Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 962

Gerald Young

Unifying Causality
and Psychology
Being, Brain, and Behavior
Unifying Causality and Psychology
Gerald Young

Unifying Causality
and Psychology
Being, Brain, and Behavior
Gerald Young
Toronto, ON, Canada

ISBN 978-3-319-24092-3 ISBN 978-3-319-24094-7 (eBook)


DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7
Library of Congress Control Number: 2016936102

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016


This work is subject to copyright. All rights are reserved by the Publisher, whether the whole or
part of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of
illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in any other physical way,
and transmission or information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software,
or by similar or dissimilar methodology now known or hereafter developed.
The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this
publication does not imply, even in the absence of a specific statement, that such names are
exempt from the relevant protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use.
The publisher, the authors and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information in
this book are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the publisher nor
the authors or the editors give a warranty, express or implied, with respect to the material
contained herein or for any errors or omissions that may have been made.

Printed on acid-free paper

This Springer imprint is published by Springer Nature


The registered company is Springer International Publishing AG Switzerland
Preface

We are all born with this basic curiosity about understanding our origins and
heritage. We all want to understand not only what happens, what people are
like, and what things are interesting but also why things happen; why people
behave, think, and feel like they do; and why things work and how. This book
is about the causes of behavior considered broadly. It examines behavior both
in terms of actions and its mental content, such as cognition, motivation, and
emotion. It examines behavior that is considered abnormal as well as normal.
It adopts an approach to the causes of behavior that respects the extreme posi-
tions that they are all biological (Nature) or environmental (Nurture) by creat-
ing an inclusive interactional model. Moreover, the model addresses the role
of personal or self-factors in development, such as free will and self-control.
I have written on the topic of causality in behavior in development
(Development and Causality: Neo-Piagetian Perspectives, Springer Science
+ Business Media, 2011) and psychological injury (Causality of Psychological
Injury: Presenting Evidence in Court, Springer Science + Business Media,
2007) and expanded these endeavors in subsequent publications (e.g.,
Malingering, Feigning, and Response Bias in Psychiatric/Psychological
Injury: Implications for Practice and Court, Springer Science + Business
Media, 2014). This new book on the topic greatly expands these initial
endeavors in understanding causality in behavior. It provides comprehensive
chapters ranging from genetics and epigenetics, to the brain and stress
response in adversity, to the role of development and the environment. It
deals with topics as diverse as free will and psychopathology. It presents new
models related to behavioral causality; reworks other models, such as the
renowned Maslow model of motivation; and generally puts together a com-
prehensive understanding of behavior and its causes.
My career in psychology began with studying facial expressions in infants
from an evolutionary perspective (publishing an article in American Behavior
in 1977). Then I edited a book on brain development (Manual Specialization
and the Developing Brain, Academic Press, 1983). Next, I wrote a book on
adult development (Adult Development, Therapy, and Culture: A Postmodern
Synthesis, Plenum, 1997). Also, I began my externship to become a clinical
psychologist about that time. It led to my work on psychological injury and
law, for which I founded the first journal and first society dedicated to the
topic [Psychological Injury and Law (PIL; www.springer.com) and
Association of Scientific Advancement in Psychological Injury and Law
(ASAPIL; www.asapil.net)]. Many colleagues have helped in these multiple

v
vi Preface

endeavors (e.g., see the PIL masthead for the board members). We all share
an abiding and deep interest in studying the causes of behavior, and this book
is a culmination of a long voyage in that study. Its broad scope is the only way
to tackle the intricacies of the question and to present new ideas toward stim-
ulating further work on it. Please take the challenge.

Toronto, ON, Canada Gerald Young


Acknowledgments

The constant encouragement and support of the editorial and production team
at the publishers has been instrumental toward completing this book, in par-
ticular. I owe so much thanks to Sharon Panulla and Sylvana Ruggirello in the
editorial office and Project Manager Ramya Prakash, Project Coordinator
Alamelu Damodharan, and their production team. My staffs has been respon-
sible for the onerous task of typing and keeping track of the manuscript as it
has been written. Jenny X. Wang especially has worked at it and kept it orga-
nized, with Joyce Chan helping diligently as well and I am so thankful for
that. My colleagues at Glendon College at York University have always sup-
ported my work as well as my teachers over the years. Finally, this book has
been inspired by the need to have students see the big picture in psychology,
and I thank mine for all their probing questions over the years.
Evidence-supported practice in psychology is important to the field, as it
is in medicine, and I hope that this book contributes to that trend and the
respect that science deserves. This book reflects the nature of science, its
proponents, and its hardworking and insightful researchers who produce rep-
licable results and refined theory. In this regard, this is my third massive book
in the last few years having an integrative scientific theme (also see Young
(2011) and Young (2014)). Finally, the book is dedicated to our grandchildren
and to our daughters.

vii
Brief Biography

Gerald Young, Ph.D., C. Psych., is an associate professor in the Department


of Psychology at Glendon College, York University, Toronto, ON, Canada,
who has just been elected as a Fellow of the American Psychological
Association. He has just received an award for outstanding lifetime contribu-
tions for his trauma research from the Canadian Psychological Association.
In addition, he is a practicing psychologist. He is the sole author or senior
editor/coauthor of seven books, including one on malingering (Malingering,
Feigning, and Response Bias in Psychiatric/Psychological Injury:
Implications for Practice and Court published by Springer SBM, New York,
2014). For the area of psychological injury and law, he is the first to have
organized (a) a scientific association (www.asapil.net), and (b) an academic
journal [Psychological Injury and Law (PIL; www.springer.com)], and (c) he
has written integrative articles in multiple journals on the topic. His other
areas of research include child development (Development and Causality:
Neo-Piagetian Perspectives, Springer SBM, 2011) and the DSM-5 (he coed-
ited two PIL special issues on the topic, in 2010 and 2013). His most recent
work is on revising the ethics code of the American Psychological Association
(articles in 2014 and 2016). He has successfully testified in a case involving
the Supreme Court of Canada on the rights of injured workers.

ix
Contents

Part I Core Causality in Behavior: Foundations and Models

1 Brief Book Description and Book Assumptions ........................ 3


Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 3
Goal ............................................................................................ 3
Outline........................................................................................ 5
Axes ........................................................................................... 5
Unifying Causality and Psychology: Being,
Brain, and Behavior ....................................................................... 5
Preamble: The Causal Self, Freedom in Being, Stages,
and Unifying Psychology........................................................... 5
Introduction .................................................................................... 10
Book Parts ...................................................................................... 11
Parts............................................................................................ 11
Comment .................................................................................... 11
The Broader Context ...................................................................... 12
Integrations ................................................................................ 12
Causality .................................................................................... 12
Limitations ................................................................................. 14
Assumptions................................................................................... 14
General ....................................................................................... 14
Specifics ..................................................................................... 15
Biopsychosocial ......................................................................... 16
Change ....................................................................................... 17
Systems and Axes ...................................................................... 17
Integration, Exceptionalism, and Essence.................................. 19
Chapter Conclusions .................................................................. 20
References ...................................................................................... 20
2 Overview of Book Parts and Chapter by Chapter
Overview ....................................................................................... 23
Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 23
Parts of the Book ............................................................................ 23
Introduction ................................................................................ 23
Parts............................................................................................ 23
Conclusion ................................................................................. 24

xi
xii Contents

Part I: Core Causality in Behavior: Foundations and Models........ 24


Part II: Biology and Revolutions.................................................... 24
Part III: Normal and Abnormal Development and Free Will:
Normal Development and Free Will .............................................. 25
Part IV: Abnormalities in Development and the DSM-5 ............... 26
Part V: Personal Contributions to the Study of Causality
in Behavior: New Models .............................................................. 26
Part VI: The Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian Model ...................... 27
Conclusion ................................................................................. 27
Chapter Descriptions...................................................................... 28
Part I: Core Causality in Behavior: Foundations and Models........ 28
Part II: Biology and Revolutions.................................................... 32
Part III: Normal and Abnormal Development and Free Will:
Normal Development and Free Will .............................................. 35
Part IV: Abnormalities in Development and the DSM-5 ............... 38
Part V: Personal Contributions to the Study of Causality
in Behavior: New Models .............................................................. 41
Part VI: The Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian Model ...................... 42
Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 44
References ...................................................................................... 44
3 Introducing Causality in Psychology ......................................... 45
Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 45
Causality in Psychology................................................................. 46
Introduction ................................................................................ 46
Causal Reasoning Skills Training .............................................. 47
History........................................................................................ 48
Critical Terms............................................................................. 48
Critical Concepts............................................................................ 49
Reducing Reductionism ............................................................. 49
Hot vs. Cold Causality ............................................................... 49
Causal Streams and Three Major Causality Axes...................... 49
Mechanism ................................................................................. 50
Genetics/Epigenetics .................................................................. 50
Evolution .................................................................................... 52
Development .............................................................................. 53
Nonlinear Dynamical Systems................................................... 54
Dimensions ................................................................................ 54
Further Elaboration of the Three Major Axes
in Causality Study .......................................................................... 55
Dimensional Causality Model.................................................... 55
The Causality Landscape ........................................................... 57
Free Will ........................................................................................ 59
Concept ...................................................................................... 59
Comment .................................................................................... 59
Freedom in Being....................................................................... 60
Biopsychosocial Causality ......................................................... 60
Contents xiii

Mechanism ..................................................................................... 61
Model ......................................................................................... 61
Big History ................................................................................. 63
Mapping ......................................................................................... 63
Model ......................................................................................... 63
Comment .................................................................................... 65
Model ......................................................................................... 65
Comment .................................................................................... 65
Model ......................................................................................... 66
Comment .................................................................................... 66
Conclusion ................................................................................. 66
Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 68
References ...................................................................................... 68
4 Causality in Philosophy; Philosophy in Psychology.................. 71
Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 71
The Constitution and Construction of Reality ............................... 72
Reductionism and Constructivism ............................................. 72
Neoconstructivism ..................................................................... 73
Determinism and Indeterminism................................................ 74
Co-Existentialism....................................................................... 74
Comment .................................................................................... 75
Free Will, Causality Modeling, and Philosophy ............................ 76
Neurophilosophy and Free Will ..................................................... 76
Emergence.................................................................................. 76
Networks .................................................................................... 77
Comment .................................................................................... 80
Philosophy and Free Will ............................................................... 80
Schools ....................................................................................... 80
A Compatible Semi-Compatibilism........................................... 80
A New Semi-Compatibilism Model .......................................... 82
Causality in Philosophy ................................................................. 84
Introduction ................................................................................ 84
Interventionism .......................................................................... 84
Dispositionalism ........................................................................ 84
Mechanism ................................................................................. 85
Comment .................................................................................... 85
Relationism .................................................................................... 85
Model ......................................................................................... 85
Supporting Work ........................................................................ 86
Comment .................................................................................... 87
Kuhnian Paradigms ........................................................................ 87
Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 87
References ...................................................................................... 88
5 Models and Systems of Causality of Behavior........................... 93
Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 93
Introduction .................................................................................... 93
Biopsychosocial Model.................................................................. 94
xiv Contents

Model ......................................................................................... 94
Interim Conclusions ....................................................................... 98
The Embodiment Model ................................................................ 98
Cognition Embodied .................................................................. 98
Embodied Cognition .................................................................. 99
Social/Emotional ........................................................................ 100
Evidence..................................................................................... 101
Extensions .................................................................................. 103
Causation.................................................................................... 105
Interim Conclusions ................................................................... 106
Systems Models and Causality ...................................................... 106
Introduction ................................................................................ 106
Complex Adaptive Systems ....................................................... 107
Systems .......................................................................................... 109
Model ......................................................................................... 109
Applications ............................................................................... 111
Brain........................................................................................... 112
Integrating the Models ............................................................... 113
Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 114
References ...................................................................................... 114
6 Statistical Concepts and Networks in Causality ....................... 121
Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 121
Testing and Causality ..................................................................... 122
Introduction ................................................................................ 122
Testing ........................................................................................ 122
Causality .................................................................................... 123
Statistical Causal Modeling ........................................................... 124
Introduction ................................................................................ 124
Models........................................................................................ 124
Comment .................................................................................... 125
Epidemiology ................................................................................. 125
Introduction ................................................................................ 125
Statistical Models ....................................................................... 125
Comment .................................................................................... 127
Bayesian Approach ........................................................................ 127
Introduction ................................................................................ 127
Models........................................................................................ 127
Conclusion ................................................................................. 129
Methods.......................................................................................... 129
Introduction ................................................................................ 129
Designs....................................................................................... 130
Statistical Strategies ................................................................... 131
Causal Mediation ........................................................................... 131
Introduction ................................................................................ 131
Statistical Strategies ................................................................... 131
Comment .................................................................................... 133
Applications ................................................................................... 133
Contents xv

Psychopathology ........................................................................ 133


Other Areas ................................................................................ 134
Comment .................................................................................... 136
Brain............................................................................................... 136
Granger Causality ...................................................................... 136
Comment .................................................................................... 137
Ecology .......................................................................................... 137
Interventions .............................................................................. 137
Granger Causality ...................................................................... 137
Convergent Cross-Mapping ....................................................... 138
Comment .................................................................................... 138
PTSD Networks ............................................................................. 139
Concept ...................................................................................... 139
Comment .................................................................................... 140
Related Research ........................................................................ 141
Comment .................................................................................... 143
Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 143
References ...................................................................................... 143

Part II Biology and Revolutions

7 Brain: The Neuronal Network Revolution ................................ 151


Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 151
Introduction .................................................................................... 151
Networks ........................................................................................ 152
Introduction ................................................................................ 152
Brain........................................................................................... 152
Comment .................................................................................... 153
Connectome ................................................................................... 154
Model ......................................................................................... 154
Terms.......................................................................................... 154
Systems ...................................................................................... 156
Evidence..................................................................................... 157
Conclusions ................................................................................ 158
Core Networks ............................................................................... 158
Model ......................................................................................... 158
Systems ...................................................................................... 159
Evidence..................................................................................... 160
Comment .................................................................................... 162
Free Energy and Surprise ............................................................... 162
Model ......................................................................................... 162
Systems ...................................................................................... 164
Neurons ...................................................................................... 164
Connectome ............................................................................... 167
Comment .................................................................................... 167
Cells ............................................................................................... 167
Concept Cells ............................................................................. 167
xvi Contents

Astrocytes .................................................................................. 169


Comment .................................................................................... 169
Psychological Networks................................................................. 170
Comment .................................................................................... 172
Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 172
References ...................................................................................... 173
8 Lateralization and Specialization of the Brain.......................... 177
Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 177
Lateralization and Specialization Development
by Age Period ................................................................................ 178
Prenatal ...................................................................................... 178
Neonates..................................................................................... 179
First Year .................................................................................... 181
One Year..................................................................................... 182
Year Two .................................................................................... 182
Children...................................................................................... 183
Other Developmental Topics.......................................................... 185
Networks .................................................................................... 185
Differential Susceptibility .......................................................... 185
Language Development ............................................................. 186
Comment .................................................................................... 188
Inhibition in Children................................................................. 188
Inhibition in Adults ........................................................................ 189
Model ......................................................................................... 189
Concepts Consistent with the Present Model............................. 190
Evidence..................................................................................... 191
Evolution ........................................................................................ 194
Doubts ............................................................................................ 194
Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 194
References ...................................................................................... 195
9 The Genetics Revolution.............................................................. 201
Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 201
Introduction .................................................................................... 201
Neogenomics and G × E ................................................................. 202
Introduction ................................................................................ 202
Terms.......................................................................................... 202
Behavior Genetics ...................................................................... 202
SNPs and CNVs ......................................................................... 203
Epigenetics ................................................................................. 203
Programming.............................................................................. 204
GWAS ........................................................................................ 204
Phenotypic Plasticity.................................................................. 206
Causality .................................................................................... 206
Comment .................................................................................... 206
Genetics and Behavior ................................................................... 207
Introduction ................................................................................ 207
Dopamine Genes ........................................................................ 207
Contents xvii

G × G........................................................................................... 208
G × E ........................................................................................... 208
Attention and Genes................................................................... 208
Reward and Genes ..................................................................... 209
Comment .................................................................................... 209
Applications ................................................................................... 210
Introduction ................................................................................ 210
ADHD ........................................................................................ 210
ASC ............................................................................................ 210
Missing Heritability ....................................................................... 210
Methodology Explains ............................................................... 210
Hypercomplexity Explains......................................................... 211
GCTA Resolves.......................................................................... 213
Commonalities and Pleiotropy in Psychopathology ...................... 214
Explanation ................................................................................ 214
General p Factor ......................................................................... 215
Generalist Genes ........................................................................ 216
Others ......................................................................................... 217
Comment .................................................................................... 217
Child Genomics ............................................................................. 217
Reaction Range .............................................................................. 218
Model ......................................................................................... 218
Evidence..................................................................................... 219
Conclusion ................................................................................. 219
Genes/Causality ............................................................................. 220
Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 221
Phenome..................................................................................... 221
Evolvability ................................................................................ 221
Versatility ................................................................................... 221
Loveome..................................................................................... 221
References ...................................................................................... 221
10 Gene × Environment Interaction: The Environmental
Revolution ..................................................................................... 227
Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 227
The G × E Model ............................................................................ 227
Candidate Genes ........................................................................ 227
Comment .................................................................................... 229
Complexities .............................................................................. 229
Comment .................................................................................... 235
Recent Empirical Research ............................................................ 235
Externalizing .............................................................................. 235
Internalizing ............................................................................... 240
Comment .................................................................................... 243
(G × E) × Development.................................................................... 244
Comment .................................................................................... 247
Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 247
References ...................................................................................... 248
xviii Contents

11 Genes and Environments: The Person Revolution ................... 255


Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 255
Epigenetics ..................................................................................... 255
DNA Methylation ...................................................................... 255
Effects ........................................................................................ 256
Applications ............................................................................... 257
Extensions .................................................................................. 258
Comment .................................................................................... 260
Externalizing .............................................................................. 260
Internalizing ............................................................................... 260
Comment .................................................................................... 261
Correlated Gene × Environment ..................................................... 261
Psychopathology and rGE.......................................................... 261
Cultural Neuroscience .................................................................... 265
5-HTTLPR ................................................................................. 265
OXTR ......................................................................................... 268
DRD4 ......................................................................................... 268
Comments .................................................................................. 269
Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 269
References ...................................................................................... 270
12 Nature and Nurture: Evolution and Complexities.................... 275
Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 275
Evolution ........................................................................................ 275
Epigenesis ...................................................................................... 277
Systems .......................................................................................... 277
Complexity ..................................................................................... 280
Niche Construction ........................................................................ 280
Development .................................................................................. 285
Nature and Nurture (and Ourselves) .............................................. 287
Intelligence................................................................................. 287
Neuroticism ................................................................................ 289
Social Genomics ............................................................................ 292
Model ......................................................................................... 292
CTRA ......................................................................................... 294
RNA ........................................................................................... 294
Comment .................................................................................... 294
Evidence..................................................................................... 295
Health ......................................................................................... 295
Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 296
References ...................................................................................... 298

Part III Normal and Abnormal Development


and Free Will: Normal Development and Free Will

13 Differential Susceptibility: Orchids, Dandelions,


and the Flowering of Developmental Psychology...................... 305
Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 305
Differential Susceptibility .............................................................. 305
Model ......................................................................................... 306
Contents xix

Elaborations ................................................................................... 312


Belsky and Colleagues ............................................................... 312
Ellis and Colleagues................................................................... 315
Conclusions .................................................................................... 316
Extensions ...................................................................................... 317
Life History Theory ....................................................................... 318
Recent Research ............................................................................. 320
Supportive Research .................................................................. 320
Nonsupportive Research ............................................................ 324
Conclusion ................................................................................. 324
Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 325
References ...................................................................................... 325
14 Early Adversity, Fetal Programming, and Getting
Under the Skin.............................................................................. 331
Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 331
Enduring Effects ............................................................................ 331
Model ......................................................................................... 331
Evidence..................................................................................... 332
Comment .................................................................................... 333
Allostasis and Allostatic Load Model ............................................ 333
Model ......................................................................................... 333
Evidence..................................................................................... 335
Comment .................................................................................... 336
Differential Susceptibility .............................................................. 336
Model ......................................................................................... 336
Evidence..................................................................................... 336
Comment .................................................................................... 337
Adaptive Calibration Model........................................................... 337
Stress Generation ........................................................................... 338
Model ......................................................................................... 338
Evidence..................................................................................... 339
Comment .................................................................................... 340
Genes and Environments ............................................................... 341
Environment ................................................................................... 341
Support ....................................................................................... 341
Preconception............................................................................. 343
Socioeconomic Status/Poverty ................................................... 343
Other Work..................................................................................... 344
Attachment ................................................................................. 344
Early Adversity .......................................................................... 346
Inflammation .............................................................................. 347
Brain........................................................................................... 347
Coping ........................................................................................ 347
Biopsychosocial Findings .............................................................. 348
Genes and Environment Contribution ........................................ 348
The Personal Contributions........................................................ 349
Comment .................................................................................... 349
xx Contents

Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 349


References ...................................................................................... 350
15 Connecting the Social Dots.......................................................... 355
Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 355
Biology........................................................................................... 356
Biobehavioral Synchrony ........................................................... 356
Activation/Inhibition Coordination ............................................ 357
Brain........................................................................................... 357
Brain, Cognitive, and Social ...................................................... 359
Embodiment ............................................................................... 360
Evolution ........................................................................................ 364
Nonhuman Primates ................................................................... 364
Culture............................................................................................ 366
Development .................................................................................. 367
Models........................................................................................ 367
Developmental Research Review................................................... 369
Year 1 and Before....................................................................... 369
Year 2 ......................................................................................... 371
Children...................................................................................... 373
Applications ................................................................................... 374
Public Good ............................................................................... 374
Politics........................................................................................ 375
Self ................................................................................................. 376
Model ......................................................................................... 376
Comment .................................................................................... 377
Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 377
Piaget Missing............................................................................ 377
Research Review ........................................................................ 378
Piaget.......................................................................................... 378
Explaining the Review According to Piaget .............................. 379
Conclusion ................................................................................. 380
References ...................................................................................... 380
16 Causal Learning: Understanding the World ............................. 387
Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 387
Bayesian Learning Model .............................................................. 387
Introduction ................................................................................ 387
Model ......................................................................................... 388
Research ..................................................................................... 388
Elaboration ................................................................................. 389
Comment .................................................................................... 391
Piagetian Contributions to Understanding Causal Learning .......... 391
Piaget on Causality .................................................................... 391
Rational Construction ................................................................ 391
Construction and Computation .................................................. 393
Observation ................................................................................ 394
Natural Pedagogy ........................................................................... 397
Contents xxi

Integrating Bayes and Piaget ......................................................... 397


Rational Constructivism............................................................. 397
Changes by Age in Causal Learning .............................................. 399
Newborns ................................................................................... 400
Comment .................................................................................... 400
Young Infants ............................................................................. 400
Comment .................................................................................... 402
One- to Two-Year-Olds .............................................................. 402
Comment .................................................................................... 404
Children...................................................................................... 405
Comment .................................................................................... 407
Adults ......................................................................................... 407
Comment .................................................................................... 410
Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 410
References ...................................................................................... 410
17 Developing the Mind, Minding Development ............................ 417
Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 417
Major Acquisitions of Mind........................................................... 417
Theory of Mind in Early Childhood .......................................... 417
Beyond Infancy .............................................................................. 420
Children...................................................................................... 420
Adults ......................................................................................... 420
Comment .................................................................................... 421
Executive Function......................................................................... 421
Infants ........................................................................................ 421
Children...................................................................................... 421
Adults ......................................................................................... 423
Comment .................................................................................... 424
Inhibition ........................................................................................ 424
Early ........................................................................................... 424
Children...................................................................................... 425
Piaget.......................................................................................... 425
Adults ......................................................................................... 425
Comment .................................................................................... 426
Major Developmental Models Related to Mind ............................ 426
Biopsychosocial Model.............................................................. 426
Embodiment ................................................................................... 428
Introduction ................................................................................ 428
Embodiment and Relational Development ................................ 429
Piaget.......................................................................................... 429
Reaching for the Mind ............................................................... 431
Mirror Neurons .......................................................................... 432
Embodiment by Age Period ........................................................... 433
Prenatal ...................................................................................... 433
Neonatal ..................................................................................... 433
First 6 Months ............................................................................ 433
6–12 Months .............................................................................. 434
xxii Contents

Year 2 ......................................................................................... 435


Children...................................................................................... 436
Adults ......................................................................................... 437
System Theory ............................................................................... 437
General Model ........................................................................... 437
Neural Model ............................................................................. 440
Comment .................................................................................... 441
Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 441
References ...................................................................................... 442
18 Free Will in Behavior: Believing Makes It So ........................... 451
Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 451
Philosophy...................................................................................... 451
Views.......................................................................................... 451
Free Will from a Psychological Perspective .................................. 454
Free Will Psychology ................................................................. 454
Belief in Free Will...................................................................... 455
Lay Belief................................................................................... 456
Conformity ................................................................................. 457
Individual Differences.................................................................... 458
Introduction ................................................................................ 458
Model ......................................................................................... 458
Comment .................................................................................... 459
Motivation .................................................................................. 459
Consciousness ................................................................................ 460
Introduction ................................................................................ 460
Baumeister ................................................................................. 460
Bargh .......................................................................................... 461
Others ......................................................................................... 463
Development of Free Will .............................................................. 465
Model ......................................................................................... 465
Comment .................................................................................... 466
Evolution ........................................................................................ 466
Model ......................................................................................... 466
Comment .................................................................................... 466
The Brain and Free Will................................................................. 467
Model ......................................................................................... 467
Comment .................................................................................... 467
The Politics of Free Will ................................................................ 470
Model ......................................................................................... 470
Comment .................................................................................... 471
Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 471
References ...................................................................................... 472
19 An Integrated Model of “Free Will” and New Free
Will Questionnaires...................................................................... 477
Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 477
Depletion ........................................................................................ 477
Introduction ................................................................................ 477
Contents xxiii

Glucose ...................................................................................... 478


Personal Belief/Will Power ........................................................ 478
Embodiment ............................................................................... 479
Social.......................................................................................... 479
Brain........................................................................................... 480
Inhibition .................................................................................... 481
Motivation .................................................................................. 483
Cognitive .................................................................................... 484
Self ............................................................................................. 484
Comment .................................................................................... 485
Self-Regulation .............................................................................. 485
Introduction ................................................................................ 485
Social.......................................................................................... 485
Biological ................................................................................... 486
Personal ...................................................................................... 486
Dual-Process Models ..................................................................... 487
Models........................................................................................ 487
Types .......................................................................................... 488
Brain........................................................................................... 489
Piaget.......................................................................................... 489
Comment .................................................................................... 490
A Combined Biopsychosocial/Depletion,
Dual-Process/Consciousness-Unconsciousness Model
in Behavioral Causality .................................................................. 491
Introduction ................................................................................ 491
Model ......................................................................................... 491
Evidence..................................................................................... 491
Comment .................................................................................... 493
Free Will and Depletion Questionnaires ........................................ 493
Introduction ................................................................................ 493
Extant Free Will Questionnaires ................................................ 493
Proposed New Scale on Free Will ............................................. 495
Belief in Free Will/Determinism................................................ 501
Depletion .................................................................................... 502
Belief and Passion as Part of Behavioral Causation and Causality
Engines........................................................................................... 502
Introduction ................................................................................ 502
Belief .......................................................................................... 503
Passion ....................................................................................... 503
Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 506
References ...................................................................................... 507

Part IV Abnormalities in Development and the DSM-5

20 Free Will in Psychotherapy: Helping People Believe................ 513


Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 513
Free will in Psychotherapy............................................................. 513
Introduction ................................................................................ 513
Model ......................................................................................... 514
xxiv Contents

Helping People Believe .................................................................. 515


Introduction ................................................................................ 515
Self-Control in Free Will ........................................................... 515
Comment .................................................................................... 516
The Transdiagnostic Psychotherapeutic Module
on Free Will Belief and Change ..................................................... 516
Introduction ................................................................................ 516
Functional Perspective ............................................................... 517
Deception ................................................................................... 517
Daily Life ................................................................................... 518
Self-Regulation .......................................................................... 519
Consciousness ............................................................................ 520
Reasoning and Motivation ......................................................... 522
Meaning ..................................................................................... 523
Change ....................................................................................... 525
Stage........................................................................................... 526
Addictions .................................................................................. 527
Comment .................................................................................... 528
Growth ........................................................................................... 528
Post-Trauma ............................................................................... 528
My Model................................................................................... 529
Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 531
References ...................................................................................... 531
21 PTSD: Traumatic Causation ....................................................... 535
Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 535
Introduction .................................................................................... 535
DSM-5........................................................................................ 535
Epidemiology ............................................................................. 536
Pathways .................................................................................... 536
Modeling ........................................................................................ 537
Major Models ............................................................................. 537
Fear Model ................................................................................. 537
Comment .................................................................................... 539
Endophenotypes ............................................................................. 540
Introduction ................................................................................ 540
Model ......................................................................................... 540
Comment .................................................................................... 540
Genes.............................................................................................. 540
Candidate Genes ........................................................................ 541
Heritability ..................................................................................... 542
Evidence..................................................................................... 542
Comment .................................................................................... 542
GWAS ............................................................................................ 542
Evidence..................................................................................... 542
Comment .................................................................................... 543
Epigenesis ...................................................................................... 543
Introduction ................................................................................ 543
Model ......................................................................................... 544
Contents xxv

Fear ............................................................................................ 544


Abuse ......................................................................................... 544
Stress .......................................................................................... 545
Programming.............................................................................. 547
Applications ............................................................................... 548
Conclusion ................................................................................. 548
Brain............................................................................................... 548
Introduction ................................................................................ 548
Imaging ...................................................................................... 549
Neurocircuitry ............................................................................ 549
Networks .................................................................................... 551
Comment .................................................................................... 552
Neuroendocrine .............................................................................. 552
Neuropsychology ........................................................................... 552
Neurogenesis .................................................................................. 552
Synapses..................................................................................... 552
Neurogenesis .............................................................................. 553
Comment .................................................................................... 553
HPA Axis ....................................................................................... 553
Research ..................................................................................... 553
Comment .................................................................................... 554
Pathways ........................................................................................ 554
Evidence..................................................................................... 554
Comment .................................................................................... 555
Allostasis ........................................................................................ 555
Research ..................................................................................... 555
Comment .................................................................................... 556
Five Factor Model .......................................................................... 556
Research ..................................................................................... 556
Comment .................................................................................... 557
Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 557
References ...................................................................................... 558
22 DSM-5: Basics and Critics .......................................................... 565
Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 565
Introduction .................................................................................... 565
Goals .............................................................................................. 566
Assumptions................................................................................... 567
Science and Utility ..................................................................... 567
Etiology ...................................................................................... 567
Biopsychosocial ......................................................................... 568
The DSM in Detail ......................................................................... 569
Preface........................................................................................ 569
Introduction ................................................................................ 570
Forensics .................................................................................... 571
Comment .................................................................................... 571
Specific Changes in the DSM-5 and Their Critique ...................... 572
Changes ...................................................................................... 572
Comment .................................................................................... 572
xxvi Contents

Supporting DSM-5 ..................................................................... 576


Critiquing DSM-5 .......................................................................... 577
General Critique ......................................................................... 577
Paris (2013) ................................................................................ 577
Paris and Phillips (2013) ............................................................ 579
Comment .................................................................................... 580
Others ......................................................................................... 580
Forensic Critique ........................................................................ 582
DSM-5 Field Trial Critique........................................................ 582
Defining Mental Disorder in the DSM-5 ....................................... 584
The WHODAS 2.0 ......................................................................... 584
Instrument .................................................................................. 586
Critique ...................................................................................... 587
Conclusion ................................................................................. 587
Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 588
References ...................................................................................... 588
23 The DSM-5 and the RDoC: Grand Designs
and Grander Problems ................................................................ 591
Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 591
Research Domain Criteria .............................................................. 591
Introduction ................................................................................ 591
Comment .................................................................................... 592
Endophenotype and the RDoC................................................... 592
Development .............................................................................. 593
Comment .................................................................................... 593
Not Reductionistic ..................................................................... 593
Comment .................................................................................... 593
Epigenesis .................................................................................. 594
Comment .................................................................................... 594
DSM-5........................................................................................ 595
Comment .................................................................................... 595
Most Recent Criticisms .............................................................. 595
Comment .................................................................................... 596
The DSM-5 and Psychological Injuries ......................................... 596
PTSD in the DSM-5 ....................................................................... 597
Description and Concerns .......................................................... 597
Other .......................................................................................... 598
Supportive Research .................................................................. 600
Criticisms ................................................................................... 602
Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 606
References ...................................................................................... 607
24 The Disordered DSM-5 Disorders .............................................. 611
Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 611
Neurocognitive Disorder ................................................................ 611
Somatic Symptom Disorder ........................................................... 613
Chronic Pain in the DSM-IV-TR ............................................... 613
Chronic Pain in the DSM-5........................................................ 613
Somatic Symptom Disorder in the DSM-5 ................................ 614
Contents xxvii

My Specific Concerns for SSD .................................................. 615


Alternative Diagnoses Involving Pain in the DSM-5 ................. 616
Recommendations for the DSM-5.1 .............................................. 617
Understanding Chronic Pain ...................................................... 617
Chronic Pain Complications Disorder ....................................... 617
Painful Conclusions ................................................................... 620
Other DSM-5 Considerations ........................................................ 620
Personality Disorder................................................................... 620
Depression.................................................................................. 621
Malingering ................................................................................ 622
Comment .................................................................................... 624
The ICD-11 .................................................................................... 624
Complex PTSD .......................................................................... 624
Evidence..................................................................................... 625
Conclusions ................................................................................ 625
Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 626
References ...................................................................................... 626
25 DSM-5: Recommendations ......................................................... 629
Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 629
Causality and Etiology in Psychology and Psychiatry .................. 629
Concepts..................................................................................... 630
Epigenetics ................................................................................. 632
Other Considerations ................................................................. 632
A Combined Top-Down/Bottom-Up Integrated Causal
(Etiological) Model of Mental Disorder ........................................ 634
Endophenotypes ............................................................................. 635
Concept ...................................................................................... 635
Interim Conclusion......................................................................... 639
Recommendations .......................................................................... 640
An Endophenotypic Model ........................................................ 640
Critique ...................................................................................... 641
Modeling .................................................................................... 642
Practice....................................................................................... 643
Ethics.......................................................................................... 646
Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 646
For DSM-5 and Etiology ........................................................... 646
For Assessment .......................................................................... 646
For Reports/Court ...................................................................... 648
References ...................................................................................... 649

Part V Personal Contributions to the Study of Causality


in Behavior: New Models

26 Causality in Psychological Injury and Law:


Basics and Critics ......................................................................... 653
Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 653
Introduction .................................................................................... 653
xxviii Contents

Causality and Causation Terms in Law.......................................... 654


Law ............................................................................................ 654
Causality and Causation............................................................. 655
New Terms ................................................................................. 656
Negligence and Law....................................................................... 657
Psychological Injury and Law ....................................................... 658
Medical Injury and Law ................................................................. 661
Psychological Causality in Criminal Cases ................................... 662
Introduction ................................................................................ 662
Biopsychosocial Model.............................................................. 663
Mens Rea ................................................................................... 664
Neurolaw .................................................................................... 666
New Term ................................................................................... 668
Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 669
References ...................................................................................... 670
27 Causality in Psychological Injury and Law: Models ................ 673
Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 673
Iatrogenesis in Psychological Injury .............................................. 674
Terms.......................................................................................... 674
Context ....................................................................................... 675
How Systemic Factors Influence Outcome
in Psychological Injury .................................................................. 676
Posttraumatic Stress Disorder .................................................... 676
Traumatic Brain Injury............................................................... 677
Pain ............................................................................................ 677
Compensation Neurosis ............................................................. 679
Conclusion ................................................................................. 680
New Model of Causation in Psychological Injury,
Including Iatrogenesis .................................................................... 681
Introduction ................................................................................ 681
Coping ........................................................................................ 681
Psycho-Ecological Model .......................................................... 683
Biases ......................................................................................... 684
Iatrogenesis .................................................................................... 687
Introduction ................................................................................ 687
Other Models ............................................................................. 687
My Integrated Model of Causality in Psychological Injury
and Complicating Factors, Including Iatrogenesis..................... 689
Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 694
Summary .................................................................................... 694
Recommendations ...................................................................... 694
References ...................................................................................... 695
28 Stimulus–Organism–Response Model: SORing
to New Heights.............................................................................. 699
Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 699
History............................................................................................ 699
Contents xxix

Contemporary Theory .................................................................... 700


Fuzziness .................................................................................... 700
Comment .................................................................................... 700
What Is a Fuzzy Stimulus? ............................................................ 700
Precursors................................................................................... 700
Model ......................................................................................... 701
Others ......................................................................................... 702
What Is a Fuzzy Organism? ........................................................... 703
What Is Fuzzy Response? .............................................................. 703
What Is a Fuzzy System? ............................................................... 703
Revised S–O–R Model................................................................... 704
Model ......................................................................................... 704
Stimuli ........................................................................................ 708
Organism .................................................................................... 708
Response .................................................................................... 709
Further Details ........................................................................... 710
Reflections...................................................................................... 711
Fuzziness .................................................................................... 711
Philosophy.................................................................................. 712
Causality .................................................................................... 712
Dimensions ................................................................................ 713
Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 715
References ...................................................................................... 716
29 Networked Causal Terms ............................................................ 719
Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 719
Terms.............................................................................................. 719
Standard ..................................................................................... 719
Innovation .................................................................................. 719
Integrated Cross-Network Model................................................... 723
Introduction ................................................................................ 723
Model ......................................................................................... 723
Cross-Networks.......................................................................... 723
Basic Behavioral Community .................................................... 728
Intrapersonal, Interpersonal, Interfaced ..................................... 728
Yoking ........................................................................................ 729
Peridynamical ............................................................................ 729
Constrained Emergence ............................................................. 729
Neoreductioconstructionism ...................................................... 729
Biopersonalsocial ....................................................................... 729
Hypertransactionalism ............................................................... 729
Causal System ............................................................................ 730
Ontogeny/Phylogeny .................................................................. 730
Multifactorial ............................................................................. 730
Fuzziness .................................................................................... 730
GEODS Model ............................................................................... 730
Introduction ................................................................................ 730
Model ......................................................................................... 730
Comment .................................................................................... 733
xxx Contents

Eye-Catching Causal Terms ........................................................... 733


The Causal Zoo .......................................................................... 733
Causicles .................................................................................... 734
Coexistential Causal Intraactivism................................................. 735
Model ......................................................................................... 735
Models........................................................................................ 737
Psychology ................................................................................. 739
Conclusions ................................................................................ 741
Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 741
References ...................................................................................... 742
30 Change Mechanisms .................................................................... 743
Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 743
Neuromal Network......................................................................... 743
Introduction ................................................................................ 743
Model ......................................................................................... 744
Activation/Inhibition Coordination ................................................ 745
Model ......................................................................................... 745
Emergence.................................................................................. 746
Comment .................................................................................... 748
Steps ............................................................................................... 748
Activation/Inhibition Coordination ............................................ 748
Chaos.......................................................................................... 749
Comment .................................................................................... 749
Readiness for Change .................................................................... 750
Introduction ................................................................................ 750
Model ......................................................................................... 751
Comment .................................................................................... 754
Dimensions of Change ................................................................... 754
Dimensions ................................................................................ 754
Comment .................................................................................... 757
Infant Development........................................................................ 758
Introduction ................................................................................ 758
Model ......................................................................................... 758
Comment .................................................................................... 760
General Development .................................................................... 760
Introduction ................................................................................ 760
How We Treat Each Other ......................................................... 761
Management Style ..................................................................... 761
Cognitive (Mis)Perception of the Other..................................... 762
Comment .................................................................................... 762
Intraactive Terminology ................................................................. 763
Introduction ................................................................................ 763
Application................................................................................. 763
Conclusion ................................................................................. 764
Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 764
References ...................................................................................... 765
Contents xxxi

Part VI The Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian Model

31 A Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian 25-Step
(Sub)Stage Model ......................................................................... 769
Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 769
The Present Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian Stage
and Substage Model ....................................................................... 771
Model ......................................................................................... 771
The Model as Biopsychosocial .................................................. 772
Biology Elaborated in the Model ................................................... 778
Activation/Inhibition Coordination ............................................ 778
Broad Steps in Evolution ........................................................... 778
Mind Evolving ........................................................................... 779
Psychology Elaborated in the Model ............................................. 780
Environment Elaborated in the Model ........................................... 781
Interim Conclusion......................................................................... 781
Yoking Further Explained .............................................................. 781
Introduction ................................................................................ 781
Yoking ........................................................................................ 782
Backward–Forward .................................................................... 782
Multiply Intelligent .................................................................... 783
Dual Track Stages ...................................................................... 783
Multiple Intelligences ................................................................ 783
Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 783
References ...................................................................................... 784
32 Further Expansions of the Present Stage Models ..................... 785
Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 785
Neo-Piagetian................................................................................. 785
Introduction ................................................................................ 785
Human Exceptionalism .............................................................. 785
Social-Emotional........................................................................ 786
Free Will .................................................................................... 788
Neo-Eriksonian .............................................................................. 789
Model ......................................................................................... 789
Elaboration ................................................................................. 792
Yoking ........................................................................................ 793
Comment .................................................................................... 793
Neo-Maslovian Model ................................................................... 793
Introduction ................................................................................ 793
Model ......................................................................................... 794
Development Outside of Development .......................................... 796
Introduction ................................................................................ 796
Psychology ................................................................................. 796
Evolution .................................................................................... 796
Comment .................................................................................... 798
Revising Steps ................................................................................ 798
Introduction ................................................................................ 798
xxxii Contents

Dual Process Revised ................................................................. 798


Free Will Revised ....................................................................... 799
Ethical Thought Revised ............................................................ 799
Controversy .................................................................................... 804
Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 804
References ...................................................................................... 805
33 Generic Change Model ................................................................ 807
Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 807
Generic Change .............................................................................. 807
Model ......................................................................................... 807
Application................................................................................. 808
Comment .................................................................................... 808
Stages of Change in Pain ............................................................... 808
Introduction ................................................................................ 808
Progressive ................................................................................. 808
Regressive .................................................................................. 809
Comment .................................................................................... 811
Information Processing .................................................................. 811
Introduction ................................................................................ 811
Model ......................................................................................... 811
Discovering Learning ..................................................................... 812
Introduction ................................................................................ 812
Model ......................................................................................... 812
Comment .................................................................................... 812
Open-Ended Change ...................................................................... 812
Introduction ................................................................................ 812
Model ......................................................................................... 813
Executive Function......................................................................... 813
Introduction ................................................................................ 813
Model ......................................................................................... 813
Comment .................................................................................... 814
Patients ........................................................................................... 814
Introduction ................................................................................ 814
Model ......................................................................................... 814
Case Formulation ........................................................................... 815
Introduction ................................................................................ 815
Model ......................................................................................... 815
Education ....................................................................................... 817
Introduction ................................................................................ 817
Learning ..................................................................................... 817
Teaching ..................................................................................... 817
Interim Conclusion......................................................................... 818
Evolution ........................................................................................ 818
Introduction ................................................................................ 818
Mechanisms ............................................................................... 818
Model ......................................................................................... 818
Comment .................................................................................... 820
Contents xxxiii

Stages ............................................................................................. 820


Introduction ................................................................................ 820
Model ......................................................................................... 821
Comment .................................................................................... 821
Social Driver .................................................................................. 823
Introduction ................................................................................ 823
Model ......................................................................................... 823
Comment .................................................................................... 823
Data Driver ..................................................................................... 824
Causality ........................................................................................ 825
Introduction ................................................................................ 825
Genes/Epigenesis ....................................................................... 825
Causal Graphs ............................................................................ 826
Stimulus–Response .................................................................... 827
Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 828
References ...................................................................................... 829
34 Revising Maslow........................................................................... 833
Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 833
Models............................................................................................ 834
Revised Maslow in Young (2011) .............................................. 834
Re-Revising Maslow in the Present Book ................................. 834
Enaction ..................................................................................... 834
Polarities of Experience ............................................................. 835
Self-Determination..................................................................... 835
Moral Motives ............................................................................ 836
Moral Foundations ..................................................................... 838
Integrated Motivations ............................................................... 839
Revising the Maslow Revision....................................................... 841
Introduction ................................................................................ 841
Assumptions............................................................................... 843
Environmental Self ........................................................................ 843
Model ......................................................................................... 843
Comment .................................................................................... 843
Five Foundational Moral Motives .................................................. 844
Introduction ................................................................................ 844
Revising Foundational Motives ................................................. 845
Revising Moral Motives ............................................................. 846
Creating Environmental Motives ............................................... 847
Naming the Five Foundational Moral Motives .............................. 847
Introduction ................................................................................ 847
Names ........................................................................................ 848
Poles ........................................................................................... 848
Conclusion ................................................................................. 849
Mechanism ................................................................................. 850
New Questionnaire......................................................................... 850
Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 852
References ...................................................................................... 853
xxxiv Contents

35 Staging Revolutions and Paradigms ........................................... 857


Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 857
Kuhn’s Model of Paradigm Change ............................................... 857
Model ......................................................................................... 857
Comment .................................................................................... 858
Revising Kuhn on Paradigm .......................................................... 858
Relationism ................................................................................ 858
Comment .................................................................................... 859
A Neo-Kuhnian Approach ............................................................. 859
Model ......................................................................................... 859
Steps ........................................................................................... 861
Example ..................................................................................... 862
Unifying Psychology ..................................................................... 863
Modeling .................................................................................... 863
Theories...................................................................................... 863
The Model .................................................................................. 864
Philosophy.................................................................................. 865
Causal Self ..................................................................................... 867
Introduction ................................................................................ 867
Model ......................................................................................... 867
Conclusion ................................................................................. 869
Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 869
References ...................................................................................... 869
36 New Directions in Psychological Causality ................................ 871
Chapter Introduction ...................................................................... 871
Models of Neuroticism, Self-Control, and Self/Other ................... 871
Neuroticism ................................................................................ 871
Self-Control................................................................................ 872
Self/Other ................................................................................... 872
Revising the Models of Neuroticism, Self-Control,
and Self/Other ................................................................................ 874
Neuroticism ................................................................................ 874
Self-Control................................................................................ 875
Self/Other ................................................................................... 876
Revising Free Will ......................................................................... 877
Revising PTSD............................................................................... 878
Further Revising Causality of Behavior......................................... 878
Chapter Conclusions ...................................................................... 880
Book Conclusions .......................................................................... 882
The End ...................................................................................... 882
The Beginning ............................................................................ 883
References ...................................................................................... 888
37 Epilogue ........................................................................................ 889
Introduction .................................................................................... 889
Genes and Environment ................................................................. 892
Genes.......................................................................................... 892
Environment ............................................................................... 895
Contents xxxv

Development .................................................................................. 896


Models........................................................................................ 896
Domains ..................................................................................... 897
Free Will and Self-Control ............................................................. 897
Free Will .................................................................................... 897
Self-Control................................................................................ 898
Posttraumatic Stress Disorder ........................................................ 898
Dimensions ................................................................................ 898
Genes and Brain ......................................................................... 899
Malingering ................................................................................ 900
DSM-5........................................................................................ 900
Modeling ........................................................................................ 900
The Relational Model ................................................................ 900
Piagetian Modeling .................................................................... 901
Neo-Piagetian Model ................................................................. 901
Central Conceptual Structures ................................................... 903
The Network Model ................................................................... 904
Nonlinear Dynamical Systems Theory ...................................... 905
Causality ........................................................................................ 906
Introduction ................................................................................ 906
Areas .......................................................................................... 907
Comment .................................................................................... 907
New Hybrid Symptom Network Construct Model ........................ 908
Model ......................................................................................... 908
Comment .................................................................................... 908
Application................................................................................. 908
Comment .................................................................................... 910
Conclusion ................................................................................. 911
Reconceptualizing Cognitive Stages .............................................. 912
Existing Concept ........................................................................ 912
Comment .................................................................................... 912
Reconceptualization ................................................................... 912
Multiple Emotional Intelligences................................................... 919
Multiple Intelligences ................................................................ 919
Emotional Intelligence ............................................................... 921
Multiple Emotional Intelligences............................................... 922
Epilogue Conclusions .................................................................... 924
References ...................................................................................... 925

Index ...................................................................................................... 931


Part I
Core Causality in Behavior: Foundations
and Models
Brief Book Description and Book
Assumptions 1

search for understanding causality of behavior


Chapter Introduction and should be called Homo Causa.
Psychology studies both the description (or
Goal structure) of behavior and its causes or processes.
Much of psychology is concerned with the latter
Introduction The major goal of the present and establishing the “why” or “how” of behavior.
book is to meet the challenge presented by its However, there is no general book in psychology
title: Unifying Causality and Psychology: Being, explicitly devoted to causality, causation, origins,
Brain, and Behavior. First in this regard, the and determinants. Therefore, a major goal of the
book constitutes a project on unifying psychol- present book is to promote leading-edge concep-
ogy. It does not provide an answer for the project tualization on the topic of causality or causation
but, rather, presents a path or process toward the that integrates psychological research and knowl-
integration of psychology. Second, the book edge with interdisciplinary scholarship. How do
deals with the related project of integrating cau- multiple proximal, or immediate, and distal, or
sality. The primary assumption of the book is that more remote or removed, causal streams combine
by integrating knowledge on the causality of in their impact or influence on a particular behav-
behavior we can proceed toward the integration ior or on a behavior set in a particular situation?
of psychology. In this regard, the book also When do the influences include only proximal
attempts to integrate different concepts related to ones, such as present context, and when are there
the etiology of disordered behavior. Third, the more distal ones, too, not only in genetic influ-
book examines the multiple causes of behavior, ences but also in the environment, such as deriv-
both normal and abnormal. Further, it adapts an ing from one’s past, one’s development, or one’s
approach that is constructivist rather than reduc- early unconscious influences that had been
tionist. In this regard, it allows for the emergence repressed? To what extent do immediate influ-
of factors that influence behavioral causation ences include room for free will, especially in
such as self and . In the end, it adds these “per- terms of the effects of believing in it? More spe-
sonal” components to the standard argument that cifically, does having a belief in free will alter the
Nature and Nurture interact in determining options considered in a particular situation and the
behavior. Finally, it expands the concept of free one eventually chosen? Or, are we simply a deter-
will to include freedom in being, freeing the ministic product of our genes and environment
brain, and so on. Also, it expands the concept of without an active say in our own development and
the self to include the causal self. Indeed, the life course and, therefore, any construction or
book proposes that humans are unique in their model of behavior that includes any role for free

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 3


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_1
4 1 Brief Book Description and Book Assumptions

will is inconsistent with the science in the matter? literature for its conceptual and empirical contri-
The present book is dedicated to answering ques- butions and in integration of prior theories to that
tions such as these, toward an integration of not review that still have value in cohering psychol-
only the area of causality in behavioral study but ogy as a unified discipline in the present context.
also the integration of psychology, itself. However, my approach to these traditional mod-
To review, the study of causality in psychology els has been to update them to the current context
rarely is a central topic that is integrated across its of conceptual and empirical study in psychology,
separate components. The two goals of the pres- so that I end of presenting revised models for
ent book concern the integration of causality in them, e.g., Neo-Maslovian, Neo-Eriksonian, and
psychology and, indeed, movement toward the Neo-Piagetian, and this makes them more foun-
integration of psychology. In this regard, this dational than traditional. Moreover, at many
book represents the first wide-ranging integration junctures in the present book, I show how the dif-
of causality in psychology. As well, it emphasizes ferent foundational models can be integrated
that causality has the potential to be a unifying themselves, especially after I have arrived at their
concept in psychological science. Finally, the revision, and moreover, they can even be inte-
book promotes the concept of , freedom in being grated with newer models, such as embodiment,
as one that can help fulfill its two primary goals. the biopsychosocial model, and systems theory.
First, freedom in being is considered an essential
driving force in the causality of behavior. Second, Certainty That being said, there is no one
the concept of freedom in being can help integrate umbrella model yet in psychology that can serve
psychology because it describes the epitome of to integrate it, and perhaps accomplishing that
what it means to be human. task is impossible. In this regard, we might be
able to better integrate the various theories in the
Probability Is causality a sufficient focus to field, but none hold promise to be the axis in this
integrate psychology even though it is a ubiqui- regard. The integration has to take place at a dif-
tous aspect even if an underemphasized one of ferent level, in which science is placed at the top
behavioral study? In its present status, in the of the hierarchy of needs in the integrative task,
field, it does not have that potential. To repeat, it which automatically places causality as a prime
needs integration itself before that goal can be focus, aside from the reliable and valid descrip-
accomplished. Moreover, in and of itself, it can- tion of behavior and its organization, per se. The
not help unify the field, but only point to direc- theoretical models have to follow that lead and,
tions in this regard. in the end, a co-existential model of how each of
That being said, the directions toward its inte- them contributes to the whole in the field would
gration that the field of psychology needs to take be sufficient.
through the medium of causality are clear. On The theories in psychology form an integrated
the one hand, having causality as a focus as an system that develops just as the subject matter of
integrating concept in psychology enables con- the theories develops—that is, we constitute
sideration of its multifactorial nature and the ever-changing systems, especially in terms of all
ramifications of such a differentiated process in the the complexities and causal forces impinging on
determination of both normal and abnormal behav- us, and perhaps that perspective constitutes the
ior. On the other hand, with causality as a focus best axis for integrating psychology, holding
toward integrating psychology both older and more than any other axis, including that of any
newer concepts in the field can serve the task, as one theory about human behavior. We are causal
long as they are relevant to it and they fit the con- beings both in how we grow and change and in
ceptual construction involved and the empirical how we think, feel, and act. Perhaps that is the
directions that are needed to support its validity. only certainty about ourselves, and perhaps that
In this regard, the present work is founded constitutes the best axis on which to have psy-
both in a comprehensive review of the current chology integrate.
Unifying Causality and Psychology: Being, Brain, and Behavior 5

Outline impetus in the causality of our behavior, every-


thing else being equal. The book explores novel
This first chapter of the present work emphasizes concepts in this regard that I have developed,
its central assumption of the primacy of causality including, among others: , freedom in being; hav-
in psychology and explicates the tens of other ing a sense of free will; free will working models
assumptions that have guided the book’s construc- (which concern the quite-studied concept of free
tion. The chapter after this one describes the book will belief, as well as having a sense of free will);
in depth, especially chapter by chapter. The next psychotherapeutic questions based on promoting
chapter that follows, the third one of the book, free will; a model of maturity that puts responsi-
describes the starting point of the book, that is, the bility and free will at its fulcrum, and a free will
ideas on causality presented in Young (2011) and questionnaire.
the beginnings of how these ideas have been
expanded. That chapter discusses aspects of three
major axes in the study of causality in psychology Unifying Causality and Psychology:
(Young, 2011)—free will, mechanism, and causal Being, Brain, and Behavior
graph modeling—as well as providing some new
perspectives on the topic, including on the major Preamble: The Causal Self, Freedom
theme of the book, that of freedom in being. , The in Being, Stages, and Unifying
remaining 30+ chapters in the book together espe- Psychology
cially provide a comprehensive review of causal-
ity in psychology and related disciplines, before Introduction
proceeding to a last series of chapters on my per- This preamble introduces critical terms and con-
sonal contributions to understanding causality. cepts related to the present book. Specifically, it
addresses factors related to causality, free will, a
unified psychology, and stage and change models
Axes applicable to psychology.

The number of axes on causality in psychology The Causal Self


considered in the book has expanded from three Model The causal self connotes the central
to tens of them, and the book expounds on many nature of causality to our psychological identity.
of them, while keeping the three primary ones in The self concerns the personal representation that
central focus. That is, despite expanding well we have cognitively and affectively of our sub-
beyond them in the present work, the three major jective sense and of the personhood that we proj-
axes of the book on causality—of mechanism, ect or display to others. In this present book, I
free will, and graphic modeling approaches— argue that the self is causal because much of what
together still stand as the primary ones toward we do, think, and feel relates to causality. We per-
understanding the causality of behavior. Finally, ceive phenomena causally. We try to decipher the
consistent with the title of the book, I note that causes of events, people’s actions, natural phe-
free will constitutes a central axis behavioral cau- nomena, and so on. We learn about causality and
sality, as well as associated personal/self factors reason causally. We are motivated to gain causal
in the determination of behavior. control of events, people, phenomena, and so on.
In this regard, whenever discussing free will Overall, we strive to become active causal agents
in the present book, I maintain that we develop of our behavior that supercedes the passive influ-
toward and remain people who can create, choose ences on us of biology and of environment. The
from among, and act on options, thereby doing world is a causal one, and we want to take our
otherwise than prior and present factors might place in the world not merely as effects of the
dictate based uniquely on our biology and our forces that create the universe but as effects, in
environment. We ourselves constitute the central part, in at least part of that creation.
6 1 Brief Book Description and Book Assumptions

Comment The concept of the causal self is the Being/Being Becoming Freedom.” However,
last one that I developed for the book, when look- even if these latter terms capture better the
ing back at what it all means. Therefore, I have essence of the underlying concept, they are
introduced the concept at this juncture, and, in unwieldy and I refrain from pursuing their use.
Chap. 35, I will integrate material in the present The term Freedom in Being might connote to
book on what it teaches about the causal self. For some a being in freedom, in which the word
example, for the chapter on revising Maslow’s “being” is a noun. Instead of this meaning for the
concept of a hierarchy of needs, I refer to a tripar- term, I prefer to associate it with the meaning of
tite distinction in the self of the self-definitional freedom of the person in becoming, as men-
self, the relatedness self, and the competence/ tioned, so that, in this context, the word “being”
environmental/ecological self. This distinction in the term Freedom in Being is a gerund as much
can be seen to replace the classic Jamesian dis- as a noun. In this regard, all of us are beings who
tinction of the “I” and the “me,” the subjective are always in process or, said in another way, we
and the objective self, and so on. are people on pathways to stations rather than
individuals living at stations. In this sense, beings
Freedom in Being continually engage in being and do not stand still;
Model The concept of Freedom in Being bor- they do not always just be (or exist as they are)
rows heavily from Heidegger’s (1927/1962) con- without dynamically changing. Rather, they live
ception of Dasein, which I described as a critical in the processes of change and of becoming, or at
one for understanding adult development (Young, least having that potential.
1997; also see Han-Pile, 2013). Dasein translates The concept of Freedom in Being is important
as Being-in-the-World, and in Young (1997) I to the book, but in terms of the amount of work
expanded the concept to Being-Becoming-World/ devoted to it in the book, there is not much rela-
World-Becoming-Being (see Fig. 1.1). Similarly, tive to the question of behavioral causality, in
Freedom in Being is really a multiple, dialectical general. In this sense, the particular concept of
concept reflective of how we continue to become Freedom in Being exists as a guide to the book
and to be dialectically. It encapsulates the prod- and, in contrast, the work on causality, in general,
uct, or state, of Freedom in (and of) Being (or provides much of its substance.
being fully in the moment), as well as the process As presently conceived, the concept of
of becoming or developing toward Freedom in Freedom in Being has multiple components and
and of Being. Becoming is a trajectory more than can dynamically change in the person. In particu-
an end-state, and we never really get to full lar, the present conceptualization of Freedom in
Freedom in Being (or Being Freedom), and so Being has two major components—free will
on, because of the constraints both in ourselves belief and having a sense of free will (see
and in the world, no matter how conducive toward Fig. 1.1). The concept of having a sense of free
full mature growth that they might be. will is a new one, much like the case for the over-
Therefore, the concept of Freedom in Being as arching concept in which it is embedded.
applied in the present work is quite like However, the concept of belief in free will is
Heidegger’s understanding of Dasien (Han-Pile, becoming well-known and well-received (e.g.,
2013), and also quite like other concepts related Baumeister, 2008, 2014). In this regard, when the
to it, such as Freedom of Being (Frazier, 2012). present book deals with the topic of free will, or
Because it is a concept of becoming, as found in Freedom in Being, it is mostly in terms of the
my understanding of Dasein as Being-Becoming- work on belief in free will and its effects.
World/World-Becoming-Being (Young, 1997),
the term of Freedom in Being could be expanded A Parallel From a conceptual point of view, the
to denote a multiplicity of meanings and, in this psychology of free will belief is not a uniquely
regard, could be referred to as “Freedom unitary construct but exists as part of a complex
Becoming Being” or even “Freedom Becoming of related subcomponents, and any free will
Unifying Causality and Psychology: Being, Brain, and Behavior 7

Being

Becoming World

Being- Becoming-World/ Becoming-Being-World/ Becoming-World-Being/


World-Becoming-Being World-Being-Becoming Being-World-Becoming

Fig. 1.1 Dasein as being-becoming-world/world- be activity in the Vygotskian sense of the word. Its ethos
becoming-being. Dasein is dynamic potential. “it is a is ethics; its action is moral practice; its agency is com-
mode of being … which is never static, always moving munal; its communion is agentic. If Freud described
forward toward new potentialities … ‘Dasein is in every mature life as work and love, I would qualify it as world
case what it can be, and in the way it is its possibility’” work and world love. The meaning of life is the life of
(Heidegger, 1927/1962, p. 143). Mind and related con- meaning, especially as constituted in togetherness. At this
cepts may be characterized, in particular, as “becoming level, work and love become orders of magnitude more
being-in-world/world-in-being,” or more simply “being- vibrant, more authentic, and more enduring. Adopted with
becoming-world/world-becoming-being.” When defined permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young,
at this level, the separate body and mind do not seem to G. (1997). Adult Development, therapy, and culture: A
exist. Nor do the separate self-defined-as-distinct-from-- postmodern synthesis. New York: Plenum; with kind per-
other and other-defined-as-distinct-from-self. Implicated mission from Springer Science + Business Media B. V.
in this concept of mind as a shared relation is that it must [Figure 11.1, Page 256]

questionnaire should be broad enough to cover Therefore, having a sense of free will becomes
these components. In particular, free will belief specified as both (a) the manner in which one
is the cognitive component of a broader construct behaves in relationships and social exchange to
of the psychology of free will, in that behavior, convey that one has less constraints on behavior
by definition, is colored and influenced by emo- than is the norm, or even that one can overcome or
tions, the social context, self-factors, broad bypass such constraints and, therefore, think,
meanings and acting on the beliefs involved, choose, decide, act, and relate in a manner reflect-
where possible. This multifactorial approach to ing that one is behaving freely despite the con-
free will belief is consistent with the model of the straints, and (b) actually demonstrating in behavior
person (Blatt, 2008) that includes a self- that this is indeed the case.
definitional and relatedness component. It is con-
sistent with the research relating it to the desire Comment Note that it is beyond the scope of
to punish transgressions by others. Finally, it the present work to examine in depth the concept
enables it to fit into a broader biopsychosocial of Dasein (see Wrathall, 2013), not only because
view of its causes. the book is more about psychology than philoso-
As for the fit with Blatt’s (2008) work on a self- phy but also because the concept of Freedom in
definitional and relatedness self as per Young Being that animates the book is different from the
(2011), it would be appropriate to assign free will concept of Dasein and takes on its own meaning
belief to the self-definitional component. About relative to its precursors. To conclude, this book
the relatedness component of the self, up to this is about Freedom in and of Being, and honors the
point in the present work, I have been using having transcendence inherent in the concept of Dasein
a sense of free will in parallel with the term of free from which it emanates, but it has meanings dis-
will belief. It would be appropriate to juxtapose tinct from related concepts. Moreover, I have
having a sense of free will and free will belief, and presented it in a way that keeps it grounded and
relate the former to the relatedness self (while amenable to study in empirical science, with test-
relating the latter to the self-definitional one). able predictions.
8 1 Brief Book Description and Book Assumptions

About the other component of the book title abruptly as contended, everything else being
involving brain, I refer to “freeing the brain,” equal. Moreover, there are mechanisms that can
which is an approach consistent with new para- be used to explain their qualitative transitioning.
digms of understanding the brain (e.g., Friston,
2010). The concept of freeing the brain indicates: (a) First, stages are not universal because every-
the constructivist nature of brain activity; its lack one develops individually in context to adapt
of reductionistic, deterministic functioning; and to the contingencies in the context at hand
its potentially emergent and free functioning and, if there are commonalities from one per-
from lower-order levels. Also, the term is consis- son to the next, it is only because the solu-
tent with network approaches to the brain, which tions in context found by the various
highlight that the brain functions as a predictive individuals in the population at hand in the
and probability-related entity to reduce “surprise” development that takes place are common
and unexpected and nonoptimal energy expendi- ones.
ture. Several parts of the book describe in depth (b) Second, the order in the development of suc-
this new approach to brain function. Note that it is cessive stages might seem universal for the
quite linked to the one of nonlinear dynamical same reasons but, once more, the common-
systems theory (NLDST), in that both consider alities in individual solutions to the adaptive
emergence as possible if not inevitable in behav- challenges in development lead to the per-
ior. Therefore, both are quite consistent with, and ception of a universal program that applies to
speak to, the notion of free will as an emergent all, when none really exists.
force in, or driver, in behavioral causality. (c) Third, development is especially individual
and contextual, which clearly allows for
Stages exceptions to the rule that passage through a
Model Throughout the book, I refer to the con- sequence of stages that seem like the best
cept of stages in development. The manner in adaptive route to functionality in context
which I use the term is a soft and radical one, and should be found universally.
not a hard and traditional one. In the latter frame- (d) Fourth, the same logic applies to the varia-
work, a stage is a qualitatively different organiza- tions in acquisitions associated with a stage
tion of the components of a system, and one that at issue. There should be no hard and fast
will appear universally in a sequence if there are rule that all should be acquired at the same
a number of them that apply to the population at time or close to it, or else exceptions to the
hand. There is little room for flexibility and indi- rule explained away when it does not happen
vidual difference in the stage structure that only because of task and contextual varia-
applies and, moreover, the manner in which the tions. Each actor passing through the stage
system at issue can reorganize at a higher-order sequence at issue will have internal as well as
level remains a puzzle and seemingly impossible, external factors that serve to disrupt smooth
but some sort of internal program might be attrib- passage through the system, finding the
uted to the process. Further, in this view, the vari- modal solutions involved, and so on.
ous acquisitions in the system should manifest (e) Fifth, these fundamental attributes of the
their new properties more or less simultaneously radical stage conception that I am proposing
and, if not, the décalages in the sequencing can apply to the proposed substages in any appli-
be readily explained by task or contextual and cable stage model.
other external factors rather than internal ones. (f) Sixth, another confounding factor for tradi-
In developing the opposing soft approach to tional stage models is that they contend that
stages, I remove all the rigidities associated with once the individual arrives at a new stage or
the concept. In this regard, stages are neither uni- substage, it incorporates the prior one for the
versal (necessarily manifesting in the same acquisition at hand, and it is no longer avail-
sequence for everybody) nor do they appear as able. Moreover, the new qualitative advance
Unifying Causality and Psychology: Being, Brain, and Behavior 9

spreads throughout the system involved, empirical directions to test them. That being
bootstrapping the whole system to its more said, in using the terms of stages or substages in
advanced level. However, it is more likely the present book, often I take them from the con-
that as new advanced levels are constructed text in which they were presented without this
in the system, they do not necessarily replace qualifier of how they can be changed according
the prior ones, but can co-exist with them. to the present version.
For example, there is no reason to presume
that lower-order sensorimotor thinking pro- Unifying Psychology
cesses cannot co-exist with higher-order Introduction Counterintuitively, I maintain that
abstract ones, and even supplement them as psychology cannot be unified. However, psy-
they work together in solving a problem. In chology can adopt the project of attempting to
Young (2011), I referred to the process of unify itself. The unification of psychology is
using simultaneously lower- and higher- more of a process or a pathway than a product or
order thought processes as yoking. Moreover, a unified model. There are many contributions in
they come together locally to solve the prob- this present book to this unification of psychol-
lem at hand, can drop out, reappear, bring in ogy project. However, at the same time, I admit
intermediate forms, and so on. That is, the and even fully endorse that the project will never
components of the wider cognitive system be complete, nor should it be.
constituted in stage models function in an
ongoing, adaptive, soft-assembly manner. Models Sternberg and Grigorenko (2001)
(g) Seventh, the mechanisms that allow for the described that unified psychology should be mul-
emergence of qualitatively different levels in tiparadigmatic, multidisciplinary, and integrated
any system are being elucidated, and they through converging operations such as learning
apply to stage modeling, as well, in particu- and memory as a focus of study from multiple
lar, systems theory refers to—emergence; the points of view. They described that Staats (1983,
whole being greater than the sum of the parts; 1991, 1993, 1999) argued for a unified empirical
new states in the system being unpredictable positivistic approach to help unify psychology
from knowledge of the parts and their prop- over its different hierarchical levels. Sternberg
erties; self-organization; complexity; differ- and Grigorenko (2001) noted some similarity
ent levels within the system from lower to with Staats’s approach and that of system theory
higher; circular causality (which I have (e.g., Thelen & Smith, 1994, 1998).
called causal circular emergence); being far The first book that has attempted unification
from equilibrium, or at the edge of order and of psychology is published in 2011 by Henriques,
disorder, or of stability and change, perhaps and he called the book “A New Unified Theory of
with a minor perturbation nonlinearly and Psychology.” He argued that unification of the
dynamically enabling system change (e.g., scientific discipline of psychology should
bifurcating to a new state, basin, or regime; approach more folk psychology. In this regard, he
the butterfly effect). related human exceptionality to our capacity for
symbolic language. And, languages are espe-
Comment Given these premises of how stages cially useful for social justification, that is, for
function in a highly adaptive, ongoing, and flex- explaining one’s behavior in terms of what is
ible way, the rigidities associated with traditional socially legitimate. Further, human self-
models of stages in psychology have been obvi- consciousness exists to function as a system of
ated and, therefore, stage conceptions should not justification. Therefore, humans are justifying
be seen as inexact, misleading, unable to explain both to themselves and others their behavior.
the data, and failures. Rather, the new concep- Ultimately, they formulate justification narratives,
tion allows for a rereading of the data that applies which provide meaning to their behaviors, and
to any stage model and also it suggests new that make sense their world and their place in it.
10 1 Brief Book Description and Book Assumptions

Finally, humans develop cultures that are espe- psychology can be conceived in terms of concepts
cially justification focused. Cultures are consti- such as causality and free will, as illustrated in my
tuted by social constructions that are large scale approach to a unifying project for psychology.
collective systems of justification aimed that Also, any discipline, super, sub, or moderate in
coordinating people, for example, in its laws, size, in psychology or a neighboring discipline,
norms, values, and religions. such as psychiatry, will find commonality with
He had three more frames that constituted his others related to it through a focus on causality
unified theory of psychology and, as with the jus- and free will and similar concepts, as evidenced in
tification hypothesis he created these frames him- the present work.
self. The broadest frame is the tree of knowledge
system, which is based on the work of Chaisson Comment Although I respect the desire of
(2001). This work serves the present book in its Sternberg and Grigorenko, Staats, and Henriques,
efforts at unification, as well. That is, its “big his- as well as others striving to integrate or unifying
tory” approach and emphasis on energy and ther- psychology, I believe that, by definition, any one
modynamics give a broad picture of not only answer, no matter how intellectually cohesive
human evolution and behavior but also the evolu- and nuanced, will be limited and not arrive at the
tion and behavior of the universe. Another impor- goal. Recall that I consider the unification of psy-
tant frame in Henriques’s (2011) unified theory chology more of a process than a product. It is a
of psychology is behavioral investment theory. It, project that we need to adopt, knowing from the
too, concerns energy and evolution, but also it beginning that it will never be complete. Just as
concerns genetics, neurocomputational control, any area of psychology keeps evolving and sci-
learning, and development. These principles of ence, itself, keeps evolving, psychology can
the theory are related to Tinbergen, four ques- never be fully integrated and unified into one
tions, as discussed in Chap. 3. The last compo- answer, model, theory, or paradigm. At the end of
nent of Henriques’s model is the influence matrix. the present book, in Chap. 36, I elaborate this
It presents various motivations and emotions idea of how the pathway toward unifying psy-
along three major axes: power, love, and free- chology can proceed, yet without indicating its
dom. In the present book, I deal with these vari- absolute final status in this regard, which is
ous aspects of behavior in Chap. 34, in which I impossible, and thankfully so.
present a modified Neo-Maslovian model.
In 2013, the journal, Review of General
Psychology published a special issue on unifying Introduction
psychology. Aside from Henriques’s (2013) out-
line of the concepts in his 2011, it included other This book is the first comprehensive one on the
articles, many of which I have integrated into the topic of the causality of behavior in psychology
present book (e.g., Chemero, 2013). Marsh and and related disciplines. Also, it is only the second
Boag (2014) attempted to integrate these articles book on the unification of psychology, and it is
along a “continuum of practical assumptions,” and much broader in scope of the first one (Henriques,
placed the Henriques’s paper on the risk end 2011). By placing causality as a central axis on
because of its experimental predictions. An exam- which the integration of psychology can be built,
ple of work at the metaphysical end involves the book will speak to all the subareas of psychol-
Petocz and Mackay (2013; on situational realism). ogy, and of related disciplines, as well. It offers
Green (2015) maintained that psychology multiple ways that causality can constitute an
cannot become unified because of its lack of clear integrating concept in psychology and related dis-
boundaries. He referred to the development of ciplines. Moreover, it integrates the study of cau-
“super sub-disciplines” as one way to give psy- sality in psychology not just by showing its
chology some coherence (at least within each). undeniable breadth but also by offering ways cau-
The central tenet of the present work is that any sality as a construct can, itself, be cohered or inte-
continuum that arranges approaches to unifying grated. It reviews many theoretical models on
Book Parts 11

causality or related topics and also conducts an models. The second part of the book examines
extensive literature review of contemporary the brain, especially in terms of neuronal net-
empirical research on or related to the topic. It works and hemispheric and manual specializa-
includes many new concepts that I have devel- tion (lateralization). There are three chapters on
oped, especially related to free will, but also oth- genetics and related topics. The part concludes
ers. The latter include new concepts about with a chapter on evolution. The third part of the
causality, in general. In addition, I present revised book considers development as well as free will.
models related to major figures in psychology, The last chapter in this part is on self-control and
especially Piaget, Erikson, Maslow, and Kuhn. its depletion, in particular. The fourth part of the
Finally, at the applied level, I present a reworked book is applied. It deals with the use of free will
definition of mental disorder, I rework several dis- in psychotherapy, posttraumatic stress disorder
orders in the DSM-5 (Diagnostic and Statistical (PTSD) and the DSM-5 (American Psychiatric
Manual of Mental Disorders, Fifth Edition; Association, 2013), including on etiology. It
American Psychiatric Association), and I present presents an integrated top-down/bottom-up
a workable approach toward revising the DSM-5. model of the etiology of mental disorder. The
If there is one simple concept that covers fifth part of the book presents my personal con-
much of the integrated nature of behavioral cau- ceptualizations and innovations, for example, for
sality covered in the present book, it is the one of the area of psychological injury and law. Also, I
the biopsychosocial model. The book adopts a present a revised model of Stimulus-Organism-
biopsychosocial perspective in that behavior is Response (S-O-R) and new terms that I have cre-
considered influenced not only by Nature and ated. A model that I developed to represent the
Nurture but also by the self. As humans develop, contents of the book is called the Co-existential
we become increasingly the primary active agents Causal Intraactive model. The part includes a
of our behavior and are not simply the passive chapter on change mechanisms. The last part of
outcomes of biology and environment. Behavior the book reviews my Neo-Piagetian/Neo-
is not simply deterministic in nature, or shaped Eriksonian developmental model (Young, 2011,
by the past and present context. Rather, we have also in Young, 2014), I apply the model to revis-
an element of free will in the choices on which ing Maslow’s and Kuhn’s, and to develop a
we focus and the decisions that we make. In this generic change model. The book concludes with
regard, the book considers an important aspect of a process model of behavioral causality.
self/personal influence on behavior—freedom in
being, which develops in the person through its
major components of believing in free will and Comment
having a sense of free will.
With these prefatory comments that help grasp Overall, the present book stands out by its com-
the nature of the present book, I proceed to prehensive integration on the topic of causality of
describe its major parts, or groups of chapters, behavior and by attempting to place the concept
and then its assumptions. A more detailed of causality as a unifying construct for the field.
description of each chapter can be found in the Also, the present book has concrete and practical
next chapter. applications, such as dealing with psychopathol-
ogy, the DSM-5, and new questionnaires, includ-
ing ones related to free will. Lastly, it places the
Book Parts self—and especially free will—as an emergent
important aspect of behavioral determination,
Parts emphasizing that we have the ultimate role in
establishing the causality of our own behavior. In
The first part of the book gives a general over- many ways, the book deals with human excep-
view in the study of behavioral causality. It tionalism, and what makes us unique as a species.
includes a chapter on philosophy and others on In this regard, I hope that by acquiring a better
12 1 Brief Book Description and Book Assumptions

understanding of the causes of our behavior In this regard, psychology might want to consider
through this book, other sources, and scientific its role in this perspective and adopt a “Big
investigation, we can better facilitate that our Psychology” viewpoint. This suggestion might
advanced capacities are used for the benefit of all justify developing unifying ideas in psychology
species and the planet. related to critical factors and models that have
potential unifying power, such as dynamical, ther-
modynamic, and emergent systems modeling of
The Broader Context behavior, embodiment modeling, the superordinate
meta-model of relationism, and so on. However,
Integrations the present work opts for two other potential unify-
ing modeling foci for psychology—behavioral
Human scholarship aims to understand human causality and the role of free will compared to
behavior in all its pulses and origins, and psy- determinism in behavior, along with models that
chology constitutes a critical field of endeavor in are related to or that encompass them (e.g., the bio-
this regard. Psychology is an integrative science psychosocial model). I have addressed above the
that borrows from and contributes to disparate import of free will and related concepts and, in the
fields, such as genetics, anthropology, evolution, following, I turn to the centrality that causality
and sociology. It shares their concern for rigorous could have as a unifying force in psychology.
study, testable conceptualization, empirical sup-
port, and replicable research using reliable and
valid methods. It is an offshoot of philosophy Causality
and, historically, the latter field has been more
concerned with conceptualization in its approach, Unification Causality can serve as a unifying
although oriented to empirical verification ques- force in psychology but, before disciplinary inte-
tions to a degree. That being said, philosophy is gration such as this can take place, the work on
now gravitating to the experimental front. the topic itself needs to be integrated. Moreover,
Disciplines in the social sciences might lack causality would appear to be central not only to
unified principles that help to coalesce them into psychology but to any field of scholarship, espe-
coherent bodies of conceptualization and study. cially science.
They migrate in multiple, disparate directions, Aside from more clearly embedding itself in
and presently appear to lack the need for and other scientific and scholarly approaches to
search for integrative, overarching concepts understanding human behavior and its origins,
across the whole field. Consilience (Wilson, psychology should address in more depth ques-
1999) is the endeavor to find common ground in tions that are common to all related disciplines.
scholarship, and, as with philosophy, among In this regard, whatever the discipline, prominent
other disciplines, psychology is becoming more questions for students and academics relate to the
concerned with broad theoretical and empirical “wh” questions. These can be simplified to
issues and with unifying models. Workers such as understanding the “what” or description of the
Chemero (2013) and Clark (2013a, 2013b) are phenomena at issue, and their “why” or how,
making inroads on these regards, but we still need which concerns causality and causation. The
broad, meta-theoretical models (Overton, 2015). present work attempts to address this larger pic-
Moreover, other areas of social and humanistic ture in psychology, dealing with both the phe-
studies are further along than psychology in its nomenological description of behavior and its
cross-disciplinary and integrative efforts, for causal origins. Only by tackling in concert both
example, especially history, with its concept of of these major foci, might we obtain an apprecia-
“Big History” (Chaisson, 2010, 2011). The latter tion of the study of causality as one unifying
explores history in terms of antecedents that shaped force in psychology, placing it at the forefront of
human evolution, from the Big Bang onwards. our activities in scholarship in the field.
The Broader Context 13

Even if it is not a unifying factor in present Recently, Shrout (2011) edited a book that
scholarship, despite appearances to the contrary, focused on epidemiology and psychopathology,
causality does constitute the central question in in particular. Psychology deals with mental ill-
scholarly investigation, especially in science. ness, and all advances in the field related to its
Because of its ubiquity in scientific/scholarly etiology are welcome. Markus and Borsboom
investigation, in and of itself, most would argue (2013) wrote a book on testing and causality,
that it does not seem to be a topic of predominant which I review in Chap. 6. Mikulincer and Shaver
focus. However, it is an undercurrent in every (2014) edited a work on social connection, which
area of research, and the ultimate question to I review in Chap. 15. Corrigan (2014) edited a
which each one is addressed. work on the causes of disability and stigma.
Doubt about the centrality of causality in Relative to present purposes, it is too specific for
research appears to apply to social science, in me to give it more than a brief mention, but it
particular, perhaps because often it is difficult to illustrates that there is an evident increasing focus
undertake strict experimental studies in its disci- on causation in psychology.
plines. Relative to correlational research, con- The books that have been written earlier on the
trolled experimental research allows the topic also had been quite specific in focus. They
investigator to better grasp causality. However, include ones by Rodin, Schaie, and Schooler
when dealing with human populations, ethical (1990) on self-directedness, Ouimette and Brown
issues impose limitations on the experimental (2003) [updated in Ouimette and Read (2013)] on
manipulations needed to address directly the trauma and substance abuse, and Haynes (1992)
matter of causality of behavior. on psychopathology. The latter book is classic to
Also, in the social sciences, strict positivism, the field, having investigated causality in psycho-
or empiricism, is being challenged by approaches pathology both conceptually and statistically. My
that are more constructivist, relational, herme- own books have been on causality in psychologi-
neutical (interpretative), relativistic, dialectical, cal injury and development (Young, Kane, &
and so on. Therefore, the foundations of the dis- Nicholson, 2007; Young, 2011, respectively).
ciplines in social science are challenged at every With Young, Kane, and Nicholson (2006), the
turn in terms of the “established” facts, informa- former book helped coalesce this relatively new
tion, empirical output, data, and so on. Because field in psychology (also see Young, 2008). The
these disciplines are still focused on establishing 2011 Young book is a precursor to the present
the conceptual grounds for their research and on one, and it is entitled Development and Causality.
describing the phenomena that comprise the field In some senses, the present book could be entitled
of study, the investigation of their associated its inverse—Causality and Development.
causes often is left behind and, even if under-
taken, left uncertain. However, alternative ways Conclusion The present work considers causal-
of addressing causality in behavior are bearing ity as a potentially core, unifying focus in psy-
fruit, as shall be shown in this present work. chology. Every behavior of interest requires not
only careful elucidation of its objective character-
Other Books Of the books with causality, cau- istics but also incisive clarification of its causal-
sation, cause, or causal in the title, none have ity, and especially in terms of mechanisms. Also,
been integrative across psychology. I mention the quest to elaborate the descriptive phenome-
and review all the books having these terms in nology of behavior should not be considered sep-
the title for psychology and related disciplines as arate from search for its causal origins; the
the present work proceeds. Much work in the streams of seeking to know the “what” and the
area is on statistical methodology and causal “why” of behavior should be integrated at every
graph modeling, but we can only give a flavor turn; each of the two informs the other and pro-
here (e.g., Pearl, 2009). Other books emphasize vides information that reciprocally innervates the
the application of this latter approach to psychol- study and understanding of the other. Describing
ogy (e.g., Sloman, 2005). behavior gives the product of the processes
14 1 Brief Book Description and Book Assumptions

involved while, at the same time, the processes description of one article after another in a
provide ground on the particular product (behav- particular section without ongoing integrative
ior) at hand, so that in psychology product and efforts taking place.
process constitute a unified intrinsic interrelation. In the next part of the chapter, I describe some
Note that at several junctures in the book, I refer basic premises and concepts that guided my
to the “what” and the “why” of behavior at prod- understanding of causality as I proceeded in my
uct and process, respectively. attempt to summarize all the relevant material and
integrate it. In the chapters that follow, often
I return to these themes. There are 30 of these
Limitations foundational assumptions to the present book,
and they are organized into common themes.
The present work covers a large portion of the
conceptualization and research investigation of
causality in psychology. In addition, it explores Assumptions
the topic in several related disciplines, such as
philosophy, psychiatry, ecology, epidemiology, In this description of the 30 fundamental assump-
evolution, neuroscience, law, statistics, and net- tions underlying present work, I present in an
work modeling. The causality concepts in these accessible way the basic notions that conditioned
latter disciplines are rich and complex, and the my approach to the study of causality in psychol-
empirical findings are dense and burgeoning, so ogy. The assumptions range from the importance
that it is becoming exponentially more difficult to of being inclusive to understanding causality to
seize the essence of the area of causality in any placing it centrally in the efforts to find an inte-
one of them, let alone over all of them. grative concept in psychology. The assumptions
Nevertheless, the goal of the present work is to and constructs involved will be described with
conduct a partial survey of how causality is con- more precision and in depth as the work pro-
sidered in these various disciplines, especially in ceeds. They are divided into six major groups of
how it relates to psychology. five assumptions.
Given that there was so much material to cover
in order to understand the causality of behavior,
much of the book involves description of critical General
concepts and empirical research on the topic. As
I delved into the topic, my approach was to learn 1. Causality is central to the study of psychol-
from every article, chapter, or book. As I read ogy, but despite its ubiquity it has not been
them, I considered each of them as independent given sufficient prominence in the field as a
“data” that had to be described carefully before I distinct focus. For example, in psychology,
proceeded to comment on them. The reader will there are very few books with the words cau-
notice that many times there are headings in the sality, causation, cause, or causal in the title.
book related to models, evidence, and commen- 2. Causality is one of the two major arms of psy-
tary, or similar ones. This approach of describing chological study, the other being the descrip-
the work of others directly before commenting on tion of behavior. The study of the “what” and
them permitted me to have a large fund of mate- the “why” of a system go hand in hand, and
rial related to causality written by many others knowledge of the why could alter understand-
before arriving at constructed integrations in the ing of the what, as much as the inverse applies.
field. [Of course, please understand that in Indeed, trying to define the “what” in a system
describing the extant research, many times it was should always mean trying to define the “why,”
impossible to give all the pertinent details, espe- as well. Both of these foci of behavior—the
cially methodological ones]. Nevertheless, this “what” and “why,” product and process, and
approach has limitations in that often it leads to phenomenological description and causal
Assumptions 15

explanation—need to be investigated in psy- directly in the name of the model allows me to


chological research and practice. The descrip- include under its rubric work on free will as an
tive “what” of a discipline cannot be well essential aspect of the personal component in
understood separately from a good grasp of its the causality of human behavior.
causal why or how; approaches to description 4. Causality in psychology requires sophisticated
and explanation reciprocally inform each statistical approaches that can tease apart the
other. As one example, the nosological manu- confounder variables inherent in research
als of psychiatric disease are into their next designs that are not strictly experimental.
generation (DSM-5; American Psychiatric There is much progress being made in this
Association, 2013; International Classification regard, and whole disciplines exist in which
of Diseases, ICD-11, World Health only observational and correlational data can
Organization, 2017), but despite what the be gathered (e.g., epidemiology, astronomy),
manuals proffer as the causal bases underlying yet causality is addressed nonetheless.
the categories in the manuals (i.e., etiology), 5. Much of behavior reflects biological influ-
often the categories involved are presented in ences. It is so complex that only isolated com-
the manuals only as symptom-based and with- ponents might seem totally environmental. As
out reference to underlying causes, which are a whole, its biological, genetic, and evolution-
still being differentiated in the literature. As ary bases need to be explicated in order to
the latter effort progresses, the psychiatric phe- understand what it is and its causal why and
notypes proposed by the manuals are qualified how. That being said, the present work is nei-
or changed with each new edition. Where there ther nativistic nor especially biological in
is little causal understanding, the danger is that nature. To the contrary, it adopts an interactive
new categories could proliferate in new edi- approach in its biopsychosocial emphasis, but
tions. Generally, the manuals have too many adds the personal component to the
categories, and ones that are not necessarily interaction.
reliable and valid. By working from cause to
disorder, and back, the quagmires and conun-
drums in these regards might demonstrate Specifics
progress or resolve more quickly.
3. Causality requires integrated concepts in psy- 6. The integrated concepts needed in the study
chology. At the heuristic level, variants of the of causality in psychology, and the methods,
biopsychosocial model can capture its major as well, should be broad enough to cover
constituents. For example, these would behavior in any species, at any age, and in
include genetic/neuronal, personality/self, any context. If we are to understand behav-
and family/cultural factors, respectively. ioral causality in humans, we need an inte-
However, this type of model needs to be grative approach that incorporates
expanded to cover all possible contingencies evolutionary, developmental, and contextual
in causal analysis. In this regard, one model (e.g., cultural) foundations and variations.
that can help to understand the “what” and the 7. The organisms of the species studied in psy-
“why” of behavior is the biopersonalsocial chology and related disciplines should not be
one (Young, 2011), a label that is a variant of considered static entities. Even if apparently
the biopsychosocial model. I changed the ter- static in nature, a state never exists as a state
minology of the model in this way to indicate without change. A state in equilibrium exists
that, in behavior, we have an active say in our in dynamic tension among it constituents
growth, and behavioral causality is not just and with its context, and so is changing in
about “nature” and “nurture” but also about the sense that it keeps adjusting to the
ourselves. Moreover, referring to a personal changes in its constituents/context in order to
component in the causality of behavior preserve its ongoing state characteristics.
16 1 Brief Book Description and Book Assumptions

8. Behavior takes place over multiple time multiple levels in behavioral organization
frames, from the micro- to macro-, from the that do not include the brain. Nevertheless, in
immediate and over the lifespan, and from one way or another, brain structure, function,
within the lifespan to across it over genera- connectivity, networking, specialization, and
tions [and prior to it in its influences from our properties are involved in all behavior.
ancestral past]. The models developed on Moreover, these various system levels are
causality should integrate these multiple time complicated in their relation and, as men-
frames, from the milliseconds in neuronal fir- tioned, they even allow for emergence, e.g.,
ing, to the ongoing micro-attunements to through reciprocal circular causality in bot-
context, to the macro changes in develop- tom-up and top-down influences. Therefore,
ment, and to the cross-generational transitions although behavior is always about the brain,
from one generation to the next, if not over the relationship between brain and behavior
the paleontological epochs in evolution. is complex, with multiple mediators and
9. The causal models developed should avoid moderators that are involved, and even emer-
isolating organism from context, stimulus gent properties not predicted the components
from response, action from perception (and that constitute them.
appraisal), mind from brain, and so on. The 12. Behavior is always about the person. It is
phenomena in psychology exist in a rela- more than the effect of genes/biology/brain
tional matrix in which it is difficult to isolate and culture/group/family influences, because
complementarities that exist reciprocally. the person has a say in her or his own growth.
We might be tempted to consider as linear Each person is unique even if there are uni-
the stream of behavior and its effects and versals that provide scaffolds on which one’s
outcomes and to consider its evident organi- uniqueness is molded.
zational tiers simply as reflections of ones 13. Self-regulation is essential for behavior that
lower in the hierarchy that is revealed for an is adaptive environmentally. It leads to effi-
area. However, although positivism and cient and effective behavioral control and
reductionism might be needed to help in execution. However, it can become problem-
understanding at one level the issues at hand, atic, for example, due to early adversity/mal-
their use might mask the depth needed to treatment (especially when biological
fully understand them. vulnerability factors also present). Also,
10. Behavior exists in systems, functions as part self-control can be depleted by context and
of them and, indeed, reflects them. Causality the sequences involved in behavioral
is as much about systems as particular behav- adaptation.
iors. From a dynamical systems perspective, 14. Behavior is about both (a) commonalities or
it is impossible to separate the “what” and the universals and (b) individual or group differ-
“why” in a system. Cause resides in system ences. To understand causality in full, we
pattern configurations, and these re-arrange need to understand both of these aspects of
through self-organization. Moreover, system behavior. However, in this regard, the study
change could include emergent patterns that of behavior at times is more about the indi-
are unpredictable from full knowledge of the vidual and group differences among people
elements (and their characteristics) involved. more than the normative averages collated
from the individual and group differences
expressed. Individual differences include
Biopsychosocial group differences, such as those related to
age, sex, and culture. To understand the cau-
11. Behavior is always about the brain (and sality of behavior, psychology needs to con-
related central and peripheral nervous sys- ceptualize and study both universal and
tem agents). This does not deny that there are individual differences in behavior.
Assumptions 17

15. Behavior in the present is always stochastic Models of behavioral causality need to be
and probabilistic. It is never fully specified generic in this sense, as well.
or determined by priors or pre-existing 19. At the same time, therapeutic interventions
states/factors, whether biological, personal, can help when behavior becomes problem-
or environmental. This does not make it any atic. The generic change mechanisms
less deterministic at a global level. General described in a generic change model need to
patterns might involve attractors, for exam- be general enough to cover change through
ple, in which system states inevitably gravi- psychotherapeutic interventions and treat-
tate to powerful basins in their state space ment. Moreover, often the latter tackle com-
despite momentary, ongoing deviations from mon undercurrents to disorders, or have
them (although attractor regimes are subject shared transdiagnostic or cross-disorder
to change). commonalities, including in stages of
change. Models of change processes in psy-
chotherapy should be general enough to
Change accommodate to factors such as these so that
the models of therapeutic change fit the
16. Psychology needs to elucidate general generic change models that are developed as
change mechanisms in behavior. Because much as the case for any other area.
transformation in organisms is ubiquitous 20. The change models and mechanisms pro-
and constant (as argued above, even stasis in posed even should be general enough to apply
behavior involves a type of ongoing change to change processes in nonliving systems. For
to ongoing system variability toward the example, nonlinear dynamical systems theory
homeostatic target), causal modeling needs (NLDST) applies to the rapid and radical
to account for both change and preservation transformations that can take place in multi-
of the status quo without apparent change. ple types of systems, including nonliving
The concepts of causality in behavior need to ones. The so-called chaos of change is a mis-
be generic enough to account both for any nomer. Chaotic change in NLDST really is
types of change and their resistance. about orderly change, for example, in the pro-
17. Part of the general change mechanisms in cesses that take place at the cusp of change.
behavior should be able to accommodate
qualitative transformation (to new, quite dif-
ferent states), in that change is not always Systems and Axes
quantitative and accretional. In developmen-
tal psychology, stage models, such as those 21. The systems structures hypothesized to char-
of Piaget and Erikson, reflect conceptualiza- acterize behavior should be sufficiently flex-
tion of development as qualitative and step- ible to accommodate multiple levels and
like. Change models need to account for their arrangements, for example, both in ver-
stage transitions that are qualitative as much tical and hierarchical interactions. Moreover,
as accounting for quantitative change and multiple system levels can express both bot-
general change. tom-up and top-down processes. This could
18. The change mechanisms developed in the happen both within and across them. Systems
field should be able to accommodate regres- are constituted by elements and their interre-
sions, problematic behavior, the effect of lations, and reflect the dictum that the whole
adversities, and so on, and not just change in is greater than the sum of the parts. Moreover,
an increasingly adaptive, adjusting, and pro- how much is there correspondence over lev-
gressive direction. Behavior can go awry, els in systems due to fractalization processes?
become disturbed, or even grossly psychotic For example, behavior cannot be uniformly
and criminal. The root causes are multiple. reduced to physiological or brain processes,
18 1 Brief Book Description and Book Assumptions

or mind to stimulus–response connections. as a unique or distinct focus in psychology is


Indeed, factors in behavioral causality at the nascent. It needs to respect extant terms but
personal level exist independent as emergent also create novel ones reflective of and also
phenomena of these more basic levels in the instigative of new ideas and fresh directions.
behavioral system. This applies to the influ- Granted, the topic of causality is ubiquitous
ence of free will on our behavior. The propo- in psychology, and the dictum that correla-
sition that it is important to behavioral tion does not mean causation is present per-
causality has validity only to the extent that vasively. However, innovations conceptually
conceptually we agree that it reflects a can spur work in the area, and allow for
higher-order level of behavior distinct from cohering of its disparate directions. In this
lower levels and capable of influencing them regard, one concept that I promote is that
as much as they influence it. Fractalization humans are Homo Causa. .It is not just that
permits propagation of kernels of behavioral we consider causality important to discover.
causality throughout the behavioral system Rather, discovering causality is the essence
as self-similar expressions over levels. of who we are and how we behave.
22. The behavior to which causal explanations 24. The search for causality in the different areas
are aimed should vary from the most simple of psychology should constitute its primary
to the most complex, and the relationships axis of integration. In a certain sense, how
over the levels in the full system at issue causality is studied defines a field.
acknowledged, despite any emergence that Psychology needs an integrated approach to
might take place in the system being exam- this question. As the study of causality
ined. For example, in terms of simplicity, matures in psychology, it should come to
what are the causal mechanisms in the sim- inform, influence, and even transform and
plest neuronal firings for the simplest new- dictate to other areas of psychology. Granted,
born behaviors? Do they exhibit the psychology has distinct fields or domains of
complexities evident in other levels in their inquiry and it is separated into major areas
system? At the other extreme, in terms of that might not have much cross-talk.
complexity, how does the emergent property However, ways should be found to allow for
of free will in the personal level of the sys- better integration over its separate fields or
tem relate to the simplest neuronal firings in domains. Also, the value in a movement to
the newborn? Are there common properties integrate the fields or domains of psychology
to different levels of a behavior system applies equally to other disciplines and also
despite any intermediary emergence that to their relationships with psychology (e.g.,
appears to differentiate their basic character- with neuroscience). In this regard, by placing
istics? Similarly, relative to the development causality as a central axis in psychological
of the simplest of behaviors in the person, study, it can help cohere it, on the one hand,
how do the most complex develop in groups over its fields and domains, and on the other
of people or in their institutions; for exam- hand, over its links to their disciplines.
ple, how does scientific thought itself 25. As the study of causality matures, it will also
develop? How do scientific paradigms that continue to grow, transform, change, differ-
govern the frameworks in which scientific entiate, and integrate. Indeed, it could become
thought evolve function to evolve them- center stage in the study of behavior as it does
selves? How do societies organize into so. Yet, it never should be considered to have
superordinate structures from the collection evolved to a final understanding, and having
of individuals involved? reached a plateau of knowledge. Rather, as
23. Most areas of psychology witness an increas- with other areas of psychology specifically
ing differentiation and integration in con- and science and scholarship generally, the
cepts, terminology, and definition as the study of causality and change in behavior
areas evolve. However, the study of causality should constantly change and improve.
Assumptions 19

Integration, Exceptionalism, 29. Causality is not only the essence of psychol-


and Essence ogy but also causality is psychology, and
vice versa. Without understanding the ori-
26. One fruitful avenue toward the study of cau- gins of what we describe as behavior, we can
sality in behavior lies in my own work (e.g., never be certain that the descriptions are
Young, 2011, 2014). The last portion of the accurate. That is, we have seen that we need
present work explores further how my ideas to understand the “why” and “how” of
in my prior books have contributed to the behavior to truly understand the “what” of
study of causality in psychology and how behavior. Further, because every field or
they can be further expanded. I unabashedly domain of psychology seeks causal under-
support a stage model of change, one that standing, concepts about causality in each of
can even be applied to nonliving systems. In them need to have shared characteristics over
this regard, I have developed a Neo- them in order to facilitate communicative
Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian lifespan model of exchange and integration. As much as cau-
development and sought its general charac- sality is potentially central to psychology, its
teristics so that its proposed underlying present state of dispersion detracts from its
change process can be applied even to non- potentially integrative role. In this regard, a
living systems. Other concepts that I have book such as the present one can help the
developed can help in the study of causality. causality project that I am advocating for
For example, the concept of activation/inhi- psychology, for example, through its collec-
bition coordination across the diverse levels tion of the diverse elements in its study into
of the behavioral, brain, neuronal network, one source, its innovations, and the models
development, and social relational systems that I have created.
could prove helpful in this regard. 30. Psychology, in general, struggles with inte-
27. Causality generally considered involves nor- gration and differentiation. On the one hand,
mal and abnormal behavior. However, for I have come across efforts to integrate it.
abnormal behavior alone, causality refers to Also, it is more seamless in many ways than
etiology. A broad understanding of behav- the cut and dry nature of its distinctions
ioral causality needs to include concepts that imply. This is true, for example, for stimulus
are applicable to etiology. In both cases, the vs. response, organism vs. context, mind vs.
integration of top-down and bottom-up pro- brain, gene vs. environment, and even “what”
cesses over different levels of the system vs. “why” and “how.” However, on the other
involved would be important. hand, it is very difficult for these efforts
28. Behavior is about human exceptionalism. toward integrating psychology to have much
What makes us a distinct species? Is it our impact despite their promise. It could be
superordinate abstract thought, our apparent argued that it is either premature to under-
free will, the choices that we make for our- take this type of integration, given the early
selves and our children, our capacity to teach nature in the development of the discipline
them formally and have them learn greatly relative to some others, or that, indeed, the
from our endeavors, our capacity to con- task itself is impossible. Nevertheless, the
struct cities and other collective and cultural fundamental assumption of the present book
institutions, and so on? Perhaps part of the is that causality can be the unifying force in
answer lies in causality, in that we appear to psychology, especially if its ideas advance
be the only species that can affect the course further enough and are integrated them-
of our behavior and also our environment. selves. To help along this causality project,
Moreover, perhaps one aspect of human cau- that causality can take its central, unifying
sality contributes especially to our excep- place in psychology and also that its center
tionalism—that related to free will. can be understood better, some of the
20 1 Brief Book Description and Book Assumptions

disjunctive divisions in psychology that have its understanding and in how to help children,
been mentioned, themselves, need better people in need, and society, in general. Causality
conceptualization and integration toward could be the superordinate unifying concept to the
being unified. That is, the higher-order goal disparate models in the field, given its potential
of placing causality as a central axis in psy- central axis in the study of behavior generally.
chology to address some of its divisiveness To conclude this introduction to the present
can be achieved only if some of its lower- book, it underscores the potential unifying role
order separations can be congealed. for psychology of understanding the causality of
Psychology needs to create a superordinate behavior, both normal and abnormal and how it
system of behavioral understanding and needs to be unified itself before it can have a uni-
research, as well as a system that is multidis- fying role in psychology. Moreover, the study of
ciplinary in this regard, with the aim to con- causality in behavior can help us understand our
ceptualize better behavioral causality and the own place in the determination of our behavior—
consequences of its causes, including norma- at the apex of its influences, and hopefully as a
tively and psychopathologically. free being that seeks to be free in helpful actions
both for the self and others.

Chapter Conclusions
References
The present book is about the causality of behav-
American Psychiatric Association. (2013). Diagnostic
ior, for which free will is considered a cardinal
and statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM-5
factor. One major focus of the present work is the (5th ed.). Washington, DC: Author.
concept of “free being,” which I explain further Baumeister, R. F. (2008). Free will in scientific psychol-
in the next chapters. Other chapters in the book ogy. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 3, 14–19.
Baumeister, R. F. (2014). Constructing a scientific theory
deal more in depth on free will in behavior. The
of free will. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral
last chapter of the book includes a more integra- psychology: Free will and moral responsibility (Vol. 4,
tive model of the causal origins of free being. pp. 235–255). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
To conclude this introduction to the first chap- Blatt, S. J. (2008). Polarities of experience: Relatedness
and self-definition in personality development, psy-
ter of the present work, another guiding concept
chopathology, and the therapeutic process.
has been the biopsychosocial model, which I Washington: American Psychological Association.
have modified and labeled the biopersonalsocial Chaisson, E. J. (2001). Cosmic evolutions: The rise of
model. It reflects that the causes of behavior are complexity in nature. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
multiple and interactive in dynamic ways over
Chaisson, E. J. (2010). Energy rate density as a complexity
the whole behavioral system. Behavior can metric and evolutionary driver. Complexity, 16, 27–40.
become dysfunctional, disturbed, and so on, and Chaisson, E. J. (2011). Energy rate density. II. Probing
the biopsychosocial model constitutes a unifying further a new complexity metric. Complexity, 17,
44–63.
one for understanding normal and abnormal
Chemero, A. (2013). Radical embodied cognitive science.
behavior, as well as how to deal with the latter. Review of General Psychology, 17, 145–150.
Yet one model is insufficient to capture conceptu- Clark, A. (2013a). Whatever next? Predictive brains, situ-
ally the state of affairs in psychology at present. ated agents, and the future of cognitive science.
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36, 1–24.
Other integrative models that appear throughout
Clark, A. (2013b). Are we predictive engines? Perils,
the book include the ones of NLDST, networks, prospects, and the puzzle of the porous perceiver.
and embodiment, among others. Behavior and Brain Sciences, 36, 53–64.
There are many other theoretical and concep- Corrigan, P. W. (2014). The stigma of disease and disabil-
ity: Understanding causes and overcoming injustices.
tual sources to the present work that will become
Washington, DC: American Psychological
evident as it unfolds. However, I emphasize that Association.
the study of causality in psychology and related Frazier, J. (2012). The freedom of being: At ease with what
disciplines could help lead to a paradigm shift in is. Newburyport, MA: Weiser.
References 21

Friston, K. (2010). The free-energy principle: A unified & K. Ornstein (Eds.), Causality and psychopathology:
brain theory? Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 11, Finding the determinants of disorders and their cures
127–138. (pp. 3–24). New York: Oxford University Press.
Green, C. D. (2015). Why psychology isn’t unified, and Sloman, S. (2005). Causal models: How people think
probably never will be. Review of General Psychology, about the world and its alternatives. New York:
19, 207–214. Oxford University Press.
Han-Pile, B. (2013). Freedom and the “choice to choose Staats, A. W. (1983). Psychology’s crisis of disunity:
oneself” in being and time. In M. A. Wrathall (Ed.), Philosophy and method for a unified science. New
The Cambridge companion to Heidegger’s being and York: Praeger.
time (pp. 291–319). New York: Cambridge University Staats, A. W. (1991). Unified positivism and unification
Press. psychology: Fad or new field? American Psychologist,
Haynes, S. N. (1992). Models of causality in psychopa- 46, 899–912.
thology: Toward dynamic, synthetic and nonlinear Staats, A. W. (1993). Separattism and unification. In H. V.
models of behavior disorders. New York: Macmillan. Rappard, P. J. Van Strien, L. P. Mos, & W. J. Baker
Heidegger, M. (1927/1962). Being and time (J. Macquarrie (Eds.), Annals of theoretical psychology (Vol. 9, pp.
& E. Robinson, Trans.). Oxford, UK: Blackwell. 155–164). New York: Plenum.
(Original work published 1927) Staats, A. W. (1999). Unifying psychology requires new
Henriques, G. (2011). A new unified theory of psychology. infrastructure, theory, method, and a research agenda.
New York: Springer Science + Business Media. Review of General Psychology, 3, 3–13.
Henriques, G. (2013). Evolving from methodological to Sternberg, R. J., & Grigorenko, E. L. (2001). Unified psy-
conceptual unification. Review of General Psychology, chology. American Psychologist, 56, 1069–1079.
17, 168–173. Thelen, E., & Smith, L. B. (1994). A dynamic systems
Markus, K. A., & Borsboom, D. (2013). Frontiers of test approach to the development of cognition and action.
validity theory: Measurement, causation, and mean- Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
ing. New York: Routledge. Thelen, E., & Smith, L. B. (1998). Dynamic systems theo-
Marsh, T., & Boag, S. (2014). Unifying psychology: Shared ries. In W. Damon (Series Ed.) & R. M. Lerner (Vol.
ontology and the continuum of practical assumptions. Ed.), Handbook of child psychology (5th ed., Vol. 1,
Review of General Psychology, 18, 49–59. pp. 563–634). New York: Wiley.
Mikulincer, M., & Shaver, P. R. (2014). Mechanisms of Wilson, E. O. (1999). Consilience: The unity of knowl-
social connection: From brain to group. Washington, edge. New York: First Vintage Books.
DC: American Psychological Association. World Health Organization. (2017). International
Ouimette, P., & Brown, P. J. (2003). Trauma and sub- Classification of Disease, 11th Revision.
stance abuse: Causes, consequences, and treatment of Wrathall, M. A. (2013). The Cambridge companion to
comorbid disorders (1st ed.). Washington, DC: Heidegger’s being and time. New York: Cambridge
American Psychological Association. University Press.
Ouimette, P., & Read, J. P. (2013). Trauma and substance Young, G. (1997). Adult development, therapy, and cul-
abuse: Causes, consequences, and treatment of ture: A postmodern synthesis. New York: Plenum.
comorbid disorders (2nd ed.). Washington, DC: Young, G. (2008). Causality and causation in law, medi-
American Psychological Association. cine, psychiatry, and psychology: Progression or
Overton, W. F. (2015). Relational developmental systems regression? Psychological Injury and Law, 1,
and developmental science. In R. M. Lerner, W. F. 161–181.
Overton, & P. C. Molenaar (Eds.), Handbook of child Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
psychology and developmental science: Vol. 1. Theory Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science +
and method (7th ed., pp. 9–62). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley. Business Media.
Pearl, J. (2009). Causality: Models, reasoning, and infer- Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feigning, and response
ence (2nd ed.). New York: Cambridge University bias in psychiatric/psychological injury: Implications
Press. for practice and court. Dordrecht, Netherlands:
Petocz, A., & Mackay, N. (2013). Unifying psychology Springer Science + Business Media.
through situational realism. Review of General Young, G., Kane, A. W., & Nicholson, K. (Eds.). (2006).
Psychology, 17, 216–223. Psychological knowledge in court: PTSD, pain, and
Rodin, J., Schaie, K. W., & Schooler, C. (1990). Self- TBI. New York: Springer Science + Business Media.
directedness: Cause and effects throughout the life Young, G., Kane, A. W., & Nicholson, K. (Eds.). (2007).
course. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Causality of psychological injury: Presenting evidence
Shrout, P. E. (2011). Integrating causal analysis into psy- in court. New York: Springer Science + Business
chopathology research. In P. E. Shrout, K. M. Keyes, Media.
Overview of Book Parts
and Chapter by Chapter Overview 2

it, as well as making psychotherapeutic sugges-


Chapter Introduction tions. Also, it offers several new questionnaires,
including on the topic of free will.
This overview chapter of the book, its second,
includes description of each of its chapters. This
chapter informs the scope of the book and its Parts of the Book
basic concepts and conclusions. This is the first
integrative book on the causality of behavior in Introduction
the field of psychology, but it will be useful to
related disciplines, such as psychiatry. It focuses This book is based on a comprehensive literature
on influences on behavior not only in terms of review in multiple areas of causality in the disci-
Nature and Nurture but also for those related to pline of psychology, while touching some related
the self, such as those involving free will. disciplines that deal with behavioral causality. It
The book presents many innovations to help examines the classic influences on behavior of
integrate the study of causality in behavior. Aside Nature and Nurture, and their interaction, as well
from those related to free will and causality that I as the powerful forces in behavioral causality
have developed (e.g., the concept of Freedom in related to the self (e.g., free will); hence the
Being; humans as Homo Causa, respectively), oth- book’s title. The book is comprised of six parts,
ers that are central to the present enterprise include each with five to seven chapters.
ones related to my developmental Neo-Piagetian/
Neo-Eriksonian (sub)stage model and also a revi-
sion of Maslow’s classic hierarchical model based Parts
on this model. In addition, I have created a generic
change model based on the developmental one The first part of the book presents the core of con-
(Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian). Further, based ceptualization and research on the causality of
on these models, I have developed a Neo-Kuhnian behavior. It considers foundations and assump-
model of paradigmatic change in the sciences (and tions underlying the study of behavioral causal-
also in any scholarly activity). Finally, the present ity, and then it elaborates the biological portion in
work has practical applications related to presenta- psychological causality, especially with respect
tion and critique of the DSM-5 (Diagnostic and to genes, the brain, and evolution. It addresses
Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, Fifth the revolutions that are taking place in the study
Edition; American Psychiatric Association, 2013), of behavioral causation, including the work on
and it includes many recommendations to improve epigenesis and differential susceptibility.

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 23


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_2
24 2 Overview of Book Parts and Chapter by Chapter Overview

The second part of the book deals both with it provides a philosophical discussion not only on
development and free will. As well, it considers causality but also for psychology, in general. The
abnormal behavior/psychopathology and its integrative models that it considers include the
diagnosis in the DSM-5 (American Psychiatric biopsychosocial, embodiment, and network mod-
Association, 2013). This applied portion of the els. It seeks organizational principles across brain
book includes concrete applications, such as a and behavior, including in nonlinear dynamical
new free will questionnaire and recommenda- systems theory (NLDST) and the concept of acti-
tions for the DSM-5. vation/inhibition coordination.
The third part of the book presents my per- The study of causality of behavior exists in
sonal contributions to the study of and conceptu- dynamic tension between more statistical, meth-
alization of behavioral causality. First, I present odological, empirical approaches and more theo-
models related to the causes of psychological retical, modeling, philosophical ones. For
injury, and then new models and terms related to example, at the statistical level, experimentation
stimulus–response relations, and their relations to is considered crucial in causal determination, and
the organism, networks, and the brain (the “neu- randomized control trials, in particular, are con-
rome”). The last part of the book concludes with sidered the sine qua non in establishing causality
description and extension of my Neo-Piagetian/ in the clinical domain. However, psychology and
Neo-Eriksonian lifespan developmental model psychiatry often are limited ethically in the abil-
(Young, 2011; and extended in Young, 2014) and ity to conduct experiments, and have to resort to
its applications and extensions for understanding quasi-experiments, longitudinal designs using
behavioral causality. This includes a generic statistical controls, and advanced statistical pro-
change model, a revised model of Maslow’s hier- cedures. The last chapter in this part reviews sta-
archy of needs, and a revised model of Kuhn’s tistical approaches to causality. It includes
paradigmatic approach to scientific change. network and graphing approaches, which are
becoming increasingly important.

Conclusion
Part II: Biology and Revolutions
The present book is comprehensive and massive,
but only an approach such as this can do justice to The basic models presented in the first part of the
the topic of the causality of behavior. It will test book continue to appear in the later parts, and
your patience but improve your knowledge as they are interweaved as the book unfolds. For
you work through it. It might inspire you to adopt example, in the second part of the book, I present
its major goals—of trying to unify psychology, the biological bases of behavior, in particular.
unify the study of causality, and include free will I start with two chapters on the brain, and both
as central to both endeavors, while considering reflect the increasing influence of the network
my models as contributory in these regards. approach to conceptualizing behavior. The next
three chapters are on genetics and the genetic
revolution. Genes no longer are considered only
Part I: Core Causality in Behavior: for their direct effects on behavior; rather, their
Foundations and Models intricate interaction with the environment pre-
dominates in understanding their influence on
The first part of the book deals with the causality behavior. The study of the interaction of genes
of behavior from the smallest of genes and their and environment (G × E) includes the burgeoning
molecular constituents to the largest complex area of epigenetics, as well as the areas of cul-
systems in which behavior resides. The first part tural neuroscience and social genomics. These
of this book serves as an introduction to the areas further stamp the study of the genetic influ-
basics in causality modeling, in particular. Also, ence on behavior as complex and intimately
Part III: Normal and Abnormal Development and Free Will: Normal Development and Free Will 25

entwined with the environment. At the same (e.g., brain network concepts), so are there envi-
time, the ability of genes to affect the environ- ronmental revolutions.
ment is indicated in the phenomenon of corre- As the same time, in keeping in mind the major
lated G × E interactions. The phenomenon of the focus of the present book on Freedom in Being,
interaction of G by E presents a challenge not another revolution in behavioral understanding
only to understanding genetic effects on behavior seems evident. From the point of view of the bio-
but also environmental ones. The last chapter of psychosocial model that I espouse as a crux in
this part of the book deals with evolution. understanding the causality of behavior, there are
Darwinian influences on behavior have expanded not only biological (genetic) and environmental
to include concepts relating genes and culture. revolutions in behavioral study, there are also rev-
olutions in understanding the person’s contribu-
tion to his/her own development and behavior.
Part III: Normal and Abnormal People have different personalities, coping skills/
Development and Free Will: resiliencies, directions in self-development, and
Normal Development other factors that contribute to how their develop-
and Free Will ment unfolds and how their behavior is expressed
in their contexts. In this regard, believing in and
This third part of the book shifts to the topics of having a sense of free will is especially important
developmental and social psychology. For devel- in freeing the person from being passive before the
opment, I focus on the early years, in particular, biological and environmental influences on her or
to determine to what extent behavior seems core him. Living in freedom of being can help the per-
and “prepared,” e.g., in empathy and prosocial son to construct actively at least to some degree
behavior. For social psychology, I focus on the aspects of her or his development and behavior so
study of free will in behavior. The part begins that it is more probabilistic and emergent instead
with a chapter on the evolution of behavior from of being fully deterministic and reductionist. Keep
a developmental perspective, and the fascinating in mind that themes like this about behavior being
model of differential susceptibility to the envi- the product or output of more than the combined
ronment. This model integrates evolution, genet- effects of Nature and Nurture, given the additional
ics, development, life history, resilience, influences of personal or self factors in this regard,
vulnerability, social buffering, and positive as have powerful antecedent historical antecedents,
well as negative outcomes, such as antisocial such as found in humanism’s third force and
behavior. It is a lifespan perspective. The next Piaget’s tertium (third) quid.
chapter continues with a lifespan approach to The third part of the book shifts from chapters
development and its positive as well as negative on development to presentation of ones on con-
outcomes, by considering the effects of early cepts and empirical research related to free will.
adversity, fetal programming, and the enduring These include the belief in free will and its conse-
effects model, among others. quences, and it should be noted that this belief in
The environment no longer can be considered free will is quite widespread and quite conse-
according to the classic model, or as an indepen- quential. The last chapter in this part of the book
dent entity that impacts people who, in turn, are considers the related topic of “ego” or resource
considered to stand as separate from the environ- depletion and its effects on self-control. After
ment. Rather, in contemporary thought, the envi- reviewing the literature on the topic, the chapter
ronment “gets under the skin” not only in presents an integrated biopsychosocial model of
phenomena such as epigenetics and cultural depletion effects, specifically (and of self-control,
genomics but also in its early effects in differen- generally). This chapter concludes with a new
tial susceptibility and from early adversity. In this questionnaire on free will, after cogent analysis
sense, just as there are genetic and, generally, of extant ones. Also, I describe another question-
biological revolutions in the study of behavior naire on depletion.
26 2 Overview of Book Parts and Chapter by Chapter Overview

Part IV: Abnormalities I present an integrated top-down/bottom-up


in Development and the DSM-5 model of how mental disorder and symptoms
causally relate to each other.
The fourth part of the present work considers
applied aspects related to the causality of behav-
ior. For the causality of abnormal behavior or dis- Part V: Personal Contributions
order, often one refers to etiology rather than to the Study of Causality
causality, in general. in Behavior: New Models
The first chapter of this part shows how free
will can be used in psychotherapy, which might The biopsychosocial model can help explain
be especially useful for addictions. Next, the part much of the nature of causality of the psychologi-
considers the origins of posttraumatic stress dis- cal injuries. However, PTSD, chronic pain, and
order (PTSD), especially in terms of endopheno- mild TBI are all contentious diagnoses and are
types, or the pathway from genes to disease. difficult to discern in assessment because of the
The remaining four chapters of this part deal potential for evaluees to express secondary gain,
with the DSM-5 (American Psychiatric exaggeration, and even malingering. Therefore,
Association, 2013). This diagnostic manual of in this area, an astute forensic perspective helps in
mental disorders is a compendium developed by arriving at equitable determinations. However,
workgroups, and its major goal is to be clinically the person is not the only source possible bias,
useful, while considering current research. given the negative effects of the insurance/legal
However, as does medicine more generally, it has process (and even medical process, referred to as
difficulty attaining its stated goal of finding spe- iatrogenesis). Because of these complicating fac-
cific etiological causes leading to each specific tors, establishing, the etiology of psychological
disorder, and then finding specific treatments to injuries and indeed, the whole assessment process
help or to cure them. The first chapter of the four of these disorders, needs careful evaluation. I note
in the series describes the changes in the that the best manner of achieving these goals is to
DSM-5 in relation to the DSM-IV-TR (Diagnostic assess complainants from a comprehensive,
and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, impartial, and scientific perspective from the
Fourth Edition, Text Revised; American point of referral, and throughout the assessment,
Psychiatric Association, 2000) and the views of right to offering conclusions in reports or in testi-
the critics of the DSM-5. The second and third mony to court. In the next chapters in this part, I
chapters in this four-part series on the DSM-5 leave the topic of psychological injury and refer
concentrate on the basic psychological injuries to a host of new models related to causality in
(PTSD, chronic pain, mild traumatic brain injury psychology, in general. First, I consider options to
(TBI)), given that psychological injuries are the the classic model of stimuli (S) leading to response
primary focus of my clinical work. I review how (R), in which these components are considered as
they are treated in the DSM-5 and review criti- separate entities. Rather, the organism/processor
cisms in this regard, leading to recommendations needs to be considered in the S-R relationship
on how to improve their diagnostic criteria. The and, in so doing, it becomes evident that they are
last mentioned chapter on the DSM also consid- not separable, distinct components in behavioral
ers the Research Domain of Criteria (RDoC) causality. In this regard, to conclude the part, I
project, which seeks a more biologically (neuro- expand upon an integrated cross-network model
scientifically) informed understanding of psycho- of behavior and also present many other novel
pathology. For both the DSM-5 and the RDoC, terms and concepts, such as that of the neurome.
I recommend a more biopsychosocial approach. Another new terminology that I created on cau-
This last chapter of the four on the DSM-5 in this sality is “Coexistential Causal Intraactionism.”
part also considers recommendations for the Finally, the part examines change mechanisms,
DSM, in general, including with respect to cau- for example, related to activation/inhibition coor-
sality and etiology. In particular for the latter, dination and readiness for change.
Part VI: The Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian Model 27

Part VI: The Neo-Piagetian/ countering passive deterministic impacts of biol-


Neo-Eriksonian Model ogy and environment and (b) maintaining that
the integrative model being espoused is not
The last part of the present book elaborates my Cartesian, dualistic, and separative of mind and
Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian (sub)stage model body. That is, in a behavioral system such as the
of 25 steps in lifespan development, as well as its one being described, emergent properties are still
applications and implications. The first chapter contained within and reflect the system, are part
focuses on its socioemotional component, in par- of it, and do not stand out of it. They are hierar-
ticular, as described in Young (2011). The next chically arranged within it, perhaps at a superor-
one examines its cognitive extensions, especially dinate level, and can act top-down on these
as presented in Young (2014). The third chapter levels, but are still constitutively derived ele-
presents a generic change model of five steps ments of the system and its component interac-
based on the model. I show how it can be applied tions, aside from being subject themselves to
to multiple phenomena, including in normal and lower-order influences in the system. The mind
abnormal behavior. does not stand as distinct from the body even if it
The last three chapters of the book present is more than the body. The unity of both might be
more innovations for the study and conceptual- captured by concepts such as embodiment, in
ization of behavioral causality. First, it presents a which higher-order, more abstract psychological
Neo-Maslovian model based on my Neo- (mental) structures still maintain integral compo-
Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian one. It is a revision of nents, linkages, and dynamics involving more
the one presented in Young (2011). The second grounded, sensorimotor and related structures
last chapter of the book also is based on my 2011 and, indeed, reflect and are empowered by them.
model, and it presents a revised Kuhnian model Also, there is no contradiction (a) in referring
of paradigms in scientific change. In this regard, to free will as part of the apex of self forces that
it considers Overton’s (2013, 2014) examination behave actively in generating free choice, deci-
of the Kuhnian model in terms relationism, and sions, and actions and (b) in maintaining that free
shows how my Neo-Kuhnian model is consistent will as being described for present purposes (free
with that view. Also, the latter model that I cre- being, as per the book title), might not be an active
ated would appear to be applicable to any area of component much of the time in the life of the per-
scholarship, not just scientific ones. Finally, the son. First in this regard, many unconscious pro-
book concludes with a chapter on new directions cesses are involved in behavioral production and,
for the study of behavioral causality. Most of the second, even if it is active in conscious ways at
models presented in this concluding chapter elab- times, free will aspects might not be predominant,
orate the present overall perspective, for exam- the arbiter of final choices, decisions, and actions,
ple, in its consideration of free will, which is and so on. That being said, free will has the poten-
central focus of the present work. tial to be the ultimate contributor to behavioral
guidance at any one moment. Moreover, in terms
of setting long-term life goals, moral values, and
Conclusion so on, it could be the supreme guide, setting the
agenda even if not involved directly in building
The factual description of the parts of the present behavior in any or every moment.
book that has just been presented belies the com- Finally, there is no contradiction (a) in refer-
plexity in the study of psychology as well as ring to free will (and its aspects) as an emergent,
some of its raging debates, controversies, and higher-order phenomenon and (b) in considering
issues. In this regard, note that there is no contra- that it is grounded, participatory, developmental,
diction (a) in espousing a view of behavioral and related to lower-order phenomena. That is,
causality that includes emergence and aspects of free will is embodied in and constituted by ele-
free will as part of a self-agent acting in its own ments of lower-order phenomena, in a systems
best interest in an active way and, in doing so, perspective. In this sense, free will in psychology
28 2 Overview of Book Parts and Chapter by Chapter Overview

should be considered as “embodied free will” and, each one that are altering the field. The reader
similarly in this regard, the apex in psychological should refer to the chapter introductions and
growth “free being,” should be considered an summaries for a comprehensive description of
embodied product of an embodied process, or as their contents.
“embodied free being.” Further, the hypothesized
major constituents of free being—free will belief
and having a sense of free will—should be consid- Part I: Core Causality in Behavior:
ered “embodied free will belief” and the “embod- Foundations and Models
ied sense of having free will,” respectively.
The present line of thought leads to a complex Chapter 1: Brief Book Description and Book
understanding of emergence as an embodied pro- Assumptions Psychology is a field growing
cess producing an embodied product. Emergence rapidly, and also it is developing links to many
in a system does not lead to higher-order, super- other areas of study, such as psychiatry, genetics,
ordinate, top-down levels distinct from, divorced neuroscience, evolutionary modeling, law, and
from, or separate from lower levels of the system philosophy. Therefore, it is difficult to perceive it
involved, but ones intimately related to them, as in its entirety, or grasp fundamental unifying con-
are all levels of any system in their hierarchical ceptions that could tie it together and give it a
and integrative relationship. In this sense, any coherent, practical sense. Each subarea in psy-
emergent phenomena or level in a system is chology believes that it has developed a central
always embodied or linked to any lower-order axis that could help integrate psychology into a
level(s) and reflective of them. Therefore, it cohesive field. Moreover, as soon as a new focus
might be best to refer to any emergence as develops in a subarea, new ones materialize and
“embodied emergence” and any of its related spread rapidly even beyond the subarea involved.
products as embodied, as well, as should be the As I approached the task of promoting causal-
process producing them (i.e., embodied X and its ity as central to psychology and a possible unify-
embodied or embodying process, respectively). ing axis for it, I realized the vast nature of the
Human free will is part of our causality engine. task. Only a book as elaborate as the present one
Free will is part of our personal contributions to can give the topic justice. In this regard, this first
our behavioral causality and stands at the apex in chapter of the book begins the process of champi-
this regard. I chose the title for the book as “The oning causality as a cardinal, unifying concept
Unifying Psychology and Causality Project: for psychology. It indicates the book’s multidisci-
Freedom in Being, Brain, Self, and Behavior” plinary nature and its underlying assumptions.
because of my emphasis on the psychology of Also, I present 30 assumptions that are funda-
free will in psychological causation. I look for- mental toward integrating causality as a unifying
ward to further work on the study of causation of concept in psychology and also I emphasize the
behavior; on free will as an essential focus in this need to explain better the multifactorial nature of
regard; and perhaps with my own modeling serv- causality in psychology. Some of the models that
ing as relevant axes in this pursuit. help toward this end include the biopsychosocial
model, NLDST, and the model of embodiment.
As well, the assumptions that underlie the present
Chapter Descriptions book underscore the importance of evolutionary
processes, genetics, brain networks, develop-
In the following, I provide brief chapter descrip- ment, and free will in the causation of behavior
tions with the goal of showing exciting develop- (and they mention my own work on stage/step
ments in the field of psychology pertaining to models in development).
causality. Rather than describing in depth each
chapter for its specific contents, I take a step back Chapter 2: Part Overview and Chapter by
and indicate the novel findings and modeling in Chapter Overview The present chapter provides
Part I: Core Causality in Behavior: Foundations and Models 29

an overview of the parts and chapters of the book. susceptibility. The chapter also presents other
It does not go into depth in describing the chap- critical models that help in understanding better
ters; rather, it focuses on the critical concepts, the causality of behavior. These include NLDST,
innovations, and modeling that informed and that a stage or step approach to both evolution and
emerged from the present book. development, and the concept of activation/inhi-
I wrote this present chapter to serve as a gen- bition coordination.
eral accessible introduction that shows both the The next part of the chapter gives new mate-
vigor of the field and my excitement and integra- rial about the three major axes in the study of
tive efforts in dealing with it. Above all, this behavioral causality. (a) Specifically, for the topic
chapter emphasizes the book’s critical content of free will, it presents more material on free
and major concepts and models, including of the being, which concerns: having a belief in free
centrality of causality in psychology and also the will and also having a sense of free will. (b) As
centrality of ourselves as active, emergent agents for mechanism, I especially present work on
in determining our own psychology (and the role energy dynamics as sources of causality through-
of our “free will” in this regard). Also, in writing out the universe and its evolution over time.
this chapter description, I created new terms rel- Inevitably, this concept applies to psychology, as
evant to the major themes of the book, for exam- well, for example, in NLDST. (c) Finally, I give
ple, embodied free being, as well as embodied new material on explaining causal graph/network
free will belief and an embodied sense of having modeling. This relates to the work of Sloman
free will. Also, at a different point in the chapter, (2005), which I use to help structure a better
I refer to the concept of “causality engine” in understanding of behavioral causality.
behavior, for example, of which our free will
beliefs are prime drivers. We are indeed Homo Chapter 4: Causality in Philosophy;
Causa. Philosophy in Psychology This chapter of the
book on philosophy deals with philosophy, in
Chapter 3: Causality in Psychology This general, as it relates to psychology, and also it
chapter of the present book further elaborates the deals more specifically with key topics in philos-
triadic axis model of causality in the study in psy- ophy in relation to causality and to free will.
chology, as presented in Young (2011). Although, Some of the positions broached include the dis-
it describes the scope of the study of causality tinctions between reductionism and constructiv-
across multiple disciplines, it still considers the ism, causalism and acausalism, and determinism
primary axes in this regard as being free will, and compatibilism (also libertarian and semi-
mechanism, and causal graph modeling. In this compatibilist views). Some of the particular,
chapter, I elaborate further on these three axes in intermediate, or integrative positions considered
the study of causality in psychology. include eliminative reductionism, elemental con-
This chapter is especially based on the details structivism, criterial causation, and probabilistic
of my approach to causality as described in determinism. The opposition between positivism
Young (2011). I have taken the kernel arguments and relationism is treated toward the end of the
related to causality in that book and summarized chapter. The smorgasbord of philosophical view-
them. Of note, I introduce the following concepts points continues with discussion of ones for
related to causality as central to psychology: the reductionism (moderate, constitutive, neo), con-
causal landscape and causal streams; hot vs. cold structivism (emergent, situated, neo), dualism
causality; and dimensions in causality study. (property), positivism (neo), determinism (hard,
Also in Young (2011), as summarized in this soft), compatibilism (semi), and dispositional-
third chapter of the present book, I was develop- ism. The chapter explores brain-based research
ing models to help in the study of behavioral cau- related to free will, including intrinsic networks.
sality, such as one integrating the concepts of It presents a model termed “apparent” mental
reaction range with the model of differential causation.
30 2 Overview of Book Parts and Chapter by Chapter Overview

As for my contributions to the study of phi- redescription of behavioral phenomena rather


losophy in relation to psychology, I have formu- than a model with sufficient explanatory transfor-
lated the integrative concepts of neoreductio mative acumen. Certainly, this present work is
constructivism, co-existentialism, dialectical dedicated to integrating these various integrative
semi-compatibilism, quantum neoepistemology, models in psychology and providing them with a
and Neo-Kuhnianism. In addition, for the devel- reliable and valid suite of change mechanisms
opment of emergent psychological maturity, that can help explain stability/instability and
which might permit free will to manifest psycho- gradual/abrupt changes in behavior.
logically, as mentioned, at many points in the As for key terms in this chapter, there are a
present book I describe the concept of Free few for the biopsychosocial approach, given its
Being. For me, mental causation is as real as bio- prevalence throughout the present book. I refer to
logical and social causation. the psychological component of this model as the
“personal” one because all three components are
Chapter 5: Models and Systems of Causality involved in the psychology or behavior and it
of Behavior This chapter reviews three major makes no sense to consider one of the compo-
models in psychology relevant to the present nents of the term as especially psychological
work—the biopsychosocial model, complexity/ when, in essence, all three are psychological in
NLDST, and embodiment. In Young (2011), nature. It is important to note that the three com-
I reviewed in depth the first two of these models. ponents involved in the model are not as distinct
All three models are considered wide-ranging, as their separate presentation might indicate.
integrative ones. Some examples of the biological, psychologi-
However, each of the models includes limita- cal (personal), and social components of the
tions—for example, each possesses properties model included in the present book follow. These
that make it difficult to apply clearly to the examples are taken from throughout the book and
domains that have been considered under its not uniquely from Chap. 5 that is being summa-
scope. rized here.
In this regard, the biopsychosocial model suf- For the biological component of the biopsy-
fers from a lack of precise mechanisms in how its chosocial model, among others, the present work
major components might interact to produce a examines the influence on behavior of
behavior at issue (e.g., illness, psychopathology) genes/epigenetics; Gene × Environment (G × E)
or how the treatments under its guise might work. interactions and correlated G × E (rGE); the brain
Also, the NLDST approach provides a generic and brain networks (the Connectome, structural
approach to describing system states and their and functional); lateralization and hemispheric
change, as well as the processes that might bring specialization; evolution, life history theory, and
about the change, but it has not made the differential susceptibility; as well as the stress
widespread inroads in psychology predicted for response and its major physiological systems
it. Part of the reason might lie in the different (hypothalamic pituitary adrenal (HPA) axis;
approaches that are espoused under its umbrella sympathetic adrenal medullary (SAM) system),
(as well as its complex mathematics and its dif- and critical molecular biochemicals and neu-
ferent approach to variability in behavior, which rotransmitter components (cortisol, norepineph-
is considered “noise” in many of the standard rine, glucocorticoid receptors) and their action on
approaches in psychology but the primary sub- neurons and the brain.
ject matter in this approach to psychology). For the psychological (personal) component
Finally, the embodied approach is only begin- of the biopsychosocial model, among others, the
ning to prosper as a potentially unifying one in book examines aspects of the self; self-control/
psychology, and it too needs to work on specific regulation (cognitive, emotional); executive
mechanisms than entrain development and function; relevant cognitive acquisitions, includ-
change, or else it will be considered simply as a ing belief; resilience and coping; personality and
Part I: Core Causality in Behavior: Foundations and Models 31

temperament; motivation and attention; and free Chapter 6: Statistical Concepts and Networks
will and resource (ego) depletion. in Causality The present chapter focuses on
For the social component of the biopsychoso- more statistical approaches to causality, includ-
cial model, among others, the book explores cul- ing network approaches. It examines test validity
tural and societal influences; socioeconomic models (reflective, formative, mutualistic) and
status (SES), minority status, and other demo- causal models in testing (regularity, counterfac-
graphics; prenatal influences, early adversity, tual, process). Test validity involves two major
early life experiences; parenting, parenting style, approaches—behavior domain theory and causal
and schooling; maltreatment, abuse; buffering theory of measurement.
the environment, etc. Statistical approaches to causality are impor-
Clearly, free will is a major anchor of the pres- tant, but classic experimental approaches to cau-
ent book. Another component to the personal sality need to be supplemented by other means
agency in behavioral causation that I introduce in when the classic approaches cannot be applied,
this chapter concerns passion. I review the defini- for example, due to ethical considerations in set-
tion of passion and also the questionnaire cur- ting up certain experimental manipulations. The
rently in use in evaluating it and, in both regards, classical causal model involving experimentation
develop better ones. gives validity (and generalizability) cardinal
As for the complexity and NLDST, they espe- importance, and these are difficult to target in
cially refer, in particular, respectively, (a) to com- nonexperimental designs but, through their statis-
plex adaptive systems, networks, and agents, and tical innovations, they are narrowing their limits
(b) to attractors, self-organization, emergence, in these regards. The supplementary statistical
fractals, and circular causality. They also refer to approaches in the study of behavioral causality
collective autocatalytic sets and to complexity include the potential outcomes model and the
pyramids, as well as to control and order param- directed acyclic graphs (DAGs) model. The for-
eters, respectively. mer includes a basis in hypothetical outcomes
The key terms and concepts in the embodi- that cannot be ascertained directly, involving the
ment model of behavior are proliferating. The SUTVA (stable unit treatment value assumption),
embodiment model has been differentiated into and the latter includes the equivalent of experi-
strong, secondary, hybrid, and radical versions. A mental manipulations in its graph surgery/“do”
similar model is that of radical enactivism. It has operators (interventions), causal descendants,
been applied to cognition, affect, the brain (e.g., and counterfactuals. A variation of this latter
the mirror system), and even the extended mind, approach is the ICA (integrated counterfactual
inter-brain, embodied attunement, and conjoined approach). Some of the new approaches to statis-
people (through joint attractors). It incorporates tical mediation analysis include: average causal
extended concepts of behavior, such as mediation effect; left-out variables error method;
body-becoming-mind and the brain-body-envi- latent growth curve modeling; state space model-
ronment landscape, yet also quite basic ones, ing; and the ignorability-based approach.
such as chemosignals in intersubjectivity and Some of the philosophical precursors to statisti-
force dynamics in language and sociality. Some cal and related causality not only concern interven-
of its concepts are rarified, such as having a tionist/counterfactual accounts but also concepts
hypergrip on affordances and also hermeneutic such as NESS and INUS. The former is defined as
realism. As for my contributions to the area of necessary element for the sufficiency of a suffi-
embodiment, I develop the concepts of embodied cient set and the latter as insufficient but necessary
causation or etiology and of causal or etiological components of unnecessary but sufficient causes.
embodiment. Also, I refer to the human species These are complex concepts that inform but to not
as Homo Causa in this chapter and to the causal- direct statistical approaches to causality in psy-
ization process as inimical to who we are and chology. Aristotle’s concept of four causes still has
how we become. currency today (material, efficient, formal, final),
32 2 Overview of Book Parts and Chapter by Chapter Overview

with efficient causes considered as the equivalent pathoconnectomics. Brain connectivities might
of mechanisms. be structural, functional, or effective. Connections
Baye’s theorem is an emerging approach in are established by connection matrices, which
the statistical approach to causality. It is subjec- include graphs, nodes, edges, hubs, cores, and
tive rather than classically frequentist. It deals paths. The connectivities might evidence rich
with concepts such as priors, precision, likeli- clubs or small worlds. The measures include ones
hood, posteriors, and credibility instead of confi- of centrality and betweenness.
dence intervals, and it stands in opposition to the The field has determined up to 14 brain net-
classic approach to testing null vs. experimental works, but three generally are considered pri-
hypotheses. mary—the salience network, the central executive
Other portions of the chapter deal with network, and the default mode network. Another
FACCDs (Functional Analytic Clinical Case one referred to in the chapter is the frontoparietal
Diagram), ecology, Granger Causality (GC), and network.
networks. The latter is explored in much more A major theory cutting across networks
detail in subsequent chapters on the brain, in par- involves a Bayesian model of the brain acting to
ticular. Among the notable aspects of networks reduce its free energy or surprise by minimizing
discussed in the present chapter include measures prediction errors and otherwise functioning ther-
of centrality and betweenness. modynamically (Friston, 2010). This work is
The chapter also covers epidemiology, with its important enough to have been emphasized in the
emphasis on temporality (e.g., predisposing, pre- title of the book, when I refer to freeing the brain.
cipitating, perpetuating factors), and causal webs Other concepts in this model include the ones of
or pies. The chapter includes new models of sta- local and global dynamics, inference machines,
tistics and causality, such as the decision theo- meta-stability/quasi-stability, and hidden causes
retic approach, minimal causal models, dynamic and econiches.
causal modeling, and convergent cross-mapping. The chapter refers to other causality-related
The chapter includes a section on PTSD terms, such as causal flow. One article discusses
because McNally et al. (2015) related it to the network organization in terms of “cacti.” The
concept of networks. For this area of research, work on networks incorporates the perspective on
the authors contrasted network modeling with the NLDST, and the chapter is replete with terminol-
approach of latent variable/constructs. Some of ogy from this model and related ones. For exam-
the network concepts applied to the data include: ple, it refers to “criticality,” which is the region in
networks of association, concentration, and state space of a system that facilitates state
relative importance. The key measures used also change, including to “chaotic” regimes. Also, the
related to centrality and betweenness. chapter refers to state space “viscosity,” a concept
not traditionally encountered in NLDST.
The chapter examines systems at the micro
Part II: Biology and Revolutions level, that is, neuronal networks and even the net-
worked nature of concept cells and of astrocytes.
Chapter 7: Brain: The Neuronal Network Finally, wherever one looks in research and con-
Revolution This chapter deals with a central ceptualization about the brain, one finds evidence
concept in causality in psychology and related supporting the present model of activation/inhi-
disciplines—that of networks, and especially as bition coordination as being a common metric
the concept is applied to the brain. On the one within each of and across brain and behavior, and
hand, it deals with the Connectome, in general, as in this chapter I point out areas where this con-
applied to brain networks and, on the other hand, cept applies.
it describes intrinsic or core brain networks. The As for the application of network models to
concept of the Connectome is part of the burgeon- more behavioral phenomena, the chapter
ing field of connectomics, which also involves describes a network causal system model that
Part II: Biology and Revolutions 33

treats items or symptoms of mental disorder. It is specialization, and behavioral lateralities, and their
contrasted to the latent variable/construct model. relationship to handedness, language develop-
Causality inheres in linkages across symptoms ment, cognitive achievement, and so on, it consid-
themselves rather than to underlying constructs ers each age period separately from preconception
relating them or central constructs that they into childhood, in particular. For each age period
address. under review, first, results of research related to
manual lateralities are presented. Then, for each
Chapter 8: Lateralization and Specialization age period, other results related to the brain are
of the Brain The second chapter in the present presented. Finally, aside from considering the
book on the brain is on cerebral hemispheric spe- developmental origins of specialization/lateraliza-
cialization and the associated topic of behavioral tion, the chapter considers evolutionary ones.
lateralization. As with other areas of brain study,
the concept of networks is making inroads in this Chapter 9: The Genetics Revolution The
area. The findings in this regard reinforce the left- study of causality of behavior is marked by fields
hemisphere as differentially specialized for its undergoing rapid expansion, including the one of
skills relative to the right. Although each hemi- genetics. The genetic revolution has witnessed
sphere has its specializations, the left hemisphere the classic model of genotype ⟶ transcrip-
has been called dominant and, in this regard, the tion ⟶ protein ⟶ phenotype evolve to become
network approach is touting its efficiency and a supercomplex one of multiple “-omics”
also its more centrally organized characteristics. (genomics, epigenomics, etc.). The research on
Moreover, the findings show that even neonates candidate genes that aims to find simple gene–
possess this type of left hemisphere specializa- behavior associations has been supplemented by
tion. These findings on the differential network- genome-wide association studies and genome-
ing in the hemispheres are consistent with the wide complex trait analysis (GWAS, GCTA,
present model that the left hemisphere possesses respectively). The classic search for the heritabil-
better activation/inhibition coordination skills ity in behavioral variation explanation has
compared to the right hemisphere, which has been supplemented for a search of “missing”
other inhibitory skills. heritability. Instead of straightforward genetic
Aspects of manual behavior reflect the differ- main effects, researchers also look for
ential skills of the left and right hemispheres, Gene × Environment interaction. These include
and so reflect a manual specialization that MAOA × Maltreatment interaction in antisocial
reflects its underlying hemispheric specializa- behavior outcome.
tion. Handedness is not as clearly related to Aside from considering G × E influences on
hemispheric specialization as are other manual behavior, one needs to consider multiple genes
behaviors. Most often, language abilities are interacting with E and also multiple environmen-
associated with the left hemisphere, which is why tal factors in interaction beyond their interaction
it is called the dominant hemisphere, but each with G (G × G × E and G × E × E, respectively), as
hemisphere has its skill set (e.g., certain spatial well as all these types of interactions with D
skills in the right hemisphere) and, moreover, the (development). Also, there are correlated G × E
advantages that each hemisphere possesses are findings (rGE), which lie more on the genetic
relative rather than absolute ones. Research is than the environmental side of behavioral causal
showing that the left hemisphere is associated influence (e.g., phenotypes underlain by certain
with certain cognitive skills, as well. The hemi- genotypes lead to behaviors that influence the
spheres work in concert in adaptation to context, environment, rather than vice versa). In addition,
problem-solving, and so on. Interhemispheric research is demonstrating epigenetic effects
communication is important in this regard. (gene silencing) on genes, which lies more
As for how the chapter is organized as it reviews on the environmental side relative to the
the research on hemispheric specialization, manual genetic side of behavioral causal influence.
34 2 Overview of Book Parts and Chapter by Chapter Overview

These examples illustrate that even in the area findings are complex, including differential
of genetics of behavior the dividing line effects according to age, gene, environment, and
between genes and environment are fuzzy and outcome. Moreover, the qualifications G × G × E,
interactive. G × E × E, and G × E × D interactions reveal the
There are numerous key genetic terms in the complexities in behavioral genetics research.
chapter, given its genetic focus. They include The chapter examines other genetic processes,
CNVs (copy number variations), VNTRs (vari- such as epigenetics, differential susceptibility,
able number of random repeats), and LPR (length and NLDST.
polymorphism in MAOA promoter region). Some of the most striking findings in the
Among the genetic polymorphisms in the chapter, chapter relate to the longitudinal associations
one will find 5-HTTLPR (serotonin transporter found. Clearly, just as the environment early in
polymorphism), COMT (catechol-O-methyltrans- life is now considered as having an enduring
ferase), DRD4 (dopamine receptor D4), and impact so, too, should the effects of genes; they
MAOA (monoamine oxidase A). are not overwhelmed in their causal impact on
The chapter considers broader phenomena behavior by environmental impacts. Once more,
related to genes, such as biointelligence, evolv- the interaction of genes and environment in
ability, versatility, and polygenetic scores. As for behavioral causality stands out according to the
my contributions to the field, I suggest investiga- empirical research.
tion of the “phenome” to better understand the
disparate and sometimes conflicting or nonrepli- Chapter 11: Genes and Environment: The
cated results on the genome (not to mention my Person Revolution Whereas the introductions
concept of the “loveome”). to the two prior chapters on genetics and behav-
ior have addressed the fast-pace changes in the
Chapter 10: Gene × Environment Interaction: field, the present chapter accelerates in this pro-
The Environmental Revolution The phenom- gression. It considers in detail epigenetics, cor-
enon of Genetic × Environmental (G × E) interac- related Gene × Environment (rGE) interactions,
tion illustrates not only the genetic revolution but and cultural neuroscience. Moreover, in doing so,
also the environmental one. Neither genes nor it illustrates further the difficulty in separating
environment is considered as separate and addi- genes, environments, and the person as distinct
tive causal factors in development. Rather, now entities. Finally, it includes other models perti-
they are each considered multifactorial, as is their nent to the present work, such as differential sus-
interaction. The current chapter especially pres- ceptibility. The genes, environment, and person
ents a detailed literature review of the effects of form a complex causal behavioral system, which
G × E on behavior. Some of the polymorphisms includes developmental, learning, evolutionary,
involved include those related to MAOA, and contextual factors. Moreover, the interplay
5-HTTLPR, OXTR (oxytocin receptor), CRHR1 among these diverse factors in behavioral causal-
(corticotropin releasing hormone receptor 1), ity is so intricate that only the refined types of
BDNF (brain-derived neurotrophic factor), NET conceptualization and empirical study as
(norepinephrine transporter; SLC6A2; solute car- described in the chapter can elucidate the com-
rier family 6 member 2), and DAT1 (dopamine plexity involved.
active transporter gene). The outcomes include In epigenesis, among other processes, DNA
antisocial behavior, anger, depression, ADHD methylation helps silence genes in their promoter
(attention deficit hyperactivity disorder), educa- regions. Moreover, the effects can be transmitted
tional attainment, etc. Generally, the psycho- over generations through epigenetic marks. The
pathological effects can be qualified as chapter refers to the “methylome” in this regard.
internalizing and externalizing. The environ- [There are other epigenetic processes related to
ments involved include child abuse, early adver- histones and micro-RNA, in particular].
sity, and multiple aspects of parenting. The Epigenetic effects could take place prenatally,
Part III: Normal and Abnormal Development and Free Will: Normal Development and Free Will 35

such as through maternal distress. They could A more integrated process of evolution with
influence development through their genetically- other models would consider the influence of
modified alterations in critical neurogenetic niche, culture, development, and person. As
processes, including in brain regions and emphasized in the approach of niche construc-
related functions, such as in the stress-mediating tion, organisms are active, casual agents in their
HPA axis. own evolution.
Overall, it is argued that the best metaphorical Life history theory indicates that evolution
formula to describe the causes of behavior is not constructs each developmental period as adap-
Nature or Nurture or Nature and Nurture but tive. This model is consistent with the notions
Nature is Nurture, given the apparent Lamarkian- that development affords flexibility and that evo-
like effects of epigenesis. Some of the epigenesis- lution is informed by optimization.
susceptible gene polymorphisms involved Social genomics indicates that the genome is
include NR3C1 (nuclear receptor subfamily 3, fluid, and that it is a metagenome. The socioaf-
group C, member 1), OXTR, BDNF, and COX2 fective environment gets “under the skin,” as in
(cytochrome c oxidase subunit II). The work on epigenetics; but more so—it gets “onto the
epigenesis shows how it can lead to either inter- genome.” For example, social rejection can cre-
nalization or externalization behavioral difficul- ate social signals of even a short-term immediate
ties. As for rGE, some of the genetic nature that have long-lasting molecular imprints
polymorphisms involved include 5-HTTLPR and that affect health through effects on the HPA axis
D2 (TaqIAI allele). For cultural neuroscience, and also on inflammatory responses.
they include 5-HTTLPR, OXTR, and DRD4. Overall, the concept of evolution is evolving,
If rGE illustrates that genes influence environ- as is the concept of genetic influence on behavior.
ment, for example, through their evocative active Both need to adopt a broader framework in which
effects, cultural neuroscience illustrates how the environment is included in a systems frame-
environment (through culture) alters gene work. For example, the field needs to integrate
expression through genetic susceptibility to dif- social genomics with evolution, and ask how
ferential cultural effects. That being said, in the social genomics has influenced evolution.
present book, the person stands as the ultimate Already, epigenesis has been shown to have
influence in behavioral causation. Genes and transgenerational effects and the same might be
environment are both passive players relative to true of social genomics, for example, through
our own potential to be in control of our own epigenetic and related processes. Similarly, if
behavior. there might be transgenerational effects through
epigenesis and perhaps through social genomics,
Chapter 12: Nature and Nurture: Evolution one could ask to what extent the field of evolution
and Complexities Evolutionary psychology has should consider better how the environment has
been presented as a unifying force in psychology. gotten in our forebears under their skin and onto
In this chapter, I emphasize that, in adapting a their genome (and subsequently ours).
systems perspective in which evolution is consid-
ered as one primary factor, a pathway can be laid
down toward the unification of psychology. Part III: Normal and Abnormal
Tinbergen’s four questions are still seminal for Development and Free Will:
the field (adaptive function, phylogeny, ontogeny, Normal Development and Free Will
mechanism). They can serve to create an integra-
tive meta-model of behavioral causality along Chapter 13: Differential Susceptibility:
with the biopsychosocial model, NLDST, and Orchids, Dandelions, and the Flowering of
related models. The NLDST gives one axis of Developmental Psychology The chapter on
integration in these regards through its related developmental evolutionary models especially
concept of complexity. concerns differential susceptibility. Comparable
36 2 Overview of Book Parts and Chapter by Chapter Overview

models include biological sensitivity to context depression/anxiety; abuse/neglect, low SES; pov-
and adaptive calibration. These interactive mod- erty; and maternal factors (depression, caregiver
els involving polyphenotypic options are distinct sensitivity/attachment style promotion). The
from unilateral uniphenotypic ones of combined genes involved in the interaction include
vulnerabilities and adversities (diathesis-stress, 5-HTTLPR, COMT, NR2C1 (nuclear receptor
allostatic load). They are evolutionary through subfamily 2, group c, member 1), DAT1, and
the concepts of bet hedging, conditional adapta- DRD4. The effects include on disease/mortality;
tion, and stochastic developmental switch. They telomere length/inflammatory markers; depres-
offer accounts of differential life history strate- sion/neuroticism; delinquency/other externaliza-
gies (slow, less risky; fast, risky), in psychologi- tion behavior; and working memory/academic
cal acceleration, depending on early environment attainment. The mediating effect of epigenesis
quality. The former is fashioned by predictable (environmentally-induced gene-silence) appears
early environments and the latter by unpredict- a prominent intermediate mechanism in the rela-
able ones, for example. Therefore, forecasting tions described.
based on early environmental sampling appears a
mechanism in life history strategy.
Another aspect of the model of differential Chapter 15: Connecting the Social Dots The
susceptibility concerns certain polymorphisms chapter emphasizes the distinctiveness in humans
having susceptibility to environment impacts of our extreme social skills and/or organization.
relative to others and, furthermore, in ways that It investigates the evolutionary and developmen-
could be more positive for supportive environ- tal origins of these skills. For example, are they
ments with a susceptibility allele present but innate, prepared, and core, or do they depend on
more negative for nonsupportive environments gradual learning, for example, in imitation? The
with the same allele present. Some of the alleles chapter includes work on social neuroscience,
in this regard include those related to 5-HTTLPR, and emphasizes the frontalization process, as
DRD4, DAT1, BDNF, OXTR, and MAOA, with well as the mirror neuron system and the somatic
polygenetic combinations also involved. Some of marker hypothesis. Also, it refers to biobehav-
the early stressors in this research include mater- ioral synchrony and physiological attunement
nal emotionality/sensitivity. The negative out- that happens in the neonatal-parental embodied
comes involved in early adversity include dance or intersubjectivity. Other more biological
externalizing (e.g., conduct disorder) and inter- topics include the perception–action mechanism
nalizing (e.g., depression) ones. The mediators in and supramodal perception. Generally, the mod-
the relationships include stress-response physiol- els presented are quite biopsychosocial, includ-
ogy. The mechanisms affecting the genes ing the “SOCIAL” model and ones of stress
involved appear to be epigenetic. contagion and shared embodiment.
Other models in the chapter include the empir-
Chapter 14: Early Adversity, Fetal ical/nativist enactivism one, and one involving an
Programming, and Getting Under the Skin affective sharing device. In addition, the chapter
Early adversity affects long-term physical and includes the goal alignment and social normative
mental health, but in interaction with and media- models, as well as the prosocial construal and
tion by many factors. Related models refer to partner choice ones.
fetal programming and enduring effects. The About evolution, the concepts reviewed
environment is considered to “get under the skin” include superorganism, cultural evolution, group
even prenatally. The pathways are multiple and selection, and cultural group selection, as well as
include hypo- and hyperactivation of cortisol gene–culture co-evolution. Some of the terms
and, generally, effects on the HPA axis and the indicating the complexity of human social behav-
SAM axis. The early adversities described in ior include group mindedness, collective morality,
this chapter include: prenatal substance abuse/ collective intentionality, and hypercollaboration.
Part III: Normal and Abnormal Development and Free Will: Normal Development and Free Will 37

The proximal mechanisms involved in early Yet the field also encounters contrary concepts,
social learning include not only imitation and such as infants possessing an abstract framework
parental practice but also factors such as emula- and the blessing of abstraction. In a nativist-
tion and overimitation. The most intriguing friendly approach, neonates might even under-
research is with infants, and this includes work stand physical causation/Michottian launching
on biobehavioral synchrony, even in heart rate events. Yet, in the contrary view, only older chil-
coordination, and work with puppets who are dren might develop a full theory of mind, which
helpers or hinderers/mean or nice, and infants has been referred to as a “theory” theory. Aside
responding to them (e.g., preferring not only from innate factors, the chapter refers to natural
helpers but hinderers of hinderers). The chapter pedagogy, and observational causal learning/
spans the full developmental range, and for interventionist, causality-informative behavior.
adults, it refers to narrative/self-autobiography/ For some of the intriguing methods used in the
identity, as well as the public good/political ide- research, they include “blicket” detectors, sticky
ology. Also, it includes research not only on mittens, everted rabbits, and win-stay/lose-shift
humans but also nonhuman primates. In this strategies. Other concepts in the chapter include
chapter on connecting the social dots, clearly, I causal, higher-order relational cognition and the
had to consider many dots to connect. quantum probability model of causal reasoning.

Chapter 16: Causal Learning: Understanding Chapter 17: Developing the Mind, Minding
the World This chapter focuses heavily on Development This chapter bridges the next
empirical research on whether causal learning is ones on free will, reviewing (a) the development
evident very early in life as an associative or as a of executive function, which includes self-con-
primitive inferential, abstract fashion. The current trol and inhibition, and (b) developmental ver-
predominant view is that it is Bayesian, statistical, sions of models that have informed the present
probabilistic, computational, and so on, and not work (biopsychosocial, embodiment, NLDST).
governed by either innate preformed abstraction- It bridges the previous chapter by presenting
ready modules or associative, nonrepresentational views on development of theory of mind. In all
mechanisms. The Bayesian point of view in this these spheres, a primary issue concerns the nativ-
chapter is complemented by the interventionist ist vs. learning perspectives and the speed
and causal mapping ones. In working in this area, of development in the different domains. For
the traditional Piagetian perspective on mental example, is early theory of mind/false belief
schemas still appears useful, and it is much cited. understanding best considered as being (a)
However, others dismiss its utility. In my compro- implicit, rule-based, and emergent-expressive or
mise position, I show how a modified, integrative (b) explicit reasoning, and mentalizing based,
Neo-Piagetian view can be informative. including in usage-base? In these acquisitions,
The associative point of view is promoted by are biologically-based systems, such as mirror
theorists who argue that too much is read into neuronal systems, or environmentally-based
studies of very young infants in terms of their ones, such as parenting and rapid cultural learn-
early abstractive abilities. Rather than being little ing, more involved? Integrative models, of
logicians, young children are intuitive statisti- course, would argue that all these factors are
cians. A view that accommodates to the opposi- involved in the multifactorial complexity of
tion of the fast minimal nativist and slow behavioral causality. Finally, the chapter consid-
constructivist points of view on early causal ers that Piagetian concepts have much to offer
learning concerns the middle-of-the-road one of the needed integration in the field.
rational constructivism.
Early cognitive structures in the associationist Chapter 18: Free Will in Behavior: Believing
camp have been referred to as intuitive and non- Makes It So Free will is not an illusion, and
theoretical, with motor resonance involved. its belief is widespread and has important
38 2 Overview of Book Parts and Chapter by Chapter Overview

consequences, for example, in self-control. Part IV: Abnormalities


The research findings apparently show that the in Development and the DSM-5
intention to move follows rather than precedes
movement (Libet), but this type of research has Chapter 20: Free Will in Psychotherapy:
not been undertaken with ecological validity. Helping People Believe This chapter takes the
Questionnaires have been developed to measure work on free will in psychology and translates it
free will, and the results indicate relevant associ- in a module on the use of free will in psycho-
ations, such as with personality attributes and therapy. Sample questions that one could use in
motivation. That free will is relevant to psycho- this regard include the following:
logical function does not deny that unconscious
influences are important in behavior. They pro- (a) For free will in everyday life: “Think of sev-
vide the automaticity for much of our daily eral ways in your daily life that you show you
actions. However, conscious causation appears to have a sense of free will. Then, think of sev-
play a superordinate, deliberative role. Much of eral ways your sense of free will can be
the chapter deals with the neuronal and brain improved, e.g., in helping you reach desired
bases thought to underlie free decision making, goals and outcomes. How can you help your-
which appears emergent and not uniquely reduc- self increase your sense of free will in your
tionist. There are enough bases in the chapter to everyday life? Think of several ways.”
enable further conceptual work on free will in (b) For self-regulation: “Delay of gratification is
psychology, such as through my own concept on important to everyday life. List several ben-
free being. efits in waiting for better choices later on
rather than seeking immediate gratification.
How can you improve this skill?”
Chapter 19: An Integrated Model of “Free (c) For conscious causation: “Writing about or
Will” and New Free Will Questionnaires The talking about past events that need rework-
question of free will is related closely to that of ing, such as traumas, improves the ability to
self-control and its depletion. Self-control can move forward.”
be depleted in successive relevant self-control (d) For mechanisms in motivation: “I might feel
tasks in the laboratory in which the first one that I should act impulsively, but I can get
serves to degrade self-control in the second. The back on target and control that.”
phenomenon has been termed ego-depletion, (e) For meaning making: “Whenever you think
and it has been related to physiological deple- that free will does not exist for you, how can
tion in available glucose. This model is a you bring it back as a part of you?”
resource one, and other models have been devel- (f) For promoting logic: “How have you used
oped for self-control depletion that are inclusive automatic thought, intuition, or fast respond-
of motivational and social factors. In this chap- ing without thinking through first, and it
ter, I present an integrated biopsychosocial helped? When did it not? How could you
model of self-control, across these various fac- have handled it differently?”
tors thought to affect self-control, which helps (g) For the change process: “Growth happens by
explain the depletion effect. Also, I present a exchanging ideas, talking, reflecting on the
biopsychosocial concept of free will. Further, I exchanges and ideas, etc. How can you keep
develop a new free will questionnaire that is it going so that change for the better contin-
consistent with the biopsychosocial approach to ues or is maintained despite ups and downs
free will. The chapter also deals with dual pro- over time?”
cess cognitive models, which I integrate into the (h) For addictions: “Belief that addiction can be
general theme of the chapter. Finally, the chapter controlled begins with the belief that it is a
integrates some of my other work on activation/ condition for which such control is possible;
inhibition coordination and cognitive stages in it is not only medical and biological but also
development. psychological and social.”
Part IV: Abnormalities in Development and the DSM-5 39

The chapter develops some novel concepts noradrenergic receptor polymorphism


related to free will in psychotherapy. These (α2cDel1322-325); gamma-aminobutyric acid
include free will working schemata. Also, we (GABA); (allo)pregnanolone (ALLO); neuropep-
develop asymptotically in free will growth. tide Y (NPY), catecholamines, serotonin, corti-
Further, we endure a paradoxical loss of free will sol, corticotrophin-releasing factor (CRF),
to do anything that we want when we mature and dehydroepiandrostorone, (allo)pregnalolone,
take on our responsibilities. and immune factors. The general message of
the chapter is that progress is being made in
Chapter 21: PTSD: Traumatic Causation The determining the pathway to disorder for
causality of abnormal or disordered behavior is PTSD. However, as with the many disorders in
referred to as etiology. The various versions of the DSM, effort to establish the endophenotype
the DSM diagnostic manual are based on the of PTSD needs to consider the biopsychosocial
medical model, which seeks clear, specific rela- model. A strict biological emphasis on the ori-
tionships among etiology, disorder category, and gins of PTSD will confound understanding of its
treatment. A major approach to understanding causality (etiology).
etiology involves the search for endophenotypes
that lie between genes and disorders. This chap- Chapter 22: DSM-5: Basics and Critics The
ter reviews current conceptualization and next four chapters of the present work review the
research on PTSD, focusing on the biological DSM-5 (American Psychiatric Association,
markers of the disorder that might constitute 2013), in general, and particular DSM categories,
endophenotypes. The search for candidate endo- especially PTSD. It gives voice to critics of the
phenotypes in PTSD must begin with determin- DSM-5, and ends with recommendations. The
ing its genetic bases, as well as the effects of first chapter of the four in this series begins with
epigenesis on their expression. However, estab- an overview of the DSM-5 and the assumptions
lishing the endophenotype of PTSD is con- that are needed to revise it. It examines etiology
founded by the uncertainty of which model best and also the biopsychosocial model. Then, it
conceives it and the factor structure of its symp- gives the major specific changes incorporated in
toms, let alone that both the number of its symp- the DSM-5.
toms and their arrangement in clusters change The critique of the DSM-5 has focused on
from one version of the DSM to the next. deficits in its utility, reliability, and validity. In
The chapter is heavily biological and is too addition, often it sets a bar too low, and exposes
dense to summarize in detail in this regard. Some both vulnerable people and normal ones to
of the candidate genes for the endophenotype for the risks of overdiagnosis and of pathologizing
PTSD mentioned in the chapter include: normal conditions.
SLC6A39 (dopamine transporter gene polymor- Further, apparently the DSM-5 workgroups
phism, allele 9), FKBP5 (glucocorticoid receptor were compromised ethically. Also, the field trials
co-chaperone protein 5), COMT, RGS2 (regula- for the DSM-5 used a draft version that was
tor of G-protein signaling 2), 5-HTTLPR, BDNF, changed for the final version. Finally, I compared
NR3C1, and DRD2 (dopamine receptor D2). the draft and final version, and found that any
Some of the brain areas involved in PTSD mention of the term biopsychosocial was
include: the hippocampus, the amygdala, the removed.
anterior cingulate, the insula, the orbitofrontal My contributions to the field in this chapter
region, and the medial prefrontal cortex. As for include developing a better definition of mental
neurotransmitters, they include: prefrontal cortex disorder. I underscore the need to adopt the bio-
alpha 2c (PFC α 2c); alpha, noradrenergic (nor- psychosocial approach in psychiatry, generally,
adrenergic α); dopamine type 1 (DA1); serotonin and for revising the DSM-5, specifically. To con-
type 2 receptor (5HT2R); dehydroepiandros- clude, I note that using the DSM-5 might induce
terone, or its sulfated derivative (DHEA (S)); can- in the users the humorously entitled DSM-5
nabinoid type 1 receptor (CB1R); alpha 2c Confusion Disorder.
40 2 Overview of Book Parts and Chapter by Chapter Overview

Chapter 23: The DSM-5 and the RDoC Grand prior DSM manual (DSM-IV-TR; American
Designs and Grander Problems The two great Psychiatric Association, 2000).
projects in psychiatry concern the psychiatric Other disorders were changed so much by the
diagnostic manual DSM-5 (American Psychiatric working groups in charge of revising the DSM-
Association, 2013) and the neuroscientific-based IV-TR that they were consigned to the DSM-5’s
psychiatric research project RDoC (Insel et al., appendix section for further study, given the out-
2010; Insel & Lieberman, 2013). Insel et al. cry about their lack of clinical clarity and utility
(2010) had considered the latter as a step in (e.g., personality disorders). Finally, other catego-
improving psychiatric understanding of mental ries in the DSM-IV-TR that had been roundly criti-
disorder and eventually as a key for a new cized and even ignored (e.g., malingering) have
approach to psychiatric diagnosis. More recently, remained relatively unchanged in the DSM-5.
he considered the two projects as collaborative In this chapter, I review these various catego-
and mutually-informing (Insel & Lieberman, ries in the DSM-5, how they had been treated in
2013). This chapter first examines the multiple the DSM-IV, the criticisms raised about them,
criticisms of the RDoC project, which are eerily including my own, and the recommendations
similar to those applicable to the DSM-5. Both made to revise them for the DSM-5. In particular,
projects appear insular and focused on the neuro- I present a revision of SSD and label it Chronic
biology of mental disorder, in particular, despite Pain Complications Disorder. It takes the best of
protestations to the contrary. the criteria for SSD, revises them, and adds oth-
Next, the chapter describes once more PTSD, ers, while maintaining chronic pain as a focus in
but this time as treated in the DSM-5. I review its the disorder and also dealing with the criticisms
criteria, its factor structure, and so on, and pres- of the category applied to it in the DSM-IV. Another
ent recent research and criticisms related to it. I recommendation that I make for the DSM-5 is
describe my own research on PTSD, including on how to better define malingering.
the excessive symptom combinations possible
because of its polythetic structure, especially Chapter 25: DSM-5: Recommendations The
when possible comorbidities are considered fourth chapter on the DSM-5 (American
(Young, Lareau, & Pierre, 2014). It would appear Psychiatric Association, 2013) in the present
that simplifying the approach to symptom orga- work reviews the psychiatric approaches to etiol-
nization for PTSD makes sense, and the same ogy and endophenotype. Then, it proceeds to
message applies to many DSM-5 disorders. make recommendations for revising in psychia-
try the approach to both assessment and diagno-
Chapter 24: The Disordered DSM-5 sis. For etiology, I highlight Kendler’s models on
Disorders As much as PTSD was presented in emergence and mechanism, and other work indi-
the DSM-5 (American Psychiatric Association, cating the multifactorial, fuzzy nature of psychi-
2013), it is open to criticism. Other disorders in atric symptoms and disorders, including the
the DSM-5 have been subject to even more neg- network approach. I argue for an inclusive bio-
ative evaluations of their conceptualization and psychosocial model not only for etiology but also
symptom criteria. For example, Neurocognitive for the related concept of endophenotypes.
Disorder (NCD) has specifiers for Mild and Further, I propose a reciprocally dynamic causal
Major but not Moderate. Many patients with model of mental disorder that considers its rela-
TBI diagnosed using this system will find that tion to symptoms in an integrated top-down/bot-
the bar has been set too high for their moderate tom-up fashion.
condition, and they will be assigned a mild level As for recommendations to revise the extant
of TBI. As for patients with chronic pain, they DSM nosology system and assessments related
will be given a diagnosis of somatic symptom to it, I propose the following: (a) a manner to
disorder (SSD), with pain as a specifier, instead integrate categorical and dimensional approaches,
of Pain Disorder, which is a category in the and (b) use of a range of assessment dimensions.
Part V: Personal Contributions to the Study of Causality in Behavior: New Models 41

Note that all the DSM chapters in the present causality of behavior. The first of these chapters
work consider forensic factors, given the import is on a model on stimulus–organism–response
of the DSMs in forensic work and the problems (S-O-R) relations. The next two are on new con-
raised in using them this way. cepts and terms for the field. The last of these
three chapters introduces applications in under-
standing behavioral causality in terms of my
Part V: Personal Contributions 25-step Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian develop-
to the Study of Causality mental model, a process that especially takes up
in Behavior: New Models most of the last six chapters of the present book.
The revised S-O-R model that I propose is
Chapter 26: Causality in Psychological Injury based on the interrelational quality of the compo-
& Law: Basics and Critics In the next two nents of the model, wherein each of stimulus,
chapters of the present work, I turn to an area of organism, and response are considered “fuzzy”
psychology in which I have helped place causal- and probabilistic, or without distinct boundaries
ity as a central concept (psychological injury and (or even standard order in their sequencing; e.g.,
law; e.g., Young, 2014, 2015; Young & Drogin, does S always enter the organism independently
2014). Psychological injuries concern conten- without the effects of feedback/forward mecha-
tious conditions, especially PTSD, chronic pain, nisms?). Free will plays a role in the model
and mild TBI. The chapter considers causation through free will belief and its effects on behav-
both in civil law and in terms of mens rea in crim- ior. Just as genes can evoke active effects in the
inal law. I propose new terms that might help dis- environment (gene–environment correlations), I
ambiguate some of the confusion in the field propose that free will belief engaged in the per-
(e.g., biopsychosocial causation). The biopsy- son can do the same (“free will/environment
chosocial model serves as a central focus in the correlations”).
area of psychological injury and law (along with
forensic considerations). Chapter 29: Networked Causal Terms This
chapter proposes integrative models of behavioral
Chapter 27: Causality in Psychological Injury causality, notably an Integrated Cross Network
& Law: Models In the second chapter in the model and a GEODS (Genes, Environment,
present book on causality in the area of psycho- Organism, Development, Systems) model. In
logical injury and law, I present a new model that addition, it presents some catchy terms meant to
includes iatrogenesis among the various influ- promote further interest in the study of behavioral
ences on individuals with psychological injuries. causation, given its disparate focus in psychology.
Much of the chapter deals with iatrogenesis, which These new terms include not only simpler ones,
has not been a central topic in psychology despite such as embodied causation, but also more
its importance in the medical field. I review other thought-provoking ones, such as humans consti-
models in the area of psychological injury and law tuting a species of Homo Causa and also the uni-
that include iatrogenesis, as well as the many verse being comprised of cause–effect relations,
terms related to it. This chapter and the prior one or of “causicles.” The most important new term
emphasize the need to conduct comprehensive that I created is meant to capture the broad
assessments that are impartial and scientifically approach that I took in it with respect to behavioral
informed in order to evaluate effectively psycho- causality, and it is called “Coexistential Causal
logical injury determinations and their causality. Intraactionism.” The first and last of the compo-
nents if this term indicate, respectively, (a) that
Chapter 28: Stimulus–Organism–Response opposite concepts might be really complementary
Model: SORing to New Heights This chapter and (b) phenomena exist not as interactions among
begins a series of nine chapters in which I present their components but in the interactions them-
major innovations that I have proposed about the selves, or their intraactive interactions.
42 2 Overview of Book Parts and Chapter by Chapter Overview

Chapter 30: Change Mechanisms This chap- The chapter considers some cognitive applica-
ter presents review of the critical change mecha- tions of the model especially in terms of the
nism of activation/inhibition coordination and it growth in two more advanced cognitions.
gives details of two conceptual innovations that I Specifically, from Young (2014), it looks at the
have proposed in the book, those of neuromal growth of free will belief and of ethical thought.
networks and readiness for change in terms of my Both emerge and continue to develop in the ado-
25-step (5 stage × 5 substage) developmental lescent and adult periods, and so start with single
model. The neuromal network model is a abstract acquisitions and then superordinate ones.
developmentally-tuned one that helps explain
behavioral acquisitions. The readiness for change Chapter 32: Further Expansions of the Present
model is one that helps explain behavioral Stage Model This chapter explains more the
changes, in general. The chapter also describes socioaffective correspondences to the cognitive
dimensions involved in change. ones in the present 25-step model of development.
It especially describes how a Neo-Eriksonian
developmental sequence corresponds to the Neo-
Part VI: The Neo-Piagetian/Neo- Piagetian one. It shows how a modified Neo-
Eriksonian Model Maslovian sequence fits it, as well. It indicates
how other acquisitions, such as theory of mind
Chapter 31: A Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian and having a sense of responsibility, fit it, too. It
25-Step (Sub)Stage Model This chapter pres- looks at correspondences across cognitive steps
ents the Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian develop- and both therapeutic advances and dysfunctional
mental model that I have developed and expanded regressions (in pain patients). It even explores
(Young, 2011, 2014). The model is a lifespan one broader changes, such as might take place with
that is not only consistent with and integrates the controversies as processed in thought and how
prior models on which it is based but also inte- they might resolve. The chapter also considers the
grates and often explains better the data that had growth of scientific thought (e.g., Darwin), in that
been used in building the prior models. In Young I show that the model of individual development
(2011), I explicated how the current 25-step that I have proposed can be applied to other devel-
model that I created accounts for the data used by opmental phenomena. Indeed, it would be inter-
both Fischer and Case in their Neo-Piagetian esting to analyze current, psychological theorizing
models and is comprehensive to the point that it along these lines in its effort to create a unifying
fills in gaps in their (sub)stage sequences. concept for the discipline.
Presentation of these arguments is beyond the
scope of the present work. Chapter 33: Generic Change Model This
In this first chapter of five devoted to my chapter presents a generic change model based
model, I integrate prior material to show that the on the Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian one that I
model includes descriptions of biological, per- have developed. It helps in understanding other
sonal (psychological, self), and environmental/ step models of various psychological phenomena
social components at each step. For example, at by showing their consistency with this one. It
the biological level, it gives the presumed evolu- helps by indicating generic change processes
tionary phase in which the step might have applicable even to nonliving systems. Some of
evolved and the presumed brain organization that the topics referred to in this chapter with respect
might subserve it. At the personal/psychological/ to the present generic change model include
self level, it refers to the cognitive (mis)percep- readiness for change, information processing,
tion of the other that develops at each step. As for discovery learning, open-ended change, execu-
the environmental/social side, I give the social tive function, psychotherapy, education, evolu-
self-working schemata that might develop in tion, social drivers, and causality itself (e.g.,
response to the social environment. genes/epigenesis, causal graphs).
Part VI: The Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian Model 43

Chapter 34: Revising Maslow This chapter tral to the unification needed in the field (as well,
focuses on revising my Neo-Maslovian model perhaps, using my own models in this regard).
(Young, 2011) by incorporating social psychol- The chapter concludes with how the concept of
ogy conceptualization on moral and other motives the causal self can help unify psychology.
(Forbes, Haidt, and Janoff-Bulman and col-
leagues). My first Maslovian model revision in Chapter 36: New Directions in Psychological
Young (2011) had divided his well-known trian- Causality The prior chapters in this last portion
gular model of hierarchical needs into two of the book have shown the value of the develop-
halves—one on self-definition and one on relat- ment and generic change models that I have cre-
edness (after Blatt, 2008). The current revision ated. In the last chapter of the book, I create a
adds a third component to the triangular model, different generic model on behavioral causality
related to environmental mastery/competence. that is not step-based. It covers distal, proximal,
Like the other two aspects of the self in the and triggering causes in behavior. I apply it to
revised model, I show how it develops in five rework the three models that helped in creating
stages that are consistent with the five levels in them (on neuroticism, action/self-control, and
the model on hierarchical needs. Moreover, my self-definition/relatedness). Then, I show its
reworking of Maslow in this way allowed me to value in helping to understand the origins of free
revisit the work of Forbes, Haidt, and Janoff- will (free being, believing in free will, having a
Bulman and colleagues and show how their mod- sense of free will), depletion in self-control, and
els need to be revised in light of my own. In PTSD. Potentially, the model has wide applica-
particular, I developed a model of foundational bility in indicating the multifactorial causation in
moral motives based on Haidt’s work on founda- behavior, in general, and how it could be concep-
tional motives and Janoff-Bulman’s on moral tualized and researched.
motives. To close the last chapter and the book, I pres-
Finally, I added a superordinate sublevel to ent further modeling of behavioral causality, this
Maslow’s one of self-actualization and related time returning to my generic change model for
concepts, such as generativity, that involves “psy- the most part. I apply it to free will, in particular,
chological completeness.” At the same time, I but also to growth in modeling and change
referred to the process of becoming psychologi- mechanisms.
cally complete or “psychological completing.”
These concepts could complement other con- Chapter 37: Epilogue The epilogue examines
cepts related to adult psychological maturity, the most recent literature on behavior and causal-
such as psychological integrity or wisdom. ity, including on genes and environment, devel-
opment, free will, and psychopathology
Chapter 35: Staging Revolutions and (posttraumatic stress disorder, PTSD). Next, it
Paradigms Kuhn’s concept of paradigm shift is examines recent work on critical models, includ-
a prominent one in science. This chapter describes ing the relational, Piagetian/Neo-Piagetian, net-
a revision of the model by showing that the work (e.g., in neurocircuitry), and nonlinear
changes that take place in paradigms fit the pres- dynamical systems theory (NLDST), as well as
ent five-step generic change model. First, I pres- ones related to causality (e.g., top-down
ent and rework Overton’s revision of Kuhn’s processes). Then, it presents three models that
work. I refer to his concept of relationism as one I created having the common theme of top-down/
central to my own work, too. The chapter covers bottom up coordination in multilevel hierarchical
broad topics of interest, such as unifying psy- systems (for symptom-construct relations, the
chology and presenting a co-existential philo- nature of cognitive stages, and multiple emo-
sophical model. Overall, the chapter continues tional intelligences). Conclusions value the need
the work in this last part of the book of revising to place causality as central to psychology and its
critical theorists in the behavioral sciences unification, while considering both as ongoing
(Maslow, Kuhn) and integrating causality as cen- dynamic projects.
44 2 Overview of Book Parts and Chapter by Chapter Overview

Chapter Conclusions Insel, T. R., & Lieberman, J. A. (2013). DSM-5 and


RDoC: Shared interests. The National Institute of
Mental Health. www.nimh.nih.gov
This general overview and specific chapter McNally, R. J., Robinaugh, D. J., Wu, G. W. Y., Wang, L.,
description of the present book on behavioral Deserno, M. K., & Borsboom, D. (2015). Mental dis-
causality in psychology and related disciplines orders as causal systems: A network approach to post-
traumatic stress disorder. Clinical Psychological
underscores the massive nature of its scope.
Science, 3, 836–849.
Moreover, work in the area is accelerating in Overton, W. F. (2013). Relationism and relational devel-
multiple, disparate directions that defy unifying opmental systems: A paradigm for developmental sci-
them. Nevertheless, the concept of causality itself ence in the post-cartesian era. In R. M. Lerner & J. B.
Benson (Eds.), Advances in child development and
could serve as a unifying focus in psychology
behavior. Embodiment and epigenesis: Theoretical
and related disciplines once it gains some con- and methodological issues in understanding the role
ceptual and methodological clarity. In this regard, of biology within the relational developmental system.
I present models, both extant ones and new ones Part A: Philosophical, theoretical, and biological
dimensions (Vol. 44, pp. 21–64). Oxford, UK:
that I have developed, that can help unify the
Elsevier.
study of behavioral causality and point to direc- Overton, W. F. (2014). The process-relational paradigm and
tions in unifying psychology itself. relational-developmental-systems metamodel as con-
text. Research in Human Development, 11, 323–331.
Sloman, S. (2005). Causal models: How people think
about the world and its alternatives. New York:
References Oxford University Press.
Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
American Psychiatric Association. (2000). Diagnostic Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science +
and statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM- Business Media.
IV-TR (4th ed., text rev.). Washington, DC: Author. Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feigning, and response
American Psychiatric Association. (2013). Diagnostic bias in psychiatric/psychological injury: Implications
and statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM-5 for practice and court. Dordrecht, Netherlands:
(5th ed.). Washington, DC: Author. Springer Science + Business Media.
Blatt, S. J. (2008). Polarities of experience: Relatedness Young, G. (2015). Causality in civil disability and crimi-
and self-definition in personality development, psycho- nal forensic cases: Legal and psychological compari-
pathology, and the therapeutic process. Washington, son. International Journal of Law and Psychiatry,
DC: American Psychological Association. 42–43, 114–120.
Friston, K. (2010). The free-energy principle: A unified Young, G., & Drogin, E. (2014). Psychological injury and
brain theory? Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 11, law I: Causality, malingering, and PTSD. Mental
127–138. Health Law & Policy Journal, 3, 373–417.
Insel, T. R., Cuthbert, B. N., Garvey, M. A., Heinssen, Young, G., Lareau, C., & Pierre, B. (2014). One quintillion
R. K., Pine, D. S., Quinn, K. J., et al. (2010). Research ways to have PTSD comorbidity: Recommendations
domain criteria (RDoC): Toward a new classification for the disordered DSM-5. Psychological Injury and
framework for research on mental disorders. American Law, 7, 61–74.
Journal of Psychiatry, 167, 748–751.
Introducing Causality
in Psychology 3

and the work of Chaisson (2010, 2011) on ther-


Chapter Introduction modynamics in the universe as a mechanistic
driving force in Big History. I elaborate these
This chapter looks both back and forward. three causality axes in psychology, in particular,
It presents material from my recent book on indicating their hierarchical and coordinated
development and causality (Young, 2011) that nature, and show how they relate to recent work
served as a springboard for the present book, on concepts that I have developed—on freedom
while presenting some new material related to in being, the biopersonalsocial model, and cross-
the topic of the book that prepares the way for the network models, in particular.
present much expanded tome on causality in psy- Content-wise, (a) mechanism remains the pri-
chology, as described in the remainder of the mary focus of the present book on causality, as it
book, which goes way beyond my effort on the must be. From this perspective, I review material
topic in the 2011 book. In particular, this chapter on genetics, epigenesis, neural networks and
expands my original model of the axes of causal- neurons, the brain, and so on. (b) At the same
ity relevant to psychology from the three primary time, free will remains the center of advanced
ones that I had considered as crucial in Young development and thought in human behavior
(2011) to over 20 of them (still keeping the three (e.g., belief in free will). It represents the epitome
primary ones central). In this regard, the three of the causal force at the apogee of influences in
primary axes in the study of causality concern the causality of behavior, that of the self, or the
mechanism, causal mapping/learning, and free person him/herself, and one’s emergence as an
will. Specifically, the major foci in the study of active contributor beyond Nature and Nurture to
causality number: (a) causal learning/mapping, one’s growth.
which includes the counterfactual argument; (b) By reviewing and extending the material in
mechanisms, which include systems modeling, Young (2011) on these themes, I prepare the way
brain-behavior processes, epigenetics, development, for what follows in the book in the 30+ chapters
and evolution; and (c) free will/consciousness, remaining, which give a comprehensive review of
which includes consequences for having belief in the literature on behavioral causality and also the
free will (Baumeister, 2008; Young, 2011). new conceptualizations that I propose for under-
In this chapter, I organize the material taken standing the causality of behavior. (c) The work on
from Young (2011) for purposes of this present causal graph modeling is making inroads in causal-
chapter in terms of these three axes, while adding ity conceptualization and research, and it appears
to their description, such as by presenting the throughout the book, as well as in this chapter
work of Sloman (2005) on causal graph modeling through the work of Sloman (2005), in particular.

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 45


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_3
46 3 Introducing Causality in Psychology

Although, generally, psychology has adapted Throughout the book, I present up-to-date
a nuanced nature–nurture interaction perspective literature reviews and integrative concepts, such as
on behavioral causality, or a biological–environ- on stimulus–response relations, gene–environment
mental interface perspective, in understanding interactions, endophenotypes, activation/inhibition
the “why” of behavior, the discipline of psychol- coordination, and emergent circular causality.
ogy lacks an overriding theoretical focus. Toward That said, the major focus of the present book
rectifying this lack, the present book promotes an involves highlighting free will as a central con-
integrated biopsychosocial model of causality cept in the study of causality in behavior, as per
situated in nonlinear dynamical system theory the title of the book. In this regard, the book con-
(NLDST; with multiple levels, e.g., distal, proxi- sistently reviews the work of Baumeister (e.g.,
mal, immediate sequentially; higher-order, such 2008), in particular, for example, on the conse-
as free will belief, lower order, such as brain quences of believing in free will, and considers
mechanisms), and other potentially unifying its implications and applications. In particular,
models (e.g., networks, embodiment). The model for the latter, I develop a developmental model of
of nonlinear dynamical systems, among others, free will, a questionnaire on free will, and also
appears at many junctures in the book, because therapeutic modules that can be used to promote
concepts related to nonlinear dynamical systems, it with patients.
as well as the related construct of networks, have To summarize, the present chapter examines
gained increasing currency and even primacy in key terms and concepts in the study of causality, as
psychology. well as integrative models. It describes the work of
The book supports the notion that the person Young (2011) that served as a starting point for the
her- or himself has an active say in her/his devel- book. It presents a figure showing the multiple
opment with the psychological or personal/self areas of psychological study of causality beyond
component of the person including possibility of the three major ones of mechanism, graphic model-
influence of believing in free will on behavior. ing, and free will. The study of behavioral causality
If it is properly elaborated in a nuanced integra- is expanding exponentially, but it needs a coherent
tive fashion, the construct of causality has the focus and, in this regard, the present book offers
potential to stand as a unifying one in psychology one way of arriving at this necessary anchor for the
and, indeed, in the social sciences and also the field of psychology and related disciplines.
sciences generally.
The study of causality/causation is found
widespread in psychology, even if its study is Causality in Psychology
dispersed. For example, the basic tenet that
correlation does not mean causation is one of the Introduction
overriding themes in psychology. However,
despite its ubiquity, it is not considered a central The study of causality in psychology is wide-
focus, and not even close to a unifying force in spread but has been very limited as a distinct
psychology. Recently, its conceptualization and focus, for example, in books devoted to the topic.
study have increased quickly, but consideration Aside from recent ones by Young (Young, 2011;
of the integrative nature of causality in areas in Young, Kane, & Nicholson, 2007), there have
which its study is accelerating is elusive and, as a been only a handful of books in psychology with
focus of study, it remains disparate and uninte- the terms causality or causation in the title (e.g.,
grated. Therefore, in this book, I expand the Shrout, Keyes, & Ornstein, 2011). But the impor-
description of causality in psychology, and tance of causality in the sciences is gaining trac-
include others areas of scholarship for which the tion in the field, as illustrated by a “manifesto” of
topic of causality, potentially is central, such as why one should study causality in the sciences
those of epidemiology, ecology, and law. (Illari, Russo, & Williamson, 2011a, 2011b).
Causality in Psychology 47

The classic issue in science concerning information related to patient issues and their
causality relates to the distinction between cor- treatment. Causal reasoning can help elucidate a
relation and causation, and it still permeates the patient’s causal matrix, including precursors,
field. Philosophers, psychologists, and other sci- mechanisms, pathways, and consequences. Causal
entists are expanding this work in several ways reasoning skills training should involve five cur-
(such as in the work on causal mappings and ricular modules.
learning; Beebee, Hitchcock, & Menzies, 2009;
Gopnik & Schulz, 2007; Illari et al., 2011a, Modules In the first module, students should
2011b; Markus, 2011; Pearl, 2000, 2009; Russo, learn about the important domains of clinical
2009; Sloman, 2005; etc.). However, they have practice in which making causal inferences is
been more concerned with immediate, proximal crucial. These include understanding etiology,
causal processes, as represented by causal graph formulating an assessment plan, determining
and their mathematical underpinnings, and they whether clinically significant distress/impairment
have ignored other approaches, such as answer- is present, creating an intervention plan, and
ing to Tinbergen’s (1963) four questions about monitoring therapeutic progress and responding
causation, which cover longer term causal pro- to the information. Also, causal reasoning is
cesses, including evolution and development. In important in understanding the research in the
this regard, toward its beginning, the present field and integrating one’s clinical experience
book examines in depth these latter fields, as with it.
well as that of genetics. In addition, as In the second module, students should learn
mentioned, an important axis in the study of critical causal concepts. Also, they should learn
causality relates to free will and consciousness common errors in causal reasoning.
(Baumeister, 2008; Baumeister, Crescioni, & In the third module, they should learn about
Alquist, 2011), and later portions of the book both internal and external validity. The former is
deal in depth with this aspect. In Young (2011), I about the research allows for causal inferences
concentrated on the question of mechanism per- and the former is about generalizability of results
taining to causality (e.g., Gene × Environment in research.
(G × E) interaction, epigenetics), but there is In module four, students should learn how to
room for integrating the diverse approaches on formulate and evaluate working theories about
causality (e.g., genes, environment, evolution, the determinants of patients’ presenting problems
brain, development, psychopathology, free will, and how they are maintained. In this regard, the
mechanism), and the book is dedicated to under- students should consider the “ecopathology” and
taking this task in depth for each area “ecoresilience” of patients.
considered. In the last module, causal reasoning skill train-
ing should focus on planning, targeting, and eval-
uating interventions. Diagrams might be helpful
Causal Reasoning Skills Training in this regard to generate causal hypotheses.
Layne et al. (2014) concluded that causal
Introduction Layne, Steinberg, and Steinberg modeling can help in case conceptualization,
(2014) argued that causal reasoning skills should intervention planning, and prioritizing target foci
be central in training mental health professionals. in interventions. Causal modeling in clinical
Causal reasoning is “pervasive and indispens- practice helps in generating causal hypotheses
able” in clinical decision-making and practice. It with patients, implementing causal experiments
should be part of core competency training. For in therapy, and monitoring and evaluating out-
example, clinicians assemble causally-relevant comes of interventions.
48 3 Introducing Causality in Psychology

History establishing when agents genuinely cause


effects.
There are several major academic streams in the (b) Causation. Garner described that causation
study of causality, and its origins have a venerable refers to causality, and defined it as the caus-
history in philosophy. The topic has been important ing or producing of an effect (Garner, 2009). I
in philosophy, and Arisotle’s approach to the four add that the effect must be produced by an
causes still marks the field. Moreover, Aristotle’s agent, act, or process. Garner (2009) noted
views have influenced psychology. that, in law, for causation what matters is lia-
However, the study of causality has not emerged bility. Is the causative source proximate or
as a distinct field of study, despite its ubiquity as an dominant, or at least contributory, substantive,
underlying theme in multiple disciplines, including or material, and not tangential or “de mini-
psychology. Aside from a lack of a unifying struc- mus.” Establishing the material contribution
ture for the study of causality, there is even a philo- of an event at claim might be more relevant to
sophical point of view of acausalism (promoted by it than invoking the “but-for” test (Douglas,
Hume and Russell, in particular), which minimizes Huss, Murdoch, Washington, & Koch, 1999).
the importance of seeking causality, or even denies The latter argument indicates that the psycho-
its existence. logical condition at issue would not have
existed “but for” the occurrence of the index
event (Cocchiarella & Lord, 2001). This term
Critical Terms reflects the counterfactual condition, which is
so important to causal graph modeling
Introduction Part of the difficulty in the study of approaches (Pearl, 2009), and philosophical
causality in psychology is that the terms used in the related approaches.
field are at times not clearly defined. Young (Young, (c) Layne et al. (2014) elaborated that a cause
2008; Young et al., 2007; Young & Shore, 2007) could be partial/contributory or sole. It could
found this to be true for the study of causality in the be conjunctive or disjunctive. It could be
area of psychological injury and law. For example, necessary or sufficient. It could be complex
there is misconception about terms such as causality through reciprocal effects or through multi-
and causation, and related ones. In the following, I step chains. It could involve a moderator
provide definitions related to the two terms. that is a vulnerability factor, protective,
Moreover, I add others from the list of critical terms facilitative, or inhibitory. It could involve a
related to causality that had been noted by Layne mediator that is partial, or full. It might
et al. (2014). involve a risk marker, or even one that is
causal.
(d) General causation refers to whether the
Terms event at claim legally is capable of induc-
(a) Causality. Defined as the principle of causal ing the alleged harm. General causation is
relation; the relationship between cause and compared to specific causation, for which
effect (Garner, 2009, p. 249). Layne et al. the event at issue had “actually caused” the
(2014) defined it as the relation between two alleged harm (Young & Shore, 2007).
conditions/events in which the antecedent one
determines in whole or part the consequent Comment Young et al. (2007) distinguished
one. Garner noted the equivalence of the term causality and causation in terms of the distinc-
“causation” and “causality.” Pearl (2009) noted tion between product and process although, in
that although the concept of causality is funda- practice, the terms are used interchangeably.
mental to human thought, it is embedded in Causation is associated more with product and
mystery and controversy, given the difficulty in causality is associated more with process.
Critical Concepts 49

Moreover, it would seem that in the hierarchy “hot” or “cold” causality. This distinction allows
of explanatory terms, mechanism is more spe- for individual differences in the influence of the
cific; mechanisms serve the unfolding of causal person as agent in behavioral determination.
principles. Much of the present book attempts “Hot” causality refers to when people themselves
to discern critical mechanisms in producing buffer influences on them, such as environmental
behavior. adversity. They serve as their own buttresses in
their development. Individuals are buffeted by
powerful influences and immersed in complex
Critical Concepts life scenarios but, nevertheless, could strive to
achieve an assertive, active stance in which they
Reducing Reductionism can evaluate prudently their options, and even act
to create better ones, in order to adapt better to
Some major approaches in science and psychology the environment and alter it for the better.
are deterministic, reductionistic, and passive with In contrast, “cold” causality refers to an
respect to the role of the person himself/herself in absence of or fundamentally compromised hot
causality (e.g., behaviorism). Typically, they under- causality. That is, the individual cannot rationally
stand behavior or events as the product of unalter- take charge of the self and the situation, even in a
able influences in the past and present, so that simpler one, and ends up choosing not at all or
factors such as free will and self, agency and auton- poorly from among the choices that might be
omy, and consciousness cannot influence behavior. available (Young, 2011).
In this predominant approach in the sciences
about behavior and its influences, behavior is con-
sidered the product of the chain of biological and Causal Streams and Three Major
environmental influences in a deterministic fashion; Causality Axes
it is considered the outcome of a passive causality.
Rather than perceiving the individual as having an In Young (2011), I addressed the disparate study
active voice in the direction and path of choices that of causality and causation as a predominant topic
could be made, behavior and choice are viewed as in psychology by referring to three areas of its
reflections of internal and external constraints. Free study—as mechanism, in causal mapping/learn-
will is relegated to illusory status and, at best, con- ing, and in free will (see Fig. 3.1). In the follow-
sciousness to a reductionist epiphenomenon. ing, I elaborate the approach taken in Young
(a) However, basically, behavior can be consid- (2011) with respect to these axes, adding new
ered the result of more than biology and environ- material related to them.
ment because people themselves are involved in
their own development. (b) Also, behavior should Causal Mapping and Learning Contemporary
be considered the expression of system factors that study in this approach to causality began with the
include emergence beyond the influences involved. work of the philosophers, Spirtes, Glymour, and
(c) Third, part of behavior includes the possibility Scheines (2001) and the computer scientist-
of belief in free will, which has major consequences statistician, Pearl (2000, 2009), in particular.
in how people behave (independent of the philo- Sloman (2005) and Gopnik and Schulz (2007)
sophical question of whether it exists; Baumeister, have written books extending the approach into
2008). the psychological domain. It is consistent
with the counterfactual approach to causality.
Woodward (2007) explained that counterfactual
Hot vs. Cold Causality theories in philosophy are about difference-
making and typal accounts of cause, whereas the
One way of distinguishing a passive versus active causal process approach to causation eschews the
approach to causality is to refer to the concept of general for particular or individual accounts of
50 3 Introducing Causality in Psychology

Mechanism is consistent with the present one that behavior


evolved through steps of increasing gene co-
option through individual-level natural selection,
as described below.
Given that free will is related to conscious-
ness, Young (2011) examined briefly how it
develops. Zelazo (2004; Zelazo, Carlson, &
Kesek, 2008), Carlson (2010) noted that, first,
Free Will Causal Mapping consciousness is considered minimally present,
and, then, more deliberate action develops. Next,
Fig. 3.1 Causality landscape. The three major axes in
conscious control develops, in which action is
conceptualizing the causality of behavior include mecha-
nism, causal graph modeling, and free will. The present formulated based on explicit rule systems. Berger
books builds on this model presented in Young (2011), (2011) presented a skill-based model of self-
and elaborates many more axes while considering these regulation, labeling it the self-regulatory strength
three as fundamental. Adopted with permission of
model.
Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2011).
Development and causality: Neo-Piagetian perspectives.
New York: Springer Science + Business Media; with kind
permission from Springer Science + Business Media B. V. Mechanism
[Figure 35.5, Page 835]

In the following, I review briefly the topics cov-


ered in Young (2011) that are related to mecha-
cause. In this regard, one way used in this nism. They concern the processes of epigenetics,
approach in order to support the validity of the evolution, development, hemispheric specializa-
causal sequence described is to apply “interven- tion, and nonlinear dynamics.
tions” that could alter it in predictable ways
(e.g., “graph surgery”). This type of approach is
consistent with the counterfactual or but-for Genetics/Epigenetics
argument.
Introduction The research in the area of gene–
Free Will A third locus in the study of causality environment interaction and epigenesis is
in psychology concerns free will and conscious- remarkable and is revolutionizing our under-
ness. Free will can never be proven outright, but standing of psychology and the biological influ-
on average people believe they have free will, ences on behavior. Genetic × Environment
which affects their behavior (Baumeister, 2008). (G × E) interaction research is indicating the
Baumeister maintained that we have evolved a complexities involved, such as complex interac-
form of action-control involving self-control tions involving G × E1 × E2. The research also
and rational choice, which corresponds to popu- indicates G × G and multi-gene x multi-environ-
lar notions of free will. Therefore, free will ment modeling (G × G × E × E interactions). The
involves: personal responsibility, conscious developmental pathways prescribed by how
deliberation, abstract rules and principles in these interactions unfold are neither nativist nor
guiding behavior, autonomous initiative, and empiricist. For example, in social genomics,
resisting urges. This approach reflects the active social-environmental influences (e.g., perceived
view of behavior, that we have voice or agency loneliness) can affect the immune system
in determining our behavior beyond any biolog- response, and even survival. One conclusion is
ical or environmental influences. that modern study of genetics needs to be “envi-
Baumeister et al. (2011) elaborated that free ronmentally conscious.”
will evolved to meet the demands of “enlight- Caspi et al. (2002) examined the functional
ened self-interest” in cultural context. This view polymorphism related to the promoter region of the
Critical Concepts 51

monoamine oxidase A (MAOA) gene. In particular, shaped interaction represents the traditional
they found a functional polymorphism in the gene diathesis-stress framework and is consistent with
that encodes MAOA, which is a neurotransmitter- the concept of “vulnerability” genes, whereas the
metabolizing enzyme. Their results showed that cross-over interaction graph is consistent with
the functional polymorphism moderated the effects Belsky and Pluess’s differential susceptibility
of maltreatment. Specifically, male adolescents model of genes (“plasticity genes”).
who carried the allele that conferred high levels of
MAOA expression were less likely to develop anti- Epigenetics Recent epigenetic research is con-
social behavioral problems had they been exposed firming a role for genetic polymorphisms in
to childhood maltreatment. interaction with environmental vulnerability fac-
To their credit, Belsky and Pluess (2009a, tors for behaviors that are associated with self-
2009b) noticed other major findings in the results control. Epigenetics concerns how environmental
of Caspi et al. (2002). Participants who were factors such as adversity can alter gene expres-
most susceptible genetically to adverse effects of sion, e.g., silencing them at promoter regions due
childhood maltreatment but who had not been to DNA methylation. Carver, Johnson, Joormann,
exposed to childhood maltreatment obtained Kim, and Nam (2011) found that a polymorphism
the lowest scores on the study’s measures of (s, short allele) in the promoter region of sero-
anti-social behavior. Belsky and Pluess (2009a, tonin transporter gene, 5-HTTLPR, is linked to
2009b) posited that particular alleles could measures of impulsive reactions to emotions in
heighten vulnerability to a wide range of envi- students who reported early childhood adversity
ronments. In particular, for MAOA, supportive (e.g., in care received, abuse). In a prospective
and risky environments promote positive and study, Dick et al. (2011) reported an association
negative child outcomes, respectively. Through between the gene CHRM2 (codes for the cholin-
their astute analysis, Belsky and Pluess have ergic muscarinic 2 receptor) and adolescent
developed a differential susceptibility model of externalizing behavior as measured by standard-
genes. It resembles Ellis and Boyce’s (2008) con- ized instruments, but particularly in the context
cept of biological sensitivity to context. of low parental monitoring, as measured by a
Caspi et al. (2003) presented similar results questionnaire.
for the influence of the serotonin transporter Figure 3.2 presents a model representing the
gene, 5-HTT. Individuals carrying the short concept of epigenetics in a general fashion. The
allele, relative to being homozygous for the long figure presents a model indicating how epigene-
one, were found to experience a greater influence tic effects can have either more negative or posi-
of stressful life events on depression (its symp- tive behaviorally adaptive outcomes, depending
toms and diagnosis, as well as suicidality). on individual and environmental differences. In
Caspi, Hariri, Holmes, Uher, and Moffitt epigenetics, the outcome is not necessarily nega-
(2010) indicated that there are at least four tive in cases of susceptible alleles affecting
types of evidence for the involvement of the behavioral adaptation. Belsky and Pluess (2009a,
5-HTT gene in stress sensitivity. A recent meta- 2009b) have posited that when genes are silenced
analysis supported the reliability of the research, in promoter regions involved in behavioral reac-
with strong evidence found that 5-HTTLPR tivity, the outcome could involve more resilience,
moderates the relationship between stress and and not only more behavioral difficulties, at least
depression (Karg, Shedden, Burmeister, & when the environment is supportive rather than
Sen, 2011). adverse. Moreover, the figure shows that the
effects might accentuate with development. Also,
Reaction Range Dick (2011) argued that the epigenetic changes are known to be transmitted
most appropriate manner of representing gene– over generations, creating a dynamic trajectory
environment interactions is by a “cross-over” of increased or decreased adaptation in individ-
graph rather than a “fan”-shaped graph. The fan- ual lines.
52 3 Introducing Causality in Psychology

Fig. 3.2 Environmental


action leads to increased
Higher
reaction range in gene
expression for certain
alleles. Epigenetic
c1
processes act to increase c2
reaction range, or degree
of gene-mediated
susceptibility to
environmental influence,

Trait Adaptability
and in which the
reaction can be either
adaptive or not in the c3
a b
long term. Adopted with
permission of Springer
Science + Business
Media. Young, G.
(2011). Development
and causality: Neo-
Piagetian perspectives.
New York: Springer
Science + Business
Media; with kind
permission from Lower
Springer Science +
Business Media B. V.
[Figure 30.5, Page 699] (a) Initial (b) Standard Reaction (c) Epigenetically
Reaction Range Augmented Reaction
Range
Developmental Time

Evolution is demonstrated by sterile worker castes helping


to raise offspring of the queen and creating a
Life History The life history approach to bio- colony, or a “super-organism.” The traditional
logical evolution offers a developmental pers- explanation of eusociality involves kin selection,
pective that informs the present approach which is based on the concept of inclusive fit-
(Simpson & Belsky, 2008). In this evolutionary ness. Nowak et al. argued that standard natural
model, due to competing pressures and options selection theory is sufficient to explain the evolu-
for alternate lifestyles, each developmental stage tion of eusociality, and that it is a genuine “gene-
and its prominent acquisitions have been selected centered” approach, unlike the one of inclusive
for their ongoing and immediate contribution fitness.
to survival (permitting eventual reproduction). In Novak et al.’s model, eusociality evolved in
They are not pre-adaptations that serve, in a tele- five steps. (a) First, groups formed in freely mix-
ological fashion, later adaptations, but they are ing populations. They built and occupied defen-
primed to function concurrently in the equivalent sible nests, and the behavior arose because of
of the niche in which they had evolved. “individual-level” selection. (b) In the second
phase, the groups more tightly formed. (c) Next,
Eusociality Nowak, Tarnita, and Wilson (2010) actual eusocial alleles originated, either by muta-
presented a new interpretation of the evolution of tion or recombination. (d) Most likely, the fourth
eusociality, which occurs when some individuals phase involved evolution of ecologically-
of a species reduce their own reproductive poten- adaptive behaviors related to the nest, such as
tial over their lifetime in order to raise the off- fierce defense against predators, parasites, and
spring of others. In the social insects, eusociality rival colonies. These behaviors had been shaped
Critical Concepts 53

through “natural selection by environmental the cerebral hemispheres are differentially


forces.” (e) Finally, in the fifth phase, the more specialized for inhibition. In particular, the left
advanced eusocial species evolved very special- hemisphere is considered the primary site of
ized, elaborate social systems. In contrast to the inhibitory control, specializing in a sophisticated
other steps, this one involved multilevel selection, interweaving of activation and inhibitory skills.
which includes group selection as well as natural Activation/inhibition coordination particularly
selection. It served to help drive changes in the involves the suppression of interference due to
colony behavior to more elaborate extremes. inappropriate alternative behavior, both when
selecting adaptive goal-directed activity and dur-
ing its (movement) transitions. Through this skill,
Development the left hemisphere controls the subtle, refined
sequences in both language and fine motor activi-
Stages The Neo-Piagetian stage model in Young ties. Moreover, successful unfolding of these
(2011) consists of 25 steps (5 stages × 5 sub- functions requires not only activation/inhibition
stages), and it includes parallel cognitive inter-coordination within the left hemisphere but
and socio-affective acquisitions. The stages are also activation/inhibition coordination over the
named: (a) reflexive, (b) sensorimotor, (c) periop- hemispheres.
erational (representational; preoperational and In contrast to the left hemisphere, the right
concrete operational), (d) abstract, and (e) collec- hemisphere appears specialized for less dynamic
tive intelligence. The cyclically-recurring inhibition, such as general damping of activity
substages are labeled: (a) coordination, (b) hierar- over time, or activation/inhibition coordination
chization, (c) systematization, (d) multiplication, instantaneously or for a short time period. The
and (e) integration. The corresponding 25 Neo- latter capacity would be conducive to spatial
Eriksonian steps in the model are built around the processes. In summary, the hemispheres seem to
original eight Eriksonian stages (at the second have complementary, cooperative specializations
and fourth substages of each of the last four for inhibition.
stages of the model), with 17 other steps created Vauclair and Imbault (2009) found that 10- to
to complete the sequence. 40-month-olds pointed with their right hand even
The combined Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian if they were left-handers or ambidextrous. The
model helps understand multiple areas of devel- results showed that the correlation between man-
opment. For example, Maslow’s model of a hier- ual preference and pointing preference was stron-
archy of needs consists of five levels, and Young gest during the development of vocabulary spurt
(2011) showed how they can be reworked to and the development of syntactic capacity. Their
relate to the five developmental stages of the results support the argument that, in the left cere-
present model. Other examples relate to a rework- bral hemisphere, there are dual systems for con-
ing of the concept of internal working models in trolling communicative gesture and language, on
attachment theory in terms of their development the one hand, and pure motor functions, such as
through the steps of the present model, and also object manipulation, on the other hand. According
reworking of the steps in the development of the- to Vauclair and Imbault, the left hemisphere
ory of mind and multiple intelligences in terms of expresses a hyper-mobilization during critical
the steps of the present model. periods of language acquisition because of a
“better facilitatory/inhibitory” system within the
Activation/Inhibition Coordination Young (e.g., left hemisphere. This hypothesis is quite consis-
Young, 2011; Young & Gagnon, 1990) presented tent with Young’s about the left hemisphere’s
a model of hemispheric specialization in which superior activation/inhibition coordination skills.
54 3 Introducing Causality in Psychology

Nonlinear Dynamical Systems present work concern: time, the person, control,
and nonlinear dynamical systems.
Systems theory helps understand not only the con-
tents of development, through examination of how 1. Understanding causality as an integration in
components of wholes cohere, but also its change its time line—from evolutionary time right to
mechanisms (e.g., Kauffman, 1993; Thelen & immediate neuronal firing in synaptic time.
Smith, 2006, respectively). Dynamical systems The time line stretches from millions of years
are capable of autonomously generating self- ago to nano-seconds ago. It even includes the
organizing emergent forms. Self-organization future, in terms of anticipations and expecta-
proceeds in the system’s moment-to-moment tions that guide behavior.
adaptive, contextual transitioning. In emergence, 2. Appreciating that the multiple factors involved
new system states would not be predictable can be grouped into biological, environmen-
uniquely from knowing the pre-existing state of tal, and personal (psychological) ones, and
the system in its context. New forms of the state that they interact. Causality is exquisitely con-
could be discontinuous, being very different than textual and relational; the environment is not
its preceding form-state. For example, systems an independent player acting without personal
might evolve into attractor forms. Attractors are perception/appraisal/filtering, nor is the per-
viewed as system trajectories that gravitate son able to function without the reciprocity of
repeatedly to the same attractor basins, or fixed participation in the environment. That is, cau-
values, despite their initial values or ongoing sality does not reside in the person alone nor
perturbations. his/her biology, but how the person and envi-
Systems are reworked constantly, even if in ronment reciprocally, causally influence each
equilibrium, because of perturbations. Systems other in their interaction—it is emergent in
might change abruptly, for example, at bifur- that process, and the process defines it as
cations points. Perturbations move systems to much as the product. As Young (2011) has
change state. In the butterfly effect, quite minor written, biology predisposes, the environment
inputs to the system can elicit system change disposes, but the individual composes.
because of sensitivities to initial conditions. 3. Studying causality from the perspective of con-
Lower-level interactions in systems constitute trol: ranging from determinism/unconscious
“bottom-up” processes, and higher-level interac- influences, and so on, to autonomous, free will,
tions are considered “top-down” processes. probabilistic, compatibilist approaches.
In fractals, one finds that a system is self- 4. NLDST describes emergent, self-organizing
similar across different levels. Fractal organiza- properties of systems, their top-down and bot-
tion facilitates multiple-level system change tom-up influences, and their fractal nature, in
toward complexity. In complexity theory, systems particular.
tend to hover on the edge of order and disorder,
or on the cusp of change. In this regard, systems One manner of presenting the dimensions
are considered at the edge of chaos, which is not in behavior involved in causality is offered in
chaotic at all in the colloquial sense of the word. Table 3.1. The table organizes major themes in
causality into a dimensional framework. As per
the dimensions in causality just presented, it con-
Dimensions siders the acquisition of a sense of free will as
cardinal in development (Baumeister, 2008). It
Dimensions involve continua with oppositions or indicates that (a) time can vary in the immediate
poles, and they should cover major components or longer terms (evolution, development); (b) the
of behavior for the topic of causality. In this person evolves and develops as a biopsychoso-
regard, the ones that are emphasized in the cial entity; (c) part of what develops is a sense of
Further Elaboration of the Three Major Axes in Causality Study 55

Table 3.1 Development, causality, and free will: dimensions


Area Axes Poles, components
Time Immediate Distal (before moment)
Proximal (at moment)
Development (steps, other) Normative (universal, average)
Individual (unique)
Evolution Adaptation (selective advantage)
Speciation (evolutionary tree/bush)
Person Biological Brain, hemispheres
Physiology, body, epigenetics
Social Sociocultural, general
Context, specific
Personal Cognition, appraisal
Affect, mood
Control Free will in self Free/flexible action to perceive/create/act on
choices (defined as “hot” causality)
Determined/unconscious/fixed action (“cold”
causality)
Its perception in other Same
Direction, value Positive, moral, responsible
Negative, immoral, irresponsible
Mechanism Organization Emergent, self-organizing
Random, perceived chaos
Level Macrolevel, top-down
Microlevel, bottom-up
Nonlinear dynamics Deterministic globally (in attractors)
Probabilistic in particular trajectory
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science + Business Media; with kind permission from Springer Science +
Business Media B. V. [Table 35.9, Page 835]

one’s personal control, including in liberty of inhibitory interneurons. The model includes a
action, and the perception of the same in the Hebbian layer (or of cell assemblies).
other; and (d) nonlinear dynamical system pro- The concept of activation/inhibition coordina-
cesses, such as emergence and self-organization, tion seems to apply at multiple points in causality
can help explain the mechanisms of development. study. For example, this dynamic helps to under-
Note that an overarching theme that could standing organization of both brain and behavior,
explain multiple levels of any behavioral system including in the processes that facilitate the
is activation/inhibition coordination, which could acquisition of a sense of free will.
be a common metric that could help explain mul-
tiple frames in behavior. This dynamic is appar-
ent at multiple levels of behavior and its control, Further Elaboration of the Three
from neurons and the brain to society and its Major Axes in Causality Study
agents/institutions.
In their dynamic neural field theory, Spencer, Dimensional Causality Model
Austin, and Schutte (2012) illustrated and mod-
eled the interplay of activation and inhibition in Figure 3.3 presents an integrated causality model
neurons in their dynamic neural field theory of behavior that is based on the dimensions of cau-
modeling of their functioning. Specifically, lay- sality presented in Table 3.1. The model combines
ers of excitatory neurons couple with layers of several graphic devices. Time is indicated on the
56 3 Introducing Causality in Psychology

Activation –
S
Inhibition
Y Bio -
Context
S

T Psycho -
Person a
E
b
M Social c
CONTROL

Coordination

TIME

d g

e h
f i

a = Negative, Positive Control f = Linear, Nonlinear


b = Self, Other Control g = Immediate Time
c = Free Will in Control h = Evolutionary Time
d = Random, Emergent Self-Organization i = Developmental Time
e = Micro-, Macro-level

Fig. 3.3 Dimensions in causality. The figure indicates psychosocial influences processed in context, leading to
central components to consider in modeling causality in behavioral control variations, including in the influence of
psychology. The causality system over time involves bio- free will belief

X-axis and system organization on the Y-axis. sense of having free will, and Young (2011)
Time concerns behavior in the immediate context, describes a developmental model of free will and
over developmental time, or as inherited evolu- its components based on the Neo-Piagetian stage
tionarily. Systems exist at hierarchical levels, are model that he described. The figure indicates that
either linear or nonlinear, and are either self- the dimension of free will vs. unconsciousness can
organized or random, with emergence associated be applied positively or negatively, and to the per-
with the former. The person behaving in context ception of the self or the other.
is illustrated in the concentric circle model. The construct of activation/inhibition coor-
The components of the biopsychosocial complex dination is highlighted as surrounding the
(interaction of biology, personal psychology, person and context. Young (2011) proposed that
sociocultural factors) influence behavior, as indi- activation/inhibition coordination characterizes
cated by the arrows leading from the components both elements of the person and context. For
to the person-in-context representation. example, for the person, both the brain and
The central focus of the outcome of the model behavior can be described in terms of the ebb and
is control, and it emphasizes that control concerns flow of activation and inhibition and their coordi-
having a sense of free will. Baumeister (2008) has nation. Similarly, the environment presents to the
described the psychological components that con- person as the waxing and waning of activations
tribute to the development and maintenance of a and inhibitions in relationship.
Further Elaboration of the Three Major Axes in Causality Study 57

In this regard, control processes, being the The Causality Landscape


focus output of the person in the figure, are also
considered the effect of activation/inhibition Introduction
coordination. Ideally, in this regard, the person For the most part, the three major topics in the
activates positives capacities, such as good will, study of causality in psychology being discussed
sense of responsibilities, moral imperatives, (causal mapping/learning, mechanism, free will)
psychological maturity, rational thinking, creat- are studied separately. Causality is studied from
ing and thinking through options, choosing quite different perspectives and needs an inte-
effectively from among them, and so on, associ- grating landscape. Developing a causality land-
ated with optimally mature human activity. scape requires steps toward developing an
Simultaneously, the person inhibits interfering integrative model.
tendencies, temptations, search for immediate Figure 3.4 lists other axes in its study of cau-
gratification, short term but ineffective solutions, sality beyond the three core ones. The central
irrational thinking, irresponsible behavior, and triangular portion of the figure indicates that
immature and immoral behavior, so that planned, the study of causal learning/mapping, mecha-
directed, and free will guided behavioral output nism, and free will stand as the major axes in
obtains. the area.

Mechanism

Psychology
Scientific Explanation
Psychopathology
Statistics

Systems Psychotherapy

Law/ Forensics Biopsychosocial


Philosophy Social Science Model
Michottian Collisions Science
(Perceptual Learning) Development

Monism/ Dualism Causal Learning


((Non) Consciousness)

Causal Mapping
Free Will Life and
Biology/ Evolution Physical Sciences Physics/ Chemistry

Genetics/ Epigenetics Neuroscience

Medicine/ Medical Model Epidemiology

Fig. 3.4 Causality landscape: causality axes coming approach would keep these axes as fundamental, but
together. Note. Aside from all the areas mentiond, this include others. The present book elaborates many of the
figure from Young (2014) also could mention, among varying degrees of study mentioned in the figure, seeking
others, the disciplines of ecology, engineering, political an integrated framework for the study of the causality of
science, sociology, and history, and the notion of inter- behavior. It considers free will as the apex of behavioral
disciplinary. The three major axes in conceptualizing causation, in the sense that we develop to the degree pos-
causality concern (a) elaboration of causal maps and sible to arrive at making self-determined free choices
learning using Bayesian probabilities and counterfactual among the behavioral options in any one situation, while
argumentation, (b) as well as mechanisms, such as in escaping the deterministic influences of biology and
development, and (c) free will. A more integrative environment. Adapted from Young (2014)
58 3 Introducing Causality in Psychology

The figure includes 24 components or areas in of disease to include a biopsychosocial model, in


the study of causality and causation related to which multiple factors interact [although in
psychology and related disciplines. medicine, traditional approaches still have
much influence, as in the DSM (Diagnostic and
Model Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders) and
The discipline of science is placed at the center of RDoC (Research Domain Criteria) projects]. In
the figure, in that science stands as the umbrella many ways, the new field of psychiatric genetics
discipline for all the other areas in terms of the is leading the way in studying the causality of
study of causality and causation. Other areas of behavior, as with the concepts of gene by envi-
science consider and investigate causality (e.g., ronment interactions and epigenetics. In epigen-
the social sciences, the life sciences, and the esis, environmental factors can help “silence”
physical sciences), and often have concepts and genes involved in the regulation of behavior, and
models similar to those in psychology (e.g., the the effects can be transmitted intergenerationally.
value of experimentation, statistics). The roots of The study of evolution also is undergoing change,
the study of causality lie in classical Greek philo- in that group selection is now considered a com-
sophical theories, especially that of Aristotle and plementary process to natural selection.
his concept of four types of causes. Implicit in The field of epidemiology is another one
one of them resides the notion that mechanism is studying causality and causation from disparate
critical to understanding cause. Mechanism lies perspectives. Hill’s criteria help, but statistical
at the heart of any scientific explanation of cause, and causal mapping approaches are becoming
and it typically takes the form of—some combi- important. Causal mapping includes not only
nation of genetic and environmental contribu- mapping graphical causal linkages in events and
tions at the distal level; brain and networks at the their effects but also mapping the altered out-
intermediate level; and factors such as stimuli, comes that arise after interventions. When stud-
stress, and situation at the proximal level, but ied developmentally, interesting experiments
within a transactional model that includes indi- reveal that 2- to 3-year-olds and even infants
vidual differences in perceptions, or appraisal of appreciate (perceive) causality and engage in
the input involved. causal learning. Causal perception has a storied
Psychological and philosophical models [for past in the research of Michotte. A systems per-
example, the counterfactual model] consider that spective of causality and causation offers a trans-
causes are evident by the changes effected by the disciplinary approach that might help simplify
event at issue and the corresponding realization the plethora of concepts and approaches in the
that, absent the event, there would be none of field. The study of the brain is being marked
changes in state that had transpired. This argu- increasingly by systems concepts, such as
ment takes the form of the “but-for” test in law networks, and the subfield of Connectomes is
(e.g., “but for the accident, the patient would not emerging rapidly in neuroscience in this regard.
be expressing…”). Both the philosophical and The concepts of causality and causation are cen-
psychological approaches to causality include an tral to the areas of psychopathology and psycho-
interventionist component in some ways, as therapy, through the associated concept of
in experimentation. However, the study of cau- etiology. There are controversies in the field,
sality is not restricted to such accounts and and the most significant relate to free will, and
procedures. the (un)consciousness, and their link to action.
Some models in the field of causality are quite Libet’s research, which showed an unconscious
restricted in scope, as in the medical model. The preparation of movement before it takes place
field of medicine takes a classic biological, phys- and before the person expresses an intention to
iological, and reductionist approach to physical move, leads to question about free will. However,
disease and mental health. However, psychiatry Baumeister and others maintain that although we
and psychology are expanding its understanding can never ascertain truly whether behavior is
Free Will 59

genuinely free or deterministic, there are important much as any other factor. (c) Behaving as if we
consequences in believing that one has free will were free, toward being free, and in being free
relative to those who do not. The study of indi- characterizes the human will and the human way.
vidual differences in belief in free will is increas- This is referred to as “free being.” (d) Free will is
ing. The field needs more integrative models of neither free nor will. It is hard-earned rather than
causality and causation in psychology and related being “free” and it more than will. Rather, will
disciplines. provides the starting point for the behavior at
issue, but it is up to us to implement it. (e) We
Comment never reach full free will in the sense of belief
Clearly, the study of causality in psychology and and sense. However, we can keep moving in that
related sciences is expanding rapidly, but without direction. Integration along these lines is as much
a cohering framework. Like in the model of the a path as a state. (f) Not having free will is an
inflationary expansion of the universe, the dispa- illusion. Most people believe it and act as if they
rate areas in its study risk losing contact with feel free. (g) Free being is as much cultural, col-
each other and working in their separate clusters lective, and interpersonal as it is individual, inte-
of study. The present book attempts to provide rior, and intrapersonal.
coherence to the field in this regard, but still with In short, as we grow in and toward psycho-
the three axes that are highlighted in the book as logical maturity, experiencing being free or hav-
a central focus in this pursuit. ing a free being is facilitated. In turn, this helps to
As for expanding these three axes in the pres- be free in all phases of behavior, from selecting
ent chapter, for each I take a broader view. (a) For input, creating and choosing from options, decid-
free will, I consider the integrative concept of ing, and acting upon decisions.
Freedom in Being. (b) For mechanism, I discuss There are both cognitive and social affective
causal modeling in terms of thermodynamics. components of free being, which are termed free
(c) For causal graph modeling, I present a good will belief and having a sense of free will. These
introduction in the work of Sloman (2005). components exist in dynamic relation and consti-
tute an integrated, inseparable whole. Free being
grows asymptotically to full freedom, but rarely
Free Will gets there, given the constraints on and limita-
tions in the development of each of us. In this
Concept sense, the model is an asymptotic one. It is also
paradoxical in the sense that, as we grow toward
In my view, free will is a psychological phenome- and into free being, we inevitably opt to choose
non that does not manifest universally but is con- to undertake responsibilities, which acts to con-
ditional on reducing control of, and eliminating, strain being free in the more primitive sense of
constraints to its constitutive application. As a cor- acting with freedom on anything we wish to do.
ollary, then, free will (or being) is exquisitely indi-
vidual and varies with not only psychological
immaturity but also with developmental prog- Comment
ression and adaptation, motivation and emotion,
energy and effort, temperament and personality, The general message for the causality of behav-
rationality and reflectivity, self-control and self- ior is that free will is an emergent force that ends
regulation, context and constraint, opportunity and up participating in defining our essence and also
invitation, openness and possibility, and so on. in defining the causes of our behavior through its
The basic premises of the present work are the position at the apex of maturity in behavior. It
following that (a) we have an active, causal say in could be involved, as well, when behavior goes
our behavior beyond the influences of biology awry in disturbances and abnormality in behav-
and environment. (b) We cause our behavior as ior, for example, in addictions.
60 3 Introducing Causality in Psychology

Biopersonalsocial (Biopsychosocial) Causality

Biology (Genes, Brain, etc.) Personal/ Self Environment


(Psychology) (SocioCultural)

Freedom in Being

Free Will Being in the World

Free Will Belief Having a Sense of


Free Will

Fig. 3.5 Freedom in being as central to the causality of Freedom in Being stands at the apex of the suite of concepts
psychology. Free will is constituted by a cognitive compo- on free will. Free will is an essential component of the per-
nent and by an affective component (free will belief, sense sonal, self-determined psychological forces in the causality
of free will, respectively). Freedom of being is a superordi- of behavior, which are part of the multifactorial biopsycho-
nate concept that includes free will and being in the world. social (biopersonalsocial) influences on behavior

Freedom in Being causality of behavior. In this regard, consider


modeling causality with both (a) a vertical axis in
Figure 3.5 clarifies the relationship of free will to which there are multiple interacting components
the overall perspective of the present work. It that have more or less equal effect and (b) a hori-
indicates that behavioral causality should be con- zontal axis for which each of the multifactorial
sidered as influenced by biopsychosocial (bioper- components has a series of increasing complex
sonalsocial) factors, and that free will is a critical levels. Therefore, on the one hand, behavioral
aspect of the psychological (personal) compo- causality concerns a broad array of interacting
nent of the model, through the concept of factors, as in the biopsychosocial model. On the
Freedom in Being. In addition, the figure incor- other hand, each of these factors is constituted by
porates Heidegger’s concept of Dasein, or being both simpler and more complex processes. The
in the world (Heidegger, 1927/1962), which is more complex ones might be emergent, or deriv-
the root of the concept of freedom of being as ing from lower-order levels in a way that is more
used in the present work. That is, Freedom in than additive and reductionistic. Figure 3.6 illus-
Being should be considered as deriving from and trates a model in this regard that considers the
being encapsulated in participatory, dialogic, co- place of free will in a broad behavioral causality
actional, constitutive relations in the world. system-type model.
The figure indicates that not only free will but
also other important components involving free-
Biopsychosocial Causality dom stand at the apex of the biological, psycho-
logical (personal), and social influences on
A systems approach would seem beneficial for behavior. Freedom in being implies not only a
viewing the broad, multifactorial perspective psychological maturity that actively drives
involved in how free will participates in the behavior but also a brain free of more passive
Mechanism 61

TOP DOWN

Freeing the Freedom in Freedom from


Brain Being the Environment

Hierarchy in
Biopsycho- Psychological
social Factor Biological (Personal, Self) Social (Cultural)
Complexity

Agent
Genes Processing Stimuli

BOTTOM UP

Biopsychosocial Factor Array

Fig. 3.6 Biopsychosocial causality: a broad vertical/ related to free will and freedom. Behavioral causality is
horizontal systems model. The figure models causality in much more than reaction to lower-order levels in the vari-
behavior to vary (a) horizontally in terms of its multifac- ous interactive causal forces on behavior, such as genes
torial (biopsychosocial, biopersonalsocial) influences and and stimuli producing passive response. Rather, behavior
(b) vertically in terms of the hierarchical arrangement of is actively emergent in a system, with self forces involved
its different levels of complexity. At the apex of all three psychologically as causal factors
major causal influences on behavior stand constructs

influences, such as physiological and environ- of their components and their interacting
mental ones, and an environment that is not in relationships but also in terms of the factors that
active of the person; rather, the person has devel- promote state changes in their configurations.
oped to the point of expressing freedom from The latter provide impetus to change, depending
capture by the environment. on their degree of distance from equilibrium (and
In the following, I turn to expanding descrip- also depending on how the system handles
tion of mechanism in behavioral causation. After incoming energy, information. See Fig. 3.7).
that, I extend work on causal graph modeling, the In my approach to mechanism in the present
third of the three major axes on causality in the work, I try to avoid reductionistic, biology-based
present work. conceptualizations that are only lower-level in
complexity. For example, a reductionistic expla-
nation of having cancer might dismiss smoking
Mechanism as a cause, and also societal influences encourag-
ing smoking, and only seek physiological change
Model mechanisms coupled with genetic risk ones.
However, a hierarchical, multilevel conceptual-
Introduction In the next part of this chapter, I ization of causality in behavior would recognize
show how a vertical–horizontal systems perspec- that both lower-order and higher-order levels
tive, as presented in Fig. 3.7, can help understand arranged in a hierarchical model help explain the
the mechanism component to causality. Mecha- link between smoking and lung cancer. Moreover,
nism relates to causality through the specific by acknowledging a biopsychosocial model even
causal processes that it describes for the products for cancer, and that mechanism can reside in any
of the system. Systems can be defined in terms of the components of the biopsychosocial model,
62 3 Introducing Causality in Psychology

TOP DOWN

Resilience-Risk/ Mediators (Direct)/


Vulnerabilities Moderators (Indirect) Trigger

Hierarchy in
Temporal
Factor Distal Proximal Immediate
Complexity

Agent
Genes Processing Stimuli

BOTTOM UP

Temporal Factor Array

Fig. 3.7 Temporal behavioral causality: a broad vertical/ of behavior, nor are immediate triggers that apparently pre-
horizontal systems model. Temporality in the causality of cede it. Instead, more inclusively, there are higher-order
behavior does not proceed simply at the basic level from factors in behavioral causation, including mediators com-
stimulus to response, or from genes leading to agent pro- ing from the person him- or herself, that are more active,
cessing passively and then to outcome. That is, distal and dynamic, emergent, and altering of all other causal factors
proximal influences on behavior are not fully deterministic in behavior and the temporal sequences that precede it

then mechanism cannot be considered either Conclusion In the end, when examining the
reductionisticly, linearly from genes upward to temporality of causal factors in behavior, seq-
behavior, or unifactorially. uences are never what they seem because they
are embedded in larger systems in which they
Model In this regard, I constructed a hierarchi- function. A birds-eye view of causality focuses
cal horizontal/vertical model of causality related too strictly on sequences, apparent cause and
to temporality of putative cause and effect. effect, and so on. But a wider eagle-eye view will
Events, situations, triggers, and stimuli do not see that causality does not lie in any one level, in
automatically lead to responses, behavior, and any one mechanism, in any one cause–effect
outcome. The agent processing the incoming sequence, and so on. Rather, causality lies in the
material does not perceive it passively but rather, whole behavioral system. In this sense, the com-
adds an adaptive filtration, an anticipation, a ponent of free will belief (and associated free will
future-oriented element, and so on. Often, in factors) has an equal if not superordinate role to
human behavior, one thinks of agent as a passive play in behavioral causality.
perceptual system and a brain reacting passively In the following, I look at mechanism from the
to the impact of the environment. However, the perspective of the widest system possible, that of
person has a say in her or his psychology even at the universe. Chaisson (2010, 2011) describes
this level. The environment does not just exist at Big History in terms of the origins of behavior
a lower level in terms of its physical, quantita- since the Big Bang. He emerges with a model
tive properties in how it impacts the person. that integrates living and non-living systems,
Rather, at a higher level, the person serves as a which is a goal of the present work, as well.
qualitative, active intermediary between envi- Perhaps his work will lead to a Big Psychology
ronment and behavior. perspective.
Mapping 63

Big History the competition of natural selection, as well as its


reproductive success.
Introduction Chaisson (2010, 2011) has pre- Chaisson (2010) explained that at critical
sented a model of Big History that is mechanism- energies or thresholds, after departure from equi-
driven in terms of energy, evolution, and culture, librium, when there is availability of optimal
in particular. The search for mechanism is basic energy, systems can draw the power of the energy
to the present work. to construct structures or functions needed to
adaptively “engage” the energies. If they cannot,
Model Chaisson’s (2010, 2011) model unifies they risk deterioration, destruction, or loss in
evolutionary causation of diverse natural phe- competition. In this sense, the most successful
nomena in the physical, biological, and cultural regimes remain dynamic steady states after
realms. He begins with cosmic evolution and energy influx, and they have the capacity to cre-
ends with contemporary phenomena, such as ate the pathways needed to arrive at equilibrium,
computers. Whatever the realm, he perceives with other options selected out.
them as products of energy rate density, which is
a complexity metric, or an evolutionary “driver.” Conclusion Chaisson (2010) concluded that
In this regard, the concept of energy rate density energy flow is a universal process in evolution,
has more general applicability toward unifying from the Big Bang to galaxies to humans, and
evolutionary causation compared to other con- it can be represented in the way indicated.
cepts, such as those based on information or Ultimately, appropriate energy flow helps to con-
entropy. Energy rate density is a mass-normalized trol a system’s dissipation to disorder (in entropy).
(free) energy flow, represented by Φm. It helps construct increasingly ordered, localized
Chaisson (2010, 2011) considered “indisput- systems having to deal with the increasingly dis-
able” that, on a grand scale, in the course of evo- ordered wider environment.
lution, complexity inexorably increases. Energy Chaisson (2011) added that culture has acceler-
flow provides the basis for establishing a unifying ated human evolution, taking it beyond the results
metric across all complex living and nonliving of Darwinian natural selection. Culture functions
systems, helping to explain their origin, mainte- in accompanying the effects of natural selection
nance, and complexification. Generally, whether with its own intergenerational adaptive transmis-
living or nonliving, complex systems are open, sions, bringing it into the realms of Lamarckian
ordered, nonequilibrated entities in which energy processes. Chaisson qualified that natural selec-
is important. In complex systems, energy is tion and cultural selection are processes that are
acquired, stored, and expressed in the systems. reciprocally interrelated as adjacent evolutionary
According to Chaisson, natural selection influences. The products of culture help deal with
works in tandem with energy evolution as bio- the limitations in the environment impeding evo-
logical systems evolve. Life forms are open to lution by selection. Humans are even capable of
resource flow exchange and, from a systems challenging the environment. Through its innova-
point of view, are selected partly for their capac- tions, human culture can work in tandem with
ity to “command” energy. Systems adapt more energy to catalyze human evolution.
effectively if they undertake the latter. If not, they
are selected out. Moreover, energy appears to
“drive” systems beyond equilibrium. If advanta- Mapping
geously adaptive, the emergent, more complex
forms that are constructed in the process are Model
selected. That is, the capacity of a system to reach
normalized energy flow (in terms of managing According to Sloman (2005), the study of cau-
the increased energy flow after system perturba- sality is important from a psychological point of
tion per unit mass) indicates its survivability in view because we are agents who have goals and
64 3 Introducing Causality in Psychology

B D E

D1 F

A = Causal Mapping/ Learning D = Integrating Causality Areas

B = Mechanisms (Biopsychosocial) E = Causality Centralizing in Sciences

C = Free Will/ Consciousness F = Causality Centralizing in Psychology

D1=Causality Study, General

Fig. 3.8 A causal Bayes network. The figure indicates duty because it uses the causal Bayes network or causal
how different areas in the study of causality and causation mapping/graphing approach to illustrate the area of study
in psychology need to coalesce toward an integrated sci- of causality. For examples with specific event sequences,
ence of causality in which causality is promoted as its cen- see Sloman (2005)
tral construct. At the same time, the figure serves double

act as if we have free will. Moreover, under- effects would follow had the causes been
standing causation is central in trying to under- different or absent). Therefore, agency involves
stand the world. Agency refers to the ability to thinking about how things might be otherwise
intervene on the environment and change it, should the correct intervention be implemented,
beyond anything it might mean with respect to or about representing interventions, both real
consciousness and intentionality. Moreover, and imagined (see Fig. 3.8).
people attempt to represent their ability to act on Sloman (2005) continued that understanding
the world and change it. Often, knowledge that of causal systems depends on our cognition, or
we acquire is about causal mechanisms that construals. We construct causal frames in order to
bring about effects, or their “why.” Moreover, help understand the mechanisms that have pro-
causal knowledge includes statements about duced the world as we know it and how it might
counterfactuals (belief statements about possi- be otherwise in different circumstances and with
bilities other than the one of concern; which different mechanisms.
Mapping 65

The approach of developing causal maps Model


based on Bayesian networks is consistent with
this approach to causality, because it allows us to Sloman (2005) proceeded to explain the relation-
represent in graphical form both real and imag- ship between causal relations and mechanisms.
ined actions and their effects. Moreover, they For him, cause involves “change over time” and
speak to the diversity of causal relations, whether causal relations are “enacted” over time. Causal
probabilistic or deterministic, necessary or suffi- relations imply that a mechanism “unfolds” over
cient, weak or strong, direct or indirect, or actual time to produce an effect, “using” the cause.
or background. Time could be immediate (e.g., a shadow is cre-
Causal models, maps, or networks are created ated) or extensive (e.g., the continually inflating
to represent causal relations found in invariants universe since the Big Bang). Therefore, mecha-
in information. Individuals establish invariants in nisms are any type of “process” that “takes”
the world by using psychological capacities, such causes to produce effects. Mechanisms are at a
as selective attention. Indeed, the critical focus of lower level in the hierarchy of a system compared
reasoning and learning relates to the invariance to principles that might govern it. Nevertheless,
of causal structure. Sloman maintained that the most valuable appraisals that we can make
causal relations function or hold “across space, are about mechanisms.
time, and individuals” (italics mine, added Experiments are good ways of establishing
for emphasis; p. 20). Consistent with this line of cause, because potential causes (independent
argument, Sloman continued that the logic of variables) are manipulated to determine potential
causality is the guide that people use for predic- effects (on independent variables). Correlations
tion, explanation, and action, and that “people cannot establish causation because, at best, they
are designed to learn and to reason with causal describe associations and cannot specify counter-
models” (p. 20). factuals, or possible worlds, which experiments,
in particular, can help ascertain.

Comment
Comment
Note that I agree with Sloman that seeking and
understanding causality is central to everything I would add that, although cause involves change,
that we do, think, [and emote]. However, I would as Sloman emphasized, cause could also involve
argue that individual selective attention, percep- stability without change in a system. Each
tion, understanding, interpretation, prediction, moment in the life of a system brings the possi-
and control are crucial elements of the individu- bility of change, but often the system gravitates
al’s appraisal of context and world. Appraisal is to stability and keeps its equilibrium. Moreover,
individual and personal and is involved in estab- this might happen even if the system is far from
lishing informational invariants for the person equilibrium and even if a perturbation of the sys-
alone; they are not universal causal structures tem is major. Systems have conserving as well
that cut across individuals. That is, we construct as change tendencies. This being said, even the
our world individually at each moment, and maintenance of stability can be viewed as change,
although we are influenced by cultural norms in because the inputs into the system and its contex-
these regards, as well as our past constructions, tual ground change unceasingly overt time, but
each moment is uniquely created and highly indi- the whole that is the system and its surround pre-
vidual, and greatly related to the immediate and serves a constancy despite the erstwhile changes
individual adaptation needed in the world. in the surround and the inputs into it.
66 3 Introducing Causality in Psychology

Model causal relations forward in time, and not back.


Moreover, once we graph a causal model, we can
Sloman (2005) continued that causes could be act on it, intervene, or conduct a “do” operation
enabling or disabling, and he added that, in a on it (conduct “graphic surgery”; Pearl, 2009).
certain sense, everything can be a cause. Events These types of graphic modeling concern creat-
could have alternate causes that can act together ing imagined outcomes as interventional proba-
or separately (conjunctively or disjunctively). bilities rather than conditional ones (e.g., the
They can create chains of causal links. Each link counterfactual: “If we eliminate the peptic ulcer,
is local, autonomous, and stable. The nature what is the probability of gut pain?”). In conclu-
of the links is subject to the counterfactual sion, for Sloman, the power of the causal model-
argument—links are considered part of the chain ing framework lies in its synergy of causal links,
when it can be established that had they not mechanisms, and interventions [and I would
occurred, other links and the ultimate effect at add—the counterfactual reasoning and imagi-
issue would not have occurred. nary actions that it permits].
In terms of probabilities that are central to the
causal modeling framework, Sloman indicated
that patterns of probability involving dependence Comment
and independence derive from particular causal
structures. Causal structures can be inferred from Danks (2014) proposed that causal graph model-
dependencies based on two assumptions. In the ing can be used as a common framework for
causal Markov condition, the direct causes of a understanding and reinterpreting many areas of
variable, or its “parents,” render the variable cognition (not only causal learning). He described
“probabilistically independent of” or “screened his approach as one that affords a unified under-
off” from other variables, such as indirect ones standing of mind.
[except for its effects], at least when the “parent” Danks (2014) makes the bold statement that
values are “fixed.” The second assumption is that his version of representations of graphical mod-
of stability or “faithfulness,” which specifies that els actually represents how we think and navigate
probabilistic independencies in a data set are due the world successfully. Different cognitions have
to causal structure and not due to chance or coin- a seamless, common store of cognitive represen-
cidence. Or, independence in a system is neither tations that are structured as representational
due to chance nor is incidental, because it arises graphic models. His concept reduces the impor-
in the absence of causal relatedness. tance of modular domains in cognition and helps
Of course, the task becomes to specify all explain its flexibility, that which permits “free-
relevant variables such that there is no error or ranging” cognition. Different cognitive domains
chance that can be invoked in establishing cause. vary in the “operations” they conduct on the core
Theoretically, this is possible—prediction is models. [Not all domains can be graphed this
deterministically-based in systems under the way, though, e.g., perceptual causation.]
assumption that all relevant variables and param- Not only does each of us have a common rep-
eters can be specified. Practically, “noise” is part resentational graphical model, which can differ-
and parcel of any system under real-world inves- entiate to for different domains but also our
tigation. Our powers at specifying the full range shared cognitive representations are structured
of variables and parameters in a system often are this way.
limited, at best, to all major ones.
Sloman indicated this by noting that when we
cannot identify a unique causal structure, we can Conclusion
still limit the set of possible causal structures.
Causal networks are constructed as best fits to the The causal graph modeling approach (Pearl,
data, and their arrows are acyclic, characterizing 2000, 2009) is an influential one in psychology.
Mapping 67

Its concept of interventions and “graph surgery” different causal graphing models into a framework
as indicative of causal relations is an important according to their complexity and focus.
one. (a) However, it is not the only graphical NLDST graphs phenomena in terms of attrac-
model that has gained currency in psychology. tors, which can shift in basins according to both
For example, network modeling is increasing in internal dynamics (e.g., tension due to far-from-
scope and has found application in research in equilibrium state) and external ones (e.g., even
psychology and beyond (neuroscience; see Chap. minor perturbations can produce chaotic effects).
7). (b) Also, at the clinical level, Haynes, O’Brien, I refer to these various models as top-down
and Kaholokula (2011) described functional ana- or bottom-up, depending on whether system
lytic clinical case diagrams that are perceptive parameters can influence their behavior (top-
(see Chap. 6). I refer to my own network model down) or whether the behavior of the elements
as an Integrative Cross-Network one (see Chap. creates patterns that exert relatively minor
29). A complementary perspective in graphical influence relative to the component activity
modeling of behavior involves NLDST, which I themselves. In this sense, NLDST belongs
described in depth in Young (2011) and to which with casual graph modeling theory as higher-
refer to quite often in the present work (e.g., order top-down ones, along with my cross-net-
about emergence). Figure 3.9 organizes these work model.

TOP DOWN

Causal Graph Nonlinear


Complexity of Mapping Approach

(Bayesian) Dynamical Cross-Network


Modeling Systems

Distal Proximal Immediate

Brain Behavior
FACCD
(Connectome) (Symptom)
BOTTOM UP Networks Network

Focus of Mapping Approach

FACCD = Functional Analytic Clinical Case Diagram

Fig. 3.9 Conceptual flow map of causal mapping perspective (including on development) in understanding
approaches. Network approaches to causal model are bur- causality. Other mapping approaches to causality vary in
geoning. They have been applied to the brain (Connectome; whether they tackle lower-order or higher-order system
Sporns, 2011, 2012) and symptoms (Borsboom & Cramer, organization. For example, FACCD (Haynes et al., 2011)
2014; McNally et al., 2015). They are concerned more are about patient patterns and constitute a lower-order
with proximal/immediate causal antecedents rather approach while DAGs (Directed Acyclic Graphs)/causal
than distal ones. The proposed integrated cross-network graph modeling (e.g., Pearl, 2000, 2009) are more generic
approach (see Chap. 29) takes a broader network and constitute a higher-order one
68 3 Introducing Causality in Psychology

Chapter Conclusions References

In particular, the present chapter examines criti- Baumeister, R. F. (2008). Free will in scientific psy-
chology. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 3,
cal terms in the field and describes the three
14–19.
axes in the study of causality (causal mapping/ Baumeister, R. F., Crescioni, A. W., & Alquist, J. L.
learning, mechanisms, free will) that were (2011). Free will as advanced action control for human
emphasized in Young (2011). Then, it presents social life and culture. Neuroethics, 4, 1–11.
Beebee, H., Hitchcock, C., & Menzies, P. (2009). The
integrative models that expand the focus of
Oxford handbook of causation. New York: Oxford
behavioral causality study, yet still emphasizes University Press.
these three areas as central to understanding Belsky, J., & Pluess, M. (2009a). Beyond diathesis stress:
behavioral causality. Differential susceptibility to environmental influences.
Psychological Bulletin, 135, 885–908.
Causality is an increasing focus in some
Belsky, J., & Pluess, M. (2009b). The nature (and nur-
aspects of psychology (for example, in psycho- ture?) of plasticity in early human development.
logical injury and law; Young, 2008, 2014, 2015). Perspectives on Psychological Science, 4, 345–351.
Also, for training in psychology, Layne et al. Berger, A. (2011). Self-regulation: Brain, cognition, and
development. Washington: American Psychological
(2014) has recommended that it takes a more
Association.
central stage. However, in psychology, in gen- Borsboom, D., & Cramer, A. O. J. (2014). Network analy-
eral, causality is more of a background consider- sis: An integrative approach to the structure of psycho-
ation rather than a key focus. pathology. Annual Review of Clinical Psychology, 9,
91–121.
The chapter illustrates the general approach of
Carlson, S. M. (2010). Development of conscious control
the present book to consider (a) causality as cen- and imagination. In R. F. Baumeister, A. R. Mele, &
tral to the study of behavior and (b) free will and K. D. Vohs (Eds.), Free will and consciousness: How
related aspects as an important component in the might they work? (pp. 135–152). New York: Oxford
University Press.
causality of behavior. As with all behavior, indi-
Carver, C. S., Johnson, S. L., Joormann, J., Kim, Y., &
vidual differences are critical in the expression of Nam, J. Y. (2011). Serotonin transporter polymor-
causality-related behavior, such as happens with phism interacts with childhood adversity to predict
free will belief. In this regard, despite general aspects of impulsivity. Psychological Science, 22,
589–595.
models related to universally present factors, the
Caspi, A., Hariri, A. R., Holmes, A., Uher, R., & Moffitt,
causality of behavior never expresses itself uni- T. E. (2010). Genetic sensitivity to the environment:
versally in the same way for everyone, so that it The case of the serotonin transporter gene and its
is marked normatively by extensive individual implications for studying complex diseases and
traits. American Journal of Psychiatry, 167,
differences.
509–527.
Key terms introduced in the chapter related to Caspi, A., McClay, J., Moffitt, T. E., Mill, J., Martin, J.,
causality include systems, emergence, mechanisms, Craig, I. W., Taylor, A., & Poulton, R. (2002). Role of
free will, causal mapping/learning, control, dim- genotype in the cycle of violence in maltreated chil-
dren. Science, 297, 851–854.
ensions, and activation/inhibition coordination,
Caspi, A., Sugden, K., Moffitt, T. E., Taylor, A., Craig,
as well as the areas of development, genetics, I. W., Harrington, H., et al. (2003). Influence of life
evolution, and the brain. The remainder of the stress on depression: Moderation by a polymorphism
present book expands on these concepts and in the 5-HTT gene. Science, 301, 386–389.
Chaisson, E. J. (2010). Energy rate density as a complex-
areas, while introducing others as it progresses.
ity metric and evolutionary driver. Complexity, 16,
Causality can stand as the central unifying con- 27–40.
struct in psychology, and the book’s extensive Chaisson, E. J. (2011). Energy rate density. II. Probing
study of it and effort to integrate it are dedicated further a new complexity metric. Complexity, 17,
44–63.
to that proposition.
References 69

Cocchiarella, L., & Lord, S. J. (Eds.). (2001). Master the Illari, F. Russo, & J. Williamson (Eds.), Causality
AMA guides fifth (5th ed., pp. 327–341). Chicago: in the sciences (pp. 240–269). New York: Oxford
American Medical Association. University Press.
Danks, D. (2014). Unifying the mind: Cognitive represen- McNally, R. J., Robinaugh, D. J., Wu, G. W. Y., Wang, L.,
tations as graphical models. Cambridge, MA: The Deserno, M. K., & Borsboom, D. (2015). Mental dis-
MIT Press. orders as causal systems: A network approach to post-
Dick, D. M. (2011). Gene-environment interaction in traumatic stress disorder. Clinical Psychological
psychological traits and disorders. Annual Review of Science 3, 836–849.
Clinical Psychology, 7, 383–409. Nowak, M. A., Tarnita, C. E., & Wilson, E. O. (2010). The
Dick, D. M., Meyers, J. L., Latendresse, S. J., Creemers, evolution of eusociality. Nature, 466, 1057–1062.
H. E., Lansford, J. E., Pettit, G. S., et al. (2011). Pearl, J. (2000). Causality: Models, reasoning, and infer-
CHRM2, parental monitoring, and adolescent exter- ence. New York: Cambridge University Press.
nalizing behavior: Evidence for gene-environment Pearl, J. (2009). Causality: Models, reasoning, and infer-
interaction. Psychological Science, 22, 481–489. ence (2nd ed.). New York: Cambridge University
Douglas, K. S., Huss, M. T., Murdoch, L. L., Washington, Press.
D. O., & Koch, W. J. (1999). Posttraumatic stress dis- Russo, F. (2009). Causality and causal modeling in the
order stemming from motor vehicle accidents: Legal social sciences: Measuring variations. New York:
issues in Canada and the United States. In E. J. Springer Science + Business Media.
Hickling & E. B. Blanchard (Eds.), The international Shrout, P. E., Keyes, K. M., & Ornstein, K. (Eds.). (2011).
handbook of road traffic accidents and psychological Causality and psychopathology: Finding the determi-
trauma: Current understanding, treatment and law nants of disorders and their cures. New York: Oxford
(pp. 271–289). New York: Elsevier. University Press.
Ellis, B. J., & Boyce, W. T. (2008). Biological sensitivity Simpson, J. A., & Belsky, J. (2008). Attachment theory
to context. Current Directions in Psychological within a modern evolutionary framework. In J. Cassidy
Science, 17, 183–187. & P. R. Shaver (Eds.), Handbook of attachment:
Garner, B. A. (Ed.). (2009). Black’s law dictionary (9th Theory, research, and clinical applications (pp. 131–
ed.). St. Paul, MN: West. 157). New York: Guilford Press.
Gopnik, A., & Schulz, L. (2007). Causal learning: Sloman, S. (2005). Causal models: How people think
Psychology, philosophy, and computation. New York: about the world and its alternatives. New York:
Oxford University Press. Oxford University Press.
Haynes, S. N., O’Brien, W. H., & Kaholokula, J. K. Spencer, J. P., Austin, A., & Schutte, A. R. (2012).
(2011). Behavioral assessment and case formulation. Contributions of dynamic systems theory to cognitive
Hoboken, NJ: Wiley. development. Cognitive Development, 27, 401–418.
Heidegger, M. (1927/1962). Being in time. London, UK: Spirtes, P., Glymour, C., & Scheines, R. (2001). Causation,
SCM. prediction, and search. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Illari, P. M., Russo, F., & Williamson, J. (Eds.). (2011a). Sporns, O. (2011). Networks of the brain. Cambridge,
Causality in the sciences. New York: Oxford MA: MIT Press.
University Press. Sporns, O. (2012). Discovering the human connectome.
Illari, P. M., Russo, F., & Williamson, J. (2011b). Why Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
look at causality in the sciences? A manifesto. In P. M. Thelen, E., & Smith, L. B. (2006). Dynamic systems theo-
Illari, F. Russo, & J. Williamson (Eds.), Causality in ries. In W. Damon & R. M. Lerner (Eds.), Handbook
the sciences (pp. 3–22). New York: Oxford University of child psychology: Vol. 1. Theoretical models of
Press. human development (6th ed., pp. 258–312). Hoboken,
Karg, K., Shedden, K., Burmeister, M., & Sen, S. NJ: Wiley.
(2011). The serotonin transporter promoter variant Tinbergen, N. (1963). On aims and methods in ethology.
(5-HTTLPR), stress, and depression meta-analysis Zeitschrift für Tierpsychologie, 20, 410–433.
revisited: Evidence of genetic moderation. Archives of Vauclair, J., & Imbault, J. (2009). Relationship between
General Psychiatry, 68, 444–454. manual preferences for object manipulation and point-
Kauffman, S. (1993). The origins of order: Self- ing gestures for infants and toddlers. Developmental
organization and selection in evolution. New York: Science, 12, 1060–1069.
Oxford University Press. Woodward, J. (2007). Interventionist theories of causation
Layne, C. M., Steinberg, J. R., & Steinberg, A. M. (2014). in psychological perspective. In A. Gopnik & L. Schulz
Causal reasoning skills training for mental health (Eds.), Causal learning: Psychology, philosophy, and
practitioners: Promoting sound clinical judgment in computation (pp. 19–36). New York: Oxford University
evidence-based practice. Training and Education in Press.
Professional Psychology. doi:10.1037/tep0000037. Young, G. (2008). Causality and causation in law,
Markus, K. A. (2011). Real causes and ideal manipula- medicine, psychiatry, and psychology: Progression
tions: Pearl’s theory of causal inference from the point or regression? Psychological Injury and Law, 1,
of view of psychological research methods. In P. M. 161–181.
70 3 Introducing Causality in Psychology

Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo- in court. New York: Springer Science + Business
Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science + Media.
Business Media. Young, G., & Shore, R. (2007). Dictionary of terms related
Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feigning, and response to causality, causation, law, and psychology. In G. Young,
bias in psychiatric/psychological injury: Implications A. W. Kane, & K. Nicholson (Eds.), Causality of psycho-
for practice and court. Dordrecht, Netherlands: logical injury: Presenting evidence in court (pp. 87–135).
Springer Science + Business Media. New York: Springer Science + Business Media.
Young, G. (2015). Causality in civil disability and crimi- Zelazo, P. D. (2004). The development of conscious con-
nal forensic cases: Legal and psychological compari- trol in childhood. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8,
son. International Journal of Law and Psychiatry, 37. 12–17.
Young, G., & Gagnon, M. (1990). Neonatal laterality, Zelazo, P. D., Carlson, S. M., & Kesek, A. (2008). The
birth stress, familial sinistrality, and left brain inhibi- development of executive function in childhood. In
tion. Developmental Neuropsychology, 6, 127–150. C. Nelson & M. Luciana (Eds.), Handbook of develop-
Young, G., Kane, A. W., & Nicholson, K. (2007). mental cognitive neuroscience (2nd ed., pp. 553–574).
Causality of psychological injury: Presenting evidence Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Causality in Philosophy;
Philosophy in Psychology 4

Note that in Chap. 35, I present a philosophi-


Chapter Introduction cal model related to the ones under discussion,
referred to as a “co-existential” model for episte-
Philosophical concepts of mind, brain, behavior, mology. It combines different viewpoints on
and their relationships, including on causality positivistic reality and its social construction.
and free will, provide essential intellectual fore- This prior philosophical work of mine illustrates
ground in the psychological study of these con- how different philosophical positions can be
cepts. The present book deals with the complexity combined into superordinate ones involving a
of the causes of behavior, and has been informed dialectical integration of the constituents. Later
by the philosophical work in the area. This chap- in the present chapter, I develop an equivalent
ter of the present work reviews critical philo- integrative philosophical model of “neoreductio-
sophical issues in the field related to behavior and constructivism.” It serves to create an interdia-
its causation, and it proposes concepts that might logue of predominant themes on the philosophical
help bridge the philosophical and psychological discourse about psychology, and also it applies
constructs in the area. quite well to the issue at hand of the causality of
The first part of the chapter explores the rela- behavior. That is, by proposing a hierarchical
tion of psychology and philosophy from the psy- model subsuming the philosophical extremes on
chological perspective. It concentrates on schools the question of the nature of reality and its cau-
of thought such as reductionism and construc- sality, none predominate to muddy the discourse.
tionism. Lilienfeld (2012a, 2012b) proposed an Moreover, the constitutive emergence of the
integrated model of “constitutive reductionism.” whole that they create allows for a more rational
It allows for emergence of higher-order levels in debate on the question in which all sides are
behavior, a concept that lends itself to viable respected for their contributions to understand-
models of free will in human behavior. Newcombe ing behavior and its origins.
(2011a, 2011b) proposed an integrative model of The work of Barrett and colleagues (e.g.,
“neoconstructivism,” and Allen and Bickhard Lindquist & Barrett, 2012) on a constructivist
(2011, 2013a, 2013b) proposed an “emergent approach to psychological constructs places
constructivist” one. In other work in this chapter, the brain and its networks at the heart of
Seligman, Railton, Baumeister, and Sripada understanding psychological “primitives.” The
(2013) and Sripada, Railton, Baumeister, and neuronal network approach is an important one
Seligman (2013) argued for a model of causation in the present book, and helps keep the philo-
that is probabilistic and appears adeterministic. sophical debates grounded in “hard” science.

