Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 10

The Practice Movement and Planning Theory

Watson
10.1177/0739456X02238446

䉴 Instruction

Do We Learn from Planning Practice?


The Contribution of the Practice
Movement to Planning Theory

Vanessa Watson

Abstract here is a growing consensus in planning theory literature that there has been an

This article examines a central assumption


T emergence of a distinct and identifiable approach to the theorizing of planning.
Broadly termed the practice movement (Liggett 1996), this new approach is character-
that underlies what has been termed the
practice movement in planning theory. The ized by the study of individual planners and planning practice: the documentation and
term refers to the great diversity of recent analysis of the many and varied activities of planners, their products, their interactions,
writings that focus on the activity of plan- and their impacts. The assumption is that it is possible to learn from practice to inform
ning and the practices of planners. It is as-
practice. This raises some central questions: Can documented accounts of experience
sumed that empirical accounts of
planning practice can help to build a more contribute to learning? What theoretical and methodological approaches to the
useful and pragmatic kind of planning understanding of practice can best fulfill its pedagogical potential? and What form can
theory than can the generalized proce- “practice writing” most usefully take? Different forms of practice writing are evident in
dural or normative models that previously
recent literature, and this offers an opportunity to assess the usefulness of this kind of
constituted planning theory and that they
have a pedagogical role to play in relation work.
to practicing planners and planners in The article reviews, first, the emergence of the practice movement within planning
training. This article asks questions about theory and some of the products to which it has given rise. It then examines some
how we learn from practice, how we learn
assumptions about learning from practice by drawing on ideas from the fields of expe-
from other people writing about practice,
and therefore what kind of writing about riential learning and cognitive psychology. The article draws conclusions about the
practice will be most conducive to a learn- kind of approaches and textual strategies that can best promote a learning process.
ing experience.

䉴 The Practice Movement: What Planners Do When They Plan

In the 1950s and 1960s, planning theory was dominated by the rational planning
model, which was concerned primarily with procedural planning issues. It had origins
in writings by Meyerson and Banfield (1955), who in turn were operating within a posi-
tivist epistemology (Faludi 1996) rooted in the enlightenment tradition of modernity
(Healey 1992b). In keeping with its intellectual informants, the rational planning
model assumed that through “the application of scientific knowledge and reason to
human affairs, it would be possible to build a better world, in which the sum of human
Vanessa Watson is a professor in the School Journal of Planning Education and Research 22:178-187
of Architecture and Planning, University DOI: 10.1177/0739456X02238446
of Cape Town, South Africa. © 2002 Association of Collegiate Schools of Planning

178
The Practice Movement and Planning Theory 179

happiness and welfare would be increased” (Healey 1992b, intellectual lenses (Harris 2000) through which the activities
145) and that this can be achieved by the application of a scien- of planners are viewed. Some use this understanding to
tifically rational method by rational individuals (planners). develop normative positions about planning; others focus on
While the rational planning model can still claim defenders analyzing and evaluating planning processes. The outcomes of
(see Faludi 1996; Alexander 1996, 1998) and there have been this work are sometimes difficult to recognize as theory: those
suggestions that it might be making a cautious comeback writing within the practice movement do not necessarily pro-
(Yiftachel 1999), the disillusionment with this approach duce generalizable truths or theories about planning. But they
among planning theorists and practitioners has been widely claim that their highly specific, context-bound accounts of
documented. From the early 1970s, the inability of the rational planning activity are able to bridge the gap between theory and
model to direct or explain planning activity satisfactorily led to practice and are able to give better insight into the nature and
the posing of numerous counterpositions in planning theory. possibilities of planning practice than previous theories were
Some of these attempted to address the inadequacies of the able to do (Innes 1995).
rational model (e.g., incrementalism), some attempted to pre- While this type of work has been referred to in some writ-
scribe different roles for planners (advocacy- and community- ings as a new position, it is generally recognized that as an iden-
based planning), and some analyzed and questioned the role tifiable approach, it has been in existence for fifteen years or
of planning within capitalism (the political economy more (Beauregard 1996). A 1974 article by Martin Krieger sets
approach). The highly fluid nature of planning theory since out many of the basic concepts that were later to inform the
this time has provided fertile ground for the emergence of new practice movement, but these ideas do not find their way into
thinking and space for the ascendancy of new theoretical other published work until the end of the decade. Krieger
domains. questioned the desire for formal generalized models of plan-
Liggett’s (1996) term practice movement is a useful generic ning that remain at the level of generalities and that are
descriptor for the great diversity of writings that are now begin- acontextual. He goes on to argue that a model that is not for-
ning to occupy this space. What distinguishes these contribu- mal, but rather one that incorporates people and that makes
tions from earlier work in planning theory is that they focus on sense, is the model of the everyday life of the community. He
planning as an activity and on the actual practices of planners suggests sources of theory that could be drawn on to develop
as they undertake work that is now accepted as fundamentally this model: phenomenology, language philosophy
political in nature. To quote Mandelbaum (1996) in the intro- (Wittgenstein), linguistics, ethnomethodology, pragmatism,
duction to the volume that was a first attempt to define the and ideas put forward by Habermas. John Forester, later to
shape of this new territory, there is “a pervasive interest in the become a leading contributor to the practice movement, was a
behaviour, values, character and experiences of professional student of Krieger’s when he introduced Habermasian ideas to
planners at work” and in the practices of these planners, which his planning students in the early 1970s (Martin Krieger, per-
encompass “ways of talking, rituals, implicit protocols, rou- sonal communication, 14 September 1997). Howell Baum
tines, relational strategies, character traits and virtues” (1983, 1986, 1996) was another central figure in the develop-
(p. xviii). Judith Innes (1995), in her oft-quoted attempt to ment of this approach. Breakfast meetings in a Cincinnati res-
define practice movement writings as a new planning para- taurant were initiated and organized in 1980 by Howell Baum
digm, describes the “new type of planning theorist” as those with the purpose of bringing together researchers studying
who “take practice as the raw material of their inquiry.” As planning. Along with Charles Hoch and John Forester (Hoch
opposed to their armchair-theorizing predecessors, they 1994, vii) participants soon included Jerry Kaufmann, Richard
ground their theorizing on a “richly interpretative study of Bolan, Helen Liggett, Jim Throgmorton, and many others.
practice” in an attempt to understand both what planners do This became an informal Association of Collegiate Schools of
and to reflect critically on that practice (p. 183). And John For- Planning research group, which had an important impact on
ester (1997), a leading writer in this field, states simply, “Prac- thinking and publishing in the field. In the early 1980s as well,
tice can lead theory, and in planning, the practice of astute, Donald Schon (1983) was developing a critique of professional
sensitive and skilful planners can sometimes lead the more knowledge based on technical rationality and arguing for the
abstract theories of planning academics” (p. 1). development of “an epistemology of practice implicit in the
Practice movement writers have asked both analytical and artistic, intuitive processes which some practitioners do bring
normative questions of planning practice. Thinking in the to situations of uncertainty, instability, uniqueness and value
social and political sciences is drawn on to help structure this conflict” (p. 49). This he termed reflection in action. To support
documentation and analysis, giving a wide variety of this new form of professional knowledge, he argued for the
180 Watson

