Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 289

The Bloomsbury Companion to

Political Philosophy
Other volumes in the series of Bloomsbury Companions

Aesthetics, edited by Anna Christina Locke, edited by S.-J. Savonious-Wroth, Paul


Ribeiro Schuurman and Jonathan Walmsley
Analytic Philosophy, edited by Barry Dainton Metaphysics, edited by Robert W. Barnard
and Howard Robinson and Neil A. Manson
Continental Philosophy, edited by John Ó Philosophical Logic, edited by Leon Horston
Maoilearca and Beth Lord and Richard Pettigrew
Epistemology, edited by Andrew Cullison Philosophy of Language, edited by Manuel
Ethics, edited by Christian Miller Garcia-Carpintero and Max Kolbel
Existentialism, edited by Felicity Joseph, Jack Philosophy of Mind, edited by James Garvey
Reynolds and Ashley Woodward Philosophy of Science, edited by Steven
Hegel, edited by Allegra de Laurentiis and French and Juha Saatsi
Jeffrey Edwards Plato, edited by Gerald A. Press
Hume, edited by Alan Bailey and Dan Pragmatism, edited by Sami Pihlström
O’Brien Socrates, edited by John Bussanich and
Hobbes, edited by S. A. Lloyd Nicholas D. Smith
Kant, edited by Gary Banham, Dennis Spinoza, edited by Wiep van Bunge, Henri
Schulting and Nigel Hems Krop, Piet Steenbakkers and Jeroen van de
Leibniz, edited by Brendan Look Ven
THE BLOOMSBURY
COMPANION TO POLITICAL
PHILOSOPHY

Edited by

Andrew Fiala

Bloomsbury Academic
An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc

L ON DON • N E W DE L H I • N E W Y OR K • SY DN EY
Bloomsbury Academic
An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc

50 Bedford Square 1385 Broadway


London New York
WC1B 3DP NY 10018
UK USA

www.bloomsbury.com

BLOOMSBURY and the Diana logo are trademarks of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc

First published 2015

© Andrew Fiala and Contributors, 2015

Andrew Fiala has asserted his right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988,
to be identified as the Editor of this work.

All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or


transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including
photocopying, recording, or any information storage or retrieval system,
without prior permission in writing from the publishers.

No responsibility for loss caused to any individual or organization acting on or


refraining from action as a result of the material in this publication can be accepted by
Bloomsbury or the authors.

British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data


A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library.

ISBN: HB: 978-1-84706-554-4


╇╇╇╛╛╛ePDF: 978-1-44114-217-7
╇╇╇╇╛ePub: 978-1-44111-434-1

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data


A catalog record for this book is available from the Library of Congress

Typeset by Newgen Knowledge Works (P) Ltd., Chennai, India


CONTENTS

List of Contributors vii

INTRODUCTION 1
Andrew Fiala
  1. THE HISTORY OF POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 19
James Alexander
  2. SOVEREIGNTY 33
Andrew Fiala
  3. COSMOPOLITANISM 47
Gillian Brock
  4. HUMAN RIGHTS 61
Siegfried Van Duffel
  5. DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE 75
Ovadia Ezra
  6. REASSESSING PUNISHMENT: RETRIBUTIVE VERSUS
RESTORATIVE JUSTICE 95
Trudy D. Conway
  7. WAR 109
George R. Lucas, Jr
  8. PEACE 127
Andrew Fitz-Gibbon
  9. LIBERAL TOLERATION 139
Robert Paul Churchill
10. DEMOCRATIC THEORY 153
Jacquelyn Ann K. Kegley
11. FEMINISM AND GENDER 167
Anca Gheaus
12. IMMIGRATION AND BORDERS 183
Shelley Wilcox

v
contents

13. THE FUTURE(S) OF POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 199


Matthew Voorhees and J. Jeremy Wisnewski
14. GLOBALIZATION, COSMOPOLITICS, DECOLONIALITY:
POLITICS FOR/OF THE ANTHROPOCENE 213
Eduardo Mendieta

Chronology 223
Glossary 227
Research Resources 255
Annotated Bibliography 259
Index 265

vi
LIST OF CONTRIBUTORS

James Alexander, PhD is an assistant pro- Gillian Brock, PhD is Professor of


fessor in the Department of Political Philosophy at the University of Auckland
Science, Bilkent University, Ankara, Turkey. in New Zealand. Her most recent work
Originally a Cambridge historian, educated has been on global justice and related
in the era of Cowling, Skinner, and Dunn, fields. Her books include: Debating
he shifted, as many did, to political phil- Brain Drain (Oxford University Press,
osophy, and is still trying to make philo- 2015), Cosmopolitanism versus Non-
sophical sense of the distinctively historical Cosmopolitanism (Oxford University Press,
approach to politics. He is the author of 2013), Global Heath and Global Health
“The Contradictions of Conservatism,” Ethics (Cambridge University Press, 2011),
Government and Opposition (2013); “Notes Global Justice: A Cosmopolitan Account
Towards a Definition of Politics,” Philosophy (Oxford University Press, 2009), Necessary
(2014); and “The Major Ideologies of Goods: Our Responsibilities to Meet
Liberalism, Socialism and Conservatism,” Others’ Needs (Rowman & Littlefield,
Political Studies (2014). 1998), and Current Debates in Global
Justice (Springer, 2005).
Andrew Fiala, PhD is Professor of Philosophy,
Chair of the Philosophy Department, and Siegfried Van Duffel, PhD has taught Ethics
Director of the Ethics Center at California and Political Theory at the University of
State University, Fresno. He is the author of Groningen, the University of Hong Kong,
a number of books and articles on ethics, and Nazarbayev University. He also
religion, and political philosophy including: held post-doc positions at the National
The Just War Myth (Rowman & Littlefield, University of Singapore and the University
2008), Public War, Private Conscience of Helsinki and was visiting Associate
(Continuum, 2010), Against Religions, Professor at Huafan University and
Wars, and States (Rowman & Littlefield, National Taiwan University. He is cur-
2013), Civility and Education in a World of rently writing a book on human rights and
Religious Pluralism, co-edited with Vincent cultural differences. He has published in
Biondo (Routledge, 2013), and Ethics: journals such as The Pacific Philosophical
Theory and Contemporary Issues, eighth Quarterly, The Journal of Political
edition, with co-author Barbara MacKinnon Philosophy, The Monist, and The European
(Cengage Publishing, 2014). Journal of Philosophy.

vii
LIST OF CONTRIBUTORS

Ovadia Ezra, PhD is a senior lecturer in Military Intervention (University of


the Department of Philosophy at Tel Aviv California Press, 2001), Lifeboat Ethics: the
University and a human rights activist. He Moral Dilemmas of World Hunger (Harper
was incarcerated several times in a military & Row, 1976), Poverty, Justice, and the Law:
jail for refusing to serve reserve military serv- Essays on Needs, Rights, and Obligations
ice in the occupied territories. He writes on (UPA, 1986), and a number of other books
ethics, political, and social philosophy. He is and articles.
the author of the books: The Withdrawal Of
Rights: Rights from A different Perspective Andrew Fitz-Gibbon, PhD is a fellow
(Kluwer, 2002), Moral Dilemmas in Real of the Royal Society of Arts, Professor
Life: Current Issues in Applied Ethics (Spring, of Philosophy, Chair of the Philosophy
2006), Justice and Equality: Affirmative Department, and Director of the Center
Action Needed (Hakibutz Hameuhad-Sifriat for Ethics, Peace and Social Justice, at the
Poalim, 2006). State University of New York College at
Cortland. He is the author, co-author, or edi-
Trudy D. Conway, PhD is Professor of tor of ten books, numerous book chapters,
Philosophy at Mount Saint Mary’s University and articles in peer-reviewed journals such
in Maryland; prior to that she taught at as Social Philosophy Today, The Journal for
Shiraz (formerly Pahlavi University) in Iran. Peace and Justice Studies, The Acorn, Peace
Her areas of specialization are contemporary Review, and Philosophical Practice. He is
philosophy, virtue ethics, especially virtues an associate editor, VIBS, Editions Rodopi,
associated with cross-cultural understanding B.V., where he edits the Social Philosophy
and dialogue, and cross-disciplinary stud- Series.
ies of the death penalty. She is the author of
Wittgenstein on Foundations (Humanities Robert Paul Churchill, PhD is Elton Professor
Press International, 1989), Where Justice of Philosophy at George Washington
and Mercy Meet (Liturgical Press, 2013), University where he has also served as
and Cross-Cultural Dialogue on the Virtues Chair of the Department of Philosophy and
(Spring, 2014) and a range of articles on spe- Director of the Peace Studies Program. He
cific virtues and select issues in contempor- is the author or editor of five books and has
ary philosophy. published dozens of book chapters and jour-
nals and encyclopedia articles on a variety
George R. Lucas, Jr, PhD is Class of 1984 of subjects including altruism, civil disobe-
Distinguished Chair in Ethics in the Vice dience, crimes against humanity, genocide,
Admiral James B. Stockdale Center for humanitarian intervention, human rights,
Ethical Leadership at the United States just war theory, nonviolence, pacifism, tol-
Naval Academy (Annapolis), and Professor erance, and violence. His most recent book
of Ethics and Public Policy at the Graduate is Human Rights and Global Diversity
School of Public Policy at the Naval (Pearson, 2005).
Postgraduate School (Monterey, CA). He is
the author of Anthropologists in Arms: The Jacquelyn Ann K. Kegley, PhD is Professor
Ethics of Military Anthropology (AltaMira of Philosophy at California State University,
Press, 2009), Perspectives on Humanitarian Bakersfield. She is author of Josiah

viii
LIST OF CONTRIBUTORS

Royce in Focus (Indiana University Press, Matthew Voorhees, PhD is currently an


2008) and Genuine Individuals and Genuine associate professor of Political Science at
Communities: A Roycean Public Philosophy Hartwick College, where he teaches courses
(Vanderbilt University Press, 1997). She is on the history of political thought, democratic
an author and editor of Genetic Knowledge, theory, American political thought, the phi-
Human Values and Responsibility (Paragon, losophy of law and American Constitutional
1999)  and Persuasion and Compulsion in law. He has published work on the relation-
Democracy (Lexington, 2013). She was ship between Rousseau’s musical and politi-
President of the Society for the Advancement cal theory and his current research focuses on
of American Philosophy from 2010 to 2012 African-American autobiographical writing
and a recipient of the Herbert Schneider as a form of political discourse in American
Award for outstanding contributions of political thought.
American Philosophy.
J. Jeremy Wisnewski, PhD is Associate
Anca Gheaus, PhD works at the universi- Professor of Philosophy at Hartwick College.
ties of Umea in Sweden and Sheffield in the He is the author of numerous publication
United Kingdom. Her main research is in in phenomenology and moral and political
caring relationships and what they mean for philosophy. His books include Wittgenstein
distributive justice, in the nature and value and Ethical Inquiry (Continuum, 2007),
of childhood and in gender justice. A recent The Politics of Agency: Toward a Pragmatic
publication on the latter topic is “Gender Philosophical Anthropology (Ashgate, 2008),
Justice” in the Journal for Ethics & Social and Understanding Torture (Edinburgh
Philosophy 6(1) (2012). She is currently University Press, 2010).
working toward a monograph on justice in
childrearing. Eduardo Mendieta, PhD is Professor of
Philosophy, and Chair of the Department of
Shelley Wilcox, PhD is Professor of Philosophy, at the State University of New
Philosophy at San Francisco State University. York, Stony Brook. He is the author of The
She works in the areas of social and politi- Adventures of Transcendental Philosophy
cal philosophy, feminist philosophy, and (Rowman & Littlefield, 2002)  and Global
applied ethics, with a special interest in Fragments: Globalizations,Latinamericanisms,
immigration, global justice, and urban envi- and Critical Theory (SUNY Press, 2007). He is
ronmental issues. She has published articles also co-editor with Jonathan VanAntwerpen
on the ethics of immigration and globaliza- of The Power of Religion in the Public Sphere
tion in Philosophical Studies, Social Theory (Columbia University Press, 2011), and with
and Practice, Journal of Social Philosophy, Craig Calhoun and Jonathan VanAntwerpen
Philosophy Compass, and The Stanford of Habermas and Religion (Polity, 2013),
Encyclopedia of Philosophy, as well as in and with Stuart Elden of Reading Kant’s
numerous anthologies. She is currently serv- Geography (SUNY Press, 2011). His book
ing as Book Review Editor for Hypatia: A The Philosophical Animal will be published by
Journal of Feminist Philosophy. SUNY Press in 2015.

ix
INTRODUCTION
Andrew Fiala

Political philosophy is a broad field of inquiry important names in the history of philosophy
with a deep history, a vexing set of prob- in general: Plato, Aristotle, Hobbes, Locke,
lems, and a contested methodology. Political Rousseau, Kant, Hegel, Marx, and Mill.
philosophy can also have important practi- The problems of political philosophy have
cal impacts. The field includes a variety of inspired and troubled the best minds in the
questions about the legitimacy and optimal philosophical canon; and issues in political
structure of states, the role of citizens within philosophy are connected to issues in the rest
these states, the proper behavior of governing of philosophy. Contemporary political phil-
authorities, relations between states, and the osophy builds upon this history, while also
status of norms—such as justice and rights— criticizing it. Contemporary authors includ-
in both domestic and international contexts. ing feminists, cosmopolitans, anarchists, and
Beneath this set of issues are profound others are pushing boundaries and challen-
questions about human nature. Are human ging the assumptions of the discipline—in-
beings individuals first, whose membership cluding the Eurocentric assumptions of the
in social groups is only legitimately derived canon of political philosophy.
from individual consent by a social contract? Political philosophy develops along with
Or are states and other associations histori- the rest of culture. Political philosophy
cally, ontologically, and normatively more impacts political reality, as political philoso-
significant than the individuals who con- phers such as Locke or Marx have inspired
stitute them? Are we warlike and competi- revolutions. But political philosophy must
tive or are we cooperative and reasonable? also respond to the political world. Issues in
Can we live well without social interaction the contemporary world drive philosophical
and legal regulation or do we benefit from inquiry. Locke or Marx, for example, were
the benevolent control of ruling authorities? responding to the concerns of their contem-
How ought we regulate our lives, structure porary political actuality—including issues
our social organizations, and relate to one arising out of the Reformation, colonialism,
another across the globe? How do we define or the development of capitalism. Today’s
and ground key concepts such as human emerging issues include secularization, mod-
rights, justice, equality, and liberty? ernization, globalization, democratization,
It is no surprise that the big names in the liberalization, and the lingering problems of
history of political philosophy are, indeed, the Eurocentrism and postcolonial development.

1
Andrew Fiala

Our thinking about borders, immigration, inquiry is itself part of the political landscape
and sovereignty is being revised. Our under- engaged in struggles for power and recog-
standing of the power of nonviolence, the nition, subject to the changing turmoil of
norms of warfare, and the role of interna- social, cultural, and historical circumstance.
tional law is changing. Also we continue While Marx and others would view philoso-
to question the status (and application) of phy as ideology and thus would locate phi-
principles of retributive and distributive jus- losophizing in the struggles of political life,
tice, human rights concepts, and ideas about others—perhaps following Plato or Hegel—
basic norms of political decision making. view philosophy as speculative reflection
Contemporary issues inform contemporary hovering outside of political life. A middle
political philosophy, and contemporary path is found in the work of pragmatists such
political philosophers—from Foucault and as Dewey or in the democratic theorizing of
Rawls to feminism—inspire political action. someone like Joshua Cohen who maintains
This volume attempts to offer an overview that “the point of political philosophy is to
of the field and the depth of the issues. No contribute reflectively to the public reason-
single text can offer full coverage of a subject ing about what we ought to do that always
as broad as political philosophy. The chap- already forms one part of political life”
ters collected here range across the topic, (Cohen, 2009, 4). Political life involves both
while attempting to provide sufficient depth power struggles and reason-giving. Cohen,
to inspire further reflection. Dewey, and others maintain that political
philosophers can help to contribute to this
process of reasoning, even if we give up on
the quest to escape from Plato’s cave.
POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY, A related issue is the political danger of
UTOPIA, AND REALISM doing political philosophy in a political envi-
ronment that is not conducive to philosophi-
There is no single method of political philos- cal reflection. Socrates was killed for political
ophy. Pluralism is implicit in the topic, since reasons. Locke had to flee the country. Marx
there is an ambiguity exposed in the two inspired a global revolution. Those who ques-
terms that make up the name of the subject, tion the norms and structures of political life
“political philosophy.” On the one hand, phi- continue to find themselves in a precarious
losophy is often conceived as reflection on situation with regard to life in the polis. This
transcendent categories of being and thought is especially true in parts of the world where
that are contemplated from a disembodied authoritarian regimes continue to rule. The
vantage point outside of Plato’s cave. On the freedom to philosophize that we take for
other hand, political life includes the tumult granted in the liberal-democratic world is not
and change of history, including the rise and shared in other political milieus. The problem
fall of cities, civilizations, states, and forms of is found at the heart of Plato’s foundational
life. One of the deepest challenges for politi- cave allegory. Plato implies that there will
cal philosophy is the question of whether be no rest from troubles until philosophers
there are transcendental categories, eternal become kings or kings become philosophers.
truths, and transcultural norms. A related But he also implies that when the philoso-
question is the extent to which philosophical pher returns to the cave to impart wisdom to

2
INTRODUCTION

the enslaved masses, the masses will laugh, political philosophy. The liberal idea of over-
mock, and kill him. Plato asks us to consider lapping consensus acknowledges that diver-
whether political philosophers can be under- sity is a fundamental fact of political life,
stood and whether it is possible for political while other more idealistic political theories
philosophers to change the world. aim to eliminate diversity by establishing a
A central question of political philosophy normative theory grounded in fundamental
is whether Plato’s paternalistic view of philo- truth. The tough question of political phil-
sophical wisdom is really appropriate in an age osophy is whether political philosophy is
of democracy. It might be that there is no a pri- grounded in fundamental truth or whether
ori vantage point—no access to the world out- it is grounded in the fundamental fact that
side of the cave—as Dewey, Rorty, and other we disagree about fundamental truth. This
pragmatists and postmoderns imply. Platonic leaves us either with intractable conflict, with
political philosophy is utopian: it imagines an a mere modus vivendi that simply avoids vio-
ideal of political life and imparts its wisdom lence while giving up hope for agreement, or
from the outside. Some may reject this entirely with a more substantial but similarly fra-
and locate philosophy itself within political gile overlapping consensus that establishes
struggle. Thrasymachus, Marx, and Nietzsche coexistence and cooperation without deeper
point in this direction, understanding philoso- agreement.
phy as simply another form of ideology. Most We see this problem in the very etymol-
contemporary political philosophy is found ogy of the term political philosophy—which
somewhere between these extremes. Consider is a term loaded with European baggage. It is
Rawls’s understanding of political philosophy common to begin a discussion of political phi-
as “realistically utopian”: political philosophy losophy by acknowledging that both terms,
extends the limits of practical political possi- political and philosophy, come to us from
bility while also reconciling us to our political Greek origins. The root of the word political
and social condition (Rawls, 2001). Utopian is the word polis, the name of the city-states
thought extends by imagining ideals and aspi- of ancient Greece. The word philosophia can
rations, while realism reconciles us to political be literally translated from the Greek as “love
reality. Political philosophy involves a process of wisdom.” Combining these terms gives us
of balancing between extension and reconcili- love of wisdom about the city-state. One
ation, idealism and realism. wonders whether the endeavor to philoso-
The idealists and utopians will argue that phize about the political is merely a product
philosophizing about political life should of Western culture. Can there be a political
aim to provide us with true answers and a philosophy articulated in Chinese, Navajo,
correct or optimal theory of political reality. or Swahili? Would those who do not live
But realists will argue that, given the fact of in cities need a political philosophy? Would
diversity, no such agreement is possible and those who do not philosophize in the Greek
the best we can do is to establish a pragmatic sense—say, religious fundamentalists—be
and partial accommodation and agreement. receptive to political philosophy? A signifi-
Again Rawls is helpful: his idea of over- cant worry in our postcolonial era is whether
lapping consensus is an account of how the enterprise of political philosophy is ines-
we might agree to disagree. But this points capably Eurocentric. Does political philoso-
toward an intractable problem at the heart of phy describes states, justice, human rights,

3
Andrew Fiala

and human nature from a privileged vantage fall of man, political authority is necessary
point? Or can political philosophers tran- to prevent human beings from falling fur-
scend the blinders of the citadels of power ther, with political dominion understood as
and see political reality without ideological protective care for those who are ruled by a
and historical limitation? benevolent statesman who cares for his sub-
Rousseau and other radical critics (such jects as a father cares for his family. Thomistic
as the neoprimitivist “green anarchists”) political thought tends to hold that political
have suggested that the norms of political authority is less focused on negative restric-
philosophy only make sense within the con- tion as a remedy for sin and more oriented
text of “civilization” (another value-laden toward promoting human flourishing and
Eurocentric concept)—and that uncivilized the common good. This dispute has impli-
people in the state of nature may have no cations for how we think about the relation
use for these concepts. Of course, it is nearly between divine (or natural) law and civil law
impossible for us to imagine what life would and for ideas about the separation of church
be like for “noble savages” in a Rousseau-ian and state. Religious speculation about the
state of nature. But the primitivists remind origins of political life directs our attention
us that we ought not take civilization and to questions about paternalism and the com-
political life for granted: it is possible at mon good. Also the ideal of genuine commu-
least to imagine Homo sapiens in a prepo- nity as imagined in some Edenic paradise has
litical state—and indeed Homo sapiens lived often inspired utopian political aspiration.
quite well for long millennia without devel- Leaving religion aside, we might still won-
oping cities. The city, the state, and political der whether political hierarchy, division of
philosophy are quite late developments in labor, and the social and political structures
the life of our species. Thus political phi- of civilization are merely contingent ways
losophers ought to pay attention to the find- of organizing human life. Could there be a
ings of sociobiologists, archaeologists, and political philosophy of hunter–gatherers that
anthropologists who offer suggestions about ignores or rejects the idea of the nation-state?
the evolutionary roots of social cooperation If we continue to evolve beyond the era of
and the stability of hunter–gatherer social nation-states in a cosmopolitan direction,
structure. what would a political philosophy of the
While the musings of contemporary future look like? The modern Western tradi-
anarcho-primitivists may seem like a minor tion assumes that humanity made a necessary,
current in the ocean of political philoso- logical, and progressive step when it left the
phy, the question of whether human beings state of nature and created the original social
are naturally political beings is a serious contract, which left us with a world carved
philosophical concern. We often take it for up into nation-states. But critics have pointed
granted that Aristotle was right that to be out that the leap into political life cannot be
human is to live in cities and to be politi- assumed to be unequivocally good and that the
cal. But Christian authors from Augustine move toward the social contract often served
to Aquinas and Ockham wondered whether the interests of the powerful. Cosmopolitan
political life was merely a necessity of our critics add that the modern emphasis on
post-lapsarian condition. Augustinian politi- nation-states may impede us from delivering
cal philosophy tends to hold that after the on the promise of global justice.

4
INTRODUCTION

Critics also contend that the contempo- The deeper methodological question is
rary global system of nation-states rests whether the supposed truths of political
upon an often sordid history of colonial and philosophy are members of the same spe-
imperial domination of the rest by the West. cies as the truths of other sciences. We don’t
One might argue that the categories of polit- think that geometry is a uniquely Greek or
ical philosophy are universal and are thus Pythagorean science. But what about politi-
not liable to the sort of genealogical criti- cal philosophy: is it merely “political” or
cism that wants to throw Western political do the truths of political philosophy have
philosophy baby out with the Eurocentric a nonpolitical status similar to the truths of
bathwater. In this volume, James Alexander geometry? This points toward a fundamen-
suggests, for example, that “Europe is to tal disagreement about the very nature of
the World what Greece was to Rome.” He the topic under discussion and the method
means that we cannot deny the historical of inquiry. Can political philosophy arrive
source of political philosophy, even though at knowledge, truth, and wisdom? Or do
we have developed a global political philoso- the concepts of political philosophy merely
phy that has developed beyond its European reflect the contingent ideologies of a par-
roots. Critics will wonder whether the cat- ticular and limited form of life? How do
egories of political thought are tainted by we ground values and normative concepts
this historical origin. Eduardo Mendieta such as liberty, human rights, democracy,
argues in this volume that contemporary equality, etc.? Do these concepts point to
political philosophy ought to reimagine and real things: are “rights” real—grounded per-
reconstruct the colonialist narratives of our haps in the endowment of some Creator?
philosophical inheritance. He worries that Or are “rights” merely conventions of the
“the future remains mortgaged to the vision Hobbesian sort—or even worse, “nonsense
of progress projected by both Occidentalism on stilts” as Bentham argued? The significant
and Orientalism.” problem here is methodological: how do we
There is a deep methodological question know what we are talking about in political
here. On the one hand, we do not suspect philosophy—and what access do we have to
that mathematical truths are tainted by their the objects of political ontology? This meth-
Greek origin in Euclid or Pythagoras. So odological problem comes to a head in the
why should the truths of political philoso- question of normativity: what provides the
phy be tainted by their origin in Plato or normative impetus of political thinking? Is
Aristotle—or Augustine, Hobbes, Locke, and there a natural law of some sort that helps
Kant for that matter? On the one hand, those us understand and ground a normative hier-
who suspect a taint here will point out that archy of political structures and values? Or
the ideas of European political philosophy are the norms of political philosophy merely
have been used to support crusades, colo- the product of a historically contingent per-
nialism, imperialism, and other pernicious spective subject to the deflationary critique
endeavors. But, on the other hand, it may not of conventionalists and nominalists?
be fair to lay blame for the misbehavior of What method should we employ to work
political agents on the philosophers whose our way through these sorts of questions:
ideas were appropriated (and often distorted) empirical political science or speculative
by unphilosophical political agents. political metaphysics? Other branches of

5
Andrew Fiala

philosophical inquiry have begun to turn parts of the world continue to refuse the lib-
toward empirical and naturalistic explana- eral-democratic impetus of the modern age,
tions and accounts of value. Perhaps political maintaining that monarchic (or even theo-
philosophy ought to be reduced to social sci- cratic) rule is best.
ence and give up on its normative aspirations. Another approach in political philosophy
Others may argue, following Wittgenstein (or resists analytical schematism, focusing instead
Rorty), that since we cannot make progress on the nature of “the political” as a sphere
toward fundamental truth about politics, we of conflict, domination, and social struggle.
should give up on the effort (perhaps, after This more radical approach is associated
going through appropriate Wittgensteinian with a tradition running from Heraclitus
therapy). Yet, nothing seems more important and the Cynics to Marx, Nietzsche, Schmitt,
than finding ways to ground the norms of Arendt, Marcuse, and Foucault. From this
political life. Without such a grounding—in perspective, the analytical effort to classify
natural law, social contract, dialectical mate- constitutional schemes is insufficient since
rialism, or some other approach—we are left it ignores the motive force of political life,
unable to criticize political life, unable to jus- which is power or the struggle for recogni-
tify revolutionary activity, unable to justify tion. The analytical effort of the radical theo-
and legitimate states and constitutions. rists is to understand and describe ways that
power is organized and channeled. Again the
normative problem arises and some of the
efforts to describe social conflict slide over
CLASSIFICATION SCHEMES toward social theory and sociology (in so far
AND ASSUMPTIONS as they resist the effort to impose norms on
“the political”).
A primary concern of political philosophy Another tradition turns away from the
has traditionally been the classification, political entirely either to focus on the next
organization, and justification of structures world (as Christian anarchists have occa-
of power. A very basic method found in sionally done) or to focus on a simple life
Plato, Aristotle, and Hegel is to apply math- of a-political domesticity (as Epicureans of
ematical notions to political structures, leav- all ages have done). While apolitical and
ing us with an account of ruling power that anarchist trends in political philosophizing
says either that one rules (monarchy), some are often ignored as merely rejectionist, the
rule (oligarchy), all rule (democracy), or that challenge from outside of the city is to show
there is no rule whatsoever (anarchy). Such why participation in political life is either
a metapolitical analytic is compelling in its necessary or optimal for human flourishing.
purity. But analysis without norms leaves Indeed, some of the most radical anarchist
us merely with a cold and abstract calcu- critics reject the basic claim, which goes back
lus that is unable to rank the mathematical to Aristotle, that man is a political animal
alternatives. Is rule of one better than rule by (zoon politikon). This idea may itself be an
all—and how would we know? So disputes ideological imposition used to condemn the
continue about which basic constitution is outsiders. Aristotle suggested that only gods
better. While the European sphere of interest or beasts live outside of cities—and since
has embraced the idea of democracy, other human beings are not gods, this includes an

6
INTRODUCTION

implicit condemnation of the “barbarians” private sphere of domestic life, which was
who live outside city walls. The claim that often viewed as the domain of women and
“man” is a “political animal” (as Aristotle’s slaves). However, the term political has fur-
anthropos is often translated) is also loaded ther connotations that include both power
with gendered assumptions, as feminists will struggles within private affairs (marriages,
point out. The idea that “man” is political families, friendships, and careers contain an
is also loaded with theological assumptions element of the political in this sense) and the
about the fallen or imperfect nature of politi- question of international, global organiza-
cal life (as Augustine argued). tion (as in the somewhat oxymoronic term
While Aristotle suggests that human cosmopolitan—the city of the whole cos-
beings flourish in political communities, mos). While the ancient Greeks wrangled
there is no doubt that political formations about the relation between law, morality, and
are only a part of a larger whole of human religion—and about the proper structure of
life that includes the domestic sphere that society, the family, and the polis—profound
was traditionally associated with the female. puzzles remain, as indicated by recent work
Aristotle locates political philosophy within by Žižek and others who call the ontology
the broader inquiry of ethics and what he of “the political” into question. Žižek indi-
calls the “philosophy of human affairs” cates that our use of the term “political”
(anthropeia philosophia) at the end of his presumes a fundamental ontology contain-
Nicomachean Ethics (1181b). This reminds ing a normative hierarchy. As Žižek puts it,
us that political philosophy is only a por- drawing upon insights found in the work of
tion of a larger inquiry into human nature or Arendt, “in human society, the political is the
anthropology. As Aristotle explains in Book I englobing structuring principle, so that every
of Nicomachean Ethics, a student of poli- neutralization of some partial content as
tics must study the nature of happiness, the ‘nonpolitical’ is a political gesture par excel-
nature of human activity, the nature of vir- lence” (Žižek, 2000, 191). From this vantage
tue, and the nature of the soul. Thus politi- point, everything is political (love, ethics,
cal philosophy includes an open and difficult religion, Darwinian evolution, and so on).
question about what is natural for human Even when we attempt to identify a nonpo-
beings. It may be that only gods and beasts litical sphere of concern (say in domestic life
do not live in cities—but we are still work- or in the private sphere or in “the state of
ing out the details of whether we ought to nature”), the effort to isolate the nonpolitical
strive to become more divine or more beastly, is connected to “the political.” It is certainly
and whether we should be content with our “political” in this sense to say that feminin-
middle position as zoon politikon. That deep ity is private, domestic, and nonpolitical.
normative question is central to the spirit The political is a primary term and start-
that animates inquiry in political philosophy. ing place so that attempts to find something
Who are we? How ought we to live? And a-political or nonpolitical can only proceed
how should we organize our communal life? by negation. Our concepts and categories are
The term “political” contains a variety of laden with political significance (it is curious
connotations and denotations. The political that “the state of nature” includes the word
may be viewed as merely focused on issues “state,” for example). A related point is made
of “public” concern (as opposed to the by Raymond Geuss who cautions against

7
Andrew Fiala

any simplistic distinction between concepts the philosophical tradition he inspired were
and their application in political philoso- intent on proving Thrasymachus wrong: the
phy (Geuss, 2008). He reminds us that ideal philosophers looked (and continue to look)
theories often fail to account for the reality for knowledge and wisdom about the politi-
of political life (and its motivating forces). cal that transcends political struggle. But the
We also underestimate the power of ideals in Thrasymachus–Socrates dialectic continues
political life. to unfold. Millennia later, when Hegel main-
Political philosophy in its broadest sense tained that the modern European state repre-
includes just this sort of speculation about sented the end of history, Marx viewed this
human nature, the nature of the political, and as an ideological claim that failed to account
the status of our ideals. Political philosophy for its own economic, social, and political
thus connects with questions of psychology, basis. One philosopher’s truth-claims will be
sociology, and anthropology—and even biol- viewed by another as a political ploy. Thus
ogy and theology. But within the modern aca- one might worry that the whole endeavor of
demic discipline of political philosophy, the political philosophy is fraught with hypoc-
topic is often more narrowly circumscribed, risy, double standards, and Machiavellian/
as a discussion of justification and legitima- Orwellian manipulations. Political philoso-
tion of governmental organization and social phy may be merely the voice of patriarchy, of
power. A philosophical inquiry into justifi- capitalism, or Christianity, of Eurocentrism,
cation and legitimation would seem to rise and so on. Radical critics worry that the
above the merely empirical question of who more strenuously a political philosophy
is in power or what constitution is in place. denies its political motivations, the more rea-
Such a “philosophical” inquiry would not son we have to be suspicious. One wonders
itself be political—that is engaged in politi- whether the philosopher’s voice can be ade-
cal struggle. Rather, it would be focused on quately distinguished from the voice of the
logical analysis, claims about truth, and con- politician and whether political philosophy
cern for justice. When we assert a truth about can be distinguished from mere politics (see
political life—for example, that democracy Fiala, 2002).
is the best form of governance—we appear After Marx, Nietzsche, Freud, Foucault,
to rise above political squabbling and reach and others suspicious hermeneuts, it is no
the level of justification. However, radical longer possible to simply accept that we even
critics of the truths that are articulated and know what we are talking about (or what
defended in political philosophy may argue we are inheriting and perhaps obfuscating)
that the truth-claims and justifications of when we employ the language of political
political philosophy are themselves merely philosophy. This postmodern conclusion may
political—based upon partial perspectives be understood either as the nadir or as the
and engaged in a struggle for power and zenith of political philosophy. For those who
legitimation that falls short of the discourse are interested in simply making “progress”
of philosophical justification and truth. in political philosophy, the deep question
Thus Thrasymachus defined justice as what of the meaning and extent of “the politi-
is in the interest of the stronger party and cal” creates an impediment (indeed, asking
denied that there was any discourse of jus- us to pause and reconsider what we mean
tification beyond the political. Socrates and by “progress” as well as by “the political”

8
INTRODUCTION

and whose interests are being served by natural law, or Kantian deontology). Applied
our definitions). Yet, it is commonplace— ethics applies these normative theories to
especially in Anglo-American thought—to various problems. This tripartite scheme is
hold that we have made progress and that useful for organizing political philosophy
we are making progress in both political phi- as well. Political philosophy in its broadest
losophy and in the world of political reality. sense (similar to metaethics—and thus per-
The work of Rawls, for example, is viewed haps properly called metapolitics) asks about
as ground-breaking and progressive, since the nature of the political and about methods
he reconstructed the social contract in a way of justification. At this level, we might find
that worked better than previous iterations. questions about human nature and prob-
With the advent of the United Nations and lems familiar from metaethics, such as the
the end of the Cold War, it is thought that we issue of relativism. At the level of normative
are making progress in disseminating ideas political theory, we find concrete theories
about human rights, in developing secular of justice and political organization: social-
governments, and in developing institutions ism, capitalism, democracy, communism,
of international law (cf. Fukuyama’s [1992] and so on. These normative theories often
once triumphant claim about the end of his- simply assume that the metapolitical issues
tory). There is no denying that Rawls’s work have been resolved and proceed with a defi-
is influential and creative, and there is no nition of what is best or just. While norma-
denying that the world looks quite different tive political theory makes up the majority of
today than it did in prior centuries. However, what students of political philosophy study,
political philosophy that is not merely an we ought not forget that metapolitical issues
apology for the status quo continues to arise as we attempt to compare and judge the
encourage deep questioning with regard to different normative theories. When we evalu-
liberal political theory and the world that is ate the difference between negative liberty
developing. Are we better? Is political philos- and positive liberty, for example, we discover
ophy better? While it certainly seems that we a metapolitical question (the meaning of the
are doing better, philosophers recognize the concept of liberty) that is resolved in diverse
difficulty of drawing final conclusions. ways by proponents of different normative
political theories.
Applied political philosophy occurs when
we employ normative political theories to
METAPOLITICS, POLITICAL resolve concrete problems such as immigra-
THEORY, AND APPLIED POLITICAL tion, crime, or economic issues. As in applied
PHILOSOPHY ethics, there is often quite a bit of interplay
between our intuitions about specific prob-
Ethicists generally recognize a distinction lems and the way we understand and justify
between metaethics, normative theory, and our normative theories. Thus if we think that
applied ethics. Metaethics focuses on con- distributive justice and moderating inequal-
ceptual problems (such as relativism and ity are fundamental, we may adjust our the-
absolutism). Normative theory focuses on ory of political life accordingly (and adopt
concrete theories of ethics that provide a defi- some version of socialism). But if our intui-
nition of what is good (such as utilitarianism, tion is that liberty is more important than

9
Andrew Fiala

inequality, we may end up adopting some points toward two ways of understanding
version of libertarianism. the purpose or end of political philosophy: as
This process of adjusting our theories to a practical inquiry with useful applications
our intuitions and vice versa is similar to what in the real world (as a means to an end) and
Rawls described as “reflective equilibrium.” as a critical, utopian, and even paradoxical
One important lesson to be learned from the inquiry that creates wonder (as an end in
field of applied ethics is that contexts and cir- itself). Many view political philosophy (and
cumstances matter. Euthanasia and abortion ethics and anthropology more broadly con-
are issues that depend in part on the sorts strued) as merely practical wisdom. Aristotle
of technologies that are available. Likewise, suggests in Nicomachean Ethics that ethi-
political topics such as the status of interna- cal and political inquiry ought to provide a
tional law or the problem of cross-border way to live a good, productive, and happy
immigration and refugees depend upon his- life. However, Aristotle also notes (in Book
torical contingent circumstances, technologi- X of Nicomachean Ethics) that there is a
cal development, access to information, basic higher good for human beings, which is con-
economics, climate, geography, and so forth. templation. While one expects contempla-
Most will agree that our theoretical and tion to have some practical significance, the
normative commitments ought to be respon- contemplative act of philosophizing may
sive to changing circumstances. However, be an end in itself. This contemplative side
some may worry that this responsiveness is of philosophy grows out of the experience
a sign of relativism and inconsistency. This of wonder, which was described by Plato in
directs us back to the metapolitical ques- Theatetus (155d) as the origin of philoso-
tion of whether there are absolute and true phy, an idea that was reiterated by Aristotle
answers to the questions of political philoso- in Metaphysics (1933a, 982b). In his dis-
phy or whether the very nature of political cussion of wonder in Metaphysics, Aristotle
theory is such that it ought to be responsive to notes that wonder and speculation grow out
historical, economic, or cultural variations. of a feeling of ignorance and the experience
This book contains both metatheoretical of being perplexed or bewildered. Moreover,
considerations (e.g. in the chapters on sover- he notes that speculative contemplation
eignty and human rights), chapters focused develops out of leisure time, as a “recreation
on concrete or normative political theory and pastime,” such as “when practically all
(e.g. in the chapters on democracy and cos- the necessities of life were already supplied”
mopolitanism), and chapters focused on (982b). The contemplative and wondering
applied issues (distributive justice, retributive side of political philosophy is connected to
justice, war, peace, immigration, and so on). metapolitical questions. This may be under-
stood in contrast with the more practical set
of concerns that we encounter as political
agents within applied political philosophy.
UTOPIAN CONTEMPLATION AND The first more practical approach finds
PRACTICAL REASON its roots in Aristotle’s book Politics (1933b).
Aristotle suggests that the philosophical
What is the goal or telos of political phi- study of politics should aim to be scientific
losophy? The Greek tradition of philosophy in the sense of analytical comprehension of

10
INTRODUCTION

the origins and organization of political real- compact, they simplified the actual history
ity. For Aristotle, the knowledge provided by of state formation. The idea of the social
political science has practical import insofar contract is as ideal and utopian as Plato’s
as statesmen and politicians can employ this philosopher-king: there never was a social
knowledge both in the construction of con- contract of the sort imagined by Hobbes,
stitutions and in the technical task of ruling. Locke, or Rousseau. However, this process
This leads Aristotle to suggest in Book IV of of simplification helps to clarify ideals and
Politics that the technical art and science of normative principles. This sort of speculative
governing ought to be supplemented by an idealization continues in the work of more
analysis of what the best form of constitu- contemporary political philosophers such
tion is and how different constitutions are as John Rawls, who imagines an even more
adapted to different people in different ways. explicitly ideal sort of social contract situa-
But Aristotle notes that the science of politics tion—known as the original position under
ought not to stray too far into an inquiry into the veil of ignorance. Rawls admits that this
the ideal that neglects the question of what is is merely a heuristic—a device for imagining
practical and useful. As Aristotle puts it, we how impartiality, rationality, and fairness
must examine both what is best and what is work in theorizing about justice. It is import-
possible. ant to clarify ideals in this way. The effort to
But a different conception of political imagine political ideals in this way may be
philosophy sees it as an exploration of ideas an end in itself—an act of wondering. One
that is primarily speculative and engaged wonders whether political philosophy must
in the philosophical art of wondering. This always have a practical impact or whether
approach may be more closely associated philosophizing about the political should be
with Plato, who explores utopian schemes free to wander in the fields of imagination.
and plays with myths in his discussion of While we may expect political philosophy
political subjects. In Apology, Plato’s Socrates to result in prescriptions that ought to change
speculates about the afterlife, refers to the the world, as Marx put it in his critique of
Delphic oracle, and invokes his daimon. In Hegel, we should also acknowledge that spec-
Crito, Socrates imagines an encounter with ulating and reflecting on political reality is
the personification of the Laws. In Republic, intrinsically fascinating. We might acknowl-
Socrates imagines a perfect state based upon edge, as Hegel attempted to show, that there
the fantastical idea of the philosopher-king is a kind of enlightenment and freedom that
and a eugenic project intended to create a can arise from contemplation of political
just and harmonious social order. While Plato reality that does not dare to articulate a plan
may have become more practical in his later for how the world ought to be. Political phi-
work—as in Laws—the speculative impulse losophers are often pulled back down into
of political philosophy continues to inspire. Plato’s cave and passionately motivated to
Political philosophers attempt to apply change the world. But it might be that one
reason and order to the world of human way to change the world is to stimulate the
reality, which may indeed be resistant to this sort of wonder that is associated with con-
process. When modern political philosophers templation. Indeed, Aristotle suggests in Book
imagined the creation of states from out X of Nicomachean Ethics that contemplation
of the state of nature by way of the social is based in leisure and peace and is closely

11
Andrew Fiala

connected to happiness. Of course, the more the focus of political philosophy per se,
active political philosophy of someone like which addresses metapolitical issues in ways
Marx would say that there is a fundamental that are informed by work in epistemology,
injustice when the majority of people lack the metaphysics and ontology, ethics, and philo-
leisure to contemplate, while others are free sophical logic.
to wonder about how those who lack free- In the academy in the United States, the
dom provide a material basis for the leisurely divide between the humanities and the social
contemplation of the philosophical class. sciences helps to explain the divide between
political theory and political philosophy
(although this generalization admits a vari-
ety of exceptions). While the social sciences
HUMANITIES OR SOCIAL SCIENCE? employ empirical reasoning including quan-
titative techniques of analysis, the humani-
In addition to considering whether political ties tend to be more focused on conceptual
philosophy is a means to an end or an end analysis, textual hermeneutics, and norma-
in itself, we ought also consider the proper tive theory. As one facet of the social scien-
method for engaging in political philosophy. tific discipline of political science, political
Should political philosophy be an enter- theory in the social sciences is more closely
prise of idealization abstracted from politi- allied with empirical methodologies and less
cal reality or should it arise from within inclined toward normative claims of humani-
political reality and primarily be empirical ties scholars (although political theorists are
reflection on practical, lived experience? more normative and “philosophical” than
The issue of method leads to a loose dis- other scholars in the social sciences). On
tinction between political science, political the other hand, political philosophy—as a
theory, and political philosophy. “Political subfield within the discipline of philosophy,
science” (as it is called in the United States) which is usually located in the humanities—is
is an established discipline in the social sci- more deeply grounded in the history of ideas,
ences that is based upon empirical methods. more concerned with the status of normative
While political scientists may want to remain claims, and not as reluctant to imagine uto-
neutral and refrain from making prescriptive pian alternatives to the status quo.
claims, political scientists do offer advice and As a discipline within philosophy and the
evaluation of policies and institutions. But humanities, political philosophy is connected
these normative claims are usually limited with other philosophical concerns: epistemol-
by advice that works within a given politi- ogy, metaphysics, ethics, and even psychol-
cal framework. Political theory is the more ogy and aesthetics. Thus political philosophy
theoretical or philosophical side of political wonders how (and whether) we know what
science—often grounded in a more historical we think we know about political reality. It
orientation and more interested in normative asks about the foundations of political phe-
claims and connection with larger moral and nomena, including the ontological status of
historical issues. Political theorists are thus political entities, the origin of these things,
more willing to question the frameworks and their purpose or teleology. It is concerned
that political scientists take for granted. The with questions about justice and the good,
larger metapolitical questions are exclusively as well as questions about human happiness

12
INTRODUCTION

and flourishing. It may also be interested in and what a perfect or ideal world might look
questions about taste, inclination, and mean- like.
ing. While these topics are also the concern of Political philosophy tends to be con-
political science (and other social sciences— cerned with analysis of meta-level norms.
such as economics and sociology), political Thus Rawls defines justice as fairness and
philosophers are interested in deep and broad provides an analysis of this definition. Thus
reflection on these concerns and issues. They democratic theory is often focused on the
are also interested in the hermeneutical and status of the norms of democracy such as
phenomenological questions that arise when legitimation or participation. This exercise
we realize that inquiry in political philosophy in conceptual analysis aims to clarify what
implicates the inquirer. When we contemplate we mean when we are discussing topics in
political reality, we must also contemplate the political philosophy. Conceptual analysis of
fact that such contemplation arises within a this sort is usually understood as a central
political context that limits and determines feature of philosophy as a discipline in the
norms and knowledge. humanities. This method is similar to related
Consider one example: the question of efforts at conceptual analysis in discussing
how political constitutions are organized. philosophy of mind or philosophy of science
As Plato and Aristotle did, political scientists and so on. Philosophy of science, for exam-
may categorize and analyze various sorts of ple, studies how knowledge claims are made
constitutions. There is quite a bit of social in scientific disciplines—including the ques-
scientific work to be done that involves tion of what distinguishes science from other
reflection on the various ways that human forms of thought. In a similar fashion, philos-
beings have organized our lives politically. ophy of politics studies the way that norms
Such work can often be grounded in high- function in political life and the question
powered empirical methods and can provide of what distinguishes “the political” from
useful information about voting methods, other aspects of human life. It is important
voter participation, cycles of political power, to note that philosophers of science are not
the relation between the economy and politi- scientists engaged in the act of discovery and
cal movements, how leaders succeed, and hypothesis testing that scientists are engaged
so on. However, political philosophers ask in. In the same way, political philosophers
deep questions about the meaning and pur- are not engaged in the effort of political sci-
pose of all of this: why do we need consti- ence, conceived as a discipline in the social
tutions, is voting really important, why can sciences. Political scientists focus on discov-
we not agree about power, should economic ery and hypothesis testing in the realm of the
concerns be included, what virtues should a political. But political philosophers wonder
good leader possess, and so on. While politi- whether the empirical approach of political
cal philosophy should not ignore the find- science is valuable, while also reflecting on
ings of empirically oriented political science, the very subject matter and asking what is
political philosophers should not loose sight (or is not) political.
of the importance of a deeper set of ques- Consider another example: the question of
tions about the sorts of beings we are, what justice. In the social sciences, one studies jus-
our purpose and function is, how we know tice in an empirical fashion. Criminologists,
what we claim to know about these things, for example, study the nature of criminal

13
Andrew Fiala

justice, asking what works or does not work they can also offer admonishments, inspira-
in terms of crime reduction and punishment. tion, and incite us to act.
Philosophers wonder, however, how we In Republic (Book II), Glaucon suggest
define crime and why it deserves punishment. that justice is a middle path between unbri-
Or, in political science, one might study the dled power and abject suffering. As Glaucon
structure of a particular constitutional sys- asserts, echoing Thrasymachus, the best thing
tem or the emerging norms of international would be to get away with unjust actions but
law. The inquiry of political science will be not be punished, while the worst thing would
informed by history and interested in empir- be to suffer injustice without hope of retali-
ical questions about popular opinion, about ation. He further suggested that justice is a
conflicts arising within structures of politi- lesser evil. As he puts it, no one would will-
cal life, and about the lived implications of ingly submit to the rule of law if he had the
certain structures and institutions. However, power to get away with injustice with impu-
political philosophers will be interested in nity. This points toward one of the deepest
questions about whether history matters questions of political philosophy—why we
with regard to politics (or whether the politi- accept social and political norms. Socrates
cal realm ought to be considered under the attempt to provide an explanation through-
rubric of a-historical and universal norms). out the rest of Republic, ultimately pointing
Political philosophers will ask fundamen- toward a myth at the end of Book X, where
tal normative questions about the status he suggests that justice is somehow linked to
of institutional frameworks—including the happiness both in this life and in the next.
question of which framework is better or This is an answer to the question of why we
best. should care about the norms and concepts
of political life. Plato’s Republic ultimately
exhorts us to be just.
Political philosophy points beyond the
JUSTICE, THE GOOD LIFE, AND mere analysis and dispassionate inquiry of
POLITICAL EXHORTATION empirical political science. Several of the
books of Republic offer analytical discus-
Let’s return to the idea that political philoso- sion of the virtues and vices of various forms
phy is part of the larger inquiry into human of government: the famous story about the
life. This fact reminds us that political philos- dissolution of the perfect state through aris-
ophy ought to have some existential impact: tocracy, oligarchy, democracy, and on to tyr-
it ought to transform our lives. While there anny. Such analysis is important. But political
have been significant discussions of philoso- philosophers will also wonder why this mat-
phy as therapy or philosophy as a way of ters—what is at stake for us in analyzing
life (e.g. in works by Pierre Hadot), we often political reality in this way? Plato’s answer
forget that philosophizing about the political in Book X of Republic provides a key. He
is central to such projects of philosophical implies that an inquiry into the nature of jus-
transformation. One underappreciated form tice and political life will have an existential
of discourse connected to political philoso- impact. It will make us better persons.
phy is what we might call political exhorta- This points us toward a final problem
tion. While philosophers analyze and argue, in terms of defining the field of political

14
INTRODUCTION

philosophy. Do explicitly activist speech-acts polemical and tendentious. Philosophical


qualify as political philosophy? A standard reflection would seem to be more ecumenical,
anthology of political philosophy will include universal, and abstract. Liberatory political
examples of activist exhortation, for example: exhortations on the Left call for revolutionary
Machiavelli’s Prince, Jefferson’s “Declaration of action, reminding us that we’ve got nothing
Independence,” Marx’s Communist Manifesto, to lose but our chains. But those on the Right
or King’s “Letter from Birmingham Jail.” Each will remind us to hold fast to traditions and
of these documents was written in reaction to ideas that are threatened with disruption by
a specific political context, directed toward a the forces of revolution. One reason we might
specific audience, and aimed at stimulating want to claim that exhortative texts are not
political action. Do such texts count as political properly political philosophy is that they are
philosophy? They are not purely disembodied one-sided in this way. Political philosophy per
considerations of abstract truth—even though se would seem to look beyond a particular
they contain claims about truth, justice, and political agenda and take in the whole of the
other norms. But they are central texts for con- field. But one may argue—following Marx’s
sidering key questions about governance and critique of Hegel or following feminist cri-
power, about revolutionary action, and about tiques of contemporary philosophy—that the
equality, ideology, and justice. disembodied vantage point privileges a certain
One key feature of exhortative texts is that class–gender–culture matrix. It thus might be
they raise our consciousness—directing our that abstract Platonic (or Hegelian) political
attention to unspoken features of our lives philosophy is itself a sort of exhortation—that
(including our own double standards and inspires us toward a certain form of life (even
hypocrisy). The idea of consciousness-raising while it denies its own tendentiousness).
is a central one for feminists, who think that A very narrow version of political philoso-
women must be given the opportunity and free- phy would deny that exhortative texts count
dom to properly experience and understand as political philosophy. But a broader under-
their oppression. A similar effort is found in standing of the existential import of politi-
Marxism, which wanted to bring class strug- cal philosophizing would find such texts to
gle out of the ideological shadows and make be primary examples of what political phi-
it an explicit theme of thinking. On the cut- losophy ought to do, which is to help us live
ting edge of this effort of political philosophy better lives. As we’ve discussed in this intro-
as consciousness-raising today are those who duction, political philosophy also recognizes
are exploring globalization and Eurocentrism. that there are no easy and obvious answers
We take certain linguistic and social catego- to the question of how best to organize our
ries for granted: patriarchal, racist, classist lives and how best to live.
(or bourgeois), and Eurocentric language and
concepts permeate our thinking and our insti-
tutions. One seemingly universal exhortation
of political philosophy is that we ought to be PRECIS/SYNOPOSIS
aware of how our language and culture limits
our political thinking and activity. The chapters collected in this volume exam-
A remaining problem is that political ine the sorts of questions discussed here,
exhortation is seemingly one-sided—it is while also extending reflection more deeply

15
Andrew Fiala

into specific topics. This volume begins with and others, Ezra examines arguments about
James Alexander’s reflection on the history inequality and the role of the state in redis-
of political philosophy. Alexander considers tributing wealth, ensuring equality of oppor-
the very question of whether it is important tunity, and managing social and economic
to consider political philosophy from the difference. Ezra links his consideration to the
vantage point of history or whether political emerging problem of global environmental
philosophy can be understood in a-histori- justice, showing how the question of dis-
cal terms. He concludes that both historical tributive justice is applied in a vexing global
depth and a-historical reflection are of use: context to deal with the problem of resource
“If philosophy without history is a desert, distribution and risk mitigation in the face of
and history without philosophy is a jungle, climate change. The question of justice and
then we certainly need something of both.” distributions of harms and benefits becomes
Andrew Fiala considers the question of concrete in discussion of immigration.
sovereignty, while pointing toward problems Taking up a different thread with regard
of civil disobedience, the challenge of anar- to justice, Trudy Conway examines a differ-
chism, and development of international ent aspect of concern for justice by consider-
law and what some are calling a “post-sov- ing retributive justice and alternative models
ereignty” era. Gillian Brock explores related of viewing punishment. She situates this in
issues under the topic of cosmopolitanism. the history of political philosophy, with a
Brock is concerned with the question of defin- particular focus on Plato and Kant, while
ing the concept of cosmopolitanism and with also examining contemporary issues such
the question of what a cosmopolitan world as the problem of mass incarceration. She
would look like. She wonders whether cos- reminds us that the question of the justice of
mopolitanism is inevitable as a matter of nor- punishment is a central concern for political
mative theory. The issues considered by Brock life and for political philosophy. The ques-
are connected with questions about human tion of domestic crime is related to the ques-
rights and the ground of political life and jus- tion of international aggression, warfare, and
tice. These concerns are taken up by Siegfried international law. George Lucas develops the
Van Duffel, who explores the status of human discussion of justice by considering the topic
rights in both domestic and international con- of war. Lucas focuses our attention on the
texts. Van Duffel suggests that there is a major way that the evolution of warfare in the con-
dispute between moral theories of rights and temporary era requires that we reassess our
more politically oriented theories. He further understanding of just war theory, the status
suggests that a middle path can be found by of international law, and the military profes-
way of limited descriptive theories of rights. sion. In each of these chapters, it is important
A central concern for political philoso- to notice how philosophical accounts develop
phy—especially liberal-democratic politi- together with and in light of developments in
cal philosophy—is the question of justice. the real world of political actuality.
Several chapters take a look at specific While punishment and justice in war are
notions of justice and their application. traditional concerns of applied political
Ovadia Ezra considers the topic of distribu- philosophy, an alternative point of view is
tive justice. Dealing with important recent that of pacifism. Andrew Fitz-Gibbon pro-
work by Rawls, Dworkin, Hayek, Nozick, vides an overview of the topic of peace and

16
INTRODUCTION

nonviolence, exploring the power of nonvio- Gheaus’s concern represents an approach to


lence as a method of political activism, includ- issues in political philosophy that develops
ing a brief history of pacifism and an account feminist concern in a way that is different
of recent and successful examples of nonvi- than that considered by Kegley. Following
olence. In a related chapter, Paul Churchill this thread and returning to issues found in
examines the notion of toleration, which is a the discussion of cosmopolitanism, Shelley
key value for liberal political regimes and a Wilcox examines the issue of immigration,
vexing topic for liberal political philosophy. asking whether liberal-democratic states have
Churchill provides a historical overview of a right to exclude immigrants, while also con-
the development of the concept as well as a sidering the rights of foreigners who are in
contemporary account of remaining prob- need of aid. She points toward a vexing cir-
lems. He works through so-called paradoxes cularity haunting this discussion, in the issue
of toleration and the concept of state neutral- of who is able to express consent and benefit
ity, while touching upon a variety of concrete from the right of self-determination. It might
and applied issues: freedom of speech, hate be, she suggests, that central liberal-demo-
speech, pornography, and the challenge of cratic principles such as liberty and equality
religion. Churchill and Fitz-Gibbon remind point toward open borders or cross-border
us of a certain brand of contemporary politi- redistribution. But proposed solutions are
cal life associated with liberal regimes that problematic, and these issues become more
value toleration, nonviolence, and the like. complicated when we take into account class
Developing the idea of liberal political and gender disparities—such as “global care
philosophy further, Jacquelyn Ann K. Kegley chains” involving domestic labor—in immi-
examines emerging issues in democratic the- gration and cross-border relations.
ory. She considers the problem of social con- Near the end of this book, coauthors
tract theory, consequentialist justifications of Jeremy Wisnewski and Matthew Voorhees
democracy (what she calls democratic instru- discuss the future of political philosophy.
mentalism), and the ideas of deliberative They examine current trends in the discipline
democracy and public reason. She reminds us by providing an empirical analysis of recent
of the breadth and complexity of the concept publications. They identify ongoing con-
of democracy and its linkage to other moral/ cern for liberal theory and the work of John
political concepts such as equality, autonomy, Rawls, as well as emerging issues of diversity/
and authenticity. She shows how democratic difference and cosmopolitanism. They remind
theory develops as a critique of paternalism. us that political philosophy ought to be
She considers feminist critiques and so-called grounded in hope and concern for the future:
agonistic pluralism—a radical view of politi- “If political philosophy has no bearing on our
cal life as an unavoidable field of contested political future, then political philosophy will
values and struggles for power and recogni- itself have no future—save being a boutique
tion. The consideration of feminism is taken hobby for intellectuals who are predisposed
up in more detail by Anca Gheaus in her chap- to considering its themes.” They note that
ter. Gheaus offers an examination of feminist philosophical inquiry develops in response
critiques of political philosophy with a spe- to political reality (ex. torture emerges as a
cial focus on care ethics and practical effort topic after Bush permits it—and other emerg-
to respond to the demand for gender equality. ing applied topics: surveillance and high tech,

17
Andrew Fiala

intellectual property, income inequality, ter- — (1933a), Metaphysics in Aristotle in


rorism, etc.). Thus they conclude by reminding 23 Volumes, Vols. 17, 18, trans. H.
us that the discipline will undoubtedly change Tredennick. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
as new issues emerge and philosophers turn University Press; London: William
their attention to them. Finally, Edouardo Heinemann Ltd., 1933, 1989; from
Mendieta provides an afterword to this vol- Perseus digital library: www.perseus.tufts.
ume that reminds us that philosophy is his- edu/hopper/.
torically and culturally located. Eurocentrism — (1933b), Politics in Aristotle in 23
remains a problem—and indeed a central Volumes, Vol. 21, trans. H. Rackham.
challenge of political philosophy. Could there Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
be a truly global political philosophy? As Press; London: William Heinemann Ltd.,
our globe shrinks and cosmopolitan concern 1944; from Perseus digital library: www.
grows, can we reimagine political philosophy perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/.
from a perspective that is not haunted by the Cohen, J. (2009), Philosophy, Politics,
shadow of Eurocentrism? Democracy: Selected Essays. Cambridge,
This book concludes with several appen- MA: Harvard University Press.
dices that provide resources for research- Fiala, A. (2002), The Philosopher’s Voice:
ers: a chronology, a glossary of key terms, a Philosophy, Politics, and Language in the
list of research resources, and an annotated 19th Century. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
bibliography. Fukuyama, F. (1992), The End of History
and the Last Man. New York: The Free
Press.
Geuss, R. (2008), Philosophy and Real
WORKS CITED Politics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Aristotle (1894), Nicomachean Ethics Rawls, J. (2001), The Law of Peoples.
from Aristotle’s Ethica Nicomachea, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
N. J. Bywater (ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Žižek, S. (2000), The Ticklish Subject: The
Press; from Perseus digital library: www. Absent Center of Political Ontology.
perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/. London: Verso.

18
1
THE HISTORY OF
POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY
James Alexander

Oakeshott once wrote that political philoso- to his Caesar, but he may also be Jesus to
phy concerns the relation “between politics his Lazarus. The consequence of this extreme
and eternity.” “At all other levels of reflection indeterminacy is that there is no way to leg-
on political life we have before us the single islate for the history of political philosophy
world of political activity, and what we are which cannot be immediately contradicted.
interested in is the internal coherence of that In this chapter, therefore, I seek not to legis-
world; but in political philosophy we have in late for it, but instead to clarify some of its
our minds that world and another world, and constitutions, conditions, and contradictions.
our endeavour is to explore the coherence of The first thing to observe is that each of its
the two worlds together.” This is a vivid con- three substantive terms—“history,” “poli-
ception of political philosophy. But it is one tics,” “philosophy”—is contested.
which is challenged by history. Oakeshott Politics, before the twentieth century, was
rather blithely claimed that the history of always subjugated to something else—to the
political philosophy is simply the recogni- polis, or to empire, church, or state. But in
tion that political philosophy so defined has the twentieth century, there were attempts to
a “continuous history in our civilisation” define politics (or the category of “the polit-
(Oakeshott, 1991, 225). But if history is the ical”) as something in itself. This was evident
antithesis of eternity, then the history of pol- in classic works like Schmitt’s Concept of
itical philosophy may be nothing other than the Political, Collingwood’s New Leviathan,
the death of political philosophy so defined. Arendt’s The Human Condition, Oakeshott’s
History has an essentially contradictory On Human Conduct, and even in more quix-
nature. We may write history after we have otic works like Badiou’s Metapolitics and
lost something, as Acton suggested, or in Rancière’s Dis-Agreement. The consensus
order to lose it, as Goethe suggested (Goethe, now, however, seems to be that politics has
1904, 158). The historian may bury the past no simple meaning: it can mean more or less
by writing about it, but he may also bring it anything (Alexander, 2014). In the last half
back to view. This is why the philosopher is century or so, almost everything has become
never sure whether the historian is his friend subject to what we could call the last laugh of
or his enemy. The historian may be Brutus Protagoras—the possibility that everything is

19
James Alexander

relative, that there is nothing true about pol- History complicates everything. It places
itics. It is in this situation that we attempt to everything in the framework not of truth but of
make sense of politics in historical or philo- time: and so raises questions about whether we
sophical terms, or both. are telling a story or set of stories about what
Philosophy is, I have argued elsewhere, was thought true rather than trying to establish
any attempt to respond to the world, or any whether it is true or not. Consciousness of time
part of it, in terms of wonder, faith, doubt, or makes us aware of broken traditions, of litera-
skepticism (Alexander, 2012). It is, of course, tures canonical and uncanonical, of disconti-
a rather high specification for thought: it nuities and silences in our stories, and of the
appears to exclude ordinary thought, while difficulty of assessing the motives behind and
being related to it. I think we have to admit meanings of the relics which survive of older
that political philosophy cannot always be thoughts, theories, and philosophies. Perhaps
very securely distinguished from political it also increases our consciousness of the fra-
theory or political thought. When they are gility of our own understanding, generating
distinguished it is usually on the grounds that a caution about saying anything at all. And
political thought includes any judgment, no then there is also, as Condren has observed,
matter how fragmentary or incoherent (e.g. the fact that we read historic works of political
“Legislate!”), that political theory is some- philosophy for a variety of reasons: sometimes
thing more ordered so it includes justifica- because they are original, sometimes because
tions of certain ideas used in politics (e.g. they are coherent, and sometimes because they
“Liberalism”), and that political philosophy are influential. It should be obvious to every-
is something further narrowed and intensified one that what is original may not be coherent
so it includes all attempts to understand and or influential; that what is coherent may not
explain what politics is and where it stands be influential or original; and that what may
in relation to other human concerns (e.g. be influential may not be original or coherent
Leviathan). It would be a mistake to distin- (Condren, 1985).
guish them too severely: to only suppose, say, The problem of history was evident to
that ideas do not matter in politics, or that Aristotle when he distinguished poetry and
ideas matter in politics only in terms of what history. On the one hand, philosophy, like
purposes they serve, or that ideas are only of poetry, has always been with the gods, while
significance when they enable us to under- history has always been human, all too human.
stand politics without regard to purpose. But Hegel wrote in the Phenomenology that “phi-
if the three were blurred together without losophy moves essentially in the element of
argument, then we would be unable to distin- universality” (Hegel, 1977, 1). History, on the
guish prescription, justification, and explana- other hand, moves essentially in the element
tion. There would be no distinction between of particularity. Within the “fundamental cat-
“We should do this,” “We should do this for egory of historical thought,” as Collingwood
this set of reasons,” and “We say ‘We should put it, we no longer look “for a change-
do this for this set of reasons’ for this set of less and knowable something.” We sup-
reasons” (Oakeshott, 2008, 193). Where all pose that there is “no unchanging substrate
this leaves political philosophy is, of course, behind the changes, and no unchanging laws
unclear: which is why we sometimes turn to according to which the changes took place”
history. (Collingwood, 1945, 10–13). This is clear.

20
THE HISTORY OF POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY

But such an emphasis on change may seem to with a new future” (Koselleck, 1985, 16).
undermine philosophical certainty altogether. In this modernity, politics is neither natu-
Oakeshott noticed that “almost impercep- ral nor artificial but emergent. As Marx put
tibly, Collingwood’s philosophy of history it, “Men make their own history, but they
turned into a philosophy in which all knowl- do not make it just as they please; they do
edge is assimilated to historical knowledge, not make it under circumstances chosen by
and consequently into a radically sceptical themselves but under circumstances existing
enquiry” (Oakeshott, 2007, 199). Skepticism already, given and transmitted from the past”
is a form of philosophy, and perhaps the most (Marx, 1963, 15). In this continually chang-
influential one now (though we resist it), ing situation, and one recognized as such, it
because of our tendency to think historically. becomes much harder to postulate a founda-
But the history of political philosophy draws tion of politics. Aristotle simply assumed that
our attention to the fact that most political politics must be in harmony with the laws
philosophers were concerned with essences, of nature: it was our nature to be political.
ideas, and truth, and rarely concerned them- Hobbes thought this too complacent. He sug-
selves with history. History itself, therefore, gested that politics had another foundation,
seems to ask whether the historian always has namely, the brutal necessity imposed on us by
to think historically. Certainly, no one until nature to find some artifice by which we can
the last few centuries could have imagined achieve order. Many contemporary philoso-
the possibility that history might be the fun- phers still begin with Aristotle or Hobbes. But
damental category of thought. this is to ignore the fact that political philoso-
It is important to recognize that the emer- phy since at least the time of Hegel has begun
gence of our historical consciousness has a with the lack of any certain foundation. Hegel
history. In The Idea of Nature, Collingwood did not think that this was a problem, since
argued that at certain critical points in the his philosophy was meant to explain every-
past there has been a ruling analogy which thing without depending on any foundational
has enabled men to explain nature—and assumptions. But Schopenhauer, Kierkegaard,
also, we may add, politics. The first was an and Marx all criticized Hegel’s philosophy
analogy between nature and man, so that in very different ways, and those who have
nature was macrocosm and man microcosm. followed—apart from the scientists who can
When this analogy was brought into poli- continue on Cartesian or Baconian assump-
tics, it suggested that politics was natural, in tions—have made these criticisms their start-
harmony with the universe. The second was ing point. This is still not understood as well
an analogy between God as the creator of as it should be. It explains why political phi-
the world and man as creator of machines. losophy is generally now so fragmentary, and
When this analogy was brought into politics, why it blurs into political theory and thought,
it suggested that politics was artificial. The and their histories. Most modern writings are
third was an analogy between the history of indirect testimony to our failure to sketch a
nature and the history of man, so that nature total understanding of politics in relation to
was seen to be historical, subject to change what we have done in history and in relation
(Collingwood, 1945, 3 ff). This third analogy to what we can think in philosophy.
“detached early modernity from its past and It is unlikely we could understand this with-
at the same time inaugurated our modernity out the history of political philosophy. Some

21
James Alexander

modern writers have understood it: Andrew Vincent divides the different attitudes to
Vincent in The Nature of Political Theory, foundations somewhat differently. In his book
a book which deals with everyone but the he distinguishes, first, those who believe in
marxisant French; and Olivier Marchart in transcendental foundations: foundations of
Post-Foundational Political Thought, a book politics derived from some external sources,
which deals only with the marxisant French. such as divine revelation, natural law, and
Marchart distinguishes modern political phi- even perhaps, although more ambiguously,
losophers into three categories. First, there are historical inevitability and scientific gen-
foundational philosophers, who posit some eralization; secondly, those who believe in
foundation for politics. Most philosophers immanent foundations, which are founda-
before the nineteenth century fit into this cat- tions found within politics itself: what these
egory. It survives into the present, although are is highly contested, since writers are torn
heavily modified: since instead of simply pos- between universal claims, usually constructed
tulating that there are foundations, philoso- abstractly or in terms of discourse, and “con-
phers like Rawls and Habermas have instead ventional” claims which depend on particu-
sought to construct them. Yet this classical tra- lar historical traditions; and, thirdly, those
dition has come under severe assault. For there who do not believe in foundations, since they
are also anti-foundational philosophers who consider that everything is conventional and
claim that such foundations do not exist, and therefore particular (Vincent, 2004, 3–14). If
so instead propose theories that tend to be rel- we combine these two schemes together, then
ativistic, skeptical, or nihilistic. Thirdly, there I think we have something like a complete
are post-foundational philosophers, who posit scheme. There are five possible claims:
that the “lack” or “absence” of foundations
is itself constitutive of political philosophy, 1. The claim that there are foundations,
which then becomes “a constant interrogation which are transcendental and universal,
of metaphysical figures of foundation—such and that these can be known.
as totality, universality, essence and ground” 2. The claim that foundations can be some-
how constructed through or for the sake
(Marchart, 2007, 2). This involves paradoxes
of universal agreement, so we can avoid
which have to be accepted as a matter of faith.
contingency.
If one accepts them, then one can adopt the 3. The claim that the foundations are con-
obscure terminology of Baudrillard, Badiou, tingent and conventional, so not universal
and the rest; if one does not, then one can, as but particular (and traditional).
many do, ignore it. Most moderate commen- 4. The claim that since everything is contin-
tators, such as Vincent, think that the best we gent there are no foundations.
can do is to adopt the sort of position sketched 5. The claim that there are no foundations,
by Gadamer, who simply says we cannot but that our need for foundations is so
escape our traditions and prejudices. But it is fundamental that it may still be consid-
far from clear what the consequence of this ered constitutive of whatever we think
about the world.
would be, or that Gadamer, despite his sophis-
tication, has done as much as Collingwood,
Koselleck, Arendt, Oakeshott, and MacIntyre Each suggests a different purpose for the
have done to dramatize its difficulties in rela- history of political philosophy. The first sug-
tion to politics. gests that history is unified in terms of the

22
THE HISTORY OF POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY

understanding and misunderstanding of the Lecky, Freeman, Maine, Bryce, and Bury was
truth, and otherwise in terms of the contin- threatened in the mid-twentieth century by
ual failure to enact this truth in the past in the positivistic view that ideas were of no sig-
any particular politics. The second suggests nificance in explaining politics (Momigliano,
that history is a repository of earlier con- 1977, 1). It was in answering this sort of claim
structions, which are only to be studied for that certain figures tried to justify the status
the sake of better construction. The third of history of political philosophy within the
suggests that history is a constitutive form of modern academic study of politics. In the early
study, since the supposition here is that we part of the twentieth century, the history of
can only understand politics in terms of our political philosophy and political science were
own historical finitude: although here there is rarely distinguished: they were part of a single
no secure way of distinguishing history from study of politics. But the establishment of pol-
tradition. The fourth goes further and sug- itics as a science forced what were now rival
gests that history is anything and everything. branches of political study to justify them-
The fifth suggests that history is evidence selves. Justification for the history of politi-
for the intractable nature of our condition cal philosophy came, Vincent suggests, in two
of being permanently committed to certain- waves. Those of the first wave of the 1940s
ties we can neither wholly believe nor wholly and 1950s—Strauss, Arendt, Oakeshott, and
abandon belief in. even to some extent others like MacIntyre
All of these except the first would have later—suggested that if the history of political
struck everyone before Burke as possibilities philosophy was correctly carried out it would
to be avoided. This is one reason why we still enable us to establish what was of permanent
read the classics: for the reason that, even philosophical significance. The books of these
if we cannot agree with them, we recognize writers were still meant to be contributions
that our own writings are in certain respects to political philosophy. But the writers of the
inferior to them. This is, perhaps, a mini- second wave of the 1960s and after—Pocock,
mal justification for the continued study of Skinner, and Dunn—suggested that, since his-
the history of political philosophy. But here torians could only show what was of histori-
we return to the original contradiction. We cal significance, nothing was of permanent
may study the history of political philoso- philosophical significance (Vincent, 2004,
phy because our commitment to a historical 37–51). This position was associated with
form of understanding makes it impossible the intensification of historical study found in
to believe in the certainties held about poli- The Political Thought of John Locke (1969),
tics in the past by the political philosophers The Machiavellian Moment (1975), and The
we study. The history of political philosophy Foundations of Modern Political Thought
both enables us to emancipate ourselves from (1978), which are still taken to be models
the past and encourages us to recover it. We for the subject. A subject was legislated for:
are in the interesting situation of remember- methods established, enemies identified, and
ing something we have chosen to forget. books written. Skinner and Pocock between
The history of political philosophy is only them drew our attention to two different
a few centuries old. Momigliano notes that ways of writing the history of political phi-
the English were rather good at it in the nine- losophy. Either we can write the history of
teenth century. But the tradition of Grote, the uses of argument found in the works of

23
James Alexander

political philosophers, so emphasizing the us of older ideas. In the end, it may be that
particularity of each argument, the question most histories of this type are nothing more
it was meant to answer, and the supposed use than archival compilations complicated by
to which the argument was meant to be put; the subjectivity of the historian, in which case
or we can write the history of the changes the history of political philosophy is nothing
in the languages or discourses of political more than a high form of literature for failed
philosophy in terms of the longue durée. In politicians and frustrated philosophers.
practice, the difference between these may This may seem like a dead end. So it is
not be very great, although they may register interesting to note that Dunn recanted. He
slight differences in temperament and even in saw that the revolution associated with the
political inclination. If Foucault’s historical “Cambridge” contextualizing methods of
writings were tainted with a radical hue, and Skinner and Pocock was no revolution at all,
Koselleck’s with a reactionary hue, Skinner’s and that reaction was necessary if the history
and Pocock’s have been tainted with the hues of political philosophy was to have any sig-
of moderate reformism and restraint. Even nificance (Dunn, 1996). He argued that the
though their works are meant to be good his- study of politics should be
tory, they are also meant to offer something to
contemporary political philosophers. Skinner committed by its central tasks to a rejec-
has suggested that the value of history is in tion of the intellectually, educationally,
recovering past ideas in order to challenge and politically disastrous divorce between
a purely historicist history of politi-
present ones (Skinner, 1997). Pocock has
cal ideas, a style of political philosophy
suggested that its value is in performing “the
committed to political inconsequence by
liberal-conservative function of warning the the self-conscious purity of its methods,
ruler on the one hand, and the revolution- and a political science ludicrously aping
ary on the other, that there is always more the sciences of nature and uninformed
going on that either can understand or con- by any coherent conception of political
trol” (Pocock, 2009, xiii). These, though not value (and thus at the mercy of the most
unreasonable, hardly require an elaborate superficial of local ideological perspec-
apparatus of historical learning. What we tives and sentiments). (Dunn, 1985, 2)
may observe is that, unlike Koselleck, the
leading figure of the German philological tra- This is the broad justification for the con-
dition of Begriffsgeschichte, who was mainly tinued study of the history of political phi-
concerned to characterize what is distinctive losophy over against the almost deliberately
about our modernity—the modernity con- unhistorical political philosophy of Rawls
stituted by a distinctive historical conscious- and Habermas. The major significance of
ness—Pocock and Skinner have concerned Rawls’s Theory of Justice (1971) was that
themselves with earlier eras. So they have had it established a form of political philosophy
to face difficult questions about how their that confined itself to a sphere in which it
study relates to the present which Koselleck was untroubled or uncomplicated by his-
did not have to face. They are not characteriz- tory and that, within the modern univer-
ing our world, so they are perhaps explaining sity, could exist alongside political science.
its origins, merely characterizing an earlier Oakeshott once said that philosophy is
era for its own sake, or even only reminding “radically subversive” (Oakeshott, 1993,

24
THE HISTORY OF POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY

141), but academic political philosophy is enthusiasm and skepticism. It is necessary to


at best moderately subversive and at worst say something about this.
radically supportive of whatever is going on In a short chapter, it is only possible to
politically. Bevir and Adcock say that politi- sketch some of the antinomies involved.
cal philosophy has always been “the locus of These antinomies are not symmetrical, and
hostility—whether conservative, radical or do not form a logical set. They are the alter-
some curious blend of them—to the scien- natives which arise as soon we attempt to
tific aspirations of the discipline’s new main- reflect in the present on thought which is
stream” (Adcock and Bevir, 2010, 90). But supposed to have come from the past. These
this is only true of political philosophy when antinomies cannot be resolved unless we set-
it is reinforced by the history of political phi- tle for arbitrary compromises which only
losophy. History to Rawls was no more than conceal the contradictions. It is more impor-
the conflict of Protestants and Catholics in tant to recognize contradictions than try to
the sixteenth century, and to Habermas lit- resolve them. So we have:
tle more than the newspapers and clubs of
the eighteenth century. Both, of course, paid 1. Either history is the objective past, or his-
some attention to their own heritage: Rawls tory is whatever the historian subjectively
lectured on Hobbes, Kant, Sidgwick, and believes about the remains of the past.
others, while Habermas has written about 2. Either history can be written of the entire
almost everyone from Hegel to Derrida. But past, or history can only be written of
this has all been a lot less reflective, and a partial pasts.
lot less subversive, than the work of oth- 3. Either history is concerned with the past
ers—such as Oakeshott, Arendt, MacIntyre, for the sake of the present, or history is
Cowling, Dunn, and Geuss—who have seen concerned with the past for its own sake.
4. Either history is conditioned by some-
history as less anticipatory of, or exemplary
thing which does not itself have a history
for, modern trends. My own view is that the
because it exists outside of time and is
theories of Rawls and Habermas are nothing eternal, or history is not conditioned by
but moments, or arrests, in what is possible— anything outside time, so history has to
footnotes to Kant, say, or worth a page or two be understood only in terms of its own
of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right. Geuss (2008) conditions.
has recently made this sort of claim respect- 5. Either not everything can be studied his-
able. The claim, in short, is that the political torically (not all objects are historical), or
philosopher should not ignore the history of everything can be studied historically (all
political philosophy. But it is never easy to objects are historical).
see where the history of political philosophy 6. Either the history of political philosophy
is a form of study which is secondary to
points with any clarity (which is a particular
political philosophy: a mere retrospective
matter of despair for any impatient academ-
study of the earlier attempts to generate
ics who seek “outputs” and “impacts” from a philosophical view of politics, or the
political philosophy): I think this is because history of political philosophy is a form
an openness to history involves an openness of study which is inseparable from and
to fundamental difficulties. It opens us to therefore not secondary to political phi-
both the transcendent and the immanent, to losophy because it is the study of what
both the universal and the particular, to both constitutes political philosophy, perhaps

25
James Alexander

at any time, and certainly, now at a time Arendt but also Derrida. On the other side,
when we suppose that everything is con- Hegel was equally fascinated with Indian and
stituted by its history. Chinese philosophy, and incorporated both
of the great Eastern civilizations of China
Some of these antinomies are very close— and India into his philosophy of history and
the fourth and fifth, for instance—and all even, although more as preliminaries than
are related. They raise great difficulties. To anything else, into his history of philosophy.
take only the second antinomy, we may ask Schopenhauer, on the one hand, suggested
whether it is possible to write a history of that there is a dilemma: we have to choose
political philosophy for the entire world or either a Pelagian, ethical, or world-affirming
only for part of it. If we suppose that the form of philosophy, or an Augustinian, anti-
history of political philosophy is contin- nomian, or world-denying form. Hegel, on
gent and largely discontinuous, then it can the other hand, suggested that there was a dia-
include whichever elements we happen to lectic whereby the simple unities of Chinese
find exemplary. These have always tended to thought were logically opposed by the simple
be the “European” or “Western” traditions of multiplicities of Indian thought and whereby
Classical, Christian, and Enlightened thought, both were reconciled through the compli-
but there is no reason to exclude others if we cated unity-in-multiplicity of Greek thought
are skeptical about the importance of our tra- into the distinctive and familiar tradition of
dition. If the history of political philosophy is the Christian West. These are two magnifi-
continuous and therefore constitutive of our cent and influential myths, and we have not
current political philosophy, then the ques- entirely abandoned them. It is of course sig-
tion is a much harder one. Yet it is possible nificant that Hegel and Schopenhauer wrote
to answer it, and again in terms of history. I in a century when it was thought that the his-
mentioned earlier that a historical conscious- tory of humanity could be told as one story.
ness emerged in the eighteenth century. The If we scale down our ambition, as we have
impact of this on how philosophers saw the tended to do since what Thomas Mann called
history of philosophy was total, whether or the “bad nineteenth century,” then a story
not they thought history was contingent less tendentious is necessary. Perhaps the
or constitutive. By the time of Hegel and best available one is the one sketched in The
Schopenhauer, it was common to see phi- Nomos of the Earth, where Schmitt argued
losophy historically. Both were interested in that there was no unity in history until there
the discovery of other traditions besides their was unity in geography. It was the contingent
own. But Schopenhauer still saw history as achievement of the Europeans to unite the
contingent: indeed, of no significance at all. world geographically. (Hegel would have said
His philosophy was in large part a Western or it was a constitutive achievement.) But we
Kantian reinterpretation of Buddhistic recog- could say, with Schmitt, that this achievement,
nitions, as he himself saw: he took elements though contingent, was imaginatively deci-
of Indian religion to be exemplary of a cor- sive. There was a consciousness which arose
rect philosophical understanding. Much later, in Europe, which was taken across the world
with less verve and more obscurity, Heidegger so that the unity of the world was forged in
saw pre-Socratic philosophy as equally exem- relation to it, and which then was separated
plary—a view which influenced not only from its origin to become a complete world

26
THE HISTORY OF POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY

consciousness, and which has been reflected something deeper, more intractable. I think
back into Europe (Schmitt, 2003). There is it is fair to say that the first ends in triviality
reflexivity here: this consciousness is now no and the second absurdity, taken separately.
longer that of Europe, but that of the world; According to the former, the history of politi-
yet, for contingent reasons, the European cal philosophy would simply be a category
story is the only one into which all other into which we collect anything and every-
traditions can be placed to form a unity. It is thing which remains of earlier thought: a
common for writers of the history of political category of the relics of political philosophy
philosophy to emphasize that they are writ- perhaps modified by the insistence that we
ing about the Western tradition only: but this understand them historically. This certainly
is, for the most part, just good manners. For would not require any of the historical sub-
the moment, the Western tradition is the only tlety we have acquired since the eighteenth
unitary tradition. Everything else, so far, is century. According to the latter, the history of
partial (Dunn, 1996, 15). This does not mean political philosophy would depend on some-
that there could not be alternative traditions, thing like a philosophy of history. Here his-
say, Confucian or Vedic or Islamic. But these tory would be unified not through facts, but
would involve revolutions in thought of which in terms of a theory or event which relates
there is as yet no sign. Europe is to the World everything—a theory such as, say, natural
what Greece was to Rome. Indeed, there is selection or historical materialism, or an event
good historical justification for the claim that such as crucifixion-resurrection. If any the-
the Greeks invented politics, that the Romans ory or event of this sort were to be believed,
invented law—that is, they invented the habit then clearly it would change our idea of his-
of treating them separately from religion, tory, which would no longer be “one damned
ethics, and each other—and that Europeans thing after another” but many damned or
conveyed these two paradigms of politics saved things, one after another, or, at least,
and law to the world, along with, eventually, many things ordered according to one struc-
a third paradigm of a separately treated eco- turing principle. The point is that such a the-
nomics (McCloskey, 2010, Schiavone, 2012, ory or event would not itself be historical but
11). But we have to admit that there is noth- abstract or timeless or eternal. “Modern his-
ing in this dual or triple legacy which prevents torians have always reacted, understandably,
an evangelical interruption of the sort which against philosophies of history,” comments
came with Christianity—although it could Perry Anderson. But philosophies of history
come in the future from Islam, Buddhism, or “have not gone away, and are unlikely to, as
elsewhere. long as the demand for social meaning over
The point is that the antinomies are ines- time persists” (Anderson, 1992, 284–285). It
capable: we exist between simple and coher- seems that historians of political philosophy
ent positions which we cannot possibly are always in danger of turning into philoso-
entirely adopt. The most immediately rel- phers of history—or turning back into mere
evant antinomy here is of course the sixth. historians.
This is the question of whether we suppose In this situation, I think we have to admit
the history of political philosophy is simply that there is no way to legislate for the his-
an additional way of reflecting upon texts tory of political philosophy which is not
we already reflect upon philosophically, or is arbitrary. Yet if philosophy without history

27
James Alexander

is a desert, and history without philosophy is of study concerned to establish speculatively


a jungle, then we certainly need something of why the ideas came in the form that they
both. There is certainly nothing to be gained did; and, fourthly, “doxology”: by which he
by being too concerned with historical or meant simply textbook history. Rorty did
philosophical correctness. To some extent, not think much of the fourth, although it
the “methodological” writings of the last is still by far the most common. (Consider
half century came out of anxiety caused by any “History of Political Thought” you have
the requirement to be exact. Skinner was too ever read.) He thought the third is the most
subtle to simply encourage a mindless con- interesting, since it “meets needs which nei-
cern with “historical context” but there is no ther unphilosophical history not unhistorical
question that at least part of his legacy is the philosophy is likely to fulfil,” since it estab-
view that we should not look at philosophi- lishes the nature of the canons of our ideas.
cal works without some historical awareness It is “parasitic on, and synthesises, the first
of context (Tully, 1988). What he left to one two genres.” He even added a fifth, which
side was, as Leavis put it, that “context, as is the general intellectual history or history
something determinate is, and can be, noth- of ideas which offers the “raw material” for
ing but [the historian’s] postulate; the wider the other four (Rorty, 1984, 59, 61). In a dif-
he goes in his ambition to construct it from ferent register, MacIntyre has distinguished,
his reading in this period, the more it is his first, “encyclopaedia,” an unhistorical form
construction (in so far as he produces any- of understanding in which systematic order
thing more than a mass of heterogeneous is sought, on the belief that all knowledge
information alleged to be relevant)” (Leavis, is related to all other knowledge; secondly,
1968, 293). Oakeshott famously suggested in “genealogy,” a historical form of understand-
his introduction to Hobbes’s Leviathan that ing in which everything is to be explained
if Hobbes had written a masterpiece, as he in terms of contingent continuities and dis-
had, then its context should be nothing other continuities, especially in terms of uses and
than the entire history of political philoso- powers; and, thirdly, “tradition,” which is a
phy (Oakeshott, 1991, 223). If we agree with form of understanding neither straightfor-
this, then we end up in circularities, for the wardly historical nor unhistorical, in which
history of political philosophy is whatever everything is to be explained in relation
we suppose it to be. to a tradition which has a truth at its core
Awareness of what we are doing is not (MacIntyre, 1990). The first is enlightened:
the same as doing it. But it is important to it requires history to be treated as no more
be aware of different ways of carrying out than a set of cases. The second is critical: it
the history of political philosophy. Rorty dis- requires history to be treated as a set of past
tinguished, first, “rational reconstruction”: particulars. The third is neither enlightened
which is the study of older ideas in terms of nor critical: it requires history to be taken
their truth, with the intention of saying them seriously enough to see whether we can find
better; secondly, “historical reconstruction”: any certainties there that can survive enlight-
which is the study of older ideas, whether enment and criticism. To take the second,
or not we consider them true, in terms what the most influential now, Nietzsche claimed
they meant at the time of writing; thirdly, that history as genealogy was a weapon to
“geistgeschichte”: by which he meant a form be used against other forms of history for the

28
THE HISTORY OF POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY

sake of our present unhistorical ends. In his the relations between its different elements.
later writings, he did not quite answer the Even the great philosophers in our tradition
question he had posed in his earlier writings, did not always know how to relate them.
which is whether to think historically is to Just to take one instance, Hume and Hobbes
think ironically and therefore to damage our were rather untroubled by hypocrisy in pol-
capacity to act. But in his earlier writings he itics when writing philosophically, but were
also suggested that we might write history far more censorious about it when writing
for any of three reasons: and, following him, historically (Runciman, 2008, 17).
we could say that we might write the history The distinctions I have drawn in this chap-
of political philosophy for these three same ter should indicate that history discloses no
reasons: because it inspires us to strive to simple attitude to political philosophy. We
write great works of political philosophy, it are torn, finally, between two main theoreti-
enables us to preserve the older traditions of cal possibilities:
political philosophy we revere, or it enables
us to overcome our suffering in politics by Either the history of political philoso-
studying historically the means of delivering phy is simply an assemblage of useful or
ourselves philosophically from it (Nietzsche, amusing materials about politics: written
to amuse and edify readers, and used,
1997, 67).
when we are neither amused nor edified,
Much is still written in all of these cat-
by sociologists, protestors, journalists,
egories in our time by those who seek some politicians and dictators as evidence for
authority in the history of philosophy for the particular points they want to make:
their explanations, justifications, and pre- it is a fragmentary set of materials, valu-
scriptions. We might ignore this if we were able because exemplary.
only to follow a narrow contextualist method Or the history of political philosophy is
or limit ourselves to a study of Skinner’s or the only correct way to understand the
Pocock’s methodological writings. The ten- continuing fragility of our attempts to
sion between historical and unhistorical impose political order on the world by
approaches to political philosophy is still ordering it philosophically: it is not frag-
a great matter of concern to political phi- mentary but complete, even if impossible,
losophers. This is not only because history since it is a bringing into consciousness
puts the certainties of philosophy into ques- of the highest elements of the history by
which our own thought about politics is
tion, but also because for some time it has
constituted.
seemed as if the unhistorical political phil-
osophy of Rawls and Habermas has failed
to adequately theorize politics as it really is In short, it may be exemplary or constitu-
(Floyd and Stears, 2011). Arguments about tive: we may study it to find examples of
these matters are likely to be repeated, espe- great political philosophy, or we may study
cially by those who do not know how old it because the history of philosophy is a con-
they are. The truth is, of course, that “the scious emanation of some philosophy of his-
unhistorical and the historical are necessary tory. In the first our relation to the past is
in equal measure” (Nietzsche, 1997, 63). discontinuous, in the latter it is continuous.
But the history of political philosophy will These seem the only wholly coherent possi-
always face questions about the adequacy of bilities, even if one risks triviality, the other

29
James Alexander

absurdity. There is no way to completely Floyd, J. and Stears, M. (eds) (2011),


harmonize them. Compromises will con- Political Philosophy Versus History?
tinue to be sought, and contradictions will Contextualism and Real Politics in
continue to be found. The history of politi- Contemporary Political Thought.
cal philosophy is both the recollection of our Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
former attempts to understand politics philo- Geuss, R. (2008), Philosophy and Real
sophically and the explanation of why we no Politics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
longer fully understand it philosophically. It University Press.
is not political philosophy, but political phi- Goethe, J. W. von (1904), Criticisms,
losophy is nothing without it. Reflections and Maxims of Goethe, trans.
W. B. Rönnfeldt. London: Walter Scott.
Hegel, G. W. F. (1977), The Phenomenology
of Spirit, trans. A. V. Miller. Oxford:
WORKS CITED Oxford University Press.
Koselleck, R. (1985), Futures Past: On the
Adcock, R. and Bevir, M. (2010), “Political Semantics of Historical Time, trans. Keith
Science,” in R. Backhouse and P. Fontaine Tribe. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
(eds), The History of the Social Sciences Leavis, F. R. (ed.) (1968), A Selection from
since 1945. Cambridge: Cambridge Scrutiny, Vol. II. London: Cambridge
University Press, pp. 71–101. University Press.
Alexander, J. (2012), “The Four Points of McCloskey, D. (2010), Bourgeois Dignity:
the Compass,” Philosophy, 87: 79–107. Why Economics Can’t Explain the
— (2014), “Notes Towards the Definition of Modern World. Chicago: University of
Politics” Philosophy, 89: 273–300. Chicago Press.
Anderson, P. (1992), “The Ends of History,” MacIntyre, A. (1990), Three Rival Versions
in A Zone of Engagement. London: of Moral Enquiry: Encyclopaedia,
Verso, pp. 279–376. Genealogy, and Tradition. London:
Collingwood, R. G. (1945), The Idea of Duckworth.
Nature. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Marchart, O. (2007), Post-Foundational
Condren, C. (1985), The Status and Appraisal Political Thought: Political Difference
of Classic Texts: An Essay on Politics, in Nancy, Lefort, Badiou and Laclau.
Its Inheritance and the History of Ideas. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Princeton, NJ : Princeton University Press. Marx, K. (1963), The Eighteenth Brumaire
Dunn, J. (1969), The Political Thought of of Louis Napoleon. New York:
John Locke. Cambridge: Cambridge International Publishers.
University Press. Momigliano, A. (1977), “A Piedmontese
— (1985), Rethinking Modern Political View of the History of Ideas,” in Essays
Theory: Essays 1979–83. Cambridge: in Ancient and Modern Historiography.
Cambridge University Press. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 1–7.
— (1996), “The History of Political Nietzsche, F. (1997), “On the Uses and
Theory,” in The History of Political Disadvantages of History for Life,”
Thought and Other Essays. Cambridge: in Untimely Meditations. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, pp. 11–38. Cambridge University Press, pp. 59–123.

