C. (1974). The subjective estima-
learning in infancy. Child Development, 78, tion of syllable frequency. Perception and
1559–1571. Psychophysics, 16, 193–196.
Kuhl, P. K., & Meltzoff, A. N. (1982). The bimodal Saegert, S., Swap, W., & Zajonc, R. B. (1973).
perception of speech in infancy. Science, 218, Exposure, context, and interpersonal attrac-
1138–1140. tion. Journal of Personality and Social
Landy, M. S., Maloney, L. T., Johnston, E. B., & Psychology, 25, 234–242.
Young, M. (1995). Measurement and modelling Saff ran, J. R., Aslin, R. N., & Newport, E. L. (1996).
of depth cue combination: In defense of weak Statistical learning by 8-month-old infants.
fusion. Vision Research, 35, 389–412. Science, 274, 1926–1928.
Lewkowicz, D. J. (2000). The development of Saff ran, J. R., Johnson, E. K., Aslin, R. N., &
intersensory temporal perception: An epige- Newport, E. L. (1999). Statistical learning of
netic systems/limitations view. Psychological tone sequences by human infants and adults.
Bulletin, 126, 281–308. Cognition, 70, 27–52.
Lewkowicz, D. J., & Turkewitz, G. (1980). Cross- Sedmeier, P., Hertwig, R., & Gigerenzer, G.
modal equivalence in early infancy: Auditory– (1998). Are judgments of the positional
visual intensity of matching. Developmental frequencies of letters systematically biased
Psychology, 16, 597–607. due to availability? Journal of Experimental
Lichenstein, S. P., Slovic, P., Fischoff, B., Layman, Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition,
M., & Combs, B. (1978). Judged frequency 24, 754–770.
of lethal events. Journal of Experimental Shapiro, B., J. (1969). The subjective estimation
Psychology: Human Learning and Memory, 4, of relative word frequency. Journal of Verbal
551–578. Learning and Verbal Behavior, 8, 248–251.
Massaro, D. W. (1999). Speechreading: Illusion Smith, W. C., Johnson, S. P., & Spelke, E. S.
or window into pattern recognition. Trends in (2003). Motion and edge sensitivity in percep-
Cognitive Science, 3, 310–317. tion of object unity. Cognitive Psychology, 46,
Mayhew, J. E., & Frisby, J. P. (1980). The computa- 31–64.
tion of binocular edges. Perception, 1, 69–86. Spelke, E. S. (1979). Perceiving bimodally specified
Meulemans, T., Van der Linden, M., & Perrouchet, events in infancy. Developmental Psychology,
P. (1998). Implicit learning in children. Journal 15, 626–636.
of Experimental Child Psychology, 69, 199–221. Spelke, E. S. (1981). The infant’s acquisition of
Morrongiello, B. A., Fenwick, K. D., & Chance, knowledge of bimodally specified events.
G. (1998). Cross modal learning in new- Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 31,
born infants: Inferences about properties of 279–299.
auditory–visual events. Infant Behavior and Sperling, G., Landy, M. S., Dosher, B. A., &
Development, 21, 543–554. Perkins, M. E. (1989). Kinetic depth effect
Nissen, M. J., & Bullemer, P. (1987). Attentional and identification of shape. Journal of
requirements of learning: Evidence from per- Experimental Psychology: Human Perception
formance measures. Cognitive Psychology, 19, and Performance, 15, 826–840.
1–32. Todd, J. T., & Akerstrom, R. A. (1987). Perception of
Richardson, D. C., & Kirkham, N. Z. (2004). three-dimensional form from patterns of opti-
Multi-modal events and moving locations: cal texture. Journal of Experimental Psychology:
44 OBJECTS AND SPACE

Human Perception and Performance, 13, Xu, F. & Carey, S. (1996). Infants’ metaphys-
242–255. ics: the case of numerical identity. Cognitive
Wentworth, N. Haith, M. M., & Hood, R. (2002). Psychology, 30, 111–153.
Spatiotemporal regularity and interevent con- Zajonc, R. B. (1968). Attitudinal effects of mere
tingencies as information for infants’ visual exposure. Journal of Personality and Social
expectations. Infancy, 3, 303–321. Psychology Monograph Supplement, 9, 1–28.
CHAP TER 3
Perceptual Completion in Infancy

Scott P. Johnson

Sensory systems provide information about • Perception of units as complete across space
the environment so that we might prepare and and time despite gaps in perception due to
enact actions appropriate for the context. Visual occlusion and movement of objects.
perception, in particular, is useful in acquiring • Deduction of 3D shape from limited views
information about near and distant objects in due to objects’ self-occlusion.
our surroundings. Consider, for example, the • Recognition of objects encountered before.
scene in Figure 3.1, adjacent to the beach in • Tracking the identity of previously encoun-
Venice, California. This scene is typical of what tered objects over time.
we might encounter when we move about in the • Categorization of similar objects.
world: the ground extends into the distance and • Detecting affordances for action.
consists of different materials (concrete, grass,
This way of decomposing object perception
sand) that might dictate our route, and there
underscores its complexity, and also provides
are many objects that might either be avoided
hints as to how investigations into its mecha-
or approached as we move about, depending on
nisms and development might proceed. In this
our goals.
chapter, I will describe a program of research
In everyday contexts, we hold certain com-
whose goal is to elucidate the developmental ori-
monsense expectations about the objects we see.
gins of object perception, with particular focus
We expect most objects, for example, to be solid
on perceptual completion, which constitutes a
and three-dimensional, persistent across space
subset of the steps just described: assembly of
and time, and we plan our actions around these
visible surfaces into units despite gaps in percep-
expectations. How are these commonsense
tion due to occlusion by other objects, and per-
expectations about objects achieved? Object
ception of 3D shape despite self-occlusion. I will
perception and action planning typically seem
describe three kinds of perceptual completion
so effortless and rapid that we may fail to appre-
and consider the developmental mechanisms
ciate their complexity. But there are many steps
involved in each: spatial completion, perceiving
involved in perceiving objects:
the unity of partly occluded surfaces; spatiotem-
• Segmentation of a scene into its component poral completion, perceiving the unity of partly
surfaces based on differences in color, lumi- occluded trajectories; and 3D object completion,
nance, motion, shape, orientation, distance, perceiving the 3D shape of objects seen from a
and so forth. limited vantage point.
• Assembly of the surfaces into units (units, or In principle, perceptual completion might be
collections of units, constitute objects). accomplished innately—in the absence of visual

45
46 OBJECTS AND SPACE

Figure 3.1 A scene in Venice, California.

experience—if the developmental processes birth (Johnson, 2004). It is unknown if there


that build those parts of the visual system that is a one-to-one correspondence between these
support it were complete at birth. In the mature developmental events, as might be predicted on
primate visual system, for example, spatial a strictly maturational account (e.g., if growth of
completion is accomplished in part by interac- neural connections causes spatial completion),
tions among neurons in relatively low levels of but maturation is likely an important part of
the visual system (V1 and V2), which, when fir- the overall developmental story. The evidence is
ing in response to a visible edge, connect with clearer, however, for a direct and important role
other neurons that are tuned to similar edge for learning as a principal means of develop-
orientations (Peterhans & von der Heydt, 1991). ment of perceptual completion. I will describe
In this way, activation “spreads” among neu- this evidence subsequently.
rons coding for a specific edge orientation when The remainder of this chapter is organized
that orientation is detected—so-called “local” as follows. In the next section, I will describe
circuits—and activation can propagate across a two theoretical views of object perception in
spatial gap. As it happens, connections among infancy, one of Jean Piaget and the other of
low-level local circuits in the human visual theorists espousing a nativist view. In the fol-
system are likely first formed at about 2 post- lowing sections, I will describe in more detail
natal months (Burkhalter, 1993; Burkhalter, the three kinds of perceptual completion men-
Bernardo, & Charles, 1993), and consistent with tioned previously (spatial, spatiotemporal, and
this timing, infants begin to provide evidence of 3D object completion), and some of the devel-
perceptual completion at about 2 months after opmental mechanisms involved. The chapter
PERCEPTUAL COMPLETION IN INFANCY 47

will conclude by considering implications of of infants’ behavior has been disputed on the
our research for constructivist theory, which of basis of more recent experiments employing
course is the theme of this book. methods claimed to be more sophisticated and
sensitive than reaching in tapping infants’ cog-
nitive constructs. Some of these methods capi-
THEORETICAL CONSIDERATIONS
talize on infants’ tendency to show clear visual
Piaget (1954) described the first systematic preferences for particular stimuli over others;
investigations of how infants, beginning at birth one such method, known as the “violation of
and extending across the next several years, expectation” method, is claimed to demonstrate
respond to objects and their spatial relations. infants’ knowledge of event sequences that are
According to Piagetian theory, the development physically impossible. For example, in an exper-
of object knowledge consists of construction of iment described by Baillargeon, Spelke, and
two related concepts: first, that objects persist Wasserman (1985), 5-month-old infants viewed
across time and space, and second, that objects a box and a screen arranged such that the screen
exist external to the self in a particular spatial rotated and appeared to move through the
arrangement. Piaget devised a series of clever space occupied by the box, a so-called “impos-
activities involving objects, often occluded sible” event, accomplished with one-way mir-
objects, which he presented to infants and chil- rors. Infants were reported to look longer at
dren, and he recorded the children’s responses. this event than at a “possible” version in which
These observations revealed a developmental the screen stopped at an appropriate place in its
sequence of behaviors thought to reflect under- rotation, before moving through the box, there-
lying knowledge of objects and their spatial rela- fore providing evidence for object permanence
tions. Initially, infants provided no responses earlier than acknowledged by Piagetian theory.
to indicate knowledge of object permanence, A second example comes from an exper-
though there was recognition of familiar iment described by Bower (1967) in which
objects. Between 3 and 6 months, infants begin 1-month-old infants viewed a triangle made of
to show evidence of a sense of objects as having wire, its center occluded by a rectangular object.
boundaries that extend beyond the visible, such Bower did not record looking times toward the
as searching for (whole) objects that are only object; instead, he recorded rates of sucking on
partly visible, and directing gaze toward the a pacifier during viewing and reasoned that
expected point of emergence of a moving object a change in sucking rates upon presentation
that became hidden. Later, at around 8 months of a novel stimulus would indicate perceptual
of age, infants search for fully hidden objects; discrimination of the new stimulus from the
still later (around 18–24 months), infants solve original. Following the occluded object, infants
more complex hiding tasks involving more than viewed four new stimuli presented individually:
one location, at which point Piaget ascribed a whole triangle, a triangle with crossed lines in
them full object permanence. the center, and two different kinds of incomplete
At birth, therefore, the infant experiences triangles, each with a gap in the center. All four
not objects per se but rather surfaces that appear test stimuli were consistent with the visible por-
and disappear erratically—fleeting images that tions of the triangle seen during training. The
are arbitrary and subjective, rather than sub- infants maintained sucking rates in response to
stantial, predictable, and permanent. Piaget the complete object, and reduced sucking rates
suggested, furthermore, that the principal most when viewing the two incomplete forms.
mechanisms of development were rooted in the This implies generalization of the complete form
infant’s own behavior: engaging with objects, to the partly occluded object, and response to
following their motions, and taking note of the the incomplete forms as novel.
consequences of self-directed actions. Noting the inconsistencies between the
Many of Piaget’s observations have been Bower study and Piaget’s observations, Kellman
replicated repeatedly, but his interpretation and Spelke (1983) undertook a more thorough
48 OBJECTS AND SPACE

examination of young infants’ perception of of cognitive development stressing an innate


partly occluded objects. In one such experi- knowledge component (i.e., independent of
ment, infants were first presented with a mov- experience) that guides infant responses to
ing, partly occluded rod until habituation objects. This theory is founded principally on
of looking occurred; that is, looking times the assumption that object knowledge is innate
declined according to a predetermined crite- because responses to occlusion are observed at
rion. The infants were then tested with incom- an early age, and there is inadequate opportu-
plete (or broken) and complete versions of this nity for infant learning of foundational con-
display without the occluder (see Figure 3.2). cepts, such as persistence and permanence
The test stimulus that attracted the most atten- (Baillargeon, 1995). On a nativist account,
tion was assumed to be perceived as most novel Piaget may have underestimated infants’ object
relative to the initial stimulus. Four-month-old knowledge and the age at which competence at
infants showed reliable preferences for a broken object permanence can be elicited because of
rod test display when the partly occluded rod the insensitivity of his methods. Piaget’s meth-
(the habituation stimulus) was seen to move lat- ods are thought to rely too heavily on overt
erally relative to the background and occluder manual responses, such as coordinated reach-
(as depicted in Figure 3.2). (In this study, and ing. Difficulties with reaching may mask latent
the others described in this chapter that use cognitive capacities that can be revealed with
habituation methods, a separate age-matched methods that rely on relatively simpler action
control group was observed for evidence of sequences, such as looking and sucking.
spontaneous preference for one of the test stim- Yet the nativist account has three funda-
uli; in all cases, none were found.) There was no mental flaws with respect to infants’ responses
evidence of unity perception, however, in dis- to partly and fully occluded objects. First, find-
plays in which the rod remained stationary, in ings from experiments using measures that do
contradiction to the results reported by Bower. not require manual search skills, such as look-
The discrepancies between the findings of the ing times, in reality are broadly consistent with
Kellman and Spelke study concerning unity Piaget’s observations: Infants provide evidence
perception and the Bower experiment are dif- of representing partly occluded objects a few
ficult to reconcile, but it is noteworthy that the months after birth, and fully occluded objects
Kellman and Spelke finding has been replicated by about the middle of the first year. Some have
on multiple occasions. claimed that infants have a sense of object per-
These studies and others have been sug- manence on the basis of evidence from looking
gested to provide support for a nativist theory time studies (e.g., Baillargeon et al., 1985), but

Figure 3.2 Schematic depictions of displays used to assess infants’ perception of object unity, or spatial
completion. Left: The display shown during habituation consists of two aligned rod parts moving in
tandem above and below an occluder. Center: Broken test display. Right: Complete rod test display.
Note: Real, 3D objects were used in the original Kellman and Spelke (1983) experiments; displays
depicted here are adapted from 2D versions (Johnson & Náñez, 1995).
PERCEPTUAL COMPLETION IN INFANCY 49

in fact the best that can be said about infant preference; the 4-month-olds and neonates show
performance in most such paradigms is that opposite patterns of preference. This has led to
there is a short-term representation of an object the more general conclusion that neonates are
that is maintained for a matter of seconds (cf. unable to perceive occlusion, and that occlusion
Haith, 1998; Kagan, 2008). This is a far cry from perception emerges over the first several post-
Piaget’s criteria for full object permanence, natal months (Johnson, 2004). That is, “piece-
which requires accurate search in multiple meal” or fragmented perception of the visual
locations for a desired hidden object, accessing environment extends from birth through the
knowledge of both persistence and the spatial first several months afterward, implying a fun-
relations between the object, the hiding loca- damental shift in the infant’s perceptual experi-
tions, and the infant. ence: “During the first few months of existence
Second, nativist theories contribute little if the child’s universe is really lacking permanent
any substantive knowledge about developmen- objects . . . this means that perceived figures
tal mechanisms underlying object perception. simply appear and disappear like moving tab-
Even on a strictly maturational account stipu- leaux and exhibit a series of changing shapes in
lating developments that are exclusive of visual between” (Piaget & Inhelder, 1956, p. 9).
experience, there are means by which the infant Because neonates and 4-month-olds appear
comes to perceive and represent objects, and to regard rod-and-box displays differently—as
these means may be amenable to empirical separate surfaces and as occluded objects,
investigation. respectively—an important step in understand-
Third, there is substantial evidence that ing development of spatial completion is inves-
newborn infants do not perceive moving, tigations of performance in infants between
partly occluded objects as having hidden parts. these ages. In the first such investigation,
Instead, neonates appear to construe such stim- 2-month-olds were found to show an “inter-
uli solely in terms of their visible parts, failing mediate” pattern of performance—no reliable
to achieve spatial completion (Slater, Johnson, posthabituation preference—implying that spa-
Brown, & Badenoch, 1996; Slater et al., 1990; tial completion is developing at this point but
but see Valenza, Leo, Gava, & Simion, 2006, not yet complete (Johnson & Náñez, 1995). A
for evidence against this possibility). This and follow-up study examined the possibility that
other findings show clear evidence for a devel- 2-month-olds will perceive unity if given addi-
opmental progression in perceptual comple- tional perceptual support. The amount of visible
tion and call for an explanation of underlying rod surface revealed behind the occluder was
mechanisms of change. This is the goal of the enhanced by reducing box height and by adding
experiments described in the following sections gaps in it, and under these conditions 2-month-
of this chapter. olds provided evidence of unity perception
(Johnson & Aslin, 1995). With newborns, how-
ever, this manipulation failed to reveal similar
SPATIAL COMPLETION
evidence: Even in enhanced displays, newborns
Adults and 4-month-old infants construe the seemed to perceive disjoint rather than unified
occlusion display depicted in Figure 3.2 as con- rod parts (Slater et al., 1996; Slater, Johnson,
sisting of two parts, a single rod or bar moving Kellman, & Spelke, 1994). These experiments
back and forth behind an occluding rectangle served to pinpoint more precisely the time of
(Kellman & Spelke, 1983). Neonates, by con- emergence of spatial completion in infancy: the
trast, perceive this display as consisting of three first several weeks or months after birth under
separate parts: two disjoint rod parts and an typical circumstances.
occluder (Slater et al., 1990, 1996). These con- Additional experiments explored the kinds
clusions arise from looking time experiments of visual information infants use to perceive
described previously in which posthabituation spatial completion. Our starting point was the
looking patterns are thought to reflect a novelty Gestalt cues of good continuation and common
50 OBJECTS AND SPACE

Figure 3.3 Schematic depictions of displays used to assess 2-month-olds’ spatial completion. Infants
perceived completion only when rod parts were aligned and the occluder was relatively narrow (left).
Infants provided evidence of perceiving disjoint surfaces in the other displays. Adapted from Johnson
(2004).

motion, also known as common fate. The serving to segment the scene into its constitu-
Kellman and Spelke (1983) experiments pro- ent surfaces, and then serving to bind moving
vided evidence that 4-month-olds perceived surfaces into a single object (Johnson, Davidow,
object unity only when the rod parts moved in Hall-Haro, & Frank, 2008).
tandem behind a stationary occluder. We rep- In summary, experiments that examine
licated and extended this finding, showing in development of spatial completion provide sup-
addition that 4-month-olds provided evidence port for the possibility that young infants ana-
of completion only when the rod parts were lyze the motions and arrangements of visible
aligned (Johnson & Aslin, 1996). Later experi- surfaces and initially (at birth) perceive them as
ments revealed similar patterns of performance separate from one another and the background.
in 2-month-olds when tested using displays Only later do infants integrate these surfaces into
with different occluder sizes and edge arrange- percepts of coherent, partly occluded objects.
ments, as seen in Figure 3.3 (Johnson, 2004). According to this view, therefore, development
Perceptual completion obtained only when rod of object knowledge begins with perception of
parts were aligned across a narrow occluder; in visible object components, and proceeds with
the other displays, infants provided evidence of increasing proficiency at representation of those
disjoint surface perception. object parts that cannot be discerned directly.
One possible interpretation of these findings
Learning to Perceive Spatial Completion
is that alignment, motion, and occluder width
(i.e., the spatial gap) are interdependent contri- In this section, I will describe experiments
butions to spatial completion, such that com- designed to elucidate developmental mecha-
mon motion is detected most effectively when nisms of spatial completion. An important
rod parts are aligned (Kellman & Arterberry, part of the developmental explanation revealed
1998). I evaluated this possibility in experiments by these experiments is the strong relation
probing 2-month-olds’ discrimination of differ- between oculomotor scanning patterns—eye
ent patterns of rod motion with varying orien- movements—and unity perception. Amso and
tations of rod parts and occluder widths. Under Johnson (2006) and Johnson, Slemmer, and
all tested conditions, infants discriminated the Amso (2004) observed 3-month-old infants in
motion patterns, implying that motion discrim- a spatial completion task using the habituation
ination was neither impaired nor facilitated by paradigm described previously. Infants’ eye
misalignment or occluder width. The precise movements were recorded with a corneal reflec-
contributions of motion to spatial completion tion eye tracker during the habituation phase
in infants remain unknown; one possibility of the experiment. We found systematic dif-
is that motion serves multiple functions, first ferences in scanning patterns between infants
PERCEPTUAL COMPLETION IN INFANCY 51

Figure 3.4 Scan patterns of a “perceiver” (left) and a “nonperceiver” (right), both 3-month-olds, from
Amso and Johnson (2006). The leftmost and rightmost positions of the rod during its motion are
shown. Scan paths are depicted as lines between points, which represent fi xations.

whose posthabituation test display preferences acquisition may lead to a “default” response
indicated unity perception and infants who to the visible surfaces only, characteristic of
provided evidence of perception of disjoint sur- neonates, yielding a novelty preference for the
faces: “Perceivers” tended to scan more in the complete rod at test. Either of the possibilities
vicinity of the two visible rod segments, and is consistent with the idea that efficient visual
to scan back and forth between them (Figure exploration is an important mechanism of
3.4). In a somewhat younger sample (58 to 97 development in object perception.
days), Johnson et al. (2008) found a reliable cor- How do these findings provide evidence for
relation between posthabituation preference— learning as a mechanism of spatial completion?
our index of spatial completion—and targeted A nativist view stressing innate mechanisms
visual exploration, the proportion of eye move- that are independent of experience might posit
ments directed toward the moving rod parts, that spatial completion stems exclusively from
which we reasoned was the most relevant aspect maturation of neural structures responsible for
of the stimulus for perception of completion. object perception, such as connections in V1
Spatial completion was not predicted by other and V2 mentioned previously. Then, as infants
measures of oculomotor performance, includ- begin to perceive occlusion, their eye move-
ing mean number of eye movements per sec- ment patterns support or confirm this percept.
ond, mean distance between fi xations, and the Unequivocal evidence for a direct role for tar-
“dispersion” of visual attention, an assessment geted visual exploration in development of spa-
of “global” versus “local” scanning activity. tial completion would come from experiments
Spatial completion was best predicted by sacca- in which individual differences in oculomotor
des directed toward the vicinity of the moving patterns were observed in both spatial com-
rod parts. This can be a challenge for a develop- pletion and some other visual task, and this
ing oculomotor system, attested by the fact that was recently reported by Amso and Johnson
targeted scans almost always followed the rod as (2006). We found that both spatial completion
it moved, rarely anticipating its position. and scanning patterns were strongly related to
How targeted visual exploration emerges performance in an independent visual search
in infancy to maximize effective uptake of task in which targets were selected amongst
visual information is not yet known. Very distracters. This finding is inconsistent with
young infants’ ability to perceive occlusion the possibility that scanning patterns were
may be challenged by difficulties in accessing tailored specifically to perceptual completion,
visual information for unity such as alignment and instead suggests that a general facility with
and common motion of edges across a spatial targeted visual behavior leads to improvements
gap. Alternatively, insufficient information across multiple tasks.
52 OBJECTS AND SPACE

How might developing object perception objects—that is, spatial completion—findings


systems benefit from targeted scans? Eye move- that raise the question of how perception of
ments may serve as a vital binding mechanism complete occlusion emerges during the first few
due to the relatively restricted visual field and months after birth. Apart from Piaget’s theory,
poor acuity characteristic of young infants’ this question has received relatively little serious
vision. Visual information in the periphery is attention until recently, in favor of accounts that
more difficult to access with a single glance, stress innate object concepts (e.g., Baillargeon,
increasing the need to scan between features to 2008; Spelke, 1990).
ascertain their relations to one another. Infants To address this gap in our knowledge, my
who are more likely to do this will increase their colleagues and I have conducted experiments
processing of relevant features and their corre- with computer-generated displays in which
spondences, as irrelevant features are ignored. objects moved on a trajectory, disappeared
In summary, the individual differences behind an occluder, reappeared on the far side,
in targeted visual exploration that we have and reversed direction, repeating the cycle. We
observed suggest that scanning patterns make reasoned that manipulation of spatial and tem-
a vital contribution to the emergence of veridi- poral characteristics of the stimuli, and the use
cal object perception. Evidence suggests that as of different age groups, might provide insights
scanning patterns develop, they enable learning into development of spatiotemporal completion,
of relevant visual features of the environment, as they did in the case of spatial completion.
and support binding of these features into These investigations revealed a fragmented-
coherent percepts of unified objects. to-holistic developmental pattern, and revealed
spatial and temporal processing constraints as
well. Both sets of results are in parallel with the
SPATIOTEMPORAL COMPLETION
investigations of spatial completion described
A number of studies using different meth- in the previous section. Spatiotemporal com-
ods (e.g., looking times, reaching in the dark) pletion was tested using similar methods:
have shown that young infants can main- habituation to an occlusion display (Figure 3.5),
tain representations for hidden objects across followed by broken and complete test displays,
brief delays (e.g., Aguiar & Baillargeon, 1999; and different versions of the partly hidden tra-
Clifton, Rochat, Litovsky, & Perris, 1991; Spelke, jectory seen during habituation. At 4 months,
Breinlinger, Macomber, & Jacobson, 1992). Yet, infants treat the ball-and-box display depicted
as mentioned previously, newborns provide in Figure 3.5 as consisting of two disconnected
little evidence of perceiving partly occluded trajectories, rather than a single, partly hidden

Figure 3.5 Schematic depictions of displays used to assess infants’ perception of occluded trajectories,
or spatiotemporal completion. Left: The display shown during habituation consists of two segments of
object trajectory. Center: Discontinuous trajectory test display. Right: Continuous trajectory rod test
display. Adapted from Johnson, Bremner et al. (2003).
PERCEPTUAL COMPLETION IN INFANCY 53

path (Johnson et al., 2003); evidence comes This work leads to two conclusions. First,
from a reliable preference for the continuous there may be a lower age limit for trajectory
version of the test trajectory. By 6 months, completion (between 2 and 4 months), just
infants perceived this trajectory as unitary, as as there appears to be for spatial completion
revealed by a reliable preference for the dis- (between birth and 2 months). Second, young
continuous trajectory test stimulus. When infants’ spatiotemporal completion is based on
occluder size was narrowed, however, reduc- relatively simple parameters. Either a short time
ing the spatiotemporal gap across which the or short distance out of sight leads to percep-
trajectory had to be interpolated, 4-month- tion of continuity, and this may occur because
olds’ posthabituation preferences (and thus, the processing load is reduced by these manipu-
by inference, their percepts of spatiotemporal lations. The fragile nature of emerging spatio-
completion) were shifted toward the discon- temporal completion is underscored as well
tinuous, partway by an intermediate width, by results showing its breakdown when either
and fully by a narrow width, so narrow as to occluder or path orientation is nonorthogonal.
be only slightly larger than the ball itself. In
2-month-olds, this manipulation appeared to Learning to Perceive Spatiotemporal
have no effect. Completion
Reducing the spatiotemporal gap, therefore, Piaget (1954) described a series of infants’
facilitates spatiotemporal completion. Reducing behaviors providing evidence for an emerging
the temporal gap during which an object is hid- ability to track objects that became occluded.
den, independently from the spatial gap, also Before the development of skilled manual
supports spatiotemporal completion. Increasing search at about 4 to 6 months, search for hid-
the ball size (Figure 3.6) can minimize the time den objects was exclusively visual. For example,
out of sight as it passes behind the occluder, Piaget’s son Laurent, at 2 months, was reported
and this led 4-month-olds to perceive its tra- to maintain gaze at a point where Piaget had
jectory as complete. Accelerating the speed of been seen previously, a passive expectation of
a smaller ball as it passed behind the occluder his father’s reappearance. More active visual
(and appeared more quickly) had a similar effect search behavior emerged after 4 months, such
(Bremner et al., 2005). On the other hand, alter- as visual “accommodation,” as when an infant
ing the orientation of the trajectory-impaired would respond to a dropped object by looking
path completion (Figure 3.6), unless the edges of down toward the floor, a behavior observed
the occluder were orthogonal to the path; these in Laurent at 6.5 months. On Piaget’s theory,
findings are similar to outcomes of experiments visual accommodation or anticipation becomes
on edge misalignment described in the previous more consistent as the infant learns from self-
section (Bremner et al., 2007). directed manipulation of objects, providing

Figure 3.6 Schematic depictions of displays used to examine conditions under which infants show
evidence of spatiotemporal completion. Adapted from Bremner et al. (2005, 2007).
54 OBJECTS AND SPACE

direct experience with dropping and retrieval, of occluded objects are weak if not nonexistent
and develops alongside reconstruction of partly in very young infants, and gradually strengthen
occluded objects from visible fragments, which across the first year after birth (Munakata, 2001;
I have referred to in this chapter as spatial com- Piaget, 1954).
pletion. Piaget suggested that increasing visual, To examine the possibility that learning
tactile, and manual experience is a vital devel- plays an important role in development of spa-
opmental mechanism in developing more com- tiotemporal completion, my colleagues and
plex concepts of objects. I presented ball-and-box displays to 4- and
More recent research has shown that by 6-month-olds as we recorded their eye move-
6 months, infants’ representations of hid- ments (Johnson, Amso, & Slemmer, 2003). The
den objects are sufficiently robust to guide stimulus was identical to the displays used by
reaching prospectively to intercept objects on Johnson, Bremner et al. (2003) (Figure 3.5).
occluded trajectories (Clifton et al., 1991; von Because 6-month-olds provided evidence of
Hofsten, Vishton, Spelke, Feng, & Rosander, spatiotemporal completion in these displays
1998). Researchers have built on these ideas by when tested with a habituation paradigm, we
recording infants’ eye movements as they view predicted that oculomotor anticipations would
repetitive events in which objects move behind be more frequent in the older age group. This
an occluder and subsequently reemerge, such prediction was supported. A higher proportion
as that shown in Figure 3.5. The question is the of 6-month-olds’ eye movements was classified
extent to which infants produce anticipatory as anticipatory (i.e., initiated prior to the ball’s
eye movements toward the place of reemergence emergence from behind the occluder) relative
while the object is out of view, implying a func- to 4-month-olds, corroborating the likelihood
tional representation of the object that guides that spatiotemporal completion strengthens
oculomotor behavior. between 4 and 6 months.
At 4 months, prospective behavior— As noted previously, 4 months is a time of
anticipations from eye and head movements to the transition toward spatiotemporal completion,
place of reappearance of an object seen to move raising questions about the role of experience
behind an occluder—is adapted to variations in in oculomotor anticipation performance at this
occluder width and object speed, implying that age. There is mixed evidence for short-term
under some conditions, infants may track with gains in predictive performance, gains that
their “mind’s eye” (von Hofsten, Kochukhova, & hypothetically might arise from repeated expo-
Rosander, 2007). At 6 months, infants begin to sure to a target object that moves in a perfectly
respond to nonlinear trajectories, showing spa- predictable manner (to adults). In other words,
tially accurate predictive eye movements when a we might expect infants to show more reliable
target moves on a partly occluded circular path anticipation as they view multiple instances of
(Gredebäck & von Hofsten, 2004; Gredebäck, an object emerging from behind an occluder.
von Hofsten, & Boudreau, 2002). Yet the evi- Rosander and von Hofsten (2004) found that
dence from habituation experiments described predictive performance of the oldest infants
previously indicates 4-month-olds process they observed (21-week-olds) improved with
partly occluded trajectories in terms of visible repeated exposure to four complete cycles of
components only, not complete paths, when motion, in terms of decreasing eye movement
tested under conditions that challenge spatio- latencies as a function of trial. By contrast,
temporal completion (Johnson, Bremner, et al., Gredebäck et al. (2002) and Johnson, Amso,
2003), and, notably, the lower bound for predic- and Slemmer (2003) found that oculomotor
tive tracking is about 12 weeks (Rosander & von anticipations declined across trials in infants
Hofsten, 2004). These results indicate that repre- ranging from 4 to 9 months. In these studies,
sentations of occluded objects in 4-month-olds infants were exposed to several dozen opportu-
may be rather fragile and not completely estab- nities to learn about the repetitive event during
lished, and, more broadly, that representations the sequence of trials, yet performance declined
PERCEPTUAL COMPLETION IN INFANCY 55

consistently. In general, therefore, infants do For associative learning about occlusion to


not seem to capitalize on the predictable nature be a viable means of dealing with real-world
of occlusion stimuli in producing predictive events, associations between visible and partly
eye movements, implying that infants do not occluded paths must be committed to memory.
acquire spatiotemporal completion solely by How long do such rapidly acquired associations
means of this kind of experience. last? To address this question, we replicated the
But of course the visual environment in the Johnson, Slemmer, and Amso (2003) methods
real world is not limited to dynamic occlusion and observed a nearly identical pattern of antic-
events. There are many instances of objects that ipatory behaviors by 4-month-olds in baseline
move in full view, and infants will track mov- and training conditions (Johnson & Shuwairi,
ing objects from the first opportunities to do 2009). A third group received a half-hour break
so, at birth (Slater, 1995). What do infants learn between training and test, and performance
by watching such events? We addressed this reverted to baseline, implying that memory for
question with a “training” paradigm: present- the association was lost during the delay. But a
ing infants with unoccluded object trajectory fourth group, provided with a single “reminder”
displays for 2 min immediately preceding the trial after an identical delay, showed a recovery
occlusion stimulus seen in Figure 3.5 (Johnson, of oculomotor anticipations equivalent to the
Amso, & Slemmer, 2003). Following training, no-delay training condition. (A fi ft h group,
the 4-month-olds’ performance was statistically provided only a single training trial, showed
indistinguishable from that of the 6-month- no benefit in the form of anticipatory looking.)
olds, providing evidence for rapid learning of These findings suggest that accumulated expo-
spatiotemporal completion. Data from a sec- sure to occlusion events may be an important
ond training condition indicates that we were means by which spatiotemporal completion
not simply facilitating horizontal eye move- arises in infancy.
ments that carried over from training to test. In summary, research that examines infants’
This second training condition used a vertical oculomotor anticipations as they view repeti-
unoccluded trajectory for training, followed tive dynamic occlusion events is broadly consis-
as before by the (horizontal) occlusion display. tent with Piaget’s original descriptions of infant
Again, performance was statistically indistin- performance: There is little evidence of system-
guishable from that of the older infants. atic predictive behavior prior to 4 months, after
Brief training, therefore, brought 4-month- which time anticipations become robust and
olds to a level of predictive performance similar flexible, and performance continues to improve
to that of older infants. How might this work with age. It seems unlikely, however, that direct
in infants’ everyday environment? In the real manual experience with objects is a principal
world, infants are exposed to many different developmental mechanism driving the emer-
objects moving in different ways, presenting gence of this predictive behavior, because oculo-
multiple opportunities for learning. It may be motor anticipations begin to become established
that repeated exposure to moving objects, and prior to the onset of functional goal-directed
repeated viewing of objects as they move in and reaching and manual object manipulation in
out of view due to occlusion, leads to an asso- developmental time. Experiments described in
ciative link between the two scenarios. These the next section, however, provide evidence for
associations accrue gradually in everyday learn- a vital role for manual experience in develop-
ing, attested by the relatively long span between ment of perception of objects as coherent in 3D
improvements in performance (between 4 space.
and 6 months), but the learning mechanisms
themselves are remarkably efficient, attested by
3D OBJECT COMPLETION
the very brief training interval (2 min) neces-
sary to bridge this gap in performance in the Spatial and spatiotemporal completion consist
laboratory. of fi lling in the gaps in object surfaces that have
56 OBJECTS AND SPACE

been occluded by nearer ones. Solid objects also In a follow-up study (Soska & Johnson,
occlude parts of themselves such that we cannot 2008b), we used these same methods with a
see their hidden surfaces from our present van- more complex stimulus: a solid “L”-shaped
tage point, yet our experience of most objects is object with eight faces and vertices, as opposed
that of fi lled volumes rather than hollow shells. to the five faces and six vertices in the wedge-
Perceiving objects as solid in 3D space despite shaped object described previously. We tested
limited views constitutes 3D object completion. 4-, 6-, and 9.5-month-olds. As in the Soska and
In contrast to spatial and spatiotemporal com- Johnson (2008a) study with the wedge stimulus,
pletion, little is known about development of 3D we found a developmental progression in 3D
object completion. We recently addressed this object completion: 4-month-olds’ posthabitu-
question with a looking time paradigm similar ation looking times revealed no evidence for
to those described previously (Soska & Johnson, completion, whereas 9.5-month-olds consis-
2008a). Four- and 6-month-olds were habitu- tently looked longer at the hollow test display,
ated to a wedge rotating through 15° around the implying perception of the habituation object
vertical axis such that the far sides were never as volumetric in 3D space. At 6 months, inter-
revealed (Figure 3.7). Following habituation, estingly, only the male infants showed this pref-
infants viewed two test displays in alternation, erence; females looked about equally at the two
one an incomplete, hollow version of the wedge, test displays. (At 9.5 months, the male advan-
and the other a complete, whole version, both tage had disappeared: both males and females
undergoing a full 360° rotation revealing the looked longer at the hollow shape.)
entirety of the object shape. Four-month-olds Data from the Soska and Johnson (2008a,
showed no consistent posthabituation prefer- 2008b) studies provide evidence for a develop-
ence, but 6-month-olds looked longer at the mental progression in infants’ 3D object com-
hollow stimulus, indicating perception of the pletion abilities, and for a sex difference in these
wedge during habituation as a solid, volumetric abilities that is revealed at a transitional period
object in 3D space. in this skill—6 months—but only when infants’

Habituation: pivots through 15°

Test: rotates through 360°


Incomplete
Complete

Figure 3.7 Schematic depictions of displays used to investigate 3D object completion in infants.
Adapted from Soska and Johnson (2008a).
PERCEPTUAL COMPLETION IN INFANCY 57

views were tested with relatively complex explore objects from multiple viewpoints would
stimuli. It may be that the infants who were also have had more opportunities to learn about
successful at 3D object completion engaged in objects’ 3D forms outside the laboratory. Thus,
mental rotation in this task: manipulation of within this age range, individual differences in
a mental image of the object and imagining it coordinated visual–manual exploration (rota-
from a different perspective. Mental rotation is tions, fingerings, and transfers with looking at
a cognitive skill for which men have an advan- toys) and self-sitting experience should predict
tage relative to women (Shepard & Metzler, individual differences in infants’ looking pref-
1971; Zacks, 2008), and two recent reports have erences to the complete and incomplete object
provided evidence of a male advantage in young displays, our index of 3D object completion.
infants as well (Moore & Johnson, 2009; Quinn These predictions were supported. We found
& Liben, 2009). It remains to be determined strong and significant relations between both
definitely whether mental rotation is involved self-sitting and visual–manual coordination
in 3D object completion; at present, it is clear (from the motor skills assessment) and our
that it develops early in postnatal life, alongside measure of 3D object completion (from the
spatial and spatiotemporal completion. habituation paradigm). (Other motor skills
we recorded, such as holding skill and man-
Learning to Perceive 3D Object
ual exploration without visual attention to the
Completion
objects, did not predict 3D object completion.)
How does 3D object completion arise? One Self-sitting experience and coordinated visual–
possibility is that emerging motor skills sup- manual exploration were the strongest predic-
port perception of objects as coherent vol- tors of performance on the visual habituation
umes. Two types of motor skills, both of which task, but it seems that the role of self-sitting
undergo dramatic improvements between 4 and was indirect, influencing 3D completion chiefly
6 months, may be particularly important: self- because of its support of infants’ visual–manual
sitting ability and coordinated visual–manual exploration. Self-sitting infants performed more
object exploration. Independent sitting frees manual exploration while looking at objects
the hands for play and promotes gaze stabiliza- than did nonsitters, and visual–manual object
tion during manual actions (Rochat & Goubet, exploration is precisely the skill that provides
1995). Thus, self-sitting might spur coordina- active experience viewing objects from multi-
tion of object manipulation (e.g., rotating and ple viewpoints, thereby facilitating perceptual
transferring objects hand-to-hand) with visual completion of 3D form. These results provide
inspection, providing infants with multiple evidence for a cascade of developmental events
views of objects. Stroking, poking, turning, and following from the advent of visual–motor coor-
transferring objects hand to hand may promote dination, including learning from self-produced
learning about object form by supplying tactile experiences.
information and would provide multiple views In principle, 3D object completion might
at the same time. develop from more passive perceptual experi-
To examine these possibilities, we tested ences, but the findings yielded by the Soska et
infants between 4.5 and 7.5 months in a al. (in press) experiment indicate that passive
replication of the Soska and Johnson (2008a) experience may be insufficient to learn about
habituation experiment with the rotating 3D object form. Active exploration provides
wedge stimuli (Soska, Adolph, & Johnson, in information to the infant about her own con-
press). In addition, we assessed infants’ manual trol of an event while simultaneously generating
exploration skills by observing their spontane- multimodal information to inform developing
ous object manipulation in a controlled setting object perception skills. Coordinating visual
and obtained parental reports of the duration inspection with manual exploration seems
of infants’ sitting experience. We reasoned to be critical: Only the visual–manual skills
that infants who showed a greater tendency to involved in generating changes in object
58 OBJECTS AND SPACE

viewpoint—rotating, fingering, and transfer- oculomotor and manual action systems in spa-
ring while looking—were related to 3D object tial and 3D object completion, respectively, and
completion. learning by observation, evinced by the impor-
tance of associating views of fully visible and
partly occluded trajectories in spatiotemporal
SUMMARY AND CONCLUSIONS
completion. The potential role of learning fun-
I have described a set of object perception skills damental object concepts and their develop-
that develop early in infancy, focusing on three mental antecedents is becoming increasingly
ways in which observers fi ll in the gaps in per- clear from the experiments I have described in
ception imposed by occlusion: spatial comple- this chapter, in their suggestion that infants use
tion, spatiotemporal completion, and 3D object developing perceptual, cognitive, and action
completion. And I have described experiments systems to learn about the visual environment,
designed to examine developmental mecha- and to assemble its constituent parts into coher-
nisms of perceptual completion in infants. The ent wholes.
best evidence to date suggests that newborn
infants do not fi ll in the gaps in perception, and
therefore, do not perceive objects as do adults. ACKNOWLEDGMENT
Instead, the visual world of neonates seems to Preparation of this article was supported by NIH
consist solely of surface fragments that have no grants R01-HD40432 and R01-HD48733.
substance, volume, or continuity. Infants ini-
tially appear to process complex stimuli as sim-
ple isolated units, and subsequently integrate REFERENCES
them into higher-order patterns. Aguiar, A., & Baillargeon, R. (1999). 2.5-month-
This developmental progression is consistent old infants’ reasoning about when objects
with a constructivist view of cognitive devel- should and should not be occluded. Cognitive
opment, and consistent with developmental Psychology, 39, 116–157.
patterns in other domains, as described in the Amso, D., & Johnson, S. P. (2006). Learning by
remainder of the chapters in this book. A con- selection: Visual search and object perception
structivist view attempts to understand devel- in young infants. Developmental Psychology, 6,
opment in terms of information processing 1236–1245.
Baillargeon, R. (1995). A model of physical rea-
principles (Cohen & Cashon, 2006). According
soning in infancy. In C. Rovee-Collier & L.
to this approach, infants process information at
P. Lipsitt (Eds.), Advances in infancy research
the highest level of complexity possible, but this (Vol. 9, pp. 305–371). Norwood, NJ: Ablex.
level depends on the infant’s individual capac- Baillargeon, R. (2008). Innate ideas revisited: For a
ity and on task demands. Processing capac- principle of persistence in infants’ physical rea-
ity expands with development, which helps soning. Perspectives on Psychological Science,
to explain why older infants and children are 3, 2–13.
better able to see configurations and relations Baillargeon, R., Spelke, E. S., & Wasserman, S.
among parts, and it is constrained by task com- (1985). Object permanence in five-month-old
plexity, which helps to explain why perception of infants. Developmental Psychology, 20, 191–208.
intricate, multielement stimuli may break down Bower, T. G. R. (1967). Phenomenal identity and
form perception in an infant. Perception &
when perceptual systems become “overloaded”
Psychophysics, 2, 74–76.
(see the chapter by Cohen in this volume).
Bremner, J. G., Johnson, S. P., Slater, A., Mason, U.,
Each of the three kinds of filling-in I have Cheshire, A., & Spring, J. (2007). Conditions
described appears to proceed on a separate for young infants’ failure to perceive trajec-
developmental timetable with a unique set of tory continuity. Developmental Science, 10,
developmental mechanisms, yet they have in 613–624.
common a prominent role for learning: learn- Bremner, J. G., Johnson, S. P., Slater, A. M., Mason, U.,
ing by doing, evinced by the importance of Foster, K., Cheshire, A., et al. (2005). Conditions
PERCEPTUAL COMPLETION IN INFANCY 59

for young infants’ perception of object trajecto- pletion originates in information acquisition.
ries. Child Development, 74, 1029–1043. Developmental Psychology, 44, 1214–1224.
Burkhalter, A. (1993). Development of forward and Johnson, S. P., & Náñez, J. E. (1995). Young infants’
feedback connections between areas V1 and perception of object unity in two-dimensional
V2 of human visual cortex. Cerebral Cortex, 3, displays. Infant Behavior & Development, 18,
476–487. 133–143.
Burkhalter, A., Bernardo, K. L., & Charles, V. Johnson, S. P., Slemmer, J. A., & Amso, D. (2004).
(1993). Development of local circuits in human Where infants look determines how they see:
visual cortex. The Journal of Neuroscience, 13, Eye movements and object perception perfor-
1916–1931. mance in 3-month-olds. Infancy, 6, 185–201.
Clifton, R. K., Rochat, P., Litovsky, R. Y., & Perris, Kagan, J. (2008). In defense of qualitative changes
E. E. (1991). Object representation guides in development. Child Development, 79,
infants’ reaching in the dark. Journal of 1606–1624.
Experimental Psychology: Human Perception Kellman, P. J., & Arterberry, M. E. (1998). The cra-
and Performance, 17, 323–329. dle of knowledge: The development of perception
Cohen, L. B., & Cashon, C. H. (2006). Infant in infancy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
cognition. In D. Kuhn & R. S. Siegler (Eds.), Kellman, P. J., & Spelke, E. S. (1983). Perception
Handbook of child psychology: Vol. 2. Cognition, of partly occluded objects in infancy. Cognitive
perception, and language (6th ed., pp. 214–251). Psychology, 15, 483–524.
New York: Wiley. Moore, D. S., & Johnson, S. P. (2008). Mental
Gredebäck, G., & von Hofsten, C. (2004). Infants’ rotation in human infants: A sex difference.
evolving representations of object motion dur- Psychological Science, 19, 1063–1066.
ing occlusion: A longitudinal study of 6- to Munakata, Y. (2001). Graded representations in
12-month-old infants. Infancy, 6, 165–184. behavioral dissociations. Trends in Cognitive
Gredebäck, G., von Hofsten, C., & Boudreau, J. P. Sciences, 5, 309–315.
(2002). Infants’ visual tracking of continuous Peterhans, E., & von der Heydt, R. (1991).
circular motion under conditions of occlu- Subjective contours—bridging the gap between
sion and non-occlusion. Infant Behavior & psychophysics and physiology. Trends in Neuro-
Development, 25, 161–182. sciences, 3, 112–119.
Haith, M. M. (1998). Who put the cog in infant Piaget, J. (1954). The construction of reality in
cognition? Is rich interpretation too costly? the child (M. Cook, Trans.). New York: Basic
Infant Behavior & Development, 21, 167–179. Books. (Original work published 1937).
Johnson, S. P. (2004). Development of perceptual Piaget, J., & Inhelder, B. (1956). The child’s concep-
completion in infancy. Psychological Science, tion of space. New York: Routledge. (Original
15, 769–775. work published 1948).
Johnson, S. P., Amso, D., & Slemmer, J. A. (2003). Quinn, P. C., & Liben, L. S. (2008). A sex differ-
Development of object concepts in infancy: ence in mental rotation in young infants.
Evidence for early learning in an eye tracking Psychological Science, 19, 1067–1070.
paradigm. Proceedings of the National Academy Rochat, P., & Goubet, N. (1995). Development of sit-
of Sciences, USA, 100, 10568–10573. ting and reaching in 5- to 6-month-old infants.
Johnson, S. P., & Aslin, R. N. (1995). Perception Infant Behavior & Development, 18, 53–68.
of object unity in 2-month-old infants. Rosander, K., & von Hofsten, C. (2004). Infants’
Developmental Psychology, 31, 739–745. emerging ability to represent occluded object
Johnson, S. P., & Aslin, R. N. (1996). Perception motion. Cognition, 91, 1–22.
of object unity in young infants: The roles of Shepard, R. N., & Metzler, J. (1971). Mental rota-
motion, depth, and orientation. Cognitive tion of three-dimensional objects. Science, 171,
Development, 11, 161–180. 701–703.
Johnson, S. P., Bremner, J. G., Slater, A., Mason, Slater, A. (1995). Visual perception and memory
U., Foster, K., & Cheshire, A. (2003). Infants’ at birth. In C. Rovee-Collier & L. P. Lipsitt
perception of object trajectories. Child (Eds.), Advances in infancy research (Vol. 9, pp.
Development, 74, 94–108. 107–162). Norwood, NJ: Ablex.
Johnson, S. P., Davidow, J., Hall-Haro, C., & Frank, Slater, A., Johnson, S. P., Brown, E., & Badenoch,
M. C. (2008). Development of perceptual com- M. (1996). Newborn infants’ perception of
60 OBJECTS AND SPACE

partly occluded objects. Infant Behavior & Spelke, E. S. (1990). Principles of object percep-
Development, 19, 145–148. tion. Cognitive Science, 14, 29–56.
Slater, A., Johnson, S. P., Kellman, P. J., & Spelke, E. S. Spelke, E. S., Breinlinger, K., Macomber, J., &
(1994). The role of three-dimensional depth cues Jacobson, K. (1992). Origins of knowledge.
in infants’ perception of partly occluded objects. Psychological Review, 99, 605–632.
Early Development and Parenting, 3, 187–191. Valenza, E., Leo, I., Gava, L., & Simion, F. (2006).
Slater, A., Morison, V., Somers, M., Mattock, A., Perceptual completion in newborn human
Brown, E., & Taylor, D. (1990). Newborn and older infants. Child Development, 77, 1810–1821.
infants’ perception of partly occluded objects. von Hofsten, C., Kochukhova, O., & Rosander, K.
Infant Behavior & Development, 13, 33–49. (2007). Predictive tracking over occlusions in
Soska, K. C., Adolph, K. A., & Johnson, S. P. (in 4-month-old infants. Developmental Science,
press). Systems in development: Motor skill 10, 625–640.
acquisition facilitates 3D object completion. von Hofsten, C., Vishton, P., Spelke, E. S., Feng,
Developmental Psychology. Q., & Rosander, K. (1998). Predictive action
Soska, K. C., & Johnson, S. P. (2008a). Development in infancy: Tracking and reaching for moving
of 3D object completion in infancy. Child objects. Cognition, 67, 255–285.
Development, 79, 1230–1236. Zacks, J. M. (2008). Neuroimaging studies of
Soska, K. C., & Johnson, S. P. (2008b). Infants’ mental rotation: A meta-analysis and review.
3D object completion in complex displays. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 20, 1–19.
Manuscript in preparation.
CHAP TER 4
Numerical Identity and the Development
of Object Permanence

M. Keith Moore and Andrew N. Meltzoff

described the curious fact that young infants


INTRODUCTION
would not search for a highly desired object
Numerical identity refers to an object being the when it was hidden. For Piaget, a central task for
selfsame individual over time. Our principal infants was to extract an independent, enduring
way of knowing an object’s numerical identity concept of objects from the infants’ sensorimo-
is by tracing its spatial history. This is how we tor experience with them. Piaget’s first key theo-
find “our” Coke can on a table full of Coke cans retical assumption was the primacy of the role of
that all look alike. Numerical identity allows us action. In early infancy, to “know” an object was
to construe the changes in an object’s appear- to act upon it. Development derived from relat-
ance, location, motion, orientation, and visibil- ing actions to one another and to consequences
ity, as different manifestations of a single object in the perceptual world (sensory–motor con-
rather than as many objects. It enables us to dif- nections). The second key assumption was that
ferentiate an encounter with a new object from a lack of sensory contact, especially invisibil-
a reencounter with the same one again. In this ity, was an insurmountable problem for young
chapter, we propose that infants’ developing infants. When sensory contact with objects was
understanding of numerical identity underlies lost, objects ceased to exist for the infant (“out of
their discovery of object permanence. We also sight is out of mind”). The development of rep-
suggest a mechanism for developmental change resentation around 18 months of age was pos-
that derives from this view. tulated as the way infants transcended a purely
Object permanence refers to the fact that sensorimotor world to realize that objects were
material objects are preserved over breaks in permanent over all occlusion events. An object
perceptual contact. When an occluder moves was not deemed to be fully independent of per-
in front of an object, adults understand that the ception and action, and thus permanent, until
occluder blocks visual access to it. They know infants could represent the invisible movements
that the object still exists in a specific location of an object that was stationary when it was
in the world for every moment it is occluded. occluded, an invisible displacement in Piaget’s
This understanding is what we mean when we terms, at 18–24 months of age. His age-ordered
say that objects are permanent over occlusion search tasks were seen as measures of progress
events. Thus conceived, object permanence pro- toward that end (see Table 4.1).
vides a powerful tool for extracting structural Many studies have replicated Piaget’s stages
regularity from experience. of search for hidden objects. Yet, modern empir-
Psychologists have been fascinated by infant ical research has largely undermined his key
object permanence ever since Piaget (1954) theoretical assumptions. We are left then with

61
62 OBJECTS AND SPACE

Table 4.1 Summary of Piaget’s Stages of Object Permanence Development

Stage Age Sensorimotor Level Object Permanence Manual Search


(months) Behavior
1 0–1 Reflex repetition None None
2 1–4 Reflexes are coordinated Search is only an extension None
by action on a of current action; visual
common O tracking
3 4–8 Action is differentiated Manual acts on part to Finds partially hidden
from its result; acts to conserve visible whole O O, but not one totally
prolong the result hidden
4 8–12 Actions can be O’s existence is dependent Finds totally hidden O
coordinated to on the last action on O in one location, but
achieve results; returns there if O
means–ends acts is hidden in a new
location (the A-not-B
error)
5 12–18 Explores all variations O’s existence depends on Finds O where last
of a new means act prior perception, but not displaced visibly, but
discovered by chance prior action not if moved invisibly
6 18–24 Representation allows O is independent of action Finds O after invisible
invention of new and perception because displacement from its
means; hidden causes represented last visible location
Note. O indicates object.

the puzzle of his ordered sequence in infants’


Identity Development Account’s Relation
manual search for hidden objects. A compre-
to Other Theoretical Positions
hensive theory of object permanence should
explain the development of manual search for Several strands of contemporary research,
occluded objects and the invariant ordering of including ours, have been influenced by
these steps. Bower’s (1967, 1971) assertion that infants’
Here we offer a solution to this puzzle that notion of object identity influences their
does not rely on Piagetian theory. In our view, behavior. Studies building on this insight have
the fundamental issue of object permanence explored how infants individuate different
is how infants use the visible transformations objects to determine how many are involved
of their perceptual world, such as an object’s in a visual event (e.g., two objects seen simul-
occlusion and disocclusion, to develop an taneously in different locations are different
understanding of an invisible world that links objects; Wilcox & Baillargeon, 1998; Xu &
these visible events. The infant’s primary data Carey, 1996). Leslie and colleagues (e.g., Leslie,
are their encounters with objects disappearing Xu, Tremoulet, & Scholl, 1998) demonstrated
and reappearing, which immediately poses a that object identification (i.e., distinguishing
question about numerical identity. Thus, we which objects are involved in an event) is a
propose that the origins and development of related but more difficult task than individu-
object permanence are preceded by develop- ation (for a review, see Krøjgaard, 2004). Still
ment in infants’ understanding of how to deter- another strand of research on object identity
mine and trace numerical identity. We call this has focused on how infants determine that the
view the identity development (ID) account of object before them is the same unique individ-
object permanence (Moore & Meltzoff, 1999). ual that they encountered previously—that it
NUMERICAL IDENTITY AND THE DEVELOPMENT OF OBJECT PERMANENCE 63

is the same one again (e.g., Moore, Borton, & a disappearance–reappearance unless they
Darby, 1978; Moore & Meltzoff, 1978). In this got the same object back. The permanence
strand, infants’ notions of numerical identity judgment depends on identity. Conversely, an
are said to develop and change as they experi- adult does not interpret such an event as two
ence objects in the world. encounters with the same object unless it con-
tinued to exist between encounters. The iden-
Structure of the Argument tity judgment depends on permanence. We
As required of all developmental theories, the hypothesize that as infants begin to under-
ID account has the burden of specifying (a) the stand permanence, it is only understood for
foundational primitives underlying the earli- certain kinds of disappearances and not oth-
est notions of object identity, (b) the principles ers. We capture this by saying that permanence
that determine the course of successive develop- is constrained to the kinds of disappearance
ments, and (c) a mechanism of change account- events that the infant can construe as preserv-
ing for how the transition from having no ing the numerical identity of the object. Thus,
concept of permanence to having permanence permanence depends on identity, but not the
occurs. This is a substantial challenge, and few other way round.
developmental theories have met it. In our view, the infants’ prepermanence
We turn first to the theoretical assump- world is stranger still. They can determine
tions and hypotheses of the ID account, and object identity but do not treat objects as per-
then take up the empirical methods needed to manent. To illustrate this by analogy, infants’
test it using manual search, and new evidence unusual cognitive representation of their prep-
obtained with such methods. We then propose a ermanence world would be like projecting an
detailed mechanism of change for the transition adult’s 3-D perceptual world onto a 2-D TV
from treating occluded objects as impermanent screen. All of the interactions of objects would
to treating them as permanent. We conclude by be visible because there are no invisible dimen-
evaluating four theories of object permanence: sions. Objects disappear at edges by deletion
Piagetian, dynamical systems, nativist, and the and reappear by accretion; there is no image
ID account. overlap, so nothing is hidden. In this 2-D
world, an individual image can be reidenti-
fied after absences on the basis of its place or
THEORETICAL UNDERPINNINGS OF THE
trajectory of motion, without requiring that it
IDENTITY DEVELOPMENT ACCOUNT
be somewhere between appearances. It is spa-
The ID account utilizes three theoretical terms tiotemporally the same image, but it does not
that are often conflated—representation, iden- exist constantly, because there is nowhere for it
tity, and permanence. We wish to differenti- to exist out of sight.
ate them and show the resulting implications
for describing infants’ understanding of object Identity and Representation
permanence. A second assumption of the ID account is that
the infant representational system can relate a
Identity and Permanence
currently perceived object to a stored represen-
The fi rst fundamental assumption of the ID tation of that object. Identity criteria provide a
account, and one that cannot be overstressed, means of linking the currently perceived object
is that the infant’s notion of the relation to its previously formed representation (i.e.,
between permanence and numerical iden- the criteria describing the object representa-
tity is radically different from that of adults. tion match the criteria of the perceived object).
For adults, permanence entails identity, and We have argued that infants have such a rep-
identity entails permanence. Adults do not resentational system from birth, and that it is
interpret an object as being permanent over sufficient to maintain the numerical identity
64 OBJECTS AND SPACE

of visible objects participating in events with as described by philosophers (e.g., Strawson,


visible outcomes in a steady-state world—for 1959). The primary way of knowing that an
example, reidentifying objects after looking object at one point in time is numerically iden-
away from them—and enabling infants to tical to an object perceived at another point in
learn to predict object appearances after dis- time is by tracing the object’s spatiotemporal
appearances (for details, see Meltzoff & Moore, history between these points of contact: If it is in
1998). the right place in space at the right time when-
ever it is seen, it is numerically the same object.
Representation and Permanence The psychological reality of this analysis has
been demonstrated by the use of spatiotemporal
Another tenet of the ID account is that a
coordinates to address “object fi les” in studies of
further change in the representational system
adult attention (Kahneman, Treisman, & Gibbs,
is needed to account for permanence. Object
1992; Treisman, 1992) and object identity and
permanence, as we defi ne it, is not simply
indexing in infants (Bower, 1982; Carey & Xu,
maintaining a representation in mind, no mat-
2001; Leslie et al., 1998).
ter how long it lasts. Nor, is it reidentifying the
2. Infants are innately prepared for a
object as the same one again after it disappears
Newtonian world operating according to the
and then reappears. Object permanence is the
first law of kinematics: Objects at rest remain
understanding that an individual object, while
at rest; objects in motion continue in motion.
it is still invisible, continues to exist in a hid-
Infants are evolutionarily prepared for inter-
den location in the external world. To encom-
acting with objects in a Newtonian steady-state
pass permanence, the representational system
world, and the fi rst spatiotemporal distinction
has to link the representation of the object and
is whether the object is at rest or in motion. The
the representation of its location, while neither
spatiotemporal parameters that capture this
object nor location is currently visible. When
distinction are its place in space for a station-
this is achieved, the infant can be said to know
ary object or its trajectory of motion for a mov-
where the object is while it is out of sight. Such
ing object. Neuroscientists have shown that
understanding is necessary to support inten-
the location of objects in space and their tra-
tional, permanence-directed search for an
jectories of motion can be established by per-
occluded object.
ceptual processing (Haxby et al., 1991; Köhler,
Kapur, Moscovitch, Winocur, & Houle, 1995;
IDENTITY DEVELOPMENT ACCOUNT Watamaniuk & McKee, 1995; Watamaniuk,
McKee, & Grzywacz, 1995).
In this section, we elucidate a series of 10 To be “evolutionarily prepared” does not
interlocking hypotheses that comprise the ID mean that infants are born with an adult-like
account. The series describes the development notion of trajectory, for example, but rather
and interrelationship of infants’ notions of that they are predisposed to detect a trajectory
identity and permanence over the first 2 years of visual motion—the constant movement of a
of life. Because they are hypotheses, we cite rel- visual feature in a particular direction—from a
evant evidence where available. Finally, we pro- background of random-direction noise. These
pose a theoretically appropriate way to describe “trajectory detectors” are thought to be higher-
occlusion events. level units in the visual system extracting coher-
ent signals in space and time from lower-level
Identity and Permanence Development:
motion detectors (Grzywacz, Watamaniuk, &
10 Hypotheses
McKee, 1995). Such evolutionary preparedness
1. The fundamental criteria for numerical underlies the development of smooth pursuit
identity are spatiotemporal parameters. This idea visual tracking, the perception of object tra-
draws on “quantitative” or “numerical” identity jectories, and their representation (Aslin, 1981;
NUMERICAL IDENTITY AND THE DEVELOPMENT OF OBJECT PERMANENCE 65

Bremner et al., 2005; Johnson, Bremner et al., object properties are preserved over events (so
2003).1 long as the object can be construed as the same
3. The spatiotemporal parameters of an object’s one—i.e., in the same place or on the same tra-
place and/or trajectory act as identity criteria, jectory). Initially, an object’s properties play
allowing the object to be identified as the same one no role in judgments of numerical identity (#3
again after breaks in perceptual contact. The earli- above). Thus, the utility of object properties to
est identity logic used by infants is that a station- confirm or disconfirm numerical identity is
ary object encountered in the same place as one learned (although there is some disagreement
seen previously in that place is the same object over the age at which this learning occurs, see:
again. Similarly, a moving object encountered on Krøjgaard, 2007; Van de Walle et al., 2000).
the same trajectory of motion as one seen previ- 5. Young infants use the spatiotemporal
ously on that trajectory is the same object again. parameters to reidentify an object as the numeri-
Spatiotemporal parameters initially override cally same individual over a disappearance–
featural appearance in judgments of numeri- reappearance event, without implying that the
cal identity. Young infants do not treat a pre- to object was located anywhere in the external world
postdisappearance change of object features as during the period of occlusion. Initially, infants
specifying a different object as long as the altered are using the spatiotemporal parameters to iden-
object reappears in the place or on the trajectory tify individual objects over changes in the visible
established by their first encounter with it (Bower, world, and even to anticipate where the same
Broughton, & Moore, 1971; Krøjgaard, 2007; one is likely to be seen again (e.g., extrapolating
Newcombe, Huttenlocher, & Learmonth, 1999; an object’s visible trajectory across an occluder
Van de Walle, Carey, & Prevor, 2000; Wilcox & to anticipate its next appearance in the visible
Baillargeon, 1998; Xu & Carey, 1996). world). These spatiotemporal identity criteria
4. Experience from repeated encounters with provide an overarching structure, allowing young
visible objects allows infants to learn which infants to extract predictable regularities from
visible events. However, unlike adults, the crite-
1
A trajectory of motion can be described as a vec- ria do not specify the object’s location while it is
tor specifying direction and speed. As an example of invisible, which is consistent with young infants’
the predisposition to detect trajectories, 4-month-old
infants visually extrapolated the left to right order in the failure to search for occluded objects (Meltzoff
sequential illumination of a linear array of lights into the & Moore, 1998). There is broad consensus for
space beyond the array. Th is occurred even though there such failure before 8 or 9 months of age, despite
was no “object” in motion and the pattern of illumina-
tion did not continue in that direction (Haith, Kessen, &
infants’ ability to anticipate reappearances.
Collins, 1969). A broad range of infant behavior is con- 6. Object permanence is the understanding
sonant with the idea that a notion of trajectory underlies that a particular object continues to exist in an
it: The prospective control of head tracking and reach-
ing for visibly moving objects (von Hofsten, Vishton, invisible location or on an invisible trajectory in
Spelke, Feng, & Rosander, 1998); learning to extrapolate the external world during the period of occlu-
the trajectory of a moving object across an occluder to sion or break in perceptual contact—while it is
predict its reappearance (Johnson, Amso, & Slemmer,
2003; Rosander & von Hofsten, 2004); the facilitation of still invisible. Permanence refers to a state of
predictive tracking over occlusions by unoccluded tra- affairs that is beyond the infant’s perception. It
jectory experience, and subsequent generalization to a is the basis for infants’ prediction of an object’s
new trajectory direction (Johnson, Amso, et al., 2003);
and adjusting the time of an object’s expected appear- occluded location after disappearance and
ance over varying occluder widths by the trajectory’s during the time when it is still invisible. Such
velocity (von Hofsten, Kochukhova, & Rossander, 2007). predictions about the object’s location while it
Conversely, when a constant velocity is not maintained,
reappearances are not predicted (e.g., if the object is cannot be seen provide the goals for infants’
decelerating as it disappears; Rosander & von Hofsten, intentional search acts and are the hallmarks of
2004) and overtrial learning to do so does not occur permanence-governed search.
(e.g., if the object moves constantly while behind an
occluder on some trials and delays behind it on others; 7. Object permanence develops from numeri-
Bertenthal, Longo, & Kenny, 2007). cal identity. An infant must be able to construe
66 OBJECTS AND SPACE

the disappearance and reappearance of an object 8. Initially, object permanence understand-


as involving a single individual, a numerical ing is an interpretation infants make of observed
identity, before the answer to where the object physical events that satisfy two conditions: the
was located during the period of occlusion can object participating in an occlusion event is iden-
be obtained. Unless numerical identity can be tified as a single individual, and both the object
established, objects appearing after an occlusion and its occluded location can be independently
are new and different ones, rather than reap- represented. Permanence understanding unites
pearances of the same one again. And, if new the object and its hidden location by an interpre-
and different objects are popping into view after tation of the occlusion event—a deduction based
occlusions, the question of what happens to a on the occlusion—that links the now-hidden
single object between appearances, while it is but represented object with the now-hidden but
invisible, never arises and could not be learned represented location. This is the representational
“from experience.” Numerical identity renders basis for infants’ knowing where that particular
this problem solvable. object is after it disappears. We hypothesize that
Disappearance events can be described in development proceeds by infants at first reinter-
spatiotemporal terms relevant to numerical preting the event after the reappearance of the
identity as the places and trajectories of objects object—“the same object was there before it
and their occluders over the time course of an reappeared”—and only with further experience
occlusion. Rather than describe disappearances is the interpretation prompted by the occlusion
in terms of the recovery actions needed for event itself.
search (as Piagetian theory did), the ID account 9. Once objects as wholes are interpreted as
describes them in terms of the places and trajec- permanent over a particular class of disappear-
tories of all the objects involved. For example, ance events (a disappearance transform), further
“a stationary object’s occlusion in place by the experience with that same transformation allows
movement of an occluder” specifies one type of infants to learn which object properties are also
disappearance transform and implies that the preserved over that disappearance transform.
object can be reidentified as the same one again This learning process is parallel to the one in
by its place of disappearance—reappearance hypothesis #4 above except that now it is based
(Moore & Meltzoff, 1999). on the object’s permanence over the disappear-
Since the spatiotemporal parameters serve as ance transform, and the preserved properties
criteria for reidentifying the reappearing object are taken to be permanent properties of the
as the same one again (see #5 above), the nature object in its occluded state.
and development of these spatiotemporal Infant cognition is conservative. Infants
parameters for numerical identity provide the do not assume that all properties of a predis-
skeleton underlying permanence development. appearance object are preserved in that same
In other words, the age ordering of disappear- object postdisappearance. Conservation of the
ance transforms over which infants treat objects whole has priority, and initially infants accept
as permanent depends on the order of disap- a reappearing object satisfying the spatiotem-
pearance transforms for which the numerical poral identity criteria regardless of its visual
identity of an object can be maintained. When features or function. They then learn that some
infants can understand a disappearance trans- properties, such as orientation and perspective,
form as one in which “the same object has come often are not preserved over occlusions; and that
back,” they can then use subsequent experience others, such as shape and functional properties
to learn that the object is permanent over this like sound, usually are (referred to here as the
disappearance transform. Thus, we say infants’ object’s “distinctive features and functions”).
understanding of permanence is dependent on 10. Once some object features and functions
the type of disappearance transform involved, are also known to be permanent over a par-
or “permanence is transformationally depen- ticular disappearance transform, they can play
dent knowledge.” an independent role in determining an object’s
NUMERICAL IDENTITY AND THE DEVELOPMENT OF OBJECT PERMANENCE 67

numerical identity for that transformation. serves as a fi lter, separating out disappearance
Object features and functions that are perma- transitions that destroy the object (e.g., implo-
nent over a particular transform allow infants sions, dissolutions, instantaneous disappear-
to use three identity criteria—spatiotemporal, ances, etc.) from ones that do not. Only events
featural, and functional—to determine numeri- that survive this fi ltering engage the next two
cal identity. Now infants do not have to accept a components and feed into infants’ determina-
featurally or functionally different object as the tion of identity and permanence.
same one again just because its reappearance (b) Degree of object occlusion. The degree of
satisfies the spatiotemporal identity criteria. For object occlusion refers to the extent of occlu-
example, an object reappearing in the expected sion—that is, how much of the whole object is
place with the wrong (unexpected) features or occluded (totally, partially, or not obscured at
functions given the disappearance transform all; Moore & Meltzoff, 2008).
could lead to further search for the original (c) The disappearance transform. Both
object. Similarly, if an object was moved to a descriptions of the Michottean transition and
new location when infants were not watching, the degree of occlusion apply to disappearance
they can weigh whether the identity of the one transforms, but a transform is not reducible to
they see is the same as the one that disappeared them. As we define the term, the “disappear-
(because it looks the same but is in the wrong ance transform” describes the spatiotemporal
place). The answer is not completely determined arrangement of object(s) and occluder(s) over
by its location, all three of the identity criteria the entire course of the occlusion event (e.g.,
can be taken into account in decision-making. the occlusion of a stationary object in place by
the movement of an occluder). A disappearance
Describing an Occlusion Event transform refers to a class of equivalent events;
An occlusion event can be characterized by they are spatiotemporally equivalent. Thus, any
three components, all of which bear on per- total occlusion of a stationary object in place by
manence understanding: (a) the psychophysics the movement of an occluder is the same disap-
of the transition to invisibility, (b) the degree pearance transform—the objects, locations, and
of object occlusion, and (c) the type of disap- occluders can all vary. This means that many
pearance transform. All three components are events, which are different on the surface, can
incorporated in the ID account. be grouped as the same abstract disappearance
transform. In the ID view, it should not matter
(a) Psychophysics of transition: Michottean to infants whether a cloth covers a stationary
disappearance events. Different types of visual object or a vertical barrier is placed in front of
events are specified psychophysically by the it—both are occlusions of a stationary object in
nature of the transition to invisibility (Michotte, place.
1962) and have been shown to differentially
affect looking, sucking, predictive tracking,
REQUIREMENTS FOR TESTING A STRONG
and electroencephalogram (EEG) responses
FORM OF OBJECT PERMANENCE
in young infants (e.g., Bertenthal, Longo, &
Kenny, 2007; Bower, 1967; Kaufman, Csibra, Testing the ID account of infants’ object perma-
& Johnson, 2005). For example, a progressive nence development presents two major empiri-
deletion of the visible portion of an object at an cal challenges. Object permanence refers to
edge is a necessary, though not always sufficient, infants’ understanding of a postocclusion state
condition to perceptually specify that the object of affairs. The first challenge is how to assure
slipped behind/under the edge during the tran- that infants’ search acts are actually launched
sition, and has not been destroyed by the disap- on the basis of the object in its occluded state,
pearance (Bremner et al., 2007; Gibson, Kaplan, rather than on some other basis. We call this the
Reynolds, & Wheeler, 1969). In the ID account, “occluded object standard.” The second chal-
this innate, Michottean perceptual mechanism lenge is how to assess whether infants represent
68 OBJECTS AND SPACE

the object in a specific, invisible location. We In short, if infants’ search acts are initiated
call this the “invisible location standard.” The after the object is fully occluded, and if infants
point of this section is to provide the logic of an are looking to where the object should reappear
empirical method that can meet both standards as a consequence of their acts, before the object
and why it is necessary to adopt these safeguards is visible, then such acts are valid evidence of
in order to be sure one is tapping infants’ object object permanence. Permanence measured this
permanence understanding rather than some way is called the strong form of object perma-
lower-order action. nence for clarity, because it meets both stan-
dards. These more rigorous requirements lead
Occluded Object Standard to slightly more conservative age estimates than
In order to force infants to act off of their repre- studies that use “occluder removal” alone as a
sentation of the occluded object while it is invis- direct measure of permanence. We believe that
ible, we hide the object while it is out of reach. these precautions allow a more valid measure of
Infants are thus prevented from initiating search infants’ object permanence understanding, and
until after the occlusion is complete and they will use them in assessing the ID account.
are brought back within reach. This procedure
protects against one kind of artifact—continua- EMPIRICAL EVIDENCE
tions of search action already in progress before
the disappearance is complete. From that point Of the 10 ID account hypotheses, those num-
on, any action taken toward the hidden object bered 1–4 have substantial empirical support.
would have to be governed by their representa- There is less evidence bearing on hypotheses
tion of the object in its occluded state. 5–10, because few studies have assessed the
There are other potential artifacts that must strong form of object permanence until recently.
also be prevented: (a) acts based on prior prac- We turn now to consider such evidence.
tice with occluder removal in the test situa-
tion (e.g., extensive warm-up trials in a study); Is a Strong Form of Object Permanence
(b) acts based on clues from the experimenter Needed to Account for Search Behavior
such as drawing attention to an occluder by in Infancy?
“touching it last” (Diamond, Cruttenden, & Studies of object permanence, whether using
Neiderman, 1994; Smith, Thelen, Titzer, & visual habituation or manual search methods,
McLin, 1999); or (c) acts based on contingen- are typically conducted within one spatial set-
cies set up by the experimenter accidentally or ting and the infant situated in one position
by training (e.g. continued testing after chance within it. Thus, an object’s permanence may
success has uncovered the object in a particu- be put in doubt by an occlusion, but perma-
lar place). Search based on any of these do not nence of the spatial setting is preserved through
meet the occluded object standard because it unbroken perceptual contact. Many other cir-
need not be based on the object’s disappearance cumstances in infants’ lives lead to an object’s
(Moore & Meltzoff, 2008). disappearance where the setting is changed
before they ever see it reappear or get an oppor-
Invisible Location Standard
tunity to act. Infants are removed from the set-
Under the conditions above, correct manual ting, they go to sleep, they travel, and objects
search coupled with spatially directed visual are moved to new settings unobserved by them.
anticipation of the object’s reappearance locus Obviously, the adult notion of permanent
is evidence about where infants think the object objects is rich enough to encompass these situ-
is located while it is out of sight. Such behavior ations. For the adult, absent objects continue to
implies that the location of the object is repre- exist in hidden locations after all forms of per-
sented while both the object and its location are ceptual contact with the original setting have
occluded. been severed. And, if another agent has moved
NUMERICAL IDENTITY AND THE DEVELOPMENT OF OBJECT PERMANENCE 69

the objects, the adult believes they continue to object was in the hiding place on day 2, so no
exist in some new location. Do infants view the infants found it there. When the original object
world in this way? Most studies of object per- was later shown in the middle of the room to
manence, regardless of method, are silent on infants who had seen it hidden on day 1, they
this fundamental point. engaged in “verifying search.” They went across
In a recent study, 14-month-old infants the room to the hiding place and looked inside,
watched an object being hidden, left the test even though the object was in full view (Moore
environment, and returned 24 h later. The results & Meltzoff, 2004). Despite the fact that the fea-
showed that when they were brought back to tures and functions of the visible object matched
the same room the next day, they searched suc- the one they saw hidden, they checked in the
cessfully (Moore & Meltzoff, 2004). This test hiding place before playing with it. Our inter-
satisfies both standards for strong object per- pretation of this behavior is that the 14-month-
manence. Successful search under these condi- olds were searching the disappearance place
tions shows that in addition to representing the to verify that the original object was not there.
object, a representation of the hiding place was This would help them determine if the visible
also set up at the disappearance event (concor- object was the numerically correct individual
dant with hypothesis # 8). For at least one basic or merely one that looked and acted like it. This
disappearance transform, “the occlusion of an behavior supports hypothesis # 10 on the inter-
object in place,” 14-month-olds’ search after a play of the three identity criteria, because the
24-h break suggests that the object’s existence object’s features and functions were sufficient
in the world is not dependent on maintaining to tentatively identify it (as the same one), and
any kind of perceptual contact with the disap- the spatiotemporal information (the place of its
pearance locale. expected reappearance) was used to confirm or
disconfirm that provisional identity.
Does Numerical Identity Play a Role
Taken together, the room-change results
in This Strong Form of Infant Object
and the verifying search behavior suggest that
Permanence?
these infants were seeking, in the same hiding
The ID account holds that the aim of infants’ place, within the same disappearance locale,
permanence-governed search is to recover the selfsame object that they saw hidden on day
exactly the same object that disappeared. 1. Violating the global spatiotemporal criterion
Leaving the locale of an object’s disappear- for the identity of a stationary object (the room)
ance and returning after 24 h poses a ques- led to no search at all if it was the wrong locale.
tion of numerical identity. If one returns to the Violating the local spatiotemporal criterion (the
same locale, the object hidden on day 1 could place in the room) led to verifying search if the
be found here; but, if this is a different locale, object was in the wrong place within the cor-
then the expectation should be that the origi- rect global locale. The role of numerical identity
nal object could not be found here. To test this in object permanence understanding provides
idea, we instituted a “room change” condition. an explanatory concept for both behavior
The findings were that the 14-month-old infants patterns.
in the room-change group did not search while
Is a Strong Form of Object Permanence
the same-room infants searched successfully
Present from Birth?
(Moore & Meltzoff, 2004). This result com-
ports with the idea that infants were seeking If the strong form of object permanence is pres-
the original object and supports hypothesis # 7 ent at some time during infancy, is it present at
that numerical identity underlies permanence- all times? The classic argument has been that
governed search. attempts to answer this question using man-
A new behavior was also discovered that ual search tend to underestimate competence
points up the importance of numerical identity because of “performance constraints” (e.g.,
to object permanence. In these experiments, no Baillargeon, Graber, DeVos, & Black, 1990).
70 OBJECTS AND SPACE

A recent study investigated whether four com- 8.75- and 10-month-old infants, there were no
monly cited performance constraints presumed differences in search success whether the object
to limit infant search actually caused failures: was behind an occluder or under an occluder:
motor skills, means–ends coordination, spatial The younger infants failed even when the object
understanding, and memory span (Moore & was behind an upright occluder (Moore &
Meltzoff, 2008). Meltzoff, 2008).
A new partial occlusion task was used to Another commonly cited performance con-
assess whether 8.75-month-old infants had straint for young infants concerns memory. If
the means–ends coordination and motor skills the memory span required by a total occlusion
needed to remove an occluder (see also Johnson, were too great, infants might forget the object
this volume, for more on partial occlusions). In before they could search (Diamond, 1985;
the standard Piagetian task, the visible part Harris, 1987). This limitation was addressed
extends toward the infants, and they typically by hiding an object that emitted a continuous
pull on the visible part because it is close and sound to prevent forgetting. Even with this
easy to reach. In the new task, the object’s vis- memory aid, 8.75-month-olds did not succeed.
ible part projected laterally from the occluder, Older infants were also tested. The introduction
so both part and occluder were equally avail- of the sounding object more than doubled the
able. The first question was whether the infants success rate for the 10-month-olds, but it did
would recover the object by removing the not help the younger infants (Moore & Meltzoff,
occluder. If infants do this, their lift ing or dis- 2008, Experiment 2).
placing of the occluder demonstrates the same In sum, these fi ndings show that infants at
motor and means–ends skills needed to remove 8.75 months of age possess the requisite skills
it on total occlusions. The next question was to search for the hidden object. But they did
whether the infants who removed the occluder not search. Taken together, with the fact that
on partial occlusions also removed it on total 14-month-olds demonstrate the strong form
occlusions, as would be expected if they under- of object permanence for this same disap-
stood permanence. The fi ndings showed they pearance transform, we infer that a notion of
did not: Fully half of the 32 8.75-month-old permanence begins to develop between 8.75
infants tested had the requisite skills, but only and 10 months of age and is quite robust by 14
two used them to remove the occluder from a months.
totally hidden object (Moore & Meltzoff, 2008,
If Object Permanence Develops, Is the
Experiment 1).
Change Once and for All or a Series
If motor skills and means–ends coordina-
of Steps?
tion were not the limiting factors, what was
the impediment? Bower (1982) has argued that In the work discussed thus far, only the degree
a source of difficulty is the spatial relationship of the object’s occlusion has been manipulat-
between an occluder and the object it occludes. ed—partial hidings are easier to solve than total
He predicted that when some distance separates hidings. On the ID account, however, changes
a stationary object and a totally occluding verti- in the type of disappearance transform should
cal screen, the object is perceived as behind the also affect search success even when the degree
occluder. However, if there is no spatial separa- of occlusion is exactly the same. A study test-
tion between object and occluder (e.g., under ing this idea compared two types of total occlu-
cloths or inside cups), the search task is more sions in which the same object was hidden in
difficult, because the occluder appears to be the same place behind the same screen (Moore
taking the place of the object rather than hiding & Meltzoff, 1999). If infants solved one task but
it during the disappearance event. Therefore, not the other, this task differentiation could
he argued that using cloth occluders would not be attributed to the types of performance
underestimate infants’ understanding of object constraints previously mentioned, because
permanence. When we tested this idea with the same search response to the same totally
NUMERICAL IDENTITY AND THE DEVELOPMENT OF OBJECT PERMANENCE 71

Occlusion-on-a-carrier
Occlusion-in-place to-a-place

Figure 4.1 Two types of disappearance transforms. The left column depicts occlusion-in-place and
the right column depicts occlusion-on-a-carrier-to-a-place. Occlusion-in-place begins with the exper-
imenter carrying the object to a place on the table next to the folded cloth and depositing it there. The
occlusion occurs by unfolding the cloth over the object. The experimenter’s hand then returns to the
starting point in the center of the table. Occlusion-on-a-carrier-to-a-place begins with the experi-
menter carrying the object toward the cloth. The occlusion occurs as the object goes under the cloth;
it is then deposited on the table. The experimenter’s hand returns to the starting point in the center of
the table. Adapted from Moore & Meltzoff (1999).

occluded object, in the same spatial location Identity Development Interpretation of the
was needed in both (Figure 4.1). In one occlu- Empirical Data
sion, a stationary object in place on the table
On the ID account, the occlusion-in-place is a
was totally hidden by the movement of a screen.
total disappearance of an object at rest on the
In the other, the object was carried under the
table by the movement of a cloth occluder. In
stationary screen by hand, occluding it on the
an occlusion-on-a-carrier-to-place, an object at
carrier/hand, and deposited on the table; then
rest on the carrier is moved under the cloth. At
the carrier emerged empty.
this point in the occlusion-on-a-carrier, both
Th ree age groups were tested and the occlu-
tasks occlude an object that is at rest relative to
sion-in-place was significantly easier than
the surface it is on (table or carrier). For both,
the occlusion-on-a-carrier-to-a-place at 10
the object would be identified by the spatiotem-
and 12 months of age; only the 14-month-old
poral criterion of place of disappearance and
group was equally successful on both tasks.
expected to reappear there. For infants who
Even though a majority of the younger infants
understand permanence for the occlusion-in-
succeeded on the total occlusion-in-place,
place transform, the object in its invisible state
only a small minority succeeded on the total
continues to exist in that place (table or carrier)
occlusion-on-a-carrier-to-place. Importantly,
for both tasks. However, in the occlusion-on-
therefore, the permanence understanding
a-carrier, the object is deposited on the table
that enables success on one total occlusion is
under the cloth and the carrier is withdrawn
insufficient to solve the other. In fact, about 4
empty. No object is present on the carrier where
months elapse before a majority of infants can
that same one would be expected. If infants use
solve both tasks. These fi ndings suggest that
their permanence understanding to uncover
object permanence is not a once-and-for-all
the place of disappearance in order to find the
attainment: The nature of the disappearance
hidden object, on the occlusion-in-place task
transform matters.
72 OBJECTS AND SPACE

they succeed because they uncover the place on Violations of Strong Object Permanence
the table; but on the occlusion-on-a-carrier task Cause Negative Emotion in Infants
they fail, because the disappearance place (the
Adults can be driven to distraction when some-
carrier) is empty. Thus, the identity criterion
thing important is inexplicably lost. If object
or rule that underlies infants’ comprehension
permanence were an equally fundamental
of one task leads to noncomprehension of the
understanding of the world for infants, then vio-
other. 2
lations of permanence should generate strong
In terms of numerical identity for the 10- and
negative affect—conflict, upset, and avoidance.
12-month-old infants, the original object has to
The 10-month-olds’ response to the occlusion-
reappear on the carrier to be the same object—
on-a-carrier-to-place in the Moore and Meltzoff
there is no other place in the external world
(1999) study provides a test of this idea. As
where that object could be identified as the same
argued above, the empty carrier emerging from
one. If numerical identity guides search, it also
under the occluder violates the place rule for
follows that there is nowhere else to search for
where the hidden object should be. By contrast,
that same object. The 10-month-olds who failed
the place rule is not violated when the object
this task provide support for this interpretation
disappears by an occlusion-in-place, because a
because the overwhelming majority of them did
majority of infants at this age understand that
not search at all (even when they searched cor-
the object still resides in the now invisible place
rectly on the other occlusion task).
that it disappeared. Therefore, there should be
In terms of permanence, if there is no place
a difference in their emotional reactions to the
in the world for that same object to be after dis-
two tasks.
appearance except on the carrier, then, when the
Infants’ active avoidance was the measure
carrier is empty, it is evidence for the infant that
of affect used. The results were that avoidance
the object is not permanent. In this sense, one
was strongly associated with the occlusion-
transform preserves the object over an occlu-
on-a-carrier-to-place. The avoidance of the
sion (permanent for occlusion-in-place) and
occlusion-on-a-carrier did not simply reflect
the other transform does not (impermanent for
infants’ frustration at not finding the object.
occlusion-on-a-carrier-to-place). This provides
This was examined using infants who failed
support for a key claim of the ID account: An
both tasks. Significantly more of these infants
infant can understand objects as permanent for
avoided occlusion-on-a-carrier but did not avoid
one type of disappearance transform, but still
occlusion-in-place than infants who did the con-
think that objects are not permanent and are
verse (Moore & Meltzoff, 1999). Thus, infants’
nowhere to be found under a different trans-
avoidance of occlusion-on-a-carrier-to-place
form. This is what we mean when we say object
appears to be a reaction to the disappearance
permanence understanding is transformation-
transform, rather than to search consequences.
dependent; it is not an all-or-none attainment.
This differential avoidance pattern suggests
The pattern of these fi ndings and their interpre-
that infants were treating the “empty hand” as
tation suggests that permanence development
a violation of their understanding of perma-
proceeds in a transformationally dependent
nence, which is apparently important enough to
manner and also that the steps can be described
produce conflict when violated, and as argued
by the spatiotemporal parameters for numerical
above, for which their identity rules provide
identity.
no alternative understanding. These findings
2
suggest that the strong form of object perma-
For ease of exposition, we often characterize these
spatiotemporal criteria as “rules” because the spa- nence reflects a fundamental understanding of
tiotemporal parameters yield a rule-governed pattern the infants’ world as early as 10-months of age.
of operation (e.g., a place rule for permanence, a trajec- When this understanding is violated, there is a
tory rule for identity, a place-to-place rule, etc). They are
functional descriptions; we are not speculating on the strong emotional response (not just increases in
underlying neurophysiology. looking time, but avoidance and even upset).
NUMERICAL IDENTITY AND THE DEVELOPMENT OF OBJECT PERMANENCE 73

A MECHANISM OF CHANGE FOR object markedly improved the success rate of


DEVELOPING OBJECT PERMANENCE the 10-month-olds. This change in the use of
sound suggests that a developmental transition
We have argued that the strong form of object occurs between these ages.
permanence is not innately specified, but devel- Our specific mechanism of permanence
ops. We sketched the ID account that perma- development has two interwoven parts. First,
nence develops from infants understanding infants’ understanding of partial occlusions
of numerical identity and reviewed the new is a necessary precursor to locating stationary
empirical evidence bearing on this claim. The objects that are totally occluded and to estab-
results suggest that permanence is the under- lishing their identity when they are out of sight.
standing that allows infants to make sense of Second, infants’ discovery of permanence for a
what happens between encounters with objects total occlusion is a process of reinterpreting the
that can be reidentified as the same one again. occlusion event based on their existing under-
Object permanence fi lls the spatiotemporal standing of the precursor, the partial occlusion.
gap between an object’s disappearance and its
reappearance. Transition From Impermanence to
The theoretical problem is now sharply Permanence: The Crucial Role of Partial
posed. If permanence is a discovery that arises Occlusions
from a precondition in which objects are not When an object is hidden on a table, the total
permanent, how does the concept develop? This occlusion of the object is only a partial occlusion
raises the classic nativist challenge to all devel- of the table surface on which it sits. The occluded
opmental theories and all claims for conceptual place on the partially occluded table continues
change (Fodor, 1981). In particular, how can a to exist after occlusion (for infants who under-
concept of object permanence evolve from pre- stand partial occlusions) and provides an invis-
cursors that do not already entail a notion of ible location for the totally occluded object to
permanence? reside while it is out of sight. Thus, infants could
Genesis of Object Permanence for the
understand that there is somewhere in the
Occlusion of an Object in Place
external world for the totally occluded object to
be. Moreover, if that invisible place continues
The crux of the developmental problem is the to exist, then it could satisfy the place criterion
transition from impermanence to permanence. that identifies the object in that place, when it is
Here, we will describe a mechanism of per- out of sight, as the same one that disappeared
manence development for a particular case of there. We suggest that this development in spa-
occlusion. In the next section, we extend these tial cognition lays the groundwork for discover-
ideas to provide a generative mechanism of per- ing permanence over total occlusions in place.
manence discovery and development. Two key Infants can use the permanence of the partially
findings for theory construction emerged from hidden portion of the table supporting the
the Moore and Meltzoff (2008) study. First, the object to provide an invisible, but still existing,
infants’ pattern of success established an invari- location for the object to reside after it is totally
ant ordering: Many infants solved partial occlu- occluded, and also to provide a place criterion
sions by removing the occluder and failed total identifying it as the same one while it is invisible
occlusions, but none of the infants failed par- and when it is disoccluded.
tial occlusions and solved total occlusions. This
Sounding Objects as a Window on the
suggests that understanding the easier, partial
Process of Discovery
occlusion serves as a foundation for under-
standing the more difficult, total occlusion. There are at least three ways that sound from an
Second, as noted above, 8.75-month-olds were occluded object could help infants search. First,
no more successful searching for a sounding sound from the object could aid in remember-
object than a silent one. However, the sounding ing and localizing the object. If this were true,
74 OBJECTS AND SPACE

then sound should help both age groups, but a deductive inference that restructures what the
the younger group more than the older. Second, infants already know about partial occlusions to
infants might not be able to interpret sound as yield the new understanding.
coming from a hidden object unless they knew How did sound from the object help? We
that the object still existed in the hidden loca- think it provided an interpretive aid. Hypothesis
tion (i.e., the object is already permanent). If # 8 suggests that the normal developmental
this were true, then only infants who could course would be for infants to first reinterpret
solve occlusions with silent objects would solve the disappearance as conserving the object
them with sounding ones. Third, sound could in place after reappearance (because they can
function as a catalyst, triggering a new way to confirm the reappearing object’s identity after
understand the occlusion that was not accessible disocclusion); subsequently, they begin to make
when the object was silent. The data showed that that interpretation after the object’s disappear-
a sounding object was of no help to the youn- ance but before it reappears. On this view, the
ger infants, but significantly more of the older characteristic sound from the object provides a
infants succeeded with the sounding object shortcut enabling the interpretation to be made
than with the silent one (Moore & Meltzoff, at disappearance, because it allowed infants to
2008). This pattern suggests that sound acted as confirm the object’s identity by its sound from
a catalyst. How might that work? the represented place before it reappeared. Thus,
The fact that partial occlusions appear to be the auditory provision of identity and localiza-
a precursor to solving total occlusions suggests tion information before disocclusion fostered
that infants who understand partial occlusions interpretation by infants who were already able
are developmentally poised to discover how to to represent the hidden place.
understand total occlusions from experience. In sum, search for the sounding object is a
Once infants have this framework, a character- special case, but illustrates a process of inter-
istic sound from the object could provide addi- pretation that could be applied more generally.
tional spatial and identity information about According to the specific mechanism of change
how to interpret an object’s disappearance. described here, permanence arises only when
Sound from the hidden object, localized as com- an existing means for determining numerical
ing from the partially occluded surface, could identity and a developing understanding of par-
help catalyze a reinterpretation: the same object tial hidings have prepared the ground. On this
that disappeared is the source of this sound foundation, an occlusion event that was previ-
and remains unseen on that partially occluded ously interpreted as not preserving the object
surface. Based on this view, permanence is an can be interpreted in a new way, and confirmed
interpretation infants make of the occlusion by subsequent experience, as actually preserv-
event. The logic is concordant with hypothesis ing the object in a precise hidden location—it is
#8, the object is interpreted as permanent over now permanent over this disappearance trans-
a transform if it is identified as a single individ- form, a total occlusion in place.
ual, and both the object and the occluded loca-
Generalizing the Mechanism of Change:
tion are independently represented.
From Transform T to Transform T+1
We are not arguing that the role of sound is
a general explanation for how infants acquire We have suggested that the process of develop-
object permanence for total occlusions in place. mental change is one in which an understanding
Nor are we arguing that the 10-month-olds who of permanence and the experience gained with a
did not succeed on total occlusions with silent simpler disappearance transform make a harder
objects, but did with sounding objects, acquired transform amenable to reinterpretation so long
object permanence from that experience alone. as the numerical identity of the object can be
Rather, we think that the results with the sound- maintained. In the case of total occlusions, the
ing object give us a window on the process of how advance occurred because infants could use the
permanence is acquired for total occlusions: It is permanence of the partially hidden portion of
NUMERICAL IDENTITY AND THE DEVELOPMENT OF OBJECT PERMANENCE 75

the table supporting the object to provide (a) 2004). Infants treated the properties of an object
an invisible, but still existing, location for the seen hidden on day 1 as bearing on numerical
object to reside after it was totally occluded, identity because, when the object was presented
and (b) a continuously existing “place” criterion in a new location on day 2, infants searched in
identifying it as the same individual from dis- the original hiding place before playing with it.
appearance to reappearance. In this context, a Even though it was in the wrong place, the fea-
reinterpretation of total occlusions became pos- tural and functional identity criteria confl icted
sible. In what follows, we utilize this analysis with the spatiotemporal criterion and raised the
and our new findings to extend the developmen- question of its identity. For this disappearance
tal process toward a more general mechanism of transform then, the distinctive features and
change and development. functions of the object implied its numerical
There are two major problems confronting identity at 14 months of age.
a general mechanism. One is how to explain This suggests a general mechanism of
the step-like progression of occlusion tasks change that could account for the ordering of
that infants can solve as they develop. We have search tasks found in the longitudinal studies
reviewed data on two ordered steps here: the par- and how infants might use apparent violations
tial to total occlusion transition, and the occlu- of permanence. We will state the hypothesis in
sion-in-place to occlusion-on-a-carrier-to-place its most abstract form and illustrate it with a
transition. Other steps have been suggested by simple transform that violates the place rule for
previous longitudinal studies (Kramer, Hill, & permanence and identity. The general problem
Cohen, 1975; Piaget, 1954). A second problem is how “rule R” for the identity and permanence
arises when infants find that applying their cur- of an object and its features over transform T
rent permanence rule to a disappearance trans- changes to rule “R+1” for a new disappearance
form does not preserve the object. This obstacle transform. The proposed mechanism is shown
was illustrated in the Moore and Meltzoff (1999) schematically in Figure 4.2. Here it is applied to
study. Infants, who had a place rule to solve an a task in which the object is moved after disap-
occlusion-in-place, found that applying it to an pearance in place X to a second place Y by means
occlusion-on-a-carrier resulted in an empty of the screen (e.g., a cup covers an object and is
reappearance place, and an apparently upset- then pushed to a new location with the object
ting violation of permanence. still underneath). According to rule R, the infant
The general process of developmental change searches place X on the table and finds it empty,
focuses on what else develops once a transform which violates the spatiotemporal logic of rule
is understood as conserving an occluded object R. Meanwhile, the object reappears at place Y,
as a whole. The major claim is that infants learn which confirms the featural logic of rule R—it
which features and functions of an object are can be interpreted provisionally as the same one
themselves permanent over that transform and again. This produces conflict because rule R is
can bear independently on identity determina- both confirmed and violated. The infant has to
tion (hypotheses # 9 & 10). Thus, an object’s per- weigh the apparent violation of permanence for
manent features and functions could also serve the object at X and the appearance of a featur-
as identity criteria for distinguishing that object ally identical object at Y against the validity of
when spatiotemporal parameters are absent, rule R. This conflict is resolved by reinterpreting
neutral, or even in disagreement. We term these the spatiotemporal logic of rule R to encompass
criteria the object’s “distinctive” features and the change of location (X →Y). This reorganiza-
functions. This discovery offers new developmen- tion provides the new spatiotemporal logic of
tal leverage because the spatiotemporal param- rule R+1, maintaining an object’s identity and
eters, the object’s properties, and its permanence permanence over a new transform T+1.
can all interact in interpreting occlusion events. In the terms we have been using, the exam-
The phenomenon of “verifying search” pro- ple above captures the process of reinterpreting
vides relevant evidence (Moore & Meltzoff, a place rule for identity and permanence to yield
76 OBJECTS AND SPACE

Object disappears place X:


engages rule R for
disappearance transform T

Object displaced Infant searches place X


to place Y by screen according to spatiotemporal
logic of rule R

Object reappears at Y: Place X empty:


confirming violates
featural logic of rule R spatial logic of rule R

Conflict:
Violation/Confirmation
of rule R

Re-interpret
spatiotemporal
logic of rule R to
include object at X Y

New spatiotemporal logic


of rule R + 1
for new transform T + 1

Figure 4.2 A mechanism of change for developing object permanence. An object disappears at place X
and reappears at place Y. The infant expects the object to reappear at X according to permanence rule
R. The flowchart illustrates the hypothesized process for changing the spatiotemporal component of
rule R to rule R+1. Conflict occurs between confirmation of the featural component of rule R, which
is satisfied by the object appearing at Y, and disconfirmation of the spatiotemporal component, which
is violated by the object’s failure to appear at X. Changing the spatiotemporal component of rule R to
rule R+1 resolves the conflict. See text for details. Adapted from Moore (1975).

a new place-to-place rule. An object disappear- transform T+1 (i.e., after occlusion, the occluder
ing in place X can be the same one again when moves from the place disappearance to a new
it reappears in place Y. The identity and perma- place). The particular rules are engaged by the
nence of the whole object are preserved over spatiotemporal structure of the various disap-
the new transform and the process of learning pearance transforms. We think that this kind of
which properties of an object are also preserved mechanism of development would account for
can begin again for the R+1 transform. Note the stepwise progression of infant success on
that rule R+1 does not overwrite rule R. Rather, search tasks because the steps are generated by
rule R is engaged by observing transform T (i.e., the order of the underlying spatiotemporal cri-
after occlusion the occluder remains at the place teria for identity and the resulting understand-
of disappearance) and rule R+1 is engaged by ings of object permanence.
NUMERICAL IDENTITY AND THE DEVELOPMENT OF OBJECT PERMANENCE 77

More broadly, when an object is occluded, different type of total occlusion (an occlusion-
the goal of search is quite specific: Infants are on-a-carrier-to-a-place) demonstrates that
seeking the same object that disappeared—no Piaget’s developmental sequence is incomplete.
other object will do. Successful search recon- The same search action at the same location
nects the infant with the same predisappear- was required to find the object in both tasks.
ance object and maintains order in the infant’s For Piaget (1954), there is no easy explanation
cognitive world; failed search confronts infants for how total hidings in one place, solved by
with disorder, which can have affective con- the same recovery act, can be developmentally
sequences. Infants’ striving to preserve order different.
and coherence in their world is the motivation Moreover, there is further evidence that
for permanence development, and tracing an does not comport with Piagetian theory. Piaget
object’s identity over transformational events is is correct in claiming that success on partial
a means to achieve it. occlusions precedes success on total occlusions.
But, his theory provides no explanation for the
new data showing that infants fail to remove
IMPLICATIONSFOR EXISTING THEORIES OF
the occluder of a totally hidden object when
OBJECT PERMANENCE IN INFANCY
they have the means–ends coordination to do
Infant object permanence has been the focus so. Such coordination characterizes Piaget’s
of attention for seven decades. Four basic stage 4, and infants who uncovered the partially
approaches have been articulated. We consider occluded object should have uncovered the
them in light of the evidence and arguments totally occluded object, but they did not.
presented here and make suggestions for future Taken together, the new studies suggest that
research. Piaget’s diagnosis of infants’ problems in devel-
oping object permanence was off target, and his
Piagetian Approaches action-based theory of development does not
According to Piaget (1952, 1954), infants fit the evidence. The infant’s conceptual prob-
develop a concept of objects as permanent by lem is not separating objects from the matrix of
increasingly separating the object itself from action, representing them in mind, or position-
the matrix of actions upon it, culminating in ing them in visible space—the early perceptual
an object’s representation independent of both and representational systems do all three.
perception and action (Table 4.1). A number
Dynamic Systems Theory
of theorists have broadened his theoretical
terms to include a “gradual strengthening of Dynamic systems theorists believe that infants’
representation” or “movement of the observer initial appreciation of objects is embedded in the
either by actions of the infant or by being car- dynamics of their acts of attending, reaching,
ried through space” as the sources of develop- and remembering (Thelen & Smith, 1994). They
ment while narrowing their focus to explaining think that objects are so inextricably bound up
how infants first solve a total occlusion or over- in attention and action that a concept of per-
come the A-not-B search error (Bremner, 1989; manence is not developed in infancy (Thelen,
Campos et al., 2000; Mareschal, Plunkett, & Schoner, Scheier, & Smith, 2001), and in that
Harris, 1999; Munakata, McClelland, Johnson sense, postulate an even less cognitive, more
& Siegler, 1997; Newcombe & Huttenlocher, action-bound infant than Piaget. The study of
2000). Piaget’s manual search tasks are differ- 14-month-olds’ search after a 24-h delay tests
entiated in terms of three major factors: (a) the this assertion (Moore & Meltzoff, 2004). Infants
actions required for recovery, (b) the degree of observed an object’s disappearance with no
occlusion, and (c) the number of hiding loca- familiarization play with the hiding places and
tions. The research reviewed here showing that immediately left the laboratory. Upon return
infants can solve one type of total occlusion (an 24 h later, no attention was drawn to the hiding
occlusion-in-place) 4 months before solving a place, yet infants successfully found the object.
78 OBJECTS AND SPACE

From the dynamic systems perspective, there occlusion. The results showed that by 10 months
were no practiced acts to repeat, no directing of age, infants could understand permanence
of infants’ attention to the hiding place. Infants for a total occlusion-in-place. Importantly, that
searched based on a stored representation of was not the end of development. Recall that
the absent object and its location in space. 10-month-olds, who solved this form of total
This suggests that some conception of perma- occlusion, did not succeed on a total occlusion-
nence is needed to guide search on the second on-a-carrier to-a-place until 14 months of age.
day contrary to the dynamic systems’ model of These data suggest there are at least two steps in
infancy. permanence development, unexplained by per-
formance constraints, which challenge nativist
Nativist Theory theory. Permanence neither seems to be innate
Object permanence nativists claim that it is log- nor a once-and-for-all acquisition.
ically impossible for infants to learn that objects
Identity Development Theory
are permanent from the chaos of sensory expe-
rience (Spelke, 1994). In this approach, object On the ID account, object permanence develops
is an innate conception resulting from per- from a prior understanding of numerical iden-
ceptual processing that entails permanence tity—the spatiotemporal criteria infants use to
(Baillargeon, 2008; Spelke, 1990). Permanence reidentify an object as the same one again after
does not develop; it is present from the begin- a break in perceptual contact. When infants
ning and part of what it means to perceive an can parse a particular disappearance transform
object. as maintaining the identity of the object, they
Nativists claim that search necessarily are in a position to discover what happens to
underestimates infants’ competence. Instead, it between appearances. Then, experience with
increased looking time to events in which object reappearances can be understood in
occluded objects do not reappear when/where a new way, allowing infants to reinterpret the
they are expected to reappear is the appropri- occlusion as preserving the object in a hidden
ate measure. This method leads to the paradox place.
that infant’s putative knowledge of permanence Once infants understand the total occlusion
at birth as inferred from looking time measures of an object in place as preserving it invisibly
does not guide action: Infants fail to search in that place, they still do not understand all
manually for hidden stationary objects (for total occlusions (as argued above). The ID claim
review: Marcovitch & Zelazo, 1999), and they is that the interplay of an object’s spatiotem-
fail to “catch” moving objects that briefly disap- poral parameters and its permanent features
pear and reappear (Berthier et al., 2001; Jonsson and functions afford a mechanism of develop-
& von Hofsten, 2003; Spelke & von Hofsten, mental change, which enables the discovery
2001) until about 9 months of age. This age dis- of other disappearance transforms over which
crepancy is usually explained as a result of per- the object’s identity and its permanence are
formance constraints on the innate knowledge. preserved. Hence, permanence understanding
However, the new finding of a developmen- is constrained to specific types of disappear-
tal difference in search for occluded objects, ance transforms, and develops one transform
when performance factors are controlled and at a time. The ID account holds that object per-
search skills are available, casts doubt on this manence develops in ordered steps, and that
explanation for the failure to search. Infants search tasks, properly conducted, can assess
who succeeded on partial hidings by removing this development.
the occluder should also succeed in removing On the surface, the ID account resembles
the occluder on total hidings if they under- Piaget’s in arguing for a step-like development
stood permanence. But they did not succeed. in object permanence and for the validity of
We interpret this to mean that the 8.75-month- manual search as a measure of it. However, this
olds do not understand permanence for a total resemblance is more apparent than real. There
NUMERICAL IDENTITY AND THE DEVELOPMENT OF OBJECT PERMANENCE 79

are profound differences. Empirically, the ID Permanence is knowledge of an invisible state of


account encompasses additional steps in per- affairs. This contrasts with the nativists’ equat-
manence development and in visual search not ing object permanence with continuity in space
included in Piaget’s account. Theoretically, the and time (Spelke, Breinlinger, Macomber, &
ID account bases infant development on an Jacobson, 1992), but being unable, using prefer-
initial capacity for representation and numeri- ential looking or habituation methods, to assess
cal identity rather than seeing representation as infants’ reactions to continuity/discontinuity
the culmination of development at 18 months while the object is still invisible. Essentially, what
of age. Moreover, the ID engine of development is measured by looking time is postreappearance
is cognitive, and stems from infants’ striving knowledge. That is, what is directly measured is
to understand which objects in the external whether the visible, preocclusion state of affairs
world are the same ones encountered previ- is consistent with or discrepant from the visible,
ously, rather than from Piaget’s hierarchical postocclusion state. Looking time measures are
coordination of sensorimotor action schemes. retrospective and based on the visible structure
This striving for a coherent understanding of of the entire disappearance–reappearance cycle.
the appearance and disappearance of the same By contrast, the search measures described here
object, which leads to the discovery of perma- (i.e., incorporating spatially directed visual
nence and orders the course of development, is anticipation of the object’s reappearance locus)
more objective and independent of action than are predictive. Search success under these con-
envisaged by Piaget. ditions shows that infants are seeking the object
where it is located while it is still in its occluded
Future Directions in Object
state. In light of this distinction, one resolution
Permanence Research
of the dilemma is that we are not in fact assess-
At present, the field has two methods that yield ing the same concept at all.
diametrically opposed results, yet both claim On the other hand, we have identified some
to measure the same concept—object perma- markers of the strong form of object perma-
nence. This dichotomy poses deep difficul- nence that nativists could use to demonstrate
ties. According to the nativists, permanence is that the two approaches are measuring the same
an innately perceived property of objects, and concept. It would be interesting if the looking
increased looking time to events incompatible time methods could be adapted to allow young
with permanence demonstrates this implicit infants to leave the locale where the object dis-
knowledge of permanence. According to ID appeared and return later for assessment. Or,
theory, permanence is a function of the disap- could the violation-of-expectation method be
pearance transforms that infants understand, adapted to show strong emotion for a violation
and the order of the manual search tasks solved of permanence (rather than simply increased
by infants demonstrates the development of this looking time), as shown by search tests with
understanding. A paradox arises because the 10-month-olds? One corollary of the nativists’
innate knowledge shown by looking time mea- view seems less persuasive in light of our new
sures does not lead to search before 9 months of data: It is difficult to maintain that infants fail to
age. This paradox still engenders considerable search due to known performance constraints.
debate (e.g., Cohen & Cashon, 2006; Kagan, We found no evidence for this in two indepen-
2008; Meltzoff & Moore, 1998; Newcombe, & dent studies and three different ages.
Huttenlocher, 2006; Quinn, 2008). Conversely, one might wonder then whether
In this chapter, we have tried to narrow the the ID account has any explanation for the
gap to some extent. On the one hand, we have looking-time phenomena demonstrated by the
clarified the definition of object permanence—it nativist approach. We have taken up this chal-
refers to a prereappearance understanding that lenge for some of the phenomena (Meltzoff
an occluded object continues to exist in a par- & Moore, 1998). Essentially, our argument
ticular hidden location in the external world. is that many of the looking time effects result
80 OBJECTS AND SPACE

from the early representational system oper- ACKNOWLEDGMENTS


ating to maintain an object’s numerical iden-
tity even in the absence of object permanence This work was supported by NIH (HD-22514),
NSF (SBE-0354453), and the Tamaki Foundation.
(hypothesis # 5). The ID account contends that
Any opinions, findings, and conclusions expressed
this representational system allows infants to in the paper are those of the authors and do not
learn and retain the spatiotemporal structure of necessarily reflect the views of these agencies.
disappearance and reappearance events in the We thank Calle Fisher and Craig Harris for their
visible world, and to form expectations about assistance and S.J. for very helpful comments on
the visible outcomes of such events (Johnson, an earlier version of this chapter.
Amso, et al., 2003; Kochukhova & Gredebäck,
2007). When discrepancies from expected out-
comes occur, they will recruit increased atten- REFERENCES
tion. Thus, on the ID account, such discrepancies Aslin, R. (1981). Development of smooth pursuit in
could explain increased looking times to the human infants. In D. F. Fischer, R. A. Monty, &
events that have been studied, without imply- E. J. Senders (Eds.), Eye movements: cognition
ing actual infant knowledge of permanence (for and visual perception (pp. 31–51). Hillsdale, NJ:
details, see Meltzoff & Moore, 1998). Erlbaum.
In the end, a full developmental theory has Baillargeon, R. (2008). Innate ideas revisited: For a
to be compatible with the facts: Infants learn, principle of persistence in infants’ physical rea-
develop, and change seemingly based on input; soning. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 3,
2–13.
they solve problems; they care about conse-
Baillargeon, R., Graber, M., DeVos, J., & Black, J.
quences and show emotion; and they act. They do (1990). Why do young infants fail to search for
not just sit and perceive, receive, and parse events hidden objects? Cognition, 36, 255–284.
in the world. They go out and change it. We have Bertenthal, B. I., Longo, M. R., & Kenny, S. (2007).
begun to provide an account of object perma- Phenomenal permanence and the develop-
nence development compatible with these facts. ment of predictive tracking in infancy. Child
Development, 78, 350–363.
Summary
Berthier, N. E., Bertenthal, B. I., Seaks, J. D., Sylvia,
We have proposed an ID account of object per- M. R., Johnson, R. L., & Clifton, R. K. (2001).
manence that locates the origins and develop- Using object knowledge in visual tracking and
ment of permanence in infants’ notions of how reaching. Infancy, 2, 257–284.
Bower, T. G. R. (1967). The development of object-
to determine and trace numerical identity. The
permanence: Some studies of existence con-
arguments and evidence generated from this stancy. Perception & Psychophysics, 2, 411–418.
approach suggest a number of conclusions: (a) Bower, T. G. R. (1971). The object in the world of
object permanence understanding is not an all- the infant. Scientific American, 225, 30–38.
or-none attainment; (b) permanence is under- Bower, T. G. R. (1982). Development in infancy
stood for some disappearance transforms but (2nd ed.). San Francisco: Freeman.
not others; (c) the development of infants’ spa- Bower, T. G. R., Broughton, J. M., & Moore, M. K.
tiotemporal criteria for numerical identity pro- (1971). Development of the object concept as
vide the form and ordering of the disappearance manifested in changes in the tracking behav-
transforms over which they understand perma- ior of infants between 7 and 20 weeks of age.
nence; (d) apparent violations of permanence Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 11,
182–193.
can cause negative emotion; and (e) taking
Bremner, G. (1989). Development of spatial aware-
seriously the conceptual distinctions between ness in infancy. In A. Slater & G. Bremner
representation, identity, and permanence offers (Eds.), Infant Development (pp. 123–141).
considerable theoretical power. Finally, we pro- Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
posed a mechanism of change to account for the Bremner, J. G., Johnson, S. P., Slater, A., Mason, U.,
transition from having no concept of perma- Cheshire, A., & Spring, J. (2007). Conditions
nence to having permanence. for young infants, failure to perceive
NUMERICAL IDENTITY AND THE DEVELOPMENT OF OBJECT PERMANENCE 81

trajectory continuity. Developmental Science, infancy: Evidence for early learning in an eye-
10, 613–624. tracking paradigm. Proceedings of the National
Bremner, J. G., Johnson, S. P., Slater, A., Mason, U., Academy of Sciences, USA, 100, 10568–10573.
Foster, K., Cheshire, A., et al. (2005). Conditions Johnson, S. P., Bremner, J. G., Slater, A., Mason,
for young infants, perception of object trajec- U., Foster, K., & Cheshire, A. (2003). Infants’
tories. Child Development, 76, 1029–1043. perception of object trajectories. Child
Campos, J. J., Anderson, D. I., Barbu-Roth, M. Development, 74, 94–108.
A., Hubbard, E. M., Hertenstein, M. J., & Jonsson, B., & von Hofsten, C. (2003). Infants’ abil-
Witherington, D. (2000). Travel broadens the ity to track and reach for temporarily occluded
mind. Infancy, 1, 149–219. objects. Developmental Science, 6, 86–99.
Carey, S., & Xu, F. (2001). Infants’ knowledge of Kagan, J. (2008). In defense of qualitative changes in
objects: Beyond object fi les and object track- development. Child Development, 79, 1606–1624.
ing. Cognition, 80, 179–213. Kahneman, D., Treisman, A., & Gibbs, B. J.
Cohen, L. B, & Cashon, C. H. (2006). Infant cog- (1992). The reviewing of object fi les: Object-
nition. In D. Kuhn, R. S. Siegler, W. Damon, & specific integration of information. Cognitive
R. M. Lerner, (Eds.). Handbook of child psychol- Psychology, 24, 175–219.
ogy, (Vol. 2, pp. 214–251). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley. Kaufman, J., Csibra, G., & Johnson, M. H. (2005).
Diamond, A. (1985). Development of the abil- Oscillatory activity in the infant brain reflects
ity to use recall to guide action, as _ indi- object maintenance. Proceedings of the National
cated by infants’ performance on AB. Child Academy of Sciences, USA, 102, 15271–15274.
Development, 56, 868–883. Kochukhova, O., & Gredebäck, G. (2007). Learning
Diamond, A.,_ Cruttenden, L., & Neiderman, D. about occlusion: Initial assumptions and rapid
(1994). AB with multiple wells: 1. Why are adjustments. Cognition, 105, 26–46.
multiple wells sometimes easier than two Köhler, S., Kapur, S., Moscovitch, M., Winocur,
wells? 2. Memory or memory + inhibition? G., & Houle, S. (1995). Dissociation of path-
Developmental Psychology, 30, 192–205. ways for object and spatial vision: A PET study
Fodor, J. A. (1981). Representations: Philosophical in humans. Neuroreport, 6, 1865–1868.
essays on the foundations of cognitive science. Kramer, J. A., Hill, K. T., & Cohen, L. B. (1975).
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Infants’ development of object permanence:
Gibson, J. J., Kaplan, G. A., Reynolds, H. N., & A refined methodology and new evidence
Wheeler, K. (1969). The change from visi- for Piaget’s hypothesized ordinality. Child
ble to invisible: A study of optical transitions. Development, 46, 149–155.
Perception & Psychophysics, 5, 113–116. Krøjgaard, P. (2004). A review of object individua-
Grzywacz, N. M., Watamaniuk, S. N. J., & McKee, tion in infancy. British Journal of Developmental
S. P. (1995). Temporal coherence theory for the Psychology, 22, 159–183.
detection and measurement of visual motion. Krøjgaard, P. (2007). Comparing infants’ use of
Vision Research, 35, 3183–3203. featural and spatiotemporal information in an
Haith, M. M., Kessen, W., & Collins, D. (1969). object individuation task using a new event-
Response of the human infant to level of com- monitoring design. Developmental Science, 10,
plexity of intermittent visual movement. Journal 892–909.
of Experimental Child Psychology, 7, 52–69. Leslie, A. M., Xu, F., Tremoulet, P. D., & Scholl,
Harris, P. L. (1987). The development of search. B. J. (1998). Indexing and the object concept:
In P. Salapatek & L. Cohen (Eds.), Handbook Developing ‘what’ and ‘where’ systems. Trends
of infant perception (Vol. 2, pp. 155–207). New in Cognitive Sciences, 2, 10–18.
York: Academic Press. Marcovitch, S., & Zelazo, P. D. (1999). The A-not-B
Haxby, J. V., Grady, C. L., Horwitz, B., Ungerleider, error: Results from a logistic meta-analysis.
L. G., Mishkin, M., Carson, R. E., et al. (1991). Child Development, 70, 1297–1313.
Dissociation of object and spatial visual pro- Mareschal, D., Plunkett, K., & Harris, P. (1999).
cessing pathways in human extrastriate cor- A computational and neuropsychological
tex. Proceedings of the National Academy of account of object-oriented behaviors in infancy.
Sciences, USA, 88, 1621–1625. Developmental Science, 2, 306–317.
Johnson, S. P., Amso, D., & Slemmer, J. A. Meltzoff, A. N., & Moore, M. K. (1998). Object rep-
(2003). Development of object concepts in resentation, identity, and the paradox of early
82 OBJECTS AND SPACE

permanence: Steps toward a new framework. Newcombe, N., Huttenlocher, J., & Learmonth, A.
Infant Behavior & Development, 21, 201–235. (1999). Infants’ coding of location in continu-
Michotte, A. (1962). Causalité, permanence, et réal- ous space. Infant Behavior & Development, 22,
ité phénoménales: Études de psychologie expéri- 483–510.
mentale. Louvain: Publications Universitaires. Piaget, J. (1952). The origins of intelligence in chil-
Moore, M. K. (1975, April). Object permanence dren (M. Cook, Trans.). New York: International
and object identity: A stage-developmental Universities Press.
model. In M. K. Moore (Chair), Object iden- Piaget, J. (1954). The construction of reality in
tity: The missing link between Piaget’s stages the child (M. Cook, Trans.). New York: Basic
of object permanence. Symposium conducted Books.
at the meeting of the Society for Research in Quinn, P. C. (2008). In defense of core competen-
Child Development, Denver, CO. cies, quantitative change, and continuity. Child
Moore, M. K., Borton, R., & Darby, B. L. (1978). Development, 79, 1633–1638.
Visual tracking in young infants: Evidence for Rosander, K., & von Hofsten, C. (2004). Infants’
object identity or object permanence? Journal emerging ability to represent occluded object
of Experimental Child Psychology, 25, 183–198. motion. Cognition, 91, 1–22.
Moore, M. K., & Meltzoff, A. N. (1978). Object Smith, L. B., Thelen, E., Titzer, R., & McLin,
permanence, imitation, and language devel- D. (1999). Knowing in the context of act-
opment in infancy: Toward a neo-Piagetian ing: The task dynamics of the A-not-B error.
perspective on communicative and cognitive Psychological Review, 106, 235–260.
development. In F. D. Minifie & L. L. Lloyd Spelke, E. S. (1990). Principles of object percep-
(Eds.), Communicative and cognitive abilities— tion. Cognitive Science, 14, 29–56.
Early behavioral assessment (pp. 151–184). Spelke, E. S. (1994). Initial knowledge: Six sugges-
Baltimore: University Park Press. tions. Cognition, 50, 431–445.
Moore, M. K., & Meltzoff, A. N. (1999). New find- Spelke, E. S., Breinlinger, K., Macomber, J., &
ings on object permanence: A developmen- Jacobson, K. (1992). Origins of knowledge.
tal difference between two types of occlusion. Psychological Review, 99, 605–632.
British Journal of Developmental Psychology, Spelke, E. S., & von Hofsten, C. (2001). Predictive
17, 623–644. reaching for occluded objects by 6-month-old
Moore, M. K., & Meltzoff, A. N. (2004). Object infants. Journal of Cognition and Development,
permanence after a 24-hr delay and leaving the 2, 261–281.
locale of disappearance: The role of memory, Strawson, P. F. (1959). Individuals: An essay in
space, and identity. Developmental Psychology, descriptive metaphysics. London: Methuen.
40, 606–620. Thelen, E., Schöner, G., Scheier, C., & Smith, L. B.
Moore, M. K., & Meltzoff, A. N. (2008). Factors (2001). The dynamics of embodiment: A
affecting infants’ manual search for occluded field theory of infant perseverative reaching.
objects and the genesis of object permanence. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24, 1–86.
Infant Behavior & Development, 31, 168–180. Thelen, E., & Smith, L. B. (1994). A dynamic sys-
Munakata, Y., McClelland, J. L., Johnson, M. H., & tems approach to the development of cognition
Siegler, R. S. (1997). Rethinking infant knowl- and action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
edge: Toward an adaptive process account of Treisman, A. (1992). Perceiving and re-perceiving
successes and failures in object permanence objects. American Psychologist, 47, 862–875.
tasks. Psychological Review, 104, 686–713. Van de Walle, G. A., Carey, S., & Prevor, M. (2000).
Newcombe, N. S., & Huttenlocher, J. (2006). Bases for object individuation in infancy:
Development of spatial cognition. In D. Kuhn, Evidence from manual search. Journal of
R. S. Siegler, W. Damon, & R. M. Lerner, (Eds.). Cognition and Development, 1, 249–280.
Handbook of child psychology (Vol. 2, pp. von Hofsten, C., Kochukhova, O., & Rosander,
734–776). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley. K. (2007). Predictive tracking over occlusions
Newcombe, N. S., & Huttenlocher, J. (2000). by 4-month-olds. Developmental Science, 10,
Making space: The development of spatial rep- 625–640.
resentation and reasoning. Cambridge, MA: von Hofsten, C., Vishton, P., Spelke, E. S., Feng,
MIT Press. Q., & Rosander, K. (1998). Predictive action
NUMERICAL IDENTITY AND THE DEVELOPMENT OF OBJECT PERMANENCE 83

in infancy: Tracking and reaching for moving Wilcox, T., & Baillargeon, R. (1998). Object indi-
objects. Cognition, 67, 255–285. viduation in infancy: The use of featural infor-
Watamaniuk, S. N. J., & McKee, S. P. (1995). mation in reasoning about occlusion events.
Seeing motion behind occluders. Nature, 377, Cognitive Psychology, 37, 97–155.
729–730. Xu, F., & Carey, S. (1996). Infants’ metaphys-
Watamaniuk, S. N. J., McKee, S. P., & Grzywacz, ics: The case of numerical identity. Cognitive
N. M. (1995). Detecting a trajectory embed- Psychology, 30, 111–153.
ded in random-direction motion noise. Vision
Research, 35, 65–77.
This page intentionally left blank
PART II

Words, Language, and Music


This page intentionally left blank
CHAP TER 5
Connectionist Explorations of Multiple-Cue
Integration in Syntax Acquisition

Morten H. Christiansen, Rick Dale, and Florencia Reali

Among the many feats of learning that children By 12 months, infants are attuned to the
showcase in their development, syntactic abil- phonological and prosodic regularities of their
ities appear long before many other skills, such native language (Jusczyk, 1997; Kuhl, 1999). This
as riding bikes, tying shoes, or playing a musical perceptual attunement may provide an essential
instrument. This is achieved with little or no direct scaffolding for later learning by biasing children
instruction, making it both impressive and even toward aspects of language input that are par-
puzzling, because mastering natural language ticularly informative for acquiring grammati-
syntax is one of the most difficult learning tasks cal knowledge. In this chapter, we hypothesize
that humans face. One reason for this difficulty is that integrating multiple probabilistic cues
a “chicken-and-egg” problem involved in acquir- (phonological, prosodic, and distributional) by
ing syntax. Syntactic knowledge can be charac- perceptually attuned general-purpose learning
terized by constraints governing the relationship mechanisms may hold promise for explaining
between grammatical categories of words (such how children solve the bootstrapping problem.
as noun and verb) in a sentence. At the same Multiple cues can provide reliable evidence
time, the syntactic constraints presuppose the about linguistic structure that is unavailable
grammatical categories in terms of which they from any single source of information.
are defined; and the validity of grammatical cat- In the remainder of this chapter, we first
egories depends on how they support those same review empirical evidence suggesting that infants
syntactic constraints. A similar “bootstrapping” may use a combination of phonological, pro-
problem faces a student learning an academic sodic, and distributional cues to bootstrap into
subject such as physics: understanding momen- syntax. We then report a series of simulations
tum or force presupposes some understanding demonstrating the computational efficacy of
of the physical laws in which they figure; yet multiple-cue integration within a connectionist
these laws presuppose these very concepts. The framework (for modeling of other aspects of cog-
bootstrapping problem solved by very young chil- nitive development, see the chapter by Mareschal
dren seems much more daunting, both because & Westermann, this volume). Simulation 1 shows
the constraints governing natural language are how multiple-cue integration results in better,
so intricate, and because these children do not faster, and more uniform learning. Simulation
have the intellectual capacity or explicit instruc- 2 uses this initial model to mimic the effect of
tion present in conventional academic settings. grammatical and prosodic manipulations in a
Determining how children accomplish the sentence comprehension study with 2-year-olds
astonishing feat of language acquisition remains (Shady & Gerken, 1999). Simulation 3 uses an
a key question in cognitive science. idealized representation of prenatal exposure