development of reflective research in which research takes place and in relation to the play of political and economic interests.
in the context of practice to enhance the practitioner’s capac- Lauria and Whelan (1995, 9) have termed the communicative
ity for reflection in action. approach substantively vacuous, and they, together with
By the late 1980s, there were indications on both sides of Feldmann (1997) and Lauria (1997), have called for an under-
the Atlantic of a growing interest in the activities of planning standing of planning within the context of theories of urban
practitioners. By this stage, however, planning theorists were political economy. Fainstein (1995) has criticized the focus on
increasingly drawing on the work of social and political think- process at the expense of a concern with outcomes.
ers to help them formulate analytical and normative ideas Sandercock (1995, 1998), concerned with the substantive
about planning. It is these intellectual roots that have tended ethic of respect for diversity and difference, has called for alter-
to influence the formation of distinct “camps” within the prac- native “ways of knowing” as well as the drawing in of “voices
tice movement and vigorous debate between adherents to dif- from the borderlands” to build progressive planning practices.
fering theoretical positions.1 In a particularly significant challenge, Bent Flyvbjerg
Within the practice movement, the communicative plan- (1998a, 1998b) has taken issue with the understanding of
ning theorists appear currently to hold a dominant position, power used by those drawing on the writings of Habermas. His
largely inspired by the writings of Habermas. Although writers own work, using a Foucaultian concept of power, understands
within this position (Forester, Healey, Hillier, Hoch, Innes, power as always and inevitably present (in either or both pro-
Mandelbaum, Throgmorton, and others) often follow signifi- ductive or dominatory forms) and that cannot be done away
cantly different lines of argument, this approach focuses with by a communicatively rational process. The purpose of
broadly on processes of communication and knowledge pro- understanding planning practices is therefore, for Flyvbjerg,
duction in planning. A central assumption is that no act of to uncover the tactics and strategies of power so that its abuses
communication is ever purely technical and neutral: all techni- can be countered.
cal knowledge is “inevitably infused with biases reflecting par-
ticular interpretative predilections and normative values”
(Healey 1992a, 9). Communicative acts cannot therefore be 䉴 Different Methods, Different Products
taken at face value but have to be interpreted to uncover the
meanings, values, and motives that lie below the surface of Practice movement writers have used different methods to
“technical talk.” A focus on discourse is therefore usually of understand what planners do and have presented the results in
importance to these writers. Also frequently distinguishing different ways. From the earlier efforts to survey planners, on
these writers is a normative (as well as analytical) purpose to the part of writers such as Baum and Hoch, they and others
their work. Forester’s landmark book of 1989 draws on later shifted to a more ethnographic approach that relied on
Habermas’s critical communications theory of social action to in-depth interviews with individual planners.
develop a normative approach to planning, to guide progress The tendency in some of this later work has been to “sur-
toward more democratic decision-making processes. This face the planners” by using direct quotes, and some of For-
work seeks to give guidance to public-serving planning practi- ester’s (1997) recent work, in particular, relies heavily on first-
tioners who are trying to act ethically and responsibly in the person narratives. What is important for Forester is the nature
face of hegemonic powers. Healey’s (1997, 1998, 1999) most of the discourse that occurs in particular situations and the
recent work shifts to an interest in governance processes interpretations that he can draw from it. The style of his many
through which conflicts around spatial and environmental writings on this issue reflects this particular interest: they
issues are managed. She draws on the ideas of “new institu- include snippets of interviews with planners describing their
tional” thinking within the social sciences to “focus the institu- experience or transcripts of meetings, together with his own
tional terrain of the communicative approach in planning the- commentary and interpretation. It is not always clear who
ory” (Healey 1998, 4). these planners are, why they are arguing a particular position,
The kind of practice writing evidenced by Forester and oth- or what the circumstances are surrounding the issues they
ers located within the communicative approach to planning debate. But these details lie beyond the immediate concern of
has drawn comment from a variety of sources.2 Beauregard Forester, who wants to use planners’ discourse to illustrate
(1999) has criticized the “microsociological” approach to more general theoretical points. Other writers, including
planning at the expense of “institutional understandings” Hoch (1994) and Healey (1992a), have, at times, followed this
(p. 99). Fischler (1998) has made this point as well and has approach.
called for a planning theory that contextualizes planning his- Other writers have placed their understanding of planning
torically (and suggests that genealogies form a basis for this) practices within the context of fully elaborated case studies,
The Practice Movement and Planning Theory 181