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 71


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_4
72 4 Causality in Philosophy; Philosophy in Psychology

At the same time, philosophers are venturing into Reductionism and Constructivism
neuroscientific study and conceptualization, and
this is quite evident in the section of the chapter Lilienfeld (2012a) characterized the predominant
on the philosophy of free will. view in psychology as “constitutive reduction-
Philosophers deal with free will in terms of ism.” In this view, mental phenomena are consid-
the axis of determinism or its lack in behavior ered material products of brain and other central
and the issue of compatibilism of free will and nervous system activity [I would add in interac-
determinism. Compromise stances include semi- tion with the peripheral nervous system]. A more
compatibilist ones. In the chapter, I propose a extreme version of reductionism is “eliminative
semi-compatibilist model that is based on the reductionism,” which is a neurocentric perspec-
construct of “free being” rather than free will. tive. In this view, neuroscience leads the way in
The chapter concludes with presentation of translating all behavior, emotion, and thought
the integrated approach of relationism, which is into neural activity (which is also called “greedy
a metatheoretical/worldview approach that is reductionism”; Dennett, 1995).
heavily developmental. Also, it refers to Kuhn’s Lilienfeld (2012a) noted that an extreme
(1962, 1970) philosophy of science concept of reductionist point of view discounts that behavior
paradigms in science, and their shifts to new and psychology can be analyzed at several levels.
paradigms once the inertia of change reaches the However, constitutive reductionism allows for
tipping point. In a chapter toward the end of the the “emergence” of higher-order properties that
book, I return to the topics of relationism and derive from the interaction of lower-order ele-
paradigms in psychology. I develop an inte- ments at different levels of the behavioral system,
grated model of paradigms and their changes and cannot be reduced entirely to the lower-order
based on the work of Overton (2013, 2014a, constituents involved. Lilienfeld gave the exam-
2015), showing how my generic model of the ple of traffic jams as an emergent phenomenon.
change process (Young, 2011) can be used to He noted that, in the end, the concept of emer-
elaborate Overton’s work, and consequently gence might not be supported. Nevertheless, that
Kuhn’s. Indeed, much of the latter part of the would not deny the validity of a hierarchical
book is based on applications of my change model of behavior in which neuroscience and
model and its corresponding model of Neo- psychology function at different valid levels.
Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian development over the Lilienfeld (2012b) continued that constitutive
lifespan (Young, 2011, 2012, 2014). reductionism disavows the proposition of “sub-
stance dualism,” which considers that mind and
body are fundamentally distinct, or composed of
The Constitution and Construction different “stuff.” Instead, it accepts that mind and
of Reality brain comprise different levels of analysis of psy-
chological phenomena, a viewpoint that he
The great debate in psychology as well as phi- termed “property dualism.”
losophy about the nature of behavior is whether Lilienfeld (2012b) addressed causality of
it can be reduced to biochemical and physical behavior, indicating that psychology is studying
processes in body and brain or whether it can be critical variables in this regard as well as “rough
more than that and even constructed (including outlines” of their “directional pathways.” He
by mind) at levels beyond reductionistic influ- argued that the field should clarify the precise
ences. The following section of the chapter steps linking relevant causal variables into inte-
delves into these thorny issues, and terminates grated etiological explanations.
by presenting my own co-existential model on He responded to Tryon (2012a), who criti-
the question. cized the biopsychosocial model as providing
The Constitution and Construction of Reality 73

simply a list of contributing factors without Just as wetness cannot be predicted from knowl-
explaining how causal connections work, or what edge of the atoms constituting water, so the prop-
are the mechanisms involved, thereby promoting erties of neural networks cannot be predicted
only an “illusion of understanding.” Lilienfeld from knowledge of their constituent neurons.
(2012b) agreed that the biopsychosocial model is
unfalsifiable, without much explanatory power.
[However, I have developed a modified biopsy- Neoconstructivism
chosocial model terms “biopersonalsocial,” that
could have more relevance to psychological sci- Newcombe (2011a, 2011b) noted that Piaget
ence (Young, 2011).] bridged or reconciled the nativism–empiricism
Tryon (2012a) favored the connectionist split in cognitive development by adopting a con-
model as one that circumvents these lacunae in structivist stance. An emerging neoconstructivist
psychological theory construction. However, in viewpoint extends the constructivist model; it
another exchange on the philosophical roots of advocates that minds are biologically prepared at
behavioral study, Newcombe (2011a, 2011b) the outset and that they interact in biologically-
devalued the connectionist model as applied to evolved ways within their varying but expectable
developmental psychology. Before delving into environments. The environment provides rich
that issue, I examine Tryon’s informative presen- structures, redundancies, and correlations that
tation on cause and mechanism. serve like Gibsonian (Gibson, 1979) affordances
Tryon (2009) referred to Kazdin (2008), who and support experience-expectant learning
distinguished mechanism and causation. (Bahrick, Lickliter, & Flom, 2004; Greenough,
Mechanism refers to the processes that explain Black, & Wallace, 1987).
why things (e.g., therapy) work and how they Neoconstructivism cuts across nativist and
produce change. For example, at the causal level, empirical perspectives and, moreover, it views
it is well-known that cigarettes cause cancer but both learning and development, including of rea-
the precise main mechanism involves mediation soning, as probabilistic, statistical, and Bayesian
by DNA mutation induced by nicotine exposure. (Gopnik & Tenenbaum, 2007). It is both quanti-
However, in psychology, causal modeling is often tative and qualitative, depending on the granular-
approached using “box-and-arrow schematic dia- ity of the lens used.
grams” as explanations, but these lack informa- Neoconstructivism also integrates (a) devel-
tion on mechanisms. They might identify opment with (b) neural, (c) evolutionary, and (d)
mediators (more direct causal influences) and ecological (current state) approaches. This per-
moderators (more indirect ones), but these are at spective cuts across all four of Aristotle’s view of
a level removed from establishing mechanism. causes: (a) formal, (b) material, (c) final, and (d)
Tryon (2012a) continued that psychology is efficient, respectively. Finally, it is an umbrella
infused with three major explanatory problems. term that covers other views, such as dynamic
First, it is comprised of separate mini-theories, systems theory/emergence models (Thelen &
schools, or camps that lack integration. Second, Smith, 1994) and stage (e.g., Young, 2011) and
often the problem in this regard relates to the use wave (e.g., Siegler, 2006) models.
of distinct terminology in each mini-theory/ Allen and Bickhard (2011, 2013a, 2013b) pro-
school/camp. Third, the various approaches lack posed an “emergent constructivist” model. They
in precise mechanistic explanations and, instead, explained that both the nativist and empiricist
they rely too heavily on functional ones. Tryon points of view of the starting point of cognitive
defined mechanism as a sequence of causal events development in infancy are “foundational.” That
that are necessary or sufficient to bring about a is, they proposed that further learning takes place
result at issue as it operates. For Tryon (2012b), because of the presence of givens in “core knowl-
psychological phenomena can be emergent, or edge” or perceptual skills (“feature”), respec-
not predictable from the constituents involved. tively. The two points of view disallow any
74 4 Causality in Philosophy; Philosophy in Psychology

possibility of emergence. Further, both empirical Causality derives from prospective processes.
and nativist models are passive ontological mod- However, at the metaphysical level, the concept
els of the developing person, concerning environ- of prospection is agnostic about determinism.
ment or innate factors, respectively. Even if The authors also make the strong claim that the
models try to combine empirical and nativist scientific method and even fundamental scientific
approaches, they just attempt to bridge the divide principles do not inevitably stand on or require
and not transcend it. Only a “third way” can do determinism, given that natural science theoriz-
that, which Piaget termed “tertium quid.” In ing now involves “probabilistic elements.”
Allen and Bickhard’s model of cognitive devel- Fukukura, Helzer, and Ferguson (2013) com-
opment, called representational emergence, mented that Seligman et al. (2013) are incorrect
action systems are constructed, and representa- to dismiss determinism in science. By definition,
tions emerge from the pragmatic, functional, science implicates a “deterministic understand-
interactive activity involved. Their model, there- ing” of human behavior and thought. Sripada
fore, allows for emergent constructivism in new et al. (2013) replied that determinism should not
knowledge learning. The model is quite Piagetian be considered inviolate but simply an empirical
(Piaget, 1954), in that Piaget had posited that the thesis about the types of laws in nature (the uni-
starting point of cognitive development involves verse). Sripada et al. (2013) then presented the
goal-oriented sensorimotor activity on which contrasting view of a quantum universe, which is
emergence can take place. Allen and Bickhard fundamentally “stochastic” and marked by physi-
(2013a) added that their version of this action- cal laws that yield a distribution of probabilities
based model especially concerns anticipations. in outcome. Beyond quantum phenomena, natu-
Allen and Bickhard (2011) noted, “New con- ral ones, including psychological ones, are under-
structions can emerge from variations of an inter- stood best in terms of statistical generalizations
nally organized emergence base” (p. 165). on laws rather than deterministic ones.
Development takes place on the basis of emer- In another example, work in political science
gence out of action, which is an (inter)action indicates that causality in this area is not determin-
perspective. istic (Acemoglu & Robinson, 2012; Fukuyama,
Newcombe (2011b) concluded that empiri- 2011). As for particular major (macrolevel) areas
cism might be best referred to as a bottom-up related to psychology, no firm conclusions can be
theory. She placed dynamic systems theory drawn yet whether probabilistic causation explains
among the bottom-up theories, as per Thelen and operation (e.g., neurons, brain). The same applies
Smith’s (1994) description of it. to the particular area of free will.

Determinism and Indeterminism Co-Existentialism

The exchange by Seligman and colleagues and One manner of describing the metatheoretical
Fukukura and colleagues in 2013 tackles the approach to the question of determinism in psy-
role of determinism in psychological behavior chology, as presented in Seligman et al. (2013)
and causation. Seligman et al. (2013) champi- and Sripada et al. (2013), is to term it a “probabi-
oned prospection as a central process to frame listic adeterministic” one. Another possibility is
behavior, mind, and brain. It focuses on future that the label of “probabilisticism” best captures
orientation, allowing probabilistic elements to their approach to reality construction and deter-
interpose in strict determination of present from minism. In this regard, the authors also refer to
past. Humans are considered as active agents the concept of prospection that they consider
who are constantly constructing alternative pos- important in human cognition as being “agnos-
sibilities, evaluating them, and electing which tic” about determinism. I would add that the con-
ones to follow. cept of emergence as a possible outcome in the
The Constitution and Construction of Reality 75

probabilistic universe of behavior solidifies the stances as co-existential and not mutually incom-
construct that human behavior is probabilistic patible, despite what they might advocate at their
and adeterministic. intellectual origins, it is a quantum one. Perhaps
In this regard, especially considering that phil- it is best to refer to the proposed blended
osophical debates about the role of determinism epistemological model as a co-existential
in human behavior cannot end with definitive epistemological one, but another way of captur-
answers, a combined, pluralistic view that ing its intricacy is to refer to it as one involving
acknowledges multiple possibilities and realities quantum neo-epistemology. The model being
in the causal construction of behavior might be proposed allows integration of Lilienfeld’s
an appropriate blended approach. Evidence (2012a, 2012b) concept of constitutive reduc-
might be found supporting either extremes of the tionism, Newcombe’s (2011a, 2011b) concept of
continuum of determinism and probabilism in neoconstructivism, Allen and Bickhard’s (2011)
human behavior causation but, more likely, evi- concept of emergent constructivism, and
dence might be lacking, be ambiguous, or be Seligman et al.’s (2013)/Sripada et al.’s (2013)
interpretable in different ways, taking different approach that I have labeled “probabilisticism”
quantum faces depending on the observer. or probabilistic adeterminism. In this regard, the
One way of accommodating the various combined model of reality and causal elucidation
approaches to reductionism, constructivism, that I am proposing could be termed “neo-
determinism, adeterminism, causalism, acausal- reductioconstructivism.” Specifically, the model
ism, probabilism, and any “fixism” in under- accepts that reality at once is reductionist and
standing the external world and its reality is to constructionist, deterministic and adeterministic,
suggest they can co-exist epistemologically, in and causal but perhaps with some aspects acausal.
one metaview of reality. The co-existence could Emergence can mark it, but within the constraints
reflect that some aspects of reality are already offered at any and all levels involved by pre-
reduced or reducible, cannot be constructed de existing factors, present context, and prospection.
novo, etc., while others can be personally or The perception of reality is influenced by positiv-
socially constructed. istic factors in the present but, in the end, in the
Also, some aspects of reality could be wholly human case, it is influenced, as well, by percep-
determined by preceding factors, deriving from tions of projected reality into the future based on
either immediate proximally preceding anteced- past and present context and even the goal to alter
ents or, rather, quite distal ones, for example, it in order to allow for better adaptation.
even ones that are evolutionarily, intergeneration-
ally, genetically, or post-conceptually distal in
origin. In contrast, other aspects of reality could Comment
be wholly probabilistic, even emergent, and
utterly unpredictable from prior states, events, The integrated, synthetic, co-existential model
stimuli, or conditions/contexts, and so on. that I have developed on the construction of real-
Finally, it is conceivable that some aspects of ity and the empirical influences that impact that
reality are indeed totally random and without construction speaks to my dialectical, construc-
cause, with no probabilistic element. They might tivist, yet realistic, positivistic approach to other
not even reflect in any way extant system elements, similar philosophical questions, such as whether
their configurations, and system inputs. This type free will exists or is an illusion and whether cau-
of reality might be deemed acausal. However, sality exists or is a figment of behavioral percep-
most if not all reality should reflect causal pro- tion and interpretation. In the following, I turn to
cesses at work in its initiation and maintenance. the latter two philosophical questions, dealing
This combined point of view of the nature of first with free will and then causality. In both
reality is a neo-epistemological one, and because cases, I support the pertinence of the study of and
it recommends viewing different epistemological reflection on the matter—first, free will exists and
76 4 Causality in Philosophy; Philosophy in Psychology

can influence behavior, partly through its emer- neuroscientific studies in the area, their method-
gent and constructed qualities; and, second, cau- ological drawbacks, and their implications for
sality not only exists but is central to understanding understanding free will in autonomous acting
behavior, including through free will as a primary agents, or its lack in this regard. Therefore, in the
factor in these regards and the mechanisms that following, I review the work on brain and net-
allow for it and other aspects of behavior. works in causality, as presented by Tse (2013)
philosophically in terms of the concept of emer-
gence and Lindquist and Barrett (2012) psycho-
Free Will, Causality Modeling, logically in terms of the concept of
and Philosophy constructionism at the level of networks. A later
chapter in the present book that is fully on free
The present model of epistemology is consistent will (see Chap. 18) explores further the philo-
with the psychological and neuroscientific litera- sophical and neuroscientific bases involved.
ture. For example, it fits the view that people can
express free will belief, which in turn influences
their behavior (Baumeister, 2008). Russell and Neurophilosophy and Free Will
Deery (2013) showed how the classic debates
about the question of whether free will exists Emergence
(and influences behavior) have evolved into more
nuanced and integrated approaches. Nevertheless, Tse (2013) adopted a more pragmatic approach
the great divide in the issues, such as determin- to the question of free will by examining its neu-
ism/indeterminism, compatibilism/incompatibil ral basis. Neuronal circuits exhibit “emergent”
ism, and the matter of responsibility remain spatiotemporal properties that are not found in
cogent in contemporary philosophy. any single neuron. Circuits need to exhibit pre-
For other recent philosophical work on causal- cise timing and interplay over activation (“excita-
ity, the reader should consult Gibb, Lowe, and tion”) and also inhibition, in cascades of activity
Ingthorsson (2013), Lawson (2013), Markus involving the whole network and without a “com-
(2012), Reiss (2015), Mumford and Anjum mand” neuron. An example of emergence in
(2013), Paul and Hall (2013), and Reutlinger behavior relative to neurons underpinning the
(2013). Balaguer (2014) has written an accessible behavior is that we can engage in swimming even
philosophical book on free will, as did Mele though no one neuron encodes for it.
(2014a, 2014b). Castellani and Quitterer (2007) According to Tse (2013), in this approach to
edited a philosophy book to help decipher the neurons, in terms of input, the energy involved
relationship between agency and causation. It also is spatiotemporal in pattern. The patterns are
includes chapters on free will (e.g., Mele, 2007). higher-order and emergent but this does not mean
For example, Reiss (2015) explained the relation- that they are beyond physical laws. They exert
ship among causation, evidence, and inference. “downward” causal influences and have a degree
He described the historical roots of causality of independence, but they do not do the “causal
scholarship, and the recent approaches related to work” in and of themselves. Rather, meeting
regularity, probability, process, counterfactuals, thresholds of neural activation does the causal
interventions, radical causal pluralism, and power work involved.
theory, while developing his inferentialist philo- Tse (2013) pointed out that input patterns
sophical theory of causation. Review of these could genuinely cause behavior only if neurons
books is beyond the scope of the present work. detect them at the necessary threshold levels, and
Philosophers increasingly are not adverse to thereby change the body and brain. It’s not just
broaching neuroscientific and experimental energy transfer or amount that is causal in neural
work, and this is especially true for the topic activity, but energy patterns meeting thresholds
of free will. They examine both the classic that trigger a neuronal response.
Neurophilosophy and Free Will 77

Past Present Future

Preferred Future Path

Present

Primary Past Paths

Secondary Past Paths Alternative Future


Paths

Fig. 4.1 An actual and several possible paths. In the case lines indicate possible paths that would not be part of any
of causation among neurons, criteria on neuronal input informational causal chain. There is downward causation
realize possible paths that are also links in informational by threshold-released detectors of input spatiotemporal
causal chains, as indicated by the solid line. The dashed patterns. Adapted from Tse (2013)

Tse (2013) presented much detail of how neu- level, are capable of voluntary, purposive choice
rons work. In this regard, he maintained that free in deliberating, moving, and refraining to move.
will is especially “about the future.” In particular, The emergentist view acknowledges superordi-
free will relates to “the next cycle in iterative nate, top-down functioning levels in hierarchical
information processing loops” (p. 15). Specially, organization of behavior, but does not deny that
the way free will works in causation is through we are partly constituted by lower-order, bottom-
“criterial causation.” Figure 4.1 presents Tse’s up processes, such as neural activities.
(2013) model of criterial causation. In the model, For further neuroscientific work related to free
the path actually followed from among possibili- will, refer to Pockett, Banks, and Gallagher (2006).
ties in neuronal activity indicates downward For example, they discussed the work of Libet
causation by criterially-released detectors of spa- (1994) and Wegner (2002), who essentially deny
tiotemporal input patterns that are involved “in the validity of considering free will in behavior.
informational causal chains.” Therefore, for the
neural basis of free will, Tse (2013) supported a
model of downward influence on neural activity Networks
due to “criterial” thresholds of input toward neural
activity causation. Neuronal criterial causation is a Lindquist and Barrett (2012) adopted a construc-
model that is compatible with the philosophical tionist approach to understanding basic human
positions of both determinism and indeterminism. faculties, such as emotions, cognitions, and per-
Runyan (2014) presented a philosophically- ception. As their starting point, they took the
based analysis of human agency in terms of fac- functional networks being described in cognitive
tors that cannot be reduced to neural causes. neuroscience, and proposed that they can be
Specifically, he considered humans as “emer- described as lower-level, basic psychological
gent” voluntary agents who, at the macro/whole operations that interact to produce the typical
78 4 Causality in Philosophy; Philosophy in Psychology

modular categories associated with a “faculty” state (more than pan-emotional or specific emo-
approach to psychological mental state. The con- tional) psychological operations.
structionist approach has several variants. In Specifically, Lindquist and Barrett (2012)
“elemental” constructionism, a mental state can related emotional experience/perception process-
be disassembled or reduced to units that retain ing brain-region activation to similar activation
their structure and function. In “emergent” con- by memory/theory of mind/navigation/prospec-
structionism, a mental state is more than the sum tion (Spreng, Mar, & Kim, 2009), semantics
of its parts, just as bread is more than the sum of (Binder, Desai, Graves, & Conant, 2009), moral
its ingredients. Third, context-dependent or “situ- decision-making/empathy (Bzdok et al., 2012),
ated” constructionism allows for conceptual cre- and pain (Yarkoni, Poldrack, Nichols, Van Essen,
ation of specific instances of a category (e.g., fear & Wager, 2011). Similarly, regions of the default
of snakes vs. falling). network are activated not only in emotions but
The neuronal network analyses taking place in also in empathy (Bzdok et al., 2012), semantic
the research inform these models. Neuroimaging processing (Binder et al., 2009), moral judgments
research supports the utility of examining neuro- (Bzdok et al., 2012), mentalizing about other
nal networks as platforms for the articulation of people (Bzdok et al., 2012; Spreng et al., 2009),
psychologically meaningful yet basic primitives autobiographical memory (Spreng et al., 2009),
in constructing mental state (see Table 4.1). and imagining the future (Spreng et al., 2009).
Lindquist and Barrett’s (2012) review of the lit- The authors provided similar data about other
erature supports multiple networks (seven, after networks, including the limbic one.
Yeo et al., 2011) as important in psychological Lindquist and Barrett (2012) concluded that
operations. These include the three core ones networks are broadly-distributed, flexible assem-
emphasized by Menon (2011, 2012)—salience, blies that fire together in probabilistic ways.
the executive, and the default model—as well as Psychological operations “emerge” from neuro-
four others related to the limbic system, atten- nal interplay, although the exact emergentic
tion, and perception. The authors referred to the mechanism has not been elucidated. The authors’
psychological operations in the salience network constructionist approach calls for abandoning
as body-directed attention, those in the executive naïve realism that psychological faculties/catego-
one as executive control, and those in the default ries, such as emotions, reveal understanding of
one as conceptualization. The limbic system con- causal mechanisms in the brain. It is more accu-
cerns core affect generation, the attention one rate to seek psychological “primitives” in these
visuospatial attention, and the perceptual ones regards, and even the ones mentioned still might
exteroceptive perception (auditory/tactile visual). be further decomposable.
To show that the networks involved function Note that Hamann (2012) adopted an approach
both cross-categorically yet specific to instances to neural networks quite similar to that of
of categories, Lindquist and Barrett (2012) Lindquist and Barrett (2012). However, he based
referred to the literature on these networks and his work on Kober et al. (2008), who found six
emotions. In this regard, meaning-making under primary, functionally distributed groups that help
executive control is associated with multiple neu- serve in the generation of emotional states.
ronal networks and is involved in creation of all Kelly, Biswal, Craddock, Castellanos, and
mental states. For example, the brain regions Milham (2012) referred to the complete set of
associated with emotional experiences also are intrinsic functional connections in the brain as the
associated with other mental phenomena, as per a “functional connectome.” They cautioned that
review of meta-analyses. These findings are con- functional maps such as these need to consider
sistent with a model that brain regions are individual differences and variations in func-
enabling (“implementing”) basic pan-mental tional zones in relation to variations in behavior.
Table 4.1 Intrinsic networks and their functional description in the constructionist framework
Network name(s) Brain regions included Psychological operation in a constructionist ontology
“Limbic” (Yeo et al., 2011) Medial temporal lobe, subgenual Core affect generation: representing visceromotor states from prior experience
anterior cingulated cortex, medial, or engaging visceromotor control of the body to create the core affective tone
and lateral orbitofrontal cortexa (pleasure or displeasure with some degree of arousal) that is a basic feature of all
conscious experience and that directs basic approach/withdrawal behaviors.
“Salience network” (Seeley et al., 2007) Anterior midcingulate cortex Body-directed attention: using representations from the body to guide attention
“Ventral attention network” (Yeo et al., 2011) (aMCC), bilateral dorsal anterior and behavior. This process might use changes in the homeostatic state of the body
“Cingulo-opercular network” (Vincent, Kahn, insula, and frontal operculum to signal salient events in the environment and regulate behavioral responses.
Snyder, Raichle, & Buckner, 2008) Likely, this network can be decomposed further into aspects that represent bodily
Neurophilosophy and Free Will

Network # 8 (Smith et al., 2009) states (a ventral anterior insula network) and use bodily states to drive attention
and behavior (a dorsal anterior insula network) (Touroutoglou, Hollenbeck,
Dickerson, & Feldman Barrett, 2012)
“Default network” (Yeo et al., 2011) Medial prefrontal cortex, Conceptualization: representing prior experiences (i.e., memory or category
Network # 4 (Smith et al., 2009) retrosplenial area, posterior knowledge). During autobiographical memory or representation of concept
cingulate cortex/precuneus, medial knowledge, this process simulates prior sensory-motor experiences. During
temporal lobe (hippocampus, perception of objects, this process helps to make meaning of sensations from the
entorhinal cortex), bilateral world in a context-specific manner. During emotion, this process helps to make
superior temporal sulcus meaning of sensations from the body in a context-specific manner.
“Frontoparietal network” (Yeo et al., 2011) Bilateral dorsolateral prefrontal Executive control: modulating activity in other networks to create a unified
“Executive control network” (Seeley et al., 2007) cortex, inferior parietal lobe, inferior conscious field during the construction of a mental state (e.g., selecting some
Network # 9 (Smith et al., 2009) parietal sulcus, precuneus, and conceptual content when meaning is made of sensations and inhibiting other
middle cingulated cortex (mCC) content; selecting some sensations for conscious awareness and inhibiting others).
“Dorsal attention network” (Yeo et al., 2011) Bilateral frontal eye fields, dorsal Visuospatial attention: modulating activity in exteroceptive sensory regions
Network # 9 (Smith et al., 2009) posterior parietal cortex, fusiform (e.g., selecting which visual sensation is selected for conscious awareness and
gyrus, area MT+ inhibiting others). This process may be specific to visual sensations given the
importance of these sensations in human evolution.
“Sensorimotor” (Yeo et al., 2011) Precentral and postcentral gyri Exteroceptive sensory perception: representing auditory and tactile sensations
(sensorimotor cortex), Heschl’s
gyrus (primary auditory cortex)
cortex, posterior insula
“Visual” (Yeo et al., 2011) Occipital lobe Exteroceptive sensory perception: representing visual sensations
a
Although Yeo et al. (2011) did not include subcortical structures in their analysis, we include subcortical structures in this network based on their known anatomical connections.
We include the nuclei of the basal ganglia, which are involved in orchestrating effortful behavior and motor control (Wager et al., 2008). We also hypothesize that the central
nucleus of the amygdale, which is involved in producing autonomic responses (Wager et al., 2008), and the midbrain periaqueductal gray, which is involved in coordinating
coherent physiological and behavioral responses (Wager et al., 2008), are part of this network. The basal ganglia, the amygdale, and the periaqueductal gray all project to the
ventromedial prefrontal cortex (vmPFC), the major cortical site in Yeo et al.’s (2011) limbic network
Adopted with permission of Elsevier. Reprinted from Trends in Cognitive Sciences, Vol. 16, Lindquist, K. A., & Barrett, L. F., A functional architecture of the human brain:
79

Emerging insights from the science of emotion, Pages 533–540, Copyright 2012; with kind permission from Elsevier. [Table 1, Page 536]
80 4 Causality in Philosophy; Philosophy in Psychology

Comment also “new” compatibilists, who argue that free


will is a type of “dispositional power.” In the lat-
The danger of focusing on the brain and its work- ter approach, concepts such as reflective self-
ings in the philosophical context is that behavior control are important.
is reduced to biochemical and physical processes. In semi-compatibilism (e.g., Fischer, 1994;
However, the positions that I have described in Fischer & Ravizza, 1998; Ravizza, 1994), moral
this section related to free will adhere to a con- responsibility but not free will is compatible with
structionist, emergentist account of behavior determinism. The former is compatible with it
both philosophically and psychologically. That because it does not require the power to do other-
being said, as in any area of philosophy, and in wise. However, freedom is not because it does
any discipline for that matter, when contemplat- require this power, and, essentially, semi-
ing the question of free will, there always will be compatibilists maintain that this is impossible.
a dynamic tension between more liberal and con- From a libertarian framework, Doyle (2010)
servative views about its existence and its differ- developed a theory that seems like a semi-
entiation from the biophysical bases that compatibilistic one. In his model, there is, first,
constitute the brain and body. an indeterministic stage involving factors that
The next part of the discussion of philosophi- might influence choice. Then, there is a second
cal points of view related to causality and free stage that is deterministic and in which the actor
will leaves the neuroscientific, constructionist exercises control about the choice made in light
approach for more classical philosophical debates of the factors considered in the first step.
on the question. The models discussed lead to a Kane (2011c) developed a libertarian view of
semi-compatibilistic one that I have developed free will that focuses on indeterminism in choices
for the issue. and decisions themselves. He emphasized “ulti-
mate responsibility,” involving actors having free
will as the ultimate source of their actions or their
Philosophy and Free Will wills in performing the actions.
Kane (2011a) noted that the philosopher
Schools William James (1956) had distinguished “hard”
and “soft” determinism. Only the latter is com-
Kane (2011a, 2011b) noted that determinism also patibilist. There is also a point of view called
is referred to as a doctrine of “conditional neces- “hard” incompatibilism. He continued that
sity,” and that it constitutes a “threat” to free will. Smilansky (2002) has taken an “unusual” view of
Determinism can be referred to as conditional free will, in that Smilansky argued that “we can
necessity because, given determining conditions, and should be both incompatibilists and compati-
the occurrence of an event inevitably is deter- bilists about freedom and responsibility” (p. 26).
mined. Determinism poses a threat to free will, as That is, “certain forms of moral responsibility,
mentioned, because, typically, we view ourselves desert, and blame require libertarian free will,
as agents having free will and capable of influ- whereas other forms can be sustained without it”
encing the world. There are open alternatives (p. 26). It would appear that this is a semi-
from which we can choose and it is up to us to compatibilist position in which hard determinism
choose them so that, although we choose one and compatibilism exist simultaneously, or co-
option, we could have acted otherwise. We have exist in one understanding of “truth.”
control over the sources of our action.
Compatibilists argue that determinism does
not really pose a threat to free will. For example, A Compatible Semi-Compatibilism
there might be “contextual emergence,” in which
higher-level phenomena mentally self-organize Introduction Note that I am attracted to the
in novel ways from lower-level phenomena. semi-compatibilist position not only because it
There are not only “classic” compatibilists but appears to reflect better psychological “truth”
Philosophy and Free Will 81

compared to other philosophical positions on free will and moral responsibility reflects common
will but also because it admits to ambiguity and sense, and that should return to the center stage
uncertainty in understanding that “truth.” in philosophy. The common sense view of cau-
Moreover, it allows for constructive integration sality, free will, and moral responsibility mini-
of the diverse positions, even if the term is some- mizes a role of determinism in understanding
what ambiguous and uncertain. This might be a behavior because we still have free will even if
better approach than strongly advocating for one all our behavior is predictable from the laws of
position rather than another and falling toward a nature (no matter how uncertainly established
possible morass of philosophical squabbles and might be the laws at present). For Vihvelin (2013)
incoherent chaos. In this sense, one possible label determinism cannot be used as a basis to deny
to capture the essence of my argument is that a that we have free will, even though we are gov-
good way to describe the present semi- erned by natural laws. In contrast, maintains that
compatibilist position is that it is a “dialectical we have free will, being free to choose from
semi-compatibilism.” alternative options, so that we are morally respon-
Perhaps it is best to accept that there is not sible for our behavior. That responsibility could
only quantum-level entanglement at the micro be undermined for any one individual at any one
level but also entanglement at the macrolevel of time, but not by any blanket reason, such as
philosophy. Entanglement might one day be determinism.
shown to involve the macrolevel of our physical Part of the reason that a deterministic world
selves (Lvovsky, Ghobadi, Chandra, Prasad, & cannot negate the possibility of free will is that at
Simon, 2013), so why not also the macrolevel of least some of the fundamental laws in the world
our abstract mental ideas? Another way of saying are not all-encompassing but are probabilistic.
this is that an understanding of free will should The world, therefore, is partly indeterministic
be continuously dialectical, indeterminate (but and probabilistic rather than solely deterministic
also determinate), unfolding, discursive, and her- without room for free will. Quantum physics
meneutical in process, and one in which we all informs us about this indeterminate nature of the
should engage. However, at the psychological world. Nevertheless, Vihvelin (2013) maintained
level, research is showing that, despite the philo- that, in her view, both moral responsibility and
sophical uncertainty about the status of free will, free will are compatible with determinism.
whether we believe in it or not has profound con- However, she also argued that our ability to act
sequences (Baumeister, 2008). and to choose is compatible not only with deter-
minism but also with indeterminism.
Evidence In this regard, the experimental phi- Berofsky (2012) is another philosopher who
losophers Nichols and Knobe (2013) showed that maintained that determinism does not “pre-
in abstract conditions, participants tend toward clude” free will. Because we are “decision-mak-
incompatibilism about moral responsibility, but ers,” we can determine, in part, the laws that
in concrete, affective ones, they are more com- govern us. Psychological laws are “autono-
patibilistic. Nahmias, Morris, Nadelhoffer, and mous” and not reducible to the physical. They
Turner (2013) found that, after imagining a diffi- are autonomous when they are created without
cult choice to make, participants then chose a coercion but by rationally stepping back, weigh-
compatibilist compared to an incompatibilist ing, reflecting on, and choosing in an indepen-
description of the ability to do otherwise as a dent way that is based on deepest desires or
description reflecting their previously imagined values. Psychological laws are facilitated by
experience. “emotional maturity.” We are active beings
determining our own self, our world, and our
Similar Models Vihvelin (2013) has written a destiny, including accepting responsibility.
philosophical treatise on causality and free will This is a compatibilist view in which free will
that represents very well the present position. She is conceived of as self-determination, “self-
argued that the folk psychological view of free control,” or “self-regulation.”
82 4 Causality in Philosophy; Philosophy in Psychology

In the compatibility mind frame, determinism are all part of a chain of causes outside of con-
exists as well as free will. As Berofsky (2012) scious awareness and over which we have no
explained, free will is not a facet of being that is control. Harris (2012) concluded that, “the illu-
enabled only in an indeterministic world. To the sion of free will is itself an illusion.”
contrary, a genuinely active agent with person-
hood who is making decisions does not passively Comment The question of whether free will is
wait for a breach in the deterministic world, oth- an illusion will not be resolved either by philo-
erwise remaining impotent. Governance is self- sophical debate or empirical investigation. What
directed and freedoms can flourish through free matters is that its belief and related psychological
will, but freedoms are meaningless without being phenomena have psychological consequences
accompanied by having decision-making powers (Baumeister, 2008), which can be rigorously
and moral responsibility for decisions taken. In investigated (e.g., Alquist, Ainsworth, Baumeister,
behaving at this level, we participate with free Daly, & Stillman, 2015). Moreover, the philo-
will in the deterministic world about us and sophical positions either denying it or advocating
within which we must live. its existence can be nuanced by intermediate
stances, as well, such as in semi-compatibilism.
The Illusion of No Free Will Others have
weighed in with the criticism of the approach that
free will is an “illusion.” For example, Mele A New Semi-Compatibilism Model
(2003, 2009, 2010, 2011) described the limits of
the views of Libet and Wagner for understanding Model The compatibilistic view and the prag-
consciousness and unconsciousness. Freeman matic “ neuroemergence” view together suggest
(2006) described a view of consciousness, inten- that we can be active, autonomous agents in
tionality, and causality that is based on circular decision-making. In this regard, as mentioned,
causality. In this nonlinear, dynamical model of Berofsky (2012) took a more psychological view
causality, intentionality and awareness emerge as and indicated that behaving in this autonomous
the result of self-organizing neuronal processes way requires emotional maturity. Similarly, I
that include feedback and “enslavement,” serving maintain that free will is a psychological function
to enhance coherence. He related his model to that develops with increasing psychological
standard concepts in nonlinear dynamical system maturity, in a model that I refer to as the para-
theory, such as attractors and control of chaos. doxical, asymptotic model of free will (i.e., being
In contrast, Harris (2012) is a neuroscientist mature for one’s age leads us to choose responsi-
who ended up denying that free will exists. He bilities that reduce freedom of action).
maintained that, in order to actually have free The model that I present is a semi-
will, we need to be aware of all the factors that compatibilistic model in that, for me, free will
determine our behavior and have complete con- does not always exist compatibly in a determinis-
trol over them. However, there are many factors tic world because whether it is present or not
of which we are unaware that are behind our depends on the person’s psychology. That is, free
behavior, including unconscious ones. Moreover, will is emergent when the person develops to the
we have a sense of freedom only because of our threshold of psychological maturity for one’s age
“moment-to-moment ignorance” of the prior and, therefore, is capable of living at or beyond
causes of our behavior. The next choice we make that threshold so that the person voluntarily and
in our behavior will emerge from “the darkness consciously chooses the best adaptive options in
of prior causes” that we did not have at hand. We all the steps in giving attention, selecting action,
cannot decide what we will decide to do even and deploying action in behavior. Free will is
though we can decide to do what we have more than “will” and more than “free” because it
decided. Even though there are choices, efforts, is all of being in a process of being free or func-
intentions, and reasoning that influence us, they tioning as a “free being.”
Philosophy and Free Will 83

Note that this semi-compatibilistic psychology in individuals who do not grow toward psycho-
model of free will is different from the philosophi- logical maturity, e.g., in terms of Erikson’s con-
cal approach to semi-compatibilism in free will cept of generativity. Moreover, even if one enters
scholarship. For example, the latter might mean this phase, there will always be distractions and
that free will does not exist in a deterministic depletions impeding full psychological maturity
world but that moral responsibility still does exist and, therefore, lapses in free will. In this regard,
(e.g., Fischer, 1994; Haji, 2009). Reading between the model that I am proposing for free will growth
the lines of this approach, free will is taken as a is an asymptotic one in that we never fully arrive
universal that marks each of us in the deterministic at full psychological maturity and constant
world that we inhabit. However, from a psycho- deployment of free will. Moreover, the model is a
logical point of view, free will, or, as we are defin- paradoxical one in that in developing psychologi-
ing it—free being—is something that develops, is cal maturity and being able to dispose our free
gained with difficulty, and not necessarily in all of will freely in such development, we especially
us, or even at all times in all of us who have it. opt for behaviors related to generativity, e.g., car-
Table 4.2 presents different philosophical ing for others, family, children, society, and/or
positions about free will and moral responsibility the environment, and going beyond our personal
in relationship to determinism and indetermin- (and selfish) needs (Young, 2014).
ism. It also includes the traditional philosophical Philosophically, my position is consistent with
semi-compatibilist approach and my version of that of Lévinas (1985), who considered that
dialectical semi-compatibilism. The table indi- Responsibility constitutes a critical human activ-
cates that traditional semi-compatibilism admits ity (Morgan, 2011). In my model that I developed
to determinism, but my approach entails a dialec- based on the work of Lévinas, I refer to the
tical engagement between determinism and human imperative as one involving
indeterminism. Re-Responsibilities rather than Responsibility.
This is because to be engaged responsibly, we
Free Will Development The implication of my must constantly re-dedicate ourselves and do so
dialectical semi-compatibilist model on the ques- to each of our multiple responsibilities (see Chap.
tion of free will is that free will might not develop 32 for further presentation of this model).

Table 4.2 Philosophical positions that relate Free Will (FW) and Moral Responsibility (MR) to determinism
Philosophical position
Determinism Indeterminism Stance on Free Will/Moral Responsibility
Compatibilism Libertarianism (Incompatibilist) Present
Hard determinism Hard incompatibilism Absent
Traditional semi-compatibilism (Philosophical) Only MR, not FW
Dialectic semi-compatibilism (Young, present volume) As we mature psychologically, we grow
asymptotically toward free will and, also,
paradoxically, we accept the constraints
of responsibility (including MR)
Compatibilism maintains that FW and MR are compatible with determinism. Incompatibilism does not accept this
view: Hard determinists are incompatibilists who think that determinism is true and that we do not have free will.
Libertarians maintain that determinism is false and that we have free will. Hard incompatibilists believe that FW and
MR are impossible, independently of whether (in)determinism is true, both being incompatible with either option.
“Semi-compatibilism” accepts that MR is possible in a deterministic universe even if FW is not [Note that Bertelsen
(2011) adds that hard libertarianism allows for free will and rejects that it is compatible with scientific methods of
explanation. In soft libertarianism, the person is seen to relate with his/her own self-construction of the world]
Adapted from Roskies (2012) and Bertelsen (2011)
84 4 Causality in Philosophy; Philosophy in Psychology

Comment Having pondered the most difficult Interventionism


question of free will, responsibility, and morality,
I have arrived at an intermediate position about Menzies (2012) supported the interventionist
whether it can exist in a deterministic world. approach to causation. By extending it into a
Essentially, free will develops and might not reach “structural equations” framework, he indicated
the critical threshold of making a difference in that it provides a clear account of the “causal
behavior if it is ephemeral, transient, at risk, or structure of mechanisms” (citing Craver, 2007).
otherwise compromised through genetics, biology Claveau (2012) supported the interventionist
(brain), environment (including family or culture), approach in helping to determine causation.
developmental program, and so on. In this regard, He referred to it as the “counterfactual-
the model that I espouse is a dialectical, semi- manipulationist” account of causality. Extensions
compatibilistic one. Moreover, the model allows of the approach include Pearl’s (2009) causal
for rectification by the environment of less than mapping work (“graph surgery” = intervention)
optimal support for having free will in behavior, and Rubin’s (1974, 1990) potential outcomes
as in psychotherapy. For direct application of free framework.
will concepts in psychotherapy, refer to Chap. 20. In this approach of manipulationist counter-
The next part of this philosophical chapter of factuals, for two “disjoint” variables (X, Y), X
this book on causality considers directly the topic causes Y only if there is an “ideal” manipulation
of causality in philosophy. Overall, just as one of X that alters Y’s value, or its probability distri-
finds with free will that there are deniers of its bution. The counterfactual component refers to
existence, so too for causality there are its deniers. “what if” manipulative, interventionist scenarios
That school of thought began with Hume, and (the present value of Y would not exist absent the
though it is still current, I am not the one to think current value of X).
that causality is an illusion. Kerry, Eriksen, Lie, Mumford, and Anjum
(2012) considered causation in evidence-based
practice (EBP), which often is based on epide-
Causality in Philosophy miological evidence. Whereas randomized con-
trolled trials (RCTs) provide clearer evidence of
Introduction causation relative to epidemiology research
(observational study; Broadbent, 2011), the
Allen and Stoneham (2011a, 2011b) provided a regularities found in the latter type of study
historical perspective on the philosophy of causa- could be revealing. More important, although
tion, describing that past issues are still unre- RCTs are consistent with an interventionist-
solved. Aristotle’s four causes (material, formal, counterfactual approach to causality, both the
efficient, final) have informed philosophical latter approach to causality and the one of obser-
debate on causation. For example, in the seven- vational regularity might be limited to indicating
teenth century, scholarship on causation shifted the “symptoms” of causality rather than being
from an emphasis on final causes (e.g., purpose) “constitutive” of it.
to efficient ones (e.g., mechanism). Another issue
that bedevils philosophical study of causation
relates to whether causes can be independent of Dispositionalism
their effects or are mutually related to them.
Blasimme, Maugeri, and Germain (2013) Mumford and Anjum (2011; as cited in Blasimme
specified that explanatory frameworks are super- et al., 2013) provided an account of causation that
ordinate to mechanistic models. The explanatory is “dispositional.” For these authors, causation is
and mechanistic levels are dynamically related. a “primitive” that cannot be reduced to “non-
As explanatory frameworks change, their sub- causal” facts, including any counterfactual or
sumed mechanisms can be seen or interpreted in regularity. In dispositionalism, a cause does not
novel ways, and also openings are provided to necessarily effect an outcome but it only “tends”
discovery of new mechanisms that might apply. toward doing so. For example, smoking tends
Relationism 85

toward cancer. Further, the approach considers efficient: something is initiated from …; formal:
cause and effect as “partners” rather than discrete something is done according to …; final: some-
events. In this regard, in causal dispositionalism, thing is done for the sake of …]. They concluded
as applied to health, the patient is of utmost that in order to understand developmental causa-
importance. tion, we need to consider differentially all the
In dispositionalism, causality is individual- organism–environment relationships at each
ized, probabilistic, context-sensitive, and com- juncture in development.
plex. It is not simply a population-level
phenomenon but is rich at the individual level,
with the same putative universal cause potentially Comment
having different effects. Causation is not distantly
statistical and without variance but is embedded The philosophy of causality includes approaches
in the patient’s activity and is proximal. Tendency that are differentiated in its support, as has been
is less than necessity because of causal multiplic- shown, and others that even deny its existence
ity and also because of nonlinear interactions. In (e.g., Russell, 1919, on acausalism). The present
this perspective, interventions are just one more book maintains a view that supports the differen-
causal factor to consider in the tendencies tiating models, including those on intervention-
involved in causal dispositions. The real nature of ism/counterfactuals, mechanisms, and free will
causation can be found in the single case. (reviewed above), as axes in the study of causal-
Note that in the area of psychology and ity, including philosophically. One point of view
law, we make a distinction between general that affords integration among these diverse
and specific causation, or population-level and points of view in causality study is that of rela-
individual-level causation, respectively. The con- tionism. Aside from the description below, Chap.
cept of dispositionalism is kindred in spirit to this 35 considers an elaboration of relationism from
distinction. the point of view of Kuhn’s (1962) model of sci-
entific paradigms, and shows how relationism
and Kuhnianism can be redescribed in terms of
Mechanism the model in the present work on stages in change
and generic change.
Chao, Chen, and Millstein (2013) explored the
relationship between causality and mechanism in
philosophy. They described the various Relationism
approaches to both, and the complexities in relat-
ing them. In the end, they supported Darden Model
(2013), who noted that the concept of mechanism
is much more detailed and specific than that of Overton (2014a) elaborated that relational
causality. developmental systems theory fits into the rela-
Some of the earliest books on causality in psy- tional tradition of metatheory, scientific pursuit,
chology related to development, and in one phi- and methodology rather than the more conven-
losophy had been considered. Butterworth and tional Cartesian, reductionist, neopositivist one.
Bryant (1990) edited a volume on causes of At the psychological level, in this worldview,
development. They covered biological and social/ individuals are active, embodied in activity,
cultural topics, as well as cognitive ones. In this open, adaptive, contextual, complex, systemic,
volume, Hopkins and Butterworth (1990) related self-organizing, subject to emergence, plastic,
Aristotle’s conception of four types of causes to individualized, and so on.
Piagetian theory (Piaget, 1971). The authors For reductionism, causal explanation lies
equated Aristotle’s material, formal, efficient, especially in mechanisms (Aristotle’s efficient
and final causes with biology, cognitive structure, cause). However, in relationism, all four of
environment, and equilibration, respectively Aristotle’s causes are considered. For example, at
[Material: something is produced from …; the psychological level, material cause refers to
86 4 Causality in Philosophy; Philosophy in Psychology

the substance of inquiry (e.g., the neuron) and According to Overton (2014a), all living sys-
efficient cause to the forces in causation (e.g., the tems are relational and developmental ones. They
neuron firing). Formal cause refers to the organi- actively function, organize structures and pro-
zation of the resultant activity. In relational devel- cesses, and undergo “directed” sequences of
opmental systems, mechanisms are critical, and “emergent” change in their organization, involv-
they refer to structure (architecture)—function ing new relations in structure–function. The
(activity) relations. The latter can develop into models of Piaget (stages in cognitive develop-
novel structural forms or relations, as in Piaget’s ment) and Bowlby (attachment) are relational
theory (1952, 1985). developmental models that fit the relational
Overton (2014a) elaborated the relational worldview (and its methodology).
developmental systems perspective in terms of About Piaget, Overton (2014a) concluded that
methodology (the set of guiding principles for he adopted a “person” standpoint (as actor) rather
establishing particular methods). Methodology than a biological or cultural one (although the lat-
serves to complement metatheory in the dis- ter are relevant resources or conditions). In this
courses in scientific research programs/paradigms. regard, both Overton’s (2014a) emphasis on the
Metatheories vary in terms of worldviews, and person as focus and agent in development and
relationism is opposed to the Cartesian neoposi- Piaget’s equivalent focus place mechanism as
tivistic/instrumental view in this regard. having priority over any domain of understand-
In the Cartesian view, methodology moves ing related to causality in behavior. However, for
from description/reduction, to explanations and both, mechanism lies in active processes in
their antecedent mechanisms (causes), to induc- dynamic relations that can produce emergent,
tion of hypothesis/theory/“law.” In the methodol- contextualized, increasingly complex change at
ogy associated with relationism, the reductionist the individual level.
turn is replaced by relational analysis. Explanation
is replaced by seeking relational action patterns.
Finally, induction (and deduction) is replaced by Supporting Work
cyclical “abductive” (retroductive) logic (expla-
nation derives from observation–background The relational systems perspective is quite biopsy-
integration as complementary polarities). chosocial in nature, but it adds a developmental
As for causality, Overton (2014a) maintained component (Aldwin, 2014). In this view, adult
that the methodology of relationism dictates a development is considered “purposive.” We have
radical stance about causes. That is, because sys- the potential to make conscious decisions to change
tem and activity are dynamically joined, under- aspects of ourselves (Aldwin, 2007). Overton
standing causation in terms of “conditions” (2014b) concurred that behavior can attain purpo-
associated with behavior should be the foci, in sive attributes in behavior. In this regard, according
that they serve as assets/resources for “intraindi- to Aldwin (2014), free will/agency (Baumeister,
vidual” changes that might take place. Genes and 2008) involves a developmental process in which
environment are not causes in this view, but con- individuation from context enables deployment of
ditions that facilitate growth. free will. Development is about increasing free-
For Overton (2014a), if causes are “best dom from social and biological influences.
understood” as conditions in this view, the deter- Therefore, it appears to me that development in a
minants of behavioral change remains an open relational systems framework allows for stages in
question. He referred to “mechanism” as the development (qualitative discontinuities; Lerner,
source of behavioral change, but only as defined Agans, DeSouza, & Hershberg, 2014), as per my
with respect to the relational perspective. In this own work (Young, 2011).
regard, a mechanism is an active “process” inher- Greenberg (2014a, 2014b) underscored the
ent in the “structure–function” relations serving importance of emergence, self-organization, rela-
to “identify” action patterns. tional systems, the biopsychosocial approach, and
Chapter Conclusions 87

holism in development. There might be room for Kuhn’s (1962) concept of paradigm depends
a “moderate reductionism” in science as long as it on a dominant consensus in a field of study.
does not ignore the possibility of emergence. Timmins (2013) argued that the historiography of
Witherington (2014) considered self- WWII consisted of three periods—the orthodox
organization as part of top-down and bottom-up thesis, the revisionist one, and then the post-
reciprocal effects both between and within sys- revisionist one. Paradigms might shift due to fac-
tem levels and the system as a whole (parts-to- tors internal to a discipline or external to it
whole and whole-to-parts influences). The (social, political). In his model of historiography,
bottom-up component is embedded in a broader the new and old formulations exist in an essential
framework of circular causality that affords tension. Moreover, there is not an abrupt transi-
emergence or organic development. Overton and tion but more of a gradual one. Finally, the fac-
Lerner (2014) considered concepts that fit the tors leading to change in historiography are more
meta-theoretical approach of “relationism.” internal than external.
Later in the present work, as mentioned,
I present a revised Neo-Kuhnian model of para-
Comment digm. It allows for evolution in any field of schol-
arship and not just that of science, which is
Overall, the present chapter so far has demon- consistent with the approach of Timmins (2013).
strated that philosophy has much to offer to psy-
chology and related disciplines in understanding
behavior, including at the levels of comprehend- Chapter Conclusions
ing what are reality, free will, and causality.
Nevertheless, the field needs an overarching per- Psychologists are both inspired by philosophy
spective that coheres the diverse philosophical and tackle it with trepidation. The present chapter
positions on these various topics. One prominent mostly deals with the relationship of psychology
position in this regard is that of relationism, and philosophy from the point of view of
which contrasts with realism, for example. Later psychologists making it more tangible. It includes
in the book, in Chap. 35, I show how relationism mention of experimental philosophy and the brain
can be incorporated into a growing process in (as well as neurons and networks), providing fur-
philosophical and psychological thought that is ther familiarity. Moreover, the integrated con-
consistent with and explained by the present cepts proposed by psychologists in the areas
framework on stages and steps in development involved (related to behavior, brain, mind, free
and change. I applied the same modeling to will, causality) are based on combined reduction-
Kuhn’s (1962) philosophy of science concept of ist, positivistic and constructivist, relationist
paradigm change, which I review and comment approaches, and so are inviting readers to persist.
on below. My own contributions to the area are about:
(a) integrating differing views of epistemology
on realism/constructivism and compatibilism/inc
Kuhnian Paradigms ompatibilism; and (b) creating the concept of
“free being” (an integrated psychological con-
Timmins (2013) examined the “Kuhnian” con- struct of free will belief and having a sense of
cept of paradigms in science and its applicability free will). Baumeister (2008) has been important
to historiography. Specifically, he focused on in arguing that the philosophical debate of
understanding of the Second World War (WWII) whether free will exists is an intractable one, but
of 1939–1945 in terms of the evolution of the believing in free will is quite prevalent and has
conceptualization of its nature. He noted that psychological consequences. My proposal of the
Kuhn’s (1962) work was formulated for the sci- concept of free being can carry that logic farther
ences, but it has been applied widely in the social in understanding the human proclivity to believe
sciences. in free will and to act on it.
88 4 Causality in Philosophy; Philosophy in Psychology

References neural correlates of moral cognition: ALE meta-


analysis on morality, theory of mind and empathy.
Brain Structure and Function, 217, 783–796.
Acemoglu, D., & Robinson, J. (2012). Why nations fail:
Castellani, F., & Quitterer, J. (2007). Agency and causa-
The origins of power, prosperity, and poverty.
tion in the human sciences. Paderborn, Germany:
New York: Crown.
Mentis.
Aldwin, C. M. (2007). Stress, coping, and development:
Chao, H.-K., Chen, S.-T., & Millstein, R. L. (2013).
An integrative approach (2nd ed.). New York: Guilford
Mechanism and causality in biology and economics.
Press.
Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer Science + Business
Aldwin, C. M. (2014). Rethinking developmental science.
Media.
Research in Human Development, 11, 247–254.
Claveau, F. (2012). The Russo-Williamson these in the
Allen, J. W. P., & Bickhard, M. H. (2011). Emergent con-
social sciences: Causal inference drawing on two
structivism. Child Development Perspectives, 5,
types of evidence. Studies in History and Philosophy
164–165.
of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 43, 806–813.
Allen, J. W. P., & Bickhard, M. H. (2013a). Stepping of
Craver, C. (2007). Explaining the brain: Mechanisms and
the pendulum: Why only an action-based approach
the mosaic unity of neuroscience. New York: Oxford
can transcend the nativist-empiricist debate. Cognitive
University Press.
Development, 28, 96–133.
Darden, L. (2013). Mechanisms versus causes in biology
Allen, J. W. P., & Bickhard, M. H. (2013b). The pendulum
and medicine. In H.-K. Chao, S.-T. Chen, & R. L.
still swings. Cognitive Development, 28, 164–174.
Millstein (Eds.), Mechanism and causality in biology
Allen, K., & Stoneham, T. (2011a). Causation and mod-
and economics (pp. 19–34). Dordrecht, Netherlands:
ern philosophy. New York: Taylor & Francis.
Springer Science + Business Media.
Allen, K., & Stoneham, T. (2011b). Introduction. In
Dennett, D. C. (1995). Darwin’s dangerous idea.
K. Allen & T. Stoneham (Eds.), Causation and mod-
New York: Simon & Schuster.
ern philosophy (pp. 1–12). New York: Taylor &
Doyle, B. (2010). Jamesian free will: The two-stage
Francis.
model of William James. William James Studies, 5,
Alquist, J. L., Ainsworth, S., Baumeister, R., Daly, M., &
25–50.
Stillman, T. (2015). The making of might-have-beens:
Fischer, J. M. (1994). The metaphysics of free will.
Effects of free will belief on counterfactual thinking.
Oxford, UK: Blackwell.
Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 41,
Fischer, J. M., & Ravizza, M. S. J. (1998). Responsibility
268–283.
and control: A theory of moral responsibility.
Bahrick, L. E., Lickliter, R., & Flom, R. (2004).
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Intersensory redundancy guides infants’ selective atten-
Freeman, W. J. (2006). Consciousness, intentionality, and
tion, perceptual, and cognitive development. Current
causality. In S. Pockett, W. P. Banks, & S. Gallagher
Directions in Psychological Science, 13, 99–102.
(Eds.), Does consciousness cause behavior?
Balaguer, M. (2014). Free will. Cambridge, MA: MIT
(pp. 73–105). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Press.
Fukukura, J., Helzer, E. G., & Ferguson, M. J. (2013).
Baumeister, R. F. (2008). Free will in scientific psychol-
Prospection by any other name? A response to
ogy. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 3, 14–19.
Seligman et al. (2003). Perspectives on Psychological
Berofsky, B. (2012). Nature’s challenge to free will.
Science, 8, 146–150.
New York: Oxford University Press.
Fukuyama, F. (2011). The origins of political order: From
Bertelsen, P. (2011). Intentional activity and free will as
prehuman times to the French revolution. New York:
core concepts in criminal law and psychology. Theory
Farrah, Straus and Giroux.
& Psychology, 22, 46–66.
Gibb, S. C., Lowe, E. J., & Ingthorsson, R. D. (2013).
Binder, J. R., Desai, R. H., Graves, W. W., & Conant, L. L.
Mental causation and ontology. Oxford, UK: Oxford
(2009). Where is the semantic system? A critical
University Press.
review and meta-analysis of 120 functional neuroim-
Gibson, J. J. (1979/1986). The ecological approach to
aging studies. Cerebral Cortex, 19, 2767–2796.
visual perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
Blasimme, A., Maugeri, P., & Germain, P. L. (2013).
Gopnik, A., & Tenenbaum, J. B. (2007). Bayesian net-
What mechanisms can’t do: Explanatory frameworks
works, Bayesian learning and cognitive development.
and the function of the p53 gene in molecular oncol-
Developmental Science, 10, 281–287.
ogy. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological
Greenberg, G. (2014a). Emergence, self-organization, and
and Biomedical Sciences, 44, 374–384.
developmental science: Introduction. Research in
Broadbent, A. (2011). Epidemiology, risk and causation.
Human Development, 11, 1–4.
Cambridge, UK: PHG Foundation.
Greenberg, G. (2014b). How new ideas in physics and
Butterworth, G., & Bryant, P. (1990). Causes of develop-
biology influence developmental science. Research in
ment: Interdisciplinary perspectives. Hertfordshire,
Human Development, 11, 5–21.
UK: Harvester Wheatsheaf.
Greenough, W. T., Black, J. E., & Wallace, C. S. (1987).
Bzdok, D., Schilbach, L., Vogeley, K., Schneider, K.,
Experience and brain development. Child
Laird, A. R., Langner, R., et al. (2012). Parsing the
Development, 58, 539–559.
References 89

Haji, I. (2009). Incompatibilism’s allure: Principal argu- behavior as unscientific. American Psychologist, 67,
ments for incompatibilism. Peterborough, ON: 111–129.
Broadview Press. Lilienfeld, S. O. (2012b). Further sources of our field’s
Hamann, S. (2012). Mapping discrete and dimensional embattled public reputation. American Psychologist,
emotions onto the brain: Controversies and consensus. 67, 808–809.
Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 16, 458–466. Lindquist, K. A., & Barrett, L. F. (2012). A functional
Harris, S. (2012). Free will. New York: Free Press. architecture of the human brain: Emerging insights
Hopkins, B., & Butterworth, G. E. (1990). Concepts of from the science of emotion. Trends in Cognitive
causality in explanations of development. In Sciences, 16, 533–540.
G. Butterworth & P. Bryant (Eds.), Causes of develop- Lvovsky, A. I., Ghobadi, R., Chandra, A., Prasad, A. S., &
ment: Interdisciplinary perspectives (pp. 3–32). Hove, Simon, C. (2013). Observation of micro–macro entan-
UK: Erlbaum. glement of light. Nature Physics, 9, 541–544.
James, W. (1956). The dilemma of determinism. In Markus, K. A. (2012). A review of bias and causation:
W. James (Ed.), The will to believe and other essays in Models and judgment for valid comparison. Journal of
popular philosophy (pp. 145–184). New York: Dover. Educational and Behavioral Statistics, 37, 475–476.
Kane, R. (2011a). Introduction: The contours of contem- Mele, A. (2003). Motivation and agency. New York:
porary free-will debates (part 2). In R. Kane (Ed.), The Oxford University Press.
Oxford handbook of free will (2nd ed., pp. 3–35). Mele, A. (2007). Free action, moral responsibility, and
New York: Oxford University Press. alternative possibilities: Frankfurt-style cases revis-
Kane, R. (2011b). The Oxford handbook of free will (2nd ited. In F. Castellani & J. Quitterer (Eds.), Agency and
ed.). New York: Oxford University Press. causation in the human sciences (pp. 125–140).
Kane, R. (2011c). Rethinking free will: New perspectives Paderborn, Germany: Mentis.
on an ancient problem. In R. Kane (Ed.), The Oxford Mele, A. (2009). Efficacious intentions. Oxford, UK:
handbook of free will (2nd ed., pp. 381–400). Oxford University Press.
New York: Oxford University Press. Mele, A. R. (2010). Conscious deciding and the science of
Kazdin, A. E. (2008). Evidence-based treatment and prac- free will. In R. F. Baumeister, A. R. Mele, & K. D. Vohs
tice: New opportunities to bridge clinical research and (Eds.), Free will and consciousness: How might they
practice, enhance the knowledge base, and improve work? (pp. 43–65). New York: Oxford University Press.
patient care. American Psychologist, 63, 146–159. Mele, A. R. (2011). Free will and science. In R. Kane
Kelly, C., Biswal, B. B., Craddock, R. C., Castellanos, (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of free will (2nd ed.,
F. X., & Milham, M. P. (2012). Characterizing varia- pp. 499–514). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
tion in the functional connectome: Promise and pit- Mele, A. R. (2014a). A dialogue on free will and science.
falls. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 16, 181–188. New York: Oxford University Press.
Kerry, R., Eriksen, T. E., Lie, A. N., Mumford, S., & Mele, A. R. (2014b). Free: Why science hasn’t disproved
Anjum, R. L. (2012). Causation and evidence-based free will. New York: Oxford University Press.
practice: An ontological review. Journal of Evaluation Menon, V. (2011). Large-scale brain networks and psy-
in Clinical Practice, 18, 1006–1012. chopathology: A unifying triple network model.
Kober, H., Barrett, L. F., Joseph, J., Bliss-Moreau, E., Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 15, 483–506.
Lindquist, K., & Wager, T. D. (2008). Functional Menon, V. (2012). Functional connectivity, neurocogni-
grouping and cortical-subcortical interactions in emo- tive networks, and brain dynamics. In M. I. Rabinovich,
tion: A meta-analysis of neuroimaging studies. K. J. Friston, & P. Varona (Eds.), Principles of brain
NeuroImage, 42, 998–1031. dynamics: Global state interactions (pp. 27–47).
Kuhn, T. S. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Menzies, P. (2012). The causal structure of mechanisms.
Kuhn, T. S. (1970). The structure of scientific revolutions Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and
(2nd ed.). Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Biomedical Sciences, 43, 796–805.
Lawson, T. (2013). Emergence and morphogenesis: Morgan, M. L. (2011). The Cambridge introduction to
Causal reduction and downward causation? In M. S. Emmanuel Lévinas. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge
Archer (Ed.), Social morphogenesis (pp. 61–84). University Press.
New York: Springer Science + Business Media. Mumford, S. D., & Anjum, R. L. (2011). Getting causes
Lévinas, E. (1985). Ethics and infinity. Pittsburgh: from powers. New York: Oxford University Press.
Duquesne University Press. Mumford, S., & Anjum, R. L. (2013). Causation: A very
Lerner, R. M., Agans, J. P., DeSouza, L. M., & Hershberg, short introduction. Oxford, UK: Oxford University
R. M. (2014). Developmental science in 2025: A pre- Press.
dictive review. Research in Human Development, 11, Nahmias, E., Morris, S., Nadelhoffer, T., & Turner,
255–272. J. (2013). The phenomenology of free will. In P. Russell
Libet, B. (1994). A testable field theory of mind-brain & O. Deery (Eds.), The philosophy of free will: Essential
interaction. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 1, readings from the contemporary debates (pp. 486–505).
119–126. New York: Oxford University Press.
Lilienfeld, S. O. (2012a). Public skepticism of psychol- Newcombe, N. S. (2011a). What is neoconstructivism?
ogy: Why many people perceive the study of human Child Development Perspectives, 5, 157–160.
90 4 Causality in Philosophy; Philosophy in Psychology

Newcombe, N. S. (2011b). Three families of isms. Child responsibility and free will? Current Opinion in
Development Perspectives, 5, 171–172. Neurobiology, 22, 1022–1026.
Nichols, S., & Knobe, J. (2013). Moral responsibility and Rubin, D. B. (1974). Estimating causal effects of treat-
determinism: The cognitive science of folk intuitions. ments in randomized and non-randomized studies.
In P. Russell & O. Deery (Eds.), The philosophy of free Journal of Educational Psychology, 66, 688–701.
will: Essential readings from the contemporary Rubin, D. B. (1990). Formal modes of statistical inference
debates (pp. 506–529). New York: Oxford University for causal effects. Journal of Statistical Planning and
Press. Inference, 25, 279–292.
Overton, W. F. (2013). Relationism and relational devel- Runyan, J. D. (2014). Human agency and neural causes:
opmental systems: A paradigm for developmental sci- Philosophy of action and the neuroscience of volun-
ence in the post-cartesian era. In R. M. Lerner & J. B. tary agency. London, UK: Palgrave Macmillan.
Benson (Eds.), Advances in child development and Russell, B. (1919). Introduction to mathematical philoso-
behavior. Embodiment and epigenesis: Theoretical phy. London, UK: George Allen and Unwin.
and methodological issues in understanding the role Russell, P., & Deery, O. (2013). The philosophy of free
of biology within the relational developmental system. will: Essential readings from the contemporary
Part A: Philosophical, theoretical, and biological debates. New York: Oxford University Press.
dimensions (Vol. 44, pp. 21–64). Oxford, UK: Elsevier. Seeley, W. W., Menon, V., Schatzberg, A. F., Keller, J.,
Overton, W. F. (2014a). Relational developmental sys- Glover, G. H., Kenna, H., et al. (2007). Dissociable
tems and developmental science. In P. C. M. Molenaar, intrinsic connectivity networks for salience processing
R. M. Lerner, & K. M. Newell (Eds.), Handbook of and executive control. Journal of Neuroscience: The
developmental systems theory and methodology Official Journal of the Society for Neuroscience, 27,
(pp. 19–65). New York: Guilford Press. 2349–2356.
Overton, W. F. (2014b). The process-relational paradigm Seligman, M. E. P., Railton, P., Baumeister, R. F., &
and relational-developmental-systems metamodel as Sripada, C. (2013). Navigating into the future or
context. Research in Human Development, 11, driven by the past. Perspectives on Psychological
323–331. Science, 8, 119–141.
Overton, W. F. (2015). Relational developmental systems Siegler, R. S. (2006). Microgenetic analyses of learning.
and developmental science. In R. M. Lerner, W. F. In W. Damon, R. M. Lerner, D. Kuhn, & R. S. Siegler
Overton, & P. C. Molenaar (Eds.), Handbook of child (Eds.), Handbook of child psychology: Cognition, per-
psychology and developmental science, Vol. 1: Theory ception, and language (6th ed., Vol. 2, pp. 464–510).
and method (7th ed., pp. 9–62). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley. New York: Wiley.
Overton, W. F., & Lerner, R. M. (2014). Fundamental Smilansky, S. (2002). Free will, fundamental dualism, and
concepts and methods in developmental science: A the centrality of illusion. Retrieved from http://evans-
relational perspective. Research in Human experientialism.freewebspace.com/smilansky.htm
Development, 11, 63–73. Smith, S. M., Fox, P. T., Miller, K. L., Glahn, D. C., Fox,
Paul, L. A., & Hall, N. (2013). Causation: A user’s guide. P. M., Mackay, C. E., et al. (2009). Correspondence of
Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. the brain’s functional architecture during activation
Pearl, J. (2009). Causality: Models, reasoning, and infer- and rest. Proceedings of the National Academy of
ence (2nd ed.). New York: Cambridge University Sciences of the United States of America, 106,
Press. 13040–13045.
Piaget, J. (1952). The origins of intelligence in children. Spreng, R. N., Mar, R. A., & Kim, A. S. (2009). The com-
Oxford, UK: International Universities Press. mon neural basis of autobiographical memory,
Piaget, J. (1954). The construction of reality in the child. prospection, navigation, theory of mind, and the
New York: Basic. default mode: A quantitative meta-analysis. Journal of
Piaget, J. (1971). Biology and knowledge. Edinburgh, UK: Cognitive Neuroscience, 21, 489–510.
Edinburgh University Press. Sripada, C., Railton, P., Baumeister, R. F., & Seligman,
Piaget, J. (1985). The equilibration of cognitive struc- M. E. P. (2013). Reply to comment. Perspectives on
tures. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Psychological Science, 8, 151–154.
Pockett, S., Banks, W. P., & Gallagher, S. (2006). Does Thelen, E., & Smith, L. B. (1994). A dynamic systems
consciousness cause behavior? Cambridge, MA: MIT approach to the development of cognition and action.
Press. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Ravizza, M. (1994). Semi-compatibilism and the transfer Timmins, A. (2013). Kuhnian consensus & historiogra-
of non-responsibility. Philosophical Studies, 75, 61–93. phy. Journal of the Philosophy of History, 7, 82–105.
Reiss, J. (2015). Causation, evidence, and inference. Touroutoglou, A., Hollenbeck, M., Dickerson, B. C., &
New York: Routledge. Feldman Barrett, L. (2012). Dissociable large-scale
Reutlinger, A. (2013). A theory of causation in the social networks anchored in the right anterior insula sub-
and biological science. New York: Palgrave serve affective experience and attention. NeuroImage,
Macmillan. 60, 1947–1958.
Roskies, A. L. (2012). How does the neuroscience of deci- Tryon, W. W. (2009). Missing mechanism information.
sion making bear on our understanding of moral American Psychologist, 64, 273–274.
References 91

Tryon, W. W. (2012a). A connectionist network approach in developmental science. Research in Human


to psychological science: Core and corollary princi- Development, 11, 22–36.
ples. Review of General Psychology, 16, 305–317. Yarkoni, T., Poldrack, R. A., Nichols, T. E., Van Essen,
Tryon, W. W. (2012b). Emergence vs. reductionism. D. C., & Wager, T. D. (2011). Large-scale automated
American Psychologist, 67, 806–807. synthesis of human functional neuroimaging data.
Tse, P. U. (2013). The neural basis of free will: Criterial Nature Methods, 8, 665–670.
causation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Yeo, B. T., Krienen, F. M., Sepulcre, J., Sabuncu, M. R.,
Vihvelin, K. (2013). Causes, laws, and free will: Why Lashkari, D., Hollinshead, M., et al. (2011). The orga-
determinism doesn’t matter. New York: Oxford nization of the human cerebral cortex estimated by
University Press. intrinsic functional connectivity. Journal of
Vincent, J. L., Kahn, I., Snyder, A. Z., Raichle, M. E., & Neurophysiology, 106, 1125–1165.
Buckner, R. L. (2008). Evidence for a frontoparietal Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
control system revealed by intrinsic functional connec- Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science +
tivity. Journal of Neurophysiology, 100, 3328–3342. Business Media.
Wager, T. D., Barrett, L. F., Bliss-Moreau, E., Lindquist, Young, G. (2012). A unitary Neo-Piagetian/Neo-
K., Duncan, S., Kober, H., et al. (2008). The neuroim- Eriksonian model of development: Fundamental
aging of emotion. In M. Lewis, J. M. Haviland-Jones, assumptions and meta-issues. New Ideas in
& L. F. Barrett (Eds.), The handbook of emotions (3rd Psychology, 30, 241–249.
ed., pp. 249–271). New York: Guilford Press. Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feigning, and response
Wegner, D. M. (2002). The illusion of conscious will. bias in psychiatric/psychological injury: Implications
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. for practice and court. Dordrecht, Netherlands:
Witherington, D. C. (2014). Self-organization and explan- Springer Science + Business Media.
atory pluralism: Avoiding the snares of reductionism
Models and Systems of Causality
of Behavior 5

Dynamical systems theory and other systems


Chapter Introduction approaches (related to complexity) offer the
potential to explain both the structure and causal
Models in science range from metatheoretical origins of behavior (Thelen & Smith, 1994;
worldviews, to theories and mini-theories, to local Young, 2011). Moreover, the models are general
models on reduced subject matter, to straightfor- enough to apply to nonliving systems, as well.
ward empirical-centered hypotheses in research. The work in this area includes key concepts
The present chapter considers three major models for the present book, such as emergence, self-
in psychology that are more theories than mini- organization, attractors, and circular causality.
theories or larger worldviews—biopsychosocial, Along with other newer models in the field of
embodiment, and systems theory. psychology and related disciplines, such as net-
The biopsychosocial model was developed work modeling and differential susceptibility, the
originally to help explain the origins of disor- present work has a broad theoretical basis with
dered behavior, psychosomatic conditions, vul- which to work and to attempt to integrate toward
nerabilities to psychopathology, etc. (Melchert, a unifying model for psychology.
2015; Sperry, 2009), but also it has been applied
to development and other areas of psychology
(Overton, 2015; Young, 2011). It allows for a Introduction
multifactorial consideration of each of the causal
factors underlying behavior, its expression and, if The biopsychosocial model, by definition,
applicable, its treatment. As such, it stands as a attempts to be an integrative one. Originally, it
fundamental model undergirding the present was developed in the medical and illness context
work. I consider the psychological portion of the to indicate the multifactorial nature of health and
biopsychosocial model as “personal” in nature. disease. It has been applied to other areas of psy-
For example, it includes free will as a factor. This chology, including psychotherapy and develop-
topic is one of the central ones in the book. ment. With modification, it can stand as an
The view of embodiment in behavior has been integrative model in many domains of psychol-
applied especially to the area of cognition, but it ogy. However, it is more descriptive of behavior
is gaining widespread currency as a potential uni- and its causes than offering insight in exact mech-
fying model in psychology (Chemero, 2013). anisms of its origins. The model of embodiment
The research undertaken and the findings are discussed in the present chapter also might suffer
emerging in the area are intriguing. from this lack. The systems model considers the

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 93


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_5
94 5 Models and Systems of Causality of Behavior

multiplicity of factors that are involved in behav-


ior, like the biopsychosocial model, but, in addi- Biological
Time Time
tion, it includes plausible mechanisms of
Psychological
behavioral expression and change through its
concepts of self-organization, emergence, attrac- Sociocultural
tors, being on the cusp of change at far from equi-
librium, the butterfly effect, and so on.
Together, the three models discussed in this Fig. 5.1 The biopsychosocial metatheoretical approach.
Human psychology is explained by the interactions
chapter are central to the task of understanding of
among the three inextricably intertwined biopsychosocial
behavioral causality. Each offers conceptual, dimensions across time. Adapted from Melchert (2011)
methodological, and empirical foundations that
themselves should be integrated into a unified
model of behavioral causality, along with other Melchert (2015), the biopsychosocial approach is
relevant models. Moreover, they allow room for a metatheoretical one (although I disagree; it is
free will as one factor in the array of factors that more of a theoretical-level model than a meta-
influence behavior, and so fit the framework that theoretical one). For Melchert (2015) the
the present work promotes. biopsychosocial model not only is “not” a theo-
In the following section, I present in depth the retical approach, but it is also not an eclectic,
biopsychosocial model and then turn to the practice one. It needs to work in concert with an
embodiment and systems models. Because I have ethical stance in effective psychotherapeutic
presented in great depth the biopsychosocial practice. Schools of thought about psychotherapy
model and the systems model in Young (2011), should be relegated under its umbrella.
the chapter presents less material on these models Behavioral heath care should consider the fol-
relative to the one of embodiment. The latter lowing areas: (a) biological—general medical
model is a fascinating one, and the evidence for its history, childhood health history, medications,
validity is growing. Nevertheless, it can be seen as health habits/behaviors; (b) psychological—his-
one more way of combining biopsychosocial tory of presenting problems, level of psychologi-
influences in behavioral causality. That being said, cal function, individual psychological history,
I have developed in this chapter concepts related substance use/addictions, suicidal ideation/risk
to embodiment that might be quite relevant (e.g., assessment, individual development history,
embodied causation; causal embodiment). childhood abuse/neglect history, other trauma,
mental status exam, personality style/characteris-
tics; and (c) sociocultural—relationships/support
Biopsychosocial Model system, current living situation, family history,
education, employment, financial resources,
Model legal/criminal issues, military record, activities/
interests/hobbies, religion/spirituality, and (multi)
Health Melchert (2015) proposed a unifying cultural issues.
concept for psychology and behavioral health Magnavita and Anchin (2014) also supported
care in terms of the biopsychosocial model that the value of the biopsychosocial model in psy-
he labeled as biopsychosocial practice. According chotherapy. Like Melchert (2015), they consid-
to Melchert, biological, psychological, and socio- ered it a unifying construct. They contrasted
cultural influences, along with developmental the holistic and reductionistic approaches to
ones, are “inextricably intertwined” in behavior science, referring to the latter as insufficient. For
(see Fig. 5.1). A science-based psychological Magnavita and Anchin (2014), the two approaches
approach provides a unified perspective on psy- are complementary and stand in a dialectical
chological practice. It can lead the field into a relationship. In terms of paradigm, the biopsy-
paradigmatic phase (Kuhn, 1962). According to chosocial model is a systems metatheory that is a
Biopsychosocial Model 95

holistic system one. In this sense, it should be McEwen and Getz (2013) illustrated how the
called biopsychosocial systems theory. This medical model needs to incorporate psychosocial
approach potentially provides unifying principles aspects. In the context of personalized medicine,
for psychotherapy and accommodates to the lim- they advocated that the person encompasses both
its in the field that are evident at present. biological and “biographical” components. In
Note, as with my disagreement with Melchert medicine, bio-molecular aspects of the person
(2015), I cannot support the notion that a bio- need to be informed by sociocultural ones, espe-
psychosocial model is a metatheory. It is just not cially if the goal is to promote healthy brains and
in the same camp as schools of thought such as bodies, as well as healthy society. Human experi-
relationism. Even referring to it as a biopsycho- ence becomes “inscribed” in the developing per-
social systems theory does not elevate it to son, for example, in epigenetics. Also, human
meta-theoretical status. experience can work either favorably or unfavor-
Peterson, Goodie, and Andrasik (2015) ably [especially in cases of differentially suscep-
described clinical health psychology in terms of tible genes having either protective resilient or
the biopsychosocial model (see Fig. 5.2, based on reactive, potentially damaging alleles, depending
the work of Belar & Deardorff, 2009, 2015). on the presence of adverse or supportive environ-
They elaborated the factor of the psychological ments, respectively, in a Gene × Environment
component to include behavioral, emotional, and interaction]. In adverse environments, stressors
cognitive domains. They considered each of the can create an “allostasis” overload that is
factors (biological, psychological, social) as chronically unbuffered, leading to pathogenesis
varying from minimal to significant. and disease.

Fig. 5.2 A domain and


S

intensity
biopsychosocial model.
The factors in the S
biopsychosocial model
include different
domains, and they vary
in intensity toward their
contributions to clinical
psychological health.
Adapted from Peterson
et al. (2015)

BIOLOGICAL
M S
SOCIAL

PSYCHOLOGICAL

M
M

M = Minimal; S = Significant
96 5 Models and Systems of Causality of Behavior

McEwen and Getz (2013) indicated that pro- Livneh, Chan, and Kaya (2014) presented
tection and damage in health involves networked, models of disability that encapsulate causation of
interacting, nonlinearly dynamic mediators that stigma. These include the moral, biomedical,
can affect all body organs, including the brain. functional, social, and biopsychosocial models
The brain is plastic, early life experiences mark (e.g., Schultz & Stewart, 2008). As for specific
it, and the social context (gradient, e.g., socioeco- origins (determinants) of stigma, the authors
nomic status, SES) has a major role to play in developed a two-dimensional model that varies
individual and public health. along the phylogenetic–ontogenetic continuum
Both Helmchen (2013) and Stier (2014) sup- and whether sources are internally or externally
ported a biopsychosocial model of mental illness. derived (e.g., inner needs, socioculture, respec-
At the same time, it needs to specify better how tively). Livneh et al. (2014) concluded by pre-
its major components interact and operate, so that senting relevant attitude change strategies.
it is integrative rather than arbitrary.
Wiggins and Monk (2013) presented an inte- Pain The primary model of pain experience is
grated model of psychopathology that speaks to that it is biopsychosocial (Gatchel, McGeary,
the biopsychosocial model (see Fig. 5.3). It McGeary, & Lippe, 2014; Jensen & Turk, 2014).
includes changes in developmental disorder man- Flor (2014) noted there is a brain–body
ifestation with context and genetic variation. The interaction, involving neurophysiological char-
different levels are interactive, and in ways that acteristics of pain. Treatment should not only
differ depending on developmental period. be pharmacological but also psychological.

Developmental Disorder

Symptoms
Environment (Context)

Sensation/ Perception/ Cognition/ Behavior

Brain Structure & Function


(and Non-Brain Physiology)

Genetic Activity
(DNA → RNA → Protein)

Genetic Variation

Development (Time)

Fig. 5.3 The translational development neuroscience function in context. In unsupportive rather than supportive
framework. The figure indicates the generic pathway from environments, brain, psychological processes, develop-
genetic variation to disorder. Genes prescribe protein ment, and behavior can become disordered. Adapted from
activity that leads to the construction of neural structure Wiggins and Monk (2013)
and function. Psychological activity derives from brain
Biopsychosocial Model 97

Psychological interventions can have effects on to keep systems at equilibrium after environmen-
“somatic” processes, in general. The biopsycho- tal perturbations. In the broadest sense, it includes
social model of pain also has considered its posi- feed forward (damage prevention) mechanisms.
tive consequences (Bastian, Jetten, Hornsey, & Understanding individuals as biopsychosocial
Leknes, 2014). Generally, biopsychosocial mod- entities under the influence of negative feedback
els of somatic-related disorders should consider provides one common embodied process for
predisposing, precipitating, and perpetuating fac- understanding behavior. In this vein, action is not
tors (Lievesley, Rimes, & Chalder, 2014). the result of a trigger that activates a chain lead-
Two studies recently explored the relationship ing to it, but an effort to reinstate disturbed states
between pain and cognition. Schoth, Nunes, and due to environmental impact to their reference
Liossi (2012) studied the role of attentional bias levels. I note that any perspective on adaptive,
in the causation and maintenance of chronic pain. flexible, and changing behavior should offer
It leads to focusing on pain-related information, opportunities for functional change in state, or
especially in both initial orienting of attention adaptive new references, as well as their return to
and in maintained, later attention, findings that a reference point.
are consistent with a role for rumination in per-
petuating pain. This attentional bias could affect Conclusion My approach to the question of the
negatively more general cognitive performance. value of the biopsychosocial model and the
Wager and Atlas (2013) reviewed neuroimag- mechanisms involved is to refer to the full array
ing research to show that pain can be manipu- of personal psychological processes that mediate
lated psychologically because it is influenced by interaction among biology (body), psychology
social-cognitive processes. Even placebos consti- (e.g., mind), and the social (environment) in
tute cognitive interventions that can produce real determining behavior outcome, including in
changes in the processing of pain. Pain experi- development or of illness or abnormal behavior.
ence is intimately linked to megamaps in work- The personal processes involved include apprais-
ing memory, emotion, and physical pain in the als, beliefs, attitude, motivation, and so on. The
brain that partially overlap, and also pain is grand question is how these multifactorial contri-
related to the opioid system. According to Wager butions to behavior interact over time in the spe-
and Atlas (2013), biology, cognition, emotion, cific micromoments of their transactions as they
and social processes interact in pain experience, create the longitudinal course of development
indicating that mental events are more than local- and behavioral change.
ized brain patterns. In addition, mechanism does not just lie in a
biophysical process or location, such as the brain,
Comment Weidig and Michaux (2015) pro- but in a process that is more general and covers all
posed an integrative framework for the biopsy- aspects of the biopsychosocial system. In this
chosocial model. They noted an absence of sense, in the biopsychosocial model, one can
relationship understanding explicit means of speak of biopsychosocial inputs, biopsychosocial
relating between biological and psychological processes, and biopsychosocial outputs (with the
processes. Essentially, their model referred to the processes including biopsychosocial therapy),
domain of memory as an integrative ground. In while acknowledging that the distinctions between
this regard, they referred to confined and com- these levels are not as clearly cut as presented.
municative memories. The former are associa- Further, the common metric that could
tive, motor, and sensory memories, and the latter describe both the behavioral structure and the
concern cultural memes. mechanisms involved in its undergirding and
Carey, Mansell, and Tai (2014) argued that the change must be general enough to cover each of
biopsychosocial model is missing a mechanism the biological, personal/psychological, and social
underlying it, and, in this regard, they proposed a components of the model. Systems theory does
negative feedback one. Negative feedback serves afford the necessary language in these regards, in
98 5 Models and Systems of Causality of Behavior

that it describes systems in terms of constituents framework. The personal contributions we bring
that adopt patterns of organization, which, in and to our own growth and change in behavior are
of itself, is sufficient to lead to organizational based on our positioning as selves at least some-
preservation or change, e.g., depending on what free of biology and environment, which are
whether the system involved has gravitated to the passive influences compared to our active, agen-
pressure point of being too far from equilibrium. tic selves, and its elements related to free will, for
Embodiment theory might help, too, in that body, example.
brain, behavior, and mind, and so on, are not The next section of the chapter examines the
really separate entities but ones that constitu- model of embodiment, which relates cognition,
tively help compose and reflect each other, so in particular, to body-centric processes rather
that stability and change processes for one neces- than merely fully abstract, representational ones.
sarily entail stability and change processes for Models generally emphasize their special contri-
the others. butions in silos to underscore their uniqueness,
However, it might be best to find the underly- and then they begin to differentiate and integrate
ing common metric to mechanistic processes other conceptions under their umbrellas. This is
across the biological, personal/psychological, and happening to the embodiment model, as it moves
social, as well as cultural/contextual components to a more active, agentic formulation of behav-
involved in establishing behavioral stability and ioral expression, for example. In this sense, its
instability. The one that I find pertinent in this unifying potential in psychology holds promise,
regard concerns activation/inhibition coordination as it maintains. Nevertheless, all the major mod-
(Young, 2011). In this regard, behavior as well as els in psychology need the type of integration
brain processes can be redescribed quite well in toward unification being promoted in the present
this type of language. For example, I developed work, and there is not one by itself that should be
this concept while watching the baby reach, notic- privileged.
ing how interfering movements are controlled bet-
ter in the right arm and hand (and the left
hemisphere) relative to the opposite sides involved The Embodiment Model
(Young & Gagnon, 1990). Social behavior can be
described in terms of activation/inhibition coordi- Cognition Embodied
nation, as well. Moreover, psychotherapy can be
conceived as attempts to better structure behav- Model
ioral activation/inhibition coordinations in patients Foglia and Wilson (2013) noted that the construct
(and in the underlying brain processes involved). of embodied cognition is providing new perspec-
Similarly, throughout the present work, wherever tives on mind–body reductionism. This approach
I find evidence of it, I indicate how the brain is underscores the role of sensory and motor func-
involved in activation/inhibition coordination. tions in cognitive activity. The mind is consid-
Later in the book (see Chap. 31), I pursue this line ered anchored in sensory and motor groundings.
of thought and show how a model of activation/ The boundaries between cognition, body, and
inhibition coordination provides a powerful mech- context are blurred (“no fracture”). Therefore, the
anism for preserving behavioral statis and for agent’s body constrains, regulates, and fashions
effecting its change. the nature of cognition. This happens not neces-
sarily through direct intrinsic control but through
experiential reenactment in perceptual-action
Interim Conclusions systems moderated by the brain. Information is
not just represented abstractly and nonmodally.
The present book focuses on the free will as Knowledge is not just symbolic, representational,
an influential force in the causality of behavior, and propositional. Activity is not simply the
and it embeds easily in the biopsychosocial result of representational instructions.
The Embodiment Model 99

Among other mechanisms, mirror neurons nition is body-grounded but also not wholly deter-
subserve embodied cognition. They activate in mined in this way, thereby allowing for autonomy
observing/understanding another’s action and, of a “kind” to psychological processing.
moreover, they are activated when the body acts
the same way (Rizzolatti & Craighero, 2004). Philosophy
Therefore, in understanding/mentalizing about Slife and Christensen (2013) presented a philo-
the other, mirror neurons ensure that the neces- sophical approach to psychology that is compat-
sary body/motor systems are intrinsically ible with the embodied one, called “hermeneutic
involved. This network provides the foundation realism.” The focus in psychology should be not
for complex social life, social coordination, on “self-contained objects” but, rather, on
empathic emotion, learning by imitation, and “contextually-constituted” meanings. Moreover,
communication by language. Single-cell research the meanings are neither purely relativistic nor
in humans has provided the first evidence of neu- subjective, but are “grounded in the reality of the
rons responding to both the observation and exe- world.” Objects form relationships of which
cution of grasping actions (Mukamel, Ekstrom, their “betweenness” is more relevant to under-
Kaplan, Iacoboni, & Fried, 2010), so that even standing behavior than are the objects them-
individual neurons are now being detected with selves. In this view, free will exists but not in
“mirror-like properties.” isolation from mechanistic forces. Rather, it
For Foglia and Wilson (2013), the implica- exists as a range of possibilities involving con-
tions of embodied cognition include cognition straints and opportunities.
being “body-scaled” even if it is “disconnected” Tonneau (2013) also presented a philosophi-
from the environment. Second, the body is cal view compatible with embodied cognition. In
involved in cognition not only directly (in online “neorealism,” cognition and environment are uni-
embodiment) but also indirectly (in neural simu- fied. The contents of cognition reflect parts of the
lation, offline embodiment). Third, embodied environment. In this regard, consciousness ema-
online activity can be stored for use later in nates from the relationship between knower and
offline processing. Fourth, embodied cognition known.
requires certain advances in evolutionary thresh-
olds, but because species’ bodies are different,
their embodied cognition is different. Embodied Cognition
As for the roles or functions of embodied cog-
nition, it serves as constraint and distributor. For Views
the former, the body functions to cognitively con- There are different points of view on the degree
strain, e.g., talking/thinking about objects engages that embodiment characterizes cognition. In gen-
specific bodily activity patterns. For the latter, the eral, I have promoted the embodied cognition
body “spreads” cognitive activity over neural and view, but there are dissenters. At the other
nonneural structures, helping partially in realizing extreme, there are radical versions in which the
mentation. That is, the body does not just simply essence of behavior, brain, and all their manifes-
transduce perceptual input into cognition, in prep- tations are embodied.
aration to produce behavioral output from internal
cognitive processing; but, rather, the body is an Skepticism According to Wellsby and Pexman
active control agent in perception and action. (2014), although embodied cognition is a power-
Foglia and Wilson (2013) concluded that ful concept (e.g., Glenberg & Gallese, 2012),
embodied cognition addresses the traditional some argue that the converse concept of disem-
divide between considering the psychological as bodied cognition is still relevant (see Meteyard,
autonomous and the mind as reducible to the body Cuadrado, Bahrami, & Viglicco, 2012). A “strong”
(brain). An integrated perspective based on embodied cognition model maintains that cogni-
embodied cognition would acknowledge that cog- tion is constituted in sensorimotor processing and
100 5 Models and Systems of Causality of Behavior

action, recreating direct sensory experiences. Finally, Kiverstein and Miller (2015) pre-
“Secondary” embodiment models maintain that sented an updated version of radical embodied
cognitive processing activates, as a by-product, cognitive neuroscience. They included the notion
sensorimotor brain areas. A “weak” embodiment that emotions and cognitions are inseparable and
model suggests that cognitive concepts derive that both are deeply dependent on the living body.
partially from sensorimotor experience/informa- They promoted an ecological and dynamical
tion, but end up as independent organization. approach to cognitive neuroscience that builds on
Wilson and Golonka (2013) argued that the work of Chemero (2009) and Barrett (2011),
embodied cognition is not merely about how among others.
body states modify mind states. Rather, disem-
bodied cognition does not exist, and embodiment Comment
occupies the center in the organism’s effort to In the embodied point of view, I find an unre-
resolve any problem or tasks. solved tension between its Gibsonian anti-
representational stance and its valuation of
Radicalism A combined, hybrid, or “pluralist” action-oriented representations. The model is
embodied model allows for more embodiment both “skeptical” of representations yet accentu-
processing for concrete concepts and less so for ates an embodied perspective on them. For
abstract ones, which might even be disembodied Gibson, the thinker is embedded in the world,
(e.g., Dove, 2011). In this regard, Chemero (2013) and does not “causally impinge” on it. Rather, the
presented the notion of a “radical embodied cog- person interacts dynamically with it, and does not
nitive science.” It integrates phenomenological, have to form representations to do so. However,
ecological, and dynamical systems approaches although this argument might apply to perception
to psychology. For example, in this view, men- and perceptual learning, which were the focus of
tal representations are “action-oriented” (Clark, Gibson’s work, it applies less readily to the cog-
1997). Representations are geared to an organ- nitive sphere. A more dynamical model of envi-
ism’s “not-neutral” affordant perceptions of the ronment, body, and mind might argue that
environment (Gibson, 1979), as are the actions abstract representations can form beyond the
involved. The approach is consistent with a com- effects of the environment on the person, but they
putational one, at least if one broadens the scope are still environmentally mediated and constitu-
and refers to a “wide computationalism.” In the tive of interaction with the environment. That is,
latter perspective, computational system repre- neither the extreme embodiment view nor the
sentations span body, brain, and context. extreme non-embodiment view of cognition
Hutto (2013) proposed a similar approach to seems adequate in explaining cognition.
radical embodied cognitive science, which he
labeled “radical enactivism”. In this approach,
mental activity is considered embodied activity. Social/Emotional
It contrasts with the approach of traditional cog-
nitivism, which focuses on internalism, intellec- The concept of extended mind is one of an embod-
tualism, and individualism. Cognition is not ied cognition or an enactive mind (Robinson,
hands-off (off-stage, behind-the-scenes) but a 2013). The mind interacts with body and world,
hands-on engagement of the organism with fea- and these interactions are constitutive of and
tures of the environment in specific ways. inseparable from thought. Mind participates in
Cognition is self-organizing, contextualized, material events and, as it does so, feels or experi-
messily interactive, and “without representing, ences phenomenologically. Therefore, mind arises
reasoning, or thinking” about the contextual out of affect and conation standing as intermediar-
world in ways involving content (“contentful ies between the physical movements of the body
ways”). That being said, meaning-making and the qualities of mind. For Robinson (2013),
emerges from shared linguistic practices and nar- “affective-becoming-conative sociality” is the
ration, so that the mind is socially scaffolded. primary extension of “body-becoming-mind.”
The Embodiment Model 101

[Similarly, Voestermans and Verheggen (2013) joint attractors developing over self and other).
have applied the concept of embodiment to This conceptualization is not an embodied one,
culture.] per se, but stems from it in that individuation is
McGann, De Jaegher, and Di Paolo (2013) conceived as both a person-centered cognitive
provided insight into the dynamical and enactive embodiment and a social, networked one.
nature of mind. It does not inhere in the person Similarly, Gallotti (2013) referred to a second-
but is dynamically emergent in individual–con- personal plural approach to social cognition, or
text interaction. We make sense of the world by the “we” mode.
coupling, coordinating, and dynamically adapt-
ing to its constraints (e.g., Kelso, 2009). Cognition
is relational and the brain is interactive and medi- Evidence
ating. When disorder arises, it’s not localized in
the individual but resides in the engagements of Cognitive
the individual in the constitutive context. In this Glenberg, Witt, and Metcalfe (2013) provided a
perspective, the “incorporated” is considered range of studies demonstrating the importance of
environmental rather than external. embodiment in cognition. First, they reminded
In the embodied view of social cognition that in the embodied cognition view, action
(Winkielman & Kavanagh, 2013), information shapes cognition; thinking is strongly influenced
processing is shaped by specific body and ner- by body; cognition reflects a dynamic interplay
vous system “forms,” along with interactions in of brain, bodily action, and perception; the body
the physical environment. Therefore, thinking in action fashions the self and language; cogni-
involves, in part, the reproduction or “simula- tion and perception exist in order to permit and
tion” of motor and experiential states “presented” guide bodily movement; action intention influ-
when the individual engages with the focus of ences perception; emotions exist also to underpin
perception. action, and so on.
Fuchs and Koch (2014) extended the embodi- Some findings in support of this model follow.
ment concept into the emotional realm. They Glenberg et al. (2013) reviewed that Casasanto
referred to “embodied affectivity,” personal (2011) found that right- and left-handers’ think-
bodily resonance, inter-affectivity, interbodily ing about action verbs used different regions of
resonance, movement/vitality rhythms/contours, the brain. Havas, Glenberg, Gutowski, Lucarelli,
and the relevance of these concepts for psychopa- and Davidson (2010) showed that inhibiting
thology and therapy. frowning by blocking the corrugator muscle with
Similarly, Gapenne (2014) proposed an botox slows sentence processing for descriptions
embodied concept of the self. The self and world of sad and angry events but not happy ones.
(exterior) are co-constituted in action and in pro- These studies revealed that thinking appears
prioception coupling. He referred to this concept “grounded” in the “sensorimotor system.”
as applying to even the simplest of life forms. In Perception appears similarly grounded in the
this vein, Soliman, Gibson, and Glenberg (2013) action system. Gibson’s (1979) concept of affor-
proposed that the ground of culture influences the dances is consistent with this notion. Self-
embodiment of sensorimotor mechanisms in the locomotion is instrumental in perception (Held &
constitution of thoughts. The mechanism of Hein, 1963, in a kitten study). Action is essential
embodiment can serve the cognitive, social, and for learning how to perceive (Campos et al.,
cultural levels. Therefore, sensorimotor processes 2000; in an infant study).
can help unify psychology. Bodily mechanisms With adults, Brockmole, Davoli, Abrams, and
might reflect a foundational principle in the struc- Witt (2013) found that having participants place
tural and functional organization of the brain. their hands next to the visual display in studies
Also, Kyselo and Tschacher (2014) developed influences their visual attention, detection,
a joint enactive model of dyadic relationships search, and inhibition processes. Also, variations
that is based on dynamical systems theory (e.g., in apparent size of participants’ bodies in virtual
102 5 Models and Systems of Causality of Behavior

reality research affect the perceived distance to (de Groot, Smeets, Kaldewaij, Duijndam, &
objects and their size (Linkenauger, Mohler, & Semin, 2012). The signals are outside of con-
Bülthoff, 2011). The hand is used to scale the size scious access but have emotion-specific effects.
of objects that are graspable (Linkenauger, Witt, In this study, fear chemosignals generated facial
& Proffitt, 2011). expressions of fear (medial frontal is activity in
Mechanisms exist for coordinating discourse by EMG recording) and increased sniff magnitude/
aligning speaker rate, word choice, and syntax eye scanning (fear sensory acquisition). In con-
(Pickering & Garrod, 2013). Memory is enhanced trast, disgust chemosignals generated disgust-
when it is amenable to actions by the self, or when related facial expressions (in levator labii
“self involvement” otherwise is involved (e.g., activity). de Groot et al. (2012) concluded that
Engelcamp, 1995). Hearing action words, such their work supports an embodied social-commu-
as “pick,” involving the hand, activates regions of nication model (Semin, 2007).
the brain controlling hand movements (Hauk,
Johnsrude, & Pulvemüller, 2004). Understanding Brain
emotion-relevant language engages emotion- Aspell et al. (2013) provided evidence that self-
related neural systems (Havas et al., 2010). Inclusion consciousness and the body self form integrated
of action facilitates learning to read, solving math- cortical systems for bodily self-consciousness.
ematical problems, etc. (e.g., Glenberg, Willford, Embodied cognition extends into consciousness
Gibson, Goldberg, & Zhu, 2012). and self-cognition. Integration includes signals
Glenberg et al. (2013) have integrated a wide- from inside and outside the body (interoceptive
ranging literature related to embodied cognition. and exteroceptive signals, respectively), which
They have shown its importance in basic pro- are associated with distinct anatomical systems.
cesses, such as perception, and the role of the Consult their fascinating study on heartbeat, pro-
sensorimotor system even in more advanced cog- jected (“virtual”) bodies, and their synchroniza-
nitive activities, such as language and education. tion in “cardio-visual” signals.
Pulvermüller (2013) presented evidence on
Chemical the brain mechanisms involved in “embodied”
Semin and de Groot (2013) related human social- semantics, as well as abstract-symbolic general-
ity to “shared bodily state.” People respond to meaning semantics. The embodied mechanisms
other’s chemosignals, and it usually takes place are anchored in sensorimotor neural systems, in
outside of “verbal awareness,” or automatically. contrast to the non-embodied ones, which are
We are capable of distinguishing another’s sweat anchored in multimodal convergence zones (e.g.,
depending on the state in which it was collected. prefrontal, posterior parietal, temporal cortex).
Sociality has a chemical basis that leads us to Pulvermüller noted that the “semantic hubs” in
simulate the signals received in chemosensory the brain seem to express differential semantic
perception so that we “reproduce” the other’s contributions. There are semantic category
emotional state. Communication is “grounded” effects. For example, the left inferior frontal cor-
and “vicariously” reconstituted. tex (iFC) and bilateral frontocentral motor sys-
Oxytocin is being used for social enhance- tems are most strongly active when processing
ment (Farah, 2012). It is given intravenously or in action-related phrases and words. However,
inhaled doses to alter behavior (e.g., trust, gener- at the supramarginal gyrus, the left iFC is
osity). Stallen, De Dreu, Shalvi, Smidts, and most strongly activated by spatial language. The
Sanfey (2012) investigated the degree to which it temporal cortex is more involved in sounds,
stimulates in-group conformity. The results names, color/form words, and emotional terms.
showed that it can influence subjective prefer- Pulvermüller (2013) presented multiple findings
ences in context. relating the making of meaning to neuronal
In general, chemosignals are better under- activity, including in sensory and motor areas of
stood as being important in human emotions the cortex.
The Embodiment Model 103

The currents toward an integrated rather than Overall, we can conclude that the embodiment
isolationist view of person, brain, and environ- approach provides a rich source of ideas condu-
ment include the work of Schilbach et al. (2013; cive to integrating diverse areas of psychology,
and commentaries). Schilbach et al. (2013) and the brain constitutes a primary focus in this
referred to a second-person neuroscience, which regard.
they contrasted with a “spectator” view of cogni-
tion. Rather than using detached inference-
making in social knowing, we immediately Extensions
experience, interact, engage with, and know
the other through the engagement. The world is Introduction
not “ready-made” or out there, and passively In the following, I indicate how models of
construed; rather, it is embodied actively in embodiment are being integrated with other
our situated, embedded, coupled cognition. models and being extended by this integration. In
Understanding of the world is facilitated by particular, there is work relating it to the biopsy-
emotional engagement and leads to interaction chosocial model, Gibsonian affordances, net-
dynamics that are emergent, and reflective of works, and systems theory.
“inter-brain” effects on relational activity.
Froese, Iizuka, and Ikegami (2013) referred to Biopsychosocial
the “brain-body-environment-body-brain” sys- The concept of embodiment provides one possi-
tem in order to illustrate the dynamical, situated, ble cohering mechanism to the biopsychosocial
embodied, constituted, coupled social interac- model. Zhang and Risen (2014) referred to
tional approach as a second-person neuroscience embodied motivation to understand goal activa-
(see Fig. 5.4). tion. For example, sometimes physical and social

Actor/ Agent 1 Interacting with Actor/ Agent 2

Environment
(Context)

1’s Body 2’s Body

1’s Brain 2’s Brain

Fig. 5.4 Dynamical perspective on the interaction The influence of environmental context on the reciprocal,
between two situated, embodied agents/actors. Not only multiple embodiments that take place in human interac-
does the person live an embodied brain-behavior rela- tion complicate even more any understanding of behav-
tionship, for interacting people do, as well, which com- ior. Adapted from Froese et al. (2013)
plicates understanding of dyadic and group processes.
104 5 Models and Systems of Causality of Behavior

warmth correlate positively, but they might Networks


correlate negatively, too, depending on context. Bruineberg and Rietveld (2014) attempted to
Clearly, biological influences become embod- integrate the free energy principle approach to
ied in brain and behavior. But embodiment can the brain and also dynamical systems theory
also influence reciprocally brain and behavior. (especially in the concept of self-organization)
Also, it can affect social and affective processes, into their embodiment theory. In the free energy
but in turn these can affect embodiment. principle (Friston, 2010, 2011, 2012, 2013), sur-
Ultimately, the person is the seat of embodiment, prisal is a measure of the unexpectedness of an
and can influence it, in turn, thereby affecting its event, and free energy is the upper bound in sur-
influence on biology, brain, behavior, and him- or prisal that might obtain in some data, such that it
herself as an acting agent. is the sum of prediction errors or difference
between anticipated and actual sensory input.
Affordances Organisms strive to minimize free energy, for
McGann (2014) extended the construct of radical example, by using their “anticipating” brain.
embodied cognition (Chemero, 2009) by sup- Perception and action subserve this principle,
porting its alignment with an intentional theory and, in consequence, reflect the nature of the
of Gibsonian ecological affordances (Gibson, environment (that is, the niche “implies” an
1986; Heft, 1989). The mind is world-involving, organism’s structure). The organism is an agent
situated, embedded, and participatory, and so on; that “infers” the causal structure of the environ-
the person is agentic and active; and the environ- ment (not at the cognitive level, but in a generic
ment offers affordances of place that are joint. adaptive sense, to reduce surprise).
However, affordance-promoted actions cannot be
understood without considering the embodied Systems
motivations and intentions in the dynamical, As for dynamical systems theory, according to
relational nature of affordances. Bruineberg and Rietveld (2014), circular causal-
Bruineberg and Rietveld (2014) also attempted ity refers to intra-organismic, cross-level con-
an embodied-focused integration of several pre- straining relationships, whereas secondary
dominant theories. They elaborated Gibson’s circularity refers to organism-environment, mutu-
(1979) model of affordances in the environment ally constraining relationships. Self-organization
to include solicitations in a landscape or field of refers to the internal dynamics of a system that
affordances in the econiche. Individuals in con- adapt to its components and context. System
text, for example, expressing skilled intentionality, component might couple, or seek meta-stability
acquire a “grip” on the affordances or even a in their coupling and in their independent action.
“hypergrip.” Another way of understanding This regime enables systems to be poised at the
solicitations is to conceive them as gradients or edge of stability–instability so that they are ready
prediction errors helping in attunement to the to transition between multiple attractors in their
environment (or disattunement). Solicitations state space (Davids, Araújo, Hristovski, Passos,
lead to active anticipatory patterns that facilitate & Chow, 2012; Kelso, 2012). Just as there are
optimal grip. Organisms are “selectively open” to optimal affordances, there are optimal metastable
affordances that are relevant to their particular distances or environmental attunement.
circumstance. The authors concluded that skilled activity
This conception of affordances is quite consis- reflects not a set of desires or goals. Rather, it
tent with the emerging field of radical embodied concerns adaptive, coupled, dynamic self-
cognitive neuroscience (Chemero, 2009). For organizing systems that allow for adequate inter-
example, affordances function in a brain–body action, or embodied attunement and anticipation
landscape and a brain–body–environment system. involving organism in environment.
The Embodiment Model 105

Favela (2014) expanded the radical embodied Causation


cognition model of Chemero (2009, 2013) to the
area of neuroscience. In doing so, the author gave Wolff (2008) reviewed the major approaches to
less importance to the Gibsonian model of affor- understanding causation. For Hume (1975), all
dances (e.g., Gibson, 1966/1979, 1973/1983) and that people can observe is spatial–temporal conti-
gave more importance to the concept of self- guity, successive events, and covariation, but not
organized criticality (e.g., Bak, Tang, & force, necessary connection, causal power, and
Wiesenfeld, 1987, 1988). Both views of radical energy (Dowe, 2000). Therefore, conjectures of
cognitive embodiment highlight systems theory causality do not relate to “reality.” Causality is
as central in efforts to unify psychology (e.g., “invisible” and, therefore, in contemporary psy-
Thelen & Smith, 1994, 2006). This approach is chology, approaches adhering to this tradition
consistent with that of the present work. study causality only in terms of observables and
Kugler, Kelso, and Turvey (1980) had already their frequencies.
proposed that action is not a product of an inner Another Humean-type approach to causation
agent using sensory representations to develop concerns Bayesian probability network models
motor ones. Rather, human behavior is dynami- (e.g., Pearl, 2000; Sloman, 2005). However, these
cally self-organizing and nondecomposable with theories involve statistical dependencies of the
the environment. visible/observable and so also are limited in efforts
Siegel (2012) adopted a systems perspective to understand the intrinsic processes in causality.
in defining the mind as an embodied and rela- Wolff (2008) added that Michotte’s
tional process that regulates energy and informa- (1946/1963) model of causality in collisions does
tion flow. It does so both within and between not address representation of force and energy
brains. The mind is a process that is emergent mechanisms. Rather, it concerns perceptions,
from brain, body, and relational activity. Mind, possible innate mechanisms, and perceptual illu-
brain, and relationships are not independent enti- sions of causality more than casual understand-
ties but, rather, are three components of energy/ ing, per se.
information flow. They are three faces of “one Aside from Humean models of causation,
reality.” physicalist models allow for partial isomorphism
between representations and reality. Causal con-
Comment cepts can represent physical quantities in the real
Theorists in embodiment are leading the way in world, such as force and energy exchange or
efforts to integrate theoretical work over differ- transmission (Dowe, 2000). However, according
ent integrative models, by specifying linkages to Wolff (2008), physicalist models cannot dif-
with their models and other leading ones, such as ferentiate causation from other events involving
the biopsychosocial model and dynamical sys- energy transfer.
tems theory. At the same time, these extensions Wolff (2008) referred to his force dynamics
may be broadening the base of theoretical inte- model as a physicalist model. However, instead
gration, but they are missing the theoretical glue of emphasizing energy transfer, it examines pat-
that would make them genuinely integrated and terns of forces and end-states represented by
interactive. I have argued already that integrative position vectors. The vectors are (a) qualitative;
theoretical work in psychology needs to focus on (b) concern the variables of cause, “enable,” and
mechanism, such as afforded by the concept of prevent; (c) apply equally to sociopsychological
activation/inhibition coordination that cuts and physical causation; and (d) are represented as
across both efforts to characterize the “what” of tendency, concordance, and the end state
behavior and the “why.” In this regard, in the approached (result). The studies conducted in
next section of the chapter, I examine the support of the model (Wolff, 2007) suggest that a
embodiment model from the point of view of person’s causal concepts are formulated in terms
causation. of force configurations.
106 5 Models and Systems of Causality of Behavior

Wolff (2008) concluded that event dynamics embodiment, and causality search and under-
are central to causal conceptualization and indi- standing in behavior concerns “causal embodi-
cate that we are grounded to the real world as we ment.” We engage and embroil in the complexity
try to represent causality. Finally, the model helps and chaos of the physical and social worlds as
appreciate that “causation might be experienced active agents whom are physically and socially
in our own bodies.” grounded in order to explore and create causal
understanding so that we can relate appropriately
to that environment, survive in it, and ultimately
Interim Conclusions reproduce. It is not that we engage in cognition
including on causality, through embodiment;
A concept that I created to encapsulate both cau- rather, we live embodiment and cognition, includ-
sality and embodied cognition is compatible with ing on causality, and causality is central to that
the dynamic force approach to understanding cau- project. In these regards, causal embodiment
sality. The concept that makes sense in this context constitutes the quintessential modality of human
is “embodied causation.” It refers to the grounded behavior and its relational adaptation to the real-
“body-centric” origin of causal understanding. It ity of the physical and social worlds.
is consistent with the Piagetian approach to under- In terms of mental illness and psychopathol-
standing causality as a sensorimotor acquisition ogy, the concepts that I have proposed of embod-
(Young, 2011) and also with the recent research on ied causality and causal embodiment subsume
the development in infancy of causal understand- the equivalent concepts that also seem appropri-
ing (e.g., Gopnik & Wellman, 2012). ate to propose—those of “embodied etiology”
The concept of embodied causation is consis- and “etiological embodiment.” When behavior is
tent with the physicalist model of causality. disturbed or disordered, it is imperative to under-
Causality understanding develops from a partici- stand its psychiatric origins and, inevitably, that
pation in the environment in an active way that will be developmental and also sourced from the
promotes better adaptation to the environment. In body. When deep understanding of behavior is
addition, the participation is heavily organism- sought, causality must be considered its central
centric from early in life, with the person’s body axis, including in mental disorder.
constraining the nature of causal activity and This discussion of embodied causation/etiol-
shaping its understanding. ogy and causal/etiological embodiment con-
Finally, I propose that the developing embod- cludes the section of the chapter on embodiment.
ied cognition that results from active grounding in In the next section, I move to presentation of
the environment is marked by the centrality of work on systems theory. The reader will be famil-
causal search and understanding, given the impor- iar with some of its major concepts because of
tance of understanding causality for survival. their discussion in the embodiment section. I
Embodied cognition, therefore, includes embod- value this theory greatly, viewing its concepts of
ied causation and, furthermore, exists in order to emergence, self-organization, circular causality,
foster an exquisite and sensitive adaptivity in the the cusp of change, and so on, as ones that are
environment. Cognition, in general, (as well as applicable not only to my work on behavioral
embodied cognition, in particular) is an adaptive causality but also on integrating psychology.
function that exists especially to seek and explain
causality because, without its proper understand-
ing, adaptation to the environment cannot take Systems Models and Causality
place. The increasing emphasis on social cognition
fits this perspective, as well. Without proper under- Introduction
standing of the complex vicissitudes of social cau-
sality, adaptation cannot take place effectively. Systems models come in two major types. One
In all these senses, although I have been concerns complex adaptive systems (CAS)
describing “embodied causation,” the primary and agent-based modeling, and the like, and the
concept that covers the multifaceted cognition, other nonlinear dynamical systems, and the like.
Systems Models and Causality 107

The latter approach comes in two varieties, as Lineweaver, Davies, and Ruse (2013a) col-
well, depending on whether the systems involved lected workers in the hard and soft sciences and
are soft-assembled from the bottom or ground up in philosophy to consider the role of complexity
or might include some form of top-down influ- in evolution. Lineweaver, Davies, and Ruse
ence, as well. Either way, causality is understood (2013b) noted the difficulty in reaching a com-
to reside in the system as a whole through the mon understanding of complexity. About the the-
interactions among its components and their orga- sis on the directionality of evolution toward
nization, its inputs and how they are processed in increasing complexity, Gould (1996) had noted
the system, and the contexts in which they that there is no evolutionary driving force toward
dynamically reside and change or resist change. increasing complexity. However, complexity
emerges in evolution in the sense of increasing
diversity (e.g., McShea & Brandon, 2010)
Complex Adaptive Systems “by the simple accumulation of accidents.”
Others have noted that new niches provide the
Model context for the survivability of increasing
The major approaches to complexity in science accidents/complexity and that “free energy” is
reside in the approaches of Holland (2012) and needed to “generate” or “transfer” any increasing
Kauffman (1993, 2013). Holland (2012) complexity. In this regard, Chaisson (2013)
described an approach to CAS that differs from maintained that specific free energy flow/energy
Kauffman’s (1993) approach. The latter is con- rate density is important in understanding
cerned with self-organization, order, emergence, increasing complexity in the universe and life.
far-from-equilibrium (the edge of chaos), criti- Lineweaver et al. (2013b) continued that there
cality, landscapes, attractors, evolution, Boolean appears to be a complexity pyramid, and that free
networks, and so on. Holland (2012) considered energy might be oriented to keep increasing the
agents, networks and flows, control, autonomy, complexity of the most complex objects in the
boundaries, signals and their processing, adapta- pyramid. This local complexification process
tion and evolution, emergence, and so on (see affects other regions of the pyramid.
Fig. 5.5). Holland’s approach is important to cur-
rent network approaches and Kauffman’s is Applications
important in nonlinear dynamical systems work. Based on the work of Wilson and Holt (2001),
Kauffman (2013) described how Darwinian Merbitz, Merbitz, and Ripsch (2012) applied the
natural selection and complexification could concept of CAS to rehabilitation (see Tables 5.1
work synergistically in evolution. “Collective and 5.2). The upshot of the model for illness and
autocatalytic sets” can emerge spontaneously at health is that they are neither predictable nor
system phase transitions. Indeed, their emer- amenable to modeling in simple cause-effect
gence is “expected.” Moreover, because the ways. Individuals are interconnected so that the
“law” applies to any type of system amenable to systems that they form alter the predictability
phase transitions, it is generalizable beyond par- afforded by any one aspect of the system involved.
ticular materials and processes. The sets can The integrated nature of illness and health is
become webbed, linked, or cross-coupled, and indicated in the complex model of coping, stress,
transformed themselves. In becoming “general- and care giving in multiple sclerosis (Pakenham,
ized (collective) autocatalytic sets,” they can 2012; see Fig. 5.6). Stressors are impacted by all
“jointly cause … continued co-creativity” from of internal factors, context, treatment, percep-
one to the other(s), even in terms of creating new tion/appraisal, and coping strategies and
niches for each other. Kauffman (2013) con- resources, which lead to adjustment outcome.
cluded with the example of stars forming a gal- Walton (2014) viewed social problems as
axy that outlives (some of) them and also gives complex and multicaused. They are complex sys-
birth to new ones. tems with dynamic, recursive trajectories, in
108 5 Models and Systems of Causality of Behavior

Adaptive agent

[Adaptive agents
interact] Network of
adaptive agents

The aggregate behavior


and agent behavior
reciprocally interact

Because of agent
interactions, the behavior
of the aggregate is greater
than the sum of the agent
actions
Aggregate agent
[Aggregate behavior]

Fig. 5.5 Complex adaptive systems. A complex adaptive inside the boundary present for processing/sending sig-
system is comprised of interacting network agents creat- nals. Also, there are and mechanisms in place for changing
ing aggregate agents/behaviors greater than the sum of (adapting) a program in response to learning/experience.
agent actions. One interesting variation of dynamical sys- Emergence comes from patterns or properties that
tems has been described by Holland (2012), complex appear under the constraints imposed by the rules of com-
adaptive systems (cas), in general, are characterized by bination in a system. In cas, emergent properties could
subtle hierarchal arrangements of boundaries and signals. occur when coevolving signals and boundaries generate
Nodes represent bounded entities (species, neurons, new levels in hierarchical organization. Similarly, emer-
organelles); and internodal connections represent the sig- gence is generated by combining building blocks, which
nal flow. Agents are bounded (sub)systems capable of contrasts with the view of emergence as a holistic phe-
internal processing. They might be organized hierarchi- nomenon. In the latter, the emergent phenomenon cannot
cally. In other systems, the aggregate behavior depends on be reduced to an interaction of components. However, the
local interactions in distributed control. Learning can take building block approach allows for reduction. That being
place in such autonomous systems, for they are not driven said, the reduction involved surpasses the traditional
alone by current ongoing stimuli. Hierarchies could result, reduction in which “the whole is equal to the sum of its
of enclosing semi-permeable boundaries, with matching parts.” The interactions between signals and boundaries in
signals at each level. a cas cannot be simply added together. When these condi-
The components of a cas are bounded subsystems tional interactions are included, reduction is understood as
(agents) that adapt or learn as they interact. The agents part of a system’s emergent properties in signal/boundary
“accept” some signals and ignore others, with “programs” relations. Adapted from Holland (2012)

which interventions can be short-term yet “wise,” people-centered and financial-centered attractors
having long-term downstream consequences. By in the system.
targeting relevant psychological processes in Hollenstein and Lougheed (2013) applied the
complex systems, key levers or drivers of system concept of CAS to adolescence. In the CAS per-
dysregulation can be addressed with timely spective, constant, dynamic interaction moment-
interventions. by-moment both within and between people
Sturmberg, O’Halloran, and Martin (2012) causally produces behavior and also provides
applied the concept of CAS to the health explanatory mechanisms of behavioral change,
system. They referred to the opposition of including in adolescents.
Systems 109

Table 5.1 Properties of system in rehabilitation them frameworks or models. The approaches
Level Explanation involve: system dynamics, agent-based model-
1 The body has multiple interacting/self- ing, and network analysis. In the above, I have
regulating physiological systems, including reviewed Holland’s (2012) approach to agent-
biochemical/neuroendocrine feedback loops
based modeling. As for the construct of networks,
2 Behavior is determined both by an internal set
the next chapter examines it in more detail. This
of rules based and responses to new stimuli
3 Individuals are embedded within social
section of the chapter is concerned with systems.
relationships and within social, political, and The value of these approaches is that they inte-
cultural systems. These can influence grate multiple levels of analysis (from cells to
outcomes in entirely novel/unpredictable ways behavior to society) in attempting to understand
4 A small change in the system could lead to a development.
much larger change through nonlinear
DiDonato, England, Martin, and Amazeen
5 Therefore, behavior, including illness is not
predictable and it cannot be reflected in a (2013) provided a tutorial on nonlinear dynami-
simple cause and effect approach cal systems theory (Thelen & Smith, 1994, 2006).
Adapted from Wilson and Holt (2001) Nonlinearity is indicated in the example of a
horse’s gallop style shifting to a running style at
a certain speed threshold. In their review,
Table 5.2 Properties of complex adaptive systems
(CAS) in rehabilitation DiDonato et al. (2013) referred to self-
organization, emergence, attractors, fractals, and
Explanation
so on. When control parameters reach threshold,
Adaptable System element can change
elements themselves. Under the right the order parameter governing system behavior
conditions, change can happen shifts, moving the system to a different attractor
from within configuration; moreover, the change might be
Simple rules Complex outcomes can develop abrupt. Energy entering the system provides
from a few simple rules applied
“escapement,” e.g., as evidenced in oscillations
locally
across two attractors regions. As for fractals,
Emergent Continual creativity is a natural
behavior, novelty state of the system DiDonato et al. (2013) found fractal patterns in
Unpredictable in Prediction takes place globally nested patterns of change in behavior over days,
detail not in locally. For example, weeks, and months.
detailed, accurate long-range Vallacher, Van Geert, and Nowak (2015)
weather forecasting is essentially
impossible
argued that, in psychology, the dynamic approach
Self-organization Systems can appear ordered of nonlinear dynamical systems theory (NLDST;
despite not having central control. Thelen & Smith, 1996) is a promising “integra-
Self-organization takes place tive paradigm” over its diverse landscape of top-
inherently ics. Rather than considering psychological
Co-evolution A cas evolves through constant processes only in terms of external cause and
tension and balance (e.g.,
certainty vs. uncertainty) related effects, it considers them, as well, as
Adapted from Wilson and Holt (2001)
reflective of internal, intrinsic dynamical mecha-
nisms, and also their interaction with new system
input. In NLDST, variability within the person’s
behavior over time might be more important than
Systems any average in understanding behavior. The
sequence of system states leading to the present
Model also is important.
A system is comprised of a set of intercon-
Urban, Osgood, and Mabry (2011) noted that nected elements that try to find balance over iter-
there are three major scientific “methodologies” ations, or “mutual coherence.” As elements
associated with systems, although I prefer to call adjust to one another, they are self-organizing in
110 5 Models and Systems of Causality of Behavior

ILLNESS TREATMENT
E.g., disease E.g., type of
severity, treatment, side
disability, COPIN G COPIN G
effects, adherence APPRAISAL
symptoms STRATEGIES RESOURCE S
Care Tasks (e.g. ,
Care Tasks (e.g. , giving injections, Threat Emotion-focused: Internal (e.g.,
assisting with arranging doctor Harm approach (e.g., mindfulness,
self-care & visits, supervising Challenge acceptance, optimism,
mobility) medications) Control disclosure of personality,
Illness emotions) and hope)
Uncertainty avoidant (e.g.,
Self-efficacy wishful thinking)
External (e.g.,
social support,
Rebuilding Problem-focused community
STRESSOR (e.g., problem facilities,
Meaning (e.g.,
sense making, solving) finances)
benefit finding)
BIOGRAPHICS Meaning-focused
(e.g., positive
E.g., age, gender, reframing)
employment status,
ethnicity Family &
Care giving Relationship- community
Care giving context stress focused (e.g., care giving
(e.g., carer-patient appraisals Supportive resources &
relationship, co- encouragement, services
residence, care giving coercion)
duration)

ADJUSTMENT OUTCOME S

Negative (e.g., distress, depression, anxiety)

Positive (e.g., life satisfaction, positive emotions, health, social


role functioning, purpose in life, mastery)

Carer-patient relationship satisfaction, caregiving satisfaction ,


carer subjective burden

Fig. 5.6 Summary of a stress and coping framework for with MS and caregiver are depicted by regular font; and
assessing and intervening in the coping processes that variables specific to care giving are denoted by the bolded
shape adjustment to multiple sclerosis and the care giving and shaded italics. Adapted from Pakenham (2012)
role. Key generic variables applicable to both the person

a bottom-up fashion. Self-organization allows for change (self-organized criticality at a critical


the emergence of higher-order pattern from ele- value; Bak, 1996). Therefore, systems express
mental interaction. As systems stabilize, they both stability and flexibility, depending on con-
constrain system behavior toward their patterns, text. Finally, a system’s temporal patterns might
and new input “evolves” toward them even if behave fractally, with similar patterns over dif-
they are initially discrepant with them. Stable ferent time-scales (short, long).
systems are referred to as attractors, and there To conclude, Vallacher et al. (2015) noted that
might be more than one attractor in any one sys- external forces have their effects on behavior
tem Attractors are state convergence loci in the through the intrinsic dynamics mediating them in
system. External influences might perturb or dis- the systems that they engage. Ignoring system
rupt a system’s stability; in response, the system dynamics in determining causal factors will lead
might damp these influences over time, or lead to to an “incomplete and potentially misleading”
system change. understanding of behavior.
Attractors might owe their stability to control Afraimovich, Rabinovich, and Varona (2012)
parameters, and critical thresholds in the latter presented a tutorial on nonlinear dynamical
might lead to change in system organization. The systems theory. They indicated that dynamical
system might resist change until pushed to its systems are mathematical models that represent
limits, and then undergo nonlinear “dramatic” deterministic processes. In a dynamic system, a
Systems 111

state is any point in time (t > 0) that is determined system patterning. The organism constructs
solely by its initial state. A collection of variables behavior from moment to moment from among
x describes a state. The set of a system’s states multiple interacting components that combine
describes its phase space of states. States in a sys- “freely” according to context, the task at hand,
tem change in time according to the system’s set and developmental history.
of evolution operators (ϕt, t > 0) that expresses Stanton and Welsh (2012) have applied sys-
the mathematical law that governs system state tems theory to therapy with couples and family.
change (at initial point x0 to point xi at point in They were influenced by the work of
time t). Formulaically, the set of operators satis- Lunkenheimer and Dishion (2009) and col-
fies the “group identity”: leagues (e.g., Granic, Hollenstein, Dishion, &
Patterson, 2003). In systems, collective variables
f t 1 + t 2 x 0 = f t 2 (f t 1 x 0 ) are the equivalent of dependent variables and
control parameters are the equivalent of indepen-
As states follow trajectories in phase space, dent variables. Systems express patterns repre-
they follow an attractor regime if they gravitate sented as attractors (e.g., a couple gravitates
to preferred states, or their basins. The attractors easily during conflict to a “violence” attractor).
can take many forms—from point ones, to limit Attractors can be mapped in time, and critical
ones, to “strange” or chaotic ones. transition points can be identified (phase transi-
Freeman (2006) described circular causality tions). These periods are amenable to psychother-
in terms of macroscopic, top-down and apeutic intervention (e.g., moving to cooperative
microscopic, bottom-up mutual influences, such rather than hostile state space regions).
that there are no simple, direct cause-effect rela- Langer, Cohen, and Djikic (2012) applied the
tions within a system but only “second-order per- concept of attractors to mindfulness. They con-
turbations” having “higher-order capacities.” sidered mindfulness as a psychological attractor,
Macroscopic “back flow” by upper level “order and that people expressing it are considered more
parameters” helps regulate behavior by the circu- “attractive”. Dolcos, Iordan, and Dolcos (2011)
lar causality entailed in “holding or releasing” reminded that cognition involves emotion and
lower levels (e.g., subsystems). Microscopic the two are reciprocally related in complex
fluctuations might also have effects by initiating dynamical behavior.
state phase transitions. Circular causality is Cabell and Valsiner (2014a, 2014b) presented
divorced from agency, which resides in the self- a catalytic model of mental activity, which is sim-
organization of the system dynamics in toto. ilar to a systems approach. It is grounded in semi-
osis. It considers all of Aristotle’s four
causes—material, formal, efficient, and final.
Applications Typically, psychology engages in the study
mostly of the third one, which concerns the sys-
Spencer, Austin, and Schutte (2012) noted that, tem in which the cause operates. For the authors,
in systems theory, qualitative change takes place Aristotle’s other three types of causes are equally
when either the number of or the type of attractor relevant for psychology. Also, we need to study
changes (Thelen & Smith, 1994). The changes in how a phenomenon emerges, develops, and dis-
attractor organization during qualitative change appears; what form it takes and why; and what is
occur at bifurcation points. The qualitative shifts its purpose, goal, or intention.
might even transpire after gradual quantitative In semiotic cultural psychology, mediating
changes in one particular aspect of a system. For processes are viewed as changing the relation-
example, horses shift from walking to running at ship between cause and effect, stimulus–
a transition in quantitative speed after which their response, or two associated phenomena. Semiotic
gait shifts qualitatively to the new regime. regulators have a direct impact on effects, but
Spencer et al. (2012) also noted that, in sys- semiotic catalyzers are noninvasive interven-
tems, soft assembly governs the process of tions. Valsiner (2014) explained that catalysis is
112 5 Models and Systems of Causality of Behavior

a concept derived from chemistry. Toomela Brain


(2014) considered the model preliminary, e.g.,
about its proposals for how downward and Rolls (2010) described neuronal networks in
upward causation relate. Rather, for Toomela, attractor terms (see Fig. 5.7). He considered
parts of a system change qualitatively as the attractor neural networks as interconnections
whole emerges. that settle into stable firing patterns (e.g., in the

a Shallow basin, unstable Deep basin, stable


State Transition

Basin Trajectory

b Spontaneous state attractor Decision state attractor

Fig. 5.7 State transitions through basin trajectories. (a) Second, a high level of noise adds to the possibility that a
Attractor dynamics can be depicted by state transition tra- system will jump over an energy boundary from one state
jectories in effective energy landscapes, which indicate to another. For neural functioning, as depicted in the fig-
the basins of attraction by valleys. Attractor states (or ure, the noise in the network caused by random spiking
fixed points) are depicted as balls moving over the land- means that, on some trials of measurement, for given
scape, e.g., captured at the bottom of valleys. The stability inputs, the neurons in the first attractor are more likely to
of an attractor is indicated by the average time in which fire and, on other trials, the neurons in the second attractor
the system stays in a basin, resisting of noise, which can are more likely to fire. This makes the decision-making in
instigate movement to other attractor basins (and states). neural firing probabilistic. In (b), for example, the noise
Two factors determine the stability of an attractor. First, if involved influences when the neural system will jump out
the depth of an attractor basin is shallow (as in the left of the spontaneously firing, stable (low energy) state, and
compared to the right valley), less force is needed to move into the high-firing state for one “decision” or another.
an attractor (ball) from the shallow valley to another. Adapted from Rolls (2010)
Systems 113

hippocampus, a seat of memory). The intercon- I conclude that any concept of memory and its
nections are excitatory. Firing rates vary, and representation, as well as its underpinning in neu-
those that are persistent could reflect a particular rons, assemblies, and attractors, need to consider
memory. When incoming information is partial, multilevel modeling in which motivation, affect,
attractors can complete it. Attractors can vary in emotions, and the general architecture and inte-
stability and reactivity to input. The “decision- gration of the “emergent” mind works top-down
making” of competing attractors is “probabilis- reciprocally along with bottom-up influences.
tic.” Attractors can be held “online,” allowing
powerful computations.
Mustafa et al. (2012) hypothesized that the Integrating the Models
cerebral cortex is akin to a fractal structure. It is
constituted by parts that reflect similarities with In the following, I show how various develop-
the whole. Its cortical fractal structure lies espe- mental models are being integrated with a focus
cially in the irregularity of the external cortical on systems theory.
surface, and in white matter complexity, which Lickliter and Honeycutt (2013) presented the
can be represented mathematically as a fractal metatheoretical assumptions in the developmen-
dimension (FD). In their research, they found tal evolutionary approach. They maintained that
that FD was associated with fluid intellectual development unfolds within a hierarchical orga-
abilities. They referred to environmental influ- nization of embedded, reciprocally-influencing
ence on brain structure as the mediating variable relational systems. Control of developmental
in their findings. Similarly, Im et al. (2006) had processes takes place in a distributed fashion.
found that cortical surface FD related to intelli- The innate and acquired cannot be separated in
gence and years of education. their integrated multilevel interaction, which
Bassett and Gazzaniga (2011) considered the begins the moment of conception. Developmental
brain as a site of complexity organization. changes are the product of self-organization.
Complex network theory is quite applicable to its Developmental changes provide the phenotypic
study. It is characterized by emergent phenomena variation on which evolutionary forces can act.
in “bidirectional” causation and complementarity The variations arise in organismic-environmental
over top-down and bottom-up processes, with the transactions. A developmental evolutionary
former feeding back to the latter in downward framework allows for a “causal analysis” of
causation. Emergence is “upward,” that is, it behavior, “unpacking” developmental dynamics
takes place as a higher-order emergence deriving over multiple levels.
from a lower level in the system involved. The Michel (2013) described the similar develop-
mind and brain constitute an interface with “con- mental psychobiological approach. It offers
ditional causation” (causes are neither necessary explanations both of species-typical behavior and
nor sufficient in all relevant contingencies). individual differences. It explores the causal
According to Bassett and Gazzaniga (2011), mechanisms behind developmental trajectories.
the mind is not reducible in that components have It asks what are the mechanisms leading to devel-
“causal power” in systems, such as the mind– opmental behaviors and what are the ones that
brain system (referred to as “nonfundamental cau- account for their individual differences.
sality” as distinct from “determinism”). Therefore, The approach uses the concepts in the dynami-
Bassett and Gazzaniga (2011) considered “mind- cal systems approach. System elements are inter-
brain emergence” as a “strong” emergence, as dependent and express periodic (“punctuated”)
opposed to “weak” ones (e.g., substance, conjunc- phase transitions (e.g., stages) in development,
tion, property, function, living emergence). with these reorganizations resulting in the emer-
van der Helm (2012) introduced the concept gence of “new,” stable behaviors after the insta-
of “transparallel processing” to help explain how bility preceding the shifts. Perturbations that
“hyperstring-like” neural assemblies are formed. effect transitions might be small or large, and they
He referred to the latter as “gnosons.” help define individual vulnerability/resilience.
114 5 Models and Systems of Causality of Behavior

As for the relational developmental view, one that includes ourselves as participatory
Lerner, Agans, DeSouza, and Gasca (2013) agents, for example, through the activity of the
referred to the mutually-influential, bidirectional, self of ourselves and of aspects of free will. This
reciprocal, synergistic, and fused relations over approach suggests a continual interaction between
the multiple levels in development, including of the organism, agent, or individual and the envi-
the individual in context achieving adaptive ronment or context in terms of seeking and under-
developmental regulation. Gene-context relations standing causality. Given the primacy of causality
afford developmental plasticity and within- in our psychology that I am suggesting, it is as if
individual change. Diversity is substantive in we should be designated, as a species, as “Homo
development and cannot be reduced to genetic Causa” (or Homo Humanus Causa).
mechanisms alone. In this view, the human focus on causality
means that we continually “causalize,” or seek
and propose causal understanding. Moreover, we
Chapter Conclusions continually act for the causal outcomes involved
and the world is filtered for what it contributes to
Efforts to create more inclusive models in psy- causal understanding and causal action.
chology have focused on the ones mentioned in Therefore, one could argue that, as much is the
the present chapter. In later chapters, I show how case for our internal world, the external world
they apply to the area of development. All these exists only through its causal relations, or cause-
models help understand behavior and its change. effect co-ordinations. Not only our mental activ-
They consider causality to a degree. However, ity but also our relations with things, people, and
causality could be one axis that serves to inte- events are defined by their causal history and par-
grate them. The biopsychosocial model considers ticipation in causal co-ordinations.
its major components as interactional. The To summarize briefly, reality is imbued by
embodiment model considers them as constitu- causality and humans are causalizing agents. In
tive. The systems model considers them as this regard, the psychological models that we
primed for change. Together, the models offer develop should place causality at the forefront
positive portents of a more integrative model than both as an integrating concept and as the product
each of them allows by itself, despite their and process of what we do, of who we are, and of
increasing outreach. As argued throughout the what distinguishes us as exceptional. The models
present work, causality could be the interstitial should cover individual (and group) differences
glue that functions to cohere putative integrating in this regard and, as well, the change mecha-
psychological models into a unifying structure. nisms involved as we change (hopefully for the
At the same time, causality could be the essen- better both for ourselves and others).
tializing psychological characteristic of the
human species. Perhaps we adapt especially in
terms of deciphering the causal influences around References
us, reasoning about and with causality, and
becoming causal influences in our own right. Afraimovich, V. S., Rabinovich, M. I., & Varona, P.
Notions of causality that we develop should (2012). Short guide to modern nonlinear dynamics. In
not be uniquely abstract, but also related to the M. I. Rabinovich, K. J. Friston, & P. Varona (Eds.),
Principles of brain dynamics: Global state interac-
participation that we engage in life, including the tions (pp. 313–338). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
cosocial and, therefore, causality is best con- Aspell, J. E., Heydrich, L., Marillier, G., Lavanchy, T.,
ceived as emergent from and dialectical with con- Herbelin, B., & Blanke, O. (2013). Turning body and
text. That being said, causality is actively lived self inside out: Visualized heartbeat alter bodily self-
consciousness and tactile perception. Psychological
and conceived. The physicalist notion of causal- Science, 24, 2445–2453.
ity acknowledges some degree of isomorphism Bak, P. (1996). How nature works: The science of self-
between its “psycholization” and its reality, but organized criticality. New York: Springer.
References 115

Bak, P., Tang, C., & Wiesenfeld, K. (1987). Self-organized Chemero, A. (2013). Radical embodied cognitive science.
criticality: An explanation of 1/ƒ noise. Physical Review of General Psychology, 17, 145–150.
Review Letters, 59, 381–384. Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body, and
Bak, P., Tang, C., & Wiesenfeld, K. (1988). Self-organized world together again. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
criticality. Physical Review A, 38, 364–375. Davids, K., Araújo, D., Hristovski, R., Passos, P., &
Barrett, L. (2011). Beyond the Brain: How Body and Chow, J. Y. (2012). Ecological dynamics and motor
Environment Shape Animal and Human Minds. learning design in sport. In N. H. Mark Williams (Ed.),
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Skill acquisition in sport: Research, theory, and prac-
Bassett, D. S., & Gazzaniga, M. S. (2011). Understanding tice (2nd ed., pp. 112–130). London: Routledge.
complexity in the human brain. Trends in Cognitive de Groot, J. H. B., Smeets, M. A. M., Kaldewaij, A.,
Sciences, 15, 200–209. Duijndam, M. J. A., & Semin, G. R. (2012).
Bastian, B., Jetten, J., Hornsey, M. J., & Leknes, S. (2014). Chemosignals communicates human emotions.
The positive consequence of pain: A biopsychosocial Psychological Science, 23, 1417–1424.
approach. Personality and Social Psychology Review, DiDonato, M. D., England, D., Martin, C. L., & Amazeen,
18, 256–279. P. G. (2013). Dynamical analysis for developmental
Belar, C. D., & Deardorff, W. W. (2009). Clinical health science: A primer for intrigued scientists. Human
psychology in medical settings: A practitioner’s Development, 56, 59–75.
guidebook (2nd ed.). Washington, DC: American Dolcos, F., Iordan, A. D., & Dolcos, S. (2011). Neural
Psychological Association. correlates of emotion-cognition interactions: A review
Belar, C. D., & Deardorff, W. W. (2015). Fundamentals of of evidence from brain imaging investigations. Journal
assessment in clinical health psychology. In of Cognitive Psychology, 23, 669–694.
F. Andrasik, J. L. Goodie, & A. L. Peterson (Eds.), Dove, G. (2011). On the need for embodied and dis-
Biopsychosocial assessment in clinical health psy- embodied cognition. Frontiers in Psychology, 1, 242.
chology (pp. 8–20). New York: The Guilford Press. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2010.00242.
Brockmole, J. R., Davoli, C. C., Abrams, R. A., & Witt, Dowe, P. (2000). Physical causation. Cambridge, UK:
J. K. (2013). The world within reach: Effects of hand Cambridge University Press.
posture and tool-use on visual cognition. Current Engelcamp, J. (1995). Visual imagery and enactment of
Directions in Psychological Science, 22, 38–44. actions in memory. British Journal of Psychology, 86,
Bruineberg, J., & Rietveld, E. (2014). Self-organization, 227–240.
free energy minimization, and optimal grip on a field Farah, M. J. (2012). Neuroethics: The ethical, legal, and
of affordances. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 8, societal impact of neuroscience. Annual Review of
599. doi:10.3389/fnhum.2014.00599. Psychology, 63, 571–591.
Cabell, K. R., & Valsiner, J. (2014a). The catalyzing mind: Favela, L. H. (2014). Radical embodied cognitive neuro-
Beyond models of causality. New York: Springer science: Addressing “grand challenges” of the mind
Science + Business Media. sciences. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 8, 796.
Cabell, K. R., & Valsiner, J. (2014b). Systematic system- doi:10.3389/fnhum.2014.00796.
ics: Causality, catalysis, and developmental cybernet- Flor, H. (2014). Psychological pain interventions and neu-
ics. In K. R. Cabell & J. Valsiner (Eds.), The catalyzing rophysiology: Implications for a mechanism-based
mind: Beyond models of causality (pp. 3–13). approach. American Psychologist, 69, 188–196.
New York: Springer Science + Business Media. Foglia, L., & Wilson, R. A. (2013). Embodied cognition.
Campos, J. J., Anderson, D. I., Barbu-Roth, M. A., Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science, 4,
Hubbard, E. M., Hertenstein, M. J., & Witherington, 319–325.
D. (2000). Travel broadens the mind. Infancy, 1, Freeman, W. J. (2006). Consciousness, intentionality, and
149–219. causality. In S. Pockett, W. P. Banks, & S. Gallagher
Carey, T. A., Mansell, W., & Tai, S. J. (2014). A biopsy- (Eds.), Does consciousness cause behavior?
chosocial model based on negative feedback and con- (pp. 73–105). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
trol. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 8, 94. Friston, K. (2010). The free-energy principle: A unified brain
doi:10.3389/fnhum.2014.00094. theory? Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 11, 127–138.
Casasanto, D. (2011). Different bodies, different minds: Friston, K. (2011). Embodied inference: Or ‘I think there-
The body specificity of language and thought. fore I am, if I am what I think.’. In W. Tschacher &
Current Directions in Psychological Science, 20, C. Bergomi (Eds.), The implications of embodiment
378–383. (cognition and communication) (pp. 89–125). Exeter,
Chaisson, E. J. (2013). Using complexity science to UK: Imprint Academic.
search for unity in the natural sciences. In C. H. Friston, K. (2012). A free energy principle for biological
Lineweaver, P. C. W. Davies, & M. Ruse (Eds.), systems. Entropy, 14, 2100–2121.
Complexity and the arrow of time (pp. 68–79). Friston, K. (2013). Active inference and free energy.
New York: Cambridge University Press. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36, 212–213.
Chemero, A. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. Froese, T., Iizuka, H., & Ikegami, T. (2013). From
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. synthetic modeling of social interaction to dynamic
116 5 Models and Systems of Causality of Behavior

theories of brain-body-environment-body-brain sys- Frontiers in Psychology, 4, 269. doi:10.3389/


tems. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36, 420–421. fpsyg.2013.00269.
Fuchs, T., & Koch, S. C. (2014). Embodied affectivity: On Holland, J. H. (2012). Signals and boundaries: Building
moving and being moved. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, blocks for complex adaptive systems. Cambridge, MA:
508. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00508. MIT Press.
Gallotti, M. (2013). Why not the first-person plural in Hollenstein, T., & Lougheed, J. P. (2013). Beyond storm
social cognition? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36, and stress: Typically, transactions, timing, and tem-
422–423. perament to account for adolescent change. American
Gapenne, O. (2014). The co-constitution of the self and Psychologist, 68, 444–454.
the world: Action and proprioceptive coupling. Hume, D. (1975). In L. A. Selby-Bigge & P. H. Nidditch
Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 594. doi:10.3389/ (Eds.), Enquiry concerning human understanding and
fpsyg.2014.00594. concerning in principles of morals (3rd ed.).
Gatchel, R. J., McGeary, D. D., McGeary, C. A., & Lippe, New York: Oxford University Press. (Original work
B. (2014). Interdisciplinary chronic pain management: published 1748).
Past, present, and future. American Psychologist, 69, Hutto, D. D. (2013). Psychology unified: From folk psy-
119–130. chology to radical enactivism. Review of General
Gibson, J. J. (1966/1979). The ecological approach to Psychology, 17, 174–178.
visual perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin. Im, K., Lee, J. M., Yoon, U., Shin, Y. W., Hong, S. B.,
Gibson, J. J. (1973/1983). The senses considered as per- Kim, I. Y., et al. (2006). Fractal dimension in human
ceptual systems. Westport, CT: Greenwood Press. cortical surface: Multiple regression analysis with cor-
Gibson, J. J. (1979). The ecological approach to visual tical thickness, sulcal depth, and folding area. Human
perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin. Brain Mapping, 27, 994–1003.
Gibson, J. J. (1986). The ecological approach to visual Jensen, M. P., & Turk, D. C. (2014). Contributions of psy-
perception. New York: Psychology Press. chology to the understanding and treatment of people
Glenberg, A. M., & Gallese, V. (2012). Action-based lan- with chronic pain. American Psychologist, 69,
guage: A theory of language acquisition, comprehen- 105–118.
sion, and production. Cortex, 48, 905–922. Kauffman, S. A. (1993). The origins of order: Self-
Glenberg, A. M., Willford, J., Gibson, B., Goldberg, A., & organization and selection in evolution. New York:
Zhu, X. (2012). Improving reading to improve math. Oxford University Press.
Scientific Studies of Reading, 16, 316–340. Kauffman, S. A. (2013). Evolution beyond Newton,
Glenberg, A. M., Witt, J. K., & Metcalfe, J. (2013). From Darwin, and entailing law: The origins of complexity
the revolution to embodiment: 25 years of cognitive in the evolving biosphere. In C. H. Lineweaver, P. C.
psychology. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 8, W. Davies, & M. Ruse (Eds.), Complexity and the
573–585. arrow of time (pp. 162–190). New York: Cambridge
Gopnik, A., & Wellman, H. M. (2012). Reconstructing University Press.
constructivism: Causal models, Bayesian learning Kelso, J. A. S. (2009). Coordination dynamics. In R. A.
mechanisms, and the theory. Psychological Bulletin, Meyers (Ed.), Encyclopedia of complexity and system
138, 1085–1108. science (pp. 1537–1564). Heidelberg, Germany:
Gould, S. J. (1996). Full house: The spread of excellence Springer Science + Business Media.
from Plato to Darwin. New York: Harmony Books. Kelso, J. A. S. (2012). Multistability and metastability:
Granic, I., Hollenstein, T., Dishion, T. J., & Patterson, Understanding dynamic coordination in the brain.
G. R. (2003). Longitudinal analysis of flexibility and Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, B:
reorganization in early adolescence: A dynamic sys- Biological Sciences, 367, 906–918.
tems study of family interactions. Developmental Kiverstein, J., & Miller, M. (2015). The embodied brain:
Psychology, 39, 606–617. Towards a radical embodied cognitive neuroscience.
Hauk, O., Johnsrude, I., & Pulvemüller, F. (2004). Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 9, 237. doi:10.3389/
Somatotopic representation of action words in human fnhum.2015.00237.
motor and premotor cortex. Neuron, 41, 301–307. Kugler, P. N., Kelso, J. A. S., & Turvey, M. T. (1980).
Havas, D. A., Glenberg, A. M., Gutowski, K. A., Lucarelli, Coordinative structures as dissipative structures:
M. J., & Davidson, R. J. (2010). Cosmetic use of botu- I. Theoretical lines of convergence. In G. E.
linum toxin-A affects processing of emotional lan- Stelmach & J. Requin (Eds.), Tutorials in motor
guage. Psychological Science, 21, 895–900. behavior (pp. 3–47). Amsterdam, Netherlands:
Heft, H. (1989). Affordances and the body: An intentional North-Holland.
analysis of Gibson’s ecological approach to visual percep- Kuhn, T. S. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions
tion. Journal of the Theory of Social Behavior, 19, 1–30. (3rd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Held, R., & Hein, A. (1963). Movement-produced simula- Kyselo, M., & Tschacher, W. (2014). An enactive and
tion in the development of visually guided behavior. dynamical systems theory account of dyadic
Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology, relationships. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 452.
56, 872–876. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00452.
Helmchen, H. (2013). Different conceptions of mental ill- Langer, E. J., Cohen, M., & Djikic, M. (2012). Mindfulness
ness: Consequences for the association with patients. as a psychological attractor: The effect on children.
References 117

Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 42, McGann, M., De Jaegher, H., & Di Paolo, E. (2013).
1114–1122. Enaction and psychology. Review of General
Lerner, R. M., Agans, J. P., DeSouza, L. M., & Gasca, S. Psychology, 17, 203–209.
(2013). Describing, explaining, and optimizing McShea, D. W., & Brandon, R. N. (2010). Biology’s first
within-individual change across the life span: A rela- law. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
tional developmental systems perspective. Review of Melchert, T. P. (2011). Foundations of professional psy-
General Psychology, 17, 179–183. chology: The end of theoretical orientations and the
Lickliter, R., & Honeycutt, H. (2013). A developmental emergence of the biopsychosocial approach. London,
evolutionary framework for psychology. Review of ON: Elsevier.
General Psychology, 17, 184–189. Melchert, T. P. (2015). Biopsychosocial practice: A
Lievesley, K., Rimes, K., & Chalder, T. (2014). A review science-based framework for behavioral health
of the predisposing, precipitating and perpetuating care. Washington, DC: American Psychological
factors in Chronic Fatigue Syndrome in children and Association.
adolescents. Clinical Psychology Review, 34, Merbitz, N. H., Merbitz, C. T., & Ripsch, J. P. (2012).
233–248. Rehabilitation outcomes and assessment: Toward
Lineweaver, C. H., Davies, P. C. W., & Ruse, M. (2013a). a model of complex adaptive rehabilitation. In
Complexity and the arrow of time. New York: P. Kennedy (Ed.), The oxford handbook of rehabilita-
Cambridge University Press. tion psychology (pp. 96–127). New York: Oxford
Lineweaver, C. H., Davies, P. C. W., & Ruse, M. (2013b). University Press.
What is complexity? Is it increasing? In C. H. Meteyard, L., Cuadrado, S. R., Bahrami, B., & Viglicco,
Lineweaver, P. C. W. Davies, & M. Ruse (Eds.), G. (2012). Coming of age: A review of embodiment
Complexity and the arrow of time (pp. 3–16). and the neuroscience of semantics. Cortex, 48,
New York: Cambridge University Press. 788–804.
Linkenauger, S. A., Mohler, B. J., & Bülthoff, H. H. Michel, G. F. (2013). The role of developmental psycho-
(2011, May). Welcome to wonderland: The apparent biology in the unification of psychology. Review of
size of the self-representing avatar’s hands and arms General Psychology, 17, 210–215.
influences perceived size and shape in virtual environ- Michotte, A. E. (1946/1963). The perception of causality.
ments. Poster presented at the 10th Annual meeting of New York: Basic Books.
the Vision Sciences Society, Tampa, FL. Mukamel, R., Ekstrom, A. D., Kaplan, J., Iacoboni, M., &
Linkenauger, S. A., Witt, J. K., & Proffitt, D. R. (2011). Fried, I. (2010). Single-neuron responses in humans
Taking a hands-on approach: Apparent grasping abil- during execution and observation of actions. Current
ity scales the perception of object size. Journal of Biology, 20, 750–756.
Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Mustafa, N., Ahearn, T. S., Waiter, G. D., Murray, A. D.,
Performance, 37, 1432–1441. Whalley, L. J., & Staff, R. T. (2012). Brain structural
Livneh, H., Chan, F., & Kaya, C. (2014). Stigma related to complexity and life course cognitive change.
physical and sensory disabilities. In P. W. Corrigan NeuroImage, 61, 694–701.
(Ed.), The stigma of disease and disability: Overton, W. F. (2015). Relational developmental systems
Understanding causes and overcoming injustices and developmental science. In R. M. Lerner, W. F.
(pp. 93–120). Washington, DC: American Overton, & P. C. Molenaar (Eds.), Handbook of child
Psychological Association. psychology and developmental science, Vol. 1: Theory
Lunkenheimer, E. S., & Dishion, T. J. (2009). and method (7th ed., pp. 9–62). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.
Developmental psychopathology: Maladaptive and Pakenham, K. I. (2012). Multiple sclerosis. In P. Kennedy
adaptive attractors in children’s close relationships. In (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of rehabilitation psychol-
S. J. Guastello, M. Koopmans, & D. Pincus (Eds.), ogy (pp. 211–234). New York: Oxford University
Chaos and complexity in psychology: The theory of Press.
nonlinear dynamical system (pp. 282–306). New York: Pearl, J. (2000). Causality: Models, reasoning, and infer-
Cambridge University Press. ence. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.
Magnavita, J. J., & Anchin, J. C. (2014). The emergence Peterson, A. L., Goodie, J. L., & Andrasik, F. (2015).
of a unifying paradigm for psychotherapy. In J. J. Introduction to biopsychosocial assessment in clinical
Magnavita & J. C. Anchin (Eds.), Unifying psycho- health psychology. In F. Andrasik, J. L. Goodie, &
therapy: Principles, methods, and evidence from clini- A. L. Peterson (Eds.), Biopsychosocial assessment in
cal science (pp. 3–34). New York: Springer Publishing clinical health psychology (pp. 3–7). New York: The
Company. Guilford Press.
McEwen, B. S., & Getz, L. (2013). Lifetime experiences, Pickering, M., & Garrod, S. (2013). An integrated view of
the brain and personalized medicine: An integrative language production and comprehension. Behavioral
perspective. Metabolism Clinical and Experimental, & Brain Sciences, 36, 329–347.
62, S20–S26. Pulvermüller, F. (2013). How neurons make meaning:
McGann, M. (2014). Enacting a social ecology: Radically Brain mechanisms for embodied and abstract-
embodied intersubjectivity. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, symbolic semantics. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 17,
1321. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.01321. 458–470.
118 5 Models and Systems of Causality of Behavior

Rizzolatti, G., & Craighero, K. (2004). The mirror-neuron Sturmberg, J. P., O’Halloran, D. M., & Martin, C. M.
system. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 27, 169–192. (2012). Understanding health system reform – A com-
Robinson, D. (2013). Feeling extended: Sociality as plex adaptive systems perspective. Journal of
extended body-becoming-mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 18, 202–208.
Press. Thelen, E., & Smith, L. B. (1994). A dynamic systems
Rolls, E. T. (2010). Attractor networks. Wiley approach to the development of cognition and action.
Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science, 1, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
119–134. Thelen, E., & Smith, L. B. (1996). A dynamic systems
Schilbach, L., Timmermans, B., Reddy, V., Costall, A., approach to the development of cognition and action.
Bente, G., Schlicht, T., et al. (2013). Toward a second- Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/Bradford Books.
person neuroscience. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, Thelen, E., & Smith, L. B. (2006). Dynamic systems theo-
36, 393–462. ries. In R. M. Lerner (Ed.), Handbook of child psy-
Schoth, D. E., Nunes, V. D., & Liossi, C. (2012). chology: Theoretical models of human development
Attentional bias toward pain-related information in (Vol. 1, pp. 258–312). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.
chronic pain; a meta-analysis of visual-probe investi- Tonneau, F. (2013). Neorealism: Unifying cognition and
gations. Clinical Psychology Review, 32, 13–25. environment. Review of General Psychology, 17,
Schultz, I. Z., & Stewart, A. M. (2008). Disentangling dis- 237–242.
ability quagmire in psychological injury and law. Part Toomela, A. (2014). A structural systemic theory of cau-
II. Evolution of disability models: Conceptual, meth- sality and catalysis. In K. R. Cabell & J. Valsiner
odological and forensic issues. Psychological Injury (Eds.), The catalyzing mind: Beyond models of causal-
and Law, 1, 103–121. ity (pp. 271–292). New York: Springer Science +
Semin, G. R. (2007). Grounding communication: Business Media.
Synchrony. In A. W. Kruglanski & E. T. Higgins Urban, J. B., Osgood, N. D., & Mabry, P. L. (2011).
(Eds.), Social psychology: Handbook of basic princi- Developmental systems science: Exploring the appli-
ples (2nd ed., pp. 630–649). New York: Guilford Press. cation of systems science methods to developmental
Semin, G. R., & de Groot, J. H. B. (2013). The chemical science questions. Research in Human Development,
bases of human sociality. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8, 1–25.
17, 427–429. Vallacher, R. R., Van Geert, P., & Nowak, A. (2015).
Siegel, D. J. (2012). The developing mind: How relation- The intrinsic dynamics of psychological process.
ships and the brain interact to shape who we are (2nd Current Directions in Psychological Science, 24,
ed.). New York: The Guilford Press. 58–64.
Slife, B. D., & Christensen, T. R. (2013). Hermeneutic Vallerand, R. J., Mageau, G. A., Ratelle, C., Léonard, M.,
realism: Toward a truly meaningful psychology. Blanchard, C., Koestner, R., et al. (2003). Les passions
Review of General Psychology, 17, 230–236. de l’âme: On obsessive and harmonious passion.
Sloman, S. (2005). Causal models: How people think Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 85,
about the world and its alternatives. New York: 756–767.
Oxford University Press. Valsiner, J. (2014). Breaking the arrows of causality: The
Soliman, T., Gibson, A., & Glenberg, A. M. (2013). idea of catalysis in its making. In K. R. Cabell &
Sensory motor mechanisms unify psychology: The J. Valsiner (Eds.), The catalyzing mind: Beyond mod-
embodiment of culture. Frontiers in Psychology, 4, els of causality (pp. 17–32). New York: Springer
885. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00885. Science + Business Media.
Spencer, J. P., Austin, A., & Schutte, A. R. (2012). van der Helm, P. A. (2012). Cognitive architecture of per-
Contributions of dynamic systems theory to cognitive ceptual organization: From neurons to gnosons.
development. Cognitive Development, 27, 401–418. Cognitive Process, 13, 13–40.
Sperry, L. (2009). Treatment of chronic medical condi- Voestermans, P., & Verheggen, T. (2013). Culture as
tions: Cognitive-behavioral therapy strategies and embodiment: The social turning of behavior. West
integrative treatment protocols. Washington, DC: Sussex, UK: Wiley-Blackwell.
American Psychological Association. Wager, T. D., & Atlas, L. Y. (2013). How is pain influ-
Stallen, M., De Dreu, C. K. W., Shalvi, S., Smidts, A., & enced by cognition? Neuroimaging weighs in.
Sanfey, A. G. (2012). The herding hormone: Oxytocin Perspectives on Psychological Science, 8, 91–97.
stimulates in-group conformity. Psychological Walton, G. M. (2014). The new science of wise psycho-
Science, 23, 1288–1292. logical interventions. Current Directions in
Stanton, M., & Welsh, R. (2012). Systemic thinking in Psychological Science, 23, 73–82.
couple and family psychology research and practice. Weidig, T., & Michaux, G. (2015). How the tower of infor-
Couple and Family Psychology: Research and mation leads to an integrated framework for biopsy-
Practice, 1, 14–30. chosocial ideas. New Ideas in Psychology, 36, 25–29.
Stier, M. (2014). The biopsychosocial model between Wellsby, M., & Pexman, P. M. (2014). Developing embod-
biologism and arbitrariness. A commentary to ied cognition: Insights from children’s concepts and
H. Helmchen. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 126. language processing. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 506.
doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00126. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00506.
References 119

Wiggins, J. L., & Monk, C. S. (2013). A translational Wolff, P. (2007). Representing causation. Journal of
neuroscience framework for the development of Experimental Psychology: General, 136, 82–111.
socioemotional functioning in health and psychopa- Wolff, P. (2008). Dynamics and the perception of causal
thology. Development and Psychopathology, 25, events. In T. Shipley & J. Zacks (Eds.), Understanding
1293–1309. events: How humans see, represent, and act on events.
Wilson, A. D., & Golonka, S. (2013). Embodied cognition New York: Oxford University Press.
is not what you think it is. Frontiers in Psychology, 4, Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
58. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00058. Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science +
Wilson, T., & Holt, T. (2001). Complexity science: Business Media.
Complexity and clinical care. British Medical Journal, Young, G., & Gagnon, M. (1990). Neonatal laterality,
323, 685–688. birth stress, familial sinistrality, and left brain inhibi-
Winkielman, P., & Kavanagh, L. C. (2013). The embodied tion. Developmental Neuropsychology, 6, 127–150.
perspective on cognition-emotion interactions. In Zhang, Y., & Risen, J. L. (2014). Embodied motivation:
M. D. Robinson, E. R. Watkins, & E. Harmon-Jones Using a goal systems framework to understand the
(Eds.), Handbook of cognition and emotion (pp. 213– preference for social and physical warmth. Journal of
230). New York: Guilford Press. Personality and Social Psychology, 107, 965–977.
Statistical Concepts and Networks
in Causality 6

former model is related to potential outcomes


Chapter Introduction and the latter model to counterfactuals (directed
acyclic graphs, DAGs). The chapter refers to
This chapter focuses on statistical concepts and Pearl’s (2014a) updating of his important work
applications in the study of causality over a range (Pearl, 2000, 2009).
of topics in psychology and related disciplines. It Epidemiology is an observational science and
shows that even classic designs related to uncov- so it is highly dependent on statistical techniques
ering causal influences (controlled studies, ran- for inferring causality. In this present chapter,
domized control trials) can be complemented Shrout, Keyes, and Ornstein (2011), in particular,
statistically by informative approaches. In addi- present the various statistical approaches in epide-
tion, the chapter introduces the concept of net- miology. The works of Rubin and of Pearl are cen-
works in psychology and related disciplines, tral in this discipline, too, but chapters in Shrout
which is a cardinal concept in several chapters et al. (2011) show how they are being revised.
and one that permits the type of integration in The Bayesian approach constitutes a major
psychology being sought in the book. The work advance in the field and is becoming increasingly
in networks brings with it a new set of concepts important and prevalent. I review the accessible
in how components of networks relate to each summary of the Bayesian approach provided by
other. Also, this work is heavily statistical, for van der Schoot et al. (2013).
example, in calculating the concepts of efficiency Other work elaborates methods in statistics that
and betweenness in networks. help elucidate causal inference. In particular, in
The first part of the chapter looks at causal mod- this regard in this chapter, I review the work of
eling in psychological testing theory, for which Berzuini, Dawid, and Bernardinelli (2012a, 2012b)
Markus and Borsboom (2013) covered a range of on approaches to this question. It is noteworthy
theories and issues. For example, for testing, they that the work of Rubin and Pearl is involved (and
considered reflective, formative, and mutualistic updated). The book by Berzuini et al. includes a
models and, for causation, they considered regular- chapter by Rutter (2012) on relevant design.
ity, counterfactual, and process theories. The next section of the chapter provides exam-
Shadish and Sullivan (2012) explored in depth ples of psychological study in which causality has
three major approaches to statistical causal mod- been a central focus. Often, these designs are lon-
els. There is much overlap in their review and gitudinal and consider possible reverse causation
that of Markus and Borsboom (2013). They com- (e.g., pre-existing factors can account for patterns
pared and contrasted the classic causal model imputed to a putative intervening variable).
(Campbell) with those of Rubin and Pearl. The Generally, in this type of research, confounders,

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 121


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_6
122 6 Statistical Concepts and Networks in Causality

moderating, and mediating influences need to be Testing and Causality


considered.
In the area of psychopathology, Haynes has Introduction
been a leader in the field in explaining how cau-
sality can be determined. He has augmented his The two fields of statistics (and mathematics) and
classic 1992 work with another (Haynes, O’Brien, conceptions of reality are fields of inquiry that
& Kaholokula, 2011), which I review. influence each other. Statistical scholarship
Friston, Moran, and Seth (2013) described the involves more than methodological tools, because
techniques that are used to establish neuronal statistical methods reflect naturally present con-
connectivity in brain research, such as in fMRI cepts that they are meant to represent. At the
(functional magnetic resonance imaging). The same time, proposals of naturally present con-
dynamic approach has been complemented by cepts might be bereft of the subtleties that math-
the newer Granger Causality (GC) approach. The ematics allow, and so they can be complemented
latter originated in economics but has been and fleshed out by translation into mathematics,
applied to multiple disciplines. where possible. That being said, statistics and
GC has been applied to ecology, as well. The mathematics cannot propose by themselves the
next portion of the chapter presents work in the concepts needed to understand nature. They
area of ecology related to causality involving GC might emanate from and reflect them, but con-
and other approaches. This work could have ceptual modeling can take place independently
import for psychopathology (e.g., bipolarity), from them. However, statistics and mathematics
given the effort to map tonic and phasic activity can be so far advanced that they actually create
in ecological systems. the natural concepts that we seek. They are lan-
The chapter terminates with an in-depth pre- guages in their own right that verbal representa-
sentation of the concepts of networks in psychol- tions of nature might find hard to grasp. Truly,
ogy. Borsboom and colleagues have been leaders science needs statistics and mathematics to stand
in the field in network modeling of psychological at the frontlines of its conceptual endeavors, and
disorder, and I describe their work on PTSD not just its empirical ones.
(posttraumatic stress disorder), in particular
(McNally et al., 2015). The major types of net-
works in psychological phenomena relate to cen- Testing
trality compared to various measures of
dispersion. McNally et al. (2015) investigated the Markus and Borsboom (2013) offered a view of
symptom structure in PTSD with respect to their test validity theorizing in which causation is cen-
dynamical linkages. They indicated that their tral. Their points of view are indicated by the fol-
approach is superior to the standard latent con- lowing questions. Do latent constructs act to cause
struct model of psychological disorder. Other test score values, as in latent variable models? Or,
workers have investigated PTSD in ways that do behavioral/test item indices act to cause latent
speak to networks, and this research includes constructs? Or, rather, is there no causal relation-
research on biomarkers and the brain. However, I ship involved, merely empirical ones? The latent
argue for a more integrated approach to networks variable argument maintains that individual differ-
in psychopathology, consistent with a more trans- ence in (item) response probabilities are “caused”
diagnostic approach, for example, and one that by individual differences in the latent variable,
determines core symptoms of disorder, as well. aside from other item factors. The other views
Note that the concept of networks is explored in deny this classic version of test theory.
more depth in the ensuing chapters on the brain Markus and Borsboom elaborated that, in
and its lateralization. As well, it surfaces in the models governing testing statistics, behavior
chapters on the DSM-5 (Diagnostic and Statistical domain theory (BDT) conceptualizes item
Manual of Mental Disorder, Fifth Edition; responses as samples from behavior domains,
American Psychiatric Association, 2013). which is one way of conceptualizing constructs.
Testing and Causality 123

In the causal theory of measurement (CTM), con- This concept is conducive to a network model,
structs represent common causes that underlie such as in directed acyclic graph (DAG) causal
sets of item responses. The former model requires modeling (Pearl, 2009). In this model, if there are
generalization from item to domain, and is no feedback loops, conditional independence
“agnostic” about causation, while the latter is relations between the variables in the network
“generic” about causal inference. can be found (which is not the case for latent
These theoretical test models relate to the psy- variable models). However, generally, in the psy-
chometric models of reflective and formative test chological sphere, network nodes are connected
construction, respectively. In the former model, and reciprocal. The authors noted that the model
standard statistical clustering approaches are needs further work for effective application
used (e.g., factor analysis); individual item scores psychometrically.
are decomposed into a common latent variable To conclude, for traits such as found in per-
and a unique score. In the latter model, newer sta- sonality, one can take the stance that they reflect
tistical methods are used (e.g., principle compo- constructs, or that they, simply, are pragmatic
nents analysis); a composite variable is modeled synthesizing descriptions. Further work is needed
as a weighted summation of item scores. These to integrate these approaches, and, in this regard,
contrasting positions (BDT, CTM) can be com- variations of network modeling might be the ave-
bined into a compatibilist model within the nue to take.
reflective approach by considering items as caus-
ally homogenous behavior domains. They reflect
“attributes” that cause item scores. They lead to Causality
domain scores that supervene over item scores.
As for causality in measurement, Markus and Markus and Borsboom (2013) considered three
Borsboom (2013) returned to the difference major theories of causation. (a) In regularity the-
between reflective and formative models. In the ory, causation is found in basic regularities in
former model, test scores are modeled as effects nature, actual states, and empirical reductionist
of the construct. It implies that item responses variables. (b) Counterfactual theories attempt to
have local independence. In the latter model, test reduce causation to counterfactuals (such as “but-
scores are modeled as causes of the construct. It for” evidence), and are quite popular today (e.g.,
denies local independence of item responses. The Pearl, 2009; Rubin, 1974). (c) Process theories
reflective model has a step in its working that concern mechanisms, or the assumptions under-
tests whether the composite score calculated is an lying the theories.
estimate of the attribute, unlike the case for the Regularity theory is not much more than
formative model. “probability” theory about regularities in actual
Markus and Borsboom (2013) proposed that it events. Counterfactuals examine “unrealized pos-
is difficult to establish unifactorial models, such as sibilities.” Process theories are about the causal
“g” for intelligence, because there are usually processes that “sustain” causal relationships.
multiple underlying latent variables or causes About interpretation, regularity theory does
involved. Even when, statistically, one factor not go much beyond the evidence. Counterfactual
seems predominant, simply, it could be through theory seeks evidence about possible dependen-
shared multiple “bonds.” A similar model has been cies. Process theories seek evidence beyond
proposed, the watershed model, in which there are dependencies.
downstream phenotypes and upstream influences, Markus and Borsboom (2013) ended their
which are more distal, such as genes, and with book with work on causal interpretations in mea-
intermediate influences along the pathway, such as surement models. In regularity causation, models
cerebral volume and neural plasticity. are robust when control variables are “inert.” It
An alternate model of intelligence considers seeks generalization to new populations and situ-
its subtests as positively intercorrelated, or ations (“transfer over inert variables”). In coun-
“mutualistic” (Van der Maas et al., 2006). terfactual causation, interventions are applied,
124 6 Statistical Concepts and Networks in Causality

and it seeks support for causal links that are the theoretical constructs that they supposedly
robust against changing control variables. In pro- represent). CCM gives importance to threats to
cess causation, causal models remain robust to validity, and these should be minimized by appro-
interventions that do not change the response priate study design.
process. It seeks evidence that the mechanism is In RCM, Y represents the outcome measure.
responsible for the relevant causal link. The independent variable is W. Y(1) represents
Markus and Borsboom (2013) have presented the potential outcome if the unit/participant is
a work at the frontier of test validity theory. I exposed to the treatment level of W(1). Y(0) rep-
have left aside their mathematical work, concepts resents the potential outcome if there is no such
on validity, and so on. However, the authors are exposure (W = 0). Given these parameters, the
to be complemented for placing causation at the potential individual causal effect is the difference
forefront in test construction and modeling. between Y(1) and Y(0). Once treatment begins,
depending on which is administered, potential
outcomes become measurable. Therefore, the
Statistical Causal Modeling difficulty in RCM is estimating missing, nonob-
served potential outcomes, which are sometimes
Introduction referred to as counterfactuals.
In PCM, causal inference is established by a set
Shadish and Sullivan (2012) compared and con- of statistical rules, including nonparametric struc-
trasted three primary statistical causal models in tural equation models (SEM) and path analysis.
psychological science: Campbell’s Causal Model DAGs resemble diagrams but include graph the-
(CCM); Rubin’s Causal Model (RCM); and ory and elements from logic study. They are
Pearl’s Causal Model (PCM). The first model Markovian (acyclic). Being nonparametric in
was developed by Campbell (1957) and then SEMs, they do not specify whether links between
extended (e.g., Shadish, Cook, & Campbell, nodes are linear, quadratic, cubic, etc. Nodes are
2002). The second model is attributed to a group represented by single solid dots in DAGs. Also,
of workers headed by Rubin (e.g., Holland, 1986; arrows represent “edges,” which indicate the link
Rubin, 2004a, 2004b, 2010; and also Rubin & between variables (e.g., X, Y). When arrows are
Thomas, 1992). The third model is based on the “directed,” or are going in one direction, they indi-
work of Pearl and colleagues (e.g., Pearl, 2000, cate the presumed causal effect or relationship.
2009; Tian & Pearl, 2000). CCM is based on Edges could be bidirectional, could form path
validity typology, RCM on estimating potential sequences, etc. Statistically independent variables
outcomes, with its core assumption of stable- are considered “d” separated (directional separa-
unit-treatment-value assumption (SUTVA); and tion). The mathematical operator do(x) helps
PCM on path models based on DAGs. model causal effects and counterfactuals.
Shadish and Sullivan (2012) noted that PCM
differs from CCM and RCM by emphasizing
Models explanatory compared to descriptive causation
(respectively, addressing the causal model within
CCM begins with the distinction between inter- which X and Y are embedded; did X cause Y?).
nal and external validity, or representativeness The explanations sought provide the basis for
and generalizability (the latter is considered the more general causal claims (the necessary and
most important type of validity). It adds statisti- sufficient conditions that allow for generalized
cal conclusion validity (the validity of inferences descriptive causal relations).
about the correlation/covariation between treat- Also, Shadish and Sullivan (2012) pointed out
ment and outcome) and, as well, construct valid- that PCM’s definition of causal effect depends on
ity, which is a mainstay of psychological science solving an equation set that represents a DAG in
(inferring validity from a study’s operations to order to estimate the effect of X (X = x) on Y,
Epidemiology 125

using the do(x) operator (usually by calculating a Hill’s (1965) framework is the classic one in
regression coefficient). Another approach is in arriving at decisions about causal inference in
relation to the difference in the effect involving X epidemiology. For example, in temporality, expo-
as x1 and x2. sure to the causal factor precedes disease onset in
According to Shadish and Sullivan (2012), a reasonable amount of time. Causality decision
critics of the PCM note that cause-probing stud- making is a process of judgment. Biological
ies in field settings cannot lead to accurate DAGs interaction refers to the relationship of the causal
(e.g., due to selection biases). PCM is an induc- components in disease. Statistical interaction is
tivist approach and both CCM and RCM require not equivalent to this—it refers to the joint effects
good research design and deduction. of different exposures.
Bracken (2013) referred to the ultimate cause
as equivalent to Aristotle’s final one. It is the nec-
Comment essary and sufficient cause, the tipping cause that
produces a disease, notwithstanding risk factors
Shadish and Sullivan concluded that the three that are proximal in the core of causation.
models are beginning to cross-reference each Rabins (2013) developed a causal epidemio-
other, and this portends a truly integrated theory logical model that refers to predisposing (vulner-
of causation in the social sciences. Similarly, ability) and precipitating (triggering) cause
Gelman (2011) noted that PCM “do” operators [Generally, there is also perpetuating cause that
are like interventions. The “causality-as- accompanies the other two]. For Rabins, two
intervention” perspective needs to be comple- other causes in epidemiology concern program-
mented by a “system-variable” perspective. matic cause and purposive cause. Programmatic
Pearl (2014a) furthered his work on statistical cause refers to systemic, interactional factors and
modeling by developing notions and mathematics purposive cause to the why an event occurred
related to the interpretation and identification of (e.g., natural selection). The four levels in this
causal mediation. According to Pearl (2014a), the model were derived from the Aristotelian con-
modeling presented could facilitate real-world cepts of material, efficient, formal, and final
causal scenario understanding. cause, respectively.

Epidemiology Statistical Models

Introduction Shrout et al. (2011) co-edited a book on the topic


of epidemiological study of psychopathology, and
Gerstman (2013) presented the epidemiological it covers a range of topics conceptually and meth-
view of causality. Disease is induced by causal odologically related to the question. The difficulty
interactions, some of the components of which that this area of study needs to confront with
must necessarily be present. Other factors are respect to causality concerns making causal infer-
contributing. Causal complements complete the ences from observational data. The contributors
set of needed components for a disease. Causes presented both conceptual and methodological
are arrayed in a causal web, some of which are advances that removed some of the uncertainties
direct, downstream, or proximal and others of inevitably associated with the question. The book
which are indirect, upstream, or distal. Direct deals with the models by Rubin and Pearl and
causes usually are found at the microlevel, and colleagues, but gives insight beyond them, too.
indirect ones at the macrolevel. Deciding the In the book’s introduction, Shrout (2011) pre-
presence of causality in a system demands causal sented several outstanding themes in causal analy-
inference, given the observational, nonexperi- sis. Rubin (1974, 1978) pioneered work on making
mental nature of epidemiology. strong causal inferences even in nonexperimental
126 6 Statistical Concepts and Networks in Causality

studies by using a “potential outcomes approach.” analysis of a causal dynamic, the next step of
The approach asks to consider the differential determining the meaning of the data might not be
effects of causes A vs. B as they might influence a clear. Causality is heterogeneous in scope and
given individual, even though the person cannot effects are individualized (e.g., to intervention).
experience both causes/conditions. Only one Schwartz, Gatto, and Campbell (2011) pre-
treatment, for example, can be administered to an sented a variation of the counterfactual approach
individual for a given outcome measurement. and its emphasis on causal intervention or manip-
Shrout (2011) pointed out that although indi- ulation. It involves two preliminary steps—causal
vidual causal effects cannot be known in this area identification and causal explanation. The former
of study, the average causal effects can be esti- concerns identifying whether an exposure/treat-
mated in appropriate research designs. In particu- ment had caused an outcome, while the latter
lar, between-individual information can be used concerns how the exposure/treatment caused it.
to estimate the within-person treatment counter- Causation is multiply determined and can be
factual potential outcome causal effects. established through manipulation.
However, in this type of research, the subjects Schwartz et al. (2011) contended that manipu-
must be equivalent on all relevant parameters, or lation in experiments or hypotheticals constitute
be interchangeable. Rubin (1980, 1990) referred ideal cases that do not necessarily apply to the real
to this assumption as SUTVA, as mentioned. world. A study might have internal validity but not
In experiments with actual clinical trials, external validity, lacking real-world generaliza-
methodological confounders relate to nonadher- tion. Therefore, Schwartz et al. (2011) developed
ence to treatment, missing data, and confounding their model of an integrated counterfactual
variables, which serve to create bias in the causal approach (ICA). In step 1, causal identification is
effect. Participants might be dealt with in terms undertaken, following Mackie’s (1965, 1974) con-
of intent to treat (ITT). As for nonexperimental cept of INUS (insufficient but necessary compo-
observational studies, the alleged causal effects nents of unnecessary but sufficient causes) and
might be overstated without consideration of all Rothman’s (1976) “causal pies.” The upshot of the
confounding variables. Given the difficulties in approach is that causality is multi-determined.
designing randomized controlled trials (RCTs) Schwartz et al. (2011) contrasted the ICA
for many of the topics in psychopathology, alter- model with the traditional potential outcomes
nate designs, such as quasi-experimental ones, approach (see Table 6.1). Whereas in the former,
might be used. the goal is to establish effects of causes, in the lat-
However, analytic approaches have been ter, the goal is to establish causes of effects. The
developed to deal with confounding variables. former’s quantitative approach can inform the lat-
Pearl’s (2000, 2009) work on DAGs is the most ter, which remains a qualitative one. Moreover, in
noteworthy in this regard. DAGs constitute ICA any factor can be a cause, even if it is not
explicit statements of assumed causal paths. They manipulable. In interpretation, the former model
include concepts such as “do” operators, causal expects inconsistencies but not the latter.
“descendents,” and “control” variables. About causal explanation, it involves tradi-
Shrout (2011) noted that DAGs tend to empha- tional concepts of validity (construct, and exter-
size causal relations as if they had their effects nal). What ingredients and pathways are involved
simultaneously, without due consideration of and can the results be generalized?
temporal patterns. For example, outcome might As for causal manipulation, Schwartz et al.
be unstable and change over time. Also, Shrout (2011) contended that the interpretative approach
(2011) noted the difference in mediation and should involve dynamic complexity theory and sys-
moderation of causal effects. Mediators might tems analysis. This promotes an integrated causal
fully or partially explain causal effects, and are understanding that can account for feedback loops.
considered involved in indirect causal paths. It facilitates appropriate policy and therapeutic
Moreover, even if moderators (influences) and decisions. In this step, the focus is on prediction
mediators are fully established in a mediation and on the mediators, moderators, and other
Bayesian Approach 127

Table 6.1 Comparison of the potential outcomes model and the integrated counterfactual approach
Potential outcomes model Integrated counterfactual approach
Goal Estimates true causal effects Identifies true causes
• Estimate • Identify
• Quantitative • Qualitative
• Effects of causes • Causes of effects
Mean Compares two potential outcomes Compares a fact with a counterfactual
• Entire population under two exposures • Exposed under two conditions
• Manipulable causes • Any factor
• Stable Unit Treatment Value Assumption (SUTVA) • Construct validity
• Mimics random assignment • Mimics assignment of exposed
Interpretation Potential outcome in future Causal effect of past
• Consistency expected • Inconsistency expected
Adopted by permission of Oxford University Press. Schwartz et al. (2011). What would have been is not what would
be: Counterfactuals of the past and potential outcomes of the future. In P. E. Shrout, K. M. Keyes, & K. Ornstein (Eds.),
Causality and psychopathology: Finding the determinants of disorders and their cures (pp. 25–46). New York: Oxford
University Press. Reprinted by permission of Oxford University Press, USA. [Table 2.1, Page 39]

nodes in the system. The authors concluded that analysis (BA) is that it permits the incorporation
the methods for this level in their model are not of background knowledge into statistical testing,
yet fully developed. instead of setting aside lessons from past studies.
The major statistical underpinnings to BA com-
pared to NHST relate to that, in the latter, the
Comment paradigm is “frequentist,” whereas, for the for-
mer, it is “subjective.”
Kendler (2011) advocated for the interven-
tionist/counterfactual approach for psychiatry.
Psychopathology is ill-suited to the deductive- Models
nomological and mechanistic approaches to
causality, in that these approaches are reductive. In the NHST frequentist approach, the base of
In contrast, DAG/interventionist/counterfactual calculations depends on “long run” frequency,
approaches can account for the “extraordinary” such as in an infinite coin toss. For this example,
complexity of psychiatric disorders and their the probability p of head and tail outcomes is
causes. The approach is practical, empirical, enumerated in a “sample space” of possibilities.
atheoretical, and causality-oriented (“optimal”). In the BA subjective approach, probability is
interpreted as “the subjective experience of
uncertainty.” The paradigmatic example for this
Bayesian Approach statistical approach to probability is “placing a
bet.” This approach allows for learning from
Introduction experience, such as from prior information and
using personal judgment. Once the outcome is
According to van der Schoot et al. (2013), the established, it leads to appropriate revision of pri-
Bayesian approach to statistical analysis offers ors. The ingredients of the BA approach, there-
an alternative to traditional approaches and fore, include the following core factors.
might allow for better understanding of psycho- They help contrast the BA approach from the
logical phenomena. The contrasting approach, frequentist one:
the predominant one in psychological science, is (a) Background knowledge of the parameters of
referred to as null hypothesis significance testing the model being tested. This ingredient is
(NHST; in it Ho is contrasted to the experimental “captured” in the distribution of priors, or
hypothesis H1). The main advantage of Bayesian “prior distribution,” which might take the
128 6 Statistical Concepts and Networks in Causality

form of a normal distribution. The uncer- Priors need to be determined before examination
tainty parameter is expressed by the variance of obtained data.
in the prior distribution, the inverse of which According to BT, prior distributions and cur-
is referred to as “precision.” rent data are employed in combination to form
(b) The second BA ingredient is constituted by the posterior distribution. In most cases, a simu-
the information contained in the sample data. lation process using Markovian chain Monte
This “observed” evidence is expressed by the Carlo methods specifies the posterior distribu-
“likelihood function” of the sample data in tion. It uses an iterative procedure to estimate
light of the model parameters. parameters instead of traditional analysis for
(c) The third ingredient in BA reflects a combi- “point estimates.”
nation of the prior two. It is referred to as the In the traditional approach, confidence inter-
“posterior inference.” vals (CIs; e.g., 95 %) specify the certainty of the
Together, these three fundamentals constitute range of possible values associated with a result
a working version of Bayes’ theorem (BT). obtained statistically (or, better, the degree to
Specifically BT states that an updated under- which the true parameter is captured under Ho).
standing of parameters of interest, given observed The equivalent BA calculation to this frequentist
data, depends on prior knowledge about these approach is referred to as “posterior probabilities
parameters weighted by the current evidence, as intervals” (PPIs). This “credibility” interval
based on the parameters. refers to the probability (e.g., 95 %) in the popu-
The knowledge and empirical base in any area lation at hand that the parameter at issue lays
of study might not allow for enough prior infor- between the two specified values. Although clas-
mation to help in elaborating posterior infer- sical CIs are interpreted this way, that is mis-
ences. In the BA approach, this state of affairs taken, for they are really reflections of how well
can still be captured into statistical specification. replications of the same study will capture the
Quantifying “ignorance” is as important as quan- fixed yet unknown parameter at issue, assuming
tifying cumulative understanding in an area. If that the alternative hypothesis about the parame-
the prior distribution cannot be estimated with ter is “true.” Thus, PPIs appear “easier” to com-
confidence, different prior specifications are municate than NHST CIs. Moreover, the more
compared for outcomes according to their influ- priors are accurate estimates, the more Bayesian
ence, in a process of prior “sensitivity analysis.” PPIs are lower than equivalent NHST CIs; that is,
If there is none of relevant prior data, accumu- one can be “more certain” about the obtained sta-
lated knowledge, or meta-analyses, the prior dis- tistical results.
tribution is referred to as “noninformative” and, Model fitting is a statistical process in BA
in this regard, it parallels the NHST and its fre- accomplished with the chi-square statistic. It con-
quentist approach of letting the data speak for trasts with traditional frequentist approaches,
themselves. e.g., SEM, which evaluate an entire model rather
However, often, informative expected prior than a single hypothesis. Model fitting in BA
distributions can be estimated and, in such cases, involves assessing model predictive accuracy via
the parameters involved are referred to as “hyper- posterior “predictive checking.” The better the
parameters.” They might refer to an estimated model fits, the less the data are discrepant, and
prior mean or average and the associated prior the BA process inherently functions toward arriv-
precision. If the precision estimate is low (the ing at this end because of BA’s capacity to adjust
associated prior variance is high), the prior distri- priors in light of accrued knowledge. Chi-square
bution is considered “low-informative.” Every is used in cases in which model fit is quantified
parameter in an applicable model requires speci- by computing Bayesian posterior predictive p
fication of its associated prior distribution. These values (ppps). The ppp value is calculated as the
become more accurate estimates with appropriate proportion of chi-square values obtained in simu-
specification of inclusion/exclusion criteria. lated data relevant to the problem that are in
Methods 129

excess of the actual data, so that models that fit et al. (2013) referred the interested reader to
well have ppp values of around 0.50. the online version of the article, which includes
demonstrations of applicable statistical programs
(e.g., Mplus; Muthén & Asparouhov, 2012).
Conclusion Indeed, even the brain can be described in
attributes related to freedom. The Bayesian
According to van der Schoot et al. (2013), even model has been applied to brain theory (De
when there are large sample sizes and all parame- Ridder, Vanneste, & Freeman, 2014). A Bayesian
ters are normally distributed, BA might represent brain is like a “probability machine” aimed at
a better approach than NHST because of its advan- reducing the perception of uncertainty, prediction
tages in interpretation (even though in such cases error, and “free energy” (Friston, 2009, 2010).
the specific results would be quite comparable). Bayesian models of behavior are important to
First, the results in BA are more “intuitive,” being the present work on causality of behavior. The
focused on predictive accuracy. Second, BA indeterminacy of causal influences and their sub-
incorporates background knowledge via a prior jective appraisals are evident in this approach.
distribution. Also, it specifies when there is a lack Therefore, it is consistent with a model of behav-
or ignorance of such knowledge. When the latter ioral causality that de-emphasizes the inevitable
is present, they might influence results. Third, the one-to-one correspondence between (a) biological
BA procedure allows for updating knowledge, and social/environmental influences on behavior,
instead of engaging in repeated null hypothesis and their interaction and (b) behavioral outcome.
testing in an area. Practically, in particular, there is
less worry about small sample sizes and about
non-normal distributions of parameters. Methods
The authors concluded that Bayesian meth-
ods could be applied fruitfully to psychological Introduction
study. They contrasted frequentist and Bayesian
statistics in the following way. (a) For definition The statistical study of causality is an essential
of p value, traditionally, p refers to the probability component to its scientific study. Berzuini et al.
of obtaining the same or more extreme data in the (2012a) described approaches in the field. In the
population, assuming Ho is true. In BA, p value following, I focus on background and material
is the probability of H0, or “the (null) hypoth- accessible to psychology.
esis.” (b) For sample sizes, the NHST approach Berzuini et al. (2012b) noted that before the
requires large ones when normal theory-based field began to mature (Fisher, 1935), epidemiol-
measures are used and, in BA, this is “not necessar- ogy and biostatistics were cautious about causal-
ily” the case. (c) For inclusion of prior knowledge, ity. Studies had to be “secure” and did not rely on
the contrast lies in the fact that it is not part of any special assumptions pertaining to the nature
the statistical procedure in NHST, but it is pos- of any “uncontrolled variation.” Only through
sible in BA. (d) For nature of model parameters, randomization in experimental studies could
in NHST, they are “unknown but fixed,” whereas security be achieved, in that any pre-existing
in BA they are “unknown and therefore random.” group differences in treatment groups are con-
(e) For population parameters, “one true value” trolled by randomization.
in NHST is contrasted with “a distribution of The classic epidemiological approach to
values reflecting certainty” in BA. (f) For defin- causality is based on Hill’s (1965) criteria (see
ing certainty, compare “the sampling distribu- Table 6.2). They allow for inference about cau-
tion” based on the notion of “infinite repeated sality in the absence of critical experimentation
sampling” in NHST with “probability distribu- and solely on observational data (see Chen &
tion for the population parameter” in BA. (g) For Cao, 2012).
estimated intervals, CI in NHST is contrasted Hill’s (1965) criteria for establishing causa-
with credibility interval in BA. van der Schoot tion in observational studies constituted an
130 6 Statistical Concepts and Networks in Causality

Table 6.2 Hill’s criteria for causation individual cases (which is important legally, for
Criteria Explanation example), as to the population level. In this regard,
Strength of The stronger the more likely they make the distinction between “scientific”
association causal causality, which is interested in the “effects of
Consistency The observed association causes,” and “legal” causality, which is concerned
repeatable in different
populations at different times
with the “causes of effects.”
Temporal The cause precedes the effect Sauce and Matzel (2013) distinguished
relationship between the normative causation of behavior and
Biological gradient Dose–response relationship the causes of individual differences in behavior.
Plausibility Must make sense biologically The former might be only an ideal in that sys-
Coherence The observation should not temic variation in behavior is the norm. Moreover,
conflict with existing knowledge individual differences result from an interaction
Experimental A controlled study firmly of causes. Sauce and Matzel (2013) concluded
evidence supports causation
that, in this sense, correlational methods are quite
Specificity Associated with only one outcome
relevant to the study of causality.
Analogy Can be applied to similar case
Adapted from Hill (1965)

Designs
advance in the area. He proposed a list of guide-
lines to support inferences about causal interpre- Rutter (2012) examined “natural” or “quasi”
tation in such studies. experiments, or the research designs available
At the philosophical level, Berzuini et al. other than randomization ones, such as in behav-
(2012b) referred to Mackie’s (1965) INUS model ior genetics. He found that causal inferences
and Wright’s (1988) NESS one. The latter refers could be established with natural experiments
to “necessary element for the sufficiency of a suf- (Cook & Campbell, 1979; Shadish et al., 2002).
ficient set” and the former, as mentioned, to “an Beyond genetically sensitive designs (twin,
insufficient but necessary part of a necessary but adoptee, migration studies), one could examine
sufficient condition.” discordant sibling pairs, the children of twins,
As reviewed above, cause-effect relations were offspring of assisted reproductive technology
also studied through potential outcomes (Rubin, applications, adoption involving radical change
1974) and graphical representation (e.g., Non in environment (Romanian orphanage studies),
Parametric Structural Equation Models, NPSEMs; universal introduction of risk (WWII famine
Pearl, 2000; also called DAGs) approaches. The studies), and universal removal of risk (stopping
decision theoretic approach (Dawid, 2012) devel- use of putatively dangerous environmental vari-
oped as an alternative and is considered superor- ables). To rule out reverse causation, designs
dinate to these latter approaches. could include Mendelian randomization and
Berzuini et al. (2012b) remarked that studies study of early puberty. To deal with unmeasured
based on randomization might be secure but do confounders, one approach is to use regression
little to unravel mechanism. They described that discontinuity design. Rutter (2012) concluded
there are different approaches to the concept of that no design is free of limitations. Emsley and
mechanism, each having different statistical Dunn (2012) noted the potential mediators in ran-
approaches. For example, one could ask if a treat- domized control trials involving psychotherapy.
ment causally affects an outcome directly or indi- Donofrino, Class, Lahey, and Larsson (2014)
rectly (via mediators and moderators, respectively; suggested that family-based, quasi-experimental
Baron & Kenny, 1986). designs can be used carefully to test the causal link
Berzuini et al. (2012b) continued that causality between early risk factors and later psychopatho-
is dynamic and its elucidation requires synthesis logical outcomes independent of confounding
of multiple streams of evidence. Moreover, it factors. These techniques include design features
applies as much to establishing causal relations in that can act to “rule out” confounding influences
Causal Mediation 131

and, therefore, are more powerful in this regard finer-grained change at critical developmental
than statistical techniques involving the control of junctions. Also, within-individual changes allow
relevant covariates. Similar to Rutter (2012), children to serve as their own control in the more
Donofrino et al. (2014) noted the utility of family- elaborate statistical procedures available (e.g.,
based quasi-experimental designs, which include regression discontinuity).
sibling comparison, cotwin control, offspring of
siblings/twins, adoption at birth, and in vitro
fertilization. Causal Mediation

Introduction
Statistical Strategies
Shpitser (2012) described “compromise”
McLanahan, Tach, and Schneider (2013) reviewed approaches to potential outcome (e.g., Rubin’s)
the multiple methodological strategies being used and Non-Parametric Structural Equation Models
to ascertain causal effects when questions arise (NPSEM; e.g., Pearl’s) approaches. They include
about variable bias and reverse causality. The minimal causal models (MCMs, Robins &
topic they addressed concerned the effects of Richardson, 2011) and using covariate adjustment
father absence. The studies reviewed use innova- in NPSEMs for identifying causal effects (Shpitser,
tions such as lagged dependent variable (LDV) VanderWeele, & Robins, 2010). Both Dawid
models, growth curve models, individual fixed (2012) and Greenland (2012) have noted that there
effects models, sibling fixed effects models, pro- is no formal explication of statistical causality that
pensity score matching models, and natural could satisfy the different approaches.
experiments. Each approach was considered to
have limitations as well as advantages, with the
LDV and growth curve models tending to find Statistical Strategies
“stronger” evidence for some outcome variables.
Duncan and Magnuson (2012) indicated how MacKinnon and Pirlott (2015) examined statisti-
components of socioeconomic status (SES) cal approaches for enhancing causal interpreta-
could be causally related to cognitive function- tion in statistical mediation methods. They
ing even without the possibility of studying presented new statistical methods to help infer
global SES in experimental designs. For exam- mediator variables (M) as indicators of causes or
ple, quasi-experimental or natural experiments psychological processes underlying outcome
could take place (e.g., increased income avail- (dependent) variables (Y) at issue (independent of
able through change in income tax policies) in independent variables, X) in research. The first
ongoing research on children’s cognitive func- approach might be to reduce the effect of con-
tion. Or, actual early intervention programs can founder bias and the second to address their pos-
be studied experimentally in random assignment sible influences. Confounder bias severely limits
designs in which aspects of cognitive function the capacity to infer causation of the mediator for
are measured. the dependent outcome variable. Randomization
To move from correlates to causes, Jaffee, research can deal with confounders, at least for
Strait, and Odgers (2011) suggested using quasi- the relationship of X to M and X to Y, but not of
experimental and twin research designs. the M to Y mediation (the “b” effect in regres-
Statistically, the authors recommended propensity sion), where “a” and “c” represent the estimated
score approaches (e.g., Rosenbaum & Rubin, X to M and X to Y relations).
1985) and group-based trajectory modeling com- To control for confounder bias, in sensitivity
bined with them. To conclude, to help ascertain analysis, counterfactual/potential outcomes mod-
causal chains, Jaffee et al. (2011) recommended eling can be used. This type of modeling is
the use of longitudinal research with measurement needed because there is no randomization experi-
burst designs. This allows capturing short-term ment and, in the typical case, individuals partici-
132 6 Statistical Concepts and Networks in Causality

pate in only one condition. The strategy in this For longitudinal mediation analyses, there are
approach is to estimate outcome by asking the three major types: the approaches of (a) cross-
counterfactual “what might their behavior be oth- lagged panel modeling (CLPM); (b) latent growth
erwise?” Practically, one could determine how curve modeling (LGM); and (c) latent change
large a confounder effect on the M to Y relation scores (LCS). Even better models are emerging
must exist in order to compromise causal inter- in this regard, such as state-space modeling
pretation. MacKinnon and Pirlott (2015) referred (SSM), and continuous time modeling (CTM).
to this method under the rubric of “average causal For example, the former recognizes explicitly
mediation effect” (ACME). A second approach that mediation is a “within-person” process; it
was developed by VanderWeele (2010), and is uses either a single individual’s multivariate time
beyond the scope of the present paper. A third series or those of multiple people.
approach is the left-out variables error method For the section of causal inference for indirect
(LOVE). It calculates correlations using a effects, Preacher (2015) referred to the Campbell
hypothesized confounder (for the confounder approach (e.g., Campbell & Stanley, 1963),
with Y and with M), making an observed media- which is a design-based one, and model-based
tion effect zero (MacKinnon, Cox, Miocevic, & traditions (e.g., Rubin, 1974, 2004a). These
Kisbu-Sakarya, 2012). approaches had been compared in Shadish and
As for statistical methods to improve causal Sullivan (2012), as reviewed above. Other
conclusions from mediation data, new approaches approaches in this regard include Pearl’s (2009)
to address violations of assumptions about con- DAGs approach. Imai, Jo, and Stuart (2011) and
founder bias have been formulated. They involve: Imai, Tingley, and Yamamoto (2013) have devel-
(a) comprehensive structural equation models oped an approach that borrows the strength of
(Bollen, 1989); (b) instrumental variable methods each of these approaches, especially the design-
(Holland, 1988; Sobel, 2008); (c) principal strati- and model-based approaches.
fication (Frangakis & Rubin, 2002; Jo, 2008); and Categorical/nonnormal variables in mediation
(d) inverse probability weighting (Robins, Hernán, modeling include generalized linear mediation mod-
& Brumback, 2000). In (a), the researcher attempts els (GLMs). For mediation in multilevel designs,
to measure all possible confounders; in (b), a ran- Preacher (2015) referred to multilevel modeling
domized X predicts M and then the predicted val- strategies and multilevel structural equation model-
ues of M predict Y. The coefficient related M ing. He concluded that there is not one correct way
predicted to Y can stand as the causal estimator of to implement mediation analysis of data.
b (under certain conditions); in (c), investigators Pearl (2014a, 2014b) reviewed the foundations
identity hypothetical subsets of subjects on the of mediation analysis, building on his earlier work
basis of how M might change in response to exper- (e.g., Pearl, 2000). Part of his goal was to compare
imental manipulation X or control (an approach his approach that of Imai and colleagues (e.g.,
applicable to categorical mediators); and in (d), Imai, Keele, & Tingley, 2010; Imai, Keele, Tingley,
investigators use observed covariates to measure & Yamamoto, 2014), who used an “ignorability”-
confounder effects and then to adjust analyses to based approach. Pearl’s approach is based on
remove any confounder bias. DAGs, as we have seen, which he deems essential
Mediation analyses are designed to extract in judging/interpreting plausibility because, for
information about causal mechanism(s) through identification analysis, it enables researchers to
which a predictor variable affects an outcome or “mechanize” choices made of relevant covariates.
outcomes. Preacher (2015) reviewed current His approach focuses on the “natural” mediated
approaches to statistical mediation analysis. effect, which concerns the expected output change
They include mediation analysis in: (a) longitu- when letting the mediator change “as if” the input
dinal research; (b) in causal inferences; (c) for changed. Pearl concluded that, for proper defini-
discrete/nonnormal variables; and (d) in multi- tion, the concept of mediation requires counterfac-
level designs. tual conditionals rather than Bayes ones.
Applications 133

Comment According to Haynes et al. (2012), causes can


be sufficient, necessary, insufficient, and imme-
This concludes a complex sojourn into the statis- diate (proximal). A sufficient cause does not have
tical basis in the study of causality, and work in to be exclusive in eliciting the indicated outcome.
epidemiology has led the field. The classic A necessary cause can still occur without the out-
approach of establishing validity as best one can come taking place. An insufficient cause implies
has been supplemented by the approaches of that multiple causative factors need to be present
potential outcomes and DAGs, and these, in turn, in order to induce the outcome, including the one
have been revised. Moreover, other models have at issue. An immediate or proximal cause is indi-
been developed. In addition, meditational analy- cated by temporal contiguity, but practically, it is
ses have taken center stage, and the tests that can hard to determine if intervening causes are indeed
be used are becoming too complex for simple excluded in the chain. Distal causes precede
presentation in a brief review, so that the reader proximal ones, such as in the case of medication
should consult the original sources mentioned. noncompliance eventually leading to more proxi-
That said, population-level research needs to mal complications.
establish with rigor causality in order that it can In order to infer a causal relationship, Haynes
be applied effectively to individuals, such as in et al. (2011) described that four necessary condi-
the health professional-patient context. tions need to be present: covariation, temporal
In research on causality in psychology, precedence, alternative explanation exclusion,
Stephen Haynes has been a leader in the field. For and logical connection. Each presents challenges.
population research, he refers to classical statis- For example, for covariation, measurement error
tics, but for work with patients he uses diagrams. must be controlled. For temporal precedence, a
In the following, I switch course from advanced third variable might be involved. For alternative
statistics to see how causality might be treated explanation exclusion, controlled experiments
classically at the statistical level, given that this are not always possible nor might they give defin-
approach still predominates. After in this section, itive answers. As for logical connection, the vari-
I examine Haynes’ diagrammatic approach to ables should be at the same level so that
patients. mechanism (mediating variables) can be imputed.
Once Hayne’s work is reviewed, I look at For example, the construct of frustration should
other areas in psychology in which statistics are be broken down to explain how specific types of
relevant to establishing causality. Then, I con- aggression might be caused by it.
sider it in neuroscience, ecology, and other non- According to Haynes et al. (2011), in psycho-
psychological areas. To close the chapter, I return pathology the causal relations involved might
to the causality of psychology by considering change over time or exhibit dynamic features.
networks in PTSD. States at a point in time exhibit patterns over time
(phases), so that appreciation of state dynamic
phase functions can accommodate to the chang-
Applications ing nature of causality. Also, in a process of
reciprocal determinism or circular causation,
Psychopathology environment influences state. These might
include positive feedback loops, include more
Populations Haynes, O’Brien, Kaholokula, and complex (e.g., triadic) relations, and so on.
Witteman (2012) analyzed concepts of causality The statistical approaches to establishing cau-
in psychopathology, extending Hayne’s work sality in nonexperimental designs are varied,
(1992; Haynes et al., 2011). They argued that cli- dynamically changing, and expanding, but they
nicians need a firm understanding of causality for still cannot ascertain with enough precision the
psychological assessment, case formulation, and causality involved in this type of research relative
functional analysis. to research based on experimental designs.
134 6 Statistical Concepts and Networks in Causality

That said, methods in the latter vein, such as RCTs, assessment and to case formulation (Haynes
have their own problems, including relative to eco- et al., 2011), including of FACCDs. The first fig-
logical validity. For example, RCTs on the effec- ure of the two (Fig. 6.1) documents the problems
tiveness of psychotherapies conducted in controlled faced by a family in terms of relations, and their
lab settings with ideal, selected patients might not importance, causes, and modifiability. The sec-
emerge with results that are generalizable to the ond figure of the two (Fig. 6.2) explains the sym-
real world of messy clinics with messy patients. bols in the diagram.

Patients In the FACCDs (Haynes et al., 2011)


model, functional analysis concerns the identifica- Other Areas
tion of important, controllable functional relation-
ships in specified behaviors of individuals, whether Landolt, Ystrom, Stene-Larsen, Holmstrøm, and
causal or noncausal. Functional analysis leads to Vollrath (2013) demonstrated the value of using
dynamic modeling of patient symptoms, goals, SEM in exploring causal pathways of child
and relationships, with FACCD graphic represen- behavior (internalizing) and maternal mental
tations used to diagram the patient maps of her/his health (distress) in families having a child with
difficulties. Therefore, the FACCD procedure congenital heart disease. Their longitudinal study
individualizes causality in relation to psychologi- between 6 and 36 months in child age found that
cal difficulties in immediate contexts of patients. both individual and family-based (shared) factors
contributed to risk for mental health problems.
Figures 6.1 and 6.2 together offer pertinent Also, it found that a mutual influence mechanism
details of the functional approach to behavioral model proved useful in understanding the data.

Parenting Functional
Skills Impairments
Deficits in Marital,
Parental, and
Occupational
Roles
Financial Frank’s
Husband’s Problems Conduct
Excessive Problems
Alcohol Use

Reduced
Frequent Persistent
Physical and
Conf licts with Depressed
Social
Husband’s Husband Mood
Activity
Stressful Work
Environment

Marital Worry and


Delayed
Problem- Self-Blame
Sleep
Solving Skills Onset
Deficit Family
History of
Depression

Fig. 6.1 Functional Analytic Clinical Case Diagram modifiability, and functional relations between causal
(FACCD). FACCD illustrates several behavior problems variables and behavior problems. Adapted from Haynes,
with different levels of importance, their functional rela- Yoshioka, Kloezeman, and Bello (2009)
tions, multiple causal variables with different degrees of
Applications 135

Symbols
Y or Z Y or Z
x x x (effect of (effect of
problem) problem)

Original, Unmodifiable Causal Variable; Hypothetical Causal Behavior Problem; Hypothetical Behavior
Causal Variable Mediating Variable Variable or Mediating Effect of Behavior Problem or Effect of
Variable Problem Behavior Problem

Type and Direction of Functional Relations between Variables

x Y x Y

Noncausal, Correlational x Y Bidirectional Causal x1 x2 Y

Unidirectional Causal Moderating Relationship

Strength of the Functional Relations between Variables


Indicated by Arrow Thickness

x Y x Y x Y

Weak Moderate Strong

Importance of Behavior Problem and Modifiability of Causal Variables


Indicated by Square and Circle Thickness

Y1 Y2 x1 x2

Less Important More Important Less Modifiable More Modifiable

Fig. 6.2 Symbols used in FACCDs. FACCD Functional NJ: Wiley. Copyright © 2011 and John Wiley & Sons, Inc.
Analytic Clinical Case Diagram. Adopted with permis- Reproduced with permission of John Wiley & Sons, Inc.
sion of John Wiley & Sons. Haynes et al. (2011). [Figure 2.2, Page 53]
Behavioral assessment and case formulation. Hoboken,

Van Bockstaele et al. (2013) analyzed research reviewed provided the strongest evidence for
and causation criteria to determine the temporal the association.
primacy of attentional bias toward threatening For the case of antisocial behavior, Jaffee et al.
stimuli in the manifestation of fear/anxiety. (2011) queried the types of research and statistics
The authors noted that causality refers not only to that can be used to identify better the causes of
“strict” linear cause-effect relations (etiology) behavior that are not amenable to experimental
but also to roles for vulnerability, maintaining, manipulation. Risk factors might appear causative
and exacerbating factors. The research on the but a third variable might be involved, or, evoca-
topic investigates strength of relation, consis- tive or active gene-environment correlation might
tency, dose–response curve, plausibility, tempo- be involved (the former is also called reverse cau-
rality, prospective studies, experimental evidence, sation). Or, the risk factor might appear as a cor-
and analogy (Hill, 1965). related feature. That being said, the ideal solution
Van Bockstaele et al. (2013) arrived at a con- of controlled experimentation, such as using ran-
clusion of reciprocal (bidirectional, mutually domized control trials, have their own limitations,
reinforcing, circular) causality in the relation- such as possible low external validity.
ship of attentional bias and fear/anxiety, rather Marshall, Parker, Ciarrochi, and Heaven (2013)
than a unique causal impact of the bias on the queried whether self-esteem is a “cause or con-
emotions. The experimental research that they sequence” of social support. They investigated
136 6 Statistical Concepts and Networks in Causality

longitudinally 961 adolescents (mean of 13.4 at scientific reasoning in arriving at justifiable con-
the start) across five time points over 4 years. By clusions constitutes the best strategy in causality
using more of the latter time points in their study and disability determination for court.
and the same measures at the waves, they could
better test the causal antecedents of the outcomes. Populations The classic distinction in causality
Self-esteem and perceived social support (net- estimation of deciphering more direct mediators
work, size) were measured using self-report ques- of the relationship between independent variable/
tionnaires, respectively, by Rosenberg (1979) and risk factors and dependent variable/outcomes and
a revised version of a questionnaire by Ciarrochi, more indirect, moderating influences on the rela-
Chan, and Bajgar (2001; 4 items). Covariates tionships involved still remains a fruitful one to
were measured on the self-esteem questionnaire. consider in establishing causality, but the statis-
Item parcels were created for latent variable anal- tics based on this distinction are changing.
ysis, given the scale’s large number of items (10). Moreover, alternative approaches in establishing
SEM was used with a latent variables approach, causality based on alternative methods related to
analyzed with Mplus. Chi-square and other fit Rubin’s potential outcomes and Pearl’s DAGs
indices were calculated. hold promise, but they too are lacking in some
The results showed that causal priority lied ways according to the literature review, most
with self-esteem rather than perceived support. likely due to the inherent difficulty with estab-
Self-esteem was found to predict increasing lishing causation in nonexperimental research.
levels of social support (quality, in particular, also Psychology and other behavior-based disciplines
size). The study illustrates the classical manner in have come a long way from shying away from
which SEM analysis can discern causal relations. tackling causality issues when observations and
correlations are the methods and statistics used.
Developmental research is limited ethically in
Comment using RCTs, but longitudinal research, for exam-
ple, using prospective designs, to some degree,
Individuals In determining causality in psy- have their advantages toward establishing causal-
chology, population-level research has difficulty ity. Nevertheless, everything considered, the lim-
transferring its conclusions to clinical situations its of statistics in establishing causality need to be
in which one patient at a time is assessed and recognized. That said, the area constitutes a
treated. Epidemiology provides odds ratios about dynamically evolving field, and psychology
the influence of risk factors on health outcomes. needs to keep abreast of the developments in it.
As documented in Young (2014), I was involved
in a case that has gone and that is going again to
the Supreme Court of Canada in which I had to Brain
review the population-level research on work
stress and depression/disability relative to other Granger Causality
stressors and also relative to the outcome of
PTSD instead of depression. Even here, there Friston et al. (2013) examined statistical
was confusion in the court present in the testi- approaches to analyzing functional integration
mony by the “dueling” epidemiologists relative (directed connectivity) in neuronal macrocir-
to the odds ratios involved, and I had to clarify. cuits. The neuronal information might be
Statistical work of the population-level research acquired by electroencephalography (EEG) or by
offers a powerful pathway to causal understand- fMRI. The two approaches compared concern
ing, but clinical work also needs astute observa- Granger Causality (GC) and Dynamic Causal
tional and clinical skills. In this regard, use of the Modeling (DCM).
scientific approach in information gathering in an In DCM, causality lies in the “form” of the
individual assessment, then in the interpretation model, and inferred “hidden” or unobservable
of psychological test results, and finally in using neuronal states are taken to fluctuate and thereby
Ecology 137

“cause changes” in other hidden neuronal states. Comment


In DCM, causal interactions are “mediated” by
the hidden neural dynamics. It is a multi-input, In the next section, I review in more depth GC in
multi-output model, with augmented “forward” the ecological field. As with brain research, the
observation modeling of mapped neural activity review of ecology shows that GC is an important
and observed responses. The model is “fully” in statistical parameterization, yet is being com-
generative, with key outputs including “posterior plemented by other approaches.
parameter estimates” of the best data-fitting model
with respect to intra brain-region coupling.
DCM can estimate coupling between brain Ecology
regions in fMRI for a particular modeled archi-
tecture using Bayesian methods. It helps account Interventions
for “directed” brain region connections, disam-
biguating neural “drivers” of neuronal events/ Raerinne (2011) offered an account of causal
signal propagation. It can be used after GC to elu- mechanism in ecology that considers the relative
cidate more mechanistic characterization of the lack of ecological laws in the discipline. Raerinne
system involved (i.e., with respect to specific argued that ecological generalizations can be
models/hypotheses). The DCM models hidden explanatory as long as they are invariant even if
neuronal state coupling that could generate the they are not lawlike. Generalizations can be dem-
observations made. It attempts to get beneath onstrated as invariant if they are maintained in
the data surface structure in order to understand “interventions” that change the value of the vari-
the “how” of their generation. To conclude, ables involved. The philosophical stance by
Friston et al. (2013) considered the newer GC Woodward (2000, 2001, 2003) on causality has
“complementary” to approaches in analyzing gained wide application, including in psychology
neural connectivity for its causality. (Gopnik & Wellman, 2012), and here it is
Hu and Liang (2012) proposed a revision of extended to ecology.
GC as applied to spectral GC in the frequency Raerinne (2011) noted that interventions can
domain. They showed that spectral GC analysis demonstrate whether causes are “difference mak-
as presently constituted leads to “misleading” ers” in that the variable altered leads to conse-
results. Their model speaks to the need for better quences in the system (e.g., the intervention of
tools in causality analysis of neural connectivity. reducing habitat has the effect of lowering spe-
Other workers have modified GC approaches. cies diversity). In “simple” causality chains, there
For example, von Eye, Wiedermann, and Mun might be an invariant relationship, but no known
(2013) incorporated configural frequency analy- or proposed mechanisms to account for it. In
sis into it for categorical data, and showed the mechanistic explanations, the internal causal
approach applied to determining which changes structure in the phenomena is discerned, and
in adolescent aggressive impulses led to changes interventions can contribute to their elucidation.
in peer aggression.
Friston et al. (2014) elaborated GC methodol-
ogy for analysis of biological time series. They Granger Causality
demonstrated that GC analyses can be unreliable
when there is measurement noise, whether the Establishing causality in time-dependent trans-
analyses are based on autoregressive models or formations existing in systems such as ecological
nonparametric measures. They “finessed” the prob- ones (that cannot be manipulated experimentally)
lem by deriving spectral causality measures from presents formidable challenges. In order to iden-
“Volterra kernels,” which were estimated using the tify causation, given the problems with correla-
approach of DCM rather than based on GC, per se. tion for imputing causation, Granger (1969)
DCM uses a Bayesian state-space model with “hid- developed an approach, now referred to as GC,
den” states in generating data in continuous time. which was based on prediction in time-series
138 6 Statistical Concepts and Networks in Causality

variables. In Granger modeling, a critical require- In order to detect causality in complex ecosys-
ment is that information pertaining to a putative tems in which GC might not apply, Sugihara
causal factor is independent and unique to that et al. (2012) developed a convergent cross-
variable (e.g., on predator effects) so that it can be mapping (CC-M) approach. It is a method based
removed or eliminated from the model involving on nonlinear state-space reconstruction in time-
time series (e.g., on prey). However, in ecological series variables. It calculates to what degree the
systems, variable separability might not obtain, historical record of Y values can estimate reliably
nor would coupling be strongly coupled or syn- states of X values. The model tests for correspon-
chronized, which is another condition for GC. dence between attractor “shadow” manifolds,
Detto et al. (2012) presented a revision of the which are constructed using “lagged” coordinate
GC approach in ecology that is nonparametric embeddings of X and Y. The authors concluded
and spectral (frequency-based). The approach is that the CC-M avoids the problem of mirage cor-
termed “conditional” GC. It can accommodate or relations, changes in threshold in regimes, and
untangle oscillatory, external, time-dependent, also the ubiquity of nonlinear dynamical systems
periodic drivers overlapping self-sustaining, in nature acting to confound the determination of
endogenous, natural, signature dynamics, and causality.
the direct and feedback relationships involved.
This permits the approach to map any early
effects or state variable on later outcomes or Comment
other state variables, indicating the “directional-
ity” in coupling inherent in ecological causality. GC has been applied to mental health research
Also, it can establish associated variable cou- especially in the area of neuroscience. GC
plings related to any external drivers, compared (Granger, 1969, 1988) originated in the field of
to the endogenous structure of the core ecologi- econometrics, but it has been applied to multiple
cal system or network. disciplines, including neuroscience. It helps
detect phenomena due to effects laying in prior
causes in time, which other approaches, such as
Convergent Cross-Mapping SEM, cannot do. Also, “G”-causality can distin-
guish unidirectional and bidirectional couplings,
Sugihara et al. (2012) faced the difficulty in as well as accommodate colinearity, unlike path
establishing causality in complex systems for analysis or other SEM approaches. The condi-
which observational data had been collected. tional G-causality approach helps decompose
Correlations change in complex ecosystems, as and analyze causal relations as a function of
variables might be coupled positively, negatively, spectral frequency (e.g., diurnal, seasonal) rather
or not at all, depending on time of observation than using correlations over time. As for mecha-
and extant system state (state-dependent behav- nisms that might be involved, these would have
ior). The system expresses “radically different to be inferred from the data. To conclude, even
dynamic control regimes,” either top-down or though experiments are not readily applicable to
bottom-up, thereby altering correlational dynam- some fields, such as ecology, by using refined sta-
ics (e.g., in predator–prey relations). A system tistical approaches, to a degree, causality still can
having properties such as this is considered non- be determined.
linear dynamical and complex. The altering cor- Aside from its application to neuroscience and
relational profile is considered ephemeral or to ecology, GC has much potential for applica-
“mirage,” which is a common finding in even the tion to development. von Eye and Wiedermann
simplest of nonlinear dynamical systems. The (2015) developed a taxonomy of GC models
variables alter their coupling to even become applicable to developmental research. They
decoupled or “anti-correlated,” and this might argued that Granger models help interpret caus-
happen “spontaneously.” ally the relations between variables. But different
PTSD Networks 139

models imply different causal theories of the In this network view, ontologically, a diagnos-
relations. In their taxonomy, the authors help tic attribution is neither an essentialist, carved-at-
structure existing models and allow for derivation the-joint category nor a socially-constructed,
of new ones. The classification includes models convenient DSM (Diagnostic and Statistical
based on considering: (a) order effects; (b) type Manual of Mental Disorders) category, but a real-
of contemporaneous effects; (c) the a priori ist entity carved by the causality among the sys-
assumptions applicable to the status of variables tem dynamics themselves. For example, an
as explanatory causes or outcome effects; and (d) episode of a disorder follows a course as symp-
the sectioning of a dependent series that is pre- tom nodes in the network “turn on” and “transmit
dicted from an independent one. activation” to nodes connected to them.
To test their model, McNally et al. conducted
a questionnaire study of a 2008 Chinese earth-
PTSD Networks quake, with over 360 survivors. They used a
translated version of the PCL (Posttraumatic
Concept Checklist—Civilian; Weathers, Litz, Herman,
Huska, & Keane, 1993; Mandarin Chinese ver-
McNally Et al McNally et al. (2015) developed sion; Li et al., 2010). The questionnaire is keyed
a network approach to the symptoms of PTSD, to the DSM-IV (Diagnostic and Statistical
imputing causality to the functional interacting Manual of Mental Disorders, Fourth Edition;
symptom linkages themselves (while refuting the American Psychiatric Association, 1994).
notion that an underlying latent construct can Among the survivors, the questionnaire indicated
explain the configuration of symptoms in the dis- that 38 % met the criteria for probable PTSD (5
order). The McNally et al. work on PTSD is years after the earthquake when the data were
based heavily on the approach of Borsboom and gathered).
colleagues on the network approach to psychopa- Data analysis included search for common
thology and network calculation (respectively, network properties. In “association” networks,
Borsboom & Cramer, 2014; Epskamp, Cramer, each edge represents the correlations between
Waldorp, Schmittmann, & Borsboom, 2012). symptoms, from zero-order to larger, with mag-
In the network approach, symptoms covary or nitude indicated by edge thickness in the dia-
couple variably, and through their constitutive grams (not direction). A more restricted
relationship (rather than due to a presumed association network (involving only links for
underlying latent construct of disease). which r ≤ 0.30) was also calculated. In “concen-
Symptoms in this sense are directly constitutive tration” networks, edges indicate partial correla-
of mental disorder and there are no intermediates tions, controlling for all other correlations in the
causally in their relationship to disorder, such as network with the symptom pair at hand. In “rela-
underlying disease entities. Symptoms affect tive importance” networks, each edge indicates
each other through feedback loops, homeostatic the relative significance of a symptom as a
relations, and so on, and they are not condition- predictor of another symptom (both for magni-
ally independent of the stressors that might lead tude and direction). As for symptom centrality,
to them. the authors calculated node strength, closeness,
The symptom network view affords and and betweenness. Degree refers to the number of
exquisite sensitivity to individual differences in links to a node, but strength refers to the sum of
symptom expression and their causality, unlike correlation magnitudes (weights) of each edge
the contrasting model of common cause/latent linked to a node. The variable of closeness is
variable approach to mental disorder. In this net- indicated by the mean distance to all other nodes
work view, diagnostic symptoms are not caused from the node of concern. Betweenness refers to
by or are reflective of a latent entity or entities; the amount of times a node lies on the shortest
rather, they are constitutive of them. path between two other nodes.
140 6 Statistical Concepts and Networks in Causality

The results showed that the 17 DSM-IV PTSD cortex (mPFC) coupling during unpleasant word
symptoms are highly interconnected in the popula- processing. Also, re-experiencing severity moder-
tion studied. When results with r ≤ 0.30 are ated insula/putamen hippocampus connectivity
excluded in the association network calculated, during both pleasant and unpleasant word stimuli.
strong associations become more evident. They The authors concluded that different PTSD
included the symptoms of hypervigilance and star- symptoms moderate different functional neural
tle and also avoidance of thoughts and activities connectivities during emotional interference.
(about the trauma and associated with it, respec- There appears to be separable components of
tively). Numbing and dissociation symptoms were dysfunctional inhibitory control in PTSD during
strongly linked (loss of interest in enjoyable activi- affective processing. Therefore, I conclude that
ties; feeling distance from others, respectively). network modeling at the central level in PTSD
Finally, nightmares, flashbacks, and intrusive highlights mechanisms different than network
memories related to the trauma were tightly linked. modeling at the symptomatic level.
The authors noted that these various symptom link- Lehrner and Yehuda (2014) noted that PTSD
ages appear related to the three DSM-IV symptom is a complex phenomenon so that no one single
clusters of hyperarousal, avoidance/numbing, and biomarker can be isolated to indicate it. They
re-experiencing, respectively. However, other argued that PTSD symptoms should be conceptu-
symptom linkages did not conform to these DSM alized as emergent characteristics of dynamic
clusters—those of startle-concentration problems networks rather than uniquely as outcomes only
and anger-concentration problems. of core biological processes. Their model is a
Other results accentuated these findings. For multifaceted one, with risk as well as illness net-
example, the concentration network showed that works, and with possible biomarkers for each of
two re-experiencing symptoms were not con- diagnosis/severity, risk factor/predictors, trauma
nected to the others (physiological reactivity, exposure susceptibility, recovery (prediction,
feeling upset at reminders), but quite connected verification), and subtyping.
to each other. Centrality calculations showed that
perceiving the future as foreshortened is highly
central. Overall, the authors concluded that Comment
hypervigilance, future foreshortening, and sleep
appear predominant symptoms in PTSD symp- The network approach to symptom linkages in
tom network analysis, with multiple symptom mental disorder is a novel one and it adds incre-
linkages involved, including some not previously mental findings to the field. However, first, it
considered. needs to be supplemented by work in mental dis-
order development, course, and comorbidity
Others Sadeh, Spielberg, Warren, Miller, and (e.g., PTSD mutually maintained with chronic
Heller (2014) conducted a neural connectivity pain). Moreover, network analysis can be per-
study during an emotional processing task in formed on risk factors before mental illness onset
trauma-exposed adults. The participants were and also on therapeutic response after it. The core
assessed for PTSD symptoms using the SCID- symptoms in both cases might be different than
IV-TR (Structured Clinical Interview for DSM- during the active onset phase.
IV-TR; First, Spitzer, Gibbon, & Williams, 2002). Second, the symptom network approach
Emotional processing was evaluated on an should not readily dismiss other avenues of con-
emotion-word Stroop task. Both reaction time ceptualization and empirical investigation of
and error frequency were scored. The participants mental disorder. For example, confirmatory fac-
were subject to fMRI functional data acquisition. tor analysis is suggesting apparently valid
multiple-factor models of PTSD. Moreover, the
PTSD symptom severity (especially hyper- latent variable approach could be modified to
arousal) moderated amygdala medial-prefrontal help explain better some of the core symptoms
PTSD Networks 141

that emerge in network research. McNally et al. and therapeutic response. In the following, I
(2015) themselves showed the value of a modi- review the most consistent findings among the
fied latent variable approach to PTSD in this biological findings (for the illness markers only),
regard by referring to the model of PTSD that and exclude the research cited on possible cogni-
describes it as a syndrome involving continued tive and related markers of PTSD. For PTSD sus-
impending threat (Ehlers & Clark, 2000) when ceptibility, Schmidt et al. (2013) referred to,
they explained the centrality of the symptom of elevated sensitivity of leukocytes of glucocorti-
hypervigilance in their findings. coid receptors (GR) in peripheral blood mono-
Therefore, the authors might have to prema- cytes prior to deployment (in trauma-exposed
turely dismissed the approaches of Barlow, Dutch soldiers). Other evidence indicated molec-
Sauer-Zavala, Carl, Bullis, and Ellard (2014) and ular regulators of the hypothalamus-pituitary-
of Caspi et al. (2014) on general factors in psy- adrenal (HPA) axis activity, especially for GR
chopathology. I am not suggesting that the latter and associated molecules, as predictive of PTSD
approaches are more powerful than network (e.g., in this military sample; Geuze et al., 2012;
ones, but they could be complementary. There is van Zuiden, Geuze, et al., 2012; van Zuiden
room for both bottom-up (network) and top- et al., 2011; van Zuiden, Heijnen, et al., 2012).
down (latent variable) concepts of psychopathol- Epigenetic effects also seem involved (in
ogy in an integrated hierarchical multilevel another military sample). In individuals with and
multicausal model. Symptom linkages express without PTSD post-deployment, the genomic
causal relations but so might other factors facili- repetitive elements LINE-1 and Alu were differ-
tative of their cohering. entially methylated pre-deployment. Genetic
Finally, any multilevel, multifactorial com- polymorphisms associated with PTSD suscepti-
bined hierarchical model, as being suggested bility include FKBP5 (FK506 binding protein 5),
could justify combining network and latent entity COMT (catechol-O-methyltransferase), and the
approaches by explaining that both are needed to dopamine transporter and receptor genes (Wu
understand how individual differences in causal- et al., 2013).
ity of symptom expression and connection might As for PTSD disease markers, Schmidt et al.
scaffold on general tendencies in behavioral con- (2013) referred to the HPA axis (dysregulation;
figuration that are promoted by causal biological attenuation) and the sympathetic adrenomedul-
and environmental factors. Overall, the supple- lary system (overdrive) (Pitman et al., 2012;
mental research on networks and related aspects Yehuda, 2002, respectively). Note that biomarkers
of PTSD cited in this section indicates that the are not necessarily endophenotypes (part of a
application of network conceptualization to chain in causation leading back to genes).
PTSD is burgeoning but should integrate to the
degree possible other relevant work. Brain Scott et al. (2015) conducted a meta-
analysis of neurocognitive function in PTSD,
involving 60 studies. Their review found deficits
Related Research in PTSD for attention, verbal memory, and speed
of information processing, in particular. However,
This section of the chapter on networks in PTSD the analysis could not differentiate whether the
considers related concepts such as biomarkers cognitive deficits related to the disorder itself or
and other aspects of brain function. Genetics to pre-existing factors. Also, in terms of possible
takes its place, as well. confounders, the 60 studies rarely screened using
symptom validity testing or urine toxicology/
Biomarkers Schmidt, Faltwasser, and Wotjak breathalyzer methods. Nevertheless, according to
(2013) reviewed the research on potential bio- Scott et al. (2015), the results found by their
markers in PTSD. They differentiated between meta-analysis support a view of PTSD as involv-
possible biomarkers of risk, disorder expression, ing dysregulation of frontolimbic circuitry.
142 6 Statistical Concepts and Networks in Causality

As for neuroendocrine abnormalities in PTSD, their thoughts, affect, context, and appraisals, but
Zoladz and Diamond (2013) referred to studies five item adjectives were selected for the study
on cortisol and abnormal HPA axis function, (cheerful, insecure, content, down, suspicious;
among others. Neurobiological abnormalities filled in on a 7-point Likert scale).
focused on amygdala hyperresponsivity, reduced The results indicated that having a diagnosis
prefrontal cortex (PFC) activity, and possibly of depression, in particular, was associated more
small hippocampal size/function, although the strongly with connected moment-to-moment net-
amygdala and hippocampal findings especially work structures over momentary mental states
might concern pre-existing factors. (that were reported in the sampling). Also, there
were elevated interconnections between positive
Genes Zoladz and Diamond (2013) conducted a and negative mental states in the participants in
similar review of genetic factors in PTSD suscep- this group. The authors considered results of con-
tibility. Their list of possible genetic factors in firmatory factor analysis, as well. They con-
PTSD was quite extensive: FK506-binding protein cluded that the network approach might be useful
(FKP5), neuropeptide Y (NPY), dopamine beta- to map transdiagnostic processes.
hydroxylase (DBH), COMT, dopamine receptor Hong and Cheung (2015) investigated the
D2 (DRD2), dopamine transporter (DAT), solute common core cognitive vulnerabilities to depres-
carrier family 6, member 4 (SLC6A4), serotonin sion and anxiety. They conducted a meta-analytic
2A receptor (5-HTR2A), gamma-aminobutyric review over 73 relevant articles and found that six
acid receptor alpha 2 (GABARA2), regulator of cognitive vulnerabilities (e.g., for depression,
G-protein signaling 2 (RGS2), and brain-derived rumination; for anxiety, uncertainty tolerance)
neurotrophic factor (BDNF) (e.g., Digangi, were moderately to strongly correlated. They
Guffanti, McLaughlin, & Koenen, 2013; Klengel found that a single latent-factor model best fit the
et al., 2013; Skelton, Ressler, Norrholm, Jovanovic, data (e.g., “common core vulnerability;” repeti-
& Bradley-Davino, 2012). tive negative thinking with uncertainty/uncon-
trollability present, along with cognitive
Zoladz and Diamond (2013) concluded that distortions). The authors concluded that the find-
there might be different biomarker profiles for ings are consistent with a transdiagnostic
different PTSD subtypes. PTSD is the result of a etiological process underpinning emotional dis-
complex interaction among genetic, neurobio- order (e.g., Barlow et al., 2014).
logical, endocrine, immunological, and devel- Lane and Sher (2015) found that, in Alcohol
opmental factors. It does not appear to be a Use Disorder (AUD; in the DSM-5; American
single disorder, but multiple ones, with each Psychiatric Association, 2013), the assumptions
having different biomarker “signatures.” of equal criterion severity and strict additivity
of criteria combinations are questionable. The
Transdiagnostics The studies in this section do DSM uses a polythetic format that is problem-
not pertain to PTSD, per se. But they have impli- atic (“highly fallible”) not just for AUD but
cations for determining both the common and also for all disorders subject to this format. The
unique characteristics of DSM disorders. authors recommended a dimensional approach
to symptom criteria, with graded severity of
Wigman et al. (2015) used the network each symptom in any one disorder instead of
approach to differentiate the symptom dynamics the present 0–1/present–absent categorical
of individuals (N = 599) with depression, with approach. They noted that different causes may
psychotic disorder, and as controls. The partici- be involved in a mild compared to a more severe
pants filled in a structured self-report diary at symptom in a disorder. Using such an approach
quasi-random moments 10 times in the day over to the etiology of mental disorders might help
most of a week (when signaled; this is the ESM, find unique, transdiagnostic etiological pro-
experience sampling method). They reported on cesses across disorders.
References 143

Comment ecology. In psychology, it covers material related


to psychological tests and psychopathology, as
The predominant model in psychopathology is the well as the brain and development. Many other
medical one, in which disorders typically are con- examples could be provided. Essentially, with
sidered categories. The extant diagnostic manuals appropriate design and statistics, causality is
have hundreds of separate disorders in their noso- amenable to inference in scientific study even
logical tomes. Moreover, in them, each category is when the ideal designs are impossible to use.
considered as associated with or potentially asso- However, these methods and concepts are in flux
ciated with a particular cause or etiology and a par- and keep being refined, so that causal inference in
ticular cure or helpful treatment. However, the any discipline requires the care for which science
transdiagnostic approach seeks common and dif- often is exemplary.
ferential symptoms across and within disorders, The chapter hints at the difference between
respectively, so has the advantage of being ame- population estimates of causality and causality in
nable to network modeling, aside from the sim- individual cases (e.g., legal ones). This refers to
plicity it could create for clinicians in the field. the distinction between general and specific cau-
The conceptual distinction between markers sation. I deal with this aspect of causal conceptu-
of risk, disease expression, and therapeutic alization and study in two later chapters on
response is a welcome one. However, research on psychological injury (e.g., due to negligence in
biomarkers, in general, as well as on risk and legal cases).
therapeutic response, might not address directly The most important and fastest growing area
the related question of endophenotypes. of statistical applications to the study of causality
Endophenotypes are thought to represent path- of behavior relates to networks. I have described
ways from gene to disease expression. the basics in this area, especially as it applies to
Given its spreading influence, the study of net- PTSD. Later chapters in the present work con-
works might introduce a new way of studying endo- sider network analysis for brain connectivity and
phenotypes in PTSD. Network modeling could also for the causality of psychopathology.
isolate the core, essential components of each
disorder, as well as causal relations among them.
However, the research on PTSD endopheno-
References
types even from a network perspective might be
limited by focus on linear modeling. On the one American Psychiatric Association. (1994). Diagnostic
hand, the amount of variance explained in behav- and statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM-IV
ior by any one gene or even one gene complex is (4th ed.). Washington, DC: Author.
limited. Moreover, epigenetic and other environ- American Psychiatric Association. (2013). Diagnostic
and statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM-5
mental factors need to be considered in a full bio- (5th ed.). Washington, DC: Author.
psychosocial model of endophenotypes for Barlow, D. H., Sauer-Zavala, S., Carl, J. R., Bullis, J. R.,
PTSD. Finally, network concepts both neurally & Ellard, K. K. (2014). The nature, diagnosis, and
and symptomatically can refine understanding of treatment of neuroticism: Back to the future. Clinical
Psychological Science, 2, 344–365.
the biological factors involved in PTSD and how Baron, R. M., & Kenny, D. A. (1986). The moderator-
they dynamically interact with the genes involved, mediator variable distinction in social psychological
the environment involved, and the personal (self) research: Conceptual, strategic and statistical consid-
vulnerability and resilience factors involved. erations. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
51, 1173–1182.
Berzuini, C., Dawid, P., & Bernardinelli, L. (2012a).
Causality: Statistical perspectives and applications.
Chapter Conclusions West Sussex, UK: Wiley.
Berzuini, C., Dawid, P., & Bernardinelli, L. (2012b). An
overview of statistical causality. In C. Berzuini,
This chapter shows the centrality of statistics for P. Dawid, & L. Bernardinelli (Eds.), Causality:
the study of and elucidation of causality in disci- Statistical perspectives and applications (pp. 1–4).
plines such as psychology, epidemiology, and West Sussex, UK: Wiley.
144 6 Statistical Concepts and Networks in Causality

Bollen, K. A. (1989). Structural equations with latent Ehlers, A., & Clark, D. M. (2000). A cognitive model of
variables. New York: Wiley. posttraumatic stress disorder. Behavior Research and
Borsboom, D., & Cramer, A. O. J. (2014). Network analy- Therapy, 38, 319–345.
sis: An integrative approach to the structure of psycho- Emsley, R., & Dunn, G. (2012). Evaluation of potential
pathology. Annual Review of Clinical Psychology, 9, mediators in randomized trials of complex interven-
91–121. tions (psychotherapies). In C. Berzuini, P. Dawid, &
Bracken, M. B. (2013). Risk, chance, and causation: L. Bernardinelli (Eds.), Causality: Statistical perspec-
Investigating the origins and treatment of disease. tives and applications (pp. 290–326). West Sussex,
New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. UK: Wiley.
Campbell, D. T. (1957). Factors relevant to the validity of Epskamp, S., Cramer, A. O. J., Waldorp, L. J.,
experiments in social settings. Psychological Bulletin, Schmittmann, V. D., & Borsboom, D. (2012). qgraph:
54, 297–312. Network visualization of relationships in psychomet-
Campbell, D. T., & Stanley, J. C. (1963). Experimental ric data. Journal of Statistical Software, 48, 1018.
and quasi-experimental designs for research on teach- First, M., Spitzer, R., Gibbon, M., & Williams, J. (2002).
ing. In N. L. Gage (Ed.), Handbook of research meth- Structural clinical interview for DSM-IV-TR, Research
ods for studying daily life (pp. 171–246). Chicago: Version, Nonpatient Edition. New York: New York
Rand McNally. State Psychiatric Institute, Biometric Research.
Caspi, A., Houts, R. M., Belsky, D. W., Goldman-Mellor, Fisher, R. A. (1935). Statistical methods for research
S. J., Harrington, H., Israel, S., et al. (2014). The p fac- workers. Edinburgh, UK: Oliver and Boyd.
tor: One general psychopathology factor in the struc- Frangakis, C. E., & Rubin, D. B. (2002). Principal stratifi-
ture of psychiatric disorders? Clinical Psychological cation in causal inference. Biometrics, 58, 21–29.
Science, 2, 119–137. Friston, K. (2009). The free-energy principle: A rough
Chen, Y., & Cao, Y. (2012). Epidemiological context and guide to the brain? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 13,
concerns. In P. Kennedy (Ed.), The Oxford handbook 293–301.
of rehabilitation psychology (pp. 88–95). New York: Friston, K. (2010). The free-energy principle: A unified
Oxford University Press. brain theory? Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 11,
Ciarrochi, J., Chan, A. Y. C., & Bajgar, J. (2001). Measuring 127–138.
emotional intelligence in adolescents. Personality and Friston, K. J., Bastos, A. M., Oswal, A., van Wijk, B.,
Individual Differences, 31, 1105–1119. Richter, C., & Litvak, V. (2014). Granger causality
Cook, T. D., & Campbell, D. T. (1979). Quasi- revisited. NeuroImage, 101, 796–808.
experimentation: Design and analysis issues for field Friston, K., Moran, R., & Seth, A. K. (2013). Analysing
settings. Chicago: Rand McNally. connectivity with Granger causality and dynamic
Dawid, P. (2012). The decision-theoretic approach to causal modeling. Current Opinion in Neurobiology,
causal inference. In C. Berzuini, P. Dawid, & 23, 172–178.
L. Bernardinelli (Eds.), Causality: Statistical perspec- Gelman, A. (2011). Causality and statistical learning.
tives and applications (pp. 25–42). West Sussex, UK: American Journal of Sociology, 117, 955–966.
Wiley. Gerstman, B. B. (2013). Epidemiology kept simple: An
De Ridder, D., Vanneste, S., & Freeman, W. (2014). The introduction to traditional and modern epidemiology.
Bayesian brain: Phantom percepts resolve sensory Oxford, UK: Wiley-Blackwell.
uncertainty. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, Geuze, E., van Wingen, G. A., van Zuiden, M., Rademaker,
44, 4–15. A. R., Vermetten, E., Kavelaars, A., et al. (2012).
Detto, M., Molini, A., Katul, G., Stoy, P., Palmroth, S., & Glucocorticoid receptor number predicts increase in
Baldocchi, D. (2012). Causality and persistence in amygdala activity after severe stress.
ecological systems: A nonparametric spectral Granger Psychoneuroendocrinology, 37, 1837–1844.
causality approach. The American Naturalist, 179, Gopnik, A., & Wellman, H. M. (2012). Reconstructing
524–535. constructivism: Causal models, Bayesian learning
Digangi, J., Guffanti, G., McLaughlin, K. A., & Koenen, mechanisms, and the theory. Psychological Bulletin,
K. C. (2013). Considering trauma exposure in the con- 138, 1085–1108.
text of genetics studies of posttraumatic stress disor- Granger, C. W. J. (1969). Investigating causal relations by
der: A systematic review. Biology of Mood and Anxiety econometric models and cross-spectral methods.
Disorders, 3, 1–12. Econometrica: Journal of the Econometric Society,
Donofrino, B., Class, Q., Lahey, B., & Larsson, H. (2014). 37, 424–438.
Testing the developmental origins of health and dis- Granger, C. W. J. (1988). Some recent developments in
ease hypothesis for psychopathology using family- the concept of causality. Journal of Econometrics, 39,
based, quasi-experimental designs. Child Development 199–211.
Perspectives, 8, 151–157. Greenland, S. (2012). Causal inference as a prediction
Duncan, G. J., & Magnuson, K. (2012). Socioeconomic problem: Assumptions, identification and evidence
status and cognitive functioning: Moving from corre- synthesis. In C. Berzuini, P. Dawid, & L. Bernardinelli
lation to causation. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: (Eds.), Causality: Statistical perspectives and appli-
Cognitive Science, 3, 377–386. cations (pp. 43–58). West Sussex, UK: Wiley.
References 145

Haynes, S. N. (1992). Models of causality in psychopa- Shrout, K. M. Keyes, & K. Ornstein (Eds.), Causality
thology: Toward synthetic, dynamic and nonlinear and psychopathology: Finding the determinants of
models of causality in psychopathology. Des Moines, disorders and their cures (pp. 66–78). New York:
IA: Allyn & Bacon. Oxford University Press.
Haynes, S. N., O’Brien, W. H., Kaholokula, J. K., & Klengel, T., Mehta, D., Anacker, C., Rex-Haffner, M.,
Witteman, C. (2012). Concepts of causality in psycho- Pruessner, J. C., Pariante, C. M., et al. (2013). Allele-
pathology: Applications in clinical assessment, clinical specific FKBP5 DNA demethylation mediates gene-
case formulation and functional analysis. Journal of childhood trauma interactions. Nature Neuroscience,
Unified Psychotherapy and Clinical Science, 1, 87–103. 16, 33–41.
Haynes, S. N., O’Brien, W. H., & Kaholokula, J. K. Landolt, M. A., Ystrom, E., Stene-Larsen, K., Holmstrøm,
(2011). Behavioral assessment and case formulation. H., & Vollrath, M. E. (2013). Exploring causal path-
Hoboken, NJ: Wiley. ways of child behavior and maternal mental health in
Haynes, S. N., Yoshioka, D., Kloezeman, K., & Bello, I. families with a child with congenital heart disease: A
(2009). Clinical applications of behavioral assess- longitudinal study. Psychological Medicine, 44,
ment: Identifying and explaining behavior problems in 3421–3433.
clinical assessment. In J. Butcher (Ed.), Oxford hand- Lane, S. P., & Sher, K. J. (2015). Limits of current
book of clinical assessment (pp. 226–249). Oxford, approaches to diagnosis severity based on crite-
UK: Oxford University Press. rion counts: An example with DSM-5 alcohol
Hill, A. B. (1965). The environment and disease: use disorder. Clinical Psychological Science, 3,
Association or causation? Proceedings of the Royal 819–835.
Society of Medicine, 58, 295–300. Lehrner, A., & Yehuda, R. (2014). Biomarkers of PTSD:
Holland, P. W. (1986). Statistics and causal inference. Military applications and considerations. European
Journal of the American Statistical Association, 81, Journal of Psychotraumatology, 5, 1–11.
945–970. Li, H., Wang, L., Shi, Z., Zhang, Y., Wu, K., & Liu, P.
Holland, P. W. (1988). Causal inference, path analysis, (2010). Diagnostic utility of the PTSD Checklist in
and recursive structural equation models. Sociological detecting PTSD in Chinese earthquake victims.
Methodology, 18, 449–484. Psychological Reports, 107, 733–739.
Hong, R. Y., & Cheung, M. W.-L. (2015). The structure of Mackie, J. L. (1965). Causes and conditions. American
cognitive vulnerabilities to depression and anxiety: Philosophical Quarterly, 4, 245–264.
Evidence for a common core etiologic process based Mackie, J. L. (1974). Cement of the universe: A study
on a meta-analytic review. Clinical Psychological of causation. Oxford, UK: Oxford University
Science, 3, 892–912. Press.
Hu, S., & Liang, H. (2012). Causality analysis of neural MacKinnon, D. P., Cox, M. G., Miocevic, M., & Kisbu-
connectivity: New tool and limitations of spectral Sakarya, Y. (2012, March). Methods to assess
Granger causality. Neurocomputing, 76, 44–47. confounder bias applied to an anabolic steroid pre-
Imai, K., Jo, B., & Stuart, E. A. (2011). Commentary: vention program. Paper presented at the Frontiers in
Using potential outcomes to understand causal media- Causal Inference Conference, Harvard University,
tion analysis. Multivariate Behavioral Research, 46, Cambridge, MA.
861–873. MacKinnon, D. P., & Pirlott, A. G. (2015). Statistical
Imai, K., Keele, L., Tingley, D., & Yamamoto, T. (2014). approaches for enhancing causal interpretation of the
Comment on Pearl: Practical implications of theoreti- M to Y relation in mediation analysis. Personality and
cal results for causal mediation analysis. Psychological Social Psychology Review, 19, 30–43.
Methods, 19, 482–487. Markus, K. A., & Borsboom, D. (2013). Frontiers of test
Imai, K., Keele, L., & Tingley, D. (2010). A general validity theory: Measurement, causation, and mean-
approach to causal mediation analysis. Psychological ing. New York: Routledge.
Methods, 15, 309–334. Marshall, S. L., Parker, P. D., Ciarrochi, J., & Heaven,
Imai, K., Tingley, D., & Yamamoto, T. (2013). P. C. L. (2013). Is self-esteem a cause of consequence
Experimental designs for identifying causal mecha- of social support? A 4-year longitudinal study. Child
nisms. Journal of the Royal Statistical Society, 176, Development, 85, 1275–1291.
5–51. McLanahan, S., Tach, L., & Schneider, D. (2013). The
Jaffee, S. R., Strait, L. B., & Odgers, C. L. (2011). From causal effects of father absence. Annual Review of
correlates to causes: Can quasi-experimental studies Sociology, 39, 399–427.
and statistical innovations bring us closer to identify- McNally, R. J., Robinaugh, D. J., Wu, G. W. Y., Wang, L.,
ing the causes of antisocial behavior? Psychological Deserno, M. K., & Borsboom, D. (2015). Mental dis-
Bulletin, 138, 272–295. orders as causal systems: A network approach to post-
Jo, B. (2008). Causal inference in randomized experi- traumatic stress disorder. Clinical Psychological
ments with meditational processes. Psychological Science, 3, 836–849.
Methods, 13, 314–336. Muthén, B., & Asparouhov, T. (2012). Bayesian SEM: A
Kendler, K. S. (2011). Causal thinking in psychiatry: A more flexible representation of substantive theory.
genetic and manipulationist perspective. In P. E. Psychological Methods, 17, 313–335.
146 6 Statistical Concepts and Networks in Causality

Pearl, J. (2000). Causality: Models, reasoning, and infer- Rubin, D. B. (2010). Reflections stimulated by the com-
ence. New York: Cambridge University Press. ments of Shadish (2010) and West and Thoemmes
Pearl, J. (2009). Causality: Models, reasoning, and infer- (2010). Psychological Methods, 15, 38–46.
ence (2nd ed.). New York: Cambridge University Rubin, D. B., & Thomas, N. (1992). Characterizing the
Press. effect of matching using linear propensity score meth-
Pearl, J. (2014a). Interpretation and identification of causal ods with normal covariates. Biometrika, 79, 797–809.
mediation. Psychological Methods, 19, 459–481. Rutter, M. (2012). “Natural experiments” as a means of
Pearl, J. (2014b). Reply to commentary by Imai, Keele, testing causal inferences. In C. Berzuini, P. Dawid, &
Tingley, and Yamamoto concerning causal mediation L. Bernardinelli (Eds.), Causality: Statistical perspec-
analysis. Psychological Methods, 19, 488–492. tives and applications (pp. 253–272). West Sussex,
Pitman, R. K., Rasmusson, A. M., Koenen, K. C., Shin, UK: Wiley.
L. M., Orr, S. P., Gilbertson, M. W., et al. (2012). Sadeh, N., Spielberg, J. M., Warren, S. L., Miller, G. A., &
Biological studies of post-traumatic stress disorder. Heller, W. (2014). Aberrant neural connectivity during
Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 13, 769–787. emotional processing associated with posttraumatic
Preacher, K. J. (2015). Advances in mediation analysis: A stress. Clinical Psychological Science, 2, 748–755.
survey and synthesis of new developments. Annual Sauce, B., & Matzel, L. D. (2013). The causes of variation
Review of Psychology, 66, 825–852. in learning and behavior: Why individual differences
Rabins, P. (2013). The why of things: Causality in science, matter. Frontiers in Psychology, 4, 395. doi:10.3389/
medicine, and life. New York: Columbia University fpsyg.2013.00395.
Press. Schmidt, U., Faltwasser, S. F., & Wotjak, C. T. (2013).
Raerinne, J. (2011). Causal and mechanistic explanations Biomarkers in posttraumatic stress disorder: Overview
in ecology. Acta Briotheoretica, 59, 251–271. and implications for future research. Disease Markers,
Robins, J. M., Hernán, M. A., & Brumback, B. (2000). 35, 43–54.
Marginal structural models and causal inference in Schwartz, S., Gatto, N. M., & Campbell, U. B. (2011).
epidemiology. Epidemiology, 11, 550–560. What would have been is not what would be:
Robins, J. M., & Richardson, T. S. (2011). Alternative Counterfactuals of the past and potential outcomes of
graphical causal models and the identification of direct the future. In P. E. Shrout, K. M. Keyes, & K. Ornstein
effects. In P. E. Shrout, K. M. Keyes, & K. Ornstein (Eds.), Causality and psychopathology: Finding the
(Eds.), Causality and psychopathology: Finding the determinants of disorders and their cures (pp. 25–46).
determinants of disorders and their cures (pp. 103– New York: Oxford University Press.
158). New York: Oxford University Press. Scott, J. C., Matt, G. E., Wrocklage, K. M., Crnich, C.,
Rosenbaum, P. R., & Rubin, D. B. (1985). Constructing a Jordan, J., Southwick, S. M., et al. (2015). A quantita-
control group using multivariate matched sampling tive meta-analysis of neurocognitive functioning in
methods that incorporate the propensity score. The posttraumatic stress disorder. Psychological Bulletin,
American Statistician, 39, 33–38. 141, 105–140.
Rosenberg, M. (1979). Conceiving the self. New York: Shadish, W. R., Cook, T. D., & Campbell, D. T. (2002).
Basic Books. Experimental and quasi-experimental design for gen-
Rothman, K. J. (1976). Reviews and commentary: Causes. eralized casual inference. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
American Journal of Epidemiology, 104, 587–592. Shadish, W. R., & Sullivan, K. J. (2012). Theories of cau-
Rubin, D. B. (1974). Estimating causal effects of treat- sation in psychological science. In H. Copper, P. M.
ments in randomized and non-randomized studies. Camic, D. L. Long, A. T. Panter, D. Rindskopf, & K. J.
Journal of Educational Psychology, 66, 688–701. Sher (Eds.), APA handbook of research methods in
Rubin, D. B. (1978). Bayesian inference for causal effects: psychology, Vol 1: Foundations, planning, measures,
The role of randomization. Annals of Statistics, 6, and psychometrics (pp. 23–52). Washington:
34–58. American Psychological Association.
Rubin, D. B. (1980). Discussion of “Randomization anal- Shpitser, I. (2012). Structural equations, graphs, and inter-
ysis of experimental data in the Fisher randomization ventions. In C. Berzuini, P. Dawid, & L. Bernardinelli
test”, by D. Basu. Journal of the American Statistical (Eds.), Causality: Statistical perspectives and appli-
Association, 75, 591–593. cations (pp. 15–24). West Sussex, UK: Wiley.
Rubin, D. B. (1990). Formal models of statistical infer- Shpitser, I., VanderWeele, T., & Robins, J. M. (2010). On
ence for causal effects. Journal of Statistical Planning the validity of covariate adjustment for estimating
and Inference, 25, 279–292. causal effects. Proceedings of the 26th Conference of
Rubin, D. B. (2004a). Direct and indirect causal effects Uncertainty and Artificial Intelligence (pp. 527–536).
via potential outcomes. Scandinavian Journal of Corvallis, WA: AUAI Press.
Statistics, 31, 161–170. Shrout, P. E. (2011). Integrating causal analysis into psy-
Rubin, D. B. (2004b). Teaching statistical inference for chopathology research. In P. E. Shrout, K. M. Keyes,
causal effects in experiments and observational stud- & K. Ornstein (Eds.), Causality and psychopathology:
ies. Journal of Educational and Behavioral Statistics, Finding the determinants of disorders and their cures
29, 343–367. (pp. 3–24). New York: Oxford University Press.
References 147

Shrout, P. E., Keyes, K. M., & Ornstein, K. (Eds.). (2011). VanderWeele, T. J. (2010). Bias formulas for sensitivity
Causality and psychopathology: Finding the determi- analysis for direct and indirect effects. Epidemiology,
nants of disorders and their cures. New York: Oxford 21(540), 551.
University Press. von Eye, A., & Wiedermann, W. (2015). Manifest vari-
Skelton, K., Ressler, K. J., Norrholm, S. D., Jovanovic, T., able Granger causality models for developmental
& Bradley-Davino, B. (2012). PTSD and gene variants: research: A taxonomy. Applied Developmental
New pathways and new thinking. Neuropharmacology, Science, 19, 183–195.
62, 628–637. von Eye, A., Wiedermann, W., & Mun, E.-Y. (2013).
Sobel, M. E. (2008). Identification of causal parameters in Granger causality – Statistical analysis under a config-
randomized studies with mediating variables. Journal ural perspective. Integrative Psychological and
of Educational and Behavioral Statistics, 33, 230–251. Behavioral Science, 48, 79–99.
Sugihara, G., May, R., Ye, H., Hsieh, C.-H., Deyle, E., Weathers, F. W., Litz, B. T., Herman, D. S., Huska, J. A.,
Fogarty, M., et al. (2012). Detecting causality in com- & Keane, T. M. (1993, October). The PTSD Checklist
plex ecosystem. Science, 338, 496–500. (PCL): Reliability, validity, and diagnostic utility.
Tian, J., & Pearl, J. (2000). Probabilities of causation: Paper presented at the meeting of the International
Bounds and identification. In C. Boutilier & Society for Traumatic Stress Studies, San Antonio,
M. Goldszmidt (Eds.), Proceedings of the conference TX.
on uncertainty in artificial intelligence (pp. 589–598). Wigman, J. T. W., van Os, J., Borsboom, D., Wardenaar,
San Francisco, CA: Morgan Kaufmann. K. J., Epskamp, S., Klippel, A., et al. (2015). Exploring
Van Bockstaele, B., Verschuere, B., Tibboel, H., De the underlying structure of mental disorders: Cross-
Houwer, J., Crombez, G., & Koster, E. H. W. (2013). diagnostic differences and similarities from a network
A review of current evidence for the causal impact of perspective using both a top-down and a bottom-up
attentional bias on fear and anxiety. Psychological approach. Psychological Medicine. doi:10.1017/
Bulletin, 140, 682–721. S0033291715000331.
Van der Maas, H. L. J., Dolan, C. V., Grasman, R. P. P. P., Woodward, J. (2000). Explanation and invariance in the
Wichertz, J. M., Huizenga, H. M., & Raijmakers, special sciences. British Journal of Philosophy, 51,
M. E. J. (2006). A dynamical model of general intel- 197–254.
ligence: The positive manifold of intelligence by Woodward, J. (2001). Law and explanation in biology:
mutualism. Psychological Review, 113, 842–861. Invariance is the kind of stability that matters.
van der Schoot, R., Denissen, J., Neyer, F. J., Kaplan, D., Philosophical Science, 68, 1–20.
Asendorpf, J. B., & van Aken, M. A. G. (2013). A Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of
gentle introduction to Bayesian analysis: Applications causal explanation. New York: Oxford University
to developmental research. Child Development, 85, Press.
842–860. Wright, R. W. (1988). Causation, responsibility, risk,
van Zuiden, M., Geuze, E., Willemen, H. L. D. M., probability, naked statistics, and proof: Pruning the
Vermetten, E., Maas, M., Amarouchi, K., et al. (2012). bramble bush by clarifying the concepts. Iowa Law
Glucocorticoid receptor pathway components predict Review, 73, 1001–1077.
posttraumatic stress disorder symptom development: Wu, G., Feder, A., Cohen, H., Kim, J. J., Calderon, S.,
A prospective study. Biological Psychiatry, 71, Charney, D. S., et al. (2013). Understanding resilience.
309–316. Frontiers in Behavioral Neuroscience, 7, 10.
van Zuiden, M., Geuze, E., Willemen, H. L. D. M., doi:10.3389/fnbeh.2013.00010.
Vermetten, E., Maas, M., Heijnen, C. J., et al. (2011). Yehuda, R. (2002). Current status of cortisol findings in
Pre-existing high glucocorticoid receptor number pre- post-traumatic stress disorder. Psychiatric Clinics of
dicting development of posttraumatic stress symptoms North America, 25, 341–368.
after military deployment. American Journal of Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feigning, and response
Psychiatry, 168, 89–96. bias in psychiatric/psychological injury: Implications
van Zuiden, M., Heijnen, C. J., Maas, M., Amarouchi, K., for practice and court. Dordrecht, Netherlands:
Vermetten, E., Geuze, E., et al. (2012). Glucocorticoid Springer Science + Business Media.
sensitivity of leukocytes predicts PTSD, depressive Zoladz, P. R., & Diamond, D. M. (2013). Current status on
and fatigue symptoms after military deployment: A behavioral and biological markers of PTSD: A search
prospective study. Psychoneuroendocrinology, 37, for clarity in a conflicting literature. Neuroscience and
1822–1836. Biobehavioral Reviews, 37, 860–895.
Part II
Biology and Revolutions
Brain: The Neuronal Network
Revolution 7

including famous people. Also, in this regard,


Chapter Introduction astrocytes integrate with neurons to form
dynamic systems.
Network concepts are being applied to many As for psychological networks, Schmittmann
disciplines, including neuroscience and psy- et al. (2013) expound that the reflective and for-
chology. The present chapter reviews the work mative models of the relationship between items
involving the brain, in particular. The prototypi- and constructs should be replaced by network
cal construct in network science as applied to the ones. As happens with other network models, this
brain is the connectome (e.g., Sporns, 2012). The one allows for nonlinear dynamical emergence in
intricacies of neuronal linkages and patterns the causality of behavior.
are acquiring their own language, such as hubs.
Researchers are finding core networks in the
brain, involving, in particular, three major ones— Introduction
central executive, salience, and default (resting
state) networks. Some topics in science are obtuse, unobservable,
Concepts involving brain networks include enigmatic, and downright dry. The brain stands at
those emphasized in Friston’s (2010, 2012) work the opposite ends in all these regards. We hunger
on entropy, “free energy,” and “surprise.” In this for news on it, views of it, scans of its activations,
approach, the brain is described in thermody- ideas on its inner workings, and so on. Yet there
namic terms, and functions as if it seeks to mini- are dangers in brain science, as well, to which we
mize the descent into disorder. As with many can fall prey. We might believe that if a brain
systems treated as nonlinear dynamical ones, in region “lights up” on a scan while a person is
this view, the brain functions optimally when it is resolving one task or the next, it means that the
held between order and disorder. As well, in brain region involved is “responsible” uniquely
Friston’s view, perception (and action) aims to for the behavior. We might believe that if a scan
improve accuracy of perception and predictabil- for a criminal indicates abnormalities relative to
ity. In this regard, brain function is Bayesian in norms, then the person should be absolved of
its process. responsibility for the crime at issue. Clearly,
The chapter also reviews work on networks at there is more to behavior than just the brain
the cellular level. Cells in the brain also function regions associated with it. Moreover, there is
in dynamic complexity. For example, “concept” more to the causality of behavior than all things
cells code and fire in order when they are regis- neurological and neuronal. The concepts driving
tering response to specific people or places, neuroscience are proliferating exponentially, and

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 151


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_7
152 7 Brain: The Neuronal Network Revolution

the present chapter examines networks in this for the latter (in patterns of behavior and learning;
regard. However, the reader should be aware of see Table 7.1).
the limitations of their capacity to explain behav- Developmentally, changing physical bodies
ior, as is presently being argued. I am enamored and their activities modify the statistical inputs
of the brain, like all of you. However, I perceive to the brain, molding brain networks. In turn,
it as just one more part of the puzzle of what we the latter promote further changes in input and
do and why in our behavior. In the end, as I tell behavior. Brain networks extend from the brain
my patients, the brain does not control us. Rather, into the environment; development emerges at
we should place ourselves in position where we the level of process from extended networks
control it, at least to the degree possible. involving brain, body, and behavior. These
extended networks actively select and even cre-
ate information, which in turn modifies the
Networks brain’s networks and their dynamics. Develop-
mental change, therefore, is neither maturational
Introduction nor universal.
Brain regions cooperate and coactivate, yet
Brandes, Robins, McCranie, and Wasserman are mutually constrained. They manifest individ-
(2013), who founded the journal Network ual activity differences that are associated with
Science, indicated the increasing importance of differences in cognitive and behavioral perfor-
networks in science. Network models consider mance (Kanai & Rees, 2011; Koyama et al.,
networked phenomena, and develop network 2011; Zatorre, Fields, & Johansen-Berg, 2012).
concepts, including representations, leading to Connectivity is not passive, but generates com-
network explanations of the data. Network theory plex, system-wide dynamics. External inputs are
assumes that any of a cause, an effect, or an asso- not received passively. Instead, their perturba-
ciation can be represented as a network, even in tions have widespread effects. Therefore, an indi-
complex cases. It asks for specification of the vidual’s cumulative history of input perturbations
constituents in a relation, the strength of their leaves a map of the past in changing connectivi-
ties, and so on. ties, and this varies over individuals. Connectivity
involves constant dialogue over multiple param-
eters of network systems and their inputs and out-
Brain puts. Therefore, brain networks are adaptive,
online systems that are dynamically co-evolving
Byrge, Sporns, and Smith (2014) applied the con- over multiple time scales (Gross & Blasius,
cept of brain networks to development. Structural 2008). The process is circular and cascading, and
brain networks consist of anatomical connections changes with development.
between distinct cortical and subcortical brain Byrge et al. (2014) concluded that network
areas. Functional networks involve inter-regional connectivity and dynamics can lead to both con-
connections that reflect statistical dependencies tinuous and discontinuous (qualitatively differ-
in neural activity temporal patterns, either in neu- ent) change both in the input patterns affected by
ral activity during tasks (evoked) or intrinsically behavior and in neural system coupling. Brain
at rest (spontaneous). In the longer-term, struc- networks develop dynamically and their changes
tural networks evidence some change. However, have widespread effects. We need to consider the
even in the short term, functional networks can extended brain–body–behavior network in devel-
change continuously, although they might stabi- opment. This gives us a more mechanistic view
lize. Structural and functional networks interact of development, resituating the developing brain
both in the short term and long term, in a recipro- in the developing organism. However, at the
cal shaping/constraining process for the former same time, the model gives a “less deterministic”
and in the generation of and modulating process comprehension of the process of development.
Networks 153

Table 7.1 Common social network measures and concepts


Level of analysis Network measure Definition
Individual Degree centrality Count of an actor’s total number of social ties.
Indegree refers to incoming ties, and outdegree refers
to outgoing ones
Betweenness centrality A node could lie between or connects two nodes that
would not otherwise be connect; its extent
Closeness centrality A node could be close to all other nodes in the
network; its extent
Structural equivalence A node could play a similar role within a network; its
extent
Group or subgroup Modularity A network could divide into modules; its strength.
High modularity means a network has dense
connections between the nodes within modules but
sparse connections between nodes in different
modules
Clique A clique has every individual directly tied to every
other individual in a subgroup
Transitivity Two nodes could be are connected to a same third
node and also connected to each other; the extent
Network Density The proportion of pairs of nodes that have ties of a
given type (existing ties in a network/all possible ties
in the network)
Reciprocity The proportion of all directional ties that are
reciprocated
Centralization A network could revolve around one or a few nodes;
the extent
Diameter Geodesics (paths between two nodes); the longest
Clustering A network has clumps (small subgroups within the
network with close ties to each other); the extent
Core concepts Stocks An accumulation representing a system’s memory or
state (e.g., in infant behavior)
Flows Stocks change because of associated flow dynamics
connecting stocks (outflow to inflow at rates)
Feedback A structural feature causing cascades in other factors
when it affects a stock (positive or negative; could be
in balance)
Systems structure/Causal Illustrate system reinforcing feedbacks, polarities
loop diagrams involves, whether vicious or virtuous cycles develop
Agent-based modeling Dynamic modeling of system states that includes
(ABMS) parameters, rules, environments, emergence,
complexity, etc.
Adapted from Urban, Osgood, Okamoto, Mabry, and Lich in Molenaar, Lerner, and Newell (2014)

That is, the multiple influences and constraints Comment


on behavior and brain development are exqui-
sitely complex and involve biological, physical, The work of Byrge et al. (2014) and that of oth-
and cultural factors that yield modal similarities, ers, such as Urban, Osgood, Okamoto, Mabry,
yet reveal deep individual, unique variation both and Lich (2014), illustrate the growing research
in moment-to-moment expression and in devel- of network modeling (e.g., Sporns, 2011, 2012)
opmental path. that is being applied increasingly to behavior.
154 7 Brain: The Neuronal Network Revolution

A lot of the concepts that they describe reflect Terms


general network concepts, but some are unique to
the particular applied context, such as develop- Sporns (2011, 2012) provided detailed defini-
ment or the social situation. Other workers tions and explanations of critical terms and
who are informed by network analysis (e.g., concepts in brain network research. In the fol-
Borsboom, 2008, on psychopathology) use com- lowing, I enumerate them.
parable language. Generally, network modeling A graph or network is an abstract depiction of
is consistent with other modeling approaches, a set of interconnected elements (nodes and
such as dynamical systems theory (e.g., Thelen & edges) representing the system at hand. A sim-
Smith, 1994) and causal graph modeling (e.g., ple graph is composed of a set of nodes and
Pearl, 2009). edges. A node (vertex) is a fundamental element
of a system (e.g., a neuron, a person). An edge
connects pairs of nodes. An edge can be either
Connectome directed (e.g., synaptic link, causal effect) from
origin to destination, or undirected (represent-
Model ing a symmetrical relationship). It can be binary
(0, 1) or weighted (fractional; positive or nega-
Sporns (2011, 2012) is leading the way in speci- tive). Most neuroscientific work has been on
fying the brain as a “Connectome,” which refers binary, undirected graphs, usually with binary
to the way neurons and brain regions are inter- graphs resulting when a cut-off is used with
connected. Sporns indicated that, generally, bio- continuous data. An example of a directed graph
logical systems are organized as networks having (or digraph) would involve chemical synaptic
components connected in complex patterns. connections.
Moreover, biological systems function well glob- Topology refers to the geometric relation
ally because they coordinate the action of net- between nodes. An adjacency matrix (or connec-
works. Figure 7.1 presents a map of levels of tion matrix) defines graph topology in rows and
organization in biological systems and the columns in matrix format. Node neighbors are a
brain—moving from molecules; to synapses and node’s set of connected links. The degree of a
neurons; to networks, maps, and systems; to node is its number of incoming and outgoing
behavior (Fig. 7.1a). In this perspective, the ner- edges, and they can be mapped in a degree distri-
vous system is considered a hierarchy of networks bution for a system. Strength is a concept similar
that are multi-scalar and, also, the connectome is to degree. Degree constitutes the most fundamen-
considered to involve network scales operating tal attribute of a graph. Assortivity refers to the
between the cellular and social levels (Fig. 7.1b). correlation between the degrees of connected or
Networks of the brain are mapped at three neighboring node pairs.
modality levels, or in terms of: (a) structural con- A path is a series of unique edges that connect
nectivity across regions, or physical linkages node pairs. Path length involves the number or
(synapses, pathways); (b) functional connectiv- sum of its edges (weights). Characteristic path
ity, or mutual information/coherence as indicated length is constituted by the mean of the finite dis-
by statistical dependencies; and (c) effective con- tances in a network. A path is an ordered sequence
nectivity, which involves causal relations among of unique edges and intermediate nodes. A cyclic
collections of nodes (Jirsa & McIntosh, 2007). path connects a node to itself, or it loops. Distance
Therefore, networks are not metaphors but actual is the shortest topological path in a node pair,
representations of empirical, neuroscientific data with diameter being the maximum distance
that are mathematically formulated. possible in a node pair. Distance matrices
Connectome 155

a b
Mind Social
Behavior

Behavior
Social
Hierarchical, Vertical, Interlevel Organization

Network
Central Nervous
System

Hierarchical, Vertical Interlevel Organization


Regions and
Pathways
System (macroscale)

Map
Circuits and Cell
Populations Connectome
(mesoscale)
In Multiples

Network

Neurons and
Neuron
Synapses
(microscale)

Synapse
Gene and Protein
Networks
Molecule

Horizontal, Interlevel Organization Horizontal Interlevel Organization

Fig. 7.1 The vertical and horizontal organization under- nent to the original model, as indicated by the lines to the
lying the connectome. The first part of the figure (a) illus- right. Adapted from Churchland and Sejnowski (1992).
trates the progression from biochemical constituents of The second part of the figure (b) illustrates the basic levels
cells to cells and their networks/maps to larger systems of the connectome in terms of the output of social net-
and behavior. I added a horizontal diversifying compo- works/behavior. Adapted from Sporns (2012)

complement connection matrices in describing A rich club is a set of high-degree nodes, a


network communication patterns. term related to the core. A random network has
Other network properties include the cluster- stochastic interconnections; in the simplest case,
ing coefficient, or the fraction of connections its edges between nodes are randomly assigned
connecting node neighbors (representing net- with fixed and uniform probabilities. In a scale-
work neighborhood “cliquishness”). Connectivity free network, its degree distribution follows a
refers to the set of node connections. Modules are power law. A small world network combines high
communities of strongly interconnected nodes, clustering (as in a regular lattice network) and
having connection patterns and “partitions.” short characteristic path length (as in a random
A core is a coherent, highly and mutually network). Global efficiency is a distance mea-
interconnected node set. A hub is a node that is sure, and centrality is a node or edge measure.
influentially important, or central to network Generally, graph measures involve segregation,
interconnectivity. Connector hubs function to integration, or influence.
link nodes over modules. Provincial hubs The work of Sporns (2011, 2012) can be con-
link constituent nodes in a module. A motif is a sulted for the massive details of the connectome.
reduced subset of network nodes and edges, or a Two conclusions in Sporns (2012) that I found
subgraph. important relate to intrinsic brain networks and
156 7 Brain: The Neuronal Network Revolution

intermediate endophenotypes. For the former, Table 7.2 Seven resting-state brain networks/systems
Raichle (2011) has found seven major resting- and their interconnections
state brain networks and their interconnections Central regions of interest
(see Table 7.2). For the latter, Sporns postulated Resting-state brain (According to BOLD, blood-
network/system oxygen-level dependent values)
that the connectome will serve an integral
Default mode Posterior cingulate/precuneus
mediator in understanding genetic-behavioral (DMN) Medial prefrontal
linkages. L lateral parietal
R lateral parietal
L inferior temporal
Systems R inferior temporal
Medial dorsal thalamus
Sporns (2011) explained the value of network R posterior cerebellum
thinking in brain theory and research. It allows an Dorsal attentional L posterior cerebellum
integrative look at brain function from a complex (DAN) L frontal eye field
connectivity perspective. It incorporates complex- R frontal eye field
ity science as a framework for understanding ele- L posterior inferior parietal
ment coupling and interconnections. Networks sulcus
R posterior inferior parietal
create dynamical patterns of interrelationships that
sulcus
are not reducible to parts. Brain networks have L anterior inferior parietal
multiple scales in their arrangements, from cells to sulcus
the social networks that they allow. These levels R posterior inferior parietal
are interrelated, with the patterns of each critically sulcus
dependent on processes that unfold at lower and at L middle temporal area
higher levels. In this hierarchy, there are no privi- R middle temporal area
leged level, with neither full-scale reduction to Executive control Dorsal medial prefrontal cortex
(ECN) L anterior prefrontal cortex
lower levels nor inclusive top-down influences
from higher levels. In this type of modeling, con- R anterior prefrontal cortex
L superior parietal
nectivity permits neurons to act in both indepen-
R superior parietal
dent and collective ways. Connectivity permits
Salience (SN) Dorsal anterior cingulate
brain integration. In other words, the brain func-
L anterior prefrontal cortex
tions like any network in complex systems.
R anterior prefrontal cortex
Sporns (2011) noted that network models run
L insula
counter to both the doctrine of the centrality of the R insula
neuron and the mechanistic functional localization L lateral parietal
of the brain. Rather, they help explain how neu- R lateral parietal
rons and regions work and also how they are inter- Sensorimotor (SS) L motor cortex
connected. In this regard, Sporns (2011) described R motor cortex
various neuroanatomical pathways and linkages in Supplementary motor area
terms of “connectomal fingerprints,” such as con- Auditory (AS) L auditory area
nectional fingerprints, connectional families, hier- R auditory area
archical fingerprints, and motif fingerprints. Visual (VS) R visual area 1
“Connectomics” means that two brains from L visual area 1
different individuals are never exactly the same. Adapted from Raichle (2011)
Despite these individual differences, their brains Note: L = left, R = right, N = network, S = system
Connectome 157

still express functional homeostasis, or common superordinate variables and reducing degrees
activity in outcome, at least to a certain degree. of freedom, and so “contracting” the regions of
In this perspective, the functional localization space accessible to systems [but without denying
approach of the brain comes closer to a distribu- movement to the cusp of change and emergence
tionist approach to the brain. Local specialization of new regimes and meta-stability] (e.g., Kello,
should be seen as the result of patterned and dis- Beltz, Holden, & Van Orden, 2008). It appears
tributed interactions involving individual and that brains are primed to inhabit this state space
collective elements. Therefore, the brain should of order and disorder, facilitating phase transi-
be considered an integrative system with emer- tions marked by variable stability, instability, and
gent and complex properties. In this regard, Fair meta-stability.
et al. (2009) found that functional networks seem
to progress from local/segregated to distributed/
integrated organizational modes. Evidence
Sporns (2011) also examined brain networks
from the perspective of dynamics, which allows Sporns and van den Heuvel (2013) statistically
for integration of stability and change and diver- analyzed weighted projections among different
sity in systems. Systems express a multi-scale, cortical regions in healthy volunteers (van den
nested hierarchical structure that is neither Heuvel, Kahn, Goñi, & Sporns, 2012; van den
entirely stable nor unstable but, instead, is “meta- Heuvel & Sporns, 2011). Their model includes
stable.” System trajectories travel in manifolds network “hubs,” defined in terms of high-degree
with attractor “pockets” that slow or entrap node connectivity. They posed the question
them, creating intermittent, “quasi-stable,” tem- whether hubs themselves, proportionately, are
poral behavior. The wells or indentations into highly mutually connected, in what is called a
which the systems fall are visited repeatedly, in a “rich club.”
process of chaotic itinerancy, or itinerant roam- The results revealed a rich club core involving
ing motion. The flow is turbulent because, portions of the following brain regions: superior
although the system elements are globally cou- frontal cortex, superior parietal cortex, precu-
pled, they are far-from-equilibrium. The system neus, cingulate cortex, and insula. These areas
trajectories alternate between order and transi- are midline focused, with a rich club set found in
tion, losing their coupling coherence within the each hemisphere. The work of Sporns and van
movement between attractor “ruins.” den Heuvel (2013) showed that rich club brain
Systems might contain “saddle point” chains connectives constitute central communication
that both attract and repel trajectories, creating the cores of global information. They are widely
meta-stable dynamic. Also, network connection distributed, and often their connections span rela-
facilitates creation of “collector” variables that tively long distances. According to the authors,
“enslave” lower levels, reducing their degrees of longer connection lengths are “costly,” but the
freedom, thereby adding to stabilization tenden- advantages of having core communicating
cies. But, as system order moves toward disorder, hubs involving them comprise a communicative
in the critical region or at the “edge of chaos,” “backbone” in the brain.
emergence of novelty and complex system modes van den Heuvel and Sporns (2013) expanded
become favored (Bak, Tang, & Wiesenfeld, 1987). on the role of hubs in brain networks. For exam-
Criticality might be a property favored in the ple, the interaction of frontal hubs and distributed
dynamic regime of systems, given the inherent cortical regions increase in development. The
tradeoff of randomness and regularity in environ- hubs and their connections are critical in infor-
ments. Connectivity could promote stability and mation integration and in efficient neural signal-
diversity by collecting system behavior into ing/communication in the brain.
158 7 Brain: The Neuronal Network Revolution

Conclusions network (CEN), the salience network (SN), and


the default mode network (DMN). The salience
Sporns (2011) concluded that complexity is a network is involved in dynamic switching to the
central design feature of the brain, allowing it to other two (DMN, CEN), which are focused on
adapt to variable and partly predictable envir- endogenously-mediated/self-referential mental activ-
onments. The organism becomes autonomous ity and exogenously driven/cognitively-demanding
because it is part of a rich dynamic web of per- mental activity, respectively (see Fig. 7.2).
son, brain, mind, and environment in which the The CEN is especially comprised of intercon-
organism is not controlled by any algorithm or nectivity of the dorsolateral prefrontal cortex
blueprint but is expressed in the full network (DLPFC) and posterior parietal cortex (PPC).
system. The SN is anchored in the anterior insula (AI),
I would add that a full network understanding the adjoining fronto-insular cortex (FIC), and the
of the brain, its networks, and the person in con- anterior cingulate cortex (ACC). The DMN is
text considers emergent properties of mind, such focused in the posterior cingulate cortex (PCC),
as free will. Emergent concepts such as these medial prefrontal cortex (mPFC), medial tempo-
allow escapement from network constraints and ral lobe (MTL), and angular gyrus (AG). These
dictates, and inform bidirectionally development three networks are considered core because they
of networks so that they actively function beyond can be involved in a very broad array of cognitive
the influences of biology and environment. A cru- tasks and they are reciprocally related and
cial element in this regard is the emergent sense dynamically engaged and disengaged (Greicius
of freedom from internal or external constraint or & Menon, 2004; Raichle et al., 2001; Sridharan,
control that the person can develop and use, at Levitin, & Menon, 2008).
least partially, to direct and determine behavior. Network analysis of temporal dynamics
Behavior is never fully free nor is it the complete reveals “causal flow” over core networks. In both
product of free will. However, believing in it and auditory and visual tasks, the right hemisphere
having a sense of free will give us some freedom FIC had the highest number of causal outflow
of action (Baumeister, 2008), and that is the best connections (out-degree) and the lowest number
system we, and our brains, along with their net- of inflow, in-degree ones, as well as the shortest
works, can hope to and happen to have. path length of measured regions (also ACC,
rDLPFC, rPPC, VMPFC, PCC). These results
combine to give the rFIC the highest net causal
Core Networks outflow to inflow ratio (out-in degree), making it
a causal outflow “hub” in the SN to which it is
Model anchored.
The AI, in general, is considered the integral
Menon (2012) investigated neurocognitive net- hub of the SN. As a dynamic switching mecha-
works in brain dynamics as evidenced by intrin- nism to endogenous and exogenous stimuli, the
sic functional connectivity. During cognitive SN includes bottom-up and top-down interac-
tasks, brain areas that are engaged appear to tions that underpin attentional control. Bottom-up
form coherent global networks. Shirer, Ryali, stimulus-detection signals (in CPS, cycles per
Rykhlevskaia, Menon, and Greicius (2012) have second) are transmitted to brain regions that
identified 14 intrinsic connectivity networks in include the AI, which amplifies them, thereby
resting-state functional MRI neuroimaging data. triggering a strong ACC response. The ACC gen-
They are important not only in sensory process- erates a top-down control signal, including to the
ing but also in higher cognitive functions. CEN. Premotor cortical and temporoparietal
According to Menon (2012), among these 14 areas respond. Response mediation also takes
networks, three appear “core” neurocognitive place in other areas (e.g., supplementary motor
networks. They are termed the central executive cortex).
Core Networks 159

Sensory and Limbic


Inputs

Default Mode Salience Central-Executive


Network Network Network

VMPFC AI DLPFC

PCC ACC PCC

Endogenously mediated/ Dynamic Exogenously driven/


Self-referential mental switching Cognitively demanding
activity mental activity

Fig. 7.2 Multinetwork switching initiated by the salience DMN: ventral medial prefrontal cortex (VMPFC) and
network. The SN (salience network) is hypothesized to posterior cingulate cortex (PCC). Key nodes of the CEN:
initiate dynamic switching between the CEN (central- dorsolateral prefrontal cortex (DLPFC) and the posterior
executive network) and DNM (default mode network) and parietal cortex (PPC). Adapted from Menon (2012), based
to mediate between attention to endogenous and exoge- on Bressler and Menon (2010), original from Uddin and
nous events. In this model, sensory and limbic inputs are Menon (2009). Adopted with permission of Elsevier.
processed by the anterior insula (AI), which detects salient Reprinted from Neuroscience and Behavioral Reviews,
events and initiates appropriate control signals to regulate Vol. 33, Uddin, L. Q., & Menon, V., The anterior insula in
behavior via the anterior cingulate cortex (ACC) and autism: Under-connected and under-examined, Pages
homeostatic state via the mid and posterior insular cortex. 1198–1203, Copyright 2009; with kind permission from
Key nodes of the SN: AI and ACC. Key nodes of the Elsevier. [Figure 2, Page 1202]

Menon (2013) described six emerging Systems


principles of developmental pathways for func-
tional brain networks. Among them are the Singer (2013) described cortical networks as
development of “small-world,” hierarchical dynamic, nonlinear, self-organized, and com-
organization and hubs, segregation of functional plex. Their organization allows support of “high
circuits, their pruning and reconfiguration, and a dimensional” states and the binding of local
balance in excitation/inhibition in underpinning processors into highly interconnected coherent
physiology in neurotransmitters (impacting local global states. The organization constitutes a
circuits and large-scale connectivity). “dense connectome” that permits essentially
Rubinov and Bullmore (2013) indicated that, “unconstrained” interactions between any pair of
in psychiatric disorder, there might be “patho- neurons in the cortical mantle. The couplings can
connectomics” at work. However, at present, the be modified very quickly by inhibition in syn-
evidence for specific relationships between disor- chronized oscillating cell circuits at the correct
der and such pathology is inconclusive. phase.
160 7 Brain: The Neuronal Network Revolution

The connectome varies between randomness view of brain architecture, and related it to an
and regularity so that its complexity and dim- integrated emotion-cognitive perspective of the
ensionality is neither excessively stochastic brain.
(independent, highly dimensional) nor synchro-
nized (low dimensionality), but is intermediate
along this continuum. The resting-state dynamics Evidence
of cortical networks appear to function like a
self-organized critical system, a characteristic Cognition Zanto and Gazzaley (2013) reviewed
that is favorable for computations (Deco & Jirsa, a study by Cole et al. (2013) demonstrating that
2012; Priesemann, Valderrama, Wibral, & Van the fronto-parietal network (FPN) is altered in
Quyen, 2013; Wang, Hilgetag, & Zhou, 2011). its functional connections with other networks
Ruths and Ruths (2014) proposed a model of according to task goals. The FPN is a control-
complex networks that included multiple control type network compared to others that are process-
nodes. Networks consist of branching nodes and oriented. It involves the lateral prefrontal cortex
“dilation” points; also, each “stem” in the system and posterior parietal cortex areas. It is associ-
has a control mechanism. We need to understand ated with cognitive control abilities in initiation
the configuration and causal origin of a network’s and modulation. Control networks are flexible,
minimal control points to grasp it better. Stems rapid, and dynamic compared to processing
have buds and cycles, and are referred to as networks, which are relatively task-specific,
“cacti.” Biological neural and social networks are modular, and static.
not top-down driven; rather, they are source- The authors concluded that dynamic multi-
dominated in control, allowing uncorrelated network interactions that appear to take place in
behavior and distributed processing. cognition denote a flexible hub model of connec-
Moretti and Muñoz (2013) have modified the tome activity. Task resolution flexibility leads not
criticality model of complex systems by specify- only to intra-neural network reorganization but
ing that operating at the edge of chaos (in the also inter-network reorganization in a synchro-
critical region) is not simply a borderline or sin- nous fashion. Harmelech and Malach (2013)
gular point between organization and disorgani- examined the spontaneous activity in the resting
zation but a whole extended region around it. The brain (no overt task). They found that spontane-
existence of such a “stretched” criticality (called ous fluctuations in this default mode revealed
Griffith phases, GPs) facilitates self-organization by BOLD-fMRI (blood-oxygen-level dependent
toward criticality. Brain networks that are hierar- functional magnetic resonance imaging) readings
chical and modular (as in the connectome) appear seem to reflect the person’s profile of prior neuro-
to function in this way, facilitating their adaptive nal connectivity and cognitive biases. The latter
functionality. serve to influence “synaptic efficacies” in cortical
Hilgetag and Hütt (2014) pointed out that crit- networks. As such, they can be remodeled.
icality allows for adaptation because a small Therefore, their current state offers a window
change in an external control parameter can lead into their past states (priors), inner (cortical)
to disproportionately large reconfiguration in world, pathologies, cognitive biases and traits,
system state organization. Stretching criticality and personality traits/tendencies (e.g., Adelstein
in hierarchical modular brain connectivity takes et al., 2011).
place through regional mixtures of sub- and Reinhart and Woodman (2013) demonstrated
super-critical behavior in the GPs. The concept of the online dynamic reorganization in oscillatory
stretched criticality in brain networks could be coupling of large-scale neuronal networks in
applied to “dysfunctional” functional networks relation to changing phases and task demands of
(e.g., for depression, see Sombataro, Wolf, a search task lasting several seconds in which
Pennuto, Vasic, & Wolf, 2014; van Tol et al., participants had to locate target objects in
2014). Similarly, Pessoa (2014) took a network cluttered visual scenes. The task phases tapped
Core Networks 161

reward encoding, working memory, and attentional Applied Using voxel-based lesion-symptom
processes. The reward cue indicated the mone- mapping in focal brain-injury patients, Barbey,
tary value of the trial in process. The target Colom, and Grafman (2014) demonstrated that a
cue was presented briefly (100 ms), so that common neural network is engaged in executive,
information retention in working memory was social, and emotional processes. Specifically, a
needed in relation to the attentional phase. The broadly distributed neural network of frontal,
final search phase lasted 2 s. Recordings that temporal, and parietal regions is shared or con-
indicated oscillatory coupling involved cross- vergent with not only general intelligence but
frequency coupling analyses of participant EEG also with emotional intelligence and personality.
oscillations, in search of fast rhythmic temporal The authors concluded that behavior is orches-
correlations of neuronal activity. trated in multiple brain regions that aggregate in
The results showed that each cognitive opera- function supporting intellectual and affective
tion led to formation and dissolution of func- processes. The broad neural network architecture
tional connectivity between different brain areas. involved is coordinated, integrated, interactive,
In particular, in large reward conditions, initial/ intersecting, connective, and collaborative, rather
task phase theta and beta oscillations over pre- than being localized, selective, or distinct.
frontal brain regions realized a distributed Barch (2013) examined brain network interac-
network as defined by the coupling of these fre- tions, as well. He focused on the research of
quencies. In the next task phase of working Palaniyappan, Simmonite, White, Liddle, and
memory, the theta and alpha oscillations across Liddle (2013), which showed that deficits in
frontoparietal areas formed a neuronal network, reciprocal causal interactions across the salience
which was distinct in dynamic relative to the one and CENs are implicated in schizophrenia. In
in the first task phase. Next, in the target search particular, they focused on interactions involving
phase, theta and alpha oscillations over fronto- the insula (part of the salience system) and the
temporal areas formed another distinct network. DLPFC (part of the CEN). The deficits involved
Other results showed that networks could form difficulties related to inhibition of the DLPFC
quickly, and they predict even better than either and excitations into it (both findings in relation to
local oscillations or ERPs (event-related poten- the insula).
tials) subsequent network strength and actual
behavioral response (speed and accuracy) that Sex Ingalhalikar et al. (2014) illustrated in the
takes place seconds later. research the value of studying whole-brain con-
The authors concluded that the results support nectome networks. They studied sex differences
a dynamic or transient stimulus coding model. in the structural connectome in 8- to 22-year-
Also, large-scale neuronal network activity consti- olds. In all supratentorial regions, males showed
tutes an intermediate organization level between greater within-hemisphere connectivity, with
circuit-level computation and higher-order behav- connections extending front to back. In contrast,
ior/experience. females showed greater between-hemisphere
Matsumoto and Kakigi (2013) noted that the connectivity. Males also differed by their enhan-
dynamic balance of left frontal and temporal cor- ced modularity/transitivity, compared to females
tical regions can be primed by subliminal uncon- who, in contrast, were more cross-module in
scious semantic cues. In their study, subliminal connectivity.
semantic priming induced significant modulation The authors concluded that the results reflect
of alpha band activity in the left inferior frontal fundamental cerebral functional differences in
cortex and of gamma band activity in left inferior males and females. The former have brains struc-
temporal regions. The influence of the priming tured to facilitate connection between perception
extended beyond local brain regions to online and coordinated action. In contrast, females have
dynamics that were over them. a brain organization conducive to communication
162 7 Brain: The Neuronal Network Revolution

between analytic and intuitive processing modal- activation/inhibition coordinations superordinate


ities. Finally, the male difference emerges earlier to rather than reflective of brain networks and
than the female one. behavioral networks both within and between
people? Are they the constitutive stuff of brain,
behavior, and their networks, the defining attri-
Comment butes of their interactions, in what I have referred
to as the intraactive interactional dynamics that
Network modeling provides a rich conceptual constitute the essence of phenomena more than
network and vocabulary that greatly expands our the components of the interactions themselves?
understanding of brain and behavior. In systems, In the next section of the chapter, I elaborate
we can now determine the degree of centrality the construct of free energy in the brain that has
and distribution, efficiency and dispersion, path- already been introduced because of its impor-
ways and functions, and so on. The work on brain tance to the book and its understanding of behav-
networks has focused on core ones, such as those ioral causality. I have supported a role of free will
relating to salience and attention, executive func- in behavior and this concept of free energy related
tion, and resting state. Network concepts are to brain function is consistent with it. However,
greatly intertwined with those of systems theory, the relationship between free will and free energy
such as emergence, criticality, attractors, and the appears to be an inverse one. Free energy in the
cusp of change. The marriage is fortified by the brain might compromise free will in behavior
development of new systems concepts, such as because it reflects disorder more than order and
stretched criticality. I note that the research in the the brain works to diminish it. In this regard, the
area refers to activations and inhibitions. more the brain is successful in the task, the more
This latter point is consistent with my pro- there should be degrees of freedom available in
posal that a common metric that crosses brain its functioning to implement free will (in choos-
and behavior is activation/inhibition coordina- ing and deciding and so on), so that freedom of
tion. As networks self-organize into adaptive pat- being obtains.
terns to support the behavior of the organism, it
does not happen without an implicit economical
process that accounts for system stretching to the Free Energy and Surprise
edge of change after perturbation. In this regard,
the construct of activation/inhibition coordina- Model
tion should be added into the network lexicon
and rework some of its terms while adding new As described by Friston (2010), organisms and
ones. In addition, the construct applies equally their brains function according to adaptive resis-
well not only to internal dynamics of brain and tance toward disruptive disorder. In order to main-
behavior but also to interactive ones of individu- tain equilibrium in its environment, any biological
als with one or more others. entity or agent needs to self-organizationally mini-
For example, do network betweenness, cen- mize its free energy. In resisting tendency to disor-
trality, efficiency, or small world and rich club der, a small range of adaptive states is entered into
characteristics develop because certain nodes and (the entity, phenotypic expression), which means it
edges in network pathways are inhibited while has low “entropy.” “Surprise” refers to the average
others are activated, and how does this happen entropic state (mathematically, the negative log-
through intrinsic dynamics? Can psychological probability of an outcome). By keeping surprise
activation/inhibition coordination dynamics feed low, which is the biological equivalent of the sec-
into neural network ones and create characteris- ond law of thermodynamics, the principle of a nat-
tics parallel to them, or vice versa, and how might ural decline in disorder and also increase in entropy
this happen reciprocally between brain and (the “fluctuation” theorem) is violated “construc-
behavior? In this regard, to what extent are tively” by the adapting biological entities/agents.
Free Energy and Surprise 163

a AGENT ENVIRONMENT
Sensation

States (Internal) States (External)

Signals (Action/
Control)

b Free-energy limit
on “surprise”

Perceptions optimize Actions minimize


prediction prediction error

Fig. 7.3 Principle of free energy. Part (a) of the figure erates sensory samples (and their causes). The latter is
indicates the elements among the factors that define free akin to a probabilistic generative model. Part (b) of the
energy. These include the internal states of the brain and figure indicates that free energy minimization involves
its exchange with the environment, which involves sen- action reducing it by increasing accuracy (i.e., by selec-
sory signals leading to action. Sensory input includes tively sampling predicted data). Conversely, the optimiza-
hidden states, parameters, and precisions. Internal brain tion of brain states constructs the “representation” of
states and action serve to minimize free energy, and it “approximate conditional density” of “causes” of senso-
involves, the “recognition density” that is encoded by rial inputs. This process allows action to avoid sensory
internal states. The free energy depends on two probabil- encounters that are surprising. Adapted from Friston
ity densities—the one of recognition and the one that gen- (2010)

Free energy regulation optimizes movements sensations and internal states. The environment
from one state to another, thereby minimizing can be represented mathematically in equations
surprise and keeping the state movements within that specify its “hidden states.” Therefore, the
a small set of adaptive states, referred to as a “causes of sensory input” include such hidden
global random “attractor.” Surprise is an infor- states. Moreover, brain states function to mini-
mation “theoric quantity” and not an energetic mize free energy either by increasing or optimi-
thermodynamic one. The agent entity can regu- zing “accuracy,” or by minimizing prediction
late it as a function of sensory state and “recogni- errors (e.g., selectively sampling data that are
tion density,” which refers to factors such as predicted).
neuronal activity and connection strength (for the According to a more formal description of the
brain). It is defined as an approximate probability model, in optimization, the entity/agent imp-
distribution of the causes of data (e.g., sensory licitly represents or infers the causes behind its
input). sensory data in a “Bayes-optimal” manner. By
The figure presenting Friston’s model changing sensory input, either by acting on the
(Fig. 7.3) shows that external states might pro- environment or by changing an internal state, an
duce action or control signals, but only by way of entity/organism can self-organize appropriately
164 7 Brain: The Neuronal Network Revolution

to avoid excessive surprise. “Bayesian surprise” average surprise or unexpected events. Friston
refers to the difference between a prior recogni- (2012) maintained that self-organization is insuffi-
tion density, e.g., about beliefs about the state of cient to explain how biological agents can avoid
the environment before assimilation of sensory surprise in an indefinite fashion.
data, and posterior beliefs. The entity/agent acts For Friston (2012), the answer to this conun-
to formulate “active” inferences about anticipa- drum lies in agents maximizing evidence for
tions/expectations and tries to confirm them. their models of sensory exchanges with the
In the Bayesian brain hypothesis (Knill & world. Our brains or its agents are model opti-
Pouget, 2004), by using sensory inputs or infor- mizers, or inference machines, based on statis-
mation, or updated posterior beliefs, the brain tical engines with reference to sensory data
optimally uses probability theory to form opti- available to us. In Bayesian brain models, the
mized, constructed perceptions. In the Bayesian brain makes inferences about its sensations. The
brain model, the brain is construed as an infer- brain becomes a dynamic model of its collective
ence machine or engine that actively optimizes environmental “econiches.” Moreover, surprise
probabilistic representations of the causes of sen- is minimized in this model by creating free-
sory input, using them simultaneously. It actively energy “bounds.” Therefore, in the Bayesian
predicts and explains sensations, using predictive brain hypothesis, minimizing variational free
coding. The predictions enable testing of sensory energy entails “Bayes-optimal” perception, or
samples to help update belief about their causes. reducing prediction errors. Further, to minimize
Generative models help facilitate mapping prob- prediction error, either perception or action can
abilistic likelihoods and priors, and their inver- be altered; with the latter giving us agency to act
sions, so that adaptive perception results from on the world in order to ensure that predictions
sensory input. Hierarchical generative models arise as they should. Moreover, prior expecta-
help explain how prior beliefs are formed and are tions produce “policies” that are followed. State
consistent with the hierarchical architecture of spaces are characterized by “viscosity,” which
cortical areas. can be negative, with a slowing friction, or which
can be positive. Agents wander in state space to
find spaces equivalent to priors to which they had
Systems gravitated and, at this point, viscosity switches
from positive to negative. If the priors are reward-
Friston (2012) further described his “free energy” ing and low-cost, they are “exploited” and popu-
model of global brain dynamics (see Table 7.3). lated. Stability prevails and disorder is resisted,
To review, it includes concepts such as “surprise” unless rewards and costs determine otherwise.
and “hidden causes.” The model helps explicate
self-organized neuronal activity in relation to
brain activity. The neuronal dynamics involved Neurons
are framed in terms of “optimization” (e.g., func-
tion minimization). The brain functions to model Deco, Jirsa, and Friston (2012) explicated the
sensorial input, including with free energy mini- systemic nature of local and global network
mization and consideration of Bayesian priors. dynamics in brain activity. They examined (a)
Friston (2012) continued that the brain is not integrate-and-fire spiking neurons at the local
equally distributed in energy and potential states, level and (b) large-scale anatomical connectivity
but gravitates to a small number. As a biological matrices of local nodes over distributed brain
agent, it maintains a distribution of low entropy areas at the global level. The global dynamics
(high order) among the states it could occupy. In included functional integration and effective con-
this regard, entropy is the average “surprise” (or nectivity across segregated, interacting, and mutu-
negative log probability) of an agent being in a spe- ally influencing brain areas. They were found to
cific state. The agent involved seeks to minimize emerge from the local ones of each brain area.
Table 7.3 Generic variables and quantities in the free-energy formation of active inference under Laplace assumption
(i.e., generalized predictive coding)
Variable Description
Generative model or agent In the free-energy formulation, each agent or system is taken to be a model of the
environment in which it is immersed. It corresponds to the form (e.g., degrees of
freedom) of a model entailed by an agent, which is used to predict sensory signals
Action These variables are states of the world that correspond to the movement or
configuration of an agent (i.e., its effectors)
Sensory signals These generalized sensory signals or samples comprise the sensory states, their
velocity, acceleration, and temporal derivatives to high order. In other words, they
correspond to the trajectory of an agent’s sensations
Surprise This is a scalar function of sensory samples and reports the improbability of
sampling some signals under a generative model of how those signals were
caused. It is sometimes called (sensory) surprisal or self-information. In statistics,
it is known as the negative log-evidence of the model
Entropy Sensory entropy is, under ergodic assumptions, proportional to the long-term time
average of surprise
Gibbs energy The negative log of the density specified by the generative model; namely,
surprise about the joint occurrence of sensory samples and their causes
Free energy A scalar function of sensory samples and a proposal density, which upper bounds
surprise. It is called free energy because it is the expected Gibbs energy minus the
entropy of the proposal density. Under a Gaussian (Laplace) assumption about the
form of the proposal density, free energy reduces to the simple function of Gibbs
energy shown
Free action A scalar function of sensory samples and a proposal density, which upper bounds
the entropy of sensory signals. It is the time or path integral of free energy
Proposal density Also known as a variational ensemble or recognition density. It becomes
(approximates) the conditional density over hidden causes of sensory samples
when free-energy is minimized. Under the Laplace assumption, it is specified by
its conditional expectation and covariance
True and hidden causes Quantities that cause sensory signals. The true quantities exist in the environment,
and the hidden homologues are those assumed by the generative model of the
environment. Both are partitioned into time-dependent variables and time-
invariant parameters
Hidden parameters Parameters of the mapping (e.g., equations of motion) that constitute the
deterministic part of a generative model
Log-precisions Parameters that control the precision (inverse variance) of fluctuations that
constitute the random part of a generative model
Hidden states Hidden variables that encode the hierarchical states in a generative model of
dynamics in the world
Hidden causes Hidden variables that link different levels of a hierarchical generative model
Deterministic mappings Equations at the ith level of a hierarchical generative model that map from states
at one level to another and map hidden states to their motion within each level.
They specify the deterministic part of a generative model
Random fluctuations These relate to hidden causes and the motion of hidden states. Gaussian
assumptions about these fluctuations furnish the probabilistic part of a generative
model
Precision matrices The inverse covariances among (generalized) random fluctuations on the hidden
causes and motion of hidden states
Roughness matrices The inverse of a matrix encoding serial correlations among (generalized) random
fluctuations on the hidden causes and motion of hidden states
Prediction errors The prediction errors on the hidden causes and motion of hidden states evaluated
at their current conditional expectation
Precision-weighted The prediction errors weighted by their respective precisions
predic tion errors
Adopted by permission of The MIT Press. Rabinovich, Mikhail I., Karl J. Friston, and Pablo Varona, eds., Principles of
Brain Dynamics: Global State Interactions, Table 12.1, pp. 13, pp. 264–265, © 2012 Massachusetts Institute of
Technology, by permission of The MIT Press. [Table 12.1, Pages. 264–265]
166 7 Brain: The Neuronal Network Revolution

Reciprocally, the global level constrains or decision-making in cognitive functions (e.g.,


couples with local activity. Also, the whole sys- Brunel & Wang, 2001).
tem expresses self-organization. The interaction Attractor networks of spiking neurons are
of the levels can be described in terms of the hypothesized to consist of fixed-point attractors
concept of circular causality, attractors, function- representing local networks. The network consists
ing in critical regimes that power phase tran- of excitatory and inhibitory neural populations
sitions, and other dynamical system concepts. (see Fig. 7.4). Dynamical equations can be used to
Self-organization occurs through enslavement of describe the activity of each neuron, which settle
neuronal populations within a specific brain area into particular regions of their state space to which
by large-scale intercortical dynamics. they are consistently pulled. The excitatory and
The dynamical approach is consistent with the inhibitory neurons influence each other through
computational neuroscience one in which this coupling and connectivity.
approach is embedded. The computational neuro- Specifically, spikes arriving at a given synapse
science approach attempts to describe the dynam- constitute input to the neuron, leading to postsyn-
ics of neuronal and synaptic networks with aptic excitatory or inhibitory firing potentials at
realistic models to reproduce “emergent” charac- postsynaptic receptors. In the present case, the total
teristics, or to predict neurophysiological data synaptic current is an expression of glutamatergic
and associated behavior. The concept of attractor (excitatory) and GABAergic (inhibitory) transmit-
dynamics has been applied to represent neural ters deriving from reciprocally modulated excit-
computations related to attention, memory, and atory pyramidal cells and inhibitory interneurons.