87
88 WORDS, LANGUAGE, AND MUSIC

to gross-level phonological and prosodic cues, native language. Recently, a wealth of compel-
leading to facilitation of postnatal learning of ling experimental evidence has accumulated,
syntax by the model. Simulation 4 demonstrates suggesting that children do not initially use
that adding additional distracting cues, irrele- abstract linguistic categories. Instead, they
vant to the syntactic acquisition task, does not seem to employ words at first as concrete indi-
hinder learning. Finally, Simulation 5 scales up viduals (rather than instances of abstract kinds),
these initial simulations, showing that connec- thereby challenging the usefulness of hypothe-
tionist models can acquire aspects of syntactic sized innate grammatical categories (Tomasello,
structure from cues present in actual child-di- 2000). Whether we grant the presence of exten-
rected speech. sive innate knowledge or not, it seems clear that
other sources of information are necessary to
solve the bootstrapping problem.
THE NEED FOR MULTIPLE
Language-external information, such as cor-
LANGUAGE- INTERNAL CUES
relations between the environment and seman-
In this section, we identify three kinds of con- tic categories, may contribute to language
straints that may serve to help the language acquisition by supplying a “semantic bootstrap-
learner solve the syntactic bootstrapping prob- ping” solution (Pinker, 1984). However, because
lem. First, innate constraints in the form of children learn linguistic distinctions that
linguistic universals may be available to dis- have no semantic basis (e.g., gender in French:
cover to which grammatical category a word Karmiloff-Smith, 1979), semantics cannot be
belongs, and how they function in syntactic the only source of information involved in solv-
rules. Second, language-external information, ing the bootstrapping problem. Other sources of
concerning observed semantic relationships language-external constraints include cultural
between language and the world, could help learning, indicated by a child’s imitation of lin-
map individual words onto their grammatical guistic forms in socially conventional contexts
function. Finally, language-internal informa- (Tomasello, Kruger & Ratner, 1993). For exam-
tion, such as aspects of phonological, prosodic, ple, a child may perceive that the idiom “John
and distributional patterns, may indicate the let the cat out of the bag,” used in the appropri-
relation of various parts of language to each ate context, means that John has revealed some
other, thus bootstrapping the child into the sort of secret, and not that he released a feline
realm of syntactic relations. We discuss each of from captivity. Despite both of these important
these potential constraints below, and conclude language-external sources, to break down the
that some form of language-internal informa- linguistic forms into relevant units, it appears
tion is needed to break the circularity. that correlation and cultural learning must be
Although innate constraints likely play a role coupled with language-internal information.
in language acquisition, they cannot solve the We do not challenge the important role that
bootstrapping problem. Even with genetically the two foregoing sources of information play in
prescribed abstract knowledge of grammati- language acquisition. We would argue, however,
cal categories and syntactic rules (e.g., Pinker, that language-internal information is fundamen-
1984), the problem remains: Innate knowledge tal to bootstrapping the child into syntax. Because
requires building in universal mappings across language-internal input is rich in potential cues
languages, but the relationships between words to linguistic structure, we offer a requisite feature
and grammatical categories clearly differ cross- of this information for syntax acquisition: Cues
linguistically (e.g., the sound /su/ is a noun in may only be partially reliable individually, and
French (sou) but a verb in English (sue)). Even a learner must integrate an array of these cues
with rich innate knowledge, children still must to solve the bootstrapping problem. For exam-
assign sound sequences to appropriate gram- ple, a learner could use the tendency for English
matical categories while determining the syn- nouns to be longer than verbs to conjecture that
tactic relations between these categories in their bonobo is a noun, but the same strategy would
CONNECTIONIST EXPLORATIONS OF MULTIPLE-CUE INTEGRATION 89

fail for ingratiate. Likewise, although speakers Prosodic cues help word and phrasal/clausal
tend to pause at syntactic phrase boundaries in segmentation and may reveal syntactic structure
a sentence, pauses also occur elsewhere during (e.g., Gerken, Jusczyk & Mandel, 1994; Gleitman
normal language production. And although it is & Wanner, 1982; Kemler-Nelson, Hirsh-Pasek,
a good distributional bet that the definite arti- Jusczyk, & Wright Cassidy, 1989; Morgan, 1996).
cle the will precede a noun, so might adjectives, Acoustic analyses find that pause length, vowel
such as silly. The child therefore needs to inte- duration, and pitch all mark phrasal boundaries
grate a great diversity of probabilistic cues to in English and Japanese child-directed speech
language structure. Fortunately, as we review in (Fisher & Tokura, 1996). Perhaps from utero
the next section, there is now extensive evidence (Mehler et al., 1988) and beyond, infants seem
that multiple probabilistic cues are available in highly sensitive to such language-specific pro-
language-internal input, that children are sen- sodic patterns (Gerken et al., 1994; Kemler-Nelson
sitive to them, and that they facilitate learning et al., 1989; for reviews, see Gerken, 1996; Jusczyk
through integration. & Kemler-Nelson, 1996; Morgan, 1996). Prosodic
information also improves sentence comprehen-
Bootstrapping through Multiple
sion in 2-year-olds (Shady & Gerken, 1999). In
Language-Internal Cues
experiments using adult participants, artificial
We explore three sources of language-internal language learning is facilitated in the presence
cues: phonological, prosodic, and distributional. of prosodic marking of syntactic phrase bound-
Phonological information includes stress, vowel aries (Morgan, Meier & Newport, 1987; Valian
quality, and duration, and may help distinguish & Levitt, 1996). Neurophysiological evidence in
grammatical function words (e.g., determiners, the form of event-related brainwave potentials
prepositions, and conjunctions) from content (ERP) in adults shows that prosodic information
words (nouns, verbs, adjectives, and adverbs) in has an immediate effect on syntactic processing
English (e.g., Cutler, 1993; Gleitman & Wanner, (Steinhauer, Alter, & Friederici, 1999), suggesting
1982; Monaghan, Chater & Christiansen, 2005; a rapid, on-line role for this important cue. While
Monaghan, Christiansen & Chater, 2007; prosody is influenced to some extent by a num-
Morgan, Shi, & Allopenna, 1996; Shi, Morgan, & ber of nonsyntactic factors, such as breathing pat-
Allopenna, 1998). Phonological information may terns, resulting in an imperfect mapping between
also help separate nouns and verbs (Monaghan prosody and syntax (Fernald & McRoberts,
et al., 2005, 2007; Onnis & Christiansen, 2008). 1996), infants’ sensitivity to prosody argues for its
For example, English disyllabic nouns tend to likely contribution to syntax acquisition (Fisher &
receive initial-syllable (trochaic) stress whereas Tokura, 1996; Gerken 1996; Morgan, 1996).
disyllabic verbs tend to receive final-syllable Distributional characteristics of linguis-
(iambic) stress, and adults are sensitive to this tic fragments at or below the word level may
distinction (Kelly, 1988). Acoustic analyses also provide cues to grammatical category.
have also shown that disyllabic words that are Morphological patterns across words may
noun–verb ambiguous and have the same stress be informative—e.g., English words that are
placement can still be differentiated by syllable observed to have both –ed and –s endings are
duration and amplitude cue differences (Sereno likely to be verbs (Maratsos & Chalkley, 1980). In
& Jongman, 1995). Even 3-year-old children are artificial language learning experiments, adults
sensitive to this stress cue, despite the fact that acquire grammatical categories more effectively
few multisyllabic verbs occur in child-directed when they are cued by such word-internal pat-
speech (Cassidy & Kelly, 1991, 2001). Additional terns (Brooks, Braine, Catalano & Brody, 1993;
noun/verb cues in English likely include dif- Frigo & McDonald, 1998). Corpus analyses
ferences in word duration, consonant voicing, reveal that word co-occurrence also gives useful
and vowel types, and many of these cues may cues to grammatical categories in child-directed
be cross-linguistically relevant (see Kelly, 1992; speech (e.g., Mintz, 2003; Monaghan et al., 2005,
Monaghan & Christiansen, 2008, for reviews). 2007; Redington, Chater, & Finch, 1998). Given
90 WORDS, LANGUAGE, AND MUSIC

that function words primarily occur at phrase segmentation, and may provide further cueing
boundaries (e.g., initially in English and French of syntactic relations. Despite the value of each
and finally in Japanese), they can also help the source, none of these cues in isolation suffices
learner by signaling syntactic structure. This to solve the bootstrapping problem. The learner
idea has received support from corpus analyses must integrate these multiple cues to overcome
(Mintz, Newport & Bever, 2002) and artificial the limited reliability of each individually. This
language learning studies (Green, 1979; Morgan review has indicated that a range of language-in-
et al., 1987; Valian & Coulson, 1988). Finally, ternal cues is available for language acquisition,
artificial language learning experiments indi- that these cues affect learning and processing,
cate that duplication of morphological patterns and that mechanisms exist for multiple-cue inte-
across related items in a phrase (e.g., Spanish: gration. What is yet unknown is how far these
Los Estados Unidos) <COMP: Keep underline cues can be combined to solve the bootstrapping
for clarity.> facilitates learning (Meier & Bower, problem (Fernald & McRoberts, 1996). Here we
1986; Morgan et al., 1987). present connectionist simulations to demon-
It is important to note that there is ample strate that efficient and robust computational
evidence that children are sensitive to these mechanisms exist for multiple-cue integration
multiple sources of information. After just 1 year (see also the chapters in this volume by Hannon,
of language exposure, the perceptual attune- Kirkham, and Saffran, for evidence from human
ment of children likely allows them to make infant learning).
use of language-internal probabilistic cues (for
reviews, see Jusczyk, 1997, 1999; Kuhl, 1999;
SIMULATION 1: MULTIPLE- CUE
Pallier, Christophe & Mehler, 1997; Werker &
INTEGRATION
Tees, 1999). Through early learning experiences,
infants already appear sensitive to the acoustic Although the multiple-cue approach is gaining
differences between function and content words support in developmental psycholinguistics, its
(Shi, Werker & Morgan, 1999) and the relation- computational efficacy still remains to be estab-
ship between function words and prosody in lished. The simulations reported in this chapter
speech (Shafer, D. W. Shucard, J. L. Shucard & are therefore intended as a first step toward a
Gerken, 1998). Young infants are able to detect computational approach to multiple-cue inte-
differences in syllable number among isolated gration, seeking to test its potential value in
words (Bijeljac, Bertoncini & Mehler, 1993). In syntax acquisition. Based on our previous expe-
addition, infants exhibit rapid distributional rience with modeling multiple-cue integration
learning (e.g., Gómez & Gerken, 1999; Saff ran, in speech segmentation (Christiansen, Allen, &
Aslin, & Newport, 1996; see Gómez & Gerken, Seidenberg, 1998), we used a simple recurrent
2000; Saff ran, 2003 for reviews), and impor- network (SRN; Elman, 1990) to model the inte-
tantly, they are capable of multiple-cue integra- gration of multiple cues. The SRN is feed-forward
tion (Mattys, Jusczyk, Luce, & Morgan, 1999; neural network equipped with an additional
Morgan & Saff ran, 1995). When facing the copy-back loop that permits the learning and
bootstrapping problem, children probably also processing of temporal regularities in the stimuli
benefit from characteristics of child-directed presented to it (see Figure 5.1). This makes it par-
speech, such as the predominance of short sen- ticularly suitable for exploring the acquisition of
tences (Newport, Gleitman & Gleitman, 1977) syntax, an inherently temporal phenomenon.
and exaggerated prosody (Kuhl et al., 1997). The networks were trained on corpora of
In summary, phonological information helps artificial child-directed speech generated by a
to distinguish function words from content grammar that includes three probabilistic cues
words and nouns from verbs. Prosodic informa- to grammatical structure: word length, lexical
tion helps word and phrasal/clausal segmenta- stress, and pitch. The grammar (described fur-
tion, thus serving to uncover syntactic structure. ther below) was motivated by considering fre-
Distributional characteristics aid in labeling and quent constructions in child-directed speech in
CONNECTIONIST EXPLORATIONS OF MULTIPLE-CUE INTEGRATION 91

Time t + 1

Lexical layer

1:1 copy back

Hidden layer Context layer

Activation at time t – 1

Lexical input

Time t

Figure 5.1 The general architecture of the simple-recurrent network (SRN) employed across simula-
tions. An input layer representing information relevant for individual words along with an utterance
boundary marker feeds into a hidden layer, and then to an output that predicts information relevant
to the following word in a corpus. The hidden layer copies itself to a context layer, which supplies a
limited memory for past words.

the CHILDES database (MacWhinney, 2000). Materials


Simulation 1 demonstrates how the integration
We constructed an idealized but relatively com-
of these three cues benefits the acquisition of
plex grammar based on independent analyses
syntactic structure by comparing performance
of child-directed speech corpora (Bernstein-
across the eight possible cue combinations
Ratner, 1984; Korman, 1984) and a study of
ranging from the absence of cues to the pres-
child-directed speech by mother–daughter
ence of all three.
pairs (Fisher & Tokura, 1996). As illustrated in
Method Table 5.1, the grammar included three primary
sentence types: declarative, imperative, and
Networks interrogative sentences. Each type consisted
Ten networks were trained per condition, with of a variety of common utterances reflecting
an initial randomization of network connec- the child’s exposure. For example, declarative
tions in the interval [–0.1, 0.1]. Learning rate sentences most frequently appeared as transi-
was set to 0.1, and momentum to 0. Each input tive or intransitive verb constructions (the boy
to the networks contained a localist representa- chases the cat, the boy swims), but also included
tion of a word (one unit = one word) and a set of predication using be (the horse is pretty) and
cue units depending on cue condition. Words second person pronominal constructions com-
were presented one by one, and networks were monly found in child-directed corpora (you are
required to predict the next word in a sentence a boy). Interrogative sentences were composed
along with the corresponding cues for that of wh-questions (where are the boys?, where do
word. With a total of 44 words (see below) and a the boys swim?), and questions formed by using
pause marking boundaries between utterances, auxiliary verbs (do the boys walk?, are the cats
the networks had 45 input units. Networks in pretty?). Imperatives were the simplest class of
the condition with all available cues had an sentences, appearing as intransitive or transitive
additional five input units. The number of input verb phrases (kiss the bunny, sleep). Subject–verb
and output units thus varied between 45 and 50 agreement was upheld in the grammar, along
across conditions. Each network had 80 hidden with appropriate determiners accompanying
units and 80 context units. nouns (the cars vs. *a cars).
92 WORDS, LANGUAGE, AND MUSIC

Table 5.1 The Stochastic Phrase-Structure Grammar Used to Generate Training Corpora for
Simulations 1–4
S → Imperative [0.1] | Interrogative [0.3] | Declarative [0.6]
Declarative → NP VP [0.7] | NP-ADJ [0.1] | That-NP [0.075] | You-P [0.125]
NP-ADJ → NP is/are adjective

That-NP → that/those is/are NP

You-P → you are NP


Imperative → VP
Interrogative → Wh-Question [0.65] | Aux-Question [0.35]

Wh-Question → where/who/what is/are NP [0.5] |

Where/who/what do/does NP VP [0.5]

Aux-Question → do/does NP VP [0.33] |

Do/does NP wanna VP [0.33] |

is/are NP adjective [0.34]


NP → a/the N-sing/N-plur
VP → V-int | V-trans NP

Each word was assigned a unit for input into thermometer encoding—that is, one unit would
the model, and we added a number of units to be on for monosyllabic words, two for bisyl-
represent cues. Two basic cues were available to labic words, and three for trisyllabic words.
all networks. The fundamental distributional Pitch change is a cue associated with syllables
information inherent in the grammar could that precede pauses. Fisher and Tokura (1996)
be exploited by all networks in this simulation. found that these pauses signaled grammatically
As a second basic cue, utterance-boundary distinct utterances with 96% accuracy in child-
pauses signaled grammatically distinct utter- directed speech, allowing pitch to serve as a cue
ances with 92% reliability (Broen, 1972). Th is to grammatical structure. In the networks, this
was encoded as a single unit that was activated cue was a single unit that would be activated at
at the end of all but 8% of the sentences. Other the fi nal word in an utterance. Finally, we used
semireliable prosodic and phonological cues a single unit to encode lexical stress as a pos-
accompanied the phrase-structure grammar: sible cue to distinguish stressed content words
word length, stress, and pitch. Network groups from the reduced, unstressed form of function
were constructed using different combinations words. Th is unit would be on for all content
of these three cues. Cassidy and Kelly (1991) words.
demonstrated that syllable count is a cue avail-
Procedure
able to English speakers to distinguish nouns
and verbs. They found that the probability of Eight groups of networks, one for each combi-
a single syllable word to be a noun rather than nation of cues (all cues, 2 cues, 1 cue, or none),
a verb is 38%. Th is probability rises to 76% at were trained on corpora consisting of 10,000
two syllables, and 92% at three. We selected sentences generated from the grammar. Each
verb and noun tokens that exhibited this dis- network within a group was trained on a dif-
tinction, whereas the length of the remaining ferent randomized training corpus. Training
words was typical for their class (i.e., function consisted of 200,000 input/output presentations
words tended to be monosyllabic). Word length (words), or approximately 5 passes through the
was represented in terms of three units using training corpus. Each group of networks had
CONNECTIONIST EXPLORATIONS OF MULTIPLE-CUE INTEGRATION 93

cues added to its training corpus depending on able to assess SRN performance on novel sen-
cue condition. Networks were expected to pre- tences in which the definite determiner “the”
dict the next word in a sentence, along with the followed the example fragment (as in “The boy
appropriate cue values. A corpus consisting of chases the cat”’). Formally, we thus have the fol-
1,000 novel sentences was generated for testing. lowing Equation 1 with ci denoting the category
Performance was measured by assessing the of the ith word in the sentence:
networks’ ability to predict the next set of gram-
Freq(c1 , c2 ,!, c p−1 , c p )
matical items given prior context. Importantly, P (c p | c1 , c2 ,!, c p−1 ) ≅ (5.1)
this measure did not include predictions of cue Freq(c1 , c2 ,!, c p−1 )
information, and all network conditions were
where the probability of getting some member
thus evaluated by exactly the same performance
of a given lexical category as the pth item, cp, in
criterion.
a sentence is conditional on the previous p–1
To provide a statistical benchmark with
lexical categories. Note that for the purpose of
which to compare network performance, we
performance assessment, singular and plural
trained bigram and trigram models on the
nouns are assigned to separate lexical categories
same corpora as the networks. These finite-state
throughout Simulations 1–4, as are singular
models, borrowed from computational linguis-
and plural verbs. Given that the choice of lexical
tics, provide a simple prediction method based
items for each category is independent, and that
on strings of two (bigrams) or three (trigrams)
each word in a category is equally frequent, the
consecutive words. Comparisons with these
probability of encountering a particular word
simple models provide an indication of whether
wn, which is a member of a category cp, is simply
the networks are learning more than simple
inversely proportional to the number of items,
two- or three-word associations.
Cp, in that category. So, overall, we have the fol-
Results lowing equation:

After training, SRNs trained with localist out- Freq(c1 , c2 ,!, c p−1 , c p )
P (wn | c1 , c2 ,!, c p−1 ) ≅ (5.2)
put representations will produce a distributional Freq(c1 , c2 ,!, c p−1 )C p
pattern of activation closely corresponding to a
probability distribution of possible next items. If the networks are performing optimally, then
In order to assess the overall performance of the vector of output unit activations should
the SRNs, we made comparisons between net- exactly match these probabilities. We evaluate
work output probabilities and the full condi- the degree to which each network performs suc-
tional probabilities given the prior context. For cessfully by measuring the mean squared error
example, the full conditional probabilities given between the vectors representing the network’s
the context of “The boy chases . . . ” can be rep- output and the conditional probabilities (with 0
resented as a vector containing the probabili- indicating optimal performance).
ties of being the next item in this sentence for All networks achieved better performance
each of the 44 words in the vocabulary and the than the standard bigram/trigram models
pause. To ensure that our performance measure (p-values < .0001), suggesting that the networks
can deal with novel test sentences not seen dur- had acquired knowledge of syntactic structure
ing training, we estimate the prior conditional beyond the information associated with simple
probabilities based on lexical categories rather pairs or triples of words. Figure 5.2A illustrates
than individual words (Christiansen & Chater, the best performance achieved by the trigram
1999). Suppose, in the example above, that every model as well as SRNs provided with no cues
continuation of this sentence fragment in the (the baseline network), a single cue (length,
training corpus always involved the indefinite stress, or prosody), and three cues. The nets pro-
determiner “a” (as in “The boy chases a cat”). If vided with one or more phonological/prosodic
we did not base our full conditional probability cues achieved significantly better performance
estimates on lexical categories, we would not be than baseline networks (p-values < .02). Using
94 WORDS, LANGUAGE, AND MUSIC

trigram performance as criterion, all multiple- Finally, using Brown-Forsyth tests for variability
cue networks surpassed this level of performance in the final level of performance, we found that
faster than the baseline networks as shown in the three-cue networks also exhibited signifi-
Figure 5.2B (p-values < .002). Moreover, the cantly more uniform learning than the baseline
three-cue networks were significantly faster networks (F(1,18) = 5.14, p < .04), as depicted in
than the single-cue networks (p-values < .001). Figure 5.2C.

A 0.100

0.095
Final mean squared error

0.090

0.085

0.080

0.075

0.070
Trigram Baseline Length Stress Pitch All cues

B 90
80
Amount of training to trigram

70
60
mean (x 1000)

50
40
30
20
10
0
Baseline Length Stress Pitch All cues

C 3.5

3.0

2.5
Variance (Z-score)

2.0

1.5

1.0

0.5

0.0
Baseline Length Stress Pitch All cues

Figure 5.2 Comparison of learning performance for different cue combinations in Simulation 1,
showing that multiple-cue integration leads to (A) better learning (as measured by the lowest error
obtained on the test corpus), (B) faster learning (measured in terms of the amount of training needed
to surpass the performance of the trigram model), and (C) more uniform learning (as indicated by less
variance across the performance of the different instances of the network). (Error bars = S.E.M.)
CONNECTIONIST EXPLORATIONS OF MULTIPLE-CUE INTEGRATION 95

SIMULATION 2:SENTENCE match the stimuli in Shady and Gerken. Twelve


COMPREHENSION IN 2-YEAR- OLDS sentences for each prosody condition (pause
location) were constructed. Pauses were sim-
Simulation 1 provides evidence for the general ulated by activating the utterance-boundary
feasibility of multiple-cue integration for sup- unit. Because these pauses probabilistically sig-
porting syntax learning. To further demon- nal grammatically of distinct utterances, the
strate the relevance of the model to language utterance-boundary unit provides an approxi-
development, closer contact with human data mation of what the children in the experiment
is needed (Christiansen & Chater, 2001). In would experience. Finally, the nonsense word
the current simulation, we demonstrate that was added to the stimuli for the within group
the three-cue networks from Simulation 1 are condition (grammatical vs. ungrammatical
able to accommodate experimental data show- vs. nonsense). Adjusting for vocabulary differ-
ing that 2-year-olds can integrate grammatical ences, the networks were tested on comparable
markers (function words) and prosodic cues sentences, such as (2):
in sentence comprehension (Shady & Gerken,
1999: Experiment 1). In this study, children 2. Where does [e] the/is/gub [u] dog [l] eat?
heard sentences, such as (1) [see below], in one of
three prosodic conditions depending on pause Procedure
location: early natural [e], late natural [l], and Each group of networks was exposed to the set
unnatural [u]. Each sentence moreover involved of sentences corresponding to its assigned pause
one of three grammatical markers: grammati- location (early vs. late vs. unnatural). No learn-
cal (the), ungrammatical (was), and nonsense ing took place, since the fully trained networks
(gub). were used. To approximate the picture selec-
1. Find [e] the/was/gub [u] dog [l] for me. tion task in the experiment, we measured the
degree to which the networks would activate
The child’s task was to identify the correct picture the groups of nouns following the/is/gub. The
corresponding to the target noun (dog). Children two conditions were expected to affect the acti-
performed the task best when the pause location vation of the nouns.
delimited a phrasal boundary (early/late), and
with the grammatical marker the. Simulation 2 Results
models these data by using comparable stimuli
and assessing noun unit activations. The human results for the prosody condition in
Shady and Gerken (1999) is depicted in Figure
Method 5.3A. They reported a significant effect of pros-
ody on the picture selection task. The same
Networks
was true for our networks (F(2,33) = 1,253.07,
Twelve three-cue networks of the same archi- p < .0001), and the pattern of noun activations
tecture and training used in Simulation 1 closely resembles that of the toddlers’ correct
were used in each prosodic condition in the picture choice as evidenced by Figure 5.3B.
infant experiment. Th is number was chosen The late natural condition elicited the highest
to match the number of infants in the Shady noun activation, followed by the early natural
and Gerken (1999) experiment. An additional condition, and with the unnatural condition
unit was added to the networks to encode the yielding the least activation. The experiment
nonsense word (gub) in Shady and Gerken’s also revealed an effect of grammaticality as can
experiment. be seen from the human data shown in Figure
5.3C. We similarly obtained a significant gram-
Materials
maticality effect for our networks (F(2,70) =
We constructed a sample set of sentences 69.85, p < .0001), which, as illustrated by Figure
from our grammar that could be modified to 5.3D, produced the highest noun activation
96 WORDS, LANGUAGE, AND MUSIC

A 70 B 0.6
Percent correct picture identification

Accumulated Noun Activation


60 0.5
50
0.4
40
0.3
30
0.2
20

10 0.1

0 0.0
Early Late Unnatural Early Late Unnatural

C 70 D
Percent correct picture identification

0.8
60
Accumulated Noun Activation

0.7
50 0.6
40 0.5
0.4
30
0.3
20
0.2
10 0.1
0 0.0
Grammatical Nonsense Ungrammatical Grammatical Nonsense Ungrammatical

Figure 5.3 The effect of prosody and grammatical markers on human and SRN sentence processing.
(A) Percent correct picture identification by 2-year-olds in the prosody condition of the Shady and
Gerken (1999) experiment, with pauses inserted early, late, or in the unnatural position between the
determiner and the noun. (B) Total activation of nouns by the SRN when exposed to the same pro-
sodic manipulation as the human children. (C) Picture identification performance in the grammatical
marker condition in Shady and Gerken (1999), involving a grammatical, nonsense, or ungrammatical
word before the target noun. (D) Matching SRN activation of nouns for the same three types of gram-
matical markers. (Error bars = S.E.M.)

following the determiner, followed by the non- 1996). Thus, the results suggest that the syntac-
sense word, and lastly for the ungrammatical tic knowledge acquired by the networks mirrors
word. Again, the network results match the the kind of sensitivity to syntactic relations and
pattern observed for the toddlers. One slight prosodic content observed in human children.
discrepancy is that the networks are producing Together with Simulation 1, the results also
higher noun activation following the nonsense demonstrate that multiple-cue integration may
word compared to the ungrammatical marker. both facilitate syntax acquisition, and underlie
This result is however consistent with the results some patterns of linguistic skill observed early
from a more sensitive picture selection task, on in human performance. In the next simula-
showing that children were more likely to end tion, we show that the multiple-cue perspective
up with a semantic representation of the tar- can simulate possible prosodic scaffolding that
get following nonsense syllables compared to occurs much earlier in development: prenatal
incorrectly used morphemes (Carter & Gerken, attunement to prosody.
CONNECTIONIST EXPLORATIONS OF MULTIPLE-CUE INTEGRATION 97

SIMULATION 3: THE ROLE OF PRENATAL the prediction of following words, ignoring the
EXPOSURE cue units.

Studies of 4-day-old infants suggest that the Results


attunement to prosodic information may begin
prior to birth (Mehler et al., 1988). We suggest Both network groups exhibited significantly
that this prenatal exposure to language may pro- higher performance than the bigram/trigram
vide a scaffolding for later syntactic acquisition models (F(1,18) = 25.32, p < .0001 for prenatal,
by initially focusing learning on certain aspects F(1,18) = 12.03, p < .01 for non-prenatal), again
of prosody and gross-level properties of phonol- indicating that the networks are acquiring com-
ogy (such as word length) that later will play an plex grammatical regularities that go beyond
important role in postnatal multiple-cue inte- simple adjacency relations. We compared the
gration. In the current simulation, we test this performance of the two network groups across
hypothesis using the connectionist model from different degrees of training using a two-way
Simulations 1 and 2. If this scaffolding hypoth- analysis of variance with training condition
esis is correct, we would expect that prenatal (prenatal vs. non-prenatal) as the between-net-
exposure corresponding to what infants receive work factor and amount of training as within-
in the womb would result in improved acquisi- network factor (five levels of training measured
tion of syntactic structure. in 20,000 input/output presentation intervals).
There was a main effect of training condition
Method (F(1,18) = 12.36, p < .01), suggesting that pre-
natal exposure significantly improved learning.
Networks
A main effect of degrees of training (F(9,162) =
Ten SRNs were used in both prenatal and non- 15.96, p < .001) reveals that both network groups
prenatal groups, with the same initial condi- benefited significantly from training. An inter-
tions and training details as Simulation 1. Each action between training conditions and degrees
network was supplied with the full range of cues of training indicates that the prenatal networks
used in Simulation 1. learned significantly better than postnatal net-
works (F(1,18) = 9.90, p < .01). Finally, as illus-
Materials
trated by Figure 5.4, prenatal input also resulted
A set of “fi ltered” prenatal stimuli was gener- in faster learning (measured in terms of the
ated using the same grammar as previously amount of training needed to surpass the tri-
(Table 5.1), with the exception that input/out- gram model; F(1,18) = 9.90, p < .01). The expo-
put patterns now ignored individual words and sure to prenatal input—void of any information
only involved the units encoding word length, about individual words—promotes better per-
stress, pitch change and utterance boundar- formance on the prediction task as well as faster
ies. The postnatal stimuli were the same as in learning overall. This provides computational
Simulation 1. support for the prenatal scaffolding hypothesis,
derived as a prediction from the multiple-cue
Procedure
perspective on syntax acquisition.
The networks in the prenatal group were first
trained on 100,000 input/output fi ltered pre-
SIMULATION 4: MULTIPLE- CUE
sentations drawn from a corpus of 10,000 new
INTEGRATION WITH USEFUL AND
sentences. Following this prenatal exposure, the
DISTRACTING CUES
nets were then trained on the full input patterns
exactly as in Simulation 1. The non-prenatal So far, simulations have demonstrated the
group only received training on the postnatal importance of cue integration in syntax acqui-
corpora. As previously, networks were required sition, that integration can match data obtained
to predict the following word and correspond- in infant experiments, and that this perspec-
ing cues. Performance was again measured by tive can provide novel predictions in language
98 WORDS, LANGUAGE, AND MUSIC

35

Amount of training to trigram mean (x 1000)


30

25

20

15

Figure 5.4 Speed of learning 10


for networks trained with or
without prenatal exposure to 5
prosody and gross-level prop-
erties of phonology. (Error bars 0
= S.E.M.) No prenatal Prenatal

development. A possible objection to these cue, word-final voicing, also does not provide
simulations is that our networks succeed at useful distinguishing properties of word classes.
multiple-cue integration because they are only Finally, as an additional prenatal and postnatal
provided with cues that are at least partially cue, overall pitch quality was added to the stim-
relevant for syntax acquisition. Consequently, uli. This was intended to capture whether the
performance may potentially drop signifi- speaker was female or male. In prenatal train-
cantly if the networks themselves had to dis- ing, this probability was set to be extremely high
cover which cues were partially relevant and (90%), and lower in postnatal training (60%).
which are not. Simulation 4 therefore tests the In the womb, the mother’s voice naturally pro-
robustness of our multiple-cue approach when vides most of the input during the final trimes-
faced with additional, uncorrelated distractor ter when the infant’s auditory system has begun
cues. Accordingly, we added three distractor to function (Rubel, 1985). The probability used
cues to the previous three reliable cues. These here was intended to capture the likelihood that
new cues encoded the presence of word-initial some experience would derive from other speak-
vowels, word-final voicing, and relative (male/ ers as well. In postnatal training, this probability
female) speaker pitch—all acoustically salient drops, representing exposure to male members
in speech, but which do not appear to cue syn- of the linguistic community, but still favoring
tactic structure. mother–child interactions.
Procedure
Method
Prenatal stimuli included the three previous
Networks
semireliable cues, and only the additional pro-
Networks, groups, and training details were the sodic, distractor cue encoding relative speaker
same as in Simulation 3, except for three addi- pitch. In the postnatal stimuli, all three dis-
tional input units encoding the distractor cues. tractor cues were added. Training and testing
details were the same as in Simulation 3.
Materials
Results
The three distractor cues were added to the stim-
uli used in Simulation 3. Two of the cues were As in Simulations 1 and 3, both groups per-
phonetic and therefore available only in postna- formed significantly better than the bigram/
tal training. The word-initial vowel cue appears trigram models (F(1,18) = 18.95, p < .0001 for
in all words across classes. The second distractor prenatal, and F(1,18) = 14.27, p < .001 for non-
CONNECTIONIST EXPLORATIONS OF MULTIPLE-CUE INTEGRATION 99

25
Amount of training to trigram mean (x 1000)

20

15

10

5
Figure 5.5 Speed of learning
for networks trained with or
0 without distractor cues. (Error
Good cues only Including distractors bars = S.E.M.)

prenatal). We repeated the two-factor analysis artificial corpora. Next, we scale up the model
of variance computed for Simulation 2, reveal- to deal with naturalistic child-directed speech.
ing a main effect for training condition (F(1,18)
= 4.76, p < .05) and degrees of training (F(9,162)
SIMULATION 5: MULTIPLE- CUE
= 13.88, p < .0001). This indicates that the pres-
INTEGRATION WITH FULL- BLOWN
ence of the distractor cues did not hinder the
CHILD - DIRECTED SPEECH
improved performance following prenatal lan-
guage exposure. As in Simulation 3, the prenatal In this final simulation, we take a further step
networks learned comparatively faster than the toward describing the computational underpin-
non-prenatal networks (F(1,18) = 5.31, p < .05). nings of multiple-cue integration. The previous
To determine how the distractor cues affected series of simulations have demonstrated that
performance, we compared the prenatal con- SRNs provide a suitable model for integrating
dition in Simulation 3 with that of the current multiple cues when exposed to input generated
simulation. There was no significant difference by a psychologically motivated artificial gram-
in performance across the two simulations mar. Here we further show that the SRN scales
(F(1,18) = 0.13, p = .72). Moreover, as shown in up to deal with real child-directed speech. In
Figure 5.5, there was no difference in the speed particular, we seek to determine the extent to
of learning between the SRNs trained only which these networks are sensitive to the lex-
with good cues and those whose input included ical category information present in the set of
distractor cues (F(1,18) = .57, p = .46). A fur- phonological cues. To accomplish this task, we
ther comparison between these non-prenatal set up two identical groups of networks, each
networks and the bare networks in Simulation provided with a different encoding of the cor-
1 showed that the networks trained with cues pus. The encoding of the first corpus was based
of mixed reliability significantly outperformed on 16 phonological cues, previously shown by
networks trained without any cues (F(1,18) = Monaghan et al. (2005) to provide information
14.27, p < .001). This indicates that the uncor- useful for syntax acquisition. The second set
related cues did not prevent the networks from of input was encoded using the same cue vec-
integrating the partially reliable ones toward tors but randomized across lexical categories.
learning grammatical structure. Together with Possible performance differences in networks
the first three simulations, Simulation 4 dem- trained with these different input sets would be
onstrates that SRNs can integrate multiple cues due to lexical category information revealed by
efficiently when exposed to relatively complex the multiple phonological cues.
100 WORDS, LANGUAGE, AND MUSIC

Method over a 4- to 5-month period when the children


were between the ages of 1 year and 1 month
Networks
to 1 year and 9 months. The corpus includes
Ten SRNs were used for the phonetic-input 1,371 word types and 33,035 tokens distributed
condition and the random-input condition, over 10,082 utterances. The sentences incorpo-
with an initial weight randomization in the rate a number of different types of grammatical
interval [–0.1, 0.1]. A different random seed was structures, showing the varied nature of the lin-
used for each simulation. Learning rate was guistic input to children. Utterances range from
set to 0.1 and momentum to 0.7. Each input to declarative sentences (Oh you need some space)
the network contained a thermometer encod- to wh-questions (Where’s my apple) to one-word
ing for each of the 16 phonological cues from utterances (“Uh” or “hello”). Each word in the
Monaghan et al. (2005), listed in Table 5.2. This corpus corresponded to one of the 14 following
encoding required 43 units (each of them in a lexical categories: nouns (19.5%), verbs (18.5%),
range from 0 to 1) and a pause marking bound- adjectives (4%), numerals (<0.1%), adverbs
aries between utterances, resulting in the net- (6.5%), articles (6.5%), pronouns (18.5%), prep-
works having 44 input units. Each output was ositions (5%), conjunctions (4%), interjections
encoded using a localist representation consist- (7%), complex contractions (8%), abbreviations
ing of 14 different lexical categories and a pause (<0.1%), infinitive markers (1.2%), and proper
marking boundaries between utterances, result- names (1.2%). The training set consisted of
ing in networks with 15 output units. Each net- 9,072 sentences (29,930 word tokens) from the
work furthermore was equipped with 88 hidden original corpus. A separate test set consisted of
units and 88 context units. 963 additional sentences (2,930 word tokens).
Each word was encoded in terms of the
Materials
following 16 phonological cues from Table 5.2:
We trained and tested the network on a corpus number of phonemes (1–11), number of syllables
of child-directed speech (Bernstein-Ratner, (1–5), stress position (0 = no stress, 1 = 1st
1984). This corpus contains speech recorded syllable stressed, etc.), proportion of reduced
from nine mothers speaking to their children vowels (0–1), proportion of coronal consonants

Table 5.2 Phonological Cues that Distinguish between Lexical Categories

Nouns and Verbs


Nouns have more syllables than verbs (Kelly, 1992)
Bisyllabic nouns have 1st syllable stress, verbs tend to have 2nd syllable stress (Kelly & Bock, 1988)
Inflection -ed is pronounced /d/ for verbs, /@d/ or /Id/ for adjectives (Marchand, 1969)
Stressed syllables of nouns have more back vowels than front vowels. Verbs have more front vowels than
back vowels (Sereno & Jongman, 1990)
Nouns have more low vowels, verbs have more high vowels (Sereno & Jongman, 1990)
Nouns are more likely to have nasal consonants (Kelly, 1992)
Nouns contain more phonemes per syllable than verbs (Kelly, 1996)

Function and Content Words


Function words have fewer syllables than content words (Morgan, Shi & Allopenna, 1996)
Function words have minimal or null onsets (Morgan, Shi & Allopenna, 1996)
Function word onsets are more likely to be coronal (Morgan, Shi & Allopenna, 1996)
/D/ occurs word-initially only for function words (Morgan, Shi & Allopenna, 1996)
Function words have reduced vowels in the first syllable (Cutler, 1993)
Function words are often unstressed (Gleitman & Wanner, 1982)
CONNECTIONIST EXPLORATIONS OF MULTIPLE-CUE INTEGRATION 101

(0–1), number of consonants in onset (1–3), on to use pragmatic and other cues to discover
consonant complexity (0–1), initial /D/ (1 if the meaning of words. Given that the networks
begins /D/, 0 otherwise), reduced first vowel in our simulations only have access to linguis-
(1 if first vowel is reduced, 0 otherwise), any tic information, we see lexical categories as a
stress (0 if no stress, 1 otherwise), final inflec- “stand-in” for more ecologically valid cues that
tion (0 if none, /@d/ or /Id/, 1 if present), stress we hope to be able to include in future work.
vowel position (from front to back, 1–3), vowel
position (mean position of vowels, from front Results
to back, 1–3), final consonant voicing (0: vowel,
We recorded the output vectors for the two
1: voiced, 2: unvoiced), proportion of nasal con-
groups of networks. Because the output con-
sonants (0–1) and mean height of vowels (0–3).
sisted of localist representations for each lex-
The cues that assume only binary values were
ical category (one unit = one lexical category)
encoded using a single unit (e.g., “any stress”,
along with the utterance-fi nal pause, we could
“initial /D/”). The cues that take on values
use Equation 5.1 to estimate the full condi-
between 0 and 1 (e.g., proportion of vowel con-
tional probabilities, comparing network pre-
sonants) were also encoded using a single unit
dictions to the full conditional probabilities for
with a decimal number, whereas the cues that
the next lexical category using the mean cosine
assume values in a broader range (e.g., number
of the angle between the two vectors (with 1
of syllables) were represented using a thermom-
corresponding to optimal performance). We
eter encoding; for example, one unit would
compared the predictions of the phonetic-in-
be on for monosyllabic words, two for bisyl-
put networks with those of the random-input
labic words, and so on. Finally we used a single
networks. Figure 5.6A shows a comparison of
unit that would be activated at pauses between
test–set performance for the phonetic-input net-
utterances.
works with that of the random-input networks.
The random-input networks were trained
The phonetic-input networks were significantly
using input for which we randomly distributed
better than the random-input networks at pre-
the multiple-cue vectors among all the words
dicting the next combination of lexical catego-
in the corpus. Thus, the vector encoding for a
ries (p-values < .00005). These results suggest
given word would be randomly reassigned to
that distributional information is generally a
a different word in the corpus regardless of its
stronger cue than phonological information,
lexical category. Each phonological vector was
even though the latter does lead to better learn-
assigned to only one word. Moreover, each
ing overall. However, phonological information
token of a word was represented using the same
may provide the networks with a better basis for
random vector for all occurrences of that word
processing novel lexical items. Next, we probe
in the test and training sets.
the internal representations of the two sets of
Procedure networks in order to gain further insight into
their performance differences.
Ten networks were trained on phonological
cues and 10 control networks were trained on Probing the Internal Representations
the random vectors. Training consisted of one
pass through the training corpus. We used Simulation 5 indicated that the phonetic-input
the same 10 random seeds for both simulation networks did not benefit as much as one perhaps
conditions. The networks were trained to pre- would have expected from the information pro-
dict the lexical category of the next word. The vided by the phonological cues. However, the
task of mapping phonological cues onto lex- networks may nonetheless use this information
ical categories may seem somewhat artificial to develop internal representations that better
because children are not provided directly with encode differences between lexical categories.
the lexical categories of the words to which they This may allow them to go beyond the phonetic
are exposed. However, children do learn early input and integrate it with the distributional
102 WORDS, LANGUAGE, AND MUSIC

A 0.70 B

80

Percent correct classification


0.65
Final mean cosine

70
0.60

0.55 60

0.50 50
Distrib cues only Phon + Distrib cues Distrib cues only Phon + Distrib cues

Figure 5.6 Performance of the network models trained on full-blown child-directed speech. (A) Test
performance for networks provided only with distributional cues and networks provided with both
phonological and distributional cues. (B) Results of the discriminant analyses, comparing the ability
of the two types of networks to place themselves in a “noun state” and a “verb state” when processing
novel nouns and verbs, respectively. (Error bars = S.E.M.)

information derived from the sequential order vector when the hidden unit activations were
in which these vectors were presented. To inves- recorded for a noun (phonetic) input vector. We
tigate these possibilities, we carried out a series also included a condition in which the noun/
of discriminant analyses of network hidden unit verb labels were randomized with respect to the
activations as well as of the phonetic input vec- hidden unit vectors for both sets of networks, in
tors, focusing on the representations of nouns order to establish a random control.
and verbs.
Results
Method
We first compared the categorization perfor-
Informally, a linear discriminant analysis mance of the two sets of networks, as illustrated
allows us to determine the degree to which it in Figure 5.6B. The phonetic-input networks
is possible to separate a set of vectors into two had developed hidden unit representations
(or more) groups based on the information con- that allowed them to correctly separate 80.30%
tained in those vectors. In effect, we attempt to of the 400 nouns and verbs. This was signifi-
use a linear plane to split the hidden unit space cantly better than the random-input networks,
into a group of noun vectors and a group of verb which only achieved 73.15% correct separation
vectors. Using discriminant analyses, we can (t(8) = 5.89, p < .0001). Both sets of networks
statistically estimate the degree to which this surpassed their respective randomized controls
split can be accomplished given a set of vectors. (phonetic-input control: 69.05% – t(8) = 11.51,
We recorded the hidden unit activations p < .0001; random-input control: 68.20% –
from the two sets of networks in Simulation 5. t(8) = 3.92, p < .004). The controls for the two
The hidden unit activations were recorded for sets of networks were not significantly different
200 novel nouns and 200 novel verbs occurring from each other (t(8) = 0.82, p > .43). As indicated
in unique sentences taken from other CHILDES by our previous analyses of phonetic cue infor-
corpora (MacWhinney, 2000). The hidden unit mation in child-directed speech (Monaghan
activations were labeled such that each corre- et al., 2005), the phonetic input vectors con-
sponded to the particular lexical category of the tained a considerable amount of information
input presented to the network (though the net- about lexical categories, allowing for 67.25%
works did not receive this information as input). correct separation of nouns and verbs, but
For example, a vector would be labeled a noun still significantly below the performance of the
CONNECTIONIST EXPLORATIONS OF MULTIPLE-CUE INTEGRATION 103

phonetic-input networks (t(4) = 25.97, p < .0001). the service of syntactic acquisition when trained
The random-input networks also surpassed the on a naturalistic corpus of child-directed speech
level of separation afforded by their input vec- (Simulation 5). Analysis of the networks’ hidden
tors (59.00% – t(4) = 12.80, p < .0001). unit activations provided further evidence that
The results of the hidden-unit discriminant the integration of phonological and distribu-
analyses suggest that not only did the phonet- tional cues during learning leads to more robust
ic-input networks develop internal representa- internal representations of lexical categories, at
tions better suited for distinguishing between least when it comes to distinguishing between
nouns and verbs, but they also went beyond the the two major categories of nouns and verbs.
information afforded by the phonetic input and Overall, the simulation results presented in
integrate it with distributional information. this chapter provide support not only for the
Crucially, the phonetic-input vectors were able multiple-cue integration approach in general,
to surpass the random-input networks, despite but also for using neural network architectures
that the latter was also able to use distributional to explore the integration of distributional,
information to go beyond the input. Consistent prosodic, and phonological information in lan-
phonological information thus appears to be guage acquisition. Some researchers have chal-
important for network generalization to novel lenged the value of multiple probabilistic cues
nouns and verbs. (e.g., Fernald & McRoberts, 1996), but we have
computationally demonstrated that their inte-
gration results in faster, better, and more uni-
GENERAL DISCUSSION
form learning, even in the face of distracting
As described in an earlier part of this chapter, information. Our simulations, along with arti-
children who are learning syntax face a complex ficial language learning experiments (Billman,
“chicken-and-egg” bootstrapping problem. A 1989; Brooks et al., 1993; McDonald & Plauche,
growing bulk of evidence from developmental 1995; Morgan et al., 1987), underscore multiple-
cognitive science has suggested that a solution cue integration as a means of facilitating the
may come from a process of integrating mul- complex task of syntax acquisition.
tiple sources of probabilistic information, each We have elsewhere explored the evolution-
of which is individually unreliable, but jointly ary emergence of phonological cues in agent-
advantageous (cf. Smith & Pereia chapter in based simulations (Christiansen & Dale, 2004).
this volume). What has so far been lacking is a In these evolutionary simulations, languages
demonstration of the computational feasibility were mutated slightly across generations of ran-
of this approach and the series of simulations domized SRN learners. For any given genera-
reported here takes a first step toward accom- tion, the languages best learned by the networks
plishing this. We have demonstrated that pro- were allowed to be passed down to the next
viding SRNs with prosodic and phonological generation. Results showed that there emerges
cues significantly improves their acquisition of cross-linguistic variation in stable linguistic
syntactic structure (Simulation 1), and that the cues. Nevertheless, observed stable cue sys-
three-cue networks can mimic children’s sen- tems were consistent in that syntactic categories
sitivity to both prosodic and grammatical cues were marked by phonological cues, as found in
in sentence comprehension (Simulation 2). The English, French, Japanese, and other languages
model illustrates the potential value of prenatal (as reviewed above). This stability was particu-
exposure (Simulation 3) and provides evidence larly strong when languages had larger lexicons,
for the robustness of multiple-cue integration, indicating that multiple-cue integration may
since highly unreliable cues did not interfere have contributed to language evolution by aid-
with the integration process (Simulation 4). ing a learner’s acquisition of growing set of lexi-
Finally, we expanded these results by showing cal items and classes.
that SRNs can also utilize highly probabilistic Because different natural languages employ
information found in 16 phonological cues in different constellations of cues to signal syntactic
104 WORDS, LANGUAGE, AND MUSIC

distinctions, an important question for further context information to resolve a syntactically


research is exactly how a child’s learning mech- ambiguous sentence does not appear until
anisms discover which cues are relevant and about 8 years of age, considerably later than the
for which aspects of syntax. This problem is knowledge of constraints on constructions that
compounded by the fact that the same cue may may follow specific verbs (Snedeker & Trueswell,
work in different directions across different 2004). To reveal cue integration and its develop-
languages. A case in point is that nouns tend to ment, models must capture the developmental
contain more vowels and fewer consonants than trajectory of cue use across different phases of
verbs in English, whereas nouns and verbs in language acquisition. We anticipate that the
French show the opposite pattern (Monaghan availability of so-called “dense” corpora, which
et al., 2007). So how can the child learn which sample the child’s input at a higher frequency
cues are relevant and in which direction? One (e.g., Behrens, 2006; Maslen, Theakston, Lieven,
possibility may be to encode the correlations & Tomasello, 2004), will help the development
between cues in the linguistic environment. of such constructivist-oriented models of lan-
This view is supported by related mathemati- guage acquisition.
cal analyses based on the Vapnik-Chervonenkis Future work should therefore provide more
(VC) dimension (Abu-Mostafa, 1993), showing detailed analysis of the developmental trajec-
that the integration of multiple “hints” or cues tory of multiple-cue integration. Most work
of correlated information reduces the number of on cue availability in the child’s environment
hypotheses a learning system has to entertain. makes the simplifying assumption that all infor-
The VC dimension specifies an upper bound for mation is available to the child simultaneously.
the amount of input needed by a learning pro- This is an oversimplification: Children’s pro-
cess that starts with a set of hypotheses about ductions indicate that the whole of language is
a task solution. Cue information may lead to not acquired in one step, but that overlapping
a reduction in the VC dimension by weeding phases of acquisition occur, where learning
out unhelpful hypotheses and thus lowering progress at any one time relies on progress that
the number of examples needed to find a solu- preceded it. Attempts to explain and exploit
tion. In other words, the integration of multiple these learning phases in computational mod-
cues may reduce learning time by reducing the els has been successful in accounting for early
number of steps necessary to find an appropri- processing constraints that facilitate later learn-
ate function approximation, as well as reduce ing of complex syntactic structures (Elman,
the set of candidate functions considered, thus 1993), phrasal productions and errors in young
potentially ensuring better generalization. children (Freudenthal, Pine, & Gobet, 2005),
More generally, the development of compu- and the development of the lexicon (Steyvers
tational multiple-cue integration models is still & Tenenbaum, 2005). Such approaches could
in its infancy. There now exists a wealth of sup- equally be applied to the computational sim-
port for the usefulness of multiple probabilis- ulation of multiple-cue integration reported
tic cues for language acquisition, and although in this chapter: The reliability of phonological,
theoretical models abound (e.g., Gleitman & prosodic, or distributional cues could be based
Wanner, 1982; and contributions in Morgan & on the most frequent, or earliest-learned words,
Demuth, 1996; Weissenborn & Höhle, 2001), and constructed incrementally, and such a con-
only a few psychologically plausible computa- structivist approach would enhance the cogni-
tional models for multiple-cue integration are tive plausibility of the availability and process of
on offer (e.g., Cartwright & Brent, 1997). Extant use of such cues by the developing child.
models tend to capture the end-state of learn- The wide array of phonological, prosodic,
ing rather the developmental process itself. This and distributional information sources in pri-
approach cannot identify the time course of dif- mary linguistic input may make the child’s
ferent cues as they become important for acqui- learning task substantially easier than it might
sition. For example, the ability to use visual seem when we consider only the complexities
CONNECTIONIST EXPLORATIONS OF MULTIPLE-CUE INTEGRATION 105

of syntax that they acquire. A domain-general utterances? Developmental Psychology, 29,


learning mechanism, such as the SRN archi- 711–721.
tecture used here, can capitalize on this rich Billman, D. (1989). Systems of correlations in rule
information to acquire deep domain-specific and category learning: Use of structured input
knowledge that emerges through developmen- in learning syntactic categories. Language and
Cognitive Processes, 4, 127–155.
tal time. Along with this language-internal
Broen, P. (1972). The verbal environment of the
information, surely innate and language-exter- language-learning child. ASHA Monographs,
nal constraints also contribute to the task, and No. 17. Washington, DC: American Speech
future work should aim to integrate all three and Hearing Society.
fundamental sources of constraints. We have Brooks, P. J., Braine, M. D., Catalano, L. & Brody,
nevertheless shown that even with relatively R. E. (1993). Acquisition of gender-like noun
simple domain-general assumptions about the subclasses in an artificial language: The con-
learner, multiple-cue integration can facilitate tribution of phonological markers to learning.
the complex task of syntax acquisition. Theories Journal of Memory and Language, 32, 76–95.
of the language learner therefore should not Carter, A. & Gerken, L. A. (1996). Children’s use of
overburden innate and language-external con- grammatical morphemes in on-line sentence
comprehension. In E. Clark (Ed.), Proceedings
straints where language-internal multiple-cue
of the Twenty-Eighth Annual Child Language
integration can help. Research Forum (Vol. 29). Palo Alto, CA:
Stanford University Press.
Cartwright, T. A. & Brent, M. R. (1997). Syntactic
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS categorization in early language acquisition:
This research was supported in part by a Formalizing the role of distributional analysis.
Human Frontiers Science Program Grant Cognition, 63, 121–170.
(RGP0177/2001-B) to M.H.C. Some of the material Cassidy, K. W., & Kelly, M. H. (1991). Phonological
in this chapter was adapted from Christiansen, information for grammatical category assign-
M. H., & Dale, R. (2001), Integrating distribu- ments. Journal of Memory and Language, 30,
tional, prosodic and phonological information in 348–369.
a connectionist model of language acquisition, in Cassidy, K. W., & Kelly, M. H. (2001). Children’s
Proceedings of the 23rd Annual Conference of the use of phonology to infer grammatical class in
Cognitive Science Society (pp. 220–225), Mahwah, vocabulary learning. Psychonomic Bulletin and
NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum, and Reali, F., Christiansen, Review, 8, 519–523.
M. H., & Monaghan, P. (2003), Phonological and Christiansen, M. H., Allen, J., & Seidenberg, M. S.
distributional cues in syntax acquisition: Scaling (1998). Learning to segment speech using mul-
up the connectionist approach to multiple-cue tiple cues: A connectionist model. Language
integration, in Proceedings of the 25th Annual and Cognitive Processes, 13, 221–268.
Conference of the Cognitive Science Society Christiansen, M. H., & Chater, N. (1999). Toward
(pp. 970–975), Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum. a connectionist model of recursion in human
linguistic performance. Cognitive Science, 23,
157–205.
REFERENCES Christiansen, M. H., & Chater, N. (2001).
Connectionist psycholinguistics: Capturing
Abu-Mostafa, Y. S. (1993) Hints and the VC dimen- the empirical data. Trends in Cognitive Sciences,
sion. Neural Computation, 5, 278–288. 5, 82–88.
Behrens, H. (2006). The input–output relationship Christiansen, M. H., & Dale, R. (2004). The role
in first language acquisition. Language and of learning and development in the evolu-
Cognitive Processes, 21, 2–24. tion of language. A connectionist perspec-
Bernstein-Ratner, N. (1984). Patterns of vowel tive. In D. Kimbrough Oller & U. Griebel
modification in motherese. Journal of Child (Eds.), Evolution of communication systems:
Language, 11, 557–578. A comparative approach. The Vienna Series in
Bijeljac, R., Bertoncini, J., & Mehler, J. (1993). How Theoretical Biology (pp. 90–109). Cambridge,
do 4-day-old infants categorize multisyllabic MA: MIT Press.
106 WORDS, LANGUAGE, AND MUSIC

Cutler, A. (1993). Phonological cues to open-and Jusczyk, P. W. (1999). How infants begin to
closed-class words in the processing of spoken extract words from speech. Trends in Cognitive
sentences. Journal of Psycholinguistic Research, Sciences, 3, 323–328.
22, 109–131. Jusczyk, P. W., & Kemler-Nelson, D. G. (1996).
Elman, J. L. (1990). Finding structure in time. Syntactic units, prosody, and psychologi-
Cognitive Science, 14, 179–211. cal reality during infancy. In J. L. Morgan &
Elman, J. L. (1993). Learning and development in K. Demuth (Eds.), Signal to syntax: Boot-
neural networks: The importance of starting strapping from speech to grammar in early
small. Cognition, 48, 71–99. acquisition (pp. 389–408). Mahwah, NJ:
Fernald, A., & McRoberts, G. (1996). Prosodic Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
bootstrapping: A critical analysis of the argu- Karmiloff-Smith, A. (1979). A functional approach
ment and the evidence. In J. L. Morgan & to child language: A study of determiners
K. Demuth (Eds.), From Signal to syntax and reference. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
(pp. 365–388). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum University Press.
Associates. Kelly, M. H. (1988). Phonological biases in gram-
Fisher, C., & Tokura, H. (1996). Acoustic cues matical category shifts. Journal of Memory and
to grammatical structure in infant-directed Language, 27, 343–358.
speech: Cross-linguistic evidence. Child Kelly, M. H. (1992). Using sound to solve syntactic
Development, 67, 3192–3218. problems: The role of phonology in grammati-
Freudenthal, D., Pine, J. M., & Gobet, F. (2006). cal category assignments. Psychological Review,
Modelling the development of children’s use of 99, 349–364.
optional infi nitives in English and Dutch using Kemler-Nelson, D. G., Hirsh-Pasek, K., Jusczyk, P.
MOSAIC. Cognitive Science, 30, 277–310. W., & Wright Cassidy, K. (1989). How the pro-
Frigo, L., & McDonald, J. L. (1998). Properties of sodic cues in motherese might assist language
phonological markers that affect the acqui- learning. Journal of Child Language, 16, 55–68.
sition of gender-like subclasses. Journal of Korman, M. (1984). Adaptive aspects of maternal
Memory and Language, 39, 218–245. vocalization in differing contexts at ten weeks.
Gerken, L. A. (1996). Prosody’s role in language First Language, 5, 44–45.
acquisition and adult parsing. Journal of Kuhl, P. K. (1999). Speech, language, and the brain:
Psycholinguistic Research, 25, 345–356. Innate preparation for learning. In M. Konishi
Gerken, L. A., Jusczyk, P. W., & Mandel, D. R. & M. Hauser (Eds.), Neural mechanisms of
(1994). When prosody fails to cue syntactic communication (pp. 419–450). Cambridge,
structure: Nine-month-olds’ sensitivity to pho- MA: MIT Press.
nological vs. syntactic phrases. Cognition, 51, Kuhl, P. K., Andruski, J. E., Chistovich, I. A.,
237–265. Chistovich, L. A., Kozhevnikova, E. V., Ryskina,
Gleitman, L. & Wanner, E. (1982). Language V. L., et al. (1997). Cross-language analysis
acquisition: The state of the state of the art. of phonetic units in language addressed to
In E. Wanner & L. Gleitman (Eds.), Language infants. Science, 277, 684–686.
acquisition: The state of the art (pp. 3–48). MacWhinney, B. (2000). The CHILDES project:
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Tools for analyzing talk (3rd ed.). Mahwah, NJ:
Gómez, R. L., & Gerken, L. A. (1999). Artificial Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
grammar learning by 1-year-olds leads to spe- Maratsos, M., & Chalkley, M. A. (1980). The inter-
cific and abstract knowledge. Cognition, 70, nal language of children’s syntax: The ontogen-
109–135. esis and representation of syntactic categories.
Gómez, R. L., & Gerken, L. A. (2000). Infant arti- In K. Nelson (Ed.), Children’s language (Vol. 2,
ficial language learning and language acquisi- pp. 127–214). New York: Gardner Press.
tion. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 4, 178–186. Maslen, R., Theakston, A., Lieven, E., & Tomasello,
Green, T. R. G. (1979). The necessity of syntax M. (2004) A dense corpus study of past tense
markers: Two experiments with artificial lan- and plural overregularization in English.
guages. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Journal of Speech, Language and Hearing
Behavior, 18, 481–496. Research, 47, 1319–1333.
Jusczyk, P. W. (1997). The discovery of spoken Mattys, S. L., Jusczyk, P. W., Luce, P. A., & Morgan,
language. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. J. L. (1999). Phonotactic and prosodic effects
CONNECTIONIST EXPLORATIONS OF MULTIPLE-CUE INTEGRATION 107

on word segmentation in infants. Cognitive Morgan, J. L., Shi., R., & Allopenna, P. (1996).
Psychology, 38, 465–494. Perceptual bases of grammatical categories. In
McDonald, J. L., & Plauche, M. (1995). Single J. L. Morgan & K. Demuth (Eds.), Signal to syn-
and correlated cues in an artificial language tax: Bootstrapping from speech to grammar in
learning paradigm. Language and Speech, 38, early acquisition. (pp. 263–283). Mahwah, NJ:
223–236. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Mehler, J., Jusczyk, P. W., Lambertz, G., Halsted, Newport, E. L., Gleitman, H., & Gleitman, L. R.
N., Bertoncini, J., & Amiel-Tison, C. (1988). (1977). Mother, I’d rather do it myself: Some
A precursor of language acquisition in young effects and non-effects of maternal speech style.
infants. Cognition, 29, 143–178. In C. E. Snow & C. A. Ferguson (Eds.), Talking
Meier, R. P., & Bower, G. H. (1986). Semantic refer- to children: Language input and acquisition
ence and phrasal grouping in the acquisition of (pp. 109–149). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
a miniature phrase structure language. Journal University Press.
of Memory and Language, 25, 492–505. Onnis, L., & Christiansen, M. H. (2008). Lexical
Mintz, T.H. (2003). Frequent frames as a cue categories at the edge of the word. Cognitive
for grammatical categories in child directed Science, 32, 184–221.
speech. Cognition, 90, 91–117. Pallier, C., Christophe, A., & Mehler, J. (1997).
Mintz, T. H., Newport, E. L., & Bever, T. G. Language-specific listening. Trends in Cognitive
(2002). The distributional structure of gram- Sciences, 1, 129–132.
matical categories in speech to young children. Pinker, S. (1984). Language learnability and lan-
Cognitive Science, 26, 393–424. guage development. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
Monaghan, P., Chater, N., & Christiansen, M. H. University Press.
(2005). The differential contribution of phono- Redington, M., Chater, N., & Finch, S. (1998).
logical and distributional cues in grammatical Distributional information: A powerful cue
categorisation. Cognition, 96, 143–182. for acquiring syntactic categories. Cognitive
Monaghan, P., & Christiansen, M. H. (2008). Science, 22, 425–469.
Integration of multiple probabilistic cues in Rubel, E. W. (1985). Auditory system develop-
syntax acquisition. In H. Behrens (Ed.), Trends ment. In G. Gottlieb & N. A. Krasnegor (Eds.),
in corpus research: Finding structure in data Measurement of audition and vision in the first
(pp. 139–163) (TILAR Series). Amsterdam: year of postnatal life (pp. 53–89). Norwood, NJ:
John Benjamins. Ablex.
Monaghan, P., Christiansen, M. H., & Chater, N. Saffran, J. R. (2003). Statistical language learn-
(2007). The phonological–distributional coher- ing: Mechanisms and constraints. Current
ence hypothesis: Cross-linguistic evidence in Directions in Psychological Science, 12, 110–114.
language acquisition. Cognitive Psychology, 55, Saff ran, J. R., Aslin, R. N., & Newport, E. L. (1996).
259–305. Statistical learning by 8-month-old infants.
Morgan, J. L. (1996). Prosody and the roots of Science, 274, 1926–1928.
parsing. Language and Cognitive Processes, 11, Sereno, J. A., & Jongman, A. (1995). Acoustic cor-
69–106. relates of grammatical class. Language and
Morgan, J. L., & Demuth, K. (1996). Signal to syn- Speech, 38, 57–76.
tax: Bootstrapping from speech to grammar Shady, M., & Gerken, L. A. (1999). Grammatical
in early acquisition. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence and caregiver cues in early sentence comprehen-
Erlbaum Associates. sion. Journal of Child Language, 26, 163–175.
Morgan, J. L., Meier, R. P., & Newport, E. L. (1987). Shafer, V. L., Shucard, D. W., Shucard, J. L., &
Structural packaging in the input to language Gerken, L. A. (1998). An electrophysiologi-
learning: Contributions of prosodic and mor- cal study of infants’ sensitivity to the sound
phological marking of phrases to the acqui- patterns of English speech. Journal of Speech,
sition of language. Cognitive Psychology, 19, Language, and Hearing Research, 41, 874–886.
498–550. Shi, R., Morgan, J., & Allopenna, P. (1998).
Morgan, J. L., & Saff ran, J. R. (1995). Emerging Phonological and acoustic bases for earliest
integration of sequential and suprasegmental grammatical category assignment: A cross-
information in preverbal speech segmentation. linguistic perspective. Journal of Child
Child Development, 66, 911–936. Language, 25, 169–201.
108 WORDS, LANGUAGE, AND MUSIC

Shi, R., Werker, J. F., & Morgan, J. L. (1999). Tomasello, M., Kruger, A. C., & Ratner, H. H.
Newborn infants’ sensitivity to perceptual cues (1993). Cultural learning. Behavioral and Brain
to lexical and grammatical words. Cognition, Sciences, 16, 495–552.
72, B11–B21. Valian, V., & Coulson, S. (1988). Anchor points in
Snedeker, J., & Trueswell, J. (2004). The devel- language learning: The role of marker frequency.
oping constraints on parsing decisions: The Journal of Memory and Language, 27, 71–86.
role of lexical-biases and referential scenes in Valian, V., & Levitt, A. (1996). Prosody and adults’
child and adult sentence processing. Cognitive learning of syntactic structure. Journal of
Psychology, 49(3), 238–299. Memory and Language, 35, 497–516.
Steinhauer, K., Alter, K., & Friederici, A. D. (1999). Weissenborn, J., & Höhle, B. (Eds.) (2001).
Brain potentials indicate immediate use of Approaches to bootstrapping: Phonological, lex-
prosodic cues in natural speech processing. ical, syntactic and neurophysiological aspects of
Nature Neuroscience, 2, 191–196. early language acquisition. Philadelphia, PA:
Steyvers, M., & Tenenbaum, J. (2005). The large John Benjamins.
scale structure of semantic networks: Statistical Werker, J. F., & Tees, R. C. (1999). Influences
analyses and a model of semantic growth. on infant speech processing: Toward a new
Cognitive Science, 29, 41–78. synthesis. Annual Review of Psychology, 50,
Tomasello, M. (2000). The item-based nature of 509–535.
children’s early syntactic development. Trends
in Cognitive Sciences, 4, 156–163.
CHAP TER 6
Shape, Action, Symbolic Play, and
Words: Overlapping Loops of Cause
and Consequence in Developmental Process

Linda B. Smith and Alfredo F. Pereira

Human beings are remarkably inventive, learning through developmental changes in


possessing the ability to solve problems and visual object recognition.
to create novel things. Th is chapter is about At a broader level, this chapter is about the
one early form of inventiveness that has long fundamentally constructive nature of develop-
intrigued developmentalists—what is some mental process itself: how development creates
times called symbolic play, but more narrowly, new forms of behaviors and abilities from inter-
is also known as “object substitution in play.” action of multiple processes, engaged in differ-
The specific phenomenon consists of young ent assemblies in overlapping tasks; how every
children using some object not for what it is developmental cause is itself a consequence of
but as a “stand in” for something else in play—a developmental process; how development is
banana as a phone, a box as a doll bed, a shoe made of weird loops of causes and consequences
as a toy car. Piaget (1962) considered object- with far-reaching and unexpected developmen-
substitution in play—the using of a banana as tal dependencies.
phone, for example—as “symbolic” because A summary of the developmental story we
the substituted object could be interpreted as will narrate is provided by Figure 6.1: Learning
“standing for” the real thing. Th is view that object names increases children’s attention to
object-substitution is a form of symbolizing shape, which in turn speeds up object name
(whatever precisely that means) has been dis- learning. Learning object names also changes
puted (Namy, 2002; Perner, 1991). Regardless of how children perceive object shape, which facil-
different opinions on this issue, object substi- itates learning and generalizing object names
tution in play remains a signal of developmen- and of actions. Acting on objects, in turn, refines
tal achievement, emerging at the same time (18 and tunes—making even more abstract—the
to 24 months) as children’s spoken vocabulary representation of object shape. Along the way,
also expands. Perhaps most critically, object we will suggest and provide evidence for the
substitution in play is strongly linked to indi- idea that the abstract representation of object
vidual children’s language development (see shape is the critical link between object name
McCune, 1995; McCune-Nicolich, 1981; Shore, learning and object substitutions in play.
O’Connell, & Bates, 1984; Veneziano, 1981),
with the lack of this behavior being a strong
LOOP 1: LEARNING TO ATTEND
predictor of significant subsequent language
TO OBJECT SHAPE
delay (e.g., McCune-Nicolich, 1981; Weismer,
2007). This chapter is about how and why these Common object categories, categories such as
object substitutions may be linked to language chair, cup, spoon, house, and dog are (by adult

109
110 WORDS, LANGUAGE, AND MUSIC

Learing substantial area of research has generated a


object names large number of well-replicated results impor-
tant to the first loop.
Attention to First, attention to shape increases as children
shape
learn object names. Children initially (12- to
18-month-olds, see Gershkoff-Stowe & Smith,
Perception of 2004; Rakison & Butterworth, 1998a, 1998b)
object shape do not systematically attend to object shape in
naming and categorization tasks, but increas-
ingly do so in the period between 18 and 30
Symbolic
play/action months. Moreover, longitudinal studies show
that in individual children, the emergence of the
Figure 6.1 Loops of causes and consequences in shape bias is temporally linked to a measurable
the development of visual object recognition. spurt in the growth of object name vocabulary
(Gershkoff-Stowe & Smith, 2004). Attention to
shape also predicts developmental delays. Late
judgment) well organized by shape (Biederman, talkers—children delayed in their early noun
1987; Rosch, Mervis, Gray, Johnson, & Boyes- acquisitions—show systematic deficits in atten-
Braem, 1976; Samuelson & Smith, 1999). More tion to object shape in naming tasks (Jones,
critically, in the vocabulary of typically devel- 2003; Jones & Smith, 2005).
oping 2-year-olds, over 70% of the nouns are for Second, attention to shape is causally related
objects similar in shape (Samuelson & Smith, to object name learning. Teaching children to
1999). Accordingly, a large literature has been attend to shape facilitates novel noun acqui-
concerned with children’s attention to three- sitions and accelerates the rate of real-world
dimensional object shape in the context of early vocabulary development (Smith, Jones, Landau,
word learning. Landau, Smith, and Jones (1988) Gershkoff-Stowe & Samuelson, 2002; see also,
reported one key result: They showed 2- and Samuelson, 2002). This study was a 9-week lon-
3-year-old children a novel wooden object of gitudinal study. The children were 17 months
a particular shape and named it with a novel of age at the start—too young to show a shape
count noun, “This is a dax.” The children were bias in novel noun generalization tasks and
then presented with test objects that matched also on the early side of the increasing rate of
the exemplar in shape, size, or texture and new object names that begins around 18 to 22
were asked about each of those objects “Is this months for most children. The children in the
a dax?” Children generalized the name to test “Experimental” condition came to the labo-
objects that were the same in shape as the exem- ratory once a week for 7 weeks. During that
plar but not to test objects that were different in time, they played with 4 pairs of objects. The
shape. The degree of children’s selective atten- objects in each pair matched in shape but dif-
tion to shape was considerable: for example, fered markedly in all other properties—color,
they extended the name “dax” to same-shaped texture, material, and size. The objects in each
test objects that were 100 times the size of the pair were named by the same novel name (e.g.,
original. This “shape bias” in novel noun gener- “dax, riff, zup, toma”) and during each weekly
alization tasks has been demonstrated in many play session, the experimenter named each of
different studies and by different experimenters these training objects by its designated name at
using a variety of both specially constructed and least 20 times.
real objects (e.g., Gathercole & Min, 1997; Imai, On week 8, children’s ability to general-
Gentner, & Uchida, 1994; Keil, 1994; Soja, 1992) ize these trained names was tested. If children
and is evident in children learning a variety of learned that two particularly shaped objects
languages (Colunga & Smith, 2005; Gathercole were “daxes,” would they judge a novel object—
& Min, 1997; Yoshida & Smith, 2003). This new size, new color, new material but the same
SHAPE, ACTION, SYMBOLIC PLAY, AND WORDS 111

shape—to also be “a dax?” The answer is yes; 1994) at the start and end of the experiment.
the children learned the category. On week 9, There was a marked increase in new noun learn-
children were tested in a novel noun general- ing for children in the Experimental but not the
ization task, with all new objects and all new Control conditions, and training influenced the
names. If shown a new never-before-seen thing rate with which children in the Experimental
and told its name, would these children know condition added new objects names to their
how to generalize the name to new instances by vocabulary but not the rate with which they
shape? Again, the answer is yes. The children added other words. Learning names for things
learned not just about particular categories and in shape-based categories teaches children to
the importance of shape, but also that shape in attend to shape when generalizing names for
general matters for naming objects. A variety things, and doing so accelerates the learning of
of control conditions were run in these series new object names, lexical categories that are in
of training studies, including grouping with- general well-organized by shape.
out naming, playing with objects with neither These training experiments may be micro-
grouping or naming, or learning names for genetic and targeted versions of what hap-
groups organized by texture or color. None of pens in the everyday development. In the real
the children in these training groups general- world, young children more slowly learn names
ized novel names for novel things on week 9 by for many different things at the same time.
shape. Although these categories are not as well orga-
The most dramatic result from these studies nized by the shape as the training categories,
is the finding that training children to attend many are categories of things that are mostly
to shape in this laboratory task increased their similar in shape. As children learn these catego-
rate of new object name acquisitions outside of ries, attention to shape in the context of nam-
the laboratory. Figure 6.2 shows the number of ing things may increase, and, as a consequence,
object names in children’s productive vocabu- children may learn object names more rapidly,
lary (as measured by the MCDI, Fenson et al., which should further tune attention to object

80 80

70 70
Mean number of object names

Mean number of other words

60 60

50 50

40 40

30 30

20 20

10 10

0 0
Pre (17 months) Post (19 months) Pre (17 months) Post (19 months)
Trained
Control

Figure 6.2 Object names and other words in children’s productive vocabulary at the start and end of
training in the Smith et al. (2002) study.
112 WORDS, LANGUAGE, AND MUSIC

shape. Every word learned sets the stage for and table as a particular and favorite cup. Although
constrains future learning. The shape bias in competing theories of object recognition
early noun learning is in this way both a cause (Biederman, 1987; Edelman, 1999; Ullman,
and a consequence of learning object names. 2000) often pit different kinds of hypothesized
processes and representations against each
other, it is likely that human object recognition
LOOP 2: BUILDING ABSTRACT
is dependent on a multitude of partially distinct
REPRESENTATIONS OF OBJECT SHAPE
and partially overlapping processes (Hayward,
There is one critical unexplained aspect of Loop 2003; Hummel, 2000; Marr, 1982; Peissig &
1. In order for a shape bias to work to help chil- Tarr, 2007; Peterson, 1999). That is, no single
dren learn names for everyday object categories, mechanism is likely to explain the full range of
children must be able to recognize sameness in contexts in which people recognize objects as
shape across different instances of a category. individuals and as instances of categories.
This is trivial in artificial noun-learning tasks Theories of object recognition that concen-
since all objects are relatively simple and “same- trate on how people rapidly recognize instances
shaped” (objects are the exact same shape). But of novel categories (and approaches to machine
this is not trivial in the real world. In order for vision that attempt to build devices that can rec-
children to learn, for example, that chairs are ognize novel instances of categories) often pro-
“chair-shaped” and to use that knowledge to rec- pose processes of shape recognition that depend
ognize a new chair, they must be able to abstract on abstract, sparse representations of the global
the common shape from a whole array of chairs shapes of things. There are two general classes
that have been experienced, each with its own of such theories. According to “view-based”
unique and detailed shape. Real world instances theories, people store representations of specific
of common noun categories, though judged by views of experienced instances and use proto-
adults to be the “same shape” (e.g., Samuelson types—a kind of average simplified shape that
& Smith, 1999) are not exactly the same shape, captures the global structure—to recognize new
but only similar in shape at some appropriate category instance (Edelman, 1995; Edelman
level of abstraction. This then is the critical & Duvdevani-Bar, 1997; Edelman & Intrator,
next question: What is the proper description 1997). In Edelman’s (1995) account, category
of shape for common object categories? When learning plays the critical role in creating proto-
and how do children discover that description? types of the holistic shape of category members.
Before answering this question, we step back to Novel instances are subsequently categorized by
consider what is known about adult shape rep- their overall similarity to these representations.
resentations and visual object recognition. “Object-based” theories such as Biederman’s
The first key fact about human visual object (1987) recognition-by-components (RBC)
recognition is that it is impressive: it is fast, account present another idea about what con-
seemingly automatic, robust under degraded stitutes “sameness in shape.” Th is theory pro-
viewing conditions, and capable of recognizing poses that objects are perceptually parsed,
novel instances of a very large number of com- represented, and stored as configurations of geo-
mon categories (Biederman & Gerhardstein, metric volumes (“geons”). Within this account,
1993; Cooper, Biederman, & Hummel, 1992; object shape is defined by 2 to 4 geometric vol-
Fize, Fabre-Thorpe, Richard, Doyon, & Thorpe, umes in the proper spatial arrangement, an idea
2005; Pegna, Khateb, Michel, & Landis, 2004). supported by the fact that adults need only 2 to
The second key fact is that object recognition 4 major parts to recognize instances of com-
is not a single skill but a consortium of abili- mon categories (Biederman, 1987; Hummel &
ties. For example, in their everyday lives, peo- Biederman, 1992) as illustrated at the bottom of
ple routinely recognize the dog whose nose Figure 6.3. This account thus posits sparse and
is sticking out from the blanket, the highly impoverished representations that, through
unique modernistic chair, and the cup on the their high level of abstraction, can gather all
SHAPE, ACTION, SYMBOLIC PLAY, AND WORDS 113

Figure 6.3 Pictures of some of the three-dimensional objects, richly detailed and shape caricatures,
used in Smith (2003).

variety of highly different things into a “same from sparse representations of the geometric
shape” category. Both classes of theories fit structure as can adults (e.g., Biederman, 1987).
aspects of the adult data, which include strong The experiment specifically contrasted richly
view dependencies in object recognition and detailed typical examples with “shape cari-
also knowledge of part structure and relations. catures” as shown in Figure 6.3. The task was
Accordingly, there is a growing consensus that name comprehension (“get the camera”) and
both kinds of theories may capture important the 18- to 24-month participants were grouped
but different processes in mature object recog- into developmental level by the number of object
nition (Hayward, 2003; Peissig & Tarr, 2007; names in their productive vocabulary. The main
Peterson, 1999; Stankiewicz, 2003; Tarr & results were that children with smaller and
Vuong, 2002). For this chapter, the important larger vocabularies (below 100 object names ver-
point is that both approaches posit that sparse sus more than 100 object names) recognized the
and abstract representations of object shape richly detailed instances equally well. However,
support the recognition of instances of com- children with smaller noun vocabularies per-
mon object categories. The question we want formed at chance levels when presented with
to answer is when and how children develop the shape caricatures, whereas the children
these representations. Despite the importance with high noun vocabularies recognized the
of object recognition to many domains of cog- shape caricatures as well as they did the richly
nitive development, there was, until recently, detailed and typical instances.
extraordinarily little developmental research in These results have been replicated in two
this area (see Kellman, 2001). further studies (Son, Smith, & Goldstone,
The first study (Smith, 2003) asked whether 2008; Pereira & Smith, 2009). Further, a study
young children (18 to 24 months) could rec- of older late talkers (children whose produc-
ognize instances of common object categories tive vocabulary is below the 20th percentile for
114 WORDS, LANGUAGE, AND MUSIC

their age) found a deficit in the recognition of object recognition that are used in different
shape caricatures but not richly detailed typi- contexts or for different kinds of tasks, perhaps
cal instances (Jones & Smith, 2005). Altogether, these processes each have their own develop-
these results suggest a potentially significant mental trajectories with more “fragments”
change in how young children represent and or “feature” processes developing earlier and
compare object shape that is developmentally sparse representations of global geometric
linked to the learning of objects names. In par- structure emerging as a consequence of learn-
ticular, sparse representations of object shape ing many shape-based object categories (see
appear to emerge between 18 and 24 months. also the chapter in this volume by Johnson, for
One other line of research suggests that a similar developmental trajectory in young
these developmental changes may also involve infants’ perceptual completion).
a shift in the kind of stimulus information used Pereira and Smith (2009) provide support for
to categorize and recognize objects. In particu- this idea in a direct comparison of young chil-
lar, a number of studies suggest that children dren’s ability to recognize objects given local
younger than 20 months attend to the individ- featural details versus global geometric struc-
ual parts or local details of objects rather than ture. The stimulus sets that they used resulted
overall shape (Rakison & Butterworth, 1998a). from a 2 × 2 design: the presence and absence
In a series of programmatic studies, Rakison of global information about geometric struc-
and colleagues (Rakison & Butterworth, ture (which they labeled by +Shape Caricature
1998b, Rakison & Cohen, 1999, Rakison and and –Shape Caricature) and localized and fine
Cicchino, 2008) showed that 14- and 22-month detailed information predictive of the category
old children based category decisions on highly (which they labeled by +Local Details and –Local
salient parts (such as legs and wheels) and not Details). Examples of the four stimulus condi-
on overall shape. For example, when children tions are in Figure 6.4. The +Shape Caricatures,
were presented with cows whose legs had been structured as in the Smith (2003) experiment
replaced by wheels, they classified the cows were made from 1 to 4 geometric components
with vehicles rather than animals; likewise they in the proper spatial relations. The –Shape
categorized a vehicle as an animal when it had Caricatures were alterations of the +Shape cari-
cow legs. Similarly, Colunga (2003) showed that catures: the shapes of at least two component
18-month-olds tended to only look at a small volumes were altered and if possible the spatial
part of any pictured object, using clusters of arrangements of two volumes relative to each
local features such as the face when recognizing other were rearranged. The presence of detailed
animals, or the grill and headlights when recog- local information was achieved by painting sur-
nizing vehicles. face details on these volumes that were predic-
These results raise the possibility that very tive of the target category, for example, the face
young children—perhaps before they develop of a dog, wheels, and so forth.
more sparse representations of object struc- Figure 6.5 shows the main result; the darker
ture—recognize objects via what Cerella (1986) bars indicate performance when local details
called “particulate perception,” concentrat- were present (+Local Details) and the solid bars
ing on local components unintegrated into the indicate performance given the +Shape cari-
whole. Such “part”-based object recognition is catures, that is, when the appropriate though
also suggestive of an approach to object recog- sparse global shape structure was present. The
nition that has emerged in the machine vision children in the lowest vocabulary group show
literature: in particular, Ullman has developed their highest level of performance (the darker
a procedure through which objects are success- bars) when the stimuli present local details,
fully recognized via stored representations of and for these stimuli, the presence or absence
category specific fragments (Ullman & Bart, of appropriate shape structure does not matter.
2004; Ullman, Vidal-Naquet, & Sali, 2002). If The children in the most advanced vocabulary
adults possess multiple distinct processes of group perform best given the appropriate sparse
SHAPE, ACTION, SYMBOLIC PLAY, AND WORDS 115

Figure 6.4 Photos of the stimuli used in Pereira and Smith’s (2009) experiment 2. Each set of four
pictures contains clockwise from the upper left: (–Local Details, +Shape Caricature), (–Local Details,
–Shape Caricature), (+Local Details, –Shape Caricature), (+Local Details, +Shape Caricature). The
black line close to each object is one inch in length.

representations of global shape. In brief, there is The very idea that object recognition may
increasing recognition of the shape caricatures change substantially during this developmen-
with increasing vocabulary size and a greater tal period is not commonly considered in stud-
dependence on local features earlier in their ies of categorization and concepts in infancy
vocabulary development. These results add to and early childhood. This is so even though we
the growing number of findings suggesting sig- know that there is at last one domain in which
nificant changes in visual object recognition in recognition undergoes significant changes as
the second year of life (Rakison & Lupyan, 2008; a function of development and experience.
Smith, 2003; Son, Smith, & Goldstone, 2008). Specifically, face recognition is characterized
116 WORDS, LANGUAGE, AND MUSIC

1.00 –Local Details AND +Shape Caricature


–Local Details AND –Shape Caricature
+Local Details AND +Shape Caricature
Proportion of objects correctly categorized

+Local Details AND –Shape Caricature

* Error Bars show Mean ± 1.0 SE


0.80 Bars show Means
*
*: Mean differs from
change (t-test comparing
mean with average
* * * performance of 33% for
0.60 * random choice, p < 0.05)
*

0.40

0.20

Group I Group II Group III

Figure 6.5 Mean proportion of number of objects correctly categorized (out of 6 trials) across the
three groups of vocabulary level for the Local Details × Shape Caricature interaction (Pereira & Smith,
2009). Between-subjects conditions –Local Details and +Local Details are shown in white and black
bars, respectively. Within-subjects conditions +Shape Caricature and –Shape Caricature are shown in
solid and patterned bars, respectively.

by strong early sensitivities in infancy yet also of object shape may foster more rapid category
shows a slow and protracted course of devel- learning and generalization (see especially, Son,
opment with adult-like expertise not achieved Smith, & Goldstone, 2007).
until adolescence (e.g., Mondloch, Le Grand, & At the very least, there is growing evi-
Maurer, 2002). In this context, the idea of signif- dence for significant changes in visual object
icant changes in object recognition and a possi- recognition during the developmental period in
bly protracted course of development seem less which children’s object name learning is rapidly
surprising (as also suggested by Abecassis, Sera, expanding. Multiple kinds of information may
Yonas, & Schwade, 2001). be used to recognize objects and it appears that
It seems likely that the visual system devel- very young children, at the start of a period of
ops the kinds of representations that support the rapid category learning, mostly rely on detailed
task that needs to done (Biederman & Kalocsai, local information to recognize instances of
1997; Nelson, 2001). The task of object recogni- common categories but not more abstract infor-
tion for many different categories with many mation about geometric structure. Children
different potential instances in each category who are only slightly more advanced, how-
may demand a more abstract and geometric ever, do recognize common objects from such
description of object shape—–one in which, for shape caricatures. Th is period of rapid develop-
example, a chair is a horizontal surface (to sit mental change seems crucial to understanding
on) and a vertical surface (to support one’s back). the nature of human object recognition and
The period in which children learn the names may also provide a crucial missing link in our
for many different categories of things could understanding of the developmental trajectory
be a driving force behind these developments. in early object name learning, a trajectory
And certainly, more abstract representations of vocabulary growth that begins slow but
SHAPE, ACTION, SYMBOLIC PLAY, AND WORDS 117

Figure 6.6 Sample stimulus set from Smith and Pereira (2008) for the symbolic play task.

progresses to quite rapid learning characterized around a theme but with one key object miss-
by the fast-mapping of object names to catego- ing. A sample set is shown in Figure 6.6. For
ries of things alike in shape. this set, the child was given a doll, a blanket,
and a pillow—three objects suggesting a “going
Unexpected Connections—Symbolic Play
to bed” theme—but no bed. Instead the fourth
These changes in visual object recognition object was block. The question was whether the
raise a new hypothesis about the develop- child would engage in thematic play, using the
mental origins of object substitutions in play. block as a bed. There were four such sets, the
Although these inventive actions seem likely to bed theme, an eating theme (doll, plate, spoon,
involve many interacting processes (including pompoms to be potentially used as food), a car
wanting to engage in thematic play), they may theme (road, bridge, stoplight, wooden shoe to
also depend critically on abstract descriptions be potentially used as car), and a house theme
of object shape. Using a banana as a phone, a (house, table, chair, and stick to be potentially
shoe as a car, a stick as a bottle, and a pot as a hat used as a person). Because children might inad-
all suggest sensitivity to high-level structural vertently use the object in a way consistent with
properties of shape. Accordingly, in a recently its targeted role, we required that children do
completed study, we examined whether chil- two successive acts involving the target object
dren’s recognition of shape caricatures might in thematic play (e.g., laid the doll on the block
predict the likelihood of object substitutions in then immediately put the blanket on the doll) to
play (Smith & Pereira, 2008). The participants score it as an instance of symbolic play.
were children 17 to 22 months of age. There Figure 6.7 shows the performances of chil-
were three dependent measures: (1) the number dren with fewer and greater than 100 object
of nouns in the children’s productive vocabu- names in their vocabulary: the proportion of
lary (by MCDI parent report, see Fenson et al., shape caricatures they recognized (given they
1993), (2) children’s recognition of common cat- recognized the richly detailed instances) and the
egories from shape caricatures (given that they proportion of trials on which they engaged in
could recognize richly detailed instances of the symbolic play (as defined above). Children with
same thing), and (3) performance in a symbolic fewer than 100 object names in their produc-
play task. tive vocabulary were much less likely to use the
To encourage children to engage in symbolic target objects in thematic play and also much
play, they were given a set of toys organized less likely to recognize the shape caricatures for
118 WORDS, LANGUAGE, AND MUSIC

1 Shape caricature
task
Symbolic play task
Error bars: ± 1.00 SE
0.8
Mean proportion of trials

0.6

0.4

0.2

0
Under 100 nouns Over 100 nouns
Vocabulary lavel

Figure 6.7 Mean proportion of trials on which children with fewer and with more than 100 object
names in productive vocabulary recognized the shape caricatures in the caricature recognition task
and used the target object for the missing object in the symbolic play task (Smith & Pereira, 2008).

common nouns. In contrast, children with over visual object recognition, which are influenced
100 object names in their productive vocabu- by learning names for things.
lary both used the target object for the missing
object and also readily recognized the shape
LOOP 3: ACTION AND SHAPE PERCEPTION
caricatures for common categories. Across the
36 children who participated in this study, there The link between object substitution in play
was a strong correlation between recognition of and the recognition of three-dimensional cari-
shape caricatures and symbolic play (r =.66, p catures of the geometric structure of common
< .001). Further a control study, which replaced objects suggests that an abstract and sparse
the target object with richly detailed instances description of object structure invites the gen-
(e.g., replaced the block with a toy bed, the stick eralization of actions and potentially classes of
with a person), did not yield vocabulary-related actions. This makes sense as there is a strong
differences in symbolic play nor a reliable cor- causal link between the shape of things, how
relation with shape caricature recognition. they are held, how they feel while being held,
Finally, although vocabulary and age are cor- and the actions those objects afford.
related, size of the object name vocabulary is Contemporary research in cognitive neuro-
a better predictor of both symbolic play and science also indicates a coupling between brain
shape caricature recognition than is age (see regions involved in visually recognizing objects
also, Pereira & Smith, 2009). and in producing action that may be particu-
Although many abilities seem likely to be larly relevant to an understanding of the devel-
important to the development of thematic play opmental relationship between the abstraction
and children’s inventive object substitutions in of sparse descriptions of object structure and
that play, these results suggest that these object action. In particular, perceptual-motor interac-
substitutions may be, at least in part, linked to tions have been shown in behavioral paradigms
language through developmental changes in and in recordings of brain activation (Christou
SHAPE, ACTION, SYMBOLIC PLAY, AND WORDS 119

& Bulthoff, 1999; Craighero et al., 1996; Freyd,


1983; Harman, Humphrey, & Goodale, 1999;
James, Humphrey, & Goodale, 2001; James et al.,
2002; Tong et al., 1995; Wexler & von Boxtel,
2005; A. Wohschlager & A. Wohlschlager,
1998). Specifically, there appear to be automatic
links among visual systems used for object per-
ception and recognition, and motor systems
used to act on objects (Arbib, 1981; Chao &
Visual processing Moter plan
Martin, 2000; Grezes & Decety, 2002; James Shape Proprioception
et al., 2006; Longcamp, Boucard, Gilhodes, & Motion Haptic system
Vely, 2005; Paillard, 1991; Vivani & Stucchi,
1992) such that, upon visual perception of an Figure 6.8 A schematic representation of the
object, motor areas are automatically activated. inter-relating of multiple simultaneous repre-
These studies have demonstrated that activation sentations across modalities.
in motor cortices emerges upon visual presenta-
tion of manipulable objects such as tools (Chao
& Martin, 2000) and kitchen utensils (Gerlach Figure 6.8 provides a schematic representa-
et al., 2000 ; Grezes & Decety, 2002; Grezes tion of this possibility—of what Edelman (1987)
et al., 2003; Mecklinger, Gruenewald, Besson, calls re-entry, the explicit interrelating of multi-
Magnie, & Cramon, 2002); and manually cre- ple simultaneous representations across modal-
ated objects such as letters (James & Gauthier, ities. For example, when a child is given a toy
2006; Longcamp et al., 2005). That is, visual to hold and look at, both the visual and motor
presentations of objects with which we have had systems are simultaneously engaged. Together,
extensive motor interactions appear to auto- they yield a constellation of sensations and
matically activate the motor areas responsible movements associated with various actions on
for those actions. the toy and their consequences. Importantly,
There are several open questions about these multimodal experiences are time-locked
these links, including why and how they are and correlated. Changes in the way the hand
constructed, and whether they play a role in feels when it moves the toy are time-locked with
visual recognition (James & Gauthier, 2006; the changes the infant sees as the toy is moved.
Mecklinger et al., 2002; Wexler & van Boxtel, The time-locked correlations potentially create a
2005). One possibility is that such links are powerful learning mechanism, as illustrated in
neural correlates of mere associations, so that the figure, which shows five related mappings.
although the motor regions are activated in One map is between the physical properties of
response to visual stimuli, perhaps as prepara- the toy and the neuronal activity in the visual
tion for action, they play no role in the visual system. Another map is between the physical
recognition of the objects. A second possibility properties of the toy and neuronal activity in
is that these motor activations feed back on and the motor planning, proprioceptive, and haptic
actually influence and help select activations in systems. A third map is between the motor sys-
visual regions. More radically, a third possibility tems and actions on the object. The fourth and
is that a developmental history of the dynamic fift h maps are what Edelman calls the re-entrant
coupling of visual and motor activations con- maps: activity in the visual system is mapped
stitutes the stored representation of the object, to the motor (and haptic and proprioceptive)
with the history of activations in visual regions systems, and activity in the motor system is
influencing stored representations in motor mapped to the visual system. Thus independent
regions, and with the history of activations in mappings of the stimulus—the sight of it and
motor regions influencing stored representa- the action on it—provide qualitatively different
tions in visual regions. takes on the world.
120 WORDS, LANGUAGE, AND MUSIC

By being correlated in real time, these planar and nonplanar views and (2) the major
different takes can potentially educate each axes of an object. We consider each of these in
other. At the same time as the visual system turn, presenting background on why they are
is activated by time-varying changes in visual likely structural properties for seeking a rela-
information about shape and collinear move- tion between action and object recognition and
ment of points on the toy, the motor and pro- also new evidence suggesting marked develop-
prioceptive system is activated by action and mental change during the period between 18 to
felt movements. At every step in real time, the 24 months.
activities in these heterogeneous processes are
Preferred Views
mapped to each other, potentially enabling the
coupled systems through their own activity to There is ample evidence that not all viewpoints
discover higher-order regularities that tran- of objects are equal in terms of the ease with
scend the individual systems considered alone. which an object is recognized from that view-
Again, developmental relations may be bidi- point. Two views—off-axis versus on-axis
rectional—changes in the perception of object views—have generated considerable interest in
shape may foster the generalizations of actions, the adult object recognition literature. These
and action, in turn, may promote attention to or two perspectives, illustrated in Figure 6.9 are
the representation of relevant geometric prop- often called the “3/4” and “planar” (front on and
erties of shape. side on) views. These are the terms we will use
As a first step in considering how action may here. With familiar objects, adults can recog-
educate a sparse structural description shape— nize an object faster from a single image if that
the kind of category encompassing description image is a 3/4 or off-axis view than if it is a planar
that enables one to recognize the sameness in view (Blanz, Tarr, & Bulthoff, 1999; Humphrey
shape across all varieties of shape—we have & Jolicouer, 1993; Lawson & Humphreys, 1998;
concentrated on two structural properties that Newell & Findlay, 1997; Palmer, Rosch, &
are related to each other, commonly considered Chase, 1981). In addition, when asked to pick
important across a wide variety of different the- the “best” view of an object, adults will usually
ories of human and machine visual object rec- pick a 3/4 view (Blanz et al., 1999; Palmer et al.,
ognition and potentially informed by action: (1) 1981). Critically, these results are specific to the

Figure 6.9 A planar and nonplanar view of an object.


SHAPE, ACTION, SYMBOLIC PLAY, AND WORDS 121

recognition of pictures of well-known category 18 and 24 months, the very same period in
instances. When adults are asked to pick the which children learn many object names, in
“best” view of a novel object, the planar views which the shape bias emerges, in which chil-
are picked as often as the 3/4 views (Blanz et al., dren begin to recognize objects from sparse
1999), perhaps because these views are less representations of geometric structure, and
likely to occlude relevant object features that in which they fi rst show shape-based object
cannot be inferred for novel things. Similarly, substitutions in thematic play. One cannot ask
when adults dynamically explore novel objects 18- to 24-month-old children to manipulate
prior to visual recognition tasks, they actually computer-rendered images with a trackball
prefer planar over 3/4 views. That is, during (the method used by James et al.). What we did
active exploration, adults spend a significantly instead was that we asked children to manu-
greater amount of time looking at views of ally and visually explore objects while wearing
objects where axes are foreshortened (front) a head-camera, a methodology for tapping the
or elongated (side) (Harman et al., 1999; James fi rst-person view developed by Yoshida and
et al., 2001, 2002; Perrett & Haries, 1988; Perrett Smith (2008). Children were given novel and
et al., 1992). The suggestion from the above familiar objects to explore as they sat in a chair
work is that the preferred view of an object with no table so that each object could only be
depends upon whether the task is one of rec- held by one or two hands. The child was given
ognition (retrieval of information) or explora- one object at a time to look at and explore for
tion (encoding of information), on whether the up to 20 s.
object in question is highly familiar or novel, The data were coded using a custom-made
and on whether it is a static, two-dimensional soft ware application that allowed a coder to
representation versus an actively perceived compare an image taken from the camera to
three-dimensional thing. an image of a computer-rendered object. Here,
In a series of studies particularly relevant to we will report two analyses. The fi rst is at a
our developmental work, James and colleagues coarser grain, and just asked whether the view
asked the adult subjects to view, for later tests was “near planar” (within 15º) for each of the
of recognition, computer rendered, virtual 3-D 6 possible planar views compared to a random
objects on a computer monitor by rotating them object manipulation. The second analysis yields
using a trackball device (Harman et al., 1999; a detailed continuous presentation of the actual
James et al., 2001). Subjects rotated the objects x, y, and z coordinates, a map of dwell times.
in any dimension (x, y, and z) for a total of 20 The 18-month-old children showed no prefer-
s. The subjects spent most of their viewing time ence for the planar compared to baseline when
on the planar views (see also James et al., 2002; they explored either the novel or the familiar
Perrett & Harries, 1988; Perrett, Harries, & objects. In contrast, the 24-month-old chil-
Looker, 1992). In a separate experiment, James dren showed marked preferences for the pla-
et al. (2001) also showed that dynamically view- nar views for known but not for novel objects
ing mostly planar views facilitated subsequent as shown in Figure 6.10. These results suggest
recognition when compared with the dynamic an emerging preference for planar views in the
viewing of mostly 3/4 views. Thus, not only active exploration of objects that begins with
do adults prefer to study planar views of novel known object shapes and thus potentially may
objects, but also when these views are controlled develop from experience with those particular
experimentally, dwelling on and around the objects. An important detail to consider here
planar views promotes the formation of more is that in the James et al. study, adults spent
robust memories of object shape. around 70% of their dwell time around planar
When and how do these preferences views. Th is is considerably higher that the val-
emerge developmentally? We have new results ues here, even for the older group, so it seems
(Pereira, James, Smith, & Jones, 2007) that that we have identified the beginning of this
suggest that this preference emerges between phenomenon.
122 WORDS, LANGUAGE, AND MUSIC

the very least, all the results reviewed thus far


Proportion dwell time on planar views

suggest that fundamentally important changes


30% in visual object recognition—evident in a vari-
ety of task domains—are occurring between
Novel 18 and 24 months.
Known
Axes of Elongation

Planar and 3/4 views are defined by the relation


of the object’s axis of elongation to the viewer;
that is, in the planar view, the axis of elongation
Under 100 object Over 100 object is parallel or perpendicular to the viewer’s line
names names
of sight. Many theorists of visual object recog-
Figure 6.10 Dwell times on planar views given nition have posited that axes of elongation (and/
exploration of novel and known objects for chil- or symmetry, which is often correlated with
dren with fewer and with more than 100 object the axis of elongation) play a particularly criti-
names in productive vocabulary as compared to cal role in a current input’s activation of stored
that expected (the solid line) by random object object representations (Biederman, 1987; Marr
rotations (Pereira et al., 2007). & Nishihara, 1992). This is because the object’s
major axes are proposed to play an important
role in parsing objects into their main parts and
To the best of our knowledge, there are no for the comparison of sensory inputs to stored
prior developmental studies directly comparing representations (Biederman, 1987; Jolicoeur,
children’s recognition of objects from 3/4 and 1985, 1990; Marr & Nishihara, 1992; Ullman,
planar views and no prior studies of the views of 1996). This makes sense: the principal axes are
objects that children actively generate for them- enduring characteristics of objects and provide
selves as they explore objects. This is a critical a systematic means for transforming and com-
gap in our understanding of the development of paring images by defining a common reference
visual object recognition. Children’s first-hand frame for alignment. Axes of elongation and
views of objects are the visual experiences on their relation to the body are also important
which they must build their object recognition determiners of how objects are picked up, held,
systems and their representations of specific viewed, and used (Goodale & Humphrey, 1998;
objects (see chapter by Johnson in this volume). Jeannerod, 1988, 1997; Jones & Lederman, 2006;
That these views change with development— Milner & Goodale, 1995; Turvey, Park, Dumais,
that younger children present different views & Carello, 1998).
to themselves than do older children—suggest Studies of the influence of axes of elongation
a link between perceptual development and in adult object recognition mainly involve the
action, with developmental changes in object presentation of objects from various viewpoints
representations perhaps driving changes in the that differ in the relation of the axes of elonga-
views that children present themselves. These tion to the viewer. Put together, these studies
self-generated views, in turn, seem likely to have yielded mixed results. Studies that have
be driving forces in the development of object used pictures of highly familiar objects rotated
representations. Although we have not made in the picture plane typically find, at best, small
the direct link yet, the fact that these changes effects (Large, McMullen, & Hamm, 2003;
in preferred views begin at the same time when Sekuler, 1996). As Large et al. note, strong top-
children learn many object category names, down effects in adults’ recognition of prototypi-
begin to build abstract and category encom- cal pictures of things may overwhelm any role
passing representations of object structure, for variations in the main axes. Consistent with
and engage in shape-based object substitutions this idea, Liu and Cooper (2001) found strong
in play suggest that they may be connected. At axis of symmetry effects in judgments about
SHAPE, ACTION, SYMBOLIC PLAY, AND WORDS 123

nonsense objects. Thus, the principal axes may development in other domains (e.g. Amso &
be particularly important in setting up one’s Johnson, 2006; Bushnell & Bourdreau, 1993;
initial representations of an object, and perhaps Gibson, 1969; Needham, Barrett, & Peterman,
in integrating multiple images into a coherent 2002; Ruff & Rothbart, 1996). Two recent devel-
whole. In support of this idea, Jolicoeur (1985) opmental studies in our laboratory suggest that
found that axes of elongation were important in this may also be the case in children’s represen-
recognizing novel objects, but played a decreas- tation of the major axes of an object.
ing role with increasing object familiarity. The first relevant study (Smith, 2005)
There is also evidence that object shape, and demonstrates how action may promote the
perceived axes of elongation and symmetry, discovery of deeper regularities concern-
depend on (and also influence) the perceived ing three-dimensional object structure, par-
frame of reference (Quinlan & Humphrey, 1993; ticularly, the definition of an object’s axes of
Rock, 1973; Sekuler, 1996; Sekuler & Swimmer, elongation and symmetry. The participants
2000). For example, the same pattern can be seen were 24- to 30-month-old children. In the first
as a square or a diamond, depending on how experiment, the children were given a three-
one assigns the reference frame and the main dimensional object to hold in one hand that is
axis of symmetry (Rock, 1973). Particularly shown in Figure 6.11A. This nearly sphere-like
relevant to our interest in the relation between exemplar object did not have a single main
action and perception, the perceived axes of axis of elongation. In one condition, children
elongation and symmetry in adults are also moved the object up and down along a 1-m ver-
influenced by motion (Bucher & Palmer, 1985; tical path. In a second condition, they moved
Rock 1973; Sekuler & Swimmer, 2000). Adults the object back and forth on a 1-m horizontal
are biased to see both the main axis of symme- path. Immediately following, children were
try and the main axis of elongation as parallel to asked to group the exemplar object with other
the path of movement (Morikawa, 1999; Sekuler like things. No movement was involved in this
& Swimmer, 2000). categorization task. Children who had acted on
There is almost no evidence on how children the exemplar by moving it vertically grouped
perceive axes of elongation, on how principle it with objects elongated on their vertical axes
axes relate to the development of object recog- (Figure 6.11B), but children who had moved the
nition or on how action—holding and mov- exemplar horizontally grouped it with objects
ing objects—may be related to the perceptual elongated on their horizontal axes. These cat-
definition of the principle axes of an object egorization choices emerged only as a conse-
(but see E.J. Gibson, 1969; Turvey et al., 1998) quence of action and not when children merely
even though object shape and axes of elonga- observed someone else move the exemplar along
tion strongly influence not only how we hold the same path. The path of action thus selected
and grasp objects, but also how objects may be or highlighted the corresponding visual axis,
used functionally (Goodale & Humphrey, 1998; altering the perceived similarity of the exemplar
Jeannerod, 1988; Jones & Lederman, 2006; to the test objects.
Milner & Goodale, 1995). However, if the axes of The second experiment in this study used
elongation are important for setting up frames an exemplar like that shown in figure, part C,
of reference for the perception of shape, as many an exemplar not quite symmetrical around its
theories of visual object recognition suggest, center axis. The actions are illustrated in the
and if axes of elongation determine how we hold, figure, part D. Children who held the exemplar
grasp, and use objects, then children’s actions in one hand by one part and moved it back and
on objects may play an important developmen- forth subsequently grouped the exemplar with
tal role in their discovery and representation test objects (part E) that were less symmetrical
of these axes, and thus in visual object recog- in shape than the exemplar itself, as if they saw
nition. There are many well-documented dem- the exemplar as composed of two unequal parts.
onstrations of how action organizes perceptual Children who held the exemplar in the two
124 WORDS, LANGUAGE, AND MUSIC

Figure 6.11 Exemplars and test


objects used in Smith (2005).

hands and rotated it about a central axis sub- to have selected compatible visual descriptions
sequently grouped the exemplar with objects of object shape.
more symmetrical in shape than the exemplar, Axes of elongation and symmetry are
as if they saw the exemplar as composed of two higher-order dimensions of object shape fun-
comparable and symmetric parts. Again, these damental to processes of human object recogni-
results only obtained when children acted on tion (e.g., Marr, 1982). These results suggest that
the objects, not when they watched someone they may be developmentally defined not by
else do the action. The enacted action appears vision alone but by the in-task coordination of
SHAPE, ACTION, SYMBOLIC PLAY, AND WORDS 125

visual and motor processes. This is potentially shapes and asked to fit them into a container
of considerable importance. Theories of object through holes specific to those shapes (Wyly,
recognition are for the most part theories of 1997). Although there are normative standards
static object recognition (see also, Liu & Cooper, for preschool children’s success in these tasks
2003). Yet how we act on objects is intimately (and their perseveration in the task), there is
related to their shapes, and may even develop- remarkably little empirical study of the pro-
mentally be defining of them. Every time the cesses and skills that underlie success. We have
child lays a doll in a doll bed, or perhaps on preliminary evidence in a version of a shape-
top of a block as a pretend bed, the child acts sorting task designed to measure children’s abil-
in ways that may help define the major axes of ity to abstract the axis of elongation of shapes of
an object and the frame of reference for com- various complexities.
paring one shape to another. There are physi- Our approach is based on the “posting”
cal and biological constraints on how we can studies of Efron (1969) with adults and neu-
hold and move objects of different shapes and ropsychological patients (see also Goodale &
thus highly constrained associations between Milner, 1992; Milner, Perrett, & Johnston.,
symmetry, elongation, and paths of movement 1991; Warrington 1985). In these studies, sub-
that may bootstrap these developments. Related jects were given a range of “Efron rectangles”:
to this idea is Morikawa’s (1999) proposal that flat, simple, plaques that differ in their height–
adults are biased to perceive movement paral- width ratio. Their task was to insert them in a
lel to an object’s long axis and this bias derives slot aligned at a particular orientation. The crit-
from a regularity in the world, that objects in ical dependent measure was whether subjects
general move on paths parallel to their long axis oriented the handheld object to match the slot.
(there are obvious exceptions: people, e.g., move We use a much simpler version of this “posting
orthogonally to their long axis). Still, a person’s task” to ask whether—given the goal of insert-
movements of objects (rather than, or as well ing an object in a slot—children align that
as, how objects move on their own) may well be object’s axis of elongation to the axis of elonga-
systematically related to shape in ways that mat- tion of the slot. This task thus provides a good
ter to the development of object recognition. measure of children’s ability to abstract the axis
And critically, the visual information young of elongation and to make use of that informa-
learners receive about objects varies systemati- tion in action. The participants are 30 children
cally with their own actions on those objects. in two age groups, 17–18 and 23–24 months of
Thus it seems likely that changes in visual object age. Children are presented with a box with a
recognition support developmental changes in quite large slot (7 by 21 cm) oriented either
action (including object substitution in play) horizontally or vertically. They are then given
and that those activities in turn help define and objects, one at a time, and asked to put them
refine structural descriptions of shape. Th is, into the slot. All the objects can be easily fit into
then, is another potential loop of codeveloping the slot–either by aligning the axis of orienta-
processes, of causes as consequences and conse- tion or by tilting the object so that the foreshort-
quences as causes. At the very least, the present ened end goes in first. The key independent
results show that action has a strong influence variables were: the Orientation of the objects on
on the range of shapes 2-year-olds take as being the table (that were Matching or Mismatching
similar and appears to do so by defining axes of the orientation of the slot); and the Complexity
elongation and symmetry. of the objects. Complexity of shape was manip-
Our most recent work on this topic (Street, ulated in three ways: Shape Matches, solid rect-
Smith, James, & Jones, 2008) uses a task that angular blocks whose shape matched the slot;
is commonly used to diagnose developmental Simple Shapes, novel forms with height–width
delays and is included in many assessment pro- ratios comparable to the rectangular blocks);
cedures. This is a shape-sorting task in which and Known Shapes, complex real objects
children are presented with objects of various with height–width ratios comparable to the
126 WORDS, LANGUAGE, AND MUSIC

rectangular blocks but with multiple parts and again suggest marked growth during this devel-
a canonical axis of orientation (e.g., a tiger ver- opmental period in children’s representation
sus a rocket). Children wear the head-camera in and use of the structural dimensions of three-
this study so that we can record the alignment dimensional shape.
of object and slot from their point of view.
This is a highly enjoyable and engaging
FROM VISUAL OBJECT RECOGNITION
task and on virtually every trial the children
TO SYMBOLIC PLAY TO WORD LEARNING
inserted the object into the slot in one way or
AND BACK
another. The first main result, however, is that
this skill undergoes considerable developmen- This chapter began with a phenomenon often
tal change in this period. Eighteen-month-old known as symbolic play, an extremely inter-
children struggle in this task, often making esting behavior that has been strongly linked
many wrong attempts (see Figure 6.12). In con- to language learning, to social interactions in
trast, 24-month-old children are nearly per- collaborative play, and to developing tool use
fect, aligning and inserting the object rapidly (see Rakoczy, Tomasello, & Striano, 2006). The
and almost without error. Our main depen- program of research reviewed in this chapter
dent measure is degree of alignment, measured in no way explains symbolic play, since that
from the head-camera view as shown in Figure explanation will likely consist of a cascade of
6.12. For the younger children, this angle aver- interacting processes beyond those involved in
ages 33º across all objects, that is, these children perceiving and representing object shape. The
were typically off the mark, and their error was findings reviewed here, however, do suggest
greater for complex than for simple objects. In that one component of that larger developmen-
contrast, older children’s alignment error was tal story will be changes in fundamental pro-
less 10º for all objects. How the objects were cesses of visual object recognition, which is the
presented did not matter, perhaps because main focus of this chapter. The entire pattern
the children held and rotated them, exploring of results reviewed here strongly suggests that
them, before attempting insertion. These results there are significant and consequential changes

Figure 6.12 Head-camera views from Street et al. (2008) of a 18-month-old infant inserting objects
into slots. The smaller images show the view was an additional camera. As shown in the third image,
alignment at first attempt is measured by the angle between the major axis of the slot and the major
axis of the object to be inserted.
SHAPE, ACTION, SYMBOLIC PLAY, AND WORDS 127

in how children perceive, represent, and Arbib, M. A. (1981). Visuomotor coordination:


compare three-dimensional object shape, a shift From neural nets to schema theory. Cognition
from more piecemeal emphasis on local details and Brain Theory, 4, 23–39.
to a sparse, and thus category encompassing, Biederman, I. (1987). Recognition-by-components:
description of shape in terms of global geomet- A theory of human image understanding.
Psychological Review, 94(2), 115–147.
ric structure. These changes are seen in (1) the
Biederman, I., & Gerhardstein, P. C. (1993).
recognition of instances of common categories, Recognizing depth-rotated objects: Evidence
(2) in object substitution in pretend play, (3) in and conditions for three-dimensional view-
active exploration of objects, and (4) in actions point invariance. Journal of Experimental
that make use of structural properties. Psychology, 19(6), 1162–1182.
From this first set of studies, we cannot know Biederman, I., & Kalocsai, P. (1997). Neuro-
with any certainty what causes what, but it may computational bases of object and face rec-
well be, as suggested by the opening Figure 6.1, ognition. Philosophical Transactions of the
that there are causal influences in all directions. Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences,
Development, after all, occurs in real time, in 352(1358), 1203–1219.
incremental steps, across a number of inter- Blanz, V., Tarr, M. J., & Bulthoff, H. H. (1999).
What object attributes determine canonical
leaved real-time experiences. The child hears a
views? Perception, 28(5), 575–599.
new object named (say an oddly shaped mug), Bucher, N. M., & Palmer, S. E. (1985). Effects of
uses it to drink from, sees and imitates his older motion on perceived pointing of ambiguous
brother pretend to use it as a hat. All these expe- triangles. Perception and Psychophysics, 38(3),
riences influence what the child sees, what the 227–236.
child feels, and how this one experience is con- Bushnell, E. W., & Bourdreau, J. P. (1993). Motor
nected to other experiences. The inventiveness development and the mind: The potential role
of human cognition, its adaptability and power, of motor abilities as a determinant of aspects of
may, quite literally, be constructed from the perceptual development. Child Development,
overlapping, mutually influencing, interactions 64(4), 1005–1021.
of many different tasks involving and educating Cerella, J. (1986). Pigeons and perceptrons. Pattern
Recognition, 19, 431–438.
the same component processes.
Chao, L. L., & Martin, A. (2000). Representation
of manipulable man-made objects in the dorsal
stream. NeuroImage, 12(4), 478–484.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
Christou, C. G., & Bulthoff, H. H. (1999). View
This research was supported by National Institute dependence in scene recognition after active
for Child Health and Development (R01HD 28675); learning. Memory and Cognition, 27(6),
Portuguese Ministry of Science and Higher 996–1007.
Education PhD scholarship SFRH/BD/13890/2003 Colunga, E. (2003, April). Where is the cow hiding?
and a Fulbright fellowship to AF.P. A new method for studying the development
of features. Paper presented at the Biennial
meeting of the Society for Research on Child
REFERENCES Development, Tampa, FL.
Colunga, E., & Smith, L. B. (2005). From the lexi-
Abecassis, M., Sera, M. D., Yonas, A., & Schwade, con to expectations about kinds: A role for
J. (2001). What’s in a shape? Children represent associative learning. Psychological Review,
shape variability differently than adults when 112(2), 342–382.
naming objects. Journal of Experimental Child Cooper, E. E., Biederman, I., & Hummel, J. E.
Psychology, 78, 213–239. (1992). Metric invariance in object recogni-
Amso, D., & Johnson, S. P. (2006). Learning by tion: A review and further evidence. Canadian
selection: Visual search and object perception Journal of Psychology, 46(2), 191–214.
in young infants. Developmental psychology, Craighero, L., Fadiga, L., Umilta, C. A., &
42(6), 1236–1245. Rizzolatti, G. (1996). Evidence for visuomotor
128 WORDS, LANGUAGE, AND MUSIC

priming effect. Cognitive Neuroscience and Goodale, M. A., & Humphrey, G. K. (1998) The
Neuropsychology, 8(1), 347–349. objects of action and perception. Cognition, 67,
Edelman, G. (1987) Neural darwinism. The theory of 181–207.
neuronal group selection. New York: Basic Books. Grezes, J., & Decety, J. (2002). Does visual percep-
Edelman, S. (1995). Representation, similarity, and tion of object afford action? Evidence from a
the chorus of prototypes. Minds and Machines. neuroimaging study. Neuropsychologia, 40,
5(1), 45–68. 212–222.
Edelman, S., & Duvdevani-Bar, S. (1997). Hayward, W. G. (2003). After the viewpoint debate:
Similarity, connectionism, and the problem of where next in object recognition? Trends in
representation in vision. Neural Computation, Cognitive Science, 7(10), 425–427.
9(4), 701–720. Harman, K. L., Humphrey, G. K., & Goodale,
Edelman, S., & Intrator, N. (1997). Learning as M. A. (1999). Active manual control of object
extraction of low-dimensional representations. views facilitates visual recognition. Current
In R. L. Goldstone, D. L. Medin, & P. G. Schyns Biology, 9(22). 1315–1318.
(Eds.), Perceptual learning. The psychology of Hummel, J. E. (2000). Where view-based theories
learning and motivation, (pp. 353–380): San break down: The role of structure in shape per-
Diego, CA: Academic Press. ception and object recognition. In E. Dietrich
Edelman, S., & Intrator, N. (2003). Towards struc- & A. Markman (Ed.), Cognitive dynamics:
tural systematicity in distributed, statically Conceptual change in humans and machines
bound representations. Cognitive Science, 27, (pp. 157–185). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
73–109. Hummel, J. E., & Biederman, I. (1992). Dynamic
Efron, R. (1969). What is perception? Boston binding in a neural network for shape recogni-
Studies of the Philisophical Society, 4, 137–173. tion. Psychological Review, 99(3), 480–517.
Fenson, L. Marchman, V. A., Thal, D. J., Dale, P. Humphrey, G. K., & Jolicoeur, P. (1993). An
S., Reznick, S., & Bates, E. (1993). MacArthur- examination of the effects of axis foreshorten-
Bates communicative development inventories ing, monocular depth cues, and visual field on
(2nd ed.). Baltimore, MD: Brookes Publishing. object identification. The Quarterly Journal of
Fize, D., Fabre-Thorpe, M. I., Richard, G., Doyon, Experimental Psychology, 46(1), 137–159.
B., & Thorpe, S. J. (2005). Rapid categoriza- Imai, M., Gentner, D., & Uchida, N. (1994).
tion of foveal and extrafoveal natural images: Children’s theories of word meaning: The
Associated ERPs and effects of lateralization. role of shape similarity in early acquisition.
Brain and Cognition, 59(2), 145–158. Cognitive Development, 9(1), 45–75.
Freyd, J. J. (1983). Representing the dynamics of James, K. H., Humphrey, G. K., & Goodale, M. A.
static form. Memory & Cognition, 11, 342–346. (2001). Manipulating and recognizing virtual
Gathercole, V. C. M., & Min, H. (1997). Word objects: Where the action is. Canadian Journal
meaning biases or language-specific effects? of Experimental Psychology, 55(2), 111–120.
Evidence from English, Spanish and Korean. James, K. H., Humphrey, G. K., Vilis, T., Baddour,
First Language, 17, 31–56. R., Corrie, B., & Goodale, M. A. (2002).
Gerlach, C., Law, I., Gade, A., & Paulson, O. B. Learning three-dimensional object structure:
(2000). Categorization and category effects A virtual reality study. Behavioral Research
in normal object recognition: A PET study. Methods, Instruments and Computers, 34(3),
Neuropsychologia, 38, 1693–1703. 383–390.
Gershkoff-Stowe, L., & Smith, L. B. (2004). James, K. H., & Gauthier, I. (2006). Letter process-
Shape and the first hundred nouns. Child ing automatically recruits a sensory-motor brain
Development, 75(40), 1098–1114. network. Neuropsychologia, 44, 2937–2949.
Gibson, E. J. (1969). Principles of perceptual learn- Jeannerod, M. (1988) The neural and behavioral
ing and development. New York: Appleton organization of goal-directed movements. New
Century Crofts. York: Oxford University Press.
Gibson, J. J. (1979). The ecological approach to Jeannerod, M. (1997). The cognitive neuroscience of
visual perception. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. action. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.
Goodale, M. A., & Milner, A. D. (1992) Separate Jolicoeur, P. (1985). The time to name disoriented
visual pathways for perception and action, natural objects. Memory and Cognition, 13(4),
Trends in Neurosciences, 15, 2025. 289–303.
SHAPE, ACTION, SYMBOLIC PLAY, AND WORDS 129

Jolicoeur, P. (1990). Identification of disoriented McCune-Nicolich, L. (1981). Toward symbolic


objects: A dual-systems theory. Mind and functioning: Structure of early pretend games
Language, 5(4), 387–410. and potential parallels with language. Child
Jones, S. S. (2003). Late talkers show no shape bias Development, 52(3), 785–797.
in object naming. Developmental Science, 6(5), McCune, L. (1995). A normative study of repre-
477–483. sentational play in the transition to language.
Jones, L. A., & Lederman, S. J. (2006). Human hand Developmental psychology, 31(2), 198–206.
function. New York: Oxford University Press. Mecklinger, A., Gruenewald, C., Besson, M.,
Jones, S. S., & Smith, L. B. (2005). Object name Magnie, M. N., & Cramon, D. Y. (2002).
learning and object perception: A deficit in Seperable neuronal circuitries for manipu-
late talkers. Journal of Child Language, 32(1), lable and non-manipulable objects in working
223–240. memory. Cerebral Cortex, 12(11), 1115–1123.
Keil, F. C. (1994). The birth and nurturance of con- Milner, D., & Goodale, M. (1995) The visual brain
cepts by domains: The origins of concepts of liv- in action. New York: Oxford University Press.
ing things. In L. A. Hirschfeld & S.A. Gelman Milner, A. D., Perrett, D. I., & Johnston, R. S.
(Eds.), Mapping the mind: Domain specificity in (1991). Perception and action in ‘visual form
cognition and culture (pp. 234–254). New York: agnosia’. Brain, 114, 405–428.
Cambridge University Press. Mondloch, C. J., Le Grand, R., & Maurer, D.
Kellman, P. J. (2001). Separating processes in (2002). Configural face processing develops
object perception. Journal of Experimental more slowly than featural face processing.
Child Psychology. Special Issue: Reflections, Perception, 31(5), 553–566.
78(1), 84–97. Morikawa, K. (1999). Symmetry and elongation of
Landau, B., Smith, L., & Jones, S. (1988). The objects influence perceived direction of trans-
importance of shape in early lexical learning. lational motion. Perception and Psychophysics,
Cognitive Development, 3, 299–321. 61, 134–143.
Large, M. E., McMullen, P. A., & Hamm, J. P. Namy, L. (2002) Symbol use and symbolic repre-
(2003). The role of axes of elongation and sym- sentation: Developmental and Comparative
metry in rotated object naming. Perception and Perspectives: New York: Rutledge
Psychophysics, 65(1). 1–19. Needham, A., Barrett, T., & Peterman K. (2002). A
Lawson, R., & Humphreys, G. W. (1998). View- pick-me-up for infants’ exploratory skills: Early
specific effects of depth rotation and foreshort- simulated experiences reaching for objects
ening on the initial recognition and priming of using “sticky mittens” enhances young infants’
familiar objects. Perception and Psychophysics, object exploration skills. Infant Behavior and
60(60), 1052–1066. Development, 25(3), 279–295.
Longcamp, M., Boucard, C., Gilhodes, J. C., & Nelson, C. A. (2001). The development and neu-
Vely, J. L. (2005). Remembering the orienta- ral bases of face recognition. Infant and Child
tion of newly learned characters depends on Development. Special Issue: Face Processing in
the associated writing knowledge: A compar- Infancy and Early Childhood, 10(1–2), 3–18.
ison between handwriting and typing. Human Newell, F. N., & Findlay, J. M.(1997). The effect
Movement Science, 25(4–5), 646–656. of depth rotation on object identification.
Liu, T., & Cooper, L. A. (2003). Explicit and Perception, 26(10), 1231–1257.
implicit memory for rotating objects. Journal Paillard, J. (1991). Brain and space. New York:
of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, Oxford University Press.
and Cognition, 29, 554–562. Palmer, S. E., Rosch, E., & Chase, P. (1981).
Marr, D. (1982) Vision: A computational investiga- Canonical perspective and the perception
tion into the human representation and process- of objects. In J. Long & A. Baddeley (Eds),
ing of visual information. New York, NY: Henry Attention and performance (pp. 135–151)
Holt and Co., Inc. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Marr, D. & Nishihara, H. K. (1978). Representation Pegna, A. J., Khateb, A., Michel, C. M., & Landis,
and recognition of the spatial organization T. (2004). Visual recognition of faces, objects,
of three-dimensional shapes. Proceedings and words using degraded stimuli: Where and
Royal Society of London, Series B, 200(1140): when it occurs. Human Brain Mapping, 22(4),
269–94 300–311.
130 WORDS, LANGUAGE, AND MUSIC

Pereira, A. & Smith, L. B. (2009). Developmental play actions. British Journal of Developmental
changes in visual object recognition between 18 Psychology, 24(2), 305–335.
and 24 months of age. Developmental Science, Rock, I. (1973). Orientation and form. New York,
12(4), 67–80. NY: Academic Press.
Pereira, A., James, K. H., Smith, L. B., & Jones, S. S. Rosch, E., Mervis, C. B., Gray, W. D., Johnson, D.
(2007). Preferred views in children’s active explo- M., & Boyes-Braem, P. (1976). Basic objects
ration of objects, Society for Research in Child in natural categories. Cognitive Psychology, 8,
Development, Annual Meeting, Boston, MA. 382–439.
Perner, J. (1991). Understanding the representa- Ruff, H. A., & Rothbart, M. K. (1996). Attention
tional mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. in early development. New York: Oxford
Perrett, D. I., & Harries, M. H. (1988). Characteristic University Press.
views and the visual inspection of simple fac- Samuelson, L. K. (2002). Statistical regularities
eted and smooth objects: Tetrahedra and pota- in vocabulary guide language acquisition in
toes. Perception, 17(6), 703–720. connectionist models and 15–20-month-olds.
Perrett, D. I., Harries, M. H., & Looker, S. (1992). Use Developmental Psychology, 38(6), 1016–1037.
of preferential inspection to define the viewing Samuelson, L. K., & Smith, L. B. (1999). Early noun
sphere and characteristic views of an arbitrary vocabularies: Do ontology, category structure
machined tool part. Perception, 21, 497–515. and syntax correspond? Cognition, 73, 1–33.
Peissig, J. J., & Tarr, M. J. (2007). Visual object rec- Sekuler, A. B. (1996) Axis of elongation can deter-
ognition: Do we know more now than we did mine reference frames for object perception.
20 years ago? Annual Review of Psychology, Canadian Journal of Experimental Psychology,
58(1), 75–96. 50(3), 270–279.
Peterson, M. (Ed.) (1999) The MIT encyclopedia Sekuler, A. B., & Swimmer, M. B. (2000).
of the cognitive sciences. Cambridge, MA: The Interactions between symmetry and elonga-
MIT Press. tion in determining reference frames for object
Piaget, J. (1962). Play, dreams, and imitation in perception. Canadian Journal of Experimental
childhood. New York: Norton. Psychology, 54(1), 42–56.
Quinlan, P. T. & Humphreys, G. W. (1993). Sekuler, E. B. (1996). Perceptual cues in pure alexia.
Perceptual frames of reference and two-dimen- Cognitive Neuropsychology, 13(7), 941–974.
sional shape recognition: further examination Shore, C., O’Connell, B., & Bates, E. (1984). First
of internal axes. Perception. 22(11):1343–64. sentences in language and symbolic play.
Rakison, D. H., & Butterworth, G. E. (1998a). Developmental Psychology, 20(5), 872–880.
Infants’ attention to object structure in early Smith, L. B. (2003). Learning to recognize objects.
categorization. Developmental Psychology, 34(6), Psychological Science, 14(3) 244– 251.
1310–1325. Smith, L. B. (2005). Action alters perceived shape.
Rakison, D. H., & Butterworth, G. E. (1998b). Cognitive Science, 29, 665–679.
Infant’s use of object parts in early categoriza- Smith, L. B., Jones, S. S., Landau, B., Gershkoff-
tion. Developmental Psychology, 34(1), 49–62. Stowe, L., & Samuelson, S. (2002). Early noun
Rakison, D. H., & Cicchino, J. B. (2008). Induction learning provides on-the-job training for
in infancy. in S. Johnson (Ed.), A neo-construc- attention. Psychological Science, 13, 13–19.
tivist approach to early development. New York: Smith, L. B., & Pereira. A. F. (2008) Symbolic
Oxford University Press. play links to language through object recogni-
Rakison, D. H., & Cohen, L. B. (1999) Infants’ use tion. Unpublished manuscript, Department
of functional parts in basic-like categorization. of Psychological and Brain Sciences, Indiana
Developmental Science, 2, 423–431. University Bloomington, Bloomington, IN.
Rakison, D. H., & Lupyan, G. (2008). Developing Soja, N. N. (1992). Inferences about the meanings
object concepts in infancy: An associative of nouns: The relationship between perception
learning perspective. Monographs of the SRCD, and syntax. Cognitive Development, 7, 29–45.
73(1). Son, J.Y., Smith, L.B., & Goldstone, R.L. (2008).
Rakoczy, H., Tomasello, M., & Striano, T. (2006). Simplicity and generalization: Short-cutting
The role of experience and discourse in chil- abstraction in children’s object categorizations.
dren’s developing understanding of pretend Cognition, 108, 626–638.
SHAPE, ACTION, SYMBOLIC PLAY, AND WORDS 131

Stankiewicz, B. J. (2003). Just another view. Trends their use on classification. Nature Neuroscience,
in Cognitive Science, 7, 526. 5(7), 682–687.
Street, S., Smith, L. B., James. K. H., & Jones, S. S. Vivani, P., & Stucchi, N. (1992). Biological
(2008). Posting ability and object recognition in movements look uniform: Evidence for
18–24 month old children. Unpublished manu- motor-perceptual interactions. Journal of
script, Department of Psychological and Brain Experimental Psychology, 18, 603–623.
Sciences, Indiana University Bloomington, Warrington, E. K. (1985). Agnosia: the impairment
Bloomington, IN. of object recognition. In P. J. Vinken, G. W.
Tarr, M., & Vuong, Q. C. (2002). Visual object rec- Bruyn, & H. L. Klawans (Eds.), Handbook of
ognition. In S. Yantis (Ed.), Steven’s Handbook clinical neurology. Amsterdam: Elsevier.
of Experimental Psychology: Vol. 1. Sensation Weismer, S. E. (2007). Typical talkers, late talkers,
and Perception (Vol. 1). New York, NY: John and children with specific language impairment:
Wiley & Sons, Inc. A language endowment spectrum? Mahwah,
Tong, F. H., Marlin, S. G., & Frost, B. J. (1995). NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Cognition map formation in a three-dimensional Wexler, M., & van Boxtel., J. (2005). Depth percep-
visual virtual world. Poster presented at the tion by the active observer. Trends in Cognitive
IRIS/PRECARN Workshop,Vancouver, BC. Science, 9, 431–8. s
Turvey, M. T., Park, H., Dumais, S. M., & Carello, Wohlschlager, A., & Wohlschlager, A. (1998).
C. (1998). Nonvisible perception of segments Mental and manual rotation. Journal of
of a hand-held object and the attitude spinor. Experimental Psychology, Human Perception
Journal of Motor Behavior, 30(1), 3–19. and Performance, 24(2), 397–412.
Ullman, S. (1996). High level vision. Cambridge, Wyly, M. V. (1997). Infant assessment. Boulder,
MA: MIT Press. CO: Westview Press.
Ullman, S. (2000). High-level vision: Object recog- Yoshida, H., & Smith, L. B. (2003). Shift ing
nition and visual cognition. Cambridge, MA: ontological boundaries: How Japanese- and
MIT Press. English-speaking children generalize names
Ullman, S., & Bart, E. (2004). Recognition invari- for animals and artifacts. Developmental
ance obtained by extended and invariant fea- Science, 6, 1–34.
tures. Neural Networks, 17(5/6), 833–848. Yoshida, H. & Smith, L.B. (2008). What’s in view
Ullman, S., Vidal-Naquet, M., & Sali, E. (2002). for toddlers? Using a head camera to study
Visual features of intermediate complexity and visual experience. Infancy, 13(3), 229–248.
CHAP TER 7
Musical Enculturation: How Young Listeners
Construct Musical Knowledge through
Perceptual Experience

Erin E. Hannon

Human musical capacities have recently become their native language, every member of a
the focus of an exploding quantity of theoretical particular culture—with or without formal
and empirical contributions in the psychologi- musical training—can be expected to acquire
cal and brain sciences (Avanzini Lopez, Koelsch, basic musical competence and a working knowl-
& Majno, 2006; Compston, 2006; Peretz, 2006; edge of familiar musical structures (Bigand &
Spiro, 2003; Wallin, Merker, & Brown, 2000; Poulin-Chourronnat, 2006; Hannon & Trainor,
Zatorre & Peretz, 2003). This marks a signif- 2007).
icant change in the status of musical behavior The question of exactly how this musical
and cognition as the topic of empirical inves- knowledge is structured and acquired during
tigation. Until recently, it was widely assumed development is of great interest but as of yet
that musical skills and knowledge were only unanswered. One proposal is that such knowl-
possessed by an elite, highly trained minority, edge arises from a “music faculty” that is modular
a view bolstered by characterizations of music and built from innate, “core” capacities (Hauser
as frivolous, devoid of adaptive significance, & McDermott, 2003; Peretz & Coltheart, 2003;
and subject to insurmountable individual and Peretz & Morais, 1989). Proponents of the mod-
cross-cultural variability (Pinker, 1997, 2002). ular approach have cited evidence of music-
Current approaches refute this view by empha- specific neural circuitry in adults (Janata et al.,
sizing biological substrates of music (i.e., Zatorre 2002; Koelsch & Siebel, 2005), cases of double-
& Peretz, 2003), potential survival advantages of dissociations between music and other cogni-
music (Huron, 2003; Miller, 2000), and the ubiq- tive or linguistic abilities in patients with brain
uity of many basic musical skills. For example, damage (Peretz et al., 1994; Vignolo, 2003), and
most adults have sufficient musical knowledge parallels between the musical abilities of adults
to sing a familiar tune (Dalla Bella, Giguere, & and young infants (Trehub, 2003). According
Peretz, 2007), detect “wrong notes” in a musical to the modular view, musical knowledge and
sequence (Drayna et al., 2001; Hyde & Peretz, behavior arise from an innate set of music-
2004; Trainor & Trehub, 1992), recognize and specific evolutionary adaptations.
experience emotions communicated by music An alternative to the modular approach,
(Grewe, Kopiez, & Altenmüller, 2005; Juslin embraced here, is that highly specialized knowl-
& Laukka, 2003), and move or dance in syn- edge of music in adulthood arises through
chrony with music (Large, Fink, & Kelso, 2002; simple perceptual learning mechanisms that
McAuley, Jones, Holub, Johnstone, & Miller, build increasingly specific representations from
2006; Snyder & Krumhansl, 2001). Thus, just as domain-general capacities (Trehub & Hannon,
most children eventually learn to understand 2006). According to this view, the appearance

132
MUSICAL ENCULTUR ATION 133

of domain-specificity and even encapsulation mechanisms to infer structure across a number


in adult music processing does not necessarily of domains (Conway & Christiansen, 2006;
signify the existence of modularity in the initial Kirkham, Slemmer, & Johnson, 2002; Saff ran,
state—rather, such specialization could be the Aslin, & Newport, 1996; see Kirkham, Saff ran,
result of developmental processes (Karmiloff- and Gomez chapters, this volume). Statistical
Smith, 1992; McMullen & Saff ran, 2004). Thus, learning depends on the perceiver’s simple
observed parallels between adult and infant capacity to track the frequency with which cer-
performance in music cognition tasks may arise tain units or combinations of units occur. Many
from general properties of the nervous system examples of statistical learning have been docu-
that are not necessarily specific to music or even mented in the language domain. For instance,
to humans. Such initial abilities constrain musi- infants infer phonemic distinctions between
cal enculturation, the process through which syllables only when the prototypical speech
everyday exposure to the statistics of music sounds occur more frequently than nonproto-
drives the acquisition of culture-specific musi- typical sounds (Maye, Werker, & Gerken, 2002).
cal knowledge. Transitional probabilities between units (i.e.,
This chapter explores the question of how the likelihood that one unit will be preceded or
infants and children build musical representa- followed by another) enable infants to segment
tions, with particular focus on perception and unfamiliar sequences of syllables or tones into
knowledge of temporal structure in music, such groups or “words” after brief exposure (Saff ran,
as rhythm and meter. Rhythm and meter are Johnson, Aslin, & Newport, 1999). Multiple and
fundamental to most socially significant and correlated statistical cues provide a powerful
universal musical behaviors, such as synchro- means by which infants can rapidly build
nous dancing or ensemble performance (Brown, increasingly complex representations from sim-
2003). In this chapter, I will review published ple learning mechanisms (Christiansen, Allen,
and new evidence that infants can perceive & Seidenberg, 1998; Christiansen, Dale, & Reali,
rhythm and meter by attending to the same sta- this volume; Thiessen & Saff ran, 2007).
tistical properties that underlie adults’ percep- Relatively little is known about the role of sta-
tion, that representations of rhythm and meter tistical learning in the development of musical
undergo reorganization as a result of culture- representations. Transitional probabilities and
specific perceptual experience, and that infants frequency of occurrence likely provide informa-
and adults share some basic temporal process- tion about the hierarchical pitch organization of
ing constraints despite infants’ initial flexibil- Western music or tonality, since tonally promi-
ity. In addition to examining development of nent pitches tend to occur more frequently than
music-specific knowledge, a parallel goal is to do other pitches, and the sequential structure of
understand the emergence of domain-specific pitch sequences is often highly constrained by
representations in auditory cognition. If we harmonic cadences (Krumhansl, 2004). When
assume that early representations of music are presented with an unfamiliar pitch sequence,
primarily domain-general and become culture- adults can use frequency of occurrence to infer
specific through perceptual experience, then a tonal prominence (Creel & Newport, 2002), and
question of great interest is whether overlap- a self-organizing neural network exposed to the
ping structures are present and detected in the statistics of Western music can simulate tonal
musical and linguistic input available to infants expectations (Tillman, Bharucha, & Bigand,
and children. I will briefly review some new evi- 2000). Despite the presence of such statistical
dence suggesting that this is may be the case. information, however, it does not appear that
tonality is learned during infancy. On the con-
trary, most evidence suggests that adult-like
STATISTICAL LEARNING AND MUSICAL TIME
knowledge of tonality does not emerge until
Numerous studies suggest that infants and after at least 5 years of age (Cuddy & Badertscher,
adults use domain-general statistical learning 1987; Koelsch, Fritz, Schulze, Alsop, & Schlaug,
134 WORDS, LANGUAGE, AND MUSIC

2005; Krumhansl & Keil, 1982; Schellenberg, (i.e., “duple” meter) (see Figure 7.1). After
2005; Trainor & Trehub, 1992). By contrast, sta- habituation, they were presented with two novel
tistical information about temporal structure rhythms that were otherwise matched but dif-
in music is available and used by infants and fered only in the extent to which the frequency
adults alike. distribution of events and accents supported the
Musical meter is the hierarchical temporal meter induced during habituation. Infants dis-
structure of music. The ability to dance or move habituated to the stimulus with a novel meter,
in synchrony with music depends on a listen- which demonstrates that they not only detected
er’s ability to infer the underlying meter in the changes in the temporal statistics of the rhythms
auditory input, which in turn guides temporal but that they categorized rhythms on the basis
expectations and gives rise to the subjective of the underlying meter. Interestingly, a third
experience of a primary pulse and alternating experiment suggested that infants could also
patterns of strong and weak beats. Although learn to associate particular pitches with strong
the pulse of a simple metronomic or isochro- and weak metrical positions. Because tonally
nous sequence is obvious from the acoustic prominent pitches tend to occur at strong met-
input (i.e., every tone onset corresponds to a rical positions in music (Järvinen & Toivianien,
pulse), real music presents a greater challenge to 2000; Meyer, 1973; Palmer & Pfordresher, 2003),
the listener because any number of amplitude this finding suggests that at least in principle
peaks or event onsets could mark multiple and infants’ ability to infer meter could provide a
sometimes conflicting primary pulse rates. It is foundation for learning about tonality through
nevertheless trivial for most adults to perceive similar statistical learning processes.
and move in synchrony with music. Evidence Not only do infants infer meter from sta-
suggests that adult listeners infer the meter by tistics in auditory input, but recent fi ndings
attending to periodically occurring statistics. suggest they also integrate metrically relevant
For example, in Western music (both classi- information across sensory modalities. When
cal and children’s), event onsets tend to occur presented with an ambiguous rhythm in which
more frequently at strong than at weak metrical events and accents support either triple or
positions (Palmer & Krumhansl, 1990; Palmer duple meter, 7-month-old infants use move-
& Pfordresher, 2003). Events that are accented ment cues to infer the meter (Phillips-Silver
or made salient through changes in amplitude, & Trainor, 2005). In this set of experiments,
length, pitch, or grouping also tend to occur infants were familiarized with an ambiguous
more frequently at strong metrical positions rhythm while being bounced or while watching
in music (Huron & Royal, 1996). Frequencies an experimenter bounce on every two or three
of event and accent occurrence predict when beats. After familiarization, infants preferred
adults will tap to music (Snyder & Krumhansl, listening to a version of the rhythm containing
2001) and their perception of meter in unfamil- disambiguating cues that matched the meter to
iar melodic patterns (Hannon, Snyder, Eerola, which they were bounced, but showed no pref-
& Krumhansl, 2001). Figure 7.1 illustrates how erence when they had only watched someone
a given set of events and accents might sup- bouncing. Thus, infants use information from
port duple or triple meters by virtue of their their own movement patterns to structure their
frequency distribution at metrically weak or metrical interpretations. This result under-
strong locations over time. scores the importance of movement for meter
Infants use frequency of occurrence to perception, and it converges with numerous
infer the meter in simple rhythmic patterns. adult studies documenting robust associations
In Hannon and Johnson (2005), 7-month- between movement and time perception using
old infants were habituated to three unique behavioral measures (Ivry & Hazeltine, 1995;
rhythms containing events and accents that Meegan, Aslin, & Jacobs, 2000; Phillips-Silver
were more likely to occur every three units & Trainor, 2007; Todd, Cousins, & Lee, 2007;
(i.e. “triple” meter) or every two and four units Trainor, 2007) and brain responses (Platel
Triple meter

Metrical stress S W W S W W S W W S W W S

Event/Accents

1
0.9 Events
0.8 Accents
Frequency of Occurrence

0.7
(Triple Meter)

0.6
0.5
0.4
0.3
0.2
0.1
0
Every 2 Every 3 Every 4

Duple meter

Metrical Stress S W S W S W S W S W S W S

Event/Accents

Events
1
Accents
0.9
Frequency of occurrence

0.8
(Duple meter)

0.7
0.6
0.5
0.4
0.3
0.2
0.1
0
Every 2 Every 3 Every 4

Figure 7.1 Patterns that support duple and triple meters. Both rhythmic patterns have potentially
13 temporal units during which events could occur, but the frequency distribution of event onsets
(depicted by squares) and accents (depicted by larger squares) differs dramatically depending on
whether the rhythm supports a triple meter (i.e., sww or strong weak weak) or a duple meter (i.e., swsw
or strong weak strong weak). Specifically, events and accents occur most frequently every three units
in the triple-meter rhythm but every two or four units in the duple-meter pattern. The bar graphs
represent the average frequency of events and accents for duple- and triple-meter rhythms used in
Hannon and Johnson (2005).