where time and place become important informants of what different ways and for different reasons. Communicative plan-
planners do. James Throgmorton (1996) is also interested in ning theorists are interested primarily in discourse, whether in
discourse, and his intentions are also pedagogic: his book on speech or text. Writers such as Forester acknowledge the insti-
electric power planning seeks to “help planners and others tutional contexts within which these discussions take place, but
learn how to argue coherently and persuasively about contest- they are not interested in analyzing them. Throgmorton’s
able views of what is good, right and feasible” (p. xiii). He too (1996) story of electric power planning inevitably draws him to
makes extensive use of what his planners and those they inter- consider the context in which his actors are operating, but he
act with have to say. However, he also does a great deal more acknowledges that Foucault would have problems with his fail-
than this. He situates the reader within the history of nuclear ure to account sufficiently for the “discursive formation” cre-
power expansion and within the contemporary economic and ated in the course of the project (p. 268). For writers drawing
political environment affecting power provision. He sketches on Foucault, practices can be both material and discursive.
in the local political milieu and consumer and community Flyvbjerg’s work presents what is said and written, but it also
dynamics. Planners and other central actors in the book are shows how ideas and concepts are produced, reproduced, and
presented “in the round,” and the reader comes to know who changed by the practices of those involved in the Aalborg
they are and whether they can be believed. One learns a lot project.
about the role of discourse from reading this book but not only The point of this article is to provide further argument for
from Throgmorton’s directed interpretations. The material is contextualized practice writing. If practice writing is to achieve
presented in sufficient detail to enable the reader to draw addi- the pedagogic purposes to which many of its advocates refer,
tional or even different conclusions about what these planners then it is particularly important, first, that the pedagogical
say. value of telling planning stories is recognized, and second, that
The same comments could be made about Bent Flyvbjerg’s these stories be told in a way that maximizes their contribution
(1998b) book Rationality and Power. Like Throgmorton, his to learning and hence to a practical and useful planning the-
story of the Aalborg project is placed thoroughly in context, ory. It is to these issues that the article now turns.
both in time and space; in fact, Flyvbjerg finds it necessary to go
back centuries in time to understand the institutional power
relations within which the planners are operating. His actors 䉴 Learning from Practice:
are described, introduced, and allowed to speak. He presents Seeking New Meanings in Old Experience
the minutiae of the Aalborg case quite explicitly to “provide
(readers) with the basis to form their own judgements about Most practice movement writers—some more, some less
the case and its implications” (p. 1). explicitly—see the purpose of their focus on the doings of
Significantly, it is Flyvbjerg’s Foucaultian method (of power planners to be the building of some kind of understanding,
analytics) that leads him to take this approach: an understand- which can in turn be of help or guidance to practicing plan-
ing of power cannot be derived from a theory; it must be “eluci- ners and, presumably, to students of planning as well. The
dated via examples.” Thus, both communicative planning the- notion of learning from practice to assist practice is therefore a
orists and those drawing on Foucault focus on agency but in central one.
different ways and for different reasons. For writers such as Schon and Rein (1994, 196)3 are very clear on this point.
Forester, the focus is on the individual planner, to make clear They argue for collaborative research between academics and
how he or she is helped or hindered in a process of communi- practitioners, which benefits the academic both through the
cation. Fischler (1998, 45) argues that this is ethnographic satisfaction gained from helping practitioners generate usable
enquiry, the aim being the elucidation of the communicative knowledge and through giving the academic better insights
act. For Foucault, and consequently Flyvbjerg, however, the into practice than could otherwise be gained. If policy academ-
focus on agency is part of his historiographical methodology. ics disregard what practitioners already know or are trying to
His genealogies raise questions by explaining how the prac- know, then they will neither grasp what is going on nor succeed
tices we observe came about. As opposed to the Habermasian in getting practitioners to listen to them.
aim of explaining what planners do, a Foucaultian approach The “learning from practice in order to improve practice”
seeks to explain why they do what they do—why planners theme is evident in other writings as well. Yiftachel (1999)
engage in the specific practices of analysis and regulation that notes that “communicative scholars analyze planning with a
characterize modern planning. clear normative task of reforming and improving planning
Both communicative planning theorists and those drawing from within” (p. 268), and communicative theorist Innes
on Foucault are also concerned with discourse but again in (1995) believes that “the planning theorists’ goal should be to
182 Watson