(AMPA, NMDA)

(AMPA, NMDA)

Excitatory
population

GABA

Inhibitory
population
External inputs

GABA

Fig. 7.4 A local network. The network consists of interneurons. Adopted by permission of The MIT Press.
spiking neurons with realistic AMPA (α-Amino-3- Rabinovich, Mikhail I., Karl J. Friston, and Pablo Varona,
hydroxy-5-methyl-4-isoxazolepropionic acid), NMDA eds., Principles of Brain Dynamics: Global State
(N-methyl-D-aspartate receptor), and GABA (gamma- Interactions, Figure 1.1, pp. 13, pp. 13, © 2012
Aminobutyric acid) synaptic dynamics. The network Massachusetts Institute of Technology, by permission of
contains excitatory pyramidal cells and inhibitory The MIT Press. [Figure 1.1, Page 13]
Cells 167

Connectome both prior states and predictions of the future


(state, environment, best adaptive response, etc.)
As for the global level of brain organization, is impossible. At the same time, Bayesian think-
Deco et al. (2012) referred to the concept of the ing that is probability-governed and contextual
connectome (e.g., Jirsa, Sporns, Breakspear, needs higher-order thought and reflection to
Deco, & McIntosh, 2010). The authors continued guide the pathways to optimization in thought
that, as a whole, the brain is not passive, nor is it and subsequent action. This brings free will into
driven by information but, in contrast, the brain the picture of the Bayesian brain, because con-
actively generates predictions and, in its resting scious reflective thought enables distancing from
state, networks participate in priming it for pre- the context so that a fuller picture of the options,
dictivity. The global attractor landscape is condi- choices that can be made, and aware decision-
tioned by global inter-area coupling strength that making, and so on, can be formulated. Because
emerges in form as multi-stable, dispersed fixed- the brain is Bayesian, so is behavior and so can
point areal attractors under optimal intermediate free will in behavior exist. Difficulty in engaging
global coupling. Real brain dynamics adopt this in efficient probability processes in brain and
pattern; otherwise, there is mostly either inhibi- thinking processes complicate the ability to
tory neuronal firing or excitatory (epileptic) engage in free will. Said another way, an unadap-
neuronal firing. Moreover, the brain does not tive amount of free energy complicates the stabil-
have a central pattern generator orchestrating ity needed for free will to manifest and be used
this real-world dynamics, but it is inherently self- effectively. The more free energy present, then,
organizing and settles into attractor landscape the less there is free will.
regions near phase transition bifurcations so that In the following, I examine to what extent
it can function toward an itinerant or wandering cells are governed by network models, in particu-
(chaotic) dynamic that facilitates adaptivity. This lar, the so-called “concept” cells and astrocytes.
type of model has been applied to whole brain In both of these cases, network and systems
and to neocortical connectivity (Sporns, 2011; model concepts apply, and we learn that we can
Buice & Cowan, 2009; respectively). no longer consider cells as straight-through ave-
nues of signal detection and conduction. The cell
assemblies and interlockings that they form
Comment are plastic and environmental-responsive. This
makes them psychological at their core.
The work by Friston on free energy in the brain is
consistent with the thermodynamic approach of
systems theory to system organization and its Cells
drivers. The emphasis on the brain as a predictive
organ trying to reduce surprise or unpredictabil- Concept Cells
ity is a Bayesian concept that indicates the brain
is a probability-regulating machine trying to “Concept cells” in the medial temporal lobe
adapt to the landscape of probabilities possible in (MTL) appear crucial to declarative memory
the environment and also that are involved in the functions (Quiroga, 2012). One avenue of
present context and in future courses of action. research demonstrating the firing of these cells
The brain is rendered the ideal adaptive learner in involves patients who are suffering from intrac-
having these properties, because it builds on pri- table epilepsy. The hippocampus portion of the
ors, or its past states that have led it to its present MTL appears especially open to encoding the
organization. “meaning” of a stimulus. Meaning is subjective
When Bayesian concepts are applied to the and the cells fire explicitly to the conscious
thinking process, they allow for intuitive knowl- perception of the stimulus. The cells are “remark-
edge and guessing, given that full knowledge of ably” selective in firing, and had once been
168 7 Brain: The Neuronal Network Revolution

Fig. 7.5 Hierarchical


processing in the human Hippocampus
medial temporal lobe.
The medial temporal
lobe consists of the
hippocampus, entorhinal Amygdala
cortex, parahippocampal
cortex, perirhinal cortex,
and amygdala. “Concept
cells”—that is, neurons Entorhinal
that encode the meaning cortex
of the stimulus—mostly
are located in these areas:
TE temporal area, TE/
TEO temporal occipital
area, TF temporal area,
TH temporal area.
Adopted from Quiroga
(2012), original from
Quiroga, Kraskov, Koch,
and Fried (2009).
Adapted with permission Parahippocampal Perirhinal
of Elsevier. Reprinted cortex cortex
from Current Biology, TF TH
Vol. 19, Quiroga, R. Q.,
Kraskov, A., Koch, C., &
Fried, I., Explicit
encoding of multimodal
percepts by single
neurons in the human
brain, Pages 1308–1313,
Copyright 2009; with
kind permission from V4 TE/ TEO Auditory cortex
Elsevier. [Figure 4, Visual cortex
Page 1312]

labeled “Jennifer Aniston” neurons. Other “Brangelina?”). The details encoded in the cells
famous celebrities have been shown to be are “sparse,” so that the learning and specifi-
involved in single neurons (e.g., Brad Pitt). Both cation happens rapidly, and could happen even
pictures and written names can elicit their firing, after single exposures. The cells are organized
and even just thinking of the person can elicit non-topographically. They appear to constitute
their firing. “attractors,” or networks of neural representa-
Quiroga (2012) proposed that concept cell tions. I note that this concept of concept
firing is embedded within related facts and cir- cells opens them to investigation in terms of far-
cumstances, facilitating semantic representation, from-equilibrium state transitions (e.g., can
associations, and flow of consciousness, aside “Brangelina” cells bifurcate if the couple splits?).
from memory. The processing permitting this Suthana and Fried (2012) presented an account
undertaking takes place hierarchically in the of concept cells similar to that of Quiroga (2012).
MTL (see Fig. 7.5). They noted that the cells might respond to land-
In this model, cells could form abstract speci- marks (such as the Sydney Opera House) as well
ficities, could become interlinked in “cell assem- as people. The representations are not coded
blies,” could fire sequentially, etc. (see Fig. 7.5). in a single cell alone. They help transform
Quiroga (2012) gave the example of Star Wars novel stimuli to representations available for
and a Luke Skywalker cell assembly (What about later conscious retrieval as episodic memories.
Cells 169

The authors noted that stimulation of specific precise communications with synapses. For
neural networks might be the way to “unlock” example, they organize functionally similar to
memories, moving from correlation to causation. cortical neurons. In this regard, in the ferret,
For example, Liu et al. (2012) used optogenetic visual cortical astrocytes respond to visual stim-
stimulation of specific hippocampal neurons to uli, expressing distinct spatial receptive fields
reactivate fear memory recall. and sharp tuning to features of visual stimuli
Smith, Smith, Branco, and Häusser (2013) (e.g., orientation, spatial frequency; Schummers,
found that cortical pyramidal neurons also engage Yu, & Sur, 2008). The findings of astrocyte par-
in in vivo computational activities. In a mouse ticipation in synaptic function have profound
study, they found that dendritic spikes that implications for brain and behavior.
are triggered by visually evoked sensory input
serve to enhance stimulus orientation selectivity
in the visual cortex. Comment

I find it interesting that researchers in neuronal,


Astrocytes synaptic, and astrocyte coordination are refer-
ring to aspects such as causality. Moreover, if a
De Pittà et al. (2012) described the conceptual particular neuronal cell can register an item in
revolution taking place in understanding brain memory that can be recalled easily enough, such
communication. It appears that information is as a famous person, the implication is that there
transmitted and processed not only in neuronal are many cells that are concept ones and that reg-
circuitry but also in an expanded network of neu- ister significant others in our lives, significant
ronal–glial cell interactions. In particular, glial objects/landmarks, and so on. Research should
cell astrocytes engage in synaptic interactions by continue to specify the role of these cellular
means of calcium signaling and setting the basal structures not only in memory but even socially,
physiological tone of synaptic transmission. The e.g., in the mirror system. It could be that the
synapse needs to be considered as a tripartite linkages from stimuli, to registration, to action
entity that includes astrocytes modulating synap- proceed as much through these cells as the more
tic release and contributing to its plasticity. frequent more generic ones and that they are
Astrocytes possess the properties of not only reciprocally altered by them, once they become
sensing neighboring neuronal activity but also committed. Also notable is the mention of acti-
releasing neuroactive agents, which are called vation and inhibition in astrocyte complexes,
gliotransmitters. They form a complex signaling which is consistent with my activation/inhibition
network that even regulates synapses. They influ- coordination model of brain and behavior. No
ence presynaptic and postsynaptic terminals doubt, the molecular interactions in calcium
and are influenced themselves by synaptic cleft channel workings and other related functions in
activity. In addition, they are modulated further neuronal and glial cell functioning, as well as
downstream by other input/output pathways. The synaptic cleft and related activity involving
synapses and astrocytes are intrinsically coupled neurotransmitters found in intercellular neuro-
and mutually influence each other. They maintain nal activity should evidence this type of
both feedforward and feedback relationships. coordination.
Astrocyte signaling derivatives can facilitate In the following, I switch from considering
either increase or decrease in neurotransmitter networks and related concepts in the micro-
release. Their activity can promote or inhibit, firings of neuronal cells to the networks in the
thereby activating or inactivating synaptic macro-activity in behavior. Network concepts
activity. Aside from modulating synapses toni- would appear to be translatable across different
cally and diffusely, evidence is accumulating that levels of human activity and, indeed, the broader
they engage in more focused, constrained, and biosphere.
170 7 Brain: The Neuronal Network Revolution

b Networked Causal System Model

Other
behavior

a Latent Variable Model

Panic Concern Worry Other Concern Worry


attack behavior

Panic
Panic disorder attack

Fig. 7.6 Latent variable and networked causal models. Panel “a” depicts the relation between panic disorder and its
symptoms. Panel “b” depicts these symptoms as a networked causal system. Adapted from Borsboom (2008)

Psychological Networks that causes depression’s observable symptoms.


As for Fig. 7.7 that presents the models involved,
Borsboom and colleagues have developed net- the authors represent the component or construct
work models of relationships between observable of the reflective model by placing the attribute in
variables that challenge more traditional models the center of a circle, with outward-directed
and that address the question of causality. arrows varying in relation to the strength of the
Schmittmann et al. (2013) presented a network items (scores, observables) involved.
model on the relationship between psychological The second prevailing viewpoint on the rela-
attributes (e.g., neuroticism) and observed vari- tionship between psychological attributes and
ables (e.g., jittery, worried). In their model, attri- observables is termed the formative model (see
butes are considered network systems of Fig. 7.8). In this approach, observed scores are
causally-coupled or directly related observable understood as contributors to the attribute, defin-
variables (see Fig. 7.6). ing or determining it as a composite score. Latent
The model of these authors is distinct from the composite variables are modeled as an attribute
two prevalent ones in the field. In the first com- existing as a function of the indicators, or items,
mon model in the field, the reflective model, an involved. For example, socioeconomic status
attribute is conceptualized as a common cause of (SES) is viewed as a composite of other vari-
obtained scores. For example, neuroticism might ables. Therefore, in terms of diagramming the
emerge as the best label in a factor analysis for a formative model, for the example of neuroticism,
particular factor. Of the items loading on the fac- it can be mapped in relation to items as a central
tor, the construct of neuroticism is viewed as the component with inward arrows pointing to it
attribute that serves as the common cause of from the surrounding items involved (with differ-
observed scores and their variation. In another ent arrow strengths indicative of item contribu-
example, the construct of depression is a construct tion to the composite score).
Psychological Networks 171

1
Schmittmann et al. (2013) concluded that
both the reflective and formative models are
“extremely problematic” for addressing causal
6
2 relations. They noted three difficulties in these
prior models leading to this latter conclusion.
First, the models lack a temporal dimension,
thereby compromising the understanding of cau-
sality. Typical causality models involve causes
that temporally precede effects. Second, the
N models do not lend themselves to breaking down
causal relations into precise mechanisms under-
lying them. For example, although smoking gen-
erally causes lung cancer, specific physiological
pathways constitute precise mechanisms and, in
5 3 contemporary research in cancer, these are being
elucidated. In contrast to fuller causal modeling,
the reflective and formative models of causal
4
relationships rarely advance to this process level
of causality. For example, we do not really
Fig. 7.7 Reflective model of neuroticism items. In the know in these models how neuroticism causes
reflective model, one underlying factor determines the
variation in the items. The thicker the arrow is from the worry. Third, the reflective and formative models
factor to an item, the higher is the factor loading. Residual entirely exclude seeking causal relations between
variances are not represented. Adapted from Schmittmann (among) the observed indicators involved.
et al. (2013), slightly modified These three criticisms of prior models led
Schmittmann et al. (2013) to develop their net-
work perspective. In this model, observables are
1 considered autonomous causal entities in dynam-
ical relations. The observables are autonomous in
6 the sense of being active causal connectors, and
2
their underlying linkage processes can be studied
or are known. The observables have functions in
the network (e.g., some are more dominant in
strength of relations with other variables). This
dynamical network model of the relationship
N between psychological attributes and observ-
ables does not place any attribute as privileged as
the center of a nexus. Rather, the mapping of the
network uses algorithms that place more domi-
nant observables as nodes toward the center and
also place the relationship between nodes as
5 3 edges indicating the empirical statistics involved
(e.g., correlations). Strongly correlated sets of
4 items are clustered together (see Fig. 7.9).
According to Schmittmann et al. (2013), the
Fig. 7.8 Formative model of neuroticism items. In the changing nature of interconnected network vari-
formative model, arrows point from the items to the com- ables can be formalized by dynamical system
posite variable (circle). The thicker is the arrow, the higher
theory equations (Van der Maas & Molenaar,
is the contribution of the item to the composite score.
Correlations between items are not represented. Adapted 1992). The system’s state is represented by
from Schmittmann et al. (2013), slightly modified the set of interrelations among the variables.
172 7 Brain: The Neuronal Network Revolution

As proposed, the network model helps explain


1 emergent phenomena because they are governed
by nonlinear dynamical system properties. More-
over, causality does not reside in the overall state
of the network but might depend on only a few of
its elements, in particular.
2

Comment
3
Although a powerful model, the network
approach to psychological attributes might have
engaged in oversimplification of behavioral item
(and symptom) networking in explaining causal-
5
ity and their relationship to higher-order attri-
4 butes. For example, the authors integrate systems
theory in their modeling, but do not consider, as
might happen in systems generally, that a higher-
order level (e.g., the attribute level) can develop
in systems from lower-order ones (such as at
6 item/symptom levels) and interact with the
lower-order levels, with the various levels recip-
Fig. 7.9 A network of neuroticism items. Nodes represent rocally shaping each other through their interac-
items: Edges represent the empirical correlations between tions. Moreover, the higher-order levels in any
items. Numbers in nodes refer to items. A stronger corre- system might be emergent in ways that are unpre-
lation is represented by a thicker and darker edge. Adapted
from Schmittmann et al. (2013) based on Epskamp, dictable from knowing the lower-order levels,
Cramer, Waldorp, Schmitmann, and Borsboom (2011), and be quite informative of the full system pic-
slightly modified ture. A more inclusive network model relative to
the ones proposed by the authors would allow for
both reflective-type and formative-processes in
State changes depend on how variables influence the interactions over different levels of the sys-
each other, as represented by equations describ- tem as it forms its networks. That is, the differ-
ing prior and present state dependencies. If the ences in the various models involved in the
system gravitates to an attractor state, its dynami- present context might not be in opposition, but
cal path converges on it (globally, despite proba- might be offering complementary perspectives of
bilistic variations) and might stay in equilibrium a larger system.
in it. State transitions are regulated by parame-
ters. Transition to new attractors indicates quali-
tative change in the system. For example, there Chapter Conclusions
might be different system attractors indexing
depression and mental equilibrium, and the two The concept of networks is revolutionizing the
might alternate in the system’s (person’s) state understanding of brain and behavior because net-
space. In the network model of psychological work approaches are integrating hierarchical
phenomena proposed by Schmittmann et al. multi-level analysis of brain and behavior
(2013), networks are considered systems that can with subtle within-level dynamical analysis.
come to interrelate themselves. For example, They reveal the dynamical nature of millisecond-
psychiatric comorbidity reflects such network by-millisecond brain activity and micro-relations
intercoordination. in ongoing behavior within and across people,
References 173

while enabling macro-level functioning. They Cole, M. W., Reynolds, J. R., Power, J. D., Repovs, G.,
translate into reframing psychological constructs, Anticevic, A., & Braver, T. S. (2013). Multi-task con-
nectivity reveals flexible hubs for adaptive task con-
such as depression and neuroticism, not just as trol. Nature Neuroscience, 16, 1348–1355.
symptom clusters relating to broader terms but Deco, G., & Jirsa, V. K. (2012). Ongoing cortical activity
also especially as symptom systems that change at rest: Criticality, multistability, and ghost attractors.
dynamically, jump to different states, hover on Journal of Neuroscience, 32, 3366–3375.
Deco, G., Jirsa, V., & Friston, K. J. (2012). The dynamical
the edge of order–disorder bifurcations, and so and structural basis of brain activity. In M. I.
on. They collapse cause and effect into trackable Rabinovich, K. J. Friston, & P. Varona (Eds.), Prin-
systems instead of intractable concepts. That ciples of brain dynamics: Global state interactions
being said, I offer ways to integrate the models (pp. 9–25). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
De Pittà, M., Volman, V., Berry, H., Parpura, V., Volterra,
that neuronal network ones are dismissing into A., & Ben-Jacob, E. (2012). Computational quest for
more integrated perspectives. understanding the role of astrocyte signaling in syn-
aptic transmission and plasticity. Frontiers in
Computational Neuroscience, 6, 98. doi:10.3389/
fncom.2012.00098.
References Epskamp, S., Cramer, A. O. J., Waldorp, L. J.,
Schmitmann, V. D., & Borsboom, D. (2011). Qgraph:
Adelstein, J. S., Shehzad, Z., Mennes, M., DeYoung, Network representations of relationships in data. R
C. G., Zuo, Z.-N., Kelly, C., et al. (2011). Personality package version 0.4.10. Available from http://
is reflected in the brain’s intrinsic functional architec- CRAN.R-project.org/package=qgraph
ture. PLoS One, 6(11), e27633. doi:10.1371/journal. Fair, D. A., Cohen, A. L., Power, J. D., Dosenbach, N. U.
pone.0027633. F., Church, J. A., Miezin, F. M., et al. (2009). Functional
Bak, P., Tang, C., & Wiesenfeld, K. (1987). Self-organized brain networks develop from a “local to distributed”
criticality: An explanation of the 1/f noise. Physical organization. PLoS Computational Biology, 5,
Review Letters, 59, 381–384. e1000381. doi:10.1371/journal.pcbi.1000381.
Barbey, A. K., Colom, R., & Grafman, J. (2014). Distri- Friston, K. (2010). The free-energy principle: A unified
buted neural system for emotional intelligence brain theory? Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 11,
revealed by lesion mapping. Social Cognitive and 127–138.
Affective Neuroscience, 9, 265–272. Friston, K. (2012). A free energy principle for biological
Barch, D. M. (2013). Brain network interactions in health systems. Entropy, 14, 2100–2121.
and disease. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 17, Greicius, M. D., & Menon, V. (2004). Default-mode
603–605. activity during a passive sensory task: Uncoupled
Baumeister, R. F. (2008). Free will in scientific psychol- from deactivation but impacting activation. Journal of
ogy. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 3, 14–19. Cognitive Neuroscience, 16, 1484–1492.
Borsboom, D. (2008). Psychometric perspectives on diag- Gross, T., & Blasius, B. (2008). Adaptive coevolutionary
nostic systems. Journal of Clinical Psychology, 64, networks: A review. Journal of the Royal Society
1089–1108. Interface, 5, 259–271.
Brandes, U., Robins, G., McCranie, A., & Wasserman, S. Harmelech, T., & Malach, R. (2013). Neurocognitive
(2013). What is network science? Network Science, 1, biases and the patterns of spontaneous correlations in
1–15. the human cortex. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 17,
Bressler, S. L., & Menon, V. (2010). Large-scale brain 606–615.
networks in cognition: Emerging methods and princi- Hilgetag, C. C., & Hütt, M.-T. (2014). Hierarchical modu-
ples. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 14, 277–290. lar brain connectivity is a stretch for criticality. Trends
Brunel, N., & Wang, X. J. (2001). Effects of neuromodu- in Cognitive Sciences, 18, 114–115.
lation in a cortical network model of object working Ingalhalikar, M., Smith, A., Parker, D., Satterthwaite,
memory dominated by recurrent inhibition. Journal of T. D., Elliott, M. A., Ruparel, K., et al. (2014). Sex dif-
Computational Neuroscience, 11, 63–85. ferences in the structural connectome of the human
Buice, M. A., & Cowan, J. D. (2009). Statistical mechan- brain. Proceedings of the National Academy of
ics of the neocortex. Progress in Biophysics and Sciences, USA, 111, 823–828.
Molecular Biology, 99, 53–86. Jirsa, V. K., & McIntosh, A. R. (2007). Handbook of brain
Byrge, L., Sporns, O., & Smith, L. B. (2014). Develop- connectivity. New York: Springer Science + Business
mental process emerges from extended brain-body- Media.
behavior networks. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 18, Jirsa, V. K., Sporns, O., Breakspear, M., Deco, G., &
395–403. McIntosh, A. R. (2010). Towards the virtual brain:
Churchland, P. S., & Sejnowski, T. J. (1992). The compu- Network modeling of the intact and the damaged
tational brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. brain. Archives Italiennes de Biologie, 148, 189–205.
174 7 Brain: The Neuronal Network Revolution

Kanai, R., & Rees, G. (2011). The structural basis Raichle, M. E., MacLeod, A. M., Snyder, A. Z., Powers,
of inter-individual differences in human behavior W. J., Gusnard, D. A., & Shulman, G. L. (2001). A
and cognition. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 12, default mode of brain function. Proceedings of the
231–242. National Academy of Sciences, USA, 98, 676–682.
Kello, C. T., Beltz, B. C., Holden, J. G., & Van Orden, Reinhart, R. M. G., & Woodman, G. F. (2013). Oscillatory
G. C. (2008). The pervasiveness of 1/f scaling in coupling reveals the dynamic reorganization of large-
speech reflects the metastable basis of cognition. scale neural networks as cognitive demands change.
Cognitive Science, 32, 1217–1231. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 26, 175–188.
Knill, D. C., & Pouget, A. (2004). The Bayesian brain: Rubinov, M., & Bullmore, E. (2013). Fledgling pathocon-
The role of uncertainty in neural coding and computa- nectomics of psychiatric disorder. Trends in Cognitive
tion. Trends in Neuroscience, 27, 712–719. Sciences, 17, 641–647.
Koyama, M. S., Di Martino, A., Zuo, X. N., Kelly, C., Ruths, J., & Ruths, D. (2014). Control profiles of complex
Mennes, M., Jutagir, D. R., et al. (2011). Resting-state networks. Science, 343, 1373–1376.
functional connectivity indexes reading competence Schmittmann, V. D., Cramer, A. O. J., Waldorp, L. J.,
in children and adults. Journal of Neuroscience, 31, Epskamp, S., Kievit, R. A., & Borsboom, D. (2013).
8617–8624. Deconstructing the construct: A network perspective
Liu, X., Ramirez, S., Pang, P. T., Puryear, C. B., on psychological phenomena. New Ideas in
Govindarajan, A., Deisseroth, K., et al. (2012). Psychology, 31, 43–53.
Optogenetic stimulation of a hippocampal engram Schummers, J., Yu, H., & Sur, M. (2008). Tuned responses
activates fear memory recall. Nature, 484, 381–385. of astrocytes and their influence on hemodynamic sig-
Matsumoto, A., & Kakigi, R. (2013). Subliminal semantic nals in the visual cortex. Science, 320, 1638–1843.
priming changes the dynamic causal influence between Shirer, W. R., Ryali, S., Rykhlevskaia, E., Menon, V., &
the left frontal and temporal cortex. Journal of Greicius, M. D. (2012). Decoding subject-driven cog-
Cognitive Neuroscience, 26, 165–174. nitive states with whole-brain connectivity patterns.
Menon, V. (2012). Functional connectivity, neurocogni- Cerebral Cortex, 22, 158–165.
tive networks, and brain dynamics. In M. I. Rabinovich, Singer, W. (2013). Cortical dynamics revisited. Trends in
K. J. Friston, & P. Varona (Eds.), Principles of brain Cognitive Sciences, 17, 616–626.
dynamics: Global state interactions (pp. 27–47). Smith, S. L., Smith, I. T., Branco, T., & Häusser, M.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (2013). Dendritic spikes enhance stimulus selectivity
Menon, V. (2013). Developmental pathways to functional in cortical neurons in vivo. Nature, 503, 115–120.
brain networks: Emerging principles. Trends in Sombataro, F., Wolf, N. D., Pennuto, M., Vasic, N., &
Cognitive Sciences, 17, 627–640. Wolf, R. C. (2014). Revisiting default mode network
Moretti, P., & Muñoz, M. A. (2013). Griffiths phases and function in major depression: Evidence for disrupted
the stretching of criticality in brain networks. Nature subsystem connectivity. Psychological Medicine, 44,
Communications, 4, 1–10. 2041–2051.
Palaniyappan, L., Simmonite, M., White, T. P., Liddle, Sporns, O. (2011). Networks of the brain. Cambridge,
E. B., & Liddle, P. F. (2013). Neural primacy of the MA: MIT Press.
salience processing system in schizophrenia. Neuron, Sporns, O. (2012). Discovering the human connectome.
79, 814–828. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Pearl, J. (2009). Causality: Models, reasoning, and infer- Sporns, O., & van den Heuvel, M. P. (2013). Network
ence (2nd ed.). New York: Cambridge University maps of the human brain’s rich club. Network Science,
Press. 1, 248–250.
Pessoa, L. (2014). Précis of the cognitive-emotional brain. Sridharan, D., Levitin, D. J., & Menon, V. (2008). A criti-
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 10, 1–66. cal role for the right fronto-insular cortex in switching
Priesemann, V., Valderrama, M., Wibral, M., & Van between central-executive and default-mode net-
Quyen, M. L. (2013). Neuronal avalanches differ from works. Proceedings of the National Academy of
wakefulness to deep sleep – Evidence from intra- Sciences, USA, 105, 12569–12574.
cranial depth recordings in humans. PLoS Computa- Suthana, N., & Fried, I. (2012). Percepts to recollections:
tional Biology, 9, e1002985. doi:10.1371/journal. Insights from single neuron recordings in the human
pcbi.1002985. brain. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 16, 427–436.
Quiroga, R. Q. (2012). Concept cells: The building blocks Thelen, E., & Smith, L. B. (1994). A dynamic systems
of declarative memory functions. Nature Reviews approach to the development of cognition and action.
Neuroscience, 13, 587–597. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Quiroga, R. Q., Kraskov, A., Koch, C., & Fried, I. (2009). Uddin, L. Q., & Menon, V. (2009). The anterior insula
Explicit encoding of multimodal percepts by single in autism: Under-connected and under-examined.
neurons in the human brain. Current Biology, 19, Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 33,
1308–1313. 1198–1203.
Raichle, M. E. (2011). The restless brain. Brain Urban, J. B., Osgood, N., Okamoto, J., Mabry, P., &
Connectivity, 1, 3–12. Lich, K. H. (2014). Developmental systems science:
References 175

Extending developmental science with systems catastrophe theory. Psychological Review, 113,
science methodologies. In M. Molenaar, R. M. Lerner, 842–861.
& K. M. Newell (Eds.), Handbook of developmental van Tol, M.-J., Li, M., Metzger, C. D., Hailla, N., Horn,
systems theory and methodology (pp. 95–127). D. I., Li, W., et al. (2014). Local cortical thinning links
New York: Guildford Press. to resting-state disconnectivity in major depressive
van den Heuvel, M. P., Kahn, R. S., Goñi, J., & Sporns, O. disorder. Psychological Medicine, 44, 2053–2065.
(2012). A high-cost, high-capacity backbone for Wang, S.-J., Hilgetag, C. C., & Zhou, C. (2011). Sustained
global brain communication. Proceedings of the activity in hierarchical modular neural networks: Self-
National Academy of Sciences, USA, 109, organized criticality and oscillations. Frontiers in
11372–11377. Computational Neuroscience, 5, 30. doi:10.3389/
van den Heuvel, M. P., & Sporns, O. (2011). Rich-club fncom.2011.00030.
organization of the human connectome. Journal of Zanto, T. P., & Gazzaley, A. (2013). Fronto-parietal net-
Neuroscience, 31, 15775–15786. work: Flexible hub of cognitive control. Trends in
van den Heuvel, M. P., & Sporns, O. (2013). Network Cognitive Sciences, 17, 602–603.
hubs in the human brain. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, Zatorre, R. J., Fields, D. R., & Johansen-Berg, H. (2012).
17, 683–696. Plasticity in gray and white: Neuroimaging changes in
Van der Maas, H. L. J., & Molenaar, P. C. M. (1992). brain structure during learning. Nature Neuroscience,
Stagewise cognitive development: An application of 15, 528–536.
Lateralization and Specialization
of the Brain 8

However, about the fundamental nature of dif-


Chapter Introduction ferential hemispheric function, there has not been
one accepted model of the distinctive, unique and
This chapter focuses on manual lateralization and underlying, integrative nature of each hemi-
the related area of hemispheric specialization, as sphere, with the model capturing the full range of
well as on early handedness and hemispheric behaviors and skills with which each hemisphere
dominance for language. These are areas that had (and cross-lateralized manual behavior) is associ-
considered that the preferred sides involved ated. Various models refer to differences in the
either (a) acquire their shifts gradually in an equi- left and right hemispheres related to: language/
potential and then progressively shifting model fine motor versus spatial function; analysis versus
early in life or (b) that they are acquired rapidly synthesis/holistic function; and so on. Of course,
and innately, with the patterns involved reflecting for proper adaptivity, the hemispheres need to
early on the characteristics of the later emerging work together effectively with their differential
adult model in these regards. functions, skills, and associated behaviors.
Generally, the research is quite supportive of Note that the research in the area does not nec-
latter the rapid, innate model of early manual lat- essarily support the connection between all later-
eralization and hemispheric specialization. In alized manual behavior and all verbal/spatial
particular, it points to early right-hand manual behavior that are putatively associated with the
lateralization and a corresponding underlying hemispheres. In particular, notable exceptions in
early left-hemisphere specialization, respectively these regards involve handedness as an index of
(the relationship of manual lateralization to cor- hemispheric dominance and also language disor-
responding control by the hemispheres is cross- ders as problems deriving from uniquely a left-
hemispheric). That is, the left hemisphere appears hemisphere difficulty. This is especially the case
specialized for its functions (verbal/language; for early phases in the development of these vari-
fine motor) from early in life onward and the ous behaviors and problems. That is, early hand-
right hemisphere for its skills (e.g., spatial) also edness is not as distinct as later handedness and
early in life. Therefore, the selection of appropri- correlates minimally with hemispheric specializa-
ate tasks of manual lateralization, such as grasp- tion, in general. Also, advances in early language
ing and spatial-related ones, respectively, for the skills, or problems in this regard, do not relate
functions of the left and right hemispheres, will unequivocally with left-hemisphere function.
give results corresponding to the manual lateral- The development of manual lateralization and
ization’s associated hemispheric specialization corresponding hemispheric specialization/differ-
function. entiation of hemispheric architecture appears to

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 177


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_8
178 8 Lateralization and Specialization of the Brain

being prenatally (Hepper, 2013), but both are The chapter also considers the evolutionary
more plastic early in life compared to later on. The origins of lateralization and specialization in
chapter reviews the development of manual later- behavior and in the brain. It shows some fascinat-
alization and hemispheric specialization together ing links across lateralization/specialization mod-
at each age period from the fetal and neonatal els and those of differential susceptibility and
periods onward, through the various infancy ages neuronal networks. For example, for the network
to childhood. The chapter reviews the patterns in research on the topic, right from birth, the left
right–left manual lateralization of behavior on hemisphere appears specialized for intraregional
many types of tasks, such as reaching, grasping, integration and segregation in the interconnection
and even tool use. It reviews associated hemi- among its various regions and also for “between-
spheric specialization function and corresponding ness centrality.” Network wise, the left hemisphere
structural differences across the hemispheres. presents as more efficient. This work is consistent
Early hemispheric specialization also reflects with description of the left hemisphere’s func-
early motivational/emotional lateralization dif- tional advantages and, as well, especially in terms
ferences, with the left hemisphere being related of the model that these advantages relate to its bet-
to approach and to positive emotions relative to ter capacity for activation/inhibition coordination.
the right one, which is more associated with
withdrawal/negative emotions. The left-
hemisphere specialization for positive emotions Lateralization and Specialization
is consistent with its apparently more advanced Development by Age Period
functions and its ability to weave together activa-
tion and inhibition, a process that is implicit in Prenatal
positive social and emotional behavior of a con-
tinual interacting type. Manual Behavior Hepper (2013) described his
The left-hemisphere advantage translates not prior research on fetal laterality, before present-
only into advances in language development but ing a further study. Hepper, Shahidullah, and
also in cognitive development to a degree. This White (1991) had found right thumb sucking in
chapter reviews the literature on those varied top- the fetus. This research was followed by their
ics, including data showing that the left hemisphere study on fetal right head turning (Hepper,
is associated with some general cognitive advances. McCartney, & Shannon, 1998). McCartney and
I have proposed a model as critical in differen- Hepper (1999) found that right arm movement
tiating the underlying functions of the left and preference was consistently displayed in the fetal
right hemispheres. It refers to the left hemisphere period (also see Ververs, de Vries, van Geijn, &
expressing a refined specialization for activation– Hopkins, 1994; Kurjak et al., 2002; in contrast,
inhibition coordination, in particular (Young, see de Vries, Wimmers, Ververs, Hopkins,
2011; Young & Gagnon, 1990). Reciprocally, the Savelsbergh, & van Geijn, 2001). Hepper, Wells,
right hemisphere is specialized for less complex and Lynch (2005) showed that right thumb suck-
inhibition skills. [Keep in mind that manual and ing in the fetus predicted right-handedness in 10-
hemispheric left-right side differences are found to 12-year-olds. Hepper (2013) replicated the
in a relative sense and they are plastic to a degree. finding of more right arm reaching in the fetus,
Also, the patterns are present better in the typical but the preference decreased as the fetal period
right-hander compared to in the typical left- progressed (from 24 to 36 weeks; although the
hander]. As a general model of hemispheric func- author indicated using a small sample size).
tion and corresponding manual lateralization Hepper (2013) noted that although structural
differences, when the literature is supportive of it, hemispheric differences are being found fetally,
the chapter points out the role of activation/inhi- their relationship to any manual lateralities is
bition coordination as a mechanism in the devel- unknown (e.g., Habas et al., 2012; Kasprian et al.
opment of brain and of behavior. 2011; Kivilevitch, Achiron, & Zalel, 2010).
Lateralization and Specialization Development by Age Period 179

Reissland, Francis, Aydin, Mason, and Exley specialization does not appear valid today, and
(2014) examined prenatal mouth opening move- even the notion of progressive lateralization is
ments using scan technology. The scans took difficult to establish for behaviors and functions
place between 24- to 36-weeks gestation. The that are age-appropriate, and this obtains in the
mouth movements were upper lip raisers and prenatal period, as well.
mouth stretches. The results showed greater left
lateralization in mouth opening movements.
Although not a manual lateralization study, it Neonates
is worth noting that Van Dongen et al. (2014)
investigated asymmetry in limbic bones at 10- to Manual Behavior Nagy, Pal, and Orvos (2014)
20-weeks of gestation. Already at this age, the demonstrated that neonates could imitate mod-
right side appears larger than the left side for sev- eled gestures involving the index finger, and two-
eral bones of both the upper and lower limbs. The and three-finger movements. In addition, the first
authors related the findings to the influence of study of the series investigated manual laterality.
internal asymmetric organ positioning. The The infants were about 2 days old. There were
developmental process involved might include two conditions—baseline and modeling (finger
asymmetric gene expression acting in concert raise). Gestures were made about every 12 s and
with differential mechanical loading. they lasted about 2 s. As for the results, the left
hand proved more accurate and also quicker.
Brain The hemispheric differences appear to According to the authors, the results suggest a
develop at the structural level even prenatally, lateralized neural network involved in neonatal
with first cortical signs favoring the left hemi- gestural imitation. In this regard, there might be
sphere in the superior temporal sulci (more fre- an early sensitive period, in that older neonates
quent sulcal pits; Im et al., 2010). For white (8+ days) typically do not imitate gesturally.
matter, the arcuate fasciculus and corticospinal Nagy et al. (2014) related these results to the
tract seem involved (Dubois et al., 2009). mirror neuron system, and also elsewhere (e.g.,
Kasprian et al. (2011) demonstrated the prena- the inferior frontal gyrus, the inferoparietal lob-
tal origin of cerebral lateralization in an in vivo, ule). These areas have been implicated in early
in utero neuroimaging investigation. First, they interaction and intersubjectivity.
described the research of Sun et al. (2005) that The authors did not relate left-hand preference
referred to early asymmetry of gene transcription for early neonatal imitation to models of develop-
(as early as 12 weeks gestational age, GW) in the ing lateralization. Nagy et al.’s (2014) findings on
cerebral cortices. In their neuroimaging study, in imitation patterns of finger movements to demon-
a large sample between 18 and 37 gestational strated models should be analyzed for whether
weeks of age, Kasprian et al. (2011) found tem- they are more related to underlying functions
poral lobe asymmetry. The asymmetry favored a involving left- or right-hemisphere skills. In this
larger temporal lobe on the left side. Also, they regard, imitating finger postures and movements
found an earlier appearance of the right superior appears more space-related and holistic rather
temporal sulcus by 23 GW. than verbal and sequential, as described in Young
(2011). The results are consistent with Young and
Comment Overall, the results in the various Gagnon (1990), who found that, in 2-day-olds,
investigations reviewed for the prenatal period the left hemisphere relative to the right appears
indicate that, in some senses, the hemispheres are specialized for speech relative to musical stimu-
structurally programmed in this period already lus processing. That is, already at this age, the
like in the adult. There might be continued right hemisphere appears specialized in its turn
anchoring and embedding of the relative skills of for spatial-related functions, or less complex
the hemispheres as development proceeds but the ones relative to speech ones that are associated
concept of equipotentiality in early hemispheric with the left hemisphere.
180 8 Lateralization and Specialization of the Brain

To conclude, the results on early neonatal imi- Ratnarajah et al. (2014) investigated asymme-
tation of finger movements found by Nagy et al. try in structural brain connectivity in the neonatal
(2014) are consistent with other research on early brain. They used diffusion tensor imaging (DTI)
hemispheric specialization, which has found that deterministic tractography and structural network
the left hemisphere is “prepared” from birth for analysis based on graph theory. They tracked
specializations related to speech and fine motor white-matter axonal pathways characterizing
coordinations, such as reaching and hand- interregional connections in 32 defined cortical
opening, and the right hemisphere is specialized and subcortical regions.
for spatial skills and exploration. In the follow- Both cerebral hemispheres revealed a connec-
ing, I examine whether this trend is evident both tivity marked by “small world” properties, which
in research directly on the brain in this age period means that regions are tightly connected (and
and also in later ages. with shorter paths; any one region is only a few
paths away from any other region within a hemi-
Brain Streri and de Hevia (2015) reviewed sphere). As for efficiency in structural connectiv-
research on newborns tested for cross-modal ity, the left hemisphere already proved more
transfer of shape from touch to vision using the efficient than the right at birth. That is, the neona-
habituation paradigm (Streri & Gentaz, 2004). tal left hemisphere evidences better intraregional
They were habituated to an object haptically and integration and segregation in their interconnec-
then were presented visually with it or a novel tion. Moreover, this takes place in regions known
shape. The participants showed visual recogni- to develop later on functional specializations in
tion if they were habituated to the familiar object motor, language, and memory functions. Further,
with the right hand, but not the left one. Generally, the left-hemisphere advantage in efficiency man-
2-month-olds retain better object shape informa- ifested at both local and global levels. This sug-
tion with their left hand. Also, young infants gests that shorter circuit paths in the left
detect object contour changes better with the left hemisphere facilitate speedier information trans-
hand, but object detail ones better with the left fer and flow. Other findings implicated leftward
hand (Streri, 2002). Overall, the results are con- asymmetries in the connectivity measure of
sistent with the differential analytic vs. global “betweenness centrality.” Overall, the results
distinction of left- and right-hemisphere func- support an early specialization of the hemi-
tion, respectively, even for the period after birth. spheres consistent with the adult model.
In a longitudinal study, Li et al. (2014) mapped Cheng, Lee, Chen, Wang, and Decety (2012)
structural hemispheric asymmetries at birth, 1 showed that neonates within the first few days of
year of age, and 2 years of age. They used life already appear to have a neural mechanism
surface-based morphometry of MRIs (magnetic responsible for emotional vocalization discrimi-
resonance imaging). They found that the left pla- nation. In particular, the neonates demonstrated a
num temporale was larger and deeper than the mismatch in electroencephalographic response
right at all three time points. Also, the right supe- over the right hemisphere when exposed to
rior temporal sulcus (STS) and the right parieto- emotionally-laden stimuli (happy or fearful com-
occipito sulcus were larger and deeper than the pared to neutral syllables).
corresponding left-side regions. Using DTI, Dubois et al. (2009) demonstrated
These longitudinal, postnatal results are con- leftward asymmetries in microstructure, in par-
sistent with other findings, such as by Habas ticular, in the arcuate fasciculus and in the
et al. (2012) and Kasprian et al. (2011), who cortico-spinal tract. The participants were 1–4
studied asymmetries in in utero fetal MRIs, and months of age, with results already evident at 1
by Hill et al. (2010) and Glasel et al. (2011), who month. The two tracts are in white-matter net-
obtained similar results postnatally, with the lat- works, and the former is associated with lan-
ter three studies all showing findings related to a guage development whereas the latter is a
right-side advantage in asymmetry for the STS. sensorimotor one.
Lateralization and Specialization Development by Age Period 181

Comment Studies of neonatal manual lateral- (2015) and Campbell, Marcinowski, Latta, and
ization and hemispheric specialization have dem- Michel (2015) examined manual preferences in
onstrated the left- and right-side advantages that samples studied monthly to 14 months of age,
are associated with adults, and they have shown beginning from 6 and 8 months of age, respec-
that the left hemisphere already possesses net- tively. The tasks in the latter study required
work properties that are consistent with its advan- acquiring objects and, although the study was not
tages. Moreover, the differential structural aimed at establishing which hand is preferred, a
properties of the hemispheres at birth already are cascading model from acquisition behavior to
of the type that is consistent with the adult model. unimanual manipulation fits the data. The tasks
The early presence of hemispheric specialization in the former study required manipulative behav-
and its associated manual lateralizations speak to ior mostly, and it showed a right-hand preference
the evolutionary significance of the structural dif- mostly, although not to the degree of the adult.
ferences across the hemispheres and the func- Rönnqvist and Domellöf (2006) studied 6- to
tional and behavioral differences that are 36-month-olds. They related infants’ early right-
associated with these cerebral differences. handed reaching preference to their capacity to
reach straighter with the right arm.
That handedness is not co-lateralized with
First Year other lateralizations is indicated by the results of
the study by Babik, Campbell, and Michel (2013).
Manual Behavior Morange-Majoux, Lemoine, They investigated the influence of postural con-
and Dellatolas (2013) found that, in the 20- to straints on the longitudinal development of reach-
30-week age period, in a task in which an object ing from 6 to 14 months of age, as well asymmetric
was placed to the left or right, the average latency bimanual coordination for object acquisition. The
time to approach was shorter for the left hand and results showed a weak right-side advantage for
the average latency time to grasping it was shorter lateralized infants, and the laterality developed
with the right hand. The results are consistent further in the first year, only to decrease later on.
with a hemispheric specialization view of manual Jacquet, Esseily, Rider, and Fagard (2012) fol-
lateralization in which the left hemisphere is spe- lowed 8- to 20-month-olds in grasping and
cialized for fine motor activity and the right spa- declarative pointing, and found them “loosely”
tial activity, as argued in Young (2011). correlated. The left-hemisphere superiority for
Morange-Majoux and Devouche (2014) language dominance appears relatively indepen-
examined spontaneous manual preference in dent of lateralization related to grasping (and
6-month-olds to mid-line positioned figurines on pointing should be related to that).
a table placed within reaching distance. A minor-
ity of the infants exhibited a manual preference, Brain Aslin, Shukla, and Emberson (2015)
but when they did the ratio of right to left-hand reported a right-hemisphere advantage for face
preference was about 2:1. processing in 4- to 8-month-old infants over five
Michel, Babik, Shue, and Campbell (2013) studies (Grossmann et al., 2008; Grossmann,
followed infants from 6 to 14 months of age in Parise, & Friederici, 2010; Lloyd-Fox et al.,
object acquisition behavior (lift, move toy). 2009; Nakato, Otsuka, Kanazawa, Yamaguchi, &
Right-hand preference was evident in most Kakigi, 2011; Otsuka et al., 2007). However, the
infants (38 % clearly, 48 % trend, left 14 %). The left hemisphere appeared involved, as well. For
groups differed in developmental trajectory. The example, this was evident in a mutual gaze face
authors found a right-shift from a continuous dis- paradigm [for the left fronto-polar cortex and the
tribution, which is consistent with Annett’s left prefrontal channel in 4- and 5-month-olds,
(2002) genetic model. Follow-up studies from respectively (Grossmann et al. 2008, 2010,
this research group confirm these findings, respectively)] and for videos of faces [the left
Campbell, Marcinowski, Babik, and Michel posterior temporal area (Lloyd-Fox et al., 2009)].
182 8 Lateralization and Specialization of the Brain

Maternal synchrony (coordination of maternal Sacrey, Arnold, Whishaw, and Gonzales


social behavior with infant signal) was associated (2013) studied reach-to-eat compared to reach-
with greater left nucleus accumbens activation. to-grasp movement in 1- to 5-year-olds. The lat-
Further, maternal intrusiveness was related to ter behavior was right lateralized at 1 year of age,
right amygdala activation (Atzil, Hendler, & but the former only at 4 years of age.
Feldman, 2011). Vauclair and Cochet (2013) studied pointing
Missana and Grossmann (2014) measured gesture in the age range of 12–30 months of age.
frontal electroencephalographic (EEG) alpha The infants were tested with pictures and toys.
asymmetry in response to dynamic “happy” body They demonstrated a right-hand pointing prefer-
expressions and also “fearful” ones in 4- and ence as early as 12 months of age. Moreover, for
8-month-old infants (stimuli either upright or infants with a developmental quotient (DQ) for
inverted). The 8-month-olds exhibited the language above 100, the more they were right-
expected left frontal activation to the upright handed for pointing, the more their DQ increased.
happy stimuli and right frontal activation to the
fearful ones (but not the 4-month-olds). Brain Gander and Buchheim (2015) reviewed
The next two studies described relate to brain research on attachment classification in relation
function, but were based on behavioral results to frontal lobe EEG asymmetry. For example,
(non-manual). Smith, Gibilisco, Meisinger, and securely attached infants showed greater right
Hankey (2013) found that 5- to 8-month-old frontal activity when their nondepressed mothers
infants focused on a talker’s right eye as she pro- walked to the door, in contrast to those of
duced infant-directed speech stimuli. The results depressed mothers, who showed greater left-
are consistent with the approach-withdrawal hemisphere activation (e.g., Dawson et al., 2001).
(motivation) and positive–negative (valence)
emotion models of left-hemisphere cerebral lat- Comment The range of methods and behaviors
eralization (which includes that the right hemi- studied in relation to manual laterality and hemi-
sphere is specialized for withdrawal/negative spheric specialization increases in the first year
emotions; Davidson, Ekman, Saron, & Senulius, of life. The studies involve behaviors such as
1990; Davidson & Fox, 1982). The results could hand to mouth behavior and accuracy in reach-
reflect an early specialization for left-hemisphere ing, and various indices of emotional and social
language processing, as well (at least for infant- differences associated with the hemispheres.
directed speech, Zangl & Mills, 2007). Nevertheless, the same pattern of results is found
Holowka and Petitto (2002) found that 5- and as with earlier and later ages, and they indicate
12-month-old infants expressed right-mouth side that the adult model of hemispheric specializa-
asymmetries while babbling, but left-side ones tion and its functional and behavioral conse-
when smiling. The results are consistent with a quences are present from early in life onward.
left-hemisphere cerebral specialization for lan-
guage and a right one for expressiveness and
related processes. Year Two

Manual Behavior Esseily, Jacquet, and Fagard


One Year (2011) found a right-side grasping and pointing
preference in 14-month-olds, with the right-side
Manual Behavior Corbetta, Friedman, and Bell pointing laterality related to word production.
(2014) found that 12-month-olds reached for Cochet and Vauclair (2010) showed that toddlers
small toys with the right hand to grasp them, but (15 months and older) used the right hand more
only if they were experienced walkers compared in “informative pointing” gestures. They found
to novice or non-walkers. They related their results similar results with 11- to 38-month-olds in natu-
to arm coupling practiced during early walking. ral observations (Cochet & Vauclair, 2010).
Lateralization and Specialization Development by Age Period 183

Cochet (2012) also argued that different left- The research on early prosociality supports
hemisphere cerebral networks control object- the view that consists of relatively independent
directed action and pointing gestures. She studied and heterogeneous behaviors that are often
15-month-olds longitudinally to 25 months, and placed under one umbrella. For example, Paulus,
found a right-sided preference for the two behav- Kühn-Popp, Licata, Sodian, and Meinhardt
iors but little relationship between them. (2013) found that empathic responding/comfort-
Rat-Fischer, O’Regan, and Fagard (2013) ing in the second year of life was associated with
examined toddler manual preference tool use. left frontal hemispheric activation, which stands
The children had to use a rake to get a toy that in contrast to a right-centered temporal lobe
was out of reach. Even the 16-month-olds pre- asymmetry for instrumental helping. Note that
ferred to grasp the rake with the right hand. Dunfield (2014) also argued for different and
Wilbourn, Gottfried, and Kee (2011) found an separate modalities in early prosocial-related
interesting relationship between consistency in behavior (helping, sharing, comforting).
18- to 42-month manual drawing preference in
girls (almost all ended up right-handed), but not Comment The range of behaviors studies for
boys, and the participants’ 10- to 17-year-old ver- manual lateralization in the second year has
bal intelligence and reading achievement. The expanded to include raking and wrist movements.
authors related their results to early left-hemisphere The results in these studies are indicating the
specialization maturation in the consistent girls, as long-term relations between early lateralization/
well as early exposure to reading (frequency, specialization and much later language/cognitive
intensity). Björk, Brus, Osika, and Montgomery development. This speaks to the stability of the
(2012) found a relationship between results on a former and also to their importance for
test of left-side hand control and lower scholastic development.
test scores, and they related their results to possi-
ble “suboptimal” hemispheric specialization.
Using motion-capture technology, Kahrs, Children
Jung, and Lockman (2014) filmed right-handed
toddlers hammering a peg into a pegboard. The Manual Behavior Michel, Babik, Nelson,
toddlers were 19–25 months of age. Only the Campbell, and Marcinowski (2013) supported an
older ones used more distally (wrist) controlled embodied view of the development of handed-
movements, but the findings were limited to the ness in relation to language development and its
right hand. Wrist specialization might be uniquely left-hemisphere specialization. Manual skills
human and, moreover, as a lateralized phenome- develop as sensorimotor acquisitions through
non, it follows in development for that of reach- pre-reach, reach, grasping, manipulating, and
ing and bimanual coordination. object use, leading eventually to imitation and to
differentiate bimanual manipulation. Arbib
Brain Fagard, Sirri, and Rämä (2014) investi- (2006) had also postulated a sensorimotor basis
gated N400 event-related potential in a semantic for the development of language—from actions
primary task in infants who were 18- to 24-months to speech gestures to (proto) speech. According to
old. Only infants who were 24 months of age had Michel et al. (2013), sensorimotor manual skills
a more pronounced N400 effect over the right might help promote speech processing by influ-
parietal-occipital recording sites. However, this encing the development of “tool-using and object
was found only if they were right-handers in management” skills. The mediation of the two
grasping and had a significantly higher vocabu- trajectories might take place through elaboration
lary size. Aside from the laterality findings, and development of “proprioceptive maps.”
according to the authors, the results do not sup- Nelson, Campbell, and Michel (2013) found
port a general causal relationship between hand- that, in bimanual manipulation, the majority of
edness and language lateralization. children were right-handed. In their longitudinal
184 8 Lateralization and Specialization of the Brain

study, those who were bilateral earlier ended up Berl et al. (2014) examined the relationship
right-sided. between core language skills in 4- to 12-year-
Gonzalez, Li, Mills, Rosen, and Gibb (2014) olds and lateralization in the distributed language
related manual preference in “grasp-to-mouth” network. The core language skills were corre-
feeding movements of small food items to articu- lated with greater right lateralization in the
latory differentiation of the “sh” and “s” sounds. cerebellum.
The children were 4–5 years of age. The more Yu et al. (2014) used MEG to investigate sex
that they were right lateralized in their grasping, differences in language lateralization in children
the more enhanced was their articulatory dis- (4–18 years of age). Boys manifested the
crimination for these two sounds. The compari- expected left-hemisphere lateralization (in the
son condition of “grasp to construct” did not frontal and temporal regions) according to low-
show this relationship. gamma event-related desynchrony during an
Gonzalez et al. (2014) found a relationship in overt visual verb generation task. However, girls
5- to 6-year-olds and 9- to 10-year-olds between evidenced a more bilateral pattern, especially in
greater right-hand grasping and higher scores on the frontal regions. These differential lateraliza-
executive function (EF), as per indicators on the tion and sex of child results were especially
BRIEF (Behavioral Rating Inventory of Executive found in the younger age period.
Function; Gioia, Isquith, Guy, & Kenworthy, Kurth, Mayer, Toga, Thompson, and Luders
2000). The authors related the results to a greater (2013) found that, in 170 healthy children and
structural efficiency in the left hemisphere, which adolescents, better pegboard task performance
supports enhanced EF. As mentioned, Ratnarajah with the right (dominant) hand was associated
et al. (2014) had found this advantage in greater with greater callosal thickness (isthmus and pos-
structural efficiency for the left hemisphere terior mid-body). Given the role of the corpus
already present in the neonate brain. callosum in interhemispheric communication,
the results suggested to the authors that there is
Brain Kikuchi et al. (2011) found that, in pre- more influence of the left hemisphere compared
schoolers, left-hemisphere dominance in parieto- to the right in interhemispheric inhibition.
temporal coherence of theta band activity was Sheridan, Kharitonova, Martin, Chatterjee,
associated with better performance on language- and Gabrieli (2014) studied cognitive conflict
related tasks (but not nonverbal cognitive ones). detection and resolution in 5- to 10-year-olds,
For language/cognitive testing, the Kaufman was using fMRI, during a blocked spatial response
used (Kaufman Assessment Battery for Children, incompatibility task. Among other results, the
Kaufman & Kaufman, 1983). The authors right prefrontal cortex activated more during
concluded that left-lateralized connectivity via incompatible experimental conditions relative to
theta band (6–8 Hz) oscillation resulted in better compatible ones.
semantic processing performance due to a phase- Yaakoby-Rotem and Geva (2014) studied 5-
locked connectivity (long distance; temporal and to 6-year-olds in their alerting efficiency to tar-
parietal regions). The frontotemporal coherence gets displayed in the left (L) and right (R) visual
did not provide similar results, but the authors fields (VF). They found a right-hemisphere
stated that their frontal placement of the sensors advantage in alerting-attention, in that there was
in this magnetoencephalographic (MEG) study a higher alerting efficiency for stimulus targets
might be one reason. displayed in the LVF.
Cheyne, Jobst, Tesan, Crain, and Johnson MacDonald, Ganjavi, Collins, Evans, and
(2014) studied self-initiated right or left index fin- Karama (2014) studied 6- to 18-year-olds (mean
ger movements generated in a video game-type 11) on a measure of IQ (intelligence quotient;
task in right-handed 3- to 4-year-olds. According Wechsler Abbreviated Scale of Intelligence,
to pediatric MEG, all the children showed activa- Wechsler, 1999) in relation to striatal volume
tion of the right superior temporal gyrus. (caudate nucleus and putamen), as determined by
Other Developmental Topics 185

MRI. They found a positive correlation between Functionally, the shift to the left hemisphere
IQ and left striatal volume. The findings have takes place progressively (Friederici, Brauer, &
import for the lateralization of general higher- Lohmann, 2011). There are individual differ-
order cognitive function and ability. ences associated with degree of leftward asym-
Hemisphere lateralization has functional con- metry/activation (e.g., for verbal IQ, Everts et al.,
sequences, especially for language and motor 2009; and for syntactic verbal performance/
functions. Barber et al. (2012) found that 8- to skills, respectively, Lebel & Beaulieu, 2009;
12-year-old right-handed children, who had dem- Nuñez et al., 2011).
onstrated in a scanner left-hemisphere lateraliza- According to Hervé et al. (2013), Turken and
tion of intrinsic, resting state functional motor Dronkers (2011) described a left-hemisphere
circuit connectivity, performed better motorically brain network critical in sentence comprehen-
on a battery (PANESS, Denckla, 1985). sion. It includes temporo-parietal and IFG (infe-
rior frontal gyrus) regions connected by the
Comment As with the prior ages reviewed for inferior occipitofrontal arcuate, and middle/infe-
research findings on manual behavior and hemi- rior longitudinal fasiculi. Also, Morillon et al.
spheric function that are sided one way or the (2010) found leftward asymmetries in a core net-
other, the present section on children reveals an work of intrinsic connectivities combining audi-
increasing range of behavior studies, more tory, somatosensory motor, and inferior parietal
refined central findings, and more associations cortices. In contrast, an attentional network has
between the cerebral hemispheric specialization been found for the right hemisphere.
and language and cognitive consequences. Barbey et al. (2012) found that patients having
Results related to sex differences are emerging, focal brain damage, as assessed by voxel-based
too. However, it must be kept in mind that the lesion-symptom mapping, had impaired perfor-
differences between the left and right sides of the mance on a measure of g (general intelligence;
body and brain in terms of structure, function, using the WAIS; Wechsler Adult Intelligence
and behavior are relative, and the same applies Test; Wechsler, 1997) and of executive function
for any interactions in these regards with respect (using the Delis–Kaplan Executive Function
to gender differences. System; Delis, Kaplan, & Kramer, 2001).
Specifically, they implicated damage to a distrib-
uted network of left-lateralized brain areas (white
Other Developmental Topics matter, including the superior longitudinal/arcu-
ate fasciculus, which connects the frontal and
Networks parietal cortices).
I note that some of these results in the last two
Hervé, Zago, Petit, Mazoyer, and Tzourio- are mixed with respect to the predominant pat-
Mazoyer (2013) conducted a review of neuroim- terns in the literature that are being described. For
aging research on hemispheric specialization and example, the right hemisphere seems more effi-
its development. This research allows for in vivo cient and hemispheric specialization seems to
macroscopic, fine-grained description of the take place progressively in development accord-
physiological basis of hemispheric asymmetry. ing to some of the findings.
For example, the right hemisphere appears more
efficiently organized, having greater interregional
connectivity. In contrast, the left hemisphere con- Differential Susceptibility
tains more “crucial” network hub regions (Iturria-
Medina et al., 2011). This distinction in networking Fortier et al. (2014) related the two areas of (a)
enables the different specialization of the two hemispheric specialization for emotions/motiva-
hemispheres (L: highly demanding, e.g., lan- tion and (b) biological sensitivity context (the
guage; R: broader, e.g., visuospatial integration). orchids/dandelion hypothesis). Greater right
186 8 Lateralization and Specialization of the Brain

frontal lobe EEG resting state activity (RSA) has The controlled condition (activity viewing nonso-
been associated with a predisposition to experi- cial clips compared to social ones) did not show
ence negative emotions or behavioral withdrawal these patterns (readings from the parietal; and
(Davidson, 2000; Fox, 1991; Schmidt, 1999). In results for the catechol-O-methyltransferase
contrast, left frontal asymmetry (LFA) is associ- (COMT) Val158Met polymorphism). The authors
ated with positive emotions and motivation also studied whether the genetic and hemispheric
(Harmon-Jones, Gable, & Peterson, 2010; differences in the groups were related to internal-
Schmidt, Shahinfar, & Fox, 1996). At the same izing and externalizing symptomology, but these
time, the emotions specialized in the left hemi- results were not significant. I conclude that this
sphere might be negative but with an approach exciting area of research relating differential sensi-
motivation (e.g., anger). tivity/susceptibility, differential hemispheric spe-
In their study, Fortier et al. (2014) studied the cialization, and effects on behavior is beginning
effects of extremely low birth weight (ELBW; and will further show the importance of lateraliza-
<1 kg) compared to normal birth weight (NBW; tion/specialization of behavior and brain.
>2.5 kg). Birth weight was a critical variable in As for the results of the study, Fortier et al.
their hypothesis, representing the quality of the (2014) found that ELBW LFA adults had the
intrauterine environment. Specifically, ELBW highest scores on measures of attention problems
stood as a proxy for developmental insults. It was and of withdrawn behavior (see Fig. 8.1), while
hypothesized that ELBW would have a negative NBW LFA adults had the lowest scores. This pat-
impact developmentally, but only in interaction tern of results represents a statistical interaction
with FA. That is, ELBW could lead to differential effect. Further analysis revealed that RFA adults
outcomes, depending on the pattern of frontal had moderate problem behavior scores irrespec-
lobe alpha-activation asymmetry. In this regard, tive of birth weight. Behavior problems were
the authors posited that LFA constitutes a biologi- measured using the Young Adult Self-Report
cal or differential sensitivity/susceptibility factor (YSR; Achenbach, 1991), a questionnaire filled
(and its proxy measure of BW), leading to either in when the participants were 30–35 years of age.
positive or negative outcome depending on envi- The authors concluded that LFA is associated
ronmental quality (Belsky & Pluess, 2009; Pluess with developmental susceptibility/sensitivity to
& Belsky, 2013; Ellis, Boyce, Belsky, Bakermans- context. Furthermore, the results support a moti-
Kranenburg, & van IJzendoorn, 2011). vational (e.g., approach-withdrawal) rather than
Although suggestive of relationship between a valence (i.e., positive–negative) view of differ-
differential sensitivity/susceptibility and differen- ential frontal lobe specialization with respect to
tial hemispheric specialization for emotion/moti- resting EEG.
vation, the research did not include genetic
variables typically used in this kind of research.
However, Christou et al. (2015) studied variations Language Development
in the single nucleotide promoter polymorphic
region of the serotonin transporter gene Corballis, Badzakova-Trajkov, and Häberling
(5-HTTLPR) in relation to differential frontal (2012) noted that there are genetic models of
hemispheric EEG asymmetries in 4- to 6-year- human handedness (e.g., Annett, 2002;
olds. Children who were homozygous for the short McManus, 2002), but that epigenetic models also
(s) allele exhibited rightward alpha band asymme- have been proposed (Crow, 2010; Klar, 2004).
tries (the s allele is associated with lower basal However, handedness and manual praxis appear
genetic activity/protein production) and those to depend on different lateralized systems, with
homozygous for those long (1) allele exhib- the latter more closely linked to language lateral-
ited leftward asymmetries, with heterozygous ization than the former. This conclusion is similar
exhibiting equal left and right frontal activation. to the one of Bishop (2013).
Other Developmental Topics 187

Fig. 8.1 The association 0.6


between birth weight

(a) YSR Attention Problems Score and


and YSR subscale
scores. Average scores

(b) YSR Withdrawn Score


on (a) the attention
problems subscales, and
(b) the withdrawn b
subscale of the Young
a
Adult Self-Report (YSR;
Achenbach, 1991) as a 0.4
function of birth weight
and frontal alpha-
activation asymmetry.
Adapted from Fortier
et al. (2014)
a
b

0.2
Extremely Normal
Low Birth Birth
Weight Weight

Left Frontal Asymmetry

Right Frontal Asymmetry

Bishop (2013) proposed that the relationship cause rather than a consequence of atypical cere-
between cerebral asymmetry and language devel- bral asymmetry. Granted, research has found a
opment might be best explained in a way oppo- relationship between structural and functional
site to traditional explanations. Traditionally, the brain lateralization and vocabulary in children
research shows that left-side language lateraliza- (receptive vocabulary, vocabulary score, respec-
tion typically is reduced in specific language tively) in studies by Lebel and Beaulieu (2009)
impairment, which suggests that reduced cere- and Groen, Whitehouse, Badcock, and Bishop
bral asymmetry might be a mediating endophe- (2012), respectively (on laterality of the arcuate
notype between genes involved in cerebral fasciculus measured by diffuse tensor imaging
asymmetry and outcomes in language develop- and in using FTCD (functional transcranial
ment. However, according to Bishop (2013), the Doppler ultrasound), respectively). However, the
research does not support that genes clearly affect results of these studies did not preclude normal or
individual differences in cerebral lateralization. better language development with atypical
Instead of genetic influence being predominant, lateralization.
nongenetic, experience-dependent language Bishop (2013) concluded that, for cerebral lat-
learning might be especially responsible for the eralization to develop normally, the child has to
development of cerebral asymmetry. engage lateralized systems for language learning
Bishop (2013) acknowledged the presence of and analysis (Minagawa-Kawai, Cristià, &
early prenatal differences in this regard, but the Dupoux, 2011). In addition, cerebral asymmetry
evidence is that reduced cerebral lateralization is might not be a unitary trait in development, but a
not clearly related to language impairments. multidimensional one that changes as develop-
More likely, poor language development is a ment proceeds.
188 8 Lateralization and Specialization of the Brain

Comment Go/No-Go task as they underwent a functional


MRI scan. In addition, they examined activation
The work on differential susceptibility in in correct inhibition. The go/no-go task requires
emotion-related aspects of behavior and of lan- inhibition of a prepotent response when infre-
guage development in relation to hemispheric quent “no go” signals occur in relation to frequent
specialization illustrates that not all lateralized “go” signals. Participants could display inhibition
phenomena or behaviors that express a side pref- successfully on a no-go trial or fail in inhibition
erence are related in a straightforward manner to on a no-go trial. Specifically, the children were
hemispheric specialization. There are too many given instructions to respond to target stimuli
variables involved both in the behaviors at issue (letters other than X) by pressing a button (the go
and in the cerebral hemispheres as they develop trials) or by not pressing it to nontarget stimuli (X
to expect clear brain–behavior relationships for letters, no-go trials). Stimuli lasted ½ second and
all behaviors and functions. The behaviors that were followed by 3 s of fixation. Both reaction
show the best correspondences in this regard are time (RT) and accuracy were measured.
behaviors that reflect the basic or fundamental The study was a longitudinal one in which the
functional specializations of the hemispheres. In relationship of inhibition, laterality, and later
this vein, note that I have argued that the left substance use was determined. Externalizing dif-
hemisphere is specialized for activation–inhibi- ficulties were measured at ages 3–8, 9–12, and
tion coordination and that the right hemisphere is 11–13 years. Drug use/problem alcohol use was
specialized for less complex inhibitions. The fol- determined at age 13–16.
lowing sections of the chapter address the The results indicated no difference in activa-
research on inhibition in brain and in behavior tion during correct inhibition in relation to base-
from a lateralized point of view. line. However, the user/problem group in relation
to matched controls demonstrated blunted activa-
tion during failed inhibition in the left middle
Inhibition in Children frontal gyrus (MFG). The at-risk group devel-
oped more externalizing problems at ages 11–13.
Left Houdé et al. (2011) used functional mag- By applying logistic regression, left MFG activa-
netic resonance imaging (fMRI) during conser- tion during inhibition errors was found to predict
vation of number task performance (Piaget, group membership, and even after statistical con-
1942/1952) in 5- to 6-year-olds and 9- to 10-year- trol of externalizing problems and RT.
olds. The control condition involved determining Heitzeg et al. (2014) concluded that early
whether the two rows of objects had the same teenage substance abuse and increased risk of
color. The results showed that both for younger substance abuse disorder (SUD) might derive
and older children, but especially for the latter, from under-controlled behavior associated with
task success was related to bilateral parietofron- blunted left MFG activation for required inhibi-
tal network activity, which is known to be tory self-control. In this regard, they found that
involved in numerical and executive (e.g., work- left MFG activation to inhibitory errors on the
ing memory) functions. The network found no-go task was inversely correlated with degree
included the bilateral intraparietal sulcus and the of externalizing difficulties.
bilateral inferior frontal gyri, the latter of which The Heitzeg et al. (2014) study is relevant to
is also associated with inhibition (Aron, Robbins, the present model that the left hemisphere is spe-
& Poldrack, 2004). There was also associated left cialized for more complex activation/inhibition
hemisphere and bilateral activity in the cingulate, coordination and the right for less complex inhi-
insula, and thalamus. bition functions, such as stopping outright (or
In the study of lateralized brain activation, quite short-term activation–inhibition coordina-
Heitzeg et al. (2014) investigated inhibitory errors tion). That is, in an ongoing task in children, when
in 9- to 12-year-old children (primarily male) in a inhibition was called for, the left hemisphere
Inhibition in Adults 189

(the MFG) was associated with the inhibitory the left dorsolateral prefrontal cortex (DLPFC)
skill of actively suppressing erroneous inhibition. inhibit negative distractors, while those in the
Not only does the study support the activation/ right inhibit positive distractors. That is, the left
inhibition model of left-hemisphere specializa- PFC subserves inhibition of withdrawal rather
tion and its differential inhibitory function rela- than being an instrument of approach. Also, the
tive to the right, it indicates its developmental right PFC subserves inhibition of approach rather
presence, as per Young (2011). than withdrawal, per se. In this regard, the model
puts EF front and center in the differential under-
Neither Dempster and Brainerd (1995) had standing of the hemispheres, with its inhibition
emphasized the importance of inhibition for suc- component being primary. Grimshaw and Carmel
ceeding in conservation. For example, successful (2014) also noted that, in EEG and neuroimaging
conservation involves suppressing the first research, left-hemisphere lateralization of inhibi-
response on conservation tasks in order to con- tion of negative stimuli is “stronger” than that of
sider variations in the two dimensions that are the right for positive stimuli, given that inhibiting
typically involved on these problems. Aside from negative stimuli (words, faces) is more “taxing”
parietal and frontal regions, the insula also is than inhibiting positive ones.
involved in inhibition (Houdé, Rossi, Lubin, & Sainburg’s (2014) model of handedness and
Joliot, 2010). Therefore, it appears that the brain brain lateralization is consistent with the one in
network found to be associated with number con- the present work. He argued that, for motor con-
servation includes widespread inhibition functions trol processes, the left hemisphere is specialized
(i.e., parietal, frontal, insula areas, the activation for behavior that predicts the effects of body/
of which leads to inhibitory functioning). environment dynamics. The left-hemisphere
Borst, Poirel, Pineau, Cassotti, and Houdé function allows it to account for predicable
(2013) extended the research group’s analysis of dynamic conditions, facilitating mechanical and
inhibitory skills required in Piagetian tasks to energetic efficiency (as in precise trajectory and
class inclusion (for example, one asks “Are there coordinated patterns, e.g., at the end of a move-
more green squares than squares?” after seeing a ment). In contrast, the right hemisphere is special-
series with many green and some other colored ized for “impedance” control processing in order
squares), although they did not consider to contain possible errors in unexpected “mechan-
hemispheric specialization in this regard. The ical” events and conditions, which together con-
authors made a distinction between inhibiting stitute a process that serves to obtain steady-state
content and inhibiting strategy (i.e., misleadingly postures (equilibrium). The right-hemisphere
focusing on subordinate classes in this task; e.g., function leads to positional and velocity stability,
green vs. other colored squares). The study allowing greater flexibility and robustness in situ-
showed that not only 10-year-olds but also ations of unpredictability and instability.
20-year-olds needed inhibitory skills to solve the Sainburg (2014) argued that his dynamic domi-
task. The study did not address side differences, nance hypothesis of motor lateralization is consis-
as mentioned, but it illustrates the importance of tent with the general model of lateralization
inhibition for the tasks involved. proposed by Rogers, Zucca, and Vallortigara
(2004). They had maintained that the left hemi-
sphere is specialized for well-established behavior
Inhibition in Adults patterns performed in environments that are famil-
iar, and the right hemisphere functions in response
Model to unforeseen events in the environment.

Both Grimshaw and Carmel (2014) presented a Comment Both the Grimshaw and Carmel
model of hemispheric specialization of emotions (2014) and Sainburg (2014) models are consis-
that focused on inhibition. First, mechanisms in tent with my own model of activation/inhibition
190 8 Lateralization and Specialization of the Brain

coordination (Young, 2011), in which the left In contrast, the right hemisphere compensates for
hemisphere is specialized for subtle, dynamic its “reduced efficiency” in its capacity in “paral-
activation/inhibition coordination and the right lel information transfer” by having more focal
for less nuanced inhibition processes (e.g., short- betweenness centrality.
term coordination in this regard, or more full- The results of Caeyenberghs and Leemans
scale inhibition by itself). For example, (2014) speak to the present work’s emphasis on
Sainburg’s emphasis on left-hemisphere acuity in the specialization of the left hemisphere for acti-
efficiency, precision, and coordination fits the vation–inhibition coordination. In showing that
activation–inhibition coordination model, with the left hemisphere is more efficient and inte-
the left hemisphere doing this more proficiently. grated both locally and globally in its networked
The research supports that the hemispheres interconnections over regions, a structural basis
developed their specializations independently appears evident for the suggested activation–
and that the right hemisphere did not take on its inhibition coordination in the left hemisphere.
functions only because the left hemisphere had Marinsek, Turner, Gazzaniga, and Miller
already been specialized for language (e.g., (2014) reviewed the research on split-brain and
Rosch, Bishop, & Badcock, 2012). Also, although brain-damaged patients, in particular. They
the lateralizations of language and manual skills argued that, in inferential reasoning strategies,
are co-lateralized in the left hemisphere, to a the left hemisphere appears to create explana-
degree, handedness appears independent of this tions, make inferences, and bridge information
complex (Vingerhoets et al., 2012). The left gaps. In contrast, the right hemisphere appears to
hemisphere would appear to have (some of) its detect conflicts, update beliefs, facilitate shifts in
advantages due to a superior inter-hemispheric mental sets, and monitor and inhibit (“brake”)
inhibition capacity (Talelli, Ewas, Waddingham, behavior. As a summary model, they conjectured
Rothwell, & Ward, 2008). that the left hemisphere appears to create hypoth-
eses and “represent causality.” In contrast, the
right hemisphere appears to evaluate hypotheses
Concepts Consistent and reject evidence-evident implausible/incon-
with the Present Model sistent ones. Finally, for Marinsek et al. (2014),
the left hemisphere functions to reduce uncer-
Left The work of Caeyenberghs and Leemans tainty and the right to resolve inconsistency.
(2014) revealed a topological organization in Marinsek et al. (2014) related their model of
structural brain networks consistent with an hemispheric specialization to other lateralization
advantage of the left hemisphere in efficiency in theories. For example, Bowden, Jung-Beeman,
organization. They used fiber tractography to Fleck, and Kounios (2005) considered that the
build (“reconstruct”) the networks, considering left hemisphere is more finely-tuned, and Braun
45 nodes in each hemisphere in doing so. (2007) considered that the right is more inhibi-
The results showed that the left hemisphere is tory (to “freeze and recoup”) in a process of
structured to be more efficient than the right. In “effortful inhibition” (Aron et al., 2014).
contrast, the right hemisphere demonstrates more About causality, Marinsek et al. (2014) con-
“small world” properties and “betweenness cen- tinued that the left hemisphere appears superior
trality.” This occurred especially in brain regions in making judgments about causal structure. In
associated with typical left- and right-hemisphere contrast, the right hemisphere has its own causal-
specializations (for language/motor actions; ity skills (in making perceptual and possible
memory/visuospatial attention, respectively). social causal judgments and influences).
The authors concluded that the left hemi- The authors concluded that the left hemi-
sphere is more optimal for information process- sphere may be especially recruited for creativity
ing compared to the right. Its efficiency is found and “liberal” inference making. In contrast, the
both for global and local levels. The left hemi- right hemisphere is recruited for caution and con-
sphere is integrated better in its interconnections. servative reasoning. Overall, the emphasis on the
Inhibition in Adults 191

left hemisphere in reducing uncertainty and (e.g., planning, decision-making), knowledge


more expansive inference making, in contrast to representation, social regulation/well-being, and
the right one’s skill in more temperate influences, self-preservation/adaptation, all of which con-
is consistent with the present emphasis on cern higher-level emotional processing. It is
left-hemisphere skill in activation–inhibition detached and transformative, and integrates the
coordination. information received from the right hemisphere
Shobe (2014) presented a model of left- and into higher-level cognitions. The left hemisphere
right-hemisphere specialization for emotional is limited by a positivity bias, so that both hemi-
processing that is quite consistent with the pres- spheres are needed in processing negatively-
ent model of left-hemisphere superiority for valenced emotional information.
complex tasks, such as activation–inhibition
coordination, as in sociality and in positive emo- Left Different models and tasks have associated
tions. Shobe’s (2014) model emphasizes the inde- inhibition functions more with one hemisphere or
pendent yet collaborative contributions of the two the other (e.g., right hemisphere, Bourgeois,
hemispheres. At the same time, he supported that Chica, Milgliaccio, Thiebaut de Schotten, &
the left hemisphere has a higher-order role in this Bartolomeo, 2012; Wright & Hardie, 2011; left
duality. For Shobe (2014), the research indicates hemisphere, Kurth et al., 2013), with age differ-
that the right hemisphere’s pulvinar-amygdala- ences also evident (e.g., Vidal, Mills, Pang, &
superior colliculus pathway deals with fast, Taylor, 2012). Reid and Serrien (2012) presented
course, and unconscious processing of emotional a model consistent with the present one that the
stimuli. Its subcortical connections provide addi- left hemisphere, in particular, is specialized for
tional processing capacity of emotional stimuli. activation–inhibition coordination (Young,
Overall, then, the right hemisphere mediates 2011). On a bimanual task, right-handers but not
directly the identification/comprehension of left-handers evidenced increased inhibitory pro-
emotional stimuli, whether positive or negative in cessing that “favored” left-hemisphere control.
valence. It is the seat of subjective feelings. This Specifically, right-handers appeared to express
happens in steps; first, it comprehends/processes intra- and interhemispheric inhibitory asymme-
the valence of emotional stimuli, and then it gen- tries or enhanced within- and cross-hemisphere
erates the feeling that fits the interpretation. So it inhibitory processing.
is the perceptual and experiential locus of emo- These models are consistent with Gazzaniga
tional processing. (2013) who referred to the left hemisphere as
The role of the left hemisphere appears far having a facility in interpretation. It generates
more complex in emotional processing and it narratives or stories explaining what we do and
occurs later in the process compared to the role why, through a dedicated “special module.” In
for the right hemisphere, although the hemi- this regard, Mackey, Whitaker, and Bunge (2012)
spheres communicate via the corpus callosum. found data in support of left-hemisphere special-
The left hemisphere is involved in a secondary, ization for “reasoning” (also Krawczyk, 2012).
additional emotional interpretation after it As well, it might achieve its superiority in rea-
receives the right-hemisphere information. soning by efficiently recruiting homologous
That is, for Shobe (2014), the left hemisphere right-hemisphere cortex areas, especially for
gives a verbal, propositional (semantic, linguis- complex reasoning.
tic, meaningful) code to the emotional informa-
tion (and the brain regions activated during
emotional processing in the left hemisphere are Evidence
language-related). It directs our conscious inter-
pretation of and also our interaction with emo- Right Aron et al. (2014) considered the right
tional stimuli. It is involved with emotional inferior frontal cortex (rIFC) as an inhibitory
regulation (e.g., attenuating/reinterpreting the pausing device or brake and not just for outright
negative; problem solving), executive function stopping. It functions accordingly along with one
192 8 Lateralization and Specialization of the Brain

or more fronto-basal-ganglia networks. I note reflect the type of activation/inhibition coordina-


that these studies are differentiating the types of tion that I suggest is central to left-hemisphere
tasks, techniques, inhibitory skills, areas of the functioning.
brain and subareas, and developmental trends in
behavior control. Left Serrien and Sovijävi-Spapé (2013) deter-
Dambacher et al. (2014) examined adult ability mined a relationship between hemispheric spe-
to inhibit responses in action restraint and action cialization and inhibition. Inhibition is important
cancellation (as indexed in a go/no-go task and a for successful goal-directed behavior, for exam-
stop signal task, respectively). They used fMRI ple, of irrelevant information or to sudden
data and response to continuous theta burst brain changes in the environment. Habitual responses
stimulation. Action restraint was associated with that could interfere with task completion need to
right anterior insula (AI) and right superior frontal be contained.
gyrus activation, among others, while action can- To measure response inhibition, a common
cellation was associated with the right AI and the task that is used in the laboratory is the Go/
right MFG, among others. The brain stimulation No-Go or Go/Stop task. Participants must either,
acts to disrupt targeted regions. This technique respectively, withhold or discontinue a prepared
found the right AI had been disrupted in both tasks response to target cues. Distinct inhibitory pro-
used. For the right superior frontal gyrus, only the cesses are involved in the two conditions—action
restraint task had inhibition interrupted. restraint and action cancellation, respectively. If
Bourgeois, Chica, Valero-Cabré, and the behavior itself needs to be altered, this is
Bartolomeo (2013) conducted a study of cortical referred to as “switching.”
control of inhibition of return (IOR) in adults, In their research, the authors used EEG coher-
which demonstrated that the right hemisphere is ence as an index of functional connectivity.
involved in less complex inhibitory function. Inhibition has been related to a widespread brain
This type of inhibition involves inspection of spa- network, with differential left- and right-
tial locations. Ones already inspected generate hemisphere involvement depending on inhibition
longer response times relative to those that have demand characteristics of the task used.
not yet been inspected. The research demon- As for the methods of their study, Serrien and
strates right parietal cortex involvement in the Sovijävi-Spapé (2013) tested right and left-
inhibition, but not left. handed young adults. The task involved reaction
Similarly, O’Connor, Upton, Moore, and time to visually-presented stimuli. In the Go con-
Hester (2014) demonstrated with a go/no-go task dition, participants had to fixate a cross that was
that enhanced action withholding especially is presented for 1 s. Then, a preparation cue (L or
associated with the right inferior frontal junction R) was presented for 400 ms. This procedure
(and precentral gyrus). This area is involved not allowed participants to prepare a response with
only with “outright stopping” (Aron et al., 2014) either the left or right index finger, as cued.
but also with “pausing” and “braking” responses, Interstimulus intervals lasted for 1 s ± 200 ms
in general. The authors related their results to (random). During these intervals, the screen was
impulse control disorders, such as SUD. blank. Then, the target cue, a colored square, was
Shackman, McMenamin, Maxwell, Greischar, presented for 920 ms. The square was either
and Davidson (2009) found that higher self- green in color (Go) or red (No-Go). If the square
reported behavioral inhibition was associated was blue, the participants had to switch index fin-
with greater tonic (resting) high-resolution EEG ger used. Training trials were used to encourage
in the right dorsolateral prefrontal cortex. These rapid response or inhibition/change, as required.
series of studies are confirming a role for the With respect to EEG, measurements took
right hemisphere in inhibition functions, but I place in the alpha band (8–12 Hz), which cap-
note that the type of inhibitions involved do not tures both response excitation and inhibition.
Inhibition in Adults 193

Coherence was established over the regions of memories; (c) shifting attention within WM; and
interest chosen, which corresponded to dorsal, (d) updating WM contents. The review revealed a
prefrontal, premotor, primary motor, and superior broad network of medial and lateral frontal and
parietal areas. parietal regions involved in WM executive
The results for EEG coherence revealed processing.
strengthening of interregional coupling in the Some of the main results indicated laterality
alpha band following presentation of target cues, effects. The midlateral prefrontal cortex was
with an association with fronto-medial circuitry. involved in nonspatial content and reflected a left
Also, parietal areas appeared to be involved in lateralization. The more dorsal caudal superior
response switching. The relationship between frontal sulcus appeared sensitive to spatial con-
behavioral response and EEG measures indicated tent. The results reflect a dual selection model
a functional significance of left-side hemispheric (focused on “what” and “where” functions,
regions for successful response inhibition and respectively). Inhibitory functions (intrusion
response switching. For both right- and left- resistance) appeared right-lateralized in the infe-
handers, the left hemisphere appeared special- rior frontal sulcus, but other functions related to
ized for goal-directed activity or higher-order inhibition (distractor resistance) were more left
aspects of action, with its inhibitory function lateralized.
(e.g., response selection, response withholding) Ocklenburg, Ness, Güntürkün, Suchan, and
critical to success. Beste (2013) conducted a study consistent with
The authors analyzed the temporal patterns in the model that the initial processing of verbal
the inhibition that was evident. Early coupling stimuli takes place in the left hemisphere and
started within ≤ 100 ms in the No-Go condition, leads to more efficient response inhibition in that
implying attentional control. Between 100 and hemisphere. Using a facial go/no-go task, they
200 ms, the coupling that took place appeared to found an equivalent inhibitory advantage in these
involve decision to withhold/regulation. Next, regards for the right hemisphere.
coupling after 200 ms appeared to reflect actual Cerutti (2013) reported in his research that
deployment of inhibition and potential conflict stimulating the left prefrontal cortex by anodal
monitoring. The interval related to decision- stimulation improves a verbal task performance
making was the one more related to left-sided with EF (memory load) demand. Similarly, using
frontal region coupling. Note that although Go/ inhibitory cathodal stimulation of the corre-
No-Go comparisons yielded results implicating sponding region in the right hemisphere improved
left-hemisphere control for inhibition, the switch- performance on a verbal task of semantic organi-
ing tasks yielded bilateral associations, but the zation. The results show how facilitatory and
authors did implicate the left hemisphere in switch- inhibitory links function in inter- and intra-
ing, too (p. 288). Note that the research in the field regional neuronal connectivity.
supports that stopping is a right-hemisphere func- Balconi, Finocchiaro, and Canavesio (2014)
tion (Rubia et al., 2001). Overall, the data support examined lateralized cortical frontal alpha band
Young’s (2011) model that the left hemisphere is oscillation modulation in relation to Iowa
specialized for activation (excitation)/inhibition Gambling Task performance in both an SUD
coordination and the right hemisphere for less group and controls. They administered a ques-
complex inhibitions (e.g., stopping). tionnaire on the Behavioral Activation and
Nee et al. (2012) conducted a meta-analysis to Behavior Inhibition Systems (BAS and BIS,
determine the “operations” that contribute to respectively). The SUD group revealed a pat-
working memory (WM). The four component tern on the gambling task favoring the choice
executive functions central to WM involve: (a) for immediate reward and also an increase in
controlling external distraction (distractor resis- left-hemisphere activation in response to the
tance); (b) controlling intrusion by irrelevant choice associated with immediate reward.
194 8 Lateralization and Specialization of the Brain

The authors concluded that the SUD group could spatiotemporal patterns of language lateralization
have a higher left-hemisphere mediated BAS using MEG, and found age-related sex differ-
trait relative to controls [who would have a more ences on a visual verb generation task.
left (BAS)—right (BIS) balance; note that in the Part of the reasons for the conflicting results in
latter description I added the BIS function to the the field related to the disjoint in lateralization of
right hemisphere]. the brain, related manual skills, and handedness.
The latter might reflect environmental influences
more than the other lateralities, in that handed-
Evolution ness is an expression of multifactorial genetic
and environmental influences (Ocklenburg,
Cochet and Byrne (2013) noted that there might Beste, & Güntürkün, 2013).
be evolutionary continuity in the origins of man- The research on the relationship of lateraliza-
ual laterality and hemispheric specialization. In tion and the expression of autism in children gen-
this regard, they considered possible drivers in erally reveals little conclusive findings (e.g.,
skilled manipulative activity (tool use), gestural Dennis & Thompson, 2013; Preslar, Kushner,
communication, organization complexity in Marino, & Pearce, 2014). However, Joseph et al.
action (hierarchical structure), and goal-directed, (2014) examined structural asymmetries in rela-
intentional action for manual lateralization and tion to language function in 4- to 7-year-old chil-
associated hemispheric specialization. They dren with autism spectrum disorder (ASD) and
referred to a possible “association” of hemi- matched controls. They used structural MRI and
spheric dominance of language and specific char- magnetic resonance DTI tractography.
acteristics that cut across the typical right-sided The researchers found no gray matter differ-
laterality in manual tasks. ences between the groups, but did find white-
MacNeilage (2014) presented a model of the matter differences. The ASD group was less
evolution of human handedness as a right- left-lateralized than controls both in the volume
favoring adaptation in the context of an earlier and radial diffusivity of the arcuate fasciculus
evolved left-handedness. Specifically, the left (AF). Also, within the ASD group, decreased left-
hand was specialized by prosimians for postural side/increased right-side asymmetry of the pars
support in their arboreal habitat. Later, simians opercularis was associated both with an earlier lan-
evolved right-side adaptations for each of the guage onset and with a greater ability in language.
behaviors of: manipulation; lead hand in biman- To conclude, the area of the neurodevelop-
ual coordination; throwing; and manual commu- ment of lateralities and how it becomes affected
nication. Humans cemented the right-hand bias in disturbances in development holds much
through an evolved “superstructure” related to promise. However, as well, it illustrates the com-
tool-use and language. plexities in lateralization development.

Doubts Chapter Conclusions

Not all results reveal a clear lateralization effect The study of laterality of behavior and specializa-
in children’s manual or hemispheric specializa- tion of the brain should be considered a core area
tion. Scharoun and Bryden (2014) indicated con- in development because of the implications of
troversy on the age of emergence of hand this area of research for the brain, networks,
preference and hand performance abilities. developmental abnormalities, developmental
Johansson, Domellöf, and Rönnqvist (2014) adversity and differential susceptibility, under-
found that only full-term (compared to preterm) pinning to motivation/emotion, and general over-
birthed children showed side differences in goal- arching models of brain and behavior (such as
directed movements. Yu et al. (2014) investigated activation–inhibition coordination). The research
References 195

on the evolution of laterality in behavior and motor performance in children. Cerebral Cortex, 22,
51–59.
hemispheric specialization in the brain reveals its
Barbey, A. K., Colom, R., Solomon, J., Krueger, F.,
origins in basic protomammalian brain–behavior Forbes, C., & Grafman, J. (2012). An integrative
relations, and not just in nonhuman primates and architecture for general intelligence and executive
their ancestors. Indeed, it stretches earlier into function revealed by lesion mapping. Brain, 135,
1154–1164.
our evolution and stands as an important building
Belsky, J., & Pluess, M. (2009). The nature (and nurture?)
block in our evolutionary heritage. The model of of plasticity in early human development. Perspectives
neuronal networks has led to research that the left on Psychological Science, 4, 345–351.
hemisphere congenitally is more efficient in con- Berl, M. M., Mayo, J., Parks, E. N., Rosenberger, L. R.,
VanMeter, J., Ratner, N. B., et al. (2014). Regional dif-
nectivity. This fits Young’s (2011) model that it is
ferences in the developmental trajectory of lateraliza-
specialized for activation–inhibition coordina- tion of the language network. Human Brain Mapping,
tion. Lateralization might be prevalent in animal 35, 270–284.
species, but its evolution to its current state in Bishop, D. V. M. (2013). Cerebral asymmetry and lan-
guage development: Cause, correlate, or consequence?
humans might address aspects of human excep-
Science, 340, 6138. doi:10.1126/science.1230531.
tionality and their underpinning basis in the brain. Björk, T., Brus, O., Osika, W., & Montgomery, S. (2012).
Laterality, hand control and scholastic performance:
A British birth cohort study. British Medical
References Journal Open, 2, e000314. doi:10.1136/bmjopen-
2011-000314.
Achenbach, T. M. (1991). Manual for the adult self-report Borst, G., Poirel, N., Pineau, A., Cassotti, M., & Houdé, O.
and 1991 profile. Burlington, VT: University of (2013). Inhibitory control efficiency in a Piaget-like
Vermont, Department of Psychiatry. class-inclusion task in school-age children and adults: A
Annett, M. (2002). Handedness and brain asymmetry: developmental negative priming study. Developmental
The right shift theory. Hove, UK: Psychology Press. Psychology, 49, 1366–1374.
Arbib, M. A. (2006). The mirror system hypothesis on the Bourgeois, A., Chica, A. B., Migliaccio, R., Thiebaut de
linkage of action and languages. In M. A. Arbib (Ed.), Schotten, M., & Bartolomeo, P. (2012). Cortical con-
Action to language via the mirror neuron system trol of inhibition of return: Evidence from patients
(pp. 3–47). New York: Cambridge University Press. with inferior parietal damage and visual neglect.
Aron, A. R., Robbins, T. W., & Poldrack, R. A. (2004). Neuropsychologia, 50, 800–809.
Inhibition and the right inferior frontal cortex. Trends Bourgeois, A., Chica, A. B., Valero-Cabré, A., &
in Cognitive Sciences, 8, 170–177. Bartolomeo, P. (2013). Cortical control of inhibition of
Aron, A. R., Robbins, T. W., & Poldrack, R. A. (2014). return: Exploring the causal contributions of the left
Inhibition and the right inferior frontal cortex: One parietal cortex. Cortex, 49, 2927–2934.
decade on. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 18, 177–185. Bowden, E. M., Jung-Beeman, M., Fleck, J., & Kounios,
Aslin, R. N., Shukla, M., & Emberson, L. L. (2015). J. (2005). New approaches to demystifying insight.
Hemodynamic correlates of cognition in human Trends in Cognitive Science, 9, 322–328.
infants. Annual Review of Psychology, 66, 349–379. Braun, C. M. J. (2007). Evolution of hemispheric speciali-
Atzil, S., Hendler, T., & Feldman, R. (2011). Specifying sation of antagonistic systems of management of the
the neurobiological basis of human attachment: Brain, body’s energy resources. Laterality, 12, 397–427.
hormones, and behavior in synchronous and intrusive Caeyenberghs, K., & Leemans, A. (2014). Hemispheric
mothers. Neuropsychopharmacology, 36, 2603–2615. lateralization of topological organization in struc-
Babik, I., Campbell, J. M., & Michel, G. F. (2013). tural brain networks. Human Brain Mapping, 35,
Postural influences on the development of infant later- 4944–4957.
alized and symmetric hand-use. Child Development, Campbell, J. M., Marcinowski, E. C., Babik, I., & Michel,
85, 294–307. G. F. (2015). The influence of a hand preference for
Balconi, M., Finocchiaro, R., & Canavesio, Y. (2014). acquiring objects on the development of a hand prefer-
Reward-system effect (BAS rating), left hemispheric ence for unimanual manipulation from 6 to 14 months.
“unbalance” (alpha band oscillations) and decision Infant Behavior and Development, 39, 107–117.
impairments in drug addiction. Addictive Behaviors, Campbell, J. M., Marcinowski, E. C., Latta, J., & Michel,
39, 1026–1032. G. F. (2015). Different assessment tasks produce dif-
Barber, A. D., Srinivasan, P., Joel, S. E., Caffo, B. S., ferent estimates of handedness stability during the
Pekar, J. J., & Mostofsky, S. H. (2012). Motor “dexter- eight to 14 month age period. Infant Behavior and
ity”? Evidence that left hemisphere lateralization of Development, 39, 67–80.
motor circuit connectivity is associated with better Cerutti, C. (2013). Building a functional multiple intelli-
gence theory to advance educational neuroscience.
196 8 Lateralization and Specialization of the Brain

Frontiers in Psychology, 4, 950. doi:10.3389/ Dawson, G., Ashman, S. B., Hessl, D., Spieker, S., Frey,
fpsyg.2013.00950. K., Panagiotides, H., et al. (2001). Autonomic and
Cheng, Y., Lee, S. Y., Chen, H. Y., Wang, P., & Decety, brain electrical activity in securely- and insecurely-
J. (2012). Voice and emotion processing in the human attached infants of depressed mothers. Infant Behavior
neonatal brain. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 24, and Development, 24, 135–149.
1411–1419. de Vries, J. I. P., Wimmers, R. H., Ververs, I. A. P.,
Cheyne, D., Jobst, C., Tesan, G., Crain, S., & Johnson, B. Hopkins, B., Savelsbergh, G. J. P., & van Geijn, H. P.
(2014). Movement-related neuromagnetic fields in (2001). Fetal handedness and head position prefer-
preschool age children. Human Brain Mapping, 35, ence: A developmental study. Developmental
4858–4875. Psychobiology, 39, 171–178.
Christou, A. I., Endo, S., Wallis, Y., Bair, H., Zeggers, Delis, D. C., Kaplan, E., & Kramer, J. H. (2001). Delis
M. P., & McCleery, J. P. (2015). Variation in serotonin Kaplan executive function system. San Antonio, TX:
transporter linked polymorphic region (5-HTTLPR) The Psychological Corporation.
short/long genotype modulates resting frontal electro- Dempster, F., & Brainerd, C. (Eds.). (1995). Interference
encephalography asymmetries in children. and inhibition in cognition. San Diego, CA: Academic.
Development and Psychopathology, 1–12. Denckla, M. B. (1985). Revised PANESS.
doi:10.1017/S0954579415000413. Psychopharmacology Bulletin, 21, 773–800.
Cochet, H. (2012). Development of hand preference for Dennis, E. L., & Thompson, P. M. (2013). Mapping con-
object-directed actions and pointing gestures: A nectivity in the developing brain. International
longitudinal study between 15 and 25 months of age. Journal of Developmental Neuroscience, 31,
Developmental Psychobiology, 54, 105–111. 525–542.
Cochet, H., & Byrne, R. W. (2013). Evolutionary origins Dubois, J., Hertz-Pannier, L., Cachia, A., Mangin, J. F.,
of human handedness: Evaluating contrasting hypoth- Le Bihan, D., & Dehaene-Lambertz, G. (2009).
eses. Animal Cognition, 16, 531–542. Structural asymmetries in the infant language and
Cochet, H., & Vauclair, J. (2010). Pointing gestures pro- sensori-motor networks. Cerebral Cortex, 19,
duced by toddlers from 15 to 30 months: Different 414–423.
functions, hand shapes and laterality patterns. Infant Dunfield, K. A. (2014). A construct divided: Prosocial
Behavior and Development, 33, 431–441. behavior as helping, sharing, and comforting subtypes.
Corballis, M. C., Badzakova-Trajkov, G., & Häberling, Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 958. doi:10.3389/
I. S. (2012). Right hand, left brain: Genetic and evolu- fpsyg.2014.00958.
tionary bases of cerebral asymmetries for language Ellis, B. J., Boyce, W. T., Belsky, J., Bakermans-
and manual action. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Kranenburg, M. J., & van IJzendoorn, M. H. (2011).
Cognitive Science, 3, 1–17. Differential susceptibility to the environment: An
Corbetta, D., Friedman, D. R., & Bell, M. A. (2014). evolutionary-neurodevelopmental theory.
Brain reorganization as a function of walking experi- Development and Psychopathology, 23, 7–28.
ence in 12-month-old infants: Implications for the Esseily, R., Jacquet, A.-Y., & Fagard, J. (2011).
development of manual laterality. Frontiers in Handedness for grasping objects and pointing and the
Psychology, 5, 245. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00245. development of language in 14-month-old infants.
Crow, T. J. (2010). A theory of origin of cerebral asym- Laterality, 16, 565–585.
metry: Epigenetic variation superimposed on a fixed Everts, R., Lidzba, K., Wilke, M., Kiefer, C., Mordasini,
right-shift. Laterality, 15, 289–303. M., Schroth, G., et al. (2009). Strengthening of lateral-
Dambacher, F., Sack, A. T., Lobbestael, J., Arntz, A., ity of verbal and visuospatial functions during child-
Brugmann, S., & Schuhmann, T. (2014). The role of hood and adolescence. Human Brain Mapping, 30,
right prefrontal and medial cortex in response inhibi- 473–483.
tion: Interfering with action restraint and action can- Fagard, J., Sirri, L., & Rämä, P. (2014). Effect of handed-
cellation using transcranial magnetic brain stimulation. ness on the occurrence of semantic N400 priming
Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 26, 1775–1784. effect in 18- and 24-month-old children. Frontiers in
Davidson, R. J. (2000). Affective style, psychopathology, Psychology, 5, 355. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00355.
and resilience: Brain mechanisms and plasticity. Fortier, P., Van Lieshout, R. J., Waxman, J. A., Boyle,
American Psychologist, 55, 1196–1214. M. H., Saigal, S., & Schmidt, L. A. (2014). Are
Davidson, R. J., Ekman, P., Saron, C. D., & Senulius, J. A. orchids left and dandelions right? Frontal brain activa-
(1990). Approach-withdrawal and cerebral asymme- tion asymmetry and its sensitivity to developmental
try: Emotional express and brain physiology. context. Psychological Science, 25, 1526–1533.
International Journal of Personality and Social Fox, N. A. (1991). If it’s not left, it’s right:
Psychology, 58, 330–341. Electroencephalograph asymmetry and the develop-
Davidson, R. J., & Fox, N. A. (1982). Asymmetrical brain ment of emotion. American Psychologist, 46,
activity discriminates between positive and negative 863–872.
affective stimuli in human infants. Science, 218, Friederici, A. D., Brauer, J., & Lohmann, G. (2011).
1235–1237. Maturation of the language network: from inter-to
References 197

intrahemispheric connectivities. PLoS ONE, 6, Hepper, P. G. (2013). The developmental origins of later-
e20726. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0020726. ality: Fetal handedness. Developmental Psychobiology,
Gander, M., & Buchheim, A. (2015). Attachment classifi- 55, 588–595.
cation, psychophysiology and frontal EEG asymmetry Hepper, P. G., McCartney, G. R., & Shannon, E. A.
across the lifespan: A review. Frontiers in Human (1998). Lateralised behavior in first trimester human
Neuroscience, 9, 79. doi:10.3389/fnhum.2015.00079. fetuses. Neuropsychologia, 36, 531–534.
Gazzaniga, M. S. (2013). Shifting gears: Seeking new Hepper, P. G., Shahidullah, S., & White, R. (1991).
approaches for mind/brain mechanisms. Annual Handedness in human fetus. Neuropsychologia, 29,
Review of Psychology, 64, 1–20. 1107–1111.
Gioia, G. A., Isquith, P. K., Guy, S. C., & Kenworthy, L. Hepper, P. G., Wells, D. K., & Lynch, C. (2005). Prenatal
(2000). Behavior rating inventory of executive func- thumb sucking is related to postnatal handedness.
tion (BRIEF). Odessa, FL: Psychological Assessment Neuropsychologia, 43, 313–315.
Resources. Hervé, P. Y., Zago, L., Petit, L., Mazoyer, B., & Tzourio-
Glasel, H., Leroy, F., Dubois, J., Hertz-Pannier, L., Mazoyer, N. (2013). Revisiting human hemispheric
Mangin, J. F., & Dehaene-Lambertz, G. (2011). A specialization with neuroimaging. Trends in Cognitive
robust cerebral asymmetry in the infant brain: The Sciences, 17, 69–80.
rightward superior temporal sulcus. NeuroImage, 58, Hill, J., Dierker, D., Neil, J., Inder, T., Knutsen, A.,
716–723. Harwell, J., et al. (2010). A surface-based analysis of
Gonzalez, C. L. R., Li, F., Mills, K. J., Rosen, N., & Gibb, hemispheric asymmetries and folding of cerebral cor-
R. L. (2014). Speech in action: Degree of hand prefer- tex in term-born human infants. Journal of
ence for grasping predicts speech articulation compe- Neuroscience, 30, 2268–2276.
tence in children. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 1267. Holowka, S., & Petitto, L. A. (2002). Left hemisphere
doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.01267. cerebral specialization for babies while babbling.
Gonzalez, C. L. R., Mills, K. J., Genee, I., Li, F., Piquette, Science, 297, 1515. doi:10.1126/science.1074941.
N., Rosen, N., et al. (2014). Getting the right grasp on Houdé, O., Pineau, A., Leroux, G., Poirel, N., Perchey, G.,
executive function. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 285. Lanoë, C., et al. (2011). Functional magnetic reso-
doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00285. nance imaging study of Piaget’s conservation-of-
Grimshaw, G. M., & Carmel, D. (2014). An asymmetric number task in preschool and school-age children: A
inhibition model of hemispheric differences in emo- neo-Piagetian approach. Journal of Experimental
tional processing. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 489. Child Psychology, 110, 332–346.
doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00489. Houdé, O., Rossi, S., Lubin, A., & Joliot, M. (2010).
Groen, M. A., Whitehouse, A. J., Badcock, N. A., & Mapping numerical procession, reading, and executive
Bishop, D. V. (2012). Does cerebral lateralization functions in the developing brain: An fMRI meta-
develop? A study using functional transcranial analysis on 52 studies including 842 children.
Doppler ultrasound assessing lateralization for lan- Developmental Science, 13, 876–885.
guage production and visuospatial memory. Brain and Im, K., Jo, H. J., Mangin, J. F., Evans, A. C., Kim, S. I., &
Behavior, 2, 256–296. Lee, J. M. (2010). Spatial distribution of deep sulcal
Grossmann, T., Johnson, M. H., Lloyd-Fox, S., Blasi, A., landmarks and hemispherical asymmetry on the corti-
Deligianni, F., Elwell, C., et al. (2008). Early cortical cal surface. NeuroImage, 58, 716–723.
specialization for face-to-face communication in Iturria-Medina, Y., Pérez Fernández, A., Morris, D. M.,
human infants. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Canales-Rodríguez, E. J., Haroon, H. A., García
Biological Sciences, 275, 2803–2811. Pentón, L., et al. (2011). Brain hemispheric structural
Grossmann, T., Parise, E., & Friederici, A. D. (2010). The efficiency and interconnectivity rightward asymmetry
detection of communicative signals directed at the self in human and nonhuman primates. Cerebral Cortex,
in infant prefrontal cortex. Frontiers in Human 21, 56–67.
Neuroscience, 4, 201. doi:10.3389/fnhum.2010.00201. Jacquet, A.-Y., Esseily, R., Rider, D., & Fagard, J. (2012).
Habas, P. A., Scott, J. A., Roosta, A., Rajagopalan, V., Handedness for grasping objects and declarative
Kim, K., Rousseau, F., et al. (2012). Early folding pat- pointing: A longitudinal study. Developmental
terns and asymmetries of the normal human brain Psychobiology, 54, 36–46.
detected from in utero MRI. Cerebral Cortex, 22, Johansson, A.-M., Domellöf, E., & Rönnqvist, L. (2014).
13–25. Long-term influences of a preterm birth on movement
Harmon-Jones, E., Gable, P. A., & Peterson, C. K. (2010). organization and side specialization in children at 4–8
The role of asymmetric frontal cortical activity in years of age. Developmental Psychobiology, 56,
emotion-related phenomena: A review and update. 1263–1277.
Biological Psychology, 84, 451–462. Joseph, R. M., Fricker, Z., Fenoglio, A., Lindgren, K. A.,
Heitzeg, M. M., Nigg, J. T., Hardee, J. E., Soules, M., Knaus, T. A., & Tager-Flusberg, H. (2014). Structural
Steinberg, D., Zubieta, J-K., et al. (2014). Left middle asymmetries of language-related gray and white mat-
frontal gyrus response to inhibitory errors in children ter and their relationship to language function in
prospectively predicts early problem substance use. young children with ASD. Brain Imaging and
Drug and Alcohol Dependence, 141, 51–57. Behavior, 8, 60–72.
198 8 Lateralization and Specialization of the Brain

Kahrs, B. A., Jung, W. P., & Lockman, J. J. (2014). Marinsek, N., Turner, B. O., Gazzaniga, M., & Miller,
When does tool use become distinctively human? M. B. (2014). Divergent hemispheric reasoning strate-
Hammering in young children. Child Development, gies: Reducing uncertainty versus resolving inconsis-
85, 1050–1061. tency. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 8, 839.
Kasprian, G., Langs, G., Brugger, P. C., Bittner, M., doi:10.3389/fnhum.2014.00839.
Weber, M., Arantes, M., et al. (2011). The prenatal ori- McCartney, G., & Hepper, P. G. (1999). Developmental of
gin of hemispheric asymmetry: An in utero neuroim- lateralised behavior in the human fetus from 12 to 27
aging study. Cerebral Cortex, 21, 1076–1083. weeks’ gestation. Developmental Medicine and Child
Kaufman, A., & Kaufman, N. (1983). Kaufman assess- Neurology, 41, 83–86.
ment battery for children: Administration and scoring McManus, C. (2002). Right hand, left hand. London:
manual. Circle Pines, MN: American Guidance Weidenfeld & Nicolson.
Service. Michel, G. F., Babik, I., Nelson, E. L., Campbell, J. M., &
Kikuchi, M., Shitamichi, K., Yoshimura, Y., Ueno, S., Marcinowski, E. C. (2013). How the development of
Remijn, G. B., Hirosawa, T., et al. (2011). Lateralized handedness could contribute to the development of lan-
theta wave connectivity and language performance in guage. Developmental Psychobiology, 55, 608–620.
2- to 5-year-old children. Journal of Neuroscience, 31, Michel, G. F., Babik, I., Shue, C.-F., & Campbell, J. M.
14984–14988. (2013). Latent classes in the developmental trajecto-
Kivilevitch, Z., Achiron, R., & Zalel, Y. (2010). Fetal ries of infant handedness. Developmental Psychology,
brain asymmetry: In utero sonographic findings. 50, 349–359.
American Journal of Obstetrics and Gynecology, 202, Minagawa-Kawai, Y., Cristià, A., & Dupoux, E. (2011).
359.e1–e8. Cerebral lateralization and early speech acquisition: A
Klar, A. (2004). An epigenetic hypothesis for human developmental scenario. Developmental Cognitive
brain laterality, handedness, and psychosis develop- Neuroscience, 1, 217–232.
ment. Cold Spring Harbor Symposia Quantitative Missana, M., & Grossmann, T. (2014). Infants’ emerging
Biology, 69, 499–506. sensitivity to emotional body expressions: Insights
Krawczyk, D. C. (2012). The cognition and neuroscience from asymmetrical frontal brain activity.
of relational reasoning. Brain Research, 1428, 13–23. Developmental Psychology, 51, 151–160.
Kurjak, A., Vecek, N., Hafner, T., Bozek, T., Funduk- Morange-Majoux, F., & Devouche, E. (2014). Social
Kirjak, B., & Ujevic, B. (2002). Prenatal diagnosis: encouragement can influence manual preference in 6
What does four-dimensional ultrasound add? Journal month-old-infants. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 1225.
of Perinatal Medicine, 30, 57–62. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.01225.
Kurth, F., Mayer, E. A., Toga, A. W., Thompson, P. M., & Morange-Majoux, F., Lemoine, C., & Dellatolas, G.
Luders, E. (2013). The right inhibition? Callosal cor- (2013). Early manifestations of manual specialization
relates of hand performance in healthy children and in infants: A longitudinal study from 20 to 30 weeks.
adolescents callosal correlates of hand performance. Laterality, 18, 231–250.
Human Brain Mapping, 34, 2259–2265. Morillon, B., Lehongre, K., Frackowiak, R. S., Ducorps,
Lebel, C., & Beaulieu, C. (2009). Lateralization of arcuate A., Kleinschmidt, A., Poeppel, D., et al. (2010).
fasciculus from childhood to adulthood and its relation Neurophysiological origin of human brain asymmetry
to cognitive abilities in children. Human Brain for speech and language. Proceedings of the National
Mapping, 30, 3563–3573. Academy of Sciences USA, 107, 18688–18693.
Li, G., Nie, J., Li, W., Shi, F., Lyan, A. E., Lin, W., et al. Nagy, E., Pal, A., & Orvos, H. (2014). Learning to imitate
(2014). Mapping longitudinal hemispheric structural individual finger movements by the human neonate.
asymmetries of the human cerebral cortex from birth Developmental Science, 17, 841–857.
to 2 years of age. Cerebral Cortex, 24, 1289–1300. Nakato, E., Otsuka, Y., Kanazawa, S., Yamaguchi, M. K.,
Lloyd-Fox, S., Blasi, A., Volein, A., Everdell, N., Elwell, & Kakigi, R. (2011). Distinct differences in the pattern
C. E., & Johnson, M. H. (2009). Social perception in of hemodynamic response to happy and angry facial
infancy: A near infrared spectroscopy study. Child expressions in infants—a near-infrared spectroscopic
Development, 80, 986–999. study. NeuroImage, 54, 1600–1606.
MacDonald, P. A., Ganjavi, H., Collins, D. L., Evans, Nee, D. E., Brown, J. W., Askren, M. K., Berman, M. G.,
A. C., & Karama, S. (2014). Investigating the relation Demiralp, E., Krawitz, A., et al. (2012). A meta-
between striatal volume and IQ. Brain Imaging and analysis of executive components of working memory.
Behavior, 8, 52–59. Cerebral Cortex, 23, 264–282.
Mackey, A. P., Whitaker, K. J., & Bunge, S. A. (2012). Nelson, E. L., Campbell, J. M., & Michel, G. F. (2013).
Experience-dependent plasticity in white matter Unimanual to bimanual: Tracking the development of
microstructure: Reasoning training alters structural handedness from 6 to 24 months. Infant Behavior and
connectivity. Frontiers in Neuroanatomy, 6, 32. Development, 36, 181–188.
doi:10.3389/fnana.2012.00032. Nuñez, S. C., Dapretto, M., Katzir, T., Starr, A., Bramen,
MacNeilage, P. F. (2014). Evolution of the strongest ver- J., Kan, E., et al. (2011). fMRI of syntactic processing
tebrate rightward action asymmetries: Marine mam- in typically developing children: Structural correlates
mal sidedness and human handedness. Psychological in the inferior frontal gyrus. Developmental Cognitive
Bulletin, 140, 587–609. Neuroscience, 1, 313–323.
References 199

O’Connor, D. A., Upton, D. J., Moore, J., & Hester, R. motor inhibition: Conjunctive brain activations across
(2014). Motivationally significant self-control: different versions of go/no-go and stop tasks.
Enhanced action withholding involves the right infe- NeuroImage, 13, 250–261.
rior frontal junction. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, Sacrey, L-A., Arnold, B., Whishaw, I. Q., & Gonzales, C. L.
27, 112–123. (2013). Precocious hand use preference in reach-to-eat
Ocklenburg, S., Beste, C., & Güntürkün, O. (2013). behavior versus manual construction in 1- to 5-year-old
Handedness: A neurogenetic shift of perspective. children. Developmental Psychobiology, 55, 902–911.
Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 37, Sainburg, R. L. (2014). Convergent models of handedness
2788–2793. and brain lateralization. Frontiers in Psychology, 5,
Ocklenburg, S., Ness, V., Güntürkün, O., Suchan, B., & 1092. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.01092.
Beste, C. (2013). Response inhibition is modulated by Scharoun, S. M., & Bryden, P. J. (2014). Hand preference,
functional cerebral asymmetries for facial expression performance abilities, and hand selection in children.
perception. Frontiers in Psychology, 4, 879. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 82. doi:10.3389/
doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00879. fpsyg.2014.00082.
Otsuka, Y., Nakato, E., Kanazawas, S., Yamaguchi, M. K., Schmidt, L. A. (1999). Frontal brain electrical activity in
Watanabe, S., & Kakigi, R. (2007). Neural activation shyness and sociability. Psychological Science, 10,
to upright and inverted faces in infants measured by 316–320.
near infrared spectroscopy. NeuroImage, 34, 399–406. Schmidt, L. A., Shahinfar, A., & Fox, N. A. (1996).
Paulus, M., Kühn-Popp, M., Licata, M., Sodian, B., & Regional brain electrical activity (EEG) in toddlers’
Meinhardt, J. (2013). Neural correlates of prosocial externalizing problems. Infant Behavior and
behavior in infancy: Different neurophysiological Development, 19, 75.
mechanisms support the emergence of helping and Serrien, D. J., & Sovijävi-Spapé, M. M. (2013). Cognitive
comforting. NeuroImage, 66, 522–530. control of response inhibition and switching:
Piaget, J. (1941/1952). The child’s conception of number. Hemispheric lateralization and hand preference. Brain
London: Kegan Paul, Trench, & Trubner. and Cognition, 82, 283–290.
Pluess, M., & Belsky, J. (2013). Vantage sensitivity: Shackman, A. J., McMenamin, B. W., Maxwell, J. S.,
Individual differences in response to positive experi- Greischar, L. L., & Davidson, R. J. (2009). Right dor-
ences. Psychological Bulletin, 139, 901–916. solateral prefrontal cortical activity and behavioral
Preslar, J., Kushner, H. I., Marino, L., & Pearce, B. (2014). inhibition. Psychological Science, 20, 1500–1506.
Autism, lateralization, and handedness: A review of Sheridan, M., Kharitonova, M., Martin, R. E., Chatterjee,
the literature and meta-analysis. Laterality, 19, 64–95. A., & Gabrieli, J. D. E. (2014). Neural substrates of
Rat-Fischer, L., O’Regan, J. K., & Fagard, J. (2013). the development of cognitive control in children ages
Handedness in infants’ tool use. Developmental 5–10 years. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 26,
Psychobiology, 55, 860–868. 1840–1850.
Ratnarajah, N., Rifkin-Graboi, A., Fortier, M. V., Chong, Shobe, E. R. (2014). Independent and collaborative con-
Y. S., Kwek, K., Saw, S. M., et al. (2014). Structural tributions of the cerebral hemispheres to emotional
connectivity asymmetry in the neonatal brain. processing. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 8, 230.
NeuroImage, 75, 187–194. doi:10.3389/fnhum.2014.00230.
Reid, C. S., & Serrien, D. J. (2012). Handedness and the Smith, N. A., Gibilisco, C. R., Meisinger, R. E., & Hankey,
excitability of cortical inhibitory circuits. Behavioral M. (2013). Asymmetry in infants’ selective attention
Brain Research, 230, 144–148. to facial features during visual processing of infant-
Reissland, N., Francis, B., Aydin, E., Mason, J., & Exley, directed speech. Frontiers in Psychology, 4, 601.
K. (2014). Development of prenatal lateralization: doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00601.
Evidence from fetal mouth movements. Physiology & Streri, A. (2002). Hand preference in 4-month-old infants:
Behavior, 131, 160–163. Global or local processing of objects in the haptic
Rogers, L. J., Zucca, P., & Vallortigara, G. (2004). mode. Current Psychology Letters, 7, 39–50.
Advantages of having a lateralized brain. Proceedings Streri, A., & de Hevia, M. D. (2015). Manual lateraliza-
of the Royal Society B: Biological Science, 271, tion in infancy. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 1575.
S420–S422. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.01575.
Rönnqvist, L., & Domellöf, E. (2006). Quantitative Streri, A., & Gentaz, E. (2004). Crossmodal recognition
assessment of right and left reaching movements in of shape from hand to eyes and handedness in human
infants: A longitudinal study from 6 to 36 months. newborns. Neuropsychologia, 42, 1365–1369.
Developmental Psychobiology, 48, 444–459. Sun, T., Patoine, C., Abu-Khalil, A., Visvader, J., Sum, E.,
Rosch, R. E., Bishop, D. V., & Badcock, N. A. (2012). Cherry, T. J., et al. (2005). Early asymmetry of gene
Lateralised visual attention is unrelated to language transcription in embryonic human left and right cere-
lateralisation, and not influenced by task difficulty–a bral cortex. Science, 308, 1794–1798.
functional transcranial Doppler study. Talelli, P., Ewas, A., Waddingham, W., Rothwell, J. C., &
Neuropsychologia, 50, 810–815. Ward, N. S. (2008). Neuro correlates of age-related
Rubia, K., Russell, T., Overmeyer, S., Brammer, M. J., changes in cortical neurophysiology. NeuroImage, 40,
Bullmore, E. T., Sharma, T., et al. (2001). Mapping 1772–1781.
200 8 Lateralization and Specialization of the Brain

Turken, A. U., & Dronkers, N. F. (2011). The neural Wechsler, D. (1999). Wechsler Abbreviated Scale of
architecture of the language comprehension network: Intelligence (WASI). San Antonio, TX: The
Converging evidence from lesion and connectivity Psychological Corporation.
analyses. Frontiers in Systems Neuroscience, 5, 1. Wilbourn, M. P., Gottfried, A. W., & Kee, D. W. (2011).
doi:10.3389/fnsys.2011.00001. Consistency of hand-preference across the early years:
Van Dongen, S., Galis, F., Broek, C. T., Heikinheimo, K., Long-term relationship to verbal intelligence and
Wijnaendts, L. C. D., Delen, S., et al. (2014). When reading achievement in girls. Developmental
right differs from left: Human limb directional asym- Psychology, 47, 931–942.
metry emerges during very early development. Wright, L., & Hardie, S. M. (2011). “Not ready to sort it
Laterality, 19, 591–601. yet”: Revised reinforcement sensitivity theory (rRST)
Vauclair, J., & Cochet, H. (2013). Hand preference for predicts left-handed behavioral inhibition during a
pointing and language development in toddlers. manual sorting task. Laterality, 16, 753–767.
Developmental Psychobiology, 55, 757–765. Yaakoby-Rotem, S., & Geva, R. (2014). Asymmetric atten-
Ververs, I. A. P., de Vries, J. I. P., van Geijn, H. P., & tion networks: The case of children. Journal of the
Hopkins, B. (1994). Prenatal head position from 12 to International Neuropsychological Society, 20, 434–443.
38 weeks. 1. Developmental aspects. Early Human Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
Development, 39, 83–91. Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer
Vidal, J., Mills, T., Pang, E. W., & Taylor, M. J. (2012). Science + Business Media.
Response inhibition in adults and teenagers: Young, G., & Gagnon, M. (1990). Neonatal laterality,
Spatiotemporal differences in prefrontal cortex. Brain birth stress, familial sinistrality, and left brain inhibi-
and Cognition, 79, 49–59. tion. Developmental Neuropsychology, 6, 127–150.
Vingerhoets, G., Acke, F., Alderweireldt, A. S., Nys, J., Yu, V. Y., MacDonald, M. J., Oh, A., Hua, G. N., De Nil,
Vandemaele, P., & Achten, E. (2012). Cerebral lateral- L. F., & Pang, E. W. (2014). Age-related sex differ-
ization of praxis in right- and left-handedness: Same ences in language lateralization: A magnetoencepha-
pattern, different strength. Human Brain Mapping, 33, lography study in children. Developmental Psychology,
763–777. 50, 2276–2284.
Wechsler, D. (1997). Wechsler Adult Intelligence Test Zangl, R., & Mills, D. L. (2007). Increased brain activity
administration and scoring manual. San Antonio, TX: to infant-directed speech in 6- and 13-month-old
The Psychological Corporation. infants. Infancy, 11, 31–62.
The Genetics Revolution
9

To conclude the chapter, I refer to the impor-


Chapter Introduction tance of evolvability and versatility.

The area of genetic research is evolving at a diz-


zying speed and differentiating into multiple Introduction
-omics (including genomics and epigenomics).
The search for candidate genes to help explain Genes are expanses on our DNA that regulate
the origins of specific disorders has given way to protein production, leading to the construction of
multifactorial approaches in the genes studied our body and brain. However, genes do not con-
and in the disorders investigated in any one study. struct our mind. Moreover, the environment has
Some of the research methods include GWAS much influence in how our genes regulate the
and GCTA. A central concern in the area is the production of our morphology, including our
“missing heritability” problem, which the chap- brain. Factors such as the newly-discovered epi-
ter addresses for intelligence, in particular. genesis, let alone what we know about early pres-
The classic approach of Nature interacting ent toxins, radiation, and other negative influences
with Nurture, and even the behavioral genetic that affect early brain development, affect the
approach of seeking Gene × Environment (G × E) genetic program so that we are not merely reflec-
interactions, are approaches that are rapidly tions uniquely of its straightforward unfolding.
being replaced by more nuanced ones that are However, both genes and environment are pas-
consistent with the complexity of genetic influ- sive controls in the causality of our behavior and,
ences on behavior. In this regard, to complement as we develop, we can take an increasing active,
the search for the genome, I suggest that behav- agentic role in determining who we are and what
ioral geneticists search for each species their we want to become. Nevertheless, our causality
“phenome,” or the collection of phenotypes lies in the grounding of both our genes and the
characterizing any one species. The relationship environment, and knowledge of their role in our
between the genome and the proposed phenome behavioral causality is important in order to help
for a species will be mapped better as the bur- us find our place as agents beyond them in the
geoning research in the field continues to expand. determination of our behavior.

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 201


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_9
202 9 The Genetics Revolution

Neogenomics and G × E shifts in the field as “neogenetics” or “neogenom-


ics” and not only “postgenomics.” He stated that
Introduction the major implication of this new area involves
the “blurring” between genes and environment.
Boyce and Kobor (2015) indicated that gene–
environment interplay is comprised of at least
three types of processes: Gene × Environment Terms
(G × E) interaction, gene–environment correla-
tion (rGE), and epigenesis. The present chapter Charney (2012) provided some basic definitions
gives the background to delve into these topics. worth noting. Genes are DNA segments that code
Charney (2012) examined behavior genetics for the production of RNA/proteins. Transcription
in the contexts of postgenomics and the paradigm allows for the translation of DNA into messenger
shift that is taking place in genetics. Standard RNA (mRNA) and then proteins. Copies of genes
dogmas in genetics refer to DNA (deoxyribonu- are called alleles, and normally they come in pairs,
cleic acid) as (a) the unchanging template of one maternal and one paternal. Paired alleles
heredity; (b) identical in all cells/tissues; and (c) might be identical or might differ by as little as
the sole agent in inheritance. one nucleotide, with the subunits comprising the
However, contemporary research has estab- DNA molecule. If in the population an allele is
lished that (a) as a template, DNA is subject to rare (less than 1 %), it is considered a mutation.
environmentally-induced change; (b) .somatic Otherwise, it is considered a polymorphism.
mosaicism characterizes cells/tissues (there are When paired alleles are identical, we call them
different genomes in different cells/tissues of the homozygous. Otherwise, they are heterozygous.
individual); and (c) the epigenome can be inherited Mendelian inheritance refers to classic indi-
via the germline, so that DNA is now understood vidual allele inheritance and also to the domi-
as just one and not the only agent of inheritance. nance–recessive relationship that they might
(In this regard, there is extranuclear mitochondrial express in phenotypes. Most psychological traits
DNA maternal, or non-Mendelian, transmission.) are multiallelic or polygenetic in biological ori-
DNA is not fixed or sequenced at the time of gin, and so are not inherited in a classical
conception. Rather, it is dynamic and altered by Mendelian manner (with notable exceptions in
rearrangements, insertions, and deletions. monogenetic disorders).
For example, in embryogenesis, retrotranspo- Heritability is defined as the proportion of
sons, the putative “jumping genes,” duplicate and phenotypic variance that is attributable to geno-
insert themselves in a mobile way within the typic variance in a particular population at a
DNA sequence involved. About the epigenome, given time. [Note it is a population statistic, not
which is the system that regulates gene expres- an individual one, so the total genotypic and non-
sion, and which is “highly environmental respon- genetic variance involved can be additive. In this
sive,” it can turn genes on and off and modify regard, at the individual level, we do not consider
their “transcribability” and heritability, and also that genetic and environmental contributions to
their intergenerational transmission, without the phenotype are additive; rather, we consider
affecting the DNA involved, per se. Because them multiplicative, e.g., Nature × Nurture.]
these new findings about epigenesis indicate that
the phenotypic changes that they induce can be
passed on intergenerationally, the process has Behavior Genetics
been referred to as “Neo-Lamarckian” (e.g.,
Gissis & Jablonka, 2001) but without Lamarck. In behavior genetics, studies typically examine
Charney (2012) addressed the implications of biological twins, adoptees, and families for phe-
these contemporary developments in genetics for notypic concordances and discordances between/
the field of behavior genetics. He referred to the among subjects in relation to their presumed
Neogenomics and G × E 203

degree of genetic similarity/dissimilarity. The several behavior disorders (autism spectrum dis-
commonest modeling technique for VP, the total order, schizophrenia, and ADHD; among others,
phenotypic variation for a trait, partitions it into the former two mentioned have been associated
additive contributions from genetic (genotypic) with mitochondrial DNA, as well).
and environmental variation (VC and VE, respec-
tively). It is acknowledged that the model is a
simplification—there are non-additive genetic Epigenetics
effects, e.g., dominance–recessive interactions
among alleles at a single locus; epistatic interac- Charney (2012) proceeded to discuss the epig-
tions across alleles at a different locus; and gene– enome. He defined epigenetics in terms of heri-
environment interactions between alleles and the table changes that take place without alteration of
environment (G × E). G × E interactions are cen- DNA sequences, e.g., by gene silencing, so that
tral to the study of behavior genetics. Aside from the genes are not transcribed. Epigenetic modifi-
heritability research, the field has proliferated cations can be environmentally contingent,
with gene or GWAS, which investigate whether responding to environmental input. The term
single nucleotide polymorphisms (SNPs) differ “environmental epigenomics” has been created
in individuals with and without a trait of interest. to reflect the constant interplay between the epig-
Charney (2012) continued that germline enome and the environment. Note that the envi-
inheritance concerns genetic information trans- ronment might be exogenous (external) or
mission through sexual reproduction but, in con- endogenous (i.e., internal, e.g., hormonal).
trast, somatic inheritance takes place The most studied epigenetic mechanisms are
postconception when changes in non-gametic DNA methylation, histone modification, and
DNA are passed on via mitosis. The genome expression of non-coding micro RNAs (see
includes up to 50 % of transposable jumping Table 9.1). It is worthwhile to consider Charney’s
genes, most of which are retrotransposons. They (2012) detailed but accessible description of epi-
have a critical influence on the transcriptome, or genetic mechanisms. Nuclear DNA, as opposed
transcription output of the genome. to mitochondrial DNA, wrap around a core of
histone proteins. Their tails or strands wrap
around the DNA molecule. In the process of his-
SNPs and CNVs tone modification, the processes of acetylation,
methylation, and phosphorylation are the primary
DNA variation is marked by SNPs. However, modes in the chemical modifications involved.
structural variations (SVs) increasingly are being They alter the histone structure to either facilitate
given prominence in the literature. They are or inhibit access of the DNA to transcription fac-
changes in the chromosomal architecture due to tors. In DNA methylation, a methyl group is
deletions, insertions, duplications, and inver- added to cystine–guanine (C–G) dinucleotides,
sions, in particular. CNVs are submicroscopic thereby barring transcriptional activity.
“copy number variations.” They consist of at Noncoding (including micro RNA) epigenetic
least 1000 consecutive base pairs in DNA that are modification does not concern transcription, but
either deleted or multiply copied. Many are poly- regulates gene silencing, nonetheless, by binding
morphic, and are referred to as “copy number to messenger RNA post-transcriptionally.
polymorphisms.” Sometimes they consist of mul- Behavioral epigenetic studies have shown that
tiple deletions or copies of whole genes, which epigenetic modifications contribute to abnormal
average up to 60,000 base pairs (CNVs average gene expression in neuropsychiatric disorders,
250,000 base pairs). CNVs constitute a major such as in people with autism and schizophrenia.
force in intraindividual and interindividual varia- As shown by Charney (2012; see Fig. 9.1),
tion and in phylogenetic evolution. CNVs have epigenetic stamps or marks even can lead to acti-
been identified as potential causal elements in vated/silenced genetic/epigenetic differences in
204 9 The Genetics Revolution

Table 9.1 Primary epigenetic modifications and pathways


Mechanism Description
DNA DNA is wrapped around histone proteins for packaging in the nucleus. Methyl groups are added to
methylation cytosines on DNA by way of DNA methyltransferases (DNMTs), and the subsequent binding of
methyl-CpG-binding protein 2 (MeCP2) can either recruit histone deacetylases (HDACs) or other
corepressors to repress transcription or transcription factors like CREB1 to promote transcription
Histone Posttranslational modifications to histone H3 include lysine (K) acetylation and methylation (for
modification clarity, only lysines and their modifications discussed). Histone acetyltransferases (HATs)
facilitate gene activation by adding acetyl groups, which loosen chromatin packaging to allow for
transcription factors to bind. HDACs remove acetyl groups, and therefore repress transcription
and silence a gene. Histone methyltransferases (HMTs) and histone demethylases (HDMs)
catalyze lysine methylation and demethylation, respectively, and their effects on gene transcription
or suppression depend upon which basic residue is targeted and the degree of methylation
MicroRNA The binding of microRNAs (miRNAs) to target mRNA can induce gene silencing. The molecular
processing cascade of events that leads to gene silencing begins with the presence of a primary miRNA
(pri-miRNA) transcript, which is cleaved in the nucleus by a microprocessor complex containing
the Rnase III Drosha and the RNA-binding protein DGCR8 (DiGeorge critical region 8). The
binding of DGCR8 and cleaving action of Drosha in the nucleus are critical in the initiation of
miRNA biogenesis, and malfunction of either of these proteins interferes with the generation of
mature miRNAs. After processing in the nucleus, the immature pre-miRNA is transported to the
cytoplasm via the Exportin-5 (Exp5) pathway, in which the Exp5, in combination with its
cofactor Ran-GTP, binds the pre-miRNA and induces nuclear export. In the cytoplasm, the Rnase
III Dicer cleaves the pre-miRNA into a mature miRNA duplex, and deletion of Dicer decreases
and even eliminates mature and functional miRNAs produced in the cytoplasm. After cleavage
by Dicer, the newly mature miRNA duplex is loaded into an Argonaute (Ago) protein of the
RNA-induced silencing complex (RISC). Once loaded, the RISC binds to the target mRNA,
facilitating gene silencing via mRNA degradation, destabilization, or translational inhibition
Adopted with permission of John Wiley & Sons. Blaze, J., & Roth, T. L. (2013). Epigenetic mechanisms in learning and
memory. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science, 4, 105–115. Copyright © 2013 and John Wiley & Sons,
Inc. Reproduced with permission of John Wiley & Sons, Inc. [Excerpt from Figure 1 Text, Page 107]

monozygotic co-twins. All of the various compo- corticotrophin releasing factor (CRF) promoter
nents of the neogenome—retroposons, CNVs, in the amygdala, and so on.
mitochondrial DNA, epigenetics, and aneuploidy
(i.e., other than the typical diploidy)—indicate
that although it constitutes a distinct class of “her- GWAS
itable agents,” it does not concern specifically
either G (genes) or E (environment) alone, or their Charney (2012) returned to the assumptions under-
G × E interaction. Therefore, heritability studies lying gene association studies, and found them
that seek heritability estimates, G × E interactions, wanting. Because of three factors, in particular,
etc., might not constitute valid approaches. ((a) somatic mosaicism, (b) epigenesis, and (c) a
lack of specific allele-specific protein production
relations), GWAS studies are not as productive as
Programming first hoped. [In this regard, Chabris et al. (2012)
found that most reported genetic associations with
Prenatal programming is an important area of general intelligence (g) were not replicated in data
study in the field. For example, prenatal stress sets taken from three major studies involving
has developmental consequences, and research is almost 10,000 subjects.]
revealing that, in animal models, first-trimester About the latter of the three points, genes in
stress is associated with hypermethylation of the humans might contain several DNA sequences
glucocorticoid receptor (GR) promoter in the coding for amino acids (exons) that are
hypothalamus, with reduced methylation of the interspersed with noncoding regions (introns).
Neogenomics and G × E 205

Timeline Growth Heterogeneity Source

sperm egg

CNVs
Long interspersed
nucleotide element
Germ cells RNA (L1-RNA)
epigenome
microRNAs
aneuploidy
retrotransposition
zygote mtDNA (oocytes)

twin 1 twin 2 CNVs


epigenome
L1-RNA
retrotransposition
mtDNA
Prenatal
aneuploidy

Postnatal epigenome
retrotransposition

Fig. 9.1 Overview of several sources of genetic and epi- develop non-identically in the two twin embryos. Prenatal
genetic heterogeneity between germ cells of the same two environmental inputs that may affect any of these phenom-
individuals and between monozygotic co-twins. Germ ena in the prenatal environment may include maternal
cells: spermatocytes exhibit interindividual variation in stress, anxiety, depression, diet, activity, (prenatal) envi-
L1-RNA, copy number variations (CNVs), epigenetic pro- ronmental toxins, intrauterine position effects, and chorion
files, and microRNAs (miRNAs) (as well as smaller dif- effects. Postnatal environment: intertwin discordance due
ferences in aneuploidy). Oocytes exhibit interindividual to difference epigenomes and differences in ongoing ret-
variation in L1-RNA, CNVs, epigenetic profiles, and miR- rotransposition resulting from neurogenesis in the hippo-
NAs, as well as significant differences in mitochondrial campus. The epigenomes of the twins are depicted as
DNA (mtDNA) and aneuploidy. Environmental inputs being substantially different due to differences in life
influencing germ cell variation may include maternal experiences and environments. Adopted with permission
stress, activity, diet, and environmental toxins. Prenatal of Cambridge University Press. Charney, E. (2012).
environment: splitting of the zygote into two (monozy- Behavior genetics and postgenomics. Behavioral and
gotic twins): CNVs, aneuploidy, mtDNA partitioning and Brain Sciences, 35, 331–410; with kind permission from
heteroplasmy, L1 retrotransposition, and the epigenome Cambridge University Press. [Figure 2, Page 343]

In the process of gene transcription, first, pre- particular gene can potentially code for multiple
messenger RNA is copied. When pre-mRNA rather than one protein, indicating protein diver-
exons combine in different ways to form different sity and molecular plasticity, e.g., in the brain.
proteins, the process is referred to as “alternate Moreover, even monogenetic disorders do not
splicing.” Therefore, as understood now, a single simply express one phenotype, because they
206 9 The Genetics Revolution

are complex traits, although the phenotypic forward loops. The genome is a critical
differences involved do not mean that there are component of this “exceedingly complex, inte-
different diseases involved. grated, interactive, multilevel process,” but not
the only or privileged one.
The environment is essential, too, in the vari-
Phenotypic Plasticity ous -omics in neogenetics. In the postgenomic
perspective, the environment functions as a car-
This example illustrates the prevalence of “phe- rier/transmitter of information at the DNA
notypic plasticity.” Organisms inherit not only sequence in terms of shaping both phenotypes
genes but also ecological niches that optimize and information that can help predict specific
developmental, life-course adaptive (survival phenotypes. Gene expression varies greatly sto-
and reproductive) strategies (Pigliucci, 2010). chastically, and genetic “hyperdiversity” might
Developmental plasticity is fostered by “maternal be the rule that allows an adaptive phenotypic
programming,” as happens in “intergenerationally- hyperdiversity.
transmitted epigenetic modifications.” The Similarly, epigenomic function also is highly
mother is capable of adjusting offspring pheno- stochastic, in that gene promoters can vary
type in response to the environment, transmitting greatly in epigenetic state, to the point that quan-
to them adaptive information, for example, dif- tum mechanical models are being used in the
ferentially expressing one epigenetic pathway to context of probability landscape models of epi-
best match a particular ongoing environmental genetic states. They are considered as stochastic
condition and passing on that information adap- networks that are not simply modeled by compu-
tively to offspring because, normally, the partic- tational approaches. To conclude, Charney
ular environmental condition should continue in (2012) noted that these types of genetic and epi-
the next generation. Parental investment itself genetic stochastic processes might have served
might be compromised in harsh environments, rapid evolution (Feinberg & Irizarry, 2010).
so that instead of high-quality parenting, as
might obtain in supportive environments and
reduced reproduction rate, the adaptive strategy Comment
involved leads to quantitative reproductive strat-
egies, or accelerated mating, which epigeneti- Charney (2012) has provided an essential intro-
cally might be programmed in offspring as per duction to the field of the new area of neoge-
differential life history models (e.g., Ellis, 2004). nomics. It gives the tools for understanding the
basics in gene expression, epigenetics, the
effects of the environment on genes, and
Causality the complex system involved in phenotypic
expression and plasticity. Monogenetic control
In the last section of his informative article, of behavior is rare and does not apply to com-
Charney (2012) considered postgenomics and plex psychological behavior.
causation. There are both bottom-up and top- Chabris, Lee, Cesarini, Benjamin, and Laibson
down influences in biological systems that are (2015) noted that GWAS studies allow for expla-
evident (respectively, related to the molecular nation of the genetics underlying behavior, but
level, and all other levels, from the cellular to the that any behavioral trait associated with genes
organism and environment) (Noble, 2010; does so through many genetic variants.
Shapiro, 2009; Srividhya, Li, & Pomerening, Furthermore, each of them accounts for only a
2011). The influences are reciprocally causal, minimal percentage of the behavioral variability
and pervade the different levels of the hierarchi- involved. Chabris et al. (2015) referred to this
cal system involved through feedback and feed- effect as the fourth law of behavior genetics.
Genetics and Behavior 207

Genetics and Behavior Dopamine Genes

Introduction Berger (2011) examined several dopamine genes


related to self-regulation. The dopamine D4
Berger (2011) provided a tutorial on genetics. receptor (DRD4 gene) is located on chromosome
DNA is a molecule that includes genes, which are 11 at 11p15. Dopamine constitutes an important
DNA portions that code for the production of neurotransmitter. The DRD4 polymorphism most
protein (after transcription). Codons are trinucle- studied is in exon III, in which the base pair
otide units that genetically code for an amino sequence represents a VNTR, and for which the
acid; amino acids are constituents of proteins. most frequent allelic variations are the 4-repeat
The nucleotides in a codon consist of guanine, and the 7-repeat alleles. The polymorphism is
adenine, thymine, and cytosine (G, A, T, C). involved in dopamine receptor function.
DNA consists of a chain of paired molecules that The 7-repeat allele has been associated with
typically take the form of a double-stranded particular behavioral tendencies related to self-
helix. G, A, T, and C form the bases of the strands regulation from early after birth onward. In par-
and are paired in exclusive complementary ticular, studies of diverse selected and executive
pairs—A–T and C–G. The particular sequence of attention skills have shown an association in self-
bases along DNA strands provides the code for regulation and the DRD4 7-repeat allele (e.g.,
transcribing particular proteins. In transcription/ Posner, Rothbart, & Sheese, 2007; using the
translation, DNA leads to the synthesis of mes- Attention Network Task, ANT). The allele also
senger ribonucleic acid (mRNA), which leads to has been associated with disorganized attach-
the production of polypeptides and proteins. The ment, and especially in conjunction with the
coding region of a gene begins with the initiation −521 C/T polymorphism in the regulatory region
codon (usually ATG) and ends with a termination of the gene (Lakatos et al., 2000, 2002).
codon (TAA, TAG, or TGA). Another dopamine gene related to self-
Human DNA consists of 23 pairs of chromo- regulation via attention is catechol-O-
somes, 22 of which are autosomes and one pair of methyltransferase (COMT). It codes in the
which is constituted by the sex chromosomes X process of clearing dopamine from extracellular
and Y. A chromosome has a central centromere and space after the release of this neurotransmitter
four arms—the short pair is designated p and the into synaptic space. The COMT enzyme involved
long arm q. The genes’ cytogenetic location on the appears to work especially in the prefrontal cor-
arms refers to the band it occupies on an arm. In the tex (PFC). Its location is in 22q11. A variation in
standardized format for representing genes, the the G/A base pair at codon 158 of the gene allows
first alphanumeric code indicates the chromosome dopamine to stay longer in extracellular space,
number involved, the second indicates the arm, and especially in the PFC, and another, the valine
the third and fourth indicate the specific position on allele, has been associated with effects on atten-
the arm, that is, designating a region and the tion (positive and negative, respectively).
band itself, with increased numbering indicating Another dopamine gene for which variants
increased distance from the centromere involved have been related to self-regulation is the DAT1;
(e.g., 7q21). There might be a decimal place and it codes for the dopamine transporter. The risk
more digits if there is a sub-band involved. allele involved is 480-bp (also called 10R), a
[As mentioned previously, typically, genes are VNTR at 5p15.3. The gene is expressed espe-
divided into exon and intron regions, with only cially in the basal ganglia.
the former found in mRNA transcripts. Genes Finally, the monoamine oxidase (MAOA) gene is
vary in form, consisting of different alleles. located on chromosome X at Xp11. It codes for
Variation is determined by a number of factors, enzymes involved in catalyzation of biogenic
including the number of repetitions (variable amines, including dopamine, serotonin, and another
number of random repeats, VNTR).] neurotransmitter, norepinephrine. Research has
208 9 The Genetics Revolution

specified several MAOA polymorphisms involved The dynamic attentional model is consistent
in attention (e.g., C vs. T; 4-repeat length polymor- with the one of Johnson et al. (2005) of interac-
phism in MAOA promoter region (LPR), vs. tive specialization. In the latter model, the envi-
3-repeat). ronment facilitates brain development through
person–environment interactions. Brain regions
supportive of the behavior involved continually
G×G mature in these interactions along with the rele-
vant interregional connections (through their
Gene–gene (G × G) interactions are also impor- reorganization). This point of view contrasts with
tant to consider in self-regulation. Berger (2011) the traditional one in which developing behav-
specified that interactions involving the serotonin ioral function is mapped onto developing brain
transporter gene (5-HTT) and different dopamine structure.
genes affect self-regulation related behavior. In Consistent with Berger (2011), who referred
particular, the allelic variation involved is to the importance of attentional mechanisms,
5-HTTLPR, which could be short (s) or long (l). Posner, Rothbart, Sheese, and Voelker (2012)
It is a repetition in the promoter regulatory region provided evidence for a neural control network in
of the gene. Schmidt, Fox, and Hamer (2007) early development related to attentional pro-
reported that 7-year-olds scoring higher on a cesses. In particular, they highlighted an infant
checklist that measures internalizing and exter- brain network underlying attentional orienting to
nalizing behavior had long DRD4 alleles and one sensory events, and including areas of the supe-
or more risk 5-HTT alleles. rior and inferior parietal lobe and also the frontal
eye fields. The proposed network “provides the
chief means” of infant self-regulation. The net-
G×E work appears moderated by the nicotinic cholin-
ergic system based in the nucleus basalis.
Moreover, G × E interactions are ones that are rel- With development, by 3–4 years of age, the
evant to understanding self-regulation. executive network takes over in control and other
Bakermans-Kranenburg and van IJzendoorn neuromodulators are involved. Specifically, exec-
(2006) and Sheese, Voelker, Rothbart, and Posner utive attentional control of cognition and emotion
(2007) found that externalizing/temperament in self-regulation becomes focused in the brain
(sensation seeking) in children was affected by network that includes areas of the anterior cingu-
maternal sensitivity/parenting quality and also late gyrus, anterior insula, and basal ganglia, as
the presence of the 7-repeat allele of DRD4. well as parts of the PFC and connections of the
Other G × E interactions have been shown for network to more remote brain areas. The execu-
MAOA (Caspi et al., 2002) and 5-HTT (Caspi tive attention network is neuromodulated primar-
et al., 2003; Fox et al., 2005). ily by the dopaminergic system based in the
ventral tegmental area.
A third network is involved in attention, the
Attention and Genes alerting network. It is modulated by the norepi-
nephrine system. The orienting network is related
Ristic and Enns (2015) promoted a dynamic view to the frontoparietal network. The executive net-
of attention in development, in that it is taken to work shares brain regions with the cingulo-
both influence and be influenced by interactions opercular network according to resting state
between the individual and environment. fMRI studies (functional magnetic resonance
Attention mediates between environment and imaging; Fair, Dosenbach, Petersen, & Schlagger,
behavior by influencing and being influenced by 2012; Gao et al., 2009). Intranetwork connectiv-
sensory cues and by the person, factors that ity is sparse in the neonate and rapidly expands
include goals and consciousness, respectively. by 2 years of age, and later.
Genetics and Behavior 209

The authors discussed genetic underpinnings Hariri (2013) examined dopamine-related genes
to the executive control system. They concern the in terms of reward processing from a neuroge-
DRD4 gene and the COMT gene for the dopa- netic or a genetic/neuroimaging approach.
mine system and the CHRNA4 (cholinergic Reward processing refers to collecting, storing,
receptor, nicotinic, alpha 4) gene for the choliner- and utilizing information about the appetitive
gic modulation. These links are not exclusive, value of stimuli to promote survival and well-
and also environmental (parental) practices are being. The brain regions involved form a distrib-
involved according to the research (e.g., in the uted mesocorticostriatal circuitry critically
positive sense, perhaps by parents presenting regulated by dopamine, which is a neurotransmit-
objects and reading to young infants). The ter functioning as a mediator in the system. They
research undertaken by Posner et al. (2012) sup- described the dopamine signaling and metabolic
ported the notion of transition in attentional con- activity of various polymorphisms that differen-
trol networks early in life. Relevant longitudinal tially affect areas of the reward processing neural
correlations on the measures used were found circuitry (see Fig. 9.2).
across the ages of 6–7 months and 4 years.

Comment
Reward and Genes
Much of the remaining section of this portion of
Berger (2011) had focused on genes regulating the chapter on genetics takes the same approach as
neurotransmitters in terms of attention. Others Berger (2011) on the genetics of behavior.
relate them to more downstream processes, such The research in the area is booming. As I describe
as reward. For example, Nikolova, Bogdan, and the empirical literature, often I repeat for the reader

Presynaptic
ventral
tegmental area
D2S
(VTA)
dopaminergic DAT
neuron

D4

Soma
Postsynaptic
D2L striatal target
L-tyrosine
neuron
COMT
HVA MAOA

D1
D4

DAT

Fig. 9.2 Schematic representation of a dopaminergic D4, dopamine receptors; D2L, dopamine D2 receptor long
synapse and the genes involved. The figure illustrates the (postsynaptic) isoform; D2S, dopamine D2 receptor short
multiple genes involved in the functioning of the dopa- (presynaptic) isoform; DAT, dopamine transporter; HVA,
mine neurotransmitter at the level of interneuronal syn- homovanillic acid; MAOA, monoamine oxidase
apses. COMT, catechol-O-methyltransferase; D1, D2, D3, A. Adapted from Nikolova, Bogdan, and Hariri (2013)
210 9 The Genetics Revolution

that full name of the genes involved and their nor- (ASC), specifically related to social behavior.
mative effects, before getting to either interactions According to the neuroimaging research, the dor-
with the environment, the behavioral difficulties somedial prefrontal cortex (dMPFC) appears
with which they might be associated, and so on. hypoactivated during theory of mind tasks in
ASC. As well, other areas show similar hypoacti-
vation in ASC social cognition and they comprise
Applications a complex neural circuit, including the ventral
MPFC (vMPFC). Another circuit appears
Introduction affected in ASC for face processing (e.g., includ-
ing the amygdala). For the authors, the circuits
This section of the present work contrasts (a) reflect neural endophenotypes in ASC that index
search for particular genes associated with par- specific social impairments, with the vMPFC
ticular psychiatric conditions with (b) search for serving as a hub. Because of the hypoactivations
multiple genes implicated in multiple conditions. discovered, other regions might compensate with
The two approaches in genomic research should hyperactivations (e.g., involved in nonsocial cog-
be considered complementary. nitive strategies).
As for the gene polymorphisms associated
with neuroimaging results related to facial pro-
ADHD cessing circuitry in ASC, they include the sero-
tonin transporter gene (SLC6A4), the arginine
The work on neural endophenotypes is bringing vasopressin receptor 1A gene (AVPR1A), and the
psychiatry closer to a genetically-mediated neuro- cannabinoid receptor, type 1 gene (CNR1).
chemical and neuroanatomical basis for under- Chakrabarti et al. (2009) studied genetic asso-
standing psychiatric conditions. del Campo, ciations related to empathy in Asperger’s syn-
Müller, and Sahakian (2012) focused on neuroim- drome, and 27 genes were discerned, falling into
aging techniques in studies of ADHD. These three classes: (a) social emotional responsivity
measures provide data on ADHD that is more related, i.e., genes coding for oxytocin and its
proximal to the susceptibility genes that might receptor (OXT, OXTR); (b) neural growth and
underpin the disorder. The two gene loci most connectivity; and (c) sex steroid related. Given
associated with ADHD are the dopamine (DA) the deficits in social cognition in ASC, these
receptor type 4 (DRD4) and the DA transporter genetic underpinnings to facial processing and
gene (DAT1) (e.g., Brookes et al., 2006). The neu- empathy underscore its downstream, genetic
ral circuitry often associated with ADHD involves base, and also its upstream neuroendophenotypic
(a) the distributed fronto-striato-cerebellar cir- (intermediary to phenotypic expression) base.
cuits, which are implicated in top-down cognitive Although the search for specific gene loci
control processes, and (b) the meso-cortico-limbic associated with specific disorders continues, oth-
network, which appears to underlie motivational ers are taking a wider perspective. They seek
processes. These circuits are neuromodulated by multiple genes that might be simultaneously
catecholamines. Research is showing that, in associated with multiple disorders.
adult ADHD, there appears to be decreased DAT
as well as D2/D3 receptor availability in select sub-
cortical regions of the left hemisphere. Missing Heritability

Methodology Explains
ASC
Manuck and McCaffery (2014) noted that,
Lombardo, Baron-Cohen, Belmonte, and despite much research on genetic variants in rela-
Chakrabarti (2011) examined possible neural tion to behavioral phenotypes, only a small por-
endophenotypes in autism spectrum conditions tion of its heritable variation has been accounted
Missing Heritability 211

for (the missing heritability problem, as men- (GCTA) has been applied to schizophrenia
tioned). One plausible explanation of the missing (Visscher, Goddard, Derks, & Wray, 2012), major
heritability problem lies in G × E interaction depression (Lubke et al., 2012), intelligence
effects. Heritability estimates reflect the propor- (Chabris et al., 2012), and personality traits (e.g.,
tion of phenotypic variation attributable to indi- Verweij et al., 2012). Respectively, the genetic
vidual genetic differences in a population variation estimated in the research explained up to
(specific in time and (range of) environment). 40 % of the variance in schizophrenia, 30 % in
Behavioral genetics uses linkage analysis to depression, 50 % in intelligence, and 12 % in per-
study gene–effect relations. It seeks variants in sonality. These percentages are approaching the
DNA sequence (potential markers) found in asso- heritability estimates associated with the behav-
ciation with disease/disorder in pedigreed families iors/conditions.
having both affected and unaffected members. The Despite these improved results, there are still
method is limited in detecting variants with other confounds in this type of research. For example,
than large effects. Diseases/disorders might involve G × E interaction effects could “dilute” genetic
multiple genetic variants each with small effects. main effects. G × E interaction involves genotype-
In the candidate gene method of study in dependent variation in phenotypic reaction to
molecular genetics, specific target genes consid- variations in conditions in the environment. The
ered associated with the disease/disorder can be problem might not be with missing heritability
studied outside of pedigreed families. Usually, in but with missing the right questions to ask—main
behavioral research, the genes relate to compo- effect questions related to heritability, by defini-
nents of neurotransmission, neuroendocrine tion, do not account for G by E interactions.
function, or other cellular processes in the path-
way to disease/disorder. Either known allelic
variants of gene polymorphisms or multiple Hypercomplexity Explains
polymorphisms are studied within the same gene
(haplotypes). However, many candidate genes in Introduction Richardson (2013) explored the
putative relations with disease/disorder might be possible reasons for “missing heritability”in rela-
published with much fanfare, but they do not tion to intelligence research. In behavior genet-
stand up to replication research. ics, for intelligence, the “missing heritability”
GWAS uses probe for SNPs tagging common problem has remained intractable.
genetic variation. It can detect small genetic The heritability findings for intelligence based
effects, but only with very large samples. GWAS on twin studies and standard statistics (analysis
research is often replicated well. GWAS that looks of variance) suggest that over 50 % of normal
at common genetic contributions to major dis- variation in intelligence in the population can
eases/disorders (studied simultaneously) have be attributed to genetic factors. Nevertheless,
accounted for up to 6 % of the variance in behavior the search for the genetic substrate for the herita-
disorders (Smoller, Kendler, & Craddock, 2013). bility of intelligence has been elusive, and
However, twin studies often find results with Richardson (2013) suggested heritability has
up to 50 % of individual differences in behavioral been eclipsed.
traits accounted for by genetic influences (but GWAS have sought variations in specific gene
without being specific about the polymorphisms alleles and related variations in measure of intel-
involved). This gap between the percentage of ligence, or IQ (intelligent quotient) scores. In
heritable differences explained by family research GWAS, DNA is scanned at the level of SNPs. But
and GWAS research (the “missing heritability” despite early promise and hopes, molecular
problem) needs better research and explication. genetics has failed to identify reliably genetic
That said, research is reducing the missing underpinning that could explain the high herita-
component in the knowledge about heritability for bility estimates for variation in IQ scores (Davis
mental disease/disorder. For example, the tech- et al., 2010; Deary, Penke, & Johnson, 2010;
nique of “genomewide complex trait analysis” Turkheimer, 2011).
212 9 The Genetics Revolution

Standard explanations for the missing herita- and cooperative, so that phenotypic variation
bility problem concern (a) the large number of might appear to be majorly genetic in origin but
genetic loci that must underly the noted varia- “really is environmental” (e.g., Bell, Tiwari,
tions, and also (b) the resultant massive research Thomä, & Schübeler, 2012; Feil & Fraga, 2012).
undertaken required to detect their cumulative These epigenetic and related processes lead to
effects (Plomin & Davis, 2009). However, expla- continuous “rewiring” of the network of genes as
nations also range into ones that the high herita- they respond to environmental change. New gene
bilities involved are “phantom” and do not exist, expressions are created allowing new adaptabili-
e.g., are artifacts of twin studies or the approach ties. The intensity, speed, and novelty of the mul-
in genetics to the matter (Zuk, Hechter, Sunyaeva, tiple processes involved in this cross-talk of
& Lander, 2012). multiple “-omic” levels (genomic, epigenomic,
Richardson (2013) invoked the notion that the transcriptomic, etc.) are “unlikely” to be the
search for “missing heritability” in IQ research products of linear deterministic processes. Rather,
might be misplaced because of new approaches cells are maintained in “far-from-equilibrium”
to understanding genetics, environment, and states in which nonlinear dynamics in molecular
intelligence. In each case, the systems involved networks create “criticality,” or edge-of-change
are considered complex and interdependent, with movements, that might cascade into novel states
independent agency residing in neither genes nor in response to even minor perturbations.
environment. Richardson (2013) concluded that this logic of
metabolism extends into the different develop-
Biointelligence Indeed, at the molecular level, mental levels of the organism. Therefore,
Richardson (2013) referred to a “biointelligence.” self-organized system conceptualizations are
For example, cells in multicellular organisms suggesting “radical” changes in understanding
encounter “storms” of signals from other cells nature, genes, and phenotypic variation.
and constantly adapt. Richardson termed the Offspring inherit not autonomous gene command
environment as providing “structure in experi- centers but whole dynamic, emergent develop-
ence” or “information in structure” even at the mental systems.
cellular level, thereby providing “structure-for- With respect to the question of “missing heri-
predictability” in complex environments. Cells tability,” its traditional conceptualization leads to
negotiate their environments by abstracting it being “hidden.” In dynamic, biointelligence
underlying patterns and self-organizing ongoing conceptions of cells, genes, and environment (as
states based on them. Remarkably, Richardson well as in upper levels in the network of relevant
(2013) described cells as exhibiting “emergent” systems, such as in nervous systems), traditional
properties, such as highly-processed novel signal accounts of heritability do not apply, and for the
integration, feedback loops, and metabolic and best of evolutionary reasons.
developmental pathways (Hlavecek & Faeder, Physiological systems are now described as
2009; López-Maury, Marguerat, & Bähler, 2008). “homeodynamic” rather than homeostatic (Yates,
Richardson (2013) continued that cells respond 2008). At one level, nervous systems are com-
to these signals through pathways involving genes, prised of emergent networks that modulate cell
but not as independent agents or predetermined activity in the context of environmental informa-
codes/commands. The traditional model of gene tion. Animals respond not to external stimuli but
transcription—having a complementary RNA to activity patterns within relevant brain struc-
copy of the relevant strand of DNA functioning as tures that they engender, as created by emergent,
a messenger template in protein production—no intelligent, nonlinear dynamics (see Freeman,
longer applies. Rather, the transcription process 2000; who used mice olfactory bulb responsive-
can be radically altered by the environment, as ness as an example).
happens through epigenetics. The process is As for cognitive intelligence, for Richardson
highly fluid and dynamic, and is multi-regulatory (2013), it is also emergent and self-organized,
Missing Heritability 213

being generated from its own activity. Piaget cannot be explained causally in either individual
(1988) referred to this process as “reflective genes or environments (in the same way that geo-
abstraction.” Artificial neural networks (ANNs) graphical planetary plate tectonics cannot be
demonstrate the same properties (e.g., Ciszac, explained in properties of individual rocks).
Montina, & Arecchi, 2009; Hollis, Kloos, & Van The work by Richardson (2013) on the miss-
Orden, 2009). Network ensembles are activated ing heritability problem illustrates the fast-
and yoked together, demonstrating emergent changing landscape in the study of genetics in
properties, including hierarchically-organized, behavior. The issue is not only whether the search
progressively developing (toward increased for specific gene—specific outcome—is appro-
abstraction) “attractor” states. According to priate compared to broader searches, including
Richardson (2010, 2013), this cognitive differen- pleiotropy, but just how central is the question of
tiation and lifelong development in cognitive direct genetic influences on behavior either way.
speed, efficacy, and creativity in responding Although, the work of Richardson suggests that
allow organisms to better predict, to anticipate, the missing heritability problem is artifactual,
and to even “make” the future, a concept that is novel genetic approaches are suggesting
similar to Seligman, Railton, Baumeister, and otherwise.
Sripada’s (2013) one of “prospection.”
Richardson (2013) next examined evolution
and culture in his work on the foundations of GCTA Resolves
intelligence. The emergent, self-organized, and
dynamical cognitive systems that could develop Introduction Plomin, Haworth, et al. (2013)
have fueled evolutionary change in an evolution- addressed the “missing heritability” problem
ary spiral co-activated by the social cooperativity through empirical investigation. Their research
enabled by the intelligence (and the underlying has moved the field toward resolving the prob-
larger network capacity and brains). The social lem. Moreover, they based their study on a novel
cooperativity involved needed refined attentions genome-wide approach consistent with the much
and actions, which could only be achieved used but often criticized GWAS approach. As
through interindividual “epicognitive” regulation mentioned, the missing heritability problem
(e.g., as in language, tools, rules) or culture. As refers to the disjoint in the behavioral genetic
dynamical brains interact, they too can form research that twin and adoption studies have
emerging hierarchies of nested attractors that shown that heritability estimate for general cog-
manifest reflective abstraction. Through socio- nitive ability is about 0.50, or substantial (Plomin,
economic processes such as this, which includes DeFries, Knopik, & Neiderhiser, 2013), yet
the scientific enterprise, humans have gone GWAS investigations have not yet found the
beyond an intelligence of adapting to the envi- genetic variants that might account for the herita-
ronment to one of adapting the environment to bility (Davies et al., 2011). Plomin, Haworth,
themselves. [I would add that both adaptive et al. (2013) noted that GWAS have investigated
aspects are involved in each of individual and associations without much success perhaps
group intelligent environmental adaptation.] because the typical study excludes rare DNA
variants among the SNPs typically researched.
Conclusion In Richardson (2013), Turkheimer Plomin, Haworth, et al. (2013) addressed the
(2011) is given the last word. He argued that problem of missing heritability by using a new
“complex human behavior emerges out of a hyper- method that is population- rather than family-
complex developmental network” (p. 600). Genes based. In GCTA, all the SNPs genotyped in a
and environment constitute inputs to the system. sample can be used, not just those from
They have no direct “causal effects,” in that any genetically-related individuals (twins, families, or
are “lost” in the hypercomplex developmental net- adoptees). Therefore, to estimate the genetic vari-
work. Complex differences in human behavior ance of these individuals, whose genetic similarity
214 9 The Genetics Revolution

might range only from 0.00 to 0.02, SNPs are traits, but does not approach 100 %, as found in
compared pair-wise to decipher phenotypic simi- more physical and physiological traits (e.g.,
larity for each pair of individuals in a sample Mash & Wolfe, 2015). As workers in the field
based on their total SNP similarity. emphasize, this leaves ample room for under-
standing phenotypic expression as an interaction
Evidence The GCTA investigation of the of genetic and environmental influences.
genetic variants that might account for heritabil-
ity of cognitive abilities conducted by Plomin,
Haworth, et al. (2013) was based on over 3000 Commonalities and Pleiotropy
12-year-old co-twins. The methods included in Psychopathology
measures of language (verbal, nonverbal) and
general intelligence. The variants investigated Explanation
were common only, not rare. Note that the nature
of the GCTA method does not allow for identifi- Introduction The Psychiatric Genomics
cation of which SNPs might contribute to the Consortium, which has the largest psychiatric
total heritability estimate captured by DNA GWAS data set currently available, studied the
markers. genetic relatedness of five major psychiatric dis-
The results showed that tagged DNA markers orders (Cross-Disorder Group of the Psychiatric
accounted for, on average, 0.66 of the estimated Genomics Consortium, 2013). This psychiatric
twin heritability, or that common genetic variants genomics consortium headed by Smoller, Kendler,
can account for two thirds of the putative missing et al. (2013) studied risk loci, or specific allelic
heritability in cognitive ability, with the results variants on genes having or underlying shared
for general cognitive ability being the highest genetic effects, on ASD, ADHD, bipolar disorder,
(although all were significant). major depressive disorder, and schizophrenia.
These five major psychiatric disorders (child and
Conclusion The authors concluded that GCTA adult onset) have been studied singly and in vari-
provides a powerful technique in genome–behav- ous combinations for risk loci, but never together
ior association research because, in terms of until this GWAS (Cross-Disorder Group of the
genetic influences, it is much harder to dispute Psychiatric Genomics Consortium, 2013).
evidence that is DNA-based relative to findings
from twin and adoption studies. They argued that Evidence The consortium calculated the esti-
the GCTA method could “mark the beginning of mate of the total variance in liability for disorder
the end of the nature-nurture controversy” about explained together by common genetic polymor-
a role for genetics in cognitive ability, although phisms (such as SNPs) for the disorders. The
the specific SNPs and nucleotides involved authors analyzed genome-wide genotype data
require further research. from the Consortium database both for cases and
I would add that the amount of variance controls. The consortium analyzed SNPs in over
explained by any one collection of SNPs in the 60,000 cases and controls, mostly of European
overall variance explanation attributable to genet- ancestry. The methods included search for allelic
ics is bound to be moderate, even if significant. effects of each disorder and cross-disorder effects.
The approach taken by Plomin, Haworth, et al. The results of the study revealed that the
(2013) might be the way to salvage not only the genetic contribution of common SNPs to the five
concept of missing heritability but also the funda- major psychiatric disorder studied is important.
mental assumptions of behavioral genetics, in SNPs “explained” 17–29 % of the variance in
particular. In this regard, it is worth noting that in liability for disorder. Four SNPs met criteria for
twin concordance studies, the rate usually is cross-disorder effects on multiple or all disor-
moderate or perhaps high for behavioral pheno- ders, and they especially involved ones in
types, including for intelligence and personality voltage-gated calcium-channel signaling.
Commonalities and Pleiotropy in Psychopathology 215

Specifically, for four of the five disorders stud- help explain the frequent comorbidities in use of
ied, cut-off was exceeded for genome-wide sig- traditional nosology and also inform valid
nificance in the primary (e.g., fixed-effects) approaches to psychopharmacological treatment.
meta-analysis. The common risk loci involved In this regard, for the authors, as in other med-
SNPs at regions on chromosomes 3p21 and ical fields, there might be broad pleiotropy of
10q24 andSNPs in two L-type voltage-gated genetic risk factors cutting across descriptive
calcium-channel subunits—CACNA1C and DSM boundaries and also the vulnerabilities of
CACNB2, introns of brain-expressed genes. The the disorders. The results speak to a shared
CACNA1C polymorphism has been termed a genetic etiology and pathophysiology underlying
“susceptibility gene,” in that its variants have these disorders. Further, the mechanism at work
effects on a range of structural and functional in broad risk pleiotropy might relate to gene loci
brain genotypes, e.g., circuitry involved in emo- involved in brain-located calcium-channel activ-
tions, executive function, attention, and memory. ity, in general, and its alterations.
Aside from genetic research calling into ques-
Conclusion The authors concluded that genetic tion the splitting of psychiatric disorder in sepa-
risk factors are shared among the major neuro- rate categories that might not have validity
psychiatric disorders studied, having broad phe- because of lacunae in addressing their etiology,
notypic effects, or pleiotropic effects, on at least other research is arriving at the same conclusions
two of the five disorders studied. There appears using symptom clustering techniques. For exam-
to be a sharing of genetic risk across key psychi- ple, as shown next, there might be a common p
atric disorders, as found in the study, and with (psychopathology) factor to multiple disorders.
results uncontaminated by environment because
of the distant genetic relatedness among individ-
uals in the sample studied. General p Factor
Individual and aggregate molecular genetic
risk factors were shown to be shared among the Introduction Caspi et al. (2014) conducted a
five common psychiatric disorders studied even revealing study of psychopathology that calls
though they are treated separately in psychiatric into question the standard paradigm that the field
diagnostic systems. Psychiatric nosology needs should focus on individual disorders or psychiat-
to move beyond diagnostic categories that are ric categories. In intelligence research, not only
descriptive to a classification system informed by are specific ability factors found (e.g., verbal,
causation of conditions. visuospatial, working memory, processing speed)
The authors maintained that diagnostic manu- but also a general g factor emerges (Deary, 2001).
als, such as those of the DSM-5 (Diagnostic Similarly, Caspi et al. (2014) asked the provoca-
Statistical Manual of Mental Disorder, Fifth tive question whether their results support the
Edition; American Psychiatric Association, existence of a general p factor of psychopathol-
2013) and the upcoming ICD-11 (International ogy in the structure of psychiatric disorders,
Classification of Diseases, 11th Edition; World indicative of a common etiological (developmen-
Health Organization, 2017), need to move beyond tal) pathway to disorders.
constructing syndromes descriptively toward a
classification system informed by etiology. By Evidence Caspi et al. (2014) tested participants
seeking shared cause at a molecular level, the in the Dunedin Multidisciplinary Health and
task of describing psychiatric disorder and deter- Development Study (N = 1037 to begin, with 95 %
mining cause is facilitated. Some loci will evi- tested of the 1007 participants still alive in the last
dence diagnostic specificity but others a more wave). Assessments took place at ages 3, 5, 7, 9,
common thread, with both individual and aggre- 11, 13, 15, 18, 21, 26, 32, and 38. Mental disor-
gate molecular genetic risk factors involved. The ders were investigated longitudinally over 20
widespread pleiotropy that seems involved could years from adolescence onward. To accomplish
216 9 The Genetics Revolution

this, interviews were included in the assessment, “single unitary cause.” There should be a pleio-
and they asked about past-year psychopathology. tropic genetic liability involved. That genetic
Gaps were queried using a life history calendar. variants have been found to be linked to multiple
The interviews included the Diagnostic Interview diagnoses fits this conjecture (Smoller, Craddock,
Schedule (Robins, Cottler, Bucholz, & Compton, et al., 2013; also Cross-Disorder Group of the
1995) in the last five waves. Prevalence rates for Psychiatric Genomics Consortium, 2013).
the disorders investigated (common ones, 11 dis- Caspi et al. (2014) examined the implications
orders or clusters) that were found in this research of their findings for understanding causality of
study were similar to those in the extant literature. single disorders. These would seem difficult to
Caspi et al. (2014) reviewed the literature on identify. Not only are disorders often comorbid but
factor structure of psychopathology and different also they share common risk factors and corre-
models have been proposed. The literature sup- lates. The authors’ results suggest that the attempt
ports a two-factor structure to common mental to find biomarkers, genetic underpinnings, and
disorders—internalizing and externalizing (e.g., distinct cause in single disorders is misplaced.
for children, young adults, and adults, respec- Other research is consistent with the approach
tively, Achenbach & Edelbrock, 1981; Forbush & of Caspi et al. (2014) toward the existence of a
Watson, 2013; Krueger, Caspi, Moffitt, & Silva, general psychopathological factor. I note that the
1998). Other research adds a third factor of authors discussed the etiology or causality of
thought disorder. Lahey et al. (2012) proposed psychopathology in these terms and the import of
that mental disorders might reflect one common their findings for psychiatric classification and its
underlying factor, in addition to internalizing and general splitting rather than lumping approach to
externalizing ones. mental disorder.
Caspi et al. (2014) used confirmatory factor
analysis to test the various multiple, bi-, and uni-
factor approaches to symptom structure. They Generalist Genes
used multitrait-multimethod models, seeking sig-
nificant polychoric correlations. Their three- Introduction Rhee, Lahey, and Waldman
factor model fits the data well, and its (2014) reviewed the literature showing signifi-
intercorrelations were all positive. Their bifactor cant common genetic influences in all psychiatric
model had to be adjusted, however, but ended up disorders but, in contrast, nonshared environ-
fitting the data, as well, and slightly more parsi- mental influences on specific disorders (Cosgrove
moniously. Further analyses suggested that the p et al., 2011; Lahey, Van Hulle, Singh, Waldman,
factor model fits well the data, but that the inter- & Rathouz, 2011). The results support the “gen-
nalizing and externalizing dimensions added eralist gene and specialist environments” model
information beyond p. However, all three indi- of psychopathology (Eley, 1997; Kendler et al.,
vidual factors were highly correlated with p. Also, 2011). The common underlying feature to psy-
higher p scores were associated with relevant risk chopathology might be a pervasive disposition
factors related to life impairment, familiarity, toward experiencing unpleasant affective state
developmental history, and early brain function. (Lilienfeld, 2003) or negative emotionality/neu-
roticism (Lahey & Waldman, 2003).
Conclusion Caspi et al. (2014) interpreted their
range of findings as supportive of a general p fac- Evidence Rhee et al. (2014) noted that studies
tor in psychopathology. The existence of a gen- have found common genetic influences involving
eral psychopathology factor in the structure of neuroticism and externalizing/internalizing disor-
mental disorder suggests a general risk to develop ders and related aspects, e.g., negative emotional-
“any and all forms” of common mental disorders. ity and externalizing behavior (Kendler, Gardner,
The p dimension seems to lie in “neurological Gatz, & Pedersen, 2007; Taylor, Allan,
roots,” or in dynamic developmental processes. Mikolajewski, & Hart, 2013, respectively). Twin
It suggests that all disorders are “united,” with a studies have indicated that negative emotionality/
Child Genomics 217

neuroticism is a heritable common feature under- cess in finding such associations is rare, but one
lying the overlap between internalizing and exter- attempt that has succeeded relates to speech and
nalizing disorders in children (Hink et al., 2013; language disorder. Nudel and Newbury (2013)
Mikolajewski, Allan, Hart, Lonigan, & Taylor, have reviewed the forkhead box P2 gene (FOXP2)
2013; Tackett et al., 2013). Other studies have in relation to the disorder. The FOXP2 gene func-
revealed that SNPs help explain a significant pro- tions as a transcription factor that “represses the
portion of variance for disorders (internalizing, expression of neural targets,” especially in brain
externalizing) and for neuroticism, which relate circuits involved in vocal learning/communica-
to them (respectively, Lubke et al., 2012; tion. The gene was found originally in one human
Vinkhuyzen et al., 2012; Vrieze et al., 2014). family. It should not be confused with the genetic
array found in specific language impairment,
Conclusion The authors concluded that a hier- which is polygenetic, not monogenetic.
archical model fits the data (Lahey et al., 2011).
That is, some genes influence risk, generally, for
psychopathology, and others are specific to cer- Comment
tain dimensions.
Similarly, Chow, Ho, Wong, Waye, and The Smoller–Kendler–Craddock research, the
Bishop (2013) studied nonverbal, cognitive, lan- Caspi team study, and others’ work is important
guage, and reading abilities in 3- to 11-year-old for both researchers of psychiatric disorders and
Chinese co-twins, as part of a larger cognitive practitioners. It calls into question the very nature
ability battery. The results indicated shared of the category-dominated approach of the DSM
genetic origins for the three areas involved, enterprise and points to important general etio-
although distinct genetic influences were found logical considerations. At the same time, it might
for verbal skills. They concluded that the “gener- serve to entrench a biological rather than more
alist” gene hypotheses could be universal in dif- inclusive biopsychosocial understanding of the
ferent languages, such that the same set of genes etiology, expression, and treatment of psychiatric
“largely” influences diverse cognitive abilities, as disorder. Workers in the field should be wary of
per Plomin and Kovas (2005). falling into this one-sided position.

Others Child Genomics

Despite these findings of general gene effects on Grigorenko and Dozier (2013) edited a special
behavior, other studies show very specific genetic issue on genomics and child development.
effects. For example, Avinun et al. (2011) found Genomics concerns the science of the genome’s
that the arginine vasopressin receptor 1A structure and function. The Human Genome
(AVPR1A) gene is associated with adult altruistic Project had sequenced the full human genome
behavior, especially the specific 327 bp allele of and has led to GWAS, to remind, which attempt
one of its promoter region polymorphisms (R53). to match DNA variants with particular disorders.
Their research found that, in contrast, for 3-year- The underlying rationale for this kind of research
old twin preschoolers the target allele was associ- is the common disease-common variant (CD-
ated with less altruistic type behavior. The age CV) hypothesis; that is, specific allelescause spe-
difference could reflect either environmental or cific diseases. In the special issue, in an interesting
developmental influences, still to be discovered. innovation, Connolly, Glessner, and Hakonarson
Molecular analysis for genetic risk is con- (2013) showed that specific polymorphisms,
ducted not only for shared risk over disorders by SNPs, were related to items on assessment instru-
multiple genetic alleles but also in the more tradi- ments, in this case, on ASDs [the usual search is
tional way of finding single (candidate) genes for SNP–phenotype associations]. GWAS and
that might affect psychological disorder. The suc- related studies continue to proliferate and include
218 9 The Genetics Revolution

such innovations because the initial hope that it As for the transcriptome, involved in the
would clarify genetic underpinnings to disease RNA-based translation/transcription of the
has not been met. genome to proteins, Naumova, Lee, Rychkov,
As mentioned, in the “missing heritability” Vlasova, and Grigorenko (2013) examined the
problem, genetic variance does not account for brain transcriptome. It permits focusing on the
an estimated heritability (Plomin, 2013). whole system involved as “causative change”
However, Grigorenko and Dozier (2013) indi- agents, rather than just focusing on causative
cated that ongoing conceptualization and research genes, and on patterns of gene regulation and
might clarify the problem. New approaches expression. Similarly, Hu (2013) reviewed the
include the common disease-rare variant (CD- area of ASD and concluded that findings need to
RV) hypothesis. be integrated systematically over the different
Moreover, Grigorenko and Dozier (2013) “omic” sciences (genomics, epigenomics, tran-
explained that the research is now focusing on scriptomics, proteomics, interactomics) for better
epigenetics and epigenomics, which lead to the understanding of the disorder.
genome changing across the life span, e.g.,
through gene silencing. Unlike for genomic
research, it would not be possible to find a single Reaction Range
reference epigenome, although it might be pos-
sible to specify a minimum epigenome of impor- Model
tance. Future research should seek to find the
causal roots of clinical diseases and disorders in Manuck and McCaffery (2014) have described a
common genomic and epigenomic factors. That model relating genotype and phenotype in the
is, the CD-CV and CD-RV hypotheses could be context of models important to the present book.
elaborated into a common CD-GE hypothesis. Figure 9.3 in Manuck and McCaffery (2014)

HI

Gene by
Gradient of Variation of

Environment
the Phenotype

Main Effect
Gene by (Gene)
Environment

LO

LO HI

Gradient of Environmental Variation

Fig. 9.3 Hypothetical reaction ranges (variations in pos- mental variability than in “a.” Dashed lines indicate pos-
sible phenotypes) for genotypes/variations in environ- sible extensions of the reaction norms for a and c. The
ment. The possible reaction ranges are for gradients of differential susceptibility model is represented in the mid-
variability related to the phenotypes and the environment. range of the environmental gradient, while the diathesis-
Slope angle indicates degree of variability. a = G × E; stress one is represented at the end portions. Adapted from
b = G; c = G × E but, for the latter, at a different environ- Manuck (2010)
Reaction Range 219

presents Manuck’s (2010) model of a “reaction (2014) conducted a meta-analysis of the child-
norm” perspective on phenotypic variation in hood maltreatment × MAOA (low vs. high activity
relation to environmental variation. A reaction allele) interaction effect that has been found for
norm refers to the range of variation in pheno- later male aggressive and antisocial behavior out-
types observable over different environments comes. For the differential susceptibility model,
found in individuals having the same genotype. Hankin et al. (2011) found variations in the gene
In the figure, the slopes of the lines depicting 5-HTTLPR and affectivity in both supportive and
the model indicate whether there is greater or unsupportive parenting/environments (but did not
lesser plasticity in producing a broad range of find the association with alternate genotypes).
phenotypic expressions across the gradient of Manuck and McCaffery (2014) presented
variation in the environment. The parallel lines in research illustrating what the environment does
the slopes represent an absence of G × E interac- and to what the E refers in G × E. For the former,
tion, whereas the lines with different slopes rep- they showed how stress (recent widowhood) leads
resent interaction. In the latter, different to inflammation, but only in carriers of an allele
phenotypes (in the same environmental range) (G, not C) of an SNP labeled IL6-174G/C
serve to yield different phenotypic responses. (Schultze-Florey et al., 2012). The mechanism
Note that, according to the authors, the a–b implicated is a genotype-dependent stressor effect
interaction exemplifies the diathesis-stress [vul- on inflammatory responses (involving interleu-
nerability × stress] model of psychopathology kin-6, It6). For the former, rGE indicates that vari-
(e.g., Caspi et al., 2002, 2003) and the a–c one the ables in G × E research are not necessarily genetic
differential susceptibility model (Belsky & or environmental (rGE = correlated gene by envi-
Pluess, 2009). [In the latter model, certain allelic ronment effects, e.g., heritable predispositions
variations in concert with positive or negative influence activity in or evocation of the environ-
environments are sensitive to context and lead to ment; Plomin, DeFries, McClearn, & McGuffin,
phenotypically positive or negative phenotypes, 2008). Only experimentally-manipulated envi-
respectively.] In terms of the model of reaction ronmental exposures can address rGE confounds.
norm or range in the figure, differential suscepti-
bility effects are captured mid-range in the envi-
ronmental gradient and those of (vulnerability) Conclusion
diathesis-stress are captured at either end (also
called the vantage sensitivity model). As an overall conclusion, the authors noted that
Parenthetically, I note that the diatheses-stress the field should adopt the broader term of “G × E
model is not quite equivalent to the genetic by expression,” or gene × environmental exposure
environmental (G × E) model, unlike the conten- interactions, which would include “complexly”
tion of the authors, and Caspi’s research should determined experiences, dispositions, abilities,
not be an example that is in line with it. The attitudes, and affective states.
diatheses-stress model is about cumulative vul- I note that the conclusions offered by Manuck
nerabilities, in particular, and not the vulnerabil- and McCaffery (2014) on genotype–phenotype
ity afforded by certain alleles, which is the case relations cover the range of topics reviewed in the
for the G × E model. book, including—development, psychopathol-
ogy, genes, and environment. The models cov-
ered include diathesis-stress compared to
Evidence differential susceptibility and G × E and rGE in
the genetic area. The concept of reaction range is
As for recent research in support of the various used to integrate much of this work. In Young
models cited by Manuck and McCaffery (2014), (2011), I also used this concept to help explain
for the diathesis-stress model, Byrd and Manuck epigenesis.
220 9 The Genetics Revolution

Genes/Causality Wahlsten (2013) emphasized how genes form


networks and do not function in isolation. They
Wahlsten (2013) elaborated definitions related to interact with each other and also with the envi-
gene function (see Fig. 9.4), which I present as a ronment. At a larger-scale, when gene interac-
reminding tutorial. (a) The figure indicates that tions involve thousands of genes, workers now
any one gene can alter several phenotypes. This refer to the “interactome” (Li et al., 2004).
is termed pleiotropy. (b) Also, genes could inter- Krimsky (2013) added that genetic compo-
act with each other (epistasis). (c) In heterogene- nents act nonlinearly so that genetic causation is
ity, multiple pathways to outcome can take place, complex. Causation is multiple, involving not
depending on which genes are implicated. In only genes but also epigenetic effects, the envi-
gene–environment interaction, the strength of ronment in interaction, and so on. In this regard,
influence of a particular gene and a particular Turkheimer (2011) referred to the “hyper-complex
environment become evident only when both are developmental network.” Landrigan, Lambertini,
present simultaneously. and Birnbaum (2012) referred to the “causal tree.”

a Pleiotropy c Epistasis (G x G interaction)


Phenotype 1 Phenotype 1
Gene A
Phenotype 2
A

Phenotype 3
Gene B

Phenotype 4 Phenotype 2

C B
b Heterogeneity

Equifinality (Heterogeneity I)

Gene A defect
d G x E interaction

Gene B defect Phenotype 1 Environment I (not II)


Gene 1
Gene C defect Phenotype
Gene 2

Equifinality (Heterogeneity II)

Phenotype 1 Environment B
Gene 1
Gene A defect Phenotype
Gene 2
Phenotype 2

Fig. 9.4 Pleiotropy, heterogeneity, epistasis, and G × E in in networks in which genes influence each other.
genetic influence. (a) A specific gene could influence Interactions might be unidirectional or bidirectional. (d)
more than one phenotype, and most phenotypes, in turn, The influence of a gene on a phenotype depends on the
are influenced by different genes. Any one gene does not organism’s environment, and the allele of the gene itself.
simply code for one particular phenotype, despite the The strength of the influence, therefore, is determined
name that might be given to the gene. (b) Different genetic jointly by two factors, and their influences cannot be sepa-
defects could result in the same disease. Conversely, one rated statistically. Adapted from Wahlsten (2013)
defect could lead to different disease. (c) Genes function
References 221

Chapter Conclusions adaptive response. Being ready for change permits


systems to optimize variations and adaptability
Phenome within and across in each of the cases of (a) intra-
agent systems, (b) whole individual agent (pheno-
One -ome that has not been considered in the vari- typic) systems, and, as applicable, (c) multiple
ous publications just reviewed is the “phenome,” a inter-agent (e.g., over individuals, radiation over a
term that I coined to indicate the collection of phe- niche/niches) systems.
notypes in a species. Moreover, phenotypes within By taking a systems approach to the phenome
the individual are multiple, and infinitely varied, and its context, some of the complexities and
especially in the human case. Multiple species are contradictions in the genetic and molecular
endowed with the capacity for phenotypic plastic- genetic research on behavior might be demysti-
ity that enables rapid online adaptation and that fied. In studying the genetics of behavior, as with
promotes not just survival and well-being, but many aspects in the study of behavior, one needs
also, in a different, more prolonged time frame, to take a step backwards, at times, in order to try
Darwinian adaptation and even speciation in to see the whole, or the forest between the trees.
appropriate contexts. The system-wide “omic”
integrations that characterize phenotypes appear
to work together to maximize robust phenotypic Loveome
adaptation in both the online and evolutionary
sense and also the ability to flexibly resist or meet Aside from establishing a species’ genome and
environmental or niche challenges. phenome and their interactions, researchers
should work toward establishing the range of
environmental factors that can affect each of the
Evolvability genome and phenome. In the human case, one
aspect in this regard could be called the “loveome”
Two more terms that I find important in order to (or “lovome”). How that interacts to produce the
understand the concept of the “phenome” are range of human behavior expressed in the human
evolvability and versatility. Evolvability does not phenome should deserve the same scrutiny being
just relate to genetic variations and alterations that applied to the case of the genome. The best in
promote adaptive heritable phenotypes, but also human outcomes requires the best in supportive
system-wide genomic and related -omics, includ- environments. A too great focus on genetics could
ing epigenetic ones, that function in these regards. place this issue in the background, along with the
biopsychosocial model within which it fits.

Versatility
References
As for the concept of versatility as it applies to
evolutionary thought, evolution appears to be Achenbach, T. M., & Edelbrock, C. (1981). Behavioral
especially about versatility in an active way rather problems and competencies reported by parents of
than in only a passive type of flexibility or plastic- normal and disturbed children aged 4 through 16.
Monographs of the Society for Research in Child
ity that might be required for environmental or
Development, 46, 1–82.
niche challenges. This is not to say there is an American Psychiatric Association. (2013). Diagnostic
active “design” to evolution in a teleological sense. and statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM-5
Rather, evolutionary systems, in general, are (5th ed.). Washington, DC: Author.
Avinun, R., Israel, S., Shalev, I., Gritsenko, I., Bornstein,
poised at the “cusp of change,” to use Kauffman’s
G., Ebstein, R. P., et al. (2011). AVPR1A variant associ-
(1993) nonlinear dynamical systems theory ated with preschoolers’ lower altruistic behavior. PLoS
(NLDST) term, in order to maximize flexibility in One, 6, e25274. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0025274.
222 9 The Genetics Revolution

Bakermans-Kranenburg, M. J., & van IJzendoorn, M. H. Chow, B. W.-Y., Ho, C. S.-H., Wong, S. W.-L., Waye,
(2006). Gene-environment interaction of the dopamine M. M. Y., & Bishop, D. V. M. (2013). Generalist genes
D4 receptor (DRD4) and observed maternal insensitiv- and cognitive abilities in Chinese twins. Developmental
ity predicting externalizing behavior in preschoolers. Science, 16, 260–268.
Developmental Psychobiology, 48, 406–409. Ciszac, M., Montina, A., & Arecchi, F. T. (2009). Control
Bell, O., Tiwari, V. K., Thomä, N. H., & Schübeler, D. of transient synchronization with external stimuli.
(2012). Determinants and dynamics of genome acces- Chaos, 19, 015104. doi:10.1063/1.3080195.
sibility. Nature Reviews Genetics, 12, 554–564. Connolly, J. J., Glessner, J. T., & Hakonarson, H. (2013).
Belsky, J., & Pluess, M. (2009). The nature (and nurture?) A genome-wide association study of autism incorpo-
of plasticity in early human development. Perspectives rating ADI-R, ADOS, and SRS. Child Development,
on Psychological Science, 4, 345–351. 84, 17–33.
Berger, A. (2011). Self-regulation: Brain, cognition, Cosgrove, V. E., Rhee, S. H., Gelhorn, H. L., Boeldt, D.,
and development. Washington, DC: American Corely, R. C., Ehringer, M. A., et al. (2011). Structure
Psychological Association. and etiology of co-occurring internalizing and exter-
Blaze, J., & Roth, T. L. (2013). Epigenetic mechanisms in nalizing disorders in adolescents. Journal of Abnormal
learning and memory. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Psychology, 39, 109–123.
Cognitive Science, 4, 105–115. Cross-Disorder Group of the Psychiatric Genomics
Boyce, W. T., & Kobor, M. S. (2015). Development and Consortium. (2013). Genetic relationship between five
the epigenome: The “synapse” of gene-environment psychiatric disorders estimated from genome-wide
interplay. Developmental Science, 18, 1–23. SNPs. Nature Genetics, 45, 984–994.
Brookes, K., Xu, X., Chen, W., Zhou, K., Neale, B., Lowe, Davies, G., Tenesa, A., Payton, A., Yang, J., Harris, S. E.,
N., et al. (2006). The analysis of 51 genes in DSM-IV Liewald, D., et al. (2011). Genome-wide association
combined type attention deficit hyperactivity disorder: studies establish that human intelligence is highly herita-
Association signals in DRD4, DAT1 and 16 other ble and polygenic. Molecular Psychiatry, 16, 996–1005.
genes. Molecular Psychiatry, 11, 934–953. Davis, O. S., Butcher, L. M., Docherty, S. J., Meaburn,
Byrd, A. L., & Manuck, S. B. (2014). MAOA, childhood E. L., Curtis, C. J., Simpson, M. A., et al. (2010).
maltreatment and antisocial behavior: Meta-analysis A three-stage genome-wide association study of gen-
of a gene-environment interaction. Biological eral cognitive ability: Hunting the small effects.
Psychiatry, 75, 9–17. Behavior Genetics, 40, 759–767.
Caspi, A., Houts, R. M., Belsky, D. W., Goldman-Mellor, Deary, I. J. (2001). Intelligence, a very short introduction.
S. J., Harrington, H., Israel, S., et al. (2014). The p fac- Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
tor: One general psychopathology factor in the struc- Deary, I. J., Penke, L., & Johnson, W. (2010). The neuro-
ture of psychiatric disorders? Clinical Psychological science of human intelligence differences. Nature
Science, 2, 119–137. Reviews Neuroscience, 11, 201–211.
Caspi, A., McClay, J., Moffitt, T. E., Mill, J., Martin, J., del Campo, N., Müller, U., & Sahakian, B. J. (2012). Neural
Craig, I. W., et al. (2002). Role of genotype in the and behavioral endophenotypes in ADHD. Current
cycle of violence in maltreated children. Science, 297, Topics in Behavioral Neurosciences, 11, 65–91.
851–854. Eley, T. (1997). General genes: A new theme in develop-
Caspi, A., Sugden, K., Moffitt, T. E., Taylor, A., Craig, mental psychopathology. Current Directions in
I. W., Harrington, H., et al. (2003). Influence of life Psychological Science, 6, 90–95.
stress on depression: Moderation by a polymorphism Ellis, B. J. (2004). Timing of pubertal maturation in girls:
in the 5-HTT gene. Science, 301, 386–389. An integrated life history approach. Psychological
Chabris, C. F., Hebert, B. M., Benjamin, D. J., Beauchamp, Bulletin, 130, 920–958.
J., Cesarini, D., van der Loos, M., et al. (2012). Most Fair, D. A., Dosenbach, N. U. F., Petersen, S. E., &
reported genetic associations with general intelligence Schlagger, B. L. (2012). Resting state studies on the
are probably false positives. Psychological Science, development of control systems. In M. I. Posner (Ed.),
23, 1314–1323. Cognitive neuroscience of attention (2nd ed., pp. 291–
Chabris, C. F., Lee, J. J., Cesarini, D., Benjamin, D. J., & 311). New York: Guilford Press.
Laibson, D. I. (2015). The fourth law of behavior Feil, R., & Fraga, M. F. (2012). Epigenetics and the envi-
genetics. Current Directions in Psychological Science, ronment: Emerging patterns and implications. Nature
24, 304–312. Reviews Genetics, 13, 97–109.
Chakrabarti, B., Dudbridge, F., Kent, L., Wheelwright, S., Feinberg, A. P., & Irizarry, R. A. (2010). Stochastic epi-
Hill-Cawthorne, G., Allison, C., et al. (2009). Genes genetic variation as a driving force of development,
related to sex-steroids, neural growth, and social- evolutionary adaptation & disease. Proceedings of the
emotional behavior are associated with autistic traits, National Academy of Sciences of the United States of
empathy, and Asperger syndrome. Autism Research, 2, America, 107, 1757–1764.
157–177. Forbush, K. T., & Watson, D. (2013). The structure of
Charney, E. (2012). Behavior genetics and postgenomics. common and uncommon mental disorders.
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 35, 331–410. Psychological Medicine, 43, 97–108.
References 223

Fox, N. A., Nichols, K. E., Henderson, H. A., Rubin, K., for syndromal and subsyndromal common DSM-IV
Schmidt, L., Hamer, D., et al. (2005). Evidence for a Axis I and Axis II disorders. American Journal of
gene-environment interaction in predicting behavioral Psychiatry, 168, 29–39.
inhibition in middle childhood. Psychological Science, Kendler, K. S., Gardner, C. O., Gatz, M., & Pedersen,
16, 921–926. N. L. (2007). The sources of co-morbidity between
Freeman, W. (2000). Brains create macroscopic order major depression and generalized anxiety disorders in
from microscopic disorder by neurodynamics in per- the Swedish national twin sample. Psychological
ception. In P. Århem, C. Blomberg, & H. Liljenström Medicine, 37, 453–462.
(Eds.), Disorder versus order in brain function: Essays Krimsky, S. (2013). Genetic causation: A cross disciplin-
in theoretical neurobiology (pp. 205–219). Singapore: ary inquiry. In R. M. Lerner & J. B. Benson (Eds.),
World Scientific. Advances in child development and behavior.
Gao, W., Zhu, H., Giovanello, K. S., Smith, J. K., Shen, Embodiment and epigenesis: Theoretical and method-
D., Gilmore, J. H., et al. (2009). Evidence on the emer- ological issues in understanding the role of biology
gence of the brain’s default network from 2-week-old within the relational development system. Part A:
to 2-year-old healthy pediatric subjects. Proceedings Philosophical, theoretical, and biological dimensions
of the National Academy of Sciences of the United (Vol. 44, pp. 307–323). Waltham, MA: Academic
States of America, 106, 6790–6795. Press.
Gissis, S. B., & Jablonka, E. (Eds.). (2001). Krueger, R. F., Caspi, A., Moffitt, T. E., & Silva, P. A.
Transformations of Lamarckism: From subtle fluids to (1998). The structure and stability of common mental
molecular biology. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge disorders (DSM-III-R): A longitudinal-epidemiological
University Press. study. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 107, 216–227.
Grigorenko, E. L., & Dozier, E. (2013). Introduction to Lahey, B. B., Applegate, B., Hakes, J. K., Zald, D. H.,
the special section on genomics. Child Development, Hariri, A. R., & Rathouz, P. J. (2012). Is there a gen-
84, 6–16. eral factor of prevalent psychopathology during adult-
Hankin, B. L., Nederhof, E., Oppenheimer, C. W., hood? Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 121,
Jenness, J., Young, J. F., Abela, J. R., et al. (2011). 971–977.
Differential susceptibility in youth: Evidence that Lahey, B. B., Van Hulle, C. A., Singh, A. L., Waldman,
5-HTTLPR x positive parenting is associated with I. D., & Rathouz, P. J. (2011). Higher-order genetic
positive affect “for better and worse.”. Translational and environmental structure of prevalent forms of
Psychiatry, 4, e44. doi:10.1038/tp.2011.44. child and adolescent psychopathology. Archives of
Hink, L. K., Rhee, S. H., Corley, R. P., Cosgrove, V. E., General Psychiatry, 68, 181–189.
Hewitt, J. K., Schulz-Heik, R., et al. (2013). Personality Lahey, B. B., & Waldman, I. D. (2003). A developmental
dimensions as common and broadband-specific fea- propensity model of the origins of conduct problems
tures for internalizing and externalizing disorders. during childhood and adolescence. In B. B. Lahey,
Journal of Abnormal Child Psychology, 41, 939–957. T. E. Moffit, & A. Caspi (Eds.), Causes of conduct dis-
Hlavecek, W. S., & Faeder, J. R. (2009). The complexity of order and juvenile delinquency (pp. 76–117).
cell signaling and the need for a new mechanic. Science New York: Guilford Press.
Signaling, 2, pe46. doi:10.1126/scisignal.281pe46. Lakatos, K., Nemoda, Z., Toth, I., Ronai, Z., Ney, K.,
Hollis, G., Kloos, H., & Van Orden, G. C. (2009). Origins Sasvari-Szekely, M., et al. (2002). Further evidence
of order in cognitive activity. In S. J. Guastello, for the role of the dopamine D4 receptor (DRD4) gene
M. Koopmans, & D. Pincus (Eds.), Chaos and com- in attachment disorganization: Interaction of exon III
plexity in psychology: The theory of nonlinear dynam- 48-bp repeat and the −521 C/T promoter polymor-
ical systems (pp. 206–241). Cambridge, MA: phisms. Molecular Psychiatry, 7, 27–31.
Cambridge University Press. Lakatos, K., Toth, I., Nemoda, Z., Ney, K., Sasvari-
Hu, V. W. (2013). From genes to environment: Using inte- Szekely, M., & Gervai, J. (2000). Dopamine D4 recep-
grative genomics to build a “systems-level” under- tor (DRD4) gene polymorphism is associated with
standing of autism spectrum disorders. Child attachment disorganization in infants. Molecular
Development, 84, 89–103. Psychiatry, 5, 633–637.
Johnson, M. H., Griffin, R., Csibra, G., Halit, H., Farroni, Landrigan, P., Lambertini, L., & Birnbaum, L. S. (2012). A
T., De Haan, M., et al. (2005). The emergence of the research strategy to discover the environmental causes
social brain network: Evidence from typical and atypi- of autism and neurodevelopmental disabilities.
cal development. Development and Psychopathology, Environmental Health Perspectives, 120, A258–A260.
17, 599–619. Li, S., Armstrong, C. M., Bertin, N., Ge, H., Milstein, S.,
Kauffman, S. (1993). The origins of order: Self- Boxem, M., et al. (2004). A map of the interactome
organization and selection in evolution. New York: network of the metazoan. Science, 303, 540–543.
Oxford University Press. Lilienfeld, S. O. (2003). Comorbidity between and within
Kendler, K. S., Aggen, S. H., Knudsen, G. P., Røysamb, childhood externalizing and internalizing disorders:
E., Neale, M. C., & Reichborn-Kjennerud, T. (2011). Reflections and directions. Journal of Abnormal Child
The structure of genetic and environmental risk factors Psychology, 31, 285–291.
224 9 The Genetics Revolution

Lombardo, M. V., Baron-Cohen, S., Belmonte, M. K., & Plomin, R., DeFries, J. C., McClearn, G. E., & McGuffin,
Chakrabarti, B. (2011). Neural endophenotypes of P. (2008). Behavioral genetics (5th ed.). New York:
social behavior in autism spectrum conditions. In J. T. Worth.
Cacioppo & J. Decety (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of Plomin, R., & Kovas, Y. (2005). Generalist genes and
social neuroscience (pp. 830–847). New York: Oxford learning disabilities. Psychological Bulletin, 131,
University Press. 592–617.
López-Maury, L., Marguerat, S., & Bähler, J. (2008). Plomin, R., Haworth, C. M. A., Meaburn, E. L., Price, T. S.,
Tuning gene expression to changing environments. Wellcome Trust Case Control Consortium 2, & Davis,
Nature Reviews Genetics, 9, 583–594. O. S. P. (2013). Common DNA markers can account for
Lubke, G. H., Hottenga, J. J., Walters, R., Laurin, C., de more than half of the genetic influence on cognitive
Geus, E. J., Willemsen, G., et al. (2012). Estimating abilities. Psychological Science, 24, 562–568.
the genetic variance of major depressive disorder due Posner, M. I., Rothbart, M. K., Sheese, B. E., & Voelker,
to all single nucleotide polymorphisms. Biological P. (2012). Control networks and neuromodulators of
Psychiatry, 72, 707–709. early development. Developmental Psychology, 48,
Manuck, S. B. (2010). The reaction norm in gene x environ- 827–835.
ment interaction. Molecular Psychiatry, 15, 881–882. Posner, M. I., Rothbart, M. K., & Sheese, B. E. (2007).
Manuck, S. B., & McCaffery, J. M. (2014). Gene- Attention genes. Developmental Science, 10, 24–29.
environment interaction. Annual Review of Psychology, Rhee, S. H., Lahey, B. B., & Waldman, I. D. (2014).
65, 41–70. Comorbidity among dimensions of childhood psycho-
Mash, E. J., & Wolfe, D. A. (2015). Abnormal child psy- pathology: Converging evidence from behavior genet-
chology (6th ed.). Boston: Cengage Learning. ics. Child Development Perspectives, 9, 26–31.
Mikolajewski, A. J., Allan, N. P., Hart, S. A., Lonigan, Richardson, K. (2010). The evolution of intelligent sys-
C. J., & Taylor, J. (2013). Negative affect shares tems: How molecules became minds. Basingstoke,
genetic and environmental influences with symp- UK: Palgrave.
toms of childhood internalizing and externalizing dis- Richardson, K. (2013). The eclipse of heritability and the
orders. Journal of Abnormal Child Psychology, 41, foundations of intelligence. New Ideas in Psychology,
411–423. 31, 122–129.
Naumova, O. Y., Lee, M., Rychkov, S. Y., Vlasova, N. V., Ristic, J., & Enns, J. T. (2015). The changing face of
& Grigorenko, E. L. (2013). Gene expression in the attentional development. Current Directions in
human brain: The current state of the study of specific- Psychological Science, 24, 24–31.
ity and spatiotemporal dynamics. Child Development, Robins, L. N., Cottler, L., Bucholz, K. K., & Compton, W.
84, 76–88. (1995). Diagnostic Interview Schedule for DSM-IV. St.
Nikolova, Y. S., Bogdan, R., & Hariri, A. R. (2013). Louis, MO: Washington University School of Medicine.
Neurogenetics approach: Insights from studies of Schmidt, L. A., Fox, N. A., & Hamer, D. H. (2007).
dopamine signaling and reward processing. In M. D. Evidence for a gene-gene interaction in predicting
Robinson, E. R. Watkins, & E. Harmon-Jones (Eds.), children’s behavior problems: Association of sero-
Handbook of cognition and emotion (pp. 19–34). tonin transporter short and dopamine receptor D4 long
New York: Guilford Press. genotypes with internalizing and externalizing behav-
Noble, D. (2010). Biophysics and systems biology. iors in typically developing 7-year-olds. Development
Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A: and Psychopathology, 19, 1105–1116.
Mathematical, Physical and Engineering Sciences, Schultze-Florey, C. R., Martinex-Maza, O., Magpantay,
368, 1125–1139. L., Breen, E. C., Irwin, M. R., Gündel, H., et al.
Nudel, R., & Newbury, D. F. (2013). FOXP2. Wiley (2012). When grief makes you sick: Bereavement
Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science, 4, induced systemic inflammation is a question of geno-
547–560. type. Brain, Behavior, and Immunity, 26, 1066–1071.
Piaget, J. (1988). Piaget’s theory. In K. Richardson & Seligman, M. E. P., Railton, P., Baumeister, R. F., &
S. Sheldon (Eds.), Cognitive development to adoles- Sripada, C. (2013). Navigating into the future or
cence. Hove, UK: Erlbaum. driven by the past. Perspectives on Psychological
Pigliucci, M. (2010). Phenotypic plasticity. In M. Piliucci Science, 8, 119–141.
& G. B. Müller (Eds.), Evolution: The extended syn- Shapiro, L. (2009). Making sense of mirror neurons.
thesis (pp. 355–378). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Syntheses, 167, 439–456.
Plomin, R. (2013). Child development and molecular Sheese, B. E., Voelker, P. M., Rothbart, M. K., & Posner,
genetics: 13 years later. Child Development, 84, M. I. (2007). Parenting quality interacts with genetic
104–120. variation in dopamine receptor D4 to influence tem-
Plomin, R., & Davis, O. S. (2009). The future of genetics perament in early childhood. Developmental
in psychology and psychiatry: Microarrays, genome- Psychopathology, 19, 1039–1046.
wide association, and non-coding RNA. Journal of Smoller, J. W., Craddock, N., Kendler, K., Lee, P. H.,
Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 50, 63–71. Neale, B. M., Nurnberger, J. L., et al. (2013).
Plomin, R., DeFries, J. C., Knopik, V. S., & Neiderhiser, Identification of risk loci with shared effects on five
J. M. (2013). Behavioral genetics (6th ed.). New York: major psychiatric disorders: A genome-wide analysis.
Worth. Lancet, 381, 1371–1379.
References 225

Smoller, J. W., Kendler, K., & Craddock, N. (2013). extraversion. Translational Psychiatry, 2, e102.
Identification of risk loci with shared effects on five doi:10.1038/tp.2012.49.
major psychiatric disorders: A genome-wide analysis. Visscher, P. M., Goddard, M. E., Derks, E. M., & Wray,
Lancet, 381, 1371–1379. N. R. (2012). Evidence-based psychiatric genetics,
Srividhya, J., Li, Y., & Pomerening, J. R. (2011). AKA the false dichotomy between common and rare
Open cascades as simple solutions to providing ultra- variant hypothesis. Molecular Psychiatry, 17,
sensitivity and adaptation in cellular signaling. 474–485.
Physiology & Behavior, 8, 046005. doi:10.1088/ Vrieze, S. I., Feng, S., Miller, M. B., Hicks, B. M.,
1478-3975/8/4/046005. Pankratz, N., Abecasis, G. R., et al. (2014). Rare
Tackett, J. L., Lahey, B. B., Van Hulle, C., Waldman, I., nonsynonymous exonic variants in addiction and
Krueger, R. F., & Rathouz, P. J. (2013). Common genetic behavioral disinhibition. Biological Psychiatry, 75,
influences on negative emotionality and a general psy- 783–789.
chopathology factor in childhood and adolescence. Wahlsten, D. (2013). A contemporary view of genes and
Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 122, 1142–1153. behavior: Complex systems and interactions. In R. M.
Taylor, J., Allan, N., Mikolajewski, A. J., & Hart, S. A. Lerner & J. B. Benson (Eds.), Advances in child devel-
(2013). Common genetic and nonshared environmen- opment and behavior. Embodiment and epigenesis:
tal factors contribute to the association between socio- Theoretical and methodological issues in understand-
emotional dispositions and the externalizing factor in ing the role of biology within the relational develop-
children. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, ment system. Part A: Philosophical, theoretical, and
and Allied Disciplines, 54, 67–76. biological dimensions (Vol. 44, pp. 285–306).
Turkheimer, E. (2011). Commentary: Variation and cau- Waltham, MA: Academic Press.
sation in the environment and genome. International World Health Organization. (2017). International
Journal of Epidemiology, 40, 598–601. Classification of Disease, 11th Revision.
Verweij, K. J., Yang, J., Lahti, J., Veijola, J., Hintsanen, Yates, F. E. (2008). Homeokinetics/homeodynamics:
M., Pulkki-Råback, L., et al. (2012). Maintenance of A physical heuristic for life and complexity. Ecological
genetic variation in human personality: Testing evolu- Psychology, 20, 148–179.
tionary models by estimating heritability due to com- Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
mon causal variants and investigating the effect of Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science +
distant inbreeding. Evolution, 66, 3238–3251. Business Media.
Vinkhuyzen, A. A. E., Pedersen, N. L., Yang, J., Lee, Zuk, O., Hechter, E., Sunyaeva, S. R., & Lander, E. S.
S. H., Magnusson, P. K. E., Iacono, W. G., et al. (2012). The mystery of missing heritability.
(2012). Common SNPs explain some of the variation Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of
in the personality dimensions of neuroticism and the United States of America, 109, 1193–1198.
Gene × Environment Interaction:
The Environmental Revolution 10

Chapter Introduction The G × E Model

Gene × Environment (G × E) interaction is a cru- Candidate Genes


cial aspect of behavior genetics, and the extent of
and types of research in the area continues to Introduction Duncan et al. (2014) reviewed the
accelerate. The present chapter reviews the dif- psychiatric genetic and psychological science
ferentiation that is taking place on the question. approaches to Gene × Environment (G × E) inter-
The chapter reviews the different ways that the action, noting a “growing divide” in these two
field addresses G × E (Rutter, 2011). Notably, approaches to the question. The first studies in
there is debate about the replicability of critical behavioral genetics focused on heritability with-
findings in the area (Duncan, Pollastri, & Smoller, out considering molecular genetics. Typically,
2014), yet most of the research is supportive. these studies examine family constellations,
Most of the chapter reviews recent research especially in twins, to estimate the proportionate
supporting G × E effects in genes, which, for the contributions of genetic and environmental fac-
most part are related to neurotransmitters (espe- tors. This research has established a robust con-
cially 5-HTTLPR, MAOA, DRD4). The review is tribution of genetic factors to disorders such as
divided into the G × E effects on externalizing schizophrenia, for which heritability appears to
and internalizing outcomes. Some of the research exceed 70 % (Sullivan, Daly, & O’Donovan,
is becoming quite nuanced in methodology, for 2012). Also, heritability approaches 30–40 % for
example, on the one hand, combining genetic the heritability of internalizing disorders (depres-
analyses, or, on the other hand, differentiating sion, anxiety). However, unlike the case for psy-
types of adverse (e.g., parental) environments chiatric genetics, behavior genetics does not
that lead to negative outcomes in the presence of specify specific genetic risk factors.
certain alleles. Also, the area is complicated by Psychiatric genetics is riding the exponential
interactions beyond G × E, such as G × G and growth in knowledge and also application of
G × E × D. Finally, lack of replication is found polymorphic genetic loci as risk factors in psychi-
in some studies of certain G × E effects, so atric disorder. The first wave of studies in the area
that large-scale and cross-genomic studies are could deal with only a few hundred genetic loci of
beginning to proliferate, and sometimes with the millions of polymorphic loci in the human
novel results. genome. The techniques involved linkage analysis

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 227


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_10
228 10 Gene × Environment Interaction: The Environmental Revolution

and candidate gene studies. The former examined decade (2000–2009) of cG investigation related
chromosome regions among family members to G × E interactions (referred to as cG × E). They
sharing an illness and the latter examined candi- found 103 studies in 98 publications that met
date genes (cG) that could elucidate pathways to their inclusion criteria. The field flourished with
disorder (usually involving neurotransmitters). the studies by Caspi et al. (2002, 2003). The for-
According to Duncan et al. (2014), these were mer found that childhood maltreatment was asso-
“low throughput” approaches to genetic studies, ciated with antisocial behavior, but only in the
and failures to replicate were more common than presence of a functional polymorphism in the
expected in the candidate gene studies. gene encoding monoamine oxidase A (MAOA).
As technology advanced, phenotypic expres- The latter found that stressful life events were
sion could be studied in relation to millions of associated with depression, but only for one allele
common genetic allele variants over the whole for 5-HTTLPR, a serotonin-related locus (sero-
genome, in an approach referred to as genome- tonin transporter linked polymorphic region).
wide association study (GWAS). Because of the The Duncan et al. (2014) review of the litera-
multiple statistical tests involved in any one study, ture found 14 studies similar to Caspi et al. (2002)
the alpha or p value of significance in results has and 32 similar to Caspi et al. (2003) (with over 50
been established at p < 0.00000005, which is far other studies). The subsequent research involving
stricter than the typical value in psychological sci- these two Caspi team studies did not offer
ence (usually, p < 0.05, 0.01, or 0.001). unequivocal support for the original findings.
In general, GWAS results are changing under- Indeed, of the two Caspi et al. studies, only the
standing of psychiatric genetics. Not only are one in 2002 has found some positive support. For
candidate gene findings not being replicated but example, in a very similar study, Fergusson,
also the effect sizes for any one gene loci are Horwood, Miller, and Kennedy (2011) did not
exceedingly small even if significant. Also, replicate the 2003 study.
GWAS findings are leading to surprising results, Aside from the Caspi and colleagues research,
for example, related to gene loci associated with the field has investigated to a sufficient degree
psychiatric disorder not even in the protein- four other cG × Es (at least two replication
coding portion of genes. That is, the gene loci attempts). These include three others involving
being underscored are in intergenic and intro- 5-HTTLPR—Kaufman et al. (2004) on social
genic regions of the genome rather than within support and depression; Kaufman et al. (2007) on
exons, which had been the focus in cG research. adverse life events in predicting alcohol use/
A field related to psychiatric genetics is neuro- abuse; and Kendler, Kuhn, Vittum, Prescott, and
genetics (Hyde, 2015). For example, it describes Riley (2005) on adverse life events in predicting
Imaging Gene × Environment interaction (IG × E). anxiety—as well as Bradley et al. (2008) on
It describes how G × E affects brain and behavior, adverse life events and depression for CRHR1.
and I have cited some research in this book in this The two Kaufman studies have not been con-
regard. The new field is finding linkages in com- firmed, as was found for Caspi et al. (2003),
mon genetic polymorphisms to variations in brain while results for the other two are mixed, as was
structure, function, and connectivity. For example, found for Caspi et al. (2002).
Glaser et al. (2014) found the pathway from geno-
type (corticotropin-releasing hormone receptor 1 Conclusion Duncan et al. (2014) concluded that
gene) [CRHR1] to neural reactivity (right ventral– cG × E research in psychiatry has investigated six
lateral prefrontal cortex) and then to negative major interactions, of which only three have
emotionality was moderated by childhood stress received “preliminary” support in the literature.
in the link from genotype to neural reactivity. In addition, the variant G × E hypothesis of
“differential susceptibility” (Ellis, Boyce, Belsky,
Evidence Duncan et al. (2014) reviewed the Bakermans-Kranenburg, & van IJzendoorn,
research in the field of psychiatry in the first 2011) has not received empirical support at the
The G × E Model 229

stringent research significance levels that are now Complexities


the norm in psychiatric genetics. It still needs to
be shown to an acceptable rigorous statistical Introduction In the following, first, I discuss
standard that some genetic alleles are more imper- some complexity in the genetics of G × E
vious to environmental effects while others vary approaches and, then, do the same with respect to
extremely toward negative or positive outcome, the environmental aspect. G × E is not a straight-
depending on the quality of the environment forward interaction of independent factors.
(hardship or the “right” environment, respec-
tively). The authors advocated for a “biopsycho- Genes Uher (2011a) reviewed the major G × E
social” etiology of mental health disorder. interactions that have been found for mental
health outcomes (see Table 10.1). He noted that
none involve a direct genetic effect independent
Comment of the interactions involved. The table lists nine
genes relevant to mental health. For the environ-
Duncan et al. (2014) reviewed the literature from ment, the exposures range from child abuse to
2002 to 2009, and their conclusions seem prema- parenting rules. The outcomes include antisocial
ture that there are only three cG × Es with some behavior, depression, psychosis, attention deficit/
evidence in their support. In the 5 years since the hyperactive disorder (ADHD), alcohol use, and
year of the last studies that they reviewed, the posttraumatic stress disorder (PTSD). The
field has published relevant G × E research in an research started with the work of Caspi et al.
exponential fashion and the conclusions offered (2002), but has burgeoned. Uher (2011a) appears
by Duncan et al. (2014) no longer apply, despite more positive about the work and validity of the
their recent vintage. In the following, I trace Caspi group findings compared to Duncan et al.
some of the critical concepts and empirical (2014).
research since 2009 in the field in order to but- Caspi, Hariri, Holmes, Uher, and Moffitt
tress this conclusion. (2011) noted that the serotonin transporter gene,
That being said, the work of Dick et al. (2015) the 5-HTTLPR gene, that is involved in G × E
cautioned that candidate Gene × Environment interactions or genetic sensitivities to the environ-
research (cG × E) has problems with replicability. ment that promotes stress sensitivities, has had its
They referred to the use of small N’s, low power, effects replicated in multiple studies and, more-
publication bias, and so on. Even in studies in over, intermediate pathways are being investi-
which N’s are large and candidate disorders are gated. The research considers areas as diverse as
associated with genetic contributions (e.g., bullying, PTSD, aggression, and regulation of
schizophrenia), there still is lack of statistical negative affect. The brain regions apparently
power to detect genotype-relative risks that involved include the amygdala and the medial pre-
are < 1.1. Typically, the effect size in this research frontal cortex (PFC), as well as increased hypotha-
is small. The “false discovery” rate might be lamic pituitary adrenal (HPA) axis reactivity.
“unacceptably high.” In the methodology, genes, For 5-HTTLPR, Fig. 10.1, taken from Caspi
environment, and even the scale and statistical et al. (2011), indicates that short allele (s) carri-
model used might be chosen inappropriately. It is ers, who are more susceptible, have up to five
impossible to control for all covariates and con- brain regions/neural circuitry affected in their
founders in cG × E research. Nevertheless, the response to threat/stress in the environment. It
literature presents a fast-developing field con- appears the variant is related to a more general
verging on certain genes as especially important personality trait involving negative affect or neu-
as influences on behavior, development, disorder, roticism (instability), rather than to a more spe-
and so on. cific mood, such as depression.
230

Table 10.1 Gene–environment interactions on mental health outcomes reported in the literature
Direct first-order effects
Gene Exposure Outcome Genotype Exposure Reference Replicated Reviewed
MAOA Child abuse Antisocial behavior No Yes Caspi et al. (2002) Yes Taylor and Kim-Cohen (2007)
SERT Child abuse/life Depression No Yes Caspi et al. (2003) Yes Uher and McGuffin (2008)
events Brown and Harris (2008)
Munafo, Durrant, Lewis, and Flint (2009)
Risch et al. (2009)
10

CRHR1 Child abuse Depression No Yes Bradley et al. (2008) Yes


FKBP5 Child abuse Posttraumatic stress disorder No Yes Binder et al. (2008)
COMT Cannabis Psychosis No Yes Caspi et al. (2005)
DRD4 Season of birth Attention-deficit No Yes Seeger, Schloss, Schmidt,
hyperactivity disorder Ruter-Jungfleisch, and Henn
(ADHD) (2004)
DRD4 Parenting ADHD No Yes Sheese, Voelker, Rothbart, Yes Thapar, Langley, Owen, and O’Donovan
and Posner (2007) (2007)
DRD2 Parenting (rules) Alcohol use No Yes van der Zwaluw et al. (2010)
DAT1 Mother alcohol ADHD No Yes Brookes et al. (2006)
use in pregnancy
Adopted by permission of Oxford University Press. Uher, R. (2011a). Gene-environment interactions. In K. S. Kendler, S. R. Jaffee, & D. Romer (Eds.), The dynamic genome and
mental health: The role of genes and environments in youth development (pp. 29–58). New York: Oxford University Press. Reprinted by permission of Oxford University Press,
USA. [Table 2.1, Page 38]
Gene × Environment Interaction: The Environmental Revolution
The G × E Model 231

Fig. 10.1 The 5-HTTLPR S T P


(Short) polymorphism affects (volume increased)
the neural circuitry for
responding to stress and
threat in the environment (as
implicated in humans and
nonhuman primates).
Abbreviation: T = thalamus,
P = pulvinar, mPFC = medial
prefrontal cortex,
UC = urcinate fasciculus,
A = amygdala. Note. Increases
in s carriers: conditioned fear;
startle (auditory); sympathetic
nervous system reactivity;
hypothalamic pituitary
adrenal (HPA) reactivity; mPFC
attention to threat bias; (altered A functional
retrograde amnesia coupling)
(emotionally induced);
financial risk aversion,
blushing (socially). Adapted
from Caspi, Hariri, Holmes, UC A
Uher, and Moffitt (2011), (reduced integrity of (reactivity increased)
slightly modified microstructure)

Qualifications Kendler (2011) noted that genet- (rGE) is much “firmer” (e.g., genetic risk factors
icists understand environment as everything that for disease also increase the probability of expo-
is not genetic. For social scientists, it refers to sure to the environmental stressor). The concept
what is “outside the skin.” In its extreme, the of rGE “flips” the causal relationship from
geneticists’ definition of environment includes humans as passive recipients of the environment
measurement error. Also, Kendler noted that to active environmental “creators” outside the
genetics and environment are considered interre- skin (see Fig. 10.2).
lated both statistically and biologically, or in Development adds complexity to gene–envi-
terms of how environment influences gene ronment effects. Genetic influence might be
expression. Biologically, it refers to how genes delayed and a new genetic variation could impact
and environment work together in creating phe- the phenotype later on. Genetic attenuation is
notype. Statistically, it refers to the effect of cer- when it has less of an effect later on.
tain combinations of allelic variants of genes and Developmental homotypy is when genes influ-
certain environments relevant to the functional ence the phenotype the same way over time. In
activity of the genes. I note that these are quite developmental heterotypy, the genes express dif-
different conceptions, with the latter limiting out- ferent phenotypes at different developmental
comes to a simultaneous presence of specific periods. For Kendler (2011), this illustrates the
components of two factors (genetic, environmen- dynamic nature of development and that the
tal) and the former expansively allowing any boundary between genes and environment is
type of additive interactions over multiple vari- more porous and less clear than it seems.
ants of both factors. Rutter (2011) also noted the distinction
Kendler (2011) queried the impact of G × E between statistical and phenomenal interaction in
interactions, and the extent to which they have G × E. He discussed whether G × E interactions
been surpassed by other genetic phenomena. For reflect statistical/mathematical manipulations
Kendler, the G × E interaction might be ephem- only, or also whether they address underlying
eral. In contrast, gene–environment correlation psychological, developmental, and biological
232 10 Gene × Environment Interaction: The Environmental Revolution

Fig. 10.2 Disease a Traditional Model


etiology in relation to
environment. The top
model (traditional)
shows disease
susceptibility resulting Genes, G
from genetic pathways [DNA
and the environment, (RNA
with the latter effect due Protein)] Susceptibility Environment (E)
solely from the
environment to the
organism. The bottom Body Skin
model presents an
outside-the-skin
pathway—genetic
factors influence the b “Outside The Skin” Model
brain and behavior,
so that the organism
can alter the Genes, G [DNA (RNA, Protein)]
environment. Adapted
from Kendler (2011)

Brain Behavior Environment (E)

Body Skin

mediation of the outcomes involved. Statistically Burt (2011) noted that in gene–environment
significant interactions should be discussed in the interplay in genetics, protective factors might
context of theory and of postulated mechanisms “deactivate” genetic influences. Adverse environ-
and not just abstract statistical technicalities. ments might “diminish” the importance of genetic
Moreover, in the latter, there is no firm or best factors. Risky environments might not accentuate
approach, i.e., in neither the approach of analysis but, rather, “obviate” the potential influence of
of variance (ANOVA) statistical nor that of genetic risk, reducing their consequences. She
regression. referred to this phenomenon as “G × E protec-
tion.” In Burt (2015), she added that in “bioeco-
Environment Shanahan and Bauldry (2011) logical” G × E environments that are deleterious
noted that G × E interaction research typically function to amplify environmental influences on
uses measures of environmental markers, such as the behavioral outcomes involved. Further, G × E
stressors. They advocated for a systems approach, vary in their effects across development.
which organizes environmental features (or can- Dickens, Turkheimer, and Beam (2011) pre-
didates) into interrelated interactive networks of sented a reciprocal effects model of cognitive
risk, or coalesced associations. Environmental ability that makes an interesting distinction
candidates accumulate in risk and could become between endogenous and exogenous environ-
nonlinear in mechanism, and their temporal his- ments (see Fig. 10.3). The former are aspects of
tory must be considered (e.g., sensitive periods or the environment affected by individual ability,
programming), including for history prior to whereas the latter are not. Genetic influences on
events at issue. Risks are contextually and per- exogenous environments could become magni-
sonally influenced, too (e.g., prior vulnerabilities/ fied in the process of rGE by the feedback, multi-
protective-resilience factors, subjective meaning plier process between cognitive ability and
ascribed, role-social support at time). endogenous environment.
The G × E Model 233

Fig. 10.3 Reciprocal


Genetics (G)
effects model of
cognitive ability.
Differentiation of the
environment in influence
on behavior (e.g.,
cognitive ability)
includes its endogenous Phenotype
(internal) and exogenous (Cognitive ability)
(external) components.
Adapted from Dickens,
Turkheimer, & Beam
(2011)

Endogenous Exogenous

Environment (E)

Mill (2011) noted that epigenetic changes rather, mental illness is multiply causative or etio-
could serve as pathways to mediate G × E interac- logical heterogeneous. In the case of 5-HTTLPR,
tions. Moreover, epigenetic programming can be the short (s) allele renders carriers more vulnerable
reversed. This might allow for therapeutic inter- to depression following childhood adversity, but
vention, and some psychopharmacological the long (l) allele might lead to depression because
agents might work due to epigenetic program- of other challenges, such as hormonal changes in
ming effects. This illustrates further the dynamic pregnancy (Doornbos et al., 2009).
nature of the genome and epigenome. Also, Uher (2011b) pointed out that factors
Rutter and Dodge (2011) specified that envi- that cause and then perpetuate depression might
ronmental stress is more adverse when chronic, differ (see Fig. 10.4). Proximal factors seem
constituting “the main causal mechanism” in more involved in the former and distal factors in
G × E sensitivities. Moreover, because other peo- the latter (e.g., stressful event, childhood abuse,
ple are involved, it is necessary to “separate respectively) (Brown, Craig, & Harris, 2008).
cause and consequence” pertaining to the indi- However, distal factors might have their influ-
vidual’s own role in the matter. Moreover, inter- ence through epigenetic stamps (see Fig. 10.5)
personal risk processes typically are reciprocal or that accumulate from the early adversity effects,
relational, so their separation and causal role leading to induction of the illness later on after
might be difficult to differentiate. further epigenetic modifications.
Rutter and Dodge (2011) added that environ- Kaufman and Perephetchikova (2011) noted
mental risk factors might be proximal or distal, that, in the case of 5-HTTLPR and of maltreated
and which one is causal in a chain might not be children, there might be a G × G (gene by gene
clear. For example, if it is distal, the proximal one interaction) in expression of gene–environment
only operates noncausally as a by-product of the sensitivities toward depression (with the G × G
distal one. interaction taking place with the brain-derived
Most important, Rutter and Dodge (2011) neurotrophic factor gene, BDNF; Kaufman et al.,
noted that true environmental effects might relate 2006). However, the researchers also found a
to only how the environment is perceived by the moderation of this effect with positive social sup-
individual, or the meaning ascribed. That is, port, indicating a G × G × E × E 4-way interaction
objective environmental features might not be the effect! The supportive environmental appears to
relevant ones in a particular G × E interaction. affect epigenetic marks on glucocorticoid recep-
Uher (2011b) described that G × E effects indi- tor gene promoter activity in the hippocampus
cate that genes do not directly cause mental illness; (McGowan et al., 2009; Weaver et al., 2004).
234 10 Gene × Environment Interaction: The Environmental Revolution

Childhood
abuse/
neglect

Relationships

Stress PERPETUATION

Depression Depression
Starts Chronic
Self-esteem

Fig. 10.4 Child abuse/neglect affects onset/maintenance esteem, help explain it. Childhood abuse/neglect can also
of depression. Child abuse/neglect is associated with act directly to maintain depression. Adapted from Uher
depression onset. Proximal factors, including stressful life (2011b), modified with data from Brown, Craig, and
events, quality of intimate relationships, and low self- Harris (2008)

Early Later Treatment


Environmental neglect relationships antidepressants
Influences abuse work psychotherapy

Developing
Person DEPRESSION

M M M
Genetics/
Epigenetics A A
H M
M H M
M H M
M H
A
DNA

Fig. 10.5 Developmental model of depression etiology treatments counterbalance. Adopted with permission of
and treatment. Genetic script modified by epigenetic Guilford Press. Genes, environment, and personalized
stamps (e.g., DNA methylation, “M”), early environmen- treatment for depression by Uher, R. in Gene-environment
tal factors. Environment in adolescence/adulthood leads to interactions in developmental psychopathology by K. A.
further changes (e.g., histone [H] modifications, “A”), Dodge & M. Rutter, Copyright 2011, reproduced with
depression triggered. Pharmacological/psychosocial permission of Guilford Press. [Figure 8.2, Page 145]
Recent Empirical Research 235

Comment Recent Empirical Research

The concepts qualifying the nature of G × E The following section examines research on
interactions and the nature of the environment G × E in psychological science. It examines
in the interactions point to the complexity of the extensions of the work of Caspi et al. (2002) on
phenomenon and the difficulty in separating child maltreatment and antisocial behavior. It
genetic and environmental effects on behavior. continues with other externalizing behavior.
Statistically, it is possible to establish main Then, it turns to G × E in internalizing behavior,
effects and environmental ones on outcome, as such as depression.
well as interaction effects, but, systemically, the
factors work together and without the clear
boundaries defining them that are assumed in Externalizing
statistical research. For genes, statistically, the
complexities include G × G interaction effects, MAOA Cicchetti, Rogosch, and Thibodeau
and the same type of complicating interaction (2012) have conducted a study illustrating G × E
occurs with E (E × E). Moreover, the interac- interactions in child maltreatment. They con-
tions involved might be over genes and over ducted the first multigenic investigation of the
environmental factors together. Furthermore, question. They considered three candidate genes
the research points to G × E × D (development) as moderators—ones related to tryptophan
interactions. These types of interactions at the hydroxylase, serotonin transporter, and mono-
statistical level narrow the range of what is amine oxidase A (TPH1, 5-HTT, and MAOA,
involved in obtaining outcomes at issue because respectively). All are involved in the regulation of
of the multiple factors involved. However, at the neurotransmitter serotonin, and all have been
the phenomenological level, the complexities in shown to be linked to the suite of aggression, vio-
the types of multifactorial interactions that lence, and other antisocial behavior, beginning
might be at play for any one person are even with the breakthrough research of Caspi et al.
more complex, and expand the range of factors (2002) with MAOA. The authors investigated 10-
to consider in understanding outcome and its to 12-year-olds from low-income homes (in prior
causation or etiology. research, older participants usually have been
In order to understand all the facets of causal- investigated). They used multiple measures and
ity genetically and its interaction with the envi- multiple informants (self, peer, adult camp coun-
ronment, science needs to meet practice, and selor) in a prospective study with a large sample.
emerge with workable formula that consider sta- Maltreatment was evaluated comprehensively.
tistical interactions in the population level There was a control group. In the statistical treat-
research but also factorial interaction at the indi- ment of the data, covariates were used, as well as
vidual level. This will help in elaborating the Bonferroni adjustments to reduce Type I error.
appropriate protective and supportive environ- Cicchetti et al. (2012) described in depth the
ments, including in psychotherapy, which would study by Caspi et al. (2002). These latter research-
lead to controlled or even cured psychopatho- ers had found that negative effects of child mal-
logical outcomes. Just as there are generalist treatment in a longitudinal study of males were
genes that might be involved transdiagnostically significantly less if participants had high com-
in psychopathology, there might be “generalist pared to low MAOA activity, as moderated by the
environments” (e.g., transdiagnostic therapeutic MAOA upstream variable number tandem repeat
approaches) as well as specific ones to help indi- (u-VNTR) polymorphism. They examined four
viduals who suffer disorder and psychological indices of violent behavior (conduct disorder
conditions. diagnosis, violent crime conviction, disposition
236 10 Gene × Environment Interaction: The Environmental Revolution

to violence, antisocial personality disorder symp- antisocial behavior in girls, not boys (Douglas
toms). The Caspi et al. (2002) results indicated et al., 2011; Li & Lee, 2010).
that low MAOA activity could not serve as a buf- As for the results of the Cicchetti et al. (2012)
fer to maltreatment in its effects on violence indi- study, child maltreatment variables demonstrated
cators due to a concomitant effect on strong main effects on antisocial behavior out-
neurotransmitter systems (norepinephrine, sero- come. Genetic effects were clearly G × E ones, in
tonin, dopamine). particular. For nonmaltreated children, genetic
Cicchetti et al. (2012) noted that a meta- variation did not affect indicators of antisocial
analysis by Kim-Cohen et al. (2006) supported behavior. In contrast, for maltreated children,
the findings of Caspi et al. (2002) and replica- specific polymorphisms for each of the three can-
tions have been conducted since (e.g., Åslund didate genes were related to heightened antiso-
et al., 2011; Fergusson, Boden, Horwood, Miller, cial behavior, as indicated by self-report
& Kennedy 2011; Weder et al., 2009; for adults, (Pittsburgh Youth Survey; Loeber, Farrington,
adolescents, and children, respectively; although Stouthamer-Loeber, & Van Kammen, 1998). For
not all studies replicate). MAOA, this referred to the low activity variant of
According to Cicchetti et al. (2012), there the gene and self-report both for lifetime and past
have not been reported G × E studies involving 6-month behavior, but only for boys (see
TPH1. There have been two with 5-HTT, but the Fig. 10.6). [Multiple findings related to TPH1
polymorphism involved (5-HTTLPR) moderated and 5-HTTLPR, but these are not reported here].