135
136 WORDS, LANGUAGE, AND MUSIC

et al., 2007; Schubotz, Friederici, & Yves von


BUILDING MUSICAL KNOWLEDGE THROUGH
Cramon, 2000).
ENCULTURATION
Do infants ignore visual information related
to meter? Although infants in Phillips-Silver and Throughout first several months after birth,
Trainor (2005) were not able to use visual infor- exposure to the statistics of the environment
mation to infer meter in an ambiguous rhythm, begins to alter infants’ basic perceptual pro-
infants may nevertheless perceive congruence cesses in a number of seemingly disparate
of metrical information across auditory and domains. One well-documented example of
visual modalities and use this information to this comes from speech perception, where
further their music learning. In a recent experi- infants develop language-specific biases during
ment (Hannon, in preparation-a), 10-month-old the second half of the first year after birth. At
infants were habituated to a movie of a woman only a few months of age, infants discriminate
dancing to a fast or a slow song. After habitua- speech sounds from virtually all spoken lan-
tion, infants saw two movies containing a novel guages, even languages they have never heard
segment of the same song they had already (Eimas, 1974, 1975; Eimas, Siqueland, Jusczyk,
heard, but the visual stimulus (i.e. the dancing) & Vigorito, 1971; Trehub, 1976). These early
that accompanied that segment differed for each abilities change dramatically by the end of the
movie. For the synchronous movie, the dancing first year, when infants only discriminate speech
matched the song and for the asynchronous sounds that demarcate meaning in their native
movie the dancing matched a separate song language, presumably because of their expo-
with a contrasting tempo. Infants dishabituated sure to linguistic input containing dispropor-
only to the asynchronous video, presumably tionately frequent exemplars of native-language
because they noticed that the dancing did not categories (Kuhl, Williams, Lacerda, Stevens,
match the music. In a control condition, infants & Lindblom, 1992; Kuhl et al., 2006; Maye
showed no preference after habituation to the et al., 2002; Werker & Lalonde, 1988; Werker &
same visual stimuli presented without sound, Tees, 1984). Other recent findings suggest that
suggesting that discrimination in the experi- a similar progression occurs for face identifi-
mental condition was based on true intersen- cation, where accurate discrimination of indi-
sory perception. Although previous studies vidual monkey and human faces is robust early
have shown that infants perceive audiovisual in infancy (i.e., before 6 months) but declines
synchrony when both auditory and visual stim- between 6 and 9 months, when infants continue
uli contain discrete events, such as the sight and to accurately discriminate only individuals of
sound of a ball bouncing (Lewkowicz, 1996), their own species (Pascalis, de Haan, & Nelson,
the above task requires inference of metrical 2002) or race (Kelly et al., 2007). Even intersen-
structure from rich and complex information sory perception may undergo comparable devel-
in both modalities. Thus, infants may be sensi- opmental changes, such as discriminating the
tive to visual temporal information that is cor- visual head and lip movements of one’s native
related with musical meter. Future studies will language from those of a foreign language, an
investigate the relative contributions of both ability that declines between 4 and 8 months of
vestibular/movement and visual cues in infants’ age (Weikum et al., 2007).
music learning. The above examples demonstrate percep-
To summarize, the findings described above tual tuning for socially significant, frequently
strongly support the claim that infants can infer encountered stimuli in multiple domains. Given
temporal structure in music from the same basic the prominence of music in early caregiving
statistics that are known to influence adults’ contexts (Trehub & Trainor, 1998), it is not sur-
perception of such structures. Moreover, they prising that enculturation to musical structures
do this not only in the auditory modality, but is also characterized by a similar developmental
also make use of multiple and redundant cues trajectory, where young infants discriminate
available through movement and vision. musical structures that elude their parents but
MUSICAL ENCULTUR ATION 137

begin to exhibit culture-specific declines by the example, in order for the rhythm depicted
end of the first year. in Figure 7.2 (top) to support an isochronous
metrical hierarchy, its event onsets must occur
Developmental Changes in Perception
primarily at strong metrical positions, which
of Meter
naturally leads to 1:1 and 2:1 duration ratios.
It is widely assumed that when listeners infer The challenge of inferring a primary pulse
the meter in music, they not only experience in music seems particularly daunting when
a primary pulse that is isochronous (i.e. com- one considers the fact that live music is rarely
posed of equal duration intervals), but they also isochronous but instead tends to contain inter-
perceive additional isochronous levels that are onset intervals that vary continuously as a func-
subdivisions or multiples of the primary pulse, tion of the performer’s expressive intentions
all of which are integral to the metrical hier- (Repp, 1992). For example, when a performer
archy (Lerdahl & Jackendoff, 1983; Palmer & begins to slow down at the end of a phrase, the
Krumhansl, 1990). Figure 7.2 (top) illustrates a interonset intervals will become incrementally
typical Western, isochronous metrical hierar- longer, but this does not necessarily lead the
chy, with three levels of isochronous structure listener to reinterpret the meter. Rather, the
giving rise to weak, strong, and stronger met- listener ignores the subtle differences in inter-
rical positions. Because perception of meter is val size and consequent interval ratios, and
dependent on the regular occurrence of events categorizes intervals according to the metrical
at strong metrical positions, isochronous met- hierarchy that he or she has inferred (Desain &
rical hierarchies tend to constrain the pattern Honing, 2003).
of interonset intervals in music by requiring Abundant evidence of metrical categoriza-
primarily simple-integer duration ratios. For tion can be found in studies of perception and

Isochronous

Metrical hierarchy

Metrical stress S w s w S w s w S w s w S

Rhythm

Interval ratios 2 : 1 : 1 : 2

Nonisochronous

Metrical hierarchy
Metrical stress S w w s w s w S w w w s w

Rhythm

Interval ratios 3 : 2 : 2 : 3 : 2

Figure 7.2 Metrical hierarchies for isochronous Western (top) and nonisochronous Balkan (bottom)
meters. In an isochronous metrical hierarchy, typical of Western music, multiple levels of isochro-
nous structure can be felt simultaneously, giving rise to simple duration ratios in the set of interonset
intervals comprising the rhythm. In a nonisochronous metrical hierarchy, typical in Balkan music,
multiple levels can also be felt but the intermediate level, which tends to be the primary pulse for danc-
ing and movement, is made up of alternating long and short intervals having a 3:2 ratio. These ratios
are also evident in the rhythm that supports that meter.
138 WORDS, LANGUAGE, AND MUSIC

production of rhythms. In spontaneous rhythm This is reflected in the performance of North


production tasks, French adults tend to produce American adults (“Western Adults”), who
exclusively 1:1 and 2:1 ratios (Fraisse, 1978) even notice superthreshold temporal disruptions
when asked to tap irregularly (Fraisse, 1982). of a folk tune only when that tune has an iso-
When attempting to reproduce or synchro- chronous meter (with 2:1 ratios) but not when
nize with target rhythms containing complex it has a nonisochronous meter (with 3:2 ratios,
interonset interval ratios, most adults ignore see Figure 7.3) (Hannon & Trehub, 2005a). By
instructions and instead tend to produce 2:1 contrast, adults from Macedonia and Bulgaria
and 1:1 ratios (Cummins & Port, 1998; Essens, (“Balkan Adults”) perform equally well in both
1986; Essens & Povel, 1985; Povel, 1981; Repp, isochronous and nonisochronous conditions,
London, & Keller, 2005; Snyder, Hannon, Large, presumably because both are equally familiar
& Christiansen, 2006). Likewise, the brain activ- to these subjects.
ity that accompanies rhythmic reproduction Western adults may fail to detect disruptions
tasks is qualitatively different for simple- ver- to nonisochronous meters because their encod-
sus complex-ratio sequences, with more auto- ing of the original stimulus is compromised
matic processing associated with simple ratios by a strong tendency to assimilate all patterns
(Sakai et al., 1999). In perception tasks, listen- toward a familiar metrical template. The ten-
ers will label or transcribe (i.e. put into musical dency to assimilate can thus be interpreted as
notation) a rhythm according to a simple-ratio evidence of acquired culture-specific knowledge
category despite a continuous range of interval of meter, which may begin to emerge as early
ratios in the physical stimulus (Clarke, 1987; as infancy. After familiarization with the same
Desain & Honing, 2003; Large, 2000). These folk tunes described above, 6-month-old infants
findings probably reflect listeners’ tendency to exhibit a novelty preference for disrupted ver-
assume that rhythms fit into metrical hierar- sions, regardless of whether the familiarization
chies and thus assimilate complex-integer ratios stimulus was isochronous or nonisochronous
toward simple-integer ratios that support famil- (Figure 7.3) (Hannon & Trehub, 2005a). By 12
iar Western meters (the section “Constraints on months, however, this pattern changes, and
Music Learning” will discuss additional expla- Western infants fail to discriminate rhythmic
nations of simple-ratio biases). variations in the nonisochronous condition,
If biases toward simple-integer ratios arise even though they continue showing a nov-
from a tendency to assimilate patterns to iso- elty preference in the isochronous condition
chronous metrical hierarchies, then a listener’s (Hannon & Trehub, 2005b). Thus, enculturation
musical experience and knowledge would be to musical rhythms, more specifically acqui-
expected to exert at least some influence on sition of culture-specific metrical categories,
performance. In particular, listeners who are rapidly changes infants’ behavior and closely
accustomed to nonisochronous meters should parallels trends observed in other domains,
not have difficulty reproducing or identifying where initial discrimination abilities are main-
ratios other than 2:1 or 1:1 if such ratios exist tained for familiar structures but decline for
in the music of their culture. Both isochronous unfamiliar structures by the end of one year.
and nonisochronous meters are very common
The Role of Everyday Music Listening
in traditional music from throughout the world,
in Perceptual Reorganization
such as Africa, the Middle East, Eastern Europe,
and South Asia (Clayton, 2000; London, 1995, The observed developmental changes in Western
2004). Figure 7.2 (bottom) provides an example infants’ musical rhythm perception are pre-
of a typical Balkan rhythm and its metrical sumably driven by exposure to Western music,
hierarchy. Note that in addition to having fre- where simple ratios are much more frequent
quent 1:1 ratios, the rhythm also contains 3:2 than complex ratios. Thus, infants may build
ratios that are usually challenging for Western their culture-specific musical representations
listeners to perceive and produce (Essens, 1986). by simply listening to music, in the same way
MUSICAL ENCULTUR ATION 139

3 0.8
Isochronous
NonIsochronous
2 0.7

Novelty preference
1 0.6
Accuracy

0 0.5

–1 0.4

–2 0.3

–3 0.2
Western adults Balkan adults 6-month-olds 12-month-olds

Figure 7.3 Perception of isochronous and nonisochronous meters by infants and adults. Adults’
accuracy for the perceptual judgment task (i.e., tendency to state that a disrupted version of a folk tune
is dissimilar relative to a standard) is on the left y-axis, while infants’ novelty preference (amount of
orienting to the disrupted variation divided by total looking time) is on the right y-axis. Dashed line
indicates chance performance. Balkan adults and 6-month-old infants accurately differentiate rhyth-
mic variations in isochronous and nonisochronous contexts, while Western adults and 12-month-
olds only perform accurately in the isochronous metrical context. Data replotted from Hannon and
Trehub (2005a, 2005b).

that listening to native language and watching condition (Hannon & Trehub, 2005b). In this
familiar faces leads to declines in perception of study, parents of 12-month-old infants were sent
unfamiliar speech and faces (Kelly et al., 2007; CDs containing 10 minutes of Balkan folk dance
Pascalis, et al., 2002; Werker & Tees, 1984). music having nonisochronous meters, which
Simple training paradigms have been used to they were asked to play for their infants twice
demonstrate the effects of perceptual experi- per day for 2 weeks prior to coming into the lab-
ence, by testing discrimination in older infants oratory. During testing, infants were then pre-
after exposure to unfamiliar structures. For sented with the same stimuli as described above.
example, after American 9-month-old infants Importantly, the specific recordings heard at
are exposed to Mandarin Chinese through a home were completely different from the stim-
series of interactions with native speakers over a uli presented in the laboratory aside from shar-
4- to 6-week period, they successfully discrimi- ing nonisochronous meters. Nevertheless, after
nate Mandarin speech contrasts that their age- exposure to the Balkan music, 12-month-old
matched American counterparts do not (Kuhl, infants successfully discriminate nonisochro-
Tsao, & Liu, 2003). Similarly, when 9-month- nous rhythms on the basis of metrical disrup-
old infants are sent home with picture books tions. As can be seen from Figure 7.4, novelty
containing monkey faces, they subsequently preferences in the nonisochronous condition
discriminate individual monkey faces, unlike after exposure are indistinguishable from those
9-month-olds without such exposure (Pascalis obtained from Western 12-month-olds in the
et al., 2005). isochronous condition.
A brief period of at-home exposure to foreign It is tempting to conclude from these results
music also reverses the decline in the perfor- that by 12 months of age, infants have achieved
mance of older infants in the nonisochronous adult-like knowledge of meter. However,
Infants (12 months)
0.6

Novelty preference
0.55

0.5
Isochronous
Nonisochronous

0.45
No Exposure After Exposure

2 Children (4–8 years)

1.5

1
Accuracy

0.5

0
Isochronous
–0.5 Nonisochronous

–1
Session 1 Session 2

Adults (18 +years)

1.5

1
Accuracy

0.5

–0.5 Isochronous
Nonisochronous
–1
Session 1 Session 2

Figure 7.4 Effects of perceptual experience at different ages. For 12-month-old infants (top), at-home
exposure to nonisochronous meters results in significant improvement in discrimination perfor-
mance, where a novelty preference is only obtained in the non-isochronous condition after expo-
sure. For children (middle), comparable results are obtained using a perceptual judgment paradigm.
Preexposure performance reflects accurate performance in the isochronous condition but chance
performance in the nonisochronous condition. After exposure, children’s performance in the noni-
sochronous condition is above chance and indistinguishable from performance in the isochronous
condition. By contrast, the performance of adults (bottom) in the nonisochronous condition does
change after at-home exposure, but never reaches above-chance levels or levels of accuracy obtained
in the isochronous condition. Infant and adult data are replotted from Hannon and Trehub (2005b).
Child data are from Hannon and Soley (in preparation).

140
MUSICAL ENCULTUR ATION 141

exposure to foreign music does not have the in adults. Despite the fact that Western adults
same effect on adults, who improve after the do improve in the nonisochronous condition, a
same amount of exposure but do not discrim- considerable gap remains between performance
inate nonisochronous rhythms above chance in isochronous versus nonisochronous contexts
levels off after 2 weeks of at-home exposure even after exposure. Thus, by investigating the
(Figure 7.4) (Hannon & Trehub, 2005b). It is extent to which a representation is susceptible
not clear exactly why the effects of training to modification, we learn that culture-specific
differ across ages, but such disparities may indi- representations of musical rhythm and meter
cate that infants’ musical representations have may continue to undergo developmental change
greater flexibility and are more susceptible to throughout childhood.
being influenced by perceptual experience than
Mechanisms of Perceptual Development
are those of adults. In particular, it should be
and Reorganization
possible to document developmental changes
not only in a listener’s tendency to assimilate Across speech, face, and music perception, we
unfamiliar rhythms to culture-specific catego- see a strikingly similar developmental picture.
ries, but also in the extent to which those assim- What drives these developmental changes
ilative tendencies can be modified by passive during infancy and why are similar patterns
exposure to unfamiliar music. observed across such disparate domains? One
Recent research on this topic (Hannon & proposal is that repeated exposure to particular
Soley, in preparation) suggests that adult-like sounds and sights leads neural circuits underly-
representations of musical meter may not ing perception to become increasingly commit-
emerge until after age 8. North American chil- ted to the statistics of the input (Kuhl, 2004).
dren aged 4–8 undertook the same basic train- Thus, initial abilities to discriminate unfamil-
ing regimen as described above for adults. iar structures arise from immature, uncom-
Testing occurred at repeated sessions 2 weeks mitted circuitry, which is then “warped” by
apart, using a game-like procedure adapted experience, whereby representations of more
from the adult task in which they judged the frequently encountered stimuli expand as pro-
similarity of two musical stimuli by adjusting totypes. These modified representations in turn
the position of a game piece. During the 2-week influence the extent to which future learning is
training period, children listened at home to possible because novel stimuli will tend to be
10-min recordings of Balkan folk music twice assimilated toward the prototype if they share
every day. Figure 7.4 shows that data from chil- its properties.
dren replicate the classic findings obtained with This account is generally consistent with
Western adults and 12-month-olds prior to patterns of early brain development. Infancy
exposure; 4- to 8-year-old children successfully is characterized by a proliferation of synap-
distinguish rhythms in the isochronous condi- ses followed by pruning, a process driven by
tion but perform at chance levels in the noniso- Hebbian learning through which repeated use
chronous condition. Importantly, performance (i.e., exposure to particular types of faces) leads
in the isochronous and nonisochronous condi- to a strengthening of neural circuits and disuse
tions differs significantly. After exposure, how- (i.e., lack of exposure to other-species or other-
ever, children perform at above-chance levels race faces) leads to deterioration (Huttenlocher
in both isochronous and nonisochronous con- & Dabholkar, 1997; Scott, Pascalis, & Nelson,
ditions and their performance in the two con- 2007). It is also consistent with studies of sec-
ditions is indistinguishable. As can be seen in ond language learning, in which adult learners
Figure 7.4, children’s accuracy is lower than have greater difficulty perceiving and produc-
that of adults in all conditions, but it is never- ing foreign speech contrasts than do younger
theless striking that passive exposure to foreign learners, especially when the target contrasts
music gives rise to native-like levels of perfor- interfere with the phonology of the subjects’
mance in children (and 12-month-olds) but not native language (Flege, Yeni-Komshian, & Liu,
142 WORDS, LANGUAGE, AND MUSIC

1999; Iverson et al., 2003; McCandliss, Fiez, which the system automatically overcomes or
Protopapas, Conway, & McClelland, 2002). suppresses perceptual distinctions that are not
Such a model might also describe the formation relevant to a particular individual’s experience
of culture-specific metrical categories, where (Rivera-Gaxiola et al., 2000).
frequent exposure to simple ratios and isochro- Consistent with this view is the notion that
nous meters leads to the formation of metrical developmental changes across these multiple
prototypes that subsequently influence how lis- domains arise from domain-general aspects of
teners interpret events and form expectations cognitive development, such as the ability to
while listening to music. inhibit irrelevant information. Indeed, when 8-
Importantly, the observed declines in to 10-month-old infants’ nonnative consonant
discrimination across modalities have not discrimination is compared with their perfor-
been interpreted as signifying a loss of ability. mance in object search (A not B) and visual cat-
Rather, they are seen to reflect an enhancement egorization tasks, developmental changes across
of representations that code familiar structures tasks appear to occur in synchrony (Werker
and a rise in the ability to ignore irrelevant & Lalonde, 1995). In other words, infants who
information. In the speech domain, recent perform most accurately in a nonspeech task
evidence suggests that declines in discrimina- are also poorest at nonnative consonant dis-
tion of nonnative contrasts are accompanied crimination. It is not currently known whether
by improvements in perception of native con- performance on nonmusical cognitive tasks
trasts (Kuhl et al., 2005, 2006). Similarly, indi- would correlate with perception of unfamiliar
vidual variability in discrimination of native musical structures.
and nonnative speech contrasts is correlated Maturational changes in neural plasticity
with language skills during childhood, such and cognitive control may account for the occur-
as language production, comprehension, and rence of similar patterns of perceptual develop-
reading (Burnham, 2004; Kuhl et al., 2005; ment across music, speech, and face perception,
Tsao, Liu, & Kuhl, 2004). Thus, declines in and may explain why adults have greater dif-
discrimination of foreign meters are probably ficulty learning unfamiliar, culture-specific
not due to a worsening of music perception, structures than do infants. It is also worth con-
but rather the result of strengthened culture- sidering, however, the ways in which perceptual
specific music knowledge. experience itself could function to change the
Moreover, despite showing poor discrimi- nature of the learner, independent of matura-
nation of unfamiliar structures in behavioral tion. One possibility is that age-related changes
tasks, paradigms using eye-tracking or event- in the ability to learn novel structures arise from
related brain potentials reveal that adults the amount of interference between culturally
and older infants do in fact, at a preattentive unfamiliar and familiar structures (Flege et al.,
level, respond to subtle distinctions in foreign 1999). As representations of familiar structures
speech and in nonhuman faces (McMurray & become more elaborate and more entrenched,
Aslin, 2005; Rivera-Gaxiola, Csibra, Johnson, whether for own-species faces, native language
& Karmiloff-Smith, 2000; Rivera-Gaxiola, speech contrasts, or familiar musical meters,
Silva-Pereyra, & Kuhl, 2005; Scott, Shannon, the impact of unfamiliar structures on the
& Nelson, 2006). At some level, older infants, existing representation will diminish because
children, and adults must also remain sensitive the unfamiliar structures will be perceptu-
to complex ratios and meters in music despite ally assimilated or ignored. Studies of second
their poor performance in the behavioral task, language learning are largely consistent with
otherwise it would not be possible for discrimi- this account (Iverson et al., 2003; McCandliss
nation to improve as a result of exposure. Thus, et al., 2002), but controlled studies are made
developmental declines across all modalities difficult by the fact that age and acquisition of
may be less indicative of perceptual deteriora- knowledge are typically confounded through-
tion and more indicative of a reorganization in out development. Evidence from animal models
MUSICAL ENCULTUR ATION 143

suggests that after being deprived of patterned absorb all information encountered. Yet infants
input to sensory cortex, cortical organization somehow manage to focus on the statistics that
in deprived but older animals closely resembles lead to mastery of appropriate structures in
that of younger animals (Chang & Merzenich, appropriate domains. In this section, I will dis-
2003). This strongly supports the notion that cuss possible constraints for learning musical
by preventing experience-related tuning from rhythm and meter.
occurring, we can reverse or postpone expected What are the starting points for music learn-
developmental changes independent of age or ing? It is sensible to assume that all learning will
maturation. be constrained to some extent by intrinsic prop-
To summarize, multiple mechanisms may erties of the nervous system, such as the struc-
account for parallel developmental changes ture of sensory organs. The phenomenon of
across the music, face, and language domains, musical consonance and dissonance provides a
ranging from brain maturation and pruning classic example of this in the auditory domain.
to cognitive control to experience-based inter- Simultaneous pitches that stand in simple inte-
ference. An important goal for future research ger ratios (such as 2:1, 3:2, and 4:3, corresponding
will be to describe in more detail the develop- to the octave, fifth, and fourth) are termed con-
mental trajectory of culture-specific knowledge sonant, while pitches standing in more complex
in multiple domains and to compare individ- ratios (such as 11:12 or 45:32, corresponding to
ual development across domains to under- the minor second and the tritone) are termed
stand why such change occurs. For example, if dissonant. Throughout the world and over the
experience-based changes are solely responsible course of history, consonant intervals tend to
for developmental change, we should see little occur more frequently in music and give rise to
correlation across domains and individual dif- positive affective responses, whereas the oppo-
ferences that vary according to amount of expo- site is true of dissonant intervals (Cross, 2001;
sure in a specific domain. If, however, more Dowling & Harwood, 1984; Kilmer, Crocker, &
general maturational factors also play a role, Brown, 1976; Koelsch, Fritz, Cramon, Müller, &
we would expect to see more congruence across Friederici, 2006). The distinction between con-
domains and relatively small individual differ- sonance and dissonance likely originates in the
ences as a function of specific experience. Music structure of the ear—the frequencies of disso-
may provide a particularly unique opportunity nant intervals tend to be too close to be resolved
to address these questions, because exposure to on the basilar membrane so their resulting vibra-
music even within a culture is subject to much tion patterns give rise to beating and percep-
greater individual variability (i.e., different lis- tion of roughness (Fishman et al., 2001; Tramo,
tening practices across families and individu- Cariani, Koh, Makris, & Braida, 2003). It is pre-
als) than exposure to other structures such as sumably for this reason that human infants and
speech and faces. even nonhuman animals are able to discriminate
and categorize sounds on the basis of consonance
and dissonance (Schellenberg & Trainor, 1996;
CONSTRAINTS ON MUSIC LEARNING
Watanabe, Uozumi, & Tanaka, 2005).
The above sections focus on the role of percep- Humans not only discriminate conso-
tual experience and learning mechanisms in nance and dissonance, but they find beating
acquiring music knowledge. It is also impor- and roughness aversive, which is probably why
tant, however, to understand the constraints robust listening preferences to consonant over
that define the starting point for learning and dissonant intervals have been observed in very
limit what can be learned. Because newborns young infants, including hearing newborns of
are faced with a virtual cacophony of struc- deaf mothers who may have reduced prena-
tures across all sensory modalities, we might tal exposure to musical intervals (Masataka,
expect the learning process to be easily derailed 2006; Trainor & Heinmiller, 1998; Trainor,
as infants voraciously and indiscriminately Tsang, & Cheung, 2002; Zentner & Kagan,
144 WORDS, LANGUAGE, AND MUSIC

1996). Interestingly, encoding and memory for


Biological Basis for Biases toward
musical patterns can be compromised by dis-
Regularity?
sonance. For example, adults and 6-month-old
infants have greater difficulty detecting subtle Why are irregular rhythms so challenging for
frequency changes in patterns containing dis- listeners? Most explanations rely on the assump-
sonant intervals than in patterns containing tion that internal timekeeping mechanisms,
consonant intervals (Acker, Pastore, & Hall, such as a grid, clock, or bank of oscillators, con-
1995; Schellenberg & Trehub, 1994, 1996). The strain rhythmic perception and behavior such
phenomenon of consonance and dissonance that regular sequences are more efficiently pro-
thus illustrates how peripheral properties (i.e., cessed than irregular sequences. Clock or grid
frequency resolution in the ear) can give rise models assume that the listener deduces a max-
to a cascade of effects shaping discrimination, imally efficient description of rhythmic patterns
esthetic preferences, and efficiency of encod- where individual events line up with the period
ing in infants and adults, which may ultimately of one or more internal clocks (Povel, 1984).
determine which structures humans prefer in Rhythms containing event onsets that do not
music throughout the world. consistently support a single clock (or when they
Do similar constraints affect temporal struc- simultaneously support many clocks) are not
tures in music? Although the ear is not a likely easily described, and thus force the listener to
candidate for constraining perception of rhythm rely on explicit memory of each interval instead
and meter, domain-general mechanisms in the of iterated interval categories (Janata & Grafton,
nervous system—such as those underlying pre- 2003; Povel, 1984; Semjen & Ivry, 2001).
diction and movement—may give rise to intrin- Dynamical systems approaches describe
sic biases for temporal regularity. Unpredictable rhythmic pattern coordination using the math-
auditory sequences result in more anxiety-like ematics of nonlinear oscillators (Large, 2001;
behavior and sustained amygdala activity than Treff ner & Turvey, 1993). One model of musi-
do predictable sequences, suggesting that at cal meter proposes that temporal patterns are
some level, listeners find temporal irregular- represented by a bank of internal oscillators
ity aversive and may therefore seek out regu- that entrain to periodicities in the stimulus
larity (Herry et al., 2007). Adult listeners also and compete for activation through inhibition
have greater difficulty discriminating tempo- (Large, 2001; Large & Jones, 1999). The intrin-
ral intervals, patterns, or individual pitches sic dynamics of oscillators give rise to greater
when the preceding context is unpredictable stability for simple ratios and greater instability
than when it is predictable (Barnes & Jones, for complex ratios. Importantly, the behavioral
2000; Drake & Botte, 1993; Jones, Johnston, & output of coupled oscillators need not rely on
Puente, 2006; Jones, Moynihan, Mackenzie, & complex or highly specialized neural substrates.
Puente, 2002). As reviewed above, the simplic- The ratios that are most stable for human inter-
ity of serial interval ratios predicts how well limb coordination (Peper et al., 1995) are also
adults can reproduce, identify, remember, and most stable for synchronous behavior in sing-
synchronize with rhythmic patterns (Collier & ing birds (Laje & Mindlin, 2003) and courting
Wright, 1995; Desain & Honing, 2003; Essens, fireflies (Buck, 1988), suggesting that in prin-
1986; Essens & Povel, 1985; Hannon & Trehub, ciple, similar mechanisms could be responsi-
2005a; Large, 2000; Povel, 1981; Repp et al., ble for movement coordination across species.
2005; Snyder et al., 2006). Abundant evidence Thus, basic human interlimb coordination,
also suggests that production and perception of such as walking, running, and other forms of
parallel ratios (i.e., the ratios between two simul- movement, may give rise to temporal process-
taneous periodic patterns, such as polyrhythms) ing mechanisms that bias listeners toward regu-
is affected by ratio simplicity (Deutsch, 1983; larity (Summers, 2001).
Klapp, 1981; Klapp et al., 1985; Peper, Beek, & By claiming that simple-integer temporal
van Wieringen, 1995; Treff ner & Turvey, 1993). ratios are intrinsically easier for timekeeping
MUSICAL ENCULTUR ATION 145

mechanisms to represent, the above accounts rhythmic patterns (Nakata & Mitani, 2005;
are seemingly at odds with findings reviewed Soley & Hannon, submitted), and they appear
in the section “Building Musical Knowledge to have difficulty in processing and remember-
through Enculturation,” which underscore the ing patterns having unconventional rhythmic
role of culture and experience by showing that structure (Trehub & Hannon, 2009). In this
one’s prior exposure to nonisochronous musi- study, adults listened to a corpus of rhythmic
cal structures dramatically shapes the extent arrangements of a 12-note pitch sequence and
to which irregularity disrupts performance labeled each arrangement as either “good” or
(Hannon & Trehub, 2005a, 2005b). Learning “bad.” The arrangement most frequently labeled
and experience are also implicated by individ- bad and the one labeled good were selected
ual differences in production of complex-ratio for use in a detection task, where adults and
sequences, because 3:2 ratios can pose great dif- 6-month-old infants were trained to respond
ficulty for most subjects (Povel, 1981) but pose to subtle disruptions of either the good or
minimal difficulty for subjects with extensive bad arrangement (adults responded by rais-
music training (Collier & Wright, 1995; although ing a hand while infants made a head-turn).
this was not found by Hannon & Trehub, 2005a Although changes were successfully detected
or Repp et al., 2005). Training studies also show in all conditions, both infants and adults were
that practice can dramatically improve the pro- significantly better at detecting a 260-ms rhyth-
duction of complex-ratio polyrhythms (Krampe, mic change to the good arrangement than to the
Kliegl, Mayr, Engbert, & Vorbert, 2000; Zanone bad arrangement, even though the serial posi-
& Kelso, 1992). Any explanation of intrinsic tion and size of the change was identical in both
biases toward regularity must therefore account conditions. Thus, some aspect of rhythm in the
for the effects of experience and learning. sequence most preferred by adults may have
afforded better perceptual processing regard-
The Importance of Temporal Regularity
less of experience and culture. The basis for this
for Infants
processing advantage is difficult to determine,
To the extent that basic timing mechanisms of however, because the good and bad arrange-
the nervous system are responsible for biases ments were unique and thus differed from each
toward temporal regularity in adults, we should other in multiple ways. One potential explana-
expect infants and adults to have equal dif- tion is that the good rhythm implied a consis-
ficulty processing irregular patterns. Instead, tent underlying pulse whereas the bad rhythm
as described above, 6-month-olds outperform implied multiple pulses at different points in
adults at discriminating patterns containing the pattern. Without controlled manipulation
3:2 ratios, suggesting that either (1) infants in of specific structures, however, it is impossible
these experiments are not processing rhythmic to know why the good arrangement gave rise to
patterns in an entirely adult-like fashion but are superior performance.
using some alternative strategy such as remem- The above finding implies that infants’
bering interval sequences or (2) infants and rhythm perception is not infinitely flexible, but
adults process patterns using the same mecha- might instead be constrained by at least some
nisms, which can accommodate slightly com- of the limitations that apply to adults. If infants
plex ratios such as 3:2 but not highly complex and adults rely on the same basic temporal
ratios—enculturation processes during infancy mechanisms, we should see even very young
then suppress ratios not used in familiar musi- infants struggle with highly complex ratios
cal styles. The mechanisms underlying infants’ that are relatively rare in music. If, however,
perception of rhythm and meter are not yet infants use an alternative strategy to discrim-
understood, but recent fi ndings lend support to inate rhythmic patterns, such as memorizing
the latter hypothesis. a sequence of specific intervals, then the com-
Like adults, young infants exhibit lis- plexity of interval ratios should not matter as
tening preferences for simple over complex long as the serial structure of rhythms is simple.
146 WORDS, LANGUAGE, AND MUSIC

Hannon (in preparation-b) recently addressed continuity between infants and adults in the
this question by examining how 4- to 6-month- nature and limitations of basic temporal pro-
old infants perceive rhythmic patterns having cessing mechanisms. Although such mecha-
varying levels of ratio complexity. Three rhyth- nisms are not fully understood, they may derive
mic variations of the same folk tune were cre- from dynamic behaviors such as anticipatory
ated containing simple Western (2:1), complex attending and the coordination of various
Balkan (3:2) and highly complex “Alien” (7:4) types of movement. Models of rhythmic tim-
ratios (see Figure 7.5). In all three conditions, ing suggest that perfectly isochronous meters
the song cycled through a sequence of Long– are optimal, but they also suggest that there is
Short–Short intervals with the duration of the a continuum of complexity with ratios such as
long interval set at 756 ms; the only difference 3:2 positioned at the simpler end. In this light,
between conditions was the size of the short it is interesting to consider features of non-iso-
interval and the resulting ratio. After habitua- chronous musical meters throughout the world,
tion to the standard version of one of the three such as those common in India, the Balkans, and
variations, infants were alternately presented throughout Africa, which tend to be restricted,
with the standard and a changed version con- at least in practice, to alternating patterns of
taining a 200-ms increase in the duration of the 2 and 3 (London, 2004; Powers & Widdess,
long interval. Thus, across the three conditions, 2001). By better understanding early tempo-
the absolute size of the target interval and the ral processing constraints, future research can
change were held constant. Infants showed a develop more thorough and complete accounts
novelty preference for the disrupted stimulus in of musical rhythm learning.
the simple and complex conditions, but showed
no preference in the highly complex condition,
CULTURE-SPECIFICRHYTHMIC STRUCTURES
suggesting that ratio complexity does influence
IN MUSIC AND SPEECH
how listeners perceive rhythms even prior to
enculturation. Music and speech unquestionably depend on
In summary, although young infants are specialized perceptual processes that are often
culture-general music listeners, they are never- associated with distinct and separable brain
theless influenced by the regularity of rhythmic areas (Binder et al., 2000; Narain et al., 2003;
patterns and the simplicity of temporal inter- Peretz et al., 1994; Vouloumanos, Kiehl, Werker
val ratios, presumably because there is some & Liddle, 2001), a fact that has contributed to

Standard Change (L+200)

Simple 2:1 756 378 956 378

Complex 3:2 756 504 956 504

Highly 7:4 756 432 956 432


complex

Figure 7.5 Simple, complex, and highly complex versions of a folk tune used in three conditions of
a habituation experiment with young infants (Hannon, in preparation-b). The standard rhythm in
the simple condition contained a repeating cycle of long and short intervals having a 2:1 ratio. The
complex Balkan rhythm contained 3:2 ratios, whereas the highly complex rhythm contained a 7:4
ratio, which is relatively rare in music. In all three conditions, the standard and a changed version
were presented after habituation. The change consisted of a 200-ms increase in the duration of the
long interval. Note that the absolute size of the long interval was identical across conditions for the
standard and change stimulus.
MUSICAL ENCULTUR ATION 147

the widely held assumption that music and as the process through which culture-specific
language abilities arise from modular, innate knowledge is built through everyday listening
adaptations (Fodor, 1983; Liberman & Mattingly, experiences, as infants and children attempt
1985; Peretz & Coltheart, 2003; Peretz & Hyde, to actively predict and interpret patterns that
2003). However, these assumptions have been unfold over time. Because speech and music
challenged by evidence that individuals with are both complex and dynamic acoustic struc-
music-specific deficits also exhibit impairments tures, young listeners likely build music- and
in speech perception (Patel, Foxton, & Griffiths, language-specific representations in paral-
2005) and that individuals with language- lel. Thus, if the culture-specific structures of
specific deficits also show impairment on music child-directed music and speech contain a high
tasks (Alcock, Passingham, Watkins, & Vargha- degree of overlap, this might have implications
Khadem, 2000). Studies using brain-imaging in for early representations of music and speech.
normal adult listeners have provided additional Rhythm is not unique to music. Rhythmic
evidence that purportedly language-specific structure is also fundamental for speech com-
brain regions, such as Broca’s area, are also prehension and in fact probably plays a vital role
involved in music processing (Maess, Koelsch, in infants’ early responses to language. Within
Gunter, & Friederici, 2001). Thus, evidence of days of birth, newborn infants can discrimi-
at least some shared processes for music and nate native from foreign utterances of speech
speech contradicts a strictly modular account. (Bahrick & Pickens 1988; Mehler et al., 1988;
Nevertheless, there are undoubtedly many Moon, Cooper, & Fifer, 1993). The preference is
speech- and music-specific structures in the maintained even when utterances are low-pass
adult brain, although the origins of such special- fi ltered, preserving only the rhythmic prop-
ization are not clear. Some behavioral evidence erties of speech and mimicking the quality of
suggests that speech-specific processes may be sound in utero (Abrams et al., 2000; Mehler
functional very early—for example, 2-month- et al., 1988).
old infants prefer speech to nonspeech stim- Language-specific rhythmic structures
uli, even when the acoustic structure of speech probably form the basis for these early native-
and nonspeech is very similar (Vouloumanos & language preferences. The speech rhythm of a
Werker, 2004) and infants may employ a type language has historically been defined by lin-
of rule-learning that is optimally suited to lan- guists as arising from the way languages divide
guage (Marcus, Fernandes, & Johnson, 2007, but time; syllable-timed languages such as French
see Saff ran, Pollak, Seibel, & Shkolnik, 2007 for and Spanish use the syllable to mark equal time
an example of rule-learning in vision). It is not units whereas stress-timed languages such as
clear, however, that fully lateralized, language- English and Dutch use stressed syllables to mark
and music-specific structures exist in the brain equal units of time (Cutler, 1994; Jusczyk, 2002).
of the newborn (Dehaene-Lambertz, 2000). These rhythm-based classifications also map
In fact, recent studies suggest that language- onto newborn’s discrimination of languages—
specific brain areas do not emerge until late newborns fail to discriminate languages from
in infancy or after infancy (Imada et al., 2006; the same rhythmic class but easily discrimi-
Minagawa-Kawai, Mori, Naoi, & Kojima, 2007). nate languages from separate rhythmic classes
Thus, it is worth considering the possibility (Nazzi, Bertoncini, & Mehler, 1998). Acoustic
that domain-specificity develops—that infants measures have been identified that can classify
might initially approach both speech and music languages based on the amount of variability
with one set of basic auditory perceptual skills that characterizes adjacent vocalic and inter-
and learning mechanisms. vocalic intervals (Grabe & Low, 2002; Ramus,
As representations of music become increas- Nespor, & Mehler, 1999). One such measure, the
ingly culture-specific, so too might repre- normalized pairwise variability index (nPVI),
sentations of sound become increasingly has been successfully used to distinguish stress-
domain-specific. Enculturation is defined here timed languages such as English and German,
148 WORDS, LANGUAGE, AND MUSIC

which have higher vocalic interval variability, question to ask is whether such differences exist
from syllable-timed languages such as French in musical input directed toward young listen-
and Spanish, which have lower vocalic interval ers and if so whether the differences can be
variability. perceived.
Recent evidence suggests that there may be To address the fi rst question, 140 songs
a link between rhythmic structure in language from French- and English-speaking cultures
and music. Inspired by musicologists’ specula- were selected from children’s music antholo-
tions that a culture’s language influences its gies and analyzed for their rhythmic proper-
music, Patel and Daniele (2003) used nPVI to ties (Hannon, in preparation-c). Consistent
examine the variability of musical note dura- with prior fi ndings, English-language songs
tions in the themes of instrumental art music contained higher nPVI values than did French-
written by English- and French-speaking com- language songs (see Figure 7.6). Interestingly,
posers. They discovered that, like actual utter- the magnitude of the difference in children’s
ances of English and French speech, English music was somewhat larger than has been
musical themes contained higher durational obtained in prior studies using instrumental
contrast than did French themes. Subsequent (Huron & Ollen, 2003; Patel & Daniele, 2003)
studies have further verified a relationship and popular music (Sadakata et al., 2004). Th is
between speech prosody and musical struc- could arise if child-directed musical input
tures (Huron & Ollen, 2003; Patel, Iverson, & exaggerates culture-specific rhythmic proper-
Rosenberg, 2006; Sadakata, Desain, Honing, ties, but it could also result from the presence of
Patel, & Iversen, 2004). Given that culture-spe- words in all children’s songs examined, which
cific differences in rhythmic structure appear might have maximized the influence of the
to exist in both speech and music, a natural native language on musical rhythm over more

50
45 English
French
40
35
30
nPVI

25
20
15
10
5
0
Adults Children
Audience

Figure 7.6 Analysis of rhythmic variability in French and English songs for children and adults
(Hannon, in preparation-c). The normalized pairwise variability index (nPVI) for adjacent musical
notes represents the y-axis, and the compilation from which songs were selected as children’s or adult’s
(i.e., traditional folk songs with text) is on the x-axis. Dark bars represent English songs and light bars
represent French songs. For songs taken from adult compilations, the nPVI for English was slightly
higher (M = 41.6, N = 70) than for French (M = 40.01, N = 70). For songs taken from children’s compila-
tions, the nPVI for English was much higher (M = 42.03, N = 70) than for French (M = 33.54, N = 70).
Error bars represent standard error.
MUSICAL ENCULTUR ATION 149

instrumental samples. To test this possibility, SUMMARY


a second set of 140 French and English songs
with text were selected from traditional folk This chapter has outlined a research program
and popular music anthologies. Th is analysis that aims to understand how individuals build
revealed the same trend but much more mod- musical representations throughout develop-
est differences (see Figure 7.6). Future research ment. Instead of framing the question of musi-
will further explore differences between child- cal knowledge and behavior in terms of modular
and adult-directed songs, but these initial and unique capacities evolved through natural
fi ndings point toward the presence of culture- selection, this approach emphasizes the role of
specific rhythm differences in music directed perceptual experience and statistical learning
toward young listeners. that is domain-general, operating in tandem
In order for such differences to affect infants’ with simple constraints that arise from proper-
learning of music and speech, speech-based ties of the sensory organs and the nervous sys-
rhythmic structures must actually be meaning- tem. Infants learn about music as they actively
ful to listeners in the context of music. Although attempt to predict and interpret musical events
it is clear that infants and adults can perceive that unfold over time, and these experiences in
and categorize utterances of spoken language turn influence the nature of subsequent per-
on the basis of nPVI (Nazzi et al., 1998; Ramus ception and learning. Investigations of musi-
et al., 1999), comparable structures in music cal knowledge acquisition therefore have the
may simply exist as a by-product of setting text potential not only to shed light on the nature
to music and not necessarily be perceived by and origins of human musical behavior but also
listeners. To address this question, adult listen- may inform our understanding of perceptual
ers were required to categorize instrumental development across a number of domains.
versions of French and English children’s songs
as belonging to one of two fictional languages
(Hannon, in press). During the training phase, REFERENCES
they received feedback following every trial, but Abrams, R. M., Gerhardt, K. J., Huang, X., Peters,
during the test phase, they had to categorize an A. J. M., & Langford, R. G. (2000). Musical
entirely novel set of French and English chil- experiences of the unborn baby. Journal of
dren’s songs. Results showed that listeners were Sound and Vibration, 231, 253–258.
highly accurate (77% correct) in their categori- Acker, B. E., Pastore, R. E., & Hall, M. D. (1995).
zation of novel songs after training. Moreover, Within-category discrimination of musi-
cal chords: Perceptual magnet or anchor?
performance was unchanged after pitch infor-
Perception & Psychophysics, 57, 863–874.
mation was removed from the songs, suggest- Alcock, K. J., Passingham, R. E., Watkins, K., &
ing that rhythm was the primary cue and not Vargha-Khadem, F. (2000). Pitch and tim-
culture-specific pitch structure or familiar- ing abilities in inherited speech and language
ity. Thus, adult listeners were able to perceive impairment. Brain and Language, 75, 34–46.
and use language-based rhythmic differences Avanzini, G., Lopez, L., Koelsch, S., & Majno, M.
to categorize novel songs, suggesting that in (Eds.). (2006). The neurosciences and music II:
principle, infants may also be sensitive to these From perception to performance. New York:
structures. The New York Academy of Sciences.
In summary, a burgeoning research area is Bahrick, L. E., & Pickens, J. N. (1988). Classification
beginning to explore similarities in music and of bimodal English and Spanish passages by
infants. Infant Behavior and Development, 11,
language processing from a developmental
277–296.
perspective. By examining the nature of audi- Barnes, R., & Jones, M. R. (2000). Expectancy,
tory input in the environment of the young lis- attention, and time. Cognitive Psychology, 41,
tener, we may better understand developmental 254–311.
changes in culture-specific representations Bigand, E., & Poulin-Charronnat, B. (2006). Are
across music and speech domains. we “experienced listeners”? A review of the
150 WORDS, LANGUAGE, AND MUSIC

musical capacities that do not depend on formal Cummins, F., & Port, R. (1998). Rhythmic con-
music training. Cognition, 100, 100–130. straints on stress timing in English. Journal of
Binder, J. R., Frost, J. A., Hammeke, T. A., Phonetics, 26, 145–171.
Bellgowan, P. S. F., Springer, J. A., Kaufman, J. Cutler, A. (1994). Segmentation problems, rhyth-
N., et al. (2000). Human temporal lobe activa- mic solutions. Lingua, 92, 81–104.
tion by speech and nonspeech sounds. Cerebral Dalla Bella, S., Giguere, J., & Peretz, I. (2007).
Cortex, 10, 512–528. Singing proficiency in the general population.
Brown, S. (2003). Biomusicology, and three bio- Journal of the Acoustical Society of America,
logical paradoxes about music. Bulletin of 121, 1182–1189.
Psychology and the Arts, 4, 15–17. Deutsch, D. (1983). The generation of two iso-
Buck, J. (1988). Synchronous rhythmic flashing of chronous sequences in parallel. Perception &
fireflies. II. The Quarterly Review of Biology, 63, Psychophysics, 34, 331–337.
265–289. Dehaene-Lambertz, G. (2000). Cerebral special-
Burnham, D. (2004). Language specific speech ization for speech and non-speech stimuli in
perception and the onset of reading. Reading infants. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 12,
and Writing, 16, 573–609. 449–460.
Chang, E., & Merzenich, M. (2003). Environmental Desain, P., & Honing, H. (2003). The formation
noise retards auditory cortical development. of rhythmic categories and metric priming.
Science, 300(5618), 498–502. Perception, 32, 341–365.
Christiansen, M. H., Allen, J., & Seidenberg, M. S. Dowling, W. J., & Harwood, D. L. (1986). Music
(1998). Learning to segment speech using mul- cognition. Orlando, FL: Academic Press.
tiple cues: A connectionist model. Language Drake, C. & Botte, M. (1993). Tempo sensitivity in
and Cognitive Processes, 13, 221–268. auditory sequences: Evidence for the multiple
Clarke, E. F. (1987). Levels of structure in the orga- look model. Perception and Psychophysics, 54,
nization of musical time. Contemporary Music 277–286.
Review, 2, 211–239. Drayna, D., Manichaikul, A., de Lange, M.,
Clayton, M. (2000). Time in Indian music. New Snieder, H., & Spector, T. (2001). Genetic cor-
York: Oxford University Press. relates of musical pitch recognition in humans.
Collier, G. L., & Wright, C. E. (1995). Temporal res- Science, 291, 1969–1972.
caling of simple and complex ratios in rhythmic Eimas, P. D. (1974). Auditory and linguistic process-
tapping. Journal of Experimental Psychology: ing of cues for place of articulation by infants.
Human Perception and Performance, 21, Perception & Psychophysics, 16, 513–521.
602–627. Eimas, P. D. (1975). Auditory and phonetic coding
Compston, A. (Ed.). (2006). Music and the brain of the cues for speech: Discrimination of the
[Special Issue]. Brain, 129. [r-l] distinction by young infants. Perception &
Conway, C. M., & Christiansen, M. H. (2006). Psychophysics, 18, 341–347.
Statistical learning within and between modali- Eimas, P. D., Siqueland, E. R., Jusczyk, P. W., &
ties: Pitting abstract against stimulus specific rep- Vigorito, J. (1971). Speech perception in infants.
resentations. Psychological Science, 17, 905–912. Science, 171, 303–306.
Creel, S. C., & Newport, E. L. (2002). Tonal profi les Essens, P. (1986). Hierarchical organization of
of artificial scales: Implications for music learn- temporal patterns. Perception & Psychophysics,
ing. In C. Stevens, D. Burnham, G. McPherson, 40, 69–73.
E.Schubert, & J. Renwick (Eds.), Proceedings Essens, P., & Povel, D. (1985). Metrical and non-
of the 7th International Conference on Music metrical representations of temporal patterns.
Perception and Cognition, Sydney. Adelaide: Perception & Psychophysics, 37, 1–7.
Causal Productions. Fishman, Y. I., Volkov, I. O., Noh, M. D., Garell,
Cross, I. (2001). Music, cognition, culture and P. C., Bakken, H., Arezzo, J. C., et al. (2001).
evolution. Annals of the New York Academy of Consonance and dissonance of musical chords:
Sciences, 930, 28–42. Nural correlates in auditory cortex of monkeys
Cuddy, L. L., & Badertscher, B. (1987). Recovery of and humans. The Journal of Neurophysiology,
the tonal hierarchy: Some comparisons across 86, 2761–2788.
age and levels of musical experience. Perception Flege, J. E., Yeni-Komshian, G. H., & Liu, S. (1999).
& Psychophysics, 41, 609–620. Age constraints on second-language acqui-
MUSICAL ENCULTUR ATION 151

sition. Journal of Memory and Language, 1, Hannon, E. E., & Trehub, S. E. (2005a). Metrical
78–104. categories in infancy and adulthood.
Fodor, J. A. (1983). The modularity of mind: An Psychological Science, 16, 48–55.
essay on faculty psychology. Cambridge, MA: Hannon, E. E., & Trehub, S. E. (2005b). Tuning in
MIT Press. to rhythms: Infants learn more readily than
Fraisse, P. (1978). Time and rhythm perception. adults. Proceedings of the National Academy of
In E. C. Carterette & M. P. Friedman (Eds.), Sciences (USA), 102, 12639–12643.
Handbook of perception (Vol. 8, pp. 203–254). Hauser, M. D., & McDermott, J. (2003). The evolu-
New York: Academic Press. tion of the music faculty: A comparative per-
Fraisse, P. (1982). Rhythm and tempo. In spective. Nature Neuroscience, 6, 663–668.
D. Deutsch (Ed), The psychology of music Herry, C., Bach, D. R., Esposito, F., Di Salle,
(pp. 149–180). New York: Academic Press. F., Perrig, W. J., Scheffler, K., et al. (2007).
Grabe, E., & Low, E. L. (2002). Durational vari- Processing of temporal unpredictability in
ability in speech and the rhythm class hypoth- human and animal amygdala. The Journal of
esis. In C. Gussenhoven & N. Warner (Eds.), Neuroscience, 27, 5958–5966.
Laboratory phonology (pp. 515–546). Berlin: Huron, D. (2003). Is music an evolutionary adap-
Mouton de Gruyter. tation?. In I. Peretz & R. J. Zatorre (Eds.), The
Grewe, O., Kopiez, R., & Altenmüller, E. (2005). cognitive neuroscience of music (pp. 57–75).
How does music arouse “chills”? Investigating New York: Oxford University Press.
strong emotions, combining psychological, Huron, D., & Ollen, J. (2003). Agogic contrasts in
physiological, and psychoacoustic methods. French and English themes: Further support
Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, for Patel and Daniele (2003). Music Perception,
1060, 446–449. 21, 267–271.
Hannon, E. E. Infants know bad dancing when Huron, D., & Royal, M. (1996). What is melodic
they see it: Audiovisual synchrony perception accent? Converging evidence from musical
of dancing to music in 10-month-old infants. practice. Music Perception, 13, 489–516.
Manuscript in preparation-a. Huttenlocher, P. R., & Dabholkar, A. S. (1997).
Hannon, E. E. Infants’ perception of musical rhythm Regional differences in synaptogenesis in
is culture-general but constrained by ratio sim- human cerebral cortex. Journal of Comparative
plicity. Manuscript in preparation-b. Neurology, 387, 167–178.
Hannon, E. E. Speech rhythms are exaggerated in Hyde, K. & Peretz, I. (2004). Brains that are out
children’s music. Manuscript in preparation-c. of tune but in time. Psychological Science, 15,
Hannon, E. E., & Soley, G. Children learn to 356–360.
perceive foreign musical structures after Imada, T., Zhang, Y., Cheour, M., Taulu, S.,
passive listening experience. Manuscript in Ahonen, A., & Kuhl, P. K. (2006). Infant speech
preparation. perception activates Broca’s area: A devel-
Hannon, E. E. (in press). Perceiving speech opmental magnetoencephalography study.
rhythm in music: Listeners categorize instru- Neuroreport, 17, 957–962.
mental songs according to language of origin. Iverson, P., Kuhl, P. K., Akahane-Yamada, R.,
Cognition. Diesch, E., Tohkura, Y., Kettermann, A., et
Hannon, E. E., & Johnson, S. P. (2005). Infants al. (2003). A perceptual interference account
use meter to categorize rhythms and melodies: of acquisition difficulties for non-native pho-
Implications for musical structure learning. nemes. Cognition, 87, B47–B57.
Cognitive Psychology, 50, 354–377. Ivry, R. B., & Hazeltine, R. E., (1995). Perception
Hannon, E. E., Snyder, J. S., Eerola, T., & and production of temporal intervals across
Krumhansl, C. L. (2004). The role of melodic a range of durations: Evidence for a common
and temporal cues in perceiving musical meter. timing mechanism. Journal of Experimental
Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Psychology: Human Perception and Performance,
Perception and Performance, 30, 956–974. 21, 3–18.
Hannon, E. E., & Trainor, L. J. (2007). Music Janata, P., Birk, J. L., Van Horn, J. D., Leman, M.,
acquisition: Effects of enculturation and formal Tillman, B., & Bharucha, J. J. (2002). The cor-
training on development. Trends in Cognitive tical topography of tonal structures underlying
Sciences, 11, 466–472. western music. Science, 298, 2167–2170.
152 WORDS, LANGUAGE, AND MUSIC

Janata, P., & Grafton, S. T. (2003). Swinging in Klapp, S. T., Hill, M. D., Tyler, J. G., Martin, Z.
the brain: Shared neural substrates for behav- E., Jagacinski, R. J., & Jones, M. R. (1985).
iors related to sequencing and music. Nature On marching to two different drummers:
Neuroscience, 6, 682–687. Perceptual aspects of the difficulties. Journal
Järvinen, T., & Toivianien, P. (2000). The effect of of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception
metre on the use of tones in jazz improvisation. and Performance, 11, 814–827.
Musicae Scientiae, 4, 55–74. Krampe, R., Kliegl, R., Mayr, R., Engbert, R.,
Jones, M. R., Johnston, H. J., & Puente, J. (2006). & Vorbert, D. (2000). The fast and the slow
Effects of auditory pattern structure on antici- of skilled bimanual rhythm production:
patory and reactive attending. Cognitive Parallel vs. integrated timing. Journal of
Psychology, 53, 59–96. Experimental Psychology: Human Perception
Jones, M. R., Moynihan, H., Mackenzie, N., & and Performance, 26, 206–233.
Puente, J. (2002). Temporal aspects of stim- Kuhl, P. K. (2004). Early language acquisition:
ulus-driven attending in dynamic arrays. Cracking the speech code. Nature Reviews
Psychological Science, 13, 313–319. Neuroscience, 5, 831–843.
Juslin, P. N., & Laukka, P. (2003). Communication Kuhl, P. K., Conboy, B. T., Padden, D., Nelson, T.,
of emotions in vocal expression and music & Pruitt, J. (2005). Early speech perception and
performance: Different channels, same code? later language development: Implications for
Psychological Bulletin, 129, 770–814. the “critical period.” Language Learning and
Jusczyk, P. W. (2002). How infants adapt speech- Development, 3–4, 237–264.
processing capacities to native-language Kuhl, P. K., Stevens, E., Hayashi, A, Deguchi, T.,
structure. Current Directions in Psychological Kiritani, S., & Iverson, P. (2006). Infants show
Science, 11, 15–18. a facilitation effect for native language pho-
Karmiloff-Smith, A. (1992). Beyond modularity: A netic perception between 6 and 12 months.
developmental perspective on cognitive science. Developmental Science, 9, F13–F21.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Kuhl, P. K., Tsao, F-M., & Liu, H-M. (2003).
Kelly, D. J., Quinn, P. C., Slater, A. M., Lee, K., Ge, L., Foreign-language experience in infancy:
& Pascalis, O. (2007). The other-race effect devel- Effects of short-term exposure and social inter-
ops during infancy: Evidence of perceptual nar- action on phonetic learning. Proceedings of
rowing. Psychological Science, 18, 1084–1089. the National Academy of Sciences (USA), 100,
Kilmer, A. D., Crocker, R. L., & Brown, R. R. 9096–9101.
(1985). Sounds from silence: Recent discoveries Kuhl, P. K., Williams, K. A., Lacerda, F., Stevens,
in ancient Near Eastern music. Berkeley, CA: K. N., & Lindblom, B. (1992). Linguistic experi-
Bit Enki Publications. ence alters phonetic perception in infants by 6
Kirkham, N. Z., Slemmer, J. A., & Johnson, S. P. months of age. Science, 255, 606–608.
(2002). Visual statistical learning in infancy: Krumhansl, C. L. (2004). The cognition of tonal-
Evidence for a domain general learning mech- ity: As we know it today. Journal of New Music
anism. Cognition, 83, B35–B42. Research, 33, 253–268.
Koelsch, S., Fritz, T., Cramon, Y., Müller, K., & Krumhansl, C. L., & Keil, F. C. (1982). Acquisition
Friederici, A. D. (2006). Investigating emo- of the hierarchy of tonal function in music.
tion with music: An fMRI study. Human Brain Memory & Cognition, 10, 243–251.
Mapping, 27, 239–250. Laje, R., & Mindlin, G. B. (2003). Highly struc-
Koelsch, S., Fritz, T., Schulze, K., Alsop, D., & ture duets in the song of the South American
Schlaug, G. (2005). Adults and children pro- Hornero. Physical Review Letters, 91, 1–4.
cessing music: An fMRI study. NeuroImage, Large, E. W. (2000). Rhythm categorization in con-
25, 1068–1076. text. In C. Woods, G. B. Luck, R. Brochard, S.
Koelsch, S., & Siebel, W. A. (2005). Towards a A. O’Neill, & J. A. Sloboda (Eds.), Proceedings
neural basis of music perception. Trends in of the 6th International Conference on Music
Cognitive Sciences, 9, 578–584. Perception and Cognition. Keele, Staffordshire,
Klapp, S. T. (1981). Temporal compatibility in dual UK: Department of Psychology.
motor tasks II: Simultaneous articulation and Large, E. W. (2001). Periodicity, pattern formation,
hand movements. Memory & Cognition, 9, and metric structure. Journal of New Music
398–401. Research, 30, 173–185.
MUSICAL ENCULTUR ATION 153

Large, E. W., Fink, P., & Kelso, J. A. (2002). Tracking McMurray, B., & Aslin, R. D. (2005). Infants are
simple and complex sequences. Psychological sensitive to within-category variation in speech
Research, 66, 3–17. perception. Cognition, 95, B15–B26.
Large, E. W., & Jones, M. R. (1999). The dynam- Mehler, J., Jusczyk, P. W., Lambertz, G., Halsted,
ics of attending: How we track time varying N., Bertoncini, J., & Amiel-Tison, C. (1988).
events. Psychological Review, 106, 119–159. A precursor of language acquisition in young
Lerdahl, F., & Jackendoff, R. (1983). A generative infants. Cognition, 29, 143–178.
theory of tonal music. Cambridge, MA: MIT Meegan, D. V., Aslin, R. N., & Jacobs, R. A. (2000).
Press. Motor timing learned without motor training.
Lewkowicz, D. (1996). Perception of auditory- Nature Neuroscience, 3, 860–862.
visual temporal synchrony in human infants. Meyer, L. B. (1973). Explaining music. Chicago:
Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human University of Chicago Press.
Perception and Performance, 22, 1094–1106. Miller, G. F. (2000). Evolution of human music
Liberman, A. M., & Mattingly, I. G. (1985). The through sexual selection. In N. L. Wallin,
motor theory of speech perception revised. B. Merker, & S. Brown (Eds.), The origins of music
Cognition, 21, 1–36. (pp. 329–360). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
London, J. (1995). Some examples of complex Minagawa-Kawai, Y., Mori, K., Naoi, N., & Kojima,
meters and their implications for models of S. (2007). Neural attunement processes in
metric perception. Music Perception, 13, 59–77. infants during the acquisition of a language-
London, J. (2004). Hearing in time: Psychological specific phonemic contrast. The Journal of
aspects of musical meter. New York: Oxford Neuroscience, 10, 315–321.
University Press. Moon, C., Cooper, R. P., & Fifer, W. P. (1993). Two-
Maess, B., Koelsch, S., Gunter, T. C., & Friederici, day-olds prefer their native language. Infant
A. D. (2001). Musical syntax is processed Behavior and Development, 16, 495–500.
in Broca’s area: An MEG study. Nature Nakata, T. & Mitani, C. (2005). Influences of tem-
Neuroscience, 4, 540–545. poral fluctuation on infant attention. Music
Marcus, G. F., Fernandes, K. J., & Johnson, S. Perception, 22, 401–409.
P. (2007). Infant rule learning facilitated by Narain, C., Scott, S. K., Wise, R. J. S., Rosen, S.,
speech. Psychological Science, 18, 387–391. Leff, A., Iversen, S. D., et al. (2003). Defining
Masataka, N. (2006). Preference for consonance a left-lateralized response specific to intelligi-
over dissonance by hearing newborns of deaf ble speech using fMRI. Cerebral Cortex, 13,
parents and of hearing parents. Developmental 1362–1368.
Science, 9: 46–50. Nazzi, T., Bertoncini, J., & Mehler, J. (1998).
Maye, J., Werker, J. F., & Gerken, L. (2002). Infant Language discrimination by newborns: Toward
sensitivity to distributional information can an understanding of the role of rhythm. Journal
affect phonetic discrimination. Cognition, 82, of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception
B101–B111. and Performance, 24, 756–766.
McAuley, D., Jones, M. R., Holub, S., Johnstone, H. Palmer, C., & Krumhansl, C. L. (1990). Mental
M., & Miller, N. S. (2006). The time of our lives: representations for musical meter. Journal of
Life span development of timing and event Experimental Psychology: Human Perception
tracking. Journal of Experimental Psychology: and Performance, 16, 728–741.
General, 135, 348–367. Palmer, C., & Pfordresher, P. Q. (2003). Incremental
McCandliss, B. D., Fiez, J. A., Protopapas, A., planning in sequence production. Psychological
Conway, M., & McClelland, J. L. (2002). Success Review, 110, 683–712.
and failure in teaching the [r]-[l] contrast to Pascalis, O., de Haan, M., & Nelson, C. A. (2002).
Japanese adults: Tests of a Hebbian model of Is face-processing species-specific during the
plasticity and stabilization in spoken language first year of life? Science, 296, 1321–1323.
perception. Cognitive, Affective, and Behavioral Pascalis, O., Scott, L. S., Kelly, D. J., Shannon,
Neuroscience, 2, 89–108. R. W., Nicholson, E., Coleman, M., et al.
McMullen, E., & Saff ran, J. R. (2004). Music and (2005). Plasticity of face processing in infancy.
language: A developmental comparison. Music Proceedings of the National Academy of
Perception, 21, 1–23. Sciences, USA, 102, 5297–5300.
154 WORDS, LANGUAGE, AND MUSIC

Patel, A. D., & Daniele, J. R. (2003). An empirical Povel, D. (1984). A theoretical framework for
comparison of rhythm in language and music. rhythm perception. Psychological Research, 45,
Cognition, 87, B35–B45. 315–337.
Patel, A. D., Foxton, J. M., & Griffiths, T. D. Powers, H. S., & Widdess, R. (2001). Theory and
(2005). Musically tone-deaf individuals have practice of classical music: Rhythm and tala.
difficulty discriminating intonation contours In S. Sadie & J. Tyrrell, (Eds.), The new Grove
extracted from speech. Brain and Cognition, dictionary of music and musicians (2nd ed., pp.
59, 310–333. 195–202). London: MacMillan.
Patel, A. D., Iversen, J. R., & Rosenberg, J. C. Ramus, F., Nespor, M., & Mehler, J. (1999).
(2006). Comparing the rhythm and melody of Correlates of linguistic rhythm in the speech
speech and music: The case of British English signal. Cognition, 73, 265–292.
and French. Journal of the Acoustical Society of Repp, B. H. (1992). Diversity and commonality
America, 119, 3034–3047. in music performance: An analysis of timing
Phillips-Silver, J. & Trainor, L. J. (2005). Feeling microstructure in Schumann’s “Träumerei”.
the beat: Movement influences infant rhythm Journal of the Acoustical Society of America,
perception. Science, 308, 1430. 92, 2546–3568.
Phillips-Silver, J., & Trainor, L. J. (2007). Hearing Repp, B. H., London, J., & Keller, P. E. (2005).
what the body feels: Auditory encoding Production and synchronization of uneven
of rhythmic movement. Cognition, 105, rhythms at fast tempi. Music Perception, 23,
533–546. 61–78.
Peper, C. E., Beek, P. J., van Wieringen, P. C. W. Rivera-Gaxiola, M., Csibra, G., Johnson, M.
(1995). Multifrequency coordination in H., & Karmiloff-Smith, A. (2000). Electro-
bimanual tapping: Asymmetrical coupling physiological correlates of cross-linguistic
and signs of supercriticality. Journal of speech perception in native English speakers.
Experimental Psychology: Human Perception Behavioral and Brain Research, 111, 11–23.
and Performance, 21, 1117–1138. Rivera-Gaxiola, M., Silva-Pereyra, J., & Kuhl, P.
Peretz, I. (Ed.). (2006). The nature of music [Special K. (2005). Brain potentials to native and non-
Issue]. Cognition, 100. native speech contrast in 7- and 11-month-old
Peretz, I., & Coltheart, M. (2003). Modularity American infants. Developmental Science, 8,
of music processing. Nature Neuroscience, 7, 162–172.
688–691. Sadakata, M., Desain, P., Honing, H., Patel, A. D., &
Peretz, I., & Hyde, K. L. (2003). What is specific Iversen, J. R. (2004). A cross-cultural study of the
to music processing? Insights from congeni- rhythm in English and Japanese popular music.
tal amusia. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7, Proceedings of the International Symposium on
362–367. Musical Acoustics (ISMA), 41–44. Nara.
Peretz, I., Kolinsky, R., Tramo, M., Labrecque, Saff ran, J. R., Aslin, R. N., & Newport, E. L. (1996).
R., Hublet, C., Demeurisse, G. et al. (1994). Statistical learning by 8-month-old infants.
Functional dissociations following bilat- Science, 274, 1926–1928.
eral lesions of auditory cortex. Brain, 117, Saff ran, J. R., Johnson, E. K., Aslin, R. N., &
1283–1301. Newport, E. L. (1999). Statistical learning of
Peretz, I., & Morais, J. (1989). Music and modular- tone sequences by human infants and adults.
ity. Contemporary Music Review, 4, 277–291. Cognition, 70, 27–52.
Pinker, S. (1997). How the mind works. New York: Saff ran, J. R., Pollak, S. D., Seibel, R. L., & Shkolnik,
Norton. A. (2006). Dog is a dog is a dog: Infant rule
Pinker, S. (2002). The blank slate: The modern learning is not specific to language. Cognition,
denial of human nature. New York: Penguin. 105, 669–680.
Platel, H., Price, C., Baron, J., Wise, R., Lambert, J., Sakai, K., Hikosaka, O., Miyauchi, S., Takino, R.,
Frackowiak, R. S. J., et al. (1997). The structural Tamada, T., Iwata, N., et al. (1999). Neural rep-
components of music perception: A functional resentation of a rhythm depends on its inter-
anatomical study. Brain, 120, 229–243. val ratio. The Journal of Neuroscience, 15,
Povel, D. (1981). Internal representation of sim- 10074–10081.
ple temporal patterns. Journal of Experimental Schellenberg, E. G. (2005). Children’s implicit
Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, knowledge of harmony in Western music.
7, 3–18. Developmental Science, 8, 551–566.
MUSICAL ENCULTUR ATION 155

Schellenberg, E. G., & Trainor, L. J. (1996). Sensory of rhythm. Empirical Musicology Review, 2,
consonance and the perceptual similarity of 1–13.
complex-tone harmonic intervals: Tests of adult Trainor, L. J., & Heinmiller, B. M. (1998). The
and infant listeners. Journal of the Acoustical development of evaluative responses to music:
Society of America, 100, 3321–3328. Infants prefer to listen to consonance over dis-
Schellenberg, E. G. & Trehub, S. E. (1994). sonance. Infant Behavior and Development, 21,
Frequency ratios and the discrimination of pure 77–88.
tone sequences. Perception & Psychophysics, Trainor, L. J. & Trehub, S. E. (1992). A com-
56, 472–478. parison of infants’ and adults’ sensitivity
Schellenberg, E. G., & Trehub, S. E. (1996). Natural to Western musical structure. Journal of
musical intervals: Evidence from infant listen- Experimental Psychology: Human Perception
ers. Psychological Science, 7, 272–277. and Performance, 18, 394–402.
Schubotz, R. I., Friederici, A. D., & Yves von Trainor, L. J., Tsang, C. D., & Cheung, V. H. W.
Cramon, D. (2000). Time perception and motor (2002). Preference for sensory consonance in
timing: A common cortical and subcortical 2- and 4-month-old infants. Music Perception,
basis revealed by fMRI. NeuroImage, 11, 1–12. 20, 187–194.
Scott, L. S., Pascalis, O., & Nelson, C. A. (2007). A Tramo, M. J., Cariani, P. A., Koh, C. K., Makris,
domain-general theory of the development of N., & Braida, L. D. (2003). Neurobiology of har-
perceptual discrimination. Current Directions mony perception. In I. Peretz and Zatorre, R.J.
in Psychological Science, 16, 197–201. (Eds.), The cognitive neurosciences of music (pp.
Scott, L. S., Shannon, R. W., & Nelson, C. A. (2006). 121–151). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Neural correlates of human and monkey face Treff ner, P. J., & Turvey, M. T. (1993). Resonance
processing by 9-month-old infants. Infancy, 10, constraints on rhythmic movement. Journal of
171–186. Experimental Psychology: Human Perception
Semjen, A., & Ivry, R. B. (2001). The couled oscil- and Performance, 19, 1221–1237.
lator model of between-hand coordination in Trehub, S. E. (1976). The discrimination of foreign
alternate-hand tapping: A reappraisal. Journal speech contrasts by infants and adults. Child
of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception Development, 47, 466–472.
and Performance, 27, 251–265. Trehub, S. E. (2003). The developmental origins of
Snyder, J. S., Hannon, E. E., Large, E. W., & musicality. Nature Neuroscience, 6, 669–673.
Christiansen, M. H. (2006). Synchronization Trehub, S. E., & Hannon, E. E. (2006). Infant
and continuation tapping to complex meters. music perception: Domain-general or domain-
Music Perception, 24, 135–146. specific mechanisms? Cognition, 100, 73–99.
Snyder, J. S., & Krumhansl, C. L. (2001). Tapping Trehub, S. E., & Hannon, E. E. (2009).
to ragtime: Cues to pulse-fi nding. Music Conventional rhythms enhance infants’ and
Perception, 18, 445–489. adults’ perception of musical patterns. Cortex,
Soley, G. & Hannon, E.E. Infants prefer music of 45, 110–118.
their own culture: A cross-cultural compari- Trehub, S. E., & Trainor, L. J. (1998). Singing to
son. Manuscript submitted for publication. infants: Lullabies and play songs. Advances in
Spiro, J. (Ed.). (2003). Music and the brain [Special Infancy Research, 12, 43–77.
Issue]. Nature Neuroscience, 6. Tsao, F.-M., Liu, H.-M., & Kuhl, P. K. (2004).
Summers, J. (2001). Practice and training in Speech perception in infancy predicts
bimanual coordination tasks: Strategies and language development in the second year of
constraints. Brain and Cognition, 48, 1–13. life: A longitudinal study. Child Development,
Thiessen, E. D., & Saff ran, J. R. (2007). Learning 75, 1067.
to learn: Infants’ acquisition of stress-based Vignolo, L. A. (2003). Music agnosia and auditory
strategies for word segmentation. Language agnosia. Annals of the New York Academy of
Learning and Development, 3, 73–100. Sciences, 999, 50–57.
Tillman, B. A., Bharucha, J. J., & Bigand, E. (2000). Vouloumanos, A., Kiehl, K. A., Werker, J. F., &
Implicit learning of tonality: A self-organized Liddle, P. F. (2001). Detection of sounds in the
approach. Psychological Review, 107, 885–913. auditory stream: Event-related fMRI evidence
Todd, N. P. M., Cousins, R., & Lee, C. S. (2007). for differential activation to speech and non-
The contribution of anthropometric factors speech. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 13,
to individual differences in the perception 994–1005.
156 WORDS, LANGUAGE, AND MUSIC

Vouloumanos, A., & Werker, J. F. (2004). Tuned Werker, J. F. & Lalonde, C. E. (1995). Cognitive
to the signal: The privileged status of speech influences on cross-language speech perception
for young infants. Developmental Science, 7, in infancy. Infant Behavior and Development,
270–276. 18, 459–475.
Wallin, N. L., Merker, B., & Brown, S. (2000). The Werker, J. F., & Tees, R. C. (1984). Cross-language
origins of music. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. speech perception: Evidence for perceptual
Watanabe, S., Uozumi, M., & Tanaka, N. (2005). reorganization during the first year of life.
Discrimination of consonance and dissonance Infant Behavior and Development, 7, 49–63.
in Java sparrows. Behavioural Processes, 70, Zanone, P. G., & Kelso, J. A. S. (1992). Evolution
203–208. of behavioral attractors with learning:
Weikum, W. M., Vouloumanos, A., Navarra, Nonequilibrium phase transitions. Journal of
J., Soto-Faraco, S., Sebastian-Galles, N., & Experimental Psychology: Human Perception
Werker, J. F. (2007). Visual language discrim- and Performance, 18, 403–421.
ination in infancy. Science, 316, 1159. Zatorre, R. J., & Peretz, I. (Eds.). (2003). The neu-
Werker, J. F., & Lalonde, C. E. (1988). Cross- rosciences and music. New York: The New York
language speech perception: Initial capabili- Academy of Sciences.
ties and developmental change. Developmental Zentner, M. R., & Kagan, J. (1996). Perception of
Psychology, 24, 672–683. music by infants. Nature, 383, 29.
PART III

Learning Mechanisms
This page intentionally left blank
CHAP TER 8
Integrating Top-down and Bottom-up Approaches
to Children’s Causal Inference

David M. Sobel

Several chapters in this volume are dedicated information. One might consider this tradi-
to describing how children learn conceptual tion more “top-down.” The second goal of this
structure from the data available to them (e.g., chapter is to consider how to integrate these two
Kirkham, this volume; Rakison & Cicchino, approaches for describing children’s causal rea-
this volume; Sloutsky, this volume). My plan for soning abilities.
this chapter is to focus this discussion on a par- In particular, following a set of propos-
ticular piece of conceptual knowledge: under- als developed by Josh Tenenbaum and Tom
standing the causal relations among events. Griffiths (Griffiths & Tenenbaum, 2005, 2007;
Piaget, on whom the constructivist approach to Sobel, Tenenbaum, & Gopnik, 2004; Tenenbaum
cognitive development is based, recognized the & Griffiths, 2001, 2003), I will suggest a
importance of causality in children’s cognitive description of children’s causal inference. This
development (Piaget, 1929, 1930). However, he approach offers a way of considering how causal
failed to attribute significant causal reasoning principles are acquired from data to learn rep-
abilities to young children, with preoperational resentations of causal structure. I will first pres-
children often receiving the label “precausal” ent some background information, then some
based on their verbal explanations of behaviors empirical work consistent with this description
in the world. The first goal of this chapter is to as well as what might be developing. Finally, I
highlight young children’s sophisticated causal will consider some limitations of this mecha-
reasoning abilities. nism, focusing on other information that might
There are two approaches to causal learn- be available to the child to facilitate their causal
ing that are critical to the present discussion inference and learning.
in this volume. First, there is a long tradition
of research in causal learning and inference
CAUSALLEARNING FROM “BOTTOM- UP”
that has focused on how causal knowledge is
MECHANISMS
acquired from observing events—algorithms
that construct a mental model of causal knowl- There have been numerous accounts of causal
edge from patterns of correlational informa- learning in which a representation of causal
tion. One might consider such a tradition more structure is built from observing data in the
“bottom-up.” But there is a second tradition environment. On these accounts, children use
of research in cognitive development—dating little prior knowledge to learn about causal rela-
back to Piaget—describing how children using tions. Often, they only have the ability to trans-
their prior knowledge or contextual informa- late associations among events into a causal
tion in the environment to learn new causal representation. The simplest such account is

159
160 LEARNING MECHANISMS

that children associate causes and effects in the information. The critical difference between
same way that animals associate conditioned these models and the ones mentioned above is
and unconditioned stimuli in classical con- that they estimate the strength of a fi xed rep-
ditioning (e.g., Mackintosh, 1975; Rescorla & resentation of causal structure, and do so accu-
Wagner, 1972). rately only given sufficiently large quantities
But since associative models only output of data (see Tenenbaum & Griffiths, 2001, for
strength relations, they do not appear to make further discussion of this issue). Most of these
predictions about how learners use causal models, however, are agnostic as to how that
knowledge to generate interventions to elicit causal structure is fi xed, with a potential excep-
effects. It appears that even rats are capable of tion being the Power PC model (Cheng, 1997;
causal reasoning in a manner that reflects more Novick & Cheng, 2004), which suggests ways of
than just an associative mechanism (Blaisdell, discerning cause from effect (see e.g., Cheng &
Sawa, Leising, & Waldmann, 2006). As a result, Novick, 1990).
several independent research programs have
suggested that to generalize an associative
CAUSAL STRUCTURE LEARNING
approach, causal learning occurs by transform-
ing a measure of associative strength into a The models described above focus on deriving
measure of causal strength. Measures of causal the strength of a set of known causal relations.
strength are then used to make inferences or Informally, here is the first way in which tradi-
generate interventions. Some of these models tionally bottom-up accounts of causal learning
were based on the Rescorla-Wagner equation can be integrated with prior knowledge: If the
(see e.g., Cramer et al., 2002). Other accounts learner is determining the strength of a known
emerged as researchers discovered a set of cause and effect, then there must be some knowl-
learning paradigms that this model has trouble edge in addition to the data that identifies cause
explaining (e.g., Krushke & Blair, 2000; Van from effect. While there are several theories of
Hamme & Wasserman, 1994; Wasserman & causal inference that place such mechanistic
Berglan, 1998). One advantage of these accounts information central to understanding causality
is that they allow a way to describe how a learner (Ahn, Kalish, Medin, & Gelman, 1995; Shultz,
might generate interventions on the world— 1982), such knowledge might also be entirely
actions (usually intentional) that change the minimal, perhaps limited to only priority, con-
value of an event exogenously (without affecting tiguity, and contingency (e.g., Hume, 1978/1739;
other variables in the model directly). To use a Michotte, 1962).
traditional example, some associative mecha- However, there are some contemporary
nisms were designed to describe classical condi- accounts of causal learning that consider
tional paradigms, in which the learner passively how causal structure is learned: How do chil-
observed the environment. These accounts of dren (and adults) recognize that an event is
human learning also take operant paradigms a cause or effect of another event (in addition
into account, in which the learner also gener- to considering the strength of that causal rela-
ates actions, which have varying degrees of effi- tion)? Most of the psychological investigation
cacy, and must learn the strength of the existing on this approach has concentrated on adult
causal relation (see e.g., Dickinson & Shanks, causal learning (Griffiths & Tenenbaum, 2005;
1995, for a detailed discussion). Lagnado & Sloman, 2004; Steyvers, Tenenbaum,
Still other endeavors have considered more Wagenmakers, & Blum, 2003; Tenenbaum &
complex relations among events beyond stimu- Griffiths, 2001; Waldmann & Hagmayer, 2005;
lus, response, and reinforcement (e.g., Allan, see Lagnado, Waldmann, Hagmayer, & Sloman,
1980; Cheng, 1997; Shanks, 1995). These mod- 2007, for a review). There are also investigations
els estimate the strength of a particular causal that suggest that children construct an abstract
model using the probability that an effect representation of the causal structure among
occurs given a cause and some background a set of variables (Gopnik, Sobel, Schulz, &
INTEGR ATING TOP-DOWN AND BOTTOM-UP APPROACHES 161

Glymour, 2001; Schulz & Gopnik, 2004; Sobel, example, if I make the rooster to crow at 2 am,
Tenenbaum, & Gopnik, 2004; see Gopnik et al., I should not expect the sun to rise; the causal
2004, for a review). relation between sunrises and roosters crowing
This description of causal learning and runs in the opposite direction (see Woodward,
inference has been grounded in the literature on 2003, for further discussion). Children clearly
causal graphical models, which have been devel- learn causal structure from observing (and gen-
oped in computer science and statistics (Pearl, erating) these interventions (see e.g., Schulz,
2000; Spirtes, Glymour, & Scheines, 2001). Gopnik & Glymour, 2007).
Causal graphical models are representations of A second assumption that underlies causal
a joint probability distribution: the probability graphical models is the faithfulness assumption.
that each possible combination of events occurs. Faithfulness specifies that data are indicative of
These representations embody conditional the causal structure in the world. Suppose that
probability information among events. Events three events are related in the following manner:
are represented as nodes, and causal relations X→Y←Z and that X has a generative relation with
are represented as edges between nodes. Y (i.e., the occurrence of X raises the probability
Making inferences from this account relies that Y will occur) and that Z has a preventative
on a set of assumptions. One assumption is relation with Y (i.e., the occurrence of Z lowers
that any vertex represents a causal relation the probability that Y will occur). Faithfulness
between two nodes, specifically in the form of states that the causal relations among X, Y, and
a mechanism that can be either observed or Z will never be such that X and Z exactly cancel
unobserved (following Pearl, 2000). As such, each other’s effects on Y, so that the three events
any graph is consistent with a set of probabilis- appear independent. I do not know of a psycho-
tic models that specify the nature of the relation logical investigation dedicated to faithfulness;
among the variables. A unique causal structure however, most psychologists investigating chil-
is formed by defining the probability distribu- dren’s causal learning assume this to be true.
tion for each variable conditioned on its parents A third assumption is the Markov assump-
(called parameterizing a graph). Parameterizing tion, which is a way of translating between
a graph can be thought of as assigning weights causal relations and conditional probability
to each edge that represent the strength of information (Pearl, 2000). The Markov assump-
the corresponding causal relations. A graph’s tion states that the value of an event (i.e., a node
parameterization can reflect the nature of the in the graph) is independent of all other events
mechanism(s) by which causes produce effects. except its children (i.e., its direct effects) condi-
Causal graphical models support reasoning tional on its parents (i.e., its direct causes). For
about interventions—actions that change the example, consider the causal model A→B→C.
value of variables in the graph (without directly In this model, the values of events A and C are
influencing those other variables, see Pearl, dependent. The Markov assumption states that
2000). Consider the simple graph X→Y. In this these values become independent conditional
graph, the probability that event Y takes a par- on the value of event B. C has no children, and
ticular value given that event X takes a particu- B is its only parent. If you want to predict the
lar value is the same when you observe that X value of C and know the value of B, additional
has that value as when you act to make X have knowledge about the value of A does not help:
that value. Such interventions are represented the only influence that A has on C is through B.
by Pearl (2000) and others as the do(X) operator. In the next section, I will consider evidence
Note that the opposite is not true in this graph: that suggests children engage in causal reason-
The probability that X has a particular value ing in a manner consistent with the Markov
given that you observe Y has a particular value is assumption. Specifically, this evidence suggests
not necessarily the same as the probability that that young children can recognize dependen-
X has that value given that you force Y to take cies among events as well as when events are
on the same value. To use a classic philosophical independent based on the presence of a third
162 LEARNING MECHANISMS

event. Such inference is tantamount to recog-


nizing the difference between correlations due
to causal relations and correlations due to spuri-
ous associations.

LEARNING CAUSAL STRUCTURE USING


STRUCTURE LEARNING: DATA FROM
YOUNG CHILDREN

In order to investigate whether children rec-


ognize the difference between dependence and
conditional independence information, we need
Figure 8.1 A blicket detector (specifically the
a method that presents a novel causal property
detector used in Gopnik and Sobel, 2000, and
to children wherein researchers can control the elsewhere). In this case, an object is placed on
amount of prior knowledge they possess. Much the detector, and it is enabled, so that the object
of the research I will describe uses a blicket is activating the detector. This particular detec-
detector (shown in Figure 8.1), a machine that tor lights up red and plays fur elise.
lights up and plays music (controlled by the
experimenter) when certain objects are placed
upon it. The blicket detector presents a novel, times, and activated two out of three times.
nonobvious causal property, which any object Children categorized both objects as blickets.
might possess. Both objects individually activated the detector;
Gopnik et al. (2001) trained 3- and 4-year- they just did so with different frequencies.
olds that objects that activated the detector were These data suggest that children recognize
labeled, “blickets.” Children quickly learned this the difference between two events that are
relation. Then, children observed a set of trials dependent because of a causal relation and two
in which objects either independently activated events that are dependent because of the pres-
the machine, or did so only in the presence of ence of a third (causal) event.1 This procedure
another object. Specifically, on the one-cause tri- generalizes beyond reasoning about physical
als, children were shown two objects. Children events: Schulz and Gopnik (2004) demonstrated
observed one object (A) activate the detector by that 3- and 4-year-olds make similar inferences
itself. Then, they saw that the other object (B) across a variety of domains. Using some slight
did not activate the detector by itself. Finally, manipulations to the procedure, Gopnik et al.
they saw objects A and B activate the detector (2001) demonstrated that 30-month-olds also
twice together. Children were asked whether made these inferences.
each object was a blicket. Three- and 4-year-olds The trouble with simply concluding that chil-
labeled only object A as a blicket (although this dren reason according to the Markov assumption
was more likely for the older children), recogniz- is that the data presented above are analogous to
ing that object B only activated the detector in blocking, a phenomenon from the animal condi-
the presence of the object A. tioning literature (Kamin, 1969). In a blocking
Performance on these trials were compared
with performance on two-cause trials, in which 1
Th is kind of inference has often been called “explain-
the same children were shown two objects that ing away.” It is consistent with the Markov assumption,
activated the detector individually with the but is a different inference from the example provided
in the previous section (in which an individual reasons
same frequency as the objects in the one-cause about a causal chain). There is evidence that under some
trials. Specifically, children saw two new objects conditions, children can learn causal chains from these
(C and D). Object C was placed on the machine patterns of data (Sobel & Sommerville, 2009), but most
of the evidence suggesting children reason accord-
three times and activated it all three times. ing to the Markov assumption asks them to make this
Object D was placed on the machine three “explaining away” inference.
INTEGR ATING TOP-DOWN AND BOTTOM-UP APPROACHES 163

procedure, a learner is shown an association consistent with it being a blicket and not being
between a conditioned and unconditioned stim- one. However, these intuitions differ from the
ulus (e.g., that a tone predicts the occurrence of associative relations that objects B and D have
food). This association is trained until asymp- with the machine’s activation. In both cases,
tote, and then the learner is shown a novel stim- children observe the object activate the machine
ulus, which presented in compound with the in conjunction with another object. That other
established conditioned stimulus will predict object (A or C) then activates or fails to acti-
the same unconditioned stimulus (e.g., that the vate the machine, but this piece of informa-
same tone paired with light will predict food). In tion should not change the associative relation
most cases, learners do not learn that the second between objects B and D and the machine’s acti-
stimulus is predictive. Various models of asso- vation. If children were responding on the basis
ciative reasoning (e.g., Rescorla & Wagner, 1972) of these associative calculations, they should
were designed to explain this phenomenon. In treat these objects the same. Three- and 4-year-
the blicket detector paradigm described above, olds responded in a manner consistent with the
one might consider object A to be analogous to intuitions, not the associative relations: object B
the first stimulus, object B the second stimulus, was almost always judged to be a blicket, while
and the detector’s activation the unconditioned object D was judged to be so approximately 35%
stimulus. Children’s performance, thus, is analo- of the time. Preschoolers reasoned in a man-
gous to that of animal learners. ner consistent with the Markov assumption,
It is necessary to consider alternate proce- and less consistent with at least some models of
dures that models of associative reasoning have causal reasoning based on calculations of asso-
difficulty explaining. One such example involves ciative strength (e.g., Rescorla & Wagner, 1972).
considering how children reason retrospectively
about ambiguous events (following Shanks,
AN ASIDE: DATA FROM INFANTS
1985, 1995). Sobel et al. (2004) introduced 3- and
4-year-olds to the blicket machine in the same An open question raised by the previous sec-
manner as Gopnik et al. (2001), and then pre- tion is whether younger children would reason
sented them with two types of trials. In their one- in a similar manner. A variety of researchers
cause trials, children saw that two objects (A and have suggested that children’s causal reason-
B) activated the machine together, and then that ing abilities develop during the preschool years
object A did not activate the machine by itself. (e.g., Bullock, Gelman, & Baillargeon, 1982; Das
In their backwards blocking trials, children saw Gupta & Bryant, 1989; Goswami & Brown, 1990;
two new objects (C and D) activate the machine Gottfried & Gelman, 2005). Further, children’s
together, and then that one of those objects (C) ability to relate causal inferences to perceptions
did activate the machine by itself (note that this of time develops after the preschool years (e.g.,
procedure is analogous to the reverse of Kamin’s McCormack & Hoerl, 2005).
blocking procedure described above, hence its But these findings are mostly concerned with
name). Children were asked whether each of how children understand causal mechanisms—
these objects were blickets. how events are related to each other in a causal
The blicket status of objects A and C are manner. In subsequent sections, I will outline a
unambiguous given these data, but one’s intu- description of a domain-general causal learning
itions about objects B and D should differ. Object mechanism, and then demonstrate how domain-
B should be a blicket in the one-cause trial; this specific knowledge influences children’s use of
is consistent with the Markov assumption: this mechanism. But before we consider those
object A only activates the machine dependent ideas, the issue of whether younger children’s
on the presence of object B, so object B must be causal reasoning is consistent with the Markov
the causal factor. Object D’s status is uncertain; assumption is still open.
the data (under a few assumptions, which I will Sobel and Kirkham (2006) considered this
make clear in subsequent sections) are equally question by investigating 19- and 24-month-olds’
164 LEARNING MECHANISMS

inferences using a similar procedure to the auditory streams based on statistical probabil-
one-cause and backwards blocking trials ities even when the stimuli are tones (Saff ran,
described above. In their one-cause condition, Johnson, Aslin, & Newport, 1999). This suggests
they placed two objects (A and B) on the machine that the ability to perceive statistical structure is
together, which activated, and then showed perhaps not language-specific.
the children that object A failed to activate the Further evidence for this position comes
machine by itself. The objects and detector were from work on infants’ parsing of visuospatial
slid over to the child, who was asked to “make it sequences of events. Using a procedure analo-
go.” In their backwards blocking condition, they gous to Saff ran et al. (1996), Kirkham, Slemmer,
placed three objects on the table (C, D, and E). and Johnson (2002) demonstrated that infants
Objects C and D made the machine go together, as young as 2 months old register statistical
and then object C made the machine go by itself. relations among sequences of visual events (see
Object C was removed, and the child was given Kirkham, this volume, for a detailed descrip-
objects D and E with the detector to “make it tion of this literature). Similarly, Fiser and Aslin
go.” Twenty-four-month-olds used object B to (2002) demonstrated that 9-month-olds can rec-
activate the machine in the one-cause trial, more ognize conditional probability relations between
often than they used object D to do so in the the spatial positions of visual events. Both of
backwards blocking trial. However, the younger these projects have their origins with work by
children responded at chance levels, and did not Haith and colleagues (Haith, 1993; Wentworth,
discriminate between objects B and D. Haith, & Hood, 2002), who demonstrated that
A difficulty with asking children this young young infants (3–4-month-olds) learn simple,
to make manual responses consistent with their two-location spatial sequences of events. Haith
causal knowledge (i.e., put objects on the detec- and colleagues used a visual expectation para-
tor to make it go), is that there are cases in which digm, in which infants’ eye gaze to a particular
18-month-olds fail to engage in simple imitative spatial location represented where the infants
“means–ends” behaviors (e.g., Uzgiris & Hunt, thought an event would appear.
1975; see also Gopnik & Meltzoff, 1992). In the Sobel and Kirkham (2006) modified this tech-
one-cause trial, children had to inhibit an event nique to investigate whether infants reasoned
they observed activate the machine (placing about sequences of events in a manner similar
both objects on it) in favor of a novel interven- to preschoolers’ causal inference. Eight-month-
tion (placing only object B on it). The demand olds were shown a video screen similar to what
characteristics of this experiment might have is seen in Figure 8.2. Four frames were always
overwhelmed the toddlers, and prevented them
from producing the appropriate responses.
There is reason to believe that 18-month-
olds, and even younger infants, have the abil-
ity to detect conditional probabilities among
events. Saff ran, Aslin, and colleagues found that
8-month-old infants could parse a stream of
auditory stimuli based solely on the transitional
probabilities within and between syllables (i.e.,
the likelihood that one syllable would predict
the next syllable; Aslin, Saffran, & Newport,
1998; Saff ran, Aslin, & Newport, 1996). Infants’
statistical learning abilities extend beyond
learning word boundaries. Infants are capa-
ble of recognizing and discriminating between Figure 8.2 A screenshot shown to infants in
complex grammars relating words together Sobel and Kirkham (2006, 2007). In this shot,
(e.g., Gomez & Gerken, 1999). They also parse events A and B are presented together.
INTEGR ATING TOP-DOWN AND BOTTOM-UP APPROACHES 165

present on the screen. I will refer to the top cen- by itself, followed by the D event. This sequence
ter frame as A and the bottom center frame as was shown twice. Infants in the backwards block-
B, the right frame as C and the left frame as D, ing condition observe only the A event followed
but this was counterbalanced in the experiment. by the C event (twice). Immediately after this,
Infants observed sequences of events appear in infants were shown the B event, and then the
their respective frames. During familiarization, screen went blank. The music that had accompa-
infants saw a sequence of three types of events nied the C and D events began to play, and at this
(the first event was randomly chosen from the point infants’ eye gaze was measured for 8 s.
three). One was that the A and B events could One might think of this sequence of events
appear in their respective frames together. These in a manner similar to objects being placed on
were two grayscale events that silently rotated in a blicket detector. Events A and B correspond
space for 8 s. The AB compound predicted the to the two objects being placed on the detector,
occurrence of the C event (which occurred in and events C and D correspond to the detector
the C frame) with 100% certainty. The C event activating or not, respectively. In the indirect
was a more interesting color event, which moved screening-off condition (analogous to the one-
around in the frame and was accompanied by cause condition in the previous experiments
a piece of cartoonish music. It also lasted for described above), events A and B together pre-
8 s. The C event, however, did not predict any dict C, and then A alone does not. Events A
event. Half of the time it was followed by the AB and C are dependent in the presence of B, but
compound (in which case, the subsequent event independent, conditioned on the absence of B;
would again be C), and half of the time it was fol- this makes B predictive of C. The expectation
lowed by the D event, which was the same color is that infants will look more to the C frame,
event occurring in the D frame for 8 s accom- expecting an event to appear there. In the back-
panied by the same music. The D event also did wards blocking condition, the associative rela-
not predict anything. Half of the time it was fol- tion between events B and C is the same as in
lowed by the AB compound, and half of the time the indirect screening-off condition, but since A
it was followed by C. and C are not independent, conditioned on the
Infants observed this sequence of events until absence of B, B is not necessarily predictive of C.
they saw four occurrences of the AB→C pair- We would expect to find an interaction between
ing (usually 11 events total). Immediately after the amount of time spent looking at each frame
the last AB→C pairing, infants who had been and the condition the infant was assigned to.
assigned to the indirect screening-off condition This was exactly what was found (see Figure
observed only the A event appear on the screen 8.3). Eight-month-olds spent more time looking

Mean looking times to the frames

5-month-olds 8-month-olds
(Sobel & Kirkham, 2007) (Sobel & Kirkham, 2006)
800
700 C
600 D
Time (ms)

500
400 Figure 8.3 Amount of time
300 spent looking to the C and D
200 frames in the indirect
100
screening-off and back-
0
Backwards Indirect Backwards Indirecting wards blocking conditions
blocking screening- blocking screening- by 8-month-olds (Sobel &
off off Kirkham, 2006) and 5-month-
Condition olds (Sobel & Kirkham, 2007).
166 LEARNING MECHANISMS

in the C frame in the indirect screening-off Natasha Kirkham and I have begun several
condition than the D frame, and more time investigations focused on this question. One
looking in the D frame than the C frame in the involves infants watching videos of objects
backwards blocking condition. Moreover, they placed on a blicket detector, consistent with the
spent more time looking in the C frame in the data shown in the one-cause and backwards
indirect screening-off condition than back- blocking conditions described above. Using a
wards blocking condition. violation-of-expectation procedure, we should
These data suggest that infants’ statistical be able to discern infants’ expectations about
learning abilities appear to be consistent with the causal efficacy of individual objects. Further,
the Markov assumption. However, this infer- using the anticipatory eye-gaze paradigm, we
ential ability may not be available to younger are attempting to train children that looks to
infants. In a follow-up, Sobel and Kirkham particular locations of a screen actually cause
(2007) found that 5-month-olds’ pattern of look- events to occur. Using eye gaze to allow infants
ing time in response to the same procedure was to generate interventions might allow them to
quite different (see Figure 8.3). Five-month-olds respond in a causal manner to sequences simi-
looked longer at the C frame in the backwards lar to the one used in our previous work. These
blocking condition, and equally long at the two investigations are currently underway.
frames in the indirect screening-off condition,
inconsistent with the Markov assumption. One
BAYESIAN INFERENCE AS A DESCRIPTION
interpretation of these data is that infants might
OF CAUSAL STRUCTURE LEARNING
be developing a mechanism for causal and sta-
tistical reasoning that moves from recognizing An objection that one might have to the lines of
associations among events to one that incor- research described above is that the difference
porates the Markov assumption. However, the between responses in the indirect screening-
5-month-olds’ responses were inconsistent with off or one-cause condition and responses in
an associative mechanism as well. An alterna- the backwards blocking condition is problem-
tive interpretation is that when events A and atic for certain models of associative reasoning
B occur together, younger infants might sim- (e.g., Rescorla & Wagner, 1972), but not others.
ply treat them as the same event. If infants are Several contemporary accounts of associative
treating event A alone, event B alone, and the reasoning were designed with the backwards
AB compound as the same event, then their blocking paradigm in mind (e.g., Kruschke &
pattern of performance is consistent with both Blair, 2000; Van Hamme & Wasserman, 1994;
associative reasoning mechanisms and reason- Wasserman & Berglan, 1998). For instance,
ing mechanisms consistent with the Markov Wasserman and Berglan (1998) use a derivative
assumption. More research is necessary to dis- of the Rescorla-Wagner equation, in which the
criminate between these possibilities. strength of a relation changes positively when a
Second, the research on infancy presented potential cause and effect occur and negatively
so far has focused on infants’ statistical reason- when the effect occurs without a potential cause.
ing, and not necessarily their understanding of Similarly, models of causal reasoning that rely
cause and effect. These data do not demonstrate on the estimation of causal parameters based
that 8-month-olds register that event B causes on the frequency with which events co-occur
event C in the indirect screening-off condition. also explain the backwards blocking data (e.g.,
Rather, they suggest that infants’ statistical rea- Cheng, 1997; Shanks, 1995). These models cate-
soning is consistent with the Markov assump- gorize events as causes or effects and then cal-
tion, and may form the building block for a culate the probability that an effect occurs given
representation of causal knowledge. An open a cause and some background information.
question is to consider how to convert this pro- For example, Cheng’s (1997) Power PC model
cedure to one in which infants’ causal reasoning makes a clear prediction about the causal effi-
can be measured. cacy of the objects in the one-cause conditions,
INTEGR ATING TOP-DOWN AND BOTTOM-UP APPROACHES 167

but generates an undefined value in the back- of B, then the p(d | h) = 0 for this particular
wards blocking case, which can be interpreted hypothesis. This hypothesis requires B to occur
as consistent with the present findings. whenever A occurs, and that is not the case.
Is there a method of distinguishing among To see this computational description
all of these competing options as explanations in action, consider the backwards blocking
of children’s causal reasoning? One difficulty sequences in which two objects activate the
with considering the majority of these algo- blicket detector together and then one of those
rithms is that they rely on multiple pieces of two objects activates the detector by itself. There
data (i.e., large sample sizes) in order to make are four hypotheses potentially consistent with
rational inferences. What we have observed in these data:
children’s causal reasoning is that they appear
h1: that neither object is a blicket
capable of making such inferences based on
h2: that only the first is a blicket
small amounts of data. Following research-
h3: that only the second is a blicket
ers in adult cognition and cognitive science
h4: that both are blickets
(e.g., Griffiths & Tenenbaum, 2005; Steyvers
et al., 2003; Tenenbaum & Griffiths, 2001, 2003), The data are equally inconsistent with hypoth-
Sobel et al. (2004, see also Griffiths, Sobel, eses h1 and h3 (i.e., p(d | h) = 0), since the first
Tenenbaum, & Gopnik, submitted) proposed object has to be a blicket (it activates the machine
that children’s causal learning and inference by itself, but more on this in the subsequent sec-
was better described by a model that relies on tions). The data, however, are equally consistent
Bayesian inference. with the other two hypotheses (h2 and h4), and
On this view, causal reasoning can best be as such the p(d | h) = 1 for both. But this descrip-
described by inference over a set of hypotheses tion allows for another piece of information to
(H). Hypotheses take the form of a causal graph- influence causal inference, namely the prior
ical model with a particular parameterization. probabilities, and these priors might affect chil-
Each hypothesis (h1, h2 , . . . hn) is assigned a prior dren’s inferences.
probability, p(h) before observing any data. A rational way in which these priors might
These priors reflect the learner’s causal knowl- be assigned is through observing the base rate
edge about possible causal structures as well as of objects with causal efficacy—the frequency of
any other information the learner gleams from blickets in the world. If there are few blickets in
the environment before observing the data. the world, then the prior probability of hypoth-
Given the data, d (values for the variables in the esis h2 should be higher than that of h4, since
hypotheses), the learner computes the posterior h2 posits fewer blickets. Similarly, if blickets are
probability that each hypothesis is the actual relatively common, then the reverse should be
causal structure of the system, p(h | d). This is true. Using this logic, Sobel et al. (2004) pre-
done using Bayes’ rule: sented 3- and 4-year-olds with a version of the
backwards blocking procedure in which they
p(d | h) p(h)
p(h | d ) = initially manipulated the base rate of blickets.
∑ p(d | h⬘) p(h⬘)
h⬘∈H
(1)
Children were shown the blicket detector, and
taught that blickets make the machine go. The
The prior p(h) is the probability that each experimenter then brought out a box of identi-
hypothesis is the hypothesis that actually gen- cal blocks. In one condition (the rare condition),
erated the data. The value p(d | h) is the likeli- 2 out of the first 12 blocks shown to the child
hood of the observed data being generated if activated the detector, and were categorized as
that particular hypothesis was the actual causal blickets. In the other condition (the common
structure in the world. For example, if A→B with condition), 10 out of the first 12 blocks activated
a deterministic parameterization (i.e., A always the detector, and were blickets. Then the exper-
causes B) is one of the hypotheses, and the data imenter brought out two more blocks (A and
consists of trials of A occurring in the absence B), and proceeded with the backwards blocking
168 LEARNING MECHANISMS

demonstration: these blocks together activated causal perception (e.g., Leslie & Keeble, 1987;
the detector, and then that object A activated Oakes & Cohen, 1990), and preschoolers’ causal
the detector by itself. knowledge (e.g., Bullock et al., 1982; Sophian &
The causal status of object A is unambigu- Huber, 1984), it seems reasonable to assume that
ous— it is a blicket—and all of the children cat- young children reason according to these two
egorized it as such. The causal status of object principles. Such knowledge limits the hypoth-
B is ambiguous given the data, but if children esis space to the four models described above.
relied on the observed base rates, they should But children also need to understand that
treat this object differently between the rare and there is a particular parameterization between
common conditions. In the common condition, objects and the detector activating—what
both 3- and 4-year-olds claimed that object B Tenenbaum and Griffiths (2003) and Sobel et
was a blicket, consistent with children recogniz- al. (2004) called the activation law. Do chil-
ing prior probabilities when evaluating ambigu- dren recognize that there is something about a
ous data. In the rare condition, the 4-year-olds blicket that makes the machine go? The activa-
claimed that object B was not a blicket, again tion law specifies that children recognize that
consistent with recognizing priors, but the there is some mechanism that relates blickets to
3-year-olds did not. They judged that the B the detector’s activation in a deterministic (or
object was a blicket regardless of the base rate of near-deterministic) manner. This information
blickets in the environment. allows the learner to recognize that the data in
There are two conclusions from these data. the backwards blocking procedure are ambigu-
The first is that 4-year-olds’ inferences were ous. Without this information (i.e., if children
consistent with the Bayesian description in believed that blickets only sometimes made
so far as they could recognize priors from the the machine go), the data are more consistent
environment and use that information to make with object B having the capacity to activate
rational inferences about ambiguous data. The the detector than not. To illustrate this, sup-
second is that there was a developmental dif- pose that blickets only activated the detector
ference between 3- and 4-year-olds’ inferences. 80% of the time. Even though object A clearly
It is possible that a system for causal inference is a blicket (by virtue of activating the machine
develops between these ages. However, there is alone), it might have failed to be responsible
another possibility, which involves considering for activating the machine when it was placed
what information is necessary for the child to together with object B on the machine; there
possess in order to formulate a hypothesis space would be a nontrivial chance that the detector’s
accurately. activation was uniquely caused by object B hav-
ing the efficacy to activate the machine.
While there is some good evidence that sug-
CHILDREN’S DEVELOPING KNOWLEDGE
gests 4-year-olds treat causal relations, including
ABOUT BLICKET DETECTORS
causal relations involving the blicket detector,
In the previous section, I asserted that there were as deterministic (Bullock et al., 1982; Schulz
four hypotheses consistent with the backwards & Sommerville, 2006), it is not clear whether
blocking data. What knowledge was necessary younger children do so as well. Further, even
to form this hypothesis space? Do children pos- this work does not suggest that children recog-
sess this knowledge? nize that deterministic data are related to partic-
Some spatiotemporal knowledge appears ular causal mechanisms. As such, in a series of
necessary. First, placing an object on the blicket investigations, my colleagues and I considered
detector activates it; the detector’s activation how 3- and 4-year-olds reasoned about the rela-
should not cause the experimenter to place tion between the causal properties of artifacts
an object on it. Second, an object’s location in and nonobvious, internal properties. Our ques-
space should be independent of another object’s tion was whether 3- and 4-year-olds recognized
locations in space. Given research on infants’ that insides of objects could act as mechanisms
INTEGR ATING TOP-DOWN AND BOTTOM-UP APPROACHES 169

for those objects’ causal properties, and whether the member of the pair with the internal part
children might understand such mechanisms activated the detector, and they were asked to
differently across domains of knowledge. show the experimenter another object that
In one set of experiments (Sobel, Yoachim, would activate the machine. The majority of
Gopnik, Meltzoff, & Blumenthal, 2007), we children chose the other object with the internal
presented children with the blicket detector part (66% of the time), significantly more often
(although we simply labeled it as a machine, than chance. Four-year-olds also claimed that
so that children were not influenced by object objects that shared internal parts were more
label information) and a set of objects such as likely to share causal properties (i.e., activate
those shown in Figure 8.4. Two objects were the detector) than objects that shared external
externally identical, and another was unique in parts (e.g., had stickers on them).
appearance. All three objects had holes drilled This inference also worked in the other
into them, covered by dowels, which could direction. In another experiment 3- and 4-year-
reveal whether each contained an internal part. olds were shown the same sets of objects and the
Four-year-olds were shown the insides of each blicket detector (again, without it being labeled
toy: one of the identical objects and the unique as such), and were shown the causal efficacy
object contained an internal part (a white map of the three objects. One member of the pair
pin), while the third member of the set was and the unique object activated the detector,
empty inside. Children were then shown that while the other member of the pair did not. The