help planners develop a new type of critical, reflective practice Significantly, within the field of education, experiential
which is both ethical and creative” (p. 185). Writers who would learning has become an important thrust. Current leading
not regard themselves as communicative theorists also have writers in the field (Boud, Cohen, and Walker 1993) argue that
pragmatic ambitions. Flyvbjerg (1998a), for one, has been it is “meaningless to talk about learning in isolation from expe-
clear that he sees the analyzing of relations of power in plan- rience . . . learning builds on and flows from experience. . . .
ning processes as a precursor to the development of strategies Learning can only occur only if the experience of the learner is
that can counter the negative exercise of power. engaged” (p. 8). Echoing the position of Schon and the
An important assumption underlying this thinking is that Dreyfus brothers, they suggest that the challenge of new expe-
learning takes place on the basis of experience and, further, riences can be juxtaposed with the “seeking of new meanings
that experience can yield a more useful learning process than, in old experience. . . . We do not simply see a new situation
for example, learning from general theories or rules. There is afresh—what is before us—but in terms of how we relate to it,
a growing body of writing that supports this position. From how it resonates with what past experience has made us.” Cog-
within the planning field, Schon and Rein (1994) argue that nitive psychologists use the term recursion to describe this: the
the purpose of understanding policy practice is “not to draw mind loops back on the output of a previous computation and
from it rules of effective policy making” (p. 193). Policy design- treats it as an input for the next operation (Bruner 1986, 97).
ers, or planners, they suggest, do generalize from particular sit- There is, therefore, support for the idea that the ability to
uations that they have been in but not to produce “covering perform (a professional task) depends on the practitioner’s
laws.” They build up a mental “usable repertoire of unique being able to bring past accumulated experience fruitfully to
cases” (p. 205). When confronted with a new situation, they bear on the problem in hand. For the practice movement,
scan their repertoire of cases looking for points of similarity, however, two important questions remain.
and from past experience they construct an understanding The first is, Can learning, and particularly practitioner
appropriate to the new situation. In this process of “reflective learning, be fostered by indirect experience in the form of
transfer,” both the pattern carried over from the previous situa- texts and reports of practice experiences, that is, through
tion and the understanding formed in the new one are trans- “mediated learning,” as well as by direct encounters with real-
formed. Rather than applying abstract and decontextualized ity? Can academics or planning theorists thus play a role in
rules, they are using judgment based on experience. improving practice by documenting, analyzing, and reflecting
Flyvbjerg (1989, 2001) argues a similar point based on his on the experience of practitioners?
understanding of the Dreyfus Learning Model (Dreyfus and The second question, following from the first, is, If this is
Dreyfus 1986). This phenomenological account of skill acqui- the case, what kind of accounts of practice will be most useful
sition posits a five-step learning sequence that starts with the in generating learning, both among practitioners and also in
level of novice and progresses to the levels of advanced begin- the context of planner training?
ner, competence, proficiency, and, finally, expertise. Novice
learning is characterized by the mastering of a set of context-
independent, generalized rules relating to the skill or exper- 䉴 Mediated Learning: No Lonely
tise in question. The novice can follow these without the bene- Voyage of Each on Their Own
fit of any prior experience, and performance can be judged on
the basis of how well the rules are followed. For the novice to There would seem to be general agreement from the expe-
progress to subsequent stages of learning, it is necessary to riential learning field that direct, firsthand, contact-with-
begin to understand how the rules can be applied under differ- reality kind of experience is very important in fostering learn-
ent conditions or in differing contexts. As Flyvbjerg points out, ing. Some argue that it is the most powerful source of the
exposure to a growing number of cases or situations allows stu- changes that affect an individual’s cognitive and emotional
dents to recognize different features or aspects and apply the functioning (Feuerstein, Klein, and Tannenbaum 1991). This
rules accordingly, adapting their application rather than fol- may be true as well, although to a lesser extent and qualitatively
lowing the rules rigidly. With increasingly complex cases, stu- different, for simulated learning experiences of the kind
dents learn to organize the information by adopting a “per- offered to many planning and architectural students in a stu-
spective” and responding to the features and aspects that the dio setting. Schon (1987) felt strongly about the value of this
perspective makes important. Expertise is achieved only on the form of teaching: “However much students may learn about
basis of a great deal of experience of real-life and varying situa- designing from lectures or readings, there is a substantial com-
tions. Ultimately, the response of the expert becomes intuitive ponent of design competence—indeed, the heart of it—that
rather than based on a consideration of which rules to apply. cannot be learnt in this way” (p. 157).4
The Practice Movement and Planning Theory 183