30
THE HISTORY OF POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY

Oakeshott, M. (1991), Rationalism in Schneewind, R. Rorty, and Q. Skinner


Politics and Other Essays, T. Fuller (ed.). (eds), Philosophy in History: Essays
Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Press. on the Historiography of Philosophy.
— (1993), Religion, Politics and the Moral Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Life, T. Fuller (ed.). New Haven, CT: Yale Runciman, D. (2008), Political Hypocrisy:
University Press. The Mask of Power, from Hobbes to
— (2007), The Concept of a Philosophical Orwell and Beyond. Princeton, NJ:
Jurisprudence: Essays and Reviews Princeton University Press.
1926–51, L. O’Sullivan (ed.). Exeter: Schiavone, A. (2012), The Invention of
Imprint Academic. Law in the West, trans. J. Carden and A.
— (2008), The Vocabulary of a Modern Shugaar. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.
European State, L. O’Sullivan (ed.). Schmitt, C. (2003), The Nomos of the
Exeter: Imprint Academic. Earth in the International Law of the
Pocock, J. G. A. (1975), The Machiavellian Jus Publicum Europaeum, trans. G. L.
Moment: Florentine Political Thought Ulmen. New York: Telos Press.
and the Atlantic Republican Tradition. Skinner, Q. (1978), The Foundations of
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Modern Political Thought. Cambridge:
— (2009), Political Thought and History: Cambridge University Press.
Essays on Theory and Method. — (1997), Liberty before Liberalism.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rawls, J. (1971), A Theory of Justice. Tully, J. (ed.) (1988), Meaning and Context:
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Quentin Skinner and His Critics.
Press. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Rorty, R. (1984), “The Historiography Vincent, A. (2004), The Nature of Political
of Philosophy: Four Genres,” in J. B. Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

31
2
SOVEREIGNTY
Andrew Fiala

One of the most important and vexing a right to command. The normative account
issues in political philosophy is the ques- holds that the sovereign power has the de
tion of who or what should have supreme jure authority to use coercive power within
ruling authority within a territory. While a territory, including the right to kill, and
some have dreamed of identifying a single freedom from intervention when it exercises
ultimate source of authority, in reality there that right. The sovereign is often conceived
are multiple relationships and directions of as the person or institution that constitutes
power as well as plural sources of normative the law. On some interpretations the sover-
authority. Often there are layers and levels eign is understood as residing outside the
of sovereignty: superior power is concen- law, retaining the de jure right (or de facto
trated and centralized in larger structures, power) to make exceptions to the law. Other
but inferior powers still retain some auton- interpretations establish a basic limit to the
omy, resulting in jurisdictional conflict and exceptional power of the sovereign located
instability. Sovereignty may describe the de in the normative primacy of something like
facto supremacy of a particular institution natural law. While the natural law tradition
or person—the entity to which others defer. provides a guide for the proper exercise of
In international law, sovereignty is primarily sovereign power, natural law may also be
understood as a descriptive feature of states used to support the idea of civil disobedience
that mutually recognize one another, with- in which violators of the law assert allegiance
out appeal to any metaphysical or norma- to the sovereign natural law; related claims
tive ground. But de facto sovereignty ignores are made about the sovereign authority of
normative evaluation. As Francis Fukuyama the individual conscience. A less metaphysi-
notes in some cases—as in Afghanistan or cal notion of positive law (associated with
Somalia—sovereignty is a “fiction or a bad legal positivists such as Hart) identifies a de
joke” (Fukuyama, 2004, 97). Indeed, the facto sovereign in a legal regime or (in ideas
international community appears to agree found in Hayek) in common law as a sponta-
that violations of “sovereignty” in the case neous but evolving source of authority.
of failed states is morally permissible. Thus Sovereignty is a threshold or liminal con-
sovereignty often also includes a normative cept, which can inspire contemplation, awe,
ideal of legitimacy: sovereign power is justi- wonder, and fear. The sovereign—whether
fied power that ought to be obeyed and has the political executive or the conscientious

33
Andrew Fiala

individual—may retain the right to break 92). In the Bible, the account of God’s lord-
the law. Sovereignty is thus a trump that pre- ship or sovereignty shows up, for example, in
vents criticism or intervention. The focus on Psalm (71:16), where the Sovereign Lord God
supremacy at the outside edge of the legal is praised for his mighty deeds and as the sole
system has religious overtones. God (or the source of justice. We see this in the phrase
Church) was once viewed as the sovereign, “the Almighty” which is also used to describe
symbolized in the coronation of the mon- God, even occasionally piling on epithets to
arch by Pope or bishop. But in the modern emphasize power, as in the phrase, “Lord
period, the state emerged as sovereign, with God Almighty” (kyrios theos pantokratōr)
secular governments asserting sovereignty found in Revelation. Revelation makes clear
over religious institutions. Sovereignty is a the hope, foreshadowed in the Psalms, that at
practical concept used to describe structures some point God will rule over the kingdoms
of power and deference in international law of the world (Revelation 11). Thus sover-
and domestic political science. But the hier- eignty can have a metaphysical and religious
archies of authority, power, and obedience significance. Even though we take sovereignty
continue to provoke philosophical reflection. as “the sine qua non of political life,” as Jean
This chapter examines the concept of sover- Elshtain puts it, the concept reflects a com-
eignty by explaining (1) how the concept of plex interplay between theology and political
sovereignty evolved in Western political phi- philosophy (Elshtain, 2008, xiii–xvi).
losophy and (2) how the concept functions in The debate about sovereignty reflects a
contemporary legal theory, political science, conflict between Platonic (and later Christian)
and Anglo-American political philosophy. views of political authority as grounded in a
moral and metaphysical hierarchy, on the one
hand, and the modern liberal, democratic idea
of citizen or individual sovereignty, on the
GENEALOGY OF THE CONCEPT other hand, as the revolutionary antithesis
OF SOVEREIGNTY to religious paternalism and political despot-
ism. Sovereignty has been a primary focus for
The sovereign is the supreme or superior political philosophy since Plato. The catalogue
authority: superanus in Vulgar Latin; souve- of regime types in Republic can be under-
rain in French; in German rendered either as stood as a catalogue of the varieties of sover-
Souveränität or with two words, Staatshoheit eign power. Bloom points out that the debate
und Staatsgewalt indicating the majesty/dig- between Thrasymachus and Socrates at the
nity and power of the state (see Bluntschi, beginning of Republic is about sovereignty—
1892, Beaulac, 2004). Behind this is the Greek about whether there is some principle supe-
terms kyrios, which is most frequently trans- rior to strength that could limit its exercise
lated as “Lord” or “sovereign” in the Bible (Bloom, 1991, 326–327). In his translation of
(along with the Hebrew Adonai). The term Republic, Bloom points toward an interpreta-
kyrios was employed to identify the Roman tion of Plato’s cave allegory (Republic 517c) as
emperor—as in the title Kyrios Kaisar (Lord a discussion of sovereignty: the good (or sun)
Caesar), which was countered by Christians in the cave allegory is kyrios or sovereign—the
who denied that Caesar was Lord and source of light and of truth. Arendt explains
affirmed Kyrios Christos (see Jongeneel, 2009, that Plato thus suggests that politics ought to

34
SOVEREIGNTY

be subordinated to philosophy (Arendt, 2005, of sovereignty (as traditionally understood).


130). Not only is the philosopher-king the Arendt suggested that revolutionary political
paradigm of the wise, virtuous, and just sov- activity—as in the American (and French)
ereign authority, but also his knowledge of the revolutions—aimed to abolish sovereignty
truth connects him with the sovereign power entirely (Arendt, 2006, 144). Arendt sug-
of the universe. gests that the early American experiment in
This metaphysical conception of sover- self-government showed that political socie-
eignty is linked to Christian ideas about the ties and bodies could enjoy power and claim
divine right of kings and idea of absolute rights “without possessing or claiming sover-
sovereignty. Bodin explained in the sixteenth eignty” (Arendt, 2006, 159).
century that the prince’s power is derived One wonders whether there could be a
from the absolute sovereignty of God (Bodin, political organization that does not possess
1992, 34–35). At the turn of the twentieth or claim sovereignty. Arendt’s suggestion
century, Figgis argued that during the medi- that sovereignty and tyranny are the same
eval period, God and church were held to be is a hint in the anarchist direction, which
superior to the state. It was only in the tran- holds that sovereignty is primarily about
sition to modernity that the notion of divine domination, dominion, and paternal or des-
right of kings developed—as an attempt to potic rule. However, for the mainstream of
stipulate that the state was independent of the Western tradition in political philosophy,
the church. Nonetheless, Figgis followed which develops after Plato, political philoso-
Bodin and others in arguing that the best phy has often primarily been concerned with
place for sovereignty to rest was in the will the justification of sovereignty.
of the monarch and that the idea of a lim- Discussions of sovereignty emphasize that
ited monarchy was a contradiction in terms there is (or ought to be) a supreme authority
(Figgis, 1914, 6). in a territory, whose rulings trump those of
Hobbes and the social contract tradi- other lesser authorities. There are two rival
tion developed in a different direction, not directions of the evolution of the idea: (1)
grounded in a metaphysical or religious toward centralization in modern bureau-
account of divine right. Rather, for Hobbes, cratic states and (2) away from central power
the absolute power of the sovereign was in liberal democratic theory. In feudal organi-
grounded in the original contract. From zation, the king was said to be sovereign over
Hobbes, it is a short leap to modern demo- the princes and other feudal lords within his
cratic revolutionary politics that calls hierar- territory. In federations and federal systems—
chical and absolutist accounts of sovereignty as in the United States—the federal authority
into question. Absolutist ideas can be found and its bureaucracy is said to have sover-
in the work of Schmitt, whose theory of sov- eign power, which trumps the authority and
ereignty—as the exception beyond the law— power of the confederated states and local
was related to Hobbesian notions (Schmitt, authorities. At the same time, democratic
1985, 2008). But Schmittian absolutism has states are based upon some notion of popu-
been opposed by a more radical development lar sovereignty, which is the decentralized
of the social contract idea. In its most radical notion of governmental legitimacy as based
iteration, liberal, democratic ideas are revo- upon the consent of the governed. Liberal
lutionary and may even aim at the abolition political philosophy also tends to hold that

35
Andrew Fiala

sovereignty should include a foundation in 1960, 67). Indeed, anarchists often hold that
human rights, which can be understood as individual autonomy (or “self-sovereignty”
asserting the sovereignty of the individual as or “personal sovereignty” as it is variously
a person with inherent dignity and the right called) is absolute and inviolable. Thus for
to obey the authority of conscience. While the the anarchist, political sovereignty is, at best,
notion of individual sovereignty is the most an oxymoron, since political organizations
radical, since it asserts that each individual ultimately undermine the sovereignty of the
possesses supreme authority, a related (and self. The anarchist challenge forces us to
more limited) notion of “citizen sovereignty” confront the question of where sovereignty
also appears in the literature (see Dworkin, resides: in the self or in the state.
2002, Vanberg, 2007). Citizen sovereignty The mainstream tradition assumes—
is the liberal, democratic idea that politi- contra the anarchists—that some form of
cal power is derived from and legitimated supreme ruling authority is justified. The
by the choices and consent of citizens; indi- question was not usually whether sovereign
vidual sovereignty points beyond citizenship authority ought to exist but, rather, how best
toward the purity of conscience and individ- to conceive and organize it—whether sover-
ual autonomy. eignty was absolute or not, whether sover-
The idea of human rights and related eignty was focused internally or externally,
ideas about of the sovereignty of citizens or and who—monarch or demos—should prop-
individuals can call the political notion of erly hold supreme authority (see Philpot,
sovereignty into question along with related 2011). The deepest question in this tradi-
notions of authority, obedience, loyalty, tion has to do with the moral limit of sov-
patriotism, and national identity. In a cosmo- ereignty—whether sovereignty ought to be
politan world of diverse allegiances entered grounded in virtue, wisdom, and the natural
into voluntarily by sovereign individuals, it law, whether sovereignty is best conceived as
is unclear that the political notion of sover- limited by fiduciary relations (as in modern
eignty can remain useful. Indeed, one might liberal-democratic ideas about the state), or
argue that the most important question of whether sovereignty is an amoral concept
political philosophy is whether there should merely identifying who has de facto power.
be any sovereign political authority at all. Political sovereignty is a concept closely
Nozick writes, “The fundamental question of associated with the idea of the supremacy
political philosophy, one that precedes ques- of “the state.” A state is an entity that exists
tions about how the state should be organ- in a delimited geographic area, consisting of
ized, is whether there should be any state at a more or less permanent group of people,
all. Why not have anarchy?” (Nozick, 1974, organized under the authority of a central-
4). Anarchism represents one extreme on the ized and hierarchical government who has
continuum of answers about who should the power ultimately to decide on questions
rule and how ruling should be organized: of life and death. While anarchists may argue
for the anarchist, the answer is that no one against the sovereignty of states, states have
should rule—there should be no sovereign de facto and often de jure power and author-
authority in the political sense. As Goldman ity that routinely trumps the power and
explained, anarchism is “the philosophy of authority of individuals and their voluntary
the sovereignty of the individual” (Goldman, local associations. Jackson explains, “when

36
SOVEREIGNTY

the government of a state is said to be sover- liberal, democratic theorists who hold to one
eign, it holds supreme authority domestically extent or another that individuals are born
and independent authority internationally, at free and retain sovereign power over them-
one and the same time” (Jackson, 2007, 6). selves. The modern idea that natural right
We should note that the ideal of supreme and individual conscience is sovereign has
and independent authority is merely an ideal. been developed in a libertarian (and nearly
In reality, state sovereignty is limited in a vari- anarchist) direction by authors such as
ety of ways: domestic culture and tradition, Machan, who explains, “the libertarian view
international treaty, and moral law. The idea is that each individual is a sovereign person,
that there is an absolute and independent sov- in possession of basic negative rights to life,
ereign power that can trump all other histori- liberty, and property (and whatever other
cal, social, and moral norms in an arbitrary rights are implied by these). None may vio-
act of political will is quite unrealistic and late these. If one needs to protect these rights,
ideal. One might argue, following Elshtain, the option exists of doing so oneself or hiring
that the notion of absolute sovereignty can others” (Machan, 2008, 63). One significant
be derived from a sort of nominalism and implication of this idea is that individuals
voluntarism about power and law that can may be permitted (or even obliged) to diso-
be traced back to medieval nominalists such bey the law. The notions of civil disobedience
as Ockham (Elshtain, 2008, 36–39). Elshtain and conscientious refusal—as developed in
argues that the more coherent notion of sov- the work of Thoreau, Gandhi, and King—
ereignty—even of God’s sovereignty—is less imply that political authority is not ultimate.
focused on arbitrary (voluntaristic) power The usual defense of civil disobedience is
and better understood as law governed and grounded in the idea that the authority of
reasonable activity. This idea of sovereign natural law trumps the authority of the posi-
power as reasonable and law-governed is tive law. Civil disobedience does not usually,
connected with Aquinas and the natural law however, eliminate the notion of political
tradition, which developed into the modern sovereignty, nor does it necessarily lead to
notion of human rights (see Philpot, 1996). anarchism. Rather, civil disobedience usually
When, for example, Locke offers a revolu- depends upon what Rawls (Rawls, 1971, sec-
tionary challenge to government, he appeals tions 55–59) calls “fidelity to law” or what
to the importance of natural rights. Locke is Walzer explains as the need for public jus-
also arguing—in his less studied First Treatise tification and dialogue about the status of
of Government—against Filmer’s notion rights, laws, responsibility, and sovereignty
of absolute monarchic sovereignty. Filmer (Walzer, 1970, Chapter 1). Civil disobedience
held that Adam’s sovereign power was a gift is not usually an argument against sovereign
from God, that men are not naturally born power, rather it is an argument for just gov-
free, and that political power is based upon ernment grounded in respect for natural law.
patriarchal sovereignty. Locke describes this The idea that natural law provides a trump
notion of sovereign power as “absolute, arbi- that may override sovereignty is a central
trary, unlimited, and unlimitable” (Locke, idea in modern liberal-democratic regimes
1764, section 9). and in evolving notions about humanitar-
The idea of unlimited and arbitrary sov- ian intervention across borders. This idea is
ereign power is rejected by Locke and other grounded in the claim that individuals have a

37
Andrew Fiala

kind of sovereignty that states ought not vio- individuals might transfer sovereignty to the
late. Donnelly quotes former UN chief Kofi state, which then has the power to trump the
Annan to make the point that “individual sovereignty of the individual—even though
sovereignty, rooted in human rights, is taking the anarchists have long complained that this
its place in international relations along side violates the sovereignty of the self.
state sovereignty” (Donnelly, 2003, 251). The notion of sovereignty provides a rich
Annan’s idea is that traditional notions of metaphorical framework for discussions of
state sovereignty should not prevent inter- a variety topics in religion and metaphysics.
ventions intended to protect individuals Agamben and Derrida have shown that sov-
from being harmed by their states. This idea ereignty is an ontological concept. Derrida
culminated in the newly evolving interna- says, “The sovereign, in the broadest sense of
tional idea of a “responsibility to protect” as the term, is he who has the right and strength
articulated by the International Commission to be and be recognized as himself, the same,
on Intervention and State Sovereignty, which properly the same as himself” (Derrida,
provided a framework for understanding the 2011, 66). Agamben writes, “Potentiality
relationship between sovereignty and human . . . is that through which Being founds itself
rights. The ICISS report of 2001 redefined sovereignly, which is to say, without anything
state sovereignty in a way that emphasizes preceding or determining it other than its
the state’s responsibility to defend human own ability not to be. And an act is sovereign
right. As the report states, “State sover- when it realizes itself by simply taking away
eignty implies responsibility, and the primary its own potentiality not to be, letting itself be,
responsibility for the protection of its people giving itself to itself” (Agamben, 1998, 32).
lies with the state itself” (ICISS, 2001, ix). Pursuing the metaphor of sovereignty
The report indicates that this idea and the after Agamben and Derrida reminds us how
sorts of international interventions implied thick and rich the notion of sovereignty is.
by it “herald a new world in which human However, we will confine our discussion
rights trumps state sovereignty” (see Badescu, in what follows primarily to political sov-
2009, 2). Some worry that this will be mis- ereignty within the mainstream of Anglo-
used by imperialistic power. But the idea that American political philosophy. A fuller
human rights trump state sovereignty is an genealogy would include a more extended
important one, connected to the idea that discussion of Plato—as well as Aristotle, the
individuals have a sort of sovereignty that Cynics, and the Stoics. It would consider
cannot be violated by the political sovereign. Augustine and Aquinas. It would examine
Hoffman suggests that the idea of the sov- Hobbes and Bodin in more detail. It would
ereignty of individuals is a central feature consider Weber’s account of power and cha-
of liberal political theory: “liberalism con- risma, while also including further discussion
ceives of individuals as having a sovereignty of Schmitt’s account of the sovereign excep-
which is independent of the state” (Hoffman, tion. It would include an extensive discussion
1998, 85). The problem, however, is that this of revolutionary liberal-democratic ideas and
notion of individual sovereignty is “abstract” Westphalian international law as found in
and ahistorical as Hoffman puts it. In reality, Grotius, Locke, Pufendorf, Rousseau, and
political forms preexist the individual. The others. It would also include more details
social contract theory shows how and why about the idea of individual sovereignty as

38
SOVEREIGNTY

developed by Thoreau and other defenders during the past several centuries. While these
of conscientious refusal and civil disobedi- ideas developed in the European sphere, they
ence. Finally, it would include a critique of were gradually exported globally through
sovereignty as ideological and the result of European colonialism and imperialism. In
power—from a Marxist or Nietzschean van- the postcolonial era, former colonial hold-
tage point, from ideas found in the Frankfurt ings were released from bondage and granted
School of critical theory, and from Foucault’s sovereignty. The present world is carved up
critique of so-called governmentality. But into sovereign states, which are held to have
let’s turn our attention to contemporary basic rights to territorial control, noninter-
Anglo-American theory and emerging issues. ference, and a sort of equality as members of
the United Nations.
One significant problem is that sovereign
states often include minority groups who
CONTEMPORARY POLITICAL THEORY may want sovereign power for themselves.
AND EMERGING ISSUES Some want control in autonomous regions
within a sovereign territory; others contest for
In recent years, sovereignty has been reevalu- supremacy in the whole of a state’s territory. A
ated in light of developments in interna- related problem is that ethnic, religious, and
tional law and international institutions. In other affiliations transcend national borders,
the post-World War II era, states have joined creating claims to authority, loyalty, and obe-
monetary and defensive unions, have ceded dience that point beyond national boundaries
sovereignty to federations, and have been and sovereignty understood in political terms.
invaded and reconstructed by international Nonetheless, the international system in the
forces which justify their actions in the name postcolonial era is based upon a community
of human rights. These developments have of sovereign nations, which assumes that
led some to urge rejection of the concept of each state has an equal sovereign right to self-
sovereignty or, at least, to allow for the emer- governance and self-defense. The notion of
gence of a post-sovereignty era and the end of sovereign equality idea is foundational in the
traditional notions of political sovereignty. United Nations Charter, which stipulates in
The Peace of Westphalia, which ended Article 2, Paragraph 1: “The Organization is
the Thirty Years War in 1648, created a sys- based on the principle of the sovereign equal-
tem of nation states in Europe based upon ity of all its members” (also see Article 78).
a notion described as Westphalian sover- Sovereign equality in international law views
eignty which holds that states have the right states externally, treating them as individual
to determine and organize themselves with- entities. This means that domestic political
out external intervention. This right is based arrangements of states are ignored (along
upon a claim to territorial supremacy: a with internal disputes and minority claims),
sovereign state has a right to defend its bor- with the status of sovereign statehood pro-
ders and exert control within those borders. viding equal recognition at the international
The international order has slowly come to level. The emphasis on sovereign equality is
respect basic principles of noninterference, pluralistic. It aims toward a system in which
equality among states, and related notions states with quite different domestic arrange-
constitutive of the system of nation states ments are equally recognized as having a

39
Andrew Fiala

certain political status. This notion has been genocide. The notion of “responsibility to pro-
described and defended as a form of sovereign tect” (discussed earlier) has evolved to explain
state realism, which accepts state sovereignty why, in some circumstances, state sovereignty
as a fact of political life. From this perspec- is not absolute and ought not be used to pro-
tive, once a sovereign power is established tect injustice and allow oppression.
and acknowledged by the international com- The modern Westphalian notion of sov-
munity, there is no justification for foreign ereignty has evolved in other ways in recent
interference. Such interference is conceived decades, as borders became more permeable
as a violation of sovereignty. Critics of this under globalization, as national identity is
approach will argue that this permits rogue challenged by the fact of internal diversity,
states and outlaw regimes to have an equal and as international institutions developed as
place at the international table. Such critics restraints on the sovereignty of nations. For
may advocate liberal internationalism, cos- example, the Breton Woods agreements about
mopolitan norms, natural law, and human international monetary policy and other eco-
rights ideals—holding that the idea of de nomic integration resulted in a loss of sover-
facto state sovereignty must be qualified by eignty—as a state’s domestic economic and
other values and norms including the idea of fiscal policies were pegged to international
domestic legitimacy (as understood in liberal- monetary arrangements. Moreover, as capi-
democratic terms). Critics of sovereign state tal and labor flows across borders in the era
realism will argue that sovereignty is not of globalization, it is no longer clear that ter-
merely a fact about who holds power and ritoriality remains an important concept for
authority—it also includes a normative claim political organization. Global corporations
about what the responsibilities and obliga- and international banking and trade organiza-
tions of legitimate sovereign power ought tions (such as the World Trade Organization
to be. and the World Bank) point toward a changed
One crucial contemporary issue is how understanding of borders, territory, and how
we evaluate the conflict between the norma- this relates to human development and struc-
tive idealism of sovereignty as conceived by tures of authority. Remaining conflicts in
liberal internationalists and the descriptive international relations and domestic poli-
and historically grounded account of sover- tics often involve disputes among those who
eignty as conceived by less idealistic realists. defend traditional notions of Westphalian
This conflict comes to a head with regard sovereignty and those who see an evolving
to the question of intervention and the right “post-sovereign” era. While several centuries
of self-defense. The UN Charter admits that of political philosophy simply presume that
“members” (conceived as sovereign states) something like Westphalian sovereignty is
retain a right of self-defense (as in Article 51). natural and normal, this notion is collaps-
This implies that sovereign states are entitled ing from within (by the challenges of immi-
to defend themselves against external interfer- gration, multiculturalism, and differential
ence. But some will argue that there are good sovereignty for various autonomous regions
reasons to think that interventions ought to be and groups); it is also being challenged from
employed to defend citizens against the mis- without by the evolving cosmopolitan scene.
deeds of their own states, especially to prevent We are left with sovereignty as a muddy
crimes against humanity, ethnic cleansing, and and vague concept. Krasner has shown that

40
SOVEREIGNTY

there are a variety of ideas that can be gath- be wary of pernicious ideology and possible
ered together under the term sovereignty. double standards in rejecting sovereignty.
Krasner identifies four types of sovereignty: Cohen writes that sovereignty in the “clas-
domestic sovereignty, Westphalian sover- sic, absolutist (predatory) sense remains alive
eignty, international legal sovereignty, and and well, but only for very powerful states—
interdependence sovereignty. These can be including those controlling global govern-
grouped together as a “family resemblance” ance institutions .  .  . The direction of the
concept along Wittgensteinian lines: sov- new world order is, in other words, toward
ereignty may be understood as a basket or hierarchy not sovereign equality, and the
bundle of properties. As Fowler and Bunck appropriate concepts are not cosmopolitan
explain, “while every state has a basket, the constitutionalism but ‘grossraum,’ regional
contents are by no means the same” (Fowler hegemony, neo-imperialism, or empire”
and Bunck, 1995, 70, see Krasner, 1999, (Cohen, 2012, 4). In other words, one should
220). The basket or bundle approach to sov- note that the concept of sovereignty is used
ereignty is grounded in an empirical method (and criticized) for ideological purposes.
that begins with facts and works toward gen- Rich and powerful states may argue that
eralizations. It does not start from an a priori weak states lack sovereign protection against
or absolute notion of sovereignty. The a pri- foreign intervention in our post-sovereignty
ori notion of sovereignty as the ultimate or era, but the rich and powerful states would
supreme source is most properly defended by protest if a weaker state were to invade and
those who adopt a less empirical approach to violate their own sovereignty.
political theory. Despite these problems, the concept of
Some theorists argue that sovereignty is a sovereignty continues to be employed. We’ve
dirty word—imposed by those in power and already noted that the concept of sovereignty
grounded in ideological claims—that ought may be either a descriptive or a normative
to be discarded as we move in the direction concept. Sovereignty may also be understood
of international institutions and cosmopoli- as either a concern of domestic hierarchy
tan political theory. Henkin writes of sov- and legitimacy or a matter of external rela-
ereignty: “Its birth is illegitimate, and it has tions among states. This distinction is con-
not aged well. The meaning of ‘sovereignty’ nected to the distinction between domestic
is confused and its uses are various, some and comparative political theory and inter-
of them unworthy, some even destructive of national relations theory. Sovereignty must
human values” (Henkin, 1999, 1). Cohen be understood in its relation to different
explains, “it is alleged that the concept of types of political/legal theory: positive law,
sovereignty is useless as an epistemological natural law, and contractual or constitutional
tool for understanding the contemporary theory. Finally, sovereignty points toward the
world and that it is normatively pernicious” ontological problem of limits and borders. A
(Cohen, 2012, 2). This allegation is made serious philosophical question of sovereignty
from the standpoint of cosmopolitan politi- remains: whether the sovereign is subject to
cal theory, which wants to reconceive the glo- the law or outside of the law. The idea that
bal political scene in a way that looks beyond sovereign power is subject to the law is typi-
the limits of sovereign states as traditionally cal of constitutional regimes and natural law
understood. But Cohen argues that we must accounts (whether liberal or otherwise) and

41
Andrew Fiala

an emphasis on positive law, while the idea of arms or at the ballot box. The theory of
that sovereign power lies outside the law is “legal positivism” in the philosophy of law
associated with dictatorships and with what provides one approach to a merely descrip-
is called legal voluntarism. This issue has prac- tive account of sovereignty. The great legal
tical implications in the era of torture, extra- positivist Austin, for example, maintains that
judicial rendition, and ubiquitous surveillance. the concept of law can be defined in terms
Does the sovereign have the right to violate of the commands of a sovereign, which are
the law (including the moral law) to ensure backed up by appropriate sanctions. The
the stability and continuity of the state? sovereign is the source of the commands of
Sovereignty also delimits geographic law, which include commands of punishment
regions, creating territories defined by bor- for disobedience. Austin further maintains
ders. But the ontological and legal status of that there can only be one sovereign—as the
those borders are themselves subject to philo- idea that there is a limitation on sovereignty
sophical skepticism: are they merely conven- points toward a regress of authorities. This
tional or does geography and ethnic identity regress must stop at some point, at which we
have a deeper source in some transcendent then find the sovereign power or supreme
political reality? This question points toward authority. As Austin puts it, “supreme power
issues related to transnational labor and cap- limited by positive law is a flat contradic-
ital markets, the problem of immigration and tion in terms” (Austin, 1873, 270). Within
citizenship, and emerging trans-border issues the scope of positive law, the sovereign is the
concerning the environment. Is a global source of command to which (or to whom)
sovereign need to resolve our global issues? obedience is required by law. Said differently,
Ophuls once suggested a dilemma: either a from the standpoint of positive law and
global state or environmental collapse—as descriptive political science, the sovereign
he put it “Leviathan or Oblivion” (Ophuls, is the source of de facto habitual obedience.
1973). Will our ideological and metaphysi- As Austin concludes, “In respect of positive
cal commitment to sovereign states leave us law, a sovereign political government which
unable to solve global issues? Or will we find is established or present, is neither lawful or
a way to resolve these problems within the unlawful: in respect of positive law, it is nei-
current system of diffused sovereignty? ther rightful nor wrongful, it is neither just or
Methodological issues regarding the study unjust. Or (changing the expression) a sover-
of sovereignty remain unresolved. Ought we eign political government which is established
take sovereignty as a given fact of empiri- or present, is neither legal or illegal” (Austin,
cal political theory? Should we appeal to 1873, 336). Austin’s account of positive law
a normative theory that transcends politi- focuses on the fact of the obedience-author-
cal fact? Can we imagine alternatives and ity structure, without inquiring into the nor-
a standpoint from which to critique such mative question of whether obedience ought
a central concept? At the level of empirical to be given or whether sovereignty is legiti-
description, the idea of sovereignty may be mate or justified. Related to this is the more
used to describe who or what has effective nuanced legal positivism of Hart, who notes
control over a territory. From the descriptive that laws constitute their own authority. Hart
standpoint, it does not matter how power defines sovereignty in terms of the vertical
and control are achieved—whether by force structure of command and obedience. The

42
SOVEREIGNTY

people must obey the sovereign authority, While such a positivist approach to sover-
but the sovereign authority owes obedience eignty is useful in its own way, one wonders
to no other. However, Hart argues that this whether it allows for any critical space from
is an extremely simplistic image of the law which to criticize norms or structures of sov-
(Hart, 2012). Hart notes that legal systems ereignty. Hayek’s critique of positive law is rel-
persist through time—beyond the lives of evant here. Hayek argued that legal positivists
individual law-givers and their subjects. One had no way to avoid the sorts of transforma-
explanation of this is that obedience (and the tions of law that occurred, for example, in Nazi
related notion of compulsion) is inadequate Germany: if law is entirely a matter of human
to describe the way that persons accept the creation or arbitrary assertion of sovereign
legal system (we mostly accept it as a habit power, there is no way to criticize a totalitar-
or custom, e.g. taken implicitly without ian legal system. While Hayek does not suggest
any explicit notion of “acceptance”—the a simplistic return to traditional natural law
sovereign is thus the one who is customar- accounts, he does see some value in the idea
ily deferred to). Furthermore, Hart explains that law is not simply created, but also found
that the idea of a sovereign as a single person (Hayek, 1960/2011). Hayek’s approach empha-
who resides outside of the legal framework sizes the fact that the rule of law arises spon-
(as found, e.g. in Hobbes or Schmitt) is mis- taneously out of orderly interactions among
leading and in some cases false—as in the people. But unlike natural law theorists, Hayek
case of democratic governments with a con- does not appeal to an external law that pro-
stitutional division of power (Hart’s exam- vides a critique of positive or constructed laws.
ples are the United States and Australia). Rather, Hayek decentralizes sovereignty as the
As Waldron notes, Hart “knocked the stuff- spontaneous creation of free people involved in
ing out of the presupposition of absolute free exchange. Unfortunately, this still leaves us
Hobbesian sovereignty” (Waldron, 2008, with the challenge of the sovereignty of natural
82). Sovereignty after Hart—from a legal law and conscience. It is not clear how a legal
positivist point of view—is merely a notion positivist such as Hart or a libertarian critic
describing the status of authoritative norms such as Hayek would deal with the challenges
within a social system along with the recog- of the anarchists and individualists with whom
nition that the social structure and its norms we began—those who claim a right to violate
are part of a complex language game or form the law based upon a claim grounded in natu-
of life (to make Wittgensteinian themes in ral law and the sovereignty of conscience.
Hart’s work explicit here) which is not eas-
ily reduced to the will of a single person or
to a singular command-obedience hierarchy
(see Azmanova, 2012). As Shapiro explains, CONCLUSION
Hart’s idea is not that the sovereign makes
the rules but that “the rules make the sover- Thousands of years of political philosophy
eign” (Shapiro, 2009, 2011). Moreover, Hart held that there was a law-giver behind the
emphasizes the normative power of law (as law and a normative structure that provided
opposed to habits, customs, etc.) in the social a proper grounding for the law (in the idea
recognition of certain institutions, standards, of the Good, in God’s will, in the notion
and principles as legally binding. of justice or natural law, or in the social

43
Andrew Fiala

contract, etc.). But in our postmodern era, Badescu, C. G. (2009), “The Responsibility
the normative and metaphysical ground to Protect: Embracing Sovereignty and
of the law is not clear. We may be moving Human Rights,” in N. Shawki and M.
into an era in which Westphalian political Cox (eds), Negotiating Sovereignty and
sovereignty has lost its luster. Political phi- Human Rights. Burlington, VT: Ashgate
losophers have directed our attention to the Publishing.
queer, questionable, and quaint ideas related Beaulac, S. (2004), The Power of Language
to the notion of sovereignty. But the con- in the Making of International Law.
cept remains important—for understanding Leiden, The Netherlands: Martinus-
international relations, for understanding Nijhoff.
domestic power structures, and for thinking Bloom, A. (1991), “Interpretive Essay,” in
about the value of individual conscience in The Republic of Plato, 2nd edn, trans. A.
opposition to political power. Given con- Bloom. New York: Basic Books.
temporary movements that point in rival Bluntschi, J. C. (1892), The Theory of the
directions—toward centralized hierarchies State, 2nd edn. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
and toward decentralized individualism—it Bodin, J. (1992), On Sovereignty.
is clear that we are in the middle of a tran- Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
sition that will result in a serious transfor- Cohen, J. L. (2012), Globalization and
mation of our understanding of sovereignty. Sovereignty: Rethinking Legality,
Future work in political philosophy must Legitimacy, and Constitutionalism.
consider and criticize the metaphysical, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
ontological, and normative status of the Derrida, J. (2011), The Beast and the
concept of sovereignty. Sovereign. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Donnelly, J. (2003), University Human
Rights in Theory and Practice. Ithaca,
WORKS CITED NY: Cornell University Press.
Dworkin, R. (2002), Sovereign Virtue.
Agamben, G. (1998), Homo Sacer: Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Sovereign Power and Bare Life. Stanford, Press.
CA: Stanford University Press. Elshtain, J. B. (2008), Sovereignty: God,
Arendt, H. (2005), The Promise of Politics. State, and Self. New York: Basic Books
New York: Random House. Figgis, J. (1914), The Divine Right of
— (2006), On Revolution. New York: Kings, 2nd edn. Cambridge: Cambridge
Penguin Books. University Press.
Austin, J. (1873), Lectures On Fowler, M. R. and Bunck, J. M. (1995), Law,
Jurisprudence: The Philosophy of Positive Power, and the Sovereign State. University
Law. London: John Murray. Park, PA: Penn State Press.
Azmanova, A. (2012), The Scandal of Fukuyama, F. (2004), State-Building:
Reason: A Critical Theory of Political Governance and World-Order in the 21st
Judgment. New York: Columbia Century. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University
University Press. Press.

44
SOVEREIGNTY

Goldman, E. (1960), “Anarchism,” in E. Philpot, D. (1996), “On the Cusp of


Goldman (ed.), Anarchism and Other Sovereignty: Lessons from the Sixteenth
Essays. New York: Dover. Century,” in L. E. Lugo (ed.), Sovereignty
Hart, H. L. A. (2012), The Concept of Law, at the Crossroads? Morality and
3rd edn. Oxford: Oxford University Press. International Politics in the Post-Cold
Hayek, F. (1960/2011), The Constitution War Era. Lanham, MD: Rowman &
of Liberty, Definitive edn. Chicago: Littlefield.
University of Chicago. — (2011), “Sovereignty,” in G. Klosko (ed.),
Henkin, L. (1999), “That ‘S’ Word: The Oxford Handbook of the History
Sovereignty, and Globalization, and of Political Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford
Human Rights, Et Cetera,” Fordham University Press.
University Law Review, 68, 1–14. Rawls, J. (1971), A Theory of Justice.
Hoffman, J. (1998), Sovereignty. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Minneapolis, MN: University of Press.
Minnesota Press. Schmitt, C. (1985), Political Theology.
ICISS (2001), Report of the International Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Commission on Intervention and State — (2008), The Leviathan in the State
Sovereignty (http://responsibilitytoprotect. Theory of Thomas Hobbes: Meaning and
org/ICISS%20Report.pdf. Failure of a Political Symbol. Chicago:
Jackson, R. (2007), Sovereignty: The University of Chicago Press.
Evolution of an Idea. Cambridge: Polity Shapiro, S. J. (2009), “What is the Rule of
Press. Recognition (and Does it Exist)?” in M.
Jongeneel, J. A. B. (2009), Jesus Christ in D. Adler and K. E. Himma (eds), The Rule
World History. Frankfurt: Peter Lang. of Recognition and the U.S. Constitution.
Krasner, S. D. (1999), Sovereignty: Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Organized Hypocrisy. Princeton, NJ: — (2011), Legality. Cambridge, MA:
Princeton University Press. Harvard University Press.
Locke, J. (1764), First Treatise of Vanberg, V. J. (2007), “Democracy,
Government in Two Treatises of Citizen Sovereignty, and Constitutional
Government, T. Hollis (ed.), London: Economics,” in J. C. Pardo and P.
A. Millar et al.; accessed from http://oll. Schwartz (eds), Public Choice and the
libertyfund.org/title/222. Challenges of Democracy. Northampton,
Machan, T. R. (2008), “Reconciling MA: Edward Elgard Publishing.
Anarchism and Minarchism,” in R. T. Waldron, J. (2008), “Hart and the Principles
Long and T. R. Machan (eds), Anarchism/ of Legality,” in M. Kramer, C. Grant, B.
Minarchism. Burlington, VT: Ashgate Colburn, and A. Hatzistavrou (eds), The
Publishing. Legacy of H.L.A. Hart: Legal, Political,
Nozick, R. (1974), Anarchy, State, Utopia. and Moral Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford
New York: Basic Books. University Press.
Ophuls, W. (1973), “Leviathan or Oblivion,” Walzer, M. (1970), Obligations: Essays
in H. Daly (ed.), Toward a Steady State on Disobedience, War, and Citizenship.
Economy. San Francisco: W.H. Freeman. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

45
3
COSMOPOLITANISM
Gillian Brock

INTRODUCTION the points of tension between cosmopolitans


and those resistant to such approaches, we
Early cosmopolitans, such as the Stoics, need to cover more ground. One fear about
proclaimed that they were “citizens of the cosmopolitanism is that it might give too
world” (Kleingeld, 2006). These cosmopoli- little weight to (or possibly even ignore)
tans hoped to reject several dominant eth- people’s important affiliations and identi-
nocentric ideas prevalent at the time and to ties, especially those that stem from their
proclaim instead that they were members of membership in states. This leads to a set of
a community of human beings bigger than concerns that have attracted much attention
one’s city of origin, with important responsi- which we might phrase in terms of the fol-
bilities to others in a wider and larger human lowing set of questions: in endorsing global
community. Drawing on these ideas of world obligations must we also thereby reject spe-
citizenship, contemporary cosmopolitans cial obligations to those in our state? How,
also encourage us not to let local obliga- if at all, does membership in states matter to
tions crowd out responsibilities to distant our obligations to assist non-compatriots? Is
others. Cosmopolitans highlight the respon- partiality toward compatriots justified in a
sibilities we have to those whom we do not world filled with the more pressing needs of
know, but whose lives should be of concern non-compatriots? Is there any proper scope
to us. Contemporary cosmopolitans typi- for patriotic concern? Does respecting politi-
cally emphasize that every person has global cal self-determination conflict with commit-
stature as the ultimate unit of moral concern ments to global justice?
and is therefore entitled to equal respect and In this chapter, we survey some cur-
consideration no matter what her citizenship rent debates among cosmopolitans and
status or other affiliations happen to be.1 their critics. We begin in the next sec-
But if cosmopolitanism requires us to rec- tion, “Cosmopolitanism: Two Important
ognize everyone’s equal moral worth and Distinctions,” outlining some common dis-
show all equal respect, surely all normatively tinctions typically drawn among kinds of
defensible views must be cosmopolitan in cosmopolitanisms, before canvassing some of
flavor, someone might wonder. Is cosmopoli- the diverse varieties of cosmopolitan justice in
tanism trivially true, then? In order to locate the section “What Does Cosmopolitan Justice

47
Gillian Brock

Require?” The section “Are Compatriots one about responsibility. As a thesis about
Special?” explores the grounds on which identity, being a cosmopolitan indicates that
compatriots might be thought to be special one is a person who is influenced by various
and therefore deserving of considerably more cultures. Cosmopolitanism as a thesis about
weight in our responsibilities to one another. identity also maintains that belonging to a
We then explore some common concerns particular culture is not an essential ingredi-
about cosmopolitanism—such as whether ent for personal identity or living a flourish-
cosmopolitan commitments are necessarily ing life: one can select elements from diverse
in tension with other affiliations people typi- cultures, or reject all in favor of noncultural
cally have (the section “Must Cosmopolitans options that are perceived as yet more impor-
Reject Any Form of Partiality?”) and how we tant to particular people in living a flourish-
should deal with issues concerning a perceived ing life, as Jeremy Waldron (1992) maintains.
lack of authority in the global domain (the Cosmopolitanism as a thesis about respon-
section “Is the Matter of Legitimate Authority sibility generates much debate, as discussed
in the Global Domain Problematic?”). In later. Roughly, the idea is that as a cosmopoli-
the section “Cosmopolitanism in the Real tan, one should appreciate that one is a mem-
World,” we look briefly at how the concern ber of a global community of human beings.
with feasibility of normative ideals has led As such, one has responsibilities to other
some to take up the challenge of devising members of the global community. As Martha
public policy that is cosmopolitan in outlook Nussbaum elaborates, one owes allegiance
before offering some concluding remarks on “to the worldwide community of human
future directions in these debates. In a vari- beings” and this affiliation should constitute
ety of ways, we come to appreciate that the a primary allegiance (Nussbaum, 1996, 4).
topics dealt with by cosmopolitans and their We discuss responsibility cosmopolitanism in
critics encompasses a broad range of issues of more detail in several sections later.
central concern to political philosophers.
2. Moral and institutional cosmopolitanism

The core idea of moral cosmopolitanism is


COSMOPOLITANISM: TWO a commitment to everyone’s equal moral
IMPORTANT DISTINCTIONS worth and equal consideration of their inter-
ests. Thomas Pogge has an influential and
We begin by reviewing some of the key dis- widely cited synopsis of the key ideas, as he
tinctions widely in use in the literature. sees them:

1. Identity and responsibility cosmopolit­anism Three elements are shared by all cosmo-
politan positions. First, individualism:
Being a cosmopolitan is most often character- the ultimate units of concern are human
beings, or persons—rather than, say, fam-
ized in terms of being a citizen of the world.
ily lines, tribes, ethnic, cultural, or reli-
This idea of being a citizen of the world cap-
gious communities, nations, or states. The
tures the two central aspects of cosmopoli- latter may be units of concern only indi-
tanism, as it is frequently understood today, rectly, in virtue of their individual mem-
namely it involves a thesis about identity and bers or citizens. Second, universality: the

48
COSMOPOLITANISM

status of ultimate unit of concern attaches possibilities for discharging cosmopolitan


to every living human being equally—not duties globally that would not amount to a
merely to some sub-set, such as men, world state (as discussed in the section “Is
aristocrats, Aryans, whites, or Muslims. the Matter of Legitimate Authority in the
Third, generality: this special status has
Global Domain Problematic?”).
global force. Persons are ultimate units of
concern for everyone—not only for their
compatriots, fellow religionists, or such
like (Pogge, 1992, 48).
WHAT DOES COSMOPOLITAN
JUSTICE REQUIRE?
Considerable debate surrounds what the
cosmopolitan commitment requires. Indeed, Accounts of justice that characterize themselves
cosmopolitanism’s force is often best appre- as cosmopolitan can originate from a number
ciated by considering what it rules out. For of theoretical perspectives. There are, after all,
instance, it rules out positions that attach no many different conceptions of how to treat peo-
moral value to some people, or weights the ple equally especially with respect to issues of
moral value some people have differentially distributive justice, and this is often reflected in
according to their race, ethnicity, or nation- these different accounts. Cosmopolitan justice
ality. Furthermore, assigning ultimate rather could be argued for along various lines, includ-
than derivative value to collective entities ing: utilitarian (prominently, Singer, 1972);
such as nations or states is prohibited. If such rights-based accounts (Shue, 1980, Jones,
groups matter, they matter because of their 1999, Caney, 2005, Pogge, 2008); Kantian
importance to individual human persons (O’Neill, 2000); Aristotelian or capabilities-
rather than because they have some inde- based (Nussbaum, 2000, 2006); contractarian
pendent, ultimate (say, ontological) value. (Beitz, 1979, Pogge, 1989, Moellendorf, 2002,
A common misconception is that cosmo- Brock, 2009); and sometimes using more than
politanism requires a world state or govern- one approach (Pogge, 1989, 2002, Beitz, 1979,
ment. To avoid this mistake, a distinction is 2009).
often drawn between moral and institutional There are several different ways of arguing
cosmopolitanism. Institutional cosmopoli- for cosmopolitan justice widely used in the
tans maintain that fairly deep institutional literature. One common divide in accounts
changes are needed to the global system in of cosmopolitan justice exists between those
order to realize cosmopolitan commitments who argue for “humanist” and “associativ-
adequately and such transformations would ist” or “relational” approaches. Humanists,
yield a world state. Moral cosmopolitans such as Simon Caney, believe that our duties
need not endorse that view, in fact many are of justice track our shared humanity. We have
against radical institutional transformations. duties of justice toward all human beings in
Such theorists maintain that our cosmopolitan virtue of our humanity. Associativists or rela-
commitments (such as protecting everyone’s tional theorists, by contrast, believe duties of
basic human rights or ensuring everyone’s justice track co-membership in some associa-
capabilities are met to the required thresh- tion, such as political or economic association.
old) can be effectively discharged, via several Unless we are members of some important
suitable arrangements. There are various association, we have no justice duties toward

49
Gillian Brock

such persons. On such accounts, if we hap- that Rawls believes should govern relations
pen to come across persons existing on some among peoples in the international domain
distant planet, with whom we have no prior is that we should respect each people as free
interactions, we could not have any duties and equal. Goods such as self-determination
of justice toward such people (though there and political autonomy are therefore promi-
might be some more minimal humanitar- nent in this account. In respecting equality
ian obligations that we have toward them). among peoples (rather than individual per-
Associativists, such as Darrel Moellendorf, sons), liberals will need to adopt a foreign
tend to emphasize that all persons are part policy that tolerates much diversity, especially
of at least one relevant association namely a in allowing non-liberal peoples to be admit-
global economic association and this is espe- ted as full and equal members of the interna-
cially salient in our current era of economic tional community of states in good standing.
globalization. Rawls believes that we have a duty “to assist
Cosmopolitan approaches to justice are burdened societies to become full members of
often contrasted with “statist” accounts.2 the Society of Peoples and to be able to deter-
For statists, states are an important factor mine the path of their own future for them-
in determining our duties of justice and they selves” (1999, 118) but this duty should not
frequently maintain that the kinds of duties take the form of a Global Difference Principle
we have to fellow members of our state as such a principle would not have a target or
are different from and typically stronger a cutoff point, and these targets and cutoffs
than the duties we have to nonmembers. are provided by his account which aims at all
Cosmopolitans tend to place individuals people’s political autonomy.
front and center of their theorizing about Cosmopolitans have expressed many
justice, though there might well be deriva- criticisms of these views. For instance, they
tive implications concerning duties for states claim that Rawls ignores both the extent to
that flow from their analyses (Moellendorf, which unfavorable conditions may result
2009). Statists, however, give the fact of from factors external to the society and that
membership in a state a certain kind of pri- there are all sorts of morally relevant con-
macy of standing which cosmopolitans do nections between states, notably that they
not. There is a prominent debate between are situated in a global economic order that
John Rawls and his critics that nicely fol- perpetuates the interests of wealthy devel-
lows these tracks and will provide a good oped states with little regard for the interests
illustration of the differences between the of poor, developing ones. Such facts mean
two approaches. Furthermore, this debate that there is a context of global cooperation
has been enormously influential in current such that distribution according to a Global
debates on cosmopolitan justice, so we dis- Difference Principle is appropriate (Beitz,
cuss this very briefly next. 1979, Moellendorf, 2002).
In Rawls’s theory of justice for the inter- Thomas Pogge, arguably the most promi-
national realm, our membership in a “peo- nent contemporary cosmopolitan, has done
ple” makes for a very different justice much to advance arguments which show our
context, when compared with the views involvement in perpetuating poverty in devel-
Rawls famously argues for in A Theory of oping countries (1994, 2001, 2002, 2008,
Justice (1971). One of the core principles inter alia). The international borrowing

50
COSMOPOLITANISM

privilege and the international resource ARE COMPATRIOTS SPECIAL?


privilege provide good examples. Any group
that exercises effective power in a state is Even the most staunch defenders of views
recognized internationally as the legitimate which advocate favoring the interests of
government of that territory, and the interna- compatriots do not believe that non-compa-
tional community is not concerned with how triots count for nothing. If one came across
the group came to power or what it does a small child drowning in a shallow pond in
with that power. Oppressive governments a so-called easy rescue case, one would have
may borrow freely on behalf of the country a responsibility to perform the life-saving
(the international borrowing privilege) or act of pulling the child to safety, no matter
dispose of its natural resources (the interna- whether the child were a compatriot or not
tional resource privilege) and these actions (Singer, 1972). We have some basic (even pos-
are legally recognized internationally. These itive) duties to everyone, irrespective of their
two privileges can have disastrous implica- citizenship status. Everyone would concede
tions for the prosperity of poor countries this much, at least in the abstract. However,
(for instance) because these privileges pro- it seems equally clear, to some at least, that
vide incentives for coup attempts, they often in certain kinds of matters we may defensi-
influence what sorts of people are motivated bly favor the interests of our compatriots,
to seek power, they facilitate oppressive gov- typically in decisions concerning the distri-
ernments being able to stay in office, and, bution of resources, such as the distribution
should more democratic governments get of state benefits with respect to health care
to be in power, they are saddled with the or education (Tamir, 1993, Miller, 1995).
debts incurred by their oppressive predeces- In defense of such decisions, it is frequently
sors, thus draining the country of resources claimed that the connections between com-
needed to firm up new democracies. Local patriots are more substantial and of the right
governments have little incentive to attend to kind to generate stronger obligations of jus-
the needs of the poor, since their being able to tice (R. Miller, 1998, Hurka, 1997, Blake,
continue in power depends more on the local 2002). For instance, because we cooperate in
elite, foreign governments, and corporations. a shared institutional order from which we
Because foreigners benefit so greatly from the derive benefits or which involves significant
international resource privilege, they have an coercion, we owe compatriots more concern.
incentive to refrain from challenging the situ- Some theorists have argued that positions
ation (or even to support oppressive govern- such as compatriot favoritism can be justi-
ments). For these sorts of reasons, the current fied in virtue of the special relations in which
world order largely reflects the interests of we stand to fellow citizens as well as the spe-
wealthy and powerful states. Those in afflu- cial projects we undertake together, such as
ent developed countries have a responsibil- governing ourselves and building a common
ity to stop imposing this unjust global order life together (Tamir, 1993, D. Miller, 1995, R.
and to make various institutional reforms to Miller, 1998).
better align the global order with justice. A What relevance does co-membership in
number of institutions should be reformed a state have to our obligations and can it
including the international resource and bor- justify having more substantial responsibili-
rowing privileges (Pogge, 2008).3 ties to those with whom we share a state?

51
Gillian Brock

According to several prominent theorists, Another attempt to justify distinguishing


membership in particular states can be rel- between duties to compatriots and duties to
evant to what we owe one another. One cur- non-compatriots proceeds from an aware-
rent debate rages between those who believe ness that social cooperation grounds special
that full egalitarian justice applies within the duties (Freeman, 2006, Sangiovanni, 2007).
state but not outside it, and those who believe A democratic society is one in which there
that the state does not and cannot make this is fair social cooperation and in which fair
kind of difference to one’s commitment to social cooperation is understood in terms of
egalitarian distributive justice. There are sev- the idea that the arrangements that govern
eral forms of the argument. Here I outline citizens’ lives should be ones that they can
two variants of this position. reasonably endorse. Members of a state owe
One kind emphasizes the fact that states egalitarian duties of justice to one another
are legally able to coerce, whereas this is pur- because each member plays a part in uphold-
portedly not the case in the global sphere, and ing and sustaining the collective goods of
so the lack of a global legal coercive author- the society, such as maintaining a stable sys-
ity rules out the need for global equality (R. tem of property rights or doing their part to
Miller, 1998, Blake, 2002). The idea here is ensure society’s security. Reasonably endors-
that legal coercion, if it is to be legitimate, able social arrangements do not create mor-
must be justifiable to those whose autonomy ally arbitrary social inequalities. Since there
would be restricted. Legal coercion would be is no scheme of global social cooperation
justifiable if no arbitrary inequalities were of the same type or scale as a state, there is
permissible in the society and this is the idea no similar requirement at the global level.
central to traditional egalitarian conceptions Several cosmopolitans have challenged the
of distributive justice. This form of argument view that there is no set of global institutions
has been criticized from several directions. based on social cooperation (Beitz, 1979,
For example, one strategy is to challenge the Moellendorf, 2002). Others contest the nor-
idea that coercion is necessary for ground- mative view that duties of egalitarian justice
ing a concern with egalitarian distributive arise only when there is social cooperation,
justice, and contends that there are other rea- maintaining instead that justice can require
sons to care about equality in the absence of the very establishment of such institutions of
coercion. Another line of attack emphasizes social cooperation (Abizadeh, 2007, Caney,
that even if we agree that coercion triggers 2008). Sufficient interaction among agents
egalitarian duties of justice, in fact coercion may obligate them to ensure that their inter-
is pervasive at the global level if we con- actions proceed on fair terms, and this might
sider the scope of international law and the require establishing institutional arrange-
ways in which powerful institutions (such ments that can secure or protect such fair
as the WTO, the IMF, and the World Bank) terms.
impose policies (such as the terms of trade) At any rate, those who defend claims that
on weaker parties, as a condition of belong- our duties to co-members are more exten-
ing to the organization or being able to ben- sive than those to others with whom we do
efit from it. Thus the necessary condition for not share membership in a state point to
egalitarian duties of justice is met (Cohen several key features in attempting to justify
and Sabel, 2006, Abizadeh, 2007). their position. The fact that we are involved

52
COSMOPOLITANISM

in mutually beneficial cooperation or a by the luck egalitarian view. This leaves us


coercive institutional scheme seems very with a number of questions:
important to many statists. Others draw
attention to features such as shared national • Should “the moral arbitrariness of birth-
identity, shared history, or shared efforts in place” be a factor in determining the
creating a community or set of institutions nature of our duties to one another?
which instantiates much value. In elaborat- Alternatively,
• Should we take as our starting point
ing on the kind of importance these features
important facts about situatedness in par-
should have, such theorists might point to
ticular societies that many of us seem to
the independent value of democracy, self- care about a great deal, albeit that this is
determination, or living a life that gives somewhat arbitrary from the moral point
shared expression to important aspects of of view?
one’s identity. Some theorists (e.g. Tamir, • What weight should membership in states
1993, D. Miller, 2007)  argue that national have and is such weight necessarily in ten-
membership can be very important to peo- sion with cosmopolitanism?
ple and, moreover, people are entitled to • Is there a way to navigate between duties
national self-determination. We therefore to those within states and those beyond
need to make space in any account of our them, so we can accommodate the force
of each?
obligations to one another for respecting
nations and the political autonomy they
need.
Cosmopolitans often take as their point MUST COSMOPOLITANS REJECT ANY
of departure a so-called luck egalitarian FORM OF PARTIALITY?
intuition. Consider how it is a matter of luck
whether one is born into an affluent, devel- Critics of cosmopolitanism often maintain
oped country or a poor, developing nation. that cosmopolitans cannot accommodate
Yet where one happens to have been born special attachments and commitments that
tends to have such an important bearing on fill most ordinary human beings’ lives with
how one’s life will go. The current distribu- value and meaning. It is commonly thought
tion of global wealth and opportunities does that cosmopolitans must reject attachments
not track persons’ choices and efforts, but to those in local or particular communities
rather is greatly influenced and distorted by in favor of an ideal of impartial justice that
luck. What is thought to be objectionable the individual must apply directly to all, no
here is that existing social and political insti- matter where they are situated on the globe.
tutions have converted contingent brute facts But this is not a position advocated by many
about people’s lives into significant social cosmopolitans.4 Indeed, most contemporary
disadvantages for some and advantages for cosmopolitans recognize that for many peo-
others. Persons as moral equals can demand ple, some of their most meaningful attach-
that any common order that they impose on ments in life derive from their allegiances to
one another start from a default assump- particular communities, be they national,
tion of equality and departures from this be ethnic, religious, or cultural. Their accounts
justified to those who stand to be adversely often seek to define the legitimate scope for
affected. Many cosmopolitans are persuaded such partiality, by situating these attachments

53
Gillian Brock

in a context which clarifies our obliga- indeed compatible with having many other
tions to one another. Cosmopolitan justice particular commitments and attachments,
provides the basic framework or structure including attachments to compatriots and
and thereby the constraints within which commitments to co-nationals.
legitimate patriotism may operate (see, for
instance, Tan, 2004, 2005). Cosmopolitan
principles should govern the global institu-
tions, such that these treat people as equals IS THE MATTER OF LEGITIMATE
in their entitlements (regardless of nation- AUTHORITY IN THE GLOBAL
ality and power, say). However, once the DOMAIN PROBLEMATIC?
background global institutional structure is
just, persons may defensibly favor the inter- There are some who are skeptical of the
ests of their compatriots (or co-nationals, or cosmopolitan idea of obligations of justice
members of other more particular groups), that extend globally, at least given our cur-
so long as such partiality does not conflict rent circumstances. Grounds for such skep-
with their other obligations, for instance, to ticism include the fact that since there is no
support global institutions. So cosmopolitan way to enforce obligations of justice at the
principles should govern the global institu- global level, there can be no such obligations
tions, but need not directly regulate what (Nagel, 2005). Another concern revolves
choices people may make within the rules around fears that often accompany undesir-
of the institutions. One of the strengths of able results which can ensue when there is a
Tan’s view (e.g. 2004)  is that even though concentration of power (Kukathas, 2006).
cosmopolitan justice provides the justifica- Underlying these concerns is an assumption
tion for the limits of partiality toward group that obligations concerning cosmopolitan jus-
members, the value of those attachments is tice require a world state, and since we have
not reduced to cosmopolitan considerations, reason to fear the potential for world gov-
which is arguably a flaw with other attempts ernment to lead to oppressive consequences,
(e.g. Nussbaum, 1996). we have reasons to fear cosmopolitanism.
Cosmopolitanism is essentially committed While some cosmopolitans do advocate for a
to these two central ideas: world state (Falk and Strauss, 2001, Cabrera,
2004, 2011, Deudney, 2007, Lu, 2008),
1. The equal moral worth of all individuals, many (probably the vast majority) reject the
no matter what borders separate them assumption that a world state is necessary or
from one another. desirable and differentiate between global
2. The idea that there are some obligations government and global governance (Held,
that are binding on all of us, no matter
1995, Caney, 2005, Nussbaum, 2006, Brock,
where we are situated.
2009). Although we may need some ways to
coordinate management of our transnational
Acknowledging these two claims leaves affairs, this need not amount to world gov-
plenty of room to endorse additional obliga- ernment. Supra-state organizations need not
tions that derive from more particular com- replace state-level ones, such as currently
mitments. So, we see that cosmopolitanism is exists with the European Union or the United

54
COSMOPOLITANISM

Nations. In these cases, transnational institu- as those who advocate education for world
tions complement rather than replace states. citizenship might maintain (e.g. Nussbaum,
Different models are available for thinking 1996).5
through a “post-sovereign” political world
order, which incorporate scope for state-
level institutions, as well as ones which are
sub-state and supra-state level (Pogge, 1992, COSMOPOLITANISM IN THE
Held, 1995). REAL WORLD
A frequently raised issue concerns how
divided authority and sovereignty arrange- Increasingly, philosophers have turned their
ments might work in practice. In fact, we attention to making recommendations for
have examples of divided and delegated improvements in global policies, arrange-
authority that work reasonably well in prac- ments, and institutions often, in the process,
tice. States in a federation (such as in the advocating for important changes. I have
United States), local and regional authorities already noted some of the proposals Pogge
within a state, and the European Union, all has made concerning reforms to interna-
involve divided authority and often function tional borrowing and resource privileges
effectively on a day-to-day basis. Forms of in the section “What Does Cosmopolitan
global governance can be diffuse and over- Justice Require?” Barry and Reddy’s work
lapping, so long as they have clear sites of (2008) also provides a noteworthy attempt
accountability. Indeed, whether we like it to outline detailed proposals for how Just
or not, we already have a system of global Linkage arrangements can promote fair
governance that is just like this, given all trade, creating desirable trading opportuni-
the international bodies that have authority ties for those who offer improved employ-
over various domains that govern our lives ment conditions. Several others have detailed
(such as the United Nations, World Trade proposals concerning institutional reforms,
Organization, World Health Organization, for instance to promote global health (Pogge,
or World Bank). Cosmopolitans might 2011) or improved taxation and accounting
instead focus their arguments on how to arrangements (Pogge, 2008, Brock, 2009,
reform this system to make it more respon- Moellendorf, 2009).
sive to the ideals of moral equality or other In many ways, the widespread and grow-
goals of global justice. As Thomas Nagel ing commitment to the importance of human
(2005) notes, we have transitioned to more rights in regulating our international affairs
just arrangements in the past by demanding is something of a cosmopolitan achievement
that the existing concentration of power be in the struggle for global justice. The fact
exercised more justly, that is, by working on that we have documents that clearly specify
what is already there. It is likely that there the entitlements that all human beings have
will be a similar path to global justice. People is quite remarkable, given the diversity of
might be motivated to demand more legiti- worldviews and perspectives represented
macy of the institutions that dominate their among the world’s people. Furthermore,
lives if their sense of global solidarity, com- we have an international legal order that
passion, or empathy for others is increased, has certain commitments to uphold these

55
Gillian Brock

entitlements. All those states that are mem- • How, if at all, does equality matter at the
bers of the United Nations have signed up global level? What kinds of reforms to
to respecting human rights in at least certain our global and local institutions do cos-
contexts. The cosmopolitan idea that each mopolitan concerns require?
• Are these reforms feasible, even if norma-
person has equal moral worth and deserves
tively desirable?
some fundamental protections and entitle-
• What account of feasibility ought we to
ments is not just a theoretical position but embrace in discussing which cosmopoli-
has made some significant inroads in interna- tan proposals could feasibly be imple-
tional law and global policy making, though mented in our world?
this is not to deny that we still have far to go • What might the cosmopolitan recommend
before the cosmopolitan vision is adequately as just policy in specific domains such as
instantiated in the world. climate change, immigration, fair trade,
In each of the preceding sections, I have health care, taxation, and the like?
highlighted current points of tension in
debates and shown how one might navigate
a range of issues and challenges that are pre- These kinds of questions emphasize that
sented for cosmopolitanism. However, by much work remains for all normative theo-
offering possible ways cosmopolitans could rists concerned with justice in the global
resolve issues or respond to challenges, this domain and show how the cosmopolitan
should not mask the fact that all these matters position is central to much contemporary
are still the subject of lively debate. Indeed, work in political philosophy.
none of the debates raised here are settled.
Every aspect of cosmopolitanism treated
here is still the subject of critical engagement:
from the very ways in which one ought to Notes
define cosmopolitanism to what cosmopoli-
tan commitment entails (see for instance, The 1
For more on this convergence, see Gillian
Monist 94, no.4 and Brock, 2013). Brock and Harry Brighouse (eds), The Political
In addressing the main issues identified as Philosophy of Cosmopolitanism (Cambridge:
salient to various kinds of cosmopolitans and Cambridge University Press, 2005) and Gillian
Brock, “Cosmopolitanism Versus Non-
their critics, more work is needed on a range Cosmopolitanism: The State of Play,” The
of central questions, including: Monist, 94 (2011), 455–465.
2
A note about terminology might be in order
• How does membership in global and before we proceed. Those identified as statists
national associations influence our duties include quite a diverse variety of different posi-
to one another in the global context? tions including liberal nationalist, civic nation-
• To what extent are cosmopolitan and spe- alist, or other conventional statist accounts.
cial duties reconcilable? I use the term “statist” to include all of these
positions, since what they have in common
• What significance, if any, does the moral
is the view that membership in a sub-world
arbitrariness of birthplace have to community (such as a state, people, or nation)
accounts of global distributive justice? matters in determining our obligations to one
• Do forms of coercion matter to the nature another.
of our duties to one another and if they 3
In the space provided, I cannot possibly do
do, how and why does coercion matter? justice to all the complexities of Rawls’s

56
COSMOPOLITANISM

sophisticated account or that of his critics, Defenses, Reconceptualisations. Oxford:


but for some more detailed exposition, critical Oxford University Press.
discussion, and defense of the views, see Martin
Brock, G. and Brighouse, H. (eds)
and Reidy (2007), Samuel Freeman (2006),
David Reidy (2006), Moellendorf (2002), Tan (2005), The Political Philosophy
(2004), and Brock (2009). of Cosmopolitanism. Cambridge:
4
See, for instance, the essays in Brock and Cambridge University Press.
Brighouse (2005). Cabrera, L. (2004), Political Theory of
5
See, for instance, the Council for Education in
Global Justice: A Cosmopolitan Case for
World Citizenship at: http://www.cewc.org.
the World State. London: Routledge.
— (2011), “World Government: Renewed
Debate, Persistent Challenges,” European
Journal of International Relations, 16:
WORKS CITED 511–530.
Caney, S. (2005), Justice Beyond Borders: A
Abizadeh, A. (2007), “Cooperation, Global Political Theory. Oxford: Oxford
Pervasive Impact, and Coercion: On the University Press.
Scope (Not Site) of Distributive Justice,” — (2008), “Global Distributive Justice
Philosophy and Public Affairs, 35: and the State,” Political Studies, 57:
318–358. 487–518.
Barry, C. and S. Reddy (2008), International Cohen, J. and Sabel, C. (2006), “Extra
Trade and Labor Standards. New York: Republicam Nulla Justitia?” Philosophy
Columbia University Press. and Public Affairs, 34: 147–175.
Beitz, B. (1979), Political Theory and Deudney, D. (2007), Bounding Power:
International Relations. Princeton, NJ: Republican Security Theory from Polis
Princeton University Press. to the Global Village. Princeton, NJ:
— (2009), The Idea of Human Rights. Princeton University Press.
Oxford: Oxford University Press. Falk, R. and Strauss, A. (2001), “Toward
Blake, M. (2002), “Distributive Justice, Global Parliament (Citizen Input on
State Coercion, and Autonomy,” Globalization),” Foreign Affairs, 80:
Philosophy and Public Affairs, 30: 212–218.
257–296. Freeman, S. (2006), “The Law of Peoples,
— (2005), “International Justice,” Stanford Social Cooperation, Human Rights, and
Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http:// Distributive Justice,” Social Philosophy
plato.stanford.edu/entries/international- and Policy, 23: 29–68.
justice/. Held, D. (1995), Democracy and the
Brock, G. (2009), Global Justice: A Global Order: From the Modern State to
Cosmopolitan Account. Oxford: Oxford Cosmopolitan Governance. Stanford, CA:
University Press. Stanford University Press.
— (2011), “Cosmopolitanism Versus Non- Hurka, T. (1997), “The Justification of
Cosmopolitanism: The State of Play,” The National Partiality,” in R. McKim and
Monist, 94: 455–465. J. McMahan (eds), The Morality Of
— (ed.) (2013), Cosmopolitanism versus Nationalism. Oxford: Oxford University
Non-Cosmopolitanism: Critiques, Press, pp. 139–157.

57
Gillian Brock

Jones, C. (1999), Global Justice. Oxford: — (2006), Frontiers of Justice: Disability,


Oxford University Press. Nationality, Species Membership.
Kleingeld, P. (2006), “Cosmopolitanism,” Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, O’Neill, O. (2000), Bounds of Justice.
http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
international-justice/. Pogge, T. (1989), Realizing Rawls. Ithaca,
Kukathas, C. (2006), “The Mirage of NY: Cornell University Press.
Global Justice,” in E. Paul, F. Miller, and — (1992), “Cosmopolitanism and
J. Paul (eds), Justice and Global Politics. Sovereignty,” Ethics, 103: 48–75.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, — (1994), “An Egalitarian Law of Peoples,”
pp. 1–28. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 23 (3):
Lu, C. (2008), “World Government,” in E. 195–224.
N. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia — (2001), “Priorities of Global Justice,”
of Philosophy, http://plato.stanford. Metaphilosophy, 32: 6–24.
edu/archives/fall2008/entries/world- — (2008), World Poverty and Human
government. Rights. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Martin, R. and Reidy, D. (2006), Rawls’s — (2011), “The Health Impact Fund,” in
Law of Peoples: A Realistic Utopia? S. Benatar and G. Brock (eds), Global
Malden, MA: Blackwell. Health and Global Health Ethics.
Miller, D. (2000), Citizenship and National Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Identity. Cambridge: Polity Press. Rawls, J. (1971), A Theory of Justice.
— (2007), National Responsibility Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
and Global Justice. Oxford: Oxford — (1999), The Law of Peoples. Cambridge:
University Press. Harvard University Press.
Miller, R. (1998), “Cosmopolitan Respect Reidy, D. (2006), “Political Authority and
and Patriotic Concern,” Philosophy and Human Rights,” in R. Martin and D.
Public Affairs, 27(3): 202–224. Reidy (eds), Rawls’s Law of Peoples:
Moellendorf, D. (2002), Cosmopolitan A Realistic Utopia? Malden, MA:
Justice. Boulder, CO: Westview Press. Blackwell, pp. 169–188.
— (2009), Global Inequality Matters. New Sangiovanni, A. (2007), “Global Justice,
York: Palgrave MacMillan. Reciprocity, and the State,” Philosophy
Nagel, T. (2005), “The Problem of Global and Public Affairs, 35: 3–39.
Justice,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, Scheffler, S. (2001), Boundaries and
33: 113–147. Allegiances. Oxford: Oxford University
Nussbaum, M. (1996), “Patriotism and Press.
Cosmopolitanism,” in J. Cohen (ed.), Shue, H. (1980), Basic Rights: Subsistence,
For Love of Country: Debating The Affluence, and U.S. Foreign Policy.
Limits of Patriotism. Boston, MA: Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Beacon Press. Press.
— (2000), Women and Human Singer, P. (1972), “Famine Affluence, and
Development. Cambridge: Cambridge Morality,” Philosophy and Public Affairs,
University Press. 1 (3): 229–243.

58
COSMOPOLITANISM

Tamir, Y. (1993), Liberal Nationalism. of Cosmopolitanism. Cambridge:


Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Cambridge University Press,
Tan, K. (2004), Justice Without Borders: pp. 164–179.
Cosmopolitanism, Nationalism, and The Monist (2011), special issue on
Patriotism. Cambridge: Cambridge Cosmopolitanism, 94 (4).
University Press. Waldron, J. (1992), “Minority Rights and
— (2005), “The Demands of Justice and the Cosmopolitan Alternative,” University
National Allegiance,” in Brock and of Michigan Journal of Law Reform, 25:
Brighouse (eds), The Political Philosophy 751–793.