Figure 8.4 Stimulus set used to measure whether children appreciated the relation between objects
causal properties and insides (Sobel et al., 2007).
170 LEARNING MECHANISMS

member of the pair that activated the detector not. We also showed children that the detec-
was opened to reveal that it contained an inter- tor activated if at least one object with a blicket
nal part, and children were asked which other inside was on it. After receiving this training,
object also contained such an inside. A striking children were shown two objects (A and B),
developmental difference was found: 3-year- which activated the machine together. The door
olds chose the other object that activated the on object A was opened to reveal it was empty.
detector 31% of the time, significantly lower Children had no trouble inferring whether each
than what would be expected by chance. Four- object contained an internal part. The critical
year-olds chose this object with significantly question was an intervention question—chil-
greater frequency (72%), and more often than dren were asked to make the machine go. The
chance responding. Importantly, Sobel et al. child has observed the experimenter generate
(2007) also ran a condition in which the associ- an intervention that activates the machine—
ation between the detector’s activation and each placing both objects on it. But this imitative
object was held constant, but the object was not response is not the most efficient way of acti-
causally related to the machine. Each object was vating the machine. If children recognize that
held over the detector, and the experimenter the internal part is responsible for the object’s
pressed a button on the detector for the objects causal property, then they should recognize
that would have activated the machine. Here, there is no need to put object A on the detector,
both 3- and 4-year-olds made causal responses and when asked to generate an intervention that
less than 30% of the time, significantly lower activates the machine, place only object B on the
than what would be expected by chance. machine. This was the response generated by
What these data suggest is that 4-year-olds, the majority of 4-year-olds, significantly more
but not 3-year-olds, recognize that there is a often than the younger children. The younger
relation between an object’s causal and internal children were more likely to imitate, and place
properties. However, these data do not demon- A and B on the machine together (Sobel &
strate that 4-year-olds understand an activation Blumenthal, in preparation).
law—that there is something about the internal These data suggest that 4-year-olds tie
part that is responsible for activating the detec- together the correlational information they
tor. Four-year-olds do integrate some amount observe between each object and the detector’s
of correlational information together when activation, and mechanism information about
making inferences about causal mechanisms: what is necessary for each object to activate
they only respond on the basis of the machine’s the detector: namely, a nonobvious property.
activation when the spatiotemporal connec- Three-year-olds have a harder time integrating
tion between the object and machine warrants this information. This development might relate
a causal relation. A stronger argument would to children’s developing use of a Bayesian mech-
be to demonstrate that 4-year-olds, but not anism of causal inference. Correlational infor-
younger children, interpret an object’s internal mation is reflected in how the data generate
parts as being necessary and sufficient for the posterior probabilities of each hypothesis being
detector’s activation. correct. Mechanism information is reflected in
To test this, Emily Blumenthal and I intro- how those hypotheses are formed: what causal
duced 3- and 4-year-olds to the blicket detector structures come under consideration and how
and provided children with (what we thought those causal structures are parameterized.
was) the strongest possible information about its Specifically, what we would like to show
efficacy. We told children that the machine was is that children who recognize the activation
a “blicket machine” and “things with blickets law, by virtue of connecting objects’ causal and
inside made the machine go.” We then showed internal parts together, are more likely to engage
children that a set of objects with internal parts in inferences consistent with recognizing the
(labeled blickets) all activated the machine, and prior probability information they observe. The
that a set of objects without internal parts did 3-year-olds who failed to discriminate between
INTEGR ATING TOP-DOWN AND BOTTOM-UP APPROACHES 171

the rare and common conditions in Sobel et al.’s given to the children, they preferred to play with
(2004) procedure might have lacked the under- the toy associated with the first person. This sug-
standing that the way an object can produce its gests that children infer a nonobvious property
causal properties can be related to its insides. to the toy based on another’s desires, since that
Lacking this knowledge might indicate that property must be responsible for those desires
they lacked an activation law relating objects (see also Perner, 1991; Yuill, 1984).
with the detector, which would make their fail- Sobel and Munro (2009) manipulated the
ure to respond like the older children rational. blicket detector to attempt to introduce it to
3-year-olds as a psychological agent. They
placed a set of cardboard eyes on the machine
THAT’S
MR. BLICKET TO YOU: CAUSAL
(shown in Figure 8.5) and introduced it to chil-
MECHANISMS ACROSS DOMAINS
dren as “Mr. Blicket.” The experimenter con-
In order to test this hypothesis, we need to ducted a dialogue with the machine, which
consider how we might facilitate 3-year-olds’ activated spontaneously in response to ques-
understanding of an activation law. One possi- tions and comments (this procedure was mod-
bility is to consider how children reason about eled after Johnson, Slaughter, and Carey (1998)
such causal relations in another domain of and Johnson, Booth, and O’Hearn (2001), who
knowledge; all of the experiments mentioned so used a similar procedure to study agent gaze-
far have been exclusive to the domain of blicket following in infants). The children were then
detectors and aspects of physical causality. Can told that they were going to play a game in which
similar manipulations be performed in another Mr. Blicket would tell them whether he liked an
domain? There is some reason to suspect that object. They then repeated the procedure used
some causal inference abilities, such as infer- by Sobel et al. (2007) to study whether 3-year-
ences consistent with the Markov assump- olds linked the internal parts of objects with
tion, appear to be domain-general (e.g., Schulz their causal property (in this case, whether Mr.
& Gopnik, 2004). However, these inferences Blicket liked the object). Three-year-olds did
involved general logical principles, not specific link the causal property with the object’s insides
pieces of causal mechanism information. in this condition, significantly more often
Research in theory of mind tells us that than in another condition, in which the same
young children understand a particular mental procedure was performed with a machine that
state—the results of an agent’s desires—at very spontaneously activated during the warm-up
young ages. Eighteen-month-olds recognize that of the procedure, with the same temporal con-
others can have desires different from their own tiguity as Mr. Blicket’s activation (70% vs. 41%
(Repacholi & Gopnik, 1997). Two- and 3-year- of the time).
olds have a good understanding of the outcomes
of fulfi lled and unfulfi lled desires (Wellman &
Woolley, 1990). Three-year-olds can also keep
track of their own and other’s desires over time
and changes in the environment (e.g., Gopnik
& Slaughter, 1991). Fawcett and Markson
(2005) asked 2-year-olds to make inferences
about their own preferences based on another’s
desires. They showed children that one person
consistently played with toys that matched the
child’s preferences, and that another person
consistently played with toys that did not match
the child’s preferences. They then presented two
novel (equally preferential) toys, and each per-
son played with one. When those two toys were Figure 8.5 Mr. Blicket.
172 LEARNING MECHANISMS

These data suggest that 3-year-olds might we gave another group of 3-year-olds the same
integrate the correlational data they observe Mr. Blicket procedure, except that we labeled his
about agent’s desires toward objects with mech- activation as indicating what he was thinking
anism information—that there must be some- about, instead of what he liked. Unlike desire,
thing about those particular objects responsible 3-year-olds have little knowledge of other’s
for Mr. Blicket’s desires. If this is the case, then belief states (e.g., Wellman, Cross, & Watson,
3-year-olds might have an activation law about 2001), the role of thinking in other mental activ-
Mr. Blicket’s desire, and reason more consis- ities (Flavell, Green, & Flavell, 1995; Johnson &
tently with the Bayesian description than they Wellman, 1982; Lillard, 1996), or the possibility
do in the physical domain. To test this, we (Sobel that thoughts could be related to objects or other
& Munro, 2009) introduced 3-year-olds to Mr. thoughts (Eisbach, 2004). It seemed likely that
Blicket in the same manner as described above, only a few 3-year-olds would recognize that an
and then gave them the same rare or common agent’s thoughts could be based on an internal
training as in Sobel et al. (2004), followed by the property of objects, which would provide them
same backwards blocking trial. Two new objects with a causal mechanism equivalent to the acti-
(A and B) were placed on Mr. Blicket together, vation law. This also appeared to be the case. In
and he activated. Then object A alone was this condition, 3-year-olds categorized object B
placed on him with the same result. All children as something Mr. Blicket was thinking about
claimed that Mr. Blicket liked object A, and the 72% of the time, more often than in the desire
question was how they categorized object B. condition.
Three-year-olds claimed that Mr. Blicket Further, in the three conditions in which
liked object B 44% of the time when trained children were trained that the causal power
that he liked relatively few things (recall that the (Mr. Blicket’s desire, thoughts, or the activation
base rate in this condition was 1/6). By contrast, of a spontaneous machine) was rare, we also gave
when Mr. Blicket liked many things (a base children a set of unrelated cognitive measures as
rate of 5/6), children responded that he liked well as a measure in which they were asked to
object B 93% of the time, a significant difference relate the causal power of objects to those objects
between the conditions. Performance in the insides (analogous to the procedure used in
rare condition, however, could have been influ- Sobel et al., 2007). Across all of these conditions,
enced by a number of factors. One possibility is the ability to relate the causal property of objects
that children were influenced by the spontane- to those objects’ insides predicted whether chil-
ous activation of the box, and would respond dren claimed that object B did not have causal
in a similar manner to a blicket machine that efficacy (i.e., a response consistent with the
they observed spontaneously activate. This was Bayesian description), even when age and other
not the case. Another group of 3-year-olds were measures of general cognition were considered.
shown a blicket machine that spontaneously These data indicate that children are not
activated during the initial part of the proce- specifically developing causal inference abilities
dure. They were trained that objects that acti- between the ages of 3 and 4. Rather, children
vate the machine (and hence, are blickets) were appear to have such an inferential mechanism
rare, and were given the same procedure. In this in place at the age of three, and lack the particu-
condition, 3-year-olds categorized object B as a lar domain-specific knowledge necessary to use
blicket 72% of the time, more often than in the that mechanism appropriately. The Bayesian
desire condition. description I am suggesting here (following
Similarly, another possibility is that chil- similar proposals by Griffiths & Tenenbaum,
dren were simply more interested in Mr. Blicket 2005; Griffiths et al., submitted; Tenenbaum &
than when it was a blicket machine. There are Griffiths, 2001, 2003; Tenenbaum, Griffiths, &
cases where children’s interest level clearly Niyogi, 2007) offers a rational way of consider-
mediates their cognition (e.g., Renninger & ing how children’s developing prior knowledge
Wozniak, 1985). To consider this possibility, influences their causal reasoning abilities.
INTEGR ATING TOP-DOWN AND BOTTOM-UP APPROACHES 173

An open question is how such causal detector is probabilistic, then there should be
knowledge might be acquired. In the final sec- the possibility that object B is a blicket; object
tions, I want to consider two possibilities. The B might have failed to be effective when it was
first is an extension of the Bayesian mechanism. placed on the machine alone, but demonstrated
The second attempts to integrate other pieces of its efficacy when placed on the machine with
information from the environment. object A. If the detector is deterministic, then
this is not the case: object A should be a blicket,
and object B should not be by virtue of it failing
LEARNING CAUSAL MECHANISMS
to activate the detector independently. Gopnik
So far we have considered how children recover et al. (2001) found that overall, children (partic-
a representation of the causal environment ularly 4-year-olds) who were shown these data
based on the data they observe. Th is learn- responded consistently with the deterministic
ing mechanism is guided by a particular set of interpretation. Tom Griffiths and I reanalyzed
causal principles, which potentially constrain performance on the one-cause trials as a func-
the hypothesis space children consider and the tion of whether they observed a two-cause trial
parameterization of those hypotheses. An open first (recall that in the two-cause trial, one object
question is how children develop knowledge of activates the detector probabilistically; it fails to
these causal principles. activate the machine the first time it is placed on
Consider the mechanism that underlies the it, and does so the next two times). Four-year-
blicket detector. The previous sections argued olds were more likely to say that object B was a
that preschoolers develop a conception that the blicket in the one-cause trial if they saw a two-
mechanism that underlies the detector’s activa- cause trial first.
tion is deterministic. This knowledge is what Griffiths et al. (submitted) considered more
allows us (and young children) to make infer- systematically whether children and adults
ences based on small samples of data. In almost can extract mechanism information from the
all of the experiments described above, children data they observe. Specifically, if learners first
are never shown data that contradict a deter- observe evidence that the detector is determin-
ministic mechanism. What happens if this is istic will they make different inferences about
the case? the same data than if they first observe evidence
In Gopnik et al. (2001), children were shown that the detector is not deterministic? This ques-
cases in which objects sometimes made the tion can also be formulated as one of Bayesian
machine go and sometimes did not. In their inference, although the hypotheses are about
two-cause trials, children inferred that an the principles that govern how hypotheses about
object that activated the blicket detector two out causal models are formulated. In this example,
of three times was a blicket most of the time. the hypotheses include the nature of the activa-
This trial provides evidence that the detector is tion law—the mechanism that relates objects to
not deterministic and might activate based on the detector—in addition to the specific causal
a more probabilistic mechanism. How might structures (following Tenenbaum, Griffiths, &
seeing this trial first affect children’s inferences Kemp, 2006; Tenenbaum et al., 2007). For pur-
on other trials, in which a deterministic mecha- poses of space, I will only describe the psycho-
nism is required? logical investigation with young children, but
Like the backwards blocking procedure, we have done similar investigations on adults.
Gopnik et al.’s (2001) one-cause procedure Griffiths et al. (submitted) showed 4-year-
relies on children understanding that there is a olds the blicket detector, and trained them that
deterministic mechanism that relates blickets to the detector was either deterministic or proba-
the blicket detector (recall that on a one-cause bilistic. In the deterministic condition, children
trial, object A activates the machine by itself, were introduced to the detector as in Gopnik
object B does not by itself, then both objects et al. (2001). They then observed six objects, each
activated the machine together twice). If the placed on the machine three times. Five of the
174 LEARNING MECHANISMS

six objects activated the machine all three times, the older children treat them as if they were the
and were labeled blickets; the other object failed mechanism for the detector’s activation, with-
to activate the machine all three times, and out (apparently) a real conception of how such
was labeled as not a blicket. In the probabilistic mechanisms function.
condition, children received the same introduc-
tion, and saw the same six objects. But here, the INTEGRATING TOP-DOWN AND
objects that activated the machine perfectly in BOTTOM - UP LEARNING
the previous condition did so with some noise.
Objects either activated the machine perfectly Appealing to a Bayesian description of a causal
(one object), two out of three times (two objects) learning mechanism—specifically one that
or one out of three times (two objects), and any might be able to extract such mechanism knowl-
of the objects that activated the machine was edge from observed data—does not imply that
labeled a blicket. The object that failed to acti- all causal learning is “bottom-up.” Instead, the
vate the machine all three times was still labeled Bayesian description seems more integrative:
as not a blicket, keeping the base rate of blickets “top-down” principles for constraining causal
the same across the conditions. learning can be derived from data, but this
Children then observed a set of trials simi- should not be considered the only way causal
lar to the one-cause condition in Gopnik et al. learning works. Below, I suggest several addi-
(2001). The critical part of the trial involved them tional ways children might be able to acquire
observing two new objects (A and B). Object A information about the principles for causal
activated the machine by itself once. Object B learning.
failed to activate the machine by itself once, and
Testimony
then A and B together activated the machine
twice. Children were asked whether each was More likely than not, the best way in which chil-
a blicket. In the deterministic condition, per- dren learn new causal structures (or new causal
formance paralleled Gopnik et al. (2001): chil- principles) is through direct instruction—what
dren stated that object A was a blicket (100% of Harris and Koenig (2006) call learning from
the time), and object B was not (only 9% of the “testimony.” Harris, Pasquini, Duke, Asscher,
time). In the probabilistic condition, children and Pons (2006), for example, demonstrated
stated that object A was a blicket (92% of the that children made strong ontological commit-
time), but were significantly more likely to state ments about different nonobservable scientific
that object B was as well (79% of the time). and endorsed entities (e.g., vitamins vs. Santa
These data offer preliminary evidence that Claus). Further, the degree of their commitment
4-year-olds not only can recover information in these entities varied with the exposure that
about causal models from the data that they they received about them.
observed, but that they also recover the prin- More generally, one could imagine that chil-
ciples necessary to learn causal structure from dren learn a great deal of causal structure simply
those data. Given the same correlational infor- by being told about that structure (something
mation, their inferences were different depend- that might be particularly important in learning
ing on the nature of the mechanism they were science, see Klahr & Nigam, 2004). This is evi-
exposed to. Children’s understanding of these dent in the introduction to most blicket detec-
mechanisms might not be terribly deep; they tor experiments, in which children are told that
might not have explicit understanding of the the machine is a “blicket machine,” and that
mechanism, but rather just be aware that some objects that make it go are “blickets.” The fact
kind of mechanism exists, which constrains that children learn this readily (established in
inference in certain ways. Th is seems con- the pretests of almost all of these experiments),
sistent with the work on relating causes and suggests that they can learn causal principles
insides: the internal parts of the objects in directly from the language they hear, but this is
Sobel et al. (2007) are dummy mechanisms, but a topic for further investigation.
INTEGR ATING TOP-DOWN AND BOTTOM-UP APPROACHES 175

Analogy similar data in adult participants (Lagnado &


Sloman, 2004; Steyvers et al., 2003; Waldmann
Numerous investigations suggest that young
& Hagmayer, 2005), in child participants
children can make inferences from analogies
(Schulz et al., 2007), and in animals (Blaisdell et
(e.g., Brown & Kane, 1988; Gentner, 1977), and
al., 2006). Moreover, young children appear to
this is especially true when reasoning about
treat their own data as more informative than if
causal relations (e.g., Goswami & Brown, 1989;
the same data were generated by another person
Goswami, Leevers, Pressley, & Wheelwright,
(Kushnir & Gopnik, 2005).
1998; Ratterman & Gentner, 1998). This sug-
Jessica Sommerville and I investigated how
gests that children can come to make new causal
young children’s causal learning was affected
inferences from analogous information, or learn
by particular contextual demands (Sobel &
new information faster/more accurately if the
Sommerville, in preparation). We found that
analogy is mapped out for them. Emily Hopkins
4-year-olds whose free play with a system allowed
and I (Hopkins & Sobel, 2007; Sobel & Hopkins,
them to discover causal structure learned that
submitted) have recently considered this possi-
structure better than children whose free play
bility by looking at a particular type of causal
with a system came after they observed an
inference: reasoning about enabling condition.
experimenter generate a small number of inter-
Specifically, we found that 4-year-olds struggled
ventions on the system (enough to discover the
to understand enabling conditions in a decon-
structure). Further, when children were shown
textualized environment (where the part of an
identical intervention data, which was sufficient
object that acted as the enabling condition was
to learn a causal structure, children who were
labeled an “inside”). However, young children
given an inappropriate rationale for why the
do appear to understand enabling conditions
experimenter has generated those data failed to
in a particular setting: a Child Language Data
learn the system; children given an appropriate
Exchange System (CHILDES; MacWhinney,
rationale learned above chance values (Sobel &
2000) analysis revealed that children talk about
Sommerville, 2009). These contextual factors
how batteries are necessary to make machines
are not part of the computational description
and toys function. Four-year-olds were able to
I have described so far, and must be accounted
make proper inferences about enabling condi-
for therein.
tions in a condition in which the part that acted
in this manner was labeled as a battery.
CONCLUSIONS
Contextual Information in Data
In this chapter, I have suggested a description
A potential limitation of the causal graphi- of causal inference based on Bayesian infer-
cal model framework is that it does not easily ence, which illustrates how children engage in
describe a way in which contextual cues can causal learning (for a more detailed description
influence learning. For example, active con- of this model, see e.g., Griffiths & Tenenbaum,
struction of knowledge in the world is a hallmark 2007). This description is meant at the compu-
of both classic (e.g., Montessori, 1912; Piaget, tational level of analysis (followed Marr, 1982),
1952) and certain contemporary (e.g., Gopnik & which means that an obvious limitation of this
Meltzoff, 1997) approaches to cognitive develop- approach is that it should not be taken for the
ment. The computational approaches described actual algorithm by which children learn causal
here do not consider whether the child has an knowledge, nor should it be considered how
active hand in constructing its knowledge as the brain instantiates such inference. However,
opposed to recovering causal structure from in describing the way in which children learn
simply observing the environment. causal knowledge, we provide insight into these
The ability to control what data one observes, questions.
and generate interventions consistent with those I want to conclude by emphasizing that com-
data appear to facilitate learning over observing putational models are a good way to focus an
176 LEARNING MECHANISMS

investigation, but a psychological description of Bullock, M., Gelman, R., & Baillargeon, R. (1982).
human causal learning should not be completely The development of causal reasoning. In W. J.
model-dependent (whether that model be bot- Friedman (Ed.), The developmental psychology of
tom-up, top-down, or something in between). time (pp. 209–254). New York: Academic Press.
One should integrate model with human work- Cheng, P. W. (1997). From covariation to causa-
tion: A causal power theory. Psychological
ings to describe psychological accounts of
Review, 104, 367–405.
reasoning (what Lagnado et al., 2007, calls a Cheng, P. W., & Novick, L. R. (1990). A proba-
“heuristic-based” approach). Here, it should be bilistic contrast model of causal induction.
emphasized that young children possess con- Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
siderable causal reasoning abilities, starting at a 58, 545–567.
very young age. The goal of future research is to Cramer, R. E., Weiss, R. F., Williams, R., Reid, S.,
describe these abilities, and potentially develop Nieri, L., & Manning-Ryan, B. (2002). Human
an algorithmic and implementational level of agency and associative learning: Pavlovian
children’s causal inference—in more detail. principles govern social process in causal
relationship detection. Quarterly Journal of
Experimental Psychology: Comparative and
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS Physiological Psychology, 55B, 241–266.
Das Gupta, P., & Bryant, P. E. (1989). Young chil-
I was supported by NSF (DLS-0518161 to D.M.S.)
dren’s causal inferences. Child Development,
during the writing of this chapter. I would like to
60, 1138–1146.
thank all of the parents and children who par-
Dickinson, A., & Shanks, D. (1995). Instrumental
ticipated in the research described here. I would
action and causal representation. In D. Sperber,
also like to thank Scott Johnson, David Buchanan,
D. Premack, & A. J. Premack (Eds.), Causal cog-
Claire Cook, Tom Griffiths, Natasha Kirkham and
nition: A multidisciplinary debate (pp. 5–25).
the members of the NYBUG workshop for helpful
New York: Clarendon Press/Oxford University
discussions about material in this chapter.
Press.
Eisbach, A. O. D. (2004). Children’s developing
REFERENCES awareness of diversity in people’s trains of
thought. Child Development, 75, 1694–1707.
Ahn, W., Kalish, C. W., Medin, D. L., & Gelman, Fawcett, C., & Markson, L. (2005). Developing
S. A. (1995). The role of covariation versus ideas about other’s preferences. Poster pre-
mechanism information in causal attribution. sented at the 2005 meeting of the Cognitive
Cognition, 54, 299–352. Development Society, San Diego, CA.
Allan, L. G. (1980). A note on measurement of Fiser, J., & Aslin, R. N. (2002). Statistical learn-
contingency between two binary variables in ing of new visual feature combinations by
judgment tasks. Bulletin of the Psychonomic infants. Proceedings of the National Academy of
Society, 15, 147–149 Sciences, USA, 99, 15822–15826.
Aslin, R. N., Saff ran, J. R., & Newport, E. L. (1998). Flavell, J. H., Green, F. L., & Flavell, E. R. (1995).
Computation of conditional probability sta- Young children’s knowledge about thinking.
tistics by 8-month-old infants. Psychological Monographs of the Society for Research in
Science, 9, 321–324. Child Development, 60(1, Serial No. 243).
Blaisdell, A. P., Sawa, K., Leising, K. J., & Gentner, D. (1977). Children’s performance on a
Waldmann, M. R. (2006). Causal reasoning in spatial analogies task. Child Development, 48,
rats. Science, 311, 1020–1022. 1034–1039.
Blumenthal, E. J., & Sobel, D. M. (2008). Gomez, R. L., & Gerken, L. A., (1999). Artificial
Preschoolers’ developing knowledge of causal grammar learning by 1-year-olds leads to spe-
and internal properties of artifacts. Manuscript cific and abstract knowledge. Cognition, 70,
in preparation, Brown University. 109–135.
Brown, A. L., & Kane, M. J. (1988). Preschool Gopnik, A., Glymour, C., Sobel, D. M., Schulz, L.
children can learn to transfer: Learning to E., Kushnir, T., & Danks, D. (2004). A theory of
learn and learning from example. Cognitive causal learning in children: Causal maps and
Psychology, 20, 493–523. Bayes nets. Psychological Review, 111, 3–32.
INTEGR ATING TOP-DOWN AND BOTTOM-UP APPROACHES 177

Gopnik, A., & Meltzoff, A. N. (1992). Categorization In C. Granrud (Ed.), Visual perception and
and naming: Basic-level sorting in eighteen- cognition in infancy (pp. 235–264). Hillsdale,
month-olds and its relation to language. Child NJ: Erlbaum.
Development, 63, 1091–1103. Harris, P. L., & Koenig, M. A. (2006). Trust in tes-
Gopnik, A., & Meltzoff, A. N. (1997). Words, timony: How children learn about science and
thoughts, and theories. Cambridge, MA: MIT religion. Child Development, 77, 505–524.
Press. Harris, P. L., Pasquini, E. S., Duke, S., Asscher,
Gopnik, A., & Slaughter, V. (1991). Young chil- J. J., & Pons, F. (2006).Germs and angels: The
dren’s understanding of changes in their men- role of testimony in young children’s ontology.
tal states. Child Development, 62, 98–110. Developmental Science, 9, 76–96.
Gopnik, A., & Sobel, D. M. (2000). Detecting Hopkins, E. J., & Sobel, D. M. (2007, March).
blickets: How young children use informa- Children’s causal inferences about enabling
tion about novel causal powers in categoriza- conditions in the physical and psychological
tion and induction. Child Development, 71, domains. Poster presented at the 2007 Biennial
1205–1222. meeting of the Society for Research in Child
Gopnik, A., Sobel, D. M., Schulz, L., & Glymour, Development, Boston, MA.
C. (2001). Causal learning mechanisms in very Hume, D. (1978). A treatise of human nature.
young children: Two, three, and four-year-olds Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Original
infer causal relations from patterns of variation work published 1739)
and co-variation. Developmental Psychology, Johnson, C. N., & Wellman, H. M. (1982).
37, 620–629. Children’s developing conceptions of the mind
Goswami, U., & Brown, A. L. (1989). Melting and brain. Child Development, 53, 222–234.
chocolate and melting snowmen: Analogical Johnson, S., Slaughter, V., & Carey, S. (1998).
reasoning and causal relations. Cognition, 35, Whose gaze will infants follow? The elicita-
69–95. tion of gaze-following in 12-month-olds.
Goswami, U., & Brown, A. L. (1990). Higher-order Developmental Science, 1, 233–238.
structure and relational reasoning: Contrasting Johnson, S. C., Booth, A., & O’Hearn, K. (2001).
analogical and thematic relations. Cognition, Inferring the goals of a nonhuman agent.
36, 207–226. Cognitive Development, 16, 637–656.
Goswami, U., Leevers, H., Pressley, S., & Kamin, L. J. (1969). Predictability, surprise, atten-
Wheelwright, S. (1998). Causal reasoning tion, and conditioning. In B. A. Campbell &
about pairs of relations and analogical rea- R. M. Church (Eds.), Punishment and aversive
soning in young children. British Journal of behavior (pp. 279–296). New York: Appleton-
Developmental Psychology, 16, 553–569. Century-Crofts.
Gottfried, G. M., & Gelman, S. A. (2005). Kirkham, N. Z., Slemmer, J. A., & Johnson, S. P.
Developing domain-specific causal-explana- (2002). Visual statistical learning in infancy.
tory frameworks: The role of insides and imma- Cognition, 83, B35–B42.
nence. Cognitive Development, 20, 137–158 Klahr, D., & Nigam, M. (2004). The equivalence
Griffiths, T. L., Sobel, D. M., Tenenbaum, J. B., & of learning paths in early science instruction.
Gopnik, A. (2008). Bayesian reasoning in adults’ Psychological Science, 15, 661–667.
and children’s causal inferences. Manuscript Kruschke, J. K., & Blair, N. J. (2000). Blocking and
in preparation, University of California at backward blocking involve learned inattention.
Berkeley. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review, 7, 636–645.
Griffiths, T. L., & Tenenbaum, J. B. (2005). Kushnir, T., & Gopnik, A. (2005). Young Children
Structure and strength in causal induction. Infer Causal Strength from Probabilities
Cognitive Psychology, 51, 334–384. and Interventions. Psychological Science, 16,
Griffiths, T. L., & Tenenbaum, J. B. (2007). Two 678–683.
proposals for causal grammars. In A. Gopnik & Lagnado, D. A., & Sloman, S. (2004). The advantage
L. E. Schulz (Eds.), Causal learning: Psychology, of timely intervention. Journal of Experimental
Philosophy, and Computation (pp. 323–346). Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition,
New York: Oxford University Press. 30, 856–876.
Haith, M. M. (1993). Future-oriented processes Lagnado, D. A., Waldmann, M. R., Hagmayer, Y., &
in infancy: The case of visual expectations. Sloman, S. A. (2007). Beyond covariation: Cues
178 LEARNING MECHANISMS

to causal structure. In A. Gopnik & L. E. Schulz and recall in young children. Developmental
(Eds.), Causal learning: Psychology, philoso- Psychology, 21, 624–632.
phy, and computation (pp. 154–172). New York: Repacholi, B. M., & Gopnik, A. (1997). Early rea-
Oxford. soning about desires: Evidence from 14- and
Leslie, A. M., & Keeble, S. (1987). Do six-month- 18-month-olds. Developmental Psychology, 33,
old infants perceive causality? Cognition, 25, 12–21.
265–288. Rescorla, R. A., & Wagner, A. R. (1972). A the-
Lillard, A. S. (1996). Body or mind: Children’s cat- ory of Pavlovian conditioning: Variations in
egorizing of pretense. Child Development, 67, the effectiveness of reinforcement and nonre-
1717–1734. inforcement. In A. H. Black & W. F. Prokasy
Mackintosh, N. J. (1975). A theory of attention: (Eds.), Classical Conditioning II: Current theory
Variations in the associability of stimuli with and research (pp. 64–99). New York: Appleton-
reinforcement. Psychological Review, 82, Century-Crofts.
276–298. Saff ran, J. R., Aslin, R. N., & Newport, E. L. (1996).
MacWhinney, B. (2000). The CHILDES project: Statistical learning by 8-month-old infants.
Tools for analyzing talk (3rd ed.). Mahwah, NJ: Science, 274, 1926–1928.
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Saff ran, J. R., Johnson, E. K., Aslin, R. N., &
Marr, D. (1982). Vision. New York: Henry Holt. Newport, E. L. (1999). Statistical learning of
McCormack, T., & Hoerl, C. (2005). Children’s tone sequences by human infants and adults.
reasoning about the causal significance of Cognition, 70, 27–52.
the temporal order of events. Developmental Schulz, L. E., & Gopnik, A. (2004). Causal learning
Psychology, 41, 54–63. across domains. Developmental Psychology, 40,
Michotte, A. (1962).Causalite, permanence et 162–176.
realite phenomenales. Oxford, England: Publi- Schulz, L. E., Gopnik, A., & Glymour, C. (2007).
cations Universitaires. Preschool children learn causal structure from
Montessori, M. (1912/1964). The montessori conditional independence. Developmental
method. New York: Schocken. Science, 10, 322–332.
Novick, L. R., & Cheng, P. W. (2004). Assessing Schulz, L. E., & Sommerville, J. (2006). God does
interactive causal influence. Psychological not play dice: Causal determinism and chil-
Review, 111, 455–485. dren’s inferences about unobserved causes.
Oakes, L. M., & Cohen, L. B. (1990). Infant percep- Child Development, 77, 427–442.
tion of a causal event. Cognitive Development, Shanks, D. R. (1985). Forward and backward
5, 193–207. blocking in human contingency judgment.
Pearl, J. (2000). Causality: Models, reasoning, and Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology,
inference. New York: Cambridge University 37B, 1–21.
Press. Shanks, D. R. (1995). Is human learning rational?
Perner, J. (1991). Understanding the representa- Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology
tional mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. A, 48, 257–279.
Piaget, J. (1929). The child’s conception of the world. Shultz, T. R. (1982). Rules of causal attribution.
London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Monographs of the Society for Research in Child
Piaget, J. (1930). The child’s conception of physical Development, 47(1, Serial No. 194).
causality (M. Gabain, Trans.). London: Lund Sobel, D. M. & Blumenthal, E. J. (2009). Children’s
Humphries. causal inferences about ambiguous evidence reflect
Piaget, J. (1952). The origins of intelligence in their developing understanding of mechanisms.
children (M. Cook, Trans.). Madison, WI: Manuscript in preparation, Brown University.
International Universities Press. Sobel, D. M., & Hopkins, E. (2009). Batteries not
Ratterman, M. J., & Gentner, D. (1998). More included: Children’s causal inferences about
evidence for a relational shift in the develop- enabling conditions. Manuscript in prepara-
ment of analogy: Children’s performance on a tion, Brown University.
causal-mapping task. Cognitive Development, Sobel, D. M., & Kirkham, N. Z. (2006). Blickets
13, 453–478. and babies: The development of causal rea-
Renninger, K. A., & Wozniak, R. H. (1985). Effect soning in toddlers and infants. Developmental
of interest on attentional shift, recognition, Psychology, 42, 1103–1115.
INTEGR ATING TOP-DOWN AND BOTTOM-UP APPROACHES 179

Sobel, D. M., & Kirkham, N. Z. (2007). Bayes nets Annual Conference on the Advances in Neural
and blickets: Infants developing representa- Information Processing Systems.
tions of causal knowledge. Developmental Tenenbaum, J. B., Griffiths, T. L., & Kemp, C.
Science, 10, 298–306. (2006). Theory-based Bayesian models of
Sobel, D. M., & Munro, S. A. (2009). Domain gen- inductive learning and reasoning. Trends in
erality and specificity in children’s causal infer- Cognitive Science, 10, 309–318.
ences about ambiguous data. Developmental Tenenbaum, J. B., Griffiths, T. L., & Niyogi, S. (2007).
Psychology, 45, 511–524. Intuitive theories as grammars for causal infer-
Sobel, D. M., & Sommerville, J. A. (2009a). ence. In A. Gopnik & L. E. Schulz (Eds.), Causal
Rationales in children’s causal learning from learning; Psychology, philosophy and computa-
other’s actions. Cognitive Development, 24, tion (pp. 301–322). New York: Oxford.
70–79. Uzgiris, I. C., & Hunt, J. M. V. (1975). Assessment
Sobel, D. M. & Sommerville, J. A. (2009b). The in infancy: Ordinal scales of psychological devel-
importance of discovery for children’s causal opment. Oxford, England: University of Illinois
learning from interventions. Manuscript in Press.
preparation, Brown University. Van Hamme, L. J., & Wasserman, E. A. (1994). Cue
Sobel, D. M., Tenenbaum, J. B., & Gopnik, A. competition in causality judgments: The role of
(2004). Children’s causal inferences from nonpresentation of compound stimulus ele-
indirect evidence: Backwards blocking and ments. Learning and Motivation, 25, 127–151.
Bayesian reasoning in preschoolers. Cognitive Waldmann, M. R., & Hagmayer, Y. (2005). Seeing
Science, 28, 303–333. versus doing: Two modes of accessing causal
Sobel, D. M., Yoachim, C. M., Gopnik, A., knowledge. Journal of Experimental Psychology:
Meltzoff, A. N., & Blumenthal, E. J. (2007). The Learning Memory and Cognition, 31, 216–227.
blicket within: Preschoolers’ inferences about Wasserman, E. A., & Berglan, L. R (1998). Backward
insides and causes. Journal of Cognition and blocking and recovery from overshadowing in
Development, 8, 159–182. human causal judgment: The role of within-
Sophian, C., & Huber, A. (1984). Early develop- compound associations. Quarterly Journal
ments in children’s causal judgments. Child of Experimental Psychology: Comparative &
Development, 55, 512–526. Physiological Psychology, 51, 121–138.
Spelke, E. S., Breinlinger, K., Macomber, J., & Wellman, H. M., Cross, D., & Watson, J. K. (2001).
Jacobson, K. (1992). Origins of knowledge. A meta-analysis of theory of mind: The truth
Psychological Review, 99, 605–632. about false belief. Child Development, 72,
Spirtes, P., Glymour, C., & Scheines, R. (2001). 655–684.
Causation, prediction, and search (Springer Wellman, H. M., & Woolley, J. D. (1990). From sim-
Lecture Notes in Statistics, 2nd ed., Rev.). ple desires to ordinary beliefs: The early devel-
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. opment of everyday psychology. Cognition, 35,
Steyvers, M., Tenenbaum, J. B., Wagenmakers, E. 245–275.
J., & Blum, B. (2003). Inferring causal networks Wentworth, N. Haith, M. M., & Hood, R. (2002).
from observations and interventions. Cognitive Spatiotemporal regularity and interevent con-
Science, 27, 453–489. tingencies as information for infants’ visual
Tenenbaum, J. B., & Griffiths, T. L. (2001). expectations. Infancy, 3, 303–321.
Structure learning in human causal induction. Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A the-
Proceedings of the 13th Annual Conference ory of causal explanation. New York: Oxford.
on the Advances in Neural Information Yuill, N. (1984). Young children’s coordina-
Processing Systems. tion of motive and outcome in judgments of
Tenenbaum, J. B., & Griffiths, T. L. (2003). Theory- satisfaction and morality. British Journal of
based causal inference. Proceedings of the 14th Developmental Psychology, 2, 73–81.
CHAP TER 9
What Is Statistical Learning, and
What Statistical Learning Is Not

Jenny R. Saffran

Over the past decade, researchers in develop- processing, statistical learning typically refers
mental cognitive science and psycholinguistics to a set of processes or procedures for parsing,
have become increasingly interested in the role part-of-speech tagging (e.g., discovering lexical
that statistical learning may play in perceptual categories), or induction of grammatical struc-
and cognitive development. Despite the term tures using such procedures as Hidden Markov
being weighty, the idea is quite simple. To the Models (e.g., Charniak, 1993). The broad idea
extent that structure in the environment is behind this body of research is that bottom-up
patterned, learners with appropriate learning processes tracking joint frequencies, condi-
mechanisms can make use of that patterning to tional probabilities, prior probabilities, mutual
discover underlying structure. This idea has a information, and/or entropy (among many
long history, across myriad domains. For exam- other possible computations) may efficiently
ple, linguists in the first half of the twentieth discover structure in complex domains, at least
century routinely examined the distribution of given relatively constrained search spaces.
sounds, words, and categories of words in novel Consistent with but largely separate from
languages to infer the structures that gener- these developments, computational modelers
ated those distributions, including phonemes, in cognitive science were developing novel tech-
words, morphemes, and rudimentary syntax niques for learning via ‘dumb’ algorithms oper-
(e.g., Bloomfield, 1933; Harris, 1955). Similarly, ating en masse, intended to mimic the operation
researchers studying the behavior of nonhuman of neural structures (e.g., Hebbian learning).
animals, both in the laboratory and in their nat- Again, working within relatively constrained
ural habitats, discovered that nonhuman ani- domains and/or toy corpora, researchers dem-
mals skillfully track environmental regularities onstrated discovery procedures using neural
to increase the probabilities of reward (for an network models that essentially capitalized on
extensive review, see Gallistel, 1990). statistical properties of the input to parse sen-
The term “statistical learning” itself origi- tences, discover lexical categories, and discern
nated in the area of computer science. Statistical structure via learning (e.g., Allen & Seidenberg,
learning algorithms are typically used for pat- 1999; Chater & Redington, 1999; Curtin et al.,
tern recognition processes and are applied across 2001; Mintz, Newport, & Bever, 2002; Reali &
numerous domains from face recognition to Christiansen, 2005; Seidenberg & MacDonald,
speech processing. In this field, statistical learn- 2001). These models have been highly effective
ing is sometimes used to refer to algorithms in demonstrating the information content avail-
that themselves learn from data. In the subfield able in various types of input, as they permit
of computer science known as natural language researchers to determine what types of cues are,

180
WHAT IS STATISTICAL LEARNING 181

in principle, available to actual human learners were intended to provide an existence proof
and to test specific hypotheses concerning how that infants can, at least under certain circum-
learning might operate (e.g., the debate between stances, track types of information that are
proponents of rules vs. statistics: cf. Altmann, relevant to linguistic structure (according to
2002; Christiansen & Curtin, 1999; Marcus, the computational and linguistic literatures).
1999a, 1999b, 2001; McClelland, McClelland, & Importantly, the initial claims never suggested
Plaut, 1999; Rohde & Plaut, 1999; Seidenberg & that statistical learning could account for all of
Elman, 1999). language acquisition, or even all of any subset
Connectionist models have had a tremendous of language (e.g., discovering words in fluent
impact on theoretical and empirical work in the speech). The intent was to develop methods,
cognitive sciences. Interestingly, because these using artificial languages, which would allow
are learning models, they are arguably more subsequent researchers to test specific hypoth-
relevant to developmental psychology than to eses concerning the role of statistical learning
any other branch of cognitive science. Perhaps in language acquisition in infancy and beyond.
because of this fact, connectionist models have And to a large extent, this is exactly what has
been especially vulnerable to the kinds of cri- happened.
tiques and concerns raised most prominently by However, perhaps because of its relatively
developmentalists. For example, each model is simple beginnings, the area of statistical lan-
typically tailored to handle just one type of task. guage learning has been caricatured as focusing
That is, a model trained to learn the past tense of on a single computation (pairwise transitional
English verbs cannot turn around and do object probabilities) performed between physically
segregation as well (the input/output representa- observable entities (syllables) in a highly artificial
tions are wrong; even given overlapping represen- language. Given this view of statistical language
tations, new learning would lead to catastrophic learning, it is indeed the case that the theoreti-
interference, erasing the prior learning). These cal oomph of statistical learning is extremely
kinds of observations raise questions about how limited. To acquire natural languages, learn-
domain-specific such models need to be. What ers need to detect more complex relationships
is “innate” or prespecified in the representations between more abstract entities in a far richer set
and/or architectures of individual models? What of input. The insufficiency of statistical learn-
about types of learning—e.g., more abstract ing is even true for a task like detecting word
structures—that do not appear to be captured by boundaries in fluent speech. While tracking
statistical models? Perhaps most importantly, do sequential probabilities is demonstrably useful,
developing humans really learn this way? given corpus analyses (Swingley, 2005), other
Perhaps because of these developments and sources of information are absolutely necessary
debates, the initial findings that infants can to achieve good learning outcomes. These might
track the probabilities of sequential elements range from tracking additional regularities in
(syllables and/or phonemes) in speech received speech, such as the degree of stress carried by a
a great deal of attention (Aslin, Saff ran, & syllable (Curtin, Mintz, & Christiansen, 2005),
Newport, 1998; Goodsitt, Morgan, & Kuhl, to potential innate knowledge concerning uni-
1993; Hauser, Newport, & Aslin, 2001; Saff ran, versal phonological regularities (Yang, 2004).
Aslin, & Newport, 1996), both positive and neg- Importantly, the initial reports concerning
ative. On the positive side, these results unam- statistical learning attempted to be very explicit
biguously demonstrated that infants can track on this point, repeatedly pointing out the fact
regularities in rapid speech, without the benefit that sequential statistics alone are not enough
of added linguistic cues, social cues, or exter- to fully solve any real language learning prob-
nal reinforcement; learning itself appears to be lems. For example, Saff ran et al. (1996) noted
reinforcing in these tasks. This is not to say that that “although experience with speech in the
other sorts of information are not beneficial— real world is unlikely to be as concentrated as
indeed they are, as discussed below. These data it was in these studies, infants in more natural
182 LEARNING MECHANISMS

settings presumably benefit from other types the extent that this caricature is accurate, the
of cues correlated with statistical information” potential role for statistical learning in language
(p. 1928). In an adult study of this phenom- acquisition is limited at best. For the remainder
enon also published in 1996, these investiga- of this chapter, I will focus on three issues that
tors explicitly manipulated an additional cue to are implicit in this characterization of statisti-
word boundaries, vowel lengthening, to inves- cal learning: the nature of the computations,
tigate additive effects of multiple cues (Saff ran, the complexity of the learning problem, and the
Newport, & Aslin, 1996). It has become increas- role of artificial languages.
ingly clear that sequential statistical cues (such
as transitional probabilities) operate in tandem
WHICH STATISTICS ARE COMPUTED DURING
with other types of regularities in the service
STATISTICAL LEARNING?
of infant word segmentation, including lexi-
cal stress (e.g., Curtin et al., 2005; Johnson & The short answer to this question is that we do
Jusczyk, 2001; Jusczyk, 1999; Jusczyk, Houston, not yet know. There are (at least) three differ-
& Newsome, 1999; Thiessen & Saff ran, 2003, ent ways to approach this problem. The fi rst
2007), known words (Bortfeld, Morgan, is to analyze language corpora to determine
Golinkoff, & Rathbun, 2005), and other rel- which statistics, in principle, might be useful/
evant cues in speech to infants (for a recent necessary to capture language structure. The
review, see Saff ran, Werker, & Werner, 2006). second is to create carefully designed experi-
Moreover, use of sequential statistics appears ments to determine whether appropriately
to be enhanced by the presence of attention- aged learners can make use of the statistics
grabbing infant-directed speech (Thiessen, Hill, in question. These two approaches, in tan-
& Saff ran, 2005). dem, have been quite useful, in that they have
It is thus very much not the case that sequen- shown that infants can keep track of, at mini-
tial statistics operate in a vacuum; this point is mum, the adjacent pairwise probabilities (e.g.,
both implicitly and explicitly made through- Aslin et al., 1998) that corpus analyses suggest
out this burgeoning literature. Moreover, it would be useful for word segmentation (e.g.,
is important to note that many of the types of Swingley, 2005), nonadjacent pairwise proba-
information usually considered in opposition to bilities (e.g., Gomez, 2002), and histogram fre-
statistics are themselves nondeterministic. For quencies (e.g., Maye, Werker, & Gerken, 2002).
example, the lexical stress information upon The latter case is particularly interesting, as it
which English-learning 9-month-olds rely to suggests that infants not only track the indi-
segment bisyllabic words (first syllable stress) vidual frequencies of occurrence of elements,
is itself probabilistic (Cutler & Carter, 1987). but the distribution of those frequencies,
An issue for the field, then, is to decide what distinguishing unimodal and bimodal func-
“counts” as statistical. Are probabilistic regu- tions from one another. Importantly, these
larities that are not sequential still statistical? It functions are useful for discovering speech
seems that the logical answer is yes, in which categories given the statistics of real speech
case the question becomes how to characterize samples (Vallabha, McClelland, Pons, Werker,
the myriad different types of statistical regu- & Amano, 2007; Werker et al., 2007). These
larities in the input, including phonological sorts of statistics, along with others currently
and social cues (Goldstein, King, & West, 2003; described in the adult literature—e.g., clus-
Kuhl, 2007; Kuhl, Tsao, & Liu, 2003). tering words into categories (Mintz, 2002);
With these considerations in mind, let us tracking probabilities of individual word pairs
return to the caricature: statistical learning (Thompson & Newport, 2007)—suggest that
consists of a single computation (pairwise tran- infants may have access to a powerful tool set
sitional probabilities, either adjacent or non- for exploiting the distributional regularities of
adjacent) over simple elements (e.g., phonemes human languages. The exact nature of this tool
or syllables) in a highly artificial language. To set, however, remains underspecified.
WHAT IS STATISTICAL LEARNING 183

The third approach is somewhat different disorders). Making use of expectations is even
and is perhaps best exemplified by connec- more critical in language production, where
tionist models. Rather that trying to specify decisions about future speech acts constantly
which statistics are used by infant learners, the inform current motor actions.
problem can be turned on its head by asking We can thus consider statistical learning as a
what task infants are attempting to perform. component of language processing and use. By
Computational models such as simple recur- anticipating what will come next, infants can
rent networks (SRNs) take as their task the potentially increase the efficiency of their lan-
problem of trying to predict what is coming up guage comprehension—which is necessary given
downstream in the input (Elman, 1990). This the amazing rapidity of speech. Patterns in the
idea—learning by predicting—is consistent input thus can serve to influence this compre-
with a body of recent work in adult language hension, by biasing perceivers toward likely out-
comprehension that has focused on predicting comes. Sequential patterns at numerous grains
during skilled language processing (for a recent of analysis could be construed as providing such
review, see MacDonald & Seidenberg, 2006). biasing information. For example, predicting
For example, event-related potential (ERP) which syllable will come next provides informa-
evidence suggests that adults use the phonology tion about where a word might end, facilitating
of a determiner (e.g., a versus an) to generate word segmentation and, eventually, lexical access.
expectations concerning what noun will come Predicting which word will come downstream
next: consonant-initial nouns follow a, while facilitates lexical access and subsequent sentence-
vowel-initial nouns follow an (DeLong, Urbach, level parsing. Category-level predictions (e.g., that
& Kutas, 2005). Semantic information in the nouns follow adjectives, or that certain types of
verb (e.g., eats) constrains adults’ anticipatory verbs are followed by the complementizer “that”)
eye movements, such that listeners look toward are likely to be particularly germane to syntac-
object pictures that are consistent with the verb tic structure; that is, predicting which word class
(e.g., cake) well before the noun itself occurs should follow another word class.
(Altmann & Kamide, 1999; Kamide, Altmann, Moreover, such predictions might serve as an
& Haywood, 2003); this effect is maintained important learning signal. Connectionist net-
even when the noun pictures are removed works frequently take this approach, learning
(Altmann, 2004). Similarly, adults and young by predicting the next element in the input and
children can use the gender of a determiner assessing the match between the prediction and
(e.g., le vs. la in French) to generate expecta- what actually occurs. Differences between pre-
tions concerning the following noun (Dahan, dicted input and actual input serve as an implicit
Swingley, Tanenhaus, & Magnuson, 2000; error signal, such that weights can be updated
Lew-Williams & Fernald, 2007). to reflect actual occurrences (e.g., Elman, 1990).
It is thus possible that infants, along with Note that this idea is quite different from the
adults and children, exploit patterns in their lin- classic concept of “negative evidence,” wherein
guistic environment—including statistics—to learners are provided with explicit corrections;
make predictions about what will come next, as such evidence is argued to be rarely available
well as to interpret what has already occurred to children, and often not useful even when it
(which is necessary given the vast amount of does occur (Brown, Hanlon, & 1970; Marcus,
ambiguity in natural language). The question 1993; Morgan & Travis, 1989). Implicit negative
then is not which statistics do infants compute, evidence, based on prediction, could provide
but which statistics inform infants’ expecta- corrective information at far more time points,
tions about subsequent input? Efficient tracking facilitating learning relative to explicit negative
of relevant regularities would allow infants to evidence. This intuition is supported by model-
become skilled at rapid language processing, as ing results contrasting different approaches to
observed occurs over the course of typical lan- learning a toy grammar (Spivey-Knowlton &
guage development (in the absence of language Saff ran, 1995).
184 LEARNING MECHANISMS

Despite extensive evidence suggesting that deterministic—that is, 100% probability from
adults generate predictions while comprehend- one word to the next—than when the word
ing language, and a few exciting studies showing sequence is probabilistic—50% probability
similar abilities in early childhood, no stud- from one word to the next (Romberg & Saffran,
ies have yet tested the hypothesis that infants 2009). The targets were names of animals that
generate predictions concerning sequences our 16-month-old participants would already
of sound. We know that infants are of course likely know; the names were paired with pic-
highly attuned to sequential information in tures shown on a large computer screen. These
language, including the statistical knowledge noun targets were preceded by adjectives. Our
described above. However, these tasks are essen- principal manipulation concerned the distri-
tially off-line, with measurement after learning bution of the adjective/noun pairs. Some pairs
has already occurred. We also know that in were deterministic: e.g., pretty always preceded
nonlinguistic tasks, infants appear to generate doggie. Other pairs were probabilistic: e.g., little
on-line predictions. For example, infants gener- preceded kitty on half the trials and fish on the
ate anticipatory eye movements when exposed other half; the specific pairing of nouns and
to patterns of shapes (e.g., Canfield & Haith, adjectives was counterbalanced. Infants lis-
1991; Canfield, Smith, Brezsnyak, & Snow, 1997; tened to several minutes of speech in which this
Haith, Hazan, & Goodman, 1988; Haith, Wass, distributional information was provided: e.g.,
& Adler, 1997), and can even do so when the “This little kitty and one pretty doggie and one
patterns are removed and the screen is blank little fish and . . .”. During this training phase,
(Richardson & Kirkham, 2004). Infants com- infants also watched pictures of animals on the
pute trajectories, anticipating where objects will screen. Each of the animals always appeared in
appear (e.g., Johnson, Amso, & Slemmer, 2003), the same position—right or left—on the screen
and their hand movements suggest computa- and flashed when it was spoken in the accom-
tion of expectancies (e.g., von Hofsten, Vishton, panying audio stream. This gave the infants the
Spelke, Feng, & Rosander, 1998). However, to opportunity to learn the positions of the animal
date, the only infant studies examining on-line pictures while also learning about the adjective/
anticipation in a linguistic task have involved noun distributions.
speech perception (McMurray & Aslin, 2004): Following this brief training, infants were
infants who have learned an arbitrary sound/ tested to see if they generated anticipatory looks
object correspondence can use the sound to as a function of the distributions of the adjec-
predict the object’s location, as indexed by their tive/noun pairs. Unlike the visual stimuli pre-
anticipatory eye movements. sented during training, the screen was blank
We have recently begun to develop a meth- during the test until the onset of the noun when
odology to ask whether infants generate antici- the matching picture would flash on the screen.
pations on-line during sequential linguistic However, the auditory materials were the same
events. To do so, we have borrowed from prior as those presented during exposure. We hypoth-
studies that use eye movements to interrogate esized that if infants were using the adjectives
infant predictions. As a starting point, we began to predict the upcoming nouns, we should see
by examining infant processing of extremely anticipatory looks to the position where the
simple grammatical structures: determiner– noun picture would occur, prior to the noun/
adjective–noun sequences. Of course, our picture event. In particular, we predicted a dif-
studies concern spoken language, but the ference between deterministic pairs and proba-
dependent variable concerns infants’ eyes, so bilistic pairs. In the deterministic pairs, infants
the method requires that the infant link spoken could—in principle—generate an expectation
words with visually presented objects. In our regarding the upcoming noun based on the
first study, we decided to simply ask whether adjective. However, in the probabilistic pairs,
infants show different levels of anticipation no information was available to tell the infant
from word to word when the word sequence is which noun would follow the adjective. Indeed,
WHAT IS STATISTICAL LEARNING 185

as hypothesized, infants only made reliable word boundary information must be learned.
anticipatory eye movements to the target loca- Or was the intent to argue that statistical learn-
tion (on the blank screen) for the deterministic ing functioned for tasks up the linguistic food
pairs using the adjective as a cue to the upcom- chain, including the acquisition of syntax?
ing target noun. For the probabilistic pairs, At the time, we viewed this to be rightly
infants did not reliably fi xate the target location an empirical question and the decade that fol-
until the onset of the noun itself. These results lowed has seen the publication of numerous
suggest that the statistics of the input influenced adult studies focusing on the role of statistics in
infants’ eye movements in response to sequen- syntax learning (Lany, Gomez, & Gerken, 2007;
tial linguistic stimuli, as we would expect if Saff ran, 2001a, 2002; Thompson & Newport,
infants generate on-line expectations about 2007). The broad claim is that, analogous to the
upcoming linguistic events. work in segmentation and other phonological
While this is just an initial study, and the processes, learners can track statistical regulari-
methodology is still under development, these ties across words and/or word classes that afford
results suggest that like adults and young chil- detection of syntactic patterns. Importantly, the
dren, infants can use distributional information presence of multiple correlated cues, such as
in speech to generate expectations about what prosodic or phonological regularities, appears
might come next. On the basis of this view, to facilitate this process (Gerken, Wilson, &
infants are not static computers, using a set of Lewis, 2005; Gomez & Lakusta, 2004; Kaschak
algorithms to perform some set of computations. & Saff ran, 2006; Morgan, Meier, & Newport,
Instead, infants may be engaged in a dynamic 1987), just as observed in word segmentation.
process of using whatever information they can Nevertheless, much remains unknown
amass that might help to generate informative about the manner in which these regularities
predictions, thereby facilitating comprehen- are learned. Some of these issues revolve around
sion and, eventually, production. The goal of the long-standing rules versus statistics debates,
our ensuing research will be to determine how whose roots lie in the fracas that emerged fol-
infants assess which aspects of linguistic input lowing the publication of the original Parallel
are informative and which are not, and to test Distributed Processing volume (Pinker &
the related hypothesis that part of the learning Prince, 1988; Rumelhart & McClelland, 1987).
process entails input-driven error correction. More recent incarnations of this debate have
surrounded artificial language learning stud-
ies involving different types of syllable-level
ARE STATISTICS USED IN HIGHER- LEVEL
computations tracked over streams of speech.
LANGUAGE TASKS?
To what extent do generalizations in these tasks
The initial reports about statistical learning in require rule-level processes (Pena, Bonatti,
infants concerned word segmentation; track- Nespor, & Mehler, 2002) as opposed to statis-
ing the probabilities of syllable co-occurrences. tical processes (Perruchet, Tyler, Galland, &
At the time of the Saff ran et al. (1996) Science Peereman, 2004; Seidenberg, MacDonald, &
paper, it was unclear how broad the claims Saff ran, 2002)? That is, can statistical learning
should be. While the paper itself restricted the operate over primitives that are more abstract
claims to the domain of word segmentation, than physically available syllables or words, or
an accompanying “Perspective” piece broad- is this necessarily the purview of algebraic rules
ened the implications to include critiques of (Marcus, 2000, 2001)?
nativist approaches to syntax acquisition (Bates In order to be useful for grammar acquisi-
& Elman, 1996), and a furor erupted in the tion, the relevant computation(s) must be able to
“Correspondence” pages of subsequent issues. operate over classes or categories. As observed
Was the claim simply that statistical learning 50 years ago by Chomsky (1959), the accept-
played a role in word segmentation—a relatively ability of nonsensical sentences like “Colorless
uncontroversial idea, given that on any theory, green ideas sleep furiously” means that our
186 LEARNING MECHANISMS

representations must supercede word-to-word with which rules occur, and detect violations as
transitions to include transitions between cate- a function of the rules’ likelihood.
gories of words (e.g., nouns, verbs, adverbs, etc.). These possibilities are extremely challenging
The question, again, becomes what “counts” as to disentangle empirically, particularly given
statistical. On some views, only observable ele- the relatively simple structures typically used
ments can be tracked in this fashion (Marcus & in infant language studies—and also given that
Berent, 2003). There are many ways to address patterns can be tracked across various levels of
these representational questions, ranging from representation, from individual exemplars (e.g.,
computational models designed to implement words) to categories (e.g., grammatical classes).
one process or another to adult studies that In a recent study, we began to investigate this
carefully manipulate structures in artificial issue by manipulating the types of ungram-
grammars. Our approach has largely involved matical sentences used at test (Saff ran, 2009).
studies of infant learners, in an attempt to ascer- Twelve-month-old infants were first exposed to
tain which sorts of regularities they detect. a small grammar, written over small lexical cat-
In one set of studies, we exposed 12-month- egories. Critically, some of the transitions in the
old infants to two types of grammatical struc- grammar were high probability (100%) while
tures (Saffran et al., 2008). One grammar others were not (50%). Infants were then tested
structure contained statistical cues to phrase on grammatical sentences versus two different
structure, providing infants with information types of ungrammatical sentences (between-
concerning the types of words that typically co- subjects manipulation); all test sentences were
occurred together. In the other grammar struc- novel. In one group, infants were tested on
ture, these particular cues were absent, though grammatical sentences versus ungrammatical
the grammar was otherwise equally complex. sentences that violated a high-probability tran-
Across several experiments manipulating the sition. In the second group, infants were tested
size of the grammar structure, we consistently on grammatical sentences versus ungrammati-
found the same result: learning only occurred cal sentences that violated a low-probability
when statistical dependencies within phrases transition. Importantly, both types of transi-
were present. These findings mirrored previous tions were equally frequent in the exposure
results with adults and children (Saff ran, 2002), corpus. We hypothesized that if infants were
which suggested that learners’ focus on these sta- responding solely to grammaticality, then dis-
tistical regularities was not specific to language. crimination performance should be equivalent
In infant artificial grammar studies, the crit- across the two groups, as the ungrammatical
ical test contrasts compare infants’ responses to sentences both violated the same number of
familiar (grammatical) versus novel (ungram- transitions and were matched for frequency of
matical) sentences, which violate one or more transitions. However, if infants were attuned to
of the regularities in the language. In the case the probability of the transitions presented dur-
of infant artificial grammar learning studies, ing training, we hypothesized that violations of
while it is clear that infants have learned some- the high-probability transitions should be more
thing about the patterns that differ between the readily detected than the violations of the low-
grammatical and ungrammatical sentences, the probability transitions.
nature of this knowledge remains unclear. One The data were consistent with the latter pre-
possibility is that infants have learned the rules diction: only those infants tested on violations
of the language, which are then violated in the of high-probability transitions discriminated
ungrammatical sentences. Another possibility between the grammatical and ungrammatical
is that infants have learned the (high) probabil- sentences. Importantly, data from a no-exposure
ity sequences of the language, which differ from control group confirmed that these results were
the low probability sequences in the ungram- due to language exposure, not idiosyncratic
matical sentences. A third possibility is a hybrid features of the test items. These data thus sup-
system, in which infants learn the probabilities port the hypothesis that at least when learning
WHAT IS STATISTICAL LEARNING 187

artificial grammars, infants are sensitive to the artificial, simplified materials. This issue is
probabilities with which words (or possibly gaining attention; indeed, a summer workshop
word classes) co-occur. To the extent that infant in 2007 was dedicated to the topic of “Current
language learning is subserved by the same Issues in Language Acquisition: Artificial and
mechanisms as adult language processing, these Statistical Language Learning.” The question
results are consistent with myriad results from is whether the mechanisms that appear to sub-
sentence processing, suggesting that adult com- serve learning in simplified laboratory tasks are
prehenders are attuned to the statistical prop- also operating “in the wild”; that is, given more
erties of syntactic structures at multiple grains naturalistic types of language input. Again, it is
of analysis, from concrete to abstract (e.g., necessarily the case that infant language learn-
MacDonald & Seidenberg, 2006; Seidenberg & ers exploit cues beyond sequential statistics.
MacDonald, 2001). Indeed, it may be the case that sequential sta-
tistics help learners to discover other cues in the
input, which may be specific to an individual
MOVING BEYOND ARTIFICIAL LANGUAGES
language and thus require some initial learning.
One major critique of studies focused on sta- For example, infants in a word segmentation
tistical learning is the artificial nature of the task can use transitional probability statistics
experimental tasks. These methods originated to discover an additional word boundary cue in
from a tradition in cognitive psychology and the input, even one that is entirely novel, which
experimental psycholinguistics, which involved can then be used for subsequent segmentation
the use of artificial language materials (Gomez (e.g., Sahni, Seidenberg, & Seidenberg, 2009).
& Gerken, 2000). Dating back to the 1970s, Across several lines of research, we have
researchers used these miniature languages begun to ask whether statistical learning in these
to test specific hypotheses—with adults— artificial tasks translates into actual language
concerning the types of information used by learning skill. We know that infants do appear
language learners (Braine, 1987; Moeser & to be sensitive to natural language statistics, at
Bregman, 1973; Morgan et al., 1987; Morgan, least in some limited domains. For example,
Meier, & Newport, 1989; Morgan & Newport, infants are known to track phonotactic proba-
1981; Smith, 1966). While these methods were bility information in their native language: the
clearly very artificial, like those used through- likelihood that certain phonemes will co-occur
out cognitive psychology at the time, they per- in particular positions within a word (Friederici
mitted researchers to isolate particular cues & Wessels, 1993; Jusczyk, Friederici, Wessels, &
hypothesized to influence language learning, Svenkerud, 1993; Jusczyk, Luce, & Charles-Luce,
while controlling other potential confounding 1994). Laboratory tasks have demonstrated that
variables. At the same time, the field of implicit infants can make use of these phonotactic prob-
learning developed parallel methodologies abilities when segmenting novel words from
using artificial grammars, but with a focus pri- fluent speech (Mattys & Jusczyk, 2001; Mattys,
marily on learning and memory rather than on Jusczyk, Luce, & Morgan, 1999) and when map-
the acquisition of structures found in natural ping novel labels to objects (Graf Estes, Edwards,
languages (Allen & Reber, 1980; Reber, 1967, & Saffran, 2009). Do artificial language statistics
1993). Despite largely separate literatures dur- operate in a similar way?
ing the 1980s and 1990s, these two literatures To date, we have pursued three different
are beginning to converge in an exciting way, approaches to this question. The first approach
generating testable predictions that constrain has involved experiments in which we ask
theories of both implicit learning and language whether the “words” from our artificial speech
acquisition (Perruchet & Pacton, 2006). streams are treated in a word-like fashion by
Nevertheless, one can critique both infants. For example, 8-month-old infants
literatures—artificial language learning and appear to integrate the nonsense words from
implicit learning—for their use of highly our speech streams into English test sentences
188 LEARNING MECHANISMS

(Saff ran, 2001b). In related work, we found that typical sample, performance on the artificial
18-month-olds more readily mapped these language task was correlated with standardized
nonsense words to novel meanings (objects) measures of English vocabulary, providing an
than part-words, which violated the statistics of additional link between statistical learning skill
the artificial speech stream (Graf Estes, Evans, and native language proficiency (Evans et al.,
Alibali, & Saff ran, 2007). Infants can also go 2009).
from segmentation to syntax, first finding non- The third source of evidence required us
sense words in fluent speech and then learning to move away from artificial language meth-
about their order, as required for natural lan- odologies. To what extent is statistical learn-
guage learning (Saff ran & Wilson, 2003). Across ing performance tied to the use of these highly
all these studies, the results support the hypoth- unnatural structures? The statistical learning
esis that infants are doing the very things with studies performed in our laboratory and else-
these sound sequences that we would expect where typically entail speech that is monotone,
infants acquiring language to do. isochronous (that is, devoid of variations in
The second line of research is focused on rhythm), and synthesized. We have manipulated
individual differences in natural language these features to some extent, but always within
acquisition. Approximately 5%–10% of elemen- the purview of artificially devised systems. For
tary school-aged children are diagnosed with example, we manipulated the pitches of our arti-
specific language impairment (SLI): despite ficial speech streams to mimic infant-directed
nonverbal IQ in the normal range, their lan- pitch contours versus adult-directed pitch
guage skills lag significantly behind their peers. contours; the results suggested that statistical
We hypothesized that if individual differences learning was facilitated by the expansive pitch
in statistical learning abilities are related to the contours of infant-directed speech, likely due
emergence of SLI, individuals with SLI should to enhanced attention (Thiessen et al., 2005).
find our artificial tasks more challenging than Related work suggests that infants show better
an age- and nonverbal IQ-matched comparison memory for sung word sequences than for spo-
group (Evans, Saff ran, & Robe-Torres, 2009). ken word sequences (Thiessen & Saffran, 2009).
We compared two groups of grade-school chil- Multiple studies have also examined the inter-
dren, those with a diagnosis of SLI and those action between sequential statistics and lexical
with age-appropriate language skills, on an stress cues in artificial language segmentation
incidental artificial language word segmenta- tasks, showing that the importance of sequential
tion task previously used with children (Saff ran statistical cues varies as a function of the avail-
et al., 1997). As predicted, the children with ability of other cues and the age of the learner
SLI evinced poorer performance on this task, (e.g., Johnson & Jusczyk, 2001; Thiessen &
though they caught up with additional expo- Saffran, 2003). We have also used natural speech
sure. Interestingly, given the language focus of produced like a synthesizer in various stud-
this diagnosis, the children with SLI also per- ies (e.g., Graf Estes et al., 2007). However, these
formed more poorly than comparison children studies all used artificial languages, in the sense
on an analogous statistical learning task using that the words are nonsense and the materials
nonlinguistic tone sequences (Saff ran, Johnson, were created without all the variability inherent
Aslin, & Newport, 1999). Thus, school-aged in natural speech. Can infants make use of sta-
children with a diagnosed language disorder tistics in natural language segmentation tasks?
found both linguistic and nonlinguistic statisti- We are currently addressing this ques-
cal learning tasks particularly challenging. Th is tion using a hybrid natural/artificial language
finding is consistent with prior research testing design, in which the materials are spoken nat-
adolescents with SLI on a different nonlinguis- urally and the words are all from Italian, but
tic implicit learning task, visual serial reaction the words were chosen to exemplify specific sta-
time (Tomblin, Mainela-Arnold, & Zhang, tistical distributions (Pelucchi, Hay, & Saff ran,
2007). Moreover, we found that even within our 2009). In this study, 8-month-old infants were
WHAT IS STATISTICAL LEARNING 189

exposed to sentences produced by a native cues as a function of syllable position within a


Italian speaker, with natural infant-directed word). Infants can make use of such regularities
prosody. Critically, the sentences were care- on-line and given natural language input.
fully designed to contain: (1) target words that Is this interest in statistical learning an indi-
contained high-probability syllable sequences cator of the return of flat-earth empiricism? The
(relative to the exposure corpus) and (2) foil answer, we believe, is very much no. In order
words that occurred equally often but which to make use of all of this information, infants
contained low-probability syllable sequences. must come to the task of language learning
Importantly, unlike our prior studies, these with learning mechanisms that are “factory-
materials were naturally produced, with all the installed”; such learning is likely part and
variability inherent in Italian speech—which is parcel of neural systems. In this sense, these
of course foreign to our monolingual Wisconsin mechanisms—including both statistical learn-
infants. Nevertheless, infants successfully dis- ing mechanisms and other types of learning
criminated the target words from novel Italian mechanisms—are innate. Rather than a nativ-
words, replicating Jusczyk and Aslin’s (1995) ism of specific knowledge, however, this claim
seminal study with a cross-language design concerns the nativism of learning mechanisms,
(English learners, Italian speech). Most germane including categorization abilities and perceptual
to the issue of statistical learning in natural systems that are a good fit to incoming linguis-
languages, infants also successfully discrimi- tic information. Notably, the linguistic informa-
nated the high-probability target words from tion may be structured to provide this good fit.
low-probability foil words, despite the fact that Human learning abilities potentially play a role
both types of words occurred equally often in in structuring human languages, as suggested
the speech stream. These results provide a con- by studies contrasting the acquisition of pos-
ceptual replication of the infant results from the sible versus impossible languages, and human
artificial language learning literature, but with versus nonhuman learners (e.g., Newport &
natural language materials. We can now con- Aslin, 2004; Newport, Hauser, Spaepen, &
tinue on to examine how other cues (e.g., lexical Aslin, 2004; Saff ran, 2002, 2003; Saff ran et al.,
stress) interact with sequential statistical cues 2008; Saff ran & Thiessen, 2003). To the extent
in natural language segmentation tasks. that this is the case, we might expect learning
mechanisms to operate over stimuli that are not
solely linguistic, but which are similarly struc-
WHAT IS STATISTICAL LEARNING,
tured across important stimulus attributes (e.g.,
AND WHAT STATISTICAL LEARNING
Kelly & Martin, 1994; Kirkham, this volume;
IS NOT: LOOKING AHEAD
Kirkham, Slemmer, & Johnson, 2002; Saff ran
The answer to the question of what statistical et al., 1999; Saff ran, Pollak, Seibel, & Shkolnik,
learning is and what it is not remains in the 2007; Saff ran & Thiessen, 2007).
eye of the beholder. Empirical results are rap- To better address these issues, I would expect
idly rolling in, and these should serve to dis- future research to focus on a few specific ques-
ambiguate the myriad views concerning these tions. One is the nature of generalization. Under
learning mechanisms. If one thing is clear, it which circumstances do infants generalize, and
is this: statistical learning is not just a single what data do infants take as relevant for their
computation over a single set of primitives. generalizations (for two recent elegant exam-
Learners, including infants, appear to be capa- ples, see Gerken, 2004, 2006). A related ques-
ble of tracking multiple levels of regularities in tion concerns categorization: when do infants
complex input. Some of these regularities are group linguistic elements into categories, and
the types of sequential patterns we traditionally what kinds of computations can be performed
think of as “statistical”; others are still statisti- across these categories? Dynamic learning sys-
cal, but are more correlational (e.g., phonolog- tems should cascade, such that the output of one
ical regularities, such as placement of stress learning process serves as input to another—or
190 LEARNING MECHANISMS

to itself. Exciting new work has begun to focus Altmann, G. T. M., & Kamide, Y. (1999).
on how these newly identified learning pro- Incremental interpretation at verbs: Restricting
cesses work together in this fashion (for a recent the domain of subsequent reference. Cognition,
review, see Gómez, 2006; this volume). 73(3), 247–264.
I would also anticipate continued interest Aslin, R. N., Saff ran, J. R., & Newport, E. L. (1998).
Computation of conditional probability sta-
in studying individual differences in statisti-
tistics by 8-month-old infants. Psychological
cal learning processes, both as a way to better Science, 9, 321–324.
understand how typical learning unfolds and Bates, E., & Elman, J. (1996). Learning rediscov-
to examine potential causes for language delays ered. Science, 274(5294), 1849–1850.
and disorders. There have been numerous Bloomfield, L. (1933). Language. New York: Holt.
recent studies that have taken a longitudinal Bortfeld, H., Morgan, J. L., Golinkoff, R. M., &
approach, predicting native language outcomes Rathbun, K. (2005). Mommy and me: Familiar
from language learning and processing tasks in names help launch babies into speech-stream
infancy (Fernald, Perfors, & Marchman, 2006; segmentation. Psychological Science, 16(4),
Newman, Bernstein Ratner, A. M. Jusczyk, 298–304.
P. W. Jusczyk, & Dow, 2006; Tsao, Liu, & Kuhl, Braine, M. D. S. (1987). What is learned in acquir-
ing word classes—A step toward an acquisition
2004). These, in concert with emerging studies
theory. In B. MacWhinney (Ed.), Mechanisms
using language-disordered children and adults of language acquisition (pp. 65–87). Hillsdale,
(Evans et al., 2009; Plante, Gomez, & Gerken, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
2002; Tomblin et al., 2007), hold great potential Brown, R., & Hanlon, C. (1970). Derivational
for uncovering the manner in which language complexity and order of acquisition in child
learning actually unfolds across development, speech. In J. R. Hayes (Ed.), Cognition and
and, eventually, possible hope for novel inter- the development of language (pp. 11–54). New
ventions that target the learning process. York: Wiley.
Canfield, R. L., & Haith, M. M. (1991). Young
infants’ visual expectations for symmetric and
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS asymmetric stimulus sequences. Developmental
Psychology, 27, 198–208.
Preparation of this manuscript was supported by a
Canfield, R. L., Smith, E. G., Brezsnyak, M. P., &
grant to J.R.S. from NICHD (R01HD37466). I am
Snow, K. L. (1997). Information processing
grateful to Julia Evans, Katie Graf Estes, Jessica
through the first year of life: a longitudinal
Hay, Bruna Pelucchi, Alexa Romberg, Sarah
study using the visual expectation paradigm.
Sahni, and the members of the UW-Madison
Monographs of the Society for Research in Child
Infant Learning Lab for many helpful discussions
Development, 62(2), 1–145.
about these issues.
Charniak, E. (1993). Statistical language learning.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
REFERENCES Chater, N., & Redington, M. (1999). Connectionism,
theories of learning, and syntax acquisition:
Allen, J., & Seidenberg, M. S. (1999). The emergence Where do we stand? Journal of Child Language,
of grammaticality in connectionist networks. 26(1), 226–232.
Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Chomsky, N. (1959). Review of B. F. Skinner’s
Allen, R., & Reber, A. S. (1980). Very long term Verbal learning. Language, 35, 26–58.
memory for tacit knowledge. Cognition, 8(2), Christiansen, M. H., & Curtin, S. (1999). Transfer
175–185. of learning: Rule acquisition or statistical
Altmann, G. T. M. (2002). Statistical learning in learning? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 3(8),
infants. Proceedings of the National Academy of 289–290.
Sciences USA, 99(24), 15250–15251. Curtin, S., Mintz, T. H., Byrd, D., Do, A. H.
Altmann, G. T. M. (2004). Language-mediated eye J., Dominguez, L., & Johansen, A. (2001).
movements in the absence of a visual world: Coarticulatory cues enhance infants’ rec-
The ‘blank screen paradigm’. Cognition, 93(2), ognition of syllable sequences in speech.
B79–B87. Proceedings of the Boston University Conference
WHAT IS STATISTICAL LEARNING 191

on Language Development. Somerville, MA: Gómez, R. (2006). Dynamically guided learning.


Cascadilla Press. In Y. Munakata & M. H. Johnson (Eds.),
Curtin, S., Mintz, T. H., & Christiansen, M. H. Processes of change in brain and cognitive
(2005). Stress changes the representational development: Attention and performance XXI.
landscape: Evidence from word segmentation. Oxford: University Press.
Cognition, 96(3), 233–262. Gomez, R. L., & Gerken, L. (2000). Infant artificial
Cutler, A., & Carter, D. M. (1987). The predomi- language learning and language acquisition.
nance of strong initial syllables in the English Trends in Cognitive Science, 4(5), 178–186.
vocabulary. Computer Speech and Language, 2, Gomez, R. L., & Lakusta, L. (2004). A first step in
133–142. form-based category abstraction by 12-month-
Dahan, D., Swingley, D., Tanenhaus, M. K., & old infants. Developmental Science, 7(5),
Magnuson, J. S. (2000). Linguistic gender and 567–580.
spoken-word recognition in French. Journal of Goodsitt, J. V., Morgan, J. L., & Kuhl, P. K. (1993).
Memory and Language, 42(4), 465–480. Perceptual strategies in prelingual speech seg-
DeLong, K. A., Urbach, T. P., & Kutas, M. (2005). mentation. Journal of Child Language, 20(2),
Probabilistic word pre-activation during 229–252.
language comprehension inferred from elec- Graf Estes, K., Edwards, J., & Saff ran, J. R. (2009).
trical brain activity. Nature Neuroscience, 8(8), Phonotactic constraints on infant word learn-
1117–1121. ing. Manuscript submitted for editorial
Elman, J. L. (1990). Finding structure in time. review.
Cognitive Science, 14(2), 179–211. Graf Estes, K., Evans, J. L., Alibali, M. W., &
Evans, J., Saff ran, J. R., & Robe-Torres, K. (2009). Saff ran, J. R. (2007). Can infants map mean-
Statistical learning in children with Specific ing to newly segmented words? Statistical seg-
Language Impairments. Journal of Speech, mentation and word learning. Psychological
Language, & Hearing Research, 52, 321–335. Science, 18(3), 254–260.
Fernald, A., Perfors, A., & Marchman, V. A. (2006). Haith, M. M., Hazan, C., & Goodman, G. S. (1988).
Picking up speed in understanding: Speech Expectation and anticipation of dynamic
processing efficiency and vocabulary growth visual events by 3.5-month-old babies. Child
across the 2nd year. Developmental Psychology, Development, 59(2), 467–479.
42(1), 98–116. Haith, M. M., Wass, T. S., & Adler, S. A. (1997).
Friederici, A. D., & Wessels, J. M. (1993). Phonot- Infant visual expectations: Advances and
actic knowledge of word boundaries and its issues. Monographs of the Society for Research
use in infant speech perception. Perception & in Child Development, 62(2), 150–160.
Psychophysics, 54(3), 287–295. Harris, Z. S. (1951). Methods in structural linguis-
Gallistel, C. R. (1990). The organization of learn- tics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
ing. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Hauser, M. D., Newport, E. L., & Aslin, R. N.
Gerken, L. (2004). Nine-month-olds extract struc- (2001). Segmentation of the speech stream in
tural principles required for natural language. a non-human primate: statistical learning in
Cognition, 93(3), B89–B96. cotton-top tamarins. Cognition, 78(3), B53–B64.
Gerken, L. (2006). Decisions, decisions: Infant Johnson, E. K., & Jusczyk, P. W. (2001). Word seg-
language learning when multiple generaliza- mentation by 8-month-olds: When speech cues
tions are possible. Cognition, 98(3), B67–B74. count more than statistics. Journal of Memory
Gerken, L., Wilson, R., & Lewis, W. (2005). Infants and Language, 44(4), 548–567.
can use distributional cues to form syntactic Johnson, S. P., Amso, D., & Slemmer, J. A. (2003).
categories. Journal of Child Language, 32(2), Development of object concepts in infancy:
249–268. Evidence for early learning in an eye-tracking
Goldstein, M. H., King, A. P., & West, M. J. paradigm. Proceedings of the National Academy
(2003). Social interaction shapes babbling: of Sciences, 100(18), 10568–10573.
Testing parallels between birdsong and speech. Jusczyk, P. W. (1999). How infants begin to extract
Proceedings of the National Academy of Science words from speech. Trends in Cognitive Science,
USA, 100(13), 8030–8035. 3(9), 323–328.
Gomez, R. (2002). Variability and detection of Jusczyk, P. W., & Aslin, R. N. (1995). Infants’
invariant structure. Psychological Science, 13(5), detection of the sound patterns of words in flu-
431–436. ent speech. Cognitive Psychology, 29, 1–23.
192 LEARNING MECHANISMS

Jusczyk, P. W., Friederici, A. D., Wessels, J. M., and D.C. Plaut (1999). Trends in Cognitive
& Svenkerud, V. Y. (1993). Infants’ sensitiv- Sciences, 3(5), 168–170.
ity to the sound patterns of native language Marcus, G. F. (1999b). Reply to Seidenberg and
words. Journal of Memory and Language, 32(3), Elman. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 3(8),
402–420. 289–289.
Jusczyk, P. W., Houston, D. M., & Newsome, M. Marcus, G. F. (2000). Pabiku and Ga Ti Ga: Two
(1999). The beginnings of word segmentation in mechanisms infants use to learn about the
English-learning infants. Cognitive Psychology, world. Current Directions in Psychological
39(3–4), 159–207. Science, 9(5), 145–147.
Jusczyk, P. W., Luce, P. A., & Charles-Luce, J. Marcus, G. F. (2001). The algebraic mind: Inte-
(1994). Infants’ sensitivity to phonotactic pat- grating connectionism and cognitive science.
terns in the native language. Journal of Memory Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
and Language, 33(5), 630–645. Marcus, G. F., & Berent, I. (2003). Are there lim-
Kamide, Y., Altmann, G. T. M., & Haywood, S. its to statistical learning? Science, 300(5616),
L. (2003). The time-course of prediction in 53–55.
incremental sentence processing: Evidence Mattys, S. L., & Jusczyk, P. W. (2001). Phonotactic
from anticipatory eye movements. Journal of cues for segmentation of fluent speech by
Memory and Language, 49(1), 133–159. infants. Cognition, 78(2), 91–121.
Kaschak, M. P., & Saff ran, J. R. (2006). Idiomatic Mattys, S. L., Jusczyk, P. W., Luce, P. A., & Morgan,
syntactic constructions and language learning. J. L. (1999). Phonotactic and prosodic effects
Cognitive Science, 30(1), 43–63. on word segmentation in infants. Cognitive
Kelly, M. H., & Martin, S. (1994). Domain-general Psychology, 38(4), 465–494.
abilities applied to domain-specific tasks: Maye, J., Werker, J. F., & Gerken, L. (2002). Infant
Sensitivity to probabilities in perception, cog- sensitivity to distributional information can
nition, and language. Lingua, 92, 105–140. affect phonetic discrimination. Cognition,
Kirkham, N. Z., Slemmer, J. A., & Johnson, S. P. 82(3), B101–B111.
(2002). Visual statistical learning in infancy: McClelland, J. L., McClelland, J. L., & Plaut, D. C.
Evidence for a domain general learning mech- (1999). Does generalization in infant learning
anism. Cognition, 83(2), B35–B42. implicate abstract algebra-like rules? Trends in
Kuhl, P. K. (2007). Is speech learning ‘gated’ by Cognitive Sciences, 3(5), 166.
the social brain? Developmental Science, 10(1), McMurray, B., & Aslin, R. N. (2004). Anticipatory
110–120. eye movements reveal infants’ auditory and
Kuhl, P. K., Tsao, F. M., & Liu, H. M. (2003). visual categories. Infancy, 6(2), 203–229.
Foreign-language experience in infancy: Mintz, T. H. (2002). Category induction from
Effects of short-term exposure and social distributional cues in an artificial language.
interaction on phonetic learning. Proceedings Memory & Cognition, 30(5), 678–686.
of the National Academy of Sciences, 100(15), Mintz, T. H., Newport, E. L., & Bever, T. G.
9096–9101. (2002). The distributional structure of gram-
Lany, J., Gomez, R. L., & Gerken, L. (2007). The matical categories in speech to young children.
role of prior experience in language acquisi- Cognitive Science, 26(4), 393–424.
tion. Cognitive Science, 31(3), 481–507. Moeser, S. D., & Bregman, A. S. (1973). Imagery
Lew-Williams, C., & Fernald, A. (2007). Young and language acquisition. Journal of Verbal
children learning Spanish make rapid use of Learning and Verbal Behavior, 12, 91–98.
grammatical gender in spoken word recogni- Morgan, J. L., Meier, R. P., & Newport, E. L. (1987).
tion. Psychological Science, 18(3), 193–198. Structural packaging in the input to language
MacDonald, M. C., & Seidenberg, M. S. (Eds.). learning: Contributions of prosodic and mor-
(2006). Constraint satisfaction accounts of phological marking of phrases to the acquisi-
lexical and sentence comprehension. London: tion of language. Cognitive Psychology, 19(4),
Elsevier. 498–550.
Marcus, G. F. (1993). Negative evidence in lan- Morgan, J. L., Meier, R. P., & Newport, E. L. (1989).
guage acquisition. Cognition, 46(1), 53–85. Facilitating the acquisition of syntax with cross-
Marcus, G. F. (1999a). Connectionism: With or sentential cues to phrase structure. Journal of
without rules? Response to J.L. McClelland Memory and Language, 28(3), 360–374.
WHAT IS STATISTICAL LEARNING 193

Morgan, J. L., & Newport, E. L. (1981). The role Reber, A. S. (1993). Implicit learning and tacit
of constituent structure in the induction of an knowledge: An essay on the cognitive uncon-
artificial language. Journal of Verbal Learning scious. New York: Oxford University Press.
& Verbal Behavior, 20(1), 67–85. Richardson, D. C., & Kirkham, N. Z. (2004).
Morgan, J. L., & Travis, L. L. (1989). Limits on neg- Multimodal events and moving locations: Eye
ative information in language input. Journal of movements of adults and 6-month-olds reveal
Child Language, 16, 531–552. dynamic spatial indexing. Journal of Exper-
Newman, R., Bernstein Ratner, N., Jusczyk, A. M., imental Psychology: General, 133(1), 46–62.
Jusczyk, P. W., & Dow, K. A. (2006). Infants’ Rohde, D. L., & Plaut, D. C. (1999). Simple recur-
early ability to segment the conversational rent networks can distinguish non-occurring
speech signal predicts later language develop- from ungrammatical sentences given appropri-
ment: A retrospective analysis. Developmental ate task structure: Reply to Marcus. Cognition,
Psychology, 42(4), 643–655. 73(3), 297–300.
Newport, E. L., & Aslin, R. N. (2004). Learning at a Romberg, A. R., & Saff ran, J. R. (2009). Statistical
distance I: Statistical learning of non-adjacent regularities influence on-line processing in
dependencies. Cognitive Psychology, 48(2), infancy. Manuscript under editorial review.
127–162. Rumelhart D. E., & McClelland J. L. (1986).
Newport, E. L., Hauser, M. D., Spaepen, G., & On learning past tenses of English verbs.
Aslin, R. N. (2004). Learning at a distance II: In McClelland, J. L. and Rumelhart, D. E.
Statistical learning of non-adjacent depen- (Eds), Parallel Distributed Processing: Vol.
dencies in a non-human primate. Cognitive 2: Psychological and Biological Models.
Psychology, 49(2), 85–117. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Pelucchi, B., Hay, J. F., & Saff ran, J. R. (2009). Saff ran, J. R. (2001a). The use of predictive depen-
Statistical learning in a natural language by dencies in language learning. Journal of
8-month-old infants. Child Development, Memory and Language, 44(4), 493.
manuscript in press. Saff ran, J. R. (2001b). Words in a sea of sounds: the
Pena, M., Bonatti, L. L., Nespor, M., & Mehler, J. output of infant statistical learning. Cognition,
(2002). Signal-driven computations in speech 81(2), 149–169.
processing. Science, 298(5593), 604. Saff ran, J. R. (2002). Constraints on statistical
Perruchet, P., & Pacton, S. (2006). Implicit learn- language learning. Journal of Memory and
ing and statistical learning: one phenomenon, Language, 47(1), 172–196.
two approaches. Trends in Cognitive Science, Saff ran, J. R. (2003). Statistical language learn-
10(5), 233–238. ing: Mechanisms and constraints. Current
Perruchet, P., Tyler, M. D., Galland, N., & Directions in Psychological Science, 12(4),
Peereman, R. (2004). Learning nonadja- 110–114.
cent dependencies: No need for algebraic- Saff ran, J. R. (submitted). Weighing their words:
like computations. Journal of Experimental Infants track statistics in artificial grammars.
Psychology—General, 133(4), 573–583. Manuscript under editorial review.
Pinker, S., & Prince, A. (1988). On language and Saff ran, J. R., Aslin, R. N., & Newport, E. L. (1996).
connectionism: Analysis of a parallel distrib- Statistical learning by 8-month-old infants.
uted processing model of language acquisition. Science, 274(5294), 1926–1928.
Cognition, 28(1), 73–193. Saff ran, J. R., Hauser, M., Seibel, R., Kapfhamer,
Plante, E., Gomez, R., & Gerken, L. (2002). J., Tsao, F., & Cushman, F. (2008). Cross-
Sensitivity to word order cues by normal and species differences in the capacity to acquire
language/learning disabled adults. Journal of language: Grammatical pattern learning by
Communicative Disorders, 35(5), 453–462. human infants and monkeys. Cognition, 107,
Reali, F., & Christiansen, M. H. (2005). Uncovering 479–500.
the richness of the stimulus: Structure depen- Saff ran, J. R., Johnson, E. K., Aslin, R. N., &
dence and indirect statistical evidence. Newport, E. L. (1999). Statistical learning of
Cognitive Science, 29(6), 1007–1028. tone sequences by human infants and adults.
Reber, A. S. (1967). Implicit learning of artificial Cognition, 70(1), 27–52.
grammars. Journal of Verbal Learning & Verbal Saff ran, J. R., Newport, E. L., & Aslin, R. N. (1996).
Behavior, 6, 855–863. Word segmentation: The role of distributional
194 LEARNING MECHANISMS

cues. Journal of Memory and Language, 35(4), feedback. In Proceedings of the 17th Annual
606–621. Conference of the Cognitive Science Society.
Saff ran, J. R., Newport, E. L., Aslin, R. N., Tunick, Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
R. A., & Barrueco, S. (1997). Incidental lan- Swingley, D. (2005). Statistical clustering and the
guage learning: Listening (and learning) out contents of the infant vocabulary. Cognitive
of the corner of your ear. Psychological Science, Psychology, 50(1), 86–132.
8(2), 101–105. Thiessen, E. D., Hill, E. A., & Saff ran, J. R. (2005).
Saff ran, J. R., Pollak, S. D., Seibel, R. L., & Shkolnik, Infant-directed speech facilitates word seg-
A. (2007). Dog is a dog is a dog: Infant rule mentation. Infancy, 7(1), 53–71.
learning is not specific to language. Cognition, Thiessen, E. D., & Saff ran, J. R. (2003). When cues
105, 669–680. collide: Use of stress and statistical cues to
Saff ran, J. R., & Thiessen, E. D. (2003). Pattern word boundaries by 7- to 9-month-old infants.
induction by infant language learners. Developmental Psychology, 39(4), 706–716.
Developmental Psychology, 39(3), 484–494. Thiessen, E. D., & Saff ran, J. R. (2007). Learning
Saff ran, J. R., & Thiessen, E. D. (2007). Domain- to learn: Infants’ acquisition of stress-based
general learning capacities. In E. Hoff & M. strategies for word segmentation. Language
Shatz (Eds.), Blackwell handbook of language Learning and Development, 3(1), 73–100.
development. (pp. 68–86). Malden, MA: Thiessen, E. D., & Saff ran, J. R. (2009). How the
Blackwell Publishing. melody facilitates the message, and vice versa,
Saff ran, J. R., Werker, J. F., & Werner, L. A. (2006). in infant learning and memory. Proceedings of
The infant’s auditory world: Hearing, speech, the New York Academy of Sciences, manuscript
and the beginnings of language. In D. Kuhn & in press.
R. S. Siegler (Eds.), Handbook of child psychol- Thompson, S. P., & Newport, E. L. (2007).
ogy: Vol. 2, Cognition, perception, and language Statistical learning of syntax: The role of tran-
(6th ed., pp. 58–108). Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley sitional probability. Language Learning and
& Sons. Development, 3(1), 1–42.
Saff ran, J. R., & Wilson, D. P. (2003). From sylla- Tomblin, J. B., Mainela-Arnold, E., & Zhang, X.
bles to syntax: Multilevel statistical learning by (2007). Procedural learning in adolescents
12-month-old infants. Infancy, 4(2), 273–284. with and without specific language impair-
Sahni, S. D., Seidenberg, M. S., & Saff ran, J. R. ment. Language Learning and Development, 3,
(2009). Connecting cues: Overlapping regu- 269–293.
larities support cue discovery in infancy. Tsao, F.-M., Liu, H.-M., & Kuhl, P. K. (2004). Speech
Manuscript submitted for publication. perception in infancy predicts language devel-
Seidenberg, M. S., & Elman, J. L. (1999). Networks opment in the second year of life: A longitudinal
are not ‘hidden rules.’ Trends in Cognitive study. Child Development, 75(4), 1067–1084.
Sciences, 3(8), 288–289. Vallabha, G. K., McClelland, J. L., Pons, F., Werker,
Seidenberg, M. S., & MacDonald, M. C. (2001). J. F., & Amano, S. (2007). Unsupervised learn-
Constraint satisfaction in language acquisi- ing of vowel categories from infant-directed
tion and processing. Westport, CT: Ablex speech. Proceedings of the National Academy of
Publishing. Sciences USA, 104(33), 13273–13278.
Seidenberg, M. S., MacDonald, M. C., & Saff ran, J. von Hofsten, C., Vishton, P., Spelke, E. S., Feng,
R. (2002). Does grammar start where statistics Q., & Rosander, K. (1998). Predictive action
stop? Science, 298, 553–554. in infancy: Tracking and reaching for moving
Smith, K. H. (1966). Grammatical intrusions in objects. Cognition, 67(3), 255–285.
the recall of structured letter pairs: Mediated Werker, J. F., Pons, F., Dietrich, C., Kajikawa, S., Fais,
transfer or position learning? Journal of L., & Amano, S. (2007). Infant-directed speech
Experimental Psychology, 72, 580–588. supports phonetic category learning in English
Spivey-Knowlton, M., & Saff ran, J. R. (1995). and Japanese. Cognition, 103(1), 147–162.
Inducing a grammar without an explicit Yang, C. (2004). Universal grammar, statistics, or
teacher: Incremental distributed prediction both. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 451–456.
CHAP TER 10
Processing Constraints on Learning

Rebecca Gómez

If research on infant cognition has taught as a function of development is a challenging


us anything it is that very young infants are problem.
equipped with precocious abilities, ranging As with work on object perception, there
from their capacity to reason about physical has been a spate of recent work suggesting
events in the world (Baillargeon, 1987; Kellman that infants are extremely facile learners (e.g.,
& Spelke, 1983; Xu & Garcia, 2008), to their Gómez & Gerken, 2000; Kirkham, Slemmer,
understanding of and ability to make infer- & Johnson, 2002; Saff ran, Aslin, & Newport,
ences based on number (McCrink & Wynn, 1996a). Though the evidence is persuasive, the
2007; Wynn, 1992; Xu & Garcia, 2008) to their story is not simple. Showing that infants are
rational ability to attribute goals to agents (Bíró, fast learners is an initial step, but we need to
Csibra, & Gergely, 2007; Gergely, Nádasdy, know more about the mechanics of learning.
Csibra, & Bíró 1999) and in their understanding Challenges have to do with determining how
of intentions of others (Woodward, 2005). In learning is constrained—how learners home in
the beginning of infancy work, the early onset on the “right” information, whether they can
of an ability was often associated with innately do so under noisy learning conditions, and how
given expectations or constraints, but with they build on prior knowledge to generalize to
increased study on what develops the picture is more complex forms. We also need to under-
changing. For instance, the fi nding that infants stand how learners use memory in generalizing
can perceive the persistence of partly occluded to cases that are similar, but not identical, to
objects at 4months of age was initially taken previous learning experiences.
as evidence for innate knowledge of principles To this end, I will discuss three types of pro-
governing objects (Kellman & Spelke, 1983). cessing constraints on learning. The first type
However, research since then shows that the of constraint arises from the learning process
ability to perceive the unity of occluded objects itself. The other two constraints arise from two
is experientially driven (Johnson, Davidow, naturally occurring memory processes: con-
Hall-Haro, & Frank, 2008) and develops over solidation and reconsolidation. With respect
time (e.g., Johnson & Aslin, 1995; Johnson to learning constraints, I will discuss research
et al., 2003). Thus, if there is a lesson to be from my laboratory suggesting that learning
learned, it is that the question of what develops is a dynamically guided process, arising in the
is a complicated one. Determining the abilities interaction of internal and external pressures,
with which infants come equipped, their mech- and one that is fairly robust with respect to
anisms for obtaining and retaining knowledge, noisy input. Moreover, learners, and the struc-
and whether and how these abilities change ture they can acquire, change as a function of

195
196 LEARNING MECHANISMS

experience. With respect to memory processes incidentally when their presentation is second-
instrumental in learning, one set of findings I ary to a primary task (Saff ran, Newport, Aslin,
will describe demonstrates a type of memory Tunick, & Barrueco, 1997). However, immediate
consolidation occurring with sleep, one that sequential dependencies are not the only ones
results in generalization to novel cases. Another language learners must acquire. Many depen-
set of findings demonstrates how the process dencies occur across longer distances, especially
of memory reconsolidation enables memory in language. Some examples are dependencies
change. Both memory processes are important between auxiliaries and inflectional morphemes
for understanding how children sustain sensi- (e.g., is quickly running), and between nouns
tivity to prior knowledge while incorporating and verbs in number and tense agreement (The
new information. In contrast to “knowledge” boys in the tree are laughing). If the tendency to
constraints traditionally proposed in the liter- track adjacent structure is a default, what might
ature on development and learning, the con- tune learners into more remote dependencies in
straints discussed here arise naturally from the sequential structure such as those separated by
mechanics of learning and memory processes intervening words?
themselves. My colleagues and I have investigated this
question by familiarizing infants with an artifi-
cial language that can be learned only if infants
CONSTRAINTS ARISING FROM detect nonadjacent dependencies (Gómez, 2002;
THE LEARNING PROCESS Gómez & Maye, 2005). Infants were exposed to
one of two versions of an artificial language and
Choosing among Multiple Possibilities
were tested with sentences from each language
A particularly vexing problem has to do with such that a grammatical sentence for one group
how infants choose among multiple types of of infants was ungrammatical for the other
structure. One proposal is that learners are con- group (this two-version design is used in all of
strained to prefer certain kinds of information the artificial language studies discussed here).
over others. Although such biases may exist, it Version 1 sentences followed the patterns aXb
would be a mistake to ignore other constraints or cXd (e.g., pel-wadim-jic, vot-kicey-rud). In
on the learning process, including informa- Version 2, the relationship between the first
tion in the environment itself, or the possibil- and third elements was reversed such that pel
ity that learning may arise in the interaction of sentences ended with rud, and vot sentences
the joint pressures from internal and external ended with jic (aXd : pel-wadim-rud, cXb: vot-
constraints. For instance, there is good reason kicey-jic) (see Figure 10.1). The a, b, c, d, and X
to think that the ability to track dependencies elements were restricted to the same positions
between adjacent elements in sequential struc- in the two languages and adjacent dependen-
ture may be a default in learning (adjacent cies were identical (aX occurred in both lan-
dependencies hold between elements that occur guages as did Xd) so that sentences could only
next to each other in sequence, for example, be distinguished by learning the relationships
in the sentence “The boy jumped off the rock,” between the nonadjacent fi rst and third words.
the words “The boy” and “boy jumped”). Many We also manipulated the size of the pool from
different species can track adjacent dependen- which the middle element was drawn (set-size
cies, including humans, nonhuman primates, = 3, 12, or 24) while holding frequency of expo-
birds, and rats (Christie & Dalrymple-Alford, sure to the nonadjacent dependencies constant.
2004; Hauser, Newport, & Aslin, 2001; Terrace, The purpose of this manipulation was to deter-
Chen, & Jaswal, 1996; Terrace, Son, & Brannon, mine whether high variability in the middle
2003; Toro & Trobalón, 2005). Adjacent depen- element would lead to better perception of non-
dencies are learned easily by infants and by adjacent dependencies even though these were
adults (Saff ran et al., 1996a; Saff ran, Newport, equally frequent in all three set-size conditions.
& Aslin, 1996b). They also appear to be learned This manipulation captures a characteristic of
PROCESSING CONSTR AINTS ON LEARNING 197

|X| = 3 |X| = 12 |X| = 24

a X1 b a X1 b a X1 b
c X2 d c X2 d X2
X3 X3 c X3 d
. .
. .
. .
X12 .
Sentences in Version 1 of the language take the form aXb and cXd. .

In Version 2 they take the form aXd and cXb. a = pel, b = vot, c = rud, .

d = jic, X1 = kicey, X2 = deecha, X3 = wadim, X4 = coomo…X24 = loga X24

Figure 10.1 Depiction of the artificial language used in Gómez (2002) demonstrating the three vari-
ability conditions.

long-distance dependencies in natural language distinguish the two versions of the language).
between frequent morphemes such as “is” and Thus, the learning function will be flat with dis-
“-ing.” These frequent morphemes occur in the crimination at chance.
context of verb stems that themselves belong to A third possibility assumes some ordering
very large sets (e.g., “run” in “is running,” “play” of constraints in that conditional probabilities
in “is playing,” “sleep” in “is sleeping”) poten- could be a default form of learning, but also that
tially making the frequent morphemes more learners will only track a preferred structure to
perceptible. the extent that it occurs with some minimum
There were three possibilities for the out- degree of statistical certainty. Below that point,
come of this experiment according to three learners will track alternative sources of infor-
different learning models. In a statistics-driven mation. Although adjacent dependencies may
model, learners could attend to multiple types have a more privileged status than nonadjacent
of statistical information, weighing a type’s ones (because of perceptual salience or ease of
importance by degree of statistical regularity. processing), statistical structure in the input
By this view, learners would be biased to track plays a determining role in whether learners
conditional probabilities between adjacent ele- will focus on one type of structure or another.
ments but learning should closely mirror the This model would predict a nonlinear func-
statistical probabilities in the stimulus set with tion such that nonadjacent dependency learn-
learners increasingly more likely to track non- ing does not emerge gradually with increasing
adjacent dependencies as conditional probabili- set size, but instead emerges more abruptly.
ties between adjacent elements decrease. Thus, Figure 10.2 shows looking times to trained ver-
this model predicts a monotonically increasing sus untrained strings after 3-min exposure to
function such that nonadjacent dependency one of three variability conditions.
learning emerges gradually with increasing set The results were consistent with the last
size across the X-axis (and decreasing condi- proposed model, with learning occurring only
tional probabilities). under conditions of the greatest variability for
In a constraints-driven model, learners will infants and adults (see Gómez, 2002 and Gómez
always attend more to a favored structure even & Maye, 2005). One explanation for these find-
if the less favored one has greater statistical ings is that learners focused on conditional
certainty. This solution assumes no learning probabilities between adjacent elements when
with our stimulus materials if learners have a these were relatively high (in the small set-size
tendency to stick to their bias of favoring con- conditions), but when conditional probabilities
ditional probabilities (because in our language between adjacent elements were sufficiently low
knowledge of conditional probabilities will not (when set-size was 24) the adjacent dependencies
198 LEARNING MECHANISMS

12 in the middle element where what constitutes


Familiar Unfamiliar “sufficient” presumably varies as a function of
Mean listening time (sec)

10
the difficulty of the learning problem. In this
8 way, the joint pressures of internal biases and
6 external structure interact to result in dynam-
ically guided learning. Thus, learning is con-
4
strained by the process itself without having to
2 build in complex internal constraints for guid-
0 ing the choices learners make.
3 12 24
Set size of irrelevant intervening element Generalizing with Inconsistent Input
Figure 10.2 Mean listening times for 18-month- Consistent with the question of how learners
olds as a function of the variability manipulation choose among multiple possibilities in input
from Gómez (2002). The middle word in the is the issue of the degree to which children can
sentence comes from a set of 2, 6, or 24 possible learn in the face of inconsistent input. In the
elements. Discrimination only occurs in the course of normal language acquisition, all chil-
set-size = 24 condition.
dren are exposed to inconsistencies of one type
or another, in adults’ informal speech, in chil-
were no longer stable sources of structure, dren’s own ungrammatical utterances, and in
causing learners to instead track nonadja- the ungrammatical utterances of other learners
cent structure. Notably, learners did not show such as playmates and siblings. Inconsistencies
incremental increases in sensitivity to nonad- also occur naturally in language, for instance,
jacent structure with incremental increases in in English the degree to which verbs take the
variability of the middle element, a pattern we regular -ed ending for the past tense, or in
would expect if learners were responding pri- Spanish the extent to which feminine nouns
marily to the statistical structure. Instead, they end in -a. Other instances of inconsistencies
seemed to focus on adjacent dependencies long in linguistic input are less widespread, such as
after these ceased providing reliable informa- when a deaf child is exposed to American Sign
tion. In an experiment conducted with adults Language through a hearing parent who has
(where adults judged the acceptability of indi- not achieved proficiency in this language and
vidual sentences and there were three nonadja- whose repertoire of grammatical forms is not
cent dependencies to learn), the probability of only inconsistent, but limited. In all of these
the initial word being followed by a particular instances, children must distinguish grammat-
X-element was .33 (or 1 in 3) in a set-size 2 con- ical from ungrammatical instances, and they
dition. This probability decreased to .17, .08, must generalize beyond the data to which they
and .04 with set sizes of 6, 12, and 24, respec- are exposed, making it relevant to ask how well
tively. In contrast, in all conditions the proba- infants learn on exposure to inconsistent struc-
bility of the initial element being followed by a ture. This question is also important because
third element was 1. If responses to changes in critics of learning have cautioned that without
conditional probabilities had been veridical, we strong internal constraints, learners would have
might have expected to see learning of nonadja- no way to distinguish relevant from irrelevant
cent structure in the set-size 6 condition (given structure and would acquire grammar indis-
the low conditional probability of .17). However, criminantly, even ungrammatical forms. But is
it was only after substantial variability was this an issue of real concern?
introduced in the middle element that learners Gómez and Lakusta (2004) investigated this
appeared to rely on the nonadjacent structure question by familiarizing 12-month-olds with
(when set size was equal to 24). What appears to an artificial language with aX and bY strings (or
be critical for getting learners to notice the non- aY/bX strings in Language 2). There were two
adjacent dependencies is sufficient variability each of the a- and b-words and 6 each of the Xs
PROCESSING CONSTR AINTS ON LEARNING 199

Language 1 (S→aXbY or bYaX) Language 2 (S→bXaY or aYbX)


a X b X

ong coomo alt coomo


erd fengle ush fengle
kicey kicey Figure 10.3 Depiction of the
loga loga
puser puser Language 1 and Language 2
wadim wadim familiarization stimuli used
in Gómez and Lakusta (2004).
b Y a Y Sentences from Language 1
alt deech ong deech are ong-coomo ush-ghope,
ush ghope erd ghope ush-jic erd-loga, alt-ghope
jic jic ong-kicey, etc. Infants were
skige skige
vabe vabe tested on strings with new
tam tam X- and Y-words to assess
generalization.

and Ys, the latter of which were distinguishable Predominant training language
by syllable number. Infants had to learn that Other language
Mean listening time (sec)

a-elements went with Xs and not Ys (and vice 10


versa for b-elements). Three groups of infants 8
were familiarized with one of three levels of 6
probabilistic structure (see Figure 10.3). In a 4
100/0-condition, all of the training strings were 2
from the infants’ “predominant” training lan- 0
guage. In this case, infants received strings of 100/0 83/17 67/33
only the aX and bY forms. In an 83/17-condi-
Figure 10.4 Mean listening times for 12-month-
tion, approximately 83% of the training strings
olds to novel test strings from the predominant
were from the predominant aX/bY language, or the nonpredominant familiarization lan-
whereas the remaining 17% of the strings fol- guage in one of three probability conditions in
lowed an aY/bX form such that one Y-word went Gómez and Lakusta (2004). Infants show dis-
with the two a-words as opposed the bs and an crimination after familiarization with the 100/0
X-word went with the two bs as opposed to the and 83/17 probability conditions.
as. Thus these particular strings were inconsis-
tent with the aX/bY structure. In the 67/33-con-
dition, the split between the predominant and shown in Figure 10.4, infants in the 100/0
nonpredominant training languages was 67% and 83/17 conditions showed significant lev-
and 33%. At test, infants had to discriminate els of learning and they learned equally well
strings from the predominant language with as reflected in longer looking times to strings
those from the nonpredominant one, but with instantiated in the predominant as opposed to
novel X- and Y-elements to test generalization. the nonpredominant language, suggesting that
We were interested in knowing whether (a) they are able to track regularities in probabi-
infants could separate a predominant from a listic input even when the regularities do not
nonpredominant structure such that they would occur with perfect probability (as was the case
show learning in the presence of inconsistent with the 83/17 ratio). Thus fairly young infants
input and (b) whether learning would break appear able to track a regular structure even
down at some point as it should if the predom- with some inconsistencies present. However,
inant structure drops below a minimum level learning does need to be based on some min-
of predictability. As seen in the looking times imum degree of consistency, as demonstrated
200 LEARNING MECHANISMS

by the fact that infants in the 67/33-condition sensitivity to complex syntactic patterns, and
failed to learn. specifically how prior learning impacts the
In sum, infants appear able to separate rel- acquisition of nonadjacent dependencies (Lany
evant from irrelevant structure, but such learn- & Gómez, 2008). Infants in these studies were
ing is dependent on the quality of the signal. 12-month-olds who in previous studies have
Thus, learning appears to be constrained as a been unable to track nonadjacent structure
natural by-product in infants’ processing of sta- (Gómez & Maye, 2005). Infants were famil-
tistical structure. iarized with aX and bY strings, where X- and
Y-elements were distinguishable by syllable
Bootstrapping from Simpler to More
number, and where infants had to learn that
Difficult Structure
a-elements went with Xs and not Ys (and vice
A third way that learning is constrained by the versa for b-elements). After familiarization with
learning process stems from prior learning. In the aX/bY structure infants were able to detect
the real world, and particularly during early the aX and bY relationships in a more complex
development, learning is unlikely to result in language involving long-distance dependencies
an end state. Instead, learners encounter new (e.g., in acX and bcY sentences). See the results
examples with potential to build on, interfere in Figure 10.5. This language was particularly
with, or alter the type of generalizations they challenging for this age group because the
are able to make. Furthermore, the types of intervening c-element required the infants to
generalizations infants make are influenced by track nonadjacent dependencies between a- and
their prior experience. As such, it is important X- and b- and Y-words. A control group who did
to begin to understand how prior knowledge not receive prior experience with the simpler
supports or detracts from the learning of new “adjacent” form of the language was not able to
or more complex forms. track the critical dependencies when they were
There is precedent for the role of prior expe- nonadjacent. Thus, with prior exposure to sim-
rience already in language acquisition in the pler adjacent structure infants are able to detect
work on infant speech perception showing that the more difficult nonadjacent form. This find-
infants can discriminate speech sounds that ing is relevant for showing how infants might
occur in other languages early on in develop- scaffold learning of more difficult structure
ment but become more limited in the nonnative from learning of more simple forms and for
forms they can discriminate as they become showing how prior experience can affect later
more attuned to their native language input learning. These findings also demonstrate how
(Best, McRoberts, & Sithole, 1988; Polka & constraints can arise from the learning pro-
Werker, 1994; Werker & Tees, 1984). Presumably cess itself, as opposed to being part of learners’
this change is a function of experience. Similar knowledge beforehand.
findings have been reported in the infant learn- In summary, the findings showing that (1)
ing literature. Gerken and Bollt (2008) fi nd that internal biases and external statistics inter-
younger 7-month-olds are able to acquire an act to guide the choice of which structure is
unnatural linguistic rule that older 9-month- learned when multiple possibilities are avail-
olds cannot. Presumably increased tuning to able, (2) learning of a predominant form can
the statistics of English helps older infants persist in the face of inconsistent input but only
ignore unnatural generalizations in favor of lin- to a point, and (3) prior experience can in some
guistically natural ones. In this way, experience cases constrain and in others enable learning,
constrains the types of generalizations infants are important for increasing our understand-
will make, but can prior experience also enable ing of how learners negotiate complex statistical
learning of forms that are normally too difficult structure. They also shed light on how con-
to acquire? straints and statistical structure both contrib-
Evidence for this comes from studies inves- ute to this process. Particularly important are
tigating how prior learning might bootstrap the insights they provide into how the learning
PROCESSING CONSTR AINTS ON LEARNING 201

Generalization to withheld pairs across wake states, sleep is particularly instru-


12 mental in memory consolidation. Additionally,
Habituation
Mean listening time (sec)

10 Test memories are updated with new information


8 as a matter of course in learning. A candidate
process for such updating is memory reconsoli-
6
dation. Mounting evidence suggests that when
4 memories are reactivated, they become labile
2 and open to change. Retrieval can reinforce the
0 reactivated memory, or update it through the
Experimental Control incorporation of new information. Such trans-
formed memories then undergo a time-depen-
Figure 10.5 Twelve-month-olds’ mean listen- dent reconsolidation process. Although the idea
ing times to grammatical versus ungrammati- that memories are malleable is not new in cogni-
cal strings. Infants were familiarized with aX/ tive development (e.g., Loftus, 2005), the mech-
bY (or aY/bX) phrases for which a subset of anism underlying such change has not been well
pairs were withheld. After habituation to acX/ understood. Work on memory reconsolidation
bcY (or acY/bcX) phrases, they were tested on has begun to define the critical determinants of
phrases that were ungrammatical with respect
episodic memory change and holds promise for
to their familiarization language. From Lany
and Gómez (submitted).
identifying the conditions affecting the updat-
ing of prior knowledge in learning and cogni-
tive development. Thus, memory consolidation
process itself constrains learning dynamically, and reconsolidation both have implications for
such that learning arises in the interaction of constraining children’s generalizations. These
preferences that may guide learning initially but topics are addressed below.
that change in response to environmental pres-
Memory Consolidation
sure, in infants’ ability to track predominant
structure, and in the role of prior experience on Memory consolidation is a process in which
constraining later learning. I will turn next to a newly formed memory trace is converted to
the role of memory in constraining children’s a stable, less disruptable state over a period
generalizations. of days to years (McGaugh, 2000). In addi-
tion to stabilizing the memory, consolidation
is thought to result in an enhancement of the
THEROLE OF MEMORY PROCESSES IN
remembered information in the form of greater
CONSTRAINING LEARNING
accuracy and speed of execution, and better
Most learning studies test performance imme- generalization. Memories are also thought to
diately after training, but in fact newly encoded become more integrated with existing knowl-
information undergoes a series of involuntary edge as a function of consolidation. Although
brain-dependent changes raising the possibility there is evidence that memories become sta-
that what infants retain after memory consol- bilized during wake states (Brashers-Krug,
idation is different in nature from what we see Shadmehr, & Bizzi, 1996, Muellbacher et al.
initially. Such changes include stabilization of 2002, Walker, Brakefield, Hobson, & Stickgold,
the memory, enhancement of it, and integration 2003), memory enhancement appears to be a
of new information into what is already known. unique product of sleep (Fischer, Hallschmid,
Thus, in addition to constraints that arise from Elsner, & Born, 2002; Gais, Plihal, Wagner,
the learning process itself, a second form of con- & Born, 2000; Karni, Tanne, Rubenstein,
straint arises in the transformation of new expe- Askenasy, & Sagi, 1994; Korman, Raz, Flash,
riences into a more permanent form through & Karni, 2003; Stickgold, James, & Hobson,
a process of consolidation (or stabilization). 2002a; Stickgold, Whidbee, Schirmer, Patel, &
Interestingly, although memories can stabilize Hobson, 2002b; Walker et al. 2002a; Walker,
202 LEARNING MECHANISMS

Brakefield, Hobson, & Stickgold, 2002b; novel words after a 24-h interval (during which
Walker & Stickgold, 2006). Importantly, these both groups slept).
improvements appear to arise from molecu- In addition to better performance and gen-
lar, cellular, and systems-level processes that eralization, sleep has also been implicated in
are specifically linked with sleep. For instance, qualitative changes in memory having to do
there is some evidence that patterns of activa- with gaining insight into a problem solution
tion occurring during training reappear dur- (Wagner, Gais, Haider, Verleger, & Born, 2004).
ing rapid eye movement (REM) sleep (e.g., Participants exposed to a problem that could be
Maquet et al., 2000; Wilson & McNaughton, solved either in an iterative step-by-step fashion
1994; Euston, Tatsuno, & McNaughton, 2007) or according to a hidden rule were more likely
and immediate performance on a learning task to make the critical insight regarding the hid-
can be shown to correlate with the magnitude den rule after sleep than after an equivalent time
of later brain activity during REM (Peigneux awake. Two times as many of the participants in
et al., 2003). While these fi ndings suggest that the sleep group detected the hidden rule as com-
brain activity during sleep is affected by train- pared to the group who did not sleep, suggesting
ing earlier in the day, brain activity during that sleep was implicated in a transformation
sleep also correlates with later memory per- in memory that made it easier for learners to
formance and improvement, demonstrating discover the hidden rule. Sleep has also been
a link not just between the original learning implicated in memory transformations involv-
experience and sleep but also between sleep ing transitive inference of relations (Ellenbogen,
and memory consolidation as measured after Hu, Payne, Titone, & Walker, 2007), and learn-
sleep (Peigneux et al., 2004). The fi ndings link- ing of higher-order associations and their gen-
ing brain activity to earlier training, and brain eralization (Cohen, Pascual-Leone, Press, &
activity to later consolidation, are important Robertson, 2005; Keele, Ivry, Mayr, Hazeltine,
for ruling out explanations of memory stabi- & Heuer, 2003; Spencer, Sunm, & Ivry, 2006).
lization and enhancement having to do with Ellenbogen et al. trained participants on visual
a decrease in sensory input (or a decrease in stimuli of the form A>B (A precedes B), B>C,
interference) during sleep. C>D, D>E, E>F then tested them for general-
How does sleep affect the consolidation of ization to novel inference pairs (B>D, C>E, and
new learning? Research with adults shows that B>E) after varying intervals that either did or
learners were faster and more accurate in tap- did not contain sleep (20 min, 12 h wake, 12 h
ping out a sequence with their fingers in a pro- sleep, 24 h). Retention of the learned pairs was
cedural learning task after sleep than before similarly high for all groups (85%), but gener-
(Walker et al., 2003). Sleep also appears to be alization occurred only for groups tested 12 or
implicated in a type of memory consolidation more hours later, with sleep in the 12-h groups
that leads to generalization. Fenn, Nusbaum, providing an additional boost for the most dis-
and Margoliash (2003) found that adults were tant, and most difficult, inference pair (B>E,
better able to recognize phonemes in new words 69% wake, 93% sleep). Additionally, Cohen et al.
after a night of sleep than after an equivalent (2005) found that transfer of goal-based versus
interval of wake–time during the day. Learners movement-based skill in a serial reaction-time
were tested 12 h after training and either slept task improved differentially during wake and
or not during this interval. Participants who did sleep with knowledge of movements themselves
not sleep showed decreased levels of recognition improving during wake and knowledge involv-
whereas those who did sleep showed the same ing goals improving with sleep.
high levels of generalization on novel words as Although there is an established litera-
learners tested immediately after training. The ture on patterns of infant sleep–wake states
time of day learning took place was not a fac- (Kleitman & Engelmann, 1953; Thoman, 1990),
tor. Groups who learned in the morning and in little is known about the role of sleep in infant
the evening had identical performance gains on learning with the exception that sleep–wake
PROCESSING CONSTR AINTS ON LEARNING 203

state organization is a predictor of cognitive not nap. Typically, infants this age look longer
development in infancy (Gertner et al., 2002), as to familiar versus unfamiliar strings immedi-
well as the finding that sleep plays an instrumen- ately after familiarization, reflecting memory
tal role in brain development in animals (Frank, of specific nonadjacent word-pairs (Gómez &
Issa, Stryker, & Keck, 2001). However, given the Maye, 2005). However, if sleep induces a trans-
adult findings on the importance of sleep in formation in memory, infants might remember
memory consolidation, there is every reason something more abstract involving a predictive
to think that sleep is also implicated in infant relationship between the first and third words.
memory. Indeed, recent research supports this If so, infants might show a preference for the
view (Gómez, Bootzin, & Nadel, 2006). nonadjacent word-pairs encountered on the
In the first experiment designed to test the first trial of the test even when they were not
effects of sleep on learning, 15-month-old infants the exact nonadjacent words encountered ear-
were exposed to a learning experience prior to lier. If time alone plays a role in memory con-
a nap then were tested afterward. The infants solidation, infants in both the nap and no-nap
were familiarized with the artificial language groups should show the same pattern of effects.
discussed in the first section on learning con- However, if sleep is the determining factor, then
straints detailed above. The artificial language performance should differ between the two
required infants to track sequential dependen- conditions. A nap-control group was also tested
cies between the first and third words in sen- to determine whether sleep alone would alter
tences such as pel-wadim-jic or vot-kicey-rud. learning. This group was exposed to the artifi-
Recall that previous research from our labora- cial language but the middle word came from
tory showed that the nonadjacent relationships a set of only three items, a condition that does
between the first and third words are learned not normally lead to nonadjacent dependency
only when there is high variability in the mid- learning.
dle position (created by selecting middle words Infants were tested on sentences that both
from a large as opposed to a small set), making preserved the specific nonadjacent dependency
the flanking nonadjacent word-dependencies encountered during familiarization and on sen-
more salient perceptually (Gómez, 2002; Gómez tences that contained violations of the specific
& Maye, 2005). Because the two versions of the nonadjacent dependency. The head-turn pref-
language were identical with respect to absolute erence method was used to assess discrimina-
position of words and dependencies between tion of the two stimulus types in the form of
adjacent words, they can only be distinguished listening time differences (Kemler Nelson et al.,
by noting the nonadjacent relationship between 1995). The results are shown in Figure 10.6.
the first and third words. This feature of the lan- Infants in the no-nap group listened longer
guage enabled us to ask whether sleep-enhanced to familiar over unfamiliar trials consistent
memory of specific nonadjacent word-pairs (e.g. with veridical memory of specific nonadja-
that pel predicted jic), or promoted learning of cent word-pairs. In contrast, infants in the nap
an abstract rule (that the first word predicts the group listened longer to sentences consistent
last in an utterance, despite the specific words with the trial-type encountered on the first
involved). test trial, suggesting they had abstracted away
Infants were familiarized with the lan- from specific nonadjacent words such that they
guage in their homes by a research assistant noticed particular nonadjacent dependencies on
who played the artificial language from a tape the first test trial (whether identical or not) and
recorder while playing quietly with the infant. showed a greater tendency to listen to strings
Familiarization lasted approximately 15 min. with the same nonadjacent dependencies in
Infants were tested in the laboratory 4 h after remaining trials. The control group showed no
familiarization. There were two groups of pri- learning whatsoever, eliminating the possibility
mary interest: infants who napped between that sleep alone can alter memory apart from
familiarization and test and those who did the learning manipulation.
204 LEARNING MECHANISMS

4.5
Familiar–Unfamiliar Veridical memory
3.5
2.5

Mean looking time differences (sec)


1.5
0.5
Figure 10.6 Fifteen-month-
olds’ mean listening times, 4 –0.5
h after familiarization in Nap, –1.5
No Nap Nap Nap control
No-Nap, and Nap-control con-
4.5
ditions. Infants who napped in Abstraction: Difference
the interval between famil- 3.5 Cons w/Trial 1–Inconsistant
conditional on first
iarization and test showed a 2.5 post-sleep trial
significant difference on the 1.5
abstraction measure. Infants
who did not nap showed 0.5
significant veridical memory. –0.5
From Gómez, Bootzin, and –1.5
Nadel (2006). No Nap Nap Nap control

More recently, we have asked whether differently immediately after learning, the idea
15-month-olds need to nap fairly soon after that infants forget specific details of the stimulus
learning or whether, like adults, any sleep later with sleep seems more likely given that infants
in the day will do (Hupbach, Gómez, Bootzin, who did not sleep immediately after test showed
& Nadel, in press). We familiarized two groups no memory of the artificial language 24 h later.
of infants with the artificial language used in Additionally, what kind of sleep is involved?
Gómez (2002) and Gómez et al. (2006). One Plihal and Born (1997) found that declara-
group was scheduled at a time of day when tive learning in a paired-associates task was
they were likely to nap in the 4-h interval after enhanced during slow-wave sleep (SWS) and
familiarization. Another group was scheduled procedural learning in a mirror-tracing task
when they were not likely to nap until at least was linked with REM. It is not clear whether our
4 h later. Both groups were tested 24 h after artificial language studies engage declarative or
familiarization. Thus, all infants slept during procedural knowledge, however the naps of chil-
the night, but only the nap-group slept in the dren this age contain components of both REM
4-h interval after familiarization. Interestingly, and SWS (Louis, Cannard, Bastuji, & Challamell,
the nap group showed generalization 24 h later, 1997). Thus, with testing of sleep architecture, it
whereas the no-nap group showed no learning should be possible to determine which specific
of any kind. Thus, sleep fairly soon after a learn- stage or stages of sleep are most involved.
ing experience appears to be critical not only Finally, the findings showing that sleep soon
for memory retention, but for abstraction of the after learning is important for retention raises
learned information. the question of when in childhood learning
These findings raise important questions becomes less nap-dependent such that chil-
about the role of sleep in memory change. For dren, like adults (Gais et al., 2007), are able
one, how do memories become more abstract? to consolidate memories with only nighttime
One possibility is that infants are sensitive sleep. It is tempting to assume that the rate at
to both specific and abstract information but which children nap is sufficient and necessary
weight these differentially before and after sleep. for any given age, but differences in cultural
A second is that infants forget specific details of practice and in individual families’ schedules
the stimulus with sleep. Although infants may make it difficult to use existing napping norms
indeed weight specific and abstract information to answer this question.
PROCESSING CONSTR AINTS ON LEARNING 205

In sum, these findings suggest that the mem- Nader et al. (2000) showed that reactivation
ory process itself is instrumental in constrain- of a fear-response could bring a well-consol-
ing learning. In our particular studies, memory idated fear memory back to a labile state that
consolidation associated with sleep introduced could then be disrupted by inhibiting protein
flexibility into performance such that infants synthesis in the amygdala (the same treatment
abstracted a pattern and detected it at test that disrupts initial consolidation), demon-
regardless of whether it was instantiated exactly strating that memories require de novo pro-
as before. In this way, the process of memory tein synthesis in order to survive. Importantly,
consolidation gives rise to plasticity in learning impairment was not observed in the absence of
by sustaining sensitivity to previously encoun- reactivation. Reconsolidation has since been
tered information, while enabling children to demonstrated in variety of species and learn-
generalize to similar but not identical cases. ing situations and it appears to be distinct from
Memory change involving abstraction may be consolidation in its neurobiological process (for
particularly important for developing infants a review, see Dudai, 2006).
who must retain key aspects of prior experience Reconsolidation has also been recently
while generalizing in novel situations. demonstrated in two procedural memory tasks
I turn next to the role of memory reconsoli- with humans. Walker et al. (2003) trained adult
dation in learning, starting with a discussion of participants to tap out a visually presented
how the processes of memory consolidation and sequence (e.g., 4-1-3-2-4) on a numeric key-
reconsolidation differ. pad with their corresponding fingers. Twenty-
four hours later, participants learned a second
Memory Reconsolidation
sequence (e.g., 2-3-1-4-2) in one of two conditions
Memory consolidation is a process that stabi- (one in which the first sequence was either briefly
lizes a new memory trace. There are changes in rehearsed, reactivating it, or one in which it was
the brain structures critical for memory storage not rehearsed). Participants were then tested
and/or retrieval at both cellular and systems 24 h later for their accuracy and speed on the
levels. At the cellular level, there are changes in original sequence. Performance in the group that
synaptic efficacy and at the systems level, there was reminded was significantly impaired in com-
are thought to be changes in memory expres- parison to the group who did not rehearse the first
sion such that it is no longer dependent on the sequence before learning the second one, demon-
hippocampus (Squire, Cohen, & Nadel, 1984). strating that reactivating a memory destabilizes
Two tenets of this process are that once com- it such that a competing motor pattern can then
plete, memories are stable and no longer sub- interfere. There is also evidence from a procedural
ject to change. Additionally, consolidation is learning task with 3-month-olds that reconsoli-
thought to involve strengthening of the mem- dation occurs in very young infants. Galluccio
ory as opposed to memory modification. How (2005) and Galluccio and Rovee-Collier (2005)
then does new information get incorporated? investigated the effects of reactivated memories
The answer lies in a phenomenon known as on infants trained to kick their foot to activate a
memory reconsolidation. Contrary to the view mobile. After a delay, the moving mobile was pre-
that memories become stable and resistant to sented for a brief period during which it was no
change, reactivating a memory appears to make longer attached to the baby’s foot (reminding the
it labile and open to change. By this view, reac- child of the original learning experience). After
tivation transfers memory from a passive to an reactivation, infants were exposed a novel mobile.
active state during which it can be altered and/ One day later, infants who were exposed to the
or disrupted (Lewis, 1979; Misanin, Miller, & novel mobile no longer recognized the origi-
Lewis, 1968; Nader, Schafe, & Le Doux, 2000; nal one—they responded solely with a kicking
see also Sara, 2000). Altered memories must response to the novel mobile, suggesting that the
then undergo a time-dependent period of experience with the new mobile had overwritten
reconsolidation to register change. memory for the old one.
206 LEARNING MECHANISMS

These findings were important for demon- third session, participants were asked to recall
strating how memories could be altered by new the first set of objects only, the objects learned
information, and thus are relevant to theories of in the original session.
learning and development, such as those having Reminded subjects showed a high number of
to do with the misinformation effect (Loftus, intrusions from the second set of objects when
2005). However, they also raised important recalling the first set, whereas participants who
questions. First, how broadly does reconsolida- had not been reminded showed virtually no
tion apply to different forms of memory? The intrusions, demonstrating that the updating of
reconsolidation effects described thus far apply preexisting memory is dependent on reactiva-
to tasks involving implicit memory, a form of tion of that memory (Panel 1 in Figure 10.7).
memory that does not require conscious rec- Importantly, the effect is not evident immedi-
ollection. But does reconsolidation also apply ately after learning the second set of objects as
to explicit memory, a form of memory that would have been predicted if this were retro-
allows for the conscious recollection of events active interference (Panel 2). Instead the effect
(episodic memory) and facts (semantic mem- took time to emerge. Therefore, as with ani-
ory)? Additionally, previous demonstrations mal fear conditioning (e.g., Nader et al., 2000)
of reconsolidation have shown that new infor- and human procedural memory (Walker et al.,
mation interferes with previous learning, but 2003), reactivated episodic memories appear to
can reconsolidation also be instrumental when undergo a time-dependent reconsolidation pro-
learners have to incorporate new information cess. However, our findings differ in an impor-
into established memories? tant way from previous ones in demonstrating
These questions have been explored in the constructive memory effects as opposed to
context of an explicit memory paradigm devel- interference of new information on old mem-
oped by Hupbach, Gómez, Hardt, and Nadel ories. Furthermore, the updating effect occurs
(2007). Adult participants learned a set of 20 only for the reactivated memory. When partici-
common objects during a first session (e.g., pants were asked to recall objects from the sec-
bandaid, sunglasses, pencil, cup, sponge, etc.). ond training session, intrusions of objects from
The objects were contained in a yellow basket the original memory were rare, arguing against
and were pulled out one-by-one and named. simple source-memory confusion (Panel 3).
The participants were asked to recall the items Although conducted with adults, this
immediately after exposure to the entire set. The memory-reconsolidation process is relevant
procedure was then repeated until participants for understanding memory updating gener-
recalled at least 17 of the 20 objects or com- ally in learning and development. Such a pro-
pleted four rounds of recall trials. Forty-eight cess appears to depend on reactivating memory
hours later. participants were reminded of the through some form of reminding, providing
original learning experience or not. Reminding new information at the time of reactivation,
took the form of the same experimenter tak- and allowing time for the new information to
ing the participant back to the same location be incorporated with the old.
in the psychology building and asking them if We have also tested 5- and 9-year-old
they remembered what they had done previ- children to see whether the updating effect
ously with the yellow basket. Participants were occurs at earlier points in developmental time
encouraged to describe the procedure only. (Hupbach, Gómez, & Nadel, in preparation).
They were stopped if they began to recall any It would be particularly informative to know
of the objects. Participants in the no-reminder whether 5-year-olds show the asymmetri-
group were taken by a different experimenter to cal updating effect in the form of updating of
a different location in the building and were not the original memory because source memory
reminded of the yellow basket. All participants errors are high in this age group relative to
learned a second set of objects (in the case of the children 6 years of age and older (Drummey &
reminder group learning occurred immediately Newcomb, 2002). Five-year-olds might be just as
after reminding). Forty-eight hours later in a likely to intrude objects from the fi rst learning
PROCESSING CONSTR AINTS ON LEARNING 207

60 experience into their recall of the second set as


Recall (List 1)
Mean percentage of objects recalled

Intrusions (List 2) they are to include the second set of objects into
50 the original memory. Children were tested with
45.0
a similar design as the adults with three excep-
40 tions: 9-year-olds were tested with 12 objects
36.3 and 5-year-olds with 8, the children were tested
30
in their homes instead of in the laboratory, and
20 23.8
the delays between sessions were 24 h instead of
48 h in duration.
10 Children of both ages showed robust intru-
sion effects. Importantly, 5-year-olds showed the
4.9
0 asymmetrical updating effect. Thus, although
Reminder No-reminder children this age tend to have difficulty mon-
itoring the source of newly acquired informa-
60 tion, they do not show such errors when a prior
Recall (List 1)
Mean percentage of objects recalled

Intrusions (List 2) memory is reactivated at a later point in time.