But there are forceful arguments within the field of cogni- experiences of planning), but they need to be able to identify
tive psychology to the effect that direct, contact-with-reality the nature of the similarity between entities. This requires that
experience may not be enough to foster mental development reference classes be made specific, where these refer to ways in
or learning. This idea first appeared in the work of the Russian which X and Y are similar, or under what circumstances the
psychologist Vygotsky, who argued that conceptual learning is similarity is valid (Verma 1993, 15). The metaphor, which
a collaborative enterprise. We should stop thinking about the unites ideas that do not necessarily belong together, can be
growth of the mind as a “lonely voyage of each on his own.” thought of as a useful tool to form these connections where the
Rather, intelligence is the readiness to use culturally transmit- nature of the relationship can be made explicit. Also impor-
ted knowledge and procedures as “prostheses of the mind” tant to his argument are the kinds of similarities that should be
(Bruner 1986, 141-42). Vygotsky coined the term Zone of Proxi- sought for when comparing different fields or cases. He is insis-
mal Development to describe the distance between a person’s tent that planners focus on teleological similarities, where this
actual development level as determined by independent prob- refers to common purpose between fields, as opposed to mor-
lem solving and his or her level of potential development as phological similarity, which refers to common forms (some-
determined through problem solving in collaboration with times physical) or structures (Verma 1993, 19), while not deny-
more capable peers. These ideas have been developed in more ing that teleological similarity can give rise to morphological
recent work by those concerned with the mediated learning similarity. Planning, he argues, is a teleologically driven disci-
experience (see Feuerstein, Klein, and Tannenbaum 1991). pline and can find different ways of addressing the same prob-
They argue that some individuals are exposed to certain expe- lem. Getting stuck on morphological similarity can interfere
riences throughout their lives without being affected by them with creative choice and freedom.
in the direction of higher levels of functioning, understand-
ing, and adaptation. Rather, we can explain human growth
and cognitive development only by the two-modalities hypoth- 䉴 Writing about Practice:
esis, in which both direct experience and mediated experience The Value of Planning Stories
are involved. In their terms, learning is mediated by the “impo-
sition of an initiated, intentional human being who mediates This section addresses the second question posed above: If
the stimuli” (Feuerstein, Klein, and Tannenbaum 1991, 7). documented accounts of planning practices can play a devel-
Reinforcing this notion of the necessary relationship between opmental role in relation to the practice of planning, what
direct and mediated (in this case, textual) experience, Usher kind of accounts of practices will be most useful in generating
(1993) argues that “learning from experience is conditional this learning? How can practicing or training planners be
on counterpoising experience to something that is not experi- offered information about and interpretation of instances of
ence . . . a point outside experience” (p. 177). planning practice that they might find practically useful in the
Mediated experience can be imparted in a wide variety of forming of judgments about new situations? The ideas raised
ways: verbally, through direct teaching or tutoring; through by writers concerned with learning processes offer some direc-
the studio-based mode of teaching; in text, through the docu- tion in this regard.
mentation of experience; through art, film, literature, and Schon, the Dreyfus brothers, and experiential learning the-
photography, and so on. Documented cases of planning expe- orists all seem to be making a similar point in relation to the
rience must therefore have a crucial role to play in the intellec- learning process. The practitioner will mentally carry a “usable
tual development of either practicing planners or planners in repertoire of unique cases” (Schon and Rein 1994) or “experi-
training, as a supplement to real life or simulated experience. ence of real-life and varying situations” (Dreyfus and Dreyfus,
In certain other teaching fields, in which schools of public in Flyvbjerg 2001). In a new (planning) situation, practitioners
management appear to have become leaders in this regard, will “scan their repertoire of cases looking for points of similar-
teaching on the basis of case studies has long been the norm ity, and from past experience construct an understanding
(see Christensen, Garvin, and Sweet 1991; Schutte 1997). appropriate to the new situation” (Schon and Rein 1994, 205).
The question that needs to be raised, however, is whether Dreyfus and Dreyfus (1986) talk about how
indirect learning from texts or reports of experience needs to
experience-based holistic recognition of similarity pro-
be as intuitive or random as some of this writing suggests. The duced deep situational understanding. . . . The mind of the
work of Niraj Verma (1993, 1995) suggests ways in which this proficient performer seems to group together situations
process can be made more rigorous. Verma argues that plan- sharing not only the same goal or perspective but also the
same decision, action or tactic. At this point not only is a sit-
ners can and should learn by making connections between dif-
uation, when seen as similar to a prior one, understood, but
ferent fields of inquiry (and presumably between different
184 Watson