59
4
HUMAN RIGHTS
Siegfried Van Duffel

As I’m writing this, Christians are bru- which we would have had even if these pro-
tally murdering Muslims in the Central tections didn’t exist.
African Republic; people in Syria are being This point seems intuitively so obvious
bombed, starved, and tortured; and homo- that it is hard to see how anyone could deny
sexuals still face the death penalty in Iran it. Slavery violates a human right, not just
as well as long prison sentences in countries because some UN body agreed on a document
like Uganda and Nigeria and persecution that says that slavery violates a human right.
by thugs in many countries. These atroci- Surely those who were enslaved before the
ties and many other disturbing phenomena second half of the twentieth century had their
are often called “human rights violations.” human rights violated as well. Not everyone,
What gives them this status? That is a ques- however, has shared this intuition. Some have
tion about which there has been a surpris- thought that it is at least awkward, perhaps
ing amount of disagreement among political even downright incoherent to think of human
philosophers. rights as somehow “existing” independent of
Not so long ago, the question “What are the declarations that affirm them, or inde-
human rights?” would most likely have been pendently of any legal framework which
answered with a simple definition. Something brings them into existence (I take it that this is
like “Human rights are the rights that we the point of Bentham’s famous denouncement
have simply by virtue of being human.” The of human rights as “nonsense upon stilts”).
phrase “simply by virtue of being human” The idea that human rights are essentially
may be harder to unpack than it seems at connected to institutions has recently taken
first, but one of the commonly held ideas a different form. Under the influence of John
was that the possession of human rights is Rawls, several philosophers have developed
not dependent on any convention or insti- what are now called “political theories of
tution. Human rights, in other words, are human rights.” A prominent feature of several
moral rights. This doesn’t prevent them from of these theories is the suggestion that human
becoming enshrined in treatises and conven- rights are misconceived if taken as an ethical
tions or from receiving protection through doctrine rather than part of a distinctly polit-
legal mechanisms, but legally protected ical morality. Since this position has become
human rights are also moral rights—rights influential, I shall first discuss two prominent

61
Siegfried Van Duffel

versions of this account. The relative merit remarked that according to Rawls’s account,
of political theories versus alternatives will to prevent women or members of a particu-
ultimately depend—among other things—on lar racial or ethnic minority from getting
how they accommodate our most firmly held an education, from voting, or from holding
beliefs about the topic. Beitz, in particular, public office would not count as a violation
has argued that his theory provides a better of their human rights (Buchanan, 2010, 21).
fit with human rights doctrine and practice Rawls’s motivation seems to have been to
than traditional approaches to human rights. avoid charges of parochialism. He remarked
If he is right, we should indeed abandon the that human rights “as thus understood, can-
traditional approach to human rights and not be rejected as peculiarly liberal or special
adopt some version of the political theory. to the Western tradition” (Rawls, 1999, 65).
As we shall see, however, the case in favor This raises two questions: First, why should
of political theories is at least overstated we refrain from affirming “peculiarly lib-
and the case for abandoning the traditional eral” human rights? Rawls does not seem
approach to theorizing human rights perhaps to think much needs to be said in defense of
misguided. More positively, I shall suggest the need for a “non-parochial” list of human
another approach—what I call a “descriptive rights. He simply states that if all societies
approach”—that promises to do better on were required to be liberal “then the idea of
most of the criteria put forward to evaluate political liberalism would fail to express due
theories of human rights. toleration for other acceptable ways .  .  . of
ordering society” (59). He presents a hypo-
thetical example of a regime, Kazanistan,
which—though it is not perfectly just—
POLITICAL THEORIES OF seems to Rawls decent because it protects
HUMAN RIGHTS this limited number of human rights (and
is not expansionist and has a consultation
One of the most controversial elements in hierarchy) and then appeals to the reader’s
Rawls’s theory of international relations is intuition to agree with his judgment (76–78).
the truncated list of human rights. Rawls There is little else by way of an argument.
mentions rights to the means of subsistence The other question is how Rawls arrives at
(but not to health care or education); to his peculiar list of human rights. It would not
freedom from slavery, serfdom, and forced be possible (nor does Rawls intend) to argue
occupation, and to a sufficient (but not nec- for this selection from actual agreement: even
essarily equal) measure of liberty of con- if such agreement were to exist, it would not
science; to personal property; and to formal carry the normative weight necessary to jus-
equality as expressed by the rules of natural tify a list of human rights. He seems to think
justice (i.e. that similar cases be treated simi- that the list can be justified by employing the
larly) (Rawls, 1999, 65). Many commenta- idea of a system of social cooperation. When
tors have found Rawls’s list of human rights these rights are regularly violated, he writes,
objectionably illiberal. Such crucial rights “we have command by force, a slave system,
as freedom of expression and association, and no cooperation of any kind” (68). Again,
as well as the right to democratic participa- however, this is merely stated, not argued. It
tion are missing from the list. Buchanan has is not clear why, say, a state that used public

62
HUMAN RIGHTS

resources to support a hereditary elite in lux- particularly influential. His general approach
ury and keeps everyone else at the level of to the topic, however, has received consider-
subsistence (Buchanan, 2010, 21)  would able following. Charles Beitz, for example,
count as a system of social cooperation, even presents what he calls a “practical approach”
if this state had a decent consultation hierar- to human rights that is inspired by Rawls.
chy, or why personal property is a prerequi- He suggests that “human rights” is an emer-
site for social cooperation. gent political practice, rather than a norma-
Human rights perform a specific func- tive idea (Beitz, 2009, xii). Consequently,
tion in Rawls’s theory: their violation can talk about human rights being possessed by
justify military intervention by foreign pow- humans “simply in virtue of their humanity”
ers (Tasioulas, 2009). He does recognize a is at best a confusing way of indicating that
broader set of rights—which he calls liberal they apply to all human beings—confusing
constitutional rights—that are genuinely pos- because it falsely suggests that these rights
sessed by all, but are not properly human have some existence independently of the
rights because their violation does not give practice. His approach shares two crucial
rise to a (defeasible) reason for the interna- features with Rawls’s account. One is that
tional community to forcefully intervene human rights have a distinctly political role.
in a society. This is highly revisionist: while According to Beitz, human rights apply in
humanitarian intervention is increasingly the first instance to the political institutions
accepted in international law, justifying it is of states, but they may become a matter of
by no means the only, or even the main, func- international concern when governments fail
tion of human rights. Liberal and decent soci- to carry out their duties. When they do so,
eties, says Rawls, have the right not to tolerate human rights have an interference-justifying
outlaw states, and they have a duty of assist- role. This role is central to understanding the
ing burdened societies (i.e. societies which are discursive functions of human rights, Beitz
unable to become well-ordered on their own). maintains, even if it does not exhaust the
The duty of assistance must—within the con- range of measures for which human rights
tractarian framework of the law of peoples— violations might provide reasons. The second
be derived from the self-interest of liberal and feature that this account shares with Rawls’s
decent societies (Steinhoff, 2012). Similarly, is that it denies that we can adequately theo-
we might think that the specific list of human rize human rights through ordinary moral
rights could somehow be derived from the reasoning. Since human rights is a prac-
interest of well-ordered societies, perhaps in tice, we can only understand the concept of
creating an international environment free human rights by analyzing what is inherent
from instability. However, even if we can in it. If successful, the analysis would rep-
readily think of situations where intervention resent a consensus among competent par-
to protect human rights serves the interest ticipants in the practice, but not necessarily
of other states in international stability and a consensus about the practice’s normative
peace, it again remains completely unclear contents. Beitz uses the Rawlsian distinction
how this interest would ground the specific between concept and conception to clarify
list favored by Rawls. this thought. Different people who have
Some of this may explain why Rawls’s spe- different conceptions of human rights may
cific treatment of human rights has not been nevertheless share the same concept, because

63
Siegfried Van Duffel

they could agree on the role of human rights separate phenomena. Moral human rights
in practical reasoning about the conduct of (HR) are the subject of traditional, naturalist,
global political life (99). theories of human rights, while international
There is something strangely odd about human rights (IHR) are the preoccupation of
this account. While it seems very empirically political theories of human rights. But this is
oriented, it is also clearly revisionist. The obviously unsatisfactory. If moral theorizing
problem is not with the claim that past theo- strives to be relevant to our actual going-
ries of human rights have misdescribed some- about in the world, as it certainly should,
thing essential. It is rather with the thought then theories of moral human rights should
that the authors of these theories could have have the ambition to bear on actual attempts
been mistaken about the very fact that they to legally protect human rights, and hence
were discussing a normative idea. To this, on IHR. For example, a theory of HR may
Beitz might respond that these authors could find that some human rights are not yet
well have been discussing a normative idea, protected by international institutions, even
but that they were mistaken in identifying though they ought to be. Or it might con-
this normative idea with the idea (or practice) clude that many of the supposed human
of human rights. Such a response, however, rights enshrined in international declarations
is inconsistent with linguistic practice, even and conventions are not real (moral) human
with the language used in UN declarations rights. This may or may not be a problem. It
and conventions. More importantly, how- could be a problem, for example, if the pro-
ever, it would only turn the disagreement into motion of otherwise worthwhile social goals
a terminological quibble that could be easily under the guise of human rights damages the
resolved by distinguishing—as, for exam- sense of urgency that is properly attached to
ple, Wellman (2011) does—between “moral a claim that a human right is not sufficiently
human rights” and “international human protected or has been violated.
rights.” Beitz, of course, would resist the con- If it is implausible or undesirable to think
clusion that a mere terminological decision of moral human rights as entirely independ-
could resolve the issue, since he thinks that ent of IHR, it would be equally misguided to
conceiving human rights as natural rights has shift to the other end of the spectrum. That
contributed much of the distortion in philo- is, it would be equally wrong to think that
sophical understandings of human rights. the rights protected by IHR can only be justi-
fied if for each legal human right there is a
corresponding moral human right. The inter-
national system of human rights treatises and
MORAL RIGHTS AND conventions may serve several goals. One of
INTERNATIONAL HUMAN RIGHTS those goals should obviously be to further
the protection of moral human rights, but
How should we conceive the relation another possible goal served by IHR could
between moral human rights and interna- be to promote peace. Preventing war is of
tional human rights—meaning the existing course also likely to decrease the violation of
global legal-institutional phenomenon of moral human rights, but the mere avoidance
human rights? (Buchanan, 2010). At one end of human suffering may be an independent
of a spectrum, one could think that these are and sufficient ground for promoting peace

64
HUMAN RIGHTS

through international human rights legisla- that the strong moral force attached to many
tion. Again, IHR may have as one of its aims or most of the rights acknowledged by IHR
to further social justice and in the pursuit of is due to the fact that they are (also) preexist-
that aim some of its agents could well prom- ing moral rights, as I think they do, then the
ulgate rights that are not moral human rights. illumination of HR is not just a luxury but
Clearly, the mere fact that some of the rights quite simply an essential element of a proper
incorporated in IHR are not moral human assessment of IHR.
rights is not in itself sufficient ground to con-
clude that the inclusion of those rights in IHR
is illegitimate. Nor does this stance imply that
theories of moral human rights have no prac- CONSTRAINTS ON THEORIES
tical consequences. If we found, for example, OF HUMAN RIGHTS
that the introduction of certain legal rights
in IHR in pursuit of otherwise worthy goals How should we evaluate a theory of human
would undermine the system’s effectiveness in rights? A helpful starting point is Allen
protecting genuine moral human rights, this Buchanan’s list of desiderata:
would raise serious questions regarding the
desirability of these legal rights. The protec- 1. Consonance. A theory of HR should be
tion of moral human rights may not always consonant with our most stable intuitions
take priority over the pursuit of other goals, on the topic.
but it certainly does in many cases. 2. Reasonable fit. It should fit reasonably
with the doctrine and practice of human
It seems that we have reason to value IHR,
rights.
whether or not we find that it is best seen as
3. Constraint. It should curb human rights
nothing more than a straightforward attempt inflation.
to enforce moral human rights. Hence, even 4. Content. It should help us determine the
a significant divergence of HR from IHR content of various human rights.
would not automatically justify a demand to 5. Guidance. It should help us resolve con-
reform the latter. In fact, any theory of moral flicts among human rights.
human rights would bear a significant bur- 6. Non-parochialism. It should include a
den of justification if it recommended dras- response to the parochialism objection.
tic changes in IHR. None of this, however,
warrants the dismissal of normative theories Anyone who agrees with the suggestion
of HR as irrelevant or misguided when they that moral human rights is a distinct idea
aspire to provide a yardstick for the assess- that deserves to be taken seriously because of
ment of IHR. The language of the UDHR the influence it (still) has on the practice of
and of the most important other conventions human rights will also agree that desideratum
shows that the drafters of these documents #1 should take priority over desideratum #2.
thought of human rights as preexisting moral However, I shall suggest that even the natural
rights. If moral philosophers have been mis- rights theories that perform best on this cri-
taken in thinking that moral human rights terion (say, those of Gewirth, 1978, Griffin,
are relevant, they are surely in good com- 2008) fail the desideratum of consonance in
pany. But if the majority of current partici- important respects. The main reason for this
pants in the practice of IHR share the idea is that our intuitions regarding human rights

65
Siegfried Van Duffel

are the historical offspring of two very dif- theories. Libertarians typically deny that we
ferent (traditions of) natural rights theories: have any innate moral right to such things as
theories of property rights (in a very broad basic health care or elementary education. For
sense) and theories of welfare rights (in a some political theorists, this in itself serves to
very broad sense). So even if we find that show that the libertarian is not talking about
no particular natural rights theory satisfies (international) human rights. The libertarian,
desideratum #1, it doesn’t rule out the pos- however, is unlikely to be impressed by this,
sibility that different natural rights theories for she is unlikely to share the political theo-
together satisfy the criterion. However, since rist’s view of the relation between HR and
these theories are incompatible in their prac- IHR. Most libertarians would condemn the
tical consequences, the only way we could practice of levying tax on citizens in order
regard them as satisfying the criterion of to finance a system of universal health care
consonance together is to abandon the per- or education as a violation of the property
spective of normative theorizing. As long as rights of the wealthy. This is not even a case
we are merely trying to find out what human of a conflict of rights—the rights of property
rights are, that is no objection. I shall point owners on the one hand and the rights of
out later that this way of asking the question the needy on the other—since the libertarian
what human rights are will affect the desider- denies that the needy have moral rights to
ata and hence what we expect from a theory such provisions. To the extent that IHR stim-
of human rights rather dramatically. ulates states to finances systems of universal
health care through taxation, the libertarian
will view it as complicit in the large-scale vio-
lation of the human rights of property own-
FIVE CHALLENGES AGAINST ers rather than attempting to protect human
NATURALISTIC THEORIES rights. If the political theorist wants to insist
that the libertarian is talking about natural
Theories of HR can be (and have been) chal- rights rather than human rights, she may
lenged on most of these criteria. Four of the well do so but it will seem little more than
most significant challenges have to do with a word game to the libertarian. After all, the
scopes (#1 and #3), the political nature of crucial function of libertarian natural rights
human rights (#2), the distribution of cor- is to distinguish legitimate from illegitimate
relative duties (#4), and the relation between uses of government force, which is also the
human rights and their justification (#6). most important function of human rights for
1. At the most general level, the issue of the political theorist. So while the political
scope is about whether any naturalist theory theorist may think that the libertarian has
of HR is able to give a satisfactory answer to not even addressed human rights, the liber-
the question which rights we have. But there tarian will obviously disagree.
is a problem. Anyone’s view on whether a par- The criterion of consonance as applied
ticular theory has given a satisfactory answer to scope is also likely to leave us begging
to the question which rights we have obvi- the question when intuitions differ. Given
ously depends on one’s view of what counts that most right-libertarian theories do not
as a satisfactory answer. Take, for example, acknowledge such rights as health care and
contemporary libertarian natural rights education, most of us may find that these

66
HUMAN RIGHTS

theories are not consonant with “our” most protesters. When we talk about rights that
stable intuitions on the topic. This doesn’t we have against other people, we usually
seem to bother most libertarians, and it is have legal rights in mind. Most of us would
not immediately clear that it should. Instead, not ordinarily speak of yourself as having a
they may well scorn the suggestion that the right against your friend that she goes to the
truth about human rights should depend on movies with you because she promised to
the intuitions of even a majority of people. do so. I gather that even philosophers who
Unfortunately, the role of intuitions in dis- are prone to talk about promises generat-
covering ethical truth raises problems far too ing rights would not use the word “right”
complex to be pursued here. in ordinary life when describing the situa-
What if we take for granted that most of tion created by a promise. Compared to this,
us (non-libertarians) agree sufficiently on it is perhaps a remarkable feat about our
the scope of human rights for there to be a linguistic intuitions that talk about prom-
benchmark to compare theories of human ises generating rights doesn’t come across
rights with? Let us further assume that this as awkward at all. Because the notion of a
quasi-consensus is fairly close to the list of right of a promise doesn’t strike us as a cat-
human rights endorsed by the most impor- egory mistake, the divergence in philosophi-
tant human rights treaties and conventions. cal work from ordinary linguistic practice is
Would this give us a reason to discard natu- not normally considered a ground for reject-
ralist theories of human rights because the ing theories that construe promises as gen-
list of rights they generate is simply too short erating rights. This is important because the
to be recognizable as a list of human rights? idea that human rights are distinctly political
It would if all naturalist theories were of the rather than moral could be seen as receiving
libertarian variety. But that is not the case: support from linguistic practice in a similar
philosophers like Gewirth and Griffin have manner. We are more likely to use phrases
built theories that imply much more exten- like “human rights violations” when con-
sive sets of human rights. So the complaint fronted with large-scale violence and oppres-
about the limited normative reach of natu- sion committed by government agents against
ralistic theories rests on a disregard for the civilians, especially because these incidents
considerable variety in this group of theories. are also far more prevalent than, say, simi-
The problem of scope takes on a different lar violence committed by rogue militia. Still,
form for several of these theories, though, since the label “human rights violations” does
because it is unclear whether they are able to not induce a conceptual shock when applied,
prevent rights inflation (#3; see later). for example, to the atrocities committed by
2. What reason might we have to think nongovernmental militia in Syria, we should
that human rights are in the first instance resist the temptation to take linguistic prac-
rights against states? Philosophers are used tice as sufficient basis for theoretical claims
to thinking of some rights as moral entities. about human rights.
In daily life, however, we think of ourselves Another argument brought forward by
as exercising rights primarily in legal/politi- proponents of political theories of human
cal contexts. The main idea that comes to rights is that some human rights presuppose
mind when we think of a right to protest is the existence of modern states. Such rights
a duty of the government not to persecute as the right to asylum, or to a nationality

67
Siegfried Van Duffel

are not even conceivable outside the frame- or flourishing, but merely to what is needed
work of modern nation-states. Does this for human status” (34). This suggests a very
show that human rights are specifically mod- minimalist interpretation of the requirements
ern, and hence that they cannot possibly be of human rights. Most of us will grow up to
rights imagined by natural rights theorists be autonomous beings even without a formal
which human beings could have even in a education. People living in severe poverty are
state of nature? There is a simple answer normally able to act, even if they may not be
to this objection. Such rights as the right to able to derive much satisfaction from their life
asylum are derived from more fundamental or achieve many of their goals. Again, people
rights which do not presuppose the existence who are imprisoned may be prevented from
of a state system (see, e.g. Wellman, 2011, pursuing many of their projects, but not nec-
41–70). One of the main grounds for grant- essarily to such an extent as to be deprived of
ing refugees asylum is that they risk persecu- their personhood. Thus it seems that the set
tion. It is thus easy to see that the right not of human rights generated by Griffin’s theory
to be persecuted is more fundamental than must be exceedingly small—so small as to be
the right to asylum. Even more fundamen- hardly recognizable as a list of human rights.
tal than the right not to be persecuted is the In fact, the criterion of personhood may not
right to physical integrity. This right surely even prohibit most forms of torture.
could conceivably exist in a world that has Griffin realizes that a strict interpreta-
no modern system of sovereign states (but tion of the agency criterion doesn’t pro-
see Beitz, 2009, 55). duce a plausible list of human rights, but he
3. The first complaint against natural rights denies that this is the conception at the core
theories was that their scope is much more of his theory. Instead, he claims to have in
restricted than that of contemporary human mind a “somewhat ampler picture” of some-
rights practice. As we saw, this may be true of one autonomous “who, within limits, is not
some naturalistic theories, but is certainly not blocked from pursuing his or her conception
true of all of them. For some of these theories, of a worthwhile life” (34). The crucial ques-
the opposite may well be true. That is, they tion is where to draw the line. For exam-
fail to constrain the proliferation of human ple: we are told that education is necessary
rights. Consider, for example, Griffin’s recent because it is a condition for effective agency,
defense of rights based on personhood. but that there are levels of education beyond
“Human rights,” Griffin writes, “can be seen what is required by human rights (53).
as protections of our human standing, or, . . . Since education is almost never needed for a
personhood” (Griffin, 2008, 33). To be a per- human being to become an agent, and since
son or agent in the fullest sense of which we Griffin insists that we do not have a right to
are capable, we need three things: autonomy education sufficient for human flourishing,
(being able to choose one’s own path through the theory should be able to tell us something
life), minimal provision (so that we are able about the amount of education necessary for
to act upon our choices), and liberty (others “effective” agency. Griffin, unfortunately,
not forcibly stopping us from pursuing what tells us nothing of the kind, and he is equally
we see as a worthwhile life) (33). Griffin silent regarding the level protection required
also tells us that human rights “are rights by minimal provision. These problems are not
not to anything that promotes human good specific to Griffin’s theory. Other versions of

68
HUMAN RIGHTS

the theory that aims to ground rights in per- someone who has a duty to provide neces-
sonhood (like those of Gewirth or Plant) suf- sities when they are lacking. The problem is
fer the exact same weaknesses. They start out that most people also believe that you can
with the idea that human rights only require have a duty to do something only when you
that we have the things that allow us to be are able to do it. If a train is about to crash
agents, but—realizing that this is insufficient into a crowd and kill dozens of people, I cer-
for a plausible theory of human rights—con- tainly have a duty to stop it if I can, but it
tinue that we should have the means for the doesn’t make sense to say that I have such
effective exercise of our agency. Of course, a duty if I am unable to fulfill it. A signifi-
no theory could be plausible if it required cant difference between negative duties and
that we should have the means for any or positive duties, however, is that it is always
all of our actions to be effective. The prob- possible for everyone to abstain from mur-
lem is that these theories lack the theoretical dering someone, but we may often be unable
resource to nonarbitrarily limit the amount to provide food or education or health care
of support that human rights require. Griffin for everyone in need. If we can only have a
appeals to “practicalities” to plug the gap, duty when we are able to fulfill it, then we
but he doesn’t provide much insight as to cannot have a duty to provide health care for
how these are supposed to work (Van Duffel, everyone, and if we don’t have this duty then
2013). Thus the best contemporary natural there can be no human right to health care.
rights theories fail to provide a convincing Some have hence concluded that the idea of
cure for the proliferation of rights. social and economic human rights is incoher-
The proliferation of human rights and the ent (see Cranston, 1967).
inability of natural rights theories to stop This criticism has given rise to an extensive
that proliferation may be a serious cause for literature, much of which has been devoted
concern, but it is not a reason to embrace to defending such human rights as the right
political theories of human rights. The phe- to subsistence, to education, to health care.
nomenon of human rights proliferation that Some have questioned the practical import
disturbs many is internal to the IHR practice. of the distinction between negative and posi-
Some political theories may rule out certain tive rights, claiming that protecting a right
candidates as incompatible with the idea of to bodily integrity requires that governments
human rights as it is inherent in IHR, but maintain a police force and a judicial system.
these theories have as yet not given us a cred- Others have pointed out that positive rights
ible instrument to constrain the proliferation only require that we support institutions
of human rights. that provide for the needy. Yet others have
4. Many of the rights that we have are maintained that human rights only require
correlative to duties of other people. Some that we do what is in our power to provide
of these duties—so-called negative duties, the things that people have a right to. A
like the duty not to kill—can be fulfilled fourth suggestion is to restrict the use of the
simply by abstaining from certain actions. phrase “human right” to legally enforceable
Some rights, however, are correlative to posi- claims. I have argued elsewhere (Van Duffel,
tive duties, which require others to actually 2013)  that none of these responses are sat-
provide a good or a service. A human right isfactory, and so we are left with a problem.
to subsistence is only meaningful if there is Our intuitions regarding moral human rights

69
Siegfried Van Duffel

seem incoherent because these rights demand theories and the cultural experience from
more of us than we might at times be able which they have emerged have had a sig-
to provide. As far as I can see, this problem nificant influence on the development of the
is not solved by political theories of human human rights movement, how do we know
rights. The fact that they allocate primary that the idea of human rights is not culturally
duties to states which are generally better specific as well? Can we just take for granted
able to respond to standard threats than indi- that discarding the theory and replacing the
viduals is not sufficient to render the idea of phrase “natural rights” with “human rights”
positive human rights coherent. suffices to shrug off the cultural baggage that
5. No matter how dominant the language came with the former? This raises another
of human rights has become in the public issue: Is it legitimate to set non-parochial-
arena, doubts regarding the universality (or, ism as a criterion for a proper concept of
better, non-parochialism) of human rights human rights? In one sense, human rights
have never entirely disappeared. Indeed, one are of course necessarily universal: noth-
of the prime incentives for the development ing is a human right if it is not held by all
of political theories may have been the desire human beings. But if we think that an idea
to detach the idea of human rights from sub- or a theory can be parochial, it can hardly be
stantive commitments to the liberal tradi- satisfactory to assume from the outset that
tion or to any particular normative theory. nothing can count as an idea of human rights
Christians, Muslims, and atheists, as well as unless it is non-parochial. The demand that
conservatives and socialists may agree on it must be non-parochial makes sense if one
most fundamental human rights even though intends to build a normative theory, but it
they share few or no other normative beliefs. is unwarranted when one is primarily inter-
From a practical point of view, disagreement ested in understanding the concept itself.
on the grounds of these rights is quite unim-
portant as long as we agree on at least the
basic rights. Even though agreement on a
comprehensive list of human rights in the IHR HUMAN RIGHTS AS A CULTURAL
practice may sometimes seem hard enough to PHENOMENON
reach and is likely to remain precarious, it is
certainly easier to attain than agreement on Although this overview was much too brief to
any substantive theory of moral rights. establish any firm conclusions, the foregoing
Whether naturalist theories of human discussion may nevertheless motivate us to
rights are indeed parochial is a controversial explore an alternative to both naturalist and
matter. In fact, those who assume that they political theories of human rights. I suggest
are usually don’t find it necessary to substan- that an illuminating way to study the idea
tiate their assumption. The reason for this, of human rights is to probe the structure of
I suspect, is that it is not at all clear what our beliefs about human rights. Rather than
it means to say that a theory is parochial or asking which rights we might have, I shall
culturally specific. Another problem is this: suggest that we might profitably ask which
Suppose that we accept, for the sake of argu- rights we think we have. Call this the descrip-
ment, that existing natural rights theories tive approach. Another way to put this is
are culturally specific. Assuming that these that we should think of the idea of human

70
HUMAN RIGHTS

rights as a cultural phenomenon. How is the This opens up a tangle of thorny questions,
descriptive approach different from that of like: Is there a group of people whose
(naturalist and political) normative theories? beliefs on the topic are similar enough to
I can only briefly mention five points. allow amalgamation? But answers to such
First, the descriptive approach is not com- questions cannot be settled in advance: they
mitted to taking a position regarding the must be the result of the description.
truth-value of normative claims. Normative This brings us to the third point, which is
theories of human rights strive to answer that we may treat normative theories them-
questions such as “Which human rights selves as a source of knowledge about the
do we have?” “What grounds our rights?” idea of human rights. Normative ­theorists
and “Who has duties to provide the things are rarely interested in merely stating what
to which we have rights?” They attempt to others think: they want to argue what
ground rights, for example, in claims about human rights are, not what we think they
human nature, or claims about prerequisites are. However, most normative theorists have
for the legitimacy of states. The descriptive attempted to appeal to widely shared ideas
approach is not interested either in affirming, about human rights, the many articles and
or in rejecting the truth-value of normative books that they have written on the topic
claims. It does not deny that normative ques- provide a convenient source of information
tions are important in their own right, but it for anyone who wants to access these ideas.
leaves these questions aside. That is not to say that the process of bas-
Secondly, normative theories are (or ing claims about what “we” believe about
can be) revisionist with regards to com- human rights on a sample of these theories
monly accepted beliefs about human rights. is entirely unproblematic.
A normative theory could make a case for The fourth point will be controversial:
the existence of certain human rights that normative theories of human rights not only
haven’t made it to any widely accepted list. provide a good source for studying human
Or it could entail that we do not really have rights as a cultural phenomenon, but also
a human right to some of the things that are provide the best available source of its kind.
widely claimed to be human rights. There Studying human rights as a cultural phe-
clearly is only a limited stretch on the ability nomenon essentially is studying the practi-
of normative theories to redraw the bounda- cal experience which brought into being
ries of human rights. If a theory entails too the tradition of human rights theories. The
many claims that run counter to what most descriptive approach studies theories as theo-
of us are inclined to believe—for example, if retical reflections on this practical experience
its list of human rights is too sparse or too (though these theoretical reflections of course
capacious—we may conclude that the theory helped in turn to shape that experience).
doesn’t capture the idea of human rights ade- Fifthly, the description of human rights
quately. For obvious reasons, the descriptive theories must be historical in its scope. This is
approach cannot be revisionist in the same because the complex development of the idea
way as a normative theory. of human rights has left us with theoretical
A descriptive approach cannot take problems which can only be fully untangled
beliefs of individuals as basic, but must take by taking into account intuitive remnants
as its subject a cultural tradition as a whole. from past incarnations of these theories.

71
Siegfried Van Duffel

Unfortunately I can only give the briefest plague the other approaches. I shall, again all
possible outline of the story that would too briefly, indicate how it might do this.
emerge if we put this approach to work. 1. The account generated by the descrip-
The experience which has brought human tive approach will be consonant with our
rights theories into being is that of a cul- most stable intuitions on the topic if these
ture which has for some time been influ- intuitions are nontrivially shaped by the two
enced by a monotheistic religion. In such traditions of natural rights theories, as indeed
a religion, the basic ethical requirement is they are. One way in which it is easy to see
to obey the commands of the author of the the superiority of this approach is that it can
universe. This has engendered a shift in ethi- accommodate the fact that our intuitions were
cal outlook from a virtue ethics to a law-like formed by two theories which are practically
morality (Anscombe, 1958, Williams, 1985). incompatible and have generated conflicting
A necessary component of this ethical out- sets of rights (fundamental property rights of
look is the idea that human beings have a pharmaceutical companies versus rights of
will, and hence that all genuine actions are patients, for example, or rights of democratic
intentional actions (Dihle, 1982). Religion majorities versus rights of individuals).
further spreads the idea that human beings 2. An account of human rights should be
have a role to play in God’s plan, and hence able to accommodate both the sense in which
that certain sets of actions are morally these rights are conceived as interactional
necessary. (held by all against all individuals) as well as
From this ethical outlook and its concep- the special place of governments both in IHR
tion of the requirements of agency, two dis- and in our intuitions regarding human rights.
tinct (traditions of) natural rights theories One way in which the descriptive approach
have emerged (Tuck, 1979, Van Duffel, 2010). is again superior to both naturalist and polit-
The first is a theory of rights to subsistence ical theories is that it can do this by showing
or “welfare rights” (in a very broad sense). that these seemingly conflicting intuitions are
It starts from the idea that people must be the result of the influence of two conflicting
able to make decisions and act upon them. theories of natural rights and the result of the
In the religious version, it requires people to historical development of the theory of wel-
maintain the conditions created by God that fare rights.
enable people to act upon His will. The secu- 3. The descriptive approach does not aim
lar version requires us to generate the condi- to curb human rights inflation, but rather
tions that allow people to realize their goals. aims to explain both the phenomenon of
The second is a theory of “property rights” human rights inflation and the intuition that
(again in a very broad sense). It starts from this inflation is deeply problematic. It does
the idea that our acts of will have normative this by showing how inflation is the result of
consequences for others. It secularizes the the secularization of the theory of rights to
idea of God’s authority over his creation by subsistence (for this point and the next, see
suggesting that human beings create as well Van Duffel, 2013).
and that they must have a similar authority 4. The problem of assigning duties correla-
over their creation. tive to positive rights can also be explained
A full defense of this approach involves by the same account. Historically, rights to
showing that it resolves the problems that subsistence were negative rights, not positive

72
HUMAN RIGHTS

rights. Hence the correlative duties could not Political Theory and the Rights of Man.
be excessively demanding. Again the descrip- Minneapolis, MN: Indiana University
tive approach helps us describe human rights Press.
without violating crucial intuitions. Dihle, A. (1982), The Theory of Will
5. The descriptive approach explains the in Classical Antiquity. Berkeley, CA:
persistent suspicion that the idea of human University of California Press.
rights is culturally specific, but it does Gewirth, A. (1978), Reason and Morality.
this without entailing cultural relativism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Although we may be indeed feel compelled to Griffin, J. (2008), On Human Rights. New
reconsider the soundness of current human York: Oxford University Press.
rights theories, none of this implies that we Rawls, J. (1999), The Law of Peoples.
should tolerate cruelty or persecution in the Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
name of culture. Press.
Steinhoff, U. (2012), “Unsavory
Implications Unsavory Implications of
A Theory of Justice and The Law of
CONCLUSION Peoples: The Denial of Human Rights
and the Justification of Slavery,” The
Proponents of political theories are right when Philosophical Forum, 43(2): 175–196.
they point out shortcomings of naturalistic Tasioulas, J. (2009), “Are Human Rights
theories of human rights. However, political Essentially Triggers for Intervention?”
theories certainly do not fill the gap left by Philosophy Compass, 4 (6): 938–950.
theories of moral human rights. At most, they Tuck, R. (1979), Natural Rights Theories:
might fill a hiatus in our theorizing about IHR. Their Origin and Development.
Although the case for the descriptive approach Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
is tentative and as yet underdeveloped, this Van Duffel, S. (2010), “From Objective
approach may help further our understand- Right to Subjective Rights: The
ing of human rights and the culture in which Franciscans and the Interest and Will
theories of human rights developed. Conceptions of Rights,” in V. Mäkinen
(ed.), The Nature of Rights: Moral
and Political Aspects of Rights in Late
Medieval and Early Modern Philosophy.
WORKS CITED Helsinki: The Philosophical Society of
Finland.
Anscombe, G. E. M. (1958), “Modern — (2013), “Natural Rights to Welfare,” The
Moral Philosophy,” Philosophy, 33: 1–19. European Journal of Philosophy, 21 (4):
Beitz, C. (2009), The Idea of Human 641–664.
Rights. New York: Oxford University Wellman, C. (2011), The Moral Dimensions
Press. of Human Rights. New York: Oxford
Buchanan, A. (2010), “The Egalitarianism of University Press.
Human Rights,” Ethics, 120: 679–710. Williams, B. (1985), Ethics and the Limits
Cranston, M. (1967) “Human Rights, Real of Philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
and Supposed,” in D. D. Raphael (ed.), University Press.

73
5
DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE
Ovadia Ezra

The concept of distributive justice has been the meaning of this concept in recent usage
continuously modified since its first appear- relate to the content of the distributed goods,
ance in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. to the criteria according to which they should
According to Aristotle, distributive justice is be distributed, by whom, and recently, to
a kind “which is manifested in distribution of which range the distribution scheme should
honour or money or the other things that fall apply. Past discussions of this term limited
to be divided among those who have a share its range to the borders of nations, states, or
in the constitution (for in these it is possible societies, assuming that goods should be dis-
for one man to have a share either unequal tributed only among people who belong to
or equal to that of another)” (Aristotle, 1947, the same political or social framework. Many
1130b). In his view, retributive justice “plays of the current discussions, however, extend
a rectifying part in transactions between man the scope of distribution to the world as a
and man” (ibid.). Aristotle maintains that whole. Those who oppose the concept and
“what is just in distribution must be according implementation of distributive justice at the
to merit in some sense” (ibid.) What Aristotle domestic sphere also oppose its implementa-
meant to say is that justice is a way of suiting tion at the global level. Here I present some
one’s possession or share, to one’s merit and/ common theoretical approaches to this con-
or entitlement. If one deserves a larger share of cept, and then, consider some ways and prac-
something, distributive justice requires that his tices involved in promoting just distribution,
share in the distribution scheme will represent both at the domestic and global levels.
his or her privileged position. In this chapter, I Like any other discussion in political phi-
point out the radical changes in meaning that losophy, the meaning and interpretation of
this term has undergone, and the different any term is connected to our understanding
understandings of its current usage. of related terms, within the same context.
One thing that has not been changed with Dworkin expresses this idea by presenting
regard to the usage of this concept is the com- his theory of rights as one which is “rela-
prehensive agreement that distributive justice tive to the other elements of political theory”
refers to the way assets, goods, wealth, capital, (Dworkin, 1986, 370). In the same way,
resources, benefits, burdens, and so on should Postema thinks that: “to understand the lan-
be distributed within political or social frame- guage of rights we need to mark out its dis-
works. The differences in opinion regarding tinctive place in this complex of fundamental

75
Ovadia Ezra

normative notions” (Postema, 1989, 109– distribution of goods or benefits requires


110). “With regard to distributive justice, I justification. Sometimes an equal distribu-
can paraphrase Thomson, who creatively tion that neglects other considerations is
suggests that we think of morality as a con- wrong, inappropriate, or even unjust. Even
tinent, and of rights as a territory or realm Aristotle’s concept of distributive justice
within that continent” (Thomson, 1990, 3). insisted on differential distribution, accord-
The same can be said regarding distributive ing to merit. Justice requires that we should
justice, and following Thomson we can say distribute different shares to different people,
that understanding what is within the realm in accordance with their entitlements.
of distributive justice requires getting a sense Equal distribution is sometimes inappro-
of where it is situated in the continent of priate. Think of a party in which we distrib-
morality in general, and of justice in particu- ute the birthday cake. If we give an adult and
lar. Thus, we must have a general idea of our a 3-year-old child a piece of the same size, we
moral and political conceptions, and then are probably making two mistakes. While the
we should locate the concept of distribu- adult may receive a piece that is smaller than
tive justice in its appropriate place. In order he wants or needs, the young child will prob-
to decide in favor of any of the competing ably get a much larger piece than he or she
theories regarding justice, we have to check can actually eat, and we should not regard
the suitability of the concept of distributive such a distribution as justifiable. The same
justice in relation to our deepest moral and piece may be too small for the adult and too
political beliefs and presumptions, regarding big for the child.
human nature, justice, equality, mutuality, However, we still presume an essential
and so on. equality between human beings, and this
The most fundamental presumption assumption forces us to refer to the idea of
which lies at the basis of any modern discus- equality in every distributional scheme we
sion within the Western tradition of political wish to justify. Dworkin, who deals with
thought regarding distributive justice is that the basic demands for equal treatment of
“All human beings are born free and equal in human beings, makes a distinction between
dignity and rights” as stated in Article 1 of what he calls the right to equal treatment,
the Universal Declaration of Human Rights.1 and the right to treatment as an equal. The
This presumption presents our deepest belief former is “the right to an equal distribution
that in spite of contingent differences between of some opportunity or resource or burden”
people, there is an essential and fundamental (Dworkin, 1977, 227), such as a person’s
equality in value between them, in the sense right to an equal vote in democracy. The
that they are all endowed with reason and latter, the right to treatment as an equal, is
conscience (as the cited article reminds us). not the right to receive the same amount of
What many theorists, as well as politicians burden or benefit which is distributed, but
and decision makers deduce from this pre- the right “to be treated with the same respect
sumption is that equal concern should be the and concern as anyone else” (ibid.). To elab-
one and only principle of any distributional orate this idea, Dworkin gives an example
scheme, and the sole requirement of such a where one has two children, and one of them
scheme. Current debates regarding distribu- is dying from a disease, while the other, even
tive justice are aware of the fact that equal though he suffers from the same disease,

76
DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

merely feels unwell or uncomfortable. The in favor of equality, or any other overall
father has only one dose of the medicine. end, state or patterning. It cannot merely
Equal treatment requires that he should flip a be assumed that equality must be built into
coin to decide which of the children will have any theory of justice” (Nozick, 1974, 233).
the only dose of the drug. However, such a Nozick opposes any consideration of equal-
way of deciding on the appropriate distribu- ity in the concept of justice. He also opposes
tion of that medicine will not show equal the whole idea of distributive justice that
concern to the children’s future. Dworkin redistributes current assets and goods.
concludes from this example that the right to Nozick denies that there is any central dis-
treatment as an equal is fundamental while tribution or any person or group who is enti-
the other right, the right to equal treatment is tled to control resources within the state, or
only derivative. Sometimes the right to treat- to jointly decide how the resources should be
ment as an equal entails equal treatment, but “doled out” (Nozick, 1974, 149). The only
many times not. This is one of the fundamen- justice he believes should prevail is what he
tal intuitions that grounds most of the con- calls “justice in holdings.” According to this
temporary discussions regarding distributive concept:
justice. Most of us understand that if we
really want to realize justice through distri- 1. A person who acquires a holding in
bution of goods, benefits, assets, or burdens, accordance with the principle of justice in
we have to go beyond the formal scheme of acquisition is entitled to that holding.
equality and search for a more progressive 2. A person who acquires a holding in
accordance with the principle of justice in
and enlightened distribution mechanism.
transfer, from someone else entitled to the
holding, is entitled to the holding.
3. No one is entitled to a holding except by
(repeated) applications of 1 and 2 (ibid.,
A LIBERTARIAN APPROACH TO 151).
DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

Even though the earlier claim is widely What Nozick wishes to say is that the com-
accepted, there are still modern theorists who plete principle of distributive justice would
believe that the whole concept of an upper say simply that a distribution is just “if eve-
framework (the state or society) which regu- ryone is entitled to the holdings they possess
lates or controls the distribution of benefits under the distribution” (ibid.). Accordingly,
and burdens among its citizens or members, he rejects any external or governmental
or that there are common goods whose distri- attempt to regulate or control future pos-
bution should be decided by that framework, session of goods, since there is no legitimate
does not cohere with or is not fitting for any principle of distribution other than everyone’s
satisfying or moral concept of justice. One of entitlement to their current possession. Any
the most familiar versions of this approach is other distribution might disregard the fact
Nozick’s theory of justice, which is based on that there should be a link between the rights
the idea of entitlement in holdings. Nozick of those who produce goods and wealth, and
insists that “The entitlement conception of are thus entitled to enjoy them, and the way
justice in holdings makes no presumption others decide to distribute those goods.

77
Ovadia Ezra

Another libertarian objection to the idea justice, he presents his view that the phrase
that there should be a collective aggregate social justice is not “an innocent expression
of resources that should be distributed justly of good will towards the less fortune” as
was raised by Hayek, who believes that jus- most people feel, but “a dishonest insinua-
tice should remain an attribute of human tion that one ought to agree to a demand of
conduct, without any collective or social some special interest which can give no real
meaning. Accordingly, the terms “just” or reason for it” (ibid., 97). To express the dete-
“unjust” refer only to human conduct, and rioration of the current political discourse
“to apply the term ‘just’ to circumstances and the endless violence to language when
other than human actions or the rules gov- the term social justice (which he believes to
erning them is a category mistake” (Hayek, be meaningless and empty) has given rise to
1976, 31). Hayek mentions the current use of the expression of “global justice,” when an
social justice and distributive justice as syno- ecumenical gathering of American religious
nyms, and maintains that since justice has leaders referred to its opposite, namely to
meaning only as a rule of human conduct, “global injustice,” “as characterized by a
there is no distribution which could be mean- dimension of sin in the economic political
ingfully described as just or unjust (Hayek, social sexual and class structures and system
1978, 58). For Hayek, the phrase social jus- of global society” (ibid., 80). Hayek argues
tice is completely empty, since “no agreement that the understanding of people as separate
exists about what social justice requires in individuals denies the relevance of using the
particular instances .  .  . there is no known term justice in the context of a distribution
test by which to decide who is right if people scheme even within the state or society. He
differ . . . no preconceived scheme of distribu- is upset by the thought that people start
tion could be effectively devised in a society thinking of distributive justice in the global
whose individuals are free” (ibid.). sphere. For Hayek, the concept is fraudulent
Hayek says that the commitment to social and intellectually dishonest.
justice has unfortunately become “the chief Hayek’s negative approach to social jus-
outlet for moral emotion, the distinguishing tice, and his denial of the appropriateness
attribute of the good man, and the recognized of applying the term “justice” to social
sign of the possession of a moral conscience” frameworks can be a good starting point
(Hayek, 1976, 66). His recommendation is to for understanding his objection to what he
regard social justice as religious superstition calls the “near universal acceptance” of the
which people “must fight when it becomes the term. Starting with Mill’s understanding of
pretext of coercing other men” (ibid.). Hayek “social and distributive justice” gives Hayek
complains that the idea of social justice, in a clue to the meaning of current use of the
our current understanding of the term as a term. Hayek says that appropriate reading
synonym for distributive justice, has received of Mill leads to understand the demand for
“a near universal acceptance,” and warns social justice as “a demand that the members
us that “the prevailing belief in ‘social jus- of society should organize themselves in a
tice’ is at present probably the gravest threat manner which makes it possible to assign
to most other values of a free civilization” particular shares of the product of society
(ibid., 66–67). In the conclusion of his dis- to the different individuals or groups” (ibid.,
cussion regarding “social” or “distributive” 64). This is roughly the way most theorists

78
DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

have been dealing with distributive justice there is a need for a more egalitarian scheme
during the last four decades. Hayek’s analy- of distribution. Current theories of distribu-
sis of the common use of the term “social” tive justice, which share the ideas that Hayek
(with reference to social justice) considers it accuses them of holding, attempt to find
to be not a natural product of society or of the substantive content of what should be
social process, but a conception which some distributed. They also consider the extent
thinkers wish to impose on society (ibid., of distribution and those who should be
78). Indeed, the comprehensive use of social the target of the distribution scheme. The
or distributive justice today seems more like most influential theory of justice in general
a prescriptive term rather than descriptive. and of distributive justice in particular, for
Hayek argues that when this term came into several decades, is Rawls’s theory of justice.
general use it meant to convey an appeal to According to Rawls, the main answers to the
the ruling classes to concern themselves more earlier question is that we should distribute
with the welfare of numerous poor people what he calls “primary goods,” to the extent
whose interests had not received appropriate that enables each person to develop his or
consideration. It was an appeal to the con- her moral capabilities, and that the distribu-
science of the upper classes to take responsi- tion scheme should be aimed at improving
bility for the welfare of the poor. Gradually, the most deprived groups in society.
social policy became, according to Hayek’s
analysis, “the chief concern of all progressive
and good people, and ‘social’ came increas-
ingly to displace such terms as ‘ethical’ or RAWLS’S EGALITARIAN VIEW
simply good” (ibid., 79). Even though Hayek
exaggerates the dimensions of the process, Rawls’s concept of justice is first and fore-
his claim is provocative—that the concept most political and not metaphysical. This
has expanded from the demand to recognize means that justice relates to what Rawls calls
the unfortunate ones as members of the same “the basic structure of society,” which is “the
society, to the demand that society ought fundamental social institutions and their
to hold itself responsible for the particu- arrangement into one scheme” (Rawls, 1979,
lar material position of its members (ibid.). 9). He refers to those institutions which
Hayek misleads his readers by saying that regulate or affect the distribution of wealth,
society wants to assure that each member power, and status in society. Barry gives a few
receives what is “due” to him, but he is right examples for institutions which fall under the
in his claim that the current understanding of basic structure, among which he includes the
society is that of a framework which is capa- rules which allocate fundamental rights and
ble of being guided in its operation by moral privileges, the rules that specify how access
principles. to political decision-making power is gained,
Approaches such as those of Hayek or the rules that allow the concentration of pri-
Nozick that deny that justice ought to be vate decision-making power, the institutions
concerned about inequality, and thus, are that determine access to professions and
indifferent regarding any inequality within occupational positions, and “the whole com-
the society, the state, or the nation. Those plex of institutions (.  .  . including rules for
who do believe in such equality feel that the acquisition and inheritance of property

79
Ovadia Ezra

and the system of taxation and transfers) conception of the good as best they can,
that determine the distribution of income whatever it may be” (ibid.). Rawls’s basic
and wealth in society” (Barry, 1989, 146). idea is that people should have the minimal
According to Rawls’s view, these institu- requirements for developing their moral abil-
tions, which basically determine the access to ities, and the difference principle should be
resources and means within the social frame- used by the institutions of the basic structure
work, should follow two principles of justice, for fulfilling these requirements.
the first of which governs the assignment of When Rawls tries to characterize the neces-
rights and duties, and requires that: sary requirements for developing the two moral
1. “Each person is to have an equal right powers, he uses the term basic goods, which he
to the most extensive basic liberty compat- divides into five sections (ibid., 526):
ible with a similar liberty for others” (Rawls,
1971, 60). 1. The basic liberties (freedom of thought,
The second principle regulates the dis- liberty of conscience, etc.)
tribution of social and economic primary 2. Freedom of movement and free choice of
goods, and requires that: occupations
3. Powers and prerogatives of offices and
2. “Social and economic inequalities are to
positions of responsibility
be arranged so that they are both (a) to the
4. Income and wealth, understood broadly
greatest benefit of the least advantaged, and as they must be
(b) attached to offices and positions open to 5. The social bases of self-respect.
all under conditions of fair equality of oppor-
tunity” (ibid., 83).
This second principle, which is known as Just institutions are those institutions
the difference principle, can be accommo- which regulate the distribution of these
dated to the general conception of justice, primary goods according to the difference
which is its application to all primary goods. principle, and thus enable moral persons to
Rawls, who in many senses holds a Kantian develop their moral powers. What should be
conception with regard to human nature, clarified at this point is that neither Rawls,
considers human beings as rational, free, and nor other theorists intend to achieve sub-
equal, and as such he ascribes to them two stantive at the end of the social process.
moral powers. The first is the capacity for an They all want to assure the minimal welfare,
effective sense of justice which is the capac- resources, or opportunities (in Rawlsian ter-
ity to understand to apply and to act from minology, the minimal amount of primary
the principles of justice. The second moral goods) that enable human beings to realize
capacity is “to form, to revise and rationally their essential nature as moral persons. In
to pursue a conception of the good” (Rawls, other words, to provide moral persons with
1980, 525). This power expresses people’s the minimum they need for maintaining their
autonomy. Correspondingly, Rawls pre- moral capabilities.
sumes that moral persons are motivated by Such an approach, that considers justice
two highest order interests: to realize and to as related to institutions rather than to indi-
exercise these powers. In addition they have vidual outcomes, identifies distributive jus-
another interest, not a highest but a higher tice with social justice, as for example Barry
interest “in protecting and advancing their does (Barry, 1989, 355). Accordingly, justice

80
DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

becomes an attribute of institutions, and the between Equality of Welfare and Equality
justice of institutions deals with the way they of Resources is one of the most illuminat-
distribute benefits and burdens. For Barry, ing (Dworkin, 1981). Equality of welfare is
“the currency of social or distributive justice the attempt to make people equal “in terms
is one of rights and disabilities, privileges and of happiness or the extent to which people’s
disadvantages, equal or unequal opportuni- desires are satisfied” (McKerlie, 1989, 475).
ties, power and dependency, wealth (which Equality of resources relates to the distribu-
is a right to control the disposition of cer- tion of possessions and services like wealth,
tain resources) and poverty” (ibid.). To some property, medical care, and so on (ibid.).
extent, distributive justice regards institu- Dworkin prefers the version of equality of
tions as creators of burdens and benefits, and resources, mainly since we cannot really
is aimed at their appropriate distribution. decide which of people’s desires and expec-
The content and meaning of “appropriate” tations would be considered as legitimate,
or “just” distribution and what should be for whom, and how should we compare the
distributed, to what extent and range is the extent to which people realize their expecta-
subject matter of each theory of distributive tions and desires. Equality of resources is more
justice. applicable and measurable, and can function
We have already mentioned Rawls’s view as a criterion for comparison between peo-
which refers to “primary goods” as what ple. Thus, for the context of social justice, we
should be distributed, and the least advan- should suit our distributional scheme to the
taged groups as those who should have pri- concept of equality of resources. However,
ority in the distribution. His justification for unlike Rawls, who compares between groups
this approach was that primary goods are and imposes his distributional scheme on
necessary for the development of a person’s groups, Dworkin denies that groups should
moral abilities, and that it is rational or logi- function as the reference for distribution
cal for people who want to reduce risks, to or comparison between people’s classes. In
choose this distributional scheme. He uses any event, he considers Rawls’s difference
the model of people behind a veil of igno- principle as an interpretation of equality of
rance who use the maximin principle which resources, but insists that any distribution of
leads them to make a rational choice based resources should apply only to individuals
upon enlightened self-interest, which leads and not to classes (Dworkin, 1981).
them to favor of a principle that distributes
resources to the least advantaged group, and THE CAPABILITIES APPROACH
which promotes equality of opportunity. (OR THE HUMAN DEVELOPMENT
APPROACH)

This approach was developed and elaborated


OTHER SCHEMES OF DISTRIBUTION by Sen and Nussbaum, and roughly defined
as “an approach to comparative quality-of-
DWORKIN’S VIEW life assessment and to theorizing about social
justice” (Nussbaum, 2011, 18). This approach
Among many ways of interpreting what focuses on choice and freedom, and main-
should be distributed, Dworkin’s distinction tains that the key question for comparing

81
Ovadia Ezra

between societies and for assessing basic these capabilities and enjoy a dignified and
decency and justice is “what is each person flourishing life.
able to do and to be” (ibid.). Regarding each Unlike Rawls’s theory, which concentrates
individual as an end this approach does not on the distribution of primary goods, Sen’s
deal with the total or average well-being, view concentrates on opportunities. In The
but with the opportunities which are open Idea of Justice, Sen presents the capabilities
to each individual. Since individuals’ capa- approach as a “general approach, focusing
bilities differ between different individuals on information on individual advantages,
not only in quantity but also in quality, this judged in terms of opportunities rather than
approach requires that we try to understand a specific ‘design’ for how a society should be
each person’s capabilities and demand that organized” (Sen, 2009, 232). Thus, he rejects
government and public policy improve the Rawls’s idea of primary goods, as a means
quality of peoples’ lives as defined by their for other things, while emphasizing that dis-
individual capabilities (ibid.). tributional scheme should be concentrated
Similar to Rawls’s demand that peo- on opportunities (ibid., 234).
ple should have the minimal quantity of The capability approach is based upon
primary goods to develop their moral two concepts. The first is functioning, which
capabilities, Nussbaum believes that each reflects the spectrum of things which a per-
government has to enable its citizens to pur- son may value doing or being. This spectrum
sue a dignified and minimally flourishing includes very basic desires such as being pro-
life. Thus, a decent or just political frame- tected against avoidable disease and complex
work should provide all its citizens with states or activities such as being part of a
at least a threshold level of what she calls community. The other concept is capability,
Central Capabilities. She mentions ten such which refers to combinations of function-
capabilities: ings which are actually feasible for a person.
This makes capability the substantive free-
  1. Life dom to achieve various lifestyles (Sen, 1999,
  2. Bodily Health 75). The capability approach is demand-
  3. Bodily Integrity ing us to expand the alternative function-
  4. Senses, Imagination, and Thought ing combinations from which a person can
  5. Emotions
practically choose. For this, there is a need
  6. Practical Reason
for two types of information: one is what
  7. Affiliation
  8. Other Species (in the sense of being able a person is able to choose, and the other is
to live with concern for animals, plants, what this person actually does, that is which
and the world of nature) alternative he or she practically realizes.
  9. Play The assessment of the realization of justice
10. Control Over One’s Environment (ibid., according to the capability approach should
33–34). not be measured in terms of the resources or
primary goods people actually hold, but in
However, this approach insists that we terms of “the freedom they actually enjoy to
should think of each individual’s specific choose the lives they have reason to value”
capabilities, and enable him or her to develop (Sen, 1992, 81).

82
DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE AND exclusion is an exclusion which is based on


EQUALITY OF OPPORTUNITY irrelevant, inappropriate, irrational, or
unreasonable grounds in obtaining the lim-
The prescriptive demands of many of the ited goods in question (Williams, 1962, 124–
current theories of distributive justice can be 125). Irrelevant grounds include race, gender,
reduced, either directly or indirectly, to the color, and socioeconomic background. In any
demand to provide people with real equal- event, what we seek when we translate dis-
ity of opportunity. Rawls argues this explic- tributive justice to equality of opportunity is
itly when insisting on terms of fair equality to reduce inequalities in people’s accessibility
of opportunity in his differential principle to goods which are necessary for the realiza-
of justice, while Sen demands it indirectly tion of their essence as human beings.
by insisting on people’s freedom to choose,
and this practically means a demand to
enlarge people’s opportunities. The first and
foremost implication of the interpretation FROM THEORY TO PRACTICE
of distributive justice in terms of equality
of opportunity is the claim that distributive For those who consider distributive justice
justice does not intend to achieve equality not only as a theoretical issue but also as a
in consequences, results, or achievements. It policy that should be applied, governmental
does require that people be able to realize action is acutely necessary for promoting
certain capabilities or essential characteris- justice. However, governmental control of
tics we ascribe to them while regarding them the just distribution of benefits and burdens,
as human beings. Translating this idea into as well as policy that aims at promoting dis-
political theory means that we try to reduce tributive justice are not the only means for
inequalities in people’s access to goods which achieving this aim. Indeed, the state as the
they need, value, or desire (depending on the major framework within which people con-
theory of distributive justice with which we sider themselves as sharing common (and
deal). Williams, for example, argues that the often mutual) obligations and loyalties is
concept of equality of opportunity is designed the main factor in regulating the distribu-
to secure certain goods for every member of tion of benefits and burdens among its citi-
society. This term becomes relevant to politi- zens, first and foremost through legislation
cal discourse when we deal with access to and official practices, statutes, and policy.
three kinds of goods: (1) goods desired by all But a significant role in reducing social and
or most people; (2) goods which are said to economic inequalities in society is fulfilled
be earned or achieved; or (3) goods which are by nongovernmental and private bodies and
not available to all who desire them. What organizations.
we try to assure through a distributional Many social and economic practices have
policy which tries to promote equality of their roots in the idea of distributive justice,
opportunity, according to Williams’s view, is and they became so frequent and familiar
that limited goods will not be distributed in that their comprehensive acceptance causes
a way that a priori excludes any person who us to forget their principal grounds. The idea
may desire them. What he means by a priori of differential taxation, which takes a larger

83
Ovadia Ezra

share of taxes from those who earn more and backgrounds the chance of being full-fledged
exempts those who earn a minimal wage, members of their society. In any event, many
or even the whole idea of social security, governmental initiatives to promote distribu-
expresses the concept of distributive justice. tive justice remain within the boundaries of
In Rawlsian terms, we have already inserted nation-states, expressing social responsibility
certain requirements of distributive justice for citizens, assuming that this is the duty of
into the basic structure of society. the government.
However, there are other, more contro- However, many of the current programs
versial, policies, such as affirmative action that promote distributive justice are carried
programs (either through hiring for desired out either by private or by public nongovern-
positions or through the acceptance of mental bodies and institutions (sometimes
members of deprived groups to prestigious with governmental support or coordination,
programs in higher education institutions), and many times separately and free of any
became familiar practices in society, while governmental involvement). The withdrawal
being backed, promoted, and even sup- of governments from many social and wel-
ported by governments. Another controver- fare domains on the one hand, and the rise
sial practice is the estate tax or inheritance of the civil society as a significant factor in
tax. This tax in its various versions becomes society and communal life, imposes social
an effective, as well as available instrument responsibility on many nongovernmental
to redistribute the incredible wealth which organizations, some of which are local, but
is sometimes held by a few people in many many are part of international movements
modern countries. This tax is one of the most and organizations. These organizations take
significant means for reducing economic ine- responsibility and try to improve the welfare
qualities in society. of people, not only in their own countries,
There are many other practices, statues, but also in other deprived areas.
regulations, and policies through which gov-
ernments, directly and indirectly, try to mini-
mize poverty, reduce inequality, and promote
distributive justice among their citizens. The GLOBAL DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE
acceptance of these practices as well as of
many others during the last two generations The moral principles that justify distributive
resulted partly from the acknowledgment of justice within the state can also be used, to
basic welfare rights that should be assured to some extent and with appropriate modifica-
every human being in an enlightened society, tions, at the international level. These prin-
but mainly from the immense accumulation ciples become relevant to the global sphere
of wealth which is held in many countries by if we adopt the idea of the essential equal-
very few people and causes incredible ine- ity in value between all human beings, as
qualities between people who belong to the such, regardless of the question where they
same social and political frameworks. These live or act. Considering all people as shar-
inequalities pushed governments to carry ing this essential characteristic enables us to
out rehabilitation initiatives and legislation say that the mutual responsibility and soli-
that were meant to reduce these inequalities, darity among human beings should not end
and give people from deprived groups and or stop at the borders of their own political

84
DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

framework or state. The situation where question, the discussion should concentrate
there are huge differences in the very basic on the extent to which rich countries should
elements of human life, first and foremost in help the poor, and why, after all, the duty to
life expectancy and nutrition, between people help the poor remains within the framework
in different countries, has made the demand of national states and international organi-
for international efforts to reduce such ine- zations, rather than being understood as a
qualities an urgent moral imperative. duty which is imposed on every human being
In the background of this urgency lay wherever he or she lives.
the appalling statistics on people’s welfare There are several ways to deal with the
around the world, which indicate marked first question, regarding the need to disre-
differences between rich and poor countries gard the boundaries of states when distrib-
even in the twenty-first century. For example, uting resources. One is the humanitarian
while the World Bank defines the level of $2 approach which was offered by Singer and
(US) a day as the global poverty line, and the elaborated and developed by Barry. This
level of $1.25 as the extreme poverty line, in argument presumes:
2005, about 900 million people lived under
this line.2 Other statistics indicate a differ- 1. That the suffering or dying from lack of
ence of 30 years in life expectancy between food, shelter, or medical care is morally
rich countries and poor countries.3 In 2008, bad.
about 8.8 million children under the age of 2. If we can prevent something bad from
happening with a minimal sacrifice, we
5 years died, and about 40 percent of them
morally ought to do it.
came from three countries: India, Nigeria,
and the Democratic Republic of the Congo.4
These and other distressing data raised the This rationale brings Barry to follow
demand for global justice, and not only char- Singer and conclude that “humanity requires
ity, benevolence, or good will. that rich countries give aid to poor ones”
(Singer, 1972, Barry, 2008).
Another way to justify the transfer of
resources from rich countries to the poor
JUST DISTRIBUTION IN THE comes from the concept of justice. Here there
GLOBAL SPHERE are several ways of justifying this transfer.
One is the claim that there should be a global
For those who principally accept the idea of distribution of resources, since their natural
distributive justice within the state, there is location is arbitrary, and in the same man-
still a need to show why people in a certain ner that we try to repair the arbitrariness of
country should care about people in other distribution of resources and wealth within
countries, with whom they allegedly do the state, we should do so at the global
not have any formal or legal relations, and level. This argument presumes that nation-
thus do not feel any communion. In other states have no exclusive rights on the natural
words, why should distributive justice and resources which are located on their terri-
mutual social responsibility expand beyond tory, and these resources should be globally
the borders of the nation-state? After giv- redistributed. Such an argument is raised, for
ing a reasonable or accepted answer to this example, by Beitz (2008).

85
Ovadia Ezra

The idea of Global Distributive Justice or the dominant political conception. Indeed,
has a more comprehensive view not only on cosmopolitanism gives the strongest ground
the distribution of benefits and burdens, but and justification for a global distributive jus-
also on the way we consider peoples’ mutual tice, since its central idea is “that every human
interactions and interrelations on this planet. being has a global stature as an ultimate unit
The essential core of the demand for a global of moral concern” as Pogge puts it (Pogge,
distributive justice is our belief that the tradi- 2002, 169). Pogge, whose central interest is
tional separation of intranational and inter- promoting human rights in the global sphere,
national relations should be broken. Pogge, suggests the idea of cosmopolitanism as a
one of the most profound current theorists ground for assuring human rights for indi-
of Global Justice, and Follesdal give moral viduals wherever they are. His ethical con-
and geopolitical reasons for this conceptual cept of Interactional Cosmopolitanism refers
reorientation. Their political claim is that the to the conduct of persons and groups, and
traditional concept of international relations assigns responsibility for the fulfillment of
as consisting only of states is untenable due human rights on other individuals. However,
to the stature of other factors in the interna- for the matter of justice, he needs a politi-
tional stage, such as multinational corpora- cal concept: Institutional Cosmopolitanism.
tions, international organizations, regional This concept postulates certain fundamental
associations, NGO’s, and so on (Follesdal principles of social justice, and assigns the
and Pogge, 2005, 5). The ethical implication responsibility for the fulfillment of human
of this political situation is that people’s lives rights on international schemes (ibid., 170).
are now affected by decisions of external However, even Pogge realizes that “so long
institutions and bodies (the World Bank, the as there is a plurality of self-contained cul-
World Trade Organization, the International tures, the responsibility for unfulfilled human
Monetary Fund, etc.), so that it is no longer rights does not extend beyond their bounda-
morally plausible or adequate to consider ries” (ibid., 171). In such a world, instead of
the state governments’ interests as the only imposing principles of justice on rich states,
moral and political considerations relevant assuming that it is their moral obligation, the
for international relations. There is less and fulfillment of (mainly welfare and economic)
less sense in considering nation-states as human rights in developed countries remains
unique and ultimate whether as the owners dependent on their benevolence, and many
of the resources within their territories, or times is turned into charity. Pogge’s first and
the unique and ultimate bodies who repre- foremost justification for the demand to
sent the interests of their citizens (particularly impose global justice, that is, “to eradicate
in developing countries where governments the severe poverty that currently blights the
rule their citizens by force). Thus there is a lives of nearly half of the human population,”
need for expanding both the discussion and seems to many, particularly in rich countries,
practice of justice beyond the borders of as someone else’s problem (Pogge, 2010, 12).
states, and to consider distributive justice as Even though, as Pogge estimates, a 2 percent
something which should be implemented in shift in the distribution of global household
the global sphere. income can achieve this aim, there is a need
This does not necessarily require that we for a more convincing reason for recruiting
should adopt cosmopolitanism as the only a global effort to redistribute wealth and

86
DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

income between the rich and poor countries, WHY NOT GLOBAL RETRIBUTIVE
since the moral conception of social justice is JUSTICE AND COMPENSATION
still far from being universalistic or univer-
sally accepted. One way to justify the demand for justice
Pogge thinks that in order to be universalis- for the peoples of developing countries is
tic, a moral conception (such as that of social to appeal to principles of retributive jus-
justice) has to fulfill three conditions: First, tice. Such an appeal presumes that “many
it subjects all persons to the same system of things which are done in a world of inter-
fundamental moral principles; second, these national trade and economic activity should
principles assign the same moral benefits and be changed because they are in themselves
burdens to all; and third, these benefits and unjust” (Dower, 1993, 274). This injustice
burdens are formulated in general terms so as results from the exploitation of resources and
not to privilege or disadvantage certain indi- of cheap labor in the developing countries,
viduals or groups arbitrarily (Pogge, 2002, and the demand that rich countries, as ben-
92). So far, the global share of moral princi- eficiaries of this injustice, should “stop active
ples is far from being a reality, and still people injustice as well, and also make recompense
feel a lot more kinship and relation to people for what has been done” (ibid., 275).
from their own nationality, culture, religion, This call for compensation encounters
and even race and language. Thus, moral cos- several difficulties that raise doubts about
mopolitism is still far from being acceptable, its ability to establish a solid moral obliga-
and is currently considered as a utopian vision. tion on the part of the rich countries, and
Pogge may be right in his claim that the tra- an appropriate moral entitlement or a valid
ditional realm of international relations has claim for justice on the part of the poor coun-
undergone two major transformations—the tries. The main problem is that the acknowl-
proliferation of international, transnational, edged principles of retributive justice, since
supernational, and multinational actors (UN, their first use in Aristotle’s writings, require
EU, IMF, etc.) and the profound influence of that compensation be demanded from the
rules and activities of these organizations on person, institution, or group who is directly
the domestic life of national societies (Pogge, or indirectly responsible for the damage to
2010, 14). However, this process has not yet be compensated. Additionally, the compen-
been expressed in the ethical and political sation should be given to the direct or indi-
spheres. Thus, a sincere effort to promote glo- rect victim of the evil which grounds the
bal distributive justice should remain within demand for compensation. However, since
the political frameworks of states and govern- we demand justice and not charity (which is
ments, within which people still feel a certain usually an appeal to individuals, and requires
measure of solidarity and mutuality. However, mercy, kindness, and compassion), we wish
it should find common denominators where to impose the duty to carry out justice on
people in different states feel that their lives states. However, even though it is clear that
are linked together, and that they share some many of the residents of rich countries were
segments of life. This can establish, at least to beneficiaries of past exploitation, it is not
some extent, mutual responsibility between easy to transfer the duty of compensation
people, through the intermediation of their to the state. Additionally, some of the cur-
governments. rent rich countries were not involved in past

87
Ovadia Ezra

exploitation, and some did not exist until the current attempts to justify the assistance
recently as independent states, so imposing of poor countries by the rich are frequently
the duty to compensate for something in grounded on principles of distributive jus-
which they were not involved would be an tice, with the appropriate adjustments and
injustice in itself. This problem exists also on modifications of such principles to the global
the part of the recipients of the compensa- sphere.
tion. A country which was not exploited in
the past, but currently is extremely poor, will
not be assisted according to the principles of
retributive justice. GLOBAL DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE AND
In any event, the two main reasons for GLOBAL ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE
insisting on the demand for global distributive
justice rather than on demanding retributive The urgent need for a global cooperation and
justice are related to the desire to include as governmental responsibility for global acute
many countries as possible both on the part issues was not raised in the context of world
of the giving states, as well as on the receiving hunger or extreme poverty (which is Pogge’s
states. Currently rich countries which were and Singer’s main concern) but in the con-
not involved in past atrocities or exploitation text of the environmental crisis in general,
(such as Norway, e.g. whose wealth comes and the danger of global heat in particular.
from oil fields which just recently were dis- Until the end of the twentieth century this
covered in its territory) bear the duty to help crisis had been considered, like many other
poor countries not because of their past guilt, global issues, as something that should be
but because of demands for global distribu- dealt with exclusively by the developed and
tive justice (which will soon be presented). industrialized countries. Most of the coun-
The other reason refers to the identity of the tries considered as the main human cause of
receiving countries. There are many poor global warming, due to their massive share in
countries, whose misery does not necessar- greenhouse gas emission to the atmosphere,
ily result from exploitation, and sometimes it believed that it is their responsibility to
even results from internal conflicts and civil reduce that emission and to reduce the risk of
wars. If the assistance to poor countries will global heat. Indeed, the last international offi-
be dependent on past (or present) exploita- cial document before the twenty-first century
tion, such countries will not have a claim to that dealt with this issue, the Kyoto Protocol,
be assisted, something which might starve was an agreement that imposed burdens only
their citizens. The desire to impose the duty on countries which were part of “Annex I” to
to help poor countries on every rich coun- the protocol, which were basically the indus-
try on the one hand, and to include every trial countries.5 On developing countries,
poor country on the receiving side, makes this protocol did not impose any obligations
retributive justice insufficient to establish a to reduce emissions. This protocol expressed
demand for imposing principles of global the separation of the world into rich, indus-
justice. We should demand justice from rich trialized, and developed countries on the one
states regardless of their liability or account- hand, and poor and developing countries
ability for past evils, and assist poor coun- on the other. Accordingly the world order,
tries regardless of past exploitation. Thus including the share of benefits and burdens,

88
DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

was considered as something that should be domination to the industrial countries on


arranged, controlled, and dominated by the distributing global burdens and benefits.
rich and developed countries. Adopting the Not surprisingly, even at this meeting there
traditional attitude toward the global dis- was a secret document that was prepared by
tribution of benefits and wealth, which left the Danish delegation and a few members of
the developing countries outside the circle developed countries, which was called “the
of decision making, this protocol regarded Danish Text.” This document gave the rich
developing countries as passive, and thus, left countries the power to dominate the distri-
them outside the circle of the international bution of the huge amount of money that
efforts to reduce the danger of global heat. was supposed to be distributed to poor coun-
Global distribution of wealth was still con- tries for their share in the final agreement.
sidered to be charity and dependent on the However, this time the developing countries
good will and benevolence of the rich coun- rejected the idea that the distribution of
tries that control the world, for better or for benefits and burdens would exclusively be
worse. In the same manner, global distribu- decided by rich countries, and demanded to
tion of burdens, such as greenhouse gas emis- have a say in global issues, maintaining that
sions, remained a problem for rich countries their preferences and needs should be seri-
to deal with. ously considered at the global level.
The results of the Kyoto Protocol were That conference ended with an informal
disappointing, largely because the major agreement between the United States, and
country responsible for greenhouse gas emis- “the BASIC countries,” China, India, Brazil,
sions at that time, namely the United States, and South Africa, which threatened that they
did not join and sign the protocol. Another walk out of the conference if the developed
factor that raised the need to expand the cir- countries forced their own terms on the
cle of states which should reduce greenhouse developing countries. Even though the final
emissions was the rapid industrial develop- agreement was imperfect, it raised, for the
ment in some developing countries, first and first time, the need to associate also poor
foremost, in the most populated states in the countries in decisions regarding the global
world: China and India. This development distribution of benefits and burdens.6 This
caused an increasing use of energy both for event established a new way of considering
private use (such as private cars and home global distributive justice.
electricity) and for the use of huge indus- Previous environmental disputes such as
trial corporations and factories which were the deforestation of rain forests, referred
immensely enlarged. At this point, develop- only to the countries that should be involved
ing countries became a factor that was no in the solution to those disputes (in this
longer marginal when considering the global example, those countries within which there
distribution of benefits and burdens, at least are rain forests). With regard to the prob-
with regard to greenhouse gas emission. This lems that might be caused by climate change,
made the Copenhagen conference on climate every country is involved, at different levels
change in December 2009, a unique oppor- and to different extents, both in causing the
tunity for developing countries to express problem, and more importantly, in resolving
their presence in the global political sphere, it. The need to reduce greenhouse gas emis-
and their objections to the concept that gave sions even in poor countries raised other

89
Ovadia Ezra

problems, such as poverty, health, life expect- are located up in the atmosphere becomes
ancy, child mortality, illiteracy, and so on, a factor in considering the common destiny
as problems that should be globally solved, down on earth, as well as beneath it. This is
through genuine global distributive justice, the new and promising way to enforce global
and not through charity. In this manner, the distributive justice on those for whom moral-
demand that poor countries should share the ity and ethical considerations of justice were
burden of reducing emissions to the com- not convincing enough until the recent crisis
mon atmosphere would be balanced by the of climate change appeared. Utterances such
demand that the rich countries should share as that of the former US President George H.
the burden of reducing absolute poverty on W. Bush, that “the American way of life is
the common planet. not negotiable”7 became no longer relevant
The connection between Global Distributive when it was realized that the Chinese and
Justice and Global Environmental Justice Indian way of life should also be negotiable.
follows previous attempts to challenge
the exclusive rights of countries to benefit
from the resources which are found within
their territories. These attempts refer to the PRACTICES AND AIMS OF GLOBAL
arbitrariness of the distribution of natural DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE PROJECTS
resources such as oil and minerals among AND INITIATIVES
states, and demand that at least a small part
of the benefits from these resources should We saw earlier that in Domestic Distributive
be globally distributed. Politicians in rich Justice the minimal demand is only to reduce
countries (as well as many libertarian theo- outrageous inequalities and to provide each
rists) have difficulties in accepting or even member of society with the minimal welfare
understanding this type of argument, in the necessary for developing moral abilities and
same manner as politicians in developing preserving human nature. In the same manner,
countries such as Brazil have difficulties in we do not look for global equality; nor do we
considering the rain forests as something ask that developing countries enjoy the wel-
whose treatment and use should involve glo- fare and standard of living in developed coun-
bal considerations. However, the dangers of tries (which is significantly varied among and
the new environmental crisis are much easier within the rich countries too). We also content
to understand. It is much easier to consider ourselves with minimizing greenhouse gas
the atmosphere as common, and the green- emissions in industrial countries, but we do
house gas emissions as something whose not expect them to reach the levels of devel-
usage should involve global considerations, oping countries. We will be satisfied with rea-
and should be distributed under conditions sonably and responsibly restricting the use of
of justice and fairness. The territorial myth energy, and with restraining uncontrollable
about the exclusiveness of national coun- irresponsibility in the matter of greenhouse
tries to use the natural resources beneath gas emissions. The same modesty and mini-
their land is no longer convincing when we malism characterizes current initiatives and
speak about resources which are located practices of global distributive justice.
above those countries’ land. Thus, the com- The first comprehensive and sincere ini-
mon destiny that results from dangers which tiative to reduce extreme poverty began in

90
DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

1970, and demanded that the governments pricing in exchange for a reward based on the
of the rich countries should commit 0.7 per- global health impact of their new medicines.
cent of their Gross National Product (GNP) Companies who register with this project sell
to the Official Development Assistance the medicine globally at cost, and in return
(ODA) project for the poor countries. This receive for a fixed time, payments based on
target had not yet been achieved (and will the product’s assessed global health impact.
not be achieved until 2015), but in 2002, the Since this project has a huge budget, which
United Nations began a comprehensive and is divided up in proportion to the assessed
ambitious project that expresses a genuine health impact of each product each year,
desire to realize global solidarity and mutual firms have an interest to earn a share of the
responsibility through distributive justice: money by developing and distributing new
the UN Millennium Project.8 This project medicines to obtain the largest possible global
has 8 goals and 18 targets. The first goal is to health impact.9 This project promotes global
eradicate extreme hunger and poverty. This distributive justice by encouraging medicine
aim is to halve the number of people who producers, as well as state governments to
live in extreme poverty and hunger between go beyond the usual market economy and
the years of 1990 and 2015. The second goal consider a more comprehensive and consider-
to be achieved by 2015 is that every girl and ate way to benefit from their products. Such
boy everywhere will be able to complete a projects have more chance of being successful,
full course of primary schooling. Another since they offer a model that gives profit to
goal is to reduce by two-thirds childhood the producers of goods, and make these goods
mortality rates between 1990 and 2015, and available for many who otherwise would not
by three-quarters maternal mortality rates. be able to enjoy them.
Other goals are to combat HIV/AIDS and Another project is The United Nations
malaria, and more. What we see is that when Collaborative Programme on Reducing
we speak of Global Distributive Justice, we Emissions from Deforestation and Forest
content ourselves with minimal demands Degradation in Developing Countries.
such as reducing extreme poverty, hoping This program was launched in September
that even on these minimal goals, the inter- 2008, and is aimed at Reducing Emissions
national community will be able to establish from Deforestation and forest Degradation
a consensus, and allocate financial and mate- (REDD) in developing countries. This project
rial resources. connects many organizations, such as the
Today there are many projects that are Food and Agriculture Organization of the
run by private institutions and NGO’s that United Nations (FAO), the United Nations
are much smaller than the UN Millennium Development Programme (UNDP), and the
Project, but many of them are quite successful. United Nations Environment Programme
One example of such a project is The Health (UNEP).10 Together with its continuing pro-
Impact Fund whose president is Pogge. This gram REDD+, this project hopes to help
project tries to make new medicines which developing countries not only to reduce
are protected by patents accessible also to emissions but also to internalize the ideas
poor people in poor countries. The project of conservation, sustainable management of
is financed by governments and donors and forests, and enhancement of forest carbon
offers patentees the option to forgo monopoly stocks.11

91
Ovadia Ezra

Projects such as the REDD shows that WORKS CITED


the environmental crisis puts people around
the world under common dangers, exposes Aristotle (1947), “Nicomachean Ethics,”
them to common threats, and in some sense in R. McKeon (ed.), Introduction to
creates a common destiny for all people. Aristotle. New York: The Modern
Overcoming these threats requires a new Library.
concept of social justice which regards Barry, B. (1989), Theories of Justice.
people as both subjects and addressees of Berkeley, CA: University of California
the demands for justice. The traditional Press.
approach in which distributive justice was — (2008), “Humanity and Justice in Global
limited only to the national or domes- Perspective,” in T. Pogge and
tic boundaries becomes less and less rel- D. Moellendorf (eds), Global Justice.
evant, and in many senses has already been St. Paul, MN: Paragon House.
replaced by a more global concept. Beitz, C. R. (2008), “Justice and
International Relations,” in T. Pogge and
D. Moellendorf (eds), Global Justice.
Notes St. Paul, MN: Paragon House.
Dower, N. (1993), “World Poverty,” in
1
http://www.un.org/en/documents/udhr/ P. Singer (ed.), A Companion to Ethics.
2
http://www.adb.org/Documents/Presentations/ Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.
New-Poverty-Estimates/Poverty-Data-
Dworkin, R. (1981), “What is Equality?
Implications.pdf
3
http://www.commondreams.org/ Part 1: Equality of Welfare,” Philosophy
archive/2007/09/07/3697 and Public Affairs, 10 (3) (Summer):
4
http://www.unicef.org/childsurvival/ 185–246; and “What is Equality? Part 2:
index_51095.html Equality of Resources,” Philosophy and
5
For the English version of the protocol see:
Public Affairs, 10 (4) (Fall): 283–345.
http://unfccc.int/key_documents/kyoto_proto-
col/items/6445.php — (1986), A Matter of Principle. Oxford:
6
It demanded of the United States, for Clarendon Press.
example, to reduce only 4 percent greenhouse — (1977), Taking Rights Seriously.
gas emission between 1990 and 2020, while Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
China should reduce emissions between
Follesdal, A. and Pogge, T. (2005),
25 percent and 40 percent between the years
of 2005 and 2020, and India between “Introduction,” in A. Follesdal and
20 percent and 25 percent between 2005 and T. Pogge (eds), Real World Justice.
2020. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Springer.
7
http://www.theguardian.com/environment/ Hayek, F. A. (1976), Law Legislation and
2012/jun/19/rio-20-earth-summit-1992-
Liberty, Vol. 2. London and Henly:
2012
8
http://www.unmillenniumproject.org/goals/gti. Routledge & Kegan Paul.
htm#goal1 — (1978), New Studies in Philosophy,
9
http://healthimpactfund.org/the-health-impact- Politics, Economics and the History of
fund-a-summary-overview/ Ideas. London and Henly: Routledge &
10
http://www.un-redd.org/About
Kegan Paul.
UNREDDProgramme/tabid/583/Default.aspx
11
http://www.un-redd.org/AboutREDD/ McKerlie, D. (1989), “Equality and Time,”
tabid/582/Default.aspx Ethics, 99 (April): 475–491.

92
DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

Nozick, R. (1974), Anarchy, State and Politics and Society, 5th edn. Oxford:
Utopia. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Basil Blackwell.
Nussbaum, M. C. (2011), Creating — (1980), “Kantian Constructivism in
Capabilities. Cambridge, MA: The Moral Theory,” Journal of Philosophy,
Belknap Press of Harvard University LXXVII (9): 515–572.
Press. Sen, A. (1992), Inequality Reexamined.
Pogge, T. (2002), World Poverty and Human Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Rights. Cambridge: Polity Press. Press.
— (2005), Global Institutions and — (1999), Development as Freedom. New
Responsibilities: Achieving Global Justice. York: Alfred A. Knopf.
Malden, MA: Blackwell. — (2009), The Idea of Justice. Cambridge,
— (2010), Politics as Usual. Malden, MA: MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard
Polity Press. University Press.
Postema, G. J. (1989), “In Defense of Singer, P. (1972), “Famine, Affluence and
`French Nonsense: Fundamental Rights Morality,” Philosophy and Public Affairs,
in Constitutional Jurisprudence,” in B. 1(3): 229–243.
Zenon and M. Neil (eds), Enlightenment, Thomson, J. J. (1990), The Realm of Rights.
Rights and Revolution. Aberdeen: Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Aberdeen University Press. Press.
Rawls, J. (1971), A Theory of Justice. Williams, B. (1962), “The Idea of Equality,”
Oxford: Oxford University Press. in P. Laslett and W. G. Runciman (eds),
— (1979), “A Well-Ordered Society,” in Philosophy, Politics and Society (Second
P. Laslet and J. Fishkin (eds), Philosophy Series). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

93
6
REASSESSING PUNISHMENT:
RETRIBUTIVE VERSUS
RESTORATIVE JUSTICE
Trudy D. Conway

Justice must always question itself, just as society can exist only by means of the work it does on
itself and on its institutions. (Foucault, 1983)

Punishment is clearly an institutional prac- In June 2013 Paula Cooper, a ­16-year-old


tice worth questioning. Yet most of us, rarely sentenced to death by electrocution, was
notice or think about it, let alone rigorously released from an Indiana prison at the age
question its rationale, reach, and repercus- of 43. Cooper had been sentenced to death
sion. Removed from the everyday activities for the 1985 petty robbery and brutal
of our lives, we are not struck by questions murder of Ruth Pelke, a 78-year-old Bible
raised behind the secured doors of court- teacher. Initially passionately supportive of
rooms and prisons. Yet the questions remain, Cooper’s execution, Pelke’s grandson Bill
haunting lives shaped by the work of these became an equally passionate participant in
institutions. Are these institutions focused national and international efforts to overturn
on retributive justice (the assigning of what Cooper’s death sentence (King, 2003, Pelke,
is justly due to violators of the law), restora- 2003). In 1989, the Indiana Supreme Court
tive justice (the reparative healing of persons commuted Cooper’s sentence to 60  years, a
and relations damaged by offenders), or the sentence further reduced for good behavior
avoidance of injustice (the deterring of disor- and engagement in educational and service
der causing misery); are courts and prisons activities. During her imprisonment, Cooper
institutions for manifesting the power of the completed a high school and college degree
state, furthering individual and communal correspondence program and served as a
well-being or maintaining entrenched societal trainer of companion dogs for disabled per-
structures and orders? Victims and offenders sons and inmate counselor. Based on her
are thrust into questions not surfacing within behavior, Paula received permission to par-
the daily concerns of many persons. ticipate in a work release program enabling
her to contribute earnings to victim support
*** programs. Meeting with Cooper upon her

95
Trudy D. Conway

release, Pelke reiterated his commitment to of such action. Social biologists argue that
supporting her efforts to begin life anew fol- instinctual responses of anger are a result of
lowing 28 years of imprisonment. In a 2004 our evolutionary development, for human
Indianapolis Star interview, Cooper stated survival required responses conveying that
that, “Everybody has a responsibility to do harmful wrongdoing would not go unad-
right . . ., and if you do wrong, you should be dressed. The call for punishment appears to
punished,” adding that “rehabilitation comes be traceable to this elemental and visceral
from you. If you’re not ready to be rehabili- response. In raising children, failures to care
tated, you won’t be.”1 about and respond to harmful wrongdoing,
be it by children or caretakers, justifiably
JUST RETRIBUTION elicit concern. Callous indifference to harms
done to others reveals a narrow focusing
Paula Cooper’s punishment, commutation, on self-concern. Aristotle describes anger as
and release focus well a range of responses to a response to perceived injustice, slight, or
fundamental questions about state responses injury, while recognizing the challenge of
to illegal wrongdoing. They also bring us to responding with righteous anger to the right
address the fundamental questions—why and person, at the right time, to the right extent,
how should the state punish? Since the time for the right duration, in the right manner,
of Socrates’s imprisonment and execution, and for the right reason (Aristotle, 1941,
philosophers have grappled with questions 1380–1381, 1999, 61–62, 80). Avoiding the
regarding punishment on both theoretical extremes of indifference or inappropriately
and practical levels. Historical, sociological, tepid anger and the varied forms of excessive
economic, psychological, and legal consid- anger, persons are called to work on cultivat-
erations have only deepened our awareness ing virtuous anger described as a righteous
of the complexity of punishment and our response leaning more toward the deficient
responses to it. The three decade span of the and evidencing a propensity toward mildness
Paula Cooper case reveals the reassessments and away from revenge (Aristotle, 1999, 26).
of approaches to punishment found in delib- A person who has cultivated such a response
erations about punishment since the trial “is ready to pardon, not eager to exact a pen-
of Socrates. Shifting historical emphases on alty” (61). While adumbrating the contours
retribution, deterrence, and restoration char- of such virtuous response, Aristotle cautions
acterize our deliberations about this human us to recognize the difficulty of hitting such
practice and institution. The last half century a mean, resulting in the virtuous response
of American society mirrors such shifting being “rare, praiseworthy, and fine” (29).
understandings of why and how the state Such righteous anger requires the exercising
should punish. of practical wisdom, seasoned deliberation
There appears to be agreement that harm- about how to respond to the anger-evoking
ful wrongdoing does and should evoke offender.
response; such reasoning is found within In a similar way, citizens hold states respon-
relationships, families, communities, and sible for responding to harmful wrongdoing.
civil societies. Failure to respond manifests This development took the power to impose
a callous disregard of persons who are, punishment away from private individuals,
could have been or could still be the targets establishing a legal system which retained a

96
REASSESSING PUNISHMENT

retaliatory principle, requiring that wrong- through deliberative institutions with codi-
doers suffer for their actions, but transferred fied guidelines and procedures. Punishment
its application from victims to the state. In exacted through a criminal justice system is
doing so, the legal system asserted the power thus seen as a matter of just retribution or
of the state against the law-violating offender, deserved “payback” for victims and mem-
allowing victims and affiliated persons to play bers of society. Some retributivists argue that
a role solely as witnesses in a process focused in feeling anger and demanding just retribu-
on due process and the rights of offenders in tion, society shows a level of respect for per-
the meeting out of punishment for legal viola- sons committing crimes in holding them to
tions. Such a state versus offender approach be free and responsible agents. Just retribu-
conducted through the adversarial roles tion is thus seen as a matter of rectificatory
of prosecutors and defense attorneys often justice, whereby we right wrongs, measure
sidelines the needs and concerns of victims for measure, by making the convicted suffer
and affiliated persons, thereby resulting in as the victim suffered. On the basis of this
the state focusing on a violation of the legal reasoning, graver crimes evoke greater anger
system. and demand greater punishment. Given
Private response came to be replaced by this, punishment must entail the infliction
a civic, suitably restrained system of public of some kind of pain, harm, deprivation,
punishment directed by the state through a or something normally considered undesir-
legal system providing for trials and pun- able and unpleasant. Such punishment must
ishment of convicted offenders. States were be administered by some rightful author-
invested with the responsibility of respond- ity according to reasonable standards and
ing to wrongdoing codified as illegal. In vio- procedures to a person judged guilty of an
lating laws binding citizens across and within offense against some publically codified law
generations in ways that make shared civic or rule. In focusing on the goal of just retri-
life possible, offenders anger members of bution, such a conception of punishment has
society who refuse to commit such offenses. a clear retrospective orientation. Herein pun-
Such offenders not only harm victims, but ishment focuses on condemning and righting
also violate the trust, goodwill, and solidarity past wrongs by giving offenders what they
essential to communal life. Acting as moral deserve. Thus retributive justice (pay back
free-riders, they benefit from, while violating, for wrongs done) allows for just rectification
the rule of law enabling civic life. The desire (righting of wrongs).
for retaliatory punishment stems from the Kant, a strong retributivist, sharpens the
expectation that such persons must be held focus of such a retributive approach to pun-
accountable for the wrongs they have com- ishment, laying the foundation for modern
mitted against fellow persons. Offenders are retributivist approaches.2 While recognizing
seen as the proper targets of righteous anger, a type of natural punishment through which
followed by the desire to retaliate and make the evil ways of persons result in their own
wrongdoers pay for their crimes in terms of suffering, Kant focuses on juridical punish-
just reciprocity. Law-abiding citizens seek ment imposed by the state on offenders. The
to be avenged by and through the law. The state punishes offenders simply and only
legal system came to be the surrogate of because it is the right thing to do, because
personal judgment and response channeled justice demands that it render to each what

97
Trudy D. Conway

each deserves. Thus guilt is the necessary the right of retaliation must be the only
and sufficient condition of punishment. principle regulating the decisions of judicial
According to Kant’s reasoning, in refusing deliberators. The principle of equality—like
to constrain their actions within the law with like—must set the mode and measure
and taking advantage of others’ law abid- of punishment thereby ensuring “pure and
ing, offenders willed their own punishment. strict legal justice” (139). Offenders can
In unbalancing the scales of justice, offend- thereby come to recognize, “Accordingly, any
ers obligate a legal rectifying of their wrongs. undeserved evil that you inflict on someone
The standard guiding the determination of else among the people is one you do to your-
justice must be ius or lex talionis, the right self. If you vilify, you vilify yourself; if you
or law of retaliation, governed by the princi- steal from him, you steal from yourself; if
ple of equality. Violations of societal laws are you kill, you kill yourself” (138). Thus the
seen as rationally demanding commensurate right of retaliation (ius talionis), when prop-
retaliation according to the talionic princi- erly understood, is the only principle which,
ple. The courts must use reason to determine in regulating a public court as distinguished
a punishment that fits and thereby equalizes from private, individual judgment, can
the crime. Hegel reinforces such retributive assign both the quality and quantity of just
reasoning: “[T]he universal feeling of peoples punishment.
and individuals toward crime is, and always Kant’s strong retributivist reasoning is
has been, that it deserves to be punished, and shown most clearly in his succinct justifica-
what the criminal has done should be done to tion of capital punishment—“if .  .  . he has
him .. . . [E]quality remains merely the basic committed a murder, he must die.” Persons
measure of the criminal’s essential desert, convicted of murder must be executed
but not of the specific external shape which because “there is no juridical substitute that
the retribution should take .. . . It is then . . . will satisfy the requirements of legal justice”
a matter for the understanding to seek an (139). There is no equality between life, how-
approximate equivalence” (128–129). The ever miserable, and death, and therefore there
exclusive focus of punishment for retributiv- is no equality between the crime of murder
ists must be justice in response to an offender and the retaliation of it but what is judicially
having been found guilty of a criminal accomplished by the execution of the crimi-
offense. As Kant emphasizes, “Juridical pun- nal. Kant goes so far as to argue that even
ishment can never be administered merely if a civil society is to be dissolved through
as a means to promote some other good for the consent of its citizens, execution of mur-
the criminal himself or for civil society, but derers must occur prior to such dissolution,
instead it must in all cases be imposed on for otherwise the former citizens will bear
him only on the ground that he has commit- bloodguilt as accomplices in a public viola-
ted a crime; for a human being can never be tion of legal justice. Justice demands that no
manipulated merely as a means to the pur- wrong go unrectified through juridical pun-
poses of someone else .  .  . ” (138). Justice ishment. But, very importantly, Kant adds the
demands that convicted criminals pay in due requirement that such punishment must be
measure for the crimes they have commit- kept free of all inhumane maltreatment and
ted. Consequentialist preoccupations must be administered in accordance with a system
not mar the singular focus of punishment; of law that insures that only the deserving

98
REASSESSING PUNISHMENT

are punished following fair procedures of that entail acts that degrade the punisher or
judicial deliberation. Kant’s caveat is clear: the punished. Thus the range of punishment
justice and justice alone must determine the must be set within moral limits. In seeking just
justification, end, procedures, and means of retribution, we must not allow the humanly
punishment. degrading acts of offenders to dictate our
Interestingly, attentiveness to these Kantian punitive response. We stop short of punish-
stipulations brings some retributivists to cri- ments that cross a moral boundary, even if
tique forms of punishment judged by Kant to such punishment meets out what is retribu-
fulfill the requirements of retributive justice.3 tively deserved. Thus on the basis of evolv-
The history of forms of punishment clearly ing standards of decency, a proportionate,
manifests evolving standards of decency. rather than a strict, retributivism, is required.
We look with horror on past punishments In upholding such standards, society clearly
such as torturous stretching on the rack, states a refusal to retaliate in kind in all cases.
public stockades, chain gang labor, ston- Such refusals clearly demarcate the difference
ing, disemboweling, quartering, gassing, and between the punished and punisher.
electrocuting. Over time, our ways of pun- Such reasoning, drawing a limit to kinds
ishment have shifted from corporeal forms of morally acceptable punishments, can be
of punishing to forms restricting the exer- seen in the constitutional reviews of punish-
cising of rights and range of freedom. Even ment in light of the Eighth and Fourteenth
in response to extremely heinous crimes, a Amendments of the U.S. Constitution
retributive approach as articulated by Kant (“Excessive bail shall not be required, nor
does not necessarily require doing the same excessive fines, nor cruel and unusual punish-
kind of retaliatory act. It is thus reasoned that ment inflicted,” and no state shall “deprive
retributive justice requires proportionate, not any person of life, liberty or property, without
strictly identical, punishment. In some cases, due process of the law; nor deny to any person
it would be logically impossible to follow a within its jurisdiction the equal protection of
strict retributivism, for example in the case of the laws”). To be declared unconstitutional,
a serial killer. In other cases, moral concerns punishments need only be shown to be
restrict our punishment possibilities. Such a cruel and unusual or to violate due process.
proportionate retributivist approach assumes Heinously cruel acts cannot be punished by
there is a range of punishment. A punishment equally cruel responses; punishments cannot
beyond what is deserved would be unjust to be arbitrarily and randomly applied in unjust
the convicted offender; a degree of punish- ways. Numerous Supreme Court delibera-
ment below what is deserved would be unjust tions have seen the Justices reverse previous
to the victim. The upper limit of retributive rulings upholding the constitutionality of
punishment would strictly equal the crime, types of punishment, in light of such evolv-
fitting the demands of ius talionis exactly ing standards of decency as shown in, for
or as close as is possible. While retributively example, Atkins v. Virginia overturning Penry
just, such punishment would be unacceptable v. Lynaugh, Roper v. Simmons overturning
if it was judged to violate morally acceptable Stanford v. Kentucky/Thompson v. Oklahoma
forms of punishment. Just as we refuse to and Justices Stevens, Powell, and Blackmun’s
rape rapists and torture torturers in punish- reversals on the death penalty in the decades
ing them, so we must exclude all punishments following Furman v. Georgia (Cohen, 2013).