50 As with the adults, the effect is time-dependent.
It does not appear when children are asked to
40
recall the original list immediately after learn-
ing the second one. Instead, the effect only
30 31.9
29.2 shows up 24 h later after memory reconsolida-
tion has taken place.
20
One question has to do with the cues that
10 trigger memory reconsolidation and updating.
0.2 0.9 For adults and 5-year-old children, unfamiliar
0 locations in themselves can serve as a reminder
Reminder No-reminder (updating occurs even when the experimenter
is different and the reminder question is not
asked, as long as the spatial context remains
60
Recall (List 2) the same, Hupbach, Hardt, Gómez, & Nadel,
Mean percentage of objects recalled

Intrusions (List 1) 2008; Hupbach, Gómez, & Nadel, in prepara-


50
tion). However, not surprisingly, spatial context
47.1
40 does not serve as a reminder when children are
42.6
tested in a familiar spatial context such as when
30 they are tested in their homes. In that case, the
experimenter and reminder question together
20 serve to reactivate memory (Hupbach, Gómez,
& Nadel, in preparation). The importance of
10
spatial context for determining whether memo-
1.7
5.4 ries of events are reactivated and updated makes
0
Reminder No-reminder sense given that the particulars of a current
situation often determine which responses are
Figure 10.7 Mean number of objects correctly appropriate (see Nadel, 2007). Other cues, may
and falsely recalled in the reminder and the act as reminders for a different reason. Having
no-reminder groups. Panel 1: Recall of Set 1 in an unknown person visit and interact with a
Session 3. Panel 2: Immediate recall of Set 1 in child at home is an unusual and salient event,
Session 2. Panel 3: Recall of Set 2 in Session 3. whereas an interaction with a new person is
Error bars represent standard errors of means.
not so unusual when a child is in an unfamil-
Note in Panels 2 and 3 that there are no intru-
iar location, as the data with children show. In
sions in the reminder conditions. From Hupbach,
Gómez, Hardt, and Nadel (2007). that case, spatial location serves as the reminder
208 LEARNING MECHANISMS

(Hupbach, Gómez, & Nadel, in preparation). from learning of a simpler form of information
Regardless of which reminders reactivate mem- (e.g., adjacent dependencies) when that source
ory and why, the triggers demonstrated thus far is not informative to other forms of structure
are incidental in nature. They occur frequently that are not as simple (e.g., nonadjacent depen-
in experience with potential to reactivate dencies; Gómez, 2002). In this way, the choice
memories continually, resulting in a process of of which structure to learn can arise naturally
learning and memory that is fluid, as opposed from the competing pressures of internal biases
to static, in nature, that may play a central role and information in the environment. We have
in cognitive development. also documented learning under noisy condi-
tions showing that infant learners can track a
predominant probabilistic structure despite
SUMMARY
irregularities in the input, and can even gen-
The central problem in cognitive development eralize on this basis (Gómez & Lakusta, 2004).
is understanding how cognition grows and Importantly learning diminishes, as it should,
changes over time. Research has had tended to when the input contains higher levels of irreg-
focus on changes in the knowledge base itself ular structure, demonstrating that learning is
in terms of documenting types of knowledge constrained by the reliability of the information
and abilities children exhibit at different ages, children encounter. Finally, we have seen how
and asking how that knowledge constrains the the information children acquire at one point in
choices children make. An example is children’s time can constrain what they are able to learn
tendency to extend labels to novel objects taxo- at older ages (Gerken & Bollt, in press) and can
nomically, within the same category, as opposed also enable learning of more difficult forms
to extending them to thematically related choices (Lany & Gómez, 2008). This work raises ques-
(e.g., extending a novel label for dog to a pig, but tions regarding the types of processing biases
not to a bone; see Markman & Hutchison, 1984). available to learners and which biases are likely
Although children may well employ such con- to be employed in different learning situations.
straints, it is important to ask whether and how The findings also raise questions about the way
they are learned. One possibility is that children learning changes as infants’ cognitive processes
note the consistency of the association between a are increasingly able to handle more difficult
label and objects of similar shape (e.g., cups come information. Do the learning processes them-
in a variety of colors and sizes, but they are simi- selves become more complex or are they able to
lar in their shape), allowing them to generalize execute over more difficult information?
the principle that categories contain objects of We have also documented the role of mem-
similar shapes. This principle is consistent with ory processes in constraining learning, both
children’s taxonomic choices and is relevant for the role of memory consolidation and sleep in
understanding how such choices come to be transforming learned experiences into a more
manifested in children’s behavior (Colunga & abstract form (Gómez et al., 2006) and the role
Smith, 2004, 2005; Jones & Smith, 2002; Smith, of reconsolidation in constructive memory
Jones, Landau, Gershkoff-Stowe, & Samuelson, (Hupbach, Gómez, Hardt, & Nadel, 2007). Both
2002). In this way, experience itself can lead to memory processes are important for under-
the formation of a general principle (see Lany & standing how children sustain sensitivity to
Gómez, in press, for a more thorough discussion prior knowledge while incorporating new infor-
of this idea). mation. In addition to the role of memory pro-
In the tradition of emphasizing developmen- cesses in constraining learning, it is important
tal processes, an aspect of development explored to test memory to ensure that the behavioral
here is how learning and memory processes effects seen immediately after a learning phase
themselves might serve to constrain learning. are not simply the result of short-term accli-
There are processes that appear to guide learn- matization to a stimulus as opposed to a more
ing dynamically, enabling infants to switch permanent change. That is, for the learning we
PROCESSING CONSTR AINTS ON LEARNING 209

observe in the laboratory to contribute in any developed in humans until approximately


meaningful way to development, it should result 18–24 months (Nadel & Hupbach, 2008). Thus,
in some kind of memory change that is retained reconsolidation involving episodic memory
long enough to be reinforced or to be instru- should not occur much before 18–24 months of
mental in later learning. Additionally, what is age, but it should occur later. Further research
remembered after sleep or after a 24-h delay will be necessary for understanding the exact
(Gómez et al., 2006; Hupbach et al., in press) nature of reactivation and reconsolidation of
may be very different than what is remembered memories at younger ages, such as in the find-
immediately after learning. Importantly, adult ings reported by Galluccio and Rovee-Collier
work shows distinct processes of stabilization (2005).
and enhancement in memory consolidation. As In sum, in contrast to “knowledge” con-
such, it will be important to fi ll in the develop- straints traditionally proposed in the literature
mental picture of how infant memories stabilize on development and learning, the constraints
over wake and sleep states, whether this differs proposed and discussed here arise naturally
at different ages, and how this is linked to what from the mechanics of learning and memory
we already know about infant memory. processes themselves.
With respect to the role of reconsolidation in
memory change, additional research will be nec-
essary for characterizing reconsolidation more REFERENCES
fully, in terms of determining whether the effect
Baillargeon, R. (1987). Object permanence in 3.5-
is transient or long-lasting, whether the pro-
and 4.5-month-old infants. Developmental
cess is similar for older as compared to younger Psychology, 23, 655–664.
memories, how it is affected by sleep, and how it Best, C. T., McRoberts, G. W., & Sithole, N. M.
is affected by different kinds of reminders (e.g., (1988). Examination of the perceptual reorga-
what happens when learners are asked to recall nization for contrasts: Zulu click discrimina-
an established memory as opposed to reacti- tion by English-speaking adults and infants.
vating it implicitly?). Most importantly, how do Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human
these factors change across development and as Perception and Performance, 14, 245–360.
children gain expertise in a particular domain, Bíró, S., Csibra, G., & Gergely, G. (2007). The role
such as in language? The answers to these ques- of behavioral cues in understanding goal-
directed actions in infancy. Progress in Brain
tions will be important for understanding the
Research, 164, 303–322.
scope and limits of reconsolidation—and the
Brashers-Krug, T., Shadmehr, R., & Bizzi, E.
implications for learning and development are (1996). Consolidation in human motor mem-
far-reaching. In particular, the interference ory. Nature, 382, 252–255.
effects documented in the animal literature Christie, M. A., & Dalrymple-Alford, J. C. (2004).
(Nader et al., 2000) and in human procedural A new rat model of the human serial reac-
memory (Walker et al., 2003) may explain how tion time task: Contrasting effects of cau-
children recover from incorrect, or erroneous, date and hippocampal lesions. The Journal of
generalizations. Presumably, if a generaliza- Neuroscience, 24, 1034–1039.
tion is activated, though incorrect, it will be Cohen, D. A., Pascual-Leone, A., Press, D. Z., &
overwritten in time by more statistically prob- Robertson, E. M. (2005). Off-line learning of
motor skill memory: A double dissociation of
able data. Furthermore, the memory updating
goal and movement. Proceedings of the National
effects that occur with reconsolidation of epi-
Academy of Sciences USA, 102, 18237–18241.
sodic memories are relevant to understanding Colunga, E., & Smith, L. B. (2003). The emergence
how learners incorporate new information or of abstract ideas: Evidence from networks and
experiences into prior memory. An important babies. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal
consideration is the fact that reconsolidation Society, 358, 1205–1214.
of episodic memory should be hippocampally Colunga, E., & Smith, L.B. (2005). From the lexi-
mediated, but the hippocampus is not fully con to expectations about kinds: A role for
210 LEARNING MECHANISMS

associative learning. Psychological Review, 112, environment: Implications for early cognitive
347–382. development. Early Human Development, 68,
Drummey, A., & Newcombe, N. (2002). 93–102.
Developmental changes in source memory. Gómez, R. L. (2002). Variability and detection of
Developmental Science, 5, 502–513. invariant structure. Psychological Science, 13,
Dudai, Y. (2006). Reconsolidation: The advan- 431–436.
tage of being refocused. Current Opinion in Gómez, R. L., Bootzin, R., & Nadel, L. (2006).
Neurobiology, 16, 174–178. Naps promote abstraction in language learning
Ellenbogen, J. M., Hu, P. T., Payne, J. D., Titone, infants. Psychological Science, 17, 670–674.
D., & Walker, M. P. (2007). How relational Gómez, R. L., & Gerken, L. A. (2000). Infant arti-
memory requires time and sleep. Proceedings ficial language learning and language acquisi-
of the National Academy of Sciences USA, 104, tion. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 4, 178–186.
7723–7728. Gómez, R. L., & Lakusta, L. (2004). A first step in
Euston, D. R., Tatsuno, M., & McNaughton, B. form-based category abstraction by 12-month-
L. (2007). Fast-forward playback of recent old infants. Developmental Science, 7, 567–580.
memory sequences in prefrontal cortex during Gómez, R. L., & Maye, J. (2005). The develop-
sleep. Science, 318, 1147–1150. mental trajectory of nonadjacent dependency
Fenn, K., Nusbaum, H., & Margoliash, D. (2003). learning. Infancy, 7, 183–206.
Consolidation during sleep of perceptual learn- Hauser, M. D., Newport, E. L., & Aslin, R. N.
ing of spoken language. Nature, 425, 614–616. (2001). Segmentation of the speech stream in
Fischer, S., Hallschmid, M., Elsner, A. L., & Born, a non-human primate: Statistical learning in
J. (2002). Sleep forms memory for finger skills. cotton-top tamarins. Cognition, 78, B53–B64.
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences Hupbach, A., Gómez, R. L., Bootzin, R., & Nadel,
USA, 99, 11987–11991. L. (in press). Nap-dependent learning in
Frank, M., Issa, N., Stryker, M., & Keck, W. (2001). infants. Developmental Science.
Sleep enhances plasticity of the developing Hupbach, A., Gómez, R., Hardt, O., & Nadel, L.
visual cortex. Neuron, 30, 275–287. (2007). Reconsolidation of episodic memories:
Gais, S., Plihal, W.,Wagner, U., & Born, J. (2000). A subtle reminder triggers integration of new
Early sleep triggers memory for early visual information. Learning & Memory, 14, 47–53.
discrimination skills. Nature Neuroscience, 3, Hupbach, A., Hardt, O., Gómez, R., & Nadel, L.2008.
1335–1339. The dynamics of memory: Context-dependent
Gais, S., Albouy, G., Boly, M., Thien Thanh, D-V, updating. Learning & Memory, 15, 574–579.
Darsaud, A., Desseilles, M., et al. (2007). Sleep Hupbach, A., Gómez, R. L., & Nadel, L. Memory
transforms the cerebral trace of declarative capacity increases between 5- and 9-years of
memories. Proceedings of the National Academy age, but memory reconsolidation is present at
of Sciences USA, 104, 18778–18783. both ages. Manuscript in preparation.
Galluccio, L. (2005). Updating reactivated memo- Johnson, S. P., & Aslin, R. N. (1995). Perception
ries in infancy: I. Passive- and active-exposure of object unity in 2-month-old infants.
effects. Developmental Psychobiology, 47, 1–17. Developmental Psychology, 31, 739–745.
Galluccio, L., & Rovee-Collier, C. (2005). Updating Johnson, S. P., Bremner, J. G., Slater, A., Mason,
reactivated memories in infancy: II. Time pas- U., Foster, K., & Cheshire, A. (2003). Infants’
sage and repetition effects. Developmental perception of object trajectories. Child
Psychobiology, 47, 18–30. Development, 74, 94–108.
Gergely, G., Nádasdy, Z., Csibra, G., & Bíró, S. Johnson, S. P., Davidow, J., Hall-Haro, C., & Frank,
(1999). Taking the intentional stance at 12 M. C. (2008). Development of perceptual com-
months of age. Cognition, 56, 165–193. pletion originates in information acquisition.
Gerken, L. A., & Bollt, A. (2008). Three exemplars Developmental Psychology, 44, 1214–1224.
allow at least some linguistic generalizations: Jones, S. S., & Smith, L. B. (2002). How children
Implications for generalization mechanisms. know the relevant properties for generaliz-
Language Learning and Development, 4, 228–248. ing object names. Developmental Science, 5,
Gertner, S., Greenbaum, C., Sadeh, A., Dolfi n, Z., 219–232.
Sirota, L., & Ben-Nun, Y. (2002). Sleep–wake Karni, A., Tanne, D., Rubenstein, B. S., Askenasy,
patterns in preterm infants and 6 month’s home J. J., & Sagi, D. (1994). Dependence on REM
PROCESSING CONSTR AINTS ON LEARNING 211

sleep of overnight improvement of a perceptual McCrink, K., & Wynn, K. (2007). Ratio abstrac-
skill. Science 265, 679–82. tion by 6-month-old infants. Psychological
Keele, S. W., Ivry, R., Mayr, U., Hazeltine, E., Science, 18, 740–745.
& Heuer, H. (2003). The cognitive and neu- McGaugh, J. L. (2000). Memory—A century of
ral architecture of sequence representation. consolidation. Science, 287, 248–251.
Psychological Review, 110, 316–339. Misanin, J. R., Miller, R. R., & Lewis, D. J. (1968).
Kellman, P., & Spelke, E. (1983). Perception of Retrograde amnesia produced by electrocon-
partly occluded objects in infancy. Cognitive vulsive shock after reactivation of a consoli-
Psychology, 15, 483–524. dated memory trace. Science, 160, 554–555.
Kemler Nelson, D. G., Jusczyk, P. W., Mandel, D. Markman. E. M., & Hutchison, J. E. (1984).
R., Myers, J., Turk, A., & Gerken, L. A. (1995). Children’s sensitivity to constraints on word
The head-turn preference procedure for test- meaning: Taxonomic vs. thematic relations.
ing auditory perception. Infant Behavior and Cognitive Psychology, 16, 1–27.
Development, 18, 111–116. Muellbacher, W., Ziemann, U., Wissel, J., Dang,
Kirkham, N. Z., Slemmer, J. A., & Johnson, S. P. N., Kofler, M., & Facchini, S. (2002). Early con-
(2002). Visual statistical learning in infancy: solidation in human primary motor cortex.
Evidence for a domain general learning mech- Nature, 415, 640–644.
anism. Cognition, 83, B35–B42. Nader, K., Schafe, G. E., & Le Doux, J. E. (2000).
Kleitman, N., & Engelmann T. (1953). Sleep Fear memories require protein synthesis in the
characteristics of infants. Journal of Applied amygdala for reconsolidation after retrieval.
Physiolology, 6, 263–282. Nature, 406, 722–726.
Korman, M., Raz, N., Flash, T., & Karni, A. (2003). Nadel, L. (2007). Hippocampus and context revis-
Multiple shifts in the representation of a motor ited. In S. J. Y. Mizumori (Ed.), Hippocampal
sequence during the acquisition of skilled per- place fields: Relevance to learning and memory
formance. Proceedings of the National Academy (pp. 3–15). New York: Oxford University Press.
of Sciences USA, 100, 12492–12497. Nadel, L., & Hupbach, A. (2008). The hippocam-
Lany, J. A., & Gómez, R. L.2008. Twelve-month- pus in infancy. In M. Haith & J. Benson (Eds.),
olds benefit from prior experience in sta- The encyclopedia of infant and early childhood
tistical learning. Psychological Science, 19, development (Vol. 2, pp. 89–96). San Diego:
1247–1252. Academic Press.
Lany, J. A., & Gómez, R. L. (in press). Prior expe- Peigneux, P., Laureys, S., Fuchs, S., Collette, F.,
rience shapes abstraction and generalization Perrin, F., & Reggers, J. (2004). Are spatial
in language acquisition. In M. Banich & D. memories strengthened in the human hippo-
Caccamise (Eds.), Optimizing generalization campus during slow wave sleep? Neuron, 44,
of knowledge: Multidisciplinary perspectives. 535–545.
Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Peigneux, P., Laureys, S., Fuchs, S., Destrebecqz,
Lewis, D. J. (1979). Psychobiology of active and A., Collette, F., et al. (2003). Learned material
inactive memory. Psychonomic Bulletin, 86, content and acquisition level modulate cerebral
1054–1083. reactivation during posttraining rapid eye-
Loftus, E. F. (2005). Planting misinformation in movements sleep. Neuroimage 20, 125–134.
the human mind: A 30-year investigation of the Plihal, W., & Born, J. (1997). Effects of early and
malleability of memory. Learning & Memory, late nocturnal sleep on priming and spatial
12, 361–366. memory. Psychophysiology, 36, 571–582.
Louis, J., Cannard, C., Bastuji, H., & Challamell, Polka, L., & Werker, J. F. (1994). Developmental
M-J. (1997). Sleep ontogenesis revisited: A lon- changes in perception of nonnative vowel
gitudinal 24-hour home polygraphic study on contrasts. Journal of Experimental Psychology:
15 normal infants during the first two years of Human Perception and Performance, 20,
life. Sleep, 20, 323–333. 421–435.
Maquet, P., Laureys, S., Peigneux., P., Fuchs., S., Saff ran, J. R., Aslin, R. N., & Newport, E. L. (1996a).
Petiau, C., & Phillips, C. (2000). Experience- Statistical learning by eight-month-old infants
dependent changes in cerebral activation dur- Science, 274, 1926–1928.
ing human REM sleep. Nature Neuroscience, 3, Saff ran, J., Newport, E., & Aslin, R. (1996b).
831–836. Word segmentation: The role of distributional
212 LEARNING MECHANISMS

cues. Journal of Memory and Language, 35, Toro, J. M., & Trobalón, J. B. (2005). Statistical
606–621. computations over a speech stream in a rodent.
Saff ran, J., Newport, E., Aslin, R., Tunick, R., & Perception & Psychophysics, 67, 867–875.
Barrueco, S. (1997). Incidental language learn- Wagner, U., Gais, S., Haider, H., Verleger, R., &
ing: Listening (and learning) out of the corner Born, J. (2004). Sleep inspires insight. Nature,
of your ear. Psychological Science, 8, 101–05. 427, 352–355.
Sara, S. J. (2000). Retrieval and reconsolida- Walker, M. P., Brakefield, T., Morgan, A., Hobson,
tion: Toward a neurobiology of remembering. J. A., & Stickgold, R. (2002a). Practice with
Learning & Memory, 7, 73–84. sleep makes perfect: Sleep-dependent motor
Squire, L. R., Cohen, N. J., & Nadel, L. (1984). The skill learning. Neuron 35, 205–211.
medial temporal region and memory consoli- Walker, M. P., Brakefield, T., Hobson, J. A., &
dation: A new hypothesis. In H. Weingartner Stickgold, R. (2003). Dissociable stages of
& E. Parker (Eds.), Memory consolida- human memory consolidation and reconsoli-
tion (pp. 185–210). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence dation. Nature 425, 616–620.
Erlbaum. Walker, M. P., Liston, C., Hobson, J. A., & Stickgold,
Smith, L .B., Jones, S. S., Landau, B., Gershkoff- R. (2002b). Cognitive flexibility across the
Stowe, L., & Samuelson, L. (2002). Object name sleepwake cycle: REM-sleep enhancement of
learning provides on-the-job training for atten- anagram problem solving. Cognitive Brain
tion. Psychological Science, 13, 13–19. Research, 14, 317–324.
Spencer, R. M., Sunm, M., & Ivry, R. B. (2006). Walker, M. P., & Stickgold, R. (2006). Sleep, mem-
Sleep-dependent consolidation of contextual ory and plasticity. Annual Review of Psychology,
learning. Current Biology, 16, 1001–1005. 57, 139–166.
Stickgold, R., James, L., & Hobson, J. A. (2000a). Visual Werker, J. F., & Tees, R. C. (1984). Cross-language
discrimination learning requires posttraining speech perception: Evidence for perceptual
sleep. Nature Neuroscience, 2, 1237–1238. reorganization during the first year of life.
Stickgold, R., Whidbee, D., Schirmer, B., Patel, V., Infant Behavior and Development, 7, 49–63.
& Hobson, J. A. (2000b). Visual discrimina- Wilson, M., & McNaughton, B. (1994). Reactivation
tion task improvement: A multi-step process of hippocampal ensemble memories during
occurring during sleep. Journal of Cognitive sleep. Science 265, 676–679.
Neuroscience, 12, 246–254. Woodward, A. L. (2005). The infant origins of
Terrace, H. S., Chen, S., & Jaswal, V. (1996). Recall intentional understanding. In R. V. Kail (Ed.),
of three-item sequences by pigeons. Animal Advances in child development and behavior
Learning & Behavior, 24, 193–205. (Vol. 33, pp. 229–262). Oxford: Elsevier.
Terrace, H. S., Son, L. K., & Brannon, E. M. Wynn, K. (1992). Addition and subtraction by
(2003). Serial expertise of rhesus macaques. human infants. Nature, 358, 749–750.
Psychological Science, 14, 66–73. Xu, F. & Garcia, V. (2008). Intuitive statistics
Thoman, E. (1990). Sleeping and waking states in by 8-month-old infants. Proceedings of the
infants: A functional perspective. Neuroscience National Academy of Sciences USA, 105,
of Biobehavioral Reviews, 14, 93–107. 5012–5015.
CHAP TER 11
Mixing the Old with the New and the New
with the Old: Combining Prior and Current
Knowledge in Conceptual Change

Denis Mareschal and Gert Westermann

One of the greatest challenges facing the This tension between needing to hold on to
developing child is knowing how to combine your beliefs while at the same time updating
new experiences with existing prior knowl- and constructing a system of world knowledge
edge. Th roughout infancy and childhood, the is central to many theories of cognitive develop-
growing child continually explores the world. ment. Indeed, Piaget’s notions of assimilation,
She soon discovers new objects, new events, accommodation, and equilibration (e.g., Piaget,
and new situations that she has never been con- 1952) capture the idea that cognitive develop-
fronted with before. Th is raises an important ment consists of a balancing act between these
conundrum. On the one hand, she will want to two sources of information.
learn from the new experiences. She will there- While many authors recognize this problem,
fore need to adjust her world model (or world few have tackled it straight on (see Keil, 1984 for
knowledge) in response to the new events so one important exception). One reason for this
that next time a similar event is encountered, dearth of research is that answers to this prob-
she will be able to draw on her prior experi- lem require researchers to be explicit about how
ences to respond rapidly to this new situation. knowledge is represented, how learning takes
On the other hand, because of the stochastic places, and how the learning of new knowledge
nature of experiences in the world, she will not affects previously stored knowledge. These are
know how representative or important a new the questions that computational modeling
experience is, and thus to what extent it needs can attempt to answer. Implemented computer
to be remembered and her world knowledge models force the researcher to be explicit about
revised. such things as knowledge representations,
Consider the example of a young child learn- learning mechanisms, and how one affects the
ing about birds. Perhaps as a 2-year-old, she has other (Mareschal & Thomas, 2007; Mareschal
encountered a dozen different bird types and et al. 2007a; Lewandowski, 1991).
has a clear idea that birds fly. Then, on an out- In this chapter, we will examine two
ing to the zoo, she is confronted with an ostrich approaches to resolving the question of how
that clearly does not fly. Should this child revise prior knowledge and current knowledge inter-
her beliefs about birds to remove the constraint act in category learning. The first relies on
that birds fly? The answer to this question will mathematical models of statistical inference.
depend on how representative the ostrich is The second is an implemented connectionist
of the birds that she is likely to meet and how computational model. To illustrate the useful-
important it is to know that not all birds fly. ness of these latter models, we will sketch out

213
214 LEARNING MECHANISMS

a possible connectionist model of how prior Chater, 2007, for a more detailed discussion of
knowledge and on-line learning integrate dur- Bayesian inference and reasoning).
ing early concept learning.
BAYESIAN STUMBLING BLOCKS
THE BAYESIAN PROPOSAL
At the heart of this Bayesian “revolution” in
One promising approach to the problem of developmental research is the desire to under-
how prior knowledge affects on-line learning stand how prior knowledge combines with
directly during development draws on concepts on-line learning. However, as models of devel-
taken from Bayesian statistical inference. The opment, the current Bayesian proposals still have
Bayesian approach has been adopted by a num- a number of obstacles to overcome (see Shultz,
ber of researchers with slightly different theo- 2007). First, current developmental models
retical frameworks (e.g., Gopnik & Tenenbaum, never state where the prior distribution informa-
2007; Gopnik et al., 2004; Xu & Tenenbaum, tion comes from (e.g., Gopnik et al., 2004; Xu &
2007; see also chapter by Sobel in this volume) Tennebaum, 2007—though see the Sobel chap-
who explicitly ask how prior knowledge influ- ter in this volume for an initial discussion of this
ences inferences that can be drawn from evi- issue). Without such information, the models are
dence acquired in the here and now. The basic no longer developmental. Instead of explaining
idea is that the inferences that we make based how a child or infant gets from one level of com-
on current events are modulated by our prior petence to the next, it becomes a model of how
beliefs about the distribution of events in the children at different ages (with different prior
world (see Box 11.1: Bayesian inference). So, for probability assumptions) function. This is cer-
example, imagine that you are returning home tainly informative, but falls into the same trap
from work to what you believe to be a safe low- that many rule-based models of cognitive devel-
crime neighborhood. As you turn into your opment fell into in the 1970s and early 1980s
street, you see a masked man running down (Sternberg, 1984; Shultz, Schmidt, Buckingham,
the road past you. Masked men are often associ- & Mareschal, 1995). While theoreticians were
ated with burglaries so you could image that the able to come up with sets of rules that captured
most likely interpretation of this event is that children’s thinking at different ages (e.g., Klahr
there has been a burglary near by. However, & Wallace, 1978; Young, 1979), they were never
suppose you now consider the fact that there has truly able to come up with a plausible learning
not been a burglary in your neighborhood for algorithm that would enable a system to move
well over 10 years. Based on this prior experi- from one set of rules describing a 3-year-old
ence, the likelihood that there has actually been to a second set of rules describing a 5-year-old.
a burglary seems reduced. In fact, in light of this Without explaining transitions, development has
information, it may seem more likely that there not been explained (Elman et al., 1996; Mareschal
is some other (perhaps initially more complex et al, 2007a; Sternberg, 1984; Simon, 1963; Simon
or less frequent) explanation for why a masked & Halford, 1995; Thelen & Smith, 1994).
man is running down your street (for example, Fortunately, this is not the death knell for
that it is Halloween).1 the Bayesian approach. Indeed, it is not in
The point of this example is to illustrate how principle impossible to come up with a mech-
often and how naturally we draw inferences anism by which prior probability distributions
not only on the basis of the events that we are would change with experience. In fact, this
experiencing right now, but also on the basis is a very active research question in machine
of probabilistic knowledge of the distribution learning (Mackay, 2003) but, as we shall see
of events that occurred before (see Oaksford & below, answering such questions may require
researchers to commit a little more forcefully
to the machinery that underlies learning and
1
Th is example is adapted from Anderson (1990). knowledge representation.
Box 11.1 Bayesian Inference and Bayesian Belief Networks

Bayesian approaches are increasingly popular in Artificial Intelligence (MacKay, 2003;


Mitchel, 1997), visual sciences (Kersten, Mamassian, & Yuille, 2003), and the human reason-
ing literature (Heit, 1998; Oaksford & Chater, 2007). All of these approaches share a set of
fundamental principles derived from Bayesian statistics. More specifically, Bayesian theory is
a branch of mathematical probability theory that allows one to model uncertainty about the
world and outcomes of interest by combining commonsense knowledge and observational
evidence. Bayesian inference involves starting with a predefined set of hypotheses about
events in the world, then collecting evidence that is meant to be consistent or inconsistent
with a given hypothesis. As evidence accumulates, the degree of belief in the hypotheses is
changed. As a result of these changes, our belief in certain prior hypotheses will often become
very high or very low.
This change in beliefs can be embodied mathematically using a simple theorem from prob-
ability theory. Bayes’ theorem adjusts probabilities of hypotheses given new evidence in the
following way:
Prob(H|E) = [Prob(E|H)]/[Prob(H) × Prob(E)] where:

• Prob(H) represents the probability (according to our prior beliefs) of a hypothesis before
new evidence (E) became available. This is called the prior probability of hypothesis H.
• Prob(E | H) is the probability of seeing the evidence E if hypothesis H is indeed true. This is
sometimes referred to as the conditional probability of observing E if H is true.
• Prob(E) is the probability of witnessing the new evidence (E) under all circumstances.
• P(H|E) is the probability that H is indeed true given that we have just observed E. This is
sometimes called the posterior probability of H and reflects our belief that H is true after
observing some new evidence E.
The factor [Prob(E|H)]/[Prob(E)] represents the impact that the evidence has on the belief
(Prob(H)] that the hypothesis H0 is true. If it is likely that the evidence will be observed when
the hypothesis under consideration is true, then this factor will be large. Multiplying the prior
probability of the hypothesis by this factor would result in a large posterior probability of the
hypothesis given the evidence. In a sense, Bayes’ theorem reflects how much new evidence
should alter a belief in a hypothesis. Such procedures are used in models of word and category
learning (e.g., Xu & Tenenbaum, 2007).
A related but distinct set of formalisms are called Bayesian Belief Networks (Gopnik et al.,
2004; Pearl, 2000). A belief network involves (1) a set of variables, (2) a graphical structure
connecting the variables, and (3) a set of conditional distributions over the values of these
variables.
A belief network is commonly represented as a graph, which is a set of vertices and edges.
The vertices, or nodes, represent the variables and the edges, which represent the conditional
dependencies in the model. The absence of an arc between two variables indicates conditional
independence; that is, there are no situations in which the probabilities of one of the variables
depend directly upon the state of the other. Prior causal knowledge about the relating between
the variables is often used to guide the connections made in the graph to specify the initial
conditional distributions between the variables. Bayesian statistics (such as that described
above) can then be used to update the links in the graph as a function of new evidence.

215
216 LEARNING MECHANISMS

A second problem with current Bayesian Marr’s approach has dominated much of
models of development is that they generally cognitive science research since the 1980s (e.g.,
operate in “batch mode”: when drawing infer- Fodor, 1983; Pylyshyn, 1984). It has been par-
ences on the basis of currently available infor- ticularly influential (albeit indirectly) in devel-
mation, they compute the probability of events opmental theorizing. Indeed, much theoretical
occurring over the whole set of available events work in the 1980s and early 1990s chose to
(e.g., I observe 10 birds at the zoo and then focus only on the computational level, putting
calculate the frequency of observing wings by aside questions of how the cognitive processes
summing over all the birds I have encountered proposed were carried out and how they might
during my visit). This is unlikely to be plausible be implemented in the brain (Carey, 1985; Keil,
as (1) children have limited working memories 1989; Marcus, 2001; Gelman, 2003; Mandler,
and (2) in the real world, it is unlikely that we 2004). However, both in the adult and in the
experience a whole clustered set of events like developmental literature, several groups of
that. Therefore, while the Bayesian approach researchers have begun to argue that this arti-
may work well for modeling inferences that are ficial partitioning of levels cannot work (e.g.,
drawn on the basis of the complete set of infor- Elman et al., 1996; Mareschal et al., 2007a;
mation provided during a test session in an Rumelhart & McClelland, 1986; Thelen &
experiment, it seems implausible as an account Smith, 1994).
of how the child learns in the real world. Again, There are two main reasons why we believe
this is not an insurmountable problem, but one that the different levels of description cannot
that modelers and theoreticians need to address be studied independently (see Mareschal et
if their models are to be taken seriously as al., 2007). The first is for reasons of computa-
explaining cognitive development. tional efficiency. While it is true that different
A third, and to our mind the greatest, prob- computations can be carried out in a multitude
lem with the Bayesian approach has to do with of different ways (thus, the computational and
the fact that it is restricted to the computational algorithmic levels may appear separate), these
level of description (Chater, Tenenbaum & will have different resources costs. So, it may
Yuille, 2006; Gopnik & Tenenbaum, 2007). The be possible to construct a rule-following sys-
computational level is one of the three levels tem from a neural network (e.g., Touretzky &
of description proposed by Marr (1982). Marr Pomerlo, 1994), but this is very computationally
argued that (cognitive) computational systems expensive. Similarly, while it may be possible to
could be studied at three independent levels. The construct a context-sensitive parallel processing
first (top) level was the computational level that system from rules (Newell, 1990), this as well
specified what needed to be computed to solve turns out to be very computationally expensive,
a particular problem (e.g., when interpreting a requiring many rules and a complex control
visual scene, figure/ground segmentation must system. Thus, decisions made at the algorithmic
be computed to determine what are objects and and implementation levels do impinge on the
what is background to make sense of the scene). computational level if resource constraints are
The second level was the algorithmic level that taken into consideration.
specified how the computation was carried out In fact, resource constraints are particu-
(e.g., perhaps using an edge detection strategy). larly important in systems that are dynami-
Finally, the implementational level specified cally evolving such as the developing brain. The
how the algorithm was implemented in the par- developing system only responds (adapts) to
ticular hardware used (e.g., how edge detection local pressures, without a global view of what it
would be implemented in a neural network). should be developing toward. Thus, at any point
According to Marr, each of the levels could be in development, it is likely to select the least
studied independently because what happens at computationally expensive (hence easiest to
one level is not dependent on decisions made at implement) computational solution. As a result,
another level. there will be a bias toward solutions emerging at
MIXING THE OLD WITH THE NEW AND THE NEW WITH THE OLD 217

each level that are most easily reconcilable with Instead, they attempt to strike the balance
the constraints at work at the other levels. between importing some of the key ideas from
The second reason is that models that focus the neurosciences while maintaining sufficiently
only on the computational level (with no com- discrete and definable components to allow
mitment to how the computations are carried questions about behavior to be formulated in
out or how they are implemented in the brain) terms of a high-level computational concepts.
are generally unable to say anything about Connectionist networks are an ideal tool for
how the system goes wrong. In other words, modeling development because they develop
they cannot predict the kind of errors children their own internal representations as a result
will make when cognitive load is exceeded or of interacting with an environment (Plunkett
what kind of errors atypically developing chil- & Sinha, 1991). However, these networks are
dren with developmental disorders will make. not simply tabula rasa empiricist learning
Indeed, recent research has found a host of dif- machines. The representations they develop
ferent subtle behavioral patterns arising in chil- can be strongly predetermined by initial con-
dren with a range of developmental disorders straints. These constraints can take the form
(Karmiloff-Smith, 1998). These patterns betray of different associative learning mechanisms
not only the different adaptations that have attuned to specific information in the envi-
been made to altered constraints arising from ronment (e.g., temporal correlation or spatial
an atypical genome, but also the kind of plastic- correlation), or they can take the form of archi-
ity and compensation that is possible in a given tectural constraints that guide the flow of infor-
system given the implementational constraints mation in the system. Although connectionist
(Thomas & Karmiloff-Smith, 2002). modeling has its roots in associationist learning
Thus, while current Bayesian accounts may paradigms, it has inherited the Hebbian rather
provide us with a description of what children than the Hullian tradition. That is, what goes on
need to do to combine prior knowledge with inside the network is as important in determin-
current online learning, they do not provide us ing the overall behavior of the networks as is the
with a causal account of how this is done that correlation between the inputs (stimuli) and the
will allow us to understand and predict the outputs (responses).
kinds of errors observed in typically and atypi- In the next section, we will illustrate how
cally developing children. a connectionist system (Box 11.2) can be used
to investigate how prior knowledge and on-
line learning combine to explain behaviors
CONNECTIONIST SOLUTIONS
both across developmental time and real time.
So what is the solution? The solution is to con- We focus on the domain of concept learning
sider cognitive computational models that take because it typifies a domain were prior knowl-
seriously constraints from at least the algorith- edge and current experience interact heavily.
mic level. Connectionist neural networks pro-
vide one such tool (Elman et al., 1994; Shultz,
2003; see also chapter by Christiansen, Dale MODELING INFANT CATEGORY LEARNING
& Reali in this volume), though other valid
How Do Infants Form Categories?
approaches also exist (see Mareschal et al.,
2007a, 2007b). Forming categories is one of the most fundamen-
Connectionist models are computer models tal aspects of cognitive processing. Therefore,
loosely based on the principles of neural infor- studying the development of this ability in
mation processing (Elman, Bates, Johnson, infancy is vital for understanding the basics of
Karmiloff-Smith, Parisi, & Plunkett, 1996; cognitive processing as a whole. As infants can-
McLeod, Plunkett, & Rolls, 1998; Rumelhart not speak and communicate their knowledge
& McClellend, 1986). However, they are not verbally, nonlinguistic methods of probing early
intended to be models of neurons in the brain. categorization have been developed. However,
Box 11.2 Connectionist Information Processing

Connectionist networks are made up of simple processing units (idealized neurons) intercon-
nected via weighted communication lines (idealized synapses). Units are often represented as
circles and the weighted communication lines, as lines between these circles. Activation flows
from unit to unit via these connection weights. Figure B11.1 shows a generic connectionist
network in which activation can flow in any direction. However most applications of connec-
tionist networks impose constraints on the way activation can flow.
Figure B11.1 also shows a typical feed-forward network. Activation (information) is con-
strained to move in one direction only. Some units (those units through which information
enters the network) are called input units. Other units (those units through which informa-
tion leaves the network) are called output units. All other units are called hidden units. In a
feed-forward network, information is first encoded as a pattern of activation across the bank

A B Output units

Hidden
units

Input units

Figure B11.1 Schema of (A) a generic and (B) a feed-forward connectionist network.

of input units. That activation then fi lters up through a first layer of weights until it produces
a pattern of activation across the band of hidden units. The pattern of activation produced
across the hidden units constitutes an internal re-representation of the information originally
presented to the network. The activation at the hidden units continues to flow through the
network until it reaches the output unit. The pattern of activation produced at the output units
is taken as the network’s response to the initial input.
Each unit is a very simple processor that mimics the functioning of an idealized neuron.
The unit sums the weighted activation arriving into it. It then sets it own level of activation
according to some nonlinear function of that weighted input. The nonlinearity allows the
units to respond differentially to different ranges of input values. The key idea of connectionist
modeling is that of collective computations. That is, although the behavior of the individual
components in the network is simple, the behavior of the network as a whole can be very
complex. It is the behavior of the network as a whole that is taken to model different aspect of
infant behaviors.
The network’s global behavior is determined by the connection weights. As activation
flows through the network, it is transformed by the set of connection weights between succes-
sive layers in the network. Learning (i.e., adapting one’s behavior) is accomplished by tuning
the connection weights until some stable behavior is obtained. Supervised networks adjust

218
MIXING THE OLD WITH THE NEW AND THE NEW WITH THE OLD 219

their weights until the output response (for a given input) matches a target response. That
target can come from an active teacher, or passively through observing the environment, but
it must come from outside the system. Unsupervised networks adjust their weights until some
internal constraint is satisfied (e.g., maximally different input must have maximally different
internal representations). Backpropagation (Rumelhart, Hinton, & Williams, 1986) is a popu-
lar training algorithm for supervised connectionist networks.
Many connectionist network models are very simple and only contain some 100 units.
This does not imply that the part of the brain solving the corresponding task only uses 100
neurons. It is important to understand that these models are not neural models but informa-
tion processing models of behavior. The models provide examples of how systems with similar
computational properties to the brain can give rise to the behaviors observed in infants. As
such, they constitute possible explanations of those behaviors in terms of neurally plausible
mechanisms. Sometimes, individual units are taken to represent pools of neurons or cell
assemblies rather than single neurons. According to this interpretation, the activation level
of the units corresponds to the proportion of neurons firing in the pool (e.g., Changeux &
Dehaene, 1989).

different methods have yielded sometimes con- evidence that infants under 6 months of age
flicting results on infants’ categorization abili- can form perceptual categories even of complex
ties (Mareschal & Quinn, 2001; see also chapters visual stimuli such as different animals and fur-
by Rakison & Chicchino and Quinn in this vol- niture items (Mareschal & Quinn, 2001; Quinn
ume), making it difficult to integrate them into & Eimas, 1996a; Quinn, Eimas, & Rosenkrantz,
an overall picture of category development. 1993). The level (global or basic) at which
One set of methodologies by which infant objects are categorized is dependent on the
categorization has been studied relies on the variability and distribution of information in
fact that infants tend to show a preference for the environment (Mareschal, French, & Quinn,
novel stimuli (Fantz, 1964). Studies exploiting 2000; French, Mareschal, Memillod, & Quinn,
this novelty preference usually employ a famil- 2004). For example, in one study (Quinn &
iarization stage in which infants are shown a Eimas, 1996b), 3- to 4-month-olds were famil-
sequence of images of objects from one cate- iarized with cats and subsequently were shown
gory (e.g., cats) on a computer screen. The time to have formed a basic-level category repre-
that the infants spend looking at each image is sentation of domestic cats that excluded birds,
measured and is expected to decrease as infants dogs, horses, and tigers. Likewise, when famil-
become familiarized with the objects. Th is stage iarized with chairs, infants formed a basic-level
is followed by a test phase in which infants are category representation of chairs that excluded
shown novel stimuli from the familiarized cat- couches, beds, and sofas. In a different study
egory (e.g., a novel cat) and stimuli from a dif- (Behl-Chada, 1996), 3- to 4-month-olds were
ferent category (e.g., a dog). Preference for the familiarized on different mammals, resulting
object from the different category can then be in their forming of a global-level category rep-
taken as evidence that the infants have formed a resentation of mammals that included novel
category representation that includes the novel mammals but excluded nonmammals such as
category member (the novel cat) but excludes birds and fish, as well as furniture. When famil-
the object from the other category (the dog). iarized with different furniture items, infants
Research based on this paradigm has provided formed a global-level category representation
220 LEARNING MECHANISMS

of furniture that included novel furniture items Whereas the results from preferential
but excluded mammals. It therefore seems that looking and generalized imitation studies seem
infants at 3 to 4 months can show categorization to contradict each other, with infants in prefer-
on different levels. However, it has been argued ential looking studies showing categorical dif-
that even younger infants appear to form global ferentiation much earlier than in generalized
distinctions only (Quinn & Johnson, 2000). imitation studies, a possible reconciliation can
Other experimental paradigms are not be suggested by highlighting the different task
based on novelty preference and do not involve requirements in these paradigms. Preferential
a familiarization stage. For example, in the looking studies examine within-task on-line
generalized imitation paradigm (Mandler & category formation and analyze looking behav-
McDonough, 1996), infants are shown a sim- ior to infer category formation. Generalized
ple action involving toy figures, such as giv- imitation studies tap into background knowl-
ing a cup of drink to a dog. The infant is then edge and require complex motor responses.
encouraged to imitate this event with different Thus, we argue that these different studies can
toys, for example, a different dog, a cat, or a car. be construed as providing a set of collective
Category formation is inferred from observ- insights into the development of a complex neu-
ing to which novel objects the infants general- rocognitive system that contains multiple inter-
ize the modeled action. Due to the absence of acting memory systems.
familiarization, this kind of task is assumed The existence of multiple memory systems is
to tap into the background knowledge that well established in the adult literature (Ashby &
infants have acquired during their everyday Ell, 2001; McClelland, McNaughton, & O’Reilly,
experiences (Mandler, 2000). In this paradigm, 1995). Simply speaking, the idea is that there is a
it has been found that global category distinc- division of labor between a fast learning system
tions (such as animals vs. vehicles) emerge in the hippocampus and a slow learning corti-
first at around 7 months of age, whereas basic cally based system. The hippocampus is respon-
level distinctions (such as cats vs. dogs) do not sible for the rapid learning of new information,
appear until around 14 months of age (Mandler whereas cortical representations develop more
& McDonough, 1998). gradually and integrate new with previously
The different experimental paradigms used in learned knowledge. Here we suggest that this
infant category formation have also given rise to approach can also account for the unfolding
conflicting theories of the mechanisms underly- categorization abilities in infants.
ing early categorization. According to one view Although little is known so far about the
(e.g., Quinn, 2004), early category formation development of memory systems in infancy,
is entirely based on the perceptual properties Nelson (1995) has hypothesized that novelty
of observed objects. With increasing experi- preference in infants relies on a hippocampal
ence, interacting with objects, and the onset preexplicit memory system that is functional
of language, representations gradually become from shortly after birth. According to Nelson,
enriched to transcend this purely perceptual explicit memory becomes functional only after
information toward more abstract concepts. By 6 months of age. It is based on the hippocampus
contrast, a dual process view of category forma- as well as on cortical areas such as inferotem-
tion (e.g., Mandler, 2000) assumes two separate poral cortex and entorhinal cortex. For explicit
mechanisms for perceptual and conceptual memory to become fully functional, it is thus
categorization, respectively. According to this necessary to develop the entire hippocampus,
view, the perceptual mechanism is operational the relevant cortical areas, as well as connections
from birth, and a conceptual mechanism devel- between hippocampus and cortex. Furthermore,
ops in the second half of the first year of life. complex tasks such as deferred imitation appear
Category formation is then based on integrat- to rely on interactions between the two memory
ing the separate representations emerging from systems, involving the hippocampus as well as
both mechanisms. occipital, premotor, left inferior prefrontal, and
MIXING THE OLD WITH THE NEW AND THE NEW WITH THE OLD 221

frontal cortices. From this perspective, it is clear output error requires more adaptation steps and
that categorization tasks relying on cortical thus can be likened to an infant’s longer looking
representations will show a later development time.
of categories than those relying on preferential While simple autoencoder models have been
looking. successful in accounting for different results
from infant looking time studies, they do not
Previous Connectionist Models of
take prior knowledge into consideration. Thus,
Infant Categorization
they can only be applied in simulations of with-
Previous connectionist models of infant cat- in-task category formation that involves famil-
egorization have often employed autoencoder iarization and does not take into account the
neural networks (Mareschal, French, & Quinn, infant’s background knowledge. In the context
2000; Mareschal & French, 2000; Westermann of Nelson’s (1995) framework of memory devel-
& Mareschal, 2004). These are simple three- opment, simple autoencoders would implement
layer backpropagation models in which input preexplicit memory only. However, a compre-
and target are the same, that is, the model learns hensive understanding of infant categorization
to reproduce its input on the output side (see requires that the mechanisms of both within-
Figure 11.1). In most autoencoders, the hidden task and long-term category formation are
layer is smaller than the input and output layers, integrated into a single system. Furthermore,
forcing the model to extract regularities from an infant’s background knowledge can have
the input in order to reproduce it. The ratio- an effect even on within-task category forma-
nale behind using these networks for modeling tion. For example, one recent study (Pauen &
infant categorization is that the network error Träuble, 2004) showed that whether infants had
can be linked to infant looking time. One theory cats and dogs at home affected their categori-
of infant novelty preference is that when infants zation of cats and dogs in an experimental set-
look at an object, they gradually build up an ting. In another study, Quinn and Eimas (1998)
internal representation of this object, and look- argued that young infants’ categorization of
ing continues until internal representation and humans versus nonhuman animals in a visual
object match (Sokolov, 1963). The more unusual preference experiment is affected by differential
an object is, the longer it will take to build this experience with members from the two classes
representation, and the longer the object will be that occurs prior to the experiment.
fi xated. Likewise, in the autoencoder, succes- Here we describe a model that extends pre-
sive weight adaptations lead to a match between vious categorization models by investigating
an input (the object) and output (the infant’s the unfolding interactions between different
internal representation of the object). A higher memory systems through development. The

A B Output units: target = input


and test
Decode

Adjust weights

Compare/test Adjust
hidden
units
encode

Encode

Perception Input units


Perception

Figure 11.1 Novelty preference as a process of representation construction in (A) infants and (B) con-
nectionist autoencoder networks. (After Mareschal & French, 2000.)
222 LEARNING MECHANISMS

model is loosely linked to the hippocampal/ until a stable state was reached. Activation was
cortical memory systems in the brain. It then propagated to the output layers. All weights
therefore allows for the investigation of the were adjusted with the backpropagation algo-
development of category representations in rithm at each stimulus presentation.
long-term memory on the basis of experience In the simulations reported here, the net-
with the world as opposed to laboratory-based work parameters were as follows: learning rate
experiments only. By modeling interactions in the hippocampal model, 0.5; learning rate in
between both memory systems, it is also possi- the cortical model, 0.001; learning rates of the
ble to examine the role of previously acquired lateral connections between the networks, 0.01;
knowledge on performance in a laboratory momentum for all weights, 0.4; size of each hid-
task. den layer, 15.

A Dual Memory Model of Categorization The Training Data


in Infancy Photographs of objects from 19 different basic-
The model illustrated in Figure 11.2 consists of level categories previously used to test infants
two linked autoencoder networks, one of which were encoded according to a number of percep-
represents the earliest, preexplicit memory sys- tual features. These were maximal height, mini-
tem based on the hippocampus, and the other mal height, maximal width, minimal width,
represents later memory systems that are largely minimal width of base, number of protrusions,
cortically based. In line with theories of adult maximal length/width of left, right, lower and
memory, the “hippocampal” system is charac- upper protrusion, minimal width of lower pro-
terized by rapid learning (high learning rate) trusion, texture, eye separation, face length,
with susceptibility to interference (catastrophic and face width. These features comprise both
forgetting), and the “cortical” system by slower general (geometric) and object specific (facial)
learning (low learning rate). Unidirectional characteristics. Feature values were scaled
links between the two components implement between 0 and 1.
interactions between the two memory systems. The object categories were chairs, sofas,
Training of the model worked as follows: an tables, beds, drawers, horses, giraffes, birds,
input was presented and activation was propa- rabbits, squirrels, elephants, deer, fishes, cars,
gated to the hidden layers. Activation then was males, and females. They fell into four global-
cycled back and forth between the hidden layers level categories (furniture, animals, vehicles,
(which were updating each other’s activations) humans) all previously used to test infant cat-
egory formation (Quinn & Eimas, 1996b) and
varied in their within-category perceptual simi-
larities. Each category consisted of 10 exemplars
Output = Input Output = Input (for some categories additional exemplars were
created by interpolating the representations of
the measured photos). For each category, a pro-
totype was generated by averaging the represen-
“Hippocampal”
tations of all members of that category.
“Cortical”
The model was trained in two different ways.
Familiarization Training was meant to replicate
the experience of an infant in a laboratory set-
Input
ting: the model was first familiarized on a set of
stimuli until criterion was reached and was then
Figure 11.2 The architecture of the dual mem- tested on test stimuli. Background Training
ory categorization model. (From Westermann & aimed to capture the experience of an infant
Mareschal, in press.) with the world by training on random stimuli
MIXING THE OLD WITH THE NEW AND THE NEW WITH THE OLD 223

for random amounts of time before switching to subdivisions (e.g., male-female; bed-sofa) vis-
a new random stimulus. ible after 1,500 stimuli.2 This result provides an
explanation for the global-to-basic shift in cat-
Development of Long-Term Representations
egory development that is found in nonfamil-
In a first experiment, the hidden representa- iarization tasks.
tions developed by the cortical component of The spread of representations was compared
the model were explored. This was interesting for 10 models each trained with and without lat-
for three reasons: the first was that a neural eral connections between the cortical (LTM) and
network that is trained on a sequence of pat- hippocampal (STM) components. For the mod-
terns can be subject to catastrophic forgetting els trained with lateral interactions, the aver-
(French, 1999) when a new pattern is learned; age pairwise distance between cortical hidden
the representations for previous patterns can representations for all stimuli was 0.74 and for
be overridden and the learned mapping for models trained without lateral connections (i.e.,
these patterns is lost. Here we wanted to inves- with no interaction between memory systems)
tigate if catastrophic forgetting can be avoided this distance was 0.38, which was significantly
through the interactions between the fast and smaller (F(9) = 34.66, p<.0001). Thus, hippocam-
slow components in the model. The second rea- pal input to cortex in addition to direct sensory
son for studying the hidden representations of input led to an increased differentiation of cor-
the model was that there was overlap between tical category representations, indicating that
the perceptual representations of patterns from interactions between memory systems support
different categories. This experiment could differentiation of long-term representations and
therefore show how the model clustered exem- reduce interference between objects.
plars based on perceptual information alone.
Effect of Background Knowledge on
The third reason was the assumption made
Familiarization
in the model that complex responses such as
generalized imitation depend on cortical rep- We investigated the effect of background
resentations. In these tasks, infants show a glob- knowledge of different categories on the time
al-to-basic development of categories and this required to reach familiarization criterion in
could be explained by a similar development of hippocampus-based familiarization tasks. For
cortical category representations. background knowledge to have an effect, cor-
The model was trained in Background tical representations must alter hippocam-
Training mode for 10 epochs, that is, each of the pal representations that arise from perceptual
190 training exemplars were presented to the experience with objects during a familiariza-
model in random order, and for random lengths tion task.
of time (between 1 and 1,000 weight updates), To investigate this question, a simulation
for 10 times. To assess the effect of interactions was carried out in which dogs were used as
between the hippocampal and cortical compo- familiarization items, and prior Background
nents, the model was trained 10 times with lat- Training was on either all items except dogs,
eral connections between the hidden layers, and or on all items except animals. The prediction
10 times without connections. Results were thus was that familiarization times for dogs would
averaged over 10 runs of each model. reduce more when the Background Training
Figure 11.3 shows the development of the data contained animals than when it did not. In
hidden representations for category proto-
types in the cortical component at four points 2
Because of the relatively limited set of image views
in training, after exposure to 5, 50, 100, and used in the training set (e.g., only canonical views of
1,500 stimuli. Over training, the representa- tables), inevitable idiosyncrasies in object representa-
tions become more distinct, with global-level tions arose (e.g., the close similarity between dogs and
tables in the current simulations). A more representative
categories (humans, furniture, animals) already sample of object views would presumably avoid these
well separated after 100 stimuli and basic level spurious similarities.
224 LEARNING MECHANISMS

5 50
0.8 0.8

0.6 0.6

0.4 0.4

0.2 0.2

0 0
bed
drawer
chair
table sofa
car
fish
rabbit
pp pppp p
birdsquirrel
bed
fish
sofa
bird
table
car
rabbit
cat
squirrel
giraffe
chair
deer
dog
elephant
lion
drawer
horse deer
p
lion elephant p p
–0.2 male
femalepp pp p
pppppp pp
–0.2 female giraffe
male p p catdog horse
p p p pp

–0.4 –0.4

–0.6 –0.6

–0.8 –0.8

–1 –1
–0.8 –0.6 –0.4 –0.2 0 0.2 0.4 0.6 0.8 1 –0.8 –0.6 –0.4 –0.2 0 0.2 0.4 0.6 0.8 1
100 1500
0.8 0.8

0.6 0.6

0.4 sofa 0.4


drawer
bed
chair drawer p
chair bed p
car pp p p p
0.2 cat p 0.2 female
malep sofa p
dogdeer p
p fish p deer p
p aarabbit
0 birdp p p 0 cat pcar
female
male pp giraffe p p
lionp dog p table fish p
–0.2 –0.2 lionp p
squirrel p rabbit p
giraffe p elephant p
horse p birdp
–0.4 –0.4

–0.6 –0.6 elephant p


horse p
–0.8 –0.8 squirrel p

–1 –1
–0.8 –0.6 –0.4 –0.2 0 0.2 0.4 0.6 0.8 1 –0.8 –0.6 –0.4 –0.2 0 0.2 0.4 0.6 0.8 1

Figure 11.3 Development of the hidden representations of category prototypes (subscript p) in the
cortical component of the model. Representations are plotted in terms of their first two principal
components. (From Westermann & Mareschal, in press.)

the Animals condition, the model was trained type of background knowledge also made a
on all stimuli, excluding dogs but including difference: models that had prior experience
other animals, for 10 epochs (1,800 exemplars). with animals also familiarized significantly
In the No-Animals condition, the model was faster than those that only had experience with
trained on all stimuli excluding animals for 22 humans, vehicles, and furniture (F(99)= 3.6967,
epochs (1,760 exemplars; training was on more p<.001). This result indicates that prior learn-
epochs than in the Animals condition to ensure ing from experience with the environment can
an approximately equal number of exemplars). affect an infant’s performance in a familiariza-
The results of this simulation are displayed tion experiment in the laboratory.
in Figure 11.4A. Background Training (experi- The effect of prior knowledge on familiariza-
ence with the world) led to a significant decrease tion was further explored for cases in which an
in familiarization time. Familiarization time infant has experience with members of the spe-
(stimulus presentations necessary to reach cific category that is then tested in the laboratory.
error criterion) to dogs was significantly shorter For this simulation, one random dog exemplar
when the model had previous experience with was removed from the stimulus set. Then, the
animals than when it had not been trained on model was background-trained either on the
background knowledge. However, the specific remaining 9 dogs for 20 epochs (180 exemplars),
MIXING THE OLD WITH THE NEW AND THE NEW WITH THE OLD 225

A 40 B 40
** ** ** **

Mean adaptation time (looking time)


Mean adaptation time (looking time)

30 30

20 20

10 10

0 0
Before training All except dogs All except mammals Before training Dogs only Mammals
Background knowledge Background knowledge

Figure 11.4 (A) Familiarization time to dogs depending on different types of prior knowledge. (B)
Familiarization time to dogs depending on whether the model had prior experience with dogs. Results
are averaged over 10 runs. (From Westermann & Mareschal, in press.)

or on all mammals except the extracted dog, for


GENERAL DISCUSSION
2 epochs. (178 exemplars). The result (Figure
11.4B) showed that the model adapted signifi- We began this chapter by reiterating what has
cantly faster to the dog when it had only been been one of the great mysteries of cognitive devel-
trained on the other dogs than on all mam- opment research: How does the developing child
mals (F(9) = 3.7973, p<.01). This result provides learn from new experiences while at the same
further evidence that adaptation time (looking time maintaining a reliable knowledge base? We
time) is affected by experience, and that expe- discussed Bayesian approaches and found that
rience with similar objects reduces adaptation they were promising but failed to address learning
time to novel objects. Conversely, this result and development other than at the computational
also shows that familiarization times are fast- level of description (Marr, 1982). This, we argued,
est when prior experience is maximally simi- made them unable to account for developmental
lar to the stimuli tested in the familiarization transitions and to provide causal explanations
experiment, and that broader experience can that would enable us to explain the errors that
slow down familiarization time compared with atypically developing children make or typically
narrow experience. The mechanism by which developing children make under cognitive strain.
previous experience affects current knowledge We proposed that it was essential to take the other
works through the interactions between the two levels seriously and suggested that connection-
memory systems: when an input is presented to ist methods provided one tool for doing this. To
the model, it activates representations both in illustrate this point, we described a well-specified
the hippocampal and in the cortical network. connectionist model of concept learning that
Through the interconnections between the sys- explains how prior knowledge interacts with on-
tems the long-term representations stored in line learning to explain the patterns of concept
the cortical system feed into the hippocampal learning that are observed in early development.
system, generating an attractor state in the hip- The connectionist simulations reported in
pocampal hidden layer that is a blend between this chapter describe preliminary explorations
the current input and the evoked long-term rep- with a multiple memory model of infant category
resentations for previously experienced similar development. However, they raise some impor-
stimuli. As a consequence the hippocampal rep- tant issues about infant studies. Although famil-
resentation becomes more similar to the current iarization/novelty-preference studies examine
input, reducing the novelty of this input. within-task category formation, the model
226 LEARNING MECHANISMS

suggests that presented stimuli in perceptual Bayesian models are (1) explicit learning mech-
categorization tasks can activate top-down long- anisms, (2) access to the knowledge representa-
term representations that impact on the forma- tions (i.e., with an implemented model we can
tion of representations for the familiarization ask question about how knowledge is repre-
stimuli. It was not necessary for the models to sented internally and how this affects the way
have background knowledge of the specific basic- new knowledge and old knowledge can be com-
level category that was tested in the familiariza- bined), and (3) change over time. By building
tion task. Instead, experience with other animals a computational model, we can observe how
and even nonanimal categories was sufficient to competence gradually changes over time. We
speed up familiarization to dogs. These results can therefore ask how events that occur earlier
highlight the need for assessing both the back- in development will go on to have effects on
ground knowledge of infants and the similarity events happening later in development.
of experimental stimuli to objects known to the Finally, the astute reader may have noticed
infant in experimental familiarization studies. that we opened this chapter by discussing the
The connectionist model also highlighted difficulties of combining prior knowledge with
that it is important to consider which repre- new knowledge and new knowledge with prior
sentations are exploited by different experi- knowledge. The Bayesian approach is really all
mental paradigms. Cortical representations in about the first half of this. That is, it examines
the model show a gradual differentiation from how prior knowledge is used to modify infer-
global-to-basic level categories, suggesting that ences that an individual child might make
tasks based on these representations show the on the basis of recent evidence. However, the
same profile. Thus, the model provides initial Bayesian approach remains quiet about how
evidence that a multiple-memory system per- this new knowledge might influence the old
spective provides a useful framework for under- knowledge (might change the prior probability
standing the development of categorization in distributions). The connectionist model that we
infancy. Beyond just explaining the existing typ- described is explicit about both these mecha-
ical developmental profiles, this framework can nisms. Indeed, there is a pathway for events in
also be used to enable us to explore the effects of STM to affect representation in LTM while rep-
damage or atypical development one or another resentations in LTM affect events in STM.
part of the system. Thus, it acts as a tool for bridg- In sum, the integration of new and old
ing between information processing theories of knowledge during development is at the heart
typically and atypically developing children. of constructivism. The question of how this is
Is connectionist modeling incompatible with achieved has been grappled with since Piaget’s
Bayesian approaches? The answer is a resound- first reflections on this question began almost a
ing no. Because Bayesian models make no century ago. Implemented computational mod-
commitment to the algorithmic level, they are els that are explicit about how knowledge is rep-
consistent with any number of computational resented, and how learning occurs provide the
approaches (see Mitchell, 1997 for an example of tools necessary (we believe) to make substantial
this). It is therefore entirely possible that a sim- progress on this question.
ple connectionist model could be designed that
is consistent with the Bayesian model to explain
aspects of child development (see for example, ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
McClelland & Thompson, 2007). In fact, sub-
This work was supported by EC grants 516542
stantial progress has been made in showing the
(NEST) and ESRC grant RES-000–22-3394.
equivalence between some forms of Bayesian Thanks to Paul C. Quinn for providing the images
learning and existing connectionist learning from which the modeling data was derived and for
algorithms (MacKay, 2003; McClelland, 1998). discussions on an early version of this work, and
The advantages of using connectionist mod- to David Sobel for comments on an earlier draft
els over the principles described by the current of this chapter.
MIXING THE OLD WITH THE NEW AND THE NEW WITH THE OLD 227

REFERENCES Karmiloff-Smith, A. (1998) Development itself


is the key to understanding developmental
Anderson, J. R. (1990) Cognitive psychology and disorders. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 2,
its implications (4th edition). New York, NY: 389–398.
Freeman and Company. Keil, F. C. (1984). Constraints on knowledge and
Ashby, F. G., & Ell, S. W. (2001). The neurobiol- cognitive development. Psychological Review,
ogy of human category learning. Trends in 88, 197–227.
Cognitive Sciences, 5, 204–210. Keil, F. C. (1989). Concepts, kinds, and cognitive
Behl-Chadha, G. (1996). Basic-level and superor- development. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
dinate-like categorical representations in early Kersten, D., Mamassian, P., &Yuille, A. L. (2003).
infancy. Cognition, 60, 105–141. Object Perception as Bayesian Inference
Carey, S. (1985). Conceptual change in childhood. Annual Review of Psychology, 55, 271–304.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Klahr, D., & Wallace, J. G. (1976). Cognitive
Changeux, J. P., & Dehaene, S. (1989). Neuronal development: An information processing view.
models of cognitive function. Cognition, 33, Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
63–109. Lewandowsky, S (1993). The rewards and hazards
Chater, N., Tenenbaum, J. B., & Yuille, A. (2006). of computer simulations. Psychological Science,
Probabilistic models of cognition: Conceptual 4, 236–243.
foundations. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 10, MacKay, D. J. C. (2003). Information theory, infer-
292–293. ence, and learning algorithms. Cambridge:
Elman, J., Bates, E., Johnson, M. H., Karmiloff-Smith, Cambridge University Press
A., Parisi, D., & Plunkett, K. (1996) Rethinking Mandler, J. M. (2000). Perceptual and conceptual
Innateness: A connectionist perspective on devel- processes in infancy. Journal of Cognition and
opment. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Development, 1, 3–36.
Fantz, R. L. (1964). Visual experience in infants: Mandler, J. M. (2004). Foundations of mind:
Decreased attention to familiar patterns rela- Origins of conceptual thought. New York:
tive to novel ones. Science, 146, 668–670. Oxford University Press.
Fodor, J. A. (1983). Modularity of mind. Cambridge, Mandler, J. M., & McDonough, L. (1996). Drinking
MA: MIT Press. and driving don’t mix: Inductive generaliza-
French, R. M. (1999). Catastrophic forgetting in tion in infancy. Cognition, 59, 307–335.
connectionist networks. Trends in Cognitive Mandler, J. M., &. McDonough, L. (1998). On
Sciences. 3, 128–135. developing a knowledge base in infancy.
French, R. M., Mareschal, D., Memillod, M., & Developmental Psychology, 34, 1274–1288.
Quinn P. C. (2004). The role of bottom-up pro- Marcus, G. F. (2001). The algebraic mind:
cessing in perceptual categorization by 3-to Integrating connectionism and cognitive science.
4-month-old infants: Simulations and data. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Journal of Experimental Psychology—General, Mareschal, D., French, R. M., & Quinn, P. (2000). A
133, 382–397. connectionist account of asymmetric category
Gelman, S. A. (2003). The essential child: Origins learning in infancy. Developmental Psychology,
of essentialism in everyday thought. New York: 36, 635–645.
Oxford University Press Mareschal, D., Johnson, M. H., Sirois, S., Spratling,
Gopnik, A., & Tenebaum, J. B. (2007). Bayesian M., Thomas, M., & Westermann, G. (2007a).
networks, Bayesian Learning and cogni- Neuroconstructivism Vol. 1: How the brain con-
tive development. Developmental Science, 10, structs cognition. Oxford: Oxford University
281–287. Press.
Gopnik, A., Glymour, C., Sobel, D. M., Schulz, L. Mareschal, D., Sirois, S., Westermann, G.,
E., Kushnir, T. & Danks, D. (2004). A theory of & Johnson, M. H. (Eds.) (2007b). Neuro-
causal learning in children: Causal maps and constructivism, Vol. 2: Perspectives and pros-
Bayes nets. Psychological Review, 111, 1–30. pects. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Heit, E. (1998). A Bayesian analysis of some forms Mareschal, D., French, R. M., & Quinn P.C. (2000).
of inductive reasoning. In M. Oaksford & N. A connectionist account of asymmetric category
Chater (Eds.), Rational models of cognition learning in early infancy. Developmental
(pp. 248–274). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Psychology, 36, 635–645.
228 LEARNING MECHANISMS

Mareschal, D., & Quinn, P. C. (2001). as an organizing framework for understand-


Categorization in infancy. Trends in Cognitive ing infant concept formation. Developmental
Sciences, 4. 443–450. Science, 7. 511–513.
Mareschal, D., & Thomas M. S. C. (2007). Quinn, P. C., & Eimas, P. D. (1996a). Perceptual
Computational modeling in developmental cues that permit categorical differentia-
psychology. IEEE Transactions on Evolutionary tion of animal species by infants. Journal of
Computation (Special Issue on Autonomous Experimental Child Psychology, 63, 189–211.
Mental Development), 11, 137–150. Quinn, P. C., & Eimas, P. D. (1996b). Perceptual
Marr, D. (1982). Vision. San Francisco: W. organization and categorization in young
Freeman. infants. In Rovee-Collier & L. C. Lipsitt (Eds.),
McClelland, J. L. (1998). Connectionist models Advances in Infancy Research (pp. 1–36)
and Bayesian inference. In M. Oaksford & N. Norwood, NJ: Ablex.
Chater (Eds.), Rational models of cognition (pp. Quinn, P. C., & Eimas, P. D. (1998). Evidence for a
21–53). Oxford: Oxford University Press. global categorical representation of humans by
McClelland, J.L., McNaughton, B. L., & O’Reilly, young infants. Journal of Experimental Child
R. C. (1995). Why there are complementary Psychology, 69, 151–174.
learning systems in the hippocampus and Quinn, P.C., Eimas, P. D., & Rosenkrantz, S. L.
neocortex: Insights from the successes and (1993). Evidence for representations of percep-
failures of connectionist models of learn- tually similar natural categories by 3-month-
ing and memory. Psychological Review. 102, old and 4-month-old infants. Perception, 22.
419–457. 463–475.
McClelland, J. L., & Thompson, R. M. (2007). Using Quinn, P. C., & Johnson, M. H. (2000). Global-
domain-general principles to explain children’s before-basic object categorization in connec-
causal reasoning abilities. Developmental tionist networks and 2-month-old infants.
Science, 10, 333–356. Infancy, 1, 31–46.
McLeod, P., Plunkett, K., & Rolls, E. T. (1998). Rumelhart, D. E., Hinton, G. E., & Williams, R. J.
Introduction to connectionist modeling of cog- (1986). Learning representations by back-
nitive processes. Oxford: Oxford University propagating errors. Nature, 323(6088), 533–536.
Press. Rumelhart, D. E., & McClelland, J. L. (1986). Parallel
Mitchell, T (1997). Machine learning. New York: distributed processing: Explorations in the micro-
McGraw Hill. structure of cognition. Volume 1: Foundations
Nelson, C. A. (1995). The ontogeny of human (Vol. 1). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
memory—A cognitive neuroscience perspec- Shultz, T. R. (2003). Computational developmental
tive. Developmental Psychology, 31, 723–738. psychology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Newell, A (1990). Unified theories of cognition. Shultz, T. R. (2007). The Bayesian revolution
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. approaches psychological development.
Oaksford, M., & Chater, N. (2007) Bayesian ratio- Developmental Science, 10, 357–364.
nality. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Shultz, T. R., Schmidt, W. C., Buckingham, D.,
Pauen, S., & Träuble, B. (2004). Does experience & Mareschal, D. (1995). Modeling cogni-
with real-life animals influence performance in tive development with a generative connec-
an object examination task? Paper presented tionist algorithm. In T. Simon & G. Halford
at the Biennial Meeting of the International (Eds.), Developing cognitive competence: New
Conference on Infant Studies, Chicago, IL. approaches to process modeling (pp. 347–362).
Pearl, J. (2000). Causality: Models, reasoning and Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
inference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Simon. T. J., & Halford, G. S., (1995) Developing
Press. cognitive competence: New approaches to pro-
Piaget, J. (1952). The origins of intelligence in the cess modeling. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
child. New York: International Universities Sokolov, E. N. (1963). Perception and the condi-
Press. tioned reflex. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1984). Computation and cogni- Sternberg, R. J. (1984). Mechanisms of cognitive
tion: Towards a foundation for cognitive sci- development. San Francisco, CA: Freeman
ence. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Press.
Quinn, P. C. (2004). Multiple sources of informa- Thomas, M. S. C. & Karmiloff-Smith, A. (2002).
tion and their integration, not dissociation, Are developmental disorders like cases of adult
MIXING THE OLD WITH THE NEW AND THE NEW WITH THE OLD 229

brain damage? Implications from connection- Westermann, G., & Mareschal, D. (2004). From parts
ist modelling. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, to wholes: Mechanisms of development in infant
25, 727–788. visual object processing. Infancy, 5, 131–151.
Thelen, E. & Smith, L. B. (1994). A dynamic sys- Xu, F., & Tenenbaum, J. B. (2007). Word learning
tems approach to the development of cognition as Bayesian inference. Psychological Review,
and action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. 114, 245–272.
Touretzky, D. S., & Pomerleau, D. A. (1994). Young, R. (1976). Seriation by children: An arti-
Reconstructing physical symbol systems. ficial intelligence analysis of a Piagetian task.
Cognitive Science, 18, 345–353. Basel: Birkhauser.
This page intentionally left blank
PART IV

Induction
This page intentionally left blank
CHAP TER 12
Development of Inductive Inference in Infancy

David H. Rakison and Jessica B. Cicchino

Imagine, if you will, that you are walking with a experience we form concepts—mental represen-
friend near a lake and happen upon two bird-like tations or depictions—that encapsulate some,
creatures like those depicted below (Figure 12.1). but certainly not all, of the properties of the
Your friend asks you “If the duck on the left has things we have encountered. It is these concepts
Mallard blood, does the one on the right also that we use to generalize during inductive infer-
have Mallard blood?” What is your response? ence as well as during the process of categori-
On the one hand, you may respond with a “No.” zation whereby we group similar items together
After all, although they appear similar in shape (i.e., if X1 is a P, then X2 is also a P). Sometimes we
and have similar features—for example, eyes, may infer inductively using conceptual knowl-
a head, a beak, and webbed feet—at the same edge about specific instances—that ducks with
time other aspects of their appearance are quite certain body and face colorings are Mallards—
different: one has a brown body and the other and at other times we may perform induction
a gray body and one has a brown head and the by relying on more general knowledge about
other has a green head. On the other hand, you the statistical regularities in the world (e.g., if
may respond with a “Yes.” Your knowledge of an animal is the shape of a duck then it is prob-
ducks—learned in school or more informally— ably a duck).
may allow you to recall that they are the male Inductive inference is particularly problem-
and female of the same species called Anas atic for infants. They have experienced a rela-
platyrhynchos, or more commonly, the Mallard tively small fraction of the objects, entities, and
duck. events in the environment, and although they
Regardless of your response, the process undergo perhaps the most rapid period of con-
that you use to make such a decision is called cept acquisition that occurs during the life span,
inductive inference. It is the ability to use pre- they possess little in the way of specific or gen-
vious experience to determine how far to gener- eral knowledge about the world. An additional
alize a specific observation to a novel instance, difficulty for the infant is that there is rarely
or, more formally, the ability to infer that if X1 direct feedback during induction; when a novel
has property P then X2 also has property P. This instance is encountered, the infant must deter-
process is fundamental to human cognition mine how to generalize prior knowledge to it
because we can experience only a small por- often without the aid of a caretaker. Nonetheless,
tion of the objects, entities, features, and events over the last 10 years, researchers have begun to
in the world and must rely on generalization examine when infants are capable of induction
from our previous experience to interpret new and on what basis they generalize from their
objects and events. During a great deal of this previous experience to a novel exemplar.

233
234 INDUCTION

Figure 12.1 Do these ducks have the same blood?

As is common within the infancy literature, term does not (at least in this chapter) imply
there are wildly diverging theoretical views anything about the content or structure of those
about when inductive inference begins and how representations. We use the term bottom-up
it operates. According to one view, as early as 9 processes for those behaviors that rely predom-
months of age, infants’ induction primarily is inantly on the current, or recent, sensory input.
a top-down process that relies on abstract con- Inherent in our perspective is the notion that
ceptual knowledge about the world (Mandler, general rather than specific mechanisms are
2004; Mandler & McDonough, 1996, 1998; the foundation of early learning. From this per-
Pauen, 2002; Poulin-Dubois, Frenkiel-Fishman, spective, infants’ extension of an action from
Nayer, & Johnson, 2006). For instance, it has dogs to cats or from cars to trucks is not based
been suggested that young infants general- on knowledge about category membership
ize drinking from a dog to a cat not because or an understanding of the characteristics of
dogs and cats look alike but because they animals and vehicles. Instead, we propose that
understand that they are both animals that are infants generalize from one object to another
capable of similar bodily, sensory, and motion- on the basis of the features of those objects—
related actions. Proponents of this perspective for example, things with legs drink and things
theorize that this knowledge develops within with wheels start with keys—and that the spe-
the fi rst year of life because infants possess spe- cific features that act as the basis for generaliza-
cialized mechanisms that rapidly interpret or tion are dependent on the whether or not there
recode what is observed into a more concep- is prior knowledge about the observed property
tual abstract format. or action.
According to an alternative view—the one In this chapter, we provide an overview of
we present here—induction is initially a bot- theoretical arguments and empirical evidence
tom-up process that becomes more top-down for both the top-down and bottom-up perspec-
over time; but crucially, the primary basis for tives of infant inductive generalization. The
generalization remains the surface features or goal of the chapter is to synthesize the research
properties of things (Cicchino & Rakison, 2008; to date in an attempt to provide a coherent view
Rakison, 2005). We use the term top-down pro- of the development of inductive generalization,
cesses to refer to behaviors that involve access- the learning mechanisms involved, and to gen-
ing prior representations or knowledge, but the erate ideas for future directions of the area.
DEVELOPMENT OF INDUCTIVE INFERENCE IN INFANCY 235

THE ORIGINS OF RESEARCH ON INDUCTIVE tools, and so on. There is a large database on
INFERENCE IN INFANCY such induction in children older than 3 years of
age, which suggests that at least by the preschool
Research on induction in the first years of years, they rely on labels and category knowl-
life did not begin in earnest until the 1990s, edge to generalize a novel property (Gelman &
perhaps because the visually based paradigms Markman, 1986, 1987; cf., Sloutsky & Fisher,
that were used to study infant cognition and 2004). However, it is only since the emergence
perception—notably, habituation and preferen- of novel infant-oriented methodology called
tial looking—were not considered appropriate the generalized imitation technique (Mandler
to its study. With a growing interest in inductive & McDonough, 1996, 1998; McDonough &
inference, researchers began to develop experi- Mandler, 1998) that work in this area has pro-
ments that relied not on visual attention but gressed at a rapid pace. Because the majority of
instead on infants’ tendency to imitate actions the work described here used this technique, we
or events that they have observed. These studies describe it here briefly.
laid the groundwork for more recent research
by demonstrating that infants as young as 9 to THE GENERALIZED IMITATION PROCEDURE
10 months of age can generalize from one object
to another and that there are limits on how far The generalized imitation, or inductive gener-
they will extend a given property. For instance, alization, procedure uses scale model toys, is
Killen and Uzgiris (1981), who performed one of simple to implement, and is suitable for infants
the first inductive generalization study in which as young as 9 to 10 months of age and for chil-
infants were required to perform an action, dren as old as 2½ to 3 years. In the prototypical
found that 10- and 16-month-old infants—but version of the task there is a baseline, a mod-
not 22-month-olds—are more likely to repeat eling, and a generalization phase. In the base-
conventional social actions modeled by an line phase, infants typically are shown two toys
experimenter (e.g., putting a comb to their hair) drawn from different categories—for instance, a
than counterconventional ones (e.g., putting a cat and a truck—as well as a prop that is related
comb to a car). Baldwin, Markman, and Melartin to one or perhaps both of them; for instance,
(1993) used an exploratory play task to examine a cup. Infants are allowed to interact with the
inductive inference in 9- and 14-month-olds. toys and the prop in any way they wish for a
Infants were given a brief exposure to the prop- brief time without any interaction from the
erty of a novel toy—for example, a can made a experimenter, after which the toys and prop are
sound when squeezed—and then tested to see if withdrawn from view. This phase is included to
they expected a toy with a similar appearance to determine any a priori preference for one of the
have the same property. The results showed that toys and to discover whether infants perform
infants in both age groups expected that toys of spontaneously the action they will observe dur-
similar appearance—those that differed only in ing the next phase of the task. In the modeling
color or pattern—would have the same prop- phase, the experimenter introduces a novel toy,
erty. Finally, Bauer and Dow (1994) found that typically from the same category as one of the
that 16- and 20-month-olds enacted events they first two exemplars and then enacts an action
had seen 1 week earlier (e.g., a teddy bear going with that toy and the prop. For instance, the
in a toy crib) with novel, functionally equivalent experimenter might use a dog to “drink” from
props (e.g., Big Bird going in a bed). the cup while making concurrently an appro-
These studies, although informative about priate vocalization such as “sip sip.” This action
infants’ ability to perform inductive generaliza- is usually modeled three or four times, after
tion more generally shed relatively little light on which the novel stimulus is withdrawn.
how and when infants start to use their knowl- During the final, generalization phase,
edge about the world to make inferences about infants are presented with the same prop and
the properties of animals, people, vehicles, toys presented in the baseline phase and are
236 INDUCTION

encouraged to repeat the action performed by the


THE TOP- DOWN APPROACH TO INFANT
experimenter. This encouragement can include
INDUCTIVE GENERALIZATION
a hand movement that repeats the motion of the
action and a verbal prompt (e.g., Can you show Mandler and McDonough (1996, 1998;
me “sip sip”), but it is the infants’ choice to use McDonough & Mandler, 1998) used the gener-
one or both of the toys to imitate the action they alized imitation technique to examine whether
observed in the modeling phase. infants between 9 and 14 months of age under-
Mandler and McDonough’s (1996, 1998; stand that animals are capable of certain kinds
McDonough & Mandler, 1998) rationale for of actions (e.g., drinking from a cup, going to
this task was as follows. If infants understand bed) and that vehicles are capable of different
that the modeled action is specific to the cat- kinds of actions (e.g., starting with a key, giving
egory of the novel exemplar (e.g., animals a ride). The rationale for these studies was to test
drink), they should enact the event with the a top-down view of early induction developed
toy stimulus from the appropriate category by Mandler (1992; Mandler & McDonough,
and not with the stimulus from the inappro- 1996). According to this view, infants possess
priate category (i.e., they should make the cat a specialized mechanism called perceptual
drink but not the truck). However, if the two analysis that allows them form perceptual as
test stimuli are from the same category, and well as conceptual categories very early in life.
that category is appropriate for the modeling The perceptual categories include information
action (e.g., a cat and a rabbit for drinking), about surface appearance and allow infants
then infants should enact the observed event to identify what an object is; in contrast, the
equally often with both stimuli. The dependent conceptual categories incorporate information
variable for the task is typically the object cho- about how things move, the actions in which
sen to enact the event, although in variations they typically engage, and category relatedness
of the task involving motion-related actions it (e.g., “there is a category of animals”). Mandler
has also been the way in which the stimuli are and McDonough (1996, 1998) argued that
moved by infants (Cicchino & Rakison, 2008; infants’ induction (and categorization) is driven
Rakison, 2005; Rakison, Cicchino, & Hahn, entirely by their conceptual knowledge about
2007). animals, vehicles, furniture, and other superor-
As we shall show, this task has proved a dinate classes. For instance, they claimed that
useful tool in gathering data on infants’ gen- infants’ imitations “are based on their concep-
eralization behavior. At the same time, it is tual interpretations of what they have observed,
common for researchers to make a number of not the physical appearance of the items per se”
assumptions in their interpretation of infants’ (Mandler & McDonough, 1998, p. 37) and that
behavior in the task and these assumptions “conceptual control of inductive generaliza-
must be re-assessed before strong conclu- tion begins early in life. There does not seem to
sions can be drawn about the nature of early be a period in which infants respond only on
knowledge. There are also a number of more the basis of physical appearance” (Mandler &
minor issues with the task—for example, that McDonough, 1996, pp. 230–231).
a human hand moves the toys in the study and What is the evidence in support this view?
that younger infants may not respond in the Mandler and McDonough (1996, 1998) found
task due to limited imitation capacities—that that infants between 9 and 14 months of age
will not be discussed here (for discussions, see tended to generalize animal properties to novel
Cicchino & Rakison, 2008; Rakison, 2005). animals but not vehicles and vehicle properties
Below we present research that has been used to novel vehicles but not animals. Thus, infants
to support the view that infants’ behavior in generalized going to bed to a dog but not a truck
the task is underpinned by conceptual knowl- and giving a ride to a car but not a dog. They
edge about the properties of members of a cat- also found that infants generalized these prop-
egory (e.g., animals “drink”). erties for prototypical category members (e.g.,
DEVELOPMENT OF INDUCTIVE INFERENCE IN INFANCY 237

a car, a cow) as well nonprototypical category possess conceptual knowledge about the
members (e.g., an eagle, a plane). These studies bodily, sensory, and motion related properties
were extended by Mandler and McDonough of animate entities. They used the inductive
(1998) who used the same four actions as the generalization procedure with 14-, 16-, and
modeled properties but in some conditions pre- 20-month-olds to examine whether they would
sented infants with two members of the appro- extend properties such as going to bed, looking
priate category for the action (e.g., after seeing in a mirror, and jumping over a wall from ani-
a dog drink from a cup infants were allowed to mals to other animals, from people to animals,
imitate with a dog and a cat or a dog and a rab- and from a monkey to people and animals. The
bit). The authors predicted that if infants have results of the studies showed that 14-month-
conceptual knowledge that animals drink or go olds generalized bodily and sensory properties
to bed, then they should enact the action they from an animal to another animal rather than
observe with both of the category appropriate a vehicle, and that both 16- and 20-month-olds
exemplars. This prediction was borne out by the generalized motion and sensory properties
data: infants were just as likely to imitate the from a person to other mammals rather than
animal actions with a cat, a rabbit, and a dog, to vehicles. They also found that 20-month-olds
and they were just as likely to imitate the vehicle generalized motion properties from a monkey
actions with a car, a truck, and a motorcycle. to people, cats, and tigers but that they gener-
Mandler and McDonough (1998;) presented alized sensory properties to people more than
additional data that they claimed supports the to animals.
notion infants’ inductive inference is based
on a conceptual understanding of the behav-
REINTERPRETING THE DATA: A BOTTOM - UP
iors of animals and vehicles. In one series of
APPROACH TO INFANT INDUCTIVE
experiments, Mandler and McDonough (1998)
GENERALIZATION
tested infants with domain-general actions—
those that are typical of both animals and On the surface, the results from these studies
vehicles such as being washed or going into a with the inductive generalization paradigm
building—as well as domain-specific actions indicate that infants are precocious concept
that are typical of only one category (e.g., start- formers and that by 14 to 16 months of age, if
ing with a key or drinking from a cup). Their not earlier, they understand that animals, peo-
results indicated that infants at 14 months gen- ple, and vehicles engage in distinct bodily (e.g.,
eralized domain-general actions to animals and drinking), sensory (e.g., looking at a sign), and
vehicles—though it is worth noting that they motion-related (e.g., jumping) actions. There
first imitated with an exemplar from the same are nonetheless a number of reasons to be cau-
category member as the model exemplar—but tious before jumping to a rich interpretation of
they generalized the domain-specific actions infants’ performance in the inductive general-
to the appropriate category members alone. ization procedure.
Finally, to examine whether infants’ behavior is First, it remains to be seen to what extent
driven primarily by imitation of what they have the model exemplar used by the experimenter
seen, Mandler and McDonough (1996) modeled influences infants’ choice during the general-
domain-specific events for 14-month-olds with ization phase. It could be the case that infants
both an appropriate and an inappropriate exem- observe which exemplar the experimenter
plar; for instance, a dog and a car were put to employs to enact the event and then chooses
bed. The results showed that infants were more one that is perceptually similar to that exemplar
likely to choose an appropriate exemplar than (what has previously been labeled perceptual
an inappropriate exemplar for their first action. matching and imitation (Rakison, 2003)). For
More recently, Poulin-Dubois et al. (2006) example, infants may imitate drinking from a
supported a similar top-down oriented view cup with a dog rather than a truck after seeing
that infants as young as 14 months of age the experimenter use a cat to model the event
238 INDUCTION

because the dog is more similar to the cat than concepts do not encapsulate global categories
the truck. As outlined above, Mandler and such as animals and vehicles or animates and
McDonough (1996) attempted to address this inanimates as Mandler, Poulin-Dubois, Pauen,
issue by enacting an event with both an appro- and others have suggested. Second, it may
priate and inappropriate exemplar; however, nonetheless be the case that infants relied on
although infants were more likely to imitate a matching and imitation strategy during the
first with an appropriate exemplar, they were domain-specific tasks administered by Mandler
just as likely to use an inappropriate exemplar and McDonough (1998). Careful inspection
for their second action (56%) as they were to use of their data shows that infants’ first imitation
an appropriate one for their first action (57%). tended to be with the exemplar that was from
In other words, infants imitated the actions the same category as the model exemplar; when
with both the appropriate and inappropriate a car was made to move into a building, infants
exemplars. Mandler and McDonough (1998) would initially use the novel test vehicle to go
claimed that infants’ generalization of an action into the building and then they would perform
to two animal or two vehicle exemplars is also a second action with the other test exemplar
evidence that they understand in a conceptual that belonged to the other category (e.g., an ani-
sense that both are capable of that action. Yet, mal moving into the building). Note that this
this behavior too can be explained by percep- behavior is similar to that found in the task in
tual matching and imitation because both of the which both the appropriate and inappropriate
test exemplars (e.g., a cat and a rabbit) were per- exemplar was used to model the events; in our
ceptually similar to the model exemplar (e.g., a view, it is important to be consistent in evalu-
dog). Likewise, in the studies by Poulin-Dubois ating the data such that infants’ second action
et al. (2006), infants generalize from a cat to a should be not be disregarded in one condition
dog rather than a vehicle, from a person to an and considered in another.
animal rather than a vehicle, and from a mon- A second issue concerns the basis for infants’
key to a person and an animal. In all of these inductive inferences. According to one per-
cases, infants’ generalization can be explained spective, early concept learning—and thus
by similarity matching to the model exemplar. categorization and induction—is grounded
One piece of evidence that could be taken in specialized learning mechanisms or innate
as contrary to this explanation is that infants’ modules (e.g., Gelman, 1990; Mandler, 1992;
behavior in the domain-general tasks in which Premack, 1990; Poulin-Dubois et al., 2006). A
they generalized, for example, going into a corollary of this view is that infants’ inductive
building to an animal and a vehicle (Mandler inferences are based on abstract concepts of
& McDonough, 1998). In other words, if infants animals and vehicles, or even broader notions
use the surface appearance of the model object of animates and inanimates. Thus, when infants
to generalize to one of the test objects, they generalize a property from a cat to a dog, it is
should have imitated with only the test animal because they understand, in a conceptual sense,
or the test vehicle—contingent on which was that they are both animals and animates and
the model—in the domain-specific tasks. therefore engage in the same kinds of actions.
We have two points regarding these data. As stated earlier, we propose that infants may
First, our claim here is not that infants bring well arrive at the laboratory with experience-
no knowledge about the world with them to the based knowledge about the way things move
laboratory, and it is quite possible that they have and the actions of which they are capable. We
learned that a variety of things in the world, do not subscribe to the idea that this knowl-
including animals and vehicles, go in and out edge is embedded in concepts for superordinate
of buildings. As we shall show in the follow- domains (e.g., animals) or abstract notions of ani-
ing sections, in our view, infants in the second macy. The studies by Mandler and McDonough
year of life do have concepts that incorporate (1996, 1998; McDonough & Mandler, 1998) and
how things in the world move around but these Poulin-Dubois et al. (2006) provide no direct
DEVELOPMENT OF INDUCTIVE INFERENCE IN INFANCY 239

evidence whatsoever that infants’ concepts A third, perhaps less problematic, concern is
contain such information. As an alternative, whether infants appreciate that the toy objects
we have proposed that general, and not specific, used in the task represent real-world objects.
mechanisms are the keystone for early learning Th is issue is not limited to the inductive gen-
and that initial representations of the properties eralization procedure and can similarly be lev-
of animals, vehicles, and other object involve ied at other methodologies such as sequential
associative links between those properties and touching (Rakison & Butterworth, 1998) and
specific surface features (Cicchino & Rakison, object examining (Oakes, Madole, & Cohen,
2008; Rakison, 2005; Rakison & Lupyan, 2008). 1991) that use scale model objects. According
Infants, according to this view, associatively to one perspective, infants understand that
learn the relation between an action—self-pro- the toys in the task are symbolic representa-
pelled motion, looking in a mirror, or drinking tions of their real-world equivalents and their
from a cup—and the features that are conjointly performance in the laboratory demonstrates
moving with those features (e.g., legs walk- this to be the case (Mandler & McDonough,
ing, heads turning, hands grasping). The pres- 1996, 1998). At the same time, there is grow-
ence of one of these two associatively learned ing evidence that infants may not have such a
features is then sufficient to activate the rep- deep understanding of the toys that they use
resentation of the other; the presence of legs to enact the events they observe. Tomasello
activates the expectation that an object can be and collaborators, for example, proposed that
self-propelled and goal-directed and the obser- children’s symbolic understanding of objects
vation that something is self-propelled or goal- is limited until early in the third year of life
directed activates the expectation that an object because those younger than 24 months of age
will have legs. This kind of associative learning show symbolic skills with gestures but not with
means that initially infants may make incorrect objects (Tomasello & Striano, 2001; Tomasello,
generalizations—they may extend a property to Striano, & Rochat, 1999). Likewise, using a
any object that possesses the feature associated version of the inductive generalization task,
with an action even if it is from an inappropri- Younger and Johnson (2004) found that chil-
ate category. However, over time, they make sec- dren under 2 years of age rarely understand
ondary associations to which an action is then that scale model objects are symbols for their
extended. For instance, if infants learn the rela- “real” world counterparts.
tion between legs and self-propulsion and they We are somewhat agnostic on this issue but
then learn that legs and hand are correlated, they nonetheless believe that care must be taken in
will generalize self-propulsion to things with assuming that infants comprehend that the toys
hands as well as legs. in the task are symbolic representations of real-
Note that our claim is not that every fea- world objects. In our view, scale models serve as
ture will become associated with the action to appropriate stimuli in the inductive generaliza-
which it is connected. It is entirely possible, for tion, and object examining tasks because they
example, that young infants will not associate possess the same features, shape, and struc-
opening mouths with drinking either because ture as the real-world objects they are meant to
mouths often open without drinking or because represent. This means that when infants gener-
other aspects of the event may be more salient alize from one toy object to another—for exam-
(e.g., the hand used to reach for the glass or ple, from a model car exemplar to a test truck
cup). We also acknowledge that at some point exemplar—in all likelihood they rely on aspects
in developmental time, infants and young chil- of the objects that would be used during induc-
dren will generalize on the basis of category tive generalization in the real world. Naturally,
membership (e.g., because two objects are both the scale model toys are impoverished versions
“animals”) or even animacy; however, the age at of real-world objects and some features may be
which this occurs is yet to be specified and will minimized or missing entirely; nonetheless, we
vary for different actions and events. believe that in general the characteristic features
240 INDUCTION

of objects are included in scale model toys and by a more top-down approach (e.g., Mandler &
could be used to generalize in the laboratory. McDonough, 1996, 1998; Pauen, 2002; Poulin-
Dubois et al., 2006).
Summary and Predictions of the Model
If infants arrive at the laboratory without any
In our view, it cannot be assumed that infants’ prior knowledge of the actions they are shown,
behavior in the inductive generalization task is their behavior will be guided by bottom-up
driven by either (a) any knowledge of the prop- processes such that they will most likely imitate
erties on which they are tested or (b) abstract with the exemplar most similar to the model
conceptual knowledge of the capabilities of ani- exemplar regardless of whether it is appropriate
mates and inanimates. Figure 12.2 illustrates for the action. If infants arrive with some prior
how infants may respond in any given induc- knowledge about the event, their behavior is
tive generalization task contingent on whether guided more by top-down processes such that
or not they come to the task with prior knowl- they will enact an event with exemplars that
edge about the action or event they are shown. possess the appropriate features for the action.
Note that regardless of the path one follows, the The prediction deriving from our theoretical
behavior that would be observed in many of the perspective suggests, however, that infants who
tasks that have employed the inductive general- have some representational content for specific
ization paradigm would be identical. However, event should generalize actions to objects with
this view leads to a number of unique predic- the appropriate parts for those actions rather
tions about infants’ behavior in the inductive than on the basis of category membership (e.g.,
generalization task that would not be generated being an animal). Finally, at some point in

Knowledge content in Mental behavior during


Action in test phase
task task

Choose object(s) with


appropriate feature(s)
for the action
Activation of
associatively linked
object feature
Prior knowledge about Enact event with dog
action shown in task rather than truck
Things with mouths and
legs drink

Cat drinks from cup


Inductive Choose object(s) that
Test objects: dog and
generalization task share feature(s) with
truck
model exemplar
Compare surface
features of test objects
with model exemplar
No prior knowledge
about action shown in Enact event with dog
task rather than truck
Dog is more similar to
cat than truck is to cat

Figure 12.2 Model of infants’ behavior in the inductive generalization task contingent on whether
they have prior knowledge or no prior knowledge about the action they observe.
DEVELOPMENT OF INDUCTIVE INFERENCE IN INFANCY 241

developmental time, infants should generalize moving linearly for vehicles). Consistent with
an action to objects that possess the appropri- the results of other research with the induc-
ate parts even if the object that possesses those tive generalization procedure (e.g., Mandler &
parts is from an inappropriate category for the McDonough, 1996, 1998; Poulin-Dubois et al.
action (e.g., a table for walking). In the sec- 2006), when the events were modeled with a suit-
tions that follow, we outline research using the able exemplar, infants tended to enact the events
inductive generalization procedure with infants with the test stimulus from the appropriate cat-
between 14 and 26 months of age that tested egory. For example, when infants observed an
these predictions. experimenter move a cat in a nonlinear walk-
ing motion, they enacted the event with a dog
Is Infants’ Inductive Inference Based On
rather than a truck. However, when the iden-
Prior Knowledge?
tical events were modeled with an unsuitable
Recall that Mandler and McDonough (1996) exemplar—for example, a car moving in a walk-
attempted to address the issue of percep- ing motion—a separate group of infants of the
tual matching by modeling bodily actions to same age repeated what they had seen with an
14-month-old infants with both appropriate inappropriate exemplar (e.g., a truck moving in
and inappropriate objects for the actions. Recall a walking motion). This basic effect held regard-
also that in their task infants enacted the events less of whether the motions modeled to infants
they observed with both of the test stimuli. This were context specific or context general.
provides tentative evidence that infants indeed A similar design was employed by Furrer,
engage in some kind of similarity matching to Younger, and Johnson (2005) to test whether
the model exemplar. However, there are alter- infants relied on perceptual matching and imi-
native and perhaps better methods to investi- tation for two of events used by Mandler and
gate whether infants’ behavior in the inductive McDonough (1996, 1998). Infants at 14 and
generalization task is based on perceptual 16 months of age were tested with one animal
matching. A first step for any bodily, sensory, action (drinking from a cup) and one vehicle
or motion event that will be studied is to estab- action (starting with a key) and the events were
lish whether infants enact it with an appropriate modeled either with a conventional category
exemplar when modeled with an appropriate member or an inappropriate one. In accord with
exemplar. Assuming this to be the case, there the results of Rakison (2003), infants in both age
are two potential subsequent approaches. A groups enacted events with the appropriate cat-
first method is to model an action only with an egory exemplar when they observed an experi-
inappropriate exemplar. If infants are using a menter model with a conventional object (e.g., a
matching strategy, they should enact the action bus starting with a key) but enacted events with
the observed with the inappropriate test exem- an inappropriate category exemplar when the
plar rather than the appropriate test exemplar. event was modeled with a counterconventional
To test whether infants are indeed using item (e.g., a dog starting with a key).
a perceptual matching strategy, Rakison Taken together, these results suggest that
(2003, Rakison & Poulin-Dubois, 2000) tested 14- to 16-month-old infants’ behavior in at least
14-month-old infants with a variety of motion some inductive generalization tasks may be
events that were modeled either with an appro- based on their ability to compare the similarity
priate or inappropriate category exemplar. For of the two test stimuli to the model exemplar.
each event, a novel appropriate and inappro- Clearly, this strategy would best be described
priate stimulus was presented during the gen- as bottom-up; infants arrive at the laboratory
eralization phase. The motion events included with little or no knowledge of the events they
motions that were context-specific (e.g., going are shown and must determine during the
upstairs for animals, jumping from one ramp task—on-line—how perceptually similar are
to another for vehicles) or context-general (e.g., the test stimuli to the one manipulated by the
acting as an agent in a causal event for animals, experimenter.
242 INDUCTION

A second method to address the issue of per- (Figure 12.3A(i)) was identical to that used by
ceptual matching is to use an ambiguous object Gergely et al. (1995). In the other three events,
as the model exemplar. The rationale for this an object moved over a hill (Figure 12.3A(ii)) or
design is that infants are provided no featural travelled across a bridge that was above a val-
cues during the modeling phase and conse- ley (Figure 12.3A(iii)) or a sheer drop (Figure
quently their choice of the appropriate exemplar 12.3A(iv)). In the test phase, the environment was
to enact an event cannot be a result of percep- changed (Figure 12.3B) and the infant was given
tual matching. Instead, it must be based on prior an animal and a vehicle with which to enact an
knowledge about the event and the objects or event. In each case, infants could move the test
features of objects that generally engage in that objects either along a nonrational path similar
event (Rakison, 2005; Rakison et al., 2007). In to that they had observed during the modeling
one such study to adopt this approach, Rakison phase or along a rational path (illustrated with
et al. (2007) examined infants’ inductive gener- a dotted line in Figure 12.3B). The variables of
alization of the path that objects take to reach a interest were infants’ choice of object (either ani-
goal. Seminal work by Gergely, Nádasdy, Csibra, mal or vehicle) and the path that the object was
and Biro (1995) suggested that infants as young moved as it traveled toward the goal.
as 9 to 12 months of age apply a teleological In the first experiment with this design, the
stance—or a naïve theory of rational action—to model exemplar was an animal. The 16-month-
interpret goal-directed events. In their stud- old age group in this condition demonstrated
ies, infants were habituated to a visual event in more goal-directed motions with the animals
which a small ball jumped over an obstacle to than the vehicles; yet, they were just as likely to
reach a large ball. In a control condition, infants move the animals along rational as nonrational
were habituated to an identical event except that paths. The 20-month-olds, however, demon-
the obstacle was absent. The movement over the strated goal-directed actions with animals and
block in the experimental condition was ratio- moved them along a rational path to reach the
nal and goal-directed—it was the only way to goal. These results suggest that infants at 20
reach the larger ball—but the same action in months of age, but not those at 16 months of age,
the control condition was goal-directed but not understand that animals follow rational paths
rational. There were two test trials in both con- to reach a goal. As with the studies by Mandler
ditions in which the obstacle was not present: and McDonough (1996, 1998), however, these
in one, the smaller ball jumped (the nonrational data can be explained by perceptual matching;
action), and in the other, the smaller ball moved that is, both the younger and older age groups
in a straight line (the rational action) (see Figure may have chosen the animal because the model
12.3A(i)). Infants in the experimental condition exemplar was an animal.
looked longer at the nonrational action than to Consequently, in a follow-up experiment,
the rational straight-moving one; in contrast, infants at 16 and 20 months of age were tested
infants in the control condition looked equally with the same design except the model stim-
long at the two events. In follow-up experi- uli were ambiguous objects (see Figure 12.4).
ments, 9- and 12-month-olds behaved similarly The stimuli were made from clay and varied in
when cues to animacy, such as self-propulsion, color. Th is study was also designed to address
were absent (Csibra, Gergely, Biro, Koos, & Csibra et al.’s (1999) claim that animacy cues
Brockbank, 1999). are neither sufficient nor necessary for a teleo-
To examine when and how infants gener- logical interpretation of an object’s behavior.
alize rational, goal-directed action to animals The results of the experiment were somewhat
and not vehicles, Rakison et al. (2007) used the different from those found when the model
inductive generalization procedure to test 16- object was an animal. In contrast to the fi rst
and 20-month-olds with a number of similar experiment, 20-month-olds just as often moved
events to that in Gergely et al. (1995).The four objects along rational and nonrational motion
events are presented Figure 12.3. One event paths and they were just as likely to choose an
DEVELOPMENT OF INDUCTIVE INFERENCE IN INFANCY 243

A
(i) (ii)

(iv)
(iii)

B (ii)
(i)

(iii) (iv)

Figure 12.3 (A) Motion events modeled in Rakison et al. (2007). The small circle is the moving object;
the large circle represents the goal. The motion paths modeled were (i) jumping over a block, (ii) going
across a bridge over a valley, (iii) climbing over a hill, and (iv) going across a bridge over a gap. (B)
Motion arenas in generalization phase of Rakison et al. (2007). Rational motion paths are illustrated by
the solid line; the nonrational motion paths are illustrated by the dotted line. Note that two of the ratio-
nal and nonrational paths were linear and two of the rational and non-rational paths were nonlinear.

Figure 12.4 Ambiguous blocks used as model exemplars in Experiment 2 of Rakison et al. (2007).

animal as a vehicle to imitate what they had ceptual cues to interpret their motion toward a
seen. Taken together, these experiments do goal as rational.
not support Gergely, Csibra, and colleagues’ We speculate that infants associate humans,
(Csibra et al., 1999; Gergely et al., 1995) notion and later animals, with goal-directed actions
that infants apply a teleological stance to the because these entities invariably move toward
movement of objects as early as 9 months of goals. What has been labeled a “teleological”
age. The data suggest that infants as old as interpretation emerges later from experience
16 months do not understand that objects— with the movement of humans and animals,
specifically, animals—follow a rational path the constraints of the physical world, and the
to reach a goal and that infants at 20 months motions typical of those entities. Thus, animates
require objects to possess certain surface per- tend to remain in contact with the ground as
244 INDUCTION

they move, do not “jump” in the absence of dynamic, parts (Cicchino & Rakison, 2008;
an obstacle, and do “jump” only when there is Rakison, 2003, 2005, 2006; Rakison & Lupyan,
an obstacle or a gap. Representations that are 2008). For example, an associative learning
formed via an associative learning mechanism mechanism that is sensitive to statistical regu-
that is sensitive to such regularities in the world larities in the world will encode that a cat’s legs
would lead infants to expect certain actions— tend to move only when it self-propels or acts
those we label rational—and not others. as an agent in a causal event. A prediction that
stems from this view is that infants will initially
Summary
generalize actions or events to objects with the
In conjunction, the series of studies described in appropriate parts (e.g., legs, hands) rather than
this section cast doubt about the extent to which objects from the appropriate category that do
infants apply prior knowledge in tasks designed not possess such parts (e.g., a snake for walk-
to test their use of this knowledge in inductive ing). In a number of recent studies, we have
inference (see Mandler & McDonough, 1996, explicitly tested this view by examining the
1998; McDonough & Mandler, 1998; Poulin- basis for induction in infancy.
Dubois et al., 2006). The available data suggest In one series of studies to address this issue,
that it cannot be assumed that infants’ behavior Rakison (2005) used a novel version of the
in the inductive generalization task is guided inductive generalization procedure to examine
by abstract knowledge—or indeed any knowl- infants’ knowledge about the path of motion
edge—about the bodily, sensory, or motion typical of animals and vehicles. In particular,
related actions of animals or vehicles. As we infants at 18 and 22 months of age were tested
outlined earlier, this is not to say that infants in with two simple motions for animals (walking
the second year of life have no representations or hopping and flying) and two simple motions
for the various actions of the members of these for vehicles (rolling and flying). Contrary to
categories; indeed, as we shall show in the fol- previous experiments with the inductive gener-
lowing section, this knowledge is in place by the alization task, Rakison (2005) presented infants
middle of the second year if not earlier. However, with four test stimuli instead of two during the
we suggest that caution be taken before inter- baseline and testing phases of the experiments.
preting their behavior in the inductive general- The rationale for this approach was to inves-
ization task to mean that they understand—in a tigate directly the basis for induction; infants
conceptual sense—that members of a category were given stimuli that were either from the
engage in specific actions. appropriate category for the motion, that pos-
sessed the appropriate parts for the motion,
The Basis for Induction in Infancy
some combination of the two of these factors,
Clearly, at some point in developmental time, or neither of these factors. For example, if the
infants do learn about the various bodily, sen- experimenter modeled nonlinear “walking”
sory, and motion-related actions of things in with a cat, one test object was a dog (same cat-
the world and will use this knowledge to make egory, same parts), another was a dolphin (same
inductive inferences, among other things. As category, different parts), another was a table
we discussed earlier, our view is that the mech- (different category, same parts), and another
anisms that underpin this learning are gen- was a car (different category, different parts).
eral rather than specific. Consequently, we do This version of the task gives researchers
not conform to the view that infants form an the tool to examine more closely the basis for
abstract concept of animal or vehicle in the first early induction; specifically, it allows a test of
year of life (Gelman, 1990; Leslie, 1995; Mandler, whether infants generalize bodily, sensory, or
1992; Premack, 1990). Instead, we have argued motion properties to objects on the basis of cat-
that infants’ initial representations for actions egory membership or an abstract concept of
of entities and objects involve an associative animacy (Mandler, 2004), or on the basis of spe-
link between those actions and specific, often cific object parts as we predicted. For the sake of
DEVELOPMENT OF INDUCTIVE INFERENCE IN INFANCY 245

simplicity, we discuss here only the data for the the ambiguous block as the model exemplar
conditions in which land-based motions were meant that the basis for any generalization of
modeled (i.e., nonlinear and linear movement the observed action could only be attributable
in contact with a flat surface). to prior knowledge brought to the task. The
In the first experiment with this design results of the experiment were indeed revealing
(Rakison, 2005, Experiment 1), the model exem- about the basis for induction and the inductive
plars were animals and vehicles with the appro- generalization task. Infants at 18 months of age
priate parts for the motion in question (i.e., a behaved similarly to those in the first experi-
cat with legs and a car with wheels). In line with ment; they enacted the actions they had seen
the prediction that infants initially associate using the exemplars with the appropriate parts
specific functional parts with specific motion for the motion even though they did not nec-
properties, the younger age group enacted the essarily belong to the appropriate category. The
linear and nonlinear motions with objects that 22-month-olds, however, enacted the linear and
possessed the appropriate parts regardless of nonlinear motions with stimuli from the appro-
whether they belonged to the appropriate cat- priate category regardless of whether they pos-
egory for the motion. For instance, having seen sessed the appropriate parts. In other words, the
an experimenter move a cat in a “walking” older age group imitated the nonlinear walking
motion, infants repeated the action with a dog motion with the two animals (e.g., a sheep and
and a bed. Somewhat surprisingly, however, the a snail) and linear rolling motion with the two
older age group enacted the linear and nonlinear vehicles (e.g., a car and a snowmobile).
motion events only with the test object that was This latter finding is important for two
from the appropriate category and possessed reasons. First, it suggests that the 22-month-
the appropriate parts for the motion in ques- olds in the first experiment were indeed influ-
tion. Note that in a separate study with the same enced by the model exemplar; why else would
design that tested 14-month-olds’ generaliza- infants who are given no information about the
tion, infants did not choose any particular test identity of the object (as was the case in these
object to enact the motions they had observed. later experiments) outperform those who were
This first experiment revealed that 18-month- shown a clearly identifiable category member as
olds generalize walking to objects with legs and a model? Second, although the behavior of the
rolling to things with wheels irrespective of cat- 22-month-olds suggests that they generalized on
egory membership. Yet, it remains to be seen the basis of category membership (e.g., walking
whether both age groups’ choice of exemplar in to animals), it remains to be seen whether their
the test phase was based on perceptual match- choice of the appropriate category without the
ing to the model exemplar. It could argued, for appropriate parts for the motion was grounded
example, that the younger age group focused on in other, as yet unknown, surface features. For
the legs of the cat and the wheels of the dog and example, it is possible that by 22 months of age
generalized on this basis; the older age group, in infants have learned that things with legs move
contrast, were more constrained in their match- nonlinearly, that things with legs tend to have
ing to the model exemplar. eyes, and therefore that things with eyes tend
To address this issue, Rakison (2005, to move nonlinearly. Ongoing research in our
Experiments 2 and 3) tested infants at 18 and laboratory is pursuing this explanation.
22 months of age with the same linear and The work by Rakison (2005) was a first step in
nonlinear motions and with the same set establishing that the initial basis for induction
(Experiment 2) and a different set (Experiment in infancy is not an abstract concept of animal
3) of test exemplars. However, as in the experi- or vehicle but rather is a represented associa-
ments by Rakison et al. (2007), an ambiguous tive link between a dynamic feature (e.g., legs,
block was the model exemplar for the various wheels) and a specific motion. More recently, we
land movements (the block was the stimulus have explored the basis for induction for another
on the far right of Figure 12.4). As before, using important characteristic motion of animates,
246 INDUCTION

namely, goal-directed action (Cicchino & the study instead of a hand, they no longer
Rakison, 2008). Goal-directed action can be looked longer at the new goal event than at the
defined as motion that is aimed at another new side event.
entity, object, or location and that is governed To examine at what point in developmental
by an intention (Cicchino & Rakison, 2008; time infants generalize goal-directed action to
Woodward, Sommerville, & Guajardo, 2001). It animals and not vehicles, Cicchino and Rakison
has been proposed that infants’ earliest appre- (2007) tested infants between 14 and 26 months
ciation of goal-directed action encompasses of age with an inductive generalization ver-
the ability to associate actions with the objects sion of Woodward’s (1998) task. Infants saw an
at which they are directed (Woodward, 2005) experimenter move an object a number of times
and that in developmental time, this under- toward one of two goal objects on a premade
standing deepens to include the identification environment. Figure 12.5 illustrates the testing
of the intentions that motivate these actions environment and the four-goal stimuli (a bed,
(Csibra & Gergely, 1998; Tomasello, Carpenter, food, toys, and a ball). After the modeling phase,
Call, Behne, & Moll, 2005). The development the locations of the two objects were switched
of infants’ understanding of goal-directed and infants were encouraged to move the same
action has received much attention in the lit- object that the experimenter had moved toward
erature over the past 10 years, perhaps because the goal objects. Note that in contrast to the
the research pertaining to this topic straddles other inductive generalization tasks described
the realms of social cognition and conceptual in this chapter, in these experiments, infants
development. used the same toy exemplar as the experimenter
To examine when and how infants learn to enact an event. Unlike the prediction that
that animates but not inanimates are goal- followed from Woodward’s (1998) habituation
directed, Cicchino and Rakison (2007) used task, it was hypothesized that if infants attrib-
a version of the now classic task developed by uted goal-directedness to an object, they would
Woodward (1998, 1999). In the original tasks, move it more often toward the same object as
5- and 9-month-old infants were habituated the experimenter had during the modeling
to an event in which a hand reached for one of phase than toward the same side; if infants did
two objects on a stage. In the test phase of the not associate the object with the object it had
study, the locations of the two objects on the contacted, performance was expected to be at
stage were switched. Infants viewed a new side chance levels.
test trial in which they saw the hand reach to the In a first study designed to address when
same object as that during habituation but to a infants generalize goal-directed action to ani-
new location, and a new goal test trial in which mals and not vehicles (Cicchino & Rakison,
they viewed the hand reach toward the same 2008, Experiment 1), 14-, 18-, and 22-month-
location as that during habituation but toward olds participated in the task with two animals
a different object. It was hypothesized that if and two vehicles as the test exemplars. When
infants viewed the hand’s action in habituation infants were shown an animal moving toward a
to be directed at a specific object, they would goal, 14-month-olds did not display a preference
then look longer at the new goal test trial than at for either the location or the path, 18-month-
the new side test trial, because only the new goal olds moved the toys along the same path as that
test trial violated the relationship between the seen during the modeling phase, and 22-month-
hand and the object learned during habituation. olds imitated the action of the experimenter by
Infants at both 5 and 9 months of age displayed moving the toys toward the same object as in the
this pattern of results and looked longer at the modeling phase. In contrast, when infants were
new goal test trial than at the new side test trial. shown a vehicle moving toward a goal, infants
However, when infants were presented with a in all three age groups showed no reliable pref-
rod, hand-shaped occluder, or mechanical claw erence for the either the same object or the same
that made contact with the object throughout path as that observed in the modeling phase.
DEVELOPMENT OF INDUCTIVE INFERENCE IN INFANCY 247

Figure 12.5 Testing environment and goal stimuli in Cicchino and Rakison (2007).