the associated decision, action or tactic simultaneously phenomenon within some real-life context” (p. 1). This
comes to mind. (P. 32)
is not to suggest that other kinds of writing about plan-
Experiential learning theorists believe that the “challenge ning—general reviews or surveys of planning across a
of new experiences can be juxtaposed with the seeking of new range of contexts, conceptual explorations of planning
meanings in old experience,” or the mind does a recursive issues and problems, recommendations for strategies of
loop. Verma (1993) has put forward a possible method to certain kinds, and so on—are any less useful. But case
studies, which by definition are contextually grounded,
guide such a loop. So one role for practice writing is to help
comprehensive, and empirically detailed, can poten-
planners (through mediated experience) to build up their
tially address the basic practice movement assumption
mental repertoire of past experience, which in turn will be
that planning theory (and not a planning theory) can
interpreted into thinking about new situations or problems.
be built on a better understanding of planning prac-
But it is important not to treat this position uncritically. In
tices.
learning from the experience of others, it is necessary to ask,
• A crucial aspect of this contextualizing has to do with pro-
Whose experience is this? Under what circumstances was it 5
cess, or history. If the aim is to produce mediated accounts
gained? Is “higher ground” better ground? And how do I evalu-
of experience that can be interpreted, incorporated, and
ate another’s experience or interpretation of experience?
mobilized in the practitioner’s mental repertoire of cases,
Experiential learning theorist Robin Usher (1993) probes fur-
then history is a crucial dimension of these experiences. As
ther. As he points out, “Accounts are, of necessity, discursive,
Fischler (1998, 2000) has suggested, history is a source of
they are cast in and communicated through language and are good case studies of planners in action as it provides instruc-
understood by us in terms of our discursive frameworks” tive precedent, and it is of great value in explanatory plan-
(p. 169). Experience does not have its own intrinsic meaning ning theory when we want to understand why planners act
waiting to be discovered: experience is understood from a par- 6
in particular ways, as well as understand what they do. In
ticular standpoint and through the preunderstandings that sit- Foucaultian terms, such inquiry takes the form of docu-
uated the person exposed to this experience. Furthermore, menting sequences of actual events rather than focusing on
writing about this experience occurs in and through language. the history of discourse or theories (Flyvbjerg 1998a). It ad-
The discourses within which we operate, the textual strategies dresses the question, How did the practices that we can ob-
we use, create a particular world that is a truth but not the truth. serve come about? It also addresses the development of
In the end, meaning is in the hands of the readers of the text. professional modes of thinking and acting, or practices of
For practice movement writers, then, it can be accepted analysis and action that have been developed to address
that there is no simple translation of an experience (of a particular problems, and how particular planners operate
planning-related problem or situation) from the practitioner within and against these practices. For Fischler (1998),
to the writer, to the reader of the text, and to the user of its there is a further need to take into account the evolution of
ideas. Framing and reframing of this experience, interpreta- the institutional and legislative context within which plan-
tion, and reinterpretation take place at a number of stages in ners operate, bringing together “the ethnographic analysis
of planners’ behaviour, the geneological analysis of plan-
the process. And this should not necessarily be regarded as
ning practices and the political-economic analysis of plan-
some kind of interference or imposition of authority: it can
ning institutions” (p. 27).
provide perspectives or counterpoints that add to learning.
These ideas do, however, have implications for the kind of • Accounts of planning practices that are rich in contextual
detail also allow readers to add to their mental repertoire of
research and writing that is useful if it is to fulfill the type of
unique instances of planning and to judge the extent to
learning function described above:
which there are sufficient points of similarity with a current
• Case studies of planning, which lend themselves at least problem for it to be useful. Perhaps one of the most difficult
to partial demarcation (spatially, temporally, institution- problems that have to be faced when trying to draw on un-
ally, organizationally, experientially, etc.), potentially of- derstandings or ideas developed in a different context is
fer a framework for interrelating actors, circumstances, that of how transferable they are: What is unique to a partic-
contextual settings, and sequences of events. The case ular time and place, and what is more general? It is only
study, Fischler (1998) suggests, is the primary weapon of depth of contextualizing detail (thick description) that will
the planning theorist. Research methodologist Yin allow this kind of judgment to be made. Deep situational
(1994) argues that case studies are the preferred re- understanding is essential input when dealing with new
search method “when ‘how’ or ‘why’ questions are be- problems and circumstances.
ing posed . . . and when the focus is on a contemporary
The Practice Movement and Planning Theory 185

• Hoch (1996, 43) has suggested that planners become “sto- speak through the use of direct quotes has been used
rytellers of practice,” and several recent examples of plan- effectively by most practice movement writers. But it is also
ning case study writing (Flyvbjerg 1998a; Forsyth 1999; necessary to understand this discourse in its context of a se-
Throgmorton 1996; Watson 2002) have indeed adopted quence of events if the reader is to move beyond a partial
the narrative approach. Narratives have a number of char- and simplistic view of who is doing the talking.
acteristics that separate them from history, although there • In the same vein, writers of planning texts—documenters
are clearly many overlaps. Narratives have a temporal or se- of planning experience—are also rarely, if ever, neutral,
quential framework, they have an element of explanation technical, and rational beings. The greatest possible trans-
or coherence, they have some element of the general in the parency in terms of who is doing the writing, for what rea-
particular, and they recognize generic conventions relating son, under what circumstances, and with what conceptual
to the expected framework, protagonists, and modes of baggage can allow the reader greater scope for interpreting
performance or circulation (Finnegan 1998, 9). Bruner the meaning and usefulness of the material. This requires a
(1986, 1996) has argued that “ordinary people go about degree of self-reflection and the writing of the author into
making sense of their experiences” (Bruner 1996, 130) by the text.
construing their reality through the narrative mode. Re-
lating (planning) experiences through narrative may thus
be the most effective way of communicating and transfer- 䉴 Conclusion
ring this experience to others. This is particularly applica-
ble given that the aim of relating experience is less to This article has argued for the value of the new focus in
provide the reader with universal truths or generalizations planning theory: on planning practices. It has examined the
about plans or planning (the existence of which in any assumption that documented planning practices provide a
event is questionable, in the highly particular and context- vehicle for learning and has found support for this from the
bound situations in which much planning occurs) but
disciplines of education and experiential learning. Fulfilling
rather to give insight into how messy problems involving
the learning potential of practice writing, however, seems to
values, judgment, multiple interpretations, planners’ par-
require that practices are documented in particular ways, and
ticular identities, and personal and group agendas have un-
the article calls attention to the value of in-depth, case-study
folded in particular contexts. Any one narrative on its own
research that takes the form of fully contextualized stories of
cannot provide the definitive guidance that planners seek
planning practice.
in their daily work. But as the literature on learning re-
ferred to above suggests, the building of a mental reper-
Author’s Note: A previous version of this article was presented at the
toire of many such narratives and cases can provide the
Planning Research 2000 Conference, London School of Economics (March
basis for the kind of expert judgment required in the day-to-
2000). It has benefited greatly from the comments of three anonymous re-
day work of planners. viewers, one of whom in particular I would like to thank for information on
• Linked to the above, actors or practitioners need to be por- Baum’s breakfast meetings.
trayed in text as richly and transparently as possible. Baum
(1996) has argued that we need to “discard reassuring but
simplistic notions of what planners do” (p. 378). Rarely are 䉴 Notes
they neutral, technical, rational beings. They think and feel
about their work, experience pleasure and anxiety, have ir- 1. These debates have taken place within journals (particularly
rational feelings, operate on the basis of particular values or Planning Theory) and at conferences, with the Third Planning The-
ethics, and, importantly, they function in a context in which ory Conference at Oxford in 1998 providing an important plat-
form for discussion.
they try to exert power and are affected by power.
2. Yiftachel (1999) identifies practice movement writers falling
Beauregard (1999, 93) has demanded that planning theo- outside the communicative-pragmatist school as Beauregard,
rists report on more than just the activities that comprise Fainstein, Feldman, Flyvbjerg, Friedmann, Hajer, Huxley, Lauria,
practice but that they also “write the planner who will carry Marcuse, Richardson, Sandercock, and himself, but he recognizes
out these actions” and “address the identity of their plan- that there is also great diversity in terms of their areas of interest
and lines of argument.
ners” and hence the often-implicit assumptions that under-
3. Schon (1983, 1987) develops these ideas in earlier work as
lie what they do and say. Such advice is important but needs well.
to recognize that individuals can be complex and conflict 4. The word design here, as used by Schon (1987), reflects broad
ridden and can assume different identities in different situ- problem-solving activity rather than physical design in the narrow
ations. The tactic of allowing actors and practitioners to sense.
186 Watson