99
Trudy D. Conway

In 2008, Baze v. Rees ruled that Kentucky’s comparison with execution by electrocution
triple cocktail lethal injection method did or asphyxiation, is seen by some retributivists
not violate the Eighth Amendment, uphold- as not fulfilling the demand for retaliatory jus-
ing the primary execution method used in tice for heinously cruel offenses. Such current
the then current 35 retention states. Yet seven punishment is here interpreted to fail to return
Justices wrote separate opinions in this case, like with like for capital crimes. Responses
indicating that the Court is far from having such as this reveal the extent to which
reached a consensus regarding this method American society continues to wrestle with
of punishment. It is expected that new chal- the pure demands of retributive justice, while
lenges will emerge, as the Court continues to strongly emphasizing such an approach.
grapple with the standard expressed in In re
Kemmler in 1890 and still upheld that con- QUESTIONING RETRIBUTIVE JUSTICE
sistent with the Eighth Amendment, capital
punishment must result in nothing more than The Pelke family’s immediate response to
“the mere extinguishing of life” in response Ruth’s murder was to demand punishment
to the heinous taking of life. In an interesting equal to the crime committed. For them,
twist on retributive justification of types of anything less than that would be a travesty
punishment, retired Justice John Paul Stevens of justice. Some relatives expressed relief
argued that Justice John Roberts’s opinion in that the judge “had the guts” to give Paula
this ruling evidenced that the Court rejected exactly what she deserved—a death sen-
the premise that capital punishment serves tence. Over time Bill Pelke, Ruth’s grandson,
a retributive purpose. Drawing on chal- became deeply troubled by the demands of
lengeable assumptions about the practice of such retributivist reasoning which seemed
execution by lethal injection, Justice Stevens to cast the state in the role of Ruth’s right-
reasoned that eous avenger. While Kant esteemed the purity
and clarity of retributive justice, Pelke came
The Eighth Amendment has been con- to question the narrow restrictedness of this
strued to prohibit needless suffering and retrospective approach to punishment. Pelke
significant risks of harm to the defend- began a journey of inquiry bringing him to
ant. As a matter of constitutional law,
take a far more holistic and prospective
what was once a gruesome event has been
approach to punishment and to examine
transformed into a procedure compara-
ble to the administration of anesthesia in the concrete realities at play in the powerful
a hospital operating room. By requiring application of punishment. He came to rea-
that an execution be relatively painless, son that a conception of punishment exclu-
we protect the inmate from enduring any sively and narrowly focused on the state’s
punishment that is comparable to the righting past wrongs not only fails to address
suffering inflicted on his victim. We have the human suffering caused by wrongdoing,
thus undermined the premise on which but also results in compounding human suf-
public approval of the retribution ration- fering over time. He grew increasingly con-
ale is based. (218)4 cerned that a purely retributive conception
of punishment bracketed questions about
In an ironic twist of reasoning, lethal injec- the sources of criminal behavior and the con-
tion, viewed as a more humane punishment in sistency of application of punishment. Pelke

100
REASSESSING PUNISHMENT

began to delve deeper into questions about bomb detonating within him, shattering
the powerful reach of institutions exacting him into pieces. Tony Hicks was quickly
punishment and its impact on communi- named a suspect. Shortly before the murder,
ties. He suspected the narrow focus of just California had passed a “tough on crime”
retribution masked a more elemental desire law allowing adolescents under the age of 16
for retaliatory, anger-driven revenge. He to be prosecuted as adults. The new ruling
recognized that no punishment could ever changed everything in Tony’s life. Egged on
truly right the horrific wrong done to his to hold a pistol, angered by Tariq’s refusal
grandmother. Drawing on the principles that to give up the pizzas, and encouraged to
shaped her deepest convictions, Bill sought shoot, Tony fired the fatal shot. Azim found
more than a retrospective punishment. He it incredible that three 14-year-olds and an
sought a prospective punishment that might ­18-year-old had been arrested in connection
transform Paula Cooper—what he described with his son’s killing. Azim began to be trou-
as a civilized type of punishment that also bled by the chorus of voices crying for just
had a civilizing effect on the offender and retribution. From the paralysis of his grief
society. Recognizing Paula’s insight that she came his inspiration. Rather than having
would have to be the agent of such transfor- Tariq’s killer be the target of his anger, he
mation, he advocated a type of punishment would target the forces that contributed to
that would set up conditions encouraging this senseless act of juvenile violence. Rather
such an effect over time. than demanding retaliatory justice, Azim
Bill sought out members of Paula’s fam- threw his energy into building a foundation
ily to understand her past and the possibil- committed to ending youth violence. With
ity of such transformation; his contact with the support of Tony’s grandfather Ples and
Paula encouraged such development. As his eventually Tony himself, the Tariq Khamisa
understanding of an alternative approach to Foundation began to thrive. Their shared
punishment deepened, he worked to create commitment to the foundation transformed
a number of murder victim family member their lives, helping them to heal and Tony to
organizations focused on what came to be accept responsibility. Tony pleaded guilty to
termed “restorative justice.” Through one first-degree murder to avoid the pain a trial
of them, he encountered persons like Azim would cause these two families. Expressing
Khamisa who, on their own, had shaped an deep regret for his senseless act of violence,
alternate understanding of justice and a way he hoped for Azim’s forgiveness, which in
to live this understanding. Like Bill, Azim turn filled Azim with hope for this young
was thrown into reflection on punishment man’s moral transformation. After hear-
due to a personal tragedy (King 250–273). ing the sentence of 25  years to life, Azim’s
On January 21, 1995, a 19-year-old response focused on restorative rather than
California University student named Tariq retributive justice. He sought to relieve his
Khamisa began the final run of his pizza anger by working to heal and restore all
delivery shift. Realizing he has been set up persons affected by Tariq’s murder, and to
for a pizza-jacking, Tariq attempted to drive work to address conditions contributing to
away. At that moment, a bullet shattered the youth violence and prison recidivism. Azim
window taking his life. His father described and Ples collaborated on a school-based pro-
the news of his son’s death as a nuclear gram teaching that violence is an evil choice

101
Trudy D. Conway

with tragically irrevocable consequences for cautionary note regarding the risk of right-
a wide range of persons. Tony participated eous anger sliding into moral outrage and
through letters explaining his regrettable issuing in vengeance, since vengeance “is
choices and their wide-ranging repercus- not judgment—for judgment is, like justice,
sions. The program’s success led to national a good.” Rather vengeance is a consequence
recognition and funding and even more of moral failing (“iniquity”) and results in
importantly Tony’s deepening commitment further suffering, for “[h]e that meets it and
to living a better life. Azim encouraged Tony he that misses it are alike unhappy, the one
to participate in educational programming because he gets no healing . . ., the other in
and walk a straight path in prison, leading that he is cut off for the salvation of many
toward the possibility of his parole after another” (Laws, V. 728c). Plato’s comments
25 years and eventual work at their founda- on punishment in numerous dialogues do
tion. Azim gained strength through persons not deny an important retributive dimen-
like Bill Pelke who helped from an organi- sion in punishment, but speak to the need
zation, Murder Victims for Reconciliation, to avoid reducing punishment solely to this
which works to reorient the justice system dimension. Plato clarifies that ideally “judg-
from retributive toward restorative jus- ment by sentence of law is never inflicted for
tice. Over time both Bill and Azim came to harm’s sake. Its normal effect is one of two;
explore the complex contributing factors of it makes him that suffers it a better man, or
crime and the gravely unequal functioning failing this, less of a wretch” (Laws 854d).
of the criminal justice system as tied to hier- Punishment must be more than an exercise
archies of race and class. The pure demands in retributive justice, and retribution itself
of retributive justice began to ring hollow must be transformed from mere retaliative
the more they learned of the power of the matching of “like with like” to bringing
state in selectively and inequitably prosecut- offenders to recognize the harm they have
ing and punishing lower and upper class done and the debt they owe to the victim and
criminal behavior set across a racial divide. community harmed by their crime. Here, the
Both began to recognize competing strands emphasis shifts from what the state does to
of discourse found within their Christian offenders to what offenders owe to victims.
and Muslim traditions on the purpose and What is done to offenders is transformed
methods of punishment, pulling toward a into what offenders must sacrifice and do.7
purely, strictly retributive understanding or Retribution is thus transformed into restitu-
toward a more restorative understanding.5 tion and restoration. Plato emphasizes that
Since the late 1970s, there has been “one ought not to return a wrong or an
growing national and global interest in injury to any person, whatever the provoca-
programs focusing on restorative justice.6 tion is” (Crito 49d). Herein the focus sub-
Yet the philosophical reasoning underlying tly shifts from doing retaliatory harm to
such programs has been part of the philo- offenders suffering loss, pain, or sacrifice to
sophical tradition since its origins in ancient compensate for harm done by them to their
Greece. Aspects of the broader restorative victims. To be so transformed, punishment
approach to punishment affirmed by Pelke must engage offenders as moral beings. In
and Khamisa are traceable to the writings arguing that punishment must encour-
of Plato (1963). In the Laws, Plato issues a age recognition of both wrongs done and

102
REASSESSING PUNISHMENT

the need for restitution to victims for such of convictions and principles consistent
wrongs, Plato emphasizes that, with the orientation revealed in Plato’s
comments. Rather than narrowly focusing
the purpose of the penalty is not to cancel on retributive responses to legal violations,
the crime—what is once done can never they focus on addressing human harms and
be made undone—but to bring the crimi- needs—the needs of crime victims, local
nal and all who witness his punishment
communities, and offenders. Crime victims
in the future to complete renunciation of
need the disclosure of truth—a recognition
such criminality, or at least to recovery
in great part from this dreadful state. For and acknowledgement of the harm done
all these reasons, and since it has all these by agents and a need to rectify the wrong
ends in view, the law must take careful in some way. Communities need recogni-
aim at its mark; it must be exact in deter- tion of the fact that crime violates shared
mining the magnitude of the correction values and damages all of us, rendering us
imposed on the particular offense, and, more vulnerable and less secure and trust-
above all, the amount of compensation ing. Offenders need to recognize and be held
to be paid. (Laws 934b) accountable for the harm they chose to do
to persons and provide restitution or repara-
A purely retributive approach always risks tion, even if only partial and symbolic due
masking what is rightly termed retaliatory to penal restrictions on their actions. Our
vengeance. In the Protagoras, Plato explains, adversarial judicial system works against
addressing such multiple needs. Often even
In punishing the wrongdoers, no one con- when sentenced, offenders are not encour-
centrates on the fact that a man has done aged to take responsibility for their action,
wrong in the past, or punishes him on that face the harms their actions have produced,
account, unless taking blind vengeance like
and act to rectify their offenses. Moral repa-
a beast. No, punishment is not inflicted by
ration for wrongs and harms often goes
a rational man for the sake of the crime
that was committed—after all one cannot unattended. Aristotle describes shame as a
undo what is past—but for the sake of the quasi-virtue which opens the possibility of
future, to prevent either the same man or, transformation. But this quasi-virtue in no
by spectacle of his punishment, someone way entails reducing the person to a shame-
else from doing wrong again . . . Whoever ful act in a way that counteracts transforma-
stays outside the lines [of the law], it pun- tion. Agents who feel shame recognize they
ishes, and the name given to this punish- could have chosen otherwise and can now
ment both among yourselves and in many do so; without this, there is no reason for
places is correction, intimating that the associating this response with the virtues.
penalty corrects or guides. (324b, 326e)
At the same time recognition of contribut-
ing factors in crime, even the extent to which
Repeatedly in numerous dialogues, Plato harms done to offenders contributed to
presents arguments in support of punishment their choices, plays a role in the promotion
that is more a matter of restorative justice rather of self-examination and transformation of
than merely reducible to retributive justice. offenders. Punishment should thus focus not
Restorative justice programs, although exclusively on retribution, but on bringing
varied in practice, focus on a constellation offenders to recognize and respond to the

103
Trudy D. Conway

need for moral, and in some cases material, to persons, and (4) rehabilitation of offend-
reparation for harms done to persons and ers. Howard Zehr, a leading spokesperson
communities. Such a restorative approach of this model, emphasizes that we should
to punishment is far more demanding than conceive of systems of punishment along a
a retributive one. While the American penal continuum between retributive and restora-
system remains focused on an adversarial tive justice approaches and attentively work
approach strongly oriented toward retribu- to move our criminal justice systems increas-
tive justice, a variety of programs and prac- ingly toward the restorative end of the spec-
tices inside and outside prisons foster a far trum. Zehr also stresses that the common
more restorative justice approach. focus of both approaches is rectificatory
At the center of restorative justice is the justice—the righting of wrongs; they differ
recognition of crime as entailing harms done in terms of their account of what actually
to persons within communities rather than rights wrongs. Retributive justice is seen as
mere legal transgressions. Restorative jus- righting the wrongs done through legal vio-
tice entails a paradigm or “lens” shift from lations by inflicting proportionate suffering
exclusively punitive responses to reparations on the culpable offender. In contrast,
for harms done by persons to persons. Such
harms include material and psychological Restorative justice theory argues that
damage to victims and affiliates, the ero- what truly vindicates is acknowledg-
sion of social trust and security, and dam- ment of victims’ harms and needs, com-
bined with an active effort to encourage
age done by offenders to themselves and
offenders to take responsibility, make
their affiliates. Restorative justice programs
right the wrongs, and address the causes
require that members of society address of their behavior. By addressing this
ways of preventing crime and of rehabili- need for vindication in a positive way,
tating persons who commit crimes, hold- restorative justice has the potential to
ing them responsible and accountable, but affirm both victim and offender and to
also capable of transformation. Refusing to help them transform their lives. (Zehr,
reduce offenders to their worst acts, such a 2002, 59)
restorative justice approach opposes punitive
measures that give up on offenders, defining Herein the focus shifts to harms done to vic-
them reductively and permanently as crimi- tims and communities and offenders coming
nals. Many restorative justice programs also to acknowledge the human consequences of
offer the option of restorative mediation their actions and the need to make restitution
between offenders and victims when volun- for such harms. Restitution to and support
tarily chosen and carefully counseled. Such of victims conveys their suffering is being
encounters play a significant role in both the taken seriously and encourages offenders to
moral transformation of persons sentenced respond constructively. From such a perspec-
to punishment and the healing process of tive, punishment would not be solely retribu-
crime victims. From such a broad perspec- tive, retrospectively righting wrongs from the
tive, punishment must serve multiple inter- past but would be prospectively directed to
woven ends—(1) protection of the common human transformation and restoration in the
good of persons in society, (2) restoration of context of community. As John Braithwaite
public order, (3) restitution for wrongs done emphasizes,

104
REASSESSING PUNISHMENT

[R]estorative justice involves a shift the settled tendency toward a purely retribu-
toward an active conception of respon- tive approach to punishment.
sibility, while still finding a more limited Much can be said in favor of such a
place for passive responsibility than is restorative approach to punishment and
standard in criminal jurisprudence. While
efforts to move the criminal justice system
passive responsibility means an offender
in that direction. Movement toward such an
being responsible for a wrong he has com-
mitted in the past, active responsibility is approach would modify, supplement, or pro-
a virtue, the virtue of taking responsibil- vide alternatives to the state-pitted-against-
ity for repairing the harm that has been the-offender adversarial model. In other
done, the relationships that have been societies such a restorative model has long
damaged. Restorative justice is about been the norm, as exemplified in the Afghani
creating spaces where not only offend- jirga practice, Navajo peacemaking courts,
ers, but also other concerned citizens will Maori conferencing practices, and aboriginal
find it safe to take active responsibility sentencing circles in native Canadian com-
for righting the wrong done. (342) munities. In recent years, international atten-
tion has been directed to noteworthy models
Some scholars argue that we must choose of restorative justice, such as South Africa’s
between a punishment paradigm and a restor- Truth and Reconciliation Commission and
ative paradigm (Ashworth, 1999). But Zehr’s indigenous practices fostering reconcilia-
continuum would seem to argue against such tion following grave violence, such as the
forced options. As Plato emphasized, we can Fambul Tok practice following the Sierra
reconceive punishment as being a part of or Leone internecine war, and the reconciliation
aiming at restoration of the offender and the practices following the Rwandan massacres.8
community. Numerous communities and local courts in
In the United States, restorative justice the United States have begun to institutional-
approaches have been focused largely on ize incrementally such restorative practices.9
juvenile offenses and minor adult offenses. A Awareness of this alternative model has very
reorientation toward restorative approaches gradually increased in the United States, but
to major adult offenses would entail a foun- for the most part American citizens continue
dational shift in this criminal justice system. to conceive criminal justice solely in terms
At present, restorative approaches tend to of the retributive model. The stark contrast
supplement rather than replace retributive between indigenous practices of restorative
approaches. Such a supplemental approach justice in other parts of the world and the
recognizes that a restorative approach may predominant Western model of punishment,
be unworkable in all cases, given that recalci- which now tends in a far more retributive
trant offenders and excessively vindictive vic- direction, raises another set of questions. Is
tims may undermine the possibility of such it the case that more restorative models tend
an approach. While recognizing this, the to be embedded in communities holding a
wide range of innovative restorative prac- far more communitarian conception of per-
tices developing in specific countries (such as sons in contrast to more liberal conceptions
New Zealand and Canada), local communi- emphasizing autonomous selves and pro-
ties, and particular corrections facilities fur- cedural justice focusing on protecting indi-
ther a restorative reorientation that balances viduals’ rights? The indigenous restorative

105
Trudy D. Conway

practices emphasized in response to grievous transformation seen in Paula Cooper and


harms found in the societies of South Africa, Tony Hicks. Such for-profit prisons risk
Rwanda, and Sierra Leone appear to be deeply reducing offender responsibility, transfor-
rooted in the conception of Ubuntu which mation, and reintegration in communities.
conceives persons as inextricably embedded A profit-making business model, an over-
in an interconnected network of interpersonal crowded penal environment, and increas-
relations.10 Emphases on restoration, recon- ing budgetary pressures work against the
ciliation, rehabilitation, and reconstruction orientation Zehr and Braithwaite encour-
stem from this fundamental core conception. age. In addition, relocating prisons from
Is it the case that a more liberal polity pulls local communities to remoter rural settings
toward one end of Zehr’s spectrum and a diminishes the possibility of familial and
more communitarian polity toward the other, communal relations which so often play a
lending toward more retributive or restora- role in personal transformation and reinte-
tive conceptions of punishment? gration. The constellation of such factors
While we have seen increased aware- greatly increases the likelihood of prisons
ness of the theory and practice of restora- being transformed into debilitating and
tive justice in the United States, significant crime ridden holding cells for recidivist
changes in the American criminal justice offenders.
system work dramatically against moving Failure to reorient the criminal justice
this system in a restorative direction. Mass system in a restorative direction will likely
incarcerations due to three-strike and rigid result in pushing this system toward the
mandatory minimum sentencing practices other end of the spectrum—toward a puni-
have resulted in prisons being transformed tive system that increasingly warehouses
into massive human warehouses of con- an endlessly increasing supply of offend-
victed felons.11 Such practices have resulted ers whose actions once evoked justifiable
in the United States: having the highest anger, who have been removed from local
incarceration in the world with 2¼ million communities, and are seen now as best for-
prisoners; while having 5  percent of the gotten, so long as they get their just deserts.
world’s population, having 25 percent of the Such an approach fosters recidivism, indif-
world’s prison population; 1 in every 107 ference to the plight of both victims and
adult Americans being in prison. The esca- offenders, and manifests a glaring failure to
lating prison population over the past three address the complexity of the sources, reali-
decades has resulted in massive overcrowd- ties, and consequences of crime that harms
ing and fiscal burdens, during a period of persons. Such a system tragically ends up
declining crime rates.12 Overcrowding and only remotely connected with the noble
stretched resources work against restorative concern of justice. Foucault’s warning is
approaches. In recent times, the outsourc- right. To be committed to justice requires
ing of prisons to for-profit corporations us to devote ourselves to examining cease-
that seek to minimize costs and maximize lessly our conceptions and practices of it.
profits decreases the availability of coun- This alone enables us to live justly with one
seling, spiritual ministry, and rehabilitative, another. We fail to do so at the risk of per-
educational, vocational, and reentry pro- petuating a current criminal justice system
gramming which contribute to the personal only remotely focused on justice. To do so

106
REASSESSING PUNISHMENT

diminishes not only our practicing of jus- of severe punishments and Sufi understand-
tice but also in the end our capacity for ings of Islamic punitive justice as being strictly
applicable only in societies that have already
even thinking about justice. As Plato rightly
fulfilled the demands of distributive and eco-
recognized in response to Socrates’ punish- nomic justice.
ment, our humanity is in peril if we fail to 6
The last four decades have produced a range
attend closely to justice. of philosophical and theological writings plus
more recent jurisprudence writings such as
John Braithwaite’s Restorative Justice and
Responsive Regulation (New York: Oxford,
Notes 2001), Clifford Dorne’s Restorative Justice
in the United States (Upper Saddle River, NJ:
See http://www.dailymail.co.uk/news/arti-
1 Prentice Hall, 2007), Johnstone and van Ness’s
cle-2343663/Paula-Cooper-released-Grandson- Handbook of Restorative Justice (Cullompton,
Bible-studies-teacher-murdered-1986-wants- UK: Wilan, 2006), and Sullivan and Tifft’s
killer-meal-shops-released-prison-yesterday. Handbook of Restorative Justice: A Global
html Perspective (London: Routledge, 2008).
2
See Kant’s Metaphysical Elements of Justice, 7
This shifts the interpretation of “an eye for
2nd edn (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1999). an eye” from the punisher damaging the
This chapter focuses on retributive approaches offender’s eye to retaliate his damaging of the
and contrasting restorative approaches. victim’s eye to the punished restoring the dam-
Overall, there have been three broad modern age done to the eye of the victim. See Buck for
approaches to punishment. From 1780 to an analysis of the commonly misunderstood
1860, debates focused on Kantian/Hegelian phrase.
retributive approaches and Bentham’s utilitar- 8
Documentaries have recorded these varied
ian approach. From 1860 through 1960, utili- practices found in South African, Rwandan,
tarian approaches were emphasized, followed and Sierra Leone communities. See Facing the
by a more retributive approach from the 1960s Truth with Bill Moyers (www.films.com), As
through today. Restorative justice approaches We Forgive (www.asweforgivemovie.com), and
began to gain attention in the 1980s. For Fambul Tok (www.fambultok.com).
such a broad historical overview, see Michael 9
Howard Zehr’s works offer a good intro-
Tonry’s “Thinking about Punishment,” in Why duction to restorative justice programming
Punish? How Much? (Tonry, 2011). models.
3
Jeffrey Reiman offers an example of this 10
See Desmond Tutu, No Future Without
reasoning in his “Justice, Civilization and the Forgiveness (New York: Doubleday, 1999) for
Death Penalty,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, a discussion of Ubuntu (31–32).
14, no. 2 (Spring 1985): 130. 11
In 2003, Ewing v. California ruled that a
4
Justice Stevens went on to add in his separate 25 year-to-life sentence for a third offence
opinion, “Quoting from an earlier opinion by consisting of the theft of three golf clubs did
Justice White, I stated that the death penalty not violate the Constitution’s ban on cruel
represents ‘the pointless and needless extinction and unusual punishment (583 U.S. 11). All
of life with only marginal contributions to any principled retributivists would condemn the
discernible social and public purposes’” (218). injustice of such a grossly disproportionate
5
Pelke still witnesses the divided Christian punishment.
conceptions of punishments as played out 12
http://www.economist.com/blogs/economist-
in the Southern Bible Belt’s fundamentalist explains/2013/08/economist-explains-8.
enthusiasm for the death penalty versus the In 2011, the Supreme Court ruled that
abolitionist activism of other Christian denom- California must drastically reduce its prison
inations. Khamisa’s Pakistani background population to relieve extreme overcrowding
discloses tensions between fundamentalist that exacerbates risks of violence, illness, and
demands for strict Sharia-based applications death.

107
Trudy D. Conway

WORKS CITED Hegel, G. (1999), “Wrong [Das Unrecht]


from Elements of the Philosophy of
Aristotle (1941), “Rhetoric,” in The Right,” A. Wood (ed.). New York:
Collected Works of Aristotle, trans. Cambridge University Press.
R. McKeon. New York: Random. In re Kemmler (136 U.S. at 447, 34 L. Ed.
— (1999), Nicomachean Ethics, trans. 519, 10 S. Ct. 930).
T. Irwin. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett. Kant, I. (1999), Metaphysical Elements of
Ashworth, A. (1999), “Some Doubts about Justice, 2nd edn. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.
Restorative Justice,” Criminal Law King, R. (2003), Don’t Kill in Our Names,
Forum, 4: 277–299. Families of Murder Victims Speak
Braithwaite, J. (2011), “In Search of Out Against the Death Penalty. New
Restorative Jurisprudence,” in M. Tonry Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers.
(ed.), Why Punish? How Much? Pelke, B. (2003), Journey of Hope . . . From
New York: Oxford, pp. 337–352. Violence to Healing. Bloomington, IN:
Buck, R. (2013), “Hebrew Scriptures—‘An Xlibris.
Eye for An Eye,’” in V. Schieber, T. Plato (1963), The Collected Dialogues of
Conway, and D. McCarthy (eds), Where Plato, E. Hamilton and H. Cairns (eds).
Justice and Mercy Meet. Collegeville, MI: Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Liturgical Press. Reiman, J. (1985), “Justice, Civilization
Cohen, A. (2013), “Why Don’t Supreme and the Death Penalty,” Philosophy and
Court Justices Ever Change Their Public Affairs, 14 (2), 115–148.
Minds in Favor of the Death Penalty?” Schieber, V., Conway, T., and McCarthy, D.
The Atlantic (December 10). Available (2013), Where Justice and Mercy Meet.
online: http://www.theatlantic. Collegeville, MI: Liturgical Press.
com/national/archive/2013/12/ Stevens, J. (2011), Five Chiefs: A Supreme
why-dont-supreme-court-justices- Court Memoir. New York: Little, Brown.
ever-change-their-minds-in-em-favor-em- Tonry, M. (2011), Why Punish? How
of-the-death-penalty/282100/ (accessed Much? New York: Oxford.
September 23, 2014). Tutu, D. (1999), No Future Without
Foucault, M. (1983), “Vous êtes dangereux,” Forgiveness. New York: Doubleday.
in Libération (Paris, June 30), 20. Repr. Zehr, H. (2002), The Little Book of
in Didier Eribon, Michel Foucault, 1989; Restorative Justice. Intercourse, PA: Good
tr. 1991. Books.

108
7
WAR
George R. Lucas, Jr

While the topic of this chapter stands by other means.” The goal of armed conflict
most obviously in sharp relief to the com- in pursuit of a nation’s political objectives
panion chapter on “Peace,” it bears sig- is, he argued, to defeat the enemy’s armies,
nificant connection to other topics in this occupy his cities, and break his will to fight
Companion, ranging from Sovereignty and or resist.
Cosmopolitanism, to Immigration and bor-
der control, to revolutions fought for the
sake of liberty, equality, justice, and human
rights. THE STATE-CENTRIC CONCEPTION
War—conventionally understood as the OF WAR (REALISM) AND ITS
opposite of peace, tranquility, security, and PRESUPPOSITIONS
stability—represents a form of conflict among
nations and peoples in which armed force, or This conventional or “classical” understand-
the threat of armed force, is used by a nation’s ing of what warfare itself is, as well as when
political leadership and elites in order to fur- it might be expected to occur, is highly ana-
ther their nation’s (and perhaps also their lytical, rationalistic, and heavily dependent
allies’) interests in one or more of the areas upon the underlying paradigm of the nation-
cited earlier. War, in particular, is thought to state. Indeed, Clausewitz’s own treatment
represent a form of political conflict between of the subject is frequently characterized as
adversaries in which everyday modes of con- a “Newtonian” conception, steeped in the
flict resolution—such as diplomacy, nego- metaphors of classical physical mechanics, in
tiation, sanctions, and compromise—have which the political interests of well-defined
proven ineffective or futile. Armed force is nation-states collide like billiard balls, and
finally resorted to instead, in order to com- the competing “forces” of rival national
pel the recalcitrant adversary to comply with armies are exerted like opposing vectors
a more powerful nation’s will or ambitions upon some political “center of gravity” in
(Orend, 2006, 2008). The nineteenth-cen- order to force political affairs into some final
tury Prussian military strategist, Clausewitz desired configuration.
(1830/1976: book I: chapters 1–2), provided Thus, in this conventional or classical
the classic summative assessment of war as understanding, conflict itself arises almost
precisely such a “continuation of State policy inevitably, due to the multiplicity and the

109
George R. Lucas, Jr

frequent incompatibility of more or less 1848); from defects in the nonrepresentative


reasonable state interests (e.g. in acquir- structure or internal political organization
ing territory or natural resources, providing of authoritarian and non-rights respecting
for their own individual safety and security, states (Kant, 1795); or, most enduringly, from
or expanding profitable trade relations). the competitive, aggressive, or otherwise per-
Moreover, while an individual nation-state’s verse and self-destructive nature of human
policies, predicated on the pursuit of these beings themselves (ranging from Augustine
interests, may represent a perfectly rational [ca. 410 ce] to a host of twentieth-century
or logical course of action for that particular social psychologists and cultural anthro-
nation (or coalition of allies), the multiplicity pologists, notably Freud [1915, 1930/2002],
of such interests virtually guarantees inces- Allport [1937, 1954, 1960], Morris [1967],
sant conflict between rival sets of interests and Jaynes [1976]). While popular in the
and their competing policy objectives. Hence middle of the last century, the conceptions of
an occasional resort to armed force in order war that attribute its frequency and perva-
to resolve at least some of these conflicts is siveness to features of human psychology or
all but inevitable. biology have especially fallen into disfavor.
This conventional conception of warfare In contrast to these rivals, the virtue of
as stemming inevitably from the perpetual the conventional conception of international
rivalry among competing state interests is anarchy is that it both serves to explain the
implicit in the thought of Hobbes (1660), historical pervasiveness and ubiquity of war-
and is rendered explicit simply by substitut- fare, and offers a foundation for alterna-
ing the condition of individual states in place tive strategies to avoid it through persistent
of the condition of biological individuals in recourse to less-violent management of com-
a “state of nature.” The implication of this peting state interests. Importantly, the classi-
conception was more clearly and fully artic- cal conception scrupulously avoids offering
ulated in essays on war and international a moral evaluation of the activity of warfare
relations by the Swiss political philosopher, itself, or of the adversaries or enemies who
Rousseau (1755a, 1755b, circa 1756), and is resort to it. While not at all minimizing the
largely presupposed as incontrovertible fact propensity of armed conflict to inflict great
by Clausewitz. In the contemporary era, this human suffering, misery, or destruction, the
view of political realism or “international theory of “international anarchy” does not
anarchy” has been championed by political seek to morally decry or condemn this fea-
scientists like Waltz (1954). ture of armed conflict, so much as it attempts
Realism or international anarchy has to account for it.
largely supplanted rival theories regarding Specifically, the classical conception
the origins of warfare, including conceptions of international anarchy presupposed in
grounded in the propensities of human behav- Clausewitz’s description of war, in particular,
ior, or, alternatively, in the internal political does not attribute the causes of armed con-
structure of specific individual states. Those flict strongly to deviant state structure, nor
rival theories variously attempted to portray rely implausibly on preventing war through
warfare as arising from factors such as the forcing a uniform political organization
corrupt or misguided policies of defective on all nations and societies. Neither does
or morally unjust states (Marx, 1844, 1845, it rest upon a “theory” of “human nature,”

110
WAR

nor otherwise propose (or desire) that indi- by rational principles do not always seem
vidual human beings be other than they are. to behave in accord with such principles in
Instead, the structure and function of indi- actual practice.
vidual states, like the variant natures and In particular, with respect to war, there
interests of individual human beings them- seem to a variety of other, less “rational”
selves, is simply taken for granted as a ran- causal factors that nonetheless play a power-
dom background feature of the international ful role in fomenting armed conflict, includ-
community. ing contrasting moral or religious beliefs,
As remarked earlier, just as this feature of collective or widely shared feelings of ethnic
ungoverned or lawless individuals in a hypo- or national solidarity and pride (sometimes
thetical state of nature is a formula for cease- even in the absence of a formal state struc-
less conflict in Hobbes, so the actual fact of ture), coupled with lingering resentment over
an ungoverned multiplicity of states in the past experiences of cruelty or injustice (often
international area is a formula for constant inflicted during previous armed conflicts), or
conflict in Rousseau. The formation of alli- the present infliction of cruelty and injustice
ances and political coalitions, as well as the by one national or ethnic group on the mem-
pursuit of modes of conflict resolution that bers of other, rival groups, or societies. The
can defuse the most extreme competition or classical conception of war as arising from
bring competing interests into greater align- the competition of rival nation-state inter-
ment or equilibrium represent procedural ests, moreover, is not especially effective in
approaches that follow logically from the explaining wars of insurgency and revolution,
analysis of nation-state competition and con- in which internal competition for control of
flict offered by the resulting “realist” model the state itself and its cultural or political
of the international system itself. institutions and policies seem to constitute
One glaring conceptual weakness of the paramount factors of conflict that lead to
this theory is its reliance on the underlying violence and the use of armed force.
paradigm of the nation-state as the funda-
mental unit of agency in the international
arena. Yet humankind’s historical experi-
ence of war considerably antedates the RECENT CHALLENGES TO THE
Treaty of Westphalia (1648) that gave rise STATE-CENTRIC MODEL
to the nation-state system itself—a system
that, indeed, was itself devised as a proposed World Wars I and II in the twentieth cen-
“cure” for, or solution to, the perpetual tury, along with the subsequent Korean War
wars of religious Reformation and counter- (1950–1953), certainly represent paradig-
Reformation in Europe that predated it. The matic instances of conventional or classical
rational foundations of the theory in the col- warfare of the sort Clausewitz character-
lective or common pursuit of the self-interest ized, based upon his own experiences of the
of discrete states, in addition, runs afoul of Napoleonic wars and the campaigns of
the problems that plague similar rationalis- Frederick the Great in Europe during the
tic theories in other behavioral disciplines eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. The
like economics: namely, that the beings American war of intervention in Vietnam,
whose behavior is hypothetically governed and likewise the intervention of the Soviet

111
George R. Lucas, Jr

Union in Afghanistan toward the end of conflict for the resolution of any future such
the last century, however, constitute less political disputes.
clear-cut cases (although both were, at the Two military strategists in the Peoples’
time, thought to be conventional conflicts, Liberation Army of China (PLA), for exam-
or at least “proxy wars” for such interstate ple, writing in the immediate aftermath of
“superpower” rivalries during the so-called the (First) Persian Gulf War, all but proph-
Cold War). esied the end of any future attempts at a
Perhaps the paradigmatic case of classi- full-scale conventional use of armed con-
cal or conventional war was the Falklands flict, certainly if directed against the United
War of 1984, in which two sovereign nation- States or its allies (Liang and Xiangsui, 1999).
states, Argentina and Great Britain, led the Their monograph, entitled “unrestricted war-
leaders of each to focus their rival interna- fare,” acknowledged that, for the foreseeable
tional interests on control of the Falkland future, no nation could any longer plausibly
Islands (Malvinas). Their unresolved conflict expect to oppose the conventional or nuclear
over the ownership and control of this oth- military power of the United States. Far from
erwise remote and relatively insignificant eschewing interstate conflict, however, the
territory resulted in a highly choreographed authors recommended that the only way for-
and symmetric escalation of the use of armed ward for China (and, by implication, other
force against one another, until the stronger adversaries) was to develop offensive and
and more determined military power finally defensive capabilities in other areas, includ-
prevailed. In the final analysis, this conflict ing economic and legal competition (or “law-
constituted nothing short of a perfectly cho- fare;” see Dunlap, 2001), and especially in
reographed Clausewitzian ballet (Regan, the new domain of cyberspace. All of these
2013). sectors, but particularly the cyber domain,
The armed conflict between the nation of were areas in which developed nations like
Iraq under the leadership of President Saddam the United States were themselves highly vul-
Hussein, and a UN coalition force under the nerable and by no means dominant. Political
command of the United States in early 1991, adversaries of such nations, the Chinese mili-
however, may well have constituted the last tary theorists argued, must be willing to use
instance of thoroughly conventional or “clas- their own capabilities to exploit their oppo-
sical” warfare of the Clausewitzian sort for nents’ vulnerabilities in the pursuit of their
the foreseeable future. The clashing armies national interests. Thus were born the relent-
of the two powers initially appeared to be of less, state-sponsored campaigns allegedly car-
comparable size, material constitution, and ried out by a top-secret branch of the PLA,
technological might. What proved in fact to “Unit 61398,” based in Shanghai, of cyber
be the vastly superior military technology, espionage, as well as of alleged covert actions,
training, and tactical leadership of the ground such as the planting of trap doors and logic
forces under US command, however, led to bombs in vital civilian infrastructures, as
so devastating a defeat and destruction of the well as massive theft of industrial and classi-
opposing army in the deserts of Kuwait as fied military technologies from many nations
to raise serious questions, especially among throughout the world (Lucas, 2014c).
competitors and adversaries of this coalition, During roughly the same period, armed
about the viability of conventional armed attacks against civilian targets in the United

112
WAR

States, Tanzania, Kenya, the United Kingdom, and humanitarian support from the interna-
France, Mali, Spain, and in the Russian tional community. Despite widespread and
Federation by so-called Islamic extrem- gravely erroneous assumptions to the con-
ist terrorist organizations (like al-Qaeda) trary, it turned out that the 1948 Convention
are likewise thought to have ushered in yet required little concrete action on the part
another new form of unrestricted, “irregu- of signatory nations other than a pledge to
lar,” or unconventional warfare, undertaken refrain themselves from committing or oth-
this time by organizations with no formal erwise sponsoring acts of genocide, and to
state affiliation whatsoever, and often absent assist both in actively apprehending, and
any recognizable or well-articulated political refusing to grant either political asylum or
interests or objectives, other than foment- safe harbor within their borders to, indi-
ing fear and undermining security and the viduals charged with fomenting or carrying
rule of law itself. Anger, moral and religious out such acts elsewhere (Lucas, 2014a). This
outrage, or festering frustration and resent- tragic lacuna led, in the ensuing decade, to
ment, rather than conventional self-interest an international movement to define the
or the pursuit of discernable state policy, “Responsibility to Protect” (R2P, or R to P)
seem to constitute both the cause of, and the as an additional military obligation on the
apparent justification for, these new forms of part of otherwise sovereign states (Pattison,
armed conflict. Importantly, in any case, all 2010, Scheid, 2014).
these forms of armed conflict appear to lie These manifestations of irregular or “post-
entirely outside the predictive or explanatory modern” war (Eco, 1991, Lucas, 2010)  are
power of the nation-state paradigm, and of deeply disturbing, in part because they seem
Clausewitz’s attendant conception of con- immune to normal “rationalistic” appeals
ventional military strategy. to state interests that might resolve or amel-
Perhaps most tragically, in the aftermath iorate the conflicts, such as compromise or
of the collapse of the Berlin Wall in 1989 appeasement (on one hand) or threats of
and the putative end to the half-century of punishment and retaliation that might nor-
the Russo-American “Cold War,” what was mally serve as deterrents (on the other). They
at first heralded as a new era of global peace have proven highly destabilizing, because the
and prosperity quickly degenerated into a source of the dangers are often unclear, and
succession of humanitarian crises and acts of the tactics employed by the proponents of
genocide in failed and inept states through- violence are difficult to detect and to defend
out the world. Nations in a position to assist against.
or prevent these crises, meanwhile, often The horrific Rwandan Genocide of 1993–
had no compelling “state interests” or poli- 1994, for example, was preceded by only a
cies at stake, nor had they any compelling few months of sinister political unrest and
desire to intervene militarily in conflicts not the public broadcast of ethnic hate mes-
of their own making. The United Nations sages throughout the country whose signifi-
Genocide Convention of 1948, enacted in cance was, for the most part, unrecognized
the aftermath of World War II in response to by outsiders. The armed violence that sud-
disclosure of the horrors of the Holocaust in denly erupted, in turn, was carried out
Germany and Eastern Europe, proved to be largely by unorganized mobs armed with
ineffective in marshaling the needed military clubs and machetes rather than sophisticated

113
George R. Lucas, Jr

armaments, who nonetheless managed in A host of legal and ethical questions and
only a short time to massacre nearly 1 mil- conundrums arise primarily from this relent-
lion victims. less tactical arms race, even as the conven-
Likewise, the determined al-Qaeda opera- tional, Clausewitzian understanding of war
tives who secretly mastered flight control, is radically transformed by this perennial
overpowered flight crews, and subsequently “give and take” between political adversar-
flew commercial aircraft as suicide weap- ies, and even more between coalitions of
ons into the Trade Towers in New York City security forces upholding the rule of law, and
and the Pentagon in Washington, DC on international criminals intent on circumvent-
September 11, 2001 proved extremely capa- ing that rule.
ble and resourceful in avoiding detection or
apprehension by security and law enforce-
ment officials. Their activity could at best be
understood as at least analogous to a highly “MILITARY ETHICS” AND THE
organized but unique international crimi- LAWS OF WAR
nal conspiracy of the sort that lies utterly
outside the boundaries of conventional The comparatively unrestrained use of deadly
Clausewitzian conceptual framework of con- force, resulting in widespread destruction
ventional warfare. and devastation of property and the death
This, in turn, provokes a final striking fea- or injury of hundreds of thousands of human
ture of unconventional or “irregular” war- beings, both combatants and noncombatants,
fare (Lucas, 2009, 2011). First, adversaries may hardly seem fertile territory for talking
and insurgent interest groups, frustrated by about morality or legal governance. Indeed,
the radical asymmetries in military power war, in either its conventional or postmod-
stacked in favor in conventional forces, adopt ern manifestations, seems to represent a dra-
new tactics of disrupting social systems and matic breakdown of the normal rule of law,
attacking the weak links in logistical supply together with the (temporary) abandonment
chains through the use (for example) of suicide of moral judgment and restraint.
bombers and IEDs, or of cyber attacks, that Clausewitz, indeed, famously warns
throw conventional military forces seriously against allowing moral scruples to play a
off balance. Subsequently, new technologies role in the conduct of war. Ethics, and espe-
owned initially by the besieged conventional cially “benevolence born of philanthropy” he
forces become the optimal response. Drone writes,
attacks, for example, are “systemic” in pre-
cisely the same sense as are IEDs and suicide . . . is an error which must be extirpated;
bombers, disrupting the insurgent’s command for in such dangerous things as War, the
structure, relentlessly hunting him out where errors which proceed from a spirit of
benevolence are the worst. As the use of
he lives and hides, and so demoralizing him
physical power to the utmost extent by
in return, and hopefully breaking his ability
no means excludes the co-operation of
and will to fight. Massive cyber surveillance the intelligence, it follows that he who
on an almost inconceivable scale likewise uses force unsparingly, without refer-
frustrates the most determined attacker, and ence to the bloodshed involved, must
carries the cyber fight back to its source. obtain a superiority if his adversary uses

114
WAR

less vigour in its application (Book I, if all the male population of a country,
chapter 1).1 capable of bearing arms, exercise this
calling, still it always continues to be dif-
Interestingly, Clausewitz does not overtly ferent and separate from the other pur-
suits which occupy the life of man ..  . .
question the validity of the reasons, let alone
However much pains may be taken to
the authority of the State, that lead it to
combine the soldier and the citizen in
declare war. But once war is decided upon as one and the same individual, whatever
the appropriate course of action, one ought may be done to nationalize Wars, and
(he argues) to prosecute the war as fully, however much we may imagine times
efficiently, effectively, and (presumably) as have changed since the days of the old
mercilessly or pitilessly as possible, lest the Condottieri, never will it be possible to
war itself drag on too long, do far too much do away with the individuality of the
damage on its own, and squander the politi- business; and if that cannot be done,
cal opportunities and purposes for which it then those who belong to it, as long as
was fought. they belong to it, will always look upon
themselves as a kind of guild, in the regu-
Yet, in Book III, when continuing his
lations, laws and customs in which the
analysis of strategy, Clausewitz waxes elo-
“Spirit of War” by preference finds its
quent upon the importance of “moral force” expression (Book III, chapter V).
and the moral qualities of wars, and of the
nations that wage them. Some of this inter-
esting but somewhat chaotic discussion has This seems to offer at least a rudimentary
to do (at least indirectly) with the qualities of reflection on what might be termed “profes-
the reasons of State that lead it to declare and sional ethics,” or “the virtues of the profes-
prosecute war. Presumably, some reasons are sion of arms.” It is the sort of observation
better than others, while some states behave about the norms, rules, customs, and prin-
more admirably and prudently than others in ciples that guide and constrain practice, and
pursuing their chosen military strategy, and inform the members of a specific practice, of
hence their militaries can be counted upon which MacIntyre writes (1981, 1988, 1990).
to pursue the fight with more vigor, courage, The norms that govern the aspirations, best
and enthusiasm on that account. Presumably, practices, and limits of acceptable practice
this is a theoretical reflection on the remark- arise from the experience of that practice,
able but imprecise saying, often attributed to and reflections on it, as carried out by mem-
Napoleon, that: “In War, the Moral is to the bers of the profession. We will return to this
Physical as Three to One.”2 intriguing suggestion concerning war and
In most other respects, however, “professional ethics” in conclusion.
Clausewitz’s “ethical focus” (if we are even Otherwise, it is helpful to note that these
entitled to call it that) is on the military itself various comments and reflections can be
(his focus is almost exclusively upon land taken to suggest that there are two broad
forces, and on the individuals that comprise moral issues to be addressed with reference
a nation’s Army). He observes: to war. The first concerns when it is appro-
priate and justifiable for a nation or an alli-
War is a special business, and however ance of nations to abandon other procedures
general its relations may be, and even for conflict resolution, and decide to pursue

115
George R. Lucas, Jr

their military options. Historically, this first historically or otherwise, that militaries that
question (or set of questions) has come to honor professional customs (such as refrain-
be designated in the Latin terminology of ing from attacking noncombatants, or mis-
medieval law as jus ad bellum, the justifica- treating prisoners of war) fare any less well
tion for entering into war. The second con- in determining the outcome of the war than
cerns what primarily interests Clausewitz those forces who ignore such customs and
himself: namely, what he seems to think of constraints. Indeed, once again, Clausewitz’s
as the “professional” question of how a war subsequent observations on “moral force”
is best waged by those actually involved in and the importance of professional demeanor
fighting it. This second discussion of the con- in Book III seem to imply just the opposite in
duct of war, and of the preparation, training, practice: that well-trained and professional
character, and conduct of combatants in war, military forces (including attention to the
is commonly designated by the Latin legal moral principles, customs, and traditions of
idiom, jus in bello. the profession of arms) perform with greater
Historically, there is considerable reflec- enthusiasm, effectiveness, and hence effi-
tion, especially in the philosophical literature ciency in the field than do their adversaries
of Western culture, on both sets of questions, who lack such “moral force.”
which are thought to be conceptually dis- Three decades after the posthumous pub-
tinct, although obviously related. The first, lication of vom Krieg, Lieber, a German-
jus ad bellum, is thought to be the purview born American legal scholar well acquainted
primarily of statesmen and political lead- with Clausewitz’s views on professionalism,
ers, charged with the welfare and defense of was asked by President Abraham Lincoln to
the State. The second, jus in bello, pertains draft a series of regulations and guidelines
primarily to the military forces of the state, for troops in the Union Army during the US
and seems to entail or encompass reflections Civil War. The result, “General Orders #100”
on the ethics of the profession of arms itself. (known traditionally as the “Lieber Code”)
Clausewitz is prescient in hinting at their enshrined a great many of these principles
interconnection, however, at least in implying of professional decorum and constraint
that statesmen and nations which collectively regarding the use of force, noncombatant
comport themselves well and honorably, and immunity, treatment of prisoners, and other
exercise prudent judgment in declaring war, matters touched upon earlier. Interestingly,
are likely to inspire their militaries to best the result was so admired for enshrining
professional practice in the field of combat. military professionalism along the general
Discussion of war and ethics, and (sepa- outlines that Clausewitz had first proposed,
rately) of military ethics, are nonetheless that the American document was subse-
often disparaged as irrelevant, or worse, as quently adopted as doctrine by Clausewitz’s
disadvantaging the side that takes such issues own military force, the Prussian Army, from
to heart (as Clauswitz himself initially seems whence it spread to the military services of
to imply) by constraining them to use their other European militaries and policy-mak-
physical power and material forces more ing communities, where key elements of
sparingly, and hence less effectively than their the Lieber Code then served as the founda-
adversary. The latter is an empirical obser- tion for the first Geneva Conventions of the
vation, however, and there is little evidence, late nineteenth century, prescribing limits or

116
WAR

constraints on the appropriate conduct of talked about war, they have talked about it
armed hostilities (Reichberg et al., 2003). in terms of right and wrong . . . . Reiterated
This kind of reasoning about war, to be over time,” he observes, “[these] arguments
certain, has a long history in Western culture, and judgments shape what I want to call the
but it is as far from being merely a Western moral reality of war—that is, all those experi-
cultural artifact as the practice of war itself ences of which moral language is descriptive
(Hensel, 2010). Warfare constitutes a highly or within which it is necessarily employed”
variable form of what anthropologists some- (Walzer, 1977). The “necessity” of this moral
times term “cultural performance,” and (one discourse, moreover, is not one born of com-
might also observe) such performances are pulsion, but seems quite instead to reflect
routinely accompanied by equally unique the individual or collective agency of human
forms of cultural discourse concerning the beings themselves—that is, their freedom,
circumstances under which the performance and their ability, individually and collectively
is to be staged, and to what extent, and by to deliberate, decide, choose among alterna-
whom, against whom, and most importantly, tive courses of action, and finally both act or
for what ends (French, 2003, Robinson, refrain from acting, and offer better or worse
2003). Hence, we find the principal charac- accounts of what they have finally chosen to
ters, Arjuna and Krisna, debating precisely do, and why. Similar to MacIntyre’s account
these questions in the Bhagavad Gita, while of the origins of professional norms in delib-
laws in ancient India clearly defined those erative discourse, as noted earlier, “just war
who were to be exempt from attack in the theory” represents the norms collectively
midst of war (Morkevicius, 2010, Roy, elicited through such reflective discourse by
2012). The Confucian military strategist, its practitioners on better and worse forms
Sun Tzu (whose much earlier reflections are of the practice of war itself.
often compared with those of Clausewitz), Indeed, one could argue even more plau-
famously offers delicately nuanced and sibly that the discourse about war and its
understated views on precisely these ques- conduct in any culture is very much akin to
tions in The Art of War (1994). In twentieth- the discourse about a variety of actions or
century China, Chairman Mao denounced practices with which all persons of all cul-
his own culture’s earlier forms of discourse tures and epochs are all too familiar—killing,
and limitations on the practice of combat as lying, breaking solemn promises or violat-
“asinine,” but then proceeded to proclaim ing contracts, betraying loyalty, disobedi-
his own “Eight Points for Attention” govern- ence, and law-breaking, for example—all
ing the conduct of his own insurgency forces of which, including going to war, represent
in their conduct of guerilla war in 1938. the kinds of practices from which persons in
The Qur’an and its accompanying Hadith every known culture and every known his-
declaim frequently and at length upon torical epoch have been exhorted to refrain.
when, how, and to what extent to make war Yet individuals do these kinds of things all
upon unbelievers, along with when, if ever, the time. Usually, such actions are thought
Muslims should raise the sword against fel- to be wrong, and those engaging in them
low Muslims (Kelsay, 2009). are held liable under prevailing principles
The renowned political philosopher,Walzer, of law, morality, and customary behavior
writes “For as long as men and women have for having engaged in wrongdoing. In what

117
George R. Lucas, Jr

are unquestionably culturally and histori- • One should have taken every possible
cally dependent fashions, the wrongdoers are measure short of war itself to resolve the
punished, excoriated, imprisoned, exiled, or conflicts addressed (“last resort”).
executed—unless, that is, they can be found • One’s intentions in resorting ultimately to
warfare must be benevolent rather than
by their peers to have had justificatory (or at
malevolent—the restoration of peace and
least, exculpatory) reasons, motives, or inten-
satisfaction of the demands of justice, for
tions in engaging in the otherwise-prohibited example, as opposed to revenge, terror, or
practices. We hold law-breakers (like Gandhi self-aggrandizement.
or King) accountable for violating established • There must be some measure of com-
legal norms; we hold “whistle-blowers” (like mensurability (or “proportionality”)
Edward Snowden) accountable for violating between the justifying cause and the
obligations of loyalty and betraying their ends to be sought through war, and the
trust; we hold killers accountable under law damage and destruction it will surely
and morality for taking the lives of others. bring about.
But in every case, we are led to wonder if • Finally, such reasoning on the part of the
responsible decision makers, the “moral
the civil disobedient, the whistle-blower, the
agents,” must be capable of withstand-
killer, or the liar had good cause for delib-
ing “peer review” or judicial review (i.e.
erately engaging in what seems to us, prima they must meet the test of “Publicity,”
facie, as wrongdoing. in which impartial, reasonable observers
Warfare, precisely on account of its devas- confronted with the same situation could
tation, death, and destruction, is thought to be expected to elicit the same or similar
be foremost among these things that we ordi- judgment).
narily are not supposed to do, even when we
nonetheless proceed to do so anyway. In fact, Exclusive focus in some, more philosophically
the theological, political, or intellectual lead- inclined cultural traditions on the problem of
ership, or members of the society in general warfare has produced additional, nuanced
who are witness to, and presumably wronged conditions or criteria that should be con-
collectively, by such actions may have a right sidered, such as, in the case of going to war,
to pose two significant kinds of questions to requiring an advance, public declaration to
the wrongdoer: (1) “did you have good and do so, coupled with some reasonable expecta-
sufficient reasons—justified cause—for your tion that satisfactory or successful resolution
actions? And, (2) did you go about deciding of the conflict is indeed possible and feasible.
and carrying out these normally-prohibited However, such demands seem compatible in
actions in the right fashion?” principle with the other instances of what I
In the case of jus ad bellum, or decisions term a morality of “exceptions,” such as civil
to go to war, the justifying reasons, while not disobedience, so-called whistle-blowing, or
identical, are roughly similar to those gov- decisions to engage in strategies of promise-
erning decisions to override prevailing norms breaking, disloyalty, secrecy, deceit, or decep-
in these other cases: tion. The moral justification of any and all
of these otherwise-distinct actions or policies
• One should have a compelling reason (or requires good justificatory reasons embody-
“just cause”) for overriding the prohibi- ing “right intention,” and must be undertaken
tion against fighting and killing. only after exhausting less-extreme options,

118
WAR

determining the proportionality between the United Nations, in which the Principle
the harm that will ensue and the good to be of Publicity is inherently vested and guaran-
achieved thereby, and usually only if publicly teed. This makes unilateral decisions by indi-
acknowledged, likely to succeed, and capa- vidual nations to declare war (other than in
ble of post-facto review and consensus on exigent circumstances of armed self-defense
the part of disinterested others (e.g. Lucas, in response to an unprovoked attack) deeply
2014b). suspect, let  alone decisions by nonstate
Warfare, unlike the other categories of actors or organizations (such as the radi-
activities from which moral agents should cal Sunni Islamic organization, al-Qaeda) to
normally refrain, however, embodies some declare war upon others. Indeed, we might
unique elements that arise from a fundamen- observe that the question of sovereignty and
tal equivocation over agency: that is, over the “legitimate authority” in just war doctrine
“one” or the “we” that makes these determi- now constitutes the single most vexed and
nations. Decisions to deceive, blow the whis- contentious issue in international relations
tle, or break the law most often reside with in the twenty-first century (Johnson, 2014).
individual human beings (or at most, a small Otherwise—and quite unlike an individ-
group of persons) capable both of making ual’s personal decision to blow the whistle,
them, and of being held accountable for the break a promise, or deliberately violate the
results. law—the decision to go to war commits a
The question of collective agency—that is, subset of the society, nation, or coalition
“sovereignty,” or possessing the “legitimate (normally its designated military and secu-
authority” to make decisions that commit a rity forces) to carry out this general will on
society to a course of action threatening the behalf of the declaring authority. Thus, if
entire body politic with harm, and with being we customarily hold individuals account-
held accountable for the infliction of harm— able for making themselves exceptions
is considerably more vexed. This is especially to the normal constraints on their justifi-
true with respective recent developments in able behavior, how does this accountability
“irregular warfare,” terrorism, and insur- translate into a canon of expectations and
gency, in which decisions reached by indi- constraints imposed upon the designated
viduals and small groups may unknowingly subset of agents empowered, on the state’s
or unwillingly commit a much wider society behalf, to wage its wars? And, even more
to the risk of harm. problematically, to what extent may one
In conventional thinking, “sovereignty” anticipate that the conventional or tradi-
(and hence, legitimate authority) resides tional answers to this important question in
with a representative leader—king, prime the past will automatically “carry over” into
minister or leader of parliament, elected the realm of unrestricted or “irregular” war-
president—who symbolizes, and is at least fare in the present, especially when irregu-
tacitly deputized to speak for, the body poli- lar warfare is waged by agents of the State
tic. Increasingly in the past century, such against terrorists or insurgents, who utterly
authority is even thought to exceed that of lack any legitimate authority to wage war
the heads of individual nation-states, and themselves, and who are therefore often
requires a collective judgment on the part of contemptuous of any constraints on their
a representative congress of nations, such as own behavior?

119
George R. Lucas, Jr

JUS IN BELLO AND PROFESSIONAL much a matter of prudence and common sense
MILITARY ETHICS as of morality, per se. Why on earth, Sun-Tzu
wonders, would a commander risk harm to
Although not nearly so clearly demarcated, such his army if the military objective could be
reflections on better and worse practice, and achieved without a single battle? Why on
on the limits of acceptable practice in the con- earth, Socrates asks his students, as they reflect
duct of war (jus in bello) likewise pervades the upon the aftermath of the Peloponnesian War,
literature and lore of many historical eras and would we slaughter the innocent bystanders
cultural traditions, and even predates the more and helpless family members of the enemy, or
formalized, reflective, and systematic discourse raze their cities and lands, when we hope to
pertaining to decisions to engage in war (jus ad restore friendly, and economically viable rela-
bellum). Once again, in contrast to the mistaken tionships with them following their defeat?
stereotype that these discussions are of limited Perhaps the most famous and fascinat-
scope and origin in Western culture (let alone ing of these ruminations is found in William
that their provenance lies wholly within some Shakespeare’s play, Henry V, which has
specific theological tradition), we find these dis- long figured among the required reading of
cussions infused in the reflective literature and military academy students in many parts
philosophy of cultures and religions stretching of the world. The larger play is read for a
from China through India, to the Middle East variety of reasons, as discussing, for exam-
and beyond (Kaplan, 2002). Some of the ear- ple, that elusive topic of “moral force” to
liest examples (in addition to the many cited which Clausewitz averred (espirit de corps;
earlier) are those of Sun-Tzu (The Art of War) morale). But it is the debate among two ordi-
and Socrates (Plato, The Republic), concern- nary infantry captains in Act IV, Scene vii,
ing issues such as: when to fight, and when to after King Henry has ordered the execution
refrain from fighting, the proper targeting of of French prisoners of war, which is the focus
enemy combatants, noncombatant immunity, of our attention. What is striking is that this
and the distinction between true “military drama was at least loosely based on history
necessity” and indiscriminate and largely gratu- concerning a very popular king, and directed
itous destruction: a fundamental principle often at an audience primarily of laypersons who
labeled, “the Economy of Force.” would have known the history and largely
These and other cultural sources down shared this respect and fondness for “King
through the ages opine, in addition, on who Harry.” And in the incident itself, it is not
is liable to attack, the degree of force to be knights, peers, or noblemen, but two ordi-
expended against enemies (once more, the nary commoners, two captains of the infan-
general consensus is, as little as possible, try, charged with organizing and carrying out
and no more than is absolutely necessary to the execution, who comment on it:
achieve the legitimate military objective), and Henry V (dialogue of two infantry cap-
importantly, on who is exempt from attack tains: Act IV, scene VII)
(usually those thought to represent no threat
of harm, such as women, children, the elderly, (1) “Kill the prisoners?? ‘Tis expressly
or enemy prisoners rendered hors de combat against the law of arms, as arrant a piece
through imprisonment or injury). As often as of knavery, mark you now, as can be
not, the impetus for such considerations is a offer’t.

120
WAR

(2) Tis the King himself hath ordered it . . . Conflict” (LOAC), intended to constrain and
O, tis a gallant king! manage the application of armed force, or else
(1) Aye! And them as fled the fight before, mandating proper treatment of war’s victims,
now eagerly comply!” such as refugees and prisoners of war, under
These lines would have been delivered to provisions designed to alleviate some of the
an audience who knew the history, and would worst forms of suffering among war’s victims.
have to be intelligible to them. Here we find This latter body of legislation is usually termed
this behavior condemned in the early seven- “International Humanitarian Law” (IHL).
teenth century, referring to a war in the six- The demarcation is not sharp, nor always
teenth, and using the phrase “law of arms” well observed or understood by lawyers and
as if this were a commonly understood term even legal scholars, sometimes resulting in a
well before modern legal scholars, such as conflation of, or confusion between the two
Grotius, Vattel, and Pufendorf (Reichberg distinct legal regimes, the former emanating
et al., 2003), would publish their initial reflec- primarily from Hague Conventions in the late
tions, let alone centuries before formal stand- nineteenth and early twentieth century, and
ards, such as the International Laws of Armed the latter contained primarily in Geneva con-
Conflict, would find themselves enshrined in ventions adopted following both World War I
treaty and black-letter law. This notion of and World War II.
humane treatment of prisoners is thus an More broadly, however, the central moral
example of a once-emergent, and now well- principles underlying both distinct sets
established professional norm among soldiers of concerns and drawn, in turn, from the
at arms. centuries of reflection encompassed in the
Such principles, dimly discerned, none- just war tradition itself, are enshrined in
theless survive the ages in the subsequent what are often termed the “Five Pillars” of
reflections of philosophers, theologians, International Law. These are:
and statements in many cultures, languages,
and religions. It was that body of reflection • Prevention of Superfluous Injury and
that Lieber sought to embody in “General Unnecessary Suffering
Orders #100.” And in so codifying these • Military Necessity (the Economy of Force)
intuitions, the Lieber Code incorporated • Proportionality
• Distinction (Discrimination or Non­
what the Dominican priest, Francisco di
combatant immunity)
Vitoria (1539), decrying the harsh treatment
• Command Responsibility (Accountability)
inflicted on indigenous populations during
the Spanish Conquest, had earlier described
as the “customs and habits of civilized peo-
ples and nations” (jus gentium). CONCLUSION: RECENT
Such fundamental norms and long-prevail- DEVELOPMENTS IN THE
ing intuitions thus find their circuitous way UNDERSTANDING OF
into contemporary international law. They are POSTMODERN WAR
often mandated in the legislative language of
specific treaties and conventions, such as those Space does not permit more than a brief men-
banning the use of certain kinds of weapons tion of two of the most recent developments
as part of what is termed “the Law of Armed in the just war tradition, both of which bear

121
George R. Lucas, Jr

importantly on the advent of postmodern “just preparedness for war,” this new devel-
war. opment directly addresses the responsibility
The first is now commonly termed jus of reasonably just, responsible, and at least
post bellum, and describes the need to end minimally rights-respecting nations to equip
wars properly, so as to inhibit the likelihood and train military forces to properly carry
of future outbreaks of violence and armed out their new responsibilities in accordance
conflict. While often attributed to the recent with international law, and specifically, to
pioneering work of Brian Orend, an eminent know how they are expected to behave and
Canadian scholar of international relations carry out both military and stability/peace-
(2000, 2006), Orend himself attributes the keeping duties properly, and avoid policies
origins of this concern to Kant, particularly and actions that will inflame or reignite
in the late essay, Perpetual Peace (1795). the conflict they are attempting to resolve.
Kant, in turn, although often understood to Principal among the formulators of this new
be a critic of conventional just war think- dimension of military preparedness for post-
ing (e.g. Grotius), nonetheless outlined some modern war are scholars Wertheimer (2010)
conditions and prerequisites for winding up and Van der Linden (2010), while the assess-
wars so as not to have the end of one serve as ment, evaluation, and reform of various
cause for the next. In the contemporary era, national programs of military education in
Orend cites the excessively punitive nature of the world’s principal developed nations has
the Treaty of Versailles (1918), ending World constituted the work and publication of the
War I, as an example of precisely what Kant “Military Ethics Education Network,” led
sought to avoid, while the Marshall Plan in by British scholars and military education
Europe following World War II serves as a reformers Paul Robinson, Don Carrick, and
recent example of ending war successfully, in James Connelly (see Robinson 2008, 2009).
a manner to inhibit future conflict among the The topic of warfare—what it is, as well as
warring parties (Patterson, 2012, 2013). when and how it is to be waged, brought to
Jus post bellum became a prominent fea- an end, and even prepared for—is under-
ture in the wars fought in Afghanistan and standably a complex and somewhat inchoate
Iraq by the United States, NATO, and their topic, owing in part to its longstanding his-
allies during the first decade of the present torical ubiquity and its multitude of sources
century. Often variously called “peace-keep- and experiences. It is not to be wondered
ing and stability operations,” nation-building, that individuals might find themselves con-
hybrid war, or MOOTW in military circles, fused, especially regarding topics like the
jus post bellum and its proper military and justification of war, the limitations placed
post-military dimensions now constitute a upon combatants engaged in it, let  alone a
principal focus of military training and lead- topic such as “military ethics” as a species of
ership development. professional ethics and the emergent norms
The importance of proper education, of practitioners. All have, over the centuries,
training, and leadership development among been the objects of an extraordinary degree
the world’s prominent military forces, in of confusion, misinformation, and outright
turn, is the focus of the other (less thor- error, perhaps none more so than the nature
oughly explored) dimension of postmodern and origin of the “just war tradition” itself.
war. Termed variously jus ante bellum, or A clear, comprehensive, and authoritative

122
WAR

account of these important matters, however, MA: Harvard University Carr Center for
might one day prove sufficient to dispel, once Human Rights Policy. http://people.duke.
and for all, the remaining vestiges of that edu/~pfeaver/dunlap.pdf.
confusion. Eco, U. (1991), “Reflections on War,” La
Rivista dei libri (April 1, 1991); reprinted
in Eco, Five Moral Pieces, trans. McEwen.
New York: Harcourt, Inc.
Notes French, S. E. (2003), The Code of the
Warrior: Exploring Warrior Values, Past
1
Clausewitz’s views on ethics are complicated and Present. Lanham, MD: Rowman &
and thoroughly unsystematic. He eschews Littlefield.
benevolence and pity, but believes that restrains
Freud, S. (1915), “Thoughts for the Times
(such as not killing the enemy’s prisoners
of war) arise instead as a result of prudence on War and Death,” Reflections on War
and the civilizing effects of intellect. He talks and Death, trans. A. A. Brill and A. B.
extensively of “moral force” and “character,” Kuttner. New York: Moffat, Yard & Co.
but usually intends the former in the sense of Freud, S. (1930/2002), Civilization and Its
morale, or esprit de corps, while “character”
Discontents. London: Penguin.
refers to those traits and habits, like courage,
calmness, and steadfastness, that aid in the Hensel, H. M. (2010), The Prism of Just
pursuit of conflict. War: Asian and Western Perspectives on
2
Although frequently invoked, and presumably the Legitimate Use of Military Force.
constituting one of Napoleon’s “115 Maxims” London: Ashgate Press.
on statecraft, I have never seen this famous
Hobbes, T. (1660), The Leviathan. http://
quote properly cited.
oregonstate.edu/instruct/phl302/texts/
hobbes/leviathan-contents.html.
Jaynes, J. (1976), The Origins of
WORKS CITED Consciousness in the Breakdown of the
Bicameral Mind. New York: Houghton
Augustine (ca. 410) (1998), The City of God Mifflin & Co.
against the Pagans, trans. R. W. Dyson. Johnson, J. T. (2014), Sovereignty.
New York: Cambridge University Press. Washington, DC: Georgetown University
Allport, G. (1937), Personality: A Press.
Psychological Interpretation. New York: Kant, I. (1795), Toward Perpetual Peace
Holt, Rinehart, & Winston. and Other Essays, trans. T. Humphrey.
— (1954), The Nature of Prejudice. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing.
Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley. Kaplan, R. (2002), Warrior Politics: Why
— (1960), Personality & Social Encounter. Leadership Demands a Pagan Ethos.
Boston, MA: Beacon Press. New York: Random House.
Clausewitz, K. (1830/1976), On War, trans. Kelsay, J. (2009), Arguing the Just War
Howard and Paret (ed.). Princeton, NJ: in Islam. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
Princeton University Press. University Press.
Dunlap, C. (2001), “Law and Military Liang, Q. and Xiangsui, W. (1999),
Interventions: Preserving Humanitarian Unrestricted Warfare. Beijing: PLA
Values in 21st Conflicts.” Cambridge, Literature and Arts Publishing House.

123
George R. Lucas, Jr

Lucas, G. R., Jr (2009), “‘This is Not Your Morkevicius, V. (2010), “Hindu Perspectives
Father’s War’: Confronting the Moral on War,” in H. M. Hensel (ed.), The Prism
Challenges of ‘Unconventional’ War,” of Just War. London: Ashgate Press,
Journal of National Security Law and pp. 169–191.
Policy, 3 (2): 331–342. Morris, D. (1967), The Naked Ape: A
— (2010), “Postmodern War,” Journal Zoologist’s Study of the Human Animal.
of Military Ethics 9 (4) (December): New York: Random House.
289–298. Orend, B. (2000), War and International
— (2011), “New Rules for New Wars: Justice: A Kantian Perspective. Waterloo,
International Law and Just War Doctrine ON: Wilfred Lauier University Press.
for Irregular Warfare,” Case-Western — (2006), The Morality of War.
Review of International Law, 677–705. Peterborough, ON: Broadview Press.
— (2014a), “Revisiting Armed Humanitarian — (2008), “War,” The Stanford
Intervention: A 25-year Retrospective,” Encyclopedia of Philosophy, E. N. Zalta
in D. Scheid (ed.), Ethics of Armed (ed.), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/
Humanitarian Intervention. Cambridge: fall2008/entries/war/.
Cambridge University Press, pp. 26–45. Patterson, E. (2012), Ending Wars Well.
— (2014b), “The Case for Preventive War,” New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
in D. K. Chatterjee (ed.), The Ethics of — (2013), Ethics Beyond War’s End.
Preventive War. New York: Cambridge Washington, DC: Georgetown University
University Press, pp. 46–63. Press.
— (2014c), “Military Ethics and Cyber Pattison, J. (2010), Humanitarian
Warfare,” in J. T. Johnson and E. Intervention and the Responsibility to
Patterson (eds), Ashgate Handbook of Protect: Who Should Intervene? Oxford:
Military Ethics. London: Ashgate Press. Oxford University Press.
MacIntyre, A. (1981), After Virtue. South Regan, R. (2013), “The Falklands War,” in
Bend, IN: Notre Dame University Press. Just War: Principles and Cases, 2nd edn.
— (1988), Whose Justice? Which Washington, DC: Catholic University of
Rationality? South Bend, IN: Notre Dame America Press.
University Press. Reichberg, G., Syse, H., and Begby, E.
— (1990), First Principles, Final Ends, and (2003), The Ethics of War: Classical
Contemporary Philosophical Issues. and Contemporary Readings. London:
“Aquinas Lecture.” Milwaukee, WI: Blackwell Publishers.
Marquette University Press. Robinson, P. (2003), Just War in
Marx, K. (1844/2007), Economic & Comparative Perspective. London:
Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844, trans. Ashgate Press.
M. Milligan. Mineola, NY: Dover Books. — (2008), Ethics Education in the Military,
— (1845/1939), The German Ideology P. Robinson, J. Connelly, and D. Carrick
(w/F. Engels). Moscow: The Marx-Engels (eds). London: Ashgate Press.
Institute. — (2009), Ethics Education for Irregular
— (1848/2012), The Communist Manifesto Warfare, in P. Robinson, J. Connelly,
(w/F. Engels). New Haven, CT: Yale and D. Carrick (eds). London: Ashgate
University Press. Press.

124
WAR

Rousseau, J. J. (1755a/1997), The Origins of Sun-Tzu (ca. 6th Century bce/1994), The
Inequality Among Men. ‘The Discourses’ Art of War, trans. R. D. Sawyer. New
and Other Early Political Writings, trans. York: Basic Books.
V. Gourevitch. Cambridge: Cambridge Van der Linden, H. (2010), “Just Military
University Press. Preparedness,” International Journal of
— (1755b/1997), The Political Economy. Applied Philosophy, http://works.bepress.
‘The Discourses’ and Other Early com/harry_vanderlinden/43/.
Political Writings, trans. V. Gourevitch. Vitoria, F. di (1539/1991), “Di Indis et Di
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Juri Belli.” Vitoria: Political Writings,
— (c. 1756/1962), “A Lasting Peace through A. Padgen and J. Lawrance (eds).
the Federation of Europe,” and “The Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
State of War,” in C. E. Vaughan (ed.), Waltz, K. N. (1954), Man, the State, and
The Political writings of Jean-Jacques War: A Theoretical Analysis. New York:
Rousseau. Oxford: Blackwell. Columbia University Press.
Roy, K. (2012), Hinduism and the Ethics of Walzer, M. (1977), Just and Unjust Wars.
Warfare: from Antiquity to the Present. New York: Basic Books.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Wertheimer, R. (2010), Empowering our
Scheid, D. (ed.) (2014), The Ethics of Armed Military Conscience: Transforming
Humanitarian Intervention. Cambridge: Just War Theory and Military Moral
Cambridge University Press. Education. London: Ashgate Press.

125
8
PEACE
Andrew Fitz-Gibbon

THE NATURE OF PEACE AND oppressors in their own persons (2001, 3ff).
THE STATE OF NATURE In time the oppressor would cease violence,
having had a fill of it. He called this the “law
Just as history by and large is the history of self-sacrifice,” the “law of nonviolence,”
of wars, so in political philosophy more and the “law of suffering.” Just as the require-
is written on war than on peace. In politi- ment of the military is training in how to use
cal philosophy, peace is most often a nega- violence effectively, satyagrahis needed to be
tive concept, being the absence of something trained in how not to be violent (ibid., 92 ff).
else—the absence of war. More fruitful for Gandhi even called for an official “non-vio-
political philosophy has been the analysis of lent army” of trained volunteers numbering
conditions for, conduct of, and the justice of the thousands who could put themselves in
war, with an assumption that war, if not a harmful way to end violence (ibid., 86).
necessary aspect of social life, is more com- Martin Luther King, Jr relied extensively
mon than not. Yet, peace is the backdrop to on Gandhi’s developed nonviolent tech-
the commonly discussed areas within politi- niques (see his “Pilgrimage to Nonviolence”
cal philosophy—human and civil rights, in King 1986, 54–62). In his “My Trip to the
contracts, justice, property rights, and law. land of Gandhi,” King says, “True nonviolent
Without peace, these aspects of common resistance is not unrealistic submission to evil
human life make little sense. power. It is rather a courageous confronta-
Nonetheless, despite the predominance of tion of evil by the power of love, in the faith
war in political affairs, peace and nonvio- that it is better to be a recipient of violence
lence were central ideas behind much politi- than the inflictor of it, since the latter only
cal activism in the twentieth century. M. K. multiplies the existence of violence and bit-
Gandhi was the first to use techniques of terness in the universe, while the former may
nonviolent resistance, first in South Africa develop a sense of shame in the opponent,
(1893–1914) and then in India (1915–1947). and thereby bring about a transformation
For Gandhi, nonviolent protest required as and change of heart” (1986, 44).
much courage as warfare. The satyagrahis— King’s understanding of nonviolence led
those who practice satyagraha, “truth force” him eventually to oppose all war and to make
or “love-force”—were to resist oppressive significant protest of the Vietnam War. He
sanctions by absorbing the violence of their said, “I have come to the conclusion that the

127
Andrew Fitz-Gibbon

potential destructiveness of modern weapons Arab Spring revolutions of 2010–2011 (see


of war totally rules out the possibility of war Gan, 2013, 70).
ever serving as a negative good. If we assume However, some on the Left criticize non-
that mankind has a right to survive then we violent direct action as politically ineffective
must find an alternative to war and destruc- and not going far enough. Ward Churchill
tion” (ibid., 60). Gandhi and King held in in his Pacifism as Pathology says, “Pacifism
creative tension the notion that nonviolence as a strategy of achieving social, political,
was a “good,” an end in itself—something and economic change can only lead to the
akin to love or truth—with the notion of dead end of liberalism” (Churchill and Ryan,
nonviolent resistance as a political strategy. 2007, 33). Yet, in Eastern Europe, it was just
In other words, nonviolence was not merely such liberalism that the masses pursued as
a political technique, but the outworking of Soviet Communism faded.
a deeper metaphysics. Those who see nonviolence as more than
Since King, nonviolence as a political tool a sociopolitical strategy also have criticized
has been developed most especially by Gene the direction that Sharp, Ackerman, and
Sharp (1973a–c, 2005). Sharp analyzed dif- Duvall have taken. Barry L. Gan notes a
ferent techniques for using nonviolent pro- distinction between “selective nonviolence”
test as a means of achieving political ends. and “comprehensive nonviolence” (2013,
He suggested 198 different methods of non- 73 ff). Selective nonviolence rejects the use
violent action in order to bring about social of violence for pragmatic reasons in order
change. Peter Ackerman and Jack Duvall to accomplish a political aim. The “good” is
(2000) built on the pioneering work of not nonviolence itself, but rather the politi-
Sharp. Ackerman and Duvall analyzed 12 cal goal. If violence could achieve the goal
different movements in the twentieth cen- more effectively and quickly, then violence
tury which accomplished social and politi- would be used. However, some selective non-
cal change by direct nonviolent action. On violentists consider nonviolence as always a
close analysis, many of the movements better strategy than violence, and so make no
were not as clearly nonviolent as Ackerman resort to violent tactics. Nonetheless, non-
and Duvall suggest. Such change is accom- violence is still considered merely a tool to
plished by seizing the initiative to control a use toward some other goal. Comprehensive
conflict to make the opposition give-in to nonviolence is the rejection of violence in all
demands against their will. In practice, non- its forms; nonviolence being considered a
violent direct action is far from “peaceful.” good in itself. A comprehensive nonviolentist
Nonetheless, their conclusion is persua- will attempt to practice nonviolence in all
sive: nonviolent direct action is a powerful aspects of personal, social, and political life.
means of social and political change. Their Comprehensive nonviolentists reject some of
organization, the International Center on the techniques suggested by Sharp as being
Nonviolent Conflict, through its publi- inherently violent.
cations and DVDs was influential in the Gan also suggests that between the
overthrow of Serbian leader Slobodan extremes of selective and comprehensive
Milosevic in 2000, and Ukrainian leader nonviolence is a wide spectrum of under-
Viktor Yanukovych in 2004–2005. Their standings and practices. He places Tolstoy,
techniques were extensively used in the Gandhi, and King toward the pole of

128
PEACE

comprehensive nonviolence, and Sharp, newsletter. This 16-volume collection is the


Ackerman, and Duvall toward the pole of largest published collection of papers by phi-
selective nonviolence.1 losophers on the philosophy of peace.
Feminism has contributed to understand- In some recent political philosophy, a dis-
ings of peace through the ethics of care tinction has been made between “negative
and other feminist philosophical writing peace” and “positive peace.” Negative peace
(see Ruddick, 1990, Noddings, 2003, Held, is the mere absence of war. Positive peace
2007). Ethicists of care argue that it is, in has taken on a more full conceptualization, a
part, the impersonal masculinist themes of condition more akin to the Jewish notion of
political philosophy and ethics (contracts, Shalom and is a state of well-being, free from
rights, and duties) that allow even the con- violence. In different presentations, positive
templation of war as a good. The ethics of peace is a eudemonic, or else, a loving state.
care, focused on networks of personal caring Duane L. Cady says of positive peace, “the
relationships, would make war and violence point is always to build on and broaden our
less likely than other ethical schemes. sense of community by stressing interdepend-
Notable organizations involved in paci- ence, respect, tolerance, common aspirations,
fism and antiwar are the Fellowship of and understanding” (2010, 86).
Reconciliation, founded in 1914 as a Johan Galtung analyzes negative peace as:
Christian antiwar movement. It has since (a) the absence of violence of all kinds (physi-
become an interfaith organization involv- cal and psychological; (b) structural violence
ing all faiths and includes those who have (violence embedded in institutions); and (c)
no formal faith commitment (see the col- cultural violence (attitudes and values that
lection of writings from the Fellowship of tolerate harm) (1996, 31). In moving the
Reconciliation, Wink, 2000). discussion of violence beyond the bounds
Concerned Philosophers for Peace is the of physical violence (to psychological, struc-
largest organization of antiwar philosophers tural, and cultural harm), Galtung moves
in the United States. According to William the discussion of negative peace beyond the
Gay: notion of the absence of war. Although a
nation may not be at war, its citizens may be
Since its inception in 1981, Concerned subject to internal strife and various harms
Philosophers For Peace has become that Galtung classifies as violence. Positive
the largest and most active organiza- peace, then, is not only the absence of war
tion of professional philosophers in
together with these diverse violent harms,
North America oriented to the critique
but also a different kind of human interac-
of militarism and the search for a just
and lasting peace. Currently, Concerned tion. Michael Allen Fox suggests that positive
Philosophers For Peace has over 500 peace includes four aspects: (a) subjective (a
members in North America (2003). state of well-being); (b) objective (a goal
with a process to reach the goal); (c) cosmic
Concerned Philosophers for Peace has a (unity with a larger whole—not merely peace
book series in the Rodopi, Amsterdam, Value between human beings, but with other sen-
Inquiry Books Series, Philosophy of Peace tient beings and with the environment); and
Series (16 volumes at the time of writing with (d) prescriptive/visionary (guiding principles
3 more in preparation), and a semiannual and outlook) (2014, 188–193).

129
Andrew Fitz-Gibbon

HISTORICAL AND MULTICULTURAL it is not true to say that the Daodejing is a


PRECEDENTS pacifist text. In exceptional circumstances,
when attacked, the good ruler may use force
From ancient times, war has been an accepted of arms, but minimally so and with much
part of human interaction. In the ancient regret.
world, arguments against war are few and In the Zhuangzi, the treatment of war and
far between, though in the Crito Plato argues peace is more complex than in the Daodejing.
that we should never return evil for evil. One Scholars now realize that the Zhuangzi is a
interpretation of Plato would be to say that text from a number of writers in different
retaliation is morally wrong. As the con- periods, and so it does not speak with merely
duct of war is largely retaliatory, often with one voice (see Lynn, 2008). Those chap-
extreme violence, Plato’s argument might ters most likely written by Master Zhuang
be taken as an early argument against war accept that war is a fact of life and is best
(2011, Crito 48b–c). However, even if this avoided. When government becomes tyran-
is a true construction, Plato’s suggestion is a nical, it is acceptable to enter war as a last
mere drop of war resistance in a bucketful of resort to overthrow such governments. In
the political acceptance of, and justifications common with much other Daoist writing,
for, war. the Zhuangzi refrains from making value
It is not that notions of peace were absent judgments about the rightness or wrongness
from the ancient world. The Epicureans pur- of actions, and looks rather to a way to man-
sued ataraxia as the goal of human life—a age the many changes of life, which includes
state of tranquility untouched by the chances violence. However, the “anarchist chapters”
and changes of life—hence peace. Yet of the Zhuangzi, on the contrary, suggest that
ataraxia belongs to peace as an inner state. war is always morally wrong, even to allevi-
The pursuit of ataraxia was engaged in with ate the sufferings of others.
the knowledge that the world is one of con- Mozi makes a different argument than the
flict and war. There was no Epicurean anti- Daoists against war. He roots his antiwar
war movement in any political sense. sentiment in universal love. Even so, Mozi
In the East, early Daoist writings can be is not totally antiviolence. He makes an
interpreted as antiwar. Although in some argument for war against oppressors on the
interpretative traditions, the Daodejing is basis of justice. Universal love may, at times,
considered a military text, it tends toward require the strong to act violently on behalf
peace, personally and socially, rather than of the weak (Mo Tzu, 1963, 50–61).
war (Zhang, 2012). The Daodejing sees Ancient Buddhism and Jainism share the
peace as the natural way. War begins with concept of ahimsa—nonharm—and from
desire and the dao is to move beyond desire the sixth-century bce onward had a direct
toward a life of harmony with “the ten thou- influence on Hindu thought. Yet, in Buddhist
sand things”—all that is. Chapters  30 and thought the notion that all of life is suffering,
31 of the Daodejing are especially antiwar and that the eightfold path leads one away
seeing weapons as “ominous instruments,” from suffering have tended toward a social
sometimes translated as “instruments of evil.” conservatism and individualism. As suffering
The good ruler “will oppose all conquest by will be always a part of the human condi-
force of arms” (Waley, 2010, 149). However, tion, why try to eradicate it? The best hope

130
PEACE

is to become personally nonattached, and war of all against all. Peace, in a Hobbesian
hence avoid suffering. The political attempts world, is only possible by the imposition of
to embrace Buddhism as public policy, peace by a Leviathan, a governing authority
and hence antiwar, have been few and far that guards against the excesses of the natu-
between. A notable exception is Aśoka who ral state through imposition of law, backed
ruled most of India from c. 265 to 238 bce by force. For John Locke, whose state of
(see Cortwright, 2008, 186). However, more nature is more benign than Hobbes’s—a
recently a new tradition, known as engaged tabula rasa—natural reason shows human-
Buddhism, has taken the Buddhist notion of ity to be social, and therefore tending toward
metta—loving-kindness, as a starting point peaceful intercourse rather than violence. In
for engaged social action to alleviate suffer- response to Hobbes, Jean-Jacques Rousseau
ing and protest war. Vietnamese monk Thich gives us a third, more romantic view of the
Nhat Hanh (1992) and the Dalai Lama state of nature. Human beings, neither good
(1999) are notable in this regard. nor bad by nature, tend toward the develop-
The Western world had to wait for the early ment of peace when unaffected by the tram-
Christian movement for its first brief hiatus mels of civilization.
looking toward an antiwar philosophy. For Although in each view of the human con-
its first 250  years of existence, Christianity dition peace is a “good,” the Hobbesian view
was a pacifist movement (Hershberger, 1981, tends toward a realism that rejects pacifism,
64–70). Christians were forbidden from preferring an enforcing of limited peace.
being soldiers in the army of empire until The Lockean views something closer to a
around 174 ce, under the reign of Marcus liberal and reasonable searching for peace.
Aurelius, though it must be remembered Romanticism tends toward an unrealistic
that early Christianity was a movement utopian view of society where peace would
composed of slaves, women, and subaltern reign, if only we let it.
Jewish males. However, when Constantine Modern philosophers built their under-
embraced Christianity in the early fourth- standing of human nature—whether fun-
century ce, the pacifist religion became the damentally aggressive or pacifistic—from a
favored religion of Empire and began its careful reading of ancient texts, by obser-
own justifications for war. Besides some ele- vation of human behavior, and sometimes
ments of monasticism and a few minor sects because a certain view of human nature
in the medieval period, Christianity was at matched well with a religious or ideological
ease with violence, either enacted by the state viewpoint. However, recent developments
against other states in war, or in pogroms, in brain science have challenged the often-
inquisitions, and crusades. Some Christians held view that human beings are ineluctably
returned to pacifist roots, but not until the aggressive by nature. Suggestions, backed by
early sixteenth century (see later). science, that human beings are an empathic
In political philosophy, the possibilities and species have caused some controversy (see
procedures for peace depend, in part, on an Rifkin, 2009). At the very least psychologists
understanding of the human condition. What seem to have established that the human
would human nature look like in its natural being rather than being either always aggres-
state? Philosophers have been divided. For sive, or else pacifistic, has the potential for
Thomas Hobbes, the state of nature is one of predation, vengeance, and violence on the

131
Andrew Fitz-Gibbon

one hand, and for compassion, reason, and religious and political groups thrived. Some
peacefulness on the other (see Pinker, 2011, radicals were truly revolutionary, though
483–696). more often than not of an apocalyptic bent,
while some embraced the pacifism of a non-
violent Christ (Stayer, 1976). Those groups
that gradually embraced pacifism were his-
PACIFISMS torically longer lived as movements than the
violent revolutionaries. Although both types
Pacifism is generally taken to mean some- of radical were persecuted by both Catholic
thing like “opposition to war.” However, and Protestant state authorities, the peace-
there is no single understanding of pacifism in ful sects continued through migration, first
the literature. Scholars note these main types to Eastern Europe, and then to the new
of pacifism: (a) principled opposition to war world. These groups we know now as the
in all its forms, but not to all forms of vio- Amish, the Mennonites, and the Hutterites,
lence; (b) principled opposition to all kinds the historic peace churches. They have
of violence, which includes war; (c) princi- been largely pacifist groups who see them-
pled opposition to some kinds of war, such selves as islands of holiness in the vast sea
as in nuclear pacifism, but not to “conven- of godlessness—what Stayer terms “separa-
tional” war. However, Duane L. Cady (2010) tist nonresistance.” Those within the radical
suggests a moral continuum from warism to communities see themselves as within “the
pacifism, with the different versions of paci- perfection of Christ.” The rest of society is
fism melding into each other with no clear outside “the perfection of Christ.” The world
boundaries. is characterized mostly by violence, which
The early sixteenth century saw profound the Anabaptists eschew. Although pacifists,
changes in the political and social landscape the Anabaptists had a generally pessimis-
of Europe. Besides the major reforms pro- tic view of society and of political author-
duced by Martin Luther, Ulrich Zwingli, John ity, though most viewed the government as
Calvin, and others, a number of small radical God-given. They did not expect society to
sects arose—loosely termed Anabaptist—in become more peaceful (Brock, 1981, 20).
part in the wake of the breaking of the Nonetheless, the peaceful sixteenth-century
hegemony of the Roman church, and in part radicals influenced the pacifist groups of
as a reaction to the slow progress of reform the seventeenth century—most notably the
by the magisterial reformers. Once charac- Quakers—and many pacifists since. Whereas
terized as violent revolutionaries (in some the Anabaptists tended to withdraw from
tellings as proto-Marxist), the sixteenth- society, the Quakers under William Penn’s
century radicals were rebranded as pacifists leadership attempted the “holy experiment”
in the historiography of Mennonite scholars of a pacifist colony in the new world—
from the 1940s onward (see Estep, 1963, Pennsylvania. The pacifist colony was in
Hershberger, 1981). Careful, and non-par- part successful (in relationships with native
tisan, scholarship places the radicals some- Americans and in its generally humanitar-
where in between. The beginning of religious ian approach to law), but following Penn’s
and political freedom in the sixteenth century death Pennsylvania gradually moved away
was fertile ground in which many varieties of from its pacifist roots (Brock, 1981, 43–46).

