Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 8

David Seamon Concretizing Heidegger´s Notion

of Dwelling
The Contributions of Thomas Thiis-Evensen
and
Christopher Alexander

1In "Building Dwelling Thinking," phenomenological philosopher Martin Heidegger discusses the
notion of dwelling and contends that "only if we are capable of dwelling, only then can we build"
(Heidegger, 1971, p. 160). A major problem with dwelling as an idea is its lack of specificity,
particularly in terms of design significance. This article argues that the work of two architects--
Thomas Thiis-Evensen and Christopher Alexander—indicates important but different ways in
which Heidegger’s dwelling can be translated into more grounded architectural meaning. Thiis-
Evensen and Alexander's ideas, placed in a Heideggerian framework, point toward a way of
thinking that might lead to the kind of dwelling-building relationship suggested by Heidegger when
he writes that "to build is already to dwell" (ibid., p. 146).

DWELLING AND BUILDING


2In "Building Dwelling Thinking," Heidegger's major means of investigation is etymological: what
is the word history of "to build" ("bauen") and its links to dwelling? Bauen, says Heidegger, relates
to nearness and neighborliness and also implies "to cherish and protect, to preserve and care for"
(ibid., p. 147). Bauen also relates to the old High German word for building, "baun," which means
"to dwell" in the sense of remaining or staying in place.
In emphasizing this link to place, Heidegger suggests that building relates to dwelling, which
therefore can be said to involve a sense of continuity, community, and at-homeness (Harries,
1983). The crux of dwelling, Heidegger argues, is sparing and preserving--the kindly concern for
land, things, creatures, and people as they are and as they can become (ibid., p. 149;
Zimmerman, 1983). As human beings, we cannot fail to dwell, for dwelling, ultimately, is the
essential existential core of human being-in-the-world from which there is no escape.
At the same time, dwelling is just as much a means as an end. There will always be a certain
tension, a kind of imperfection, between what we wish, do, and make. The significant questions
are how do we dwell in our own particular situations and how can we shape the quality of our
dwelling for better or worse? Heidegger links the quality of our dwelling to the quality of our
building, since an effective building arises from a genuine sense of sparing and preserving (see
Foltz, 1995, pp. 159-63).

3Heidegger also argues that, in practical terms, dwelling involves the gathering of the fourfold--
the coming together of earth, sky, people, and a sense of spiritual reverence, or "the gods," as he
signifies higher realities (ibid.). In this sense, dwelling is no mere extension of existential space or
place; rather, "it becomes itself the fundamental human activity, in the light of which both place
and space find their first clarification" (Jager, 1983, p. 154). As Heidegger interprets dwelling, the
built environment is crucial because it supports and reflects a person and group's way of being-in-
the-world. The built environment is a certain embodied grasp of the world, a particular way of
taking up the body and the world, a specific orientation disclosing certain aspects of a worldly
horizon (ibid., pp. 154-155). The world in which we find ourselves completes us in what we are,
and therefore the specific nature of the built environment becomes crucial.
In other words, people are immersed in their world, and this immersion is qualitative, subtle—in
many ways, ineffable. Thus a walk through a well-tended garden evokes a different state of being
than a similar walk through an uncared-for garden or an unsightly vacant lot. Similarly, entering a
church evokes a different human stance than entering a nightclub or a shopping mall or an empty
street or a street filled with human activity. One aim for aim for architects is to become sensitive to
these experiences and to become more aware of how specific qualities of the built environment
enhance or stymie particular human experiences.

4Heidegger argues that, in our modern age, human dwelling is reduced and so, therefore, is
building. His explication of why we dwell less fully today is complicated; he suggests that, in part,
it is because we manipulate and demand from our world rather than meet it an attitude of sparing
and preserving--i.e., allowing it to be and become. In this sense, a key to dwelling is letting
ourselves and the world be, and this letting-be includes the ways we build, see, understand, and
think.
It is this need for letting-be in designing and understanding that marks the value of Thiis-Evensen
and Alexander's work for a deeper, more grounded, understanding of dwelling. Both architects
seek concrete means for identifying and describing built qualities that sustain and strengthen the
quality of dwelling. Through evoking one style of sparing and preserving, Thiis-Evensen and
Alexander provide ways to see and think more clearly, which, in turn, might lead to better
designing and building.