This pattern of results suggests that 18-month- conceptual representation for animals (in
old infants associated animals, but not vehicles, which case they would move only the intact cow
with their path of motion but not with their final toward the same object as that observed during
goal, and that 22-month-olds can selectively the modeling phase). The results of the experi-
associate the actions of nonhuman animals, but ment showed that 22-month-olds generalized
not of vehicles, with a goal object. goal-directed action to objects with legs and did
To address whether the basis for this induc- so regardless of whether or not they possessed
tive behavior was an abstract concept of ani- facial features; however, they did not generalize
macy or salient perceptual cues, in a follow-up goal-directed action to entities on the basis of
experiment Cicchino and Rakison (2007, facial features alone. This pattern of behavior,
Experiment 3) used the same procedure with which is consistent with that of previous induc-
22-month-olds but the test exemplars were an tion and categorization studies (Rakison, 2005;
intact scale model cow, a cow missing legs, a Rakison & Butterworth, 1998), suggests that
cow missing facial features, and a cow missing the presence of legs, but not of facial features, is
both facial features and legs. These stimuli are critical for infants to attribute goal-directedness
illustrated in Figure 12.6. The rationale for this to animals.
design was to determine whether infants gen- In a final study designed to determine if and
eralize goal-directed action for animals on the when young children generalize goal-directed
basis of legs, facial features, or a more abstract action to animals more broadly—that is, not
248 INDUCTION

Figure 12.6 Modified cow stimuli used in Experiment 3 by Cicchino and Rakison (2008).

on the basis of legs—26-month-olds were tested and goal-directed action for infants and young
in the same procedure but the four test stimuli children (Cicchino & Rakison, 2008; Rakison,
were chosen based on their category member- 2005). A distinct developmental trend was
ship and whether or not they had legs. The observed for infants’ knowledge of linear and
rationale for this choice of stimuli was similar nonlinear land motions; their initial represen-
to that in Rakison (2005); one object was an ani- tations involved an associative link between
mal with legs (a camel), another was an animal specific features and specific motion paths but
without legs (a snake), one was not an animal later, around 22 months of age, this link was
but possessed legs (a table), and a final object extended to include objects that did not possess
was not an animal and did not have legs (a car). those features. In contrast, infants’ knowledge
It was predicted, based on Rakison (2005), that of goal-directed action showed a developmen-
26-month-olds would generalize goal-directed tal progression in terms of when they started
action to the two animals and not to the objects to understand that animals and not vehicles
with legs; however, the results showed that even are goal-directed. However, object features
in the third year of life, children generalize remained the basis for induction as late as 26
goal-directed action on the basis of parts rather months of age.
than category membership. In other words,
Summary
26-month-olds moved the camel and the table
toward the same goal as the experimenter had The studies reported in this section provide
during the modeling phase, but they did not do strong evidence against the view that infants’
so for the snake or the car. inductive inference is based on an abstract con-
In conjunction, this program of research ceptual representation for animals, vehicles, and
shows that perceptual features—such as legs— other superordinate categories and that it is not
act as the basis for induction for simple motions influenced by the surface appearance of objects
DEVELOPMENT OF INDUCTIVE INFERENCE IN INFANCY 249

(Mandler & McDonough, 1996, 1998; Pauen, at the laboratory; and (2) the basis for induc-
2002; Poulin-Dubois et al., 2006). Clearly, fur- tion for any property must be studied before
ther research on infants’ inductive inferences for conclusions can be drawn about the nature and
other motion properties such as self-propulsion content of infants’ concepts. In support of these
or agency is necessary to solidify this claim, and views, we provided data from inductive gener-
indeed such research is already underway in our alization studies with 14- to 26-month-olds that
laboratory. Nonetheless, the available data cast show that infants are influenced by the model
doubt on the idea that the mechanisms for learn- exemplar used by the experimenter and that
ing such information are specialized rather than perceptual features—such as legs and wheels—
general. Recall that a corollary of such a view is act as the basis for early induction for motion
that infants are precocious concept formers, and properties.
that they develop rich representations about, for In light of the fact that research on induc-
example, animals that incorporate how they tion in infancy is a recent development, there
move in the world. The experiments discussed is clearly much work to be done. The work to
here show that such representations are not in data has focused largely on the bodily, sensory,
place until at least the end of the second year and motion properties of animals and vehicles
of life, findings that are incompatible with the but has largely ignored infants’ knowledge of
“top-down” view of Mandler and others. other animates—people and insects—and the
many categories of inanimate objects (e.g.,
CONCLUDING COMMENTS tools, furniture). Research from our laboratory
has started to investigate infants’ understand-
In this chapter, we have challenged the pre- ing of the properties of the members of these
dominant “top-down” view of early inductive categories, but important questions remain
inference. According to this view, induction unanswered. Which surface features are associ-
and categorization by infants as young as 9 to 11 ated with which actions? How are specific fea-
months of age is based on abstract knowledge ture-property associations generalized to other
about the properties of things that is acquired features? How much experience is required to
through specialized mechanisms, modules, or form such associations? And how do these asso-
innate principles (Gelman, 1990; Leslie, 1995; ciations generalized to categories of objects? In
Mandler, 1992; Mandler & McDonough, 1996, time, answers to these, and other, questions will
1998; Poulin-Dubois et al., 2006). We contested surely be forthcoming. In the meantime, it is
this perspective both on theoretical and empiri- the responsibility of researchers to be pragmatic
cal grounds. in their interpretation of infants’ behavior in
First, we proposed that infants’ concepts for the inductive generalization task and to design
objects and entities are generated via general experiments that will elucidate the nature and
rather than specific mechanisms. As a corol- content of infants’ developmental representa-
lary of this view, we argued that early knowl- tions for the objects and entities in the world.
edge about the properties of things in the world
involves an associative links between specific
surface features and those properties, and that REFERENCES
such representations are not in place until the
middle or end of the second year of life (see also Baldwin, D. A., Markman, E. M., & Melartin, E.
M. (1993).Infants’ ability to draw inferences
Oakes & Madole, 2003; Quinn & Eimas, 1997;
about nonobvious object properties: Evidence
Smith, Jones, & Landau, 1996). Second, we
from exploratory play. Child Development, 64,
argued that care must be taken in interpreting 711–728.
infants’ behavior within the inductive gener- Bauer, P. J., & Dow, G. A. (1994). Episodic memory
alization procedure. In particular, we claimed in 16- and 20-month-old children: Specifics are
that (1) infants’ behavior in the task is not always generalized but not forgotten. Developmental
driven by knowledge acquired prior to arriving Psychology, 30, 403–417.
250 INDUCTION

Cicchino, J. B., & Rakison, D. H. (2008). Infants’ Oakes, L. M., & Madole, K. L. (2003). Principles
attribution of goal-directed action to non-hu- of developmental change in infants’ category
man animals. Manuscript under review. formation. In D.H. Rakison & L.M. Oakes
Csibra, G., & Gergely, G. (1998). The teleologi- (Eds.), Early category and concept develop-
cal origins of mentalistic action explanations: ment: Making sense of the blooming, buzzing
A developmental hypothesis. Developmental confusion (pp.159–192). New York: Oxford
Science, 1, 255–259. University Press.
Csibra, G., Gergely, G., Bíró, S., Koós, O., & Oakes, L. M., Madole, K. L., & Cohen, L. B. (1991).
Brockbank, M. (1999). Goal attribution with- Infant habituation and categorization of real
out agency cues: The perception of ‘pure rea- objects. Cognitive Development, 6, 377–392.
son’ in infancy. Cognition, 72, 237–267. Pauen, S. (2002). Evidence for knowledge-based
Furrer, S. D., Younger, B .A., & Johnson, K. E. category discrimination in infancy. Child
(2005, April) Do planes drink? Generalized Development, 73, 1016–1033.
imitation following modeling with an inappro- Poulin-Dubois, D., Frenkiel-Fishman, S., Nayer,
priate exemplar. Poster presented at the Society S., & Johnson, S. (2006). Infants’ inductive
for Research in Child Development Biennial generalization of bodily, motion, and sensory
Conference, Atlanta, GA. properties to animals and people. Journal of
Gelman, R. (1990). First principles organize Cognition and Development, 7, 431–453.
attention to and learning about relevant data: Premack, D. (1990). The infants’ theory of self-
Number and the animate–inanimate distinc- propelled objects. Cognition, 36, 1–16.
tion as examples. Cognitive Science, 14, 79–106. Quinn, P. C., & Eimas, P. D. (1997). A reexami-
Gelman, S. A., & Markman, E. M. (1986). nation of the perceptual-to-conceptual shift
Categories and induction in young children. in mental representations. Review of General
Cognition, 23, 183–209. Psychology, 1, 171–187.
Gelman, S. A., & Markman, E. M. (1987). Young Rakison, D. H. (2003). Parts, categorization, and
children’s inductions from natural kinds: the animate–inanimate distinction in infancy.
The role of categories and appearances. Child In D. H. Rakison, & L. M. Oakes, (Eds.), Early
Development, 58, 1532–1541. category and concept development: Making sense
Gergely, G., Nádasdy, Z., Csibra, G., & Bíró, S. of the blooming buzzing confusion (pp. 159–192).
(1995). Taking the intentional stance at 12 New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
months of age. Cognition, 56, 165–193. Rakison, D. H. (2005). Developing knowledge of
Killen, M., & Uzgiris, I. C. (1981). Imitation of motion properties in infancy. Cognition, 96,
actions with objects: The role of social meaning. 183–214.
Journal of Genetic Psychology, 138, 219–229. Rakison, D. H. (2006). Make the first move: How
Leslie, A. (1995). A theory of agency. In D. Sperber, infants learn about the identity of self-pro-
D. Premack, & A.J. Premack (Eds.), Causal cog- pelled objects. Developmental Psychology, 42,
nition (pp. 121–141). Oxford: Clarendon. 900–912.
Mandler, J. M. (1992). How to build a baby: II. Rakison, D. H., & Butterworth, G. (1998).
Conceptual primitives. Psychological Review, Infants’ use of parts in early categorization.
99, 587–604. Developmental Psychology, 34, 49–62.
Mandler, J. M. (2004). The foundations of mind: Rakison, D. H., Cicchino, J. B., & Hahn, E. R.
Origins of conceptual thought. New York: (2007). Infants’ knowledge of the identity of
Oxford University Press. rational goal-directed entities. British Journal
Mandler, J. M., & McDonough, L. (1996). Drinking of Developmental Psychology, 25, 461–470.
and driving don’t mix: Inductive generaliza- Rakison, D. H., & Lupyan, G. (2008). Developing
tion in infancy. Cognition, 59, 307–335. object concepts in infancy: An associa-
Mandler, J. M., & McDonough, L. (1998). Studies tive learning perspective. Monographs of the
in inductive inference in infancy. Cognitive Society for Research in Child Development,
Psychology, 37, 60–96. 73(1), 1–110.
McDonough, L., & Mandler, J. M. (1998). Inductive Rakison, D. H., & Poulin-Dubois, D. (2000, July).
generalization in 9- and 11-month-olds. Infants’ understanding of animate and inani-
Developmental Science. 1, 227–232. mate motion events. In D.H. Rakison (Chair),
DEVELOPMENT OF INDUCTIVE INFERENCE IN INFANCY 251

Components of the animate–inanimate distinc- Woodward, A.L. (1998). Infants selectively encode
tion in infancy. Paper presented at the twelft h the goal object of an actor’s reach. Cognition,
Biennial International Conference on Infant 69, 1–34.
Studies, Brighton, UK. Woodward, A. L. (1999). Infants’ ability to distin-
Sloutsky, V. M., & Fisher, A. V. (2004). Induction guish between purposeful and non-purposeful
and categorization in young children: A behaviors. Infant Behavior and Development,
similarity-based model. Journal of Experimental 22, 145–160.
Psychology: General, 133, 166–188. Woodward, A. L. (2005). The infant origins of
Smith, L. B., Jones, S. S., & Landau, B. (1996). intentional understanding. In R. Kail (Ed.),
Naming in young children: a dumb attentional Advances in child development and behavior
mechanism? Cognition, 60, 143–171. (Vol. 33, pp. 229–262). Oxford: Elsevier.
Tomasello, M., Carpenter, M., Call, J., Behne, T., Woodward, A. L., Sommerville, J. A., & Guajardo,
& Moll, H. (2005). Understanding and sharing J. J. (2001). How infants make sense of inten-
intentions: The origins of cultural cognition. tional action. In B. Malle, L. Moses & D.
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 28, 675–735. Baldwin (Eds.) Intentions and intentionality:
Tomasello, M., & Striano, T. (2001) Social Foundations of social cognition (pp. 149–169).
and object support for early symbolic play. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Developmental Science, 4, 442–455. Younger, B. A., & Johnson, K. E. (2004). Infants’
Tomasello, M., Striano, T., & Rochat, P. (1999) comprehension of toy replicas as symbols
Do young children use objects as symbols? for real objects. Cognitive Psychology, 48,
British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 207–242.
17, 563–584.
CHAP TER 13
The Acquisition of Expertise as a Model
for the Growth of Cognitive Structure

Paul C. Quinn

If one is interested in the question of how in adult participants (Bukach, Gauthier, & Tarr,
knowledge is acquired, then the period of 2006; Palmeri, Wong, & Gauthier, 2004; Tanaka
infancy becomes an important time window of & Gauthier, 1997). This literature has pointed
empirical inquiry. During the first few months to two hallmark characteristics of perceptual
of life, infants begin to experience objects from expertise. One is that objects within an expert
various classes, but at different rates or frequen- domain tend to be recognized at a specific, sub-
cies of presentation. For example, infants are ordinate, individual-exemplar level, rather than
likely to encounter conspecifics, other humans, at a generic, basic, category level. For example,
more frequently than say, nonhuman animals, a bird expert is likely to identify a sparrow as a
even in a family environment that includes a “sparrow” rather than as a “bird.” Th is marker of
nonhuman animal (cat or dog) as a pet. This expertise has been referred to as the “downward
feature of infants’ early experience allows inves- shift in recognition” (Tanaka, 2001). Notably,
tigators to ask whether there are differences the shift corresponds with an effect which has
in the (1) way that infants categorize humans been observed in studies of category learning
versus nonhuman animals, (2) nature of the in adults, namely, that during the time course
category representations formed by infants for of learning a category, individuals come to sup-
humans versus nonhuman animals, (3) per- plement a rule-based or summary structure
ceptual attributes that infants use to categorize with a structure that represents the individual
humans versus nonhuman animals, and (4) rel- exemplars (Gauthier & Tarr, 1997; Johansen &
ative amounts of top-down versus bottom-up Palmeri, 2002; Smith & Minda, 1998). A second
processing used to categorize humans versus manifestation of expertise is the tendency for
nonhuman animals. objects to be perceived holistically (Gauthier &
The contrast between how infants respond to Tarr, 2002). This mode of perceptual encoding
humans versus nonhuman animals may repre- emphasizes that there are performance advan-
sent an expert–novice difference in the early tages associated with processing the whole as
development of perceptual category representa- opposed to processing individual parts (e.g., a
tions. This interpretation provides the starting whole superiority effect).
point for the broader proposal that the “train- Given that the downward shift in recogni-
ing and transfer of perceptual expertise” may tion and holistic processing effects have been
represent a model for thinking about knowl- documented as markers of expertise in adults,
edge acquisition and cognitive development in developmentalists interested in when exper-
general. Over the last 10 years, a literature has tise emerges can ask whether there are any
arisen on how perceptual expertise can emerge stimulus domains where these effects become

252
MODEL FOR THE GROW TH OF COGNITIVE STRUCTURE 253

evident in infants. In addition, studying how


expertise may arise early in development could CATEGORIZATION OF NONHUMAN ANIMALS
provide investigators with insights that may BY YOUNG INFANTS
not be achieved in studies that train exper-
Looking Time Studies
tise in adults. Specifically, adults who acquire
expertise in a particular domain have an entire A familiarization/novelty-preference procedure
knowledge base that can be recruited as the has been used to study how infants categorize
expertise is acquired. By contrast, young infants nonhuman animals such as cats and horses
who may develop expertise are doing so without (Mareschal & Quinn, 2001). Infants are pre-
an extensive knowledge base, and thus one may sented with multiple instances from a common
be better able to determine how the expertise category during familiarization and then with
affects the representation of generic nonexpert a preference test pairing a novel instance from
object information that is being acquired in the the familiar category and a novel instance from
same developmental time window as the exper- a novel category. Categorization is inferred if
tise. That is, by studying how expertise emerges infants generalize their familiarization to the
in young infants, one may be in a stronger posi- novel instance from the familiar category and
tion to assess how that expertise structures the display a preference for the novel instance from
acquisition of nonexpert information, thereby the novel category. The preference is measured
providing a more informed sense of how infor- in looking time, and it is important to demon-
mation can accrue to existing representations strate in control procedures that the preference
and form a domain of knowledge. On this basis, cannot be attributed to (1) an a priori prefer-
investigations of the effects of expertise devel- ence for instances of the novel category over
opment in infants may inform studies exam- instances of the familiar category or (2) the
ining how the training of expertise may bring inability to discriminate among instances of the
about cognitive change in adults. familiar category. Concluding that categoriza-
The chapter will begin by asking whether tion has occurred based on this pattern of per-
infants can form category representations for formance accords well with the traditional way
nonhuman animals, via what stimulus attri- categorization has been defined in the adult con-
butes such representations might be formed, cept literature, namely, as equivalent respond-
and whether infants are forming these cat- ing to discriminably different instances from
egory representations on the basis of stimulus a common class based on some internalized
images presented in the laboratory. The chap- representation of the class (Bruner, Goodnow,
ter will proceed to a discussion of whether & Austin, 1956).
infants categorize humans, and whether the With the familiarization/novelty-preference
category structure that infants use to represent procedure, 3- to 4-month-old infants famil-
humans differs from the structure infants use iarized with a dozen visual images of cats have
to represent nonhuman animals. Also consid- generalized their familiarization to novel cats
ered will be the stimulus information infants and displayed novel category preferences for
use to represent humans as well as whether exemplars of birds, dogs, and horses (Oakes
infants respond to human images presented in & Ribar, 2005; Quinn, Eimas, & Rosenkrantz,
the laboratory on the basis of knowledge about 1993; Younger & Fearing, 1999). Likewise,
humans acquired prior to arrival at the labora- same-aged infants familiarized with photo-
tory. The chapter will conclude with the the- graphic instances of horses have generalized
sis that what infants know about nonhuman their familiarization to novel horses and shown
animals can be likened to what novices know novel category preferences for exemplars of cats,
about generic object categories, whereas what giraffes, and zebras (Eimas & Quinn, 1994).
infants know about humans can be likened These novel category preferences are not attrib-
to what experts know about their domain of utable to a priori preference, nor can they be
expertise. explained by an inability to discriminate among
254 INDUCTION

the familiar category instances. The results


indicate that infants can form individuated cat-
egory representations for cats and horses, each
of which excludes instances of the other as well
as exemplars of other basic-level nonhuman
animal categories.
Examples of the cats can be seen in seen in
Figure 13.1, where it can be observed that the
images presented to the infants are realistic
and depict different breeds of cats in a variety
of colors and stances. The variation amongst
the exemplars decreases the likelihood that
the infants could represent one or more spu-
rious stimulus attributes that are common to
a small set of stimulus images but not neces-
sarily diagnostic of “catness” as it exists in the
natural world. It should also be mentioned that
each category was represented by 18 different
instances. Having this many stimuli included
in each category allowed each individual infant
to be presented with a randomly selected set of Figure 13.1 Examples of the cat images
12 exemplars during familiarization, and with presented in the studies investigating infants’
randomly selected pairings of novel stimuli categorization of nonhuman animals.
from the familiar and novel categories during
the preference test. This feature of the experi-
mental design increases the ecological valid- investigated whether neural correlates of cat-
ity of the study given that no two infants are egory learning by infants might be measurable.
likely to experience the same set of cats in the They did so by developing an event-related poten-
same order during early development. Finally, tial (ERP) analog of the behavioral looking-time
Figure 13.1 makes clear that the stimuli from procedure. This involved placing a 64-channel
within a category are highly discriminable and Geodesic Sensor Net on the head of the partici-
this underscores again that the preferences can- pating infants to record their brain wave activ-
not be attributed merely to processes of per- ity (Tucker, 1993). Attempting to make the ERP
ceptual discrimination between categories (cf., recording procedure equivalent to the behav-
Bauer, Dow, & Hertsgaard, 1995; Dueker & ioral looking-time procedure can be challenging
Needham, 2005; Pauen, 2002; Xu, 1997). The given that ERPs are measured for short, discrete,
infants can discriminate between the different half-second presentations of visual stimuli,
instances of the cats just as readily as they can whereas in the behavioral looking-time studies,
discriminate between a cat and a dog, yet they the images are continuously available for 10 to 15
are also able to look through this variation so s at a time. In an effort to provide the infants in
as to group together the various cat images into the ERP procedure with an amount of category
a common representation that excludes the dog structure at least somewhat comparable to that
images. presented in the looking-time studies, Quinn et
al. compensated for the shorter-duration stimuli
Neural Correlates
by presenting more of them, while at the same
As a complement to the behavioral looking-time time remaining cognizant of the limited atten-
studies demonstrating category formation for tion span of infants and the total number of
the various nonhuman animal species by infants, stimulus presentations the infants would toler-
Quinn, Westerlund, and Nelson (2006) recently ate. These considerations led to an experimental
MODEL FOR THE GROW TH OF COGNITIVE STRUCTURE 255

design in which infants were presented with 36 The analytical plan involved partitioning
cat images followed by 20 novel cat images inter- the results (i.e., the neural activations observed
spersed with 20 dog images. in different parts of the scalp up to a second
It should also be acknowledged that the and a half after stimulus presentation) into
participants in the ERP studies were 6-month- four different conditions: cats 1–18, cats 19–36,
olds, approximately 2.5 months older than the novel cats, and novel dogs. The rationale is
3- to 4-month-old participants in the behav- that if there is a neural signal that corresponds
ioral studies. The age change was necessitated with category learning, then the responses to
because pilot testing revealed a substantially cats 1–18 and the novel dogs (reflecting initial
higher attrition rate of the younger infants par- experience with exemplars of a category) are
ticipating in the ERP procedure. The higher equivalent. The responses to cats 19–36 and
attrition rate could be attributed to a greater the novel cats (reflecting a learned category
likelihood for the younger age group to engage of cats) should also be equivalent, but differ-
in head movements during stimulus presenta- ent from the responses to cats 1–18 and the
tions, thereby creating artifacts in the resulting novel dogs.
neural activity that make it difficult to determine With regard to expectations for how the
what portions of the neural response were due amplitude and latency of the brain wave com-
to the head movement and what portions were ponents of infants might be affected in a cate-
due to the stimulus presentation. Fortunately, gory learning procedure, the only guide was the
6-month-olds, like their younger counterparts, brain wave responsiveness of infants observed
have been shown to form category representa- in studies of simple recognition memory (e.g.,
tions for nonhuman animal species in behav- Nelson, 1994; Reynolds & Richards, 2005). Of
ioral looking-time procedures (Eimas & Quinn, interest is a late-slow wave component observed
1994), thereby facilitating comparison with in the time window between 1,000 and 1,500
outcomes obtained from ERP procedures. A ms after stimulus presentation. The amplitude
6-month-old wearing the geodesic sensor net is of the slow wave has been associated with the
depicted in Figure 13.2. differentiation of familiar and novel stimuli. In

Figure 13.2 A 6-month-old infant wearing the Geodesic sensor net (Courtesy of Alissa Westerlund).
256 INDUCTION

Front of head

15

10
Amplitude (microvolts)

5 Back of head

–5

–10
NSW
–15
–100 100 300 500 700 900 1100 1300
Latency (milliseconds)
Cats 1–18 blue, Cats 19–36 red, Novel Cats orange, Nobvel Dogs green

Figure 13.3 Grand average infant ERPs reflecting the negative slow wave (NSW) response to the first
set of familiar cats (blue), second set of familiar cats (red), novel cats (orange), and novel dogs (green)
for a group (average) of left occipital-parietal electrodes.

particular, a slow wave that returns to baseline


Perceptual Processes Supporting Category
has been associated with the recognition of
Formation by Infants: What is the
familiarity, whereas a slow wave that deflects
Significance?
away from baseline in either the positive or
negative direction is associated with the detec- With infant category learning of nonhuman ani-
tion of novelty. As is depicted in Figure 13.3, mal species evident in both brain and behavior,
greater negative amplitude was recorded over one can ask what the larger significance of these
left occipital parietal scalp in the time window findings is for the conceptual development liter-
between 1,000 and 1,500 ms after stimulus ature. As described by Rogers and McClelland
onset in response to cats 1–18 and novel dogs (2004), “. . . these studies are viewed as being
than in response to cats 19–36 and novel cats. important for conceptual development, because
Th is analysis reveals that the infant’s brain they demonstrate that in many cases, the visual
responded to novel cats with activity equiva- similarities apparent from photographs of real
lent to that displayed for cats 19–36. More objects can be sufficient to allow the discrimina-
generally, it points to the neural instantiation tion of semantic categories” (p. 124). To expand
of a key behavioral indicant of categorization: on the observation of Rogers and McClelland,
responding to the novel as if it is familiar. That the studies of infant learning of nonhuman ani-
there is distinct brain activity corresponding mal categories suggest that young infants pos-
to the formation of a category representation sess abilities to divide the world of objects into
for the exemplars presented during famil- perceptual clusters that approximate a basic
iarization (e.g., the cats) provides convergent level of exclusivity. These perceptual cluster
evidence with the looking-time studies and representations later come to have conceptual
indicates a neural preparedness at 6 months to significance for adults. As such, the conceptual
represent category information on the basis of representations found later in development can
perceptual experience. be viewed as informational enrichments of the
MODEL FOR THE GROW TH OF COGNITIVE STRUCTURE 257

category representations that infants form on Smith, 1993). Moreover, Hampton, Estes, and
the basis of perceptual experience. Simmons (2007; see also Hampton, 1995) have
To provide a concrete example of the actually presented cases in which a majority
aforementioned ideas, consider infants who are of research participants weight characteristic
presented with exemplars of cats and horses. perceptual features more heavily than defi ning
The looking time and ERP studies suggest essentialist features in decisions about category
that the exemplars are not experienced as an identity.
undifferentiated bunch of grapes, but rather as Arguments about the relative force of per-
separate groups that fall into distinct represen- ceptual and nonobvious features aside, the
tations. These representations could then serve major claim here is that it is difficult to envision
as placeholders for the acquisition of the more how a child could go from experiencing cats and
abstract and nonobvious information that horses as an undifferentiated bunch of grapes to
occurs beyond infancy, through language and representing cats as having cat DNA and horses
more formal learning of semantic categories. as having horse DNA without the perceptual
Thus, over time, the perceptual placeholder placeholder representations that organize the
representation for horses will come to include individual cats and horses into distinct repre-
the information that horses eat hay, carry sentations serving as facilitating intermediaries.
heavy loads, give birth to foals, have horse In other words, it is hard to imagine how a child
DNA, and are labeled as “horses,” whereas the could even acquire the more abstract attributes
perceptual placeholder representation for cats and map them onto their correct object refer-
will come to include the information that cats ents without having category representations
eat tuna, hunt mice, give birth to kittens, have available from perceptual experience to serve
cat DNA, and are labeled as “cats.” The acqui- as support structures. Mapping attributes onto
sition of this additional information serves to objects on a case by case would arguably be a
enrich the original perceptually based category much slower and labor-intensive process. The
representations to the point that they attain the perceptual category representations of infants
richness and boundedness of the more mature may thus form an important linkage mecha-
conceptual representations of children and nism for conjoining concrete object classes
adults. with their nonobvious attributes in an efficient
It is important to acknowledge that this manner.
view does not deny that in some instances, the It is also important to acknowledge that the
more abstract information can supplant the emphasis in interpreting the category learning
more perceptual information when the two abilities is on the demonstration of perceptual
sources of information are placed in competi- parsing skills. There is no evidence, for exam-
tion as determinants of category identity (Keil, ple, that infants who are familiarized with cats
1989). Th is type of evidence has been used or horses in the laboratory are leaving the labo-
to support an “essentialist” view of concept ratory with long-term memory representations
development (Gelman, 2003), a perspective for these classes. The claim is that infants are
that argues that the organization of perceptual demonstrating perceptual grouping or cluster-
experience is not sufficient to explain the full ing abilities in the laboratory that are presum-
course of category development. While “essen- ably engaged when infants encounter cats and
tialist” arguments are persuasive, the claims horses in the course of experience in the world
have been challenged on the grounds that at outside the laboratory (or images of them as
least some of the evidence in which nonobvious depicted in videos and picture books). The latter
features win over perceptual features as indica- representations are those believed to be the ones
tors of category identity was obtained because that serve as the supports for the acquisition of
of salience differences between the individual the nonobvious attributes that occurs beyond
features presented in the comparisons (Jones & the infancy period.
258 INDUCTION

What Perceptual Information Do Young The conclusion of Quinn and Eimas (1996)
Infants Use to Categorize Nonhuman is supported by an additional study in which
Animals? infants were familiarized with whole cat or dog
images and then preference tested with hybrid
Although the chapter has thus far centered on
stimuli, i.e., cat head on dog body versus dog
the learning of category representations formed
head on cat body (Spencer, Quinn, Johnson, &
on the basis of perceptual experience, what has
Karmiloff-Smith, 1997). Examples of the stimuli
not yet been considered is the question of what
are presented in Figure 13.4. Infant preference
perceptual attributes infants are using to con-
followed the direction of the novel category head.
struct the category representations. One can ask
That the head region provided infants with the
whether it is the whole of the stimulus images that
information to separate cats and dogs into dif-
infants are using or whether it is a particular part
ferent category groupings is consistent with the
or the pattern of correlation across multiple parts.
broader idea that young infants’ category rep-
The answer to this question is not obvious, given
resentations for nonhuman animal species are
that the animal category representations sorted
structured by perceptual part or attribute infor-
by infants include cats, dogs, and horses, where
mation that can be detected from the surfaces
the exemplars of each category possess attributes
of the exemplars. In other words, young infants
in common such as a head, torso, legs, and a tail.
may represent nonhuman animal categories on
Quinn and Eimas (1996) examined the abili-
a featural basis. Interestingly, adults also seem
ties of 3- to 4-month-olds to categorize cats ver-
to emphasize the head when representing non-
sus dogs when provided with the whole stimuli,
human animal species (Reed, McGoldrick,
just the heads (with the body occluded), or just
Schackelford, & Fidopiastis, 2004).
the bodies (with the head occluded) during both
the familiarization and preference test por- Head Preference: Attentional Bias
tions of the experiment. The results were that or Diagnostic Feature?
the infants categorized when presented with
the whole stimuli (this outcome should not be A question of recent interest has been why infants
surprising given that it constitutes a replication use the heads to categorize the cats as separate
of results already described) and also when pre- from the dogs. Use of the head could arise from
sented with just the heads, although not with a biasing mechanism that orients infant atten-
just the bodies. The findings indicate that the tion to attend to head information that is pres-
head provided a sufficient basis for the infants ent in a visual scene (Johnson & Morton, 1991).
to categorize cats versus dogs. Such a biasing mechanism would be adaptive in

Figure 13.4 Examples of the cat–dog hybrid stimuli presented to the infants in Spencer et al. (1997).
MODEL FOR THE GROW TH OF COGNITIVE STRUCTURE 259

terms of insuring that infants will attend to and the body to partition cats and dogs into separate
eventually recognize faces. It is also possible categories has relied on eye tracking to measure
that the infants simply learn that the head is the the eye movements that infants use to scan the
most diagnostic part of the stimulus and that the visual images that they are presented with in
head feature is flexibly created as the basis for the category learning task. This in turn allows
the category representation during the course of one to conduct the same behavioral experi-
experience with the exemplars (Quinn, Schyns, ments that have used looking time as a measure
& Goldstone, 2006). This possibility seems rea- of categorization performance and learn where
sonable to suggest given that the head may have on the stimulus images the infants are fi xating.
fewer degrees of freedom relative to the body On the assumption that stimulus regions used
in terms of the various stances presented to the for categorization will be preferentially fi xated
infants (Reed, Stone, & McGoldrick, 2005). As over those not used, Quinn, Doran, Reiss, and
such, it might be more easily extracted as an Hoff man (2009) reasoned that if the head pref-
invariant feature. erence results from a biasing mechanism, then
To tease apart whether use of the heads infants should fi xate more on the heads than the
was due to top-down or bottom-up influences, bodies of the exemplars throughout the course
Mermillod, French, Smeets, and Spencer (2005) of the familiarization portion of a category
employed an empirical strategy based on com- learning procedure. Alternatively, if the infants
putational modeling. In particular, Mermillod are learning that the head is the most diagnostic
et al. followed the lead of Mareschal and French region of the stimuli, then the head preference
(1997) who proposed that the learning that should emerge during the course of the famil-
occurs in infant looking time experiments is iarization trials.
analogous to the learning that occurs in sim- Quinn et al. (2009) tested 6-month-old
ple connectionist networks. In particular, the infants on the eye-tracking version of the cat-
extent to which an infant continues to look at egorization familiarization task. The findings
a stimulus reflects the difference between the were that 46% of the fi xation time that was
actual stimulus and the mental representation on the stimulus was on the head and 54% on
of the stimulus in the same way that error in the body, percentages that remained constant
an autoassociative network reflects the extent throughout familiarization. The percentages
to which output does not match with input. take on additional meaning when one considers
Mermillod et al. simulated the Spencer et al. that the head area represented only 17.5% of the
(1997) experiments with the hybrid stimuli by whole stimulus area of the cat and dog images;
training an autoencoder on cat or dog images, the body took up the remaining 82.5%. This
with each image expressed as an input vec- means that on a per unit area basis, equating
tor with 7 features from the head and 7 from for the size difference between the head and the
the body. When the network was tested on body, when the infants are fi xating the stimulus,
the hybrid images presented in accord with they are actually spending 80% of their fi xation
the same input scheme, the head preference time per unit area of the head and 20% of their
observed in the experiment with the infants fi xation time per unit area of the body.
was not reproduced. Error was equivalent for The results are consistent with the idea that
both kinds of the hybrid images, instead of the reliance on the head for the categorical pars-
there being greater error for the images with the ing of cats and dogs arises from a biasing mecha-
novel category head. This finding is consistent nism. However, one could still argue that infants
with the idea that the head preference does not are simply orienting to the head because it con-
arise from bottom-up processes deriving the tains high contrast internal features and infants
head as a diagnostic feature from the statistics are attracted to the most visible portion of the
of the input. stimulus (Banks & Salapatek, 1981). To address
Another approach taken to address the ques- this possibility, a control study was undertaken
tion of why infants rely on the head rather than that repeated the eye-tracking version of the
260 INDUCTION

category familiarization procedure, but with trajectory of learning” (Thelen & Smith, 1994,
stimulus images that were inverted (Quinn p. 315). Such biases may be especially important
et al., 2009). If the head preference resulted in determining the course of concept acquisi-
from infants’ simply orienting to the most vis- tion in a system that is otherwise characterized
ible portion of the stimulus, then it should still by flexibility.
be observed with inversion. However, if the
On-Line Learning or Preexisting
infants orient to the head because of a bias that
Representations?
is in place to facilitate face recognition, then one
would not expect it to be present with stimulus One question not yet considered is whether the
inversion, given that inversion changes the nor- representations that human infants form for
mal configuration of facial features, and faces nonhuman animals are learned as the infants
are believed to be recognized on a configural are presented with images of the categories dur-
basis by infants in the age range investigated ing the course of the familiarization trials or
(Cohen & Cashon, 2001). whether the experiments are tapping into rep-
The results of the control study revealed resentations that were formed on the basis of
that in the inversion condition only 11% of the experiences that occurred prior to arrival at the
fi xation time on the stimulus was on the head, laboratory. A way of addressing this issue is to
whereas 89% was on the body. This outcome ask if infant experience with a home pet affects
suggests that when the images are inverted, the categorization performance. That is, if a group of
relative distribution of fi xations to the head and infants is reared with a pet at home that belongs
body regions are proportional to the relative to the same category as that experienced during
areas of these regions. The control results the familiarization trials of a category learning
indicate that the bias to fi xate on the head experiment, one can ask if this group performs
over the body in the initial experiment is not differently than another group of infants reared
because the head contains high-contrast fea- in a household without a pet. Because a num-
tures. When the images were inverted, the fi xa- ber of our studies have involved the category
tion time to the head was substantially reduced contrast of cats versus dogs, the most common
despite the same sensory power emanating from family pets, we have had the opportunity to
the head region across the two experiments. compare the performance of 3- to 4-month-old
This finding provides evidence that infants infants without a pet at home with those who
use the head to categorize upright cat and dog had a cat or dog as a pet a home that was a match
images because of a preexisting biasing mecha- with the cat or dog category presented during
nism that responds to face information. familiarization of a category learning task. This
As proposed by Johnson and Morton (1991), analysis has not yielded a reliable difference.
a bias to attend to face information present in The lack of an effect of a home pet on infant
a visual display may play a facilitative role in performance on categorization tasks involving
terms of allowing infants to attend to and rec- nonhuman animals is consistent with the idea
ognize members of their own species and also that the infants are processing the stimuli based
specific persons such as the primary caregiver. on the information presented in the laboratory
The present studies suggest that the bias could tasks rather than on the basis of representations
more broadly assist conceptual development that existed prior to arrival at the laboratory.
by allowing infants to differentiate categories Another clue to whether infant categoriza-
that have faces (e.g., animals) and those that do tion of nonhuman animals is based on within-
not (e.g., furniture), as well as partition clas- task learning or preexisting representations
ses marked by distinctive facial make-ups (e.g., comes from an asymmetry that is observed
cats vs. dogs). The bias may also aid infants in when one compares the performance of infants
selecting from among various features that are familiarized with cats or dogs and tested with
potentially available in the input (i.e., head or novel cats versus novel dogs (Quinn et al., 1993).
body), and in this way “set the system on the In particular, when infants are familiarized
MODEL FOR THE GROW TH OF COGNITIVE STRUCTURE 261

with cats, they prefer dogs over novel cats; had been observed in infant looking time. In
however, when infants are familiarized with particular, when trained on cat images, the
dogs, attention is divided evenly between cats network produced a high level of error for dog
and novel dogs. This asymmetry is surpris- images and little error for novel cat images. In
ing given that on an a priori basis, one might contrast, when trained on dog images, the net-
predict that infants presented with a category work produced equivalent amounts of error for
contrast in a completely balanced experimental cat and novel dog images.
design would show evidence of categorization Because the network had only the measure-
in both directions (cat to dog or dog to cat) or in ments of the stimuli to learn from, and was able
neither direction. The asymmetrical pattern of to simulate the behavior of the infants, the indi-
preference is actually consistent with the possi- cation is that the key to explaining the perfor-
bility that there could be a spontaneous prefer- mance asymmetry lies in the statistics of the
ence for dogs that would interfere with a novel input presented to the infants. This suggestion
category preference for cats after familiariza- is confirmed through detailed examination
tion with dogs and work in concert with a novel of the distribution of values measured for the
category preference for dogs after familiariza- individual attributes of the cat and dog images.
tion with cats. However, when infants were pre- Consider the attribute of nose width. What can
sented with a category preference test involving be seen in Figure 13.5 is that the distribution of
cat–dog pairings, no spontaneous preference values of the nose width attribute correspond-
was observed; the infants attended equally to ing to the dog images is broader than that of the
the cat and dog images. cat images, thereby creating an inclusion rela-
Another explanation for the asymmetry tion in which the cat values are subsumed by the
arose because visual inspection of the stimuli dog values. This inclusion relation was observed
suggested that the dog images were more var- for a majority of the attributes.
iable than those of the cats. As noted earlier, an The outcome of the analysis of the individ-
attempt had been made to gather cat and dog ual attributes provides an explanation for the
images for presentation to the infants that were original category learning performance asym-
representative of the categories as they existed metry of the infants: Following familiariza-
in nature. Nevertheless, the differences between tion with cats, there is a good likelihood that
the Calico, Siamese, Tabby, and Birman breeds, a dog image will follow outside of the familiar-
for example, seemed not to match the variation ized range of values and be detected as novel;
among the French Poodles, Bulldogs, Collies, however, after familiarization with dogs, there
and Terriers. is a strong probability that a cat image will fall
To develop a more quantitative account of within the familiarized range of values, and not
the category variability explanation for the
performance asymmetry, a number of the sur-
face attributes of the cat and dog images were Cats
measured. The attributes included those from
the head and face (given the importance of
this region for the category distinction) along
with those corresponding with the basic skel-
Dogs
etal dimensions of stimuli. The measurements
allowed each stimulus to be expressed as a vec-
tor of values that could be presented as input
0.2 0.4 0.6 0.8 1
to a connectionist autoencoder (Mareschal,
French, & Quinn, 2000). When the autoencoder Figure 13.5 Gaussian probability distributions
was trained on either cat or dog images and generated from the means and standard devia-
then tested with novel cat versus dog images, it tions of the normalized nose width feature of
reproduced in the form of network error what cats and dogs.
262 INDUCTION

be viewed as novel. In other words, infants form different from categories of nonhuman ani-
a category representation for cats that excludes mals. Given the perceptual differences between
dogs, and a category representation for dogs humans and nonhuman animals (i.e., humans
that includes cats, and these representations wear clothes, stand upright, and have arms) and
are predictable from the on-line learning of the given the abilities of young infants to separate
statistical structure of the images. The compu- various nonhuman animal species into differ-
tational account of the cat–dog categorization ent categories, the expectation was that infants
asymmetry is thus consistent with the null would represent humans as distinct from cat-
effect of the home pet assessment in suggest- egories of nonhuman animals. To determine
ing that infants are learning their category whether this was the case, 3- to 4-month-olds
representation for nonhuman animals based were presented with a dozen photographic
on within-task learning (i.e., the information images of clothed humans (males and females)
presented during laboratory familiarization in standing, walking, and running poses, and
procedures). then preference tested with a novel human
paired with a horse or cat image (Quinn &
Eimas, 1998). Counter to expectation, the
A REPRESENTATION FOR HUMANS infants generalized their familiarization to the
novel humans, cats, and horses; they did not
An Inclusive Category
exhibit novel category preferences for the cats or
Given that infants in the studies just reviewed horses. In addition, a control experiment assess-
showed evidence of categorizing classes of ing a priori preference showed that infants did
nonhuman animals, the issue arose as to how not have a spontaneous preference for looking at
infants would categorize humans. The general humans over cats or horses. This latter outcome
question of how humans are conceptualized means that the null results in the categorization
among other animals has met with different experiment could not be explained by a spon-
answers in the cognitive literature. For exam- taneous preference for humans interfering with
ple, Carey (1985) has proposed that humans novel category preferences for cats or horses.
are the prototype for other animals, whereas In addition, adult observers did not judge the
Medin and Waxman (2007) have argued that exemplars of the human category to be more
humans are represented as having a dual status variable than the exemplars of the horse or cat
inclusive of a general representation in which categories, thereby weakening potential expla-
humans are represented as being like other nations based on inclusion relations.
animals and a more specific representation in The next step was to investigate further how
which humans are represented as being distinct infants represent humans by familiarizing with
from other animals. In addition, there has been human stimuli and preference testing with addi-
discussion of whether infants represent humans tional contrast categories. This further testing
as intentional agents that are not constrained was necessary because the null results of the ini-
by physical principles (Kuhlmeier, Bloom, & tial investigation (i.e., the generalization to cat
Wynn, 2004), or as solid, material objects (Saxe, and horse exemplars) left open the question of
Tzelnic, & Carey, 2005). There has also been the whether infants were categorizing humans at all
suggestion that infants represent the configu- or whether they were forming a broad category
ration of parts that make up the human body representation that was inclusive of nonhuman
(Gliga & Dehaene-Lambertz, 2005), although animals. The additional contrast categories con-
with debate regarding when during early devel- sisted of exemplars of fish and cars. The fish allow
opment this configural representation emerges one to determine how infants would respond to
(Slaughter & Heron, 2004). a nonmammalian animal category and the cars
What the infant studies thus far described enable one to learn how infants would react to
have not addressed is the question of whether a nonanimal category with no obvious overlap
infants categorize humans as similar to or with humans in terms of perceptual attributes.
MODEL FOR THE GROW TH OF COGNITIVE STRUCTURE 263

The findings were that infants familiarized with summary structures (i.e., prototypes), whereas
humans generalized their familiarization to the the representation for the more frequently
fish, but preferred the cars. The overall pattern experienced category would be supplemented
of outcomes indicates that infants were in fact by information about the individual exem-
forming a category representation for humans, plars. To investigate this possibility, a group of
one that was sufficiently broad so as to include 3- to 4-month-olds was presented either with
novel humans, cats, horses, and even fish, but a dozen images of humans or cats. The infants
not cars. were then administered two preference tests:
one was the standard test of categorization
An Asymmetry and an Exemplar-based
pairing a novel exemplar from the novel cat-
Representation
egory with a novel exemplar from the familiar
The next question became why there was a category (i.e., novel cat versus novel human),
difference in exclusivity in how infants rep- the other was a test probing the nature of the
resented the categories of nonhuman animals representation (i.e., novel exemplar from the
and humans. That is, the infants were forming familiar category versus familiar exemplar
a category of humans that included nonhuman from the familiar category). Th is latter test is
animals, but they were also forming category based on the following rationale: if infants are
representations for nonhuman animal spe- representing the category solely as a summary
cies that excluded exemplars from contrasting structure, then there should be a null prefer-
nonhuman animal species. What lies behind ence; however, if infants are also representing
the asymmetry? One possibility for the “over- the category in terms of individual exemplars,
shoot” in the human representation is because then they should prefer the novel exemplar.
infants have greater experience with humans The results were that infants familiarized
including parents, siblings, and caregivers with cats preferred a novel human over a novel
than they have with nonhuman animal spe- cat in the test of categorization, but did not
cies. Differential experience and knowledge prefer a novel over a familiar cat in the test of
have been used to account for why young chil- exemplar memory. In contrast, infants famil-
dren use humans as the prototype for their iarized with humans did not prefer a novel cat
projections about other animals in children’s over a novel human, but did prefer a novel over a
inductive reasoning tasks (Inagaki & Hatano, familiar human. The findings indicate first that
1999). Supporting this experiential account of the exclusivity difference in the way that infants
the asymmetry is the fi nding that children who represent humans versus nonhuman animals is
have experience raising goldfish use goldfish as actually a full-blown asymmetry. That is, infants
well as humans as a base for inductive general- form a category of humans that includes cats,
ization (Inagaki, 1990). whereas they form a category representation for
If differential experience with humans ver- cats that excludes humans. Second, there are
sus nonhuman animals affects infants’ cat- differences in the nature of the representation
egorization for these classes, then one might such that infants represent nonhuman animals
expect that the nature of the representation as a summary structure, possibly a prototype
that infants have for humans and nonhuman that encompasses an averaging of the familiar
animals will be different. In particular, fol- exemplars, whereas the human representation
lowing from the studies that have investigated is supplemented by information about the indi-
the time course of category learning in adults vidual exemplars. Of interest is that category-
(Gauthier & Tarr, 1997; Johansen & Palmeri, level recognition of other species and individual
2002; Smith & Minda, 1998) and the downward recognition of conspecifics have also been dem-
shift in recognition associated with enhanced onstrated in monkeys (Humphreys, 1974) and
experience (Tanaka, 2001), one might expect have been attributed to differential experience
infants to represent the less experienced cat- (Sugita, 2008) indicating that the effects are not
egories (i.e., nonhuman animals) in terms of human-specific.
264 INDUCTION

An Attractor Account Based on A After familiarization with humans


Differential Experience
Catn
How does one tie together the notions of dif- Humanf Human1
ferential experience, the inclusivity–exclusivity Humanf
difference, and the exemplar–prototype dis- Humanp
tinction into a coherent account of how infants Humanf Human4
categorize and represent humans versus non- Human2
Human3
human animals? The account proposed here
Humanf
maintains that infants who are presented with
Humann
images of humans and nonhuman animals in
the laboratory bring different knowledge bases
about humans and nonhuman animals into the
laboratory prior to their participation in the B After familiarization with cats
categorization task and then come to represent
different information during on-line learn- Catn
Human1 Catp
ing while being familiarized with the stimulus
images. As depicted in Figure 13.6A, infants may
Humanp
bring to the task of learning about humans a Human4
summary representation for humans along with Human2
representations of individual humans (i.e., par- Human3
ents, siblings, caregivers) into the experiment.
They then learn about the individual exemplar Humann
humans presented during familiarization. By
contrast, in Figure 13.6B, infants may not bring Figure 13.6 A schematic depiction of the men-
preexisting representations of nonhuman ani- tal space used to represent humans and cats after
familiarization with humans (A) or cats (B). The
mals to the task of learning about nonhuman
numbers correspond to individual exemplars of
animals and form only a summary represen-
humans represented before the familiarization
tation of the nonhuman animals during the trials. The letter p corresponds with a summary
course of familiarization with them. As a conse- (prototype) representation formed either dur-
quence of these differences in prior knowledge ing familiarization (in the case of cats) or before
base and within-task learning, infants end up familiarization (in the case of humans). The letter
with an expansive representation for humans, f corresponds with individual exemplars repre-
which is broadly accepting of stimuli that have sented during the familiarization trials, and the
attributes in common with humans (e.g., a head letter n corresponds with novel individual exem-
attached to a torso with skeletal appendages). plars presented during the preference test trials.
In this way, the human representation comes
to act as an attractor or perceptual magnet for
nonhuman animals. By contrast, the individual was shown capable of reproducing the cat–dog
representations for nonhuman animal species asymmetry was not able to simulate the human–
are tightly constructed around prototype struc- nonhuman animal asymmetry. In particular,
tures, do not have attractor properties, and thus when the network was trained on either horses
come to exclude humans. or humans, and then tested on novel horses and
Evidence from computational simulations novel humans, the network produced consis-
is consistent with the account of the human– tently more error for the images from the novel
nonhuman animal categorization asymmetry categories, irrespective of the trained category.
that is based on prior knowledge about humans However, when a long-term memory compo-
(Mermillod, French, Quinn, & Mareschal, nent that received prior training on humans was
2004). The same connectionist autoencoder that added and coupled with the short-term memory
MODEL FOR THE GROW TH OF COGNITIVE STRUCTURE 265

component for learning about the images pre- such expertise comes to structure how children
sented during familiarization, the human– come to conceptualize the biological world.
nonhuman animal asymmetry was reproduced.
That is, the “dual network” architecture, when
What Perceptual Information Do Young
trained on humans, produced equivalent error
Infants Use to Categorize Humans?
for novel humans and novel horses; however,
when trained on horses, the network produced While differential experience may be necessary
small error for novel horses and large error for to account for the human–nonhuman animal
novel humans. The network simulations provide categorization asymmetry, it may not be suf-
additional evidence that the human–nonhuman ficient. This is because the human representa-
animal asymmetry reflects the different knowl- tion included nonhuman animals, but excluded
edge base that infants have for humans versus cars, even though neither contrast category was
nonhuman animals. likely to be experienced much by infants in the
The finding that infants include nonhuman first 3 to 4 months of life. This aspect of the
animals in their representation for humans results points to a role for perceptual informa-
is consistent with work of Pauen (2000) who tion shared by humans and nonhuman animals,
reported that 5-month-old infants included but not by cars, without specifying what that
different mammals in their representation for perceptual information is.
humans in a habituation–dishabituation cat- On the one hand, the evidence described ear-
egorization task. The human–nonhuman ani- lier indicated that infants represent nonhuman
mal asymmetry in infant categorization also animals on a featural basis (Quinn & Eimas,
appears to foreshadow the human–nonhuman 1996; Spencer et al., 1997). On the other hand, the
animal asymmetry in child induction that was expertise hypothesis predicts that infants would
reported by Carey (1985) and subsequently represent humans on a holistic basis (Gauthier &
investigated by others (Atran et al., 2001). The Tarr, 2002). To evaluate the stimulus information
asymmetry was initially interpreted by Carey in that was the basis for the human–nonhuman ani-
terms of young children’s failure to distinguish mal categorization asymmetry, 3- to 4-month-
naive psychology from naive biology, although olds were presented with the category contrast of
other investigators have more recently sug- cats versus humans in experimental conditions
gested an important role for differential expo- in which the whole stimulus, just the head (with
sure and expertise (Inagaki, 1990; Ross, Medin, body information occluded) or just the body
Coley, & Atran, 2003), which is in keeping with (with head information occluded), was avail-
the framework proposed here. As described by able for processing from each image during both
Inagaki and Hatano (2006), “young children familiarization and preference test (Quinn, 2004).
draw analogically on their knowledge about The major finding was that a category representa-
humans when attributing properties to less tion for humans that included cats and a category
familiar living entities . . . Young children do representation for cats that excluded humans was
this because they possess fairly rich knowledge observed only in the whole stimulus condition.
about humans compared with their knowl- This result indicates that the human–nonhuman
edge about other animals . . .” (pp. 177–181). The animal asymmetry is based on holistic process-
results reported here suggest that the seeds of ing of the overall structure of the stimulus. That
the human-based inference or person anal- holistic information shared by humans and non-
ogy system of reasoning observed in children human animals is likely to consist of the head, a
may be planted very early in development. body torso, and skeletal appendages.
Here then may be an example of how differ- A recent study has shown further that
ential perceptual experience that infants have a representation for humans that includes
with humans versus nonhuman animals leads nonhuman animals is observed only when the
infants to become more expert in representing human images presented during familiariza-
humans with the eventual consequence that tion are in an upright orientation (Quinn, Lee,
266 INDUCTION

Pascalis, & Slater, 2007). When these data are trials of a laboratory categorization task.
considered in conjunction with the Quinn Behavioral and computational analyses sup-
(2004) findings and the observation that inver- ported this assertion. It was also argued that
sion disrupts configural processing (Freire, infants categorize humans based at least in part
Lee, & Symons, 2000), the suggestion is that on information that infants had acquired about
the holistic information that is the basis for the humans prior to their arrival at the laboratory.
incorporation of nonhuman animals into the In the present section, evidence is offered to
human representation has a configural aspect. buttress this latter claim. The evidence comes
That is, the head, body, and skeletal appendages from how infants process particular attributes
may need to be in a particular arrangement in of humans, namely, the gender and race of their
order for the attractor effect to occur. Although faces. In the initial study, 3- to 4-month-olds
the precise nature of the configural arrange- were presented with photographic images of
ment of head, body, and skeletal appendages eight male or female faces and then preference
is difficult to specify based on a single set of tested with a novel male face and a novel female
inversion results, it may be the case that skeletal face (Quinn, Yahr, Kuhn, Slater, & Pascalis,
appendages attached to the head rather than the 2002). The results were asymmetrical: infants
body would violate the arrangement (Slaughter familiarized with male faces preferred novel
& Heron, 2004), although further studies using female faces, however, infants familiarized with
a “feature scrambling” methodology would be female faces did not prefer novel male faces over
needed to confirm this suggestion. novel female faces. Notably, the same asymme-
The idea that the human versus nonhuman try was previously reported by Leinbach and
animal categorization asymmetry in infants Fagot (1993) who used a serial habituation–
is rooted in both the frequency and similarity dishabituation procedure and a different set of
structure of one’s experience with various object face stimuli with 5- to 12-month-olds. That the
classes may have a parallel with an occurrence asymmetry was observed in two different labs
observed in the word learning literature. In par- with different stimuli and under different pro-
ticular, increased experience with a particular cedural variants suggests that the phenomenon
class of objects leads to a tendency observed in is robust (see also Strauss, Newell, & Best, 2003,
child word learners to extend the label associated for an additional report of female face prefer-
with that class to less familiar, similar classes of ence in 5- to 8-month-olds).
objects, although not to less familiar, dissimilar The question now became how to interpret
classes of objects (Clark, 1973). Moreover, in a the asymmetry. The form of the asymmetry is
connectionist simulation designed to capture suggestive of an a priori preference. That is, if
this behavior, a model that was trained with infants prefer female over male faces, then such
dog patterns appearing more frequently than a preference would have facilitated a novel cat-
other mammals, extended the label dog to goats egory preference for female faces after famil-
and even robins, but not to oak trees (Rogers & iarization with male faces, but interfered with
McClelland, 2004). The correspondence between a novel category preference for male faces after
behavior and computational simulation observed familiarization with female faces. To inves-
in both infant categorization and child lexical tigate the possibility of an a priori preference
acquisition suggests that a common learning pro- for female over male faces, 3- to 4-month-olds
cess operating on the regularities of a structured were administered a spontaneous preference
environment may underlie both phenomena. test that consisted of male–female face pairings
presented without a familiarization period. The
On-Line Learning or Preexisting
infants looked more at the female faces.
Representations?
It now became important to determine what
Earlier in the chapter, it was argued that infants perceptual or cognitive factors might contribute
categorize nonhuman animals based on learn- to the heightened visual attention to the female
ing taking place during the familiarization faces on the part of the infants. One possibility
MODEL FOR THE GROW TH OF COGNITIVE STRUCTURE 267

is that the female faces were marked by longer presented with the upright faces without hair,
hair than the male faces; however, when the and 7 of the 8 displayed a preference for the male
spontaneous preference test was repeated with faces (see also Quinn et al., 2003). The findings
hair cues removed, the preference for the female indicate that how infants respond to faces in a
faces was unaffected. Another possibility is that laboratory task is influenced by what they know
the female faces were marked by higher-contrast about faces prior to arrival at the laboratory.
internal features possibly related to greater cos- More generally, how infants respond to human
metic use. Arguing against this account is the images is affected by what previously acquired
result that the female face preference dropped knowledge they possess about humans.
to chance when the spontaneous preference test The idea that previously acquired knowl-
was repeated with inverted heads without hair. edge is a determinant of how infants respond
If the female preference was driven by more sen- to information about humans in laboratory
sory power in the female faces, then it should experiments receives additional support from
have been preserved with the inversion manipu- studies examining how infants respond to
lation, given that the individual face features are race information in faces. When newborn
presented in both upright and inverted orienta- Caucasian infants, just 2 to 3 days old on aver-
tions. The inversion finding indicates that the age, are presented with Caucasian faces paired
female preference depends on the perception of with African, Asian, or Middle-Eastern faces,
faces in the upright orientation that depicts the examples of which are shown in Figure 13.7, no
canonical arrangement of internal features. consistent preferences for one or another race
With lower-level perceptual factors failing were observed (Kelly et al., 2005). However,
to provide an account of the female face prefer- when 3-month-old Caucasian infants reared
ence, one can ask whether a higher-level cogni- by Caucasian caregivers and exposed to pre-
tive factor might be determining performance. dominantly Caucasian faces were tested with
All of the infants discussed thus far from the the same face pairings as the newborns, the
Quinn et al. (2002) study had a female primary 3-month-olds displayed a reliable preference
caregiver. Given that familiarity is known to for the Caucasian (own-race) faces. In addition,
play a role in face processing by young infants when 3-month-old Chinese infants reared with
(e.g., Bartrip, Morton, & DeSchonen, 2001), it Chinese caregivers and with little or no expo-
seemed reasonable to suggest that infants with sure to other-race faces were presented with the
female primary caregivers might look more face pairings, they manifested a reliable prefer-
toward female faces than male faces because the ence for the Chinese (own-race) faces (Kelly, Liu
female faces bore a greater resemblance to the et al., 2007). The preference for own-race faces
face of the caregiver. If this was the case, then was also observed in a contrast of 3-month-old
it should be possible to reverse the spontaneous Israeli infants who preferred Caucasian faces
preference in a sample of infants raised by male and Ethiopian infants who preferred African
primary caregivers. Eight such infants were faces (Bar-Haim, Ziv, Lamy, & Hodes, 2006).

Caucasian Middle Eastern African Asian

Figure 13.7 Examples of the stimuli used in Kelly et al. (2005, 2007a).
268 INDUCTION

Bar-Haim et al. demonstrated further that nonhuman animals at a basic level of exclusivity,
Israeli-born infants of Ethiopian parentage on the basis of part information, via a summary
who had extensive exposure to both Caucasian representation, and because of learning taking
and African faces did not prefer either group of place within the experimental task. In contrast,
faces. The results indicate that differential expo- infants categorize humans at a global-level of
sure to faces from different racial groups dur- exclusivity with magnet-like properties, on the
ing the first 3 months of postnatal experience basis of holistic information, with an exemplar
is sufficient to produce a visual preference for representation, and via recruitment from a pre-
same-race faces. The findings provide another existing knowledge base.
demonstration that knowledge acquired about The various differences between how infants
humans outside the laboratory can affect how categorize humans versus nonhuman animals
infants visually attend to human visual images can be interpreted with different theoretical
presented inside the laboratory. accounts. For example, as Carey (1985) has
In addition to the spontaneous visual atten- argued about child induction, perhaps it is the
tion preferences that have been observed for case that infants have not yet separated the psy-
faces matching the gender of the primary care- chological domain of humans from the biolog-
giver and same-race faces at 3 to 4 months, ical domain of nonhuman animals. Another
there also appears to be superior recognition way to think about the differences is that they
memory. Specifically, 3- to 4-month-olds reared reflect an expert–novice distinction. In support
by female primary caregivers presented with of this conjecture, two of the differences in how
a series of female faces, preferred a novel over infants respond to nonhuman animals versus
familiar female face; however, when presented humans are consistent with behavioral markers
with a series of male faces, there was no differ- of expertise that have been reported for adults.
ential preference for a novel over familiar male First, consistent with the findings that novices
face (Quinn et al., 2002). In addition, although identify objects at the basic level (Murphy &
3-month-old Caucasian infants exposed pre- Smith, 1982; Rosch, Mervis, Gray, Johnson, &
dominantly to Caucasian faces and 3-month- Boyes-Braem, 1976), infants categorized non-
old Chinese infants exposed predominantly to human animals at the basic level. In addition, in
Chinese faces performed as well on a recogni- accord with the results that expertise training
tion memory task involving either own- or in adults shifts the entry level at which recog-
other-race faces, 6- and 9-month-old infants nition occurs to the subordinate level (Tanaka,
demonstrated superior recognition memory 2001; Tanaka, Curran, & Sheinberg, 2005;
for own-race faces (Kelly, Quinn, et al., 2007b; Tanaka & Taylor, 1991), infants represented
Kelly et al., in press). These findings indicate humans at the level of individual exemplars.
that differential experience within the cat- Second, in concert with the data showing that
egory of humans occurring outside the labo- experts tend to encode information about a
ratory can produce processing differences on stimulus across a wide spatial extent inclusive
laboratory tasks that measure abilities which go of the entire stimulus and are less able to attend
beyond spontaneous preference (i.e., exemplar selectively to individual parts (Gauthier & Tarr,
memory). 2002), infants represented humans based on
information about their configural structure,
but represented nonhuman animals based on
CATEGORIZATION OF HUMANS VERSUS
part information.
NONHUMAN ANIMALS BY INFANTS: AN
An additional characteristic that has been
EXPERT– NOVICE DISTINCTION
associated with the acquisition of expertise in
The findings reviewed in the previous sec- adults also appears to manifest itself in terms
tions of the chapter have compared how young of how infants process information about
infants categorize humans versus nonhuman humans. Specifically, even within domains of
animals. The data suggest that infants categorize expertise, experience can affect how exemplars
MODEL FOR THE GROW TH OF COGNITIVE STRUCTURE 269

are processed (Bukach et al., 2006). Within the category and its attractor properties. Moreover,
domain of faces, for example, adults have been this trend toward increased distinctiveness and
shown to remember faces from their own race commonality observed in the infant representa-
better than faces from other races (Malpass & tion for humans has also been observed in stud-
Kravitz, 1969). Likewise, within the category ies of acquired expertise in adults. For example,
of humans, infants reared by female caregivers Murphy and Wright (1984), in a comparison
have demonstrated superior recognition mem- of novices and experts on child psychopathol-
ory for female relative to male faces, and infants ogy, found that experts were more likely than
exposed predominantly to individuals from a novices to list both distinctive and common
particular race have displayed superior recogni- features of disorders. Thus, not only are experts
tion memory for same-race faces. able to recognize instances from their domain at
The present results showing that infants more specific levels than novices, they are also
respond to humans versus nonhuman animals better able to recognize commonalities across
at different levels of specificity is also consistent a domain. Notably, the dual trends toward
with evidence from the anthropology literature both differentiation and generalization that
showing that different cultures differ in the level occur with increased experience have also been
of specificity at which they recognize objects reported in the trajectory of learning observed
depending on the amount of experience they in connectionist networks operating on input
have with those objects (Malt, 1995). For exam- where one class is presented more frequently
ple, Dougherty (1978) reported that Tzetlal than others (Rogers & McClelland, 2004). An
Mayan children reared in a nonindustrialized important facet of the simulation work is that
culture were more likely to name plants at a it links together the differentiation and gener-
subordinate category level, whereas American alization behavior in a common framework in
children reared in Berkeley, California were which the representational space devoted to the
more likely to name the plants at a basic cat- more experienced class becomes larger than
egory level. Just as expertise effects can arise that allocated to less experienced classes.
within a culture based on differential experi- The generalization aspect of expertise may
ence with different classes, it can also arise as be especially relevant for cognitive development
a consequence of cultural differences in experi- and the structuring of domains of knowledge.
ence with various categories. For example, for children to develop a domain
There is yet another parallel that may be of biological knowledge, they will need to repre-
drawn between what is observed with infants’ sent a broad category of animals that includes
representation of humans versus nonhuman both humans and nonhuman animals. Despite
animals and what has been reported in the adult the perceptual differences between humans and
expertise literature. Concurrently with recog- nonhuman animals, infants display an ability
nizing humans at a more specific level (as indi- to generalize from humans to nonhuman ani-
vidual exemplars) than nonhuman animals (as mals based on their underlying commonalities.
members of a basic-level category), infants were Thus, in perhaps the same sense in which phys-
also able to represent humans at a global level ics experts look past superficial similarities and
that included nonhuman animals. As described group physics problems based on nonobvious
earlier, these two effects that take infants’ rep- resemblances (Chi, Feltovich, & Glaser, 1981),
resentation in two different directions, toward infants may develop a category representation
increased specificity and generality, may be for animals that includes both humans and
related. Specifically, the addition of individual nonhuman animals based on abstract structural
exemplars to a summary structure that comes information about overall biological form (e.g.,
with increased experience is what serves to a head attached to a body with skeletal append-
expand the range of variation of the attributes ages). By this account, the generalization from
that are represented for the category, thereby humans to nonhuman animals may represent
giving rise to the increased inclusivity of the an important component in the construction
270 INDUCTION

of a broad concept of animal. And in this way, In T. E. Moore (Ed.), Cognitive development
the acquisition of expertise may represent an and the acquisition of language (pp. 65–110).
important vehicle for the growth of category New York: Academic Press.
structure during early cognitive development. Cohen, L. B. & Cashon, C. H. (2001). Do 7-month-
old infants process independent features
or facial configurations? Infant and Child
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS Development, 10, 83–92.
Dougherty, J. W. D. (1978). Salience and relativ-
Preparation of this chapter was supported by ity in classification. American Ethnologist, 5,
Grants HD-42451 and HD-46526 from the 66–80.
National Institute of Child Health and Human Dueker, G., & Needham, A. (2005). Infants’ object
Development. The author thanks Scott P. Johnson category formation and use: Real world context
for inviting the contribution, and the partici- effects on category use in object processing.
pants in the NYU-BUG workshop for comments Visual Cognition, 12, 1177–1198.
that helped to structure the major themes of the Eimas, P. D., & Quinn, P. C. (1994). Studies on the
chapter. formation of perceptually based basic-level cat-
egories in young infants. Child Development,
REFERENCES 65, 903–917.
Freire, A., Lee, K., & Symons, L. A. (2000). The
Atran, S., Medin, D. L., Lynch, E., Vapnarsky, V., face-inversion effect as a deficit in the encod-
Ucan Ek’, E., & Sousa, P. (2001). Folkbiology ing of configural information: Direct evidence.
doesn’t come from folkpsychology: Evidence Perception, 29, 159–170.
from Yukatec Maya in cross-cultural perspec- Gauthier, I., & Tarr, M. J. (1997). Becoming a
tive. Journal of Cognition and Culture, 1, 4–42. “Greeble” expert: Exploring mechanisms
Banks, M. S., & Salapatek, P. (1981). Infant pattern for face recognition. Vision Research, 37,
vision: A new approach based on the contrast 1673–1682.
sensitivity function. Journal of Experimental Gauthier, I., & Tarr, M. J. (2002). Unraveling
Child Psychology, 31, 1–45. mechanisms for expert object recognition:
Bar-Haim, Y., Ziv, T., Lamy, D., & Hodes, R. M. Bridging brain activity and behavior. Journal
(2006). Nature and nurture in own-race face of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception
processing. Psychological Science, 17, 159–163. and Performance, 28, 431–446.
Bartrip, J., Morton, J., & De Schonen, S. (2001). Gelman, S. A. (2003). The essential child: Origins
Responses to mother’s face in 3-week to of essentialism in everyday thought. Oxford:
5-month old infants. British Journal of Oxford University Press.
Developmental Psychology, 19, 219–232. Gliga, T., & Dehaene-Lambertz, G. (2005).
Bauer, P. J., Dow, G. A., & Hertsgaard, L. A. (1995). Structural encoding of body and face in
Effects of prototypicality on categorization human infants and adults. Journal of Cognitive
in 1- to 2-year-olds: Getting down to basic. Neuroscience, 17, 1328–1340.
Cognitive Development, 10, 43–68. Hampton, J. A. (1995). Testing the prototype
Bruner, J. S., Goodnow, J. J., & Austin, G. A. (1956). theory of concepts. Journal of Memory and
A study of thinking. New York: Wiley. Language, 34, 686–708.
Bukach, C. M., Gauthier, I., & Tarr, M. J. (2006). Hampton, J. A., Estes, Z., & Simmons, S. (2007).
Beyond faces and modularity: The power of Metamorphosis: Essence, appearance, and
an expertise framework. Trends in Cognitive behavior in the categorization of natural kinds.
Sciences, 10, 159–166. Memory & Cognition, 35, 1785–1800.
Carey, S. (1985). Conceptual change in childhood. Humphreys, N. K. (1974). Species and individuals
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. in the perceptual world of monkeys. Perception,
Chi, M. T., Feltovich, P. J., & Glaser, R. (1981). 3, 105–114.
Categorization and representation of physics Inagaki, K. (1990). The effects of raising animals
problems by experts and novices. Cognitive on biological knowledge. British Journal of
Science, 5, 121–152. Developmental Psychology, 8, 119–129.
Clark, E. V. (1973) What’s in a word? On the child’s Inagaki, K., & Hatano, G. (1999). Chidren’s
acquisition of semantics in his first language. understanding of mind–body relationships.
MODEL FOR THE GROW TH OF COGNITIVE STRUCTURE 271

In M. Siegal & C. Peterson (Eds.), Children’s M. G. Shafto & P. Langley (Eds.), Proceedings of
understanding of biology and health (pp. 23–44). 19th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Society (pp. 484–489). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Inagaki, K., & Hatano, G. (2006). Young chil- Mareschal, D., French, R. M., & Quinn, P. C. (2000).
dren’s conception of the biological world. A connectionist account of asymmetric cate-
Current Directions in Psychological Science, 15, gory learning in early infancy. Developmental
177–181. Psychology, 36, 635–645.
Johnson, M. H., & Morton, J. (1991) Biology and Mareschal, D., & Quinn, P. C. (2001).
cognitive development: The case of face recogni- Categorization in infancy. Trends in Cognitive
tion. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. Sciences, 5, 443–450.
Johansen, M. K., & Palmeri, T. J. (2002). Are there Medin, D. L. & Waxman, S. R. (2007). Interpreting
representational shifts during category learn- asymmetries of projection in children’s induc-
ing? Cognitive Psychology, 45, 482–553. tive reasoning. In A. Feeney & E. Heit (Eds.),
Jones, S. S., & Smith, L. B. (1993). The place of Inductive reasoning (pp. 55–80). New York:
perception in children’s concepts. Cognitive Cambridge University Press.
Development, 8, 113–139. Mermillod, M., French, R. M., Quinn, P. C., &
Keil, F. C. (1989). Concepts, kinds, and cognitive Mareschal, D. (2004). The importance of
development. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. long-term memory in infant perceptual cate-
Kelly, D. J., Liu, S., Ge, L., Quinn, P. C., Slater, A. gorization. In R. Alterman & D. Kirsh (Eds.),
M., Lee, K., et al. (2007). Cross-race preferences Proceedings of the 25th Annual Conference of
for same-race faces extend beyond the African the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 804–809).
versus Caucasian contrast in 3-month-old Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
infants. Infancy, 11, 87–95. Mermillod, M., French R. M., Smeets, H., &
Kelly, D. J., Liu, S., Lee, K., Quinn, P. C., Pascalis, Spencer, J. (2005). A neural network investiga-
O., Slater, A. M., et al. (in press). Development tion of the head preference: problems explain-
of the other-race effect in infancy: Evidence ing empirical results by bottom-up processes
towards universality? Journal of Experimental alone. In A. Cangelosi, G. Bugmann, & R.
Child Psychology. Borisyuk (Eds.), Modeling Language, Cognition
Kelly, D. J., Quinn, P. C., Slater, A., Lee, K., Ge, L., & Action: Proceedings of the Ninth Neural
& Pascalis, O. (2007b). The other-race effect Computation and Psychology Workshop (Vol.
develops during infancy: Evidence of per- 16, pp. 361–366). Singapore: World Scientific.
ceptual narrowing. Psychological Science, 18, Murphy, G. L., & Smith, E. E. (1982). Basic level
1084–1089. superiority in picture categorization. Journal of
Kelly, D. J., Quinn, P. C., Slater, A. M., Lee, K., Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 21, 1–20.
Gibson, A., Smith, M., et al. (2005). Th ree- Murphy, G. L., & Wright, J. C. (1984). Changes in
month-olds, but not newborns, prefer own- conceptual structure with expertise: Differences
race faces. Developmental Science, 8, F31–F36. between real-world experts and novices.
Kuhlmeier, V. A., Bloom, P., & Wynn, K. (2004). Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning,
Do 5-month-old infants see humans as mate- Memory, and Cognition, 10, 144–155.
rial objects? Cognition, 94, 95–103. Nelson, C. A. (1994). Neural correlates of recog-
Leinbach, M. D., & Fagot, B. I. (1993). Categorical nition memory in the first postnatal year of
habituation to male and female faces: Gender life. In G. Dawson & K. Fischer (Eds.), Human
schematic processing in infancy. Infant behavior and the developing brain (pp. 269–
Behavior & Development, 16, 317–332. 313). New York: Guilford Press.
Malpass, R. S., & Kravitz, J. (1969). Recognition Oakes, L. M., & Ribar, R. J. (2005). A comparison
for faces of own and other race. Journal of of infants’ categorization in paired and succes-
Personality and Social Psychology, 13, 330–334. sive familiarization tasks. Infancy, 7, 85–98.
Malt, B. (1995). Category coherence in cross cul- Palmeri, T. J.,Wong, A., & Gauthier, I. (2004).
tural perspective. Cognitive Psychology, 29, Computational approaches to the development
85–148. of perceptual expertise. Trends in Cognitive
Mareschal, D., & French, R. M. (1997). A Sciences, 8, 378–386.
connectionist account of interference effects Pauen, S. (2000). Early differentiation
in early infant memory and categorization. In within the animate domain: Are humans
272 INDUCTION

something special? Journal of Experimental bodies represented differently from other ani-
Child Psychology, 75, 134–151. mate and inanimate objects? Visual Cognition,
Pauen, S. (2002). Evidence for knowledge-based 11, 523–550.
category discrimination in infancy. Child Reed, C. L., Stone, V. E., & McGoldrick, J. E. (2005).
Development, 73, 1016–1033. Not just posturing: Configural processing of
Quinn, P. C. (2004). Is the asymmetry in young the human body. In W. Prinz, M. Shiff rar,
infants’ categorization of humans versus non- I. Thornton, G. Knoblich, & M. Grosjean (eds.),
human animals based on head, body, or global The human body: From the inside out (pp. 229–
Gestalt Information? Psychonomic Bulletin & 258). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
Review, 11, 92–97. Reynolds, G. D., & Richards, J. E. (2005).
Quinn, P. C., Doran, M. M., Reiss, J. E., & Familiarization, attention, and recogni-
Hoff man, J. E. (2009). Time course of visual tion memory in infancy: An ERP and corti-
attention in infant categorization of cats ver- cal source localization study. Developmental
sus dogs: Evidence for a head bias as revealed Psychology, 41, 598–615.
through eye tracking. Child Development, 80, Rogers, T. T., & McClelland, J. L. (2004). Semantic
151–161. cognition: A parallel distributed processing
Quinn, P. C., & Eimas, P. D. (1996). Perceptual cues approach. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
that permit categorical differentiation of ani- Ross, N., Medin, D. L., Coley, J. D., & Atran, S.
mal species by infants. Journal of Experimental (2003). Cultural and experiential differences
Child Psychology, 63, 189–211. in the development of folkbiological induction.
Quinn, P. C., & Eimas, P. D. (1998). Evidence for a Cognitive Development, 18, 25–47.
global categorical representation of humans by Rosch, E., Mervis, C. B., Gray, W., Johnson, D., &
young infants. Journal of Experimental Child Boyes-Braem, P. (1976). Basic objects in natural
Psychology, 69, 151–174. categories. Cognitive Psychology, 8, 382–439.
Quinn, P. C., Eimas, P. D., & Rosenkrantz, S. Saxe, R., Tzelnic, T., & Carey, S. (2006). Five-
L. (1993). Evidence for representations of month-old infants know that humans are
perceptually similar natural categories by solid, like inanimate objects. Cognition, 101,
3- and 4-month-old infants. Perception, 22, B1–B8.
463–475. Slaughter, V., & Heron, M. (2004). Origins and
Quinn, P. C., Lee, K., Pascalis, O., & Slater, A. M. early development of human body knowledge.
(2007). In support of an expert–novice differ- Monographs of the Society for Research in Child
ence in the representation of humans versus Development, 69, Serial number 276.
non-human animals by infants: Generalization Smith, J. D., & Minda, J. P. (1998). Prototypes in
from persons to cats occurs only with upright the mist: The early epochs of category learning.
whole images. Cognition, Brain, & Behavior Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning,
(Special Issue on the Development of Memory, and Cognition, 24, 1411–1436.
Categorization), 11, 679–694. Spencer, J., Quinn, P. C., Johnson, M. H., &
Quinn, P. C., Schyns, P. G., & Goldstone, R. L. Karmiloff-Smith, A. (1997). Heads you
(2006). The interplay between perceptual win, tails you lose: Evidence for young
organization and categorization in the rep- infants categorizing mammals by head and
resentation of complex visual patterns by facial attributes (Special Issue: Perceptual
young infants. Journal of Experimental Child Development). Early Development and
Psychology, 95, 117–127. Parenting, 6, 113–126.
Quinn, P. C., Westerlund, A., & Nelson, C. A. Strauss, M. S., Newell, L. C., & Best, C. A. (April,
(2006). Neural markers of categorization in 2003). The perception and recognition of faces
6-month-old infants. Psychological Science, 17, by infants, preschoolers, and individuals
59–66. with autism. In C. A. Nelson (Organizer),
Quinn, P. C., Yahr, J., Kuhn, A., Slater, A. M., & The development of facial expertise.
Pascalis, O. (2002). Representation of the gen- Symposium conducted at the meeting of the
der of human faces by infants: A preference for Society for Research in Child Development,
female. Perception, 31, 1109–1121. Tampa, FL.
Reed, C. L., McGoldrick, J. E., Shackelford, Sugita, Y. (2008). Face perception in monkeys
R., & Fidopiastis, C. (2004). Are human reared with no exposure to faces. Proceedings
MODEL FOR THE GROW TH OF COGNITIVE STRUCTURE 273

of the National Academy of Sciences, 105, eye of the beholder? Cognitive Psychology, 23,
394–398. 457–482.
Tanaka, J. W. (2001). The entry point of face recog- Thelen, E., & Smith, L. B. (1994). A dynamic sys-
nition: Evidence for face expertise. Journal of tems approach to the development of cognition
Experimental Psychology: General, 130, 534–543. and action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Tanaka, J. W., Curran, T., & Sheinberg, D. L. Tucker, D. M. (1993). Spatial sampling of
(2005). The training and transfer of real-world head electrical fields: The geodesic sensor
perceptual expertise. Psychological Science, 16, net. Electroencephalography and Clinical
145–151. Neurophysiology, 87, 154–163.
Tanaka, J. W., & Gauthier, I. (1997). Expertise in Xu, F. (1997). From Lot’s wife to a pillar of salt:
object and face recognition. In R. L. Goldstone, Evidence that physical object is a sortal con-
P. G. Schyns, & D. L. Medin (Eds.), The psy- cept. Mind & Language, 12, 365–392.
chology of learning and motivation (Vol. 36, pp. Younger, B. A., & Fearing, D. D. (1999). Parsing
83–125). San Diego: Academic Press. items into separate categories: Developmental
Tanaka, J. W., & Taylor, M. (1991). Object cate- change in infant categorization. Child
gories and expertise: Is the basic level in the Development, 70, 291–303.
CHAP TER 14
Similarity, Induction, Naming, and
Categorization: A Bottom-up Approach

Vladimir M. Sloutsky

People are remarkably smart: they know of things, including, any part of the object, its
language, possess complex skills, and function color, texture, manner of motion, or the speak-
in a complex dynamic environment. However, er’s attitude toward the situation. Again, despite
they do not exhibit evidence of this knowledge the fact that the referential situation appears to
at birth and one of the central and most inter- be severely under constrained, even very young
esting issues in the study of human cognition is children somehow manage to determine that
the question of how people acquire this knowl- the word (at least if it is a noun) refers to the
edge in the course of development. One possi- object (see Woodward & Markman, 1998, for a
bility is that sensory and cognitive systems have review).
the capacity to extract regularities from struc- It has been argued that these examples indi-
tured input. However, this possibility has been cate that infants and young children perform
frequently criticized as an untenable candidate these tasks with some expectations about the
for a complete story. In particular, it has been language and the world (e.g., they may expect
often argued that input data are severely under- words to refer to objects). This hypothesis raises
determined: the same data are compatible with a number of important questions. Where does
multiple possibilities. Consider a visual occlu- this knowledge come from? How is this knowl-
sion phenomenon presented in Figure 14.1: the edge represented? And how do infants and
same event presented in Figure 14.1A is com- young children deploy this knowledge? If the
patible with events presented in Figures 14.1B, input is under constrained, then the “cognitive”
C, D, and E, or an infinite number of other pos- constraints imposed on the input cannot be
sibilities, and there is not enough information acquired from the input, and hence these con-
in the input to decide among these possibilities. straints have to be a priori. Therefore, accord-
However, under many conditions, even very ing to this position, some aspects of structured
early in development, people are more likely to knowledge (e.g., knowledge of syntax, semantics,
expect the situation presented in Figure 14.1B or visual organization) are a priori and the task
than situations presented in Figure 14.1C and of learning is to recognize these structures in
14.1D (Kellman & Spelke, 1983; Spelke, 1990, the input. To reflect the fact that the constraints
but see Johnson, 2003). are a precondition rather than a consequence of
Similarly, when adults label objects for young learning, I will refer to this position as a “top-
children (e.g., “Look, look, a dax!”), a mere co- down approach.” “Top-down” here refers to the
occurrence of an object and a word is not suffi- origins of knowledge and many constraints that
cient for determining that the word refers to the emerge in the bottom-up manner (in the course
object. In fact, the word could refer to a variety of learning) do not have “top-down” origins.

274
SIMILARITY, INDUCTION, NAMING, AND CATEGORIZATION 275

A B C

D E

Figure 14.1 An example of visual occlusion, B–E. Possible states of the world compatible with A.

However, there is a growing body of evidence conditions may result in a similar or identical
indicating that input is substantially richer than output. Similarly, if cognitive development is a
the above examples imply and that human learn- top-down process, then acquisition of syntax,
ing is powerful enough to extract regularities the development of perception, and the develop-
from structured, albeit somewhat noisy, input. ment of generalization (such as word leaning or
Of course, if this is the case, then people may not categorization) are constrained by knowledge,
need a priori constraints. To reflect the fact that beliefs, or biases that are independent of input.
regularities are extracted from data (rather than As a result, radically different input conditions
imposed on the data), I will refer to this position should result in similar linguistic and percep-
as a “bottom-up” approach. The primary focus tual development outcomes.
of this chapter is whether learning and cognitive Alternatively, we say that the process is bot-
development are constrained by a priori knowl- tom-up when an outcome of the process stems
edge (and are thus top-down processes) or by the from an interaction of simpler processes, none of
nature of the input and by learning mechanisms which alone can determine the outcome. In this
(and are thus bottom-up processes). case, the regularity in the outcome emerges from
regularities in the input. For example, although
it cannot be known in advance how many light
TOP-DOWN VERSUS BOTTOM - UP LEARNING
bulbs will be produced in the United States in a
We say that a process is top-down when an out- given year, the production (as well as the price)
come of a process is determined by a higher- is a function of market conditions (e.g., the cost
order structure. For example, the number of light of energy, the amount of construction activity,
bulbs produced in North Korea in a given year etc.), and it is likely that similar market condi-
(as well as their price) is completely determined tions will result in somewhat similar production
by a government plan. The plan is not influenced outcomes. Similarly, acquisition of syntax, the
by market conditions, but is designed to affect development of perception, and the develop-
these conditions. Therefore, the plan, rather than ment of generalization is a joint function of the
the market conditions, prescribes the manufac- regular input and the ability of the organism to
turers’ output, and radically different market extract and exploit these regularities.
276 INDUCTION

The distinction between top-down and bot-


TOP-DOWN APPROACHES TO
tom-up approaches to learning has been recur-
GENERALIZATION
ring under different names. For example, in the
domain of language learning, there has been a According to this position, even at the outset of
distinction between inductive and deductive development, infants and young children have
approaches to language learning (e.g., Wexler a repertoire of “smart” conceptual assumptions
& Culicover, 1980; Xu & Tenenbaum, 2007). about the language and the world (R. Gelman,
According to the former view, learners extract 1990; Gelman & Markman, 1987; Gelman &
regularities from linguistic input. In contrast, Wellman, 1991; Keil, 1989; Mandler, 1997, 2004;
according to the latter view, learners entertain Soja, Carey, & Spelke, 1991; Wellman & Gelman,
a fi xed set of a priori hypotheses, and the role of 1992). Although conceptual knowledge plays a
input is to eliminate the inappropriate hypoth- prominent role in top-down approaches, it is hard
eses, thus enabling the learner to settle on the to pin down what exactly the top-down theorists
correct hypothesis. mean by “conceptual knowledge” is. One possi-
In this chapter, I focus on a different bility is that conceptual knowledge is knowledge
domain—the ability to extend knowledge from that cannot be observed directly, but has to be
known to novel. People deploy this ability every inferred. Therefore, knowledge that birds have
time they (1) extend a known word to a novel wings is perceptual, whereas knowledge that
entity (i.e., in naming or label extension), (2) birds and fish share many biological properties is
treat a novel entity as a member of a familiar conceptual. Another issue that remains unclear
class (i.e., categorization), and (3) extend a prop- is the origin of conceptual knowledge. Does con-
erty from a familiar entity to a novel entity (i.e., ceptual knowledge emerge as generalization over
projective induction). data? Or does it exist independently of data? And
Th is ability to extend knowledge from if the latter is the case, where does it come from?
known to novel, or inductive generalization, Although these questions remain unanswered,
and the development of this ability are inter- conceptual knowledge plays a prominent role in
esting and controversial issues in human cog- top-down theories of generalization.
nition. Some researchers propose a top-down According to some accounts (see Massey &
approach to generalization, arguing that even R. Gelman, 1988; Spelke, 1994) conceptual
early in development, conceptual knowledge knowledge constrains (or even overrides) per-
is a critical component of inductive general- ceptual input, while remaining impervious to
ization (Gelman, 2003; Gelman & Wellman, perceptual input. Conceptual effects in an induc-
1991; Keil, Smith, Simons, & Levin, 1998). Th is tive generalization task have been described as
position is commonly known as knowledge- follows. When “trying to determine whether to
based (or naïve theory) approach. Others sug- draw an inference from object A to object B, a
gest that inductive generalization may develop child would not simply calculate the similarity
in a bottom-up manner, with similarity play- between the two objects. Rather the child would
ing a critical role in early induction (Colunga determine whether A and B belong to members
& Smith, 2005; French, Mareschal, Mermillod, of the same natural kind category that encom-
& Quinn, 2004; Rogers & McClelland, 2004; passes both A and B” (Gelman & Coley, 1991,
Sloutsky, 2003; Sloutsky & Fisher, 2004a). While p. 185). Therefore, according to this account
both positions agree that bottom-up processes, of generalization, abstract (and not directly
such as similarity computation, play a role (e.g., perceptible) category information is of greater
Keil et al.,1998; Keil, 2003), there is less agree- importance than appearance information.
ment about the role and origins of top-down Furthermore, identification of an abstract cate-
knowledge. For example, there no agreement gory is a necessary step in inductive generaliza-
on whether these top-down constraints are tion, and therefore induction in young children
necessary for inductive generalization, when is category-based (e.g., Gelman, 1988).
these constraints come online, and where they Overall, among the putative conceptual
come from. assumptions, two are especially important for
SIMILARITY, INDUCTION, NAMING, AND CATEGORIZATION 277

inductive generalization. The category assump- presented young children with a Target item and
tion is the belief that individual entities are mem- two Test items, with one Test item looking more
bers of more general categories and that members like the Target and another Test item sharing the
of the same category share many unobserved label with the Target. Participants were also told
properties. The linguistic assumption is the belief that one Test item had a hidden property (e.g.,
that words (especially count nouns) denote cat- “This one has hollow bones”), whereas another
egories rather than individuals. When perform- Test item had a different hidden property (e.g.,
ing induction, people rely on these assumptions “This one has solid bones”), and asked to induce
to conclude that entities sharing a label belong to a hidden property to the Target. Results indicated
the same kind, and therefore share many unob- that young children tended to induce properties
servable properties. For instance, when shown a from the identically labeled, but not from the sim-
picture of a yellow fish and told that this fish needs ilarly looking item. Similar findings were reported
branchia to breathe, children are more likely to with infants. Specifically, when objects were not
generalize this property to a red fish than to a labeled, infants generalized nonobvious prop-
turtle or a couch (Gelman, 1988). Presumably, erties based on appearance similarity, whereas
children apply the two assumptions to infer that when objects were labeled participants were using
since the entities have a matching label (i.e., both labeling information (Welder & Graham, 2001).
are referred to as “a fish”), these entities belong
Challenges to the Top-Down Approach
to the same kind, and therefore they share many
important properties. There are several challenges to the idea that
early generalization is driven by top-down con-
Supporting Evidence
ceptual assumptions. Some of these challenges
There are several lines of research supporting the stem from fi ndings indicating that conceptual
idea of the linguistic and category assumptions in knowledge is not an a priori constraint, but is
infants and children. For example, in support of the rather a product of learning and development.
linguistic assumption, Markman and Hutchinson Other challenges stem from fi ndings question-
(1984) demonstrated that in an absence of a label, ing the very existence of particular conceptual
children may group things thematically (e.g., a assumptions early in development.
police car and a policeman), whereas when the Most importantly, empirical evidence does
police car was named “a dax” and children were not lend unequivocal support to the idea that
asked to select another “dax,” they selected the children’s inductive generalization is driven by
passenger car, thus grouping the cars together. a priori assumptions, such as the linguistic and
More recently, Gelman and Heyman (1999) dem- the category assumptions. In particular, several
onstrated that young children were more will- lines of research on categorization, word learn-
ing to generalize properties from one person to ing, and projective induction cast doubt on the
another when both persons were referred to by a existence of a priori assumptions in infants and
noun (i.e., “carrot-eaters”) than when both were young children (Colunga & Smith, 2005; French
referred to by a descriptive sentence (e.g., “both et al.,2004; Oakes & Madole, 2003, Rakison,
like to eat carrots”). Furthermore, infants and 2003, Smith, Jones, & Landau, 1996; Yoshida &
children may also expect words to refer to cat- Smith, 2005). For example, it has been demon-
egories, although, younger infants may hold this strated that category learning in early infancy
expectation not only for count nouns, but also for can be readily accounted for by the distribution
other speech sounds (e.g., Balaban & Waxman, of feature values within a category and across
1997; Booth & Waxman, 2002). categories (French et al.,2004). It has been also
There is also evidence supporting the idea that found that when categorizing objects or induc-
young children expect things to belong to catego- ing properties, the type of property infants focus
ries and they expect members of the same category on changes in the course of development (e.g.,
to share important properties. This evidence stems Madole, Oakes, & Cohen, 1993; Rakison, 2003).
primarily from the study of inductive generaliza- Similarly, “biases” that drive word learning have
tion. For example, Gelman and Markman (1986) been found to come on-line in the course of
278 INDUCTION

learning rather than being a priori. For example, (i.e., 3- to 5-year-old children). For example, there
Smith, and colleagues (e.g., Smith, Jones, Landau, are recent findings indicating that effects of labels
Gershkoff-Stowe, & Samuelson, 2002) examined on categorization and induction may be driven by
the developmental course of the “shape bias”— attentional factors and do not have to stem from
the tendency of toddlers to extend a novel word the linguistic assumption (Napolitano & Sloutsky,
to items that have the same shape as the originally 2004; Sloutsky & Napolitano 2003). In particular,
labeled item. These researchers hypothesized that Amanda Napolitano and I demonstrated that
the shape bias is not a prerequisite, but a conse- under many conditions, auditory input (includ-
quence of word leaning. The underlying idea is ing linguistic input) automatically captures young
that in the course of language acquisition, babies children’s attention, thus overshadowing (or
first detect that a particular shape co-occurs with attenuating processing of) corresponding visual
a particular label (e.g., “cup-shaped” objects are input. Therefore, it is possible that (due to over-
called “cups,” while “ball-shaped” objects are shadowing effects) shared labels contribute to the
called “balls”). As the corpus of evidence grows, overall similarity of compared entities (Sloutsky
they detect a more abstract regularity: similar- & Fisher, 2004a; Sloutsky & Lo, 1999), and thus to
shaped entities have the same name, and this both categorization and induction.
more abstract regularity, in turn, makes shape Furthermore, there are reasons to be skeptical
an important predictor of category membership. whether some of the findings, which are being
If this hypothesis is correct, then the shape bias used as evidence for linguistic and category
is a function of word learning experience and assumptions, do in fact constitute such evi-
it should emerge as children accumulate their dence. For example, Anna Fisher and I (Sloutsky
vocabularies. This is exactly what Smith and col- & Fisher, 2004a) reexamined young children’s
leagues found, thus presenting evidence that the performance on Gelman and Markman (1986)
“shape bias” in naming is not an a priori assump- task. Similar to the original task, we presented
tion, but is a product of learning. 4- to 5-year-olds with triads of items, with each
Additional challenges to the top-down triad consisting of a target and two test items
approach come from studies with preschoolers (these are presented in Figure 14.2B). Also, as

A 1
Predicted
0.9 Observed
0.8
*
Proportion of B-choices

0.7 *
*
0.6
0.5
0.4
0.3
0.2
0.1
0
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 Average
Picture triad

Figure 14.2 (Originally presented in Sloutsky & Fisher, 2004a). (A) Predicted and observed propor-
tions of B-choices by stimuli triads in induction task. Error bars represent standard errors of the mean.
(B) Stimuli used in Gelman and Markman (1986). Note: *Above chance; p < .05. Triad 1: Bird-Bat-
Bird. Triad 2: Coral-Plant-Coral. Triad 3: Flower-Sea Anemone-Flower. Triad 4: Snake-Worm-Snake.
Triad 5: Bug-Leaf-Bug. Triad 6: Starfish-Pinecone-Starfish. Triad 7: Squirrel-Rabbit-Squirrel. Triad 8:
Dinosaur-Rhinoceros-Dinosaur. Triad 9: Lizard-Snake-Lizard. Triad 10: Fish-Dolphin-Fish.
B

Bat Coral Plant

Bird

Bird
Coral

Sea anemone Worm


Flower Snake

Snake
Flower

Leaf Bug Starfish


Pinecome

Bug
Starfish

Rabbit Squirrel Dinosaur


Rhinoceros

Squirrel Dinosaur

Lizard
Snake Fish Dolphin

Lizard Fish

Figure 14.2 (Continued)

279
280 INDUCTION

in the original task, we named items, such that similarities, among presented entities. Because
one test item shared the label with the target, members of the same category often happen to
whereas the other appeared more similar to be more perceptually similar to each other than
the target. Finally, as in the original task, we they are to nonmembers (i.e., a yellow fish is
told participants that each of the test items had more similar to a red fish than it is to a turtle or
a particular nonobvious property and asked a couch), children are more likely to generalize
them to guess the property of the target. The properties to members of a category than to non-
entire procedure, including pictures, labels, and members. Furthermore, common labels could
properties were identical to the original study. be features directly contributing to perceptual
In addition, prior to the experiment proper, we similarity rather than denoting a common cat-
conducted a separate experiment estimating for egory (Sloutsky & Fisher, 2004a; Sloutsky &
each triad the similarity of the test items to the Lo, 1999). Proponents of this view challenge
target. the position that young children hold concep-
While replicating the overall mean reported tual assumptions, and they argue that induc-
by Gelman and Markman, we demonstrated tion with both familiar and novel categories is
that (a) children’s performance varied drasti- similarity-based. In the remainder of this sec-
cally across picture triads (which should not tion, I will consider a recently proposed model
be the case if induction was driven by a set of of generalization (SINC standing for Similarity,
assumptions), (b) appearance similarity made a Induction, Naming, and Categorization) that
sizable contribution to induction, and (c) a sim- considers categorization, induction, and nam-
ple model of similarity (the model is presented ing as variants of similarity-based generaliza-
below) very accurately predicted how children tion (see Sloutsky & Fisher, 2004a).
perform on individual triads (see Figure 14.2A
for a comparison of predicted and observed SINC Model
means). Therefore, a detailed analysis of chil-
Overview
dren’s performance does not support the con-
clusion that in the presence of shared labels, SINC assumes that young children consider lin-
children ignore appearance information. guistic labels as attributes of objects that con-
Another serious challenge to the idea that tribute to similarity among compared entities.
early generalization is constrained by a priori This assumption has been supported empirically
conceptual knowledge is that it is unclear how (Sloutsky & Lo, 1999; Sloutsky, Lo, & Fisher,
this knowledge (even if it existed) could be imple- 2001). Qualitatively, SINC suggests that linguis-
mented and deployed in real-life situations. For tic labels contribute to similarity of compared
example, in order for infants and young chil- entities and that similarity drives induction and
dren to ignore salient (yet surface-level) percep- categorization in young children. The model is
tual information in favor of nonobservable and based on the product-rule model of similarity
thus less salient conceptual information, they (Estes, 1994; Medin, 1975) that specifies simi-
should have a substantial level of control over larity among nonlabeled feature patterns. In
their attention. However, there is little evidence the product-rule model, similarity is computed
indicating that young children have sufficient using the following equation:
control of attention, enabling them to focus on
Sim(i, j) = SN–k (14.1)
less salient (yet deep) information, while ignor-
ing more salient (yet surface) information. where N denotes the total number of relevant
attributes, k denotes the number of matches,
and S (0 ≤ S ≤ 1) denotes values (weights) of a
BOTTOM- UP APPROACHES TO
mismatch. For example, suppose that one is pre-
GENERALIZATION
sented with two visual patterns (e.g., schematic
According to this view, young children general- faces A and B). Further suppose that these pat-
ize on the basis of multiple commonalities, or terns consist of four distinct features (i.e., the
SIMILARITY, INDUCTION, NAMING, AND CATEGORIZATION 281

shape of the face, eyes, and nose, and the size of as a separate term in the equation because they
ears) that the patterns share two of these features are expected to have larger attentional weight
(i.e., the shape of the face and eyes) and differ on than most visual attributes (Sloutsky & Lo,
the other two. Assuming that S = 0.5 [the value 1999). In the case that the weight of a label does
frequently derived empirically (Estes, 1994)], not differ from that of other attributes, the label
similarity between A and B would be equal to will become one of the attributes in the compu-
0.25 (i.e., 0.52). Note that similarity between tation of similarity, and Equation 14.2 becomes
entities decreases very rapidly with a decrease Equation 14.1.
in the number of mismatches, approximating Why would labels contribute to similarity?
the exponential decay function discussed else- And what might be a mechanism underlying
where (Nosofsky, 1984). For example, if the the greater weight of labels at earlier age demon-
faces shared only one of the four features, their strated in previous research (e.g., Sloutsky & Lo,
similarity would be equal to 0.125 (i.e., 0.53). On 1999)? One possibility is that labels have larger
the other hand, if the faces shared all four fea- weights because they are presented auditorily,
tures, they would be identical, and their simi- and auditory processing dominates the visual
larity would be equal to 1 (i.e., 0.50). processing in infancy and early childhood, but
According to SINC, similarity of labeled fea- this dominance decreases with age (Lewkowicz,
ture patterns could be calculated using the fol- 1988a, 1988b; Sloutsky & Napolitano, 2003).
lowing equation: Alternatively, it is possible that larger weights of
labels are grounded in a special status of sounds
1−L N −k ⎧
L = 1, if Li = L j ⎫ of human speech (Balaban & Waxman, 1997;
Sim ( i, j ) = WLabel SVis .attr ⎨ ⎬ (14.2)
⎩ = 1, otherwise ⎭
L Waxman & Markow, 1995). We discuss both
possibilities in the “Why Do Labels Contribute
Again, N denotes the total number of visual to Similarity” section.
attributes, k denotes the number of matches, Finally, SINC suggests that if the child is pre-
Svis.attr. denotes values (attentional weights) of a sented with a Target feature pattern (T) and Test
mismatch on a visual attribute, WLabel denotes feature patterns (A and B) and asked which of
values of label mismatches, and L denotes a the Test patterns is more similar to the Target,
label match. the child’s choice for one of the Test items (e.g.,
When there is a label match, L = 1 and Test B) could be predicted using a variant of the
WLabel = 1; when there is a label mismatch, Luce’s choice rule presented in the following
L = 0 and WLabel < 1. Note that S and W (their equation:
values vary between 0 and 1) denote attentional
weights of mismatches and the contribution Sim (T , B )
P (B) = (14.3)
of S and W is large when these parameters are Sim (T , B ) + Sim (T , A )
close to 0 and is small they are close to 1. This is
because the closer the value of these parameters We argue that if induction and categorization
to 1, the smaller the contribution of a mismatch in young children are indeed similarity-based,
to the detection of difference, while the closer then this model that predicts similarity judg-
the value to 0, the greater the contribution to ment in young children (e.g., Sloutsky & Lo,
the detection of difference. When two entities 1999) should be able to predict their induction.
are identical on all dimensions (i.e., there are no However, for the majority of naturalistic
mismatches), their similarity should be equal to visual stimuli patterns, it is impossible to indi-
1; otherwise, it is smaller than 1. viduate features and calculate feature overlap
Note that, according to the model, when nei- (e.g., think about photographs of two animals
ther entity is labeled (i.e., WLabel = 1), similarity and the multiplicity of perceptual features that
between the entities is determined by the num- they have). At the same time, perceptually rich
ber of overlapping visual attributes, thus con- naturalistic stimuli constitute the most interest-
forming to Equation 14.1. Labels are presented ing and informative test of the proposed model.
282 INDUCTION

Because neither N nor k presented in Equation used for predicting specific probabilities of
14.1 are determinable a priori for perceptually induction and categorization.
rich naturalistic stimuli, we made several addi- One important (and testable) consequence
tional steps to apply the model to naturalistic of this proposal is that because linguistic labels
stimuli. Denoting similarity of Test stimuli A contribute to similarity in a quantitative man-
and B to the Target as Sx and Sy, respectively, and ner rather than in a qualitative “all-or-nothing”
performing simple derivations from Equation manner, they should also make a quantitative
14.3 allow us to get equations predicting cat- contribution to induction as well. Therefore,
egorization and induction performance. First, the top-down approach and SINC make dif-
consider the case when entities are not labeled. ferent predictions about the effect of linguistic
Substituting Sim(T,B) and Sim(T,A) by Sx and Sy, labels on induction. If inductive generalization
we get the following equation: is made solely on the basis of linguistic label (as
predicted by the linguistic assumption), then
Sx Sx 1
P (B) = = = induction should be independent of appearance
S x + S y S x (1 + S y −x ) Sy (14.4)
1+ x similarity. Alternatively, SINC predicts that
S labels make a quantitative contribution to simi-
larity and thus to induction.
For the labeled entities, derivations remain
essentially the same, except for the WLabel param- Empirical Findings Generated by SINC
eter. The parameter equals to 1, if there is a label
SINC is a model implementing a theory of
match, otherwise it varies from 0 to 1, and the
inductive generalization, which can predict a
smaller the value of W, the greater the contri-
wide range of phenomena across a variety of
bution of label mismatch. Therefore, in the case
tasks. These phenomena include: (1) effects of
of labeled entities, the probability of selecting
labels on similarity early in development; (2)
the item that shares the same label (say item B
effects of phonological similarity of labels on
if it shares the label with the Target) could be
induction; (3) low-level attentional mecha-
derived as follows:
nisms underlying effects of labels on similarity
Sx Sx 1 and induction; (4) flexible (yet nondeliberate)
P (B) = = x =
S + WS
x y
S (1 + WS y −x ) WS y (14.5) adjustment of attentional weights of different
1+ x sources of information; (5) differential effects
S
of induction on recognition memory at dif-
In short, Equations 14.4 and 14.5 should pre- ferent points of development; (6) dissocia-
dict participants’ induction responses in tion between label and category information;
label and no-label conditions, respectively. In (7) integration of labeling and appearance
other words, their willingness to induce from information in the course of similarity judg-
Test B to the Target should be a function of ment and induction; and (8) interrelationships
the ratio of Sy/Sx (i.e., of similarity of A and among induction, categorization, naming, and
B to the Target) when no labels are provided, similarity.
and it should be a joint function of Sy/Sx and First, it has been demonstrated that early in
W (i.e., the attentional weight of label) when development, labels contribute to similarity of
labels are provided. Note that Equation 14.5 compared entities (Sloutsky & Fisher, 2004a;
reflects a situation when the Target and Test Sloutsky & Lo, 1999). In particular, when two
B have the same labels, whereas Test A has a entities share a label, young children tend to
different label. For the purpose of expository consider these entities as looking more alike
convenience, in the description of data and in than when the same entities are presented with-
figures, I will refer to the Test stimulus sharing out labels, and, as we explain below, these effects
the label with the Target as “Test B.” Note that stem from attentional factors, such as auditory
both W and Sy/Sx can be estimated from data, information overshadowing (or attenuating pro-
and therefore Equations 14.4 and 14.5 can be cessing) of corresponding visual information
SIMILARITY, INDUCTION, NAMING, AND CATEGORIZATION 283

(Napolitano & Sloutsky, 2004; Robinson & (Sloutsky & Spino, 2004), attention to labels or to
Sloutsky, 2004; Sloutsky & Napolitano, 2003). appearances was manipulated by varying their
Second, if labels are features contributing predictive values (when a cue is consistently
to the overall similarity, then it is possible that nonpredictive, attention to this cue decreases,
labels are perceived as subjectively continuous see Hall, 1991, for a review). After training,
variables, in which case, not only the iden- participants were presented with an induc-
tity, but also phonological similarity of labels tion task, which was repeated again 3.5 months
would contribute to the overall similarity and after training. It was found that as a result of
to induction. Therefore, the theory underly- training, young children exhibited (depending
ing SINC suggests that phonological similar- on the training condition) either appearance-
ity of labels may contribute to induction. There based or label-based induction, with either pat-
is recent evidence supporting this prediction tern being different from pretraining induction.
(Fisher & Sloutsky, 2004): Young children were Furthermore, 3.5 months after training, young
more likely to generalize a property from a test children retained these effects of training.
item to a target item if the test and target items Fift h, SINC enabled a novel prediction regard-
had a phonologically similar label (e.g., Guma ing effects of induction on recognition memory.
and Gama) than if it had a phonologically dif- Recall that according to SINC, early induction
ferent label (Guma and Fika). Furthermore, is driven by similarity, whereas according to
young children tended to extend phonologically the knowledge-based approach, even early in
similar words to visually similar entities. development induction is category-based and is
Third, according to SINC, effects of words driven by more abstract category information.
on similarity and thus on induction stem To address this issue, Anna Fisher and I devel-
from low-level attentional mechanisms rather oped the Induction-then-Recognition (ITR)
than from an understanding of the conceptual paradigm, allowing the distinction between
importance of labels. Based on this idea, it was these two possibilities (see Sloutsky & Fisher,
predicted that words, as well as other auditory 2004a, 2004b).
stimuli, may affect processing of correspond- The ability of ITR to distinguish between
ing visual information. This prediction was these possibilities is based on the following
confirmed empirically: For infants and young reasoning. Research on false-memory phe-
children, auditory information overshadows nomena showed that deep semantic process-
corresponding visual information (Napolitano ing of studied items (including grouping of
& Sloutsky, 2004; Robinson & Sloutsky, 2004; items into categories) often increases memory
Sloutsky & Napolitano, 2003). In particular, intrusions—false recognition and recall of non-
when discriminable visual and auditory stim- presented “critical lures” or items semantically
uli (including human speech) were presented associated with studied items (e.g., Koutstall &
together, discrimination of visual (but not of Schacter, 1997; Thapar & McDermott, 2001).
auditory) stimuli decreased compared to a uni- Thus “deeper” processing can lead to lower
modal baseline. recognition accuracy when critical lures are
Fourth, because effects of words and visual semantically similar to studied items. In con-
information on induction stem from atten- trast to deep processing, focusing on percep-
tional mechanisms rather than from under- tual details of pictorially presented information
standing of the conceptual importance of labels results in accurate recognition (Marks, 1991).
or appearances, SINC predicts that contribu- Therefore, a memory test administered after an
tion of labels or appearance to induction can induction task may reveal information about
be changed by changing attentional weights of how items were processed during the induction
labels or appearance through associative train- task. If participants processed the items rela-
ing. This prediction was supported in a set of tively abstractly as members of a category (i.e.,
experiments (Fisher & Sloutsky, 2006; Sloutsky they performed category-based induction), then
& Spino, 2004). In one set of experiments they would likely have difficulty discriminating
284 INDUCTION

studied targets from conceptually similar criti- SINC does not consider category labels to be
cal lures. If, on the other hand, they processed category markers, the prediction is different.
items more concretely, focusing on perceptual In particular, because labels may overshadow
details (i.e., they performed similarity-based corresponding visual information, introduc-
induction), then they should discriminate rela- tion of labels may disrupt encoding of visual
tively well. This is exactly what we found: After information, thus resulting in a decreased pro-
performing induction with pictures of members portion of hits. Furthermore, category labels
of familiar categories (e.g., cats), young children and individual labels should have comparable
exhibited greater recognition accuracy than did effects on recognition memory. This is exactly
adults, with recognition gradually decreasing what was found—individual label and category
with increasing age (Fisher & Sloutsky, 2005a; labels exerted similar effects on recognition
Sloutsky & Fisher, 2004a, 2005). Their accuracy, memory (Fisher & Sloutsky, 2005b). However,
however, dropped to the level of adults when when young children were trained to perform
they were trained to perform induction in a category-based induction (Fisher & Sloutsky,
category-based manner—by deciding whether 2005b), not only did their induction perfor-
the test and the target items belong to the same mance increase, but participants also exhibited
kind. patterns of recognition accuracy that were simi-
Unlike some top-down approaches that con- lar to those of adults (i.e., high hits and elevated
sider linguistic labels as category proxies, SINC false alarms).
clearly differentiates between labeling infor- We also found that labels and visual simi-
mation and category information: According larity jointly contribute to induction early in
to SINC, linguistic labels contribute to induc- development, and SINC can quantify these
tion by contributing to similarity rather than contributions: For example, as mentioned
by denoting categories. Initial evidence for this above, SINC accurately predicted young chil-
distinction comes from the fact that young chil- dren’s performance on individual triads with
dren’s induction is not category-based (Fisher Gelman and Markman (1986) stimuli and,
& Sloutsky, 2005a; Sloutsky & Fisher, 2004a, as predicted, children’s induction was driven
2004b), yet labels contribute to early induc- by the overall similarity rather than by reli-
tion by affecting similarity (Sloutsky & Fisher, ance on labels. Also, as shown in Figure 14.3,
2004a; Sloutsky et al.,2001). SINC accurately predicts young children’s
More direct evidence for the distinction performance on a similarity judgment task
comes from a set of recent studies using the (Figure 14.3A) and on induction and catego-
ITR paradigm (Fisher & Sloutsky, 2005b). Note rizations tasks (Figure 14.3B). Finally, SINC
that in the recognition studies using the ITR assumes the interrelatedness of similarity,
paradigm discussed above (Fisher & Sloutsky, induction, and categorization, and results sup-
2005a; Sloutsky & Fisher, 2004a, 2004b), pic- port this assumption, pointing to high inter-
tures were not accompanied by labels. If label correlations among similarity, induction, and
and category information are the same for categorization (Sloutsky & Fisher, 2004a).
young children, then when presented entities However, it could be argued that reliance on
are labeled, children should exhibit effects of similarity does not constitute unequivocal evi-
semantic processing—low-recognition accu- dence against the idea that conceptual assump-
racy stemming from high hits and elevated false tions constrain generalization. For example, it
alarms. Furthermore, effects of category labels has been argued that categorization and induc-
(i.e., the words Cat referring to each individ- tion “reflect an interaction of perceptual knowl-
ual cat) should differ from those of individual edge, language, and conceptual knowledge”
labels (i.e., a different count noun referring to (Gelman & Medin, 1993, p. 159). Therefore, it is
each member of a category). In particular, only important to know whether or not young chil-
the former, but not the latter should promote dren’s generalization is driven by the category
category-based induction. However, because and linguistic assumptions.
SIMILARITY, INDUCTION, NAMING, AND CATEGORIZATION 285

A
0.9
0.8
Proportion of B-choices 0.7
0.6 Condition
Label-Observed
0.5
Label-Predicted
0.4
No-Label-Observed
0.3
0.2
0.1
0
1 1.22 1.86 9
Similarity ratio

B
1.2
CAT and IND Label-
1 Predicted
Proportion of B-choices

CAT-Label-Observed
0.8
IND-Label-Observed

0.6 IND and Cat No-Label-


Predicted
CAT-No-Label-
0.4 Observed
IND-No-Label-Observed
0.2

0
1 1.22 1.86 9
Similarity ratio

Figure 14.3 (Originally presented in Sloutsky & Fisher, 2004a). (A) Predicted and observed prob-
abilities of B-choices as a function of similarity ratio and labeling in the similarity judgment task.
(B) Predicted and observed probabilities of B-choices as a function of similarity ratio and labeling in
induction and categorization tasks. Error bars represent standard errors of the mean.

In an attempt to answer this question, we conceptual information is an important factor


conducted a study, in which 4- to 5-year-olds in early generalization, even when this informa-
learned a novel category and then performed tion is directly given to young children.
an induction task (Sloutsky, Kloos, & Fisher,
2007). The category was bound by a relational
WHY DO LABELS CONTRIBUTE
inclusion rule rather than by similarity (see
TO SIMILARITY?
Figure 14.4 for examples). After successfully
learning the category, participants were pre- As mentioned above, linguistic labels play an
sented with a triad induction task, such that important role in the early generalization: if
one test item shared category membership with two items are accompanied by the same label,
the target and another was similar to the tar- young children are more likely to general-
get (while being a member of a different cate- ize properties from one item to another than
gory). Despite the fact that young children ably when labels are different or no labels are intro-
learned the categories and readily categorized duced. In an attempt to explain these effects,
items throughout the experiment, they did two classes of explanations have been proposed.
not use this knowledge when making induc- According to the language-specific explana-
tions, relying instead on appearance similarity. tion, young children assume that (a) entities
Therefore, there is little evidence that top-down are members of categories and (b) count nouns
286 INDUCTION

Category 1 items (Ziblets)

Category 2 items (Flurps)

Figure 14.4 Examples of stimuli used by Sloutsky, Kloos, and Fisher (2007).

convey category membership (Gelman & Coley, the target items (i.e., AUDT VIST). Other test
1991). Furthermore, for 9-month-old infants, items had either the auditory component
even speech sounds devoid of morphosyntac- changed (AUDnewVIST), the visual component
tic information may communicate category changed (AUDT VISnew), or both components
membership (Balaban & Waxman, 1997). These changed (AUDnewVISnew). Participants had to
assumptions lead young children and infants respond same if the two compound stimuli had
to infer that entities that are denoted by the the same auditory and visual components, and
same count noun belong to the same category to respond different if either the auditory or
(Gelman & Markman, 1986; Markman, 1989; see visual component differed between the target
also Waxman & Markow, 1995 for a discussion). and test items. The auditory components con-
Therefore, according to the language-specific sisted of unfamiliar nonlinguistic sounds and
explanation, if entities share a label presented as the visual components consisted of unfamiliar
a count noun, then this shared count noun sug- images (e.g., geometric shapes). If participants
gests that entities belong to the same category encode both auditory and visual stimuli, then
(thus supporting categorization), and further, they should accept target items as the same and
belonging to the same category indicates that reject items that had either new visual or new
the members of the category share nonobvious auditory components.
properties (thus supporting inductive inference It was found that 4-year-olds failed to report
about these properties). that the visual components changed when
However, it is also possible that effects of stimuli were cross-modal, whereas they had
labels stem from attentional factors, such as no difficulty noticing when the same visual
auditory information overshadowing (or attenu- components changed in the unimodal condi-
ating processing) of corresponding visual infor- tion (see Figure 14.5 for overshadowing effects
mation (Napolitano & Sloutsky, 2004; Robinson in 4- and 6-year-olds). As shown in Figure
& Sloutsky, 2004; Sloutsky & Napolitano, 2003). 14.5, processing of visual stimuli was not dif-
As a result of overshadowing, young children ficult per se: in the absence of auditory stimuli,
may consider entities that share the label as young children ably encoded the visual stimuli,
looking more similar (Sloutsky & Fisher, 2004a; whereas when both visual and auditory stimuli
Sloutsky & Lo, 1999), with similarity affecting were presented simultaneously, encoding of
inductive generalization. visual (but not of auditory) stimuli decreased
Initial evidence for overshadowing was pre- compared to a unimodal baseline (Napolitano
sented in the Sloutsky and Napolitano (2003) & Sloutsky, 2004; Robinson & Sloutsky, 2004;
study, in which 4-year-olds and adults were Sloutsky & Napolitano, 2003). The results pre-
presented with an auditory-visual target item sented in Figure 14.5 also indicate that there was
(AUDT VIST), where the visual and the audi- a decrease in overshadowing effects between 4
tory components were presented in synchrony. and 6 years of age. Furthermore, we found no
The Target was followed by one of the four evidence of overshadowing in adults: adults ably
test items. Some test items were identical to processed both auditory and visual stimuli.
SIMILARITY, INDUCTION, NAMING, AND CATEGORIZATION 287

Presentation condition: under a wider range of stimulus conditions than


Unimodal (Baseline) children and adults.
Bimodal
1 Although these auditory overshadowing
0.9
Proportion correct

0.8 effects should hinder forming word-object asso-


0.7 ciations, it is well known that 14- and 15-month-
0.6
0.5 olds can form such associations (e.g., Schafer &
0.4
0.3
Plunkett, 1998; Werker, Cohen, Lloyd, Casasola,
0.2
Changed Changed Changed Changed & Stager, 1998). To examine whether words also
visual auditory visual auditory overshadow corresponding visual input, we
stimulus stimulus stimulus stimulus
paired the same visual stimuli that were used
4-year-olds 6-year-olds in Robinson and Sloutsky (2004) with nonsense
words (Sloutsky & Robinson, 2008). Results
presented in Figure 14.6A indicate that 8- and
Figure 14.5 Recognition accuracy by modal-
ity, presentation condition and age. Error bars 12-month-olds only encoded the word, whereas
represent standard errors of the mean. 16-month-olds encoded both the word and
visual stimulus. Thus, at 8 and 12 months of age,
both unfamiliar words and unfamiliar sounds
Finding overshadowing effects in young overshadowed visual input, whereas, at 16
children and the decrease of these effects in the months, words did not overshadow correspond-
course of development enabled us to make pre- ing visual input. Therefore, when cross-modal
dictions about infants’ ability to encode cross- stimuli are presented for a protracted period
modal stimuli. If overshadowing effects decrease of time (such as in familiarization or habitu-
with age, then infants should exhibit even stron- ation paradigms), by 16 months of age, words
ger overshadowing effects than young children. stop interfering with visual processing, whereas
These predictions were confirmed empiri- nonlinguistic sounds continue to interfere.
cally (Robinson & Sloutsky, 2004). In a set of Why is there a difference between encoding
experiments, Chris Robinson and I (Robinson visual stimuli accompanied by words and by
& Sloutsky, 2004) presented the same auditory sounds at 16 months of age? First, it is possible
and visual compounds to infants, children, and that human speech is a special class of stimuli
adults. In the infant task, 8-, 12-, and 16-month- for humans, with infants and young children
olds were familiarized to an auditory-visual having broad assumptions that words refer to
compound (AUDTVIST). At test, infants were categories (e.g., Waxman & Booth, 2003). Thus,
presented with four test trials where either the according to this “language-specific hypoth-
auditory component changed (AUDnewVIST), esis,” labels play a special role in processing of
the visual component changed (AUDTVISnew), visual information by directing children’s atten-
both components changed (AUDnewVISnew), or tion to visual input (e.g., Balaban & Waxman,
neither component changed (AUDTVIST). If 1997; Baldwin & Markman, 1989; Xu, 2002).
infants encode the auditory component dur- Alternatively, it is possible that the decreased
ing familiarization, then they should increase interference of words in visual processing at 16
looking when the auditory component changes months of age stems from familiarity effects:
at test (i.e., AUDnewVIST – AUDTVIST > 0), and by that age, human speech may become more
if infants encode the visual stimulus, then they familiar than many other sounds (e.g., Jusczyk,
should increase looking when the visual com- 1998; Napolitano & Sloutsky, 2004), and, under
ponent changes at test. Even though infants repeated presentation conditions, more famil-
ably encoded the visual stimuli when presented iar stimuli may be processed faster and may
unimodally, they often failed to encode visual be less likely to interfere with processing of
stimuli when paired with an auditory stimu- visual stimuli. If familiarity can account for the
lus (auditory overshadowing). Furthermore, increased processing of visual input, then prefa-
infants exhibited auditory overshadowing miliarizing infants to the nonlinguistic sounds
288 INDUCTION

A New visual
New auditory
New auditory/new visual
6000

* *

Difference in looking times compared to


5000
* * *
*
4000 *

Target item (ms)


3000

2000

1000

0
8-Months 12-Months 16-Months
-1000 Age

-2000

B No auditory baseline
Unfamiliar sounds
Unfamiliar words
Pre-familiarized words
Pre-familiarized sounds
5000
compared to the target item (ms)

* * *
* *
Difference in looking times

4000
*
3000 * *

Figure 14.6 (A) Encoding of 2000


auditory and visual stimuli at
8-, 12-, and 16-months of age. 1000
(B) 16-month-olds’ encoding
0
of auditory and visual compo- Auditory Visual
nents across different auditory –1000
conditions. Modality

prior to the experiment proper should attenuate was affected by the familiarity of the auditory
overshadowing effects. input. When the auditory input was unfamiliar,
To determine whether the effects of words at the sounds overshadowed corresponding visual
16 months were language-specific or stemmed input and the words did not interfere with pro-
from familiarity, we conducted another experi- cessing of visual input (compared to the uni-
ment, in which 16-month-olds were presented modal baseline). However, when infants were
with the same visual patterns accompanied by first prefamiliarized to the auditory component
the same auditory input (i.e., either linguistic or (either sound or word), prefamiliarized sounds
non-linguistic). However, prior to the experi- and words facilitated processing of correspond-
ment proper, participants were prefamiliarized ing visual input—in these conditions, infants
to the auditory input. Note that the presence were more likely to encode the visual stimuli
of prefamiliarization was the only difference than in a unimodal baseline. Therefore, under
between this and the previous experiment. As these conditions, familiar auditory stimuli
can be seen in Figure 14.6B, across the different tuned attention to corresponding visual input.
auditory conditions, infants ably encoded audi- Taken together, these findings present evi-
tory input. In contrast, encoding of visual input dence that early in development, auditory input
SIMILARITY, INDUCTION, NAMING, AND CATEGORIZATION 289

may affect attention allocated to visual input predictors) is not fi xed, but can be flexibly (yet
and in the course of development, visual pro- nondeliberately) adjusted in a course of learn-
cessing becomes more independent from audi- ing suggests how generalization can change in
tory processing. If this is the case, then effects the course of learning and development. At the
of words may stem from the dynamics of cross- same time, there are several issues that remain
modal processing rather than from conceptual unresolved. Most importantly, SINC cannot
assumptions. As processing of visual input account for many aspects of mature generaliza-
becomes more independent of processing of tion, such as some of the sophisticated strategies
auditory input and as children learn that under exhibited by adults, or for the transition from
many conditions, words are reliable cues, effects the early to mature generalization. These are
of words may become more “conceptual” in interesting challenges that have to be addressed
nature. This account may elucidate mechanisms in the future.
underlying effects of words on early generaliza-
tion: many of these effects may stem from audi-
CONCLUSIONS
tory input affecting processing of visual input. In
addition, this account suggests that the impor- In this chapter, I considered two broad theoreti-
tance of words is not “given,” but is acquired in cal approaches to cognitive development. One
the course of learning and development. approach advocates the importance of a priori
constraints in cognitive development (i.e., the
top-down approach). Evidence for these con-
UNRESOLVED ISSUES
straints comes from a variety of studies with
In sum, SINC—a bottom-up model reviewed in infants and young children, indicating that even
this chapter—can account well for early gener- early in development, infants and children treat
alization. First, the model accurately predicts some aspects of input as more “important” or
children’s performance on similarity judgment, central than others. Another approach argues
induction, and categorization tasks. I presented that people have powerful learning mechanisms
evidence from induction, categorization, and enabling them to extract regularities from the
recognition memory tasks, indicating that early input (i.e., the bottom-up approach). Proponents
generalization is driven by similarity rather than of the latter approach argue that conceptual
by abstract conceptual information. Second, the knowledge is not a priori, but it emerges in the
model quantifies effects of labels on similarity course of learning and development. Therefore,
and generalization early in development, and whenever children treat some aspects of input
the theory underlying SINC suggests the mech- as more “important,” these “important” stimuli
anism driving the effects of labels. I presented have to be natural “attention grabbers”; other-
evidence indicating that labels affect similarity wise the importance of these stimuli has to be
(and thus generalization) by attenuating visual learned. In the course of learning, children may
processing. The reviewed findings indicate that realize that some stimuli are regular and reli-
many effects of labels may stem from dynam- able predictors of other important events and
ics of cross-modal processing rather than from they may start treating the reliable predictors
conceptual assumptions about the language differently from the less reliable ones.
and the world. These ideas also explain why I then reviewed a recently proposed bot-
phonologically similar labels may affect early tom-up model of inductive generalization and
generalization in a manner similar to that of several phenomena predicted by the model; some
identical labels. Finally, the model suggests of these phenomena present challenges to the top-
that the contribution of various predictors (e.g., down approach. I specifically focused on the role
labels, appearances, etc.) to early generalization of label and appearance information in induction
is determined by attention allocated to these and presented evidence that labels affect induc-
predictors. The fact that attention allocated tion by contributing to the overall similarity of
to predictors (i.e., attentional weights of the compared items. I also considered a mechanism
290 INDUCTION

that may underlie the effects of labels on general- Estes, W. K. (1994). Classification and cognition.
ization: I suggested that labels (and other sounds) New York: Oxford University Press.
contribute to similarity by overshadowing (or Fisher, A. V., & Sloutsky, V. M. (2004). When mats
attenuating processing of) corresponding visual meow: Phonological similarity of labels and
input and presented supporting evidence from induction in young children. In K. Forbus,
D. Gentner, & T. Regier (Eds.), Proceedings of
studies with infants and young children. Finally, I
the XXVI Annual Conference of the Cognitive
discussed how effects of words may change in the Science Society. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
course of development as a function of increasing Fisher, A. V., & Sloutsky, V. M. (2005a). When induc-
familiarity of human speech. tion meets memory: Evidence for gradual tran-
I also tried to make it clear throughout the sition from similarity-based to category-based
chapter that much of the developmental story induction. Child Development, 76, 583–597.
remains a mystery. Despite the significant Fisher, A. V., & Sloutsky, V. M. (2005b). Effects of
advances in the study of inductive generaliza- category labels on induction and visual process-
tion in the past 20 years, the most interesting ing: Support or interference? In B. G.Bara, L.
developmental question has not been answered: Barsalou, & M. Bucciarelli (Eds.), Proceedings of
How do people become so smart, acquiring the XXVII Annual Conference of the Cognitive
Science Society. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
extraordinary complex knowledge that shapes
Fisher, A. F., & Sloutsky, V. M. (2006). Flexible
their striking intellectual abilities? A detailed attention to labels and appearances in early
answer to this question would likely to consti- induction. In R. Sun and N. Miyake (Eds.).
tute the most significant contribution to the Proceedings of the XXVIII Annual Conference
study of cognitive development. of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 220–225).
Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
French, R. M., Mareschal, D., Mermillod, M., &
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS Quinn, P. C. (2004). The role of bottom-up
processing in perceptual categorization by 3-
Th is research was supported by grants from
to 4-month-old infants: Simulations and data.
the NSF (BCS-0720135) and from the Institute
Journal of Experimental Psychology: General,
of Education Sciences, U.S. Department of
133, 382–397.
Education (R305H050125) to VM.S. The opin-
Gelman, R. (1990). First principles organize
ions expressed are those of the authors and do not
attention to and learning about relevant data:
represent views of the awarding organizations. I
Number and the animate–inanimate distinc-
thank Anna Fisher and Chris Robinson for help-
tion as examples. Cognitive Science, 14, 79–106.
ful comments.
Gelman, S. A. (1988). The development of induc-
tion within natural kind and artifact catego-
ries. Cognitive Psychology, 20, 65–95.
REFERENCES
Gelman, S. A. (2003). The essential child: Origins
Balaban, M. T., & Waxman, S. R. (1997). Do words of essentialism in everyday thought. London:
facilitate object categorization in 9-month- Oxford University Press.
old infants? Journal of Experimental Child Gelman, S. A., & Coley, J. (1991). Language and
Psychology, 64, 3–26. categorization: The acquisition of natural
Baldwin, D. A., & Markman, E. M. (1989). kind terms. In S. A. Gelman, S. & J. P. Byrnes
Establishing word–object relations: A first step. (Eds.), Perspectives on language and thought:
Child Development, 60, 381–398. Interrelations in development (pp. 146–196).
Booth, A. E., & Waxman, S. R. (2002). Word learn- New York: Cambridge University Press.
ing is ‘smart’: Evidence that conceptual infor- Gelman, S. A., & Heyman, G. D. (1999). Carrot-
mation affects preschoolers’ extension of novel eaters and creature-believers: The effects of lex-
words. Cognition, 84, 11–22. icalization on children’s inferences about social
Colunga, E. & Smith, L. B. (2005). From the lex- categories. Psychological Science, 10, 489–493.
icon to expectations about kinds: A role for Gelman, S. A., & Markman, E. (1986). Categories
associative learning. Psychological Review, 112, and induction in young children. Cognition,
347–382. 23, 183–209.
SIMILARITY, INDUCTION, NAMING, AND CATEGORIZATION 291

Gelman, S. A., & Markman, E. M. (1987). Young Recent advances (pp. 163–189). Hove, England:
children’s inductions from natural kinds: Psychology Press.
The role of categories and appearances. Child Mandler, J. (2004). The foundations of mind:
Development, 58, 1532–1541. Origins of conceptual thought. New York, NY:
Gelman, S. A., & Medin, D. L. (1993). What’s so Oxford University Press.
essential about essentialism? A different per- Madole, K. L., Oakes, L. M., & Cohen, L. B. (1993).
spective on the interaction of perception, Developmental changes in infants’ attention
language, and concrete knowledge. Cognitive to function and form–function correlations.
Development, 8, 157–167. Cognitive Development, 8, 189–209
Gelman, S. A., & Wellman, H. M. (1991). Insides Markman, E. (1989). Categorization and naming
and essences: Early understanding of the obvi- in children. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
ous. Cognition, 38, 213–244. Markman, E. M., and Hutchinson, J. E. (1984).
Hall, G. (1991). Perceptual and associative learn- Children’s sensitivity to constraints on word
ing. New York: Oxford University Press. meaning: Taxonomic versus thematic rela-
Johnson, S. P. (2003). Development of frag- tions. Cognitive Psychology, 16, 1–27.
mented versus holistic object perception. In Marks, W. (1991). Effects of encoding the percep-
G. Schwarzer & H. Leder, Helmut (Eds.), The tual features of pictures on memory. Journal of
development of face processing (pp. 3–17). Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory,
Ashland, OH: Hogrefe & Huber Publishers. and Cognition, 17, 566–577.
Jusczyk, P. W. (1998). The discovery of spoken lan- Massey, C. M., & Gelman, R. (1988). Preschooler’s
guage. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. ability to decide whether a photographed unfa-
Keil, F. C. (2003). Categories, cognitive develop- miliar object can move itself. Developmental
ment and cognitive science. In D. H. Rakison Psychology, 24, 307–317.
& L. M. Oakes (Eds.), Early category and con- Medin, D. (1975). A theory of context in discrimi-
cept development: Making sense of the bloom- nation learning. In G. Bower (Ed.), The psy-
ing buzzing confusion (pp. vi–xi). New York: chology of learning and motivation (Vol. 9, pp.
Oxford University Press. 263–314). New York: Academic Press.
Keil, F. C. (1989). Concepts, kinds, and cognitive Napolitano, A. C., & Sloutsky, V. M. (2004). Is a
development. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. picture worth a thousand words? The flexible
Keil, F. C., Smith, W. C., Simons, D. J., & Levin, nature of modality dominance in young chil-
D. T. (1998). Two dogmas of conceptual dren. Child Development, 75, 1850–1870.
empiricism: Implications for hybrid models Nosofsky, R. M. (1984). Choice, similarity, and
of the structure of knowledge. Cognition, 65, the context theory of classification. Journal of
103–135. Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory,
Kellman, P. J., & Spelke, E. S. (1983). Perception & Cognition, 10, 104–114.
of partly occluded objects in infancy. Cognitive Oakes, L. M., & Madole, K. L. (2003). Principles
Psychology, 15, 483–524. of developmental changes in infants’ category
Koustall, W., & Schacter, D. L. (1997). Gist-based formation. In D. H. Rakison & L. M. Oakes
false recognition of pictures in older and (Eds.), Early category and concept develop-
younger adults. Journal of Memory & Language, ment: Making sense of the blooming, buzzing
37, 555–583. confusion (pp. 132–158). New York: Oxford
Lewkowicz, D. J. (1988a). Sensory dominance in University Press.
infants: 1. Six-month-old infants’ response to Rakison, D. H. (2003). Parts, motion, and the
auditory-visual compounds. Developmental development of the animate–inanimate dis-
Psychology, 24, 155–171. tinction in infancy. In Rakison & L. M. Oakes
Lewkowicz, D. J. (1988b). Sensory dominance in (Eds.), Early category and concept development:
infants: 2. Ten-month-old infants’ response to Making sense of the blooming, buzzing confu-
auditory-visual compounds. Developmental sion (pp. 159–192). New York, NY: Oxford
Psychology, 24, 172–182. University Press.
Mandler, J. M. (1997). Development of Robinson, C.W., & Sloutsky, V.M. (2004).
categorisation: Perceptual and concep- Auditory dominance and its change in the
tual categories. In G. Bremner, A. Slater & course of development. Child Development, 75,
G. Butterworth (Eds.), Infant development: 1387–1401.
292 INDUCTION

Rogers, T. T. and McClelland, J. L. (2004). Semantic learning provides on-the-job training for atten-
cognition: A parallel distributed processing tion. Psychological Science, 13, 13–19.
approach. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Soja, N. N., Carey, S., & Spelke, E. S. (1991).
Schafer, G., & Plunkett, K. (1998). Rapid word Ontological categories guide young children’s
learning by fi fteen-month-olds under tightly inductions of word meaning Object terms and
controlled conditions. Child Development, 69, substance terms. Cognition, 38, 179–211.
309–320. Spelke, E. S. (1990). Principles of object percep-
Sloutsky, V. M. (2003). The role of similarity in tion. Cognitive Science, 14, 29–56.
the development of categorization. Trends in Spelke, E. S. (1994). Initial knowledge: Six sugges-
Cognitive Sciences, 7, 246–251. tions. Cognition, 50, 431–445.
Sloutsky, V. M. & Fisher, A. V. (2004a). Induction Thapar, A., & McDermott, K. B. (2001). False recall
and categorization in young children: A sim- and false recognition induced by presenta-
ilarity-based model. Journal of Experimental tion of associated words: Effects of retention
Psychology: General, 133, 166–188. interval and level of processing. Memory &
Sloutsky, V. M., & Fisher, A. V. (2004b). When Cognition, 29, 424–432.
development and learning decrease memory: Werker, J. F., Cohen, L. B., Lloyd, V. L., Casasola,
Evidence against category-based induction in M., & Stager, C. L. (1998). Acquisition of word–
children. Psychological Science, 15, 553–558. object associations by 14-month-old infants.
Sloutsky, V. M. & Fisher, A. V. (2005). Similarity, Developmental Psychology, 34, 1289–1309.
Induction, Naming, and Categorization (SINC): Waxman, S. R., & Booth, A. E. (2003). The origins
Generalization or Inductive Reasoning? Response and evolution of links between word learning
to Heit and Hayes. Journal of Experimental and conceptual organization: New evidence
Psychology: General, 134, 606–611. from 11-month-olds. Developmental Science,
Sloutsky, V. M., Kloos. H., & Fisher, A. V. (2007). 6, 130–137.
What’s beyond looks? Reply to Gelman and Waxman, S. R., & Markow, D. B. (1995). Words
Waxman. Psychological Science, 18, 556–557. as invitations to form categories: Evidence
Sloutsky, V. M., & Napolitano, A.C. (2003). Is a from 12- to 13-month-old infants. Cognitive
picture worth a thousand words? Preference Psychology, 29, 557–302.
for auditory modality in young children. Child Welder, A.N., & Graham, S.A. (2001). The influences
Development, 74, 822–833. of shape similarity and shared labels on infants’
Sloutsky, V. M., & Lo, Y.-F. (1999). How much does inductive inferences about nonobvious object
a shared name make things similar? Part 1: properties. Child Development, 72, 1653–1673.
Linguistic labels and the development of simi- Wellman, H. M., & Gelman, S. A. (1992). Cognitive
larity judgment. Developmental Psychology, 35, development: Foundational theories of core
1478–1492. domains. Annual Review of Psychology, 43,
Sloutsky, V. M., Lo, Y.-F., & Fisher, A. (2001). 337–375.
How much does a shared name make things Wexler, K., & Culicover, P. W. (1980). Formal prin-
similar? Linguistic labels, similarity and the ciples of language acquisition. Cambridge MA:
development of inductive inference. Child MIT Press.
Development, 72, 1695–1709. Woodward, A. L., & Markman, E. M. (1998). Early
Sloutsky, V. M., & Spino, M. A. (2004). Naive the- word learning. In W. Damon, D. Kuhn & R.
ory and transfer of learning: When less is more Siegler (Eds.), Handbook of child psychology,
and more is less. Psychonomic Bulletin and Volume 2: Cognition, perception and language
Review, 11, 528–535. (pp. 371–420). New York: John Wiley and Sons.
Sloutsky, V. M., & Robinson, C. W. (2008). The role Xu, F. (2002). The role of language in acquiring object
of words and sounds in visual processing: From kind concepts in infancy. Cognition, 85, 223–250.
overshadowing to attentional tuning. Cognitive Xu, F., & Tenenbaum, J. B. (2007). Word learning
Science, 32, 354–377. as Bayesian inference. Psychological Review,
Smith, L. B., Jones, S. S., & Landau, B. (1996). 114, 245–272.
Naming in young children: A dumb attentional Yoshida, H., & Smith, L. B. (2005) Linguistic
mechanism? Cognition, 60, 143–171. cues enhance the learning of perceptual cues.
Smith, L. B., Jones, S. S., Landau, B., Gershkoff- Psychological Science, 16, 90–95.
Stowe, L., & Samuelson, L. (2002). Object name
PART V

Foundations of Social Cognition


This page intentionally left blank
CHAP TER 15
Building Intentional Action Knowledge
with One’s Hands

Sarah Gerson and Amanda Woodward

Understanding others’ actions as intentional is The question of interest was whether infants,
fundamental to everyday social life. Adults view like adults, would represent this event as goal-
even the simplest and most concrete actions not directed, that is, in terms of the relation between
as sheer movements, but rather as actions orga- the agent and her goal. Following habituation,
nized by intentions. To illustrate, observing a the positions of the two toys were switched.
group of children and a ball traversing a soc- Then the experimenter reached for either a new
cer field, we perceive the motions of the former, toy in the same place (new-object trials) or the
but not the latter, as structured with respect to same toy in a new place (new-side trials). Infants
a goal, in this case the goal of driving the ball looked longer to the new-object trials than the
across the field to score. This foundational new-side trials, indicating that they represented
aspect of social perception is a critical ingredi- the event in terms of the relation between agent
ent in social, cognitive, and linguistic develop- and goal, rather than strictly in terms of physi-
ment. In the first years of life, children acquire cal properties such as the movement and posi-
a great deal of knowledge from other people. By tion of the actor’s arm.
12 to 18 months of age, if not earlier, this learn- Critically, several subsequent findings con-
ing is mediated by an analysis of others’ inten- firmed that infants’ responses in this paradigm
tions (Baldwin & Moses, 2001; Meltzoff, 1995; indicate more than an association between the
Tomasello, 1999). Deficiencies in this ability hand and the object it grasps. Rather, infants
have devastating developmental effects, as seen encoded the reaching events in terms of the
in individuals with autism. In this chapter, we relational structure of the action. This conclu-
will consider the potential origins of the ability sion is supported by the outcomes of compar-
to discern others’ intentions in acting. ison events in which one object moves toward
Recent findings have shown that by the mid- another, but, unlike the hand, the moving
dle of the first year, infants represent certain object is not readily construed as an agent. For
actions in terms of their intentional structure example, in one control condition, infants saw
(Gergely & Csibra, 2003; Kuhlmeier, Wynn, a mechanical claw move toward and grasp a toy
& Bloom, 2003; Luo & Baillargeon, 2007; (Woodward, 1998). If infants only encoded the
Woodward, 1998; Woodward & Guajardo, association between two “objects” (the hand and
2002). For example, in a series of studies from toy or the claw and toy), their responses in these
our laboratory (Guajardo & Woodward, 2004; two situations would be equivalent. However,
Woodward, 1998, 1999, 2003), infants 6 months infants in the mechanical claw condition looked
of age and older viewed events in which a per- equally long at the new-object and new-side test
son reached toward and grasped one of two toys. events.