Fig. 10.6 Monoamine 10


Oxidase A (MAOA) and
Self Report Past Six Month Conduct Symptoms - Low MAOA Activity
maltreatment status
predict antisocial Self Report Past Six Month Conduct Symptoms - High MAOA Activity
behavior for boys only. 9 Self Report Lifetime Conduct Symptoms - Low MAOA Activity
The figure indicates that Self Report Lifetime Conduct Symptoms - High MAOA Activity
MAOA interacts with
maltreatment experience
in predicting later
8
antisocial behavior in
the boys studied. The
antisocial measure
Antisocial Measure

involved self-reported
conduct symptoms in 7
either the past 6 months
or over the lifetime. The
robust findings and
similar pattern in 6
maltreated and
nonmaltreated
participants speak to the
replicability and 5
generalizability of the
results. Adapted from
Cicchetti, Rogosch, and
Thibodeau (2012) 4

3
Nonmaltreated Maltreated

Maltreated Status
Recent Empirical Research 237

Cicchetti et al. (2012) concluded that there is a (dACC) and also in the amygdala cortex (involved
genetic moderation of the linkage between child in anger regulation and arousal, respectively) as a
maltreatment and antisocial behavior that function of MAOA genotype.
involves polymorphisms of genes related to sero- Denson et al. (2014) found that men possess-
tonin. Moreover, the genetic moderation in this ing the high-risk allele of the MAOA-uVNTR
case is multigenic. Neither direct effect of genes polymorphism expressed greater neural activity
nor rGE effects were found that could account for in the indicated regions compared to the low-risk
antisocial behavior in the population studied. allele (men were tested because the gene is
X-linked). The low-risk allele was associated
MAOA Other Research Choe, Shaw, Hyde, with functional decoupling of the dACC and the
and Forbes (2014) conducted a longitudinal study amygdala, indicating top-down disengagement
of low-income males over 20 years on early puni- of the dACC in anger control when bottom-up
tive discipline and later antisocial behavior. Early amygdala pull is involved, but only for this func-
punitive discipline at 1.5–5 years was related to tional polymorphism.
antisocial behavior at 15–20 years, but only in In G × E research, other studies are examining
those participants with low-activity MAOA geno- externalizing behavior different than antisocial
types. [As mentioned, Caspi et al. (2002) had behavior, and also related behavior, in conjunction
originally shown a G × E interaction in relation to with environmental interactions. Calkins, Propper,
childhood maltreatment and later anti-social and Mills-Koonce (2013) reported G × E interac-
behavior by examining physical abuse and tions involving parenting behavior and develop-
neglect in conjunction with MAOA]. mental psychopathology. For example, Enoch,
The Choe et al. (2014) study expanded the Steer, Newman, Gibson, and Goldman (2010)
scope of the Caspi et al. findings by extending found that the low activity allele of MAOA-LPR
them to measures of harsh parenting. The mea- (length promoter region, a 30-base pair repeat in
sure involved punitive discipline. An early par- the promoter region) was associated with hyper-
enting coding system was applied during activity for 4- and 7-year-old girls who had been
laboratory tasks (e.g., scoring—too strict, exposed to more stressful life events in the period
demanding). Mothers’ behavior had an earlier 0.5–3.5 years of age. For boys, the relationship
effect in these regards compared to that of fathers, involved 0.5–2.5-year adversity and 7-year hyper-
with the effects more visible in toddlerhood for activity. Willoughby, Mills-Koonce, Propper, and
mothers and starting in late adolescence for Waschbusch (2013) found that harsh and intrusive
fathers. The results did not differ according to maternal parenting behavior interacted with the
race (Caucasian, African American). The authors methionine allele of the BDNF gene in 3-year-
concluded that the genetic vulnerability to harsh olds expressing oppositional and callous unemo-
environments includes an effect of punitive disci- tional behavior. Calkins et al. (2013) concluded
pline on later antisocial behavior. that this line of research needs to consider G × G
Denson, Dobson-Stone, Ronay, von Hippel, interactions, as per Sulik et al. (2012).
and Schira (2014) explained that individuals with
the low-risk allele in the promoter region of this 5-HTTLPR Davies and Cicchetti (2014) inves-
gene (high expression allele, MAOA-H, 4 variable tigated mechanisms that are more proximal in the
number tandem repeat allele; uVNTR) are less at interaction of early maternal unresponsiveness
risk for increased aggression compared to those and the 5-HTTLPR genotype, and ultimately
having the high-risk allele (low expression function as precursors to later disruptive behav-
MAOA-L, 3-repeat; Caspi et al., 2002; Kuepper, ioral problems. They postulated that exposure to
Grant, Wielpuetz, & Hennig, 2013). In a labora- adversity early in life leads to negative emotional
tory study, Denson et al. (2014) investigated the reactions when serotonergic function is compro-
relationship of anger-control to an insult, and mised, as with the 5-HTTLPR s allele, and then it
neural activation in the dorsal anterior cingulate leads to externalizing problems (see Fig. 10.7).
238 10 Gene × Environment Interaction: The Environmental Revolution

Functional S allele
High

LL allele
Maternal Unresponsiveness
Low

0 0.5 1 1.5 2 2.5 3 10 20 30 40 50 60 70


Children’s Angry Reactivity Children’s Externalizing Symptoms
to Maternal Anger

Fig. 10.7 The interaction between maternal unrespon- child’s angry reactions to maternal anger, as well as in the
siveness and the 5-HTTLPR gene in children’s anger child’s symptoms of externalization. The particular func-
reactivity and children’s externalizing symptoms. A G × E tional alleles involves are S, L. The outcome measure was
interaction is apparent in degree of maternal responsive taken over 2 years in the latter case and at 1 year in the
and the gene 5-HTTLPR in the outcome measure of the former case. Adapted from Davies and Cicchetti (2014)

The s allele appears to magnify the association fest a heightened irritability in response to mater-
between early maternal unresponsiveness and nal negativity.
later externalization by increasing emotional Beaver, Ratchford, and Ferguson (2009)
reactivity in children confronted by stressful investigated the mediating effect of the
parental events. However, the authors posited 5-HTTLPR polymorphism on the relationship
possible racial differences, in that, for American between exposure to delinquent peers and degree
Black preschoolers, maternal unresponsiveness of self-control. The study found that measures of
predicted later externalization if they carried the level of self-control in adolescence and young
5-HTTLPR ll genotype (e.g., after Anderson & adulthood over 7 years was related to delinquent
Mayes, 2010). peer affiliation in adolescence.
The sample tested consisted of disadvantaged Brody et al. (2014) found a genetic modera-
Black 2-year-olds and their mothers. Two years tion involving 5-HTTLPR serotonin transporter
after initial testing, early maternal unresponsive- promoter gene (SLC6A4) in the longitudinal rela-
ness did indeed predict later externalizing symp- tionship between age-11 harsh parenting experi-
toms for those having the ll genotype. The results ence and age-19 health. The latter was measured
further revealed that these carriers evidenced the using three indicators (C Reactive protein, CRP, a
association by virtue of their tendency to mani- biomarker of chronic inflammation; self-reported
Recent Empirical Research 239

health problems; and depression, as measured by study, early life adversity was scored in the preg-
the Center for Epidemiologic Studies Depression nancy, birth, 6-month, and 5-year assessments.
scale (CES-D; Radloff, 1977). The teenagers Smearman et al. (2014) found that the G allele
were African American youths living in the rural participants who had experienced high social
south. Also, they had their degree of anger mea- stress showed higher age-20 antisocial behavior.
sured at ages 16–18 using the State-Trait Anger Also, they also found an age-15 main effect for G
Expression Inventory (STAEI; Spielberger, allele participants, which was associated with
Jacobs, Russell, & Crane, 1983). more conduct problems. The authors concluded
The results showed that elevated levels of that their G × E results concerned polymorphisms
anger forecast 19-year health, but only for s-allele of rs53576 in interaction with high social stress,
carriers of 5-HTTLPR. That is, ll carriers were which together influence social salience, leading
conferred buffering against poorer health out- to antisocial behavior outcomes.
comes by early harsh parenting.
DRD4 Boyce and Kobor (2015) noted that
OXTR Smearman, Winiarski, Brennan, Najman, Zohsel et al. (2014) found an interaction of
and Johnson (2014) conducted a G × E study on the maternal report of prenatal stress and the 7-repeat
oxytocin receptor gene (OXTR) and antisocial allele of DRD4 (the dopamine D4 receptor gene)
behavior. They argued that the study is interesting for predicting the outcome of conduct/opposi-
because oxytocin is called the love or cuddle hor- tional defiant disorder in early adolescence.
mone. However, rather than being uniquely a posi- Smith, Kryski, Sheikh, Singh, & Hayden (2013)
tive outcome associated hormone, it might found interplay between parenting behavior and
generally heighten the salience of either socially genetic factors in predicting effortful control,
positive or negative stimuli. Genetically, the G which is a self-regulatory ability. It concerns
relative to the A allele of the rs53576 polymor- inhibiting a dominant response option so as to
phism of the OXTR gene might be associated with produce, instead, a subdominant one. It is associ-
giving more attention to salient social cues rather ated with a brain region network involving exec-
than being associated with prosocial behavior utive attention and having dopamine D4
only. The authors studied these possibilities in high receptors, regulated in part by the DRD4 gene.
risk youth (exposed to early maternal depression). The DRD4 7-repeat variant of the exon III
In the study, report measures included the YSR VNTR (variable number tandem repeat) is asso-
(Youth Self-Report; Achenbach, 1991) and the ciated with decreased signal transduction effi-
CBCL (Child Behavior Checklist; Achenbach & ciency, decreased RNA stability, and decreased
Edelbrock 1981) for age 15 youth conduct prob- protein folding efficiency. These alterations
lems. Interviews were used to rate conduct disor- appear to affect signaling and functioning of neu-
der (KSADS-E; Schedule for Affective Disorders ral circuits involved in effortful control. In addi-
and Schizophrenia for School-Aged Children, tion, research has established its association with
Epidemiological Version; Orvaschel, 1995). For behavioral conditions that relate to effortful con-
reported age-20 antisocial behavior, the study trol (e.g., poorer inhibitory control; Congdon,
used the ASR (Adult Self-Report; Achenbach & Lesch, & Canli, 2008). However, at times, the
Rescorla 2003) and ABCL (Adult Behavior research yields contradictory findings (e.g.,
Checklist; Achenbach & Rescorla 2003). Kramer et al. 2009; linking the gene to greater
Antisocial behavior was rated using the SCID-II inhibitory control). This suggests straightforward
(Structured Clinical Interview for DSM-IV Axis genetic models might be only part of the under-
II disorders; First, Gibbon, Spitzer, Williams, & standing of DRD4 in relation to effortful control.
Benjamin, 1997). Social stress at both ages was In this regard, the research demonstrates that
measured by the UCLA Life Stress Interview parenting is a primary social experience that
(UCLALSI; Adrian & Hammen, 1993; Rao, shapes effortful control (Karreman, van Tuijl,
Hammen, & Daley, 1999). In this longitudinal van Aken, & Dekovic, 2006, 2008). However,
240 10 Gene × Environment Interaction: The Environmental Revolution

G × E interaction effects have been found in that Preschoolers who averaged 40 months of age
positive and negative parenting behavior might were tested in the laboratory on two IC tasks. In
affect certain children more than others, in a dif- the tower of patience task, the experimenter and
ferential susceptibility model (Belsky & Pluess, child took turns in building a cardboard block
2009). For example, the 7-repeat DRD4 poly- tower. The experimenter waited in increasing
morphic variant seems to increase differential delays before placing her blocks, forcing the
susceptibility to parenting effects (Bakermans- child to wait longer each time. In the snack delay
Kranenburg & van IJzendoorn 2011). Similarly, task, the child had to wait for a bell to ring before
Sheese, Rothbart, Voelker, and Posner (2012) being allowed to get a candy that was in view
found this type of interaction in work with chil- under an upside down transparent cup. Once
dren’s effortful control. more, the child was forced to wait up to 30 s.
Li et al. (2016) found results concerning the The results showed a main effect for negative
dopamine transporter gene in relation to effortful parenting on IC. In addition, positive parenting
control in children and to their mother’s observed interacted with the participants’ DRD4 7-repeat
parenting quality. The data in the study fit the status in predicting IC. Specifically, having the
diathesis-stress model and not the differential allele was associated with lower IC, but in con-
susceptibility model. The children were studied junction with less positive parenting. As for the
longitudinally between 30 and 54 months. positive parenting behaviors involved, they con-
Effortful control was measured behaviorally, for cerned supportive presence and engagement.
example, by latency to touch a gift bag. Maternal Smith et al. (2013) concluded that further
parenting quality was assessed from videotaped research could specify which aspects of effortful
free play and instructional situations at 30 control are more sensitive to influence of parent-
months, with the behavior measured involving ing and genetic variation.
maternal warmth, sensitivity, and intrusiveness.
The dopamine transporter gene (SLC6A3) vari- Polygenic Salvatore et al. (2015) showed the
ants measured involved single nucleotide poly- power of polygenic scores as predictors in devel-
morphisms (SNPs) and variable number tandem opmental psychopathology. They developed
repeats (VNTR), as well as haplotypes of these scores based on weights of SNPs used in GWAS
variants. The VNTRs involved in the results serve with adults. The scores were found to predict in
to reduce gene expression and so lower dopamine 14-year-olds and in 20-year-olds externalizing
function. These variants specifically concerned disorder score composites and related measures
Intron 8-A/Intron 13-G, Intron 8-A3′-VTR (subclinical externalizing behavior, impulsivity-
VNTR-10, and Intron 13-G/3′-UTR VNTR-10 related traits), including after accounting for rele-
haplotypes. As for the direction of the results, vant confounders. At the same time, parental
children without these VNTR haplotypes were monitoring, in particular, moderated the relation-
susceptible to maternal quality effects on the ships found. The authors concluded that polygenic
effortful control tasks, being less reactive/sensi- scores help reveal G × D (Gene × Development)
tive to varying levels of maternal parenting qual- and G × E effects related to risk for externalizing
ity. Also, these children performed better on disorder and related behavior.
effortful control tasks in the context of less sup-
portive maternal parenting. There were many
other results, but we do not discuss them here. Internalizing
Smith et al. (2013) found that negative parent-
ing interacted with the DRD4 7-repeat variant in 5-HTTLPR G × E research has investigated
predicting laboratory-measured effortful control in internalizing outcomes, and not only externaliz-
preschoolers. They focused on inhibitory control ing ones. For example, Vrshek-Schallhorn et al.
(IC), which concerns inhibiting impulsive behav- (2014) undertook a study that helps specify the
ior in relation to social/contextual motivation. environmental contribution to G × E interactions
Recent Empirical Research 241

in major depression. Recall that Caspi et al. 5-HTTLPR was associated with an increase in
(2003) had found an interaction between the symptoms of depression, but only if they had
5-HTTLPR and stressful life events (SLEs) in the experienced childhood emotional abuse. The
onset of major depressive episodes (MDEs). authors concluded that 10- to 12-year-old girls
Meta-analytic studies have confirmed the out- might be especially sensitive to the negative
come of more depression under the load of stress effects of early childhood emotional abuse, but
increases when carrying the s allele (Karg, only if they have the s allele of 5-HTTLPR.
Burmeister, Shedden, & Sen, 2011), especially Starr, Hammen, Conway, Raposa, and
when stress is measured in interview. Brennan (2014) conducted a study on the sensi-
Vrshek-Schallhorn et al. (2014) extended this tizing effect of early adversity (EA) on depres-
line of research by examining, in particular, inter- sive reactions to later (proximal) stress (PS) in a
personal major SLEs relative to non-interpersonal 20-year longitudinal investigation. Their results
ones in relation to 5-HTTLPR. They measured life showed a G × E × E (Gene × Environment × Envir
stress using the UCLA Life Stress Interview (LSI, onment) interaction (involving EA × PS and
Hammen, 1991). The participants were high 5-HTTLPR s alleles and also CRHR1 A alleles
school juniors oversampled for high neuroticism. (rs110402)). These polymorphisms in serotonin
They were followed annually for 5 years, includ- transporter and corticotropin-releasing hormone
ing using the SCID/NP (Structured Clinical receptor genes moderated the relationship
Interview for DSM-IV Axis I Disorders, nonpa- between depression and recent (proximal)
tient edition; First, Spitzer, Gibbon, & Williams, chronic stress in the context of EA through stress
2001). The authors found that, among major sensitization (resulting in stronger associations
SLEs, only interpersonal ones contributed signifi- between depression and PS).
cantly to the G × E interaction with 5-HTTLPR. In youth from at-risk families, Willner, Morris,
Chronic family stress also appeared involved in McCoy, and Adam (2014) investigated the effect
the results. Vrshek-Schallhorn et al. (2014) con- cumulative risk exposure on a measure of HPA
cluded that, just as genetic studies seek candidate axis activity (diurnal cortisol rhythms over 2
genes, they should study candidate environments. days), but as moderated by the presence of allelic
Banducci et al. (2014) examined the relation- variants considered more at-risk in the promoter
ship between childhood emotional abuse and region of the 5-HTTLPR. For the results of con-
later depressive symptoms in 10- to 12-year-olds. cern to the present section, they found that for ll
They explored the mediation by (or G × E interac- allelic variants, greater cumulative risk exposure
tions of) the 5-HTTLPR gene. The behavioral was associated with lower average cortisol out-
data was collected using scales: the Emotional put. They concluded that dysregulated diurnal
Abuse subscale of the Childhood Trauma cortical rhythms, especially for cortisol waking
Questionnaire (CTQ; Fink, Bertstein, levels, constitute a risk for psychopathology, but
Handelsman, Foote, & Lovejoy 1995) and the in relation to 5-HTTLPR as a risk factor.
Revised Child Anxiety and Depression Scale
(RCADS; Chorpita, Moffitt, & Gray, 2005). COMT Hygen, Guzey, Belsky, Berg-Nielsen,
Caspi et al. (2003) had shown an association and Wichstrøm (2014) showed that different
in adults of this variant and depression, but only styles of parent-oriented behavior in children
if trauma/abuse had been experienced. The with disorganized attachment might be related to
results addressed neither the adolescence period genetic underpinnings rather than to presumed
nor sex differences. Later research has done so parental behavior. In particular, disorganized
(e.g., Åslund et al., 2009; Benjet, Thompson, & attachment is associated with two styles of
Gotlib 2010), but the studies have not examined parent-oriented behavior—controlling-punitive
specific subtypes of abuse, such as childhood (e.g., harsh, threatening, or physical) parent-
emotional abuse. Banducci et al. (2014) found oriented behavior and controlling/caregiving
that, for girls only, each copy of the s allele of (proactively being cheery, polite, or helpful, as if
242 10 Gene × Environment Interaction: The Environmental Revolution

wanting to prevent the parent from becoming As for origins of internalizing difficulties
upset) parent-oriented behavior. related to caregiving, Lavigne et al. (2013) under-
In their prospective, longitudinal study from took a methodologically differentiated study of
4- to 6-years of age (N = 704; Norwegians), G × E interactions in 4-year-old children exam-
Hygen et al. (2014) examined the effect of the ined for behavioral difficulties and parenting risk
catechol-O-methyltransferase (COMT) Val158Met factors. The three target candidate genes exam-
genotype in moderating the effect of disorga- ined were the serotonin transporter gene, 5-HTT,
nized attachment on parental report (mothers also termed SLC6A4, the DRD4, and the MAOA.
overrepresented) of aggressive behavior (accord- The risk factors measured were wide-ranging and
ing to the Children’s Behavior Checklist, (CBCL; included socioeconomic status (SES), life stress,
Achenbach, 1991) and social skills (as per the caregiver depression, caregiver support, care-
Social Skills Rating System, SSRS; Gresham & giver hostility, and their scaffolding skills.
Elliot, 1990). Attachment style was measured In contrast to results with adults for 5-HTTLPR,
using the MCAST (Manchester Child Attachment in which the short (s) allele expresses environ-
Story Task; Green, Stanley, Smith, & Goldwyn, mental sensitivity, the long (l) allele of the sero-
2000), which is a dimensional measure. tonin transporter gene was associated with
The COMT gene carries a SNP located at increased symptoms of oppositional defiance in
codon 158 (Val158Met) that varies in whether it interaction with family stress and also with
transcribes (instructs) for the enzyme COMT the greater increases in depression/anxiety symp-
amino acid valine or methionine. This enzyme toms in interaction with caretaker depression/
breaks down the neurotransmitters (especially family conflict/SES. Other interaction results
dopamine) in the prefrontal cortex (PFC). The were found for boys for MAOA. The DRD4
Val/Val (homozygous for the valine allele) results were limited. There were no rGE effects.
expresses four times as much COMT enzyme
activity in the PFC compared to Met/Met (methi- HTR2A Fraley, Roisman, Booth-LaForce,
onine allele homozygosity), rendering it a more Owen, and Holland (2013) investigated the rela-
at-risk allele. However, the facilitation of its risk tionship between early antecedents of long-term
depends on the presence of childhood adversity. consequences in attachment in terms of genetic
Specifically, for the results in the Hygen et al. and interpersonal origins. Because their study
(2014) study, the behavioral measures used stood was longitudinal, they could determine the rela-
as proxies for the two types of attachment styles, tive weight of early compared to later influences
and gave data significant in the predicted direc- and their changes over developmental time.
tion. Highly attachment-disorganized preschool- Although early antecedents were found, changes
ers who were Val/Val in alleles for COMT became in the effect of variables constituted the most
more aggressive over 2 years and also reduced important influences. The authors concluded that
their positive self-oriented social skills (self- the developmental trajectories involved are
regulation, assertiveness). In Met/Met carriers nuanced and changing, with associations being
who were highly disorganized in attachment, over relatively small.
time, aggressive behavior increased and other- The sample studied was taken from National
oriented social skills (cooperation, responsibility) Institute of Child Health and Human Development
decreased. The authors concluded that the COMT study of Early Child Care and Youth Development
genotype interacts over time in young children (N = 707, followed from age 1 month to age 18
with attachment disorganization status and degree years). Attachment was measured globally by the
in behavioral change (aggression, social skill). Relationships Scales Questionnaire (Griffin &
Alleles allowing for higher dopamine function in Bartholomew, 1994), which examines attachment-
the PFC may favor a less spontaneous/more related avoidance and anxiety. Romantic attach-
deliberate behavioral style in dealing with threat- ment styles were assessed using the Experiences
ening environments, such as in aggressive/fright- in Close Relationships-Revised Questionnaire
ening, unpredictable parental behavior. (Fraley, Waller, & Brennan, 2000). Maternal
Recent Empirical Research 243

sensitivity was assessed in mother–child interac- equivalent type, duration, and intensity of
tions using developmentally appropriate tasks maltreatment (on the MCS; Maltreatment
eliciting engagement (at 6 months, 15 months, 24 Classification System, Barnett, Manly, &
months, 36 months, 54 months, grade 1, grade 3, Cicchetti, 1993). The G-G variant might confer
grade 5, and age 15). Maternal depression was sensitivity to negative social experiences, such as
assessed using the Center for Epidemiological maltreatment in the family, so that carriers are
Studies Depression Scale (Radloff, 1977). Father more attuned to it and affected by it.
absence was scored on a binary scale at each In a study of individual vulnerability to the
wave. Social competence was assessed using the effects of prenatal anxiety on later developing
Social Skills Questionnaire (Gresham & Elliot, child internalizing symptoms up to 15 years of
1990). Friendship quality was scored on the age, O’Donnell, Glover, Holbrook, and O’Connor
Friendship Quality Questionnaire (Parker & (2014) found a role for BDNF polymorphisms
Asher, 1993). Early (54 months) temperament (rs11030121, rs7124442) in G × E interactions.
was assessed with the Children’s Behavior The results showed that there are individual dif-
Questionnaire (Rothbart, Ahadi, Hershey, & ferences in prenatal programming, which acts to
Fisher, 2001). set the body’s response, e.g., in the stress
As for the results, after controlling for con- response, as development proceeds, because of
founds, attachment avoidance was associated the adaptive advantage of predicting and setting
more with changes in maternal sensitivity, as well response to future challenges.
as social competence and friendship relations.
For anxiety, the results involved maternal depres-
sion and social competence. Temperament had Comment
little influence. Genetically, there were signifi-
cant findings only for one polymorphism of The research that has followed upon Caspi et al.’s
interest. Individuals homozygous for the C allele (2002) findings of a (G × E) Maltreatment × Genetic
of the serotonin reception gene HTR2A (rsb313) interaction in the outcome of antisocial and
scored higher in global attachment-related anxi- related behavior is differentiating both the genetic
ety relative to those with the TT or TC alleles. A and environmental sides of the findings. On the
G × E interaction was found—TT carriers of the one hand, multiple polymorphisms seem to be
gene exhibited a greater negative association involved. On the other hand, the parenting behav-
between maternal sensitivity increase and avoid- iors associated with maltreatment are being dif-
ant attachment. These results partially replicate ferentiated. These findings are at the specific level
those of Salo, Jokela, Lehtimäki, and Keltikangas- of the interaction. At the same time, at the broader
Järvinen (2011). level, the polymorphism involved is not associ-
ated only with antisocial behavior. Moreover,
Other Hostinar, Cicchetti, and Rogosch (2014) child maltreatment does not only lead to antiso-
investigated the interaction of maltreatment, per- cial and related behavior. The range of Genetic ×
ceived social support, and presence of the SNP in Environmental interactions that have been studies
the oxytocin receptor gene (OXTR; rs53576) in now includes not only externalizing-related disor-
low SES (socioeconomic status) 13- to 15-year ders and behavior but also internalizing ones.
olds. The G-G homozygote genotype was associ- Overall, genes involved in regulating neu-
ated with a perception of lower social support (on rotransmitters still seem primary in gene–envi-
the NRI, Network of Relationships Inventory; ronment interactions, but this candidate gene
Furman & Buhrmester, 1992) relative to approach is being complemented by studies
A-carriers who had been maltreated. The former examining multiple genes with large study Ns,
youth also reported more internalizing problems and integrating polygenic measures that do not
(on the YSR, Youth Self-Report, Achenbach, specify particular genes. Candidate genes might
1991) than the A-carriers, despite expressing an be found to be significant in the research on
244 10 Gene × Environment Interaction: The Environmental Revolution

Gene × Environment interactions, and we do need Association, 2000) categories generally are “not
to know which ones they are and there locations grounded in biology” (p. 1201), being too hetero-
and mechanisms of action in the brain, but the geneous and complex for discovering gene-
movement in the field is toward ascertaining phenotypic associations.
genetic influence together across genes, and as Instead of using behavioral phenotypes in this
well, in concert with broad environmental mea- type of research, Vrieze et al. (2012) called for
sures, and not just early maltreatment. Moreover, using endophenotypes related to underlying brain
the question of G × E differences for the same processes. They would be more proximal to the
gene–environment combinations at different ages effect of genes, more homogeneous, and more
or developmental epochs (G × E × D) complicates heritable. For Vrieze et al., endophenotypes are
facile understanding of G × E and related genetic developmental in their nature. For example,
influences in the causality of behavior, as shown Iacono and Malone (2011) found that for genetic
next. risk of substance abuse and related disorders, a
promising developmental endophenotype relates
to reduced amplitude of the P300 event-related
(G × E) × Development potential (ERP) as found on an “oddball” task.
Partridge (2011) explored an integration of
Model Vrieze, Iacono, and McGue (2012) developmental behavioral genetics and nonlinear
argued for the importance of psychological the- dynamical systems theory. The author presented
ory about etiology in guiding research on genes, a heuristic phase-space model of variance in
environment, development, and their interaction. developmental history that graphed correspond-
In this regard, they referred to G × E × D interac- ing variance in genetic background and environ-
tion, noting that developmental factors can mod- mental context. The structure of the graph
ify G × E interaction. They advocated for G × D resembles a “butterfly,” and I graphed it simpler
studies [and rG × D ones; rG = correlated gene than in the original (see Fig. 10.9). Each point of
(environment)]. Moreover, to improve theoreti- the figure in the phase portrait represents a phe-
cal and empirical accuracy, they suggested use of notypic possibility within the organism’s hypo-
increasingly refined endophenotypes. thetical ecology. At the midpoint in the figure,
Vrieze et al. (2012) provided a useful diagram even minor, seemingly trivial variations in the
illustrating human DNA structure and variability biology or ecology of the organism can lead to
(see Fig. 10.8). It gives an example of an autoso- major, large-scale, radical phenotypic change,
mal segment of chromosomal DNA. There are with phenotype A or B favored, depending on
several major types or sources of genetic varia- phenotypic place or history in the phase portrait
tion with SNPs, constituting a major such source (the midpoint region is referred to as the “separa-
in humans. Genetic research has focused on com- trix”). However, generally, there is little variation
mon SNPs (e.g., the Val158Met (rs4680) polymor- biologically and ecologically outside of norma-
phism is COMT). Other relevant genetic variants tive ranges, so one phenotype or the other domi-
for psychology include insertions/deletions nates phenotypic dynamics, which gives the
(indels), VNTRs, and copy number variants illusion of strong genetic control (or reduced
(CNVs). reaction range). When phase portraits incorporate
In behavioral genetic research, the search for time, evolution can be plotted within the model.
relationships between genes and behavior has When regions are less explored, the system evi-
been too broad. GWAS studies are computational dences more compactness, canalization, resis-
intensive, without theory and, behaviorally, the tance to change, inflexibility, and vulnerability.
phenotypes examined are far removed from Systems theory allows for concepts such as hier-
proximal genetic influence. For example, DSM archy, levels, self-organization, and emergence,
(Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental and it can inform G × E approaches from a rela-
Disorders, Text Revision; American Psychiatric tional developmental systems perspective.
(G × E) × Development 245

Paternal …ACCCC…
Chromosome …TGGGG…
TTGGCCTAACCCCCGATTAT
x TTGGCCTAACCACCGATTAT
Maternal …ACCACC…
Chromosome …TGGTGG… Simplified Representation of an
Individual’s DNA Sequence
(with SNP)

ATTGGCCTAACCCCCGATTAT
SNP ATTGGCCTAACCACCGATTAT

ATTGGCCTAACCGATCCCGATTAT
Insertion-Deletion (Indel) ATTGGCCTAACC…….CCCGATTAT

ATTGGCCTAACCCCCGATTAT
Block Substitution
ATTGGCCTAACAGTAGATTAT

ATTGGCCTAACCCCCGATTAT
Inversion ATTAATCCGGCCCCCGATTAT

Variable Number ATTCAGCAGCAGACCCCCGATTAT


Tandem Repeat (VNTR) ATTCAGCAG…….ACCCCCGATTAT

Copy Number Variant (CNV) ATTCGATCATGTCGGTGGGGCTA…


ATT………………………………………...

Note. Bolded dots indicate that paternal


segment does not exist on maternal
chromosome
(i.e., an indel)

Fig. 10.8 Common forms of DNA variation in genetics, maternal and paternal autosomal segments. The figure
with chromosome sources. Humans have two chromo- indicated the SNP as well as several common types of
somes, one inherited from the biological father (paternal, structural variation, which is not necessarily all within
Y or X) and one from the biological mother (maternal, X). any one person. For example, the individual person dia-
The DNA sequences involved are represented by two grammed is heterozygous for the SNP, but other individu-
rows of bases: (adenine (A) with thymine (T); cytosine als may be homozygous CC or homozygous AA. Adapted
(C) with guanine (G). The CA single nucleotide polymor- from Vrieze, Iacono, and McGue (2012)
phism (SNP) represents the only difference between the

Overton (2011) concluded the special issue on Belsky and Hartman (2014) argued that a sys-
G × E interplay edited by Wanke and Spittel tems level genetic approach is needed in G × E
(2011) by considering the cohesion afforded by research. They referred to Belsky and Pluess
integrating relational developmental systems (2009, 2013), who have shown that G × E interac-
models and behavior genetics. The former con- tions involve susceptibility genes (carriers of cer-
centrates on causal patterns in the development tain genes respond for better or worse, depending
of intraindividual variation, or in differences on the quality of the environment experienced).
within the individual, and this approach can There is evidence for a domain-general plasticity
inform the quantitative and population approach in this regard. For example, in a meta-analysis of
of behavior genetics, which focuses on interindi- child and adolescent G × E research, for
vidual variation, or individual differences. 5-HTTLPR, in Caucasian children under 18 years
246 10 Gene × Environment Interaction: The Environmental Revolution

Phenotype 1
variability y

Phenotype 2
variability
Separatrix

Fig. 10.9 Heuristic phase-space model (a) The x-axis refers to variance in developmental history. Adapted from
refers to genetic background variance. (b) The y-axis Partridge (2011)
refers to environmental context variance. (c) The z-axis

of age, s compared to l allele carriers proved The four candidate genes studied included:
more susceptible to both positive and negative (a) 5-HTTLPR. Differences in the promoter
developmental experiences (van IJzendoorn, region of the serotonin transporter linked
Belsky, & Bakermans-Kranenburg, 2012). polymorphic region of the 5-HTT gene have
been related to stress-vulnerability (Caspi
Evidence Cicchetti and Rogosch (2014) con- et al., 2003; Cutuli, Raby, Cicchetti, Englund,
ducted a study of genetic moderation of child & Egeland, 2013; McGrath, Weill, Robinson,
maltreatment on depression/internalizing symp- Macrae, & Smoller, 2012).
toms that illustrates the complexity of gene (b) A second candidate gene that has been
effects on behavior. Not only did they find main studied in relation to depression/internal-
effects for maltreatment but also they found vari- ization concerns BDNF (Gunnar et al.,
ous genetic effects, none of which were straight- 2012). This gene is involved actively in
forward. That is they found G × E, and G × G × E neurogenesis, and is especially distributed
interactions, and also effects of developmental in the cerebral cortex, hippocampus, and
timing (D). Moreover, they examined the gene- basal forebrain.
outcome relationships across four gene polymor- (c) Another gene implicated in this type of
phisms related in the literature to depression/ research is CRHR1 (corticotropin-releas-
internalizing problems. ing hormone receptor 1; Bradley et al.,
Chapter Conclusions 247

2008). CRHR1 serves in the activation of Comment


the HPA axis. It binds to receptors involved
in initiating the stress response, leading to By definition, genes and environment begin to
the release of cortisol from the adrenal have their effects on behavior with conception, if
cortex. not before (think epigenesis and cross-generational
(d) Fourth, the NET (SLC6A2) SNP is located on transmission, as well as the effects of the environ-
the gene that encodes for the norepinephrine ment on the health of the pre-pregnant mother).
(NE) transporter (T). These transporters are That is, in this sense, gene–environment interac-
located on noradrenergic neurons. tions always are developmental (never are not
The participants in the study involved 7- to developmental). Evolutionary concepts, as well,
12-year-old African American children (N = 1096, are gravitating to a central role for development
maltreated and nonmaltreated). Measures (e.g., life history strategy, differential susceptibil-
included the Children’s Depression Inventory ity, evo-devo). Nevertheless, as with the previous
(CDI; Kovacs, 1992), and the Teacher Report discussion of G × E, in general, there are statistical
Form (TRF; Achenbach, 1991, filled in by camp and conceptual differences in the construct, and
counselors). G × E × D could be a narrowing one for effects on
The findings showed that maltreatment was outcomes given the three-way interaction
consistently associated with both outcome involved. Nevertheless, these types of findings
measures of depression/internalization. For the illustrate both the nuances in development and its
CDI, a G × E interaction was found (BDNF × mal- hypercomplexity genetically and environmen-
treatment). The G × G × E findings concerned: tally. They allow for a more comprehensive
BDNF and triallelic 5-HTTLPR both in interac- understanding of the multifactorial interactions in
tion with maltreatment. For the TRF, maltreat- psychopathological outcome that could help in
ment was moderated by triallelic 5-HTTLPR, establishing differentiated and even individual-
with the effects elaborated based on developmen- ized treatments for the child.
tal timing of the maltreatment. Another G × G × E
interaction involved NET moderating the G × E
of maltreatment × 5-HTTLPR. This G × G × E was Chapter Conclusions
extended in terms of variation of maltreatment
subtype. Another G × G × E involved the genes The recent research on the topic of G × E is mov-
BDNF and CRHR1. ing quickly in new directions. At the same time,
As for the particular findings of interest related the phenomenon is not always replicated and,
to the G × G × E interactions, maltreated children moreover, the research also finds that straightfor-
having the s/s genotype of 5-HTTLPR and either ward direct influences of environment or of genet-
of the G genotype (AG, GG) of BDNF scored ics on behavior could occur. For example, Musci
significantly higher on self-reported depression et al. (2016) conducted a study on the course of
compared to controls. Also, maltreated children internalizing symptoms from late childhood to
with the s/l genotype and the AA genotype of late adolescence. They used the major depressive
5-HTTLPR and BDNF, respectively, had signifi- disorder “polygenic” score, which was a signifi-
cantly higher self-reported depression than cant predictor of the outcome involved. Also, the
equivalent controls. The results showed a similar early childhood stressor divorce or death was
pattern for maltreatment in conjunction with involved in the predictions. Finally, no G × E
the l/l and AA alleles of the respective gene interaction was found as predictor in the results.
polymorphisms involved. Overall, the multige- As for studies with G × E findings moving in
netic approach adopted to understand the origins new directions, Rietveld et al. (2014) undertook a
of depression/internalization proved necessary large-scale GWAS on education attainment as an
and fruitful. outcome. They replicated prior findings involving
248 10 Gene × Environment Interaction: The Environmental Revolution

three SNPs in educational attainment. Moreover, attenuated, conditional, or even non-existent,


they had created “polygenic” scores as combined with publication bias a probable confound.
indices of the SNPs, and also replicated the rela- Just as the original thrust in genetic research
tionship between these scores and educational on behavior moved from monogenetic studies to
attainment. They noted the small effect sizes of polygenetic ones, and also from genetic ones to
the individual SNPs involved, which works G × E ones, the research continues to evolve in
against finding them as statistically significant in complexity as its conceptual base evolves. For
small-scale studies. Although the topic of the example, one finds G × G, G × E × D (develop-
research (educational attainment, and its SNPs) is ment), and related extensions.
not the focus of the present work, the general In the field of G × E research, it is too early to
message—that candidate gene studies have some pronounce definitely which genes are associated
value; large-N studies can help replicate results with which outcomes, how the environment mod-
from candidate gene research; GWAS is a power- ifies the relationships, and how exactly they lead
ful approach to the question; and polygenic scores to negative outcomes, such as antisocial and other
add much value to it—are worth nothing. externalizing behaviors and also to depression
However, in examining the range of research and other internalizing behaviors. Moreover,
on G × E, the results are not always consistent or genes and environment themselves are not sepa-
even replicated. For example, Pluess et al. (2011) rable components that independently contribute
found that the effects of maternal anxiety during to their interaction. Their boundaries could be
pregnancy on offspring 6-month temperament fuzzy, as in correlated gene–environment interac-
was moderated by the serotonin transporter poly- tions in which genetic predispositions actively
morphism 5-HTTLPR. Specifically, short (s) influence the environment.
allele carriers were more susceptible to adverse
behavioral profiles in interaction with maternal
antenatal anxiety. However, Braithwaite et al. References
(2013) did not replicate these findings for boys
aged 6 months. Moreover, the results did not Achenbach, T. M. (1991). Integrative guide for the 1991
extend in their longitudinal sample into the CBCL/4-18, YSR, and TRF profiles. Burlington, VT:
13-year age reviewed. The studies appear to differ University of Vermont, Department of Psychiatry.
Achenbach, T. M., & Edelbrock, C. (1981). Behavioral
methodologically on critical variables, and could
problems and competencies reported by parents of
use measures that provide more than a snapshot normal and disturbed children aged 4 through 16.
before the phenomenon at issue is tested fully. Monographs of the Society for Research in Child
Bastiaansen et al. (2014) illustrated the vari- Development, 46, 1–82.
Achenbach, T. M., & Rescorla, L. A. (2003). Manual for
ability in findings on candidate genes and out-
the ASEBA school-age forms and profiles. Burlington,
come. In this case, they investigated the VT: University of Vermont, Research Center for
relationship between the 5-HTTLPR and amyg- Children, Youth, and Families.
dala activation. Hariri et al. (2002) had shown Adrian, C., & Hammen, C. (1993). Stress exposure and
stress generation in children of depressed mothers.
that carriers of the short (s) allele exhibit an
Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology, 61,
increased amygdalar response to negative emo- 354–359.
tional stimuli. A meta-analysis replicated the find- American Psychiatric Association. (2000). Diagnostic
ings (Murphy et al., 2013). Therefore, it appears and statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM-
IV-TR (4th ed., text rev.). Washington, DC: Author.
to be a genetic risk factor for affective disorder.
Anderson, E. R., & Mayes, L. C. (2010). Race/ethnicity
However, as described in their paper, and internalizing disorders in youth: A review. Clinical
Bastiaansen et al. (2014) not only failed to repli- Psychology Review, 30, 338–348.
cate the past findings in their own study but also Åslund, C., Leppert, J., Comasco, E., Nordquist, N.,
Oreland, L., & Nilsson, K. W. (2009). Impact of the
their meta-analysis failed to support them. The
interaction between the 5HTTLPR polymorphism and
authors concluded that the association between maltreatment on adolescent depression. A population-
5-HTTLPR and amygdala activation might be based study. Behavior Genetics, 39, 524–531.
References 249

Åslund, C., Nordquist, N., Comasco, E., Leppert, J., Braithwaite, E. C., Ramchandani, P. G., O’Connor, T. G.,
Oreland, L., & Nilsson, K. W. (2011). Maltreatment, van IJzendoorn, M. H., Bakermans-Kranenburg, M. J.,
MAOA, and delinquency: Sex differences in gene- Glover, V., et al. (2013). No moderating effect of
environment interaction in a large population-based 5-HTTLPR on associations between antenatal anxiety
cohort of adolescents. Behavior Genetics, 41, and infant behavior. Journal of the American Academy
262–272. of Child and Adolescent Psychiatry, 52, 519–526.
Bakermans-Kranenburg, M. J., & van IJzendoorn, M. H. Brody, G. H., Yu, T., Beach, S. R. H., Kogan, S. M.,
(2011). Differential susceptibility to rearing environ- Windle, M., & Philibert, R. A. (2014). Harsh parenting
ment depending on dopamine-related genes: New evi- and adolescent health: A longitudinal analysis with
dence and a meta-analysis. Development and genetic moderation. Health Psychology, 33, 401–409.
Psychopathology, 23, 39–52. Brookes, K. J., Mill, J., Guindalini, C., Curran, S., Xu, X.,
Banducci, A. N., Gomes, M., MacPherson, L., Lejuez, Knight, J., et al. (2006). A common haplotype of the
C. W., Potenza, M. N., Gelernter, et al. (2014). A pre- dopamine transporter gene associated with attention-
liminary examination of the relationship between the deficit/hyperactivity disorder and interacting with
5-HTTLPR and childhood emotional abuse on depres- maternal use of alcohol during pregnancy. Archives of
sive symptoms in 10-12-year-old youth. Psychological General Psychiatry, 63, 74–81.
Trauma: Theory, Research, Practice, and Policy, 6, 1–7. Brown, G. W., Craig, T. K., & Harris, T. O. (2008).
Barnett, D., Manly, J. T., & Cicchetti, D. (1993). Defining Parental maltreatment and proximal risk factors using
child maltreatment: The interface between policy and the childhood experience of care & abuse (CECA)
research. In D. Cicchetti & S. L. Toth (Eds.), Child instrument: A life-course study of adult chronic depres-
abuse, child development, and social policy (pp. 7–73). sion-5. Journal of Affective Disorders, 110, 222–233.
Norwood, NJ: Ablex. Brown, G. W., & Harris, T. O. (2008). Depression and
Bastiaansen, J. A., Servaas, M. N., Bernard, J., Marsman, serotonin transporter 5-HTTLPR polymorphism: A
C., Ormel, J., Nolte, I. M., et al. (2014). Filling the review and a hypothesis concerning gene-environment
gap: Relationship between the serotonin-transporter- interaction. Journal of Affective Disorders, 111, 1–12.
linked polymorphic region and amygdala activation. Burt, A. (2011). Some key issues in the study of gene-
Psychological Science, 25, 2058–2066. environment interplay: Activation, deactivation, and
Beaver, K. M., Ratchford, M., & Ferguson, C. J. (2009). the role of development. Research in Human
Evidence of genetic and environmental effects on the Development, 8, 192–210.
development of low self-control. Criminal Justice and Burt, A. (2015). Evidence that the gene-environment
Behavior, 36, 1158–1172. interactions underlying youth conduct problems vary
Belsky, J., & Hartman, S. (2014). Gene-environment across development. Child Development Perspectives,
interaction in evolutionary perspective: Differential 9, 217–221.
susceptibility to environmental influences. World Calkins, S. D., Propper, C., & Mills-Koonce, W. R.
Psychiatry, 13, 87–89. (2013). A biopsychosocial perspective on parenting
Belsky, J., & Pluess, M. (2009). Beyond diathesis stress: and developmental psychopathology. Development
Differential susceptibility to environmental influences. and Psychopathology, 25, 1399–1414.
Psychological Bulletin, 135, 885–908. Caspi, A., Hariri, A. R., Holmes, A., Uher, R., & Moffitt,
Belsky, J., & Pluess, M. (2013). Beyond risk, resilience T. E. (2011). Genetic sensitivity to the environment:
and dysregulation: Phenotypic plasticity and human The case of the serotonin transporter gene and its
development. Development and Psychopathology, 25, implications for studying complex diseases and traits.
1243–1261. In K. A. Dodge & M. Rutter (Eds.), Gene-environment
Benjet, C., Thompson, R. J., & Gotlib, I. H. (2010). interactions in developmental psychopathology
5-HTTLPR moderates the effect of relational peer vic- (pp. 18–58). New York: Guilford Press.
timization on depressive symptoms in adolescent girls. Caspi, A., McClay, J., Moffitt, T. E., Mill, J., Martin, J.,
Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 51, Craig, I. W., et al. (2002). Role of genotype in the
173–179. cycle of violence in maltreated children. Science, 297,
Binder, E. B., Bradley, R. G., Liu, W., Epstein, M. P., 851–854.
Deveau, T. C., Mercer, K. B., et al. (2008). Association Caspi, A., Moffitt, T. E., Cannon, M., McClay, J., Murray,
of FKBP5 polymorphisms and childhood abuse with R., Harrington, H., et al. (2005). Moderation of the
risk of posttraumatic stress disorder symptoms in effect of adolescent-onset cannabis use on adult psy-
adults. JAMA: The Journal of the American Medical chosis by a functional polymorphism in the catechol-
Association, 299, 1291–1305. O-methyltransferase gene: Longitudinal evidence of a
Boyce, W. T., & Kobor, M. S. (2015). Development and gene × environment interaction. Biological Psychiatry,
the epigenome: The “synapse” of gene-environment 57, 1117–1127.
interplay. Developmental Science, 18, 1–23. Caspi, A., Sugden, K., Moffitt, T. E., Taylor, A., Craig,
Bradley, R. G., Binder, E. B., Epstein, M. P., Tang, Y., I. W., Harrington, H., et al. (2003). Influence of life
Nair, H. P., Liu, W., et al. (2008). Influence of child stress on depression: Moderation by a polymorphism
abuse on adult depression: Moderation by the in the 5-HTT gene. Science, 301, 386–389.
corticotrophin-releasing hormone receptor gene. Choe, D. E., Shaw, D. S., Hyde, L. W., & Forbes, E. E.
Archives of General Psychiatry, 65, 190–200. (2014). Interactions between monoamine oxidase A
250 10 Gene × Environment Interaction: The Environmental Revolution

and punitive discipline in African American and moderator of the effects of adverse childhood experi-
Caucasian men’s antisocial behavior. Clinical ences on risk of antisocial personality disorder.
Psychological Science, 2, 591–601. Psychiatry Genetics, 21, 240–248.
Chorpita, B. F., Moffitt, C. E., & Gray, J. (2005). Duncan, L. E., Pollastri, A. R., & Smoller, J. W. (2014).
Psychometric properties of the revised child anxiety Why many geneticists and psychological scientists have
and depression scale in a clinical sample. Behavior discrepant view about gene-environment interaction
Research and Therapy, 43, 309–322. (G × E) research. American Psychologist, 69, 249–268.
Cicchetti, D., & Rogosch, F. A. (2014). Genetic modera- Ellis, B. J., Boyce, W. T., Belsky, J., Bakermans-
tion of child maltreatment effects on depression and Kranenburg, M. J., & van IJzendoorn, M. H. (2011).
internalizing symptoms by serotonin transporter Differential susceptibility to the environment: An
linked polymorphic region (5-HTTLPR), brain-derived evolutionary-neurodevelopmental theory.
neurotrophic factor (BDNF), norepinephrine trans- Development and Psychopathology, 23, 7–28.
porter (NET), and corticotrophin releasing hormone Enoch, M. A., Steer, C. D., Newman, T. K., Gibson, N. N., &
receptor 1 (CRHR1) genes in African American chil- Goldman, D. D. (2010). Early life stress, MAOA and
dren. Development and Psychopathology, 26, gene-environment interactions predict behavioral disinhi-
1219–1239. bition in children. Genes, Brain and Behavior, 9, 65–74.
Cicchetti, D., Rogosch, F. A., & Thibodeau, E. L. (2012). Fergusson, D. M., Boden, J. M., Horwood, L. J., Miller, A.
The effects of child maltreatment on early signs of L., & Kennedy, M. A. (2011). MAOA, abuse exposure
antisocial behavior: Genetic moderation by tryptophan and antisocial behavior: 30-year longitudinal study.
hydroxylase, serotonin transporter, and monoamine British Journal of Psychiatry, 198, 457–463.
oxidase A genes. Development and Psychopathology, Fergusson, D. M., Horwood, L. J., Miller, A. L., & Kennedy,
24, 907–928. M. A. (2011). Life stress, 5-HTTLPR and mental disor-
Congdon, E., Lesch, K. P., & Canli, T. (2008). Analysis of der: Findings from a 30-year longitudinal study. The
DRD4 and DAY polymorphisms and behavioral inhi- British Journal of Psychiatry, 198, 129–135.
bition in healthy adults: Implications for impulsivity. Fink, L. A., Bertstein, D., Handelsman, L., Foote, J., &
American Journal of Medical Genetics Part B: Lovejoy, M. (1995). Initial reliability and validity of
Neuropsychiatric Genetics, 147, 27–32. the childhood trauma interview: A new multidimen-
Cutuli, J. J., Raby, K. L., Cicchetti, D., Englund, M. M., & sional measure of childhood interpersonal trauma.
Egeland, B. (2013). Contributions of maltreatment and American Journal of Psychiatry, 152, 1329–1335.
serotonin transporter genotype to depression in child- First, M., Gibbon, M., Spitzer, R. L., Williams, J. B. W., &
hood, adolescence, and early adulthood. Journal of Benjamin, L. S. (1997). Structured clinical interview
Affective Disorders, 149, 30–37. for DSM-IV Axis II personality disorders (SCID-II).
Davies, P. T., & Cicchetti, D. (2014). How and why does Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Press.
the 5-HTTLPR gene moderate associated between First, M., Spitzer, R., Gibbon, M., & Williams, J. (2001).
maternal unresponsiveness and children’s disruptive Structured clinical interview for DSM-IV-TR Axis I
problems? Child Development, 85, 484–500. disorders—non-patient edition. New York: Biometrics
Denson, T. F., Dobson-Stone, C., Ronay, R., von Hippel, Research Department, New York State Psychiatric
W., & Schira, M. M. (2014). A functional polymor- Institute.
phism of the MAOA gene is associated with neural Fraley, R. C., Roisman, G. I., Booth-LaForce, C., Owen,
responses to induced anger control. Journal of M. T., & Holland, A. S. (2013). Interpersonal and
Cognitive Neuroscience, 26, 1418–1427. genetic origins of adult attachment styles: A longitudi-
Dick, D. M., Agrawal, A., Keller, M. C., Adkins, A., nal study from infancy to early adulthood. Journal of
Aliev, F., Monroe, S., et al. (2015). Candidate gene- Personality and Social Psychology, 104, 817–838.
environment interaction research: Reflections and rec- Fraley, R. C., Waller, N. G., & Brennan, K. A. (2000). An
ommendations. Perspectives on Psychological item response theory analysis of self-report measures
Science, 10, 37–59. of adult attachment. Journal of Personality and Social
Dickens, W. T., Turkheimer, E., & Beam, C. (2011). The Psychology, 78, 350–365.
social dynamics of the expression of genes for cognitive Furman, W., & Buhrmester, D. (1992). Age and sex dif-
ability. In K. S. Kendler, S. R. Jaffee, & D. Romer (Eds.), ferences in perceptions of networks of personal rela-
The dynamic genome and mental health: The role of tionships. Child Development, 63, 103–115.
genes and environments in youth development (pp. 103– Glaser, Y. G., Zubieta, J-K., Hsu, D. T., Villafuerte, S.,
127). New York: Oxford University Press. Mickey, B. J., Trucco, E. M., et al. (2014). Indirect
Doornbos, B., Dijck-Brouwer, D. A., Kema, I. P., Tanke, effect of corticotrophin-releasing hormone receptor 1
M. A., van Goor, S. A., Muskiet, F. A., et al. (2009). gene variation on negative emotionality and alcohol
The development of peripartum depressive symp- use via right ventrolateral prefrontal cortex. Journal of
toms is associated with gene polymorphisms of Neuroscience, 34, 4099–4107.
MAOA, 5-HTT and COMT. Progress in Green, J. M., Stanley, C., Smith, V., & Goldwyn, R.
Neuropsychopharmacology and Biological Psychiatry, (2000). A new method of evaluating attachment
33, 1250–1254. representations on young school age children—The
Douglas, K., Chan, G., Gelernter, J., Arias, A. J., Anton, Manchester Child Attachment Story Task. Attachment
R. F., Poling, J., et al. (2011). 5-HTTLPR as a potential and Human Development, 2, 48–70.
References 251

Gresham, F. M., & Elliot, S. N. (1990). Social skills rating Kaufman, J., Yang, B. Z., Douglas-Palumberi, H., Grasso,
system manual. Circle Pines, MN: American Guidance D., Lipschitz, D., Houshyar, S., et al. (2006). Brain-
Service. derived neurotrophic factor-5-HTTLPR gene interac-
Griffin, D., & Bartholomew, K. (1994). Metaphysics of tions and environmental modifiers of depression in
measurement: The case of adult attachment. In children. Biological Psychiatry, 59, 673–680.
K. Bartholomew & D. Perlman (Eds.), Advances in Kaufman, J., Yang, B-Z., Douglas-Palumberi, H.,
personal relationships: Vol. 5. Attachment processes in Houshyar, S., Lipschitz, D., Krystal, J. H., et al.
adulthood (pp. 17–52). London, UK: Jessica Kingsley. (2004). Social supports and serotonin transporter gene
Gunnar, M. R., Wenner, J. A., Thomas, K. M., Glatt, moderate depression in maltreated children.
C. E., McKenna, M. C., & Clark, A. G. (2012). The Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences,
brain-derived neurotrophic factor Val66Met polymor- USA, 101, 17316–17321.
phism moderates early deprivation effects on attention Kendler, K. S. (2011). A conceptual overview of gene-
problems. Development and Psychopathology, 24, environment interaction and correlation in a develop-
1215–1223. mental context. In K. S. Kendler, S. R. Jaffee, &
Hammen, C. (1991). Generation of stress in the course of D. Romer (Eds.), The dynamic genome and mental
unipolar depression. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, health: The role of genes and environments in youth
100, 555–561. development (pp. 5–28). New York: Oxford University
Hariri, A. R., Mattay, V. S., Tessitore, A., Kolachana, B., Press.
Fera, F., Goldman, D., et al. (2002). Serotonin trans- Kendler, K. S., Kuhn, J. W., Vittum, J., Prescott, C. A., &
porter genetic variation and the response of the human Riley, B. (2005). The interaction of stressful life events
amygdala. Science, 297, 400–403. and a serotonin transporter polymorphism in the pre-
Hostinar, C. E., Cicchetti, D., & Rogosch, F. A. (2014). diction of episodes of major depression: A replication.
Oxytocin receptor gene polymorphism, perceived social Archives of General Psychiatry, 62, 529–535.
support, and psychological symptoms in maltreated Kim-Cohen, J., Caspi, A., Taylor, A., Williams, B.,
adolescents. Development and Psychopathology, 26, Newcombe, R., Craig, I. W., et al. (2006). MAOA,
465–477. maltreatment, and gene-environment interaction pre-
Hyde, L. W. (2015). Developmental psychopathology in dicting children’s mental health: New evidence and a
an era of molecular genetics and neuroimaging: A meta-analysis. Molecular Psychiatry, 11, 903–913.
development neurogenetics approach. Development Kovacs, M. (1992). Children’s depression inventory man-
and Psychopathology, 27, 587–613. ual. North Tonawanda, NY: Multi-Health Systems.
Hygen, B. W., Guzey, I. C., Belsky, J., Berg-Nielsen, T. S., Kramer, U. M., Rojo, N., Schule, R., Cunillera, T., Schöls,
& Wichstrøm, L. (2014). Catechol-O-methyltransferase L., Marco-Pallarés, J., et al. (2009). ADHD candidate
Val158Met genotype moderates the effect of disorga- gene (DRD4 exon III) affects inhibitory control in a
nized attachment on social development in young chil- healthy sample. BMC Neuroscience, 10, 150.
dren. Development and Psychopathology, 26, 947–961. doi:10.1186/1471-2202-10-150.
Iacono, W. G., & Malone, S. M. (2011). Developmental Kuepper, Y., Grant, P., Wielpuetz, C., & Hennig, J. (2013).
endophenotypes: Indexing genetic risk for substance MAOA-uVNTR genotype predicts interindividual dif-
abuse with the P300 brain event-related potential. ferences in experimental aggressiveness as a function
Child Development Perspectives, 5, 239–247. of the degree of provocation. Behavioral Brain
Karg, K., Burmeister, M., Shedden, K., & Sen, S. (2011). Research, 247, 73–78.
The serotonin transporter promoter variant Lavigne, J. V., Herzing, L. B. K., Cook, E. H., LeBailly,
(5-HTTLPR), stress, and depression meta-analysis S. A., Gouze, K. R., Hopkins, J., et al. (2013).
revisited: Evidence of genetic moderation. Archives of Gene × Environment effects of serotonin transporter,
General Psychiatry, 68, 444–454. dopamine receptor D4, and monoamine oxidase A
Karreman, A., van Tuijl, C., van Aken, M. A. G., & genes with contextual and parenting risk factors on
Dekovic, M. (2006). Parenting and self-regulation in symptoms of oppositional defiant disorder, anxiety,
preschoolers: A meta-analysis. Infant and Child and depression in a community sample of 4-year-old
Development, 15, 561–579. children. Development and Psychopathology, 25,
Karreman, A., van Tuijl, C., van Aken, M. A. G., & 555–575.
Dekovic, M. (2008). Parenting, coparenting, and Li, J. J., & Lee, S. S. (2010). Latent class analysis of anti-
effortful control in preschoolers. Journal of Family social behavior. Interaction of serotonin transporter
Psychology, 22, 30–40. genotype and maltreatment. Journal of Abnormal
Kaufman, J., & Perephetchikova, F. (2011). Promoting Child Psychology, 38, 789–801.
resilience in maltreated children. In K. A. Dodge & Li, Y., Sulik, M. J., Eisenberg, N., Spinrad, T. L., Lemery-
M. Rutter (Eds.), Gene-environment interactions in Chalfant, K., Stover, D. A., et al. (2016). Predicting
developmental psychopathology (pp. 159–188). childhood effortful control from interactions between
New York: Guilford Press. early parenting quality and children’s dopamine
Kaufman, J., Yang, B-Z., Douglas-Palumberi, H., Crouse- transporter gene haplotypes. Development and
Artus, M., Lipschitz, D., Krystal, J. H., et al. (2007). Psychopathology, 28, 199–212.
Genetic and environmental predictors of early alcohol Loeber, R., Farrington, D. P., Stouthamer-Loeber, M., &
use. Biological Psychiatry, 61, 1228–1234. Van Kammen, W. B. (1998). Multiple risk factors for
252 10 Gene × Environment Interaction: The Environmental Revolution

multiproblem boys: Co-occurrence of delinquency, moderates effects of prenatal maternal anxiety on


substance use, attention deficit, conduct problems, infant negative emotionality. Biological Psychiatry,
physical aggression, covert behavior, depressed mood, 69, 520–525.
and shy/withdrawn behavior. In R. Jessor (Ed.), New Radloff, L. S. (1977). The CES-D scale: A self-report
perspectives on adolescent risk behavior (pp. 90–149). depression scale for research in the general population.
New York: Cambridge University Press. Applied Psychological Measurement, 1, 385–401.
McGowan, P. O., Sasaki, A., D’Alessio, A. C., Dymov, S., Rao, U. M. A., Hammen, C., & Daley, S. E. (1999).
Labonté, B., Szyf, M., et al. (2009). Epigenetic regula- Continuity of depression during the transition to adult-
tion of the glucocorticoid receptor in human brain hood: A 5-year longitudinal study of young women.
associates with childhood abuse. Nature Neuroscience, Journal of the American Academy of Child &
12, 342–348. Adolescent Psychiatry, 38, 908–915.
McGrath, L. M., Weill, S., Robinson, E. B., Macrae, R., & Rietveld, C. A., Conley, D., Eriksson, N., Esko, T.,
Smoller, J. W. (2012). Bringing a developmental per- Medland, S. E., Vinkhuyzen, A. A. E., et al. (2014).
spective to anxiety genetics. Development and Replicability and robustness of genome-wide-
Psychopathology, 24, 1179–1193. association studies for behavioral traits. Psychological
Mill, J. (2011). Epigenetic effects on gene function and Science, 25, 1975–1986.
their role in mediating gene-environment interactions. Risch, N., Herrell, R., Lehner, T., Liang, K. Y., Eaves, L.,
In K. S. Kendler, S. R. Jaffee, & D. Romer (Eds.), The Hoh, J., et al. (2009). Interaction between the sero-
dynamic genome and mental health: The role of genes tonin transporter gene (5-HTTLPR), stressful life
and environments in youth development (pp. 145– events, and risk of depression: A meta-analysis.
171). New York: Oxford University Press. Journal of the American Medical Association, 301,
Munafo, M. R., Durrant, C., Lewis, G., & Flint, J. (2009). 2462–2471.
Gene × environment interactions at the serotonin trans- Rothbart, M. K., Ahadi, S. A., Hershey, K., & Fisher, P.
porter locus. Biological Psychiatry, 65, 211–219. (2001). Investigations of temperament at three to
Murphy, S. E., Nobury, R., Godlewska, B. R., Cowen, seven years: The children’s behavior questionnaire.
P. J., Mannic, Z. M., Harmer, C. J., et al. (2013). The Child Development, 72, 1394–1408.
effect of the serotonin transporter polymorphism Rutter, M. (2011). Gene-environment interplay: Scientific
(5-HTTLPR) on amygdala function: A meta-analysis. issues and challenges. In K. A. Dodge & M. Rutter
Molecular Psychiatry, 18, 512–520. (Eds.), Gene-environment interactions in developmen-
Musci, R. J., Masyn, K. E., Benke, K., Maher, B., Uhl, G., tal psychopathology (pp. 3–17). New York: Guilford
& Ialongo, N. S. (2016). The effects of the interplay of Press.
genetics and early environmental risk on the course of Rutter, M., & Dodge, K. A. (2011). Gene-environment
internalizing symptoms form late childhood through interactions: State of the science. In K. A. Dodge &
adolescence. Development and Psychopathology, 28, M. Rutter (Eds.), Gene-environment interactions in
225–237. developmental psychopathology (pp. 87–101).
O’Donnell, K. J., Glover, V., Holbrook, J. D., & O’Connor, New York: Guilford Press.
T. G. (2014). Maternal prenatal anxiety and child Salo, J., Jokela, M., Lehtimäki, T., & Keltikangas-
brain-derived neurotrophic factor (BDNF) genotype: Järvinen, L. (2011). Serotonin receptor 2A gene mod-
Effects on internalizing symptoms from 4 to 15 years erates the effect of childhood maternal nurturance on
of age. Development and Psychopathology, 26, adulthood social attachment. Genes, Brain and
1255–1266. Behavior, 10, 702–709.
Orvaschel, H. (1995). The schedule for affective disorders Salvatore, J. E., Aliev, F., Bucholz, K., Agrawal, A.,
and schizophrenia for school-age children—epidemio- Hesselbrock, V., Hesselbrock, M., et al. (2015).
logic version 5 (K-SADS-E-5). Fort Lauderdale, FL: Polygenic risk for externalizing disorders: Gene-by-
Author. development and gene-by-environment effects in ado-
Overton, W. F. (2011). Relational developmental systems lescents and young adults. Clinical Psychological
and quantitative behavior genetics: Alternative or par- Science, 3, 189–201.
allel methodologies? Research in Human Development, Seeger, G., Schloss, P., Schmidt, M. H., Ruter-Jungfleisch,
8, 258–263. A., & Henn, F. A. (2004). Gene-environment interac-
Parker, J. G., & Asher, S. R. (1993). Friendship and friend- tion in hyperkinetic conduct disorder (HD + CD) as
ship quality in middle childhood: Links with peer group indicated by season of birth variations in dopamine
acceptance and feelings of loneliness and social dissat- receptor (DRD4) gene polymorphism. Neuroscience
isfaction. Developmental Psychology, 29, 611–621. Letters, 366, 282–286.
Partridge, T. Y. (2011). Methodological advances toward a Shanahan, M. J., & Bauldry, S. (2011). Improving envi-
dynamic developmental behavioral genetics: Bridging ronmental markers in gene-environment research:
the gap. Research in Human Development, 8, Insights from life-course sociology. In K. S. Kendler,
242–257. S. R. Jaffee, & D. Romer (Eds.), The dynamic genome
Pluess, M., Velders, F. P., Belsky, J., van IJzendoorn, and mental health: The role of genes and environments
M. H., Bakermans-Kranenburg, M. J., Jaddoe, V. W., in youth development (pp. 59–78). New York: Oxford
et al. (2011). Serotonin transporter polymorphism University Press.
References 253

Sheese, B. E., Rothbart, M. K., Voelker, P. M., & Posner, Uher, R., & McGuffin, P. (2008). The moderation by the
M. I. (2012). The dopamine receptor D4 gene 7-repeat serotonin transporter gene of environmental adversity
allele interacts with parenting quality to predict effort- in the aetiology of mental illness: Review and method-
ful control in four-year-old children. Child ological analysis. Molecular Psychiatry, 13, 131–146.
Development Research, 1–6. doi:10.1155/2012/863242. van der Zwaluw, C. S., Engels, R. C., Vermulst, A. A.,
Sheese, B. E., Voelker, P. M., Rothbart, M. K., & Posner, Rose, R. J., Verkes, R. J., Buitelaar, J., Franke, B., &
M. I. (2007). Parenting quality interacts with genetic Scholte, R. H. (2010). A serotonin transporter poly-
variation in dopamine receptor D4 to influence tem- morphism (5-HTTLPR) predicts the development of
perament in early childhood. Developmental adolescent alcohol use. Drug and Alcohol Dependence,
Psychopathology, 19, 1039–1046. 112, 134–139.
Smearman, E. L., Winiarski, D. A., Brennan, P. A., van IJzendoorn, M. H., Belsky, J., & Bakermans-
Najman, J., & Johnson, K. C. (2014). Social stress and Kranenburg, M. J. (2012). Serotonin transporter geno-
the oxytocin receptor gene interact to predict antiso- type 5HTTLPR as a marker of differential
cial behavior in an at-risk cohort. Development and susceptibility? A meta-analysis of child and adoles-
Psychopathology, 27, 309–318. cent gene-by-environment studies. Translational
Smith, H. J., Kryski, K. R., Sheikh, H. I., Singh, S. M., & Psychiatry, 7, e147. doi:10.1038/tp.2012.73.
Hayden. E, P. (2013). The role of parenting and dopa- Vrieze, S. I., Iacono, W. G., & McGue, M. (2012).
mine D4 receptor gene polymorphisms in children’s Confluence of genes, environment, development, and
inhibitory control. Developmental Science, 16, 515–530. behavior in a post Genome-Wide Association Study
Spielberger, C. D., Jacobs, G., Russell, S., & Crane, R. S. world. Development and Psychopathology, 24,
(1983). Assessment of anger: The State-Trait Anger 1195–1214.
Scale. In J. N. Butcher & C. D., Spielberger (Eds.) Vrshek-Schallhorn, S., Mineka, S., Zinbarg, R. E., Craske,
Advances in personality assessment (pp. 159–187). M. G., Griffith, J. W., Sutton, J., et al. (2014). Refining
Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. the candidate environment: Interpersonal stress, the
Starr, L. R., Hammen, C., Conway, C. C., Raposa, E., & serotonin transporter polymorphism, and gene-
Brennan, P. A. (2014). Sensitizing effect of early environment interactions in major depression. Clinical
adversity on depressive reactions to later proximal Psychological Science, 2, 235–248.
stress: Moderation by polymorphisms in serotonin Wanke, K. L., & Spittel, M. L. (2011). Advancing research
transporter and corticotrophin releasing hormone in gene-environment interplay: Can developmental
receptor genes in a 20-year longitudinal study. science lead the way? Research in Human
Developmental and Psychopathology, 26, 1241–1254. Development, 8, 165–172.
Sulik, M. J., Eisenberg, N., Lemery-Chalfant, K., Spinrad, Weaver, I. C., Cervoni, N., Champagne, F. A., D’Alessio,
T. L., Silva, K. M., Eggum, N. D., et al. (2012). A. C., Sharma, S., Seckl, J. R., et al. (2004). Epigenetic
Interactions between serotonin transporter gene haplo- programming by maternal behavior. Nature
types and quality of mothers’ parenting predict the Neuroscience, 7, 847–854.
development of children’s noncompliance. Weder, N., Yang, B. Z., Douglas-Palumberi, H., Massey,
Developmental Psychology, 48, 740–754. J., Krystal, J. H., Gelernter, J., et al. (2009). MAOA
Sullivan, P. F., Daly, M. J., & O’Donovan, M. (2012). genotype, maltreatment, and aggressive behavior: The
Genetic architectures of psychiatric disorders: The changing impact of genotype at varying levels of
emerging picture and its implications. Nature Reviews trauma. Biological Psychiatry, 65, 417–424.
Genetics, 13, 537–551. Willner, C. J., Morris, P. A., McCoy, D. C., & Adam, E. K.
Taylor, A., & Kim-Cohen, J. (2007). Meta-analysis of (2014). Erratum: Diurnal cortisol rhythms in youth
gene-environment interactions in developmental psy- from risky families: Effects of cumulative risk expo-
chopathology. Developmental Psychopathology, 19, sure and variation in the serotonin transporter linked
1029–1037. polymorphic region gene. Development and
Thapar, A., Langley, K., Owen, M. J., & O’Donovan, Psychopathology, 26, 1185–1188.
M. C. (2007). Advances in genetic findings on atten- Willoughby, M. T., Mills-Koonce, W. R., Propper, C. B.,
tion deficit hyperactivity disorder. Psychological & Waschbusch, D. A. (2013). Observed parenting
Medicine, 37, 1681–1692. behaviors interact with a polymorphism of the brain
Uher, R. (2011a). Gene-environment interactions. In K. S. derived neurotrophic factor gene to predict the emer-
Kendler, S. R. Jaffee, & D. Romer (Eds.), The dynamic gence of oppositional-defiant and callous-unemotional
genome and mental health: The role of genes and envi- behaviors at age 3 years. Development and
ronments in youth development (pp. 29–58). Psychopathology, 25, 903–917.
New York: Oxford University Press. Zohsel, K., Buchmann, A. F., Blomeyer, D., Hohm, E.,
Uher, R. (2011b). Genes, environment, and personalized Schmidt, M. H., Esser, G., et al. (2014). Mothers’ pre-
treatment for depression. In K. A. Dodge & M. Rutter natal stress and their children’s antisocial outcomes –
(Eds.), Gene-environment interactions in developmental A moderating role for the Dopamine D4 Receptor
psychopathology (pp. 140–158). New York: Guilford (DRD4) gene. Journal of Child Psychology and
Press. Psychiatry, 55, 69–76.
Genes and Environments:
The Person Revolution 11

The chapter concludes by calling for


Chapter Introduction conceptualization related to “G × E × P” (person)
interaction. Behavioral causality lies not only in
The present chapter examines three rapidly genes, environment, and their interaction, but
emerging areas in behavior-genetic studies— also in ourselves as active agents beyond the pas-
epigenetics, correlated Gene × Environment inter- sive influence of biology and environment.
actions (rGE), and cultural neuroscience. The
research in the areas is nothing short of astound-
ing and revolutionary. Epigenetics is showing how Epigenetics
the environment can “silence” genes (turn off their
promoter regions, e.g., by DNA methylation), in a DNA Methylation
frank challenge to classic genetics. Moreover, the
altered functionality of the genes can be main- Nikolova and Hariri (2015) noted that epigenesis
tained in subsequent generations because the epi- concerns a non-DNA sequence-based source of
genetic stamps that are involved are passed on as variability in the genome and, together, epigenetic
much as are the genes themselves. effects refer to the epigenome. Epigenetic modifi-
As for rGE, the evocative and active types, in cations do not alter the underlying nucleotide
particular, suggest that genes elicit correspond- sequence; for example, they alter gene promoter
ing environmental effects via the phenotypic regions and subsequent gene expression. There
characteristics that they help promote. Moreover, are several types of epigenetic processes, with the
genes might even lead the promoted phenotypes most widespread concerning DNA methylation.
to seek environmental opportunities (or niches) Specifically in the epigenetic mechanism of DNA
that are consistent with their characteristics (also methylation, a methyl group (-CH3) is added at
called niche construction). the 5-carbon position in the cytosine carbon ring,
Finally, in cultural neuroscience, a strong most often, within a CpG (cytosine-guanine dinu-
interaction among genes, environment, and phe- cleotide) site, to form 5-methylcytosine (5-MC),
notype (including brain) is indicated, including which itself might be further hydroxylated (to
in the selection of different alleles of polymor- 5-MC). When the DNA methylation takes place
phisms in different cultures, or the same allele in CpG-rich regions near the starting (initiation)
having quite different effects in different cultures. site of transcription of a gene (its promoter region,
Some of the brain regions involved in cultural i.e., at CpG islands), the process tends toward
neuroscience includes the medial prefrontal cor- repression of gene expression (full gene silencing
tex (mPFC) and the temporoparietal junction. or relatively reduced gene transcription).

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 255


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_11
256 11 Genes and Environments: The Person Revolution

Zovkic, Meadows, Kaas, and Sweatt (2013) glucocorticoid receptor (GR; NR3C1) gene in the
noted that DNA is methylated initially at the 5′ hippocampus of the brain.
position of the cytosine-pyrimidine (5mc) ring by Boyce and Kobor (2015) explained that DNA
the de novo DNA methyltransferase enzymes methylation is a relatively stable epigenetic tag.
DNMT3a and DNMT3b. The mark can be It involves catalyzation by a group of enzymes
demethylated, for example, in response to envi- referred to as DNA methyltransferases (DNMTs).
ronmental stimuli. Therefore, cycling of epigen- In the methylation, a direct covalent chemical
etic modification and return to the original state modification takes place of a cytosine base posi-
in neuronal elements is normal. tioned next to a guanine base that is adjacent to it
According to Baker-Andresen, Ratnu, and (referred to as CpG dinucleotides). CpG “islands”
Bredy (2013), DNA methylation is mediated by are areas in the genome with relatively high CpG
DNA methyltransferases, with different ones at presence, being notable because, comparatively,
different developmental periods and others at any CpG dinucleotides generally are infrequent in the
time in development. In this regard, DNMT3a genome comparatively. The islands are hypo-
and DNM3b active in embryonic neurogenesis, methylated and express about 70 % of gene pro-
DNMT3a is active in early postnatal neuronal moters. These are the regulatory, transcription
maturation, and DNMT3a (3b?) active in synap- control, noncoding portions of genes. Promoter
tic plasticity. DNMT1, like the de novo DNMT3a, region DNA methylation yielding epigenetic
is active throughout development. marks often takes place in these predisposed
CpG islands.
Boyce and Kobor (2015) also noted the epi-
Effects genetic “paradox.” In early embryogenesis,
epigenesis functions in histological differentia-
Szyf and Bick (2013) pointed out that, in epi- tion such that cellular pathways are stabilized
genetics, DNA methylation markings early in life toward specific ends despite their generic genetic
take place system-wide, and the epigenetic adap- instructions. Epigenesis narrows the genes invol-
tations due to early social adversity could even ved to a genetic “singularity,” a genetic “tabula
affect the T-cells of the immune system. For rasa,” thus finely-tuning the genome for purposes
example, McGowan et al. (2011) had indicated of ontogenetic stability. In contrast, as has been
that chemical, social, and biosphere activity discussed throughout, epigenesis also functions
dynamically interrelates in signal pathways in the elicitation of dynamic variation in tran-
affecting target DNA methylation and demethyl- scriptional activity in response to the effects of
ation enzymes for multiple targets in the genome. environmental cues and contexts. Epigenesis is
Szyf and Bick (2013) continued that the pheno- ubiquitous in brain function and can lead to not
type is altered dynamically by and reciprocally only normal brain development, but also prob-
with, DNA (de)methylation induced by the envi- lems and pathologies therein. As this process
ronment. The resultant DNA methylation matrix becomes increasingly known, it has generated
dynamically and reciprocally “defines” the phe- much enthusiasm for the potential of epigenesis
notype’s relationship with the environment. to help explain many pertinent psychological
Specifically, the research by McGowan et al. phenomena.
(2011) with rats and Suderman, McGowan, However, as noted by Mill and Heijmans
Hallett, Meaney, and Szyf (2012) with humans (2013), the application of epigenesis to under-
indicates that variations in maternal care and standing epidemiology is fraught with statistical
childhood abuse, respectively, affect DNA meth- and conceptual conundra and errors. Nevertheless,
ylation across relevant gene clusters and beyond, despite this caution, Boyce and Kobor (2015)
broadly throughout the genome. In the human maintained that the field is developing a mole-
case, results apply to the genomic region cular account of the interplay of genes and
involving the 6.5 million base-pair region at the environment.
Epigenetics 257

Baker-Andresen et al. (2013) referred to DNA moderate outcome. In terms of mechanism and
methylation as dynamic and affording genomic its locus for epigenetic effects, the placenta
plasticity in support of behavioral adaptation. appears to be highly susceptible to the effects of
Moreover, “the methylome” is regulated “dynam- maternal distress and epigenetic dysregulation
ically” throughout the lifespan. Further, “the neu- (see Fig. 11.1).
ronal methylome” is part of a complex epigenetic Oberlander et al. (2008) studied the impact of
process of many marker types that interact syner- prenatal maternal depression/anxiety in the third
getically. In so doing, the epigenetic modifica- trimester on infant stress response and epigenetic
tions construct an “epigenetic code” that permits dysregulation. They found a correlation of mater-
and regulates synaptic plasticity. The genome is nal distress (as indicated by a questionnaire) and
“metaplastic” yet enduring because of epige- epigenetic effect, or degree of DNA methylation
nesis. For example, “learning-induced” tran- within the glucocorticoid receptor gene as mea-
scriptions are encoded epigenetically, and these sured in fetal cord blood (specifically nuclear
experience-dependent marks help prime (a) the receptor subfamily 3, group C, member 1
transcriptional response to later occurring stimuli [NR3C1]). Further, at 3 months postnatally, the
that are learning-related, as well as (b) associated epigenetic effect predicted an increase in a
neuronal re-activation. salivary-derived measure of cortisol stress
response in the HPA axis on a habituation
information-processing task. Similarly, Radtke
Applications et al. (2011) found that maternal distress (due to
intimate partner violence) in pregnancy was
Monk, Spicer, and Champagne (2012) reviewed associated with the same epigenetic effect in 10-
the research linking prenatal maternal adversity to 19-year-olds. McGowan et al. (2009) helped
to infant development, pointing to a role for epi- specify the brain regions involved in human epi-
genetic pathways. Prenatal maternal distress can genetic effects due to stress. They examined post-
affect not only fetal development but also postna- mortem hippocampal tissue in cases of childhood
tal development, although a prenatal–postnatal abuse (leading to suicide), finding decreased
interplay and also postnatal experiences can expression of the NR3C1 gene, and increased

Placental
function
EV

Maternal
distress Prenatal Infant
EV development development
(prenatal)

Maternal EV
distress
(postnatal)

Fig. 11.1 Epigenetic variation (EV) influences infant tion with prenatal maternal distress). Also, postnatal
behavior. Both direct/indirect pathways of epigenetic maternal distress and placental function are important.
modification influence infant development (in conjunc- Adapted from Monk, Spicer, & Champagne (2012)
258 11 Genes and Environments: The Person Revolution

epigenetic DNA methylation within the gene’s that might accompany early epigenesis due to
regulatory region. That is, early adversity has adversity.
been shown to increase risk for later psychopa- As for the apparent target of prenatal epigen-
thology by epigenetic effects. In this regard, in etic imprints, Monk et al. (2012) described that
further research on adult suicide completers, epigenetic marks can affect gene transcription
compared to completers without an abuse history, within the placenta. The genes involved are
ones having a history of childhood abuse showed termed “imprinted genes,” given their capacity to
different hippocampal GR DNA methylation of be “silenced” by epigenetic stamps, producing
NR3C1 (the GR gene) and also ribosomal RNA epigenetic variations in gene expression. In
genes (Labonté, Yerko et al., 2012). Roth (2013) humans, heightened maternal anxiety in preg-
described that Tyrka, Price, Marsit, Walters, nancy correlated negatively with placental
and Carpenter (2012) showed that parental loss, messenger RNA levels (mRNA of the enzyme
childhood maltreatment, and parental care dis- 11β-hydroxysteroid dehydrogenase 2 gene),
ruption were associated with increased NR3C1 which leads to enzymic inactivation of glucocor-
promoter DNA methylation. Similarly, Tyrka ticoids, so normally reducing circulating mater-
et al. (2015) found that, in preschool-aged chil- nal stress hormones.
dren, methylation of exons 1D and 1F of the GR
gene promoter region was associated with com-
posite measure of adversity. Severe abuse could Extensions
affect hundreds of gene promoter regions in hip-
pocampal DNA (Labonté, Suderman et al., 2012). van IJzendoorn, Bakermans-Kranenburg, and
Boyce and Kobor (2015) noted that early Ebstein (2011) presented a modified G × E model
social adversity gets embedded by epigenesis in of behavioral genetics that included the epigene-
the genome and can have long-term effects. tic process of DNA methylation as a factor
Oberlander et al. (2008) found increased NR3C1, that influences development. They depicted their
GR gene methylation in infants of mothers who model as G × M × E, in which M represents
had experienced high depressive symptoms in methylation status (see Fig. 11.2; van IJzendoorn,
the last trimester of pregnancy. Caspers, Bakermans-Kranenburg, Beach, &
For another polymorphism, Ouellet-Morin Philibert, 2010). Due to the pervasiveness of epi-
et al. (2013) reported more epigenetic stamping genetic stamps deriving from experience that
by DNA methylation of the serotonin transporter silence genes or otherwise alter their expression
gene (5-HTTLPR) in bullied relative to non- in context, the authors described the epigenome
bullied monozygotic co-twins. as dynamic and they recommended that child
Longitudinal research extending into adoles- development be reconceptualized as experiences
cence and adulthood is finding associations involv- sculpting the individual’s DNA through methyla-
ing: (a) childhood disadvantage and genome-wide tion (and presumably other epigenetic change
promoter methylation at mid-life (Borghol et al., mechanisms).
2012); (b) parental stress during infancy and later Epigenesis even affects differentially the
adolescent differential DNA methylation (Essex genetic expression of genes in monozygotic co-
et al. 2013); and (c) early SES (socioeconomic twins, and the effect increases with age (epigenetic
status) and later upregulated inflammatory gene drift; Fraga et al., 2005; Martin, 2005). Epigenesis
expression in the leukocyte transcriptome (Powell begins to work its effect in utero, but it continues
et al., 2013). Methylation of the 5HTT serotonin throughout development (Meaney, 2010).
transporter gene, along with the s allele of the gene, According to van IJzendoorn et al. (2011),
has been associated with adolescent depression methyl binding proteins that bind to the promoter
(Olsson et al. 2010). This type of research speaks to regions of genes are caps that impede access to
the long-term physical (and mental) consequences the gene for the transcription process leading
Epigenetics 259

Fig. 11.2 The


influences on the
phenotype, including
epigenesis Genotype (G)
(methylation). Note. I X
added the developmental
component. The
influence of the
environment on the
phenotype is moderated
by genes and by Environment (E) = Phenotype
epigenesis (methylation,
M; Phenotype =
G × M × E). Adapted
from van IJzendoorn, X
Bakermans-Kranenburg,
and Ebstein (2011)
Methylation (M)

Development

to mRNA and eventual protein production. negative environments compared to controls and,
In embryogenesis, the process of epigenesis acts moreover, if in positive environments, they profited
paradoxically, as has been shown, and could most (Bakermans-Kranenburg & van IJzendoorn,
involve activation as well as gene silencing. At the 2011).
level of activation, it constitutes the mechanism van IJzendoorn et al. (2011) asked in what
that differentiates body cells having the same way could DNA methylation fit into the differen-
DNA sequence by gene expression into cells with tial genetic susceptibility model. They suggested
specialized functions. [Epigenesis is also involved that a possible mechanism involves prenatal
in sexually-differentiated phenotypic expression.] methylation leading to prenatal programming
Therefore, the environmentally-mediated epigen- that renders the affected individuals more liable
esis related to gene-expression in phenotypic to respond negatively to environmental chal-
development is based on a naturally-occurring lenge/adversity (Oberlander et al., 2008). [The
widespread genetic-related process rather than a authors noted that positive postnatal environ-
totally novel adaptation, allowing the flexible ments still could lead to demethylation and better
responses to environmental change and challenge development.]
that it permits across the lifespan. The authors concluded that epigenesis sug-
van IJzendoorn et al. (2011) examined their gests that, in contradistinction to the typical
model in relation to the differential genetic suscep- “nature or nurture” or “nature and nurture” for-
tibility model of Belsky and colleagues (e.g., mula of biological–environmental (interactional)
Belsky, Bakermans-Kranenburg, & van IJzendoorn, promotion of development, to a clear degree,
2007). It concerns the different susceptibility “nature is nurture.” Epigenetic products rather
availed by certain allelic variations to either posi- than genes alone contribute to the canalization of
tive or negative environments in a style that is for development. Epigenesis allows the environment
better or worse. For example, children having less to become “embodied” in the developing indi-
efficient dopamine-related genes fared worse in vidual’s epigenome.
260 11 Genes and Environments: The Person Revolution

Comment with the single nucleotide polymorphism


rs1042778 in the 3′ untranslated region of the
I would add that the manner in which van OXTR, in particular. The authors concluded that
IJzendoorn et al. (2011) have described epigene- the OXT system might serve as a developmental
sis and their G × M × E model clearly suggests antecedent to psychopathology.
that each of us are unique products of our genetic
and environmental histories in which neither G
or E, G × E, or any combination with other terms Internalizing
(G × E × D, G × M × E) prescribe constants in
development applicable across our life histories. For changes in DNA methylation as a function of
At best, G × E, epigenesis, and so on, provide prenatal environment, Roth (2013) described the
scaffolds and their interstices are fitted with per- work of Oberlander and colleagues. Infants born
sonal experiences, including one’s activities to mothers who had reported increased depres-
sought and promoted by our active selves. sion and anxiety in the third pregnancy trimester
In the following, I examine the role of epigen- expressed increased methylation of the NR3C1
esis in both externalizing and internalizing promoter in cord blood cells (Oberlander et al.,
behavior and disorders. Genes do not act alone 2008). The gene encoding the serotonin trans-
in psychopathology, as we have seen in the last porter (SLC6A4) also seemed involved in a simi-
chapters. Moreover, environmental effects can lar effect (Devlin, Brain, Austin, & Oberlander,
silence them in epigenesis. At the same time, 2010).
these epigenetic effects can be reversed through Weder et al. (2014) found that epigenetic
the new psychopharmacologies being developed. marks in conjunction with child abuse in 10-year
These are exciting times for psychiatry in that olds (range 5–14) predicted dimensional ratings
influences on genes that lead to psychopathology of depression. The maltreated children had been
can be targeted and even reversed. removed from their homes; they were compared
to healthy controls. Psychiatric diagnosis was
accomplished using the Schedule for Affective
Externalizing Disorders and Schizophrenia (K-SADS-PL;
Kaufman et al., 1997); the Child Behavior
Recent research implicates a role for DNA meth- Checklist (CBCL; Achenbach & Rescorla, 2001);
ylation epigenetic effects of the gene encoding the Child Dissociative Checklist (CDC; Putnam,
the serotonin transporter in cases of antisocial Helmers, & Trickett, 1993); the Teachers Report
behavior in childhood sexual abuse. This was Form (TRF, a teacher version of the parent-
reported by Beach, Brody, Todorov, Gunter, and scored CBCL; Achenbach & Rescorla, 2001);
Philibert (2011), Vijayendran, Beach, Plume, and the Posttraumatic Stress Disorder Checklist
Brody, and Philibert (2012). (PTSD-CL; Amaya-Jackson, Newman, & Lipschitz,
Dadds et al. (2014) found greater methylation 2000). A questionnaire was used to establish dep-
of the OXTR (oxytocin receptor) gene for two pro- ression (The Mood and Feelings Questionnaire,
moter region CpG nucleotide and guanine nucleo- MFQ; Costello & Angold, 1988).
tide phosphate-linked sites in adolescent males The results concerned methylation values in
expressing oppositional-defiant or conduct disor- three genes (CpG sites) that were significant
der and having higher levels of callous-unemotional genome-wide in predicting depression—DNA-
traits (CUs), as well as child conduct problems Binding Protein Inhibitor ID-3 (ID3); Gluta-
(CPs). The authors concluded that epigenetic mate Receptor, Ionotropic N-methyl-D-aspartate
changes might be contributing to the demonstrated (NMDA) 1 (GRIN1); and Tubulin Polymerization
behavioral outcomes. Promoting Protein (TPPP). ID3 is associated
In another study by Dadds et al. (2014), in two with the stress response, GR1NI with neuroplas-
samples having CPs, high CU trait was associated ticity, and TPPP in neurocircuitry development.
Correlated Gene × Environment 261

The action of methylation of three genes appeared Correlated Gene × Environment


to act independently in affecting depression.
Lower depression was associated with greater Psychopathology and rGE
epigenetic methylation at the CpG sites within
each of the three genes. Introduction Knafo and Jaffee (2013) and
The authors concluded that epigenetic changes Jaffee and Price (2012) reviewed the importance
to genes due to early environmental adversity lead of gene–environment correlation (rGE) in devel-
to pathophysiological impacts and psychiatric ill- opmental psychopathology. It is studied much
ness. However, that the pathways involve epigen- less than G × E interactions, but could have much
esis speaks to their reversibility and that the more impact. Although both concepts involve
window of opportunity is wider than previously genes and environment, rGE might reflect more
believed [also see Nemeroff and Binder (2014)]. genetic influence than G × E because, in the phe-
Kaliman et al. (2014) studied expert medita- nomenon, genes affect the environment. In a
tors who participated in intense meditation using certain sense, this balances the influence of epi-
mindfulness meditation (Kabat-Zinn, 1982), genesis in developmental psychopathology, in
compared to a control group who participated in which the environment can alter gene expression
leisure activities. They found that the meditation (e.g., in gene silencing).
group evidenced apparent epigenetic effects on “rGE” refers to the process through which
genes related to inflammatory processes. In par- the genotype influences or is associated with an
ticular, the meditation group expressed reduced individual’s exposure to the environment result-
activation of histone deacetylase genes (HDAC 2, ing in attendant genetic differences in exposure
3, 9), altered global modification of histones to particular environments. Plomin, DeFries,
(H4ac, H3K4me3), and decreased expression of and Loehlin (1977) described three main ways
pro-inflammatory genes (RIPK2, COX2). Also, in rGE functions in behavior genetics. (a) First, in
both groups, lower level of RIPK2 and HDAC2 passive rGE, genetic relatedness between off-
predicted better recovery of cortisol level in a spring and parent accounts for statistical rela-
social stress test. tions between partially heritable (behavioral)
As for other stress-related research, epigenetic traits and the offspring’s environment (e.g., a
effects in cases of adversity measures and PTSD- parent possesses and transmits a genetic risk for
related measures were found by Koenen et al. aggression that increases both her/his use of
(2011) for SLC6A4 and Uddin et al. (2011) for physical discipline and the offspring’s display
MAN2C1. In terms of changes in DNA methyla- of aggression). (b) In evocative (or reactive)
tion in relation to events later in life, Unternaehrer rGE, the environment reacts to the partially
et al. (2012) found that adults who had experi- heritable (behavioral) traits involved and an
enced war adversity, and who were tested on a association is evident between an offspring’s
social stress test, evidenced stress-evoked DNA genetically-influenced behavior and others’
methylation effects on two stress-related genes— reactions to it. (c) In active rGE, through their
oxytocin receptors and the brain-derived neuro- own actions, offspring actively select or create
trophic factor gene (BDNF). environments or niches that fit a partially heri-
table (behavioral) trait.
Figures 11.3 and 11.4 specify how rGE leads
Comment to more differentiated understanding of causality
in developmental psychopathology. For Knafo
Despite the rapid advance in understanding the and Jaffee (2013), passive and evocative rGE
impact of epigenesis on behavior, McGowan and imply reciprocal causality between parent and
Roth (2015) maintained that it provides only a offspring. Given the feedback involved, minor
beginning toward understanding better how individual differences earlier in life can become
nature and nurture relate to each other. magnified over development.
262 11 Genes and Environments: The Person Revolution

a Evocative (Active) b Passive

Parental
Parental
Genotype behavior
genotype
(Environment)

Behavior Offspring
Offspring
mental
genotype
disorder

Mental
Environment
disorder

Fig. 11.3 Types of genotype-environment correlation use. In passive rGE (b), parental genotype confounds the
(rG × E). In active/evocative genotype-environment correla- relationship between family environment and child behav-
tion (rGE) (a), genotype confounds the relationship between ior. For example, genes predispose the parent to use harsh/
environment and behavior. For example, genes predispose physical discipline and also predispose the child to manifest
to sensation-seeking/seeking out deviant peers/substance aggressive behavior. Adapted from Jaffee (2011)

Parenting Recent research demonstrates rGE. Avinun and Knafo (2014) conducted a meta-
Pener-Tessler et al. (2013) found that mothers analysis of 32 “children-as twin” studies (M2-D2
modified their parenting behavior based on their child twin research) in order to investigate causality
3-year-old boys’ ability for self-control. More- in child outcomes. They distinguished parenting as
over, the child’s 5-HTTLPR genotype affected a factor and whether the child’s genetic influences
the positive parenting behavior involved, in an “affect and shape” parental behavior through rGE,
association driven by the child’s genotype (evoc- in this case “evocative” rGE, or responses evoked
ative rGE). The boys’ self-control mediated the in the environment by genetically-influenced char-
genotype effect (5-HTTLPR) on parenting behav- acteristics. The parental behaviors examined were
ior. That is, the genotype affects self-control, parental positivity and negativity.
which in turn affects positive parenting. In con- The main results of the research found a heri-
clusion, the results show that a simple causal tability estimate of 23 % for parental behavior
model (parenting ⟶ offspring behavior) in this (especially in parental report), supporting a child
area is being supplanted by one that starts with evocative effect on parenting that is genetically
the offspring’s genetic makeup. influenced. The shared and nonshared environ-
Jaffee, Price, and Reyes (2013) noted that mental components in the research accounted for
Hicks et al. (2013) found that lower scores related higher percentages of the variance than the rGE
to following rules/endorsing conventional norms one, suggesting the presence of both parenting
in 11-year-old twins were associated with higher consistency and differential sibling treatment
levels of contextual risk later on in their adoles- within the family. The shared and nonshared
cence. The relationship appeared accounted for environmental influences at play included cul-
by genetic factors as well as shared environmen- ture/SES and intrauterine environment/friend
tal ones common to both constructs. differences, respectively.
Correlated Gene × Environment 263

I. Environmental causality model

Environment Psychopathology

II. Passive rGE

(c) Inheritance
Parent’s genotype Child’s genotype

(a) Heritability: (b) Heritability:


parental behavior child’s behavior

Parenting or parent
Child’s psychopathology
psychopathology

Correlation ref lecting passive rGE

III. Evocative rGE


Child’s genotype

(a) Heritability:
child’s behavior
(b) Evoking response

Environment reacting
Child’s psychopathology
to child
(c) Reaction of environment

Fig. 11.4 Environmental causality model, passive gene- pathology is confounded or initiated by genotype.
environment correlation, and evocative gene-environment Adopted with permission of Cambridge University Press.
correlation. The top panel shows how experience in the Knafo, A., & Jaffee, S. R. (2013). Gene-environment cor-
environment plays a causal role in increasing risk for relation in developmental psychopathology. Development
psychopathology. The middle and bottom panels show and Psychopathology, 25, 1–6; with kind permission from
how the association between the environment and psycho- Cambridge University Press. [Figure 1, Page 2]

The authors concluded that genetically- parenting. The study is noteworthy by showing
influenced child behavior, as evidenced in their that twin studies, or quantitative genetic methods,
rGE data of the evocative type (responses elicited can still provide rich data in the genomic era.
by genetically-influenced characteristics) can Recent molecular genetic studies complement
influence parenting and that parenting is not the the children-as-twin paradigm by showing that
sole factor in child outcome. Children’s geno- the Taq I A1 allele of the dopamine receptor D2
types can causally lead to “meaningful” effects in is related to greater negative mood during parent–
264 11 Genes and Environments: The Person Revolution

child interactions (Mills-Koonce et al., 2007; also genetically-influenced externalizing problems.


see Pener-Tessler et al., 2013). The literature also indicates that child-based
In rGE, genetically-influenced child charac- genetic effects on parenting alter dynamically
teristics elicit parental responses tailored to them, over development and, in considering parent–
so that these genetic influences are “child driven.” child relationships, in general, both parent and
In a twin study, Klahr, Thomas, Hopwood, child genes hold influence.
Klump, and Burt (2013) investigated rGE using a Genetic research is nuancing understanding of
task in which mother–child interactions were typical etiological mechanisms proposed for
rated in real time and according to the interper- common behavioral difficulties and psychiatric
sonal dimensions of warmth and control. disorders. Barnes et al. (2013) found genetic
The results showed that maternal control was influence on early childhood externalizing behav-
especially influenced by rGE processes. In par- ior problems (EBP). Specifically, they examined
ticular, genetic influences on maternal control the relationship in spanking, self-regulation, and
were a function of genetic influences on the EBP, especially in a twin subsample. Typically,
control-oriented behavior of the children. To be EBP has been considered either the result of low
more specific, the children varied in their domi- self-regulation or corporal punishment (leading
nant/submissive behavior, which was partially a to imitation). However, an alternative causal
function of their genetic predispositions, and model is that rGEs are involved, both passive and
the mothers responded online to the variations, evocative (i.e., children shape their environments
thereby indirectly responding to the children’s according to their personal characteristics).
control-oriented genetic predispositions. To con- The results of the study supported the latter
clude, in the study, a driver of maternal behavior hypothesis; the major variables showed bidirec-
appeared based to a degree in the genetic predis- tional relationships and, moreover, genetic influ-
position of the children. ences accounted for some variance for each of
Marceau et al. (2013) investigated the associa- the three measures. It even accounted for some
tions between parental negativity and adolescent of the covariance among them. The authors con-
externalizing problems using a novel experimen- cluded that the causal relationship involved
tal design that allowed them to determine whether might reflect the sequence of genetic risk
rGE could help explain the results. The standard factors → self-regulation → EBP.
model is unidirectional in mechanism—parental
negativity contributes to adolescent behavior. SES Tucker-Drob and Briley (2013) presented
Other theories are transactional or bidirectional. the concept of Gene × SES interaction in cogni-
The twin study design used by Marceau et al. tive development. They argued that, although
(2013) allowed them to combine (a) twin parents behavior genetic and molecular genetic studies
and their adolescents and (b) adolescent twins, support that genes account for 50–70 % of the
their siblings, and their parents. The study variation in cognition, i.e., cognition is heritable
allowed them to investigate a third hypothesis on at this level, the environment has an important
the matter—the genes of adolescents contribute role to play in cognition. Indeed, genetic effects
to both their externalizing problems and their in cognition result from the accumulation of
parents’ negative behavior toward them. environmental effects encountered. Specifically,
The results of the study indicated that parental genetic influences on cognition increase in higher
negativity was associated with adolescent exter- SES. With increased environmental opportunity,
nalizing problems. Moreover, the best explana- individual differences that are genetically under-
tion involved evocative rGE rather than passive pinned increasingly can manifest, and this might
rGE or direct environmental effects. In evocative include selection of environments that are condu-
rGE, parenting behavior style is a response to cive. Therefore, early, slight individual differ-
adolescent externalizing behavior. This impli- ences become magnified with development in
cates parental negativity toward the adolescents’ appropriate context.
Cultural Neuroscience 265

The model described by Tucker-Drob and environmental factors/cultural selection and


Briley (2014) is a transactional one. It is based on evolutionary processes, which in turn cause their
rGE, in which genes influence environmental further refinement for storage/transmission of
experience, constituting a “key mechanism” in adaptive cultural attributes. Moreover, the latter
cognitive development. The transactional model might be represented in domain-specific modules
is bidirectional with positive feedback loops. (see Fig. 11.5). The situation/ontogeny/phylogeny
Selected environments have causal effects, in triangularization mutually affects the reciprocal
turn, on cognition, thereby reinforcing the initial relations among genes, brain, behavior, mind,
genetically-underpinned behavior that led to their and culture. Work on Gene × Culture interactions
selection. (Sasaki, 2013) underscores the complexity in this
Research supports the Gene × SES model in system.
cognition. For low-SES children, heritability
of cognition “approaches zero” (e.g., Harden,
Turkheimer, & Loehlin, 2007), whereas for high 5-HTTLPR
SES, the variance accounted for (individual dif-
ferences explained) is toward 80 %. In support of the model of cultural neuroscience,
Chiao and Blizinsky (2010) examined culture-
gene co-evolution of the cultural values of
Cultural Neuroscience individualism–collectivism and its relation to the
serotonin transporter gene (SLC6A4). They
Chiao, Cheon, Pornpattananangkul, Mrazek, and mapped the degree of individualism–collectivism
Blizinsky (2013) presented an interdigitational in multiple countries in relation to the percent of
model of culture, genes, development, and mind/ the population expressing the short (s) allele of
behavior. Cultural neuroscience is an interdisci- the polymorphism 5-HTTLPR (relative to the
plinary field that explains how neurobiological long, l, allele). The results revealed that nations
processes contribute to the development of dif- expressing more collectivism also showed a
ferential cultural behaviors, values, beliefs, and greater percentage of s allele carriers. The s allele
practices and, in turn, how culture conditions was also associated with nations manifesting less
such neurobiological processes, with the time anxiety/mood disorders, in a relationship medi-
scales involved in the reciprocal causation both ated by an increased prevalence of collectivism.
at the micro and macro levels. Culture stands as a Finally, in a fascinating result, nations with
dynamical system with looping effects and with more pathogen presence exhibited more collec-
neurocultural interactions [Also see Chiao and tivism, in a relationship mediated by the s allele
Immordino-Yang (2013); Han et al. (2013), and of the 5-HTTLPR gene. Chiao and Blizinsky
Sasaki (2013)]. (2010) interpreted the findings in terms of col-
Culture can be differentiated in neurobiologi- lectivist values serving antipathogen functions,
cal processes related to genes and behavior; for i.e., preference for in-group compared to out-
example, cognitive variation has been found in group members. In addition, collectivism serves
brain function across cultures (Han & Northoff, an anti-psychopathological function. The pattern
2008). Other relevant findings concern cultural of results was attributed to cultural and genetic
influences on neural representation of self/iden- selection, e.g., of alleles of the serotonin trans-
tity (Vogeley & Roepstorff, 2009). Culturally- porter gene.
patterned neuronal activities facilitate social Another cultural difference that expresses
survival and reproductive success (Kitayama & gene-culture co-evolution is societal tightness/
Uskul, 2011), indicative of culture-gene (neuro- looseness, which refers to the degree to which a
biological) co-evolution. Core cognitive and neu- nation is sensitive to compliance/violation of
ral architecture might culturally differentiate in social norms (Gelfand et al., 2011). Mrazek,
structure and function due to the interaction of Chiao, Blizinsky, Lun, and Gelfand (2013) found
266 11 Genes and Environments: The Person Revolution

Mind

Vertical, Hierarchical, Interlevel/ Organization Social-affective-


cognitive e.g., Networks
neuroscience

Brain

e.g., Candidate
Neurogenetics functional
polymorphisms
Genes

Horizontal, Intra Level Organization

Time (ontogeny/ phylogeny)

Context (including situation,


culture)

Fig. 11.5 Framework of cultural neuroscience. Cultural are reciprocally constitutive. On the other hand, context is
neuroscience integrates theory and methods in cultural not independent of culture. In the original figure, ontog-
psychology, social-affective-cognitive neuroscience, and eny and phylogeny were considered different time scales.
neurogenetics across research in multiple time scales— For this figure, I removed situation from time scales, and
specifically, situational, ontogenetic, and phylogenetic. considered it as part of overall context. Adapted from
Note that I modified the figure by placing culture as part Chiao, Cheon, Pornpattananangkul, Mrazek, & Blizinsky
of context. In the original figure, culture was placed at a (2013), based on Chiao & Ambady (2007), Chiao (2009),
higher level than mind. On the one hand, mind and culture and Chiao (2011)

that cultural tightness/looseness co-evolved with positive affective cues. Chiao and Blizinsky
the serotonin transporter gene in the production (2010) linked their results to culture-gene
of moral behavior (justification of things like co-evolution.
taxes and cheating). Ecological threat was deter- Similarly, countries ranked high in power dis-
mined in 21 nations, and it predicted tightness/ tance (preference for social hierarchy), which is
looseness due to the s allele variation; also, the related to social hierarchy, have more 5-HTTLPR
latter predicted moral behavior justifiability due s allele carriers (Chiao, 2010). Social dominance
to tightness/looseness. might be another area implicated in gene-cultural
Chiao and Blizinsky (2010) concluded that co-evolution involving 5-HTTLPR s and l alleles.
tight-nation populations express greater social Chiao et al. (2009) found that people living in the
norm sensitivity as a function of greater presence USA or Japan scoring as individualistic expressed
of the s allele, whereas looser nations are associ- increased neural response within the mPFC to
ated with social norm violation tolerance as a self-statements that were general (e.g., I am…)
function of carrying the l allele. The former allele compared to contextual ones (e.g., when talking
has been associated with sensitivity/vigilance to to my mother, I am…). In contrast, individuals
negative affective cues, unlike the latter allele, who were more collectivist expressed mPFC
which has been associated with sensitivity to increases to contextual compared to general
Cultural Neuroscience 267

statements. The results showed that cultural understanding the person [and I add that
values more than nationality/race are involved in developmental processes are equally important].
the modulation of neural response in the mPFC Some of the links in understanding behavior from
during self-processing. a cultural neuroscience perspective include gene-
Cheon et al. (2011) found that populations liv- culture co-evolution (theory of dual inheritance),
ing in countries that express social hierarchies, G × E interaction, gene–culture interaction, and
such as Korea, manifest increased empathic cultural shaping/moderation of brain structure/
neural response within the left temporoparietal function.
junction (L-TPJ) when viewing in-group mem- In the macrolevel interplay between genes and
bers in painful compared to neutral scenarios. culture in co-evolution, cultural selection is both
The social hierarchic populations manifested this influenced by and influences genetic selection
pattern more than egalitarian ones, such as the (also called niche construction). G × E study is
USA. There appears to be cultural influences in exemplified by Caspi’s research (Caspi et al.,
the empathic brain. 2002, 2003) on allelic variations in interaction
Kim and Sasaki (2014) presented a model of with predisposing environments to produce later
cultural neuroscience (see Fig. 11.6) that illus- psychopathologies or problems in behavior. Kim
trates its multiple strands of study. The approach and Sasaki (2014) described a paper by Ishii,
underscores that an individual’s biological and Kim, Sasaki, Shinada, and Kusumi (2014) on
psychological processes are conditioned within whether differential alleles of 5-HTTLPR modu-
cultural context. Evolution also is crucial for late cultural differences in perceiving changes in

Environment x Genetics → Brain → Output


Supportive

A
Environment (Context, Situation, Culture)

Culture Gene(s)

B
Neural
structure(s)
Physiological
F G response(s)

Contextual Neural H
Input Process(es)
Not Supportive

C Behavioral/
D psychological
process(es)

Time
Evolutionary Developmental

Fig. 11.6 Framework of cultural neuroscience: evolu- structural change; (E) gene-culture shaping brain
tionary, developmental, and environmental context. The structure; (F) culture-specific neural activities; (C, G) cul-
model indicates the contextual, environmental, develop- tural moderation of situational cue response; and (H)
ment, and evolutionary processes at work in gene-culture resultant physiological response as correlates of psycho-
interplay for: (A) gene-culture co-evolution; (B → C → D) logical behavioral outcomes. Adapted from Kim & Sasaki
gene-culture interaction; (C, D) neural correlates/ (2014)
268 11 Genes and Environments: The Person Revolution

facial expression. Japanese people judged the of Gene × Culture interaction. A particular genetic
disappearing point of a smile on videos quicker predisposition can lead to different outcomes,
than Americans; and American Asians functioned depending on cultural norms. Similarly, culture
like the latter and not the former. But the Japanese might influence people differentially, depending
with the ss genotype excelled in the task com- on genetic predispositions.
pared to those with the sl and ll genotype. The ss Kitayama et al. (2014) studied whether the
genotype has been related to greater susceptibil- DRD4 moderated cultural differences in inter-
ity to environmental input. Americans did not dependent vs. independent social orientation. In
show this genetic effect. this regard, they examined European Americans
and Asian-born Asians (who had spent 7–10
years in the USA after puberty) on six scales
OXTR (Independent subscale, of the Self-Construal
Scale, Singelis, 1994; General Self-Efficacy
Other research groups are finding relevant results Scale, Schwarzer et al. 1999; Self-Esteem Scale,
for cultural neuroscience. Kim et al. (2010) exam- Rosenberg, 1965; Value of Expression Question-
ined high psychological distress in Americans and naire; Kim & Sherman, 2007; Interdependent
Koreans and their emotional support seeking. The subscale in Singelis, 1994; and the Analysis-
polymorphism examined concerned the G or A Holism Scale; Choi, Koo, & Choi, 2007). A com-
allele of OXTR rs53576, and whether individuals posite measure was derived from the scales.
carried one or two copies of G compared to being The results revealed a Gene × Culture (G × C)
homozygous for A. Having the G allele was asso- interaction. Specifically, the expected cultural
ciated with increased emotional support-seeking difference was found for only 1- or 2-repeat
in both cultures. Kim et al. (2010) concluded that DRD4 alleles. The alleles are part of the variable-
culture and the OXTR gene interact in producing number tandem repeat (VNTR) polymorphism of
psychological well-being. Moreover, the A allele DRD4 (Wang et al., 2004). The most common
is associated with emotional suppression in forms have 2, 4, and 7 repeats (2R, 4R, 7R allele,
Koreans but, in Americans, it is the G allele that is respectively). The 7R allele is more common in
so associated (Kim et al., 2011). Western societies, with the 2R more common in
Sasaki, Kim, and Xu (2011) undertook work Asian ones. Both are associated with reduced
on religiosity, OXTR, and psychological well- dopamine feedback inhibition. This leads to
being. In G × E (culture) results, Koreans who increased dopamine signaling capacity.
expressed greater religiosity and who were The two variants appear to be plasticity alleles,
homozygous for G reported greater psychologi- responding with flourishing outcomes in support-
cal well-being, but Caucasian Americans with the ive environments and problematic ones in
same characteristics reported reduced psycho- adverse environments (Belsky & Pluess, 2009;
logical well-being. Sasaki et al., 2013). The variants could serve in
cultural learning by accentuating reward and
reinforcement. Normatively, behaviors that are
DRD4 consistent with cultural expectations are more
likely to be reinforced.
Sasaki et al. (2013) also found that priming/ Therefore, if cultures have different or even
heightening temporarily a belief in religion opposing cultural norms, the learning involved
served to modulate prosocial behavior/altruism, still could be mediated in the same way by down-
but only for the Dopamine D4 receptor gene stream activities related to the DRD4 allele vari-
(DRD4) allele carrier. This happened both for ants. Given this understanding of how the gene
Caucasian and Asian Americans living in the might function, it makes sense that Kitayama
USA. The results were not found without prim- et al. (2014) found that carriers of the 7R and 2R
ing. Sasaki (2013) explained her results in terms allelic DRD4 variants exhibited different but still
Chapter Conclusions 269

dominant social orientations culturally, compared epigenetic mechanisms, including in fetal


to noncarriers (interdependence for Asians, inde- programming.
pendence for European Americans). The DRD4 The research in the field of genomics and
R allele is not as sensitive in the way indicated to other -omics is burgeoning. However, to under-
cultural learning. stand better development, a refined understand-
However, this assumes that the general envi- ing of the components in G × E and related (e.g.,
ronment for the study participants was generally epigenesis) research is required. Moreover, G × E
favorable for their socialization (e.g., careful should be examined under the umbrella of the
guidance and scaffolding of culturally-sanctioned biopsychosocial model, or one that no longer
or desirable behaviors by relevant socializing parses its constituents into distinct components,
agents, such as parents, teachers). In unfavorable so that likewise G, E, and their interactions no
social conditions/adversity, deviant behaviors longer are considered as ones involving separa-
might eventuate instead (e.g., delinquency, risk ble entities.
taking). Kitayama et al. (2014) related their study
to the co-evolution of genes and culture, as well
as research in the field of cultural neuroscience. Chapter Conclusions

To conclude, the areas of epigenesis, rGE, and


Comments cultural neuroscience have shaken the founda-
tions of genetics, evolution, and brain study. The
Causadias (2013) described the work of Tamis- complex interactive web in the causation of
LeMonda et al. (2008) on individualism– behavior no longer readily separates its compo-
collectivism and culture. Also, he presented the nents into independent areas and, also, no longer
work of Juang, Syed, Cookston, Wang, and Kim can the influences of genes, environment, and
(2012) on an ecological model (Bronfenbrenner, person be considered as separate (and interacting
1994) that inverted the placement of culture in factors). The phenomenon of epigenesis belies
the series of concentric circles in the model, with the view that genes are distinct from the environ-
culture at the center. By doing so, the pervasive ment and inviolately biological in nature.
influence of culture on development is indicated. Similarly, rGE belies the view that the environ-
Nevertheless, Causadias (2013) took pains to ment is distinct from biology and influences
emphasize the link between biology and culture behavioral causality on its own terms. Finally, the
in development, by referring to cultural neurosci- area of cultural neuroscience brings to the fore
ence (Chiao et al., 2009), gene–culture interplay concepts such as G × C (culture), G × SES, and
(Chiao & Blizinsky, 2010), gene–culture interac- gene-culture co-evolution. Whether examining
tion (Dressler, Balieiro, Ribeiro, & Santos, 2008), humans as they are or humans as they had
and cultural epigenetics (Franklin et al., 2010). evolved, in a general sense, in order to under-
For further reading on genomic science and stand behavioral causality, different cultural
development, refer to Grigorenko and Cicchetti influences have become as much indispensable as
(2012). The special issue that they edited includes are different genetic, neuronal, and other envi-
articles on rGE (Jaffee & Price, 2012; Propper, ronmental ones.
Shanahan, Russo, & Mills-Koonce, 2012) that The nature of the indissociability of biology
are worth noting. Also, two articles examined and environment in the genesis of behavior and its
structural variation in the genome in relation to evolution point not only to the revolution taking
development (Gill, 2012; Rucker & McGuffin, place about genetics, the brain, and aspects of the
2012). Naples, Katz, and Grigorenko (2012) environment, including the social and cultural,
explored to good effect neuroendophenotypes in but also to the needed revolution in the field about
psychiatric illness. Also, refer to Knopik, the person, to a degree, as an independently active
Maccani, Francazio, and McGeary (2012) on agent in generating her or his own behavior.
270 11 Genes and Environments: The Person Revolution

The genetic revolution has blurred the boundaries findings is changing the understanding of
of genes and environment and has elaborated development and its causality in complex ways.
intricate concepts of their interaction that includes Some research might emphasize the influence of
development (G × E × D), epistatis (G × G × E), parenting (e.g., Sulik, Blair, Berry, Mills-Koonce,
and nested environmental effects )(G × E × E) but, & Greenberg 2015; on early parenting effects on
in this emerging conceptualization of the role of developing executive function) and some the influ-
biology and environment in behavioral causality, ence of epigenetics and genetics on behavior (e.g.,
there is no interaction described involving the per- Dadds, Moul, Hawes, Diaz, & Brennan, 2015; on
son (and the attributes of the person) that allows epigenetic modification of CpG sites in the NR3C1
for distancing from and active control of genetic promoter region 1 F in 4- to 16-year olds with
and environmental influences on behavior; in comorbid externalizing and anxiety problems).
this regard, we need to consider and create the Thus, the complexity of development demands a
“G × E × P” (person) interaction. Much of the book broad approach in which causality is examined
is dedicated to this premise, that the person him or multifactorially and in novel ways seeking novel
herself can actively influence instead of passively concepts.
react to genetic and environmental influences on
behavior and, consequently, choose, decide, and
act freely instead of deterministically toward References
adaptive ends, everything else being equal, includ-
ing having supportive environments toward that Achenbach, T. M., & Rescorla, L. (2001). Manual for the
end and the development toward the maturity ASEBA school-age forms & profiles. Burlington, VT:
University of Vermont, Research Center for Children,
needed to effect this aspect of self (and other) Youth, & Families.
control. Amaya-Jackson, L., Newman, E., & Lipschitz, D. S.
For example, future research could examine (2000, October). The child PTSD checklist. Paper pre-
not only candidate genes in relation to maltreat- sented at annual meeting of the American Academy of
Child and Adolescent Psychiatry, New York.
ment but also the degree of belief in free will as a Avinun, R., & Knafo, A. (2014). Parenting as a reaction
factor, in interaction with these other factors, in evoked by children’s genotype: A meta-analysis of
antisocial behavior outcome. Or, gene-culture children-as-twins studies. Personality and Social
co-evolution could examine the role of personal Psychology Review, 18, 87–102.
Baker-Andresen, D., Ratnu, V. S., & Bredy, T. W. (2013).
(self, free will) factors that mitigate the influence Dynamic DNA methylation: A prime candidate for
of genes and culture on the evolution of behavior. genomic metaplasticity and behavioral adaptation.
Culture is not monolithic, and individual differ- Trends in Neuroscience, 36, 3–13.
ences abound in attitude and behavior within cul- Bakermans-Kranenburg, M. J., & van IJzendoorn, M. H.
(2011). Differential susceptibility to rearing environ-
tures, so that one could ask to what degree these ment depending on dopamine-related genes: New evi-
types of differences are individually determined dence and a meta-analysis. Development and
through personal choices toward various free- Psychopathology, 23, 39–52.
doms and toward actively choosing, deciding, Barnes, J. C., Boutwell, B. B., Beaver, K. M., & Gibson,
C. L. (2013). Analyzing the origins of childhood
and behaving beyond the influences of genes and externalizing behavioral problems. Developmental
environment (culture). Moreover, it would seem Psychology, 49, 2272–2284.
relevant to determine how has this triune influ- Beach, S. R. H., Brody, G. H., Todorov, A. A.,
ence of heredity, environment (culture), and a Gunter, T. D., & Philibert, R. A. (2011). Methylation at
5HTT mediates the impact of child sex abuse on
personally active being had functioned in the women’s antisocial behavior: An examination of the
evolution of humans, especially in the recent past Iowa adoptee sample. Psychosomatic Medicine, 73,
epochs in our evolution in which personal factors 83–87.
had more of a chance to be pertinent and involved. Belsky, J., Bakermans-Kranenburg, M. J., & van
IJzendoorn, M. H. (2007). For better and for worse:
To conclude these chapters on the genetic and Differential susceptibility to environmental influ-
environmental influences on behavior, the expo- ences. Current Directions in Psychological Science,
nential increase in conceptualization and empirical 16, 300–304.
References 271

Belsky, J., & Pluess, M. (2009). The nature (and nurture?) Chiao, J. Y., & Immordino-Yang, M. H. (2013).
of plasticity in early human development. Perspectives Modularity and the cultural mind: Contributions of
on Psychological Science, 4, 345–351. cultural neuroscience to cognitive theory. Perspectives
Borghol, N., Suderman, M., McArdle, W., Racine, A., on Psychological Science, 8, 56–61.
Hallett, M., Pembrey, M., et al. (2012). Association Choi, I., Koo, M., & Choi, J. A. (2007). Individual differ-
with early life socio-economic position in adult DNA ences in analytic versus holistic thinking. Personality
methylation. International Journal of Epidemiology, and Social Psychology Bulletin, 33, 691–705.
41, 62–74. Costello, E. J., & Angold, A. (1988). Scales to assess
Boyce, W. T., & Kobor, M. S. (2015). Development and child and adolescent depression: Checklists, screens,
the epigenome: The “synapse” of gene-environment and nets. Journal of the American Academy of Child
interplay. Developmental Science, 18, 1–23. and Adolescent Psychiatry, 27, 726–737.
Bronfenbrenner, U. (1994). Ecological models of human Dadds, M. R., Moul, C., Cauchi, A., Dobson-Stone, C.,
development. In T. Husten & T. N. Postlethwaite Hawes, D. J., Brennan, J., et al. (2014). Methylation of
(Eds.), International encyclopedia of education the oxytocin receptor gene and oxytocin blood levels
(2nd ed., Vol. 3, pp. 1643–1647). New York: Elsevier in the development of psychopathy. Development and
Science. Psychopathology, 26, 33–40.
Caspi, A., McClay, J., Moffitt, T. E., Mill, J., Martin, J., Dadds, M. R., Moul, C., Hawes, D. J., Diaz, A. M., &
Craig, I. W., et al. (2002). Role of genotype in the Brennan, J. (2015). Individual differences in child-
cycle of violence in maltreated children. Science, 297, hood behavior disorders associated with epigenetic
851–854. modulation of the cortisol receptor gene. Child
Caspi, A., Sugden, K., Moffitt, T. E., Taylor, A., Craig, Development, 86, 1311–1320.
I. W., Harrington, H., et al. (2003). Influence of life Devlin, A. M., Brain, U., Austin, J., & Oberlander, T. F.
stress on depression: Moderation by a polymorphism (2010). Prenatal exposure to maternal depressed mood
in the 5-HTT gene. Science, 301, 386–389. and the MTHFRC677T variant affect SLC6A4 meth-
Causadias, J. M. (2013). A roadmap for the integration of ylation in infants at birth. PLoS ONE, 5, e12201.
culture into developmental psychopathology. Develop- doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0012201.
ment and Psychopathology, 25, 1375–1398. Dressler, W. W., Balieiro, M. C., Ribeiro, R. P., & Santos,
Cheon, B. K., Im, D., Harada, T., Kim, J., Mathur, V. A., J. E. D. (2008). Cultural consonance, a 5HT2A recep-
Scimeca, J. M., et al. (2011). Cultural influences on tor polymorphism, and depressive symptoms: A longi-
neural basis of intergroup empathy. NeuroImage, 57, tudinal study of gene × culture interaction in urban
642–650. Brazil. American Journal of Human Biology, 21,
Chiao, J. Y. (2009). Cultural neuroscience: A once and 91–97.
future discipline. Progress in Brain Research, 178, Essex, M. J., Boyce, W. T., Hertzman, C., Lam, L. L.,
287–304. Armstrong, J. M., Neumann, S. M., et al. (2013).
Chiao, J. Y. (2010). Neural basis of social status hierarchy Epigenetic vestiges of early developmental adversity:
across species. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 20, Childhood stress exposure and DNA methylation in
803–809. adolescence. Child Development, 84, 58–75.
Chiao, J. Y. (2011). Cultural neuroscience: Visualizing Fraga, M. F., Ballestar, E., Paz, M. F., Ropero, S., Setien,
culture-gene influences on brain function. In J. Decety F., Ballestar, M. L., et al. (2005). Epigenetic differ-
& J. Cacioppo (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of social ences arise during the lifetime of monozygotic twins.
neuroscience (pp. 742–762). New York: Oxford Proceedings of the National Academy of Science, 102,
University Press. 10604–10609.
Chiao, J. Y., & Ambady, N. (2007). Cultural neuroscience: Franklin, T. B., Russig, H., Weiss, I. C., Gräff, J., Linder,
Parsing universality and diversity across levels of N., Michalon, A., et al. (2010). Epigenetic transmis-
analysis. In S. Kitayama & D. Cohen (Eds.), Handbook sion of the impact of early stress across generations.
of cultural psychology. New York: Guilford Press. Biological Psychiatry, 68, 408–415.
Chiao, J. Y., & Blizinsky, K. D. (2010). Culture-gene Gelfand, M. J., Raver, J. L., Nishii, L., Leslie, L. M., Lun,
coevolution of individualism-collectivism and the J., Lim, B. C., et al. (2011). Differences between tight
serotonin transporter gene (5-HTTLPR). Proceedings and loose cultures: A 33-nation study. Science, 332,
of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 277, 1100–1104.
529–537. Gill, M. (2012). Developmental psychopathology: The
Chiao, J. Y., Cheon, B. K., Pornpattananangkul, N., role of structural variation in the genome. Development
Mrazek, A. J., & Blizinsky, K. D. (2013). Cultural and Psychopathology, 24, 1319–1334.
neuroscience: Progress and promise. Psychological Grigorenko, E. L., & Cicchetti, D. (2012). Genomic
Inquiry, 24, 1–19. sciences for developmentalists: The current state of
Chiao, J. Y., Harada, T., Komeda, H., Li, Z., Mano, Y., affairs. Development and Psychopathology, 24,
Saito, D., et al. (2009). Neural basis of individualistic 1157–1164.
and collectivistic views of self. Human Brain Mapping, Han, S., & Northoff, G. (2008). Culture-sensitive
30, 2813–2820. neural substrates of human cognition: A transcultural
272 11 Genes and Environments: The Person Revolution

neuroimaging approach. Nature Review Neuroscience, Kim, H. S., & Sherman, D. K. (2007). “Express yourself”:
9, 646–654. Culture and the effect of self-expression on choice.
Han, S., Northoff, G., Vogeley, K., Wexler, B. E., Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 92,
Kitayama, S., & Varnum, M. E. W. (2013). A cultural 1–11.
neuroscience approach to the biosocial nature of the Kim, H. S., Sherman, D. K., Mojaverian, T., Sasaki, J. Y.,
human brain. Annual Review of Psychology, 64, Park, J., Suh, E. M., et al. (2011). Gene-culture inter-
335–359. action: Oxytocin receptor polymorphism (OXTR) and
Harden, K. P., Turkheimer, E., & Loehlin, J. C. (2007). emotion regulation. Social Psychological and
Genotype by environment interaction in adolescents’ Personality Science, 2, 665–672.
cognitive aptitude. Behavioral Genetics, 37, 273–283. Kim, H. S., Sherman, D. K., Sasaki, J. Y., Xu, J., Chu,
Hicks, B. M., Johnson, W., Durbin, C. E., Blonigen, T. Q., Ryu, C., et al. (2010). Culture, distress, and oxy-
D. M., Iacono, W. G., & McGue, M. (2013). Gene- tocin receptor polymorphism (OXTR) interact to
environment correlation in the development of adoles- influence emotional support seeking. Proceedings of
cent substance abuse: Selection effects of child the National Academy of Sciences, USA, 107,
personality and mediation via contextual risk factors. 1517–15721.
Development and Psychopathology, 25, 119–132. Kitayama, S., King, A., Yoon, C., Tompson, S., Huff, S.,
Ishii, K., Kim, H. S., Sasaki, J. Y., Shinada, M., & Kusumi, & Liberzon, I. (2014). The dopamine D4 receptor
I. (2014). Culture modulates sensitivity to the disap- gene (DRD4) moderates cultural difference in inde-
pearance of facial expressions associated with sero- pendent versus interdependent social orientation.
tonin transporter polymorphism (5-HTTLPR). Culture Psychological Science, 25, 1169–1177.
and Brain, 2, 72–88. Kitayama, S., & Uskul, A. K. (2011). Culture, mind, and
Jaffee, S. R. (2011). Genotype-environment correlations: the brain: Current evidence and future directions.
Definitions, methods of measurement, and implica- Annual Review of Psychology, 62, 419–449.
tions for research on adolescent psychopathology. In Klahr, A. M., Thomas, K. M., Hopwood, C. J., Klump,
K. S. Kendler, S. R. Jaffee, & D. Romer (Eds.), The K. L., & Burt, A. (2013). Evocative gene-environment
dynamic genome and mental health: The role of genes correlation in the mother-child relationship: A twin
and environments in youth development (pp. 79–102). study of interpersonal processes. Development and
New York: Oxford University Press. Psychopathology, 25, 105–118.
Jaffee, S. R., & Price, T. S. (2012). The implications of Knafo, A., & Jaffee, S. R. (2013). Gene-environment cor-
genotype environment correlation for establishing relation in developmental psychopathology.
causal processes in psychopathology. Development Development and Psychopathology, 25, 1–6.
and Psychopathology, 24, 1253–1264. Knopik, V. S., Maccani, M. A., Francazio, S., & McGeary,
Jaffee, S. R., Price, T. S., & Reyes, T. M. (2013). Behavior J. E. (2012). The epigenetics of maternal cigarette
genetics: Past, present, future. Development and smoking during pregnancy and effects on child devel-
Psychopathology, 25, 1225–1242. opment. Development and Psychopathology, 24,
Juang, L., Syed, M., Cookston, J., Wang, Y., & Kim, S. Y. 1377–1390.
(2012). Everyday and acculturation-based family con- Koenen, K. C., Uddin, M., Chang, S.-C., Aiello, A. E.,
flict among Chinese American parents and adoles- Wildman, D. E., & Goldmann, E. (2011). SLC6A4
cents. New Directions in Child and Adolescent methylation modifies the effect of the number of trau-
Development, 135, 13–34. matic events on risk of posttraumatic stress disorder.
Kabat-Zinn, J. (1982). An outpatient program in behav- Depression and Anxiety, 28, 639–647.
ioral medicine for chronic pain patients based on the Labonté, B., Suderman, M., Maussion, G., Navaro, L.,
practice of mindfulness meditation: Theoretical con- Yerko, V., Mahar, I., et al. (2012). Genome-wide epi-
siderations and preliminary results. General Hospital genetic regulation by early-life trauma. Archives of
Psychiatry, 4, 33–47. General Psychiatry, 69, 722–731.
Kaliman, P., Álvarez-López, M. J., Cosín-Tomás, M., Labonté, B., Yerko, V., Gross, J., Mechawar, N., Meaney,
Rosenkranz, M. A., Lutz, A., & Davidson, R. J. (2014). M. J., Szyf, M., et al. (2012). Differential gluco-
Rapid changes in histone deacetylases and inflamma- corticoid receptor exon 1(B), 1(C), and 1 (H) expres-
tory gene expression in expert meditators. sion and methylation in suicide completers with a
Psychoneuroendocrinology, 40, 96–107. history of childhood abuse. Biological Psychiatry, 72,
Kaufman, J., Birmaher, B., Brent, D., Rao, U., Flynn, C., 41–48.
Moreci, P., et al. (1997). Schedule for affective disor- Marceau, K., Horwitz, B. N., Narusyte, J., Ganiban,
ders and schizophrenia for school-age children-present J. M., Spotts, E. L., Reiss, D., et al. (2013). Gene-
and life time version (K-SADS-PL): Initial reliability environment correlation underlying the association
and validity data. Journal of the American Academy of between parental negativity and adolescent external-
Child and Adolescent Psychiatry, 36, 980–988. izing problems. Child Development, 84, 2031–2046.
Kim, H. S., & Sasaki, J. Y. (2014). Cultural neuroscience: Martin, G. M. (2005). Epigenetic drift in aging identical
Biology of the mind in cultural contexts. Annual twins. Proceedings of the National Academy of
Review of Psychology, 65, 487–514. Sciences, USA, 102, 10413–10414.
References 273

McGowan, P. O., & Roth, T. L. (2015). Epigenetic Ouellet-Morin, L., Wong, C. C., Danese, A., Pariante,
pathways through which experiences become linked C. M., Papadopoulos, A. S., Mill, J., et al. (2013).
with biology. Development and Psychopathology, 27, Increased serotonin transporter gene (SERT) DNA
637–678. methylation is associated with bullying victimization
McGowan, P. O., Sasaki, A., D’Alessio, A. C., Dymov, S., and blunted cortisol response to stress in childhood: A
Labonté, B., Szyf, M., et al. (2009). Epigenetic regula- longitudinal study of discordant monozygotic twins.
tion of the glucocorticoid receptor in human brain Psychological Medicine, 43, 1813–1823.
associates with childhood abuse. Nature Neuroscience, Pener-Tessler, R., Avinun, R., Uzefovsky, F., Edelman, S.,
12, 342–348. Ebstein, R. P., & Knafo, A. (2013). Boys’ serotonin
McGowan, P. O., Suderman, M., Sasaki, A., Huang, T. C., transporter genotype affects maternal behavior
Hallett, M., Meaney, M. J., & Szyf, M. (2011). Broad through self-control: A case of evocative gene-
epigenetic signature of maternal care in the brain of environment correlation. Development and
adult rats. PloS ONE, 6, e14739. doi:10.1371/journal. Psychopathology, 25, 151–162.
pone.0014739. Plomin, R., DeFries, J. C., & Loehlin, J. C. (1977).
Meaney, M. J. (2010). Epigenetics and the biological defi- Genotype-environment interaction and correlation in
nition of gene × environment interactions. Child the analysis of human behavior. Psychological
Development, 81, 41–79. Bulletin, 84, 309–322.
Mill, J., & Heijmans, B. T. (2013). From promises to prac- Powell, N. D., Sloan, E. K., Bailey, M. T., Arevalo, J. M.,
tical strategies in epigenetic epidemiology. Nature Miller, G. E., Chen, E., et al. (2013). Social stress up-
Reviews Genetics, 14, 585–594. regulates inflammatory gene expression in the leuko-
Mills-Koonce, W. R., Propper, C. B., Gariepy, J. L., Blair, cyte transcriptome via beta-adrenergic induction of
C., Garrett-Peters, P., & Cox, M. J. (2007). Bidirec- myelopoiesis. Proceedings of the National Academy
tional genetic and environmental influences on mother of Sciences, USA, 110, 16574–16579.
and child behavior: The family system as the unit of Propper, C. B., Shanahan, M. J., Russo, R., & Mills-
analyses. Development and Psychopathology, 19, Koonce, W. R. (2012). Evocative gene-parenting cor-
1073–1087. relations and academic performance at first grade: An
Monk, C., Spicer, J., & Champagne, F. A. (2012). Linking exploratory study. Development and Psychopathology,
prenatal maternal adversity to developmental out- 24, 1265–1282.
comes in infants: The role of epigenetic pathways. Putnam, F. W., Helmers, K., & Trickett, P. K. (1993).
Development and Psychopathology, 24, 1361–1376. Development, reliability, and validity of a child dis-
Mrazek, A. J., Chiao, J. Y., Blizinsky, K. D., Lun, J., & sociation scale. Child Abuse & Neglect, 17, 731–741.
Gelfand, M. J. (2013). The role of culture-gene coevo- Radtke, K. M., Ruf, M., Gunter, H. M., Dohrmann, K.,
lution in morality judgment: Examining the interplay Schauer, M., & Elbert, T. (2011). Transgenerational
between tightness-looseness and allelic variation of impact of intimate partner violence on methylation
the serotonin transporter gene. Culture and Brain, 1, in the promoter of the glucocorticoid receptor.
100–117. Translational Psychiatry, 1, e21. doi:10.1038/
Naples, A., Katz, L., & Grigorenko, E. L. (2012). Lexical tp.2011.21.
decision as an endophenotype for reading comprehen- Rosenberg, M. (1965). Society and the adolescent self-
sion: An exploration of an association. Development image. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
and Psychopathology, 24, 1345–1360. Roth, T. L. (2013). Epigenetic mechanisms in the devel-
Nemeroff, C. B., & Binder, E. (2014). The preeminent opment of behavior: Advances, challenges, and future
role of childhood abuse and neglect in vulnerability to promises of a new field. Development and Psycho-
major psychiatric disorders: Toward elucidating the pathology, 25, 1279–1291.
underlying neurobiological mechanisms. Journal of Rucker, J. J. H., & McGuffin, P. (2012). Genomic struc-
the American Academy of Child and Adolescent tural variation in psychiatric disorders. Development
Psychiatry, 53, 395–397. and Psychopathology, 24, 1335–1344.
Nikolova, Y. S., & Hariri, A. R. (2015). Can we observe Sasaki, J. Y. (2013). Promise and challenges surrounding
epigenetic effects on human brain function? Trends in culture-gene coevolution and gene-culture interac-
Cognitive Science, 19, 366–373. tions. Psychological Inquiry, 24, 64–70.
Oberlander, T. F., Weinberg, J., Papsdorf, M., Grunau, R., Sasaki, J. Y., Kim, H. S., Mojaverian, T., Kelley, L. D. S.,
Misri, S., & Devlin, A. M. (2008). Prenatal exposure to Park, I. Y., & Janušonis, S. (2013). Religion priming
maternal depression, neonatal methylation of human differentially increases prosocial behavior among vari-
glucocorticoid receptor gene (NR3C1) and infant cor- ants of the dopamine D4 receptor (DRD4) gene. Social
tisol stress responses. Epigenetics, 3, 97–106. Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience, 8, 209–215.
Olsson, C. A., Foley, D. L., Parkinson-Bates, M., Byrnes, Sasaki, J. Y., Kim, H., & Xu, J. (2011). Religion and well-
G., McKenzie, M., Patton, G. C., et al. (2010). being: An analysis of an oxytocin receptor polymor-
Prospects for epigenetic research within cohort studies phism (OXTR) and culture. Journal of Cross-Cultural
of psychological disorder: A pilot investigation of a Psychology, 42, 1394–1405.
peripheral cell marker of epigenetic risk for depres- Schwarzer, R., Mueller, J., & Greenglass, E. (1999).
sion. Biological Psychology, 83, 159–165. Assessment of perceived general self-efficacy on the
274 11 Genes and Environments: The Person Revolution

Internet: Data collection in cyberspace. Anxiety, sion in a community-based epidemiologic sample.


Stress, & Coping, 12, 145–161. Psychological Medicine, 41, 997–1007.
Singelis, T. M. (1994). The measurement of independent Unternaehrer, E., Luers, P., Mills, J., Dempster, E., Meyer,
and interdependent self-construals. Personality and A. H., Staehli, S., et al. (2012). Dynamic changes in
Social Psychology Bulletin, 20, 580–891. DNA methylation of stress-associated genes (OXTR,
Suderman, M., McGowan, P. O., Sasaki, A., Huang, T. C. BDNF) after acute psychosocial stress. Translational
T., Hallett, M., Meaney, M. J., Turecki, G., & Szyf, M. Psychiatry, 2, e150. doi:10.1038/tp.2012.77.
(2012). Conserved epigenetic sensitivity to early life van IJzendoorn, M. H., Bakermans-Kranenburg, M. J., &
experience in the rat and human hippocampus. Ebstein, R. P. (2011). Methylation matters in child
Proceedings of the National Academy of Science, development: Toward developmental behavioral
USA, 109, 17266–17272. epigenetics. Child Development Perspectives, 5,
Sulik, M. J., Blair, C., Berry, D., Mills-Koonce, R., & 305–310.
Greenberg, M. (2015). Early parenting and develop- van IJzendoorn, M. H., Caspers, K., Bakermans-
ment of externalizing behavior problems: Longitudinal Kranenburg, M. J., Beach, S. R. H., & Philibert, R.
mediation through children’s executive function. (2010). Methylation matters: Interaction between
Child Development, 86, 1588–1603. methylation density and 5HTT genotype predicts
Szyf, M., & Bick, J. (2013). DNA methylation: A mecha- unresolved loss or trauma. Biological Psychiatry, 68,
nism for embedding early life experiences in the 405–407.
genome. Child Development, 84, 49–57. Vijayendran, M., Beach, S., Plume, J. M., Brody, G., &
Tamis-LeMonda, C. S., Way, N., Hughes, D., Yoshikawa, Philibert, R. (2012). Effects of genotype and child
H., Kalman, R. K., & Niwa, E. Y. (2008). Parents’ abuse on DNA methylation and gene expression at the
goals for children: The dynamic coexistence of indi- serotonin transporter. Frontiers in Psychiatry, 3, 55.
vidualism and collectivism in cultures and individuals. doi:10.3389/fpsyt.2012.00055.
Social Development, 17, 183–209. Vogeley, K., & Roepstorff, A. (2009). Contextualising
Tucker-Drob, E. M., Briley, D. A., & Harden, K. P. (2013). culture and social cognition. Trends in Cognitive
Genetic and environmental influences on cognition Sciences, 13, 511–516.
across development and context. Current Directions in Wang, E., Ding, Y.-C., Flodman, P., Kidd, J. R., Kidd,
Psychological Science, 22, 349–355. K. K., Grady, D. L., et al. (2004). The genetic architec-
Tyrka, A. R., Parade, S. H., Eslinger, N. M., Marsit, C. J., ture of selection at the human dopamine receptor D4
Lesseur, C., Armstrong, D. A., et al. (2015). Methy- (DRD4) gene locus. American Journal of Human
lation of exons 1D, 1F, 1H of the glucocorticoid Genetics, 74, 931–944.
receptor gene promoter and exposure to adversity in Weder, N., Zhang, H., Jensen, K., Yang, B. Z., Simen, A.,
preschool-aged children. Development and Psycho- Jackowski, A., et al. (2014). Child abuse, depression,
pathology, 27, 577–585. and methylation in genes involved with stress, neural
Tyrka, A. R., Price, L. H., Marsit, C., Walters, O. C., & plasticity, and brain circuitry. Journal of the American
Carpenter, L. L. (2012). Childhood adversity and epi- Academy of Child & Adolescent Psychiatry, 53,
genetic modulation of the leukocyte glucocorticoid 417–424.
receptor. Preliminary findings in healthy adults. PLoS Zovkic, I. B., Meadows, J. P., Kaas, G. A., & Sweatt, J. D.
ONE, 7, e30148. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0030148. (2013). Interindividual variability in stress suscep-
Uddin, M., Koenen, K. C., Aiello, A. E., Wildman, D. E., tibility: A role for epigenetic mechanisms in PTSD.
de los Santos, R., & Galea, S. (2011). Epigenetic and Frontiers in Psychiatry, 4, 60. doi:10.3389/fpsyt.
inflammatory marker profiles associated with depres- 2013.00060.
Nature and Nurture:
Evolution and Complexities 12

The concept of evolution has evolved itself,


Chapter Introduction including in the elaborations presented by Darwin
himself (e.g., sexual selection). However, despite
This chapter explores the multiple ways in which its theoretical branches, it remains uncontested as
Nature and Nurture interact. First, it examines the primary driver of morphology, including of
contemporary views of evolution that include the brain, and also of behavior.
a role for development, systems, complexity, For Bjorklund and Ellis (2014), evolutionary
emergence, and optimization. Similarly, in theory represents a metatheory for psychological
niche construction, environment, phenotype, and science. It helps unify psychology with the life
development interact, and it leaves room for cul- sciences. Genes are dynamically expressed in
tural influences. Next, the chapter addresses the proximal contexts, rather than having predeter-
changing face of the study of intelligence and its mined, “innate” effects. Not that the environment
factors, including work on the general g factor, is random or has random effects; nor is the envi-
implicate environmental influences as much as ronment independent of the total developmental
genetic ones. The concept of g has led to the system. Nature by nurture interactions take place
equivalent concept of p in psychopathology and in a way that phenotypes’ characteristics consti-
emotional disorders. Finally, the chapter reviews tute “emergent” properties relative to the envi-
the fast-emerging field of social genomics, which ronment and the genes involved.
explains how the environment “gets under the Developmental systems theories are either
skin.” For example, factors such as perceived “soft” or “hard” in version. The former concerns
social loneliness are found to have long-term development of the individual organism and is
implications for the health of individuals. The consistent with evolutionary inclusive fitness
chapter concludes with discussion of complexity theory, but the latter is not because it concerns
in evolution. populations of replicating “organism-environ-
ment systems” in lineages rather than in individ-
uals. The approach taken by Bjorklund and Ellis
Evolution (2014) is consistent with the soft (inclusive fit-
ness) approach to evolution and development.
Evolution is a cross-cutting paradigm that helps In this regard, they emphasized developmental
amalgamate the biological and life sciences under plasticity as an advantage in changing or variable
one inclusive rubric. It took wing with the work environments. Plasticity might be fixed prena-
of Darwin over one century ago with his concep- tally, though, as in the effects that take place due
tualization of the process of natural selection. to exposure to elevated levels of stress hormones

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 275


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_12
276 12 Nature and Nurture: Evolution and Complexities

in situations of maternal stress. For example, Flory, Halder, and Ferrell (2011) found a rela-
Rice et al. (2010) found that children’s antisocial tionship between distant familial interpersonal
behavior between 4 and 10 years of age was asso- relations/high conflict levels and early pubertal
ciated with prenatal maternal stress exposure not measures, but only in the presence of certain
only if the mothers were the biological mothers polymorphisms of the estrogen receptor gene,
but also if they were the genetically unrelated car- ESR1 (homozygous for minor alleles of two
riers after in vitro fertilization. polymorphisms). Therefore, differential suscep-
Also, plasticity might be constrained by devel- tibility qualifies life history strategies as condi-
oping in the context of species-typical environ- tional adaptations.
ments. Further, species-typical genomes act to There are also ontogenetic and deferred adap-
bias individuals to seek out or create species- tations. The former refer to the “potency” of nat-
typical environments. That being said, pheno- ural selection in the early years and its role
typic traits (e.g., cognitive mechanisms) are throughout the lifespan. The latter refer to pre-
expressed probabilistically and in bidirectional pared adaptations, ones that not only increase
interaction. Moreover, the traits often are not adaptation to a juvenile’s current niche but also to
monomorphic in structure but are genetically the ones likely encountered later on as adults.
polymorphic and varied according to encoun- Shackelford and Liddle (2014) argued that
tered environment. Individual differences are Darwinian evolutionary psychology provides a
adaptive, with differential cost-benefit trade-offs unifying approach to psychology. It emphasizes
for different structures or strategies in different the interaction between genes and environment,
niches, and this varies developmentally. unlike how it has been portrayed. In this approach,
Individuals express life history strategies, or a trait is considered to have evolved according to
chains of resource allocation decisions in con- its ability to maximize inclusive fitness (an indi-
text. Some decisions increase “embodied” capi- vidual’s own reproductive success with the addi-
tal, or qualities that increase Darwinian survival tion of the effect of the individual’s actions on the
and reproduction potential but only later on (as reproductive success of genetic relatives) in the
with the advantages of juvenile play). Life his- context of the environment of evolutionary adap-
tory theory includes fast or slow reproductive tiveness (niche) in which it evolved. In this
strategies (which are earlier or delayed, respec- model, the mind and behavior are massively
tively), depending on forecasts based on the qual- modular, with each component shaped by evolu-
ity of earlier environments (e.g., maltreatment) tionary pressures in terms of their specific advan-
for what might be present in later environments tages for survival and reproduction.
(e.g., a delay in reproduction will not bring its Richerson et al. (2014) elaborated the cultural
typically found long-term advantages in adverse group selection model to explain human coopera-
environments). tion, which is unique in its extent and inclusion of
In differential susceptibility (Belsky & Pluess, mostly non-relative actors and recipients. They do
2009), slow and fast life history strategies are not exclude a complementary role for traditional
affected by biological sensitivity to context. More evolutionary processes (e.g., natural selection, kin
reactive children are especially susceptible to selection, reciprocity, multi-level selection) in
both highly stressful and highly nurturing envi- explain human cooperativity, in that they allow
ronments (Boyce & Ellis, 2005). for gene-culture co-evolution. However, the tradi-
For example, Ellis, Shirtcliff, Boyce, tional models cannot easily explain the institu-
Deardorff, and Essex (2011) found that lower tionalized cooperation at the heart of human
quality preschool-parent relations predicted society. That is, group beneficial behavior is
faster/earlier pubertal measures, but only among spread not only by evolutionary processes but
children indexing biological sensitivity in a also by cultural factors, including related mecha-
heightened sympathic nervous system or adreno- nisms of selective imitation of successful groups
cortical reactivity. Similarly, Manuck, Craig, and selective migration between groups.
Systems 277

Epigenesis major component of genome variation or stabil-


ity within species found in evolutionary change.
Epigenesis is now being understood as a potential To conclude, Skinner et al. (2014) noted that
co-mechanism to standard evolutionary forces in genetic and epigenetic changes underlying phe-
the process of evolution (Mendizabal, Keller, notypic expression might regulate jointly not
Zeng, & Yi, 2014). The literature shows that cur- only genomic activity and consequent pheno-
rent levels of DNA methylation are predictable typic expression but also evolution generally.
from its evolutionary signatures. DNA methyla-
tion patterns appear widely conserved over
wide-ranging taxa. Human and closely related Systems
nonhuman primate species differ in genomic
region methylation pattern related to development Badcock (2012) proposed evolutionary systems
(aside from tissue specializations). Therefore, theory as a unified meta-theory of psychological
genomic sequence variants over evolution encode science in terms of a hierarchical metamodel. In
and appear to regulate distinctive epigenetic pat- particular, the model integrates Neo-Darwinian
terns (aside from the wide conservations found). concepts of evolution with concepts from nonlin-
Mendizabal et al. (2014) noted that epigenesis ear dynamic systems theory (NLDST, which he
leaves marks that affect one generation to the referred to as DST, dynamic systems theory). The
next. The research indicates that variation in DNA model permits organizing into one framework:
methylation appears heritable, in part, and subject evolutionary psychology; evolutionary develop-
to natural selection, being determined ultimately mental biology; developmental psychobiology—
by genomic variants. Finally, epigenetic evolu- and other aspects of psychology. These four areas
tionary divergence from one closely related spe- deal with, respectively—functional bases for
cies to the next is aimed at or targets specific evolved characteristics in species; between group
functions. Therefore, epigenomic factors appear differences that are phylogenetically based; indi-
to express a constant dynamic interplay between vidual differences in ontogeny; and mechanisms
short- and long-term evolutionary time scales. explaining real-time phenomena.
In order to investigate whether epigenetic By focusing on Darwinian and dynamical sys-
changes can accumulate over relative long peri- tems theory, Badcock integrated the process of
ods of evolutionary time, Skinner et al. (2014) general selection in evolution (which includes
investigated epigenetic changes in five species of natural selection) and self-organization in sys-
finches related to Darwin’s finches. Over the spe- tems. The four areas that are synthesized reflect
cies, epimutations (epigenetic alterations associ- Tinbergen’s (1963) four questions about evolu-
ated with differential DNA methylation regions) tion and behavior—adaptive function, phylog-
proved more common than copy number variant eny, ontogeny, and mechanism. Badcock (2012)
(CNV) mutations (genome-wide alterations in reviewed each of the four major areas integrated
genetic mutations according to copy number in his model, and I focus on the first three.
variations). Also, the number of epimutations (a) Evolutionary psychology considers psy-
was related monotonically (increasingly) with chological mechanisms and behavior as evolu-
degree of phylogenetic distance. tionary adaptations that have evolved according
Skinner et al. (2014) noted that epigenetic to Darwinian natural selection, or by increasing
changes might contribute to the molecular basis the probability of survival, reproduction, or both
in the evolution over close phylogenetic distance. in ancestral contexts or environmental niches
Epigenetic changes can increase the heritable (which might not be those facing contemporary
phenotypic variation on which natural selection humans) (Buss, 1995, 2004).
could act (Skinner, 2011). Indeed, epigenetics The model of evolutionary psychology is
might play a “pervasive” role in evolution conducive to considering psychological adapta-
(Klironomos, Berg, & Collins, 2013), providing a tions as modular, or distinct for the survival and
278 12 Nature and Nurture: Evolution and Complexities

reproductive advantages that they bring specifi- through cellular epigenesis as much as socially-
cally (referred to as the massive modularity and representationally-based accommodations. If
hypothesis). The model seeks (a) “functional,” environmental conditions persist over genera-
“why” properties of psychological mechanisms, tions in a species, selection will enhance the sur-
in the sense of ultimate, adaptive properties and vival and reproduction of the most adaptive
(b) “proximate” or “how” mechanisms, in terms phenotypes for the environment [including of
of input and output processes (Scott-Phillips, their epigenetic stamps or marks, although the
Dickins, & West, 2011). [Note that other models latter might not last more than a few generations].
might consider functional properties as proxi- Therefore, (a) lifetime and transgenerational plas-
mate ones.] ticity and (b) species’ evolvability through natural
A major criticism of evolutionary theory relates selection are complementary and continuously in
to its emphasis on modularity, given that different interaction (Lamm & Jablonka, 2008). By empha-
theories emphasize central general systems. sizing the importance of phenotypic ontogenesis
Badcock (2012) attempted to resolve the differ- in furnishing evolvable traits, the process becomes
ences in the approaches to modularity-general more plastic and broader in scope than a strict
features of mind by integrating both into a hierar- selection one (Ploeger, 2010; Ploeger et al.,
chical model. In his hierarchically mechanistic 2008), and specific mechanisms involved in natu-
mind model, the lower-order level consists of ral selection become found in ongoing life
domain-specific, exclusive, isolated, and encapsu- changes and in transgenerational time.
lated innate psychological mechanisms. They are Note that, compared to evo-devo, evolution-
constrained, automatic, and algorithmic in proper- ary developmental psychology has a similar inte-
ties. In contrast, at higher levels of his model, grative approach to evolution and development
Badcock places more plastic, flexible, executive, (Bjorklund & Pellegrini, 2002; Causey, Gardiner,
general, generative, and inclusive processes and & Bjorklund, 2008; Geary & Bjorklund, 2000). It
properties, and among them is consciousness. shows how evolution by natural selection explains
(b) Evolutionary developmental biology has the ontogeny of species-typical traits, and how
modified the classic Darwinian perspective of the environment can influence development to
natural selection functioning to promote better produce variable phenotypes from a genotype
adaptiveness of phenotypes due, in part, to ran- system in order to adapt to extant ongoing func-
dom mutation or novel variation in genotype tional needs.
(Ploeger, Van Der Maas, & Raijmakers, 2008; Workers are integrating NLDST into evolu-
West-Eberhard, 2003). In addition to this genetic tionary models (Caporael, 2001; Hoelzer, Smith,
process, developing phenotypes might express & Pepper, 2006; Kauffman, 1993; Kenrick et al.,
advantageous traits or characteristics that pro- 2002; Ploeger, 2010; Ploeger et al., 2008).
mote fitness “before natural selection has a chance According to Lewis (2000, 2005) and others
to operate” (Badcock, p. 12). Developmental pro- (Smith & Thelen, 2003; Witherington, 2007), trig-
cesses contribute to evolution by promoting novel gered microscopic perturbations and coordina-
morphological, physiological, or behavioral traits tions or recursive interactions in a system among
through mechanisms that are constructive rather the lower-order elements/components involved
than selective yet become subject to natural selec- might lead to the spontaneous emergence of
tion. This approach values differences at the indi- coherent, higher-order patterns through spontane-
vidual and group level, not only the species level. ous self-organization. The different levels of the
Evo-devo is a biological field that involves system themselves are coordinated in circular
inherited cellular but epigenetically modified causality, so that they are subject to developing
systems (Jablonka & Lamb, 2007). As well, in increased complexity, or global reorganizations,
the broader sense, epigenesis concerns socially- including in their nested hierarchies and function-
mediated learning and symbol-based transmis- ality, especially at phase transition or bifurcation
sion of information. Organisms can develop points at which there is increased turbulence or
Systems 279

variability. Negative feedback loops in the system Badcock (2012) integrated these diverse
facilitate stability while positive ones facilitate aspects of evolutionary study in and related to
change through sensitivity to environmental con- psychology into an evolutionary systems theory
ditions. Attractor patterns appear in the state space (see Table 12.1). Evolutionary psychology con-
trajectories through which system states gravitate cerns species × environment fit or interaction.
over time. Evolutionary developmental biology focused on
It is worth exploring Kauffman’s (1993) group × environment interaction. Developmental
seminal ideas on how evolution and self- psychobiology concerns Gene × Environment
organizational principles can co-exist in an (G × E) interaction. Psychology as a whole inves-
integrated model. In his model, self-organization tigates individual × environment interaction. The
influences population trajectories of possible timeframes for these disciplines are, respec-
genotypes and phenotypes through their state tively, evolutionary, generational, developmen-
spaces, and populations express differential fit- tal, and real-time.
ness in the spaces. As the systems self-organize, Badcock (2012) has performed a valuable ser-
they tend to move to the “edge of chaos,” or a vice in showing how these diverse fields have
zone that maximizes change. Indeed, natural complementary ways of understanding co-acting
selection favors systems that reside in this zone, evolutionary and developmental processes and
because it promotes evolvability. Similarly, also showing how NLDST can help explain the
Hoelzer et al. (2006) referred to natural selection general biological change manifold that together
as any “emergent” process. Nevertheless, evolv- they entail. Further conceptualization is needed,
ing systems self-organize in ways that preclude however, to explain multiple, simultaneous inter-
deleterious phase transitions, for example, by actions among species × group × genes × individ-
minimizing entropy (thermodynamic descent ual × environment as ontogeny and phylogeny
into disorder). reciprocally interact and unfold.
(c) Developmental psychobiology also is Other models that integrate evolutionary and
becoming increasingly integrative (Lickliter & dynamic approaches include Hoelzer et al.’s
Honeycutt, 2003). Developmentalists are attempt- (2006). They argued that both natural selection
ing to integrate biological approaches into unified and self-organization function according to
theories (e.g., Sameroff, 2010). The models thermodynamic energy principles. Moreover,
are multidirectional, or multicausal, interactive, thermodynamics better approaches explanations
transactive, and dynamically plastic. Similar inte- of ultimate cause while molecular ones bet-
grated models are being developed in personality ter approach explanations of proximate cause
theory (Sheldon, Cheng, & Hilpert, 2011). (see Fig. 12.1).

Table 12.1 An evolutionary systems theory of psychology


Research question
Paradigm Problem area and core hypotheses and temporal domain
Psychological Individual × Environment Mechanism
Biopsychosocial developmental systems Real-time
Developmental psychobiology Gene × Environment (G × E) Ontogeny
DEP (dynamical evolutionary psychology) Developmental time
Evolutionary psychology Species × Environment Phylogeny
Natural selection; inclusive fitness; genetic Evolutionary time
inheritance; massive modularity; multi-level
selection
Evolutionary developmental biology Group × Environment Ontogeny/Phylogeny
EDP (evolutionary developmental Co-evolution; epigenetic inheritance; Generational time
psychology)
Adapted from Badcock (2012)
280 12 Nature and Nurture: Evolution and Complexities

Proximate leading to complexity are less than neutral or del-


eterious, they could not survive.
Mechanics
CAUSE

Phenotypic function
Niche Construction
Natural selection

Thermodynamics Laland, Sterelny, Odling-Smee, Hoppitt, and


Uller (2011) presented an integrated view of
Ultimate
proximate (e.g., immediate) and ultimate (e.g.,
Evolution natural selection) causal explanations in biology.
According to them, causation is reciprocal
Fig. 12.1 Range spectrum of causal levels (ultimate to
proximate). The levels of ultimate and proximate causa- between these poles, shaping and responding
tion (ecology) are indicated as natural selection (NS) and equally. Developmental processes are the central
phenotypic function, respectively. Purely mechanical axis binding them. The phenotypic plasticity in
explanations would typically be more proximate in nature development can “generate” or explain the origi-
than explanations based on phenotypic function, and ther-
modynamic explanations are more fundamental than nal evolutionary change, although the develop-
those based on NS. Note. Relative to the original model mental phenotype might not be equivalent to the
presented in Hoelzer et al. (2006). I added an axis for evo- trait ultimately expressed (West-Eberhard, 2003).
lution. Adapted from Hoelzer, Smith, and Pepper (2006) A cycle of causation between proximate and ulti-
mate causation obtains in cause and effect in bio-
Complexity logical adaptation. Developmental phenotypes
could “bias” phenotypic variants, helping to pro-
Darwin’s (1859) stance on complexity in evolu- mote their selection, yet express plasticity allow-
tion considered that it evolved through adaptive ing for formation of “novelty,” too (see Fig. 12.2).
intermediate forms, with each more complex step In a combined evolutionary and developmental
sculpted by natural selection (Zimmer, 2013). model, heritable phenotypic traits are not fixed or
However, biologists are proposing natural selec- programmed by genes but are open to environmen-
tion free processes in evolution of complexity. tal effects, which themselves are altered by activities
For example, species change to complexity might associated with the heritable traits (e.g., in evo-devo,
reflect the differentiation of parts by “zero-force” niche construction theory). Feedback prompts
evolution that ends up with adaptive advantages reciprocal changes in gene expression, environ-
(McShea & Brandon, 2010). Or, mutations might ment, and development. In this sense, development
arise without intermediate steps, but reach com- is more than a proximal or immediate mechanism
plexity, nevertheless, and without natural selec- because it induces “additional” causal trajectories
tion involved (Lukeš, Archibald, Keeling, deriving from the trait in one generation to the next.
Doolittle, & Gray, 2011). In this model, the com- In niche construction, environment-altering,
plexity evolves according to “constructive neu- developing phenotypic traits co-evolve with
tral evolution,” as if there were a “ratchet” organism-modified factors in the environment,
building the complexity, which then becomes which reciprocally act back, modifying the pro-
advantageous. Kauffman (1993) had also pro- cess of causation by selection. Inheritance is
posed that complexity can increase in evolution multiply-determined, e.g., as in ecological inheri-
without evolving through natural selection. tance, epigenesis, and cultural inheritance or evo-
Indeed, the implication of these models is that lution, as well as gene-culture co-evolution (see
natural selection and complexification are recip- Fig. 12.3).
rocal dynamic processes. They do not necessarily In culture-related evolution, a trait is inherited
exclude the traditional base of evolution in ran- from the prior generation via cultural transmis-
domly occurring adaptive genetic mutations. sion across generations and from differential cul-
That being said, if mutations or other processes tural selection processes. The behavior is both
a
EVOLUTION N-1
Genes Traits Fitness Environment

Generation

N Genes Traits Fitness Environment

DEVELOPMENT

Embryo Genes Gene expression Traits Fitness Environment

Genes Gene expression Traits Fitness Environment


Developmental
time

Adult Genes Gene expression Traits Fitness Environment

b
EVOLUTION N-1
Genes Traits Fitness Environment

Generation

N Genes Traits Fitness Environment

DEVELOPMENT

Embryo Genes Gene expression Traits Fitness Environment

Developmental Genes Gene expression Traits Fitness Environment


time

Adult Genes Gene expression Traits Fitness Environment

Fig. 12.2 Causal pathways involved in the evolution and interest. The only way in which the trait in one generation
development of traits. Arrows represent possible causal causes the trait in the next is through fitness (natural selec-
influences; dashed lines represent features that persist over tion), so development can be black-boxed. (B) A modern
time. (A) Classic perspective. In evolution, genes and envi- developmental perspective. Dotted arrows denote addi-
ronment interact to cause the trait, the trait and the environ- tional causal influences relative to (A) recognized by fields
ment cause fitness, whereas the genes are determined by such as evo-devo and niche construction theory. During
the genes carried by the previous generation and the fitness development, features of the trait cause changes in both
of individuals in that generation. Relative to evolution, the gene expression and environment, which feed back to the
process of development is broken down in a similar manner developmental process, resulting in a different trait in the
but on a shorter time scale. The present-day trait is inde- adult and modifications of both developmental and selec-
pendent of other components in the graph conditional on tive environments. Development cannot be considered
the present-day genes and environment, so an explanation purely proximately causal because it results in additional
of the proximate cause of the trait must only account for causal pathways from the trait in one generation to the trait
how genes and environment interact in trait development. in future generations. Adopted by permission of
The ultimate explanation must then account for how the AAAS. From Laland, K. N., Sterelny, K., Odling-Smee, J.,
present-day genes and environment themselves were Hoppitt, W., & Uller, T. (2011). Cause and effect in biology
caused, but, because causation is only in one direction from revisited: Is Mayr’s proximate-ultimate dichotomy still
the environment to the trait, the causes of the environment useful? Science, 334, 1512–1516. Reprinted by permission
can be treated as an external system, of little biological from AAAS. [Figure 1, Page 1513]
282 12 Nature and Nurture: Evolution and Complexities

a BIOLOGICAL EVOLUTION

N-1
Genes Behavior Biological Fitness Environment

Generation

N Genes Behavior Biological Fitness Environment

b CULTURAL EVOLUTION

N-1
Genes Behavior Cultural Fitness Environment

Generation

N Genes Behavior Cultural Fitness Environment

c GENE-CULTURE COEVOLUTION

Genes Trait Biological Trait Cultural Environment


1 Fitness 2 Fitness
N-1

Generation

Genes Trait Biological Trait Cultural Environment


N 1 Fitness 2 Fitness

Fig. 12.3 Causal pathways involved in the evolution and ness of the other. [For illustration, trait 1 might be lactose
development of traits. Alternative evolutionary processes. absorption and trait 2 dairy farming or milk use.] Inheritance
(A) Biological evolution: the ultimate explanation for the pathways are shown in gray. For any given data set, causal
behavior lies in its effect on biological fitness. (B) Cultural modeling can be used to establish whether a particular
evolution: the behavior can be inherited from the previous causal influence is operating. Adopted by permission of
generation through intergenerational cultural transmission AAAS. From Laland, K. N., Sterelny, K., Odling-Smee, J.,
and differential cultural selection. Here, the ultimate expla- Hoppitt, W., & Uller, T. (2011). Cause and effect in biology
nation for behavior lies in its effect on cultural fitness. (C) revisited: Is Mayr’s proximate-ultimate dichotomy still
Gene-culture co-evolution: genetically and culturally useful? Science, 334, 1512–1516. Reprinted by permission
inherited traits co-evolve, with each trait affecting the fit- from AAAS. [Figure 2, Page 1515]

altered by culture and can alter it; however, genes affecting the fitness of the other. For example,
are not affected intergenerationally. In contrast, recent human cultural agricultural, dairy, and set-
in gene-culture co-evolution, traits that are genet- tling practices have favored individuals with
ically inherited co-evolve with those that are cul- adult lactose tolerance alleles, which led rapidly
turally inherited, with the traits in each stream to altering the human genome.
Niche Construction 283

Natural selection Population of


t Et Gene pool
organisms

Genetic
Time inheritance

Natural selection Population of


t+1 Et+1 Gene pool
organisms

b
Niche construction
Population of
t Et Gene pool
organisms
Natural selection

Ecological Genetic
Time inheritance inheritance

Niche construction
Population of
t+1 Et+1 Gene pool
organisms
Natural selection

Fig. 12.4 Developmental niche construction. (a) A con- activities of organisms. Inheritance is expanded to com-
ventional view of the process of adaptation through natural prise both genetic and ecological components (i.e., lega-
selection. Causation is primarily linear: it starts with selec- cies of selection pressures previously modified by niche
tion pressures stemming from the environment and ends construction). Causation is primarily reciprocal, with
with changes in the organism. Reciprocal causation is rec- selective environments shaping organisms, and organisms
ognized only in some “special cases” in which the source shaping selective environments, either relative to them-
of selection is biotic (e.g., sexual selection, predator prey selves or other organisms. Adopted with permission of
co-evolution). (b) The niche construction perspective. John Wiley & Sons. Flynn, E. G., Laland, K. N., Kendal,
Niche construction is explicitly recognized as an evolu- R. L., & Kendal, J. R. (2013). Developmental niche con-
tionary process. The match between organism and envi- struction. Developmental Science, 16, 296–313. Copyright
ronment results from interactions of natural selection © 2013 and John Wiley & Sons, Inc. Reproduced with per-
pressures in environments and the niche-constructing mission of John Wiley & Sons, Inc. [Figure 2, Page 297]

Flynn, Laland, Kendal, and Kendal (2013) In modifying their environmental niche, organ-
elaborated further on developmental niche con- isms co-direct their evolution (see Fig. 12.4).
struction. They defined the term in depth as the Niche construction and environmental selection
modification of both the living and non-living interact to affect the gene pool through active
components of the environment through an shaping or matching of organism and context.
organism’s activities (metabolic, physiological, Organism and environment engage in reciprocal
behavioral) and through its choices. The pro- causality over both developmental and evolution-
cesses involved are evolutionary ones that mod- ary time through contingent feedback that might
ify phenotypes and selection, with environmental continue to accelerate phylogenetic change after
modification considered not an effect of but a differential selection no longer applies. Organisms,
cause of evolution. then, are active agents in their evolution.
284 12 Nature and Nurture: Evolution and Complexities

Contextual Parameters

a
Ecological
Inheritance b Genes
X Development Behavior
Culture
c

e
f

Change in Processes Over Time

a = Gene-based niche construction

b = Modified natural selection

c = Cultural niche construction

d = Modified cultural selection

e = Developmental niche construction

f = Modified individual development

Fig. 12.5 Selective feedback at multiple levels in mul- process activity, the model avoids the inference that the
tiple niche-construction processes. Selective feedback sequence is from culture first to genes, and then back
influences niche construction at multiple levels. In this (including through development) via selective feedback.
adaptation of the original figure, I placed genetic and That being said, culture and environment can act on
cultural influences as interactive factors on develop- genes before their expression through inter-generational
ment, which then through its own processes produces epigenetic effects. Adapted from Flynn, Laland, Kendal,
behavior. Also, in modifying the temporal sequence of & Kendal (2013)

Further, niche construction does not have to be et al. (2013) referred to cognitive niche construc-
a result of genetic variation, for developmental tion and scaffolded learning (Wheeler & Clark,
and cultural processes might produce the activity. 2008; Fragaszy, 2012; respectively), and also to
Cultural, developmental, and gene-based pro- natural pedagogy and situated learning (Gergely
cesses engage in reciprocal interaction, with each & Csibra, 2013; Sterelny, 2012, respectively).
process affecting ecological inheritance in differ- They concluded that a broader evolutionary syn-
ent ways (see Fig. 12.5). Cultural niche construc- thesis appears in the offing.
tion modifies cultural selection, and vice versa, in Laland (2014) argued that classic evolution-
feedback. The same applies to developmental ary theory focuses on the effect of natural selec-
niche construction and modified individual devel- tion on gene frequencies. In his view, development
opment, as well as to gene-based niche construc- and niche construction work in concert (recipro-
tion and modified natural selection, with each of cally) with evolutionary processes in the causa-
these levels forming an integrated evolutionary, tion of behavior and its change in evolution.
cultural, and developmental system. In reviewing Developing organisms are not just evolutionary
the literature in support of their position, Flynn outcomes; in that they are the “causes of
Development 285

evolution.” Niche construction considers ecolog- As for optimization theory in evolution, for
ical context in behavior, so that evolution marches Frankenhuis et al. (2013), natural selection works
in coordination with externally expressed con- to select from among the options available the
structed processes (as well as internal ones, best ones that serve to maximize the match
development). Developmental plasticity facili- between the design properties of phenotypes and
tates “subsequent genetic accommodation” and the adaptive problems that they confront and
“rapid ecological adjustment.” need to solve. I would summarize this approach
Developmental processes are not solely the by saying that optimization is not an add-on fea-
outcome of prior selection (“under-determined”). ture of evolution but the essential driver.
To conclude, evolution cannot be reduced to nat- Evolutionary fitness in an adaptive sense that
ural selection, given the role of development and promotes survival and reproduction involves fit
niche construction. with the environment in an optimization sense of
the behaviors promoted (because their genetic
underpinnings are such that natural selection can
Development act on them so that they can confer their adaptive
advantage).
Frankenhuis, Panchanathan, and Barrett (2013) Sameroff (2010) also has an inclusive model
have presented the best arguments to date that I connecting the biological with systems, in a
have encountered on two propositions—that evo- model referred to as the biopsychosocial
lution works at the developmental level and that ecological system. Li (2003) created an equiva-
it involves optimization. Typically, evolutionary lent model, considered a co-constructive,
mechanisms, such as natural selection, are dynamical, biocultural and developmental one
described without much consideration of either (see Fig. 12.6). Li (2013) proposed a develop-
the organism’s developmental antecedents or the ment model involving biocultural co-construc-
fitness necessity of earlier or developing behav- tion. She argued that individual agency is an
iors (in terms of earlier survival contributing to active driver in development, including in niche
later survival and reproduction). Moreover, typi- construction. Moreover, proximate mechanisms
cally, evolution is considered the result of random underlie the adaptations involved at the psycho-
mutations that, in appropriate ecological niches, logical and neuromodulatory levels. Sheldon
confer additive fitness benefits. In this view, there et al. (2011) and Sheldon (2011) presented a bio-
is no optimal adaptive design to which evolution psychosocial system model related to personality
necessarily progresses and that drives the evolu- that included nonbiological as well as biopsycho-
tionary process. A third component to the propo- social processes (see Table 12.2).
sitions of the authors is that a dynamic systems Goldhaber (2012) examined the nature–nur-
approach can help integrate the developmental ture debate from the perspective of showing the
and evolutionary areas. interaction between evolution and development
Frankenhuis et al. (2013) noted that develop- and emphasizing their interdependence (e.g.,
ment systems constitute “the central units of evo- Bjorklund, 2006). He noted that adaptations
lution.” All phenotypes reflect the work of might serve immediate survival value in develop-
developmental processes. In this sense, evolu- ment (ontogenic adaptations) or only be useful in
tionary mechanisms modify phenotypic develop- this regard later on (deferred adaptations).
mental systems, in particular. Developing Goldhaber (2012) examined the full range of
phenotypes exist in an external environment sep- genetic and environment processes impacting
arate from them, and natural selection works to development, including epigenetic programs,
maximize the match of developing phenotypic which are in constant transaction with environ-
properties with properties of the environments in ment. He supported the importance of
which they are embedded and related causally. developmental systems theory (Gottlieb, 2007).
[The concept of niche construction is considered Partridge and Greenberg (2010) emphasized self-
similar to this view (Flynn et al., 2013)]. organization and developing systems, allowing
286 12 Nature and Nurture: Evolution and Complexities

Levels of Time Scales Levels of Interactive Processes

Culture-Gene
Human Epoche-1 Epoche Epoche+1… Culture-Gene Coevolution
Phylogeny (involving cultural and
evolutionary plasticity)
On this time scale, culture
exerts long-range affects on
modifying natural selection
pressures of biological
evolution

Culture-Social Situational
Context
Social Situational Contexts and
Life span Periodp-1 Periodp Periodp+1 Periodp+i…. Individual Cognition and
Ontogeny Behavior
(involving behavioral and
cognitive plasticity)
On this time scale, culture exerts
mid range mediated effects on
behavioral and cognitive
development through
intergenerational and
interpersonal social interactions in
the proximal developmental
context.

Culture-Immediate Individual Context


Microgenesis Genetic and Neuronal Epigenesis
Timet-1 Timet Timet+1 Timet+i… (involving genetic and neuronal plasticity)
On this time scale, culture exerts direct and
mediated immediate effects on the individual’s
moment-to-moment activities and experiences
at the genetic, neuronal, cognitive, and
behavioral levels.

Fig. 12.6 Coconstructive biocultural influences imple- indicate the sequences before (−) or after (+) the current e,
mented through interactive processes and developmental p, or t, where i represents an arbitrary number between 1
plasticity across levels. Schematic diagram of the cross- and infinity (e.g., p−1 = the previous life period; p + 1 = the
level dynamic biocultural coconstructive framework of next life period; p + i = a given number of life periods after
development, showing that concerted biocultural influ- the current life period). Adopted with permission of
ences are implemented through interconnected interactive American Psychological Association. Copyright © 2003
processes and developmental plasticity across levels and by the American Psychological Association. Reprinted
time scales. Downward arrows denote culture-individual with permission. The official citation that should be used
interaction, culture-situation interaction, and situation- in referencing this material is [Li, S.-C. (2003). Biocultural
individual interaction; upward arrows denote individual- orchestration of developmental plasticity across levels:
situation interaction and situation-culture-gene The interplay of biology and culture in shaping the mind
interaction. The subscripts e, p, and t represent the current and behavior across the life span. Psychological Bulletin,
epoch, life period, and moment-to-moment microgenetic 129, 171–194.]. The use of APA information does not
time, respectively. The notations of these subscripts ± 1…i imply endorsement by APA. [Figure 1, Page 174]

them to be adapted to context. Contemporary In terms of early work in the field, Hogan and
models of systems do not find a linear relation- Bolhuis (1994) edited a book on the causal mecha-
ship between cause and effect but examine the nisms of development. In the book, Hogan (1994)
whole system. reviewed Tinbergen’s four types of questions
Partridge and Greenberg (2010) referred to related to biology: causation, survival value, ontog-
“emergent phenomena” in development, and eny, and evolution. He revised Aristotle’s four
noted that they are real and observable. In addi- causal questions (material, efficient, formal, and
tion, they exhibit “radical novelty” or global/ final) into the language of matter, causation, struc-
macro characteristics that are not within other ture, and consequences, respectively. As for mech-
micro features of the system. Also, emergent anism, Hogan stated that mechanism implies cause.
phenomena exhibit coherence or a unity over In the different levels of analysis of behavior, one
time and are dynamic, being responsive to can find behavioral mechanisms, neural
changes to the system over time. mechanisms, and so on, and also functions of
Nature and Nurture (and Ourselves) 287

Table 12.2 The biopsychosocial continuum of the self in side of the equation more than the other, although
the social world this does not mean that the other side is being
Continuum Process Component diminished.
SOCIAL Cultural Social network
Organizational Environment Although in this chapter we have
Group focused on evolutionary effects in development,
PSYCHO Interpersonal Self (Traits, goals) in no way have we discounted environmental
Personality influences on development. Study of the role of
Cognitive genetics interacting with environment in the
BIO Neuronal Constitution
development of intelligence continues (e.g.,
Biological
Deary, 2012; Nisbett et al., 2012), but an undeni-
Nonbiological
able strong influence of environmental factors
Adapted from Sheldon (2011)
Conceptualizing the self as the interface between the person
keeps emerging. The role of the environment on
and the social world on the biopsychosocial continuum long-term development has been made clear in a
recent meta-analysis on the Flynn effect, or the
behavior. In this regard, Chisholm (1990) presented finding that over generations, intelligence quo-
a life-history perspective on development. For tient (IQ) scores have been increasing by several
example, early experience has “immediate” effects points per generation. For the Flynn effect, Trahan,
on development that needs to be analyzed at a Stuebing, Fletcher, and Hiscock (2014) showed
Darwinian level for “construction” of alternate that the effect is not diminishing and is robust (the
developmental pathways to “an adaptive endpoint.” observed rise in IQ scores over generations is con-
Developmental processes affect Darwinian “fit- tinuing over time). The research discounted the
ness” through natural selection, and they evolve. genetic (heterosis: hybrid vigor) hypothesis.
Sternberg (2014) advocated for an important
role of culture in the development of adaptive
Nature and Nurture (and Ourselves) competence. For example, parents socialize chil-
dren in view of their own folk conceptions, or
In the following, I examine views on two critical implicit theories of intelligence, and not accord-
higher-order aspects of behavior in terms of the ing to standardized test criteria. Also, intelligence
genetic and environmental contributions to their is as much practical/social in competencies/
development and expression. The two areas are knowledge as standard/academic or abstract.
intelligence and a facet of personality referred to Therefore, teachers who understand and use
as neuroticism. The literature review in each case approaches consistent with the former can pro-
emphasizes general factors that are genetically duce better results in students even on tasks
influenced. In both cases, I argue that a proper, aimed at the latter.
integrative model should not only include socio- Nisbett et al. (2012) noted that the importance
cultural, environmental factors, but also personal, of environmental factors is indicated for IQ by
psychological ones. For example, intelligence is the 12- to 18-point increase in IQ when children
influenced by self factors such as motivation and in adoption move from working-class to middle-
personality is influenced by a multitude of fac- class homes. Also, although early intervention
tors, as well. programs might not lead to persisting short-term
effects, they do have positive long-term out-
comes (e.g., in academic achievement). Further,
Intelligence sex differences in IQ are found to be partly due to
environmental factors. And the black–white IQ
Introduction Intelligence is a developmental gap continues to reduce. In addition, reciprocal
product of genetic and environmental influences. causation is evident between intellectual func-
Nevertheless, points of view might support one tioning and brain morphology. That is, exercise
288 12 Nature and Nurture: Evolution and Complexities

of a particular skill might function to increase the Genes Plomin and Deary (2015) described three
size of a particular brain area (e.g., Haier, laws of genetics of complex traits and five spe-
Karama, Leyba, & Jung, 2009). On the negative cial findings related to genetics and intelligence.
side, aspects of the environment (stress and social The former include: (a) all complex traits reveal
class) might act to affect adversely intelligence significant genetic influence; (b) however, no
(e.g., Eccleston, 2011). such trait is 100 % inheritable, leaving room for
Sternberg (2012) noted that the heritability environmental influence; and (c) heritability is
coefficient for intelligence (ratio of genetic to the result of multiple genes with each having a
phenotypic variation in the population) varies small effect.
between 0.4 and 0.8. Despite the evident influ- As for the five findings related to intelligence
ence of genetics in intelligence, he also noted that in these regards, Plomin and Deary (2015) first
genetics “always” expresses itself “through envi- noted that (a) heritability is relative low in
ronment.” Moreover, heritability estimates vary infancy (about 20 %) and increases dramatically
according to factors that include socioeconomic into later adulthood (about 80 %). This might
status and the range in environment. Further, for occur due to genetic amplification through gene-
racial-group differences, the groups are social environment correlation. Also, (b) intelligence
“constructed” ones more than biological ones. relates to diverse cognitive and learning abilities,
Protzko, Aronson, and Blair (2013) added that with the genes involved affecting all of them.
young children could have their intelligence level There is both pleiotropy (each gene affects mul-
raised by environmental interventions that can tiple traits) and polygenicity (multiple genes
include reading to children, aside from appropri- affect each of them). Therefore, “generalist”
ate nutrition and education. Deary (2012) con- genes are at play in intelligence and have genetic
cluded that intelligence research should be action over diverse cognitive and learning abili-
integral in the study of the causes and conse- ties upstream into brain structure and function in
quences of human development. He placed it as a network model. (c) Third, the phenotypic cor-
the center of a wider study of behavior. relation between mating partners in intelligence
Research continues to support a general (assortive mating) is higher than in other traits,
importance for environmental and not only which acts to increase additive genetic variance
genetic influences on cognitive and related in the case of intelligence. (d) Next, the low- and
behavior (e.g., Karmiloff-Smith, Casey, Massand, high-end of the intelligence distribution is sub-
Tomalski, & Thomas, 2014) and a special G × E ject to different genetic effects, as well as differ-
(Genetic × Environment) influence on behavior ent exposures to deleterious pre- and post-natal
(Tucker-Drob & Briley, 2014). In Karmiloff- trauma. (e) Finally, intelligence, education, and
Smith et al. (2014), socioeconomic status and social class might be related for genetic reasons,
stress were considered as factors that affect neu- given that the latter two are correlated with intel-
rocognitive development, but allelic differences ligence (and its higher heritability).
were shown to be important, too. They concluded The authors called for more research using
that phenotypes are emergent rather than prede- genome-wide polygenic scores and GCTA
termined. Tucker-Drob and Briley (2014) exam- (Genome-wide Complex Trait Analysis), without
ined the continuity of environmental and genetic forgetting G, C, T, A (guanine, cytosine, thymine,
influences on cognition over the life-span. Their adenine), and particular genes (DNA variants)
meta-analysis supported Gene × Environment that are formed in their base pair sequencing.
interaction and gene-environment correlation as They appear to be reminding that in the debate
important in this regard. They found an increas- over genetics and environment in intelligence,
ing phenotypic stability in development, which although both apply, the genetic contribution
was almost completely mediated by genetic fac- should be given its proper place.
tors. Yet they found the results were most consis- Counterintuitive results have been found in the
tent with a transactional model. study of general cognitive ability (g, intelligence).
Nature and Nurture (and Ourselves) 289

In a longitudinal twin study conducted at ages 7, Comment I conclude this section by noting that
9, and 12 years of age, Kovas et al. (2013) stud- there is sufficient evidence to support both a
ied literacy and numeracy, as well as g, in pri- genetic and environmental contribution to the
mary school age children. The individual development of intelligence and associated cogni-
differences found were “significantly” and “sub- tion. However, in keeping with the general theme
stantially” more heritable not for g but for liter- of the book, an interactive model of intelligence
acy/numeracy (ages 7, 9). The results suggest should be biopsychosocial and consider personal
that universal education reduces individual dif- factors as part of the psychological ones, such as
ferences in environmental disparity, so that those related to motivation, self, coping skills, and
obtained school-related differences in literacy/ even having a belief in and a sense of free will.
numeracy are due to genetic differences among
the children. Kovas et al. (2013) reminded that
the heritability of g increases as development Neuroticism
proceeds because we increasingly select and cre-
ate individually-appropriate environments that Introduction Most of the present section is
are consistent with our genetic propensities (this about common factors in psychopathology, espe-
is the process of gene-environment correlation, cially for the personality factor of neuroticism.
and I add this is the evocative type). For continuity in personality development into
Similarly, Kan, Wicherts, Doland, and van der adulthood, Briley and Tucker-Drob (2014)
Maas (2013) analyzed data from 23 twin studies. demonstrated that the trend of increasing
They obtained results supportive of the counter- phenotypic stability appears to reflect the role
intuitive notion that greater heritability coeffi- of environmental mechanisms rather than
cients were found on “culture-loaded” compared genetic ones. Nevertheless, the common factor
to “culture-reduced” subtests. Comparable approach to psychopathology suggests a genetic
results were found for subtest variance shared contribution.
with general intelligence—the proportion was a
function of cultural load (for children, as well). View 1 Barlow, Sauer-Zavala, Carl, Bullis, and
They concluded that the most heritable abilities Ellard (2014) proposed that the DSM-5
are the most culture-dependent ones. The reason (Diagnostic and Statistical Manual, Fifth edition;
relates to a greater contribution of active American Psychiatric Association, 2013) splits
genotype-environment correlation to culture- disorders to the point that their differences are
loaded compared to culture-reduced cognitive trivial. In this regard, they reviewed to the con-
abilities. That is, high achievers, by virtue of a cept of neuroticism (Eysenck, 1947), which is the
heritable contribution, have actively sought out personality tendency to experience intense and
and had exposure to more stimulating or frequent exaggerated negative emotional reac-
cognitively-demanding environments (culture), tions in response to stressors, along with the eval-
thereby better activating their potential cognitive uation that the external environment is dangerous
skill/intelligence. and constitutes a threat relative to one’s inade-
Bates, Lewis, and Weiss (2013) reported simi- quate coping skills and lack of control.
lar results. The higher the SES, the greater the The latent temperamental structure of emo-
genetic influences on intelligence in adults even tional disorders generally supports a two-
though the effect of environmental influences dimensional view of core dimensions atop a
was constant. They concluded that genes serve to hierarchical structure, and neuroticism emerges
“multiply” environmental supports related to at the primary one, with extraversion secondary.
intellectual growth. The process of augmenting Neuroticism has also been referred to as negative
social resources that act to raise the average of affect/emotionality, behavioral inhibition, trait
intellectual ability also functions to increase indi- anxiety, and harm avoidance, as well as in terms
vidual differences found in it. of internalizing disorders.
290 12 Nature and Nurture: Evolution and Complexities

Barlow, Ellard, Sauer-Zavala, Bullis, and Carl school internalizing problems overlapped with
(2014) presented a triple vulnerability model on genetic variants in common child and adult psy-
the origins of neurotic-type behavior, with gen- chiatric disorders (e.g., anxiety, depression,
eral and specific psychological experiences and schizophrenia).
vulnerabilities channeling earlier biological (her- In a similar vein, in a meta-analysis of behav-
itable) ones to particular expressions of one type ior genetic studies, Vukasović and Bratko (2015)
of disorder or another. The psychological vulner- showed that the best heritability estimate of per-
abilities involve unpredictability and uncontrol- sonality traits, or genetic contributions to indi-
lability in the environment leading to the learning vidual differences in personality, is in the order of
of specific maladaptive behaviors, and leading to 40 %. The results were found in studies using dif-
corresponding alterations in brain function and ferent behavior genetic study designs and differ-
circuits. According to Barlow, Sauer-Zavala, ent personality models. The number of studies
et al. (2014), neuroticism is malleable, treatable, involved included 45 primary studies involving
and even preventable. more than 100,000 participants, from diverse
Barlow, Sauer-Zavala, et al. (2014) opined backgrounds, and varying ages. As with the heri-
that neuroticism is characterized by emotions to tability estimate for intelligence reviewed previ-
the point that it is worthwhile to consider the ously, there is a notable estimate for personality
term of “emotional” disorder instead of neuroti- but, nevertheless, the results imply a genetic and
cism. In this regard, the authors reported the environmental contribution to development of
development of the multidimensional emotional the psychological attribute.
disorder inventory. Its major dimensions include:
anxiety/neuroticism; behavioral activation/posi- View 2 Caspi et al. (2014) have extended the
tive affect; unipolar depression; mania; somatic Barlow, Sauer-Zavala, et al. (2014) argument one
anxiety; panic and related autonomic surges; step further by advocating for a p factor, or a gen-
intrusive cognitions; social evaluation; past eral psychopathology factor, in the structure of
trauma; behavioral/interoceptive avoidance; and mental disorders. In their longitudinal study over
cognitive/emotional avoidance. 20 years (years 18–38), they examined 11 com-
Barlow, Sauer-Zavala, et al. (2014) noted that mon adult mental disorder types in a representa-
therapies that are transdiagnostic might be quite tive birth cohort (the Dunedin Multidisciplinary
efficacious, given the commonalities in DSM-5 Health and Development Study). They took into
disorders and their common core superordinate account dimensionality, persistence, comorbidity,
dimensions, including neuroticism and extraver- and sequence. The results showed three core
sion. In this regard, they described their unified psychopathological dimensions—internalizing,
protocol for transdiagnostic treatment of emo- externalizing, and thought-related one—but the
tional disorders (UP) (Barlow et al., 2011). The best explanation of psychiatric disorder involved
authors concluded that a broader view of diagno- a more generalized dimension of General
sis, assessment, and treatment might profit from Psychopathology (p, akin to g in intelligence). The
considering the concepts of neuroticism and p dimension functions to coalesce into one under-
emotional disorders. lying dimension for individual’s propensities to
Benke et al. (2014) undertook a genome-wide develop psychopathology of any nature. It appears
association meta-analysis of preschool internal- associated with early dynamic processes that
izing problems that supported the Barlow, Sauer- unfold in the environment, including its adversi-
Zavala, et al. (2014) approach to mental disorder. ties, rather than lying in a single unitary cause.
They found genome-wide single nucleotide According to Caspi et al. (2014), the disorders
polymorphisms (SNPs) that explained up to in adulthood do not evolve linearly from early
43 % of the total variance in the target behavior, disorders because early brief episodes do not
although collectively in a polygenic model. necessarily become persistent (see Fig. 12.7).
Furthermore, genetic variants influencing pre- A developmental progression takes place in
Nature and Nurture (and Ourselves) 291

p
Development (Persistence)

Impairment

Internalizing Externalizing

Female Style Male


(Gendered)

Fig. 12.7 The p factor (General Psychopathology). D. W., Goldman-Mellor, S. J., Harrington, H., Israel, S.,
Individuals might briefly manifest an episode of a gen- Meier, M. H., Ramrakha, S., Shalev, I., Poulton, R., &
dered individual disorder. A subset of these individuals Moffitt, T. E. (2014). The p factor: One general psychopa-
might develop persistent increasingly impairing external- thology factor in the structure of psychiatric disorders?
izing and internalizing disorders. Only some individual Clinical Psychological Science, 2, 119–137, Copyright
develop extreme elevation of p. Adopted with permission 2014, reprinted with permission of SAGE Publications.
of SAGE publications. Caspi, A., Houts, R. M., Belsky, [Figure 3, Page 133]

which disorder and impairment become persis- p factor (as well as smaller internalizing and
tent and broad, and often these include thought- externalizing factors). The authors concluded that
related disorder. The genes involved operate the results speak to the structure of psychopathol-
pleiotropically to augment risk for “any and all” ogy, but should not be reified, in that the general
mental disorders. Caspi et al. (2014) concluded factor found could reflect a number of causes, as
that their p factor model implies that it is fruitless yet undetermined.
to seek causes, biomarkers, consequences, and Stochl et al. (2015) also supported the work of
treatments specific to individual disorders. Caspi et al. (2014). They found that a bi-factor
In a study with adolescents, Laceulle, model with a single, unitary common mental dis-
Vollebergh, and Ormel (2015) replicated the tress factor fit the constellation of symptoms in
results found by Caspi et al. (2014) that psycho- participants expressing depression, anxiety, and
pathology reflects a latent general overall severity psychotic phenomena.
292 12 Nature and Nurture: Evolution and Complexities

Comment In later chapters in the book on the The circuitry described of mapping specific
DSM-5, my approach to psychopathology is quite biochemical signals to specific gene expression
similar to that of Barlow, Caspi, and colleagues. responses constitutes an evolved, adaptive pro-
The DSM-5 contains too many disorders and it gram in ancestral humans. The question remains
can be simplified, and the disorders have shorter whether the mapping that has evolved continues
lists of core symptoms than the longer ones that to be adaptive in present social circumstances.
are found at present. Moreover, in my therapeutic Cole (2011) referred to the genome as “fluid,”
work, I adopt a transdiagnostic, componential given the evidence for socioenvironmental
approach (Young, 2014) that is consistent with effects on gene expression. The social world has
the approach of Barlow and colleagues. the capacity to regulate gene expression. Social
In the next section of the chapter, I describe signals can influence cell surround microenviron-
the area of social genomics, which illustrates ments (e.g., hormones, neurotransmitters), which
quite well genes and environment interact, in this can end up influencing behavior and health. The
case in health, in particular. The environment can classic distinction between environment and
indeed get under the skin. organism might not be a clear division in the bio-
logical world. Early adversity might be espe-
cially deleterious in programming it effects.
Social Genomics Critical periods are found and lay the basis for
long-term molecular imprints on physiology,
Model behavior, and health.
But even transient events later on could alter
Cole (2014) described the burgeoning field of gene expression (e.g., loss of one night sleep can
human social genomics. His conceptualization alter gene expression profiles related to immu-
and literature review showed how the circum- nity; Irwin, Wang, Campomayor, Collado-
stances of everyday life are capable of influenc- Hidalgo, & Cole, 2006). The ability of even
ing gene expression. Humans create complex relatively brief socioenvironmental “shocks” to
social systems that have been referred to as alter gene expression relates to the recursive
“hypersocial,” or “meta-organisms.” In addition, structure of gene regulation networks. They
the social influence on genes indicates the cre- involve interdigitated feedback mechanisms that
ation of “metagenomes.” For Cole, extraorganis- might produce nonlinear changes in equilibrium
mic factors in the environment and intraorganismic dynamics (Kauffman, 1993; Kim, Shay, O’Shea,
physiological function stand in reciprocal inter- & Regev, 2009).
relation in the elucidation of behavior and health. Slavich and Cole (2013) elaborated further on
Cole (2014) continued that the social- human social genomics, and concluded that we
environmental conditions that influence genetics live in a human “metagenome” in which gene
in social genomics include not only social isola- expression is determined, in part, by the tran-
tion but also social threat, low/unstable social sta- scriptomes of other people, generating a system
tus, low SES, and urbanity. When social with complex emergent properties (Kauffman,
environments influence gene expression, it takes 1993). We are not a fixed molecular (genetic) self
place through physiochemical processes (e.g., but one from among potential biological selves
toxins) and psychological ones (e.g., experience expressed via social-environmental regulation of
of threat/uncertainty). The latter trigger neural our genes. The social-environmental factors
and endocrine responses (e.g., activation of the involved are subjective (e.g., perceived loneli-
sympathetic nervous system (SNS)). Either way, ness) more than objective (they are unrelated to
(physical, psychological) biochemical mediators social activity/contact), and they influence broad
act to promote receptor system activity that leads sets of genes (profiles, programs). Therefore, in
to intracellular signal transduction pathways. G × E research, it is not just that the external
In turn, these either activate or inhibit relevant social world gets “under our skin” it also gets
transcription factors. “onto our genome.”
Social Genomics 293

Social Processes
(Adverse Environment) External
Recursion
(Social)

CNS Function Social


(Threat Behavior
Perception and in Niche
Evaluation)

Peripheral
Neurobiology
(SNS / HPA
Signaling)

Internal Cellular Signal


Recursion Transduction (β-
(Physiologic) adrenergic receptor/
cAMP / PKA)

Transcription Factor
Activation
(↑CREB, ↑GATA,
↑NF-kB, ↓IRF)

Gene Expression
(Gene regulation,
CTRA: ↑pro-
inflammatory,
↓interferon)

Health

Fig. 12.8 Human social signal transduction and human adversity (CTRA) in leukoctyes. Perceptions of social
recursive network genomics. Social experiences become threat activate the )SNS, causing release of norepineph-
physiologically embedded, first, by internal physiologic rine (NE), activation of β-adrenergic receptors, and stimu-
recursion (the genes targeted by social signal transduction lation/repression of specific transcription factors in
pathways encode the molecules that mediate social signal response to the cyclic 3′–5′ adenosine monophosphate/
transduction), which sensitizes signal transduction path- protein kinase A (cAMP/PKA) signaling pathway.
ways to the external social environment. Second, external β-adrenergic-responsive transcription factors induce the
social recursion can biologically embed social experience CTRA gene expression program by stimulating transcrip-
(social signal transduction can modulate genes involved in tion of genes encoding proinflammatory cytokines and
the regulation of social behavior). The social signal trans- suppressing transcription of genes encoding Type I inter-
duction pathway permits mapping of adverse social con- ferons and IgG antibodies. Adapted from Cole (2014),
ditions onto the conserved transcriptional response to and Slavich & Cole (2013)

The social environment can affect our genes and the SNS (e.g., norepinephrine) impact cell
because proteins are replenished daily (1–2 % are surface receptors. Intracellular transcription
replaced each day), and ongoing physiological factors initiative a metabolic cascade leading to
processes are stress-responsive. Extracellular binding of gene promoters by transcription
signals from the endocrine system (e.g., cortisol) factors, which might dysregulate protein T and,
294 12 Nature and Nurture: Evolution and Complexities

ultimately, behavior and even health. Because production; and neoinnervation of lymphoid tis-
there are individual differences in binding affini- sues. Cole (2014) noted that CTRA gene expres-
ties related to DNA polymorphisms, there are sion profiles can be suppressed by physical/
corresponding individual differences in social/ psychological interventions (cognitive behav-
environmental effects on behavior and disease. ioral, Antoni et al., 2012; meditation, Black et al.,
2012; yoga, Bower et al., 2014; and Tai Chi,
Irwin et al., 2014).
CTRA

Slavich and Cole (2013) proceeded to explain RNA


how social signals are transduced in hormone
and neurotransmitter central nervous system Cole (2011, 2014) described a model of how
dynamics (see Fig. 12.8). Social-environmental RNA provides a molecular medium of recursive
stressors act on the SNS and hypothalamic-pitu- development and can be influenced by social
itary-adrenal (HPA) axis via neurocognitive conditions. As the environment influences the
appraisals, and lead to effects on the genes body and subsequent behavior and also RNA (or
involved in proinflammatory and )antiviral activ- gene expression), the next influence acts on a dif-
ity (in ILIB, IL6, IL8, TNF; and IFNA, IFNB, ferent body and RNA set (see Fig. 12.9). The
respectively). The effects involved include recur- micro-level of socioenvironmental impacts has
sive processes both transcriptionally and socially, long-term macro-level effects. Regulation of
which act to affect the sensitivity of and the behavior derives not only from genetic character-
future activity in the pathways. Other people istics but also from past and current environment,
respond differently to the social changes, ampli- including at the social level.
fying the effects. Given that the neurocognitive A self-perpetuating cycle persists well after
appraisals involved are subjective, individual dif- the originating stimulus has passed. Given the
ference factors, such as in personality (e.g., neu- effect on body and RNA in this self-modifying
roticism), can contribute to the recursions and recursive dynamic, gene expression is considered
consequent behavior and health outcomes. not only a cause but also a consequence of behav-
Cole (2014) proceeded to describe that part of ior. The model presented is an “environmentally
the differential expression of gene transcripts conscious” one of genetics and, moreover, it is a
related to social adversity includes a common evo- social one, which includes a personal perceptual
lutionarily conceived transcriptional response to and meaning component to what is considered
adversity (CTRA). The CTRA has been found to social. The “transcriptional memory” that is lain
social conditions involving: low SES (Cole et al., down by adversity suggests that the history of
2010); chronic stress (Miller et al., 2014); bereave- environmental shocks to the person should be
ment (O’Connor, Schultze-Florey, Irwin, Arevalo, detectable or backcasted with current gene
& Cole, 2014); PTSD (posttraumatic stress disor- expression profiles. Also, molecular forecasting
der; O’Donovan et al., 2011); and cancer diagnosis might be possible, e.g., future response to a ther-
(Cohen et al., 2012). CTRA involves increased apy. Cole (2011) concluded that the social world
expression of proinflammatory genes and also blows through our bodies like a breeze.
decreased expression of genes in Type I interferon
(innate) antiviral responses and IgG antibody syn-
thesis (Cole, 2010)]. Comment
Three pathways have been found to up-
regulate CTRA gene expression in immune cells Cole (2014) discounted epigenesis as a major
due to prolonged social/threat adversity—SNS/β-- factor mediating the relationship between social
adrenergic )regulation of transcriptional pro- influences and gene expression. Epigenesis has
grams in existing monocytes; de novo monocyte been found as an effect of specific environmental
Social Genomics 295

Behavior
Social Environment
Time Point 1 Configuration Body
RNA

Behavior
Social Environment
Time Point 2 Configuration Body
RNA

Fig. 12.9 RNA as a molecular medium of recursive functionally-altered body. This may result in different
development. Social conditions at point one in time (envi- behavioral and transcriptional responses at time point two,
ronment) are transduced into changes in behavior and and affect current and future behavior and health.
gene expression (RNA) through central nervous system/ Therefore, RNA appears to serve as the medium for recur-
perceptual processes that trigger neural/endocrine sive developmental changes that integrate genetic charac-
responses (body). The RNA transcriptional dynamics teristics and historical-environmental regulators. Adapted
unleashed can alter the molecular characteristics of cells from Cole (2011), based on Cole (2009)
involved in environmental perception/response, yielding a

conditions, but epigenetic profiles are correlated cells in chronically socially-isolated individuals
only weakly with differences in immune-cell relative to integrated ones. They showed both an
genetic expression. Cole concluded about epi- enhanced expression of proinflammatory immune
genesis that even transient environmental condi- response genes and down regulation of antiviral
tions can act to produce persistent biological, immune response genes. Similar effects were
psychological, and social consequences (e.g., in found for targeted social rejection (Murphy,
PTSD) without including any persistent DNA Slavich, Rohleder, & Miller, 2013) and PTSD
modification, such as through epigenetic stamps. (O’Donovan et al., 2011).
The work of Cole and colleagues on the effect
of social loneliness on health is supported by
Evidence research by Jaremka et al. (2013). They looked at
two samples of lonelier adults, one healthy and
Cole et al. (2007) and Cole, Hawkley, Arevalo, one post-treatment breast-cancer survivors
and Cacioppo (2011) showed that people experi- exposed to acute stress. Compared to less lonely
encing chronic self-isolation evidenced genome- controls, the lonely groups exhibited elevated
wide transcriptional profiling of leukocytes, with proinflammatory cytokines (e.g., interleukin-6
more than 200 genes that demonstrated greater (IL6)). The author suggested that lonelier popula-
than 50 % difference in average levels of expres- tions express a proinflammatory phenotype.
sion compared to socially-integrated individuals.
For the socially isolated individuals, genes that
were up-regulated included a set of inflammation- Health
related transcripts (e.g., ILIB, IL8), and down-
regulated ones included a set in the transcription Genes related to behavior do not only have psy-
of Type I interferon (innate) antiviral responses chiatric effects but also health ones. Murphy et al.
(e.g., ISG, IFI, MX) and of antibody production (2013) found that targeted social rejection in ado-
(e.g., IGL, IGH, IGJ, IGK). lescents influenced the signaling pathways in
As described in Slavich and Cole (2013), Cole inflammation regulation. Over a 2.5-year period,
et al. (2007) found a large change in the expression adolescents at risk for major depression who
of two gene profiles within circulating immune reported targeted rejection had more simultaneous
296 12 Nature and Nurture: Evolution and Complexities

elevations in pro-inflammatory immune response meditative interventions can promote healthier


gene activity, nuclear factor-κB (NF-κB), and an cell division, control of biological aging, and
inhibitor (I-κB) in leukocyte messenger RNA psychological well-being.
(mRNA), as well as a lower ratio of NF-κB/ Being present in the moment could lead to a
I-κB. The same data were not found for low-grade healthier psychology by detracting from trying to
inflammation signals. The results demonstrated avoid unhappy thoughts and adding to the control
an interaction effect, with the findings more evi- of chronic arousal. Researchers are finding that
dent in participants high in the adolescents’ own the phenomenon of presence and mindful accep-
perceived social standing in their peer group tance of negative affect helps reduce clinical
(social status), making them more at risk for symptoms and distress (Bieling et al., 2012).
long-term illness if targeted rejection should con- Higher telomerase activity is associated with
tinue, given the upregulation of inflammation meditation (Jacobs et al., 2011; Lavretsky et al.,
gene expression. The authors concluded that the 2013). Even social connection has been related to
genome is “quite” fluid and quite susceptible to protecting TL, although negative experiential
social influence, e.g., adverse social experiences. impacts are seen as accumulating even prenatally
[Note in the present case, the adolescents of (Puterman & Epel, 2012).
higher perceived social status could have experi- In this regard, Puterman and Epel (2012)
enced targeted social rejection as more socially referred to telomere length as capturing the inter-
adverse because of its signal as a threat to their play between genetics, life experience, and psy-
higher self-perceived social standing.] chosocial and behavioral factors. They referred
Evidence is accumulating in other areas that to it as a potential marker of multisystem resil-
severe stress can have genetic and psychological iency, depending on the stress and experience
consequences and that controlling it by mindful- involved (or a multisystem vulnerability with
ness promotes healthier states. Epel et al. (2013) increased cellular allostatic load). It is worth-
examined healthy 50- to 65-year-olds for mind while noting that healthy lifestyle, in general, can
wandering, acceptance, nonattachment, and mitigate vulnerability in the telomere-related
awareness, as well as depressive symptoms, per- aging system (Puterman et al., 2010).
ceived stress, rumination, and life satisfaction.
They measured telomere length as a proxy mea-
sure of biological aging and correlate of severe Chapter Conclusions
stress. Telomeres protect chromosome termini as
DNA-based caps, and their shortness is related to To conclude, I examine in what direction an inte-
stress, disease, )and mortality. The study exam- grated understanding of the multiple influences of
ined leukocyte telomere length (LTL) and also, behavior might lead in terms of the new under-
for a portion of the participants, telomere length standing emerging of the evolutionary process. In
(TL) in specific types of immune cells, lympho- this regard, complexity might have a bootstrap-
cytes and granulocytes. The sample consisted of ping effect on evolution and accelerate its natural
highly-educated women with relatively low stress (selection) speed. More than being a complement
experience. to it, complexity might predispose evolution to
Relative to measurement of tendency to be take place faster. Moreover, complexity might act
present in the moment, measurement of high in evolution through particular developmental
mind wandering (e.g., feel totally focused vs. not phases. For example, according to nonlinear
wanting to be there) was associated with shorter dynamical systems theory and complexity theory
telomeres in all cell types, even after controlling (Kauffman, 1993), systems live on the edge of
for stress level and other confounds. The results order and disorder because this is the region in
suggested that, specifically, less mind wandering, their state space that is optimal for change. Indeed,
more attentional focus and task-relevant thought systems that evolve to inhabit this region might be
and, generally, better executive function and even evolutionarily advantaged, even at the population
Chapter Conclusions 297

level, through the complexity and diversity that it of causal influences on behavior, at least to some
can foster, just as is the case at the developmental degree, and enslave lower-order influences, such
level for which gravitating to the cusp of change as biological and environmental ones. In this
is a frequent concept that is encountered. view, genes and environment are not the major
The theorizing on the relationship between influences on behavioral causality, but we are,
natural selection and complexity has implications (ourselves and our selves). We are sources that
for understanding causality. On the one hand, it can promote not only our development as a third
suggests that, at the biological level, natural selec- force, but even human evolution, for example, by
tion has a range of forces in its selective power. participating in the cultural advances that are at
All things considered, at one extreme, it could be play in gene-cultural co-evolution.
either majorly or uniquely involved in evolution. It would seem impossible to separate com-
However, at the other extreme, natural selection in plexity from either development or evolution,
evolution, as well as related evolutionary forces, especially because its characteristic of being
such as kin selection and reciprocity, might be primed for change is adaptive to both processes.
part of broader evolutionary systems with recipro- Development and evolution might be hierarchi-
cal influences from independent processes, such cally subsumed to system dynamics, including in
as in complexification, epigenesis, and so on. complexity. That is, both development and evolu-
Second, complexification would appear to be tion might implicitly involve complexification as
inherent in the living process at the evolutionary a driver of change to some degree, and are pro-
level, just as it is evident at the developmental cesses that have taken advantage of the drive to
level. Evolutionarily, there might not be a teleo- complexification that are inherent in them.
logical, grand design toward that end, but it could Moreover, complexity itself could hierarchically
be inherent in any system that exists because it organize and privilege some factors over others
serves to promote change, which is conducive to as enslavement ones that are superordinate in
adaptation. causality. Overall, this process might best be
Third, causality in systems might become termed “causal complexification” (or causal
inherently more complex as systems change, complexity).
including in evolutionary and developmental sys- To repeat, on the one hand, as systems evolve,
tems, because of their inherent self-organization they might develop advanced causal complexifi-
toward increasing complexity. The multiplicity of cation such that previously important causal fac-
parts, levels, and influences could become increas- tors lose their causal force or power. On the
ingly dynamically sophisticated to the point that other hand, relative to the power of prior lower
causality is embedded in a labyrinth of both evi- levels, higher-order and emergent levels might
dent and hidden influences, thus hard to discern. take on even more causal importance as the sys-
At the same time, just as systems could mani- tems complexify, integrating disparate causal
fest hierarchization over macro- and micro- mechanisms into superordinate wholes having
levels, with reduced degrees of freedom in the top-down integrative influences previously not
system by “enslaving” lower-order levels to present. That being said, as is implicit in the
higher-order ones (Haken, 1983), so could causal concept itself of systems, in the proposed causal
influences reflect a hierarchical organizational complexification process, lower-order levels
complexity in order to give more freedom of never are subsumed fully as bottom-up influ-
action. That is, the paradox in losing degrees of ences by higher-order top-down ones. Causality
freedom through superordinate, top-down always remains distributed throughout a system
enslavement of lower-order, bottom influences is despite shifting causal emphasis over time. This
that the system is chunked, which allows more reflects the circular causality inherent in the
freedom in flexibility of action. relation between top-down and bottom-up influ-
This might be true of free will, for example, or ences of higher-order and lower-order system
other self factors, which should reside at the apex levels.
298 12 Nature and Nurture: Evolution and Complexities

The concept of inherent complexification in deterministic and indeterministic influences


the evolution of systems, including that of bio- might characterize their functioning as complexi-
logical evolution, and that causality might be fication proceeds, as if in a dialectical dance.
similarly complexified, has implications for the
question of determinism versus indeterminism.
Prigogine and Stengers (1997) had maintained References
that demonstration of irreversibility and instabil-
ity in systems runs counter to determinism. American Psychiatric Association. (2013). Diagnostic
and statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM-V
Systems exist “far-from-equilibrium” and, due to
(5th ed.). Washington, DC: Author.
“sensitivity to initial conditions,” can change dra- Antoni, M. H., Lutgendorf, S. K., Blomberg, B., Stagl, J.,
matically, such as with “emergence,” but in a pro- Carver, C. S., Lechner, S., et al. (2012). Transcriptional
cess that is probabilistic or statistical rather than modulation of human leukocytes by cognitive-
behavioral stress management in women undergoing
deterministic. Therefore, system properties, such
treatment for breast cancer. Biological Psychiatry, 71,
as self-organization, emergence, and complexifi- 366–372.
cation, suggest that not only does causality com- Badcock, P. B. (2012). Evolutionary systems theory: A
plexify but also, as it does, the systems become unifying meta-theory of psychological science. Review
of General Psychology, 16, 10–23.
increasingly indeterministic. Just as natural selec-
Barlow, D. H., Ellard, K. K., Fairholme, C., Farchione,
tion might express a range in its force or power, T. J., Boisseau, C., Allen, L., et al. (2011). Unified pro-
from absolute to degrees of relativization with tocol for the transdiagnostic treatment of emotional
respect to other processes, such as complexity, so disorders. New York: Oxford University Press.
Barlow, D. H., Ellard, K. K., Sauer-Zavala, S., Bullis,
might determinism express a range of force or
J. R., & Carl, J. R. (2014). The origins of trait neuroti-
power, from absolute determinism to degrees of cism. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 9,
relativization with respect to indeterminate pro- 481–496.
cesses, including emergence. Therefore, the pro- Barlow, D. H., Sauer-Zavala, S., Carl, J. R., Bullis, J. R.,
& Ellard, K. K. (2014). The nature, diagnosis, and
cess that I am describing about system evolution
treatment of neuroticism: Back to the future. Clinical
suggests that the term for it that fits best is “deter- Psychological Science, 2, 344–365.
ministic/indeterministic complexification” (or Bates, T. C., Lewis, G. J., & Weiss, A. (2013). Childhood
deterministic complexity, for short). socioeconomic status amplifies genetic effects on
adult intelligence. Psychological Science, 24,
That is, on the one hand, as systems evolve,
2111–2116.
they might express fully deterministic causal Belsky, J., & Pluess, M. (2009). The nature (and nurture?)
mechanisms. However, on the other hand, as they of plasticity in early human development. Perspectives
evolve, they might develop aspects that are con- on Psychological Science, 4, 345–351.
Benke, K. S., Nivard, M. G., Velders, F. P., Walters, R. K.,
sistent with indeterminism, at least in part, as
Pappa, I., Scheet, P. A., et al. (2014). A genome-wide
might happen with emergence. Moreover, the association meta-analysis of preschool internalizing
deterministic complexity might grow increas- problems. Journal of the American Academy of Child
ingly within the system such that it becomes pre- & Adolescent Psychiatry, 53, 667–676.
Bieling, P. J., Hawley, L. L., Bloch, R. T., Corcoran,
dominantly indeterministic, and also comes to
K. M., Levitan, R. D., Young, L. T., et al. (2012).
manifest higher-order enslavement of any deter- Treatment-specific changes in decentering following
ministic, lower-order levels to flexible, indeter- mindfulness-based cognitive therapy versus antide-
ministic higher-order ones. Thus, as systems pressant medication or placebo for prevention of
depressive relapse. Journal of Consulting and Clinical
evolve, previously powerful deterministic levels
Psychology, 80, 365–372.
might lose their deterministic attributes to ascen- Bjorklund, D. F. (2006). Mother knows best: Epigenetic
dant, in-process, ones that are higher-order, have inheritance, maternal effects, and the evolution of
indeterministic attributes, and co-opt lower-order human intelligence. Developmental Review, 26,
213–242.
deterministic mechanisms. Therefore, nondeter-
Bjorklund, D. F., & Ellis, B. J. (2014). Children, child-
ministic influences might dominate in a system, hood, and development in evolutionary perspective.
and the intricate combination and dance of Developmental Review, 34, 225–264.
References 299

Bjorklund, D. F., & Pellegrini, A. D. (2002). The origins The role of genes and environments in youth develop-
of human nature: Evolutionary developmental psy- ment (pp. 195–225). New York: Oxford University
chology. Washington, DC: American Psychological Press.
Association. Cole, S. W. (2014). Human social genomics. PLoS
Black, D. S., Cole, S. W., Irwin, M. R., Breen, E., St Cyr, Genetics, 10, e1004601. doi:10.1371/journal.
N. M., Nazarian, N., et al. (2012). Yogic medita- pgen.1004601.
tion reverses NF-kappaB and IRF-related transcrip- Cole, S. W., Arevalo, J., Takahashi, R., Sloan, E. K.,
tome dynamics in leukocytes of family demential Lutgendorf, S., Sood, A. K., et al. (2010).
caregivers in a randomized controlled trial. Computational identification of gene-social environ-
Psychoneuroendocrinology, 38, 348–355. ment interaction at the human IL6 locus. Proceedings
Bower, J. E., Greendale, G., Crosswell, A. D., Garet, D., of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, 107,
Sternlieb, B., Ganz, P. A., et al. (2014). Yoga 5681–5686.
reduces inflammatory signaling in fatigued breast can- Cole, S. W., Hawkley, L. C., Arevalo, J. M., Sung, C. Y.,
cer survivors: A randomized controlled trial. Rose, R. M., & Cacioppo, J. T. (2007). Social regula-
Psychoneuroendocrinology, 43, 20–29. tion of gene expression in human leukocytes. Genome
Boyce, W. T., & Ellis, B. J. (2005). Biological sensitivity Biology, 8, R189. doi:10.1186/gb-2007-8-9-r189.
to context: I. An evolutionary-developmental theory of Cole, S. W., Hawkley, L. C., Arevalo, J. M., & Cacioppo,
the origins and functions of stress reactivity. J. T. (2011). Transcript origin analysis identifies
Development and Psychopathology, 17, 271–301. antigen-presenting cells as primary targets of socially
Briley, D. A., & Tucker-Drob, E. M. (2014). Genetic and regulated gene expression in leukocytes. Proceedings
environmental continuity in personality development: of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, 108,
A meta-analysis. Psychological Bulletin, 140, 3080–3085.
1303–1331. Darwin, C. (1859). On origin of species: By means of
Buss, D. M. (1995). Evolutionary psychology: A new natural selection, on the preservation of favored races
paradigm for psychological science. Psychological in the struggle for life. London: John Murray.
Inquiry, 6, 1–30. Deary, I. J. (2012). Intelligence. Annual Review of
Buss, D. M. (2004). Evolutionary psychology: The new Psychology, 63, 453–482.
science of the mind. New York: Allyn & Bacon. Eccleston, M. (2011). In utero exposure to maternal
Caporael, L. R. (2001). Evolutionary psychology: Toward stress: Effects of the September 11th terrorist attacks
a unifying theory and a hybrid science. Annual Review in New York City on birth and early schooling out-
of Psychology, 52, 607–628. comes. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Caspi, A., Houts, R. M., Belsky, D. W., Goldman-Mellor, Ellis, B. J., Shirtcliff, E. A., Boyce, W. T., Deardorff, J., &
S. J., Harrington, H.-L., Israel, S., et al. (2014). The p Essex, M. J. (2011). Quality of early family relation-
factor: One general psychopathology factor in the ships and the timing and tempo of puberty: Effects
structure of psychiatric disorders? Clinical depend on biological sensitivity to context.
Psychological Science, 2, 119–137. Development and Psychopathology, 23, 85–99.
Causey, K., Gardiner, A., & Bjorklund, D. F. (2008). Epel, E. S., Puterman, E., Lin, J., Blackburn, E., Lazaro,
Evolutionary developmental psychology and the role A., & Mendes, W. B. (2013). Wandering minds and
of plasticity in ontogeny and phylogeny. Psychological aging cells. Clinical Psychological Science, 1, 75–83.
Inquiry, 19, 27–30. Eysenck, H. J. (1947). Dimensions of personality. Oxford,
Chisholm, J. (1990). Life-history perspectives on human UK: Kegan Paul.
development. In G. Butterworth & P. Bryant (Eds.), Flynn, E. G., Laland, K. N., Kendal, R. L., & Kendal,
Causes of development: Interdisciplinary perspectives J. R. (2013). Developmental niche construction.
(pp. 238–258). Hertfordshire, UK: Harvester Developmental Science, 16, 296–313.
Wheatsheaf. Fragaszy, D. (2012). Community resources for learning:
Cohen, L., Cole, S. W., Sood, A. K., Prinsloo, S., How capuchin monkeys construct technical traditions.
Kirschbaum, C., Arevalo, J. M. G., et al. (2012). Biological Theory, 6, 231–240.
Depressive symptoms and cortisol rhythmicity predict Frankenhuis, W. E., Panchanathan, K., & Barrett, H. C.
survival in patients with renal cell carcinoma: Role of (2013). Bridging development systems theory and
inflammatory signaling. PLoS ONE, 7, e42324. evolutionary psychology using dynamic optimization.
doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0042324. Developmental Science, 16, 584–598.
Cole, S. W. (2009). Social regulation of human gene Geary, D. C., & Bjorklund, D. F. (2000). Evolutionary
expression. Current Directions in Psychological developmental psychology. Child Development, 71,
Science, 18, 132–137. 57–65.
Cole, S. W. (2010). Elevating the perspective on human Gergely, G., & Csibra, G. (2013). Natural pedagogy. In
stress genomics. Psychoneuroendocrinology, 35, M. R. Banaji & S. A. Gelman (Eds.), Navigating the
955–962. social world: What infants, children, and other species
Cole, S. W. (2011). Socioenvironmental effects on gene can teach us (social cognition and social neurosci-
expression. In K. S. Kendler, S. R. Jaffee, & D. Romer ence) (pp. 127–132). Oxford, UK: Oxford University
(Eds.), The dynamic genome and mental health: Press.
300 12 Nature and Nurture: Evolution and Complexities

Goldhaber, D. (2012). The nature-nurture debates: Kenrick, D. T., Maner, J. K., Butner, J., Li, N. P., Becker,
Bridging the gap. New York: Cambridge University D. V., & Schaller, M. (2002). Dynamical evolutionary
Press. psychology: Mapping the domains of the new interac-
Gottlieb, G. (2007). Probabilistic epigenesis. tionist paradigm. Personality and Social Psychology
Developmental Science, 10, 1–11. Review, 6, 347–356.
Haier, R. J., Karama, S., Leyba, L., & Jung, R. E. (2009). Kim, H. D., Shay, T., O’Shea, E. K., & Regev, A. (2009).
MRI assessment of cortical thickness and functional Transcriptional regulatory circuits: Predicting num-
activity changes in adolescent girls following three bers from alphabets. Science, 325, 429–432.
months of practice on a visual-spatial task. BMC Klironomos, F. D., Berg, J., & Collins, S. (2013). How
Research Notes, 2, 174. doi:10.1186/1756-0500-2-174. epigenetic mutations can affect genetic evolution:
Haken, H. (1983). Synergetics: An introduction: Model and mechanism. Bioessays, 35, 571–578.
Nonequilibrium phase transitions and self- Kovas, Y., Voronin, I., Kaydalov, A., Malykh, S. B., Dale,
organization in physics, chemistry, and biology (3rd P. S., & Plomin, R. (2013). Literacy and numeracy are
ed.). Berlin, Germany: Springer. more heritable than intelligence in primary school.
Hoelzer, G. A., Smith, E., & Pepper, J. W. (2006). On the Psychological Science, 24, 2048–2056.
logical relationship between natural selection and self- Laceulle, O. M., Vollebergh, W. A. M., & Ormel,
organization. Journal of Evolutionary Biology, 19, J. (2015). The structure of psychopathology in adoles-
1785–1794. cence: Replication of a general psychopathology fac-
Hogan, J. A. (1994). The concept of cause in the study of tor in the TRAILS study. Clinical Psychological
behavior. In J. A. Hogan & J. J. Bolhuis (Eds.), Causal Science, 3, 850–860.
mechanisms of behavioral development (pp. 3–15). Laland, K. (2014). On evolutionary causes and evolution-
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. ary processes. Behavioral Processes. http://dx.doi.
Hogan, J. A., & Bolhuis, J. J. (1994). Causal mechanisms org/10.1016/j.beproc.2014.05.008.
of behavioral development. Cambridge, UK: Laland, K. N., Sterelny, K., Odling-Smee, J., Hoppitt, W.,
Cambridge University Press. & Uller, T. (2011). Cause and effect in biology revis-
Irwin, M. R., Olmstead, R., Breen, E., Witarama, T., ited: Is Mayr’s proximate-ultimate dichotomy still
Carrillo, C., Sadeghi, N., et al. (2014). Tai chi reduces useful? Science, 334, 1512–1516.
cellular and genomic markers of inflammation in Lamm, E., & Jablonka, E. (2008). The nurture of nature:
breast cancer survivors with insomnia. Journal of the Hereditary plasticity in evolution. Philosophical
National Cancer Institute Monographs, 50, 295–301. Psychology, 21, 305–319.
Irwin, M. R., Wang, M., Campomayor, C. O., Collado- Lavretsky, H., Epel, E. S., Siddarth, P., Nazarian, N., Cyr,
Hidalgo, A., & Cole, S. (2006). Sleep deprivation and N. S., Khalsa, D. S., et al. (2013). A pilot study of
activation of morning levels of cellular and genomic yogic meditation for family dementia caregivers with
markers of inflammation. Archives of Internal depressive symptoms: Effects on mental health, cogni-
Medicine, 166, 1756–1762. tion, and telomerase activity. International Journal of
Jablonka, E., & Lamb, M. J. (2007). Précis of evolution in Geriatric Psychiatry, 28, 57–65.
four dimensions. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 30, Lewis, M. D. (2000). The promise of dynamic systems
353–392. approaches for an integrated account of human devel-
Jacobs, T. L., Epel, E. S., Lin, J., Blackburn, E. H., opment. Child Development, 71, 36–43.
Wolkowitz, O. M., Bridwell, D. A., et al. (2011). Lewis, M. D. (2005). Bridging emotion theory and neuro-
Intensive meditation training, immune cell biology through dynamic systems modeling.
telomerase activity, and psychological mediators. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 28, 169–245.
Psychoneuroendocrinology, 36, 664–681. Li, S.-C. (2003). Biocultural orchestration of development
Jaremka, L. M., Fagundes, C. P., Peng, J., Bennett, J. M., plasticity across levels: The interplay of biology and
Glaser, R., Malarkey, W. B., et al. (2013). Loneliness culture in shaping the mind and behavior across the
promotes inflammation during acute stress. life span. Psychological Bulletin, 129, 171–194.
Psychological Science, 24, 1089–1097. Li, S.-C. (2013). Lifespan development of neuromodula-
Kan, K.-J., Wicherts, J. M., Doland, C. V., & van der tion of adaptive control and motivation as an ontoge-
Maas, H. L. J. (2013). On the nature and nurture of netic mechanism for developmental niche construction.
intelligence and specific cognitive abilities: The more Developmental Science, 16, 317–319.
heritable, the more culture dependent. Psychological Lickliter, R., & Honeycutt, H. (2003). Developmental
Science, 24, 2420–2428. dynamics: Toward a biologically plausible evolution-
Karmiloff-Smith, A., Casey, B. J., Massand, E., Tomalski, ary psychology. Psychological Bulletin, 129, 819–835.
P., & Thomas, M. S. C. (2014). Environmental and Lukeš, J., Archibald, J. M., Keeling, P. J., Doolittle, W. F., &
genetic influences on neurocognitive development: Gray, M. W. (2011). How a neutral evolutionary ratchet
The importance of multiple methodologies and time- can build cellular complexity. IUBMB Life, 63, 528–537.
dependent intervention. Clinical Psychological Manuck, S. B., Craig, A. E., Flory, J. D., Halder, I., &
Science, 2, 628–637. Ferrell, R. E. (2011). Reported early family environ-
Kauffman, S. (1993). The origins of order: Self- ment covaries with menarcheal age as a function of
organization and selection in evolution. New York: polymorphic variation in estrogen receptor-a.
Oxford University Press. Developmental and Psychopathology, 23, 69–83.
References 301

McShea, D. W., & Brandon, R. N. (2010). Biology’s first length. PLoS One, 5, e10837. doi:10.1371/journal.
law: The tendency for diversity and complexity to pone.0010837.
increase in evolutionary systems. Chicago, IL: Rice, F., Harold, G. T., Boivin, J., van den Bree, M., Hay,
University of Chicago Press. D. F., & Thapar, A. (2010). The links between prenatal
Mendizabal, I., Keller, T. E., Zeng, J., & Yi, S. V. (2014). stress and offspring development and psychopathol-
Epigenetics and evolution. Integrative and ogy: Disentangling environmental and inherited influ-
Comparative Biology, 54, 31–42. ences. Psychological Medicine, 40, 335–345.
Miller, G. E., Murphy, M. L. M., Cashman, R., Ma, R., Richerson, P., Baldini, R., Bell, A., Demps, K., Frost, K.,
Arevalo, J. M. G., Kobor, M. S., et al. (2014). Greater Hillis, V., et al. (2014). Cultural group selection plays
inflammatory activity and blunted glucocorticoid sig- an essential role in explaining human cooperation: A
naling in monocytes of chronically stressed caregiv- sketch of the evidence. Behavioral and Brain Sciences,
ers. Brain, Behavior, and Immunity, 41, 191–199. 28, 1–71.
Murphy, M. L. M., Slavich, G. M., Rohleder, N., & Miller, Sameroff, A. (2010). A unified theory of development: A
G. E. (2013). Targeted rejection triggers differential dialectic integration of nature and nurture. Child
pro- and anti-inflammatory gene expression in adoles- Development, 81, 6–22.
cents as a function of social status. Clinical Scott-Phillips, T. C., Dickins, T. E., & West, S. A. (2011).
Psychological Science, 1, 30–40. Evolutionary theory and the ultimate-proximate dis-
Nisbett, R. E., Aronson, J., Blair, C., Dickens, W., Flynn, tinction of the human behavioral sciences. Perspectives
J., Halpern, D. F., et al. (2012). Intelligence: New find- on Psychological Science, 6, 38–47.
ings and theoretical developments. American Shackelford, T. K., & Liddle, J. R. (2014). Understanding
Psychologist, 67, 130–159. the mind from an evolutionary perspective: An
O’Connor, M. F., Schultze-Florey, C. R., Irwin, M. R., overview of evolutionary psychology. Wiley
Arevalo, J. M., & Cole, S. W. (2014). Divergent gene Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science, 5,
expression responses to complicated grief and non- 247–260.
complicated grief. Brain, Behavior, and Immunity, 37, Sheldon, K. M. (2011). Consilience within the biopsycho-
78–83. social system. Psychological Inquiry, 22, 52–65.
O’Donovan, A., Sun, B., Cole, S., Rempel, H., Lenoci, Sheldon, K. M., Cheng, C., & Hilpert, J. (2011).
M., Pulliam, L., et al. (2011). Transcriptional control Understanding well-being and optimal functioning:
of monocyte gene expression in post-traumatic stress Applying the multilevel personality in context (MPIC)
disorder. Disease Markers, 30, 123–132. model. Psychological Inquiry, 22, 1–16.
Partridge, T., & Greenberg, G. (2010). Contemporary Skinner, M. K. (2011). Environmental epigenetic trans-
ideas in physics and biology in Gottlieb’s psychology. generational inheritance and somatic epigenetic
In K. E. Hood, C. T. Halpern, G. Greenberg, & mitotic stability. Epigenetics, 6, 838–842.
R. Lerner (Eds.), Handbook of developmental science, Skinner, M. K., Gurerrero-Bosagna, C., Haque, M. M.,
behavior, and genetics (pp. 166–202). Malden, MA: Nilsson, E. E., Koop, J. A. H., Knutie, S. A., et al.
Wiley Blackwell. (2014). Epigenetic and the evolution of Darwin’s
Ploeger, A. (2010). Evolutionary psychology as a finches. Genome Biology and Evolution, 6, 1972–1989.
metatheory for the social sciences. Integral Review, 6, Slavich, G. M., & Cole, S. W. (2013). The emerging field
164–174. of human social genomics. Clinical Psychological
Ploeger, A., Van Der Maas, H. J. L., & Raijmakers, M. E. Science, 1, 331–348.
J. (2008). Is evolutionary psychology a metatheory for Smith, L. B., & Thelen, E. (2003). Development as a
psychology? A discussion of four major issues in psy- dynamic system. Trends in Cognitive Science, 7,
chology from an evolutionary developmental perspec- 343–348.
tive. Psychological Inquiry, 19, 1–18. Sterelny, K. (2012). The evolved apprentice. Cambridge,
Plomin, R., & Deary, I. J. (2015). Genetics and intelli- MA: MIT Press.
gence differences: Five special findings. Molecular Sternberg, R. J. (2012). Intelligence. Wiley Interdisciplinary
Psychiatry, 20, 98–108. Reviews: Cognitive Science, 3, 501–511.
Prigogine, I., & Stengers, M. (1997). The end of certainty: Sternberg, R. J. (2014). The development of adaptive
Time, chaos, and the new laws of nature. New York: competence: Why cultural psychology is necessary
Free Press. and not just nice. Developmental Review, 34,
Protzko, J., Aronson, J., & Blair, C. (2013). How to make 208–224.
a young child smarter: Evidence from the database of Stochl, J., Khandaker, G. M., Lewis, G., Perez, J.,
raising intelligence. Perspectives on Psychological Goodyer, I. M., Zammit, S., et al. (2015). Mood, anxi-
Science, 8, 25–40. ety, and psychotic phenomena measure a common
Puterman, E., & Epel, E. (2012). An intricate dance: Life psychopathological factor. Psychological Medicine,
experience, multisystem resiliency, and rate of telo- 45, 1483–1493.
mere decline throughout the lifespan. Social and Tinbergen, N. (1963). On aims and methods in ethology.
Personality Psychology Compass, 6, 807–825. Zeitschrift für Tierpsychologie, 20, 410–433.
Puterman, E., Lin, J., Blackburn, E., O’Donovan, A., Trahan, L. H., Stuebing, K. K., Fletcher, J. M., & Hiscock,
Adler, N., & Epel, E. (2010). The power of exercise: M. (2014). The Flynn effect: A meta-analysis.
Buffering the effect of chronic stress on telomere Psychological Bulletin, 140, 1332–1360.
302 12 Nature and Nurture: Evolution and Complexities

Tucker-Drob, E. M., & Briley, D. A. (2014). Continuity of Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological
genetic and environmental influences on cognition Sciences, 363, 3563–3575.
across the life span: A meta-analysis of longitudinal Witherington, D. C. (2007). The dynamic systems
twin and adoption studies. Psychological Bulletin, approach as metatheory for developmental psychol-
140, 949–979. ogy. Human Development, 50, 127–153.
Vukasović, T., & Bratko, D. (2015). Heritability of per- Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feigning, and response
sonality: A meta-analysis of behavioral genetic stud- bias in psychiatric/ psychological injury: Implications
ies. Psychological Bulletin, 141, 769–785. for practice and court. Dordrecht, Netherlands:
West-Eberhard, M. J. (2003). Developmental plasticity Springer Science + Business Media.
and evolution. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Zimmer, C. (2013). The surprising origins of life’s com-
Press. plexity: Scientists are exploring how organisms can
Wheeler, M., & Clark, A. (2008). Culture, embodiment evolve elaborate structures without Darwinian selec-
and genes: Unravelling the triple helix. Philosophical tion. Scientific American, 84–89.
Part III
Normal and Abnormal Development
and Free Will: Normal Development
and Free Will
Differential Susceptibility: Orchids,
Dandelions, and the Flowering 13
of Developmental Psychology

metaphor of the orchid implies, or shrivel without


Chapter Introduction the right support.
The biological sensitivity to context one is a
Differential susceptibility and related models of very similar model to the differential susceptibil-
development constitute the most integrative and ity one. The adaptive calibration model is a vari-
important new frameworks in psychology, com- ant of the differential susceptibility model. These
bining developmental, genetic, and evolutionary models contrast with more linear models, such as
models that have led to impressive empirical the diathesis-stress one and the allostatic load
research. They argue that certain allelic varia- one, in which vulnerabilities accumulate, whether
tions in certain adverse contexts might lead to biological or environmental, and the outcome is
negative outcomes, as in Gene × Environment uniquely negative.
(G × E) interaction, but that the genes involved These differential susceptibility and related
are not only vulnerability ones because, in sup- models include a component of environmental
portive rather than in adverse environments, the monitoring and forecast. Also, they are associ-
outcomes might be more positive than the norm. ated with life history theory. The phenotypic
The G × E interaction involved leads to positive variability that they describe fits an evolutionary
outcomes more than is the case for related allelic– adaptive, or fitness, approach to understanding
environmental interactions, i.e., ones involving development. The proponents of differential
related alleles without the susceptibility factor. sensitivity/biological sensitivity to context have
These latter alleles do not lead to the range of undertaken research in support of its predictions.
positive and negative outcomes depending on the The approach carries implications for under-
nature of the environment involved; that is, no standing development, psychopathology, and
matter what the extremes are in terms of envi- even education (e.g., more resources for those
ronmental quality or environmental interactions with more environmentally-sensitive allelic
with the allele at issue, one does not find the variations).
extremes in adverse or adaptive outcomes, e.g.,
more antisocial behavior than otherwise should
occur, or less, respectively. The differential sus- Differential Susceptibility
ceptibility model has been referred to as the dan-
delion/orchid hypothesis because those without Aside from its general advantages for the
the susceptibility allele involved will do well study of psychological science, evolutionary psy-
enough no matter what is the context, while those chology has been applied to particular psycho-
with the allele might flower quite well, as the logical domains. For example, it emphasizes that

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 305


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_13
306 13 Differential Susceptibility: Orchids, Dandelions, and the Flowering of Developmental Psychology

developmental adaptations evolved for their differences in the susceptibility, mediated


ability to solve adaptive problems in the periods neurobiologically. (f) The individual differences
to which they apply (Bjorklund & Pellegrini, are evolutionary adaptive, with the susceptibilities
2002; Buss, 2011; Ellis & Bjorklund, 2012). The having had positive fitness payoffs in evolution.
following reviews are the most powerful of (g) Neurobiological-based differential suscepti-
evolutionary-developmental models. bilities to the environment constitute regulatory
mechanisms of alternate adaptive patterns of
human development. To expand this characteristic
Model of the model, even the greater susceptibility to
putatively negative outcome in negative environ-
Introduction The model of differential suscepti- ments could be evolutionary advantageous (sur-
bility to the environment is an evolutionary one vival-wise/reproductively).
that applies to neurodevelopment and psychopa- Ellis et al. (2011) contrasted their susceptibil-
thology, including in risk behavior. It developed ity model to the diathesis-stress/dual risk one of
out of two research streams [(a) Boyce et al., vulnerability, of which G × E interactions is an
1995; Boyce & Ellis, 2005; Ellis, Essex, & Boyce, example. In this latter approach to vulnerability, a
2005; Belsky, 1997a, 1997b, 2005; (b) Belsky, synergy between vulnerability genes and envi-
Bakermans-Branenburg, & van IJzendoorn, 2007] ronmental stressors leads to psychopathology
that have been combined in the work of Ellis and or poor functioning. The genes involved might
Belsky and colleagues (Belsky, Schlomer, & Ellis, include ones such as serotonin-linked polymor-
2012; Ellis, Boyce, Belsky, Bakermans- phic region [the short allele in 5-HTTLPR (sero-
Kranenburg, & van Iizendoorn, 2011). tonin transporter gene)]. The vulnerability might
The Boyce–Ellis group proposed the biologi- be behavioral in nature (e.g., difficult tempera-
cal sensitivity to context theory (BSCT) and the ment) or physiological (e.g., endophenotypic-
Belsky group the differential susceptibility the- heightened biological reactivity to stress). Having
ory (DST). Together, the models suggest that less vulnerability means having more resilience.
some individuals express greater susceptibility or According to Ellis et al. (2011), the diathesis-
disproportionate vulnerability not only to nega- stress (and any related) model does not consider
tive environmental conditions that serve to pro- adequately low susceptibility, positive environ-
mote risk-taking behavior but also to positive ments, and favorable/positive developmental
environmental conditions that are development- enhancement (see Fig. 13.1).
enhancing. The combined model over the two According to Ellis et al. (2011), the notion that
streams indicates a neurobiological susceptibility evolution has selected the likelihood of positive
in some individuals relative to others in regulat- development to positive environments is consis-
ing environmental impacts on development, tent with the evolutionary perspective. The more
adaptation, and health. contentious component of their model from an
Ellis et al. (2011) presented seven defining fea- evolutionary standpoint is that negative environ-
tures of their model of individual differences in ments might provoke other survival-reproductive
differential susceptibility/vulnerability to the envi- strategies despite apparent disadvantaged, dis-
ronment. (a) Some individuals but not others turbed, or deleterious development and behavior.
exhibit the heightened environmental susceptibil- This latter behavioral outcome also is consistent
ity. (b) The sensitivity increases developmental with the evolutionary perspective, because no
receptivity that promotes sustained behavioral matter what might be our opinion of the behavior
changes. (c) The susceptibilities are genetically itself, it would have evolved through natural
underpinned and neurobiologically expressed. selection to function to direct or regulate devel-
(d) The genetic influence is polygenic in origin of opment and behavior that are fit or adapted to the
variation. The experience involved is developmen- negative environments encountered. For exam-
tal. (e) There are both inter- and intra-individual ple, Champagne et al. (2008) have shown, for
Differential Susceptibility 307

Positive In differential
“for better” susceptibility
model only

high susceptibility

developmental
enhancement
OUTCOME

low susceptibility
no developmental vulnerability

low susceptibility
no developmental enhancement

high susceptibility

In both
developmental differential
vulnerability susceptibility
and diathesis-
Negative stress models
“for worse”

Negative Positive

ENVIRONMENT

Fig. 13.1 The diathesis-stress/dual risk model and the vulnerability. In the differential susceptibility model,
differential susceptibility model. The differential suscep- more susceptible individuals in positive environments will
tibility and diathesis-stress models make equivalent pre- show more favorable outcomes (i.e., developmental
dictions for individuals expressing high susceptibility enhancement). To conclude, more susceptible individuals
developmental vulnerability. They differ for the context of are influenced by both negative and positive environments
high susceptibility/development enhancement (the “for relative to less susceptible individuals. They are not nec-
better” component of the expression “for better or essarily “vulnerable,” given the positive effects of sup-
for worse” that represents metaphorically the model). portive environments. Adapted from Ellis et al. (2011),
Generally, negative outcomes are experienced only by based on Bakermans-Kranenburg and van IJzendoorn
individuals displaying high susceptibility/developmental (2007)

rats, that low levels of maternal licking/grooming The conclusion offered by Ellis et al. (2011) to
(lower quality maternal care for a rat), altered this animal model is that, under the circumstances,
pups’ stress and physiology/brain morphology. the maternal care was not poor nor was the pup
The effects included higher pup corticosterone behavior evolutionarily maladaptive. Rather, the
levels, shorter length in dendritic branching, and reduced maternal care served to activate alternate
lower spine density in hippocampal neurons. behavioral adaptations in the pups that would fit
Nevertheless, the pups exhibited enhanced learn- the forecasting that the environment the pups
ing and memory processes in stressful condi- would encounter in the phase of their sexual
tions. Also, the physiological and brain changes maturity would be like that of the mother. The
involved mediated the effects of maternal behav- development and behavior produced in offspring
ior on survival- and reproduction-related behav- would make the best of a bad situation, in that the
ior in the offspring (e.g., accelerated pubertal resource-poor or otherwise stressful environment
development, increased sexual behavior and, of the mother would be associated with fitness
later, reduced parenting behavior). costs on average. The evolutionary mechanism
308 13 Differential Susceptibility: Orchids, Dandelions, and the Flowering of Developmental Psychology

Fig. 13.2 Proposed


curvilinear relationship High
between experiences of

Biological Sensitivity to Context


psychosocial support/
protection compared to
stress/adversity in early
environments and B
biological sensitivity to
context. The graph C
illustrates that extremes
in support and stress
have their effects in
contexts of biological D
sensitivity to context.
Adapted from Ellis et al.
(2011), based on Boyce A
and Ellis (2005) Low
High support/ High stress/
low stress low support
Early Psychosocial Support/
Protection vs. Stress/ Adversity

involved has been called “conditional adaptation” encountered and correlated parenting strategies.
(e.g., Boyce & Ellis, 2005), in that there are varia- Alternate adaptive strategies promote less flexi-
tions in evolutionary adaptation that are still func- bility in development for an offspring, but have
tional and competent even in stressful, dangerous, other advantages for the family involved.
and resource-poor environments. Ellis and Bjorklund (2012) also discussed the
topic of development of life history strategies.
Life History Ellis et al. (2011) proceeded to Among others, Chisholm (1999) had proposed
describe the similarities and differences in the life history theory based on fitness-related trad-
Boyce–Ellis and Belsky and colleagues’ appro- eoffs in behavioral “decisions” related to survival
aches to the question of differential susceptibility and reproduction. Life history strategies could
to the environment. Boyce and Ellis (2005; see follow slower life histories or faster ones, in
Fig. 13.2) modeled the relationship between bio- which rate of maturation, selection of mates,
logical susceptibility to context and degree of number of offspring, and parental investment
psychosocial support/protection against stress/ vary (e.g., Ellis, Figueredo, Brumbach, &
adversity. Only when there is a moderate amount Schlomer, 2009). Belsky et al.’s (1991) psycho-
of support/stress does one find low biological social acceleration theory applies especially to
sensitivity to context, or a buffering effect (curvi- risky adolescent behavior based on environmen-
linear relationship). tal stress (e.g., parental discord, single-parent
Belsky (1997a, 1997b, 2000, 2005) advanced family, low income), and it is consistent with
a model similar to that of Boyce and Ellis (2005), Chisholm’s (1999) life history model.
partly based on an earlier evolutionary model of Others have pointed out that adverse environ-
socialization that he developed with colleagues, ments might be extrinsic (external sources) or
that of psychosocial acceleration theory (Belsky, unpredictable (variable; Ellis et al., 2009). Two
Steinberg, & Draper, 1991). In this model, both studies have shown that the latter factor, in par-
conditional and alternative developmental strate- ticular, especially if experienced in the first 5
gies play a role. Conditional adaptive strategies years of life, through multiple-step pathways,
promote in development the ability to “thrive” in especially predicts faster life history strategies
a variety of niches, depending on environment that develop later on (Belsky et al., 2012;
Differential Susceptibility 309

Simpson, Griskevicius, Kuo, Sung, & Collins, Bakermans-Kranenburg and van IJzendoorn
2012). Other workers have added sexual selec- (2006) found that, in Dutch children, maternal
tion theory to the model. For example, if a teen- sensitivity at 10 months of age predicted more
ager is competitively advantaged relative to other than 2 years later the children’s mother-reported
peers for mating, riskier behavior is more proba- externalizing problems, but only for those chil-
ble (Dishion, Ha, & Véronneau, 2012; James, dren carrying a certain allele (7-repeat dopamine
Ellis, Schlomer, & Garber, 2012). receptor D4, DRD4-7R). The results followed a
Ellis et al. (2011) concluded their comparison differential susceptibility model for these
of differential environmental susceptibility and allele carriers—they displayed the most observed
other models of psychopathology in development externalizing behavior when their mothers were
by noting that, in their model, some individuals rated insensitive but the least in the case of the
are more prone to respond to positive and nega- mothers who were judged as highly sensitive.
tive life experiences and others less so, which is Other G × E results supportive of the differential
akin to having a greater or narrower reaction environmental susceptibility model were reported
range, respectively (e.g., Manuck, 2010). I made by Sheese, Voelker, Rothbart, and Posner (2007)
a similar point in Young (2011) about Belsky and and Mills-Koonce et al. (2007).
Pluess’s (2009a, 2009b) version of the DST Work continues on finding the endopheno-
model. typic variation underlying differential environ-
Also, Ellis et al. (2011) noted that making the mental susceptibility. Candidate genes include
best of a bad situation, which might be the way to not only DRD4 but also the short (s) alleles on the
characterize how differential environmental sus- 5-HTTLPR. These genes are involved in varia-
ceptibilities work in the case of adverse/corrosive/ tion in the dopaminergic and serotonergic brain
resource-poor environments, is not necessarily circuitry, respectively, which govern response
evolutionarily maladaptive in the sense of decreas- thresholds to reward and punishment. The allelic
ing fitness or survival/reproduction, despite the variations would influence attention, state regula-
costs in mental health elicited, as well. That is, tion, and orienting response, as well.
it promotes a faster life history strategy, that The mechanism that leads genes to express
although is associated with earlier and riskier sex- differential sensitivity to context needs explora-
ual activity leading to teenage pregnancy, it might tion. In this regard, epigenetic processes might
be the option that matches best extant negative lead to phenotypic changes in biobehavioral
environmental conditions and similar ones that reactivity to adversity via changes in glucocorti-
had been forecasted earlier in development lead- coid receptor gene expression (Weaver et al.,
ing to the behavior. 2004). These types of changes would alter the
reactivity of the stress-responsive hypothalamic–
Research Research is increasingly supporting pituitary–adrenal (HPA) axis. van IJzendoorn,
the differential environmental susceptibility model. Caspers, Bakermans-Kranenburg, Beach, and
Biological agents/processes have been found to Philibert (2010) found that higher levels of epi-
have bivalent effects that are context-contingent. genetic methylation of the 5-HTT polymorphism
For example, childhood obesity and insulin resis- were associated with trauma-resolution difficul-
tance appear more common at both ends of the ties in carriers of the allele 5-HTTLPR ll, which
spectrum of birth weight (Gluckman, Hanson, usually functions protectively, thereby altering
Cooper, & Thornburg, 2008), supporting Ellis’ the set point for traumatic stress reactivity.
curvilinear model of biological sensitivity to con- As for neural endophenotypes in context
text. The most intriguing supportive research for sensitivity, the two peripheral neuroendocrine
the models being discussed, though, relate to dif- stress response systems seem implicated—
ferential susceptibilities and related genetic sus- the corticotrophin-releasing hormone and the
ceptibilities, as predicted by Belsky’s model. locus coeruleus-norepinephrine (LC-NE) systems.
310 13 Differential Susceptibility: Orchids, Dandelions, and the Flowering of Developmental Psychology

When these systems are highly reactive, the offspring in certain experienced contexts, but not
individuals involved appear to experience either others. In BSCT, the) evolutionary model that
the worst or the best of developmental and health makes sense is conditional adaptation. Individual
outcomes, depending on the direction of organisms living in heterogeneous contexts need
adversity/support exposed to in the immediate to be able to monitor reliable cues related to
social context. For example, Obradović, Bush, survival and reproduction, both external (e.g.,
Stamperdahl, Adler, and Boyce (2010) studied 5- predation, resources) and internal (status, e.g.,
to 6-year-olds with high vs. low reactivity of the health, capacity to win agonistic mating-related
parasympathetic nervous system, which is modu- encounters).
lated by LC-NE )system activity. They found that The ability to match development to environ-
the high-reactive children growing up in height- mental conditions is fitness-adaptive. The fitness
ened environmental adversity were rated as less advantage of the predominant implemented phe-
prosocial. However, if they were growing up in notype in stable conditions and the alternate phe-
more favorable environments, they were rated as notype in unstable ones depends on successful
more prosocial. Moreover, children who were tracking of environmental conditions and predic-
highly cortisol-reactive, when compared to chil- tion of optimal phenotypic strategy to match
dren having low cortisol reactivity, were rated as them. Natural selection favors primary pheno-
more prosocial in growing up in low adversity types under favorable fitness conditions but pro-
contexts and less prosocial in growing up in high vides for secondary ones that, fitness-wise, make
adversity contexts. the best of bad fitness conditions.
As for behavioral phenotypes indicative of Ellis et al. (2011) noted that the BSCT) evolu-
differential environmental susceptibility, aside tionary model applies to ongoing environmental
from fast and slow life history strategies, the role adaptation both at the individual and population
of earlier-developing difficult vs. easy tempera- levels. Also, the mechanisms evolved in the
ment has been implicated, which seem reflective course of human history because of their fitness
of general emotional reactivity (e.g., Pluess & adaptiveness at each point in evolutionary time.
Belsky, 2009, 2010). For example, difficult chil- They noted that in modal (i.e., neither exces-
dren compared to easy temperamental ones sively dangerous nor supportive) environments,
exhibited more behavioral problems in the early whether present or past, heightened environmen-
school years if they had been exposed in infancy tal sensitivity does not promote fitness, and so
or in early childhood to low-quality child care, should not be selected. Also, for environmentally-
but they expressed fewer problems in the context susceptible individuals, when in adverse environ-
of high quality care (Pluess & Belsky, 2009). ments, there are not just fitness gains in adopting
According to Ellis et al. (2011), further secondary strategies, because there are fitness
research is needed to differentiate the causal ori- tradeoffs (e.g., various short-term and long-term
gins of differential susceptibility to the environ- costs, including in health). That is, there are
ment in terms of where it “resides” in the short-term reproductive gains in environments
spectrum of genomic, epigenomic, neural, neuro- that might not promote either long-term survival
endocrine, and behavioral mechanisms with (a situation that would short circuit any repro-
which it has been associated. They opted for a duction) or sufficient health to allow for
hierarchical model in which each of these levels reproduction.
is mechanistically related to the others below and In terms of the DST’s evolutionary approach,
above it in the complex system involved, it has much in common with the BSCT.) The
constituting “true mediating events” of sensitiv- critical concept in its approach is bet-hedging
ity to environment. rather than conditional adaptation. Whereas the
latter applies to flexibility in ongoing environ-
Fitness Ellis et al. (2011) next turned to the evo- mental cue reading and developmental in heter-
lutionary fitness advantages of having differen- ogenous environments, the former refers to
tial environmental susceptibility passed on to adaptively diverse optimal offspring phenotypes
Differential Susceptibility 311

in heterogeneous environmental conditions. to environment model. If environments are


If environments fluctuate unpredictably over predictable, the latter would be disadvantageous
evolutionary time, expressing differential sus- and, in contrast, producing more diverse, fixed
ceptibility to environment and its intergenera- phenotypes would be advantageous. These dif-
tional transmission is fitness adaptive. Diversity fering strategies apply to the familial context, and
derives from phenotype A being able to match act to increase or decrease phenotypic variability
environment A, phenotype B matching environ- in offspring depending on degree of early envi-
ment B, and so on, with intermediate jack-of-all- ronmental variations encountered. The authors
trade phenotypes also helpful fitness-wise. concluded that the degree of unpredictable envi-
There are fitness costs to the strategy (e.g., in ronments encountered within a generation alters
intergenerationally stable environments, having life history strategies, in order to “optimize”
the uniphenotypic strategy of propagating pheno- growth rates of lineages across generations.
types equivalent to A, assuming A is the one that Ellis et al. (2011) related high and low envi-
fits, would be superior in adaptivity compared to ronmental susceptibility genotypes to their
a diversity phenotypic strategy in which pheno- expressed phenotypes in terms of a flower meta-
type A is produced within a multiphenotypic set, phor—or as orchid and dandelion phenotypes,
in that some of the adaptive edge of the latter respectively. Orchids are phenotypes with an
variable-environment phenotype A would not associated high environmental susceptibility that
develop in the same fine-tuned way as stable- are better at changing niches when their preferred
environment uniphenotypic-based phenotype A). one becomes “overcrowded,” whereas dandeli-
That is, “spreading the risk” by increasing pheno- ons are phenotypes with an associated low envi-
typic variation among offspring might increase ronmental susceptibility and a more fixed
the probability of achieving some reproductive phenotype. Normally, both types of phenotypes
success in heterogenous environments in any one can co-exist in stable equilibrium.
generation, but such spreading of the risk is Moreover, it should be possible to show the
accompanied by the fitness cost of limiting adap- adaptive advantages of each type of phenotype in
tive success in stable, good conditions, although microenvironments. For example, Quas, Bauer,
the gain in shielding against total survival and and Boyce (2004) found that children expressing
reproductive failure in bad ones is a worthwhile high vs. low autonomic reactivity varied in their
fitness tradeoff. memory for a highly stressful event in ways con-
Research in evolutionary biology supports the sistent with the differential environment suscep-
contention that strongly fluctuating selection tibility model.
pressures can support variation of offspring phe-
notypes (in a process termed adaptive coin flip- Conclusion As an overall conclusion to their
ping), even when there is “monomorphic” genetic most stimulating work, Ellis et al. (2011) noted
structure. The process is apparently founded in a that susceptibility might translate best as a dimen-
“stochastic developmental switch” in which sional rather than categorical construct. Also, sus-
the probability of the phenotypic alternatives ceptibilities might differ at different developmental
involved corresponds to the forecast of the prob- periods for those with the relevant genotype.
ability of the corresponding environmental Finally, more research is needed on mechanism.
condition for the offspring made by the parent For example, orchid phenotypes in supportive
organism based on extant environmental cues. environments might differentially profit because
Ellis et al. (2011) noted that diversified bet- they better detect potentially positive opportuni-
hedging, or spreading the risk by producing a ties and learn to capitalize on them. As for onto-
diversity of “fixed” offspring, would be favored genetic origins of differential environmental
in highly unpredictable environments. Selection susceptibility, Ellis et al. (2011) noted that Pluess
should favor offspring with flexible phenotypic and Belsky (2011) reasoned that maternal stress
options, as in the differential susceptibility might lead to prenatal programming of a postnatal
312 13 Differential Susceptibility: Orchids, Dandelions, and the Flowering of Developmental Psychology

plasticity, but that there might be genetic bases sexual maturation (in rat studies; e.g., Cameron
(G × E interactions) involved in susceptibility to et al., 2005).
prenatal programming. Belsky, Ruttle, Boyce, Armstrong, and Essex
(2015) investigated sexual maturation and poor
health in females in relation to early adversity
Elaborations and elevated stress physiology. Path analysis
revealed that more exposure to prenatal stress
Belsky and Colleagues predicted not only more maternal depression and
qualitatively negative parenting in infancy, but
Belsky and Ellis have continued to publish on also elevated basal cortisol at the age of 4.5 years.
aspects of differential susceptibility. For exam- Moreover, the latter levels predicted accelerated
ple, Belsky (2012) referred to his earlier model of sexual development, which itself predicted
psychosocial acceleration, or fast tracking in 18-year-old physical and health problems.
development and reproduction. Ellis, Schlomer, Belsky and Pluess (2013a) elaborated their
Tilley, and Butler (2012) explored the dynamics model of differential susceptibility to environ-
in risk-taking in early sexual behavior. In the fol- mental influences (Belsky & Pluess, 2009a,
lowing, I examine the recent modeling by both 2009b), and contrasted it to similar models (Ellis
Belsky and Ellis and their colleagues. et al., 2011). To review, their model is evolution-
ary in focus. Under the influence of stressful
Acceleration Belsky (2012) described the psy- environments, development is not dysregulated
chosocial acceleration theory of human repro- but is directed toward evolutionary strategies that
ductive strategies. It is an evolutionary-influenced had been adaptive biologically in our ancestors.
model of life-history alternatives, in which both Granted, the direction might not be optimal for
alternatives “fit” in one or other of even in quite fitness compared to other strategies in more con-
different available environmental resources, ren- ducive environments, but it does “make the best
dering both evolutionarily adaptive, or promot- of a bad situation,” or mitigate to a degree reduc-
ing of reproductive “fitness.” Of the two tion in fitness.
alternatives in the model, the “fast” or earlier tra- Belsky and Pluess (2013a) noted that develop-
jectory one is riskier (e.g., teen pregnancy) and mental plasticity has become part of our pheno-
comes with costs compared to the other trajec- type, although with qualifications. Some
tory or “slow” one. However, despite the costs, individuals possess alleles that confer greater
the fast option still fits the context in which it is plasticity, while others are more resilient or cana-
promoted, for example, because of its different lized despite facing environmental variations.
type of preceding experience, differential Moreover, the plasticity might lead to negative
resources that had been available, and degree of outcomes more than expected or positive ones,
environmental uncertainty in the present. depending on whether there are susceptibility
alleles involved that bring with them this
In terms of mechanisms of influence, Belsky increased range of reaction.
(2012) indicated that the effect on the child early In contrast to the workings of a differential
in life of these various factors on attachment susceptibility process in development with its
security quality (secure, insecure) is a crucial negative and positive outcomes as possible, a
mediator. For example, insecure mother–infant diathesis-stress model argues that environmental
attachment at 15 months of age is associated with adversity leads especially to negative outcomes
early menarche (Belsky, Steinberg, Houts, in the presence of risk factors, including genetic
Halpern-Felsher, & The NICHD Early Child ones. I would add that the diathesis-stress model
Care Research Network, 2010). At the physiolog- refers to diatheses as an accumulation of vulner-
ical level, epigenetic stamps related to rearing abilities biologically or environmentally and it
regulate gene expression, including for rate of refers to stress as an immediate trigger that brings
Elaborations 313

out the latent vulnerability into the open as a externalizing problem behavior and social skills
negative outcome. However, in the differential they asked whether the effects of daycare experi-
susceptibility model, not only the vulnerability is ence are genetically moderated by the polymor-
different than in the diatheses-stress model, so is phisms DRD4 dopamine receptor gene and the
the stress. That is, in the latter model it might be serotonin transporter gene 5-HTTLPR.
an immediate trigger that activates a latent, nearly They found differential genetic, outcome
active vulnerability, but in the former model the measure, and age effects. In particular, the DRD4
stress is a cumulative and longer term one that polymorphism, but not 5-HTTLPR, moderated
indicates an ongoing presence of a resource-poor the effect of child-care quality (but not quantity/
(dangerous, unpredictable, etc.) environment, or type) on caregiver-reported externalizing diffi-
at least the forecast of one with this profile. culties when the children were 54 months of age
Belsky (2012) referred to the research with and also in kindergarten and teacher-reported
polymorphisms that express differential suscepti- social skills in kindergarten and first grade. Only
bility, Belsky and Pluess (2009a, 2009b) had carriers of the 7-repeat allele of 5-HTTLPR were
shown that certain at-risk alleles could lead to found susceptible to quality of care effects.
quite positive outcomes in supportive environ- Analysis revealed the results for behavior
ments. Research since that review has shown problems fit the differential susceptibility model
the same results for the (a) 5-HTTLPR and but the ones for social skills fit the diathesis-
(b) DRD4 polymorphisms (e.g., respectively, (a) stress model. Not all results were consistent with
Kochanska, Kim, Barry, & Philibert, 2011; van the literature, e.g., for 5-HTTLPR.
IJzendoorn, Belsky, & Bakermans-Kranenburg, Pluess, Stevens, and Belsky (2013) noted that
2012, and (b) Knafo, Israel, & Ebstein, 2011; differential susceptibility and its phenotypic
Belsky & Pluess, 2013b). consequences appear to be a quantitative trait
influenced polygenically by plasticity alleles.
Genes Other research supports “plasticity gene” Depending on the amount involved, they set up a
status for: (c) brain-derived neurotrophic factor plasticity gradient that varies on a continuum.
gene (BDNF; e.g., Chen, Li, & McGue, 2012; For example, Sonuga-Barke et al. (2009) found
Gunnar et al., 2012); (d) oxytocin receptor gene that children with candidate susceptibility alleles
(OXTR; Johansson et al., 2012; Poulin, Holman, related to DAT1 and also to 5-HTTLPR were
& Buffone, 2012; Sturge-Apple, Davies, Martin, most susceptible to higher negative maternal
Cicchetti, & Hentges, 2012); (e) FICSO6 binding emotionality in their conduct disorder outcome.
protein S gene (Bevilacqua et al., 2012); and per- Belsky and Deaver (2011) found that adolescent
haps (f) catechol-O-methyl-transferase gene males measured for self-control were more sus-
(COMT; Laucht et al., 2012), (g) monoamine ceptible to quality of parenting the more they had
oxidase A gene (MAOA; Enoch, Steer, Newman, plasticity alleles related to 5-HTTLPR, MAOA,
Gibson, & Goldman, 2010; Wakschlag et al., DRD4, DRD2, and DAT1. Genetic plasticity in
2010); and (h) the neuronal acetylcholine recep- this area of differential environmental plasticity
tor subunit α-4 genotype (CHRNA4; Grazioplene, appears to be cumulative.
DeYoung, Rogosch, & Cicchetti, 2013). Work is
proceeding on combined or multiple (polygenetic) Environment Pluess et al. (2013) also addressed
plasticity genes (e.g., Brody, Chen, & Beach, the role of the environment, even prenatally, to
2013; Simons et al., 2012). This suggests the shape susceptibility factors. Maternal stress in
validity for a “system-level” genetic approach in pregnancy can lead to prenatal programming of
the area. altered physiological and behavioral responses to
Belsky and Pluess (2013b) investigated stress, with some fetuses possibly being more
whether genetic moderation took place in early susceptible to prenatal stress effects due to their
child-care effects on social behavior. In particu- genetic make-up (see Fig. 13.3). In this regard,
lar, with respect to parent- and teacher-rated Pluess, Belsky, and Neuman (2009) found that
314 13 Differential Susceptibility: Orchids, Dandelions, and the Flowering of Developmental Psychology

Susceptibility
Genotype Factor
1

Genes
x
Prenatal

Prenatal 2

Epigenetic Mechanisms
Environment

Programming
Physiology

x
Postnatal
Behavior
Postnatal 3
Programming

=GxE =ExE

Individual Variation/ Developmental Plasticity Changing/ Altering


Over Development Time

Fig. 13.3 Genes, environment, and differential suscepti- (3) postnatal environment also influences susceptibility
bility: a process model. The figure indicates that (1) the factors (nurture); also, these variables interact (G × E,
genetic contribution to general susceptibility is partially E × E; gene–environment interaction, environment–
mediated by susceptibility factors (nature); (2) the prena- environment interaction, respectively). Adapted from
tal environment influences susceptibility factors (nurture); Pluess et al. (2013)

children with the DRD4-7R were both the most (NR3C1), which itself predicted 3-month cortisol
and least likely to develop attention deficit/ stress reactivity levels.
hyperactive disorder (ADHD) compared to chil- Pluess et al. (2013) concluded that susceptibil-
dren carrying other alleles, depending on whether ity, plasticity, and related terms should be used
the mothers involved smoked cigarettes during instead of vulnerability, because differential sus-
pregnancy, or did not, respectively. Pluess et al. ceptibility models expound that susceptibilities
(2011) found that maternal anxiety in pregnancy might lead to not only riskier development in
predicted offspring negative emotionally at 6 nonsupportive environments but also to enhanced
months for infants with one or more copies of the development in supportive environments in cases
short allele (s) of 5-HTTLPR. In contrast, infants of carrying certain alleles. Also, resilience should
homozygous for the long allele (l) did not show be considered a general immunity to environ-
this outcome. Therefore, certain genotypes in mental influence in cases of carrying other alleles.
interaction with prenatal stress appear more sus- In that sense, resilience might be a disadvantage
ceptible to developing postnatal conditions. in supportive environments. Clearly, the work in
Pluess et al. (2013) integrated epigenetic the area of differential environmental susceptibil-
mechanisms in their interactive process model of ity has profound implications.
differential susceptibility and developmental
plasticity by referring to research by Oberlander Environmental Sensitivity Pluess (2015) deve-
et al. (2008). In that study, depressed maternal loped an integrated model of environmental sen-
mood in pregnancy predicted increased epigenetic sitivity that covers work not only on differential
methylation of the glucocorticoid receptor gene susceptibility (Belsky & Pluess, 2009a) and
Elaborations 315

Table 13.1 Individual differences in environmental option is to “grow up fast,” “live it while you
sensitivity vary with sensitivity genes and environmental can,” etc., which might translate into conduct dif-
quality
ficulties, illicit drug use, and teen pregnancy
Environmental Sensitivity (e.g., Belsky et al., 2012). From an evolutionary
quality gene Sensitivity type
standpoint, this risky-behavior phenotypic strat-
Supportive Present Vantage sensitivity
(can profit phenotype egy in adverse environments might be an optimal
more than otherwise) tradeoff in terms of survival and reproduction,
Adverse Present Vulnerability (G × E; given the probability of a shorter lifespan and
diathesis-stress) uncertain future.
Neutral Absent General sensitivity Ellis and Bjorklund (2012) considered mal-
(to both negative and
positive influences)
adaptive developmental plasticity in light of their
Any Absent Low sensitivity
evolutionary stance. Natural selection has
favored developmental plasticity and, in turn, it
Adapted from Pluess (2015)
plays a critical role in evolution, being the
“creation force” behind evolutionary change.
biological sensitivity to context (Boyce & Ellis, Developmental plasticity allows for extended
2005) but also the model of sensory processing growth opportunities but, at the same time, is
sensitivity (Aron, 1996; Aron & Aron, 1997; constrained by genetically-influenced reaction
Aron, Aron, & Jagiellowicz, 2012). He noted that norms. Part of developmental plasticity as honed
individuals vary in environmental sensitivity, by evolution is that offspring as they develop
that is, in the way they perceive environmental have been selected for sensitivity to the environ-
features and process them (see Table 13.1). ment (some differentially so), allowing better
Variability in this regard might even reflect a adaptation in their environments when the envi-
higher-order personality dimension, which would ronments reflect ancestral ones, because more
be underwritten by neurobiological sensitivity, or likely than not the strategy is based on a reliable
neurosensitivity. High sensitivity in this aspect prediction and the strategy had been selected in
should characterize about 20–30 % of the our evolutionary past.
population. As reviewed by Ellis and Bjorklund (2012),
Frankenhuis and Del Giudice (2012) proposed
that developmental mechanisms might lead to
Ellis and Colleagues maladaptive outcomes in three ways: (a) risky
behavior that might be adaptively fit in some cir-
Risk-Taking Ellis, Schlomer et al. (2012) used cumstances could have negative outcomes for
a differential sibling exposure design to investi- some individuals; (b) environments could change
gate the role of fathers on risky sexual behavior in development, rendering previously positive
in daughters. They found that older and younger behaviors no longer adaptive; and (c) early devel-
sisters differed in the effects of quality of father- oping behaviors that developed due to accurate
ing on risky sexual behavior (RSB), especially in recognition of environmental cues no longer are
biologically-disrupted families with a large age matched to the environment because the cue rec-
gap between sister births (which maximizes ognition is no longer accurate. Gluckman and
differential father exposure to offspring). Low- Beedle (2012) added that a mismatch between
quality paternal investment appeared causally an individual and niche might derive because
related to RSB. Variations in the lower end of of environmental changes for an entire species
fathering quality affected RSB the most. Higher (species-wide environmental novelty) as opposed
quality fathering helped buffer against RSB. to individual developmental mismatch.