A PHENOMENOLOGY OF ARCHITECTURAL FORM

5Norwegian architect Thomas Thiis-Evensen's Archetypes in Architecture goes far in developing


a language of architectural elements as they have relation to dwelling (Thiis-Evensen 1987).1
Thiis-Evensen's aim is to understand "the universality of architectural expression" (ibid., 8). His
vehicle is what he calls architectural archetypes—"the most basic elements of architecture,"
which for Thiis-Evensen can be identified as the floor, wall, and roof (ibid.). Thiis-Evensen argues
that these three architectural elements are not arbitrary but, rather, are common to all historical
and cultural traditions. The essential existential ground of floor, wall, and roof, he argues, is the
relationship between inside and outside. Just by being what they are, the floor, wall, and roof
automatically create an inside in the midst of an outside, though in different ways: the floor,
through above and beneath; the wall, through within and around; and the roof, through over and
below.

6Using examples from architectural history as evidence, Thiis-Evensen argues that any building
can be interpreted experientially in terms of these three archetypes. His main purpose is to
describe the kinds of environmental and architectural experience that different variations of floor,
wall, and roof sustain and presuppose. The result, he claims, is "a common language of
[architectural] form which we can immediately understand, regardless of individual or culture"
(ibid., 17).
Thiis-Evensen demonstrates that a building’s relative degree of insideness or outsideness in
regard to floor, wall, and roof can be clarified through motion, weight, and substance—the three
"existential expressions of architecture" (ibid., p. 21). By motion, he means the architectural
element's sense of dynamism or inertia--that is, whether the element seems to expand, to
contract, or to rest in balance. Weight involves the sense of heaviness or lightness of the element
and how it relates to gravity. Last, substance relates to the material sense of the element--
whether it is soft or hard, coarse or fine, warm or cold, and so forth.

7In broadest terms, the central question Thiis-Evensen asks in Archetypes is, "How do floor, wall,
and roof express insideness and outsideness through motion, weight, and substance?" The
relationship between insideness and outsideness has, in fact, received considerable attention in
phenomenological research on environmental and architectural experience (e.g., Chaffin 1989,
Dovey 1985, Mugerauer 1991, Mugerauer, 1994, Seamon 1991, Silverstein 1991), especially in
geographer Edward Relph's phenomenology of place (Relph 1976), which demonstrates that
insideness is the hallmark quality transforming space into place and sustaining the deepest sense
of dwelling. One of Thiis-Evensen's contributions is to illustrate ways in which architecture
contributes to insideness and outsideness and therefore grounds a sense of dwelling.
Thiis-Evensen emphasizes that different architectural styles and cultural traditions may interpret
the inside-outside dialectic through different degrees of openness and closure (for example, the
medieval fortress's impenetrable walls versus the Renaissance palace's walls of many windows).
Regardless of the particular stylistic or cultural expression, however, floors, walls, and roofs
provide related results in that they shape an insideness in the midst of outsideness so that the
individual and group can dwell. In addition, varying physical qualities of floors, walls, and roofs
lead to different experiences of motion, weight, and substance. The result is an intricate set of
tensions between architectural elements and architectural experience:

8What is it that the roof, the floor and the wall do? As a motion, the roof rises or falls. The
walls stand up or sink, the floor spreads out, climbs or descends. In this way, weight is also
implied. That which rises is light, that which falls is heavy. And if the roof is bright and soft as a
sail, it is open. If it is dark and of stone, it is closed. If the openings in a wall are tall and narrow,
they ascend, if they are short and wide, they sink. A soft and fine floor is warm and open, but if it
is hard and coarse, it closes and is heavy ( ibid., 23).