295
296 FOUNDATIONS OF SOCIAL COGNITION

Additional evidence that infants attend to Sommerville & Woodward, 2005; Woodward &
relations between agents and goals comes from Sommerville, 2000).
recent work by Luo and Baillargeon (2007):
12-month-old infants did not show selective
ORIGINS OF INTENTIONAL UNDERSTANDING
attention to goal change events if the agent could
only see one of two objects during habituation While this evidence makes clear that the ability
(the other object was visible to the infant but to recover intentional structure from observed
hidden from the experimenter’s view). In this actions exists early in life, the ontogenetic ori-
paradigm, the association between the hand gins of this ability are still in question. How do
and the goal-object was identical to Woodward’s the beginnings of these understandings appear?
(1998) paradigm but the actor’s knowledge of How do changes in understanding come about?
the potential goals differed. Therefore, it can be As is the case in other domains of infant cog-
concluded that infants considered the agent’s nition, current positions on these questions
intentional relations to the objects, rather than range from the strongly nativist (e.g., Biro &
simply the association of the hand with the Leslie, 2006; Gergely & Csibra, 2003; Kiraly,
object it grasped. These findings also indicate Jovanovic, Prinz, Aschersleben, & Gergely,
that infants understand that an agent’s goals are 2003) to strongly emphasizing the role of expe-
limited by perception. rience (e.g., Meltzoff, 1995; Tomasello, 1999;
Infants’ sensitivity to the goal structure of Woodward, 2005). At this point, there is little
others’ actions is also evident in other para- direct evidence available to distinguish among
digms, including those that assess imitative these views because most studies have not inves-
responses (Hamlin, Hallinan, & Woodward, in tigated developmental change and its possible
press; Meltzoff, 1995) and other overt spontane- causes. Instead, studies have typically taken
ous social behaviors in experimental contexts a “snapshots” approach, seeking evidence for
(Behne, Carpenter, Call, & Tomasello, 2005). focal abilities at a particular point in time but
For example, like older infants and children, not considering how these abilities may change
7-month-old infants selectively reproduce the as a function of other events in development.
goals of observed actions, thereby revealing, In this chapter, we will attempt to begin to
with their hands, the same goal analysis that has fi ll this void by considering a category of expe-
been shown in looking time studies (Hamlin et rience that has long been hypothesized to con-
al., in press; Mahajan & Woodward, 2007). tribute to intentional understanding, namely
Toward the end of the first year of life, first-person agentive experience. The idea that
infants become increasingly able to discern action production and action understanding
the goal structure of more complex actions. By are linked in development has been around for
9 to 12 months, for example, infants represent over a century (Baldwin, 1897; Piaget, 1953).
others’ gaze as indicating relations between A number of current proposals have at their
the looker and the object at which her eyes are core the idea that one’s own actions provide
pointed. Evidence for this ability comes from unique insight into the structure of others’
looking time studies (Johnson, Ok, & Luo, 2007; actions (Barresi & Moore, 1996; Meltzoff, 1995;
Phillips, Wellman, & Spelke, 2002; Sodian & Tomasello, 1999).
Thoermer, 2004; Woodward, 2003) and studies Theoretically, it seems reasonable that one’s
assessing infants’ overt social responses (Moll own experience as an agent could provide use-
& Tomasello, 2004; Tomasello & Haberl, 2003). ful information for understanding other agents.
Further, by this same age, infants represent A true test of this general hypothesis requires
goals that span individual actions. For example, (1) measuring infants’ analysis of observed
they can represent the relation between actions action structure and (2) relating this measure to
on a tool or intermediary and the attainment variations in infants’ own actions. We turn first
of an ultimate goal (Gergely & Csibra, 2003; to recent studies that have done just this, and
Sommerville, Hildebrand, & Crane, in press; in so doing provided initial evidence that this
BUILDING INTENTIONAL ACTION KNOWLEDGE WITH ONE’S HANDS 297

general proposal is on the right track. We will Correlational Evidence


then turn to the much harder question of why
During times of developmental change, a great
self-produced experience might have an effect
deal of individual variation can be seen in chil-
on the development of action understanding.
dren at a given age, and therefore, links between
This question will lead us to consider recent
motor capabilities and understanding of these
work on mirror systems, the limits of mirror
actions can be examined keeping age constant.
systems, and the role of analogy in conceptual
For example, between 10 and 12 months of age,
development.
a great deal of variability exists in infants’ abil-
ity to produce planful actions such as pulling a
EVIDENCE FOR LINKS BETWEEN
cloth to get a toy. There is also individual var-
ACTION PRODUCTION AND ACTION
iation in the ability to understand goal struc-
UNDERSTANDING
ture in these kinds of means–end sequences.
As researchers began to document infants’ In a paradigm assessing the understanding
emerging sensitivity to the goal structure of of these means–end actions, Sommerville
action, a coincidence became apparent. Infants and Woodward (2005) habituated infants to
and children are generally able to produce par- sequences in which an actor pulled a cloth in
ticular actions around the same age at which order to get a toy on its far edge. The question
they are also able to understand these actions was whether infants represented the actor’s
in others. Around 4 to 5 months of age, infants action on the cloth as directed at the ultimate
begin to make intentional grasps themselves goal (the toy) or at the cloth itself. To address
(Bertenthal & Clifton, 1998; Rochat, 1989) and this question, after habituation, infants were
also begin to understand grasp as goal-directed shown test events in which the toys’ positions
(Woodward, 1998). Around 9 to 12 months of were reversed and the actor only produced the
age, infants begin to engage in shared attention first action in the sequence, grasping a cloth.
and triadic interactions (Adamson & McArthur, Thus, infants viewed new-cloth trials, on which
1995; Carpenter, Nagell, & Tomasello, 1998) the actor grasped the other cloth, which now
and also begin to understand gaze and point- supported the previous goal toy, or new-toy tri-
ing as implying a relation between the agent and als, on which the actor grasped the same cloth as
the target of her attention (Brune & Woodward, before, which now held a different toy. Twelve-
2007; Woodward, 2003; Woodward & Guajardo, month-olds looked longer on new-toy trials
2002). Also, as infants are first able to pro- than new-cloth trials, showing that they repre-
duce goal-directed action sequences (around sented the action on the cloth as directed at the
9 to 12 months of age; Bates, Carlson-Luden, toy. Ten-month-olds, in contrast, were variable
& Bretherton, 1980; Piaget, 1953), they begin in their responses, showing no reliable group
to understand the ultimate goal of a means– preference. At this age, there was a correlation
end sequence that another person performs between infants’ own cloth-pulling abilities and
(Sommerville & Woodward, 2005; Woodward their looking time responses (see Figure 15.1).
& Sommerville, 2000). Infants who were well organized in their own
Two approaches have been taken to follow ability to pull a cloth to get a toy looked longer
up on these coincidences to determine whether, on new-toy trials, whereas infants who were
in fact, they reflect developmental relations unable to produce an organized and planful
between acting and understanding actions. The cloth-pulling action looked longer on new-cloth
first is to assess, within the same infants, cor- trials. Importantly, this finding demonstrated
relations between action production and action that infants who were unable to perform this
perception. The second is to intervene to change means–end action were not completely disor-
infants’ self-produced experience and then ganized concerning their understanding of the
assess the effects of this intervention on infants’ intention behind this action when observing
action perception. another. Instead, these infants understood this
298 FOUNDATIONS OF SOCIAL COGNITION

60

50

Mean looking times (s)


40

New toy
30
New cloth
20

10

0
Planful Non-planful

Figure 15.1 Infants who were able to produce planful cloth-pulling actions themselves were sensitive
to the means–end structure of an observed sequence of actions. From Sommerville and Woodward
(2005).

action on a simpler level, wherein the end-goal action understanding and how this link may
of the action was the cloth, as if it were a simple lead to developmental change. It demonstrates
grasp. that the developmental concordance in time
Other studies have found additional correla- reviewed above is more than mere coincidence.
tions between infants’ own abilities to act and Importantly, however, correlational evidence
their responses to others’ actions. For example, does not shed light on the causal contributors
between 9 and 12 months of age, a great deal of to this relation. Next, we will discuss evidence
individual variation exists in infants’ produc- that goes beyond correlations in an attempt to
tion of point and engagement in shared atten- examine causality.
tion; there is also individual variation in the
Intervention Evidence
ability to understand point and gaze. Woodward
and Guajardo (2002) found a relation between In intervention studies, infants at the cusp of
infants’ ability to produce object-directed points performing a particular skill are trained or sup-
and their understanding of point in a habitua- ported in a new self-produced action and then
tion paradigm. In addition, a study by Brune the effect of the training on their understand-
and Woodward (2007) supported the correla- ing of that action is assessed. This approach
tion between production and understanding of provides clearer evidence about the effects of
pointing and also found a correlation between acting on action understanding. For example,
infants’ engagement in shared attention and 3-month-olds are generally not yet skilled in
understanding of gaze as object-directed at 10 producing goal-directed grasps and they do
months of age. not typically understand the relation between
This correlational evidence is important another’s grasp and his or her goal. In a study
in that it demonstrates a specific link between by Sommerville, Woodward, and Needham
production and understanding of particu- (2005), infants received training in which they
lar actions. In addition, these results demon- were able to manipulate the movement of toys
strate that data from looking time studies is using Velcro mittens. Infants’ object-directed
clearly related to developments in infants’ overt touching (as indicated by simultaneous looking
actions. Most importantly for the current argu- and touching of the toys) increased with the use
ments, this evidence provides an initial view of the mittens. After training, infants responded
of the link between action production and to observed mittened reaching actions as goal-
BUILDING INTENTIONAL ACTION KNOWLEDGE WITH ONE’S HANDS 299

20
18
16

Mean looking times (s)


14
12
New object
10
New side
8
6
4
2
0
No experience Experience

Figure 15.2 Infants given experience producing object-directed actions with Velcro mittens were sen-
sitive to the goal structure of an observed mittened reach. From Sommerville et al. (2005).

14
12
10
8 New toy
6 New cane

4
2 *p < .02
0
Training Observation Baseline

Figure 15.3 Infants given training producing cane-pulling actions were sensitive to the means–end
structure of an observed sequence of actions. From Sommerville et al. (in press).

directed in the habituation paradigm described provide structure for the perception of others’
earlier (see Figure 15.2). That is, infants who actions.
had undergone training showed a strong nov- Similar intervention effects have also been
elty response on new-object trials but not on found with means–ends actions such as cane-
new-side trials. In contrast, infants who had not pulling (Sommerville et al., in press). In this
undergone training looked equally on the two study, 10-month-old infants trained to use a
kinds of test trials. Moreover, in the training cane to reach for a toy were able to understand
group, there was a strong correlation between the ultimate goal of a cane-pulling sequence
the extent to which infants had engaged in in a habituation paradigm (they looked lon-
object-directed actions with the mittens and the ger to a reach for the old cane to get a new toy
degree of their novelty response on new-object than a reach for a new cane to get the old toy;
trials. Thus, engaging in object-directed action see Figure 15.3). Moreover, as in Sommerville
seemed to drive infants’ subsequent responses et al.’s (2005) study, infants’ success in cane-
to observed reaching events. These results sup- pulling during training was correlated with their
port the conclusion that infants’ own actions response to the habituation events. Infants who
300 FOUNDATIONS OF SOCIAL COGNITION

were more successful at cane-pulling during


THEORETICALLINKS BETWEEN
training showed stronger attention to the goal
ACTION PRODUCTION AND ACTION
structure of the habituation events. Critically,
UNDERSTANDING
first-person experience had unique effects on
infants’ analysis of the observed actions. Infants Natural concordance in time, correlational data,
who received observational, rather than active, and intervention data all support the conclusion
training recovered attention to both test events, that a link exists between action production and
indicating that they detected the changes in the understanding. But why? One possibility is that
test events, but did not respond differentially to by acting, infants produce for themselves exam-
the new-toy versus the new-cane events. ples for observational analysis. There is evidence
Work by Meltzoff and Brooks provides fur- that infants analyze the structure of observed
ther evidence that self-produced experience can actions in several ways that could support the
inform infants’ analysis of others’ actions. In a extraction of goal information. First, infants
previous study, Brooks and Meltzoff (2002) used attend to the outcomes of actions, and, in some
infants’ propensity to follow gaze as a measure cases, use these to infer the function, and per-
of their understanding of attentional relations. haps goal, behind the action. For example, in a
They found that, 14 and 18, but not 12-month- study by Hauf, Elsner, and Aschersleben (2004),
old, infants understood that an adult wearing a 12- and 18-month-old infants were more likely
blindfold was not attending to an object in the to imitate an action that produced a sound
direction of her head turn. Specifically, 14- and than an action that did not produce any effect.
18-month-old infants were less likely to follow Further, in some cases, action effects (such as
the direction of the adults’ gaze when the adult moving an object to a new location) may help
was wearing a blindfold, but 12-month-olds infants to interpret the goals of ambiguous
continued to follow the adults’ “gaze” under actions (Biro & Leslie, 2006; Kiraly et al., 2003;
these conditions. However, in an interven- but see Heineman-Pieper & Woodward, 2003).
tion study (Meltzoff & Brooks, in press), after In addition, infants are sensitive to statisti-
12-month-old infants were given experience cal regularities in temporally extended events
wearing a blindfold, they inhibited the tendency (Kirkham, Slemmer, & Johnson, 2003; Saff ran,
to follow gaze when the adult was wearing the Aslin & Newport, 1996; see also Gomez,
blindfold. Thus, self-produced experience with Kirkham, and Saffran chapters in this volume),
the blindfold seemed to give them insight into and may therefore be able to extract recurring
the perceptual experience of others in the same patterns in actions. Baldwin, Baird, Saylor, &
situation. Clark (2001) found that 10- and 11-month-old
These three examples demonstrating the infants were sensitive to units in naturalistic
effects of intervention suggest that being an action that corresponded to those defined by
agent provides infants with information about goal completions to adult observers. This find-
others’ actions. There are a number of issues ing may, in part, reflect infants’ statistical anal-
that require further investigation. For one, the ysis of action elements that typically co-occur
relative impacts of self-produced and matched as units (Baird & Baldwin, 2001).
observational experience require further study. Clearly, self-produced actions would provide
Sommerville et al. (in press) fi ndings indicate data for these kinds of statistical learning mech-
that self-produced experience has unique effects anisms to exploit. However, here we explore the
on infants’ action perception, but whether this further possibility that self-produced actions
is always the case is not yet known. Even so, also provide unique information for the percep-
evidence from these studies is strongly sugges- tion of goal-directed action. In support of this
tive of a causal link between action produc- possibility, consider what infants seem not to
tion and understanding. Ongoing work in our learn by watching alone. Infants are constant
laboratory seeks to replicate and extend these witnesses to goal-directed actions like grasp-
fi ndings. ing, looking, and tool use, but knowledge about
BUILDING INTENTIONAL ACTION KNOWLEDGE WITH ONE’S HANDS 301

the goal structure of these actions is not evident evidence suggests that there is some truth to the
from the start. Rather, as described earlier, general proposal that self-produced actions pro-
infants’ sensitivity to the goal structure of these vide unique information for perceiving others’
actions emerges, at different points, during the actions, it does not indicate which of these more
first year of life. specific accounts is correct. Indeed, more than
one of them could provide an accurate depic-
tion of different aspects of action knowledge
SELF-PRODUCED ACTIONS AS UNIQUE
development.
SOURCES OF INFORMATION
In one current proposal, Meltzoff (2005) pro-
Unlike observed actions, which can only provide poses a developmental framework, nicknamed
information “at the surface” (e.g., the sequelae of the “like me” account, in which information
actions), the regular patterns in self-produced about self and other is directly connected
actions could also provide unique information because both are instantiated in a common
about the underlying goal structure of action. supramodal representation and grounded in a
Agency requires representing the goals of one’s common body schema. Th is direct connection
actions at some level. To coordinate complex provides infants with a means for apprehend-
actions in service of a goal, or to acquire a new ing the inner states that correlate with others’
goal-directed skill, like reaching by gradually observed actions, and it also supports imita-
gaining control over the relevant effectors, indi- tion. By imitating an observed action, Meltzoff
viduals must continue to represent the goals that proposes, infants gain information, via their
structure their actions and adjust their actions own experience, about the inner states of the
as needed to attain the goal. This information other person. Meltzoff further proposes that
could potentially be recruited to then interpret infants do not begin with full-fledged concep-
the perceived actions of others. tions of mental states like intention or percep-
This general idea has been broadly pro- tion, but rather they construct these concepts
posed in the developmental literature (Barresi in the course of back and forth information
& Moore, 1996; Meltzoff, 2005; Sommerville & sharing about their own and others’ actions.
Woodward, in press; Tomasello, 1999). Accounts In this way, action understanding is direct and
differ, however, on two important dimensions: linked with internal states from the onset and
the nature of the information carried from self infants’ understanding of their own and oth-
to other and the means by which information ers’ mental lives becomes more abstract with
about the self is related to the actions of another development.
person. On the first dimension, some have pro- A somewhat different view has been elabo-
posed that infants or young children derive rated by Barresi and Moore (1996). In this
mental state information from first-person account, as in Meltzoff ’s, information derived
experience, which they then use to infer similar from first-person experience is critical for
states in others (e.g. Meltzoff, 2005). In contrast, understanding the mental lives of others. Their
it is possible that the information available to perspective, however, views the connection
infants from first-person experience is in terms between self and other as indirect and emerg-
of action level descriptions, rather than men- ing through analogical mapping. According to
tal states. On the second dimension, some have their perspective, triadic interactions, in which
hypothesized that children extend information individuals jointly attend to an object or event,
from self to others via a process of analogical are a key element in understanding the relation
mapping (e.g., Barresi & Moore, 1996). In con- between self and others. Through joint engage-
trast, others have suggested a direct link between ment with an adult, the infant can directly align
self and other, in the form of shared representa- the actions of himself or herself with the actions
tions for one’s own and others’ actions (Hauf, of another individual. This physical alignment
Aschersleben, & Prinz, 2007; Meltzoff, 2005; of actions provides the basis for the building of
Sommerville et al., 2005). Although current an intentional schema through analogy.
302 FOUNDATIONS OF SOCIAL COGNITION

Below, we propose an alternative account, (3) they are shaped by motor experience. Below,
similar in some respects to each of these per- we will review evidence for each of these fea-
spectives, but also differing in several respects. tures. We will then discuss the status of infancy
Our proposal is informed by recent findings con- research in this area.
cerning the mirror system and recent debates Rizzolatti and colleagues (Rizzolatti &
concerning the nature of information this sys- Arbib, 1998; Rizzolatti & Fadiga, 1998) found
tem provides the perceiver. To foreshadow, we that neurons fire during both performance and
propose that direct and indirect, mental and observation of actions in monkeys, thus provid-
action-level information sharing occur at dif- ing neural evidence for the link between action
ferent points during development. Initially, the production and perception. In research with
information provided by self-produced actions humans, transcranial magnetic stimulation
provides a direct, action-level description of (TMS) studies have found a selective increase
goal-directedness. This beginning point sets in motor-evoked potentials during observa-
up the conditions for subsequent analogical tion of actions that are specific to those mus-
mappings, which lead to more abstract levels cles used in the action (Fadiga, Fogassi, Pavesi,
of analysis. Before elaborating our proposal, & Rizzolatti, 1995; Gangitano, Mottaghy, &
we first review relevant research on the mirror Pascual-Leone, 2001). In addition, evidence of
system. corresponding areas of activation in the pre-
motor cortex during action observation and
execution has been found in functional mag-
ROLE OF MIRROR REPRESENTATIONS
netic resonance imaging (MRI) and positron
IN ACTION PERCEPTION
emission tomography (PET) studies (Buccino et
Findings from the past decade provide evi- al, 2001; Grafton et al., 1996; Grezes & Decety,
dence for a direct link between neurocognitive 2001; Iacoboni et al., 1999). More recently,
systems that subserve action production and electroencephalography (EEG) studies have
action perception. The first evidence for this found a suppression of mu rhythm in both
link came from primate research that identified the production and the observation of actions
neurons in motor regions that discharge both (Altschuler, Vankov, Wang, Ramachandran,
during the performance and the observation of & Pineda, 1997; Cochin, Barthelemy, Roux, &
goal-directed actions (Rizzolatti & Arbib, 1998; Martineau, 1999). The mu rhythm is evident
Rizzolatti & Fadiga, 1998). Subsequent research over motor areas, and is suppressed by move-
in humans has similarly indicated shared neu- ment, intended movement, or observation of
ral (Buccino et al, 2001; Grafton, Arbib, Fadiga, movement (Muthukumaraswamy, Johnson,
& Rizzolatti, 1996; Grezes & Decety, 2001; & McNair, 2004; Pineda, Allison, & Vankov,
Iacoboni et al., 1999) and cognitive (Hommel, 2000). Together, these diverse findings point to
Musseler, Aschersleben, & Prinz, 2001) repre- the existence of shared neural representations
sentations for perceiving and producing actions. for the production and perception of action.
Evidence in humans does not isolate individual Rizzolatti, Fogassi, & Gallese (2001) also
neurons. Instead, researchers ask whether com- found that mirror neurons in monkeys only
mon brain regions support the production and discharged to an agent grasping an object, not
perception of action. Our focus is not on the to either the agent or object alone, suggest-
exact nature of the neural representations, but ing that these neurons are selectively respon-
rather the functions that mirror representations sive to goal-directed actions (Gallese, Fadiga,
may support in development. Specifically, three Fogassi, & Rizzolatti, 1996). Similar findings
important functional characteristics of mir- have been obtained in humans. For example,
ror representations have been revealed across Muthukumaraswamy and colleagues (2004)
a number of studies: (1) they provide a direct found mu rhythm suppression occurred when
link between action and perception, (2) they are adults viewed a grasping action of an object
selectively sensitive to goal-directed action, and but not when this same action was produced
BUILDING INTENTIONAL ACTION KNOWLEDGE WITH ONE’S HANDS 303

without an object present. In humans, mirror a correspondence between representations of


representations seem to be sensitive to goals self and other in infancy (Meltzoff & Moore,
at more abstract levels as well, responding to 1989). In addition, the evidence from looking
events beyond the simple attainment of objects time studies with older infants that is discussed
to include such actions as a dance move- above, in which infants’ understanding of goal-
ment or the use of chopsticks (Calvo-Merino, directed actions is correlated with their actions,
Glaser, Grezes, Passingham, & Haggard, 2005; is consistent with the notion that mirror system
Calvo-Merino, Grezes, Glaser, Passingham, activity exists in infancy.
& Haggard, 2006; Järveläinen, Schürmann, & A study by Falck-Ytter, Gredeback, and von
Hari, 2004). Hofsten (2006) provides additional indirect
Work by Calvo-Merino and colleagues support for the existence of mirror representa-
(2005, 2006) highlights the expertise-driven tions in infancy. Previous research has shown
nature of mirror representations. In one study, that adults produce systematic, proactive eye
male dancers showed motor activation during movements during the production of goal-di-
the observation of dance movements they reg- rected actions. That is, adults make predictive
ularly produced but not during observation eye movements in order to control and coor-
of movements regularly performed by female dinate their actions. The same kind of predic-
dancers, with which the males were extremely tive eye movements are made when an adult is
familiar but had no firsthand experience pro- watching others produce similar goal-directed
ducing. Additionally, simple effects of gen- actions (Flanagan & Johansson, 2003). This
der were accounted for in that males watching finding is consistent with the possibility that a
females perform an action common to both common system drives both attention to one’s
genders did show activation of the mirror sys- own actions and attention to others’ actions.
tem. These findings demonstrate that action Following on this finding, Falck-Ytter and col-
experience can lead to activation of the system leagues asked whether infants anticipate the
and that mirror system activity is dependent on goals of observed actions. They showed infants
possessing a motor representation for an action sequences in which a person placed each of a set
rather than simply having visual knowledge of balls into a container. Like adults, 12-month-
of the action. Additional evidence that action old infants anticipated the goal of this sequence,
experience influences the mirror system is pro- looking to the bucket reliably before the ball’s
vided by Catmur, Walsh, & Heyes (2007). In this arrival. In contrast, infants who viewed the
study, training in producing an action oppo- same ball movements, this time without a
site to the one being observed reversed mirror human mover, followed the balls, but did not
effects, demonstrating that the mirror system is anticipate their arrival at the bucket. Based
reliant on sensorimotor learning. on these results, these researchers speculate
that the mirror system is active in infancy and
Mirror Systems in Infancy
drives infants’ predictive attention to observed
Due to limitations in techniques for brain imag- actions.
ing with infants, the majority of work concern- A recent study provides the only brain-based
ing the mirror system in humans has been done evidence for the presence of a mirror system
with adults. Currently, brain-based evidence of in human infants. Shimada and Hiraki (2006)
mirror systems in infants is extremely limited, conducted a study that examined brain activity
but behavioral studies have provided indirect during action observation in 7- and 8-month-
support for the idea that the mirror system may old infants. In this study, the sensorimotor area
be functioning in human infants (see Lepage was identified during a motor task in which
& Theoret, 2007). For example, neonatal imi- adult participants were prompted to engage
tation, in which newborn infants are able to in repetitive hand movements and infant par-
imitate tongue protrusions without the ability ticipants engaged in structured free-play. Then,
to see the action they make themselves suggests the activity of motor areas was measured using
304 FOUNDATIONS OF SOCIAL COGNITION

near-infrared spectroscopy during action goals of others. Blakemore and Decety (2001)
observation (in one condition, infants watched also proposed that mental states can be inferred
an experimenter manipulate a toy) in both directly from biological motion through a pro-
adults and infants. The sensorimotor area was cess of simulation.
selectively activated during live action observa- Other researchers have countered this view
tion in both adults and infants. This area was with the argument that the mirror system may
not activated when observing a live object- be useful in determining motor intentions but
motion condition in which the object moved that it is not sufficient for understanding prior
on its own. Additionally, coding of the infants’ intentions and mental states more generally.
arm movements during free-play indicated that Representing prior intentions entails an under-
the observed motion was part of the motor rep- standing of intentions as mental states that exist
ertoire of most infants, supporting the claim independent of the particular actions used to
that the mirror system is sensitive to motions achieve the intended goal. Motor intentions,
within an individual’s motor repertoire, even in in contrast, are specified at the level of the goal
infancy. at which a particular action is directed. Jacob
and Jeannerod (2005) argue that perceiving an
action will lead to an understanding of motor
MIRROR REPRESENTATIONS: MENTAL STATE
intention but cannot lead to the understand-
OR ACTION LEVEL DESCRIPTIONS?
ing of an agent’s prior intention. They state, for
Mirror representations provide a direct path example, that infants’ understanding of a basic
between actions of self and others that may be grasp in a habituation paradigm may be due to
in place from infancy. They respond selectively motor simulation, but that this simulation is
to goal-directed actions and are shaped by only possible for basic actions and intentions.
agentive experience. A critical open question, Prior intentions, however, wherein the goal is
however, is the extent to which mirror repre- not inherent in the action itself (i.e., opening a
sentations make contact with mental state con- drawer in order to retrieve a pen from inside),
cepts. Debates in the literature on the functions cannot be represented by mirror systems alone.
of mature mirror systems have highlighted this In its strongest form, the claim that the mir-
issue. ror system can only be used on the most basic
Some theorists have taken up the mirror sys- level has been disputed by subsequent evidence
tem findings as evidence in favor of simulation that mirror neurons in primates and mirror
theory. The simulationist account posits that systems in humans can represent not only the
individuals can gain an understanding of oth- goals of simple actions, but also overarching
ers’ mental states by mentally simulating those goals that structure action sequences (Fogassi
actions themselves (Goldman, 1989; Gordon, et al., 2005; Iacoboni et al., 2005). For exam-
1986; Harris, 1989; Heal, 1998). This theory pro- ple, Fogassi and colleagues (2005) found mirror
poses a direct link between first-person mental neurons in macaque monkeys that fired differ-
states and the comprehension of others’ men- entially to grasping actions that preceded eating
tal states. In this way, individuals can “mirror” versus placing of the grasped object when there
the actions of another and come to understand were contextual cues to support one of these
another’s actions based on their own past expe- two analyses of the grasp. Thus, these neurons
rience (without analyzing or building a theory). reflected processing, not of the basic action itself
To illustrate, Gallese and Goldman (1998) pro- (grasping), but rather the ultimate goal at which
posed that mirror systems allow an individual the grasp was apparently directed (eating versus
to detect mental states in others because mir- placing). Further, Ferrari, Rozzi, and Fogassi
roring creates a match between mental activ- (2005) report the existence of “grasping” mir-
ity of the observer and the actor, and, thus, the ror neurons that fired for grasping done by var-
observer is able to use his or her own mental ied effectors (e.g., the hand, the mouth or even
processes to understand and predict the mental a tool), thus indicating that mirror systems can
BUILDING INTENTIONAL ACTION KNOWLEDGE WITH ONE’S HANDS 305

reflect goal representations that are relatively


RELATIONALACTION REPRESENTATIONS
abstract, at the level of action plans.
AND STRUCTURE MAPPING: A PROPOSAL
Even so, mirror representations alone seem
unlikely to account for the full range of mental We propose that early in the first year, as infants
state knowledge humans eventually acquire. To begin to organize their own actions with respect
illustrate, Saxe (2005) argues that if belief attri- to external goal objects, they acquire relational
bution derived from direct simulation, then the action representations that enable the percep-
pervasive belief attribution errors seen in chil- tion of others’ actions as structured by goals.
dren (and even in adults) would be difficult to Thus, as infants acquire new ways of acting
explain. Rather, these errors indicate that peo- (i.e., reaching, using a tool to acquire an object,
ple’s judgments about others’ epistemic states pointing), they also attain new action level rep-
are the product of an interpretive system (the- resentations of each of these actions. These rep-
ory of mind) that can, in some cases, generate resentations may reflect the activity of a mirror
incorrect analyses. system that, as reviewed above, reflects repre-
This debate concerning more mature mir- sentations accessible to both action production
ror systems sheds light on the probable limita- and action perception, is tuned to actions that
tions of developing mirror systems in infants. are goal-directed, and is shaped by motor expe-
Mirror systems, on their own, seem unlikely to rience. This proposal is motivated by the find-
directly yield higher order mental state descrip- ings, reviewed above, that (1) young infants
tions. At the very least, however, they would encode others’ actions as goal-directed and
provide action level or even plan level descrip- they express this action analysis in their overt
tions of actions as structured in relation to a actions as well as their looking time responses;
goal. Descriptions at this level, whether or not (2) infants’ goal encoding is correlated with
they make contact with mental state concepts, developments in their own actions; (3) interven-
could account for many of the infant fi ndings tions that shape infants’ own actions also affect
reviewed in this chapter. For example, when an their responses to others’ actions; and (4) initial
infant responds selectively to the change in the evidence suggesting that self-produced actions
goal of a grasp in a habituation paradigm, this exert unique, or especially potent, effects on
response, at a minimum, reflects an understand- infants’ action perception.
ing of the relational goal structure of grasping On our proposal, the action representations
actions (see also Gergely & Csibra, 2003). It may infants initially glean from agentive experience
also reflect the attribution of a mental state, may be limited in two ways: They may be spe-
such as wanting the object or liking the object, cific to particular actions and they may describe
but as of yet there is not strong evidence for this action in structural rather than rich mentalistic
in infants under 12 months of age (see Biro & terms. Despite these limitations, they reflect a
Leslie, 2006; Gergely & Csibra, 2003; Onishi & critical aspect of action structure, namely, that
Baillargeon, 2005; and Woodward, 2005 for dif- actions are structured by the relation between
ferent perspectives on this issue). the agent and his or her goal. We propose that
Thus, we assume at this point that, at a this relational core provides a basis for general-
minimum, infants in the first year have action izing initial knowledge so as to create broader
level and plan level representations of goal-di- classes of goal-directed actions and to move
rected action, leaving open the possibility that toward more abstract representations of goals.
they may also represent information about the The literature on conceptual generalization
inner states that drive action. In addition to in older children and adults provides a model
accounting for the data from younger infants, of how this process could occur in infancy. In
the structural level of description could provide particular, Gentner and her colleagues have
an initial representational kernel for the subse- described a general cognitive mechanism that
quent development of intentional action knowl- can extract increasingly abstract levels of rela-
edge. We turn next to this possibility. tional similarity across instances (Gentner,
306 FOUNDATIONS OF SOCIAL COGNITION

1988; Gentner & Medina, 1998). Because it not only the relation between the bone and the
yields abstract relational representations, this hiding place (i.e., under the chair) but also the
structure mapping engine (SME) seems espe- relation between the chair and other objects in
cially well suited to the case of goal-directed the room (i.e., under the chair that is next to the
action. The structure mapping engine is essen- bed). The older children in the study were able
tially an analogy maker. Instances are aligned to use comparisons of this embedded relational
based on similar features and this alignment structure to find the hidden bone. Furthermore,
promotes attention to other shared dimensions. Kotovsky and Gentner (1996) found that align-
Alignment and comparison supports the detec- ing items based on relatively concrete relations
tion of abstract, relational similarities that may facilitated 4-year-old children’s subsequent abil-
not be initially obvious to the observer. ity to discern higher-order relational structure.
To illustrate, in one set of studies, Loewenstein For example, if children were trained with per-
and Gentner (2001) showed 3-year-old children ceptually similar examples of the relation small-
a toy bone hidden in relation to an object in a big-small, they were then better able to detect
model room (e.g., under the bed). Then, chil- the higher-order relational similarity between
dren were shown another model room that small-big-small patterns and A-B-A patterns in
had different-looking exemplars of each piece other dimensions (e.g., dark-light-dark). These
of furniture, similarly arranged to the first examples show that beginning with relatively
room. They were told there was a bone in the concrete comparisons can support the extrac-
same place in this room. Children were gener- tion of higher-order relational structure.
ally unsuccessful in finding the second bone, If infants, like older children, engage in
suggesting they found it difficult to apply the structure mapping, then this mechanism could
relational information (the bone is under the explain how initial, self-generated action repre-
bed) to the new, dissimilar room. To facilitate sentations become more general and abstract.
children’s ability to see the common relational For one, it would provide a mechanism for mov-
structure between the two rooms, Loewenstein ing beyond particular actions, e.g., grasping
and Gentner showed a second group of children with the hand, to categories of actions that sub-
two nearly identical model rooms with bones sume a broader range of instances, e.g. obtain-
hidden in the same location. Then, children ing objects with varied hand postures or other
saw the dissimilar test room and were asked to affectors. As in Loewenstein and Gentner’s
find the bone hidden in the “same place.” In this (2001) studies, infants may begin by detecting
condition, children generally succeeded in find- relational similarities among similar-looking
ing the bone. Thus, alignment of perceptually actions (e.g., grasping with the hands), and by
similar instances supported children’s ability to so doing become more sensitive to the relational
extract the common relational structure among similarity among more disparate actions.
even dissimilar instances. These effects were Recent findings show that infants sometimes
strongest when children could directly compare detect goal relations for events in which objects
the first two models at the same time. However, are moved or obtained by unusual hand pos-
even comparison across sequentially presented tures or inanimate agents (Biro & Leslie, 2006;
models helped. Hauf et al., 2004; Kiraly et al., 2003). These
Further, alignment of perceptually simi- results are generally taken as evidence that
lar instances also supports children’s extrac- infants possess abstract concepts of intention
tion of higher-order relations. For example, that arise independent of experience (see Biro &
Loewenstein and Gentner (2001) found that Leslie, 2006; Kiraly et al., 2003). However, many
the opportunity to compare similar rooms also of these findings would also be expected if
facilitated the extraction of embedded relational infants generalized familiar action representa-
similarities. Specifically, on some trials, the bone tions via structure mapping. Specifically, these
was hidden under one of two identical chairs. To extensions seem to occur most readily when (1)
find the hidden bone, children had to represent infants have a well-established relational action
BUILDING INTENTIONAL ACTION KNOWLEDGE WITH ONE’S HANDS 307

representation and (2) the situation promotes alignment of their own actions with the actions
alignment between the infants’ action represen- of others. For this reason, they hypothesize that
tation and the novel event. First, the propensity triadic interactions are especially important
to view unusual events as goal-directed is more for the process. On our proposal, infants may
often seen in older than younger infants, and represent intentional relations before they reli-
those experiments that include infants at mul- ably engage in triadic interactions.
tiple ages find age differences (Biro & Leslie, Beginning with a relational kernel would
2006; Gergely, Nadasdy, Csibra, & Biro, 1995; have several advantages. Real world actions are
Hauf et al., 2004). It could be assumed that age is not as neatly packaged as are habituation events
a reasonable proxy for the robustness of infants’ or stimuli in analogical mapping experiments.
self-produced action representations. Second, Hand trajectories and shapes differ as differ-
infants more readily construe unusual events as ent objects are grasped. People seldom grasp
goal-directed when they involve unusual hand the same object again and again. Furthermore,
postures than when they involve inanimate except in some specific contexts, like triadic
agents (Biro & Leslie, 2006; Hauf et al., 2004; interactions, it is relatively rare for infants’
Woodward, 1998). This effect may be due to the actions to be directed at the same objects as oth-
presence of hands supporting alignment with ers’ actions at the same time. Thus, infants must
familiar hand actions. be able to extract common goal structure across
Structure mapping may also facilitate exemplars that are varied and distributed in time.
extracting and generalizing the relational struc- Therefore, the conditions that have been shown
ture of embedded actions, such as using a tool to to support the extraction of relational structure
draw an object near before grasping it. Tool use from initial object similarity may rarely occur in
presents a challenge for the perceiver because the domain of action, especially early in infancy.
the action on the tool does not make direct Beginning with a few self-generated relational
contact with the goal object. Sommerville and action representations would support infants’
colleagues’ (in press) work suggests that self- ability to identify others’ goal-directed actions
produced means–end action provides insight in the face of the challenges posed by variabil-
into the embedded relational structure of others’ ity and temporal dispersion. As work with older
actions. Once this is in place, structure mapping children has shown, once children have estab-
would allow infants to generalize this structure lished relational representations, they are less
across diverse tool use events. For example, an dependent on surface similarity and physical
infant who had experienced and observed mul- alignment of instances in extending this rela-
tiple cloth-pulling events might then be able to tional information to new instances.
discern means–end structure in a novel tool Furthermore, hands move in many ways,
use event, just as children in Kotovsky and not all of them object-directed. If infants began
Gentner’s (1996) study were able to detect high- only with the ability to map events in terms of
er-order relational similarities among patterns similarities in the objects involved, they might
after aligning multiple instances of the relation. note that events with hands that grasp, gesture,
Structure mapping can extract relational snap, tap, scratch, etc. are all similar in that they
similarities starting at the level of pure object involve hands. However, they would miss the
similarity, with no initial relational content. critical underlying similarity that unites dis-
However, as detailed above, we hypothesize that parate goal-directed actions (e.g., lift ing a box
infants begin one step ahead in this process in with two hands and picking up a cheerio with
that they bring with them relational representa- a pincer grip) and makes them different from
tions of some actions. This differs from Barresi other “hand events.” Relational action represen-
and Moore’s (1996) view of the role of analogy tations would highlight for infants the common
in extracting intentional relations. In their view, relational structure of goal-directed actions,
infants do not begin with relational representa- thus distinguishing them from other hand
tions, but rather derive them from the physical movements or motion events.
308 FOUNDATIONS OF SOCIAL COGNITION

In summary, we propose that infants begin


CONCLUSION
with self-generated, relational action represen-
tations that guide their perception of others’ In this chapter, we have presented a construc-
actions. Structure mapping provides one means tivist hypothesis regarding the development
for going beyond these initial representations, of action and intention understanding. We
allowing infants to discern common relational propose that emerging abilities to act, mir-
structure across diverse actions. In this way, ror representations, and analogy each play an
infants may take the first step in separating goals important role in this constructive process. The
from the particular actions that pursue them. development of intention understanding occurs
Th is independence from particular actions through the progression from an initial struc-
is one critical piece of what it means to under- tural understanding of goal-directed actions
stand a goal or plan as a mental state. Thus, it provided by mirror systems to a more abstract
is possible that structure mapping plays a role understanding through application of general
in the development of folk concepts of mental purpose analogical mapping processes. Mirror
states. We assume that this is only part of the systems may get the process started, but further
story. Mature mental state concepts are embed- ontogenetic processes are needed to produce the
ded in and defi ned by theory-like systems of abstract action knowledge children eventually
knowledge (Wellman, 1990). The acquisition attain.
of such knowledge systems involves the inter- Our account is similar to Meltzoff ’s (2005)
play of cognitive learning mechanisms in the “like me” hypothesis in many important
child and information from the environment, ways. We concur that action understanding is
including linguistic information. Indeed, grounded in shared representation of self and
Gentner (2003) has highlighted the role of lan- other, and that action knowledge develops from
guage in supporting the acquisition of abstract relatively concrete to abstract forms during
relational concepts. Gentner and Medina infancy and early childhood. Our account dif-
(1998) have proposed a similar account for the fers in two respects. For one, we propose that
role of structure mapping in the acquisition of the extension of self-generated action repre-
folk theoretical knowledge in other domains, sentations to others can take place without the
for example the concept of essences in folk infant or child needing to engage in motor imi-
biology. tation. On Meltzoff ’s account, engagement in
Mental state knowledge becomes increas- imitation is critical for infants’ interpretation of
ingly rich during the preschool years (Wellman, others’ intentions in acting. On our view, action
1990). Even as early as 18 to 24 months of age, representations acquired from first-person
children verbally express knowledge about experience can then function “off-line” to pro-
mental states, such as states of attention, emo- vide structure for perceiving other’s actions.
tions, and intentions (Bartch & Wellman, 1995). Further, we suggest that these action repre-
Further, recent experiments suggest that by sentations can undergo change as a function of
these same ages children may understand belief observational extension. An infant with well-
states (Csibra & Southgate, 2006; Onishi & structured means-end action representations
Baillargeon, 2005; Southgate, Senju, & Csibra, may extend them to observed actions with a
2007; Surian, Caldi, & Sperber, 2007). Th is inter- novel tool, and by so doing, enrich the action
pretation of the findings is debated, but at the knowledge they can bring to bear in future
very least, these studies demonstrate relatively events. That is, once it is engaged, structure
rich understanding of others’ states of atten- mapping can operate on observational as well
tion. It is beyond the scope of this chapter to as self-produced examples. This proposal is
resolve this debate. Nevertheless, by these ages, consistent with the finding that by the second
we think it is possible that joint contributions of year of life, infants engage in observational
action analysis and linguistic input could con- learning, imitating new actions with artifacts
tribute to initial mental state concepts. or tools. Even so, because they bring with them
BUILDING INTENTIONAL ACTION KNOWLEDGE WITH ONE’S HANDS 309

relational content, self-produced actions may prediction comes from several recent lon-
continue to render especially powerful effects gitudinal studies documenting that infants’
on children’s emerging action knowledge. action analysis predicts their responses, some
A second difference between our proposal years later, on verbal theory of mind measures
and Meltzoff ’s is that we are more conserva- (Aschersleben & Hohenberger, 2007; Kuhlmeier
tive in our estimation of whether and when & Yamaguchi, 2007; Poulin-Dubois & Olineck,
infants conceive of others’ actions as being 2007; Wellman, Phillips, Dunphy-Lelii, &
caused by mental states. In Meltzoff ’s account Lalonde, 2004). Infants who respond more sys-
(2005), inner or mental states are part of what tematically to the intentional structure of oth-
is extended from self to other from the start. As ers’ actions go on to become preschoolers who
we have described, we think it is also possible respond more systematically on classic theory
to account for young infants’ action knowledge of mind assessments, like the false-belief task.
in structural terms, and we further hypothe- Thus, the initial steps we have begun to uncover
size that structural representations of goal-di- during infancy seem to begin a long journey in
rected action may provide a foundation for later the construction of folk psychology.
emerging mental state concepts. On the other
hand, our account does not make a clear pre-
diction of when in this chain of events the first ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
“mental” concepts will arise. In fact, we think The writing of this chapter was supported, in
the question of when an action representation part, by NIH grant HD35707 to A.W. We thank
counts as “mental” is complex and difficult to Annette Henderson and Scott Johnson for their
address given evidence from infancy research insightful comments on earlier versions of this
(see Woodward, 2005). manuscript.
Our proposal, though consistent with much
of what is currently known, raises a number of
REFERENCES
questions to motivate future research. To start,
we propose that infants’ own actions yield rela- Adamson, L. B., & McArthur, D. (1995) Joint atten-
tional action representations that observation tion, affect, and culture. In C. Moore, & P. J.
alone cannot provide. If we are right, then lab- Dunham (Eds.), Joint attention: Its origins and
oratory manipulations of infants’ own actions role in development (pp. 205–222). Hillsdale,
should change their perceptual responses in NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc.
Altschuler, E. L., Vankov, A., Wang, V.,
ways that observational training does not.
Ramachandran, V. S., Pineda, J. A. (1997).
Recent findings from Sommerville’s group
Person see, person do: human cortical electro-
(Sommerville et al., in press) are consistent physiological correlates of monkey see monkey
with this hypothesis, but more work is needed do cells [Abstract]. Society for Neuroscience,
to test the limits of this hypothesis. Further, we 719.
hypothesize that structure mapping processes Aschersleben, G., & Hohenberger, A. (2007).
play a role in the generalization of infants’ Does infant action interpretation predict later
action knowledge. If we are right, then the same theory of mind abilities? Paper presented
kinds of laboratory manipulations that have at the Meetings of the Jean Piaget Society,
been shown to influence older children’s gen- Amsterdam, The Netherlands.
eralization of relational information should Baird, J., & Baldwin, D. A. (2001). Making sense
of human behavior: Action parsing and inten-
influence infants’ responses to action structure.
tional inference. In B. F. Malle, L. J. Moses, & D.
Work currently underway in our laboratory is
A. Baldwin (Eds.), Intention and intentionality:
investigating each of these hypotheses. Foundations of social cognition. Cambridge,
Finally, our account predicts that the action MA: MIT Press.
representations derived in infancy contribute Baldwin, J. M. (1897). Social and ethical interpreta-
to the eventual emergence of folk concepts of tions in mental development: A study in social
mental states. Evidence in favor of this final psychology. New York: Macmillan.
310 FOUNDATIONS OF SOCIAL COGNITION

Baldwin, D. A., Baird, J. A., Saylor, M. M., & Clark, familiarity in action observation. Current
M. A. (2001). Infants parse dynamic action. Biology, 16, 1905–1910.
Child Development, 72, 708–717. Carpenter, M., Nagell, K., & Tomasello, M. (1998).
Baldwin, D. A., & Moses, L. J. (2001). Links Social cognition, joint attention, and commu-
between social understanding and early word nicative competence from 9 to 15 months of
learning: Challenges to current accounts. age. Monographs of the Society for Research in
Social Development, 10, 309–329. Child Development, 63, serial no. 255.
Barresi, J., & Moore, C. (1996) Intentional rela- Catmur, C., Walsh. V, & Heyes, C. (2007).
tions and social understanding. Behavioral and Sensorimotor learning configures the human
Brain Sciences, 19, 107–129. mirror system. Current Biology, 17, 1527–1531.
Bartch, K., & Wellman, H. M. (1995). Children talk Cochin, S., Barthelemy, C., Roux, S., & Martineau,
about the mind. New York: Oxford Press. J. (1999). Observation and execution of move-
Bates, E., Carlson-Luden, V., & Bretherton, I. ment: Similarities demonstrated by quantified
(1980). Perceptual aspects of tool using inin- electroencephalography. European Journal of
fancy. Infant Behavior and Development, 3, Neuroscience, 11, 1839–1842.
127–140. Csibra, G., & Southgate, V. (2006). Evidence for
Behne, T., Carpenter, M., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. infants’ understanding of false beliefs should
(2005) Unwilling versus unable: Infants’ under- not be dismissed. Trends in Cognitive Science,
standing of intentional action. Developmental 10, 4–5.
Psychology, 41, 328–337. Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L. Pavesi, G., & Rizzolatti, G.
Bertenthal, B., & Clifton, R. K. (1998). Perception (1995). Motor facilitation during action obser-
and action. In W. Damon, D. Kuhn, & R. vation: A magnetic stimulation study. Journal
Siegler (Eds.), Handbook of child psychol- of Neurophysiology, 73, 2608–2611.
ogy: Cognition, perception and language (pp. Falck-Ytter, T., Gredeback, G., & von Hofsten, C.
51–102). New York: Wiley. (2006). Infants predict other people’s action
Biro, S., & Leslie, A. M. (2006). Infants’ perception goals. Nature Neuroscience, 9, 878–879.
of goal-directed actions: development through Ferrari, P. F., Rozzi, S., & Fogassi, L. (2005). Mirror
cue-based bootstrapping. Developmental neurons responding to observation of actions
Science, 10, 379–398. made with tools in monkey ventral premotor
Blakemore, S. J., & Decety, J. (2001). From the per- cortex. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 17,
ception of action to the understanding of inten- 212–226.
tion. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 2, 561–567. Flanagan, J.R. & Johansson, R.S. (2003). Action
Brooks, R., & Meltzoff, A. N. (2002). The impor- plans used in action observation. Nature, 424,
tance of eyes: How infants interpret adult look- 769–771.
ing behavior. Developmental Psychology, 38, Fogassi, L., Ferrari, P. F., Gesierich, B., Rozzi, S.,
958–966. Chersi, F., & Rizzolatti, G. (2005). Parietal lobe:
Brune, C., & Woodward, A. L. (2007). Social cogni- From action organization to intention under-
tion and social responsiveness in 10-month-old standing. Science, 308, 662–667.
infants. Journal of Cognition and Development, Gallese, V., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., & Rizzolatti,
8,133–158. G. (1996). Action recognition in the premotor
Buccino, G., Binkofski, F., Fink, G. R., Fadiga, cortex. Brain, 119, 593–609.
L., Fogassi, L. et al. (2001). Action observa- Gallese, V., & Goldman, A. (1998). Mirror neurons
tion activates premotor and parietal areas in a and the simulation theory of mind reading.
somatotopic manner: an fMRI study. European Trends in Cognitive Science, 12, 493–501.
Journal of Neuroscience, 13, 400–404. Gangitano, M., Mottaghy, F. M., & Pascual-Leone,
Calvo-Merino, B., Glaser, D. E., Grezes, J., A. (2001). Phase-specific modulation of corti-
Passingham, R. E., & Haggard, P. (2005). cal motor output during movement observa-
Action observation and acquired motor skills: tion. NeuroReport, 12, 1489–1492.
An fMRI study with expert dancers. Cerebral Gentner, D. (1988). Metaphor as structure map-
Cortex, 15, 1243–1249. ping: the relational shift. Child Development,
Calvo-Merino, B., Grezes, J., Glaser, D. E., 59, 47–59.
Passingham, R. E., & Haggard, P. (2006). Gentner, D. (2003). Why we’re so smart. In
Seeing or doing? Influence of visual and motor D. Gentner & S. Goldin-Meadow (Eds.),
BUILDING INTENTIONAL ACTION KNOWLEDGE WITH ONE’S HANDS 311

Language in mind (pp. 195–236). Cambridge, Iacoboni, M., Molnar-Szakacs, I., Gallese, V.,
MA: MIT Press. Buccino, G., Mazziotta, J. C., & Rizzolatti, G.
Gentner, D., & Medina, J. (1998). Similarity and the (2005). Grasping the intentions of others with
development of rules. Cognition, 65, 263–297. one’s own mirror neuron system. PLoS Biology,
Gergely, G., & Csibra, G. (2003). Teleological rea- 3, 529–535.
soning in infancy: The one-year-olds’ naive Iacobani, M., Woods, R. P., Brass, M., Bekkering,
theory of rational action. Trends in Cognitive H., Mazziotta, J. C., & Rizzolatti, G. (1999).
Sciences, 7, 287–292. Cortical mechanisms of human imitation.
Gergely, G., Nadasdy, Z., Csibra, G., & Biro, S. Science, 286, 2526–2528.
(1995). Taking the intentional stance at 12 Jacob, P., & Jeannerod, M. (2005). The motor the-
months of age. Cognition, 56, 165–193. ory of social cognition: A critique. Trends in
Goldman, A. (1989). Interpretation psychologized. Cognitive Science, 9, 21–25.
Mind and Language 4, 161–185. Järveläinen, J., Schürmann, M., & Hari, R. (2004).
Gordon, R. M. (1986). Folk psychology as simula- Activation of the human primary motor cortex
tion. Mind and Language, 1, 158–171. during observation of tool use. NeuroImage,
Grafton, S. T., Arbib, M. A., Fadiga, L., & Rizzolatti, 23, 187–192.
G. (1996). Localization of grasp representa- Johnson, S. C., Ok, S., & Luo, Y. (2007). The attri-
tions in humans by PET: 2. Observation com- bution of attention: Nine-month-olds’ inter-
pared with imagination. Experimental Brain pretation of gaze as goal-directed action.
Research, 112, 102–111. Developmental Science, 10, 530–537.
Grezes, J., & Decety, J. (2001). Functional anatomy Kiraly, I., Jovanovic, B., Prinz, W., Aschersleben,
of execution, mental simulation, observation G., & Gergely, G. (2003). The early origins of
and verb generation of action: A meta-analysis. goal attribution in infancy. Consciousness &
Human Brain Mapping, 12, 1–19. Cognition, 12, 752–769.
Guajardo, J. J., & Woodward, A. L. (2004). Is agency Kirkham, N., Slemmer, J., & Johnson, S. (2002).
skin-deep? Surface attributes influence infants’ Visual statistical learning in infancy: Evidence
sensitivity to goal-directed action. Infancy , 6, for a domain general learning mechanism.
361–384. Cognition, 83, B35–B42.
Hamlin, J. K., Hallinan, E. V., & Woodward, A. L. Kotovsky, L., & Gentner, D. (1996). Comparison and
(2008). Do as I do: 7-month-old infants selec- categorization in the development of relational
tively reproduce others’ goals. Developmental similarity. Child Development, 67, 2797–2822.
Science, 11, 487–494. Kuhlmeier, V., Wynn, K., & Bloom, P. (2003).
Harris, P. (1989). Children and emotion. Oxford: Attribution of dispositional states by 12-month-
Blackwell Publishers. olds. Psychological Science, 14, 402–408.
Hauf, P., Aschersleben, G., & Prinz, W. (2007). Kuhlmeier, V., & Yamaguchi, M. (2007). How does
Baby do-baby see! How action produc- infants’ performance on goal-attribution tasks
tion influences action perception in infants. relate to other social-cognitive skills? Paper
Cognitive Development, 22, 16–32. Presented at the Meetings of the Jean Piaget
Hauf, P., Elsner, B., & Aschersleben, G. (2004). The Society, Amsterdam, The Netherlands.
role of action effects in infant’s action control. Lepage, J., & Theoret, H. (2007). The mirror neu-
Psychological Research, 68, 115–125. ron system: grasping others’ actions from
Heal, J. (1998). Co-cognition and off-line simula- birth? Developmental Science, 10, 513–529.
tion: Two ways of understanding the simulation Loewenstein, J., & Gentner, D. (2001). Spatial map-
approach. Mind and Language, 13, 477–498. ping in preschoolers: Close comparisons facil-
Heineman-Pieper, J., & Woodward, A. (2003). itate far mappings. Journal of Cognition and
Understanding infants’ understanding of Development, 2, 189–219.
intentions: Two problems of interpretation (A Luo, Y., & Baillargeon, R. (2007). Do 12.5-month-
reply to Kiraly et al., 2003). Consciousness and old infants consider what objects other see
Cognition, 12, 770–772. when interpreting their actions? Cognition,
Hommel, B., Musseler, J., Aschersleben, G., & Prinz, 105, 489–512.
W. (2001). The theory of event coding (TEC): A Mahajan, N., & Woodward, A. L. (2007). Imitation
framework for perception and action planning. of animate versus inanimate agents in seven-
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24, 849–937. month-old infants. Poster presentation at
312 FOUNDATIONS OF SOCIAL COGNITION

the biennial meetings of the Cognitive Rizzolatti, G., & Fadiga, L. (1998). Grasping
Development Society, Santa Fe, NM. objects and grasping action meanings: the dual
Meltzoff, A. N. (1995). Understanding the inten- role of the monkey rostroventral premotor cor-
tions of others: Re-enactment of intended acts tex (area F5). Novartis Foundation Symposium,
by 18-month-old children. Developmental 218, 81–95.
Psychology, 31, 1–16. Rizzolatti, G., Fogassi, L., & Gallese, V. (2001).
Meltzoff, A. N. (2005). Imitation and other minds: Neurophysiological mechanisms underlying
The “like me” hypothesis. In S. Hurley & N. the understanding and imitation of action.
Chater (Eds.), Perspectives on imitation: From Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 2, 661–670.
neuroscience to social science (pp. 55–77). Rochat, P. (1989). Object manipulation and explo-
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. ration in 2- to 5-month-olds. Developmental
Meltzoff, A. M. & Brooks, R. (2008). Self- Psychology, 25, 871–884.
experience as a mechanism for learning about Saff ran, J. R., Aslin, R. N., & Newport, E. L. (1996).
others: A training study in social cognition. Statistical learning by 8-month-old infants.
Developmental Psychology, 44, 1257–1265. Science, 274, 1926–1928.
Meltzoff, A. N., & Moore, M. K. (1989). Imitation Saxe, R. (2005). Against simulation: The argu-
in newborn infants: Exploring the range of ment from error. Trends in Cognitive Science,
gestures imitated and the underlying mecha- 9, 174–179.
nisms. Developmental Psychology, 25, 954–962. Shimada, S., & Hiraki, K. (2006). Infant’s
Moll, H., & Tomasello, M. (2004). 12- and brain responses to live and televised action.
18-month-old infants follow gaze to space Neuroimage, 32, 930–939.
behind barriers. Developmental Science, 7, Sodian, B., & Thoermer, C. (2004). Infants’ under-
F1–F9. standing of looking, pointing, and reach-
Muthukumaraswamy, S. D., Johnson, B. W., & ing as cues to goal-directed action. Journal of
McNair, N. A. (2004). Mu rhythm modulation Cognition & Development, 5, 289–316.
during observation of an object-directed grasp. Sommerville, J. A., Hildebrand, E. A., & Crane, C.
Cognitive Brain Research, 19, 195–201. C. (2008). Experience matters: The impact of
Onishi, K. H., & Baillargeon, R. (2005). Do doing versus watching on infants’ subsequent
15-month-old infants understand false beliefs? perception of tool use events. Developmental
Science, 308, 255–258. Psychology, 44, 1249–1256.
Phillips, A. T., Wellman, H. M., & Spelke, E. S. Sommerville, J. A., & Woodward, A. L. (2005).
(2002). Infants’ ability to connect gaze and Pulling out the intentional structure of action:
emotional expression to intentional action. The relation between action processing and
Cognition, 85, 53–78. action production in infancy. Cognition, 95,
Pineda, J. A., Allison, B. Z., & Vankov, A. (2000). 1– 30.
The effects of self-movement, observation, Sommerville, J. A., & Woodward, A. L. (in press).
and imagination on mu rhythms and readi- The link between action production and
ness potentials (RP’s): toward a brain-com- action processing in infancy. In F. Grammont,
puter interface (BCI). IEEE Transactions on D. Legrand, & P. Livet (Eds.), Naturalizing
Rehabilitation Engineering, 8, 219–222. intention in action.
Poulin-Dubois, D., & Olineck, K. M. (2007). From Sommerville, J. A., Woodward, A. L., &
intention-in-action to intention-in the mind: Needham, A. (2005). Action experience alters
Infants’ goal detection and intentional imita- 3-month-old infants’ perception of others’
tion predict later theory of mind. Presentation actions. Cognition, 96, B1–B11.
Presented at the Meetings of the Jean Piaget Southgate, V., Senju, A., & Csibra, G. (2007).
Society, Amsterdam, The Netherlands. Action anticipation through attribution of false
Piaget, J. (1953). The origins of intelligence in the belief by 2-year-olds. Psychological Science, 18,
child. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. 587–192.
Rizzolatti, G., & Arbib, M. A. (1998). Language Surian, L., Caldi, S., & Sperber, D. (2007).
within our grasp. Trends in Neuroscience, 21, Attribution of beliefs by 13-month-old infants.
188–194. Psychological Science, 18, 580–586.
BUILDING INTENTIONAL ACTION KNOWLEDGE WITH ONE’S HANDS 313

Tomasello, M. (1999). The cultural origins of behaviors. Infant Behavior and Development,
human cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard 22, 145–160.
University Press. Woodward, A. L. (2003). Infants’ developing
Tomasello, M., & Haberl, K. (2003). Understanding understanding of the link between looker and
attention: 12- and 18-month-olds understand object. Developmental Science, 6, 297–311.
what is new for other persons. Developmental Woodward, A. L. (2005). The infant origins
Psychology, 39, 906–912. of intentional understanding. In R. V. Kail
Wellman, H. M. (1990). The child’s theory of mind. (Ed.), Advances in child development and
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. behavior (Vol. 33, pp. 229–262). Oxford:
Wellman, H. M., Phillips, A. T., Dunphy-Lelii, S., Elsevier.
& Lalonde, N. (2004). Infant understanding of Woodward, A. L., & Guajardo, J. J. (2002). Infants’
persons predicts preschool social cognition. understanding of the point gesture as an
Developmental Science, 7, 283– 288. object-directed action. Cognitive Development,
Woodward, A. L. (1998). Infants selectively encode 17, 1061–1084.
the goal object of an actor’s reach. Cognition, Woodward, A. L., & Sommerville, J. A. (2000).
69, 1–34. Twelve-month-old infants interpret action in
Woodward, A. L. (1999). Infants’ ability to distin- context. Psychological Science, 11, 73–76.
guish between purposeful and non-purposeful
CHAP TER 16
A Neoconstructivistic Approach to the Emergence
of a Face Processing System

Francesca Simion and Irene Leo

INTRODUCTION TO THE view asserts that humans are born either with
NEOCONSTRUCTIVISTIC APPROACH the innate capacity to develop information pro-
cessing systems or “cognitive modules” that
Developmental theories have been dominated allow them to make sense of the world, or that
by two different views both on the origin of learning is guided by innately specified and
knowledge and on the initial mechanisms that content-specific principles that determine the
form the basis for cognitive development. On entities on which subsequent learning takes
one view, knowledge emerges on the basis of place (e.g., Gelman, 1990; Spelke, 1991).
domain-general mechanisms of learning that In this perspective, deeply influenced by
are sufficient to explain how children learn Chomskyan linguistics (1988) and by Fodor’s
about specific domains of knowledge such as modularity theory (1983), the infant comes into
language, number, space, or faces. Although the world well prepared to process different
Piagetian, behaviorist, and more recently con- domains of knowledge. For example, the infant
nectionist theories fall within this view, Piaget’s comes preprepared for processing faces, lan-
position, known as “epigenetic constructivism,” guage, space, and number, each in very different
differs because cognitive development is consid- ways. Accordingly, cognition would be special-
ered as the outcome of a self-organizing system ized from the outset in processing content-spe-
that is structured and shaped by its interaction cific inputs able to mediate complex cognitive
with the environment. functions (e.g., Spelke, 1991; Wynn, 1995). This
On the competing view, the early appearance approach seems to preclude the “epigenetic con-
of abilities hitherto unsuspected has supported structivist principle” to development because
the notion that knowledge begins early in life biological forms are not considered as a product
and constitutes parts of humans’ innate endow- of any dynamic interactions between the genes
ment. Some authors maintain that human cog- and the environment.
nition is built on domain-specific system of The dichotomy between general and specific
knowledge and that natural selection may have innate mechanisms as determinants of cogni-
favored the evolution of mechanisms that give tive development has been overcome by the
rise to this knowledge (e.g., Kellman, 1993). neoconstructivistic approach to cognition that
More specifically, the human mind is consid- combines these two different explanations and
ered to be a collection of special purpose mech- states that nativism and epigenetic principles
anisms, each shaped, through adaptation to the are not incompatible because it can be assumed
environment during the course of evolution, to the existence of some innate specified predispo-
perform a particular function. This nativistic sitions that would give the epigenetic process a

314
A NEOCONSTRUCTIVISTIC APPROACH 315

head start in each domain of knowledge. Such Within this theoretical framework, the notion
predispositions are supposed not to be knowl- of innate constraints are described as architec-
edge-impregnated and content-specific but tural, computational, and temporal biases that
instead are presumed to be less detailed specifi- shape information processing, limiting the types
cations that some nativists presuppose. Indeed, of input to be selected and constraining the com-
in the neoconstructivism approach, the cogni- putations on the input. Consequently, the word
tive activity is seen as emerging gradually as a “constraints” does not carry on any negative con-
product of the interaction between innate con- notation, but rather, it possesses a positive con-
straints and the structure of the input provided notation. In fact, constraints are defined as biases
by the species-typical environment (de Schonen, in the information processing due to the prop-
2002; Elman et al., 1996; Johnson, 1993; Michel erties of the brain architecture or of the percep-
& Moore, 1995; Nelson & Luciana, 2001). More tual systems in a given period of development.
specifically, this theoretical perspective sug- Benefits from these biases consist in selectively
gests that the specific cognitive systems are the focusing the cognitive system toward certain
product of a “process of modularization”; that is aspects of the surrounding environment or facil-
to say, the modular architecture is the result of a itating processing of certain kinds of inputs,
gradual development rather than being innately thus strengthening learning of some categories
specified. The modules are not hardwired nor of of stimuli rather than others, and, consequently,
fi xed neural architecture; they are the outcome tuning the system to become specialized.
of a continuous process that emerges through To summarize, in contrast to the clas-
the dynamic of a probabilistic epigenesis that sic nativist/modular thesis that considers the
progressively leads to an increasing functional infant brain as provided with built-in specific
specialization of neural circuits (Bates & Elman, representational contents, the neoconstructiv-
1993; Johnson, 1997; Karmiloff-Smith, 1992). istic approach stresses the role of a number of
Consequently, brain specialization, domain innately specified constraints or biases in the
specificity, and cognitive modules rather than emergence of representations and thus in the
being assumed as genetically prespecified are origins of knowledge. There is the idea that
considered to emerge epigenetically and devel- specific cognitive structures may arise from
opmentally through the interaction with post- primary, general innate constraints shaped by
natal environment. Evolution have prespecified the nature of the experience the organism is
many innate biological constraints on devel- exposed to (Karmiloff-Smith, 1992).
opment that are domain-general mechanisms Brain development is viewed in terms of an
becoming “domain-specific” with the process of increasing restriction of the fate of component
development. During this process, the same gen- elements, such as neurons and neural circuits.
eral mechanisms have been used repeatedly to In other words, as development proceeds, neu-
process a certain class of stimuli and in so doing rons and cortical circuitry become increasingly
they become specific. Some apparent constraints specialized, dedicated to particular functions
contribute to the development of new struc- and less capable of change. The cerebral cortex
tures and new modes of functioning, which will does not appear to contain intrinsic prespeci-
be advantageous at later stages of development fied representations to support functions such
(Karmiloff-Smith, 1992) and provide starting as face recognition or linguistic processing.
points that channel the subsequent perceptual Rather, the appropriate representations emerge
and cognitive development (e.g., Turkewitz & through the constraints of the complex corti-
Kenny, 1982). For instance, it has been proposed cal and subcortical networks and through the
that the constraints imposed by the development interaction between the infant and the sta-
of the sensory systems may actually facilitate sub- tistical regularities latent in its environment.
sequent perceptual development by reducing the Endogenous constraints select the successive
range of stimuli that the infant has to deal with. aspect of the environment to which paying
316 FOUNDATIONS OF SOCIAL COGNITION

attention and, interacting with the structure of they contribute to guide and shape cognitive
the input typical of the infant’s environment, activity.
guide and shape the gradual emerging of spe- In order to address these issues, a peculiar
cialized processing (Werker & Vouloumanos, class of visual stimuli, namely faces, will be
2001). Domain-specific cognitive activity is, taken into consideration because faces form
therefore, strictly linked to the exposure to a special class of visual objects elaborated in
certain experiences, i.e., activity-dependent adults by a specific face system. The first part of
(Greenough & Black, 1992). Experience appears the chapter focuses on the mechanisms under-
to play a prominent role in recruiting the cor- lying infants’ visual preference for faces and
tical areas potentially suited to be activated by on the visuoperceptual constraints that induce
certain stimuli. The activation of these cortical newborns to prefer faces.
and functional networks leads as a consequence The second part of the chapter will review
to a process of a progressive specialization that the studies on the nature of the information
emerges on condition that the critical type of newborns actually process and encode when
input is provided within the sensitive time win- they look at faces as compared to nonface stim-
dow and, in this sense, is activity-expectant uli, more specifically, whether the recognition of
(Nelson 2001, 2003). For instance, it has been faces at birth requires the same nonspecific gen-
demonstrated that deprivation of early visual eralized perceptual abilities that are involved in
input due to bilateral congenital cataract in the processing all types of visual stimuli.
first months of life impairs face processing, even
years after surgery (e.g., Le Grand, Mondloch,
MECHANISMS UNDERLYING FACE
Maurer, & Brent, 2003). This suggests that the
PREFERENCE AT BIRTH
normal visual experience is a necessary condi-
tion to develop an expert face processing system Evidence from behavioral, brain lesion, and
(e.g., Geldart, Mondloch, Maurer, de Schonen, neuroimaging studies suggests that in adults
& Brent, 2002; Le Grand et al., 2003). face processing involves distinct, domain-spe-
The fact that some perceptual and/or atten- cific perceptual processing (Maurer, Le Grand,
tional biases toward certain characteristics of & Mondloch, 2002; Schwaninger, Carbon, &
sensory information enhance learning pro- Leder, 2003) carried out by dedicated brain
cesses weakens the classical contraposition areas (e.g., Farah, Rabinowitz, Quinn, & Liu,
between nature and nurture, because innate 2000; Kanwisher, 2000). The functional and
predispositions are not stable and unchangeable neural specialization present in the adult face
and are not distinct and separated from learned processing system renders faces an ideal class
behaviors. On the contrary, innate predisposi- of stimuli in order to investigate the time
tions represent the necessary conditions to con- course and the factors affecting such special-
strain and to determine learning itself (Elman ization. Some authors claim the existence of a
et al., 1996). specialized system for face processing already
In light of this theoretical framework, since at birth (experience-independent; e.g., Farah
development cannot be explained in terms of et al., 2000), while others raise the possibility
innate, built-in representational contents, it that such specialization is a product of experi-
becomes relevant for developmental researchers ence (experience-dependent; e.g., Gauthier &
to investigate what types of general perceptual Logothetis, 2000; Gauthier & Tarr, 1997, 2002),
constrains and attentional biases are present in so developmental studies carried out with new-
the first months of life and how they contribute borns become critical to disentangle this issue.
to the specialization of the cognitive system. The preference discovered in the first days of life
The general goal of this chapter is to examine to orient to and attend at faces has been inter-
(1) whether some constraints or prewired atten- preted as supporting the existence of an innate,
tional biases are present at birth; (2) if these content-specific mechanism for face processing
constraints are general or specific, and (3) how in the human system. When presented with
A NEOCONSTRUCTIVISTIC APPROACH 317

face-like and nonface-like patterns, newborns visual window—the CSF—better than the pat-
spontaneously look longer at and orient more tern with which it is paired. Basically, the LSM
frequently toward the configuration that rep- claims that newborns’ preferences for visual
resents a face (e.g., Johnson & Morton, 1991; patterns are determined solely by their visibility.
Valenza, Simion, Macchi Cassia, & Umiltà, Faces would not be different from other visual
1996). Face preference at birth has been dem- stimuli that are preferred simply because they
onstrated with both static and moving stimuli possess more appropriate sensory properties.
(Easterbrook, Kisilevsky, Muir, & Laplante, This hypothesis succeeded in explaining
1999; Goren, Sarty, & Wu, 1975; Kleiner, 1987; preferences for a variety of visual configurations
Macchi Cassia, Simion, & Umiltà, 2001), and but failed to entirely account for newborns’
with both schematic and veridical images of preference for face-like patterns (Valenza et al.,
faces (Johnson & Morton, 1991; Macchi Cassia, 1996). In fact, empirical evidence demonstrated
Turati, & Simion, 2004; Valenza et al., 1996). that newborns still prefer a face-like pattern
However, a matter of dispute concerns the even when it is contrasted to a stimulus of equal
mechanisms underlying face preference at birth (Johnson, Dziurawiec, Ellis, & Morton, 1991;
because the presence of such a preference could Kleiner, 1987) or greater (Valenza et al., 1996)
be due to either the existence of general biases visibility.
or a content-specific mechanism. The second hypothesis, named the “struc-
Three different hypotheses have been pro- tural hypothesis” (Johnson & Morton, 1991;
posed to explain newborns’ preference for faces. Morton & Johnson, 1991), maintains that faces
The first, named the “sensory hypothesis,” are special for the newborn because human
maintains that faces are not different from other infants possess a device (i.e., Conspec), which
visual stimuli and that certain classes of stim- contains structural information concerning the
uli are preferred by newborns as a result of the visual characteristics of conspecifics. In partic-
general properties of the early stages of visual ular, this information would be concerned with
processing. the relative spatial location of elements within
This hypothesis is based on the predictions the pattern, like three high-contrast blobs in the
of the linear system model (LSM) (e.g., Banks & correct relative locations for the eyes and mouth
Salapatek, 1981; Kleiner, 1987; Kleiner & Banks, on a stimulus of about the right size. Recently,
1987). Any two-dimensional, achromatic pat- this model of the development of face process-
tern can be described on the basis of the spatial ing has been revised and updated. Johnson
frequencies, amplitude (contrast), orientation, (2005) maintains that newborns’ face preference
and phase of its constituent sine wave gratings. is due to the existence of a “low-spatial-frequen-
For any pattern, two functions may be derived: cies face-configuration detector” supported
the amplitude spectrum, comprising the ampli- by a fast subcortical route. The existence of a
tude and orientation of the component spatial content-specific template, i.e., “a face detector,”
frequencies; and the phase spectrum, compris- allows the human visual system to detect faces
ing the phase and orientation of the compo- and explains the specific bias toward faces pre-
nents. The LSM holds that the attractiveness of sent at birth (Johnson, 2005). The face detector
a pattern is determined solely by the amount of (Conspec in the original Morten & Johnson
effective energy of that pattern. The amplitude model) is responsible only for face detection
spectrum of the pattern is fi ltered through the and triggers attention toward faces, because it
contrast sensitivity function (CSF) of the sub- is a very specialized orienting mechanism. At
ject. Each age has an appropriate CSF, so in around 2 months of age, a second cortical mech-
newborns CSF removes all information at fre- anism, Conlearn, that benefits from experience
quencies greater than 2 cycles per degree (c/d). with faces, replaces Conspec, whose function is
In a choice situation, newborns’ visual prefer- essentially to “set” Conlearn.
ences are for those stimuli that provide spatial An alternative account of face prefer-
frequency and contrast information that fit the ence in newborns proposed that the visual
318 FOUNDATIONS OF SOCIAL COGNITION

preference for faces at birth reflects a preference & Rose, 1985; Slater & Sykes, 1977). These data
for a collection of general structural proper- suggest that the structural configuration of a
ties, including both the low-level components pattern is a crucial factor in determining new-
such as the contrast and the spatial frequen- borns’ preference for geometrical stimuli as well
cies content and the higher level components as for faces.
such as the structural properties of a stimulus To test whether face preference could be
described by the phase spectrum according to a explained either on the basis of some general
Fourier analysis (e.g., Macchi Cassia et al., 2004; structural properties that other stimuli may
Simion, Macchi Cassia, Turati, & Valenza, 2001, share with faces or by specific mechanisms, two
2003; Simion, Valenza, Macchi Cassia, Turati, & series of experiments were carried out in our
Umiltà, 2002). laboratory. In the first series of experiments, we
This hypothesis maintains that the human tested the presence of general, noncontent-spe-
visual system possesses some general predis- cific attentional biases toward some structural
positions toward certain general properties properties as determinants of face preferences.
embodied in a face and that the preference for In the second series of experiments, we con-
faces present since birth is in fact a preference trasted the hypothesis supporting the existence
for a collection of general properties. Each of a specific mechanism with the hypothesis sup-
single property present in a face such as sym- porting the existence of general mechanisms.
metry along the vertical axis, the presence of The rationale of the first series of experi-
more elements in the upper part, the congruent ments was that if we were able to demonstrate
distributions of the inner elements according that some nonspecific structural properties can
to the shape of the contour, could trigger new- engage attention with stimuli other than faces
borns’ attention and in so doing determine face and that these structural properties are the
preference. same as those present in a face, then it may be
To summarize this third hypothesis is in line concluded that these structural properties could
with the neoconstructivistic approach to cogni- explain face preference at birth.
tion and is consistent with both the existence Two general structural properties present in
of a more domain-general system responsive a face were tested in our laboratory: congruency
to general properties of the stimuli and with and the top-down asymmetry in the disposition
the presence of a limited number of innately of the elements in the upper part.
specified domain-general predispositions that Congruency was defined by the presence
only with time and experience would activate of a congruent or corresponding relation-
specific circuits and specific computations in ship between the shape and orientation of the
response to domain-specific inputs. The pres- bounded area, delimiting the pattern and the
ence of general, nonspecific constraints on spatial disposition of the included features.
visual processing might be sufficient to pro- Faces can be described as a congruent stimu-
duce the emergence of the functional speciali- lus in that they typically display a greater num-
zation for faces observed later in development ber of features (the eyes), in the widest, upper
through the process of modularization. The evi- portion of the face outline and only one feature
dence that supports the idea that faces may be (the mouth) in the narrowest bottom part. By
perceived at birth by general mechanisms that the use of geometrical stimulus (both triangles
can also operate on nonface stimuli is mainly and trapezoids), it has been shown that when a
grounded in evidence suggesting that faces are congruent and a noncongruent disposition of
not the only class of stimuli that can trigger the elements within a pattern were compared,
newborns’ attention and induce a preference. newborns show a significant tendency to pre-
For example, when horizontal gratings were fer the configuration that displays a congruent
paired with vertical gratings, newborns pre- spatial disposition of the elements (Figure 16.1).
ferred the horizontal ones (Farroni, Valenza, Evidence revealed that when embedded in geo-
Simion, & Umiltà, 2000; Slater, Earle, Morison, metric nonface-like stimuli, the congruency
A NEOCONSTRUCTIVISTIC APPROACH 319

The same results were replicated with


face-like stimuli and with real faces in which we
disrupted the geometry of the face. The upright
stimuli with two blobs randomly located in the
Panel A upper part of the configuration were always
preferred over the upside-down stimuli (e.g.,
Simion et al., 2003; Turati et al., 2002). The evi-
dence in all of these experiments was in favor
of the existence of an attentional bias toward
up-down asymmetrical patterns, because in
all the experiments, a pattern was always pre-
ferred when its more salient part was the upper
one (Figure 16.2). Given that faces are up-down
Panel B asymmetrical stimuli, we hypothesized that
the preference for faces at birth could be due to
the presence of such a general property in the
stimulus.
After this first step, a second series of experi-
ments was carried out to contrast the two mod-
els that explain face preference as due to general
Figure 16.1 The geometric patterns used in
or specific mechanisms. The model support-
Macchi Cassia et al. (2008). Panel A: The con-
gruent and noncongruent nonface-like patterns. ing the existence of a specific built-in mecha-
Panel B: The congruent and noncongruent face- nism, i.e., Conspec in Johnson’s terminology
like patterns. (Johnson & Morton, 1991) predicts that new-
borns are sensitive to face geometry, that is to
the correct disposition of the elements within a
property is capable of inducing a preferential face or, according to the up to date model, to the
response, which was not overcome by the pref- correct disposition of the eyes (Johnson, 2005).
erence for the face-like arrangement of the inner In contrast, our model supporting the existence
elements (Macchi Cassia, Valenza, Simion, & of general biases toward up-down asymmetrical
Leo, 2008). patterns predicts that the number of elements
The second property, tested with geometrical in the upper part is crucial in determining face
stimuli in a visual preference task, was the pres- preference (Simion et al., 2001, 2003). To test
ence of more elements in the upper part, i.e. the the opposite predictions of these two mod-
up-down asymmetry in the distribution of the els, we disrupted the geometry of the face by
elements (Simion et al., 2002; Turati, Simion, manipulating the location of the three elements
Milani, & Umiltà, 2002). Three groups of new- and this stimulus was contrasted with a face-
borns were presented with three different pairs like stimulus with a natural disposition of the
of stimuli, each composed of an upright geo- internal elements. Results showed that when a
metrical configuration, with a greater number face-like stimulus or real face were contrasted
of high-contrast areas in the upper part, and an with a nonface stimulus, paired for the num-
upside-down configuration with more elements ber of elements in the upper part, no preference
in the lower part (Simion et al., 2002; Turati for the stimuli with a natural disposition of the
et al., 2002). Results were clear in showing that inner elements was obtained, either for the face-
at birth there is a preference for up-down asym- like stimulus or for the real face (Figure 16.3).
metrical patterns with more elements in the Even more interesting were the results showing
upper part because newborns both orient more that when either a face-like or a real face were
frequently to and look longer at the upright con- contrasted with a stimulus with more elements
figurations (Simion et al., 2002). in the upper part, newborns prefer the pattern
320 FOUNDATIONS OF SOCIAL COGNITION

Figure 16.2 Stimuli used to test the preference for up-down asymmetrical patterns (Macchi Cassia
et al., 2004; Simion et al., 2002; Turati et al., 2002).

Figure 16.3 Schematic head shaped configurations and real faces used to test the role of a specific mech-
anism versus the existence of general attentional biases (Macchi Cassia et al., 2004; Turati et al., 2002).

with more elements in the upper part (e.g., explained by the result of the cumulative effect
Simion et al., 2003; Turati et al., 2002). of this set of noncontent-specific biases toward
Overall, since newborns’ visual behavior some psychophysical properties of the stimuli
was affected by the up-down arrangement of that best match the characteristics of the human
the inner features and by congruency indepen- visuoperceptual system rather than by the exis-
dently of whether such arrangement was or not tence of a specific face detector.
face-like, these findings strongly support the The effect of the up-down asymmetry on
hypothesis on the existence of general atten- newborns’ preference, for instance, might be
tional biases toward structural properties of derived from endogenous constraints that
the stimuli. Preference for faces at birth may be characterize their visual system. Specifically,
A NEOCONSTRUCTIVISTIC APPROACH 321

we have proposed that newborns may find In this same vein, Nelson (2001) suggests
top-heavy patterns more easily detectable than that the development of face processing is
other stimuli because of the existence at birth an experience-expectant process that, with
of an upper-visual-field advantage in visual sen- increasing exposure to faces, produces a “per-
sitivity (e.g., Simion et al., 2002; Turati et al., ceptual narrowing” to this class of stimuli,
2002). Indeed, in several species, a major role with a consequent increase in the selectiv-
in visual exploration of the upper visual field ity of infants’ behavioral responses to human
is played by the superior colliculus (Sprague, faces (e.g., Pascalis, de Haan, & Nelson, 2002).
Berlucchi, & Rizzolati, 1973), which is supposed Some of the strongest evidence supporting this
to affect considerably newborns’ visual behav- account comes from behavioral studies that
ior (Atkinson, Hood, Wattam-Bell, & Braddick, showed a perceptual narrowing to the stimuli
1992; Braddick et al., 1992; Bronson, 1982; most consistently present in the individual-
Johnson, 1995). Some computational models specific environment, as speech sound and faces
support a similar interpretation based on the (e.g., Cheour et al., 1998; Kelly et al., 2005; Kuhl
constraints on the newborns’ visual system and et al., 1992; Pascalis et al., 2002).
on the properties of the neurons in area V1 (e.g.,
Acerra, Burnod, & de Schonen, 2002).
FROM GENERAL TO SPECIFIC CONSTRAINTS
Overall, the results obtained in our labora-
tory support the idea that faces at birth are per- The presence at birth of general perceptual
ceived by domain-general mechanisms that can biases on visual processing seems sufficient to
also operate on nonface stimuli such as geomet- cause the human face to be a frequent focus of
rical figures. Face preference is in fact a prefer- newborns’ visual attention, allowing, through
ence for some general bottom-level properties experience, the gradual development of a face
and higher-level configurational properties that processing system. Based on the evidence pro-
faces share with other visual stimuli. vided by the studies with newborns reviewed
In other words, we maintain that the visuo- above, we investigate whether and how infants’
perceptual system allows newborns to perceive preferential response to faces becomes spe-
not only the psychophysical low-level infor- cific for this stimulus category during the first
mation embedded in a stimulus (i.e., spatial months of life.
frequency and contrast that determines its vis- Behavioral studies suggest that in 3-month-
ibility), but also the higher-level structural and old infants, preferential responses to faces
configural properties. Newborns are sensitive become more specific to the face category (e.g.,
to some general configural/structural proper- Bar-Haim, Ziv, Lamy, & Hodes, 2006; Kelly et al.,
ties of the stimuli so the preference for faces is 2007; Kelly et al., 2005). Neuropsychological
in fact a preference for such general properties. studies either with scalp-recorded brain electric
To conclude, the evidence presented in this potentials (event-related potential, ERP) (Halit,
first part is in line with a neoconstructivist view deHaan, & Johnson, 2003) or performed with
that maintains that the adult-specific face sys- positron emission topography (PET) (Tzourio-
tem arises from innate general predispositions Mazoyer et al., 2002) support the conclusion
that tune the system toward certain aspects that the first signs of cortical specialization for
of the external environment, and through faces can be observed in infants of 2–3 months
experience, neural and functional specialized of age.
processes develop. We argue that the face pro- The question driving our behavioral studies
cessing system to develop in its adult-like expert was to verify whether the same general biases
form might not require a highly specific tem- that induce face preference at birth still oper-
plate (i.e., a face-detector) but rather, a number ate and explain face preference 3 months later.
of general biases that work together to provide More specifically, we tested whether the general
the minimal information that would be suffi- structural property such as up-down asym-
cient to bootstrap the system. metry that induces face preference at birth
322 FOUNDATIONS OF SOCIAL COGNITION

still operates at 3 months of age when a certain up-down asymmetry in the distribution of the
degree of cortical specialization for faces begins inner features can not longer be considered as
to emerge (e.g., Halit et al., 2003; Tzourio- a crucial factor able to induce infants’ prefer-
Mazoyer et al., 2002). ence for a face (Simion, Turati, Valenza, & Leo,
The results from a first experiment showed 2006).
that when contrasting photographs of real faces These findings suggest that the bias toward
in the canonical upright orientation with the up-down asymmetric stimuli at birth acts as an
upside-down version, 3-month-old infants show early facilitating factor that leads to an increased
a visual preference for the upright face (Turati, specialization for faces later in development and
Valenza, Leo & Simion, 2005). contradicts the hypothesis that similar general
After having observed a face preference in constraints mediate face preference during
3-month-old infants, we investigated whether infancy (Simion et al., 2006).
the same bias present at birth toward up-down Recent evidence from an adult fMRI study
asymmetrical nonface patterns was still present supports this conclusion by showing enhanced
3 months later (Turati et al., 2005). To test this activation in cortical regions involved in face
hypothesis, the same experiments with geomet- processing (the right fusiform face area, rFFA)
rical figures carried out with newborns (Simion in response to nonface-like top-heavy stimuli
et al., 2002) were replicated with 3-month-old (Caldara et al., 2006). In line with this claim,
infants. Results indicated that the responses of adult ERPs revealed that manipulation of the
3-month-olds varied as a function of the two up-down arrangement of the features within
different types of up-down asymmetrical stim- scrambled faces modulated the response prop-
uli that were presented. erties of the N170 (Macchi Cassia, Kuefner,
When infants were shown elements orga- Westerlund, & Nelson, 2006). Together these
nized into a T, their visual behavior appeared findings demonstrated that the adult face pro-
to be radically different from that exhibited cessing system still shows sensitivity to the up-
by newborns (Simion et al., 2002), in that the down asymmetry and that this property seems
visual preference for the top-heavy upright T to play a crucial role in the development of the
disappeared when contrasted with an inverted face system.
T. However, when the other type of stimuli, Overall the developmental data support the
with four elements in the upper or lower half of notion that different mechanisms underlie face
the configuration, was considered, a different preference at birth and in 3-month-old infants.
pattern of results emerged: that is, 3-month- Face preference in newborns can be explained
olds’ behavior paralleled that shown by new- by general attentional biases toward sensory and
borns with the top-heavy configuration being structural properties of these stimuli. On the con-
preferred over the bottom-heavy configura- trary, the same general mechanisms still active
tion. These results suggest that, in 3-month- cannot explain face preference 3 months later.
old infants, the determinants of preference for Consistent with the neoconstructivist
nonface top-heavy patterns are still active but approach to cognition, our results demonstrate
are less powerful than in newborns. Th is weak that, likely by virtue of the prolonged exposure
preference for up-down asymmetrical pat- to human faces, the mechanisms responsible for
terns suggests that the bias toward up-down infant’s face preference shift from being broadly
asymmetry might still be present but cannot tuned to a wide range of visual stimuli to being
be the sole factor in determining 3-month- increasingly tuned to the human face (Nelson,
olds’ preference for faces (Turati et al., 2005). 2001).
To test this possibility, we directly compared
a natural face and a top heavy scrambled face
FACE RECOGNITION
with more elements in the upper part. Results
showed that 3-month-old infants always pre- The current developmental models on face pro-
fer the real face, demonstrating that at this age cessing diverge as for either the nature of the
A NEOCONSTRUCTIVISTIC APPROACH 323

mechanisms that attract newborns toward faces the basic arrangement of its features with two
or the existence of special processes to discrimi- eyes above a nose, which is above a mouth; (2)
nate and recognize individual faces at birth and holistic processing, integrating facial features
during the course of development. into a whole, thus rendering individual features
In adults, the behavioral signatures of face- less accessible; (3) sensitivity to second-order
specific processing derive from three specific relations, encoding of the spacing among facial
effects present with faces unlike with other features. Previous research has shown that
objects: the inversion effect (e.g., Yin, 1969), the adults process all of these three types of con-
part-whole effect (e.g., Tanaka & Farah, 1993), figural information (e.g., Tanaka & Farah, 1993;
and the composite effect (e.g., Young, Hellawell, Searcy & Bartlett, 1996) and that they are able to
& Hay, 1987). identify faces using both featural and configural
The “inversion effect” is a decrement in per- information (e.g., Carey & Diamond, 1977; Freire
formance that occurs when stimuli are inverted & Lee, 2001; Maurer et al., 2002). These behav-
(i.e., turned upside-down) and is greater for faces ioral data were explained either on the basis of
as compared with other classes of familiar and the existence of special-purpose, domain-spe-
complex objects, such as houses, airplanes, etc. cific mechanism selectively activated by faces
(e.g., Valentine, 1988; Yin, 1969). When faces are (i.e., the face specific hypothesis) (e.g., Farah
inverted, adults continue to be able to use fea- et al., 2000), or on the basis of domain-general
tural information (such as the eyes, mouth, nose mechanisms involved in processing not only
or ears) nearly as well, but are impaired in their faces but all the stimuli that require a high level
ability to use configural information (such as the of expertise and task-specific processes (i.e.,
spatial interrelationship of facial features) (e.g., a process specific hypothesis) (e.g., Gauthier,
Bartlett & Searcy, 1993; Leder & Bruce, 2000). William, Tarr, & Tanaka, 1998).
The second behavioral marker is the “part- This latter hypothesis seems to be consistent
whole effect” in which adults are more accurate with a neoconstructivistic approach to cogni-
in recognizing the identity of a feature (e.g., tion because it maintains that by virtue of the
nose) when it is presented in the context of the prolonged experience with faces and due to the
whole face rather than as an isolated features fine-grained discrimination necessary to pro-
(e.g., Tanaka & Farah, 1993). Houses, scrambled cess faces, the neural networks should become
faces, and inverted faces did not produce this specialized not only for faces but for all the
whole/part advantage, suggesting that these stimuli that share the same perceptual level of
types of stimuli are instead recognized on the expertise (expertise hypothesis; e.g., Gauthier,
basis of featural information. Tarr, Anderson, Skudlarski, & Gore, 1999).
In the “composite effect,” subjects are slower The following section of the present chapter
to identify one half of the chimeric face if it is focuses on newborns’ ability to recognize indi-
aligned with consistent other-face than if the vidual faces and on the information newborns
two half-faces are misaligned (e.g., Young et al., actually process and encode when they discrim-
1987). This phenomenon demonstrates that inate, learn, and recognize individual faces.
when upright faces are processed, the facial fea- More specifically, our focus is to investigate
tures are so strongly integrated that it becomes the nature of the operations that are utilized to
difficult to parse the face into isolated features process faces and whether such operations are
(e.g., Hole, 1994). exclusively involved in face processing at birth.
Taken together, these effects suggest that
upright faces are processed in a distinctive
WHAT KIND OF VISUAL INFORMATION
configural manner than processing each of the
NEWBORNS PROCESS AND ENCODE WHEN
parts of the face independently.
THEY RECOGNIZE A FACE?
According to Maurer et al., (2002), config-
ural processing can be divided into three types: The literature is consistent in showing that new-
(1) sensitivity to first-order relations, that is to borns can recognize individual faces despite
324 FOUNDATIONS OF SOCIAL COGNITION

limited visual abilities. There is considerable cannot be considered definitive. We have


evidence of an ability to discriminate among shown, in three different sets of experiments,
faces and recognize an individual face within a that newborns are able to process the internal
very short time after birth (e.g., Bushnell, 2001; information contained on both face and non-
Pascalis, de Schonen, Morton, Deruelle & Fabre- face stimuli. To be specific, the first set of exper-
Grenet, 1995; Walton, Bower & Bower, 1992). iments was carried out to investigate newborns’
The mother’s face is recognized and preferred ability to discriminate, recognize, and learn
over a female stranger’s face within hours from inner visual information embedded in the face-
birth (Bushnell, 2001; Bushnell, Sai, & Mullin, like and nonface-like configurations that dif-
1989; Pascalis et al., 1995). The ability to dis- fer in the shape of the inner elements (Simion,
criminate the mother from a stranger is present Farroni, Macchi Cassia, Turati, & Dalla Barba,
also when the task requires memory processes. 2002).
Using a visual preference technique, Bushnell The results demonstrate that newborns dis-
(2001) demonstrated that newborns still rec- criminated between two schematic face-like
ognize and prefer their mother’s face after a and nonface-like configurations that differed
separation of 15 min. This study suggests that exclusively in the shape of the internal local
memory for the mother’s face is established in a elements. Hence, learning processes with well-
long-term store within a few days from birth. contrasted nonface-like patterns do not appear
Newborns’ ability to recognize their mother’s different from those of face-like patterns.
face seems to be the product of a more general Further support to these conclusions comes
capacity to discriminate and recognize indi- from previous studies carried out to test
vidual human faces. Pascalis and de Schonen whether newborns can discriminate between
(1994) demonstrated that, after habituation arrays that are identical with respect to the
with a photograph of a stranger’s face, 4-day- global characteristics (i.e., columns of fi lled or
old infants looked longer at a new face than at unfi lled elements), but different with respect
the familiar one. This evidence demonstrates to the shape of the fi lled elements contained
that newborns are able to learn about a specific within the two fi lled columns (i.e., square
individual face to which they are repeatedly elements vs. diamond elements; Farroni et al.,
exposed within a short time after birth. 2000) (Figure 16.4, Panel A).
Despite convergent evidence on newborns’ Results showed that newborns are able to
ability to learn and discriminate individual discriminate the individual fi lled elements of
faces, little is known about the kind of visual the array of a stimulus and can organize such
information newborns’ face recognition relies elements into a holistic percept (Farroni et al.,
on. Some studies seem to suggest that there is an 2000). Moreover, even more interesting are the
inability of newborns to respond to the internal results showing that newborns are able to dis-
features of the face. In a study by Pascalis et al. criminate the individual elements of the array
(1995), in which the mother’s face was preferred even when they are embedded in an identical
over that of a female stranger, newborns’ pref- areas and external contour (Figure 16.4, Panel B)
erence for the face disappeared when only the (Farroni et al., 2000).
inner features of the two faces were visible (i.e., Put together, the findings obtained with face-
when both women wore scarves around their like and geometric stimuli converge to suggest
heads) and the outer contour of the head and that the operations involved in face processing
hairline were masked. Based on these findings, are the same that occur to process any visual
the authors concluded that, in order to recog- stimuli (e.g., de Schonen & Mancini, 1995; de
nize and prefer the mother, newborns used the Schonen, Mancini, & Liegeois, 1998; Johnson,
outer features of the face rather than the config- 1993, 1997).
uration of the internal features. However, this evidence cannot be extended
Nevertheless, some studies conducted in our by default to the case of real faces because faces
laboratory demonstrated that this conclusion are far more complex stimuli than schematic
A NEOCONSTRUCTIVISTIC APPROACH 325

Habituation phase Test phase

Panel A

Panel B

Figure 16.4 Examples of the stimuli used in Farroni et al. (2000) in the habituation and test phases.
Panel A: The familiar stimulus was alternating columns of black (fi lled) and white (unfi lled) squares.
In one of the two stimuli of the preference test phase the internal elements varied. Panel B: The famil-
iar stimulus was a square frame in which two fi lled black squares were arranged vertically. The two
stimuli of the preference test phase had identical areas and different internal elements.

face-like configurations, which usually display only the inner or the outer parts of the face is
inner elements all with an identical shape. As a sufficient to produce effective recognition at
result, it is possible that the visibility of the fea- birth (Turati et al., 2006). These findings are in
tures within a real face is lower than the visibil- line with the previous results demonstrating
ity of the elements that characterizes schematic that newborns can discriminate geometrical
black and white face-like patterns. Therefore, it stimuli when the external contour is identical
is possible that, within a few days from birth, (Farroni et al., 2000). The limited resolution
infants are constrained by their limited visual capacities of the visual system at birth do not
capacities to discriminate and recognize faces prevent few-day-old infants to discriminate the
relying on their most salient characteristics, information embedded in the inner portion of
that is the shape of the hair and the outer con- stimuli (e.g., Farroni et al., 2000; Simion et al.,
tour (Pascalis et al., 1995). 2002; Turati et al., 2006).
This hypothesis appears unlikely as demon- Overall, the results discussed so far support
strated by our third set of studies. The results the view that recognition of face-like, geometric,
show that newborns were able to discriminate and real faces is mediated by a general pattern-
and recognize experimentally familiarized learning mechanism dedicated to acquiring
images of real faces in three different condi- information about any visual pattern indepen-
tions: when the faces were fully visible, when dent of whether they are face or nonface stim-
only the inner features were visible, and when uli (de Schonen, 2002; de Schonen & Mancini,
the outer features alone were visible (Turati, 1995; Johnson, 1993; Johnson & de Haan, 2001;
Macchi Cassia, Simion, & Leo, 2006). The evi- Pascalis & de Schonen, 1994).
dence supports the conclusion that newborns Although it has been demonstrated that at
are able to recognize upright faces both when birth, the inner facial features alone convey
faces were fully visible, and when only the inner sufficient information in order to recognize a
or outer features are present. The presence of face, the data leave open the question whether
326 FOUNDATIONS OF SOCIAL COGNITION

newborns relied on the local or configural The presence of an inversion effect at birth
information. Indeed, these types of informa- might be interpreted as due either to face-spe-
tion are not independent of each other, because cific processes or to the early experience that
every change in the local information implies a newborns accumulate in the first days of life
change in the configuration. with a monooriented stimulus such as a face.
However, a third possible explanation could
be put forward in terms of a general superior-
WHAT IS THE NATURE OF THE OPERATIONS
ity effect of the global level in individual dis-
THAT OCCUR ON FACE RECOGNITION AT
crimination (Kimki, 1992). In both adults and
BIRTH?
infants, visual processing is dominated by
In order to investigate whether, early in life, configural-holistic properties, defined as prop-
face recognition relies upon the encoding of erties that depend on the interrelations among
the local facial features (local information) the stimulus components. Line segments are
or configural information (e.g., Maurer et al., discriminated better when presented in a con-
2002; Rhodes, Brake, & Atkinson, 1993), we textual frame than when presented in isolation
investigated whether newborns’ ability to (i.e., pattern-line effect; Pomerantz & Pristach,
recognize individual faces is affected by ori- 1989). These effects demonstrated that the global
entation (Turati et al., 2006). In the available level that involves the use of relational informa-
literature (e.g., Valentine, 1988; Yin, 1969), the tion is extracted at early stages of the perceptual
inversion effect has been taken as diagnostic processing and interferes with the processing
of configural processing. An analogue of the of the local features. The best example comes
“inversion effect,” similar to the one observed from a replication of the global–local para-
with adults (e.g., Leder & Bruce, 2000; Yin, digm (Navon, 1977) with newborns. The study
1969), has been documented in 4-month-old utilized compounded hierarchical patterns in
infants, who have been shown to be impaired which larger figures (i.e., cross or rhombus) are
in a recognition task with inverted faces as constructed from the same set of smaller fig-
compared to upright faces (Turati, Sangrigoli, ures. In the global–local paradigm, the primacy
Ruel, & de Schonen, 2004). Moreover, it has of the holistic properties is inferred from the
been shown that stimulus inversion disrupts perceptual advantage of the global level of the
newborns’ preference for attractive over unat- stimulus over the local level (Figure 16.5).
tractive face (“attractiveness effect”; Slater Our results demonstrated that newborns
et al., 2000). are able to discriminate both the local and the
In this vein, we examined whether newborns’ global levels (see New-Local and New-Global
ability to recognize a full face or a face in which conditions on Panel A, Figure 16.5). In contrast,
only the outer or the inner features were visible recognition of the local features was impaired
is preserved when the face is presented inverted, in the condition when conflicting information
that is rotated 180°. Results showed that the at the global level interfered with identification
inversion of the face differentially affected new- of the local features (i.e., there was an asym-
borns’ recognition in the three examined con- metric global-to-local interference, see Panel
ditions. Newborns were still able to recognize B, Figure 16.5) (Macchi Cassia, Simion, Milani,
a face as familiar only in the two conditions in Umiltà, 2002). The presence of an asymmetrical
which the external features were present (i.e., interference between the two levels of informa-
full face and external features only). In contrast, tion, which is consistent with a global advantage
recognition was disrupted when only the inner effect already documented with stimuli other
portion of the inverted face was present. Overall, than faces in newborns (Macchi et al., 2002) as
the lack of recognition for upside down faces in well as in 3-month-old infants (Ghim & Eimas,
the inner features condition suggests that, early 1988), might be responsible of the inversion
in life, faces are processed on the basis of config- effect obtained in the inner features condition
ural information. with faces in our study.
A NEOCONSTRUCTIVISTIC APPROACH 327

Habituation phase Test phase

New-Local Test Condition New-Global Test Condition

Familiar Novel Familiar Novel

Local-Discrimination Condition Global-Discrimination Condition


Panel A

1 Source of Novelty 2 Sources of Novelty 1 Source of Novelty 2 Sources of Novelty

Panel B Local-Global Cue-Competition Task

Figure 16.5 Examples of stimulus arrangements used during the habituation and test phase in Macchi
Cassia et al. (2002).