132
PEACE

Anabaptist pacifism was of an absolute nonviolently. Thoreau’s view is significant for


kind and has been termed nonresistance, political philosophy in its direct challenge of
based on an interpretation of the gospel the legitimacy of government. Libertarians
text where Jesus says, “Do not resist evil.” and anarchists alike have used Thoreau as a
The text was interpreted to include not justification for an antigovernment stance.
only opposition to war or any government Thoreau (along with other New England
violence—“the sword”—but also any inter- pacifists) influenced Tolstoy. In turn, Thoreau
personal violence. The Anabaptists took the and Tolstoy’s work had a direct effect on the
injunction to “turn the other cheek” quite lit- young Mohandas Gandhi, then in South Africa,
erally. Even self-defense was considered mor- and later on Martin Luther King Jr. In process
ally wrong. Although few have followed the of time, the religious argument of the teach-
Anabaptist extreme of nonresistance, most ing of the New Testament—to not resist evil,
notably Leo Tolstoy embraced such radi- to love enemies, and to bless persecutors—was
cal pacifism in the late nineteenth century conjoined with Thoreau’s notion of civil diso-
(1984). Tolstoy differed from the Anabaptists bedience, based on conscience, to become the
in holding a more hopeful view of the world. social political strategy of nonviolent resist-
The Anabaptists considered the world unre- ance, sometimes termed simply nonviolence.
deemable until some great apocalyptic event.
Hence they did not try to change society, and
simply withdrew into closed communities.
Tolstoy, on the other hand, argued that all in THE PEACE OF LIBERAL,
society should embrace nonresistance. DEMOCRATIC CAPITALISM
The Anabaptist stance has often been
considered politically irrelevant—though In 1795, Immanuel Kant published his
in the twentieth century Anabaptist were influential treatise To Perpetual Peace: A
also conscientious objectors (see Brock and Philosophical Sketch. Kant was not a roman-
Young, 1999). However, scholars have used tic. With Hobbes, he assumed that “the natu-
Anabaptist-like arguments, that is religious, ral state is one of war” (1983, 111). For this
to protest war (see, e.g. Hauerwas, 1983, reason the state of peace “must therefore be
2004, Yoder, 1994, 1996, 1997). established,” and is not merely the suspen-
A different argument against war and sion of hostilities. Derived from this little
for a peaceful life is the brief but influential tract, and other parts of the Kantian canon,
tract by Henry David Thoreau, On The Duty political philosophers now speak of the
of Civil Disobedience written originally in Kantian Triad—the mutual interplay of: (a)
1849, in part as protest both to slavery and democracy (which Kant calls a republican
to the Mexican war. Thoreau’s basis is not a constitution, meaning freedom, equality, and
religious one, but is based on the inviolabil- the rule of law, 112); (b) a “federation of free
ity of the individual conscience. Government states” (115); and (c) cosmopolitanism and
has no right to demand anything from citi- the right of universal hospitality. Although
zens (for Thoreau the best form of govern- in Kant’s paper cosmopolitanism is the third
ment is no government at all). As government of his conditions for peace, the triad is usu-
demand citizens to enter the military, it is the ally completed rather with trade and inter-
citizen’s duty to resist, to disobey government national cooperation (perhaps after Adam

133
Andrew Fitz-Gibbon

Smith who argued in Book 5 of The Wealth story of European imperialism from the
of Nations against wars of imperialism as Renaissance until the decolonization begun
being too expensive to maintain (see 2000, after the Second World War. Now, even the
277ff). The argument suggests that the best most powerful nations must practice peace-
hope for a peaceful world is one in which ful trade with those whose goods and services
nations favor democracy, international fed- they require. For all the suggested ills of mul-
erations, and free trade. tinational corporations, because of the fiscal
In brief, the argument is that democracies peace they create between nations (often in
do not go to war with each other. The notion conflict in the recent past), some argue that
has provoked debate. Much depends on what they may yet be the best hope for a world
counts toward a nation being considered free of wars, and hence at peace.2
democratic. However, from careful research In 1982, Michael Novak published his The
Bruce Russett and John Oneal, in 2001, pre- Spirit of Democratic Capitalism. Although
sented evidence that, over time, democra- initially largely ignored in the West, in Eastern
cies favor peace over war (see discussion in Europe the book became a key text in the
Gartzke, 2007, Pinker, 2011, 278–288). overthrow of Soviet Communism (first pub-
Although before its time, Kant’s view of lished underground in Poland in 1984). His
an international federation is something conception of democratic capitalism was a
like the United Nations to which member triad—the three liberations of liberalism—of
states devolve at least some of their sover- a democratic polity, a capitalist system, and
eignty for the sake of all—effectively a social a humanitarian culture of freedom. Missing
contract between nations. Just as individual from the Kantian triad is the notion of a
citizens give up their right of the lawful use humanitarian and free culture. If the Kantian
of violence to the police force and military, and Novakian are combined, a tetrad is pro-
so individual states give up their lawful use duced: democratic polity, an international
of violence to an international body. Just as federation of nations, free trade between
citizens make up the police force and military nations, and a humanitarian culture.
of any particular state, so the peacekeeping However, such an approach is not a paci-
force of the United Nations is made up of fist stance. Theorists who suggest that such is
military units from member states. the best hope for a peaceful world also sug-
Democratic nations, joined in loose inter- gest that war is sometimes a necessity, often
national confederation, will also freely trade in self-defense, and, less frequently, to effect
with each other. This argument is that those regime change. Such a conception of peace
who rely on trade with others are less likely is not comprehensively pacifist in the total
to go to war with them. Erik Gartzke makes opposition to war, but might be realistically
such an argument, though it is debated. In pacifist in seeking to restrain rogue nations—
simple terms, you do not engage in war with through force of arms if necessary.
those upon whom you depend for trade. A broad political philosophy of peace
Before the wars of the twentieth century, would need to consider all of the earlier. It
if a powerful state needed resources, and would be a synthetic construct that would
another nonstate or less powerful state has include the Kantian triad, combined with a
those resources, the first state would simply humanitarian culture. It would take notice of
take what it needed. This was the dominant the various movements of nonviolent direct

134
PEACE

action. It would include, too, a considera- Brock, P. and Young, N. (1999), Pacifism
tion of comprehensive nonviolence and an in the Twentieth Century. Toronto:
emphasis on the work of subjective peace. University of Toronto Press.
Political philosophers, who ordinarily do not Cady, D. L. (2010), From Warism
take much notice of pacifism, would do well to Pacifism: A Moral Continuum.
to look at the work of scholars of war resist- Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press.
ance. Pacifists and war resisters, whose aim Churchill, W. and M. Ryan (2007), Pacifism
must surely be the end of warfare, would be as Pathology: Reflections on the Role
helped by a more thoughtful analysis of the of Armed Struggle in North America.
Kantian Triad and its contribution to world Oakland: A.K. Press.
peace. Cortwright, D. (2008), Peace: A History
of Movements and Ideas. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Notes Estep, W. R. (1963), The Anabaptist Story.
Grand Rapids, MI: Wm. B. Eerdmans.
1
For an extended essay on the implementation Fox, M. A. (2014), Understanding Peace: A
of non-violence, see Nagler (2004). For the Comprehensive Introduction. New York
history of peace movements, see Cortwright
and London: Routledge.
(2008). For an eclectic collection of essays on
non-violence, see Zinn (2002). For the history Galtung, J. (1996), Peace by Peaceful Means:
of non-violence, see Kurlansky (2009). For a Peace and Conflict, Development and
general introduction to peace studies, see Fox Civilization. Oslo: PRIO International
(2014). For an historical collection of essays Peace Research Institute, and London:
on non-violence, see Holmes and Gan (2005).
SAGE.
2
On capitalism and peace, see Gartzke (2007).
For Hegel’s contrary view to Kant—that Gan, B. L. (2013), Violence and
perpetual peace is undesirable, that war is Nonviolence: An Introduction. Lanham:
inherent in the dialectic method, see Armstrong Rowman & Littlefield.
(1933) and Smith (1983). For Rousseau’s less Gandhi, M. K. (2001), Non-Violent
optimistic view of international peace through
Resistance (Satyagraha). Mineola, NY:
a federation of nations, see Hoffmann (1963).
Dover.
Gartzke, E. (2007), “The Capitalist Peace,”
American Journal of Political Science, 51
WORKS CITED (1): 166–191.
Gay, W. (2003), A History of Concerned
Ackerman, P. and Duvall, J. (2000), A Force Philosophers for Peace. http://
More Powerful: A Century of Nonviolent peacephilosophy.org/?page_id=97
Conflict. Palgrave: New York. (accessed December 19, 2013).
Armstrong, A. C. (1933), “Hegel’s Attitude Hanh, T. N. (1992), Peace in Every Step:
on War and Peace,” The Journal of The Path of Mindfulness in Every Day
Philosophy, 30 (December 25): 684–689. Life. New York: Bantam.
Brock, P. (1981), The Roots of War Hauerwas, S. (1983), The Peaceable
Resistance: Pacifism from the Early Kingdom: A Primer in Christian Ethics.
Church to Tolstoy. Nyack: The Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame
Fellowship of Reconciliation. Press.

135
Andrew Fitz-Gibbon

— (2004), Performing the Faith: Bonhoeffer Noddings, N. (2003), Caring: A Feminine


and the Practice of Nonviolence. Grand Approach to Ethics and Moral Education.
Rapids, MI: Brazos Press. Berkeley, CA: University of California
Held, V. (2007), The Ethics of Care: Press.
Personal, Political And Global. Oxford: Novak, M. (1982/1991), The Spirit of
Oxford University Press. Democratic Capitalism. London: IEA
Hershberger, G. F. (1981), War, Peace, and Health and Welfare Unit.
Nonresistance; A Classic Statement of a Pinker, S. (2011), The Better Angels of Our
Mennonite Peace Position in Faith and Nature: Why Violence Has Declined.
Practice. Scottdale: Herald Press. London: Penguin.
Hoffman, S. (1963), “Rousseau on War and Plato (2011), The Last Days of Socrates.
Peace,” The American Political Science London: Penguin.
Review, 57 (2) (June): 317–333. Rifkin, J. (2009), The Empathic Civilization:
Holmes, R. L. and Gan, B. L. (2005), The Race to Global Consciousness in a
Nonviolence in Theory and Practice. World of Crisis. New York: Jeremy
Longrove, IL: Waveland. P. Tarcher/Penguin.
Kant, I. (1983), Perpetual Peace and Other Ruddick, S. (1990), Maternal Thinking:
Essays. Indianapolis: Hackett. Towards a Politics of Peace. London:
King, M. L., Jr (1986), I Have a Dream: Women’s Press.
Writings and Speeches that Changed Sharp, G. (1973a), The Politics of
the World, J. M. Washington (ed.). San Nonviolent Action: Part One Power
Francisco: Harper. and Struggle. Boston, MA: Porter
Kurlansky, M. (2009), Non-Violence: The Sargent.
History of a Dangerous Idea, foreword — (1973b), The Politics of Nonviolent
by His Holiness the Dalai Lama. Action: Part Two The Methods of
New York: The Modern Library. Nonviolent Action. Boston, MA: Porter
Lama, D. (1999), Ethics for a New Sargent.
Millennium. New York: Berkley. — (1973c), The Politics of Nonviolent
Lynn, R. J. (2008), “View of War As Seen Action: Part Three The Dynamics of
in the Zhangzi as Interpreted by Guo Nonviolent Action. Boston, MA: Porter
Xiang,” in H.-G. Möller and G. Wohlfart Sargent.
(eds), Philosophieren Über Den Krieg— — (2005), Waging Nonviolent Struggle:
War in Eastern and Western Philosophies. 20th Century Practice and 21st Century
Berlin: Parega Verlag. Potential. Boston, MA: Porter Sargent.
Mo Tzu. (1963), Basic Writings, trans. Smith, A. (2000), The Wealth of Nations.
B. Watson. New York: Columbia New York: Penguin.
University Press. Smith, S. B. (1983), “Hegel’s View on War,
Nagler, M. N. (2004), The Search for the State, and International Relations,”
a Nonviolent Future: A Promise of The American Political Science Review,
Peace for Ourselves, Our Families, and 77 (3) (September): 624–632.
Our World. Maui, HI: Inner Ocean Stayer, J. M. (1976), Anabaptists and the
Publishing. Sword. Lawrence, KS: Coronado Press.

136
PEACE

Tolstoy, L. (1984), The Kingdom of God is — (1996), When War is Unjust: Being
Within You: Christianity Not as a Mystic Honest About Just War Thinking.
Religion but as a New Theory of Life, Maryknoll, NY: Orbis.
trans. C. Garnett. Lincoln: University of — (1997), For the Nations: Essays Public
Nebraska Press. and Evangelical. Grand Rapids, MI: Wm.
Waley, A. (2010), Lao Tzu: Tao Te Ching The B. Eerdmans.
Way and Its Power and Its Place in Chinese Zhang, E. Y. (2012), “Weapons are Nothing
Thought. London: The Folio Society. But Ominous Instruments:
Wink, W. (ed.) (2000), Peace is the Way: The Daodejing’s View of War and Peace,”
Writings on Nonviolence from the Journal of Religious Ethics, September,
Fellowship of Reconciliation. Maryknoll, pp. 473–502.
NY: Orbis Books. Zinn, H. (Introduction) (2002), The Power
Yoder, J. H. (1994), The Politics of Jesus. of Nonviolence: Writings by Advocates of
Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans. Peace. Boston, MA: Beacon Press.

137
9
LIBERAL TOLERATION
Robert Paul Churchill

Toleration is indispensable for liberal democ- with or using coercion to prevent the expres-
racy, both as a public recognized attitude and sion of beliefs, views, behaviors, or practices
disposition among citizens to engage publicly that one considers seriously objectionable. To
with one another on the basis of what Rawls count as serious the objection must be based
(1993) called the “duty of civility,” and as an on more than personal interest, prudence,
accepted principle that a liberal democratic preference, or taste; rather it reflects a con-
state must be neutral between competing con- sidered judgment that something is seriously
ceptions of the human good. Individual toler- wrong because of its nature or consequences.
ance, as a personal or civic virtue, is not the For example, a citizen who believes same sex
same as neutrality as an institutional norm; this civil unions are objectionable on moral or
is because, while individuals can be tolerant religious grounds is tolerant if she believes,
only by choice, constitutional provisions, laws, as well, that her objections—as strong as they
or appellate court rulings can, by imposing may be—do not provide sufficient grounds
limits on government power, thereby establish for the legal prohibition of same sex civil
an effective measure of neutrality. The major- unions or coercive interference with LBGT
ity of literature on toleration has assumed it partnerships.
to pertain to individuals, particularly beliefs These reflections show that, as Rainer
about the proper behavior of citizens, and Forst (2012b) indicates, tolerant beliefs,
appropriate attitudes and dispositions within a attitudes, dispositions, and behaviors must
liberal state. Here, we consider toleration as a have an “objection component” requiring
matter relating to individuals before consider- that the objection be nontrivial for the tol-
ing liberal neutrality and related issues. erant individual, as well as an “acceptance,”
or “forbearance” component that, though
in tension with the objection, prevails, or
“trumps,” the objection. The forbearance
NECESSARY AND SUFFICIENT condition does not cancel out the objection;
CONDITIONS FOR INDIVIDUAL rather, the tolerant individual believes that
TOLERATION the objection is reasonably grounded, but
accepts other, higher-order reasons, to guide
In general, toleration can be understood as her attitudes and actions. The higher-order
the disposition to forbear from interfering reasons may include, for example, respect for

139
Robert Paul Churchill

others’ autonomous choices, respect for the There are other attitudes or dispositions,
importance of certain beliefs and practices in variously called “indulgence,” “permissive-
other people’s lives, or beliefs about the value ness,” “indifference,” and “promiscuity” or
of a reciprocal give-and-take in a pluralistic “indiscriminateness,” that are carelessly used
society. as synonymous for “toleration.” However,
By accepting the objection and forbearance by keeping the objection and forbearance
components as necessary conditions for liberal conditions in mind, we can see why these
toleration, we can reduce much of the ambi- terms do not connote the same attitudes and
guity, and hence, vacuity that accompanies dispositions as liberal toleration. Those who
many uses of “tolerance” (Churchill, 1997). are indulgent or permissive allow the expres-
Thus, because of the objection condition, we sion of views and behaviors they themselves
cannot regard one’s forbearance as a genuine might not engage in, but either they have
instance of toleration unless the forbearance formed no objections or whatever objections
is voluntarily chosen and capable of being they do form fail to rise to a threshold of sig-
reasonable. If one grudgingly endures or puts nificance. Because they are not motivated to
up with something without having considered object, the indulgent and permissive likewise
that being reasonable recommends forbear- need no reasons for forbearance. Similarly,
ance, then one’s attitude or behavior is not those who are indifferent and indecisive
tolerant as understood here. Indeed, citizens should not be confused with the liberally
who appear willing to “go along” but offer no tolerant. The indifferent and indecisive lack
plausible reasons for voluntarily doing so and reasonable grounds for either objection or
express annoyance and disapproval, for hav- acceptance, and are therefore, hardly toler-
ing to “put up” with a situation, can be sus- ant in a liberal sense.
pected of interfering with or obstructing what What can be said then, about the happy-
they object to should they have the ability to go-lucky who have an open-handed “live
do so. If the difference between one’s letting and let live” outlook? Such generous souls
others be versus obstructing them turns on represent, in Plato’s view (c. 320 bc), both
power, or capacity, alone, then one can hardly the flowering beauty of democracy and the
be regarded as tolerant. primary reason for democracy’s self-destruc-
By contrast, it is not necessary that toler- tiveness (Republic, IX). Whatever the merits
ant persons have the power to prevent or to of Plato’s political philosophy, his criticism of
interfere with something they find seriously the promiscuity and profligacy of a democ-
objectionable (Williams, 1996). There is no racy cannot be counted as a criticism of lib-
contradiction in conceiving of a powerless eral toleration. Those, like Plato’s democrats,
minority, for instance, having serious moral who believe themselves committed in prin-
objections to a practice, such as gambling, ciple to equally accepting everything cannot
adult theatres, or dog racing, but neverthe- be truly committed to tolerance. Toleration
less tolerating a majority’s interests in these requires boundaries; if nothing can be con-
practices. It is sufficient that members of ceived to be in the realm of the intolerable
such a minority believe that even if they did and to be rejected, then toleration is a vacu-
have the requisite capacity, they would not ous concept.
interfere, and that others accept such claims This last consideration indicates that, while
as sincere. necessary, the objection and forbearance

140
LIBERAL TOLERATION

conditions are not sufficient for toleration. widely cited “paradox” is the “paradox of
A third condition, what Forst (2004, 2012b) moral tolerance” (Mendus, 1988, Horton,
calls the “rejection” condition, needs to be 1994). A paradox seems to arise when both
added to our conception of liberal toleration. the reasons for objection and the reasons for
Toleration thus lies in the middle ground acceptance are held to be “moral.” In such
between two boundaries. If the tolerable cases, it then seems to be morally required
consists of the realm of beliefs and practices or right to tolerate what is morally wrong.
one finds wrong but still marked by reasons As the discussion earlier indicates, the solu-
for forbearance, then a limiting boundary tion to this puzzle (and thus dissolution of
“above” this consists of the realm of the non- the apparent paradox) requires a distinction
objectionable. The other boundary separates between various kinds of “moral” reasons
the tolerable middle realm from the realm and a ranking of those reasons. For instance,
“below” for which reasons for rejecting cer- with respect to abortion, meat eating, gam-
tain beliefs and practices are stronger than bling, pornography, handgun ownership, and
the reasons for forbearance. so forth, persons can consistently (both con-
The addition of the “rejection” condition in ceptually and psychologically) regard these
no way commits us to a static view of the con- activities as immoral and believe and act on
tent of toleration. Deciding whether and where the conviction that higher-order moral rea-
to draw boundaries is the perennial subject of sons justify their forbearance.
debate, dispute, lobbying, influence, and politi- A second “paradox” of toleration arises
cal compromise. Moreover, there may be many out of the apparent possibility of conceiving
different reasons for drawing the boundary of an intolerant person as tolerant, which
line in one place rather than another. Consider, seems contradictory. The so-called paradox
for example, a dispute over tolerating the of the tolerant racist presumes it possible
desecration of the flag but not of religious for a racist, an anti-Semite, a xenophobe,
icons such as the crucifix or the Qur’an. This and so on to be tolerant of persons against
issue involves which type of freedom ought whom he has an irrational hatred or preju-
to prevail—whether freedom of expression dice. Should we be tempted to suppose that
or religious freedom, but there may be other a racist might be tolerant if he could curb
reasons involved as well, such as respect for his desire to discriminate against a group
religious or even national security inasmuch as he regards as inferior, and moreover, that
desecrating holy books and religious icons can he would become increasingly tolerant the
inflame violence (Newey, 1999). stronger his racist impulses as long as he
does not act them out?
The effort to formulate this puzzle reveals
why such a “paradox” is fatuous. In the first
SO-CALLED PARADOXES OF place, we must presuppose that the racist
TOLERATION harbors an irrational hatred for members
of the target group, and consequently, it is
Those skeptical that the concept of toleration extremely unlikely, if not impossible, that the
is coherent, or that being tolerant is psycho- racist’s objections to the target group will be
logically possible, occasionally speak of one reasonable in the minimal sense required by
or more “paradoxes of toleration.” The most the objection condition. Second, it makes no

141
Robert Paul Churchill

sense to regard someone as tolerant or intol- To be sure, those zealously engaged in


erant of the characteristics of persons over efforts to demarcate the limits of the “intol-
which the latter have no control, such as age, erable” may appropriate the rhetoric of toler-
conditions of birth, ethnicity, gender, race, ance to purse their own one-sided, intolerant
and sexual orientation (Churchill, 2003, objectives. Such slogans as “no toleration for
2007). As persons (generally) are not at lib- the intolerant” (Forst, 2004) reveal the error,
erty to change or alter such ascribed char- once again, of assuming that persons are pos-
acteristics, it makes no sense to hold them sible “objects” of tolerance or intolerance.
to blame for possessing them. Third, persons Those inclined to be intolerant of persons
prejudiced against a group based on a shared with whom they disagree (the “intolerant”)
group characteristic, such as being a Jew or a signify their opposition to accepting the
Muslim, cannot specify how members of the norm of toleration in the first place. Hence,
group could change or behave to be “toler- because they deny the basic norm, they sig-
able,” except, of course, to cease being mem- nify a willingness to settle the issue “outside
bers of the despised group (by conversion) or the game,” as it were, and disparage reason-
by being displaced or removed (by deporta- able debate and (often) democratic processes
tion or ethnic cleansing). This shows that, in for settling disagreements. If a group remains
addition to a blind prejudice, biased persons intransigent in its denial of the norm of tol-
are really opposed to toleration itself. eration, then those who seek to uphold the
A third so-called paradox is thought norm are not thereby “intolerant” of the
to arise out of efforts to draw boundaries detractors, but only of their destructive views
between what is tolerable and what is intol- and actions.
erable (Fish, 1997, Forst, 2004). The so-
called paradox of drawing the limit arises
because drawing limits against things des-
ignated as “intolerable” will be contested in TOLERATION, THE LIBERAL STATE,
an open and pluralistic society, thus making AND NEUTRALITY
line drawing arbitrary. Yet why presume it
impossible to draw the limits of toleration A liberal state is one characterized by
in a nonarbitrary, justifiable way? There is a the public acceptance of freedom, equal-
consensus based on reasonable grounds that ity, and fairness as foundational political
some behaviors, such as child pornography, values. Consequently, a liberal state must
smoking in workspaces shared with non- accord equal respect to autonomous choices
smokers, bullying in schools, racial profiling, regarding the good and right. It is a practi-
are intolerable. Some policy issues are indeed cal necessity therefore that a liberal state
fraught with difficulty—handgun ownership must accommodate a plurality of interests,
in America is certainly one—but arbitrary value orientations, and commitments in reli-
line drawing can be avoided if both sides gion, ethics, and so on as well as competing
accept that they must not confuse members comprehensive visions of human flourish-
of the other side with the ideas or practices ing. Moreover, it must be expected that,
they find objectionable, and both sides accept in addition to a plurality of incompatible
the necessity of offering public reasons, as interests and values, some disagreements
will be noted in the next section. over the human good will be intractable. As

142
LIBERAL TOLERATION

Rawls (1993) notes, despite the challenges or provisions protecting individual rights,
of accommodating such deep disagreements, and bodies empowered to strike down laws
they are perfectly reasonable, for they result or decrees as unconstitutional (e.g. the
from the free exercise of human reason under Supreme Court in the United States, and the
the conditions of open inquiry and freedom Constitutional Council in France). In some
of conscience the liberal state is committed to polities, notably the United Kingdom, the
safeguarding. constitution is not codified but is made up
Toleration is thus a necessary norm for a of many limitations of power dating back to
well-ordered and successfully functioning lib- Magna Carta (1215) and many reservations
eral democracy, and we can distinguish two of rights, such as the English Bill of Rights
ways in which toleration serves as an indis- (1689). In addition, while it is expected that
pensable regulative norm. Roughly speaking, the liberal state will not penalize beliefs or
there must be toleration with respect to the practices some citizens, even if a majority,
public use of force or coercion. Secondly, citi- find repugnant (e.g. X-rated adult films or
zens must be tolerant among themselves. No hate speech) usually the object of oppro-
liberal state can equally respect a plurality of brium is arguably within a realm legally or
conflicting values and visions of the human constitutionally protected against govern-
good unless there is forbearance regarding ment interference (e.g. free speech). These
the public use of force or coercion to deter, considerations show that a liberal and neu-
interfere, prevent, or punish. In other words, tral state is “tolerant” only in a secondary
unlike an illiberal state including an illiberal sense, that is, in terms of the arrangements
democracy, the coercive powers of the liberal for the use of public power citizens agreed
state must not be used in efforts to legislate to be justified.
morality, to be paternalistic, or to promote It is conceivable that liberal outcomes may
one conception of the good life against oth- be the consequences, or effects, of the for-
ers. The need for restraints on government bearance of a benevolent despot or autocrat.
power is generally expressed in democratic However, liberalism cannot be contingent on
liberal theory as the principle of neutral- the good will of an autocrat. The stability and
ity where “neutrality” is understood as the continuity of a liberal state depends, in some
requirement that the liberal state must be meaningful way, on the consent of the citizens
neutral between competing conceptions of who comprise the civil society supporting the
the good (e.g. Simmons, 2007). state. While consent is often discussed as rel-
While neutrality is a necessary require- evant to the justification of the foundational
ment for the liberal state, it is incorrect to principles of the liberal sate, the necessity of
regard neutrality as a public norm for citi- accepting the actual procedures that keep the
zens. As the conceptual analysis earlier indi- liberal state running is less often remarked.
cates, toleration as an individual attribute Yet, unless a majority of citizens consent (in
cannot be compelled. However, the power some way) to the same “rules of the game”
of the government is limited. Typically, and on a day-to-day basis, a genuinely liberal
liberal and democratic polities such as polity would be impossible. Hence, liberal
France and the United States have a writ- states need to be democracies.
ten constitution establishing a separation Citizens must accept as binding democratic
of powers and checks and balances, clauses procedures even when they know that those

143
Robert Paul Churchill

procedures may produce outcomes they find democratic processes operate. For unless
seriously objectionable. In this sense, then, citizens are confident that they will not be
citizens must be tolerant of “losses” they subject to loses concerning their deepest
experience within a system they consent to comprehensive visions of human good, they
as formally, or procedurally, just. In addition, will not consider themselves able to tolerate
citizens must accept it as a public good that their uncertain fortunes at the ballot box or
just democratic procedures can justly resolve as a result of democratic politics.
difficult issues, and they must accept it as This feature of toleration can be regarded
reasonable to attach greater importance to as a social capital, or civic virtue, within a
the outcomes of democratic procedures than liberal democracy, as we will discuss in the
to manipulating procedures to advance their next section.
own special interests.
Toleration as a general norm for demo-
cratic citizens within a functioning democ-
racy is far more implicit than explicit. Yet THE DUTY OF CIVILITY AND
reliance on just procedures is manifest every PUBLIC REASONS
time there is shared understanding of the
reasonable limits of contested interests and There is a second specification or feature
policies. Once all interested parties have had of the implicit norm of citizen toleration.
a fair opportunity to advocate, to express Tolerance is not only required to accept func-
their views, to vote, to appeal, or to compete tioning democratic procedures, but also as a
for office and a specific outcome has been form of public interaction in a liberal democ-
reached through democratic means (e.g. as racy. Toleration requires that in debating pol-
results of elections, or Supreme Court deci- icy options we recognize one another as equal
sions), then contestation must cease. An participants in self-government. Toleration
example is the decision by Vice President Al also requires that citizens respect each other’s
Gore to accept the Supreme Court decision reasonableness and decision-making capaci-
(in Bush v. Gore) that enabled George W. ties. The willingness to take this view toward
Bush to become the president-elect in 2000, fellow citizens and to be reasonable in debate
even though a continuing recount of Florida must be a form of tolerance, for we would
ballots might have shown that Gore car- certainly consider citizens intolerant if they
ried Florida and won the presidency. As this acted as if they believed that they did not
example illustrates, accepting the results of a accept the principle of equal respect, or did
democratic outcome as final and reasonable not respect autonomously made decisions
mirrors the combination of the objection and when they found them objectionable in con-
forbearance conditions necessary for tolera- tent or result.
tion. Whereas a very strong and principled This aspect of toleration bears some
objection to an outcome may remain, it is resemblance to the form of social capital
nevertheless accepted. In this connection, we called civic virtue (Almond and Verba, 1989,
also see how critically important it is that Putnam, 2004). It certainly requires that
most citizens accept foundational princi- citizens make every effort to practice what
ples—and neutrality most importantly—as Rawls called the “duty of civility” (1993);
providing the framework within which this is the duty to offer one’s fellow citizens

144
LIBERAL TOLERATION

public reasons when deliberating with them of toleration as normative corresponded


about the public good. Knowing that contro- (roughly) with the rise of democratic and
versy occurs against the backdrop of deep, liberal forms of governance. All three—tol-
possibly intractable, disagreements, we must eration, democratic theory, and liberalism—
be able to explain the basis for any law or arose in tandem with increasing claims about
policy we advocate by appealing to public the rights of man, respect for the dignity of
reasons. Reasons are “public” in the required the individual, awareness of the epistemic
sense when they are consistent with everyone limitations of knowledge, and awareness of
else’s status as a free and equal fellow citizen. the differences between the ineluctable sub-
Public reasons are thus those reasons whose jectivity of personal experience versus public
status as reasons is shared equally among responsibilities (Creppell, 2003).
citizens.
For instance, debates over the spanking of
children may not advert to religious convic-
tions or cultural traditions, as these are not JUSTIFICATIONS OF TOLERATION
public reasons. Their force as reasons relies
on faith or on cultural memberships that can Up until the twentieth century, arguments
be reasonably rejected. By contrast, public against intolerance have been more promi-
reasoning may advert to reasons relating to nent than positive arguments for toleration.
parental childrearing practices that alterna- Despite the fact that “intolerance” and “tol-
tively foster or diminish the optimal devel- erance” are not strictly contradictory, the
opment of children as democratic citizens. case against intolerance often has furnished
Reasons of the latter kind, open as they are reasons for greater tolerance. Historically,
to empirical investigation, are public for they there have been two major lines of argument
do not draw on deep, controversial concep- against intolerance. One has been primarily
tions of human flourishing. In addition, the epistemic and emphasizes the fallibility of
well-being and civic virtue of children is an human reason. Montaigne’s (1533–1592)
objective which we can expect all citizens— widely influential Essays marked a water-
whatever their other commitments—to share shed in the development of humility and
as reasons. But reasons adverting to faith or moral psychology. For Montaigne, it is via
cultural traditions can be reasonably rejected, the human body through which we engage
for it can be expected that fellow citizens and judge the world (Creppell, 2003), and
with different fundamental values will regard our sensory perspectives are always relative
them as unreasonable. to some time and place, and inevitably sub-
Rawls claimed that a liberal state retains jective. We thus cannot pretend to encounter
its legitimacy only if citizens, in their pub- life in terms of some grand prearranged plan.
lic capacity, commit to the “ideal of public The value of life must be comprehended in
reason” (1993). Hypothetically, the legiti- terms of the individual’s encounter with
macy of a law or a policy decision would be it: “Life must be its own objective, its own
a result of its justification being impossible purpose. Its right concern is to rule itself,
to reasonably reject. Given the importance of govern itself, put up with itself” (Essays III,
toleration for democratic and liberal states, it 12, 1191). For Montaigne, “Nature brought
is not surprising that the historical emergence us forth free and unbound: we imprison

145
Robert Paul Churchill

ourselves in particular confines” (Essays III, In the Philosophical Commentaries of


9, 1101); society constricts persons through 1685, Bayle also offered an epistemic argu-
the habits, tastes, and customs it imprints ment against intolerance that significantly
upon us. For Montaigne, the mind’s inquir- influenced the Enlightenment and the moral
ies, when freed from artificial strictures, are sense theorists. Whereas Montaigne argues
“shapeless and without limits; its nourish- that fallibility must be acknowledged as
ment consists in amazement, the hunt and a result of accepting the human condition
uncertainty” (Essays III, 13, 1211). itself, Bayle maintains that fallibility must
Montaigne’s cultivation of openness to new be inferred from the limitations of the intel-
experiences, and his sensitivity to his own lect itself. What Bayle called the “natural
uncertainties filled Montaigne with respect light” of practical reason discloses its own
for diversity as well as natural equality. He limitations including an inability to discern
reminds us wittily that even “upon the highest ultimate truths. In addition, Bayle argued
throne in the world, we are seated, still, upon positively for toleration as based on moral
our arses” (Essays III, 13, 426). Montaigne considerations. For Bayle, all humans possess
argued, in addition, that “There is a porous- this natural light, which reveals certain moral
ness between the self and others that prevents truths to those who consult it with humility
defining oneself and persons one encounters and sincerity of heart. It matters not, Bayle,
in unchanging categories” (Creppell, 2003, claimed what religious faith one professes, or
89). In Montaigne’s words, “there is as much even whether one is an atheist. The principles
difference between us and ourselves as there of moral respect and reciprocity revealed by
is between us and other people” (Essays II, the natural light cannot be trumped by the
1, 380). Thus, in consequence of his human- claims of religion because the latter are of an
ism, skepticism, and belief in natural equality, entirely different epistemological character.
Montaigne condemned the prejudice, cru- Religion is based on faith, and therefore its
elty, and intolerance lying behind the wars of “truths” are those of faith and trust, and not
religion, witchcraft persecutions, the use of apprehensions of an objective world.
torture, and the Spanish colonization of the By far the most important and far-
Americas. A willingness to resort to violence ­reaching argument concerning toleration in
presupposes infallibility about good and bad, the seventeenth century was Locke’s A Letter
right or wrong that defies the human condi- Concerning Toleration (1689). Continuing
tion. “To kill people, there must be sharp and the logic of limited government to protect
brilliant clarity; this life of ours is too real, too natural rights for which Locke had argued in
fundamental, to be used to guarantee these The Second Treatise of Government (1689),
supernatural and imagined events” (Essays III, in the Letter Locke turns to the proper sepa-
11, 1167). And Montaigne continues, “After ration between state or institutional power
all, it is to put a very high value on your sur- versus the freedom of the individual to auton-
mises to roast a man alive for them” (Essays omously determine for herself what religious
III, 11, 1169). Whatever the credulity persons beliefs and obligations she will take on. Thus
attach to their convictions, they cannot be Locke argues that, while it is the duty of the
more probably true, Montaigne surmises, than state to protect the natural rights of citizens,
the inherent value each of us attaches to his or the “care of the soul” cannot be the state’s
her bodily existence in the here and now. business. As a subjective matter of faith and

146
LIBERAL TOLERATION

belief, true conviction cannot be produced by interference of the government and social
coercion; only an outward pretense of con- pressure, and “other-regarding” activity, or
formity can result from coercion, and such the realm of action the government and pub-
a show cannot be pleasing to God. Hence lic may reasonably take an interest in. Mill’s
the state must respect a God-given and inal- main argument for this distinction is based
ienable right to the free exercise of religion. on his “harm principle,” according to which
Moreover, as churches themselves exist only the exercise of social or political power is
as voluntary associations of their members, legitimate only if necessary to prevent harm
churches have no right to use force to require done by one person to another (non-consent-
membership or to prevent apostasy. Allowing ing) individual. It is never permissible, Mill
churches to exercise such powers is inconsist- argued, for the state to be paternalistic, pre-
ent with a political order based on the con- suming it knows the good for an individual
sent of the governed. better than the individual knows for herself.
Locke’s argument for respect for auton- Likewise, it is not permissible for a major-
omy underlying freedom of religion was ity to use law to restrict beliefs, actions, or
incomplete, however. Locke himself believed practices it finds offensive or immoral, in the
it necessary to draw limits to toleration, absence of evidence of real harm.
disallowing religions that do not accept Mill offered two additional sets of argu-
limitations on their place in civil society (the ments that, although expressly presented
problem with Roman Catholicism, in Locke’s in defense of a maximum of individual lib-
view). In addition, still believing that moral- erty, also support political (state) and citi-
ity depended on belief in a higher being, the zen toleration. Thus Mill argues for the free
state need not tolerate atheists whose beliefs expression of all thought and opinion on
threaten the basis of social order. Thus, utilitarian grounds balancing the benefits
Locke’s primary contribution to liberal tol- of open inquiry and social progress against
eration was his separation between public social stagnation and blind prejudice as a
and private “domains” and an argument for result of the suppression of belief, thought,
limited state power that foreshadowed devel- and discussion. Likewise, Mill argues for
opment of the principle of neutrality. Yet, the toleration of “experiments in living” as
because Locke continued to think of moral- providing educational lessons as to the best
ity as derived from religion, he did not offer ways of enhancing individuality, originality,
an account of how individuals—including and living a fulfilling life.
atheists—were capable of using reason alone Many contemporary debates today over the
to achieve a secular understanding of moral- proper limits of law and public morality take
ity. It was Mill who was to make that contri- their starting points from Mill’s On Liberty.
bution in On Liberty (1859). To be sure, whether or not legal restrictions
Although he rarely uses the terms “tolera- are enacted against expressions or behaviors
tion” or “tolerance,” Mill is often regarded some regard as intolerable (e.g. abortion,
as having offered an extremely insightful and hate speech)—some citizens, and possibly
practical way of relying on public reasons to many, will merely go along with, endure, or
settle disputes. Mill distinguished between put up with what they find seriously objec-
“self-regarding” activity, a realm of action tionable. As noted earlier, it would be a mis-
in which the individual should be free from take to consider passive and unenthusiastic

147
Robert Paul Churchill

fellow travelers to be tolerant. Nevertheless, of liberal toleration are norms that certainly
many important controversies have not been satisfy this principle of justification. However,
resolved, or resolved to the satisfaction of Forst’s justificatory principle is really just the
all: among these are physician-assisted sui- reintroduction of Rawls’s ideal of public rea-
cide, biomedical engineering, the use of mari- son except that, in Forst’s case, the justifica-
juana and other recreational drugs, high-risk tion made through offering and accepting
sports, pornography, and gun ownership. public reasons are for fundamental norms,
The resolve of many to resort only to pub- rather than for policies or other outcomes of
lic reasons and to disagree respectfully about public deliberation. Thus it is not clear that
which side of the debate on each particular Forst’s justification takes us very far toward
issue is morally correct bespeaks the continu- overcoming the problem of liberal partiality
ing relevance of toleration. or circularity.
Among contemporary political philoso-
phers, the justification of toleration looms
large, given its centrality both for a neutral
government and for the civility and civic FURTHER ISSUES FOR RESEARCH
duties of citizens. Yet because toleration
is a fundamental norm of liberalism and is Certainly liberal political theorists, their
justified, in turn, by reference to conditions critics, and philosophers will continue to be
necessary for liberalism, it is far from clear interested in whether and how liberal tolera-
that there can be a noncircular or nontrivial tion can be justified. One possible way for-
justification of liberal toleration. According ward is to proceed as Rawls did in Political
to Kymlicka (1995), for instance, toleration Liberalism (1993) with his “Idea of public
derives from the respect owed to individu- reason revisited” (1997). One might then
als as personally and ethically autonomous maintain that toleration, along with free-
beings with the requisite capacities for dom, equality, and fairness, is a public politi-
choosing and realizing individual concep- cal value that will be secured by the ideal
tions of the good life. However, Kymlicka’s of public reasoning. The difficulty with this
claim appears already to presuppose that the suggestion is that those participating in the
good life must be an autonomously chosen selection process must already be tolerant
way of life. Therefore, Kymlicka’s definition if political reasoning is to proceed purely in
seems to beg the question as nonliberals (e.g. terms of public reasons, that is, in terms of
communitarians) could regard it as reason- reasons that do not draw upon deep, con-
ably questioned. troversial conceptions of human flourishing.
In Forst’s (2012a) view, the problem of Nor does it do to expect toleration to emerge
justification is best approached through from an “overlapping consensus” (Rawls,
what he calls a “discursive principle of justi- 1993), unless toleration is already present
fication.” In Forst’s view “every norm that is within deep and comprehensive accounts of
to be binding for a plurality of persons, espe- human flourishing.
cially norms that are the basis of legal coer- Forst has claimed that toleration is a
cion, must be justifiable with reasons that are “normatively dependent concept” (2012b)
reciprocally acceptable to all affected as free and certainly Forst is correct insofar as the
and equal persons” (Forst, 2012b). Principles principle of liberal toleration does not come

148
LIBERAL TOLERATION

ready made with substantive reasons for Belarus, Somalia, South Sudan, and so on
objection, forbearance, and rejection. In this until it can sustain a liberal democracy?
way, toleration appears to be formal and This is a critical question for many socie-
much like the Categorical Imperative which ties presently rent by tribal, clan, or ethnic,
does not supply us with maxims of action or religious strife. A number of additional
and good intentions, or like the principle of questions also are relevant to the relation-
utility which does not come with substantial ship between a tolerant civil society and a
reasons for preferring one policy or one rule liberal democracy. One is the status of tol-
over others. Yet, while we cannot have rea- eration as an individual virtue (Heyd, 1996,
sons for objection, forbearance, or rejection Newey, 1999, Churchill, 2003, 2007)  and
unless we know what situation or condition the relationship between this virtue and
we face, toleration may have some moral civic virtue. Can toleration be taught as
content after all. In other words, Forst may organizations such as the Southern Poverty
be mistaken in saying that “toleration is not Law Center, which distributes the magazine
a virtue or value” and that it “can only be Teaching Tolerance, presume?
a value if backed by the right normative Perhaps the most significant research
reasons” (2012b). On the contrary, tolera- issue concerns applications of principles
tion may acquire some moral content from of liberal tolerance and their limits, both
natural human responses of reciprocity, as domestically (McKinnon, 2006)  and inter-
well as dispositions to resist free riding and nationally to what Rawls (1999) called
cheating. Studies by cognitive psychologists hierarchical but “decent” peoples. In this
(Haidt, 2012)  and in evolutionary biology connection, Catriona McKinnon (2006)
(Pinker, 2011) indicate that these basic val- has helpfully suggested that the harm prin-
ues are among the “modules” with which ciple be interpreted such that a violation
humans are programmed. This subject of rights constitutes a political harm that
requires further research but points toward ipso facto registers concern about the lim-
a basis in human psychology for moral its of toleration. On this suggestion, the
responses. If this approach proves correct, way forward in hard cases (e.g. defamatory
then it would be clear why reciprocal prac- expressive acts) is to “consider whether the
tices of tolerating the values of those who complaints of parties in opposition to one
have accepted your own would be attrac- another could be made in terms of their
tive, and why cheating by attempting to rights” (McKinnon, 2006, p.  173), where
acquire public benefits by special pleading complaints must be advanced by adverting
(e.g. insisting on the truth of one’s “privi- to public reasons. Although the most fun-
leged” comprehensive account of the good) damental rights, human rights, are far from
would be condemned. fully determinate in scope, the advantage
If there is a biological basis for tolera- of McKinnon’s approach is to bring deci-
tion, there still remains the age-old riddle sions about the limits of toleration into line
of the chicken and the egg. Is a pluralistic with arguments about entitlements and cor-
and tolerant civic society a precondition relative obligations that, though far from
for a liberal democratic regime? If so, then uncontroversial in application, have already
what must be done to create and nurture incorporated the universalizing and equal
a civil society in a place such as Albania, respect ideals of public reason.

149
Robert Paul Churchill

WORKS CITED Horton, J. (1994), “Three (apparent)


paradoxes of toleration,” Synthesis
Almond, G. A. and Verba, S. (1989), The Philosophica, 9: 16–18.
Civic Culture. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. — (1996), “Toleration as a virtue,” in
Bayle, P. (1685/1987), Philosophical D. Heyd (ed.), Toleration: An Elusive
Commentaries, trans. A. G. Tannenbaum Virtue. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
(ed.). New York: Lang. University Press.
Churchill, R. P. (1997), “On the difference Horton, J. and Mendus, S. (eds) (1991),
between non-moral and moral John Locke: ‘A Letter Concerning
conceptions of toleration: the case for Toleration’ in Focus. London:
toleration as a moral virtue,” in M. Routledge.
Ravazi and D. Ambuel (eds), Philosophy, — (eds) (1999), Toleration, Identity, and
Religion, and the Question of Intolerance. Difference. New York: St. Martin’s.
Albany, NY: State University of New Kymlicka, W. (1995), Multicultural
Your Press, pp. 189–211. Citizenship. Oxford: Oxford University
— (2003), “Neutrality, and the virtue of Press.
toleration,” in D. Castiglione and C. Locke, J. (1689/1983), A Letter Concerning
McKinnon (eds), Toleration, Neutrality Toleration, J. H. Tully (ed.). Indianapolis,
and Democracy. Dordrecht and London: IN: Hackett.
Kluwer Academic, pp. 65–76. — (1689/1988), Second Treatise of
— (2007), “Toleration and deep Government, P. Laslett (ed.), Two
reconciliation,” Philosophy in the Treatises of Government. Cambridge:
Contemporary World, 14 (1) (Spring): University of Cambridge Press.
100–113. McKinnon, C. (2006), Toleration: A Critical
Creppell, I. (2003), Toleration and Identity. Introduction. London and New York:
New York: Routledge. Routledge.
Fish, S. (1997), “Mission impossible: setting Mendus, S. (ed.) (1988), Justifying
the just bounds between church and state,” Toleration. Cambridge: Cambridge
Columbia Law Review, 97: 2255–2333. University Press.
Forst, R. (2004), “The limits of toleration,” — (1989), Toleration and the Limits of
Constellations, 11: 312–325. Liberalism. Basingtoke: Macmillan.
— (2012a), The Right to Justification. New Mill, J. S. (1859/1974), On Liberty, G.
York: Columbia University Press. Himmelfarb (ed.). Harmondsworth:
— (2012b), “Toleration,” in E. N. Zalta Penguin.
(ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Montaigne, M. de (1958), The Complete
Philosophy (Summer 2012 edn), http:// Essays of Montaigne, trans. D. M.
plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2012/ Frame. Stanford, CA: Stanford
entries/toleration. University Press.
Haidt, J. (2012), The Righteous Mind. New Newey, G. (1999), Virtue, Reason, and
York: Vintage. Toleration. Edinburgh: Edinburgh
Heyd, D. (ed.) (1996), Toleration: An University Press.
Elusive Virtue. Princeton, NJ: Princeton Pinker, S. (2011), The Better Angels of Our
University Press. Nature. New York: Penguin.

150
LIBERAL TOLERATION

Plato (c. 320 BC/1964), Republic, trans. — (1997), “The idea of public reason
P. Shorey, in E. Hamilton and H. Cairns revisited,” Chicago Law Review, 64:
(eds), The Collected Dialogues of Plato. 765–807.
New York: Pantheon. — (1999), The Law of Peoples. Cambridge:
Putnam, R. D. (ed.) (2004), Democracies in Harvard University Press.
Flux. New York: Oxford University Press. Simmons, A. J. (2007), Political Philosophy.
Ravazi, M. and Ambuel, D. (1997), New York: Oxford University Press.
Philosophy, Religion, and the Question of Williams, B. (1996), “Toleration: an
Intolerance. Albany, NY: State University impossible virtue?” in D. Heyd (ed.),
of New York Press. Toleration: An Elusive Virtue. Princeton,
Rawls, J. (1993), Political Liberalism. New NJ: Princeton University Press,
York: Columbia University Press. pp. 18–27.

151
10
DEMOCRATIC THEORY
Jacquelyn Ann K. Kegley

Democratic theory concerns, among other the people” brings to fore issues of effective
things, the nature of the democratic idea, the participation, enlightened understanding,
distinctive characteristics of the democratic “public reason,” and principles of “reasona-
process including the notion of representa- bleness” and “reciprocity.” This also leads to
tive democracy, and justification of a demo- discussion of current theories of democratic
cratic form of government. Justification of processes and topics such as liberalism, delib-
democracy can take three forms: focus on erative democracy, and more radical theories
consent in social contract theory; focus on including contemporary feminist critiques
beneficial consequences in various forms of and agonistic pluralism. Closely connected
democratic instrumentalism; and emphasis to this discussion is the notion of citizen-
on a notion of public reason. Some politi- ship. Is citizenship a matter of legal status,
cal theorists, such as Dahl (1989), have also political agency, or self-identity, or all three?
taken an empirical approach to justification A traditional theory of citizenship focuses on
arguing that the idea of democracy when citizen as agent while a current liberal model
fully adopted by a people generally produces emphasizes constitutional and legal matters.
the best feasible (workable) political system Key problems of citizenship theory are inclu-
in comparison to feasible nondemocratic sion, pluralism, and expansion. Discussion
alternatives. This chapter addresses these of the question of “political legitimacy” leads
central concerns while also identifying some to an overview of social contract theory, and
key issues needing further research. its concept of justice as well as contempo-
The democratic idea encompasses notions rary criticisms and of theories of democratic
of moral and political autonomy and that of instrumentalism which emphasizes beneficial
intrinsic equal worth, which also involves a consequences of democracy. All these topics
concept of justice or fairness in the distribu- interweave in many ways and encompass as
tion of society’s goods. These notions are well the question: should political theory be
central to democratic processes and to any a normative, theoretical activity or an empiri-
justification of democracy as well as to dis- cal, scientific one. All of this leads also to key
cussions of the democratic “public,” since issues demanding exploration by those who
democracy, in its essential meaning, invests wish to research democratic theory: (1) What
political power in principle in the people, the does “rule by the people” ultimately mean
demos. Developing the idea of “the power of in today’s diverse, and contentious society?

153
Jacquelyn Ann K. Kegley

(2) As globalization and migration of peo- disagreement about authenticity. Some argue
ples increase what should be the parameters for a notion of critical self-reflection, that is,
of citizenship? (3) How does a democratic a rational appraisal of one’s desires, values,
society handle controversy and varieties of and so on which includes some test for inter-
political rhetoric? (4) Are views of democ- nal consistency and comparison to so-called
racy which are dependent on a Kantian view reliable beliefs (Haworth, 1986). Others
of autonomy with its key focus on rational- criticize the heavy emphasis on the rational
ity adequate to deal with socially embedded which ignores affective elements of decision
human beings with variable rationality and making and issues like relationships, and
who may suffer differing degrees of depend- commitment to and care for others (Meyers,
ence and disability in their life process? 2004). Concerning the competency require-
ment, there are issues of social oppression
and inhibiting conditions of personal history
and their impact on authenticity and auton-
EQUALITY AND AUTONOMY omy (Christman, 1991, Mele, 1991)  and
Nussbaum argues that a Kantian account
As stated by one political theorist, one fea- proposes an account of rationality not satis-
ture of democracy is the desire of each and fied by the mentally disabled and maybe not
every citizen to stand to other citizens in even by those temporarily dependent or disa-
a relation of fundamental moral equal- bled (Nussbaum, 2007).
ity, where any notion of significant moral The competency condition for autonomy
differences between persons is decisively leads to the issue of paternalism, that is,
rejected (Fairfield, 2008). A major problem interference with the choice or deliberation
for democratic theory is to give substance to of another person, against their will on the
the notion of “equality.” Political theorists grounds that the person interfered with will
describe equality and its worth in various be better off or protected from harm. It is
ways. The notion of equality also relates to assumed that some persons are not compe-
ideas of autonomy, intrinsic moral worth, tent in their own right to make the choice. A
and justice. Foundational for much demo- widely accepted example is that of children up
cratic theory is the Kantian notion of auton- to a certain age. More controversial examples
omy as a capacity to impose an objective include the mentally challenged, the mentally
moral law on oneself. Autonomy involves the ill, those suffering from severe Alzheimer’s, or
ability to speak for oneself, to choose one’s the withholding of relevant information con-
actions, and to be responsible for one’s acts. cerning a person’s condition by physicians. In
It implies independence in choice and delib- the political arena one encounters examples
eration and thus to be free of manipulation of state paternalism, namely, the belief that
by others. To be autonomous requires two the state “knows best” how persons should
kinds of conditions: (1) competency and (2) act and moves to protect them. Plato argued
authenticity. Authenticity involves aware- for a paternalistic government led by philos-
ness of one’s desires and values, the capac- opher-kings, while government in contempo-
ity to reflect upon them and in practice to rary Singapore seeks to oversee a broad range
endorse them (Frankfurt, 1987, Dworkin, of behaviors of its citizens. Some argue that
1988, Feinberg, 1989). There is considerable the state engages in paternalism when it seeks

154
DEMOCRATIC THEORY

to protect its citizens through legal restric- exercises his or her own judgment about
tions on various elements of personal behav- what kind of life would be successful. Dahl
ior such as drug use, wearing seatbelts in (1989) also argues for the idea of “equal
cars, using helmets while riding motorcycles. intrinsic worth” as central to the notion of
Persons treated in a paternalistic manner are democracy as “rule by the people,” that is,
assumed to be less than fully rational. Kant, rule by a “demos” for it is assumed that the
for example, argued that only rational beings demos consists of members who are consid-
qualify as moral persons and thus he excluded ered equal for the purposes of arriving at
humans who lacked rational capacity as well governmental decisions. Dahl is more specific
as nonhuman beings as moral persons. This arguing that this means that “during a proc-
leads to important questions for a democracy, ess of collective decision-making, the interests
especially one established on principles of jus- of every person who is subject to the decision
tice or rational discourse. Thus John Rawls must (within the limits of feasibility) be accu-
argues (1971) that justice is owed to all moral rately interpreted and made known” (Dahl,
persons, but in Kantian fashion, he sees per- 1989, 87). This notion will be discussed fur-
sons in the “original position” in the social ther in our overview of issues related to the
contract as equal, free, and independent and democratic process. The notion of personal
capable of public reason. Again, Nussbaum responsibility implies certain obligations of
argues that this excludes the mentally disa- citizens to others. Thus, Dworkin cites Kant’s
bled and those even temporarily dependent notion that one cannot act in a way that
or disabled from citizenship and from fair denies the intrinsic importance of any human
distribution (Nussbaum, 2007). One hardly life without insulting your own self-respect.
need to be reminded that throughout human This means, argues Dworkin, that you have
history various human beings have not been to act in a way that your actions do not show
accorded full human and/or moral status contempt for the value of other people’s lives.
whether women, persons of color, persons of This principle is crucial for understanding
various minority groups, and still today, chil- how democracy can deal with diversity and
dren. This impacts on concepts of citizenship pluralism and for an understanding of what
and on questions of effective participation in constitutes a “democratic process.”
the democratic process. Finally reverting back to autonomy and
Dworkin (2006) argues that in American the issue of paternalism, Dahl asserts a strong
democracy most people, in spite of many principle of equality that assumes that ordi-
great and evident differences, share two very nary people are in general qualified to govern
basic principles that constitute the notion of themselves. This returns us to the notion of
“human dignity”: the “principle of intrinsic competence and to equal consideration of
value” and the “principle of personal respon- interests and both are encompassed in what
sibility.” The first principle asserts that each Dahl calls the “presumption of personal
human life has a special kind of objective autonomy,” namely, the view that “no one is
value, a potentiality that demands to be real- likely to be more qualified than you to be a
ized. The second principle holds that each better judge of your own good or interest to
person has a special responsibility to realize act to bring it about” (Dahl, 1989, 99). You,
the success of his/her own life, a responsibil- of course, may choose to delegate choices to
ity that includes the notion that each person others whom you deem qualified to decide

155
Jacquelyn Ann K. Kegley

the most appropriate means to fulfill your ideal, but the real question is a question of
personal interests. This presumption of per- inclusion: Does the demos include all adults
sonal autonomy has significant implications (competent persons?) Are all members of the
for democratic theory. First, paternalism demos autonomous and capable of fully par-
needs to be attacked head on. In the absence ticipating in a rational conversation while
of compelling evidence to the contrary, eve- remaining tolerant of all participants and
ryone should be assumed to be the best judge allowing all voices to be heard?
of his or her own good or interests; the bur- Political theorists generally agree that
den of proof is always placed on those who one of the important criteria for a demo-
propose to replace personal autonomy by cratic process is effective participation by
paternalism. It should be clear that anyone those engaged in the democratic decision-
whose personal autonomy is permanently making process. Dahl describes effective
replaced by paternalistic authority would be participation in terms of two aspects of a
maintained in a perpetual state of childhood binding decision-making process: setting
and dependence and their intrinsic worth as the agenda and deciding the outcome. In
human person denied. Thus, it also argues terms of agenda setting, this means that all
that every adult member of groups claiming citizens ought to have adequate and equal
to be democratic should be considered suf- opportunity for placing questions on the
ficiently well-qualified to participate in mak- agenda. Decision making can be delegated
ing binding collective decisions that affect his but ultimately it needs to be the demos,
or her good or interests, that is, they should the people, who set the agenda. However,
be considered full citizens of the demos. This in the face of pluralism, diversity, and disa-
brings us to a discussion of democratic proc- greements, control of the agenda may not
ess and the notion of citizenship. be in actuality a possibility for many citi-
zens in contemporary democracies. In fact,
the mechanics of politics, certainly in the
United States where power distribution is
A THEORY OF THE DEMOCRATIC often dramatically unequal, demonstrates
PROCESS: WHO IS A CITIZEN? that control of agendas more frequently
reflects particular interests and the control
In developing a theory of the democratic of various advocacy groups and that, in
process, we will first do so on an ideal level, fact, particular elites exercise almost con-
that is, we will set out the ideal for such a tinual influences over the agendas and the
process, taking for granted that a perfect decision-making processes. These particu-
democratic process and a perfect democratic lar elites include entrenched bureaucrats, a
government may not have or ever will exist in small selection of partisan elites, an unrep-
actuality. Fairfield (2008) argues that democ- resentative selection of appointed judges,
racy “dreams of being an ideal deliberation and a plutocratic hierarchy of corporate
community,” one that is radically egalitarian capitalism. Democracy falters when politi-
and that engages in a fully rational conver- cal agendas for deliberation are set by the
sation in which all participate as respected power elite (Scott, 1998).
equals, where differences are acknowledged The second component of decision making
and all voices brought to the table. This is the is the decisive stage where voting produces

156
DEMOCRATIC THEORY

an outcome. Ideally, again, in a truly demo- of a legal status and in terms of certain civil,
cratic process each citizen should have an political, and social rights which a citizen
equal opportunity to express their choice can claim and for which they can seek pro-
and that choice should be counted as equal in tection. Often this can be claimed by right
weight to the choice expressed by any other of birth. Second, a citizen is a political agent
citizen (Dahl, 1989). This stated principle and the question of participation in a soci-
does not require a particular method of vot- ety’s political institutions comes to the fore-
ing or election. Democratic theory provides ground. Third, citizenship has historically
no definitive answer to the question of dem- and even today been considered a matter of
ocratic decision-making processes. Is major- identity, both psychological and sociological,
ity rule necessary or problematic? Dworkin, conveying a sense of belonging and seeming
for example, does not believe majority rule to demand a form of loyalty. There have been
is a particularly sound method of reaching two traditional models of citizenship. The
truth or securing equality of political power first, called the “republican model,” is derived
(Dworkin, 2006). In fact, Schumpeter argues from the experiences of Athenian democracy,
that democracy is a method of generat- Republican Rome, the Italian city-states, and
ing political decisions by granting power to various workers councils. The key principle
elites by electoral means (Schumpeter, 1976). is civic self-rule. This model stresses politi-
Majority decision making and minority par- cal agency and active participation in delib-
ticipation in democratic processes continue eration and decision making. The model has
to be major issues for democratic theory. been labeled impractical for today’s world of
Another key decision-making element social complexity and increasing diversity.
concerns the characteristics of the decider, The argument is that today’s heterogeneity
particularly of competency and autonomy of does not allow the kind of “moral unity” and
citizens. Dahl (1989) suggests the notion of “mutual trust” that existed in the Greek or
“enlightened understanding,” which entails Italian city-states (Walzer, 1989).
that citizens are capable of comprehending The “Liberal model” stresses citizenship as
the issues and are afforded adequate and a legal status and as membership in a com-
equal opportunities to understand means munity of shared or common law. This model
and ends for achieving their interests and for emphasizes “negative freedom”; the role of
grasping expected consequences of proposed government is to protect individual freedoms
policies and decisions for all. This requires, at from interference from other individuals or
minimum, that there be in a democracy such authorities. This allows citizens to exercise
rights as freedom of the press and freedom of their freedoms primarily in the world of
assembly. Adequate and relevant information private associations and attachments rather
and discussion opportunities are crucial. than in the political domain. Some political
Another key question, then, for democratic theorists have argued that such a view of
theory is what constitutes a people and who citizenship fosters passivity because ordinary
is a citizen? A citizen is generally defined as a citizens see political activity as insignificant.
member of a political community who enjoys This seems to be the case today in the United
the rights and assumes the duties of member- States. Further, such passivity can be danger-
ship. However, citizenship can have three dis- ous for maintaining legal status for if citizens
tinct dimensions. First, it can be seen in terms grow inattentive, the legal and governmental

157
Jacquelyn Ann K. Kegley

security provided by the authorities may exclusion for others and thus full equality
dwindle. This security must be continually and integration into the political structure
secured, sometimes against these authori- have not occurred for all citizens. Political
ties, and thus the passive enjoyment of citi- theorists such as Young (1989, 2000) argue
zenship requires that at least intermittently that the “people” must be seen as a “hetero-
citizens engage in political and legal action geneous public.” Citizens as political partici-
(see Constant, 1819). Mill, Constant, and pants start from their situated positions and
other political theorists have argued that the attempt to construct a dialogue across dif-
regular exercise of political liberty is the best ferences. This, however, requires citizens to
means of moral improvement, which also have certain characteristics. Young speaks of
opens the minds of the public to the public participants who are “public spirited,” who
interest and to the importance of defend- are open to the claims of others, and who are
ing their freedoms (Constant, 1819, Mill, not single-mindedly self-interested.
1861). This is an instrumentalist defense of This raises the question: what “virtues”
democracy. are required of citizens in a pluralist lib-
A more sustained attack on the liberal view eral democracy? There are, of course, dif-
comes from feminist political theorists. This ferent answers (Macedo, 1990, Galston,
model gives primacy to the private sphere 1991, Callan, 1997). One virtue advocated
and to the notion of noninterference in the by those from the liberal tradition is “pub-
pursuit of particular interests. However, fem- lic reasonableness.” This seems to be the
inists contend that separating the private and ability to listen to others while formulating
public political sphere leads to the definition a position in a way that is sensitive to and
of the private domain as one of necessity and respectful of different experiences and iden-
inequality which impacts on the citizen sta- tities of fellow citizens. John Rawls speaks
tus of women. Further, they argue that the of “reasoned consensus” among citizens;
private and public spheres are intimately this involves agreement on general reasons
connected as is exemplified by the fact that but can allow disagreement about interpre-
there are laws and policies that structure the tations (Rawls, 1993). Feminists, of course,
personal and private such as laws about rape oppose a rational consensus notion because
and abortion, childcare, and the allocation it tends to stifle diverse voices as well as to
of welfare benefits. Further, some personal exclude some persons.
problems have wider significance that can To speak of citizen virtues, of course,
only be solved collectively through political requires education in democratic values
action (Pateman, 1989). as John Dewey recognized in his book,
At issue here is the challenge of inter- Democracy and Education (1916). Indeed,
nal diversity which demands that a citizen many political theorists have given attention
appears as situated in a social world char- to the role of education in securing democracy
acterized by differences of gender, class, lan- as well as to the kind of education required
guage, race, ethnicity, and culture. Feminists (Gutmann, 1999, Brighthouse, 2006). The
and others argue that a universal notion of questions in this area are many: Is a common
citizen defined in terms of legal status and curriculum required and what is or should be
blind to various social differences has led to the common knowledge and values for all cit-
the extension of rights to some groups but izens? Should it be a curriculum that teaches

158
DEMOCRATIC THEORY

respect for difference while also providing information possessed by a public as well as
the necessary skills for democratic discussion the facts of diversity, disagreement, and often
across differences? (Leydet, 2011). The ques- apathy, how should democratic deliberation
tion of “democratic education” also raises the be characterized? Again we find a range of
question of paternalism in cases of children positions on this question.
whose parents or culture is not democratic. One position on this issue is “deliberative
democracy.” Benhabib provides a clear state-
ment of this position when she states that a
legitimate collective decision-making process
A THEORY OF THE DEMOCRATIC in a polity is present when the institutions of
PROCESS: THEORIES OF DEMOCRATIC this polity are so arranged that what is con-
DELIBERATION sidered in the “common interest of all results
from processes of collective deliberation
It seems clear that a particular kind of delib- conducted rationally and fairly among free
erative process is required for any society or and equal individuals” (Benhabib, 1996, 69).
organization to be properly called “demo- Rawls sees citizens as reasonable deliberators
cratic.” Democracy, in theory, puts faith in the who are able to appeal to shared standards
power and wisdom of the people. Rousseau of public reason. This view is related to the
(1993), for example, speaks of the “general notion of citizenship as a legal status for the
will.” Green and Blanshard argued that the requisite standards is embodied in institu-
general will is the foundation of democracy tions and institutional documents. Rawls
(Blanshard, 1961, Green, 1986, Fairfield, declares: “Our exercise of political power
2008). However, the concept of the “general is fully proper only when it is exercised in
will” is open to many interpretations and not accordance with a constitution, the essentials
free from controversy. Joseph Schumpeter, of which all citizens as free and equal may be
for example, argues that the general will as reasonably expected to endorse in the light
it actually functions in a democratic order of principles and ideals acceptable to their
represents an abstraction and that the gen- common human reason” (Rawls, 1993, 137,
eral will cannot be the will of any identifiable Fairfield, 2008). There are three basic ele-
set of people (Schumpeter, 1976, Fairfield, ments of deliberative democracy as set out by
2008). Dewey and Lippmann engaged in Rawls. First, there is “public reason,” which is
an extensive debate about the nature of the a form of rationality that limits reasons that
“democratic public” in the 1920s (Lippmann, citizens may give in supporting their public
1925, Dewey, 1927). Lippmann argued that opinion. These reasons must be consistent
there was no such entity while Dewey sought with seeing other citizens as equal. Here, of
to describe the characteristics needed of the course, we have the Kantian understanding
public if democracy as a way of life and sys- of how respecting others reflects back on
tem was to survive. The difficulty for demo- one’s own self-respect. Secondly, of course,
cratic theory is that to speak of the public as the framework of constitutional democratic
an “agent” seems somewhat spurious because institutions that is the setting for democratic
agency presupposes consciousness, inten- deliberative processes (Fairfield, 2008).
tionality, and volition at a minimum. Given Finally, there is embedded in the notion of
the various degrees of participation and “public reason” the idea that citizens will

159
Jacquelyn Ann K. Kegley

know and desire to follow public reason and ideal of discursive democracy relies heavily
seek to realize its ideal in their political con- on the cognitive dimension of the self; there
duct (Rawls, 1999b, 578, Fairfield, 2008). is a cognitive demand embedded in speech.
Guttmann and Thompson stress the Little attention is given to the affective and
“reason-giving” requirement of delibera- other dimensions of self and deliberation in
tive democracy, namely, that leaders should the public sphere seems immune to the forces
give reasons for their decisions and should of chaos, diversity, and conflict present in the
respond to reasons citizens give in return. real world of human life.
These reasons also ought to appeal to prin- Two schools of criticism thus emerge. The
ciples such as reciprocity, publicity, account- communitarians focus on the political subject
ability, and equality. Although followers of as socially embedded. Sandel, for example,
the deliberative democracy camp disagree rejects any notion of a Kantian disembod-
about the values, status, aims, and scope ied subject and argues for the notion of a
of deliberation, they all seem to agree that “wider subject,” a subject marked by com-
deliberative politics involves “working munity, a common vocabulary of discourse,
together in a more cooperative “first-person and a background of implicit practices and
plural spirit” (Gutmann and Thompson, understandings (Sandel, 1982). MacIntyre
2004, 7). Deliberative democrats assume and Taylor argue that the self is embedded
that arguments are made in ways everyone in a social context (MacInytre, 1984, Taylor,
can respect; and that such mutually respect- 1985). Taylor asserts “Man is a social ani-
ful deliberation will often lead to discovery mal, indeed a political animal, because he is
of areas of agreement. Two emphases are not self-sufficient alone, and in an important
present in deliberative democracy: one on sense is not self-sufficient outside the polis”
procedure, on the process of deliberation, (Taylor, 1985, 1290). For communitarians,
and an emphasis on cognitive validity. the emphasis in democratic deliberation is
These aspects are best captured by on community values; participants in the
Habermas (1962, 1971, 1975, 1987, 1990, dialogue focus on their social obligations and
1996, 1998), who understands democracy as thus a sense of loyalty to a community takes
an institutional order and whose legitimacy precedence over individualistic, egoistic cal-
depends on collective will-formation through culations, and strategic rationality. However,
discourse. He develops a theory of commu- communitarian views are criticized because
nicative reason that locates rationality in of their overemphasis on society, which fails
structures of interpersonal linguistic commu- to honor a proper balance between individu-
nication. He argues that all speech acts have alism and community.
an inherent telos, namely, the goal of mutual Feminist critiques of contemporary moral
understanding and that human beings possess and political theory have focused on two
the communicative competence to bring about contemporary views of the self—the Kantian
such understanding. Habermas imagines and “homo economicus.” The Kantian
discourse occurring in the “public sphere,” ethical subject uses abstract pure reason to
an arena in which individuals participate in transcend cultural norms and to discover
discussions about matters of common con- absolute moral truth whereas the homo eco-
cern. He focuses on consensus and views the nomicus uses instrumental reason to rank
lack of consensus as a “failure.” Habermas’s desires in a coherent order and to figure out

160
DEMOCRATIC THEORY

how to maximize desire satisfaction. Both seeking to show how we might accept and
these views isolate the individual from per- channel this positively. The agonists argue
sonal relationships and larger social forces. that deliberative democracy theorists ignore
Feminists argue that this minimizes the per- the inequalities that set agenda priorities
sonal and moral import of circumstances and constrain the alternatives that political
about which one has little or no choice and actors may consider in their deliberations.
interpersonal relationships. Feminist theorists Common discourse is itself a complex prod-
believe political theories based on a Kantian uct of structural inequality; it is hegemonic
or economic view of the self are inadequate discourse and often leads to false or distorted
because they eclipse family, friendship, pas- agreement. Young argues that the theory and
sionate love, and community, and downplay practice of deliberative democracy have no
the difficult of resolving conflicts that arise tools for raising the possibility that delib-
between these commitments and personal erations may be closed and distorted in this
values and aspirations. They also ignore way—it lacks a theory of ideology as well as
the multiple, sometimes fractious sources of an account of the genealogy of discourses
social identity constituted by one’s gender, and their manner of helping to constitute
sexual orientation, race, class, ethnicity, and the way individuals see themselves and their
so forth. Their homogenized rational subject social world (Young, 2001). In this context,
is not prey to ambivalence, anxiety, obses- Fairfield argues that what is needed is an ade-
sion, prejudice, hatred, or violence and thus quate phenomenology of democratic speech
they overestimate the immunity of the self to which does not oversanitize the language of
noxious influences, and the reliability of rea- politics (Fairfield, 2008, 53–78).
son as a corrective to distorted moral judg- Agonistic feminism is represented in
ment. A better account of self for moral and the works of Honing, Mouffe, and Ziarek
political theory is one understood as socially (Honing, 1992, 1993, 2001, Mouffe, 1992,
situated and murkily heterogeneous (Meyers, 1993, 2005, Ziarek, 2001). Agonistic views
1989, Benhabib, 1992, Jaggar, 1998). see the nature of politics as inherently conflict-
For example, Young is skeptical that dem- ual, with battles over power and hegemony
ocratic deliberative processes could lead to being the central tasks of democratic struggle.
outcomes that would be acceptable to all; Advocates of agnostic politics believe that the
deliberation as defined by Habermas is too “consensus” sought by both liberalism and
reason-based, and thus excludes forms of deliberative democrats leads to oppression or
communication that women and other mar- injustice by silencing new struggles. It often
ginalized people tend to use, such as greet- leads to paternalism which etymologically
ing, rhetoric, and storytelling (Young, 1990). has a male cast, and women and minority
Young’s approach is similar to that of the groups have often been characterized as less
group labeled as “agonists” or “agonistic “rational.” Mouffe argues that “every con-
pluralists.” Agonism is a political theory that sensus exists as a temporary result of a provi-
emphasizes the potentially positive aspects of sional hegemony, as a stabilization of power,
certain (but not all) forms of political con- and that it always entails some form of
flict, namely, in the ability to enforce or reen- exclusion” (Mouffe, 2000). Agonists seek to
force democratic inclusion. This view accepts re­orient political theory to the question: How
a permanent place for such conflict, while should we deal with irreducible difference?

161
Jacquelyn Ann K. Kegley

Adequate political theory should conceptual- fairness.” The “original position” of the con-
ize democracy so as to optimize the opportu- tract is designed to be a fair and impartial
nity for people to express their disagreements point of view that is to be adopted in reason-
and should recognize that conflict may not ing about fundamental principles of justice.
be eliminated even given sufficient time for It includes a “veil of ignorance”; the parties
deliberation. The agonists argue that politics are deprived of all knowledge of their per-
crafted in the knowledge of the inevitability sonal characteristics and social and historical
of conflicts is paradoxically freer than one circumstances. There is an “overlapping con-
which seeks to shy away from this fact. sensus,” a term referring to how supporters
of different comprehensive normative doc-
trines (those of religion, political ideology, or
morality)—that entail apparently inconsist-
JUSTIFICATION OF THE DEMOCRATIC ent conceptions of justice—can agree on par-
WAY OF GOVERNANCE ticular principles of justice that underwrite a
political community’s basic social institutions.
Political legitimacy is about explaining why The overlapping consensus depends, in effect,
the use of political power by a particular body on there being a morally significant core of
is permissible and why there is a moral duty commitments common to each of the main
to obey its commands (Rawls, 1993). A typi- comprehensive doctrines in the community.
cal way of approaching this question is via The emphasis is on a notion of “public rea-
consent: what social arrangements can we all son,” in that it identifies central core commit-
accept as free persons who have no authority ments that all, despite many disagreements,
over one another? The mechanism is a hypo- could in principle accept.
thetical agreement, a social contract, a model Some political theorists see the liberal-
of the reasoning of citizens. It embodies the ist and deliberative democracy position as
reasons a person would have for recognizing purely procedural, for the deliberative situ-
and accepting a constraint that is independ- ation is set up so that whatever principles
ent of his desires. The contract can be seen are generated are by the fact of the genera-
either in a prudential manner or in an ideal- tion: fair. Political legitimacy is created by
ized moral manner. The Hobbesian contract appropriately constrained decision-making
is prudential, based on instrumental, practical procedures (Fabienne, 2008). As noted ear-
rationality. The aim of the contract shows that lier, much of the criticisms against Rawls and
agreement is an effective way to further one’s liberalism are against this rationalized, ideal-
nonmoral aims and interests. Thus Hobbes ized, procedural notion of democracy. Again,
would argue that one chooses between a Nussbaum focuses on the notion that the
form of government and life under anarchy. individuals in the original position are equal,
The Kantian contract is focused on a moral free, and independent; they are not socially
or political principle that meets certain basic embedded but idealized rational deciders;
moral demands such as treating all as free they are not, therefore, subject to the com-
and equal and not subjecting any person to plexities of human emotions, social commit-
the will or judgment of another (D’Agostino ments, and dependencies that occur not just
et  al., 2012). In his social contract theory, for the disabled but for all persons in their
Rawls emphasizes the principle of justice “as lifespan.

162
DEMOCRATIC THEORY

In addition to social contract theories, conflict may be inevitable. A burning ques-


there are also instrumentalist defenses of tion for many nations today is the role of
democracy. Mill and others, such as Sen, religion in the public sphere. (2) As globali-
Habermas, and Dewey, argued that the dem- zation and migrations of peoples increases
ocratic method is strategically and epistemo- what should be the parameters of citizen-
logically better and that it improves the moral ship? Will citizenship be expanded to the
character of the participants (Mill, 1861). global level? Can democracy exist at the glo-
Strategically, democracy forces decision- bal level? Central questions that emerge are:
makers to take into account the interests, will new forms of citizenship develop such
rights, and opinions of most people in society as multicultural citizenship or post national
(Sen, 1999). Epistemologically, it is generally citizenship? (Kymlicka, 1995). Will the con-
more reliable in helping participants dis- cept of nationhood be reconstructed? (Miller,
cover right decisions because it emphasizes 1995). (3) How does a democratic society
discussion and boarder bases of information. handle controversy and varieties of political
Finally, Mill, Dewey, and Habermas argued rhetoric? The issue of compulsion and per-
that democracy tends to enhance autonomy, suasion in democratic processes is a crucial
rationality, and even the morality of the par- one (Kegley and Skowronski, 2013). Should
ticipants. Another somewhat instrumentalist we be developing a phenomenology of politi-
defense of democracy is the observations of cal rhetoric as well as of political protest? (4)
Jaspers that democratic institutions are able Are views of democracy which are dependent
to manage change and transformation in on a Kantian view of autonomy with its key
myriad ways (Jasper, 1953). Democracy is focus on rationality adequate to deal with
also a method for managing disagreements socially embedded human beings with vari-
through peaceful means (Fairfield, 2008, able rationality and who may suffer differ-
xiv). It should be clear by now that most the- ing degrees of dependence and disability in
orizing about democracy is idealized and on their life process? How is democratic theory
the strictly theoretical level. However, there to handle the growing social, economic, and
are some political theorists who give empiri- other inequalities present today? Those inter-
cal arguments for democracy. Thus Dahl ested in democratic political theory research
undertakes a comparison of democracies to have much fertile ground to plow.
other types of governments, and argues that
democracies tend to produce the best politi-
cal systems taken all around (Dahl, 1989).
His criteria of judging the various forms of WORKS CITED
government include producing maximum
flexible freedom, promoting human develop- Benhabib, S. (1992), Situating the Self:
ment, protecting personal interests, and the Gender, Community and Postmodernism
ability for self-correction. in Contemporary Ethics. New York:
Major questions and issues remain for Routledge.
future democratic theory research. (1) What — (1996), “Toward a Deliberative Model of
does “rule by the people” ultimately mean Democratic Legitimacy,” in S. Benhabib
in today’s diverse and contentious soci- (ed.), Democracy and Difference.
ety? Consensus may not be achievable and Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

163
Jacquelyn Ann K. Kegley

Blanshard, B. (1961), Reason and Goodness. Frankfurt, H. (1987), “Freedom of Will and
London: Allen & Unwin. the Concept of a Person,” in H. Frankfurt
Brighthouse, H. (2006), On Education. (ed.), The Importance of What We Care
London & New York: Routledge. About: Philosophical Essays. Cambridge:
Callan, E. (1997), Creating Citizens. New Cambridge University Press.
York: Oxford University Press. Galston, W. (1991), Liberal Virtues,
Christman, J. (1991), Autonomy and Citizenship Virtues and Community
Personal History. Canadian Journal of in Liberal Constitutionalism. Oxford:
Philosophy, 21 (1): 1–24. Clarendon Press.
Constant, B. (1819), “The Liberty of Green, T. H. (1986), Lectures on the Principles
Ancients Compared to Moderns,” trans. of Political Obligation and Other Writings,
A. Phillips (ed.), The Political Writings of P. Harris and J. Morrow (eds). Cambridge:
Benjamin Constant. New York: Oxford Cambridge University Press.
University Press. Gutmann, A. (1999), Democracy and
D’Agostino, F., Gaus, G., and Thrasher, Education. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
T. (2012), “Contemporary Approaches University Press.
to the Social Contract,” The Stanford Gutmann, A. and Thompson, D. (2004),
Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://plato. Why Deliberative Democracy? Princeton,
stanford.edu/archives/win2012/entries/ NJ: Princeton University Press.
contractarianism-contemporary. Habermas, J. (1962), The Structural
Dahl, R. (1989), Democracy and Its Critics. Transformation of the Public Sphere: An
New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Inquiry into a Category of Bourgeois
Dewey, J. (1916), Democracy and Society, trans. T. Burger. Cambridge, MA:
Education: An Introduction to the The MIT Press.
Philosophy of Education. New York: — (1971), Knowledge and Human Interests,
Macmillan. trans. J. Shapiro. Boston, MA: Beacon
— (1927), The Public and Its Problems. Press.
New York: Holt Publishers. — (1975), Legitimation Crisis, trans.
Dworkin, G. (1988), The Theory and T. McCarthy. Boston, MA: Beacon Press.
Practice of Autonomy. New York: — (1987), The Theory of Communicative
Cambridge University Press. Action, trans. T. McCarthy. Boston, MA:
Dworkin, R. (2006), Is Democracy Possible Bacon Press.
Here? Princeton, NJ: Princeton University — (1990), Moral Consciousness and
Press. Communicative Action, trans. C.
Fabienne, P. (2008), Democratic Legitimacy. Lenhardt and S. W. Nicholson.
New York: Routledge. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Fairfield, P. (2008), Why Democracy? — (1996), Between Facts and Norms:
Albany, NY: SUNY Press. Contributions to a Discourse Theory
Feinberg, J. (1989), “Autonomy,” in J. of Law and Democracy, trans. W. Rehg
Christman (ed.), The Inner Citadel: (trans.). Cambridge: Polity Press.
Essays on Individual Autonomy. New — (1998), The Inclusion of the Other.
York: Oxford University Press. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

164
DEMOCRATIC THEORY

Haworth, L. (1986), Autonomy: An Essay Miller, D. (1995), Nationality. New York:


in Philosophical Psychology and Ethics. Clarendon Press.
New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Mouffe, C. (1992), Dimensions of Radical
Honing, B. (1993), Political Theory and Democracy: Pluralism, Citizenship,
the Displacement of Politics. Ithaca, NY: Community. London; New York: Verso.
Cornell University Press. — (1993), The Return of the Political.
— (2001), Democracy and the Foreigner. London; New York: Verso.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. — (2000), The Democratic Paradox. New
Jaggar, A. (1988), Feminist Politics and York: Verso.
Human Nature. Lanham, MD: Rowman — (2005), On the Political, Thinking in
& Littlefield. Action. Abingdon; New York: Routledge.
Jasper, K. (1953), The Origin and Goal of Nussbaum, M. (2007), The Clash Within:
History, trans. M. Bullock. New Haven, Democracy, Religious Violence, and
CT: Yale University Press. India’s Future. Cambridge, MA: Belknap
Kegley, J. and P. Skowronski (2013), Press of Harvard University Press.
Persuasion and Compulsion in Pateman, C. (1989), The Disorder of
Democracy. New York: Lexington Press. Women: Democracy, Feminism, and
Kymlicka, W. (1995), Multicultural Political Theory. Stanford, CA: Stanford
Citizenship. New York: Oxford University Press.
University Press. Rawls, J. (1971), A Theory of Justice.
Leydet, D. (2011), “Citizenship,” The Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Press.
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/ — (1993), Political Liberalism, 2nd edn.
fall2011/entries/citizenship/. New York: Columbia University.
Lippmann, W. (1925), The Phantom Public. — (1999b), “The Idea of Public Reason
New York: Transactions Publishers. Revisited,” in S. Freeman (ed.), The
Macedo, S. (1990), Goods, Virtues & Collected Papers of John Rawls.
Diversity in the Liberal State. Cambridge: Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Cambridge University Press. Press.
MacIntyre, A. (1984), After Virtue. Notre Rousseau, J. J. (1993), The Social Contract,
Dame, IN: Indiana University Press. trans. G. D. H. Cole. New York: Knopf.
Mele, A. (1991), “History and Personal Sandel, M. (1982), Liberalism and the
Autonomy,” Canadian Journal of Limits of Justice. Cambridge: Cambridge
Philosophy, 23 (1): 271–280. University Press.
Meyers, D. (1989), Self, Society, and Personal Schumpeter, J. (1976), Capitalism, Socialism,
Choice. New York: Columbia University and Democracy. London: Allen & Unwin.
— (2004), Being Yourself: Essays on Scott, J. (1998), Seeing Like a State: How
Identity, Autonomy and Social Life. Certain Schemes to Improve the Human
Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield. Conditions Have Failed. New Haven, CT:
Mill, J. S. (1861, 1958), Considerations on Yale University Press.
Representative Government. Indianapolis, Sen, A. (1999), Development as Freedom.
IN: Bobbs-Merrill Press. New York: Knopf.

165
Jacquelyn Ann K. Kegley

Taylor, C. (1985), Philosophy and the — (1990), Justice and the Politics of
Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers 2. Difference. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. University Press.
Walzer, M. (1989), “Citizenship,” in — (2000), Inclusion and Democracy. New
T. Bell, J. Farr, and R. Hansen (eds), York: Oxford University Press.
Political Innovation and Conceptual — (2001), “Activist Challenges to
Change. Cambridge: Cambridge Deliberative Democracy,” Political
University Press. Theory, 29 (5) (October): 670–690.
Young, I. (1989), “Polity and Group Ziarek, E. (2001), An Ethics of Dissensus:
Difference: A Critique of the Ideal of Postmodernity, Feminism, and the Politics
Universalist Citizenship,” Ethics, 99: of Radical Democracy. Stanford, CA:
250–274. Stanford University Press.