5. In using history, it is obviously important to be wary of the Feuerstein, Reuven, Pnina Klein, and Abraham Tannenbaum.
simplistic use of precedent and stressing superficial similarities at 1991. Mediated learning experience: Theoretical, psychological and
the expense of fundamental differences between one age and learning implications. London: Freund.
another, as well as historicism, which holds that each age is entirely Finnegan, Ruth. 1998. Tales of the city: A study of narrative and urban
unique and that there is no continuity (and hence the possibility of life. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
learning) between past and present. Fischler, Ralph. 1998. Communicative planning theory and genea-
6. Neither Habermasians nor Foucaultians have been necessar- logical inquiry. Paper presented at the Planning Theory Con-
ily concerned with explaining why planners do what they do. The ference, Oxford Brookes University, Oxford, UK.
former have been concerned with how planning works (for better . 2000. Linking planning theory and history: The case of
or worse) and the latter, following Foucault, with how events have development control. Journal of Planning Education and Research
come about rather than causation. 19 (2): 233-41.
Flyvbjerg, Bent. 1989. Socrates didn’t like the case method: Why
should you? In Case method research and application: New vistas,
edited by Hans E. Klein, 33-42. Needham, MA: World Associa-
䉴 References tion for Case Method Research and Application.
. 1998a. Empowering civil society: Habermas, Foucault and
Alexander, Ernest. 1996. After rationality: Towards a contingency the question of conflict. In Cities for citizens: Planning and the rise
theory for planning. In Explorations in planning theory, edited by of civil society in a global age, edited by Mike Douglass and John
Seymour Mandelbaum, Luigi Mazza, and Robert Burchell, 45- Friedmann, 185-211. Chichester, UK: John Wiley.
64. New Brunswick, NJ: Center for Urban Policy Research, . 1998b. Rationality and power: Democracy in practice. Chicago:
Rutgers University. University of Chicago Press.
. 1998. Rationality revisited: Planning paradigms in a post- . 2001. Making social science matter: Why social inquiry fails and
modern perspective. Paper presented at the Planning Theory how it can succeed again. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University
Conference, Oxford Brookes University, Oxford, UK. Press.
Baum, Howell. 1983. Planners and public expectations. Cambridge, Forester, John. 1989. Planning in the face of power. Berkeley: Univer-
MA: Schenkman. sity of California Press.
. 1986. Politics and ambivalence in planners’ practice. In . 1997. Learning from practice: Democratic deliberations and the
Strategic perspectives on planning practice, edited by Barry promise of planning practice. College Park: University of Maryland
Checkoway. Lexington, MA: D. C. Heath. Press.
. 1996. Practicing planning theory in a political world. In Forsyth, Ann. 1999. Constructing suburbs: Competing voices in a debate
Explorations in planning theory, edited by Seymour Mandelbaum, over urban growth. Reading, MA: Gordon and Breach.
Luigi Mazza, and Robert Burchell, 365-82. New Brunswick, NJ: Harris, Neil. 2000. Practice through a lens: A metaphor for plan-
Center for Urban Policy Research, Rutgers University. ning theory. Journal of Planning Education and Research 19 (2):
Beauregard, Robert. 1996. Advocating pre-eminence: Anthologies 309-15.
as politics. In Explorations in planning theory, edited by Seymour Healey, Patsy. 1992a. A planner’s day: Knowledge and action in
Mandelbaum, Luigi Mazza, and Robert Burchell, 105-10. New communicative practice. Journal of the American Planning Associ-
Brunswick, NJ: Center for Urban Policy Research, Rutgers ation 58 (1): 9-20.
University. . 1992b. Planning through debate: The communicative
. 1999. Writing the planner. Journal of Planning Education turn in planning theory. Town Planning Review 63 (2): 143-62.
and Research 18 (2): 93-101. . 1997. Collaborative planning: Shaping places in fragmented soci-
Boud, David, Ruth Cohen, and David Walker, eds. 1993. Using expe- eties. London: Macmillan.
rience for learning. Bristol, UK: Society for Research into Higher . 1998. Institutional analysis, communicative planning and
Education and Open University Press. shaping places. Paper presented at the Planning Theory Con-
Bruner, Jerome. 1986. Actual minds, possible worlds. Cambridge, MA: ference, Oxford Brookes University, Oxford, UK.
Harvard University Press. . 1999. Institutional analysis, communicative planning and
. 1996. The culture of education. Cambridge, MA: Harvard shaping places. Journal of Planning Education and Research 19
University Press. (2): 111-21.
Christensen, C. Roland, David Garvin, and Ann Sweet, eds. 1991. Hoch, Charles. 1994. What planners do: Power, politics and persuasion.
Education for judgement. Boston: Harvard Business School Press. Chicago: Planners Press, American Planning Association.
Dreyfus, Hubert, and Stuart Dreyfus. 1986. Mind over machine: The . 1996. A pragmatic inquiry about planning and power. In
power of human intuition and expertise in the era of the computer. New Explorations in planning theory, edited by Seymour Mandelbaum,
York: Free Press. Luigi Mazza, and Robert Burchell, 30-44. New Brunswick, NJ:
Fainstein, Susan. 1995. Politics, economics, and planning: Why Center for Urban Policy Research, Rutgers University.
urban regimes matter. Planning Theory 14:34-41. Innes, Judith. 1995. Planning theory’s emerging paradigm: Com-
Faludi, Andreas. 1996. Rationality, critical rationalism, and plan- municative action and interactive practice. Journal of Planning
ning doctrine. In Explorations in planning theory, edited by Education and Research 14 (3): 183-89.
Seymour Mandelbaum, Luigi Mazza, and Robert Burchell, 65- Krieger, Martin. 1974. Some new directions for planning theories.
82. New Brunswick, NJ: Center for Urban Policy Research, Journal of the American Planning Association 40:156-63.
Rutgers University. Lauria, Micky, and Robert Whelan. 1995. Planning theory and
Feldmann, Marsh. 1997. Can we talk? Interpretive planning theory political economy: The need for reintegration. Planning Theory
as comedy. Planning Theory 17:43-64. 14:8-33.
The Practice Movement and Planning Theory 187