When the face is in the upright orientation, for configural processing of any visual pattern–
newborns encode both the levels (i.e. the local included faces (e.g., de Shonen & Mathivet,
and the global levels) with a superiority of the 1989). In line with this reasoning, research on
global/configural one that allows recognition infant hemispheric specialization showed that
of the face. In contrast, when the face is turned discrimination of face as well as non face stim-
upside down newborns are impaired in using uli in 4-month-old infants are based on con-
the global/configural information and due to figural differences carried out more effectively
the limited capacities of their visual system by the right hemisphere as compared to the
cannot rely upon the only use of the featural left (e.g., Deruelle & de Schonen, 1991, 1998; de
information. Schonen, Dereulle, Mancini & Pascalis, 1993).
Collectively, these results suggest that the This is probably because the right hemisphere
visuoperceptual system at birth constrains matures at a faster rate than the left hemisphere
newborns to process those coarse visual cues of during this period of early infancy when visual
a face or nonface stimuli strictly dependent on input is limited to lower spatial frequencies
low spatial frequencies that convey configural (e.g., de Schonen & Mathivet, 1990). As result,
information. young infants should be sensitive to configural
Recent evidence supports this conclusion information.
by demonstrating that the visual information
newborns use to process and recognize a face is
GENERAL CONCLUSIONS
based on low rather than high spatial frequen-
cies bands (de Heering et al., 2008). According Evidence reviewed in this chapter is relevant to
to some authors, young infants’ poor visual explain the factors affecting the emergence of a
acuity and contrast sensitivity limit encoding specialized system to process faces during the
to information carried by lower spatial fre- initial steps of development. The first section
quencies. The cortical neural networks begin focuses on the mechanisms underlying infants’
to form stable networks on the basis of this visual preference for faces and the results are
input and will eventually become specialized clear in indicating that some general biases allow
328 FOUNDATIONS OF SOCIAL COGNITION

newborns to orient toward certain structural that explains the early emergence of face pro-
properties that faces share with other stimuli. cessing as a result of the interaction between
More intriguing for the topic of a progressive innate constraints and the structure of the
specialization of the system to process faces are input provided by the species-typical environ-
the results showing that the same general biases ment (e.g., Elman et al., 1996). Evidence from
cannot explain face preferences at birth and 3 our laboratory suggests that face specificity is
months later. The replication of the same exper- not prewired, but rather arises from general
iments at these two different age levels reveals a perceptual processes that, during development,
modification in the determinants of 3-month- become progressively tuned to the human face,
old infants’ face preference, in that, contrary to as a result of extensive experience with this
what happens at birth, face preferences cannot stimulus category. Consequently, face at birth
be explained by general attentional biases. would simply represent a particular exemplar
At 3 months of age, face preference appears of a broader category of stimuli that share com-
to be the product of more specific mechanisms mon structural and configural properties. As
that respond more selectively to the percep- it is suggested by recent event-related potential
tual characteristics that distinguish faces from (e.g., de Haan & Nelson, 1999; de Haan, Pascalis,
other stimulus categories. As already suggested & Johnson, 2002) and behavioral studies (e.g.,
by some computational models (Acerra et al., Pascalis et al., 2002), with increasing exposure
2002; Bednar, 2003), this change in the mecha- to faces during the first months of life, the cat-
nisms underlying face preference in the first egory of faces shows an increasing degree of
months of life might be viewed as the gradual segregation: neural and behavioral responses to
and progressive emergence of an increasingly this class of stimuli become more and more spe-
complex system for face processing rather than cific, as a result of the narrowing of the infants’
the appearance of a novel and independent cor- perceptual window. The data presented in this
tical mechanism such as Conlearn, allowing chapter are in line with an experience-expect-
finer face encoding and thus better recogni- ant perspective (Nelson, 2003) that emphasizes
tion (Gliga & Csibra, 2007). Consistent with the the relevance of both general constraints of the
neocostructivistic approach, it can be suggested human visuoperceptual system and exposure to
that as a function of experience, the nonspe- certain experiences shortly after birth to drive
cific neural and functional networks become the system to become functionally specialized
progressively specialized for processing the cat- to process faces in the first months of life.
egory of visual stimuli to which infants are most
extensively exposed—that is, faces.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
The same general conclusion can be extended
to the processing underlying face recognition. The studies reported in the chapter were supported
Evidence suggests that at birth, the system seems by grants from the Ministero dell’Università
not to be specialized to process faces because the e della Ricerca Scientifica e Tecnologica (No.
perceptual processes carried out to recognize 2003112997_004 and No. 2005119101_003). The
different categories of stimuli did not differ. The authors are deeply indebted to Dr. Beatrice Dalla
Barba and the nursing staff at the Pediatric Clinic
visuoperceptual system at birth permits new-
of the University of Padova for their collaboration.
borns to process and to discriminate the informa-
We thank the parents and infants who participated
tion embedded in any visual pattern independent in these studies. We thank also Sandro Bettella for
of whether they are face or nonface stimuli. writing the soft ware.
Evidence supports the claim that the visual sys-
tem at birth constraints newborns to process
those coarse visual cues either of a face or nonface REFERENCES
stimuli that convey configural information. Acerra, F., Burnod, I., & de Schonen, S. (2002).
Overall, the pattern of results is in agree- Modeling aspects of face processing in early
ment with a neoconstructivism perspective infancy. Developmental Science, 5, 98–117.
A NEOCONSTRUCTIVISTIC APPROACH 329

Atkinson, J., Hood, B., Wattam-Bell, J., & Braddick, Chomsky, N. (1988). Language and the problems of
O. (1992). Changes in infants’ ability to switch knowledge: The Managua lectures. Cambridge,
visual attention in the first three months of life. MA: MIT Press.
Perception, 21, 643–653. de Haan, M., & Nelson, C. A. (1999). Brain activ-
Banks, M. S., & Salapatek, P. (1981). Infant pattern ity differentiates face and object process-
vision: A new approach based on the contrast ing by 6-month-old infants. Developmental
sensitivity function. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 34, 1114–1121.
Child Psychology, 31, 1–45. de Haan, M., Pascalis, O., & Johnson, M. (2002).
Barr-Haim, Y., Ziv, T., Lamy, D., & Hodes, R. M. Specialization of neural mechanisms underly-
(2006). Nature and narture in own-race face ing face recognition in human infants. Journal
processing. Psychological Science, 17, 159–163. of Cognitive Neuroscience, 14, 199–209.
Bartlett, J.C., & Searcy, J. (1993). Inversion and de Heering, A., Turati, C., Rossion, B., Bulf, H.,
configuration of faces. Cognitive Psychology, Goffaux, & Simion, F. (2008). Newborns’ face
25, 281–316. recognition is based on spatial frequencies
Bates, E. A., & Elman, J. L., (1993). Connectionism below 0.5 cycles per degree. Cognition, 106,
and the study of change. In M. Johnson (Ed.), 444–454.
Brain development and cognition: A reader (pp. Deruelle, C., & de Schonen, S. (1991). Hemispheric
420–440). Oxford: Blackwell Publishers. asymmetries in visual pattern processing in
Bednar, J. A. (2003). The role of internally gen- infancy. Brain and Cognition, 16, 151–179.
erated neural activity in newborn and infant Deruelle, C., & de Schonen, S. (1998). Do the right
face preferences. In O. Pascalis, & A. Slater and left hemispheres attend to the same visuo-
(Eds.), The development of face processing in spatial information within a face in infancy?
infancy and early childhood: Current perspec- Developmental Neuropsychology, 14, 535–554.
tives (pp. 133–142). New York: Nova Science de Schonen, S. (2002). Epigenesis of the cogni-
Publishers. tive brain: a task for the 21st Century. In L.
Braddick, O., Atkinson, J., Hood, B., Harkness, Backman & C. von Hofsten (Eds.), Psychology
W., Jackson, G., & Vargha-Cadem, F. (1992). at the turn of the millenium (pp. 55–88). Hove,
Possible blindsight in infants lacking one cere- UK: Psychology Press.
bral hemisphere. Nature, 360, 461–463. de Schonen, S., Dereulle, C., Mancini, J., &
Bronson, G. W. (1982). Structure, status and Pascalis, O. (1993). Hemispheric differences
characteristics of the nervous system at birth. in face processing and brain maturation.
In P. Stratton (Ed.), Psychobiology of the human In B. de Boysson-Bardies, S. de Schonen,
newborn (pp. 99–118). New York: Wiley. P. W. Jusczyk, P. McNeilage, & J. Morton (Eds.),
Bushnell, I. W. R. (2001). Mother’s face recogni- Developmental neurocognition: Speech and face
tion in newborn infants: Learning and mem- processing in the first year of life (pp. 149–163).
ory. Infant and Child Development, 10, 67–74. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Kluwer.
Bushnell, I. W. R., Sai, F., & Mullin, J. T. (1989). de Schonen, S., Mancini, J., & Liegeois, F. (1998).
Neonatal recognition of the mother’s face. About functional cortical specialization: The
British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 7, development of face recognition. In F. Simion
3–15. & G. Butterworth (Eds.), The development of
Caldara, R., Seghier, M. L., Rossion, B., Lazeyras, sensory, motor, and cognitive capacities in early
F., Michel, C., & Hauert, C. A. (2006). The fusi- infancy (pp. 103–116). Hove, UK: Psychology
form face area is tuned for curvilinear patterns Press.
with more high-contrasted elements in the de Schonen, S., & Mathivet, E. (1989). First come,
upper part. NeuroImage, 31, 313–319. first served: A scenario about the development
Carey, S., & Diamond, R. (1977). From piecemeal of hemispheric specialization in face recog-
to configurational representation of faces. nition during infancy. European Bulletin of
Science, 195, 312–314. Cognitive Psychology, 9, 3–44.
Cheour, M., Ceponiene, R., Lehtokoski, A., Luuk, de Schonen, S., & Mathivet, E. (1990). Hemispheric
A., Allik, J., Alho, K., et al. (1998). Development asymmetry in a face discrimination task in
of language-specific phoneme representations infants. Child Development, 61, 1192–1205.
in the infant brain. Nature Neuroscience, 1, Easterbrook, M. A., Kisilevsky, B. S., Muir, D. W., &
351–353. Laplante, D. P. (1999). Newborns discriminate
330 FOUNDATIONS OF SOCIAL COGNITION

schematic faces from scrambled faces. Gliga, T., & Csibra, G. (2007). Seeing the face
Canadian Journal of Experimental Psychology, through the eyes: A developmental perspective
53, 231–241. on face expertise. Progress in Brain Research,
Elman, J. L., Bates, E. A., Johnson, M. H., 164, 323–339.
Karmiloff-Smith, A., Parisi, D., & Plunkett, K. Goren, C., Sarty, M., & Wu, P. (1975). Visual follow-
(1996). Rethinking innateness. A connectionist ing and pattern discrimination of face-like stim-
perspective on development. Cambridge, MA: uli by newborn infants. Pediatrics, 56, 544–549.
The MIT Press. Greenough, W. T., & Black, J. E. (1992). Induction
Farah, M. J., Rabinowitz, C., Quinn, G. E., & of brain structure by experience: Substrates for
Liu, G. T. (2000). Early commitment of neu- cognitive development. In M. Gunnar & C. A.
ral substrates for face recognition. Cognitive Nelson (Eds.), Behavioral developmental neu-
Neuropsychology, 17, 117–123. roscience. Vol. 24. Minnesota symposia on child
Farroni, T., Valenza, E., Simion, F., & Umiltà, C. psychology (pp. 35–52). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
(2000). Configural processing at birth: Evidence Halit, H., de Haan, M., & Johnson, M. H. (2003).
for perceptual organization. Perception, 29, Cortical specialization for face processing: Face
355–372. sensitive event-related potential components in
Fodor, J. (1983). The modularity of mind. An essay 3- and 12-month-old infants. Neuroimage, 19,
on faculty psychology. Cambridge, MA: The 1180–1193.
MIT Press. Hole, G. J. (1994). Configurational factors in the
Freire, A., & Lee, K. (2001). Face recognition in perception of unfamiliar faces. Perception, 23,
4- to 7-year-old: processing of configural, fea- 65–74.
tural, and paraphernalia information. Journal Johnson, M. H. (1993). Constraints on cortical
of Experimental Child Psychology, 80, 347–371. plasticity. In M. J. Johnson (Eds.), Brain devel-
Gauthier, I., & Logothetis, N. K. (2000). Is face opment and cognition. A reader (pp. 703–721).
recognition not so unique after all? Cognitive Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.
Neuropsychology, 17, 125–142. Johnson, M. H. (1995). The development of visual
Gauthier, I., & Tarr, M. J. (1997). Becoming a “gree- attention: A cognitive neuroscience perspec-
ble” expert: Exploring mechanisms for face tive. In M. S. Gazzaniga (Ed.), The cognitive
recognition. Vision Research, 37, 1673–1682. neurosciences (pp. 735–747). Cambridge, MA:
Gauthier, I., & Tarr, M. J. (2002). Unraveling MIT Press.
mechanisms for expert object recognition: Johnson, M. H. (1997). Developmental Cognitive
Bridging brain activity and behavior. Journal Neuroscience: An Introduction. Oxford:
of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception Blackwell.
and Performance, 28, 431–446. Johnson, M. H. (2005). Subcortical face processing.
Gauthier, I., Tarr, M. J., Anderson, A. W., Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 6, pp. 766–774.
Skudlarski, P., & Gore, J. C. (1999). Activation Johnson, M. H., & de Haan, M. (2001). Developing
of the middle fusiform “face area” increases cortical specialization for visual-cognitive
with expertise in recognizing novel objects. function: The case of face recognition. In J. L.
Nature Neuroscience, 2, 568–573. McClelland & R. S. Seigler (Eds.), Mechanisms of
Gauthier, I., Williams, P., Tarr, M. J., & Tanaka, cognitive development: Behavioral and neural per-
J. (1998). Training “greeble” experts: A frame- spectives (pp. 253–270). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
work for studying expert object recognition Johnson, M. H., Dziurawiec, S., Ellis, H., & Morton,
processes. Vision Research, 38, 2401–2428. J. (1991). Newborns’ preferential tracking of
Geldart, S., Mondloch, C. J., Maurer, D., de Schonen, face-like stimuli and its subsequent decline.
S., & Brent, H. P. (2002). The effect of early visual Cognition, 40, 1–19.
deprivation on the development of face process- Johnson, M. H., & Morton, J. (1991). Biology and
ing. Developmental Science, 5, 490–501. cognitive development. The case of face recogni-
Gelman, R. (1990). First principles organize atten- tion. Oxford, England: Basil Blackwell.
tion to and learning about relevant data: num- Kanwisher, N. (2000). Domain specificity in face
ber and the animate–inanimate distiction as perception. Nature Neuroscience, 3, 759–763.
examples. Cognitive Science, 1, 79–106. Karmiloff-Smith, A. (1992). Beyond modularity.
Ghim, H. R., & Eimas, P. D. (1988). Global and Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
local processing by 3- and 4-month-old infants. Kellman, P. J. (1993). Kinematic foundations
Perception & Psychophysics, 43, 165–171. of infant visual perception. In C. Granrud,
A NEOCONSTRUCTIVISTIC APPROACH 331

Visual perception and cognition in infancy Macchi Cassia, V., Valenza, E., Simion, F., & Leo,
(pp. 121–173). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. I. (2008). Congruency as a non-specific percep-
Kelly, D. J., Liu, S., Ge, L., Quinn, P. C., Slater, A. tual property contributing to newborns’ face
M., Lee, K., et al. (2007). Cross-race preferences preference. Child Development, 79, 807–820.
for Same-race faces extend beyond the Afreican Maurer, D., Le Grand, R., & Mondloch, C. J.
versus Caucasian contrast in 3-month-old (2002). The many faces of configural process-
infants. Infancy, 11, 87–95. ing. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 6, 255–260.
Kelly, D. J., Quinn, P. C., Slater, A. M., Lee, K., Michel , G. F., & Moore, C. L. (1995). Developmental
Gibson, A., Smith, M., et al. (2005). Th ree- psychobiology: An integrative science.
month-olds, but not newborns, prefer Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
own-race faces. Developmental Science, 8, Morton, J., & Johnson, M. H. (1991). CONSPEC
F31–F36. and CONLEARN: A two-process theory of
Kimki, R. (1992). Primacy of wholistic processing infant face recognition. Psychological Review,
and global/local paradigm: A critical review. 98, 164–181.
Psychological Bulletin, 112, 24–38. Navon, D. (1977). Forest before trees: The prece-
Kleiner, K.A. (1987). Amplitude and phase spectra dence of global features in visual perception.
as indices of infants’ pattern preferences. Infant Cognitive Psychology, 9, 353–383.
Behavior & Development, 10, 49–59. Nelson, C. A. (2001). The development and neu-
Kleiner, K. A., & Banks, M. S. (1987). Stimulus ral bases of face recognition. Infant and Child
energy does not account for 2-month-old Development, 10, 3–18.
infants’ face preference. Journal of Experi- Nelson, C. A. (2003). The development of face rec-
mental Psychology: Human, Perception and ognition reflects an experience-expectant and
Performance, 13, 594–600. activity-dependent process. In O. Pascalis & A.
Kuhl, P. K., Williams, K. A., Lacerda, F., Stevens, Slater (Eds.), The development of face process-
K. N., & Lindblom, B. (1992). Linguistic experi- ing in infancy and early childhood: Current per-
ence alters phonetic perception in infants by 6 spectives (pp. 79–97). New York: Nova Science
months of age. Science, 255, 606–608. Publishers.
Leder, H., & Bruce, V. (2000). When inverted faces Nelson, C. A., & Luciana, M. (Eds.). (2001)
are recognized: The role of configural informa- Handbook of developmental cognitive neurosci-
tion in face recognition. The Quartely Journal ence. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
of Experimental Psychology A, 53, 513–536. Pascalis, O., de Haan, M., & Nelson, C. A. (2002).
Le Grand, R., Mondloch, C. J., Maurer, D., & Is face processing species-specific during the
Brent, H. P. (2003). Expert face processing first year of life? Science, 296, 1321–1323.
requires visual input to the right hemisphere Pascalis, O., & de Schonen, S. (1994). Recognition
during infancy. Nature Neuroscience, 6, memory in 3- to 4-day-old human neonates.
1108–1112. Neuroreport, 5, 1721–1724.
Macchi Cassia, V., Kuefner, D., Westerlund, A., Pascalis, O., de Schonen, S., Morton, J., Deruelle, C.,
& Nelson, C. A. (2006). Modulation of face- & Fabre-Grenet, M. (1995). Mother’s face recog-
sensitive event-related potentials by canonical nition by neonates: A replication and an exten-
and distorted human faces: The role of verti- sion. Infant Behavior & Development, 18, 79–85.
cal symmetry and up-down featural arrange- Pomerantz, J. R., & Pristach, E. A. (1989).
ment. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 18, Emergent features, attention, and perceptual
1343–1358. glue in visual form perception. Journal of
Macchi Cassia, V., Simion, F., Milani, I., & Umiltà, Experimental Psychology: Human Perception
C. (2002). Dominance of global visual proper- and Performance, 15, 635–649.
ties at birth. Journal of Experiment Psychology: Rhodes, G., Brake, S., Atkinson, A. P. (1993) What’s
General, 131, 398–411. lost in inverted faces? Cognition, 47, 25–57.
Macchi Cassia, V., Simion, F., & Umiltà, C. (2001). Schwaninger, A., Carbon, C. C., & Leder, H.
Face preference at birth: The role of an orienting (2003). Expert face processing: Specialization
mechanism. Developmental Science, 4, 101–108. and constraints. In G. Schwarzer & H. Leder
Macchi Cassia V., Turati C., & Simion, F. (2004). (Eds.), Development of face processing (pp.
Can a non specific bias toward top-heavy 81–97). Gottingen: Hogrefe.
patterns explain newborns’ face preference? Searcy, J. H., & Bartlett, J. C. (1996). Inversion
Psychological Science, 15, 379–383. and processing of component and spatial-
332 FOUNDATIONS OF SOCIAL COGNITION

relational information in faces. Journal of Tanaka, J.W., & Farah, T. (1993). Parts and wholes
Experimental Psychology: Human Perception in face recognition. The Quarterly Journal of
and Performance, 22, 904–915. Experimental Psychology A, 46, 225–245.
Simion, F., Farroni, T., Macchi Cassia, V., Turati, Turati, C., Macchi Cassia, V., Simion F., & Leo,
C., & Dalla Barba, B. (2002). Newborns’ I. (2006). Newborns’ face recognition: The
local processing in schematic face-like con- role of inner and outer facial features. Child
figurations. British Journal of Developmental Development, 77, 297–311.
Psychology, 20, 465–478. Turati, C., Sangrigoli, S., Ruel, J., & de Schonen, S.
Simion, F., Macchi Cassia, V., Turati, C., & (2004). Evidence of the face-inversion effect in
Valenza, E. (2001). The origins of face percep- 4-month-old infants. Infancy, 6, 275–297.
tion: Specific vs. non-specific mechanisms. Turati, C., Simion, F., Milani, I., & Umiltà, C. (2002).
Infant and Child Development, 10, 59–65. Newborns preference for faces: What is crucial?
Simion, F., Macchi Cassia, V., Turati, C., & Valenza, Developmental Psychology, 38, 875–882.
E. (2003). Non-specific perceptual biases at the Turati, C., Valenza, E., Leo, I., & Simion, F.
origins of face processing. In O. Pascalis & A. (2005). Three-month-old visual preference
Slater (Eds.), The development of face process- for faces and its underlying visual processing
ing in infancy and early childhood: Current per- mechanisms. Journal of Experimental Child
spectives. (pp. 13–25). New York: Nova Science Psychology, 90, 255–273.
Publishers. Turkewitz, G., & Kenny, P. A. (1982). Limitations
Simion, F., Turati, C., Valenza, E., & Leo, I. (2006). on input as a basis for neural organization
The emergence of cognitive specialization and perceptual development: a prelimi-
in infancy: The case of face preference. In M. nary theroretical statement. Developmental
Johnson & M. Munakata (Eds.), Processes Psychobiology, 15, 357–368.
of Change in Brain Development: Attention Tzourio-Mazoyer, N., de Schonen, S., Crivello, F.,
and Performance XXI (pp. 189–208). Oxford: Reutter, B., Aujard, Y., & Mazoyer, B. (2002).
University Press. Neural correlates of woman face process-
Simion, F., Valenza, E., Macchi Cassia, V., Turati, ing by 2-month-old infants. Neuroimage, 15,
C., & Umiltà, C. (2002). Newborns’ preference 454–461.
for up-down asymmetrical configurations. Valentine, T. (1988). Upside-down faces: A review
Developmental Science, 5, 427–434. of the effect of inversion upon face recognition.
Slater, A., Bremner, G., Johnson, S.P., Sherwood, P., British Journal of Psychology, 79, 471–491.
Hayes, R., & Brown, E. (2000). Newborn infants’ Valenza, E., Simion, F., Macchi Cassia, V., &
preference for attractive faces: The role of internal Umiltà, C. (1996). Face preference at birth.
and external facial features. Infancy, 1, 265–274. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human
Slater, A., Earle, D.C., Morison, V., & Rose, D. Perception and Performance, 22, 892–903.
(1985). Pattern preferences at birth and their Walton, G. E., Bower, N. J. A., & Bower, T. G. R. (1992).
interaction with habituation induced novelty Recognition of familiar faces by newborns. Infant
preferences. Journal of Experimental Child Behavior & Development, 15, 265–269.
Psychology, 39, 37–54. Werker, J. F., & Vouloumanos, A. (2001). Speech and
Slater, A., & Sykes, M. (1977). Newborn infants’ language processing in infancy: A neurocogni-
responses to square-wave gratings. Child tive approach. In C.A. Nelson & M. Luciana
Development, 48, 545–553. (Eds.), Handbook of Developmental Cognitive
Spelke, E.S. (1991). Physical knowledge in infancy: Neuroscience (pp. 269–280). Cambridge, Mass:
Reflections on Piaget’s theory. In S. Carey & R. MIT Press.
Gelman (Eds.) The epigenesis of mind: Essays on Wynn, K. (1995). Origins of numerical knowledge.
biology and cognition (pp. 133–169). Hilsdale, Mathematical Cognition, 1, 35–60.
NJ: Erlbaum. Yin, R. K. (1969). Looking at upside-down faces.
Sprague, J.M., Berlucchi, G., & Rizzolatti, G. (1973). Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 81,
The role of the superior colliculus and pretec- 141–145.
tum in vision and visually guided behavior. In Young, A. W., Hellawell, D., & Hay, D. C., (1987).
R. Jung (Ed.), Handbook of sensory physiology Configural information in face perception.
(Vol. 7, pp. 27–101). Berlin: Springer-Verlag. Perception, 16, 747–759.
PART VI

The Big Picture


This page intentionally left blank
CHAPTER 17
A Bottom-up Approach to Infant Perception
and Cognition: A Summary of Evidence
and Discussion of Issues

Leslie B. Cohen

As the author of the final chapter in this book, processing attributed to infants became more
I have been given the impossible task of sum- relational, more abstract, i.e., more cognitive.
marizing and evaluating the evidence reported Infants’ ability to categorize, their understand-
by all the previous speakers at this conference. ing of causal relations, and their knowledge of
We were all also given instructions to empha- objects, events, and even simple rules were just
size general methodological and theoretical some of the topics being investigated. Finally,
issues, the “big picture” so to speak, rather than as we enter the new century, infant cognition
the details of specific studies. Although I cannot and information processing is becoming more
possibly do the former, I will try to do the latter integrated with infant language acquisition.
and in so doing will at least raise some of the Sensitivity to correlated information and sta-
issues mentioned by other speakers. tistical regularities are being shown to be crit-
The evolution of research on infant percep- ically important to language segmentation, the
tion and cognition over the past 50 years has formation of syntactic regularities, and categor-
been truly astounding. In the 1950s and 1960s, ical structure.
infants were blasted with bright lights and loud As great as these advances have been, most
noises while their reflexive responses were being research on these topics has tended to suffer
measured. In the late 1960s and 1970s, it was from one glaring weakness, a lack of emphasis
discovered that infants preferred to look longer on development and the mechanisms underly-
at something novel than at something familiar ing developmental change. To be sure, a reason-
and this preference was exploited to study infant able percentage of published studies have tested
memory. From the mid-1970s through the 1980s, infants at different ages. Some of them have
it became clear that one could not understand even reported interesting age differences, i.e.,
how well an infant remembered until one knew differences other than younger infants cannot
what the infant remembered. That realization, do what older ones can do. But rarely, have they
in turn, led to the use of habituation and related taken the next step and attempted to describe or
memory paradigms as tools to investigate infant explain the principles or mechanisms by which
visual and auditory information processing. An these changes occur. A couple of real exceptions
explosion of studies appeared on basic visual, have been the books by Karmiloff-Smith (1992)
auditory, speech, and intermodal perception. In who explained how a modular organization of
the 1980s and 1990s, the types of information some cognitive ability can develop gradually

Th is chapter is based upon a paper presented at NSF Sponsored Workshop: A Neoconstructivist Approach to Early
Cognitive Development. New York, October, 2006.

335
336 THE BIG PICTURE

through experience, and the book by Elman and its movement, M2, may become associated
et al. (1996) that showed how connectionist as Moving Object B. Then, when Moving Object
models do, in fact, make explicit assumptions A repeatedly precedes and makes contact with
about mechanisms of developmental change. Object B, leading to Moving Object B, the entire
sequence can be organized as a conditional or
even a causal event (Cohen, Amsel, Redford, &
CONSTRUCTIVISTPRINCIPLES OF Casasola, 1998).
DEVELOPMENTAL CHANGE 4. There is a bias to process information using
the highest-formed units available. This is really
Over the years, our laboratory has investigated
a simplifying assumption. Given that some-
many different aspects of infant perception and
one can process information at multiple levels,
cognition. Most of these investigations have
it usually will be more efficient to begin at the
looked specifically at developmental changes in
highest, most inclusive or abstract level avail-
infants’ information processing abilities. From
able. When an infant is looking at her mother, it
these studies, as well as from those reported
certainly would be more appropriate and adap-
by many other investigators, we have found
tive for her to process the mother’s face and her
some striking similarities. Infants often seem
actions as a whole, rather than trying to process
to progress in a bottom-up fashion. That is,
the eye, the eyebrow, the relationship between
infants initially appear to process simple iso-
the eye and the hairline, the configuration of
lated units, and then move to the relationship
those parts with the rest of the face, the mouth
or integration of those simple units into higher-
and its movement, etc. all separately either in
order units. Furthermore, this appears to be a
series or in parallel.
domain-general progression. This progression
5. If higher units do not respond, lower units
has been reported on many topics from simple
are utilized. This is really a fallback provision.
form and object perception, to complex face
There are occasions when attempting to process
identification, to an understanding of moving
information at the highest level available fails
objects in causal events, and even to an infant’s
for some reason. On those occasions, people
ability to learn word–object associations. We
(including infants) do not automatically give
have summarized much of this evidence previ-
up. Instead, they often will drop down to a lower
ously (e.g., Cohen & Cashon, 2003, 2006), and
level and attempt to process information at that
that evidence has led us to formulate the follow-
level. Assimilating information at that level
ing set of constructivist principles to describe
eventually may lead them back to a higher level.
these developmental changes:
One could consider this provision an instance
1. Infants are endowed with a hierarchical of top-down processing rather than bottom-up
information processing system. This statement processing.
simply affirms that infants can process infor- This fallback tends to occur when the system
mation at multiple levels of abstraction. is overloaded. In our research, we have found
2. Infants form higher units from relation- examples of infants falling to a lower level
ships among lower units. These relationships may when
be correlational, conditional, or even causal. By
(a) the complexity of the task is increased,
far, most research to date has examined rela-
(b) the infant has to process a category rather
tions that based upon correlations or statistical
than a single instance,
associations.
(c) uncertainty or noise is added to the task,
3. Higher units serve as components for still-
and
higher units. This proposition simply asserts the
(d) some additional meaning is added to the
bottom-up or constructivist nature of this hier-
task
archy. For example, Object A may come to be
associated with one type of movement, M1, and Several examples of this fallback provision with
become Moving Object A. Similarly, Object B infants will be described later in this chapter.
A BOTTOM-UP APPROACH TO INFANT PERCEPTION AND COGNITION 337

6. These principles apply throughout devel- stimuli and then tested with novel and familiar
opment and across domains. These principles stimuli to determine if infants responded differ-
can be seen to apply to many different tasks at ently to the two.
many different ages. No particular level or unit
1. Angle perception studies. One of the ear-
being processed is tied to one particular age. It
liest set of studies we conducted on this topic
is not the case that 4-month-olds always pro-
examined developmental changes in infants’
cess information in an elementary form and
perception of a simple angle (Cohen & Younger,
6-month-olds always process it in an integrated
1984). In these studies, 6- and 12-week-old
form. The unit of processing at any one age is
infants were habituated to an acute 45º angle
more a function of the level of expertise on a
made with thick black lines. The infants were
particular task. In fact, these principles may
then shown four test angles, in counterbal-
be more appropriately considered principles
anced order. One angle was identical to the one
of learning rather than principles of develop-
presented during habituation. It, AfOf, was the
ment. As one learns a new task, whether it is to
familiar angle with lines in familiar orienta-
ride a bicycle, play Monopoly, or use Excel, one
tions. A second angle, AfOn, was the familiar
begins by acquiring some basic elements such
angle rotated so that the lines were in novel
as how to pedal, move a piece, or enter a num-
orientations. The third, AnOf, was a novel 135º
ber. However, once a person becomes relatively
angle, but the line orientations were familiar.
proficient at that level, he/she operates at an
They were the same as in the 45º angle used
entirely different level, going to the store, own-
in habituation. Finally, the fourth, AnOn, was
ing a whole row, or analyzing a set of data. The
a novel angle with novel line orientations. The
same may be true for an infant. But the tasks
results were clear-cut. Six-week-olds looked
are more basic and immediate, recognizing a
longer only when the orientation of the lines
face, getting fed, predicting an object’s move-
changed (i.e., at AfOn and AnOn). In contrast,
ment. This point will be raised again toward the
the 12-week-olds looked longer only when the
end of the chapter. Perhaps infant perceptual-
angle changed (i.e., at AnOf and AnOn). These
cognitive development and learning (i.e., the
results indicated that 6-week-olds were process-
development of expertise in some domain) are
ing one or more individual line segments, while
not that different. It is just that infants gradu-
12-week-olds were integrating those line seg-
ally are becoming experts about the immediate
ments into complete angles.
physical and social worlds around them.
Alan Slater (Slater, 1995; Slater, Mattock,
Brown, & Bremner, 1991) replicated this study
EVIDENCE FOR CONSTRUCTIVIST PRINCIPLES
with 1-month-old infants and found they too
Evidence for these principles has been reported responded to a change in line segment orienta-
many times in the past. A detailed account of tion. He then turned the study into a category
much of this evidence has been presented most task by habituating infants to the same angle,
recently in Cohen and Cashon (2006). I will not but on each trial in a different rotation. Now he
attempt to duplicate that account here. Instead claimed they were responding to the angle since
I will summarize briefly several examples of in the test they looked longer at a novel angle
developmental changes occurring across a vari- than at the familiar angle. However, he admits
ety of different topics within infant perception that there may be a simpler possibility. They
and cognition. It should be obvious from this may be responding to the “size of the blob” at
account that similar types of changes occur the apex of the angle. An acute angle has a larger
repeatedly but that the ages involved depend low spatial frequency “blob” at its apex than
upon the particular topic or skill. Almost all of does an obtuse angle. This “blob theory” is sup-
these studies used some version of a habituation ported by another study reported by Slater and
or familiarization paradigm in which infants Morrison (reported in Slater, 1995) that showed
were familiarized with one or more habituation infants had to be 3 months of age before they
338 THE BIG PICTURE

responded categorically to a simple geometric assumes that a rotating rod is more complex
shape. Thus, it was unlikely that 1-month-old than a translating rod by virtue of the continu-
infants in Slater et al. (1991) were responding ing changing rod/occluder angle, then research
categorically. If, on the contrary, infants were on object unity provides additional evidence for
responding to the size of the blob, then one the fallback provision.
could claim both that infants progress from 3. Face perception studies. Infant face per-
processing individual line segments to entire ception has been and continues to be a very
angles and that turning the task into a category popular area of investigation. One topic within
problem made it more difficult, and as a conse- that area is how infants perceive and organize
quence, infants fell back to yet a simpler way of the features of a face. We have both examined
processing the angle (i.e., in terms of the size of and written extensively about this topic (e.g.,
the blob). Both claims, of course, would be con- Cashon & Cohen, 2003, 2004; Cohen & Cashon,
sistent with the constructivist principles stated 2001) and our conclusions have been that devel-
earlier. opmental changes between 3 and 7 months of
2. Object unity studies. In a classic set of age tend to follow our constructivist principles.
studies reported by Kellman and Spelke (1983), The procedure we used is an instance of the
4-month-old infants were habituated to a rod “switch design” in which infants are habitu-
moving left and right (i.e., translating) behind ated to two separate pictures of female faces and
an occluder. Only the top and bottom portions then are tested with a familiar face, a new face,
of the rod were visible. In the test phase of the and most critically, a composite constructed
experiment, the occluder was absent and infants by combining the external features of one face
saw either the pieces of the rod they had seen with the internal features of the other, familiar
before or the entire rod. Infants looked longer face. The question is whether infants respond to
at the separated pieces. The authors concluded the composite face as old or new. If they treat
that the common motion of the upper and lower it as new, it must be because they are relating
pieces produced the perception, or inference, of the external with the internal features. We
an entire rod. Many subsequent studies exam- tested infants with both upright and inverted
ined the limits of this perception of object unity faces. What we found was an interesting series
(see Johnson, 2000 for one review) but for my of developmental changes. At 3 months of age,
purposes among the most interesting are those infants treated the composite face, both upright
by Slater, Johnson, Kellman, and Spelke (1994) and inverted, as old suggesting they were pro-
and by Slater, Johnson, Brown, and Badenoch cessing independent features. By 4 months
(1996) that showed newborns do exactly the of age, they responded to both upright and
opposite. They look longer at the solid rod than inverted composites as new, suggesting they
at the separated pieces. If one wishes to argue were now processing the relationship among
that infants at 4 months are integrating the internal and external features. Th is pattern of
pieces into a solid rod, then by the same logic, results, of course, fits with our constructivist
one should argue that newborns are perceiving view. At 6 months of age, they reverted back to
the separate pieces, a view consistent with our responding to the composites as old. However
constructivist principles. at 7 to 10 months of age, they differentiated
Furthermore, additional evidence by between inverted and upright faces. Inverted
Eizenman and Bertenthal (1998) indicates composite faces were still processed as old but
another developmental change between 4 and upright composite faces were new once again.
6 months of age. If the partially hidden rod Our interpretation was that infants had indeed
is seen rotating (like a propeller) rather than advanced from processing independent fea-
translating from left to right, 4-month-olds tures at 3 months to processing the relationship
fall back and respond to the separate pieces as among features at 4 months. Faces, of course,
familiar. They have to be 6 months of age before were very interesting, moving stimuli with both
they respond to the entire rod as familiar. If one visual and auditory components. However, by
A BOTTOM-UP APPROACH TO INFANT PERCEPTION AND COGNITION 339

6 months of age, faces were far more. They were story. When we made the task more complex
social, personal, interactive, perhaps, even more by using pictures of realistic toys rather than
than that. During their waking hours, infants squares or circles 6 month olds could no longer
spent much of their time in a sitting position do it (Cohen & Oakes, 1993). They had to be 10
and faces were becoming more meaningful months of age before they could perceive the
when seen upright than when seen inverted. causality. Furthermore, when we made that task
This additional meaningful component tended more complex by using different toys on each
to overload their processing system temporar- trial, thereby turning it into a category problem,
ily and the infants reverted to a simpler way of even the 10-month-old infants could not do it
processing. By 7 months of age, that meaningful and reverted back to processing the spatial and
component was incorporated (assimilated) into temporal differences between events, but not
their understanding of a face and now they pro- the causality. Thus, we found evidence for the
cessed upright and inverted faces differentially. fallback as well.
4. Causal perception studies. Of all topics Finally, we made the event more complex by
available within infant perception and cogni- embedding the simple direct launching event in
tion, our laboratory has made the most exten- a longer sequence (Cohen, Rundell, Spellman,
sive study of infant causal perception and its & Cashon, 1999). We called these events “causal
development. Research on infant causal percep- chains.” Object A hit Object B that then hit
tion was originally inspired by Michotte (1963) Object C producing a change in Object C. We
who showed that when adults see one spot move varied whether Objects A and B were involved
laterally, hit a second spot that then begins to in a direct launching or a delayed launching.
move, they perceive the event as the first spot This event was beyond the ability of 10-month-
causing or initiating the second spot’s move- olds to process. They only noticed a change in
ment. In groundbreaking work with infants, Object A. Fifteen-month-olds, on the other
Leslie (Leslie, 1982, 1986; Leslie & Keeble, 1987) hand, seemed to be able to handle the entire
found a similar phenomenon with 6-month- event. They tended to key on the causal agent,
old infants. He made a movie of an event in whether it was the first object (in the direct
which one block moved across a screen, hit, and launching version) or the second object (in the
directly launched a second block. He also made delayed launching version). Then, we made the
a slight variation of the event in which a delay task even more complex by turning it into a cate-
occurred between the first block’s contact and gory problem. Only the causality remained con-
movement of the second block, and a variation sistent. Individual objects could be involved in
in which a spatial gap remained between the either causal or noncausal relationships (Cohen,
first and second blocks. By habituating infants Cashon, & Rundell, 2004). Now only 18-month-
to one event and then testing on these other old infants seemed to understand the event.
events, Leslie found that 6-month-olds treated So our study of infant causal perception has
the direct launching (i.e., causal) differently provided us with considerable evidence of the
from the others and concluded that infants per- information processing principles stated earlier.
ceive the causal relation in the direct launching Infants progressed through multiple levels, each
event. constructed from the relationship among units
We began by replicating Leslie’s results with at lower levels. At each of these levels, they also
6-month-olds. We (Cohen & Amsel, 1998) then fell back to a simpler level when the information
tested younger infants and found that 4-month- became too complex and the system became
olds responded to the continuous movement overloaded.
and 5.5-month-olds responded to both spa- 5. Infant categorization. For at least 30 years
tial and temporal differences between events, (e.g., Cohen & Caputo, 1978; Cohen & Strauss,
but not to the causality. Thus, a constructiv- 1977), researchers have known that infants can
ist developmental progression appeared once form concepts and categories. The minimal
again. However, that was just one part of the definition of such categorization is that infants
340 THE BIG PICTURE

respond equivalently to discriminably differ- assignment (Madole & Oakes, 1999)? These
ent members of the category. In summarizing are just some of the questions whose answers
research on infant categorization, Cohen and require “process” studies.
Younger (1983) made a distinction that I believe In order to examine the processes underly-
still holds today. They divided such research into ing category acquisition one must (1) employ
“demonstration” studies and “process” studies. artificial categories the infant has not experi-
Demonstration studies show that infants can enced previously and (2) manipulate the cat-
respond on the basis of some category. There egory exemplars to determine how the infant
are now innumerable studies that indicate is processing and organizing them. Barbara
infants can respond to faces versus nonfaces, Younger and I reported several such studies
dogs versus cats; animals versus vehicles, items back in the 1980s (Younger & Cohen, 1983,
above a line versus items below a line etc. (e.g., 1986). These studies also provided some of the
Quinn, Adams, Kennedy, Shettler, & Wasnik, earliest evidence for the constructivist infor-
2003; Quinn & Eimas, 2000; Quinn, Eimas, & mation processing principles stated above. The
Rosenkrantz, 1993). studies presented infants with line drawings of
One problem with many of these studies, artificial animals. Several features varied from
particularly those that use natural categories, animal to animal, such as the type of ears, tail,
is that it is unknown to what extent infants body, and number and type of legs. In one set
learned these categories in the familiarization of experiments (Younger & Cohen, 1986) these
phase of the experiment and to what extent they feature values were tightly correlated with one
knew something about these categories prior to another so that one animal always had fluff y
entering into the experiment. A second problem ears, a horse tail, a giraffe-like body, and four
is that most of these studies do not pay sufficient long legs, while another animal always had
attention the information processing aspect antlers, a bunny tail, a bear-like body, and two
of the task, that is how infants are processing short legs. Using the switch design with these
individual exemplars and how that process- animal stimuli, we showed that 4-month-old
ing may change over age. Why do investigators infants appeared to process the separate fea-
often use simple two-dimensional shapes with tures or parts, but both 7- and 10-month-old
infants under 6 months of age and more com- infants were sensitive to the relationship among
plex line drawings or photographs with infants the parts. This developmental pattern fit nicely
later in their first year of life, and why do they with our constructivist viewpoint.
tend to use moving animation or three-dimen- Then we made the task more difficult. We
sional toys in the second year? These differ- designed animals in which only a subset of
ences in types of stimuli employed at different the features were correlated with one another.
ages seems to approximate those we discussed The remaining features varied randomly. This
when referring to infant causal perception, but change essentially converted the task from
why certain types of stimuli are most appropri- requiring processing of two separate animals to
ate at certain ages is rarely, if ever, given much processing two different animal categories. As
emphasis in the infant categorization literature. before, 4-month-olds just processed the sepa-
Even when the most appropriate type of stimu- rate features, and 10-month-olds processed the
lus for a particular age is used, it often is unclear relationship among features (i.e., in this case the
how the infant is processing that stimulus. Are categories). It was the 7-month-olds who were
they processing some subset of the features of the most interesting. In the two-object task,
the exemplars shown such as only the internal they had responded like 10-month-olds. Now
or external features? Are they really processing in the two-category task, they responded like
animals versus vehicles or legs versus wheels 4-month-olds. Apparently turning it into a cat-
(Rakison & Butterworth, 1998)? To what extent egory task overloaded the system for 7-month-
do functional characteristics, as opposed to olds and they fell back to a simpler level of
structural characteristics play a role in category processing.
A BOTTOM-UP APPROACH TO INFANT PERCEPTION AND COGNITION 341

6. Early word learning. One of the greatest switch design becomes more than a simple
accomplishments during the 12- to 18-month association task for the infant. Infants are
age period is the ability to comprehend and then attempting to learn that specific words refer to
produce meaningful words. Most experimental specific objects and that adds additional mean-
studies of infant word learning are of relatively ingfulness to the task. Making the task more
recent origin (Schafer & Plunkett, 1998; Werker, difficult by testing with minimal pairs exceeds
Cohen, Lloyd, Casasola, & Stager, 1998). In one their processing resources and infants revert to
set of studies, we used the switch design to see at a simpler way of processing the information. By
what age infants would learn to associate a word 17 to 20 months of age, infants have overcome
with an object in a short period of time. Infants this limitation and can now solve minimal pair
from 8 to 14 months of age were habituated to word-learning tasks. One prediction from the
two different objects (i.e., a toy truck and a toy resource limitation hypothesis, which Fennell
dog) each paired with its own nonsense label and Werker found to be correct, was that if
(i.e., “lif” and “neem”). The critical item in the the required resources were reduced by use of
test phase included both an object and label that familiar word–object pairs (e.g., ball and doll),
were familiar, but the pairing between them then even 14-month-olds would succeed on the
was switched. Only the 14-month-old infants switch design task. From our point of view, this
responded to this switch as novel, thereby dem- resource hypothesis view of early word learn-
onstrating they had learned the association ing is entirely consistent with our constructiv-
between the word and object. Additional con- ist principles including the bottom-up forming
trol studies indicated that the younger infants of an association, the fallback to a simpler level
could indeed discriminate between the two when the task becomes overloaded, and the
objects or between the two labels. They just were reconstruction to a higher level at an older age.
not forming the association between a label and
an object. Thus, even infant early word learning
appears to follow the bottom-up pattern pre- WHAT CAN WE CONCLUDE SO FAR?
dicted by the constructivist principles. Infants I hope this limited presentation of evidence,
first learn the lower-order units (the labels and and similar evidence exists on additional top-
the object). Only later do they learn the relation- ics as well, is persuasive that many aspects of
ship between them. infant perceptual, cognitive, and even early lan-
But that is not the entire story with respect to guage development can be described in terms of
infant word learning. When the labels used are the constructivist principles mentioned in this
minimal pairs (e.g., “bih” vs. “dih”), 14-month- chapter. If that supposition is correct, then we
olds can no longer form the association with can reach a number of conclusions.
the objects. They can discriminate between the
labels, however, when no objects are used, it 1. These principles are domain general. They
is just that the word learning task seems to be apply to the development of many different
beyond their capacity (Stager & Werker, 1997). abilities from simple angle and form perception
By 17 to 20 months of age, though, they do to more abstract cognitive abilities such as cat-
solve this minimal pairs word-learning task as egorization, the understanding of causal events,
shown by the switch design (Werker et al., 2002). and even some aspects of linguistic reference.
However, 14-month-old infants can solve mini- 2. These principles apply across a wide age
mal pairs word-learning task using the switch range. Examples have been provided from birth
design when both words and objects are familiar through 18 months. So it would be inaccurate
(e.g., “ball” vs. “doll”; Fennell & Werker, 1997). to argue that infants process simple units at one
Fennell and Werker argue that this entire age and more complex relations among those
pattern of results can be explained by a units at a specified later age. What counts as a
“resource limitation” hypothesis. According unit is itself relative and depends upon the abil-
to their hypothesis, by 14 months of age, the ity or task that is to be mastered.
342 THE BIG PICTURE

3. The bottom-up aspect of these principles Cohen & Cashon, 2006). Connectionist models
applies more to initial acquisition than to sub- have several appealing characteristics:
sequent use. Once infants have acquired an
1. The models are explicit as to the nature of
advanced level of processing, they will tend to
the input and the architecture. The input nodes
operate at that level unless something overloads
are usually numerical codings of a set of simple
the system. In that case, they will temporarily
features and the internal architecture usually
drop to a lower level. So one could argue this
includes a network of weighted interrelation-
aspect of the principles is really top-down rather
ships produced by the input. Thus, in this sense
than bottom-up.
at least, many of these models are consistent
4. The operation of these principles blurs the
with our constructivist principles.
distinction between development and learning.
2. The models tend to include actual mecha-
Assuming the domain generality of these prin-
nisms of change (or parameters of learning). In
ciples and their applicability even to adult skills
fact, they are designed to change and reorganize
or abilities, the mechanisms of developmental
as a function of repeated inputs and often feed-
change and those of learning or acquisition of
back about the errors being made.
expertise seem to overlap. These principles high-
3. They tend to simulate the behavior they
light some of the processes involved but they do
were designed to explain. Several of these mod-
not really specify the underlying mechanisms of
els were designed to simulate specific results
change. An understanding of these mechanisms
from specific experiments on topics such as
requires models that actually produce develop-
object unity, categorization, or causal percep-
mental changes consonant with the empirical
tion. They usually do a reasonable job in repro-
evidence. Hopefully, these models will also be
ducing those results.
consistent with the constructionist principles
outlined earlier in this chapter. The models also have had some serious
limitations:
CONNECTIONIST MODELING
1. Some suffer from architectural problems
TO THE RESCUE?
such as catastrophic interference. The model
One approach to explanation that has shown might gradually learn but then that learning
some promise in infant perception and cog- can be undone by one negative instance.
nition is called connectionist or neural-net 2. Some might question whether too much
modeling. (For examples, see the chapters by of the work is built into the input nodes.
Christiansen, Dale, and Reali and by Mareschal Certainly one does not have to be a com-
and Westermann in this volume.) Many types plete reductionist and assume input nodes
of connectionist models have been proposed, must reflect biochemical changes in sensory
but they all simulate a neural network to some receptors. On the other hand, one does not
degree in that they have input nodes that feed want to put too much explanatory power into
to intermediate networks that reorganize with sophisticated inputs. In that case, the actual
experience and lead to some type of output. A learning of the model may be relatively triv-
few connectionist models have been described ial compared to what the inputs are assumed
in detail in other chapters of this volume. Many to be processing.
of the early models related to infancy dealt 3. Some people question the neurological real-
with language acquisition and were a reaction ity of certain types of models. One common
to nativist assertions that the most important learning mechanism used in models is back-
aspects of language were innate (Elman et al., ward propagation, which some argue does
1996). Today, more and more of these models are not occur neurologically in the brain. Of
presented as explanations for some topic within course, the reasonableness of this criticism
infant perception and cognition, including most depends upon the goal of the modeler. If
of the topics described earlier in this chapter (see the modeler is trying to provide an accurate
A BOTTOM-UP APPROACH TO INFANT PERCEPTION AND COGNITION 343

representation of the brain, the criticism is (shown at 10 months), but each model made
valid. However, if the modeler is just trying somewhat different assumptions. Westermann
to reproduce the behavior of the infant given and Mareschal’s model assumed a decrease
certain inputs, then the criticism may not over age in the size of infants’ cortical recep-
hold. tive fields; Shultz and Cohen’s (2004) model
4. Finally, most models of infant perception assumed the addition of a hidden unit and an
or cognition deal with performance at one increase in depth of learning; and Gureckis and
particular age. Those that do look at devel- Love’s (2004) model assumed an increase in
opmental change tend to do so in a rather perceptual and/or memory ability with age.
superficial way. Often the modeler will However, the model accomplished the
assume that development can be predicted change, each had to propose some additional
from number of epochs the model has expe- mechanism to account for the developmen-
rienced with the training stimuli. Certainly tal change in infant categorization. Each also
actual developmental change involves much made specific testable predictions, which gener-
more than the amount of training includ- ally were supported. Finally, although all three
ing perhaps changes in the structure of the models predicted the transition from process-
model itself (e.g., Shultz, 2003). ing independent features at 4 months of age to
processing correlations among features at 10
months of age, none was able to reproduce the
RECENT APPROACHES TO MODELING
7-month-olds fallback to independent features
INFANT COGNITIVE DEVELOPMENT
when the task became too difficult for them.
Recently, I have taken two different approaches These models were not presented to show
to foster connectionist modeling of infant that the task is done regarding modeling the
cognitive development. The first has been to development of infant categorization. I men-
challenge modelers from three different labo- tioned them simply to illustrate two points. The
ratories, with somewhat different theoretical first is that each model had to add something or
approaches, to model the same developmental modify its architecture in some way in order to
data. These data came from the Younger and represent developmental change. The second is
Cohen (1983, 1986) experiments on infant cate- that it can be fruitful to compare and contrast
gorization mentioned earlier in this chapter. To multiple models on the same basic phenome-
recall, the experiments presented line drawings non. Each of those models made predictions
of animals to 4-, 7-, and 10-month-old infants. that could have been tested empirically to dis-
The 4-month-olds processed the separate fea- tinguish between them. Unfortunately, in this
tures. Ten-month-olds processed the corre- case, with one exception, the modelers did not
lation among the features, and 7-month-olds go on to conduct these empirical studies. Too
processed the correlation when the task was often modelers stop after successfully simulat-
simple involving only two animals. However, ing some previous empirical evidence. The true
when the task was more complex involving potential power of these models, however, is if
two categories of animals, rather than just two they make future predictions that are shown to
animals, the 7-month-olds reverted to a lower hold empirically.
level and processed separate features, as had the The second approach has been to develop
4-month-olds. our own model, on the development of infants’
Three different models (Gureckis & Love, perception of simple causal events that incor-
2004; Shultz & Cohen, 2004; Westermann & porates all of the constructivist principles
Mareschal, 2004) attempted to reproduce the mentioned earlier (Cohen, Chaput, & Cashon,
developmental changes reported by Younger 2002). Our model is a hierarchical, self-or-
and Cohen. All three models were able to sim- ganizing system that processes simple direct
ulate the transition from independent features launching and similar types of events in which
(shown at 4 months) to correlated features one ball moves across a screen and either does
344 THE BIG PICTURE

or does not make contact with a second object temporarily fall back to lower levels, and then
that then moves the remaining distance across rebuild once again.
the screen. At one level, the model organizes Even though this system describes how
two types of information separately, temporal changes may occur in many aspects of infant
information about the movement of the two perception and cognition, it still is only a
balls and spatial information about the dis- description of behavior and behavioral change.
tance between the two balls. At a higher level, A more complete explanation requires models
the model integrates the movement informa- that are explicit about the mechanisms under-
tion with the spatial information. In so doing, lying that change. Connectionist models may
it also sets up a causal continuum with the most be one vehicle for doing that, but most of the
causal event at one end, the least causal at the ones designed so far for infant perception and
other end, and the somewhat causal events in cognition are limited to a single area of applica-
the middle. This is just what infants eventually tion and do not deal adequately with underly-
seem to do (Leslie and Keeble, 1987). Finally, ing and repeated developmental changes. The
we increased the complexity of the task by models are a good fi rst step, however, and they
adding noise to the events and the model fell do highlight an interesting and important issue.
back to a simpler level, once again processing Fundamentally, they are models of learning,
the movement and spatial information sepa- some that do require feedback and others that
rately. Thus, the model clearly operated accord- just self-organize from the inputs they receive.
ing to the constructivist principles outlined in But they do raise the issue of similarities and
this chapter. differences between mechanisms underlying
learning and mechanisms underlying devel-
opment. Perhaps the two are not so different
CONCLUDING COMMENTS
after all. Perhaps neither is evolutionary change
As the title of this chapter (and of this confer- although, of course, it occurs across generations
ence) implies, I have presented a bottom-up rather than within one generation. Investigators
approach to infant perception and cognition. of infant development, and of development
I have provided evidence from topics as wide more generally, have been very good at dem-
ranging as infant angle perception to infant cat- onstrating some ability at one age and showing
egorization and early word learning that a con- that this ability differs at one or more later ages.
structivist, building block type of system seems But, the Achilles’ heel of developmental research
to capture much of the acquisition process. The has been an inability to account for the actual
system, which is domain-general, and occurs at changes that occur. Perhaps a new interdisci-
many different ages, uses correlational, condi- plinary field is needed, one that brings together
tional, and perhaps other types of relations to those who study learning, development, adapta-
construct higher-older units from combina- tion, and evolution, a field dedicated to under-
tions of lower-order units. standing various types of behavioral change.
But this only describes the acquisition pro- Each could learn from the others, and perhaps
cess, since whenever infants are confronted a more sophisticated understanding of the
with information, they do not automatically mechanisms of change would result. In the
start their processing at the bottom or most ele- present volume on neoconstructive approaches
mentary level and then move on to higher lev- to development, along with a couple of other
els. They operate at a high, more efficient level, books to have appeared recently on neurocon-
unless the system becomes overloaded, in which structive approaches to cognition, Mareschal,
case they may fall back to a lower level. That part Johnson, et al. (2007) and Mareschal, Sirois,
of the process, obviously, is top-down, so one and Westermann (2007) show that construc-
should consider the entire system as much more tive approaches to development once again are
dynamic system with repeating cycles in which on the ascendancy and they are becoming more
infants build up new levels of information, and more interdisciplinary.
A BOTTOM-UP APPROACH TO INFANT PERCEPTION AND COGNITION 345

ACKNOWLEDGMENTS cognition. Cognitive Development, 17(3/4),


1323–1343.
Much of the research presented in this chapter Cohen, L. B., & Oakes, L. M. (1993). How infants
was supported by NIH Grants HD 15035 and HD perceive simple causality. Developmental
23397. Psychology, 29, 421–433.
Cohen, L. B., Rundell, L. J., Spellman, B. A., &
Cashon, C. H. (1999). Infants’ perception
REFERENCES
of causal chains. Psychological Science, 10,
Cashon, C. H., & Cohen, L. B. (2003). The con- 412–418.
struction, deconstruction, and reconstruction Cohen, L. B., & Strauss, M. S. (1977). Concept
of infant face perception. In A. Slater & O. acquisition in the human infant. Child
Pascalis (Eds.), The development of face process- Development, 50, 419–424.
ing in infancy and early childhood (pp. 55–68). Cohen, L. B., & Younger, B. A. (1983). Perceptual
New York: NOVA Science. categorization in the infant. In E. Scholnick
Cashon, C. H., & Cohen, L. B. (2004). Beyond (Ed.), New trends in conceptual representation
u-shaped development in infants’ processing of (pp. 197–220). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum
faces [Special issue]. Journal of Cognition and Associates.
Development, 5, 59–80. Cohen, L. B., & Younger, B. A. (1984). Infant per-
Cohen, L. B., & Amsel, G. (1998). Precursors to ception of angular relations. Infant Behavior
infants’ perception of the causality of a simple and Development, 7, 37–47.
event. Infant Behavior and Development, 21(4), Eizenman, D. R., & Bertenthal, B. I. (1998). Infants’
713–731. perception of object unity in translating and
Cohen, L. B., Amsel, G., Redford, M. A., & rotating displays. Developmental Psychology,
Casasola, M. (1998). The development of infant 34(3), 426–434.
causal perception. In A. Slater (ed.), Perceptual Elman, J., Bates, E., Johnson, M. H., Karmiloff-
development: Visual, auditory, and speech per- Smith, A., Parisi, D., & Plunkett, K. (1996).
ception in infancy (pp. 167–209). East Sussex, Rethinking innateness: A connectionist perspec-
UK: Psychology Press Ltd. tive on development. Cambridge, MA: MIT
Cohen, L.B., & Caputo, N.F. (May, 1978). Instructing Press.
infants to respond to perceptual categories. Fennell, C. T., & Werker, J. F. (2003). Early word
Paper presented at Midwestern Psychological learners’ ability to access phonetic detail in
Association Convention, Chicago. well-known words. Language and Speech,
Cohen, L. B., & Cashon, C. H. (2001). Do 7-month- 46(2), 245–264.
old infants process independent features Gureckis, T. M., & Love, B. C. (2004). Common
or facial configurations? Infant and Child mechanisms in infant and adult category
Development, 10, 83–92. learning. Infancy, 5, 173–198.
Cohen, L. B., & Cashon, C. H. (2003). Infant Johnson, S. P. (2000). The development of visual
perception and cognition. In R. Lerner, A. surface perception: Insights into the ontogeny
Easterbrooks, & J. Mistry (Eds.), Comprehensive of knowledge. In C. Rovee-Collier, L. P. Lipsitt,
handbook of psychology. Vol. 6, Developmental & H. Hayne (Eds.), Progress in infancy research
Psychology. II. Infancy. (pp. 65–89), New York: (Vol. 1, pp. 113–154). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Wiley and Sons. Karmiloff-Smith, A. (1992, reprinted 1995) Beyond
Cohen, L. B. & Cashon, C. H. (2006). Infant cog- modularity: A developmental perspective on
nition. In D. Kuhn & R. S. Siegler (Eds.), cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/
Handbook of child psychology: Vol. 2. Cognition, Bradford Books.
perception, and language (6th ed., pp. 214–251) Kellman, P. J., & Spelke, E. S. (1983). Perception
New York: Wiley. of partly occluded objects in infancy. Cognitive
Cohen, L. B., Cashon, C. H., & Rundell, L. (2004, Psychology, 15, 483–524.
May). Infants’ developing knowledge of a Leslie, A. M. (1982). The perception of causality in
causal agent. Poster presented at International infants. Perception, 11, 15–30.
Conference on Infant Studies, Chicago. Leslie, A. M. (1986). Getting development off the
Cohen, L. B., Chaput, H. H., & Cashon, C. H. ground: Modularity and the infant’s percep-
(2002). A constructivist model of infant tion of causality. In P. van Geert (Ed.), Theory
346 THE BIG PICTURE

building in developmental psychology (pp. Shultz, T. R., & Cohen, L. B. (2004). Modeling age
406–437). Amsterdam: North Holland. differences in infant category learning. Infancy,
Leslie, A. M., & Keeble, S. (1987). Do 6-month-olds 5, 153–171.
perceive causality? Cognition, 25, 265–288. Slater, A. (1995). Visual perception and memory
Madole, K. L., & Oakes, L. M. (1999). Making at birth. In C. Rovee-Collier and L. P. Lipsitt
sense of infant categorization: Stable processes (Eds.), Advances in infancy research (Vol. 9,
and changing representations. Developmental pp. 107–162). Norwood, NJ: Ablex.
Review, 19, 263–296. Slater, A., Johnson, S. P., Brown, E., & Badenoch,
Mareschal, D., Johnson, M.H., Sirois, S., Spratling, M. (1996). Newborn infants’ perception of
M., Thomas, M., & Westermann, G. (2007). partly occluded objects. Infant Behavior and
Neuroconstructivism, Vol. I: How the brain con- Development, 19, 145–148.
structs cognition. Oxford: Oxford University Slater, A., Johnson, S. P., Kellman, P. J., & Spelke,
Press. E. S. (1994). The role of three-dimensional
Mareschal, D., Sirois, S., & Westermann, G. (2007). depth cues in infants’ perception of partly
Neuroconstructivism, Vol. II: Perspectives and occluded objects. Early Development and
Prospects. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Parenting, 3, 187–191.
Michotte, A. (1963). The perception of causality. Slater, A. M., Mattock, A., Brown, E., & Bremner,
NewYork: BasicBooks. J. G. (1991). Form perception at birth: Cohen
Quinn, P. C., Adams, A., Kennedy, E., Shettler, and Younger revisited. Journal of Experimental
L., & Wasnik, A. (2003). Development of an Child Psychology, 51, 395–405.
abstract category representation for the spatial Stager, C.L., & Werker, J.F. (1997). Infants listen
relation between 6- to 10-month-old infants. for more phonetic detail in speech perception
Developmental Psychology, 39(1), 151–163. than in word learning tasks. Nature, 388(6640),
Quinn, P. C., & Eimas, P. D. (2000). The emergence 381–382.
of category representations during infancy: Werker, J. F., Cohen, L. B., Lloyd, V. L., Casasola,
Are separate perceptual and conceptual pro- M., & Stager, C. L. (1998). Acquisition of word–
cesses required? Journal of Cognition and object associations by 14-month-old infants.
Development, 1, 55–61. Developmental Psychology, 34(6), 1289–1309.
Quinn, P. C., Eimas, P. D., & Rosenkrantz, S. L. Werler. J. F., Fennell, C. T., Corcoran, K. M., &
(1993). Evidence for representations of percep- Stager, C. L. (2002). Infants’ ability to learn
tually similar natural categories by 3-month- phonetically similar words: Effects of age and
old and 4-month-old infants. Perception, 22, vocabulary. Infancy, 3. 1–30.
463–475. Westermann, G., & Mareschal, D. (2004). From parts
Rakison, D. H., & Butterworth, G. E. (1998). to wholes: Mechanisms of development in infant
Infants’ use of object parts in early categoriza- visual object processing. Infancy, 5, 131–151.
tion. Developmental Psychology, 34(1), 49–62. Younger, B. A., & Cohen, L. B. (1983). Infant per-
Schafer, G., & Plunkett, K. (1998). Rapid word ception of correlations among attributes. Child
learning by fi fteen-month-olds under tightly Development, 54, 858–867.
controlled conditions. Child Development Younger, B. A., & Cohen, L. B. (1986).
69(2): 309–320. Developmental change in infants’ percep-
Shultz, T. R. (2003). Computational developmental tion of correlations among attributes. Child
psychology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Development, 57, 803–815.
AUTHOR INDEX

Abecassis, M., 116 Aujard, Y., 321


Abrams, R. M., 147 Austin, G. A., 253
Abu-Mostafa, Y. S., 104 Avanzini, G., 132
Acerra, F., 321, 328
Acker, B. E., 144
Adams, A., 340 Bachevalier, J., 5
Adamson, L. B., 297 Baddour, R., 121
Adler, S. A., 184 Badenoch, M., 49, 338
Adolph, K. A., 57 Badertscher, B., 133
Aguiar, A., 52 Badridze, N., 9
Ahn, W., 160 Bahrick, L. E., 32, 34, 147
Akerstrom, R. A., 33 Baillargeon, R., v, 47, 48, 52, 62, 65, 69, 78, 163, 195, 295,
Alcock, K. J., 147 296, 305, 308
Alibali, M. W., 188 Baird, J., 300
Allan, L. G., 160 Baker, P. N., 9
Allen, J., 34, 133, 180 Balaban, M. T., 277, 281, 286, 287
Allen, R., 187 Baldwin, D. A., 235, 287, 295, 300
Allison, B. Z., 302 Baldwin, J. M., 296
Allopenna, P., 89, 100 Banks, M. S., 33, 259, 317
Almli, C. R., 8, 9 Barba, B. D., 19
Altenmüller, E., 132 Bar-Haim, Y., 267
Alter, K., 89 Barkovich, A. J., 9
Altmann, G. T. M., 181, 183 Barnes, R., 144
Altschuler, E. L., 302 Barresi, J., 296, 301, 307
Amano, S., 182 Barrett, T., 123
Amsel, G., 336, 339 Barr-Haim, Y., 321
Amso, D., 40, 50, 51, 54, 55, 65, 123, 184 Bart, E., 114
Anderson, A. W., 323 Bartch, K., 308
Anderson, J. R., 214 Barthelemy, C., 302
Anllo-Vento, L., 19 Bartlett, J. C., 323
Arbib, M. A., 119, 302 Bartrip, J., 267
Arterberry, M. E., 50 Bastuji, H., 204
Aschersleben, G., 296, 300, 301, 302, 309 Bates, E. A., 109, 185, 297, 315, 342
Ashby, F. G., 220 Battin, M., 9
Aslin, R. N., 33, 35, 36, 49, 50, 64, 90, 133, 134, 142, 164, Bauer, P. J., 235, 254
181, 182, 184, 188, 189, 195, 196, 300 Bednar, J. A., 328
Asscher, J. J., 174 Beek, P. J., 144
Atkinson, A. P., 326 Behl-Chadha, G., 219
Atkinson, J., 4, 18, 321 Behne, T., 246, 296
Atran, S., 265 Behrens, H., 104
Attneave, F., 33 Benasich, A. A., 9

347
348 AUTHOR INDEX

Berent, I., 186 Brody, B., 3


Berglan, L. R., 160, 166 Brody, R. E., 89
Berlucchi, G., 321 Broen, P., 92
Bernardo, K. L., 46 Bronson, G. W., 4, 321
Bernstein-Ratner, N., 91, 100, 190 Brooks, P. J., 89, 103
Bertenthal, B. I., 65, 67, 297, 338 Brooks, R., 300
Berthier, N. E., 78 Broughton, J. M., 65
Bertoncini, J., 90, 147 Brown, A. L., 163, 175
Best, C. A., 266 Brown, E., 49, 326, 337, 338
Best, C. T., 200 Brown, E. D., 8, 12
Bever, T. G., 90, 180 Brown, R., 183
Bharucha, J. J., 133 Brown, R. R., 143
Biederman, I., 110, 112, 113, 116, 122 Brown, S., 133
Bigand, E., 132, 133 Bruce, V., 323, 326
Bijeljac, R., 90 Brune, C., 297
Billman, D., 103 Bruner, J. S., 253
Binder, J. R., 146 Bruno, N., 33
Biro, S., 195, 242, 296, 300, 305, 306, 307 Bryant, P. E., 163
Black, J. E., vi, 69, 316 Buccino, G., 302
Blair, N. J., 166 Bucher, N. M., 123
Blakemore, S. J., 304 Buck, J., 144
Blanz, V., 120, 121 Bukach, C. M., 252, 269
Blasdell, A. P., 175 Bulf, H., 327
Bloom, P., 262, 295 Bullemer, P., 35
Bloomfield, L., 180 Bullock, M., 163, 168
Blum, B., 160, 175 Bülthoff, H. H., 33, 119
Blumenthal, E. J., 169 Burgess, R. E., 9
Bollt, A., 200, 208 Burkhalter, A., 46
Bonatti, L. L., 185 Burnham, D., 142
Booth, A. E., 171, 277, 287 Burnod, I., 321
Bootzin, R., 203, 204, 208, 209 Bushnell, I. W. R., 324
Borenshteyn, N., 3 Butcher, P. R., 19
Born, J., 204 Butterworth, G. E., 110, 114, 239, 247, 340
Bortfeld, H., 182 Buxton, R. B., 19
Borton, R., 63
Botte, M., 144
Bouquet, F., 15 Calabresi, P. A., 19
Bourgeois, J. P., 5, 6 Caldara, R., 322
Bower, G. H., 90 Caldi, S., 308
Bower, N. J. A., 324 Call, J., 246, 296
Bower, T. G. R., 47, 62, 64, 65, 67, 70, 324 Calvo-Merino, B., 303
Boyes-Braem, P., 268 Campos, J. J., 77
Braddick, O. J., 4, 321 Canfield, R. L., 184
Braine, M. D. S., 89, 187 Cannard, C., 204
Brake, S., 326 Caputo, N. F., 339
Brakefield, T., 202 Carbon, C. C., 316
Brannon, E. M., 196 Carey, S., 39, 62, 64, 65, 171, 216, 262, 265, 268, 276, 323
Brashers-Krug, T., 201 Carlson-Luden, V., 297
Bregman, A. S., 187 Carpenter, M., 246, 296, 297
Brehmer, B., 33 Carter, A., 96
Breinlinger, K., 52, 79 Carter, D. M., 182
Bremner, J. G., 40, 52, 53, 54, 65, 67, 77, 326, 337 Cartwright, T. A., 104
Brennan, C. W., 19 Casasola, M., 336, 341
Brent, H. P., 316 Casey, B. J., 4
Brent, M. R., 104 Cashon, C. H., 58, 260, 336, 337, 338, 339, 342, 343
Bretherton, I., 297 Cassidy, K. W., 89, 92
Brezsnyak, M. P., 184 Catalano, L., 89
Brockbank, M., 242 Catmur, C., 303
AUTHOR INDEX 349

Cerella, J., 114 Courage, M., 13


Chalkley, M. A., 89 Craighero, L., 119
Challamell, M-J., 204 Cramer, R. E., 160
Chance, G., 34 Cramon, Y., 143
Changeux, J. P., 219 Crane, C. C., 296
Chao, L. L., 119 Creel, S. C., 133
Chapman, M., v Crivello, F., 321
Chaput, H. H., 343 Crocker, R. L., 143
Charles, V., 46 Cross, D., 172
Charles-Luce, J., 187 Cross, I., 143
Charniak, E., 180 Cruttenden, L., 68
Chater, N., 89, 93, 95, 180, 216 Csibra, G., 13, 67, 142, 195, 242, 243, 246, 295, 296, 305,
Chen, S., 196 307, 308, 328
Cheng, P. W., 160, 166 Cuddy, L. L., 133
Cheour, M., 321 Culicover, P. W., 276
Cheshire, A., 40, 53 Cummins, F., 138
Chi, M. T., 269 Curran, T., 35, 268
Choate, L. S., 19 Curtin, S., 180, 181, 182
Chomsky, N., v, 314 Cutler, A., 89, 100, 147, 182
Christiansen, M. H., 34, 87, 89, 90, 93, 95, 103, 133, 138, Cutting, J. E., 33
180, 181
Christie, M. A., 196
Christophe, A., 90 Dabholkar, A. S., 141
Christou, C. G., 118 Dahan, D., 183
Chun, M. M., 35, 316 Dale, R. A. C., 34, 87, 103
Cicchino, J. B., 114, 233, 234, 236, 239, 244, 246, Dalla Barba, B., 324
247, 248 Dalla Bella, S., 132
Clark, E. V., 266 Dalrymple-Alford, J. C., 196
Clarke, E. F., 138 Daniele, J. R., 148
Clayton, M., 138 Danks, D., 161
Clements, H., 9 Dannemiller, J. L., 4
Clifton, R. K., 52, 54, 297 Darby, B. L., 63
Clohessy, A. B., 19 Das Gupta, P., 163
Cochin, S., 302 Davidow, J., 50, 195
Cohen, A., 35 de Haan, M., 13, 136, 321, 325, 328
Cohen, D. A., 202 de Heering, A., 327
Cohen, L. B., 58, 75, 114, 168, 239, 260, 277, 335, 336, de Schonen, S., 267, 315, 316, 321, 324, 325, 327
337, 338, 339, 340, 341, 342, 343 de Vries, M. M., 9
Cohen, N. J., 205 Decety, J., 119, 302, 304
Cohen, Y., 17 Dehaene, S., 9, 15, 219
Coley, J. D., 265, 276, 286 Dehaene-Lambertz, G., 9, 10, 15, 147, 262
Collier, G. L., 144, 145 DeLong, K. A., 183
Collins, D. L., 8, 12, 65 Demuth, K., 104
Colombo, J., 38 Deruelle, C., 324, 327
Coltheart, M., 132, 147 Desain, P., 148
Colunga, E., 110, 208, 276, 277 Deutsch, D., 144
Combs, B., 33 DeVos, J., 69
Compston, A., 132 Diamond, A., 68, 70
Conel, J. L., 3, 7 Diamond, R., 323
Conway, C. M., 133 Dickinson, A., 160
Conway, M., 142 Doran, M. M., 259
Cooper, E. E., 112 Dosher, B. A., 33
Cooper, L. A., 125 Dougherty, J. W. D., 269
Cooper, R. P., 147 Dow, G. A., 235, 254
Corrie, B., 121 Dow, K. A., 190
Cosmides, L., v Dowling, W. J., 143
Coulson, S., 90 Doyon, B., 112
Counsell, S., 9 Drake, C., 144
350 AUTHOR INDEX

Drayna, D., 132 Fernald, A., 89, 90, 103, 183, 190
Drummey, A., 206 Fernandes, K. J., 147
Dubowitz, D. J., 19 Ferrari, P. F., 304
Dudai, Y., 205 Fidopiastis, C., 258
Dueker, G., 254 Fielding, K., 9
Duke, S., 174 Fiez, J. A., 142
Duncan, K. R., 9 Fifer, W. P., 147
Dunphy-Lelii, S., 309 Finch, S., 89
Duvdevani-Bar, S., 112 Findlay, J. M., 120
Dziurawiec, S., 317 Fink, P., 132
Fischer, S., 202
Fischoff, B., 33
Earle, D. C., 318 Fiser, J., 33, 35, 36, 164
Easterbrook, M. A., 317 Fisher, A. F., 283
Edelman, G., 119 Fisher, A. V., 235, 276, 278, 280, 282, 283, 284, 285,
Edelman, S., 112 286, 287
Eerola, T., 134 Fisher, C., 89, 91, 92
Efron, R., 125 Fishman, Y. I., 143
Eimas, P. D., 136, 219, 221, 222, 249, 253, 255, 258, 262, Fize, D., 112
265, 326, 340 Flanagan, J. R., 303
Eisbach, A. O. D., 172 Flavell, J. H., 172
Eizenman, D. R., 338 Flax, J. F., 3, 9
Ell, S. W., 220 Flom, R., 34
Ellenbogen, J. M., 202 Fodor, J. A., v, 73, 147, 314
Ellis, H., 317 Fogassi, L., 302, 304
Elman, J. L., vi, 90, 104, 181, 183, 185, 315, 316, 328, Foster, C. L., 35
336, 342 Foster, K., 40, 53
Elsner, B., 300 Fox, M., 8
Emerson, D. R., 188 Fox, P. T., 8, 12
Endress, A., 15 Foxton, J. M., 147
Engbert, R., 145 Fraisse, P., 138
Engelmann, T., 202 Frank, L. R., 19
Ernst, M. O., 33 Frank, M. C., 50, 195, 203
Essens, P., 138, 144 Freire, A., 266, 323
Estes, W. K., 280, 281 Freitas, C. S., 8
Estes, Z., 257 French, R. M., 219, 221, 223, 259, 261, 264, 276, 277
Euston, D. R., 202 Frenkiel-Fishman, S., 234
Evans, A. C., 8, 9, 10, 12 Freudenthal, D., 104
Evans, J. L., 188, 190 Freyd, J. J., 119
Friederici, A. D., 89, 136, 143, 147, 187
Frigo, L., 89
Fabre-Grenet, M., 324 Frisby, J. P., 33
Fabre-Thorpe, M. L., 112 Fritz, T., 143
Fadiga, L., 302 Furrer, S. D., 241
Fagot, B. I., 266
Falck-Ytter, T., 303
Fantz, R. L., 219 Gais, S., 202, 204
Farah, M. J., 316, 323 Galland, N., 185
Farah, T., 323 Gallese, V., 302, 304
Farroni, T., 318, 324, 325 Gallistel, C. R., 180
Fawcett, C., 171 Galluccio, L., 205, 209
Fearing, D. D., 253 Gangitano, M., 302
Feltovich, P. J., 269 Garcia, V., 195
Feng, Q., 54, 65, 184 Gathercole, V. C. M., 110
Fenn, K., 202 Gauthier, I., 119, 252, 263, 265, 268, 316, 323
Fennell, C. T., 341 Ge, L., 321
Fenson, L., 111, 117 Geertz, C., vii
Fenwick, K. D., 34 Geldart, S., 316
AUTHOR INDEX 351

Gelman, R., v, 163, 238, 244, 249, 276, 314 Grewe, O., 132
Gelman, S. A., 163, 235, 257, 276, 277, 278, 284, 286 Grezes, J., 119, 302, 303
Gentner, D., 110, 175, 305, 306, 307, 308 Griffiths, T. D., 147
Gergely, G., 195, 242, 243, 246, 295, 296, 305, 307 Griffiths, T. L., 159, 160, 163, 167, 168,
Gerken, L. A., 35, 87, 89, 90, 95, 96, 133, 164, 182, 185, 172, 173, 175
187, 189, 190, 195, 200, 208 Grzywacz, N. M., 64
Gerlach, C., 119 Guajardo, J. J., 246, 295, 297, 298
Gershkoff-Stowe, L., 110, 278 Gueze, R. H., 19
Gertner, S., 203 Gunter, T. C., 147
Gervain, J., 15 Gureckis, T. M., 343
Ghim, H. R., 326
Gibbs, B. J., 64
Gibson, E. J., 34 Haberl, K., 296
Gibson, J. J., 67, 123 Haggard, P., 303
Gigerenzer, G., 33 Hagmayer, Y., 160, 175
Giguere, J., 132 Hahn, E. R., 236
Gilles, F., 3 Haith, M. M., 35, 49, 65, 164, 184
Gilmore, J. H., 9 Halit, H., 321
Gilmore, R. O., 38 Hall, A., 9
Glaser, D. E., 303 Hall, G., 283
Glaser, R., 269 Hall, M. D., 144
Gleitman, H., 90 Hall-Haro, C., 50, 195
Gleitman, L. R., 89, 90, 100, 104 Hallinan, E. V., 296
Gliga, T., 262, 328 Hamlin, J. K., 296
Glymour, C., 161 Hamm, J. P., 122
Gobet, F., 104 Hampton, J. A., 257
Goffaux, V., 327 Hanlon, C., 183
Goldman, A., 304 Hannon, E. E., 132, 134, 135, 136, 138, 139, 140, 141,
Goldstein, M. H., 182 144, 145, 146, 148, 149
Goldstone, R. L., 113, 115, 116, 259 Hara, J., 7
Golinkoff, R. M., 182 Hardt, O., 206, 207, 208
Gómez, R. L., 35, 90, 164, 182, 185, 187, 190, 195, 196, Hari, R., 303
197, 198, 199, 200, 201, 203, 204, 206, 207, 208, 209 Harkness, W., 321
Gonzalez, S., 13 Harman, K. L., 119, 121
Goodale, M. A., 121, 122, 123, 125 Harries, M. H., 121
Goodman, G. S., 184 Harris, P. L., 70, 77, 174, 304
Goodnow, J. J., 253 Harris, Z. S., 180
Goodsitt, J. V., 181 Harvey, P. R., 9
Gopnik, A., vi, 159, 160, 161, 162, 163, 164, 169, 171, 173, Harwood, D. L., 143
174, 175, 214, 215, 216 Hatano, G., 263, 265
Gordon, R. M., 304 Hatzakis, H., 13
Gore, J. C., 323 Hauert, C. A., 322
Goren, C., 317 Hauf, P., 300, 301, 306, 307
Goswami, U., 163, 175 Hauser, M. D., 35, 132, 181, 189, 196
Gottfried, G. M., 163 Haxby, J. V., 64
Goubet, N., 57 Hay, D. C., 323
Gowland, P. A., 9 Hay, J. F., 188
Grabe, E., 147 Hayes, R., 326
Graber, M., 69 Hayward, W. G., 112, 113
Graf Estes, K., 188 Haywood, S. L., 183
Grafton, S. T., 144, 302 Hazan, C., 184
Graham, S. A., 277 Hazeltine, R. E., 134
Grave de Peraltz, R., 13 Heal, J., 304
Gray, W., 268 Heerschap, A., 9
Gredebäck, G., 54, 80, 303 Heineman-Pieper, J., 300
Green, D. M., 33 Heinmiller, B. M., 143
Green, T. R. G., 90 Heinze, H. J., 19
Greenough, W. T., vi, 316 Heit, E., 215
352 AUTHOR INDEX

Hellawell, D., 323 Iverson, P., 142


Herlihy, A., 9 Ivry, R. B., 35, 134, 144, 202
Hernandez-Reif, M., 34
Heron, M., 262, 266
Herry, C., 144 Jackendoff, R., 137
Hertsgaard, L. A., 254 Jackson, D. E., 9
Hertwig, R., 33 Jackson, G., 321
Hertz-Pannier, L., 9, 15 Jacob, P., 304
Heyes, C. M., 35 Jacobs, R. A., 134
Hildebrand, E. A., 296 Jacobson, K., 52, 79
Hill, E. A., 182 James, K. H., 119, 121, 125
Hill, K. T., 75 James, W., 41
Hillyard, S. A., 19, 20 Janata, P., 132, 144
Hinrichs, H., 19 Järveläinen, J., 303
Hiraki, K., 303 Järvinen, T., 134
Hobson, J. A., 202 Jaswal, V., 196
Hodes, R. M., 267, 321 Jeannerod, M., 122, 123, 304
Hoerl, C., 163 Jiang, Y., 35
Hoff man, J. E., 259 Johansen, M. K., 252, 263
Hohenberger, A., 309 Johansson, R. S., 303
Höhle, B., 104 Johnson, B. W., 302
Hole, G. J., 323 Johnson, C. N., 172
Holley, F. B., 5 Johnson, D., 268
Hommel, B., 302 Johnson, E. K., 35, 133, 164, 182, 188, 189
Honing, H., 148 Johnson, I. R., 9
Hood, B. M., 4, 18, 19, 20, 321 Johnson, J. A., 34
Hood, R., 35, 164 Johnson, K. E., 239, 241
Hopkins, E. J., 175 Johnson, M. H., 3, 4, 5, 7, 13, 18, 19, 38, 67, 77, 142, 220,
Houle, S., 64 258, 260, 315, 317, 319, 321, 324, 325
Houston, D. M., 182 Johnson, S. C., 171, 234, 296
Howard, D. V., 35 Johnson, S. P., 34, 36, 37, 39, 40, 41, 45, 46, 48, 49, 50, 51,
Howard, J. H., 35 52, 53, 54, 55, 56, 57, 65, 80, 123, 133, 134, 135, 147,
Huber, A., 168 164, 184, 189, 195, 274, 300, 326, 338, 342
Huizenga, H. M., 13 Johnston, E. B., 33
Hume, D., 160 Johnston, H. J., 144
Hummel, J. E., 112 Johnston, R. S., 125
Humphrey, G. K., 120, 121, 122, 123 Jolicoeur, P., 122, 123
Humphreys, G. W., 120, 123 Jones, L. A., 122, 123
Humphreys, N. K., 263 Jones, M. R., 144
Hunt, J. M. V., 164 Jones, S. S., 110, 114, 125, 208, 249, 257, 277, 278
Hunter, S. K., 4, 5, 13, 19, 20 Jongman, A., 89, 100
Hupbach, A., 204, 206, 207, 208, 209 Jonsson, B., 78
Huron, D., 132, 134, 148 Jovanovic, B., 296
Hutchison, J. E., 208 Jusczyk, A. M., 190
Huttenlocher, J., vi, 77 Jusczyk, P. W., 87, 89, 90, 136, 147, 182, 187, 188, 189,
Huttenlocher, P. R., 7, 141 190, 287
Hyde, K. L., 132, 147 Juslin, P. N., 132

Iacoboni, M., 302, 304 Kagan, J., 49, 143


Iliescu, B. F., 4 Kahneman, D., 64
Imada, T., 147 Kalocsai, P., 116
Imai, M., 110 Kalverboer, A. F., 19
Inagaki, K., 263, 265 Kamide, Y., 183
Inhelder, B., 49 Kamin, L. J., 162
Intrator, N., 112 Kane, M. J., 175
Issa, N., 203 Kangarlu, A., 9
Iversen, J. R., 148 Kanwisher, N., 316
AUTHOR INDEX 353

Kaplan, G. A., 67 Kotovsky, L., 306, 307


Kapur, S., 64 Koutstaal, W., 283
Karmiloff-Smith, A., vi, 88, 133, 142, 217, 258, 315, Kovacic, D., 15
335, 342 Kramer, J. A., 75
Karni, A., 202 Krampe, R., 145
Karthigasan, J., 3 Kravitz, J., 269
Kaschak, M. P., 185 Krojgaard, P., 62, 65
Kaufman, J., 67 Kruger, A. C., 88
Keck, W., 203 Krumhansl, C. L., 132, 133, 134, 137
Keeble, S., 168, 339, 344 Kruschke, J. K., 166
Keele, S. W., 35, 202 Kuefner, D., 322
Keil, F. C., 110, 134, 216, 257, 276 Kuhl, P. K., 34, 87, 90, 136, 139, 141, 142, 181, 182, 190,
Keller, P. E., 138 321
Kellman, P. J., 47, 48, 49, 50, 113, 195, 274, 314, 338 Kuhlmeier, V. A., 262, 295, 309
Kelly, D. J., 136, 139, 267, 268, 321 Kuhn, A., 266
Kelly, M. H., 89, 92, 100, 189 Kushnir, T., 161, 175
Kelly, R. L., 8, 12 Kutas, M., 13, 183
Kelso, J. A., 132, 145
Kemler Nelson, D. G., 89, 203
Kemp, C., 173 Lagnado, D. A., 160, 175, 176
Kennedy, E., 340 Laje, R., 144
Kenny, P. A., 315 Lakusta, L., 185, 198, 199, 208
Kenny, S., 65 Lalonde, C. E., 136, 142
Kersten, D., 215 Lalonde, N., 309
Kessen, W., 65 Lamy, D., 267, 321
Khateb, A., 112 Lancaster, J. L., 8, 12
Kiehl, K. A., 146 Landau, B., 110, 249, 277, 278
Killen, M., 235 Landing, B. H., 7
Kilmer, A. D., 143 Landis, T., 112
Kimki, R., 326 Landy, M. S., 33
Kinchla, R. A., 33 Lantz, G., 13
King, A. P., 182 Lany, J. A., 185, 200, 201, 208
Kinney, H., 3, 7 Laplante, D. P., 317
Kiraly, I., 296, 300, 306 Large, E. W., 132, 138, 144
Kirkham, N. Z., 32, 33, 34, 36, 37, 38, 39, 40, 41, 133, Large, M. E., 122
162, 163, 164, 165, 166, 184, 189, 195, 300 Laukka, P., 132
Kirschner, D., 3 Lawson, R., 120
Kisilevsky, B. S., 317 Layman, M., 33
Kjos, B. O., 9 Lazeyras, F., 322
Klahr, D., vi, 174, 214 Le Doux, J. E., 205
Klapp, S. T., 144 Le Grand, R., 116, 316
Kleiner, K. A., 317 Lecours, A. R., 3
Kleitman, N., 202 Leder, H., 316, 323, 326
Kliegl, R., 145 Lederman, S. J., 122, 123
Klingberg, T., 3, 25 Lee, K., 266, 321, 323
Kloman, A., 3 Leevers, H., 175
Kloos, H., 285, 287 Leinbach, M. D., 266
Kochukhova, O., 54, 65, 80 Leo, I., 314, 320, 322, 325
Kochunov, P. V., 8 Lepage, J., 303
Koelsch, S., 132, 133, 143, 147 Lerdahl, F., 137
Koenig, M. A., 174 Leslie, A. M., 62, 168, 244, 249, 296, 300, 305, 306, 307,
Köhler, S., 64 339, 344
Koizumi, H., 15 Levin, D. T., 276
Kojima, S., 147 Levitt, A., 89
Kok, R. D., 9 Lewis, D. J., 205
Koós, O., 242 Lewis, T. L., 4
Kopiez, R., 132 Lewis, W., 185
Korman, M., 91, 202 Lewkowicz, D. J., 32, 34, 136, 281
354 AUTHOR INDEX

Lew-Williams, C., 183 Mangun, G. R., 19


Liben, L. S., 57 Mansfield, P., 9
Liberman, A. M., 147 Maquet, P., 202
Lichenstein, S. P., 33 Maratsos, M., 89
Lickliter, R., 32, 34 Marchman, V. A., 190
Liddle, P. F., 146 Marcovitch, S., 78
Liegeois, F., 324 Marcus, G. F., 147, 181, 183, 185, 186, 216
Lieven, E., 104 Mareschal, D., 77, 213, 214, 216, 217, 219, 221, 222, 224,
Lillard, A. S., 172 225, 253, 259, 261, 264, 276, 343
Lim, K. O., 8 Margoliash, D., 202
Liotti, M., 8, 13 Markman, E. M., 208, 235, 274, 276, 277, 278, 284,
Litovsky, R. Y., 52 286, 287
Liu, G. T., 316 Markow, D. B., 281, 286
Liu, H-M., 139, 142, 182, 190 Marks, W., 283
Liu, Q., 321 Markson, L., 171
Liu, S., 321 Marr, D., 112, 122, 124, 175, 216, 225
Liu, T., 125 Martin, A., 119
Liu, W.-C., 9 Martin, S., 189
Lloyd, V. L., 341 Martineau, J., 302
Lo, Y.-F., 278, 280, 281, 282, 284, 286 Martinez, A., 19, 22, 23
Loewenstein, J., 306 Masataka, N., 143
Loft us, E. F., 201, 206 Maslen, R., 104
Logothetis, N. K., 316 Mason, U., 40, 53
London, J., 138, 146 Massaro, D. W., 33
Longcamp, M., 119 Massey, C. M., 276
Longo, M. R., 65 Mathivet, E., 327
Louis, J., 204 Mattingly, I. G., 147
Love, B. C., 343 Mattock, A., 49, 337
Low, E. L., 147 Mattys, S. L., 90, 187
Luce, P. A., 90, 187 Maurer, D., 4, 116, 316, 323, 326
Luciana, M., 315 Maye, J., 133, 136, 182, 196, 197, 200, 203
Luck, S. J., 19 Mayhew, J. E., 33
Luo, Y., 295, 296 Mayr, R., 145
Lupyan, G., 115, 239, 244 Mazoyer, B., 321
Mazziotta, J. C., 8, 12
McArthur, D., 297
Maalouf, E. F., 9 McAuley, D., 132
Macchi Cassia, V., 317, 318, 319, 320, 322, 324, 325, McCandliss, B. D., 142
326, 327 McClelland, J. L., vi, 77, 142, 181, 182, 185, 220, 226,
MacDonald, M. C., 180, 183, 185, 187 256, 266, 269, 276
MacKay, D. J. C., 214, 215, 226 McCormack, T., 163
Mackenzie, N., 144 McCrink, K., 195
Mackintosh, N. J., 160 McCune-Nicolich, L., 109
Macomber, J., 52, 79 McDermott, J., 132, 316
MacWhinney, B., 91, 102, 175 McDermott, K. B., 283
Madole, K. L., 239, 249, 277, 340 McDonald, J. L., 89, 103
Maess, B., 147 McDonough, L., 220, 234, 235, 236, 237, 238, 239, 240,
Magnuson, J. S., 183 241, 242, 244, 249
Mahajan, N., 296 McGaugh, J. L., 201
Mainela-Arnold, E., 188 McGoldrick, J. E., 258, 259
Maki, A., 15 McKee, S. P., 64
Maloney, L. T., 33 McKinstry, R. C., 8, 9
Malpass, R. S., 269 McLeod, P., 217
Malt, B., 269 McLin, D., 68
Mamassian, P., 215 McMullen, E., 133
Mancini, J., 324, 325, 327 McMullen, P. A., 122
Mandel, D. R., 89 McMurray, B., 142, 184
Mandler, J. M., 216, 220, 234, 235, 236, 237, 238, 239, McNair, N. A., 302
240, 241, 242, 244, 249, 276 McNaughton, B. L., 202, 220
AUTHOR INDEX 355

McRoberts, G. W., 89, 90, 103, 200 Müller, K., 143


Mecklinger, A., 119 Mullin, J. T., 324
Medin, D. L., 262, 265, 280, 284 Munakata, Y., 54, 77
Medina, J., 306, 308 Munro, S. A., 171
Meegan, D. V., 134 Murphy, G. L., 268, 269
Mehler, J., 15, 89, 90, 97, 147, 185 Murray, M. M., 13
Meier, R. P., 89, 90, 185, 187 Musseler, J., 302
Melartin, E. M., 235 Muthukumaraswamy, S. D., 302
Meltzoff, A. N., vi, 34, 61, 62, 63, 64, 65, 67, 68, 69, 70, Mutter, S. A., 35
71, 72, 73, 74, 75, 77, 79, 80, 164, 169, 175, 295, 296, Myers, C., 9
300, 301, 303, 308, 309
Mermillod, M., 259, 264, 276
Mervis, C. B., 268 Nádasdy, Z., 195, 242, 307
Metzler, J., 57 Nadel, L., 203, 204, 205, 206, 207, 208, 209
Meulemans, T., 33 Nader, K., 205, 206, 209
Meyer, L. B., 134 Nagell, K., 297
Michel, C. M., 13, 112, 322 Namy, L., 109
Michel, G. F., 315 Náñez, J. E., 48, 49
Michotte, A., 67, 160, 339 Naoi, N., 147
Mikiten, S. A., 8 Napolitano, A. C., 278, 281, 283, 286, 287
Milani, I., 319, 326 Narain, C., 146
Miller, G. F., 132 Narayana, P. A., 8
Miller, R. R., 205 National Institutes of Health (NIH), 8, 9
Mills, S. L., 8, 12 Navon, D., 326
Milner, A. D., 125 Nayer, S., 234
Milner, B., 8, 12 Nazzi, T., 147, 149
Milner, D., 122, 123 Needham, A., 123, 254, 298
Min, H., 110 Neiderman, D., 68
Minagawa-Kawai, Y., 147 Nelson, C. A., 116, 136, 141, 142, 220, 221, 254, 255, 315,
Minda, J. P., 252, 263 316, 321, 322, 328
Mindlin, G. B., 144 Nespor, M., 147, 185
Mintz, T. H., 89, 90, 180, 181, 182 Netto, D., 34
Misanin, J. R., 205 Neville, H. J., 13
Mitchell, T., 215, 226 Newcombe, N. S., v, vi, 65, 77, 206
Moeser, S. D., 187 Newell, A., 216
Molenaar, P. C. M., 13 Newell, F. N., 120
Moll, H., 246, 296 Newell, L. C., 266
Monaghan, P., 34, 89, 99, 100, 102 Newman, R., 190
Mondloch, C. J., 116, 316 Newport, E. L., 35, 89, 90, 133, 164, 180, 181, 182, 185,
Montessori, M., 175 187, 188, 189, 195, 196, 300
Moon, C., 147 Newsome, M., 182
Moore, C. L., 296, 301, 307, 315 Nickerson, D., 8
Moore, D. S., 57 Nigam, M., 174
Moore, M. K., 61, 62, 63, 64, 65, 67, 68, 69, 70, 71, 72, 73, Nishihara, H. K., 122
74, 75, 76, 77, 79, 80, 303 Nissen, M. J., 35
Morais, J., 132 Norman, D., 9
Morgan, J. L., 89, 90, 100, 103, 104, 181, 182, 183, 185, Nosofsky, R. M., 281
187 Novick, L. R., 160
Mori, K., 147 Nunez, P. L., 13
Morikawa, K., 123, 125, 129 Nusbaum, H., 202
Morison, V., 49, 318
Morrongiello, B. A., 34
Morton, J., 258, 260, 267, 317, 319, 324 O’Hare, E. D., 8
Moscovitch, M., 64 O’Hearn, K., 171
Mottaghy, F. M., 302 O’Reilly, R. C., 220
Moynihan, H., 144 Oakes, L. M., vi, 168, 239, 249, 253, 277, 339, 340
Muellbacher, W., 201 O’Connell, B., 109
Mueller, B. A., 8 Ok, S., 296
Muir, D. W., 317 Olineck, K. M., 309
356 AUTHOR INDEX

Oliver, A., 13 Plunkett, K., 77, 217, 287, 315, 341, 342
Ollen, J., 148 Polka, L., 200
Onishi, K. H., 305, 308 Pollak, S. D., 147, 189
Onnis, L., 89 Pomerantz, J. R., 326
Pomerleau, D. A., 216
Pons, F., 174, 182
Pacton, S., 187 Port, R., 138
Paillard, J., 119 Posner, M. I., 13, 17, 19
Pallier, C., 90 Potts, G. F., 13
Palmer, C., 134, 137 Poulin-Charronnat, B., 132
Palmer, S. E., 120, 123 Poulin-Dubois, D., 234, 237, 238, 240, 241, 244, 249, 309
Palmeri, T. J., 252, 263 Povel, D., 138, 144, 145
Parisi, D., 315, 342 Powers, H. S., 146
Parsons, L. M., 8 Premack, D., 238, 244
Pascalis, O., 136, 139, 141, 266, 321, 324, 325, 327, 328 Press, D. Z., 202
Pascual-Leone, A., 202, 302 Pressley, S., 175
Pasquini, E. S., 174 Prevor, M., 65
Passingham, R. E., 147, 303 Prince, A., 185
Pastore, R. E., 144 Prinz, W., 296, 301, 302
Patel, A. D., 147, 148 Pristach, E. A., 326
Paterson, S. J., 9 Protopapas, A., 142
Pauen, S., 221, 234, 240, 249, 254, 265 Puente, J., 144
Pavesi, G., 302 Pylyshyn, Z. W., 216
Pearl, J., 161, 215
Peereman, R., 185
Pegna, A. J., 112 Quinlan, P. T., 123
Peigneux, P., 202 Quinn, G. E., 316
Peissig, J. J., 112, 113 Quinn, P. C., 57, 219, 220, 221, 222, 249, 252, 253, 254,
Pelucchi, B., 188 255, 258, 259, 260, 261, 262, 264, 265, 266, 267, 268,
Peña, M., 15, 185 276, 321, 340
Peper, C. E., 144 Qvarnstrom, G., 33
Pereira, A. F., 109, 113, 114, 115, 116, 117, 118, 121, 122
Peretz, I., 132, 146, 147
Perfors, A., 190 Rabinowitz, C., 316
Perkins, M. E., 33 Rafal, R. D., 19
Perner, J., 109, 171 Rainey, L., 8
Perrett, D. I., 121, 125 Rakison, D. H., 110, 114, 115, 233, 234, 236, 237, 239,
Perris, E. E., 52 241, 242, 243, 244, 245, 246, 247, 248, 277, 340
Perruchet, P., 33, 185, 187 Rakoczy, H., 126
Peterhans, E., 46 Ramachandran, V. S., 302
Peterman, K., 123 Ramus, F., 147
Peters, T. M., 8, 12 Rathbun, K., 182
Peterson, M., 112, 113 Ratliff, K. R., v
Pfordresher, P. Q., 134 Ratner, H. H., 88
Phillips, A. T., 296, 309 Ratterman, M. J., 175
Phillips-Silver, J., 134, 136 Reali, F., 87, 180
Piaget, J., 47, 49, 53, 54, 61, 75, 77, 159, 175, 213, 296, 297 Reber, A. S., 187
Pickens, J. N., 147 Redford, M. A., 336
Picton, T. W., 13 Redington, M., 89, 180
Pine, J. M., 104 Reed, C. L., 258, 259
Pineda, J. A., 302 Reiss, J. E., 259
Pinker, S., 88, 132, 185 Renninger, K. A., 172
Plante, E., 190 Repacholi, B. M., 171
Platel, H., 134 Repp, B. H., 137, 138, 144, 145
Plauche, M., 103 Rescorla, R. A., 160, 163, 166
Plaut, D. C., 181 Reutter, B., 321
Plihal, W., 204 Reynolds, G. D., 13, 14, 15, 25, 255
Plumert, J. M., vi Reynolds, H. N., 67
AUTHOR INDEX 357

Rhodes, G., 326 Scheines, R., 161


Ribar, R. J., 253 Schellenberg, E. G., 134, 143, 144
Richard, G., 112 Schenck, J. F., 9
Richards, J. E., 3, 4, 5, 10, 13, 14, 15, 18, 19, 20, 21, 22, Scherg, M., 13
23, 24, 25, 255 Schmuckler, M. A., 34
Richardson, D. C., 34, 37, 38, 39, 184 Scholl, B. J., 62
Rivera-Gaxiola, M., 142 Schonen, S., 321
Rivkin, M. J., 8, 9 Schöner, G., 77
Rizzolatti, G., 302, 321 Schubotz, R. I., 136
Robe, K., 188 Schulz, L. E., 160, 161, 162, 168, 171, 175
Robertson, E. M., 202 Schürmann, M., 303
Robinson, C. W., 283, 286, 287 Schwade, J., 116
Rochat, P., 52, 57, 239, 297 Schwaninger, A., 316
Rock, I., 123 Schyns, P. G., 259
Rogers, T. T., 256, 266, 269, 276 Sciolto, T. K., 19
Rohde, D. L., 181 Scott, L. S., 141, 142
Rolls, E. T., 217 Searcy, J. H., 323
Romberg, A. R., 184 Sedmeier, P., 33
Romney, A. K., 7 Seghier, M. L., 322
Rosander, K., 54, 65, 184 Seibel, R. L., 147, 188, 189
Rosch, E., 110, 268 Seidenberg, M. S., 34, 133, 180, 181, 183, 185, 187
Rose, D., 318 Sekuler, A. B., 122, 123
Rosenberg, J. C., 148 Sekuler, E. B., 123
Rosenblum, L. D., 34 Semjen, A., 144
Rosenkrantz, S. L., 219, 253, 340 Senju, A., 308
Ross, N., 265 Sera, M. D., 116
Rossion, B., 322, 327 Sereno, J. A., 89, 100
Rothbart, M. K., 19, 123 Sereno, M. I., 19
Roux, S., 302 Shackelford, R., 258
Rovee-Collier, C., 205, 209 Shady, M., 87, 89, 95
Royal, M., 134 Shafer, V. L., 90
Rubel, E. W., 98 Shankle, W. R., 7
Rubin, D. C., 33 Shanks, D., 160
Ruff, H. A., 123 Shanks, D. R., 160, 166
Rumelhart, D. E., 185 Shannon, R. W., 142
Rundell, L. J., 339 Sheinberg, D. L., 268
Russell, G. S., 13 Shepard, R. N., 57
Sherwood, P., 326
Shettler, L., 340
Sadakata, M., 148 Shi, R., 89, 90, 100
Saegert, S., 32 Shimada, S., 303
Saff ran, J. R., 33, 35, 90, 133, 147, 164, 180, 181, 182, 183, Shkolnik, A., 147, 189
184, 185, 186, 187, 188, 189, 195, 196, 300 Shohamy, D., 33
Sahni, S. D., 187 Shore, C., 109
Sai, F., 324 Shucard, D. W., 90
Sajja, B. R., 8 Shucard, J. L., 90
Sakai, K., 138 Shukla, M., 15
Salapatek, P., 259, 317 Shultz, T. R., 160, 214, 217, 343
Sali, E., 114 Siebel, W. A., 132
Sampaio, R. C., 3, 8 Siegler, R. S., vi, 77
Samuelson, L. K., 110, 112, 278 Silva-Pereyra, J., 142
Sara, S. J., 205 Simion, F., 19, 314, 317, 318, 319, 320, 321, 322, 324, 325,
Sarty, M., 317 326, 327
Saxe, R., 262, 305 Simmons, S., 257
Schacter, D. L., 283 Simons, D. J., 276
Schafe, G. E., 205 Siqueland, E. R., 136
Schafer, G., 287, 341 Sithole, N. M., 200
Scheier, C., 77 Skudlarski, P., 323
358 AUTHOR INDEX

Slater, A. M., 40, 49, 53, 55, 266, 318, 321, 326, 337, 338 Stone, V. E., 259
Slaughter, V., 171, 262, 266 Strauss, M. S., 266, 339
Slemmer, J. A., 36, 37, 40, 50, 54, 55, 65, 133, 164, 184, Strawson, P. F., 64
189, 195, 300 Street, S., 125, 126
Sloman, S., 160, 175 Striano, T., 126, 239
Sloutsky, V. M., 235, 274, 276, 278, 280, 281, 282, 283, Stryker, M., 203
284, 285, 286, 287 Stucchie, N., 119
Slovic, P., 33 Sugita, Y., 263
Smeets, H., 259 Summerlin, J. L., 8
Smith, E. E., 268 Summers, J., 144
Smith, E. G., 184 Sunm, M., 202
Smith, J. D., 252, 263 Surian, L., 308
Smith, K. H., 187 Swap, W., 32
Smith, L. B., vi, vii, 68, 77, 109, 110, 111, 112, 113, 114, Swick, D., 13
115, 116, 117, 118, 121, 123, 124, 125, 208, 249, 257, Swimmer, M. B., 123
260, 276, 277, 278 Swingley, D., 181, 182, 183
Smith, W., 13 Sykes, M., 318
Smith, W. C., 34, 276 Symons, L. A., 266
Snedeker, J., 104
Snow, K. L., 184
Snyder, J. S., 132, 134, 138, 144 Talairach, J., 8, 10
Sobel, D. M., 159, 160, 161, 162, 163, 164, 165, 166, 167, Tanaka, J. W., 252, 263, 268, 323
168, 169, 170, 171, 172, 174, 175 Tanaka, N., 143
Sodian, B., 296 Tanenhaus, M. K., 183
Soja, N. N., 110, 276 Tarr, M. J., 112, 113, 252, 316, 323
Sokolov, E. N., 221 Tatsuno, M., 202
Soley, G., 140, 141 Taylor, D., 49
Somers, M., 49 Taylor, M., 268
Sommerville, J. A., 168, 175, 246, 296, 297, 298, 299, Tees, R. C., 90, 136, 139, 200
300, 301, 307, 309 Tenenbaum, J. B., 104, 159, 160, 167, 168, 172, 173, 175,
Son, J. Y., 115, 116 214, 215, 216, 276
Son, L. K., 196 Terrace, H. S., 196
Sophian, C., 168 Thapar, A., 283
Soska, K. C., 56, 57 Theakston, A., 104
Southgate, V., 308 Thelen, E., vi, vii, 68, 77, 260
Sowell, E. R., 8 Theoret, H., 303
Spaepen, G., 189 Th iessen, E. D., 133, 182, 188, 189
Spelke, E. S., v, 34, 47, 48, 49, 50, 52, 54, 65, 78, 79, 184, Thoermer, C., 296
195, 274, 276, 296, 314, 338 Thoman, E., 202
Spellman, B. A., 339 Thomas, K. M., 8, 15
Spencer, J., vi, 258, 259, 265 Thomas, M. S. C., vi, 213, 217
Spencer, R. M., 202 Thompson, R. M., 226
Sperber, D., 308 Thompson, S. P., 182, 185
Sperling, G., 33 Thorpe, S. J., 112
Spinelli, L., 13 Tillman, B. A., 133
Spino, M. A., 283 Titzer, R., 68
Spiro, J., 132 Todd, J. T., 33
Spirtes, P., 161 Toga, A. W., 8, 12
Spivey-Knowlton, M., 183 Toivianien, P., 134
Sprague, J. M., 321 Tokura, H., 89, 91, 92
Spring, J., 53 Tomasello, M., 88, 104, 126, 239, 246, 295, 296, 297, 301
Squire, L. R., 205 Tomblin, J. B., 188, 190
Stager, C. L., 341 Tong, F. H., 119
Steinhauer, K., 89 Tooby, J., v
Sternberg, R. J., 214 Toro, J. M., 196
Steyvers, M., 104, 160, 167, 175 Touretzky, D. S., 216
Stickgold, R., 202 Tournoux, P., 8, 10
Stokowski, L. A., 9, 10 Trainor, L. J., 132, 134, 136, 143
AUTHOR INDEX 359

Träuble, B., 221 Wagenmakers, E. J., 160, 175


Travis, L. L., 183 Wagner, A. R., 160, 163, 166
Treff ner, P. J., 144 Wagner, J., 37, 40, 41
Trehub, S. E., 132, 134, 136, 138, 139, 140, 141, 144, 145 Wagner, U., 202
Treisman, A., 64 Waldmann, M. R., 160, 175
Tremoulet, P. D., 62 Walker, M. P., 201, 202, 205, 206, 209
Trobalón, J. B., 196 Wallace, C. S., vi
Trueswell, J., 104 Wallace, J. G., vi, 214
Truwit, C. L., 3, 8 Walton, G. E., 324
Tsao, F-M., 139, 142, 182, 190 Wang, V., 302
Tseng, A., 8, 15 Wanner, E., 89, 100, 104
Tucker, D. M., 13, 254 Wasnik, A., 340
Tucker, L. A., 13, 18, 19 Wass, T. S., 184
Tunick, R. A., 188 Wasserman, E. A., 160, 166
Turati, C., 317, 318, 319, 320, 321, 322, 324, Watamaniuk, S. N. J., 64
325, 326, 327 Watanabe, S., 143
Turkewitz, G., 34, 315 Watkins, K., 147
Turvey, M. T., 122, 123, 144 Watson, J. K., 172
Tyler, M. D., 185 Wattam-Bell, J., 321
Tzelnic, T., 262 Waxman, S. R., 262, 277, 281, 286, 287
Tzourio-Mazoyer, N., 321, 322 Weikum, W. M., 136
Weismer, S. E., 109
Weiss, R. F., 160
U. S. Food and Drug Administration (USFDA), 9 Weissenborn, J., 104
Uchida, N., 110 Welder, A. N., 277
Uecker, A., 8 Wellman, H. M., 171, 172, 276, 296, 308, 309
Ullman, S., 112, 114, 122 Wentworth, N., 35, 164
Umiltà, C., 19, 317, 318, 319, 326 Werker, J. F., 90, 133, 136, 139, 142, 146, 147, 182, 200,
Uozumi, M., 143 287, 316, 341
Urbach, T. P., 183 Werner, L. A., 182
Uzgiris, I. C., 164, 235 Wessels, J. M., 187
West, M. J., 182
Westerlund, A., 254, 322
Valentine, D., 323, 326 Westermann, G., 213, 221, 222, 224, 225, 343
Valenza, E., 19, 317, 318, 320, 322 Wexler, K., 276
Valian, V., 89, 90 Wexler, M., 119
Vallabha, G. K., 182 Wheeler, K., 67
van Boxtel., J., 119 Wheelwright, S., 175
Van de Walle, G. A., 65 Widdess, R., 146
van den Berg, P. P., 9 Wilcox, T., 62
Van der Linden, M., 33 Williams, P., 323
Van Hamme, L. J., 160, 166 Williams, R., 160
van Wieringen, P. C. W., 144 Wilson, D. P., 188
Vankov, A., 302 Wilson, M., 202
Vargha-Cadem, F., 321 Wilson, R., 185
Vargha-Khadem, F., 147 Winocur, G., 64
Vaughan, J., 19 Wohlschlager, A., 119
Vecera, S. P., 19 Woldorff, M. G., 8
Vidal-Naquet, M., 114 Woldroff, M. G., 19
Vignolo, L. A., 132 Wong, A., 252
Vigorito, J., 136 Wong, E. C., 19
Vilis, T., 121 Woodward, A. L., 195, 246, 274, 295, 296, 297, 298, 300,
Vishton, P., 54, 65, 184 301, 305, 307, 309
Vivani, P., 119 Woodward, J., 161
von der Heydt, R., 46 Woolley, J. D., 171
von Hofsten, C., 54, 65, 78, 184, 303 Wozniak, J. R., 8
Vorbert, D., 145 Wozniak, R. H., 172
Vouloumanos, A., 146, 147, 316 Wright, C. E., 144, 145
360 AUTHOR INDEX

Wright, J. C., 269 Young, M., 33


Wu, P., 317 Young, R., 214
Wyly, M. V., 125 Younger, B. A., 239, 241, 253, 337, 340, 343
Wynn, K., 195, 262, 295, 314 Yuill, N., 171
Yuille, A. L., 215, 216
Yves von Cramon, D., 136
Xu, F., 39, 62, 64, 65, 195, 214, 215, 254, 276, 287

Zacks, J. M., 57
Yahr, J., 266 Zajonc, R. B., 32, 33
Yakolev, P. I., 3 Zanone, P. G., 145
Yamaguchi, M., 309 Zatorre, R. J., 132
Yang, C., 181 Zelazo, P. D., 78
Yin, R. K., 323, 326 Zentner, M. R., 143
Yoachim, C. M., 169 Zhang, X., 188
Yonas, A., 116 Ziv, T., 267, 321
Yoshida, H., 110, 121, 277 Zu, H., 9
Young, A. W., 323
SUBJEC T INDEX

3/4 Views, of objects, 120–21 spatial orienting, 17–24


3D MPRAGE T1-weighted scan, 10 eye movement, 4–5
3D object completion, 56, 55–58 Auditory cues, 33, 41
Auto-encoder neural network, 221–22, 264–65
Axes of elongation, 124, 122–26
Action Axes of symmetry, 122–23, 124
goal-directed, 242, 245–48, 300
production and understanding
evidence for links between, 297–300 Backpropagation, 219, 221, 222
correlational evidence, 297–98 Bayesian statistical inference, 214, 215
intervention evidence, 299, 298–300 belief network, 215
theoretical links between, 300–301 causal structure learning, mechanism of, 166–68,
Activation law, 168, 170, 171, 172 170, 173–74
Angle perception studies, 337–38 computational levels of description, integrating, 216–17
Animacy, 238, 239, 242, 247, See also Animal(s) problems of, 214–16
Animal(s). See also Animacy Behavioral tasks, discrimination of unfamiliar
goal-directed action to, 242, 245–48 structures in, 142
humans vs. non-human animals, categorization of, BESA, 10
268–70 Bias
non-human animals, categorization of, 253 attentional, 258–60, 319–20
category representations, 258 of object shape, 110, 112, 121
cluster representations, 256–57 towards temporal regularity, biological basis for
head preference, 258–60 music learning, constraints on, 144–45
looking-time studies, 253–54 Blicket detector, 162–63, 164, 165, 169, 171
neural correlates, 254–56 children’s developing knowledge of, 168–71
on-line learning or pre-existing representations, activation law, 168
260–62 causal relations in another domain of knowledge,
nonlinear walking motion with, 244–45 168–73
Artificial language learning, 187–89 objects causal properties and insides, relation
adjacent dependencies, detecting, 196, 197–98 between, 168–71
effects of sleep in, 203–4 objects, placing, 168
inconsistent input, 199, 198–200 one-cause, 162
nonadjacent dependencies, detecting, 196–97 two-cause, 162
Associative learning, 244–48 Blocking, 162–63
Associative reasoning, 163 backward, 163, 164
Asymmetry, on newborns’ preference Bottom-up approaches to learning, 174–75, 280
top-down, 319, 320 for causal structure learning, 159–60
up-down, 319–22 inductive generalization, 237–40
Attention development, in early infancy vs. top-down approaches to learning, 275–76
by brain development, 3 Brain development, 315–16, See Primate memory
future directions, 25–26 development

361
362 SUBJECT INDEX

Brain development (Continued) Covert orienting, 17–19


and attention development, relationship between, 3 Cross-language design, 189
non-human models of, 5–6 Cross-language speech perception, developmental
Brown-Forsyth tests, 94 changes in, 142
CSF. See Contrast Sensitivity Function
Cue(s), 32, See also Multiple-cue integration, in syntax
Categorization, of infants, 339–40 acquisition
Causal graphical model, 161 auditory, 33, 41
faithfulness assumption, 161 distributional, 89–90
graph, parameterizing, 161 Gestalt, 49
Markov assumption, 161 multiple, 33–34, See also Multiple-cue integration
Causal perception studies, 339 theory
Causal structure learning, 159, 160–66 multiple language-internal. See Multiple language-
Bayesian mechanism of, 166–68, 170, 173–74 internal cues
Blicket detectors, children’s developing knowledge phonological, 89
of, 168–73 prosodic, 89, 95–96, 99
bottom-up mechanisms of, 159–60 visual, 33, 34, 37, 41
graphical models. See Causal graphical model consistent, 38
of infants, 163–66 constant, 39
of young children, 162–63 inconstant, 39
top-down and bottom-up learning, integrating, 174–75 uninformative, 38–40
Cerebral cortex, 7, 315 Culture-specific rhythmic structures, in music and
neuroanatomical and cytoarchitecture of layers of, 7 speech, 148, 146–49
CHILDES, 91, 102 stress-timed languages, 147
Common fate, 50 syllable-timed languages, 147
Common motion, 50
Composite effect, 323
Configuring processing, types of, 323 Developmental changes
Congruency, 318–19 constructivist principles for, 336–37
Conlearn, 317, 328 in cross-language speech perception, 142
Connectionist categorization model, previous, 221–22 Developmental cognitive neuroscience, 5, 7, 10, 17
Connectionist information processing, 218–19 limitations of, 7–8
Connectionist modeling, 181, 342–44 Differential perceptual experience, 264–65
characteristics of, 342 Diff usion tensor imaging (DTI), 8
limitations of, 342–43 Direct neural lesions, 5
of infant cognitive development, 343–44 Direct neural recording, 5
Connectionist networks, 218–19 Disappearance transform, 67
feed-forward, 218 Discrimination of motion, 50
generic, 218 Dishabituation, 36, See also Habituation
Connectionist solutions, 217 Dissonant, 143
Consonant, 143 Downward shift, in recognition, 252
Conspec, 317, 319 DTI. See Diff usion tensor imaging (DTI)
Constructivist principles, evidence for, 337–41 Dual memory model, of infant categorization
angle perception studies, 337–38 architecture, 222
causal perception studies, 339 background knowledge effect on familiarization,
early word learning, 341 223–25
face perception studies, 338–39 long-term representations, development of, 223, 224
infant categorization, 339–40 training data, 222–23
object unity studies, 338 Dynamic spatial indexing, 38–40
Continuity, 79 Dynamic systems theory, 77–78
Contrast Sensitivity Function (CSF), 317
Cortex
cerebral, 7, 315 Early word learning, 341
occipital, 12, 19, 20, 21, 22, 23 EEG. See Electroencephalogram
prefrontal, 12, 24 Electroencephalogram (EEG), 10, 16–17, 20
primary visual, 5, 6, 7 advantages of, 16
temporal, 12, 16, 21, 22 for mirror representations in action perception, 302
Covert attention, 17 EMSE, 10
SUBJECT INDEX 363

Epigenetic constructivism, 314 Grammatical markers, 95–96


ERP. See Event-related potentials Grammatical pattern learning, 186–87
Event-related potentials (ERP), 14, 13–15, 19
P1 validity effects in, 20, 21, 20–22, 24
Everyday music learning, 140, 138–41 Habituation, 36, See also Dishabituation
Exemplar–prototype distinction, 264 Head preference, 258–60
Experience–expectant process, 321 Hebbian learning
Eye movement, 4–5 and early brain development, 141
reflexive saccadic, 4 Hidden representation for category prototypes,
smooth pursuit, 4 development of, 223, 224
voluntary saccadic, 4 Humans, representation for, 262
categorization asymmetry and exemplar-based
representation, 263
Face perception studies, 338–39 differential perceptual experience, 264–65
Face preference at birth, 316–21 inclusive category, 262–63
experience–expectant process, 321 on-line learning and pre-existing representations,
Fourier analysis, 317–18 266–68
sensory hypothesis, 317 on-line learning or pre-existing representations, 267
specific mechanism vs. existence of general perceptual information, 265–66
attentional biases, 319–20
structural hypothesis, 317
structural properties, 318–19, 320 Identity
Face processing system, neo-constructivistic approach development theory, 78–79
to, 314–16 numerical. See Numerical identity
face preference at birth, 316–21 object, 62
face recognition, 322–23 Inclusivity–exclusivity difference, 264
nature of operations, 326–27 Induction-then-Recognition (ITR), 283
visual information newborns process and face Inductive generalization, 240, 235–41
recognition, 323–26 baseline phase, 235
newborns’ preference, for up-down asymmetrical bottom-up approach to, 237–40
configurations, 321–22 generalization phase, 235–36
Face recognition, 115 modeling phase, 235
at birth, 322–23, 325 top-down approach to, 236–37
attractiveness effect, 326 Inductive inference, in infancy, 233, 234
composite effect, 323 based on prior knowledge, 243, 241–44
configural processing, types of, 323 basis for, 247, 244–48
inversion effect, 323, 326 inductive generalization, 240, 235–41
nature of operations, 326–27 baseline phase, 235
part-whole effect, 323 bottom-up approach to, 237–40
pattern-line effect, 326 generalization phase, 235–36
visual information newborns process and face modeling phase, 235
recognition, 323–26 top-down approach to, 236–37
fMRI. See Functional magnetic resonance imaging origins of, 235
Fourier analysis, 317–18 Infant category learning, modeling
Functional cognitive neuroscience, 13, 24 background knowledge effect on familiarization,
Functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI), 15, 223–25
16–17 categories of, 217–21
for mirror representations in action connectionist models of, 221
perception, 302 dual memory model of, 222–25
P1 validity effects in, 23 architecture, 222
background knowledge effect on familiarization, 225
long-term representations, development of, 223,
Generalized imitation procedure. See Inductive 224
generalization training data, 222–23
Generic networks previous connectionist models of, 221–22
feed-forward, 218 Infant monkeys
Goal-directed action, 242, 245–48, 300 brain development in, 5
Grammatical gender, in spoken word recognition, 183 Infer temporal structure, in music, 135, 133–36
364 SUBJECT INDEX

Innate constraints, 315 inconsistent input, 199, 198–200


Innate knowledge, 88 nonadjacent dependencies, detecting, 196–97
Intentional action knowledge with one’s hands, associative, 244–48
building, 295 causal structure. See Causal structure learning
action production and action understanding early word, 341
evidence for links between, 297–300 everyday music, 140, 138–41
correlational evidence, 297–98 Hebbian
intervention evidence, 299, 298–300 and early brain development, 141
theoretical links between, 300–301 music, 144–45
mirror representations, 302–3 object names, 110, 111, 109–12
in action perception, 304–5 processing constraints
mirror systems, in infancy, 303–4 nonadjacent dependencies, detecting, 197
origins of, 296–97 processing constraints on, 195
relational action representations and structural adjacent dependencies, detecting, 196, 197–98
mapping, 305–8 inconsistent input, 199, 198–200
self-produced actions, 301–2 memory consolidation, 204
Inversion effect, 323, 326 memory processes, role of, 201–8
Invisible location standard, 68 memory reconsolidation, 207, 205–8
ITR. See Induction-then-Recognition nonadjacent dependencies, detecting, 196–97
prior experience, role of, 200–201
second language, 141
Language sequence, 35–36
parallels with music spatial indexing, 39, 38–40
constraints on, 143–46 spatiotemporal statistical, 37–38
culture-specific rhythmic structures in, 148, statistical
146–49 complexity of, 185–87
everyday music learning, role of, 140, 138–41 statistical language, 180
perception of meter, developmental changes in, artificial language learning, 187–89
137–38 computations, nature of, 182–85
perceptual development and reorganization, explanation of, 189–90
mechanisms of, 141–43 visual statistical, 36–37
statistical learning and musical time, 135, 133–36 Like me hypothesis, 301, 308
second language learning, 141 Linear System Model (LSM), 317
sentence comprehension speech perception, 95–96 Looking-time studies, 253–54
method, 97 event-related potential (ERP) analogue of, 254–55, 256
results, 97 LSM. See Linear System Model
specific language impairment, 188
statistical learning
artificial language learning, 187–89 Magnetic resonance imaging (MRI), 8–10
complexity of, 185–87 P1 validity effects in, 23–24
computations, nature of, 182–85 T1-weighted, 3, 4, 10, 11, 12
explanation of, 189–90 T2-weighted, 10
grammatical pattern learning, 186–87 Marker tasks, 13
stress-timed, 147 Memory consolidation, 204
syllable-timed, 147 effects of sleep in, 201–5
syntax Memory processes
internal representations, probing, 102, 101–3 role, in constraint learning, 201–8
multiple-cue integration with distractor cues, consolidation, 204
97–99 reconsolidation, 207
multiple-cue integration with full-blown child- Memory reconsolidation, 207, 205–8
directed speech, 99–101, 102 Mental rotation, sex differences in, 56–57
prenatal exposure, role of, 97, 98 Mere exposure effect, 33
sentence comprehension, in two-year-olds, 95–96 Meter perception, 133, 135, 134–36
simple-recurrent network, 91, 90–94 developmental changes in, 137–38
Learning, 32 isochronous, 134, 137, 139
artificial language, 187–89 movement and, 134
adjacent dependencies, detecting, 196, 197–98 nonisochronous, 137, 139
effects of sleep in, 203–4 visual information and, 136
SUBJECT INDEX 365

Mirror representations, 302–3 Natural language processing, 180, See also Statistical
in action perception, 304–5 language learning
Mirror systems, in infancy, 303–4 Near-infrared optical spectroscopy (NIRS), 15–17
MNI brain (Montreal Neurological Institute brain), 8, Negative evidence, 183
12, 23, 24 Neural density, 7
Modularization process, 315, 318 Neural network
MRI. See Magnetic resonance imaging auto-encoder, 221–22, 264–65
Mu rhythm suppression, 302 Neural-net modeling. See Connectionist modeling
Multiple cues, 33–34, See also Multiple language- New goal test trial, 246
internal cues; Multiple-cue integration, in New side test trial, 246
syntax acquisition; Multiple-cue integration NIRS. See Near-infrared optical spectroscopy
theory Non-human animals, categorization of, 253, See also
Multiple language-internal cues Animacy; Animals
bootstrapping, 89–90 category representations, 258
need for, 88–89 cluster representations, 256–57, 258
innate constraints, 88 head preference, 258–60
language-external information, 88 looking-time studies, 253–54
language-internal information, 88–89 neural correlates, 255, 254–56
Multiple-cue integration theory, 34–35, See also on-line learning or pre-existing representations, 261,
Multiple cues 260–62
Multiple-cue integration, in syntax acquisition, 87 Nonlinear walking motion, with animals, 244–45, See
internal representations, probing, 102, 101–3 also Motion
prenatal exposure, role of, 97, 98 Nonplanar view, of objects, 120–22
sentence comprehension, in two-year-olds, 95–96 Normalized Pairwise Variability Index (nPVI), 147–48
simple-recurrent network, 91, 90–94 nPVI. See Normalized Pairwise Variability Index
with distractor cues, 97–99 Numerical identity, 61
with full-blown child-directed speech, 99–101, 102 account for object permanence, 63–64, 69
Music learning, constraints on, 143–46 disappearance transform, type of, 67
biases towards temporal regularity, biological basis empirical evidence, 68–72
for, 144–45 hypotheses, 64–67
temporal regularity, importance of, 145–46 mechanism of change, 76, 73–77
Musical enculturation, 132 object occlusion, degree of, 67
culture-specific rhythmic structures in, 148, 146–49 occluded object standard, 68
music learning, constraints on, 143–46 performance constraints, 69–70
biases towards temporal regularity, biological room change condition, 69
basis for, 144–45 search behavior, 68–69
temporal regularity, importance of, 145–46 transformation-dependent object permanence,
musical knowledge, building, 136–43 70–72
everyday music learning, role of, 140, 138–41 transition to invisibility, psychophysics of, 67
perception of meter, developmental changes in, violations of, 72
137–38 and representation, 63–64
perceptual development and reorganization, argument, structure of, 63
mechanisms of, 141–43
statistical learning and musical time, 135, 133–36
Musical knowledge, building, 136–43 Object identity, 62
everyday music learning, role of, 140, 138–41 Object names, learning, 111, 109–12
perception of meter, developmental changes in, causes and consequences, 110
137–38 Object permanence, 61–62, See also Object(s)
perceptual development and reorganization, and representation, 64
mechanisms of, 141–43 development, stages of, 61, 62
Myelin, 3 developmental change, generalization of, 74–77
Myelinated fiber density, 7 future directions, 79–80
Myelination, 3, 4, 7, 25 genesis of, 73–74
partial occlusion, role of, 73
sounding objects, 73–74
Native and non-native speech contrasts, variability in identity development account of
discrimination of, 142 disappearance transform, type of, 67
Nativist theory, 78 empirical evidence, 68–72
366 SUBJECT INDEX

Object permanence (Continued) disjoint surface, 50


hypotheses, 64–67 face, 338–39
mechanism of, 73–77 meter, 133, 134, 135, 134–36, 137–38, 139
object occlusion, degree of, 67 particulate, 114
performance constraints, 69–70 shape, 118–26
room change condition, 69 Perceptual completion, in infancy, 45, See also
search behavior, 68–69 Perception
transformation-dependent object permanence, 3D object completion, 56, 55–58
70–72 spatial completion, 47–48, 50, 49–52
transition to invisibility, psychophysics of, 67 spatiotemporal completion, 52, 53, 52–55
violations of, 72 theoretical considerations, 47–49
implications for, 77–79 Perceptual expertise, acquisition of, 252
Object shape, 109–12 Perceptual matching, 237, 238, 244–45, 242, 245
abstract representations of, 112–18 Permanent objects, 68
bias of, 110, 112, 121 PET. See Positron emission tomography studies
individual parts/local details of, 114–15, 116 Piagetian theory, of object permanence, 77
sameness in shape, 112, 120 Planar view, of objects, 120–22
sparse representation of, 113–14 dwell times on, 121, 122
Object trajectory, 40–41 Positron emission tomography (PET) studies
Object unity, 48, 49, 50, 338 for mirror representations in action perception, 302
Object(s) Prefrontal cortex, 12, 24
axes of elongation, 124, 122–26 Prenatal exposure, role of, 97, 98
nonplanar view of, 120–22 method, 97
permanent, 68 results, 97
permenance. See Object permenance Pre-permanence world, of infancy, 63
planar view of, 120–22 Primary visual cortex, 5, 6, 7
dwell times on, 121 synaptic density in, 5, 6
posting of, 125–26 Primate memory development
sounding, 73–74 non-human models of, 5–6
Occipital cortex, 12, 19, 20, 21, 22, 23 Prior experience, role of, 200–201
Occluded object standard, 68 Prior knowledge and new experience, combining, 213
Occluder removal, 68 Bayesian statistical inference, 214, 215
Occlusion computational levels of description, integrating,
partial, 70, 73, 74, 77 216–17
total, 66, 67, 71–72, 77 connectionist solutions, 217
Occlusion event, 67 problems of, 214–16
disappearance transform, type of, 67 Processing constraints, on learning, 195
object occlusion, degree of, 67 adjacent dependencies, detecting, 196, 197–98
transition to invisibility, psychophysics of, 67 inconsistent input, 199, 198–200
Occlusion-in-place, 66, 71, 72 memory consolidation, 204, 201–5
Occlusion-on-a-carrier-to-a-place, 71–72, 77 memory processes, role of, 201–8
avoidance of, 72 memory reconsolidation, 207, 205–8
Oculomotor anticipation performance, 54–55 nonadjacent dependencies, detecting, 196–97
Optical topography (OT), 15 prior experience, role of, 200–201
OT. See Optical topography
Overshadowing effects, in young
children, 288, 286–89 Rapid eye movement (REM), 202, 204, See also Sleep
Reflexive saccadic eye movement, 4
Relational action representations and structural
Particulate perception, 114 mapping, 305–8
Part-whole effect, 323 REM. See Rapid eye movement
Perception, 32, See also Perceptual completion, in Rescorla-Wagner equation, 160, 166
infancy Resource limitation hypothesis, 341
action Rhythm, 133
mirror representations in, 302–3
angle, 337–38
causal, 339 Second language learning, 141
cross-language speech perception, developmental Self-produced actions, as unique sources of
changes in, 142 information, 301–2
SUBJECT INDEX 367

Self-sitting and visual-manual coordination, Structure mapping engine (SME), 306


relationship between, 57–58 SWS. See Slow-wave sleep
Sensitivity to multimodal regularities, infants, 34 Symbolic play/action, 109, See also Object substitution
Sensory hypothesis, in face perception, 317 in play
Sentence comprehension, in two-year-olds, 95–96 and shape perception, 118–26
method, 97 axes of elongation, 122–26
results, 97 multiple simultaneous representations, inter-relating
Sequence learning, 35–36 of, 119
Similarity, induction, naming and categorization nonolanar view of objects, 120–22
(SINC) model, 274 object name vocabulary and, 117–18
empirical fi ndings, 282–85, 286, 287 planar view of objects, 120–22
linguistic labels, importance of, 288, 285–89 posting of objects, 125–26
overview of, 280–82 Synaptic density, in primary visual cortex, 5, 6
unresolved issues of, 289 Synaptogenesis, 5, 6
Simple-recurrent network (SRN), 91, 90–94, 183
method, 91–93
results, 93–94 Talairach space, 8
SINC. See Similarity, induction, naming and Targeted visual exploration, 51–52
categorization model Temporal cortex, 12, 16, 21, 22
Sleep, effects of TMS. See Transcranial magnetic stimulation studies
in memory consolidation, 204, 201–5 Top-down approaches to learning, 174–75,
rapid eye movement, 202 278, 276–80
slow-wave sleep, 204 category assumption, 277
SLI. See Specific language impairment challenges to, 277–80
Slow-wave sleep (SWS), 204, See also Sleep evidence, supporting, 277
SME. See Structure mapping engine linguistic assumption, 277
Smooth pursuit eye movement, 4 vs. bottom-up approaches to learning, 275–76
SOA. See Stimulus-onset-asynchrony Transcranial magnetic stimulation (TMS) studies
Spatial completion, 47–48, 50, 49–52 for mirror representations in action
development of, 49–50 perception, 302
Spatial indexing, 39, 38–40 Transition to invisibility, psychophysics of, 67
Spatial orienting, 20, 21, 22, 23, 24, 17–24
Spatiotemporal completion, 52, 53, 52–55
Spatiotemporal statistical learning, 37–38 Vapnik-Chervonenkis (VC) learning theory, 104
color, 37–38 Violation-of-expectation method, 47, 79
location, 37 Visual cues, 33, 34, 33, 37, 41
shape, 37–38 consistent, 38
Specific language impairment (SLI), 188 constant, 39
Speech inconstant, 39
culture-specific rhythmic structures in, 146–49 uninformative, 38–40
SRN. See Simple-recurrent network Visual information newborns process and face
Statistical language learning, 180 recognition, 323–26
artificial language learning, 187–89 Visual object recognition
complexity of, 185–87 object-based theories of, 112–13
computations, nature of, 182–85 sameness in shape, 112, 120
explanation of, 189–90 shape representation and, 112–18
grammatical pattern learning, 186–87 significant changes in, 115–16
Statistical learning and musical time, 135, 133–36 view-based theories of, 112
Stimulus, in preference habituation and test phase, 324 Visual occlusion, 274, 275
Stimulus-onset-asynchrony (SOA), 18, 19 Visual statistical learning, 36–37
Structural hypothesis, 317 color, 36
Structural mapping and relational action shape, 36
representations, 305–8 Voluntary saccadic eye movement, 4

Вам также может понравиться