THE WALL AND WINDOW AS EXAMPLES

9In the three main sections of Archetypes, Thiis-Evensen examines the ways through motion,
weight, and substance that floors, walls, and roofs express insideness and outsideness. This
work marks the start toward a descriptive language delineating the invariant elements of the built
environment that have significance for human experience and dwelling.
One example is Thiis-Evensen's explication of the wall, which, of the three archetypes, he shows
to reconcile most potently the relationship between inside and outside, since it is by way of the
wall that one "passes through" between exterior and interior, either physically or visually through
doors and windows. The wall resolves the existential tension between inside and outside in two
ways: either the wall draws exterior space inside, or the wall draws interior space outside. In turn,
this degree of penetration from inside to outside or vice versa can vary: on one hand, there can
be complete openness and invitation; on the other hand, there can be complete closure and
rejection.
One way in which the wall expresses this dialectic between openness and closure is through its
windows, which are said by Thiis-Evensen to contribute to a building's sense of inside and
outside in that they announce the mode of life within the building. Windows are "always an
expression of the interior to the world at large" (ibid., 251):

10While the door is determined by its relation to what is outside, the window is the symbol of
what is inside. Just like the eye, it expresses the interior's outlook over exterior space.... (ibid.).

11Thiis-Evensen points out that a window is much more than a wall opening: a window that is
only a gaping hole makes the wall "a lifeless skin around a dead and empty interior" (ibid., 259).
In clarifying how windows actually give life to a building, he examines the parts of a window--the
opening, the face in the opening, and the frame around the opening. He then considers how each
of these components contributes to a sense of insideness and outsideness.
For example, the frame of a window is important because it makes a setting for the inside space
and brings it toward the viewer on the outside. If the window has no frame, the outside forces its
way in. The frame is important, therefore, because it leads the inside out. This "leading out"
occurs in varying ways, depending on what parts of the frame--sill, lintel, and jambs--are
emphasized or deemphasized (figure 1). If all its parts are emphasized (a in figure 1), then the
entire interior space seems to reach outward. On the other hand, if only the lintel is highlighted,
then an upward movement and roofs take precedence (b); or, if only the sill is highlighted, a
sinking movement and floors take precedence (c). In addition, the sense of movement for a wall
as a whole can be affected by the arrangement of window frames (figures 2 & 3).

figure 1

figure 2
figure 3

12Another important quality that relates to the window's sense of insideness and outsideness is
the shape of its opening for which Thiis-Evensen identifies three variations--vertical (a in figure 4),
horizontal (b), and central (c). These different forms lead to different inside-outside relationships,
thus both vertical (a in figure 5) and central (b) windows suggest a movement coming from inside
out, while a horizontal window (c) suggests an inside lateral movement that is separate from the
person outside.

figure 4

figure 5

13In his explication of the floor, wall, and roof, Thiis-Evensen assumes that there are various
shared existential qualities -- insideness-outsideness, gravity-levity, coldness-warmth, and so
forth -- that mark the foundation of architecture. Thus, a wall with windows whose lintels are
emphasized suggests a sense of upward movement and levity, just as a wall with windows whose
sills are emphasized will feel heavier and in relationship to the ground. Or, if one studies the
experienced qualities of stairs, one realizes that narrow stairs typically relate to privacy and a
faster ascent, whereas wide stairs often relate to publicness, ceremony, and a slower pace.
Similarly, steep stairs express struggle and strength, isolation and survival--experienced qualities
that frequently lead to steep stairs' use as a sacred symbol, as in Mayan temples or Rome's
Scala Santa. On the other hand, shallow stairs encourage a calm, comfortable pace and typically
involve secular use, as, for example, Michelangelo's steps leading up to the Campidoglio of
Rome's Capitoline Hill (ibid., 89-103).

14Thiis-Evensen argues that his work has direct design implications. He claims, that, too often,
an architect's aesthetic sense is subjective because he or she has not thoughtfully considered
how architectural forms arise from and translate themselves back into shared existential qualities
like motion, weight, substance, insideness, outsideness, permeability, closure, and so forth. Thiis-
Evensen believes that understanding the archetypes "and their expressive potentialities is
essential when [a design] vision is to be turned into a realization" (ibid., 387). The result might be
a building whose formal qualities resonate with its practical needs. The possibility becomes
greater that human beings and their built world are reconciled and the quality of dwelling
strengthened.