Ellis and Bjorklund (2012) further explored early Physiology Ellis and Bjorklund (2012) moved
risk-taking behavior. For example, in dangerous on to evaluate from a psychological perspective
or unpredictable environments, a phenotypic possible mechanisms involved in life history
316 13 Differential Susceptibility: Orchids, Dandelions, and the Flowering of Developmental Psychology

Care giving

Endocrine Neural Self-


Adversity reaction networking regulation
(hormones)

Genetics

Fig. 13.4 Model of the experiential canalization of self-regulation development. Both distal and proximal influences
participate in causal outcome. Adapted from Blair and Raver (2012)

strategy choice. Del Giudice, Ellis, and Shirtcliff that, at the same time, includes space for indi-
(2011) had developed a model of individual vidual differences. They considered their model a
differences in stress responsivity from an metatheory in which natural selection is seen to
evolutionary-developmental perspective that favor developmental plasticity and that what
linked stress-responsivity individual differences evolves are developmental systems, in which
to life history strategy individual differences. In genes are expressed differentially in different
this adaptive calibration model, an individual’s environments. Evolutionary models help under-
stress-responsive physiology is associated or stand individual differences in behavior and their
matched with local environmental conditions prediction. Moreover, they help explain the adap-
and, in the early years, danger and unpredictabil- tive value of more proximal mechanisms, such as
ity are the environmental cues to which develop- physiological ones, that undergird the develop-
ment of stress reactivity is keyed. Given these mental systems and individual differences
individual differences in baseline physiological involved.
activities depending on context, life history is Sturge-Apple et al. (2012) presented a compa-
primed toward different slower or faster life his- rable model to the differential susceptibility
tory strategies. In particular, low compared to model. As applied to temperament, Hawk-type
high family stress contributes to these differential individuals (e.g., approach, dominance, bold,
strategies (Del Giudice, Hinnant, Ellis, & aggressive, impulsive, risk-prone) raised in harsh
El-Sheikh, 2012). The work of Blair and Raver (maternal) discipline rearing conditions were
(2012) related stress-responsive physiology to found to have a basal physiological activity (e.g.,
reactive and reflective regulation and the prefron- heightened parasympathetic nervous system and
tal cortex (PFC; see Fig. 13.4). cortisol responsivity) primed for fight-flight
responses to adversity. In contrast, Dove-type
individuals (e.g., avoidance, inhibition, shy,
Conclusions unaggressive, risk adversive) had a basal physiol-
ogy that appeared to prepare for vigilance, orient-
Ellis and Bjorklund (2012) concluded that their ing, and inhibitory control. Over time, Hawks
developmental/evolutionary approach is an inter- developed more externalizing behavior and
active one that excludes genetic determinism and Doves more internalizing behavior.
Extensions 317

Extensions As the organism adjusts to reading present


environmental conditions, it is also predicting
Ellis and Del Giudice (2014) described further and preparing for future environments, given
their adaptive calibration model (ACM) of stress- that, in evolutionary history, encountered envi-
health relations. They contrasted it with the ronments generally are stable. However, this con-
allostatic load (AL) model. ACM (Del Giudice ditional adaptation might not predict well in
et al., 2011) describes a broad theory of individ- some contexts, leading to mismatch and malad-
ual differences in stress-related health outcomes aptation. The mismatch might be due either to
based on integration of life history theory (Belsky novel contemporary environments that differ
et al., 1991) and the AL model (McEwen & relative to past ones encountered in the evolution
Stellar, 1993). The ACM mode)l is embedded in of the species or due to the incorrect prediction of
the evolutionary perspective, in which adaptation future environments from contemporary cues
refers to the selective promoting of appropriate earlier in life. The stress response system serves
matches of phenotype to niche for purposes of as the physiological system that receives and
Darwinian survival and reproduction, rather than embeds the cues sensed earlier in life, and it
adaptation referring to the public health concept becomes altered in ways consonant with the cues
of “desirable” outcome. so sensed and also anticipated.
In ACM, )development programming takes In terms of set points and reactivity patterns,
place in the calibration of the stress response sys- and their recalibrations, the mediating role of the
tem to local environmental conditions. When the stress response system in “coordinating” devel-
environment is adverse early, it promotes “fast”- opment of alternative fast or slow life history
track life history strategies (e.g., risky behavior, strategies is crucia)l in ACM. Ellis and Del
early reproduction; biological fitness tradeoffs) Giudice (2014) explained that heightened stress
compared to a more long-term “slow” life history responsivity in dangerous, unpredictable envi-
strategy facilitated in less aversive environments. ronments is quite adaptive in the circumstances
The AL model does not deal with long-term for purposes of Darwinian adaptation. The health
adaptive changes in biobehavioral systems, given costs of constant stress response system activa-
its focus on disease outcome, unlike the case for tion are counterbalanced in a tradeoff by an
the ACM. In ACM and related models, fast life improved detection management of possible dan-
histories are accompanied by short-term insta- ger. The fast-track, reproductive strategy that is
bilities and also by long-term disadvantages entailed optimally counterbalances long-term
relative to a slow approach, but they make the health risks in the dangerous, unpredictable envi-
best of a bad situation. ronment involved. Overreponse to potential dan-
Ellis and Del Giudice (2014) continued that ger might be costly but is necessary, and, as with
evolution favors adaptive phenotypic and devel- the analogy of smoke detectors, this behavioral
opmental plasticity in an Organism × Environment regime is not dysregulated or dysfunctional.
structured interaction. This type of interaction For example, in early life maltreatment, chil-
permits individuals to better keep track of dren demonstrate an enhanced capacity to detect,
their environments as they develop and to adjust to learn, and to remember relevant stimuli
commensurately their growing phenotypes (Frankenhuis & de Weerth, 2013). Similarly, the
(West-Ebehard, 2003). Therefore, in the evolu- behavioral problem that might result can be inter-
tionary-developmental approach, stressful rearing preted as adaptive in context (e.g., McCullough,
environments, no matter the degree and duration, Pedersen, Schroder, Tabak, & Carver, 2013).
serve to regulate physiological systems toward set Rickard, Frankenhuis, and Nettle (2014) mod-
points and patterns of reactivity that have adaptive ified the psychosocial acceleration or life history
functions (Ellis et al., 2011; Ellis, Del Giudice, model to include an internal state monitoring
et al., 2012). component. According to the model, in adverse
318 13 Differential Susceptibility: Orchids, Dandelions, and the Flowering of Developmental Psychology

environments, forecasting that the milieu will bet-hedging). The authors concluded that people
continue as negative leads to accelerated female raised in poor compared to wealthy backgrounds
maturation rate. However, Rickard et al. (2014) perceive adult mortality threat differentially
added that the mediating link might relate to according to perceived control and predictability.
monitoring of altered internal states associated Research on life history strategies is specify-
with increased risk of morbidity/mortality, rather ing its drivers and effects. Mittal and Griskevicius
than any external state, per se, involved in lead- (2014) related fast strategies in financially poor
ing to the noted accelerated maturation rate. populations to exposure to uncertainty and to
Belsky (2014) considered this addition to his lower sense of control over the environment in
model as complementary and in the “evo-devo” childhood. They did not find equivalent results of
framework to which he adheres. the effects of uncertainty/sense of control in indi-
viduals from wealthier environments. Among the
proxy measures of fast strategies were delay of
Life History Theory gratification/impulsivity and persistence. The
authors concluded the life history strategy mod-
Gibbons et al. (2012) undertook research that els have had a gap in describing adequate mecha-
combined the differential susceptibility model nisms that could account for the differential
and psychosocial acceleration theory. They stud- effects of fast and slow strategies, and the ones
ied longitudinally African American adolescents. postulated are plausible drivers in this regard.
They found that higher stress in environments Sherman, Figueredo, and Funder (2013) argued
(e.g., low parental investment, racial discrimina- that their data on personality differences in slow and
tion) increased the probability of adopting faster fast life history strategies do not implicate that the
life history strategies, with the opposite true former is more adaptive than the latter. Each style is
for lower stress contexts. However, the results adaptive to different environments, with positive
obtained only among study participants who car- and negative personality attributes evident in both.
ried more environmentally susceptible alleles. In particular, in their analysis of archival data and
See Fig. 13.5 for a good summary of slow and also observed behavior, the slow strategy was asso-
fast like history strategies (adapted from Ellis, ciated with being considerate, kind, hard-working,
Del Giudice et al., 2012). and reliable. However, also it was associated
Additional research on psychosocial accelera- with being socially awkward, insecure, and over-
tion theory tackled the concept that developing controlling. In contrast, the fast strategy was associ-
individuals in early childhood are differentially ated with talkativeness, social skill, dominance, and
responsive to environment type, and there might charm, aside from behavior that is unpredictable,
be genetic and sex differences involved as well hostile, manipulative, and impulsive.
as neurobiological indicators (Eisenberg et al., Sheskin, Chevallier, Lambert, and Baumard
2012; Sulik et al., 2012). (2014) used life history theory to explain the
White, Li, Griskevicius, Neuberg, and Kenrick apparent earlier emergence of social evaluation,
(2013) tested life-history strategy theory by which can be found in infants (e.g., Hamlin,
examining indices of mortality threat (related to Ullman, Tenenbaum, Goodman, & Barker, 2013)
perceived crime), childhood socioeconomic sta- and the apparent later emergence of moral moti-
tus (SES), and diversification (e.g., in crop plant- vation and behavior, which can be found in
ing preferences having different payoffs). For 3-year-olds. The former helps in responding to
those from low-SES backgrounds, mortality and obtaining appropriate secure caregiving,
threat augmented bet-hedging diversification while the latter helps in the transition to the wide
strategies (and a biomarker index of it, oxidative social world. The argument proposed indicates
stress); but for those from high-SES backgrounds, that, in life history theory, each developmental
the effect found was the opposite (diversification epoch can be analyzed for the adaptive advan-
reduction, putting eggs in one basket, decreased tages in an evolutionary sense of modal behavior.
Life History Theory 319

FASTER AREA SLOWER

Physiology
Faster Slower
Development Rates
Earlier Later
Puberty Onset
Faster Slower
Aging (Biological)

Mating Behavior
Earlier Later
Sexual debut
More Fewer
Sexual partners
Casual Pair bond
Relationships

Parenting Behavior
Earlier Later
Reproduction Age
Higher Fewer
Offspring Number
Lower Higher
Offspring Investment

Economic Behavior
Short Long
Time horizon
Seek Delay
Immediate gratification
Take Avoid
Risk losses for big gains
Fig. 13.5 Faster versus slower life history strategies. accelerates, mating takes place earlier, parenting is vari-
Like history theory depicts faster and slower life course able, and the psychology of economics is more immediate
trajectories, depending of resources and their forecast. and riskier. Adapted from Ellis, Del Giudice et al. (2012)
In the faster relative to the slower mode, physiology

In a G × E (Gene × Environment) study, Beach the short allele (that has 12 copies of the long
et al. (2014) investigated the association of the variant compared to 14 of a 22 base pair repeat
promoter region of the 5-HTTLPR (solute carrier element for the long allele) in the promoter region
family C6, member 4 [SLC6A4] linked polymor- of the serotonin transporter genotype was found
phic region) with epigenetic susceptibility/ to moderate the negative effect of early SES
vulnerability in socioeconomically at-risk African adversity on epigenetic methylated change in the
American youth (age 19). In the sample studied, CpG sites involved in the depression pathway.
320 13 Differential Susceptibility: Orchids, Dandelions, and the Flowering of Developmental Psychology

The results supported a differential susceptibility a test of autonomic nervous system (ANS) stress
(Belsky & Pluess, 2009a), for better/for worse reactivity. A goal of the study was to determine
pattern, compared to a diathesis (for “worse”) the underlying mechanisms in differential sus-
one of the effects of the allele involved. ceptibility—if a genomic allele confers suscepti-
Del Giudice (2014a, 2014b) applied life his- bility in a better or worse fashion (G × E
tory evolutionary theory to psychopathology. interaction), depending on the quality of the envi-
There are fast and slow life history strategies that ronment—what is the relatively immediate effect
have been postulated, and they seem associated physiologically of the allele involved that can
with “fast” spectrum and “slow” spectrum effect, in turn, the behavioral differences found?
psychopathology. In supportive environments, In the study, the adolescents (N = 113) were
risk-aversive, slow strategies are favored (e.g., 14.8 years of age. To measure early care giving,
pair-bonding). In this strategy, resources are allo- the study used the CECA interview (Childhood
cated in a way consistent with the forecast that a Experience of Care and Abuse; Bifulco, Brown, &
constructive environment (e.g., without physical Harris, 1994). To measure ANS reactivity, it used
abuse) will continue. Behavioral inhibition is the TSST (Trier Social Stress Test; Kudielka,
promoted, facilitating the slow strategies. How- Hellhammer, & Kirschbaum, 2007). The TSST
ever, fast life history strategies are promoted in involves recording ECG (electrocardiogram) and
environments that early on are unfavorable cardiac impedance in each of three 5-minute peri-
for slow strategies and associated resource ods involving speech—preparation, giving the
allocation. speech, and post-speech mental subtraction in front
The consequence of fast life history strategies of evaluators. Blood pressure also was recorded. In
is that they could lead to the development of dis- the TSST, the SNS (sympathetic nervous system)
orders such as schizophrenia, bipolar disorder, could activate either with increased cardiac output
borderline personality disorder, and depression (CO) and decreased vascular resistance (TPR;
with somatic symptoms. There are dangers for total peripheral vascular resistance) or with the
psychopathology when the slow life history strat- opposite (termed the challenge/approach or threat/
egy leads to too much inhibition, among other withdrawal responses, respectively).
vulnerabilities. The disorders that might arise in The short allele (s) of 5-HTTLPR is a poly-
this regard are autism and depression without morphism in the serotonin transporter gene pro-
somatic symptoms. Del Giudice (2014a, 2014b) moter. Compared to the long allele (l), it is
concluded that the fast–slow life style distinction associated with reduced serotonergic function
might be a better way to classify psychopathol- (having less serotonin transporter protein avail-
ogy in broad strokes than the internalizing–exter- able). The differential susceptibility model for
nalizing one. this polymorphism lies with having one or more
of the s alleles (ss/sl, vs. ll).
The confirmatory approach of Belsky, Pluess,
Recent Research and Widaman (2013) was used to test the differ-
ential susceptibility model vs. the diathesis-stress
Supportive Research model. It involved employing a reparameterized
regression model. Depending where the points on
5-HTTLPR Sumner, McLaughlin, Walsh, the regression lines for the gene groups cross on
Sheridan, and Koenen (2015) tested the differ- the care giving variable (X), the G × E interaction
ential susceptibility model compared to the would be disordinal or ordinal (supporting the
diathesis-stress model using a theory-driven con- differential susceptibility or diathesis-stress
firmatory approach. In a study of adolescents, model, respectively). In testing the strong version
they investigated whether the 5-HTTLPR geno- of the differential susceptibility model, the slope
type moderated the effect of self-reported early for X for ll carriers was constrained to zero. That
maternal care giving (e.g., critical, concerned) on is, in the strong version of the model, ll carriers
Recent Research 321

are not affected anywhere in the range in care depressive symptoms (but not fewest suicide
giving. In contrast, in the weak model, ll carriers attempts). Li et al. (2013) concluded that the
can be affected by care giving, but to a lesser s allele of 5-HTTLPR confers increased reactivity
extent than carriers with one or more s alleles. to family influences, whether positive or nega-
The results of the study supported the strong tive, in the development of depression in youth.
differential susceptibility model, in particular, This pattern fits the differential susceptibility
especially during the speech phase of the TSST. model.
That is ss/sl carriers having reported higher- South and Krueger (2013) found evidence in
quality early care manifested on the TSST support of the differential environment suscepti-
approach-type responsivity during the speech bility model in the relationship between marital
component. In contrast, low-quality care giving satisfaction and physical health. They studied
for these carriers was associated with withdrawal married twin pairs, and variation in self-reported
type responses. Individuals without the suscepti- health was greatest for marital satisfaction for
bility allele (ll) were not affected by care giving. both high and low levels (as measured by herita-
Sumner et al. (2015) concluded that ANS bility estimates). They implicated the 5-HTTLPR
reactivity might be a plausible intermediate phe- polymorphism as the genetic moderator that
notype between variation in 5-HTTLPR and indi- might be involved in the results.
vidual differences in behavior related to it, such
as depression. However, the cross-sectional, ret- DRD4 Berry, Deater-Deckard, McCartney,
rospective nature of the study precluded arriving Wang, and Petrill (2013) studied the interaction
at firm conclusions about causality. between the dopamine receptor DRD4 7-repeat
Li, Berk, and Lee (2013) researched G × E in polymorphism and early maternal sensitivity as
adolescent depression, finding a differential sus- predictors of pathways to the development of
ceptibility effect (Belsky & Pluess, 2009a). They inattention in middle childhood.
found that both negative and positive environ-
mental conditions can influence “susceptible” Berry et al. (2013) examined one polymor-
alleles of certain genes associated with problem- phism within the DRD4, a 48 base pair dopamine
atic behavior. Specifically, they examined longi- receptor gene (bp) variable number tandem
tudinally youth beginning between 12 and 20 repeat (VNTR) in region exon III, because it has
years of age in three waves (on average, at ages been associated with childhood attention difficul-
15, 16, and 22 years, respectively; N = 1030). ties. The 7-repeat variant is one of the major vari-
Indices of depression, suicidality, and family ants in this locus, and dopamine D4 receptors are
support were based on responses to self-report quite present in the prefrontal cortex, with the
questionnaires. 7-repeat marker apparently implicated in reduc-
In their study, Li et al. (2013) found that the ing D4 receptor expression in the brain region.
44-base pair polymorphism in the 5-HTTLPR The authors investigated the differential envi-
was associated with family support in influence ronmental susceptibility model in relation to the
on the outcome measures. Specifically, aside 7-repeat variant of the 48 bp VNTR polymor-
from main effects of family support (cohesion, phism in the above-mentioned DRD4 gene
communication, warmth), the study found a (Belsky & Pluess, 2009a; Boyce & Ellis, 2005).
G × E interaction effect for boys involving the Specifically, they posited that adversity in context
short (s) (vs. long, l) allele of 5-HTTLPR. Having (e.g., low-quality early child care) affects nega-
at least one short allele of the gene (in compari- tively attention-problem trajectories in children
son to boys with two l alleles), as well as having with the DRD4 7-repeat polymorphism; however,
poor family support, was associated in the boys the inverse obtains for high quality maternal care-
with more depressive symptoms and a greater giving for those with the DRD4 7-repeat. That is,
risk of suicide attempts. In contrast, high family over time, they will manifest better attention and
support in these gene carriers led to the fewest related skills. The time frames examined involved
322 13 Differential Susceptibility: Orchids, Dandelions, and the Flowering of Developmental Psychology

infancy and early childhood, and then the period reduced serotonin transporter expression and
from pre-kindergarten to grade 5. antisocial and related behavior, relative to the
Berry et al. (2013) examined longitudinal data long allele. For DRD4, the gene has a functional
gathered in an NICHD study of 711 children and polymorphism of a 48 base-pair unit that typi-
families (National Institute of Child Health and cally is grouped into a short (2–6 repeats) group
Human Development). The methods were com- and a long (7–9) one. In this case, the long allele
prehensive. Maternal sensitivity was rated during is the one that is at-risk, being associated with
mother–offspring interactions at 6, 15, 24, and 36 less efficient transcription and antisocial-related
months, and again at the pre-kindergarten and behavior. For both at-risk genes, the polymor-
grade 1, 3, and 5 levels. The observations involved phisms do not express direct effects on antisocial
a semi-structured play procedure adjusted to behavior because they interact with adverse envi-
developmental level, and a composite score was ronmental conditions (e.g., Barnes & Jacobs,
derived. As for inattention, both observational 2013). In their methods, Lei et al. (2014) con-
and questionnaire data were used to create com- structed a combined 5-HTTLPR/DRD4 allelic
posite scores (e.g., Teacher Report Form, TRF risk score.
items, Achenbach, 1991). Control variables Lei et al. (2014) hypothesized that not only
included those related to maternal prenatal smok- environmental diversity but also social support/
ing (estimated), maternal personality, and mater- network ties need to be considered in establish-
nal depression. ing the possible effects of at-risk alleles for
The results revealed the proposed cross-over antisocial-related behavior. They studied 397
effect, in that, in association with early insensi- female respondents in a study of neighborhood
tive maternal ratings, the DRD4 7-repeat poly- and family effects on health and development in
morphism was found to be associated with higher the African American population. For the result
levels of childhood inattention. In contrast, the critical to the present analysis, they found that the
association of sensitive care and the polymor- effects of neighborhood disadvantage and of
phism involved lower levels of inattention, social ties on antisocial behavior were moderated
although less clearly. The results are consistent by the alleles studied. In particular, the at-risk
with the model of differential susceptibility. As alleles were associated with higher rates of
for developmental changes, the degree of the antisocial behavior in adverse neighborhood cir-
absolute genetic effect shown increased with age, cumstances, but lower rates in advantaged neigh-
in that the developmental inattention trajectories borhoods, however, only if strong social ties
increasingly diverged, and in that early compared were present, too. The findings are consistent
to later maternal sensitivity proved partially with a differential susceptibility model of G × E
important for inattention development. interaction, although I would add that the effect
found is more like G × G × E × E, although not
5-HTTLPR & DRD4 For antisocial behavior, quite so. Susceptibility genes could lead to posi-
Lei, Simons, Edmond, Simons, and Cutrona tive outcomes compared to other genetic variants
(2014) found a complex relationship among in more positive/supportive environments, aside
environmental disadvantage, social network sup- from any findings related to them in adverse
port, and genetic variation in adult African environments (Ellis et al., 2011).
American women. The genetic moderators inclu-
ded the 5-HTT gene (5-HTTLPR) and the DRD4 COMT Sulik et al. (2015) studied the relation-
involved in the dopaminergic neurotransmitter ship between variants of COMT in relation to
system. To review, for 5-HTTLPR, the short parenting quality at 18 months of age and to later
allele (s) contains 14 repeats of a 20–22 base pair inhibitory and attention control (assessed at 42,
unit in the 5′ promoter region; the long (l) one 54, 72, and 84 months) as well as to internalizing
contains 16 repeats. In carriers, the short allele, symptoms (at 24, 30, 42, 48, and 54 months) in
relative to the long allele, is associated with 146 children (79 male). Of the three variants
Recent Research 323

studied, Val158Met [rs4680 = Val158Met] proved GABRA2 The GABRA2 gene codes for the
the most informative in explaining outcome vari- alpha-2 subunit of the receptor of the neurotrans-
ance. Each of the variants was involved in sig- mitter GABA-2A, and the receptors are expressed
nificant three-way interactions, with sex and primary in the amygdala and motor areas.
parenting, especially for inhibitory control and Therefore, allelic variants that allow for increased
for internalizing symptoms. [The other two vari- activity in these areas are associated with
ants were intron 1′ [rs737865] and 3′-untranslated increased emotional responsiveness/sensitivity to
region [rs165599]. COMT is involved in neu- context.
rotransmitter activity, and Val158Met is involved In a prospective study of externalizing behav-
in lower COMT efficiency.] The specific results ior trajectories, especially over ages 11–17,
are complex, but supported a differential suscep- Trucco, Villafuerte, Heitzeg, Burmeister, and
tibility model (Pluess & Belsky, 2013). For Zucker (2015) examined genetic variants of
example, Val158Met appeared associated with GABRA2 (rs279807, rs279826, rs279858) in
internalizing symptoms in conditions of lack of relation to parental knowledge of adolescents’
supportive parenting, but its association with (N = 504) peer group, their whereabouts, and
inhibitory control was apparent in conditions of their expectations about time spent outside the
supportive parenting. home (and the adolescents disclosure of this
The supportive research of differential sus- information to their parents). Externalizing
ceptibility compared to diathesis-stress modeling behavior was measured using the YSR (Youth
in G × E interactions shows that the effect works Self-Report; Achenbach & Rescorla, 2001). As
not only for internalizing-related behaviors in for the results of the study, those with the minor
children, but also for externalizing ones even for (G–G) genotype were affected by the parental
the same genetic polymorphism. In this regard, monitoring in a better or worse fashion, fitting
for COMT rs4680 and the Val158Met polymor- the differential susceptibility model, unlike those
phism, Hygen et al. (2015) showed that this who were A carriers. That is, adolescents with the
polymorphism reveals a G × E interaction effect GG genotype and at low parental knowledge/
for teacher-rated aggression that fits the differen- disclosure (monitoring) were more likely to
tial susceptibility model, when it is examined in belong to higher risk externalizing classes, but
conjunction with a history of serious life events, the opposite was found for GG adolescents at
as in their study of community-based children of high monitoring. Trucco et al. (2015) concluded
55 months of age. Specifically, regression analy- that the results do not support a diathesis-stress
ses showed no main effects for either the COMT model but the differential susceptibility one.
genotype or serious life events on the aggression
variable, but there was a significant interaction Multigenic Boyce and Kobor (2015) related the
effect of the former two variables on the outcome differential susceptibility effect to the working of
variable. That is, Val/Val homozygotes together epigenesis. In this regard, they referred to “indi-
with the children have experienced many serious vidual variation in epigenetic susceptibility.”
life events was a combination related to more Research is implicating genetic polymorphisms
aggression on the measure used compared to the as “sources” of differential susceptibility.
findings for other COMT polymorphisms. Also, Although the research cited by Boyce and
the polymorphism in conjunction with no history Kobor (2015) are not directly on epigenesis, the
of serious life events was associated with lower studies speak to the issues, for example, through
aggression scores compared to the findings for the early stressors in the life of the participants,
the other polymorphisms. In short, the authors which are known to induce epigenetic modifi-
noted that the differential susceptibility model is cations. In this regard, consider that Bush,
supported more so than a simple vulnerability Guendelman, Adler, and Boyce (2014) found that
model to negative life experiences for the COMT the BDNF Val66Met polymorphism is related to
genotype (Val/Val polymorphism) and its effects SES context, with Met-carriers expressing both
on childhood aggression. the highest and lowest cortisol levels, depending
324 13 Differential Susceptibility: Orchids, Dandelions, and the Flowering of Developmental Psychology

on SES level. Babineau et al. (2014) found that Uninhibited temperament served as the upstream
children having the s and 1G (an l allele variant behavioral mediation in the effect. The results
functioning like s) alleles of the gene 5-HTT in were more consistent with a diathesis-stress
conjunction with exposure to prenatal maternal model (Beauchaine & Gatzke-Kopp, 2012) rather
depression had more behavioral/cognitive dys- than a differential susceptibility one (Belsky &
regulation, in contrast to children without the Pluess, 2009a) in that the risk allele in conjunc-
exposure, who had more such regulatory capac- tion with lack of unresponsive maternal caregiv-
ity. Bogdan, Agrawal, Gaffrey, Tillman, and ing had no effect on the results.
Luby (2014) found a risk allele × stress exposure
interaction in a differential manner for depressive
symptoms in 3-year-old preschoolers. Children Conclusion
with the risk allele of 5-HTTLPR had either the
most or least depressive symptoms, depending Note that the diathesis-stress and differential
on the degree of exposure to stress. More directly susceptibility models might explain different
on the question, Beach et al. (2014) found the dif- vulnerabilities to psychopathology, or behavioral
ferential susceptibility pattern for cumulative disturbance, even in the same study (e.g.,
SES adversity in a sample of African American Hastings et al., 2014; Nederhof, Belsky, Ormel,
youth from working poor communities, for the & Oldehinkel, 2012). Moreover, the methodolo-
5-HTT s allele and for methylation of a group of gies needed to support one model relative to the
depression-related genes. other are becoming more rigorous (Bakermans-
Boyce and Kobor (2015) concluded that epi- Kranenburg & van IJzendoorn, 2015). Hastings
genetic chromatin modification by environmen- et al. (2014) concluded that multilevel models are
tal conditions, and the marks that they leave that needed to understand the complexity involved.
endure, serve as “actual” molecular mechanisms Bakermans-Kranenburg and van IJzendoorn
in promoting the differential susceptibility effect. (2015) indicated new paradigms are needed
Whether children are more resilient or suscep- (e.g., G × Ee; the e representing experimental
tible to factors such as early adversity might intervention).
depend not only on the presence of certain sus- van IJzendoorn and Bakermans-Kranenburg
ceptibility alleles (for good or for bad outcomes, (2015) conducted a meta-analysis of differential
depending) but also on the epigenetic modifica- susceptibility research involving randomized
tions to which they are susceptible. control trials (RCTs). They included studies in
the special issue on the topic (Belsky & van
IJzendoorn, 2015), only some of which are men-
Nonsupportive Research tioned individually in the following.
van IJzendoorn and Bakermans-Kranenburg
Not all research supports the differential suscep- (2015) referred to G × E studies involving RCTs
tibility. For example, in the development of pre- as Gene × Experimental Environment interaction
schooler disruptive problems, Davies, Cicchetti, studies (which I simplify to G × Eexp). They
and Hentges (2014) reported a G × E interaction referred to the model of differential susceptibility
involving a genetic composite of DAT1 suscepti- to the environment as the model of genetic dif-
bility alleles (rs27072, rs40184) and unrespon- ferential susceptibility. They noted the advan-
sive maternal caregiving. The two alleles are tages of RCTs in this type of study as helping in
single nucleotide polymorphisms (SNPs) located providing causal evidence.
on exon 15 (rs27072) and intron 14 (rs40184) van IJzendoorn and Bakermans-Kranenburg
locations of the 3′ UTR regions of the DAT1. (2015) found 22 studies with an accumulative N
DAT1 is involved in dopamine regulation espe- of 3257 that compared the effect size of the
cially in the mesolimbic reward circuit. The CC experimental manipulation (relative to controls)
genotype constitutes the susceptibility allele. involved. For participants carrying susceptibility
References 325

alleles (e.g., DRD4 7-repeat; short, s, variant of brain volumes, to which I refer because of its
5-HTT) compared to those without them (DRD4 lateralization findings (see the study for details—
4-repeat; 5-HTT long, l, respectively), they que- briefly it is consistent with neonatal hemispheric
ried whether the results differed according to specialization in the adult direction for emotional
ethnicity, type of intervention, e.g., nano vs. pro- function, aside from the differential susceptibility
grammatic, and behavioral outcome (e.g., exter- findings).
nalizing, internalizing). The authors noted that
limited number of studies in the area do not
exclude significant results being found later when Chapter Conclusions
the cumulative Ns involved as the research accu-
mulates permit more statistical power. The work in differential susceptibility and related
The results of the meta-analysis conducted by modeling is relatively new, yet it is gathering
van IJzendoorn and Bakermans-Kranenburg much influence and import in the field of devel-
(2015) on G × Eexp supported the genetic differ- opmental psychology and beyond. It is notable
ential susceptibility model in RCT research. The for its integration of developmental, evolution-
combined effect size of the interventions for the ary, physiological, and psychopathological
susceptibility genotypes was significant, but it mechanisms. As well, its emphasis of susceptible
was not for the nonsusceptible ones. This was alleles having multiple phenotypic outcomes
especially true for the dopamine-related genes depending on environment-related underpin-
(DRD4) and not the serotonin ones (5-HTT), and nings is powerful. It allows for optimal and
for programmatic (“macro”) trials. reduced risk in development in the presence
Generally, the results in the field appear to of supportive environments for certain critical
support a strong version of differential suscepti- alleles that otherwise are associated with nega-
bility (nonsusceptible genotype carriers are not tive developmental outcomes in nonsupportive or
affected by the environmental effect; in the weak adverse environments. The understanding of the
version of the model, individuals are affected dif- plasticity involved in the behavioral variability
ferentially). van IJzendoorn and Bakermans- described by developmental susceptibility and
Kranenburg (2015) concluded that the vantage related models, and the mechanisms underlying
sensitivity version of the differential susceptibil- them, augurs well for a more nuanced apprecia-
ity model is incomplete in that it only considers tion of individual differences in behavior and
the positive susceptibility component of the their developmental and evolutionary underpin-
effects found in the research. nings. These models help to bloom psychology in
Belsky and van IJzendoorn (2015) dealt with important directions, to follow up on the orchid-
the ethically difficult issue of whether the results dandelion metaphor that so well represents them
in the field indicate that interventions should be (dandelions can grow anywhere; orchids need
reserved only for those with susceptibility geno- supportive contexts).
types. They noted that nonsusceptible individuals
in any one study still might be susceptible to the
positive effects of other interventions. This sug- References
gests that differential susceptibility might be a
question of degree rather than kind or type. Achenbach, T. M. (1991). Integrative guide for the 1991
CBCL/4-18, YSR, and TRF profiles. Burlington, VT:
In the special series on G × Eexp, as examples, University of Vermont, Department of Psychiatry.
Brett et al. (2015) conducted a study on 5-HTT, Achenbach, T. M., & Rescorla, L. (2001). Manual for the
early care giving, and externalizing behavior at ASEBA school-age forms & profiles. Burlington, VT:
54 months, and Brody, Yu, and Beach (2015) con- University of Vermont, Research Center for Children,
Youth, & Families.
ducted one on DRD4, family risk, and drug use in Aron, E. N. (1996). The highly sensitive person: How to
adolescents. Chen et al. (2015) conducted a study thrive when the world overwhelms you. New York:
with BDNF, maternal anxiety, and neonatal Broadway Books (Rev. ed).
326 13 Differential Susceptibility: Orchids, Dandelions, and the Flowering of Developmental Psychology

Aron, E. N., & Aron, A. (1997). Sensory-processing Belsky, J. (2005). Differential susceptibility to rearing
sensitivity and its relation to introversion and emo- influences: An evolutionary hypothesis and some evi-
tionality. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, dence. In B. Ellis & D. Bjorklund (Eds.), Origins of
73, 345–368. the social mind: Evolutionary psychology and child
Aron, E. N., Aron, A., & Jagiellowicz, J. (2012). Sensory development (pp. 139–163). New York: Guilford
processing sensitivity: A review in the light of the evo- Press.
lution of biological responsivity. Personality and Belsky, J. (2012). The development of human reproductive
Social Psychology Review, 16, 262–282. strategies: Progress and prospects. Current Directions
Babineau, V., Gordon Green, C., Jolicoeur-Marineau, A., in Psychological Science, 21, 310–316.
Minde, K., Sassi, R., St-André, M., et al. (2014). Belsky, J. (2014). Toward an evo-devo theory of reproduc-
Prenatal depression and 5-HTTLPR interact to predict tive strategy, health, and longevity: Commentary on
dysregulation from 3 to 36 months: A differential sus- Rickard et al. (2014). Perspectives on Psychological
ceptibility model. Journal of Child Psychology and Science, 9, 16–18.
Psychiatry, and Allied Disciplines, 56, 21–29. Belsky, J., Bakermans-Branenburg, M. J., & van
Bakermans-Kranenburg, M. J., & van IJzendoorn, M. H. IJzendoorn, M. H. (2007). For better and for worse:
(2006). Gene-environment interaction of the dopa- Differential susceptibility to environmental influences.
mine D4 receptor (DRD4) and observed maternal Current Directions in Psychological Science, 16,
insensitivity predicting externalizing behavior in 300–304.
preschoolers. Developmental Psychobiology, 48, Belsky, J., & Deaver, K. M. (2011). Cumulative-genetic plas-
406–409. ticity, parenting and adolescent self-regulation. Journal
Bakermans-Kranenburg, M., & van IJzendoorn, M. H. of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 52, 619–626.
(2007). Genetic vulnerability or differential suscepti- Belsky, J., & Pluess, M. (2009a). Beyond diathesis stress:
bility in child development: The case of attachment Differential susceptibility to environmental influ-
[Research review]. Journal of Child Psychology and ences. Psychological Bulletin, 135, 885–908.
Psychiatry, 48, 1160–1173. Belsky, J., & Pluess, M. (2009b). The nature (and nur-
Bakermans-Kranenburg, M. J., & van IJzendoorn, M. H. ture?) of plasticity in early human development.
(2015). The hidden efficacy of interventions: Gene × Perspectives on Psychological Science, 4, 345–351.
environment experiments from a differential suscepti- Belsky, J., & Pluess, M. (2013a). Beyond risk, resilience
bility perspective. Annual Review of Psychology, 66, and dysregulation: Phenotypic plasticity and human
381–409. development. Development and Psychopathology, 25,
Barnes, J. C., & Jacobs, B. A. (2013). Genetic risk for 1243–1261.
violent behavior and environmental exposure to disad- Belsky, J., & Pluess, M. (2013b). Genetic moderation of
vantage and violence crime: The case for gene- early child-care effects on social functioning across
environment interaction. Journal of Interpersonal childhood: A developmental analysis. Child Develop-
Violence, 18, 92–120. ment, 84, 1209–1225.
Beach, S. R. H., Brody, G. H., Lei, M. K., Kim, S., Belsky, J., Pluess, M., & Widaman, K. F. (2013). Confir-
Cui, J., & Philibert, R. A. (2014). Is serotonin trans- matory and competitive evaluation of alternative
porter genotype associated with epigenetic suscepti- gene-environment interaction hypotheses. Journal of
bility or vulnerability? Examination of the impact of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 54, 1135–1143.
socioeconomic status risk of African American youth. Belsky, J., Ruttle, P. L., Boyce, W. T., Armstrong, J. M., &
Development and Psychopathology, 26, 289–304. Essex, M. J. (2015). Early adversity, elevated stress
Beauchaine, T. P., & Gatzke-Kopp, L. M. (2012). Instan- physiology, accelerated sexual maturation, and poor
tiating the multiple levels of analysis perspective in health in females. Developmental Psychology, 51,
a program of study on externalizing behavior. 816–22. doi:10.1037/dev0000017.
Development and Psychopathology, 24, 1003–1018. Belsky, J., Schlomer, G. L., & Ellis, B. J. (2012). Beyond
Belsky, J. (1997a). Variation in susceptibility to rearing cumulative risk: Distinguishing harshness and unpre-
influences: An evolutionary argument. Psychological dictability as determinants of parenting and early
Inquiry, 8, 182–186. life history strategy. Developmental Psychology, 48,
Belsky, J. (1997b). Theory testing, effect-size evaluation, 662–673.
and differential susceptibility to rearing influence: The Belsky, J., Steinberg, L., & Draper, P. (1991). Childhood
case of mothering and attachment. Child Development, experience, interpersonal development, and reproduc-
68, 598–600. tive strategy: An evolutionary theory of socialization.
Belsky, J. (2000). Conditional and alternative reproduc- Child Development, 62, 647–670.
tive strategies: Individual differences in susceptibility Belsky, J., Steinberg, L., Houts, R. M., Halpern-Felsher,
to rearing experience. In J. Rodgers, D. Rowe, & B. L., & The NICHD Early Child Care Research
W. Miller (Eds.), Genetic influences on human fertility Network. (2010). The development of reproductive
and sexuality: Theoretical and empirical contributions strategy in females: Early maternal harshness →
from the biological and behavioral sciences (pp. 127– earlier menarche → increased sexual risk taking.
146). Boston: Kluwer. Developmental Psychology, 46, 120–128.
References 327

Belsky, J., & van IJzendoorn, M. H. (2015). What works Bush, N., Guendelman, M., Adler, N., & Boyce, W. T.
for whom? Genetic moderation of intervention effi- (2014, submitted). BDNF allelic variants moderate
cacy. Development and Psychopathology, 27, 1–6. social disparities in children’s basal cortisol
Berry, D., Deater-Deckard, K., McCartney, K., Wang, Z., expression.
& Petrill, S. A. (2013). Gene-environment interaction Buss, D. M. (2011). Evolutionary psychology: The new
between dopamine receptor D4 7-repeat polymorphism science of the mind (4th ed.). Boston: Allyn & Bacon.
and early maternal sensitivity predicts inattention Cameron, N. M., Champagne, F. A., Parent, C., Fish,
trajectories across middle childhood. Development and E. W., Ozaki-Kuroda, K., & Meaney, M. J. (2005).
Psychopathology, 25, 291–306. The programming of individual differences in defen-
Bevilacqua, L., Carli, V., Sarchiapone, M., George, D. K., sive responses and reproductive strategies in the rat
Goldman, D., Roy, A., et al. (2012). Interaction through variations in maternal care. Neuroscience and
between FKBP5 and childhood trauma and risk of Biobehavioral Reviews, 29, 843–865.
aggressive behavior. Archives of General Psychiatry, Champagne, D. L., Bagot, R. C., van Hasselt, F.,
69, 62–70. Ramakers, G., Meaney, M. J., de Kloet, E. R., et al.
Bifulco, A., Brown, G. W., & Harris, T. O. (1994). (2008). Maternal care and hippocampal plasticity:
Childhood Experiences of Care and Abuse (CECA): A Evidence for experience-dependent structural plastic-
retrospective interview measure. Journal of Child ity, altered synaptic functioning, and differential
Psychology and Psychiatry, 35, 1419–1435. responsiveness to glucocorticoids and stress. Journal
Bjorklund, D. F., & Pellegrini, A. D. (2002). The origins of Neuroscience, 28, 6037–6045.
of human nature: Evolutionary developmental psy- Chen, J., Li, X., & McGue, M. (2012). Interacting effect
chology. Washington, DC: American Psychological of BDNF Val66Met polymorphism and stressful life
Association. events on adolescent depression. Genes, Brain, and
Blair, C., & Raver, C. C. (2012). Individual development Behavior, 54, 1066–1073.
and evolution: Experiential canalization of self- Chen, L., Pan, H., Tuan, T. A., Teh, A. L., MacIsaac, J. L.,
regulation. Developmental Psychology, 48, 647–657. Mah, S. M., et al. (2015). Brain-derived neurotrophic
Bogdan, R., Agrawal, A., Gaffrey, M. S., Tillman, R., & factor (BDNF) Val66Met polymorphism influences
Luby, J. L. (2014). Serotonin transporter-linked poly- the association of the methylome with maternal anxi-
morphic region (5-HTTLPR) genotype and stressful ety and neonatal brain volumes. Development and
life events interact to predict preschool-onset Psychopathology, 27, 137–150.
depression: A replication and developmental exten- Chisholm, J. (1999). Death, hope, and sex: Steps to an
sion. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 55, evolutionary ecology of mind and morality. New York:
448–457. Cambridge University Press.
Boyce, W. T., Chesney, M., Alkon, A., Tschann, J. M., Davies, P. T., Cicchetti, D., & Hentges, R. F. (2014).
Adams, S., Chesterman, B., et al. (1995). Psycho- Maternal unresponsiveness and child disruptive prob-
biological reactivity to stress and childhood respira- lems: The interplay of uninhibited temperament and
tory illnesses: Results of two prospective studies. dopamine transporter genes. Child Development, 86,
Psychosomatic Medicine, 57, 411–422. 63–79.
Boyce, W. T., & Ellis, B. J. (2005). Biological sensitivity Del Giudice, M. (2014a). An evolutionary life history
to context: I. An evolutionary-developmental theory framework for psychopathology. Psychological
of the origins and functions of stress reactivity. Inquiry, 25, 261–300.
Development and Psychopathology, 17, 271–301. Del Giudice, M. (2014b). A tower unto heaven: Toward an
Boyce, W. T., & Kobor, M. S. (2015). Development and expanded framework for psychopathology. Psycho-
the epigenome: The “synapse” of gene-environment logical Inquiry, 25, 394–413.
interplay. Developmental Science, 18, 1–23. Del Giudice, M., Ellis, B. J., & Shirtcliff, E. A. (2011).
Brett, Z. H., Humphreys, K. L., Smyke, A. T., Gleason, The adaptive calibration model of stress responsi-
M. M., Nelson, C. A., Zeanah, C. H., et al. (2015). vity. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 35,
Serotonin transporter linked polymorphic region 1562–1592.
(5-HTTLPR) genotype moderates the longitudinal Del Giudice, M., Hinnant, J. B., Ellis, B. J., & El-Sheikh,
impact of early care giving on externalizing behavior. M. (2012). Adaptive patterns of stress responsivity: A
Development and Psychopathology, 27, 7–18. preliminary investigation. Developmental Psychology,
Brody, G. H., Chen, Y., & Beach, S. R. H. (2013). 48, 775–790.
Differential susceptibility to prevention: GABAergic, Dishion, T. J., Ha, T., & Véronneau, M.-H. (2012). An
dopaminergic and multilocus effects. Journal of Child ecological analysis of the effects of deviant peer clus-
Psychology and Psychiatry, 54, 863–871. tering on sexual promiscuity, problem behavior, and
Brody, G. H., Yu, T., & Beach, S. R. H. (2015). A differ- childbearing from early adolescence to adulthood:
ential susceptibility analysis reveals the “who and An enhancement of the life history framework.
how” about adolescents’ responses to preventive Developmental Psychology, 48, 703–717.
interventions: Tests of first- and second-generation Eisenberg, N., Sulik, M. J., Spinrad, T. L., Edwards, A.,
gene-intervention hypotheses. Development and Eggum, N. D., Liew, J., et al. (2012). Differential sus-
Psychopathology, 27, 37–49. ceptibility and the early development of aggression:
328 13 Differential Susceptibility: Orchids, Dandelions, and the Flowering of Developmental Psychology

Interactive effects of respiratory sinus arrhythmia and Gluckman, P. D., Hanson, M. A., Cooper, C., & Thornburg,
environmental quality. Developmental Psychology, 48, K. L. (2008). Effect of in utero and early-life condi-
755–768. tions on adult health and disease. New England
Ellis, B. J., & Bjorklund, D. F. (2012). Beyond mental Journal of Medicine, 359, 61–73.
health: An evolutionary analysis of develop under Grazioplene, R. G., DeYoung, C. G., Rogosch, F. A., &
risky and supportive environmental conditions: An Cicchetti, D. (2013). A novel differential susceptibility
introduction to the special section. Developmental gene: CHRNA4 and moderation of the effect of mal-
Psychology, 48, 591–597. treatment on child personality. Journal of Child
Ellis, B. J., Boyce, W. T., Belsky, J., Bakermans- Psychology and Psychiatry, 54, 872–880.
Kranenburg, M. J., & van Iizendoorn, M. H. (2011). Gunnar, M. R., Wenner, J. A., Thomas, K. M., Glatt, C. E.,
Differential susceptibility to the environment: An McKenna, M. C., & Clark, A. G. (2012). The brain-
evolutionary-neurodevelopmental theory. Develop- derived neurotrophic factor Val66Met polymorphism
ment and Psychopathology, 23, 7–28. moderates early deprivation effects on attention problems.
Ellis, B. J., & Del Giudice, M. (2014). Beyond allostatic Development and Psychopathology, 24, 1215–1223.
load: Rethinking the role of stress in regulating human Hamlin, J. K., Ullman, T., Tenenbaum, J., Goodman,
development. Development and Psychopathology, 26, N., & Barker, C. (2013). The mentalistic basis of core
1–20. social cognition: Experiments in preverbal infants and
Ellis, B. J., Del Giudice, M., Dishion, T. J., Figueredo, a computational model. Developmental Science, 16,
A. J., Gray, P., Griskevicius, V., et al. (2012). The evo- 209–226.
lutionary basis of risky adolescent behavior: Impli- Hastings, P. D., Helm, J., Mills, R. S. L., Serbin, L. A.,
cations for science, policy, and practice. Developmental Stack, D. M., & Schwartzman, A. E. (2014). Disposi-
Psychology, 48, 598–623. tional and environmental predictors of the develop-
Ellis, B. J., Essex, M. J., & Boyce, W. T. (2005). Biological ment of internalizing problems in childhood: Testing a
sensitivity to context: II. Empirical explorations of an multilevel model. Journal of Abnormal Child
evolutionary-developmental theory. Development and Psychology. doi:10.1007/s10802-014-9951-0.
Psychopathology, 17, 183–187. Hygen, B. W., Belsky, J., Stenseng, F., Lydersen, S.,
Ellis, B. J., Figueredo, A. J., Brumbach, B. H., & Guzey, I. C., & Wichstrøm, L. (2015). Child exposure
Schlomer, G. L. (2009). Fundamental dimensions of to serious life events, COMT, and aggression: Testing
environmental risk: The impact of harsh versus unpre- differential susceptibility theory. Developmental
dictable environments on the evolution and develop- Psychology. doi:10.1037/dev0000020.
ment of life history strategies. Human Nature, 20, James, J., Ellis, B. J., Schlomer, G. L., & Garber, J. (2012).
204–268. Sex-specific pathways to early puberty, sexual debut
Ellis, B. J., Schlomer, G. L., Tilley, E. H., & Butler, E. A. and sexual risk-taking: Tests of an integrated
(2012). Impact of fathers on risky sexual behavior in evolutionary-developmental model. Developmental
daughters: A genetically and environmentally con- Psychology, 48, 687–702.
trolled sibling study. Development and Psychopatho- Johansson, A., Bergman, H., Corander, J., Waldman,
logy, 24, 317–332. I. D., Karrani, N., Salo, B., et al. (2012). Alcohol and
Enoch, M. A., Steer, C. D., Newman, T. K., Gibson, N., & aggressive behavior in men – moderating effects of
Goldman, D. (2010). Early life stress, MAOA, and oxytocin receptor gene (OXTR) polymorphisms.
gene-environment interactions predict behavioral dis- Genes, Brain, and Behavior, 11, 214–221.
inhibition in children. Genes, Brain, and Behavior, 9, Knafo, A., Israel, S., & Ebstein, R. P. (2011). Heritability
65–74. of children’s prosocial behavior and differential sus-
Frankenhuis, W. E., & de Weerth, C. (2013). Does early- ceptibility to parenting by variation in the dopamine
life exposure to stress shape or impair cognition? receptor D4 gene. Development and Psychopathology,
Current Directions in Psychological Science, 22, 23, 53–67.
407–412. Kochanska, G., Kim, S., Barry, R. A., & Philibert, R. A.
Frankenhuis, W. E., & Del Giudice, M. (2012). When do (2011). Children’s genotypes interact with maternal
adaptive developmental mechanisms yield maladap- responsive care in predicting children’s competence:
tive outcomes? Developmental Psychology, 48, Diathesis-stress or differential susceptibility? Deve-
628–642. lopment Psychopathology, 23, 605–616.
Gibbons, F. X., Roberts, M. E., Gerrard, M., Li, Z., Beach, Kudielka, B. M., Hellhammer, D. H., & Kirschbaum, C.
S. R., Simons, R. L., et al. (2012). The impact of stress (2007). Ten years of research with the Trier Social Stress
on the life history strategies of African American ado- Test-Revised. In E. Harmon-Jones & P. Winkielman
lescents: Cognitions, genetic moderation, and the role (Eds.), Social neuroscience: Integrating biological
of discrimination. Developmental Psychology, 48, and psychological explanation of social behavior
643–646. (pp. 56–83). New York: Guilford Press.
Gluckman, P. D., & Beedle, A. S. (2012). Match fitness: Laucht, M., Blomeyer, D., Buchmann, A. F., Treulein, J.,
Development, evolution and behavior: Comment on Schmidt, M. H., Esser, G., et al. (2012). Catechol-O-
Frankenhuis and Del Giudice (2012). Developmental methyltransferase Val158Met genotype, parenting
Psychology, 48, 643–646. practices and adolescent alcohol use: Testing and dif-
References 329

ferential susceptibility hypothesis. Journal of Child Pluess, M., & Belsky, J. (2011). Prenatal programming of
Psychology and Psychiatry, 53, 351–359. postnatal plasticity? Development and Psychopa-
Lei, M.-K., Simons, R. L., Edmond, M. B., Simons, L. G., thology, 23, 29–38.
& Cutrona, C. E. (2014). The effect of neighborhood Pluess, M., & Belsky, J. (2013). Vantage sensitivity:
disadvantage, social ties, and genetic variation on the Individual differences in response to positive experi-
antisocial behavior of African American women: A ences. Psychological Bulletin, 139, 901–916.
multilevel analysis. Development and Psychopa- Pluess, M., Belsky, J., & Neuman, R. J. (2009). Prenatal
thology, 26, 1113–1128. smoking and attention-deficit/hyperactivity disorder:
Li, J. J., Berk, M. S., & Lee, S. S. (2013). Differential sus- DRD4-7R as a plasticity gene. Biological Psychiatry,
ceptibility in longitudinal models of gene-environment 66, e5–e6. doi:10.1016/j.biopsych.2009.04.019.
interaction for adolescent depression. Development Pluess, M., Stevens, S. E., & Belsky, J. (2013). Differential
and Psychopathology, 25, 991–1003. susceptibility: Developmental and evolutionary mech-
Manuck, S. B. (2010). The reaction norm in gene × anisms of gene-environment interactions. In M.
environment interaction. Molecular Psychiatry, 15, Legerstee, D. W. Haley, & M. H. Bornstein (Eds.), The
881–882. infant mind: Origins of the social brain (pp. 77–96).
McCullough, M. E., Pedersen, E. J., Schroder, J. M., New York: Guilford Press.
Tabak, B. A., & Carver, C. S. (2013). Harsh childhood Pluess, M., Velders, F. P., Belsky, J., van IJzendoorn,
environmental characteristics predict exploitation and M. H., Bakermans-Kranenburg, M. J., Jaddoe, V. W.,
retaliation in humans. Proceedings of the Royal et al. (2011). Serotonin transporter polymorphism
Society B: Biological Science, 280, 1750. doi:10.1098/ moderates effects of prenatal maternal anxiety on
rspb.2012.2104. infant negative emotionality. Biological Psychiatry,
McEwen, B. S., & Stellar, E. (1993). Stress and the indi- 69, 520–525.
vidual. Mechanisms leading to disease. Archives of Poulin, M. J., Holman, E. A., & Buffone, A. (2012).
Internal Medicine, 153, 2093–2101. The neurogenetics of nice: Receptor genes for oxytocin
Mills-Koonce, W. R., Propper, C. B., Gariepy, J. L., Blair, and vasopressin interact with threat to predict prosocial
C., Garrett-Peters, P., & Cox, M. J. (2007). Bidirec- behavior. Psychological Science, 23, 446–452.
tional genetic and environmental influences on mother Quas, J. A., Bauer, A., & Boyce, W. T. (2004). Physio-
and child behavior: The family system as the unit logical reactivity, social support, and memory in early
of analyses. Development and Psychopathology, 19, childhood. Child Development, 75, 797–814.
1073–1087. Rickard, I. J., Frankenhuis, W. E., & Nettle, D. (2014).
Mittal, C., & Griskevicius, V. (2014). Sense of control Why are childhood family factors associated with tim-
under uncertainty depends on people’s childhood ing of maturation? A role of internal prediction.
environment: A life history theory approach. Journal Perspectives on Psychological Science, 9, 3–15.
of Personality and Social Psychology, 107, 621–637. Sheese, B. E., Voelker, P. M., Rothbart, M. K., & Posner,
Nederhof, E., Belsky, J., Ormel, J., & Oldehinkel, A. J. M. I. (2007). Parenting quality interacts with genetic
(2012). Effects of divorce on Dutch boys’ and girls’ variation in dopamine receptor D4 to influence tem-
externalizing behavior in gene × environment perspec- perament in early childhood. Developmental
tive: Diathesis stress or differential susceptibility Psychopathology, 19, 1039–1046.
in the Tracking Adolescents’ Individual Lives Sherman, R. A., Figueredo, A. J., & Funder, D. C. (2013).
Survey study? Development and Psychopathology, 24, The behavioral correlates of overall and distinctive
929–939. life history strategy. Journal of Personality and Social
Oberlander, T. F., Weinberg, J., Papsdorf, M., Grunau, R., Psychology, 105, 873–888.
Misri, S., & Devlin, A. M. (2008). Prenatal exposure to Sheskin, M., Chevallier, C., Lambert, S., & Baumard, N.
maternal depression, neonatal methylation of human (2014). Life-history theory explains childhood
glucocorticoid receptor gene (NR3C1) and infant cor- moral development. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 18,
tisol stress responses. Epigenetics, 3, 97–106. 613–615.
Obradović, J., Bush, N. R., Stamperdahl, J., Adler, N. E., Simons, R. L., Lie, M. K., Stewart, E. A., Beach, S. R. H.,
& Boyce, W. T. (2010). Biological sensitivity to con- Brody, G. H., Philibert, R. A., et al. (2012). Social
text: The interactive effects of stress reactivity and adversity, genetic variation, street code, and aggres-
family adversity on socioemotional behavior and sion: A genetically informed model of violent behav-
school readiness. Child Development, 81, 270–289. ior. Youth Violence and Juvenile Justice, 10, 3–24.
Pluess, M. (2015). Individual differences in environmen- Simpson, J. A., Griskevicius, V., Kuo, S. I., Sung, S., &
tal sensitivity. Child Development Perspectives, 9, Collins, W. A. (2012). Evolution, stress, and sensitive
138–143. periods: The influence of unpredictability in early ver-
Pluess, M., & Belsky, J. (2009). Differential susceptibility sus late childhood on sex and risky behavior.
to rearing experience: The case of childcare. Journal Developmental Psychology, 48, 674–686.
of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 50, 396–404. Sonuga-Barke, E. J., Oades, R. D., Psychogiou, L., Chen,
Pluess, M., & Belsky, J. (2010). Differential susceptibility W., Franke, B., Buitelaar, J., et al. (2009). Dopamine
to parenting and quality child care. Developmental and serotonin transporter genotypes moderate sensi-
Psychology, 46, 376–390. tivity to maternal expressed emotion: The case of
330 13 Differential Susceptibility: Orchids, Dandelions, and the Flowering of Developmental Psychology

conduct and emotional problems in attention deficit/ allele. Development and Psychopathology.
hyperactivity disorder. Journal of Child Psychology doi:10.1017/S0954579415000255.
and Psychiatry, and Allied Disciplines, 50, van IJzendoorn, M. H., & Bakermans-Kranenburg, M. J.
1052–1063. (2015). Genetic differential susceptibility on trial:
South, S. C., & Krueger, R. F. (2013). Marital satisfaction Meta-analytic support from randomized controlled
and physical health: Evidence for an orchid effect. experiments. Development and Psychopathology, 27,
Psychological Science, 24, 373–378. 151–162.
Sturge-Apple, M. L., Davies, P. T., Martin, M. J., Cicchetti, van IJzendoorn, M. H., Belsky, J., & Bakermans-
D., & Hentges, R. F. (2012). An examination of Kranenburg, M. J. (2012). Serotonin transporter
the impact of harsh parenting contexts on children’s genotype 5HTTLPR as a marker of differential sus-
adaptation within an evolutionary framework. Deve- ceptibility? A meta-analysis of child and adolescent
lopmental Psychology, 48, 791–805. gene-by-environment studies. Translational Psychi-
Sulik, M. J., Eisenberg, N., Lemery-Chalfant, K., Spinrad, atry, 7, e147. doi:10.1038/tp.2012.73.
T. L., Silva, K. M., Eggum, N. D., et al. (2012). van IJzendoorn, M. H., Caspers, K., Bakermans-
Interactions between serotonin transporter gene haplo- Kranenburg, M. J., Beach, S. R. H., & Philibert, R.
types and quality of mothers’ parenting predict the (2010). Methylation matters: Interaction between meth-
development of children’s noncompliance. Develop- ylation density and 5HTT genotype predicts unresolved
mental Psychology, 48, 740–754. loss or trauma. Biological Psychiatry, 68, 405–407.
Sulik, M. J., Eisenberg, N., Spinrad, T. L., Lemery- Wakschlag, L. S., Kistner, E. O., Pine, D. S., Biesecker,
Chalfant, K., Swann, G., Silva, K. M., et al. (2015). G., Pickett, K. E., Skol, A. D., et al. (2010). Interaction
Interactions among catechol-O-methyltransferase of prenatal exposure to cigarettes and MAOA geno-
genotype, parenting, and sex predict children’s inter- type in pathways to youth antisocial behavior.
nalizing symptoms and inhibitory control: Evidence Molecular Psychiatry, 15, 928–937.
for differential susceptibility. Development and Weaver, I. C., Cervoni, N., Champagne, F. A., D’Alessio,
Psychopathology, 27, 709–723. A. C., Sharma, S., Seckl, J. R., et al. (2004). Epigenetic
Sumner, J. A., McLaughlin, K. A., Walsh, K., Sheridan, programming by maternal behavior. Nature Neuro-
M. A., & Koenen, K. C. (2015). Care giving and science, 7, 847–854.
5-HTTLPR genotype predict adolescent physiological West-Eberhard, M. J. (2003). Development plasticity and
stress reactivity: Confirmatory tests on gene × environ- evolution. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
ment interactions. Child Development. doi:10.1111/ White, A. E., Li, Y. J., Griskevicius, V., Neuberg, S. L., &
cdev.12357. Kenrick, D. T. (2013). Putting all your eggs in one bas-
Trucco, E. M., Villafuerte, S., Heitzeg, M. M., Burmeister, ket: Life-history strategies, bet hedging, and diversifi-
M., & Zucker, R. A. (2015). Susceptibility effects of cation. Psychological Science, 24, 715–722.
GABA receptor subunit alpha-2 (GABRA2) variants Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
and parental monitoring on externalizing behavior tra- Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science +
jectories: Risk and protection conveyed by the minor Business Media.
Early Adversity, Fetal
Programming, and Getting Under 14
the Skin

Concepts such as early adversity, allostatic load,


Chapter Introduction prenatal programming, and even preconceptual
and epigenetic influences speak to this model.
The present chapter examines models and Christian (2015) reviewed the research show-
research on early influences on development ing that maternal psychosocial stress during
especially in terms of environmental adversity. pregnancy has adverse behavioral and health out-
The models include the ones of differential sus- comes for offspring. The mediator in the relation-
ceptibility, adaptive calibration, and allostatic ship might involve dysregulation of inflammatory
load, which were considered in the prior chapter. processes in the mother. For example, Haeri,
However, the chapter also deals with models on: Baker, and Ruano (2013) compared depressed
enduring effects; stress generation; stress sensiti- pregnant mothers and controls. The former group
zation, amplification, and inoculation; and expressed alterations in immune parameters—
Gene × Environment effects. Major environmen- higher serum interleukin 6 (IL-6) and tumor
tal influences considered include early abuse, necrosis factor alpha (TNF-α).
attachment style, and socioeconomic status/pov- There are relevant differential factors in fetal
erty. Overall, the work described in the present programming of physiological stress reactivity.
chapter supports an interactive approach across Tibu et al. (2014) found that prenatal risks lead to
biology and environment in long-term develop- increased stress reactivity in female infants
ment, but in a process that includes nuanced but decreased reactivity in males. In this regard,
effects, such as relating to preconceptual influ- they examined vagal reactivity from respiratory
ences and epigenesis on the outcome of behavior. sinus arrhythmia during stressful and nonstress
I conclude that a biopsychosocial approach to procedures.
early adversity could be a fruitful one. Quas et al. (2014) examined classes of sympa-
thetic/parasympathetic and HPA (hypothalamic-
pituitary-adrenal) axis reactivity over four studies
Enduring Effects of 4- to 14-year-olds (to laboratory challenges).
They found six patterns by latent profile analysis:
Model moderate reactivity (most frequent); parasympa-
thetic reactivity (e.g., withdrawal); anticipatory
Experience early in life might be discounted as arousal; multisystem reactivity (exaggerated);
relevant environmental influences on later devel- HPA reactivity, and underarousal. The findings
opment. However, in the enduring effects model, suggest different avenues of fetal programming,
they are considered important in these regards. for example, due to maternal prenatal anxiety.

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 331


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_14
332 14 Early Adversity, Fetal Programming, and Getting Under the Skin

Early Influence
(e.g., maternal a b b b
sensitivity)

Developmental
1 2 3 4 (c)
Pathway
(e.g., social skill)

Fig. 14.1 Early influences and developing skills accord- are uncorrelated with the particular developmental experi-
ing to revisionist and enduring effects perspectives. A ence at issue. In addition to these assumptions, the endur-
focal developmental experience (e.g., maternal sensitiv- ing effects model also assumes that the focal experience
ity) might influence early outcomes (path a; such as social continues to have an ongoing effect on outcome over
skills). Also, the outcomes might have some degree of development (path b), unlike the revisionist model.
stability early in life over development (path c). In addi- Adapted from Roisman and Fraley (2013), based on
tion, the outcomes could be affected by experiences that Fraley et al. (2013)

Roisman and Fraley (2013; also Fraley, experiences. Much of the field could profit from
Roisman, & Haltigan, 2013) have argued that Roisman, Fraley, and colleagues methodological
longitudinal developmental research has not been refinement in understanding developmental
constructed in a rigorous enough fashion to deter- mechanisms in developmental systems and,
mine developmental mechanisms, and have pro- indeed, how they might have evolved.
posed a methodological solution. Their work Raby, Roisman, Fraley, and Simpson (2015)
calls into question our understanding of whether investigated whether the enduring effects model
there are legacy sequelae of early developmental provides an adequate fit to the data gathered in a
acquisitions in later developing systems. They longitudinal study spanning 32 years for an at-
queried whether the “revisionist” model that risk population. They replicated the results of a
early experience shapes development but dissi- comparable study by Fraley et al. (2013), but also
pates in influence (becomes weakly related or extended them. Neither study supported the
unrelated) as development proceeds has enough “revisionist” model, in which early experiences
empirical support to replace traditional models of gradually dissipate in their effects over time.
preserved, sustained effects on development Initially, Fraley et al. (2013) had used data
(enduring effects models). They used a path mod- from the NICHD (National Institute of Child
eling approach (see Fig. 14.1) to show that the Health and Human Development) Study of Early
critical information needed in traditional longitu- Child Care and Youth Development (SECCYD)
dinal studies do not provide or are insensitive to in a study of a normative population into mid-
the requisite information to distinguish the valid- adolescence. In their replicating study, Raby
ity of the two developmental models. et al. (2015) used data from the MLSRA
(Minnesota Longitudinal Study of Risk and
Adaptation) on pregnant mothers living below
Evidence the poverty line and receiving prenatal services.
About half were teenage mothers (N = 243).
Roisman and Fraley (2013) re-analyzed data from To measure early maternal sensitivity in Raby
a longitudinal study that ran until participants et al. (2015), mother–child interactions were vid-
arrived at the age of 15–18, which was on early eotaped in a home feeding situation. For later
maternal sensitivity in care giving in relation to observations at 6 months, there were two feed-
later academic performance, social competence, ings and one play interaction. For 24 and 42
and psychopathology. The results supported the months, the situations were laboratory ones on
enduring effects model of legacy of childhood problem solving and teaching. For the two
Allostasis and Allostatic Load Model 333

younger ages, maternal sensitivity was measured (e.g., control of attention). In this sense, for the
using the scales of Ainsworth, Blehar, Waters, case of autism, the disorder might be more than a
and Wall (1978). For the two older ages, the reflection of an atypical “social” brain (which in
mother’s supportive presence (positive involve- regards to the formulation suggested is too
ment and secure base provision) was evaluated. upstream and too localized).
A factor analysis indicated the different mater-
nal sensitivity measures could be combined into a
composite score. Social competence during child- Allostasis and Allostatic Load Model
hood and adolescence was measured using teacher
rankings (during kindergarten, grades 1–3 and 6, Model
and at age 16). For the adult period, semi-struc-
tured interviews were used at 23 and 32 years to The concepts of allostasis and allostatic overload
determine competence in social relationships. For (AL) are important in the area of the effects of early
academic competence, the PIAT (Peabody adversity on development. It includes description
Individual Achievement Test; Dunn & Markwardt, of the physiological mechanisms involved.
1970) was used for grades 1–3 and 6. At age 16, the For Ramsay and Woods (2014), allostasis con-
study used the WJTA (Woodcock–Johnson Tests of cerns more dysregulatory (or disordered) forms
Achievement; Woodcock, 1990; Woodcock & of physiological regulation. The greater the allo-
Johnson, 1989). For the young adult period, it was static load, the more the pathology. Psychosocial
evaluated as academic attainment at ages 23, 26, stress is an important source of allostatic system
28, and 32 years. Control variables concerned child overload. Allostatic mechanisms include over-
gender, child ethnicity, SES (socioeconomic sta- connected effector responses or persistent and no
tus), and maternal education. These variables were longer adaptive ones, causing more dysregulated
considered covariates in the analyses undertaken. concurrent effector competition.
The results in the Raby et al. (2015) study Juster et al. (2011) expanded the allostatic
favored the enduring effects model compared to load model (AL; McEwen & Stellar, 1993;
the revisionist model. Specifically, early maternal Sterling & Eyer, 1988) to psychopathology
sensitivity predicted academic development, in across the life span (see Fig. 14.2). For Juster
an enduring manner, or without diminishing over et al. (2011), AL refers to the “wear and tear”
age. Moreover, neither the covariates nor the sta- experienced by the organism exposed to chronic
bility of the measures over time (and the transac- stress. The model that they developed is transdis-
tions that they represented) could account for the ciplinary and focuses in an integrative way on
results. [Note that the enduring effect model was chronic stress. Stress is considered a multidimen-
not supported for the outcome measures used for sional construct among biological, psychologi-
social competence.] cal, and environmental factors. Specifically, it is
considered a real or subjectively perceived threat
of a person’s physiological or psychological
Comment integrity. That leads to biological and behavioral
responses likely to increase adaptation. According
Other research is consistent with the enduring to AL, the three factors that are involved in stress
effects model. Gliga, Jones, Bedford, Charman, (biopsychosocial) work in synergy. Stress hor-
and Johnson (2014) suggested that early neuro- mone function is especially altered under chronic
developmental mechanisms could be brainwide stress, leading to system collapse and disease.
and also long term in effects in conditions such The AL index is a quantitative measure that
as autism. Cumulative and cascading effects illustrates the factors involved in chronic stress. It
could derive from disturbances in early sensory comprises variables related to dysregulated neuro-
processing, which, as well, are related down- endocrine, immune, metabolic, and cardiovascular
stream to synaptic function impairments that markers (Seeman, Singer, Rowe, Horwitz, &
affect biological and psychological functions McEwen, 1997).
334 14 Early Adversity, Fetal Programming, and Getting Under the Skin

Emergent SOCIAL
Property

SPIRITUAL

PSYCHOLOGICAL
BIOLOGICAL/ CLINICAL
COGNITIVE/ AFFECTIVE

BEHAVIOR

GLOBAL HEALTH

Fig. 14.2 Transdisciplinary, global health framework: an ioral, and spiritual levels, which collectively shape global
integrated biopsychosocial model. In the 1970s, Jean health. A transdisciplinary approach to health research is
Piaget coined the term “transdisciplinarity” to describe consistent with the allostatic load model, in which health/
integrative, multilevel approaches to scientific inquiry. disease is believed to emerge as a totality of life domains
For Kessel and Rosenfield (2008), emergent properties that are best understood when studied in synergy. Adapted
derive from the dynamic interactions among health from Juster et al. (2011), based on Picard, Sabiston, and
domains at the biological, psychological, social, behav- McNamara (2011)

The antecedents of AL include: (a) early primarily indexed by stress hormone dysregula-
adversity; (b) genetic factors; (c) epigenetic fac- tion (McEwen & Stellar, 1993). When the dysreg-
tors; (d) environmental toxins; and (e) interac- ulation becomes chronic, pathophysiological
tions among biological and sociocultural factors. effects are potentiated. The allostatic overload sys-
Together, these factors contribute probabilisti- tem can mutually affect the psychological and bio-
cally to health outcomes (not deterministically; logical in nonlinear ways, with context crucial, as
Cicchetti & Toth, 2009). well. Disease develops in allostatic overload,
The perception of stress leads to not only imme- which takes place after system over-activation and
diate (e.g., adrenalin) but also slightly delayed (e.g., nonlinear dynamical interactive imbalances, lead-
cortisol) biological responses. The sympathetic- ing to the breaking point (McEwen, 1998a, 1998b).
adrenal-medullary (SAM) axis is involved in the McEwen and Wingfield (2003) noted that
former and the HPA axis in the latter. Other brain allostatic overload can occur in two types. In the
areas involved in the stress response include the first variant, energy demands exceed energy
hippocampus, amygdala, and prefrontal cortex. inflow, representing a negative energy balance.
SAM and HPA activity provide examples of In the second variant, the energy balance is posi-
allostasis, which is meant to maintain equilibrium. tive (e.g., obesity). McEwen (2006) added that
Its parameters are multiply-controlled, and so system factors affect not only metabolism
health is a state of responsiveness rather than a and other disease-potential physical processes
simple homeostatic process (Sterling, 2004). but also central nervous system (CNS) functions
The interconnected allostatic system can falter, as (e.g., cognition, depression).
Allostasis and Allostatic Load Model 335

Juster et al. (2011) explicated in depth how development according to differential stressor
allostatic overload contributes to developmental sensitivities and variations in context. Beyond
and long-term psychopathology. The model was that, the model applies equally to short- and long-
developed for populations but works for the indi- term (e.g., stage) developmental periods and their
vidual level, too. Similarly, I have maintained changes. Finally, the changes in any one period
that chronic stress is the factor that is common to reflect particular stress responses and allostatic
psychological injuries (Young, 2008a) and that processes unique to the period and stressors
somatization is a multifactorial process that can involved, leading to distinct long-term conse-
begin early in life (Young, 2008b). quences for health for the associated periods,
Evans, Li, and Whipple (2013) reviewed the stressors, and contexts involved.
research and methodology on cumulative risk
and adverse development impact. Multiple risk
factor exposure is considered more deleterious Evidence
than single adverse impact exposure. The find-
ings are consistent with, among others, the AL Conradt et al. (2014) conducted a prospective
model of chronic stress (McEwen, 1998a, 1998b) longitudinal study of prenatal substance abuse
and developmental evolutionary theory (Ellis, exposure (for N = 860) and its relationship to
Figueredo, Brumbach, & Schlomer, 2009). 11-year-old outcome, with cortisol reactivity also
Figure 14.3 presents Ganzel and Morris’s assessed at the latter age. Adversity was mea-
(2011) model of modulated allostasis in develop- sured using a summary index over prenatal sub-
ment, which goes beyond initial gene and stance abuse exposure and also cumulative risk
environment sets. It indicates that allostatic across early-life stressful events. The exposure
accommodation and accumulation vary over index was collapsed over type of substance abuse.

Stressors & 1 2 3 4
Context

Genes

Allostatic 1 2 3 4
Accommodation

Allostatic 1 2 3 4
Load

Mental & Physical 1 2 3 4


Health Outcome

Time

Fig. 14.3 Modulated allostasis. Allostatic accommo- might arise at each time period (qualitative and/or
dation and also accumulation of allostatic load are quantitative differences), for example, in physiologi-
seen to vary as a function of changing stress sensitiv- cal processes. Adapted from Ganzel and Morris
ity across time (development). Different patterns (2011)
336 14 Early Adversity, Fetal Programming, and Getting Under the Skin

Outcome was assessed using the CBCL (Child will adversity have deleterious consequences.
Behavior Checklist; Achenbach, 1991) and the Moreover, in the presence of supportive environ-
DISC-IV (Diagnostic Interview Schedule for ments, the alleles involved could lead to positive
Children-IV; Shaffer, Fisher, Lucas, Dulcan, & outcomes rather than negative outcomes, again
Schwab-Stone, 2000), as well as delinquency more than expected compared to the average and
scores and a measure of executive function (EF) those without the alleles in question. Differential
involving spatial working memory, thinking time, susceptibility informs the area of the effects of
and planning. The sample included African and early adversity on long-term development.
non-African Americans. Recent research is consistent with the model in
The results showed that, in the first 6 years of these regards.
life, greater prenatal substance exposure was
related to more postnatal adversity. Also, for
African Americans, more early adversity expo- Evidence
sure related to decreased or attenuated cortisol
reactivity, which in turn related to more problem- Oldehinkel, Ormel, Verhulst, and Nederhof
atic outcome at age 11 (more externalizing (2014) found evidence in support of each of three
behavior, executive dysfunction, delinquency, distinct and apparently contradictory models of
and poor student–teacher relations). the effect of early adversity on adolescent depres-
The results support the allostatic load model sion. The stress sensitization model argues that
for which early adversity becomes “biological childhood adversity reduces the threshold to a
embedded,” leading to deleterious consequences recent stressor (e.g., Rudolph & Flynn, 2007).
in stress reactivity and later psychopathology The stress amplification model maintains that
(e.g., Lester & Padbury, 2009; McEwen, 1998a, only high-stress conditions can interact with
1998b). In these regards, cumulative early adver- early adversity to facilitate depression (e.g.,
sity also has effects. However, in the research, Kendler, Kuhn, & Prescott, 2004). The stress
moderate cortisol reactivity had more positive inoculation model indicates that adversity in
effects, aiding in alertness, memory, and problem childhood protects or “steels” the developing per-
solving during stressful situations. son against the effects of stressors later in life
(e.g., Rutter, 2006). Oldehinkel et al. (2014)
argued that individual differences in the effects of
Comment early adversities vary according to regulatory
capacity, coping, and resilience for resultant
Allostatic load is a model that is consistent with a reaction patterns.
diatheses-stress understanding of health and dis- The details of their study are complex, but
ease. However, other models do not simply con- they showed that early adversity in adolescents
sider the cumulative effects of vulnerabilities increases depression risk after exposure and then
related to biology and environment. In particular, wanes in this effect. Also, if the onset is later,
the differential susceptibility model examines counter intuitively, depression is facilitated in
differential alleles in the workings of vulnerabili- low-risk rather than high-risk stress conditions.
ties on outcome. The authors argued that early adversity functions
to program resilience for high-stress conditions,
but not for low-stress conditions, in cases in
Differential Susceptibility which depression does not appear early. They
concluded that the results support the “biological
Model sensitivity to context” model (Boyce & Ellis,
2005). In particular, relative to moderate expo-
The last chapter reviewed the differential suscep- sure, both low- and high-adversity exposure ear-
tibility and related models. The model indi- lier in life program individuals for sensitivity to
cates that only in the presence of certain alleles the current context.
Adaptive Calibration Model 337

Mitchell et al. (2014) studied the effect of The gene × social environment interaction found
social disadvantage on children’s telomere length with (dis)advantage and TL is consistent with
(TL), which is a biomarker of stress, in the con- the differential susceptibility/biological sensitivity
text of moderation by genetic variants related to to environment context (Belsky, Bakermans-
serotonin and dopamine pathways that are associ- Kranenburg, & van IJzendoorn, 2007; Boyce &
ated with genetic sensitivity. TL shortening refers Ellis, 2005).
to the shortening of the protective repeat sequence
at the end of each chromosome (TTAGGG) that
takes place with each cycle of chromosomal rep- Comment
lication and cellular division; research has shown
that it is affected by chronic stress. Differential susceptibility factors influence the
Mitchell et al. (2014) studied TL in a sample effects of early adversity on developmental out-
of Black American 9-year-old boys exposed to come, but the results in the research are complex.
disadvantaged environments, and measured by a The same is true for a variation of the model, that
combine index. Early adversity was associated of adaptive calibration.
with TL shortening, but genetic sensitivity scores
over the two neurotransmitter pathways moder-
ated the results. That is, the more genetically sen- Adaptive Calibration Model
sitive participants had the shortest TL, but only if
they were exposed to disadvantage. In contrast, The adaptive calibration model has been reviewed
they had the longest if they were exposed to in the prior chapter. This chapter reconsiders it in
advantageous environments. the context of discussing early adversity.
The study was longitudinal, with the first Hostinar and Gunnar (2013) contrasted two
wave taking place within 2 days of birth. models applicable to the developmental effects
Environment quality was measured using a com- of stress early in life, one being more evolution-
bined index of family economic conditions, par- ary and the other more contextual. In the allo-
enting practices, and family structure/stability. static load (AL) model (McEwen, 1998b, 2008;
The measure was also decomposed to examine McEwen & Stellar, 1993; McEwen & Wingfield,
each component. 2003), stress that is frequent and chronic accu-
The serotonin-related sensitivity score mulates in wear-and-tear effects, taking a corpo-
summed four serotonin markers from two genes ral toll that can lead to physical and mental
(5-HTT: 5-HTTLPR, STin2; TPH2: rs4570625, disease via allostatic overload (see Fig. 14.4).
rs1386494). For dopamine, the sums involved In the adaptive calibration model (ACM) (Del
DAT1, rs40184; DRD4, third exon variable Giudice, Ellis, & Shirtcliff, 2011), individuals
number tandem repeat (VNTR); DRD2, Taq1a differ in stress reactivity due to evolutionary
polymorphism (rs1800497); and catechol-O- selection facilitative of phenotypic matching to
methyltransferase (COMT), rs4680 (Val158Met). contextual conditions (see Fig. 14.5). The ACM
For each neurotransmitter system genetic vari- is related to the work of Ellis and Boyce (2008)
ants, the authors examined two pathways, and Belsky and Pluess (2009) on biological/dif-
involving homozygous genotypes and sensitizing ferential sensitivity/susceptibility to context/
alleles. environment. It suggests that differential adversi-
Based on these measures and their results, ties play a role in life-history strategies (e.g.,
Mitchell et al. (2014) concluded that an individu- early childbirth in unpredictable, uncontrollable
al’s genetic architecture related to TL, which is like environments). The AL and ACM models differ
a mitotic clock of senescence, interacts with exog- in focus, with the former concentrating on proxi-
enous stressors in moderating the magnitude and mal (e.g., physiological) rather than distal (evolu-
direction of physiological response to the latter. tionary) mechanisms. The ACM can be applied
338 14 Early Adversity, Fetal Programming, and Getting Under the Skin

Environmental Major life event Trauma/ abuse


stressor stressor stressor

Perceived stress

One’s
Individual
differences Behavior

Physiological
responses
Destructive
Constructive

Allostasis Allostatic load

Adaptation Disease

Fig. 14.4 Allostasis and allostatic load model. The per- is perceived, physiological/behavioral responses begin,
ception of stress is influenced by experience, genetics, and leading to allostasis/adaptation. However, over time, allo-
behavior. There are individual differences in this regard. I static load (wear/tear) can accumulate, and can have
added to the figure feedback loops among perceived adverse effects on various organ systems, leading to dis-
stress, and behavior? Physiological response. When stress ease. Adapted from McEwen (1998a)

to development (childhood stressors), and does valid tasks. Minds are “adapted” to their environ-
consider plasticity in development. The authors ments no matter how their localization or
concluded that both models need further work particular attributes had been derived.
and that the mechanism of epigenesis could
provide a means to integrate better the models.
Frankenhuis and de Weerth (2013) proposed Stress Generation
that early psychosocial adversity might not only
impair cognition but also improve aspects of it Model
related to danger and survival. The early stressors
might promote a here-and-now focus that orients Stress has been implicated in susceptibilities in
development toward adapting to local environ- development, including in genetic-mediated
mental conditions. Early-life stress exposure ones. However, stress should not be considered
could shape perception to detect and predict purely an exogenous, environmental event that is
threat, leading to hyperattention to threat and acting on a passive organism. Stress might have
danger, and even better reasoning in ecologically- its effects on development through endogenous
Stress Generation 339

Sex
Hormones
Novelties/
opportunities in
environment

Unpredictable/
uncontrollable
environment

Threats/
Life-history dangers Stress Tracks
factors Response Regulation of (fast,
in
life-history slow)
environment System
related traits

Parental behaviors/
care giving attachment
Adaptive
(in)security affected
calibration
(filtering,
amplification)

Other
context
factors

Fig. 14.5 Adaptive calibration model. Note. Growth/ threats/dangers. The opportunities and novelties in the
learning; maturation/fertility; competition/risk-taking; environment, as well as parenting and context, in general,
and pair bonding/care giving factors involved in early or also influence the life-history traits and tracks (fast, slow).
later mating and related behavior. Conceptual structure of The mediator in the behavior is the stress response sys-
the adaptive calibration model. It illustrates that life- tem, which involves an adaptive calibration (filtering,
history trajectories are influenced by evaluating and fore- amplification). Adapted from Del Giudice et al. (2011)
casting unpredictable/uncontrollable environments and

and not only exogenous processes. In this regard, relationship. The source of dependent stressors
the stress generation hypothesis of depression relates to factors such as depressogenic cogni-
has yielded relevant findings (e.g., the person tions, behaviors, and interpersonal patterns that
objectively contributes him- or herself to dissolu- persist even as the depression might not.
tion of a romantic relationship). However, the
stress generation hypothesis of depression not
only considers this factor but also others, such as Evidence
differential susceptibility.
Liu (2013) reviewed the concept of stress gen- Risk factors for stress-related depression genera-
eration in relation to depression. The standard tion include not only childhood maltreatment
model of depression includes the stress-diathesis (Liu, Choi, Boland, Mastin, & Alloy, 2013) but
model (e.g., Morris, Ciesla, & Garber, 2008), in also genetic factors. Starr, Hammen, Brennan,
which stress exposure interacts with pre-existing and Najman (2012) found that the serotonin
depression-related vulnerabilities. In the stress transporter gene polymorphism (5-HTTLPR)
generation model (Hammen, 1991, 2006), objec- interacted with depression in 15-year-olds to pre-
tive, agent-dependent stressors could actively dict dependent stressors at age 20, especially for
serve to promote depression, in addition to any those with one short (s) allele at the gene locus.
effect of independent stressors. As depression- Starr, Hammen, Brennan, and Najman (2013)
related symptoms increase, so does the probabil- found for stress generation that the 5-HTTLPR
ity of experiencing more stress, in a reciprocal genotype interacted with relational security.
340 14 Early Adversity, Fetal Programming, and Getting Under the Skin

Intrapersonal
Distal Risk Factors Genetic Factors
Sequelae

Stress Generation

Cognitive Risk Interpersonal


Factors Behavioral Risk Factors Sequelae

Fig. 14.6 Risk factors and negative outcomes of stress cognitive (negative inferential style); and behavioral
generation in depression. The figure illustrates that (negative attachment style, dependency). Examples of
depression might be a consequence of stress generation depression-related sequelae include: intrapersonal
facilitated by an individual’s various risk factors, includ- (depressive recurrence) and interpersonal (depression
ing genetic. Examples of risk factors include those that contagion) ones. Adapted from Liu (2013)
are: distal-childhood maltreatment; genetic (5-HTTLPR);

Specifically, the s allele was associated with their infrequent emotional displays. Depression,
decreased deleterious (dependent) stressors in therefore, is considered due to the infant’s
adolescents with high security but increased inhibition, i.e., general withdrawal from the
stress generation in those with low security. mother, whether or not she is unresponsive.
Liu (2013) presented an integrated model of
stress generation that includes distal and proximal
risk factors (see Fig. 14.6). The distal risk factors Comment
include childhood emotional abuse, which Liu
et al. (2013) studied in relation to negative infer- Although the stress generation hypothesis of
ential cognitive style and stress generation (i.e., depression has been supported empirically and
dependent stressors). Cognitive risk factors such an interaction effect with genetic substrate has
as these exert indirect influence in the model rela- been found, the independent environment still
tive to direct ones, such as behavioral risk factors has an important role to play in the development
(e.g., negative attachment style, dependency). of depression. Charles, Piazza, Mogle, Sliwinski,
Finally, genetic risk factors (e.g., 5-HTTLPR) act and Almeida (2013) investigated whether minor
to moderate the behavioral risk factors. daily stressors can after mental health in the long
In this regard, Dix, Meunier, Lusk, and Perfect term. Increased levels of self-reported negative
(2012) found that, for 14- to 27-month-olds, the affect on nonstressful days were associated with
mother’s depressive symptoms influenced their general affective distress and with affective dis-
infants’ facial emotions. The authors explained order symptoms 10 years later. A critical explana-
that depressed mothers give their infants less tory variable in the relationship appeared to be
support, leading to increased inhibition in their heightened affective reactivity to the wear and
emotional communication. In consequence, the tear of relatively minor daily stress events.
children exhibit flatter affect and less joy but also Another factor to consider in stress research
less sadness and negative emotion. However, concerns resilience. Rutter (2012) considered
infant passivity mediated the relationship resilience as a dynamic construct. He noted that
between their mother’s depressive symptoms and response to stress varies and also that a negative
Environment 341

response for some people leads to a “steeling indicating its protective or buffering function in
effect,” or a resistance in effect. Later responses to stress modulation. The authors concluded that
major stress or adversity include either decreased possible mechanisms affecting telomere length
sensitivities or strengthening (thus, better over- due to early-life adversity include dysregulation
coming it, yielding better outcomes). Mediators by the HPA axis and overproduction of proin-
include factors such as a sense of self-efficacy. flammatory cytokines.
G × E research has implicated an interaction with Gotlib et al. (2015) found that TL in daughters
the serotonin transporter promoter gene, as well (10–14 years) of depressed mothers was shorter
(e.g., Caspi et al., 2003; Caspi, Hariri, Holmes, than daughters of mothers with no history of
Uher, & Moffitt, 2010). Cicchetti and Rogosch depression. Also, shorter TL was associated with
(2012) found a G × E interaction effect in resil- greater (cortisol) stress reactivity in both daugh-
ience related to this gene and several others in ter groups. Covariates did not alter the results
maltreated and nonmaltreated 6- to 12-year-olds, (Tanner stage or Child Depression Inventory
with genetic variation having a greater impact on (CDI) scores; Kovacs, 1992). The daughters were
resilient functioning among the controls. healthy psychopathologically (according to the
Kiddie-Sads-Present and Lifetime (K-SADS-PL);
Kaufman, Birmaher, Brent, Ryan, & Rao, 2000).
Genes and Environments The authors concluded that shortened TL appears
to be an antecedent risk factor for possible
The environment has an important role to play in depression, and also that mediation of the effect
long-term development. However, it acts interac- could involve HPA axis dysregulation.
tively with genetics in many developmental phe-
nomena (see Chap. 11). The following does not
deal with G × E interactions, per se, but the effects Environment
of genes and environments on early adversity
influences. The biological approach to early adversity is
Asok, Bernard, Roth, Rosen, and Dozier compelling, with captivating research findings in
(2013) examined whether parental responsiveness its support. Nevertheless, the environmental point
in a semi-structured interaction task moderated of view is equally powerful in these regards. Both
the link between early life stress in 4- to 6-year- influences affect development in the long-term,
olds (either high- or low-risk) and reduced telo- and this happens in an interactive way.
mere length. They explained that telomeres are
chromosome-end TTAGGG tag repeats that help
protect chromosomal DNA from damage as they Support
replicate. Telomeres naturally reduce with each
replication so that they are considered markers of Hostinar, Sullivan, and Gunnar (2014) reviewed
biological aging. Moreover, they shorten due to the literature showing the influence of social sup-
factors such as oxidative stress, including due to port, or its lack, on stress response and the HPA
childhood adversity (Price, Kao, Burgers, axis, as well as its biological mediators in the
Carpenter, & Tyrka, 2013). oxytocinergic system and prefrontal cortical neu-
In their research, Asok et al. (2013) found ral networks. The model that they developed is a
that high-risk children compared to low-risk life span and social buffering one, which begins
ones had shorter telomeres, after controlling for to function prenatally through programming
confounding variables. However, parental effects (see Fig. 14.7). In positive circumstances,
responsiveness served to moderate the associa- early relationships are supportive, attachment fig-
tion between risk and length of telomere; paren- ures are appraised in a safety framework, and
tal responsiveness was associated with longer self-esteem and personal control/self-regulation
telomeres, but only among high-risk children, develop. Mediators of the HPA axis are moder-
342 14 Early Adversity, Fetal Programming, and Getting Under the Skin

Distal Proximal Outcome

Early Ongoing social


supportive supports
relations

Presumed biological
mediators

Attachment
figure(s) OT release/
receptor (Mal)
distribution Adaptation
Biopsycho- & binding (Emotional
social (Dys)
Social HPA axis Regulation)
factors (e.g., relationships activity
gene, Neural
culture) priming
(vmPFC
activation,
Self-esteem/ etc.)
personal Trigger
control (A
Other possible stressor)
mediators
(Dopamine
Serotonin, etc.)

Individual differences (e.g., context, gender, aging)

Learning
Development
Evolution
Unsupportive Context Supportive

Fig. 14.7 A developmental working model of social self-esteem and behavioral regulation. Mediators in the
buffering of the hypothalamic-pituitary-adrenal (HPA) development of HPA activation involve OT mechanisms
axis in humans. Both early and ongoing social support can and neural priming. The behavioral system described
moderate stressful conditions, and function as buffers of includes crucial individual differences in reactivity. OT =
any impacts on activation of the HPA axis, which might oxytocin, vmPFC = ventromedial prefrontal cortex,
have deleterious effects when it is not moderated. Early Epi = epinephrine, NE = norepinephrine. Adapted from
care giving support from attachment figures leads to better Hostinar et al. (2014)

ated by stress buffers early in life, in that care having much psychosocial resources relates to
giving experiences influence both social compe- lower stress response in the HPA (Taylor et al.,
tency and biological reactivity to stressors. 2008). (d) Social contact stimulates oxytocin
Some of the evidence in support of the model release, e.g., of plasma or urinary oxytocin (e.g.,
reviewed by Hostinar et al. (2014) included the Feldman, Singer, & Zagoory, 2010, for infants).
following: (a) Sensitive, early care giving pre- (e) Oxytocin possesses stress-relief properties,
dicts later positive self-esteem, self-regulation, e.g., in studies with intranasal administration in
and social competence, e.g., caregiver quality males, breastfeeding in females (Heinrichs,
predicts later positive, attachment-secure repre- Baumgartner, Kirschbaum, & Ehlert, 2003;
sentations of partners in young adult romantic Heinrichs et al., 2001, respectively). (f) Early
relations (Haydon, Collins, Salvatore, Simpson, social experience is associated with receptor
& Roisman, 2012). (b) Abnormal care giving expression and binding of HPA axis biological
experience/maltreatment impairs social develop- mediators, e.g., childhood maltreatment is asso-
ment, e.g., in insecure attachment patterns in pre- ciated with adult women expressing lower oxyto-
schoolers (Cicchetti, Rogosch, & Toth, 2006). (c) cin levels in cerebrospinal fluid (Heim et al.,
Social input can tamp HPA axis reactivity, e.g., 2009). (g) Abnormal rearing can lead to absent
Environment 343

HPA axis social buffering, e.g., in orphanage implications for the cross-generational transmis-
children (Wismer Fries, Ziegler, Kurian, Jacoris, sion of the effects of anxiety.
& Pollak, 2005). (h) In negative affect regulation,
prefrontal cortex activation in stress-buffering
takes place, e.g., in pain-related neural activation Preconception
in women presented images of their romantic
partners (Eisenberger et al., 2011). (i) Early care Class, Khashan, Lichtenstein, Långström, and
giving experiences appear to shape connections D’Onofrio (2013) demonstrated that the precon-
between prefrontal cortical and limbic system ception environment can influence postnatal
areas possessing excitatory input to the HPA axis development. They studied maternal stress in
(e.g., Tottenham et al., 2010). relation to infant mortality. Preconception was
Biglan, Flay, Embry, and Sandler (2012) defined as 0–6 months before conception.
emphasized the influence of nurturing environ- Maternal stress was indexed by as the death of
ments in developing human well-being and con- the mother participants’ first-degree relative.
tributing positively to society. The environment Infant mortality was indexed relative to the first
could be “toxic” but also could act to promote year of life. The results showed that preconcep-
self-regulatory behavior and psychological flexi- tion stress was associated with increased infant
bility. For toxic effects, the authors cited research mortality, unlike the case for prenatal stress.
that parental conflict in kindergarten children Class et al. (2013) concluded that the bereave-
leads to externalizing problems two years later ment involved could affect the mother’s health to
(Davies, Sturge-Apple, Cicchetti, & Cummings, the point of having epigenetic effects on the fetus
2007). Parental verbal abuse is associated with to be conceived. This would act to compromise
white matter tract intensity (Choi, Jeong, Rohan, survivability if it occurred in the sensitive period
Polcari, & Teicher, 2009). involved.
Rifkin-Graboi et al. (2015) determined that The authors described the hypothesized mech-
prenatal maternal anxiety predicted their chil- anism that could account for the association
dren’s neurodevelopment neonatally and even between preconception maternal stress and post-
psychopathology-related behavior at one year of birth infant mortality. The bereavement could
age. Specifically, they measured maternal anxiety affect the psychological, cognitive, behavioral,
using the Spielberger State-Trait Anxiety endocrine, physiological-somatic, and immune
Inventory (STAI; Spielberger, 1983) at the age of functioning of the mother to be, thereby affecting
16 weeks gestation of their offspring. Also, they in turn her nutritional or hormonal systems. The
measured variation in newborn (5–17 days post- mother’s lack of preparedness for pregnancy
natal) neuronal microstructures using diffusion could affect the fetus’s organogenesis in a vulner-
tensor imaging (DTI). Finally, they measured able period (e.g., brainstem-based control of
infant socio-emotional behavior at one year of autonomic functioning of breathing via seroto-
age using the Infant Toddler Socio-Emotional nergic and noradrenergic neuronal systems).
Assessment (ITSEA; Carter & Briggs-Gowan,
2006) instrument.
As for the result of their study, they found that Socioeconomic Status/Poverty
prenatal maternal anxiety predicted variations in
fractional anisotropy (FA) of various corticolim- Tomalski et al. (2013) showed a relationship
bic regions of the brain in the neonate that are between SES and functional brain development
known to be associated with cognitive-emotional in early infancy. They investigated resting base-
response to stress, as well as related functions line electroencephalographic (EEG) activity in
(e.g., the right insula, the right dorsolateral pre- 6- to 9-month-olds. Infants’ SES was classified
frontal cortex, the right middle occipital region, according to gross family income and parental
and the right angular gyrus). The results have occupation, which were involved in the results,
344 14 Early Adversity, Fetal Programming, and Getting Under the Skin

unlike maternal education. Methodologically, the The results on brain structure in this study gener-
research recorded absolute power of resting EEG ally concerned those areas that are associated
in two gamma frequency ranges (21–30 Hz and with language, reading, executive function, and
31–45 Hz) in four scalp areas—frontal, left tem- spatial skills in development.
poral, right temporal, and occipital.
Specifically, the results of the study revealed
region-selective differences in early infancy Other Work
(reduced gamma power over the frontal area)
among infants from lower-income families (and To conclude review of early adversity influences
at-risk occupation). The authors concluded that on long-term development, the chapter considers
the results implicate a relative desynchronization other work. For example, there are long-term
in developing language networks, placing low effects on development due to factors related to
SES infants at risk for deficits in selective atten- attachment, stress, and inflammation.
tion and executive control of attention.
As for mechanisms in the effects found, the
authors suggested exploration of prenatal factors, Attachment
epigenetic factors, and various environmental fac-
tors. I would add to this list all factors that com- The importance of early infant attachment in later
promise maternal preparedness for pregnancy. development even into adulthood is illustrated in
Evans and Cassells (2013) investigated the the following research. Puig, Englund, Simpson,
relationship between early poverty and 17-year and Collins (2012) conducted a 32-year longitudi-
mental health. Externalizing (but not internaliz- nal study. Attachment type at 12 and 18 months in
ing) and learned helplessness behavior appeared the situation of caregiver reunion after separation
affected by child poverty. However, the results (Ainsworth et al., 1978) was related to physical
were mediated by age-13 cumulative risk expo- condition later on. Specifically, insecure attach-
sure/psychosocial risk factors and also physical ment relative to secure attachment in infancy was
risk factors (respectively: violence, family tur- associated with physical illness (inflammation-
moil, family separation; noise, crowding, sub- based) 30 years later. In another study, this research
standard housing). The authors concluded that group found an association between attachment
early deprivation could have lasting mental health and global adaptive functioning at age 28 (Englund,
effects into emerging adulthood, with factors in Kuo, Puig, & Collins, 2011). Puig et al. (2012) had
the adolescent period mediating the relationship. noted that adult attachment style also is associated
Noble et al. (2015) conducted a cross-sectional with physical illness (McWilliams & Baily, 2010).
study of family income, parental education, and Esbjørn, Bender, Reinholdt-Dunne, Munck,
brain structure in participants varying between 3 and Ollendick (2012) presented a model that
and 20 years of age. This is the first study of SES early attachment style (as well as dysfunctional
factors in relation to brain structure that attempted emotional regulation) influences the develop-
to control for genetic ancestry; it included as ment of anxiety disorders into the adolescent
covariates continuously varying measures of period (see Fig. 14.8). Caregivers might not
genetic ancestry degree. match their behavior to their children’s emo-
The results revealed that, for children from tional needs. Coupled with other variables,
lower-income backgrounds, small incremental attachment insecurity and consequent emotional
differences in family income were associated regulation and anxiety might develop (e.g.,
with relative large differences in brain surface Colonnesi et al., 2011).
area, unlike the case for children from higher Morley and Moran (2011) examined other
income backgrounds. The variable of parental consequences of early attachment insecurities
education accounted for offspring variation in and their effects, in this case on later depression.
brain structural characteristics that were different The insecure attachment style is associated with
from those accounted for by parental education. helpless attributions and responses to stress, e.g.,
Other Work 345

Basic emotion regulation Basic emotion regulation


skills see below present skills are deficient

Attachment Reflective
Attachment Reflective insecurity functioning
security functioning present deficient

Parenting behavior, Parenting behavior,


Caregivers i.e., match/ mismatch of i.e., intrusiveness/ anxious
child emotional states/
modeling
needs

Anxious Specific Specific


situations situations

Selective Negative life Selective


avoidance events avoidance
Genetic Modified via Modified via
vulnerability, safety safety
e.g. inhibited behavior behavior
temperament Anxiety
disorder(s)
Attention to Attention to
threats threats
Attachment Trait anxiety
insecurity Negative Negative
Offspring appraisals appraisals

Anxiety Anxiety
responses responses
Attachment Reflective
insecurity functioning
Basic emotion deficient
regulation skills
Basic emotion
deficient, i.e., regulation skills
hypervigilance and deficient
negative affect

Infant/ Toddler Age Period Child/ Adolescent Age Period

Fig. 14.8 The role of attachment and emotion regulation on the development of childhood anxiety disorders. The fig-
ure indicates the complexity of causal models in dyadic (parental) relations. Adapted from Esbjørn et al. (2012)

failure, negative life events, and vulnerability to Booth-LaForce (2014) and colleagues ques-
depression (see Fig. 14.9). tioned the unitary construct underlying adult
Kochanska and Kim (2012) differentiated the attachment insecurity, finding relatively indepen-
view of attachment as contributory to later distur- dent dismissing and preoccupied states of mind
bances in behavior (see Fig. 14.10). The child in a study using the Adult Attachment Interview
brings characteristics, such as anger proneness, (AAI; Main, Kaplan, & Cassidy, 1985).
that complicate linear causality from early paren- Moreover, individual differences reflected more
tal behavior to outcomes (e.g., antisociality in of a dimensional than categorical model. This
early school age). They found that early insecurity type of reworking of the attachment construct
in interaction with anger proneness led to power- might lead to more nuanced models of how early
assertive parenting and, ultimately, antisocial attachment affects long-term developmental out-
behavior in early school-age children. Secure come. In this regard, refer to my developmental
infants were buffered from this effect. model of the 25 steps over the life span of attach-
Booth-LaForce (2014), Booth-LaForce and ment-related social self-working schemata (see
Roisman (2014), and Roisman, Fraley, and Chap. 31).
346 14 Early Adversity, Fetal Programming, and Getting Under the Skin

Self / Other
Representation Adverse Life Event
(Trigger)
Early
Caregiver-
Offspring
Interactions
Quality
Early Working Vulnerability to
Helplessness Depression
Model Depression

Distal Proximal
Developmental Timeline

Fig. 14.9 Proposed pathway linking quality of early event) and of early negative (parent–offspring) attach-
attachment experience to later depression. In the develop- ment interactions and representations (working models)
ment of depression and its vulnerability, there are poten- (distal influence). Adapted from Morley and Moran
tial lifelong effects of proximal stressors (e.g., adverse life (2011)

Attachment
(Infancy)

Socialization
(Preschool Age)

Child Antisocial
Child Characteristics
Outcomes
(Toddler Age)
(Early School Age)

Fig. 14.10 The causal chain from child characteristics to discipline, and power assertion. Child characteristics
parental socialization to child antisocial outcomes in inse- include temperament, anger proneness, and difficulty.
cure and secure attachment. Child and parental contribu- Child outcomes include poor self-regulation, rule-
tions to attachment and outcome. Attachment develops in breaking, opposition, aggression, callousness, and disrup-
infancy (secure, insecure), and has consequences for tiveness. Adapted from Kochanska and Kim (2012)
socialization of the child. Socialization involves control,

Early Adversity being physically hurt, sexual abuse, maternal


separation, and paternal separation. Ratings were
Slopen, Kubzansky, McLaughlin, and Koenen obtained at seven age points between 1.5 and
(2013) found that early life adversity increased 8 years, and total scores were derived. The
indices of inflammation even into 15 years of inflammatory markers were interleukin-6 and
age, having consequences for adulthood health. C-reactive protein (CRP). Cumulative risk also
They measured early adversity by maternal played a role (e.g., in the first 8 years in relation
report of five acute adverse events: foster care, to CRP at age 15).
Other Work 347

Romens, McDonald, Svaren, and Pollak neural regulatory systems (Levine, 2005). Young
(2015) found an association between early life children reared in extremely neglectful institu-
stress (physical maltreatment) and epigenetic tions evidence lasting alterations in the develop-
methylation changes in a portion of the glucocor- ment of the brain (Pollak et al., 2010), with
ticoid receptor gene in 11- to 14-year-olds (within similar results found for maltreated and foster
exon 1F in the NR3C1 promoter region of the children (Cicchetti, Rogosch, Gunnar, & Toth,
gene; CpG site 3, in particular). The gene is 2010; Fisher, Gunnar, Dozier, Bruce, & Pears,
involved in stress regulation, and stress or trauma 2006, respectively). The adverse effects on brain
has been shown to be correlated with higher development might derive from cumulative
methylation of the gene in cases of abuse and later effects rather than extreme ones (i.e., allostatic
psychopathology (e.g., McGowan et al., 2009; load; Shonkoff, Boyce, & McEwen, 2009).
Perroud et al., 2014). The results suggested that Fisher and Gunnar (2010) implicated, in particu-
HPA axis dysregulation serves as a mechanism in lar, the first 2 years of life in this effect.
stress-related psychopathology in children. Just as the developing brain is plastic to
St. Clair et al. (2014) conducted a study delin- adverse effects, so can it be affected by interven-
eating early adversity subtypes and links to later tions designed to promote neural plasticity.
adolescent depression. They found that early Generally, enriched environments work best
experiential adversity did have predictive effects, when they include complexity and novelty (Sale,
and the effects were not linear. Moreover, the Berardi, & Maffei, 2009). Physical exercise also
links diminished in boys but not in girls. The appears salutatory in this regard (Hillman,
normative/optimal parenting subtype was distin- Erickson, & Kramer, 2008). Studies on
guished from three suboptimal ones—aberrant, laboratory-based executive training studies with
discordant, and hazardous. The latter two sub- children show positive findings, as well (Bryck &
types had wider effects (in both genders). Mayr, 2005; Holmes, Gathercole, & Dunning,
2009; Karbach & Kray, 2009; Mackey, Hill,
Stone, & Bunge, 2011; Thorell, Lindqvist,
Inflammation Nutley, Bohlin, & Klingberg, 2009; Tominey &
McClelland, 2011). Training now includes eco-
Fagundes and Way (2014) reviewed that early logical components (e.g., Mackey et al., 2011).
severe life stress can impact physical health
through augmented inflammation. For example,
Lam et al. (2012) found that early-life adversity Coping
was related to genome-wide methylation (epi-
genesis) in adulthood. The physical illnesses Foland-Ross, Kircanski, and Gotlib (2014) found
potentiated in this chain include cardiovascular that 12-year-olds with a depressed mother used
disease, type 2 diabetes, some cancers, and more involuntary (e.g., escape, rumination) com-
Alzheimer’s disease. pared to voluntary (e.g., problem solving, posi-
tive thinking) coping strategies in dealing stress,
which in turn was associated with exacerbation
Brain of HPA axis dysfunction (increasing already high
levels of diurnal cortisol levels). The authors
Bryck and Fisher (2012) reviewed research noted that different coping strategies are not
showing that experience acts to shape the archi- inherently adaptive or maladaptive; for example,
tecture of the brain in development (National low-risk controls exhibited a more negative asso-
Scientific Council on the Developing Child, ciation between cortisol level and the use of
2007). Animal research reveals that stressful involuntary coping strategies, indicative of the
rearing environments appear to affect critical blunting of cortisol secretion.
348 14 Early Adversity, Fetal Programming, and Getting Under the Skin

Crum, Salovey, and Anchor (2013) demon- independent predictors of the covariation of inter-
strated that stress experience is contingent on nalizing symptoms and negative life events. In this
belief/mindset. For example, inducing a “stress- longitudinal study, the early life stress served as a
is-enhancing” mindset is associated with moder- sensitizing agent along with later cortisol readings
ate cortisol reactivity. in the participant adolescents. Early life stress was
measured through maternal report in infancy; the
cortisol was assessed at 11, 13, and 15 years; and
Biopsychosocial Findings life event quality and internalizing symptoms
were evaluated at 18 years of age. Specifically, the
The most recent research examined on adversity authors found that early life stress led to a “tighter”
shows influences on development consistent with covariation between negative life events and inter-
a multifactorial biopsychosocial confluence of nalizing symptoms. Also, among other results,
influences on development in early adversity. The lower afternoon cortisol assays led to the same
first section of the following review shows tighter covariation. The authors concluded that the
genetic and environmental influences in the effect results address the differential stress sensitization
of early adversity on development. The section model of early negative stressful experiences.
after that reviews research pointing to the role of Gee et al. (2014) demonstrated that maternal
personal contributions, or of the person him- or buffering affects amygdala-prefrontal circuitry in
herself, in influencing the effects of early adver- children, improving affect-related regulation.
sity or stress on development. Also, they found individual differences in this
regard, for example, with greater maternal influ-
ence on the indicated circuitry in stronger
Genes and Environment Contribution mother–child relationships. The children were
4–10 years of age. The circuitry was established
Strüber, Strüber, and Roth (2014) proposed a using fMRI (functional magnetic resonance
double pathway model in the effects of early imaging) during examination of the mother’s pic-
adversity on glucocorticoid regulation (GR) and tured face or one of a matched stranger. Affect
later mental disorders. In the first pathway, early regulation was assessed in a go/no-go task. The
stress, acting in conjunction with either high task was administered once with the mother pres-
maternal care or with the s allele of 5-HTTLPR, ent and once with a stranger (research assistant)
first produces upregulation of hippocampal GR present. In the go/no-go task, the children had to
and then produces long-term HPA axis hyper- press a button to a target facial expression (go),
function. In turn, this produces downregulation but not to a distractor one (no-go). At first, a
of 5-HT1A receptors, thereby heightening activ- happy face was used for the go condition and a
ity of ventromedial prefrontal cortical (VMPFC) sad one for the no-go one; then, a neutral expres-
areas. This pathway leads to increase in emo- sion was used for the no-go one. In the third
tional sensitivity and melancholic depression. block of tasks, the neutral and happy expressions
In the second proposed pathway of the effects served as the go and no-go conditions.
of early stress on GR and consequent mental dis- The authors found that adolescents did not
order, early adversity either in absence of high reveal the same buffering effect, showing that
maternal care or in the presence of the l allele of childhood appears a sensitive period for linkage
5-HTTLPR causes downregulation of hippocam- in circuitry of the amygdala and prefrontal cor-
pal GR, long-term HPA axis hypofunction, tex. The maternal buffering effect indicates the
upregulation of 5-HT1A- receptors, decreased neurobiological locus of care giving on affect
VMPFC activity, reduced emotional sensitivity, regulation in childhood; the effect may take place
and atypical depression/psychopathy. through action on the HPA axis.
Ruttle, Armstrong, Klein, and Essex (2014) Crone and Elzinga (2015) examined the litera-
found that early life stress and cortisol served as ture showing how fMRI can be used to establish
Chapter Conclusions 349

longitudinal cognitive and socioaffective growth the pathways, predictors, and consequences
trajectories and their relationship to the changing involved, as well as the genes, neurocircuitry, and
brain. For example, Emerson and Cantlon (2014) neuroendocrinology involved. At the same time,
related left intraparietal sulcus (IPS) change to the role in the environment, for example, as buf-
improvement in performance on a numerical pro- fers, is mentioned, as well as individual differ-
cessing task in children followed 2–3 years (to ences in development in the multifactorial array
ages 4–9). that influences it. Early adversity could express
Also, in children tested 2–3 times in the age long-term consequences, but many factors are
range 6–18 years, unlike for Met/Met, carriers of involved in long-term outcomes, and a biopsy-
the VAT/VA1 COMT genotype showed during a chosocial approach to development and its out-
relatively easy working memory (WM) task an comes appears a fruitful one.
increasing neural activation in ventral lateral PFC
and the angular gyrus (Dumontheil et al., 2011).
In contrast, for a harder WM task, the Met/Met Chapter Conclusions
carriers were the ones who expressed a steeper
increase in performance over time. The area of the effect of early environmental
According to Crone and Elzinga (2015), the experiences on later development has a long his-
results described show that individual differences tory in psychology. Freud’s classic model of psy-
in genetics could participate in shaping brain chodynamic development (psychoanalysis), for
development trajectories. Overall, individual example, emphasizes the role of the early years
characteristics, such as in genetics and tempera- in development. The ethologists refer to early
ment/personality, render individuals differentially critical periods in development. Contemporary
susceptible to their environment in their develop- understanding of development refers to transac-
ment, including in brain growth trajectory. tions between organism and environment from
conception on, as well as concepts such as devel-
opmental windows in which environments are
The Personal Contributions more liable to have an impact. Recent models
emphasize the concepts of—prenatal or early
In a study over 16 years with individuals as young programming; epigenesis and its long-term envi-
as 16 as starting age, Jeronimus, Riese, ronmental effects on genes, even over genera-
Sanderman, and Ormel (2014) showed that neu- tions; and differential susceptibility to the
roticism and life experiences expressed a “recip- environment [all of these models are central to
rocally causal,” mutual reinforcing process, to the the present work]. These increasingly complex
point that neuroticism appears to function as a and variegated developmental models indicate
regulatory set point. By reciprocal causation, the the importance not only of early environmental
authors meant that, aside from other aspects of the factors, such as early adversity and parental qual-
relationship between neuroticism and experience, ity, but also of the genetic substrates on which
individuals seek, shape, and evoke life events they act and function to condition them, in turn.
consistent with their personality characteristics The environment does not act independently on
(Caspi & Shiner, 2011). Experiences did play a the organism, nor do genes. They genuinely
role in the results, and also the authors distin- interact, and this takes place from the earliest
guished temporary changes in neuroticism from phases of development, if not before, as in epi-
persistent changes in one’s neuroticism set point. genetic effects in parents transmitted to off-
spring. That being said, research is showing
direct environmental effects on development
Comment from the earliest phases of life. McCrory and
Viding (2015) described a similar concept. In
The most recent research that I examined on the their model, childhood maltreatment constitutes
topic of early adversity is increasingly specifying a latent vulnerability involving altered threat
350 14 Early Adversity, Fetal Programming, and Getting Under the Skin

processing. Also, statistically speaking, in devel- Caspi, A., Hariri, A. R., Holmes, A., Uher, R., & Moffitt,
T. E. (2010). Genetic sensitivity to the environment:
opment, one finds both main and interaction
The case of the serotonin transporter gene and its
effects. However, in the ecology of those interac- implications for studying complex diseases and traits.
tions in real life, the complexities are of orders of American Journal of Psychiatry, 167, 509–527.
magnitude beyond what we have conceived until Caspi, A., & Shiner, R. (2011). Temperament and person-
ality. In M. Rutter, D. Bishop, D. Pine, S. Scott,
recently, and the research is pointing to fast-dif-
J. Stevenson, E. Taylor, & A. Thapar (Eds.), Rutter’s
ferentiating concepts that we are just beginning child and adolescent psychiatry (5th ed., pp. 182–
to grasp. 198). Malden, MA: Wiley.
Caspi, A., Sugden, K., Moffitt, T. E., Taylor, A., Craig,
I. W., Harrington, H., et al. (2003). Influence of life
stress on depression: Moderation by a polymorphism
References in the 5-HTT gene. Science, 301, 386–389.
Charles, S. T., Piazza, J. R., Mogle, J., Sliwinski, M. J., &
Almeida, D. M. (2013). The wear and tear of daily
Achenbach, T. M. (1991). Integrative guide for the 1991
stressors on mental health. Psychological Science, 24,
CBCL/4-18, YSR, and TRF profiles. Burlington, VT:
733–741.
University of Vermont, Department of Psychiatry.
Choi, J., Jeong, B., Rohan, M. L., Polcari, A. M., & Teicher,
Ainsworth, M. D. S., Blehar, M. C., Waters, E., & Wall, S.
M. H. (2009). Preliminary evidence for white matter
(1978). Patterns of attachment: A psychological study
tract abnormalities in young adults exposed to parental
of the strange situation. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
verbal abuse. Biological Psychiatry, 65, 227–234.
Asok, A., Bernard, K., Roth, T. L., Rosen, J. B., & Dozier,
Christian, L. M. (2015). Stress and immune function dur-
M. (2013). Parental responsiveness moderates the
ing pregnancy: An emerging focus in mind-body med-
association between early-life stress and reduced
icine. Current Directions in Psychological Science,
telomere length. Developmental and Psychopathology,
24, 3–9.
25, 577–585.
Cicchetti, D., & Rogosch, F. A. (2012). Gene x environ-
Belsky, J., Bakermans-Kranenburg, M. J., & van
ment interaction and resilience: Effects of child mal-
IJzendoorn, M. H. (2007). For better and for worse:
treatment and serotonin, corticotrophin releasing
Differential susceptibility to environmental influ-
hormone, dopamine, and oxytocin genes. Development
ences. Current Directions in Psychological Science,
and Psychopathology, 24, 411–427.
16, 300–304.
Cicchetti, D., Rogosch, F. A., Gunnar, M. R., & Toth,
Belsky, J., & Pluess, M. (2009). The nature (and nurture?)
S. L. (2010). The differential impacts of early physical
of plasticity in early human development. Perspectives
and sexual abuse and internalizing problems on day-
on Psychological Science, 4, 345–351.
time cortisol rhythm in school-aged children. Child
Biglan, A., Flay, B. R., Embry, D. D., & Sandler, I. N.
Development, 81, 252–269.
(2012). The critical role of nurturing environments for
Cicchetti, D., Rogosch, F. A., & Toth, S. L. (2006).
promotion of human well-being. American
Fostering secure attachment in infants in maltreating
Psychologist, 67, 257–271.
families through preventive interventions.
Booth-LaForce, C. (2014). Abstract. Monographs of the
Development and Psychopathology, 18, 623–649.
Society for Research in Child Development, 79,
Cicchetti, D., & Toth, S. L. (2009). The past achievements
vii–viii.
and future promises of developmental psychopathol-
Booth-LaForce, C., & Roisman, G. I. (2014). Introduction.
ogy: The coming of age of a discipline. Journal of
Monographs of the Society for Research in Child
Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 50, 16–25.
Development, 79, 1–14.
Class, Q. A., Khashan, A. S., Lichtenstein, P., Långström,
Boyce, W. T., & Ellis, B. J. (2005). Biological sensitivity
N., & D’Onofrio, B. M. (2013). Maternal stress and
to context: I. An evolutionary-developmental theory of
infant mortality: The importance of the preconception
the origins and functions of stress reactivity.
period. Psychological Science, 24, 1309–1316.
Development and Psychopathology, 17, 271–301.
Colonnesi, C., Draijer, E. M., Stams, G. J. J. M., Van der
Bryck, R. L., & Fisher, P. A. (2012). Training the brain:
Bruggen, C., Bögels, S., & Noom, M. J. (2011). The
Practical applications of neural plasticity from the
relation between insecure attachment and child anxi-
intersection of cognitive neuroscience, developmental
ety: A meta-analytic review. Journal of Clinical Child
psychology, and prevention science. American
and Adolescent Psychology, 40, 630–645.
Psychologist, 67, 87–100.
Conradt, E., Abar, B., Lester, B. M., LaGasse, L. L.,
Bryck, R. L., & Mayr, U. (2005). On the role of verbaliza-
Shankaran, S., Bada, H., et al. (2014). Cortisol reactiv-
tion during task set selection: Switching or serial order
ity to social stress as a mediator for early adversity on
control? Memory and Cognition, 33, 611–623.
risk and adaptive outcomes. Child Development, 85,
Carter, A. S., & Briggs-Gowan, M. (2006). The Infant-
2279–2298.
Toddler Social and Emotional Assessment (ITSEA).
Crone, E. A., & Elzinga, B. M. (2015). Changing brains:
San Antonio, TX: Pearson.
How longitudinal functional magnetic resonance
References 351

imaging studies can inform us about cognitive and Evans, G. W., Li, D., & Whipple, S. S. (2013). Cumulative
social-affective growth trajectories. Cognitive Science, risk and child development. Psychological Bulletin,
6, 53–63. 139, 1342–1396.
Crum, A. J., Salovey, P., & Anchor, S. (2013). Rethinking Fagundes, C. P., & Way, B. (2014). Early-life stress
stress: The role of mindsets in determining the stress and adult inflammation. Current Directions in
response. Journal of Personality and Social Psychological Science, 23, 277–283.
Psychology, 104, 716–733. Feldman, R., Singer, M., & Zagoory, O. (2010). Touch
Davies, P. T., Sturge-Apple, M. L., Cicchetti, D., & attenuates infants’ physiological reactivity to stress.
Cummings, E. M. (2007). The role of child adrenocor- Developmental Science, 13, 271–278.
tical functioning in pathways between forms of inter- Fisher, P. A., & Gunnar, M. R. (2010). Early life stress as
parental conflict and child maladjustment. a risk factor for disease in adulthood. In E. Vermetten,
Developmental Psychology, 43, 918–930. R. Lanius, & C. Pain (Eds.), The impact of early life
Del Giudice, M., Ellis, B. J., & Shirtcliff, E. A. (2011). trauma on health and disease (pp. 133–141).
The adaptive calibration model of stress responsivity. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews, 35, Fisher, P. A., Gunnar, M. R., Dozier, M., Bruce, J., &
1562–1592. Pears, K. C. (2006). Effects of therapeutic intervention
Dix, T., Meunier, L. N., Lusk, K., & Perfect, M. M. for foster children on behavior problems, caregiver
(2012). Mothers’ depressive symptoms and children’s attachment, and stress regulatory neural systems.
facial emotions: Examining the depression-inhibition Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences:
hypothesis. Development and Psychopathology, 24, Resilience in Children, 1904, 215–225.
195–210. Foland-Ross, L. C., Kircanski, K., & Gotlib, I. H. (2014).
Dumontheil, I., Roggeman, C., Ziermans, T., Peyrard- Coping with having a depressed mother: The role of
Janvid, M., Matsson, H., Kere, J., et al. (2011). stress and coping in hypothalamic-pituitary-adrenal
Influence of the COMT genotype on working memory axis dysfunction in girls at familial risk for major
and brain activity changes during development. depression. Development and Psychopathology, 26,
Biological Psychiatry, 70, 222–229. 1401–1409.
Dunn, L. M., & Markwardt, F. C., Jr. (1970). Peabody Fraley, R. C., Roisman, G. I., & Haltigan, J. D. (2013).
Individual Achievement Test. Circle Pines, MN: The legacy of early experiences in development:
American Guidance Service. Formalizing alternative models of how early experi-
Eisenberger, N. I., Master, S. L., Inagaki, T. K., Taylor, ences are carried forward over time. Developmental
S. E., Shirinyan, D., Lieberman, M. D., et al. (2011). Psychology, 49, 109–126.
Attachment figures activate a safety signal-related Frankenhuis, W. E., & de Weerth, C. (2013). Does early-
neural region and reduce pain experience. Proceedings life exposure to stress shape or impair cognition?
of the National Academy of Sciences of the United Current Directions in Psychological Science, 22,
States of America, 108, 11721–11726. 407–412.
Ellis, B. J., & Boyce, W. T. (2008). Biological sensitivity Ganzel, B. L., & Morris, P. A. (2011). Allostasis and the
to context. Current Directions in Psychological developing human brain: Explicit consideration of
Science, 17, 183–187. implicit models. Development and Psychopathology,
Ellis, B. J., Figueredo, A. J., Brumbach, B. H., & 23, 955–974.
Schlomer, G. L. (2009). Fundamental dimensions of Gee, D. G., Gabard-Durnam, L., Telzer, E. H., Humphreys,
environmental risk: The impact of harsh versus unpre- K. L., Goff, B., Shapiro, M., et al. (2014). Maternal
dictable environments on the evolution and develop- buffering of human amygdala-prefrontal circuitry dur-
ment of life history strategies. Human Nature, 20, ing childhood but not during adolescence.
204–268. Psychological Science, 25, 2067–2078.
Emerson, R. W., & Cantlon, J. F. (2014). Continuity and Gliga, T., Jones, E. J. H., Bedford, R., Charman, T., &
change in children’s longitudinal neural responses to Johnson, M. H. (2014). From early markers to neuro-
numbers. Developmental Science, 18, 314–326. developmental mechanisms of autism. Developmental
Englund, M. M., Kuo, S. I., Puig, J., & Collins, W. A. Review, 24, 189–207.
(2011). Early roots of adult competence: The signifi- Gotlib, I. H., LeMoult, J., Colich, N. L., Foland-Ross,
cance of close relationships from infancy to early L. C., Hallmayer, J., Joormann, J., et al. (2015).
adulthood. International Journal of Behavioral Telomere length and cortisol reactivity in children of
Development, 35, 490–496. depressed mothers. Molecular Psychiatry, 20,
Esbjørn, B. H., Bender, P. K., Reinholdt-Dunne, M. L., 615–620.
Munck, L. A., & Ollendick, T. H. (2012). The develop- Haeri, S., Baker, A. M., & Ruano, R. (2013). Do pregnant
ment of anxiety disorders: Considering the contribu- women with depression have a pro-inflammatory pro-
tions of attachment and emotion regulation. Clinical file? Journal of Obstetrics and Gynaecology Research,
Child and Family Psychology Review, 15, 129–143. 39, 948–952.
Evans, G. W., & Cassells, R. C. (2013). Childhood poverty, Hammen, C. (1991). Generation of stress in the course of
cumulative risk exposure, and mental health in emerg- unipolar depression. Journal of Abnormal Psychology,
ing adults. Clinical Psychological Science, 2, 287–296. 100, 555–561.
352 14 Early Adversity, Fetal Programming, and Getting Under the Skin

Hammen, C. (2006). Stress generation in depression: for major depression in women. Psychological
Reflections on origins, research, and future directions. Medicine, 34, 1475–1482.
Journal of Clinical Psychology, 62, 1065–1082. Kessel, F., & Rosenfield, P. L. (2008). Toward transdisci-
Haydon, K. C., Collins, W. A., Salvatore, J. E., Simpson, plinary research: Historical and contemporary per-
J. A., & Roisman, G. I. (2012). Shared and distinctive spectives. American Journal of Preventative Medicine,
origins and correlates of adult attachment representa- 35, S225–S234.
tions: The developmental organization of romantic Kochanska, G., & Kim, S. (2012). Toward a new under-
functioning. Child Development, 83, 1689–1702. standing of legacy of early attachments for future anti-
Heim, C., Young, L. J., Newport, D. J., Mletzko, T., social trajectories: Evidence from two longitudinal
Miller, A. H., & Nemeroff, C. B. (2009). Lower CSF studies. Development and Psychopathology, 24,
oxytocin concentrations in women with a history of 783–806.
childhood abuse. Molecular Psychiatry, 14, 954–958. Kovacs, M. (1992). The Children’s Depression Inventory
Heinrichs, M., Baumgartner, T., Kirschbaum, C., & (CDI). Toronto, ON: Multi-Health Systems.
Ehlert, U. (2003). Social support and oxytocin interact Lam, L. L., Emberly, E., Frazer, B., II, Neumann, S. M.,
to suppress cortisol and subjective responses to psy- Chen, E., Miller, G. E., et al. (2012). Factors underly-
chosocial stress. Biological Psychiatry, 54, ing variable DNA methylation in a human community
1389–1398. cohort. Proceedings of the National Academy of
Heinrichs, M., Meinlschmidt, G., Neumann, I., Wagner, Sciences of the United States of America, 109,
S., Kirschbaum, C., Ehlert, U., et al. (2001). Effects of 17253–17260.
suckling on hypothalamic-pituitary-adrenal axis Lester, B. M., & Padbury, J. F. (2009). Third pathophysi-
responses to psychosocial stress in postpartum lactat- ology of prenatal cocaine exposure. Developmental
ing women. Journal of Clinical Endocrinology and Neuroscience, 31, 23–35.
Metabolism, 86, 4798–4804. Levine, S. (2005). Stress: An historical perspective. In
Hillman, C. H., Erickson, K. I., & Kramer, A. F. (2008). T. Steckler, N. H. Kalin, & J. M. H. M. Reul (Eds.),
Be smart, exercise your heart: Exercise effects on Handbook on stress and the brain (pp. 3–23).
brain and cognition. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 9, Amsterdam, Netherlands: Elsevier Science.
58–65. Liu, R. T. (2013). Stress generation: Future directions and
Holmes, J., Gathercole, S. E., & Dunning, D. L. (2009). clinical implications. Clinical Psychology Review, 33,
Adaptive training leads to sustained enhancement of 406–416.
poor working memory in children. Developmental Liu, R. T., Choi, J. Y., Boland, E. M., Mastin, B. M., &
Science, 12, F9–F15. Alloy, L. B. (2013). Childhood abuse and stress gen-
Hostinar, C. E., & Gunnar, M. R. (2013). The develop- eration: The mediational effect of depressogenic cog-
mental effects of early life stress: An overview of cur- nitive styles. Psychiatry Research, 206, 217–222.
rent theoretical framework. Current Directions in Mackey, A. P., Hill, S. S., Stone, S. I., & Bunge, S. A.
Psychological Science, 22, 400–406. (2011). Differential effects of reasoning and speed
Hostinar, C. E., Sullivan, R. M., & Gunnar, M. R. (2014). training in children. Developmental Science, 14,
Psychobiological mechanism underlying the social 582–590.
buffering of the hypothalamic-pituitary-adrenocortical Main, M., Kaplan, N., & Cassidy, J. (1985). Security in
axis: A review of animal models and human studies infancy, childhood, and adulthood: A move to the level
across development. Psychological Bulletin, 140, of representation. In I. Bretherton & E. Waters (Eds.),
256–282. Growing points of attachment theory and research:
Jeronimus, B. F., Riese, H., Sanderman, R., & Ormel, Vol. 50: Monographs of the society for research in
J. (2014). Mutual reinforcement between neuroticism child development (1-2, Serial No. 209, pp. 66–104).
and life experiences: A five-wave, 16-year study to Boston, MA: Blackwell.
test reciprocal causation. Journal of Personality and McCrory, E. J., & Viding, E. (2015). The theory of latent
Social Psychology, 107, 751–764. vulnerability: Reconceptualizing the link between
Juster, R.-P., Bizik, G., Picard, M., Arsenault-Lapierre, childhood maltreatment and psychiatric disorder.
G., Sindi, S., Trepanier, L., et al. (2011). A transdisci- Development and Psychopathology, 27, 493–505.
plinary perspective of chronic stress in relation to psy- McEwen, B. S. (1998a). Stress, adaptation, and disease:
chopathology throughout life span development. Allostasis and allostatic load. Annals of the New York
Development and Psychopathology, 23, 725–776. Academy of Sciences, 840, 33–44.
Karbach, J., & Kray, J. (2009). How useful is executive McEwen, B. S. (1998b). Protective and damaging effects
control training? Age differences in near and far trans- of stress mediators. New England Journal of Medicine,
fer of task-switching training. Developmental Science, 338, 171–179.
12, 978–990. McEwen, B. S. (2006). Protective and damaging effects of
Kaufman, J., Birmaher, B., Brent, D. A., Ryan, N. D., & stress mediators: Central role of the brain. Dialogues
Rao, U. (2000). K-SADS-PL. Journal of American in Clinical Neuroscience, 8, 367–381.
Academy of Child Adolescent Psychiatry, 39, 1208. McEwen, B. S. (2008). Central effects of stress hormones
doi:10.1097/00004583-200010000-00002. in health and disease: Understanding the protective
Kendler, K. S., Kuhn, J. W., & Prescott, C. A. (2004). and damaging effects of stress and stress mediators.
Childhood sexual abuse, stressful life events and risk European Journal of Pharmacology, 583, 174–185.
References 353

McEwen, B. S., & Stellar, E. (1993). Stress and the indi- Puig, J., Englund, M. M., Simpson, J. A., & Collins, W. A.
vidual. Mechanisms leading to disease. Archives of (2012). Predicting adult physical illness from infant
Internal Medicine, 153, 2093–2101. attachment: A prospective longitudinal study. Health
McEwen, B. S., & Wingfield, J. C. (2003). The concept of Psychology, 32, 409–417.
allostasis in biology and biomedicine. Hormones and Quas, J. A., Yim, I. S., Oberlander, T. F., Nordstokke, D.,
Behavior, 43, 2–15. Essex, M. J., Armstrong, J. M., et al. (2014). The sym-
McGowan, P. O., Sasaki, A., D’Alessio, A. C., Dymov, S., phonic structure of childhood stress reactivity: Patterns
Labonté, B., Szyf, M., et al. (2009). Epigenetic regula- of sympathetic, parasympathetic, and adrenocortical
tion of the glucocorticoid receptor in human brain responses to psychological challenge. Development
associates with childhood abuse. Nature Neuroscience, and Psychopathology, 26, 963–982.
12, 342–348. Raby, K. L., Roisman, G. I., Fraley, R. C., & Simpson,
McWilliams, L. A., & Baily, S. J. (2010). Associations J. A. (2015). The enduring predictive significance of
between adult attachment ratings and health condi- early maternal sensitivity: Social and academic com-
tions: Evidence from the national comorbidity survey petence through age 32 years. Child Development, 86,
replication. Health Psychology, 29, 446–453. 695–705.
Mitchell, C., Hobcraft, J., McLanahan, S. S., Siegel, S. R., Ramsay, D. S., & Woods, S. C. (2014). Clarifying the
Berg, A., Brooks-Gunn, J., et al. (2014). Social disad- roles of homeostasis and allostasis in physiological
vantage, genetic sensitivity, and children’s telomere regulation. Psychological Review, 121, 225–247.
length. Proceedings of the National Academy of Rifkin-Graboi, A., Meaney, M. J., Chen, H., Bai, J.,
Sciences of the United States of America, 111, Hameed, W. B., Tint, M. T., et al. (2015). Antenatal
5944–5949. maternal anxiety predicts variations in neural struc-
Morley, T. E., & Moran, G. (2011). The origins of cogni- tures implicated in anxiety disorder in newborns.
tive vulnerability in early childhood: Mechanisms Journal of the American Academy of Child &
linking early attachment to later depression. Clinical Adolescent Psychiatry, 54, 313–321.
Psychology Review, 31, 1071–1082. Roisman, G. I., & Fraley, R. C. (2013). Developmental
Morris, M. C., Ciesla, J. A., & Garber, J. (2008). A pro- mechanisms underlying the legacy of childhood expe-
spective study of the cognitive-stress model of depres- riences. Child Development Perspectives, 7, 149–154.
sive symptoms in adolescents. Journal of Abnormal Roisman, G. I., Fraley, R. C., & Booth-LaForce, C.
Psychology, 117, 719–734. (2014). Pulling ourselves up by our bootstraps: A
National Scientific Council on the Developing Child. rejoinder to van IJzendoorn and Bakermans-
(2007). The timing and quality of early experiences Kranenburg (2014). Monographs of the Society for
combine to shape brain architecture (Working Paper Research in Child Development, 79, 168–173.
No. 5). Retrieved from http://developingchild.harvard. Romens, S. E., McDonald, J., Svaren, J., & Pollak, S. D.
edu/library/reports_and_working_papers/working_ (2015). Associations between early life stress and
papers/wp5/ gene methylation in children. Child Development, 86,
Noble, K. G., Houston, S. M., Brito, N. H., Bartsch, H., 303–309.
Kan, E., Kuperman, J. M., et al. (2015). Family Rudolph, K. D., & Flynn, M. (2007). Childhood adversity
income, parental education and brain structure in chil- and youth depression: Influence of gender and puber-
dren and adolescents. Nature Neuroscience, 18, tal status. Development and Psychopathology, 19,
773–778. 497–521.
Oldehinkel, A. J., Ormel, J., Verhulst, F. C., & Nederhof, Rutter, M. (2006). Implications of resilience concepts for
E. (2014). Childhood adversities and adolescent scientific understanding. Annals of the New York
depression: A matter of both risk and resilience. Academy of Sciences, 1094, 1–12.
Development and Psychopathology, 26, 1067–1075. Rutter, M. (2012). Resilience as a dynamic concept.
Perroud, N., Dayer, A., Piguet, C., Nallet, A., Favre, S., Development and Psychopathology, 24, 335–344.
Malafosse, A., et al. (2014). Childhood maltreatment Ruttle, P. L., Armstrong, J. M., Klein, M. H., & Essex,
and methylation of the glucocorticoid receptor gene M. J. (2014). Adolescent internalizing symptoms and
NR3C1 in bipolar disorder. British Journal of negative life events: The sensitizing effects of earlier
Psychiatry, 204, 30–35. life stress and cortisol. Development and
Picard, M., Sabiston, C. M., & McNamara, J. K. (2011). Psychopathology, 26, 1411–1422.
The need for a transdisciplinary, global health frame- Sale, A., Berardi, N., & Maffei, L. (2009). Enrich the
work. Journal of Alternative and Complementary environment to empower the brain. Trends in
Medicine, 17, 179–184. Neurosciences, 32, 233–239.
Pollak, S. D., Nelson, C. A., Schlaak, M. F., Roeber, B. J., Seeman, E., Singer, B. H., Rowe, J., Horwitz, R. I., &
Wewerka, S. S., Wiik, K. L., et al. (2010). McEwen, B. (1997). Price of adaptation – Allostatic
Neurodevelopmental effects of early deprivation in load and its health consequences. Archives of Internal
postinstitutionalized children. Child Development, 81, Medicine, 157, 2259–2268.
224–236. Shaffer, D., Fisher, P., Lucas, C. P., Dulcan, M. K., &
Price, L. H., Kao, H. T., Burgers, D. E., Carpenter, L. L., Schwab-Stone, M. E. (2000). NIMH Diagnostic
& Tyrka, A. R. (2013). Telomeres and early-life stress: Interview Schedule for Children Version IV (NIMH
An overview. Biological Psychiatry, 73, 15–23. DISC-IV): Description, differences from previous
354 14 Early Adversity, Fetal Programming, and Getting Under the Skin

versions, and reliability of some common diagnoses. Neural bases of moderation of cortisol stress responses
Journal of the American Academy of Child & by psychosocial resources. Journal of Personality and
Adolescent Psychiatry, 39, 28–38. Social Psychology, 95, 197–211.
Shonkoff, J. P., Boyce, W. T., & McEwen, B. S. (2009). Thorell, L. B., Lindqvist, S., Nutley, S. B., Bohlin, G., &
Neuroscience, molecular biology, and the childhood Klingberg, T. (2009). Training and transfer effects of
roots of health disparities: Building a new framework executive functions in preschool children.
for health promotion and disease prevention. The Developmental Science, 12, 106–113.
Journal of the American Medical Association, 301, Tibu, F., Hill, J., Sharp, H., Marshall, K., Glover, V., &
2252–2259. Pickles, A. (2014). Evidence for sex differences in
Slopen, N., Kubzansky, L. D., McLaughlin, K. A., & fetal programming of physiological stress reactivity in
Koenen, K. C. (2013). Childhood adversity and infancy. Development and Psychopathology, 26,
inflammatory processes in youth: A prospective study. 879–888.
Psychoneuroendocrinology, 38, 188–200. Tomalski, P., Moore, D. G., Ribeiro, H., Axelsson, E. L.,
Spielberger, C. D. (1983). Manual for the State-Trait Murphy, E., Karmiloff-Smith, A., et al. (2013).
Anxiety Inventory, STAI (Form Y) (‘Self-Evaluation Socioeconomic status and functional brain develop-
Questionnaire’). Palo Alto, CA: Consulting ment – associations in early infancy. Developmental
Psychologists Press. Science, 16, 676–687.
Starr, L. R., Hammen, C., Brennan, P. A., & Najman, Tominey, S. L. M., & McClelland, M. M. (2011). Red
J. M. (2012). Serotonin transporter gene as a predictor light, purple light: Findings from a randomized trial
of stress generation in depression. Journal of Abnormal using circle time games to improve behavioral self-
Psychology, 121, 810–818. regulation in preschool. Early Education and
Starr, L. R., Hammen, C., Brennan, P. A., & Najman, Development, 22, 489–519.
J. M. (2013). Relational security moderates the effect Tottenham, N., Hare, T. A., Quinn, B. T., McCarry, T.,
of serotonin transporter gene polymorphism Nurse, M., Gilhooly, T., et al. (2010). Prolonged insti-
(5-HTTLPR) on stress generation and depression tutional rearing is associated with atypically large
among adolescents. Journal of Abnormal Child amygdala volume and emotion regulation difficulties.
Psychology, 41, 379–388. Developmental Science, 113, 46–61.
Sterling, P. (2004). Principles of allostasis: Optimal Wismer Fries, A. B., Ziegler, T. E., Kurian, J. R., Jacoris,
design, predictive regulation, pathophysiology and S., & Pollak, S. D. (2005). Early experience in humans
rational therapeutics. In J. Schulkin (Ed.), Allostasis, is associated with changes in neuropeptides critical for
homeostasis, and the costs of adaptation (pp. 17–64). regulating social behavior. Proceedings of the National
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Academy of Sciences of the United States of America,
Sterling, P., & Eyer, J. (1988). Allostasis: A new paradigm 102, 17237–17240.
to explain arousal pathology. In S. Fisher & J. Reason Woodcock, R. W. (1990). Theoretical foundations of the
(Eds.), Handbook of life stress, cognition and health WJ-R measures of cognitive ability. Journal of
(pp. 629–649). New York: Wiley. Psychoeducational Assessment, 8, 231–258.
Strüber, N., Strüber, D., & Roth, G. (2014). Impact of Woodcock, R. W., & Johnson, M. B. (1989). Woodcock-
early adversity on glucocorticoid regulation and later Johnson Psycho-Educational Battery-Revised. Allen,
mental disorders. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral TX: DLM Teaching Resources.
Reviews, 38, 17–37. Young, G. (2008a). Causality and causation in law, medi-
St. Clair, M. C., Croudace, T., Dunn, V. J., Jones, P. B., cine, psychiatry, and psychology: Progression or
Herbert, J., & Goodyer, I. M. (2014). Childhood regression? Psychological Injury and Law, 1,
adversity subtypes and depressive symptoms in 161–181.
early and late adolescence. Development and Young, G. (2008b). Somatization and medically unex-
Psychopathology, 24, 1–15. plained symptoms in psychological injury: Diagnoses
Taylor, S. E., Burklund, L. J., Eisenberger, N. I., Lehman, and dynamics. Psychological Injury and Law, 1,
B. J., Hilmert, C. J., & Lieberman, M. D. (2008). 224–242.
Connecting the Social Dots
15

approach that social behavior of the empathic/


Chapter Introduction prosocial type is biologically mediated. The evo-
lutionary roots of social behavior suggest nonhu-
Social connection helps distinguish the human man primate origins to the behavior. However,
species. Moreover, the mechanisms involved cultural evolution also appears involved.
range from biological to environmental and to Moreover, developmentally, the evidence indi-
self, as well as other psychological ones. A prom- cates that the quality of early morality surpasses
inent behavior complex in social connection that of chimpanzees (Tomasello & Vaish, 2013).
relates to empathy and prosocial behavior. The work of Hamlin (2014a, 2014b) on early
Models of the development of social behavior, helping behavior shows that, in the first few
including of the empathic, prosocial type, impli- months of life, infants develop context-depen-
cate either (a) innate factors and early onset or (b) dent social evaluations about helpers/givers/nice
more gradual development, with those in the lat- puppets and about hindering/mean/taking ones.
ter camp maintaining that the studies in infancy For the second year of life, Waters, West, and
implicating innate factors are over-interpreted. Mendes (2014) and Cirelli, Einarson, and Trainor
However, the bulk of the evidence supports the (2014) demonstrated caregiver/parent intersyn-
view of a rapid onset of empathic/prosocial chrony factors, and Paulus (2014) described vari-
behavior early in life. That being said, the degree ous models of prosocial behavior, while opting
to which this constitutes core, innate primitives for a multifaceted view. Govrin’s (2014) approach
in this regard needs further verification. appears similar.
Moreover, there has been a paucity of research Others have developed models related to inter-
querying whether these acquisitions reflect stage subjectivity. Legerstee (2013) described an early
like acquisitions, which would constitute a com- affective attunement through an affective sharing
promise view to the debate, despite workers process. Davidov, Zahn-Waxler, Roth-Hanania,
relating this area of research to that of Piaget. and Knafo (2013) described an early-developing
Feldman’s (2014) work on early biobehav- sympathy and social connectedness. Despite these
ioral synchrony addresses the early precursors to models supporting an early-developing view of
later social behavior. In this regard, she found infant empathy/prosociality, some have queried
both biological and parental influences. Other the validity of the research and models (e.g., Dahl,
groups are specifying the neural and brain bases 2014; Tafreshi, Thompson, & Racine, 2014).
for social behavior (e.g., Anderson & Beauchamp, Work with adults emphasizes the core capac-
2012a, 2012b). The embodiment model includes ity for positive sociality, such as in social
the mirror neuron system, and it is integral to the cooperation and politics and the public good.

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 355


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_15
356 15 Connecting the Social Dots

The narratives in self-development that people perspectives (e.g., embodiment) but also inte-
create are fundamental to adult identity grated ones. The section after the next one is on
(McAdams, 2013), and so the stories that we tell evolution, which also emphasizes the biological
about ourselves can come to include the innate perspective. The section that follows the one on
goodness early in life that philosophers like evolution is on culture, which brings back the
Descartes had described. Locke’s blank slate may integrated perspective.
have met its match in contemporary research in
that empathy/prosociality might be prepared.
However, the ephemeral degree to which this Biobehavioral Synchrony
takes place, that it can be easily derailed by lack
of support or its opposite attitude, and the impor- Mikulincer and Shaver (2014a) traced mecha-
tance of environmental input in sustaining it all nisms of social behavior from brain to group
speak to the standard biology × environment behavior. Briefly, the neural basis of social bonds
interaction for understanding early empathy/pro- lies in the collection of factors of neuropeptide
sociality. Nevertheless, as with many areas in the hormones, such as oxytocin, neural circuitry of
present book, the typical Nature and Nurture view primary emotions, the mesolimbic dopamine sys-
of behavioral causality is deemed insufficient to tem, the mirror neuron system, and other bases in
capture the full range of influences on it, which is evolution and neuroscience (Mikulincer &
especially the case for empathy/prosociality. Shaver, 2014b). Developmentally, critical mech-
Without the personal choices made to actively anisms include infant attachment, biobehavioral
engage in the behavior out of free will, it will be synchrony, and parental factors. These mecha-
continually subject to the passive influences of nisms extend into romantic and couple relation-
changing biology and environment instead of ships in adults and into social groups.
being bootstrapped by the powerful active forces Feldman (2014) reported results linking
in the agency of the person him- or herself. biobehavioral synchrony to genetics and to the
The chapter concludes by showing that the lit- brain. In this regard, higher levels of parent–
erature review on changes in empathic and pro- infant gaze synchrony during parent–infant inter-
social behavior in infancy fits Piaget’s model of actions were associated with higher levels of
six sensorimotor substages in infancy, with minor oxytocin (in plasma) and also with the low-risk
adjustments. My own Neo-Piagetian model CD38 allele (Feldman et al., 2012). Other
(Young, 2011) is quite similar to Piaget’s for the research found biobehavioral synchrony in
infancy period, so that the empirical findings maternal–infant heart rate synchrony. Feldman,
reviewed closely fit my model, as well. Magori-Cohen, Galili, Singer, and Louzoun
(2011) found that, in maternal face-to-face inter-
actions with 3-month-olds, the heart rates of
Biology mother and infant were synchronized within lags
of less than one second. The same synchrony was
Undoubtedly, the environmental contributions to not found with stranger–infant interactions.
social development and behavior are pervasive, Moreover, the synchrony was more evident dur-
so for balance the chapter starts with elucidation ing epochs of affective and vocal synchrony.
of all things biological in this regard, from brain Feldman (2014) concluded that biobehavioral
to evolution. Development, however, is dynamic synchrony early in life is fine-turned. The infant’s
in its integration of these and other factors, so early subjective experiences become transformed
that emphasis on either biology or environment into interpersonal dyadic activity that changes
in the equation that governs social development the subjective into the intersubjective. The latter
is bound to be incomplete. The following section extends into intersubjective, shared brain activity
on relevant influences on social connection and other bodily (e.g., heart rate) processes. For
highlights not only the biological and related further description of Feldman’s work, see
Biology 357

Feldman (2015). In that article, not only does she Brain


describe biobehavioral synchrony, but also she
relates it to the oxytocin system and critical/sen- Introduction Brain scans such as fMRI (func-
sitive period. tional magnetic resonance imaging) are helping
elucidate the functional activity of brain regions
and their circuits that are associated with socially
Activation/Inhibition Coordination relevant behavior, such as prosocial behavior and
empathy, not only in adults but also in children.
Tucker, Poulsen, and Luu (2015) related two This research is too preliminary to establish the
models of developmental learning to possible exact regions and circuits involved, and different
associated later developmental disturbances. workers provide different regions, which vary, as
Specifically, in externalizing learning, neural well, with the behaviors examined, the tasks
representations are highly responsive to environ- used, the populations studied, their ages, and the
mental influences, and this type of learning particular scan methodology used. Therefore, I
might facilitate the development of externalizing refrain from trying to integrate this diverse and
behavior, depending on the course involved. The preliminary work, but do summarize it in detail.
learning is associated with dorsal limbic circuits
(cingulate, septal, lateral hypothalamic, hippo- The Prosocial/Empathic Brain Chakroff and
campal, ventral striatic), and is regulated partly Young (2014) referred to the brain as “prosocial.”
by locus coeruleus norepinephrine and other pro- They related the brain regions involved in social
jection systems (brain stem raphe nucleus sero- cognition (mind perception); processing conflict
tonin). The internalizing learning system serves and discomfort (unpleasant states in others); and
to separate attention and self-regulation from reward processing (reward anticipation) to proso-
immediate environmental influences, especially cial behavior (and sentiments), as well. These
if there is avoidance and threat. The learning is include, respectively, the temporoparietal junction,
associated with ventral limbic circuits (anterior precuneus, and medial prefrontal cortex (mPFC);
temporal and orbital cortex, extended amygdala, anterior cingulate cortex (ACC) and anterior insula
dorsal striatal, mediodorsal thalamic) and is self- (AI); and the ventral striatum and ventral mPFC.
regulated in part by ventral tegmental dopamine
and forebrain acetylcholine projections. This Some of the research that they cited in support
type of learning might facilitate internalizing of the circuitry of the prosocial brain that they
behavioral disturbance, depending on develop- described included the following. In fMRI stud-
mental course. ies, Rameson, Morelli, and Liberman (2012)
Developmentally, the external learning sys- found that both empathy and self-report of help-
tem predominates, at first, and then the internal- ing behavior were associated with greater activ-
izing one increasingly balances it, but at the cost ity in the mPFC and the ACC. Masten, Morelli,
of lesser flexibility. Neural stability controls in and Eisenberger (2011) related prosocial (e.g.,
the learning at issue include the balancing of consoling) content of emails to activity in the
excitatory and inhibitory processes. dorsal mPFC and the right AI. Waytz, Zaki, and
Feldman (2015) concurred that early develop- Mitchell (2012) found that prosocial behavior
ment involves a balancing of activation and inhi- (e.g., helping in a tedious task) was related to
bition processes. In critical periods, their activity in the dorsal mPFC.
transition involves inhibitory mechanisms related Decety and Howard (2014) described brain
to GABAergic processes. Generally, the neuro- responses to someone else being in distress. For the
biological mechanisms in critical/sensitive peri- adult, a meta-analysis by Lamm, Decety, and Singer
ods involve change in “balance of excitation” to (2011) integrated research on brain imaging while
inhibition. adults are exposed to stimuli about someone else
358 15 Connecting the Social Dots

expressing pain or distress. The neural network involved are not unique to moral cognition.
found associated with when another person is Developmentally, moral thinking depends on an
expressing pain or distress included the posterior emotional learning system and another one associ-
portion of the insula, the amygdala, and the medial ated with decision-making related to reinforcement
orbitofrontal cortex. For Decety and Howard (2014), expectations (mediated by the amygdala and ven-
frontalization takes place over development in cog- tromedial prefrontal cortex, respectively; Blair &
nitive control and response inhibition related to Fowler, 2008).
brain responses in the perception of another’s dis- As for the neuroscience of empathy, Singer and
tress (e.g., Decety & Michalska, 2010). Hein (2012) presented a model that differentiated it
As for brain circuits underlying moral cognition, from compassion, emotional contagion, and theory
Decety and Howard (2014) specified associations of mind (see Fig. 15.1). Some of the brain regions
with the orbitofrontal cortex, anterior cingulate cor- involved include the medial prefrontal cortex, the
tex, amygdala, ventromedial prefrontal cortex, superior temporal sulcus, and the temporoparietal
medial prefrontal cortex, and posterior superior junction (see Table 15.1).
temporal sulcus. They noted that the circuits

Compassion
(Sympathy)

Empathy
Relatedness Level

Emotional contagion

Theory of Mind

Development
Self-Other
Distinction

Fig. 15.1 Social relating in evolution: based on emo- not one’s own emotions—“Feeling as the other.”
tional contagion, empathy, compassion, and theory of Emotional contagion: emotions are passed from one per-
mind. The figure shows the association between related- son to another; affected individuals are not aware that
ness and development as drivers in evolution. Compassion: these emotions originate from others. Theory of mind:
a feeling of concern for the other and the wish to increase (cognitive perspective taking, mentalizing) cognitive
the other’s welfare—“Feeling for the other.” Empathy: inference about the other’s mental state. Adapted from
emotions of the other are shared; one knows that they are Singer and Hein (2012)
Biology 359

Table 15.1 Brain regions associated with understanding uncertainty, and conflict. Greene (2007) has asso-
others/social relating
ciated the vmPFC with more emotion-based
Theory of mind Empathy moral judgments and less so with more rational,
Medial prefrontal cortex Anterior cingulate cortex utilitarian moral judgments. However, Taber-
Temporal poles Anterior insula Thomas and Tranel (2012) qualified this dual
Superior temporal sulcus Secondary somatosensory process model into a more integrative “emotion-
cortex
reasoning” perspective of moral affect and cogni-
Temporoparietal junction –
tion. Also, they described neural systems theory
Adapted from Singer and Hein (2012)
of mind/face processing and basic motivational/
emotional processes.
Brain, Cognitive, and Social As for the socialization of social competence
in terms of the SOCIAL model, Root, Hastings,
Anderson and Beauchamp (2012b) presented a and Maxwell (2012) emphasized the parental
model in developmental neuroscience that helps role (e.g., according to attachment theory, sys-
understand social functioning in childhood (see tems theory). For biological influences, among
also Beauchamp & Anderson, 2010). The model others, they referred to the diathesis-stress model
is referred to as the sociocognitive integration of (Beck, 1967, 1983), the Gene × Environment
abilities model (SOCIAL), and it is a biopsycho- interaction (G × E) model (Caspi et al., 2003),
social one that is developmental (see Fig. 15.2). and the differential susceptibility model (e.g.,
The model integrates social cognition, com- Belsky & Fearon, 2002; Belsky & Pluess, 2009;
munication, and attention/executive function Ellis & Boyce, 2008; Ellis, Boyce, Belsky,
with brain development and internal and external Bakermans-Kranenburg, & van IJzendoorn,
factors toward the development of social skills, 2011; Obradović, Bush, Stamperdahl, Adler, &
such as adjustment, competence, and participa- Boyce, 2010).
tion. The neural bases involved relate to the pre- About their own research, Root et al. (2012)
frontal and orbitofrontal cortex, in particular. reported that Hastings and De (2008) conducted
The model is informed by the somatic marker a study of emotional socialization and parasym-
hypothesis and research on the bilateral pathetic control that supported the diathesis-
ventromedial prefrontal cortex (vmPFC; Taber- stress model. Hastings et al. (2008) reported
Thomas & Tranel, 2012). The former integrates similar results supportive of the differential sus-
basic motivational, affective, complex reasoning, ceptibility model. Hastings et al. (2011) also
and action, including in the sociomoral domain found results supportive of this model, this time
(Damasio, 1994, 1995; Damasio, Anderson, & with salivary cortisol levels to assess adrenocor-
Tranel, 2011; Damasio, Tranel, & Damasio, tical functioning.
1998). The vmPFC is essential for reactivating Yeates et al. (2012) presented a complemen-
emotional states that bear on decision-making, tary model to the SOCIAL one for social compe-
e.g., in selecting adaptive behavior, through its tence in developmental brain disorder (after
interactions with subcortical and cortical struc- Yeates et al., 2007; see Fig. 15.3). In their model,
tures. In doing so, “somatic markers” are acti- the social competence or adjustment outcomes of
vated as emotional stamps in initial learning self-perception and perception of others relate to
associated with rewarding or punishing responses social information processing, social interaction
of options chosen. In this sense, somatic markers style, and social environmental factors, aside
constitute learned anticipations of emotional from the brain insult and abnormalities and risk/
experiences associated with future choices resilience that might be involved.
(Bechara & Damasio, 2005). In this regard, About the brain regions and structures involved
Thomas, Croft, and Tranel (2011) found that the in social cognition, Yeates et al. (2012) provided an
vmPFC is critical for integrating emotions and extensive list (see Table 15.2). They noted that most
sociomoral cognition in cases of ambiguity, of the regions/structures are involved in multiple
360 15 Connecting the Social Dots

Fig. 15.2 The


Socio-cognitive Brain development/ integrity
Integration of Abilities
Model. The SOCIAL
model relates brain,
social skills, and other
factors in social- Attention/
cognitive function. Executive function
Adapted from Anderson
and Beauchamp
(2012b), based on
Beauchamp and
Anderson (2010) SOCIAL SKILLS
Communication

Social cognition

Internal (e.g., self) / external (e.g., familial) factors

social functions, and most specific functions draw implicit and body-based, and not just linguistic.
on multiple regions/structures. They noted a Mentalizing, therefore, is implicit and relies on
strong overlap in cognitive/executive and social- observable bodily actions. Social cognition is
cognitive/emotional functioning. They noted the best conceived as embodied (Gallese, 2006), and
hemispheric asymmetries involved, especially is adjustable and mutual.
that the left frontal regions are approach-related in
function and the right withdrawal-related/disin- The authors’ team developed a parental
hibitory (Davidson, 1992; Fox, 1994; Fox et al., embodied mentalizing coding system. Using it,
1995; Powell & Voeller, 2004). they showed that, when measured at 6 months,
Max (2012) also contributed an applied perspec- parental embodied mentalizing predicted infant
tive to the SOCIAL model (see Fig. 15.4). In their attachment security at 15 months (Shai & Fonagy,
model, behavioral and psychiatric symptoms are 2014), even after controlling for the more tradi-
influenced by internal–external factors, attention/ tional measure of maternal sensitivity. Moreover,
executive ones, and social skills/function, with an it predicted 54-month-old social skills/compe-
important mechanism related to approach-avoid- tence and psychological problems (internalizing
ance regulation (e.g., Sharp et al., 2011). and externalizing).
Shai and Fonagy (2014) concluded that paren-
tal embodied mentalizing is a meaningful con-
Embodiment cept and reveals how parent–infant interactions
involve the entire body and not just the head or
Supportive Shai and Fonagy (2014) referred to face. For example, their coding system for it
the parent–infant dance and how parental embod- includes personal and interpersonal space, kines-
ied mentalizing helps orchestrate this interaction. thetics in movement quality, and self- and other-
Interactions between parent and infant are regulation of distress and arousal.
Biology 361

Insult -related
risk and resilience factors
Type of insult
Severity of insult
Regional brain abnormalities

Cognitive/
executive Affiliative
function
Self-perception

Social
problem solving Aggressive

Perception of
other
Social/
affective Withdrawn
function

Social information processing Social interaction Social adjustment

Parenting style
Family functioning
Socioeconomic status

Non-insult-related
risk and resilience factors

Fig. 15.3 An integrative, heuristic model of social compe- integration of social neuroscience and developmental psy-
tence in children with brain disorder. The model is based chology by Yeates, K. O., Bigler, E. D., Gerhardt, C. A.,
on the SOCIAL one and integrates social information pro- Rubin, K. H., Stancin, T., Taylor, H. G., & Vannatta, K. in
cessing/interaction/adjustment with brain insult/abnormal- Developmental social neuroscience and childhood brain
ities/disorder and other factors. Adopted with permission insult: Theory and practice by V. Anderson & M. H.
of Guilford Press. Theoretical approaches to understand- Beauchamp, Copyright 2012, reproduced with permission
ing social function in childhood brain insults: toward the of Guilford Press. [Figure 10.1, Page 210]

Nonsupportive The demonstration that neo- Lodder, Rotteveel, and van Elk (2014) cast
nates can imitate has been controversial (Meltzoff doubt on claims that neonatal imitation is innate.
& Moore, 1997). The study involved showed that Their review found that only one behavior
newborns can imitate mouth movements such as (tongue protrusion) might show consistent results
tongue protrusion and mouth opening. The in these regards. Moreover, the imitation of this
authors offered a nativist account of the early behavior might not reflect neonatal imitation, per
imitation, relating it to proprioceptive, kines- se. Therefore, the concept of nativist enactivists,
thetic feedback mechanisms involving the devel- that infants possess non-mentalistic, embodied
opment of early maps of body movement in intersubjective understanding, does not meet the
relation to supramodal perception. However, the empirical test. More likely, early imitation
research has not always been replicated and alter- reflects learning through social interaction and is
native interpretations rely on simpler mecha- neither general nor innate. The data support a
nisms, such as stimulus–response ones related to point of view for this area that involves “empiri-
oral behavior. cal enactivism.”
362 15 Connecting the Social Dots

Table 15.2 Brain structures and social cognition


Brain structure or region Social/affective and cognitive/executive functions
Temporoparietal junction Representation of emotional response
Viewing others’ actions
Fusiform gyrus Face perception
Superior temporal gyrus Representation of perceived action
Face perception
Perception of gaze direction
Perception of biological motion
Amygdala Motivational evaluation
Self-regulation
Emotional processing
Gaze discrimination
Linking internal somatic states and external stimuli
Ventral striatum Motivational evaluation
Self-regulation
Linking internal somatic states and external stimuli
Hippocampus and temporal poles Modulation of cognition
Memory for personal experiences
Emotional memory retrieval
Basal forebrain Modulation of cognition
Cingulate cortex Modulation of cognition
Error monitoring
Emotion processing
Theory of mind
Orbitofrontal cortex Motivational evaluation
Self-regulation
Theory of mind
Medial frontal cortex Theory of mind
Action monitoring
Emotional regulation
Emotional responses to socially relevant stimuli
Monitoring of outcomes associated with punishment and reward
Dorsolateral frontal cortex Cognitive executive functions
Working memory
Adopted with permission of Guilford Press. Theoretical approaches to understanding social function in child-
hood brain insults: Toward the integration of social neuroscience and developmental psychology by Yeates,
K. O., Bigler, E. D., Gerhardt, C. A., Rubin, K. H., Stancin, T., Taylor, H. G., & Vannatta, K. in Developmental
social neuroscience and childhood brain insult: Theory and practice by V. Anderson & M. H. Beauchamp,
Copyright 2012, reproduced with permission of Guilford Press. [Table 10.1, Page 215]

Zmyj and Buttelmann (2014) proposed an inte- action. Also, infants are capable of early imitation
grative model of imitation infancy that accommo- even if it might not be in the neonatal period
dated the opposing views that it takes place (a) due (Meltzoff, 2007). Multiple researchers are refer-
to the similarity between the infant’s and model’s ring to mirror neurons in this regard.
body posture and the elicitation of action effects
(e.g., Paulus, Hunnius, Vissers, & Bekkering, Mirror Neurons Fogassi and Rizzolatti (2013)
2011a, 2011b), or (b) due to a rational evaluation described the mirror neuron mechanism as the
of the observed action (e.g., Gergely, Bekkering, neurophysiological basis for unifying action per-
& Király, 2002). In the integrated model of Zmyj ception and action execution. These neurons
and Buttelmann (2014), imitation in infancy is reside in the parieto-frontal mirror system or net-
enabled by the perception of motor resonance and, work. Originally, they were demonstrated to func-
then, is guided by rational evaluation of modeled tion in the ventral premotor cortex of the macaque
Biology 363

BEHAVIORAL/
PSYCHIATRIC
SYMPTOMS/ DISORDERS

INTERNAL/ ATTENTION/
EXTERNAL EXECUTIVE
FACTORS FUNCTION

COMMUNICATIVE SOCIAL
FUNCTION SKILLS/
FUNCTION

SOCIO-
BRAIN EMOTIONAL
DEVELOPMENT/ FUNCTION
INTEGRITY

Fig. 15.4 The SOCIAL model applied to mental symptoms/disorders. Behavioral and psychiatric symptoms are con-
tributors and outcomes of the SOCIAL model the other components. Adapted from Max (2012)

monkey. Mirror neurons show congruence Cook, Bird, Catmur, Press, and Heyes (2014)
between visual and motor responses, matching offered an account of mirror neurons that
the goal of an observed motor act and the goal of involves associative learning rather than a
an executed one. They might respond equally to “richer,” more advanced action understanding
seeing food grasped and grasping it, for example. and sociocognition. Mirror neurons are adapted
Recently, mirror neurons for eye movements have to encode the multiple correlated sensorimotor
been found in the lateral intraparietal area. Other experiences that are prevalent in the develop-
neurons encode body-directed rather than object- mental environment. These experiences derive
directed motor acts, further cementing “under- from “lean” factors, such as self-observation,
standing” of others. The mirror system has been being imitated (and being rewarded for imita-
found to have other areas associated with it (e.g., tion), and the resulting correlations in kines-
middle temporal cortex). The authors showed that thetic and proprioceptive as well as sensory
the “intention” to realize a particular motor goal is experiences in isomorphic observed and exe-
represented “directly” by “dedicated” “chained” cuted movements (per contra, for richer inter-
neuronal networks in the motor system. pretations of mirror neuron function, for
Developmentally, Fogassi and Rizzolatti example, see Rizzolatti, 2014).
(2013) described that as soon as a motor Cannon et al. (2016) found evidence for a neu-
sequence is executed, the entire motor chain ral mirror system in 9-month-olds. They mea-
implicated is activated (Cattaneo et al., 2007). sured in the mu frequency band (6–9 Hz)
EMG (electromyography) activity of the mylo- event-related desynchronization (ERD) from
hyoid muscle (MH; involved in mouth opening) electroencephalogram (EEG) recording during
was recorded during children’s grasping for reaching events (scalp electrodes over motor
either eating or placing (in a container) or to regions). The infants both reached for toys and
observations of the same. Reaching even before watched an experimenter reach for toys. Reaching
contact activated MH activity increase in the competence was measured for latency to reach,
condition of reaching for eating, whether self- reach errors, hand preshaping, and bimanual
conducted or observed, but not in the condition reaches. Reaching/grasping competence (espe-
of reaching for placement. cially speed) was associated with ERD. Also, the
364 15 Connecting the Social Dots

more the reaching was competent, the greater For Tomasello and Vaish (2013), morality
was the ERD while observing the experimenter serves as a counterbalance to human selfishness.
reach/grasp. Its main function is to promote cooperation either
As for adults, Michael et al. (2014) supported by suppressing self-interest for helping/sharing
a differentiated model of the mirror neuron sys- or by equating personal self-interest with that of
tem (MNS) as playing a causal role in action others (in reciprocity, justice, equity, norm-
understanding (identifying the goals/underlying following, and norm-enforcement).
intentions of movements). They used continuous Great apes have been found to help and share,
theta-burst stimulation over the premotor cortex, but only in situations of low cost or if reciprocity
which serves to inhibit tissue excitability. The is a realistic outcome. They collaborate, but not
stimulation was applied over the subjects’ pre- with an overarching attitude, except for some
motor hand or lip areas. Then, the participants groups in some circumstances. To the contrary,
completed a pantomime recognition task; half of they socialize especially in terms of dominance
the trials involved pantomimed hand actions and hierarchies.
half mouth ones. Showing a different pattern, human society
The results were consistent with a model of exhibits critical cooperative social organization
distinct components of action understanding in in at least six major spheres. These include food
the prefrontal motor cortex (PMC), part of the procurement (subsistence), socially-sanctioned
MNS. Hand and lip area stimulation reduced property-ownership, designation, child care,
accurate recognition of observed, pantomimed teaching, politics, and norm creation. According
hand and mouth action, respectively. The authors to Tomasello and Vaish (2013), these social
concluded that somatically organized regions of behaviors evolved in two major steps. First, our
the PMC contribute differentially to the causality ancestors became collaborative foragers. Joint
of action understanding. The mechanisms for success assured self-interest needs, so that help-
action understanding and action production over- ing others in trouble served self-interest.
lap. [For a recent review of social cognition from Controlling cheating in interdependent groups
the perspective of embodiment and mirror neu- facilitated joint and thus personal success, as
rons, see Uithol and Gallese (2015). It concerns well. The morality that evolved, therefore, was
the emotional component compared to the action “joint.” In the second phase of evolution of coop-
one, in particular.] eration and morality in our ancestors, intergroup
competition (present when modern humans first
evolved) accelerated motivation to collaborate
Evolution and to participate in group life. Individuals had to
conform to a “group mindedness” (e.g., in tribes).
Nonhuman Primates Norms that were created (to follow and to control
others) were impersonal and agent-neutral.
Model Tomasello and Vaish (2013) explored the Morality became “collective.”
origin of cooperation and morality by comparing Vaish and Tomasello (2014) further developed
human evolution, nonhuman primate findings, their theoretical model on the evolution and early
and human development for these behavioral ontogeny of cooperation and morality. They
dimensions. The authors developed a general described their model as the “interdependence”
two-step sequence applicable to human evolution hypothesis because, evolutionarily, our human
and child development, in particular. First, ancestors became interdependent in collaborative
individuals express sympathy or fairness to spe- foraging or in their mutualistic collaboration (they
cific others in mutualistic, prosocial interaction. were “forced” to by ecological change; good
Then, they follow and enforce group-wide social cooperators were “advantaged.” I would add that
norms in the larger world. Respectively, these they were “selected”). In a second evolutionary
concepts refer to second-person morality and step, emerging contemporary humans increased
agent-neutral morality. their collaborative skills and motivations related
Evolution 365

to living in groups, in general. They developed 2012a for 18-month-olds). Other research with
“group mindedness.” In this regard, note that I 18-month-olds showed they could direct people
refer to adult though as “collective intelligence” to the correct location of a sought object when
(Young, 2011). the target person had a mistaken belief about its
Herrmann, Misch, Hernandez-Lloreda, and location (Knudsen & Liszkowski, 2012b). At this
Tomasello (2015) demonstrated that the develop- age, they would fetch an object from the correct
ment of self-control from 3 to 6 years of age location when a target person had a mistaken
includes comparable skills not found in chimpan- belief it was in a box and had struggled to open it.
zees at the latter age. They gave six ecologically- At 2 years, children would return an object to a
valid tasks on self-control to both human and target person who had not ever noticed it had
chimpanzee subjects. There were two tasks in rolled away (Warneken, 2013). At 3 years, chil-
each of three categories: reactivity (approach- dren would give a target person a functioning
avoidance in situations of novelty or uncertainty); object instead of a nonfunctioning one when the
inhibitory control (inhibit a prepotent response latter had been requested (e.g., in a method using
for immediate gratification or for a just-learned a cup with a hole in it; Martin & Olson, 2013).
behavior when the task demands were changed
slightly); and attentional control (focus on a Fletcher, Simpson, Campbell, and Overall
problem having attractive distractions or repeated (2015) proposed that the evolution of human
failures). social intelligence and cooperative skills had
The results showed that the 6-year-olds were been facilitated by the prohominin propensity for
distinguished both from the 3-year-olds and from pair bonding, engaging in romantic love to solid-
chimpanzees in controlling their impulses. For ify the pair bonding, and their associated massive
example, they could better resist the impulse for investment in child rearing. For example, long
immediate gratification in order to get a later term monogamy is associated across species with
reward; they could better resist the impulse to a larger brain. Homo erectus appears to have
repeat a previously successful action that had lived in small groups centered on monogamous
become ineffective; they could better resist pair bonds and cooperative breeding. Our
attending to distracting noises while engaging in stretched development gives us the large window
problem-solving; and they could better persist in needed for our complex culture, and romantic
light of repeated task failure. love and long term pair-bonding have accelerated
The authors concluded that advances in evolutionarily this acquisition.
humans’ self-control skills take place at an age In terms of evolutionary mechanisms influenc-
consistent with the start of formal schooling. I ing human altruism, Kurzban, Burton-Chellew, and
maintain that the results of this study on self- and West (2015) referred to natural selection, inclusive
impulse-control address the question of human fitness, kin selection, reciprocity, indirect reciproc-
exceptionality, for example, in terms of advances ity, and the like. They considered group selection in
in Neo-Piagetian thought into the stage of con- the multilevel selection approach (Wilson, 1975) as
crete operations (Young, 2011) and beyond (e.g., a conceptualization of evolutionary dynamics in the
adolescent abstract formal and adult collective same way as kin selection. Both approaches (group,
intelligence thought). kin selection) find that cooperation is promoted by
the behavior resulting in increased group benefits
Others Warneken’s (2015) review of early pro- and reduced individual costs.
social behavior supported a view that it has evo- de Waal (2012), who works with primates, pre-
lutionary advantages, for example, preparing for sented a hard-wired model of empathy and imita-
participating in family chores as of 3 years of tion. Empathy activates an emotional state
age. Some of the research cited includes studies through a “perception-action mechanism” (PAM).
on 12-month-olds warning not to reach into a The “other” in a social exchange shares the
container having an aversive object (Knudsen & “same” PAM, leading to imitation and other social
Liszkowski, 2013; also Knudsen & Liszkowski, intelligence behavior. The model is presented in
366 15 Connecting the Social Dots

True imitation, Learning Perspective-


emulation taking, targeted
helping

Increased Self-Other Distinction


Less Hard-wired Socio-affective

PAM Sympathetic
Coordination, concern,
shared goals consolation

Base
Emotional
Motor mimicry [Prefrontal] contagion

Imitation Empathy

Fig. 15.5 Social relating in evolution: subsumed cores. figure (imitation), it starts with motor mimicry, and then
Empathy (at right) induces an emotional state in the sub- coordination, shared goals, imitation, and emulation. The
ject similar to that of the object. The perception-action person’s more recent evolutionary acquisitions depend
mechanism (PAM) is at its core. The figure’s outer layers both on learning and on prefrontal functioning, but they
(e.g., sympathetic concern, perspective taking) build on a still are fundamentally linked to the inner core. Adapted
hard-wired socio-affective base. As for the left side of the from de Waal (2012)

Fig. 15.5. de Waal and Ferrari (2012) argued for a can solve problems only at the level of the whole.
neuroscientific approach to mind in primates. Also, conscious attention reflects a higher-order
Ferrari and Fogassi (2012) described the evolu- behavioral entity beyond the activity of the indi-
tion of the mirror neuron system. vidual neurons involved. Groups are considered in
For an evolutionary perspective on cognition, terms of the differentiated roles of individuals.
motivation, and social behavior consult Cosmides Classic multilevel selection theory (Wilson, 2014)
and Tooby (2013). Their evolutionary psychol- emphasizes less these aspects of cultural group
ogy perspective includes discussion of game activity. The approach by Smaldino has extended
theory, cooperation, and detection of cheaters. multilevel selection to the point that it is equiva-
Granted, knowledge of evolution can inform lent to the approach of inclusive fitness.
social psychology, but a developmental perspec- Kesebir (2012) proposed a systems account of
tive also is needed, and it should be one that cov- human social behavior. He applied the concept of
ers the lifespan. “superorganism” derived from work with bees
(Hölldobler & Wilson, 2009) to the human case.
Humans appeared to possess all the properties of
Culture a superorganism, such as in communication,
unity of action, low levels of heritability, egali-
For examination of the concept of cultural evolu- tarianism, and collective conflict resolution.
tion, exclusive of its interaction with biological Henrich (2011) related the work on cultural
evolution, see Kemp and Mesoudi (2014). They learning to gene–culture co-evolutionary theory
described the concept of “cultural group selec- (Boyd & Richerson, 1985). Cultural learning
tion.” In the end, Darwinian theory can explain provides adaptations that constitute a second
human culture and serve to synthesize all the means of adaptive transmission, because it can
social sciences (Mesoudi, 2011). alter both the physical and social environments in
Smaldino (2014a, 2014b) has developed a which reproducing phenotypes function (with
model of cultural evolution that considers group- their characteristics often underpinned by their
level traits as emergent. For example, a bee colony genotypes to a degree). He cited the example of
Development 367

how cooked food became a selective force Development


through the physical/physiological changes it
permitted, leading to more energy available for Models
“brain building” (Wrangham, 2009). Henrich
(2011) proposed that over-imitation might have Nativist
evolved not only to help acquire information but In their edited book, Mikulincer and Shaver (2012)
also to learn social norms, which are crucial to included chapters on the development of moral
social integration (e.g., rituals, etiquette), and to and related behavior that covered the range of bio-
keeping one’s reputation. logical, environmental, and cognitive factors as
Nielsen (2012) supported the role of imitation causes. For example, Bloom (2012) examined the
in cultural evolution, but also, he valued the role nativist approach to the development of morality.
of pretend play. Fogarty, Strimling, and Laland He argued that we are born with an “innate and
(2011) pointed out the parallel importance of universal” moral evaluation system. As young as 3
teaching and imitation, arguing that the latter is months of age, infants prefer to look at prosocial
“extremely rare” in other animals. Dean, Kendal, characters (Hamlin, Wynn, & Bloom, 2010).
Schapiro, Thierry, and Laland (2012) added that, Jensen, Vaish, and Schmidt (2014) considered
among the suite of (a) sociocognitive and (b) that humans are unique in their ability to cooper-
teaching skills that are unique to humans, are ate with nonkin. Infants appear automatically
(a) imitation of actual actions made by others and attuned to others (Geangu, Benga, Stahl, &
(b) verbal instruction, respectively. Striano, 2010). Even in the first year, infants can
Developmentally, Hopper, Marshall-Pescini, express empathy (Rochat, 2003). They express
and Whiten (2012) described social learning and concern for distressed victims, as inferred from
culture in children and chimpanzees. Table 15.3 their nonverbal behavior (Roth-Hanania,
presents four social learning mechanisms active Davidov, & Zahn-Waxler, 2011). They can
in social learning: imitation, response facilita- express a sense of fairness (Sommerville,
tion, program-level (hierarchical) imitation, and Schmidt, Yun, & Burns, 2013). They are capable
emulation. of engaging in sharing in the first year (Schmidt
& Sommerville, 2011).
Table 15.3 Mechanisms of social learning in evolution Legerstee (2013) argued for innate social
Social learning developmental or early affective attunement
mechanism Definition mechanisms. According to her, neoconstructivists
Imitation Learning an intrinsic portion of a consider that the newborn is preadapted for early
novel act communication and intersubjective sharing. They
Response A viewed action increases the connect with the social surround, share affect,
facilitation probability of doing the same. Only
and bond socially. The young brain provides a
actions already in the repertoire can
be facilitated in this process biological basis for social interaction (for exam-
(Byrne, 1994) ple, large neocortices; Dunbar, 2013) and a mirror
Program-level Combining novel and already neuronal system (Gallese & Rochat, 2013).
imitation existing actions to duplicate a Legerstee (2013) presented her concept of an
hierarchically-organized sequence
“affect sharing device” (AFS) with which infants
Emulation Object movement reenactment—the
observer replicates the movements
appear to be born. Its components include the
of the physical artifact with which ability to: (a) recognize others as self-similar; (b)
the model interacted express sensitivity to the emotions of others and
Goal emulation—achieving but by self; and (c) perceive whether adults are in tune
using their own method to attain it
Affordance learning—learning about
with their needs/emotions. The AFS provides
the physical properties of the infants with an inborn “sense” of the people
environment/relations among objects around them with whom they can engage in
Adapted from Hopper et al. (2012) intersubjective experience and social attunement.
368 15 Connecting the Social Dots

People are not only perceived as whether they Overall, the models that Govrin (2014)
are “like me” (Meltzoff, 2007) but also whether described for early morality are experience-based
they are emotionally “with me.” (attachment), social-motivational (pleasureful),
and cognitive (goals). For recent work on the
Environment importance of the early environment on prosocial
Janoff-Bulman (2012) related parental practice to (helping) behavior and awareness of the other’s
moral-type development. Restrictive-type parent- mental state, see Dahl (2015) and Kärtner (2015),
ing versus more nurturant type behavior should respectively. The former emphasizes the role of
elicit proscriptive vs. prescriptive type responses encouragement/thanking/praising and the latter
(sensitive to negative outcomes, based on inhibi- parenting (cultural) beliefs and practices. The
tion; and sensitive to positive outcomes, based on next model under discussion was generated in the
activation, respectively, Gray, 1990). Shaver and adult context, but has relevancy to children. It,
Mikulincer (2012) related attachment security/inse- too, is cognitive-oriented.
curity experiences to empathy and authenticity.
Govrin (2014) described various models of Cognitive
early moral development. The author proposed Self Control Baumeister (2012) distinguished
that moral judgment develops in the first year of the root causes and also the proximal causes in
life through the internal representations framed expressing behavior that can be considered evil.
in caregiver attachments that develop. Early He referred to: (a) evolution; (b) threatened
social interactions facilitate the development of egotism; (c) idealism; and (d) sadism as root
an internal representation of rules system about causes and, as proximal causes, he referred to
right/wrong judgments and their construal, factors such as self-control and its breakdown.
understanding, and use. In this regard, Baumeister and Graham (2012)
Govrin (2014) described another model of related moral behavior to self-control, rational
early prosocial behavior. That is, young children choice, and intentional planning as part of a set
act prosocially in order to facilitate interacting of psychological capacities involved in free
socially, because of the latter’s pleasure and will. We can consciously imagine multiple
social affiliation. The behavior evident is more alternatives, choose the best ones, resist tempta-
for reasons of social motivation than an explicit tions and antisocial impulses, and we can
prosocial one. even select prosocial actions involving the
In the fourth model under discussion, the sacrifice of selfish advantage through these
social-normative one, the social environment is capacities, thereby promoting moral judgment
considered as the source of prosocial behavior and moral action.
through its support, fostering, and scaffolding
(e.g., Hammond & Carpendale, 2012). Piaget Hammond (2014) took the position that
Govrin (2014) continued with goal-alignment Piaget (1932/1997, 1945/1951, 1976) developed
models, in which the young child lacks self-other a body of developmental theory that could help
differentiation skills, but still can act prosocially explain early prosocial behavior in children.
because he/she appropriates the goal of the other Piaget only briefly mentioned early moral-related
as if it were his/her own. The child might feel the behavior. He considered it as involving a practice
same emotion as another in need or distress, and phase as preparatory to a later representational
“rely” on the witnessed object-directed behavior one. Helping begins at the action level and moral-
and effort to understand the “cause” of the evi- ity develops further in a developing cognitive
dent need/distress that has developed. In order to base. It is motor and egocentric in nature. In his
“alleviate” the need/distress, the child acts in a model, infants should be able to help instrumen-
manner that appears prosocial but, in actuality, is tally by learning and using their sensory and
“nonsympathetic.” motor skills.
Developmental Research Review 369

Piaget’s work can reconcile views that infants right from the first hours post-birth (Feldman &
are natural altruists and unhelpful helpers. For Eidelman, 2007). In this way, infants experience
Piaget, children must first engage actively, or a temporal matching across their state with
practice, morally relevant activity (Carpendale, maternal/social environment responsivity.
2009). The young child acquires some early At about 3 months, Feldman (2014) contin-
learning of some aspects of helping, which is ued, infants’ behavior in maternal interactions
“purely motor” and individualized, leading to becomes more active. The sequences involve
“ritualized” schemas rather than moral represen- coordinated gaze patterns, co-vocalizations,
tations (e.g., as in helping by engaging in clean- mutual positive affect expression, and affection-
ing with others). Infants can imitate helpful ate touch. Next, the 3- to 9-month period consti-
actions, but only instrumentally without moral tutes a critical period in biobehavioral synchrony.
(empathic) understanding. This view does not The degree of synchrony in this period predicts
presuppose that early helping must involve later childhood cognitive and social-emotional
knowledge of the mind of the other, unlike some acquisitions (Feldman, 2007a, 2007b), as well as
contemporary accounts. Hammond (2014) con- extent of optimal social adaptation and depres-
cluded that research is needed on ecologically sion in adolescence (Feldman, 2010).
valid, naturalistic helping behavior.
Nativism Hamlin (2014a) studied the develop-
Comment ment of helping behavior in young infants. She
The review of the various models on the origins of showed that, in the first few months of life,
early morality range from the biological (nativist) infants do not exhibit global social evaluation in
to the environmental (parental). There are also context because they lack domain-general rather
various cognitive models. Most likely, all the than domain-specific skills (related to limited
models contribute to understanding the develop- memory and processing capacities). However, at
ment of early morality. In origin, it is surely inter- 4.5 months of age, infants in the appropriate lab-
actively social, motivational, cognitive, oratory task context could indeed prefer (as dem-
environmental, including cultural, and biological. onstrated in the behavior of selectively reaching
to) those who were “nice” (givers) compared to
“mean” (hinderers) in action toward “nice” (help-
Developmental Research Review ing, prosocial) puppets and those who were mean
(not nice) to mean (antisocial) puppets. This
In the following, I review developmental research demonstrates that, at this age, infants can exhibit
and concepts that further specify the origins of context-dependent social evaluation.
early morality. The work involves not only the
earliest years but also work with children. Hamlin (2015) showed that 6- to 11-month-
olds preferred to reach for animated helpers com-
pared to hinderers. Scarf, Imuta, Colombo, and
Year 1 and Before Hayne (2012) had argued that, rather than reflect-
ing a choice for the social value of helping, the
Biobehavioral Synchrony Feldman (2014) has infants were choosing helpers due to confounding
explored extensively biobehavioral synchrony as influences of uncontrolled lower-order perceptual
a basis of social affiliation from early in life events in the scenes witnessed. However, Hamlin
onward. It is a process that facilitates social group (2015) controlled for the possible confounds. For
adhesion and collaborative function. Human example, the climbers in the revised experiment
mothers engage in synchronous, coordinated to the original (Hamlin, Wynn, & Bloom, 2007)
temporal correspondences with their infants. did not bounce when they arrived at the top of the
Indeed, they create temporal contingencies hill after being helped. Moreover, when the
between their social behavior and infant state climber’s gaze was not consistent with (looking
370 15 Connecting the Social Dots

up) to the goal of climbing, the helper was not infants prefer those who prevent the goals of
preferred relative to the hinderer in the test phase. those who had engaged in the hindering of oth-
Hamlin (2015) concluded that infants appear ers. This shows that infants do not solely prefer
sensitive to the “goal” of the actor involved, helpers. The results suggest that context is taken
and respond to the helpful/hindering actions of into account and, at this age, preferences are
agents in terms of their inferred mental states. established based on influences about the mental
When goals are facilitated by prosocial behavior, state(s) of the character(s) involved.
even young infants selectively attend to and
reach for prosocial agents relative to antisocial Prenatal Davidov et al. (2013) argued that
hindering ones. already in the first year infants can express con-
Hamlin et al. (2007) and Hamlin, Wynn, cern for others, and in their literature review they
Bloom, and Mahajan (2011) had shown that concentrated on the feeling of concern for others
infants generally prefer individuals who help oth- (e.g., sympathy). In this regard, relative to the
ers and those who mistreat others who had harmed control condition of loud sounds, newborns
third parties. Hamlin, Mahajan, Liberman, and already respond to recorded cries of other infants
Wynn (2013) reported results with 9- and by getting distressed (e.g., Geangu et al., 2010).
14-month-old infants that there might be an early
preference to like whom one recognizes as similar For infants, for the self–other differentiation
to oneself and to dislike others who are not. underlying feeling of concern, a simpler implicit
Specifically, they found that, even at 9 months of type of self-knowledge should suffice (e.g., the
age, infants preferred individuals who treated well subjective pre-reflective knowledge involved when
others similar to them and poorly others who were newborns discriminate their own recorded cries
not. Hamlin et al. (2013) noted that infants did not and those of another newborn; Dondi, Simion, &
have a blanket liking of helpers, so that the results Caltran, 1999). Infants do not need the explicit,
reflect a liking related to self–target similarity. self-reflective knowledge as found in toddlers (e.g.,
The authors concluded that the social preferences as demonstrated in their touching of their surrepti-
described might have an innate basis, but research tiously rouged nose seen in the mirror compared to
with younger infants is required before any state- the nose reflection in the mirror, which is the
ment about innate origin is testable. behavior evident in the year-old, for example).
Tafreshi et al. (2014) questioned the face According to Davidov et al. (2013), Roth-
validity of laboratory studies using looking and Hanania et al. (2011) demonstrated that moderate
reaching to infer the nature of infant morality. levels of affective and cognitive empathy are
Dahl (2014) added that morality taken in the already present in 8-month-olds responding to
broad sense (of judging right/wrong, good/bad, maternal distress and to peer distress. Moreover, the
and deserving of reward/punishment) has not degree of empathy predicted prosocial behavior in
been appropriately investigated in the first year of the second year, indicative of early dispositional
life. There are as yet no studies in this age period individual differences. For Davidov et al. (2013),
on infant evaluating negatively their own infants express a fundamental motive for social
transgressions. connectedness.
Hamlin (2014b) maintained that the evidence Further, for twin pairs examined prenatally,
does not support these assertions. She argued that movements by one co-twin toward the other com-
some of the terminology of the critics is con- pared to self-directed movements differed in
fused. Moreover, there is sufficient evidence in motion pattern (Castiello et al., 2010). Therefore,
favor of the “core knowledge” model of the early for Davidov et al. (2013), the self–other differen-
human mind pertaining to early morality and tiation necessary to support other concern, and so
sociomoral evaluations. For example, Hamlin recognize the other relative to the self as hurting,
(2014b) reported that, by 4 ½ months of age, appears to develop even in utero.
Developmental Research Review 371

Preparation Kuhlmeier, Dunfield, and O’Neill designed to induce negative or positive social
(2014) reviewed models of early prosocial behav- evaluative stress concurrent with their separation
ior and found the “partner choice” model appro- from the infants. Sympathetic nervous system
priate. This model involves choosing partners activity was monitored by electrocardiography in
based on prior interactions and inferred charac- both participants. The infants were not directly
teristics of the characters involved. When reci- exposed to the maternal stressor.
procity can be expected from others having
prosocial dispositions and “positive valence,” The study showed that mothers’ stress reactions
early prosocial behavior is promoted. The social are embodied in the infants in the reunion situation.
evaluation evidenced in the first year of life in The infants’ heart reactivity mirrored that of the
this context (e.g., Hamlin & Wynn, 2011) might mother’s reactivity to the stress exposure. The
serve as an “adaptive preparation” for later child- stress situation induced greater physiological
hood prosociality. covariation when it was negative, and the effect
became more pronounced with time. There were
Social Other researchers are more conservative behavioral consequences, as well—social stress in
about any rich interpretation of early prosocial the mothers led to more infant stranger avoidance.
behavior. In this regard, Martin and Olson (2015) Waters et al. (2014) concluded that stress con-
maintained that early prosocial behavior is quite tagion involves a reciprocal dynamic between
selective and is multiply motivated. For the for- mothers and infants. Moreover, maternal stress
mer, for example, generally it is more directed to immediately influences offspring physiological
adults that children. For the latter, it might take reactivity, indicating that mother and infant
place for both internal and external motivations engage in a “physiological attunement” in which
but might be generally social in nature rather than stress “gets under the skin.” Finally, the external
prosocial, per se. social world can affect indirectly the infant phys-
iologically through its effects on the caregiver.
Comment The review of the developmental Relative to controls, Cirelli et al. (2014) found
material on early morality and related behavior that prosocial behavior in 14-month-olds was pro-
that has been undertaken has a decidedly biologi- moted by having bounced in synchrony to music
cal flavor, with research addressing prenatal influ- with the partner. Interpersonal motor synchrony at
ences, biobehavioral synchrony, nativism, and this age encourages social bonding. The authors
preparedness. As for the work on the second year concluded that interpersonal motor synchrony helps
of life in the next section, this basic theme is establish each other as similar to the other, which
expanded to include embodiment and normative potentiates affiliative behavior. According to me,
approaches, in particular. The section after the this model is consistent with the shared embodi-
next one for the second year of life is on children ment or enactive (and dynamical) perspective of
and it returns to biological themes in developing social origins.
morality, along with cognitive ones, but with the
experiential/social always included. It would Contagion Paulus (2014) explored models of
seem that, like many other phenomena in the pres- prosocial behavior in the 1- to 2-year-old period.
ent book that have been discussed, a biopsychoso- He described four competing models in the field.
cial perspective affords an integrating model. He opted for a multifaceted approach in which
varied types of motivations underlie different
types of prosocial behavior; also, each might
Year 2 have different ontogenies and mechanisms.
In this regard, infants might help comfort and
Embodiment Waters et al. (2014) studied stress share because of emotional or affect sharing or
or affect contagion in 12- to 14-month-olds after contagion. In this model, perceiving another in a
their mothers were placed in a laboratory situation mode of need or distress triggers an equivalent
372 15 Connecting the Social Dots

(isomorphic) emotional state empathically in the characters relative to antisocial ones (Hamlin &
infant/toddler. The result is that very young chil- Wynn, 2011). Finally, they expect fair resource
dren might try to comfort him/herself, and distribution and also prefer fair distributors
through this self–other differentiation and feeling (respectively, Schmidt & Sommerville, 2011;
sympathy for the other, prosociality (comforting Geraci & Surian, 2011).
the other) develops. Overall, for Tomasello and Vaish (2013), even
infants readily engage in collaboration and they
Strategic Selectivity Martin and Olson (2015) recognize social interdependence. They help oth-
reviewed the evidence for three major theories of ers even without personal benefit, and they
early sociality and concluded that infants in the express social equity. However, they behave from
second year of life demonstrate prosocial behav- an individual standpoint and not from a norm-
ior due to multiple motivations, and are selective based one, unlike the case for toddlers.
in doing so. The research, then, support neither According to Tomasello and Vaish (2013), pre-
an extrinsic model of reinforcement leading to schoolers enter a second stage of norm-based
learning of prosociality nor an intrinsic model of morality. They are able to enforce social norms,
indiscriminate prosociality that becomes more behave appropriately when anticipating that they
selective with age. Note that selectivity at this will be judged, react negatively to a lack of remorse,
age is strategic, for example, recipients receive and, indeed, actively seek to understand and abide
help from infants so that the infants might achieve by norms.
another goal. That is, early prosociality is not As for mechanisms that enable the develop-
inherently altruistic. However, this does not mean mental progression in cooperation and morality
that the behavior is consciously strategic or that has been described, Tomasello and Vaish
expressed for purely selfish reasons. (2013) referred to social-cognitive developmen-
As for the evidence in support of the model, tal and socialization/culture influences. The for-
Martin and Olson (2015) noted that (a) 18-month- mer changes in development, but not necessarily
olds helped a party to complete a task even if they abruptly.
had to disengage from fun toys (Warneken & Vaish and Tomasello (2014) described further
Tomasello, 2008); (b) 19-month-olds preferred to research on early individual prosocial tendencies
reward helpers of third parties over hinderers and individual group-minded, normative tenden-
(Dahl, Schuck, & Campos, 2013); and (c) cies. For example, infants participate in joint activi-
21-month-olds gave a desirable object to an adult ties. Preschoolers ensure that a partner receives a
who had tried to help them (albeit unsuccess- reward in a task even after they had received theirs.
fully; control conditions—refusal to help; acci- At this age, cooperation is “inherently joint” and
dentally help; no intention to help). interdependent (Hamann, Warneken, & Tomasello,
2012).
Norms Tomasello and Vaish (2013) addressed Joint activity is indicated when infants can
early collaboration/commitment, sympathy/help- point to a location known to them for the place-
ing, and equality/sharing. For example, when ment of an object when an adult is searching for
cooperative activity breaks down, 1-year-olds it (“informative” pointing, at 12 months of age;
will try to actively re-engage the other, and this Liszkowski, Carpenter, & Tomasello, 2008).
happens even if the partner is not necessary for Further, as mentioned above, they show concern
completion of the task at hand (Warneken, and prosocial actions when a “victim” is harmed
Gräfenhain, & Tomasello, 2012). Also, 1-year- even if the victim does not indicate overt distress
olds express concern and prosocial activity (at 18 months of age; Vaish et al., 2009). Also,
toward a victim of harm even if the victim is not they prefer equal distributors and equal distribu-
overtly distressed (Vaish, Carpenter, & Tomasello, tions (at 15 months of age; Geraci & Surian,
2009). Further, they prefer to touch prosocial 2011; Schmidt & Sommerville, 2011).
Developmental Research Review 373

Children extensively connected to circuits involving emo-


tional behavior and stress response. Decety and
Cognition Chernyak and Kushnir (2013) inves- Howard (2014) concluded that the ventromedial
tigated whether giving choice to preschoolers prefrontal cortex plays a crucial role in integrating
plays a causal role in prosocial sharing. In the bodily response and affective representation
study, children who made a costly choice of allo- related to empathy and moral decision-making.
cating a resource that they could have kept were
later more prosocial with a different individual. Heritable Knafo-Noam, Uzefovsky, Israel,
The results are consistent with a prosocial- Davidov, and Zahn-Waxler (2015) conducted a
construal model, in which rational cognitive pro- twin study with 7-year-olds using questionnaire
cesses are promoted in choice that affects measures filled in by mothers with items related
subsequent prosocial behavior. It is as if children to prosociality. Statistical analysis showed five
infer that, in being prosocial, they signal to them- meaningful clusters that they considered facets of
selves that they are prosocial and like being pro- a common single factor concerning a prosociality
social. In this regard, making costly choices phenotype. The five facets involved: sharing,
might make an important contribution to young social concern, kindness, helping, and empathic
children’s development of their self- concern. Abbreviated examples of the items
understanding as “moral beings.” involved included, respectively, shares readily
Vaish and Tomasello (2014) cited multiple stud- with others, shows sympathy, kind to younger
ies indicating that, by 3 years of age, children recog- children, volunteers to help others, and helpful if
nize social norms as “general, agent-neutral, mutual someone hurts.
expectations” in the emergence of a “collective Knafo-Noam et al. (2015) estimated a high
intentionality” (e.g., Riedl et al., 2011; Schmidt, heritability of 69 % for the common-prosocial
Rakoczy, & Tomasello, 2012; Vaish, Missana, & factor. Also, each of the facets involved unique
Tomasello, 2011). They contrasted their approach genetic and environmental contributions. Overall,
to that of Piaget. the authors concluded that genetics is strongly
involved in the common factor trait of prosocial-
Brain Decety, Michalska, and Kinzler (2012) ity, with the environment additionally involved in
studied developmental changes in response to the facets.
morally-related stimuli. The participants were
4–37 years of age. The stimuli were brief, ani- Comment As a comment, I would add that the
mated scenarios that showed either people or social-cognitive development evident in the pre-
objects being injured/damaged (and either by schooler continues to grow and, moreover, it
intentional or unintentional actions). For the sce- should follow the Neo-Piagetian scaffold of stages
narios with people who were injured intentionally, and substages in cognitive development, as per
according to fMRI scan measurement, the regions either of Young’s (2011) model or other models.
of the brain that differentially activated involved For adults to express the “hypercollaboration”
the right posterior superior temporal sulcus and described by Tomasello and Vaish (2013), their
other regions associated with the perception, pre- cognitive sophistication needs to grow well
diction, and interpretation of the intentions of peo- beyond the preschooler level. There should be
ple. In addition, regions associated with processing more than the two-steps in cooperation and moral-
of affective consequences of these actions were ity described by these authors not only in human
differentially activated (i.e., the temporal poles, development but also in evolution. Young’s (2011)
insula, amygdala, and ventromedial prefrontal model would predict 25 precursor, initiation, and
cortex). Other relevant findings underscored the elaboration steps in the former case and multiple
role of the subgenual prefrontal cortex, which is underpinning steps in the latter one.
374 15 Connecting the Social Dots

Applications involved. The model includes a biological


component and cultural influences, as well as
Public Good common factors and individual differences.
Proximally, the self in context is influenced by
Parks, Joireman, and Van Lange (2013) presented distal evolutionary forces, such as kin selection
an integrative model of how cooperation, trust, and reciprocal altruism, and also by cultural
and other variables influence decisions about influences, such as individualism/collectivism.
the public good (see Fig. 15.6). The model is Other influences in the model relate to individual
relevant to present purposes because it factors, such as attachment (in)security develop-
includes relatively more distal and proximal mental history, as well as the major opposition
causes in navigating the social dilemmas between cooperation and antagonism.

Individual Influences Group (Cultural) Influences Evolutionary Influences

Causes (Distal)
Family (In)Secure Attachment (Individualism/ (Kin (Reciprocal (Competitive
Collectivism) Selection) Altruism) Altruism)

Sharing
Empathy Expectations Self-control

Cooperation Motivation
Predisposition Transformation Situation Features

Causes (Proximal)
Given Matrix
Decision Features

Effective
Matrix

Perceived Decision Rules


Consequences

Intended Level of Cooperation


Factors Affecting Behavior
(Noise)
Actual Cooperation (Own x Other’s)
Interaction
(Initial)

Outcomes
(Own, Other, Relative, Joint)
Factors Moderating
Outcome
Outcome Responses
Consequences

Rewards Punishments Structural Solutions

Subsequent Proximal Decision


Processes and Behavior Choices

Fig. 15.6 Integrative model of social dilemma decision- The model is a biopsychosocial one in this regard. In terms
making: from influences (distal, proximal) to outcome of proximal causes, the model mostly concerns personal
(interactions, consequences). The figure indicates the mul- factors, such as motivation, but also there are more bio-
titude of variables involved in decision-making with logical (predispositional) and contextual (situational)
respect to social dilemmas. The model applies equally to ones. The personal component includes a cognitive com-
other areas of behavior. There are distal causes involved, ponent and appraisals (decision feature, decision rules,
such as personal, cultural, and evolutionary (biological). perceived consequences). Adapted from Parks et al. (2013)
Applications 375

Politics Although the Fraley et al. (2012) study was


longitudinal, the authors maintained that it could
Fraley, Griffin, Belsky, and Roisman (2012) not address mechanism. For example, there could
examined the relationship between 1-month par- be multiple confounders involved related to very
enting attitudes and 18-year-old political ideol- early and much later developmental relation-
ogy. They also included temperament at 5 years ships. I would add that the findings were weak.
of age in their longitudinal analysis. Prior First, the correlations involved were low even if
research had indicated that preschoolers who had significant. Moreover, the significant level
been relatively more anxious, guilt-prone, and (alpha) was set at 0.05, which risks Type I error.
indecisive had developed to endorse conservative The regression results were in the same order
values at age 23 (Block & Block, 2006). (they were consistent with the correlations, but
Participants were taken from a National low and at p < 0.05).
Institute of Child Health and Human Development As for temperament, the associations/predic-
(NICHD) longitudinal study (the Study of Early tions were consistent with the literature. Early
Child Care and Youth Development; SECCYD). fearfulness and deficits in attentional control pre-
Sample sizes ranged from 635 to 708. Parental dicted a later conservative attitude. Also, early
political attitude was assessed with the Parental activity/restlessness predicted a later liberal
Modernity Inventory (PMI; Schaefer & Edgerton, attitude.
1985). It gave two composites—authoritarian Fraley et al. (2012) posited that conservatives
and egalitarian parenting style (e.g., about obey- might self-organize psychologically to defend/
ing the parent vs. the child’s point of view being protect the status quo, whereas liberals might
taken into account). Maternal sensitivity was express an under control of ego-related function.
scored from videotaped mother–child interac- These conclusions might go too much beyond the
tions at 6, 15, 36, and 54 months of age. At 54 data, especially in typecasting liberals and con-
months, the Children’s Behavior Questionnaire servatives. Moreover, there are differences in lib-
(CBQ, Rothbart, Ahadi, Hershey, & Fisher, 2001) eral and conservative attitudes with respect to
was administered to assess early temperament. social and economic issues (see below), making
Five factors were extracted in the temperament it premature to lump people together into two dis-
questionnaire, related to: restlessness/activity, tinct categories politically.
shyness, attentional focusing, passivity, and fear. Nevertheless, at some point in determining
It was noted that none of the factors resembled differences in some aspect of liberalism vs.
the adult’s openness to experience in the FFM conservatism, I conjecture that a common
(Five Factor Model, Costa & McCrae, 1992). variable in differential political attitude and its
Political ideology at 18 years was measured with underpinnings might relate to degree and type
the Conservatism Scale (Wilson & Patterson, of inhibitory function. That is, everything else
1968). The covariates that were controlled being equal, conservatives might deploy inhibi-
included: gender, cognitive ability (as measured tory function toward presenting equilibrium, and
by Woodcock-Johnson Psychoeducational liberals might use it to open equilibrium to
Battery, Woodcock, 1990; Woodcock & Johnson, change at thresholds less than is typical for
1989), and SES (socioeconomic status). conservatives.
In terms of results, Fraley et al. (2012) reported The research on the relationship between per-
that parents who had scored as more authoritarian sonality traits and political ideology is becoming
in parental attitude when their children were more nuanced. For example, Osborne, Wootton,
1-month-old had their children develop conserva- and Sibley (2013) found that the politeness com-
tive political ideologies at 18 years, whereas a more ponent of agreeableness correlated positively
egalitarian parenting attitude early on was associ- with political conservatism but the compassion
ated with a later liberal ideology in the offspring. component evinced the opposite relationship.
376 15 Connecting the Social Dots

McAdams, Hanek, and Dadabo (2013) demon- organized, whereas liberals relative to conserva-
strated that the narrative approach to personality tives appear more open, creative, curious, and
provided results related to political ideology above seeking of novelty.
and beyond personality traits. Openness to experi- Pulfrey and Butera (2013) demonstrated that
ence did relate to conservatism–liberalism (open- accentuating “neoliberal” (i.e., economically
ness was negatively correlated with conservatism), conservative) values (“self-enhancement”) pre-
but political conservatives also emphasized the dicted actual cheating behavior. Moreover, in
narrative theme of self-regulation while political promoting their opposite values (universalism,
liberals emphasized the theme of self-exploration. benevolence, self-transcendence), the predictive
The results are consistent with Janoff-Bulman’s relationship between self-enhancement and the
(2009) model that liberals aim to provide and also condoning of cheating no longer was present.
that they value prescriptive moralities, whereas
conservatism is associated with protection and, as
well, proscriptive moralities. Self
There is a debate in the literature whether con-
servatives compared to liberals are more fearful, Model
defensive, and low in self-esteem. Schlenker,
Chambers, and Le (2012) conducted four studies McAdams (2013) presented a developmental
in which political conservatives, compared to lib- model of the self comprised of three components
erals, were shown to be happier due to specific (actor, agent, author) that emerge sequentially in
attitude and personality differences associated development. The first self is a social actor. As
with positive adjustment/mental health. For newborns, we are already primed in a rudimen-
example, conservatives expressed more personal tary sense for social performance and, in the first
agency, positive outlook, transcendent moral months, we express constitutionally-present dif-
beliefs, and a generalized fairness belief. ferential temperament patterns. By around 18
Choma, Hafer, Dywan, Segalowitz, and months, we recognized ourselves in mirrors (e.g.,
Busseri (2012) developed a measure of conserva- Rochat, 2003).
tive and liberal political ideology in which con- The social actor self continues to evolve
servatism and liberalism did not appear to lie on throughout the lifespan, but a second self emerges
poles of the same continuum but emerged func- continuously as a motivated agent by the end of
tionally independent, or as separable constructs. childhood. However, even in the first year, infants
In their study, liberalism was associated with a express a preliminary appreciation of agency. For
universal orientation and conservatism with dog- example, they prefer to imitate intentional rather
matism. Other results related liberalism to toler- random acts (Woodward, 2009). By the age of 4,
ance of ambiguity. Findings demonstrated that they develop a theory of mind. By 8 or 9 years,
the two political orientations were moderately personal goals are established, and children are
correlated. Note that in Choma et al. the measure defining and evaluating themselves by family,
of political liberalism–conservatism consisted of peers, school, and cultural experiences and goals.
six items (how (a) conservative/(b) liberal (2 The stage acquisitions described by Erikson
options) do you tend to be—(a) in general, (b) for (1963, industry vs. inferiority) and Piaget (1970,
economical policy, and (c) for social policy [(3 concrete operational thought) in the age range
areas), (2 × 3) = 6]), as evaluated on a 9-point concerned facilitate these comparisons and con-
Likert scale. The factors that emerged were found structions proposed for children.
by confirmatory factor analysis tested for fit to a The third self is the autobiographical self, or
bipolar (single dimension) and to a bidimensional the self-narrative author, that emerges in adoles-
model, which proved the superior one. cence and early adulthood. Preliminary signs of it
Similarly, Carney, Jost, Gosling, and Potter are evident in early childhood with the develop-
(2008) opined that conservatives relative to ment of autobiographical memory (Howe &
liberals are more orderly, conventional, and Courage, 1997), and also the child’s capacity to
Chapter Conclusions 377

recall recent episodes (Fivush, 2011). As the between and across linkages in the stories relative
autobiographic author self emerges, self-stories to stories that lack self-integration (cohesion and
are amalgamated into narrative identities coherence, respectively). It would appear there is
(McAdams & Pals, 2006). At this stage in self- room to integrate network and narrative science.
growth, people use autobiographical reasoning Moreover, other models of self-development
(Habermas & Bluck, 2000). They create orga- are more elaborate than McAdams (2013). For
nized autobiographical themes. They sequence example, Young (2011) also used Piaget and
personal-valued episodes into causal chains that Erikson as bases in his work, and developed a
self-explain their development, which facilitates five stage × five substage model of unitary
personal growth and mature self-authorship. Piagetian and Eriksonian development that trans-
McAdam and McLean (2013) argued that lated into a 25-step (5 stages × 5 substages) model
aspects of narrative identity help promote mental of self-development. The three selves described
health, well-being, and psychological maturity. by McAdams would appear to readily fit Young’s
Specifically, narratives with redemptive model (e.g., actor in sensorimotor development,
sequences, or stories with meanings in suffering/ agent in perioperational development, and author
adversity (i.e., from “bad” to “good” outcome, in abstract development).
e.g., loss of loved one promoting family cohe-
sion), or with themes of personal agency/explora-
tion, serve positive mental health ends. The Chapter Conclusions
authors called for research to disentangle which
features of life stories actually promote positive Piaget Missing
psychological adaptation in “causal relations.”
McFarland, Brown, and Webb (2013) sug- This chapter has reviewed the multiple factors
gested that identification with all humanity is an that influence the development especially of
important moral concept and psychological con- empathic/prosocial behavior. The area is marked
struct. I note that this concept could be combined by disagreement about the rapidity and biologi-
with the concept of narrative identity (McAdam cal, innate bases for the development of the
& McLean, 2013) and studied for its components behavior. The different points of view on the mat-
that contribute to positive mental health, if any. ter are similar to the ones encountered in other
areas of development, and they emphasize the
common refrain of disambiguating the influences
Comment on development of Nature, Nurture, or both.
However, a more inclusive model that would help
There is value in examining the primary charac- explain the onset and growth of this behavior
teristics of narratives. They need to be cohesive would include the self component, as well as
and coherent, to borrow terms from functional related ones, given that Nature and Nurture are
linguistics. The former term refers to interlinked passive influences on development and we con-
chains in discourse and the latter term to overall tribute actively as agents in our own growth.
integration and meaning (Halliday & Hasan, Moreover, in these regards, any causal develop-
1976; Young, 2011). Moreover, self-identity nar- mental model should include a Piagetian per-
rative stories could be considered as complex net- spective, given the cognitive underpinnings to
works. In this sense, the networks that they create prosocial/empathic and related behavior and their
could be analyzed to include indicators of net- consequences for behavior such as this.
work cohesion and coherence. In this regard, in In this regard, in the following I attempt to show
terms of the topic of causality, generally, and of that the steps in the development of empathic and
narratives, specifically, causality could be speci- prosocial behavior described in the literature are
fied for cohesion and coherence, too. For exam- consistent with Piaget’s six substages in infancy. In
ple, one could ask whether the causal stories of my approach to this parallel, I add the influence of
self-integration are consistent or inconsistent mirror neuron processes that apparently allow for
378 15 Connecting the Social Dots

empathic and prosocial behavior earlier than Piaget (d) At 9 months, they appear to like self-similar
might have predicted. people (Hamlin et al., 2013).
His model for this age is based on sensorimo- (e) At 14 months of age, they express interper-
tor activity, with little hint of representational sonal motor synchrony, e.g., in bouncing to
thought until the last substage, and empathy and music, which helps each of the actors see the
prosocial behavior would appear to need some other as like me (Cirelli et al., 2014). Also, at
form of primitive representation for the behaviors 15 months of age, they prefer equal distribu-
to manifest. However, the “like me” (Meltzoff, tors and equal distributions (Vaish &
2007) comparisons that can be integrated into Tomasello, 2014).
sensorimotor development through early (quasi) (f) At 18 months of age, they show concern and
imitative and perhaps mirror-system enabled pro- prosocial actions when a “victim” is harmed
cesses might be sufficient to have develop in the even if the victim does not express overtly
sensorimotor period intuitive, action-based, any distress (Vaish et al., 2009).
embodied quasi-representational models some-
what removed from objects, events, activities,
and people in the environment that allow for a Piaget
progressively developing early empathic and pro-
social behavior. These results are highly consistent with the six
substages in Piaget’s sensorimotor period. In the
following, I describe the six substages in Piaget’s
Research Review infant sensorimotor series (Young, 2011).

In order to build the model showing the compara- (a) The first substage in the newborn is termed
bility of recent findings on empathy and proso- reflex exercise (reflexes concern repeated
cial behavior in infancy and Piaget’s model of patterns in behavior rather than reflex-arc
substages in infancy, I considered critical find- controlled ones).
ings for the infancy period in the literature review (b) The second one in the 1-month-old involves
undertaken in the present chapter on empathic primary circular reactions, which are
and prosocial behavior. In particular, I noted the accidentally-discovered, liked repetitive behav-
following from the review already provided. iors with the body (e.g., thumb sucking).
(c) At 4 months of age, secondary circular reac-
(a) In the newborn period infants are capable of tions develop, which are accidentally-
engaging in biobehavioral synchrony with discovered, liked repetitions with objects
the mother (Feldman, 2014). They have an (e.g., rattle shaking). This step is notable for
implicit type of self-knowledge, a subjective visually-directed reaching.
pre-reflective knowledge (Davidov et al., (d) In the next step at 8 months, infants engage
2013). in coordinated secondary schemas in which
(b) At 3 months of age, they show coordinated the schemas established in the prior step are
gaze patterns, co-vocalizations, mutual posi- coordinated toward new ends. For example,
tive affect expression, and affectionate touch reaching can be used in a detour to move a
(Feldman, 2014). barrier that is hiding a liked object before
(c) At 4 months of age, infants can be nice to grasping the object.
puppets that had been nice to other ones (e) At 12 months, infants can experiment to cre-
(Hamlin, 2014a) and prefer those who pre- ate new means-end combinations using pre-
vent the goals of those who had hindered oth- viously acquired relations in this regard, but
ers (Hamlin, 2014b). At 6 months, they seem only accidentally.
sensitive to the goals of others and their (f) Finally, at 18 months, they can invent new
inferred mental states (Hamlin, 2015). means-end relations by mental combinations,
Chapter Conclusions 379

but the behavior is not fully representational child behave toward the other like he/ she
for the behavior is still tied to actions (e.g., would toward the self? The behavior does
Piaget’s daughter opened her mouth before appear repetitive, out of interest, and acci-
solving a problem in which she had to open a dentally discovered, though not with inten-
drawer). tion at the outset.
(d) At 8 months of age, the next Piagetian step
develops, and it involves coordination of sec-
Explaining the Review According ondary schemas. Empirically, it has been
to Piaget shown that the infant at this age appears to
like self-similar people. This acquisition is
By comparing the two sequences, the Piagetian dependent on more advanced cognitive abili-
and the experimental, it is clear that the results of ties than in the prior step, because the infant is
the recent studies are consistent with what the coordinating self and other, and cognition and
Piagetian series in infancy would predict. The emotion, and in a way that goes beyond just
comparison undertaken next is in this vein. behaving toward the other because the indi-
vidual is “like me.” That is, in this step, first,
(a) In the reflex period, neonates do behave intui- there is the like me comparison, and, then, as
tively in creating interpersonal coordination. might be predicted from knowing of the coor-
(b) In the second one of circular or repetitive dination of secondary schemas in the Piagetian
reactions involving the body, 3-month-olds model, there is a subsequent step feeding back
manifest various interpersonal coordinations, to the other individual of liking him or her.
including of vocalizations, just as would be (e) Next, at one year of age, the infant engages in
predicted by knowing the qualities of Piaget’s accidental discoveries according to Piaget,
step of secondary (that is, nonbody) circular reworking previously acquired means-end
reactions. relations. In this regard, the empirical finding
(c) Next, at 4 to 6 months of age, they can dif- at this age is that infants are quite engaged with
ferentiate nice and mean puppets and even the other, e.g., in motor synchrony and in egali-
infer mental states. This type of behavior tarian distribution. These are new behaviors
seems more advanced than what the that clearly require rearrangement of existing
Piagetian substage sequence would predict, means-ends relations, yet I suggest that they
given that it concerns at this age only the are not preplanned but arise out of accidental
ability to engage in secondary circular reac- variations in behavior that eventually become
tions, or the repetition of liked behaviors, incorporated into the infant’s repertoire.
such as shaking rattles. However, by adding (f) Finally, the empirical research in the age
in the advances in behavior that Piaget could period of Piaget’s sixth sensorimotor sub-
not have foreseen because of his lack of stage of mental invention of new behavioral
knowledge of mirror neurons and the system combinations at 18 months of age is quite
built on them, it is possible to suggest that a consistent with the properties of that age
less rich and leaner interpretation of the period. That is, at this age infants are con-
empathic and prosocial type behavior that is cerned with victims even if they do not mani-
being described for the 4- to 6-month period fest openly their distress. This shows that
is not that nice and mean behaviors are being infants at this age can infer by mental combi-
differentiated nor that mental state infer- nation the mental state of another person and
ences are being made, but that infants at this feel emotions accordingly. However, I main-
age are merely acting out of self-similarity tain that careful analysis of the behavior
recognition in their behavior. In this regard, involved would reveal some vestige of senso-
the behavior at issue is engaging the other rimotor action. It is only at 24 months of age
party perceived as like oneself. Does the that Piaget’s model would allow for
380 15 Connecting the Social Dots

completely action-divorced representation, areas of social behavior and cognition. Basically,


as in language and pretend play. the model describes five stages in development
quite consistent with those of Piaget. Essentially,
it adds a reflexive stage before the sensorimotor
Conclusion one and a collective intelligence stage after the
formal, abstract stage. The perioperational stage
The extensive literature review undertaken on the consists of Piaget’s preoperational and concrete
development of empathy and prosocial behavior operational stages, a period to which he referred
has allowed for comparison of the research with to as representational. There are simplified way
Piaget’s model, but with the model of “like me” of describing the major foci in the stages—for
(Meltzoff, 2007) used as well. Piaget’s model example, from the physical to the spiritual.
appears to have served as a good scaffold to help In my work, I have extrapolated to what this
understand the changes in empathy and prosocial might mean for the development of empathy and
behavior from one age to the next in the infancy theory of mind. These are conjectures simply to
period. Moreover, it stands as a compromise path show that (a) the developments involved might
in the sometimes vociferous debate whether the have a cognitive stage or substage basis beyond
nativist or gradual acquisition approach to the the empirical demonstrations of their changes
behaviors involved applies. The model has helped and (b) that the Neo-Piagetian approach might
avoid the rich interpretation of the findings in help hone understanding of the progressions that
terms of the nativist account, but it is not neces- might be involved.
sarily a lean one that describes the situation bet-
ter, given the relatively advanced acquisitions
that Piaget’s account can help explain even in the
earliest substages of infancy.
References
My Neo-Piagetian model of the stages and Anderson, V., & Beauchamp, M. H. (Eds.). (2012a).
substages of development is highly compatible Developmental social neuroscience and childhood
with the Piagetian substage series because I built brain insult: Theory and practice. New York: Guilford
my model especially by considering them. In this Press.
Anderson, V., & Beauchamp, M. H. (2012b). Social: A
regard, the six substages involved in infancy in theoretical model of developmental social neurosci-
my model involve reflex coordination, which I ence. In V. Anderson & M. H. Beauchamp (Eds.),
split off from the other five sensorimotor sub- Developmental social neuroscience and childhood
stages, and then the five sensorimotor substages, brain insult: Theory and practice (pp. 3–20).
New York: Guilford Press.
which I relabeled coordination, hierarchization, Baumeister, R. F. (2012). Human evil: The myth of pure
systematization, multiplication, and integration. evil and the true causes of violence. In M. Mikulincer
Careful inspection of the empirical findings used & P. R. Shaver (Eds.), The social psychology of moral-
in the present section will show that the charac- ity: Exploring the causes of good and evil (pp. 367–
380). Washington, DC: American Psychological
teristics of the behaviors that I would predict at Association.
each age period in infancy are indeed evident in Baumeister, R. F., & Graham, J. (2012). Good and evil,
the empirical findings. In fact, it can be no other past and future, laboratory and world. In M. Mikulincer
way in that the reworking of Piaget’s series in my & P. R. Shaver (Eds.), The social psychology of moral-
ity: Exploring the causes of good and evil (pp. 401–
model fits his series and the empirical findings 412). Washington, DC: American Psychological
discussed in this chapter have been shown to fit Association.
his model, so that, by transposition, the findings Beauchamp, M., & Anderson, V. (2010). Social: An inte-
involved must fit my model. grative framework for the development of social skills.
Psychological Bulletin, 136, 255–260.
To elaborate further my full model, in Young Bechara, A., & Damasio, A. R. (2005). The somatic
(2011), I presented a Neo-Piagetian model of marker hypothesis: A neural theory of economic deci-
cognitive development and applied it to multiple sion. Games and Economic Behavior, 52, 336–372.
References 381

Beck, A. T. (1967). Depression: Clinical, experimental, National Academy of Sciences, USA, 104,
and theoretical aspects. New York: Harper & Row. 17825–17830.
Beck, A. T. (1983). Cognitive theory of depression: New Chakroff, A., & Young, L. (2014). The prosocial brain:
perspectives. In P. J. Clayton & J. E. Barrett (Eds.), Perceiving others in need and acting on it. In L. M.
Treatment of depression: Old controversies and new Padilla-Walker & G. Carlo (Eds.), Prosocial develop-
approaches. New York: Raven. ment: A multidimensional approach (pp. 90–111).
Belsky, J., & Fearon, R. M. P. (2002). Early attachment New York: Oxford University Press.
security, subsequent maternal sensitivity, and later Chernyak, N., & Kushnir, T. (2013). Giving preschoolers
child development: Does continuity in development choice increases sharing behavior. Psychological
depend on continuity of caregiver? Attachment and Science, 24, 1971–1979.
Human Development, 4, 361–387. Choma, B. L., Hafer, C. L., Dywan, J., Segalowitz, S. J.,
Belsky, J., & Pluess, M. (2009). The nature (and nurture?) & Busseri, M. A. (2012). Political liberalism and
of plasticity in early human development. Perspectives political conservatism: Functionally independent?
on Psychological Science, 4, 345–351. Personality and Individual Differences, 53, 431–436.
Blair, R. J. R., & Fowler, K. (2008). Moral emotions and Cirelli, L. K., Einarson, K. M., & Trainor, L. J. (2014).
moral reasoning from the perspective of affective cog- Interpersonal synchrony increases prosocial behavior
nitive neuroscience: A selective review. European in infants. Developmental Science, 17, 1003–1011.
Journal of Developmental Science, 2, 303–323. Cook, R., Bird, G., Catmur, C., Press, C., & Heyes, C.
Block, J., & Block, J. H. (2006). Nursery school personal- (2014). Mirror neurons: From origin to function.
ity and political orientation two decades later. Journal Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 37, 177–241.
of Research in Personality, 40, 734–749. Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (2013). Evolutionary psychol-
Bloom, P. (2012). Moral nativism and moral psychology. ogy: New perspectives on cognition and motivation.
In M. Mikulincer & P. R. Shaver (Eds.), The social Annual Review of Psychology, 64, 201–229.
psychology of morality: Exploring the causes of good Costa, P. T., & McCrae, R. R. (1992). The five-factor
and evil (pp. 71–89). Washington, DC: American model of personality and its relevance to personality
Psychological Association. disorders. Journal of Personality Disorders, 6,
Boyd, R., & Richerson, P. J. (1985). Culture and the evo- 343–359.
lutionary process. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Dahl, A. (2014). Definitions and developmental processes
Press. in research on infant morality. Human Development,
Byrne, R. W. (1994). The evolution of intelligence. In J. 57, 241–249.
B. Slater & T. R. Halliday (Eds.), Behaviour and evo- Dahl, A. (2015). The developing social context of infant
lution (pp. 223-265). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge helping in two U.S. samples. Child Development, 86,
University Press. 1080–1093.
Cannon, E. N., Simpson, E. A., Fox, N. A., Vanderwert, Dahl, A., Schuck, R. K., & Campos, J. J. (2013). Do
R. E., Woodward, A. L., & Ferrari, P. F. (2016). young toddlers act on their social preferences?
Relations between infants’ emerging reach-grasp com- Developmental Psychology, 49, 1964–1970.
petence and event-related desynchronization in EEG. Damasio, A. R. (1994). Descartes’ error: Emotion, rea-
Developmental Science, 19, 50–62. son, and the human brain. New York: Grosset/Putnam.
Carney, D. R., Jost, J. T., Gosling, S. D., & Potter, Damasio, A. R. (1995). Toward a neurobiology of emo-
J. (2008). The secret lives of liberals and conserva- tion and feeling: Operational concepts and hypothe-
tives: Personality profiles, interaction styles, and the ses. The Neuroscientist, 1, 19–25.
things they leave behind. Political Psychology, 29, Damasio, A. R., Anderson, S. W., & Tranel, D. (2011).
807–840. The frontal lobes. In K. M. Heilman & E. Valenstein
Carpendale, J. I. M. (2009). Piaget’s theory of moral devel- (Eds.), Clinical neuropsychology (4th ed., pp. 417–
opment. In U. Müller, J. I. M. Carpendale, & L. Smith 465). New York: Oxford University Press.
(Eds.), Cambridge companion to Piaget (pp. 270–286). Damasio, A. R., Tranel, D., & Damasio, H. (1998).
New York: Cambridge University Press. Somatic markers and the guidance of behavior. In J. M.
Caspi, A., Sugden, K., Moffitt, T. E., Taylor, A., Craig, Jenkins, K. Oatley, & N. L. Stein (Eds.), Human emo-
I. W., Harrington, H., et al. (2003). Influence of life tions: A reader (pp. 122–135). Malden, MA: Blackwell.
stress on depression: Moderation by a polymorphism Davidov, M., Zahn-Waxler, C., Roth-Hanania, R., &
in the 5-HTT gene. Science, 301, 386–389. Knafo, A. (2013). Concern for others in the first year
Castiello, U., Becchio, C., Zoia, S., Nelini, C., Sartori, L., of life: Theory, evidence, and avenues for research.
Blason, L., et al. (2010). Wired to be social: The Child Development Perspectives, 7, 126–131.
ontogeny of human interaction. PLoS One, 5, e13199. Davidson, R. J. (1992). Anterior cerebral asymmetry and the
doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0013199. nature of emotion. Brain and Cognition, 20, 125–151.
Cattaneo, L., Fabbi-Destro, M., Boria, S., Pieraccini, C., de Waal, F. B. M. (2012). A bottom-up view of empathy.
Monti, A., Cossu, G., & Rizzolatti, G. (2007). In F. B. M. de Waal & P. F. Ferrari (Eds.), The primate
Impairment of actions chains in autism and its possible mind: Built to connect with other minds (pp. 121–
role in intention understanding. Proceedings of the 138). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
382 15 Connecting the Social Dots

de Waal, F. B. M., & Ferrari, P. F. (Eds.). (2012). The pri- Feldman, R., & Eidelman, A. I. (2007). Maternal postpar-
mate mind: Built to connect with other minds. tum behavior and the emergence of infant-mother and
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. infant-father synchrony in preterm and full-term
Dean, L. G., Kendal, R. L., Schapiro, S. J., Thierry, B., & infants: The role of neonatal vagal tone. Developmental
Laland, K. N. (2012). Identification of the social and Psychobiology, 49, 290–302.
cognitive processes underlying human cumulative cul- Feldman, R., Magori-Cohen, R., Galili, G., Singer, M., &
ture. Science, 335, 1114–1118. Louzoun, Y. (2011). Mother and infant coordinate heart
Decety, J., & Howard, L. H. (2014). Emotion, morality, rhythms through episodes of interaction synchrony.
and the developing brain. In M. Mikulincer & P. R. Infant Behavior & Development, 34, 569–577.
Shaver (Eds.), Mechanisms of social connection: Feldman, R., Zagoory-Sharon, O., Maoz, R., Weisman,
From brain to group (pp. 105–122). Washington, DC: O., Gordon, I., Schneiderman, I., et al. (2012).
American Psychological Association. Sensitive patenting is associated with plasma oxytocin
Decety, J., & Michalska, K. J. (2010). Neurodevelopmental and polymorphisms in the OXTR and CD38 genes.
changes in the circuits underlying empathy and sym- Biological Psychiatry, 72, 175–181.
pathy from childhood to adulthood. Developmental Ferrari, P. F., & Fogassi, L. (2012). The mirror neuron sys-
Science, 13, 886–899. tem in monkeys and its implications for social cognitive
Decety, J., Michalska, K. J., & Kinzler, K. D. (2012). The functions. In F. B. M. de Waal & P. F. Ferrari (Eds.), The
contribution of emotion and cognition to moral sensi- primate mind: Built to connect with other minds
tivity: A neurodevelopmental study. Cerebral Cortex, (pp. 13–31). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
22, 209–220. Fivush, R. (2011). The development of autobiographical
Dondi, M., Simion, F., & Caltran, G. (1999). Can new- memory. In S. T. Fiske, D. L. Schacter, & S. E. Taylor
borns discriminate between their own cry and the (Eds.), Annual review of psychology (Vol. 62, pp. 559–
cry of another newborn infant? Developmental 582). Palo Alto, CA: Annual Reviews.
Psychology, 35, 418–426. Fletcher, G. J. O., Simpson, J. A., Campbell, L., &
Dunbar, R. I. M. (2013). An evolutionary basis for social Overall, N. C. (2015). Pair-bonding, romantic love,
cognition. In M. Legerstee, D. W. Haley, & M. H. and evolution: The curious case of Homo sapiens.
Bornstein (Eds.), The infant mind: Origins of the Perspectives on Psychological Science, 10, 20–36.
social brain (pp. 3–19). New York: Guilford Press. Fogarty, L., Strimling, P., & Laland, K. N. (2011). The
Ellis, B. J., & Boyce, W. T. (2008). Biological sensitivity evolution of teaching. Evolution, 65, 2760–2770.
to context. Current Directions in Psychological Fogassi, L., & Rizzolatti, G. (2013). The mirror mecha-
Science, 17, 183–187. nism as neurophysiological basis for action and inten-
Ellis, B. J., Boyce, W. T., Belsky, J., Bakermans- tion understanding. In A. Suarez & P. Adams (Eds.), Is
Kranenburg, M. J., & van IJzendoorn, M. H. (2011). science compatible with free will? Exploring free will
Differential susceptibility to the environment: An and consciousness in the light of quantum physics and
evolutionary-neurodevelopmental theory. neuroscience (pp. 117–134). New York: Springer
Development and Psychopathology, 23, 7–28. Science + Business Media.
Erikson, E. H. (1963). Childhood and society (2nd ed.). Fox, N. A. (1994). Dynamic cerebral processes underly-
New York: Norton. ing emotion regulation. In N. A. Fox (Ed.), The devel-
Feldman, R. (2007a). Mother-infant synchrony and the opment of emotion regulation: Biological and
development of moral orientation in childhood behavioral considerations. Monographs of the Society
and adolescent: Direct and indirect mechanisms of for Research in Child Development, 59 (2–3, Serial
developmental continuity. American Journal of No. 240), 152–166.
Orthopsychiatry, 77, 582–597. Fox, N. A., Rubin, K. H., Calkins, S. D., Marshall, T. R.,
Feldman, R. (2007b). On the origins of background emo- Coplan, R. J., Porges, S. W., et al. (1995). Frontal acti-
tions: From affect synchrony to symbolic expression. vation asymmetry and social competence at four years
Emotion, 7, 601–611. of age. Child Development, 66, 1770–1784.
Feldman, R. (2010). The relational basis of adolescent Fraley, R. C., Griffin, B. N., Belsky, J., & Roisman, G. I.
adjustment: Trajectories of mother-child interactive (2012). Developmental antecedents of political ideol-
behaviors from infancy to adolescence shape adoles- ogy: A longitudinal investigation from birth to age 18
cent’s adaptation. Attachment & Human Development, years. Psychological Science, 23, 1425–1431.
12, 173–192. Gallese, V. (2006). Intentional attunement: A neurophysi-
Feldman, R. (2014). Synchrony and the neurobiological ological perspective on social cognition and its disrup-
basis of social affiliation. In M. Mikulincer & P. R. tion in autism. Brain Research, 1079, 15–24.
Shaver (Eds.), Mechanisms of social cognition: From Gallese, V., & Rochat, M. (2013). The evolution of motor
brain to group (pp. 145–166). Washington, DC: cognition: Its role in the development of social cogni-
American Psychological Association. tion and implications for autism spectrum disorder. In
Feldman, R. (2015). Sensitive periods in human social M. Legerstee, D. W. Haley, & M. H. Bornstein (Eds.),
development: New insights from research on oxyto- The infant mind: Origins of the social brain
cin, synchrony, and high-risk parenting. Development (pp. 19–48). New York: Guilford Press.
and Psychopathology, 27, 369–395.
References 383

Geangu, E., Benga, O., Stahl, D., & Striano, T. (2010). Hammond, S. L., & Carpendale, J. I. M. (2012).
Contagious crying beyond the first days of life. Infant Rethinking children’s everyday help: Often active,
Behavior & Development, 33, 279–288. occasionally unhelpful, and guided by parents. Poster
Geraci, A., & Surian, L. (2011). The developmental roots presented at the biennial meeting of the International
of fairness: Infants’ reactions to equal and unequal dis- Society on Infant Studies, Minneapolis, MN.
tributions of resources. Developmental Science, 14, Hastings, P. D., & De, I. (2008). Parasympathetic regula-
1012–1020. tion and parental socialization of emotion:
Gergely, G., Bekkering, H., & Király, I. (2002). Rational Biopsychosocial processes of adjustment in pre-
imitation in preverbal infants. Nature, 415, 755. schoolers. Social Development, 17, 211–238.
doi:10.1038/415755a. Hastings, P. D., Ruttle, P. L., Serbin, L. A., Mills, R. S. L.,
Govrin, A. (2014). The ABC of moral development: An Stack, D. M., & Schwartzman, A. E. (2011).
attachment approach to moral judgment. Frontiers in Adrenocortical responses to strangers in preschoolers:
Psychology, 5, 1–15. Relations with parenting, temperament, and psychopa-
Gray, J. A. (1990). Brain systems that mediate both emo- thology. Developmental Psychobiology, 53, 694–710.
tion and cognition. Cognition and Emotion, 4, Hastings, P. D., Sullivan, C., McShane, K. E., Coplan,
269–288. R. J., Utendale, W. T., & Vyncke, J. D. (2008). Parental
Greene, J. D. (2007). Why are VMPFC patients more socialization, vagal regulation, and preschoolers’ anx-
utilitarian? A dual-process theory of moral judgment ious difficulties: Direct mothers and moderated
explains. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 11, 322–323. fathers. Child Development, 79, 45–64.
Habermas, T., & Bluck, S. (2000). Getting a life: The Henrich, J. (2011). A cultural species: How culture drove
emergence of the life story in adolescence. human evolution. A multi-disciplinary framework for
Psychological Bulletin, 126, 748–769. understanding culture, cognition and behavior.
Halliday, M. A. K., & Hasan, R. (1976). Cohesion in Psychological Science Agenda. http://www.apa.org/
English. London: Longman. science/about/psa/2011/11/human-evolution.aspx
Hamann, K., Warneken, F., & Tomasello, M. (2012). Herrmann, E., Misch, A., Hernandez-Lloreda, V., &
Children’s developing commitments to joint goals. Tomasello, M. (2015). Uniquely human self-control
Child Development, 83, 137–145. begins at school age. Developmental Science, 18,
Hamlin, J. K. (2014a). Context-dependent social evalua- 979–993.
tion in 4.5-month-old human infants: The role of Hölldobler, B., & Wilson, E. O. (2009). The superorgan-
domain-general versus domain-specific processes in ism: The beauty, elegance and strangeness of insect
the development of social evaluation. Frontiers in societies. New York: Norton.
Psychology, 5, 614. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00614. Hopper, L. M., Marshall-Pescini, S., & Whiten, A. (2012).
Hamlin, J. K. (2014b). The conceptual and empirical case Social learning and culture in child and chimpanzee.
for social evaluation in infancy. Human Development, In F. B. M. de Waal & P. F. Ferrari (Eds.), The primate
57, 250–258. mind: Built to connect with other minds (pp. 99–118).
Hamlin, J. K. (2015). The case of social evaluation in pre- Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
verbal infants: Gazing toward one’s goal drives Howe, M. L., & Courage, M. L. (1997). The emergence
infants’ preferences for helpers over hinderers in the and early development of autobiographical memory.
hill paradigm. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 1563. Psychological Review, 104, 499–523.
doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.01563. Janoff-Bulman, R. (2009). To provide or protect:
Hamlin, J. K., Mahajan, N., Liberman, Z., & Wynn, K. Motivational bases of political liberalism and conser-
(2013). Not like me = bad: Infants prefer those who vatism. Psychological Inquiry, 20, 120–128.
harm dissimilar others. Psychological Science, 24, Janoff-Bulman, R. (2012). Conscience: The do’s and
589–594. don’ts of moral regulation. In M. Milkuciner &
Hamlin, J. K., & Wynn, K. (2011). Young infants prefer P. Shaver (Eds.), The social psychology of morality:
prosocial to antisocial others. Cognitive Development, Exploring the causes of good and evil (pp. 131–148).
26, 30–39. Washington, DC: American Psychological
Hamlin, J. K., Wynn, K., & Bloom, P. (2007). Social eval- Association.
uation by preverbal infants. Nature, 450, 557–559. Jensen, K., Vaish, A., & Schmidt, M. F. H. (2014). The
Hamlin, J. K., Wynn, K., & Bloom, P. (2010). 3-month- emergence of human prosociality: Aligning with oth-
olds show a negativity bias in their social evaluations. ers through feelings, concerns, and norms. Frontiers in
Developmental Science, 13, 923–929. Psychology, 5, 1–16.
Hamlin, J. K., Wynn, K., Bloom, P., & Mahajan, N. Kärtner, J. (2015). The autonomous developmental path-
(2011). How infants and toddlers react to antisocial way: The primacy of subjective mental states for
others. Proceedings of the National Academy of human behavior and experience. Child Development,
Sciences, USA, 108, 19931–19936. 86, 1298–1309.
Hammond, S. I. (2014). Children’s early helping in action: Kemp, M., & Mesoudi, A. (2014). Experimental and theo-
Piagetian developmental theory and early prosocial retical models of human cultural evolution. Wiley
behavior. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 759. doi:10.3389/ Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science, 5,
fpsyg.2014.00759. 317–326.
384 15 Connecting the Social Dots

Kesebir, S. (2012). The superorganism account of human McAdams, D. P. (2013). The psychological self as actor,
sociality: How and when human groups are like bee- agent, and author. Perspectives on Psychological
hives. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 16, Science, 8, 272–295.
233–261. McAdams, D. P., Hanek, K. J., & Dadabo, J. G. (2013).
Knafo-Noam, A., Uzefovsky, F., Israel, S., Davidov, M., Themes of self-regulation and self-exploration in the
& Zahn-Waxler, C. (2015). The prosocial personality life stories of religious American conservatives and
and its facets: Genetic and environmental architecture liberals. Political Psychology, 34, 201–219.
of mother-reported behavior of 7-year-old twins. McAdams, D. P., & Pals, J. L. (2006). A new big five:
Frontiers in Psychology, 6, 112. doi:10.3389/ Fundamental principles for an integrative science of
fpsyg.2015.00112. personality. American Psychologist, 61, 204–217.
Knudsen, B., & Liszkowski, U. (2012a). 18-month-olds McFarland, S., Brown, D., & Webb, M. (2013).
predict specific action mistakes through attribution of Identification with all humanity as a moral concept
false belief, not ignorance, and intervene accordingly. and psychological construct. Current Directions in
Infancy, 17, 672–691. Psychological Science, 22, 194–198.
Knudsen, B., & Liszkowski, U. (2012b). Eighteen- and Meltzoff, A. N. (2007). “Like me”: A foundation for
24-month-old infants correct others in anticipation of social cognition. Developmental Science, 10,
action mistakes. Developmental Science, 15, 113–122. 126–134.
Knudsen, B., & Liszkowski, U. (2013). One-year-olds Meltzoff, A. N., & Moore, M. K. (1997). Explaining
warn others about negative action outcomes. Journal facial imitation: A theoretical model. Early
of Cognition and Development, 14, 424–436. Development and Parenting, 6, 179–192.
Kuhlmeier, V. A., Dunfield, K. A., & O’Neill, A. C. Mesoudi, A. (2011). Cultural evolution: How Darwinian
(2014). Selectivity in early prosocial behavior. theory can explain human culture and synthesize the
Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 1–6. social sciences. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago
Kurzban, R., Burton-Chellew, M. N., & West, S. A. Press.
(2015). The evolution of altruism in humans. Annual Michael, J., Sandberg, K., Skewes, J., Wolf, T., Blicher, J.,
Review of Psychology, 66, 575–599. Overgaard, M., et al. (2014). Continuous theta-burst
Lamm, C., Decety, J., & Singer, T. (2011). Meta-analytic stimulation demonstrates a causal role of premotor
evidence for common and distinct neural networks homunculus in action understanding. Psychological
associated with directly experienced pain and empathy Science, 25, 963–972.
for pain. NeuroImage, 54, 2492–2502. Mikulincer, M., & Shaver, P. R. (2012). The social psy-
Legerstee, M. (2013). The developing social brain: Social chology of morality: Exploring the causes of good and
connections and social bonds, social loss, and jealousy evil. Washington, DC: American Psychological
in infancy. In M. Legerstee, D. W. Haley, & M. H. Association.
Bornstein (Eds.), The infant mind: Origins of the Mikulincer, M., & Shaver, P. R. (2014a). Mechanisms of
social brain (pp. 233–248). New York: Guilford Press. social connection: From brain to group. Washington,
Liszkowski, U., Carpenter, M., & Tomasello, M. (2008). DC: American Psychological Association.
Twelve-month-olds communicate helpfully and Mikulincer, M., & Shaver, P. R. (2014b). Introduction. In
appropriately for knowledgeable and ignorant part- M. Mikulincer & P. R. Shaver (Eds.), Mechanisms of
ners. Cognition, 108, 732–739. social connection: From brain to group (pp. 3–12).
Lodder, P., Rotteveel, M., & van Elk, M. (2014). Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.
Enactivism and neonatal imitation: Conceptual and Nielsen, M. (2012). Imitation, pretend play, and child-
empirical considerations and clarifications. Frontiers hood: Essential elements in the evolution of human
in Psychology, 5, 1–11. culture? Journal of Comparative Psychology, 126,
Martin, A., & Olson, K. R. (2013). When kids know bet- 170–181.
ter: Paternalistic helping in 3-year-old children. Obradović, J., Bush, N. R., Stamperdahl, J., Adler, N. E.,
Developmental Psychology, 49, 2071–2081. & Boyce, W. T. (2010). Biological sensitivity to con-
Martin, A., & Olson, K. R. (2015). Beyond good and evil: text: The interactive effects of stress reactivity and
What motivations underlie children’s prosocial behavior? family adversity on socioemotional behavior and
Perspectives on Psychological Science, 10, 159–175. school readiness. Child Development, 81, 270–289.
Masten, C. L., Morelli, S. A., & Eisenberger, N. I. (2011). Osborne, D., Wootton, L. W., & Sibley, C. G. (2013). Are
An fMRI investigation of empathy for “social pain” liberals agreeable or not? Politeness and compassion
and subsequent prosocial behavior. Neuroimaging, 55, differentially predict political conservatism via dis-
381–388. tinct ideologies. Social Psychology, 44, 354–360.
Max, J. E. (2012). Pediatric brain-injury-related psychiat- Parks, C. D., Joireman, J., & Van Lange, P. A. M. (2013).
ric disorders and social function. In V. Anderson & Cooperation, trust, and antagonism: How public goods
M. H. Beauchamp (Eds.), Developmental social neu- are promoted. Psychological Science in the Public
roscience and childhood brain insult: Theory and Interest, 14, 119–165.
practice (pp. 284–298). New York: Guilford Press. Paulus, M. (2014). The emergence of prosocial behavior:
McAdam, D. P., & McLean, K. C. (2013). Narrative iden- Why do infants and toddlers help, comfort, and share?
tity. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 22, Child Development Perspectives, 8, 77–81.
233–238.
References 385

Paulus, M., Hunnius, S., Vissers, M., & Bekkering, H. Parental belief systems: The psychological conse-
(2011a). Bridging the gap between the other and me: quences for children (pp. 287–318). Hillsdale, NJ:
The functional role of motor resonance and action Erlbaum.
effects in infants’ imitation. Developmental Science, Schlenker, B. R., Chambers, J. R., & Le, B. M. (2012).
14, 901–910. Conservatives are happier than liberals, but why?
Paulus, M., Hunnius, S., Vissers, M., & Bekkering, H. Political ideology, personality, and life satisfaction.
(2011b). Imitation in infancy: Rational or motor reso- Journal of Research in Personality, 46, 127–146.
nance? Child Development, 82, 1047–1057. Schmidt, M. F. H., Rakoczy, H., & Tomasello, M. (2012).
Piaget, J. (1932/1997). The moral judgement of the child. Young children enforce social norms selectively
New York: The Free Press. depending on the violator’s group affiliation.
Piaget, J. (1945/1951). Play, dreams, and imitations in Cognition, 124, 325–333.
childhood. London: W. Heinemann. Schmidt, M. F. H., & Sommerville, J. A. (2011). Fairness
Piaget, J. (1970). Piaget’s theory. In P. Mussen (Ed.), expectations and altruistic sharing in 15-month-old
Handbook of child psychology (Vol. 1, 3rd ed.). human infants. PLoS One, 6, e23223. doi:10.1371/
New York: Wiley. journal.pone.0023223.
Piaget, J. (1976). The grasp of consciousness. Cambridge, Shai, D., & Fonagy, P. (2014). Beyond words: Parental
MA: Harvard University Press. embodied mentalizing and the parent-infant dance. In
Powell, K. B., & Voeller, K. S. (2004). Prefrontal execu- M. Mikulincer & P. R. Shaver (Eds.), Mechanisms of
tive function syndromes in children. Journal of Child social connection: From brain to group (pp. 185–203).
Neurology, 19, 785–797. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.
Pulfrey, C., & Butera, F. (2013). Why neoliberal values of Sharp, C., Pane, H., Ha, C., Venta, A., Pate, A. B., Sturek,
self-enhancement lead to cheating in higher education: J., Fonagy, P. (2011). Theory of mind and emotion
A motivational account. Psychological Science, 24, regulation difficulties in adolescents with borderline
2153–2162. traits. Journal of the American Academy of Child and
Rameson, L. T., Morelli, S. A., & Liberman, M. D. (2012). Adolescent Psychiatry, 50, 563–573.
The neural correlates of empathy: Experience, auto- Shaver, P. R., & Mikulincer, M. (2012). An attachment
maticity, and prosocial behavior. Journal of Cognitive perspective on morality: Strengthening authentic
Neuroscience, 24, 235–245. forms of moral decision making. In M. Mikulincer &
Riedl, K., Jensen, K., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2011). P. R. Shaver (Eds.), The social psychology of morality:
No third party punishment in chimpanzees. Exploring the causes of good and evil (pp. 257–274).
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.
USA, 109, 14824–14829. Singer, T., & Hein, G. (2012). Human empathy through
Rizzolatti, G. (2014). Confounding the origin and func- the lens of psychology and social neuroscience. In
tion of mirror neurons. Behavior and Brain Sciences, F. B. M. de Waal & P. F. Ferrari (Eds.), The primate
37, 218–219. mind: Built to connect with other minds (pp. 158–
Rochat, P. (2003). Five levels of self-awareness as they 174). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
unfold early in life. Consciousness and Cognition, 12, Smaldino, P. E. (2014a). The cultural evolution of emer-
717–731. gent group-level traits. Behavioral and Brain Sciences,
Root, A. E., Hastings, P. D., & Maxwell, K. L. (2012). 37, 243–254.
Environmental contribution to the development of Smaldino, P. E. (2014b). Group-level traits emerge.
social competence: Focus on parents. In V. Anderson Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 37, 281–288.
& M. H. Beauchamp (Eds.), Developmental social Sommerville, J. A., Schmidt, M. F. H., Yun, J.-E., &
neuroscience and childhood brain insult: Theory and Burns, M. (2013). The development of fairness expec-
practice (pp. 91–115). New York: Guilford Press. tations and prosocial behavior in the second year of
Rothbart, M. K., Ahadi, S. A., Hershey, K. L., & Fisher, P. life. Infancy, 18, 40–66.
(2001). Investigations of temperament at 3–7 years: Taber-Thomas, B. C., & Tranel, D. (2012). Social and
The Children’s Behavior Questionnaire. Child moral functioning: A cognitive neuroscience perspec-
Development, 72, 1394–1408. tive. In V. Anderson & M. H. Beauchamp (Eds.),
Roth-Hanania, R., Davidov, M., & Zahn-Waxler, C. Developmental social neuroscience and childhood
(2011). Empathy development from 8 to 16 months: brain insult: Theory and practice (pp. 65–90).
Early signs of concern for others. Infant Behavior and New York: Guilford Press.
Development, 34, 447–458. Tafreshi, D., Thompson, J. J., & Racine, T. P. (2014). An
Scarf, D., Imuta, K., Colombo, M., & Hayne, H. (2012). analysis of the conceptual foundations of the infant
Golden rule or valence matching? Methodological preferential looking paradigm. Human Development,
problems in Hamlin et al. Proceedings of the National 57, 222–240.
Academy of Sciences, USA, 109, E1426. doi:10.1073/ Thomas, B. C., Croft, K. E., & Tranel, D. (2011). Harming
pnas.1204123109. kin to save strangers: Further evidence for abnormally
Schaefer, E. S., & Edgerton, M. (1985). Parent and child utilitarian moral judgments after ventromedial pre-
correlates of parental modernity. In I. E. Sigel (Ed.),
386 15 Connecting the Social Dots

frontal damage. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, behavior. The Journal of Neuroscience, 32,
23, 2186–2196. 7646–7650.
Tomasello, M., & Vaish, A. (2013). Origins of human Wilson, D. S. (1975). A theory of group selection.
cooperation and morality. Annual Review of Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences,
Psychology, 64, 231–255. USA, 72, 143–146.
Tucker, D. M., Poulsen, C., & Luu, P. (2015). Critical Wilson, D. S. (2014). Groups as units of functional analy-
periods for the neurodevelopmental processes of sis, individuals as proximate mechanisms. Behavioral
externalizing and internalizing. Development and and Brain Sciences, 37, 279–280.
Psychopathology, 27, 321–346. Wilson, G. D., & Patterson, J. R. (1968). A new measure
Uithol, S., & Gallese, V. (2015). The role of the body in of conservatism. British Journal of Social and Clinical
social cognition. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Psychology, 7, 264–269.
Cognitive Science, 6, 453–460. Woodcock, R. W. (1990). Theoretical foundations of the
Vaish, A., Carpenter, M., & Tomasello, M. (2009). Wj-R measures of cognitive ability. Journal of
Sympathy through affective perspective-taking and its Psychoeducational Assessment, 8, 231–258.
relation to prosocial behavior in toddlers. Woodcock, R. W., & Johnson, M. B. (1989). Woodcock-
Developmental Psychology, 45, 534–543. Johnson Psycho-Educational Battery-Revised. Allen,
Vaish, A., Missana, M., & Tomasello, M. (2011). Three- TX: DLM.
year-old children intervene in third-party moral trans- Woodward, A. L. (2009). Infants’ grasp of others’ inten-
gressions. British Journal of Developmental tions. Current Direction in Psychological Science, 18,
Psychology, 29, 124–130. 53–57.
Vaish, A., & Tomasello, M. (2014). The early ontogeny of Wrangham, R. W. (2009). Catching fire: How cooking
human cooperation and morality. In M. Killen & J. G. made us human. New York: Basic Books.
Smetana (Eds.), Handbook of moral development (2nd Yeates, K. O., Bigler, E. D., Dennis, M., Gerhardt, C. A.,
ed., pp. 279–298). New York: Psychology Press. Rubin, K. H., Stancin, T., et al. (2007). Social out-
Warneken, F. (2013). Young children proactively remedy comes in childhood brain disorder: A heuristic integra-
unnoticed accidents. Cognition, 126, 101–108. tion of social neuroscience and developmental
Warneken, F. (2015). Precocious prosociality: Why do psychology. Psychological Bulletin, 133, 535–556.
young children help? Child Development Perspectives, Yeates, K. O., Bigler, E. D., Gerhardt, C. A., Rubin, K. H.,
9, 1–6. Stancin, T., Taylor, H. G., et al. (2012). Theoretical
Warneken, F., Gräfenhain, M., & Tomasello, M. (2012). approaches to understanding social function in child-
Collaborative partner or social tool? New evidence for hood brain insults: Toward the integration of social
young children’s understanding of joint intentions in neuroscience and developmental psychology. In
collaborative activities. Developmental Science, 15, V. Anderson & M. H. Beauchamp (Eds.),
54–61. Developmental social neuroscience and childhood
Warneken, F., & Tomasello, M. (2008). Extrinsic rewards brain insult: Theory and practice (pp. 207–230).
undermine altruistic tendencies in 20-month-olds. New York: Guilford Press.
Developmental Psychology, 44, 1785–1788. Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
Waters, S. F., West, T. V., & Mendes, W. B. (2014). Stress Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer
contagion: Physiological covariation between mothers Science + Business Media.
and infants. Psychological Science, 25, 934–942. Zmyj, N., & Buttelmann, D. (2014). An integrative model
Waytz, A., Zaki, J., & Mitchell, J. P. (2012). Response of of rational imitation in infancy. Infant Behavior and
dorsomedial prefrontal cortex predicts altruistic Development, 37, 21–28.
Causal Learning: Understanding
the World 16

As for the empirical research, I review the


Chapter Introduction recent literature on causal learning relative to
each age period in childhood, in particular, and
The topic of causal learning is marked both by point to the contrasting perspectives supported
the common issues that bedevil the field of child by the research, such as in terms of the issues
development, in general, for example, related to about nativism versus empiricism, which consti-
how early it develops and through what pro- tutes a debate, in general, in child development.
cesses, and by striking innovations in its own The area is a dynamic, fast-evolving one, because
terms in thought and theory as well as in empiri- casual reasoning provides a window on cognitive
cal research. Some of the issues on causal learn- development (and causality), in general.
ing relate to: whether it begins, at least in
primitive form, right from the first months of life;
whether it is innately prescribed or gradually Bayesian Learning Model
learned; and whether it is domain general or spe-
cific. Some of the methodological innovations in Introduction
the field include use of sticky mittens and everted
rabbits. The area of causal learning lies in the Gopnik and Wellman (2012) presented a Bayesian
forefront of modeling in child development learning model of mechanisms involved in con-
related to Bayesian learning, intervention structing cognitive theories in infancy and child-
accounts of causality, and rational constructiv- hood. They phrased their model in terms of
ism. Also, it is integrally related to research on reconstruction of constructivism, asking how
social cognition, theory of mind, and the “theory” concrete exemplars in the experience of the child
theory in these regards. could function in the development of abstract
In terms of theory related to causal learning, structures of knowledge. Extant accounts are
I provide discussion of cognitive schemas early either empirical/systemic or nativist/modular.
in life, and show how a more integrated view of Unfortunately, the authors dismissed the
early cognitive schemas affords compatibility Piagetian approach at the outset as being theo-
with the Piagetian view of cognitive develop- retically vague and empirically inadequate
ment and other views for the area of causal learn- (Piaget, 1926, 1930). However, I shall show that
ing. Moreover, I provide a Neo-Piagetian (sub) for the question of development of causality, it
stage model of cognitive development that is is rigorous on both counts and sets the stage
applicable to causal reasoning. for a combined Piagetian–Bayesian account.