166
11
FEMINISM AND GENDER1
Anca Gheaus

INTRODUCTION freedom. Yet, they tend to be underrepre-


sented in politics—particularly at the top
Gender makes a difference to many central levels—in many professions that are consid-
questions in political philosophy: the way ered traditionally male and from the higher
we understand the demands of distribu- end positions of most professions. They also
tive and relational justice, the ideal form of tend to be more affected by poverty than
democracy, the division between the private men are and receive less pay; they are the
and the public domains, and the normative victims of most rapes and domestic violence
issues raised by the acceleration of globaliza- and do most of the housework and childrear-
tion. We live in societies that are structured by ing—both in their homes and in commodi-
gender in various ways: most obviously, we fied form. Finally, their bodies are objectified
inherit a tradition of differential treatment of through pornography and commodified
women and men, which bestowed numerous through prostitution to a much larger extent
political, economic, and social privileges on than men’s. Therefore, women appear to
the latter. The legal discrimination of women have a lesser share than men in political and
has been the main object of so-called first social power, economic assets, and social rec-
wave feminism. Pioneered by philosophers ognition. The core belief of feminism is that
such as Wollstonecraft and Mill, feminists of people should not suffer disadvantage by
the first wave have insisted on the illegitimacy dint of belonging to a particular gender, and
of excluding women from political and eco- therefore the earlier facts represent core con-
nomic life and legally confining them to the cerns for feminist political philosophy.
private sphere of the family (or monastery). Indeed, current feminist political philoso-
In many countries, women are still subject to phy offers a thorough analysis of all these
legal discrimination, and therefore the aims issues and their ramifications. According to
of first-wave feminism continue to be highly Jaggar’s (1983) helpful classification, feminist
relevant in some parts of the world. thinking comes in several varieties—liberal,
Women who live in liberal democracies socialist, and radical—reflecting the diversity
today have the same legal standing as men: of feminist authors’ value and methodological
for instance, they enjoy the same legal rights commitments. More recently added broad cat-
as men with respect to voting, standing for egories include ecofeminism and postcolonial
election, holding property and occupational feminism. Not all normative feminist thinking

167
Anca Gheaus

is properly understood as a contribution to responsibilities of meeting other people’s


political theory which, traditionally, focuses needs: they are often the main caregivers
on questions concerning the legitimate limits for children, ill and disabled individuals,
and uses of state power. Because it is restricted and the frail elderly. They are also often
to political philosophy, this chapter mainly expected to take responsibility for main-
draws on work belonging to liberal and social- taining good relationships between friends,
ist feminism. By contrast, the traditions of rad- peers, and colleagues. All these are aspects
ical feminism, ecofeminism, and postcolonial of the gendered division of labor which, as
feminism are more obviously relevant to ethics I will show in the following sections, is the
and social philosophy, or else they contain sug- source of much political inequality between
gestions for political changes that are too radi- women and men (Okin, 1989a). Unlike other
cal to assess within the framework of liberal, ­inequalities—resulting, for instance, from
egalitarian, and democratic states. violence or outward discrimination—liberal
This chapter is also limited to a presenta- political philosophy has difficulties identi-
tion of the contribution made by feminism to fying the normative status of inequalities
political philosophy at the most general level. flowing from the gendered division of labor,
It discusses the two main issues in contempo- because the individual choices that gener-
rary political philosophy: justice—comprising ate them are typically uncoerced. One of the
theories of fair distributions and of equal rela- main contributions of feminist philosophy
tionships between citizens—and democratic over the past 30  years was to uncover the
theory. Theories of justice and democratic moral and political importance of caregiving.
theory are the two main areas of political phi- The general conclusion of this body of work
losophy: the first is about substantial require- is that the practical and emotional labor done
ments of justice, and the second is about the by women as caregivers should be acknowl-
procedures through which legitimate politi- edged as essential to social cooperation and
cal decisions can be reached. Gender plays a rewarded adequately.
role in both, and, in particular, the gendered First, on the moral importance of caring.
division of labor raises difficulties for main- Most generally, care is defined as the activity
stream theories in both areas. The last section of meeting another person’s needs, whether
outlines new developments in feminist theory: material or emotional (Tronto, 1993). The
explorations of the phenomena of implicit majority of care ethicists follow Noddings
bias, and stereotype threat and thinking about (1982) in the belief that, to qualify as care,
epistemic injustice in the context of gender; I the activity in question must be hands-on
explain their potential import for theories of (rather than, say, meeting someone’s needs
justice and democratic theories. indirectly, by paying someone else to provide
necessary services). Others further restrict
the definition to needs that cannot possibly
be met by the person in need herself (Bubeck,
RELATIONAL IDENTITIES AND THE 1995). The moral value of meeting needs
ETHICS OF CARE can be accounted for by major ethical tradi-
tions, yet direct reference to needs does not
Both in their professional and in their pri- figure in the most influential test of assess-
vate lives, women tend to carry most of the ing individual moral development, devised

168
FEMINISM AND GENDER

by the psychologist Kohlberg (1981). In the childrearing. Ruddick (1989) argued that
early-mid-1980s, the psychologist Gilligan people who are primarily responsible for the
made two important observations: first, that hands-on tasks of childrearing—and whom
Kohlberg’s scale of moral development— she calls “mothers” whether they are female
according to which reaching moral maturity or male—confront three specific tasks: the
depends on individuals’ ability to outgrow physical preservation of the children; their
particular attachments to other people and physical, emotional, and intellectual devel-
to reason in terms of rights and duties—was opment; and their socialization into accept-
developed using only male subjects. Second, able members of their group. To accomplish
that women typically engaged in moral rea- these tasks successfully, mothers develop,
soning in which others’ needs and relation- ideally, a number of distinct virtues and the
ships between people played a central role. ability to address daily dilemmas involving
The female, but not male, subjects of this the negotiation of conflicting needs as well as
research systematically tended to describe conflicts between the different tasks of chil-
their identities as relational (Giligan, 1982, drearing. She thought that the moral experi-
1995). Gilligan did not conclude that wom- ence of mothers, and the specific virtues they
en’s absence from Kohlberg’s studies was develop can be a valuable resource in think-
inconsequential for his theory and that those ing about peaceful conflict resolution in the
female subjects who talked about needs and political realm. This idea has been further
relationships were morally less developed elaborated by Bubeck (1999). More specifi-
than subjects able to reason in terms of rights cally, Ruddick argued that “maternal think-
and duties. Instead, she thought that in her ing” identifies each individual as being, first
conversation with girls and women she heard and foremost, the result of someone’s loving
a different “moral voice,” one equally impor- work of care, thus providing a specific justi-
tant yet different from the moral “voice of fication and motivation for pacifism. Others
justice” more familiar from men’s moral rea- relied on the fact that everybody is “some
soning. She did not think—as some critics mother’s child” (in Kittay’s words) to argue
believe—that women and men are structur- for a politics of responsibility; the thought is
ally unable to speak both “moral languages” that we all have duties to support others in
but merely noted the gendered aspect of their caregiving activities because none of us
moral reasoning, whatever their explana- could have survived and thrived without it
tion may be (Gilligan, 1995). At the time (Kittay, 1999, Engster, 2007).
when Gilligan wrote her book, the topic of Not only is our physical, intellectual, and
caregiving—that is, a large part of women’s emotional well-being the result of the care
traditional work—was absent from philoso- we received at the beginning of our lives,
phy. Gilligan’s work broke new ground in but also care is essential to our very iden-
reevaluating the moral importance of care; tity as moral beings. Held drew attention
following her, many feminists went on to to the fact that the mothering activity is not
explore “the ethics of care,” which has since merely reproductive, but a creative activity
evolved into a large body of moral and politi- because “in bringing up children, those who
cal theory. mother create new human persons” (Held,
Much of it has to do with practices of 1997, 634). Held describes the relationship
caregiving within the family, mostly in between parents and children as a paradigm

169
Anca Gheaus

case of moral relationships: it is, par excel- is more difficult to refute the criticism that
lence, a situation in which the parents’ exer- an ethics of care is potentially oppressive,
cise of power is voluntarily limited by moral by glorifying the private, and ideally selfless
reasons. This is the ideal context for a child activity of caregiving. Yet, care ethicists do
to learn that might is not right and hence to not uphold the value for strategic reasons,
get a grasp on the essence of morality (Held, but because they believe it is genuinely ethi-
1993). cally essential. One way to avoid injustice
Other feminists looked beyond the realm to caregivers may be to directly compensate
of childrearing and noted that the moral them—through various public policies—for
development of adults also requires close the work of care they do (Okin, 1989a). The
relationships such as friendship (Friedman, ideal way, however, is to encourage men to
1993). Yet others examined the importance share equally in the work of care.
of caring relationships for creating a climate To bring men into care as full partners has
of social trust, which in turn is necessary been on the political feminist agenda at least
for working political communities and even since the late 1960s, and in spite of some
more so for just institutions (Baier, 1994). degree of change it still sounds utopian.
Beyond the differences in what they choose Most care work is different from other
to emphasize, care ethicists convey the gen- types of work due to its emotional and per-
eral conclusion that care is necessary if we sonal element; for this reason, one cannot
are to survive and develop into functioning (typically) do it well if one does not wish to
and moral adults who together can run a just engage in care. Having a relational self—gen-
political community. Yet, this very important uinely valuing connection to others—may in
activity has often been seen as instrumental general be a necessary characteristic of a good
in keeping women out or on the margins caregiver. Feminist psychoanalysis offers
of the public domain of politics and the an explanation of why women, rather than
economy, and for a long time failed to earn men, tend to take on caregiving: as babies
women the status of equal and fully partici- and then small children we form ourselves in
pating citizens. Echoing de Beauvoir’s (1949) reaction to the parent who cares for us most
famous claim that one becomes a woman by of the time, that is the mother. Thus, female
taking on the functions of reproduction and children find it easier to identify with their
mothering, some contemporary philosophers mothers and therefore form a relational self,
warned that feminists should not embrace an while male children strive to separate from
ethics of care (Dietz, 1985, Card, 1990). Part the mother (Chodorow, 1978). On this view,
of the criticism to the ethics of care—that it is the overburdening of women with care work
inherently parochial because it cannot account and their ensuing social marginalization as
for duties owed to strangers with whom we well as their lack of social recognition and
have no caring relationship, nor the interest susceptibility to being dominated (Benjamin,
or hope to develop one—is easily addressed: 1988)  are rooted in the psychosexual rela-
some care ethicists have aimed from the very tionships between women and men. The
beginning to integrate the importance of care direct involvement of both women and men
with that of justice (Tronto, 1993), and oth- in the care for babies and infants holds the
ers have revised or extended their theories in key to change; much of the action, therefore,
this sense (Noddings, 2002, Held, 2006). It is in the private sphere. But, as we shall see,

170
FEMINISM AND GENDER

this does not mean that state involvement is thinking has been relying on a distinction
unwarranted. between the public life of individuals, which
is a legitimate subject to regulation, and their
private life, which ought to be free from state
intervention. Feminist philosophy challenges
JUSTICE AND GENDER this foundational liberal belief.
The criticism mounted by Okin (1989a,
Is state intervention in the private sphere 1994)  to Rawls’s theories of justice (1971,
legitimate, and in what form? How can we 1993) on the question of justice in the family
make sense of the gender component of dis- is the clearest expression of the difficulty that
tributional justice? How does gender affect political–liberal theories of justice have with
other aspects of justice beyond the distribu- integrating feminist concerns. The family is a
tive one—how does gender figure in the prime example of “the private.” Traditionally,
problem of relational justice? I now turn to the institution of the family has been par-
these questions. ticularly instrumental for keeping women
outside political and economic life, social-
The Public and the Private izing them into subordination and justify-
ing various forms of violence against them,
Many of the problems mentioned in the including marital rape. An obvious feminist
introduction are at least partly caused by requirement then is that the family ought to
decisions made by individuals who interact be internally just in order to be legitimate.
with each other in the private sphere: women Yet, according to Rawls—who formulated
(living in liberal democracies) cannot be the most influential account of liberal justice
legally coerced to do housework and child- in contemporary philosophy—the justice of
care; yet they often make career decisions a society is determined by the justice of its
that lead to lower lifetime earnings than basic structure, which is that society’s major
those of men, are more reluctant than men political, economic, and social institutions.
to engage in politics, or compete for pres- These institutions—rather than individual
tigious and powerful positions in various action or private associations such as the
organizations and end up more often than family—come under the purview of justice.
men making a living out of pornography or Rawls’s earlier thinking about justice—
prostitution. To the extent to which patterns before he moved on to defend political
of interaction are coerced—for instance, in liberalism—is more amenable to feminist
cases when prostitution is embedded in mod- concerns. Okin (1989a, b) argued that gen-
ern forms of slavery, or in cases of domestic der concerns are internal to the logic of
violence—they are obviously wrong, and Rawls’s early theory of justice (1971) in
easily addressed by liberal theories of justice. two distinct ways. First, she thought that,
(Indeed, in such cases gender seems inciden- in order for the veil of ignorance—Rawls’s
tal, rather than essential, to the problem.) device for determining the principles of jus-
By contrast, when they result from freely tice—to work in practice, individuals in the
made decisions of people interacting in their original position have to be able to exercise
private capacity they raise difficulties to lib- empathy as well as reason. Without a con-
eral theories of justice. Traditionally, liberal cern for others, the process of deliberating

171
Anca Gheaus

under the veil of ignorance would come to other hand, as voluntary associations, differ-
a standstill. As a consequence, she thought ent families legitimately reflect a variety of
that Rawls’s theory should be modified to conceptions of the good, some of which may
give up the requirement of mutual disin- indeed be inimical to feminist values. The
terestedness. Given the limited knowledge principles of justice are supposed to regu-
about the self that characterizes the parties late the basic structure in order to ensure
in the original position, plus the fact that that the interaction among a society’s major
choices in the original position are sup- political, economic, and social institutions is
posed to be made under the condition of just. A safe conclusion is that, at a minimum,
uncertainty (the parties cannot attach prob- political liberalism will rule out families that
abilities to particular outcomes), the require- deny women their basic freedoms. But this
ment of mutual disinterestedness will make does not get close to the feminist aspira-
deliberation impossible. Second, the family tion to see families shaped by internally just
as the site of childrearing is the first school arrangements.
of justice. Individuals who choose princi- A current debate within political phi-
ples of justice in the original position must losophy concerns the question of whether
be endowed with a sense of justice, which individual actions should also come under
cannot be developed in the absence of the the purview of justice. A positive answer
bonds of care that exist between parents will be friendlier to feminist goals (Cohen,
and children and that go beyond parental 1997). But even some defenders of a nega-
duty. Therefore, a theory of justice needs to tive answer take the side of Okin in consid-
acknowledge the merits of care work and ering it legitimate to regulate certain aspects
the necessity of caring relationships; in this of the family. Most prominent examples are
sense, justice is rooted in care. But the bonds regulating conditions of divorce, including
of care are not enough to ensure that chil- financial settlements between breadwinners
dren acquire a sense of justice; for this, one and homemakers and institutions concern-
also needs to be socialized in just families, in ing childcare, which are meant to enable
which the distribution of resources and bur- both women and men to compete for desir-
dens between women and men is fair. able social and economic positions (Neufeld,
However, from the perspective of politi- 2009). The latter include flexible work-
cal liberalism as defended in Rawls’s later ing hours for parents, parental rather than
thinking (Rawls, 1993), it is not clear in maternal leaves and subsidized childcare, all
which way should the family respond to of which have a direct effect on the internal
the requirements of justice. Specifically, the organization of the family. These proposals
earlier considerations about the importance however fall short of addressing the riddle of
of care and justice in the family are not suf- how a theory of justice that relies on individ-
ficient to show that the family should be uals’ sense of justice could allow individuals
internally regulated by justice (Okin, 1994, to be socialized in internally unjust families.
Lloyd, 1995). On the one hand, the family If the family and, in general, the outcomes
should be regarded as part of the basic struc- of private interactions ought to come under
ture of the society because, as the main site the purview of justice—either because justice
of childrearing, it obviously influences eve- concerns the internal organization of the fam-
rybody’s life chances from the start. On the ily as part of the basic structure, or because

172
FEMINISM AND GENDER

justice concerns individual action—how can care as a justification of the welfare state.
we assess them as gender just or unjust? Bubeck (1995, 1999), who came from a
Marxist background concerned with avoid-
Distributive Justice ing exploitation rather than from a Rawlsian
distributive paradigm, gave an account of
Both the metric (resources in general, pri- gender justice similar in its starting and end-
mary goods in particular, welfare, capabili- ing points. Starting from the assumption of
ties, outcomes) and the principle (equality, the universal dependency on care, she sug-
sufficiency, priority) of distributive justice gested the creation of a state-run civil service
are contentious issues. This is reflected in the of caregiving, which would be similar to, or
variety of accounts of gender justice. even replace, the military service.
Some feminists such as Kittay (1999) fol- Kittay’s account may be read as an attempt
low Rawls in the belief that primary goods to improve the justice of the basic structure
are the correct metric of justice. Like Okin, by ensuring that the primary good of care is
she believes that Rawls’s theory of justice is fairly distributed via the institutions of the
amenable to a modification that would let welfare state, while Bubeck’s suggestion of
it accommodate feminist concerns. Kittay a mandatory universal system of caregiving
notes that dependency is not the exception, is obviously at odds with political liberal-
but the norm of social life—we all are, at ism. But in both accounts gender plays an
times, dependent on others’ care for survival. incidental, rather than constitutive role: they
Hence she criticizes the mutual disinterested- are accounts of gender justice only because
ness of parties in the original position as a caring is a highly feminized activity. Other
normatively unacceptable distortion of social philosophers consider directly the gendered
life. According to Kittay, care is akin to a pri- aspect of typical distribuenda: opportunities,
mary good: it is necessary for individuals to welfare, outcomes, capabilities. As already
survive, let  alone develop and pursue their discussed, women fare worse with respect to
idea of a good life. A proper understanding at least some desirable social goods such as
of social life represents individuals as nodes political and economic advantage.
in a network of care, in which the burden Much contemporary thinking about dis-
of care renders those who carry it particu- tributive justice relies on the belief that it
larly vulnerable and needy. Their vulnerabil- is unjust for people to be disadvantaged by
ity results from the emotional charge of care factors that are not under their control and
and from the need to defer their own inter- for which they cannot be held responsible.
ests for the sake of meeting the needs of their By contrast, different outcomes resulting
charges. Informal caregiving does not carry from individual uncoerced and informed
economic rewards, and as a market serv- choices are just, as long as they reflect indi-
ice care is underpaid (Tronto, 1993, 2002, viduals’ level of talent and ambition (but for
Bubeck, 1995, Kittay, 1999). Caregivers a defense of equality of outcomes, includ-
ought to be able to depend on people and ing between women and men, see Phillips,
structures that support them, and the sup- 2004). This is the difficult question, then:
port should be made available as a matter is there anything unjust in women’s lesser
of justice. Kittay, and more recently Engster political participation and economic power
(2007) took this account of dependency and if they result from women’s decision to

173
Anca Gheaus

focus on childrearing and family making? Relational Justice


Some believe the answer is negative, that
we should take women’s preferences for a It is counterintuitive that all kinds of social
particular combination of work and fam- injustice in general, and gender injustice in
ily at face value and strive to accommodate particular, are distributive in nature. Some of
them (Hakim, 2000). Yet, in a world like it is relational, concerning how individuals
ours, with a history of formal discrimina- relate to each other rather than how much
tion against women’s participation in poli- each has compared to others. The demand
tics and economic life, women’s domesticity that women’s work of care be socially rec-
is not likely to be a merely individual choice ognized and rewarded is perhaps the most
but rather a significant symptom and future widespread concern of relational justice and
cause of gender injustice (Williams, 2000). It gender.
is not all history. First, social institutions are But recognition is not all there is to rela-
structured such that it is difficult to combine tional justice. Young (1990) famously distin-
work and family. Second, ambition itself is guished between several forms of injustice
socialized and so, to the extent that gender that do not fit naturally in the “distributive
norms nudge women into domesticity, their paradigm.” Together they explain, accord-
lower political and economic ambition and ing to her, how women are being oppressed
unequal outcomes in these spheres ought and dominated. The “five faces of oppres-
to come under criticism (Arneson, 1998, sion” identified by Young are exploitation,
Mason, 2000). marginalization, cultural imperialism, pow-
The likely conclusion of this debate is that erlessness, and violence. Indeed, women’s
gender justice is incompatible with gender oppression and domination are at least as
norms. (An important question, which can- salient concerns for feminists as unequal out-
not be addressed here, is whether all gender comes in politics and the economy; Haslanger
norms are incompatible with gender justice.) (2000) has proposed that the very definition
Arneson (1998) suggested that gender justice of “woman” incorporates this concern: “S is
obtains when social practices and individual a woman iff (df) S is systematically subor-
conduct are regulated such that gender does dinated along some dimension (economic,
not affect one’s life prospects. According to political, legal, social, etc.), and S is ‘marked’
Robeyns (2007) a society is gender just when as a target for this treatment by observed or
women and men have the same capability imagined bodily features presumed to be evi-
sets, are free to choose without gender-re- dence of a female’s biological role in repro-
lated constraints on choice, and enjoy “pay- duction” (Haslanger, 2000, 39).
offs” which are also unstructured by gender Yet, antifeminists may express skepticism
norms. Gheaus (2012) argued that a society about the very existence of gender oppression
is gender just only if the costs of leading a in liberal societies, pointing out that women
gender-neutral lifestyle are, for both women are active perpetrators of various mecha-
and men, lower than, or at most equal to, nisms said to oppress them. Cudd (2006),
the costs of gendered lifestyles. Costs in this who takes the oppression of women by men
context are to be understood very broadly, to to be the paradigmatic example of oppres-
cover financial burdens, time, effort, psycho- sion, answers this potential criticism by
logical discomfort, and so on. pointing out that often the best overall pay

174
FEMINISM AND GENDER

off for women in particular circumstances parties participate under conditions of equal-
depends on their compliance with oppressive ity—that is, are equally enabled to voice their
norms. A bigger worry with an account of opinions on the issues at stake. Other condi-
gender justice in terms of oppression is that tions necessary for the democratic process to
the same patriarchal gender norms that hurt lead to legitimate outcomes are that all par-
women’s interests can also hurt, in other ticipants be equally able to bring new issues
circumstances, men’s interests: for instance, into discussion and challenge the very rules
they result in men being more vulnerable to of how the deliberative process is conducted
extreme violence in the public space (particu- (Benhabib, 1996). This ideal of democracy
larly in war) and in men having less access to goes hand in hand with Benhabib’s con-
family life (because there are no “daddy job ception of cultures as constantly changing
tracks,” men are more likely to lose custody through dialogue, as well as a conception of
battles, etc.). cosmopolitan multiculturalism that strives
to combine diversity and robust equality.
She argued that all citizens of multicultural
societies ought to have the same civil, politi-
DEMOCRATIC THEORY AND GENDER cal, and economic rights and should not be
enrolled, against their will, in the culture of
Relational equality is called by some political their parents. Rather, she claims that individ-
philosophers “democratic equality” to signal uals should retain an ability to exit it at any
its importance for the well functioning of a time (and the right to be accepted by other
democratic community (Anderson, 1999). cultural groups if, for instance, they marry
This indicates that, alongside with living in one of their members) (Benhabib, 2004).
a society whose institutions, individuals, and Benhabib’s ideal of democratic society
relationships are just, we also care about the is feminist because it gives women a voice
way in which society is being shaped, namely, in every aspect of their lives and tries to
through democratic procedures. Feminists delegitimize patriarchal practices without
made distinct contributions to democratic requiring women to repudiate their culture;
theory by drawing attention to the impor- instead, it indicates the conditions in which
tance of deliberative and communicative multiculturalism need not be bad for women
democracy in giving women power and voice (to appreciate the complexity of the debate
and analyzing the way in which the gendered on feminism and multiculturalism, see Okin
division of labor has systematically excluded et al., 1999).
women from democratic participation. Other feminists working on democracy,
such as Young (1990), are less optimistic
Deliberative Democracy than Benhabib about women’s voice in poli-
tics, given their historical marginalization.
Benhabib’s work, influenced by critical the- Young’s solution to this problem is that dem-
ory, focuses on the process of shaping par- ocratic practices should go beyond the delib-
ticular social and institutional arrangements. erative—and hence rational—element and
On her account, norms of social coexistence include forms of communication that have
are valid only if they are reached through a been traditionally practiced by women (such
process of deliberation in which all affected as storytelling). Another solution for making

175
Anca Gheaus

democracies more women-friendly is intro- POLICY AND FEMINIST THEORY


ducing female quotas in politics (Phillips,
1995). As already mentioned, feminist political phi-
losophers support a variety of policy propos-
The Gendered Division of Labor and als aimed at ensuring a fairer distribution
Democracy of the burdens and benefits of social coop-
eration between women and men, and also
The gendered division of labor is also at improving the relational status of women.
important for understanding the role of Many of these proposals have to do with a bet-
gender in democratic theory. Pateman ter distribution of care work, like the earlier
(1988) explained how the tradition of the mentioned civil service (Bubeck, 1999)  and
social contract theory presupposes the with the creation of safety nets for caregivers
existence of families: women’s work in the (Kittay, 1999). In other cases, the policy justi-
home makes possible the political activity fication lies in enabling both women and men
of the polity’s members (male citizens, typi- to engage equally in paid work and family
cally) by providing for their daily needs. life. As we have seen, the gendered division of
Without such support, they would lack labor is considered the source of distributive
the time and resources needed to engage in inequalities between women and men, lower
politics; thus, the social contract between recognition of women and their work, and
citizens requires a second, sexual—or mar- women’s impaired citizenship. Such policies
riage—contract between women and men. could result in the generalization of a “car-
One result is the exclusion of women from egiving parity” model of social organization
political participation. Pateman’s account is which, according to Fraser (1994), would be
similar to Okin’s claim that “major contem- better at addressing most of the concerns dis-
porary Anglo-American theories of justice cussed earlier: it would help eliminate female
are to a great extent about men with wives poverty and income inequality, exploita-
at home” (Okin, 1989a, 110). But, while tion, marginalization, and lack of recogni-
Okin’s main concern is with the require- tion. A comprehensive policy proposal that
ments of justice in the context of a gendered would make it possible for women and men
division of labor, Pateman’s work focuses on to engage in both paid work and family care
women as citizens. Unlike the first contract, was advanced by sociologists Gornick and
the second went unrecognized by political Meyers (2003).
philosophers, thus rendering women and The next logical step for feminist demo-
their contribution to political life invisible. cratic theory was to devise an understanding
Pateman’s ultimate goal is to cast doubt of citizenship that transcends the gendered
that an organization of social life based division of labor and can therefore equally
on contracts between individuals can be empower—perhaps in spite of Pateman’s
an emancipatory strategy for women. As a skepticism—women and men. Building,
consequence of her view, she became one of among others, on the ethics of care and
the main advocates of the introduction of Bubeck’s proposal, Lister (2002) argued for
a universal, unconditional basic income as a redefinition of citizenhood to include an
a path toward women’s independence from obligation of caregiving. Lister thinks that
men (Pateman, 2004). an adequate understanding of citizenship

176
FEMINISM AND GENDER

ought to include the private sphere and so toward property-owning democracy. Both
her policy proposals partly overlap with proposals are very tempting to feminists since
those of Gornick and Meyers: employment they would lift many women from poverty,
regulations to allow parents to combine paid empower all women economically, at least
work and care, including parental leaves and in the short run, and free them from oppres-
childcare services. Other policy proposals sive marriages and market demands, allow-
are especially useful for including women as ing them to engage in caring (if they wish to)
citizens on an equal standing to men, such as without the threat of economic dependency
those concerning parliamentary design, pay and poverty (Elgarte, 2008). The introduc-
and employment equity legislation, and the tion of an unconditional basic income could
creation of adequate safety nets for women also lead to more recognition for care work
escaping domestic violence. and support people’s freedom to enjoy care
Another issue on which feminist political in non-commodified form (Baker, 2008). Yet,
theory can directly feed into public policy is the very last features are also potentially inimi-
that of pornography. Pornography is a likely cal to feminist goals because a basic income
area that feminists would want regulated for would serve as an incentive for some women
its effects on women. Some feminists believe to forgo careers and hence eventually regroup
that there is a direct causal connection between at the lower end of economic distributions
pornography and violence, including sexual (Robeyns, 2001, Gheaus, 2008). If a universal
violence, against women (MacKinnon, 1987). basic income or a property-owning democracy
Others think that pornography is, in effect, a were to replace, rather than supplement, insti-
way of subordinating women because porno- tutions such as (egalitarian) parental leaves and
graphic images and words have the illocution- subsidized childcare, the detrimental effects on
ary force of communicating that women may women would be larger (Bergmann, 2004).
be subject to degrading practices (Langton,
1995). They may also silence women by con-
veying the idea that women’s explicit opposi-
tion to engage in sex (saying “no”) does not GLOBAL JUSTICE AND GENDER
constitute a refusal (Hornsby, 1995). If there
are such causal connections—especially the All the earlier concern domestic politics, but
more direct ones—they constitute reason the acceleration of globalization is pressing
for regulating pornography. Any all-things- new issues on the feminist agenda: duties to
considered judgment would have to take into women living in nonliberal cultures, women’s
account powerful reasons to refrain from its migration and transnational employment,
criminalization: for instance, that this would the revival of a culture of domestic servants,
deprive of choices women who do not have the global transformation of caregiving, and
many choices in the first place (Nussbaum, reproductive tourism.
1999). One debate takes place between cosmo-
Recently, there has been much philosophi- politan feminists and those who are more
cal interest in more radical policy proposals skeptic about the prospects of intercultural
meant to improve the general distribution of understanding. Starting from her version of
wealth in society: the introduction of a uni- the capabilities approach rooted in a univer-
versal, unconditional basic income, or a move salistic account of human values, Nussbaum

177
Anca Gheaus

(2000) argued that we ought to promote from their children, often for many years
women’s capabilities independently from the (Hochschild, 2005). An ideal solution to the
cultures in which these women happen to live. problems of global care drain would be the
Nussbaum’s project is to draw the attention of creation of a global caring society such that
middle-class feminists from liberal democra- adequate care is provided locally to all those
cies to the plight of poor women from devel- who need it (Weir, 2005, Kittay, 2008).
oping countries and explain why the liberal Increased mobility across borders also ena-
convictions of the first commit them to the bles well-off women to obtain cheaper repro-
goal of advancing the capabilities of the sec- ductive services using the labor of poorer
ond. Yet, where there are cultural barriers, it is women. Thus, women from the so-called third
not obvious that there exist legitimate means world countries increasingly serve as surro-
for doing this. Jaggar (2005) has argued that in gate mothers to children who are then raised
order to create such means we must avoid the in richer countries. This expanding practice
assumption that oppression by illiberal cul- raises moral and political issues for all partici-
tures is the gravest injustice suffered by distant pants in the transaction: does using a surrogate
women. Material deprivation for instance—it- necessarily exploit her? (Panitch, 2013) What
self a feminized phenomenon—may be a much are the conditions in which surrogate women
more salient injustice in many cases. can be said to make an autonomous choice
The international migration of women to engage in surrogacy? Arguing that condi-
continues to provide cheap labor for domes- tions such as adequate income, education, and
tic services—primarily care services for chil- healthcare, as well as freedom from environ-
dren, disabled, and elderly persons. The mental hazards and state violence are neces-
often exploitative employment conditions of sary for autonomous decisions, Bailey (2011)
migrant women came under feminist criticism concluded that oppression is often unavoid-
(Ehrenreich and Hochschild, 2002). But, given able in surrogacy contracts.
that even in developed countries welfare states
fail to provide sufficient care services, cheap
migrant labor is often the only solution for
enabling women to pursue a career. This gen- NEW FRONTIERS
erates dilemmas for feminists. Some believe,
for example, that feminist commitments to Gender, Implicit Bias, and
social justice are incompatible with relying on Stereotype Threat
domestic servants (Tronto, 2002).
The feminization of migration in combina- We have seen why gender raises a difficult
tion with the gendered division of labor has problem—at least for liberal theories of
created shortages of care in migrants’ coun- ­justice—when inequalities between women
tries of origin. Because this phenomenon— and men arise through free interaction. The
often referred to as “care drain”  —happens liberal theory assumes that individuals could
against a background of stark global inequal- take full responsibility for such interactions.
ities, it represents an issue of global gender But what if free decisions are to a large extent
justice (Gheaus, 2013). Care drain harms not driven by unconscious judgment and/or emo-
only children and others in need of care but tional reactions? Psychological research indi-
also parents who are physically separated cates that even people who hold explicit and

178
FEMINISM AND GENDER

sincere egalitarian views make choices that individuals in their capacity as knowers; it
reflect negative biases against women or racial arises when people are being wrongly treated
minorities. (The best-known test measuring as unreliable sources of information due to
this is freely available at <https://implicit. the hearers’ prejudice. Epistemic injustice can
harvard.edu/implicit/>.) Experiments show be testimonial—for instance, when someone
that both men and women evaluate differ- is not believed because she is a woman; or it
ently vitas and job applications that are oth- can be hermeneutical, when insufficient col-
erwise identical depending on whether they lective interpretive resources generates dis-
are believed to be from men or from women. advantages—for instance, when a woman’s
Stereotype threat refers to people’s tendency complaint that she has been the subject of
to confirm negative stereotypical expectations sexual harassment cannot be made sense of
that others have of them, especially in social in a linguistic community that lacks the con-
contexts that make the stereotypes salient. cept of sexual harassment.
A growing body of literature explores the Epistemic injustice bears on most of the
effect of stereotype threat and implicit bias issues discussed in this chapter, including fair
for inequalities between women and men distributions, deliberative democracy, and
in academic philosophy (see, for instance, women’s oppression. First, there is an inter-
Saul, 2013). But the possible application esting question about the nature of the harms
of these findings is much wider: some of at stake in testimonial injustice. According to
the inequalities between women and men Fricker, the deepest harm of epistemic injus-
are likely to result from unconscious proc- tice is preventing people to become who they
esses that characterize both the people who really are, as knowers. So does the injus-
engage in competition for political and tice arise because we have a moral right to
economic positions and those who are sup- become who we are? And does the injustice
posed to evaluate the former. In this case, have a distributional side: is there a right to
it is far from clear that individuals can be become who you are as much as others do?
held fully responsible for their achieve- Second, the existence of epistemic injus-
ments (or lack thereof). This means that the tice has direct implications for thinking
“different conceptions of the good” can- about democracy, in particular its delibera-
not be straightforwardly invoked to justify tive component, since testimonial injustice
the feminization of certain jobs, women’s can prevent some individuals from having
lower earnings, and other kinds of gen- an equal voice. Similarly, it has consequences
der inequalities. Similarly, to the extent to for thinking about domination and exploi-
which mechanisms to reduce implicit bias tation, since having a voice is a main strat-
and stereotype threat are being discovered, egy for avoiding these forms of injustice: if
there may be a strong case for their use in you suffer from persistent epistemic injus-
social practices and state institutions (such tice or from hermeneutical injustice, you
as, for instance, job interviews or courts). are likely to be seriously disadvantaged in
negotiations.
Gender and Epistemic Injustice In conclusion, feminist political philosophy
has been making distinctive contributions to
According to Fricker (2007), epistemic injus- the central issues of justice and democracy.
tice is a distinct kind of injustice that harms Over the next years, it is likely that new

179
Anca Gheaus

developments in our understanding of non- Benjamin, J. (1988), The Bonds of Love.


conscious forms of discrimination and of Psychoanalysis, Feminism and the
nonconscious reactions to discrimination are Problem of Domination. New York:
likely to fuel debates about gender justice and Pantheon Books.
about the relationship between gender and Bergmann, B. R. (2004), “A Swedish-Style
democratic exercises of power. Welfare State or Basic Income: Which
Should Have Priority?” Politics and
Society, 32 (1): 107–118.
Bubeck, D. E. (1995), Care, Gender, and
Note Justice. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
— (1999), “A Feminist Approach to
I am thankful to Sine Bagatur, Andrew Fiala,
1
Citizenship,” in O. Hufton and Y.
Lisa Herzog, Lindsey Porter, and Cristina Kravaritou (eds), Gender and the Use
Roadevin for comments on an earlier draft.
of Time. The Hague: Kluwer Academic
Publishers, pp. 401–428.
Card, C. (1990), “Caring and Evil,”
WORKS CITED Hypatia, 5 (1): 101–108.
Chodrow, N. (1978), The Reproduction
Anderson, E. (1999), “What is the Point of of Mothering: Psychoanalysis and the
Equality?” Ethics, 109 (2): 287–337. Sociology of Gender. Berkeley, CA:
Arneson, R. (1998), “What Sort of Sexual University of California.
Equality Should Feminists Seek,” Cohen, G. A. (1997), “Where the action
Journal of Contemporary Legal Issues, is: On the Site of Distributive Justice,”
9: 21–36. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 26 (1):
Baier, A. C. (1994), Moral Prejudices: Essays 3–30.
on Ethics. Harvard: Harvard University Cudd, A. (2006), Analysing Oppression.
Press. New York: Oxford University Press.
Bailey, A. (2011), “Reconceiving Surrogacy: De Beauvoir, S. (1949), Le Deuxième sexe.
Toward a Reproductive Justice Account Paris: Gallimard.
of Indian Surrogacy,” Hypatia, 26 (4): Dietz, M. (1985), “Citizenship with a
715–741. Feminist Face: The Problem With
Baker, J. (2008), “All Things Considered, Maternal Thinking,” Political Theory, 13
Should Feminists Embrace Basic (1): 19–37.
Income?” Basic Income Studies, 3 (3) Ehrenreich, B. and A. R. Hochschild (eds)
Benhabib, S. (ed.) (1996), “Toward a (2002), Global Women: Nannies, Maid
Deliberative Model of Democratic and Sex Workers in the New Economy.
Legitimacy,” in Democracy and New York: Holt.
Difference: Contesting the Boundaries Elgarte, J. (2008), “Basic Income and the
of the Political. Princeton, NJ: Princeton Gendered Division of Labour,” Basic
University Press. Income Studies, 3 (3).
— (2004), The Rights of Others. Aliens, Engster, D. (2007), The Heart of Justice.
Residents, and Citizens. Cambridge: Care Ethics and Political Theory. Oxford:
Cambridge University Press. Oxford University Press.

180
FEMINISM AND GENDER

Fraser, N. (1994), “After the Family Wage. — (2006), The Ethics of Care Personal,
Gender Equity and the Welfare State,” Political, and Global. New York: Oxford
Political Theory, 22 (4): 591–618. University Press.
Fricker, M. (2007), Epistemic Injustice: Hochschild, A. R. (2005), “Love and
Power and the Ethics of Knowing. Gold,” in L. Ricciutelli, A. Miles, and M.
Oxford: Oxford University Press. H. McFadden (eds), Feminist Politics,
Friedman, M. (1993), What Are Friends Activism and Vision: Local and Global
For?: Feminist Perspectives on Personal Challenges. London, Toronto: Zed/Innana
Relationships and Moral Theory. Ithaca, Books, pp. 34–46.
NY: Cornell University Press. Hornsby, J. (1995), “Speech Acts and
Gheaus, A. (2008), “Basic Income, Gender Pornography,” in S. Dwyer (ed.), The
Justice and the Costs of Gender- Problem of Pornography. Belmont, CA:
Symmetrical Lifestyles,” Basic Income Wadsworth Publishing Company.
Studies, 3 (3). Jaggar, A. (1983), Feminist Politics and
— (2012), “Gender Justice,” Journal of Human Nature. Lanham, MD: Rowman
Ethics and Social Philosophy, 6: 1–24. & Littlefield.
— (2013), “Care Drain As An Issue — (2005), “‘Saving Amina’: Global Justice
of Global Gender Justice,” Ethical for Women and Intercultural Dialogue,”
Perspectives, 20 (1): 61–80. Ethics & International Affairs, 19 (3):
Gilligan, C. (1982), In a Different Voice: 55–75.
Psychological Theory and Women’s Kittay, E. F. (1999), Love’s Labor: Essays on
Development. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Women, Equality, and Dependency. New
University Press. York: Routledge.
— (1995), “Moral Orientation and Moral — (2008), “The Global Heart Transplant
Development,” in V. Held (ed.), Justice and Caring across National Boundaries,”
and Care. Boulder, CO: Westview Press. The Southern Journal of Philosophy,
Gornick, J. C. and M. K. Meyers XLVI: 138–165.
(2003), Families That Work. Policies Kohlberg, L. (1981), The Philosophy of Moral
for Reconciling Parenthood and Development: Moral Stages and the Idea of
Employment. New York: Russel Sage Justice. San Francisco: Harper & Row.
Foundation. Langton, R. (1995), “Speech Acts and
Hakim, C. (2000), Work Lifestyle Choices Unspeakable Acts,” in S. Dwyer (ed.),
in the 21st Century: Preference Theory. The Problem of Pornography. Belmont,
Oxford: Oxford University Press. CA: Wadsworth Publishing Company.
Haslanger, S. (2000), “Gender and Race: Lister, R. (2002), Citizenship: Feminist
(What) Are They? (What) Do We Want Perspectives. New York: New York
Them To Be?” Noûs, 34 (1): 31–55. University Press.
Held, V. (1993), Feminist Morality: Lloyd, S. A. (1995), “Situating a Feminist
Transforming Culture, Society and Criticism of John Rawls’s Political
Politics. Chicago: University of Chicago. Liberalism,” Loyola of Los Angeles Law
— (1997), “Feminism and Moral Theory,” Review, 28: 1319–1344.
in D. T. Meyers (ed.), Feminist Social MacKinnon, C. (1987), Feminism
Thought: A Reader. New York: Routledge. Unmodified: Discourses on Life and Law.

181
Anca Gheaus

Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Phillips, A. (2004), “Defending Equality


Press. of Outcome,” Journal of Political
Mason, A. (2000), “Equality, Personal Philosophy, 12: 1–19.
Responsibility, and Gender Socialisation,” — (1995), The Politics of Presence. Oxford:
Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Oxford University Press.
100 (3): 227–246. Rawls, J. (1971), A Theory of Justice.
Neufeld, B. (2009), “Coercion, the Basic Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Structure, and the Family,” Journal of — (1993), Political Liberalism. New York:
Social Philosophy, 40: 37–54. Columbia University Press.
Noddings, N. (1982), Caring: A Feminine Robeyns, I. (2007), “When Will Society Be
Approach to Ethics and Moral Education. Gender Just?” in J. Browne (ed.), The
Berkeley, CA: University of California Future of Gender. Cambridge: Cambridge
Press, 1982. University Press.
— (2002), Starting at Home: Caring and — (2001), “Will a Basic Income Do Justice
Social Policy. Berkeley, CA: University of to Women?” Analyse und Kritik, 22 (2):
California Press. 88–105.
Nussbaum, M. (1999), Sex and Social Ruddick, S. (1989), Maternal Thinking.
Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Towards a Politics of Peace. Boston, MA:
— (2000), Women and Human Beacon Press.
Development: The Capabilities Approach. Saul, J. (2013), “Implicit Bias, Stereotype
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Threat, and Women in Philosophy,” in K.
Okin, S. M. (1989a), Justice, Gender, and Hutchison and F. Jenkins (eds), Women
the Family. New York: Basic Books. in Philosophy: What Needs to Change.
— (1989b), “Reason and Feeling in Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Thinking about Justice,” Ethics, 99 (2): Tronto, J. (1993), Moral Boundaries: A
229–249. Political Argument for an Ethic of Care.
— (1994), “Political Liberalism, Justice, and New York: Routledge.
Gender,” Ethics, 105 (1): 23–43. — (2002), “The ‘Nanny’ Question in
Okin, S. M., Cohen, J., Howard, Feminism,” Hypatia, 17 (2): 34–51.
M., and Nussbaum, M. (1999), Is Young, I. M. (1990), Justice and the Politics
Multiculturalism Bad for Women? of Difference. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. University Press.
Panitch, V. (2013), “Surrogate Tourism and Weir, A. (2005), “The Global Universal
Reproductive Rights,” Hypatia, 28 (2): Caregiver: Imagining Women’s Liberation
274–289. in the New Millennium,” Constellations,
Pateman, C. (1988), The Sexual Contract. 12 (3): 308–330.
Stanford, CA: Polity Press. Williams, J. (2000), Unbending Gender:
— (2004), “Democratizing Citizenship: Why Family and Work Conflict and
Some Advantages of a Basic Income,” What to Do About It. New York: Oxford
Politics and Society, 32 (1): 89–105. University Press.

182
12
IMMIGRATION AND BORDERS
Shelley Wilcox

INTRODUCTION ARGUMENTS FOR THE STATE’S


RIGHT TO EXCLUDE
Within the past three decades, the ethics
of immigration has emerged as a topic of The Conventional View
considerable interest among political phi-
losophers. The subject includes normative Early work on the ethics of immigration
questions related to various dimensions typically defends the common intuition that
of global migration, including territorial states have a broad right to control their bor-
admissions, admission to citizenship, and ders, including a right to regulate immigra-
the rights and duties of non-citizen resi- tion in accordance with national priorities.
dents. The central question in these debates Walzer offers the best-known philosophical
is whether liberal democratic states have defense of this position (Walzer, 1983). He
a moral right to restrict immigration.1 On understands political membership as a social
the one side of the issue, philosophers argue good, constituted by the shared understand-
that states have a broad moral right to ings of a political community. This implies,
select whatever immigration policies serve Walzer believes, that members of a political
their national interest, excluding would- community should be free to decide who is
be immigrants as they see fit. On the other, admitted to their political community in
proponents contend that a commitment to accordance with their own understandings of
fundamental liberal values, such as free- it. It follows that we must know something
dom and equality, requires states to main- about the nature of liberal democratic com-
tain open borders. This chapter surveys munities in order to determine what sorts
the main lines of argument in this debate, of immigration policies are appropriate for
beginning with arguments in defense of the them. However, since political communities
state’s supposed right to exclude would-be tend to be large and abstract, their natures can
immigrants. be difficult to grasp. Thus, Walzer compares

183
Shelley Wilcox

liberal democratic societies to other, smaller societies are like families, “for it is a feature
associations that we understand more read- of families that their members are morally
ily. By examining neighborhoods, clubs, and connected to people they have not chosen,
families, and the membership policies that who live outside the household” (ibid., 41).
govern them, we can determine which immi- This kinship affinity has important implica-
gration policies are appropriate for liberal tions for immigrant admissions policies. In
democracies. particular, it implies that the relatives of cur-
The first model Walzer considers is that rent citizens and displaced ethnic nationals
of the neighborhood, a loose association of should receive admissions priority.
individuals living in close proximity to one Walzer also acknowledges an additional
another. Neighborhoods have no formal constraint on liberal immigration policies.
legal admissions policies; although residents Since admissions decisions regulate relation-
may choose not to welcome newcomers, the ships between members and foreigners, they
state does not prevent individuals from set- are governed by the principle of collective
tling in whatever neighborhood they choose. mutual aid. This principle maintains that a
Should liberal democratic societies adopt society is obligated to aid needy outsiders
membership policies analogous to those of if the need is acute and the cost of provid-
neighborhoods? That is, should liberal states ing aid is comparably negligible. Affluent
maintain open borders, permitting prospec- societies can usually fulfill these duties by
tive immigrants to settle in whatever country transferring some of their wealth to poorer
they wish? Walzer argues that they should societies as economic aid. However, in the
not. Since citizens are deeply committed to case of political asylum-seekers—­individuals
protecting their culture and political life who are fleeing their countries to escape
against perceived threats by outsiders, free political or religious persecution—the duties
migration at the state level would almost cer- of mutual aid can be fulfilled only through
tainly be resisted at the local level. Such local territorial admission. Thus, Walzer con-
closure is undesirable liberal societies; thus, cludes that liberal states have a broad right
states must be able to regulate immigration to regulate immigration in accordance with
as necessary to protect the freedom, welfare, collective self-understandings, provided
and culture of current citizens. they accept at least some refugees, narrowly
Based on these considerations, Walzer defined.2
suggests that liberal democratic societies are Several commentators have raised objec-
like clubs: both are free to choose their own tions to Walzer’s argument. One prominent
admissions decisions, admitting and exclud- line of criticism takes issue with the analo-
ing would-be members in accordance with gies he draws between liberal democratic
collective understandings. However, despite states and other associative organizations
these parallels, Walzer believes the club anal- (Cole, 2000, Higgins, 2013). For Walzer’s
ogy fails to capture an essential moral feature argument to be persuasive, they argue, it is
of liberal societies. Unlike club members, not enough for states simply to be like the
citizens have moral obligations to certain associative organizations he identifies; they
unchosen groups of outsiders, such as those must be like them in all morally relevant
with whom they share significant cultural or respects. However, this simply is not the
ethnic ties. In this sense, liberal democratic case. Consider the analogy between states

184
IMMIGRATION AND BORDERS

and clubs. These associations may share THE FREEDOM OF ASSOCIATION


some idealized features, such as a collec- ARGUMENT
tive identity or shared sense of purpose.
However, they differ in several morally rel- In a widely discussed article, Wellman argues
evant respects: most obviously, membership that the collective right to self-determination
in states is typically nonvoluntary; states includes a right to close borders, excluding
possess territorial jurisdiction that clubs do all would-be immigrants, including refugees
not; and states provide a much wider range (Wellman, 2008, Wellman and Cole, 2011).
of basic goods to their members than clubs. His argument proceeds in two stages. The first
Given these differences, critics insist that seeks to establish that states have a general
Walzer cannot simply derive the right of lib- right to self-determination, which includes a
eral democratic communities to choose their presumptive right to exclude would-be immi-
membership policies from the fact that most grants. The second aims to show that this right
clubs are free to choose their own members.3 is not outweighed by standard egalitarian and
He can only offer the observation that states libertarian considerations, and thus that states
and clubs are alike in this respect, but in may legitimately close borders in practice.
absence of further argument, this begs the The argument begins with the relatively
question of whether political communities uncontroversial claim that individuals have
have a legitimate right to choose any mem- a basic right to self-determination, which
bership policies they wish. includes a right to freedom of association.
Using the examples of religion and mar-
riage, Wellman further argues that freedom
of association has both inclusive and exclu-
SELF-DETERMINATION ARGUMENTS sive aspects. Freedom of marital association,
for example, includes both the right to marry
For reasons such as these, most liberal phi- one’s willing partner and the right to refuse
losophers reject Walzer’s defense of the to marry any given suitor or to remain sin-
state’s supposed right to exclude would-be gle altogether. He then suggests that the citi-
immigrants. Nevertheless, some insist that zens of states also have a collective right to
his argument contains a valuable insight: self-determination, which includes the right
membership decisions are tied to collective to choose which would-be immigrants are
self-determination. Recently, several of these admitted into the state or to exclude immi-
philosophers have attempted to draw out grants altogether. In his words:
the normative implications of this connec-
tion, arguing that the right to collective self- Just as an individual has a right to deter-
determination includes the right to exclude mine whom (if anyone) he or she would
would-be immigrants. I will discuss two like to marry, a group of fellow-citizens
has a right to determine whom (if anyone)
prominent arguments here.4 The first main-
it would like to invite into its political com-
tains that the state’s right to exclude follows
munity. And just as an individual’s freedom
from collective right to freedom of associa- of association entitles one to remain single,
tion, and the second attempts to derive the a state’s freedom of association entitles it
right to exclude from the collective owner- to exclude all foreigners from its political
ship of public institutions. community (Wellman, 2008, 110–111).

185
Shelley Wilcox

Wellman is quick to point out that the these vital interests. Wellman acknowledges
state’s right to exclude would-be immigrants that individuals who cannot live a minimally
is a presumptive right. As such, it can be decent life in their home countries have a
outweighed by competing moral claims. In substantial interest in moving to a new state
particular, two types of cosmopolitan moral in which their basic needs could be met, but
duties—samaritan and relational egalitar- he insists that states can fulfill their duties
ian—could, in theory, place limits on the to help these needy individuals by trans-
right to exclude. Samaritan duties, which ferring material aid. However, Fine argues
are generated by the principle of collective that individuals may also have significant
mutual aid, require affluent states to assist “familial, social, religious, cultural, political,
foreigners living in abject poverty. Relational or economic” interests that can be met only
egalitarian duties require states to mitigate by moving to a new state and immigration
inequalities that contribute to oppression restrictions wrongly thwart these interests.
within transnational structural relationships. Thus, in many cases, the right to self-deter-
However, Wellman insists that in practice, mination does not give liberal states the right
neither samaritan nor relational egalitar- to exclude would-be immigrants.
ian duties require states to open their bor- Other critics object to the second stage
ders because these obligations can be met by of Wellman’s argument. Wellman acknowl-
“exporting justice” in the form of material edges that some relationships between citi-
aid or through military intervention rather zens and outsiders are robust enough to
than by admitting immigrants (Wellman, generate relational egalitarian duties, but
2008, 129). he contends that societies can fulfill these
By attempting to derive the right to exclude duties by transferring aid. However, I have
would-be immigrants from uncontroversial argued that exporting aid is often an inap-
liberal rights rather than through analogies propriate means of fulfilling relational egali-
between liberal states and other associative tarian duties because aid transfers tend to
organizations, Wellman’s argument evades create the sorts of oppressive relationships
many of the objections to which Walzer’s that relational egalitarians reject (Wilcox,
position is subject. However, it is not without 2014). For instance, contributing economic
its critics. Some reject Wellman’s claim that aid can enable donor nations to dominate
the right to freedom of association includes recipient nations, by setting conditions for
the right to exclude would-be immigrants. its use or by leveraging the possibility of
For instance, Fine points out that the right to continued aid to gain an unfair advantage in
self-determination protects only self-regard- negotiations over other policies. Moreover,
ing actions; individuals—and importantly, aid transfers alone often cannot remedy the
groups—are not morally free to engage in injustices that generate relational egalitarian
behavior that harms others, in the sense of duties in the first place, since these injustices
setting back their significant interests (Fine, are maintained by ongoing, unfair economic
2010). Yet this is precisely what some immi- policies. Critics also reject Wellman’s claim
gration exclusions do: many would-be immi- that samaritan duties can be discharged by
grants have substantial interests in living in military intervention on similar grounds
a new state, and barring their entry thwarts (Cavallero, 2014).

186
IMMIGRATION AND BORDERS

THE ASSOCIATIVE OWNERSHIP defined as “those fleeing political persecu-


ARGUMENT tion and those trapped in abject poverty”
are an obvious case (Pevnick, 2011, 92).
Pevnick shares Wellman’s conviction that the Pevnick also acknowledges four cases of
prima facie right to exclude immigrants is con- global inequality that generate stringent
nected to the right to collective self-determi- moral duties to outsiders: (a) if one group
nation (Pevnick, 2011). However, his account falls below some minimal standard of decent
of this connection differs from Wellman’s in living while another enjoys an excess of
two important respects: he derives the right to wealth; (b) if inequalities are a direct result
exclude from claims to collective ownership of the past illegitimate actions of a better-
rather than the right to freedom of associa- off group; (c) if inequalities threaten to
tion; and he acknowledges that in practice, a undermine fair interaction among parties in
broad range of moral duties to outsiders could robust transnational relationships; and (d)
outweigh the presumptive right to exclude. if inequalities result from the unfair distri-
Thus, Pevnick’s version of the self-determina- bution of benefits or burdens within a self-
tion argument yields something of a middle- supporting scheme of social cooperation.
ground position on immigrant admissions. While Pevnick does not explicitly argue that
Pevnick argues that the right to self-deter- states must admit immigrants in order to
mination is grounded in the special ownership fulfill these moral duties, he also does not
relationship between citizens and their institu- rule out this possibility. Thus, for example,
tions. Citizens contribute to the creation and if opening borders were a suitable means
maintenance of state institutions in numerous for rectifying ongoing inequalities resulting
ways—through their labor and tax payments from a state’s past illegitimate actions, then
and by obeying the law—and as result of these the victims of such injustices would have a
efforts, they may claim ownership in state strong claim to admission.
institutions and the benefits that flow from Although some commentators applaud
them. Collective ownership supplies citizens Pevnick for developing a more moder-
with a right to self-determination with respect ate position on immigration than many of
to these institutions, including a presumptive the other theorists who defend the right to
right to decide who will have access to them exclude, critics worry that his arguments
and the benefits they produce. Since access leave many questions unanswered. Pevnick
to state institutions is inextricably linked to contends that citizens develop ownership
access to territory, Pevnick concludes that col- claims in public institutions by contribut-
lective ownership claims include the right to ing to their creation and maintenance, and
exclude would-be immigrants. that these claims include a right to self-
Pevnick contends that liberal states con- determination with respect to these institu-
siderable discretion over immigration poli- tions, including the right to determine who
cies; however, he acknowledges that some will have access to them. Some critics doubt
would-be immigrants have moral claims that Pevnick’s theory can offer a satisfac-
to admission that outweigh the right to tory account of the extent of original citi-
exclude, and in such cases, states must grant zenship in a newly founded state (Hudson,
admission to these immigrants. Refugees, 2011). Others focus on his position on

187
Shelley Wilcox

undocumented immigrants, which, they The Freedom of Movement Argument


claim, commits him to circular view. For
instance, I point out that Pevnick’s associa- Proponents of the freedom of movement
tive ownership account seems to imply that argument maintain that the liberal commit-
undocumented immigrants, who also con- ment to liberty requires that states to recog-
tribute to public institutions in various ways, nize a basic right to freedom of international
have legitimate ownership claims in these movement. In his early work, Carens
institutions, and thus a corresponding right defends this view by arguing that each of
to help to choose the membership policies the three main theoretical approaches to
that apply to them. However, Pevnick denies liberalism—utilitarianism, liberal egali-
that undocumented immigrants have legiti- tarianism, and libertarianism—implies that
mate ownership claims in public institutions liberal states should maintain open borders
because, in his view, they entered the country (Carens, 1987). Of these approaches, Carens
without the consent of citizens. This, I sug- is most interested in Rawlsian egalitarian-
gest, commits his account to a problematic ism. According to his cosmopolitan reading
circularity, according to which the consent of Rawls, parties in the original position are
of citizens is necessary to establish a right charged with selecting global principles of
to self-determination (because consent is justice rather than domestic principles that
required for ownership and ownership sup- apply only within a particular state. Like
plies the right to self-determination) and the parties in the standard original position,
right to self-determination supplies citizens representatives in the global original posi-
with the right to consent (Wilcox, 2012). tion would choose a scheme of equal basic
liberties, prioritizing these freedoms over
other principles of justice. Importantly,
Carens contends, they would include a right
ARGUMENTS FOR OPEN BORDERS to freedom of international movement in
this scheme of basic liberties. Thus, since
Some liberal thinkers, most notably Carens, right to free international mobility includes
have raised a broad challenge to arguments the right to cross national borders, he con-
in favor of the state’s supposed right to cludes that liberal states should maintain
exclude immigrants. They argue that fun- open borders.
damental liberal principles, such as freedom More recently, Carens has developed a
and equality, entail not that liberal demo- version of the freedom of movement argu-
cratic states have broad authority to restrict ment that foregoes specifically Rawlsian
immigration, but rather that states have a concepts, drawing instead on the analogy
prima facie duty to maintain open borders. between domestic freedom of movement and
I will discuss two well-known lines of argu- international freedom of movement (Carens,
ment here. The first derives the duty to main- 1992). Liberals widely acknowledge domes-
tain open borders from the purported right tic freedom of movement as a basic right of
to freedom of international movement, and liberal citizenship. Carens argues that inter-
the second draws upon luck egalitarian ide- national freedom of movement is an equally
als to establish the duty to admit all would- important freedom because every reason
be immigrants. one might have for moving to a new state

188
IMMIGRATION AND BORDERS

within a particular country could also apply The freedom of movement argument has
to moving across national borders. To name been enormously influential. However, it has
just a few: also been subject to a number of forceful
objections. Some critics charge that Carens
one might want a job; one might fall in overstates the moral importance of free inter-
love with someone from another coun- national mobility, and thus fails to establish
try; one might belong to a religion that that freedom of international movement is a
has few adherents in one’s native state
genuine human right. One prominent formu-
and many in another; one may wish to
lation of this objection, developed by Miller,
pursue cultural opportunities that are
only available in another land (Carens, rests on the distinction between a basic inter-
1992, 28). est and a bare interest (Miller, 1995). On the
one hand, a basic interest refers something
that is vital to human well-being, such as the
Thus, since the same fundamental human means of subsistence, and thus warrants pro-
interests that support the case for consider- tection by a moral right. A bare interest, on
ing freedom of domestic movement to be a the other hand, is a legitimate interest, but
basic right also support the case for consid- is generally not important enough to deserve
ering freedom of international movement to such protection. Carens maintains that there
be a basic right, Carens concludes that liberal is no morally relevant difference between
states should respect the right to free inter- free domestic movement and free interna-
national mobility, opening their borders to tional movement; both satisfy basic human
would-be immigrants.5 interests. Miller acknowledges that people
Carens believes that the right to free- have a basic interest in free domestic move-
dom of international movement establishes ment, and he concedes that free international
a strong presumption for open borders. movement may also be a basic interest in
Nevertheless, he acknowledges that certain some cases, such as when immigration is the
limitations on immigration will sometimes only way to escape political persecution or
be justified. In his view, restrictions on par- avoid starvation. However, he insists that
ticular liberties, including freedom of inter- most of the world’s people have only a bare
national movement, are legitimate if they interest in freedom of international move-
are necessary to preserve those liberties in ment. Certainly, many people wish to move to
the long run. However, because such limita- another country in order to pursue economic
tions involve overriding a basic right, they opportunities there or to participate a culture
can be justified only by the weightiest of that does not exist in their home country.
reasons and only on the basis of rationales Yet as long they have an adequate range of
that are compatible with liberal commit- opportunities in their home country—that is,
ments. Given these considerations, Carens a reasonable choice of occupations, cultural
suggests that states may legitimately limit activities, and so on—then their interest in
immigration insofar as is necessary to main- free international movement does not war-
tain public order, ensure national ensure rant protection as a basic moral right. Thus,
national security, and protect liberal institu- Miller concludes, freedom of international
tions from erosion by immigrants with illib- movement is at best a remedial right of those
eral political values. persons whose basic rights cannot be secured

189
Shelley Wilcox

in their home country; it is not a basic human is to eliminate inequalities based on factors
right as Carens claims. attributable to brute luck.
The argument begins with the uncontro-
versial claim that the country into which one
is born is a matter of brute luck, just as one’s
THE LUCK EGALITARIAN ARGUMENT race or family wealth. Proponents then argue
that since global economic inequalities among
A second leading argument for open borders individuals are determined primarily by the
draws upon luck egalitarianism. Luck egali- countries into which they are born, these ine-
tarians maintain that distributive arrange- qualities are also attributable to brute luck. It
ments are just to the extent that they track follows, they claim, that justice requires elim-
the distinction between choice and luck.6 inating global economic inequalities among
More specifically, they argue that social individuals. Borders maintain such inequali-
benefits and burdens should be allocated ties by preventing individuals born in poor
on the basis of people’s responsible choices countries from accessing the opportunities
and not on the basis of circumstances over and social benefits available in affluent soci-
which they have no control. Distributive eties. Thus, the argument concludes, global
justice requires minimizing the effects of justice requires affluent societies to maintain
factors attributable to brute luck, such as open borders.
one’s race, native abilities, intelligence, and Some of the most prominent liberal advo-
the wealth of the family into which one is cates of the open borders position endorse
born, on the allocation of social benefits versions of the luck egalitarian argument.
and burdens. Thus, luck egalitarians tend to For instance, Carens condemns immigra-
endorse redistributive policies that involve tion restrictions as tantamount to a geo-
transferring social benefits from luck-ad- graphical caste system, in which national
vantaged persons to those disadvantaged by borders serve to protect and preserve the
bad brute luck. underserved wealth of affluent countries.
Most luck egalitarians are concerned with As he puts it, “[c]itizenship in Western lib-
justice within a single, democratic political eral democracies is the modern equivalent
community. However, cosmopolitan luck of feudal privilege—an inherited status that
egalitarians believe that a commitment to greatly enhances one’s life chances. Like feu-
moral equality entails that distributive prin- dal birthright privileges, restrictive citizen-
ciples should be applied globally, without ship is hard to justify when one thinks about
regard to political borders.7 In their view, it closely” (Carens, 1987, 252). Furthermore,
justice among citizens of different countries Carens argues, immigration restrictions can-
does not differ significantly from justice not be justified “on the grounds that those
among co-citizens; people have as strong born in a given territory or born of parents
distributive obligations to foreigners as who were citizens are more entitled to the
they have to their fellow citizens. The luck benefits of citizenship than those born else-
egalitarian argument for open borders draws where or born of alien parents. Birthplace
upon this cosmopolitan insight, together and parentage are natural contingencies that
with a commitment to luck equality, which are ‘arbitrary from a moral point of view’”
maintains that the goal of distributive justice (Carens, 1987, 261).

190
IMMIGRATION AND BORDERS

The luck egalitarian argument for open could admit. Thus, open borders would leave
borders successfully evades the most promi- much poverty unmitigated. Second, increased
nent objection to the freedom of interna- migration to affluent countries will not help
tional movement argument—namely, that the worst-off. Assuming that affluent coun-
free international movement is not a genu- tries may legitimately place some upper limit
ine human right. However, the argument has number of immigrants they admit, prospec-
been subject to a number of forceful objec- tive immigrants will have to compete for the
tions. Some critics, such as Wellman, contend available positions. Affluent countries are
that the argument overstates the normative likely to prefer immigrants with the skills,
force of luck equality (Wellman, 2008). To education, and native endowments that are
defend this claim, Wellman appeals to a perceived to be in the national interest. Since
familiar thought experiment comparing two the better-off are typically relatively advan-
cases of inequality. The first case, which rep- taged in terms of these characteristics, they
resents luck equality, includes two independ- are more likely to be admitted. This advan-
ent societies, A and B. Members of A are tage also extends to remittances. It is often
considerably better off than members of B, argued that remittances by those who have
but no one in either society is aware of the been admitted to and allowed to work in one
disparity between them. The second case, of the affluent countries help to ease poverty
which represents another form of equality, in their home country. While it is true that
relational equality, includes a single society, many immigrants send money home, the
C. Members of C are aware that some of families to whom this money is being sent are
their fellows are faring considerably better often among the more privileged in the poor
or worse than they are and these disparities country in question.
affect the relationships among them, render-
ing some individuals vulnerable to oppres-
sion. Wellman believes that the inequalities
in the second case are significantly more FEMINIST ARGUMENTS
troubling than those in the first. Thus, he
concludes, although moral claims generated Many of the feminist philosophers who have
by relational equality are stringent enough written on immigration also are critical of the
to outweigh the state’s interest in excluding mainstream arguments for open borders. In
immigrants, those generated by luck equality particular, they charge that these arguments
are not. fail to account for the gendered aspects of
Other critics of the luck egalitarian argu- immigration and the normative implica-
ment acknowledge that affluent states have tions that follow from these features. Thus,
weighty redistributive duties to outsiders, although they tend to support open borders
but deny that opening borders is an appro- policies, most feminist philosophers defend
priate way to fulfill these obligations. For these policies on alternative grounds.
instance, Pogge argues that migration will Early feminist philosophers of immigra-
not solve the problem of poverty, for two tion typically argue that formally gender-
reasons (Pogge, 2006). First, the number of neutral immigration restrictions often work
needy persons in the world far exceeds the to the detriment of women immigrants in
number of immigrants that affluent countries practice. For instance, I have argued that

191
Shelley Wilcox

recent US immigration admissions policies of women into the paid workforce, without
disproportionately disadvantage women corresponding increases in public provisions
migrants (Wilcox, 2005).8 During the 1980s for childcare or the redistribution of caring
and early 1990s, the United States enacted responsibilities between genders, has created
a series of legislation designed to limit the a high demand for paid domestic labor. In
entry of unskilled immigrants by shifting poor countries, the supply of domestic labor
the balance from family-based to employ- has been stimulated by a scarcity of well-pay-
ment-based immigration preferences, and by ing jobs and in many cases, a growing reli-
restructuring the latter to favor highly skilled ance on remittances. Cuts in public services
and well-educated immigrants. This legisla- in developing countries have also encouraged
tion is formally gender neutral in the sense women to migrate as a means for earning the
that it does not explicitly make distinctions income to pay for newly privatized services
on the basis of sex or gender. However, it for their children, such as healthcare and
disproportionately disadvantages women education.
migrants in practice because women com- Feminist critics of global care chains typi-
prise the majority of immigrants who enter cally argue that traditional theories of justice
on family reunification visas. Moreover, in have difficulty articulating the precise nature
the context of a society that devalues work of the harm that they produce. Most cosmo-
traditionally performed by women, laws politan theories of justice focus on unjust
aiming to exclude unskilled workers also dis- global distributions, but it is not clear that
proportionately disadvantage women labor care should be understood as a distributive
migrants in practice, since feminized lines of good. Other features of care chains also resist
work, such as childcare and domestic labor, traditional ethical evaluation. Careworkers
are typically considered to be unskilled. are not overtly coerced to migrate, and each
Many recent feminist arguments focus on party in the global care chain appears to
what theorists refer to as “global care chains” benefit from her participation: women who
(Hochschild, 2000, 2002, Kittay, 2008, 2009, employ migrant caregivers are able to pursue
Weir, 2008). These chains, which link women opportunities in the public sphere; migrant
around the world, are established through caregivers are able to send money home;
the transnational exchange of domestic serv- and their children and sending nations ben-
ices. Global care chains are often initiated efit economically from these remittances.
when relatively well-off northern or Western Migrant caregivers are uniquely vulnerable
women enter the paid labor force and hire to exploitation and workplace abuses, and
other women, usually poorer women from they and their children suffer from their long
developing countries, to care for their children absences. However, it could be argued that
and other dependents. Migrant careworkers each of these harms is counterbalanced by
often must leave their own children behind in significant gains (Kittay, 2008, 2009).
their home countries to be cared for by even Some feminists, such as Kittay and Weir,
poorer careworkers or family members who argue that a feminist ethics of care is bet-
may already have caregiving responsibilities ter suited to theorizing global care chains
or be engaged with paid labor. Many factors (Kittay, 2008, 2009, Weir, 2008). In particu-
have contributed to the production of global lar, care ethics emphasizes several key nor-
care chains. In wealthy countries, the entry mative features and practices that traditional

192
IMMIGRATION AND BORDERS

theories tend to overlook: concrete specificity; families to move freely across national bor-
acknowledgement of human dependence and ders. Ultimately, however, eliminating care
vulnerability; and a relational understanding chains will require restructuring the global
of the self. Care ethics focuses on the ethical economy so that no one is forced to leave her
significance of relationships formed through home country to find decent working and
dependency, such as those between caregiv- living conditions.10
ers and their charges. For instance, Kittay By including the unjust background con-
argues that intimate relationships between ditions that shape current migration flows
specific individuals, in which caring and in their analyses, feminist philosophers are
affection are the norm, play a vital role in able to offer nuanced normative recommen-
forming and sustaining individuals’ self-iden- dations concerning real-world immigration
tities. When these relationships are disrupted, policies. However, some critics may object
people suffer harm to their sense of self and to the nonideal theoretical methodologies
self-respect. It follows, she contends, that the that these analyses employ. To determine the
harm involved in global care chains lies in ways in which background injustices bear on
their threat to the core relationships that are immigration arrangements, feminists must
constitutive of self-identity. take certain features of the current, nonideal
To protect dependents and caregivers world as given, at least for the time being.
from the harms that are generated by frac- These features include the background injus-
tured relationships, Kittay believes the right tices that are relevant to immigration, such
to give and receive care should be recog- as sexist assumptions about value of care-
nized as a basic human right (Kittay, 2008, work and the relative importance of family
2009).9 However, she insists that the recogni- life and economic production. Feminists also
tion of a properly formulated right to care tacitly presuppose additional features of the
would not eliminate global care chains on current political landscape, such as a pre-
its own. Care chains will persist until care, sumptive right to regulate immigration. To
whether provided by professionals or within the extent that these assumptions preclude
family networks, is socially recognized and critical inquiry into the fundamental moral-
economically supported. Caregiving respon- ity of such features, critics contend, feminist
sibilities should also be more fairly distrib- arguments inadvertently contribute to the
uted between genders and paid work should legitimization of unjust arrangements.
be organized with the recognition that all
workers—male and female, rich and poor—
are responsible for providing care. Unlocking
care chains will also require mitigating the CONCLUSION
unjust background conditions that force
women to choose between providing finan- As globalization has intensified, the ethical
cial support for their families and being with issues raised by global migration have become
and providing face-to-face care for them. increasing urgent. Philosophers of immigra-
However, open immigration policies will also tion have helped to clarify these issues and
play an important role. To begin, specific to chart a normative course toward their suc-
open borders provisions should be adopted cessful resolution. Their efforts have broad-
to make it easier for careworkers and their ened the discipline of political philosophy,

193
Shelley Wilcox

directing us away from questions pertain- to exclude in her recent survey of the debate
ing solely to the nation-state, toward those (Fine, 2013).
5
Philip Cole offers an alternative version argu-
that arise within global contexts. In doing
ment of freedom of international movement
so, philosophers of immigration challenge argument. In his view, acknowledging the right
many of the core assumptions in political to exit any state as a core liberal right commits
philosophy—for instance, that territorial one to recognizing a corresponding right to
borders are morally justified—while joining freedom of international movement because
without a right to enter and settle in a new
forces with other theorists of global justice to
state, the right to exit is useless (Cole, 2000).
develop persuasive accounts of our duties to 6
Rawls’s work initiated the contemporary dis-
outsiders. cussion of the role of luck in theories of justice.
Prominent luck egalitarians include Arneson
(1989, 1999, 2000, 2001, 2006), Cohen
Notes (2000, 2008, 2011), Dworkin (2000, 2002,
2003), Tan (2008, 2012), and Tempkin (1993,
1
Other questions concern what states owe to 2003a,b).
refugees (see Shacknove, 1985, Dummett,
7
Cosmopolitan luck egalitarians include Beitz
2001, Kukathas, 2002, Benhabib, 2004, (1979), Caney (2005), and Tan (2008, 2012).
Gibney, 2004, Nine, 2010) and non-citizen
8
See also Narayan (1995).
residents, including guestworkers and
9
See also Weir (2008).
undocumented immigrants (see Bauböck,
10
The previous summary of feminist approaches
1994, Dummett, 2001, Wilcox, 2004, 2005, to migration draws upon Parekh and Wilcox
Bosniak, 2006, Miller, 2008, Shachar, 2009, (2014).
Pevnick, 2011); what selection criteria states
may legitimately use to guide admissions
policies (see Carens, 1988, Joppke, 2005,
Miller, 2005, Wilcox, 2007, 2008, 2014, WORKS CITED
Wellman, 2008, Blake, 2012); and what
states may require of immigrants seeking citi-
zenship (Wilcox, 2004). These philosophers Arneson, R. J. (1989), “Equality and Equal
consider these questions within the context of Opportunity for Welfare,” Philosophical
liberal democratic states, asking, for instance, Studies, 56: 77–93.
whether such states can legitimately refuse — (1999), “Egalitarianism and
to admit would-be immigrants who are com-
mitted to illiberal political values. However,
Responsibility,” Journal of Ethics, 3:
many of these issues also arise with regard to 225–247.
non-liberal states. For instance, philosophers — (2000), “Luck Egalitarianism and
may be interested in the ethics of guest- Prioritarianism,” Ethics, 110: 339–349.
worker programs in China or Qatar. — (2001), “Luck and Equality,” Proceedings
2
The previous summary of Walzer’s view draws
upon Wilcox (2009).
of Aristotelian Society, 75: 73–90.
3
Some critics also reject Walzer’s claim that — (2006), “Luck Egalitarianism:
clubs are morally free to choose any member- An Interpretation and Defense,”
ship policy they wish. See Cole (2000) and Philosophical Topics, 32: 1–20.
Higgins (2013). Bauböck, R. (1994), Transnational
4
For a third, liberal nationalist version of the
self-determination argument, see Miller (1995).
Citizenship: Membership and Rights
Fine provides an excellent overview of the in International Migration. Aldershot:
self-determination arguments for the right Edward Elgar.

194
IMMIGRATION AND BORDERS

Beitz, C. (1979), Political Theory and Philosophy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton


International Relations. Princeton, NJ: University Press.
Princeton University Press. Cole, P. (2000), Philosophies of
Benhabib, S. (2004), The Rights of Exclusion: Liberal Political Theory and
Others Asylum, Residents and Citizens. Immigration. Edinburgh: Edinburgh
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. University Press.
Blake, M. (2012), “Immigration, Dummett, M. (2001), On Immigration
Association, and Antidiscrimination,” and Refugees. London and New York:
Ethics, 122: 748–762. Routledge.
Bosniak, L. (2006), The Citizen and the Dworkin, R. (2000), Sovereign Virtue.
Alien: Dilemmas of Contemporary Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Membership. Princeton, NJ: Princeton — (2002), “Sovereign Virtue Revisited,”
University Press. Ethics, 113: 106–143.
Caney, S. (2005), Justice Beyond Borders: A — (2003), “Equality, Luck and Hierarchy,”
Global Political Theory. Oxford: Oxford Philosophy and Public Affairs, 31:
University Press. 190–198.
Carens, J. (1987), “Aliens and Citizens: The Fine, S. (2010), “Freedom of Association is
Case for Open Borders,” The Review of Not the Answer,” Ethics, 120: 338–356.
Politics, 49: 251–273. — (2013), “The Ethics of Immigration: Self-
— (1988), “Nationalism and the Exclusion Determination and the Right to Exclude,”
of Immigrants: Lessons from Australian Philosophy Compass, 8: 254–268.
Immigration Policy,” in M. Gibney (ed.), Gibney, M. (2004), The Ethics and Politics
Open Borders, Closed Societies, The of Asylum: Liberal Democracy and
Ethical and Political Issues. Westport, the Response to Refugees. Cambridge:
CA: Greenwood Press, pp. 41–60. Cambridge University Press.
— (1992), “Migration and Morality: Higgins, P. (2013), Immigration Justice.
A Liberal Egalitarian Perspective,” Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
in B. Barry and R. Goodin (eds), Hochschild, A. R. (2000), “Global Care
Free Movement: Ethical Issues in the Chains and Emotional Surplus Value,”
Transnational Migration of People and in W. Hutton and A. Giddens (eds),
of Money. University Park, PA: The On the Edge: Living with Global
Pennsylvania State Press, pp. 25–47. Capitalism. London: Jonathan Cape,
Cavallero, E. (2014), “Association and pp. 131–146.
Asylum,” Philosophical Studies, 169: — (2002), “Love and Gold,” in B.
133–141. Ehrenreich and A. R. Hochschild (eds),
Cohen, G. A. (2000), If You’re An Global Woman: Nannies, Maids and
Egalitarian, How Come You’re So Rich? Sex Workers in the New Economy. New
Cambridge: Harvard University Press. York: Metropolitan Books, pp. 15–30.
— (2008), Rescuing Justice and Equality. Hudson, J. (2011), Review of Immigration
Cambridge: Harvard University Press. and the Constraints of Justice: Between
— (2011), On the Currency of Egalitarian Borders and Absolute Sovereignty,
Justice and Other Essays in Political by Ryan Pevnick, Notre Dame

195
Shelley Wilcox

Philosophical Reviews: https://ndpr. Borders and Absolute Sovereignty. New


nd.edu/news/24785-immigration-and- York: Cambridge University Press.
the-constraints-of-justice-between-open- Pogge, T. (2006), “Migration and Poverty,”
borders-and-absolute-sovereignty/. in R. Goodin and P. Pettit (eds),
Joppke, C. (2005), Selecting by Origin: Contemporary Political Philosophy: An
Ethnic Migration in the Liberal State. Anthology, 2nd edn. Oxford: Blackwell,
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University pp. 710–720.
Press. Shachar, A. (2009), The Birthright Lottery:
Kittay, E. (2008), “The Global Heart Citizenship and Global Inequality.
Transplant and Caring across national Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Boundaries,” The Southern Journal of Press.
Philosophy, 46: 138–165. Shacknove, A. (1985), “Who Is a Refugee?”
— (2009), “The Moral Harm of Migrant Ethics, 95: 274–284.
Carework: Realizing a Global Right to Tan, K.-C. (2008), “A Defense of Luck
Care,” Philosophical Topics, 37: 53–73. Egalitarianism,” Journal of Philosophy,
Kukathas, C. (2002), “Immigration,” in H. 105: 665–690.
LaFollette (ed.), The Oxford Handbook — (2012), Justice, Institutions, and Luck:
of Practical Ethics. New York: Oxford The Site, Ground and Scope of Equality.
University Press, pp. 567–590. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Miller, D. (1995), On Nationality. Oxford: Temkin, L. (1993), Inequality. New York:
Clarendon Press. Oxford University Press.
— (2005), “Immigration: The Case for — (2003a), “Egalitarianism Defended,”
Limits,” in A. Cohen and C. H. Wellman Ethics, 113: 764–782.
(eds), Contemporary Debates in Applied — (2003b), “Exploring the Roots of
Ethics. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 193–206. Egalitarian Concerns,” Theoria, 69:
— (2008), “Immigrants, Nations, and 125–151.
Citizenship,” The Journal of Political Walzer, M. (1983), Spheres of Justice: A
Philosophy, 16: 371–390. Defense of Pluralism and Equality. New
Narayan, U. (1995), “‘Male-Order’ Brides: York: Basic Books.
Immigrant Women, Domestic Violence, Weir, A. (2008), “Global Care Chains:
and Immigration Law,” Hypatia, 10: Freedom, Responsibility and Solidarity,”
101–119. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 46:
Nine, C. (2010), “Ecological Refugees, States 166–175.
Borders, and the Lockean Proviso,” Journal Wellman, C. H. (2008), “Immigration and
of Applied Philosophy, 27: 359–375. Freedom of Association,” Ethics, 119:
Parekh McGushin, S. and Wilcox, S. (2014), 109–141.
“Feminist Perspectives on Globalization,” Wellman, C. H. and Cole, P. (2011),
The Stanford Encyclopedia of Debating the Ethics of Immigration: Is
Philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/ There a Right to Exclude? New York:
archives/sum2014/entries/feminism- Oxford University Press.
globalization/. Wilcox, S. (2004), “Culture, National
Pevnick, R. (2011), Immigration and the Identity, and Admission to Citizenship,”
Constraints of Justice: Between Open Social Theory and Practice, 30: 559–583.

196
IMMIGRATION AND BORDERS

— (2005), “American Neo-Nativism and a Globalized World. Amherst, NY:


Gendered Immigrant Exclusions,” in B. Humanity Books, pp. 53–74.
Andrew, J. Keller, and L. Schwartzman — (2009), “The Open Borders Debate on
(eds), Feminist Interventions in Ethics Immigration,” Philosophy Compass, 4: 1–9.
and Politics: Feminist Ethics and Social — (2012), Review of Immigration and the
Theory. Lanham, MA: Rowman & Constraints of Justice: Between Borders
Littlefield, pp. 213–232. and Absolute Sovereignty, by Ryan
— (2007), “Immigrant Admissions and Pevnick, Ethics, 122: 617–622.
Global Relations of Harm,” Journal of — (2014), “Do Duties to Outsiders Require
Social Philosophy, 38: 274–291. Open Borders? A Reply to Wellman,”
— (2008), “Who Pays for Gender Philosophical Studies, 169: 123–132;
De-Institutionalization?” in A. M. article initially appeared as 10.1007/
González (ed.), Gender Identities in s11098-012-9902-y in 2012.