CHRISTOPHER ALEXANDER AND PATTERN LANGUAGE

15This reconciliation between people and their built world is also a major aim in the research and
design of American architect Christopher Alexander, though he works at a different experiential
scale than Thiis-Evensen, who largely emphasizes lived qualities of individual buildings.
Alexander is more concerned with architecture in its larger environmental context. In other words,
how can activities, buildings, spaces, and landscapes be designed in an integrated, coherent way
to create places that are coherent, beautiful, and alive for their residents and users? In short, the
aim is place making that sustains dwelling.
Like Thiis-Evensen, Alexander believes that architecture today often fails both practically and
aesthetically. He also believes that many built environments of the past--for example, a city like
Venice or Oxford, or a building like Chartres Cathedral or a Japanese farmhouse--generally had a
sense of togetherness and harmony (Alexander, 1979). An important focus of Alexander's work is
how architectural parts belong together in a larger environmental whole (Alexander, 1993).
Alexander argues that, if an environmental whole is made rightly, it has a powerful sense of place,
which may help people who live in and use that place to have more satisfactory, vibrant lives.

16In his work, Alexander seeks a way to return a sense of wholeness to the buildings and
environments of modern Western society. He emphasizes that the crucial process is healing.
Every new construction, whether building or square or street furniture or window detail, must be
made in such a way as to heal the environment, where "heal" especially means "make whole."
The obligation is that the thing built must work "to create a continuous structure of wholes around
itself" (Alexander 1987, p. 22).
The practical tool that Alexander develops to foster environmental wholes and healing is "pattern
language"--a conceptual method whereby the layperson or designer can identify and visualize the
underlying elements and relationships in a built environment that foster a sense of place
(Alexander et al. 1977). In his master volume, Pattern Language (ibid.), Alexander and colleagues
identify 253 of these elements, or patterns, as the are called. A pattern is both interpretive and
prescriptive: first, it is a description of a particular element of the built environment that
contributes to a sense of place (for example, "identifiable neighborhood" [no. 14], "degrees of
publicness " [36], "main gateways" [53], "high places" [62], and "window place" [180]); second, it
is a practical instruction that suggests how to design the particular element effectively (for
example, in regard to "main gateways," "Mark every boundary in the city which has important
human meaning--the boundary of a building cluster, a neighborhood, a precinct--by great
gateways where the major entering paths cross the boundary" [Alexander et al. 1977, p. 278]).

17Alexander emphasizes, however, that successful places are always composed of many
interrelated patterns that work synergistically to create a whole greater than the individual parts.
To incorporate this wholeness in pattern language, Alexander organizes the 253 patterns from
larger to smaller in three groups:

Patterns that describe larger-scale environments that cannot be designed or built all at once
(e.g. community of 7,000," [12], "shopping atterns that describe larger-scale environments that
cannot be designed or built all at once (e.g., street" [32], "housing cluster" [37]);

Patterns that describe buildings and groups of buildings (e.g., "main building" [99], "family of
entrances" [102], "positive outdoor space" [106]);

Patterns that describe individual building details (e.g., "structure follows social spaces" [205],
"columns at the corners" [212], "front door bench" [242]).

18Alexander argues that, for any new design problem, it is important to write a pattern language
that begins with larger patterns and then incorporates smaller patterns. In this way, the larger
qualities of environmental wholeness are held in sight as smaller qualities are fitted around them.
He also emphasizes that the 253 patterns in Pattern Language are illustrative and far from
complete. New design problems and environments may require revised patterns or even entirely
new patterns that the architect will need to create from scratch (e.g., Coates and Seamon, 1993).
In the end, pattern language is not a finished product but an on-going process of dialogue among
architect, client, user, builder, and site. Pattern language is not a master list of unchangeable
design principles that must be incorporated in all buildings and places. Instead, it is a way of
looking at and thinking about buildings and environments so that one can better understand how
their parts might work together to create a whole. As Alexander (1987, p. 16) explains,

19Design must be premised on a process that has the creation of wholeness as its
overriding purpose, and in which every increment of construction, no matter how small, is devoted
to this purpose.