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 387


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_16
388 16 Causal Learning: Understanding the World

The critical bridge to both lies in nonlinear For example, children move (a) from understand-
dynamical system theory, which Gopnik and ing action and intention with respect to others (b)
Wellman associated with the empiricist to representations and interpretations (theory of
approach, although it is atheoretical with respect mind). However, there is dispute whether initial
to the learning-genetic continuum of the origins perceptual structures and core knowledge consti-
of the components of the systems it examines tute intuitive theories or whether they are simply
and how they collate into wider, global wholes. innately-present “nontheoretical” structures. The
authors opt for the former stance.
Probabilistic or Bayesian models have been
Model applied to theory-like cognitive development
because they can help understand how children
Gopnik and Wellman (2012) referred to their build hypotheses, test them, and so on, trans-
approach to the development of causal models forming them into causal generative representa-
from the Bayesian perspective as “rational” con- tions. Bayes’ theorem can be represented as
structivism. Later in their article, they referred to P(H/E) α [P(E/H) P(H)], in which P = probabil-
the approach of Goodman, Ullman, and ity, H = hypothesized structure, E = Evidence,
Tenenbaum (2011) on “minimal” nativism in and / = given. P(H) is referred to as the prior,
early learning of causal models and theories. P(E/H) as the likelihood, and P(H/E) as the pos-
Either way, it appears that the infant is endowed terior. The rule, therefore, is that the posterior is
with necessary precursors to the ability to engage a function of the likelihood and of the prior.
in model and theory building and these mental A hypothesis can be represented by a map, tree,
structures can be constructed rapidly, including at or causal graph.
the rational, abstract level. One type of probabilistic model is termed
Gopnik and Wellman were involved in devel- causal Bayes nets, or causal graphical models
oping the particular constructivist model of cogni- (Pearl, 2000; Spirtes, Glymour, & Scheines,
tive development that has been labeled the 2001). Woodward (2003) developed an interven-
“theory” theory (e.g., Gopnik & Wellman, 1992; tionist account of causation that “dovetails” with
Wellman & Gelman, 1992). In this approach, chil- the causal Bayes net approach. In the approach,
dren first develop “intuitive” theories about the graphs with just a few nodes can generate multi-
world and, then, they revise them to fit new evi- ple predictions about events, and graph “surgery”
dence. The children’s theories include causal rep- or altering interventions (e.g., fixing variable val-
resentations about the world and, moreover, the ues) can be performed on the nodes to alter the
representations might coalesce into more global causal chains and probabilities involved. Or, one
“framework” theories. Children’s theories allow could ask what would happen counterfactually if
for interpretation, predictions, and wondering different variable values were in place.
how things might be different with the implemen-
tation of interventions (counterfactuals). These
theories dynamically evolve with new evidence, Research
including into the higher-order frameworks.
Children gather evidence by learning probabi- The empirical research with children has been
listic, statistical contingencies between events. supporting a Bayesian view of their representa-
Moreover, children learn about causal structures tional learning about causal structures, and also
by informally experimenting or acting on the that even infants can detect complex statistical
world, by playing, or by observing others. As patterns (for example, Wu, Gopnik, Richardson,
children revise their theories, they do so by revis- & Kirkham, 2011). Also, they can use probability
ing the probabilities associated with them and learning to infer causal properties.
alternatives. Gopnik, Sobel, Schulz, and Glymour (2001)
One of the areas of children’s theorizing conducted the first study in the area. Children
concerns the mind of others and the social world. were shown a “blicket” detector, which is an
Bayesian Learning Model 389

apparatus that lights up and plays music when an Elaboration


appropriate combination of block objects is
placed on it. Children who were as young as 2 ToM Gopnik and Wellman (2012) have inte-
years of age could infer the causal structure in the grated a major, rapidly evolving area in child
apparatus. In the study, children could use what development. Their work also includes descrip-
they learned causally to make the apparatus either tion of the steps that young children go through
stop or go. as they develop insight about mind. Wellman and
Gweon and Schulz (2011) found that even Liu (2004) created a ToM Scale that uses tasks
16-month-olds could infer causation from varia- that inform about the following progression,
tions in block placement. Sobel, Tenenbaum, which has been found in most cultures studied.
and Gopnik (2004) and Sobel and Kirkham (a) First, children develop to appreciate diverse
(2007) showed that children as young as 18 desires (having different desires targeting the
months of age could make correct causal infer- same thing). (b) Next, they develop diverse
ences from more complex statistical patterns. beliefs (having different beliefs about the same
Gopnik et al. (2004) found that children could situation). (c) Third, they develop awareness of
differentiate the direction of a causal relation- knowledge–ignorance (someone might not know
ship (A → B, not B → A). something that is true). (d) Older children then
Schulz, Gopnik, and Glymour (2007) found develop false belief (someone might believe
that 4-year-olds could work with three variables something different about something true, e.g.,
(A, B, C). Kushnir and Gopnik (2005) found that the classic Sally/Anne and Smarties box tasks;
4-year-olds could make inferences about proba- 4-year-olds but not 3-year-olds realize that if a
bilistic relations. Studies also showed that chil- peer or puppet do not see either displacement of
dren can integrate prior knowledge and new a hidden item or its contents (with the container
evidence (Griffiths, Sobel, Tenenbaum, & involved visibly indicating contents different
Gopnik, 2011; Kushnir & Gopnik, 2007). than what is in the container), then the other party
Children can make inferences in areas other will have a false belief on the task because the
than physical causation (e.g., psychological cau- 4-year-old can take the perspective of the viewer,
sation). Ma and Xu (2011) showed that 16-month- unlike the case for the 3-year-old). (e) Fifth, in
olds used probabilistic sampling in learning that hidden emotions, children learn that people can
another person’s desires could differ from their feel emotionally one way but display their emo-
own. For example, Kushnir, Xu, and Wellman tions publically in another way. The results fit the
found that 20-month-olds could use statistical Bayesian perspective because development
Bayesian reasoning in inferring the desires of changes as new evidence is experienced. Also,
another person, which is an underlying mental the order of the developmental sequence that is
state. Seiver, Gopnik, and Goodman (2013) described is found in most societies, but it can be
found that 4-year-olds could infer others’ per- altered in different cultural contexts.
sonal traits and use the information to predict
behavior patterns. Children can generalize from Abstraction Goodman et al. (2011), cited by
learned causal relationships to infer more abstract Gopnik and Wellman (2012), used the Bayesian
generalizations (Lucas, Gopnik, & Griffiths, framework to study the ideal learner, and their
2010; Schulz, Standing, & Bonawitz, 2008). work led to inferences for cognitive development.
Indeed, children might develop abstract frame- Their hierarchical Bayesian model, and the ideal
work theories before detailed specific ones, or learning paradigm, showed that learning can take
computational causal primitives constructed place simultaneously at the specific and abstract
from simpler patterns of evidence. levels. In fact, the learning that takes place at the
In the following, I indicate areas of child cogni- abstract level might be surprisingly fast, a phe-
tive development in which Bayesian modeling had nomenon referred to as the “blessing” of abstrac-
been applied. They include theory of mind (ToM), tion. In terms of infant learning, abstractions are
abstractions, generative modeling, and reasoning. acquired quickly, but this could not take place
390 16 Causal Learning: Understanding the World

without innate perceptual input “analyzers” the containing bin. When the experimental
(Carey, 2009). These modules perform simple parameters were varied, hypothesis selection
perceptual transformations of input, preparing for conformed to the posterior probability or distri-
further cognitive analysis. The perceptual input bution of hypotheses.
analyzers are domain-specific, and make input Bonawitz et al. (2014) determined that, on
suitable for domain-general inference. these types of tasks, children used a win-stay/
Goodman et al. (2011) viewed the world as a lose-shift strategy. They stayed with their origi-
collection of causal systems that infants can begin nal guess until the evidence became too strong
to model probabilistically. Then, learning about that it did not apply. In a trial-by-trial analysis,
events leads to full-scale models, which are further the authors showed that initial guesses exhibited
generalized into theory. Developmentally, abstrac- subsequent patterns of “dependencies” consistent
tions such as this could serve as scaffolds for later, with the win-stay/lose-shift strategy, such that the
language-mediated causal understanding. aggregate responses “approximated the exact
analytical Bayesian solution” (p. 500).
Generative Models Bonawitz, Denison, Griffiths, For the authors, this research illustrates that
and Gopnik (2014) postulated that children Bayesian modeling specifies the nature of gener-
appear to cope with multiple possible hypothe- ative models that children probabilistically con-
ses to explain the information before them by struct and the likelihood functions involved based
sampling hypotheses, rather than by producing on priors (formally, prior knowledge is expressed
the best guess or by naively matching frequency. in a distribution of “prior” probabilities over
Children might construct “generative” models hypotheses; in the ones to be sampled). The pre-
(intuitive theories). Moreover, they might revise cise quantitative predictions that derive in the
them through Bayesian inferences, using prior Bayesian approach to understanding children’s
knowledge. In Bayesian terms, Bayes’ rule spec- probabilistic sampling and learning needs further
ifies the way to compute a “posterior” distribu- work in other cognitive domains and tasks, as
tion that incorporates the information (data) at well as the types of algorithms involved and their
hand. This is a probabilistic approach to cogni- possible individual differences.
tive development, in which children appear to Gopnik and Bonawitz (2014) explained that in
“rationally” update a probability distribution of Bayesian learning, cognitive models help gener-
possible hypotheses in accordance with Bayes’ ate predictions about data—we create models
theorem and computations. based on data, and we revise them based on new
It is unlikely children assess all possible hypoth- data, all while using probability estimates of
eses in dealing with information, and so they appear which models might be the most probable. In
to use algorithms that maximize finding the most doing so, we start off with belief about which
likely hypotheses. The strategy is rational in that it models might be more probable (the priors). For
is a compromise between the cost of arriving at example, Kushnir, Xu, and Wellman (2010)
inductions that are in error and the cost of entertain- found that 20-month-olds could infer prefer-
ing more hypotheses by sampling all the possible ences/desires in terms of nonrandom patterns in
ones. Being guided by “priors” (prior knowledge) choice of objects. [In contrast, for a deterministic
provides a rational basis for limiting options to account of mental model building, see Khemlani,
those that are more likely. Barbey, & Jonson-Laird, 2014].
Denison, Bonawitz, Gopnik, and Griffiths
(2014) produced evidence in support of the Reasoning Rottman and Hastie (2013) provided a
Bayesian sampling hypothesis in children’s cog- tutorial on Bayesian probabilistic causal networks
nitive development. Children were exposed to a used in the study of reasoning and in making infer-
bin with varying amounts of red and blue chips. ences about causal relationships and networks.
The children “guessed” blue or red in the receiv- Causal cognition, in general, is an area of research
ing area in proportion to the color distribution in that can profit from the particular formalisms of
Piagetian Contributions to Understanding Causal Learning 391

their model. However, the empirical research offers cognitive development in infancy that consisted
areas in which the model does not apply. of six substages, as described at the end of the
Nevertheless, it illustrates the power of Bayesian last chapter. Moreover, he described the acquisi-
probability approaches to causal reasoning. tions in causality associated with three substages.
In this regard, Desrochers et al. (1995) con-
structed a sequence of tasks on causality in
Comment infancy and the steps within them that are consis-
tent with the Piagetian model. Finally, the results
Generally, research in which Gopnik has been of their study point to a sequential acquisition of
involved continued to support a Bayesian account the steps in causal learning that fits Piaget’s
of causal learning while de-emphasizing Piaget. description of the sensorimotor steps involved,
Although his sensorimotor stage in infancy as shown by the behavioral steps in the tasks
appears incompatible with the work showing that (see Table 16.1).
abstraction and generative models develop in this The work that relates early causal learning to
period, and although his concept of schemas in Piaget has not dealt with his developmental sub-
cognition lacks the Bayesian probabilistic aspect stage model in infancy, per se. Rather, as shown
in learning, the Bayesian and Piagetian views are next, different points of view point to the value of
compatible in that infant cognitive structures in the sensorimotor and action-related influences on
Piagetian sense can be understood as primitively early causal learning, as per Piaget.
generative and also their creation can be under-
stood as dependent on stochastic processes. That
is, one could elaborate a Neo-Piagetian approach Rational Construction
to early causal learning that marries the Piagetian
emphasis that they develop in fancy as cognitive Model Sommerville, Upshaw, and Loucks
schemas, and moreover, that they develop through (2013) presented a view of rational constructiv-
substages via Bayesian learning modalities that ism in relation to early causal learning that is
facilitate the process of their acquisition. quite consistent with the Piagetian tradition
Toward the development of this integrated (Piaget, 1952) [for an opposing view on the value
Bayesian–Piagetian model of early causal learning, of Piaget’s possible contribution to understand-
the next section of the chapter reviews Piagetian ing causal learning, see Xu and Kushnir (2013a,
thought on causal learning. Also, it reviews the lit- 2013b) below.]. Sommerville et al. (2013) noted
erature on causal learning that incorporates that, in some ways, infants not only construct
Piagetian thought. Finally, I make suggestions concrete-specific representations but also build
related to how my Neo-Piagetian model (Young, abstract representations (e.g., about unseen event
2011) can help elaborate an integrated Bayesian– outcomes). Representations might be simultane-
Piagetian account of early causal learning. ously concrete and abstract, and are action-based,
or built by actions on the world.
The concrete aspects of representation relate
Piagetian Contributions to “goal-relevant” features of actions in a way
to Understanding Causal Learning that is either action-specific or event-specific.
Moreover, the abstract components of the repre-
Piaget on Causality sentations also are action-related. They “sup-
port” infant perception of the action of others
Desrochers, Ricard, and Décarie (1995) have and also inferences about outcome actions that
developed a series of tasks to determine the sub- are not seen. By one year of age, infants use
stage of causality understanding in infants their representations more flexibly, and also
according to Piaget’s cognitive developmental language becomes a factor that adds to their
model. That is, Piaget had elaborated a model of abstraction.
392 16 Causal Learning: Understanding the World

Table 16.1 Piagetian causality scale (8 tasks): procedure, stage, and criterion response(s)
Task Procedure Stage Criterion responses(s)
1 A bell is fastened to a wooden board, or a rattle 3 Hits the object systematically. OR
is presented to S within reach Performs a repetitive motor act during the pause
following presentation
2 An object, which produces an interesting show, 4 Touches E’s hand lightly during the pause and
is activated by E in front of S, and kept out of waits
reach. Once the object stops, E puts his/her
hand within S’s reach
3 E drums on the table or snaps fingers, and stops 4 Touches E’s hand lightly during the pause and
abruptly, leaving his/her hand within S’s reach waits
4 E moves his/her fingers along S’s body to 4 Touches E’s hand lightly during the pause and
amuse S, and stops abruptly, leaving his/her waits
hand within S’s reach
5 A small mechanical TV toy is turned “on” and 5 Demands the toy by pointing to it between
“off” by pushing a button in front of S, out of demonstrations. OR
reach. After 2–3 demonstrations, the object is Takes the TV and gives it back to E or to
given to S mother. OR Attempts to activate or succeeds in
activating the toy
6 A roly-poly toy in the form of a Mickey Mouse 5 Demands the toy by pointing to it between
is set in motion by a gentle push. This task is demonstrations. OR
presented in the same way as in task 5 Takes the object and gives it back to E or to
mother when it is given to S
7 Four little wooden chickens are fastened to a 5 Demands the toy by pointing to it between
board and set in motion by pulling a string. demonstrations. OR
This task is presented in the same way as Acts directly on the string while looking at the
in task 5 toy when it is presented to S
8 From a position behind S, E throws a ball, 6 Turns head and looks for E. OR
which rolls close to S Picks up the ball and gives it to E
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science + Business Media; with kind permission from Springer
Science + Business Media B. V. [Table 3.5, Page 66]
S subject, E experimenter

According to Sommerville et al. (2013), the 2007). Baillargeon, Li, Gertner, and Wu (2010)
evidence supports Piaget’s (1952) view that showed that infants learn in a “category-specific”
infants build representations of actions on an way instead of learning principles across a range
action-by-action basis. Their understanding of of event outcomes (e.g., for specific properties,
goals seems “embedded” within specific actions. such as object height). There might be separate
However, at the same time, the abstract aspect of event-related representations rather than global
their representations participates in guiding their learning (e.g., in learning means–ends sequences;
perception, thereby facilitating inferences about Sommerville, 2007). Infants appear to learn
unseen action outcomes, either in their own about things in a wide variety of domains that are
actions or that of others. “object specific” and “action specific” (e.g., con-
Sommerville et al. (2013) reviewed the litera- tainment, occlusion, collision, covering;
ture showing that, despite “impressive” inferen- Baillargeon et al., 2010).
tial skills (Xu & Garcia, 2008), 1-year-olds still Also, the following indicates the primacy of
learn highly specific abstractions in certain areas. activity in infant representation. It appears that
For example, they learn which heights can be infants’ capacity to undertake goal-directed action
descended one posture at a time (Kretch & “drives” development of their perception of the
Adolph, 2013) and which parts of a tool are actions of others. For example, the degree to
meant for holding (Barrett, Davis, & Needham, which they can perform specific actions predicts
Piagetian Contributions to Understanding Causal Learning 393

their skill in identifying goals of these behaviors Piaget’s emphasis on the “active” and activity-
in the activity of other people. Moreover, when driven nature of early representation develop-
10-month-olds were given active training in novel ment indicates that it should be emphasized for
tool use to retrieve an object out of reach, they early causal learning even more than in the work
could better recognize another person’s use of the of Sommerville et al. (2013). It would appear that
tool as goal-directed, relative to a control group there is room for a revised understanding of the
that experienced visual familiarity with the tool nature of sensorimotor schemas and their evolu-
rather than production of goal-directed behaviors, tion through Neo-Piagetian substages in infancy
per se (Sommerville, Blumenthal, Venema, & that allows for the construction of schemas
Braun, 2011). Acting on the world, rather related to early sensorimotor activity yet the
than merely engaging in observation, appears development of representational primitives that
integral to representational construction and move in steps toward increasing complexity,
reconstruction. flexibility, and full representation by 2 years of
Other research by Sommerville and colleagues age. That Piaget’s work and Bayesian-type
illustrates that infants can make quite specific approaches can be integrated are illustrated in the
inferences about others’ goal-directed actions following section.
yet, in this regard, it helps to be advanced motori-
cally. Loucks and Sommerville (2011) found that
infants can infer the physical “outcomes” of par- Construction and Computation
ticular goal-directed actions (dropping actions).
Loucks and Sommerville (2012) found that Model Sobel and Legare (2014) reviewed the
10-month-olds could use information about how literature and models of how children learn the
an actor grasped an object (with a precision causal structure of the environment. They ended
grasp) in order to make inferences about the out- up supporting an integrated approach involving
come of the event. Infants who were relatively the computational and constructivist accounts.
skilled in precision grasping, unlike those who From an early age, children have been shown
were not, could “generate” outcomes for actions to possess “sophisticated” domain-specific causal
involving the grasp made by actors. reasoning that makes them “remarkable” causal
In terms of moving from action-specific to learners (Piaget, 1929). Since Piaget’s consider-
more general representations, Gerson and ation of the development of causality in early life,
Woodward (2010, 2012) suggested that infants use research has emphasized that preschoolers can
an “analogy-like” procedure. They appear to use a deal with (“recognize the importance,” “pos-
general cognitive mechanism that creates corre- sess”) temporal priority, spatial priority, contin-
spondences between their own familiar actions gency, prediction, explanation, and counterfactual
and ones that are novel that they might witness. reasoning (e.g., Legare, Gelman, & Wellman,
Sommerville et al. (2013) concluded that, at 2010; Sobel, 2004).
the level of the construction of goal-centered rep- Theories of causal learning are investigating
resentations of the action of others relative to the children’s domain-general learning and not only
more passive observational process, the active their domain-specific learning. The first block of
experience within which infants typically engage theories in this regard involves associative
plays a “privileged and/or preferential role.” strength and parameter estimation. Very young
Action is one aspect in the development of children manifest statistical learning capacities
representation. and the ability to generalize (Sobel & Kirkham,
2007; Xu & Garcia, 2008). The second block of
Comment I would add that although more theories of children’s causal learning considers
abstract and analogy-driven processes might be that even early on children learn an abstract causal
involved increasingly with age in infancy, “model” or map. The models are domain specific,
394 16 Causal Learning: Understanding the World

but the ability can represent knowledge in differ- conceptual change by exploring, and the pro-
ent (“across”) domains. Children develop “naïve” cesses of explanation and exploration interact as
theories and the models stand as “computational causal learning proceeds (Legare, 2012, 2014).
descriptions” (e.g., Gopnik et al., 2004; Gopnik & Moreover, causal learning is a social construction
Wellman, 2012). For example, 4-year-olds infer in that children integrate what they learn from
that “hidden” causes are present when they are others in this regard with the data that they
shown probabilistic, stochastic data (Schulz & acquire themselves (Sobel & Kushnir, 2013). As
Sommerville, 2006). This approach to children’s they develop causal explanations, they begin to
causal learning is represented by building causal generate “why?” questions (Wellman & Liu,
graph models (following Pearl, 2000, 2009). 2007). This opens a whole new chapter in their
According to Sobel and Legare (2014), an causal learning.
integrated account of the two causal learning
models in the field—the statistical, probabilistic Comment Sobel and Legare (2014) have contin-
learning approach and the causal model mapping ued the integrative process needed in the area of
one—can derive from the approach of Piaget causal learning over the Bayesian and Piagetian
(1952, 1955). In terms of the statistical view, for perspectives. However, we still need more work
Piaget, infants in the early sensorimotor stage on the mechanism involved in the growth of causal
experience causality only as a form of association learning through the actions that Piaget described.
of experiences. However, by engaging in activity Sensorimotor growth takes place through internal
in the environment, infants can develop recogni- dynamics, to be sure, but also through external
tion of “deeper” relationships over events. As the impetus, and among them are the imitations that
infants learn that objects themselves can be effi- the environment could foster, as discussed next.
cacious in affecting the environment (approxi-
mately in substage 4, at 8 months of age), they are
capable of abstracting the conditional probability Observation
information contained in event associations.
Sobel and Legare (2014) noted, as well, that Introduction The imitation function is not usu-
the Piagetian description of infant causal learning ally associated with transitional steps in the
is consistent with the causal graphic modeling Piagetian model. However, there is no reason
approach (which is interventionist in understand- why imitation cannot be examined from the
ing the essence of causality). Contemporary framework of the Piagetian model, especially in
research supports the graph model mapping its modern guises.
approach to early causal learning (Muentener &
Carey, 2010; Sommerville & Woodward, 2005;
Teglas et al., 2011). Early That infants’ cognitive schema might
Sobel and Legare (2014) noted that the causal involve matching schemas of own-bodily senso-
graph modeling approach to causal learning in rimotor activity and those related to actions with
children has limits, though, if considered by respect to the other is supported by work on infant
itself. The approach is Bayesian, and does not mirror system mechanisms. Turati et al. (2013)
provide algorithms of how children make causal demonstrated that 6-month-olds watching an agent
inferences. An integrated approach to the area reaching for, grasping, and then bringing an object
needs to take account of how children form spe- toward the body (mouth or head) led to recruit-
cific models and more general frameworks. ment and selective modulation of the mirror motor
According to the authors, inconsistency in system, as indicated by electromyographic (EMG)
observed data plays an important role in explana- measurement. EMG activity was recorded from
tion and hypothesis generation in children’s suprahyoid muscles (SM) that are involved in
causal reasoning. The child actively participates chewing and swallowing, and that are responsible
in constructing causal theories, knowledge, and for mouth opening. In mirror mechanisms, the
Piagetian Contributions to Understanding Causal Learning 395

actions of the other are mapped onto the observer’s because they fail to appreciate fully event–
motor representation of the same actions. event and “downstream” effects.
For the 6-month-olds studied, SM activity (c) A third way of learning causality in early life
increased especially during observation of the seems to involve “noting” correlations and
action involving mouth opening in the agent (only associations in events, e.g., in patterns of sta-
in the bringing back phase). This suggests a motor tistical covariation (Rogers & McClelland,
resonance-related, or modulation, effect already 2004) and also in associating some events
present in early infancy, and also that the motor with others (e.g., Kuhl, 2004). However,
system is recruited in observing relevant agent Meltzoff et al. (2012) noted that the statisti-
actions. The authors also found that the modula- cal approach involves more than pattern
tion of motor activity correlated with overt mouth learning because in order to infer causality in
opening behavior. It appears that the infant’s motor correlation, infants appear to use “interven-
system simulates “below threshold” observed tions,” or knowing that their use could be
action as sensorimotor processing proceeds. Turati informative (e.g., Gopnik & Schulz, 2007).
et al. (2013) concluded that motor resonance
effects might even be present at birth (e.g., Lepage About observational causal learning, Meltzoff
& Théoret, 2007; Meltzoff & Decety, 2003) and et al. (2012) suggested that an even more power-
disappear at about 3 months, only to reemerge at 6 ful (and ubiquitous) mechanism of causal learn-
months. ing involves observing others engaging in
interventionist causally-informative behavior,
Later Meltzoff, Waismeyer, and Gopnik (2012) and inferring the presence of causal relations
queried how infants and young children learn the from the observations. The authors investigated
causal structure of their world. They focused on their model by designing a “two-choice” causal
2-year-olds in their research, and they presented procedure. Infants observed an experimenter per-
an observational causal learning perspective. form two actions on two objects with equal fre-
There have been three other mechanisms that quency, but only one of them was followed
have been proposed for causal learning, which I consistently by an effect. The control condition
describe first. I note that two of them involve the involved reversing outcome and intervention.
Bayesian statistical approach and Piaget’s, with Methodological innovations implemented in the
the third one on more specific Michottean causal study involved control of contaminants: by avoid-
launching learning. ing infants hearing causal language (by the exper-
imenters); avoiding spatial/temporal conjunction
(a) The Michottean causal learning that takes (in the intervention-outcome); and avoiding
place in infancy involves the learning of intentional actions by people (experimenters) in
launching contingencies by focusing on spe- one of the conditions (by using surreptitious mag-
cific, narrowly-tuned spatiotemporal fea- nets). Also, to increase generalizability, the
tures and patterns of movement as cues in authors varied objects, events, and actions over
causal learning (e.g., Scholl & Tremoulet, four studies. Finally, the measures that were used
2000). varied (i.e., infant actions, looking).
(b) The second approach to mechanism in causal Meltzoff et al. (2012) concluded that the
learning focuses on Piaget’s (1954) idea that results of the four experiments indicated that, at
infants might learn causal relations between 2 years of age, infants are “adept” in observa-
their “willed” actions and the effects or out- tional causal learning. They do more than learn
comes of the actions. Also at this age period, associations or imitate directly actions of peo-
they might infer relations such as this in see- ple. Rather, in watching events, even without
ing someone act intentionally and directly on human intervention, they can infer causal links
an object. However, infants in their cognition between paired, sequential events. Moreover,
at this age are still “precausal” (Piaget, 1930) they can learn from what they see and intervene
396 16 Causal Learning: Understanding the World

appropriately themselves. They can intervene sensorimotor substage from 8 to 12 months of


selectively on a cause producing an effect (e.g., age, these behaviors become more differenti-
to get a marble; lift a cone; move a disc). The ated, and the reaching can serve removing a bar-
various control conditions and control of contam- rier in a detour action to get a fully hidden object
inants instituted by the authors precluded inter- (object permanence being indicated by the
pretations other than genuine observational action). This behavior would suggest intent from
causal learning taking place in the 2-year-olds. the beginning of the action to get at the desired
Infants at this age seem to adhere to the scientific object, although there are limits to the behavior
maxim that correlation does not necessarily mean (e.g., not being able to shift search to a second
causation [and that intervention can discern it]. hiding place, even when the transfer has been
The authors concluded that different develop- seen), and the intent is guided by perceptual
mental possibilities are worth considering in images of the hidden object rather than by
causal intervention learning by observation, e.g., abstract representational plans. Nevertheless,
in hypothesis construction and constraint. imitative learning could map onto the schemas
Yu and Kushnir (2014) showed that, unlike being created in the searching behavior involved,
2-year-olds, 4-year-olds are more likely to over- a postulate that illustrates the potential of the
imitate in different games. One explanation Piagetian model to show how observational
offered was that, unlike toddlers, preschoolers learning can develop in cognitive complexity
are learning about social and cultural norms, so even in the first year of life.
that over-imitation could be valuable in this Also, according to Bayesian proponents,
regard. Other explanations concerned increased research with infants in the second year of life con-
affiliative motivation. The authors added that sistently shows that infants at this age are capable
over-imitation could be important in pedagogical of making inferences, appreciating intentions, and
demonstrations (e.g., Csibra & Gergely, 2005, on engaging in higher-order relational cognition (e.g.,
natural pedagogy). Walker & Gopnik, 2014). However, as with
younger ages, one could ask the extent to which
Comment Observations afford powerful learn- the evolving capacities map onto Piagetian or
ing opportunities and, further, imitation substan- Neo-Piagetian substages in the sensorimotor stage
tiates them. However, models of observational of infancy. For example, in the 12- and 18-month
learning do not generally consider that it is a con- benchmarks in Piagetian theory, infants are capa-
structive cognitive activity that improves with ble of trial and error quasi-mental combinations
the dynamic transitions of infant cognition from and invention of new mental combinations, respec-
one skill level to the next. Observational learn- tively, but with sensorimotor conditionals/con-
ing, as much as any phenomenon based on the straints involved. Actions and sensorimotor
formation of cognitive schemes in the activity, experience still constitute the anchors for the
lends itself to models of its transformation in emerging representations in the second year of
Piagetian substages in infancy. life, and imitations of them after observation could
For example, in the 4- and 8-month-old, from add to the growing complexity of the schemas
a Piagetian perspective, infants enter into a sen- involved, but not move them by themselves
sorimotor substage in which they develop a uniquely into the representational sphere.
degree of coordination in schemas, such as in Natural pedagogy is related to imitative learn-
visually-directed reaching, and more intentional ing, but carries the learning into a different level
ones, such as moving a barrier (screen) to get at by arguing that social learning, in general, is crit-
a partially hidden object with which it had been ical to cognitive acquisition. In the next section, I
playing. Both these types of sensorimotor examine this area but, once more, argue that it
actions could be ones on which imitation after can only complement and not replace a Piagetian
observation is mapped. Moreover, in the next perspective based in action learning.
Integrating Bayes and Piaget 397

Natural Pedagogy Integrating Bayes and Piaget

Model Gergely and Jacob (2013) presented There could be room for integrating the Bayesian
evidence that infants can make inferences that do approach of infant cognitive development with
not require action support. Moreover, they the Piagetian one. Below, I consider early cogni-
appear to be at a phase in which they are open to tive development along these lines.
“natural pedagogy,” having a facility to profit
from social learning (e.g., on the basis of osten-
sive, nonverbal referential actions/demonstra- Rational Constructivism
tion). For example, infants look longer when an
actor/agent chooses relatively less efficient Model The area of cognitive development often
actions compared to other ones toward a goal is marked by extreme empiricism or extreme
state (Gergely & Csibra, 2003). Surian, Caldi, nativism. Xu and Kushnir (2013a, 2013b) elabo-
and Sperber (2007) found that 1-year-olds look rated the burgeoning middle ground or integra-
longer at an actor/agent retrieving a preferred tive approach of rational constructivism (already
food that is hidden from view for the agents but briefly introduced in discussing Gopnik and
not the infants. Infants can follow an agent’s Wellman (2012) and Sommerville et al. (2013)).
gaze shift to one of two objects (but only if a Xu and Kushnir (2013b) offered some basic
referential expectation had been set up by osten- tenets underlying this perspective and described
sive signals, such as eye contact or infant- its integrative stance.
directed speech; Senju & Csibra, 2008). In this regard, from one point of view, even
As for most studies directly on natural peda- developmentally, human learning is especially an
gogy, they typically concern older infants, unlike active inferential process and is more than just a
the case for the ones cited above (e.g., Gweon, correlational, associative learning. It generates
Tenenbaum, & Schulz, 2010; Ma & Xu, 2011). In abstract, novel, and causal processes in learning,
all cases, actions were not required of the infants conceptualization, representation, and modeling.
in order to demonstrate social learning based on However, as well, early learning also might be
social-pragmatic cues. statistical, computational, probabilistic, partial,
or graded and Bayesian. The learner begins with
Comment Overall, the research reported by a distribution of prior probabilities related to a set
Gergely and Jacob (2013) indicates that a more of hypotheses and then computes the hypotheses’
passive than active learning has a role to play in prior probabilities in light of the evidence as indi-
infant cognitive development and that the social cated by Bayesian algorithms. Also, any model
environment contributes to it. However, this does generated is open to revision, but with the con-
not deny Sommerville et al.’s (2013) conclusion of straint that whatever has been constructed
the primacy of action-based learning and infer- becomes part of the priors on which revisions can
ence. The concept of schema in the Neo-Piagetian be devised, and their influence in this regard var-
tradition should be expanded to include observa- ies with their “strength.” The child gradually
tion and social inputs. However, I note that this moves from more general purpose “domains” or
does not preclude that a type of analogic process mechanisms to more specific ones.
might be involved, but at the action level; e.g., Xu and Kushnir (2013b) contrasted their
from proprioceptive and kinesthetic feedback approach with that of Piaget (1954). First, the
mapping on wider intersensory/intermodal schema rational constructivist point of view does not
formations that permit action mapping and predic- endorse the concept of stages in development.
tion (e.g., Meltzoff, 2007). [This is where their view differs from mine, and I
398 16 Causal Learning: Understanding the World

note that this exclusion of Piagetian (sub)stages Piaget’s substage model of the sensorimotor
in the rational constructionist perspective is not period. Removal of Piaget’s first sensorimotor
part of the approach as discussed by Sommerville substage of Reflex Exercise from his sensorimo-
et al. (2013).] Second, cognitive development tor substage sequence and expanding it into its
does not begin with sensorimotor “primitives” own stage, as I have done, might help modify
having no differentiation between child and some of the criticisms associated with his version
world. Instead, very early in life, new learning of the sensorimotor period as being “primitive”
and concepts are driven by rational inferential and being neither able to permit separation of
learning processes. person and world and unable to support some sort
of inferential activity. In this regard, Schulz
Comment Once more, as with Gopnik and (2013) noted that Piaget’s (1937) concept of the
Wellman (2012), Piaget is not considered rele- child as an active learner includes in early life
vant to this area of contemporary study of cogni- “systematic attempts” to try to understand the
tive development. However, other workers (e.g., workings of the world.
Sobel & Legare, 2014; Sommerville et al., 2013) About the latter point (b) above, sensorimotor
consider Piaget’s work central to elucidating the schemas as described by Piaget are
nature of early causal learning. Perhaps the environmentally-responsive yet also constraining
exclusion of Piaget in understanding causal and in their conservative tendency to resist change
related learning early in life is because workers (accommodation and assimilation, respectively).
who support the exclusion do so grosso modo There is no reason to exclude that they function
about the sensorimotor stage conception, in gen- in the Bayesian manner suggested in the rational
eral, without examining the progression through constructivist approach. In this regard, assimila-
the six substages involved. That being said, tion, by definition, is based on prior constructions
Piaget’s conception to causal learning should framing present sampling of the environment
indeed be complemented by other approaches, as statistically. Similarly, accommodation, by defi-
applicable. Moreover, one can ask the extent to nition, constitutes revision of extant schemes
which the Piagetian and Bayesian approaches are according to probability estimates of what might
really exclusive, nonoverlapping alternative work better in context.
explanations of early causal learning. There might have to be theoretical compromise
The following considers whether the rational by both parties (accommodations!) to properly
constructivist and Neo-Piagetian views are indeed assimilate the point of view of the other in each of
in opposition, as maintained by Xu and Kushnir their perspectives. For example, Piagetian schemas
(2013b). In contrast, to their perspective, I eluci- should be understood as experience-dependent
date how the rational constructivist view is not models that have probabilistic components.
antithetical to the Piagetian one. (a) On the one Nothing that Piaget has written would deny this
hand, Neo-Piagetians have revised his model to reworked understanding of schema. Similarly, the
make it more consistent with contemporary rational constructivist approach should acknowl-
research. (b) On the other hand, the cognitive edge that its abstractions are activity-based and
developmental processes that Piaget described sensorially-based. Even if they have domain-gen-
early in life are not incompatible with the learning, eral components, either they are innately prescribed
conceptual, and inferential processes that charac- or they are readily activated by experience. Also,
terize rational constructivism. they exist adaptively as means to further promote
About the former point (a) above, Young differentiation toward the specific that affords bet-
(2011), for example, presented a modified ter reality-based activity. Further in this regard,
Piagetian cognitive developmental stage progres- although they are channeled through that sensory-
sion over the lifespan that begins with a reflexive based activity beyond their original domain-gen-
stage prenatally and then with the sensorimotor eral status, they do not become isolated abstract
stage at 1 month of age, which then consists of models that are separate from the actions that help
the remaining five sensorimotor substages in differentiating them.
Changes by Age in Causal Learning 399

In short, to rephrase Piaget in more contempo- and contextualized acquisitions above all, but ones
rary terms, the concept of schema as described by having universal features. This obtains because
Piaget is an embodied one that is activity- and they represent common dynamical solutions in the
world-contact dependent. It describes a participa- developmental process, ones that elegantly emerge
tory regime in early learning and abstraction that in the constant rational construction of the child’s
demands and encourages engagement by the child mind in the environment’s world. The program is
in a unified body–mind–brain activity. It is a feed- not a prearranged one that passively appears but an
back and feedforward anticipatory mechanism inevitable one through comparable molding by
that permits abstractions that facilitate adaptation. each individual as individuals confront the world.
However, the abstractions are reality-dependent If Piaget would be available to reflect on ratio-
even if they are constructed. They are probabilis- nal constructivism, he would applaud its inroads.
tic, empirical, rational, and “afforded,” as well as However, he might argue, as I have done, that
constructed, abstracted, and inferred. They are being a Piagetian (or Neo-Piagetian) is not contra-
primitive relative to later abstractions, quite intui- dictory with being a rational constructivist.
tive, and kinesthetic- and proprioceptive-driven Moreover, there is nothing in the term itself that
through their action base, forming integrated runs counter to Neo-Piagetian tenets. The only
cross-modal body mapping that gives them their concern that I have in this regard is the statements
generic, action-distant properties, to the degree by Xu and Kushnir (2013b) that the rational con-
that the process permits, which is only minimal. structivist and Piagetian approaches are in opposi-
They are social, observational, and imitative as tion. As I hope I have shown, there could be
much as personally driven by active construction nothing further from the rational, constructed truth.
and curiosity. In the end, they are the essence of In this regard, early causal learning would
what is demanded in a rational constructivist appear especially based on action sequence learn-
approach with respect to the cognitive construc- ing in an associative way, but on that would typi-
tions formulated by the child early in life. That is, cally involve social sequencing and the inherent
they build on the stochastic process, but on an intersubjectivity in the process right from early in
internal scaffold of cognitive schemas pregnant life. As the causal learning expands through the
with a growth program in the way indicated, Neo-Piagetian cognitive substages in the senso-
moreover, one that includes bursts of change rimotor substage sequence that bootstraps it
through generic substages that can bootstrap them along with the social participation that marks
forward to a degree. early life, it takes on the cognitive attributes of
Moreover, by understanding the concept of the substages involved, as described in Desrochers
schema in cognitive development as highly com- et al. (1995) as much as by Piaget and Young.
patible with the rational constructive approach, a Primitive sensorimotor action and activity-based
logical model is available to understand how the abstractions do become possible. The last section
child’s abstracted modeling of the world both of the book deals extensively with the present
begins and is carried forward and altered in cog- Neo-Piagetian stage model of development and
nitive development. Neo-Piagetian conceptual- its extrapolations.
izations of stages in cognitive development
include substages, dynamic evolution, and rela-
tions to discoveries in developmental neurosci- Changes by Age in Causal Learning
ence that make them not only quite consistent
with the Piagetian approach but also quite consis- This section of the chapter examines the empiri-
tent with the recent literature (Young, 2011). cal research on early causal learning from the
As much as cognitive development is individu- newborn period onward. It illustrates the dynamic
alized, there are also universal features to consider. tension between the nativist and learning points
Not that the latter reflect innate, unchanging mech- of view. The Piagetian approach that I promote
anisms. Rather, the Neo-Piagetian stages and sub- could be one way of integrating the diverse points
stages that I have described reflect individualized of view on early causal learning by providing a
400 16 Causal Learning: Understanding the World

scaffold on which the earliest primitives can subsequent movement by the second ball. The test
develop in complexity in association with event order was essentially counterbalanced
generalized, step-by-step cognitive advances in across the participants in each condition.
the sensorimotor period. In the first experiment, in the test phase, for
the sticky-mitten condition, infants increased
looking especially for the causal switch and non-
Newborns causal switch events (i.e., unfamiliar). However,
for the nonsticky-mitten condition, only the non-
Neonates Mascalzoni, Regolin, Vallortigara, causal switch condition led to more looking. In
and Simion (2013) tested the origin of causal per- the second experiment, the infants did not per-
ception at birth. Newborns (only a few hours old) ceive causality in the test phase, when their causal
demonstrated sensitivity (by looking longer) to action experience was not matched perceptually
some visual spatiotemporal cues (temporal conti- to the causal launching events viewed during the
nuity, continuity of trajectory, order appropriate) habituation phase.
of a launching event. The newborns preferred a The authors concluded that 1-month-olds are
direct physical launching compared to delayed or capable of early causal learning. Also, other
noncausal relations. The authors concluded that putative milestones in perception and cognition
innate or early developing appreciation of physi- (beyond causality) might be found to occur ear-
cal causality is a type of “jumpstart” to the devel- lier, should appropriate real-world type experi-
opment of causal reasoning. ences be used in the experiments.

One-Month-Olds Rakison and Krogh (2012)


examined causal learning in 1-month-olds. The Comment
methodology used by Rakison and Krogh (2012)
was quite innovative. There was an action phase The empirical research on the origin of causal
and then a habitation one in each of two experi- knowledge right from birth is striking both in its
ments. In the first experiment, in one condition, methodological sophistication and its theoretical
the 1-month-olds interacted with green balls import. Mascalzoni et al.’s (2013) research sup-
while wearing red Velcro sticky mittens. The mit- ports the view that Michottian physical launching
tens enabled them to contact and pick up the balls is perceived causally in the newborn period, setting
by swiping or batting. In the second condition, the stage for more advanced causal learning.
the mittens were nonsticky. After the first phase, Rakison and Krogh (2012) demonstrated that
the sticky-mitten condition was followed by the 1-month-olds are capable of perceiving differences
infants having access to Velcro-covered balls. in causal switching conditions, especially if they
For the nonsticky condition, the balls were glued had participated previous to the test phase with
to their tray. The situations lasted 3 min. sticky mittens that allowed them to pick up colored
The habituation phase involved animated balls. To conclude, physical launching sensitivity
events shown on a computer screen. In the habitu- might be innate if the right cues are present.
ation event, a launching event took place with two Moreover, more advanced causal perceptions are
balls, with a “ding” noise heard on contact once facilitated by participation in relevant actions, as
the first ball struck the second and before the sec- Piaget might predict.
ond took over in moving. Once habituation took
place (<50 % of the looks), three test events fol-
lowed. In the familiar condition, direction was Young Infants
switched to right to left instead of left to right. In
the causal switch test, the colors of the balls were Six-Month-Olds Schlottmann, Ray, and Surian
switched (from red → green to green → red). In the (2012) found that 6-month-olds demonstrated
noncausal switch condition, the first ball stopped understanding of causal reaction events, with 6
just before contact, but there was still a “ding” and months also being the time period in which they
Changes by Age in Causal Learning 401

demonstrate understanding of causal launching Ten-Month-Olds Hohenberger et al. (2013)


events. For example, in causal reaction events, A performed a study that showed understanding of
(a shape) moves toward B, which moves before physical causality in 10-month-olds was associ-
contact. Then, both move simultaneously until A ated with maternal sensitivity. They argued that
arrives at its final resting position. sensitive mothers would give more freedom to
In a causal launching study, Kim, Feldman, explore objects. This study shows that even if
and Singh (2013) found evidence that causally understanding of physical causality might happen
coherent interpretations can influence basic per- quite early for some tasks, the (maternal) environ-
ceptual processes. This conclusion does not deny ment still has a supportive role in promoting it.
that perceiving causality in launches is the end Denison, Trikutam, and Xu (2014) demonstrated
result of a chain of visual analyses involving spe- that 11-month-old infants could reason about the
cialized neural populations (Rolfs, Dambacher, probability of different outcomes after they had
& Cavanagh, 2013). learned about physical constraints on objects. The
Gerson and Woodward (2012) found that infants reasoned by applying physical rules to adjust
7-month-olds could compare a familiar and novel population base rates in estimating by inference the
action, and that this helped understand the goal of probabilities involved. They eschewed reasoning by
a tool-use action. The study used an interesting perceptual similarity. The authors concluded that
technique of aligning reaching with a tool claw. infants can learn stochastic, variable physical con-
The relational analogic learning involved had straints by powerful statistical learning mecha-
required active sensorimotor activity (reach nisms, they can do so rapidly, and they can integrate
aligning, participating). them to predict outcomes of future events.
Sobel and Kirkham (2013) noted the social Recent research on false belief does not support
influences on infant statistical learning. Infants the precocious view of infant cognition. Carlson,
need joint attention to disambiguate multiple Koenig, and Harms (2013) argued that infants
simultaneous co-occurrences. Social influences demonstrate System I understanding of false
shape cognitive development by helping selective beliefs (fast, implicit, inflexible), which precedes
focus and the avoidance of distractions (e.g., Wu development of a second system that is slower,
and Kirkham (2010); using social cues in a study explicit, and flexible. Therefore, early cognition
of 8-month-olds). Social cues also teach about might be preconceptual, rudimentary, and implicit
intentionality. (Apperly & Butterfill, 2009; Low, 2010; Onishi &
Consistent with Sobel and Kirkham (2013), Baillargeon, 2005). That is, the role of abstraction
Buchsbaum, Seiver, Beidgers, and Gopnik (2013) in false belief development appears to emerge in
noted that, just as children employ covariation in later infancy at the earliest.
physical cause–effect relations to learn about the However, Hamlin (2013) has shown that, for
world, so do they use covariation in the actions of another aspect of social cognition, young infants
people and context to form inferences about cau- appear quite preconscious. Specifically, she pro-
sation of behavior. That is, psychological causa- posed that some aspects of moral sense might be
tion and attribution belong to the same causal built in early in life. In her research, as early as 3
system as causation in the physical domain. months, infants appreciated the distinction
Brandone (2015) demonstrated that, in 8- to between hinderers and helpers (Hamlin & Wynn,
11-months-olds, maternal report of infant joint 2011). By 6 months, they evaluated positively
attention initiations and of self-locomotion skills helpers and also negatively hinderers (e.g., in a
were associated with eye-tracking documented task with a puppet either opening or slamming
ability to predict the outcome of an agent’s failed shut a box with a toy in it).
reaching actions. The results suggested to the Also, 10-month-olds appear to evaluate men-
author that social and motor experiences at this tal states. In Hamlin, Ullman, Tenenbaum,
age may serve to “shape” infant comprehension Goodman, and Baker (2013), infants preferred
of the other as an intentional agent. helpers to hinderers in a task that required lifting
402 16 Causal Learning: Understanding the World

for both agents. They appeared to evaluate others That is, I predict that we will be able to specify
as good or bad on a mentalistic level. Good agents (a) an early intuitive, primitive, still quite action-
are actors who “knowingly and intentionally” based intuitive thought in early sensorimotor
help another person. Finally, strikingly, Hamlin activity vs. (b) a later intuitive thought, still repre-
(2013) found that even 5-month-olds preferred sentational to a degree even if automatic, i.e.,
“antisocial” agents who appropriately had harmed System I related, in the preoperational sense of
hinderers relative to “prosocial” ones who inap- Piaget; with an intermediate phase between these
propriately had helped hinderers. Hamlin (2013) two types of intuitive thought involving transi-
concluded that infants can engage in some mor- tional passage through various sensorimotor sub-
ally relevant “evaluations” from early in life stages. For example, early intuitive cognition will
onward, and these mentalistic facilities are innate. be governed by action-based sensorimotor sche-
mas that involve primitive cognitive modules pre-
pared evolutionarily that, nevertheless, are
Comment susceptible to development through experience.
They would concern reflexive patterning based
Research on causal understanding in the 6-month on supramodal models formed through kines-
period has studied launching events, tool use, and thetic and proprioceptive feedback deriving from
physical causality, action-based causality, but actions. They would have mirror system proper-
also the social context, maternal sensitivity, and ties that allow for early imitations, which would
so on. It has queried the degree to which young accentuate their development. They would evolve
infants use statistical estimations/covariations, to include action repetitions of accidentally-
and the extent to which the understanding is in discovered behavior that are interesting, first with
any way abstract. For example, Carlson et al. the body and after with objects. Then, as intuitive
(2013) considered that infants show System I thought of this type develops, the substages
understanding of false beliefs, which is implicit involved would include various increasing coor-
rather than abstract. However, elsewhere in the dinations, such as Piaget described, e.g., for the
present work I have argued that System I vs. II object permanence and for the causality series.
thinking applies best to preschool vs. school-age By the end of the series, toddlers will act with rep-
thought, as in Piaget’s preoperational vs. con- resentational ability, but still tied to vestigial sen-
crete operational stage. The primitive type of sorimotor activity, before developing independent
thought in early sensorimotor development is not representations by 2 years of age, but only of the
implicit in the sense of System I thought, which System I preoperational intuitive type, that is,
is an automatic, unconscious, fast type of thought lacking reversibility, dimensionality, and so on.
compared to System II’s deliberative, conscious,
slow one (see Chap. 19). Rather, for early infancy,
intuitive thought best refers to moving from a One- to Two-Year-Olds
straight associative thought process that is solely
action-based to one with primitive guiding One-Year-Olds Xu and Kushnir (2013a) elabo-
images, even if accidentally discovered and rated that, in cognitive development, “rational
linked to sensorimotor activity. This type of constructivism” applies to causal learning and
understanding of early sensorimotor causal reasoning. It blends nativism and empiricism. As
understanding does not conflict with the work of we have seen, in this view, early learning is con-
Hamlin (2013) on early appreciation of helping sidered as rational, statistical, and inferential and
versus hindering. However, I would predict that, the learner as constructivist. Further, innate/core
in the studies that she has conducted, analysis of concepts/knowledge are combined with associa-
concomitant sensorimotor activity in the helping tive learning. Rational learners integrate prior
mode will reveal patterns that distinguish the belief/knowledge/bias with new evidence gath-
types of evaluations claimed. ered, generating posterior probabilities of the
Changes by Age in Causal Learning 403

hypotheses involved (Perfors, Tenenbaum, bilities because they can represent them logically
Griffiths, & Xu, 2011). and consistently in a “surprisingly sophisticated
One-year-olds are sensitive to probabilistic reasoning” ability. The intuitive view of early cog-
relations in making inferences (Denison, Reed, & nition, in which modal representations are found
Xu, 2013). When given prior constraints, they that help “reasoning” about the probability of a
make statistical computations, including integrat- single, future event, contrasts with the frequentist
ing them (Xu & Denison, 2009). They use prob- view, which is that infants possess simpler fre-
ability sensitivity to predict and to guide action quency detection mechanisms that track relevant
(Denison & Xu, 2010a). They consider statistics distributions. Cesana-Arlotti et al. (2013) concluded
in input as they evaluate multiple possible that infants are like “little logicians.” They can cre-
hypotheses (Gerken, 2006). ate logical representations and use them rationally.
As for constructivism, infants at this age engage Denison and Xu (2013) were more circumspect
in hypothesis testing (Gerken, 2010). Older ones in how they describe infants’ emerging cognition.
notice anomalous data (Kushnir et al., 2010) and They argued that infants can make “rudimentary”
statistical evidence is a driver in concept acquisi- probabilistic inferences and are like “intuitive stat-
tion (Ma & Xu, 2011). One-year-olds can form isticians.” Their “intuitive probabilities” notions
hypotheses at multiple levels (over-hypotheses) do not appear available to awareness and reflec-
involving perceptual input (Dewar & Xu, 2010). tion. Their “intuitive abstractions” are inductively
Infants are indeed active learners (Piaget, 1954), as formulated, allowing their rapid creation from
the research by Denison and Xu (2010b) revealed. “sparse” data. Their “guesses” are revisable, edu-
The authors concluded that infants engage in cated, probabilistic, Bayesian ones. Nevertheless,
active, inductive, inferential constructivist, and they integrate “substantive domain” knowledge
rational statistical learning across multiple domains when arriving at judgments. The authors con-
(domain general), including causal learning. cluded that the capacity to make probabilistic
Rakison and Krogh (2012) conducted informa- inferences might be an “innate” mechanism in
tive research on causal action and perception using learning from which later learning can build.
the sticky-mitten paradigm in a habituation study
with 12-month-olds. Piaget (1954) had proposed Fourteen-Month-Olds Chen and Waxman
that infants of this age are already sensitive to their (2013) followed up on evidence indicating that
own actions. However, research had failed to dem- infants go beyond observing to infer underlying
onstrate understanding at this age of Michottian goals that other might have (Brandone &
launching events. Therefore, the authors created Wellman, 2009). Infants selectively re-enact
an experimental situation involving events more behavior inferred as intentional (Southgate,
consistent with real-world experience. Chevallier, & Csibra, 2009). Gergely, Bekkering,
The results showed that engaging even briefly and Kiraly (2002) had 14-month-olds observe an
in causal action facilitated causal perception. The adult experimenter produce a novel, unconven-
mechanism permitting the perception appears tional action (head touching with the forehead to
related to attention/encoding. The mental repre- turn on a light). The infants duplicated the behav-
sentation formed can generalize somewhat to dif- ior when the adult’s hands were freed rather than
ferent contexts (objects), but not to significantly being occupied, implying that infants had under-
different ones. stood that there had been a choice not to use a
Cesana-Arlotti, Téglás, and Bonatti (2013) hand and an intention to use the forehead.
argued that 1-year-olds have an “intuitive” notion or Chen and Waxman (2013) extended this type
representation of probability. They can even use of research on infant intentionality comprehension
these for single events that they had never experi- by incorporating that infants “appreciate” that a
enced, predicting what might happen next (e.g., Xu word could signal an adult’s underlying intention
& Garcia, 2008). They can entertain future possi- (Martin, Vouloumanos, & Onishi, 2012). In the
404 16 Causal Learning: Understanding the World

head-tapping condition, in which 14-month-olds infants generally and robustly expected agents to
were tested by Chen and Waxman, the adult exper- pursue efficiently their goals, with little excess
imenter commented that (a) she would “blick” the effort expended. Specifically, infants expected
light on or, (b) she announced “Look”/“Watch” agents to choose the objects that were more acces-
(novel word and neutral language control condi- sible, whether physical or mental.
tion, respectively). As with the hands-free com- Howe and Otgaar (2013) proposed that early
pared to the hands-occupied condition undertaken memories are developmentally invariant because
in the first part of the study, the novel word of their adaptiveness/fitness in evolution. The
(blicket) condition compared to the control condi- memory principles involved concern item-specific
tion prompted imitation. Chen and Waxman and relational processing, self-referential process-
(2013) concluded that understanding another’s ing, elaboration, and distinctiveness processing.
intentions at 14 months of age can be framed or These principles allow better preservation of
clarified by language. Infants at this age appear to memory traces that are important for survival (and
assess goals and intentions of the other and arrive reproduction). Once more, for core cognitive pro-
at “principled-decisions” about whether or not to cesses, early infant skills are posited.
they should imitate (novel) actions observed. [For
a neural network view of how events in the world Eighteen-Month-Olds Walker and Gopnik
are learned for causal dependency, as in the blicket (2014) demonstrated that 18-month-olds can
experiments, see Fernando (2013).] infer higher-order relational causal principles and
Cacchione, Schaub, and Rakoczy (2013) used use the inference to guide subsequent behavior.
an ingenious procedure to show that 14-month- Moreover, achieving such causal mastery appears
olds take cognizance of causality properties in unique to humans. Humans might be uniquely
dealing with objects. Half the participants saw adapted for “higher-order relational cognition”
how a stuffed animal (pig) could be transformed (Penn, Holyoak, & Povinelli, 2008) or a general
(everted) into a different object (a ball) by a sim- “causal cognition” (Heyes & Frith, 2012).
ple mechanism. In the test phase, both aware and
unaware infants viewed a stuffed rabbit hidden in
a box. It could be everted into a carrot. In half of Comment
the trials of the study, the rabbit was everted sur-
reptitiously (switched). The research related to causal learning in the
Only infants who viewed the causal mecha- second year of life has expanded in scope, using
nism previously searched equally in both condi- sophisticated methodologies and nuanced con-
tions (i.e., they expected two objects to be cepts. For the former, the techniques include use
involved in the event). In contrast, the naïve of sticky mittens and even everted rabbits. For the
infants reacted differently to the two situations— latter, the infants have been posited to possess
they expected to find a rabbit in the box and constructed, intuitive representations, rudimen-
searched longer when it was a carrot. The authors tary probabilistic inferences, capacity to under-
concluded that infants at this age treat the causal stand the intention of others, giving importance
features of objects as more important than non- to the causal features of objects, and higher-order
causal surface ones, even if nonobvious. relational causal principles. As for the Bayesian
and statistical approach to their learning, these
Sixteen-Month-Olds Scott and Baillargeon computational mechanisms are still championed
(2013) tested whether 16-month-olds expect as being integral.
agents to act rationally. Unlike in prior research on It is worth noting that the types of advances in
the question, they did not use agents expressing causal learning in the second year of life appear to
infrequent or odd actions (e.g., Csibra, Bíró, Koós, be qualitatively different in the second half of the
& Gergely, 2003), but used scenarios involving year compared to the first. Indeed in this regard,
typical, everyday situations. They found that the Walker and Gopnik (2014) referred to the presence
Changes by Age in Causal Learning 405

of higher-order relational cognition at 18 months Kuhn (2012) continued that causal modeling by
of age, and qualified it in terms of human excep- infants affects understanding of the nature of the
tionalism. This is consistent with my view that events and categories involved (e.g., Sobel &
humans should be called Homo Causa. However, Buchanan, 2009). Causal understanding becomes
on the one hand, there is enough evidence to indi- “a source of concept formation,” or a “conceptual
cate that higher nonhuman primates express not glue” bringing concepts beyond their set of fea-
only 18-month-old Piagetian cognition but also tures (Lombrozo, 2009). This has been demon-
the ensuing one of the preoperational period (see strated in preschoolers who were able to construct
Chap. 33). In this regard, human exceptionalism at representation of causal relations that included
the causal level might be found in the concrete data and mechanism (Schulz & Gopnik, 2004).
operational guidance of causal thought in the older Wellman and Liu (2007) had presented results that
child. Moreover, on the other hand, the higher- supported that prediction is secondary in causal
order relational cognition attributed by Walker and learning to reasoning from an event about its cause.
Gopnik to the 18-month-old should reveal senso- Kuhn and Dean (2004) showed that preschoolers
rimotor vestiges according to Piagetian thought update their beliefs (expectations) in light of new
(he referred to invented mental combinations at evidence (but outside of awareness/control).
this age, but one still sensorimotorically-informed), Kuhn, Pease, and Wirkala (2009) specified
so might be best to conceive of a higher-order rela- some of the inference rules needed for better
tional cognition at this age in less than a purely causal reasoning. For example, attributing cau-
representational form. sality from co-occurrence needs to move toward
comparison. Kuhn (2010) showed that preschool-
ers can reason from outcome to cause (back-
Children wards, diagnostic reasoning) and also from cause
to expected outcome (predictive reasoning), with
Three-Year-Olds Kuhn (2012) presented a explanatory causal model building central to
framework for understanding the development of learning.
causal reasoning, and also individual differences Booth (2014) had shown that 3-year-olds
therein, in terms of how the inference rules remember novel labels better when the reference
needed in the process develop. Kuhn (2012) involved concerns causal properties rather than
organized her framework based on a distinction causally-irrelevant ones. Alvarez and Booth
between causal inference and causal prediction (2015) further studied 3-year-olds, who in the
(the more important). research observed two puppets describing prop-
For understanding the launching event as erties of items that were either causal ones or
causal (as in A strikes B), Michotte (1946) had matched noncausal ones. The children signifi-
suggested that an innate mechanism is involved. cantly preferred hearing causal descriptions on
Recent work continues with this perspective, or test trials after familiarization ones.
similar models of early causal understanding Alvarez and Booth (2015) noted that the
(Carey, 2009; Cohen, Chaput, & Cashon, 2002; results support Piaget (1952), who had argued
Sobel & Kirkham, 2007). that children function as “little scientists” in
However, even if developed early, the mecha- their quest for knowledge. The authors con-
nism for perceiving a causal connection between cluded that preschoolers are highly motivated to
two events needs addition of more specific and learn about the causal structure of their world
complex inference rules. For example, early on, and to seek out in an active way and to use
infants develop expectations about the physical learned information regarding novel causal
environment and its event-related causal rela- properties.
tions, a capacity that is revealed by surprise reac-
tions upon expectation violation (Baillargeon Four-Year-Olds Seiver et al. (2013) showed that,
et al., 2010). as in making physical causal inferences, children
406 16 Causal Learning: Understanding the World

(4- to 6-year-olds) use both covariational evidence The authors concluded that causal learning
and prior knowledge to make social causal infer- and social information search are both active pro-
ences or hypotheses. The results fit the general cesses in children. They related their model to the
findings in the field that even preschoolers are con- contention of Boyd, Richerson, and Henrich
structing more abstract causal schemes or “frame- (2011) that humans are unique not only in their
work theories” (also, see Goodman et al., 2011), causal reasoning capacities but also, and even
which in the social arena are akin to social sche- more so, because of our ability to learn from oth-
mata (Kelley, 1967). I would add that these sche- ers. Boyd et al. (2011) also noted that experts
mata are liable to development within the Piagetian might acquire a causal understanding of adaptive
cognitive developmental model, as per Young’s tools and techniques by cultural learning, includ-
(2011) Neo-Piagetian elaboration of social sche- ing overcopying; the causal understanding
mata (see Chap. 31). improves in micro-steps.
Banerjee and Bloom (2015) studied chil- Atance, Metcalf, Martin-Ordas, and Walker
dren’s beliefs about purpose in life events. Their (2014) examined children’s causal explanations
three experiments showed that children favor in terms of whether alterations in post-action
purpose-based teleological explanations. This information can alter their causal attributions.
could reflect a general bias in children to reason They found that 3- to 6-year-olds could not grasp
teleologically (e.g., about social behavior). that actions need to be related only to pre-action
Teleological explanations appear helpful to information, and not at all to post-action informa-
children in understanding why significant life tion. Specifically, the participants were shown a
events had occurred. Children seem to believe dog, and then asked to obtain some cheese to feed
that events occur to teach lessons, for example. it. Upon return, they found a mouse present rather
At first, they do this indiscriminately (e.g., age than a dog. Until the age of 7, the children
5), but then develop a more discerning approach claimed that they obtained the cheese in order to
to what is relevant. give it to the mouse. The results stand in contrast
Young, Alibali, and Kalish (2012) studied to earlier 3-year-old understanding of physical
causal learning in 5- to 6-year-olds and 9- to causality (e.g., a marble makes a puppet jump
10-year-olds. They focused on disagreements— before being impacted by it rather than after).
do others’ (agents, puppets) hypotheses affect the The authors concluded that the delay in reason-
children’s evaluations. When agents had dis- ing about the psychological world relative to the
agreed with the children’s hypotheses, for later physical world in terms of causality (in identify-
conditions without direct observation, children ing the causes of their own actions) is based on
drew stronger causal inferences in response deficits in theory of mind, inhibition, and execu-
to disagreements. Older children were espe- tive function, as well as the play of hindsight
cially sensitive to disagreement with ambiguous bias, at least for 3-year-olds. In 4- to 6-year-olds,
evidence. the delay might be caused by associative knowl-
Sobel and Kushnir (2013) showed the paral- edge (use of scripts, gists).
lels between children’s causal learning and Hoerl, McCormack, and Beck (2011) under-
their social learning from social information. scored that each of McCormack, Frosch, and
Children generally rationally evaluate their Burns (2011), Beck, Riggs, and Burns (2011), and
observational and action-related evidence in Perner and Rafetseder (2011) noted that counter-
relation to their existing conceptual knowledge factual thought is a sophisticated cognitive acqui-
in order to ascertain the relevance and informa- sition that does not fully develop until 10–12
tiveness of the evidence. At the social level, years of age. Younger children might have their
select social learning takes place and involves counterfactual reasoning masked, however
selective trust of another’s evidence or “testi- (Sobel, 2011). They might lack sufficient knowl-
mony.” For both experiential and social evi- edge of a domain to apply their counterfactual
dence selection, children are active selectors reasoning. Nevertheless, at this age, they lack a
compared to passive knowledge recipients. proper grasp of the functional role of knowledge.
Changes by Age in Causal Learning 407

Comment tion, reasoning, and aspects of language.


Sloman, Fernbach, and Ewing (2009) consid-
The research on children related to causal learn- ered causal structure as serving the infrastruc-
ing has especially focused on causal reasoning ture for moral judgments.
and its limits. The research with older children For Sloman and Lagnado (2015), these types
has moved into the area of counterfactual reason- of findings indicate that causal thought cannot be
ing. Once more, there might be parallels between accounted for by a strict Bayesian, probabilistic
the findings with preschoolers and school-age approach (e.g., Pearl, 2000). The latter approach
children in terms of Piaget’s model in that, at this does not consider sufficiently mechanisms.
age, there is a transition from preoperational to Moreover, in causal thinking, people think in
concrete operational thought. Please understand narratives and by mental simulation, which is
that I am not arguing that the Piagetian model can not accounted for by dependency modeling of
explain all the results in the field of causal learn- probabilistic knowledge. The authors concluded
ing in children. However, it might provide a scaf- that mechanisms, narratives, and mental simula-
fold to help better integrate the diverse data and tion together constitute the hallmark of causal
explain the qualitative differences from one age reasoning.
period to the next. In this regard, I note that my Güss and Robinson (2014) maintained that
Neo-Piagetian version of Piaget’s work contains causality is central to the decision-making
substages in the preoperational/concrete opera- process. Decision makers need to predict the con-
tional period, and they might help explain differ- sequences of their decisions in the process of
ences in causal learning in 2-year-olds compared arriving at them. Normally, one considers the pre-
to 4-, 6-, 8-, and 10-year-olds, the approximate dicted effects of each option in the planned actions
ages associated with the substages involved. that fit the particular contexts. This approach to
predicted causality is a constructivist one, in that
the agents’ predictions are personally-derived.
Adults Moreover, culture constitutes another factor influ-
encing the decision-making process. For example,
Causal Reality Recent modeling of causal rea- a cultural environment might not be conducive to
soning in adults has illustrated the diversity in long-term predictions. The authors concluded that
approaches in this area. Sloman and Lagnado all decisions are embedded within specific eco-
(2015) considered causal knowledge as crucial to cultural historical circumstances. In this sense, all
thought. The cognitive system is constructed to decisions are cultural ones (I would add: as much
help determine the causality of the unfolding of as personal ones).
events. Causal notions constitute the infrastruc- Reuter, Kirfel, van Riel, and Barlassina (2014)
ture of human thought. showed how the cognitive process of causal selec-
Kahneman and Tversky (1982a, 1982b) had tion in adults is influenced by both temporal factors
found that people substitute causal inferences and moral judgment. In causal selection, one or
for other types of judgments that had been more aspects of a causal structure that is complex
requested. Waldmann and Holyoak (1992) and are attributed causality for an index effect.
Cheng (1997) had argued that people judge in a Typically, later actions are attributed as causal rela-
manner that is tuned tightly to belief about tive to early ones. However, the effect is moderated
causal structure and its strength. Bechlivanidis by judgments of norm violation, for example.
and Lagnado (2013) found that causal beliefs Soto, Gershman, and Niv (2014) proposed a
can have people reorder events so that they are statistical, Bayesian model to explain com-
consistent with the temporality in the belief pound generalization (e.g., learning from one
(even if the belief is trained by an intervention). situation to the next when they are similar) in asso-
Chater and Oaksford (2013) maintained that ciative and causal learning. The person appears
causal notions are critical to learning, percep- to use rational principles of dimensional
408 16 Causal Learning: Understanding the World

generalization, and the model expands the Haidle (2014) argued that humans are unique
scope of latent cause theories in this regard. in the “drive” to seek and to generalize “causal
Meder, Mayrhofer, and Waldmann (2014) explanations.” We excel relative to other primates
examined diagnostic reasoning from single in inferring causal mechanisms relating covaria-
effects to single causes. They argued that the tions in cause and effect, which is inferential
beliefs of the person reasoning about the exis- causal reasoning. Also, we excel in the ability to
tence and strength between cause and effect in recognize that causal mechanisms underpin
linkages are involved in diagnostic judgments, events that are analogous causally, which is ana-
which then are not only based on using empirical logical causal reasoning (Vaesen, 2012). She
probabilities of causes given effects. People go applied this model to cultural performances,
beyond the information available and infer using including tool use. She concluded that the same
the unobserved causal level and not just the model can apply to “performances” in the cogni-
observed data level. tive sphere, I note that her model of cultural/cog-
Flores, Cobos, López, and Godoy (2014) nitive performances is quite biopsychosocial in
showed that even expert adults engage in fast nature (see Fig. 16.1).
causal reasoning processes when dealing online Böhm and Pfister (2015) specified layperson
(in an ongoing way) with cases in their disci- causal theories of behavior. The model includes
pline. Specifically, clinicians use idiosyncratic seven categories in the “what” of causal explana-
casual theories, structures, or scripts in dealing tion: goals; dispositions; temporary states, e.g.,
with hypothetical clinical reports for common emotions; intentional actions; outcomes; events;
DSM-IV-TR (Diagnostic and Statistical Manual and attributes of stimuli. The seven categories of
of Mental Disorders, Fourth Edition, Text lay explanations of causality appear to work
Revision; American Psychiatric Association, according to inference rules. Finally, the process
2000) disorders. This type of finding represents a of causal explanation in adults appears to incor-
“causal bias” and it comes into play early in porate knowledge-based aspects or contents.
dealing with cases. The causal reasoning process Gilbert, Tenney, Holland, and Spellman (2015)
is akin to the intuitive, automatic thinking found evidence in support of a model of causal
described in Evans and Stanovich (2013) and attributions based on the primacy of actors hav-
Kahneman (2011; Type I and System I, respec- ing knowledge relevant to a potential outcome
tively). Of course, clinicians also use slow, (even without having an intent for the action at
deliberative, logical reasoning (e.g., when there issue or a motive to immorality). In addition, the
are inconsistencies, Type II and System II, causal attributions were mediated by counterfac-
respectively). tual thinking (imagining how the outcome at
Widlok (2014) reviewed concepts of agency issue could have been prevented by different con-
in the ethnography in causality. One finds narra- trollable actions that could be implemented).
tives on natural causes and superhuman agents, Causal analysis has been applied to trait dif-
including witchcraft, powers, and gods. For ferences and their conjunctions within people by
example, the Dinka considers ultra-human pow- using causal trait theory. Critcher, Dunning, and
ers as part of the natural world. Similarly, Rom (2015) noted that causal trait theories are
Kronenfeld (2014) queried the meaning of used to explain why an individual’s status on one
“causal cognition.” He referred to “collective” trait relates to his or her status on other ones
action, knowledge, and cognition in this regard. (“causes or is caused by”). People use models
These anthropological concepts add to the bio- such as these not only about the self but also
psychosocial understanding of behavior and its about others, as they create implicit theories of
causality, with one aspect of behavior in this their personality.
regard being causal understanding and the influ- Lefèvre, Lepresle, and Chariot (2015) applied
ence on it of culture. Bayesian causal network analysis to determine
Changes by Age in Causal Learning 409

Innovation, Tradition)
(Social Learning,
Individual (Learning,
Invention, Epigenetics)

Cultural
Biological (genes, selection) Performances
Historical-Social

Development (Time Depths)

Context (Conspecifics, Relations


Agents/ Objects)

Fig. 16.1 A dimensional model of cultural performances. The three dimensions of cultural performances are embedded
in/interdependent with the particular environmental context. Adapted from Haidle (2014)

factors in total incapacity to work in assault sur- pre-existing, recorded state. Belief state is
vivors. The results complemented those of tradi- not determined before measurement; mea-
tional analyses. surement “forces a resolution” of the pre-
existing indeterminacy.
Causal Irreality Trueblood and Busemeyer (b) Preceding the process of measurement, cog-
(2014; also see Trueblood & Busemeyer, 2011) nition functions more like a wave than a par-
developed a quantum probability model of causal ticle; this allows people to experience
reasoning. It is beyond the scope of the present simultaneously ambiguities about different
work to present the advanced mathematics belief states. Consistent with quantum prob-
involved, but the authors presented four factors ability modeling, the beliefs that one might
in support of their approach. have remain in a superimposed (simultane-
According to Trueblood and Busemeyer ous) state until the final judgment is made.
(2011), a quantum approach to human judgment This resolves the uncertainty in the process,
making is viable because of the following four resulting in collapse of the cognitive wave
reasons: into a particle having a specific position.
(c) Each judgment that is made disturbs and gen-
(a) When humans arrive at judgments, they con- erates uncertainty about another in a process
struct them from the question in context; of incompatibility, e.g., any one judgment can
judgments are not merely read-outs from a affect context and, therefore, later judgments.
410 16 Causal Learning: Understanding the World

(d) The logic of cognition does not necessarily early acquisitions are more sanguine, conserva-
obey the laws of classical logic. A quantum tive, and consistent with a gradualist view.
probability model of human reasoning can However, in the chapter, I present an elabora-
accommodate to this state of affairs. tion of cognitive schema modeling that permits
Bayesian-type probabilistic thinking while allow-
ing their gradual development through cognitive
Comment substages, such as in Neo-Piagetian models.
The social and practical experience in sensorimo-
Children are well on their way to causal under- tor activity might lead to rapid, sophisticated
standing, learning, and reasoning by the pre- Bayesian-type estimates that consolidate in infer-
school period. Piaget’s preoperational and ences or their precursors. However, perspectives
concrete operational stages in this regard are sim- like these need to be complemented by cognitive
ilar to the proposed distinction between System I models that allow the development of more
and System II thinking, and therefore might advanced abstractions on which the hypothesis-
inform the progression on these matters in the generation process maps, so to speak.
childhood period. Similarly, Piaget’s formal, Nevertheless, this type of hybrid modeling needs
abstract period that develops in adolescence could to respect the limits imposed by the characteris-
be informative for that age period. Neo-Piagetian tics of the sensorimotor substages involved,
models that construe a postformal stage in the although these are evolving in Neo-Piagetian
adult age period might also be beneficial in under- work (e.g., Young, 2011).
standing the complexity of causal thinking the
adult. For example, in my model (Young, 2011),
the postformal adult stage is referred to as
References
Collective Intelligence. It would appear that not
only the higher-order thinking in adults might be Alvarez, A. L., & Booth, A. E. (2015). Preschoolers prefer
characterized especially by causal reasoning at a to learn causal information. Frontiers in Psychology,
superordinate abstract level but also the collective 6, 60. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2015.00060.
or group cognition that we create culturally might American Psychiatric Association. (2000). Diagnostic
and statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM-
be marked by the causality imperative being dis- IV-TR (4th ed., text rev.). Washington, DC:
cussed as part of human exceptionalism. Author.
Apperly, I. A., & Butterfill, S. A. (2009). Do humans have
two systems to track beliefs and belief-like states?
Psychological Review, 116, 953–970.
Chapter Conclusions Atance, C. M., Metcalf, J. L., Martin-Ordas, G., & Walker,
C. L. (2014). Young children’s causal explanations are
The study of causal learning in childhood has biased by post-action associative information.
even considered how neonates might express Developmental Psychology, 50, 2675–2685.
Baillargeon, R., Li, J., Gertner, Y., & Wu, D. (2010). How
antecedents of abstract thoughts in “primitives” do infants reason about physical events? In
that are implicitly inferential and abstract. The U. Goswami (Ed.), Handbook of childhood cognitive
young infant might rationally construct causal development (2nd ed., pp. 11–48). Oxford, UK:
cognitions both at the physical launching level Blackwell.
Banerjee, K., & Bloom, P. (2015). “Everything happens
and at more complex levels, including the under- for a reason”: Children’s beliefs about purpose in life
standing of perceived events and action-supported events. Child Development, 86, 503–518.
activities. The notion that these more advanced Barrett, T., Davis, E. F., & Needham, A. (2007). Learning
cognitive skills could take place so early on has to use a tool in infancy. Developmental Psychology,
43, 352–368.
been attributed to Bayesian, probabilistic learn- Bechlivanidis, C., & Lagnado, D. A. (2013). Does the
ing mechanisms even early in life. As usual in “why” tell us the “when”? Psychological Science, 20,
work in development, other points of view about 1221–1228.
References 411

Beck, S. R., Riggs, K. J., & Burns, P. (2011). Multiple Critcher, C. R., Dunning, D., & Rom, S. C. (2015).
developments in counterfactual thinking. In C. Hoerl, Causal trait theories: A new form of person knowl-
T. McCormack, & S. R. Beck (Eds.), Understanding edge that explains egocentric pattern projection.
counterfactual, understanding causation: Issues in Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 108,
philosophy and psychology (pp. 110–122). New York: 400–416.
Oxford University Press. Csibra, G., Bíró, S., Koós, O., & Gergely, G. (2003).
Böhm, G., & Pfister, H.-R. (2015). How people explain One-year-old infants use teleological representa-
their own and others’ behavior: A theory of lay causal tions of actions productively. Cognitive Science, 27,
explanation. Frontiers in Psychology, 6, 139. 111–133.
doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2015.00139. Csibra, G., & Gergely, G. (2005). Social learning and
Bonawitz, E., Denison, S., Griffiths, T. L., & Gopnik, A. social cognition: The case for pedagogy. In
(2014). Probabilistic models, learning algorithms, and Y. Munakata & M. H. Johnson (Eds.), Process of
response variability: Sampling in cognitive develop- change in brain and cognitive development. Attention
ment. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 18, 497–500. and Performance XXI (pp. 249–274). Oxford, UK:
Booth, A. E. (2014). Effects of causal information on Oxford University Press.
early world learning: Efficiency and longevity. Denison, S., Bonawitz, E., Gopnik, A., & Griffiths, T. L.
Cognitive Development, 33, 99–107. (2014). Rational variability in children’s causal infer-
Boyd, R., Richerson, P. J., & Henrich, J. (2011). The cul- ences: The sampling hypothesis. Cognition, 126,
tural niche: Why social learning is essential for human 285–300.
adaptation. Proceedings of the National Academy of Denison, S., Reed, C., & Xu, F. (2013). The emergence of
Sciences, USA, 108, 10918–10925. probabilistic reasoning in very young infants:
Brandone, A. C. (2015). Infants’ social and motor experi- Evidence from 4.5- and 6-month-old infants.
ence and the emerging understanding of intentional Developmental Psychology, 49, 243–249.
actions. Developmental Psychology, 51, 512–523. Denison, S., Trikutam, P., & Xu, F. (2014). Probability
Brandone, A., & Wellman, H. M. (2009). You can’t always versus representativeness in infancy: Can infants use
get what you want: Infants understand failed goal- naïve physics to adjust population base rates in
directed actions. Psychological Science, 20, 85–91. probabilistic inference? Developmental Review, 50,
Buchsbaum, D., Seiver, E., Beidgers, S., & Gopnik, A. 2009–2019.
(2013). Learning about causes from people and about Denison, S., & Xu, F. (2010a). Integrating physical con-
people as causes: Probabilistic models and social straints in statistical inference by 11-month-old
causal reasoning. In F. Xu & T. Kushnir (Eds.), infants. Cognitive Science, 34, 885–908.
Advances in child development and behavior: Rational Denison, S., & Xu, F. (2010b). Twelve- to 14-month-
constructivism in cognitive development (Vol. 43, old infants can predict single-event probability
pp. 125–160). Waltham, MA: Academic. with large set sizes. Developmental Science, 13,
Cacchione, T., Schaub, S., & Rakoczy, H. (2013). 798–803.
Fourteen-month-old infants infer the continuous iden- Denison, S., & Xu, F. (2013). Probabilistic inference in
tity of objects on the basis of nonvisible causal proper- human infants. In F. Xu & T. Kushnir (Eds.), Advances
ties. Developmental Psychology, 49, 1325–1329. in child development and behavior: Rational con-
Carey, S. (2009). The origins of concepts. New York: structivism in cognitive development (Vol. 43,
Oxford University Press. pp. 27–58). Waltham, MA: Academic.
Carlson, S. M., Koenig, M. A., & Harms, M. B. (2013). Desrochers, S., Ricard, M., & Décarie, T. G. (1995).
Theory of mind. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Understanding causality in infancy: A reassessment of
Cognitive Science, 4, 391–402. Piaget’s theory. Cahiers de Psychologie Cognitive, 14,
Cesana-Arlotti, N., Téglás, E., & Bonatti, L. L. (2013). 255–268.
The probable and the possible at 12 months: Intuitive Dewar, K. M., & Xu, F. (2010). Induction, overhypothe-
reasoning about the uncertain future. In F. Xu & sis, and the origin of abstract knowledge. Psychological
T. Kushnir (Eds.), Advances in child development and Science, 21, 1871–1877.
behavior: Rational constructivism in cognitive devel- Evans, J., & Stanovich, K. (2013). Dual-process theories
opment (Vol. 43, pp. 1–25). Waltham, MA: Academic. of higher cognition: Advancing the debate.
Chater, N., & Oaksford, M. (2013). Programs as causal Perspectives on Psychological Science, 8, 223–241.
models: Speculations on mental programs and mental Fernando, C. (2013). From blickets to synapses: Inferring
representation. Cognitive Science, 37, 1171–1191. temporal causal networks by observation. Cognitive
Chen, M. L., & Waxman, S. R. (2013). “Shall we blick?”: Science, 37, 1426–1470.
Novel words highlight actors’ underlying intentions Flores, A., Cobos, P. L., López, F. J., & Godoy, A. (2014).
for 14-month-old infants. Developmental Psychology, The influence of causal connections between
49, 426–431. symptoms on the diagnosis of mental disorders:
Cheng, P. (1997). From covariation to causation: A causal Evidence from online and offline measures. Journal
power theory. Psychological Review, 104, 367–405. of Experimental Psychology: Applied, 20, 175–190.
Cohen, L., Chaput, H., & Cashon, C. (2002). A construc- Gergely, G., Bekkering, H., & Kiraly, I. (2002). Rational
tivist model of infant cognition. Cognitive imitation in preverbal infants. Nature, 415, 755.
Development, 17, 1323–1343. doi:10.1038/415755a.
412 16 Causal Learning: Understanding the World

Gergely, G., & Csibra, G. (2003). Teleological reasoning Gweon, H., & Schulz, L. (2011). 16-month-olds rationally
about actions: The Naïve theory of rational actions. infer causes of failed actions. Science, 332, 1524.
Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7, 287–292. doi:10.1126/science.1204493.
Gergely, G., & Jacob, P. (2013). Reasoning about instru- Gweon, H., Tenenbaum, J. B., & Schulz, L. E. (2010).
mental and communicative agency in human infancy. Infants consider both the sample and the sampling pro-
In F. Xu & T. Kushnir (Eds.), Advances in child devel- cess in inductive generalization. Proceedings of the
opment and behavior: Rational constructivism in cog- National Academy of Sciences, USA, 107,
nitive development (Vol. 43, pp. 59–94). Waltham, 9066–9071.
MA: Academic. Haidle, M. N. (2014). Building a bridge – An archeolo-
Gerken, L. (2006). Decisions, decisions, decisions: Infant gist’s perspective on the evolution of causal cognition.
language learning when multiple generalizations are Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 1472. doi:10.3389/
possible. Cognition, 98, B67–B74. fpsyg.2014.01472.
Gerken, L. (2010). Infants use rational decision criteria Hamlin, J. K. (2013). Moral judgment and action in pre-
for choosing among models of their input. Cognition, verbal infants and toddlers: Evidence for an innate
115, 362–366. moral core. Current Directions in Psychological
Gerson, S., & Woodward, A. L. (2010). Building inten- Science, 23, 186–193.
tional action knowledge with one’s hands. In S. P. Hamlin, J. K., Ullman, T., Tenenbaum, J. B., Goodman,
Johnson (Ed.), Neo-constructivism (pp. 295–313). N., & Baker, C. (2013). The mentalistic basis of core
Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. social cognition: Experiments in preverbal infants and
Gerson, S. A., & Woodward, A. L. (2012). A claw is like a computational model. Developmental Science, 16,
my hand: Comparison supports goal analysis in 209–226.
infants. Cognition, 122, 181–192. Hamlin, J. K., & Wynn, K. (2011). Young infants prefer
Gilbert, E. A., Tenney, E. R., Holland, C. R., & Spellman, prosocial to antisocial others. Cognitive Development,
B. A. (2015). Counterfactuals, control, and causation: 26, 30–39.
Why knowledgeable people get blamed more. Heyes, C., & Frith, U. (2012). New thinking: The evolu-
Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin. tion of human cognition. Philosophical Transactions
doi:10.1177/0146167215572137. of the Royal Society B: Biological Science, 367,
Goodman, N. D., Ullman, T. D., & Tenenbaum, J. B. 2091–2096.
(2011). Learning a theory of causality. Psychological Hoerl, C., McCormack, T., & Beck, S. R. (2011).
Review, 118, 110–119. Understanding counterfactual, understanding causa-
Gopnik, A., & Bonawitz, E. (2014). Bayesian models of tion: Issues in philosophy and psychology. New York:
child development. Cognitive Science, 6, 75–86. Oxford University Press.
Gopnik, A., Glymour, C., Sobel, D. M., Schulz, L. E., Hohenberger, A., Elsabbagh, M., Serres, J., de Schoenen,
Kushnir, T., & Danks, D. (2004). A theory of causal S., Karmiloff-Smith, A., & Ascherslenben, G. (2013).
learning in children: Causal maps and Bayes nets. Understanding goal-directed human actions and phys-
Psychological Review, 111, 3–32. ical causality: The role of mother-infant interaction.
Gopnik, A., & Schulz, L. (2007). Introduction. In Infant Behavior and Development, 35, 898–911.
A. Gopnik & L. Schulz (Eds.), Causal learning: Howe, M. L., & Otgaar, H. (2013). Proximate mechanisms
Psychology, philosophy, and computation (pp. 1–15). and the development of adaptive memory. Current
New York: Oxford University Press. Directions in Psychological Science, 22, 16–22.
Gopnik, A., Sobel, D. M., Schulz, L., & Glymour, C. Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. New York:
(2001). Causal learning mechanisms in very young Farrar, Strauss, Giroux.
children: Two-, three-, and four-year-olds infer causal Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1982a). The simulation
relations from patterns of variation and covariation. heuristic. In D. Kahneman, P. Slovic, & A. Tversky
Developmental Psychology, 37, 620–629. (Eds.), Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and
Gopnik, A., & Wellman, H. M. (1992). Why the child’s biases (pp. 201–208). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
theory of mind really is a theory. Mind & Language, 7, University Press.
145–171. Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1982b). Variants of uncer-
Gopnik, A., & Wellman, H. M. (2012). Reconstructing tainty. Cognition, 11, 143–157.
constructivism: Causal models, Bayesian learning Kelley, H. H. (1967). Attribution theory in social psychol-
mechanisms, and the theory. Psychological Bulletin, ogy. In D. Levine (Ed.), Nebraska symposium on moti-
138, 1085–1108. vation (Vol. 15, pp. 192–238). Lincoln, NB: University
Griffiths, T. L., Sobel, D. M., Tenenbaum, J. B., & Gopnik, of Nebraska Press.
A. (2011). Bayes and blickets: Effects of knowledge Khemlani, S. S., Barbey, A. K., & Jonson-Laird, P. N.
on causal induction in children and adults. Cognitive (2014). Causal reasoning with mental models.
Science, 35, 1407–1455. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 8, 849.
Güss, C. D., & Robinson, B. (2014). Predicted causality in Kim, S. H., Feldman, J., & Singh, M. (2013). Perceived
decision making: The role of culture. Frontiers in causality can alter the perceived trajectory of apparent
Psychology, 5, 479. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00739. motion. Psychological Science, 24, 575–582.
References 413

Kretch, K. S., & Adolph, K. E. (2013). Cliff or step? Loucks, J., & Sommerville, J. A. (2012). The role of
Posture-specific learning at the edge of a drop-off. motor experience in understanding action function:
Child Development, 84, 226–240. The case of the precision grasp. Child Development,
Kronenfeld, D. B. (2014). What “causal cognition” might 83, 801–809.
mean. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 1204. doi:10.3389/ Low, J. (2010). Preschoolers’ implicit and explicit false-
fpsyg.2014.01204. belief understanding: Relations with complex syntac-
Kuhl, P. K. (2004). Early language acquisition: Cracking tical mastery. Child Development, 81, 597–615.
the speech code. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 5, Lucas, C. G., Gopnik, A., & Griffiths, T. L. (2010).
831–843. Developmental differences in learning the forms of
Kuhn, D. (2010). What is scientific thinking and how does causal relationships. In R. Camtrabone & S. Ohlsson
it develop? In U. Goswami (Ed.), Handbook of child- (Eds.), Proceedings of the 32nd Annual Conference of
hood cognitive development (2nd ed., pp. 497–523). the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 2852–2857).
Oxford, UK: Blackwell. Austin, TX: Cognitive Science Society.
Kuhn, D. (2012). The development of causal reasoning. Ma, L., & Xu, F. (2011). Young children’s use of statisti-
Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science, 3, cal sampling evidence to infer the subjectivity of pref-
327–335. erences. Cognition, 120, 403–411.
Kuhn, D., & Dean, D. (2004). Connecting scientific rea- Martin, A., Vouloumanos, A., & Onishi, K. (2012).
soning and causal inference. Journal of Cognitive Understanding the abstract role of speech in commu-
Development, 5, 261–288. nication at 12 months. Cognition, 123, 50–60.
Kuhn, D., Pease, M., & Wirkala, C. (2009). Coordinating Mascalzoni, E., Regolin, L., Vallortigara, G., & Simion, F.
effects of multiple variables: A skill fundamental to (2013). The cradle of causal reasoning: Newborns’
causal and scientific reasoning. Journal of preference for physical causality. Developmental
Experimental Child Psychology, 103, 268–284. Science, 16, 327–335.
Kushnir, T., & Gopnik, A. (2005). Young children infer McCormack, T., Frosch, C., & Burns, P. (2011). The rela-
causal strength from probabilities and interventions. tionship between children’s causal and counterfactual
Psychological Science, 16, 678–683. judgements. In C. Hoerl, T. McCormack, & S. R. Beck
Kushnir, T., & Gopnik, A. (2007). Conditional probability (Eds.), Understanding counterfactual, understanding
versus spatial contiguity in causal learning: causation: Issues in philosophy and psychology
Preschoolers use new contingency evidence to over- (pp. 54–74). New York: Oxford University Press.
come prior spatial assumptions. Developmental Meder, B., Mayrhofer, R., & Waldmann, M. R. (2014).
Psychology, 43, 186–196. Structure induction in diagnostic causal reasoning.
Kushnir, T., Xu, F., & Wellman, H. M. (2010). Young chil- Psychological Review, 121, 277–301.
dren use statistical sampling to infer the preferences of Meltzoff, A. N. (2007). “Like me”: A foundation for social
other people. Psychological Science, 21, 1134–1140. cognition. Developmental Science, 10, 126–134.
Lefèvre, T., Lepresle, A., & Chariot, P. (2015). Detangling Meltzoff, A. N., & Decety, J. (2003). What imitation tells
complex relationships in forensic data: Principles and us about social cognition: A rapprochement between
use of causal networks and their application to clinical developmental psychology and cognitive science.
forensic science. International Journal of Legal Philosophical Transaction of the Royal Society
Medicine, 129, 1163–1172. London B, Biological Sciences, 358, 491–500.
Legare, C. H. (2012). Exploring explanation: Explaining Meltzoff, A. N., Waismeyer, A., & Gopnik, A. (2012).
inconsistent evidence informs exploratory, hypothesis- Learning about causes from people: Observational
testing behavior in young children. Child Development, causal learning in 24-month-old infants.
83, 173–185. Developmental Psychology, 48, 1215–1228.
Legare, C. H. (2014). The contributions of explanation Michotte, A. E. (1946/1963). The perception of causality.
and exploration to children’s scientific reasoning. New York: Basic Books.
Child Development Perspectives, 8, 101–106. Muentener, P., & Carey, S. (2010). Infants’ causal repre-
Legare, C. H., Gelman, S. A., & Wellman, H. W. (2010). sentations of state change events. Cognition
Inconsistency with prior knowledge triggers children’s Psychology, 61, 63–86.
causal explanatory reasoning. Child Development, 81, Onishi, K. H., & Baillargeon, R. (2005). Do 15-month-old
929–944. infants understand false beliefs? Science, 308,
Lepage, J. F., & Théoret, H. (2007). The mirror neuron 255–258.
system: Grasping others’ actions from birth? Pearl, J. (2000). Causality: Models, reasoning, and infer-
Developmental Science, 10, 513–523. ence. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.
Lombrozo, T. (2009). Explanation and categorization: How Pearl, J. (2009). Causality: Models, reasoning, and infer-
“why?” informs “what?”. Cognition, 110, 248–253. ence (2nd ed.). New York: Cambridge University
Loucks, J., & Sommerville, J. A. (2011, October). Adult Press.
and infant attention during action perception in con- Penn, D. C., Holyoak, K. J., & Povinelli, D. J. (2008).
text dependent. Poster presented at the biennial meet- Darwin’s mistake: Explaining the discontinuity
ing of the Cognitive Development Society, between human and nonhuman minds. Behavioral and
Philadelphia, PA. Brain Sciences, 31, 109–178.
414 16 Causal Learning: Understanding the World

Perfors, A., Tenenbaum, J. B., Griffiths, T. L., & Xu, F. conditional interventions. Developmental Psychology,
(2011). A tutorial introduction to Bayesian models of 43, 1045–1050.
cognitive development. Cognition, 120, 302–321. Schulz, L. E., & Sommerville, J. (2006). God does not
Perner, J., & Rafetseder, E. (2011). Counterfactual and other play dice: Causal determinism and children’s infer-
forms of conditional reasoning: Children lost in the near- ences about unobserved causes. Child Development,
est possible world. In C. Hoerl, T. McCormack, & S. R. 77, 427–442.
Beck (Eds.), Understanding counterfactual, under- Schulz, L. E., Standing, H. R., & Bonawitz, E. B. (2008).
standing causation: Issues in philosophy and psychol- Word, thought, and deed: The role of object categories
ogy (pp. 90–109). New York: Oxford University Press. in children’s inductive inferences and exploratory
Piaget, J. (1926). The language and thought of the child. play. Developmental Psychology, 44, 1266–1276.
London, UK: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner, & Co. Scott, R. M., & Baillargeon, R. (2013). Do infants really
(Original work Le langage et la pensée chez l’enfant expect agents to act efficiently? A critical test of the
published 1923). rationality principle. Psychological Science, 24,
Piaget, J. (1929). The child’s conception of the world. 466–474.
London, UK: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Seiver, E., Gopnik, A., & Goodman, N. (2013). Did she
Piaget, J. (1930). The child’s conception of physical cau- jump because she was the big sister or because the
sality. New York: Harcourt Brace. trampoline was safe? Causal inference and the devel-
Piaget, J. (1937). La construction du reel chez l’enfant opment of social attribution. Child Development, 84,
[The construction of reality in the child]. Neuchatel, 443–454.
Switzerland: Delachaux et Niestle. Senju, A., & Csibra, G. (2008). Gaze following in human
Piaget, J. (1952). The origins of intelligence in children. infants depends on communicative signals. Current
Oxford, UK: International Universities Press. Biology, 18, 668–671.
Piaget, J. (1954). The construction of reality in the child Sloman, S. A., Fernbach, P. M., & Ewing, S. (2009).
(M. Cook, Trans.). New York: Basic Books. Causal models: The representational infrastructure for
Piaget, J. (1955). The child’s conception of the world. moral judgment. In D. M. Bartels, C. W. Bauman, L. J.
London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Skitka, & D. L. Medin (Eds.), Psychological of learn-
Rakison, D. H., & Krogh, L. (2012). Does causal action ing and motivation (Moral judgment and decision
facilitate causal perception in infants younger than 6 making, Vol. 50, pp. 1–26). San Diego, CA: Academic.
months of age? Developmental Science, 15, 43–53. Sloman, S. A., & Lagnado, D. (2015). Causality in
Reuter, K., Kirfel, L., van Riel, R., & Barlassina, L. thought. Annual Review of Psychology, 66, 223–247.
(2014). The good, the bad, and the timely: How tem- Sobel, D. M. (2004). Exploring the coherence of young
poral order and moral judgment influence casual children’s explanatory abilities: Evidence from gener-
selection. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 1336. ating counterfactuals. British Journal of Developmental
doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.01336. Psychology, 22, 37–58.
Rogers, T. T., & McClelland, J. L. (2004). Semantic cog- Sobel, D. M. (2011). Domain-specific causal knowledge
nition: A parallel distributed processing approach. and children’s reasoning about possibility. In C. Hoerl,
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. T. McCormack, & S. R. Beck (Eds.), Understanding
Rolfs, M., Dambacher, M., & Cavanagh, P. (2013). Visual counterfactual, understanding causation: Issues in
adaptation of the perception of causality. Current philosophy and psychology (pp. 123–146). New York:
Biology, 23, 250–254. Oxford University Press.
Rottman, B. M., & Hastie, R. (2013). Reasoning about Sobel, D., & Buchanan, D. (2009). Bridging the gap:
causal relationships: Inferences on causal networks. Causality-at-a-distance in children’s categorization
Psychological Bulletin, 140, 109–139. and inferences about internal properties. Cognitive
Schlottmann, A., Ray, E. D., & Surian, L. (2012). Development, 24, 274–283.
Emerging perception of causality in action-and- Sobel, D. M., & Kirkham, N. Z. (2007). Bayes nets and
reaction sequences from 4 to 6 months of age: Is it babies: Infants’ developing statistical reasoning abili-
domain-specific? Journal of Experimental Child ties and their representation of causal knowledge.
Psychology, 112, 208–230. Developmental Science, 10, 298–306.
Scholl, B. J., & Tremoulet, P. D. (2000). Perceptual cau- Sobel, D. M., & Kirkham, N. Z. (2013). The influence of
sality and animacy. Trends in Cognitive Science, 4, social information of children’s statistical and causal
299–309. inferences. In F. Xu & T. Kushnir (Eds.), Advances in
Schulz, L. (2013). Finding new facts; thinking new child development and behavior: Rational construc-
thoughts. In F. Xu & T. Kushnir (Eds.), Advances in tivism in cognitive development (Vol. 43, pp. 321–
child development and behavior: Rational construc- 350). Waltham, MA: Academic.
tivism in cognitive development (Vol. 43, pp. 269– Sobel, D. M., & Kushnir, T. (2013). Knowledge matters:
294). Waltham, MA: Academic. How children evaluate the reliability of testimony as a
Schulz, L. E., & Gopnik, A. (2004). Causal learning across process of rational inference. Psychological Review,
domains. Developmental Psychology, 40, 162–176. 120, 779–797.
Schulz, L. E., Gopnik, A., & Glymour, C. (2007). Sobel, D. M., & Legare, C. H. (2014). Causal learning in
Preschool children learn about causal structure from children. Cognitive Science, 5, 413–427.
References 415

Sobel, D. M., Tenenbaum, J. B., & Gopnik, A. (2004). Waldmann, M. R., & Holyoak, K. J. (1992). Predictive
Children’s causal inferences from indirect evidence: and diagnostic learning within causal models:
Backwards blocking and Bayesian reasoning in pre- Asymmetries in cue competition. Journal of
schoolers. Cognitive Science, 28, 303–333. Experimental Psychology: General, 121, 222–236.
Sommerville, J. A. (2007). From ends to means: Infants’ Walker, C. M., & Gopnik, A. (2014). Toddlers infer
developing tool use representations. Invited talk at higher-order relational principles in causal learning.
Department of Psychology colloquium series, Duke Psychological Science, 25, 161–169.
University, Raleigh-Durham, NC. Wellman, H. M., & Gelman, S. A. (1992). Cognitive
Sommerville, J. A., Blumenthal, E. J., Venema, K., & Braun, development: Foundational theories of core domains.
K. (2011). The body in action: The impact of self-pro- Annual Review of Psychology, 43, 337–375.
duced action on infants’ action perception and under- Wellman, H. M., & Liu, D. (2004). Scaling of theory-of-
standing. In V. Slaughter & C. Brownwell (Eds.), Early mind tasks. Child Development, 75, 523–541.
development of body representations (pp. 247–266). Wellman, H., & Liu, D. (2007). Causal reasoning as
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. informed by the early development of explanations. In
Sommerville, J. A., Upshaw, M. B., & Loucks, J. (2013). A. Gopnik & L. Schulz (Eds.), Causal learning:
The nature of goal-directed action representations in Psychology, philosophy, and computation (pp. 261–
infancy. In F. Xu & T. Kushnir (Eds.), Advances in 279). New York: Oxford University Press.
child development and behavior: Rational construc- Widlok, T. (2014). Agency, time, and causality. Frontiers
tivism in cognitive development (Vol. 43, pp. 351– in Psychology, 5, 1264. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.01264.
387). Waltham, MA: Academic. Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of
Sommerville, J. A., & Woodward, A. L. (2005). Pulling causal explanation. New York: Oxford University
out the intentional structure of action: The relation Press.
between action processing and action production in Wu, R., Gopnik, A., Richardson, D. C., & Kirkham, N. Z.
infancy. Cognition, 95, 1–30. (2011). Infants learn about objects from statistics and
Soto, F. A., Gershman, S. J., & Niv, Y. (2014). Explaining people. Developmental Psychology, 47, 1220–1229.
compound generalization in associative and causal Wu, R., & Kirkham, N. Z. (2010). No two cues are alike:
learning through rational principles of dimensional Depth of learning during infancy is dependent on what
generalization. Psychological Review, 121, 526–558. orients attention. Journal of Experimental Child
Southgate, V., Chevallier, C., & Csibra, G. (2009). Psychology, 107, 118–136.
Sensitivity to communicative relevance tells young Xu, F., & Denison, S. (2009). Statistical inference and
children what to imitate. Developmental Science, 12, sensitivity to sampling in 11-month-old infants.
1013–1019. Cognition, 112, 97–104.
Spirtes, P., Glymour, C., & Scheines, R. (2001). Causation, Xu, F., & Garcia, V. (2008). Intuitive statistics by 8-month-
prediction, and search. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. old infants. Proceedings of the National Academy of
Surian, L., Caldi, S., & Sperber, D. (2007). Attribution of Sciences, USA, 105, 5012–5015.
beliefs to 13-month-old infants. Psychological Xu, F., & Kushnir, T. (2013a). Advances in child
Science, 18, 580–586. development and behavior: Rational constructivism
Teglas, E., Vul, E., Girotto, V., Gonzalez, M., Tenenbaum, in cognitive development (Vol. 43). Waltham, MA:
J. B., & Bonatti, L. L. (2011). Pure reasoning in Academic.
12-month-old infants as probabilistic inference. Xu, F., & Kushnir, T. (2013b). Preface. In F. Xu &
Science, 332, 1054–1059. T. Kushnir (Eds.), Advances in child development
Trueblood, J. S., & Busemeyer, J. R. (2011). A quantum and behavior: Rational constructivism in cognitive
probability account of order effects in inference. development (Vol. 43, pp. xi–xiv). Waltham, MA:
Cognitive Science, 35, 1518–1552. Academic.
Trueblood, J. S., & Busemeyer, J. R. (2014). A quantum Young, A. G., Alibali, M. W., & Kalish, C. W. (2012).
probability model of causal reasoning. Frontiers in Disagreement and causal learning: Others’ hypotheses
Psychology, 3, 1–13. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2012.00138. affect children’s evaluations of evidence.
Turati, C., Natale, E., Bolognini, N., Seena, I., Picozzi, Developmental Psychology, 48, 1242–1253.
M., Longhi, E., et al. (2013). The early development of Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
human mirror mechanisms: Evidence from electro- Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer
myographic recordings at 3 and 6 months. Science + Business Media.
Developmental Science, 16, 793–800. Yu, Y., & Kushnir, T. (2014). Social context effects in 2-
Vaesen, K. (2012). The cognitive bases of human tool use. and 4-year-olds’ selective versus faithful imitation.
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 35, 203–218. Developmental Psychology, 50, 922–933.
Developing the Mind, Minding
Development 17

Chapter Introduction Major Acquisitions of Mind

The first part of the present chapter reviews two Theory of Mind in Early Childhood
areas of child development that relate to grow-
ing self-control and awareness of others. The Introduction
areas are theory of mind/false belief and execu- For the area theory of mind in early childhood,
tive function/inhibition. Both areas show a tran- including infancy, Low and Perner (2012)
sition to increased skills around 3–4 years of described the nativist, modular view (e.g., Surian
age. However, to a degree in both cases, the & Geraci, 2012). That is, infants either possess
skills appear evident earlier and keep developing innately, or through preparation, critical domain-
after it. specific acquisitions, and the environment serves
The chapter shifts gears in its second part, to offer facilitatory prompts in their emergence
because it is the last one on development, so that and refinement from their innate base.
I return to major models discussed in the book, This nativist, modular account contrasts with
but this time, from a developmental perspective. the associativist, empirical one of gradual con-
Most of the chapter consists of presenting three ceptual gains in new principles discovered as
major models described at the outset of the book development proceeds. There might be core
for their developmental component. The three knowledge components, but external con-
models are the biopsychosocial, embodiment, straints, in particular, limit the full use of early
and systems perspectives. These models are simi- knowledge (e.g., in memory capacity, adequate
lar in that they are broad and potentially unifying, inhibition).
as well as emphasizing that development is about Low (2010; and Low & Perner, 2012) advo-
being grounded in relational participation and cated for the latter model for the earliest ages, by
interaction with the world. However, none of the suggesting a stepwise progression. First, there is
three models include a stage component to devel- an early-developing implicit, unconscious cogni-
opment, unlike my own (Young, 2011). In this tive system that develops piecemeal. Second, as
regard, there is room for a fruitful integration of development proceeds, one finds a later-
their views with mine. developing explicit, conscious cognitive system.

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 417


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_17
418 17 Developing the Mind, Minding Development

Rakoczy (2012) supported Low’s (2010) per- Scott and Baillargeon (2014) attempted to
spective by indicating that early cognitive abili- refute Heyes (2014a) reasoning. However, Heyes
ties do not necessarily indicate even an early (2014b) countered their argument that infants use
“implicit” theory of mind. Simpler psychological more advanced lab-demonstrated cognitive
states alone might be involved. That is, the earli- capacities in false-belief tasks.
est acquisitions are neither complex/core nor Research by Kovács, Télglás, and Endress
innate/prepared, or nativist. Their simpler start (2010) has given fodder to debate. In their novel
leads to later more complex acquisitions. procedure, 7-month-olds observed a false-belief
In the following, I elaborate further these two scene using “Smurfs.” A Smurf left the scene
opposing models in the development of early after which a ball was moved, so it held the false
cognition, especially for the area of theory of belief that a ball was behind a barrier, as it had
mind. As with the prior developmental chapters, perceived before leaving. When the Smurf
I show how Piaget’s model can help moderate the returned, the barrier involved was lowered and
differences in the various accounts of early devel- the Smurf expressed surprise at the result.
opment, and I add aspects that enrich the However, the infant watching what transpired did
approach, as well. not express surprise. There was also a control
condition (true belief) in which the Smurf saw
Gradual View what happened to the ball, not leaving the scene.
Ruffman (2014) provided a conservative view of The modular approach adherents maintain
early infant social understanding. Focusing on that the infants in the Kovács et al. (2010) study
false belief, he contended that radical interpreta- are “computing” online the Smurf’s beliefs, or,
tions attributing intentionality and the like to early they have a theory of mind. However, Ruffman,
cognitive activity in such tasks are too “rich” and Taumoepeau, and Perkins (2012) noted that a
premature. In the second year, at best, infants simpler (less “rich”) explanation is that the
might reflect on or represent another’s behavior infants in that study “register” differing percep-
rather than the person’s mental state. Infants do tions in the situations. They could be “represent-
not understand false belief (per contra, Carruthers, ing” the ball’s location “as much as” the Smurf’s
2013), nor is it innate or very early developing belief about it.
(per contra, Scott & Baillargeon, 2009). For Ruffman et al. (2012), as infants engage in
Only simpler capacities are innate in the reasoning, they use experiences of behavior
infant—related to statistical learning (e.g., sequences rather than mental states (supported by
Gopnik & Wellman, 2012) and domain-specific statistical learning skills). They use situation–
biases for faces, eyes, motion, and people. With action rules to derive an implicit sensitivity to
the help of environmental social factors, such as actions without directly representing “mental
parental verbal behavior to describe agent behav- intermediates” or “intervening mental states” in
ior, an implicit (striatum-based) understanding of the causal link to action from situation.
behavior develops (e.g., by perceptual access and Yott and Poulin-Dubois (2012) and Thoermer,
pattern recognition), which only later develops Sodian, Vuori, Perst, and Kristen (2012) also
into an explicit understanding of mental states resisted a “rich” interpretation of their findings with
(frontal cortex based). 18-month-olds for the cognitive advances shown in
Heyes (2014a) argued that the putative false their particular studies. They preferred to use
belief and theory of mind understanding in behavior-based (situation-action) explanations.
infancy could be interpreted at a simpler level. From a usage-based perspective, Liszkowski
These acquisitions reflect domain-general pro- (2013) went so far as to attribute a preliminary the-
cesses and reaction to “low-level novelty.” They ory of mind to infants. Infants appear to use flexible
include focus on colors, shapes, and movements action expectations to communicate with and inter-
in the typical procedures used. According to act socially with others, including prosocially,
Heyes, the research to date has yet to show that depending on the situation and person. For exam-
infants possess even an “implicit” theory of mind. ple, a 12-month-old, who is asked ambiguously
Major Acquisitions of Mind 419

about several objects, considers the object with et al., 2014). Infants can use mental-state reason-
which the adult has not yet interacted (Moll & ing and infer aspects of the mind of the other,
Tomasello, 2007). Infants of this age also initiate rather than simply using behavioral rules to inter-
interactions flexibly depending on expectations of pret and predict the intentional actions of others.
the others’ reactions (Liszkowski, Carpenter, When infants are tested on appropriate tasks (that
Henning, Striano, & Tomasello, 2004). do not trigger a prepotent bias to respond based
Also at this age, Knudsen and Liszkowski on reality or demand inhibitory skills to suppress
(2013) found that infants could even intervene in inappropriate prepotent responses), their rich
a proactive way by anticipating a mistake by ToM capacities can be ascertained.
another person. They would warn an adult before In a study with puppets, Choi and Luo (2015)
she reached for an “oversize” object that had demonstrated that infants of 13 months of age
been put back in its original place by a second possess an emergent theory of mind. After pup-
confederate adult while she had left the scene. pets A and B interacted positively by hopping,
(Control conditions: object not oversized; clapping, facing each other, and having a laugh
replacement observed by first adult). (mouth-open) face, the infants who watched the
The usage-based account of theory of mind puppets behaved as if they expected them to con-
presented by Liszkowski (2013) argues that the- tinue interacting this way. But, if one puppet hit
ory of mind is not only used in interaction but another and a third one saw it, the observer
also that interactional experiences, including infants expected the watching puppet not to con-
those related to it, “drive” development of predic- tinue the interaction, unless the hit was by acci-
tion of actions. In this sense, competence drives dent. The study demonstrated that one-year-olds
performance so that the model is not nativist, take into account agent intentions in interpreting
even if the competence arises early in develop- actions and formulating how agents should act
ment. As early as 2–3 months of age, infants par- socially. Additionally, the research demonstrated
ticipate in dyadic face-to-face interaction that that one-year-olds understand the false belief of
incorporates contingency detection (Gergely & others.
Watson, 1999).
Low and Perner (2012) supported the view Piaget’s View
that the development of a coherent theory of Dice and Dove (2011) related the early develop-
mind awaits a later age. Further developments in ing social cognitive act of joint attention at about
language skills assist in this acquisition (e.g., San 1 year of age to Piaget’s sensorimotor stages in
Juan & Astington, 2012). [In this regard, see infancy. In the social cognitive view, young
other work on the role of language framing in infants can engage in this behavior because either
children’s causal interpretations (by Muentener they intend to share information or they under-
and Schulz (2012), and Butler and Markman stand the intent of others to share information.
(2012), as well as Legare (2012) and Cimpian This happens because infants can become aware
and Erickson (2012)).] of another’s subjective attention/experience, hav-
ing a theory of mind, or mindedness.
Rapid View In Piaget’s (1950, 1952, 1960) cognitive
Others have rejected the approach that infants developmental model, infants are not yet able to
have only an implicit understanding of the other. think about another’s mental state, being cogni-
They reject the minimalist view of the develop- tively “egocentric.” In the infants’ sensorimotor
ment of theory of mind (ToM) based on statistical world, someone looking at what they are looking
learning and pattern recognition. They prefer a at sees it as they see it.
view that is richer in conceptualization of these At 12 months of age, infants are well into
early capacities (e.g., Scott, 2014). The latter Piaget’s stage of coordination of secondary circu-
view is that infants can mentally attribute goals, lar reactions, which is focused heavily on goal-
intentions, and beliefs to agents (Baillargeon directed behavior, including in detours. In this
420 17 Developing the Mind, Minding Development

sense, joint attention can be conceived of as goal- mind. There is no reason to doubt that it develops
directed coordination of action in reference to an like other cognitive acquisitions in terms of com-
(desired) object. That is, the referential behav- plexity and abstractness into adulthood.
iors/gestures in this activity suggest that they are
“motor signifiers,” or outward manifestations of
internal thought (albeit action-based). Further, Beyond Infancy
the actions indicate that the thought involved, or
schema, includes the other person as a vicarious Children
agent or source of causality, in a precursor step to
theory of mind and transition to the next senso- Devine and Hughes (2014) conducted a meta-
rimotor substage of tertiary circular reactions. In analysis of prior research on the question of the
this Piagetian account of referencing/joint atten- temporal relation between false belief understand-
tion, the social cognitive concept of joining ing and early childhood executive function (EF).
another person does not apply. Their analysis revealed that early individual differ-
ences in executive function predict later variation
Comment in understanding of false belief. The relationship
The rich point of view of the early theory of mind was not bidirectional; variation in early false belief
of the infant and its related capacities emphasizes understanding did not predict later executive func-
that early on infants can infer about the other, tion differences (Hughes, 1998).
mentally attribute about the other, and understand The meta-analysis conducted by Devine and
beliefs that the other might hold. They can reason Hughes (2014) involved 102 articles and data
mentally about the other, use flexible expecta- sets. The results of the meta-analysis were mod-
tions in action, anticipate mistakes by the other, erately significant. The cumulative sample num-
and take into account the intention of the other in bered almost 10,000 3- to 6-year-olds, who were
interpreting their actions and understanding how typically developing. Among the studies
the other should act. Even at the age of one year, reviewed, 10 were longitudinal, like that of
infants can understand the other’s false beliefs. Hughes (1998). The effects shown were “clearly”
In contrast, the minimalist nativist point of consistent with Hughes, 1998 findings.
view considers pattern recognition and action- Devine and Hughes (2014) concluded that the
based rule construction as better ways to under- theory that best explains the data is the emergence-
stand the behavior evident in the research at expression one (Russell, 1996). Executive func-
issue. Infants use statistical learning uncon- tion includes factors such as working memory
sciously or implicitly in a low-level, associative and inhibition, which help young children to
way, and domain-specific and general processes “attend to and reflect upon” the mental states of
that are independent of any cognitive modeling themselves and others, thereby facilitating later
or schemas. understanding of false belief (as in the classic
A Piagetian account might help explain the Sally-Anne task).
findings better. For example, joint attention in the
1-year-old might involve goal-directed coordina-
tion of activity in relation to a wanted object, as Adults
suggested by translating the behavior into the
language of Piaget’s fourth sensorimotor sub- Dunbar (2014) presented a model of the social
stage of coordination of secondary circular reac- brain that related social group size in evolution to
tions. I return below to further presentation of the neocortical volume. The model applies to individ-
Piagetian approach to the development of theory ual differences in social networking, as well.
of mind. Lewis, Rezaie, Browne, Roberts, and Dunbar
In the following, I review some of the evi- (2011) and Powell, Lewis, Roberts, García-Fiñana,
dence with older children and adults on theory of and Dunbar (2012) found that, in neuroimaging
Executive Function 421

research, the size of face-to-face social networks lem solving). It refers to our mental scratch pad.
correlates with prefrontal cortex size measures. Developmentally, Diamond (1985) found that
Kanai, Bahrami, Roylance, and Rees (2012) 10- to 12-month-olds could find an object at
reported similar results for Facebook friends. Path Place B even 5 s after having seen it hidden in
analysis suggested that size of medial prefrontal Place A (also see Bell & Cuevas, 2012).
cortical regions, which are associated with mental- Cognitive flexibility involves changing
izing belief states in others (theory of mind), medi- approach or perspective to a problem, and adjust-
ates the former results. The social brain effect ing contextually to new demands, rules, or priori-
appears influenced by evolution, genetics, and ties. An example is found in task-switching or
learning. shifting set. It includes creative thinking.
Developmentally, cognitive flexibility builds on
the other two core EFs and develops later than
Comment them (e.g., at 2 ½ to 3 years). All three EFs con-
tinue to develop over the lifespan.
The select research examined for children and EF is implicated both as an important source of
adults on social sensitivity indicates that individual long-term development and an important outcome
differences are important. Moreover, the behavior that is dependent on early infancy variables.
is so primary that the brain is referred to as a social Cuevas and Bell (2013) found that, in early infancy,
organ. Finally, specific areas of the brain might infants who were efficient information processors
mediate the activity. Executive function seems crit- at 5 months of age, as indexed by looking time,
ical, as per the following section, as well. exhibited higher EF skills from 2 to 4 years of age
(“short lookers” were compared to “long look-
ers”). Looking at 5 months was measured toward
Executive Function glove puppets adorned with facial features. EF was
measured using a composite score over multiple
Infants age-appropriate tasks, including a variant of the
game Simon Says. The authors concluded that,
Diamond (2013) reviewed the development of already at 5 months of age, individual differences
executive function (EF). It is considered top- in the maturation of the frontal cortex, its connec-
down, and its cognitive control processes develop tivity, or both could underlie the findings.
to control automatic instinctual or intuitive ones Rose, Feldman, and Jankowski (2012) showed
that are “ill-advised, insufficient, or impossible.” an association between infant (7, 12 months) and
EF use requires “effort.” Consensus has noted toddler (24, 36 months) EF (in attention, process-
three core EFs: inhibition, working memory, and ing speed, memory) and 11-year-old EF (in
cognitive flexibility. working memory, inhibition, shifting). Also, the
Inhibition involves the control of attention, results revealed a path from early speed and
behavior, emotions, thoughts, or any of their memory to later working memory, and another
combination in order to “override” either an from speed to shifting. Rose et al. (2012) reported
internal predisposition or an external enticement. another study showing an association in self-
It includes self-control (behavioral inhibition) restraint as early as 14 months and EFs as late as
and interference control (selective attention and 17 years (Friedman, Miyake, Robinson, &
cognitive inhibition). Self-control concerns Hewitt, 2011).
resisting temptations, controlling impulses, and
delaying, as required. Developmentally, Diamond
(1990, 1991) found that shielding a perceptual Children
“pull” helps even 6-month-olds inhibit an incor-
rect prepotent response. The three basic core EFs themselves help contrib-
Working memory involves holding informa- ute to the development of higher-order EF, which
tion in mind and using it mentally (e.g., in prob- concerns relational reasoning, logical reasoning,
422 17 Developing the Mind, Minding Development

or fluid intelligence. Diamond (2013) presented a Chevalier, Martis, Curran, and Munakata
model showing the relationship between the core (2015) found that 5-year-old compared to
EF and higher-level EF (see Fig. 17.1). The figure 10-year-old children engage in reactive com-
illustrates that the core EF of inhibitory control is pared to proactive (advance preparation) exec-
embedded in self-regulatory processes (response utive control because of deficits in metacognitive
inhibition, attention inhibition, and maintaining processes (metacognitive decisions when they
optimal arousal levels). engage it proactive control), rather than due to
Diamond (2012, 2013) concluded that EF fundamental constraints in cognitive capaci-
could be trained in children, e.g., by training in ties. When the experimenters made the task of
task switching (Karbach & Kray, 2009), through reactive control in response to events more dif-
martial arts (Lakes & Hoyt, 2004), and in school ficult (on three tasks involving task switching),
curricula (Raver et al., 2011). According to this type of control was not favored by the
Diamond, even infants can profit in EF training younger children, as was the case with the
(also see Kray & Ferdinand, 2013). older children.

EXECUTIVE FUNCTIONS

*Self-Regulation includes (a)


response inhibition, (b) attention
inhibition, but also in addition (c)
maintaining optimal levels of
emotional, motivational, and
cognitive arousal

Self-
Regulation*

Working Memory Maintaining your goal, or what Inhibitory Control


you should and shouldn’t do, in
Including mental math, re- working memory is critical for Interference Control Response
knowing what to inhibit Inhibition
ordering items, or relating one
idea or fact to another
Inhibition Inhibition Inhibition
of thoughts at the level at the level
and of attention of behavior
Verbal Visual- memories (Selective (Self-
Working Spatial Inhibiting environmental & (Cognitiv e or Focused Control &
Memory Working internal distractions is critical for Inhibition) Attention) Discipline)
Memory staying focused on the working
memory contents of interest

Effortful Control
refers to the innate
As Executive temperamental
Attention is usually predisposition to
assessed (using a exercise better or
flanker task), it is worse Self-Regulation
completely
Cognitive Flexibility synonymous with
inhibitory control of
Including being able to “think outside the box,” see something from attention
many different perspectives, quickly switch between tasks, or
flexibility switch course when needed

supports creativity and theory of mind

Higher-Level Executive Functions

Reasoning Problem -Solving Planning

Fluid Intelligence is completely synonymous with these

Fig. 17.1 Executive functions and related terms. The fig- with permission of Annual Reviews, from Diamond, A.
ure shows the three major executive functions: their attri- (2013). Executive functions. Annual Review of
butes, relations, and superordinate functions are shown. Psychology, 64, 135–168; © by Annual Reviews, http://
Adopted with permission of Annual Reviews. Republished www.annualreviews.org. [Figure 4, Page 152]
Executive Function 423

Lee, Bull, and Ho (2013) investigated core gies. Their study extended the similar work of
EFs in 6- to 15-year-olds, and found a shift to the Friedman et al. (2008) on adults.
predominant three-factor model from an earlier
two-factor one. This is consistent with Diamond’s
emphasis on only the core EFs of inhibition and Adults
working memory being present in infancy.
Richland and Burchinal (2013) found a relation- Gross and Jazaieri (2014) defined emotional reg-
ship between early elementary school EF and ulation in terms of activating a goal to influence
15-year-old verbal analogy performance. the emotion-generating process, either implicitly
The approach taken by Engelhardt, Briley, or explicitly. It can take place by regulating one’s
Mann, Harden, and Tucker-Drob (2015) for mid- own emotions (intrinsic, intrapersonal) or those
dle childhood is that there are four core executive of others (extrinsic, interpersonal). The process
functions, with the three core ones already men- model of emotion regulation involves five
tioned complemented by a fourth one of updat- sequentially cycled active families of processes:
ing, defined as monitoring of incoming stimuli situation selection, situation modification, atten-
leading to replacement of stored information tion, appraisal, and response (modulation; see
with information that is new. In their twin study, Fig. 17.2). Emotion regulation strategies can be
Engelhardt et al. (2015) found a common EF fac- adaptive or maladaptive. Gross (2015a, 2015b)
tor that can be extracted from the four core ones, further elaborated his model. In particular, he
and that it is 100 % heritable. In contrast, variance described that emotional regulation involves
related to the four EF domains could be explained cycles of valuations, including emotionally. Diaz
by both genetic and environmental influences. and Eisenberg (2015) added that, developmen-
They concluded that general EF could function as tally, parenting affects individual differences in
an early genetic marker for later psychopatholo- emotional regulation.

Step

S1 S Attention Cognitive Response


Selection Modification Deployment Change Modulation
re S for S to S

S
of focus Attention Appraisal Response

Feedback

1S = Stimulus, situation, stressor

Fig. 17.2 The process model of emotion regulation. The cular interactive component to depiction of the model
five steps in processing in emotional regulation moves between S presentation/selection and its modification.
from stimulus/situation/stressor selection/modification to Adapted from Gross and Thompson (2007)
attention/cognition and then response. Note. I added a cir-
424 17 Developing the Mind, Minding Development

Bickel, Quisenberry, Moody, and Wilson De Franchis, 2014; Diamond, 2013, respec-
(2014) considered addiction as the result of a tively). The authors used the two-factor model of
strong impulsive decision system due to deficits Bunge, Dudukovic, Thomason, Vaidya, and
in the executive control system. They referred to Gabrieli (2002) to structure a study with 24- to
their model as a dual model of self-control failure 32-month-olds and 36- to 48-month-olds.
(competing neurobehavioral decision system). Response inhibition was measured with tasks
The model applies transdiagnostically, e.g., also such as finger circle drawing (regular speed,
to risky sexual behavior. As well, for them, appro- slowly) and a central target (fish) pointing task
priate self-control involves choosing more adap- (with distractor stimuli present).
tive delayed rewards over immediate ones and the The results according to confirmatory factor
process becomes dysfunctional with faulty learn- analysis showed a single undifferentiated inhibi-
ing or short-term depletion (Baumeister, Vohs, & tion structure at the younger age and a two-factor
Tice, 2007). Immediate stimuli associated with structure in the older children. The latter appeared
short-term wants and needs are overvalued rela- to involve response inhibition (e.g., inhibition of
tive to those associated with longer-term rewards an impulsive/inappropriate dominant response,
(e.g., drug usage versus working for money). as per the circle task) and interference suppres-
Peña-Sarrionandia, Mikolajczak, and Gross sion (e.g., cognitive inhibition/suppression of
(2015) showed that Gross’s (2013) model of interfering/prepotent/irrelevant information/
emotional regulation informs work in emotional mental representation, as per the fish task). The
intelligence (EI). For example, those high in EI authors concluded that a sequential developmen-
regulate their emotions flexibly. tal model from a unifactor to a bifactor structure
in inhibitory control can help explain early EF
development.
Comment Blackwell and Munakata (2014) demonstrated
that cognitive control in the child develops from
EF is instrumental in developing self-control. a reactive form to a proactive one. Nevertheless,
Already in infancy, its components of inhibition context determines when the latter form is advan-
and working memory are developing. Its third tageous rather than disadvantageous (i.e., main-
primary aspect of cognitive flexibility develops taining task-relevant information in anticipation
later. Skills in EF predict better outcomes, and of needing it rather than merely retrieving task-
also skills related to it (e.g., with respect to infor- relevant information when it is needed).
mation processing) predict its better develop- Cuevas et al. (2014) demonstrated that mater-
ment. Self-control is at once cognitive and nal EF even more so than care giving quality in
emotional. When it goes awry, difficulties might some analyses was associated with early child EF
ensue, such as in addictions. In addition, I would (without minimizing the importance of early neg-
add that difficulties in having an adequate theory ative quality caregiving). Maternal EF provides
of mind of the other could be compromised by unique information about child EF relative to
EF deficits. negative quality caregiving. Maternal EF is
important for self-regulation and regulation of
the infant.
Inhibition Moriguchi (2014) related the development of
EF to social interaction; they work reciprocally in
Early development. In this regard, he referred to the
quality of social interaction involved as support-
Gandolfi, Viterbori, Traverso, and Usai (2014) ive/scaffolding vs. negative/controlling parent-
noted that, for the area of inhibition in EF, there ing. As well, he noted that EF development
are unitary, dual, and tripartite models (e.g., relates to the aspect of social development
Wiebe et al., 2011; Usai, Viterbori, Traverso, & concerned with moral development. He added a
Inhibition 425

biological dimension, relating performance on an Specifically, inhibition damps less advanced


EF task (switching dimensional categorization of solutions in various cognitive domains associated
cards from one dimension, e.g., color, to another, with earlier developing Piagetian stages or, to use
e.g., shape) to activation in the lateral prefrontal another language, associated with heuristic,
areas of the brain. System I thinking compared to more advanced
logical System II thinking (Houdé, 2015).
Joliot et al. (2009) had participants resolve a
Children Piagetian numerical conservation-type task
requiring inhibition of the stratagem of “length
Wiebe, Morton, Buss, and Spencer (2014) pre- equals number,” while gathering simultaneously
sented a developmental model of EF that is combined ERP (event-related potential) and
grounded in an activation/inhibition dynamic. MEG (magnetoencephalography) data. Among
The model incorporates a role for Hebbian or their complex results, inhibitory processes
neural cell assembly learning. Also, see appeared evident in the late components of the
Arsalidou, Pascual-Leone, Johnson, Morris, and electromagnetic brain activity (a right-side P-2
Taylor (2013) for a model of activation and deac- related frontal orbital activation, in particular).
tivation balancing in brain pattern activity under The authors concluded that a top-down executive
cognitive load. control for switching might be involved. Leroux
Castellano and Tannock (2002) had suggested et al. (2009) noted that the task used in this type
that inhibitory control could constitute an “endo- of research is spatial and consistent with a right-
phenotype” for attention deficit hyperactivity dis- hemisphere advantage, aside from its executive
order (ADHD), as per Barkley’s model (1997) of function demands.
inhibitory deficits underlying ADHD. Berger,
Alyagon, Hadaya, Atzaba-Poria, and Auerbach
(2013) investigated further the question by a Adults
stop-signal reaction time task in 5-year-old boys.
Parental characteristics predicted aspects of task Duque, Olivier, and Rushworth (2013) related
performance. Also, for a subset of the children, inhibitory control to the pre-supplementary
higher hyperactivity, in particular, was related to motor area (pre-SMA) in the medial prefrontal
less activity in left frontotemporal brain areas, cortex for tasks involving unwanted motor
which are associated with inhibition. responses in competition or conflict. This inhibi-
Howard, Johnson, and Pascual-Leone (2015) tory process facilitates appropriate response
differentiated inhibitory control into automatic selection. The study leading to these conclusions
and effortful types in the context of attention. In was conducted with adults using “virtual sur-
research with 7- to 12-year-olds, they found that gery” by repetitive transcranial magnetic stimu-
the 7-year-olds arrive at adult levels for automatic lation (TMS) over the pre-SMA, in particular.
inhibition, but even 12-year-olds had not yet The authors concluded that in their study a top-
attained these levels for effortful inhibition. down inhibitory control by TMS exerted effects
in action selection in the reaction time visuomo-
tor task used.
Piaget The importance of self-regulation (and of
metacognition) also are implicated in research on
Houdé and Borst (2014) related inhibitory con- learning and on personality (Bjork, Dunlosky, &
trol to cognitive development. In particular, Kornell, 2013; Denissen, van Aken, Penke, &
advances in cognitive development according to Wood, 2013, respectively). In both cases, inhibi-
Piagetian stages are correlated with inhibitory tory function seems integral to the models devel-
function in domain-general executive ability, and oped (metamemory framework and five regulatory
is associated with prefrontal cortical activity. mechanisms, respectively).
426 17 Developing the Mind, Minding Development

Comment been applied widely to both behavioral and brain


development.
Inhibitory control appears to develop from a
reactive, unifactorial process to a proactive,
bifactorial process, with better coordination with Major Developmental Models
activation. It is facilitated in development by Related to Mind
appropriate parenting (and parental EF, as well)
and it is associated with different brain regions, Biopsychosocial Model
especially frontally. Inhibition is related to
Piagetian development, and surely is involved in Model
the development of theory of mind and related Figure 17.3 presents an integrated biopsychoso-
acquisitions, as well. cial model that I have developed. The model is
The next section of the chapter shifts gears also evolutionary, developmental, ecological,
into general models of development that are relational, and includes system/network out-
applicable across diverse developmental topics. comes that are adaptive or maladaptive. The
For example, in the following, I describe the bio- model allows for understanding of both individu-
psychosocial model and its application to under- alizing and communalizing processes in mental
standing gender differences in development. disorder (i.e., ideographic and nomothetic,
Next, the model of embodiment in development respectively). It emphasizes that the person can
is rapidly expanding in its reach, and has applica- exert self-control in an active way (e.g., think
tions in multiple developmental areas, e.g., learn- having a belief in free will and its benefits,
ing/education. Finally, the systems model is a Baumeister, 2008), aside from the usual more
primary one found in this present work, and it has passive controls affecting the person (biology,

Context (Ecology, Environment)

Environmental Control (Passive)

Society

Culture Behavior
System/
RELATIONS

Family Network
OTHER(S)
Caregiver(s) Equilibrium/
Education/ Adaptation
School/ Peers/
Teachers Friends
OR

Disturbance/
Disorder
X (Symptoms)
(interacting
with)
Biology
Evolution Personal Factors
Brain Temperament
Neurophysiology Personality
Neuroendocrinology Cognition
SELF Intelligence
Genetics
Epigenetic Emotions
Epigenomics Social Behavior
Psychological Control Mental Health
(Passive) Self-Control (Active)

DEVELOPMENT

Fig. 17.3 Biopsychosocial/ecological model. The figure (personal change), context, and self-regulation models.
represents an integrated biopsychosocial and ecological Adapted from Sameroff (2010), modified
model of development, including the developmental
Major Developmental Models Related to Mind 427

Contextual

Others

Social

Psychological

Behavior
Relations

Biological System
Network
(e.g.,
Symptoms)
Self

Development

= network of interacting elements within levels

= networking interactions across levels

Fig. 17.4 Developmental, systemic (networking) biopsychosocial psychiatric model. This figure is a simplified inte-
grated biopsychosocial and ecological model of development, including the developmental (personal change), context,
and self-regulation models

environment). In this sense, the model is as much mental influences, including genetic and epigen-
as “biopersonalsocial” one as much as it is a bio- etic ones.
psychosocial one (Young, 2011). Figure 17.4
offers a simplified version of the integrated model Applied to Gender Differences
that illustrates the network component. That nature and nurture collaborate in develop-
Some of the factors in the model include the ment is a truism. However, Eagly and Wood
following. Epigenesis indicates the complexity in (2013) noted that, in the area of gender differ-
etiology in current biological study. Epigenesis ences and similarities, researchers rarely inte-
concerns gene silencing due to DNA methylation grate these two causal sources. For example, to
induced by the environment (e.g., adversity, Szyf, explain the sex difference favoring male children
2013). It indicates that genes and environment and adults in spatial ability (e.g., mental rotation
are not considered anymore as distinct entities of of three-dimensional objects), some workers
influence on phenotypes. Phenotypic expression emphasize biological causes and others sociocul-
is a product of multiple biological and environ- tural ones.
428 17 Developing the Mind, Minding Development

For the biological influence on spatial ability, ties (women: reproductive activities; men: size,
Courvoisier et al. (2013) related the observed sex strength). Social psychological processes help to
difference in spatial ability to hormonal cycles, create gender-role beliefs that help self-regulate
whereas Chou, Cheng, Chen, Lin, and Chu the division of labor, which is tailored to each
(2011) related the spatial skill sex difference to culture’s contemporary conditions.
brain structure differences. As for sociocultural Wood and Eagly (2013) continued that an
explanations of the spatial sex difference, Estes interactive biosocial construction model of
and Felker (2012) referred to self-confidence as a human sex differences allows for explanation of
differentiating factor and Moè (2012) referred to variation in sex differences across culture and
gender stereotyping and other external causes. historical epoch. Evolutionarily, humans adopted
Eagly and Wood (2013) adopted an interac- not to particular environmental features, but to
tionist position on the roles of nature and nurture their variation (Richerson & Boyd, 2005). In this
in sex-related differences, referring, in this view, human mind and cognition are not modular
regard, to a balance, as in the balance of Yin and but are “general purpose.” This view contrasts in
Yang. For them, the area of socialization, in gen- the extreme with the modular one of Shackelford
eral, would do well to adopt an interactionist and Liddle (2014).
perspective. Granted, sociocultural factors are
important in socialization (e.g., Leaper, 2013), Comment
but so are biological ones (e.g., Campbell, 2012). Note that Eagly and Wood (2013) are describing
Even for the topic of mate preferences, emerging a biopsychosocial model of sex differences/simi-
mating theories integrate hormonal and social larities as much as a biosociocultural one
influences (e.g., Wood & Eagly, 2013). (although they did not use directly the biopsycho-
In this vein, Eagly and Wood (2013) pro- social label). For example, they refer to agency,
ceeded to build an integrated nature–nurture per- assertiveness, and power emerging in women,
spective on sex differences in behavior. For which are psychological processes that bootstrap,
example, they noted that genetic influences catalyze, and build on biological and cultural-
depend on social environmental ones. In this contextual ones.
regard, Lickliter and Honeycutt (2003) argued The biopsychosocial model is an integrative
that genes participate in networks that are modu- one because, by definition, it covers a full range
lated by environmental influences in order to of influences on behavior. However, it lacks spe-
construct and maintain an adaptive brain. About cific change mechanisms, unlike the systems
female sexual maturation, James, Ellis, Schlomer, model that is presented later on in the chapter.
and Garber (2012) found that, for girls (and not
boys), lower family quality accelerated signs of
pubertal maturation. The intermediate mecha- Embodiment
nism in this developmental acceleration could
involve stress hormone release that acts on puber- Introduction
tal development (cortisol, epinephrine in the
hypothalamic-pituitary-adrenal (HPA) Embodiment represents a quickly evolving, unify-
axis → adrenal androgens → pubertal effects). ing construct in psychology that is especially rel-
For Eagly and Wood (2013), biology and envi- evant for development. In the following, I review
ronment interact in the development of sex the model, how the Piagetian approach is consis-
differences in a “biosocial constructionist” man- tent with it and informs it, and studies on develop-
ner. Biological sex differences are moderated by mental embodiment. The research in the infancy
the social environment even in cases of division period suggests that embodiment is crucial right
of labor of biologically-mediated labor in societ- from birth if not prenatally. The work on the mir-
ies. The activities constituting the division of ror neuron system supports a place for embodi-
labor reflect differential, evolved physical capaci- ment early in development. As for young children,
Embodiment 429

among others, the work on force dynamics and Marshall (2014) suggested a cross-theoretical
speech-gesture mismatches reveals the value of integration is needed to better understand devel-
the embodiment approach to development. opment. He emphasized the importance of the
points of view of embodiment, relational devel-
opmental systems, and dynamical systems the-
ory. In embodiment, the organism and
Embodiment and Relational environment are dynamically coupled. In rela-
Development tional developmental systems, conceptual oppo-
sites, in effect, are complementarities. In
Model Marshall (2013) discussed embodiment
dynamical systems theory, top-down and bottom-
in terms of relational developmental systems
up influences are reciprocally in tension. Marshall
(Overton, 2013). Embodiment includes brain–
(2014) concluded that a fruitful integrative
body–environment coupling (Kiverstein, 2012).
approach for psychology resides in the area of
Actions modify the environment, which affects
radical embodied cognitive science (Chemero,
actions, in turn. Brain function involves a feed-
2009). He maintained that developmental theory
back loop as it guides and coordinates action
should be person-centered. Also, Mascolo (2013)
(Clark, 2013). Embodiment enables enaction for
referred to the “extended” person-environment
making sense of the world (Thompson, 2007).
system. Intentionality continues to grow into
Living systems act to create the boundary condi-
adulthood, and the evidence indicates that the
tions for the creation and maintenance of their
embodied human mind exhibits a unified mind–
self-organization (Witherington, 2011).
body that is both enacted and sustained via neu-
Overton (2013) situated embodiment within a
romotor physiology. Similarly, Ho (2013)
relational developmental perspective, which is
referred to the “fluid genome” because there are
also a biopsychosocial one, and related it to cau-
no specific “intelligence genes.” Behavior is a
sality. Relationism constitutes a worldview
multifactorial causal product in which the pro-
superordinate to developmental relationism. It
cess of embodiment could be central.
decreases the separation of basics, such as brain
and mind, arguing for their nondecomposable,
Comment Embodiment, by definition, is an
indissociable, unified, inclusive complementar-
interactive model. It relates body, brain, person,
ity. In this approach, causality is a reciprocal,
development, and cultural context. Therefore, it
coactive, fused, bidirectional, interpretative, and
is a natural ally to other positions related to it,
circular process among co-equal constitutives.
such as the biopsychosocial model and systems
Behavioral systems are holistic, synthesized, and
theory. When the embodiment approach is con-
biological/personal/cultural.
sidered with these other models, developmental
This worldview allows for individual differ-
behavioral causality is not only biological/body-
ences and universals to co-exist in a biopsycho-
centric and linked to the physical, it is also active,
social network that is co-constructed and
predictive, proactive, and anticipatory, being
co-evolves toward increasing complexity. Living
fluid, extended, and all-inclusive dynamically of
systems are active and self-organizing, with nov-
the multiple and emerging co-acting personal and
elty emerging from their activity.
social influences upon it.
In this model, embodiment is manifested in the
interdigitating relations of biology, person, and
culture. We are active, contextualized agents
Piaget
mediating constitutively the world with our bod-
ies through which our brain and mind develop.
Model Witherington (2015) considered that
The body is a reflection of lived, actively-engaged
embodiment is consistent Piaget’s concept of
experience. It references our biology, psychology,
constructivism. In this regard, Needham and
and culture in a bridged, joined, unified whole.
Libertus (2011) maintained that Piaget’s cognitive
430 17 Developing the Mind, Minding Development

developmental model provides one framework developmental cascade within a systems frame-
supporting the concept. In the model, infants are work as providing a good explanatory model.
seen to construct understanding of the world via Another one would be embodied cognition.
their own actions upon it and engagement with it.
Using the sticky mittens paradigm, Needham Comment The research on self-produced
and colleagues demonstrated that young infants actions and their effects in infancy are consistent
develop an increased interest in objects through not only with the embodiment model but also
the experience of reaching for them (e.g., with that of Piaget’s. Experience is partly self-
increased looking at, mouthing them), as well as generated and this component of it is essential for
an earlier ability to interpret another person’s understanding cognition, as Piaget (1953, 1954)
reaches as goal-directed (e.g., Needham, Barrett, had maintained.
& Peterman, 2002; Sommerville, Woodward, & The Piagetian model includes the sensorimo-
Needham, 2005). tor period as the first stage and, by definition, this
Gerson and Woodward (2014) studied stage is an embodied one. The ones after it are
3-month-old infants in situations of self-produced representational, but analyses of child and adult
and observational action experience and the dif- cognition, and not only infant cognition, reveal
ferential effects of the experiences on action the pertinence of sensorimotor experience in cog-
understanding. The authors used the sticky mit- nition. This might imply that the Piagetian pro-
ten paradigm in the training of the infants, and gram does not apply to embodied cognition after
concluded that, even at this age, active, agentic infancy. However, Piaget had maintained that
experience helps recognize the goals of other each new stage in his model builds on prior
agents. By acting on the world, or self-producing stages. Moreover, in Young (2011), I had argued
actions (Piaget, 1953), young infants change, that prior stages might still be active as new ones
among others, their knowledge, goals, social per- function, and even complement them in cognitive
ceptions, behavior, and development. activity. That is, in my Neo-Piagetian under-
Wellsby and Pexman (2014) noted that early standing of cognition, sensorimotor intelligence
development is especially about embedded cogni- is continually available to us, although trans-
tion, as per Piaget (1952). Further, sensorimotor formed by its interactions with higher-order
experience continues to influence development intelligences. In this regard, I developed the con-
throughout the lifespan, albeit in a more refined or cept of yoking of earlier developed stages to later
flexible way (Antonucci & Alt, 2011). Sensorimotor ones in cognitive activity, as the context requires,
experiences continually influence and shape learn- including even of the infant sensorimotor one in
ing, perception, action, language, and conceptual adults who engage in more advanced thought and
representation (e.g., Thelen, 2008). activities, such as problem-solving. In this sense,
Bornstein, Hahn, and Suwalsky (2013) illus- the Piagetian project is exquisitely an embodied
trated the importance of early embodied cogni- one throughout all phases of the lifespan.
tion to later cognition in their study. They Moreover, the work showing a role in behav-
measured 5-month motor-exploratory compe- ior of early mirror neuron activity is consistent
tence (motor maturity, active exploration, in par- with both the Piagetian and embodied view, and
ticular) and found that it related longitudinally to these neurons, too, are available throughout the
14-year academic achievement. Specifically, the lifespan. They provide one biological register of
more motorically mature infants were at 5 months the embodiment process and constitute one
of age and the more active exploration takes ground for the changing cognitive activity
place, the higher was their academic levels at 14 throughout the lifespan.
years of age. The authors considered the findings That being said, an integration of the embod-
consistent with Piaget’s (1970/1988) emphasis ied and Piagetian view would show how passage
that infant motor actions/exploration are “foun- through the sensorimotor substages that he
dational” in development. They described a describes in infancy modify and add to the
Embodiment 431

embodiment driver in behavioral causality. The he referred to this age as involving secondary
Piagetian model might provide an axis to show circular reactions, so that the accidentally-
how qualitative transitions in cognition in infancy discovered interesting behavior revolves around
lead to qualitative changes in embodied cogni- objects more so than the body, which evidently
tion. In the following, I examine the behavior of still is involved.
reaching as it passes through the sensorimotor
substages in infancy that Piaget described. He Eight Months At this age, Piaget referred to the
described that a new sensorimotor substage coordination of secondary schemas, for example,
appeared every few months on average, so that in in reaching to get around a detour in order to get
the first few years of life, the infant manifests six a hidden object that had been interesting before
of them. Examination of reaching in infancy being hidden. In this step, embodiment is begin-
affords both a good introduction to Piaget and ning to serve cognition as much as the inverse.
also reveals how he respected the embodiment The behavior is still body-centered and senso-
process and how the cognitive changes in the sen- rimotor, but the cognition provides an image to
sorimotor period alter that process—embodiment guide the behavior from its start. That being said,
and cognitive development are mutually interac- the cognition is not yet representational; as well,
tive in this model, as they should be. the guiding image is rudimentary and can be a
poor one when there are constraints on the behav-
ior, such as shifting the object involved in sight to
Reaching for the Mind a second screen. There is still room for active
reaching in the form of groping around and
Neonate In this regard, at first, in the neonatal exploration in an effort to find these secondarily
period, and consistent with Piaget referring to displaced objects, but errors abound.
this age period of one involving reflex exercise, it
is ballistic when triggered by a target, so that, as Twelve Months For Piaget, the 1-year-old
a body-focused activity, it derives mostly from begins a process of differentiating already learned
the body, and with only a prompt from the means–end combinations, but by accidental
environment. exploration rather than by a preconceived purely
mental plan. In this regard, they engage in the
One Month Next, in the 1-month-old, reaching behavior, that as parents we know all to well, of
is better coordinated with the object, and success- trying out new behaviors in different ways; for
ful reaches obtain, even with coordinated hand example, reaching might be used to knock over a
opening and grasping involved. Piaget referred to bowl and the infant gets to see our reactions,
primary circular reactions at this age, so that the instead of the infant engaging in reaching for the
coordinations in the behavior improve, but the spoon in the bowl and eating. In this sense, the
objects are apparently discovered accidentally as reaching is even further removed from the origi-
interesting, or without intention preceding the nal body source and even the simple object that it
action. Moreover, the repetitions involved in the usually seeks. Rather, it becomes intertwined in
behavior are body-focused more than object- cognition to the point that it allows for new cog-
focused. In this regard, at one month of age, nitions after the result of its behavior becomes
infants might be engaging more in spatial explo- known. Reaching becomes not only a means to a
ration around them as they flail and only when new end but also a means to a new cognition.
ready do they engage in object-directed reaching
(Young, 2011). Eighteen Months Piaget referred to the toddler
as developing the possibility of mental combina-
Four Months Next, for Piaget, the infant tions to discover new means–end relationships,
engages in visually-directed reaching, so that the but he still linked the behavior involved to associ-
object becomes primary in the activity. Moreover, ated action-based sensorimotor activity. For
432 17 Developing the Mind, Minding Development

example, the toddler might covertly or even is activated selectively by actions within our reper-
overtly open the mouth before reaching to a toire and also it is modifiable by experience
drawer to open it in order to remove something (Buccino et al., 2004; Tai, Scherfler, Brooks,
from it. Only at 2 years of age, after the senso- Sawamoto, & Castiello, 2004).
rimotor period of infancy, can behavior be guided
in full by representations without sensorimotor
Evidence Saby, Meltzoff, and Marshall (2013)
concomitants. In terms of the relationships
found that 14-month-olds exhibit somatotopic
among reaching, cognition, and embodiment,
neural responses to viewing human actions. The
this example shows that cognition has taken the
results speak to the early origins of embodied
upper hand in the relationships and guides the
cognition and its shared nature. Adults have been
behavior from the start mentally, although still
shown to demonstrate “neural somatotopy,” in
with an embodied component. Reaching is sub-
which viewing another person that is using a spe-
sumed to wider goals, and it leads to predicted
cific body part, such as a hand or foot, is associ-
cognitive outcomes after internal planning rather
ated with the corresponding activation in the
than ones that are discovered post-behavior, as
viewer’s brain of the matched brain area of the
found in the prior substage. The representation at
sensory strip, motor strip, or both.
this step is not quite divorced from action and the
body, but is working toward that step. To verify whether infants exhibit the phenom-
That being said, contemporary research enon, Saby, Meltzoff, and Marshall (2013) had
shows that representation never becomes 14-month-olds watch an adult reach toward/
divorced in full from the body, and indeed that touch an object (musical, spinning, colorful)
the two are co-constitutive. To repeat, this con- using either the hand or foot (condition randomly
jecture is consistent with my model that, as assigned) in 2 s trials, with inter-trial intervals of
adults, we yoke sensorimotor behavior to our 5.5 s. The investigators recorded electroencepha-
more advanced thought processes, as needed. logram (EEG) scalp signals; event-related
This is not to say that we reach for bowls and changes were analyzed in the EEG’s sensorimo-
examine others for consequences that we could tor mu rhythm. The results showed more mu
not foresee, or, perhaps on the other hand, we do rhythm desynchronization over sensorimotor
in our moments of comedy, in ways that might cortex hand areas during hand action observation
be real or imagined. (vs. foot areas), and the reverse for foot action
observation.
Saby et al. (2013) concluded that the simple
Mirror Neurons act of watching someone’s use of actions with a
particular body part activates the infant observ-
Model About the mirror neurons that seem er’s corresponding sensorimotor cortical areas.
involved in early embodied cognition, Needham According to the authors, this developing somato-
and Libertus (2011) noted that they are localized in topic organization through intercorporal or self-
the premotor cortex and parietal lobe in macaque other mapping, “supports” observational and
monkeys (di Pellegrino, Fadiga, Fogassi, Gallese, rapid cultural learning in infancy.
& Rizzolatti, 1992; Gallese, Fadiga, Fogassi, & The mu suppression response in EEG activity
Rizzolatti, 2002), and that they have been found in has been related to infants’ observations of real
humans (Iacoboni, 2008; Rizzolatti & Craighero, and mimicked goal-directed actions. Mu sup-
2004), including developmentally (Lepage & pression is a measure of the action observation/
Theoret, 2007; Nystrom, 2008; Shimada & Hiraki, action execution matching system, commonly
2006). As we observe actions, the mirror system referred to as the mirror system. Warreyn et al.
matches the observation with the motor system, (2013) observed 18- to 30-month-olds during the
providing a “sense” of action (Gallese, Rochat, aforementioned actions while recording EEG
Cossu, & Sinigaglia, 2009; Shapiro, 2009). Also, it power data from frontal, central, and parietal
Embodiment by Age Period 433

sites. The central sites provided the strongest evi- According to Delafield-Butt and
dence of mirror system activity. Also, mu sup- Gangopadhyay (2013), at 10- to 14-weeks gesta-
pression correlated with imitation quality. tion, actions express goal direction toward the
body (Piontelli, 2010) and, at 14 weeks, motor
Comment Mirror neurons form a mirror neuron planning is evident (Castiello et al., 2010).
system that includes an integrated circuitry Prospective control is evident as fetuses reach to
involving motor, cognitive, social, and related touch a twin (Piontelli, 2010).
networks. They constitute a quintessential
embodying mechanism. However, the biology of
embodiment does not reside in this unique neural Neonatal
system. Surely, individual differences will be
found related to genes, brain regions and their As development proceeds, other findings suggest
connectivity, and other aspects of the central and that there is continuity in early and later enaction.
sympathetic nervous systems. For example, neonates will engage in arm move-
ments in order to achieve specific sensory effects
(e.g., van der Meer & van der Weel, 2011).
Embodiment by Age Period Schilbach et al. (2013) claimed that social
engagement is facilitated by the “mentalizing”
In the following, I review points of view on network (Firth & Firth, 2008) and also by the
embodiment that are specific to developmental “mirror” neuron system (Rizzolatti & Sinigaglia,
periods. Embodiment has been related to the pre- 2010). The nonlinear dynamics characterizing
natal period right through to the adult one. the relational interactions, at times, even “consti-
tute our awareness” of the minds of others.
Developmentally, the system involved might
Prenatal even be present neonatally.
Lewis and Stack (2013) took issue with
The research that has been undertaken in the pre- Schilbach et al.’s (2013) nativist approach to
natal and neonatal periods indicates the impor- embodied cognition and presented a relation,
tance of early embodied experience in action-based account. They conducted work in
development. The results relate especially to which they proposed that, after direct social
motor planning and behavior but also to visual interaction, the social representation that is devel-
and visuomotor coordination. oped persists at the “bifurcation point” of reduced
Delafield-Butt and Gangopadhyay (2013) social activity.
reviewed research indicating the validity of sen- Wilkinson, Paikan, Gredebäck, Rea, and Metta
sorimotor intentionality, or goal-directedness, (2014) proposed an embodied model of neonatal
even prenatally. At this age, intentionality is pri- facial preference. Rather than considering it innate
mary, prereflective, and preconceptual. and reflective of monocular stimulus properties,
Movements are guided, even prenatally, by they suggested it derived from system level, bin-
prospection, or anticipation of future events. ocular-driven integration, or embodiment.
Cognition reflects an embodied agent in action
even in this developmental phase; that is, there is
a “proximal” prospectivity that anticipates the First 6 Months
later development of a more complex, serial, dis-
tal (goal)-oriented one. The authors concluded Introduction The research on embodiment
that the origin of sensorimotor intentionality, early in life underscores the intimate link
even prenatally, in prospective agent action indi- between sensorimotor experience, brain, mirror
cates the origins of intentionality “driving” devel- neurons, and behavior. The work refers to
opment and learning. embodiment processes as drivers of behavior,
434 17 Developing the Mind, Minding Development

and it involved in anticipation, intention, and de Klerk et al. (2015) studied the stepping
contextually-appropriate execution of behavior. movements of pre-walking 7- to 9-month-olds.
Glenberg (2010) made the broad claim that The infants were placed on a treadmill while they
body-based processes influence all psychologi- either contingently observed their own real-time
cal processes, including those involving body leg movements or, for a control group, those of
morphology, sensory systems, motor systems, another infant. Another control group received
and emotions. For example, already in infants, visual experience only with stepping actions.
physical development and associated changes in Sensorimotor alpha suppression originates in the
action function to “drive” cognitive and social primary somatosensory cortex and, as measured
development. Mirror neurons are involved in the by EEG, it is an index of sensorimotor cortex
latter (Gallese & Lakoff, 2005). Moore and activation (having downstream modulation of the
Paulus (2013) emphasized the role of joint sensorimotor cortex by mirror neuron regions in
attention and joint goal-directed action in devel- the parietal and frontal cortices).
oping understanding of self and other as inten- The results showed that, for the contingency
tional agents. group participants (during the training period),
sensorimotor alpha suppression (cortical activa-
Evidence Research has shown the intercoordi- tion) at post-test was related to (as predicted by)
nated nature of reaching by the arm with other a stronger contingency between visual-motor
bodily systems, as well as cognition. In this regard, observed and performed stepping experiences.
at 4 ½ to 5 months of age, hand orientation coordi- The authors concluded that, although other
nates with reaching to accommodate to different aspects of their results were not significant, the
objects (Wentworth, Benson, & Haith, 2000). mechanism of perceptual-motor coupling in the
The embodied intersubjectivity in caregiver– infant brain is generation by experience of a cor-
infant interactions includes word learning. Seidl, related visuomotor nature.
Tincoff, Baker, and Cristia (2015) found that A study by Corbetta, Friedman, and Bell
experimenter touch facilitated word-finding in (2014) demonstrated the embodied sensorimotor
4-month-olds during continuous speech. They nature of infant cognition. They found that
proposed that direct caregiver–infant interac- 12-month-old infants align their look to where
tions are essential in “body part” word lexical they reach to search, at least for certain objects,
acquisition (and also that acoustic emphasis rather than vice versa. They learn to map visual
helps in learning object words). They found that attention onto bodily-focused experience, in
the touch cues facilitated specification of word which they first spatially direct their movement
boundaries related to body part words in the using self-produced proprioceptive and haptic
4-month-olds. feedback, in a process of visuo-motor mapping.
This leads to visual-elicited, prospective control
of movement. The learning involved is not a top-
6–12 Months down but a bottom-up process that involves coor-
dinating reaching, proprioception, intrinsic arm
Perception de Klerk, Johnson, Heyes, and movement dynamics, and the goal of the reach-
Southgate (2015) found that the development of ing in space. To conclude, the authors noted that
perceptual-motor couplings in the brain in intentions and arm movement mapping develops
infancy is related to associative learning rather through sensorimotor experiences, in a “deeply
than an intrinsic connection between perception embodied” process.
and action. Instead of experience merely shaping
or refining existing perceptual-motor couplings Cognition Rivière (2014) elaborated that, in
from birth (e.g., Marshall, Young, & Meltzoff, embodied cognition, mind is embedded in the
2011), it plays a critical role in their generation body through bodily interaction of the organism
through correlated sensorimotor experience (e.g., with the environment. This can take place without
Cook, Bird, Catmur, Press, & Heyes, 2014).
Embodiment by Age Period 435

the requirement for modeling of the environment Comment In the second 6 months of life,
and other advanced cognitive processes, such as embodiment has been shown to involve percep-
planning and decision-making but, instead, can- tual, cognitive, and social consequences.
not be achieved without participatory engagement Embodiment in infancy extends beyond the
of the perceptual-motor system in action. The motor and visual of early life into relations with
adaptive task is not to represent the environment language development, as well, and even long-
but to continuously engage the body with it in term academic development. The results empha-
order to achieve adaptive, coordinated behavior size not only the theoretical significance of early
patterns. embodiment for development but also its long-
For Rivière (2014), this enactive model of cog- term practical effects. Embodiment seems the
nition applies quite readily to development. For participatory medium in which development
example, Piaget described the A-not-B error that takes place.
takes place in the latter half of the first year. As the
infant attempts to solve more complex object per-
manence tasks, she or he can perseverate in seek- Year 2
ing hidden objects under a first location (A,
already successfully understood as the hiding spot Social Yu and Smith (2013) demonstrated that
of the object in question), after it is transferred to parents and infants coordinate object visual atten-
(B), at least when there is a delay of a few seconds tion using eye–hand coordination, but without
before the search for the transferred object (from the traditional pathway of gaze following. They
A to B) is permitted to take place. studied the moment-to-moment tracking of eye
Standard explanations of the A not B error gaze in parents and in 13-month-olds as they
invoke inhibitory limitations, insufficient working played with toys.
memory, and motor memory (the effect of prior The results revealed coordinated joint switches
reaches). Rivière (2014) proposed that automatic in visual attention, including looking simultane-
hand movements that are triggered by sensory ously at the held toys. This goal-directed action
signals are involved. The infants develop strong, did not involve gaze following. Instead, over the
entrenched motor habits/routines that impede per- pairs, an eye–hand coupling pathway appeared
formance rather than their failing due to represen- predominant. Neither social partner dominated
tational constraints. The process of retrieving the joint attention. Hand actions of one or the
sensorimotor information mediates subsequent other had direct effects on the other’s looking,
action. Rivière’s model is consistent with that of leading to rapid online coordination in visual
Cisek (2012), in which decisions emerge as a attention.
multilevel, distributed consensus of various repre- Yu and Smith (2013) concluded that finding
sentations, some of which might be involved in attention and sensitivity to hand actions in 1-year-
sensorimotor control and others of which might olds is consistent with other research. Studies
relate to more abstract portions of behavior. have shown that infants at this age have the abil-
ity to interpret the “causal” implications of ges-
Social de Barbaro, Johnson, and Deák (2013) tures and movements (Olofson & Baldwin,
studied the development of “triadic” (child, 2011).
mother, object) attention or play at 12 months of Adamson, Bakeman, Deckner, and Nelson
age, and its relationship to earlier mother–infant (2014) showed the importance of joint engage-
coordination. They found that, for the five infants ment in early childhood. They studied social
studied longitudinally, changes in dyadic activity, interaction in infancy, and the longitudinal results
as well as internal cognitive shifts, appeared showed a relation to preschool conversational
reciprocally related to each other and built over symbol-infused joint engagement (e.g., verbally
sessions, in an approach that they considered expressed/mediated), and also with caregiver
reflective of embodied cognition. support.
436 17 Developing the Mind, Minding Development

Language Levy and McNeill (2013) argued can focus on two causal dimensions simultane-
that, already in the 1½-year-old, in narrative ously suggests that Piaget’s (1955) concept of
development, gestures help create simple refer- egocentrism, or the one-dimensional focusing
ential functional constructions. In their study, found in preschoolers, does not apply to this type
imagistic gestures embodied discourse themes of task. Children’s representations of causality at
that had recurred, cementing narrative cohesion, this age suggest the steps toward development of
or inter-utterance linkage (Halliday & Hasan, understanding complex causal events.
1976). The authors concluded that speech is In addition, I note that the findings by Göksun
inseparable from the imagery embodied in ges- et al. (2013) are consistent with the point of view
tures at this age, which constitutes the beginning of embodied cognition. The causes understood
of the shift to intralinguistic cohesion. early in life reflect the forces impacting children
and the ones that they can affect themselves.
Comment Research in 1-year-olds related to
embodiment emphasizes behavioral effects on Language/Gesture For children, physical manip-
brain activity. Visual activities alone reflect ulation of toys that were represented in stories
embodied processes and they are active in social improved children’s comprehension of the stories.
embodiment, as well. There are language and The same occurred with imagined manipulation
social factors to consider, as well. (Glenberg, Goldberg, & Zhu, 2011; Glenberg,
Gutierrez, Levin, Japuntich, & Kaschak, 2004).
Berk (2013) reviewed an aspect of cognitive
Children development related to embodiment. Speech-
gesture mismatches occur when gestures reveal
Causality Göksun, George, Hirsh-Pasek, and more than verbal statements as children try to solve
Golinkoff (2013) examined whether preschoolers problems. Goldin-Meadow (2003, 2006) showed
could understand not just simple but also inter- that children who received instruction following a
acting dual forces as they impact the movement speech-gesture mismatch were more likely than
of objects. In an ingenious methodology, a foam others to learn match problems. This assumes that
ball exiting a slanted tube (cause) could be either children who produce speech-gesture mismatches
facilitated or impeded in its motion by the “wind” are in a transitional state. Children in this state
of a hairdryer (enabled, prevented, respectively). seem to have strategies that are accessible to ges-
After practice trials, in the test phase of the ture but not to verbal acts (Goldin-Meadow, 2002),
“board” game that had been set up, the children facilitating awareness of conflicting ideas. Parents
had to predict the end point of the ball. and teachers can help children use gestures. Adults
The experiment was based on “force dynamics” who gesture while teaching help children to use
theory (Wolff, 2007), which has been applied to lan- their hands as they learn, which leads to improved
guage, in particular. The findings revealed that pre- performance (Goldin-Meadow, Cook, & Mitchell,
school children mostly understood the force 2009). Goldin-Meadow (2005) noted that adults
interactions behind each type of causal situation; would teach more problem-solving strategies to
and this could happen even at a developmental children who expressed mismatches compared to
period that preceded acquisition of the capacity for children who did not (Goldin-Meadow & Singer,
verbal representations of the forces/causes. Also, in 2003). The mechanism imputed to explain how
their judgments of ball direction and end point in working with speech-gesture mismatches in transi-
the board game, the older preschool children under- tion states involves the facilitation of representa-
stood better the integration of two forces. tion of thoughts not yet amenable to verbal
Therefore, young children seem to understand representation, which helps in executive (working
causal events that are more complex than memory) function (Ping & Goldin-Meadow,
Michottian collisions. They realize that causal 2010). Similarly, Mumford and Kita (2014) found
agents can coordinate. That children at this age an embodied cognitive effect in 3-year-olds. Iconic
System Theory 437

gestures helped map novel verbs to specific otor experience. The context that permits the
referents. pluralist model (it involves five levels of situa-
Cook, Duffy, and Fenn (2013) conducted a tional embeddedness, with abstract concepts the
study with second- to fourth-graders that illus- fifth), concerns narrative, which becomes a chief
trates that embodiment facilitates consolidation site of embodied language.
and transfer of learning. In mathematical training Pulvermuller and Garagnani (2014) suggested
that involved equations having two sides, it that long-term memories are more embodied than
helped to sweep the left hand back and forth elements residing in working memory. Zwaan
under the left half of the equation and the right (2014) suggested that the degree of embodiment
hand under the right half. The gestural activity in language comprehension depends on the
helped in this task because they might lead to degree of environmental embeddedness involved.
simulation of motor action, activation of relevant
motor regions, facilitation of a “more procedural- Comment No matter the age, embodiment pro-
ized” representation, and creation of a more cesses not only appear to complement acquisi-
“enduring” memory. tions related to perception, cognition, reasoning,
The embodied account of development has problem solving, language, and sociality, but also
been extended into moral reasoning. Beaudoin- they facilitate, promote, and even allow for them,
Ryan and Goldin-Meadow (2014) showed that creating an integrated field of body, action, feed-
requiring gestures (encouraging to gesture) in back, brain, mind, person, and environment.
fifth-graders during moral reasoning tasks led to Embodiment processes are not merely tangential
more sophisticated problem-solving strategies to behavior, but are behavior.
(more multiple perspectives) and also to profiting This section of the chapter on the embodiment
from a lesson in more reasoning. The authors model has considered not only the model but also
concluded that gestures allow (child) learners to evidence for it over the lifespan. The next section
spatialize non-spatial ideas, affording the use of of the chapter considers the systems theory model
spatial learning mechanisms. I note that the tech- of behavior. This next section completes exami-
nique might help better integrate interhemi- nation of three major models that have been pre-
spheric communication and bihemispheric use in sented in the book for their developmental roots.
the problem-solving involved.

Comment Embodied processes in the child System Theory


reflect not only language and cognitive develop-
ment but also causal understanding. The force General Model
dynamics of actions and in the world appear
related to the core of developmental processes Recent Griffiths and Tabery (2013) explained
and products. that a systems view of development includes
For the next section on embodiment in adults, hierarchical levels. Therefore, superordinate ones
I refer to just a few studies. A full review of this can exert top-down influence or causation
research is beyond the scope of the present work. through inter-level relations and their action on
Moreover, the general model has been presented inter-level ones (Craver & Bechtel, 2007). The
in Chap. 5. larger causal mechanisms produce changes in its
parts. Bechtel and Abrahamsen (2010) also noted
that dynamic explanations at the mechanistic
Adults level involve decomposition and re-composition.
Greenberg, Callina, and Mueller (2013) similarly
Language Zwaan (2014) presented a model of underscored the importance in development of
language comprehension that integrates both dynamical systems concepts, including self-
abstract symbols and grounding involving per- organization and emergence in an integrated
ception and action. The latter includes sensorim- biopsychosocial model.
438 17 Developing the Mind, Minding Development

Richardson (2013) elaborated that, in dynami- Richardson (2013) concluded that experience
cal systems, states hover in the region of with cultural tools or procedures can change
far-from-equilibrium, criticality, or the edge of brain networks (e.g., May, 2011). Finally, “epi-
chaos. This transition region permits the states to cognitive regulations” among individuals can
engage in maximum information exchange, novel serve to “greatly expand” the collective intelli-
adaptiveness, and readiness to shift basins of gence or “cognomen.”
attraction (attractors). This permits harmonious, I would add that culture can be described as a
coordinated, system-wide response to perturba- collective attractor landscape replete with multi-
tion across multiple nonlinear relations. In this ple, coordinated levels across groups and indi-
regard, systems evidence global reorganization viduals that render it highly adaptive and ever
akin to a ballet, symphony, or orchestra, yet with changing, and also novelty seeking, in order to
no conductor present, for example, as found in better promote and increase its “intelligence
bacteria (e.g., Buescher et al., 2012). Even slime complexity” and power of its activity. In this
moulds are being described as having “learning regard, in Young (2011), I referred to adult intel-
and memory,” and also unicellular prokaryotes as ligence as a collective intelligence (both for the
having knowledge, intelligence, “thinking,” and individual as the person creates superordinate
cognitive resources (e.g., del Moral, González, abstract structures and for the group intelligence
Navarro, & Marijuán, 2011). that individuals create, e.g., in brainstorming).
As for our senses, they are active, having a Witherington and Heying (2013) considered
structure-search and abstraction function. Signals the holistic, inter-level coordinative nature of
are transformed early in transmission into pat- systems, advocating for causal explanations that
terns or neural connections and correlates rather include both parts-to-whole and whole-to-parts
than remaining independent and static. The rela- aspects. The organizational whole can exert a
tional patterns that are abstracted serve to func- top-down influence not because it acts on lower
tion as attractor basins in nested hierarchies of levels but because it is a unitary structure of
attractor landscapes. The resulting networks are which its constituent elements are constitutively
optimized to detect and interpret novel data, influenced by it, so that it is both subject and
yet allow for multiple “expressions” for feeding object. The whole gives meaningful context to
forward. The brain then can elaborate actions that bottom-up, real-time, local dynamics of the parts.
are more adaptive because the seemingly disor- Huys, Perdikis, and Jirsa (2014) presented a
dered world that has been forwarded to it is more dynamical model of sensorimotor behavior. They
predictable. Nevertheless, the brain at this level is contrasted their approach with each of the com-
flexible or experience-responsive, creating a putational, equilibrium point, free energy/active
“dynamical brain” that operates robustly influence, and ecological models. The latter two
(Tschacher & Haken, 2007).For Richardson views, in particular, are consistent with, or infor-
(2013), cognitive function expresses an emergent mative of, the dynamic approach (e.g., Adams,
activity. It can generate more complex, powerful Shipp, & Friston, 2013; Friston, 2011; Gibson,
intelligence from its own activity. He draws a 1966; Warren, 2006, respectively).
comparison with this concept to Piaget’s The dynamical approach is founded on the
(1970/1988) concept of “reflective abstraction.” concept of self-organized pattern formation (e.g.,
Either way, the organism can “transcend immedi- Haken, 1983) and dynamical systems theory
ate experience,” which I take to mean that the (e.g., Perko, 2006). It describes functional archi-
organism is not simply passively buffeted by the tecture in sequential movements as structured
environment. flows on manifolds. Functional modes emerge
Richardson (2013) continued that individuals and bind one after the other. Each of them corre-
coordinate in ways analogous to neurons. They sponds to an invariant structure in phase space
form “epicognitive” patterns that are emergent topology that can be accommodated to task
from their joint activity. At a further superordi- constraints in the quantitative aspects of the flow
nate level, culture is created. involved.
System Theory 439

Other Spencer, Perone, and Buss (2011) con- Fogel (2011) continued with the theme of
sidered the systems view as a meta-approach. moment and long-term time frames. He con-
Self-organization is essential to this perspective. tended that change can be found in the stability of
Developmental structure and organization come real-time, microscopic behavior, and also that
“for free,” without a master controller. Nonlinear this type of developmental change seeds macro-
and time-dependent interactions over the multi- scopic ones. System constituents impose self-
ple levels of high-dimensional systems take regulatory constraints on patterns (e.g.,
place. Systems intrinsically create patterns, attractors). In developmental systems, time scales
including qualitatively different emergent ones are embedded. For example, an infant’s smile or
(e.g., new attractors) in freely-combined ongoing reach is soft-assembled each time according to
soft assemblies. Each second, body and brain context and history (e.g., Fogel & Garvey, 2007).
engage in continual dialogue, even in cognition As development proceeds and new regimes self-
(Spencer, Perone, & Johnson, 2009). For Spencer organize, historical and emerging frames might
et al. (2011), the concept of soft assembly renders co-exist by way of “bridging” frames that allow
it difficult to define (sub)system components, as them to experience less stress or trauma in abrupt
well as to discern the “cause” of behavior. For the shifting.
latter, different behavioral outcomes occur van Geert (2011) described a property of
because of variations in context and one’s history. dynamic systems that speaks to the approach’s
They concluded that the systems approach needs applicability to development. He wrote that
to integrate development from the ongoing dynamic systems are complex, by displaying a
moment to moment time scale to the long-term combination of orderliness and randomness.
one (see Fig. 17.5; Smith & Thelen, 2003). Intriguingly, he noted that the microscopic random

Fig. 17.5 Dynamic systems


theory levels needing Distal
integration. Dynamic systems
theory needs to formally
integrate the different Immediate
reciprocally interacting levels
in the biopsychosocial
approach. Adapted from Behavior (action)
Spencer et al. (2011)

Brain

Genes

Neural

Cognition, affect

Environment

Environment
440 17 Developing the Mind, Minding Development

erratic behavior of the components of a system and cannot be decomposed into part–part rela-
directly relates to and maintains its macroscopic tions. The local and the global move together,
orderliness. At the latter level, each state is deter- with neither privileged. Contextualist approaches
mined by its history of prior states but, neverthe- emphasize local processes; but organismic-
less, any state can evolve along different pathways, contextualist ones do not. The whole system
even emergent and novel ones, depending on its organization is what “imparts meaning” to lower-
evolution rule or “term.” order components and their relationships as much
Lewis (2011) discussed developmental trajec- as the lower-order levels are “generative” of
tories in terms of alternations between turbulent upper levels. The upper levels help create the
phase transitions and normative stages, as in cog- “boundary conditions” enabling their self-
nitive development. He noted that Neo-Piagetians organizational stability, and their ability to head
began including dynamicist notions in their cog- off “dissipative” processes. When systems regu-
nitive developmental models (Case et al., 1996; late energy and matter flow this way, they
Fischer & Bidell, 2006). “embody” circular causality. Self-organization
Witherington and Margett (2011) queried establishes stability at “far-from-equilibrium”
whether the dynamical approach is more consis- conditions in a downward causation from upper
tent with Piaget’s constructionist stage approach levels. In this sense, systems express “agency.”
(Piaget, 1952, 1954) or with Gibson’s more Witherington (2011) summarized the position
empirical approach to development (Gibson, of Deacon (2003, 2006) on first-, second-, and
1979, 1982; Gibson & Pick, 2000). For Piaget, third-order emergence. In first-order emergence,
the child and environment are constitutive com- as in thermodynamically basic systems, each
ponents that serve to structure each other, and emergence is local and does not influence future
knowledge acquisition depends on this interac- ones, such as in the successive changes of state of
tion. For Gibson, the environment provides water. In second-order emergence, the prior sys-
“objective affordances” that the child has to “dis- tem state constrains future ones by downward
cover.” For Witherington and Margett (2011), causation. In third-order emergence, the history
both approaches can be considered compatible of prior states has a cumulative effect, as in
with a dynamic systems approach because both development.
are “relational” and depend on child “activity.”
As for causality in systems, Witherington
(2011) described circular causality between Neural Model
micro- and macro-dynamics. However, the bot-
tom-up, local-to-global direction is “privileged” Perone and Spencer (2013) presented a dynami-
compared to the global-to-local, downward one. cal systems-based model of infant habituation,
Nevertheless, all levels in a system engage in referred to as the Dynamic Neural Field (DNF)
reciprocal interactions. Systems, through their model. It supports the view that infants learn
interrelated level interactions, can help explain dynamically as they engage in exploratory look-
embodiment in behavior, including cognitively ing to and away from a stimulus.
(e.g., Thelen, Schöner, Scheier, & Smith, 2001). Schöner and Thelen’s (2006) DNF model for
Witherington (2011) elaborated that the neural network models of infant behavior in
dynamical systems approach to causality is plu- looking tasks consists of coupled excitatory and
ralistic and allows for emergence through self- inhibitory layers. Looking is generated by excit-
organizational circular causality in atory layer activation. The excitatory layer acti-
structure-function cycling. Causality is “irreduc- vation also generates inhibition (and a decline in
ible” and cannot be described simply in terms of looking) by way of suppression of the excitatory
lower-order levels. Upper levels are just as “caus- layer. This particular DNF model does not
ally effective” as lower-order ones. The process include a long-term learning component, which
is “bidirectional” between lower and upper levels. Perone and Spencer (2013) addressed in their
System causality is integral to the whole system, modified DNF model.
Chapter Conclusions 441

In Perone and Spencer’s (2013) integrated In neural dynamics, neural interactions stabi-
DNF model, layers of neurons are organized by lize local excitatory peaks and, in addition, global
functional topography along continuous dimen- inhibitory interactions contain competing
sions (metrics, e.g., color). These DNF layers responses. When the system is unstable, new sta-
consist of neighboring or “similarly tuned” ble states possibly might emerge. Developmentally,
neurons that mutually excite each other while instabilities in neural regimes characterize the
inhibiting neurons tuned dissimilarly. This type developmental state prior to the growth in behav-
of neural interaction is common in the nervous ior that emerges after “boosting” of activation lev-
system—local excitatory/lateral inhibitory els in interaction-dominated regimes. Different
dynamics (e.g., Fuster, 2003). The DNF layers stable solutions might materialize, depending on
constitute lower levels of the neural “attractor” past and present system configuration. Moreover,
states in which they enter (a “higher dimen- the changes might be graded/continuous or
sional space”). abrupt/discontinuous ones.
Neural attractor states oscillate between rest-
ing, self-stabilizing ones during stimulation, and
self-sustaining ones after stimulation, e.g., to Comment
keep items in working memory (WM). When
stimuli reach thresholds (above localized peak In Young (2011), I considered the systems model
activity thresholds), they leave an activation trace crucial to understanding the mechanisms that
in a superordinate neural cell assembly, or drive behavior. The review of present systems
Hebbian learning layer of the system, which conceptualizations in this regard gives further
feeds back into the perceptual field. Connections support to this notion. The biopsychosocial and
among previously excited neurons become embodiment perspectives described previously in
strengthened, and the neural response to subse- this chapter are quite integrative. However, they
quent stimuli of the same order is strengthened. need the process account of change in the sys-
When the DNF excitatory and inhibitory layers tems model as a complement.
engage in stronger interaction (stronger local
excitation/lateral inhibition), and this interaction
is accompanied by Hebbian learning layer activa- Chapter Conclusions
tion, as well, the overall system can enter into a
self-sustaining state. For stimuli that are “re- The research in the area of theory of mind/false
presented,” WM becomes more easily self- belief and executive function/inhibition illus-
sustaining and keeps relevant items in memory, trates the burgeoning work in developmental psy-
which also happens through this process of chology, but also the need for more integrative
reaching stable peak activation and its associated models. The period of infancy for the study of
effects. As for differences between infant and both theory of mind/false belief and executive
adult DNFs, the process is more gradual in infants function/inhibition has been described as the
and learning plays a more important role. time for rapid and major, advanced acquisitions,
DNF has been applied to infant motor behav- yet others have called for a more conservative
ior (Schöner & Dineave, 2007; Thelen et al., interpretation of the data involved. For example,
2001). The DNF is conceived as a distribution of in the conservative approach, for early theory of
neural activation applicable to a relevant aspect mind/false-belief research, the more plausible
of behavior. Neuronal interactions/recurrences view is that early abstractions are quite limited, at
“drive” the systems involved. Localized peaks of best, if not absent, and that advocating for core,
activation (governed by a “movement parame- innate modules in these areas is premature, if not
ter”), for one target or another (e.g., in the case of misplaced.
reaching), are influenced by attention, task, con- One way of understanding the research in the
text, and behavioral (prior reaching) history. area is to view the development of theory of
442 17 Developing the Mind, Minding Development

mind/false belief and executive function/inhibition Barkley, R. A. (1997). Behavioral inhibition, sustained
from the point of view of Neo-Piagetian model- attention, and executive functions: Constructing a uni-
fying theory of ADHD. Psychological Bulletin, 121,
ing (Young, 2011). Another is to consider their 65–94.
relation to the other models described in this Baumeister, R. F. (2008). Free will in scientific psychol-
chapter. For example, taking the perspective of ogy. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 3, 14–19.
the other appears to involve parallel embodied Baumeister, R. F., Vohs, K. D., & Tice, D. M. (2007). The
strength model of self-control. Current Directions in
processes even early in life through the mirror Psychological Science, 16, 351–355.
neuron system. Moreover, a broad understanding Beaudoin-Ryan, L., & Goldin-Meadow, S. (2014). Teaching
of any developmental phenomenon should con- moral reasoning through gesture. Developmental
sider the biopsychosocial model. Finally, dynam- Science, 17, 984–990.
Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2010). Dynamic mecha-
ical system theory can help explicate transition nistic explanation: Computational modeling of circa-
mechanisms. There is much integrative theoreti- dian rhythms as an exemplar for cognitive science.
cal work needed on the question of early, suppos- Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 41,
edly sophisticated, and innate or prepared 321–333.
Bell, M. A., & Cuevas, K. (2012). Psychobiology of exec-
acquisitions, as demonstrated in these three utive function in early development. In J. A. Griffin,
developmental chapters in the present book that L. S. Freund, & P. McCardle (Eds.), Executive func-
have been presented. In this regard, rather than tion in preschool age children: Integrating measure-
seeking all-or-none modeling solutions one way ment, neurodevelopment and translational research.
Washington: American Psychological Association.
or another about innate and gradual approaches Berger, A., Alyagon, U., Hadaya, H., Atzaba-Poria, N., &
to early infant acquisitions, Piagetian-type mod- Auerbach, J. G. (2013). Response inhibition in pre-
eling could provide the needed scaffold for an schoolers at familial risk for attention deficit hyperac-
integrative account both through the capacities tivity disorder: A behavioral and electrophysiological
stop-signal study. Child Development, 84, 1616–1632.
that its schema-based cognitive development Berk, M. (2013). The DSM-5: Hyperbole, hope, or
affords and the transitions it describes in infancy hypothesis? BioMed Central Medicine, 11, 128.
from one developmental substage to the next. doi:10.1186/1741-7015-11-128.
Bickel, W. K., Quisenberry, A. J., Moody, L., & Wilson,
A. G. (2014). Therapeutic opportunities for self-
control repair in addiction and related disorders:
References Change and the limits of change in trans-disease pro-
cesses. Clinical Psychological Science, 3, 140–153.
Adams, R. A., Shipp, S., & Friston, K. J. (2013). Bjork, R. A., Dunlosky, J., & Kornell, N. (2013). Self-
Predictions not commands: Active inference in the regulated learning: Beliefs, techniques, and illusions.
motor system. Brain Structure and Function, 218, Annual Review of Psychology, 64, 417–444.
611–643. Blackwell, K. A., & Munakata, Y. (2014). Costs and ben-
Adamson, L. B., Bakeman, R., Deckner, D. F., & Nelson, efits linked to developments in cognitive control.
P. B. (2014). From interactions to conversations: The Developmental Science, 17, 203–211.
development of joint engagement during early child- Bornstein, M. H., Hahn, C.-S., & Suwalsky, J. T. D.
hood. Child Development, 85, 941–955. (2013). Physically developed and exploratory young
Antonucci, S. M., & Alt, M. (2011). A lifespan perspec- infants contribute to their own long-term academic
tive on semantic processing of concrete concepts: achievement. Psychological Science, 24, 1906–1917.
Does a sensory/motor model have the potential to Buccino, G., Lui, F., Canessa, N., Patteri, I., Lagravinese,
bridge the gap? Cognitive, Affective, & Behavioral G., Benuzzi, F., et al. (2004). Neural circuits involved
Neuroscience, 11, 551–572. in the recognition of actions performed by
Arsalidou, M., Pascual-Leone, J., Johnson, J., Morris, D., nonconspecifics: An FMRI study. Journal of Cognitive
& Taylor, M. J. (2013). A balancing act of the brain: Neuroscience, 16, 114–126.
Activations and deactivations driven by cognitive Buescher, J. M., Leibermeister, W., Jules, M., Uhr, M.,
load. Brain and Behavior, 3, 273–285. Muntel, J., Botella, E., et al. (2012). Global network
Baillargeon, R., Scott, R. M., He, Z., Sloane, S., Setoh, P., reorganizing during dynamic adaptations of Bacillus
Jin, K-S., Wu, D., & Bian, L. (2014). Psychological subtilis metabolism. Science, 335, 1099–1103.
and sociomoral reasoning in infancy. In M. Mikulincer Bunge, S. A., Dudukovic, N. M., Thomason, M. E.,
& P. R. Shaver (Eds.), E. Borgida & J. A. Bargh Vaidya, C. J., & Gabrieli, J. D. E. (2002). Immature
(Assoc. Eds.), APA handbook of personality and social frontal lobe contributions to cognitive control in chil-
psychology: Attitudes and social cognition (Vol. 1, dren: Evidence from fMRI. Neuron, 33, 301–311.
pp. 79–150). Washington, DC: American Psychological Butler, L. P., & Markman, E. M. (2012). Finding the
Association. cause: Verbal framing helps children extract causal
References 443

evidence embedded in a complex scene. Journal of Cuevas, K., & Bell, M. A. (2013). Infant attention and
Cognition and Development, 13, 38–66. early childhood executive function. Child Development,
Campbell, A. (2012). The study of sex differences: 85, 397–404.
Feminism and biology. Zeitschrift für Psychologie Cuevas, K., Deater-Deckard, K., Kim-Spoon, J., Watson,
[Journal of Psychology], 220, 137–143. A. J., Morasch, K. C., & Bell, M. A. (2014). What’s
Carruthers, P. (2013). Mindreading in infancy. Mind and mom got to do with it? Contributions of maternal
Language, 28, 141–172. executive function and caregiving to the development
Case, R., Okamoto, Y., Griffin, S., McKeough, A., Bleiker, of executive function across early childhood.
C., Henderson, B., & Stephenson, K. M. (1996). The Developmental Science, 17, 224–238.
role of central conceptual structures in the development de Barbaro, K., Johnson, C. M., & Deák, G. O. (2013).
of children’s thought. Monographs of the Society for Twelve-month “social revolution” emerges from
Research in Child Development, 61, i + iii-vi + 1-295. mother-infant sensorimotor coordination: A longitudi-
Castellano, F. X., & Tannock, R. (2002). Neuroscience of nal investigation. Human Development, 56, 223–248.
attention-deficit hyperactivity disorder: The search for de Klerk, C. C. J. M., Johnson, M. H., Heyes, C. M., &
endophenotypes. Nature Reviews in Neuroscience, 3, Southgate, V. (2015). Baby steps: Investigating the
617–628. development of perceptual-motor couplings in infancy.
Castiello, U. B., Cristina Zoia, S., Nelini, C., Sartori, L., Developmental Science, 18, 270–280.
Blason, L., D’Ottavio, G., et al. (2010). Wired to be Deacon, T. W. (2003). The hierarchic logic of emergence:
social: The ontogeny of human interaction. PLoS One, Untangling the interdependence of evolution and self-
5, e13199. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0013199. organization. In B. H. Weber & D. J. Depew (Eds.),
Chemero, A. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. Evolution and learning: The Baldwin effect reconsid-
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. ered (pp. 273–308). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Chevalier, N., Martis, S. B., Curran, T., & Munakata, Y. Deacon, T. W. (2006). Emergence: The hole at the well’s
(2015). Metacognitive processes in executive control hub. In P. Clayton & P. Davies (Eds.), The re-
development: The case of reactive and proactive control. emergence of emergence: The emergentist hypothesis
Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 27, 1125–1136. from science to religion (pp. 11–150). Oxford, UK:
Choi, Y.-J., & Luo, Y. (2015). 13-month-olds’ understand- Oxford University Press.
ing of social interaction. Psychological Science, 26, Delafield-Butt, J. T., & Gangopadhyay, N. (2013).
274–283. Sensorimotor intentionality: The origins of intention-
Chou, K.-H., Cheng, Y., Chen, I.-Y., Lin, C.-P., & Chu, ality in prospective agent action. Developmental
W.-C. (2011). Sex-linked white matter microstructure Review, 33, 399–425.
of the social and analytic brain. NeuroImage, 54, del Moral, R., González, M., Navarro, J., & Marijuán,
725–733. P. C. (2011). From genomics to scientomics:
Cimpian, A., & Erickson, L. C. (2012). The effect of Expanding the bioinformation paradigm. Information,
generic statements on children’s causal attributions: 2, 651–671.
Questions of mechanism. Developmental Psychology, Denissen, J. J. A., van Aken, M. A. G., Penke, L., &
48, 159–170. Wood, D. (2013). Self-regulation underlies tempera-
Cisek, P. (2012). Making decisions through a distributed ment and personality: An integrative developmental
consensus. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 22, framework. Child Development Perspectives, 7,
927–935. 255–260.
Clark, A. (2013). Whatever next? Predictive brains, situ- Devine, R. T., & Hughes, C. (2014). Relations between
ated agents, and the future of cognitive science. false belief understanding and executive function in
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36, 1–24. early childhood: A meta-analysis. Child Development,
Cook, R., Bird, G., Catmur, C., Press, C., & Heyes, C. 85, 1777–1794.
(2014). Mirror neurons: From origin to function. Diamond, A. (1985). Development of the ability to use
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 37, 177–192. recall to guide action, as indicated by infants’ perfor-
Cook, S. W., Duffy, R. G., & Fenn, K. M. (2013). mance on A-not-B. Child Development, 56, 868–883.
Consolidation and transfer of learning after observing Diamond, A. (1990). Developmental time course in
hand gesture. Child Development, 84, 1863–1871. human infants and infant monkeys, and the neural
Corbetta, D., Friedman, D. R., & Bell, M. A. (2014). bases, of inhibitory control in reaching. Annals of the
Brain reorganization as a function of walking experi- New York Academy of Sciences, 608, 637–676.
ence in 12-month-old infants: Implications for the Diamond, A. (1991). Neuropsychological insights intro
development of manual laterality. Frontiers in the meaning of object concept development. In
Psychology, 5, 245. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00245. S. Carey & R. Gelman (Eds.), The epigenesis of mind:
Courvoisier, D. S., Renaud, R., Geiser, C., Paskchke, K., Essays on biology and cognition (pp. 67–110).
Gaudy, K., & Jordan, K. (2013). Sex hormones and Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
mental rotation: An intensive longitudinal investiga- Diamond, A. (2012). Activities and programs that improve
tion. Hormones and Behavior, 63, 345–351. children’s executive functions. Current Directions in
Craver, C. F., & Bechtel, W. (2007). Top-down causation Psychological Science, 21, 335–341.
without top-down causes. Biology and Philosophy, 22, Diamond, A. (2013). Executive functions. Annual Review
547–563. of Psychology, 64, 135–168.
444 17 Developing the Mind, Minding Development

Diaz, A., & Eisenberg, N. (2015). The process of emotion mechanisms in perception and action: Attention and
regulation is different from individual differences in performance (Vol. XIX, pp. 334–355). New York:
emotion regulation: Conceptual arguments and a focus Oxford University Press.
on individual differences. Psychological Inquiry, 26, Gallese, V., & Lakoff, G. (2005). The brain’s concepts:
37–47. The role of the sensory-motor system in conceptual
Dice, J. L., & Dove, M. K. (2011). A Piagetian approach knowledge. Cognitive Neuropsychology, 21, 1–26.
to infant referential behaviors. Infant Behavior & Gallese, V., Rochat, M., Cossu, G., & Sinigaglia, C.
Development, 34, 481–486. (2009). Motor cognition and its role in the phylogeny
di Pellegrino, G., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., Gallese, V., & and ontogeny of action and understanding.
Rizzolatti, G. (1992). Understanding motor events: A Developmental Psychology, 45, 103–113.
neurophysiological study. Experimental Brain Gandolfi, E., Viterbori, P., Traverso, L., & Usai, M. C.
Research, 191, 176–180. (2014). Inhibitory processes in toddlers: A latent-
Dunbar, R. I. M. (2014). The social brain: Psychological variable approach. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 381.
underpinnings and implications for the structure of doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00381.
organization. Current Directions in Psychological Gergely, G., & Watson, J. S. (1999). Early socio-emotional
Science, 23, 109–114. development: Contingency perception and the social-
Duque, J., Olivier, E., & Rushworth, M. (2013). Top- biofeedback model. In P. Rochat (Ed.), Early social
down inhibitory control exerted by the medial frontal cognition: Understanding others in first months of life
cortex during action selection under conflict. Journal (pp. 101–136). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
of Cognitive Neuroscience, 25, 1634–1648. Gerson, S. A., & Woodward, A. L. (2014). Learning from
Eagly, A. H., & Wood, W. (2013). The nature-nurture their own actions: The unique effect of producing
debates: 25 years of challenges in understanding the actions on infant’s action understanding. Child
psychology of gender. Perspectives on Psychological Development, 85, 264–277.
Science, 8, 340–357. Gibson, E. J. (1982). The concept of affordances in devel-
Engelhardt, L. E., Briley, D. A., Mann, F. D., Harden, opment: The renascence of functionalism. In W. A.
K. P., & Tucker-Drob, E. M. (2015). Genes unite exec- Collins (Ed.), The Minnesota Symposia on Child
utive functions in childhood. Psychological Science, Psychology (The concept of development, Vol. 15,
26, 1151–1163. pp. 55–81). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Estes, Z., & Felker, S. (2012). Confidence mediates the Gibson, E. J., & Pick, A. D. (2000). An ecological
sex difference in mental rotation performance. approach to perceptual learning and development.
Archives of Sexual Behavior, 4, 557–570. New York: Oxford University Press.
Firth, C. D., & Firth, U. (2008). Implicit and explicit pro- Gibson, J. J. (1966). The sense considered as perceptual
cesses in social cognition. Neuron, 60, 503–510. systems. Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin.
Fischer, K. W., & Bidell, T. R. (2006). Dynamic develop- Gibson, J. J. (1979). The ecological approach to visual
ment of action, thought, and emotion. In W. Damon & perception. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
R. M. Lerner (Eds.), Theoretical models of human Glenberg, A. M. (2010). Embodiment as a unifying per-
development: Handbook of child psychology (6th ed., spective for psychology. Wiley Interdisciplinary
pp. 313–399). New York: Wiley. Reviews: Cognitive Science, 1, 586–596.
Fogel, A. (2011). Theoretical and applied dynamic sys- Glenberg, A. M., Goldberg, A., & Zhu, X. (2011).
tems research in developmental science. Child Improving early reading comprehension using embod-
Development Perspectives, 5, 267–272. ied CAI. Instructional Science, 39, 27–39.
Fogel, A., & Garvey, A. (2007). Alive communication. Glenberg, A. M., Gutierrez, T., Levin, J. R., Japuntich, S.,
Infant Behavior and Development, 30, 251–257. & Kaschak, M. P. (2004). Activity and imagined
Friedman, N. P., Miyake, A., Robinson, J. L., & Hewitt, activity can enhance young children’s reading com-
J. K. (2011). Developmental trajectories in toddlers’ prehension. Journal of Educational Psychology, 96,
self-restraint predict individual differences in execu- 424–436.
tive functions 14 years later: A behavioral genetic Göksun, T., George, N. R., Hirsh-Pasek, K., & Golinkoff,
analysis. Developmental Psychology, 47, 1410–1430. R. M. (2013). Forces and motion: How young children
Friedman, N. P., Miyake, A., Young, S. E., DeFries, J. C., understand causal events. Child Development, 84,
Corley, R. P., & Hewitt, J. K. (2008). Individual differ- 1285–1295.
ences in executive functions are almost entirely Goldin-Meadow, S. (2002). Constructing communication
genetic in origin. Journal of Experimental Psychology: by hand. Cognitive Development, 17, 1385–1405.
General, 137, 201–225. Goldin-Meadow, S. (2003). Hearing gesture: How our
Friston, K. (2011). What is optimal about motor control? hands help us think. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
Neuron, 72, 488–498. University Press.
Fuster, J. M. (2003). Cortex and mind: Unifying cogni- Goldin-Meadow, S. (2005). Gesture in social interactions:
tion. New York: Oxford University Press. A mechanism for cognitive change. In B. D. Homer &
Gallese, V., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., & Rizzolatti, G. C. S. Tamis-LeMonda (Eds.), The development of
(2002). Action representation and the inferior parietal social cognition and communication (pp. 259–283).
lobule. In W. Prinz & B. Hommel (Eds.), Common Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
References 445

Goldin-Meadow, S. (2006). Talking and thinking with our Embodiment and epigenesis: Theoretical and method-
hands. Current Directions in Psychological Science, ological issues in understanding the role of biology
15, 34–39. within the relational development system. Part B:
Goldin-Meadow, S., Cook, S. W., & Mitchell, Z. A. Ontogenetic dimensions (Vol. 45, pp. 67–92).
(2009). Gesturing saves cognitive resources when Waltham, MA: Academic Press.
talking about nonpresent objects. Cognitive Science, Houdé, O. (2015). Cognitive development during infancy
34, 602–619. and early childhood across cultures. In J. D. Wright
Goldin-Meadow, S., & Singer, M. A. (2003). From chil- (Ed.), International encyclopedia of the social and
dren’s hands to adults’ ears: Gesture’s role in the behavioral sciences (2nd ed.). Oxford, UK: Elsevier
learning process. Developmental Psychology, 39, Science.
509–520. Houdé, O., & Borst, G. (2014). Measuring inhibitory con-
Gopnik, A., & Wellman, H. M. (2012). Reconstructing trol in children and adults: Brain imaging and mental
constructivism: Causal models, Bayesian learning chronometry. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 616.
mechanisms, and the theory. Psychological Bulletin, doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00616.
138, 1085–1108. Howard, S. J., Johnson, J., & Pascual-Leone, J. (2015).
Greenberg, G., Callina, K. S., & Mueller, M. K. (2013). Clarifying inhibitory control: Diversity and develop-
Emergence, self-organization and developmental sci- ment of attentional inhibition. Cognitive Development,
ence. In R. M. Lerner & J. B. Benson (Eds.), Advances 31, 1–21.
in child development and behavior. Embodiment and Hughes, C. (1998). Finding your marbles: Does pre-
epigenesis: Theoretical and methodological issues in schoolers’ strategic behavior predict later understand-
understanding the role of biology within the relational ing of mind? Developmental Psychology, 34, 1326–
development system. Part A: Philosophical, theoreti- 1339.
cal, and biological dimensions (Vol. 44, pp. 95–126). Huys, R., Perdikis, D., & Jirsa, V. K. (2014). Functional
Waltham, MA: Academic Press. architectures and structured flows on manifolds: A
Griffiths, P. E., & Tabery, J. (2013). Developmental sys- dynamical framework for motor behavior.
tems theory: What does it explain, and how does it Psychological Review, 121, 302–336.
explain it? In R. M. Lerner & J. B. Benson (Eds.), Iacoboni, M. (2008). Mesial frontal cortex and super mir-
Advances in child development and behavior. ror neurons. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 31, 30.
Embodiment and epigenesis: Theoretical and method- doi:10.1017/S0140525X07003214.
ological issues in understanding the role of biology James, J., Ellis, B. J., Schlomer, G. L., & Garber, J. (2012).
within the relational development system. Part A: Sex-specific pathways to early puberty, sexual debut,
Philosophical, theoretical, and biological dimensions and sexual risk taking: Tests of an integrated
(Vol. 44, pp. 65–94). Waltham, MA: Academic Press. evolutionary-developmental model. Developmental
Gross, J. J. (2013). Emotion regulation: Taking stock and Psychology, 48, 687–702.
moving forward. Emotion, 13, 359–365. Joliot, M., Leroux, G., Dubal, S., Tzourio-Mazoyer, N.,
Gross, J. J. (2015a). Emotion regulation: Current status Houdé, O., Mazoyer, B., et al. (2009). Cognitive inhi-
and future prospects. Psychological Inquiry, 26, 1–26. bition of number/length interference in a Piaget-like
Gross, J. J. (2015b). The extended process model of emo- task: Evidence by combining ERP and MEG. Clinical
tion regulation: Elaboration, applications, and future Neurophysiology, 120, 1501–1513.
direction. Psychological Inquiry, 26, 130–137. Kanai, R., Bahrami, B., Roylance, R., & Rees, G. (2012).
Gross, J. J., & Jazaieri, H. (2014). Emotion, emotion regu- Online social network size is reflected in human brain
lation, and psychopathology: An affective science per- structure. Proceedings of the Royal Society B:
spective. Clinical Psychological Science, 2, 387–401. Biological Sciences, 279, 1237–1334.
Gross, J. J., & Thompson, R. A. (2007). Emotion regula- Karbach, J., & Kray, J. (2009). How useful is executive
tion: Conceptual foundations. In J. J. Gross (Ed.), control training? Age differences in near and far trans-
Handbook of emotion regulation (pp. 3–24). New York: fer of task-switching training. Developmental Science,
Guilford Press. 12, 978–990.
Haken, H. (1983). Synergetics: An introduction: Kiverstein, J. (2012). The meaning of embodiment. Topics
Nonequilibrium phase transitions and self- in Cognitive Science, 4, 740–758.
organization in physics, chemistry, and biology. Knudsen, B., & Liszkowski, U. (2013). One-year-olds
Berlin, Germany: Springer (3rd rev. ed). warn others about negative action outcomes. Journal
Halliday, M. A. K., & Hasan, R. (1976). Cohesion in of Cognition and Development, 14, 424–436.
English. London: Longman. Kovács, A. M., Télglás, E., & Endress, A. D. (2010). The
Heyes, C. (2014a). False belief in infancy: A fresh look. social sense: Susceptibility to others’ beliefs in human
Developmental Science, 17, 647–659. infants and adults. Science, 330, 1830–1834.
Heyes, C. (2014b). Rich interpretations of infant behaviour Kray, J., & Ferdinand, N. K. (2013). How to improve cog-
are popular, but are they valid? A reply to Scott and nitive control in development during childhood:
Baillargeon. Developmental Science, 17, 665–666. Potentials and limits of cognitive interventions. Child
Ho, M.-W. (2013). No genes for intelligence in the fluid Development Perspectives, 7, 121–125.
genome. In R. M. Lerner & J. B. Benson (Eds.), Lakes, K. D., & Hoyt, W. T. (2004). Promoting self-
Advances in child development and behavior. regulation through school-based martial arts training.
446 17 Developing the Mind, Minding Development

Journal of Applied Developmental Psychology, 25, in 14-month-old infants: An event-related EEG desyn-
283–302. chronization study. Developmental Science, 14,
Leaper, C. (2013). Gender development during childhood. 474–480.
In P. D. Zelazo (Ed.), Oxford handbook of develop- Mascolo, M. F. (2013). Developing through relationships:
mental psychology (pp. 327–377). New York: Oxford An embodied coactive systems framework. In R. M.
University Press. Lerner & J. B. Benson (Eds.), Advances in child devel-
Lee, K., Bull, R., & Ho, R. M. H. (2013). Developmental opment and behavior. Embodiment and epigenesis:
changes in executive functioning. Child Development, Theoretical and methodological issues in understand-
84, 1933–1953. ing the role of biology within the relational develop-
Legare, C. H. (2012). Exploring explanation: Explaining ment system. Part B: Ontogenetic dimensions (Vol. 45,
inconsistent evidence informs exploratory, hypothesis- pp. 185–226). Waltham, MA: Academic Press.
testing behavior in young children. Child Development, May, A. (2011). Experience-dependent structural plastic-
83, 173–185. ity in the adult human brain. Trends in Cognitive
Lepage, J. F., & Theoret, H. (2007). The mirror neuron Sciences, 15, 475–482.
system: Grasping others’ actions from birth? Moè, A. (2012). Gender difference does not mean genetic
Developmental Science, 10, 513–523. difference: Externalizing improves performance in
Leroux, G., Spiess, J., Zago, L., Rossi, S., Lubin, A., mental rotation. Learning and Individual Differences,
Turbelin, M.-R., et al. (2009). Adult brains don’t fully 22, 20–24.
overcome biases that lead to incorrect performance Moll, H., & Tomasello, M. (2007). How 14- and
during cognitive development: An fMRI study in 18-month-olds know what others have experienced.
young adults completing a Piaget-like task. Developmental Psychology, 43, 309–317.
Developmental Science, 12, 326–338. Moore, C., & Paulus, M. (2013). A second-person
Levy, E. T., & McNeill, D. (2013). Narrative development as approach cannot explain intentionality in social
symbol formation: Gestures, imagery and the emergence understanding. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36,
of cohesion. Culture & Psychology, 19, 548–569. 430–431.
Lewis, C., & Stack, J. (2013). A mature second-person Moriguchi, Y. (2014). The early development of executive
neuroscience needs a first-person (plural) develop- function and its relation to social interaction: A brief
mental foundation. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, review. Frontiers in Psychology, 5. doi:10.3389/
36, 428–429. fpsyg.2014.00388
Lewis, M. D. (2011). Dynamic systems approaches: Cool Muentener, P., & Schulz, L. (2012). What doesn’t go
enough? Hot enough? Child Development Perspectives, without saying: Communication, induction, and
5, 279–285. exploration. Language Learning and Development, 8,
Lewis, P. A., Rezaie, R., Browne, R., Roberts, N., & 61–85.
Dunbar, R. I. M. (2011). Ventromedial prefrontal vol- Mumford, K. H., & Kita, S. (2014). Children use gesture
ume predicts understandings of others and social net- to interpret novel verb meanings. Child Development,
work size. NeuroImage, 57, 1624–1629. 85, 1181–1189.
Lickliter, R., & Honeycutt, H. (2003). Developmental Needham, A., Barrett, T., & Peterman, K. (2002). A pick-
dynamics: Toward a biologically plausible evolutionary me-up for infants’ exploratory skills: Early simulated
psychology. Psychological Bulletin, 129, 819–835. experiences reaching for objects using ‘sticky mittens’
Liszkowski, U. (2013). Using theory of mind. Child enhances young infants’ object exploration skills.
Development Perspectives, 7, 104–109. Infant Behavior and Development, 25, 279–295.
Liszkowski, U., Carpenter, M., Henning, A., Striano, T., Needham, A., & Libertus, K. (2011). Embodiment in
& Tomasello, M. (2004). Twelve-month-olds point to early development. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews:
share attention and interest. Developmental Science, 7, Cognitive Science, 2, 117–123.
297–307. Nystrom, P. (2008). The infant mirror neuron system stud-
Low, J. (2010). Preschoolers’ implicit and explicit false- ied with high density EEG. Social Neuroscience, 3,
belief understanding: Relations with complex syntac- 334–347.
tical mastery. Child Development, 81, 579–615. Olofson, E. L., & Baldwin, D. (2011). Infants recognize
Low, J., & Perner, J. (2012). Implicit and explicit theory similar goals across dissimilar actions involving object
of mind: State of the art. British Journal of manipulation. Cognition, 118, 258–264.
Developmental Psychology, 30, 1–13. Overton, W. F. (2013). Relationism and relational devel-
Marshall, P. J. (2013). Coping with complexity: opmental systems: A paradigm for developmental
Developmental systems and multilevel analyses in science in the post-cartesian era. In R. M. Lerner &
developmental psychopathology. Development and J. B. Benson (Eds.), Advances in child development
Psychopathology, 25, 1311–1324. and behavior. Embodiment and epigenesis:
Marshall, P. J. (2014). Beyond different levels: Theoretical and methodological issues in understand-
Embodiment and the developmental system. Frontiers ing the role of biology within the relational develop-
in Psychology, 5, 929. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00929. mental system. Part A: Philosophical, theoretical,
Marshall, P. J., Young, T., & Meltzoff, A. N. (2011). and biological dimensions (Vol. 44, pp. 21–64).
Neural correlates of action observation and execution Oxford, UK: Elsevier.
References 447

Peña-Sarrionandia, A., Mikolajczak, M., & Gross, J. J. Richerson, P. J., & Boyd, R. (2005). Not by genes alone:
(2015). Integrating emotion regulation and emotional How culture transformed human evolution. Chicago,
intelligence traditions: A meta-analysis. Frontiers in IL: University of Chicago Press.
Psychology, 6, 160. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2015.00160. Richland, L. E., & Burchinal, M. R. (2013). Early execu-
Perko, L. (2006). Differential equations and dynamical tive function predicts reasoning development.
systems (3rd ed.). Berlin, Germany: Springer. Psychological Science, 24, 87–92.
Perone, S., & Spencer, J. P. (2013). Autonomy in action: Rivière, J. (2014). Embodiment in children’s choice:
Linking the act of looking to memory formation in Linking bodily constraints with decisional dynamics.
infancy via dynamic neural fields. Cognitive Science, Current Directions in Psychological Science, 23,
37, 1–60. 408–413.
Piaget, J. (1950). The psychology of intelligence. London, Rizzolatti, G., & Craighero, K. (2004). The mirror-neuron
UK: Routledge & Kegan (Original work published system. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 27, 169–192.
1947). Rizzolatti, G., & Sinigaglia, C. (2010). The functional
Piaget, J. (1952). The origins of intelligence in children. role of the parieto-frontal mirror circuit: Interpretations
New York: International Universities Press. and misinterpretations. Nature Review Neuroscience,
Piaget, J. (1953). The origin of intelligence in the child. 11, 264–274.
London: Routledge & Paul. Rose, S. A., Feldman, J. F., & Jankowski, J. J. (2012).
Piaget, J. (1954). The construction of reality in the child. Implications of infant cognition for executive functions
New York: Basic Books. at age 11. Psychological Science, 23, 1345–1355.
Piaget, J. (1955). The child’s conception of the world. Ruffman, T. (2014). To belief or not belief: Children’s
London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. theory of mind. Developmental Review, 34, 265–293.
Piaget, J. (1960). The child’s conception of the world. Ruffman, T., Taumoepeau, M., & Perkins, C. (2012).
Oxford, UK: Littlefield, Adams. Statistical learning as a basis for social understanding
Piaget, J. (1970/1988). Piaget’s theory. In P. Mussen (Ed.), in children. British Journal of Developmental
Handbook of child psychology (Vol. 1, 3rd ed. Psychology, 30, 87–104.
pp. 703–732). New York: Wiley. Reprinted in Russell, J. (1996). Agency: Its role in mental development.
K. Richardson & S. Sheldon (Eds.), Cognitive devel- Hove, UK: Taylor & Francis.
opment to adolescence. Hove, UK: Lawrence Erlbaum. Saby, J. N., Meltzoff, A. N., & Marshall, P. J. (2013).
Ping, R. M., & Goldin-Meadow, S. (2010). Gesturing Infants’ somatotopic neural responses to seeing human
saves cognitive resources when talking about nonpre- actions: I’ve got you under my skin. PLoS One, 8,
sent objects. Cognitive Science, 34, 602–619. e77905. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0077905.
Piontelli, A. (2010). Development of normal fetal move- Sameroff, A. (2010). A unified theory of development: A
ments: The first 25 weeks of gestation. Milan: Springer. dialectic integration of nature and nurture. Child
Powell, J., Lewis, P. A., Roberts, N., García-Fiñana, M., & Development, 81, 6–22.
Dunbar, R. I. M. (2012). Orbital prefrontal cortex vol- San Juan, V., & Astington, J. W. (2012). Bridging the gap
ume predicts social network size: An imaging study of between implicit and explicit understanding: How lan-
individual differences in humans. Proceedings of the guage development promotes the processing and rep-
Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 279, 2157– resentation of false belief. British Journal of
2162. Developmental Psychology, 30, 105–122.
Pulvermuller, F., & Garagnani, M. (2014). From senso- Schilbach, L., Timmermans, B., Reddy, V., Costall, A.,
rimotor learning to memory cells in prefrontal and Bente, G., Schlicht, T., et al. (2013). Toward a second-
temporal association cortex: A neurocomputational person neuroscience. Behavioral and Brain Sciences,
study of disembodiment. Cortex, 57, 1–21. 36, 393–462.
Rakoczy, H. (2012). Do infants have a theory of mind? Schöner, G., & Dineave, E. (2007). Dynamic instabilities
British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 30, as mechanisms for emergence. Developmental
59–74. Science, 10, 69–74.
Raver, C. C., Jones, S. M., Li-Grining, C., Zhai, F., Bub, Schöner, G., & Thelen, E. (2006). Using dynamic field
K., & Pressler, E. (2011). CSRP’s impact on low- theory to rethink infant habituation. Psychological
income preschoolers’ preacademic skills: Self- Review, 113, 273–299.
regulation as a mediating mechanism. Child Scott, R. M. (2014). Post hoc versus predictive accounts
Development, 82, 362–378. of children’s theory of mind: A reply to Ruffman.
Richardson, K. (2013). The evolution of intelligent devel- Developmental Review, 34, 300–304.
opmental systems. In R. M. Lerner & J. B. Benson Scott, R. M., & Baillargeon, R. (2009). Which penguin is
(Eds.), Advances in child development and behavior. this? Attributing false beliefs about object identity at
Embodiment and epigenesis: Theoretical and method- 18 months. Child Development, 80, 1172–1196.
ological issues in understanding the role of biology Scott, R. M., & Baillargeon, R. (2014). How fresh a look?
within the relational development system. Part A: A reply to Heyes. Developmental Science, 17,
Philosophical, theoretical, and biological dimensions 660–664.
(Vol. 44, pp. 127–160). Waltham, MA: Academic Seidl, A., Tincoff, R., Baker, C., & Cristia, A. (2015).
Press. Why the body comes first: Effects of experimenter
448 17 Developing the Mind, Minding Development

touch on infants’ word finding. Developmental Usai, M. C., Viterbori, P., Traverso, L., & De Franchis, V.
Science, 18, 155–164. (2014). Latent structure of executive function in 5-to
Shackelford, T. K., & Liddle, J. R. (2014). Understanding and 6-year-old children: A longitudinal study.
the mind from an evolutionary perspective: An over- European Journal of Developmental Psychology, 11,
view of evolutionary psychology. Wiley Interdisciplinary 447–462.
Reviews: Cognitive Science, 5, 247–260. van der Meer, A. L. H., & van der Weel, F. R. (2011).
Shapiro, L. (2009). Making sense of mirror neurons. Auditory guided arm and whole body movements in
Syntheses, 167, 439–456. young infants. In P. Strumillo (Ed.), Advances in
Shimada, S., & Hiraki, K. (2006). Infant’s brain responses sound localization. InTech. http://www.intechopen.
to live and televised action. NeuroImage, 32, c o m / b o o k s / a d va n c e s - i n - s o u n d - l o c a l i z a t i o n /
930–939. auditory-guided-arm-and-whole-body-movements-in-
Smith, L. B., & Thelen, E. (2003). Development as a young-infants
dynamic system. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7, van Geert, P. (2011). The contribution of complex
343–348. dynamic systems to development. Child Development
Sommerville, J. A., Woodward, A. L., & Needham, A. N. Perspectives, 5, 273–278.
(2005). Action experience alters 3-month-old infants’ Warren, W. H. (2006). The dynamics of perception and
perception of others’ actions. Cognition, 96, 1–11. action. Psychological Review, 113, 358–389.
Spencer, J. P., Perone, S., & Buss, A. T. (2011). Twenty Warreyn, P., Ruysschaert, L., Wiersema, J. R., Handl, A.,
years and going strong: A dynamic systems revolution Pattyn, G., & Roeyers, H. (2013). Infants’ mu suppres-
in motor and cognitive development. Child sion during the observation of real and mimicked
Development Perspectives, 5, 260–266. goal-directed actions. Developmental Science, 16,
Spencer, J. P., Perone, S., & Johnson, J. S. (2009). The 173–185.
dynamic field theory and embodied cognitive dynam- Wellsby, M., & Pexman, P. M. (2014). Developing embod-
ics. In J. P. Spencer, M. Thomas, & J. L. McClelland ied cognition: Insights from children’s concepts and
(Eds.), Toward a unified theory of development: language processing. Frontiers in Psychology, 5.
Connectionism and dynamic systems theory reconsid- doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00506.
ered (pp. 86–118). New York: Oxford University Wentworth, N., Benson, J. B., & Haith, M. M. (2000). The
Press. development of infants’ reaches for stationary and
Surian, L., & Geraci, A. (2012). Where will the triangle moving targets. Child Development, 71, 576–601.
look for it? Attributing false belief to a geometric Wiebe, S., Morton, J. B., Buss, A. T., & Spencer, J. P.
shape at 17 months. The British Journal of (2014). The emergent executive: A dynamic field the-
Developmental Psychology, 30, 30–44. ory of the development of executive function.
Szyf, M. (2013). How do environments talk to genes? Monographs of the Society for Research in Child
Nature Neuroscience, 16, 2–4. Development, 79, 1–132.
Tai, Y. F., Scherfler, C., Brooks, D. J., Sawamoto, N., & Wiebe, S., Sheffield, T., Nelson, J. M., Clark, C. A. A.,
Castiello, U. (2004). The human premotor cortex is Chevalier, N., & Espy, K. (2011). The structure of
‘mirror’ only for biological actions. Current Biology, executive function in 3-year-olds. Journal of
14, 117–120. Experimental Child Psychology, 108, 436–452.
Thelen, E. (2008). Grounded in the world: Developmental Wilkinson, N., Paikan, A., Gredebäck, G., Rea, F., &
origins of the embodied mind. In W. F. Overton, Metta, G. (2014). Staring us in the face? An embodied
U. Muller, & J. L. Newman (Eds.), Developmental theory of innate face preference. Developmental
perspectives on embodiment and consciousness Science, 17, 809–825.
(pp. 99–130). New York: Taylor & Francis. Witherington, D. C. (2011). Taking emergence seriously:
Thelen, E., Schöner, G., Scheier, C., & Smith, L. B. The centrality of circular causality for dynamic sys-
(2001). The dynamics of embodiment: A field study of tems approaches to development. Human
infant preservative reaching. Behavior and Brain Development, 54, 66–92.
Sciences, 24, 1–86. Witherington, D. C. (2015). Dynamic systems. In W. F.
Thoermer, C., Sodian, B., Vuori, M., Perst, H., & Kristen, Overton, P. C. M. Molenaar, & R. M. Lerner (Eds.),
S. (2012). Continuity from an implicit to an explicit Handbook of child psychology and developmental sci-
understanding of false belief from infancy to pre- ence (7th ed., Vol. 1). New York: Wiley.
school age. British Journal of Developmental Witherington, D. C., & Heying, S. (2013). Embodiment and
Psychology, 30, 172–187. agency: Toward a holistic synthesis for developmental
Tschacher, W., & Haken, H. (2007). Intentionality in non- science. In R. M. Lerner & J. B. Benson (Eds.), Advances
equilibrium systems? The functional aspects of self- in child development and behavior. Embodiment and
organized pattern formation. New Ideas in Psychology, epigenesis: Theoretical and methodological issues in
25, 1–15. understanding the role of biology within the relational
Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life: Biology, phenomenol- development system. Part A: Philosophical, theoretical,
ogy, and the sciences of mind. Cambridge, MA: and biological dimensions (Vol. 44, pp. 161–192).
Belknap Press/Harvard University Press. Waltham, MA: Academic Press.
References 449

Witherington, D. C., & Margett, T. (2011). How concep- Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
tually unified is the dynamic systems approach to the Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer
study of psychological development? Child Science + Business Media.
Development Perspectives, 5, 286–290. Yu, C., & Smith, L. B. (2013). Joint attention without gaze
Wolff, P. (2007). Representing causation. Journal of following: Human infants and their parents coordinate
Experimental Psychology: General, 136, 82–111. visual attention to objects through eye-hand coordina-
Wood, W., & Eagly, A. H. (2013). Biology or culture tion. PLoS One, 8, e79659. doi:10.1371/journal.
alone cannot account for human sex differences and pone.0079659.
similarities. Psychological Inquiry, 24, 241–247. Zwaan, R. A. (2014). Embodiment and language compre-
Yott, J., & Poulin-Dubois, D. (2012). Breaking the rules: Do hension: Reframing the discussion. Trends in
infants have a true understanding of false belief? British Cognitive Sciences, 18, 229–234.
Journal of Developmental Psychology, 30, 156–171.
Free Will in Behavior: Believing
Makes It So 18

Views
Chapter Introduction
Shields (2014) referred to free will as conscious
Free will is debated endlessly in philosophy, causation and also as causal efficacy of con-
perhaps to little avail, but psychologists study sciousness. It is the ability to initiate or to control
the consequences of believing in it and altering one’s thoughts/actions in a conscious, voluntarily
the belief, which indicates its relevance to the way. One’s self-controlled conscious choices can
daily lives of people. The present chapter contribute significantly to behavior. Events might
considers free will in terms of philosophy, be entirely determined; however, nonlinear neu-
social psychology, neuroscience, developmen- ral mechanisms allow for variable behavior rela-
tal psychology, and evolution. Overall, the tive to those events, in that consciousness is an
chapter emphasizes individual differences in emergent property that can modify the events
free will beliefs and their consequences in leading to it. Volitional action appears to be the
multiple areas of psychological function. Its outcome of a complex, rapid decision-making
origin lies in biological, environmental, and process involving prior decisions and cognitive
self (e.g., personality) factors. As for the study elements. Individuals appear to be able to con-
of the conscious and unconscious influences sciously control their actions.
on behavior and their relationship to free will, Doyle (2013) maintained that we have a
conceptualization and research informs that Macro mind so that we are creative authors and
both are involved in behavior decision-making originators of our ideas. We can evaluate alterna-
and unfolding. tives and, after generating alternatives, fall back
to thinking again so that we avoid the fixed past
and also behave in ways different from those pre-
Philosophy scribed by our Micro mind. For Doyle, first, we
are “free” and, then, we “will.” First, thoughts
The topic of the philosophy of free will has been come “freely” and, then, actions are produced
given more extensive coverage in Chap. 4. In “willfully.”
this chapter, I review some philosophical posi- Kane (2013) also adopted a two-stage model
tions why free will cannot be dismissed outright in free will. Deliberation happens unpredictably,
in psychology. and its outcomes influence the choices that are

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 451


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_18
452 18 Free Will in Behavior: Believing Makes It So

made. Decisions are “torn” rather than being Libet concluded that the initiation of volun-
decided deterministically. The brain is described tary action begins “unconsciously.” In addition,
using the language of nonlinear dynamics. Kane people have a window of conscious veto control
argued that far-from-equilibrium brain states ren- or movement inhibition of about 200 ms between
der the brain sensitive to “micro-indeterminacies” awareness of will and action performance. Libet
at the lower neuronal level. This is accompanied argued that the results refute the common sense
by a temporary “screen-off” of deterministic past notion that free will requires conscious action
influences. Kane (2013) concluded that full con- initiation. Libet argued that the results
sciousness allows the “deep” responsibility asso- demonstrate that although we might not have free
ciated with “genuine” free will. will in the classic sense, they show that we have
For Nahmias (2012), generally, free will is “free won’t”—that is, free will constituted by the
considered the set of capacities for choice and for capacity to control actions consciously via
action control that are essential for agents to vetoes.
demonstrate moral responsibility and blame. However, Nahmias (2012) maintained that (a)
Moreover, from a psychological point of view, the RP onset could correspond to nonconscious
different people will have varying degrees of it, “urges” (Pockett & Purdy, 2011) rather than
thereby exercising it to different degrees. Because intentions or decisions, or, (b) simply, in the
most people believe in free will, and people research, the reporting of consciousness is
develop more autonomy and control as they grow, delayed relative to the presence of conscious
in evaluating other people, we are prone to hold- intention. Nahmias (2012) concluded that con-
ing people responsible for their actions, at least to scious intention does not have to take place prior
varying degrees. Cognitive science can help to action (or neural correlates) in order to caus-
determine the cognitive capacities important in ally influence actions. Rather, as long as con-
free will and to responsible agency, as well as the scious deliberations, plans, and distal intentions
individual differences therein. For example, con- (or the neural correlates involved) have a proper
sciousness or conscious deliberation would effect downstream on actions, conscious causa-
appear to be a requisite for free will, as would tion is taking place. Conscious causation of
intention-formation skills and a capacity for this type could lead to acting according to
moral reasoning. For those scholarly perspectives consciously-considered reasons. For example,
that consider free will as an illusion (e.g., Wegner, Nahmias (2012) indicated that Baumeister,
2002) or otherwise try to explain it away, the con- Masicampo, and Vohs (2011) had provided exam-
clusions offered seem to depend on how free will ples of behaviors being improved by conscious
is defined. reasoning and conscious attention to action.
Libet (1985, 1999, 2001, 2004) conducted the In addition, Mele (2013) provided conceptual
now classic research arguing that the brain and methodological criticisms of the research by
“decides” to prepare to initiate simple motor Libet. For Mele, Libet’s data do not warrant the
actions prior to the person reporting subjective conclusions that conscious decision-making and
awareness of corresponding intention to make the intention are not involved in generating
movement. In Libet, the onset of the readiness behavior.
potential (RP) in scalp EEG (electroencephalo- Countering Libet, Schlosser (2012a) proposed
gram) occurred 550 ms on average before move- that, in motor initiation, the timing of conscious
ment onset, and it also had preceded the mental events is a secondary consideration to the
participants’ reported time of conscious aware- covariations in intentions, reasons, choices, and
ness of the movements involved by 350 ms on actions involved. Every step in a causal chain
average. The RP precedes the awareness of might have unconscious precursors, but the
“intention, desire, or urge” (RP → awareness whole chain might still be reason-responsive.
350 ms later → movement another 150 ms later; Moreover, our conscious intentions might be
Nahmias, 2012). among the various causes of our actions. Having
Philosophy 453

said that, the approach taken by Schlosser does level can be causally efficacious in initiating/
not require that the origin or source of choices guiding relevant basic actions. In support of his
that are made freely need to lie within the person, model, Schlosser (2012b) cited a meta-analysis
or that the person must be a conscious initiator. by Gollwitzer and Sheeran (2006). They found
Schlosser (2012b) examined another model that the formation of “implementation” inten-
critical of free will—that of apparent mental tions (and their changes) affects subsequent per-
causation (Wegner, 2002, 2004, 2005, 2008). In formance and goal attainment (and matching
this model, the conscious self is considered changes in behavior).
spectators or epiphenomena; they do not cause
conscious choice, and are not causally effica- Comment Suarez and Adams (2013) posed the
cious in the initiation and in the guidance of provocative question whether science is compat-
action (see Fig. 18.1). In the apparent causation ible with free will. Much of the book that they
model, we might experience a sense of having wrote deals with quantum physics. Adams and
conscious will in the relation between thought Suarez (2013) maintained that quantum random-
and action. However, the genuine precursor to ness and freedom in behavior are not incompati-
action lies in preceding unconscious causes/ ble. Brain output may exhibit quantum
thoughts. interference effects so that its output might derive
In response to Wegner (2002), Schlosser from “nonmaterial” or “immaterial” agency.
(2012b) posited the “real mental causation” Consciousness might “self-influence” the brain’s
model (see Fig. 18.2). The model distinguishes physiological parameters. Conscious choice,
the subpersonal “realizer” of intentions and the although “causal,” could be “unpredictable.”
intentions. Moreover, intentions can be subverted Uncertainty rather than determinism in behavior
for multiple reasons and so desired actions not prevails due to “free will.” In brief, mental agen-
realized. Therefore, in the model, everything else cies involving consciousness and free will “influ-
being equal, conscious intentions at the personal ence” neurons and “produce” behavior.

Fig. 18.1 Model of apparent Experience of conscious will


mental causation (AMC). The
figure illustrates one model of
unconscious determination of
motor action. Adapted from Thought Apparent causal path Action
Schlosser (2012b), based on
Wegner (2002, p. 68) and
Wegner and Wheatley (1999,
p. 483) Actual causal path

Unconscious
cause of
thought
Actual causal path

Unconscious
path?