197
13
THE FUTURE(S) OF POLITICAL
PHILOSOPHY
Matthew Voorhees and J. Jeremy Wisnewski

INTRODUCTION philosophy is a guessing game, and one that


is likely to be characterized by a good deal of
Everyone knows that predictions can be wishful thinking.1
wildly mistaken. From Margaret Thatcher’s Could Plato have anticipated work in
proclamation that she would not live to see a political philosophy concerned with, for
female Prime Minister in Britain to Einstein’s example, the role of the internet and social
claim that nuclear power is impossible, we media in fostering a deliberative democracy?
get things wrong—and often with gusto. This Could Locke have predicted the current
seems to be true across the board, but per- debate over intellectual property, or Hobbes
haps nowhere near so visibly as in the acad- the debate over the use of public funds for
emy—and within the academy, predicting the stem cell research? These rhetorical ques-
future of philosophy is perhaps as dubious tions point to the central limitation on any
an enterprise as one is likely to find. prediction we might offer: Political philos-
Kant claimed to have solved the crucial ophy, at least in part, must respond to the
problems of philosophy. Not so many years world in which it finds itself. To predict its
later, Hegel claimed the same thing, pro- future accurately would thus require predict-
nouncing an end to the history of philoso- ing the future of the world itself—its chang-
phy. In the following century, oblivious to ing social arrangements, technological feats
the errors of his predecessors, Wittgenstein and challenges, and emerging issues. We can-
once again claimed to end philosophy—and not possibly hope to do that here, or frankly,
he had the audacity to claim to end it on two anywhere else.
different occasions, in two different ways. Our aim in what follows is thus a more
It will come as no surprise, then, that the modest one. While we cannot know the
following is in one respect a work of con- future(s) of political philosophy, we can
ceit. No one can say with any certainty what highlight areas of emerging and continuing
the future of an academic discipline will be. interest, as they appear at this particular his-
Sometimes forecasters get things right, but torical moment in time, from our particu-
such success is usually a matter of luck. To lar points of view. This does not mean that
undertake to describe the future(s) of political we have only our hunches to go on. Recent

199
Matthew Voorhees and J. Jeremy Wisnewski

computer software makes it possible to iden- questions, certain kinds of analysis, as well
tify broad patterns in political philosophy by as certain historical figures over others. In an
algorithmically examining academic data- attempt to limit our own theoretical biases,
bases (such as JSTOR). We have used such we opted to utilize a well-established aca-
software in our attempt to identify trends in demic resource: JSTOR. The journals avail-
publications over the past two decades. This able through JSTOR are some of the most
sort of technology-driven empirical research, visible in political philosophy and polit-
on the rise in recent years, may itself become ical theory, and thus represent some of the
more common in the future. Our approach favored sources for many working in the
is thus largely descriptive rather than pre- field. Utilizing JSTOR also provided a rela-
scriptive. There are certainly areas that we tively accessible source for data on publish-
think ought to be explored in the future. Our ing trends over the last two decades.3
task, however, is to describe those areas that There are obvious limitations to both the
seem likely to be important in years to come. number of journals we chose to examine, as
Because political philosophy itself reflects well as the range of topics typically treated
and speaks to events in the political world, in these journals. Much excellent work in
we should expect certain questions and political philosophy is published in ven-
problems to be more prominent than others. ues not available through JSTOR—indeed,
Issues involving cosmopolitanism, diversity, some might even argue that most truly excel-
democratic politics, surveillance, cyber con- lent work is found elsewhere. Nevertheless,
flict, and human rights are sure to garner the the high visibility of the journals in JSTOR
attention of philosophers and political theo- makes it a good resource for examining what
rists in the future. The extent to which any is happening in mainstream political philoso-
of these issues gains prominence, of course, phy, even if the snapshot provided does not
depends on a variety of factors, including the allow us to see what is happening in the dis-
important challenges faced by higher educa- cipline as a whole.
tion: budget cuts, legislative pressures, and There is of course nothing magical about
the apparent rise of online courses. We con- the number of journals chosen. We might have
sider some of these issues at the end of this just as easily chosen 30 high-quality journals,
chapter. or we might have chosen only 5. Despite
only examining six journals, these journals
nevertheless span work in both historical
and contemporary political philosophy, both
THE LAST 20 YEARS Anglo-American and “continental” tradi-
tions, and include venues publishing work in
In an attempt to assess the future(s) of pol- critical race theory and feminist philosophy.
itical philosophy in a way that is grounded There will undoubtedly be many who find
in the state of the discipline, we endeavored the list inadequate. There is a straightfor-
to analyze the publication record of six lead- ward reason for this: the list is inadequate,
ing journals in political philosophy over the as any list must be. Political philosophy is a
past two decades.2 Obviously, deciding on a wide river, and excellent research appears in
list of journals is itself a political undertak- a wide variety of venues. Important articles
ing. Journals tend to favor certain kinds of sometimes appear in journals that are less

200
THE FUTURE(S) OF POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY

well-known, or in well-known journals that appeared frequently.8 Work on the history


do not focus on political theory. Moreover, of political philosophy frequently dealt with
much important work in political philosophy the social contract tradition—with Hobbes,
is done in scholarly monographs (rather than Locke, and Rousseau. Mill and Nietzsche
articles). For all of these reasons, the results also appeared with greater frequency than
we report here are tentative at best. They other notables from the history of philoso-
represent the simple fact that any sampling, phy (e.g. Montesquieu, Cicero). Judging by
by definition, will be selective. Nevertheless, word counts within topics, at least three top-
while selectivity encourages recognizing the ics crucially involved the history of political
fallibility of one’s results, it need not entail philosophy (9, 13, 14). Of the topics gener-
inaccuracy. ated by the program, two centered on issues
We collected articles for the previous related to sex, gender, and race (8, 10).9 This
20 years from six journals available through is perhaps a product of the inclusion of the
JSTOR. We then utilized the program journal Hypatia in our set of six journals,
MALLET4 to produce some basic algorith- and likely does not reflect the actual percent-
mic topic modeling. We set our topic list at age of work being done on these topics (it
20. MALLET then analyzed our collection of might be more or less, depending on one’s
texts and generated topics—a list of which sample). Nevertheless, given the reasons for
can be found in Appendix A. The term “topic” using JSTOR journals given earlier, the result
is standard in these kinds of approaches to is still rather significant: critical race theory
textual analysis, though the term “discourse” and feminist political philosophy have made
might in fact be better. As a quick look at advances toward entering the mainstream.
Appendix A will show, a “topic” in this con- Likewise, work in applied political philoso-
text is a set of terms used together in pre- phy appears to be rather healthy: issues
dictable ways. As Ted Underwood suggests, regarding labor practices, political par-
“The great thing about topic modeling is ties, egalitarian social policies, welfare, and
that it maps the actual discursive contours of healthcare were significant enough to gener-
a collection, which may or may not line up ate two topics roughly devoted to such areas
with ‘concepts’ any writer ever consciously of interest (15, 18).
held in mind.”5 In this respect, the “topics” In what follows, we will make some edu-
generated by MALLET are often orthogonal cated guesses about the future of political
to the standard topics we talk about in politi- philosophy, drawing on the analysis we have
cal philosophy. utilized where appropriate to contextualize
As one might expect, automated analy- our claims.
sis often produces messy results. Common
terms are linked with topics in multiple
ways, and the links are not always useful (the
term “moral,” e.g. appears in 5 of the 20 top- POLITICAL THOUGHT: APPROACHES
ics; “university” appears in 66). The data, as AND CONCERNS
usual, require interpretation.7
The topics that resulted from the analy- To undertake a philosophical endeavor, in
sis were in many ways predictable: liberal- one respect, is to work out one’s relation-
ism, justice, and Rawls, as one might expect, ship with the past. The great questions of

201
Matthew Voorhees and J. Jeremy Wisnewski

previous generations are, with stunning fre- political thought. For example, as we discuss
quency, very similar to the questions we find later, Rawlsian scholars continue to develop
ourselves confronting. It is thus not surpris- his ideas and bring them to bear on new
ing that traditions develop in all of the fields questions and political concerns. Postcolonial
of philosophy—that any general philosoph- thinkers will continue to explore the leg-
ical area will have its own historical conver- acies of colonial rule and the challenges of
sations and trajectories, and that one will be national sovereignty in developing coun-
called upon to respond to this tradition to tries. Of course, it is a mistake to think of
the extent that one decides to ask such ques- the study of political philosophy in either/or
tions at all. categories, as if political thought is historical,
The future of political philosophy, we or proscriptive, or critical; such approaches
thus have reason to believe, will not involve are neither discrete nor mutually exclusive.
abandoning its past. There is little doubt Thus, for example, feminist interrogations of
that Hobbes will still be read and responded canonical texts and authors promise to shed
to even as the central positions in political important light on the history of political
philosophy evolve in a way that reflects the ideas and to guide our critical reexamination
changing social and political reality around of core political concepts. In light of the dif-
us. This stands to reason. The history of phi- ferent approaches to the study of political
losophy provides the background against ideas, it therefore might make more sense to
which certain questions make sense, certain think about the future of political philosophy
answers can be given, and certain objec- in terms of areas of concern that are likely
tions raised. In this respect, asking about the to be approached from a variety of theoret-
future of political philosophy involves asking ical or methodological perspectives. These
not only what will be different from the past, areas themselves overlap in interesting and
but also how the past itself will be dealt with, important ways. Three areas seem especially
appropriated, and utilized. Thus we expect promising.
that scholars will continue to be interested in One area of political philosophy that
historical approaches to political philosophy, is generating scholarly interest and spur-
and to illuminate the ways in which political ring vigorous debate concerns the global
ideas reflect their historical and cultural con- and international dimension of politics. We
texts. Of course, such historical approaches expect that cosmopolitanism will continue
are not cut off from contemporary con- to be an important area of scholarly con-
troversies and concerns; if anything, these cern in the years to come. What many schol-
approaches help us better understand the ars see as the hegemony of Neoliberalism
ways in which contemporary political philos- has linked the political and economic fates
ophy is itself an outgrowth of and response of the Western and developing worlds, and
to the practical problems and questions that although the nation-state remains the pri-
animate contemporary politics. mary location of sovereignty and citizen-
However, the history of political thought is ship, political theorists are increasingly
but one of the many approaches available to attuned to the political and economic dimen-
scholars; proscriptive and critical approaches sion of core political concepts at the global
associated with particular authors or polit- level. Cosmopolitan approaches to political
ical projects will continue to be essential to thought are prompting important new ways

202
THE FUTURE(S) OF POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY

of rethinking political institutions so as to A growing sensitivity to the political claims


understand both the possibilities and the of the First Nations has been particularly
challenges of global governance, and these noticeable in Canada, informing the work of
approaches suggest significant revisions to a range of important political thinkers (see
Westphalian conceptions of sovereignty Taylor, 1994, Kymlicka, 1995, Tully, 1995).
that are necessary if we are to envision the However, pluralism and multiculturalism
conditions of international political institu- are also becoming important in countries—
tions. As the political and economic forces especially in, but by no means limited to,
that shape our lives become more global and Europe—that have not had the same history
trans-national in scope, so must the concepts of internal cultural diversity but which are
through which we examine and understand increasingly developing such diversity due to
these forces. As such, cosmopolitan political immigration and the legacy of colonialism.
thought promises to make important con- The insights of postcolonial and non-West-
tributions to a wide range of related topics: ern theorists are likely to figure prominently
the possibilities of global justice and ethical as these debates unfold.
judgment, concerns about global inequalities, Finally, we expect that democratic theory
the promises and limitations of human rights will continue to generate significant schol-
discourses, and the meaning of democratic arly interest. The waves of popular protests
citizenship and institutions. across the Middle East and the implications
A second ongoing area of scholarly inter- of these protests for the potential democra-
est concerns questions about inclusion, tization of political institutions in the region
exclusion, and difference as political com- will raise important questions about popular
munities become increasingly pluralistic and sovereignty, democratic deliberation, and civil
multicultural—or in some cases, increasingly society, and political philosophy has much
recognize the ways in which they already to contribute to these questions. In addition
are pluralistic and multicultural. Scholars to Rawls, Habermas remains an important
working in feminist, critical race, and queer touchstone for democratic theorists, who
theory have long sought to problematize continue to show interest both in working
the overly tidy distinction between public out the details of his ideal speech situation
and private that characterizes liberal poli- and in translating the formal conditions that
tics and have helpfully questioned liberal- guide his theory into concrete institutions
ism’s universalist pretensions. We have no and practices. Additionally—and particularly
reason to doubt that the insights of scholars in the context of formal political institutions
in these traditions will continue to inform that do not privilege democratic accountabil-
discussions about difference and inclu- ity—the role of civil society in locating and
sion, and to help us theorize more inclusive fostering forms of democratic deliberation
approaches to politics that are both sensitive promises to be an especially important area
to the demands of equality and alert to the of democratic thought. In this area of politi-
dangers of essentialism. Much recent work cal philosophy, we can clearly see the ways
on multicultural politics has been done by in which the future directions and topics of
scholars in countries with long (although by political philosophy are inextricably linked.
no means unblemished) histories of cultural For example, feminist and critical race schol-
diversity, like the United States and Canada. ars continue to highlight the ways in which

203
Matthew Voorhees and J. Jeremy Wisnewski

ideal speech conditions reflect privileged where—unlike many other Western democ-
forms of discourse and serve the interest of racies—such reconciliation remains politi-
those who use these forms. Cosmopolitan cally contentious. In the years following the
theorists raise questions about the qualities publication of A Theory of Justice, and with
of, and opportunities for democratic citizen- Rawls’s various amplifications and restate-
ship in an increasingly globalized politics: ments of that project in his subsequent work,
How can citizens take action on problems a sizeable and vigorous scholarly debate has
that are global in their scope and implica- developed and it shows no real signs of slow-
tions? To what extent are international insti- ing down. We have little reason to doubt that
tutions and governmental bodies responsive scholars associated with the Rawlsian project
to citizens’ input? How might we conceive of will continue to refine, develop, and extend
civil society in a cosmopolitan context? The his core arguments.
important questions in democratic theory will Of course, Rawls’s project has—and
benefit from a robust exchange among vari- doubtless will continue to have—its crit-
ous philosophical schools and approaches. ics and detractors, and the development of
Rawlsian scholarship will likely be driven
in large part by these critiques and the
responses to them. One particular area of cri-
THE RAWLS INDUSTRY tique has been especially important and will
likely continue to drive Rawls scholarship.
It is a truism in the United States that John Although Rawls explicitly contextualizes his
Rawls reinvigorated political philosophy— project within what he call the “fact of rea-
that he pulled it, barely alive, from the death sonable pluralism,” we expect that scholars
grips of positivism. This is undoubtedly an will continue to debate the compatibility of
overstatement, but one that contains a par- Rawlsian liberalism (and no doubt, liberal-
ticular truth. Few books have had the kind ism more generally) with robustly pluralistic
of influence that A Theory of Justice had. and multicultural societies. Feminist and crit-
Rawls continues to hold a prominent place ical race scholars have long drawn attention
in political philosophy and theory, and there to the ways in which the “veil of ignorance”
is little reason to think that this will change which grounds Rawls’s social contract the-
in the near future. This prominence speaks ory serves to bracket precisely those kinds of
to the general ascendency of liberal democ- embodied experience that such critics insist
racy as both a practical ideal and a theoreti- must be central to an inclusive view of equal-
cal commitment; not surprisingly, the words ity and justice. Rawls’s view of the original
“Rawls” and “Rawlsian” appeared most position thus reiterates the difference blind-
frequently in the topic associated with lib- ness of classical liberalism at a time when
eralism and justice (topic 5 in our MALLET critiques of formal equality are increasingly
analysis). Rawls’s attempt to reconcile clas- gaining ground.10 Rather than representing
sical liberalism’s emphasis on individual a vision of justice that is compatible with
liberty with a vision of justice which privi- a variety of particular conceptions of the
leges economic equality and the welfare state good (what Rawls refers to as “comprehen-
remains an attractive project to many politi- sive doctrines”), such scholars suggest that
cal thinkers, particularly in the United States Rawls’s conception of justice turns on a kind

204
THE FUTURE(S) OF POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY

of liberalism that itself functions as a com- theoretical work. This reflects an underly-
prehensive doctrine—one which precludes ing reality: namely, the topics that will inter-
the meaningful inclusion of racial, sexual, est political philosophers will be those that
and cultural difference (see Pateman, 1988, present themselves as the most pressing con-
Okin, 1994, Abbey, 2007). cerns of the day.
A second area of critique of Rawlsian This can be illustrated by consider-
thought—one which we only mention ing the state of research on the ethics and
here—has to do with the relevance of his politics of torture. Prior to 2002, ethics
theory of justice to the increasingly inter- research on torture was quite rare. Some
national and cosmopolitan dimensions of work was of course done on the histori-
politics. Although Rawls has attempted to cal arguments given for torture, as well
handle some of these dimensions in his later as the position various philosophers had
work, many continue to find his account taken on the practice. Nearly no one was
problematic (see Reidy, 2004). This may investigating why torture was wrong, and
speak to some of the broader difficulties even fewer were arguing that it was in
of applying classical liberalism’s under- fact acceptable in particular instances.11
standing of citizenship and government to When torture came forcefully into pub-
global political practices and institutions, lic view during the Bush administration,
but in light of the continued prominence of things changed dramatically. In the years
Rawls’s political thought, and the growing during and since the Bush administration,
importance of international political institu- many academic books and dozens of arti-
tions; we expect this to be a robust area of cles have been published on torture—some
scholarly debate. defending its use, some claiming that it
is never acceptable. A relative silence has
been replaced with what becomes a highly
technical and nuanced debate about nearly
APPLIED POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY every aspect of torture—what it is, when it
might be used, how one is to understand its
Political theory has never been shy about effects on persons, its relationship to state
weighing in on the issues of the day. Plato authority, what it reveals about the nature
made arguments about the legitimacy of cen- of pain, and so on. Had someone written
sorship, the proper role of education, the dis- this chapter in 2000, it seems doubtful that
tribution of wealth, and much more besides. this explosion of work would have been
It would be quite surprising if this traditional predicted. It is even doubtful that it could
occupation of political philosophers ceased have been predicted.12
being an area of intense theoretical work. A Our current political predicaments may
core question, of course, concerns which top- thus not be much indication of what theo-
ics are likely to be of interest in the future. It’s retical interests will occupy the attention of
quite difficult to ignore those topics that are future philosophers. Certain current topics
currently of much interest: intellectual prop- nevertheless seem to merit some attention,
erty, domestic spying, privacy, income ine- simply given the extent to which they have
quality, torture, and the relationship between garnered the attention of theoretical work in
money and politics are all ripe for continued recent years. In what is sometimes called “the

205
Matthew Voorhees and J. Jeremy Wisnewski

digital age,” it is hardly surprising to find (Lynn, 2010, 2011). Given the resources
that several current topics in political phi- being poured into developing both cyber
losophy have been on the rise. Surveillance weapons and defenses against those weap-
has been much in the news in the United ons, it is likely that this thoroughly contem-
States (and elsewhere) recently, and has been porary form of conflict will be of increasing
at the heart of a good deal of public debate. importance in the future. It is thus reason-
The extent to which citizens are entitled to able to suspect that political philosophy will
private lives—and the extent to which our become increasingly concerned with under-
activities are to be understood as part of standing it—what it is, when it is justified (if
these private lives—will likely continue to be ever), how it relates to traditional just war
the subject of intense debate in coming years. doctrine (if it does), and how current inter-
The ability to collect information about citi- national law applies to it. A fair amount of
zens is at an all-time high—one that makes work has emerged on this topic in recent
Foucault’s panopticon seem more prescient years. It is likely that the energy devoted to
than ever. The subsequent use of this infor- these topics will only increase.13
mation in planning things like unmanned Events of the recent past have also pro-
drone strikes makes the issue of surveillance duced new work on issues involving terror-
much more pressing. Indeed, the increased ism, income inequality, and the relationship
use of remote combat by governments like between religion (in particular, Islam) and
the United States has already sparked a good politics. The continuing relevance of these
deal of public debate. Political philosophy issues suggests that work in applied politi-
has followed suit. As this debate continues cal philosophy will continue to be devoted to
in the public sphere, it is likely that increased their exploration and elaboration.14
attention will be paid to the theoretical issues
underlying the use of these technologies, as
well as the arguments used both in favor of
and against them. REALITY CHECK: THE DIMINUTION
The digital age has also spawned what has OF POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY IN
come to be known as “cyberwarfare”: the use CONTEMPORARY CULTURE
of computer software for spying, hijacking,
destroying, or disrupting those computing The issue of the future of political philoso-
systems essential to the operations (mili- phy is not simply an issue of what topics
tary, commercial, and otherwise) of a given will be explored, or what theoretical devel-
country. The US Department of Defense has opments we should expect to see. The ques-
recognized this venue as another theater of tion of the future of political philosophy is
conflict (or “operational domain,” as the also a question about the place political phi-
Pentagon has called it), and has established losophy will come to occupy in our cultural
a formal organization (US Cyber Command) conversations.
to counter cyber attacks—attacks that have In the United States, things do not look
been increasing exponentially in recent years. good. The most common political philoso-
According to the US Deputy Secretary of phy explicitly appealed to by those in gov-
Defense, William J. Lynn III, “the danger of ernment appears to be that of novelist Ayn
cyberwarfare rivals that of traditional war” Rand, the patron saint of the US “Tea Party.”

206
THE FUTURE(S) OF POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY

The standards of argumentation and reason- deliberations of legislative, executive, and


ing that professional philosophers maintain judicial bodies—such as is the case in times
find little accommodation in current politi- when political theory is held in ill-repute—
cal discourse. Persons appeal to their favored the very point of political philosophy seems
first principles, and seem to regard such to be called into question.
appeal as ultimately simply a matter of pref- Consider the following: if we can have no
erence. Grand-standing about the validity of hope that political philosophy might have
particular principles thus appears to coexist some affect on political reality, even if quite
with a strange subjectivism about the justi- indirect, what is the point in engaging in it?
fication of these first principles. Appeals to The issue is more pressing in the case of pol-
evidence are present, but it is often an appeal itical philosophy, perhaps, than in other areas
to evidence reminiscent of the sophistic tradi- of philosophy. There may well be a point to
tions rather than the philosophical ones: one studying Platonic dialogues regardless of
appeals to what helps the conclusions one their applicability to modern day problems.
wants, and ignores whatever evidence does But presumably an investigation of justice,
not (see MacIntyre, 1981). or legitimate authority, or power, has as its
Could political philosophy play a role in aim more than merely comprehension and
the legislative bodies of the United States? the improvement of one’s analytical skills.
Our faith in this possibility is by no means Presumably one attempts to construct a the-
high at present—but it is at least a possibil- ory of justice, for example, in order to con-
ity. In many respects, the future of political tribute to the construction of a just society
philosophy will be determined alongside the (even if only indirectly). If political philoso-
role that political philosophy plays in a given phy has no bearing on our political future,
culture. The more value a culture places in then it will itself have no future—save being
political theorizing, the more resources it will a boutique hobby for intellectuals who are
place in fostering and maintaining a robust predisposed to considering its themes. In
political discourse. The less such things are this respect, the future(s) of political phil-
valued, the less we should expect to see osophy are connected in certain fundamen-
political theory in a state of relative health. tal ways with how political philosophy is
There have been historical instances in which perceived—as well as used and abused—by
political philosophy was prized by the politi- both the general public and those in the halls
cal leadership or by the populace at large. In of power.
such contexts, it will come as no surprise, we The issue of the perception of political
discover some of the most fruitful and lasting philosophy looms large in recent events in
contributions to political philosophy. higher education as well. For political phil-
This point has an immediate bearing on osophy to make any significant impact, we
the question of the future of research in polit- require a culture characterized by a literacy
ical philosophy. First, the esteem in which of political theory. The chances of creating
a culture holds any intellectual pursuit will such a culture seem increasingly endangered
partially determine the resources it devotes by developments in higher education. Two
to that enterprise, and also the number of major issues worth considering in the cur-
persons drawn to it. Second, if political rent context are (1) budget cuts in traditional
philosophy has no bearing on the political areas of humanities research and (2) the rise

207
Matthew Voorhees and J. Jeremy Wisnewski

of “MOOCs”—massive open-enrollment in both the quality and the diversity of polit-


online courses. ical theorizing. The core issue here is not that
It would be foolish to think that these one can watch Sandel’s lectures on Justice.
largely practical concerns will have no affect It is surely a good thing that these lectures
on the future of research in political philos- (and other lectures by political philosophers
ophy. As departments are cut down in (to) at other institutions) are freely available for
size, course offerings scaled back, and PhDs anyone who is interested and who has inter-
forced out of the academic community, we net access, regardless of economic standing,
should likewise expect to see less diversity in geographical location, or even background
the kinds of research conducted within the education. The issue here—and both the
political theory community. While this will members of the philosophy department at
not automatically result from a decrease in San Jose State University and Sandel seem to
the number of those engaging in political agree on this point—is with the use of free
philosophy research, it is nevertheless likely: resources to replace actual faculty members,
as fewer people tackle the questions of politi- each with their own perspectives on issues in
cal philosophy, we will see either fewer ques- political theory, and each taking part in the
tions addressed or fewer novel answers given ongoing dialogue that is philosophical reflec-
to the questions addressed—and very likely, tion. To lose participants in this dialogue, by
we will see both. whatever means, is to threaten the future of
Worries like this one were among the moti- political philosophy itself.
vations of the philosophy department of San
Jose State University when they decided to
reject the call to utilize MOOCs in 2013.15 To
maintain a standardized, internet-delivered CONCLUSION
course in political philosophy (regardless
of its source) would diminish the diversity As we have emphasized throughout this
essential to healthy philosophical discourse. chapter, if political philosophy takes its cue
Crucially, at no point was the issue over the from events and controversies in our polit-
quality of the course lectures the depart- ical world, any prediction about the future
ment was being asked to use. The course is inescapably speculative—clearly, there
(“Justice”—still available freely online) was is no crystal ball we can consult to foresee
one developed by Harvard Professor Michael the events and controversies that will arise.
J. Sandel, who ultimately agreed with the We live in a world in which environmental
worries expressed about the mandatory use changes confront us with difficult questions
of his course.16 about the sustainability of our energy, food,
To limit the number of perspectives in and communities, in which the possibility of
political philosophy, to reiterate, is to risk vast and sudden economic crises force us to
diminishing its future. As funds to depart- rethink the function and extent of govern-
ments are cut, faculty lines replaced by mental regulation, and in which terrorism
technological innovations, and resources and counterterrorism require us to reflect on
moved away from those who are actually the political and legal implications of surveil-
conducting research in political theory, we lance, technology, and warfare. No doubt, the
should expect to see a subsequent diminution various approaches to political philosophy

208
THE FUTURE(S) OF POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY

will continue to help us critically examine pol- law argument basic conception claim peo-
itical developments and frame our responses ple respect idea
to them. There is a certain irony in the fact 7 power body subject human identity dif-
that as the world faces the kinds of challenges ference relation experience language
that political philosophy is most qualified— world theory terms trans work discourse
and indeed necessary—to explain, the study order sense form meaning
of political thought is itself being undermined 8 women sexual men social gender black
by the budgetary considerations and cur- family white sex woman children race
ricular priorities of legislators and university racial male marriage female child rape
administrators. This is likely to be an import- lesbian
ant additional area for political theorists to 9 political natural de rousseau locke hob-
reflect on and speak to in coming years.17 bes nature university power state men
man human ed people liberty govern-
ment civil law
10 feminist women press philosophy hypatia
APPENDIX A feminism university work feminists gen-
der philosophical ed theory studies ethics
0 social science knowledge theory human sci- beauvoir philosophers issues social
entific epistemic research view work cog- 11 life people make time story sense experi-
nitive nature theories important empirical ence world art made great find kind feel
evidence epistemology world questions fear things long past live
1 law constitutional legal court constitu- 12 moral reason reasons good rational view
tion judicial review government american account action practical agent person
supreme state public power rights justice theory make sense claim argument fact
madison courts laws speech kind kant
2 harm case cases person moral responsi- 13 political politics theory history modern
bility people morally act life make claim social american thought historical work
killing argument responsible wrong risk book world intellectual ideas pp review
affairs death philosophy contemporary arendt
3 university political review philosophy 14 human religious political philosophy reli-
journal professor science john theory edi- gion politics god life good socrates aris-
tor book published articles david volume totle nietzsche christian man plato nature
ethics sage politics international divine strauss pp
4 moral book social theory human chap- 15 social economic people equality labor
ter ethics ethical rights view essays work resources market welfare work public
account argues philosophical issues phi- society property individuals poor distri-
losophy university discussion bution egalitarian health level equal
5 moral human book theory mill justice lib- 16 war international states state national
eral practical political legal view ethical global world rights united military
ethics social university argues law good human western european foreign power
principles violence nation nations economic
6 rights justice moral freedom state human 17 political public democratic liberal democ-
theory political principles principle rawls racy social citizens politics liberalism theory

209
Matthew Voorhees and J. Jeremy Wisnewski

religious cultural community groups univer- Press, 2007). The article is available here:
sity citizenship society group deliberative http://psiexp.ss.uci.edu/research/papers/
SteyversGriffithsLSABookFormatted.pdf (last
18 political policy american party state pub-
accessed December 26, 2013).
lic government politics national support 5
http://tedunderwood.com/2012/04/01/what-
democratic presidential republican par- kinds-of-topics-does-topic-modeling-actually-
ties congress states president members produce/ (last accessed December 26, 2013).
university
6
This is presumably due to in-article citations
listing university presses. MALLET does
19 moral care human ethics love book life
not distinguish all significant terms from all
caring virtue relationships trust person insignificant ones in its analysis. This is actually
children friendship nature good part uni- useful, as it allows surprising correlations to
versity relationship emerge which might not otherwise. For our
purposes, though, it is likely best to ignore this
particular term as it appears through the topics.
7
See Appendix A for the raw topic lists pro-
Notes duced by our use of MALLET. The order of
the topics is irrelevant to the frequency of said
1
The phrase “political philosophy” is typically topics.
utilized in philosophy departments, while “pol-
8
According to the Google citation index,
itical theory” is typically utilized in political Rawls’s work has been cited nearly 100,000
science departments. Although these phrases times in the texts in Google’s database (as of
may reflect differences between disciplines, we December 2013). Rawls’s name appeared in
regard these differences as less important than topic 5 nearly 8,000 times.
the shared set of concerns that animate each.
9
One might well count topic 19 as well, given
For this reason, we use the terms interchange- the prominence of the terms “care” and “vir-
ably in what follows. tue,” which arguably represents care ethics—an
2
The journals reviewed, in alphabetical order, ethical approach historically associated with
are as follows: Ethics, Hypatia, Philosophy feminism.
and Public Affairs, Political Theory, Polity,
10
Our Mallet study appears to support this point
Review of Politics. These are, admittedly, only about feminist critiques of Rawls. The words
a handful of the journals in the disciplines of “Rawls” and “Rawlsian” appear most fre-
philosophy and political science that publish quently in the topic associated with liberalism
work on political philosophy (The American and justice (topic #5), but their second most
Political Science Review, e.g. typically pub- frequent appearance is in the topic associated
lishes an article by a political theorist in each with gender and race (topic #8).
volume), but in our selection of journals we
11
Stephen Kershnar was making the argument
wanted to privilege those journals available that torture ought to be used as punishment
through JSTOR that often emphasize political prior to 2002, and Michael Levin was arguing
philosophy. that it was acceptable in ticking-bomb cases.
3
Indeed, JSTOR provides a website specifically On the other side of things, Henry Shue and
for such data: http://about.jstor.org/service/ Christopher Tindale were examining what was
data-for-research. morally problematic about the practice.
4
For information on the program, please
12
It is worth mentioning that our MALLET anal-
visit http://mallet.cs.umass.edu/. For an ysis was blind to this development. The term
introduction to topic modeling, see Mark torture appeared nearly 2,000 times—1,100
Steyvers and Tom Griffiths, “Probabilistic of which in association with topic 4—far less
Topic Modelling,” in T. Landauer, D. than many other terms. This reflects, at least
McNamara, S. Dennis, and W. Kintsch (eds), in part, the sample journals available through
Handbook of Latent Semantic Analysis: JSTOR. It also reflects the fact that many of
A Road to Meaning (Hove: Psychology articles on torture have appeared in the last

210
THE FUTURE(S) OF POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY

6–7 years. To see the increase in publications Lynn, W. J. III (2010), “Defending a New
on torture would require a diachronic analysis. Domain: The Pentagon’s Cyberstrategy,”
13
This is, of course, a prediction. The term
Foreign Affairs (September/October).
“cyber” appears only rarely in our MALLET
analysis (under 50 times in its various forms). http://www.foreignaffairs.com/
Various (minimal) references to surveillance articles/66552/william-j-lynn-iii/
and the use of computing are also present. defending-a-new-domain.
14
The term “religion” appears approximately — (2011), “The Pentagon’s Cyberstrategy,
10,000 times in our MALLET analysis.
One Year Later,” Foreign Affairs
Variation of the term “terror” and the term
“inequality” likewise occur several thousand (September 28). http://www.
times. foreignaffairs.com/articles/68305/william-
15
http://chronicle.com/article/The-Document-an- j-lynn-iii/the-pentagons-cyberstrategy-
Open-Letter/138937/ one-year-later.
16
http://chronicle.com/article/Michael-Sandel-
MacIntyre, A. (1981), After Virtue. Notre
Responds/139021/
17
We would like to thank Mark Wolff for his Dame, IN: Notre Dame University
expertise in carrying out our MALLET analy- Press.
sis. We would also like to thank Robert Tracey Okin, S. M. (1994), “Political Liberalism,
for some initial data collection. Justice, and Gender,” Ethics, 105 (23):
23–43.
Pateman, C. (1988), The Sexual Contract.
WORKS CITED Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Reidy, D. A. (2004), “Rawls on International
Abbey, R. (2007), “Back toward a Justice: A Defense,” Political Theory, 32
Comprehensive Liberalism? Justice as (3) (June): 291–319.
Fairness, Gender, and Families,” Political Taylor, C. (1994), Multiculturalism.
Theory, 35 (1) (February): 5–28. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Kymlicka, W. (1995), Multicultural Tully, J. (1995), Strange Multiplicity:
Citizenship: A Liberal Theory of Minority Constitutionalism in an Age of Diversity.
Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

211
14
GLOBALIZATION, COSMOPOLITICS,
DECOLONIALITY: POLITICS FOR/OF
THE ANTHROPOCENE
Eduardo Mendieta

DECOLONIZING POLITICAL allows us to focus the challenges we face in


PHILOSOPHY a world that has grown ever more interde-
pendent and also more fragile.
Closing a book of this type calls for a consid- It may be argued that philosophy is not
eration of the tasks ahead for political phi- only the compendium of humanity’s dialogue
losophy. In the following, therefore, I aim to with itself across time, but also the encyclo-
provide a map of the conceptual and philo- pedia of utopias, unfilled hopes, and dreams
sophical challenges we must meet in order of an undamaged and dignified humanity.
to develop a political philosophy for our Hegel’s famous formulation that “philosophy
times and for the future that we should be . . . is its own time apprehended in thoughts”
collectively constructing. In light of the most (Hegel, 2008, 15)  meant also that philoso-
recent debates within political philosophy in phy is a portrait of humanity at a given time.
particular and social theory in general, the Philosophy is always in relationship to time.
main agenda is how to “provincialize” and Philosophy, we could claim, is the autobiog-
“historicize” Europe and the West, while raphy of human thinking, but like all auto-
also undertaking the project of epistemologi- biographies, it is thus a particular type of
cal, conceptual, and theoretical decoloniza- temporal device. Therefore, all philosophy
tion. I will approach this agenda through is by definition historicized and historically
the reconstruction and exegesis of Enrique material. Philosophy is caught in time, it is
Dussel’s call for “destruction” of the history of time, and it is for time. It is temporalized
of political philosophy (Dussel, 2011, xv). In and it temporalizes. This is what Hegel’s
the second half of the chapter, I consider the phrase means, for “apprehended” (gefasst),
contemporary material conditions of possi- can also be translated as to cease, to grasp, to
bility for the projection and imagining of col- gather and grab, to bring together and join.
lective futures in terms of a discussion of the Philosophy gathers the time of humanity in
Anthropocene, the proposed name for a new thought. For this reason, we can also see why
era in the history of our planet, which I argue and how philosophy is caught in the politics

213
Eduardo Mendieta

of time, of making time, of keeping time, of location and those of other societies and
giving time, of closing time. In these closing cultures. This means that any form of philo-
reflections, I would like to think about the sophical self-reflexivity has also to involve
time from which we think and the time for a reflection about how we describe, “com-
which we think. We think from a tempo- prehend,” cease our times, and thus those
ral juncture that we are trying to diagnose. of others. All timelines or periodization that
This temporal diagnosis, however, is meant facilitate and mediate any philosophizing
to have some future consequences. Keeping or theorizing are temporalizing practices.
time and mapping time—a chronology is a Theory is a chronotopological dispositif
map of time, after all—are ways in which (Mendieta, 2001). To this extent, all theor-
we set temporal trajectories, that is, ways in izing must engage in a critique of its own
which we temporalize our future. The future temporalizing, or by the same token, detem-
is constructed, just as much as the past is poralizing effects.
always fabricated. This is precisely what Argentine-Mexican
Where are we when we are keeping world philosopher Enrique Dussel has invited
time, the time of humanity? In what time are us to do in his monumental A Politics of
we when we philosophize about the future Liberation: A Critical World History, first
of humanity? The last three decades have published in 2007 and translated in 2011
spawned a series of very intense and conten- (Dussel, 2011). In the introduction, Dussel
tious debates about the name we ought to calls for a “destruction” or “deconstruction”
give our time. Some have argued that we live of the extant histories of political philosophy
in the age of postcolonialism and postmod- in order to properly put in perspective the
ernity. Others have argued about the unfin- tasks ahead. In order to be able to construct
ished project of modernity and the second, a proper world history of political philoso-
or reflexive modernity. Others have argued phy, we are called to dismantle those with
in favor of naming our times as the age of which we are familiar, or those with which
globalization. Others have, instead, urged and through which we think, without even
a name that also implies a moral and pol- being away that we assume them. In order
itical imperative: the age of cosmopolitan- to dismantle the existing history of political
isms. Others, yet, argue that we live in an age philosophy, Dussel identifies seven limits, or
of post-Americana Pax and post European let us call the distorting prejudices. The first
hegemony. There are many more proposed limit is a deeply rooted Hellenocentrism that
names, including a newly emerging name, suffuses all histories of political philosophy.
“the Anthropocene,” which focuses on the The Greeks, Athens, Plato, Aristotle, and
global impact that human civilization, cul- the Stoics are taken as the point of depar-
ture, and politics has had on the biosphere. ture for all political thinking, neglecting not
These names are all contentions because they only the Egyptians and Mesopotamians, but
are all partial and they all reflect a particular also the extent to which Confucianism and
place on the map of the earth and the chron- the Semitic religious traditions prior to the
ology of world history. Every place on a map time of Athenian enlightenment had already
is also a conjuncture of world time. When we inaugurated a critique of politics, political
try to name our times, we are also placing power, political authority, raising questions
ourselves in relationship to our geotemporal of legality and legitimacy. Dussel notes, for

214
GLOBALIZATION, COSMOPOLITICS, DECOLONIALITY

instance, that demos is an Egyptian word Mesopotamian, Chinese, Islam, as well as


that means village. The word’s etymology is the Aztecs, Mayan, and Incas. Generally,
neither Greek nor Indo-European. He also the consideration of these cultures is left to
notes that the etymology of the word dike, anthropology, ethnography, or “Area Study”
justice, lies in duku, from the Akkadian, specialists, who engage these cultures in very
which is a Semitic language. Dussel has made circumscribed and delinking perspectives.
a stronger claim in the introduction to his This inveterate Eurocentrism is always mar-
Ethics of Liberation, which also provides us ried to an Orientalism that is as distorting
with a world history of ethical systems, which of Europe as it is of its putative “others.”
begins with the Egyptians, and their Book of Both the Westernization and Eurocentrism
the Dead, namely that Hellenocentrism cuts of histories of political philosophy project
us off from a long history of intense ethical, what has been called Occidentalism, a fiction
political, and philosophical reflection that is as false and distorting as that produced by
the very source of what we take to be origi- Orientalism, a fiction that proclaims that the
nal in the Greeks (Dussel, 2012). In fact, the “occident” is the pinnacle of human civiliza-
time between 800 and 200 bc, which Jaspers tion and the avant-garde in the time line of
called the “Axial Age,” was period in human universal history (Dussel, 1994). Overcoming
history when religious critique was also Eurocentrism, thus, requires that we dis-
political critique, which is also evident in the mantle both Occidentalism, and its shadow,
work of the Greeks (Jaspers, 1953). Orientalism (Mendieta, 2010).
The second chronotopological distor- The fourth limit that Dussel identifies
tion or limit that must be transgressed is is that of very self-serving periodizations.
the Westernization of political philosophy. These periodizations follow invidious, self-
By this, Dussel means that most histories of congratulatory, and self-aggrandizing tem-
political philosophy, in the West and Europe, poral distinctions. It is taken for granted that
marginalize, at best, or excise, at worst, the the history of political philosophy should
Eastern Roman Empire, Byzantium, and the follow the trajectory that tells a very spe-
role of Constantinople, Venice and Genoa in cific “occidentalist” narrative. It begins with
the evolution of political thinking from the the Greeks, continues with the Romans, the
collapse of the Roman Empire through the beginning of the Middle Ages, which some-
Renaissance. Along with many other schol- times is divided into late Antiquity and/or
ars, Dussel has argued that the Renaissance early Middle Ages, and Late Middle Ages,
itself would not have been possible without which then is followed by the Renaissance,
the massive migrations from Byzantium generally only circumscribed to the Italian
to Venice, Florence, and Genoa due to the city states, then to be followed by the birth of
capture of Constantinople by the Turks in the Modern period with Hobbes, Locke, and
1453. Rousseau to then be followed by the German
The third limit that needs to be overcome and French Enlightenments, and so on. This
is the relentless Eurocentrism of most histo- chronology has become so de rigueur as to
ries of political philosophy, which exclude become pedestrian. This chronology, how-
consideration of the contributions from ever, reveals to what extent all similar chro-
non-European and non-Western philo- nologies are chronotopological maps. For
sophical traditions, such as the Egyptian, this chronology privileges Central Europe to

215
Eduardo Mendieta

the detriment of Mediterranean and Eastern through the agendas and canons established
Europe (Byzantium). Here we only need to in the colonial and imperial universities and
note that this chronology makes no sense if we think tanks. This is the type of thinking
place ourselves in China, the modern Middle and philosophizing that is of our time, but
East, India, or pre-Colombian America. In that at the same time is out of our time. It
fact, what the Gulbenkian Commission on belongs to the age of postcolonialism, glo-
the Restructuring of the Social Sciences did balization, and different forms of cosmopoli-
for the Social Sciences needs to be done for tanism, but it remains “colonized” political
both political philosophy in particular and philosophy. Colonized political philosophy
philosophy in general, namely to correlate the detemporalizes by naturalizing and dehistor-
disciplinarization of knowledge into certain icizing Western and Eurocentric narratives
“faculties” that unconsciously but effectively and chronologies.
excluded the non-West from the production The seventh limit has to do with what
of knowledge (Wallerstein et al., 1996). Dussel himself has called somewhere else the
The fifth conceptual limit that must be “myth of modernity,” a myth that entails the
superseded, or at least made explicit, is the exclusion of the discovery of the Americas
secularism that is sine qua non to most histo- from the narrative of “modernity” (Dussel,
ries of political thought. This secularism is an 1994). For Dussel, there is no way to discuss
ideological effect of a certain view not only the “project of modernity” without a careful
of the political, but also of the relationship of consideration of the ways in which colonial-
societal progress and the legitimacy of politi- ism provided the material conditions of pos-
cal institutions. In the West, rationalization sibility for economic development in Europe.
qua modernization has been tied to the thesis But more than providing the material wealth
of the secularization of society. Religion(s) that would underwrite the economic growth
persists, however, and yet societies, whether of Europe, the so-called New World also pro-
Western or non-Western, are only consid- vided the intellectual, theological, and philo-
ered “modern” if they are allegedly secular. sophical impetus for the development of some
Yet even a country, as modern as the United of the foundational doctrines and concepts
States, is nonetheless deeply religious and that constitute the philosophical ground for
could hardly be considered fully secular, or modern political philosophy. Figures such as
the paragon of secularity. It is always the reli- Bartolomé de las Casas, Ginés de Sepúlveda,
gion of the “other” that we find objectiona- Francisco de Vitoria and Francisco Suárez,
ble, even as we are blind to our own religious argues Dussel, should be considered and
commitments. studied as the first political philosophers of
The sixth conceptual limit Dussel identi- modernity, before Bodin, Hobbes, Locke,
fies is what he calls theoretical, intellectual and Rousseau. They are after all the first phi-
colonialism that continues to neglect both losophers, theologians, thinkers who tried to
the philosophical political concerns of the so- develop a political philosophy that would
called global South, and the persistent privi- address the plurality of peoples and religions
leging of the Metropolitan preoccupations, in a context in which the Judeo-Christian
narratives, and chronologies. Even when religions had become one religion among
thinkers are thinking in postcolonial con- many others. The “Americas” have been con-
texts, they continue to orient their research stitutive of the very project of Europe, both

216
GLOBALIZATION, COSMOPOLITICS, DECOLONIALITY

materially and conceptually; yet these roles the “coloniality of knowledge” (Sullivan and
have been either neglected or entirely denied. Tuana, 2007). Decolonizing political philoso-
We have to do a history of political phi- phy thus requires that we be attentive to the
losophy in reverse, to use the expression by “coloniality of power” and the “coloniality
Germán Arciniegas, or read back into Europe of epistemology” that condition the kinds of
what it took from America while erasing that questions we ask, the kinds of narratives we
appropriation (Arciniegas, 1986). assume and project, and the kinds of knowl-
The persistence of this neglect and denial edges we expropriate or appropriate without
have to do with what Anibal Quijano has acknowledging their sources.
called the “coloniality of power,” by which Dussel’s call for a “deconstruction” of
he means at the very least that contemporary contemporary histories of political philoso-
power relations among colonial powers, and phy turns out to be in fact a call for the
between imperial and postcolonial nations decolonization of political philosophy. The
and cultures are suffused and always already seven limits that he identifies have to do
refracted by their colonial past, which is with the ways in which political philosophy
hardly part, and that remains ever present in general wittingly or unwittingly, overtly
(Quijano, 2000). The coloniality of power is or covertly, avowedly or disavowedly relies
the persistence of modes of thinking racial, on and projects chronologies and temporal-
sexual, and ethnic relations established dur- izing narratives that either recognize or deny
ing the colonial period. For Quijano, as well what Fabian has called the “coevalness” of
as for Dussel, we cannot speak of moder- other cultures (Fabian, 1983). To decolo-
nity without coloniality, and thus we should nize political philosophy then requires that
always speak of the modernity/coloniality we dismantle political philosophy as a chro-
duet. The coloniality of power, we could add, notopological dispositif that relegates some
conditions what could be called “the colonial- to an immemorial and stagnant past and
ity of epistemology,” or “coloniality of knowl- other to the very avant-garde of a future that
edge” (Lander, 2000). By this we mean that is only theirs. This means ceasing to philoso-
metropolitan, colonial, and imperial interests phize the political without theodicies and
and perspectives set the agenda for political soteriologies or triumphalist and develop-
philosophy; colonial and imperial institu- mentalist narratives of progress.
tions are taken to be normative and the cul-
mination of allegedly exemplary and putative
“normal” paths of development, which meth-
odologically and conceptually perpetuate an POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY FOR THE
agnotological process (i.e. the active process ANTHROPOCENE
of the production of ignorance, erasure, and
forgetfulness of the expropriation of knowl- One succinct definition of the political is
edges from other cultures) that expropriates that which has to do with the creation of
the contributions to political philosophy by collective possibilities through deliberation,
subalterns and former colonial outposts. in which a collectivity addresses itself both
Decolonizing political philosophy thus a subject and object of its deliberations. In
requires that we acknowledge and confront this sense, the political is about projecting
the “epistemology of ignorance” imposed by and making possible collective or communal

217
Eduardo Mendieta

futures. The future is always the product Climate Change (IPCC) estimates that the
of politics. But there is no future that is not planet’s atmosphere will warm up between
projected from some actuality, some present. 1.4 and 5.8 degrees centigrade. Some of the
When we think about what kind of future most immediate and evident consequences
we can project and construct today, we have of such warming are the unleashing of severe
to begin with the present conditions of pos- weather and the transformation of global
sibility. There is no better way than to sur- climates. Something that Crutzen does not
vey the present conditions of possibility than point out is that now most of humanity lives
through the term “Anthropocene,” a term in cities, and that most of the growth in urban
recently coined by Nobel Prize winner Dutch areas will take place in the global south.
chemist Paul Crutzen in an essay in Nature Something else that is not noted by Crutzen
(Crutzen, 2002). This new age in the history but which should be part of the diagnosis
of the planet refers to the human-induced of the Anthropocene is that the warming of
massive, irreversible, and unpredictable the planet is accelerating desertification in
transformation to the earth’s environment, already very vulnerable areas of the planet.
en toto, from the atmosphere to the seas. This means that more and more humans
According to Crutzen, in the last three cen- will be displaced from the countryside into
turies the world population has increased the growing cities of the planet. The megaur-
by a factor of 10 to more than 7 billion. The banization of the planet is de facto turning
United Nations estimates that by 2050 the into a megaslumization of humanity. Finally,
world population will reach 9.6 billion. The while Crutzen does note that only 25 percent
cattle needed to feel this teeming humanity, of the world population is responsible for
which produces the methane that affects the most of the pollution and consumption that
atmosphere, has risen to 1.4 billion. Humans is driving the ecological crisis, he fails to note
exploit close to half of the land surface of the that some of the causes of the present eco-
planet. Tropical forests are rapidly being cut logical crisis have to do with global relations
to clear space for cattle and farming, decreas- and trends established when Europe began
ing the ability of green areas to absorb car- the process of colonization of the Americas,
bon dioxide. Half of the available potable Africa, and Asia. Whoever speaks of the con-
water in the world is already being used. The temporary ecological crisis must also address
burning of fossil fuels and the expansion of the colonial and imperial archeology of the
agriculture have accelerated the concentra- forms of power that condition how world
tion of “green house” effects—carbon diox- resources are consumed and by whom. The
ide by 30 percent and methane by more than ecological crisis is itself a political effect of
100  percent—climbing to the highest levels the world colonialism and imperialism built
in the last 400 millennia. Crutzen points over the last 600 years.
out that most of these severe and irrevers- Whether we call this a “new period” or
ible trends have been “largely caused by only “age” of the planet the “Anthropocene” or
25% of the world population” (Crutzen, the “anthropozoic” era is itself a political
2002, 23). The accumulation of all these question. The “facts” and “trends” of this
green house gases has resulted and will con- new age are also the battleground of politi-
tinue to impact the rise of the temperature of cal deliberation. Yet, it is clear that whatever
the earth. The Intergovernmental Panel on horizon of futurity we want to deliberate

218
GLOBALIZATION, COSMOPOLITICS, DECOLONIALITY

about must include all the evidence about growing “soft power” (power of persuasion
the cataclysmic and irreversible changes and suasion, rather than military or violent
in the earth due to anthropogenic factors. power) of the world court and world criminal
These “planetary” factors have to be con- court has given rise to what could be called
sidered against the background of a series the “Human Rights-Politics Paradox.” On the
of framework conditions for the interaction one hand, it is only within nation-states, with
of humanity in the coming future. Here, we their respective constitutional guarantees of
can only identify these new social–political citizenship rights, that can effectively enforce
framework conditions and indicate how they the moral and legal principles embodied in
impact and condition the development of a human rights; on the other hand, the sover-
political philosophy for the anthropocene, eignty of these nation-states is questioned and
beyond Eurocentrism and after the decoloni- challenged from the standpoint of human
zation of political philosophy. rights. To this extent it could be claimed we
We now live, although not equita- live in a post-national age, but not yet in the
bly and within the same temporalities, in age of a global constitutionalism that guar-
what Luhmann called the “world society” antees and secures for all human beings their
(Luhmann, 2012). We may be citizens of spe- basic human rights. Finally, we live in an age
cific nation-states, but we are all part of thick in which the inequities between the poor and
and overarching webs of institutions, from the the wealthy have grown abysmally, exacer-
economy and transnational legal systems to bating questions of global justice. Enduring
the projection of a global imaginary through global inequities, established during the colo-
world cinema, literatures, and music. This nial and imperial periods, furthermore, is
means that our fates, hopes, and imaginar- being exacerbated by what could be called
ies are now interlinked in ways never before the “monetization of financial risk” at the
possible or imagined. This “world society” is global level. This is in fact one dimension of
made ever more cohesive and interdependent the “world society” of which we have become
through the emergence of a “global public unwilling members, namely the emergence
sphere” that is partly enabled by the world of a global economy that now includes the
wide web, and also by the numerous non- financial sector as a productive element of the
government organizations (NGOs) that are economy. This is why economic crises in one
continuously bringing to the attention of the country, or even one part of the world, can no
world public crises, crimes, and challenges in longer be contained within nations or even
many different regions of the world, which economic blocs. The integration of financial
nonetheless have global impact. It is part of markets at the global level means that incur-
this global public sphere to be heterogeneous, ring financial risks, such as betting on hedge
decentered, and ever emergent (Mendieta, funds and derivatives, can tap national econ-
2013). At the same time, we have the emer- omies by shifting failures to local national
gence and growing institutionalization of budgets, while privatizing the profits derived
what can be called a “global order guided by from these risks. In the age of the world soci-
human rights.” Human rights have become ety, the globalization of financial markets
the gold standard for all kinds of legiti- has become the latest tool of neoimperialist
mate political and legal orders. Interestingly, expropriation. Economic crises are the latest
the juridification of human rights and the form of imperial pillage.

219
Eduardo Mendieta

We live in an age of unprecedented interde- thus have to be a political philosophy that


pendence and asymmetrically lived vulnera- calls for more democracy, and the renewed
bilities. We live in the age of new assemblages task of submitting global economy to the
and also massive expulsions, to use Sassen’s political regulation of political actors.
language (Sassen, 2014). Political philoso-
phy is called to rethink its basic categories of
analysis and to dismantle its methodological
Eurocentrism and conceptual colonialism, WORKS CITED
as Kerner put it very aptly (Kerner, 2013).
One way in which it can begin to do both Appadurai, A. (2013), The Future as a
things is by engaging in a reflection about Cultural Fact: Essays on the Global
how all thinking is a chronotopological Condition. New York and London:
device, a method for granting time, or taking Verso.
time away. The narratives that have guided Arciniegas, G. (1986), America in Europe:
most of political philosophy over the last a history of the New World in Reverse.
500  years, those of secularization, enlight- San Diego, CA: Harcourt Brace
enment, modernity, progress, development, Jovanovich.
have placed the invented West and homog- Crutzen, P. J. (2002), “Geology of Mankind”
enized Europe at the zero hour of world his- Nature, 415: 23.
tory, at the 12 o’clock of the day on the clock Dussel, E. (2012), Ethics of Liberation in
of universal history, the time from which all the Age of Globalization and Exclusion.
others can be seen as lagging behind, always Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
too late, never ever able to be on time. — (2011), Politics of Liberation. A Critical
Appadurai has written about the future as a World History. London: SCM Press.
cultural fact (Appadurai, 2013). Echoing him, — (1994), 1492. El Encubrimineto del
I have argued here that political philosophy Otro. Hacia el origen del “mito de la
is precisely about imagining, projecting, and modernidad” Conferencias de Frankfurt.
constructing collective futures. We cannot do Octubre de 1992. La Paz, Bolivia: Plural
this collectively so long as the colonial past Editores.
continues to frame how we think about our Fabian, J. (1983), Time and the Other: How
challenges and the future remains mortgaged Anthropology Makes its Object. New
to the vision of progress projected by both York: Columbia University Press.
Occidentalism and Orientalism. A political Hegel, G. W. F. (2008), Outlines of the
philosophy that dismantles this chronoto- Philosophy of Right. Oxford: Oxford
pogical matrix may be one that thinks from University Press.
the standpoint of developing global institu- Jaspers, K. (1953), The Origin and Goal of
tions that take as a point of departure the History. New Haven, CT: Yale University
achievements of the regime of human rights; Press.
it would also be one that takes up the unfin- Kerner, I. (2013), “Differences in Inequality:
ished tasks of the constitutionalization of a Tracing the Socioeconomic, the Cultural
global legal regime that secures the self-de- and the Political in Latin American
termination of peoples while also juridifying Postcolonial Theory,” desiguALdades.
the new globalized financial market. It will net Working Papers Series 60. Berlin:

220
GLOBALIZATION, COSMOPOLITICS, DECOLONIALITY

desiguALdades.net International Research — (2013), “World Society, Public Sphere


Network on Interdependent Inequalities and Cosmopolitanism,” in R. Raúl
in Latin America. Fornet-Betancourt, H. Schelkshorn,
Lander, E. (2000), La colonialidad del saber. and F. Gmainer-Pranzl (eds), Auf dem
Eurocentrismo y ciencias sociales. Buenos Weg zu einer Gerechten Universalität:
Aires: UNESCO-CLASCO. Philosophischen Grundlagen und
Luhmann, N. (2012), Theory of Society, Politischen Perspektiven. Aachen:
Vol. 1. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Wissenschaftsverlag Mainz, pp. 127–139.
Press, pp. 83–99. Quijano, A. (2000), “Coloniality of Power,
Mendieta, E. (2001), “Chronotopology: Eurocentrism, and Latin America,”
Critique of Spatiotemporal Regimes,” in Nepantla: Views from the South, 1 (3):
W. S. Wilkerson and J. Paris (eds), New 533–580.
Critical Theory: Essays on Liberation. Sassen, S. (2014), Expulsions: Brutality
Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield and Complexity in the Global Economy.
Publishers, pp. 175–197. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
— (2010), “Postcolonialism, Sullivan, S. and Tuana, N. (eds) (2007), Race
Postorientalism, Postoccidentalism: The and the Epistemologies of Ignorance.
Past That Never Went Away and the Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
Future That Never Arrived,” in May, Wallerstein, I. (1996), Open the Social
T., Emerging Trends in Continental Sciences: Report of the Gulbenkian
Philosophy. Vol. 8. The History of Commission on the Restructuring of the
Continental Philosophy, A. D. Schrift Social Sciences. Stanford, CA: Stanford
(ed.). Durham: Acumen, pp. 149–172. University Press.

221
CHRONOLOGY

BEFORE THE COMMON ERA 800: Charlemagne crowned emperor


1215: Magna Carta
ca. 650: Draco the Lawgiver 1221–1274: Aquinas
638–558: Solon 1285–1347: William of Ockham
495–425: Pericles 1469–1527: Machiavelli
470–399: Socrates 1478–1535: Thomas More
460–395: Thucydides 1483–1546: Martin Luther
445–365: Antisthenes (founder of Cynicism) 1516: Thomas More publishes Utopia
431–404: Peloponnesian War 1517: Luther’s 95 Theses
427–347: Plato 1583–1645: Hugo Grotius
412–323: Diogenes the Cynic 1588–1653: Robert Filmer
384–322: Aristotle 1588–1679: Thomas Hobbes
336–323: Reign of Alexander the Great 1618–1648: Thirty Years War
334–262: Zeno of Citium (founder of 1625: Grotius publishes On the Laws of
Stoicism) War and Peace
106–43: Cicero 1648: Peace of Westphalia
100–44: Julius Caesar (reigned from 49–44) 1651: Hobbs publishes Leviathan
63 bce—14 ce: Augustus Caesar (reigned 1632–1694: Samuel von Pufendorf
form 27 bce–14 ce) 1632–1704: John Locke
27 bce–180 ce: Pax Romana 1642–1651: English Civil War
1688: Glorious Revolution
1689: Locke publishes Two Treatises of
Government and Letter Concerning
COMMON ERA Toleration
1689–1755: Charles de Secondat, Baron
4 bce—65 ce: Seneca Montesquieu
55–135: Epictetus 1712–1778: Jean-Jacques Rousseau
121–180: Marcus Aurelius 1724–1804: Immanuel Kant
306–337: Reign of Constantine 1729–1797: Edmund Burke
354–430: Augustine 1732–1790: Adam Smith
534: Justinian’s Code 1743–1826: Thomas Jefferson

223
CHRONOLOGY

1748–1832: Jeremy Bentham 1849: Thoreau publishes Civil Disobedience


1748: Montesquieu publishes The Spirit of 1859: Mill publishes On Liberty
the Laws 1859–1952: John Dewey
1754: Rousseau publishes Discourse on the 1860–1935: Jane Addams
Origin and Basis of Inequality Among 1861: Mill publishes Considerations on
Men Representative Government
1756: Burke publishes A Vindication of 1864–19020: Max Weber
Natural Society: A View of the Miseries 1869–1940: Emma Goldman
and Evils Arising to Mankind From Every 1869–1948: Mohandas K. Gandhi
Species of Artificial Society 1882: Bakunin publishes God and the State
1756–1836: William Godwin 1887: Nietzsche publishes On the
1759–1797: Mary Wollstonecraft Genealogy of Morals
1762: Rousseau publishes Of The Social 1888–1985: Carl Schmitt
Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 1895–1973: Max Horkheimer
1770–1831: George Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel 1898–1979: Herbert Marcuse
1775–1783: American Revolution 1899–1973: Leo Strauss
1781: Bentham publishes Principles of 1903–1969: Theodor W. Adorno
Morals and Legislation 1905–1982: Ayn Rand
1789–1799: French Revolution 1905: Weber publishes The Protestant Ethic
1791: Godwin publishes Enquiry and the Spirit of Capitalism
Concerning Political Justice and Its 1906–1975: Hannah Arendt
Influence on Morals and Happiness 1907–1992: H. L. A. Hart
1790–1859: John Austin 1909–1997: Isaiah Berlin
1790: Burke publishes Reflections on the 1914–1918: First World War
Revolution in France 1917: Russian Revolution
1792: Wollstonecraft publishes Vindication 1919: Weber publishes Politics as Vocation
of the Rights of Women 1919: Schmitt publishes Political Theology
1795: Kant publishes Perpetual Peace: A 1921–2002: John Rawls
Philosophical Sketch 1926–1984: Michel Foucault
1797: Kant publishes The Metaphysics of b. 1929: Jürgen Habermas
Morals (including Science of Right) 1930–2004: Jacques Derrida
1806–1873: John Stuart Mill 1931–2013: Ronald Dworkin
1809–1865: Pierre Proudhon 1932: Schmitt publishes The Concept of the
1814–1876: Mikhail Bakunin Political
1817–1862: Henry David Thoreau b. 1934: Enrique Dussel
1818–1883: Karl Marx b. 1935: Michael Walzer
1821: Hegel publishes Elements of the 1938–2002: Robert Nozick
Philosophy of Right 1939–1945: Second World War
1840: Proudhon publishes What is b. 1943: Chantal Mouffe
Property? 1944: Horkheimer and Adorno publish
1844–1900: Friedrich Nietzsche Dialectic of Enlightenment
1848: Marx and Engels publish Communist 1945: Founding of the United Nations
Manifesto b. 1949: Slavoj Žižek

224
CHRONOLOGY

b. 1947: Martha Nussbaum 1975: Foucault publishes Discipline and


1947–1991: Cold War Punish
1949–2006: Iris Marion Young 1977: Walzer publishes Just and Unjust Wars
1950: Adorno et al. publish The 1981: Habermas publishes Theory of
Authoritarian Personality Communicative Action
1951: Arendt publishes The Origins of 1982: Sandel publishes Liberalism and the
Totalitarianism Limits of Justice
b. 1953: Michael Sandel 1983: Walzer publishes Spheres of Justice
b. 1953: Thomas Pogge 1990: Young publishes Justice and the
1953: Strauss publishes Natural Right and Politics of Difference
History 1993: Rawls publishes Political Liberalism
1959: Strauss publishes What is Political 1995: Kymlicka publishes Multicultural
Philosophy? Citizenship
1961: Hart publishes The Concept of Law 1998: Nussbaum publishes Sex and Social
1962: Habermas publishes The Structural Justice
Transformation of the Public Sphere 1999: Rawls publishes The Law of Peoples
1963: Arendt publishes On Revolution 2000: Negri and Hardt publish Empire
b. 1962: Will Kymlicka 2002: Pogge publishes World Poverty and
1964: Marcuse publishes One-Dimensional Human Rights
Man 2005: Mouffe publishes On the Political
1969: Berlin publishes Four Essays on Liberty 2006: Nussbaum publishes Frontiers of
1970: Arendt publishes On Violence Justice: Disability, Nationality, Species
1971: Rawls publishes A Theory of Justice Membership
1974: Nozick publishes Anarchy, State, 2007: Dussel publishes Politics of Liberation
Utopia (translated to English in 2011)

225
GLOSSARY1

Absolutism:  Term used to describe regimes Aristocracy:  A form of governmental orga-


or systems of thought that are totaliz- nization ostensibly focused on rule of
ing, exceptionless, and all-encompassing. the good or best (in Greek aristos means
Absolutist regimes are autocratic: all “good” or “excellent”). In practice, aris-
power is invested in the ruler. Absolutist tocracies are constructed as governments
monarchs ruled Europe in the eighteenth ruled by wealthy landowners and nobil-
century. Defenders of enlightened abso- ity.
lutism argued that the best form of gov- Asylum:  Those who suffer persecution under
ernment was one in which a benevolent a given political organization may ask for
central authority had absolute power. See asylum from another entity with political
also totalitarianism. power (or religious power). When the right
Alien:  A person residing within a coun- to asylum is invoked, the organization
try who is not a citizen of that country. that provides sanctuary may offer protec-
Aliens may be permitted to visit, live, and tion for the asylum-seeker. International
work within a country based upon a pro- law recognizes the rights of asylum-seek-
cess involving visas and official permits. ers. Also certain spaces within sovereign
Illegal aliens are those who are in a coun- states—such as embassies—may be places
try in violation of that official permitting of asylum for those fleeing persecution.
process. Authoritarian(-ism):  A form of government
Anarchy/Anarchism:  A theory of government that emphasizes central control and hier-
(and related political movements/parties) archical structures of power. Focused on
that denies the legitimacy of governmen- structures of command and obedience
tal rule. While anarchism is often skeptical that supersede individual judgment and
and critical of political power, anarchism personal autonomy. Contrasted with
can also advocate the positive goal of creat- non-authoritarian structures and regimes,
ing a stateless society based on voluntary which are open to dissent, pluralistic, and
association. Anarchists emphasize indi- individualistic.
vidual autonomy, the importance of con- Autocracy:  A form of government that invests
sensus and unanimity in deliberation, and absolute power in one person—the auto-
a radical critique of structures of social and crat, who rules autocratically (or without
political control. From Greek an-archos constraint). Autocracy comes from Greek:
(without rule or principle). auto—meaning “self”—and—cracy/kra-

227
GLOSSARY

tos—meaning “rule”). Autocracy implies buffer zones are often monitored by inter-
independence and self-sufficiency in rul- national peacekeeping forces.
ing. While the term is not necessarily Bureaucracy:  Large organizations consisting
pernicious, autocracy has negative conno- of various offices (bureaus) and officials
tations, since autocratic rule tends to be (bureacrats). Bureaucracy often refers
despotic and absolutist. to the system of unelected officials who
Autonomy/Autonomous:  Literally “self-rule” make up the apparatus of government—
(auto = self; nomos = rule/law). As a norma- the hierarchical structure of offices orga-
tive principle autonomy establishes a right nized in what is called the civil service.
to self-rule, self-control, and self-determi- Bureaucracy can be used pejoratively to
nation, that is connected to claims about indicate a set of excessively complicated
individual rights. It can also be employed rules, regulations, and procedures. Some
to describe regions or groups that have a social theorists follow Max Weber in
legal right to self-governance or national understanding bureaucracy as part of
self-determination. Autonomy is a cen- efficient modernization necessitated by
tral concern for theories of human rights increasing complexity and the division of
and for Kantian/deontological theories of labor—creating what Weber described as
morality and politics. the “iron cage” of bureaucratic life. Crit-
Balance of Power:  A circumstance in which ics—notably the critical theorists of the
different sovereign powers or parts of Frankfurt school—argue that bureaucra-
government are held in check or bal- cies breed so-called bureaucratic ratio-
anced in opposition to other powers or nality that tends toward conformism,
parts. The balance of power can produce legalism, and deference toward author-
power sharing arrangements between ity.
various parties. In federal systems, there Capitalism:  A form of economic organi-
is a balance of power between local enti- zation that is based upon commitment
ties and the federal government. In mixed to private ownership of property and
governments with a separation of power, the ability to make profit by exchanges
there is a balance between the parts of of labor and goods in an open market.
government. In international affairs, the Capitalism is based upon wage labor, in
balance of power is understood in terms which labor is exchanged for monetary
of opposing spheres of interest, alliances, compensation. Capitalism developed in
and power differentials among nations. In the modern period out of previous feu-
international relations, the issue of bal- dalism. It was challenged as an economic
ance of power is connected with questions system by communism in the twentieth
about hegemony and structural conflicts century. Capitalism is often associated
understood in terms of unipolar, bipolar, with liberal, democratic forms of gov-
or multipolar models. ernment, since liberal democracies tend
Buffer Zones:  Border areas that are estab- to emphasize the importance of the right
lished in order to prevent or inhibit inter- to private property. Liberal democracies
action across borders. Often employed tend to embrace laissez-faire capital-
along contested international borders as ism, while socialist governments tend
a way of preventing border skirmishes to impose more regulations on the mar-
and cross-border violence. Also described ket. More authoritarian and central-
as areas of separation, zones of neutrality ized regimes (such as China) have also
(or neutral zones), or demilitarized zones. embraced a version of capitalism known
In contemporary international relations, as state capitalism.

228
GLOSSARY

Citizen/Citizenship:  A citizen is a person who Civil Disobedience:  The act of disobeying


belongs to a national political entity and a law, while accepting punishment for
has the rights, protections, and responsi- disobedience, employed in an effort to
bilities of full members of that political protest against unjust law. Civil disobe-
group—related to the idea of national- dience is often employed as a nonviolent
ity. Citizenship may be defined as mere technique of social protest. Unlike in acts
belonging, often understood either as eth- of conscientious objection or refusal, the
nic identity (so-called jus sanguinis or right laws violated in civil disobedience are
of blood citizenship) or as a birth-right of not necessarily the laws viewed as unjust.
native born persons (so-called jus soli or Civil disobeyers may violate parade
right of the soil citizenship). In the United and assembly regulations, hoping to be
States, those born within the borders of arrested as an act of protest against other
the United States are citizens by birth. In unjust laws. This method has been widely
other nations, citizenship is defined by the employed in civil rights protests around
blood of one’s parents. Citizenship can the world—inspired by ideas and activi-
also be acquired through a process of nat- ties of Thoreau, Gandhi, King, and others.
uralization: naturalized citizens are those Unlike violent revolution, which aims to
who have acquired citizenship through a overthrow the legal system, civil disobe-
deliberate process by which they swear dience occurs out of what Rawls calls
allegiance to their newly acquired nation. “fidelity to law”—with the idea that the
Citizens may have more rights than non- legal system is basically just, even though
citizens in some nations—including rights the law being protested is unjust.
to work, rights to education, healthcare, Civil Liberties:  Civil liberties are basic liber-
and so on. In this regard, citizens are pro- ties afforded to citizens. Often this includes
tected by civil rights. Citizenship may also rights or liberties, such as to freedom of
be accompanied by responsibilities includ- speech, freedom of assembly, and freedom
ing the duty to serve in the military, the of religion. These liberties are associated
obligation to vote, the requirement of jury with the private choices of individual
service, and so on. citizens. These rights are often primar-
Civilization:  An idea describing a level of ily conceived of as negative rights. Civil
political and economic development that liberties are usually extensively defended
involves the creation of cities, includ- within liberal regimes. This concept is
ing sedentary people, division of labor, closely connected with the notion of civil
surplus wealth, political and religious rights and sometimes the terms are used
hierarchy. The term “civilization” and interchangeably. However, the notion of
“civilized” are sometimes used to indi- civil liberties focuses more specifically on
cate a distinction between more primitive protecting individuals from governmental
forms of development. This way of orga- coercion in spheres of private concern.
nizing things indicates a developmental Civil Rights:  Civil rights are the rights of cit-
hierarchy, with civilization viewed as an izens. While civil liberties are understood
advancement over less primitive forms in negative terms as the basic liberties of
of life. The term civilization is also used private individual citizens, civil rights can
to identify broad trans-national cultural be understood to include a broader range
identities. This idea has been employed of political rights and positive rights. They
to describe a supposed clash of civiliza- usually include the right to participate in
tion (e.g. as found in the work of Samuel governmental decision making through
Huntington). the right to vote and petition the govern-

229
GLOSSARY

ment, the right to due process including civil society, which bind citizens together
the right to have a speedy and fair trial in a common project despite their differ-
by jury, and so on. Civil rights can extend ences.
toward a broader set of positive rights Collectivism:  A theory of social and politi-
that includes a right to fair wages, fair cal organization that emphasizes group
housing, freedom from employment dis- cohesion and unity often focused on
crimination, the right to work, the right centralized and hierarchical political
to education, and other welfare rights. organization. Or collectivism may focus
Unlike human rights that extend to all on the need for consensus and esprit de
humans, civil rights may only extend to corps. Collectivism in mass society may
citizens. be opposed to a more traditional, organic
Civil Society:  The sphere of human activity notion of community. In this sense, collec-
outside of governmental/political life. In tives are mere groups gather together en
Hegelian theory, civil society (Bürgerliche masse, while communities are groups who
Gesellschaft) is located midway between cooperate and share things in common.
merely private lives of individuals (where Communes or intentional communities
morality is a primary concern) and the are often understood in opposition to the
political life of the national community collectives of mass society. Collectivism is
(where law and legislation are primary also opposed to individualism.
concerns). This middle sphere includes Colonialism:  A theory and practice of inter-
business interests, unions, and other national expansion aimed at exploita-
social organizations. A key component of tion of either an occupied territory or
civil society is the voluntary nature of its resettlement in that territory by foreign-
organizations. While laws regulate social ers. Colonialism includes hierarchical and
and business life, participation in the hegemonic social and political structures,
institutions of civil society is voluntary. similar to imperialism. Colonialism aims
Some theorists—such as Walzer and Put- at establishing some form of governance
nam—point out that robust civil society over a foreign polity, while imperialism
is an essential feature of stable polities, aims more at exploitation and military
since civil society allows for the develop- control. In some versions, colonialism
ment of lateral relationships of trust that (like imperialism) was justified by some
bind pluralistic polities together despite version of the ideology known as the
their internal diversity. One feature of the white man’s burden—the idea that Euro-
extra-legal and voluntary coordination of pean powers had a moral obligation to
civil society is a set of virtues that allow uplift, educate, and liberate backward
for social interaction: tolerance, nonvio- and uncivilized peoples across the globe.
lence, solidarity, and civility. See also pub- Colonialism was ended with liberation
lic sphere. movements around the globe, leading the
Civility:  A social virtue that allows for development of post-colonial theory.
productive and harmonious interaction Common Good:  The good as defined in
among diverse people. Civility includes terms of what is good for the commu-
basic norms of politeness and etiquette. It nity or collective. In traditional Christian
also includes more robust norms and rules social justice teaching, the common good
for social interaction, political debate, and is understood as the sum total of good for
public deliberation. Closely related to tol- each individual as a whole. In utilitarian-
erance, civility is understood as grounded ism, the common good can be understood
in basic agreement about the norms of in terms of the greatest happiness for the

230
GLOSSARY

greatest number. Related concepts include talism. Communism may be understood


the public welfare, public interest, or as the most radical development of social-
­commonweal. ism, which aims in the direction of sub-
Commons:  The commons is what is not stantive equality. In the nineteenth and
owned in a system of private property. It is twentieth centuries, communism devel-
shared resources and spaces that are open oped especially through the influence of
for communal use. Commons include Karl Marx toward the call for global rev-
oceanic and atmospheric resources. Some olution against capitalism, which had a
resources may be understood as commons lasting impact on global politics. Commu-
within a nation, while other commons are nal ownership of goods and cooperation
open for international use. See also trag- aims, in Marxist terms, to distribute goods
edy of the commons. to each individual according to their need.
Commonwealth:  A political order that is Unlike ancient and modern communal-
oriented around the common good, the ism, which focused on separate, local, and
commonweal, or public welfare. The term self-sufficient communes, communism is
“commonwealth” is also used to indicate generally viewed as a global movement
national identity (as in the Common- that aims at a global transformation of
wealth of Australia) and federations of economic and social relations away from
nations (as in the former British colonies the class distinctions of capitalism toward
that are associated in the Commonwealth the development of a class-less society in
of Nations—formerly the British Com- which workers share ownership in the
monwealth). Commonwealth signifies means of production.
an affiliation based on shared culture, Communitarianism:  A form of social and
language, and political values. As a name political organization that emphasizes
for a national government, “common- the importance of community and tra-
wealth” indicates a “republican” form of dition. Offered as a response to liberal
government—that is government focused individualism, communitarianism focuses
on public welfare rather than the private on the connection between the individual
satisfaction of the ruling nobility. and the community. Communitarians
Commune/Communalism:  A commune is de-emphasize negative liberty and high-
a social group organized along coop- light the community’s role in establishing
erative lines and based upon notions of norms that define the meaning and pur-
shared communal resources, mutual- pose of individuality. Communitarians
ity, and reciprocity. In some cases, com- emphasize the need for responsibility,
munes have been established as separate, responsiveness, and reciprocity within a
counter-cultural communities that isolate community. Communitarians may also
themselves from the larger social whole. emphasize the importance of community
Communalism is an anarchist or radically support for individuals based upon some
decentralized alternative to state-centered notion of positive rights.
socialism/communism, which emphasizes Conscientious Objection/Refusal:  The act of
the development of small scale and auton- refusing to comply with a legal command
omous communes. based upon a claim of private conscience.
Communism:  A form of economic (and Unlike civil disobedience, conscientious
political) organization that focuses on refusal is not necessarily a strategic effort
communal ownership of property, includ- to break the law in order to foster social
ing the abolition of private property and change (although it can be that as well).
ending the profit/market system of capi- Instead, conscientious refusal and objec-

231
GLOSSARY

tion are acts of noncompliance based Cosmopolitanism:  An ideal of trans-na-


upon the claim that the command that is tional community grounded in norms and
refused violates the objector’s moral judg- values that unite people across the globe.
ment. Conscientious objection is often Although it has ancient roots, cosmopoli-
based upon religious principles or moral tanism has developed in modern European
ideals that are in opposition to the law. contexts with a focus on an international
Constitution:  The basis structure of a order that would preserve peace among
social/political organization. A constitu- nations, as developed out of natural law
tion may be written or codified in a set theory. In contemporary usage, cosmopol-
of foundational documents, which clarify itanism is oriented around universal norms
organizational structure, institutional about human rights and shared humanity
responsibilities and power, and proce- that develop out of liberal political theory.
dures. An un-codified or unwritten con- It is associated with the growth of inter-
stitution exists (as in the United Kingdom national institutions, globalization, and a
or Canada) in the series of precedents concern for global justice.
and cases that make up the history of Crime:  A violation of law that is liable to be
governmental organization. Written con- punished. In positive law theory, a crime
stitutions may also be supplemented by is an act that violates stipulated laws. The
customary developments and case law positive law approach includes the idea
precedents. Written constitutions may that if there is no law against something,
furthermore be altered by constitutional then it is not a crime to do it, ruling out ex
amendments. post facto and retroactive administration
Conservatism:  The ideology of those who of new laws. The natural law theory dif-
emphasize tradition and who are resis- fers in holding that there are some actions
tant to radical change. Conservatives are that are criminal violations of the natural
interested in preserving or conserving law, even if there is no positive law deem-
some traditional status quo. Historically, ing those actions to be criminal. Criminal
conservatism (as associated with Edmund law in liberal democracies usually includes
Burke) was opposed to the radical and the idea that criminal deeds must also be
revolutionary changes that occurred dur- accompanied by criminal intent (so-called
ing the era of the French Revolution. mens rea). A different notion of crime
Conservatism is pejoratively described as focuses only on the deed itself in a sys-
reactionary. In liberal democratic polities, tem of “strict liability.” Some violations of
conservatism has tended toward libertar- private law or common law—in torts and
ian domestic ideals and realist interna- contracts—are not punishable by courts
tional values which are associated with but are administered by civil law courts
right-wing parties. Conservatism is often (as opposed to criminal courts). See also
understood in opposition to progressiv- war crimes.
ism. Crimes Against Humanity:  A notion devel-
Coup d’etat:  A revolutionary transfer of oped in international law which is used to
power that strikes quickly, often by vio- condemn particularly odious assaults on
lence (such as assassination or a mutiny human dignity, especially the systematic
of military officers). While revolutions misdeeds of states associated with per-
often involve the movements and actions secution, ethnic cleansing, and genocide.
of the masses, coups usually involves the The notion of crimes against human-
actions of small groups—often rival par- ity developed through international war
ties within the ruling classes. crimes tribunals held after World War II

232
GLOSSARY

(the Nuremburg and Tokyo tribunals), Cultural Relativism:  The idea that values and
which clarified three categories of war norms are relative to a given culture. This
crime: crimes against the peace, crimes implies a meta-ethical and skeptical claim
against humanity, and genocide. The that there are no transculturally absolute
International Criminal Court was estab- values, which are accepted (or ought to
lished by the Rome Statute of 1998, and be accepted) by all persons in all cultures.
instituted in 2002 in The Hague. The Cultural relativism is often asserted as a
Rome Statute clarifies that crimes against descriptive claim: it is a fact that some
humanity include widespread and system- values are relative to culture. Defenders of
atic murder, enslavement, sexual crimes, objective and universal values will argue
torture, apartheid, and so on. that there are some non-relative norms
Critical Theory:  An approach to social, cul- that transcend cultural diversity. Cultural
tural, and political criticism associated relativism thus poses a challenge to claims
with the Frankfurt School and authors about universal human rights. See also
such as Horkheimer, Adorno, Marcuse, relativism.
and more recently, Habermas. By employ- Deliberative Democracy:  A form of decision
ing post-Marxist ideas about ideology, making based upon free and open pub-
materialism, and the importance of dialec- lic deliberation. Contrasted with merely
tical reasoning, the critical theorists offer preference- or interest-based voting (as
critical insight into contemporary political is assumed in most secret balloting),
structures. Critical theory employs social deliberative democracy aims to establish
scientific knowledge and historical data consensus based upon public reasoning.
in a critical (non-neutral) fashion, usually Members are expected to provide and
with the aim of opposing domination and defend the reasons for their opinions and
promoting liberation. conclusions in public. Short of unanimity,
Culture:  Social, moral, political, linguistic, the goal of deliberative democracy is to
and intellectual habits of a people or civi- ensure that minority opinions are heard
lization. Culture is the product of educa- and responded to while finding ways to
tion and habituation (cf. German Bildung) include multiple perspectives within a plu-
and can thus be understood as “second- ralistic polity, and while viewing members
nature,” as character, or as the ethos or as rational co-participants in the endeavor
way of life of a group. Culture can point of reasonable public discussion.
toward hierarchical classification—as cul- Democracy:  A form of governmental organi-
tured (or civilized) individuals are viewed zation based on rule by or of the people (in
as superior to the uncultured. Culture is Greek demos means “people”). Democ-
related to “cultivation”—as cultured indi- racy primarily identifies the structure of
viduals are cultivated or educated into the power in a political system: democratic
norms and customs of a people or civiliza- governments will place power in the peo-
tion. Culture can thus be organized into ple to some degree and in some fashion.
high- and low-cultures (including pop- Direct democracy allows for direct vot-
culture)—and dominant cultures can be ing by citizens. Representative democracy
resisted by various sub-cultures. Culture allows the people to elect representatives
is often viewed as a unitary set of values, to the governing body. There are a vari-
associated with a nation. However, there ety of ways that democratic representa-
is a growing awareness of cultural diver- tion can occur, including winner-take all
sity, the problem of cultural relativism, elections in single-member districts (as in
and the challenge of multiculturalism. the United States and the United King-

233
GLOSSARY

dom) and proportional representation of l­egitimacy in a religious claim that gives


various sorts (as in many European coun- the sovereign the “divine right” to rule. As
tries). A variation is representation by lot such, the sovereign who rules by divine
or sortition (which is called demarchy). right has no human limits on power: his
Another variant would base policy deci- power is only limited by God, who grants
sions upon random-sampling of public him the right to rule.
opinion. Democracy can also be used to Division of Labor:  The way that specific
describe the purposes and limits of politi- tasks and roles are coordinated in a soci-
cal power, with democratic governments ety. This results in specialization and can
ruling in the interests of the people. Lib- produce class distinctions. The division of
eral democracy is a democratic form of labor can be necessitated by the nature
government with limitations imposed by of technology and production; and it
the rights of the people, including protec- can reflect differences in talent and abil-
tions of individual rights. See also delib- ity among persons. However, Marxists
erative democracy; liberalism. complain that the division of labor is also
Despotism:  Despotism is rule by a sover- structured by ideology and differential
eign who has absolute, unlimited power. social power. Adam Smith and Emile Dur-
This sovereign may be a monarch or a kheim held that progress and advance-
group but the sovereign is despotic when ment result from increased specialization
its rule is absolute. Despotism often con- leading to a complex division of labor.
notes arbitrary and cruel rule that is not Dynasty:  A historical sequence of rulers who
restricted by moral or legal principles. come from the same family or group. In
However, it is possible for there to be traditional hierarchical societies, dynas-
enlightened or benevolent despotism, ties consist in lines of power that are
where the despot rules absolutely but in passed down from one generation to
the interest or for the well-being of the the other, usually according to patrilin-
people. See also autocracy, tyranny. eal rules of succession. In more contem-
Distributive Justice:  Concern for the dis- porary settings, the term dynasty can be
tribution of social goods, including used to describe ongoing political success
income, wealth, vocational and educa- of a party or group, which may or may
tional opportunity, health care, and other not have a familial connection.
sources of well-being. Principles of dis- Egalitarian/ism:  A basic commitment to
tributive justice vary according to relative equality. It can be a descriptive claim about
ranking of key values especially equality, basic equality among human beings, for
efficiency, and liberty. Some forms of dis- example, maintaining the human beings
tributive justice want to ensure substan- are created with equal rights or equal dig-
tial equality. Other forms want to ensure nity. It can be a normative claim about the
fair and equal opportunity. Still others need to create equality (by removing social/
will emphasize the importance of liberty political barriers that produce inequality).
and free exchanges, even if this results in Equality can be understood in a variety of
unequal distributions. Distributive justice ways. It can be understood as substantive
can be strictly utilitarian—aiming to max- equality, in which individuals should have
imize the greatest happiness for the great- the same amount of things; or equality of
est number. Or it can emphasize (as John outcome, which focuses on eliminating
Rawls does) maximin rationality. unequal results from social transaction. It
Divine-Right:  A principle of ruling that can be understood as political equality, in
grounds the sovereign’s power and which individuals should have the equal

234
GLOSSARY

opportunity to influence political out- and government were superseded by lib-


comes (as in the principle of “one person, eral, democratic, and capitalist theories.
one vote”) or in which persons should be Some enlightenment authors (such as Vol-
treated equally by the law. It can also be taire) thought that enlightened despots
understood in terms of equality of oppor- might rule in the interest of the people.
tunity, in which barriers to education, But enlightenment political philosophers
careers, and other opportunities should be such as Locke supported revolutionary
eliminated. Egalitarianism is opposed to movements against despotic rule based in
caste, class, ethnic, and racial hierarchies ideas about human rights and the impor-
that are based upon unequal treatment tance of liberal and democratic reform of
and unequal consideration for individu- government.
als of these different groups. Egalitarian- Environmentalism:  A social movement or
ism may also be opposed to meritocracy, set of concerns directed beyond mere
when meritocracy creates unequal social concern for human beings and toward
hierarchies—however, the idea of equality concern for the broader surround-
of opportunity may permit unequal out- ing world. Environmental concern can
comes that have meritocratic results. include or be focused on anthropocen-
Empire:  A hierarchical transnational or tric concerns—as in the idea of envi-
super-national power, ruling over other ronmental justice, which seeks to apply
nation-states, provinces, and sub-national principles of social justice and distribu-
geographic units. Empires can be estab- tive justice to environmental harms and
lished by conquest or by less violent benefits. Environmentalism can also
transfers of sovereignty (as in feudal be nonanthropocentric, in which case
marriages). Empires can use military and it is concerned with the well-being of
police power to establish direct rule over nonhuman beings including inanimate
imperial possessions. Or empires can use objects, individual animals, animal spe-
less overt means of influence to estab- cies, habitats, ecosystems, the biosphere,
lish hegemonic control—including both or even the planet itself. Environmental-
economic and cultural power. Empires ism shows up in political philosophy in
vary in terms of the amount of central- terms of the problem of representing the
ized authority exerted on client states and interests of nonhuman beings, in terms
imperial possessions—from loose alli- of the problem of environmental justice,
ances to direct control. A recent theory and in terms of thinking about interna-
of globalization (by Hardt and Negri) tional solutions to global environmental
describes the emerging capitalist global problems such as climate change.
order as an Empire. Ethics:  The study of behavior derived from
Enlightenment:  Enlightenment literally sig- the Greek word ethos which means hab-
nifies awareness, awakening, or edifica- its, customs, or character traits. Philo-
tion. In the history of Western Philosophy, sophical ethics has three main branches.
the Enlightenment (also called the Age of Metaethics focuses on problems arising in
Reason) was a period in the seventeenth the analysis of ethical concepts and ethi-
and eighteenth centuries during which cal reasoning. Normative ethics focuses
philosophers criticized traditional systems on concrete theories of what is good or
of religious, social, and political author- justice. Applied ethics focuses on the
ity. In European political philosophy, the application of normative theories to con-
Enlightenment is the time during which crete problems. Although some want to
Medieval and feudal ideas about society distinguish ethics from morality, there is

235
GLOSSARY

no firm distinction between the two. See ment that aims to liberate women. It can
also mores/moral/morality. also be understood as a broadly focused
Ethnic Cleansing:  See genocide. critique of male-dominance as it shows up
Fascism:  An autocratic or dictatorial form in patriarchal social institutions, popular
of social and political organization culture, religion, and philosophy. Some
that emphasizes national unity, military feminists (so-called liberal feminists)
strength, and centralized authority. Fas- emphasize that the liberation of women
cism developed in the twentieth century must be grounded in an expansion of
as a reaction against both international human rights in a way that includes issues
communism and liberal democracy. Asso- that concern women. Other feminists
ciated with Mussolini and Hitler, fascism (so-called radical feminists) focus their
is oriented around mythic symbolism critique on hierarchical structures based
about power and ethnic/national identity. on “gendered” concepts, such as cultural
Fascism does not tolerate opposition or norms about masculinity and femininity.
minority parties. In recent decades, fas- See also gender.
cism has been used as a pejorative term to Feudalism:  A form of social, political, and
describe centralized political power that economic organization typical of Europe
relies upon security apparatus, secretive during the so-called Medieval period.
surveillance, and military force. See also This system emphasized a hierarchy of
totalitarianism. nobilities tied together by pledges of mili-
Federalism:  A theory of sovereign power tary support and by economic centraliza-
and political hierarchy that distinguishes tion through the manorial (or seigniorial)
between constitutive part (localities, states, system in which peasants were tied to
provinces, regions, etc.) that are united land possessed by the Lord of the Manor.
together in one federation. The balance of Feudalism also included a third class—
power between the parts and the federal the clergy. The three classes or estates of
government may be worked out in vari- medieval or feudal social system were
ous ways. Most federal systems allow for the nobility, the clergy, and the common-
local control of a range of issues. Federal- ers/peasantry. In feudal social structures,
ism has been contrasted with imperialism membership in a class was determined by
and with the unitary state as a strategy for birth (with the exception of the clergy).
maintaining unity and control over large Feudalism in Europe gave way to liberal-
geographic areas. Federalism is often pre- ism and capitalism.
sumed to result from negotiated settle- Free market:  See Laissez-Faire Capitalism.
ment among the confederated parties and Freedom:  A condition in which there is lack
not merely out of military domination. of restriction, constraint, or necessity. The
Federalism allows for greater pluralism word “freedom” can be traced to Germanic
by allowing local populations or sub- roots—as related both to Freiheit (free-
national groups to maintain autonomy dom) and Friede (peace). Freedom is a con-
and self-determination, including reli- dition in which choices are not determined,
gious and linguistic autonomy, as well as in which one is permitted or licensed to
local control of fiscal policy, taxation, and choose to act. The Latin root for the same
criminal justice. idea gives us the synonym liberty, from
Feminism:  A critical social and political which we derive ideas about civil liberties.
theory that focuses on the oppression Freedom includes related notions such as
and exclusion of women. Feminism can independence, self-control (autonomy),
be understood as an activist social move- and self-governance. Liberty and freedom