ASPECTS OF AN ARCHITECTURE OF DWELLING

20Like Heidegger, both Thiis-Evensen and Alexander believe that the built world can help
illuminate and sustain essential qualities of human understanding, life, and experience, though
the two architects’ thinking is somewhat different as to what these essential qualities are.
Alexander would no doubt appreciate Thiis-Evensen's effort to understand architectural elements
existentially, but he might ask that Thiis-Evensen give more attention to how individual archetypes
join together into a larger sense of human meaning, environment, and place. For example,
Alexander would probably accept Thiis-Evensen's interpretation of the way that architectural
qualities support a sense of insideness and outsideness, but he would also emphasize that these
architectural qualities are of little use if they do not contribute to the building's wider sense of
place.
To understand more clearly this difference between Alexander and Thiis-Evensen, we can
consider one example--windows, to which both writers devote considerable attention but in
different ways. In Pattern Language, Alexander includes several patterns dealing with windows
and, in each, they work in such as way as to involve people more directly with their place. For
example, the pattern "windows overlooking life" (no. 192) insists that the building, through its
windows, have direct visual or physical relationship with the surroundings so that there will be a
connection between inside and outside. Similarly, the pattern "window place" (no. 180) says that:

21Everyone loves window seats, bay windows, and big windows with low sills and
comfortable chairs drawn up to them....Therefore, in every room where you spend any length of
time during the day, make at least one window into a "window place" (Alexander 1977, p. 834, p.
837).

22This pattern particularly well illustrates Alexander's emphasis on how buildings work as
networks of behaviors and experiences. When people enter a room with a window, Alexander
argues, they typically experience two forces: first, they are drawn toward the light; second, they
want to rest and be comfortable. A window seat automatically resolves these two forces, and a
space is transformed into a place where one can both sit comfortably and enjoy the light.
In pattern language, Alexander uses the term density to describe the multivalent meaning of the
built environment. He explains that "many patterns overlap in the same physical space: the
building is very dense; it has many meanings captured in a small space; and through this density
it becomes profound" (ibid., p. xli). A simple example of density is the "window place" pattern,
which, in terms of Thiis-Evensen’s motion, weight, and substance, could be said to gather and
reconcile darkness-light and movement-rest. By incorporating a "lighted place to be comfortable,"
a room becomes more meaningful and dense than if it included either a "lighted place" or "place
to rest" alone.
Unlike Alexander, Thiis-Evensen does not consider how windows work as a significant locus of
activity. Instead, he speaks of the window largely in terms of its formal existential expression. In
other words, how, by its specific size, shape, and physical arrangement, does a window allow the
interior and exterior of a building to speak or not to speak to the world beyond?

23Thiis-Evensen’s emphasis on how formal architectural qualities are experienced does not
mean that Alexander is more complete in his existential understanding of architecture than Thiis-
Evensen. Rather, these differences in approach and scale point toward the considerable variety
of ways in which the built environment can contribute order and pattern to human life. One can
imagine a continuum of architectural and environmental meaning that runs, on one end, from the
pure architectural element to, on the other end, complex aggregations of buildings, spaces and
environments that evoke a powerful sense of place. A thorough architectural and environmental
phenomenology would delineates this full range of architectural and environmental experience
and considers how qualities of the natural, built, and human worlds contribute to a sense of place
and environmental wholeness.

24In this sense, both Thiis-Evensen and Alexander’s theories of architecture and place are a
major contribution to clarifying Heidegger’s cryptic statement cited at the start of this article
—"Only if we are capable of dwelling, only then can we build." The work of both architects helps
us better to dwell because they help us better to see one part of our world—the way that
architecture can contribute to human being-in-the-world. In different ways, both architects seek a
virtuous circle in which people and world, thinking and designing, designing and building are all
mutually supportive. In this sense, Heidegger would no doubt cheer these works, seeing them as
a pragmatic complement to the larger philosophical questions that he reopens in his own writings.
NOTE

1. Thiis-Evensen's book is a rewritten version of his 1982 doctoral dissertation done under the
direction of Norwegian architect and architectural theorist Christian Norberg-Schulz, one of the
major figures in developing a phenomenology of architecture and environment. Though not
discussed here, Norberg-Schulz's work also draws centrally on Heidegger’s thinking and is
another major contribution to grounding Heidegger’s notion of dwelling practically. See Norberg-
Schulz, 1971, 1980, 1985, 1988.

REFERENCES

Alexander, C., 1987. A New Theory of Urban Design. New York: Oxford University Press.