Unconscious
cause of
action

Time
454 18 Free Will in Behavior: Believing Makes It So

Intentional match

Intention
Acting
to Act

personal
sub-personal

Realizer Motor control Motor


Movement
of intention system command

Predictor and
comparators

(Other causes of
Sensory feedback
motor output)

Fig. 18.2 Model of real mental causation (RMC). RMC intentional matching process involved. There are other
includes sources of the sense of agency. At the personal components to the action system not necessarily amenable
level, the mental intention to act leads to action with an to consciousness. Adapted from Schlosser (2012b)

I conclude that philosophers who support the existence do not stand up to scrutiny. Libet,
position that free will exists refer to our capacity Gleason, Wright, and Pearl (1983) and Libet
for conscious causation and making independent (1985) had shown that the RP (Bereitschafts
choices. They consider it emergent as the nonlin- potential, BP), as measured by EEG over the pre-
ear dynamical systems approach describes. They supplementary motor cortex (pre-SMA), pre-
relate it to moral responsibility. They view it as ceded by several hundred milliseconds not only a
involving a two-step process, such as blocking voluntary action (moving quickly, in a self-paced
off deterministic influences to be free in thought mode, finger/wrist flexion, or both) but also the
and then choosing willfully. They deny that the time points that participants had reported having
putative research demonstrating that it is inexis- made the conscious decision to act. However,
tent is valid for the question. They describe that multiple methodological critiques of the Libet
individual differences exist in free will. studies query whether the participants were truly
engaging in arriving at free decisions, for exam-
ple, the context of the laboratory could have had
Free Will from a Psychological an influence on the behavior.
Perspective In terms of definition, Bode et al. (2014) noted
the ambiguities prevalent in the field. Therefore,
Free Will Psychology most workers prefer to use terms such as voluntary
action/movement and internal decisions. The
Introduction Bode et al. (2014) tackled the approach taken by Bode et al. concerning this
complex issue of free will from a definitional, imbroglio was to examine the neuroscience under-
philosophical, neuroscientific, and behavioral lying research on free (or voluntary) decisions.
perspective. They noted that believing in free will When participants are asked to self-initiate an
is fundamental to our identity and self-concept. action, neuroimaging techniques (fMRI, func-
Whether it exists has been debated in philosophy tional magnetic resonance imaging; EEG) have
but, experimentally, the arguments against its found an associated network of brain regions,
Free Will from a Psychological Perspective 455

mostly in the medial prefrontal cortex (PFC), decision-making system. However, the person’s
including the pre-SMA/SMA and the rostral past history, values, motivation, etc., also contrib-
cingulate zone, the posterior parietal cortex (PPC, ute to the system. Because the system is a dynamic
especially the lateral regions of the PFC and PPC), network, it can arrive at emergent states that are
and the basal ganglia. The “default mode” network unpredictable from the collection of components
also has been implicated. Using multivariate pat- constituting it. It is especially in this sense that
tern classification analysis (MVPA) and ultra high- decisions might be emergent and free, and reflect
field fMRI, Soon, Brass, Heinze, and Haynes the person’s free choice as much as or more than
(2008) and Bode et al. (2011) demonstrated that any one putative deterministic influence.
decisions relating to pressing one or two buttons at The next section of the chapter on free will
a time of the participants’ choosing could be pre- examines the consequences of believing in it, or
dicted a full seven seconds before the reported time not, and most people do believe in it. Moreover,
of consciously deciding according to the activity of there are individual differences in this regard.
the medial prefrontal and medial posterior parietal These types of statements are based on excellent
cortex, with other findings related to the anterior research, and so they are not an illusion.
prefrontal cortex. Soon, He, Bode, and Haynes
(2013) found similar results in making abstract
decisions about adding or subtracting numbers. Belief in Free Will
The authors concluded that consciousness of
Model Baumeister et al. (2011) separated the
all these types of decisions for simple choices
psychological questions about free will and the
happens after their unconscious decision-making.
philosophical ones. First, although research
However, this does not mean that it has been dem-
shows that people who believe in free will end up
onstrated that more complex decisions cannot
with the belief affecting their behavior, research
include a free, conscious volitional component.
such as this cannot address the philosophical
Whether simple or complex, all decisions are sus-
question of whether free will really exists. That
ceptible to contextual influence. Therefore, deci-
said, even though most people believe in free
sions at any level might involve a process of
will, in psychological experiments, the belief can
“evidence accumulation,” or of integrating—the
be manipulated (Nahmias, Morris, Nadelhoffer,
probability of stimuli; external context; internal
& Turner, 2005; Vohs & Schooler, 2008).
environment; expectations, or associated factors
The research on belief in free will includes
values; past stimuli and experiences; personal his-
experimental studies (Alquist, Ainsworth, &
tory/past cues, choices, and actions; internal moti-
Baumeister, 2013; Baumeister, 2008; Baumeister
vation, preferences, and attitudes; and so on. In
& Brewer, 2012). For example, in experiments on
decision-making, all these factors serve to create
an embodied dynamical decision state network. free will, participants are induced to believe
As long as cues are relevant, even if they are weak, either less or more in free will, and dependent
unconscious, or unattended, potentially, they can measures are examined for effects of the change
influence decision-making. By arriving at a better in belief, such as being more antisocial or less
understanding “hidden” cognitive systems, a bet- conforming. There are numerous behavioral
ter understanding of the “personal” component of effects of believing in free will, in not believing
“free” decision-making will emerge. in it, or having the belief manipulated.
Vohs and Schooler (2008) initiated the latter
type of research and found that inducing disbelief
Comment The model of decision-making in
in free will resulted in participants not only cheat-
Bode et al. (2014) allows for voluntary action and
ing but also lying and stealing! Baumeister,
interval decision-making in movements. All lev-
Masicampo, and DeWall (2009) found that it
els of the relevant control system components
caused aggressive behavior (giving unwelcome
need to be described, as well as all aspects of the
hot sauce in food). It reduced volunteer behavior
environment that contribute to the dynamical
456 18 Free Will in Behavior: Believing Makes It So

(Stillman & Baumeister, 2010). It appears that However, in daily life, the complexities of
free will belief reduction makes people less believing in free will lead to various subtle
inclined to expend effort, affecting their motiva- findings that make it difficult to state with suffi-
tion and self-control. cient precision its causal role in behavior except
That is, belief in free will has powerful conse- that individual differences abound and have per-
quences in the daily lives of people, and not tinent consequences. Before reviewing the
believing in it takes away its potential positive research on the latter matter in this regard, I
effects. In this regard, Nichols (2011) reported examine the issue of lay beliefs on free will. Do
that when asked about concrete cases of wrong- they differ from academic ones? Then, I look at
doing that were highly affective, people who the relationship between free will and confor-
were manipulated toward believing in determin- mity. Does the belief lead to more or less
ism still maintained that wrongdoers have agency conformity?
and are morally culpable. This is a compatibilist
response—people believe that we are responsible
for our actions of this moral kind even if they Lay Belief
believe that the universe is determined.
Miles (2013a, 2013b) criticized the Model Laypeople struggle with understanding
Baumiesterian approach to free will, and Vonasch of free will. Baumeister and Brewer (2012) noted
and Baumeister (2013) ably responded. The that Monroe and Malle (2010) asked university
exchange is beyond the scope of the present work. students open-ended questions on what it means
Essentially, Vonasch and Baumeister summarized to have free will. Responses especially involved
that free will belief is associated with greater defining free will as having choice, doing things
empathy, support for social mobility, desire for to fulfill personal desires, and not submitting to
SES (socioeconomic status) equality, and belief coercion or external pressure. Stillman,
that the working poor’s poverty is not a fate. Baumeister, and Mele (2011) studied the ques-
Several recent papers have related free will tion by asking people to describe their actions
belief to retribution for committed transgres- either done or not done with free will. Analysis of
sions. Shariff et al. (2014) found that reducing the data revealed that, for the layperson, behaving
free will belief led people to be less retributive in with free will involved the following themes:
their punishment attitudes. They implied that reaches goal; achieves positive outcome; works
weakening free will belief lessened belief in toward long-term/distal goal; decides on basis of
moral responsibility and also in seeing “bad” conscious, deliberate thought, or reflection;
behavior as morally reprehensible. The studies behaves according to moral values; resists exter-
involved functioned to move the participants nal influences/overcomes obstacles; and avoids
toward a more mechanistic view of human behav- harming the person’s social group.
ior. Monroe, Dillon, and Malle (2014) found that Most laypeople report believing in free will,
people’s judgment of free will and blame were but in a naïve compatibilist way, in that they also
clearly related to agents’ choice capacity. express some belief in determinism (Nahmias
et al., 2005). Sarkissian et al. (2010) also found
Comment Relative to correlational research, that the majority believes in free will, including
experiments better ensure that causality can be in many different cultures.
addressed for an issue. Belief in free will research Kuhl and Quirin (2011) referred to a model of
uses experimental manipulations to show the free will that does not mean freedom “from”
power of the belief. The belief is strong enough causal determination, but to freedom “of” self-
to allow for findings of a compatibilist nature— determination (e.g., Baumeister, 2008; Pinker,
the universe might be deterministically caused 2008). Volitional freedom lies on a continuum of
but free will still has a role to play in behavior, different psychological systems or functional lev-
especially of the moral responsible kind. els, from habits to global personal goals (self-
Free Will from a Psychological Perspective 457

determined behavior). In this regard, Shepherd condition, an anti-free will condition, or a control
(2012) demonstrated that, in folk psychology, condition, with a fourth condition in the second
appreciating behavior as consciously caused study involving manipulation of “meaning
evokes judgments that free will is involved in an threat.” The pro-free will and anti-free will con-
agent’s actions. Knobe et al. (2012) added that ditions were based on the study by Vohs and
free will is attributed in cases that are more “real Schooler (2008). In the latter study, participants
and personal” (even when behavior is were exposed passively to statements that either
determined). supported or denied free will. Alquist et al.
(2013) modified this procedure by having the
Comment Folk psychology appears to have participants actively read the sentences and
developed concepts similar to those of some in rewrite them in their own words. An example of
philosophy and psychology. The debate on the a pro-free will statement is “I have free will to
existence of free will is hotly contested academi- control my actions and, ultimately, to control my
cally, but, in contrast, the typical layperson acts destiny in life.” An example of an anti-free will
according to deeply held personal beliefs. statement is “Science has demonstrated that free
will is an illusion.” In these experiments, the con-
formity measure involved rating art work after
Conformity having seen different opinions of it that were
written by the experimenters independent of the
Model Believing in free will reduces conform- actual quality of the work (and unknown to the
ing (Alquist et al., 2013), and it increases job per- participants).
formance and expectations of work success The results showed that participants who were
(Stillman et al., 2010; Stillman et al., 2011, exposed to anti-free will statements conformed
respectively). These results are found even after significantly more in their artwork ratings com-
possible confounds are controlled (e.g., in the pared to participants in the other two conditions
two studies, controlled, respectively, were—work (that is, the pro-free will condition and control
ethic/life satisfaction, and intelligence/personal- condition). Similar results were found in the sec-
ity traits/locus of control). ond study, but this time it controlled for “mean-
Alquist et al. (2013) investigated the relation- ing threat” and used a different measure of
ship between disbelief in free will and social con- conformity, that of generating predictable or
formity. They used both correlational and novel names for products.
experimental research. In their correlational Alquist et al. (2013) concluded that believing
study, Alquist et al. (2013) examined the associa- in free will contributes to resisting pressures and
tion between the FAD-Plus’s scale of free will temptations to conform and also it contributes to
(Free Will and Determinism Plus Scale; Paulhus autonomy and action. People who believe in free
& Carey, 2011) and a conformity scale. The will think more for themselves and, also, they
FAD-Plus consists of seven items related to free will depart more from social pressures and
will (with 21 others on three other factors—sci- expected norms. In contrast, not believing in free
entific determinism, fatalistic determinism, and will leads to lower motivation to engage in exer-
unpredictability). They found a correlation tion of mental effort. They noted that, among lay-
between the scales such that those individuals persons, free will is considered to involve making
who scored higher in free will belief scored lower choices based on self-directed thoughts and val-
in conformity. This illustrates that individual dif- ues rather than based on external forces (Monroe
ferences in the degree of belief in free will influ- & Malle, 2010).
ence social behavior, such as conformity.
As for their two experiments, Alquist et al. Comment It is intriguing to note that Alquist
(2013) assigned participants to a pro-free will et al. (2013) emphasized that free will involves
458 18 Free Will in Behavior: Believing Makes It So

having a sense of making the right choice, but that appears to be a distinct trait. Nevertheless, it
the seven items in Paulhus and Carey’s (2011) correlates positively with a range of variables,
scale on free will do not include anything about such as satisfaction and self-control.
choice. They include the concepts of control, Baumeister and Brewer (2012) concluded
responsibility, and strength of mind/overcoming, their review by indicating that free will belief is
as well as having free will. I return below to the associated with a prosocial/procultural attitude.
issue of creating a better free will questionnaire. In contrast, its disbelief is associated with disre-
Believing in free will has consequences for gard of societal norms and rules. Also, it is asso-
being less conforming in nature and for resisting ciated with personal agency, while its disbelief is
conformity. At the same time, in manipulating associated with passivity, indifference, and so on.
the belief, consequences for conformity in Research in judging others demonstrates that
thought and in behavior arise. Of course, some greater belief in free will leads to giving lighter
people do not believe in free will and many peo- prison sentences (Carey & Paulhus, 2011; Shariff
ple cannot deploy effectively their free will et al., 2014). However, high free will belief is
belief. I discuss ways of repairing these difficul- associated with low criminal forgiveness,
ties in the context of therapy for addictions in although the opposite seems to apply to forgiving
Chap. 20. relationship partners (respectively, Shariff et al.,
In the following, I address the consequences 2014; Crescioni, Baumeister, Ainsworth, Ent, &
of believing in free will according to correla- Lambert, 2015). Free will belief is related to
tional research seeking individual differences. As holding people responsible for their actions, and
with any correlational research, causation cannot manipulating it to be lower leads to more willing-
be established, but the patterns are consistent ness to forgive others (Brewer, 2011).
with the notion that variations in free will belief Another area studied in relation to free will
lead to variations in consequences. belief is on beliefs, attitudes, and thoughts of the
self. Crescioni et al. (2015) found that free will
belief correlated with more gratitude, finding life
Individual Differences as meaningful and being more satisfied and hav-
ing less life stress, as well as with perceived self-
Introduction efficacy and with relationship variables
(relationship commitment, and partner forgive-
Disbelief in free will, or the induction of this ness, but not with all positive variables, e.g., it
belief, has a host of consequences, such as engag- did not correlate with empathy). Other research
ing in less helping of others and lesser work qual- implicates belief in free will being associated
ity (e.g., Baumeister et al., 2009). Believing in with ways of avoiding harming others (Alquist,
free will varies and the degree of belief in free Ainsworth, Baumeister, Daly, & Stillman, 2015),
will is associated with variables such as having learning lessons from past guilt-inducing actions
self-control. (Stillman & Baumeister, 2010), and developing
long-term goals (Crescioni et al., 2015).
As for other traits, the associations of belief in
Model free will with other personality variables include
extraversion and agreeableness (Paulhus & Carey,
Baumeister and Brewer (2012) reviewed the lit- 2011), as well as conscientiousness, emotional
erature on individual differences in belief in free stability, and openness to experience (Stillman
will, or its disbelief, in relation to subjective cor- et al., 2011). Internal locus of control generally
relates and consequences. They noted that, gen- correlates with it (e.g., Paulhus & Carey, 2011;
erally, free will belief shows no or modest Stillman et al., 2011). Paulhus and Carey (2011)
correlations with other variables, so that it related it to right-wing authoritarianism, Brewer
Individual Differences 459

and Baumeister (2010) to self-control, and 2011) to evaluate whether individual differences
Crescioni et al. (2015) to self-efficacy. in free will belief predicted mastery-approach
Research has demonstrated that the induction motivation, as measured by three items on the
of a disbelief in free will changes EEG recordings Achievement Goal Questionnaire (Elliot &
that correlate with preconscious motor prepara- McGregor, 2001). Free will was measured using
tion (Rigoni, Kühn, Sartori, & Brass, 2011). The seven items on the free will scale of the FAD-
readiness potential of the readings at more than Plus. Control variables included demographics,
one second before participants took the decision acculturation, as measured by Tsai, Ying, and
consciously to move was reduced in those indi- Lee’s (2000) General Ethnicity Questionnaire (25
viduals who had read an excerpt from a book items), and an individualism-collectivism scale
implying that free will is an illusion. Indeed, it is (13 items), as measured by a scale in Kim and
noteworthy for present purposes that the degree Cho (2011). Questionnaires were administered in
of disbelief in free will reported in a questionnaire a standard order: FAD-Plus, individual-collectiv-
correlated with the amplitude of the readiness ism, acculturation, and motivation.
potentials in question in the experimental group. For purposes of the data analysis, alpha was
Alquist et al. (2015) demonstrated that indi- set at 0.01 because of the multiple analyses
vidual differences in (and experimental manipu- involved. The results showed that, in the univer-
lation of) free will belief were related to sity students, free will belief predicted degree of
counterfactual thinking. They concluded that free master-approach motivation, but only at a trend
will belief relates positively to counterfactual level (p < 0.05).
thinking, which allows for multiple possible out- Specifically, the multiple regression analysis
comes and runs counter to deterministic views of that was conducted was hierarchical and, first, it
the origins of behavior. entered demographic variables, with the individ-
ualism/collectivism and acculturation data
entered next. Demographic factors did predict
Comment mastery-approach, while the cultural variables
did not add to the predictive accuracy. Finally, in
Although most people believe in free will, the the last step, free will belief, as measured by the
variation in the strength of the belief has impor- FAD-Plus, was found to predict mastery-
tant consequences, as shown by the growing lit- approach motivation above and beyond the other
erature on the question. The research is expanding factors controlled, but only at the trend level, as
to study individual differences in free will belief indicated.
related both to brain activity and to critical con-
cepts related to free will, such as counterfactual Comment We can conclude believing in free
thinking. Based on this type of research, we real- will might have some consequences for motiva-
ized that there has been little research on individ- tion to study in university students, although fur-
ual differences related to student motivation, and ther research is needed. Aside from replicated
so Yang (2013) conducted the following study. this study with larger and different samples, it
should be determined whether the variations in
free will belief and motivation correspond to
Motivation
variation in course grades.
In the next portion of the chapter, the focus
Study For her Bachelor of Arts thesis under my
shifts to a topic related to free will, that of con-
supervision, Yang (2013) conducted a study of
sciousness. One would think that we are quite
free will belief in relation to mastery-approach
conscious in our behavior, but much of it takes
goal orientation. Undergraduates (N = 179, mostly
place automatically or unconsciously. Moreover,
female, of varied cultural background) were
the two modes of thought work in concert.
administered the FAD-Plus (Paulhus & Carey,
460 18 Free Will in Behavior: Believing Makes It So

Consciousness Baumeister et al. (2011) also found that con-


scious causation of behavior is typically evident
Introduction in situations involving multiple possibilities,
such as in deliberating multiple possible courses
Baumeister and Bargh are leaders in the field in of action. Consciousness enables the person to
the study of unconscious, conscious, and their mentally simulate nonpresent realities, including
relation to free will. In the following, I discuss possible sequences of future events. The research
their work; each shows that conscious and uncon- has not established definitely whether the act of
scious processes collaborate in behavioral choosing is conscious or unconscious—but deci-
unfolding. sions based on conscious thought should be more
effective when considering what each possible
action will produce and also whether associated
Baumeister downstream consequences are desirable.
Most important, consciousness is especially
Model Baumeister and Masicampo (2010) useful in communication (Baumeister &
argued that consciousness is best considered a Masicampo, 2010), for example, in sharing infor-
place in which the unconscious acts to construct mation and coordinating joint performance.
meaningful sequences of thought. They linked Conscious thinking helps to facilitate talking. In
this notion to evidence, for example, that the this regard, Baumeister, Masicampo, and Vohs
unconscious functions to process single words (2015) contended that consciousness serves not
but not sentences and paragraphs (e.g., Baars, only in reflection/reasoning and elaborating sense
2002). Likewise, logical reasoning deteriorates of self, but also it serves to integrate information,
sharply when consciousness is preoccupied and, thereby helping to resolve conflict. Consciousness
in contrast, it improves when consciousness is is associated with advanced thinking, and it facili-
engaged (DeWall, Baumeister, & Masicampo, tates social communication, cooperation, and col-
2008). Logical reasoning requires putting lective planning/learning, as well as even teaching.
together complex sequences of ideas while ruling It allows for thinking and complex sentences and
out other possible sequences, and that may too logic instead of the use of simple words and
big a task to do effectively without a role for con- thoughts. It enables thoughts as complex as those
sciousness, as well. associated with laws and causal theories.
Baumeister et al. (2011) reported key themes
from their survey of experimental findings on Comment The work by Baumeister and col-
conscious causation. They included the follow- leagues on conscious causation, in particular,
ing: Conscious thoughts integrate across time; constitutes a powerful demonstration of the real-
that is, conscious thought permits the deliberate ity and efficacy of conscious thought because
combining of past and future into causing present their review of research considered only ones
behavior, as well as helping present cognitions to involving experimental manipulations. Conscious
cause future behavior, and probably other and unconscious thought work together toward
combinations. optimal adaptation. That it has been shown to
Conscious thought also appears to help trans- exist offers support to the notion that free will
late abstract principles into specific behaviors, exists, as well. [For a longer description of this
such as abstract moral principles, legal rules, eco- work by Baumeister on conscious causation, see
nomic calculations, and application of scientific Chap. 20].
and mathematical principles. The unconscious In the next portion of the chapter, I examine
benefits form abstract principles in guiding the work of Bargh and colleagues, who have also
behavior. shown that conscious and unconscious thought
Consciousness 461

work in concert. In this sense, even the work that moreover, they are underlain by anatomical con-
emphasizes the role of unconscious processes in nectivity (e.g., in the insula for physical warmth/
thought leaves room for free will as a valid part of coldness and social warmth/coldness; Kang,
behavioral causation. Williams, Clark, Gray, & Bargh, 2011). (b)
Ontogenetically, early sensorimotor experiences
contribute, as described above. (c) Also, lan-
Bargh guage affords the semantic acquisition of meta-
phors that strengthen the associations (e.g., he’s a
Model Bargh, Schwader, Hailey, Dyer, and “cold” person).
Boothby (2012) highlighted the ubiquity of auto- In the area of moral judgments, even here an
maticity in social-cognitive processes, especially in innate, hard-wire basis has been proposed, one
childhood. Automaticity in this sense refers to effi- that includes automatic processes. For example,
cient and unintentional social-cognitive processes research has found that manipulations of time
that operate out of conscious awareness. The constraints and cognitive load, which impair con-
authors countered the standard view that conscious trolled processes but not automatic ones, serve to
and effortful skill acquisition precedes and sets the affect utilitarian (benefit/cost) analysis but not
stage for higher-order conscious processes. In con- rule-based moral judgments (Greene, Morelli,
trast, rather than needing extensive practice and Lowenberg, Nystrom, & Cohen, 2008; Suter &
experience to become automatic after their acquisi- Hertwig, 2011).
tion consciously, they might emerge innately or The areas of motivation and goal pursuit also
very early in development as automatic. have been fruitful in elucidating a role for uncon-
Bargh et al. (2012) distinguished between pre- scious processes. In the latter the same executive
conscious and postconscious (goal-dependent) function and working memory resources are
automaticity. The former is generated from recruited as needed in their conscious unfolding
effortless, triggering sensory/perceptual activity, (e.g., Dijksterhuis & Aarts, 2010). For example,
which might input into/activate conscious mental Hassin (2008) and Hassin, Bargh, and Zimerman
processes. The latter is dependent on prior or (2009) found that the nonconscious operation of
concurrent conscious/intentional/motivated men- an achievement goal increased working memory
tal activity, including in attention, cognition, and capacity on standard executive function tasks.
decision-making. These two types or domains of Marien, Custers, Hassin, and Aarts (2012) found
activity work in tandem. that subliminally priming goals (e.g., academic
A good example of automaticity research lies performance) diverted attentional capacity away
in the area of embodiment studies. For instance, from an ongoing conscious task (e.g.,
holding a warm beverage container activates a proofreading).
sense of social warmth (Williams & Bargh, Bargh et al. (2012) noted that individuals lack-
2008). Social rejection causes social pain and ing in awareness of pursuing nonconsciously
distress, thereby activating the same brain regions operating goals could engage in self-deception in
associated with physical pain (Eisenberger, describing them. For example, Bargh, Lee-Chai,
Lieberman, & Williams, 2003). Early sensorimo- Barndollar, Gollwitzer, and Trötschel (2001)
tor experience serves as a foundation for later found that nonconsciously pursuing a coopera-
abstract development (Williams, Huang, & tive goal did not lead to self-report of how much
Bargh, 2009; also Piaget, see Young, 2011). cooperation had taken place. Bar-Anan, Wilson,
and Hassin (2010) found that people misattribute
Mechanisms Bargh et al. (2012) described three behaviors driven by nonconscious goals to other
mechanisms contributing to embodiment effects. reasons that were plausible; consciously accessi-
(a) Phylogenetically, associative connections ble and erroneous self-understandings such as
evolved due to their adaptive significance and, these could have long-term consequences.
462 18 Free Will in Behavior: Believing Makes It So

Table 18.1 Automatic processes observed in infancy/early childhood


Domain Summary of findings
Objects Infants (i.e., under 12 months) comprehend that objects, but not substances, are solid (i.e., two
objects cannot occupy the same space at the same time) and that objects are cohesive (i.e., they
persist as single entities; Hespos & van Marle, 2012)
Numbers Infants appear to possess a core system that represents small quantities as individual objects.
They have a second system to represent quantities as approximate numerical values (Feigenson,
Dehaene, & Spelke, 2004)
Space Infants express sensitivity to distance, angles, and direction. They can use both egocentric and
allocentric frames of reference to navigate spatial environments (Vasilyeva & Lourenco, 2012)
Agents Infants organize the actions of agents in terms of the goals of the agents goals (Woodward, 2009)
Social evaluation Infants prefer prosocial agents to antisocial ones (Hamlin & Wynn, 2011)
False beliefs Children younger than 4 years do not verbally express knowledge of an agent’s false belief, yet
infants younger than that show false-belief understanding when tested with looking-time or
other implicit measures (Baillargeon, Scott, & He, 2010; Perner & Roessler, 2012)
Priming Priming can induce social behavior in toddlers and young children. For example, it can induce
helping in 18-month-olds (Over & Carpenter, 2009a). Also, it can induce affiliative imitation
following social exclusion in 5-year-olds (Over & Carpenter, 2009b)
Implicit attitudes By 12 months of age, infants can distinguish faces differing by gender and race (Pascalis et al.,
2011). By 5 years of age, children show implicit racial attitudes that are identical to those of
adults (Dunham, Baron, & Banaji, 2006)
Adapted from Bargh et al. (2012)

Development As for the development of auto- Both Together Nordgren, Bos, and Dijksterhuis
matic and unconscious psychological processes (2011) proposed an integrated model in which
in infancy and early childhood, Bargh et al. both conscious and unconscious thought pro-
(2012) reviewed the literature on (a) objects/ cesses could be involved in complex decision-
numbers/space, (b) agents/social evaluation/false making, and noted that the decisions are better
beliefs, and (c) priming/implicit attitudes (see when this happens. For a similar and more gen-
Table 18.1). For point (a), the research indicates eral perspective, see Hassin (2013).
that infants possess early sensitivities, under- As for Bargh et al. (2012) in this regard, they
standing, and core representations. For (b), oth- concluded that unconscious processes can cause
ers’ goals are understood, prosocial others are conscious ones, which in turn activate uncon-
preferred and, eventually, the ability to navigate scious ones (also Baumeister & Bargh, 2014; for
false-belief tasks develops. For (c), priming can a full review of this publication, see the next
induce helping in toddlers (Over & Carpenter, chapter, Chap. 20). Bargh et al. (2012) agreed
2009a, 2009b) and, also, the basis for implicit with Baumeister and Masicampo (2010) that
attitudes is set in early facial discrimination unconscious processes are the primary causal
skills. triggers in social behavior, but with conscious
ones important, too. In this regard, Briñol and
Unconscious First About the topic of goal- DeMarree (2012) have demonstrated that the lat-
dependent automaticity, Dijksterhuis and ter can change and redirect the former in
Nordgren (2006) proposed the “unconscious interplay.
thought” theory, which suggests that decisions According to Bargh et al. (2012), free will in
made unconsciously are superior in quality rela- philosophy refers to an “original, uncaused
tive to consciously-made ones. The research by cause.” However, in psychology, it refers to a
Bargh (2011) supports the theory to a degree, as causal role for conscious thought. The authors
that does that of Ham and colleagues, in areas concluded that the evidence supports the exis-
such as justice and morality (Ham & van den Bos, tence of conscious thought. They repeated that
2010; Ham, van den Bos, & van Doorn, 2009). unconscious and conscious thought work together.
Consciousness 463

Comment I add that there are some questions are those that are separate and parallel instead of
that Bargh et al. (2012) have not addressed that integrated. The unconscious mode of reasoning
seem worth pursuing, especially related to free might be more protracted so that, because its
will. For example, to what degree does free will influence is not perceived or made aware, we are
participate in conscious thought and thereby influ- left with the impression that our conscious rea-
ence unconscious thought, given their reciprocity? soning had been instantaneous and free in decid-
How exactly does it participate moment to moment ing, when this has not been the case.
in the causal chain from stimulus to response, in Graziano (2013) proposed a theory of con-
the steps of stimulus selection, executive work on sciousness that differs from those of Libet (e.g.,
the stimuli selected, including in planning and Libet, 1985) and others, who deny its capacity to
decision-making, and response execution and influence behavior. Consciousness refers to both
monitoring, given its reciprocity with unconscious information of which we are aware and the pro-
thought? Indeed, how does consciousness become cess of awareness of it. Through attention
conscious? schema, we build not only models of others’
Bargh and colleagues’ work on the uncon- attention but also of our own. Awareness is asso-
scious refers to developmental processes, in this ciated with the temporo-parietal junction and the
regard. One way of addressing the developmental superior temporal sulcus. It allows the brain to
aspect of conscious vs. unconscious thought and construct descriptors of awareness.
their collaboration is to examine their develop- The processes of being aware and of attending
ment from early intuitive to later logical thought, engage in a positive feedback loop. Although
for example, in the Neo-Piagetian perspective, as attention is considered an active process, aware-
I have done (Young, 2011). In particular, I ness is not but, because of their link, awareness
reworked the concept of different types of thought can become an “active controller” in directing,
(Type/System I; conscious, slow, deliberate; enhancing, suppressing, and guiding each of sig-
Type/System II; unconscious, fast, automatic) nals, choices, and actions. Awareness can actu-
into a Neo-Piagetian developmental framework, ally “cause,” thus, awareness is a phenomenon
and the model speaks to the differences in uncon- that has the capacity to alter its focus, shaping
scious and conscious thought processes and how brain processes to control behavior. To conclude,
they develop (see Chap. 32). Graziano’s (2013) attention schema theory allows
consciousness to have control over behavior.
Fingelkurts, Fingelkurts, Bagnato, Boccagni,
Others and Galardi (2012) argued that consciousness
does not have to have an isomorphic or reduc-
Awareness Pallar and Suzuki (2014) maintained tionist relationship to brain processes (see
that conscious awareness emanates from the Fig. 18.3). Instead, consciousness could be an
reciprocal exchange of information over multiple “emergent” phenomenon in which changes in it
brain regions. Consciousness is constituted by can take place without corresponding constitutive
the exchange of complex information in this changes in lower-order neural phenomena.
manner. It is richer when it involves more neuro-
nal connections/regions. Self-awareness takes Comment Neuronally, consciousness has been
place this way, and it facilitates modeling and related to attentional and awareness mechanisms,
predicting not only of our own behavior but also as well as to emergence. Once more, the ground
that of others (e.g., of our attention and intention, is laid for free will (as an emergent, aware, atten-
and also that of others). tional process) as part of conscious thought. Keep
Conscious reasoning involves coordinating in mind (no pun intended), however, that uncon-
information associated with multiple brain scious thoughts are still important and positive
sources. Unconscious influences on reasoning components of our thought, as per the following.
464 18 Free Will in Behavior: Believing Makes It So

Isomorphism
Mind

OST

Brain Emergentism
Physical
World

Fig. 18.3 Different levels in brain–mind organization their underlying microphysical properties (brain opera-
relations. OST indicates the operational space-time of the tional architectonics). Emergentism, on the other hand,
brain. In this model, the OST level represents a constitu- usually allows for changes of higher-order phenomena
tive mechanism of phenomenal consciousness and ties the (brain operational architectonics) that need not possess a
phenomenal (subjective) and neurophysiological (physi- one-on-one, direct linkage with changes at any underlying
cal) levels together. Isomorphism might be taken to mean lower-order levels (internal physical space-time of the
that there cannot be change in the arrangement of higher- brain). Adapted from Fingelkurts et al. (2012)
order phenomena (phenomenal mind) without changing

Hidden Kraft and Pressman (2012) demon- The results showed that mean heart rate during
strated the influence of a positive psychological the stress-recovering period was highest in the
frame on stress reactivity, even if it is induced neutral condition, whether compared to the smile
manipulatively and remains out of awareness. conditions or the aware/nonaware conditions,
They studied 18- to 25-year-old university stu- with the results still significant while controlling
dents. Participants were trained to activate either covariates such as perceived stress. The Duchenne
(a) a sincere, genuine, or broad (Duchenne) smile was particularly advantageous in stress
smile, by activating the zygomatic major and recovering. Kraft and Pressman (2012) concluded
orbicularis oculi muscles, or (b) a more con- that “grinning and bearing it” could have advan-
tained smile (zygomatic major muscle only). tage in stress regulation. The positive affect gen-
There were three conditions (Duchenne smile, erated might have positive effects physiologically
standard smile, neutral), with half of the partici- as well as psychologically, in addition to its
pants for the smile groups told to smile during inhibitory effect on negative affect and the latter’s
the instruction period. potentially deleterious consequences for health.
The participants were asked to grip chopsticks The study of causation has become more
in their mouths by mimicking the teeth-gripping important in psychological and psychiatric
behavior of a research assistant. In the neutral approaches to behavioral difficulties. At the same
group, the chopsticks were held downward (ver- time, the hoped-for progress in understanding eti-
tically). In the standard smile group, the chop- ology of disease in the medical field has not
sticks were held downward, but also with reached the levels aspired to. For example,
zygomatic major muscle activation. In the Axmacher (2013) examined the hidden world of
Duchenne group, the chopsticks were held hori- causation in one branch of mental health that is
zontally, and with the two indicated muscle controversial—psychoanalysis. The Freudian
groups activated. Heart rate was measured at base account is that psychic material repressed into
line and during two stress-inducing tasks (star the unconscious is inaccessible but still an impor-
tracing, cold pressor). Changes in positive and tant driver of behavior. Axmacher (2013) argued
negative affect also were measured. The resting that unconscious processes can be revealed in
period after each stressor lasted 5 min, and they therapy partly by offering hypotheses that elicit
did not include the chopstick holding. “surprise” in the patient.
Development of Free Will 465

I note that it would seem that the therapist who causation of genes and environment people are
proposes a psychoanalytic hypothesis is suggest- still free to make choices despite constraints and
ing something akin to a counterfactual–manipu- limitations imposed by biology and context.
lationist intervention. In this sense, even the Neurodevelopment is a lifelong sequential
obscure psychodynamic processes involved in unfolding guided not only by genotype but also
unconscious repression might be amenable to by environmental exposures, which might be ran-
understanding by an interventionist account. dom and, moreover, which might be ones that we
Also, neuroscience is helping to understand and choose. This type of theorizing provides a mech-
even update Freudian metatheory. anism for understanding the origins of free will.
We do not need to treat people “as if” they
Comment The issue of nonconscious processes have free will because they do, although we do
in the causation of behavior is a critical one (e.g., need to treat children that way. Free will derives
Bargh et al., 2012). However, the degree to which from variations in cognitive structure due to neu-
its contemporary study is investigating the rodevelopmental adaptation. Therefore, free will,
Freudian approach to the unconscious seems paradoxically, is “neurogenetically determined.”
minimal. Nevertheless, there would appear to be Brain development unfolds stochastically (in
room for its inclusion in neuroscientific study. response to randomness) in a way that makes
The unconscious might be hidden, but through each of us self-determined. The freedom does not
its automaticity, it allows the chunking needed to originate in the randomness. Rather, our brains
deal with the complexity of rapid, online adaptiv- capitalize on it and, along with biological param-
ity. Moreover, even the repression into the uncon- eters, lead us to develop as individual, free selves.
scious that might take place with “intra-psychic” Genes influence us but are in interaction with
conflicts might be adaptive, at least in the short the environment. Moreover, we can choose to
term. The unconscious is not merely the seat of select and alter our environment, accentuating
the primitive. Rather, it is the workhorse of our our uniqueness. Unpredictability frames genes in
thought and needs to work seamlessly with the context, so that behavior is an attempt to control
conscious to causally effect adaptive behavioral unpredictability. But this does not say the same
outcomes. thing as behavior is deterministic. It can vary, for
The following section of the chapter switches example, according to belief in free will.
gears back to the topic of free will, but from a Believing that people have free will does not
developmental perspective. Free will might be a deny causality, which is multi-dimensional. But
critical focus of human activity and development. causality in behavior does not deny autonomy,
which is real for us, and is a paradoxically emer-
gent phenomenon deriving from our genome-
guided neurodevelopmental program.
Development of Free Will
The brain builds itself, or its multineuronal
complex and hierarchical networks, through self-
Model
assembly or self-organization. The neurons con-
verse, cross-talk, and self-construct without
Goldman (2012) introduced a novel theory of
superordinate guides helping them but, instead,
free will couched in neurogenetics. The latter is a
with a constant, nuanced and subtle adjustment,
deterministic point of view, but proposes that,
adaptation, refinement, regulation, and feedback
nevertheless, the brain is capable of freely choos-
looping. As a result, unique circuitry develops in
ing. Each of us is not only neurogenetically
the brain. Moreover, individuality is amplified by
determined but also neurogenetically individual,
the (free) choices that we make, because they act
including in our brains and personalities, so our
to help shape our brains.
DNA entails allowing us freedom. This is not a
Our brains are plastic as they develop.
paradoxical state of affairs—determinism and
Neurons are dynamically interconnected, shaped,
freedom co-existing—because in the web of
466 18 Free Will in Behavior: Believing Makes It So

and being shaped by neighbors, with the same Evolution


reciprocal shaping applying to superordinate
neural networks. In self-organization, minor Model
inputs to the system can lead to chaotic or major
changes, as in the so-called butterfly effect. Baumeister, Crescioni, and Alquist (2011)
Globally, the system still is determined in this described that four forms of behavior evolved
effect, although it appears random at first when sequentially to increase the capacity to behave as
we see the small differences in perturbations that if we had free will. First, initiative evolved to
lead to the disproportionate cascade. Note that actively guide motivation and behavior. Then,
the new and old state of the system can be char- nascent ability for self-control emerged (overrid-
acterized as attractors, and their basins “tamp” or ing a response or impulse in order to act in a dif-
help control the unpredictability of the system. ferent manner). Rational choice followed in
Nevertheless, “brainbow” images taken of the evolution (arriving at an intelligent choice by
brain reveal that it has “infinite randomness” logical reasoning of the best course of action).
even with the presence of the architectural frame- Fourth, planned behavior evolved (mentally
work that guides, or constrains, the randomness. working out and then executing an organized,
The blueprint might be “strong,” but it does not optimal sequence of actions aimed at a desired
lead to exact prediction of the details of the map result).
involved. Baumeister (2010) related consciousness to
planning and simulating possibility. He used the
metaphor of making an inner movie that the brain
Comment constructs for itself. It helps to decide what
actions are performed. Consciousness is linked to
Goldman (2012) concluded in his book that “we free will, because only conscious thought can
all share one paradoxical legacy of causality and conceptualize multiple options from which to
the stochastic unfolding of the of the brain’s choose. As with the capacities that permit the
developmental program: we were born free.” perception that one has free will in thought and
(p. 234) He clarified that free will is an attribute action, consciousness evolved in steps and
that develops and is reflected in the individuality humans express the most advanced form.
of our personality and self. Genes are not destiny
(nor is environment). “Humans do seem to be
able to choose.” “Genetic influences are weak Comment
and probabilistic.” They also interact with the
environment and also how we “consciously steer” Young (2011) had presented a quite similar
our lives. Finally, according to Goldman (2012), model of the steps in changes in free will, but
part of our freedom should be to help people instead of proceeding evolutionarily, he orga-
towards ably choosing, too, thereby increasing nized a model of the development of free will
their freedom. around his model of five stages in development.
Goldman (2012) has elucidated a model of the In this regard, a fifth evolutionary step in the
development of free will that includes biological, development of free will belief might relate to the
environmental, and personal components. step of adult collective intelligence that Young
Biology and environment are passive compo- (2011) had described as the final step in cognitive
nents among these influences on development of development. To follow through with this idea,
free will. Our ability to develop to choose consti- free will belief might be conceived as a superor-
tutes the core of the active component of our dinate abstract construction that evolved in our
behavioral causality. Note that, to his credit, recent past through gene-culture co-evolution
much of the major themes of the present book are due to the survival and reproductive benefits it
echoed in the work of Goldman (2012). adds to cultural practice.
The Brain and Free Will 467

The next part of the chapter considers another free will is reducible to brain processes and that
biologically-related aspect of free will, on there is no individual responsibility; rather, our
whether brain function even allows it. whole neurological and psychological profile
Reductionists in the field would argue against functions toward the development of responsibil-
any biological support possible for the phenom- ity within the social context.
enon of free will in behavior. That said, there are Siegel and Douard (2011) emphasized that
workers who support the counter view that free free will appears a product of inhibitory control
will is inherent in brain function. and the underlying substrate in the brain. Their
model involves the PFC as a site in conditioning
neurons (see Fig. 18.6). The PFC is involved in
The Brain and Free Will regulating lower-level areas, leading to impulse
control. Therefore, even if mediating factors,
Model such as low serotonin, are present, the person can
still exert inhibition, control, consciousness, and
Callard and Fitzgerald (2014) and Filevich et al. responsibility.
(2013) argued that the subjective experience of Pockett (2006) presented a model of willed
behaving voluntarily might be dissociated from intentions in relation to the external world leading
brain circuits with action selection. Moreover, to movement. The model is among the first con-
having choice might be a constraint more than a temporary ones to implicate multiple brain regions
reason to feel free. Both Shields (2014) and that are involved in having a sense of free will. She
Navon (2014) argued that conscious control and distinguished between willed intentions and sen-
initiation of behavior do occur and are not sorimotor ones, which are lower in level and more
byproducts of preconscious brain activity. immediate. The model stresses that consciousness
According to them, the research implying that does not necessarily cause simple kinds of behav-
this cannot happen contains both methodological ior nor it is necessarily involved in the correction
limitations and conceptual ambiguities. Shields of ongoing actions. However, for complex deci-
(2014) concluded that volitional action is the out- sions and long-term intentions, actions might be
come of a complex, rapid decision-making pro- initiated consciously. In these cases, the dorsolat-
cess that incorporates cognitive elements and eral prefrontal cortex (DLPFC) and/or the pre-
prior decisions. Navon (2014) argued that a SMA might be involved in long-term intentions,
wholly physicalistic conception of behavior that and the posterior parietal cortex might be involved
denies some role for “mind” could drive to a in more immediate intentions. Moreover, Fig. 18.7
“dead-end.” indicates that there is a complex way of process-
In de Jong (2011), a neurological model of per- ing involved in these conscious intentional actions,
ception of free will includes the parietal cortex as including in the frontal cortex.
well as the prefrontal cortex. The model also gives Keller and Iverson (2013) contended that the
a place to processing in the (dorsal) premotor cor- voluntary inhibition of reflex behavior underpins
tex (see Fig. 18.4). In Rappaport’s model (2011), free will. Suppressing reflex responses allows
aside from the prefrontal and parietal area of the selection from among different possible plans of
brain, as well as relevant motor areas, the insula is behavior.
considered important toward the perception of
having free will (see Fig. 18.5). The insula is
involved in taking ownership of the sense of one’s Comment
body. The neuronal network involved in perceiv-
ing free will allows us authorship of and taking Pierre (2013) reviewed the neuroscience of free
responsibilities for our actions. Because having a will. He introduces the notion that causal explana-
sense of free will is embedded in our brains, and in tion of change in psychotherapy (cognitive, behav-
a way that is widely distributed in the brain, the ioral) is based on the assumption that thoughts are
argument that makes sense follows. It is not that subject to conscious change so that behavior can
468 18 Free Will in Behavior: Believing Makes It So

Target generation and PFc External visual stimuli and


internal action drive proprioceptive information

motive-to-sense sensorimotor
transformation transformation
A. C.
B.
Representation of Body Scheme

predicting sensory PARc


movement consequences
possible effector selection
movement intention
actual sensory
feedback

motor preparation including


selection of motor programs

PMc

final action consent or veto


PFc

Motor execution

Fig. 18.4 Body-scheme-centered parietal processing asso- that may be used for goal-directed movement. This is further
ciated with free selection. Abbreviations. PARc processing in elaborated in motor preparation, which includes selection
the parietal cortex, PFc processing in the prefrontal cortex, between motor programs within parietal–premotor circuitry.
PMc processing in the (dorsal) premotor cortex. This scheme Selection associated with the perception of self-intended
illustrates the putative sequence of initial target generation, movement additionally concerns the distinction of move-
fuelling the motive for action, and the subsequent transfor- ment “sensations” being either predicted [B] or recorded [C],
mation to the neuronal representation of a body scheme [A]. thus providing the adequate sense of a causal relation
The latter is a prerequisite for the selection between possible between movement and its effect. Adopted with permission
action effectors, a basic step of “embodiment” apparently of Elsevier. Reprinted from Cortex, Vol. 47, de Jong, B. M.,
associated with the perception of self-intended movement, Neurology of widely embedded free will, Pages 1160–1165,
i.e., the perception of free will. Early-stage selection in the Copyright 2011; with kind permission from Elsevier.
parietal cortex concerns free selection between body parts [Figure 1, Page 1163]

change. He suggested that the construct of free will, per se. Areas of the brain involved in voli-
will should be updated by emphasizing, instead, tional control and its absence, e.g., in addictions,
volitional self-control. Volitional control implies include the insula cortex, which integrates
the capacity to choose and to decide. However, amygdala and ventromedial prefrontal cortex
neuroscientifically, choices are often made uncon- (VMPC) signals (Verdejo-Garía, 2009; Li, Lu,
sciously and “within neural networks.” D’Argembeau, Ng, & Bechara, 2010).
It is the individual’s brain that is clearly “fully” The neuroscience research grapples with the
and “always” responsible for the person’s behav- question of free will in multiple ways—some by
ior (Hallett, 2007). Dualistic conceptions give promoting its possibility and localization, or at
importance to free will as opposed to volitional least association, with particular brain regions;
control. Even when behavior is unconsciously some by maintaining reductionist models denying
determined, the self exists (Haggard, 2009). Even its independence (and existence) from neuronal
a perfectly functioning brain does not have free processes; and some by changing the grounds of
The Brain and Free Will 469

Fig. 18.5 A neuroanatomical


Supplementary Motor
sketch of willed motion. Prefrontal Area Primary Motor
Agency is an awareness & & Cortex
dependent on feedback Limbic Areas Mesial Motor Regions
between the movement that
ensures after creation of a
sensory model (related to the Cerebellum &
parietal lobe). Perceiving Basal Ganglia
ownership of the body might Acting in
be involved (related to the Agency
insula). Adapted from Parietal Lobe & Inferior Parietal Lobe
Rappaport (2011) Taking
Ownership
NGW:
Consciousness
Insula
Perception of
Will

Actions

Global Neuronal
Working Space

Feeling Conscious
Perceiving Having Will

Conditioning
of neurons PFC

- - Impulsive
Hypothalamus + PAG Aggressive Rage
Behavior

Fig. 18.6 Schematic diagram illustrating the role of the ciations is associated with activation of PFC neurons,
prefrontal cortex (PFC) as a key site in the conditioning which then suppress medial hypothalamic and PAG mech-
process. PFC regulates and controls aggressive impulsive anisms, thus reducing or eliminating the expression of the
behavior that is mediated by the medial hypothalamus and impulsive rage response. The figure helps understand the
midbrain periaqueductal gray (PAG). The PFC receives neuroscience source of action and its control. Adopted
major inputs from sensory regions of cortex and thalamus. with permission of Elsevier. Reprinted from International
These inputs provide the basis by which classical condi- Journal of Law and Psychiatry, Vol. 34, Siegel, A., &
tioning of neurons in this region takes place and accord- Douard, J., Who’s flying the plane: Serotonin levels,
ingly provide the substrate for cognitive associations to be aggression and free will, Pages 20–29, Copyright 2011;
formed in this region. Activation of these cognitive asso- with kind permission from Elsevier. [Figure 1, Page 27]
470 18 Free Will in Behavior: Believing Makes It So

Fig. 18.7 Model of WILLED INTENTIONS


anatomical and functional
relationships in the motor SENSORIMOTOR INTENTIONS
system. Abbreviations. DLPFC, pre-SMA
DLPFC dorsolateral prefrontal
Posterior parietal
cortex, pre-SMA cortex
presupplementary motor area,
SMA supplementary motor
area, MI primary motor cortex. Efference
Adopted by permission of The INTENTION/ MOTIVATION copy
MIT Press. Pockett, Susan, INTERACTIONS
William P. Banks, and Shaun
Gallagher, eds., Does INTENTION/ SENSORY
Premotor, cingulate cortices, FEEDBACK
Consciousness Cause
pre-SMA, SMA, MI Corrections INTERACTIONS
Behavior? Figure 1.2, pp. 11,
© 2006 Massachusetts
Institute of Technology, by
CEREBELLUM
permission of The MIT Press. BASAL
[Figure 1.2, Page 11] THALAMUS
GANGLIA

LIMBIC SYSTEM
Visual and
somatosensory
feedback

MUSCLES

EXTERNAL WORLD

the debate, and referring to volitional control, tend to experience an increased physiological
intention, and so on. The present perspective is response to negative (adverse) environments
that free will is an emergent and biopsychosocial compared to the latter; in addition, conserva-
phenomenon and that it is multiply determined, tives devote more psychological resources to
with brain structure and function involved. them. The results of the research are more robust
The last part of the present chapter moves for the strength of this negativity bias in conser-
from the individual to the group for some topics vatives compared to the strength for more distal
related to free will, such as in politics. The next factors such as genetic differences and for more
chapter includes material on free will, as well, proximal parental political preferences.
especially in a proposal for a new questionnaire Commentators on Hibbing et al. (2014) referred
on the topic. to other aspects of the environment in these
regards, as well (e.g., threat sensitivity, arousal),
cognitive closure, values, positive aspects of the
The Politics of Free Will environment, and economic vs. sociocultural
issues. The authors denied a critical role of per-
Model sonality variables (e.g., neuroticism) in differen-
tiating conservatives and liberals.
Hibbing, Smith, and Alford (2014) queried the Carey and Paulhus (2012) investigated the
nature of differences between conservatives relationship between free will belief and mea-
(supporters of tradition/stability) and liberals sures related to a conservative worldview. They
(supporters of innovation/reform). The former used the FAD-Plus (Paulhus & Carey, 2011), and
Chapter Conclusions 471

found free will belief is associated with “tradi- Behavior is unconscious and automatic at lower
tional conservative values” as well as “religios- levels but guided by conscious deliberation at
ity” and a belief in a “just world.” Another study higher levels, being fully present and participa-
they conducted related it to punitiveness and tory in the moment rather than fashioned uniquely
moralistic standards (in judging self/others). The by the past, whether in terms of prior contexts/
authors suggested that free will belief promotes environments, psychological states/characteris-
“a strong sense” of personal responsibility for tics, or biological/genetic fixities. Free will is
one’s behavior. They combined the work of inscribed in the brain and body; genetics and
Baumeister (2008) and Haidt (2008) to argue that physiology; and behavior and mind as a potential
free will belief is associated with the expectation that increasingly activates and dominates in
that others will demonstrate self-control of behavioral determination as development pro-
impulses and, also, that they will criticize people ceeds and matures.
for not expressing such self-control. In addition, Free will is what makes us free as humans,
they expect punishment as a rightful response to willful as humans, and confident in our ability to
misbehavior. adapt potentially in a successful way to any and
all contingencies of life. It is the hallmark of our
intelligence, our emotivity, and our being. It is
Comment our birthright and our life long right. Free will is
as much in our reality as reality lies in our free
The politics of the psychology of politics is will. It is as real and vibrant as the best that is in
highly psychological. It needs the correct meth- us and the best that we can help make the other.
odology and instruments. It could be that there Free will speaks not only to the stream of our
are diverse answers to these issues depending on daily lives, the long-term goals that we set for
individual’s constellation of biopsychosocial fac- ourselves, and the strategies for problems that
tors influencing them. immediately confront us, but also, free will can
be used when things go awry psychologically. In
this regard, free will can be used in face of deep
Chapter Conclusions issues that beguile us. Further in this regard,
when we cannot marshal by ourselves the
There is enough evidence to show that free will is resources to implement it effectively and psycho-
not an illusion. The mind can function emer- logical difficulties become ingrained and trouble-
gently and distinctly from passive biological and some, free will should be an integral part of
environmental influences. It can function actively psychotherapy. Individual differences in free will
and proactively to facilitate accommodative have wide-ranging impacts, and seeding its belief
adjustment and adaptation to the environment, and sense can help people in need, such as those
choosing and deciding appropriately toward its suffering from addictions and psychopatholo-
optimal goals. The person has much to say in his gies. It is impossible to understand the causality
or her own behavior and in social relations with of behavior without understanding free will. It is
others. Free will is a property of mind as much as the epitome of who we are and the essential
is perception and action. The former is guided by driver of what we become.
subjective appraisals that are personally con- As for the flip side of free will, the debate that
structed and the latter is guided by personally- one or the other of consciousness and uncon-
derived desires, wishes, and goals. The person is sciousness is primary or even unique in decision-
a thinking and emotional whole who is not con- making and action is sterile. Both are entwined in
fined to the prescriptions of genetics and the pro- behavioral determination, and free will is related
scriptions of the environment. to consciousness, which develops as much as free
Free will is integral to the human psychology, will. That being said, the research in the area needs
and can help escape the tyranny of determinism. careful examination, for example, on the studies
472 18 Free Will in Behavior: Believing Makes It So

that lead to the conclusion that conscious experi- B. Gawronski, & Y. Trope (Eds.), Dual-process theo-
ence follows decision-making rather than preced- ries of the social mind (pp. 35–49). New York:
Guilford Press.
ing it (e.g., Libet, 1985). If free will is the driver of Baumeister, R. F., & Brewer, L. E. (2012). Believing ver-
adaptive behavior, consciousness is the ground on sus disbelieving in free will: Correlates and conse-
which it is permitted to deploy and function. quences. Social and Personality Psychology Compass,
6, 736–745.
Baumeister, R. F., Crescioni, A. W., & Alquist, J. L.
(2011). Free will as advanced action control for human
References social life and culture. Neuroethics, 4, 1–11.
Baumeister, R. F., & Masicampo, E. J. (2010).
Adams, P., & Suarez, A. (2013). Introduction. In A. Suarez Conscious thought is for facilitating social and cul-
& P. Adams (Eds.), Is science compatible with free tural interactions: How mental simulations serve the
will? Exploring free will and consciousness in the animal-culture interface. Psychological Review,
light of quantum physics and neuroscience (pp. 1–4). 117, 945–971.
New York: Springer Science + Business Media. Baumeister, R. F., Masicampo, E. J., & DeWall, C. N.
Alquist, J. L., Ainsworth, S. E., & Baumeister, R. F. (2009). Prosocial benefits of feeling free: Disbelief in
(2013). Determined to conform: Disbelief in free will free will increases aggression and reduces helpfulness.
increases conformity. Journal of Experimental Social Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 35,
Psychology, 49, 80–86. 260–268.
Alquist, J. L., Ainsworth, S., Baumeister, R., Daly, M., & Baumeister, R. F., Masicampo, E. J., & Vohs, K. D.
Stillman, T. (2015). The making of might-have-beens: (2011). Do conscious thoughts cause behavior?
Effects of free will belief on counterfactual thinking. Annual Review of Psychology, 62, 331–361.
Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 41, Baumeister, R. F., Masicampo, E. J., & Vohs, K. D.
268–283. (2015). Conscious thoughts and the causation of
Axmacher, N. (2013). Causation in psychoanalysis. Frontiers behavior. In M. Mikulincer & P. R. Shaver (Eds.), APA
in Psychology, 4. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00077. handbook of personality and social psychology
Baars, B. J. (2002). The conscious access hypothesis: (Attitudes and social cognition, Vol. 1, pp. 231–250).
Origins and recent evidence. Trends in Cognitive Washington, DC: American Psychological
Sciences, 6, 47–52. Association.
Baillargeon, R., Scott, R. M., & He, Z. (2010). False- Bode, S., He, A. H., Soon, C. S., Trampel, R., Turner, R.,
belief understanding in infants. Trends in Cognitive & Haynes, J. D. (2011). Tracking the unconscious
Sciences, 14, 110–118. generation of free decisions using ultra-high field
Bar-Anan, Y., Wilson, T. D., & Hassin, R. R. (2010). fMRI. PLoS One, 6, e21612. doi:10.1371/journal.
Inaccurate self-knowledge formation as a result of pone.0021612.
automatic behavior. Journal of Experimental Social Bode, S., Murawski, C., Soon, C. S., Bode, P., Stahl, J., &
Psychology, 46, 884–894. Smith, P. L. (2014). Demystifying “free will”: The role
Bargh, J. A. (2011). Unconscious thought theory and its of contextual information and evidence accumulation
discontents: A critique of the critiques. Social for predictive brain activity. Neuroscience and
Cognition, 29, 629–647. Biobehavioral Reviews, 47, 636–645.
Bargh, J. A., Lee-Chai, A., Barndollar, K., Gollwitzer, Brewer, L. E. (2011). Forging freely: Perceptions of moral
P. M., & Trötschel, R. (2001). The automated will: responsibility mediate the relationship between belief
Nonconscious activation and pursuit of behavioral in free will and willingness to forgive (Doctoral dis-
goals. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, sertation). Retrieved from Electronic Theses, Treatises
81, 1014–1027. and Dissertations. Paper 3044.
Bargh, J. A., Schwader, K. L., Hailey, S. E., Dyer, R. L., Brewer, L. E., & Baumeister, R. F. (2010). Relationship
& Boothby, E. J. (2012). Automaticity in social- between free will belief and self-control. Tallahassee,
cognitive processes. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 16, FL: Florida State University.
593–605. Briñol, P., & DeMarree, K. G. (Eds.). (2012). Social meta-
Baumeister, R. F. (2008). Free will in scientific psychol- cognition. New York: Psychology Press.
ogy. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 3, 14–19. Callard, F., & Fitzgerald, D. (2014). Experimental con-
Baumeister, R. F. (2010). Understanding free will and trol: What does it mean for a participant to “feel
consciousness on the basis of current research findings free?”. Consciousness and Cognition, 27, 231–232.
in psychology. In R. F. Baumeister, A. R. Mele, & Carey, J., & Paulhus, D. L. (2011, January). The indepen-
K. D. Vohs (Eds.), Free will and consciousness: How dence of free will and determinism in judgments of
might they work? (pp. 24–42). New York: Oxford moral responsibility. Poster presented at the 12th
University Press. Annual meeting of the Society for Personality and
Baumeister, R. F., & Bargh, J. A. (2014). Conscious and Social Psychology, San Antonio, TX.
unconscious: Toward an integrative understanding of Carey, J. M., & Paulhus, D. L. (2012). Worldview impli-
human mental life and action. In J. W. Sherman, cations of believing in free will and/or determinism:
References 473

Politics, morality and punitiveness. Journal of tively interferes with utilitarian moral judgment.
Personality, 81, 130–141. Cognition, 107, 1144–1154.
Crescioni, A. W., Baumeister, R. F., Ainsworth, S. E., Ent, Haggard, P. (2009). The sources of human volition.
M. R., & Lambert, N. M. (2015). Subjective correlates Science, 324, 731–733.
and consequences of belief in free will. Philosophical Haidt, J. (2008). Morality. Perspectives on Psychological
Psychology, 9, 41–63. Science, 3, 65–72.
de Jong, B. M. (2011). Neurology of widely embedded Hallett, M. (2007). Volitional control of movement: The
free will. Cortex, 47, 1160–1165. physiology of free will. Clinical Neurophysiology,
DeWall, C. N., Baumeister, R. F., & Masicampo, E. J. 118, 1179–1192.
(2008). Evidence that logical reasoning depends on Ham, J., & van den Bos, K. (2010). On unconscious
conscious processing. Consciousness and Cognition, morality: The effects of unconscious thinking on
17, 628–645. moral decision making. Social Cognition, 28, 74–83.
Dijksterhuis, A., & Aarts, H. (2010). Goals, attention, and Ham, J., van den Bos, K., & van Doorn, E. A. (2009).
(un) consciousness. Annual Review of Psychology, 61, Lady Justice thinks unconsciously: Unconscious
467–490. thought can lead to more accurate justice judgments.
Dijksterhuis, A., & Nordgren, L. F. (2006). A theory of Social Cognition, 27, 509–521.
unconscious thought. Perspectives on Psychological Hamlin, J. K., & Wynn, K. (2011). Young infants prefer
Science, 1, 95–109. prosocial to antisocial others. Cognitive Development,
Doyle, R. O. (2013). The two-stage model to the problem 26, 30–39.
of free will: How behavioral freedom in lower animals Hassin, R. R. (2008). Being open minded without know-
has evolved to become free will in humans and higher ing why: Evidence from nonconscious goal pursuit.
animals. In A. Suarez & P. Adams (Eds.), Is science Social Cognition, 26, 578–592.
compatible with free will? Exploring free will and con- Hassin, R. R. (2013). Yes it can: On the functional abili-
sciousness in the light of quantum physics and neuro- ties of the human unconscious. Perspectives on
science (pp. 235–254). New York: Springer Psychological Science, 8, 195–207.
Science + Business Media. Hassin, R. R., Bargh, J. A., & Zimerman, S. (2009).
Dunham, Y., Baron, A. S., & Banaji, M. R. (2006). From Automatic and flexible: The case of non-conscious
American city to Japanese village: A cross-cultural goal pursuit. Social Cognition, 27, 20–36.
investigation of implicit race attitudes. Child Hespos, S. J., & van Marle, S. J. (2012). Physics for
Development, 77, 1268–1281. infants: Characterizing the origins of knowledge about
Eisenberger, N. I., Lieberman, M. D., & Williams, K. D. objects, substances, and number. Wiley Interdisciplinary
(2003). Does rejection hurt? An fMRI study of social Reviews: Cognitive Science, 3, 19–27.
exclusion. Science, 302, 290–292. Hibbing, J. R., Smith, K. B., & Alford, J. R. (2014).
Elliot, A. J., & McGregor, H. A. (2001). A 2 × 2 achieve- Differences in negativity bias underlie variations in
ment goal framework. Journal of Personality and political ideology. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 37,
Social Psychology, 80, 501–519. 297–307.
Feigenson, L., Dehaene, S., & Spelke, E. (2004). Core Kane, R. (2013). Can a traditional libertarian or incom-
systems of number. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8, patibilist free will be reconciled with modern science?
307–314. Steps toward a positive answer. In A. Suarez &
Filevich, E., Vanneste, P., Brass, M., Fias, W., Haggard, P., P. Adams (Eds.), Is science compatible with free will?
& Kühn, S. (2013). Brain correlates of subjective free- Exploring free will and consciousness in the light of
dom of choice. Consciousness and Cognition, 22, quantum physics and neuroscience (pp. 255–272).
1271–1284. New York: Springer Science + Business Media.
Fingelkurts, A. A., Fingelkurts, A. A., Bagnato, S., Kang, Y., Williams, L. E., Clark, M. S., Gray, J. R., &
Boccagni, C., & Galardi, G. (2012). Toward opera- Bargh, J. A. (2011). Physical temperature effects on
tional architectonics of consciousness: Basic evidence trust behavior: The role of insula. Social Cognitive and
from patients with severe cerebral injuries. Cognitive Affective Neuroscience, 6, 507–515.
Processing, 13, 111–131. Keller, F., & Iverson, J. M. (2013). The role of inhibitory
Goldman, D. (2012). Our genes our choices: How geno- control of reflex mechanisms in voluntary behavior. In
type and gene interactions affect behavior. Amsterdam, A. Suarez & P. Adams (Eds.), Is science compatible
Netherlands: Elsevier Academic Press. with free will? Exploring free will and consciousness in
Gollwitzer, P. M., & Sheeran, P. (2006). Implementation the light of quantum physics and neuroscience (pp. 107–
intentions and goal achievement: A meta-analysis of 116). New York: Springer Science + Business Media.
effects and processes. Advances in Experimental Kim, K., & Cho, B. (2011). Development of an
Social Psychology, 38, 69–119. individualism-collectivism scale revised: A Korean
Graziano, M. S. A. (2013). Consciousness and the socials sample. Psychological Reports, 108, 393–401.
brain. New York: Oxford University Press. Knobe, J., Buckwalter, W., Nichols, S., Robbins, P.,
Greene, J. D., Morelli, S. A., Lowenberg, K., Nystrom, Sarkissian, H., & Sommers, T. (2012). Experimental
L. E., & Cohen, J. D. (2008). Cognitive load selec- philosophy. Annual Review of Psychology, 63, 81–99.
474 18 Free Will in Behavior: Believing Makes It So

Kraft, T. L., & Pressman, S. D. (2012). Grin and bear it: The Nichols, S. (2011). Experimental philosophy and the
influence of manipulated facial expression on the stress problem of free will. Science, 331, 1401–1403.
response. Psychological Science, 23, 1372–1378. Nordgren, L. F., Bos, M. W., & Dijksterhuis, A. (2011).
Kuhl, J., & Quirin, M. (2011). Seven steps toward free- The best of both worlds: Integrating conscious and
dom and two ways to lose it: Overcoming limitations unconscious thought best solves complex decisions.
of intentionality through self-confrontational coping Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 47,
with stress. Social Psychology, 42, 74–84. 509–511.
Li, X., Lu, Z., D’Argembeau, A., Ng, M., & Bechara, A. Over, H., & Carpenter, M. (2009a). Eighteen-month-old
(2010). The Iowa Gambling Task in fMRI imaging. infants show increased helping following priming with
Human Brain Mapping, 31, 410–423. affiliation. Psychological Science, 20, 1189–1193.
Libet, B. (1985). Unconscious cerebral initiative and the Over, H., & Carpenter, M. (2009b). Priming third-party
role of conscious will in voluntary action. The ostracism increases affiliative imitation in children.
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 8, 529–539. Developmental Science, 12, F1–F8.
Libet, B. (1999). Do we have free will? Journal of Pallar, K. A., & Suzuki, S. (2014). The source of conscious-
Consciousness Studies, 6, 47–57. ness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 18, 387–389.
Libet, B. (2001). Consciousness, free action and the brain. Pascalis, O., de Viviés, X. d. M., Anzures, G., Quinn, P. C.,
Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8, 59–65. Slater, A. M., Tanaka, J. W., et al. (2011). Development
Libet, B. (2004). Mind time. Cambridge, MA: Harvard of face processing. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews:
University Press. Cognitive Science, 2, 666–675.
Libet, B., Gleason, C. A., Wright, E. W., & Pearl, D. K. Paulhus, D. L., & Carey, J. M. (2011). The FAD-Plus:
(1983). Time of conscious intention to act in relation Measuring lay beliefs regarding free will and related
to onset of cerebral activities (readiness-potential): constructs. Journal of Personality Assessment, 93,
The unconscious initiation of a freely voluntary act. 96–104.
Brain, 106, 623–642. Perner, J., & Roessler, J. (2012). From infants’ to chil-
Marien, H., Custers, R., Hassin, R. R., & Aarts, H. (2012). dren’s appreciation of belief. Trends in Cognitive
Unconscious goal activation and the hijacking of the Sciences, 16, 519–525.
executive function. Journal of Personality and Social Pierre, J. M. (2013). The neuroscience of free will:
Psychology, 103, 399–415. Implications for psychiatry. Psychological Medicine,
Mele, A. R. (2013). Free will and neuroscience: Revisiting 44, 2465–2474.
Libet’s studies. In A. Suarez & P. Adams (Eds.), Is Pinker, S. (2008). The fear of determinism. In J. Baer,
science compatible with free will? Exploring free will J. C. Kaufman, & R. F. Baumeister (Eds.), Are we
and consciousness in the light of quantum physics and free? Psychology and free will (pp. 311–324).
neuroscience (pp. 195–207). New York: Springer New York: Oxford University Press.
Science + Business Media. Pockett, S. (2006). The neuroscience of movement. In
Miles, J. B. (2013a). “Irresponsible and a disservice”: The S. Pockett, W. P. Banks, & S. Gallagher (Eds.), Does
integrity of social psychology turns on the free will consciousness cause behavior? (pp. 9–24). Cambridge,
dilemma. British Journal of Social Psychology, 52, MA: MIT Press.
205–218. Pockett, S., & Purdy, S. (2011). Are voluntary movements
Miles, J. B. (2013b). The integrity of social psychology initiated preconsciously? The relationships between
turns on the free will dilemma: Reply to Baumeister, readiness potentials, urges, and decisions. In W. Sinnott-
Vonasch, and Bargh. British Journal of Social Armstrong & L. Nadel (Eds.), Conscious will and
Psychology, 52, 231–237. responsibility. New York: Oxford University Press.
Monroe, A. E., Dillon, K. D., & Malle, B. F. (2014). Rappaport, Z. H. (2011). The neuroscientific foundations
Bringing free down to earth: People’s psychological of free will. Advances and Technical Standards in
concept of free will and its role in moral judgment. Neurosurgery, 37, 3–23.
Consciousness and Cognition, 27, 100–108. Rigoni, D., Kühn, S., Sartori, G., & Brass, M. (2011).
Monroe, A. E., & Malle, B. F. (2010). From uncaused will Inducing disbelief in free will alters brain correlates of
to conscious choice: The need to study, not speculate preconscious motor preparation: The brain minds
about people’s folk concept of free will. Review of whether we believe in free will or not. Psychological
Philosophy and Psychology, 1, 211–224. Science, 22, 613–618.
Nahmias, E. (2012). Free will and responsibility. Wiley Sarkissian, H., Chatterjee, A., De Brigard, F., Knobe, J.,
Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science, 3, Nichols, S., & Sirker, S. (2010). Is belief in free will a
439–449. cultural universal? Mind & Language, 25, 346–358.
Nahmias, E., Morris, S., Nadelhoffer, T., & Turner, Schlosser, M. E. (2012a). Free will and the unconscious
J. (2005). Surveying freedom: Folk intuitions about precursors of choice. Philosophical Psychology, 25,
free will and moral responsibility. Philosophical 365–384.
Psychology, 18, 561–584. Schlosser, M. E. (2012b). Causally efficacious intentions
Navon, D. (2014). How plausible is it that conscious con- and the sense of agency: In defense of real mental cau-
trol is illusory? American Journal of Psychology, 127, sation. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical
147–155. Psychology, 32, 135–160.
References 475

Shariff, A. F., Greene, J. D., Karremans, J. C., Luguri, J. B., Vasilyeva, M., & Lourenco, S. F. (2012). The develop-
Clark, C. J., Schooler, J. W., et al. (2014). Free will and ment of spatial cognition. Wiley Interdisciplinary
punishment: A mechanistic view of human nature reduces Reviews: Cognitive Science, 3, 349–362.
retribution. Psychological Science, 25, 1563–1570. Verdejo-Garía, A. (2009). A somatic marker theory of
Shepherd, J. (2012). Free will and consciousness: addiction. Neuropharmacology, 56, 48–62.
Experimental studies. Consciousness and Cognition, Vohs, K. D., & Schooler, J. W. (2008). The value of
21, 915–927. believing in free will: Encouraging a belief in deter-
Shields, G. S. (2014). Neuroscience and conscious causa- minism increases cheating. Psychological Science, 19,
tion: Has neuroscience shown that we cannot control 49–54.
our own actions? Review of Philosophy and Vonasch, A. J., & Baumeister, R. F. (2013). Implications
Psychology, 5, 565–582. of free will beliefs for basic theory and societal bene-
Siegel, A., & Douard, J. (2011). Who’s flying the plane: fit: Critique and implications for social psychology.
Serotonin levels, aggression and free will. International British Journal of Social Psychology, 52, 219–227.
Journal of Law and Psychiatry, 34, 20–29. Wegner, D. M. (2002). The illusion of conscious will.
Soon, C. S., Brass, M., Heinze, H. J., & Haynes, J. D. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
(2008). Unconscious determinants of free decisions in Wegner, D. M. (2004). Précis of the illusion of conscious
the human brain. Nature Neuroscience, 11, 543–545. will. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 27, 649–692.
Soon, C. S., He, A. H., Bode, S., & Haynes, J. D. (2013). Wegner, D. M. (2005). Who is the controller of controlled
Predicting free choices for abstract intentions. processes? In R. R. Hassin, J. S. Uleman, & J. A.
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, Bargh (Eds.), The new unconscious (pp. 19–36).
USA, 110, 5733–5734. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
Stillman, T. F., & Baumeister, R. F. (2010). Guilty, free, Wegner, D. M. (2008). Self is magic. In J. Baer, J. C.
and wise: Belief in free will facilitates learning from Kaufman, & R. F. Baumeister (Eds.), Are we free?
self-conscious emotions. Journal of Experimental Psychology and free will (pp. 226–247). Oxford, UK:
Social Psychology, 46, 951–960. Oxford University Press.
Stillman, T. F., Baumeister, R. F., & Mele, A. R. (2011). Wegner, D. M., & Wheatley, T. P. (1999). Apparent men-
Free will in everyday life: Autobiographical accounts tal causation: Sources of the experience of will.
of free and unfree actions. Philosophical Psychology, American Psychologist, 54, 480–492.
24, 381–394. Williams, L. E., & Bargh, J. A. (2008). Experiencing
Stillman, T. F., Baumeister, R. F., Vohs, K. D., Lambert, physical warmth promotes interpersonal warmth.
N. M., Fincham, F. D., & Brewer, L. E. (2010). Personal Science, 322, 606–607.
philosophy and personnel achievement: Belief in free Williams, L. E., Huang, J. Y., & Bargh, J. A. (2009). The
will predicts better job performance. Social scaffolded mind: Higher mental processes are grounded
Psychological and Personality Science, 1, 43–50. in early experience of the physical world. European
Suarez, A., & Adams, P. (2013). Is science compatible Journal of Social Psychology, 39, 1257–1267.
with free will? Exploring free will and consciousness Woodward, A. L. (2009). Infants’ grasp of others’ inten-
in the light of quantum physics and neuroscience. tions. Current Directions in Psychological Science,
New York: Springer Science + Business Media. 18, 53–57.
Suter, R. S., & Hertwig, R. (2011). Time and moral judg- Yang, Y. (2013). Free will belief predicts master-approach
ment. Cognition, 119, 454–458. goal orientation among university students. Unpublished
Tsai, J., Ying, Y.-W., & Lee, P. A. (2000). The meaning of honors thesis. York University, Ontario, Canada.
“being Chinese” and “being American.” Variation Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
among Chinese American young adults. Journal of Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer
Cross-Cultural Psychology, 31, 302–332. Science + Business Media.
An Integrated Model of “Free Will”
and New Free Will Questionnaires 19

own based on them. Not surprisingly, the approach


Chapter Introduction that I take is to consider free will as a biopsycho-
social phenomenon. In this regard, the work on
Free will is a central topic in psychological study, free will has emphasized free will belief and its
and a fascinating one for the public. We can never effects. However, I argue that this cognitive com-
be sure it exists, but believing in free will has ponent needs to be complemented by a socioaffec-
positive consequences, including for self-control. tive one. In the end, I develop an elaborate set of
However, self-control can be derailed by a host of items related to a free will questionnaire that
factors. The phenomenon has been referred to as involve five major domains, each with eight sub-
resource or “ego” depletion. A more elaborate domains. Also, toward the end of the chapter I pro-
term for the model would be limited-resource pose a more inclusive questionnaire on resource/
model of self-regulation and executive function ego-depletion. To end this chapter, I also consider
(Vohs et al., 2014). Different models have been passion as a component of the personal agency
proposed to explain it, from the biological to the that we bring to behavioral causation. I review the
psychological to the social. After reviewing the work by Vallerand and colleagues, in particular
literature, I propose an integrative biopsychoso- (e.g., Vallerand, 2010), on the topic, presenting
cial model of depletion in self-control. both their definition and questionnaire. At the
Part of the proposal includes a role in self- same time, I develop improved versions for both.
control for dual process thinking processes. These
have been described as (a) unconscious, fast, and
automatic thinking, and (b) conscious, slow, and Depletion
deliberative thinking. Throughout the chapter, I
relate depletion and dual process models to my Introduction
own work on activation/inhibition coordination as
a general mechanism in behavioral causality. The field of depletion of self-control is a divided
Also, I relate depletion and dual process models one, with proponents extolling the advantages of
to my own work on Neo-Piagetian stage modeling various unifactorial models while decrying the
for understanding different types of thinking. disadvantages of the others. Self-control is sub-
The chapter concludes with a section on ques- ject to depletion effects in the laboratory accord-
tionnaires. I review the basic ones in the field on ing to one factor or the other, or one or the other
free will, describe my concerns, and develop my is proposed as the mechanism that can account

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 477


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_19
478 19 An Integrated Model of “Free Will” and New Free Will Questionnaires

for it. In the following, I review each of the major could index resource depletion was conducted,
areas on conceptualization and research on deple- respectively, by Segerstrom and Nes (2007) and
tion effects in self-control. Their diversity and the Inzlicht and Gutsell (2007).
partial support each garners together suggest that Gailliot et al. (2007) found that a self-regulation
they might all play a role in depletion effects, condition lowered blood glucose more than a con-
depending on the individual and context involved. trol condition. Moreover, the lowered levels pre-
Moreover, equally, they would all seem neces- dicted future self-regulation task failure. Finally, a
sary to explain resistance to depletion effects, sugary drink countered the ego-depletion, unlike
again, depending on the individual and context. the case for an artificial sweetener.
In short, laboratory tasks with a self-control
component acted to deplete blood levels of glu-
Glucose cose relative to tasks without the component.
Moreover, interventions (receiving lemonade
Baumeister and colleagues (e.g., Baumeister, with sugar) that boost blood glucose helped study
Bratslavesky, Muraven, & Tice, 1998) developed participants to resist irrational decisions, com-
the “ego depletion” model. It is a resource model pared to those who were not similarly boosted
of self-control in which the overriding of predom- (receiving lemonade with diet sweetener).
inant response tendencies affects afterwards a Baumeister et al. (2011) concluded that there
limited resource related to resistance, or “will is sufficient basis to support an energy and physi-
power,” even in apparently unrelated tasks. Belief ological model of free will. They added that more
in free will is subject to depletion in its effects. research is needed to establish the neural con-
Baumeister, Masicampo, and Vohs (2011) not comitants of the phenomenon.
only argued that believing in free will has behav- Carter, Kofler, Forster, and McCullough
ioral consequences, but also that engaging in tasks (2015) conducted a series of meta-analysis to test
requiring self-regulation leads to impaired perfor- the limited-resource model of the depletion
mance on ensuing tasks. “Ego-depletion,” then, is effect. There have been over 200 published stud-
a term referring to using limited resources that are ies of the depletion effect and Hagger, Wood,
available to maintain self-control so that, after Stiff, and Chatzisarantis (2010) conducted a
people have exerted self-control, they do not do as meta-analysis that supported it. However, Carter
well on ensuing tasks involving self-regulation et al. (2015) followed that meta-analysis with
(Vohs, Baumeister, & Schmeichel, 2012, 2013). their own that implemented several methodologi-
For Baumeister et al. (2011) energy depletion cal improvements. For example, they included
refers to the effect of using cognitive resources results from unpublished studies as well as pub-
associated with a belief in free will on brain lished ones. Their results showed that the deple-
activity, which depends on blood level glucose. tion effect research, in general, produced
Therefore, according to them, the resource deple- nonsignificant results, at least in terms of the
tion effect that is involved in self-control activity laboratory studies typically used. They concluded
especially concerns a metabolic-related deplet- that the depletion effect, as mediated by limited
able energetic resource. resources that affect self-control, is not a valid
The evidence on blood glucose depletion in psychological phenomenon. They encouraged
the study of ego-depletion supports its effects the development of other theories on when and
(e.g., Masicampo & Baumeister, 2008). Because why self-control might be depleted.
the physiological basis of self-control appears to
lie in the resources of glucose availability in cir-
culating blood, its depletion can be measured by Personal Belief/Will Power
its levels, as well as those related to heart-rate
variability (HRV) and error-related negativity In this regard, the phenomenon of ego-depletion
(ERN). The research showing the HRV and ERN has been explained by different models. The
Depletion 479

limited-resource model maintains that, after behavior. Having a belief in unlimited will power
exertion of energy or volition in self-control, cannot genuinely cause unlimited will power.
people perform worse on ensuing following self-
regulatory tasks (e.g., Baumeister, Vohs, & Tice,
2007). Vohs et al. (2013) investigated challenges Embodiment
to the model related to personal belief and will
power, and found them wanting. That is, when Ent and Baumeister (2014) related free will belief
depletion is severe, profound, or extensive, to embodied influences. They examined it in peo-
unlike what has been found for mild depletion, ple (a) who had epilepsy/panic disorder, (b) who
they demonstrated that the effects on self-control were experiencing more physical symptoms
cannot be washed out or reversed in laboratory (e.g., fatigue), and (c) who were on diets. In all
studies by either motivation or belief in unlim- cases, bodily state affected free will belief. In
ited will power. study 1, the authors demonstrated that, relative to
Vohs et al. (2013) elaborated that the subjec- controls, people with less control of bodily state
tive or personal belief/motivation model main- (epileptic group, panic disorder group) reported
tains that mindset could render people “immune” less general free will belief (according to a sub-
from ego-depletion and that depletion is all in the scale developed by Rakos, Laurene, Skala, &
mind. Factors such as pondering personal values, Slane, 2008). In a second study, the more partici-
getting incentives, or believing in unlimited will pants reported feeling sexual desire, fatigue, or
power can offset any (a) resource, (b) energy, or the need to urinate, the less were their scores on
(c) ego-depletion (respectively, Schmeichel & the “personal free will” subscale in Rakos et al.
Vohs, 2009; Muraven & Slessareva, 2003; Job, (2008). In the third study, for non-dieters only,
Dweck, & Walton, 2010). hunger related negatively to belief in personal
In their test of these latter models of self- free will. The authors concluded that even spe-
control and its depletion, Vohs et al. (2013) varied cific low-level bodily cues (sensations, states)
the amount of self-control tasks administered to could affect people’s abstract beliefs, such as
participants (0, 2, 4), with examples of the tasks philosophical beliefs about free will.
involved including the Stroop task, stifling facial/
emotional reactions to a film, and changing set in
a cross-out task. Beforehand, a questionnaire was Social
used to manipulate will power belief (e.g., con-
centrating can be inspiring; or it can be tiring). Other social and personality factors are involved
Dependent measures related to self-control ability in self-control. Ent, Baumeister, and Vonasch
(on delayed gratification and a cognitive estima- (2012) speculated that wielding power can have
tion task). In the second study, the manipulation ego-depletion effects. Gailliot, Gitter, Baker, and
was of different degrees of motivation. Baumeister (2012) conducted research that
Vohs et al. (2013) concluded that their results showed that lower trait self-control can lead to
had revealed that both of the ego-depletion model greater violations of social norms and rules that
and the personal beliefs/motivational models are difficult to follow.
contribute positively to understanding self- Coan, Brown, and Beckes (2014) contrasted
control and its interference. Physiologically- the physical resource/self-control depletion
based energy states interact with subjective, approach in human self-regulation (Gailliot &
psychological factors in determining perfor- Baumeister, 2007) to the social baseline model
mance in self-control tasks. The latter can moder- (Coan, 2008). That is, social interaction/contact
ate the former in incipient or mild resource constitutes a powerful mediator of self-control
depletion, including due to fatigue. However, will and its depletion. In the physical resource model,
power is not objectively unlimited, and extensive a specific quantity of a metabolic resource (i.e.,
ego-depletion results in decline in self-regulatory glucose) is available for self-regulation but, in the
480 19 An Integrated Model of “Free Will” and New Free Will Questionnaires

latter model, social resources can update the was accomplished by having them press a button
“budget” for self-regulation. Information related when they viewed the letter “e” in the displayed
to proximity to social resources allows for a cog- word, except if the letter was next to, or one letter
nitive regulation “economizing” of activity away from, another vowel. This condition
(Beckes & Coan, 2011). Physical contact with requires suppression of prepotent tendencies,
someone else lowers the activation of threat- relative to the control condition of pressing the
responsive areas of the brain (Coan, Schaefer, & button no matter where the latter e is situated in
Davidson, 2006). the displayed word.
These results are inconsistent with a down- The second phase involved a different task (a
regulation model or inhibitory model of self- modified multisource interference task; Bush,
regulatory brain areas responsiveness to stress in Shin, Holmes, Rosen, & Vogt, 2003). Its trials
the absence of social contact. Given the bottom-up were either congruent or incongruent. In the
regulatory impact of social support on inhibition of task, three single-digit numbers are displayed,
threat-responsive brain regions, it appears that with the target one different from the other two,
social support acts by returning an individual which are identical. The digits are between 0 and
organism to a “default” or baseline state (the “social 3, and presented horizontally. On congruent tri-
baseline”). The neuropeptide oxytocin constitutes als, the value of the target number (e.g., 3) cor-
one possible mechanism that mediates decreased, responds to its location (e.g., third position, to
socially responsive elevations in threat situations. the far right). Moreover, the font of the target
number is larger than for the other two, and the
latter is always set as 0. For incongruent trials,
Brain this type of matching does not take place, nor is
there consistency in which number is larger in
Sripada, Kessler, and Jonides (2014) related font or in having nontarget numbers always set at
depletion in regulatory control to the brain’s 0. The dependent measure in Phase 2 was reac-
default network. Baumeister et al. (1998) con- tion time variability over trials, in particular.
structed the depletion of regulatory control Statistics used ex-Gaussian modeling to account
hypothesis as a strength model. The model indi- for skewed distributions and then Fast Fourier
cates that the exercise of sustained regulatory Transform (FFT).
control is limited in capacity and is depletable. The results showed that the methylphenidate
Sripada et al. (2014) argued that methylphenidate blocked the depletion of regulatory control. The
should be capable of blocking the depletion effect spectral analysis showed that, over trials, the
because it serves to increase brain dopamine and effect took place in the slow-4 frequency band,
norepinephrine levels at the synaptic cleft by which is associated with the operation of the rest-
functioning as a catecholamine reuptake blocker. ing state default brain network (DFN).
They showed that methylphenidate (Ritalin) Sripada et al. (2014) concluded that, in their
blocked the depletion that normally takes place. study, methylphenidate affected top-down regu-
The study involved 94 participants with com- latory processing of a network that concerns
plete data. In Phase 1, there were four groups, attention, i.e., the DFN is associated with mind-
organized according to drug administration and wandering and task-irrelevant thought. By boost-
task (Placebo/Methylphenidate × Control task/ ing the brain regions involved in effortful control
Regulation task). Phase 2 involved the test condi- (at the synaptic clefts involved), that is, prefrontal
tion for all four groups. The two drug groups circuits including regions of the lateral and dorsal
received the intervention 60 min before begin- prefrontal cortex and the exterior cingulate, the
ning. The letter-e task was used in Phase 1 drug halted the typical compromise in the func-
(Baumeister et al., 1998), and was manipulated to tioning of these regions by prior regulatory exer-
demand effortful regulation of participants. This tion (e.g., by DFN suppression).
Depletion 481

Inhibition Veen, 2007). These mediators might be the direct


operations that underlie successful self-control.
In a study using reaction time, Rigoni, Kühn, Therefore, a critical component implicated in
Gaudino, Sartori, and Brass (2012) addressed the self-control appears to be action selection and
question of which part of information processing inhibition, consistent with my emphasis on acti-
changes from weakening or undermining self- vation/inhibition coordination as a general brain–
control in people to negative consequences, such behavior regulator (Young, 2011).
as antisocial behavior (Baumeister, 2008; Minda and Rabi (2015) related ego-depletion
Baumeister, Masicampo, & DeWall, 2009). They to effects on inhibitory processes. They related
examined the basic neurocognitive processes the inhibitory processes involved to self-
underlying intention actions and also their degra- regulatory ones. For example, in their depletion
dation when people are induced not to believe in task, story writing had to be undertaken without
free will. They found that the mediator in the using the letters “a” or “n.” Also, they found the
effect appears to relate to intentional inhibition, or depletion task worked for affecting learning rule-
the voluntary inhibition of an intentional response defined categories (RD) rather than non-rule-
(with perceived self-control mechanisms at play, defined ones (NRD). They related RD learning to
as well). the explicit, verbally-mediated system (prefron-
A critical mechanism in behavioral and brain tal cortex related) and the implicit associate
organization and output in the present work learning one (related to striatal cortex, tail of the
relates to activation/inhibition coordination caudate). They related RD and NRD learning to
(Young, 2011). In this regard, the findings of development, with the former harder to learn than
Rigoni et al. (2012) point to a direction in the the latter (Rabi & Minda, 2014).
type of inhibitions involved in self-control and its I would add that the explicit, verbally-mediated
deployment and in the latter’s undermining. system resembles System/Type II cognitive pro-
The notion that inhibition-related mediators are cesses (Evans & Stanovich, 2013; Stanovich, West,
involved in the pathway to self-control degrada- & Toplak, 2014) and the implicit one System/Type
tion because of glucose depletion in prior tasks has I cognitive processes. This suggests that ego-deple-
been elaborated by Sanders, Shirk, Burgin, and tion effects generally should work on System/Type
Martin (2012). Molden et al. (2012) had shown II higher-order cognitive processes (e.g., conscious,
that merely rinsing with glucose without swallow- slow, deliberative) compared to lower-order ones
ing served to negate self-control impairment from (unconscious, fast, intuitive).
one self-control task to another. The results sug- Wiecki and Frank (2013) have presented a
gest that the activation of motivation is sufficient much more complex model of inhibitory control
to interrupt the ego-depletion phenomenon. of behavior in relation to conflicting responses
Using a somewhat different methodology, that might be made in a particular situation, in
Sanders et al. (2012) replicated the primary this case, with respect to the ocular motor system.
results of Molden et al. (2012). They suggested Override or inhibitory mechanisms need to be in
that energy resource replenishment is not what place to suppress habitual activity and allow
maintains self-control. Molden et al. (2012) had executive control. They emphasized the compu-
suggested that the motivation involved in the pro- tational model and the neural network nature of
cess related to reward. However, Sanders et al. their model (see Fig. 19.1). The areas of the brain
(2012) suggested a more specific mechanism. In involved in the model include the area of frontal
particular, they reasoned that the anterior cingu- cortex (e.g., DLPFC, dorsolateral prefrontal
late cortex and striatum are activated, which are cortex; pre-SMA, presupplementary motor).
associated with the “selection and inhibition” of Inhibitory pathways for the behavior that they
action (Balleine, Delgado, & Hikosaka, 2007; addressed include those from the striatum (in the
Eagle & Baunez, 2010) and also the detection of basal ganglia) to the globus pallidus (GP) and
errors and response competition (Carter & Van then to the substantia nigra pars reticulate (SNr).
482 19 An Integrated Model of “Free Will” and New Free Will Questionnaires

Instruction
Sensory Input excitatory
Cong Incong

inhibitory

Frontal Cortex dopamine

DLPFC, SEF, FEF


pre-SMA R1 R2

ACC

Striatum

Go NoGo
STN
R1 R2 R1 R2

GPe
R1 R2

SC
SNr
SNc
R1 R2 R1 R2
Basal Ganglia

Fig. 19.1 Neural network model. The sensory input layer raising the gating threshold. Striatum is innervated by
projects to the frontal eye fields (FEF), striatum, and exec- dopamine (DA) from substantia nigra pars compacta
utive control (i.e., dorsolateral prefrontal cortex [DLPFC], (SNc), which amplifies Go relative to NoGo activity in
supplementary eye fields [SEF], and presupplementary proportion to reward value and allows the system to learn
motor area [pre-SMA]). Via direct projects to FEF (i.e., which actions to gate and which to suppress. The instruc-
cortico-cortical pathway), stimulus-responses-mappings tion layer represents abstract task cue (e.g., anti-saccade
can become ingrained (habitualized). FEF has excitatory trial). The DLPFC integrates the task cue together with
projections to the superior colliculus (SC) output layer the sensory input (i.e., stimulus location) to initiate a con-
that executes saccades once a threshold is crossed. trolled response corresponding to task rules, by activating
However, under baseline conditions, SC is inhibited by the appropriate column of units in FEF and striatum.
tonically active substantia nigra pars reticulate (SNr) Cong = congruent, Incong = incongruent, R1 = response 1,
units. Thus, for SC units to become excited, they have to R2 = response 2, ACC = anterior cingulate cortex,
be disinhibited via striatal direct pathway Go unit activa- Gpe = external segment of the globus pallidus. Adopted
tion and subsequent inhibition of corresponding SNr with permission of American Psychological Association.
units. Conversely, responses can be selectively suppressed Copyright © 2013 by the American Psychological
by striatal NoGo activity, via indirect inhibitory projec- Association. Reprinted with permission. The official cita-
tions from striatum to globus pallidus (GP) and then to tion that should be used in referencing this material is
SNr. Coactivation of mutually incompatible FEF response [Wiecki, T. V., & Frank, M. J. (2013). A computational
units leads to dorsal anterior cingulate cortex (dACC) model of inhibitory control in frontal cortex and basal
activity (conflict or entropy in choices), which activates ganglia. Psychological Review, 120, 329–355.]. The use
the subthalamic nucleus (STN). This STN surge makes it of APA information does not imply endorsement by APA.
more difficult to gate a response until the conflict is [Figure 1, Page 333]
resolved, via excitatory projections to SNr, effectively
Depletion 483

The dorsal anterior cingulate cortex (dACC) also involving reward value. Affective factors have
is involved when there are incongruent and been found in cognitive decision-making, as well
incompatible activities. The neurotransmitter in (Lerner, Li, Valdesolo, & Kassam, 2015).
this system consists of dopamine. This study does Inzlicht and Schmeichel (2012) also addressed
not relate directly to depletion effects in self-con- the underlying mechanism in ego-depletion.
trol, but it indicates the ubiquity of inhibition in They implicated an interaction between motiva-
brain–behavior relationships, and the complexi- tion and attention. According to the authors, the
ties that need to be taken into account in further proposed mechanism related to glucose availabil-
inhibitory model of self-control depletion. ity is less powerful than that of their own.
Specifically, in their model, at first, an initial
exertion in self-control shifts motivation toward
Motivation gratification and away from control. Second,
attention to cues shifts from ones for the need for
Botvinick and Braver (2015) considered that control to ones for indulgence or reward (see
motivation interacts with cognitive control in Fig. 19.2).
behavior. Work in the area should focus on Consistent with my other comments on the
reward in control models, which appears a more matter, I note that it is easy to translate these
fruitful approach than just fixating on resources shifts in terms of inhibition of control and activa-
and its depletion. Exerting control does have tion of gratification (i.e., to activation/inhibition
intrinsic subjective costs, but they are balanced coordination). Therapeutically, the concept of
by benefits in terms of the rewards or incentives activation/inhibition coordination being involved
in engagement. At the neuroscientific level, the in moderating resource/ego-depletion suggests
authors’ review showed that cognitive effort is that altering positively the dynamic involved at
associated with the executive control network, this level could help people maintain self-control,
which includes the DLPFC, the ACC, and the as in addictions.
intraparietal cortex. Other relevant networks in The research described by Inzlicht and
this regard relate to motivation, and include one Schmeichel (2012) supports their model. For

Fig. 19.2 The process model High


of ego-depletion. Belief in free Self-control works
will leads to behavioral
consequences, but it can be
depleted, e.g., in loss of “ego”
resources. Exertion in
self-control leads to self-control
failure later on. The mechanism Motivation shift
involves shifts in motivation
away from self-regulation. This
is accompanied by shifts toward Self-Control
self-gratification. Also, there are
shifts in attention away
from cues signaling the need Attention shift
for control and toward cues
signaling reward. Adapted from
Inzlicht and Schmeichel (2012)

Self-control fails
Low

Time
484 19 An Integrated Model of “Free Will” and New Free Will Questionnaires

example, Schmeichel, Harmon-Jones, and Methodologically, the series of studies by


Harmon-Jones (2010) showed that self-control Vohs et al. (2014) was noteworthy by having
exertion leads to stronger approach-related multiple experiments, manipulations, and mea-
impulses (e.g., low-stake gambles). For attention, sures. For example, the choices involved could be
Inzlicht and Al-Khindi (2012) found that self- either binding or reversible. They could be either
control application “dulls” the attentional sys- assigned or made spontaneously. They could
tem. These core mechanistic processes help have either no time limit in the task involved or
promote immediate gratification relative to better have one. They could involve either unsolvable
self-control. The authors maintained that the puzzles or time taken to try to solve solvable
model that they have proposed for self-control ones. Also, the impairment in self-control found
loss after its exertion avoids metaphorical lan- by Vohs et al. (2014) was shown on quite different
guage such as “ego depletion.” tasks, for example, physical stamina and toler-
Kurzban, Duckworth, Kable, and Myers ance for pain, persisting despite failure, and
(2013a, 2013b) questioned the value of any numerical calculation tasks.
resource model of reduced self-control with suc- Vohs et al. (2014) considered alternative
cessive cognitive effort. In commentaries to the explanations of self-control depletion for their
target article, variations in self-control models in results and ruled them out. For example, they
terms of will-power, ego-depletion, or glucose uti- considered that mood affects choice, that dura-
lization were not supported, nor were they tion affects choosing, that cognitive load could
defended to any noticeable degree. Kurzban et al. explain the depletion, and that mental effort and
supported a model that highlighted cost/benefit mental fatigue could explain it. In all these
analyses, computations, and motivation re- regards, the model that best explained the phe-
allocation. The authors defended their model with nomenon about self-control depletion was the
regard to Inzlicht and Schmeichel’s (2012) criti- one that they espoused of limited-resource model
cism that it is a cognitive “hyperrational” one. of self-regulation and executive function.
Dweck (2012) maintained that believing in
depletion is the cause of depletion, and not any
Cognitive metabolically-mediated (e.g., glucose-related)
effect. Also, see Job et al. (2010) on the matter.
Vohs et al. (2014) argued that the act of making Combining these ideas with those of
choices, in particular, is the factor that especially Baumeister on personal agency and social under-
depletes self-control. In this regard, they con- pinnings as well as Inzlicht and Schmeichel
ducted a series of studies. For example, they (2012) on motivation and attention in depletion
found that individuals who had to make choices control could lead to fruitful avenues in how to
showed self-control depletion compared to indi- bolster self-control.
viduals who did not have to make choices. The
act of choosing was more depleting of self-
control than only thinking about the options from Self
which to choose. In another study, the act of
choosing depleted self-control more than the pro- Hagger (2015) showed that Chen, Westman, and
cess of putting choices into action. Also, it was Hobfoll’s (2015) updated model of conservation
more depleting of control than forming a prefer- of resources (COR; e.g., Hobfoll, 1989) offers
ence while considering the options involved. ways to revise the “strength” or limited-resource
Vohs et al. (2014) concluded that choosing itself model of self-control (e.g., Baumeister et al.,
has a special place in self-control depletion. It 2007). In particular, in COR, the individual can
produces lasting changes in the individual’s men- use resources from different levels to regulate
tal structure by “etching” into it the requirement behavior and manage stress, including in per-
of what has to be done. sonal traits related to the self (efficacy, esteem).
Self-Regulation 485

These resources could help moderate the deple- presentation of work in the area, I present the
tion effect on self-regulatory capacity especially integrative model of the biological, psychologi-
by promoting resilience. cal (personal), and social influences on
self-control.

Comment
Self-Regulation
The review of the various models for ego/resource
depletion in self-control has covered the gamut of Introduction
possible influences. Biologically, glucose,
embodiment, and the default brain network have The book by Sokol, Grouzet, and Müller (2013)
been implicated. As for psychological factors, illustrates the biopsychosocial nature of self-
they concern cognition, belief, attention, motiva- regulation and self-control in relation to the
tion, personal belief, and power, as well as inhibi- development of autonomy. For example, Grouzet,
tion. Socially, a social baseline model has been Sokol, and Müller (2013) described that self-
proposed. In these regards, an integrative model regulation refers to the regulation of thought,
is needed to consider the multiple factors in ego/ emotion, and action by an inner self that is guided
resource depletion that acknowledge its biopsy- from the perspective of the organism’s goals and
chosocial complexity. purposes. Compared to self-regulation, self-
Moreover, it would attempt to find the under- control is a narrower concept involving selection
lying common mechanism on which the various of “desired” behavior.
influences act. Executive function concerns fac- For Deci and Ryan (2013), self-determination
tors such as working memory, shifting set, and involves different types of self-regulation that
inhibition. The research has shown that inhibition vary in their degree of external social influence.
is critical to maintaining self-control, and the all The self-determination types in their model
various factors that deplete it might affect inhibi- include—introjected (less autonomous); and
tory mechanisms in self-control. I have argued those that are more autonomous (identified,
that inhibition by itself is insufficient in the regu- intrinsic, integrated). Intrinsic forces might spec-
lation of behavior, because it is embedded in a ify what to value as being healthy (organismic
dynamic of activation/inhibition coordination valuing processes), although sociocognitive valu-
(Young, 2011) that needs to be considered in ing processes interact co-existentially with
brain/behavior relations. Therefore, the algo- organismic ones (Grouzet, 2013).
rithm of activation/inhibition coordination might
serve as the core nexus to help integrate the vari-
ous ego/resource depletion factors. Social
Another possible common factor in both the
phenomenon of ego/resource depletion and its The personal (autonomy) and social (communal)
possible underlying mechanism resides in dual- interact in self-growth and its regulation, with the
process modeling. Specifically, as self-control is dimension of being active or passive orthogonal
depleted, there might be an inability to continue to this one (Grouzet et al., 2013). Activity is evi-
to engage in higher-level deliberative, slow con- denced in self-organization and self-regulated
scious Type/System II thinking relative to lower- growth, although they both depend on social sup-
level automatic, fast, unconscious, Type/System port to achieve autonomy and related acquisi-
II thinking. Before reviewing dual model work, I tions. The acquisition of autonomy also depends
consider the area of self-regulation. on meta-cognitive abilities that facilitate self-
Self-regulation constitutes an area of work authoring and owning.
that is related to that of self-control and that illus- In short, in self-regulation, one finds a dialec-
trates the biopsychosocial factors involved. After tic between organismic and social (and cognitive)
486 19 An Integrated Model of “Free Will” and New Free Will Questionnaires

processes (e.g., respectively, organismic integra- activity in the orbito-frontal cortex (OFC). This
tion/valuing; emergence and social-cultural region is associated with coding reward value/
demands/metacognition). Parents and teachers motivation salience/liking aspects of desired
need to manifest balance in their support for food. The depleters also showed less functional
autonomy and in providing structure. activity coupling between the OFC and the
The child develops self-regulation in the sense inferior frontal gyrus. This region is associated
of voluntary control of impulses toward the ser- with self-control.
vice of personally-valued standards/goals The authors concluded that their data is con-
(Duckworth & Carlson, 2013). They develop sistent with the motivational model of Inzlicht
self-talk explanations to better internalize stan- and Schmeichel (2012) but, also, the data sup-
dard/goals, intentions, and so on, and then trans- ports the balance model of self-regulation
form/reformulate them into personal standards/ (Heatherton & Wagner, 2011). In ongoing self-
goals, intentions, etc. (Kinnucan & Kuebli, 2013, control, normally a balance is struck between
after Vygotsky). brain regions associated with impulse-control
and others involved in representing the reward
value, desirability, and emotional valence of
Biological stimuli (respectively, the lateral/medial areas of
the frontal cortex and the OFC and striatum). The
The biological component of self-regulation frontal portions of the brain are involved in exec-
involves serotonin-mediated impulse-constraint utive control and, in depletion/disruption, an
processes (Carver, Johnson, & Joormann, 2013) imbalance is set up in the reciprocally-tuned sys-
and dorsal and ventral limbic cortical divisions tems. This leads to a loss of inhibition of the sys-
(Waters & Tucker, 2013). More nuanced models tem for motivational salience, which serves to
(e.g., Grouzet et al., 2013) have replaced simpler free expression of impulses toward temptations
ones, such as that of Baumeister et al. (2007) on and also serves in a loss of self-regulation.
energy modulation and resource depletion of
self-regulation (control).
Moller, Deci, and Ryan (2006) found that Personal
autonomous types of self-regulation (intrinsic,
identified) were not associated with energy deple- Nucci (2013) examined self-regulation in the
tion. Rather, they appear to serve as a locus of context of personal choice. His model and
“psychological vitality.” However, consistent research place the personal component as a cen-
with the ego or energy/resource depletion model tral focus in self-regulation. For Nucci, children
of self-control (Baumeister et al., 2007), deple- develop in a personal domain as well as moral
tion in control was evident with less autonomous and social ones. They develop preferences and
self-regulation types (i.e., more controlled, predictions that enhance their sense of identity,
introjected). personal autonomy, and individuality. The pref-
Wagner, Altman, Boswell, Kelley, and erences relate to areas in which they can have
Heatherton (2013) presented functional neuroim- some authority in their personal zone of privacy,
aging data that implicated neural network altera- prerogatives, discretion, and own choices and
tions in self-regulatory depletion. A decisions. This manifests in their affirmative,
reward-associated center appeared enhanced, and committed noncompliance (resistance to external
connections between it and a center associated control). Children begin to show the development
with self-control appeared reduced in connectiv- of their personal domain in their play and social
ity. Specifically, chronic dieters were exposed to relations with friends. Personhood in these areas
appetizing or desirable foods, and half of them is self-constructed. According to Nucci (2013),
had completed a self-regulatory depletion task. this happens in developing people in all cultures,
The depleters showed greater food-cue related who actively construct and express this zone no
Dual-Process Models 487

matter what mixture of individualistic and collec- basic architecture in information processing (e.g.,
tivistic tendencies that the culture expresses. Smith & DeCoster, 2000).
Dual-process theories focus on functionally
distinct mental processes. Dual representation
Dual-Process Models theories emphasize different behavior outcomes
linked to functionally distinct mental representa-
Models tions. Other models include both process and rep-
resentation (dual system theories). The latter
Introduction Dual-process theories in social theories note the similarities of sets of features
psychology constitute one of its most significant (e.g., associative vs. rule-based) and seek domain-
developments (Gawronski, Sherman, & Trope, independent accounts of the human mind.
2014). They are concerned with mechanisms Gawronski et al. (2014) concluded that there
(algorithms; Marr, 1982) that mediate or translate are not only dual process but also uniprocess and
inputs into outputs. In Marr’s system, the compu- multiprocess models of mind. Nevertheless, the
tational level concerns input–output relations. dual-process models are more influential.
The implementation level concerns (neural)
underpinnings. Simply, dual-processing theories Variations In their work on dual processes,
divide mental processes into automatic and non- Baumeister and Bargh (2014) argued that both
automatic ones. The book by Sherman, conscious and unconscious processes contribute
Gawronski, and Trope (2014) illustrates the to guiding behavior. The unconscious influences
range of dual-process theories and the scope of on behavior are known to be powerful (Freud,
their operational application. 1933/1965), and contemporary research supports
Gawronski et al. (2014) clarified the distinction their influence on behavior (e.g., Bargh, 2005).
between what dual-process theories try to explain However, this does not mean that conscious will
(empirical explanandum) and the theoretical is an “illusion” (Wegner, 2002).
assumptions behind the explanations (explanans). The authors contended that one way that the
Events lead to observed behavior, which is a way two systems could be complementary is that con-
of depicting causal explanation. However, asking scious thoughts ultimately are in charge of
about the “how” of the caused or resultant behav- actions. However, unconscious processes provide
ior by the event goes one step further by seeking input and support. In another integrative view,
mechanism (mechanistic explanation). normally, unconscious processes govern behav-
Mental mechanisms also are called operating ior. In addition, conscious ones can intervene
principles. They function in operating conditions. occasionally by overriding, regulating, redirect-
If a mental process is automatic, we still might not ing, and altering the course of behavior, thereby
know the how behind the automaticity. We need providing a supporting role (Baumeister &
to learn each of when there is no conscious aware- Masicampo, 2010). Only consciousness can inte-
ness, the goal of any automatic activity, the pres- grate and manage the different potential response
ence of any associated cognitive resource outputs (Morsella, 2005).
reduction, and if the goal could include altering or Consciousness is like a navigational system
stopping the process (Bargh, 1994). However, that can simulate mentally different possible
knowing this still does not give us the how of the streams of behavior and their associated probable
automaticity. consequences. The unconscious can work with
Dual-process theories could be either domain- these mental projections in its decision-making
specific or generalized. The latter integrate and and implementation. However, it cannot construct
seek applicable rules over content (e.g., automa- complex plans itself. Consciousness sets the
ticity is associative rather than rule-based; goals/desired end states, while the unconscious
Sloman, 1996). They are concerned with the organizes actions toward their completion.
488 19 An Integrated Model of “Free Will” and New Free Will Questionnaires

Behavior might begin with unconscious Cushman and Greene (2012) contrasted (a)
impulses but the conscious is needed to imagine intuitive attitudes and (b) explicit moral principles
and plan, as well as self-regulate toward the or commitments. They indicated that their tug-of-
plan’s unfolding that the unconscious executes. If war enables achievement of a “reflective equilib-
there are competing or conflicting motivations, rium.” This approach reminds me of the
consciousness mediates, especially in allowing dual-process models of cognition (Stanovich
the “higher” impulse to predominate. In short, we et al., 2014), which also consider intuitive and
need the unconscious to plan, reason logically, more advanced models.
interpret, communicate, anticipate, and simulate,
or otherwise to facilitate adaptive responses.
Types
Others Newell (2015) supported the utility and
advantage of conscious higher-order compared to Stanovich et al. (2014) referred to their dual-
implicit, unconscious cognition in the context of processing theory in terms of Type I and Type II
complex perceptual category learning and also processing. The former type is marked by auton-
multi-attribute decision-making. When higher- omy and the latter is marked by inhibitory mech-
order thought “takes over” in these contexts, the anisms, which enables cognitive decoupling of
outcomes are more “optimal.” real-world and imaginary representations. Type
Edelman and Tononi (2000) related conscious II processing is subdivided into the algorithmic
experience to the activation/deactivation of dis- (fluid intelligence) and the reflective (rational
tributed neuronal populations. They described a thinking dispositions, including higher-level goal
higher-order consciousness evolving in humans states and epistemic thinking dispositions that
beyond a basic primary consciousness. It includes regulate behavior at a more general level).
concepts of the self, past, future, and of con- Evans and Stanovich (2013) added that Type I
sciousness itself. They related consciousness to a processes constitute the default type, and are
high degree of neural complexity, which is based qualitatively-different from higher-order reason-
on information in the neural system. ing processes (Type II), which are used to inter-
Sloman (2014) updated his earlier (Sloman, vene on Type I processes, as needed (e.g., for
1996) associative vs. rule-based dual-process difficulty, novelty) and if not inhibited. Type I
model by referring to intuition (e.g., pattern rec- and II cognitive processes correspond roughly to
ognition) and deliberation (e.g., thoughtful, intuitive and reflective thought. The latter requires
reflective) thinking modes. The former is genera- working memory (and controlled attention) and
tive and might be capable of sophisticated sym- functions with cognitive decoupling (distinguish
bolic causal reasoning. The latter serves to supposition from belief; run through experi-
attenuate the former, via gating, which is a modu- ments) and mental stimulation. Typically, Type II
lating inhibitory mechanism, which might be processes are slower, serial, conscious, abstract,
“leaky” or not always successful. The two sys- rule-based, and flexibly controlled, with import
tems interact, for example, when there is a novel for decision-making, hypothetical thinking, and
cognitive act that is needed (problem solving, cognitive ability, including fluid intelligence,
decision-making). The intuitive system is tightly which is more related to a subcomponent, the
linked to affect, while the deliberate system is algorithmic mind. Also, it can vary in mode, e.g.,
amenable to direct control through “force of between holistic and analytic styles (see
will.” The strong view is that the systems are dis- Fig. 19.3). Evans and Stanovich (2013) noted that
tinct with their own brain circuitry, yet they are the two thinking types have different underlying
complementary and interactive. neural substrates.
Dual-Process Models 489

Fig. 19.3 Knowledge Knowledge Structures


structures in the tripartite
framework. The figure Beliefs, Goals, and
Reflective Mind
illustrates the distinction General Knowledge
between automatic,
intuitive, algorithmic,
unconscious thought and
reflective, deliberate,
autonomous, conscious
thought. Adopted with Strategies and Algorithmic
permission of Elsevier.
Production Systems Mind
Reprinted from
Developmental Review,
Vol. 31, Stanovich, K. E., Type II Processing
West, R. F., & Toplak,
M. E., The complexity of Type I Processing
developmental predictions
from dual process models,
Pages 103–118, Copyright Tightly Compiled
2011; with kind permission Learned Information Autonomous
from Elsevier. [Figure 1, Mind
Page 107] Encapsulated
Knowledge Base

Brain tion at the superior temporal sulcus (TPJ/STS),


and the anterior temporal cortex (aTC). The MZS
Spunt and Lieberman (2013, 2014) related more is involved in inferring mental states, traits, social
automatic behavior (identification) to the brain’s context, and so on. Both brain systems are impor-
mirror neuron system (MNS). They related the tant in social perception, but they subserve differ-
capacity for making controlled social causal ent systems, with one more automatic and the
inferences or attributions to the brain’s mentalizing other more mentalizing.
system (MZS). The MNS appears to make sense
of the body’s actions and the MZS uses the infor-
mation to make sense of what is going on in Piaget
another person’s mind. Participants were asked
how a viewed behavior occurred or why (e.g., Pons, Harris, and de Rosnay (2012) described
reaching for phone in order to speak). This study Piaget’s approach to consciousness. In terms of
by Spunt and Lieberman (2012) showed that the its evolution with cognitive stages of develop-
two brain systems were recruited for the different ment, Piaget (1974) described three levels, with
task goals in the way hypothesized. correspondences to the stages of sensorimotor
Spunt and Lieberman (2014) indicated that the intelligence, representation (the pre-operational
MNS includes the dorsal (dPMC) and ventral and concrete operational stages), and formal,
(vPMC) regions of the premotor cortex, as well as abstract intelligence.
a region of the parietal cortex in the rostral inferior For Piaget, in the sensorimotor period, con-
parietal lobule (IPL) that extends into the intrapa- sciousness is practical and nonreflective (e.g.,
rietal sulcus (IPS). Mirror neurons translate sen- consciousness of an activation and its success/
sory input about another person’s motor actions failure). In the representational period, con-
into representations of the goals of the actions. sciousness is conceptual (e.g., consciousness of
The MZS includes the dorsomedial prefrontal the purpose of actions and the means to achieve
cortex (dmPFC), a portion of the medial parietal them, their organization, and the causative rela-
cortex from the precunius to the posterior cingu- tionship between means–goals). In the formal
late cortex (PC/PCC), the temporoparietal junc- period, consciousness is reflective (conscious-
490 19 An Integrated Model of “Free Will” and New Free Will Questionnaires

ness of one’s cognitive functions and the objects For the Type I–II model, the right prefrontal
of knowledge). I developed the concept of collec- cortex and the dorsolateral prefrontal cortex seem
tive intelligence in 1997 in a book on cognitive implicated, for example, as well as the parietal
development (Young, 1997, 2011). It refers to lobe (Evans & Stanovich, 2013). As for the men-
advanced adult logical thought. Higher forms of talizing system, there are similarities and differ-
consciousness (e.g., involving superordinate ences in proposed associations with brain areas
reflective abstractions) beyond the one related to (medial frontal and parietal cortices, temporo-
the abstract, formal period would be related to it, parietal junction, anterior temporal cortex; Spunt
as well. [Note that in 1997, Lévy also published a & Lieberman, 2013).
book using the term of collective intelligence, but To conclude, creating an integrated model of
to apply to cyberspace (Lévy, 1997).] different processing modes related to cognition
Kopp (2011) maintained that a nonverbal con- both for reasoning and social cognition might be
sciousness of body and actions develops in a goal worthy of consideration. In this regard,
infancy. In this regard, as mentioned, she noted Young (2011) has related Type I and Type II
that Piaget had developed the concept of a “prac- thought to Piaget’s conception of pre-operational/
tical” consciousness in infancy. At this age, the concrete operational and more advanced thought.
infant is conscious of his or her behavior and its As well, Young’s model of five stages in Neo-
effects, including emotions experienced. Piagetian development (with five substages each)
According to Kopp, signs of consciousness might and corresponding socioemotional (Neo-
even be evident prenatally and in the newborn Eriksonian) (sub)stages at each step over the
period (Rochat, 2003; Trevarthen & Aitken, lifespan, might be informative in this regard.
2001; Zelazo, Hong Gao, & Todd, 2007). For the They have been related to Piagetian development
latter, it would be a general, minimal, multidi- by Barrouillet (2011), with automatic ones con-
mensional consciousness. Nelson (2007) placed sidered pre-operational, and nonautomatic ones
its onset in the period after birth, later in the first considered operational.
year. For Kopp (2011), the infant’s self-owned Specifically, Barrouillet (2011) reviewed dual-
actions, simple awareness, and phenomenal process models of reasoning, as applied to devel-
experience of consciousness are indicators of a opment, and related them to Piaget’s cognitive
palpable body and action consciousness. developmental model. The central distinction
between the levels in the various dual-process
models is that the less advanced one is uncon-
Comment scious, automatic, implicit, contextualized, effort-
less, emotion-linked, intuitive, heuristic, and
There are similarities in the various dual-process probabilistic (System/Type I) and the more
models in terms of having a more basic and a advanced one is conscious, deliberative, explicit,
more advanced mode of thought, but more work decontextualized, non-emotional, reflective, ana-
is needed to integrate differences in simpler and lytic, controlled, effortful, and mental (e.g., repre-
abstract cognitions and simpler and abstract senting alternative possibilities, System/Type II).
social processing, as well as their brain network An integrated approach should consider metacog-
underpinnings. It could be that the Piagetian nitive processes and conditional reasoning.
model offers a way of expanding the type/system These models are mostly based on the work of
view of differential processing into a model with Stanovich (1999, 2009, 2011; Stanovich, West, &
more than two options, which is inherent in the Toplak, 2011) and Evans (2009, 2010, 2011a,
Stanovich model anyway, and in other models 2011b). Nevertheless, Barrouillet (2011) noted
that are more than bifactorial. However, that said, that both authors present a possible third System/
there is good evidence at the level of the brain Type (III). Further, Barrouillet (2011) remarked
that the two systems proposed have differential that System/Type I thought is not necessarily
neuronal underpinnings, replaced by System/Type II thought, and that
A Combined Biopsychosocial/Depletion, Dual-Process/Consciousness-Unconsciousness… 491

System/Type I thought stands as the default process (e.g., motivation) accounts. In the model,
model in cognition. within a central governor, subconscious compu-
According to Barrouillet (2011), the distinction tations integrate sensory/physiological and con-
in Piaget’s model (Piaget & Inhelder, 1941, 1954) ceptual/motivational influences on resisting loss
between the pre-operational stage and the concrete of self-control, as well as contextual factors (e.g.,
operational stage parallels to a degree the model of current workload, available energy, goal value,
System/Type I and System/Type II thought, opportunity costs, anticipated future exertion).
respectively, given the association of the two This modeling approach by Evans et al. (2015) is
stages with intuitive and rational (albeit concrete) consistent with my own.
logical thought, respectively. Moreover, to further
the analogy, Piaget added a stage after the concrete
operational level (formal operations), which is Model
consistent with aspects of System/Type III models
(both involve “higher-order” operations). However, an appropriate model of self-control
Barrouillet (2011) concluded that develop- and self-regulation should allow both for
mental psychology has a long-standing history in dynamic shifting due to the influence of multiple
construing dual-process thinking, but that by systemic factors and the development of longer-
integrating Piaget in the work a more inclusive term capacities (progressively or regressively).
model could be found. I concur fully with this In this sense, Fig. 19.4 presents an integrative
suggestion, and elsewhere in the present book model of progressive and regressive influences
(see Chap. 32), I describe how the multiple stages on self-regulation and the bifurcation or shifting
and substages in Piaget’s theory can function point toward progressive or regressive outcomes.
simultaneously, depending on the problem at The general dynamic appears to be one of activa-
hand, ending up yoked together toward adaptive tion/inhibition coordination. Finally, the
ends (Young, 2011). moment-to-moment decision points in self-regu-
lation appear outcomes of both specific cost/ben-
efit analysis and resource availability. Note the
A Combined Biopsychosocial/ latter can be “depleted,” but the concept is meant
Depletion, Dual-Process/ as a broad one and not just related to metabolic/
Consciousness-Unconsciousness energetic availability, will power, and the like.
Model in Behavioral Causality Rather, it refers to an integration of personal,
social, and biological resources at all levels that
Introduction serve to support self-regulatory decisions and
subsequent actions. In addition, by their very
The models on self-control to date appear static nature, systems models do not give primacy to
and they especially focus on one area of study, or isolated component influences as causal but con-
changes in a second self-control task after the sider their interactive dynamics as the driver of
“depletion” induced by a first one. Moreover, change and development.
despite their differences, they appear to converge
on the importance of cognitive, emotional/moti-
vation, and contextual (e.g., reward) factors in Evidence
self-control.
Increasingly, workers are integrating diverse Literature supportive of the proposed model
factors that influence self-control. Evans, includes the following. Inzlicht and Schmeichel
Boggero, and Segerstrom (2015) proposed a mul- (2012, 2013) have gravitated away from a strict
tiple input or factor model of self-regulatory resource model of self-control, for example, as
fatigue/ego-depletion that incorporates the physi- represented in the “ego depletion” effect. As
ological substrate (glucose) and psychological already noted, the resource model involves
492 19 An Integrated Model of “Free Will” and New Free Will Questionnaires

Deliberative/ Conscious Personal Belief


Thought (II)

(e.g., social)
Supportive Motivation Progressive Self-Control
Influences
Reward Cognitive
Salience Skill/ Level

Cost-Benefit Analysis Self-Regulation


(Specific) (Specific)

Progressive/ Regressive Progressive or


Bifurcation Point Regressive Outcome
External
Context

Resource Activation-Inhibition
Availability Coordination
(General) (General)

Impulsive “Depletion”
NonSupportive

Automatic/ Regressive
Unconscious Thought Insufficient
Influences
(I) Glucose

Fatigue Temptation

Genes/ Epigenesis Internal Context Brain


Embodiment
Time (Developmental)

Fig. 19.4 A biopsychosocial model of depletion and dual benefit model of Kurzban et al. (2013a, 2013b; which
processing. Depletion and dual process thought need to be includes motivational and other factors), and the balance
considered in the broader context of the biopsychosocial model of Heatherton (Heatherton & Wagner, 2011;
model. The model in the figure considers progressive and Wagner & Heatherton, 2013). The model is a dynamical
regressive changes that are possible in self-regulation. It systems one that accounts for moment-to-moment
presents an integrated model of self-control that considers changes, which in turn contribute to longer-term changes,
biological/physical factors (e.g., physiology, fatigue, and to development. Being a dynamical systems model, it
brain), social ones (e.g., support), and personal psycho- is open to self-organizing, nonlinear, qualitative (emer-
logical ones (e.g., cognitive skill level, which includes gent) changes in state. The activation/inhibition coordina-
automatic, conscious (Type/System I) and deliberative, tion dynamic is essential in this process. The model
unconscious (Type/System II) thought. It integrates the includes new conceptualizations (e.g., epigenetic effect of
resource depletion model of Baumeister (2008; Galinsky, genes, embodiment) that need elucidation of the specific
Maddux, Gilin, & White, 2008), the motivational empha- roles that they might play in self-control in the context of
sis in Inzlicht and Schmeichel (2012, 2013), the cost- the multiple factors in the model

difficulties in self-control after having engaged in the second task. Motivation and cues associated
a first, different self-control task. Instead of this with self-gratification/immediate reward become
model, they proposed a process, mechanistic favored, facilitating impulsive action.
model involving effects on attention and motiva- Other models have been developed to replace
tion that serve to undermine the self-control for the standard ego-depletion model of reduced
Free Will and Depletion Questionnaires 493

self-control with sequential cognitive effort. For will. Overall, the questionnaire consists of 27
example, as shown earlier in the chapter, aside items, but for free will itself, only 7 items are
from motivational aspects that might contribute involved and an elaborate protocol of factor anal-
in making choices, the general issue of cost- ysis revealed that the items are organized into
benefit analysis needs to be considered (Kurzban four independent dimensions—free will, scien-
et al., 2013a, 2013b). Particularly, cost-benefit tific determinism, fatalistic determinism, and
analysis refers to mental representations, and unpredictability (see Table 19.1). Paulhus and
their computational mechanisms related to exec- Carey (2011) maintained that the factors that
utive function, which is limited in its ability to be emerged are relatively orthogonal and are inter-
deployed over tasks. In another model (Heatherton nally consistent. They found correlations show-
& Wagner, 2011), self-control is considered the ing that believing in free will is not equivalent to
outcome of competing forces in impulse strength having an internal locus of control, and that,
relative to self-control strength. among the Big Five personality traits, it is associ-
ated with extroversion and agreeableness.

Comment Free Will Inventory Nadelhoffer, Shepard,


Nahmias, Sripada, and Thomson Ross (2014)
To conclude, the present model of self-control, developed a new measure of free will belief after
includes the resource depletion paradigm, but is showing the limitations of extant measures. For
an integrated one. However, its development example, one such scale is the Free Will and
should continue so that it becomes a genuinely Determinism Scale (Rakos et al., 2008). It places
biopsychosocial one. on opposite poles of its scale free will and deter-
Self-control constitutes and important driver minism (as incompatible). However, from a philo-
of behavior and helps the person circumnavigate sophical point of view, it is possible to believe in
powerful influences of biology and environment, both constructs (which refers to the approach of
past and present, and passivity and inertia. In this compatibilism). Paulhus and Carey (2011) avoided
regard, work on behavioral causality needs the this confusion in constructing orthogonal scales for
type integrative model proposed. free will and determinism (see Table 19.2).
However, Nadelhoffer et al. (2014) noted that
the fatalistic determinism subscale in Paulhus
Free Will and Depletion and Carey (2011) gives scores that correlate with
Questionnaires those on their unpredictability subscale.
Moreover, Nadelhoffer et al. (2014) noted that
Introduction scores for fatalistic determinism do not correlate
negatively with scores on the free will subscale.
In the next section of the chapter, I analyze Also, among the seven items in the latter scale,
questionnaires on free will, which are quite recent, three of them involve responsibility and blame,
and then I propose a new one. The extant ones which are not direct representations of free will.
involve few items, but mine is extensive with Finally, the scientific determinism subscale of the
many items, and it tries to cover free will and FAD-Plus includes items about genes and envi-
related aspects, in a biopsychosocial approach. ronmental influences on behavior rather than the
After, I propose a depletion questionnaire. philosophical understanding of determinism (that
sufficient causes exist for every event).
The Free Will Inventory that Nadelhoffer et al.
Extant Free Will Questionnaires (2014) developed after critiquing prior question-
naires is an instrument with 29 items overall, but
FAD-Plus Paulhus and Carey (2011) described with only a few related directly to a subscale on
the development of their questionnaire on free free will. In Part I, there are three five-item sub-
will, which concerned laypersons’ beliefs of free scales (on free will, determinism, and dualism/
494 19 An Integrated Model of “Free Will” and New Free Will Questionnaires

Table 19.1 FAD-Plus: free will and determinism questionnaire subscales and items
Subscale Items
Free will People have complete control over the decisions they make.
People must take full responsibility for any bad choices they make.
People can overcome any obstacles if they truly want to.
Criminals are totally responsible for the bad things they do.
People have complete free will.
People are always at fault for their bad behavior.
Strength of mind can always overcome the body’s desires.
Scientific Determinism People’s biological makeup determines their talents and personality.
Psychologists and psychiatrists will eventually figure out all human behavior.
Your genes determine your future.
Science has shown how your past environment created your current intelligence and
personality.
As with other animals, human behavior always follows the laws of nature.
Parents’ character will determine the character of their children.
Childhood environment will determine your success as an adult.
Fatalistic Determinism I believe that the future has already been determined by fate.
No matter how hard you try, you can’t change your destiny.
Fate already has a plan for everyone.
Whatever will be, will be—there’s not much you can do about it.
Whether people like it or not, mysterious forces seem to move their lives.
Unpredictability Chance events seem to be the major causes of human history.
No one can predict what will happen in this world.
Life seems unpredictable—just like throwing dice or flipping a coin.
People are unpredictable.
Life is hard to predict because it is almost totally random.
Luck plays a big role in people’s lives.
What happens to people is a matter of chance.
People futures cannot be predicted.
Adopted with permission of Taylor & Francis Ltd. Paulhus, D. L., & Carey, J. M. (2011). The FAD-Plus: Measuring
lay beliefs regarding free will and related constructs. Journal of Personality Assessment, 93, 96–104. Reprinted by
permission of the publisher (Taylor & Francis Ltd., http://www.tandfonline.com). [Appendix, Page 104]

anti-reductionism). Part II contains 14 items— item is—each person has a non-physical essence
seven about the nature of free will and seven that makes that person unique.
about moral responsibility. Although the three five-item scales in Part I of
Part I was developed over four rounds of the Nadelhoffer et al. inventory was subject to
research using factor analysis. The participants confirmatory factor analysis, the 14 items in Part
were more representative of the general popula- II of the scale were not. They were built in order
tion compared to those in Paulhus and Carey to explore in more depth associated beliefs and
(2011). The five free will items include state- attitudes about free will, determinism, and so on.
ments such as—people always have free will; Aside from this limitation of the study, there are
people ultimately have complete control over others to note. First, the validation research did not
their decisions and actions. The determinism include use of other measures to examine relevant
scale in Nadelhoffer et al. (2014) includes the relationships (e.g., another free will questionnaire,
item—everything that has ever happened had to a related concept such as locus of control).
happen precisely as it did, given what had hap- Second, some of the items are complexly writ-
pened before. As for an example of dualism, one ten or seem removed from the topic at hand given
Free Will and Depletion Questionnaires 495

Table 19.2 The free will inventory: subscales and items


Subscales Items
Free will People always have the ability to do otherwise.
People always have free will.
How people’s lives unfold is completely up to them.
People ultimately have complete control over their decisions and their actions.
People have free will even when their choices are completely limited by external
circumstances.
Determinism Everything that has ever happened had to happen precisely as it did, given what
happened before.
Every event that has ever occurred, including human decisions and actions, was
completely determined by prior events.
People’s choices and actions must happen precisely the way they do because of
the laws of nature and the way things were in the distant past.
A supercomputer that could know everything about the way the universe is now
could know everything about the way the universe will be in the future.
Given the way things were at the Big Bang, there is only one way for everything
to happen in the universe after that.
Dualism/anti-reductionism The fact that we have souls that are distinct from our material bodies is what
makes humans unique.
Each person has a non-physical essence that makes that person unique.
The human mind cannot simply be reduced to the brain.
The human mind is more than just a complicated biological machine.
Human action can only be understood in terms of our souls and minds and not just
in terms of our brains.
Adopted with permission of Elsevier. Reprinted from Consciousness and Cognition, Vol. 25, Nadelhoffer, T., Shepard,
J., Nahmias, E., Sripada, C., & Thomson Ross, L., The free will inventory: Measuring beliefs about agency and respon-
sibility, Copyright 2014; with kind permission from Elsevier. [Excerpt of 250 words, Pages 34–35]

their philosophical origin. Examples, respec- trum of categories of items that could be involved
tively, include: (a) people have free will even in free will (see Table 19.3). In developing items
when their choices are completely limited by for an improved free will questionnaire, I accom-
external circumstances, and (b) people always modated to the limitations attributed to extant
have the ability to do otherwise. questionnaires (e.g., Nadelhoffer et al., 2014;
For the items in Part II, in this regard, exam- Paulhus & Carey, 2011). In particular, I chose/cre-
ples, respectively, include: (a) free will is the ated questions that are both face valid and ame-
ability to make different choices even if every- nable to tests of construct and related validity.
thing leading up to one’s choice (e.g., the past, The tables showing the items on free will that
the situation, and their desire, beliefs, etc.) were could be used to construct a new questionnaire
exactly the same and (b) free will is the ability to include items directly on free will, but they are
make a choice based on one’s beliefs and desires organized into the components of cognitive,
such that if one had different beliefs or desires, socioemotional, self, mental construction, and
one’s choice would have been different, as well. action components of free will. The placement of
the items is driven by psychological constructs
rather than empirical factor analysis. Moreover,
Proposed New Scale on Free Will for each of the five categories that I highlighted
as relevant to free will, I described multiple sub-
Questionnaire Table 19.3 presents possible categories. This procedure might appear some-
items for a scale on free will that emphasizes what arbitrary, but it does give an indication of
choices and decisions, and covers the full spec- the range of factors involved in free will belief.
496 19 An Integrated Model of “Free Will” and New Free Will Questionnaires

Table 19.3 The positive free will belief and related belief questionnaire in five major categories (seven examples each)
Category Examples
Cognitive I freely see problems as they are.
I freely choose to find all the options before continuing.
I can justify in detail why I do anything.
I freely choose my way in everything I do.
I always have the choice to make my decisions my way.
I know what is right for me.
I always choose to think for myself.
Social-emotional I freely choose to help people.
I freely choose to do what’s right for other people.
Knowing I am free in everything I do lets me take my responsibilities easier.
I believe that people should pay for the harm they cause others.
I choose to be moral on my terms and not in the way others tell me.
The more I believe in freedom in choosing, the more I understand how other people might have
problems believing in it.
The more I believe in freedom in choosing, the more I empathize with people.
Self I am strong and determined, willful.
My power lies in me and not in others.
I can overcome obstacles.
I am assertive without being offensive.
I can change myself if I want to or have to.
I can change things that are not going well.
When I feel I am being me, people get the best of me.
Mental I make sense of the world my way.
construction I explain things and events my way.
I interpret what happens my way.
The messages I get from things and events that happen are up to me to make.
The meanings in things and events come from how I see them.
Things and events are as important as I let them be.
What is useful in a situation is for me to decide.
Action I freely choose to act the way I want.
I freely choose to live the way I want.
I can freely choose to act differently than I am acting now.
I control the series of actions made by me.
I control the series of actions made by others.
I keep on track.
I stop wrong actions.
Note. These questions can be rephrased to construct a general rather than personal free will belief questionnaire.
They can stay in the present format, or some items might need to be reversed. The answers can be provided on a
7-point Likert scale (strongly disagree to strongly agree). Factor analytic studies should be constructed to determine
their dimensional structure. As per Nadelhoffer et al. (2014), the studies addressing the final organization of the
questionnaire should use explanatory factor analysis (principle components, eigenvalues > 1, oblique rotations factor
loadings > 0.400) and then confirmatory factor analysis (checking model fit using the Goodness of Fit index, the
Comparative Fit Index, and Adjusted Goodness of Fit index, the Root Mean Square Error of Approximation, and, to
a lesser degree, the Chi Square test)
Free Will and Depletion Questionnaires 497

Associated Questionnaire The second table of constructed items that help investigate further each
the two that I constructed toward developing a new of the five major components of a broad construct
free will questionnaire borrows from Nadelhoffer of free will that was identified in Table 19.4.
et al. (2014) the idea that a second set of items can Specifically, I examined relevant subcategories for
be used to determine the types of associations and possible items of free will belief related to the cog-
extensions related to free will. In this regard, nitive, social–emotional, self, mental construction,
instead of finding items that allow determination and action components in Table 19.4. In each case,
of subtle philosophical questions, as had been the I developed the items related to free will belief in
case for Nadelhoffer et al., I adopted a broader terms of eight associated subcategories (three
psychological perspective on the question, and items per set).

Table 19.4 The positive free will belief and related belief questionnaire in subcategories (5 categories, with 8 subcat-
egories; 3 examples each)
Category Subcategory Examples
Cognitive Attention I have a good ability to pay attention in seeing a problem, thinking,
deciding, and acting.
In doing this, I see all the aspects or things I need to consider in the
situation, problem, and so on.
When I pay attention, I do not leave anything out so I can follow up with
free choice in my behavior.
Selection/detection Because I pay attention around me, I see what is important to notice.
I select important things to keep in mind as I deal with a problem.
I put up front what I select to consider, so that I might act on the
information appropriately.
Choice Of all the choices I have in a situation, I am the one who can choose the
best one.
No matter what situation I’m in and no matter how many things in it are
not of my making, I’m still the one who can choose what to do.
People tell me what to do, but I choose what to do despite what they say.
Deciding I can decide which choices I have in a situation.
I can decide which choices to choose and act on in a situation, no matter
what all the influences in the situation are.
I have control of my decisions in a situation.
Reason/logic/thinking There are valid reasons to everything I do because I always reason what I
do.
I believe that being logical is the only way to be.
When you think through everything involved, you’re really thinking.
Memory In solving problems, I keep the problem in mind.
In solving problems, I remember the possible solutions.
In solving problems, I keep my mind and memory free by avoiding
distractions, losing focus and keeping my mind from wandering.
Shifting set When one solution is not working in solving a problem, I can easily try
another instead of staying with it.
I don’t get trapped in dead-ends in my thinking.
I’m flexible in my thinking.
Inhibition We have to be able to not only think the right way, but also stop thinking
the wrong way.
When I push away a bad choice, it makes it easier to choose a good one.
For every situation, I consider the pros and cons, advantages and
disadvantages, and what to do and avoid doing.
(continued)
498 19 An Integrated Model of “Free Will” and New Free Will Questionnaires

Table 19.4 (continued)


Category Subcategory Examples
Social/ Morality I am free when I choose the right or moral thing no matter what.
emotional I believe that when you are truly free, you choose to help others.
I believe that being free is stopping immorality.
Responsibility I choose to be responsible in what I do in my life; it is me.
I believe that people should be responsible in how they undertake their
daily roles and in deal with people.
I believe that people make good choices when they are responsible in
what they do in the home and outside.
Respect I respect others in the way I wish others would respect me.
I respect what other people say and consider the options they give me,
but I still choose what to do.
I respect others’ right to have opinions.
Harm I like to help other people and not harm them.
I encourage other people not to be harmful.
Stopping other people from harming is important.
Relaxation/emotional I can think, decide, choose, and act freely because I am always
regulation emotionally balanced.
I can still think, decide, choose, and act freely after I get hyper or
stressed out.
I can think, decide, choose, and act freely, not letting my emotions cloud
my judgments.
Being present I am always present in the moment.
I live in the present, instead of being prisoner of the past.
Living in the present lets me live better in the future.
Conscious (mindful) I am aware not only of myself but also of the others.
Consciousness is not just about me; it is about others, too.
Being conscious of others and of myself go together.
Relatedness Part of how I consider myself socially is that I stay who I am in dealing
with, relating to, and being with others.
I seek to understand who I am in terms of my dealing with, relating to,
and being with others.
I value who I am in terms of my dealing with, relating to, and being with
others.
Self Definition of self Part of my personal definition of me is that I am myself in my thinking,
decisions, and actions.
I seek to understand who I am in terms of being myself in my thinking,
decisions, and actions.
I value who I am in terms of being myself in my thinking, decisions, and
actions.
Completeness I feel complete in my definition of self.
I feel complete in understanding myself.
I feel complete in valuing myself.
Autonomy I am an individual, independent of others.
I am my own person; I am myself, thinking for myself.
My behavior is not directed by outside factors, but is self-directed.
Initiative I take the initiative needed; I am not passive.
I am motivated; I do what I have to when I have to.
I am a go-getter; getting what I want.
(continued)
Free Will and Depletion Questionnaires 499

Table 19.4 (continued)


Category Subcategory Examples
Self-control I have self-control no matter what.
I believe that being free does not mean doing what you want no matter
what.
I believe that being free is not just about desire and doing but also is
resisting temptation.
Ownership I take ownership of my self/my mistakes (decisions, choices, actions,
behavior).
I take ownership of my (choices) errors/mistakes.
I take ownership of my responsibilities.
Self-confidence I believe in myself.
I have confidence in myself.
I know how to behave and to be myself.
Self-deception I do not like to deceive myself; seeing clearly is better.
I try not to lie to myself.
I try to face things as they are.
Mental Memory building What I remember is not just about what happens or about things; I build
construction memories my way.
I have a say in how events and things are remembered.
I build my memories myself; I don’t let others do it for me.
Meaning I have a say in the meanings that are important to get from events and
things.
I see events and things my way.
I understand what happens in terms of what is right for me.
Concepts I build concepts on what the world is about; these concepts are mine, not
from others.
I build concepts this way also on what I am about.
I build concepts this way also on what others are about.
Internal source of control I control my mind not my brain or body.
I’m in charge of my brain and body.
I’m my boss, not my brain or body.
External source of What others think controls how I think.
control What others feel controls how I feel.
What others do controls how I act.
Stress What is stressful is something I decide; it does not come straight from
the outside.
Stress is what I perceive and believe about any situation.
I can cope with any stress, no matter what it is.
Culture Culture (family, country) might tell me what to think, but I am the one
who decides what to think.
Culture (family, country) might tell me what to feel, but I am the one
who decides what to feel.
Culture (family, country) might tell me what to do, but I am the one who
decides what to do.
Causation I am the cause of my thinking.
I am the cause of my feelings.
I am the cause of my actions.
(continued)
500 19 An Integrated Model of “Free Will” and New Free Will Questionnaires

Table 19.4 (continued)


Category Subcategory Examples
Action Problem solving I have good problem-solving skills.
I break down problems into their manageable parts.
I juggle (multi-task) well.
Planning I make plans, knowing doing so makes life easier.
I know my priorities.
I am well organized.
Goals Goals are my guides as I live my life.
Having goals keeps me focused.
I can stick to my goals.
Rewards I can delay getting a reward when it lets me get bigger rewards.
I believe that sometimes the best rewards are the ones we feel inside.
Having patience makes me find the right way and get the right reward.
Monitoring I believe that the best thinking is when you solve the problem and there
is little follow-up needed afterward.
By seeing the bigger picture, I avoid getting lost in little details.
Pulling back from a problem helps me go back and solve the problem.
Feedback I am a flexible person, always learning from what happens.
I am a flexible person, always learning from what I do.
I am a flexible person, always learning from what people tell me.
Anticipation When I act, I consider beforehand what might happen.
My plans and goals take into account the future and not just the present.
I consider how others might be impacted before I do something.
Changing things around My problem-solving ability, planning, and goal selection include not just
me adjusting to things around me but also changing them.
I look forward to changing things around me to make life better.
I consider how others might need changes in things around them when I
try to change what is around me.

For the cognitive component of free will belief and relatedness. For the self-categories, they num-
in Table 19.4, the relevant categories include: ber definition, completeness, autonomy, initiative,
attention, selection/detection, choice, deciding, control, ownership, confidence, and self-deception.
reasoning/logic/thinking, and three major execu- For mental construction, the subcategories include
tive functions (working memory, shifting set, memory building, meaning, concepts, internal
inhibition). The list cannot be exhaustive, but it is source of control, external source of control, stress,
representative. The executive function list could culture, and causation. For action, the relevant
be longer. Components of it are elsewhere in the components involve problem solving, planning,
table (e.g., planning). Inhibition is part of the goals, rewards, monitoring, feedback, anticipa-
executive function and it could be placed in each tion, and changing the context. Many of these cat-
of the five subcategories. Recall that a general egories would have questionnaires already
mechanistic factor that I have proposed for constructed for them in the literature. However, I
behavior is activation/inhibition coordination have constructed three novel items for each of
(Young, 2011). them so that they are applicable to free will belief
For the social–emotional component of the free and having sense of free will.
will belief questionnaire, the relevant categories
include the following: morality, responsibility, Comment Research is needed to organize psy-
respect, not harming, relaxing/emotional, regula- chometrically the proposed free will question-
tion, being present, being conscious (mindful), naire items into a coherent whole by establishing
Free Will and Depletion Questionnaires 501

their factor structure. As well, it should examine description was determinist and the other was
the correlations of the resulting factors with other indeterminist (respectively, “Everything that hap-
measures in order to establish the validity of the pens is completely caused by whatever happens
questionnaire and its full meaning. before it;” “Almost everything that happens is
completely caused by whatever happens before
it. The one exception is human decision mak-
Belief in Free Will/Determinism ing”). This study led me to create a questionnaire
related to belief in free will and determinism that
Nichols and Knobe (2007) conducted an experi- might be useful. In essence, participants should
mental philosophy investigation on moral respon- be able to judge on a Likert scale to what degree
sibility and determinism. They asked participants they believe in each of the two statements on (in)
which of two universes is most like ours—one determinism (see Table 19.5).

Table 19.5 Causes in universe questionnaire


Find below three questions describing causes in our universe. For each question, indicate on the 7-point scale how
much you agree with the statement. Note. The three answers do not have to total 7; the questions are separate.
1. Imagine a universe (Universe A) in which everything that happens is completely caused by whatever happened
before it. This is true from the very beginning of the universe, so what happened in the beginning of the universe
caused what happened next, and so on right up until the present. For example, one day John decided to have
French fries at lunch. Like everything else, this decision was completely caused by what happened before it. So, if
everything in this universe was exactly the same up until John made his decision, then it had to happen that John
would decide to have French fries.
How much do you think this universe is most like ours?
Universe A Universe B
1 2 3 4 5 6 7
Disagree Strongly Agree
2. Imagine a universe (Universe B) in which almost everything that happens is completely caused by whatever
happened before it. The one exception is human decision-making. For example, one day Mary decided to have
French fries at lunch. Since a person’s decision in this universe is not completely caused by what happened before
it, even if everything in the universe is not completely caused by what happened before it, even if everything in the
universe was exactly the same up until Mary made her decision, it did not have to happen that Mary would decide
to have French fries. She could have decided to have something different.
How much do you think this universe is most like ours?
Universe A Universe B
1 2 3 4 5 6 7
Disagree Strongly Agree
3. Imagine a universe (Universe B) in which almost everything that happens is completely caused by whatever
happened before it. The one exception is human decision-making. Sometimes these are caused by whatever
happens before and sometimes not. For example, one day Mary decided to have French fries at lunch. Since a
person’s decision in this universe is sometimes not completely caused by what happened before it, even if
everything in the universe is not completely caused by what happened before it, even if everything in the universe
was exactly the same up until Mary made her decision, it did not have to happen that Mary would decide to have
French fries. She could have decided to have something different.
How much do you think this universe is most like ours?
Universe A Universe B
1 2 3 4 5 6 7
Disagree Strongly Agree
The key difference, then is, that in Universe A every decision is completely caused by what happened before the
decision—given the past, each decision has to happen the way that it does. By contrast, in Universe B, decisions are
not completely caused by the past, and each human decision does not have to happen the way that it does.
(continued)
502 19 An Integrated Model of “Free Will” and New Free Will Questionnaires

Table 19.5 (continued)


Choose the best answer for your opinion of how much control we have of our own decisions.
(a) Everything that happens in the universe is completely caused by whatever happened before it and what is
happening now. This is true for human decision-making, too. We can never decide independently of everything
that happened before and is happening now.
(b) Everything that happens in the universe is completely caused by whatever happened before it and what is
happening now. The one exception is human decision-making, but only sometimes. We can sometimes decide
independently of everything that happened before and is happening now.
(c) Everything that happens in the universe is completely caused by whatever happened before it and what is
happening now. The one exception is human decision-making, for which we have total control always. We can
always decide independently of everything that happened before and is happening now.
This questionnaire is an improvement because it includes the 3 options in one, it adds the present context as
important in decision-making, and it removes the example and, instead, restates the case in clear terms.

Table 19.6 Resource/energy/ego-depletion questionnaire


Depletion Effects
Even if I have I still can
Fatigue/pain/not eaten Choose right/decide well.
Had to control myself too much already/overexert myself Think clearly/plan ok/problem-solve
Down feelings/worry/irritability Stay cool/have self-control
No motivation/get go Keep perspective/see the big picture and details
Little support/criticism from others Overcome/keep going on right path, while avoiding
errors/wrong path
Nothing to get out of it Be myself/keep my values/do the right, responsible
thing
Note. Arrange each of 36 items on a 5-point Likert scale

Depletion tive behavioral therapy with people having addic-


tions. The focus could begin with the items
Questionnaire It would be helpful to the field to choosing/deciding/self-control in each of the
have a depletion scale. In this regard, Table 19.6 questionnaires. For example, the therapist might
presents items relevant to six resource/energy/ use them to build up a sense of choosing and
depletion factors that might affect self-control and deciding better, taking ownership, resisting temp-
related behaviors. They include: (1) physical, (2) tation, and developing a general self-control.
cognitive, (3) emotional, (4) motivation, (5) social,
and (6) incentive-related reasons for resource/
energy/ego-depletion. Possible effects of interest Belief and Passion as Part
of the depletion include: (1) choosing/deciding, of Behavioral Causation
(2) thinking/problem solving, (3) staying calm/in and Causality Engines
control, (4) keeping perspective/seeing the whole,
(5) overcoming/keep going, and (6) being oneself/ Introduction
maintaining values/responsibility.
As mentioned, I refer to the biopsychosocial
Comment Note that, once established as reli- model as the biopersonalsocial one (Young,
able and valid, both the free will belief and 2011). Aspects of the personal component
depletion questionnaires can be used therapeuti- include the self, free will belief, and coping
cally on an individual basis. For example, the skills that help give the person a sense of per-
questionnaires can be filled in to monitor cogni- sonal agency in her/his own behavioral determi-
Belief and Passion as Part of Behavioral Causation and Causality Engines 503

nation. A primary component to personal agency Passion


includes belief, in general, and the associated
construct of passion when that belief is power- Introduction An example that illustrates the
ful, is associated with emotions, and is poten- personal nature of the causal factors underlying
tially activating of follow-up associated goals behavior concerns passion. Vallerand and col-
and behaviors. leagues have been instrumental in defining it and
developing a questionnaire for it (e.g., Vallerand,
2010; Vallerand et al., 2003).
Belief
Vallerand and colleagues had defined passion
The power of belief is illustrated in people mak- as a strong inclination toward self-defining activ-
ing the ultimate sacrifice in the name of a cause ities, people, or objects that the person loves,
(Bélanger, Caouette, Sharvit, & Dugas, 2014). considers important, and is worthy of investment
The phenomenon of Martyrdom encompasses a of a significant amount of energy and time. As for
larger range of cognitive, emotional, and behav- the two scales measuring it, the six harmonious
ioral manifestations. In another vein, Thompson, items refer to harmony, appreciation, integration,
O’Donnell, Stafford, and Nordfjaern (2014) and liking, and living. The six items for the obsessive
Sullivan, Yakobov, Scott, and Tait (2014) noted scale involve terms such as obsession, losing
the power of attributions of responsibility/per- control, and “the only thing.”
ceived injustice on psychological recovery from Marsh et al. (2013) confirmed the two-factor
trauma. For me, these examples illustrate that structure of the passion scale, harmonious or
belief is a primary “causality engine” in human obsessive passion (each measured using a 6-item
behavior, especially if extreme in any way. inventory; see Table 19.7). Harmonious passion
However, beyond these extreme examples, the is related to more adaptive outcomes, given its
general beliefs that we hold influence much of intrinsic base on “loving” as the focus of the pas-
our daily activity. It would seem that a biopsy- sion (Vallerand & Verner-Filion, 2013), while
chosocial understanding of their origin would obsessive passion is related to more maladaptive
apply and be helpful. outcomes, partly related to the internal pressures
Note that the concept of “causality engine” that it creates.
appears general enough so that it might help explain The review by Marsh et al. (2013) showed that
the power of multiple personal psychological pro- passion has been found relevant in the areas of
cesses in the biopsychosocial origins of behavior. work, education, sport, leisure, and social life, as
The psychological component in the biopsychoso- well as mixed activities. Also, it relates to a mea-
cial model is a personal or self one, as noted, and sure of life satisfaction (Diener, 1985).
beliefs and passions constitute important subcom- Current research continues to expand the
ponents in this regard. Through them, the person scope of study of passion and its correlates. For
might best demonstrate that he or she should be example, Fernet, Lavigne, Vallerand, and Austin
considered the “third force” in behavioral causality (2014) and Lavigne, Forest, Fernet, and Crevier-
relative to biology and environment. That is, Braud (2014) examined passion in relation to job
through beliefs and passions, the person individu- autonomy and job control, respectively. Stenseng,
ates in her or his personal or individual psychologi- Forest, and Curran (2015) related it to recre-
cal standing and characteristics, becoming a special ational sports, and Zhang, Shi, Liu, and Miao
active causal force determining her or his own (2014) to leisure activity. Also, Lafrenière,
behavior and, therefore, can take charge of goal Vallerand, and Sedikides (2013) and Balon and
establishment and behavioral decision-making and Rimé (2013) related it to life satisfaction and per-
direction (and simultaneously help to put aside the sonality, respectively.
more passive internal (biological) and external Despite this range of positive findings using
(social) forces around us). the extant definition and measure of passion,
504 19 An Integrated Model of “Free Will” and New Free Will Questionnaires

Table 19.7 Items on the two components of the passion I find the last two changes good ones. However,
scale in several senses, the original definition that
Item Passion scale allows for passion for people or objects as much
Harmonious as for activities should be kept in the current defi-
1 This ______ is in harmony with the other ones nition. Specifically, passion does extend to these
in my life. foci. That being said, the items in both the har-
2 The new things that I discover with this ______ monious and obsessive portions of the scale refer
allow me to appreciate it even more.
to “activities” only, but instead of revising the
3 This ______reflects the qualities I like about
myself. general definition of passion to fit the scale, the
4 This ______ allows me to live a variety of scale should be revised to fit the definition.
experiences.
5 My ______ is well integrated in my life. New Definition The definition that I have con-
6 My ______ is in harmony with other things that structed for the concept of passion considers the
are part of me. following. (a) The term inclination is insufficient
Obsessive to capture the emotions involved in passion. (b) It
1 I have difficulties controlling my urge to do my is more than an emotion, though, being a motiva-
______.
tor/driver. (c) It involves goals related to the emo-
2 I have almost an obsessive feeling for this
______. tion/motivation. And the goals are focused and
3 This ______ is the only thing that really turns preferred/favored. (d) The goals involved are
me on. more than self-defining; also, they are self-
4 If I could, I would only do my ______. enhancing. (e) The goals could be outward-
5 This ______ is so exciting that I sometimes directed, such as to an activity, object, or person,
lose control over it. but also they could be inward-directed, such as
6 I have the impression that my ______ controls improving one’s mood or self-worth.
me.
Given these considerations, I have developed
Adapted from Marsh et al. (2013) a fuller definition of passion, as per below. Note
Note. The original scale includes the word “activity” in
the blank spaces. One could insert the words activity, that, as well, it includes the obsessional compo-
object, or person in the blanks, depending on research nent that might be involved.
needs. Also, for items in the harmony scale at the top, I Therefore, toward revising the concept to fit
used the word “ones” instead of activities the parameters mentioned, passion should be
defined in the following way. It is a “deeply felt
there is room for improvement in both these (e.g., liking, loving) and motivating/driven incli-
regards. In the following, I consider a broader nation or enthusiasm leading to the focused pur-
definition of passion and a more inclusive range suit of positive, personally important, defining or
of items that could be used to measure its harmo- harmonious/integrative self-enhancing, valued
nious portion. goals (which could be outward-directed, such as
in investing in an activity, person, or object;
Comment I noticed that Vallerand and Verner- accomplishing a task, or learning a preferred
Filion (2013) had altered the current definition to skill; or inward-directed, such as in gaining cer-
some extent, reverting to the original definition in tain positive experiences, feelings, or increments
Vallerand et al. (2003). Specifically, they referred in self-worth) or, rather, passion could lead to dif-
only to passion involving an activity, and ficulties in that process; depending on the nature
excluded mention of an object or a person as a of the goal, the personality, the context (which
focus in passion. They indicated the inclination includes culture), whether the passion is obses-
could be a “like” and not only a “love.” And they sive, out of control, and so on.”
removed the qualifier of “significant” to the
investment involved in passion. New Questionnaire As for revising the items in
the dual-mode passion scale, I focus just on the har-
Belief and Passion as Part of Behavioral Causation and Causality Engines 505

monious component. (a) First, the items should be the positive internal feelings it brings. The third
general and not focus just on activities. (b) Second, portion of the revised passion questionnaire is
they should emphasize goals more than the objects based on the original one, and poses six questions
of the goals. (c) Third, they should allow for both about whether the passion at issue creates har-
inward- and outward-directed focusing. (d) Fourth, mony, appreciation, self-reflection, living desired
they should allow specification if the passion is experiences, and is an integral part of one’s life.
personally-formulated, externally-driven, or both, The fourth part of the questionnaire asks the
and perhaps whether there might be a constitu- respondent to indicate from among a number of
tional (perhaps genetically-based) talent or skill adjectives that apply. The adjectives include ones
that one is pursuing. That is, the possible causes to related to the new definition. The fifth portion of
the passion at issue might be worth querying. the questionnaire also is based on the original, and
Given these considerations, I developed a asks about the negative qualities of passion.
revised passion scale consisting of six parts. The Finally, the last part of the questionnaire queries
first part specifies the focus of the passion, and the self-perceived origins of the passion, e.g., fol-
whether it has been self-selected for answers or lowing personal talents or not (see Table 19.8).
whether it is experimenter-derived. The second As with any questionnaire, empirical verifica-
part of the questionnaire asks whether the passion tion is needed to establish reliability and validity.
is about the sense of accomplishment it brings or The items were rationally derived for the most

Table 19.8 Revised passion scale


A. Think of something that is really dear to you, or important (or valued) in what you focus on by your motivation
or drive. [Or answer about the focus selected by the person administering the questionnaire.] For this focus, answer
the questions that follow:
1. My focus is ___________ ____________.
OR
2. The focus selected for me to consider by the person who gave me the questionnaire is ________ _________.
[Could be filled in for you by the person!]
B. This focus is important for me because of the sense of accomplishment it brings as a reward or, rather, because
of positive internal feelings that it brings. In this regard, the focus involved in my answers is about
1. The sense of accomplishment, to the following degree
0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
2. The positive internal feeling, to the following degree
0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
C. Here are 6 questions about the focus of your answers.
This focus:
1. Is in harmony with the other ones in my life.
0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
2. Allows me to discover new things so that I appreciate it even more.
0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
3. Reflects the qualities I like about myself.
0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
4. Allows me to live a variety of experiences.
0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
5. Is well integrated in my life.
0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
6. Is in harmony with other things that are part of me.
0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
D. For the focus that you are considering, how much does each of the following adjectives apply to it?
Passion 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
Love 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
Like 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
(continued)
506 19 An Integrated Model of “Free Will” and New Free Will Questionnaires

Table 19.8 (continued)


Deeply felt 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
Motivating 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
Driven 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
Inclination 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
Excitement 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
Enthusiasm 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
Positive 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
Self-defining 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
Self-enhancing 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
Valued 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
Good goal 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
Accomplishment 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
Internal feeling 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
Others TBA
E. This focus could be very powerful. It could involve:
1. Difficulties controlling my urge to do it.
0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
2. Almost an obsessive feeling for it.
0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
3. The only thing that really turns me on.
0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
4. If I could, it would be my only focus.
0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
5. So much excitement that I lose control over it.
0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
6. The impression that it controls me.
0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
F. Finally, the focus that you are considering might come (a) from inside you, being your choice, or (b) from what
was trained or educated in you, or (c) from your innate talents (or all of these). In this regard, my focus is:
1. From inside me, what I have personally chosen.
0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
2. From the outside, what I was trained in or taught.
0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
3. From my innate talents or skills that I have followed.
0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
Note. This scale was developed partly with my university class on emerging adulthood in the winter semester of 2015
(as was part of the definition of passion given in the text that accompanies this table)

part and they need to be empirically tailored. For sophical and complex. Nevertheless, it might
research on a new questionnaire related to free give complementary information in empirical
will, consult Deery, Davis, and Carey (2015a, research.
2015b). They developed a questionnaire from a
philosophical orientation and focuses especially
on questions related to ability to do otherwise Chapter Conclusions
(ATDO) and sourcehood, considering both relevant
freedoms. The factor structure of the question- The work in the area of free will, self-control,
naire included items related to compatibilism and depletion is accelerating rapidly. The present
and incompatibilisim. For the critical ATDO fac- chapter has reviewed the areas of depletion and a
tors, there are five questions for each of them. related one of dual processing. In addition, it
Relative to the items in my own questionnaire, I presents new questionnaires related to free will
found the wordings of their items quite philo- and depletion, in particular. Finally, it uses an
References 507

integrative biopsychosocial model that helps ultimate sacrifice in the name of a cause. Journal of
integrate under one umbrella the diverging areas Personality and Social Psychology, 107, 494–515.
Botvinick, M., & Braver, T. (2015). Motivation and cogni-
in the study of free will, self-control, depletion, tive control: From behavior to neural mechanism.
and their measurement. Annual Review of Psychology, 66, 83–113.
Bush, G., Shin, L. M., Holmes, J., Rosen, D. R., & Vogt,
B. A. (2003). The multi-source interference task:
Validation study with fMRI in individual subjects.
References Molecular Psychiatry, 8, 60–70.
Carter, C. S., & Van Veen, V. (2007). Anterior cingulate
Balon, S., & Rimé, J. L. B. (2013). Passion and personal- cortex and conflict detection: An update of theory and
ity: Is passionate behaviour a function of personality? data. Cognitive, Affective, & Behavioral Neuroscience,
Revue Européenee de Psychologie Appliquée, 63, 7, 367–379.
59–65. Carter, E. C., Kofler, L. M., Forster, D. E., & McCullough,
Balleine, B. W., Delgado, M. R., & Hikosaka, O. (2007). M. E. (2015). A series of meta-analytic tests of the
The role of the dorsal striatum in reward and decision- depletion effect: Self-control does not seem to rely on
making. Journal of Neuroscience, 27, 8161–8165. a limited resource. Journal of Experimental
Bargh, J. A. (1994). The four horseman of automaticity: Psychology: General, 144, 796–815.
Awareness, intention, efficiency, and control in social Carver, C. S., Johnson, S. L., & Joormann, J. (2013). Two-
cognition. In R. S. Wyer & T. K. Srull (Eds.), mode models of self-regulation and serotonergic func-
Handbook of social cognition (pp. 1–40). Hillsdale, tioning: Divergent manifestations of impulse and
NJ: Erlbaum. constraint. In B. W. Sokol, M. E. Grouzet, & U. Müller
(Eds.), Self-regulation and autonomy: Social and devel-
Bargh, J. A. (2005). Bypassing the will: Towards demys-
opmental dimensions of human conduct (pp. 255–278).
tifying behavioral priming effects. In R. Hassin,
New York: Cambridge University Press.
J. Uleman, & J. Bargh (Eds.), The new unconscious
Chen, S., Westman, M., & Hobfoll, S. E. (2015). The
(pp. 37–58). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
commerce and crossover of resources: Resource con-
Barrouillet, P. (2011). Dual-process theories of reasoning:
servation in the service of resilience. Stress and
The test of development. Developmental Review, 31,
Health, 31, 95–105.
151–179.
Coan, J. A. (2008). Toward a neuroscience of attachment.
Baumeister, R. F. (2008). Free will in scientific psychol- In J. Cassidy & P. R. Shaver (Eds.), Handbook of
ogy. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 3, 14–19. attachment: Theory, research, and clinical applications
Baumeister, R. F., & Bargh, J. A. (2014). Conscious and (2nd ed., pp. 241–265). New York: Guilford Press.
unconscious: Toward an integrative understanding of Coan, J. A., Brown, C. L., & Beckes, L. (2014). Out social
human mental life and action. In J. W. Sherman, baseline: The role of social proximity in economy of
B. Gawronski, & Y. Trope (Eds.), Dual-process theo- action. In M. Mikulincer & P. R. Shaver (Eds.),
ries of the social mind (pp. 35–49). New York: Mechanisms of social connection: From brain to
Guilford Press. group (pp. 89–104). Washington, DC: American
Baumeister, R. F., Bratslavesky, E., Muraven, M., & Tice, Psychological Association.
D. M. (1998). Ego depletion: Is the active self a lim- Coan, J. A., Schaefer, H. S., & Davidson, R. J. (2006).
ited resource? Journal of Personality and Social Lending a hand: Social regulation of the neural response
Psychology, 74, 1252–1265. to threat. Psychological Science, 17, 1032–1039.
Baumeister, R. F., & Masicampo, E. J. (2010). Conscious Cushman, F., & Greene, J. D. (2012). Finding faults: How
thought is for facilitating social and cultural interac- moral dilemmas illuminate cognitive structure. Social
tions: How mental simulations serve the animal-culture Neuroscience, 7, 269–279.
interface. Psychological Review, 117, 945–971. Deci, E. L., & Ryan, R. M. (2013). The importance of
Baumeister, R. F., Masicampo, E. J., & DeWall, C. N. (2009). autonomy for development and well-being. In B. W.
Prosocial benefits of feeling free: Disbelief in free will Sokol, M. E. Grouzet, & U. Müller (Eds.), Self-
increases aggression and reduces helpfulness. Personality regulation and autonomy: Social and developmental
and Social Psychology Bulletin, 35, 260–268. dimensions of human conduct (pp. 19–46). New York:
Baumeister, R. F., Masicampo, E. J., & Vohs, K. D. Cambridge University Press.
(2011). Do conscious thoughts cause behavior? Deery, O., Davis, T., & Carey, J. (2015a). The free-will
Annual Review of Psychology, 62, 331–361. intuition scale and the question of natural compatibil-
Baumeister, R. F., Vohs, K. D., & Tice, D. M. (2007). The ism. Philosophical Psychology, 28, 776–801.
strength model of self-control. Current Directions in Deery, O., Davis, T., & Carey, J. (2015b). Defending the
Psychological Science, 16, 351–355. free-will intuitions scale: Reply to Stephen Morris.
Beckes, L., & Coan, J. A. (2011). Social baseline theory: Philosophical Psychology, 28, 808–814.
The role of social proximity in emotion and economy Diener, E. (1985). Satisfaction with life scale. Retrieved
of action. Social and Personality Psychology Compass, from PsycTESTS. doi:10.1037/t01069-000.
5, 976–988. Duckworth, A. L., & Carlson, S. M. (2013). Self-
Bélanger, J. J., Caouette, J., Sharvit, K., & Dugas, M. regulation and school success. In B. W. Sokol, M. E.
(2014). The psychology of martyrdom: Making the Grouzet, & U. Müller (Eds.), Self-regulation and
508 19 An Integrated Model of “Free Will” and New Free Will Questionnaires

autonomy: Social and developmental dimensions of Gailliot, M. T., Gitter, S. A., Baker, M. D., & Baumeister,
human conduct (pp. 208–230). New York: Cambridge R. F. (2012). Breaking the rules: Low trait or state self-
University Press. control increases social norm violations. Psychology,
Dweck, C. S. (2012). Mindsets and human nature: 3, 1074–1083.
Promoting change in the Middle East, the schoolyard, Galinsky, A. D., Maddux, W. W., Gilin, D., & White, J. D.
the racial divide, and willpower. American Psychologist, (2008). Why it pays to get inside the head of your
67, 614–622. opponent: The differential effects of perspective taking
Eagle, D. M., & Baunez, C. (2010). Is there an inhibitory- and empathy in negotiations. Psychological Science,
response control system in the rat? Evidence from ana- 19, 378–384.
tomical and pharmacological studies of behavioral Gawronski, B., Sherman, J. W., & Trope, Y. (2014). Two
inhibition. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Review, 34, of what?: A conceptual analysis of dual-process theo-
50–72. ries. In J. W. Sherman, B. Gawronski, & Y. Trope
Edelman, G. M., & Tononi, G. (2000). A universe of con- (Eds.), Dual-process theories of the social mind
sciousness: How matter becomes imagination. (pp. 3–19). New York: Guilford Press.
New York: Basic Books. Grouzet, M. E. (2013). Self-regulation and autonomy: The
Ent, M. R., & Baumeister, R. F. (2014). Embodied free dialectic between organismic and sociocognitive valu-
will beliefs: Some effects of physical states on meta- ing processes. In B. W. Sokol, M. E. Grouzet, &
physical opinions. Consciousness and Cognition, 27, U. Müller (Eds.), Self-regulation and autonomy: Social
147–154. and developmental dimensions of human conduct
Ent, M. R., Baumeister, R. F., & Vonasch, A. J. (2012). (pp. 47–77). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Power, leadership, and self-regulation. Social and Grouzet, M. E., Sokol, B. W., & Müller, U. (2013). Self-
Personality Psychology Compass, 6, 619–630. regulation and autonomy: An introduction. In B. W.
Evans, D. R., Boggero, I. A., & Segerstrom, S. C. (2015). Sokol, M. E. Grouzet, & U. Müller (Eds.), Self-
The nature of self-regulatory fatigue and “ego deple- regulation and autonomy: Social and developmental
tion”: Lessons from physical fatigue. Personality and dimensions of human conduct (pp. 1–16). New York:
Social Psychology Review, 1–20. Cambridge University Press.
Evans, J. St. B. T. (2009). How many dual-process theo- Hagger, M. S. (2015). Conservation of resources theory and
ries do we need? One, two, or many? In J. St. B. T. the “strength” model of self-control: Conceptual over-
Evans & K. Frankish (Eds.), In two minds: Dual pro- lap and commonalities. Stress and Health, 31, 89–94.
cesses and beyond (pp. 33–54). New York: Oxford Hagger, M. S., Wood, C., Stiff, C., & Chatzisarantis, N. L.
University Press. (2010). Ego depletion and the strength model of self-
Evans, J. St. B. T. (2010). Thinking twice: Two minds in control: A meta-analysis. Psychological Bulletin, 136,
one brain. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. 495–525.
Evans, J. St. B. T. (2011a). The psychology of reasoning: Heatherton, T. F., & Wagner, D. D. (2011). Cognitive neu-
Reflections on four decades of research. In roscience of self-regulation failure. Trends in Cognitive
K. Manktelow, D. Over, & S. Elquayam (Eds.), The sci- Sciences, 15, 132–139.
ence of reason (pp. 423–444). Hove, UK: Psychology Hobfoll, S. E. (1989). Conservation resources: A new attempt
Press. at a conceptualizing stress. American Psychologist, 44,
Evans, J. St. B. T. (2011b). Dual process theories of rea- 513.
soning: Contemporary issues and developmental Inzlicht, M., & Al-Khindi, T. (2012). ERN and the pla-
applications. Developmental Review, 31, 86–102. cebo: A misattribution approach to studying the arousal
Evans, J. St. B. T., & Stanovich, K. E. (2013). Dual-process properties of the error-related negativity. Journal of
theories of higher cognition: Advancing the debate. Experimental Psychology: General, 141, 799–807.
Perspectives on Psychological Science, 8, 223–241. Inzlicht, M., & Gutsell, J. N. (2007). Running on empty:
Fernet, C., Lavigne, G. L., Vallerand, R. J., & Austin, S. Neural signals for self-control failure. Psychological
(2014). Fired up with passion: Investigating how job Science, 18, 933–937.
autonomy and passion predict burnout at career start in Inzlicht, M., & Schmeichel, B. J. (2012). What is ego
teachers. Work & Stress, 28, 270–288. depletion? Toward a mechanistic revision of the
Freud, S. (1933/1965). Warum krieg (Why war)? Standard resource model of self-control. Perspectives on
Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Psychological Science, 7, 450–463.
Sigmund Freud, 22, 197–224. London: Hogarth Press. Inzlicht, M., & Schmeichel, B. J. (2013). Beyond simple
Gailliot, M. T., & Baumeister, R. F. (2007). Self-regulation utility in predicting self-control fatigue: A proximate
and sexual restraint: Dispositionally and temporarily alternative to the opportunity cost model. Behavioral
poor self-regulatory abilities contribute to failure at and Brain Sciences, 36, 695–696.
restraining sexual behavior. Personality and Social Job, V., Dweck, C. S., & Walton, G. M. (2010). Ego
Psychology Bulletin, 33, 173–186. depletion – Is it all in your head? Implicit theories
Gailliot, M. T., Baumeister, R. F., DeWall, C., N., Maner, about willpower affect self-regulation. Psychological
J. K., Plant, E. A., Tice, D. M., et al. J. (2007). Self- Science, 21, 1686–1693.
control relies on glucose as a limited energy source: Kinnucan, C. J. E., & Kuebli, J. E. (2013). Understanding
Willpower is more than a metaphor. Journal of explanatory talk through Vygotsky’s theory of self-
Personality and Social Psychology, 92, 325–336. regulation. In B. W. Sokol, M. E. Grouzet, & U. Müller
References 509

(Eds.), Self-regulation and autonomy: Social and Measuring beliefs about agency and responsibility.
developmental dimensions of human conduct (pp. 231– Consciousness and Cognition, 25, 27–41.
252). New York: Cambridge University Press. Nelson, K. (2007). Young minds in social worlds:
Kopp, C. B. (2011). Development in the early years: Experience, meaning, and memory. Cambridge, MA:
Socialization, motor development, and consciousness. Harvard University Press.
Annual Review of Psychology, 62, 165–187. Newell, B. R. (2015). “Wait! Just let me not think about
Kurzban, R., Duckworth, A., Kable, J. W., & Myers, that for a minute”: What role do implicit processes
J. (2013a). An opportunity cost model of subjective play in higher-level cognition? Current Directions in
effort and task performance. Behavioral and Brain Psychological Science, 24, 65–70.
Sciences, 36, 661–726. Nichols, S., & Knobe, J. (2007). Moral responsibility and
Kurzban, R., Duckworth, A., Kable, J. W., & Myers, determinism: The cognitive science of folk intuitions.
J. (2013b). Cost-benefit models as the next, best option Noûs, 41, 663–685.
for understanding subjective effort. Behavioral and Nucci, L. (2013). “It’s a part of life to do what you what”:
Brain Sciences, 36, 707–726. The role of personal choice in social development. In
Lafrenière, M.-A., Vallerand, R. J., & Sedikides, C. B. W. Sokol, M. E. Grouzet, & U. Müller (Eds.), Self-
(2013). On the relation between self-enhancement and regulation and autonomy: Social and developmental
life satisfaction: The moderating role of passion. Self dimensions of human conduct (pp. 165–188). New York:
and Identity, 12, 597–609. Cambridge University Press.
Lavigne, G. L., Forest, J., Fernet, C., & Crevier-Braud, L. Paulhus, D. L., & Carey, J. M. (2011). The FAD-Plus:
(2014). Passion at work and workers’ evaluations of Measuring lay beliefs regarding free will and related con-
job demands and resources: A longitudinal study. structs. Journal of Personality Assessment, 93, 96–104.
Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 44, 255–265. Piaget, J. (1974/1980). Adaptation and intelligence:
Lerner, J. S., Li, Y., Valdesolo, P., & Kassam, K. S. (2015). Organic selection and phenocopy. Chicago, IL:
Emotion and decision making. Annual Review of University of Chicago Press.
Psychology, 66, 799–823. Piaget, J., & Inhelder, B. (1941). Le développement des
Lévy, P. (1997). Collective intelligence: Mankind’s emerging quantités physiques chez l’enfant. Neuchâtel,
world in cyberspace. Cambridge, MA: Perseus Books. Switzerland: Delachaux & Niestlé.
Marr, D. (1982). Vision: A computational investigation Piaget, J., & Inhelder, B. (1954). La genèse des structures
into the human representation and processing of visual logiques élémentaires. Neuchâtel, Switzerland:
information. New York: Freeman. Delachaux & Niestlé.
Marsh, H. W., Lafrenière, M.-A., Carbonneau, N., Bureau, Pons, F., Harris, P., & de Rosnay, M. (2012). Piaget and
J. S., Guay, F., Vallerand, R. J., et al. (2013). Passion: consciousness: Retrospect and prospect. In E. Marti &
Does one scale fit all? Construct validity of two-factor C. Rodriguez (Eds.), After Piaget (pp. 95–122). New
passion scale and psychometric invariance over differ- Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers.
ent activities and languages. Psychological Rabi, R., & Minda, J. P. (2014). Rule-based category
Assessment, 25, 796–809. learning in children: The role of age and executive
Masicampo, E. J., & Baumeister, R. F. (2008). Toward a functioning. PLoS One, 9, e85316. doi:10.1371/jour-
physiology of dual-process reasoning and judgment: nal.pone.0085316.
Lemonade, willpower, and expensive rule-based anal- Rakos, R. F., Laurene, K. R., Skala, S., & Slane, S. (2008).
ysis. Psychological Science, 19, 255–260. Belief in free will: Measurement and conceptualization
Minda, J. P., & Rabi, R. (2015). Ego depletion interferes innovations. Behavior and Social Issues, 17, 20–39.
with rule-defined category learning but not non-rule- Rigoni, D., Kühn, S., Gaudino, G., Sartori, G., & Brass, M.
defined category learning. Frontiers in Psychology, 6, (2012). Reducing self-control by weakening belief in free
35. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2015.00035. will. Consciousness and Cognition, 21, 1482–1490.
Molden, D. C., Hui, C. M., Noreen, E. E., Meier, B. P., Rochat, P. (2003). Five levels of self-awareness as they
Scholer, A. A., D’Agostino, P. R., et al. (2012). The unfold early in life. Consciousness and Cognition, 12,
motivational versus metabolic effects of carbohy- 717–731.
drates on self-control. Psychological Science, 23, Sanders, M. A., Shirk, S. D., Burgin, C. J., & Martin, L. L.
1130–1137. (2012). The gargle effect: Rinsing the mouth with glu-
Moller, A. C., Deci, E. L., & Ryan, R. M. (2006). Choice cose enhances self-control. Psychological Science, 23,
and ego depletion: The moderating role of autonomy. 1470–1472.
Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 32, Schmeichel, B. J., Harmon-Jones, C., & Harmon-Jones,
1024–1036. E. (2010). Exercising self-control increases approach
Morsella, E. (2005). The function of phenomenal states: motivation. Journal of Personality and Social
Supramodular interaction theory. Psychological Review, Psychology, 99, 162–173.
112, 1000–1021. Schmeichel, B. J., & Vohs, K. D. (2009). Self-affirmation
Muraven, M., & Slessareva, E. (2003). Mechanisms of and self-control: Affirming core values counteracts
self-control failure: Motivation and limited resources. ego depletion. Journal of Personality and Social
Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 29, Psychology, 96, 770–782.
894–906. Segerstrom, S. C., & Nes, L. S. (2007). Heart rate vari-
Nadelhoffer, T., Shepard, J., Nahmias, E., Sripada, C., & ability reflects self-regulatory strength, effort, and
Thomson Ross, L. (2014). The free will inventory: fatigue. Science, 18, 275–281.
510 19 An Integrated Model of “Free Will” and New Free Will Questionnaires

Sherman, J. W., Gawronski, B., & Trope, Y. (2014). Dual- Trevarthen, C., & Aitken, K. J. (2001). Infant intersubjec-
process theories of the social mind. New York: tivity: Research, theory, and clinical applications.
Guilford Press. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 42, 3–48.
Sloman, S. A. (1996). The empirical case for two systems Vallerand, R. J. (2010). On passion for life activities: The
of reasoning. Psychological Bulletin, 119, 3–22. dualistic model of passion. In M. P. Zanna (Ed.),
Sloman, S. A. (2014). Two systems of reasoning: An Advances in experimental social psychology (pp.
update. In J. W. Sherman, B. Gawronski, & Y. Trope 97–193). New York: Academic Press.
(Eds.), Dual-process theories of the social mind Vallerand, R. J., Mageau, G. A., Ratelle, C., Léonard, M.,
(pp. 69–79). New York: Guilford Press. Blanchard, C., Koestner, R., et al. (2003). Les passions
Smith, E. R., & DeCoster, J. (2000). Dual-process models in de l’âme: On obsessive and harmonious passion. Journal
social and cognitive psychology: Conceptual integration of Personality and Social Psychology, 85, 756–767.
and links to underlying memory systems. Personality Vallerand, R. J., & Verner-Filion, J. (2013). Making peo-
and Social Psychology Review, 4, 108–131. ple’s life most worth living: On the importance of pas-
Sokol, B. W., Grouzet, M. E., & Müller, U. (2013). Self- sion for positive psychology. Terapia Psicológica, 31,
regulation and autonomy: Social and developmental 35–48.
dimensions of human conduct. New York: Cambridge Vohs, K. D., Baumeister, R. F., & Schmeichel, B. J.
University Press. (2012). Motivation, personal beliefs, and limited
Spunt, R. P., & Lieberman, M. D. (2012). An integrative resources all contribute to self control. Journal of
model of the neural systems supporting the compre- Experimental Social Psychology, 48, 943–947.
hension of observed emotional behavior. NeuroImage, Vohs, K. D., Baumeister, R. F., & Schmeichel, B. J. (2013).
59, 3050–3059. Erratum to “motivation, personal beliefs, and limited
Spunt, R. P., & Lieberman, M. D. (2013). The busy social resources all contribute to self control.”. Journal of
brain: Evidence for automaticity and control in the Experimental Social Psychology, 49, 184–188.
neural systems supporting social cognition and action Vohs, K. D., Baumeister, R. F., Schmeichel, B. J., Twenge,
understanding. Psychological Science, 24, 80–86. J. M., Nelson, N. M., & Tice, D. M. (2014). Making
Spunt, R. P., & Lieberman, M. D. (2014). Automaticity, con- choices impairs subsequent self-control: A limited-
trol, and the social brain. In J. W. Sherman, B. Gawronski, resource account of decision making, self-regulation,
& Y. Trope (Eds.), Dual-process theories of the social and active initiative. Motivation Science, 1, 19–42.
mind (pp. 279–296). New York: Guilford Press. Wagner, D. D., Altman, M., Boswell, R. G., Kelley,
Sripada, C., Kessler, D., & Jonides, J. (2014). W. M., & Heatherton, T. F. (2013). Self-regulatory
Methylphenidate blocks effort-induced depletion of depletion enhances neural responses to rewards and
regulatory control in healthy volunteers. Psychological impairs top-down control. Psychological Science, 24,
Science, 25, 1227–1234. 2262–2271.
Stanovich, K. E. (1999). Who is rational? Studies of indi- Wagner, D. D., & Heatherton, T. F. (2013). Self-regulatory
vidual differences in reasoning. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. depletion increases emotional reactivity in the amyg-
Stanovich, K. E. (2009). Distinguishing the reflective, dala. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience, 8,
algorithmic, and autonomous minds: Is it time for a 410–417.
tri-process theory? In J. S. B. T. Evans & K. Frankish Waters, A. C., & Tucker, D. M. (2013). Self-regulation of
(Eds.), In two minds: Dual processes and beyond neural development. In B. W. Sokol, M. E. Grouzet, &
(pp. 55–88). New York: Oxford University Press. U. Müller (Eds.), Self-regulation and autonomy:
Stanovich, K. E. (2011). Rationality and the reflective Social and developmental dimensions of human con-
mind. New York: Oxford University Press. duct. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Stanovich, K. E., West, R. F., & Toplak, M. E. (2011). The Wegner, D. M. (2002). The illusion of conscious will.
complexity of developmental predictions from dual Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
process models. Developmental Review, 31, 103–118. Wiecki, T. V., & Frank, M. J. (2013). A computational
Stanovich, K. E., West, R. F., & Toplak, M. E. (2014). model of inhibitory control in frontal cortex and basal
Rationality, intelligence, and the defining features of type ganglia. Psychological Review, 120, 329–355.
1 and type 2 processing. In J. W. Sherman, B. Gawronski, Young, G. (1997). Adult development, therapy, and cul-
& Y. Trope (Eds.), Dual-process theories of the social ture: A postmodern synthesis. New York: Plenum.
mind (pp. 80–91). New York: Guilford Press. Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
Stenseng, F., Forest, J., & Curran, T. (2015). Positive emo- Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science +
tions in recreational sport activities: The role of pas- Business Media.
sion and belongingness. Journal of Happiness Studies, Zelazo, P. D., Hong Gao, H., & Todd, R. (2007). The
16, 1117–1129. development of consciousness. In P. D. Zelazo,
Sullivan, M. J. L., Yakobov, E., Scott, W., & Tait, R. M. Moscovitch, & E. Thompson (Eds.), Cambridge
(2014). Perceived injustice and adverse recovery out- handbook of consciousness (pp. 405–432). New York:
comes. Psychological Injury and Law, 7, 325–334. Cambridge University Press.
Thompson, J., O’Donnell, M., Stafford, L., & Nordfjaern, Zhang, S., Shi, R., Liu, X., & Miao, D. (2014). Passion for
T. (2014). Association between attributions of respon- a leisure activity, presence of meaning, and search of
sibilities for motor vehicle crashes, depressive symp- meaning: The mediating role of emotion. Social
toms, and return to work. Rehabilitation Psychology, Indicators Research, 115, 1123–1135.
59, 376–385.
Part IV
Abnormalities in Development
and the DSM-5
Free Will in Psychotherapy:
Helping People Believe 20

Chapter Introduction Free Will in Psychotherapy

This chapter presents a transdiagnostic psycho- Introduction


therapeutic module related to belief in free will
and the change process that could be used to In the edited book of Sinnott-Armstrong (2014a),
facilitate patients making better choices and also the philosophical, psychological, and neurosci-
making gains in psychotherapy. The module con- entific are areas that meld together on the topic of
sists of a series of tables that were made upon free will. His introductory chapter (2014b) expli-
reviewing the literature on free will belief, con- cated the quandaries in the field, and explains the
sciousness, self-control, and factors that could diverse points of view that are still contested
interfere with belief in free will (termed resource/ despite the increasing scientific research on the
ego depletion, e.g., in the research of Baumeister question. Arguments still vary about whether
and colleagues). The tables are constructed simi- free will exists, but workers are adopting a more
larly, with phenomena related to belief in free limited, nuanced, compatibilistic view (e.g.,
will, control, consciousness, change, and so on, Nahmias, 2014; Roskies, 2014), or a semi-
on the left and corresponding therapeutic ques- compatibilistic one (e.g., Gazzaniga, 2014; semi-
tions deriving from them on the right. The mod- compatibilism in the sense that even if free will
ule could work well with patients having cannot be assumed to exist, we still have freedom
conditions especially related to self-control in from gaining options and are responsible for our
which belief in free will can help. In this regard, actions).
one of them concerns the application of the con- Believing in free will has important conse-
cept to addiction. quences related to making appropriate choices,
Note that this chapter is based on the one in behaving more morally, and otherwise adopting
Young (2014), but with the literature cited therein better habits and a more goal-oriented lifestyle
quite elaborated. Also, it includes a new table on (Baumeister, 2008; Baumeister, Masicampo, &
the use of the concept of free will in psychother- Vohs, 2011; Baumeister & Vohs, 2011). Although
apy based on Baumeister (2014a, 2014b). Finally, there is endless debate about the construct philo-
there is overlap with the prior two chapters on sophically in terms of whether free will exists,
free will that is inevitable, but the overlap helps adopting the attitude psychologically that it does
with the module being developed on applications exist (believing in free will) is relevant in reha-
of free will in psychotherapy. bilitation and psychotherapy.

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 513


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_20
514 20 Free Will in Psychotherapy: Helping People Believe

Cognitive behavior therapy is the predominant prepare the patient to learn better habits. To
empirically-supported psychotherapeutic approach illustrate this, I have proposed tables based on
in rehabilitation (Young, 2014). However, other cognitive behavior therapy that includes accom-
approaches, such as the narrative one and positive modations to incorporate free will belief. In the
psychology, can be useful adjuncts toward treating following, I review the literature that served as
the whole person. Moreover, transdiagnostic the basis for each table as I present them. Before
approaches are the one being used increasingly beginning, however, I examine how free will
(e.g., Barlow et al., 2011). In this regard, in this belief fits into a cognitive behavioral approach
chapter, I have formulated a transdiagnostic psy- to psychotherapy.
chotherapeutic module consisting of a series of Figure 20.1 indicates that, as with any behav-
tables based on belief in free will that psychothera- ior, belief in free will is influenced by biological,
pists could use to facilitate better motivation for personal, and environmental factors. Ongoing
change. behavior gives feedback into the model by alter-
ing the experiences that can influence its subse-
quent expression, the person variables that could
Model intervene, the biological and environmental influ-
ences on it, and so on.
The concept of free will belief is applicable Behavior takes place in context; but context is
throughout the psychotherapeutic process. It influenced by appraisals, perceptions, filters,
can help challenge dysfunctional beliefs and schemas, and representations. The context

Influence
of Free A, B, C
Will Belief

Influences Stimulus
on Free Situation
Belief
Will Belief Stressor
Cognition
Thought
Consequence
Behavior
Biology Genes Appraisal/ Antecedent
Outcome
Heredity, etc. perception of Activation Choice
context
Response
x x
Emotion
Person Predisposition Affect
Personality, etc. Mood

x
x
Environment
Past experience
Family, etc. Dispute
Develop
New plan

Feedback Enact
Future planning Evaluate

D, E, F

Fig. 20.1 The ABCs of free will in psychotherapy. Belief psychotherapy. Behavior is considered as the outcome of
in free will has positive consequences for behavior biological, personal, and environmental factors, which
(Baumeister, 2008). The present model combines the can influence free will belief. At the same time, free will
belief with the cognitive-behavioral approach to psycho- belief can influence the activators, beliefs, cognitions,
therapy. The proposed model is based on the ABC compo- emotions, and choices in behavior (A, B, and C), as well as
nent of the cognitive behavioral approach, and illustrates their monitoring and revision (D, E, and F)
at what points free will belief can influence behavior and
Helping People Believe 515

provides stimuli, situations, or stressors that Helping People Believe


serve to activate behavior (or give the antecedents
to it, the A part of the ABC model), but they are Introduction
as much subjective as objective.
The classic ABC model emphasizes beliefs The following section of the chapter gives a brief
elicited by activators that, in turn, influence con- overview of self-control in free will in psychol-
sequences. However, a broader view of the ogy, preparing the way for presentation of the
sequence would include emotional mediators as psychotherapeutic module on free will. It
much as cognitive ones (or their interactions), overlaps in content with material in the last two
although individual differences might favor either chapters.
the cognitive or emotional pathway. As presented,
the model does not give precedence to either emo-
tions or cognition as preludes to behavior. Self-Control in Free Will
The ABC sequence that leads to behavior in
context might produce adaptive behavior in the Alquist and Baumeister (2012) reviewed the role
behavioral option chosen. However, better of self-control in behavior. This topic is particu-
choices often could have been made, and this larly relevant for a psychotherapy module of free
becomes an issue in psychotherapeutic cases. will, which involves self-control deployment.
The classic ABC model includes a D (dispute) Self-control is defined as the ability to alter one’s
component, and it can be expanded to include E state or response, including by exerting control
and F components to allow for new choices and over desires, impulses, emotions, and thoughts.
more adaptive outcomes. Mischel, Shoda, and Peake (1988) and Shoda,
Free will belief relates to believing that choice Mischel, and Peake (1990) had shown that a young
is possible and that best choices can be made in child’s ability to resist taking immediately one
relevant situations. The emergence of behavioral marshmallow in order to obtain a later choice of
options and the choices made in behavior do not two marshmallows predicted their teenage scho-
automatically flow deterministically from past lastic achievement test scores (SATs) and even
influences and present context. The person has a their adult interpersonal success. Duckworth and
choice partly stemming from personal character- Seligman (2005) found that self-discipline more
istics that incorporate free will belief as an impor- than IQ predicted grade point average. Having
tant mediator in behavior. The psychotherapist self-control as a child led to less adult arrests and
can work to facilitate a greater belief in free will, more family stability (i.e., raising one’s own chil-
and its application for making better choice in dren in intact families; Moffitt et al., 2011). The
context. benefits of self-control extend to mental health and
In terms of the model presented, this refers to relationships (e.g., Tangney, Baumeister, & Boone,
increasing the range of adaptive appraisals or 2004; Vohs, Finkenauer, Baumeister, 2011; Walter,
perceptions of context and, consequently, what Gunstad, & Hobfoll, 2010).
become activators of behavior. In addition, auto- The components of self-regulation include:
matic, maladaptive associations to the activators, (a) standards (what goals regulating toward); (b)
either in terms of cognition or emotion (or their monitoring/tracking goal progress; and (c) exe-
interaction) would become better controlled or cution (plan implementation, executing toward
countered, freeing openings to consider more goal) (Baumeister & Heatherton, 1996). However,
adaptive behavioral response to contextual acti- good self-control requires effort, but the ener-
vators. Also, this would encourage less need for getic resources involved are limited, so they need
dispute of past pattern and also the need for new appropriate deployment.
planning, as well as an increased learning how to Studies show that the energetic resources
use optimally belief in free will. involved in self-control can be manipulated.
516 20 Free Will in Psychotherapy: Helping People Believe

In this research, participants who engage in self- psychological interventions. If we did not believe
regulation tasks perform worse on a second unre- that our patients were amenable to change, we
lated one, as per the resource or ego depletion would not provide treatment. At the same time,
model. For example, Baumeister, Bratslavesky, as far as I know, there has not been a specific
Muraven, and Tice (1998) found that resisting attempt to integrate free will belief directly as a
cookies led to participants to quit an unsolvable module into psychotherapeutic work. The tables
puzzle earlier than those who had to resist (less in this chapter accommodate to that lacunae.
appetizing) radishes. Moreover, the results are not However, there are limits to free will belief.
explainable in terms of factors such as mood, One always confronts psychological constraints,
arousal, frustration, or even fatigue. Other whether developmental or otherwise, that inhibit
research (e.g., Vohs, Glass, Maddox, & Markham, manifestation for each of us of a totally free and
2011) shows that people conserve resources when uncontaminated ability to make in every situation
the resources are scarcer or when people are constructive positive choice. In this sense, I sup-
anticipating future self-regulation needs (e.g., port an asymptotic paradoxical model of free will.
Muraven, Shmueli, & Burkley, 2006). However, In such a model, we might come closer to an ideal
people also can expend limited resources when state of effective use of a belief in free will, but
motivated or given incentives (Muraven & none of us can achieve perfectly this summit in
Slessareva, 2003). They can express less self- personal growth. At the same time, development
control if reading about someone who did not can proceed fairly well, and even when events
exert self-control or even if told they had good happen that are negative, e.g., in Posttraumatic
self-control (respectively, Ackerman, Goldstein, Stress Disorder (PTSD), ameliorative factors,
Shapiro, & Bargh, 2009; Nordgren, van Harreveld, such as posttraumatic growth, might develop
& van der Pligt, 2009). Also, it is worth noting (either through personal and social resources or in
that high self-control relates to attachment secu- rehabilitation due to psychotherapeutic interven-
rity and relationship satisfaction (Tangney et al., tions, such as the one described in this chapter).
2004; Vohs, Finkenauer, et al., 2011). Therefore, to conclude, for those in need of them,
After their extensive review of self-control in the tables and figures developed for the free will
adults and the variables that impact it, Alquist psychotherapeutic module described in the pres-
and Baumeister (2012) concluded that self- ent chapter might be helpful as part of psycho-
control is essential to social life and that it can be therapeutic work. Clients for whom augmenting a
managed. At the same time, it is noted that its belief in free will would be beneficial might profit
lack is related to increased mental illness and from use of these tables in psychotherapy.
antisocial behavior and to less success in rela-
tionships and work. Research using methods that
interfere with people’s beliefs has shown that free The Transdiagnostic
will belief can be altered. Vohs and Schooler Psychotherapeutic Module on Free
(2008) found that undermining belief in free will Will Belief and Change
even increase the probability of cheating.
Introduction

Comment A fundamental assumption underlying psycho-


therapy is that patients can learn to make better
Augmenting belief in free will might facilitate choices. The next seven tables and two figures
behavioral change in psychotherapy. Patients specifically present the psychotherapeutic mod-
become less able to think rationally when they ule developed in the present work for promoting
are stressed, ill, or hurt. Therefore, increasing free will in psychotherapy, which is aimed at
belief in free will could help in this regard. Also, helping patients make better choices.
consider that the belief in free will is a general There are numerous barriers to the develop-
undercurrent of focus in all psychotherapy and ment of having a sense of free will, or believing
The Transdiagnostic Psychotherapeutic Module on Free Will Belief and Change 517

in free will. At the risk of being oversimplicity, ered in developing a free will belief module for
they reduce to a formula involving the person, psychotherapy. In order to facilitate their change,
biology, and environment. Table 20.1 illustrates how past patterns can be
reframed. For present ones, I emphasize develop-
ing appropriate problem solving. For moving bet-
Functional Perspective ter toward the future, the table emphasizes that
patients can increase having a sense of free will.
In the first table of the series, I use the FACCDs
(Functional Analytic Clinical Case Diagrams;
Haynes, O’Brien, & Kaholokula, 2011) model to Deception
stimulate thought on working toward liberating
issues related to past, present, and future. As Deception of self and others is considered critical
reviewed in Chap. 6, functional analysis involves to normal functioning (e.g., Mlodinow, 2012;
the identification of important, controllable func- Trivers, 2011). However, deception can become a
tional relationships in indexed behaviors of peo- major focus in psychotherapy (Kottler & Carlson,
ple, whether the behaviors are causal or not. 2011). According to Trivers (2011), we humans
Psychotherapeutically functional analysis allows have inherited the capacity to deceive ourselves
for dynamic modeling of client symptomology, in order to better deceive others. This capacity is
goals, and social relationships. This approach facilitated by a notable unconscious, internal
especially individualizes causality the causes of information reorganization. Deception could take
behavior in relation to psychological difficulties the form of overt lying, but it involves much
that are being expressed by clients in their imme- more, including of unconscious active self-
diate contexts. deception. Moreover, active other-deception need
However, the patterns found in therapy also not be defensive or passive; indeed, often it is
have roots in the past, so this should be consid- conscious and offensive. However, the main

Table 20.1 Facilitating free will in making life choices through psychotherapy from a functional perspective
Strategya How can you use this knowledge to help yourself?a
Free will with respect to past: Freeing the past:
Reframing functional causal links from perspective of We are seeking in you when some coping, growth,
choosing new ways of viewing past stress reduction, etc., had taken place in the past;
what are lessons that can be learned from the past in
this regard
Free will with respect to present: Freeing the present:
Developing behavioral, cognitive, interpersonal, narrative, How can you have a better capacity to create
and other relevant strategies to work on extant relevant effective plans to deal with issues, and better ways of
causal links still present from past implementing/monitoring them
Free will with respect to future: Freeing the future:
Developing capacity to choose different options, plans, Explaining yourself that you can develop a sense of
behaviors, etc., with respect to issues indicated by any free will that can help you be yourself and have
causal analysis of problems/predicaments/stresses that others be themselves
might arise in future You can create models of yourself that include not
only things like self-confidence and sensitivity to
others, but also sensing if one has free will and can
feel free in even the most difficult of times [and that
you can manage constraints that impinge on that
growing feeling]
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feigning, and response
bias in psychiatric/psychological injury: Implications for Practice and court. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer
Science + Business Media; with kind permission from Springer Science + Business Media B. V. [Table 23.1, Page. 595,
modified]
a
Analysis of causal links leading to patient presentation in functional analytic clinical case diagrams (FACCDs; Haynes
et al., 2011)
518 20 Free Will in Psychotherapy: Helping People Believe

Table 20.2 Self- and other-deception in the growth of free will for topics in psychotherapy
Type Example
Self-deception, constructive Over-valuing abilities
Are you underestimating challenges
This could lead to constructive outcomes if the self-depletion is not extreme, all
else being equal
Self-deception, destructive Self-depletion is extreme
For example, we hide or openly lie about personal faults, conflicts, intentions,
etc., that need moderation/resolution
Other-deception, constructive Self-depletion could involve the other, but not extremely so
Other-deception, destructive But it could be extreme, and we do not see the person clearly, perhaps with very
negative consequences
Balance The more self- and other-deception are toward the constructive side, the more likely
the constraints on developing a sense of free will and feeling free are minimized.
How can you develop balance in this regard?
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feigning, and response
bias in psychiatric/psychological injury: Implications for Practice and court. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer
Science + Business Media; with kind permission from Springer Science + Business Media B. V. [Table 23.2, Page. 595,
modified]
Note. The table illustrates one barrier to the growth of belief in free will—that of self- and other-deception. The table
illustrates how the psychotherapist can work toward balance in these regards

function of self-deception lies in its unconscious pants had to write about actions that they consid-
origins, which helps make deception more ered “free.” The other participants had to describe
difficult to detect and helps lead one to deny it their past behavior when it had not appeared to
had been intentional. reflect their own free will.
Self-deception can be moderated by having Stillman et al. (2011) continued that belief in
constructive compared to destructive directions free will might be an evolved human adaptation. It
in this regard, as per Table 20.2. The same applies has been selected because it confers advantages in
to other-deception. The therapist who is analyz- reaching desired states and goals, especially in our
ing and becoming aware of these tendencies in complex social and cultural environments
the patient should seek to readdress their imbal- (Baumeister, 2005). In addition, from an evolution-
ance in the way indicated in the table. ary perspective, free will belief contributes to sur-
The next four tables on free will in psycho- vival and reproduction (“enlightened self-interest”)
therapy are based on the work of Roy Baumeister. by its promotion of the ability to make informed
In the present tables for the psychotherapeutic choices, resist temptation and societal pressure, and
module involving belief in free will, I work from achieve greater gain later on. The authors equated
the conceptions of Baumeister and colleagues on free will with free action and also with action
free will in everyday life and on the cognitive undertaken from the agent’s “own free will.”
underpinnings to free will and apply them to the As for the results of their investigation,
psychotherapeutic context. Stillman et al. (2011) found that folk conceptions
of free will organized around major themes. They
include the adaptive value of free will and also
Daily Life the positive outcomes and goals that having a
belief in free will facilitate. Some cognitive con-
Table 20.3 focuses on the work of Stillman, comitants are considered relevant, too, e.g., delay
Baumeister, and Mele (2011) on the psychology in decision making and making conscious
of free will in daily life. The authors conducted a choices. The social-affective aspect is consid-
study of autobiographical narratives given by ered, as well, for example, morality and avoiding
psychology undergraduates. Half of the partici- external control.
The Transdiagnostic Psychotherapeutic Module on Free Will Belief and Change 519

Table 20.3 Topics of free will in psychotherapy I: free will in everyday life
Area Now can you use this knowledge to help yourself?
Free will and adaptation: In our everyday Think of several ways in your daily life that you show you have a sense
life, having a sense of free will helps us of free will. Then, think of several ways your sense of free will can be
reach positive things we want for improved, e.g., in helping you reach desired goals and outcomes. How
ourselves, especially social ones, such as can you help yourself increase your sense of free will in your everyday
attaining certain states/conditions, goals, life? Think of several ways.
or outcomes.
Positive outcomes and goal attainment Here are some specific examples to consider.
Self-interest and time frame: Having a For example, having a sense of free will allows us to resist temptations
sense of free will can help us delay and delay seeking immediate gratification for better results that we
wanting benefits right away and wait for could get in waiting. Would developing this skill help you in obtaining
better ones later on. positive outcomes and attainment of desired goals? How can you
develop the skill? List several ways.
Consciousness and freedom: Having a For example, viewing our behavior as a product of conscious thought
sense of free will is accompanied by the means that we can improve our awareness of it, which would help in
belief that our behavior is undertaken our reasoning, problem analysis, and decision making, so that our
consciously rather than automatically out choices appear freely chosen rather than not free. How can you increase
of our awareness. conscious awareness of your automatic thought so that your sense of
having free will increases? List some exercises that you might do in this
regard.
Morality and collective benefits: Having a sense of free will means behaving toward others with a sense
Behaving morally helps the other person of having chosen freely, and this includes behaving morally, as well as
and the group, aside from the outcome following a set of group standards and prohibitions that might seem to
that it is part of the behavior that enables work against our self-interest at first. However, fitting into the group
individuals to fit into the group. However, brings benefits to the person, and this might be lacking. How can you
it also might be part of human nature improve your sense of free will in terms of the choices that you are
because it brings benefits to the person making socially, morally, and collectively? List your ideas.
acting morally, e.g., respect of others,
access to resources related to the actions
involved.
External influence: Having a sense of free For example, you might have to deal with it directly, such as presenting
will socially also means that external counter-arguments, negotiating, etc., or doing what you require and
forces, pressures, and authorities can be knowing how to deal with the consequences. Or, you might have to deal
overcome, resisted, or somehow with it indirectly, such as manipulating toward your desired ends,
controlled when their exertion of control getting allies to argue for you and support you. This all requires much
over us is too detrimental. skill, but you might have done some of this in the past. What did you do
this way? How can you do more? List the ways.
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feigning, and response
bias in psychiatric/psychological injury: Implications for Practice and court. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer
Science + Business Media; with kind permission from Springer Science + Business Media B. V. [Table 23.3, Page. 597,
modified]
Note. This table and the next four ones use in promoting free will in psychotherapy are based on the work of Baumeister
and colleagues for the present table. The left side of the table is adapted from Stillman et al. (2011). Their work
describes the role of free will in everyday life. On the right side of the table, I indicate how free will might be promoted
on the basis of their understanding of free will in everyday life

As for the psychotherapeutic interventions that Self-Regulation


can be used to promote free will that are given in
the table, they were created partly based on the Baumeister and Vohs (2011) reviewed the cogni-
explanations and text accompanying Stillman tive capacities needed for effective executive
et al.’s (2011) explanation of these folk psycho- function and self-regulation. Baumeister and
logical concepts of free will. The psychothera- Vohs (2011) viewed the self as active, involved,
peutic component of the table guides patients in responsive, and intentional, including in chang-
adapting a more flexible cognitive and social ing, altering, or modifying behavior. In this
approach to problem solving and daily living. regard, the self manifests self-control, and its
520 20 Free Will in Psychotherapy: Helping People Believe

Table 20.4 Topics of free will in psychotherapy II: self-regulation and the executive function of the self
Area How can you use this knowledge to help yourself?
Delay of gratification Delay of gratification is important to everyday life. List several benefits in
waiting for better choices later on rather than seeking immediate gratification.
How can you improve this skill?
Feedback loops We need to monitor our plans, strategies for reaching them, motivation to
follow them, etc. How can you improve these skills?
Trait self-control Maintaining good habits is a great way of keeping control. How can you
work toward developing better habits and controlling bad or interfering ones?
Strengths model of self-regulation Self-regulation requires good habits related to sleep, nutrition, exercise, etc.
How can you plan effectively to reach your goals and work toward not
depleting your energy by using ineffective actions toward your goals,
following improper lifestyle habits, etc.?
Beyond self-regulation: choice, People can improve their sense of having free will and also their current
initiative, and free will sense of having choices and their initiative by completing brief exercises.
These include … How can you apply these exercises to yourself? Can you
think of others?
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feigning, and response
bias in psychiatric/psychological injury: Implications for Practice and court. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer
Science + Business Media; with kind permission from Springer Science + Business Media B. V. [Table 23.4, Page. 598,
modified]
Note. Left side of table adapted from Baumeister and Vohs (2011). In this free will psychotherapeutic model, I build on
Baumeister and Vohs (2011) work on self-regulation and executive function. The right side of the table proposes state-
ments and questions that can be used with clients in these regards

executive function selects/initiates behavior 2011). To conclude, the ego depletion section of
toward this end. In addition, self-regulation con- their review, Baumeister and Vohs (2011) referred
cerns self-directed, volitional behaviors, but it to a meta-analysis by Hagger, Wood, Stiff, and
does not have to be consciously initiated. Chatzisarantis (2010) on the “medium to large”
Baumeister and Vohs (2011) especially effect size found for the effect of an ego depletion
reviewed the literature related to self-regulation, task on self-control compared to similar tasks not
and the following summarizes their review of (a) involving ego depletion.
the “strengths model” of self-regulation and (b) These higher-order cognitive skills relate to
patterns of ego depletion. In terms of the strength self-control, problem solving, planning, working
model, self-regulation is considered to require memory deployment, and etc., as presented in
sufficient psychological energy or resource, and Table 20.4. Also, the table presents Baumeister’s
it can be depleted by self-regulatory demands. model of ego depletion (e.g., Baumeister, 2008).
For example, low levels of blood glucose are As indicated, behaving from a belief in free will
linked to various poor behavioral outcomes requires energy; and research has shown that
(Gailliot & Baumeister, 2007) and self-regulatory tasks that deplete/interfere with energy adversely
acts can serve to lower glucose bloodstream lev- affect free will belief and its attendant advan-
els (Gailliot et al., 2007). tages. Developing and maintaining a belief in
As for overtaxing self-regulatory resources, free will requires a healthy lifestyle and also
Baumeister and colleagues referred to the pro- appropriate in thinking and affect.
cess of “ego depletion.” It has been found to
influence cognitive processes and even perfor-
mance on IQ tests (Schmeichel, Vohs, & Consciousness
Baumeister, 2003). It affects resistance to cheat-
ing and honesty (Mead, Baumeister, Gino, Baumeister et al. (2011) conceptualized a rela-
Schweitzer, & Ariely, 2009). It involves more tionship between free will and consciousness.
than being physically tired (Vohs, Glass, et al., They argued that consciousness appears especially
The Transdiagnostic Psychotherapeutic Module on Free Will Belief and Change 521

useful in allowing both “nonpresent” factors and attempting to do something else. Masicampo and
social/cultural information to “shape” behavior Baumeister (2011) found that if study partici-
and also to deal with multiple, competing options/ pants formed implementation intentions (see
impulses. However, in supporting this position, next) to undertake the behavior, these types of
the authors are not disputing the notion that intrusive thoughts were reduced greatly. Another
unconscious influences impact “almost every” line of research involves implementation inten-
behavior in people, and that they mix frequently tions, which were shown to induce behavioral
with conscious ones. change beyond the effects of simply intending,
To begin their review, Baumeister et al. (2011) desiring, goal setting, and valuing (e.g.,
asked the provocative question of whether con- Gollwitzer & Sheeran, 2006; Papies, Aarts, & de
scious thoughts cause behavior. The behaviorists Vries, 2009). Similarly, Watkins (2008) found
had considered conscious thought without rele- that repetitive thought helped improve later out-
vance, an epiphenomenon, at best. Detractors had come/performance when it focused on planning.
argued that behavior is almost fully or is fully About replaying, interpreting, and reflecting
“automatic,” does not “originate” with conscious on events in the past, Baumeister et al. (2011)
processes, etc. (e.g., Bargh, 1997; Dijksterhuis, continued that the research demonstrates that
Chartrand, & Aarts, 2007). Others added that it thinking related to past events can alter future
has no causative properties and is post-hoc behavior/outcomes. For example, Anseel,
(Dijksterhuis, Aarts, & Smith, 2005; Jeannerod, Lievens, and Schollaert (2009) conducted a study
2006). Roediger, Goode, and Zaromb (2008) that shows that if a person reflects on an unsuc-
referred to Libet’s (1985) classic research that cessful task performance or on feedback related
brain wave activity related to finger movement to it, this acts to improve subsequent perfor-
showed a sharp increase prior to self-reported mance. In another example, Ciarocco, Vohs, and
conscious decision to move. They indicated that Baumeister (2010) showed that ruminating about
Libet’s findings deny that conscious “intention” how one had erred in a failed task caused signifi-
causes action. cant improvement in subsequent performance.
Baumeister et al. (2011) moved the debate to Also, writing or speaking about traumatic events
another plane by indicating that there are two one had experienced causes mental health
forms or levels of consciousness—the phenome- improvement (Pennebaker & Chung, 2007). In
nal one, e.g., subjective experience, and the terms of reasoning, deciding, and problem solv-
uniquely human one of “reflection,” reason, and ing, Baumeister et al. (2011) reviewed that
elaborated sense of self. Moreover, they pointed unconscious processes might be “superior” for
out that even if the origins of a behavior are lower-order mental processes but not higher-
unconscious, conscious contemplation intervenes order ones, such as logical reasoning. For exam-
in determining the outcome. ple, DeWall, Baumeister, and Masicampo (2008)
To verify their hypothesis of a role in behavior showed that telling participants that they would
for conscious causation, Baumeister et al. (2011) have to explain their results improved perfor-
and Baumeister, Masicampo, and Vohs (2015) mance on logic problems. The meta-analysis by
restricted their literature review to experimental Fox, Ericsson, and Best (2011) reported similar
designs with random assignment. For example, findings and conclusions. Indeed, merely expect-
studies of simulation in mental practice or ing to require an explanation of one’s actions
rehearsal have shown that it reliably improves appears to stimulate conscious thought and alter
performance in a host of areas (Kosslyn & behavior (Scholten, van Knippenberg, Nijstad, &
Moulton, 2009). Also, Masicampo and De Dreu, 2007).
Baumeister (2011) studied Zeigarnik effect in The evidence in favor of conscious causation
terms of mental causation. In the effect, goals includes research on mentally stimulating per-
that are unfulfilled cause intrusive thoughts about spective taking by the other (e.g., Galinsky,
the unfulfilled goals even when the individual is Maddux, Gilin, & White, 2008); manipulation of
522 20 Free Will in Psychotherapy: Helping People Believe

self-regard/self-affirmation (e.g., Schmeichel & In the psychotherapeutic approach in


Vohs, 2009); mental framing/goal setting (e.g., Table 20.5, psychotherapists might ask patients
McGlone & Aronson, 2007); and facilitating to engage in exercises that promote conscious
intergroup communication (e.g., Halevy, causation compared to automatic, unconscious
Bornstein, & Sagiv, 2008; Sutter & Strassmair, causation. For example, patients might engage in
2009). Other research affirms that conscious exercises that help practice, plan, reflect, reason,
thought can override automatic responses. create, empathize, self-value, reframe, and com-
Westling, Mann, and Ward (2006) demonstrated municate. In this way, a belief in and sense of free
this in their study. They showed that under low will should be facilitated.
compared to high cognitive load, smokers were
less affected by pro-smoking compared to anti-
smoking cues. Reasoning and Motivation
After this comprehensive review of the litera-
ture, Baumeister et al. (2011) concluded that con- Table 20.6 includes work by Baumeister and col-
scious causation exists and is especially shown leagues on reasoning in free will (Pocheptsova,
by “offline and indirect” effects on subsequent Amir, Dhar, & Baumeister, 2009). In addition, it
downstream behavior compared to direct control. includes work by Inzlicht and Schmeichel (2012)
The authors noted that conscious thought func- on motivation and attention in self-control and on
tions to “facilitate” social life and culture resource or ego depletion. The former empha-
(Baumeister & Masicampo, 2010). sizes focus on long term as opposed to short term

Table 20.5 Topics of free will in psychotherapy III: conscious causation


Area How can you use this knowledge to help yourself?
Mental simulation, mental practice Mentally rehearsing important activities improves performance and reaching
the goals associated with them. Give example
Anticipating, planning, intending Having specific behaviorally-focused plans helps arrive at goals. Give
example
Replaying, interpreting, reflecting Writing about or talking about past events that need reworking, such as
on past events traumas, improves the ability to move forward. Give example
Reasoning, deciding, solving Increasing the conscious motivation to be logical, to explain oneself, etc.,
problems improves performance. Give example
Counterproductive, maladaptive Having conscious goals to be creative enhances creativity. Give example
effects
Mentally simulating others’ Taking the perspective of the other, or seeing their world, view, theory, mind,
perspectives etc., helps. Give example
Manipulations of self-regard, Thinking positively about the self, its core, etc., changes behavior positively.
self-affirmation Give example
Mental framing and goal setting Believing that one is part of a high-performing group, e.g., being good in
math, helps performance. Give example
Communication and mutual Being good in group communication enhances the person’s and the group’s
understanding functioning. Give example
Overriding automatic responses It is easier to override automatic responses and be conscious about choice
when our ego or self resources are not overtaxed. Give example
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feigning, and response
bias in psychiatric/psychological injury: Implications for Practice and court. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer
Science + Business Media; with kind permission from Springer Science + Business Media B. V. [Table 23.5, Page. 598,
modified]
Note. Left side adapted from Baumeister et al. (2011). In this table, I provide constructive suggestions and exercises that
might help in becoming more conscious about causation and behaving with a belief in free will
The Transdiagnostic Psychotherapeutic Module on Free Will Belief and Change 523

Table 20.6 Topics of free will in psychotherapy IV: mechanisms in motivation, attention, and reasoning
Problematic area Counter example (How can you use this knowledge to help yourself?)
Shifts in motivation: I do not I still can control myself, if I focus and try harder. Even if my motivation lags, I
want to control myself can boost it. The rewards in the end will be worth it. I have the resources to shift
back to being motivated.
Shifts in motivation: I want to I might feel that I should act impulsively, but I can get back on target and control
go with my gut that.
Shifts in attention: Do I need to I can focus on things (cues) that get me motivated again instead of on things that
control myself now? get in the way, like shifting to actions that bring short term rewards instead of
long term ones that are much better.
Shifts in attention: I see Instead of paying attention to what is important to beneficial long term goals,
immediate rewards attention shifts to paying attention to cues related to immediate rewards that are
not as beneficial. However, I can shift back by ignoring these cues and rewards
and focusing on cues related to the long term goals. It is not just about the short
term pleasures but also about a different kind of pleasure related to having a job
well done, and the like.
Shifts in Reasoning: Resource When I get tired or low, I might think less carefully and reason by intuition only
depletion enhances the role of instead of using good problem solving skills and seeing the big picture. But
intuitive reasoning by impairing because I know that can happen, I can work hard to control it. Better to see all
deliberate careful processing the choices and choose the best one, e.g., which one is best for the long term.
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feigning, and response
bias in psychiatric/psychological injury: Implications for Practice and court. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer
Science + Business Media; with kind permission from Springer Science + Business Media B. V. [Table 23.6, Page. 599,
modified]
Note. Left side adapted from Inzlicht and Schmeichel (2012) for attention and motivation and from Pocheptsova et al.
(2009) for reasoning. The table illustrates how knowledge of core psychological processes can lead to therapeutic affir-
mative self-statements that facilitate belief in free will and constructive actions therefrom

goals. The latter refers to using deliberate reason Meaning


when there is no depletion compared to using
intuition when it is present. Specifically, in exert- Baumeister (2014a) defined free will as the capacity
ing self-control, temporary shifts in motivation for free action, or that the person could have acted
and attention take place that serve as negative differently in a situation (Haggard, Mele, O’Connor,
influences on subsequent efforts at self-control. & Vohs, 2010). Free will is essentially a belief in
Self-regulation is reduced and self-gratification that we can never know if it really exists. In this
increased, so that cues related to the need for self- sense, as a belief rather than as demonstrated empir-
control become less salient, while those related to ical fact, free will is not an illusion. For Baumeister
signals of reward are favored. (2014a), free will exists at higher organizational lev-
The research described by Inzlicht and els, and cannot be reduced to lower-level brain or
Schmeichel (2012) supports their model. For neural functions, although it is constrained by them.
example, Schmeichel, Harmon-Jones, and Free will exists on a continuum, rather than being
Harmon-Jones (2010) showed that self-control all-or-none. As for the related question of whether
exertion leads to stronger approach related impulses actions are all determined by previous actions and
(e.g., low-stake gambles). For attention, Inzlicht context, for Baumeister (2014a), the world is not
and Al-Khindi (2012) found that self-control appli- deterministic in process but it operates probabilisti-
cation “dulls” the attentional system. These core cally, including at the psychological level. There are
mechanistic processes help promote immediate multiple alternate futures that are possible.
gratification relative to better control. Note that the Randomness to some extent and variability in
model proposed by Inzlicht and Schmeichel (2012) behavior are adaptive.
for self-control loss after its exertion avoids meta- Baumeister (2014a) continued that because
phorical language such as “ego depletion.” free will exists at higher self-organized levels, it
524 20 Free Will in Psychotherapy: Helping People Believe

Table 20.7 Facilitating free will in psychotherapy by promoting better meaning making
Strategy How can you use this knowledge to help yourself?
Free will is not an illusion; it exists as a Whenever you think that free will does not exist for you, how can you
belief. bring it back as a part of you?
Free will exists on a continuum, rather than Sometimes we have a sense that we have less free will than more of it.
being all-or-none. How can you increase that you have more free will?
There is room for free will in our lives Because things and events in the future are only probable, how can
because the world in our future is probable you guide them to where you want them to go?
rather than definite (it is not determined
without choice involved).
Our mind also can think differently and We do not always think the same way every time; how can we take
generate choices because it can think of advantage of that and choose better alternatives?
options; it is good that there is some
leeway for alternatives.
Free will comes from higher levels of our Sometimes we are too tired, stressed, and so on, to function at our
mind in the self and its organization. highest levels. What could we do to make this better so that we can
feel we have more free will?
The meanings that we create about the How can we improve the meaning that we give to things so we choose
world are ours; that is a sign of free will. better in what we think, feel, and do? Sometimes we let other people
tell us what a situation means; how can we decide this for ourselves,
especially if the other person is off-base?
Because we explain and communicate our How can we improve our explanation and communication better about
choices, this is another sign of free will. our choices? This would help improve our sense of free will.
The meanings that we choose guide our How can we guide our behavior better from the inside? This will help
behavior; our behavior is not just caused by improve our sense of free will too.
the outside.
Being free means capitalizing on options How can we guide our behavior better using things from the outside?
(opportunities) out there.
The more we regulate ourselves (and our How can we be in control better of our thinking, feeling, and doing,
behavior), the more we behave with free and improve our sense of free will?
will.
Adapted from Baumeister (2014a)
Note. The left side of this table is adapted from Baumeister (2014a). His work describes the role of free will in meaning
making. On the right side of the table, I indicate how free will might be promoted on the basis of their understanding of
free will in meaning making

reflects the “meanings” incorporated into action agent to be free, the agent must use meaning as
control and causation (see Table 20.7). Meaning they decide in/deciding how to act. Then, after
derives from rational thought/calculation, moral the decision making, there is top–down causation
actions, and so on. Meaning exists in a network of of action movements. For Baumeister (2014a), by
possible thoughts and ideas that are tapped differ- deliberately participating in the process of causa-
ently by different cultures. In this framework, tion by meaning, free will derives. Free will does
free will lies in explaining choices made to others not create the probabilistic outcomes possible in
and in communicating to coordinate with others, choice, but “capitalizes” on their existence.
which means using meaning. Therefore, freedom Baumeister (2014b) added that self-regulation
is linked to meaningful causation. It is one step or the control of behavior is the essence of free
removed from physical causation, natural laws, will. It affords freedom of action so that the per-
and animal processes. The capacity to guide son can follow the dictates of rational thought.
one’s behavior by meaning is what we mean by Further, culture conditions free will. Overall,
free will. Meaning use frees the causes of action Baumeister (2014b) referred to his approach to
from being only physical and natural. For an free will as compatible with soft determinism.
The Transdiagnostic Psychotherapeutic Module on Free Will Belief and Change 525

Table 20.8 Free will in psychotherapy: promoting logic and free will
Strategy How can you use this knowledge to help yourself?
Thinking automatically and intuitively How have you used automatic thought, intuition, or fast responding
helps, but deliberate use of logic and without thinking through first, and it helped? When did it not? How
problem solving helps, too. could you have handled it differently?
Using the first thing that comes to mind to How have you used the first thing that comes to mind to deal with
deal with something can help, but thinking something in a way that helped? When did it not? How could you
through options can help, too. have handled it differently?
People often have less patience than How have you used patience to control the impulse to act quickly and
needed. Trying out different pathways in to allow you to think through different options? When did you not?
thought can help, but it means thinking How could you use it more?
through them and having patience.
Returning to a starting point of a problem How have you used the idea of returning to a starting point to try
to start again in a different direction could something else? Think of a social situation, a work or school one, or a
help. family situation. How could you do this more?
Seeing the big picture always helps. When Think of times when you have fixed on one aspect of a problem and
we focus on just one dimension of a missed the big picture. How could you learn to focus on more than
problem we become fixed on it and do not one aspect or dimension of a problem, or even more? Will it help
see all the ways to handle it. seeing the big picture and solving problems easier?
Pulling back to think about what is How can you encourage an attitude of stepping back to reflect? Think
happening always helps. Taking a time out of times when doing this might have helped.
to think can lead to better solutions.
When we take time to understand the How can you increase your understanding of the points of view or
points of view of other people, we might perspective of others? When we understand their mind, motivations,
get less trapped in our own views that are and even ways they can help us, things could go better. How can you
not helpful. This does not deny they might learn from others yet still keep your point of view in mind while you
be the best option. expand it, leading to the best of all possible worlds, and the best
solutions to problems!
Being free to think helps solve a lot of Think of times when you were either not free to think, or could not
problems. think freely and problems only got worse rather than better. How
could you have handled it differently? How could you do this more?
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feigning, and response
bias in psychiatric/psychological injury: Implications for Practice and court. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer
Science + Business Media; with kind permission from Springer Science + Business Media B. V. [Table 23.7, Page. 599,
modified]
Note. Piaget’s developmental model includes a shift from preschool pre-operational thought to child and adolescent
logical thought (concrete and formal operational, respectively). The transition is based on developing decentration,
perspective taking, reversibility, etc. Pre-operational thought includes intuitive thought, which can be useful, but it
might be used as a matter of course instead of choice, compromising logical thought and free will belief

Change this transition concern centration, egocentrism,


animistic thought, irreversibility, a lack in perspec-
Tables 20.8 and 20.9 present psychotherapeutic tive taking, etc. Based on these concepts, I provide
modules related to change in underlying cogni- simplified explanations on the left side of the table
tion. They are based on Piagetian notions of transi- and then probe on the right to facilitate transitions
tion from pre-operational to operational thought, to thinking more logically. Intuitive, automatic
which includes transition from intuitive to logical thought has an important role to play in behaving
thought (Ferrari & Vuletic, 2010; Morra, Gobbo, and choosing (Kahneman, 2011; Stanovich, West,
Marini, & Sheese, 2008; Müller, Carpendale, & & Toplak, 2011). However, patients might be too
Smith, 2009; Young, 2011a). The transition is akin engaged in this type of thinking relative to more
to the distinction described for nonconscious, intu- logical modes, in relation to certain important
itive and conscious, deliberate thought. The cen- issues, or dilemmas, bad habits in need of change,
tral mechanisms of change in Piaget’s model in decisions that have to be made, and so on.
526 20 Free Will in Psychotherapy: Helping People Believe

Table 20.9 Change process and creating a better sense of having free will
Area How can you use this knowledge to help yourself?
Change means genuine transformation Just by thinking about the answers to these questions in the table, you
are getting there. The secret is to keep the positive changes in place so
that your core thoughts, emotions, and behaviors change toward the
positive on a more permanent basis. How can you help that happen?
Change means conflict, in ideas and with Change is never easy. Your old and new ideas will conflict and you and
people others will struggle toward better outcomes, solutions, and situations.
How can you manage all that disruption for the better?
Change means constant communication, Growth happens by exchanging ideas, talking, reflecting on the
within the self and with others exchanges and ideas, etc. How can you keep it going so that change for
the better continues or is maintained despite ups and downs over time?
Change means placing new ideas in Change does not mean altering everything you were to develop a totally
contrast with old ideas and seeing their new you. It means keeping the best of the past as you change for the
advantages, and perhaps keeping old better. How can you ensure that happens as you change?
ideas around for the times they still
might be useful
Change means having new ideas work Can you think of new situations and places to which your new ideas can
their way into other areas of your life and be applied socially, with family, friends, etc., in other situations, e.g.,
thinking beyond the original use and work, school, and most importantly, how you think of life, yourself, and
function for which they developed. others?
Change means being active in life and How can you be the source of change, initiating them or the pathways
adjusting to changing situations leading to them, rather than being passive all the time and letting change
happen around you without your say? How can you adjust constantly to
new situations so that the situations reflect you and your ideas as much
as anything else, depending on the circumstances?
Having a better sense of free will means This therapeutic exercise is aimed at increasing logical thought in
having not only better logical thought but solving problems, but automatic, intuitive thought works with it. So by
also better automatic, intuitive thought improving use of logical thought we are not letting go the automatic,
working at solutions to problems intuitive thought. Rather, we are making available both forms of thought
so they can work together. Think of some situations in your life where
this would be true (e.g., for social problem, a work or school one, a
family problem).
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feigning, and response
bias in psychiatric/psychological injury: Implications for Practice and court. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer
Science + Business Media; with kind permission from Springer Science + Business Media B. V. [Table 23.8, Page. 600,
modified]
Note. In this table, I continue using Piagetian concepts of change, but ones that are more generic. For Piaget, cognitive
development refers to qualitative change in thought from one stage to the next. It is facilitated by cognitive conflict
among and communication about ideas, whether internally or socially-derived, but only when the person is in a transi-
tion state. As new cognitive capacities develop and spread in the cognitive structure of the person, they might be con-
trasted with prior ones, which still might be activated (e.g., automatic thought still can be effective). The developing
person is actively involved in self-growth, through openness, curiosity, will, etc. Psychotherapy could focus on this
change model to promote better logical thought and free will belief

Stage model, I have added a beginning reflexive stage


and an adult postformal or collective intelli-
Table 32.10 in Chap. 32 presents a stage model gence stage. Also, instead of referring to the
of the development of intuitive and logical combined pre-operational/concrete operational
thought based on my Neo-Piagetian stage model period as representational, I use the term of
(Young, 2011a). The latter model is quite consis- peri-operational.
tent with Piaget’s, in that his four major stages Using this five-stage Neo-Piagetian model,
are included (sensorimotor, pre-operational, and focusing on the distinction between intui-
concrete operational, formal). However, in my tive (pre-operational) and logical thought
The Transdiagnostic Psychotherapeutic Module on Free Will Belief and Change 527

(rational thought, concrete operational onward), possibility of yoked automatic and rational
I have reworked the distinction between thought in patients might help psychotherapists
Kahneman’s (2011) and Stanovich et al.’s in their effort to promote more effective, rational
(2011) Type/System I thought and Type/System thought, at least when it is needed, and (a return
II thought in terms of the stages in development to) belief in free will.
indicated.
Therefore, belief in free will and having a sense
of free will should be viewed as underwritten by Addictions
an increasing cognitive sophistication in terms of
improving rational, logical (and Neo-Piagetian A major problem in psychotherapeutic work con-
cognitive stage) acquisitions. However, involving cerns substance dependence and abuse, such as
such as illness, injury, and stress, as well as other alcohol addiction. The concept of belief in free
ego depletion factors, might serve to undermine will and a therapeutic module aimed at promot-
use of more logical thought processes. ing it could be quite beneficial to these patients.
Table 31.7 in Chap. 31 illustrates how In this regard, I developed a table based on cur-
Piagetian stages that develop could co-exist in rent understanding of addiction (Köpetz, Lejuez,
thought, and how even lower-order ones, such as Wiers, & Kruglanski, 2013; see Table 20.10). It
pre-operational thought and its intuitive compo- can be modified to apply to other problems in
nent, might be hierarchically predominant in cog- self-control, in which an increased belief in free
nitive deployment. The table also indicates that will can help, such as obsessive–compulsive dis-
patients might resort to lower-order thought pro- order. Köpetz et al. (2013) emphasized the gen-
cesses even when they are disadvantageous, e.g., eral nature of motivational and self-regulation
due to stress, illness, or injury. Being aware of the problems in addiction. For example, in their view,

Table 20.10 Freeing the will to believe in free will in addictions


Strategy How can you use this knowledge to help yourself?
Addiction is not a brain disease, but a Belief that addiction can be controlled begins with the belief that it
whole-person psychological problem that is a condition for which such control is possible; it is not only
can be helped medical and biological but also psychological and social
Addiction might have a biological basis, but By believing that learning can help toward the control of addiction,
it is learned and can be controlled through the person is taking another important step
learning
Addiction is a motivated behavior that Behaviors underlying addictions might first function to serve goals,
becomes an end in itself. Whatever purpose such as keeping friends, feeling better about yourself. But then the
the addiction was serving becomes addiction starts and gets out of hand and becomes the goal. Seeing
secondary to the addiction this “gateway” pattern helps
Addictions become easily triggered, and Addictions become so powerful that simple triggers that could not
even spontaneously. lead to its behavior at first become good triggers. But the triggers
have nothing special about them and can be controlled
Addictions are not about feeling good but There are other ways to obtain the consequences that addictive
about the consequences it brings, e.g., behaviors had brought at first, such as social acceptance. What are
feeling accepted by fellow addicts some of these?
Those who are most vulnerable to addiction You are free to think of better ways to avoid the consequences that
do not have other means of getting the addictions first helped to get. How can you bring out these other
desired consequences, e.g., socialization, ways, i.e., learn of them and choose them?
sports
Addictive behavior can be activated You will be pulled to the addictions despite your new efforts at being
involuntarily, or without conscious free from them. How can you increase your resistance?
awareness or control. Also, it can be
activated by triggers/contexts that are
selectively attended to
(continued)
528 20 Free Will in Psychotherapy: Helping People Believe

Table 20.10 (continued)


Strategy How can you use this knowledge to help yourself?
Addictions take over and there is less energy How can you inhibit the addictions, e.g., by freely choosing your
and will (resources) for other more new ways? How can you give yourself better effort, energy,
constructive things resources, social connections, new activities, etc., to do so?
Resisting addictions takes effort cognitively You are on your way. Your new belief in free will is helping you.
and motivationally But the effort needs to be continual. How can you encourage that?
Replacing addictions by constructive In the end, your new way of living that you are freely choosing, now
activities takes effort cognitively and that you believe in free will, is an immense help. It is bringing you a
motivationally more satisfying life that reflects self-control. You are harming less
yourself and others. Indeed, you are helping more yourself and
others. How can you keep doing that?
Addictions can be controlled by growth in How could your belief in free will become a stronger belief, a belief
belief in free will. The belief in free will that applies to many parts of your life, and a belief that even makes
starts as a small idea and can grow into an better your values, morals, and ways of living?
all-encompassing one
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feigning, and response
bias in psychiatric/psychological injury: Implications for Practice and court. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer
Science + Business Media; with kind permission from Springer Science + Business Media B. V. [Table 23.11, Page. 607,
modified]
Note. Left side of the table adapted from Köpetz et al. (2013). The last entry refers to Table 24.6 in Chap. 24

drug use is perpetuated by automatic goal activa- in the frontal and parietal cortices. To help with
tion and pursuit. In addition, the transition to addiction, the authors proposed interventions
addiction from casual use relates to general prin- related to bolstering the executive system, such
ciples of emotional transfer, accessibility, inter- as working memory training and episodic future
connectedness, and limited resources involving thinking (mind wandering, projecting oneself
goal adoption, activation, and pursuit, in general. into a plausible scenario in the future). These
Köpetz et al. (2013) noted that potential solu- transdiagnostic therapeutic processes are consis-
tions to addiction substance use include: (a) tent with the present approach for control of
increasing processing resources and (b) reducing addictions and related self-dyscontrol behavior
the saliency of the drug-use goal. For example, by augmenting free will belief.
increase in working memory capacity by training
has been shown effective (Houben, Wiers, &
Jansen, 2011). Also, Houben, Nederkoorn,
Wiers, and Jansen (2011) provided evidence that Comment
associating pictures of glasses of beer with
No-Go signals compared to Go ones reduced This completes presentation of the present trans-
weekly alcohol intake. diagnostic module on the use of free will in psy-
Bickel, Quisenberry, Moody, and Wilson chotherapy. The chapter concludes with a
(2015) considered self-control failure as a trans- transdiagnostic examination of growth.
disorder process. They related it to the inability to
forgo immediate rewards for delayed ones. In
addictions, the drug “commandeers” normal Growth
learning mechanisms, leading to dysfunctional
reward processing. This causes, in turn, aberrant Post-Trauma
decision making. In self-control difficulty, the
limbic and paralimbic systems neural network is Figure 20.2 presents a graphical depiction that I
associated with impulsive decision making and use with patients to help them understand and
becomes dysregulated relative to its normal bal- profit from the concept of posttraumatic growth
ance with the executive decision making system (e.g., Bonanno, 2004). It applies readily to the
Growth 529

Increasing

Gains,
possible Recovery
later adds this

Growth Normal
(Developmental, life path
Psychotherapeutic)

Losses,
at first

Decreasing

Time

Fig. 20.2 Growing in rehabilitation. The figure empha- with permission of Rejoining Joy Publishing. Young, G.
sizes that recovery from stress, illness, or injury can bring (2011b). Rejoining Joy: Vol. 2. Destressing. Toronto:
gains that would not have been achieved without the Rejoining Joy Publishing. Reprinted by permission of the
stress, illness, or injury. Recovery in any one area can be Rejoining Joy Publishing. [Figure 10-7, Page. 211].
more than partial, and it need not return only to the point Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business
where it would have been had the stress, illness, or injury Media. Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feigning, and
not occurred. The concept of posttraumatic growth indi- response bias in psychiatric/psychological injury:
cates that we can grow with stress, illness, or injury, that Implications for Practice and court. Dordrecht,
we can learn from them to the point that we are psycho- Netherlands: Springer Science + Business Media; with
logically stronger, and that our life course could change kind permission from Springer Science + Business Media
for the better from having experienced them. Adapted B. V. [Figure 23.2, Page. 608]

problems in the growth of belief in free will and and acceptance and commitment therapy (ACT).
difficulties. One functional goal of therapists Dimensions that are targeted include desire for
relates to helping the patient achieve optimal func- predictability and inhibitory anxiety.
tioning. For example, in the physically injured, the
growth of the person qua person should be part of
the goal (e.g., quality of life, sense of well-being). My Model
Helping in this way includes helping in the growth
of belief in free will, which can provide reciprocal Figure 20.3 illustrates the growth of belief in free
feedback into growth, in general. will and feeling free that takes place in develop-
For another transdiagnostic therapeutic model, ment. A similar growth can take place in psycho-
refer to Einstein (2014), who described interven- therapy. Piaget described cognitive schemas at
tion strategies based on reducing intolerance of the basis of developing sensorimotor, pre-
uncertainty. The model is an extension of percep- operational, and operational thought. Similarly,
tual control theory (Mansell, 2005). It applies to attachment theory describes internal working
internalizing disorders (anxiety, depression) and models; and other theoretical work in informa-
eating disorders, in particular. It spans strategies tion processing describes working memory (see
used in both cognitive behavior therapy (CBT) Young, 2011a).
530 20 Free Will in Psychotherapy: Helping People Believe

As individuals mature, believing in free


will and feeling “free” accelerates to an
asymptotic level, but a seemingly
paradoxical effect takes place. As
individuals mature, they will gravitate to
adopting more Re-Responsibilities (and
Toward removing choices)
Believing in
Free Will/ Increasing, leading to
Feeling Free psychological maturity

Activation/
Psychological
Inhibition Coordination
Integration/
Maturity

Decreasing, leading to
psychological difficulties
Away From
Believing in
Free Will/
Feeling Free
Development
(or Psychotherapeutic Progress)
as Mediated by Free Will Working Models

Fig. 20.3 Growth in belief in free will and sense of being suggests that as we develop a sense of feeling free in the
free. Note. Integration/maturity in free will working mod- psychologically mature sense, we will choose to under-
els (mindset, mode) and also in free will facilitations/acti- take responsibilities that, by their demands on us, diminish
vations and inhibitions/constraints, and their coordinations. our sense of having choices. Given that we do not ever
The concept of free will working models harkens to the attain ultimate psychological maturity, we keep striving
concept of working memory. It is like a scratchpad in for it, and so the model is asymptotic as well as paradoxi-
which we bring to the fore all that is needed to use extant cal. One of the issues confronting individuals as they
free will capacities and associated cognitive and emo- develop in psychological maturity, and as they feel more
tional underpinnings to help arrive at freely chosen plans free, and believe more in free will, is that they must navi-
and their successful implementation. There are both facili- gate the tension between individualism and collectivism,
tators and constraints in its development and use, and a which varies over family and culture. There are other fac-
good balance in activations and inhibition skills can mini- tors, such as the effects of developmental impacts, stress-
mize interference with and successful activation of free ors, illness, and injury. Adopted with permission of
will use and growth, and having a sense of feeling free. Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2014).
Free will (feeling free) constitutes a sense that can grow in Malingering, feigning, and response bias in psychiatric/
development and in psychotherapy. As these feelings gen- psychological injury: Implications for Practice and court.
uinely manifest, we are more likely than not to choose to Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer Science + Business
undertake responsibilities that, in effect, limit our freedom Media; with kind permission from Springer
as defined in other ways. The synthetic model of free will Science + Business Media B. V. [Figure 23.1, Page. 605]

I have adopted these concepts to create the in cognition, affect, sociality, and morality leads
concept of “free will working models.” They con- to psychological attributes related to Erikson’s
cern the components in thought and affect that construct of generativity. The person increases
we pull together in situations related to belief in the scope of responsibilities oriented to and
free will. They mediate growth in free will in the worked for (family, society, etc.). In Young
ways described. That is, as cognitive develop- (2012), I proposed a Neo-Eriksonian model that
ment proceeds and more logical thought devel- parallels the Neo-Piagetian one that I developed.
ops, free will working models differentiate. In terms of free will, this developmental model
In optimal human development, growth indicates that as we undertake more responsibili-
toward penultimate adult psychological maturity ties, we should have less room for less responsible
References 531

ways of living. Philosophically, Lévinas (1985) might apply to one patient but other portions to
considered a critical human characteristic as another. An analogy would be using worksheets
striving to undertake Responsibility (Morgan, and units involving maladaptive cognitions for
2011). In that I consider this motive a constant which only a portion of the types of distorted
daily re-dedication and a motive of being that thought might apply to any one patient.
takes place in the multiple, I refer to it as The free will belief psychotherapeutic module
Re-Responsibilities. In this regard, we are left that is presented deals with a variety of perspec-
with a paradox—the more we mature psycholog- tives that cut across schools of psychotherapy,
ically, the less we have free will for less differing patient statuses, and different cognitive
responsible action. In this sense, the developmen- components underlying free will belief. In these
tal model that I propose is a paradoxical one senses, it could serve as a useful adjunct in psy-
about free will; that is, the more we have free will chotherapy for many relevant psychiatric condi-
to use because of optimal development and less tions, including those prominent in psychological
constraints, the more we choose life options injury, such as PTSD, pain, and mTBI (mild trau-
(responsibilities) that limit freedom of action. matic brain injury). In addition, because free will
The free will model presented in the figure is also belief might be especially relevant for psycho-
an asymptotic one. Because we all have con- therapeutic populations involving difficulties in
straints in development and it is never fully opti- self-control, such as in addictions, the module
mal, we never approach the ideal state of having could help facilitate change in many patients with
a full sense of free will and an unfettered free will comparable disorders, such as ones related to
belief. obsessions and compulsions.
Some of the constraints on people, as they
develop, concern cultural variations. One factor
in this regard that might impact the cognitive References
constructs underlying development of a sense of
free will and belief in free will is the dimension Ackerman, J. M., Goldstein, N. J., Shapiro, J. R., & Bargh,
J. A. (2009). You wear me out: The vicarious deple-
of individualism/collectivism. There are many
tion of self-control. Psychological Science, 20,
more related to family, e.g., abuse. 326–332.
One way of appreciating the change dynamic Alquist, J., & Baumeister, R. F. (2012). Self-control:
is to consider it as an activation/inhibition coordi- Limited resources and extensive benefits. Wiley
Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science, 3,
nation (Young, 2011a). The psychotherapist
419–423.
could work toward activating appropriate free Anseel, F., Lievens, F., & Schollaert, E. (2009). Reflection
will components in the person’s free will working as a strategy to enhance task performance after feed-
model and inhibiting other maladaptive ones. back. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision
Processes, 110, 23–35.
Bargh, J. A. (1997). Reply to the commentaries. In R. W.
Wyer (Ed.), The automaticity of everyday life:
Chapter Conclusions Advances in social cognition (Vol. 10, pp. 231–246).
Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Barlow, D. H., Farchione, T. J., Fairholme, C. P., Ellard,
The transdiagnostic psychotherapeutic module K. K., Boisseau, C. L., Allen, L. B., et al. (2011).
on free will belief and change that has been Unified protocol for transdiagnostic treatment of emo-
presented in this chapter can be used with patients tional disorders. New York: Oxford University Press.
experiencing stress, illness, injury, mood disor- Baumeister, R. F. (2005). The cultural animal: Human
nature, meaning, and social life. New York: Oxford
der, or any other relevant diagnosis, syndrome, or University Press.
condition in which encouragement of proper Baumeister, R. F. (2008). Free will in scientific psychol-
decision making and positive change is needed, ogy. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 3, 14–19.
such as addiction. The tables in the module Baumeister, R. F. (2014a). Constructing a scientific theory
of free will. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral
should be used flexibly, depending on the indi- psychology: Free will and moral responsibility (Vol. 4,
vidual profile of the patient. Certain portions pp. 235–255). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
532 20 Free Will in Psychotherapy: Helping People Believe

Baumeister, R. F. (2014b). Grateful responses to thought- mance of adolescents. Psychological Science, 16,
ful comments by Holton, Paynes, and Cameron. In 939–944.
W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology: Free Einstein, D. A. (2014). Extension of the transdiagnostic
will and moral responsibility (Vol. 4, pp. 271–277). model to focus on intolerance of uncertainty: A review
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. of the literature and implications for treatment.
Baumeister, R. F., Bratslavesky, E., Muraven, M., & Tice, Clinical Psychology: Science and Practice, 21,
D. M. (1998). Ego depletion: Is the active self a lim- 280–300.
ited resource? Journal of Personality and Social Ferrari, M., & Vuletic, L. (2010). The developmental rela-
Psychology, 74, 1252–1265. tions among mind, brain and education: Essays in
Baumeister, R. F., & Heatherton, T. F. (1996). Self- honor of Robbie Case. New York: Springer
regulation failure: An overview. Psychological Inquiry, Science + Business Media.
7, 1–15. Fox, M. C., Ericsson, K. A., & Best, R. (2011). Do proce-
Baumeister, R. F., & Masicampo, E. J. (2010). Conscious dures for verbal reporting of thinking have to be reactive?
thought is for facilitating social and cultural interac- A meta-analysis and recommendations for best reporting
tions: How mental simulations serve the animal- methods. Psychological Bulletin, 137, 316–344.
culture interface. Psychological Review, 117, Gailliot, M. T., & Baumeister, R. F. (2007). Self-regulation
945–971. and sexual restraint: Dispositionally and temporarily
Baumeister, R. F., Masicampo, E. J., & Vohs, K. D. poor self-regulatory abilities contribute to failure at
(2011). Do conscious thoughts cause behavior? restraining sexual behavior. Personality and Social
Annual Review of Psychology, 62, 331–361. Psychology Bulletin, 33, 173–186.
Baumeister, R. F., Masicampo, E. J., & Vohs, K. D. (2015). Gailliot, M. T., Baumeister, R. F., DeWall, C. N., Maner,
Conscious thoughts and the causation of behavior. In J. K., Plant, E. A., Tice, D. M., et al. (2007). Self-
M. Mikulincer & P. R. Shaver (Eds.), APA handbook of control relies on glucose as a limited energy source:
personality and social psychology (Attitudes and social Willpower is more than a metaphor. Journal of
cognition, Vol. 1, pp. 231–250). Washington, DC: Personality and Social Psychology, 92, 325–336.
American Psychological Association. Galinsky, A. D., Maddux, W. W., Gilin, D., & White, J. B.
Baumeister, R. F., & Vohs, K. D. (2011). Self-regulation (2008). Why it pays to get inside the head of your
and the executive function of the self. In M. R. Leary opponent: The differential effects of perspective tak-
& J. P. Tangney (Eds.), Handbook of self and identity ing and empathy in negotiations. Psychological
(2nd ed., pp. 180–197). New York: Guilford Press. Science, 19, 378–384.
Bickel, W. K., Quisenberry, A. J., Moody, L., & Wilson, Gazzaniga, M. S. (2014). Mental life and responsibility in
A. G. (2015). Therapeutic opportunities for self- real time with a determined brain. In W. Sinnott-
control repair in addiction and related disorders: Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology: Free will and
Changes and the limits of change in trans-disease pro- moral responsibility (Vol. 4, pp. 59–74). Cambridge,
cesses. Clinical Psychological Science, 3, 140–153. MA: MIT Press.
Bonanno, G. A. (2004). Loss, trauma, and human resil- Gollwitzer, P. W., & Sheeran, P. (2006). Implementation
ience: Have we underestimated the human capacity to intentions and goal achievement: A meta-analysis of
thrive after extremely aversive events? American effects and processes. Advances in Experimental
Psychologist, 59, 20–28. Social Psychology, 38, 69–119.
Ciarocco, N. J., Vohs, K. D., & Baumeister, R. F. (2010). Haggard, P., Mele, A., O’Connor, T., & Vohs, K. (2010).
Some good news about rumination: Task-focused Lexicon of key terms. Big questions in free will project.
thinking after failure facilitates performance improve- Published online at http://www.freewillandscience.
ment. Journal of Social and Clinical Psychology, 29, com/wp/?page_id=63
1057–1073. Hagger, M. S., Wood, C., Stiff, C., & Chatzisarantis, N. L.
DeWall, C. N., Baumeister, R. F., & Masicampo, E. J. D. (2010). Ego depletion and the strength model of
(2008). Evidence that logical reasoning depends on self-control: A meta-analysis. Psychological Bulletin,
conscious processing. Consciousness and Cognition, 136, 495–525.
17, 628–645. Halevy, N., Bornstein, G., & Sagiv, L. (2008). In-group
Dijksterhuis, A., Aarts, H., & Smith, P. K. (2005). The love and out-group hate as motives for individual par-
power of the subliminal: Subliminal perception and ticipation in intergroup conflict: A new game para-
possible applications. In R. Hassin, J. Uleman, & J. A. digm. Psychological Science, 19, 405–411.
Bargh (Eds.), The new unconscious (pp. 77–106). Haynes, S. N., O’Brien, W. H., & Kaholokula, J. K.
New York: Oxford University Press. (2011). Behavioral assessment and case formulation.
Dijksterhuis, A., Chartrand, T. L., & Aarts, H. (2007). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.
Effects of priming and perception on social behavior Houben, K., Nederkoorn, C., Wiers, R. W., & Jansen, A.
and goal pursuit. In J. A. Bargh (Ed.), Social psychol- (2011). Resisting temptation: Decreasing alcohol-
ogy and the unconscious: The Automaticity of higher related affect and drinking behavior by training
mental processes (pp. 51–132). Philadelphia, PA: response inhibition. Drug and Alcohol Dependence,
Psychology Press. 116, 132–136.
Duckworth, A. L., & Seligman, M. E. P. (2005). Self- Houben, K., Wiers, R. W., & Jansen, A. (2011). Getting a
discipline outdoes IQ in predicting academic perfor- grip on drinking behavior: Training working memory
References 533

to reduce alcohol abuse. Psychological Science, 22, Morra, S., Gobbo, C., Marini, Z., & Sheese, R. (2008).
968–975. Cognitive development: Neo-Piagetian perspectives.
Inzlicht, M., & Al-Khindi, T. (2012). ERN and the placebo: New York: Erlbaum.
A misattribution approach to studying the arousal prop- Muraven, M., Shmueli, D., & Burkley, E. (2006).
erties of the error-related negativity. Journal of Conserving self-control strength. Journal of
Experimental Psychology: General, 141, 799–807. Personality and Social Psychology, 91, 524–537.
Inzlicht, M., & Schmeichel, B. J. (2012). What is ego Muraven, M., & Slessareva, E. (2003). Mechanisms of
depletion? Toward a mechanistic revision of the self-control failure: Motivation and limited resources.
resource model of self-control. Perspectives on Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 29,
Psychological Science, 7, 450–463. 894–906.
Jeannerod, M. (2006). Consciousness of action as an Müller, U., Carpendale, J. I. M., & Smith, L. (2009). The
embodied consciousness. In S. Pockett, W. P. Banks, Cambridge companion to Piaget. New York:
& S. Gallagher (Eds.), Does consciousness cause Cambridge University Press.
behavior (pp. 25–38). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Nahmias, E. (2014). Is free will an illusion? Confronting
Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking fast and slow. New York: challenges from the modern mind sciences. In
Farrar, Straus, and Giroux. W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology: Free
Köpetz, C. E., Lejuez, C. W., Wiers, R. W., & Kruglanski, will and moral responsibility (Vol. 4, pp. 1–25).
A. W. (2013). Motivation and self-regulation in addic- Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
tion: A call for convergence. Perspectives on Nordgren, L. F., van Harreveld, F., & van der Pligt,
Psychological Science, 8, 3–24. J. (2009). The restraint bias: How the illusion of self-
Kosslyn, S. M., & Moulton, S. T. (2009). Mental imagery restraint promotes impulsive behavior. Psychological
and implicit memory. In K. D. Markham, W. M. Science, 20, 1523–1528.
P. Klein, & J. A. Suhr (Eds.), Handbook of imagina- Papies, E. K., Aarts, H., & de Vries, N. K. (2009).
tion and mental stimulation (pp. 35–51). New York: Planning is for doing: Implementation intentions go
Psychology Press. beyond the mere creation of goal-directed associa-
Kottler, J., & Carlson, J. (Eds.). (2011). Duped: Lies and tions. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 45,
deception in psychotherapy. New York: Routledge/ 1148–1151.
Taylor & Francis. Pennebaker, J. W., & Chung, C. K. (2007). Expressive
Lévinas, E. (1985). Ethics and infinity. Pittsburgh, PA: writing, emotional upheavals, and health. In
Duquesne University Press. H. Friedman & R. Silver (Eds.), Handbook of health
Libet, B. (1985). Unconscious cerebral initiative and the psychology (pp. 263–294). New York: Oxford
role of conscious will in voluntary action. Behavior University Press.
and Brain Sciences, 8, 529–566. Pocheptsova, A., Amir, O., Dhar, R., & Baumeister, R. F.
Mansell, W. (2005). Control theory and psychopathology: (2009). Deciding without resources: Resource deple-
An integrative approach. Psychology and Psychotherapy: tion and choice in context. Journal of Marketing
Theory, Research and Practice, 78, 141–178. Research, 46, 344–355.
Masicampo, E. J., & Baumeister, R. F. (2011). Consider it Roediger, H. L., Goode, M. K., & Zaromb, F. M. (2008).
done! Plan making can eliminate the cognitive effects Free will and the control of action. In J. Baer,
of unfulfilled goals. Journal of Personality and Social J. Kaufman, & R. Baumeister (Eds.), Are we free?
Psychology, 101, 667–683. Psychology and free will (pp. 205–225). New York:
McGlone, M. S., & Aronson, J. (2007). Forewarning and Oxford University Press.
forearming stereotype-threatened students. Communi- Roskies, A. L. (2014). Can neuroscience resolve issues
cation Education, 56, 119–133. about free will? In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral
Mead, N. L., Baumeister, R. F., Gino, F., Schweitzer, psychology: Free will and moral responsibility (Vol. 4,
M. E., & Ariely, D. (2009). Too tired to tell the truth: pp. 103–126). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Self-control resource depletion and dishonesty. Journal Schmeichel, B. J., Harmon-Jones, C., & Harmon-Jones,
of Experimental Social Psychology, 45, 594–597. E. (2010). Exercising self-control increases approach
Mischel, W., Shoda, Y., & Peake, P. K. (1988). The nature motivation. Journal of Personality and Social
of adolescent competencies predicted by preschool Psychology, 99, 162–173.
delay of gratification. Journal of Personality and Schmeichel, B. J., & Vohs, K. D. (2009). Self-affirmation
Social Psychology, 54, 687–696. and self-control: Affirming core values counteracts
Mlodinow, L. (2012). Subliminal: How your unconscious ego depletion. Journal of Personality and Social
mind rules your behavior. New York: Pantheon Books. Psychology, 96, 770–782.
Moffitt, T. E., Arseneault, L., Belsky, D., Dickson, N., Schmeichel, B. J., Vohs, K. D., & Baumeister, R. F.
Hancox, R. J., Harrington, H., et al. (2011). A gradient (2003). Intellectual performance and ego depletion:
of childhood self-control predicts health, wealth, and Role of the self in logical reasoning and other informa-
public safety. Proceedings of the National Academy of tion processing. Journal of Personality and Social
Sciences, USA, 108, 2693–2698. Psychology, 85, 33–46.
Morgan, M. L. (2011). The Cambridge introduction to Scholten, L., van Knippenberg, D., Nijstad, B. A., & De
Emmanuel Lévinas. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge Dreu, C. K. W. (2007). Motivated information pro-
University Press. cessing and group decision-making: Effects of process
534 20 Free Will in Psychotherapy: Helping People Believe

accountability on information processing and decision Vohs, K. D., Finkenauer, C., & Baumeister, R. F. (2011).
quality. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, The sum of friends’ and lovers’ self-control scores
43, 539–552. predicts relationship quality. Social Psychological and
Shoda, Y., Mischel, W., & Peake, P. K. (1990). Predicting Personality Science, 2, 138–145.
adolescent cognitive and self-regulatory competencies Vohs, K. D., Glass, B. D., Maddox, W. T., & Markham,
from preschool delay of gratification: Identifying A. B. (2011). Ego depletion is not just fatigue: Evidence
diagnostic conditions. Developmental Psychology, 26, from a total sleep deprivation experiment. Social
978–986. Psychological and Personality Science, 2, 166–173.
Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2014a). Moral psychology: Free Vohs, K. D., & Schooler, J. (2008). The value of believing
will and moral responsibility (Vol. 4). Cambridge, in free will: Encouraging a belief in determinism
MA: The MIT Press. increases cheating. Psychological Science, 19, 49–54.
Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2014b). Introduction. In Walter, K. H., Gunstad, J., & Hobfoll, S. (2010). Self-
W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology: Free control predicts later symptoms of posttraumatic stress
will and moral responsibility (Vol. 4, pp. xiii–xvii). disorder. Psychological Trauma, 2, 97–101.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Watkins, E. R. (2008). Constructive and unconstructive
Stanovich, K. E., West, R. F., & Toplak, M. E. (2011). The repetitive thought. Psychological Bulletin, 134,
complexity of developmental predictions from dual 163–206.
process models. Developmental Review, 31, 103–118. Westling, E., Mann, T., & Ward, A. (2006). Self-control of
Stillman, T. F., Baumeister, R. F., & Mele, A. R. (2011). smoking: When does narrow attention help? Journal
Free will in everyday life: Autobiographical accounts of Applied Social Psychology, 36, 2115–2133.
of free and unfree actions. Philosophical Psychology, Young, G. (2011a). Development and causality: Neo-
24, 381–394. Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer
Sutter, M., & Strassmair, C. (2009). Communication, Science + Business Media.
cooperation and collusion in team tournaments – An Young, G. (2011b). Rejoining Joy: Vol. 2. Destressing.
experimental study. Games Economic Behavior, 66, Toronto, Canada: Rejoining Joy Publishing.
506–525. Young, G. (2012). A unitary Neo-Piagetian/Neo-
Tangney, J. P., Baumeister, R. F., & Boone, A. L. (2004). Eriksonian model of development: Fundamental
High self-control predicts good adjustment, less assumptions and meta-issues. New Ideas in Psychology,
pathology, better grades, and interpersonal success. 30, 241–249.
Journal of Personality, 72, 271–324. Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feigning, and response
Trivers, R. (2011). The folly of fools: The logic of deceit bias in psychiatric/psychological injury: Implications
and self-deception in human life. New York: Basic for practice and court. Dordrecht, Netherlands:
Books. Springer Science + Business Media.
PTSD: Traumatic Causation
21

transition pathways from genetics to disease or to


Chapter Introduction disorder, and the goal of endophenotypic research
on PTSD is to narrow the search for its genetic
The search for endophenotypes that stand between pathways to disease/disorder. Thus, the chapter
genetics and disease has been applied to the diag- examines multiple areas of study that might be
nostic entity of posttraumatic stress disorder involved in endophenotypes, starting with brain
(PTSD). Advances are being made in understand- and neuronal network ones. The chapter con-
ing the pathway to disorder in PTSD in terms of cludes that, despite the burgeoning research on the
brain regions, neuronal networks, stress-related topic, we have a long way to go in understanding
systems (e.g., the hypothalamic pituitary adrenal the multiple influences in PTSD and their relation-
(HPA) axis), and their underlying genetic and neu- ship to the genetic substrate. Moreover, from a
rogenetic bases. Gene × Environmental interactions forensic perspective, there are even more advances
(G × E) and epigenetic effects (e.g., gene silencing needed before the population-level research find-
due to DNA methylation of gene promoter regions) ings are reliable and valid enough, as well as spe-
affect the latter and, as well, the environment and cific to individual and group differences, to help
context reciprocally interrelate with them. the court and related venues in individual cases.
The present chapter concentrates especially
on several major directions in the search for bio-
logical markers of PTSD. The areas of the review Introduction
covered also include the diverse topics of PTSD
models, allostasis, pathways, and the five-factor PTSD is not only highly researched but also
model. It especially includes the most recent highly controversial (Young, 2014). It is part of a
research. Note that the material reviewed does disability epidemic, and its entry criteria, symp-
not fit clearly into the particular categories indi- toms, and their clusters are all hotly contested. Its
cated, in that sometimes some overlap is evident testing also is not straightforward, and needs to
over them in the literature examined. consider possible malingering, among other neg-
The research on the genetic basis of PTSD ative response biases, that confound cases.
serves as a starting point of the review of the lit-
erature. As mentioned, endophenotypes constitute
DSM-5
Note. This contains material from Young, G. (2014).
PTSD, endophenotypes, the RDoC, and the DSM-5. Friedman, Resick, and Keane (2014) described
Psychological Injury and Law, 7, 75–91. that, in the DSM-5 relative to the DSM-IV-TR

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 535


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_21
536 21 PTSD: Traumatic Causation

(Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental stressor-related” disorders. They noted that it fits
Disorders, Fourth Edition, Text Revised; American with this category, along with the others (e.g.,
Psychiatric Association, 2000), the number of acute stress disorder, adjustment disorder),
symptoms of PTSD has increased from 17 to 20 of because of its broad heterogeneous nature and
them, and its clusters from three to four of them; range of individual differences, including sub-
and as well, its entry criteria have changed. On types related to fear, dysphoria/anhedonia,
both conceptual and empirical grounds, Friedman aggression/substance abuse, guilt/shame, and dis-
et al. defended the validity of the approach taken sociation. They argued that the DSM-5 approach
by the DSM-5 work group on PTSD. includes the elements of complex PTSD found in
Friedman et al. (2014) described extant criti- the ICD (International Statistical Classification of
cism of the PTSD construct and replied to it. (a) Diseases and Related Health Problems; Maercker
They denied that the diagnosis of PTSD need- et al., 2013), so it does not have to be separated
lessly pathologizes people exposed to traumatic out. They noted the difference in the DSM-5
stress. Granted, the epidemiological research approach of listing 20 symptoms subdivided into
shows that most people exposed to trauma do not four clusters with the approach of the ICD-11
develop PTSD, but exposure to traumatic events (11th Revision; Maercker et al., 2013) of listing
is quite prevalent in our society. Moreover, not all only three “core” elements (nightmares/flash-
reactions to trauma exposure lie within the bounds backs, avoidance, hypervigilance/startle), and
of normality, even though extreme normal reac- with the rest as “associated” symptoms.
tions are expected and generally nonpathological.
(b) Also, PTSD is not a Western construct that is
applicable only to European Americans. It has Epidemiology
been documented throughout the world. (c) In
addition, the research has shown that traumatic Only a minority of individuals exposed to trau-
memories mostly represent the events that had matic events sufficient to an entry criteria to diag-
taken place, despite some memory difficulties and nose PTSD go on to develop it (Kessler, Sonnega,
alterations. It has not been supported that trau- Bromet, Hughes, & Nelson, 1995; 25 % of those
matic memories are not valid. (d) Similarly, ver- exposed to severe trauma). In their review, Norris
bal reports are more or less valid (Dohrenwend and Slone (2014) updated the epidemiology of
et al., 2006), so the epidemiology of (and validity trauma and PTSD. Most adults will experience a
of) the posttraumatic reactions to events as deter- traumatic event in their lifetime, but only about
mined by these instruments, generally, are valid. 7 % will develop PTSD in their lifetime. At any
(e) Finally, it is unfair to criticize the PTSD con- given time, only 1–3 % (2 %) of the civilian pop-
struct in terms of opening the floodgates to litiga- ulation will be active cases (the rate is higher in
tion because it is meant to be primarily clinical the military). The proportion of those expressing
rather than forensic, in general, like the DSM-5 in PTSD symptoms is “much larger.” Although 2 %
which it is listed. The DSM-5 has “tightened” the seems a small percentage, it translates to over six
definition of a traumatic event applicable to million of the US population presumably needing
PTSD, but it is beyond its parameters that the treatment for being active PTSD cases at any one
diagnosis might be used frivolously, dubiously, time. Nevertheless, there is much resilience in
and for monetary gain, for example, in court. The those exposed to trauma.
best remedy in this regard for professionals using
the DSM-5 for PTSD diagnosis is to assess care-
fully. One day, biomarkers will help in assessment Pathways
but, to date, they still lack the requisite sensitivity
and specificity needed for court purposes. Vogt, King, and King (2014) explored psychoso-
Friedman and Resick (2014) noted that the cial risk pathways to PTSD. The most pertinent
DSM-5 placed PTSD in a cluster of “trauma and ones are variable risk factors, which exclude
Modeling 537

fixed markers (such as demographics). Risk fac- Schema theories refer to core assumptions or
tors might be independent, overlap, be a proxy beliefs that guide the perception and interpreta-
for another, mediate, or moderate. Observational tion of traumatic stressors. In PTSD, they become
studies might be all that are possible in the study negative and troublesome. The person might
of the relationship of risk and outcome. Although either fail to accommodate to or over-
the manipulation inherent in experimental studies accommodate to trauma-relevant information.
is excluded from observational data, statistical Multiple representation structural models
techniques can still tease out, to a degree, causal build on the concept of distinct representational
associations (e.g., by using structural equation systems in memory that operate in parallel. For
modeling, SEM). Nevertheless, the limitations of example, in PTSD, one might be more verbal/
this type of research suggest using “probable” in propositional and the other more sensory and dif-
conclusions about risk–outcome relationships. ficult to communicate (Brewin, Gregory, Lipton,
The authors concluded that the methodology in & Burgess, 2010). This serves to prolong their
the PTSD “risk” research has been limited. PTSD effects.
most likely has “multiple causal pathways.” Also, Gillihan et al. (2014) concluded that it is pos-
resilience needs to be considered. sible to integrate the theories to a degree under the
guise of the mechanisms underlying PTSD. In this
regard, the formation of associations seems criti-
Modeling cal. Second, discrepancies arise between existing
schemas and current knowledge. Third, cognitive
Major Models appraisals are involved. For PTSD, the DSM-5
has been revised to take into account negative
Gillihan, Cahill, and Foa (2014) reviewed the cognitions and negative emotions. Also, theories
major psychological theories of PTSD. Conditioning of PTSD might need to be revised to account for
theories emphasize that it develops through a two- inclusion in the DSM-5 of a greater amount of
factor learning model. First, classical conditioning symptoms and clusters, and how they are arranged,
leads to associations of the traumatic event and as well as changes to its entry criterion, especially
neutral stimuli. Then, operant conditioning leads to because the need to have experienced “fear, help-
avoidance behavior to escape the distress, etc. less, or horror” has been removed.
Keane and Barlow (2002) extended the model to
include two generalized vulnerabilities—biologi-
cal/genetic and acquired, with trauma exposure Fear Model
being a third vulnerability/elicitor. Other learning
models emphasize failure to extinguish a learned Model Wilker and Kolassa (2013) and Kolassa,
fear response. Illek, Wilker, Karabatsiakis, and Elbert (2015)
Emotional processing theories revolve around examined the multifactorial nature of causality in
pathological emotions in PTSD. Memories are PTSD. They related PTSD symptoms to the for-
inappropriately emotion-laden, and they express mation of an associative neural fear network. The
relations across harmless stimuli and inappropri- fear network model helps explain how a trauma-
ate or maladaptive emotions. The cognitions that associated stimulus can activate the complete
derive are negative (e.g., “The world is danger- fear memory structure through its associative
ous”; “I am incompetent”). nature, thereby eliciting sensory, emotional,
In cognitive theory, PTSD results from behavioral, cognitive, and physiological effects.
appraisals related to threat (Ehlers & Clark, In addition, they related the development and
2000). For example, cognitive variables found in maintenance of autobiographical fear memories
motor vehicle accident (MVA) survivors emerged and representations as central to the neural fear
better predictors of PTSD compared to other network. Moreover, they related a brain neurocir-
established predictors (Ehring, Ehlers, & cuitry network as central to fear learning or con-
Glucksman, 2008). ditioning (also see Brewin et al., 2010; Nijdam &
538 21 PTSD: Traumatic Causation

Wittmann, 2015; Schnyder & Cloitre, 2015; on this, the learning involved is supported by a neu-
sensory-near/bound memories vs. relative to con- ronal circuitry associated with fear conditioning
textual/verbal representations, as per the work of (e.g., Johnson, McGuire, Lazarus, & Palmer,
Brewin et al. (2010) that was mentioned above.). 2012; see Fig. 21.1). Stimuli reaching the lateral
As for PTSD’s core feature, Wilker and amygdala lead to new associative connections.
Kolassa (2013) referred to pathological or “strong Once the fear memory is consolidated, repeated
but defragmented traumatic” memories. associations and accompanying reconsolidations
Moreover, Brewin (2011) referred to pathologi- (Nadel, Hupbach, Gomez, & Newman-Smith,
cal memory structure as the “cause of PTSD.” 2012) expand the network, while decontextual-
The pathological memory has emotional, sen- izing it (e.g., Kolassa & Elbert, 2007). Other
sory, perceptual, and cognitive components. components of the neural fear network include
In the following, I review the neurocircuitry of the amygdala, medial prefrontal cortex, and hip-
fear. As mentioned, fear conditioning provides pocampus. Also, it is impacted by the HPA axis
the beginning of a model to explain pathological and the locus coeruleus noradrenergic systems,
fear memory formation (Brewin, 2008). Beyond which are two major stress pathways.

Medial Prefrontal
Hippocampus (H)
Cortex (mPFC)

Stress
and Lateral Basal
conditioning Amygdala Nucleus
(LA) (BN)

Intercalated
Region (ITC)
Fear
network
initiation/
maintenance
Central
Nucleus (from
the amygdala)
(CE)

Hypothalamic- Other brain Locus coeruleus


pituitary-adrenal modulatory systems noradrenergic
(HPA) axis (e.g., DA, 5HT) system (LCNA)

Neuroplastic Processes

Fig. 21.1 Brain neurocircuitry involved in fear learning. fearful situations is transmitted to the amygdala by the
The amygdala is central to fear conditioning. Information hippocampus (H). The medial prefrontal cortex (mPFC)
about the conditioned stimulus and the unconditioned regulates fear expression by projecting to the multiple
stimulus converge in the lateral amygdala (LA) during sites indicated. In fear extinction learning, increased
fear acquisition. The latter area projects to the central mPFC firing to the basal nucleus (BN) stimulates
nucleus (CE) of the amygdala. It controls the initiation GABAergic intercalated region (ITC) neurons to inhibit
responses to a stressor, including by way of the hypotha- fear response emanating from the CE. Adapted from
lamic pituitary adrenal (HPA) axis and the locus coeruleus Johnson et al. (2012); who also referred to Rodrigues,
noradrenergic (LCNA) system, in particular. The system LeDoux, and Sapolsky (2009)
includes feedback mechanisms. Context information of
Modeling 539

Johnson et al. (2012) considered classical fear to the authors, memory access is not hampered
conditioning central to PTSD. It is involved in by a fragmented poorly integrated traumatic
individual differences in the acquisition, consoli- memory of an event at issue. [The findings
dation, and extinction of fear memories in PTSD. address the inconsistency in the DSM-5 PTSD
Pavlovian memory circuits differentiate pheno- criteria that PTSD is accompanied by both intru-
types related to PTSD. Memory strength in PTSD sive recollections yet by difficulty remembering
is an underlying factor in PTSD that interacts important parts of the event.]
with it; memory has qualitative (emotional, nar- Catarino, Küpper, Werner-Seidler, Dalgleish,
rative components) and stability (organization) and Anderson (2015) related PTSD to deficits in
attributes. In PTSD, the emotional quality might inhibitory suppression of salient memories
be overly “vivid” but lack access to narrative (episodic retrieval). Not only was retrieval sup-
expression, as per the work of Brewin. The stabil- pression compromised in research using the
ity of the memory might be marked by think/no-think paradigm (using aversive scenes
disorganization. cued by naturalistic reminders) in patients with
To conclude, the fear model of PTSD consid- PTSD compared to trauma-exposed control
ers it a deficit in fear conditioning, habituation, participants, but also PTSD patients having the
and extinction (cognitive control to negative largest deficits in “suppression induced forget-
valence stimuli), with influence from hyperacti- ting” expressed the most severe PTSD
vation in the amygdala and inadequate top-down symptomatology.
regulation by the mPFC and the hippocampus
(e.g., Rauch, Shin, & Phelps, 2006). Other According to Wilker and Kolassa (2013),
the limbic frontal neurocircuitry of fear is influ-
Evidence Naim et al. (2014) also implicated a enced by several neuromodulatory systems,
cognitive mechanism in PTSD. They measured including those involving serotonin and dopa-
threat-related attentional bias in MVA patients mine. The amygdala expresses an elevated
admitted to the hospital in the day of their acci- responsivity in the fear of PTSD and, as well, it
dents, and they followed up with PTSD assess- manifests an insufficient inhibition by the medial
ment at 3 months. The patients’ physical injuries prefrontal cortex. Also, PTSD involves impaired
were minor. PTSD was assessed using the CAPS memory-related hippocampal functioning.
(Clinician-Administered PTSD Scale; Blake Similarly, Mahan and Ressler (2012) posited that
et al., 1995). Threat bias was evaluated using a the neural circuitry related to PTSD involves the
dot probe task involving pairings of general threat fear neural circuit, which acts to promote fear
words (e.g., scared) and neutral words (e.g., conditioning (a function in the amygdala). Other
carpets). research showed that genetic variations associ-
The results showed that threat attentional bias ated with memory increase the risk of PTSD or
accounted for variance in PTSD beyond dissocia- its fear memory consolidation (e.g., de Quervain
tion, as also measured initially in the hospital. et al., 2007).
The authors concluded that measure of threat
bias could serve to index the risk for PTSD. Also,
the mechanism involved appears to center on
Comment
enhanced low-level attention to threat, after the
With this introduction to PTSD, the chapter
initial trauma, leading to greater memory con-
moves to tracing its endophenotypic pathway.
solidation of trauma-related elements.
The search for the latter is hampered by compli-
Berntsen and Rubin (2014) showed that emo-
cations in arriving at consensus in its symptoms,
tional arousal at the time of a traumatic event
clusters, entry criteria, epidemiology, models,
function not only to enhance involuntary memory
assessment, and diagnosis. As well, one can
access but also voluntary ones. Further, the
query whether in the research individuals who
emotional intensity of the trauma predicts well
have grossly exaggerating their PTSD or
how frequently the events are recalled. According
540 21 PTSD: Traumatic Causation

malingered have been successfully screened out. Comment


This confound further renders more difficult the
search for PTSD’s endophenotypic base. Part of the difficulty in seeking candidate endo-
phenotypes indicative of causative genes for
PTSD is that it does not fit neatly into the psychi-
Endophenotypes atric/medical model for a disease entity. In the
standard medical model, a diagnostic category
Introduction should have one etiology for the disorder and one
consequent intervention or cure, especially if the
The major portion of the chapter relates to presen- one etiological factor suggested is genetic.
tation of the concept of endophenotype and how it However, PTSD is a complex phenotype that is
relates to PTSD. I review multiple aspects related etiologically heterogeneous, including with poly-
to PTSD that might be involved in the pathway genic underpinnings. It has low penetrance
from genes to outcome. However, establishing genetically, a finding that is consistent with the
any exact links from gene to disease/disorder is in resilience to trauma found in the majority of the
a nascent stage, with the first major review on the population. Therefore, given the difficulty in iso-
topic having been published in 2011. lating the genetic contributions to PTSD and the
limited amount of variance any one gene involved
or even a set of genes might have in directly
Model “explaining” PTSD (in main effects), research
has focused on Gene × Environmental interac-
Gottesman and Gould (2003) elaborated the con- tions (G × E) in PTSD vulnerability, onset, and
cept of endophenotype, which had been devel- maintenance, as well. Typically, as conditions
oped by Gottesman and Shields (1972, 1973). such as PTSD develop (or are averted), multiple
Gottesman and Gould noted that the concept of genes and environmental events interact in con-
endophenotype refers to measurable aspects in cert or in parallel with each other and across its
the pathway between genotype to disease. For course or stream over time. In this regard, candi-
neuropsychiatric diseases, endophenotypes date PTSD-related genes should include those
might be found in the areas of neurophysiology, not only related to brain region and circuit-related
neuroanatomy, neuropsychology, cognition, bio- precursors in the causal chain but also to related
chemistry, or endocrinology, and might even physiology, such as the neurotransmitters sero-
include possible self-report data from testing. [A tonin and dopamine, as well as the interactive
more elaborate presentation of endophenotype is effects of genes, environment, and the neurobiol-
offered below.] ogy involved. I would add that genetic suscepti-
According to Segman, Shalev, and Gelernter bility to environmental influence, which might
(2007), endophenotypes constitute lower levels vary in different alleles of the genes involved, and
of analysis of the substrates involved in a disor- the quantification of such effects, should be taken
der, so that they might be closer or more proxi- into consideration in the search for PTSD
mal to genetic activity. The ultimate goal of endophenotypes.
PTSD endophenotype research has been to
locate “causative genes” that mediate heritable
vulnerability, susceptibility, or risk for PTSD. By Genes
seeking proximal candidate endophenotypes
(e.g., hippocampal volume), the hope is to nar- The next section of the chapter reviews the genetic
row the search for causative genes, but the ones research on PTSD in terms of candidate gene
targeted so far have had limited diagnostic studies and GWAS (genome-wide association
specificity. study). The field has yet to map a clear genetic
Genes 541

basis to PTSD, but there are tantalizing findings in 2007; Koenen et al., 2009; Kolassa, Ertl, et al.,
this regard. Kolassa et al. (2015) noted that the 2010; Mercer et al., 2012; Pietrzak, Galea,
most commonly studied genetic polymorphisms Southwick, & Gelernter, 2013; Xie et al., 2009;
are SNPs (single nucleotide polymorphisms; vari- Xie, Kranzler, Farrer, & Gelernter, 2012). These
ation in a single DNA base pair) and VNTRs studies that are cited found an increase of risk for
(variable number of tandem repeats; which alters PTSD when it occurs in association with environ-
the length of a repetitive region of the genome). mental stress and in conjunction with the s variant
of 5-HTTLPR, which, as described, reduces trans-
porter activity, leading to greater fear learning.
Candidate Genes
SLC6A39 However, according to Wilker and
Introduction In terms of genetic factors associ- Kolassa (2013) and Kolassa et al. (2015), for
ated with PTSD, in the first comprehensive paper dopamine, the results have been inconsistent
on endophenotypes for PTSD, Sherin and (e.g., for dopamine receptor D2 (DRD2) TaqIA),
Nemeroff (2011) found that specific polymor- although Sherin and Nemeroff (2011) reported
phisms are implicated. Further, Pitman et al. results related to the dopamine transporter gene
(2012) identified 22 candidate genes in (SLC6A39).
PTSD. The following highlights the major poly-
morphisms involved in PTSD according to recent COMT Other work supports a role for the
surveys (Kolassa et al., 2015; Sherin & Nemeroff, Val158Met polymorphism in the gene encoding
2011; Wilker & Kolassa, 2013). In particular, the catechol-O-methyltransferase (COMT; e.g.,
research highlights that, rather than having a Kolassa, Kolassa, Ertl, Papassotiropoulos, & de
direct main effect, these critical polymorphisms Quervain, 2010; dopaminergic system). The Met
have an interactive effect with environmental polymorphism in the gene encoding COMT func-
contingencies typically related to trauma. tions to enzymatically inactivate catecholamines,
Moreover, one way or another, the polymor- thereby lowering catecholamine activity, and lead-
phisms typically involve neurotransmitters. ing to higher extra-cellular dopamine and impaired
fear extinction learning. According to the research,
5-HTTLPR According to Wilker and Kolassa the Met allele is associated with constant higher
(2013) and Kolassa et al. (2015), genetic evi- PTSD risk in homozygous individuals, but the
dence suggests that there is reduced serotonin Val158Met one is more protective of PTSD. That is,
transporter binding in the amygdala in PTSD in cases of traumatic load, individuals with the
(Murrough et al., 2011), due to a polymorphism allele exhibit a dose-dependent risk association for
in 5-HTTLPR (serotonin transporter linked poly- PTSD (Boscarino, Erlich, Hoffman, & Zhang,
morphic region; the s (short) allele; Lonsdorf 2012; Kolassa, Kolassa et al., 2010).
et al., 2009). This allele, compared to the l (long)
one, is associated with lower gene transcription, FKBP5 Other systems that reveal molecular
resulting in less serotonin transporter activity and G × E effects in PTSD include the FKBP5 gluco-
serotonin clearance from the synaptic cleft corticoid receptor (cochaperone FK506 binding
(Kolassa et al., 2015). This allows for greater protein 5) rs9470080 (affecting the HPA axis;
amygdala reactivity to an emotional stimulus e.g., see Binder et al., 2008; Boscarino et al.,
and, therefore, an enhanced fear conditioning. 2012). Kolassa et al. (2015) noted that the gene
In particular, over six studies have found an encoding FKBP5 regulates cortisol-binding
association of PTSD risk with both the 5-HTTLPR affinity of the glucocorticoid receptor, decreasing
genotype and environmental stress level (G × E it, and causing a prolonged stress reaction, which
interactions; Grabe et al., 2009; Kilpatrick et al., is more marked in conjunction with trauma.
542 21 PTSD: Traumatic Causation

Other Skelton, Ressler, Norrholm, Jovanovic, for PTSD, the risk appears general for its
and Bradley-Davino (2012) also mentioned as frequent comorbidities (e.g., depression; Koenen
involved in PTSD the regulator of G-protein sig- et al., 2008).
naling 2 (RGS2), which is related to the limbic- Johnson et al. (2012) maintained that the
frontal system (the CC polymorphism). This effect strength of fear memory “is heritable.” Their fig-
takes place especially in conjunction with the pres- ure 3 lists 21 regulating genes in PTSD, and they
ence of low social support (Amstadter et al., 2009). include 5-HTTLPR and BDNF. The former is
part of a class in which increased gene expression
Conclusion Sherin and Nemeroff (2011) con- enhances fear memory and the latter in which
cluded that there is sufficient evidence for a neuro- decreased expression enhanced it.
biological model of PTSD, one that includes
genetic and other predisposing factors. Koenen
et al. (2014) reviewed the comorbidities in genetics Comment
of PTSD. Other risk factors for PTSD include epi-
genetic factors (gene silencing due to environmen- According to Logue et al. (2012), candidate gene
tal factors). In addition, PTSD risk factors involve studies have provided inconsistent results in spec-
female gender, prenatal stress, early childhood ifying which genetic loci and alleles might be
stress, physical trauma, and traumatic brain injury involved (citing Cornelis, Nugent, Amstadter, &
(TBI). As for the molecular mechanisms associ- Koenen, 2010). The heritability research related
ated with the fear learning in PTSD, for Mahan to PTSD suggests that there might be common
and Ressler (2012), they concern BDNF-tyrosine genetic underpinnings to PTSD and its comor-
kinase B (TrkB), GABAergic, and glutamatergic bidities, such as depression, which further leads
ligand receptor systems. In this regard, Kolassa to questions about its status as an independent
et al. (2015) referred to various immune system diagnostic entity in need of a search for an under-
factors in disease outcomes associated with PTSD. lying endophenotype. Moreover, the role of any
one candidate gene that could explain the herita-
bility of PTSD would be minimal, and a more
Heritability polygenic approach is needed. Further, the herita-
bility construct does not account for the complex-
Evidence ity of gene–environment interactions and related
phenomena, such as epigenetics, which compli-
Heritability is a behavioral genetic construct that cate the search for the genetic bases of PTSD.
does not concern finding the genes and alleles Overall, the genetic research holds some
related to the phenomenon at issue, but the promise for finding the genetic and gene-
amount of variance that the genetic factors might interactive bases for PTSD, but to trace them will
help explain, in general. Wilker and Kolassa require their better delineation, although GWAS
(2013) queried whether PTSD is heritable (cit- findings might one day help in this regard, when
ing Sartor et al., 2011) or whether, simply, its conducted with the rigor needed. But has the
risk is heritable due to gene–environment corre- research been promising to date?
lation (i.e., the risk of PTSD and trauma expo-
sure are both heritable in terms of the same
gene(s); as per Stein, Jang, Taylor, Vernon, and GWAS
Livesley (2002)). According to Logue et al.
(2012), twin studies give heritability estimates Evidence
that genetic factors explain up to 70 % of varia-
tion in PTSD risk (e.g., Bramsen, Dirkzwager, & Logue et al. (2012) conducted the first GWAS of
van der Ploeg, 2000). Also, Wilker and Kolassa PTSD. Logue et al. (2012) examined male and
(2013) noted that if there are genetic risk factors female white non-Hispanic military veterans and
Epigenesis 543

their intimate partners. They used two instru- some 7012. The Logue et al. (2012) findings
ments—to measure PTSD, the CAPS, and for reported above were not replicated.
traumatic life events, the Traumatic Life Events GWAS are investigating more than 300 genes
Questionnaire (TLEQ; Kubany et al., 2000). The (Solovieff et al., 2014). In their research,
sample size was modest (195 cases and 196 Solovieff et al. (2014) implicated single nucleo-
controls). tide polymorphisms (e.g., the solute carrier fam-
According to Logue et al. (2012), the retinoid- ily 18 member, SLC18A2) in relation to PTSD.
related orphan receptor alpha (RORA) gene
belongs to the NR1 subfamily of nuclear hor-
mone receptors. The AA allelic variation reduces Comment
the capacity of neurons to respond appropriately
to the biological stressors associated with trau- The GWAS studies in relation to PTSD might be
matic stress (e.g., oxidative stress, inflammation). better methodologically than that of candidate
With neuroprotective function reduced, the effect gene research, but the results of the studies are in
is to promote neuronal apoptosis. Overall, the their infancy and are not necessarily being repli-
AA allele acts to confer susceptibility to the cated, as has been found in the case of candidate
development of PTSD. gene research. Nevertheless, genetic polymor-
In support of their model, the results showed phisms related to neurotransmitters do seem to
that the SNP rs8042149 located in the RORA hold promise as influences on PTSD and also on
attained significance at the genome-wide level. its risks. That being said, the complexities of
Further, participants with relatively low trauma gene influences on behavior warrant care in
exposure according to the TLEQ but with the search for simple answers toward finding the
high-risk (GG) genotype had just as much chance starting point in the search for endophenotypes in
of developing PTSD as participants with high PTSD. This is illustrated by the phenomenon of
exposure and the low-risk genotype (AA). These epigenesis in PTSD, which generally is turning
results did not replicate with an African American genetic research on its head.
sample.
The authors concluded that, for other results
in their study, gene associations involving dopa- Epigenesis
mine and serotonin metabolism were not found
as PTSD genetic risk factors, in contrast to the Introduction
results related to them in prior candidate gene
research. Other research has implicated the To some extent, genetic explanations of PTSD
RORA in PTSD (Amstadter et al., 2013). Wilker have had difficulties finding candidate genes and
and Kolassa (2013) also noted GWAS research replicating the findings in GWAS. Part of the dif-
has shown that the gene encoding for the retinoid- ficulty in establishing the genetic origins and
related orphan receptor alpha (RORA) appears pathways to PTSD is that genetic explanations
implicated in PTSD. now include factors such as Gene × Environment
Xie et al. (2013) conducted a GWAS with interactions and epigenesis. The latter, in particu-
European (EA) and African Americans (AA) lar, has been studied in depth in relation to PTSD,
diagnosed with PTSD in a larger study on drug and it illustrates the complicated relationship
dependence/alcoholism. The interview that they between genes and environment in PTSD, which
used addressed 12 types of traumatic events; also, adds to the difficulties in finding simplified endo-
the PTSD diagnosis was based on the DSM-IV phenotypic PTSD models. DNA methylation
(Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental (modification) is the most commonly studied epi-
Disorders, Fourth Edition; American Psychiatric genetic process; it involves the methylation of
Association, 1994). The SNP that emerged most cytosine in cytosine-guanine dinucleotides
clearly significant involved rs406001 on chromo- (CpGs; 5meC).
544 21 PTSD: Traumatic Causation

Ptak and Petronis (2010) noted the following According to Koenen et al. (2014), cutting-edge
about epigenesis. (a) The epigenetic status of an research is implicating environmental epigenetic
organism is much more dynamic than the status moderation of genetic effects in PTSD. These
of its DNA sequence. (b) Certain epigenetic involve the serotonin transporter gene (SLC6A4),
marks could be inherited transgenerationally 5-HTTLPR(s), the glucocorticoid receptor gene
with the DNA sequence that has been altered. (c) (NR3C1), and FK506 binding protein 5 cochap-
Proper genomic function requires epigenetic reg- erone (FKBP5). Immune system genes also
ulation, e.g., in gene activity regulation, inactiva- appear involved. Finally, G × E interactions are
tion of “parasitic” DNA elements, and involved (e.g., for the risk genotype, rs2267735).
chromosomal segregation. (d) Epigenetic factors
might even lead to non-deleterious genes becom-
ing harmful by blocking their timely expression Fear
at the required level. (e) Epigenetic regulation is
essential for proper neural/neurological function, Maddox, Schafe, and Ressler (2013) examined
and its dysregulation contributes to etiopathogen- epigenetic regulation of fear learning and fear
esis. (f) Together, these postulates allow for an regulation in relation to PTSD. They emphasized
integrated understanding of the epidemiological, epigenetics impact on the BDNF pathway and
genetic (DNA sequence), epigenetic, environ- FKBP5 regulation of glucocorticoid receptor
mental, clinical, and molecular features or mech- (GR) function. The former gene site and its poly-
anisms of complex psychiatric diseases. (g) The morphisms have been implicated in PTSD by
epigenetic model of complex disease also Rakofsky, Ressler, and Dunlop (2012) and Smith
assumes that pre-epimutations increase an organ- et al. (2011). The latter gene site has been impli-
ism’s risk of becoming ill. Pre-epimutations are cated in research by Klengel et al. (2013), Mehta
primary epigenetic disruptions that are insuffi- et al. (2011), and Xie et al. (2010).
cient to cause outright disease until a threshold is Similarly, Wilker and Kolassa (2013) noted
reached, which might take decades and involve that the dose-dependent effect of traumatic load
multiple minor dysregulations. on PTSD risk appears affected by the epigenetic
Further, epigenetics forms part of a complex methylation pattern of the DNA of the serotonin
regulatory system in which the environment can transporter gene (Koenen et al., 2011). Another
affect extant epigenetic marks. The effects might study found an interaction of the low-function
even be reversible by appropriate environmental risk allele and higher methylation at the dopa-
support or intervention. The focus of future work mine transporter gene locus in the highest PTSD
should be on susceptible “epialleles” and identifi- risk (Chang et al., 2012). To conclude, Wilker
cation of “epigenetic biomarkers” of disease. and Kolassa (2013) noted that there is interplay
of genetic and epigenetic (and so environmental)
factors involved in the formation and modifica-
Model tion of the fear network in PTSD.