236
GLOSSARY

can be defined either as negative or posi- structed, and about the extent to which
tive (following a distinction made popu- gender should enter into questions of dis-
lar by Isaiah Berlin). Negative freedom or tributive justice. Some radical theorists
negative liberty is understood as lack of hold that there is a continuum disguised
constraint, grounded in protection against by the simple dichotomy between mascu-
the interference of others and the interfer- line and feminine, arguing that gender is a
ence of the state. Positive freedom or posi- socially constructed set of norms intended
tive liberty is understood as the ability to to organize human life into simplistic cat-
direct actions toward ends of one’s own egories. Others—natural law theorists,
choosing. Liberal political regimes tend to for example—argue that gender distinc-
emphasize negative freedom—aiming to tions reflect natural phenomena and that
restrict state interference in the actions of basic gender distinctions are essential for
individuals. Communitarians and social- reproduction. Gender is also reflected
ists tend to emphasize positive freedoms in the division of labor in society, with
and rights—asserting that freedom must roles, tasks, and careers viewed as either
be supported by economic opportunity, feminine or masculine. The gendered divi-
education, and political rights. sion of labor is connected with histori-
Game Theory:  Game theory examines the cal exploitation of women, poor wages
ethics, logic, economics, and psychol- for female occupations, degradation of
ogy behind decision strategies. Various the private sphere, and feminine virtues
models and hypotheses are explored in (such as caring and nurturing) and other
game theory in order to understand the aspects of inequality for women. See also
costs and benefits of decision procedures. feminism.
Much depends on how the game theoretic Genocide:  Genocide is literally the killing
situation is constructed. For example, one of a people (a genos). While there are
must consider whether a game is a zero- many examples from history of mass kill-
sum game (in which gains and losses are ing based on ethnic and national identity,
balanced among losers and winners) or the term was coined during the 1940s to
whether there can be a net gain shared by describe the Nazi’s attempt to exterminate
the players. The game theoretic situation the Jewish people. Modern centralized
must also consider the number of play- political conditions, mechanized means
ers, issues related to power sharing, and of killing, and racist ideology make con-
the question of knowledge and decision- temporary genocide a sui generis prob-
making in conditions of ignorance. These lem. The designation of acts of killing as
models are often applied both in domestic genocide is a politically fraught process,
political theory—to understand voting, as genocide is viewed as one of the worst
power sharing, and political strategy— crimes. Related terms include ethnic
and in international relations theory—to cleansing and crimes against humanity.
understand strategic issues related to alli- Ethnic cleansing may be viewed as a more
ances, war-making, and issues related to limited effort to purge a land of certain
the balance of power. See also prisoner’s sorts of people (which may include mas-
dilemma, tragedy of the commons. sacre or only forced deportation), while
Gender:  Gender is located in the basic genocide aims more deliberately at the
dichotomy between male and female, physical destruction/extermination of
masculine and feminine. There are impor- that people. See also war crimes.
tant debates about the status of gender: Globalization:  A process by which the world’s
whether it is biological or socially con- markets, cultures, and political systems are

237
GLOSSARY

becoming united and homogenized. One notion of cultural hegemony, as described


interpretation of globalization highlights by Gramsci, is used to explain how domi-
the increasing integration of global finan- nant social groups dominate the masses
cial systems and other economic interrela- by way of ideology. However, hegemony
tion. Other interpretations of globalization may be understood in a more neutral way
focus on cultural and technological inter- to describe the structure of power, alle-
relatedness along with the spread of a giance, and obedience—whether freely
common political ideology. Globalization consented to or not.
is often understood as a descriptive fact Human Rights:  Human rights are moral and
about the integration of the global econ- legal entitlements, which create a duty on
omy and the world’s cultures. But critics the part of others. A right is a claim to a
of globalization argue that this is a per- certain sort of treatment that establishes
nicious force driven by the self-interest a responsibility for others to respond to
of dominant economic forces. Defenders that claim. Negative rights establish pro-
of globalization argue that globalization tections against infringements by oth-
increases productivity, profit, and global ers and by the state (related to the idea
development, while also fostering progres- of negative freedom or negative liberty).
sive social and political change. Positive rights make claims for more pro-
Government:  The system by which politi- active support for agency, dignity, and
cal power and control are organized. In autonomy. Human rights are supposed to
a narrow sense, government refers to universal and inalienable, which implies
the specific administration of power at a that they are more than merely civil rights
given time, focused primarily on the party (which are rights guaranteed to citizens
and persons who are governing. This nar- within a polity). Human rights apply to all
row sense of the term is often employed in human beings, regardless of citizenship.
British English; in American English, this They thus establish basic norms that limit
sense of the term is associated with the and direct legitimate state power. In recent
term administration. In a broader sense, decades, a body of human rights policies
government is the entire political system and international law has developed, with
organized across time and including a the United Nations’s “Declaration of
variety of administrations (or govern- Human Rights,” for example, mandating
ments in the narrow sense). The broader recognition of the inherent dignity of all
concept of government includes the laws, human beings. Often human rights claims
the bureaucratic apparatus, as well as the are grounded in natural law and under-
specific persons and parties who share stood in terms of natural rights.
power within that system. Idealism:  In general, idealism is oriented
Group Rights:  See identity politics. around the idea that ideas should guide
Hegemony:  To have hegemony is to have judgment and behavior. In political phi-
power and control over something. The losophy and especially in theories of
Greek term hegemon means leader. While international affairs, idealism is the claim
the idea of leadership may be value-neu- that ideas have power in political life and
tral, hegemonic power is often under- that moral norms ought to guide judg-
stood as external power undergrided by ment and behavior. This idea is opposed
manipulation, force, and threats of force. to realism—which either denies that ideas
Hegemony can be based upon military are efficacious or that they ought to be
supremacy. But hegemony can also rest used as a guide for behavior. Idealists
upon cultural and economic power. The generally believe that concepts like jus-

238
GLOSSARY

tice or human rights should be considered ers because of the hegemonic power of
as primary concerns. They also tend to that class. Building upon this relativistic
hold that political life ought to be guided notion of ideology, some defend the cre-
by disinterested reason—as opposed to ation and dissemination of ideology as
manipulation and self-interest. As a corol- a way of promoting social cohesion and
lary, idealists tend to believe that people development.
are both reasonable and motivated by Identity Politics:  The politics of identity
moral notions. Idealism tends to be linked (or identity politics) describes social and
to liberal internationalism, such as the political movements that are focused on
approach supported by Woodrow Wilson, recognition of the claims and rights of so-
which holds that states ought to intervene called identity groups, which are social
in the domestic affairs of other states in groups organized and defined by certain
pursuit of democratizing changes that will characteristics or traits: homosexuals,
produce a just and stable international blacks, Christians, women, and so on.
order. Related to this is the democratic Identity politics has primarily been asso-
peace thesis in international relations, ciated with struggles for recognition of
which holds that as polities become lib- minority and disempowered groups. Iden-
eral and democratic—and thus share tity politics includes consciousness-raising
moral and political norms—they will tend and developing solidarity among mem-
not to fight one another. Related to this is bers of the group. It also includes work-
the neo-conservative idealism of the early ing for official recognition and inclusion
twenty-first century that sought to create of group members in political institutions
regime change by interventions aimed at and organizations. Sometimes it is con-
nation-build and democratization. Crit- nected to claims about differential group
ics of idealism will claim that it can be an rights, understood as rights that allow
ideological façade that betrays interest in social groups to maintain their identity.
empire and hegemony. See also struggle for recognition; multi-
Ideology/Ideological:  An ideology is the set culturalism.
of ideas, beliefs, and norms that are shared Imperialism:  A political effort to create
by a group. While the term ideology can empire by extending control over a for-
be employed in a value-neutral fashion to eign territory—usually by military con-
describe a set of beliefs (similar to the term quest. Imperialism is also a historical term
Weltanschauung, world-view, or orienta- used to designate the era of European
tion), the term can also be employed in expansion especially in the nineteenth
pejorative fashion to describe beliefs that and twentieth centuries (the so-called age
are not held for legitimate reasons. This of imperialism), during which the British
pejorative understand of ideology is often Empire grew along with other imperial
transformed into the adjective ideologi- ventures by European powers (and later
cal. Ideological beliefs are not grounded by the United States). A related term is
in truth or reason, rather they serve spe- the idea of cultural imperialism (similar
cific interests. Ideology, in the pejorative to cultural hegemony), which is the idea
sense, can be understood as delusion, that cultural ideas—religious, moral, eco-
self-deception, or false-consciousness. In nomic, and so on—are disseminated by
Marxism, ideology is associated with the a dominant power, often accompanied
idea that the ruling ideas are the ideas by military power. While empires and
of the ruling class—serving the interests imperialism have existed since ancient
of the ruling class and accepted by oth- times, modern imperialism develops

239
GLOSSARY

out of previous colonialism. As Hannah It can also be focused on redistributing


Arendt explains in Origins of Totalitari- social goods in a way that is fair or equi-
anism, imperialism has a more totalitar- table. Justice can also be considered as a
ian orientation—seeking to establish total virtue for individuals. Justice is generally
control over the occupied territory—than held to be the minimal requirement of
colonialism, which permits some form of social organizations and behavior, with
local autonomy. A newer version of impe- benevolence and goodness understood as
rialism—known as neo-imperialism— going beyond mere justice. Justice is often
uses economic power and nontraditional qualified by the specific area of concern:
military power to establish hegemonic as in “distributive justice,” “retributive
control. See further discussion at empire. justice,” and so on.
Individualism:  A normative theory that Just War Theory:  An account of justice in war
emphasizes the importance of the indi- that focuses on two primary concerns: jus
vidual—as opposed to an emphasis on ad bellum and jus in bello. Jus ad bellum
the community or social whole. Liberal is concerned with the justification of war-
political systems tend to be individual- fare and focuses on considerations such as
istic since they recognize the rights of just cause, right intention, proportional-
the individual as defenses against social ity, and legitimate authority. Jus in bello
interference in the life of the individual. is concerned with justice within warfare
Communitarian and socialist regimes and focuses on considerations such as
tend to emphasize the connections that discriminating between combatants and
individuals have as well as responsibilities noncombatants, respect for prisoners of
that individuals have to the community. war and other conventions of war, and
Individualism can also be understood as avoiding the use of intrinsically immoral
indicating methodological and ontologi- means (such as rape). The just war theory
cal presuppositions. Ontological individ- developed along with the natural law the-
ualism and methodological individualism ory’s idea of the law of peoples, holding
in the social sciences assume that the indi- that moral principles ought to regulate
vidual is the basic unit of social reality international behavior including warfare.
or social ­analysis—the atomic parts who Laissez-Faire Capitalism:  The idea that
join together to make up social wholes (as markets should be left alone, free from
in so-called atomic individualism). interference by the government. Laissez-
Jus cogens:  Peremptory (or overriding) faire principles can be applied domesti-
norms of international law, related to the cally and internationally. The hope of
law of peoples and to natural law. the laissez-faire ideal is that markets and
Jus gentium:  See law of peoples. the free enterprise system will regulate
Jus naturale:  See natural law. themselves in light of basic laws of sup-
Justice:  Justice is the concept of what is right ply and demand, if the state would merely
(or wrong and therefore unjust). There allow them to function by their own
are a variety of accounts of justice and logic. Opposed to laissez-faire economies
what is just. Some theories of justice focus are command economies (also known as
on social organization, including Plato’s planned economies) in which the state
account of the proper hierarchical organi- controls production and distribution of
zation of society. Other theories of justice goods.
focus on what is owed to people in light of Law of Peoples:  A theory of law and eth-
basic rights and laws. Justice can be con- ics that holds that there are custom-
cerned with retribution for past wrongs. ary norms that hold across or between

240
GLOSSARY

peoples, nations, and individuals from well as critical perspective on capitalism


diverse political and legal frameworks. and globalization. See also right-wing/
In Roman and Christian natural law tra- rightist.
dition, this was known as jus gentium— Legal Positivism:  A theory in the philosophy
the law of peoples or nations—which is of law and political theory that holds that
merely customary and is not as binding as the power of law is grounded in the social,
jus naturale or natural law—and which political, and legal institutions that posit
could also be distinguished from civil the law. Unlike the natural law tradition,
law in terms of its inter-national scope. which holds that there is a natural law
Related to the idea of the law of peoples that transcends legal systems, legal posi-
is the concept of jus cogens, which is the tivism either denies or ignores supposedly
set of so-called peremptory (absolute and transcendent sources or standards of jus-
invariable) norms that ought to govern tice. Legal positivism is often understood
international law. In contemporary set- as viewing the law as a social construction
tings, the law of peoples has been con- and attempting to keep legal concerns dis-
nected with the notion of international tinct from moral concerns. See also posi-
humanitarian law, including human tive law.
rights doctrines. The idea of the Law of Liberalism:  Liberalism is primarily concerned
Peoples may also be understood (as in with liberty and equality. Liberalism asserts
John Rawls’s later work) as developing the importance of human and civil rights
from some form of international con- and is thus connected with democratic
tractarian account. political structures. While there are varia-
Leftism/Left-Wing:  The Left (or Leftism) tions on liberalism—from the classical
in political discourse is associated with liberalism of John Locke to John Rawls’s
a concern for equality and social justice. political liberalism—the liberal ideal aims
The designation of Leftism developed to create a just and fair society that is not
out of the arrangement of parties in the grounded on hierarchical and static social
Estates General during the French Revo- and political arrangements. There is sub-
lution: anti-monarchist parties were situ- stantial variation among liberals, with
ated on the left. Leftism has generally some liberals endorsing laissez-faire capi-
been opposed to hierarchical social and talism and others defending the idea of the
political arrangements. In the nineteenth welfare-state. In general, a liberal political
Century historical context, Leftists shared position will emphasize both liberty and
much in common with liberals who equality, while offering various ways of
emphasize liberty and equality, although adjusting these values along with other
Leftists have usually been understood as political concerns. Liberal regimes tend
residing further out on the political spec- to emphasize state neutrality and official
trum, associated with communism and toleration—allowing diverse groups (reli-
anarchism. In contemporary political gious or sub-cultural) to exist without
life, less extreme Leftism has come to be the state picking sides in disputes about
associated with socialist and progressive morality, religion, and so on.
political concerns (as opposed to libertar- Libertarianism:  Libertarianism is the idea
ian and conservative concerns currently that liberty is the primary political value.
associated with the Right). These con- Libertarians generally advocate a minimal
temporary Left-Wing concerns include a state—with some libertarians advocating a
concern for the environment, opposition version of anarchism. Libertarianism may
to militarism, sympathy for feminism, as be focused primarily on economic policy,

241
GLOSSARY

emphasizing laissez-faire capitalism. But United States. The idea of mixed govern-
libertarian concerns may also extend to ment is connected with the idea of a sepa-
social policy, with libertarians emphasiz- ration of power and a system of checks
ing individual choice with regard to reli- and balances through which the parts of
gious, moral, and other issues. In general, government limit one another.
libertarians emphasize individualism and Modus Vivendi:  Literally “means of life,”
the importance of individual autonomy as a modus vivendi represents an accom-
opposed to collectivism and socialism. modation among people that permits co-
Liberty:  See Freedom. existence without substantial agreement,
Marxism:  A radical revolutionary form of as in a truce, détente, or overlapping con-
socialism associated with the philosophy sensus. A modus vivendi does not require
of Karl Marx. See Communism. deep agreement, although it can produce
Meritocracy:  A political system in which rul- civil peace and an end to violence. See
ing power is concentrated in the hands of also toleration.
those with special talents, knowledge, and Monarchism:  Monarchism is literally the
capabilities. Meritocracy is opposed to idea that there is one ruling person—the
traditional nepotistic and dynastic forms monarch. Defenders of monarchy—from
of political hierarchy that are based upon Plato to the present—will argue that
patronage, cronyism, and other distri- sovereign power ought to be united in
butions of power not based upon merit. one person. In Plato’s vision of the phi-
Meritocracies allow for social mobility losopher-king, the monarch would be a
based upon merit. While some meritoc- wise and virtuous person who ruled for
racies may create inequalities and hier- the good of the common wealth. Similar
archies, true meritocracies should be ideas can be found in modern ideas about
receptive to the achievement of talented enlightened absolutism or benevolent
and ambitious individuals. Meritocracies despotism. The notion of “the monar-
usually include some mechanism for test- chy” is often used to describe a system of
ing and evaluating talent—as in civil ser- royal and dynastic power. Constitutional
vice examinations, licensing procedures, monarchies (or limited monarchies) are
and other forms of educational sorting political structures in which the monarch
that are associated with modern bureau- presides as the head of state but in which
cracies and the civil service. the monarch’s power is effectively lim-
Mixed Government:  Any form of political ited by other parts of government and by
organization structured by combining established principles relating to the rights
different types of ruling bodies chosen of citizens. In some polities, the monarch
among various possibilities: democracy, (and the nobility more broadly construed)
oligarchy, aristocracy, monarchy, and so has been demoted to a merely ceremonial
on. Ancient political philosophers such as function, such that the monarch has no
Aristotle and Cicero imagined both pure effective power but is still retained as a
and mixed constitutional forms and frame- figurehead and symbol of the nation. See
works. These authors argued that mixed also autocracy.
government might work to avoid nega- Mores/Moral/Morality:  The term mores is
tive outcomes associated with the pure used to describe the customs, conventions,
forms of government. In modern politi- dispositions, and typical behavior and
cal philosophy, the idea of mixed govern- beliefs of a people. Mores is a Latin version
ment is associated with Montesquieu and of the Greek concept ethos. Moral may be
with the constitutional ­framework of the used as a normative term ­implying good-

242
GLOSSARY

ness: as in a “moral person.” But moral unity and can be used as a synonym
may also be used as a merely descriptive for country, commonwealth, or state.
term indicating that questions of good- However, nation—and the related term
ness (or evil) are at stake: as in a “moral nationality—can be used to connote eth-
dilemma,” which is a question concern- nic, tribal, or cultural identity that ranges
ing what is good or evil. Morality may be across state borders. Similarly, a political
used as a descriptive term to account for entity or state can include more than one
the customary comportment of people. nationality—as in the case of so-called
But morality may also be understood as multinational states. Opposed to this is
a more theoretical framework of norms. the idea of the nation-state, which pre-
For further discussion of theoretical dis- sumes a more homogeneous sort of ethnic
tinctions in moral theory and the study of and political unity.
morality, see ethics. Nationalism:  Nationalism can be under-
Multiculturalism:  As a descriptive term mul- stood as ideas and beliefs emphasizing
ticultural refers to the fact of diversity, national-level political organization.
indicating that there multiple cultural Nationalism can be understood as synon-
frameworks exist. A multicultural society ymous with patriotism. However, nation-
is one that includes plural cultures. Mul- alism can have the negative connotation
ticulturalism is a normative theory about of unquestioned loyalty to and irrational
how best to deal with cultural diversity. identification with the nation conceived
Multiculturalism is pluralistic in the sense along ethnic lines. Another negative con-
that multiculturalism tolerates, accom- notation associates nationalism with ideas
modates, and even celebrates diversity. about the superiority of one’s own nation.
Multiculturalism is understood in terms In a less negative sense, nationalism can
of various solutions to issues of cultural be understood as asserting self-determi-
identity and power-sharing that point nation and independence—in opposition
beyond mere nondiscrimination and bare to imperial or colonial domination or
toleration. Multicultural societies may forms of multinational grouping. Nation-
allow for differential rights depending alism can also be understood as asserting
upon ethnic or cultural identity—as in the national identity claims across local and
different rights permitted to First Nations regional differences.
in Canada or in the case of power-sharing Natural Law:  A tradition in thinking about
among linguistic, cultural, and religious the normative source of morality and law,
minorities in places such as Switzerland which holds that moral, legal, and politi-
or India. Sub-national groups may be per- cal norms can be found in nature and
mitted to have different rights regarding understood by reason. The natural law
a range of issues—family structure, reli- tradition is opposed to the idea of posi-
gious observance, military service, and so tive law, which holds that law is merely
on—including limited sub-national sov- man-made and transient. The natural law
ereignty (perhaps related to a version of tradition maintains that there are eternal
federalism). Opposed to multiculturalism and immutable laws, which have a nor-
is a vision of national unity, inclusivity, mative power that transcends particular
and unitary citizenship. See also plural- legal frameworks and customary morality.
ism, relativism, identity politics. The natural law tradition may be associ-
Nation:  A nation is a collection of people ated with Christian thinking about divine
who share something in common. It sources of normativity. The Christian and
often connotes geographical and ­political European source of natural law has led to

243
GLOSSARY

criticisms of the natural law theory (and (non-violence) is a source—and is derived


related notion of natural rights) in con- from Hindu, Buddhist, and Jain religion
temporary international law. However, and philosophy. See also pacifism, peace.
non-theological natural law accounts Oligarchy:  Rule by the few. Oligarchy usu-
may be developed based upon claims ally implies rule of those who have wealth
about human nature, which may avoid and property. But plutocracy is a more
the charge of Eurocentrism and Christo- precise term for rule of the rich. Other
centrism. In general, the natural law the- forms of oligarchy can be based upon rule
ory holds that there are objective values by military junta, a committee of elders, a
which can be used to criticize positive law racial elite, or even a group of noble fami-
and which establish universal norms. Also lies (as in aristocracy). Oligarchies may be
see Law of Peoples. more efficient than more broadly demo-
Natural Rights:  Natural rights are entitle- cratic systems. But oligarchies typically
ments that we have “by nature” in accord have to employ some form of coercion or
with some form of natural law theory. ideology to restrict governmental power
Natural rights are viewed as transcending from more broadly democratic structure.
merely civil rights or legal rights—which Oppression:  Cruel and unjust treatment
are rights afforded by the legal or political based upon differentials of social power.
system. Some attempt to contrast natural Oppression can be temporary or system-
rights with human rights by arguing that atic and enduring. Oppression can be
natural rights are grounded in God and overt or implicit. In some cases, oppres-
the natural law, while human rights are sion results from institutionalized struc-
merely human creations. However, most tures and ideologies—such that oppressed
view natural rights and human rights as people do not imagine things differently.
virtually synonymous. See also human Oppression that encounters resistance may
rights. be reacted to with repressive measures.
Negative Rights:  Rights that involve protec- Although oppression and repression are
tions against harms and encroachment, as closely related, repression is better under-
opposed to positive rights. See also civil stood as overt effort to prevent resistance
liberties. to oppression, while oppression is more
Nonviolence:  Nonviolence is a basic com- sustained and systematic power.
mitment to avoid violence in social and Overlapping Consensus:  A concept asso-
political life. It is often a central tenet of ciated with John Rawls’s approach to
pacifism. However, nonviolence is also a political philosophy and his ideas about
strategy that can be employed by those reasonable pluralism. Rawls suggest that
who are not committed (or absolute) pac- it is possible for diverse people to find
ifists. Nonviolent civil disobedience and common agreement about political frame-
nonviolent social protest aim to trans- works and principles of justice despite
form social and political life by employing substantial disagreements about morality,
nonviolent methods, which can include metaphysics, and religion. Overlapping
strikes, rallies, sit-ins, walk-outs, boy- consensus occurs when there is agreement
cotts, noncooperation campaigns, and so despite such differences. See also modus
on. Strategies of nonviolence have been vivendi, toleration.
developed in the past century following Pacifism:  A commitment to peace. Pacifism
especially the work of Gandhi and King, can be understood as a principled and
both of whom led nonviolent social justice absolute opposition to war and violence.
campaigns. Gandhi’s concept of ahimsa But pacifism can also be understood as an

244
GLOSSARY

opposition to violence and war in partic- Political Rights:  Those rights that are related
ular circumstances. See also nonviolence, to political representation and participa-
peace. tion, including the right to vote, the right
Patriotism:  Patriotism is identification with to organize political parties, the right
and loyalty to a country, including a sense to petition the government, the right to
of duty and obligation for the good of the ­assemble and demonstrate, and so on.
nation. Patriotism may be connected to Also see civil rights.
ethnic and nationalistic identity claims. Positive Law:  Positive law consists of laws
But a broader form of liberal or constitu- established by political authorities and
tional patriotism may be possible, which legal systems, also called statutory law.
is grounded in loyalty and dedication to Positive law has been posited, that is,
the more abstract and less nationalistic proclaimed and established. Positive law
norms of a constitutional system. See also is often opposed to natural law, which is
nationalism. not necessarily posited by any authority
Peace:  Peace can be understood as a mere ces- or contingent upon an agency or institu-
sation of violence, such as results from a tion that posits the law. Positive law is the
truce that creates a mere modus vivendi. Or primary concern of legal positivism.
peace can be understood to require a more Positive Rights:  Entitlements that involve
substantial agreement about basic goods, more than merely negative prohibitions
including a shared sense of justice and against harm and encroachment; as
social harmony, as described, for example, opposed to negative rights. See civil rights,
in the Catholic tradition as the tranquility welfare rights.
of order. See also nonviolence, pacifism. Postcolonial Theory:  An approach to social
Pluralism:  Pluralism may be understood as a and political theory that focuses on power
descriptive claim about the fact of diver- differentials and cultural structures and
sity. Pluralistic approaches to theory uti- that responds to European colonialism
lize diverse methodologies and concepts. and Western imperialism. Postcolonial
Pluralistic societies contain diverse groups. theories attempt to make sense of global
Pluralism may also be understood as a disparities, revolutionary politics, and
normative ideal that claims that there is other issues from a perspective interested
value in diversity and that celebrates mul- in historical Eurocentrism and dialectical
tiplicities of perspectives and ideas. Rawls relations between center and periphery.
and other contemporary liberal political Prisoner’s Dilemma:  A scenario imagined in
philosophers maintain that it is possible game theory that is used to model problems
to develop overlapping consensus from in strategic decision making, especially the
out of so-called reasonable pluralism. See difficulty of cooperative behavior for self-
also multiculturalism, relativism. interested parties. The model involves two
Polarity:  A concept in international relations criminals who are arrested and offered a
used to describe power relationships, con- deal for betraying each other. Given the
centrations of power, and various forms initial set-up rational, self-interested par-
of achieving balance of power. Unipolar ties end up betraying each other, thus fail-
models of international relations main- ing to cooperate and ending up with less
tain that there is one dominant hegemon than optimal outcomes. This model has
or superpower. Bipolar models emphasize been used to explain political phenomena
two-sided power structures. Multipolar including failures to cooperate in domes-
models focus on more than two parties tic and international circumstances. See
engaged in a balance of power. also tragedy of the commons.

245
GLOSSARY

Privacy:  Privacy concerns what is outside While the term appears to be opposed
of public scrutiny and regulation. While to conservatism, some conservatives
privacy and private relations may be nar- describe themselves as ­progressive—as in
rowly construed in terms of what individ- the Canadian “Progressive Conservative”
uals do with their own bodies, thoughts, party. A more appropriate antonym for
and relationship, privacy may also be progressive is regressive, which indicates
extended to include non-public matters a deliberate turn away from progress. The
conducted by clubs, unions, and busi- term progressive is also used to describe
ness interests. Privacy rights include the a structure of taxation in which richer
right to keep secrets, the right to be free people pay more—for example, when
from surveillance, and the right to asso- those with a higher income pay a higher
ciate with others without supervision or percentage in taxes. This form of taxation
scrutiny. Privacy is an important value in is progressive in the political sense insofar
modern liberal political systems, along as it redistributes wealth and moderates
with related ideas about the importance inequality. See also reactionary.
of tolerance and freedom of conscience Public Sphere/Public Reason:  The public
(and religion). sphere is opposed to the private sphere,
Private Sphere/Private Sector:  The non-po- as the place of public deliberation. Hab-
litical realm of domestic and individual ermas’s history of the public sphere
life—as opposed to the public sphere. (Öffentlichkeit) indicates that a robust
The private sphere is often construed in public sphere develops along with lib-
a broad enough fashion to include the life eral political institutions and technolo-
of business and the economy, as well as gies of publication including news media
the rest of what is often called, follow- and educational systems. In the liberal
ing Hegel, civil society. Most narrowly, public sphere, norms of tolerance and
the private sphere is what individuals are civility allow for dialogue about public
concerned with in their own lives and in goods based upon shared principles and
the life of the family (often pejoratively norms of public reason. There is a debate
associated with a gendered distinction about the status afforded to official pub-
that views the private sphere as “femi- lic deliberation (in political assemblies)
nine”). In contemporary usage, the phrase as opposed to informal and non-official
“private sector” is often used to describe public reflection (in the media, etc.). One
non-governmental business interests may differ with regard to the status of
and economic transactions (where some the norms that govern official political
portion of the economy is also run by deliberation and public (but not official)
the government—the so-called public discourse.
sector)—and there is an ongoing debate Race/Racism:  Race is a category that
about the appropriate relation between attempts to classify individuals by bio-
these sectors in an economy. See civil soci- logical features (usually phenotypic dif-
ety, privacy, public sphere ferences in skin tone, facial features, hair
Progressive/Progressivism:  Progressivism texture, etc.). Racial categorization has
may be understood as the enlightenment been central to colonialism, the slave trade,
faith in progress in history, especially the apartheid regimes, and ongoing inequality
development of republican and democratic (both domestic and global). At one time,
forms of government. In contemporary racial differences and a racialized hierar-
political rhetoric, “progressive” is often chy were supposedly grounded in empiri-
used as a synonym for liberal or Left-wing. cal science (as, e.g. in Nazi race science).

246
GLOSSARY

However, empirical science indicates that of propaganda, surveillance, or violence.


racial differences are usually merely super- Realists focus on pragmatic and strate-
ficial differences and family resemblances gic concerns such as deterrence, suprem-
among human beings. The emerging field acy, and containment of threats. Realist
of critical race studies attempts to under- often ground their criticism of moralis-
stand the history of the concept of race tic idealism in empirical generalizations
and its lasting impact on social and politi- about history and the nature of political
cal institutions and practices. Racism is life (and human psychology). Structural
unjustifiable and pernicious discrimina- realist will also note that the structure
tion against (or in favor of) a racial group. of international relations remains anar-
Some focus on racial distinctions can be chic—because there is no international
used for benevolent purposes (as with sovereign who could resolve international
regard to efforts to study and alleviate conflict—while denying the importance
disparate health or educational outcomes of international law and other cosmopoli-
for diverse racial groups). Racism can be tan forms of international cooperation.
overt and explicit—and written into the Realism can also be used to describe an
law (as in an apartheid regime). Or racism approach to the ethics of war, which holds
can be implicit, in social norms, customs, that there are no moral limits to what can
and practices that produce unequal results be done in war. In this usage, realism is
for member of different racial groups—in understood as the opposite of pacifism.
which case, it is best described as struc- See also idealism.
tural racism. See also structural discrimi- Realpolitik:  An idea about how political
nation. parties strategize and take action that is
Reactionary:  Reactionary parties or opinions grounded in realism about the nature of
are opposed to social and political change social and political life, where realism
and want to move back toward more tra- is understood as offering an assessment
ditional forms of social and political orga- of political reality that is not subject to
nization. In contemporary usage, the term idealistic or moralistic interpretation.
reactionary is often used pejoratively by Realpolitik offers a point of view on
progressives who reject far-right version political reality that recognizes the strug-
of conservatism that is opposed to liberal, gle for power and recognition. It counsels
socialist and other “progressive” social manipulation of social and political forces
and political ideas. See progressive. in the effort to consolidate power. See also
Realism:  In international affairs, realism realism.
emphasizes the struggle for power. Real- Recognition:See struggle for recognition.
ists view the international realm as lack- Refugee:A refugee is a person who has
ing any legal or moral framework that escaped from a conflict by taking refuge
could limit the pursuit of power and self- or seeking sanctuary in a neutral country
interest. Realists recommend strategies or specified locale, where they seek to be
that respond to this fact, while avoiding free from harm. Moral and legal regula-
idealism and optimism about political tions governing the treatment of refugees
behavior. Realists assess the world in include basic rules of hospitality and
terms of balances of power, hegemonic humanitarian law as well as developing
structures, spheres of influence, and so international law, regulated by the office
on. They advise the use of both soft and of the United Nations High Commis-
hard power to increase influence, without sioner for Refugees (the UNHCR). How-
worrying about moral limits on the use ever, refugees often remain displaced and

247
GLOSSARY

dispossessed in camps and with ambigu- grounded the private claims of a ruling
ous political status while conflicts con- party or family; republican forms of gov-
tinue. See also asylum. ernment emphasize equality before the
Regressive:  As the opposite of progressive, law. Republicanism is usually understood
regressive means moving in a backward as closely related to democratic gover-
direction (see also reactionary). In dis- nance. But the primary focus of a republi-
cussion of taxation, a regressive tax is can form of government is the well-being
one that taxes the rich at a lower rate and legal equality of the people who make
(the strict opposite of a progressive tax). up the commonwealth. Thus non-demo-
Other forms of taxation—a sales tax, for cratic forms of government may claim
­example—can have regressive outcomes— to be republics (e.g. as in the “People’s
since this creates the worst impacts for Republic of China”). One issue is the
those with less income, who pay a larger question of who counts in terms of the
percentage of their income on sales taxes people to be included within the public
than richer individuals. (with republican movements occasionally
Relational Justice:  An idea of justice focused understood as aiming to unite a people
on stabilizing and nurturing relationships. divided by colonial power or in some
Rather than applying abstract law and instances aiming to drive out foreign rul-
focusing on desert and retribution, rela- ers or minority ethnic groups). Another
tional justice focuses on building and sup- issue is the extent to which equality and
porting those relationships that constitute hierarchy are permitted within republican
social and political identity (drawing states. The Roman Republic, for example,
especially upon ideas found in feminist was hierarchically organized. So-called
theory). Relational justice is similar to republican states have allowed slavery
restorative justice. or denied rights to women. Contempo-
Relativism:  Relativism is a theory about the rary republican movements tend to be
status of norms, which holds that there is opposed to monarchy and aristocracy and
no absolute, eternal, or objective standard the arbitrariness of non-constitutional
for normative evaluation. Relativists hold rule (whether monarchic or popular),
that values are best understood in rela- while focusing on legal equality. In the
tion to specific contexts: values are “rela- United States, Republican is the name for
tive to” historical or cultural contexts. one of the two major parties (the Demo-
Relativism can be understood as a merely cratic party is the other major party) and
descriptive claim about diversity of val- in American political discourse Republi-
ues, which holds that empirical research canism is associated with both fiscal and
shows us that values vary according to social conservatism grounded in a claim
context. Metaethical relativism builds about the primacy of basic liberties and
upon this descriptive fact to conclude the common good.
that there are no culturally transcendent Restorative Justice:  Restorative justice is
or unconditional values. See also cultural focused on finding ways to heal and
relativism, multiculturalism, pluralism. restore communities that have been dam-
Repression:  See oppression. aged by crime. It can include strategies
Republic/Republican:  A republic is a form of forgiveness, mercy, and rehabilitation.
of political organization focused on the While it offers a critical response to the
good of the commonwealth or the public more stringent approach of retributive
good. This is opposed to political orga- justice, restorative justice accepts the fac-
nization that exploits people or that is ticity of crime, responsibility, and guilt.

248
GLOSSARY

But unlike retributive justice, restorative Rightism (and a rightist) usually connotes
justice responds to those issues in a way an extreme Right-wing (reactionary, rac-
that aims to find acceptable closure for ist, etc.) position. See also Leftism/Left-
both victims and offenders. Restorative wing.
justice is interested in developing produc- Satyagraha:  This Sanskrit term is associ-
tive alternatives to incarceration as well ated with Gandhi’s strategies of nonvio-
as rehabilitation for offenders. An exam- lent social protest. It can be translated as
ple of restorative justice is the “truth and “truth force” or “soul force.” In Gandhi’s
reconciliation” approach utilized in South strategy of nonviolent protest, satyagraha
Africa after the demise of apartheid. See is insistence on truth (and thus upon jus-
also relational justice. tice and fair treatment). It is not passive.
Retributive Justice:  Retributive justice empha- Rather it is active resistance to injustice—
sizes retaliation based in a theory of just but based upon principled commitment to
deserts. The principle of lex talionis (law nonviolence and the idea of unity between
of retaliation) is strictly retributive, requir- means and ends—where truth, non-
ing the return of harm for harm or—as in violence, and justice are viewed as both
the idea of “an eye for an eye.” Retribu- the only appropriate means for political
tive justice limits revenge by establishing action and the goal of such action.
an upper limit for punishment so that one Separation of Powers:  The idea of distin-
does not exact more than is due. Retribu- guishing among political powers—typi-
tive justice also establishes a lower limit of cally focused on the distinction between
what sort of punishment gives due respect legislative, executive, and judicial power.
to the victim and his or her injury. Retrib- This idea of what Cicero called “mixed
utive justice can be contrasted with more government” attempts to avoid concen-
consequentialist focus on restorative jus- tration of power in one person or branch
tice or prevention and deterrence—where of government in order to avoid despotic
the goal of the criminal justice system is to abuse of power. The idea was developed
produce good consequences for the com- by Montesquieu and is a fundamental
munity in the long run. Retributive justice principle of the Constitution of the United
is less concerned with consequentialist States of America, where the idea—asso-
reasoning and more concerned with giv- ciated with James Madison—is that the
ing criminals what they deserve. See also different branches of government should
restorative justice. restrain one another through a system of
Rights:  See human rights; natural rights. checks and balances.
Right-Wing/Rightist:  Right-wing parties Social Contract:  A theory of social organi-
and ideologies are conservative and/ zation that explains the origin and legiti-
or reactionary. The distinction between macy of government. Some versions of
Right-wing and Left-wing parties (or Left- social contract (or compact) theory (as in
ists and Leftism) derives from the French Hobbes, Locke, and Rousseau) attempt to
Revolution, where the parties seated on imagine a historical account of the emer-
the right in the French parliament were gence of civil society and government
supportive of the traditional hierarchy of from out of the state of nature, which
the old regime. Some Right-wing parties would have involved the consent of those
are conservative supporters of libertar- who agree to transfer their natural rights
ian ideas about free markets. Other “far to a central governing force. Other more
right” parties may be racist and national- contemporary versions of the social con-
istic and more sympathetic to state power. tract theory (as in Rawls) acknowledge

249
GLOSSARY

that there may not have been a historical social justice concerns can be found in the
contracting event but still employ a ver- Christian tradition, social justice emerges
sion of the social contract idea as a heuris- as a concern in contemporary utilitarian-
tic to explain how agreement about moral ism and socialism.
and political values might occur and to Socialism:  Socialism is a political theory
describe what that agreement might con- and movement concerned with the soci-
sist in. Social contract theories point in etal ownership and distribution of basic
a liberal direction since they ground the goods. Socialism is usually understood as
authority of the government on the con- being opposed to capitalism, when capi-
sent of the governed, often assuming that talism is understood as defending private
the importance of consent is grounded in ownership, marketplace distributions, and
some basic idea of natural rights. libertarian social and political policies.
Social Democracy:  A political ideology and Socialists want to restrain markets and
movement intended to transform society control private property, with the goal of
in a socialist direction through the use of minimizing inequality and empowering
peaceful, democratic means (as opposed the majority of the working class. Social-
to the proposed violent transition imag- ism comes in a wide variety of types—from
ined by Marxists). Social democrats anarchist and separatist socialism (some-
emphasize communitarian values and are times described as communalism) to radi-
critical of capitalism and the emphasis on cal revolutionary state-centered socialism
merely negative rights associated with so- (i.e. twentieth-century Communism) to
called libertarian democracy. Social dem- reformist and democratic socialism that
ocrats are not fundamentally opposed wants to find ways to accommodate capi-
to restrained forms of capitalism, as so- talism and private property without giv-
called democratic socialists often are. ing up on labor rights and social equality.
Social democracy is based upon com- See also communism.
mitment to political processes of inclu- Sovereignty:  Supreme authority or power
sion, nonviolence, and social welfare, within a territory including the right to
often arguing that these ideas enhance make law and administer justice. This
democracy by increasing the quality of includes the right to take life, liberty, and
participation and civic virtue. Post-war property in the name of social order and
European countries have been largely justice. Sovereignty is an important con-
influenced by social democratic ideas. See cept for international relations—as sov-
also welfare state. ereign states are understood as individual
Social Justice:  Social justice is a commit- entities and afforded sovereign equality.
ment to welfare grounded in respect for In domestic terms, sovereignty can be
the dignity of persons and the common organized and understood in a variety of
good. The idea of social justice is cen- ways: as the will of the monarch (volun-
tral to natural law and Catholic social tarism), as the will of the people (popu-
teaching, which includes a broad com- lar sovereignty), or as a mix of forms
mitment to alleviating poverty, improving and institutions. Sovereignty may also be
the quality of life, labor, and healthcare, understood in absolute terms (as a basic
and diminishing violence. Social justice is right of nonintervention that ought not
often connected with the idea of distribu- be violated) or a contingent upon the
tive justice, focused on reducing inequal- legitimacy or justice of domestic political
ity and providing fair access to social arrangements or recognition by the inter-
goods and economic opportunities. While national community.

250
GLOSSARY

State:  A state is a basic entity of politi- tive conditions. Descriptions of the state
cal organization. In Weber’s influential of nature may have some basis in archae-
description, a state is a political organi- ological and anthropological fact. How-
zation that possesses a monopoly on the ever, the early modern social contract
use of force in a given territory—which theorists often based their understanding
implies autonomy from external control of the state of nature on generalizations
and the ability to defend borders. States not grounded in the historical record: for
can be organized into larger structures— example, in Hobbes’s description of the
empires, confederations, and so on. States state of nature as a state of war in which
can contain smaller organizational units. life would be solitary, poor, nasty, brut-
This diversity of levels of organization ish, or short; or in Rousseau’s description
makes it difficult to establish with pre- of the state of nature as belonging to his
cision exactly what counts as the basic idealized conception of the noble savage.
unity of political organization. A further The state of nature is best understood
problem is that states can contain inter- as an imagined or constructed thought-
nal division and strife that prevents effec- ­experiment which is used to express
tive control or the exercise of the sorts of fundamental conceptions about human
rights and responsibilities associated with nature and political life.
states (as in so-called failed states). Statelessness:  Some refugees, displaced per-
State Capitalism:  A form of economic and sons, and exiles end up in the politically
political organization in which the state tenuous position of being stateless. State-
owns and runs business enterprises for less persons have lost citizenship rights
profit. Unlike socialist political organiza- either through their own voluntary renun-
tions in which state ownership is aimed ciation of their original citizenship or
at social welfare, equality, and the like, through coercive expulsion or through the
state capitalism is oriented toward mak- dissolution of a previous political affilia-
ing a profit. Unlike free-market (laissez- tion (as when a state collapses, dissolves,
faire) or liberal capitalism, where the state or is incorporated into another state).
avoids undue interference in private busi- Stateless persons are often refugees who
ness ventures, state capitalism can involve are unable to find a country with whom
substantial control over the domestic they can affiliate. Stateless persons exists
economy. While the concept may focus outside the boundaries of ordinary politi-
primarily on domestic organization, state cal life and especially vulnerable to human
capitalism may also be used to describe rights violations. Agamben equates the
the role of state-based economies in inter- stateless condition with the idea of homo
national markets. Advocates of global free sacer—the “sacred man” who is liable to
trade may argue that state capitalism (e.g. being killed because he resides in an extra-
as in China) is inefficient and prevents legal limbo. The United Nations has taken
fair competition on the international steps to eradicate statelessness.
market. Defenders of state capitalism will Structural Discrimination:  Structural dis-
argue that state control of profit-seeking crimination (including structural racism)
ventures allows for greater control and is discrimination that occur not because
greater distribution of social benefits. of overt expressions of bias or prejudice
State of Nature:  A pre-political condition but, rather, because of structural prob-
described by social contract theorists, lems that create unequal outcomes. It
who explain in various ways how politi- can also be described as institutional or
cal organization developed out of primi- organizational discrimination. Institu-

251
GLOSSARY

tions can be organized in ways that can which opens voting and office holding to
create sexist, racist, or classist results. all citizens.
Unlike overt racism or sexism, the nega- Tyranny:  Tyranny is understood as a per-
tive results of institutional structures may nicious, predatory, cruel, despotic, and
not be intended by any agent operating oppressive government. The term derives
within the system. For example, a system from the Greek tyrannos, which at one
in which it is easier for men to succeed time simply meant ruler. A tyrannical gov-
than for women (because of childcare ernment is usually understood as monar-
and family leave regulations) may not chical or autocratic—headed by a tyrant,
intend to discriminate against women or who is a despotic ruler, especially one who
produce inequality, even though inequal- rules for his own self-interest. However,
ity results. Related to this are discrimina- specific laws and policies (of a variety of
tory outcomes resulting from stereotypes government) can be condemned as tyran-
and media caricatures that can disem- nical when they are oppressive. See also
power members of minority groups. See autocracy, despotism.
also racism. Theocracy:  A theocracy is government based
Struggle for Recognition:  The concept of the on religion. Theocratic regimes are run by
struggle for recognition is associated with clerics, under religious law and with an
the master–slave dialectic as found in implicit or explicit claim about legitimacy
Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit. Hegel based in the will of God. In a less precise
suggested that social life could be under- usage, the term theocracy or the adjective
stood as a struggle for recognition. This theocratic can be used as a description for
concept was developed in Marxism, Criti- laws or policies that are based on religious
cal Theory, and the work of Francis Fuku- ideas or religious law.
yama who argued that liberal-democracy Tolerance/Toleration:  The terms tolerance
provided a solution to the struggle for and toleration are often used interchange-
recognition. The usual solution is mutual able, although there is an important dis-
recognition, which does not involve dom- tinction between tolerance as a virtue
ination and hierarchy. The importance of (which can be developed within individu-
the concept is that it claims that social als or associations) and toleration as a
struggle cannot be merely understood constitutional or legal policy of neutral-
in terms of the pursuit of material self- ity and impartiality. Tolerance as a virtue
interest. Rather, social struggle is about implies the habit of non-judgmentalism. It
the desire to be recognized as an agent may be understood as a minimal sort of
worthy of respect. Charles Taylor and modus vivendi, which grudgingly accom-
Axel Honneth use this idea to explain modates the fact of diversity. But it can
so-called identity politics. Nancy Fraser also be a more robust affirmation of dif-
has explained that social problems occur ference. Toleration as a political and legal
when persons suffer the burden of subor- principle implies that the state is neutral
dination of status. See also multicultural- in moral or religious disputes. The terms
ism, identity politics. are also applied in discussions of racial
Suffrage:  The ability to vote; also known and ethnic issues—as ideas that encourage
as “the franchise” as in “political fran- acceptance of racial and other differences
chise.” Suffrage also includes the idea of and overcoming prejudices and stereo-
being eligible to be elected. In the his- types. Toleration is typically thought to
tory of democracy, suffrage has gradually be an essential feature of liberal regimes.
been expanded toward universal suffrage, See also liberalism.

252
GLOSSARY

Totalitarianism:  Totalitarianism is used to tion involves imagining ideal worlds and


describe systems of governance that aim can help clarify values and principles.
for complete control over the lives of the Critics of utopian speculation in political
populace. Totalitarian government does philosophy argue that speculative utopias
not tolerate dissent and requires con- are too focused on a priori ideals and that
formity. Totalitarian governments aim utopias distract us from real-world con-
beyond mere external conformity and obe- cerns. A related term dystopia is used as
dience toward ideological purity and una- the opposite of utopia, to describe nega-
nimity. Totalitarian regimes are opposed tive worlds and bad outcomes.
to openness, nonconformity, and liberty. War:  War is a sustained armed struggle with
Totalitarian ideology is closely related to political intent, usually focused on the
fascism, often understanding the polity as goal of obtaining control over territory.
an organic whole which must be coordi- However, there are a variety of wars—
nated and organized in an all-encompass- from international wars involving federa-
ing and comprehensive fashion. tions of nations allied against one another
Tragedy of the Commons:  A problem that to civil wars, cross-border incursions, and
arises in discussions of economic ratio- small skirmishes and battles. Theories of
nality and game theory, which holds the morality of war include just war the-
that self-interested individuals will tend ory, realism, and pacifism.
to overuse common areas and shared War Crimes:  War crimes violate principles
resources, since no one will want to obey governing proper behavior in war. Dis-
limits that are not also obeyed by oth- putes about the status of the norms
ers. Without an authority able to impose governing behavior in war ask whether
limitations on use, tragic outcomes result war crimes are merely conventional (a
as the productivity and sustainability of result of treaties and agreements among
common resources will be destroyed by nations) or whether there is a natural law
overuse. See also prisoner’s dilemma. or law of peoples which transcends con-
Unitary State:  A state in which sovereignty ventional morality. The concept of a war
and control are strictly organized by cen- crime is related to the norms of the just
tralized power. Unlike a confederation or war theory. The concept of war crimes
a system based on federalism, in which has developed in recent decades with the
power is shared between local and pro- advent of post-war tribunals (e.g. the
vincial structures and the national gov- Tokyo and Nuremburg tribunals) and
ernment, a unitary state avoids this sort with the development of international
of power sharing. Unitary states may be law and institutions. These tribunals and
monarchic and absolutist or democratic, treaties establish that war crimes include
liberal, and/or republican. The question crimes against the peace (unjustified
of unity is about issues such as federalism aggression), crimes against humanity,
or a separation of powers. and genocide. War crimes include mis-
Utopia:  A utopia is an idealized form of treatment or slaughter of prisoners, the
social or political organization. The term use of poison gas, the use of civilians as
utopia was coined by Thomas More in shields, rape, ethnic cleansing, and so on.
the sixteenth century as a play on two A remaining difficulty is how war crimes
Greek terms: atopia (no place) and euto- are to be tried and punished. See also just
pia (good place). A utopia is thus under- war theory.
stood as an ideal that is also fictional and Welfare State:  The welfare state is concerned
perhaps unattainable. Utopian specula- with promoting social welfare. Mod-

253
GLOSSARY

ern bureaucratic welfare states generally not go far enough in terms of social redis-
include a system of social security, social tribution of goods. Defenders will argue
insurance, or a social safety net, as well that social welfare is one of the primary
as a system of public health care, public purposes of political association and that
education, unemployment compensa- capitalist economies benefit in the long
tion, nutritional support, and so on that run from public welfare. See also social
provide basic welfare benefits for all citi- democracy, social justice.
zens. A key idea is that the state ought to
be concerned with social justice and the
welfare of its citizens. Critics of welfare
states will argue that welfarism under- Note
mines individual initiative and promotes
dependency. Communist/socialist critics 1
Special thanks to Chisanga Chanda for her
will argue that capitalist welfare states do work on this glossary.

254
RESEARCH RESOURCES1

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Philosophy Papers Online <http://philpapers.


<http://plato.stanford.edu/cite.html> org>

One of the best internet resources in phi- Philosophy Papers Online, also known as
losophy features lengthy scholarly entries on PhilPapers, is project of the Center for Digital
a wide variety of topics and philosophers. Philosophy. It provides an online research
Entries are written by leading scholars in tool in philosophy. PhilPapers is an extensive
the field and updated regularly. Contains a index of scholarly articles and books in philos-
search engine and extensive cross references ophy, with a useful search engine and outline
between entries. Articles include extensive that organizes content according to subject-
bibliographies. Includes other academic tools matter. Useful for students interested in the
including those that teach how to cite and History of Western Philosophy; African and
format bibliographies. Entries on the website Asian Philosophy; Continental Philosophy;
can be read on via PDFs, Kindle, iPhone, and European Philosophy; Philosophies of the
Android applications. Americas; Anthropologies; and so on. While
links to some entries may be unavailable or
Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy <http:// may require permission, this website is still a
www.iep.utm.edu/> valuable resource that can be supplemented
by libraries that provide access to electronic
Another online database of peer-reviewed journal.
articles. The Internet Encyclopedia has infor-
mation similar to the Stanford Encyclopedia; The Online Library of Liberty <http://oll.­
however, it is not clear that the articles are libertyfund.org>
updated with the frequency of the Stanford
Encyclopedia. Entries in the IEP focus on A useful internet resource that includes an
topics such as the History of Philosophy; extensive archive of primary source material,
Metaphysics and Epistemology; Philosophical especially classic texts concerning the phi-
Traditions; Science, Logic, and Mathematics; losophy of liberty and political philosophy
and Value Theory. in general. The website has free electronic

255
RESEARCH RESOURCES

versions and EBooks of classical and con- and dates regarding conferences and major
temporary books about Individual liberty activities of the organization.
and Limited Government from disciplines
of Economics, History, Law, Literature, The British Philosophical Association <http://
Philosophy, Political Theory, Religion, War, www.bpa.ac.uk>
and Peace. The online library is very well
organized and easy to use. It categorizes its The British Philosophical Association is an
entire collection by the Latest Additions; important organization and internet resource
Authors by Period; Women on Liberty; and for articles, journals, and books centering
Titles by Subject. on European contemporary philosophical
issues. What makes the British Philosophical
The American Philosophical Association Association distinctive is that its membership
<http://www.apaonline.org> gives access to Oxford journals and books
published by Routledge.
The American Philosophical Association is
an organization of philosophers in the United Radical Philosophy Association <http://
States. The website allows Student Association www.radicalphilosophyassociation.org>
Membership for students at accredited
American and International colleges and uni- The Radical Philosophy Association is a
versities. Valuable for research concerning membership-based organization that pub-
contemporary issues in philosophy such as lishes peer-reviewed articles on the adverse
Feminism, Hispanic/Latino Issues, Indigenous effects of capitalism, racism, sexism, homo-
Issues, LGBT Issues, the Black Experience, phobia, disability discrimination, and envi-
Technology, Law and Medicine. The APA ronmental damage around the world.
website includes information about proceed-
ings, addresses, newsletters, and meetings of The North American Association for Social
the American Philosophical Association in its Philosophy <http://www.pitt.edu/~nassp/
three divisions: Eastern, Central, and Pacific. nassp.html>

The European Philosophy of Science The North American Association for Social
Association Philosophy (NASSP) is one of the largest
associations focused on social and political
<http://www.epsa.ac.at>The European philosophy. The organization holds annual
Philosophical Association is also an organi- meetings and publishes Journal of Social
zation of philosophers in Europe. The Philosophy. The organization also sponsors
European Association is very similar to the the Social Philosophy Today book series.
American Philosophical Association. It was
recently established (2007) and does not International Society for Military Ethics
have a variety of publications, journals, and <http://isme.tamu.edu/>
newsletters as the APA. Nonetheless, it is
useful for students interested in European The International Society for Military
Philosophy. The website is also great for links Ethics (ISME) holds an annual conference

256
RESEARCH RESOURCES

on military ethics and issues related to the Political Science and Politics. These journals
ethics of war. The ISME website includes may be beneficial for students interested in
links to case studies, publications, and other contemporary topics in political science.
resources in the field of military ethics and This is a membership-based Association.
the ethics of war. Students interested in opportunities in gov-
ernment and politics may find this organiza-
Association for Political Theory <http:// tion useful.
www.apt-us.org/>
International Association for the Philosophy
The Association for Political Theory is of Law and Social Philosophy <http://ivron-
an organization whose aim is to promote line.org/>
teaching and research in political theory
and political philosophy. The organization The International Association for the
hosts an annual meeting. The APT web- Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy
site includes links to journals publishing (IVR—for Internationale Vereinigung für
in the field of political theory as well as Rechts-und Sozialphilosophie) is an interna-
calls for papers for other organizations and tional organization that host a world con-
journals. gress focused on topics in philosophy of law,
social philosophy, and political philosophy.
Concerned Philosophers for Peace <http:// The IVR includes national branches includ-
peacephilosophy.org> ing a UK branch (http://www.law.qmul.ac.uk/
research/centres/clsgc/ivr/index.html) and
Concerned Philosophers for Peace is an the American Section of the International
organization of philosophers interested in Association for the Philosophy of Law and
the philosophy of peace and nonviolence. Social Philosophy (AMINTAPHIL) http://
The organization meets annually as well as amintaphil.philosophy.utah.edu/. Both the
holding sessions at the divisional meetings UK branch and AMINTAPHIL hold meetings
of the American Philosophical Association. focused on a topic in social, legal, or political
The organization publishes a newsletter and philosophy.
also sponsors a philosophy of peace book
series. The American Society for Political and Legal
Philosophy <http://www.political-theory.org/>
The American Political Science Association
<http://www.apsanet.org> The American Society for Political and
Legal Philosophy (ASPLP) is a scholarly
The American Political Science Association organization dedicated to scholarship in
(APSA) is the disciplinary association for legal and political philosophy. It publishes
political scientists in the United States. NOMOS an annual volume dedicated
Its website provides an excellent internet to cutting edge research in these areas.
research tool. It publishes three leading peer- According to the ASLP website, “The
reviewed journals: The American Political ASPLP leadership has included some of
Science Review; Perspectives on Politics; and the most distinguished and accomplished

257
RESEARCH RESOURCES

scholars in political and legal philoso- United Nations Human Development Report
phy including John Rawls, Lon Fuller and <www.undp.org/content/undp/en/home.
Judith Shklar.” html>

Open Library <https://openlibrary.org> The annual Human Development Report


by the United Nations is the best of several
Open Library has over 1 million free EBooks sources for students interested in economic
available online. Students of philosophy and analytical data concerning the alleviation
politics may take particular interest with of Global Poverty; Building Democratic
the website because it gives instant access Societies; Preventing Crisis; Protecting the
to books that may no longer be in print or Environment; Halting and Reversing HIV/
might be difficult to find at popular online AIDS; Empowering Women; Growing
and local bookstores. National Capacity; and so on.

The Office of the United Nations High Carnegie Council for Ethics and International
Commissioner for Human Rights <http:// Affairs <http://www.carnegiecouncil.org/
www.ohchr.org/> index.html>

The Office of the United Nations High The Carnegie Council publishes the jour-
Commissioner for Human Rights creates a nal Ethics and International Affairs. They
wide range of publications on topics related hold meetings and support research in top-
to human rights. This is a great research tool ics of concern for political philosophers. The
for students interested in or concerned about Carnegie Council website includes useful
human rights violations around the world. links and information, including links to lists
The website is also great because it provides of films of interest and a monthly column on
free access to publications and handbooks current events/issues.
from other active organizations such as
Freedom House <http://www.freedomhouse.
org>; Amnesty International <http://www. Note
amnesty.org>; Human Rights Watch <http://
www.hrw.org>. 1
Thanks to Chisanga Chanda for her assistance.

258
ANNOTATED BIBLIOGRAPHY

Arendt, H., The Origins of Totalitarianism extending principles of distributive justice


(New York: Harcourt, 1951). An account to the international realm. Denies the
of the development of totalitarian Hobbesian assumption that states are
political organization focused primarily entities that can be considered in isolation
on Nazism and Stalinism. The book from principles of justice. An important
also contains important discussions of text for understanding cosmopolitanism.
anti-Semitism, racism, and the function Berlin, I., Four Essays on Liberty (Oxford
of ideology and terror within a lawful University Press, 1969—reprinted as
government grounded on oppression and Liberty, Oxford, 2002). Contains the
domination. important essay, “Two Concepts of
— On Revolution (New York: Penguin, Liberty,” which clarifies the distinction
1962). An examination of American between positive and negative liberty.
and French revolutions that explores Berlin argues that these two concepts are
the importance of liberty and pluralism often confused and that the distinction
and a robust public sphere. A central indicates the need for a pluralistic
problem is the contrast between the approach that recognizes rival goods.
dynamic revolutionary spirit of the Cohen, J. L., Globalization and
revolutionary generation, which aims to Sovereignty: Rethinking Legality,
found a new constitution, and the less Legitimacy, and Constitutionalism
dynamic and anti-revolutionary result of (Cambridge: Cambridge University
constitutionally bound political life. Press, 2012). A book considering the
— On Violence (New York: Harcourt, newly emerging international order
1970). An attempt to define and explain under the United Nations, including
the differences between violence, power, critiques of hegemony and hierarchy and
force, strength, and authority. Arendt a call for international norms respecting
suggests that violence is a tool that can human rights, political autonomy and
create obedience; but authority and sovereignty, as well as constitutional
power are not merely created by violence. principles.
Beitz, C., Political Theory and International Cohen, J., Philosophy, Politics, Democracy:
Relations (Princeton, NJ: Princeton Selected Essays (Cambridge, MA:
University Press, 1973). Concerned with Harvard University Press, 2009). Cohen

259
ANNOTATED Bibliography

defends and describes the relation book is a genealogical account of the


between democracy and reasoned development of modern technologies of
discourse, while opposing cynicism about power and discipline—and their relation
political life (which holds that politics is to the emergence of subjectivity—with a
merely about power struggles). special focus on prisons and schools.
Dussel, E., Politics of Liberation: A Fukuyama, F., The Origins of Political
Critical Global History (London: SCM Order: From PreHuman Times to the
Press, 2011). Dussel is a prominent French Revolution (New York: Farrar,
Latin American philosopher who has Strauss, & Giroux, 2011). An account of
published several major works in which the evolution of political organizations.
he criticizes the Eurocentric bias in The first of a two volume account of the
political philosophy and in philosophy evolution (and potential devolution) of
generally. In this book, Dussel attempts to democracy.
deconstruct the Greek-centric and Euro- Geuss, R., Philosophy and Real Politics
centric lenses that structure our thinking (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
about philosophy and politics, while Press, 2008). A critical examination of
applying insights gleaned from liberation political philosophizing that criticizes
theology. abstract, idealizing approaches, while
Dworkin, R., Law’s Empire (Cambridge, emphasizing politics as a craft or skill
MA: Harvard University Press, 1986). that is historical located and motivated
Dworkin argues against the sort of legal by various interests, forces and needs.
positivism he associates with H. L. A. Gewirth, A., The Community of Rights
Hart. Dworkin maintains that there are (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
norms of consistency and interpretation 1996). An account of universality
that apply beyond merely historical and equality in human rights, which
positivism. These norms include keeping maintains that state intervention and
faith with institutional and historical active community support are necessary
precedent. Dworkin uses the example of components of rights protection.
Judge Hercules as an ideal adjudicator Habermas, J., The Structural Transformation
who should in principle be able to reach a of the Public Sphere (Cambridge, MA:
correct conclusion in hard cases of law. MIT Press, 1989—originally published
— Sovereign Virtue (Cambridge, MA: in German in 1962). Habermas’s account
Harvard University Press, 2000). A of the development of the public sphere
book focussed on equality as a primary during the Enlightenment and beyond.
value in both political structures and This demonstrates the historical basis of
distributive justice. A clear articulation Habermas’s ideal of public deliberation
of the idea of liberal egalitarianism, in and legitimation.
which governmental redistributions seek — Theory of Communicative Action,
to remedy disadvantages resulting from vols I and II (Boston, MA: Beacon,
bad luck. 1984/7—originally published in
Foucault, M., Discipline and Punish (New German in 1981). Habermas’s theory
York: Pantheon, 1977—originally of how norms and legitimation develop
published in French in 1975). This within communicative acts and within

260
ANNOTATED Bibliography

communities of discourse. The shared Stanford University Press, 2002). A


assumption of linguistic communication seminal text of the Frankfurt School of
is the goal of understanding, which critical theory. Focused on development
involves mutuality. of totalitarian social and political
— Between Facts and Norms (Cambridge, systems, with a related interest in
MA: MIT Press, 1996—originally propaganda and the culture industry.
published in German in 1992). Kymlicka, W., Multicultural Citizenship
Habermas’s account of the relation (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995).
between public discourse/deliberation A defense of minority group identity and
and the legal system. One focus is the rights, including specific representation
derivation of “rights” from principles of and legal exemptions for certain racial,
intersubjectivity and public discourse. religious or ethnic groups.
Another focus is the legitimation of law Marcuse, H., One-Dimensional Man
as a concretion of mutual understanding (Boston, MA: Beacon, 1964). An
(and not merely as external authority). important work of critical theory, which
Hart, H. L. A., The Concept of Law, 3rd argues against the tendency of large
Edition (Oxford: Oxford University Press, social and political entities to reduce
2012—originally published 1961). One and eliminate opportunities for critique,
of the most important works defending while dominating thought through both
the idea of legal positivism. Hart argues productive activity and consumer culture.
that laws and legal institutions have The solution is refusal and negation.
a normative power that results from Miller, D., On Nationality (Oxford:
general recognition of their validity. Clarendon Press, 1995). A defense of
Hayek, F., The Road to Serfdom (Chicago: nationalism and national identity—
University of Chicago Press, 1944). against both liberals and globalists who
An argument against centralized view nationalism as old-fashioned and
governmental control of the economy multiculturalists who advocate for sub-
(socialism) and defense of free market national identity.
libertarianism. Mouffe, C., On the Political (New York:
— The Constitution of Liberty (Chicago: Routledge, 2005). Mouffe defends
University of Chicago Press, 1960). A agonistic pluralism—or antagonistic
defense of classical liberalism in political political struggles—against idealizing
thought focused on protecting individual attempts to avoid the reality of political
liberty against coercion by others or by struggle. For Mouffe, reconciliation and
the state. Protection of liberty occurs best consensus are not sufficient to rule out
under the “rule of law”: public law helps the unruly aspects of democracy and
to limit the arbitrary will of despotic political life.
government. Negri, A. and M. Hardt, Empire
Horkheimer, M. and T. Adorno, Dialectic (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
of Enlightenment (Amsterdam: Querido, Press, 2000). Examines the imperial
1947; English translation in 1972 by aspects of the emerging unipolar world.
John Cumming; more recent translation Focused on the institutional structures
by Edmund Jephcott—Stanford, CA: of contemporary globalization, the book

261
ANNOTATED Bibliography

argues that there is a new post-national bear on the texts of the canon of political
capitalist structure called “Empire” that philosophy.
dominates the globe. Pogge, T., World Poverty and Human Rights
Nozick, R., Anarchy, State, Utopia (New (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2002—revised
York: Basic Books, 1974). Nozick’s second edition, 2008). Pogge’s analysis
libertarian text offers a reconstruction of of global injustice results in a call for
social contract/state-of-nature arguments. redistribution of global income and
Nozick argues in defense of what is wealth. This is a now classic text in the
called a “minimal state.” Nozick presents growing literature of cosmopolitanism.
arguments against distributive justice, Popper, K., The Open Society and Its
including a critique of John Rawls’s Enemies, 2 vols (London: Routledge,
work. 1945). An analysis of illiberal political
Nussbaum, M.C., Sex and Social philosophy from Plato to Hegel and on
Justice (Oxford: Oxford University to twentieth-century totalitarianism.
Press, 1998). A feminist approach to Popper defends democracy and liberal
international justice issues, focused “open societies” against the utopian hope
on the “capabilities approach.” This of totalitarian idealisms. While Popper’s
attempts to be sensitive to local and reading of the history of philosophy is
cultural differences, while also providing tendentious, his advocacy of the open
a critical framework for discussing the society (and his mis-reading of Hegel) has
oppression of women. been influential.
— Frontiers of Justice: Disability, Rawls, J., A Theory of Justice (Cambridge,
Nationality, Species Membership MA: Harvard University Press, 1971).
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University The definitive modern liberal account
Press, 2006). An extension of Rawlsian of distributive justice (and “justice as
liberal ideas to “marginal cases,” fairness”) based upon a hypothetical
including considerations of the disabled, contract made by rational agents who
immigrants and noncitizens, and non- agree upon principles of justice under a
human animals. “veil of ignorance” in what Rawls calls
Oakeshott, M., On Human Conduct “the original position.” Two principles of
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1975). justice are derived: the liberty principle
An analysis of political life based upon and the difference principle.
the idea of civil associations as voluntary — Political Liberalism (New York:
and reciprocal associations based upon Columbia University Press, 1993).
human intelligence and understanding Extension of Rawls’s ideas about
(and thus not compulsory association or justice as fairness that develops out of
organic holism). “reasonable pluralism.” Examines the
Pocock, J. G. A., Politics, Language, and possibility of establishing “overlapping
Time: Essays on Political Thought and consensus” among people who
History (Chicago: University of Chicago fundamentally disagree about their
Press, 1989). An explanation and defense “comprehensive schemes” or worldviews.
of the history of political thought. Brings — The Law of Peoples (Cambridge,
contemporary historical methodologies to MA: Harvard University Press, 1999).

262
ANNOTATED Bibliography

Rawls’s consideration of international a more organic polity in which citizenship


law and relations. Rawls imagines an and friendship are closely intertwined.
international agreement arising out of an Sen, A., The Idea of Justice (Cambridge,
international “original position” in which MA: Harvard University Press, 2009).
representatives of “peoples” deliberate Sen’s contribution to the critique of
about international relations. Discusses liberalism and Rawlsian political
the difference between ideal theory philosophy. Sen’s focus is comparative
and non-ideal theory (including how justice, grounded in actual arrangements
well-ordered liberal states should relate in the real world—as opposed to an
to “decent hierarchical societies” and idealized theory of justice.
“burdened states” and “outlaw regimes”). Strauss, L., Natural Right and History
Sandel, M., Liberalism and the Limits (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
of Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge 1953). Strauss’s historical inquiry
University Press, 1982). A critique into the question of whether there
of liberal political theory that is one is something called “natural right”
of the primary texts associated with which transcends history or whether
so-called communitarian criticism. Sandel “historicism” and related skeptical ideas
argues that the thinness of Rawls’s such as “positivism” and “nihilism” are
veil of ignorance divorces us from our correct. Related to this is the question
most deeply held values including our of whether political philosophy itself is
commitment to a vision of the good life. possible—as a theory of abstract and
Schmitt, C., Political Theology (originally absolute truth about political life—or
published 1919; Schwab translation first whether political philosophy is merely
published by the University of Chicago historically located.
Press, 1985). Theory of sovereignty that — What is Political Philosophy? (Chicago:
relates secular political power to religious University of Chicago, 1959). Several
ideas. Schmitt examines the limits of important essays by Strauss are collected
law in a so-called state of emergency here, including the title essay, which
to indicate that sovereign power argues that political philosophy is enquiry
resides outside of the law. A theory of about the good life.
sovereignty that was influential for anti- Walzer, M., Just and Unjust Wars (New
liberal political movements during the York: Basic Books, 1977). Walzer’s
twentieth century. now classic restatement of the just war
— The Concept of the Political (first tradition, with significant examples taken
published 1932; Schwab translation first from recent history. Walzer examines
published by the University of Chicago controversial topics such as war crimes,
Press, 1996). Schmitt’s notorious defense terrorism and supreme emergencies.
of extra-legal dictatorship. Schmitt argues Several newer editions have appeared
that a central political distinction is the with updates related to contemporary
difference between enemy and friend in issues.
the state of war. This distinction leads to — Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Pluralism
a critique of liberal polities, which permit and Equality (New York: Basic Books,
non-friends to be citizens. The solution is 1983). Walzer’s account of the complexity

263
ANNOTATED Bibliography

of justice, based upon the notion of Vocation” essay is famous for introducing
“complex equality” and various spheres in the idea that political authority possesses
which—and across and through which— a monopoly on the use of violence; as
justice is considered and distributed. well as the idea of administration or
Walzer reminds us that domination across bureaucracy.
spheres is unjust and that distributions Young, I. M., Justice and the Politics of
within each sphere should be based upon Difference (Princeton, NJ: Princeton
independent criteria. University Press, 1990). An important
Weber, M., The Protestant Ethic and the contribution to feminist theory of politics.
Spirit of Capitalism (originally published Young argues that democratic theory
1905—Kalberg translation 2010, has too long assumed a homogeneous
Oxford: Oxford University Press). Work polity (usually defined by and in terms
of sociology and political philosophy of the white, male ruling class). Young
that relates economics to religion and calls for more participation and for more
spiritual, ethical practice. Influential on opportunities for participation for groups
subsequent sociology of religion and previously excluded.
theories of economics. — Inclusion and Democracy (Oxford:
— The Vocation Lectures: Science Oxford University Press, 2001). Feminist
As a Vocation, Politics As a lens applies to issues in political
Vocation (originally published philosophy, especially democratic theory
1917/1919—Livingstone translation and liberalism. Focuses on the way that
2004, Indianapolis: IN: Hackett). Theory certain modes of discourse exclude (or
of political life and leadership, as well include) marginalized groups. Includes a
as theory of science. The “Politics as call for global democratic institutions.

264
Index

absolutism  35, 227 Bodin, J.  35, 38, 216


Adorno, T.  233, 261 bureaucracy,  35, 156, 228
agonism  153, 161–2, 261
ahimsa  130, 244 Cambridge School  23–4, 28
see also nonviolence Canada  105, 203, 242
anarchy/anarchism  4, 6, 36–8, 133, capitalism  133–5, 156, 228, 240, 251
162, 227 and communism/socialism  231, 250
Daoist  130 care chains  192–3
international  110 care ethics  129, 168–71, 192–3
anthropocene  213–20 Carens, J.  188–90
anthropocentric/-ism  235 China  26, 89, 112, 117, 120, 216,
anthropology  4, 7–8, 10, 110, 117, 215, 251 228, 248, 251
Aquinas, T.  4, 37, 38 Cicero  201, 242, 249
Arendt, H.  7, 34–5, 239–40, 259 citizenship  229, 238, 243, 251
Aristocracy  227, 244, 248 cosmopolitanism  47, 51, 55, 163, 202,
Aristotle  4, 6–7, 10–13, 20–1, 75–6, 96, 204–5
103, 214, 242 democracy  153–8, 203
associative ownership argument  187–8 immigration  183, 187–90
asylum  67–8, 113, 184, 227 sovereignty  36
Augustine  4, 5, 7, 38, 110 women  176
Austin, J.  42 civil disobedience  33, 37, 118, 133, 229,
authoritarian(-ism)  2, 110, 227 231, 244
autocracy  227, 234 civility  139, 144–5, 148, 230
autonomy  228 civilization  4, 131, 214–15, 229
and democracy  153–63 civil rights  127, 229–30, 238, 241, 244
Kantian  154 civil society  84, 230
of individuals  36, 68, 80 cosmopolitan  204
of political groups  50, 52–3 democratic theory  203
and surrogacy  178 Kant on crime in  98
and toleration  140–8 liberal-democratic  142, 149
Locke and religion  147
Beitz, C.  49–52, 62–4, 85 private sphere  246
Benhabib, S.  159, 161, 175 social contract  249
Berlin, I.  237, 259 Clausewitz, C.  109–17, 120

265
Index

Cohen, J.  2, 259 capitalism  228


Cohen, J. L.  41, 259 cosmopolitanism  51, 190
collectivism  230 deliberative democracy  153, 159–61,
colonialism  5, 39, 230 175, 233
Eurocentrism  3, 213–20 distributive justice  76
see also postcolonial feminism/gender  167–8, 171, 175–80
communism  231 immigration  183–5
and capitalism  228 peace  133–5
Soviet  128 right in  62, 72
see also Marxism; socialism social contract  35–6
communitarianism  105–6, 148, 160, 231 toleration  139–46, 149
Confucianism  27, 117, 214 despotism  34, 234
conscientious objection/refusal  33, 37, 39, Dewey, J.  2, 3, 158–9, 163
133, 229, 231 distributive justice  9, 16, 49, 52 Chapter 5
conservatism  232, 239, 241, 246 (75–93), 234, 240, 250
constitution/constitutionalism  6, 8, 11, 41, environmentalism  235
153, 232 feminism and gender  173–4, 237
democratic deliberation  159 luck  190
division of power  43, 143 divine right of kings  7, 35, 234
globalized  220 division of labor  4, 228, 234, 237
Kantian  133 gender  168, 175–6, 178
Rawls  159 domination  6, 35, 89, 174, 179, 233, 236,
rights  63, 219 252
toleration  139 Dunn, J.  23–4, 27
U.K.  143 Dussel, E.,  213–16
U.S.  99–100, 143 Dworkin, R.  36, 75–7, 81, 155, 157
contract/contractarian  see social contract/
social compact egalitarian/ism  234–5
cosmopolitan/cosmopolitanism  4, 7, 16–18, closed/open border  185–6, 188
47–56, 202–5, 232 cosmopolitanism  52–3
distributive justice  86 democracy  156
Eurocentrism  214, 216 distributive justice  79–81
feminism  175, 177 luck  190–1
immigration  186, 188, 190, 192 see also equality
peace  133 empire  235
sovereignty  36, 40–1 see also imperialism
coup d’etat  51, 232 enlightenment (and The Enlightenment)  28,
crimes against humanity  40, 232–3, 237, 252 146, 215, 220, 235
critical race theory  200–4, 246–7 environment/environmentalism  42, 88–90,
critical theory  39, 175, 233, 252 208, 235
cultural imperialism  174, 239 equality  204
cynicism  6, 38 cosmopolitanism  50, 53, 55
democracy  154–6
Dahl, R.  153, 155–7, 163 distributive justice  76–7, 79–80, 83
Daoism  130 feminism  158, 168, 173
democracy/democratic  2, 6, 8, 13, 14, 37, global equality  52, 90
53, 153–63, 203–4, 233–4 punishment principle  98

266
Index

relational  175 Galtung, J.  129


rights  62 game theory  237, 245, 253
sovereign equality  39, 41 Gandhi, M.K.  37, 118, 127–8, 133, 244,
see also egalitarian/ism 249, 2239
ethics  7, 9–10, 235 gender  167–80, 237
feminism  168–71, 192 see also feminism
military  114–22 genealogy  5, 28–9
rights  61, 67, 72 and agonism  161
torture  205 of sovereignty  34–9
ethnic cleansing  40, 142, 232 genocide  40, 113, 232, 237, 253
Eurocentric/Eurocentrism  1, 3–5, 8, 15, 18, Geuss, R.  7, 25
215–17, 219–20, 244–5 Gewirth, A.  65, 67, 69
Europe  5–6, 8, 26–7, 39, 111, 113, 116, globalization  40, 50, 154, 163, 167, 177,
122, 128, 132, 134, 203, 213–5, 193, 213–20, 237–8, 241
220, 227, 230, 232, 234–6, 239, global justice  4, 47, 55, 78, 85–91, 177–8,
243, 245 190, 219
European Union  54–8 see also cosmopolitan/cosmopolitanism

fascism  236, 253 Habermas, J.  24–5, 160–1, 163, 203, 233,
federal/-ism  35, 228, 236, 253 246
feminism  7, 17, 167–80, 202–3, 236, 237 Hart, H. L. A.  33, 42–3
consciousness-raising  15 Hayek, F.  33, 43, 78–9
democracy  153, 158 Hegel, G.W.F.  2, 6, 8, 11, 15, 20, 21, 25–6,
immigration  190–3 98, 199, 213, 230, 246, 252
Kant critique  160–1 hegemony  41, 161, 228, 235, 238–40
peace  129 Hellenocentrism  214–15
Rawls critique  204 Hinduism  26, 117, 130
feudalism  35, 190, 228, 235, 236 Hobbes, T.  5, 11, 21, 28–9, 35, 43, 110–11,
Foucault, M.  6, 8, 24, 39, 95, 106, 206 131, 133, 162, 202, 215–6, 249, 251
freedom  2, 11, 12, 15, 81–2, 236–7 homo economicus  160
assembly  157, 229 Horkheimer, M.  233
association  185–6 human rights  3, 9–10, 36–40, 61–73, 200,
conscience  143 203, 228, 230, 232, 233, 235, 236, 238,
expression  141 239, 241, 244, 251
feminism  172, 177 cosmopolitanism  49, 55–6
Kant  133–4 distributive justice  86
movement  188–90 Eurocentrism  219–20
negative  157; toleration  149
see also negative liberty under liberty
open borders  183 idealism  238–9, 247
press  157 identity politics  239, 253
punishment  99 ideology/ideological  2–4, 8, 39, 41–2, 131,
Rawls  62, 80 161–2, 216, 233, 234, 239
religious  132, 141, 146–7, 229 immigration  10, 17, 40, 183–94
speech  17, 229 imperialism  39, 41, 134, 218, 230, 236,
see also liberty 239–40, 245
Fukuyama, F.  9, 33, 252 India  85, 89–90, 117, 120, 127, 131, 243

267
Index

individualism  43–4, 48, 130, 160, 231, punishment  105


240, 242 sovereignty  34–7
international law  2, 9–10, 14, 16, 33–4, toleration  139–49
39, 206, 227, 232, 238, 240, 241, 244, libertarian/-ism  9–10, 241–2, 249–50
247, 253 distributive justice  77–9
of armed conflict  121 rights  66–7
cosmopolitanism  52, 56 sovereignty  37, 43
humanitarian law  121, 241 liberty  236, 241–2
human rights  63, 122 civil  229
International Monetary Fund (IMF)  52, democracy  158
87, 96 distributive justice  234
Islam  27, 102, 113, 117, 119, 142, 206, 215 movement  188
negative/positive  9, 231, 236–8
jus ad bellum  116, 118, 120, 240 Rawls  80, 204
jus ante bellum  122 rights  37, 62, 68, 238
jus cogens  240, 241 toleration  147
jus gentium  121, 241 totalitarianism  253
see also law of peoples US Constitution  99
jus in bello  116, 120–1, 240 see also freedom
jus natural  240–1 Locke, J.  1–2, 11, 37, 131, 146–7, 235,
see also natural law 241, 249
jus post bellum  122 luck egalitarian argument  190–1
just war theory  16, 117–22, 206, 240
MacIntyre, A.  22–3, 28, 115, 117, 160, 207
Kant, I.  25, 80, 97–100, 122, 133–5, 154–5, marginalization  161, 170, 174–6, 215
159–62, 199, 228 Marx, K.  1–3, 6, 8, 11–12, 15, 21, 110, 231
King, M.L.  15, 37, 118, 127–8, 133, 229, Marxism  22, 29, 132, 173, 231, 233–4,
244 239, 242, 250, 252
Kittay, E.  169, 173, 176, 178, 192–3 meritocracy  235, 242
Kymlicka, W.  148, 163, 203 migration  154, 163, 177–8, 183–4, 191,
193
law of peoples  63, 240–1, 253 military ethics  114–21
legal positivism  33, 42–3, 241 see also just war theory
legal voluntarism  37, 42 Miller, D.  51, 53, 163, 189
legitimacy  33, 35, 40–1, 55, 71, 133, 145, mixed government  228, 242, 249
153, 160, 162, 216 modus vivendi  3, 242, 244, 245, 252
lex talionis  98, 249 monarchy/-ism  6, 34–7, 227, 234, 242,
liberal/liberalism  3, 17, 203–5, 228, 229, 248–50, 252–3
232, 234–5, 237, 239–41, 245–6, Montesquieu, Baron de  201, 242, 249
250–2 morality  24–3, 230, 235
cosmopolitanism  50 democracy  163
democracy  153, 157, 162 distributive justice  76, 90
feminism  158, 167–8, 171–4, 178 human rights  61, 72
human rights  62–3 immigration  193
immigration  183–90 military  114, 117–18, 120
internationalism  40 parents  170
peace  133–4 religion  147

268
Index

toleration  143, 147 peace-keeping  122, 228


see also ethics peacemaking  105
multiculturalism  175, 203, 233, 239, peace of Westphalia  39
243, 245 positive/negative  129
see also war
nationalism  243, 245 Plato  1–3, 5, 6, 10–11, 13–6, 34–5, 38,
nation-state  4–5, 68, 84–6, 109–11, 113, 102–3, 105–6, 120, 130, 140, 144, 205,
119, 194, 202, 219, 235, 243 207, 214, 240, 242
NATO (North Atlantic Treaty pluralism  2, 39, 140, 142, 149, 153,
Organization)  122 155–6, 158, 161, 203–4, 230, 233,
natural law  4–6, 33, 36–7, 40–1, 236, 243–5
43, 232, 237–8, 240–1, 243–5, Pocock, J. G. A.  23–4, 29
250, 253 Pogge, T.  48–51, 55, 86–8, 91, 191
natural rights  37, 64–6, 68–70, 72, 146, political theory  9–10, 12–14, 20–2, 41,
254 153, 160–1, 168–9, 200–1, 205, 207–8,
see also human rights 210n. 1
negative rights  37, 72, 229, 238, 244–5, political science  5, 12–14, 23–5, 34, 42
250 popular sovereignty  35, 113, 250
see also liberty positive rights positive law  33, 37, 41–3, 232, 243–5
Nietzsche, F.  3, 6, 8, 28–9, 39 see also legal positivism
nonresistance  122–3 positive rights  69, 82, 229–31, 238, 254–5
nonviolence  2, 16–7, 127–9, 133, 135, see also liberty negative rights
244–5, 249–50 postcolonial  1, 3, 39–42, 167–8, 202–3,
Nozick, R.  16, 36, 77, 79 214, 216–7, 245
Nussbaum, M.  48–9, 54–5, 81–2, 154–5, see also colonialism
162, 177–8 prisoner’s dilemma  237, 245, 253
private/public spheres  7, 91, 147, 157–8,
Oakeshott, M.  19–25, 28 167–8, 170–2, 177, 203, 246
Occidentalism  5, 215, 220 progressive/-ism  232, 246, 248
Okin, S.  168, 170–3, 175–6 property 
oligarchy  6, 14, 242, 244 intellectual  199, 205
oppression  15, 40, 67, 154, 161, 174–5, personal/private  62–3, 228, 231, 250
178–9, 186, 191, 236, 244 property-owning democracy  177
Orientalism  5, 215, 220 right to  37, 52, 62, 66, 72, 79, 99,
overlapping consensus  3, 148, 162, 242, 127, 167
244–5 public reason/deliberation  2, 142, 144–5,
147–9, 153, 155, 158–60, 162, 230,
pacifism  16–7, 127–35, 169 233, 246
paternalism  3–4, 17, 34, 143, 147, 154–6, punishment  14, 16, 42, 95–107, 113,
159, 161 229, 249
patriotism  36, 47, 54, 243, 245
peace  127–35, 242, 244–5 race/racism  49, 83, 87, 102, 142, 158, 161,
crimes against  233, 253 190, 201, 246–7, 251–2
democratic  133, 239 see also critical race theory
global/cosmopolitan  113, 232 Rawls, J.  3, 9–11
human rights  63–4 civil disobedience  37, 229
Kant  122, 133 contract  11

269
Index

cosmopolitanism  50 social contract/ social compact  1, 4, 6, 9,


democracy,  155, 158–60, 162 11, 35, 38, 134, 153, 155, 162–3, 176,
distributive justice  79–84, 234 201, 204, 249–51
feminism  171–3 social democracy  250
history of philosophy  22, 24–5 socialism  9, 231, 242, 250
human rights  61–3 social justice  65, 78–81, 86–7, 92, 178, 230,
immigration  188 235, 241, 244, 250
law of peoples  241 Socrates  2, 8, 11, 14, 34, 96, 120
liberalism  241 sovereignty  33–44, 55, 119, 202–3, 219,
pluralism  245 243, 250
the Rawls industry  204–5 state of nature  4, 7, 11, 68, 110–11, 127,
toleration  139, 144–5, 148–9 131, 249, 261
see also overlapping consensus structural discrimination/racism  247, 251–2
realism  2–6, 40, 109–11, 131, 238, 247 structural inequality  161
Realpolitik  247 structural violence  129
recognition  see struggle for recognition struggle for recognition  6, 239, 252
reconciliation  102, 105 suffrage  252
Fellowship of Reconciliation  129 see also vote/voting
Truth and Reconciliation  105
see also restorative justice territoriality  39–40, 90, 185
refugee  10, 68, 184–5, 187, 247 theocracy  6, 251
relational justice  49, 167–71, 174–6, Thoreau, H.D.  37, 39, 133, 229
186, 248 tolerance/toleration  17, 62–3, 139–49, 230,
relational egalitarianism  181, 186 241–4, 246, 252
relational selfhood  193 torture  17, 42, 68, 99, 146, 205, 233
relativism  9–10, 22, 73, 233, 248 totalitarianism  43, 227, 236, 240, 253
repression  see oppression tragedy of the commons  231, 237,
republic/republican  133, 157, 231, 245, 253
246, 248–9 tyranny  14, 35, 130, 234, 252
responsibility to protect  38, 50, 113
restorative justice  95–106, 248–9 unitary state  236, 253
retributive justice  75, 87–8, 95–106, United Kingdom  113, 143, 232–3
240, 249 United Nations  9, 39, 55–6, 91, 113, 119,
rights  see human rights; natural rights 134, 218, 238, 247, 251
Rorty, R.  3, 6, 28 United States  12, 35, 43, 55, 89, 105–6,
Rousseau, J.J.  4, 21, 38, 110–11, 131, 159, 112, 122, 129, 143, 156–7, 192, 203–4,
249, 251 206–7, 216, 229, 233, 239, 242, 248
Ruddick, S.  129, 169 Universal Declaration of Human Rights 
76, 238
Sandel, M.  160, 208 utopia  2–6, 10–12, 87, 131, 170,
satyagraha  127, 249 213, 253
Schmitt, C.  19, 26–7, 35, 38, 43
Schumpeter, J.  157, 159 Vincent, A.  22–3
Sen, A.  81–3, 163 virtue  7, 13–4, 36, 72, 103, 105, 115, 139,
separation of powers  143, 228, 242, 249 144–5, 149, 158, 169, 230, 237, 240,
Singer P.,  49, 51, 85, 88 250, 252
Skinner, Q.  22–9 Aristotle  7, 103

270
Index

civic virtue  139, 144–5, 149, 150, 230, 250 cyberwar  206
democratic  158 irregular/unconventional war  113–4,
feminism  169, 237 119
forms of government  14 war crime  232–3, 253
justice  240 see also just war theory peace
leadership  13 Weber, M.  38, 228, 251
professional ethics  115 welfare rights  66, 72, 84, 230, 245
responsibility  104–5 welfare state  173, 178, 204, 241,
shame  103 253–4, 260
sovereignty  36 Wellman, C.H.  64, 68, 185–7, 191
tolerance  139, 144, 149, 252 Westphalian Peace/sovereignty  38–41, 44,
virtue ethics  72 111, 203
Vitoria, F.  121, 216 Williams B.  72–3, 140
vote/voting  13, 62, 66, 144, 156–7, 167, Wittgenstein, L.  6, 41, 43, 199
229, 233, 235, 237, 245, 252 World Trade Organization (WTO)  40, 52,
55, 86
Walzer, M.  37, 117, 157, 183–6, 230 World War  111, 113, 121–2, 134,
war  2, 16, 109–23, 232–3, 237, 240, 244, 232
247, 253
civil war  88, 116 Young, I. M.  158, 161, 174–5

271

Вам также может понравиться