Alexander, C., 1993. A Foreshadowing of 21st Century Art: The Color and Geometry of Very
Early Turkish Carpets. NY: Oxford University Press.

Alexander, C., Ishikawa, S., & Silverstein, M. 1977. A Pattern Language. New York: Oxford
University Press.

Chaffin, V. F. 1989. Dwelling and Rhythm: The Isle Brevelle as a Landscape of Home.
Landscape Journal, 7: 96-106.

Coates, G. J., and Seamon, D., 1993. Promoting a Foundational Ecology Practically
Through Christopher Alexander’s Pattern Language: The Example of Meadowcreek. In D.
Seamon, ed., Dwelling, Seeing, and Designing. Albany, NY: SUNY Press, pp. 331-54.

Dovey, K. l985. Home and homelessness. In I. Altman & C. M. Werner eds., Home
Environments. New York: Plenum, pp. 33-64.

Foltz, B. V., 1995. Inhabiting the Earth: Heidegger, Environmental Ethics, and the
Metaphysics of Nature. Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press.

Harries, K. 1983. Thoughts on a Non-Arbitrary Architecture. Perspecta, 20, 9-20; reprinted


in Dwelling, Seeing, and Designing, D. Seamon, ed. Albany, NY: SUNY Press, pp. 41-59.

Heidegger, Martin, 1971. Poetry, Language, Thought. New York: Harper and Row.

Jager, Bernd, 1983. Theorizing and the Elaboration of Place: Inquiry into Galileo and Freud,
in A. Giorgi, A. Barton, and C. Maes, eds., Duquesne Studies in Phenomenological Psychology,
vol. 4. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, pp. 153-180.

Mugerauer, R. 1993. Toward an Architectural Vocabulary: The Porch as a Between. In D.


Seamon, ed., Dwelling, Seeing, and Designing. Albany, NY: SUNY Press, pp. 103-28.

Mugerauer, R., 1994. Interpretations on Behalf of Place. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.

Norberg-Schulz, C. 1971. Existence, Space, and Architecture. New York: Praeger.Norberg-


Schulz, C. 1980. Genius Loci: Toward a Phenomenology of Architecture. New York: Rizzoli.

Norberg-Schulz, C. 1985. The Concept of Dwelling: On the Way to a Figurative


Architecture. New York: Rizzoli.

Norberg-Schulz, C. 1988. Architecture: Meaning and Place. New York: Rizzoli.

Relph, E., 1976. Place and Placelessness. London: Pion.


Seamon, D., 1979. A Geography of the Lifeworld. New York: St. Martin's.

Seamon, D., 1982. The Phenomenological Contribution to Environmental Psychology.


Journal of Environmental Psychology, 2, 119-140.

Seamon, D., l987. Phenomenology and Environment-behavior Research. In G. T. Moore


and E. Zube (Eds.), Advances in Environment, Behavior and Design, vol. l. New York: Plenum,
pp. 3-27.

Seamon, D., 1989. Humanistic and Phenomenological Advances in Environmental Design.


The Humanistic Psychologist 17 (Autumn), 280-293.

Seamon, D., 1991. Awareness and Reunion: A Phenomenology of the Person-Environment


Relationship as Portrayed in the New York Photographs of André Kertész, in Place Images in the
Media, L. Zonn (ed.). Totowa, New Jersey: Roman and Littlefield, pp. 87-107.

Seamon, D., ed., 1993. Dwelling, Seeing and Building: Toward a Phenomenological Ecology.
Albany, NY: SUNY Press.

Seamon, D. & Mugerauer, R., eds., 1985. Dwelling, Place and Environment: Towards a
Phenomenology of Person and World. New York: Columbia University Press.

Silverstein, M., 1993. The First Roof: Interpreting a Spatial Pattern. In D. Seamon, ed.,
Dwelling, Seeing, and Designing: Toward a Phenomenological Ecology. Albany, NY: SUNY Press,
pp. 77-101.

Thiis-Evensen, T., 1987. Archetypes in Architecture. Oslo: Norwegian University Press.

Zimmerman, M. 1983. Toward a Heideggerian Ethos for Rational Environmentalism.


Environmental Ethics, 5, 99-131.

Вам также может понравиться