. 1997. Communicating in a vacuum: Will anyone hear? Africa, edited by Patrick Fitzgerald, Anne McLennan, and Barry
Planning Theory 17:40-64. Munslow, 292-308. Cape Town, South Africa: Oxford University
Liggett, Helen. 1996. Examining the planning practice con- Press.
scious(ness). In Explorations in planning theory, edited by Sey- Throgmorton, James. 1996. Planning as persuasive storytelling: The
mour Mandelbaum, Luigi Mazza, and Robert Burchell, 299- rhetorical construction of Chicago’s electric future. Chicago: Univer-
306. New Brunswick, NJ: Center for Urban Policy Research, sity of Chicago Press.
Rutgers University. Usher, Robin. 1993. Experiential learning or learning from experi-
Mandelbaum, Seymour. 1996. Introduction: The talk of the com- ence: Does it make a difference? In Using experience for learning,
munity. In Explorations in planning theory, edited by Seymour edited by David Boud, Ruth Cohen, and David Walker, 169-80.
Mandelbaum, Luigi Mazza, and Robert Burchell, xi-xix. New Bristol, UK: Society for Research into Higher Education and
Brunswick, NJ: Center for Urban Policy Research, Rutgers Open University Press.
University. Verma, Niraj. 1993. Metaphor and analogy as elements of a theory
Meyerson, Martin, and Edward C. Banfield. 1955. Politics, planning of similarity for planning. Journal of Planning Education and
and the public interest: The case of public housing in Chicago. New Research 13:13-25.
York: Free Press. . 1995. What is planning practice? The search for suitable
Sandercock, Leonie. 1995. Voices from the borderlands: A media- categories. Journal of Planning Education and Research 14:178-82.
tion on a metaphor. Journal of Planning Education and Research Watson, Vanessa. 2002. Change and continuity in spatial planning:
14 (2): 77-88. Metropolitan planning in Cape Town under political transition. Lon-
. 1998. Towards cosmopolis: Planning for multicultural cities. don: Routledge.
Chichester, UK: John Wiley. Yiftachel, Oren. 1999. Planning theory at the crossroad: The Third
Schon, Donald. 1983. The reflective practitioner. New York: Basic Oxford Conference. Journal of Planning Education and Research
Books. 18 (3): 267-70.
. 1987. Educating the reflective practitioner. San Francisco: Yin, Robert. 1994. Case study research: Design and methods. Vol. 5,
Jossey-Bass. Applied Social Research Methods Series. Thousand Oaks, CA:
Schon, Donald, and Martin Rein. 1994. Frame reflection. New York: Sage.
Basic Books.
Schutte, Lauren. 1997. New training approaches: Exploring the
paradigm shift. In Managing sustainable development in South

Вам также может понравиться