Sipahi et al. (2014) found evidence of epigenetic


DNA methylation (DNAm) increases within Abuse
DNA methyltransferase loci for PTSD cases
following trauma relative to controls. The sample Szyf (2013) referred to epigenetics as the way
was small (N = 30 exposed with PTSD and 30 environments “talk” to genes. He described and
matched controls). The results mostly involved commented upon the article by Klengel et al.
DNMT1 and DNMT3B, and DNAm varied in (2013). The authors found an FKBP5 gene × child
pre–post and case–resilience comparisons. The abuse interaction in that the haplotype rs1360780
authors concluded that epigenetic variation is moderated the risk of developing PTSD after
involved in regulation of PTSD risk/etiology. early trauma. The mechanism involved includes
Epigenesis 545

rs1360780 affecting FKBP5 chromatin shape ter dopaminergic and serotinergic function
and transcription. The findings represent a (respectively, SLC6A3, SLC6A4; Chang et al.,
molecular mechanism in PTSD expression; the 2012; Koenen et al., 2011), as well as genes asso-
latter relates to the risk allele of FKBP5, which is ciated with inflammation (Uddin, Aiello, et al.,
a stress response regulator active in the hippo- 2010; Uddin, Galea, et al., 2011). Raabe and
campus response regulator. The allele is prefer- Spengler (2013) referred to epigenetic program-
entially demethylated in children exposed to ming during early sensitive windows of the HPA
trauma; the effects persist as an enhanced expres- axis in response to early-life stress as a risk factor
sion of FKBP5 into adulthood, potentiating for PTSD.
PTSD development.
The article by Klengel et al. (2013) is difficult
to read for the novice, but Szyf (2013) explicated it Stress
well. Normally FKBP5 participates in a sequence
that suppresses the stress response. In its regula- Zovkic, Meadows, Kaas, and Sweatt (2013) ana-
tion of the stress response, FKBP5 functions as a lyzed epigenesis in PTSD and interindividual
proximal negative feedback mechanism of the glu- variability in stress susceptibility. Epigenetic
cocorticoid receptor. The gene is expressed by mechanisms are no longer considered stable in
activation via the glucocorticoid receptor in reac- the changes that they effect but dynamic in doing
tion to elevated glucocorticoid (a primary stress so. Moreover, individuals harbor particular “epi-
hormone) levels. FKBP5 activity downstream pro- genetic landscapes” on which epigenetic changes
motes resistance to glucocorticoids. are written, for example, due to traumatic events;
As for the risk allele involved, demethylation and the variations involved express individual-
of intron 7 in carriers who had been exposed to specific outcomes, as in vulnerability and resil-
early-life trauma has an effect on gene expression ience to PTSD risk factors and trauma.
despite its linear displacement from another PTSD involves deregulation of endocrine
intron involved and the promoter (gene silencing stress systems and associated neurotransmitters
site in demethylation) involved. The demethyl- and neuromodulators (Baker, Nievergelt, &
ation can take place, nevertheless, because of O’Connor, 2012). Epigenetic modifications con-
three-dimensional molecular activity, through the stitute one set of drivers that serve to dysregulate
binding of RNA polymerase II (Pol II), at least these PTSD bioregulators through their role in
when the variant and early-life stressors are pres- mediating genetic expression of the endocrine
ent in interaction. The molecular effects on the system and related neural and neurohormonal
stress response system in variant carriers appear elements (e.g., molecules, transcription factors).
to affect multiple tissues, including peripheral In a bidirectional fashion, downstream epigenetic
blood cells from which the samples in the study modifications themselves are regulated by
were taken, thereby indicating the potential in upstream biofunctions.
carriers for carrying stress and health effect of In discussing PTSD and the HPA axis,
early adversity coupled with later PTSD. Zovkic, Meadows et al. (2013) indicated the lat-
Additional research on epigenetic regulation ter’s central role in adaptation to stress and the
has been conducted on the gene encoding the GR source of individual differences in risk and
NR3C1, and its polymorphism Bcl1 in stress, resilience to stress. Stressful situations lead to
anxiety, and fear, and the results suggest that the release of corticotrophin releasing hormone
increased NR3C1 promoter methylation levels in (CRH) from the hypothalamus into the pituitary
PTSD patients correlate with the severity of their gland, which stimulates the release of adreno-
childhood abuse (Perroud et al., 2011). The find- corticotropin hormone (ACTH) and activates
ings in the field also relate risk and protective fac- the release of glucocorticoids (GCs, cortisol).
tors for PTSD in epigenetic modifications of Receptors for glucocorticoids (GRs) are situ-
genetic polymorphisms related to neurotransmit- ated throughout the brain, but are especially
546 21 PTSD: Traumatic Causation

prevalent in the hippocampus, thereby influenc- Aside from the HPA axis, Gene × Environ
ing memory/cognitive formation/function and ment × Epigenetic interactions (G × E × E) relevant
also initiating negative feedback to return corti- to PTSD have been found for neuromodulators,
sol to baseline levels after acute stress (Novak, neurotransmitters, and other biochemicals related
Hamel, Kelly, Dettmer, & Meyer, 2013). PTSD to synaptic function/plasticity (Boulle et al., 2012;
patients generally manifest reduced levels in Russo, Murrough, Han, Charney, & Nestler, 2012;
their cortisol, as well as increased negative Skelton et al., 2012; Wu et al., 2013).
feedback, abnormal expression of GR, and more Epigenetic modifications can mediate the
CRH, relative to controls without trauma (e.g., effects of serious trauma even independently of a
Yehuda, Halligan, & Bierer, 2002). The blunt- predisposing factor (Chang et al., 2012). Even
ing of the GC cortisol response to stress appears after controlling for genotype, distinct methyla-
a critical risk factor for PTSD (Yehuda & tion profiles of the serotonin transporter gene dif-
LeDoux, 2007); it appears epigenetically regu- ferentially relate to risk and resilience (Koenen
lated; and the HPA axis seems an important et al., 2011). Epigenetic modifications can influ-
mediator between genes and expression in ence risk/resilience beyond the influence of
PTSD (Yehuda et al., 2009). genetic factors (Ouellet-Morin et al., 2012). The
Stress exposure regulates epigenetic modifica- critical developmental window for having stress
tion by way of GC action on GRs. The GR gene act to effect long-lasting changes extends even
promoter region is liable to much individual vari- into the teen years (Dudley, Li, Kobor, Kippin, &
ation in DNA methylation. There are develop- Bredy, 2011). Finally, epigenetic “writers” can
mental differences (sensitive periods) in also influence risk/resilience (e.g., by affecting
epigenetic modification effectiveness. Epigenetic the balance in epigenetic activators/repressors;
programming could lean toward risk or resilience, Zovkic, Guzman-Karlsson, & Sweatt, 2013).
depending on the confluence of genes (e.g., poly- Zovkic, Meadows et al. (2013) provided a
morphisms), environment (e.g., stressors), devel- summary table of epigenetic modifications appli-
opmental period (e.g., sensitive epochs), and cable to PTSD. They grouped the research by
stress system function. For example, compared to candidate gene studies and genome wide/large
what might happen at other stages, some stress scale studies, as well as others. The genes
experiences at certain developmental stages are involved and the major findings in the research
more likely to lead to resilience to PTSD in adults, on them are given in Table 21.1.
by a “stress inoculation” (Ricon, Toth, Leshem, Skelton et al. (2012) adopted an approach
Braun, & Richter-Levin, 2012). quite similar to that of Zovkic and colleagues.
Authors are now referring to Gene × Environ They argued that stress can lower cortisol level
ment × Epigenome interactions. The environment through epigenetic modifications, but only in the
and epigenetic modifications appear quite salient context of low maternal care levels in early devel-
during early life in affecting behavior, altering opmental windows (e.g., Meaney & Szyf, 2005;
the expression of multiple genes (Sundermann, Seckl & Meaney, 2006; Weaver, 2007). Similarly,
Hauschildt, & Ehlers, 2013; Sundermann, epigenetic-mediated changes in HPA axis reac-
Onwumere, Bebbington, & Kuipers, 2012). The tivity might be associated with greater suscepti-
early environment and epigenetic modification bility to PTSD. The mechanism involved might
have been implicated in potentiating PTSD by be an over-cascade in noradrenergic neurotrans-
their effects on genes associated with the HPA mission, producing over-consolidation of fear
axis (e.g., FKBP5; Klengel et al., 2013; PAC1R, a memories and also increased arousal/distress
receptor for PACAP (pituitary adenylate cyclase- subsequent to trauma, as well as early set-point
activating peptide); Dias & Ressler, 2013; Ressler alterations contributing to the effect early in life
et al., 2011). (Yehuda et al., 2010).
Epigenesis 547

Table 21.1 A summary of epigenetic modifications in human research of PTSD


Gene (s) of interest Major findings Reference
Candidate-gene studies
ADCYAP1, ADCYAP1R1 PTSD symptoms correlated with Adcyap1r1 Ressler et al. (2011)
locus (in women)
SLC6A4 Controlling for genotype, SLC6A4 Koenen et al. (2011)
methylation (m) modified the effect of PTEs
on PTSD: ↓ SLC6A4 promoter m associated
with ↑ PTSD risk; ↑ SLC6A4 promoter m
protective against PTSD
SLC6A3 ↑ SLC6A3 promoter m associated with ↑ risk Chang et al. (2012)
of lifetime PTSD in 9R allele carriers
COMT COMT Met/Met genotype interacted with Norrholm et al. (2013)
CpG m in mediation of impaired fear
inhibition in PTSD patients
FKBP5 GC exposure associated with ↑ FKBP5 GRE Klengel et al. (2013)
demethylation and ↑ FKBP5 expression in
carriers of the risk allele compared with the
protective one
Genome-wide/large scale studies
Genes involved in immunity, PTSD associated with: (a) ↑ m of DNMT3B, ↓ Uddin et al. (2010)
neurogenesis, the startle response, m of DNMT3L; (b) deregulated m of genes
DNMT3B, DNMT3L, imprinted involved in Prader–Willi and Angelman
genes: NDN, MAGEL2, ATP10A syndromes; (c) m profiles of other genes
TPR, CLEC9A, APC5, ANXA2, TLR8, PTSD associated with: (a) ↓ m of TPR and Smith et al. (2011)
BDNF, CXCL1, immune-related ANXA2 and ↑ m of CLEC9A, APC5, TLR8 in
genes PTSD; (b) ↑ m of BDNF and CXCL1; (c)
some other differentially methylated
immune-related genes
Other
33 loci previously associated with ↑ MAN2C1 m interacted with PTE in PTSD Uddin, Galea et al. (2011)
PTSD risk
Repetitive elements: LINE-1, Alu In post-deployed US military service Rusiecki et al. (2012)
members, LINE-1 was hypomethylated in
PTSD cases (vs. control). Pre-deployment,
Alu was hypermethylated in PTSD cases (vs.
control)
Note. PTE potentially traumatic event, ADCYAP1 adenylate cyclase-activating polypeptide 1 (pituitary), ADCYAP1R1
adenylate cyclase-activating polypeptide 1 (pituitary) receptor type 1, BDNF brain-derived neurotrophic factor, SLC6A4
solute carrier family 6 (neurotransmitter transporter, serotonin), member, SLC6A3 solute carrier family 6 (neurotrans-
mitter transporter, dopamine), member, COMT catechol-O-methyltransferase, FKBP5 FK506 binding protein 5,
DNMT3B DNA methyltransferases-3B, DNMT3L DNA methyltransferases-3L, NDN necdin, melanoma antigen
(MAGE) family member, MAGEL2 MAGE-like 2, ATP10A ATPase, class V, type 10A, TPR translocated promoter
region, CLEC9A C-type lectin domain family 9, member A, APC5 acid phosphatase 5, tartrate resistant, ANXA2 annexin
A2, TLR8 toll-like receptor 8, CXCL1 chemokine (C-X-C motif) ligand 1, MAN2C1 mannosidase, alpha, class 2c,
member 1. Adopted with permission of Elsevier. Reprinted from Frontiers in Psychiatry, Vol. 4, Zovkic, I. B., Meadows,
J. P., Kaas, G. A., & Sweatt, J. D., Interindividual variability in stress susceptibility: A role for epigenetic mechanisms
in PTSD, Copyright 2013; with kind permission from the author (J. David Sweatt). [Table 2, Page 14]

Programming axis function. McGowan et al. (2009) had found


that suicide completers with a history of child
As a risk factor for PTSD, McGowan (2013) abuse/severe neglect, compared to those without
explored the possible biological embedding, via it (and compared to controls), showed higher lev-
gene-altering (silencing) regulatory epigenetic els of DNA methylation of the promoter region of
mechanisms, of early adversity into altered HPA the GR gene (GR1F), which is involved in HPA
548 21 PTSD: Traumatic Causation

function regulation, in a brain area that mediates ity, and that NR3CI-1F promoter methylation
anxiety and the HPA (i.e., the hippocampus). could be used as a more sensitive measure of
Labonte et al. (2012) replicated the study. PTSD compared to more downstream endocrine
Follow-up research (Suderman et al., 2012) measures.
determined that a proto cadherin (PCDH) gene
cluster of cell-adhesion molecules showed the
largest changes in DNA modification within the Conclusion
GR locus. The authors concluded that epigenetic
regulation plays a role in programming gene The construct of epigenesis illustrates the diffi-
function in response to early life adversity, and culty in treating biology, environment, and organ-
might be indexed even by peripheral markers. ismic factors as isolated in the development of
Karsten and Baram (2013) posited that neuro- psychopathology. The organism might have allelic
nal modulation in epigenesis due to early life variants that are susceptible to environmental
adversity takes place by early postnatal repro- silencing via DNA methylation and other pro-
gramming in a “critical window.” Early life expe- cesses, which takes place without actually chang-
riences affect CRH gene expression in the ing the DNA. Moreover, the silencing can be
hypothalamus, thereby “rewiring” synaptic con- transmitted to subsequent generations. Epigenesis
nectivity (e.g., reducing excitatory synaptic input is adaptive in a Darwinian sense in that it facili-
onto stress-sensitive neurons). The epigenetic- tates contextual adaptation in the organism experi-
induced CRH alteration could be life long and encing it and also the transmission of the altered
might play a role in PTSD. genetic activity to offspring, so that the experi-
ences encountered in one generation are stored
and passed on to the next, thereby promoting in
Applications the offspring a more rapid adaptation to the envi-
ronment that presumably has the same character-
Yehuda et al. (2013) found that epigenetic mark- istics that had led to the epigenesis in the first
ers could predict symptom amelioration to place. The downside of this adaptive process is
psychotherapy in American military veterans that offspring might be more susceptible to psy-
expressing PTSD. The veterans (N = 16) received chiatric disorder without even experiencing envi-
exposure therapy, with half responding and no ronmental trauma/adversity. Epigenetic stamps
longer expressing PTSD (as evaluated by the might then serve as “biomarkers” of psychiatric
CAPS; Blake et al., 1995). Pre-treatment level of disorders, including PTSD. The task is to establish
methylation of the GR gene (NR3C1) exon 1F in exactly how this works in the case of PTSD and to
the promoter region predicted treatment out- determine the exact endophenotypic candidate in
come, while methylation of the FKBP5 gene these regards. For example, epigenetic-mediated
exon 1 promoter region (FKBP51) predicted in changes in brain structure and function (e.g., net-
recovery. works) and in HPA axis reactivity might be asso-
Yehuda et al. (2015) found an epigenetic effect ciated with greater susceptibility to PTSD and its
that could differentiate combat veterans with and developmental cascade.
without PTSD. They examined epigenetic meth-
ylation of GR gene promoter 1F (lower NR3CI-1F
promoter methylation), and the degree was lower Brain
in cases of combat PTSD. The methylation was
also associated positively with measures of glu- Introduction
cocorticoid activity that have been related to
combat PTSD and negatively with markers and Disease research is moving toward candidate
symptoms of PTSD. The authors concluded that pathway and network levels of analysis beyond
PTSD is associated with enhanced GR sensitiv- the candidate gene approach. The chapter shifts
Brain 549

from the genetic/epigenetic bases of PTSD to Neurocircuitry


more downstream portions that might be involved
in the endophenotypic pathway. This shift in Nash, Galatzer-Levy, Krystal, Duman, and
focus begins with the role of the brain and related Neumeister (2014) described the functional neu-
factors in PTSD. The conceptual and empirical rocircuitry of fear and anxiety. The major afferent
task that is just beginning and remains extremely pathways involve the “exteroreceptive” sensory
daunting is to trace effectively the upstream systems (auditory, visual, somatosensory).
genetic/epigenetic base of PTSD, the down- Auditorially and visually, the relevant sensory
stream behaviors involved and the mediation information is transmitted from peripheral recep-
between them in brain, neurocircuitry, neuroen- tor cells to the relay station of the dorsal thalamus
docrine function, and so on. In the prior sections (the olfactory and visceral pathways are differ-
of the chapter, the role of the HPA axis, in par- ent). The thalamus relays sensory information to
ticular, has been mentioned in this regard, as well primary cortical sensory receptive regions, which
as regions of the brain such as the hippocampus then project to cortical association areas. The lat-
and amygdala. Neurocircuitry research does ter connect to other brain areas, including the
more than simply list the brain regions and their amygdala, entorhinal cortex, orbitofrontal cortex,
functions involved in PTSD in that it considers and cingulate gyrus. The hippocampus is a major
pathways, feedback mechanisms, and so on, and relay endpoint, receiving convergent, integrated
it decomposes the functions to steps, such as in inputs from all sensory systems. In addition, the
learning and extinction. thalamus connects to the amygdala both for audi-
tory and visual sensory information. In turn, it
interacts neuronally with the orbitofrontal
Imaging cortex.
As for efferent pathways of the anxiety-fear
Sherin and Nemeroff (2011) discussed the typi- circuit, it includes the amygdala, locus coeruleus,
cal changes in brain structure, circuitry, and func- hypothalamus, periaqueductal gray (PAG), and
tion in PTSD found using brain-imaging methods. striatum. The autonomic changes in PTSD are
The regions implicated in PTSD focus on the hip- mediated by the sympathetic and parasympa-
pocampus (involved in memory, for example), thetic nervous systems (e.g., the hypothalamus
the amygdala (involved in emotional reactivity), and its innervations/connections).
and cortical regions, including the anterior cingu- The skeletal muscle system is activated in
late, insula, and orbitofrontal region (Rauch PTSD (e.g., fight, flight) through cortical associa-
et al., 2006). Although reduced hippocampal vol- tion areas, the motor cortex, striatum, and amyg-
ume might precede the development of PTSD, dala. The amygdala integrates the central nervous
thereby functioning as a precursor neuroendo- system activity in the expression of fear and anxi-
phenotypic vulnerability (Pitman et al., 2002), in ety. This includes regions associated with senso-
contrast, reduced anterior cingulate cortex vol- rimotor, autonomic/endocrine, and affective
ume (ACC, part of the medial prefrontal cortex, motivational responses. The brain is integrated in
mPFC) appears to be a consequence of the devel- the response, and it involves activity cortically,
opment of PTSD (Kasai et al., 2008). The mPFC, subcortically, and peripherally, and their inter-
in general, is involved in inhibition of reactive connections. The mPFC and amygdala form a
stress responses/emotionality and also in the regulatory connection. Reduction in inhibition of
extinction of conditioned fears. amygdala activity by the PFC has been related to
Kolassa et al. (2015) gave a very similar pic- PTSD.
ture of the brain regions involved in the fear net- Admon, Milad, and Hendler (2013) developed
work underlying PTSD. They referred to it as the a causal model of PTSD that disentangled
limbic-frontal neurocircuitry. acquired neural abnormalities from predisposing
550 21 PTSD: Traumatic Causation

ones. They highlighted that abnormalities within ral abnormalities in PTSD manifestation. The
the brain regions of the amygdala (Amy) and the vulnerabilities involved might accentuate one of
dorsal anterior cingulate cortex (dACC) consti- the three major components of PTSD—the
tute PTSD pre-exposure vulnerabilities, and that hyperarousal component. In contrast, the
post-exposure consequences of PTSD are found acquired dysfunctions might accentuate the re-
in dysfunctional interactions involving the hippo- experiencing and numbing components of PTSD.
campus (HC) and ventromedial prefrontal cortex Similarly, Johnson et al. (2012) maintained that
(vmPFC). the amygdala is central to fear conditioning, e.g.,
The amygdala and dACC appear to be media- in the lateral amygdala during fear acquisition.
tors of fear generation and expression (see The latter region projects to the central nucleus of
Fig. 21.2). The areas of the hippocampus and the amygdala. It controls the initiation responses
vmPFC involved in PTSD acquisition post- to a stressor including by way of the HPA axis and
trauma appear to involve the ability to extinguish the locus coeruleus noradrenergic system, in par-
or inhibit fear. Admon et al. (2013) proposed an ticular. The system includes feedback mecha-
interaction of the predisposing and acquired neu- nisms. Context information of fearful situations is

Predisposing Acquired
Genetics
Factors Traumatic Factors
event

Amy and dACC HC vmPFC


Fear generation/ PTSD
expression Fear inhibition/
extinguishing

Hyperarousal Re-experiencing,
Pre-existing (PTSD Avoidance (PTSD
experiences component) components)

Insula DmPFC Nacc

[Additional brain area mediators]

Fig. 21.2 A causal model of influences of neural abnor- inhibition, thereby promoting PTSD symptoms of avoid-
malities in posttraumatic stress disorder (PTSD): predispos- ance and re-experiencing. The described areas of the brain,
ing and acquired factors. The model of neural abnormalities as well as of their potential interactions (broken curved
in PTSD includes genetic and environmental factors, as line), could result in all three major DSM IV-TR compo-
well as their interaction (broken black line). The factors nents of PTSD being expressed. Other brain regions are
might lead some individuals pre-trauma to display abnor- potential mediators (broken grey lines) (nucleus accumbens
mal structure/hyperfunction of the amygdala (Amy) and of (Nacc), dorsomedial prefrontal cortex (dmPFC), insula)
the dorsal anterior cingulate cortex (dACC). Their predis- through their suggested roles in reward processing, emo-
positions make them susceptible to express heightened fear, tional regulation, and interoception, respectively. Adopted
expressed as PTSD hyperarousal symptoms. Following the with permission of Elsevier. Reprinted from Trends in
exposure to the traumatic event, a subset of these vulnerable Cognitive Sciences, Vol. 17, Admon, R., Milad, M. R., &
people is prone to acquire additional neural abnormalities in Hendler, T., A causal model of post-traumatic stress disor-
terms of reduced ventromedial prefrontal cortex (vmPFC) der: Disentangling predisposed from acquired neural
volume, and its connectivity with the hippocampus (HC). abnormalities, Copyright 2013; with kind permission from
These acquired abnormalities influence negatively fear Elsevier. [Figure 4, Page 343]
Brain 551

transmitted to the amygdala by the hippocampus. hippocampal-insula coupling for Stroop words
The medial prefrontal cortex regulates fear expres- (pleasant or unpleasant).
sion by projecting to the multiple sites indicated. Sadeh et al. (2014) concluded that PTSD symp-
In fear extinction learning, increased medial pre- toms differentially moderate functional neural
frontal cortex firing to the basal nucleus stimulates coupling during emotional interference. The neu-
GABAergic intercalated region neurons, to inhibit ral connectivity patterns may be aberrant in differ-
fear response emanating from the central nucleus. ent ways and function as separable indices of
dysfunctional inhibitory control during affective
processing in PTSD. That overall PTSD severity
Networks moderated right amygdala-mPFC coupling is con-
sistent with other research that the right hemi-
Determining brain networks that underscore a sphere is associated with negative emotions or
behavior involves more than establishing the neu- withdrawal (Berntson, Norman, & Cacioppo,
rocircuitry involved. For example, in a prior 2011; Grimshaw & Carmel, 2014; Harmon-Jones,
chapter (Chap. 6), McNally et al. (2015) had 2003). In this regard, the authors remarked that
shown that PTSD symptomology can be mapped PTSD symptom severity can serve as an index of
for network characteristics, such as centrality. disrupted top-down mPFC regulation of the amyg-
Dysfunctional neural networks have been impli- dala. Generally, the results support the cognitive
cated in PTSD (Bluhm et al., 2009). control deficit of PTSD in relation to dysregulation
Sadeh, Spielberg, Warren, Miller, and Heller of amygdala by the mPFC.
(2014) examined neural connectivity during According to Daniels, Bluhm, and Lanius
emotional processing in 35 adults, a majority of (2013) the default mode network (DMN; Raichle
whom were women, who had experienced a trau- et al., 2001) appears to be a core network integrat-
matic event, but only a minority of whom (5) met ing input from other resting networks, such as the
the full criteria for PTSD. Emotional processing one for dorsal attention (Fox, Corbetta, Snyder,
was measured on an emotion word Stroop task Vincent, & Raichle, 2006) and the fronto-parietal
(pushing buttons on signal to the ink color of control one (Vincent, Kahn, Snyder, Raichle, &
words, the different emotional valence of which Buckner, 2008). The regions that it spans include
served as differential distractors). fMRI was used midline frontal and parietal structures, medial and
to assess aberrant neural connectivity. lateral temporal lobes, the lateral parietal region,
In their study, Sadeh et al. (2014) attempted to the inferior-parietal lobule, and the insula and
identify relationships between the major symp- thalamus. Moreover, the network is active not
tom clusters in PTSD and neural connectivity only just during resting state but also in autobio-
patterns toward understanding better the “etio- graphical memory recall, theory of mind tasks,
logical heterogeneity” of PTSD. The study found and prospection (Spreng, Mar, & Kim, 2009).
that PTSD symptom severity served to moderate According to Daniels et al. (2013), networks of
amygdala-mPFC area coupling (especially for this type might be involved in PTSD. The neural
the hyperarousal symptoms of PTSD), during the network approach to modeling is appealing for
processing of unpleasant distractor words on the PTSD because it involves networks in interactive
Stroop task (e.g., suicide, war, victim), compared dynamics, critical branching, inhibitory control
to pleasant (e.g., laughter) and neutral (e.g., car- related to volitional action, conflicting habitual
pet) words. Also, the moderation was correlated response, and override mechanisms that implicate
positively with participant functional impairment frontal regions, in particular. Also, it has been
(indexed by the DSM-IV Global Assessment of linked to specific processes involved in mental dis-
Functioning (GAF) scale) and with amygdala orders, and might be a locus in which psychotropic
reactivity. Another PTSD cluster showed related medications have their ameliorative effects. Finally,
results in aberrant neural connectivity—the research might establish that aspects of DMN activ-
severity of re-experiencing symptoms moderated ity constitute a risk factor in some individuals.
552 21 PTSD: Traumatic Causation

Comment immediate memory), delayed memory, complex


speed of information processing, attention/work-
A candidate neuroendophenotype for PTSD lies ing memory, and verbal memory, in particular, as
in the DMN, which integrates input from other well as executive function. These results are con-
resting networks, such as the ones for dorsal sistent with a frontal cortex/limbic system cir-
attention and fronto-parietal control. The neural cuitry dysregulation in PTSD. However, the
network approach has much to offer the search analysis could not differentiate whether the neu-
for PTSD endophenotypes because it is burgeon- rocognitive deficits related pre-existing factors or
ing and includes cross-region interactive dynam- post-trauma ones (to the disorder). Nor did most
ics. However, this simplicity is accompanied by a of them include symptom and performance valid-
neuronal mapping complexity that might be dif- ity testing to check the reliability of the results.
ficult to associate with specific genomics, unless Also, they rarely screened using urine toxicol-
regulatory and other top-down allelic variants are ogy/breathalyzer methods. Nevertheless, the
found in conjunction with their activity and also results support a view of PTSD as involving dys-
with neuronal plasticity due to environmental regulation of frontolimbic circuitry.
impacts at different epochs in development.

Neurogenesis
Neuroendocrine
Synapses
Nash et al. (2014) reviewed the research on mul-
tiple neuroendocrinological and related neuro- Nash et al. (2014) also described that, at the synap-
chemical factors in PTSD. They included: tic level, plasticity of excitatory glutamatergic
prefrontal cortex alpha 2c (PFC α 2c); alpha, nor- mechanisms have been implicated in fear learning,
adrenergic (noradrenergic α); dopamine type 1 and the mechanisms, particularly, are found in the
(DA1); serotonin type 2 receptor (5HT2R); dehy- amygdala and hippocampus. Glutamate receptors
droepiandrosterone, or its sulfated derivative are important in this regard (e.g., AMPA, alpha-
(DHEA (S)); cannabinoid type 1 receptor (CB1R); amino-3-hydroxy-5-methyl-4-isox-azolepropionic
alpha 2c noradrenergic receptor polymorphism acid; and NMDA, N-methyl-d-aspartate, and its
(α2cDel1322-325); gamma-aminobutyric acid subtypes, e.g., GluN2A, GluN2B, the metabotro-
(GABA); (allo)pregnanolone (ALLO); and neu- phic glutamate receptor mGluR). Reduced hippo-
ropeptide Y (NPY). campal polyamine concentrations (SPM, spermine;
Rasmusson and Shalev (2014) reviewed neu- SPD, spermidine) are the starting point of the
roendocrinological studies on the role in PTSD chain leading to reduced mGluR receptor activity
of each of catecholamines, serotonin, cortisol, and consequent generalized fear acquisition.
corticotrophin-releasing factor (CRF), NPY, Nash et al. (2014) also described that dissocia-
dehydroepiandrostorone, (allo)pregnalolone, and tion in the trauma response might reflect NMDA
immune factors. They concluded that the study of receptor hypofunction. The endocannabinoid
pathophysiological processes in PTSD could lead system also might be involved in the pathophysi-
to translational therapeutic interventions. ology in fear extinction of PTSD, and, as well,
BDNF in neuronal growth and differentiation, or
problems therein.
Neuropsychology Rasmusson and Shalev (2014) presented an
integrated view of neuroendocrinology, neuro-
Scott et al. (2015) undertook an analysis of the chemistry, and neuroimmunology of PTSD. Like
literature with respect to neurocognitive dysfunc- Nash et al. (2014), they addressed the comorbidi-
tion in PTSD, involving 60 studies. Their review ties and commonalities with other conditions,
found moderate effects for verbal learning (i.e., such as chronic pain and depression.
HPA Axis 553

Neurogenesis stressors. However, the genome is a complex sys-


tem itself, and in the field generally G × E interac-
Research is exploring PTSD endophenotypes not tions are complemented G × G interactions
only in brain circuitry, such as involving the hippo- (epistatis), G × E × D (development) ones, and
campus and prefrontal cortex, but also in the partic- other nuances (e.g., Young, 2011) that render any
ular neurogenetic processes associated with them. search for candidate endophenotypes at an inte-
The work could lead to targeted therapies for PTSD. grative genomics level problematic.
Kheirbek, Klemenhagen, Sahay, and Hen
(2012) reviewed the role of adult hippocampal
neurogenesis in relation to PTSD and panic dis- HPA Axis
order. In their model, pattern completion/separa-
tion is modulated by adult neurogenesis in the Research
hippocampus. Under stress, neurogenesis is
slowed, leading to poorer event discrimination According to Sherin and Nemeroff (2011), the
and overgeneralization, which has consequent HPA axis constitutes a primary locus of the body’s
emotional effects. The authors concluded that stress-response system. When exposed to stress,
PTSD therapy might target neurogenesis or the hypothalamus (its paraventricular nucleus,
young neurons in the hippocampus. PVN) secretes CRH, which then binds to anterior
Blum et al. (2012) focused their therapeutic pituitary cell receptors. This leads to production/
proposal for PTSD on natural dopaminergic acti- release of adrenocorticotropin (ACTH), which is
vation, which is related to the “reward” circuitry transported to the adrenal gland. In this cascade,
and underlying “reward” genes. Hypodominergic cortisol and other adrenal hormones are produced/
function in the brain’s reward circuitry is pro- released. Cortisol acts in pathway (activate the
moted by certain gene polymorphisms, so that locus coeruleus norepinephrine system, LCNE).
dopaminergic intervention affecting gene expres- Negative feedback results for both the hypothala-
sion and upregulation via messenger RNA might mus and the pituitary gland, which leads to a lack
counteract this deficiency. The authors advocated of moderation of the stress response. Normally, the
for a safe product, KB220Z, in this regard. hippocampus and PFC act to inhibit CRH neurons
in the PVN, whereas amygdalar and aminergic
brainstem neurons stimulate them. However, in
Comment PTSD, the negative feedback is compromised, pro-
ducing dysregulatory effects.
Adult hippocampal neurogenesis might be a In PTSD, it appears that the presence of low
proper neuroendophenotypic candidate in rela- cortisol levels at the time of the traumatic expo-
tion to PTSD. Neurons in this area are involved in sure might predict its development (Yehuda,
pattern separation that prepares representations McFarlane, & Shalev, 1998). The consequence
in the hippocampal dentate gyrus. Impairments would be to promote abnormal stress reactivity
or deficits in the process might lead to overgener- and perhaps abnormalities in general fear pro-
alization of fear memory, as found in PTSD. Other cessing. According to Sherin and Nemeroff
research has focused on natural dopaminergic (2011), the catecholamines also constitute poten-
activation, which is related to the “reward” cir- tial accurate endophenotypes of PTSD, as do
cuitry and underlying “reward” genes. The deter- other neurotransmitters/neurochemicals. The
mination of specific and multiple G × E changes associated with PTSD in these regards
interactions involving neurotransmitters that include increased dopamine levels, increased
function in PTSD, as well as others involving norepinephrine levels, decreased activity levels
neurocircuits and stress-related systems, augurs of the 5HTT gene involved in serotonin regula-
well for establishing valid PTSD endopheno- tion, decreased GABA activity (involved in inhi-
types that would help predict either PTSD devel- bition), increased glutamate (for activation), and
opment or resilience in reaction to traumatic decreased stress-buffering NPY.
554 21 PTSD: Traumatic Causation

Mehta and Binder (2012) concentrated espe- African Americans). Other research has examined
cially on the HPA axis in their model of G × E functional polymorphisms in genes related to sero-
vulnerability factors in PTSD. They presented a tonin (5-HTTLPR on the SLC6A4 gene). FKBP5
programming-reprogramming-disease model. might involve alleles producing cascade effects
In the model, genetic susceptibility factors, that facilitate PTSD reactions to trauma. However,
such as those related to FKBP5 polymorphisms, once more, I note that much empirical research is
especially interact with each other to influence needed on even more complex and integrative
HPA axis reactivity, along with early adversity models before candidate endophenotypes of PTSD
(e.g., child abuse) and epigenetic modifications. can be determined with rigor. Moreover, the ulti-
The confluence of these variables sets a base- mate model of PTSD needs to be a comprehensive
line, predisposing HPA axis (e.g., in GR super- biopsychosocial one, which seems implicated in
sensitivity) to later exposure to traumatic events the work of Mehta and Binder (2012), rather than
(of variable characteristics). In turn, this might one focused on genes as the starting point toward
lead to HPA axis disease developments, such as endophenotypic development in PTSD. The work
PTSD. Moreover, each person might exhibit of this research group is highlighted in the next
individual, distinct HPA axis dysregulation and section of the chapter, as well.
other pathophysiological disturbance in these
regards. Higher GR sensitivity/expression in
set-point at baseline could be a pre-existing Pathways
vulnerability, and one that is even set epigeneti-
cally in utero (e.g., Yehuda, 2002, 2009). Evidence
The authors concluded with more details on
their HPA axis reactivity (re)programming model Mehta et al. (2013) found evidence of distinct,
of disease. They emphasized that epigenetic modi- nonoverlapping, biological profiles in PTSD for
fications might serve as a mediator of G × E inter- patients who had experienced childhood mal-
actions in PTSD development. For example, treatment compared to non-abused patients.
FKBP5 might involve alleles conferring an “ultra- Controls had trauma history without any
short” negative feedback loop on GR activity, as PTSD. The specific biological measure involved
modified epigenetically by early stressors, leading epigenetic DNA methylation in peripheral
to slower recovery to set-point in cortisol level and immune-system related blood cells, and the gene
also more anxiety symptoms. Prolonged exposure expression in the CNS (central nervous system)
to glucocorticoids (cortisol) thereby would result, involved mostly pertained to the prefrontal cor-
which would lead to epigenetic changes in the tex. The results indicated that different trajecto-
FKBP5 locus, and possibly others related to ries and outcomes pathophysiologically might
GR-regulation, and so producing cascade effects accompany PTSD, depending on childhood
that facilitate PTSD reactions to trauma. abuse history. The gene-expression changes were
associated with and probably mediated by
changes in epigenetic processes, suggesting that
Comment the differential profiles for abuse and non-abuse
participants include differential epigenetic marks
Mehta and Binder (2012) have presented an in those with traumatic history, and these marks
important model of PTSD that integrates many of confer lifelong susceptibility to disease.
the factors mentioned in the field. They included Pietrzak,, Feder, Singh, et al. (2014) followed
HPA axis reactivity, G × E vulnerability, (re)pro- World Trade Center surviving responders over 8
gramming, polymorphisms, early adversity (e.g., years. Police relative to non-traditional respond-
child abuse), and epigenetic modifications. Their ers demonstrated four PTSD trajectories: resis-
research has shown that G × E interactions involv- tant/resilient, recovering, delayed onset, and
ing child abuse and four polymorphisms within chronic. Aside from these four profiles, the latter
the FKBP5 gene predict adult PTSD symptoms (in chronic group also showed a split in degree of
Allostasis 555

chronicity (moderate, severe) and a “subsyndro- Comment


mal increasing” profile. The groups varied in per-
centages within each pathway, as well. Further, Research is showing that different trajectories and
predictors of PTSD included: prior psychiatric outcomes pathophysiologically might accompany
history; Hispanic ethnicity; trauma exposure PTSD, depending on childhood abuse history, and
severity; and trauma incident medical conditions. the research is also revealing that epigenetic marks
Protective factors included education and support due to traumatic history appear involved, serving to
(family, work). The authors concluded that the augment disease susceptibility. Trajectories include
limited amount of PTSD trajectories that they not only a resilience course but also different degrees
found is consistent with other research (Bonanno of PTSD severity, with differential predictors
et al., 2012; Bowler et al., 2010; Hobfoll, involved. The research is also focusing on differen-
Mancini, Hall, Canetti, & Bonanno, 2011). tial neural networks in those who express PTSD to
Gerson and Rappaport (2013) presented evi- traumatic stressors relative to those who do not. For
dence for critical developmental windows for example, Gong et al. (2014) found a neural network
impact of traumatic stress at the neurobiological in such cases among earthquake survivors involving
level. They referred to an interaction of risk/resil- prefrontal, temporal, parietal, and occipital grey
ience, vulnerability, and trauma factors in matter regions as well as subcortical structure.
childhood affecting developmental trajectory. Pathway analysis might prove more effective in
From infancy onward, moments of “burst” of establishing individual differences in PTSD devel-
myelination, synapse formation, pruning, and opment, relative to the static approach of using
neural networking are susceptible to disruption DSM-5 symptom criteria. Although neural net-
by stress hormones. For example, cortisol can works represent the best central candidate of PTSD
lead to suppression of glial cell division, den- endophenotype, much work remains to establish
dritic branching, synaptogenesis, and neuronal which and how many networks are involved, and
loss. The effects are compounded by corollary their variations over groups, such as differences
epigenesis (e.g., Heim, Shugart, Craighead, & across ages, in the sexes, over cultures and racial
Nemeroff, 2010). Brain regions affected might groupings, in SES (socioeconomic status), and so
include multiple ones involved in stress and on. Only when the massive amount of research is
trauma mediation (e.g., hippocampus, amygdala, undertaken at this level can we begin to query how
cerebral cortex). Each is related to different to address neuronal network profile and trajectory
symptoms in trauma outcomes. Vulnerabilities differences in individual cases. To carry that research
include genetic differences (Jovanovic & Ressler, enterprise one step further into the realm of foren-
2010). Sex and age differences play a role in the sics, in which the candidate endophenotype so
vulnerabilities. Finally, the lasting effects of derived can add incremental validity to other mea-
these neurobiological impacts early in life include sures in assessments, or even replace (some of)
later physical health effects (Yehuda, 2002). them, remains a daunting and long-term task.
Gong et al. (2014) used structural magnetic
resonance imaging (sMRI) in earthquake trauma
survivors who were with and without PTSD to Allostasis
determine whether the groups could be distin-
guished at a case level. They found that those Research
expressing PTSD were discriminated by a highly
spatially-distributed neural network involving pre- Zhou et al. (2014) found that PTSD is associated
frontal, temporal, parietal, and occipital grey mat- with dysregulation in microribonucleic acid (miR)
ter regions as well as subcortical structure. The expression. The PTSD was expressed in military
evidence suggested that post-event neuroplastic veterans; also, healthy controls were tested. The
changes were involved, rather than pre-existing PTSD patients had increased pro-inflammatory
differences, in causing the group differences, mak- Th1 and Th17 cytokine cells and decreased regu-
ing the technique potentially useful forensically. latory T cells (Tregs). Pathway analysis suggested
556 21 PTSD: Traumatic Causation

immunological changes. The authors concluded emerge in a self-organized and inflationary fash-
that the results may help lead to identification of ion relative to any stressor, including in PTSD,
biomarkers of PTSD. depending on prior vulnerabilities and history, as
Juster et al. (2011) expanded the allostatic well as on the system organization (and its stabil-
load model (AL; McEwen & Stellar, 1993; ity and disequilibrium forces at play) at the time
Sterling & Eyer, 1988) to psychopathology of the experiencing of a traumatic stressor. The
across the lifespan. According to the allostatic dynamical nature in the instigation, exacerbation,
load model, the three factors that are involved in and maintenance of PTSD in this regard needs to
stress (biopsychosocial) work in synergy. be considered in the task of searching for optimal
The antecedents of AL model include: (a) endophenotypic candidates.
early adversity; (b) genetic factors; (c) epigenetic
factors; (d) environmental toxins; and (e) interac-
tions among biological and sociocultural factors. Five Factor Model
Together, these factors contribute probabilisti-
cally to health outcomes (not deterministically; Research
Cicchetti & Toth, 2009). Disease develops in
allostatic overload, which takes place after sys- The research by Pietrzak, Galea et al. (2013) is
tem over-activation and also nonlinear dynamical indicating new directions in understanding the
interactive imbalances, leading to the breaking PTSD endophenotype. Pietrzak, Galea et al.
point (McEwen, 1998). (2013) examined 149 participants in a represen-
Juster et al. (2011) explicated in depth how tative sample of adults who had experienced
allostatic overload contributes to developmental Hurricane Ike in 2008. The participants were
and long-term psychopathology. The model was given an interview 2–5 months after the disaster.
developed for populations but works for the indi- They were divided into low exposure and high
vidual level, too. Similarly, I have maintained exposure groups according to a summary index
that chronic stress is the factor that is common to based on nine questions; as well, PTSD was
psychological injuries (Young, 2008a) and that assessed with the PCL (The PTSD Checklist;
somatization is a multifactorial process that can Weathers, Litz, Herman, Huska, & Keane, 1993)
begin early in life (Young, 2008b). Ganzel and and with additional questions. The PCL is keyed
Morris (2011) also extended the AL model to to the DSM-IV-TR symptom list. The 17 items of
development. For example, the changes in any the list as measured on the PCL were subject to
one period reflect particular stress responses and Confirmatory Factor Analysis (CFA).
allostatic processes unique to the period and The results supported Elhai et al.’s (2011)
stressors involved, leading to distinct long-term five-factor model. In this model, relative to the
consequences for health for the associated peri- DSM-IV-TR, avoidance is split into symptoms
ods, stressors, and contexts implicated. for avoidance and numbing, and hyperarousal is
split into symptoms of dysphoric arousal and
anxious arousal. The results showed good-to-
Comment excellent reliability for each of the five clusters in
terms of Cronbach’s alpha (α = 0.96).
Allostatic overload refers to the overtaxing of the Pietrzak, Galea et al. (2013) related the
“wear and tear” process experienced by the 5-HTTLPR genotype to their results. They found
organism, and it is associated with disease in con- that respondents having the low-expression allele
ditions of chronic stress and the dysregulation of variant (at least one short, s, allele) of the
the stress system. The allostatic overload system 5-HTTLPR polymorphism, relative to those
is a developmental and nonlinear one, in which homozygous for the long (l) allele, reported
pathophysiological processes related to disease greater PTSD severity, but only if they had been
reflect cumulative system activity but not in a highly exposed to the hurricane. Also, they
one-to-one reductionistic manner. Disease can reported a higher incidence of screening for
Chapter Conclusions 557

PTSD. In terms of the five-factor structure for among World Trade Center 9/11 responders in a
PTSD, this 5-HTTLPR s allele genotype × trauma longitudinal study spanning 8 years. They used
exposure interaction was significant for two of CFA and auto-regressive cross-lagged panel
the five clusters—anxious arousal and regressions to show that neither the DSM-IV
re-experiencing. three-dimensional structure (avoidance, hyper-
The 5-HTTLPR s allele has been associated arousal, re-experiencing) nor the DSM-5 four-
with greater amygdala hyperactivity and reduced dimensional structure (avoidance split into
coupling of the amygdala-cingulate neurocir- numbing, as well, aside from other symptoms
cuitry (respectively, Hariri et al., 2002; Pezawas added), nor another commonly found four-factor
et al., 2005). The allele is also associated with model (some hypervigilance symptoms added to
attentional vigilance toward negatively-valenced the numbing ones, with the factor called dyspho-
stimuli and difficulty in disengaging from nega- ria; Simms, Watson, & Doebbeling, 2002) fit the
tive stimuli (respectively, Pergamin-Hight, dimensional structure of PTSD symptoms as
Bakermans-Kranenburg, van IJzendoorn, & Bar- effectively as a five-factor model (Elhai &
Haim, 2012; Beevers, Wells, Ellis, & McGeary, Palmieri, 2011). In the latter, hyperarousal is split
2009). These findings help explain the psycho- into two components—anxious arousal (e.g.,
logical mechanisms behind the mentioned exaggerated startle) and dysphoric arousal (e.g.,
allele × trauma interaction. Finally, Pietrzak, sleep disturbance, concentration difficulties).
Galea et al. (2013) concluded that the nature of The authors concluded that the former type of
results support the validity of the five-factor arousal appears to drive, over time, re-
model of PTSD (in particular, the separation of experiencing, and the latter appears to drive emo-
anxious arousal and dysphoric arousal.) [For tional numbing symptoms.
another genetic study in relation to PTSD by the
Pietrzak research group, see Pietrzak, Henry,
Southwick, Krystal, & Neumeister, 2013.] Comment
Horn, Pietrzak, Corsi-Travali, and Neumeister
(2014) noted that there has been a dozen CFA The research on a new five-factor model of PTSD
studies on a broad range of sample types that constitutes one of the most important develop-
have confirmed the five-factor model as better fit- ments toward understanding PTSD and its
ting compared to the DSM-IV-TR and alternative (neuro)endophenotypic intermediaries in the
four-factor models (Armour, Carragher, & Elhai, pathways to its development. Young, Lareau, and
2013; Pietrzak, Tsai, Harpaz-Rotem, Whealin, & Pierre (2014) provided a table summarizing how
Southwick, 2012). the 17 PTSD symptoms in the DSM-IV-TR are
Horn et al. (2014) conducted a study linking split into the five factors; see Table 21.2.
morning plasma cortisol levels to severity of The value of the five-factor PTSD model for
emotional numbing in this five-factor model. better understanding the pathway from polygenic
They studied drug-free civilian adults having contributions to phenotypic expression and the
PTSD and the controls of trauma-exposed adults individual differences therein in PTSD also is
and non-trauma-exposed healthy individuals. indicated by its efforts to determine which one of
Horn et al. (2014) concluded that basal corti- the five factors stands out as a core one in PTSD,
sol does not constitute a biomarker of PTSD in but the answers to the question vary.
the sense that it did not distinguish trauma survi-
vors with and without PTSD. Nevertheless, its
association with emotional numbing suggests Chapter Conclusions
that it mediates a key symptom cluster among the
five in the new five-factor model of PTSD—that This chapter on PTSD undertakes a comprehen-
of emotional numbing/restricted affect. sive review of the recent literature in the areas
Pietrzak, Feder, Schechter, et al. (2014) inves- of endophenotypes, neurogenetics, epigenetics,
tigated the symptom cluster structure in PTSD neural networks, HPA axis, neuronal networks,
558 21 PTSD: Traumatic Causation

Table 21.2 Item mappings of DSM-IV-TR and structural models of PTSD symptom clusters
Item mappings
Elhai et al. Pietrzak, Galea et al. (2013)
DSM-IV-TR PTSD symptom DSM-IV-TR (2011) Factor loadings
B1. Intrusive thoughts of trauma R R .849
B2. Recurrent dreams of trauma R R .718
B3. Flashbacks R R .693
B4. Emotional reactivity to trauma cues R R .803
B5. Physiological reactivity to trauma cues R R .844
C1. Avoiding thoughts of trauma A A .867
C2. Avoiding reminders of trauma A A .917
C3. Inability to recall aspects of trauma A N .674
C4. Loss of interest A N .782
C5. Detachment A N .824
C6. Restricted affect A N .810
C7. Sense of foreshortened future A N .719
D1. Sleep disturbance H DA .853
D2. Irritability H DA .745
D3. Difficulty concentrating H DA .854
D4. Hypervigilance H AA .825
D5. Exaggerated startle response H AA .833
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G., Lareau, C., & Pierre, B. (2014). One quintillion
ways to have PTSD comorbidity: Recommendations for the disordered DSM-5. Psychological Injury and Law, 7, 61–74; with
kind permission from Springer Science + Business Media B. V. [Table 1, Page 67]

pathways, the five-factor and related PTSD American Psychiatric Association. (2000). Diagnostic
models (the DSM-5 moved from a three-factor and statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM-
IV-TR (4th ed., text rev.). Washington, DC: Author.
model to a four-factor model), and allostasis; Amstadter, A. B., Koenen, K. C., Ruggiero, K. J., Acierno,
then, it returns to the topic of endophenotypes. R., Galea, S., Kilpatrick, D. G., et al. (2009). Variant in
Neuronal networks constitute one integrating RGS2 moderates posttraumatic stress symptoms fol-
area that could help in arriving at an appropriate lowing potentially traumatic event exposure. Journal
of Anxiety Disorders, 23, 369–373.
model of PTSD endophenotype. Pathway analy- Amstadter, A. B., Sumner, J. A., Acierno, R., Ruggiero,
sis provides a rich field for discerning individual K. J., Koenen, K. C., Kilpatrick, D. G., et al. (2013).
differences in PTSD development, more so than Support for association of RORA variant and post
the static approach of using DSM-5 symptom cri- traumatic stress symptoms in a population-based study
of hurricane exposed adults. Molecular Psychiatry, 18,
teria lists. Finally, about implications for the 1148–1149.
DSM-5, for practice, and for court—it would be Armour, C., Carragher, N., & Elhai, J. D. (2013). Assessing
premature to seek individual biomarkers of the fit of the dysphoric arousal model across two
PTSD, given the current state of knowledge in nationally representative epidemiological surveys: The
Australian NSMHWB and the United States NESARC.
the field, even if it is burgeoning. Journal of Anxiety Disorders, 27, 109–115.
Baker, D. G., Nievergelt, C. M., & O’Connor, D. T. (2012).
Biomarkers of PTSD: Neuropeptides and immune sig-
naling. Neuropharmacology, 62, 663–673.
References Beevers, C. G., Wells, T. T., Ellis, A. J., & McGeary, J. E.
(2009). Association of the serotonin transporter gene
Admon, R., Milad, M. R., & Hendler, T. (2013). A causal promoter region (5-HTTLPR) polymorphism with
model of post-traumatic stress disorder: Disentangling biased attention for emotional stimuli. Journal of
predisposed from acquired neural abnormalities. Abnormal Psychology, 118, 670–681.
Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 17, 337–347. Berntsen, D., & Rubin, D. C. (2014). Involuntary memo-
American Psychiatric Association. (1994). Diagnostic ries and dissociative amnesia: Assessing key assump-
and statistical manual of mental disorders (4th ed.). tions in posttraumatic stress disorder research. Clinical
Washington, DC: Author. Psychological Science, 2, 174–186.
References 559

Berntson, G. G., Norman, G. J., & Cacioppo, J. T. (2011). Brewin, C. R., Gregory, J. D., Lipton, M., & Burgess, N.
Laterality and evaluation bivalence: A neuroevolution- (2010). Intrusive images in psychological disorders:
ary perspective. Emotion Review, 3, 344–346. Characteristics, neural mechanisms, and treatment
Binder, E. B., Bradley, R. G., Liu, W., Epstein, M. P., implications. Psychological Review, 117, 210–232.
Deveau, T. C., Mercer, K. B., et al. (2008). Association Catarino, A., Küpper, C. S., Werner-Seidler, A., Dalgleish,
of FKBP5 polymorphisms and childhood abuse with T., & Anderson, M. C. (2015). Failing to forget:
risk of posttraumatic stress disorder symptoms in Inhibitory-control deficits compromise memory suppres-
adults. Journal of the American Medical Association, sion in posttraumatic stress disorder. Psychological
299, 1291–1305. Science, 26, 604–616.
Blake, D. D., Weathers, F. W., Nagy, L. M., Kaloupek, Chang, S.-C., Koenen, K. C., Galea, S., Aiello, A. E.,
D. G., Gusman, F. D., Charney, D. S., et al. (1995). Soliven, R., Wildman, D. E., et al. (2012). Molecular
The development of a clinician-administered PTSD variation at the SLC6A3 locus predicts lifetime risk of
scale. Journal of Traumatic Stress, 8, 75–90. PTSD in the Detroit Neighborhood Health Study.
Bluhm, R. L., Williamson, P. C., Osuch, E. A., Frewen, PLoS One, 7, e39184.
P. A., Stevens, T. K., Boksman, K., et al. (2009). Cicchetti, D., & Toth, S. L. (2009). The past achievements
Alterations in default network connectivity in post- and future promises of developmental psychopathol-
traumatic stress disorder related to early-life trauma. ogy: The coming of age of a discipline. Journal of
Journal of Psychiatry & Neuroscience, 34, 187–194. Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 50, 16–25.
Blum, K., Giordano, J., Oscar-Berman, M., Bowirrat, A., Cornelis, M. C., Nugent, N. R., Amstadter, A. B., &
Simpatico, T., & Barh, D. (2012). Diagnosis and heal- Koenen, K. C. (2010). Genetics of post-traumatic
ing in veterans suspected of suffering from post- stress disorder: Review and recommendations for
traumatic stress disorder (PTSD) using reward gene genome-wide association studies. Current Psychiatry
testing and reward circuitry natural dopaminergic acti- Reports, 12, 313–326.
vation. Journal of Genetic Syndrome & Gene Therapy, Daniels, J. K., Bluhm, R. L., & Lanius, R. A. (2013).
3, 1000116. doi:10.4172/2157-7412.1000116. Intrinsic network abnormalities in posttraumatic stress
Bonanno, G. A., Mancini, A. D., Horton, J. L., Powell, disorder: Research directions for the next decade.
T. M., Leardmann, C. A., Boyko, E. J., et al. (2012). Psychological Trauma: Theory, Research, Practice,
Trajectories of trauma symptoms and resilience in and Policy, 5, 142–148.
deployed U.S. military service members: Perspective de Quervain, D. J.-F., Kolassa, I.-T., Ertl, V., Onyut, P. L.,
cohort study. British Journal of Psychiatry, 200, Neuner, F., Elbert, T., et al. (2007). A deletion variant
317–323. of the alpha2b-adrenoceptor is related to emotional
Boscarino, J., Erlich, P. M., Hoffman, S. N., & Zhang, X. memory in Europeans and Africans. Nature
(2012). Higher FKBP5, COMT, CHRNA5, and Neuroscience, 10, 1137–1139.
CRHR1 allele burdens are associated with PTSD and Dias, B. G., & Ressler, K. J. (2013). PACAP and the PACI
interact with trauma exposure: Implications for neuro- receptor in post-traumatic stress disorder.
psychiatric research and treatment. Neuropsychiatric Neuropsychopharmacology, 38, 245–246.
Disease and Treatment, 8, 131–139. Dohrenwend, B. P., Turner, J. B., Turse, N. A., Adams,
Boulle, F., Van Den Hove, D. L., Jakob, S. B., Rutten, B. G., Koenen, K. C., & Marshall, R. (2006). The psy-
B. P., Hamon, M., Van Os, J., et al. (2012). Epigenetic chological risks of Vietnam for U.S. veterans: A revisit
regulation of the BDNF gene: Implications for psy- with new data and methods. Science, 313, 979–982.
chiatric disorders. Molecular Psychiatry, 17, Dudley, K. J., Li, X., Kobor, M. S., Kippin, T. E., & Bredy,
584–596. T. W. (2011). Epigenetic mechanisms mediating vul-
Bowler, R. M., Han, H., Gocheva, V., Nakagawa, S., nerability and resilience to psychiatric disorders.
Alper, H., DiGrande, L., et al. (2010). Gender differ- Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Review, 35,
ences in probable posttraumatic stress disorder among 1544–1551.
police responders to the 2001 World Trade Center ter- Ehlers, A., & Clark, D. M. (2000). A cognitive model of
rorist attack. American Journal of Industrial Medicine, posttraumatic stress disorder. Behaviour Research and
53, 1186–1196. Therapy, 38, 319–345.
Bramsen, I., Dirkzwager, A. J., & van der Ploeg, H. M. Ehring, T., Ehlers, A., & Glucksman, E. (2008). Do cogni-
(2000). Predeployment personality traits and exposure tive models help in predicting the severity of posttrau-
to trauma as predictor of posttraumatic stress symp- matic stress disorder, phobia, and depression after
toms: A prospective study of former peacekeepers. motor vehicle accidents?: A prospective longitudinal
American Journal of Psychiatry, 157, 1115–1119. study. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology,
Brewin, C. R. (2008). What is it that a neurobiological 76, 219–230.
model of PTSD must explain? Progress in Brain Elhai, J. D., Biehn, T. L., Armour, C., Klopper, J. J.,
Research, 167, 217–228. Frueh, B. C., & Palmieri, P. A. (2011). Evidence for a
Brewin, C. R. (2011). The nature and significance of unique PTSD construct represented by PTSD’s D1-D3
memory disturbance in posttraumatic stress disorder. symptoms. Journal of Anxiety Disorders, 25,
Annual Review of Clinical Psychology, 7, 203–227. 340–345.
560 21 PTSD: Traumatic Causation

Elhai, J. D., & Palmieri, P. A. (2011). The factor structure Harmon-Jones, E. (2003). Clarifying the emotive func-
of posttraumatic stress disorder: A literature update, tions of asymmetrical frontal cortical activity.
critique of methodology, and agenda for future Psychophysiology, 40, 838–848.
research. Journal of Anxiety Disorders, 25, 849–854. Heim, C., Shugart, M., Craighead, W. E., & Nemeroff,
Fox, M. D., Corbetta, M., Snyder, A. Z., Vincent, J. L., & C. B. (2010). Neurobiological and psychiatric conse-
Raichle, M. E. (2006). Spontaneous neuronal activity quences of child abuse and neglect. Developmental
distinguishes human dorsal and ventral attention Psychobiology, 52, 671–690.
systems. The National Academy of Sciences, 103, Hobfoll, S. E., Mancini, A. D., Hall, B. J., Canetti, D., &
10046–10051. Bonanno, G. A. (2011). The limits of resilience: Distress
Friedman, M. J., & Resick, P. A. (2014). DSM-5 criteria following chronic political violence among Palestinians.
for PTSD. In M. J. Friedman, T. M. Keane, & P. A. Social Science and Medicine, 72, 1400–1408.
Resick (Eds.), Handbook of PTSD: Science and prac- Horn, C. A. C., Pietrzak, R. H., Corsi-Travali, S., &
tice (2nd ed., pp. 21–37). New York: Guilford Press. Neumeister, A. (2014). Linking plasma cortisol levels to
Friedman, M. J., Resick, P. A., & Keane, T. M. (2014). phenotypic heterogeneity of posttraumatic stress symp-
PTSD from DSM-III to DSM-5: Progress and chal- tomatology. Psychoneuroendocrinology, 39, 88–93.
lenges. In M. J. Friedman, T. M. Keane, & P. A. Resick Johnson, L. R., McGuire, J., Lazarus, R., & Palmer, A. A.
(Eds.), Handbook of PTSD: Science and practice (2nd (2012). Pavlovian fear memory circuits and phenotype
ed., pp. 3–20). New York: Guilford Press. models of PTSD. Neuropharmacology, 62, 638–646.
Ganzel, B. L., & Morris, P. A. (2011). Allostasis and the Jovanovic, T., & Ressler, K. J. (2010). How the neurocir-
developing human brain: Explicit consideration of cuitry and genetics of fear inhibition may inform our
implicit models. Development and Psychopathology, understanding of PTSD. American Journal of
23, 955–974. Psychiatry, 167, 648–662.
Gerson, R., & Rappaport, N. (2013). Traumatic stress and Juster, R.-P., Bizik, G., Picard, M., Arsenault-Lapierre,
posttraumatic stress disorders in youth: Recent research G., Sindi, S., Trepanier, L., et al. (2011). A transdisci-
findings on clinical impact, assessment, and treatment. plinary perspective of chronic stress in relation to psy-
Journal of Adolescent Health, 52, 137–143. chopathology throughout life span development.
Gillihan, S. J., Cahill, S. P., & Foa, E. B. (2014). Development and Psychopathology, 23, 725–776.
Psychological theories of PTSD. In M. J. Friedman, Karsten, C. A., & Baram, T. Z. (2013). How does a neuron
T. M. Keane, & P. A. Resick (Eds.), Handbook of “know” to modulate its epigenetic machinery in response
PTSD: Science and practice (2nd ed., pp. 166–184). to early-life environment/experience? Frontiers in
New York: Guilford Press. Psychiatry, 4, 89. doi:10.3389/fpsyt.2013.00089.
Gong, Q., Li, L., Tognin, S., Wu, Q., Pettersson-Yeo, W., Kasai, K., Yamasue, H., Gilbertson, M. W., Shenton,
Lui, S., et al. (2014). Using structural neuroanatomy to M. E., Rauch, S. L., & Pitman, R. K. (2008). Evidence
identify trauma survivors with and without post- for acquired pregenual anterior cingulate gray matter
traumatic stress disorder at the individual level. loss from a twin study of combat-related posttraumatic
Psychological Medicine, 44, 195–203. stress disorder. Biological Psychiatry, 63, 550–556.
Gottesman, I. I., & Gould, T. D. (2003). The endopheno- Keane, T. M., & Barlow, D. H. (2002). Posttraumatic
type concept in psychiatry: Etymology and strategic stress disorder. In D. H. Barlow (Ed.), Anxiety and its
intentions. American Journal of Psychiatry, 160, disorders (2nd ed., pp. 418–453). New York: Guilford
636–645. Press.
Gottesman, I. I., & Shields, J. (1972). Schizophrenia and Kessler, R. C., Sonnega, A., Bromet, E., Hughes, M., &
genetics: A twin study vantage point. New York: Nelson, C. B. (1995). Posttraumatic stress disorder in
Academic. the National Comorbidity Survey. Archives of General
Gottesman, I. I., & Shields, J. (1973). Genetic theorizing and Psychiatry, 52, 1048–1060.
schizophrenia. British Journal of Psychiatry, 122, 15–30. Kheirbek, M. A., Klemenhagen, C., Sahay, A., & Hen, R.
Grabe, H. J., Spitzer, C., Schwahn, C., Marcinek, A., (2012). Neurogenesis and generalization: A new
Frahnow, A., Barnow, S., et al. (2009). Serotonin approach to stratify and treat anxiety disorders. Nature
transporter gene (SLC6A4) promoter polymorphisms Neuroscience, 15, 1613–1620.
and the susceptibility to posttraumatic stress disorder Kilpatrick, D. G., Koenen, K. C., Ruggiero, K. J., Acierno,
in general population. American Journal of Psychiatry, R., Galea, S., Resnick, H. S., et al. (2007). The sero-
166, 926–933. tonin transporter genotype and social support and
Grimshaw, G. M., & Carmel, D. (2014). An asymmetric moderation of posttraumatic stress disorder and
inhibition model of hemispheric differences in emo- depression in hurricane-exposed adults. American
tional processing. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 489. Journal of Psychiatry, 164, 1693–1699.
doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00489. Klengel, T., Mehta, D., Anacker, C., Rex-Haffner, M.,
Hariri, A. R., Mattay, V. S., Tessitore, A., Kolachana, B., Pruessner, J. C., Pariante, C. M., et al. (2013). Allele-
Fera, F., Goldman, D., et al. (2002). Serotonin trans- specific FKBP5 DNA demethylation mediates gene-
porter genetic variation and the response of the human childhood trauma interactions. Nature Neuroscience,
amygdala. Science, 297, 400–403. 16, 33–44.
References 561

Koenen, K. C., Aiello, A. E., Bakshis, E., Amstadter, Lonsdorf, T. B., Weike, A. I., Nikamo, P., Schalling, M.,
A. B., Ruggiero, K. J., Acierno, R., et al. (2009). Hamm, A. O., & Ohman, A. (2009). Genetic gating of
Modification of the association between serotonin human fear learning and extinction: Possible implica-
transporter genotype and risk of posttraumatic stress tions for gene-environment interaction in anxiety dis-
disorder in adults by county-level social environment. order. Psychological Science, 20, 198–206.
American Journal of Epidemiology, 169, 704–711. Maddox, S. A., Schafe, G. E., & Ressler, K. J. (2013).
Koenen, K. C., Fu, Q. J., Ertel, K., Lyons, M. J., Eisen, Exploring epigenetic regulation of fear memory and
S. A., True, W., et al. (2008). Common genetic liabil- biomarkers associated with post-traumatic stress dis-
ity to major depression and posttraumatic stress disor- order. Frontiers in Psychiatry, 4, 62. doi:10.3389/
der in men. Journal of Affective Disorders, 105, fpsyt.2013.00062.
109–115. Maercker, A., Brewin, C. R., Bryant, R. A., Cloitre, M.,
Koenen, K. C., Guffanti, G., Yan, L., Haloossim, M., Reed, G. M., van Ommeren, M., et al. (2013).
Uddin, M., Nugent, N. R., et al. (2014). Genetics of Proposals for mental disorders specifically associated
PTSD. In M. J. Friedman, T. M. Keane, & P. A. Resick with stress in the International Classification of
(Eds.), Handbook of PTSD: Science and practice (2nd Diseases-11. The Lancet, 381, 1683–1685.
ed., pp. 300–312). New York: Guilford Press. Mahan, A. L., & Ressler, K. J. (2012). Fear conditioning,
Koenen, K. C., Uddin, M., Chang, S.-C., Aiello, A. E., synaptic plasticity and the amygdala: Implications for
Wildman, D. E., Goldmann, E., et al. (2011). SLC6A4 posttraumatic stress disorder. Trends in Neurosciences,
methylation modifies the effect of the number of trau- 35, 24–35.
matic events on risk for posttraumatic stress disorder. McEwen, B. S. (1998). Stress, adaptation, and disease:
Depression and Anxiety, 28, 639–647. Allostasis and allostatic load. Annals of the New York
Kolassa, I.-T., & Elbert, T. (2007). Structural and func- Academy of Sciences, 840, 33–44.
tional neuroplasticity in relation to traumatic stress. McEwen, B. S., & Stellar, E. (1993). Stress and the indi-
Current Directions in Psychological Science, 16, vidual. Mechanisms leading to disease. Archives of
321–325. Internal Medicine, 153, 2093–2101.
Kolassa, I.-T., Ertl, V., Eckart, C., Glöckner, F., Kolassa, McGowan, P. O. (2013). Epigenomic mechanisms of
S., Papassotiropoulos, A., et al. (2010). Association early adversity and HPA dysfunction: Considerations
study of trauma load and SLC6A4 promoter polymor- for PTSD research. Frontiers in Psychiatry, 4, 110.
phism in posttraumatic stress disorder: Evidence from doi:10.3389/fpsyt.2013.00110.
survivors of the Rwandan genocide. Journal of McGowan, P. O., Sasaki, A., D’Alessio, A. C., Dymov, S.,
Clinical Psychiatry, 71, 543–547. Labonté, B., Szyf, M., et al. (2009). Epigenetic regula-
Kolassa, I.-T., Illek, S., Wilker, S., Karabatsiakis, A., & tion of the glucocorticoid receptor in human brain
Elbert, T. (2015). Neurobiological findings in post- associates with childhood abuse. Nature Neuroscience,
traumatic stress disorder. In U. Schnyder & M. Cloitre 12, 342–348.
(Eds.), Evidence based treatments for trauma-related McNally, R. J., Robinaugh, D. J., Wu, G. W. Y., Wang, L.,
psychological disorders: A practical guide for clini- Deserno, M. K., & Borsboom, D. (2015). Mental dis-
cians (pp. 63–86). New York: Springer orders as causal systems: A network approach to post-
Science + Business Media. traumatic stress disorder. Clinical Psychological
Kolassa, I.-T., Kolassa, S., Ertl, V., Papassotiropoulos, A., Science, 3, 836–849.
& de Quervain, D. J. (2010). The risk of posttraumatic Meaney, M. J., & Szyf, M. (2005). Maternal care as a
stress disorder after trauma depends on traumatic load model for experience-dependent chromatin plasticity?
and the catechol-o-methyltransferase Val(158)Met Trends in Neurosciences, 28, 456–463.
polymorphism. Biological Psychiatry, 67, 304–308. Mehta, D., & Binder, E. B. (2012). Gene × environment
Kubany, E. S., Haynes, S. N., Leisen, M. B., Owens, J. A., vulnerability factors for PTSD: The HPA-axis.
Kaplan, A. S., Watson, S. B., et al. (2000). Development Neuropharmacology, 62, 654–662.
and preliminary validation of a brief broad-spectrum Mehta, D., Gonik, M., Klengel, T., Rex-Haffner, M.,
measure of traumatic exposure: The Traumatic Life Menke, A., Rubel, J., et al. (2011). Using polymor-
Events Questionnaire. Psychological Assessment, 12, phisms in FKBP5 to define biologically distinct sub-
210–224. types of posttraumatic stress disorder: Evidence from
Labonte, B., Yerko, V., Gross, J., Mechawar, N., Meaney, endocrine and gene expression studies. Archives of
M. J., Szyf, M., et al. (2012). Differential glucocorti- General Psychiatry, 68, 901–910.
coid receptor exon 1(B), 1(C), and 1 (H) expression Mehta, D., Klengel, T., Conneely, K. N., Smith, A. K.,
and methylation in suicide completers with a history Altmann, A., Pace, T. W., et al. (2013). Childhood
of childhood abuse. Biological Psychiatry, 72, maltreatment is associated with distinct genomic and
41–48. epigenetic profiles in posttraumatic stress disorder.
Logue, M. W., Baldwin, C., Guffanti, G., Melista, E., Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences,
Wolf, E. J., Reardon, A. F., et al. (2012). A genome- USA, 110, 8302–8307.
wide association study of post-traumatic stress disor- Mercer, K. B., Orchutt, H. K., Quinn, J. F., Fitzgerald,
der identifies the retinoid-related orphan reception C. A., Conneely, K. N., Barfield, R. T., et al. (2012).
alpha (RORA) gene as a significant risk locus. Acute and posttraumatic stress symptoms in a pro-
Molecular Psychiatry, 18, 937–942. spective gene × environment study of a university
562 21 PTSD: Traumatic Causation

campus shooting. Archives of General Psychiatry, 69, Pezawas, L., Meyer-Lidenberg, A., Drabant, E. M.,
89–97. Verchinski, B. A., Munoz, K. E., Kolachana, B. S.,
Murrough, J. W., Huang, Y., Hu, J., Henry, S., Williams, et al. (2005). 5-HTTLPR polymorphism impacts
W., Gallezot, J.-D., et al. (2011). Reduced amygdala human cingulate-amygdala interactions: A genetic
serotonin transporter binding in posttraumatic stress susceptibility mechanism for depression. Natural
disorder. Biological Psychiatry, 70, 1033–1038. Neuroscience, 8, 828–834.
Nadel, L., Hupbach, A., Gomez, R., & Newman-Smith, Pietrzak, R. H., Feder, A., Schechter, C. B., Singh, R.,
K. (2012). Memory formation, consolidation and Cancelmo, L., Bromet, E. J., et al. (2014). Dimensional
transformation. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral structure and course of post-traumatic stress symp-
Reviews, 36, 1640–1645. tomatology in World Trade Center responders.
Naim, R., Wald, I., Lior, A., Pine, D. S., Fox, N. A., Psychological Medicine, 44, 2085–2098.
Sheppes, G., et al. (2014). Perturbed threat monitoring Pietrzak, R. H., Feder, A., Singh, R., Schechter, C. B.,
following a traumatic event predicts risk for post- Bromet, E. J., Katz, C. L., et al. (2014). Trajectories of
traumatic stress disorder. Psychological Medicine, 44, PTSD risk and resilience in World Trade Center
2077–2084. responders: An 8-year prospective cohort study.
Nash, M., Galatzer-Levy, I., Krystal, J. H., Duman, R., & Psychological Medicine, 44, 205–219.
Neumeister, A. (2014). Neurocircuitry and neuroplas- Pietrzak, R. H., Galea, S., Southwick, S. M., & Gelernter,
ticity in PTSD. In M. J. Friedman, T. M. Keane, & J. (2013). Examining the relation between the sero-
P. A. Resick (Eds.), Handbook of PTSD: Science and tonin transporter 5-HTTPLR genotype × trauma expo-
practice (2nd ed., pp. 251–274). New York: Guilford sure interaction on a contemporary phenotypic model
Press. of posttraumatic stress symptomatology: A pilot study.
Nijdam, M. J., & Wittmann, L. (2015). Psychological and Journal of Affective Disorders, 148, 123–128.
social theories of PTSD. In U. Schnyder & M. Cloitre Pietrzak, R. H., Henry, S., Southwick, S. M., Krystal,
(Eds.), Evidence based treatments for trauma-related J. H., & Neumeister, A. (2013). Linking in vivo brain
psychological disorders: A practical guide for serotonin type 1B receptor density to phenotypic het-
clinicians (pp. 41–61). New York: Springer erogeneity of posttraumatic stress symptomatology.
Science + Business Media. Molecular Psychiatry, 18, 399–401.
Norrholm, S. D., Jovanovic, T., Smith, A. K., Binder, E., Pietrzak, R. H., Tsai, J., Harpaz-Rotem, I., Whealin, J. M.,
Klengel, T., Conneely, K., et al. (2013). Differential & Southwick, S. M. (2012). Support for a novel five-
genetic and epigenetic regulation of catechol-O- factor model posttraumatic stress symptoms in three
methyltransferase is associated with impaired fear independent samples of Iraq/Afghanistan veterans: A
inhibition in posttraumatic stress disorder. Frontiers in confirmatory factor analytic study. Journal of
Behavioral Neuroscience, 7, 30. doi:10.3389/ Psychiatric Research, 46, 317–322.
fnbeh.2013.00030. Pitman, R. K., Rasmusson, A. M., Koenen, K. C., Shin,
Norris, F. H., & Slone, L. B. (2014). Epidemiology of L. M., Orr, S. P., Gilbertson, M. W., et al. (2012).
trauma and PTSD. In M. J. Friedman, T. M. Keane, & Biological studies of posttraumatic stress disorder.
P. A. Resick (Eds.), Handbook of PTSD: Science and Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 13, 769–787.
practice (2nd ed., pp. 100–120). New York: Guilford Pitman, R. K., Sanders, K. M., Zusman, R. M., Healy, A. R.,
Press. Cheema, F., Lasko, N. B., et al. (2002). Pilot study of
Novak, M. A., Hamel, A. F., Kelly, B. J., Dettmer, A. M., secondary prevention of posttraumatic stress disorder
& Meyer, J. S. (2013). Stress, the HPA axis, and non- with propranolol. Biological Psychiatry, 51, 189–192.
human primate well-being: A review. Applied Animal Ptak, C., & Petronis, A. (2010). Epigenetic approaches to
Behaviour Science, 143, 135–149. psychiatric disorders. Dialogues in Clinical
Ouellet-Morin, I., Wong, C. C., Danesee, A., Pariante, Neuroscience, 12, 25–35.
C. M., Papadopoulos, A. S., Mill, J., et al. (2012). Raabe, F. J., & Spengler, D. (2013). Epigenetic risk fac-
Increased serotonin transporter gene (SERT) DNA tors in PTSD and depression. Frontiers in Psychiatry,
methylation is associated with bullying victimization 4, 80. doi:10.3389/fpsyt.2013.00080.
and blunted cortisol response to stress in childhood: A Raichle, M. E., MacLeod, A. M., Snyder, A. Z., Powers,
longitudinal study of discordant monozygotic twins. W. J., Gusnard, D. A., & Shulman, G. L. (2001). A
Psychological Medicine, 10, 1–11. default mode of brain function. Proceedings of the
Pergamin-Hight, L., Bakermans-Kranenburg, M. J., van National Academy of Sciences, USA, 98, 676–682.
IJzendoorn, M. H., & Bar-Haim, Y. (2012). Variations Rakofsky, J. J., Ressler, K. J., & Dunlop, B. W. (2012).
in the promoter region of the serotonin transporter BDNF function as a potential mediator of bipolar
gene and biased attention for emotional information: disorder and post-traumatic stress disorder comorbid-
A meta-analysis. Biological Psychiatry, 71, 373–379. ity. Molecular Psychiatry, 17, 22–35.
Perroud, N., Paoloni-Giacobino, A., Prada, P., Olie, E., Rasmusson, A. M., & Shalev, A. Y. (2014). Integrating the
Salzmann, A., Nicastro, R., et al. (2011). Increased neuroendocrinology, neurochemistry, and neuroim-
methylation of glucocorticoid receptor gene (NR3C1) munology of PTSD to date and the challenges ahead.
in adults with a history of childhood maltreatment: A In M. J. Friedman, T. M. Keane, & P. A. Resick (Eds.),
link with the severity and type of trauma. Translational Handbook of PTSD: Science and practice (2nd ed.,
Psychiatry, 1, e59. doi:10.1038/tp.2011.60. pp. 275–299). New York: Guilford Press.
References 563

Rauch, S. L., Shin, L. M., & Phelps, E. A. (2006). the gulf war. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 111,
Neurocircuitry models of posttraumatic stress disorder 637–647.
and extinction: Human neuroimaging research—Past, Sipahi, L., Wildman, D. E., Aiello, A. E., Koenen, K. C.,
present, and future. Biological Psychiatry, 60, Galea, S., Abbas, A., et al. (2014). Longitudinal epi-
376–382. genetic variation of DNA methyltransferases genes is
Ressler, K. J., Mercer, K. B., Bradley, B., Jovanovic, T., associated with vulnerability to post-traumatic stress
Mahan, A., Kerley, K., et al. (2011). Post-traumatic disorder. Psychological Medicine, 44, 3165–3179.
stress disorder is associated with PACAP and the Skelton, K., Ressler, K. J., Norrholm, S. D., Jovanovic, T.,
PAC1 receptor. Nature, 470, 492–497. & Bradley-Davino, B. (2012). PTSD and gene vari-
Ricon, T., Toth, E., Leshem, M., Braun, K., & Richter- ants: New pathways and new thinking.
Levin, G. (2012). Unpredictable chronic stress in juve- Neuropharmacology, 62, 628–637.
nile or adult rats has opposite effects, respectively, Smith, A. K., Conneely, K. N., Kilaru, V., Mercer, K. B.,
promoting and impairing resilience. Stress, 15, 11–20. Weiss, T. E., Bradley, B., et al. (2011). Differential
Rodrigues, S. M., LeDoux, J. E., & Sapolsky, R. M. immune system DNA methylation and cytokine regu-
(2009). The influence of stress hormones on fear cir- lation in post-traumatic stress disorder. American
cuitry. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 32, 289–313. Journal of Medical Genetics Part B: Neuropsychiatric
Rusiecki, J. A., Chen, L., Srikantan, V., Zhang, L., Yan, Genetics, 156B, 700–708.
L., Polin, M. L., et al. (2012). DNA methylation in Solovieff, N., Roberts, A. L., Ratanatharathorn, A.,
repetitive elements and post-traumatic stress disorder: Haloosim, M., De Vivo, I., King, A., et al. (2014).
A case–control study of US military service members. Genetic association analysis of post-traumatic stress
Epigenomics, 4, 29–40. disorder in over 300 genes among trauma-exposed
Russo, S. J., Murrough, J. W., Han, M. H., Charney, D. S., women from the Nurses’ Health Study II.
& Nestler, E. J. (2012). Neurobiology of resilience. Neuropsychopharmacology, 39, 1872–1879.
Nature Neuroscience, 15, 1475–1484. Spreng, R. N., Mar, R. A., & Kim, A. S. (2009). The com-
Sadeh, N., Spielberg, J. M., Warren, S. L., Miller, G. A., mon neural basis of autobiographical memory,
& Heller, W. (2014). Aberrant neural connectivity dur- prospection, navigation, theory of mind, and the
ing emotional processing associated with posttrau- default mode: A quantitative meta-analysis. Journal of
matic stress. Clinical Psychological Science, 2, Cognitive Neuroscience, 21, 489–510.
748–755. Stein, M. B., Jang, K. L., Taylor, S., Vernon, P. A., &
Sartor, C. E., McCutcheon, V. V., Pommer, N. E., Nelson, Livesley, W. J. (2002). Genetic and environmental
E. C., Grant, J. D., Duncan, A. E., et al. (2011). influences on trauma exposure and posttraumatic
Common genetic and environmental contributions to stress disorder symptoms: A twin study. American
post-traumatic stress disorder and alcohol dependence Journal of Psychiatry, 159, 1675–1681.
in young women. Psychological Medicine, 41, Sterling, P., & Eyer, J. (1988). Allostasis: A new paradigm
1497–1505. to explain arousal pathology. In S. Fisher & J. Reason
Schnyder, U., & Cloitre, M. (2015). Evidence based treat- (Eds.), Handbook of life stress, cognition and health
ment for trauma-related psychological disorders: A (pp. 629–649). New York: Wiley.
practical guide for clinicians. New York: Springer Suderman, M., McGowan, P. O., Sasaki, A., Huang, T. C.
Science + Business Media. T., Hallett, M., Meaney, M. J., et al. (2012). Conserved
Scott, J. C., Matt, G. E., Wrocklage, K. M., Crnich, C., epigenetic sensitivity to early life experience in the rat
Jordan, J., Southwick, S. M., et al. (2015). A quantita- and human hippocampus. Proceedings of the National
tive meta-analysis of neurocognitive functioning in Academy of Science, USA, 109, 17266–17272.
posttraumatic stress disorder. Psychological Bulletin, Sundermann, O., Hauschildt, M., & Ehlers, A. (2013).
141, 105–140. Perceptual processing during trauma, priming and the
Seckl, J. R., & Meaney, M. J. (2006). Glucocorticoid development of intrusive memories. Journal of
“programming” and PTSD risk. Annals of the Behavior Therapy and Experimental Psychiatry, 44,
New York Academy of Sciences, 1071, 351–378. 213–220.
Segman, R., Shalev, A. Y., & Gelernter, J. (2007). Gene- Sundermann, O., Onwumere, J., Bebbington, P., &
environment interactions: Twin studies and gene Kuipers, E. (2012). Social networks and support in
research in the context of PTSD. In M. J. Friedman, early psychosis: Potential mechanisms. Epidemiology
T. M. Keane, & P. A. Resick (Eds.), Handbook of and Psychiatric Sciences, 22, 147–150.
PTSD: Science and Practice (pp. 190–206). New York: Szyf, M. (2013). How do environments talk to genes?
Guilford Press. Nature Neuroscience, 16, 2–4.
Sherin, J. E., & Nemeroff, C. B. (2011). Post-traumatic Uddin, M., Aiello, A. E., Wildman, D. E., Koenen, K. C.,
stress disorder: The neurobiological impact of psycho- Pawelec, G., de Los Santos, R. et al., (2010). Epigenetic
logical trauma. Dialogues in Clinical Neuroscience, and immune function profiles associated with posttrau-
13, 263–278. matic stress disorder. Proceedings of the National
Simms, L. J., Watson, D., & Doebbeling, B. N. (2002). Academy of Sciences, USA, 107, 9470–9475.
Confirmatory factor analyses of posttraumatic stress Uddin, M., Galea, S., Chang, S. C., Aiello, A. E.,
symptoms in deployed and nondeployed veterans of Wildman, D. E., de los Santos, R., et al. (2011). Gene
564 21 PTSD: Traumatic Causation

expression and methylation signatures of MAN2C1 Yehuda, R., Daskalakis, N. P., Desarnaud, F., Makotkine,
are associated with PTSD. Disease Markers, 30, L., Lehrner, A. L., Koch, E., et al. (2013). Epigenetic
111–121. biomarkers as predictors and correlates of symptom
Vincent, J. L., Kahn, I., Snyder, A. Z., Raichle, M. E., & improvement following psychotherapy in combat vet-
Buckner, R. L. (2008). Evidence for a frontoparietal erans with PTSD. Frontiers in Psychiatry, 4, 118.
control system revealed by intrinsic functional connec- doi:10.3389/fpsyt.2013.00118.
tivity. Journal of Neurophysiology, 100, 3328–3342. Yehuda, R., Flory, J. D., Bierer, L. M., Henn-Haase, C.,
Vogt, D. S., King, D. W., & King, L. A. (2014). Risk path- Lehrner, A., Desarnaud, F., et al. (2015). Lower meth-
ways for PTSD: Making sense of the literature. In ylation of glucocorticoid receptor gene promoter 1F in
M. J. Friedman, T. M. Keane, & P. A. Resick (Eds.), peripheral blood of veterans with posttraumatic stress
Handbook of PTSD: Science and practice (2nd ed., disorder. Biological Psychiatry, 77, 356–364.
pp. 146–165). New York: Guilford Press. Yehuda, R., Flory, J. D., Pratchell, L. C., Buxbaum, J.,
Weathers, F., Litz, B., Herman, D., Huska, J., & Keane, T. Ising, M., & Holsboer, F. (2010). Putative biological
(1993). The PTSD checklist (PLC): Reliability, valid- mechanisms for the association between early life
ity, and diagnostic utility. Paper presented at a meet- adversity and the subsequent development of PTSD.
ing of the International Society of Traumatic Stress Psychopharmacology, 212, 405–417.
Studies, San Antonio, TX. Yehuda, R., Halligan, S. L., & Bierer, L. M. (2002).
Weaver, I. C. (2007). Epigenetic programming by mater- Cortisol levels in adult offspring of Holocaust survi-
nal behavior and pharmacological intervention. Nature vors: Relation to PTSD symptom severity in the par-
versus nurture: Let’s call the whole thing off. ent and child. Psychoneuroendocrinology, 27,
Epigenetics, 2, 22–28. 171–180.
Wilker, S., & Kolassa, I.-T. (2013). The formation of a Yehuda, R., & LeDoux, J. (2007). Response variation fol-
neural fear network in posttraumatic stress disorder: lowing trauma: A translational neuroscience approach
Insights from molecular genetics. Clinical to understanding PTSD. Neuron, 56, 19–32.
Psychological Science, 1, 452–469. Yehuda, R., McFarlane, A. C., & Shalev, A. Y. (1998).
Wu, G., Feder, A., Cohen, H., Kim, J. J., Calderon, S., Predicting the development of posttraumatic stress
Charney, D. S., et al. (2013). Understanding resilience. disorder from the acute response to a traumatic event.
Frontiers in Behavioral Neuroscience, 7, 10. Biological Psychiatry, 44, 1305–1313.
doi:10.3389/fnbeh.2013.00010. Young, G. (2008a). Causality and causation in law, medi-
Xie, P., Kranzler, H. R., Farrer, L., & Gelernter, J. (2012). cine, psychiatry, and psychology: Progression or
Serotonin transporter 5-HTTLPR genotype moderates regression? Psychological Injury and Law, 1,
the effects of childhood adversity on posttraumatic 161–181.
stress disorder risk: A replication study. American Young, G. (2008b). Psychological injury and law: An
Journal of Medical Genetics Part B: Neuropsychiatric integrative model. Psychological Injury and Law, 1,
Genetics, 159, 644–652. 150–160.
Xie, P., Kranzler, H. R., Poling, J., Stein, M. B., Anton, Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
R. F., Brady, K., et al. (2009). Interactive effect of Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer
stressful life events and the serotonin transporter Science + Business Media.
5-HTTLPR genotype on posttraumatic stress disorder Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feigning, and response
diagnosis in 2 independent populations. Archives of bias in psychiatric/psychological injury: Implications
General Psychiatry, 66, 1201–1209. for practice and court. Dordrecht, Netherlands:
Xie, P., Kranzler, H. R., Poling, J., Stein, M. B., Anton, R. F., Springer Science + Business Media.
Farrer, L. A., et al. (2010). Interaction of FKBP5 with Young, G., Lareau, C., & Pierre, B. (2014). One quintillion
childhood adversity on risk for post-traumatic stress dis- ways to have PTSD comorbidity: Recommendations
order. Neuropsychopharmacology, 35, 1684–1692. for the disordered DSM-5. Psychological Injury and
Xie, P., Kranzler, H. R., Yang, C., Zhao, H., Farrer, L. A., Law, 7, 61–74.
& Gelernter, J. (2013). Genome-wide association study Zhou, J., Nagarkatti, P., Zhong, Y., Ginsberg, J. P., Singh,
identifies new susceptibility loci for posttraumatic N. P., Zhang, J., et al. (2014). Dysregulation in
stress disorder. Biological Psychiatry, 74, 656–663. microRNA expression is associated with alterations in
Yehuda, R. (2002). Post-traumatic stress disorder. The immune functions in combat veterans with post-
New England Journal of Medicine, 346, 108–114. traumatic stress disorder. PLoS One, 9, e94075.
Yehuda, R. (2009). Status of glucocorticoid alterations in Zovkic, I. B., Guzman-Karlsson, M. C., & Sweatt, J. D.
post-traumatic stress disorder. Annals of the New York (2013). Epigenetic regulation of memory formation
Academy of Sciences, 1179, 56–69. and maintenance. Learning & Memory, 20, 61–74.
Yehuda, R., Bierer, L. M., Sarapas, C., Makotkine, I., Andrew, Zovkic, I. B., Meadows, J. P., Kaas, G. A., & Sweatt, J. D.
R., & Seckl, J. R. (2009). Cortisol metabolic predictors of (2013). Interindividual variability in stress susceptibil-
response to psychotherapy for symptoms of PTSD in sur- ity: A role for epigenetic mechanisms in PTSD.
vivors of the World Trade Center attacks on September Frontiers in Psychiatry, 4, 60. doi:10.3389/
11, 2001. Psychoneuroendocrinology, 34, 1304–1313. fpsyt.2013.00060.
DSM-5: Basics and Critics 22

the last chapter of the four on the DSM-5, I


Chapter Introduction examine more general issues, such as etiology in
psychiatric disorder and the recommendations
The present chapter is part of a series of chapters that I make for revising the DSM. Practitioners
that addresses the newest-version of the American from multiple disciplines will find the present
psychiatric diagnostic manual, the DSM-5 work on the DSM-5 quite informative, whether
(Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental clinicians, forensic workers, or otherwise and,
Disorder, Fifth Edition; American Psychiatric indeed, so will any stakeholder interested in the
Association, 2013a, 2013b). The approach of the DSM-5.
present work is multiple but, primarily, it takes a The present chapter specifically adds to the
scientific approach to understanding both the field by emphasizing the need for a biopsychoso-
positive contributions and negative pitfalls found cial approach for the DSMs. Also, it suggests a
in the DSM-5. (a) In this regard, the chapter new definition to mental disorder. Finally, it sug-
begins with an overview of the DSM-5. What are gests that one outcome of dealing with the
its major changes relative to the DSM-IV-TR DSM-5 might be DSM-5 Confusion Disorder!
(Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental
Disorders, Fourth Edition, Text Revision;
American Psychiatric Association, 2000)? Is the Introduction
DSM-5 reliable and valid? (b) Then, voice is
given to its multiple critics. Is it clinically useful? The DSMs constitute a series of psychiatric man-
I avoid the surface criticisms and hyperbolic uals developed by the American Psychiatric
rhetoric found in the public media and press. (c) Association (APA) that is used throughout the
The next two chapters after this one analyze care- world for mental illness diagnosis. The fifth edi-
fully several of the major diagnostic categories in tion was released in May 2013, and it is called
the DSM-5, especially those concerning the area The Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental
of psychological injury and law (e.g., tort cases Disorder, Fifth Edition (DSM-5; American
involving Posttraumatic Stress Disorder (PTSD), Psychiatric Association, 2013a). The DSMs usu-
chronic pain, and Traumatic Brain Injury, TBI). ally are published with a series of auxiliary
The second of the chapters includes discussion of books, and some of these are in development for
the RDoC (Research Domain Criteria) project, the DSM-5. The present work highlights the cen-
which will help in the revision of the DSM-5, but tral difficulties in the literature on the DSM-5 and
it, itself, is not without its critics. (d) Finally, in also analyzes some crucial disorders.

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 565


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_22
566 22 DSM-5: Basics and Critics

The DSM-5 was published after rancorous four in the series on it, I analyze in depth disorders
criticism of the procedures used in developing it, that are central to the area of psychological injury
the draft versions, and the final product, with and law. Two disorders in the DSM-5 of special
equally vigorous defense at all these levels. A use- concern to forensic psychologists (e.g., in disabil-
ful psychiatric diagnostic manual should reflect ity and related evaluations) are PTSD (posttrau-
practitioner utility requirements and also scien- matic stress disorder) and pain disorder. The
tific reliability and validity requirements. changes instituted for these two categories will be
However, on both these grounds, the DSM-5 has reviewed carefully and the implications of the
been attacked. Moreover, unlike the case for the changes will be discussed, for example, for what
working groups for the prior version, the DSM-IV the changes mean for PTSD tests and for what
(Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental they mean in giving a diagnosis that makes sense
Disorders, Fourth Edition; American Psychiatric for pain patients. Another category of concern is
Association, 1994; DSM-IV-TR, Text Revised; neurocognitive disorder, e.g., in TBI (traumatic
American Psychiatric Association, 2000), the pro- brain injury). The changes in it will be discussed,
cedure in constructing the manual was not open as well.
and there were accusations of conflicts of interest, In the last chapter of the present four-chapter
for instance, with pharmaceutical companies. series on the DSM-5, I describe some recent
Finally, in a point important for the present work, research on psychopathology and nosology (e.g.,
the manual has been criticized for its lack of care- systems, endophenotypes) that go beyond even
ful vetting for forensic purposes. This illustrates the contention that the DSM should be more
that much of the criticisms of the DSM-5 involve dimensional than categorical. Then, I move to
process as much as product, or how the APA and recommendations for the field, which focus on
the DSM editors and working groups proceeded the appropriate models to use and the broader
in this present iteration of the manual. assessment process, rather than on specific diag-
The direction and tenor of the criticisms of the noses and on diagnosing, per se. The DSM should
contents of the DSM-5 include not only general become a manual under constant scrutiny and
criticisms about process and procedure but also revision according to state-of-the-art science in
specific criticisms about disorders, such as the the field. To conclude this last chapter in the pres-
following. Some of the new categories proposed ent book on the DSM-5, for court use, I contend
might not have been carefully thought through, that some of the changes in the DSM-5 could
while others were kept intact, and might reflect open psychologists to criticisms by both plaintiff
the same. Some categories lower the bar in diag- and defense attorneys, and even arbitrators/
nosing disorder, while others raise it. Children judges. The best manner in hedging these criti-
appear unduly targeted, with a purported ease in cisms is to adopt a functional approach in evalu-
diagnosing some disorders and the consequent ations, in particular, and not to rely especially on
specter that is raised of overmedicating them. specific diagnostic labels as primary factors in
Only careful analysis of the contents of the conclusions to reports or testimony, which should
DSM-5 (generally; in addition to the categories) be the normative approach, in general, in good
and of the literature in the field in psychopathol- practice in the field.
ogy and its etiology can determine the degree of
difficulties contained in the manual and the direc-
tion needed in future iterations. Therefore, the goal Goals
of the first part of the present section of the present
work on the DSM-5 (that is, the present chapter) is Although the aim of the DSM-5 (and psychiatry,
to adopt this careful scientific approach in analyz- in general) is to associate specific etiologies with
ing the validity and value of the DSM-5. In the each disorder, it is well-known that knowledge of
second portion of the present work on the DSM-5, causal factors of psychiatric disorders is limited.
which consists of the two middle chapters of the Even when causal factors are specified in the
Assumptions 567

DSM-5 manual for a disorder, the literature new literature appears and (2) in using the
supporting these types of statements is not cited scientific method or reasoning in patient assess-
(and no sourcebooks are planned, unlike the case ment strategies and also in diagnostic hypothesis
of the DSM-IV). formation and attribution.
According to its critics, in terms of problems Psychiatric manuals work best in the clinical
with categories of disorder in the DSM-5, they context when they adopt, to the degree possible,
lack (a) the reliability and validity needed for a research approach and also that they respect the
efficacious use of diagnostic categories; (b) and, clinical needs of practitioners. An approach such
therefore, their utility to clinicians is compro- as this can help ensure that psychiatric manuals
mised. (c) In addition, they lack grounding in respect the research and scientific process and,
clear etiology; (d) they are not really distinct enti- also, are responsive to feedback from clinicians
ties “carved at the joints”; (e) and, therefore, on what works for them, which should always be
unlike the case for various medical diseases, they from an informed scientific perspective, as
are not amenable to efficacious treatment (read: described.
psychopharmacological medication). To con- Developers of psychiatric manuals should be
clude, the aspirational goals of the DSM-5 are open to changing the scientific roots and scien-
laudable, but it has yet to achieve them in a con- tific integrity of their manuals, partly because sci-
sistent way for many of its disorders (Frances, entific content changes so rapidly. Similarly,
2013a; Paris, 2013a). clinicians should be open to scientific learning,
for example, through educational workshops and
literature review articles for practitioners.
Assumptions In the end, a balance is needed in the construc-
tion of psychiatric manuals in terms of clinical
Science and Utility usefulness and research basis. Additionally, as
they are revised, balance is needed in research
The fundamental assumptions governing the input and clinical input.
direction needed with respect to the DSM-5, spe-
cifically, and psychiatry, generally, are that a
scientifically-informed approach should underlie Etiology
every step in creation of a psychiatric diagnostic
manual and also its use in the clinical context. Wakefield (2013) noted that most diagnostic cat-
This will help ensure that the manual is con- egories in the DSM do not express “construct
structed ethically and also used ethically. A sub- validity,” which he defined as each disorder rep-
text is that these manuals are important in the resenting one condition and having a “distinctive
forensic context so that care needs to be taken in etiology.” Instead, he noted that the DSM-5 cat-
these regards both in its construction and use. egories are only “syndromes” and, moreover,
Note that by scientifically-informed, I do not they “encompass” multiple etiologies. Ideally,
mean that the manual must be only or must be psychiatric disorders should have a specific cause
especially a research document. Rather, it means (etiology) and specific pathway to illness (patho-
that (a) its conceptual basis is scientifically ade- genesis; Paris, 2013a). I would add that any cat-
quate; (b) the research it uses and cites clearly egory found to be unreliable and not valid, by
supports both the manual’s conceptual or assump- definition, cannot represent genuine disorders
tional base and the specific disorders formulated and, therefore, cannot have “distinct” etiologies.
(in terms of constructs and also empirical find- Given that the starting point of conceptualizing
ings); and (c) also, it means that its users adopt a psychiatric diagnostic categories begins with hav-
scientific approach, in terms of both: (1) scrutiny ing a clear etiological source for each, the present
of the literature, so that they arrive at their own work reviews recent concepts and research in the
opinions on past literature, and revise them as field of psychopathology related to causality. It
568 22 DSM-5: Basics and Critics

raises issues about the standard medical or psy- in origin and demanding of psychosocial treat-
chiatric model of mental disorder, and suggests ments only. However, as a precaution, it is
ways that psychiatric manual might evolve, for acknowledged that appropriate screening of med-
example, with hybrid models of distinct diagnos- ical condition should take place in every psychi-
tic categories and dimensional constructs of men- atric clinical presentation. Moreover, even if not
tal health framed from an etiological perspective causally pertinent, biological factors still could
and the biopsychosocial approach. be at play in any case, for example, worry leading
to anxious bodily reactions. Conversely,
psychosocial factors might positively affect the
Biopsychosocial dysfunctional biological status of any individual
diagnosed with mental disorder.
Of all the assumptions underpinning the present Another important consideration essential to
work on the DSM-5, the one most essential is that the present work is its emphasis on multifactorial
psychopathology is best considered from the causality. This approach constitutes an extension
point of view of the biopsychosocial model or its of the biopsychosocial model. For example, some
equivalent. The definition of mental disorder in of the refined concepts emerging in psychiatric
the DSM-IV-TR and the DSM-5 does not mention causation include genome-wide association stud-
this term, nor do their introductory materials. ies (GWAS), Gene × Environment interactions
Nevertheless, it is partially implicit in the (G × E), gene–environment correlations (rGE),
DSM approach to mental disorder and its diagno- epigenetics, (neuro)endophenotypes, neural cir-
sis, despite the origins of the psychiatric profes- cuitry and intrinsic neural networks, differential
sion in the more biological medical model and in environmental susceptibility/biological context,
the psychoanalytic model. In the present work, I prenatal programming, and developmental plas-
call for the explicit recognition of the biopsycho- ticity. These concepts are not necessarily uniquely
social model or its equivalent as a keystone for genetic or biological, and most of them ascribe at
psychiatry in understanding etiology, classifica- least some role for the environment in psychiatric
tion, and intervention/treatment (also see mental health.
McEwen & Getz, 2013). The approach that I have described on the
Part of the reason the DSM enterprise should importance of the biopsychosocial model for
endorse the biopsychosocial approach is the sys- psychiatry would appear to stand in contrast to
tems perspective that it offers in understanding the work of Kendler (2012). However, our
psychiatric illness. Another reason is that it sug- approaches are quite similar. Kendler (2012)
gests a full range of intervention and treatment rejected the dualist framework that has governed
options, and not just those overly focused on understanding of the mind/brain system. He
psychopharmacology. Granted, the DSM-5 argued for a multiple etiological approach
advises to be aware of indiscriminate prescrip- involving causal risk factors (“difference mak-
tion of medication and the availability of nonme- ers”), which can range from the genetic and the
dicinal intervention/treatment options. But if the biological to the psychosocial. However, he
DSM openly adopts a biopsychosocial model, maintained that the biopsychosocial approach
patients will be afforded the full range of psychi- itself is not critical enough and does not guide
atric and psychological help that might prove sufficiently well the research in psychiatry.
beneficial to them. Nevertheless, I maintain that it provides a useful
It is worth noting my understanding of the role heuristic for juxtaposing the more restricted and
of the biological component in the biopsychoso- standard medical model and also psychiatric
cial formulation of mental illness. On the one models with the more open and pluralistic,
hand, biological causation or expression in men- broader typical psychological approach.
tal disorder does not have to be found in every Moreover, in its contemporary systemic guises
case. Any one case might be purely psychosocial (e.g., nonlinear dynamical system theory, Young,
The DSM in Detail 569

2011), by definition, the biopsychosocial model brain mechanisms, citing examples with respect
does not reflect just an addition of biological, to his own research (e.g., the importance of psy-
psychological, and social influences on behavior chological factors, such as meaning, in the recov-
and its psychopathology. This is the case because ery of women exposed to severe sexual abuse).
it gives direction on how the factors interact, Kendler (2012) concluded that because psy-
how symptoms reflect that interaction, and how chiatric disorders derive from multiple etiological
treatment should consider the interaction. processes, classificatory systems based on etio-
In this regard, Kendler supports the equivalent logical considerations are “deeply problematic.”
of biopsychosocial formulations for the under- I would add that in classificatory systems that are
standing of psychiatric illness (e.g., Kendler, categorical or disorder-based, diagnoses will
2008). Kendler’s (2012) approach to etiology of always have their place. Therefore, their etiologi-
psychiatric illness is strikingly advanced. He cal bases should be elucidated to the degree pos-
attempted to find “causal signatures” for three sible, or else this approach to classification will
archetypal psychiatric disorders—schizophrenia, suffer. We should not throw out the baby with the
major depression, and alcohol dependence. He bathwater, that is, we should still attempt to
considered three superordinate categories of ascertain and use etiological sources of valid
causal risks—biological, psychological, and diagnostic psychiatric systems. However, to what
“higher-order.” Biological risks included molecu- degree can we find them?
lar genetic, molecular neuroscientific, systems Given this overview of fundamental assump-
neuroscientific, aggregate genetic, and miscella- tions guiding the present work, we are ready to
neous risks. The psychological risks included neu- explore in detail the DSM-5. After presenting rel-
ropsychological, personality/cognitive/attitudinal, evant explanatory material, the DSM-5 considers
and trauma exposure risks. The higher-order risks the thorny issue of the definition of a mental dis-
were social, political, and cultural. For each of the order. Before considering it, however, I address
three disorders mentioned, he reviewed the empir- the preliminary material in the manual.
ical research for each of the causal risk factors.
He found interesting results in his review.
First, the risks for the disorders included all three The DSM in Detail
major domains (biological, psychological, and
higher-order). Also, there was no evidence of Preface
duality (separability) in risk, in terms of either
genetic/biological or psychosocial factors. Relative to the DSM-IV-TR, the DSM-5 added a
Second, aggregate genetic effects made the larg- preface in which the stated goal in the first sen-
est contributions to the causality of the disorders. tence is to arrive at reliable diagnosis of disor-
Third, there were different patterns of risk in the ders. However, it acknowledges in the third
three disorders, with schizophrenia being the sentence that full elucidation of the “underlying
most biological, major depression being the most pathological processes” is not yet available for
psychological, and alcohol dependence being the most mental disorders. The contrast in these two
most sociocultural. sentences at the beginning of the DSM-5 illus-
He noted that despite the separation of the trates the dominant tension in the field of psychi-
three major domains for purposes of the analysis, atric, mental health classification—between
they really interact and mediate and moderate research and etiology and the need for a clinically-
each other’s effects. They are actively inter- useful classificatory system.
twined with each other in multilevel, complex The preface proceeds to describe the DSM-5
causal webs or etiological pathways, and so the as a “practical, functional, and flexible guide.”
disorders are multifactorial in the causal land- However, then it suggests that it is also an “offi-
scape. He rejected the reductionist argument that cial nomenclature.” This opposition indicates
the psychological and social can be reduced to another tension in the field—the manual and its
570 22 DSM-5: Basics and Critics

disorders function like a “bible” in psychiatry, one aligns several categories along a dimension
given its official stamp of the APA yet, at the of severity, does this equate with leaving aside
other extreme, it appears as a mixture of disor- categories and examining symptoms for their
ders and criteria fabricated in committee that organization and severity along dimensions, for
lacks reliability. Considering that the reality of example, ones that are constructed statistically as
the DSM-5 lies somewhere between these poles, in factor analysis? I address this question below.
it should be used with caution and care. Note that by category-identifying markers, I
Next, the preface lists the different “orienta- do not necessarily refer to biomarkers or endo-
tions” to which the manual could be useful. These phenotypes related to genetic markers. In this
include workers using the biological, psychody- regard, marker symptoms could be characteristic
namic, cognitive, behavioral, interpersonal, and expressions of a disorder without having a bio- or
family/systems approaches. As for the type of genetic origin, or they could be environmentally-
workers, mental health care practitioners who related ones (e.g., due to marital conflict, child
will find it useful include not only psychiatrists abuse, adversity, and work stress). This approach
and other physicians, but also psychologists and to marker symptoms is consistent with the bio-
other specialists. The broad range in these list- psychosocial approach.
ings of approaches and users to which the manual The introduction to the DSM-5 continues that
is addressed justify my call to make explicit diagnosing a categorical disorder implies that it
statements of its biopsychosocial underpinnings. can be isolated or differentiated from “normal
The preface continues that the listed symptoms life variation” and also from transient stress
of disorders are concise, explicit, and facilitative responses, although the borders in these regards
of objective assessment. Disorders might reflect might be “porous.” According to the introduc-
common underlying vulnerabilities. Moreover, tion, the categorical approach in prior editions of
even diagnostic groups might be related in genetic the DSM included “structural problems,” due to
linkage, having common neurocircuitry, genetic “narrow” diagnostic categories that lent to diag-
indicators, physiological risks, and environmental nosis of comorbidities, use of the “not otherwise
exposures. specified” categories, and so on. In this vein,
there is too much symptom heterogeneity within
disorders and also symptom overlap across them
Introduction for efforts to continue to seek categories with dis-
tinct and homogeneous populations.
Moving on from the preface, the introduction to Similarly, in Young and Yehuda (2006), and
the DSM-5 adds that many mental disorder cate- then in Young, Lareau, and Pierre (2014), I had
gories appear “fluid” in nature, having symptom calculated that PTSD could be expressed in over
overlap with other ones. Therefore, nosological thousands of different ways! The polythetic
symptoms should accommodate dimensional approach to organizing and scoring criteria in the
approaches that cut across categories. DSM is the reason for heterogeneity in symptom
I note that the logic expressed in the above is expression for its disorders. Presumably, some of
a non-sequitor. If the problem in diagnosis con- its other disorders also would reveal large num-
cerns symptom overlap over categories, the direct bers of individual ways of expressing them.
solution is to have: (a) only distinct marker In this regard, I note that the polythetic approach
symptoms for each category; (b) with the more that characterizes the DSM-IV-TR and the DSM-5
overlapping symptoms removed from specific should be changed. It is noteworthy that the con-
disorders. That being said, the DSM-5’s approach stellation of potential symptom expression varia-
is well taken—categorical and dimensional tions in cases of comorbid diagnosis of disorders
approaches can co-exist in a hybrid psychiatric using the DSM-5 approach reaches into the mil-
nosological system. However, I query whether lions or more (Young et al., 2014).
the DSM-5 has approached in the best way pos- As for the characteristic of the primary dimen-
sible this hybrid concept of mental disorder. If sional differentiation to which the introduction to
The DSM in Detail 571

the DSM-5 referred, it concerns internalization Forensics


and externalization. This polarity is a common
dimensional differentiating factor in psychologi- The introduction to the DSM-5 mentions that it
cal tests, such as the Child Behavior Checklist was reviewed extensively in multiple ways. Of
(CBCL, Achenbach, 1991; Achenbach & interest to the present work, given its forensic
Rescorla, 2001). component, it is noted that the DSM-5 draft was
The DSM-5 manual indicates that despite its vetted by members of the APA Council on
recognition of the dimensional component to Psychiatry and Law for its disorders that have
psychiatric disorder, it is “premature” to alter forensic application. Either the disorders so vet-
extant categorical definitions for most disorders ted appear in forensic environments or have
listed in the DSM. Therefore, the DSM-5 remains much potential to influence “civil and criminal”
highly categorical, and without much change courtroom cases. Moreover, DSM-5 workgroups
from the DSM-IV-TR. Nevertheless, the ultimate dealing with forensically-related disorders added
goal of the DSM project is to become increas- forensic experts to the groups in order to “advise”
ingly dimensional. them.
I note that this logic constitutes another non- A later section of the introductory material in
sequitor. By organizing categories into spectra, the DSM-5 consists of a “cautionary statement”
groups, or dimensions of severity, no matter how in using the manual forensically. It is acknowl-
defined, the categories still exist. Even by defin- edged that although the DSM-5 may be a “refer-
ing each of their aspects dimensionally, they still ence” for court, it does not attempt to meet all
exist. In this regard, consider how psychological court needs. This cautionary statement notes that
tests, such as the CBCL, treat dimensions. (a) clinically diagnostic and (b) forensic/legal
Questionnaire responses are factor-analyzed and questions do not necessarily “fit” each other (e.g.,
each factor constitutes a dimensional construct in criminal responsibility or in civil disability
on which low and high scores can be compared to cases). For example, for the former, a disorder
normative distributions. With this and other does not implicate residual degree of personal
information at hand, the clinician is free to assign control. For the latter, a disorder does not address
relevant diagnostic categories, but only if desired etiology or cause.
or required. This approach is quite unlike the To conclude, for forensic use, the DSM-5
dimensional approach advocated in the DSM-5. acknowledges that there is an imperfect fit in its
The introduction to the DSM-5 goes on to dis- application for court because it is clinician-
cuss its developmental, cultural, and gender foci. It oriented. Moreover, disorders by themselves can-
ends with an explanation of how its multiaxial sys- not be used to ascertain: (a) whether legal
tem has been replaced with the one using specifiers thresholds have been reached; (b) whether there
for psychosocialcontextual factors and disability, is a specific level of an impairment or disability;
aside from having moved personality disorders and (c) what level of control a person can have of
from Axis II to Section 2. In addition, Axis V on the symptoms of a disorder. Comparison with the
disability was dropped because the Global equivalent paragraphs in the DSM-IV-TR reveals
Assessment of Functioning (GAF) Scale on which almost no change to this page on forensics.
it was based had a “conceptual lack of clarity” and
“questionable psychometrics.” Instead, the DSM-5
uses codes from the ICD (International Statistical Comment
Classification of Diseases and Related Health
Problems) classification system, as developed by As a final note to this section of the present work
the WHO (World Health Organization). In addi- on the introductory material in the DSM-5, I
tion, for disability, the WHO’s Disability observed that any mention of sourcebooks has
Assessment Schedule is included in Section 3 as a been deleted. The DSM-IV had several books
global measure of disability. Version 2 was tested published with it within a few years (Widiger,
in the DSM-5 field trials. Frances, & Pincus, 1997) that could be used for
572 22 DSM-5: Basics and Critics

investigation of its scientific research basis and, that it can be given when there is not enough
if had been needed, for justification of approaches information available. The DSM-5 text for the
taken by users for court. However, it appears that disorder (and for the other two mentioned) indi-
financial considerations have led to removal of cates that it is used when, based entirely on clini-
this important aspect of the DSM enterprise. cal judgment, a clinician decides “not” to specify
Similarly, it is noted that financial reasons appear why the criteria are not met for a specific mental
to be why the field trials were limited and, more- disorder, and the patient’s presentation does not
over, why there was removal of a follow-up test- give enough information to allow for a specific
ing of the manual after the initial field trials. diagnosis. Clearly, the category is so open-ended
There had been DSM-5 draft proposals in 2010 that Sax appears correct about its dangers. This
that invited response and subsequent modifica- type of concern permeates the commentary by
tions, and the final draft proposal appears to be Frances on the DSM-5, as described in
the one field-tested. However, to repeat, the final Tables 22.2 and 22.3.
version of the DSM-5 published in 2013 was not After reviewing the scope of the changes in
the one that was field-tested. Finally, please note Table 22.1 and these initial concerns by Frances
that space limitations have precluded dealing (2013a) in Tables 22.2 and 22.3 on the merits of
with children’s diagnoses in the present work, but some of the changes, professionals and stakeholders
the DSM-5 manual deals extensively with devel- working in the field should consider the problems
opmental considerations. I inherent in the DSM-5. Considering (a) the pleth-
ora of changes, both minor and major in the DSM-
5, and (b) the firestorm around the DSM-5 draft
Specific Changes in the DSM-5 proposals, (c) not to mention the range of criticisms
and Their Critique of the final version of the DSM-5, from mild to
vociferous, let alone the confusion engendered by
Changes the consequent changes to the first set of changes,
(d) along with the further changes after the field tri-
Table 22.1 provides the major changes that were als, it is understandable how the DSM-5 has induced
instituted in the DSM-5 relative to the DSM- quite a state of confusion in professionals and
IV-TR. The table indicates the changes that were stakeholders.
made according to an appendix in the DSM-5 and In this regard, I propose a new diagnostic
in associated web material that is more elaborate entity related to the DSM-5 for inclusion in its set
(American Psychiatric Association, 2013b). The of disorders for further study, this one concerning
present work examines closely many of these those who try to use it—DSM-5 Confusion
changes. Moreover, others have presented spe- Disorder (see Table 22.4). However, I add that
cific comments and criticisms of the changes, there is a rapid cure for any DSM-5 type confu-
including Frances (2013a, 2013b, 2013c, 2013d, sion—careful analysis of the DSM-5 and the lit-
2013e; see Tables 22.2 and 22.3). In an article in erature on it—a goal to which this work is
the public media, Sax noted that there are several therapeutically dedicated.
DSM-5 diagnoses involving the word “unspeci-
fied” that could lead to inappropriately diagnos-
ing mental disorders in many people when it is Comment
not merited (Sax, 2013). He gave the examples of
unspecified schizophrenia spectrum disorder, This completes the general introduction to the
unspecified attention-deficit/hyperactivity disor- DSM-5 and my analysis of its introductory mate-
der, and unspecified mental disorder. In checking rial in the preface and introduction. The take-
the DSM-IV-TR, he noted that the latter disorder home message is that the DSM-5 might have
is included there, as well (as “Unspecified Mental made several improvements relative to the DSM-
Disorder (nonpsychotic)”). Its description states IV-TR, but there is still much to do. Its users need
Specific Changes in the DSM-5 and Their Critique 573

Table 22.1 Notable changes made on the DSM-5 (2013) diagnostic criteria (based on the APA document highlighting
changes from DSM-IV-TR to DSM-5 (American Psychiatric Association, 2013b)
Disorder Change
Neurodevelopmental disorder
Intellectual disability Severity determined by adaptive functioning instead of IQ score.
(Intellectual developmental The term “mental retardation” is replaced by “intellectual disability.”
disorder)
Communication disorders Includes language disorder, speech sound disorder, childhood-onset fluency disorder,
and social (pragmatic) communication disorder, a new condition.
Autism spectrum disorder A single disorder, with different levels of severity, is characterized by (a) deficits in
social communication and social interaction and (b) restricted repetitive behaviors,
interests, and activities (RRBs). Because both components are required for diagnosis
of ASD, social communication disorder is diagnosed if no RRBs are present.
Attention-deficit/ Examples have been added to facilitate application across the life span; the cross-
hyperactivity disorder situational requirement has been strengthened to “several” symptoms in each setting;
the onset criterion is changed from “present before age 7 years” to “several symptoms
present prior to age 12.”
Specific learning disorder Combines reading disorder, mathematics disorder, disorder of written expression, and
learning disorder not otherwise specified.
Motor disorder Motor disorders are included in the neurodevelopmental disorders chapter.
Schizophrenia spectrum and other psychotic disorders
Schizophrenia Two Criterion A symptoms are required for diagnosis of schizophrenia. The individual
must have at least one of three positive symptoms: delusions, hallucinations, and
disorganized speech.
Schizophrenia subtypes The subtypes (i.e., paranoid, disorganized, catatonic, undifferentiated, and residual
types) are eliminated. A dimensional approach to rating severity is provided (which is
in proposals for study).
Bipolar and related disorders
Bipolar disorders Criterion A includes emphasis on changes in activity/energy as well as mood. Bipolar
I disorder, mixed episode, has been removed. For the specifiers, “with mixed features”
has been added.
Anxious distress specifier To identify patients having anxiety symptoms not part of the bipolar diagnostic
criteria.
Depressive disorders A new diagnosis, disruptive mood dysregulation disorder, is now included for patients
up to 18 years. Premenstrual dysphoric disorder has been included based on strong
scientific evidence. The category of persistent depressive disorder includes both
chronic major depressive disorder and the previous dysthymic disorder.
Major depressive disorder Added the specifier “with mixed features.”
Bereavement exclusion The exclusion criterion for a major depressive episode lasting <2 months is omitted. It
is noted that most people experiencing the loss of a loved one experience bereavement
without developing a major depressive episode.
Anxiety disorders
Agoraphobia, specific Deletion of the requirement that those over age 18 years must recognize that their
phobia, and social anxiety anxiety is excessive or unreasonable. The anxiety must be out of proportion to the
disorder (social phobia) actual danger or threat in the situation. The 6-month duration is now extended to all
ages.
Social anxiety disorder For social anxiety, the “generalized” specifier has been replaced by a “performance
(social phobia) only” specifier.
Specific phobia The different types of specific phobias are now specifiers.
Obsessive-compulsive and The chapter on obsessive-compulsive and related disorders is new in DSM-5. New
related disorders disorders include hoarding disorder, excoriation (skin-picking) disorder, substance-/
medication-induced obsessive-compulsive and related disorder, and obsessive-
compulsive and related disorder due to another medical condition.
(continued)
574 22 DSM-5: Basics and Critics

Table 22.1 (continued)


Disorder Change
Other specified and Includes obsessional jealousy or nondelusional preoccupation with a partner’s
unspecified obsessive- perceived infidelity. [Comment: Are there cautions needed here?]
compulsive and related
disorders
Trauma- and stressor-related disorders
Acute stress disorder As with PTSD, Criterion A, the criterion requires being explicit as to whether
qualifying traumatic events could be experienced directly, witnessed, or experienced
indirectly. The subjective reaction criterion (A2) to the traumatic event has been
eliminated. The DSM-IV’s emphasis on dissociative symptoms is minimized.
Adjustment disorder Reconceptualized as syndromes that occur after exposure to a distressing (traumatic or
nontraumatic) event, rather than as a residual category from clinically significant distress.
Posttraumatic stress Now has four symptom clusters: the avoidance/numbing cluster is divided into two.
disorder Includes new or reconceptualized symptoms (3 new ones).
Dissociative disorder Derealization is now included in the diagnosis of depersonalization disorder and is
now called depersonalization/derealization disorder.
Somatic symptom and Reduces the number of disorders and subcategories. Somatization disorder,
related disorders hypochondriasis, pain disorder, and undifferentiated somatoform disorder are removed.
Somatic symptom disorder “Better recognizes the complexity of the interface between psychiatry and medicine”
[Comment: Dual thinking?] Positive symptoms added (maladaptive thoughts, feelings,
and behaviors), in addition to somatic symptoms.
Medically unexplained Qualifier removed. DSM-IV overemphasized the importance of the absence of
symptoms medical explanation. Medically unexplained symptoms are limited in reliability. The
DSM-5 classification defines disorders on the basis of positive symptoms.
Hypochondriasis and Hypochondriasis is eliminated. Having high health anxiety without somatic symptoms
illness anxiety disorder leads to a diagnosis of illness anxiety disorder.
Pain disorder In DSM-IV, the pain disorder could be due to medical diseases/injuries, psychological,
or both. But psychological factors influence all forms of pain, so the disorder has been
eliminated. In DSM-5, some individuals with chronic pain might be appropriately
diagnosed as having somatic symptom disorder, with predominant pain. In addition,
for diagnosis of pain experience, psychological factors affecting other medical
conditions or also an adjustment disorder might be appropriate.
Psychological factors The first is a new mental disorder. Factitious disorder is included in this DSM chapter
affecting other medical because somatic symptoms are predominant.
conditions and factitious
disorder
Conversion disorder Emphasizes the importance of neurological examination. Relevant psychological
(Functional neurological factors might not be demonstrable in the examination.
symptom disorder)
Substance-related and addictive disorders
Gambling disorder Gambling activates the brain reward system like with drugs of abuse.
Criteria and terminology Does not separate anymore the diagnoses of substance abuse and dependence.
Neurocognitive disorders
Major and mild Dementia and amnestic disorder are subsumed under Major neurocognitive disorder
neurocognitive disorder (NCD). Mild NCD is a new disorder. An updated listing of neurocognitive domains is
provided. It is stated that the threshold between mild and major NCD is inherently
arbitrary.
Etiological subtypes New separate criteria are presented for major or mild NCD due to frontotemporal
NCD, Lewy bodies, TBI, etc.
Personality disorders The criteria for personality disorders have not changed (Section II). An alternative
approach for further study can be found in Section III. It includes core impairments
central to personality pathology. It includes characteristic pathological personality
traits related to the personality disorders they represent. The section provides an
efficient assessment approach with considerable clinical utility. [Comment: The new
diagnostic PD system was moved to the appendix Section III after much criticism]
Note. This table on the DSM-5 highlights does not cover every change
Table 22.2 Cautions in using the DSM-5 (Frances, 2013b)
Diagnostic Caution
General Beware of diagnostic inflation.
ADHD The initial onset is now later than age 12. The symptom requirement for adult
ADHD is loosened.
Grief vs. major depressive Overdiagnosis/overtreatment of major depressive disorder possible in people
disorder experiencing grief.
Disruptive mood Inability to distinguish disruptive mood dysregulation disorder (DMDD) from
dysregulation disorder normal temper tantrums in children, or from temper tantrums occurring in other
psychotic disorders.
Childhood bipolar disorders Most children diagnosed with childhood bipolar disorders only have nonepisodic
temper outbursts/irritability—not classic bipolar swings. Children who could get
diagnosed with ADHD, conduct disorder, ODD, or anxiety disorder, or no diagnosis
at all, now could get this one. It suggests a lifetime disorder that will require
continuous psychopharmacological treatment.
Generalized anxiety disorder The criteria are too loose both in the required number of symptoms and in their
duration, so the “worried well” will be over diagnosed with a mental disorder.
Posttraumatic stress disorder The gatekeeper threshold has been lowered too much by allowing the diagnosis in
people who have had no direct traumatic exposure, but have simply learned about a
violent event that was experienced by a close relative/friend. This creates a
“forensic disaster.”
Substance abuse and Collapses the previously separate substance abuse and substance dependence
substance dependence (substance use disorder). Starting to abuse clinically is now considered in the same
category as people who have end-stage addictions.
Mild neurocognitive disorder Based totally on extremely unreliable and fallible clinical criteria.
Personality dimensions in The system is untested, cumbersome, impractical, and unacceptable—serving no
DSM-5’s section 3 useful clinical or research purpose.

Table 22.3 Writing “Mistakes” in the DSM-5


Category Mistake
Autism spectrum disorder (ASD) Does not indicate exactly how many are required for its three symptoms;
Criterion A ambiguous
Permits use of the DSM-IV criterion; confusing
Disruptive mood regulation disorder Indicates four different age ranges applicable—up to 12 years (p. 155),
6–8 (p. 156), <10 (p. 156), 7–18 (p. 157); inconsistent
Major depressive disorder (MDD) (with The footnote explaining when it can be diagnosed is “so vaguely
the bereavement exclusion removed) written,” it does not help differentiate MDD during bereavement from
mild reactive depressed symptoms
Unspecified mood disorder Removed. There is no more a way to diagnose patients expressing not
yet clear bipolar I or II disorder
Bipolar and depression sections Not clear, consistent; imprecise, even impenetrable; e.g., the way to use
the “melancholic features” specifier not indicated clearly
Persistent depressive disorder New category groups relatively mild “dysthymia” with the most severe
category of chronic major depression
Intermittent explosive disorder Does not have exclusion criterion ruling out alternate ways that can
explain source of violent behavior
Intellectual disability Removes IQ requirement; forensically questionable
Somatic symptom disorder Loosely written; will lead to false diagnosis of people with legitimate
concerns for their medical conditions as having a mental disorder.
Exclusion criterion should make clear somatic complaints not due to a
medical or to other psychiatric conditions. If psychological factors
present, they should be “far beyond the expectable”
Paraphilia section Ambiguous; forensic misuses for sure to come
Brief psychotic disorder The way it is written has made the 4th item “completely superfluous”
Depressive disorders, mixed feature “Nearly every day during a majority of days”; “tautological,” “inconsistent”
specifier
Coding Mistakes made in a number of them
Adapted from Frances (2013e)
576 22 DSM-5: Basics and Critics

Table 22.4 Proposal: DSM-5 confusion disorder users and commentators, we need to be proactive
Criterion Explanation in voicing our concerns (as well as our praise,
A Diagnostic confusion where merited).
A1 Among practitioners using the DSM-5, Next, in the present work, after a general
there is cognitive, affective, or behavioral acceptance of the DSM-5 by its proponents and
disorientation.
then a critique of the DSM-5 in books by Joel
A2 Etiologically-induced by studying, using
clinically, and/or applying forensically the
Paris, I examine journal publications on the
portions of the DSM-5 that are not reliable/ DSM-5 for their perspective on its strengths and
valid/or clinically useful. weaknesses. The chapter terminates with discus-
A3 Condition is demonstrated by the sion of what is mental disorder, including my
following: diagnostic confusion symptoms own conceptualization and definition.
for the diagnostic categories in DSM-5,
and these are of the type 1, 2, and/or 3.
Type 1: Confusion for a category
unchanged from DSM-IV-TR Supporting DSM-5
Type 2: Confusion for a category modified
from DSM-IV-TR, or Kupfer, Kuhl, and Regier (2013) and Regier,
Type 3: Confusion for a category new in Kuhl, and Kupfer (2013) announced with much
DSM-5
fanfare the publication of the DSM-5 (“the future
B Diagnostic binging (inflation)
has arrived”). They noted that it emphasizes clin-
B1 Too many disorders consistently diagnosed
(co-co-co morbidities) ical care and that it is compatible with the rest of
B2 Too many people consistently diagnosed medicine. Therefore, in these regards, it has been
(prevalent prevalence) constructed to be more dimensional. Also, it is
C Diagnosis belief harmonized with the upcoming ICD-11.
C1 Strict uncritical compliance with DSM-5 Kupfer et al. (2013) continued that the DSM-5
C2 Lack of scientific verification in using it in has dropped the cumbersome multiaxial system.
diagnosis However, it has added several new disorders or
C3 “Disbelief” problems could arise (e.g., in spectra. For example, the autism spectrum disor-
court), due to C1 or C2
der combines autistic disorder, Asperger disor-
D The confusion significantly impairs
important aspects of vocational, social, or der, childhood disintegrative disorder, and
personal functioning (at least until cures pervasive developmental disorder.
attempted, although these might include The authors addressed concerns that prevalence
(in)appropriate beverage or substance estimates based on the DSM-5 will be different
(ab)use)
compared to that for the DSM-IV. They cited
E Duration lasts longer than attending
relevant presentations/workshops, reading Huerta, Bishop, Duncan, Hus, and Lord (2012) to
the literature, etc. counter this type of concern [But see Mayes,
F Disorder not accounted for by other Black, and Tierney (2013)]. In this regard, the
conditions (e.g., continuation of newly added disorder of disruptive mood dysregu-
DSM-IV-TR Confusion Disorder; being
a member of a DSM-5 workgroup)
lation is aimed at reducing the high prevalence of
Specify Psychiatrist, psychologist, other mental
childhood bipolar disorder, by giving an option for
if health professional, other stakeholder, or, diagnosis applicable to nonepisodic irritability.
most harmfully, patient Kupfer et al. continued that PTSD has been
switched to a trauma/stress chapter, and now has
four symptom clusters instead of three. For depres-
to be wary in every step of the way in assessment sion, the bereavement exclusion has been removed
and diagnosis, especially for the disorders that to allow for care of those in mourning who exhibit
might be attributed to patients based on its nosol- clinical depression. For substance use, cases of
ogy. At the same time, the DSM-5 project contin- abuse and dependence are now combined. They
ues to try to improve, in that it is considered a continued that the DSM-5 manual is “readily
“living document” and there will be changes. As updatable,” and Section III contains suggestions
Critiquing DSM-5 577

for further scrutiny, such as for personality disor- However, Paris (2013a) noted that the mental
der. Overall, Kupfer et al. (2013) concluded that disorders in the DSM-III were not associated with
the emphasis in the revision has been to give the differentiating causes, given the lack of scientific
manual “greater value” to all of medical practice. knowledge at that time. He argued that even for
the severest mental disorders, we still lack knowl-
edge of etiology, which needs to be disorder-spe-
Critiquing DSM-5 cific and explanatory. Moreover, rather than
reflecting scientific origins, the categories are
General Critique work products of expert DSM committees.
Therefore, the DSM-5 is still struggling to create
First (2014) argued that changes to the DSM valid categories that reflect psychiatric realities in
must be empirically derived. For example, the nature. Also, researchers are still seeking critical
changes proposed for personality disorder (PD; “biological markers” for the categories. Therefore,
Krueger, Hopwood, Wright, & Markon, 2014) we should not reify the disorders in the manual.
are innovative and based on research, but they They are not truly distinct from all normal varia-
changed over the years of the DSM-5 revision tions in behavior. They do overlap, too.
process. The notion that the final version for PD The consequences in using in psychiatry a
should be accepted because its structure is con- diagnostic manual such as the DSM-5 merit con-
gruent with the Five Factor Model (FFM) of per- cern. The public is diagnosed using a manual that
sonality is disputed (Widiger, 2011). is over-inclusive and pathologizes problems in liv-
Lilienfeld (2014) also advocated for a scien- ing. The DSM-5’s long term solution to use diag-
tific foundation for the DSM. He was uncertain nostic dimensions will not solve its problems, in
whether decisions regarding somatic symptom that this approach runs its own risk of over-inclu-
disorder and dissociative identity disorder met siveness. The DSM’s problems could affect the
this bar. He decried the sacrifice of scientific evi- public by (a) leading to undeserving medication
dence to the need for clinical utility in how the for normal people, (b) their stigmatization, and (c)
DSM is constructed. Yet he acknowledged that unwarranted long term, negative consequences.
many DSM categories will be a hybrid of scien- For Paris (2013a), psychiatric categories are
tific and practical considerations. He emphasized constellations of signs and symptoms structured
that the construct of categories of mental illness into syndromes, rather than being disease enti-
(natural kinds) in comparison to a dimensional ties, despite the DSM’s goal to create valid psy-
model is itself dubious. chiatric disorders. However, clinicians generally
do not think in terms of signs and symptom lists.
Rather, they typically think in terms of proto-
Paris (2013) types, or ideal cases, to which they try to match
their patients. The ICD-10 (World Health
Product Paris has written two books in 2013 on Organization, 2007; and forthcoming ICD-11)
the DSM-5 that deserve careful scrutiny. In Paris diagnostic system uses this approach, and, as
(2013a), he pointed out both where the DSM well, Frances (2013a) advocated for it. This
generally has weaknesses and some specific seems to be a major clashing point in psychiatry,
problems with its newly minted disorders. The and the one that won’t be revolved soon.
DSM-III (American Psychiatric Association,
1980) had been a significant advance, given its Comment However, I add that the research indi-
rigor in defining disorders with well-described cates that the reliability of prototype diagnoses
signs and symptoms so that, relative to the origi- might not fare as well as the polythetic (symptom
nal DSM and the follow-up DSM-II, the reliabil- and cluster) approach used in the DSMs.
ity related to its disorders increased and also Nevertheless, it could be argued that if valid diag-
theoretical dogma was removed. nostic categories can be found closer to valid psy-
578 22 DSM-5: Basics and Critics

chiatric etiology, a prototype approach to Paris reflected that, as science progresses,


describing the categories might be easier to use psychiatric diagnosis will become more accurate.
and more valid than a symptom/cluster polythetic Also, it will be shaped by a new initiative that is
approach. Also, consider that, presently, the psy- “unproven” to date. The initiative is on “Research
chiatric disorder categories have “fuzzy” edges Domain Criteria” (RDoC), which do not consider
so that their clear-cut use is not guaranteed categories in diagnosis (Insel et al., 2010). The
(Livesley, 2011). Clearly, this sticking point RDoC emphasizes five broad spectra—Negative
might be intractable and, as with other ones dis- Valence Systems, Positive Valence Systems,
cussed in the present work, a combined, hybrid Cognitive Systems, Systems for Social Processes,
approach might ultimately be the best. and Arousal/Regulatory Systems—in relation to
biology and brain-based data, in particular. Paris
Process Paris (2013a) continued by discussing (2013a) criticized the RDoC for its biological
the construction of the DSM-5 in its workgroups. emphasis. It is fair to say that the type of broad
He noted that, aside from failing to prepare a spectra that will result from further work in this
source book on the literature involved in decision- regard should also consider factors that are bio-
making, as had been the case for the DSM-IV, the psychosocial in nature.
drafts were not sent to possible opponents to the
proposals, as had been the case for the DSM-IV Definition Paris (2013a) elaborated on the defi-
(First, 2010). Also, the full draft was not pre- nition of mental disorder. His concerns related to
sented to independent experts for review, thereby the boundaries between disease or illness and
sacrificing the important process of peer review. subclinical reactions to life stressors. Aside from
Paris noted that the field trials were rushed in the problem that the definition should be clear and
order to publish the final version in 2013, because rigorous enough to avoid overdiagnosis, he noted
the manual had already been delayed by the that any psychiatric definition requires judgment.
vociferous objections to many of its proposed For example, Wakefield (1992) defined mental
changes once it was made public in 2010. I note disorder in terms of the construct of harmful dys-
that in looking over some of the retractions in the function, which cannot be strictly objective, espe-
proposals occasioned by the criticisms, some cially for determining what is harmful.
were consistent with the criticisms raised by I would add that Wakefield’s definition (also
myself, by Michael First, and by colleagues in see Wakefield, 2013) considers dysfunction per-
the special issue that First and I co-edited in 2010 haps too strictly as evolutionary mechanisms
on the DSM-5 draft in the journal Psychological gone awry, and so rendering activities of daily
Injury and Law (PIL). However, as shall be living impaired. From a biopsychosocial per-
shown later, the final version of the DSM-5 still spective, a dysfunction might be causatively
contains difficulties for the area of psychological linked to a complex that includes biological
injury and law. mechanisms, but these do not have to be evolu-
Paris (2013a) noted that the DSM-5 field trials tionary nor initiatory. Rather, if they are involved,
were conducted under a tight deadline with lack they also could be exacerbatory byproducts of
of funding, rendering them “inadequate.” psychosocial aspects, or minor.
Moreover, the rigor in the methods used is a far
cry from the real world of clinical practice, so Conclusion Paris (2013a) continued that mental
that the reliabilities obtained do not reflect what processes cannot be reduced to a brain-based
happens in mental health community use. Finally, agenda. He opined that mental processes can be
the levels considered as “acceptable” reliabilities studied on their own terms, and that “mind is an
in the DSM-5 (Kraemer, Kupfer, Clarke, Narrow, emergent property” (p. 75). The psychological
& Regier, 2012) do not reach the accepted processes of the person constitute a complex
standards in most academic journals. system having simpler components from which
Critiquing DSM-5 579

higher-order components emerge and, moreover, Table 22.5 Mental health medical industrial complex
they are “not fully determined” by the lower- Component Description
order components. Millions of people Captive, needy market wanting
Although not explicitly framing it this way, I mentally ill magic bullets
note that Paris is describing brain and behavior in Pharmaceutical Seeks increasing profits,
industry e.g., by supporting expansion
terms of nonlinear dynamical systems theory (products) of DSMs
(NLDST; for example, see Young, 2011). Service-industry Health insurance/managed care
Psychiatrists and neuroscientists are becoming (for profit) would rather pay for drugs that
aware of the self-organizing properties of the are cheaper than psychosocial
whole in psychological and neuronal processes. treatment
However, it is difficult to translate this perspec- Health care They are either acting for-profit or
system trying to reduce public costs,
tive into a classificatory psychiatric nosology. depending on jurisdiction.
Nevertheless as shall be suggested below, adopt- Mentally ill caught in middle
ing a systems perspective might facilitate creat- National politics Influence-peddling, lobbying,
ing a valid hybrid categorical and dimensional campaign financing, and conflicts
of interest all tolerated and also
understanding of psychopathology, leading the
they are common in contrast
way toward an integrated diagnostic system. to lack of voice given to
Paris (2013a) concluded his book with cogent non-pharmaceutical industry
points. Among them, the greatest danger of the and to patients
DSM-5 is its potential to overpathologize. He Advertising/mass Marketing directly to consumer,
media even for pseudo-disorders. Also,
supported the search for biological markers to
marketing to new users of
help arrive at more valid diagnostic categories patent-expiring medications. “There
and their clinically-meaningful cut-off points. He are financial incentives for DSM
asked for better psychometrics for assessing psy- authors to create new disorders”
chopathology, which I note is an important point National mental Supports research that ends up a
health “default” tax-payer subsidy to Big
for psychology and the role it can play in evolv- organizations Pharma
ing a better psychiatric classification approach. Grant reviewers have likely Big
At the level of approach to mental disorder, Paris Pharma and DSM ties
(2013a) argued that psychiatry must function Popular demand Passive public acceptance of
from the biopsychosocial perspective, which is in medication-first approach to
mental health. Few or no lobbyists
strong agreement with my own views. for alternate approaches, such as
psychotherapy
Academic Have become entrepreneurial with
Paris and Phillips (2013) medical centers “collosal” conflicts of interest,
with DSM participation
Need Big Pharma money
These authors co-edited a book on the concepts
American DSM a primary source of income,
and controversies behind the construction of the Psychiatric so changes leading to new
DSM-5. In his chapter, Shorter (2013) presented Association editions help sales. But still
the processes underlying the historical develop- conservative bias
ment of the different editions. He emphasized Adapted from Sadler (2013)
that the process of consensus in workgroups
dominated category construction. Sadler (2013) “open source” classification of mental disorder,
positioned the DSM project in the middle of the with changes conditional on appropriate testing.
“mental health medical industrial complex” Perhaps with tongue in cheek, Paris (2013b)
(MHMIC; see Table 22.5). Phillips (2013a) related psychiatry’s embrace of neuroscience ide-
added that, aside from the 10 elements of the ology as “internist envy.”
MHMIC listed by Sadler, another would be the Kinghorn (2013) maintained that the DSM
medical model. Sadler (2013) advocated for an should refrain from defining mental disorder until
580 22 DSM-5: Basics and Critics

more is known neurobiologically and psychologi- processes in disease are, therefore, multiple and
cally. Moreover, the concepts of function and intertwined (Kendler, 2012, p. 385).
dysfunction need to be clearer. Porter (2013)
emphasized the biopsychosocial model, in that bio-
logical, psychological, and social factors all con- Comment
tribute to illness. He advocated for psychosocial
research in nosological science, as well as inclusion The general critique of the DSM-5 has raised
of patient perspectives. Whooley and Horwitz important issues that cast doubt on the validity both
(2013) noted that although the DSM-5 is considered of its process and product. However, the Paris books
a living document, the manner in which its revisions point to ways that both can be improved. Some of
will be undertaken has not been clarified. the major criticisms of the DSM-5 include its
Frances (2013b) exhorted the field to be prag- embedding in the mental health medical industrial
matic and to use clinical common sense. Neither complex and the way the working groups func-
the biological reductionist nor rationalist social tioned. Its reliability as evaluated in the field trials is
constructionist models are adequate to the task of contested. The categories that comprise it might not
creating a psychiatric classification system. The even be represented the best way (it is polythetical
DSM should work from a utilitarian, instrumen- rather than prototypical). They do not have their eti-
tal epistemological stance. The concept of mental ology explained, nor do they have signature mark-
disorder defies valid definition, and there are so ers. Indeed, its concept of mental disorder is at
many mental disorders in the DSM-5 (about issue. The DSM-5 is perceived as overpathologiz-
300), diagnostic faddism gets in the way. ing, not being user-friendly, and not considering the
Pierre (2013) concurred that the DSM-5 pro- patient perspective. The emphasis given to the bio-
motes overdiagnosis, but also referred to under- psychosocial and systems approach in the Paris
diagnosis in critical arenas (e.g., major depression books is quite consistent with my orientation to how
in primary care settings). Diagnostic classifica- the DSM-5 can be improved, as shown below.
tion needs to find a balance between “lumpers”
and “splitters” (grouping or separating catego-
ries, respectively). Also, it needs to balance the Others
tendencies to minimize false negatives in diagno-
sis while guarding against creating false positives Frances and Widiger (2012) took a sanguine view
(i.e., improper attribution of normality and disor- of the DSM-5, and cite evidence for “diagnostic
der, respectively). Mishara and Schwartz (2013) inflation” (Kessler & Wang, 2008; Moffitt et al.,
argued that, in psychiatry, the patient’s phenom- 2010). They likened the situation to a diagnostic
enology has been minimized in relation to clini- epidemic. Because of the danger, diagnostic con-
cal and research endeavor. servatism is needed. Frances and Widiger noted
Phillips (2013b) referred to the need for the that the field trials were inadequate, especially
field to examine psychiatric conditions from the for radical new proposals (First, 2011). Any pro-
point of view of complexity theory (e.g., Bechtel posal for further revision should be vetted by
& Richardson, 2010; Kendler, 2012). The whole “severe” critical review in parallel with publica-
cannot be reduced to its parts nor can each part be tion of the proposals, and with risk/benefit analy-
analyzed by itself without considering all the sis considered for each one. The best organization
parts in the system. Parts lose their independence to undertake this task should be independent of
in an integrated system, so that disease cannot be the American Psychiatric Association.
reduced to the biological. In terms of etiology, a Frances (2013c) considered that the preva-
complexity approach considers that systems lence of mental disorder diagnosis would increase
compose, decompose, and reassemble the wholes due to the changes in the DSM-5. However, its
involved in the system. Multiple risk factors are principle chair, David Kupfer, disagreed and
involved, both as direct causal agents and mutually- argued there even might be a decreased preva-
influencing interacting ones. The etiological lence (Torjesen, 2013).
Critiquing DSM-5 581

Some have given the DSM-5 a “fatal diagnosis” It exhibits conceptual confusing on, for example,
for its overreach (Gornall, 2013), but others main- in its dimensional construct. Science is even left
tain that its problem relates to its use by stakehold- aside, for example, in the decision to keep an 18+
ers. That is, clinicians could use it too loosely; but, year criterion for antisocial personality disorder,
further, each of regulators, insurers, and attorneys, but not other ones.
in particular, could use it too loosely, as well (Berk, In general, Blashfield, Keeley, Flanagan, and
2013). One solution for Berk is for clinicians to con- Miles (2014) noted that the DSM-5 did not attain
duct comprehensive clinical assessments before its goals. Among other recommendations, they
arriving at diagnosis, a point that I emphasize below. called for a reduction in political bias (e.g., in the
Cosgrove and colleagues have queried the work groups).
colonization of the DSM workgroup/panel mem- Joober (2013) argued for a combined categori-
bers by the pharmaceutical industry and the cal and dimensional approach to psychiatric clas-
inherent conflicts of interest that they had not sification. Given that the goal of classification is
declared (Cosgrove & Krimsky, 2013; Cosgrove to have it based on etiology so that treatment can
& Wheeler, 2013). They maintained that the be facilitated, there is no evidence that a dimen-
transparency had been insufficient in the DSM- sional approach is superior in this regard. Joober
5’s development (e.g., about speaker fees). They continued that even if a disorder is heteroge-
queried the hegemony of the biopsychiatric neously expressed, it still could have simple cau-
approach in creation of the new disorder of pre- sation. For example, the one label of schizophrenia
menstrual dysphoria (PMDD; Cosgrove & captures better its polygenic (pleiotropic) nature
Wheeler, 2013). Also, they gave the example of than the multiple intermediate endophenotypes
how the pharmaceutical industry repackages involving it that have been proposed.
patent-expiring drugs to meet new disorders and There is concern that the symptom clusters of the
their impending prescriptions, such as has been DSM mental disorders are more heterogenous than
the case for one anti-depressant for PMDD. homogenous, casting doubt on the validity of the
Gordon and Cosgrove (2013) addressed the diagnoses involved. Khoury, Langer, and Pagnini
ethics of DSM-5. Ethical use of a psychiatric (2014) argued that direct descriptions of an individ-
diagnostic manual should assure its acceptable ual’s set of phenomenological experiences provide
reliability and validity. They queried whether better clinical insight for treatment than a nosologi-
other diagnostic approaches accomplish this bet- cal category. Fried, Nesse, Zivin, Guille, and Sen
ter than the DSM-5, given its categorical orienta- (2014) found that nine symptoms of major depres-
tion. Also, they addressed the ethics of the work sive disorder (MDD) in the DSM-5 were differen-
groups that developed the DSM-5, in that its tially associated with six risk factors, so that
members did not fully disclose their financial symptom summation procedures are “obfuscating.”
links to pharmaceutical companies. Moreover, the Wakefield (2013) is given the final word in
consensus approach in the DSM-5 work groups this section. He not only advocated for his con-
might have led to categories being included in the cept of harmful dysfunction in understanding
DSM-5 because of economical drivers rather than mental disorder but also for understanding the
ones related to scientific validity. role of context in this regard. Wakefield and
Blumenthal-Barby (2013) contended that the First (2012) had shown that context is consid-
DSM-5 has expanded invalidly its nosology, for ered in a majority of DSM diagnostic catego-
example, by failing in some cases to distinguish ries, but it can be improved in this regard. As
disordered from non-disordered conditions in mentioned, harmful dysfunction refers to evolu-
people requiring help. It leads to overdiagnosis tionarily important psychological mechanisms
and false positives, and increases the probability and also dysfunction in them according to
of inappropriate pharmacological management. socially evaluated effects. I note that Wakefield
It could medicalize and trivialize mental health. (2013)’s work on context and social consider-
Its decisions on some changes appear value- ations together supports a biopsychosocial
based and without validating empirical support. approach to mental disorder.
582 22 DSM-5: Basics and Critics

Forensic Critique especially to avoid implying that those diagnosed


have “diminished” behavioral control. First con-
Thomas (2013) queried whether the DSM-5 has cluded that, at least from the wording in the
been sufficiently vetted for its forensic-related con- DSM-5 draft, it was unclear to what extent an
text. It might lead to unexpected surprises in court. equivalent process had been followed.
In terms of specific diagnoses, she reviewed prob- To conclude, the DSM-5 has its forensic limita-
lem with the DSM-5’s approach to PTSD and NCD tions (Willis & Gold, 2014). It was not developed
(neurocognitive disorder). For PTSD, she argued to meet all the “technical needs” of legal systems.
that removal of the entry criterion of having a sub- It is an imperfect product, the forensic and legal
jective emotional response to the event at issue com- limitations of which might only be discovered
plicates establishing causality in the forensic context. through its use in practice (Appelbaum, 2014).
For NCD, Thomas criticized the DSM-5’s exclusion
of a category for moderate NCD. Also, use of self-
report or knowledgeable informants about any cog- DSM-5 Field Trial Critique
nitive decline, as permitted in the DSM-5, might not
be reliable. Finally, the DSM’s understanding of Freedman et al. (2013) reviewed the results of the
impairment is especially clinical, which might be DSM-5 field trials, and they reported mixed
different than that in the forensic context. results. Validity cannot be established without reli-
Wortzel (2013) argued that, for the DSM-5, ability, which in this case was determined by two
there is room for squabbles both about categories different trained clinicians seeing patients up two
and dimensions. There will be effects in both crimi- week apart, one time each. Category reliability
nal and civil proceedings. The adversarial system was calculated using the intraclass kappa statistic.
uses opposing experts who already have enough For some major DSM-5 disorders, such as
reason to disagree. If the experts criticize the DSM-5 schizophrenia, “good” kappa statistical results
changes, they risk being considered practitioners for reliability were obtained. But for others, such
who are outdated. If they support them, they risk as major depressive disorder, the results pre-
criticisms related to using a system that is too novel. sented an “obvious” problem. For some new
The courts will become increasingly skeptical and additions to the DSM-5, such as “mixed anxiety
cynical about mental health testimony. and depression,” the kappa levels were unaccept-
The solution to this quandary according to able, such as for disruptive mood disorder
Wortzel (2013) is to conduct meticulous and (Freedman et al., 2013). Results were acceptable
transparent forensic assessments, a point with for others that were modifications of DSM-IV
which I agree. Moreover, diagnosis usually is categories (e.g., PTSD, the results being in the
secondary in forensic cases to the legal question higher end). The new autism disorder spectrum
at hand. The expert needs to show that, whether fared well. Other disorders relevant to psycho-
the DSM-IV or DSM-5 is used, the conclusions logical injury (major neurocognitive disorder,
offered about legally-relevant constructs are not complex somatic symptom disorder) were
altered. Also, experts “should be prepared to deemed to have “good” reliability.
identify and defend against” any use of the The DSM-5 field trial results were published
DSM-5 in court that is “inappropriate or unjusti- in a set of three articles (Clarke et al., 2013;
fied” [presumably in the work by the other side]. Narrow et al., 2013; Regier, Narrow et al., 2013),
First (2010) also noted the differences in using Jones (2012) had previously published a critique.
the DSM in clinical and legal applications. He In the following, I review these articles.
explained that the caution in using the DSM-IV Clarke et al. (2013) reported that the field
in forensic cases was prepared by a committee of trials were conducted over a 7- to 10-month time
forensic experts charged with reducing its poten- frame. They did not give the dates, but inspection
tial for misuse. Moreover, the committee of their article reveals that the trials started in
reviewed the diagnostic criteria in the DSM-IV 2010 and so the clinicians were trained on an
Critiquing DSM-5 583

earlier draft. There were 11 sites involved that Table 22.6 DSM-5 dimensional cross-cutting symptom
assessment for adult patients
used 279 clinicians and 2246 patients, most of
whom were assessed two times. Number of
Symptom domain questions Content examples
The study used a stratified random sampling
Depression 2 Down
approach related to a minimal set of target diag-
Anger 1 Irritated
noses, with up to seven target diagnoses per site.
Mania 2 Sleeping less but still
This means that the study in the academic centers energetic
involved was quite unlike the typical clinical set- Anxiety 3 Worried
ting in which any patient might be expressing any Somatic distress 2 Unexplained pains
of hundreds of conditions in the DSM. Training Suicide 1 Thoughts of
of the clinicians was extensive, which also might self-hurting
not to correspond to typical clinical practice. Psychosis 2 Hearing things other
A priori, the kappa levels for excellent, very people couldn’t
good, good, questionable, and unacceptable reli- Sleep 1 Sleep quality
Memory 1 In learning new
ability were set, respectively, at the points >0.8,
information
>0.6, >0.4, >0.2, and <0.2. Reliability for dimen- Repetitive 1 Unpleasant ones
sional measures used parametrical intraclass cor- thoughts
relation coefficients. It is noted that the kappa Repetitive 1 Driven
levels for the different degrees of reliability for behaviors
the DSM-5 field trials were less stringent than for Dissociation 1 Detached/distant
the DSM-IV (Jones, 2012). from self
Personality 2 Not knowing who
Regier, Narrow, et al. (2013) provided the
really are
details of the DSM-5 field trials. Over the sites
Substance use 3 Drinking/smoking/
that tested adult populations, sufficient data were using without a
gathered for 15 separate diagnoses. Aside from doctor’s prescription,
the results already presented in Freedman et al. in greater amounts or
longer than
(2013), reviewed above, it is noteworthy that
prescribed (e.g.,
mild TBI obtained questionable reliability (in painkillers, cocaine)
contrast to major and minor NCD). Mainstays in
diagnosis, such as generalized anxiety disorder
and antisocial personality disorder, were in the clinician-evaluated psychosis and suicidality, and
questionable range. Therefore, given the already these are not discussed here.] The cross-cutting
reported low results for major depressive disor- measure contained 23 questions for adults that
der, the major internalization categories did not involved 12 domains. The items were chosen by
fare well. The lack of reliability for antisocial the DSM-5 workgroups and also by an instru-
personality disorder has important forensic impli- ment development study group, usually de novo.
cations. For the child/adolescent sites, sufficient The reliability results in Regier, Narrow, et al.
data were obtained for eight target disorders and (2013) supported use of the self-report cross-
only four were not questionable/unacceptable. cutting measure in DSM-5 diagnostic assess-
Narrow et al. (2013) reported the reliability ments. However, I am not sure exactly what the
for a newly-developed cross-cutting symptom measure concerns. I find it surprising that the
measure. The measure was elaborated as part of items simply represent a short list of major
the goal to broaden the DSM approach beyond psychiatric symptoms, each related to specific
narrow categories. Existing measures were used disorders, so that they are not cross-cutting in the
in a second round of self-report assessment by sense of overlapping multiple disorders. Perhaps
patients. However, the focus of my comments it would be best to refer to the instrument as a
concerns the first instrument (see Table 22.6). general psychiatric screening device rather than a
[Other assessment devices were related to cross-cutting one.
584 22 DSM-5: Basics and Critics

Jones (2012) critiqued the DSM-5 field trials apply; for example, it still appears a dualist
by indicating its trial cancelations, its disorgani- conception, as evidenced by examination of the
zation, its insufficient validity testing, and its pro- characteristics that Wakefield ascribes to the
cedural lacunae, such as high clinician evaluator two components of the term (social and evolu-
attrition rates. A second phase was dropped on tionary). We need to use a construct that does
any updates or changes to the draft proposals. not separate the components of mental disorder,
The population examined did not include milder but considers them systemically. In this regard,
levels of conditions, which makes the field trials I propose that terminology that is consistent
problematic in light of the lowered bar for diag- with the biopsychosocial model fits the require-
nostic thresholds for some of the disorders. ment. Moreover, the term is integral to work in
mental disorder in disciplines other than psy-
chiatry, such as psychology. Finally, the term
Defining Mental Disorder applies to not only mental distress but to func-
in the DSM-5 tionalities impacted by them. Therefore, by
specifying better the relationship of symptom-
In the DSM-5 The DSM enterprise and, indeed, atology to impairment and disability, in particu-
the field of psychiatry, in general, have long lar, some of the lacks in the definition of mental
acknowledged the difficulty if not impossibility of disorder in the DSM-5 might be rectified.
defining mental disorder. Just as natural kinds of In the table in which I present a revised
disorders are difficult to carve at the joints, so is approach to defining mental disorder, generally, I
psychiatric abnormality difficult conceptually to work toward a better definition of mental disor-
separate from ranges of normality. The various der along the lines just mentioned. Also, I par-
descriptions of the changes to the DSM-5 do not tially integrate Wakefield’s (1992, 2013) concept
mention change in definition of mental disorder. of harmful dysfunction. Specifically, I try to sep-
However, closer inspection of the definition in the arate in the definition the constructs of distress,
DSM-5 compared to that of the DSM-IV-TR (see disturbance, dysfunction, impairment, handicap,
Table 22.7) reveals a set of minor changes in the and disability. Further, I acknowledge the role of
definition that serves to tighten and clarify it to a judgment in deciding upon mental disorder.
degree. Necessarily, I emphasize the need to base the
decision on relevant, reliable information.
New Definition That being said, the psychiatric Finally, I refer to the domains that might be
field does not have one integrated acceptable involved, as well as the processes.
definition (even as acknowledged in the DSM-5). As for related factors, I consider causality and
However, in order to improve the DSM definition treatment. I underscore the value of clinical util-
of mental disorder, in Young (2014), I considered ity in diagnosis. Also, the role of factors, such as
the various terms in the field related to impair- sex, gender, and age, is given their due. Overall,
ment (e.g., disability). Also, I sought a definition the definition that I offer for mental disorder
grounded in the biopsychosocial model. reflects a biopsychosocial approach. In the fol-
The major concern about the existing defini- lowing, I turn to how disability is evaluated
tion of mental disorder is that it is not adequate according to the DSM-5.
and does not capture the essence of mental dis-
order. It is a definition of convenience that
allows for communication about mental disor- The WHODAS 2.0
der, but lacks the scientific rigor needed for its
justification. Wakefield (1992, 2013) has pro- The WHODAS-2.0 (World Health Organization
vided alternate approaches to defining mental Disability Assessment Schedule 2.0, World
disorder (as harmful dysfunction). However, the Health Organization; Üstün et al., 2010) has been
ambiguity and circularity in the definition still recommended for use by the DSM-5.
The WHODAS 2.0 585

Table 22.7 Definition of mental disorder in the DSMs (and a proposal)


Source Definition
DSM-IV-TR The clinically significant behavioral/psychological syndrome/pattern is associated with distress
(e.g., painful symptom)/disability (impairment in important functional area(s)) or with
significantly increased risk of death/pain/disability/important loss of freedom. Not simply
expectable/culturally-sanctioned response. Whatever its original cause, it is a behavioral/
psychological/biological dysfunctional manifestation. Neither deviant behavior (e.g., political,
religious, sexual) nor deviance/conflict is disorder, except if it is symptomatic of a dysfunction as
described.
DSM-5 Syndrome characterized by a clinically significant dysfunctional disturbance in cognition/
emotion regulation/behavior in psychological, biological, or developmental mental processes.
Associated with significant distress or disability in activity (social/occupational/other). An
expectable/culturally-approved response is not a mental disorder. Socially deviant behavior
also is not, unless dysfunctional as described.
Proposal Primary Definition. A mental health disorder is a behavioral syndrome (or pattern or
network of symptoms) in context that is characterized as a clinically significant
disturbance, distress, or dysfunction potentially evaluated as harmful to the individual,
to others, or to both. It is acknowledged that establishing clinical significance requires a
judgment of well-informed (and trained) individuals based on the gathering of reliable
and relevant evidence. Primary areas of expression of the disturbance or dysfunction
include cognition, mood, relations, interactions, self-regulation, and other behavior
and its organization. Primary processes that might be involved include the biological, social,
and personal (i.e., psychological), as well as the developmental. Primary impairments
usually involved are in social, occupational, or other important functional activities.
These might be judged to meet thresholds of disability. Note that mental disorder,
impairment, and disability are not handicaps; the latter only refers to possible perception
by the individual or by others.
Related Factors. A mental disorder normally should be demarcated for original (and
perpetuating) cause, both normatively in the population and individually for the patient.
However, when knowledge either of the science or of the person precludes causal
understanding, a mental disorder still can be attributed. A mental disorder normally
should be amenable to intervention or treatment, and knowing the cause, and also
isolating it as a reliable and valid category, would help in this regard. However, once
more, knowledge of the science or of the person might limit effective intervention/
treatment.
• Nevertheless, the ultimate goal of the mental health professional, and/or the society in
which they work, is to develop scientifically-informed and clinically useful mental
disorder categories, dimensions, and their combinations (e.g., in diagnostic manuals) that
help individuals diagnosed with mental disorders to stabilize/recover and have (or return
to) a healthy, functional lifestyle.
• Mental disorder has both common elements in its definition and language that allows
its application differently to individuals, for example, depending on their context,
sex (gender), majority/minority status, culture, age, history, developmental
level, socioeconomic status, different informants, and societal and political
considerations.
• Examples that do not necessarily qualify as mental disorders include (a) an
expectable or culturally-approved response to a common stressor or to a common loss,
such as in the case of the death of a family member, or (b) socially-deviant behavior
(e.g., sexual, religious, political) or conflicts that only express discord of the individual
in society.
• Overall, a mental disorder is a developmental biopsychosocial (biopersonalsocial)
expression that has a (developmental) biopsychosocial etiology or causality and also
needs a developmental biopsychosocial intervention/treatment.
586 22 DSM-5: Basics and Critics

Instrument Table 22.8 (continued)


Category Question
Üstün et al. (2010) developed the WHODAS-2.0 Life Taking care of household
as a standardized cross-cultural measure of activities— responsibilities?
Household Doing the most important
adaptive functioning and disability in six major
ones well?
life domains (see Table 22.8). The latter are tied
Getting all of it done that you
to the International Classification of Functioning, had to?
Disability and Health (ICF, World Health Getting it done on time?
Organization, 2001), and they include: (a) cogni- Life activities— [Answer only if you work
tion; (b) mobility; (c) self-care; (d) getting along School/work (paid, self-employed) or go to
(social interaction); (e) life activities (including school]
at work); and (f) participation in society. The Difficulty in day-to-day work/
school?
schedule includes 36 items and several forms
In most important tasks well?
(e.g., self-report, interviewer-administered) as
Getting all of it done that you
well as a reduced version (12 items). The DSM-5 had to?
Getting it done on time?
Table 22.8 World Health organization disability assess- Participation in Problem in joining in
ment schedule 2.0 (WHODAS 2.0) society community activities?
Category Question Problem because of barriers or
hindrances?
Question About your difficulties due to
health/mental health Problem living with dignity
conditions. Answer with one because of the attitudes/
of the responses to these actions of others?
questions (none, mild, How much time spent on
moderate, severe, extreme, or health condition/
cannot do). consequences?
Understanding and Concentrating for ten How much emotionally
communication minutes? affected?
Remembering important How much drain on financial
things? resources of you/family?
Learning new task? How much of a problem does
Generally understanding? family have because of your
health?
Starting/maintaining
conversation? How much of a problem did
you have in relaxation/
Getting around Standing 30 min or more?
pleasureful activities?
Standing up?
Adapted from World Health Organization, 2012.
Moving inside home?
Measuring health and disability: manual for WHO
Leaving home? Disability Assessment Schedule (WHODAS 2.0), World
Walking a long distance (e.g., Health Organization 2010, Geneva
1 k)?
Self-care Washing?
contains only the 36-item, self-report version.
Dressing?
The self-administered version requires 5–10 min
Eating?
to complete. Each item is answered on a 5-point
Staying alone a few days?
scale from none to extreme. The timeframe for
Getting along with Dealing with strangers?
people Keeping a friend?
ratings is the “past 30 days,” because some
Getting along with people respondents have “problems with remembering”
close to you? dysfunction that occurred more than one month
Making a new friend? previously. In testing the instrument, respondents
Sexual activities? reported difficulties with—increased effort, dis-
(continued) comfort/pain, slowness, and changes in how
The WHODAS 2.0 587

activities are undertaken. Whether by computer Gold (2014, p. 179) pointed out that although
or hand, simple scoring (summing answers) is the DSM-5 included the self-report version of the
used to obtain total scores, with the six domain WHODAS-2.0, clinicians can alter the ratings
scores also possible. The simple method would given if the evidence supports the change. Also,
seem to be the one of choice (DSM-5) for clini- for the clinician-rated version, the psychometric
cians. However, it does not come with norms. properties appear not to have been studied.
Results on the WHODAS-2.0 were calculated Therefore, there is no data on its “reliability and
with the populations tested in 19 countries. In each validity.” Consequently, in some forensic-related
site, there were four undefined groups labeled as: examinations, in some sense, careful use of the
apparent good health; people with physical disor- GAF is preferable to using the WHODAS-2.0,
ders; people with mental/emotional ones; and peo- especially given that the DSM-IV-TR is not being
ple with alcohol/drug use. The authors reported discarded for use by the DSM-5 (Gold, 2014).
that the WHODAS-2.0 schedule evidenced ade- (c) Further, the WHODAS-2.0 might not be
quate reliability and validity (for the observer/rater reliable for individuals having a high baseline
version scored with the complex method). As for before its need in an assessment. (d) The simple
differences among the four groups, they scored scoring method, the one that the DSM-5 points out
differently on items relevant to their condition or would be preferred by clinicians, has no normative
group description, indicating adequate face valid- values. (e) The WHODAS-2.0 confounds medical
ity for the instrument. Cut-off scores were not cal- and psychiatric impairment by trying to be global
culated, although IRT (Item Response Theory) and not differentiating them. (f) It does not exclude
analysis indicated that a score of 22 corresponded appropriately environmental context. (g) It lacks
to a population percentile of 80. This level would internal indices of validity. (g) Finally, the GAF is
appear to be the recommended clinically useful not going to disappear, because it is still required
cut score. It does make clinical sense, in that the in many disability assessment venues.
top 20 % of respondents on the instrument could The WHODAS-2.0 also is in the public
reasonably be termed disabled. Üstün et al. (2010) domain. Psychological tests in medical/legal
concluded that the WHODAS-2’s limitations contexts are generally only available to profes-
involve its lack of consideration of both bodily sionals, such as psychologists, rather than gener-
impairments and environmental factors. However, ally to the public. This helps maintain their
we add that, although the manual for the validity by preventing claimants from studying
WHODAS-2.0 concludes that reading it and doing for tests used in their assessments. Therefore, the
its exercises constitute sufficient user training, this WHODAS-2.0’s use in the forensic context
does not constitute sufficient training. appears compromised to begin with because of
its general availability.

Critique
Conclusion
Gold (2014) reviewed the characteristics and
limitations of the WHODAS-2.0 for use in dis- DSM-5 recommends the WHODAS-2.0 to assess
ability assessments. (a) She noted that although disability. It is a cross-culturally validated scale
the DSM-5 recommends it in the assessment of of 36 items split into six domains. However, it
global function and impairment instead of the has several properties that reduce its value in
GAF, it is placed in a section on emerging mea- some forensic assessments. Among them, it
sures only, and not in the text proper. (b) She confounds psychiatrically-related and physically-
noted issues with the psychometrics of the sched- related functional limitations. It does not assess
ule for clinician rating, and these issues apply to respondent validity. Its user qualifications appear
the proxy version, as well. not conservative enough.
588 22 DSM-5: Basics and Critics

Chapter Conclusions American Psychiatric Association. (1994). Diagnostic


and statistical manual of mental disorders (DSM-IV).
Washington, DC: Author.
The release of the DSM-5 was preceded by years American Psychiatric Association. (2000). Diagnostic
of criticisms and concerns and, surely, they will and statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM-
follow for more years now that the DSM-5 has IV-TR (4th ed., text rev.). Washington, DC: Author.
American Psychiatric Association. (2013a). Diagnostic
been published. I have shown general problems
and statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM-5
with the DSM-5 that have been described in the (5th ed.). Washington, DC: Author.
literature, as well as problems with specific disor- American Psychiatric Association. (2013b). Highlights of
ders. In order for it to achieve its goals of being changes from DSM-IV-TR-DSM-5. Retrieved from
http://www.dsm5.org/Documents/changes%20
clinically useful and based on extant research,
from%20dsm-iv-tr%20to%20dsm-5.pdf
e.g., for biomarkers, it needs to be open to input Appelbaum, P. S. (2014). Commentary: DSM-5 and
from clinicians, all stakeholders, forensic practi- forensic psychiatry. The Journal of the American
tioners, researchers, and patients. This will help in Academy of Psychiatry and the Law, 42, 136–140.
Bechtel, W., & Richardson, R. C. (2010). Discovering
developing a better definition for mental disorder
complexity. Decomposition and localization as
and also including in it better or more valid diag- strategies in scientific research. Cambridge, MA: MIT
nostic categories. As well, it will move it toward Press.
its goal of integrating a dimensional perspective. Berk, M. (2013). The DSM-5: Hyperbole, hope, or
hypothesis? BioMed Central Medicine, 11, 128.
However, only use of a stringent scientific
doi:10.1186/1741-7015-11-128.
approach and an open process in its construction Blashfield, R. K., Keeley, J. W., Flanagan, E. H., &
can help the DSM project realize its objectives. Miles, S. R. (2014). The cycle of classification:
As new iterations are developed for clinical use, DSM-I through DSM-5. Annual Review of Clinical
Psychology, 10, 25–51.
the kinds of difficulties and tensions described in
Blumenthal-Barby, J. S. (2013). Psychiatry’s new manual
this chapter should be addressed openly. (DSM-5): Ethical and conceptual dimensions. Journal
In the next two chapters of the present work, I of Medical Ethics, 40, 531–536.
examine more closely some of the major psychiat- Clarke, D. E., Narrow, W. E., Regier, D. A., Kuramoto, S. J.,
Kupfer, D. J., Kuhl, E. A., et al. (2013). DSM-5 field trials
ric disorders in the DSM-5 manual. I scrutinize the
in the United States and Canada, part I: Study design,
specific criteria for them. In addition, I conduct a sampling strategy, implementation, and analytic
literature review related to them. The chapters approaches. American Journal of Psychiatry, 170, 43–58.
include a preview of the ICD-11 for PTSD, and I Cosgrove, L., & Krimsky, S. (2013). A comparison of
DSM-IV and DSM-5 panel member’s financial asso-
compare that approach to the one in the DSM-5.
ciations with industry: A pernicious problem persists.
Most important, the chapters examine the RDoC PLoS Medicine, 9, e1001190. doi:10.1371/journal.
project, and the degree to which it can succeed in pmed.1001190.
its stated goal of establishing the neuroscientific Cosgrove, L., & Wheeler, E. E. (2013). Industry’s coloni-
zation of psychiatry: Ethical and practical implications
bases, in particular, of mental disorders toward
of financial conflicts of interest in the DSM-5.
creating a better psychiatric diagnostic system. Feminism & Psychology, 23, 93–106.
First, M. B. (2010). The PTSD stressor criterion as a bar-
rier to malingering: DSM-5 draft commentaries.
Psychological Injury and Law, 3, 255–259.
References First, M. B. (2011). DSM-5 proposals for mood disorders:
A cost-benefit analysis. Current Opinions in
Achenbach, T. M. (1991). Integrative guide for the 1991 Psychiatry, 24, 1–9.
CBCL/4–18, YSR, and TRF profiles. Burlington, VT: First, M. B. (2014). Empirical grounding versus innova-
University of Vermont, Department of Psychiatry. tion in the DSM-5 revision process: Implications for
Achenbach, T. M., & Rescorla, L. (2001). Manual for the the future. Clinical Psychology: Science and Practice,
ASEBA School-Age Forms & Profiles. Burlington, VT: 21, 262–268.
University of Vermont, Research Center for Children, Frances, A. (2013a). Essentials of psychiatric diagnosis:
Youth, & Families. Responding to the challenge of DSM-5. New York:
American Psychiatric Association. (1980). Diagnostic Guilford Press.
and statistical manual of mental disorders (3rd ed.). Frances, A. (2013b). DSM in philosophyland: Curiouser
Washington, DC: Author. and curiouser. In J. Paris & J. Phillips (Eds.), Making
References 589

the DSM-5: Concepts and controversies (pp. 95–103). hardware-software dichotomy with empirically based
New York: Springer Science + Business Media. pluralism. Molecular Psychiatry, 17, 377–388.
Frances, A. (2013c). The new somatic symptom disorder Kessler, R. C., & Wang, P. S. (2008). The descriptive epi-
in DSM-5 risks mislabeling many people as mentally demiology of commonly occurring mental disorders in
ill. British Medical Journal, 346. doi:10.1136/bmj. the United States. Annual Review of Public Health, 29,
f1580. 115–129.
Frances, A. (2013d). DSM-5 somatic symptom disorder. Khoury, B., Langer, E. J., & Pagnini, F. (2014). The DSM:
The Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 201, Mindful science or mindless power? A critical review.
530–531. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 602. doi:10.3389/
Frances, A. (2013e, June 11). DSM-5 badly flunks the fpsyg.2014.00602.
writing test. Psychiatric Times. Retrieved from Kinghorn, W. (2013). The biopolitics of defining “mental
http://www.psychiatrictimes.com/dsm-5-badly-flunks- disorder.”. In J. Paris & J. Phillips (Eds.), Making the
writing-test DSM-5: Concepts and controversies (pp. 47–61).
Frances, A., & Widiger, T. (2012). Psychiatric diagnosis: New York: Springer Science + Business Media.
Lessons from the DSM-IV past and cautions for the Kraemer, H. C., Kupfer, D. J., Clarke, D. E., Narrow,
DSM-5 future. Annual Review of Clinical Psychology, W. E., & Regier, D. A. (2012). DSM-5: How reliable
8, 109–130. is reliable enough? American Journal of Psychiatry,
Freedman, R., Lewis, D. A., Michels, R., Pine, D. S., 169, 13–15.
Schultz, S. K., Tamminga, C. A., et al. (2013). The ini- Krueger, R. F., Hopwood, C. J., Wright, A. G. C., &
tial field trials of DSM-5: New blooms and old thorns. Markon, K. E. (2014). DSM-5 and the path toward
American Journal of Psychiatry, 170, 1–5. empirically based and clinically useful conceptualiza-
Fried, E. I., Nesse, R. M., Zivin, K., Guille, C., & Sen, S. tion of personality and psychopathology. Clinical
(2014). Depression in more than the sum score of its Psychology: Science and Practice, 21, 245–261.
parts: Individual DSM symptoms have different risk Kupfer, D. J., Kuhl, E. A., & Regier, D. A. (2013).
factors. Psychological Medicine, 44, 2067–2076. DSM-5 – The future arrived. Journal of American
Gold, L. H. (2014). DSM-5 and the assessment of func- Medical Association, 309, 1691–1692.
tioning: The World Health Organization Disability Lilienfeld, S. O. (2014). DSM-5: Centripetal scientific
Assessment Schedule 2.0 (WHODAS 2.0). The and centrifugal antiscientific forces. Clinical
Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatric and Psychology: Science and Practice, 21, 269–279.
the Law, 42, 173–181. Livesley, W. J. (2011). The current state of personality
Gordon, R. M., & Cosgrove, L. (2013). Ethical consider- disorder classification. Journal of Personality
ations in the development and application of mental Disorders, 25, 269–278.
and behavioral nosologies: Lessons from DSM-5. Mayes, S. D., Black, A., & Tierney, C. D. (2013). DSM-5
Psychological Injury and Law, 6, 330–335. under-identifies PDDNOS: Diagnostic agreement
Gornall, J. (2013). DSM-5: A fatal diagnosis? British between the DSM-5, DSM-IV, and checklist for
Medicine Journal, 346. doi:10.1136/bmj.f3256. autism spectrum disorder. Research in Autism
Huerta, M., Bishop, S. L., Duncan, A., Hus, V., & Lord, C. Spectrum Disorders, 7, 298–306.
(2012). Application of DSM-5 criteria for autism McEwen, B. S., & Getz, L. (2013). Lifetime experiences,
spectrum disorder to three samples of children with the brain and personalized medicine: An integrative
DSM-IV diagnoses of pervasive developmental perspective. Metabolism, Clinical and Experimental,
disorder. American Journal of Psychiatry, 169, 62, S20–S26.
1056–1064. Mishara, A. L., & Schwartz, M. A. (2013). What does
Insel, T. R., Cuthbert, B. N., Garvey, M. A., Heinssen, phenomenology contribute to the debate about DSM-
R. K., Pine, D. S., Quinn, K. J., et al. (2010). Research 5? In J. Paris & J. Phillips (Eds.), Making the DSM-5:
domain criteria (RDoC): Toward a new classification Concepts and controversies (pp. 125–142). New York:
framework for research on mental disorders. American Springer Science + Business Media.
Journal of Psychiatry, 167, 748–751. Moffitt, T. E., Caspi, A., Taylor, A., Kokaua, J., Milne,
Jones, K. D. (2012). A critique of the DSM-5 field trials. B. J., Planczyk, G., et al. (2010). How common are
The Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 200, common mental disorders? Evidence that lifetime
517–519. prevalence rates are doubled by prospective versus
Joober, R. (2013). On the simple and the complex in psy- retrospective ascertainment. Psychological Medicine,
chiatry, with reference to DSM 5 and research domain 40, 899–909.
criteria. Journal of Psychiatry and Neuroscience, 38, Narrow, W. E., Clarke, D. E., Kuramoto, S. J., Kraemer,
148–151. H. C., Kupfer, D. J., Greiner, L., et al. (2013). DSM-5
Kendler, K. S. (2008). Explanatory models for psychiatric field trials in the United States and Canada, part III:
illness. American Journal of Psychiatry, 165, 695–702. Development and reliability testing of a cross-cutting
Kendler, K. S. (2012). The dappled nature of causes of symptom assessment for DSM-5. American Journal of
psychiatric illness: Replacing the organic-functional/ Psychiatry, 170, 71–82.
590 22 DSM-5: Basics and Critics

Paris, J. (2013a). The intelligent clinician’s guide to the Developing the World Health Organization Disability
DSM-5. New York: Oxford University Press. Assessment Schedule 2.0. Bulletin of the World Health
Paris, J. (2013b). The ideology behind DSM-5. In J. Paris Organization, 88, 815–823.
& J. Phillips (Eds.), Making the DSM-5: Concepts and Wakefield, J. C. (1992). Disorder as harmful dysfunction:
controversies (pp. 39–44). New York: Springer A conceptual critique of DSM-III-R’s definition of
Science + Business Media. mental disorder. Psychological Review, 99, 232–247.
Phillips, J. (2013a). The conceptual status of DSM-5 diag- Wakefield, J. C. (2013). The DSM-5 debate over the
noses. In J. Paris & J. Phillips (Eds.), Making the bereavement exclusion: Psychiatric diagnosis and the
DSM-5: Concepts and controversies (pp. 143–157). future of empirically supported treatment. Clinical
New York: Springer Science + Business Media. Psychology Review, 33, 825–845.
Phillips, J. (2013b). Conclusion. In J. Paris & J. Phillips Wakefield, J. C., & First, M. B. (2012). Validity of the
(Eds.), Making the DSM-5: Concepts and controver- bereavement exclusion to major depression: does
sies (pp. 159–175). New York: Springer the empirical evidence support the proposal to elimi-
Science + Business Media. nate the exclusion in DSM-5? World Psychiatry, 11,
Pierre, J. M. (2013). Overdiagnosis, underdiagnosis, syn- 3–10.
thesis: A dialectic for psychiatry and the DSM. In Whooley, O., & Horwitz, A. V. (2013). The paradox of
J. Paris & J. Phillips (Eds.), Making the DSM-5: professional success: Grand ambition, furious resis-
Concepts and controversies (pp. 105–124). New York: tance, and the derailment of the DSM-5 revision pro-
Springer Science + Business Media. cess. In J. Paris & J. Phillips (Eds.), Making the
Porter, D. (2013). Establishing normative validity for sci- DSM-5: Concepts and controversies (pp. 75–92).
entific psychiatric nosology: The significance of inte- New York: Springer Science + Business Media.
grating patient perspectives. In J. Paris & J. Phillips Widiger, T. A. (2011). A shaky future for personality dis-
(Eds.), Making the DSM-5: Concepts and controver- orders. Personality Disorders: Theory, Research, and
sies (pp. 63–74). New York: Springer Treatment, 2, 54–67.
Science + Business Media. Widiger, T. A., Frances, A. J., & Pincus, H. A. (1997).
Regier, D. A., Kuhl, E. A., & Kupfer, D. J. (2013). The DSM-IV sourcebook (Vol. 1–4). Washington, DC:
DSM-5: Classification and criteria change. World American Psychiatric Association.
Psychiatry, 12, 92–98. Willis, C. D., & Gold, L. H. (2014). Introduction to the
Regier, D. A., Narrow, W. E., Clarke, D. E., Kraemer, H. C., special section on DSM-5 and forensic psychiatry. The
Kuramoto, S. J., Kuhl, E. A., et al. (2013). DSM-5 field Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and
trials in the United States and Canada, part II: Test- the Law, 42, 132–135.
retest reliability of selected categorical diagnoses. World Health Organization. (2001). International classifi-
American Journal of Psychiatry, 170, 59–70. cation of functioning, disability and health. Geneva,
Sadler, J. Z. (2013). Considering the economy of DSM Switzerland: Author.
alternatives. In J. Paris & J. Phillips (Eds.), Making the World Health Organization. (2007). International
DSM-5: Concepts and controversies (pp. 21–38). Statistical Classification of Diseases and Related
New York: Springer Science + Business Media. Health Problems 10th Revision. Retrieved from http://
Sax, L. (2013, June 26). “Unspecified mental disorder?” www.who.int/classifications/icd/en/
That’s crazy. Psychiatry’s diagnostic bible has broad- Wortzel, H. S. (2013). The DSM-5 and forensic psychia-
ened the definition of mental illness to absurdity. Wall try. Journal of Psychiatric Practice, 13, 238–241.
Street Journal. Retrieved from http://online.wsj.com/ Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
article/SB10001424127887323844804578529030063 Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer
800200.html Science + Business Media.
Shorter, E. (2013). The history of DSM. In J. Paris & Young, G. (2014). Psychological injury and law II:
J. Phillips (Eds.), Making the DSM-5: Concepts and Implications for mental health policy and ethics.
controversies (pp. 3–19). New York: Springer Mental Health Law & Policy Journal, 3, 418–470.
Science + Business Media. Young, G., Lareau, C., & Pierre, B. (2014). One quintil-
Thomas, L. C. (2013). The DSM-5 and forensic relation- lion ways to have PTSD comorbidity:
ship status: It’s complicated. Psychological Injury and Recommendations for the disordered DSM-5.
Law, 6, 324–329. Psychological Injury and Law, 7, 61–74.
Torjesen, I. (2013). Architect of DSM-5 rejects claims it Young, G., & Yehuda, R. (2006). Understanding PTSD:
will lead to labelling of more people as mentally ill. Implications for court. In G. Young, A. W. Kane, &
British Medical Journal, 346. doi:10.1136/bmj.f3648. K. Nicholson (Eds.), Psychological knowledge in
Üstün, T. B., Chatterji, S., Konstanjsek, N., Rehm, J., court: PTSD, pain, and TBI (pp. 55–69). New York:
Kennedy, C., Epping-Jordan, J., et al. (2010). Springer Science + Business Media.
The DSM-5 and the RDoC: Grand
Designs and Grander Problems 23

personality disorder proposals in the DSM-5.


Chapter Introduction Another focus of the next chapter is on malin-
gering, especially because it was not changed
This chapter and the next one examine in depth much in the DSM-5, but merits much change.
some of the major categories of mental disorder Then, the last chapter of this two-chapter
in the DSM-5 (Diagnostic and Statistical Manual sequence on the DSM-5’s changes to its specific
of Mental Disorders, Fifth Edition; American disorders concludes with a comparison of the
Psychiatric Association, 2013), as well as their DSM-5’s and the ICD-11’s (International
criticisms. However, before beginning that pro- Statistical Classification of Diseases and Related
cess, it presents in depth details and criticisms of Health Problems, 11th Revision; World Health
the RDoC project (Research Domain Criteria; Organization, 2017) approaches to PTSD and
Insel et al., 2010; Insel & Lieberman, 2013). The related stress disorders.
RDoC is founded on the assumption that mental
illness concerns especially “brain function and
structure.” The RDoC is a project of the US Research Domain Criteria
NIMH (National Institute of Mental Health), and
it is meant to guide priorities in American federal Introduction
funding in mental health research. A second goal
of the RDoC project is to inform psychiatric Insel and Lieberman (2013) qualified that the
nosology in terms of the scientific bases in genet- RDoC (Research Domain Criteria) is based on
ics, neuroscience, and behavioral science for the the assumption that mental illness can be under-
task of establishing valid psychiatric categories. stood best as constituting disorders of “brain
The second part of this chapter considers the function and structure” that affect the domains of
major psychological injuries related to trauma, cognition, emotion, and behavior. The goal of the
which especially involves posttraumatic stress RDoC project is to create a new type of psychiat-
disorder (PTSD). In particular, this part of the ric nosology informed by genetics, neuroscience,
chapter considers the criteria for PTSD, as well and behavioral science. Long term, the goal is
as for acute stress disorder, specific phobia, and that its findings will be incorporated in future
adjustment disorder. The next chapter of the iterations of the DSM (Diagnostic and Statistical
book continues with presentation of the criteria Manual of Mental Disorders).
in the DSM-5 for neurocognitive disorder The structure of the RDoC includes five
(NCD) and somatic symptom disorder (SDD). domains of function: positive valence systems,
As well, it deals with recent research on the negative valence systems, cognitive systems,

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 591


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_23
592 23 The DSM-5 and the RDoC: Grand Designs and Grander Problems

social process systems, and arousal regulatory tory), at least as long as the measure involved lies
systems (e.g., Simmons & Quinn, 2014). Further, along the disease or syndrome pathway begin-
each of the five domains consists of constructs ning with the genetic underpinning at issue.
and, also, each must map directly onto specific Gottesman and colleagues elaborated specific
biological systems, such as neural circuits. criteria for an endophenotypic candidate. (a) It
Moreover, for each construct, there are eight must be associated with disease in a population.
units of analysis that should be considered in (b) It is heritable (unlike a biomarker, which need
research, from genes to behavior to paradigms. not be). (c) Ideally, it is state-independent, being
The negative valence domain provides a good expressed even if the disease is not yet active, and
example of the RDoC proposal. It is constituted it might be developmentally variable. (d) It
by the systems of acute threat (fear), potential expresses increased prevalence in ill relatives of
threat (anxiety), sustained threat, loss, and frus- diseased probands (subjects of study) compared
trative nonreward. to well relatives (cosegregation). (e) There are
family associations evident. (f) Ideally, it is
uniquely associated with the disease at issue.
Comment There are several benefits of adopting the
endophenotypic concept. (a) When it is elemen-
I remark that the latter two systems are not asso- tary, an endophenotype likely reflects genetic
ciated with a basic emotion, but could be, just as activity (e.g., physiological, synaptic, and other
the first two are (i.e., depression and irritability, neural mechanisms). (b) The quantitative mea-
respectively). As for the cognitive and social pro- surement involved facilitates quantitative trait
cess systems, they seem to incorrectly exclude linkage analysis. (c) By adding brain-imaging
social cognition as part of an integrated psycho- research and infrahuman animal model research,
logical model. candidate genes can be better identified. (d)
Endophenotypes could be used directly in animal
models.
Endophenotype and the RDoC As for biomarkers (Biomarkers Definition
Working Group, 2001), they include any measur-
Lenzenweger (2013) reinforced the distinction able indicator of a disease, whether heritable
between endophenotype, intermediate pheno- (genetic) or not, or actually involved in the causal
type, and biomarker. He considered the concept pathway from gene to disease or not. Therefore, a
of endophenotype as the most proximate to the biomarker might even include the impact of an
goal of the RDoC project (Insel et al., 2010). The outside environmental agent on the individual
concept of endophenotype (Gottesman & Gould, (e.g., a molecular reaction to a toxin, a pharmaco-
2003; Gottesman & McGue, 2015; Gottesman & logical response to a therapeutic intervention).
Shields, 1972; Gould & Gottesman, 2006; Lenzenweger (2013) added that although all
Shields & Gottesman, 1973) refers to a measur- endophenotypes constitute biomarkers, all the
able component that lies within the pathway to latter are not necessarily the former.
disease, from distal genotype to manifest pheno- With respect to intermediate phenotypes, its
type. Normally, an endophenotype is unseen. It is definition has varied, and more recently includes
not a risk factor in disease but a reflection of an that is a heritable trait in the pathogenetic path-
expressed genetic substrate within the disease way from genetic predisposition to psychiatric
pathway. It is an internal manifestation of an disease (Rasetti & Weinberger, 2011). This cur-
underlying disease liability. Not only is it mea- rent definition of intermediate phenotype is indis-
sured at the biological level (neurophysiology, tinguishable from that of endophenotype. Prior
endocrinology, neuroanatomical), but also it can definitions were imprecise. Moreover, the use of
be measured at the psychological one (e.g., cog- the word “intermediate” in the term renders it
nitive, neuropsychological, self-report inven- ambiguous, and it has been used in a confused
Research Domain Criteria 593

way. For Lenzenweger (2013), the term should process, rendering RDoC foci more heterogenous
be reserved for use at its origins in Mendelian than anticipated. Moreover, the research is
genetics. advancing so quickly in the field that the original
Lenzenweger (2013) concluded that finding RDoC foci might be superceded by more current
endophenotypes will serve to reduce heterogene- conceptualizations (e.g., neural networks;
ity in psychopathology research. The endopheno- Sporns, 2011, 2012). Finally, the pathway from
types for the “main processes” (etiological, genes to disease presumes understanding of the
psychopathological, developmental) involved in disease at issue. The difficulties confronted by
the RDoC proposal appear an important starting the DSMs in specifying psychiatric nosology
point. (e.g., Young, 2014) speak to the care needed in
this regard. The task is not only to move forward
from genes to disease in understanding psychiat-
Development ric causality but also to move backward from an
accurate depiction of disease toward their endo-
Beauchaine and McNulty (2013) indicated how phenotypic and genetic substrates.
difficult it is to elucidate developmental path-
ways in disease. Their example concerns trait
impulsivity, which has different developmental Not Reductionistic
outcomes at different developmental periods.
Research needs to consider comorbidities and A major advance in the RDoC approach is that it
continuities associated with developmental disor- is fully dimensional, placing normal and abnor-
ders and their underlying liabilities or trait vul- mal behavior on a continuum on which genetic
nerabilities. These latter traits, such as impulsivity, and related findings apply to the full spectrum of
lie at a level of analysis important for the RDoC phenotypic expression (Cuthbert & Kozak,
project, but the behavioral syndromes and dis- 2013). Its findings should cut across diagnostic
eases to which they contribute are the focus of the categories (Owen, 2012).
DSMs. Disease pathways start from genetic vul- Cuthbert and Kozak (2013) argued that the
nerability and expressed neural/hormonal sub- RDoC project is not reductionistic of psychiatric
strates underpinning RDoC foci, but they also illness to biology, genes, and brain disorder, a
include environmental risk mediators at all devel- criticism raised by Berenbaum (2013). Rather,
opmental phases, including prenatally. Moreover, valid psychological constructs have been incor-
influences are bidirectional, with recursive feed- porated in the RDoC project.
back loops.

Comment
Comment
However, I note that psychological constructs in
We can conclude that the complexity of develop- the RDoC are subsumed in domains selected for
mental psychopathology precludes a predomi- their biological significance as brain basis.
nant biological, neuroscientific, or exclusively Granted, the RDoC project seeks integrated “psy-
distal centration in the RDoC project. chobiological” explanations of psychiatric prob-
Endophenotypes do not exclusively lie at these lems beyond uniquely biological or psychological
levels in the causal pathway from genes to dis- ones (Cuthbert & Kozak, 2013). However, the
ease. The RDoC goal is laudable; however, we underlying model still excludes an integrated
need to ask to what extent it considers environ- “biopsychosocial” model as an integrating one, at
mental impacts, including in epigenesis, gene– least overtly as a fundamental starting point.
environment interactions, and other effects on the Overt acknowledgment of the important role
causal pathway to disease that complexify the of environment, context, and the social on an
594 23 The DSM-5 and the RDoC: Grand Designs and Grander Problems

equal footing to the biological, as well as the full in “modern neuroscience.” However, they also
panoply of psychological processes, such as with referred to the processes of learning, brain plastic-
self-processes and self-regulation (and the degree ity (although as an “orthogonal” dimension), the
that they can become emergent and go beyond environment, and epigenetics. Mental disorders
biological and social prescriptions and proscrip- are considered to express dysfunctional neural cir-
tions) is fundamental in understanding behavior. cuits that can be insidious in their effects, which
Granted, the RDoC program eschews a funda- might precede frank symptomatology by years.
mental brain–mind, or biological–behavioral Moreover, the circuits might be widely distributed
identity or isomorphism, but it still can be per- rather than localized.
ceived as “eliminative reductionistic,” despite its According to Morris et al. (2014), brains change
defense and arguments to the contrary, because it in response to experience, exposure, and learning.
does not include directly elements that stand in Developmental neuroplasticity reverberates with
direct contrast to reductionism. changes outside of genetic factors, such as epi-
Note that acceptance of a frank biopsychoso- genetics. Neurogenesis continues in the adult, but is
cial project to the RDoC proposal would not conditioned (“recapitulates”) prenatal neurogenetic
undermine its genetic, heritable, and biological “interaction” with it, thereby being “impacted” by
emphasis, because it only would supplement it early experiences. Moreover, neuroplasticity
with valid mediators and moderators of biologi- includes environmental (intrinsic, extrinsic) effects
cal effects on behavior. For example, genetic on existing neurons and their circuits. In cases of
influences work to cause behavior through envi- maladaptive behavior, the neuroplasticity might be
ronmental supports, and the effects of the envi- hyper- or hypo-, or otherwise dysfunctional.
ronment on genetics now is known to include As for epigenesis (Feil, 2008; Meaney, 2010),
epigenetic (environmentally-mediated) influ- it can affect long-term neuroplasticity, learning,
ences of genetic expression (e.g., gene silencing and memory, in that a majority of the genes that
by DNA methylation). are affected by epigenesis are expressed in brain
Therefore, the RDoC project needs to be con- tissue (Wilkinson, Davies, & Iseles, 2007). The
tinually open to new developments in the field. Its vital role played in the gene-silencing activity in
levels of analysis component permits that, but it epigenesis is demonstrated by the inheritance of
should be embedded directly into its domains, the genetic silencing that is found in offspring,
constructs and, indeed, in its overarching model. despite not having experienced the environmen-
Environment, psychology, self, and the social are tal impacts that had, in the first place, induced the
intrinsic to psychiatric disorder, and the funda- epigenetic processes.
mental assumptions undergirding the nosological Epigenesis can help explain the variation in
RDoC project should be inclusive of terms such as pattern of risk and inheritance within and among
these in the model it espouses as representative of mental disorders. As well, it can help elucidate
psychiatric processes. Granted, research in these trajectories of remission and relapse and the
non-biological lines will be supported by funding cross-disorder overlapping genetic variants.
agencies, but without acknowledging openly these According to Morris et al. (2014), these types of
important avenues, their just place in the RDoC findings do not align with traditional psychiatric
project might not be properly promoted. classification systems.

Epigenesis Comment

The RDoC project seems to be considering these Much of the remaining portions of the review of
concerns to a degree. For example, Morris, the RDoC project conducted by Morris et al.
Rumsey, and Cuthbert (2014) referred to the (2014) focused on intervention research. To their
RDoC as providing a “neuroscience-based” or credit, they included evidence-based psychothera-
“anchored” nosological framework using advances pies along with psychopharmacology. However, I
Research Domain Criteria 595

note that the goal of their review was based on a ful “scientific tasks.” This definition is quite
small range of treatments and on their neurobio- unlike the standard one for paradigms, and it
logical effects. A more overtly proclaimed biopsy- hints at their emphasis on the biological origins
chosocial focus on the RDoC project might serve to behavior and psychopathology. However, once
to expand this lens on psychotherapy, and open it more, I note that paradigms should include com-
better to effective individualized treatment. plementary perspectives to the major neurobio-
This would not deny the essential scientific and logical or neuroscientific one of the RDoC, that
practice value of the RDoC project, nor would it is, a fully scientific RDoC should include within
work against its ultimate goal. Although I acknowl- its “paradigms” especially the complementary
edge that research along these lines could take model to its primary emphasis—the biopsycho-
place outside of the RDoC parameters, by being social one.
inclusive in these areas of psychiatric study (more
or less at its outset), it might better help in the
RDoC’s ultimate goal of improving psychiatric Most Recent Criticisms
nosology and effective treatment for patients diag-
nosed with the new classification system that will The latter conclusion is echoed in the more recent
emerge as it informs work on future DSMs. literature on the RDoC. Insel (2014) referred to
the RDoC project in terms of “precision medi-
cine” for psychiatry. Lilienfeld (2014) main-
DSM-5 tained that the RDoC’s emphasis on mental
disorder “fundamentally” involving brain circuit
Morris and Cuthbert (2013) underscored the disorder risks, while de-emphasizing psychoso-
advantages of the RDoC project relative to extant cial and cultural factors. Harkness, Reynolds, and
psychiatric classificatory systems (DSMs, ICDs; Lilienfeld (2014) asked that the RDoC consider
International Statistical Classification of Diseases use of measurement operations tied to theory and
and Related Health Problems). The latter seek that are “falsifiable.” Moreover, the best measure-
diagnostic categories, but their variability or het- ment of individual differences in systems require
erogeneity in symptom expression belies their “traditional psychological” ones. About develop-
underlying rationale of including in them cate- ment, Sonuga-Barke (2014) did not consider that
gorical disorders, or unitary entities, with “nor- the RDoC sufficiently “considered” it in its
mal variance.” Therefore, it might be futile to conceptualization.
seek “common causes” that account for the het- Whooley (2014) opined that the “brain-
erogeneity in diagnostic categories. centric” focus of the RDoC serves to “decontex-
That being said, for Morris and Cuthbert tualize” mental illness and set aside “social
(2013), the extant diagnostic systems have attained embeddedness” and culture. It demotes or
a degree of success that constitutes a major obsta- reduces the social and environmental. On the
cle in their consideration of substantive change. contrary, the biological and social always should
For example, the DSMs are “completely inte- be considered interrelated and intertwined in
grated” into practice diagnostic codes, insurance mental distress. Frances (2014) reminded that
payments, and disability determinations, as well as context and environment are important in the
regulatory agency guidelines and a host of research latter.
components, such as clinical trials. Maj (2014) considered the RDoC project per-
haps “somewhat distant” from clinical phenom-
ena. It is a dehumanizing oversimplification or
Comment downgrade of psychopathology/practice.
Jablensky and Waters (2014) indicated that
As a final comment to the RDoC project from patients enter the office with their phenotypes,
Morris and Cuthbert (2013), we learn that the not with their genotypes or biosignatures. Parnas
“paradigms” described in the RDoC refer to use- (2014) added that psychiatrists treat people, not
596 23 The DSM-5 and the RDoC: Grand Designs and Grander Problems

brain circuits. First (2014) continued that the heterogeneity in illness expression and a psycho-
RDoC has to make “clinical sense.” Sartorius social and social one to understand the full range
(2014) agreed that psychopathological compo- of such heterogeneity.
nents include the biological, psychological, and Perhaps symptoms for disorders can be
social. Stein (2014) concurred that psychopathol- arranged into primary, secondary, and tertiary
ogy has multiple components, including the clusters (e.g., marker, core, and cross-diagnostic
social context. Fulford (2014) opined that the ones, with the latter ones less relevant; Young,
RDoC needs to take symptoms seriously. Lareau, & Pierre, 2014). This approach could
Wakefield (2014) worried that the environ- help lead to a better understanding of the disor-
mental/social construct in the RDoC does not ders, and reduce their heterogeneous expression,
include that human psychological mechanisms by focusing especially on primary and secondary
are prepared biologically for sensitive response symptoms instead of considering them all equal
to the social/environmental context. Phillips in their differentiating quality. Once disorders are
(2014) worried that it would not address culture better understood and simplified, it might be eas-
and the biopsychosocial because of its “siren ier to find the correct candidate endophenotypes
call” for biological “fixes.” Weinberger and that are involved in the genomic-disease path-
Goldberg (2014) worried about that “validity” of way. An approach such as this will make the
the behavioral, neural genetic, and functional RDoC “patient-centric” instead of only “brain-
dimensions of the RDoC. centric” and will help toward improving both the
In response, Cuthbert (2014a) maintained that DSM-5 and appropriate psychotherapy with
the overall matrix approach of the RDoC allows patients diagnosed with its disorders.
for environmental, neurodevelopmental, psycho-
logical, and behavioral aspects, with the neural
system serving an “implementing” function. The DSM-5 and Psychological
Cuthbert (2014b) added that the RDoC eventu- Injuries
ally will be “useful” for clinical work. Neural
systems/circuits play preponderant roles in the A psychological injury is a psychological “men-
RDoC, with the social and environment as fac- tal harm” causally related to an event at issue that
tors, too. It is “harnessing” genetics and neuro- can result in an actionable claim. It has a func-
science toward more “effective” prevention and tional impact, requires treatment, and leads to
treatment. disability. It is vetted in assessments in order to
have malingering ruled out, as well as rule-out by
pre-event psychological vulnerabilities or other
Comment factors. However, psychological injury cases are
complicated, for example, due to the “gray zone.”
The RDoC is an emerging critical framework in Among other things, in forensic/disability cases,
mental health research and it will inform and the gray zone refers to the role of exaggeration
channel conceptualization and empirical investi- and other response styles that are not direct
gation in the field, including for the DSM-5, gen- malingering, and to feigning, in general, as well
erally, and for specific disorders, such as as difficulty in diagnosing and dealing with
PTSD. However, its neuroscientific focus (even comorbidities.
though it offers qualifications on this issue) All of the critical terms in the area of psycho-
appears to preclude a wider model of psychopa- logical injury and law can be contested, e.g.,
thology and its development in context, such as mental harm, causality, functional impact, dis-
the biopsychosocial one. Fixation on biological ability, malingering, and the major diagnoses
markers of psychiatric disease might retard the involved. The typical diagnoses are PTSD, pain-
search for appropriate markers of disorder. The related conditions, mild traumatic brain injury
field needs both a biological approach to narrow (TBI), adjustment disorder, depression, or other
PTSD in the DSM-5 597

anxiety disorders (e.g., phobia, generalized anxi- validity. Therefore, we need to analyze it espe-
ety disorder). The field is further in turmoil cially carefully as presented in the DSM-5 and in
because, as has been shown, the new version of research. The following material in this chapter
the premiere diagnostic manual, the DSM-5, is and the next chapter also analyzes in depth other
itself contested. But the critical forensic question specific DSM-5 disorders that are relevant to psy-
is how much do these DSM-5 changes matter— chological injury and law. In particular, I focus
generally, in forensic work, the importance in an not only on PTSD but also on brain injury-related
assessment relates to the functional impact of the conditions and chronic pain conditions, along
injury at hand for the legal question at hand, and with other related disorders.
not in the particular disorder(s) diagnosed. That
being said, the present chapter examines
extremely carefully the criteria of the major diag- PTSD in the DSM-5
noses related to psychological injury and law.
PTSD represents the quintessential DSM-5 Description and Concerns
disorder for the area of psychological injury and
law. It is contested for its causation, symptom Table 23.1 presents the criteria defining PTSD in
expression, ease in malingering, and overall the DSM-5. Aside from the causal criterion, there

Table 23.1 DSM-5 criteria for posttraumatic stress disorder (PTSD), slightly adjusted
A. Exposure to one (or more) of these event(s): death/threatened death; actual/threatened serious injury; actual/
threatened sexual violation. This happens in the following way(s):
1. Experiencing oneself
2. Personally witnessing it as it occurs to others
3. Learning that it occurred to a close relative/friend; the actual/threatened death is violent/accidental
4. Experiencing personally repeated/extreme exposure to aversive details (e.g., first responders to human body
parts; police officers repeatedly to the details of child abuse); excludes exposure through electronic media/tele
vision/movies/pictures, except if work-related
B. Intrusion symptoms associated with it that began after it, as shown by the following way(s) (for the diagnosis,
one or more of the five symptoms in this cluster need(s) to be present):
1. Recurrent/involuntary/intrusive distressing memories of it
2. Recurrent distressing dreams; their content, affect, or both are related to it
3. Dissociative reactions (e.g., flashbacks); the person feels/acts as if it is recurring (at worst, a complete loss of
awareness of present surrounding)
4. Intense/prolonged psychological distress at exposure to internal/external signals that symbolize/resemble an
aspect of it
5. Marked physiological reactions to reminders (internal/external signals symbolizing/resembling (aspect of it))
C. Persistent avoidance of stimuli associated with it that began after it, as shown by efforts to avoid in the following
way(s) (for the diagnosis, one or both of the two symptoms in this cluster need(s) to be present):
1. (Tries to) avoid distressing internal reminders (thoughts/feelings/memories) about/associated with it
2. (Tries to) avoid external reminders (e.g., people, places, conversations, activities, objects, situations) that
induce distress (thoughts/feelings/memories) about/associated with it
D. Negative alterations in cognitions/mood associated with it begins or worsened after it, as shown by the following
ways (for the diagnosis, two or more of the seven symptoms in this cluster need to be present):
1. Inability to remember important aspect of it (typically due to dissociative amnesia, not head injury/alcohol/
drugs)
2. Persistent/exaggerated negative beliefs/expectations about one’s self, others/world (e.g., “I’m bad,” “Trust no
one now,” “The world is totally dangerous”)
3. Persistent, distorted thoughts about the cause/consequences of it, leading to self-blame/blame of others
4. Persistent negative emotional state (e.g., fear/horror/anger/guilt/shame)
5. Markedly diminished interest/participation in important life activities
6. Feeling of detachment/estrangement from others
7. Persistent inability to experience emotions that are positive (e.g., happiness/satisfaction/loving feelings)
(continued)
598 23 The DSM-5 and the RDoC: Grand Designs and Grander Problems

Table 23.1 (continued)


E. Alterations (marked) in arousal/reactivity associated with it, having begun or worsened after it, as shown by the
following ways (for the diagnosis, two or more of the six symptoms in this cluster need to be present):
1. Irritability/angry behavior (to little or no provocation), as verbal/physical aggression to people/objects
2. Recklessness/self-destructiveness
3. Hypervigilance behavior
4. Exaggerated startling response
5. Concentration problems
6. Sleep disturbance (e.g., difficulty falling/staying asleep/restless sleep)
F. Duration lasts at least one month
G. The disturbance induces clinically significant distress/impairment in social/occupational/other important
functional areas
H. Disturbance not due to physiological effects of a substance (e.g., medication/alcohol) or to another medical
condition
Adapted from American Psychiatric Association (2013)
Specify if:
With Delayed Onset: if fully diagnosable only at 6 months or more after it
Specify if:
Dissociative symptoms present (persistent, recurrent)
1. depersonalization (detailed feelings, e.g., outside observer, in a dream, feeling unreal, moving slowly)
2. derealization (unreality in surroundings (also dreamlike/distant/distorted))
Abbreviation DSM-5 = Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, Fifth Edition
Note: Applies to individuals 7 years or more in age

are the four clustering ones and others that are sion that was published. Given these extensive
qualifiers. The table gives a slightly revised ver- changes, the reliability reported for PTSD in the
sion of the criteria for PTSD. field trials do not apply directly to the final version
Table 23.2 summarizes the research on the in the DSM-5 manual. One could ask to what extent
factor structure of PTSD. The four-factor model these changes in the final version of the DSM-5
has been taken to provide the best fit to the data in relative to the draft compromise its use in relation to
the DSM-5. In particular, the King et al. (1998) PTSD. I consider this an open question with no easy
model was used to structure the DSM-5. It divides answer, but do believe, nonetheless, that the reliabil-
the DSM-IV-TR’s (Diagnostic and Statistical ity data apply to a good degree. The subtext is that a
Manual of Mental Disorders, Fourth Edition, scientific, skeptical attitude helps in understanding
Text Revised; American Psychiatric Association, the DSM-5 and its process. An extreme version of
2000) numbing-avoidance cluster into two clus- this approach might advocate that, in essence, the
ters. However, the Simms et al. (2002) model is published criteria of PTSD in the DSM-5 have
the four-factor one usually supported in the liter- never been adequately tested for reliability.
ature. It encompasses some numbing and hyper- In this regard, Table 23.4 summarizes the cri-
arousal items into one cluster, called dysphoria, teria that might be problematic in the final ver-
thereby reducing the extent of the avoidance and sion used in the DSM-5 for PTSD. Collectively,
hypervigilance clusters. However, is the four- these apparent problems with the DSM-5 PTSD
cluster model the one that is supported currently criteria point to the need for careful assessment
in the literature? The research on PTSD calls into and diagnosis of PTSD.
question its four-cluster organization in the
DSM-5. Other research presented below suggests
that a five-factor model best fits the DSM-5 Other
symptom organization for PTSD.
Table 23.3 indicates which criteria in the 2010 The next few tables present the DSM-5 criteria
draft proposal for PTSD that was field tested in for other diagnoses relevant to psychological
2010–2011 were altered in the DSM-5’s final ver- injury cases that are related to traumatic events or
PTSD in the DSM-5 599

Table 23.2 Possible symptom dimensions of PTSD


Models
King, Leskin, King, and Simms, Watson, and
DSM-IV Weathers (1998) Doebbeling (2002)
DSM-IV PTSD symptoms Three-factor Four-factor Four-factor
B1. Intrusive thoughts of trauma Intrusions Intrusions Intrusions
B2. Recurrent dreams of trauma Intrusions Intrusions Intrusions
B3. Flashbacks Intrusions Intrusions Intrusions
B4. Emotional reactivity Intrusions Intrusions Intrusions
B5. Physiological reactivity to Intrusions Intrusions Intrusions
trauma cues
C1. Avoiding thoughts of trauma Avoidance/numbing Avoidance Avoidance
C2. Avoiding reminders of trauma Avoidance/numbing Avoidance Avoidance
C3. Inability to recall aspects of Avoidance/numbing Numbing Dysphoria
trauma
C4. Loss of interest Avoidance/numbing Numbing Dysphoria
C5. Detachment Avoidance/numbing Numbing Dysphoria
C6. Restricted affect Avoidance/numbing Numbing Dysphoria
C7. Sense of foreshortened future Avoidance/numbing Numbing Dysphoria
D1. Sleep disturbance Hyperarousal Hyperarousal Dysphoria
D2. Irritability Hyperarousal Hyperarousal Dysphoria
D3. Difficulty concentrating Hyperarousal Hyperarousal Dysphoria
D4. Hypervigilance Hyperarousal Hyperarousal Hypervigilance
D5. Exaggerated startle response Hyperarousal Hyperarousal Hypervigilance
Adapted with permission from Springer Science + Business Media. Young (2014); with kind permission from Springer
Science + Business Media B.V. [Table 25.7, Page 639]

Table 23.3 Important changes in the DSM-5 criteria for PTSD in the final version relative to the draft proposal that
was field-tested
Criterion Change Wording
C1 Replacements “Internal reminders” changed to “distressing”
“Physical sensations” changed to “memories” (closely)
“Arouse recollections” changed to “associated with”
C2 Replacements Same as above
D Reduction # of polythetic criteria needed for threshold (3 changed to 2)
D2 Added “Expectations” changed to “beliefs or expectations”
D3 Replacement addition “Blame of self/others” changed to “cognitions that lead to blame of
self/others”
D7 Replacement “Unable to have loving feelings/psychic numbing” changed to
“inability to experience happiness/satisfaction/loving feelings”
E Addition “Alteration” changed to “marked alteration”
E Reduction In threshold, 3 criteria changed to 2, as above for D
E1 Replacement “Aggressive behavior” changed to “angry outbursts/with little or no
provocation typically expressed as verbal/physical aggression toward
people/objects”

to adapting to them. Table 23.5 indicates key fea- which is similar to my concern in the case of
tures of acute stress disorder (ASD), which is PTSD. Also, the symptom cluster and duration
diagnosed early after a traumatic event. My con- criteria of ASD could use closer examination.
cerns relate to the weakness of criterion A to pre- For specific phobia, the major changes in the
vent a flood of exaggerated and false claims, DSM-5 involve the duration criterion and the
600 23 The DSM-5 and the RDoC: Grand Designs and Grander Problems

Table 23.4 Problematic criteria in PTSD in the DSM-5


Criterion Descriptor Comment
A2 Witnessing event in vivo Civil floodgates open
A2 As it occurred to other(s) (family member not They open even further
specified)
A2 The individual’s response included “intense fear, This A2 criterion in the DSM-IV has been
helplessness, or horror” eliminated. The floodgates open even further
A3 Learning of event re family member or close Witnessing not required
friend Civil floodgates opened
A4 Experiencing repeated/extreme aversive details; Civil floodgates opened
could be electronically if work-related
B3 Dissociative reactions could include complete Criminal floodgates opened. Could be used in “not
loss of awareness of present surroundings guilty” pleadings
E1 Irritability/anger outburst (with little/no Criminal floodgates opened. Could be used in not
provocation, expressed as verbal/physical guilty pleadings
aggression)
E2 Reckless/self-destructive behavior Criminal floodgates opened. Could be used in not
guilty pleadings
Specifier With dissociate symptoms See B3
Specifier With delay possible >6 months See the concerns for the A criterion

Table 23.5 Acute stress disorder in the DSM-5


Criterion Descriptor Comment
A As for PTSD See PTSD table (Problematic criteria in PTSD in the DSM-5) about
concerns about opening the floodgate
B ≥9 of the 14 symptoms [So why are they placed in 5 categories?] Dissociation had been a
primary symptom in the DSM-IV (3 or more of 5 symptoms) and the
others involved symptoms related to the 3 PTSD clusters in the
DSM-IV. In the DSM-5, dissociation is de-emphasized: there are only
2 dissociation symptoms and none are necessary for the diagnosis. The
other four categories appear to reflect the four symptom clusters for
PTSD, but will this division been supported empirically as had been
the case for PTSD?
C 3 days to 1 month Why is 3 days enough for consideration as a disorder? (It had been 2
days in the DSM-IV)
D The usual impairment For 3 days, too?
criterion

requirement for the fear/anxiety experienced to ders and other anxiety disorders). When not full
be “out of proportion” to the danger/cultural con- blown, in the DSM-5, adjustment disorder can be
text associated with the event at issue. My con- diagnosed as “adjustment-like” disorder. In this
cern is that the latter criterion (D) could be used case, the bar might be set too low (see Table 23.7).
to deny valid claims of phobia because of the
high bar set for the response to the event (see
Table 23.6). Supportive Research
In the DSM-IV-TR, adjustment disorder could
not be diagnosed simultaneously with Miller, Wolf, and Keane (2014) defended the
PTSD. However, now it is not considered anxiety- decision to create a new trauma chapter in the
related (nor is PTSD), and it stands in its own DSM-5 and place PTSD in it rather than in the
chapter (independent of PTSD, other stress disor- anxiety chapter. They supported the notion that
PTSD in the DSM-5 601

Table 23.6 Changes to specific phobia in the DSM-5


Criterion DSM-IV DSM-5
A Marked and persistent Marked
Excessive or unreasonable –
B Immediate anxiety response Immediate fear or anxiety
C Recognize it as excessive or unreasonable –
D Avoided Actively avoided
Endured with intense “anxiety or distress” Fear or anxiety
E Interferes significantly, or marked distress Clinically significant distress or impairment
F For <18 years, duration >6 months Typically ≥ 6 months (a general guide having
some degree of flexibility) (no age restriction)
– (New D) The fear/anxiety “out of proportion” to
the actual danger and/or cultural context

Table 23.7 Changes to adjustment disorder in the DSM-5


Criterion DSM-IV DSM-5
In its own chapter Now classified as one of a set of trauma/stress-related
conditions
B1 In excess of expectation to stressor Out of proportion to the severity/intensity of the exposure,
exposure considering external context/cultural factors
Acute (<6 months) or chronic –
(≥6 months) specifier
– If either delayed onset (>3 months) or continuation of
disorder for 6 months after stressor cessation, diagnose
“adjustment-like disorder” under rubric of “other specified
trauma – and stressor-related disorder”

trauma reactions are heterogenous and not neces- (2013), Kilpatrick et al. (2013), and Miller et al.
sarily anxiety- or fear-related; for example, PTSD (2013).
has externalization features. About the arrangement of the symptoms,
Miller et al. (2014) supported removal of the Miller et al. (2013) had found that the new four-
peri-traumatic emotionality criterion (A2) from cluster model in the DSM-5 is supported by con-
the DSM-IV-TR PTSD criterial definition. For firmatory factor analytic research. [However, the
example, in this regard, peri-traumatic emotional best fit was with the Simms et al. (2002) model
experiences have been found not to be predictive rather than the one used by the DSM-5. Moreover,
of who will develop PTSD, nor has its severity, if factor structure for the DSM-5 model revealed
it should develop (Friedman, Resick, Bryant, & “weak” loadings for two items on the factors to
Brewin, 2011). which they belonged (inability to remember an
They noted that the definition allows for trau- important aspect of the traumatic event(s); the
matic events as well as a unique event as eliciting amnesia symptom; and reckless/self-destructive
PTSD. This is consistent with the finding that life- behavior).]
time trauma exposures cumulatively affect post- In terms of the dissociative subtype of PTSD,
trauma psychopathology severity (McLaughlin latent profile analytic research has found that
et al., 2013). derealization and depersonalization are present in
As for revisions of specific PTSD symptoms, 15–30 % of individuals expressing PTSD (e.g.,
Miller et al. (2014) noted that research has shown Wolf et al., 2012). Lanius, Brand, Vermetten,
little change in PTSD prevalence as a result of the Frewen, and Spiegel (2012) suggested that in the
changes. In this regard, they cited Carmassi et al. dissociative subtype, frontal brain regions are
602 23 The DSM-5 and the RDoC: Grand Designs and Grander Problems

overactivated, thereby actively inhibiting the lim- Forensics First (2010) was concerned forensi-
bic regions associated with emotional/fear respon- cally about the change to Criterion A for
sivity. In contrast, other individuals with PTSD PTSD. The situations mentioned as qualifying
manifest hypoactivity in frontal brain regions and traumatic events broaden the possibilities and
lack of inhibitory modulation of limbic regions. will allow for “creative litigation.” The danger in
Miller et al. (2014) addressed the ICD-11 these regards is that more individuals will become
(International Statistical Classification of in a position to malinger PTSD. First’s (2010)
Diseases and Related Health Problems, 11th concerns about the DSM-5 2010 draft apply
Revision; World Health Organization, 2017) pro- equally to the final version of the DSM-5, which
posal to separate complex PTSD (CPTSD) from has radically changed the A criterion for PTSD in
PTSD, in general (Cloitre, Garvert, Brewin, a way the opens the gate keeping role of criterion
Bryant, & Maercker, 2013). Wolf et al. (2014) A to spurious and exaggerated claims.
disputed the empirical basis for distinguishing
Forensically, PTSD has become the focus
CPTSD and PTSD as proposed for the ICD-11.
diagnosis for an explosion of tort actions (Kane
Wolf et al. (2014) found that latent class analyses
& Dvoskin, 2011). Moreover, its symptom list is
of trauma-exposed community and veteran sam-
readily available on the Internet and attorney
ples found symptom severity differences among
websites as well as being straightforward in
classes but not ones related PTSD-CPTSD in
description, so that it is subject to facility in
terms of the psychopathology endorsed. Miller
malingering (Rosen & Grunert, 2012). For Levin
et al. (2014) noted that the ICD-11 symptom
et al. (2014), some of the DSM-5’s PTSD symp-
cluster for CPTSD resembles symptoms in two
toms allow for increased scope for claims of
clusters of the DSM-5 approach (D, E). Therefore,
diminished criminal responsibility, should PTSD
CPTSD might simply be a more severe form of
be diagnosed before the act at issue.
PTSD rather than a distinct entity.
Testing Wisdom et al. (2014) noted that PTSD
Criticisms is subject to exaggeration of symptoms for sec-
ondary gain. They recommended the use of per-
Entry PTSD is a controversial diagnostic cate- formance validity testing, noting that this is not
gory in the DSM-5 for several reasons, aside common in the VA (Veterans Administration)
from issues with its criteria. First, because of its system. In this regard, the Fp-r scale of the
entry criterion of having been a victim or other- MMPI-2-RF appears to provide valid results dif-
wise part to a traumatic event, it is open to bracket ferentiating genuine and over-reported PTSD
creep in its eliciting stressors (McNally, 2003). symptoms (Wolf & Miller, 2014; also Arbisi,
Zoellner, Bedard-Gilligan, Jun, Marks, and Polusny, Erbes, Thuras, & Reddy, 2011;
Garcia (2013) also noted that alteration of the A1 Goodwin, Sellbom, & Arbisi, 2013; Marion,
entry criterion for PTSD that has taken place in Sellbom, & Bagby, 2011; Mason et al., 2013).
the DSM-5 encourages “bracket creep” (McNally, Generally, the inference is that the DSM-5 diag-
2003), in that it permits traumatic stressors to nostic categories being discussed need improve-
expand beyond “high-magnitude catastrophic ment in their symptom specification and
events” to “low-magnitude” ones, such as indi- organization. Also, their verification by testing is
rect exposure (e.g., loss of one’s farm animals, or difficult and, often, disability systems dealing
simply being present at a military base). As with with them do not even require confirmation by
others, Levin, Kleinman, and Adler (2014) take testing of claims made.
issue with the approach to PTSD in the DSM-5 at In forensic cases, assessors need to administer
the forensic and legal levels because the changes adequate psychometric testing (Larrabee, 2012),
in the criterion A about the trauma involved will including measures with respondent validity
increase claims. indicators that meet court requirements (e.g.,
PTSD in the DSM-5 603

MMPI-2-RF, Minnesota Multiphasic Personality including risky/self-destructive behavior in the


Inventory-2 Restructured Form; Ben-Porath & DSM-5 PTSD criteria, the evidence suggests that
Tellegen, 2008/2011). Nevertheless, even in the its association with PTSD might be more due to
most rigorous research, psychometric tests have either depression or borderline personality disor-
imperfect sensitivity and specificity (Young, der, which are frequently comorbid with it (e.g.,
2014). Therefore, the search for (bio)markers of Panagioti, Gooding, Taylor, & Tarrier, 2013;
PTSD that might be able to reliably differentiate Rytwinski, Scur, Feeny, & Youngstrom, 2013;
valid from invalid cases of PTSD has become an Zlotnick et al., 2003).
important avenue of research and possible appli- Zoellner, Pruitt, Farach, and Jun (2014) under-
cation for court purposes (Lareau, 2011). scored that the heterogeneity of symptoms in
PTSD obscures its core characteristics and accen-
Symptoms Weathers, Marx, Friedman, and tuates its secondary characteristics. Also, in
Schnurr (2014) noted that the DSM-5 kept a comorbid PTSD and depression, there might be
broad approach to symptom inclusion in PTSD an underlying negative affect factor (Post,
(20 symptoms) because this facilitates evaluation Zoellner, Youngstrom, & Feeny, 2011). Zoellner
and treatment. The narrowing approach (e.g., et al. (2014) concluded that because of PTSD’s
Brewin, 2013; Maercker et al., 2013) refers to heterogeneity in symptoms in the DSM-5, it is
using a reduced criterion set in order to facilitate possible for an individual to be attributed the
diagnosis, reduce comorbidity, and so on. At the diagnosis of PTSD without even expressing spe-
same time, when applied to cases, the new cific fear symptoms. Levin et al. (2014) noted that
DSM-5 symptom list and structure excludes some particular PTSD symptoms in the DSM-5
about 25 % of individuals who would meet the are ambiguous or might be hard to differentiate as
DSM-IV criteria for the disorder (Kilpatrick trauma ones (e.g., reckless behavior).
et al., 2013). This jeopardizes patients who will Young (2013) reviewed the articles in the spe-
be assessed with the DSM-5 for benefits. cial issue on the DSM-5 in the journal
As for the new symptoms added to the PTSD Psychological Injury and Law (Issue 6 (4)).
diagnosis, Zoellner et al. (2013) noted that not Among his concerns was that the polythetic
only do they serve to increase the heterogeneity approach to categorical diagnosis in the DSM-5
of symptom expression in an already diversely leads to symptom heterogeneity in presentation
presented disorder but also they are the ones that through the extensive symptom combinations
overlap with depression (being about negative allowed. He considered this problem com-
beliefs, guilt, persistent negative affect) so that pounded in cases of comorbidity.
increased comorbidity in diagnosis is promoted.
Zoellner et al. (2013) aptly critiqued the reten- Evidence Hoge, Riviere, Wilk, Herrell, and
tion of the psychogenic amnesia symptom and Weathers (2014) and McFarlane (2014) noted
the addition of the qualifier of reckless/self- that soldiers meeting the DSM-IV-TR criteria
destructive behavior to the DSM-5 PTSD item for PTSD often did not meet those of the DSM-
list. The former occurs much less frequently than 5, with the percentage involved being 30 %.
other symptoms of PTSD, especially in the severe They attributed the lack of correspondence in the
range and, also, it loads poorly relative to other criteria over the two editions of the DSM to the
items in factor analytic studies (Miller et al., separation of the numbing and avoidance symp-
2013). Moreover, retention of the psychogenic toms in the DSM-5 into their own clusters.
amnesia item gives fuel to the debate about Soldiers learn to overcome their avoidance ten-
whether a trauma survivor can really forget dencies, and so do not meet the DSM-5 criteria
strong emotional events and its relevant details as often as those for the DSM-IV-TR. Moreover,
(e.g., Lynn, Lilienfeld, Merckelbach, Giesbrecht, the numbing criteria reformulation presents its
& van der Kloet, 2012; McNally, 2009). As for own issues.
604 23 The DSM-5 and the RDoC: Grand Designs and Grander Problems

Miller et al. (2013) conducted internet-based Elhai et al. (2012) administered a web survey
surveys on PTSD with two populations—a large to college students, using an adapted version of
nationally representative (American) community the DSM draft PTSD symptoms. As in Miller
sample and a clinical sample of trauma-exposed et al. (2013), factor analysis and (also Bayesian
American military veterans expressing a high information criterion (BIC) calculation) revealed
prevalence of the disorder. They developed an that the dysphoria model (Yufik & Simms, 2010)
instrument that included DSM-5 draft PTSD fit the data as robustly or better than the DSM-5
symptoms. model. However, after considering all the data in
The prevalence results showed that the PTSD their study, the authors ended up concluding that
draft proposal criteria should be revised by relax- the DSM-5 cluster model is a “best fit” of the
ing the polythetic threshold for D and E symp- data. They added that the changes in PTSD in the
toms (from 3 to 2 in each case). Factor analysis DSM-5 relative to the DSM-IV-TR are “modest”
confirmed the four-factor structure of the 20 improvements and relatively minor and, there-
symptoms for PTSD, but the best one was for a fore, are unlikely to have any meaningful impact
model not used in the DSM-5, that of Simms (e.g., for treatment, forensic application).
et al. (2002). The DSM-5 model simply split the Elhai et al. (2012) conducted research indicat-
avoidance and numbing symptoms that were ing that the three-factor structure of the DSM-
combined in the DSM-IV (Diagnostic and IV-TR symptoms expresses five factors. In
Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, Fourth essence, in their model, the avoidance cluster is
Edition; American Psychiatric Association, divided into avoidance and numbing clusters, and
1994), whereas the Simms et al. (2002) results the hyperarousal cluster is divided into dysphoric
suggested that the best option is a rejuggling of arousal and anxious arousal.
the symptoms in terms of a primary dysphoria Biehn, Elhai, Seligman, Tamburrino, and
factor. Other results questioned inclusion of the Forbes (2013) examined the relationship between
“psychogenic amnesia” and the “reckless/ the DSM-5 diagnostic categories of PTSD items
destructive behavior” symptoms in any of the and depression, in a questionnaire study of par-
factors or clusters. ticipants with trauma history. They noted the
The authors concluded that the final revision high comorbidity between the two disorders
of the DSM-5 should use the relaxed thresholds (e.g., Elhai, Franklin, & Gray, 2008; Kessler,
indicated, which was done. They argued that Sonnega, Bromet, Hughes, & Nelson, 1995).
results about the contested factor structure of the Aside from obtaining evidence supporting the
symptoms do not necessitate changing their clus- DSM-5 factor structure, they found that PTSD’s
ter organization in the DSM-5 because “obtain- avoidance and negative alterations in arousal fac-
ing a pure diagnostic construct was not the tors were more strongly associated with depres-
primary object of the DSM-5 PTSD workgroup” sion’s somatic factor rather than its non-somatic
(p. 11). one.
However, I note that the draft proposal made Galatzer-Levy, Nickerson, Litz, and Marmar
explicit reference to validating the cluster struc- (2013) examined lifetime PTSD comorbidity pat-
ture in PTSD, but this was deleted in the ratio- terns using Latent Class Analysis (LCA). The
nale for the final version. Finally, Miller et al. authors applied the technique to a subsample of
(2013) stated that future research needs to clarify individuals from the National Comorbidity
the placement of the two symptoms that do not Study-Replication (NCS-R; Kessler et al., 1995)
fit clearly the DSM-5 factor structure. They rec- who had been diagnosed by interview as having
ommended that the first of the two perhaps PTSD.
should be a specifier and the second an associ- The study revealed a best-fitting three-class
ated feature. I noted that this recommendation solution of discrete patterns of lifetime comorbid-
was not adopted for the final version of PTSD in ity. The classes involved a low comorbidity one, a
the DSM-5. depressed-anxious one, and a substance depen-
PTSD in the DSM-5 605

dence one. The authors concluded that the amount One promising avenue to reduce the symptom
of PTSD comorbid clusters is relatively small combination problem in PTSD is to consider
and, moreover, each should be associated with reducing its diagnosis to core symptoms. For
different risks, etiology, and effective therapy. In example, Brewin, Lanius, Novac, Schnyder, and
their study, Müller et al. (2014) replicated these Galea (2009) indicated that 6 of the 17 DSM-
results, but they added that the results held for IV-TR symptoms might be sufficient to index it.
partial PTSD as much as full PTSD. Zoellner et al. (2014) focused on its core attri-
bute, related it to fear (e.g., difficulty extinguish-
Comment Frueh, Elhai, and Acierno (2010) con- ing it). This approach to simplifying the symptom
cluded about the degree of change in PTSD in the list complexity in PTSD is compatible with the
DSM-5 and their impact, that the changes were not research showing that the disorder might be
major. However, careful review of both the criteria divided into a five-factor or symptom cluster pre-
and research on PTSD in the DSM-5 casts at least sentation (e.g., Elhai et al., 2012; Horn, Pietrzak,
some doubt on this type of conclusion. Corsi-Travali, & Neumeister, 2014; Pietrzak,
The literature surveyed on PTSD comorbidity Galea, Southwick, & Gelernter, 2013; it had been
underscores the difficulties presented by the comprised of three factors in the DSM-IV-TR
comorbidity construct embedded in the DSMs; and four in the DSM-5). That is, by better under-
however, it also points to promising research standing the factor structure for PTSD, future
directions and solutions. Conceptually, in psychi- iterations of the DSM-5 might better identify its
atric classification, dimensional approaches gen- primary, core symptoms.
erally are placed in opposition to categorical Galatzer-Levy and Bryant (2013) had deter-
ones, and some of the suggestions in these regards mined that in PTSD there are 636,120 possible
have been incorporated into the DSM-5. However, symptom combinations, and they concluded that
the problem presented by heterogeneity in symp- this symptom heterogeneity is “astounding” and
tom expression within any one disorder would renders the PTSD category “amorphous.”
not be resolved by applying uniformly a dimen- Table 23.8 provides the staggering calculations
sional approach, e.g., placing categories on a involving comorbid PTSD presentations (Young
spectrum. Moreover, comorbidities across spec- et al., 2014). For example, PTSD and MDD
tra would still obtain in a system such as this, (Major Depressive Disorder) could be expressed
with all the problems inherent in this approach in as many as 270,351,000 ways. When pain is
still being evident. involved, the amount extends to 1.89 billion. If
Granted, seeking higher-order dimensions one includes mild TBI, the amount of symptom
over disorders could help reduce the classifica- combinations is 1.79 trillion. By adding in alco-
tion complexity in psychiatric classification. hol use disorder, the total escalates to 3.64 qua-
However, the clinical utility afforded by disor- drillion. Finally, when all six conditions are
ders such as PTSD might be compromised. involved, i.e., when BPD (Borderline Personality
Another simplification procedure with respect Disorder) is added, the total of possible symptom
to PTSD and its comorbid disorders concerns the combinations in cases of polytrauma with PTSD
search for discrete classes over the lifetime. as a focus arrives at inconceivable amount of
PTSD and associated disorders might reduce to a 1.39 quintillion. One could argue that the DSM-5
few pathways that have clinical utility as well as is fortunate that the total is several orders of mag-
research compatibility. However, given the nitude less than the number of stars in the uni-
amount of possible comorbid conditions in rela- verse; however, by a several orders of magnitude,
tion to PTSD, this type of approach remains chal- the total is more than the number of stars in the
lenging and is still in its infancy. Milky Way.
606 23 The DSM-5 and the RDoC: Grand Designs and Grander Problems

Table 23.8 Total combination calculations of posttraumatic stress disorder and comorbid psychological injuriesa
Disorder Combination calculations Total combinations
Posttraumatic Stress Disorder B (31) × C (3) × D (120) × E (57) 636,120
(PTSD)
Major Depressive Disorder B (425) 425
(MDD)
Somatic Symptom Disorder A (1) × B (7) 7
(SSD)
Mild Neurocognitive Disorder A (63) × B (15) 945
with Traumatic Brain Injury
(MND-TBI)
Alcohol Use Disorder (AUD) A (2036) 2036
Borderline Personality Disorder A (382) 382
(BPD)
PTSD × MDD PTSD (636,120) × MDD (425) 270,351,000 (270 million or 2.7 × 1010)
PTSD × MDD × SSD PTSD (636,120) × MDD 1,892,457,000 (1.89 billion or 1.89 × 109)
(425) × SSD (7)
PTSD × MDD × SSD × MND-TBI PTSD (636,120) × MDD 1,788,371,865,000 (1.79 trillion or
(425) × SSD (7) × MCD-TBI (945) 1.79 × 1012)
PTSD × MDD × SSD × MND- PTSD (636,120) × MDD 3,641,125,117,140,000 (3.64 quadrillion
TBI × AUD (425) × SSD (7) × MCD-TBI or 3.64 × 1015)
(945) × AUD (2036)
PTSD × MDD × SSD × MND- PTSD (636,120) × MDD 1,390,909,794,747,480,000 (1.39
TBI × AUD × BPD (425) × SSD (7) × MCD-TBI quintillion or 1.39 × 1018)
(945) × AUD (2036) × BPD (382)
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G., Lareau, C., & Pierre, B. (2014). One quin-
tillion ways to have PTSD comorbidity: Recommendations for the disordered DSM-5. Psychological Injury and Law,
7, 61–74; with kind permission from Springer Science + Business Media B. V. [Table 5, Page 68]
Note: The total number of possible combinations for each disorder is calculated by multiplying the possible combina-
tions of each disorder’s symptom criteria clusters. For example, the total number of possible combinations of MND-TBI
was calculated by multiplying the combinations of Criteria A (63) by Criteria B (15), a procedure that gave a total of
925 possible expressions
Possible combinations of comorbid disorders are calculated by multiplying the number of possible combinations for
each of the disorders involved in the comorbidity. For example, a diagnosis of PTSD comorbidly with MDD would have
[B(31) × C(3) × D(120) × E(57)] × [A(425)] or 270,351,000 possible symptom combinations. By including criteria A of
PTSD in this calculation, given that there are 4 types of trauma involved, the total symptom/stressor combination would
be approximately 4 billion combinations. However, the table focuses on symptom combinations alone and does not add
different stressors for PTSD that could cause them
a
For comparison purposes, the estimated amount of stars in the Milky Way is 300 billion (3 × 1011) and in the universe
is 1 septillion (1 × 1024) (Cain 2013; van Dokkum & Conroy, 2010; respectively)

Chapter Conclusions the criticisms of the DSM-5 involve process as


much as product, or how the APA and the DSM
A useful psychiatric diagnostic manual should editors and working groups proceeded in the
reflect practitioner utility requirements in addi- present iteration of the manual.
tion to scientific reliability and validity require- One major effort to improve the research base
ments. However, on both these grounds, the in mental illness has been formulated in the
DSM-5 has been attacked. Also, the manual has RDoC project. However, review of its criticisms,
been criticized for its lack of careful vetting for as presented in this chapter, indicates that, despite
forensic purposes. This illustrates that many of its protestations to the contrary, it is especially
biological/brain-centric/neuroscientific and,
References 607

therefore, devalues the biopsychosocial under- PTSD is quite understood as biopsychosocial


standing of mental illness. In the end, the RDoC in nature, as is its treatment. In this sense, it could
could end up helping the field of psychiatry and be at the vanguard in revising effectively the
psychology in diagnosis and dealing with DSM-5 once its kinks are worked out and it is
patients. However, it has to broaden its scope. protected from forensic disasters. The recom-
When the research in the field seeks to under- mendations to reduce it to its primary, core, and
stand mental illness from the integrative frame- related symptoms, while casting aside as impor-
work of the biopsychosocial perspective, it will tant the common ones it shares with other disor-
be easier to apply toward revising the DSM-5. ders could be relevant in this regard.
In addition to discussing the RDoC and the
DSM-5, in general, the present chapter analyzes
carefully the categories of PTSD in the DSM-5. It References
shows that, as presently conceived, there are
problems with both its reliability and validity. American Psychiatric Association. (1994). Diagnostic
There have been improvements in the construc- and statistical manual of mental disorders (4th ed.).
tion of the PTSD in the DSM-5 relative to the Washington, DC: Author.
DSM-IV-TR. However, with respect to the DSM- American Psychiatric Association. (2000). Diagnostic
and statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM-
5, analyses show that there is even more potential IV-TR (4th ed., text rev.). Washington, DC: Author.
than had been the case in the DSM-IV-TR for dif- American Psychiatric Association. (2013). Diagnostic
ficulties in forensic assessment and application. and statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM-V
For example, in using the DSM-5 approach to (5th ed.). Washington, DC: Author.
Arbisi, P. A., Polusny, M. A., Erbes, C. R., Thuras, P. R.,
PTSD, and considering difficulties with the & Reddy, M. (2011). The Minnesota Multiphasic
DSM-5, itself, there is still room for a potential Personality Inventory-2 restructured form in National
epidemic of unwarranted PTSD litigation in court Guard soldiers screening positive for posttraumatic
and related venues. stress disorder and mild traumatic brain injury.
Psychological Assessment, 23, 203–214.
The concept of endophenotype has been pre- Beauchaine, T. P., & McNulty, T. (2013). Comorbidities
sented in depth in the chapter on PTSD causa- and continuities as ontogenetic processes: Toward a
tion. Briefly, it concerns the pathway from genes developmental spectrum model of externalizing psy-
to disease, and the indices of the pathway and its chopathology. Development and Psychopathology, 25,
1505–1528.
upstream components that can stand as proxies Ben-Porath, Y. S., & Tellegen, A. (2008/2011). The
for the downstream genes involved. However, as Minnesota Multiphasic Personality Inventory-2
with the DSM-5 and the RDoC projects, the Restructured Form (MMPI-2-RF): Manual for admin-
search for endophenotypes of psychiatric disor- istration, scoring, and interpretation. Minnesota, MN:
University of Minnesota Press.
der appears to ignore the biopsychosocial, multi- Berenbaum, H. (2013). Classification and psychopathol-
factorial causality of behavior (etiology). The ogy research. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 122,
work on PTSD in this chapter speaks to the com- 894–901.
plexity of describing sufficiently well the mental Biehn, T. L., Elhai, J. D., Seligman, L. D., Tamburrino,
M., & Forbes, D. (2013). Underlying dimensions of
disorders, the lack of which in the field, in gen- DSM-5 posttraumatic stress disorder and major
eral, stands as an impediment to grasping the depressive disorder symptoms. Psychological Injury
nature of mechanisms underlying behavioral and Law, 6, 290–298.
dysfunctionality. Therefore, the search for endo- Biomarkers Definitions Working Group. (2001).
Biomarkers and surrogate endpoints: Preferred defini-
phenotypes in psychiatry cannot be made sim- tions and conceptual framework. Clinical
plistic. The field needs to adopt a broad Pharmacology & Therapeutics, 69, 89–95.
perspective in seeking to understand the complex Brewin, C. R. (2013). “I wouldn’t start from here” – An
pathway from gene to any disorder. In this regard, alternative perspective on PTSD from the ICD-11:
Comment on Friedman (2013). Journal of Traumatic
the biopsychosocial perspective serves as one Stress, 26, 557–559.
viable model that might be able to contribute to Brewin, C. R., Lanius, R. A., Novac, A., Schnyder, U., &
the task. Galea, S. (2009). Reformulating PTSD for DSM-V:
608 23 The DSM-5 and the RDoC: Grand Designs and Grander Problems

Life after criterion A. Journal of Traumatic Stress, 22, Galatzer-Levy, I. R., Nickerson, A., Litz, B. T., & Marmar,
366–373. C. R. (2013). Patterns of lifetime PTSD comorbidity:
Cain, F. (2013). How many stars are there in the A latent class analysis. Depression and Anxiety, 30,
universe? Retrieved from http://www.universetoday. 489–496.
com/102630/ Goodwin, B. E., Sellbom, M., & Arbisi, P. A. (2013).
Carmassi, C., Akiskal, H. S., Yong, S. S., Stratta, P., Posttraumatic stress disorder in veterans: The utility of
Caderani, E., Massimetti, E., et al. (2013). Post- the MMPI-2-RF Validity Scale in detecting overre-
traumatic stress disorder in DSM-5: Estimates of prev- ported symptoms. Psychological Assessment, 25,
alence and criteria comparison versus DSM-IV-TR in 671–678.
a non-clinical sample of earthquake survivors. Journal Gottesman, I. I., & Gould, T. D. (2003). The endopheno-
of Affective Disorders, 151, 843–848. type concept in psychiatry: Etymology and strategic
Cloitre, M., Garvert, D. W., Brewin, C. R., Bryant, R. A., intentions. American Journal of Psychiatry, 160,
& Maercker, A. (2013). Evidence for proposed ICD- 636–645.
11 PTSD and complex PTSD: A latent profile analysis. Gottesman, I. I., & McGue, M. (2015). Endophenotype.
European Journal of Psychotraumatology, 4. In R. L. Cautin & S. O. Lilienfeld (Eds.),
doi:10.3402/ejpt.v4i0.20706. Wiley-Blackwell encyclopedia of clinical psychology.
Cuthbert, B. N. (2014a). Response to Lilienfeld. Behavior Hoboken, NJ: Wiley. doi:10.1002/9781118625392.
Research and Therapy, 62, 140–142. wbecp423.
Cuthbert, B. N. (2014b). The RDoC framework: Gottesman, I. I., & Shields, J. (1972). Schizophrenia and
Facilitating transition from ICD/DSM to dimensional genetics: A twin study vantage point. New York:
approaches that integrate neuroscience and psychopa- Academic.
thology. World Psychiatry, 12, 28–35. Gould, T. D., & Gottesman, I. I. (2006). Psychiatric endo-
Cuthbert, B. N., & Kozak, M. J. (2013). Constructing con- phenotypes and the development of valid animal mod-
structs for psychopathology: The NIMH research els. Genes, Brain and Behavior, 5, 113–119.
domain criteria. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, Harkness, A. R., Reynolds, S. M., & Lilienfeld, S. O.
122, 928–937. (2014). A review of systems for psychology and psy-
Elhai, J. D., Franklin, C. L., & Gray, M. J. (2008). The chiatry: Adaptive systems, personality psychopathol-
SCID PTSD module’s trauma screen: Validity with ogy five (PSY-5) and the DSM-5. Journal of
two samples in detecting trauma history. Depression Personality Assessment, 96, 121–139.
and Anxiety, 25, 737–741. Hoge, C. W., Riviere, L. A., Wilk, J. E., Herrell, R. K., &
Elhai, J. D., Miller, M. E., Ford, J. D., Biehn, T. L., Weathers, F. W. (2014). The prevalence of post-
Palmieri, P. A., & Frueh, B. C. (2012). Posttraumatic traumatic stress disorder (PTSD) in US combat sol-
stress disorder in DSM-5: Estimates of prevalence and diers: A head-to-head comparison of DSM-5 versus
symptom structure in a nonclinical sample of college DSM-IV-TR symptom criteria with the PTSD check-
students. Journal of Anxiety Disorder, 26, 58–64. list. Lancet Psychiatry, 1, 269–277.
Feil, R. (2008). Epigenetics, an emerging discipline with Horn, C. A. C., Pietrzak, R. H., Corsi-Travali, S., &
broad implications. Comptes Rendus Biologies, 331, Neumeister, A. (2014). Linking plasma cortisol levels
837–843. to phenotypic heterogeneity of posttraumatic stress
First, M. B. (2010). The PTSD stressor criterion as a bar- symptomatology. Psychoneuroendocrinology, 39,
rier to malingering: DSM-5 draft commentaries. 88–93.
Psychological Injury and Law, 3, 255–259. Insel, T. R. (2014). The NIMH research domain criteria
First, M. B. (2014). Preserving the clinician-research (RDoC) project: Precision medicine for psychiatry.
interface in the age of RDoC: The continuing need for American Journal of Psychiatry, 171, 395–397.
DSM-5/ICD-11 characterization of study populations. Insel, T. R., Cuthbert, B. N., Garvey, M. A., Heinssen,
World Psychiatry, 13, 53–54. R. K., Pine, D. S., Quinn, K. J., et al. (2010). Research
Frances, A. (2014). RDoC is necessary, but very oversold. domain criteria (RDoC): Toward a new classification
World Psychiatry, 13, 47–49. framework for research on mental disorders. American
Friedman, M. J., Resick, P. A., Bryant, R. A., & Brewin, Journal of Psychiatry, 167, 748–751.
C. R. (2011). Considering PTSD for DSM-5. Insel, T. R., & Lieberman, J. A. (2013). DSM-5 and
Depression and Anxiety, 28, 750–769. RDoC: Shared interests. The National Institute of
Frueh, B. C., Elhai, J. D., & Acierno, R. (2010). The Mental Health. Retrieved from http://www.nimh.nih.
future of posttraumatic stress disorder in the DSM. gov/news/science-news/2013/dsm-5-and-rdoc-shared--
Psychological Injury and Law, 3, 260–270. interests.shtml
Fulford, K. W. M. (2014). RDoC+: Taking translation Jablensky, A., & Waters, F. (2014). RDoC: A roadmap to
seriously. World Psychiatry, 13, 54–55. pathogenesis? World Psychiatry, 13, 43–44.
Galatzer-Levy, I. R., & Bryant, R. A. (2013). 636,120 Kane, A. W., & Dvoskin, J. A. (2011). Evaluation for per-
ways to have posttraumatic stress disorder. sonal injury claims. New York: Oxford University
Perspectives on Psychological Science, 8, 651–662. Press.
References 609

Kessler, R. C., Sonnega, A., Bromet, E., Hughes, M., & responding, and genuine PTSD. Journal of Personality
Nelson, C. B. (1995). Posttraumatic stress disorder in Assessment, 95, 585–593.
the National Comorbidity Survey. Archives of General McFarlane, A. C. (2014). PTSD and DSM-5: Unintended
Psychiatry, 52, 1048–1060. consequences of change. Lancet Psychiatry, 1,
Kilpatrick, D. G., Resnick, H. S., Milanak, M. E., Miller, 246–247.
M. W., Keyes, K. M., & Friedman, M. J. (2013). McLaughlin, K. A., Koenen, K. C., Hill, E. D., Petukhova,
National estimates of exposure to traumatic events and M., Sampson, N. A., Zaslavsky, A. M., et al. (2013).
PTSD prevalence using DSM-IV and DSM-5 criteria. Trauma exposure and posttraumatic stress disorder in
Journal of Traumatic Stress, 26, 537–547. a national sample of adolescents. Journal of the
King, D. W., Leskin, G. A., King, L. A., & Weathers, American Academy of Child and Adolescent
F. W. (1998). Confirmatory factor analysis of the Psychiatry, 52, 815–830.
clinician-administered PTSD scale: Evidence for the McNally, R. J. (2003). Progress and controversy in the
dimensionality of posttraumatic stress disorder. study of posttraumatic stress disorder. Annual Review
Psychological Assessment, 10, 90–96. of Psychology, 54, 229–252.
Lanius, R. A., Brand, B., Vermetten, E., Frewen, P. A., & McNally, R. J. (2009). Can we fix PTSD in DSMV?
Spiegel, D. (2012). The dissociative subtype of post- Depression and Anxiety, 26, 597–600.
traumatic stress disorder: Rationale, clinical and Meaney, M. J. (2010). Epigenetics and the biological
neurobiological evidence, and implications. definition of gene x environment interactions. Child
Depression and Anxiety, 29, 701–708. Development, 81, 41–79.
Lareau, C. R. (2011). Posttraumatic stress disorder and Miller, M. W., Wolf, E. J., & Keane, T. M. (2014).
acute stress disorder. In D. Faust (Ed.), Coping with Posttraumatic stress disorder in DSM-5: New criteria
psychiatric and psychological testimony (6th ed., and controversies. Clinical Psychology: Science and
pp. 610–635). New York: Oxford University Press. Practice, 21, 208–220.
Larrabee, G. J. (Ed.). (2012). Forensic neuropsychology: Miller, M. W., Wolf, E. J., Kilpatrick, D., Resnick, H.,
A scientific approach (2nd ed.). New York: Oxford Marx, B. P., Holowka, D. W., et al. (2013). The preva-
University Press. lence and latent structure of proposed DSM-5 post-
Lenzenweger, M. F. (2013). Thinking clearly about the traumatic stress disorder symptoms in U.S. national
endophenotype-intermediate phenotype-biomarker and veteran samples. Psychological Trauma: Theory,
distinctions in developmental psychopathology Research, Practice, and Policy, 5, 501–512.
research. Development and Psychopathology, 25, Morris, S. E., & Cuthbert, B. N. (2013). Research domain
1347–1357. criteria: Cognitive systems, neural circuits, and dimen-
Levin, A. P., Kleinman, S. B., & Adler, J. S. (2014). sions of behavior. Dialogues in Clinical Neuroscience,
DSM-5 and posttraumatic stress disorder. Journal of 14, 29–37.
the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law, 42, Morris, S. E., Rumsey, J. M., & Cuthbert, B. N. (2014).
146–158. Rethinking mental disorders: The role of learning and
Lilienfeld, S. O. (2014). The research domain criteria brain plasticity. Restorative Neurology and
(RDoC): An analysis of methodological and concep- Neuroscience, 32, 5–23.
tual challenges. Behaviour Research and Therapy, 62, Müller, M., Vandeleur, C., Rodgers, S., Rössler, W.,
129–139. Castelao, E., Preisig, M., et al. (2014). Factors associ-
Lynn, S. J., Lilienfeld, S. O., Merckelbach, H., Giesbrecht, ated with comorbidity patterns in full and partial
T., & van der Kloet, D. (2012). Dissociation and disso- PTSD: Findings from the PsyCoLaus study.
ciative disorders: Challenging conventional wisdom. Comprehensive Psychiatry, 55, 837–848.
Current Directions in Psychological Science, 21, 48–53. Owen, M. J. (2012). Implications of genetic findings for
Maercker, A., Brewin, C. R., Bryant, R. A., Cloitre, M., understanding schizophrenia. Schizophrenia Bulletin,
Reed, G. M., van Ommeren, M., et al. (2013). 38, 904–907.
Proposals for mental disorders specifically associated Panagioti, M., Gooding, P., Taylor, P. T., & Tarrier, N.
with stress in the International Classification of (2013). A model of suicidal behavior in posttraumatic
Diseases-11. The Lancet, 381, 1683–1685. stress disorder (PTSD): The mediating role of defeat
Maj, M. (2014). Keeping an open attitude toward the and entrapment. Psychiatric Research, 209, 55–59.
RDoC project. World Psychiatry, 13, 1–3. Parnas, J. (2014). The RDoC program: Psychiatry without
Marion, B. E., Sellbom, M., & Bagby, R. M. (2011). The psyche? World Psychiatry, 13, 46–47.
detection of feigned psychiatric disorders using the Phillips, M. R. (2014). Will RDoC hasten the decline of
MMPI-2-RF overreporting validity scales: An analog America’s global leadership role in mental health?
investigation. Psychological Injury and Law, 4, 1–12. World Psychiatry, 13, 40–41.
Mason, L. H., Shandera-Ochsner, A. L., Williamson, Pietrzak, R. H., Galea, S., Southwick, S. M., & Gelernter,
K. D., Harp, J. P., Edmundson, M., Berry, D. T., et al. J. (2013). Examining the relation between serotonin
(2013). Accuracy of MMPI-2-RF validity scales for transporter 5-HTTLPR genotype x trauma exposure
identifying feigned PTSD symptoms, random interaction on a contemporary phenotypic model of
610 23 The DSM-5 and the RDoC: Grand Designs and Grander Problems

posttraumatic stress symptomatology: A pilot study. Whooley, O. (2014). Nosological reflections: The failure
Journal of Affective Disorders, 148, 123–128. of DSM-5, the emergence of RDoC, and the decontex-
Post, L. M., Zoellner, L. A., Youngstrom, E., & Feeny, tualization of mental distress. Society and Mental
N. C. (2011). Understanding the relationship between Health, 4, 92–110.
co-occurring PTSD and MDD: Symptom severity and Wilkinson, L. S., Davies, W., & Iseles, A. R. (2007).
affect. Journal of Anxiety Disorders, 25, 1123–1130. Genomic imprinting effects on brain development and
Rasetti, R., & Weinberger, D. R. (2011). Intermediate function. Nature Reviews of Neuroscience, 8, 832–843.
phenotypes in psychiatric disorders. Current Opinions Wisdom, N. M., Pastorek, N. J., Miller, B. I., Booth, J. E.,
in Genetics & Development, 21, 340–348. Romesser, J. M., Linck, J. F., et al. (2014). PTSD and
Rosen, G. M., & Grunert, B. K. (2012). Posttraumatic cognitive functioning: Importance of including perfor-
stress disorder in the workplace. In S. S. Bush & G. L. mance validity test. The Clinical Neuropsychologist,
Iverson (Eds.), Neuropsychological assessment of 28, 128–145.
work-related injuries (pp. 163–186). New York: Wolf, E. J., & Miller, M. W. (2014). The Minnesota
Guilford Press. Multiphasic Personality Inventory-2 Restructured
Rytwinski, N. K., Scur, M. D., Feeny, N. C., & Form and posttraumatic stress disorder: Forensic
Youngstrom, E. A. (2013). The co-occurrence of applications and considerations. Psychological Injury
major depressive disorder among individuals with and Law, 7, 143–152.
posttraumatic stress disorder: A meta-analysis. Wolf, E. J., Miller, M. W., Kilpatrick, D., Resnick, H. S.,
Journal of Traumatic Stress, 26, 299–309. Badour, C. L., Marx, B. P., et al. (2014). ICD-11 com-
Sartorius, N. (2014). The only one or one of many? A plex PTSD in U.S. national and veteran samples:
comment on the RDoC project. World Psychiatry, 13, Prevalence and structural associations with PTSD.
50–51. Clinical Psychological Science, 3, 215–229.
Shields, J., & Gottesman, I. I. (1973). Genetic studies Wolf, E. J., Miller, M. W., Reardon, A. F., Ryabchenko,
of schizophrenia as signposts to biochemistry. In K. A., Castillo, D., & Freund, R. (2012). A latent class
L. L. Iverson & S. Rose (Eds.), Biochemistry and analysis of dissociation and posttraumatic stress disor-
mental illness (Biochemistry Society Special der: Evidence for a dissociative subtype. Archives of
Publication) (Vol. 1, pp. 165–174). London: General Psychiatry, 69, 698–705.
Biochemical Society. World Health Organization. (2017). International
Simmons, J. M., & Quinn, K. J. (2014). The NIMH Classification of Disease, 11th Revision.
Research Domain Criteria (RDoC) project: Young, G. (2013). Breaking bad: DSM-5 description,
Implications for genetics research. Mammalian criticism, and recommendations. Psychological Injury
Genome, 25, 23–31. and Law, 6, 345–348.
Simms, L. J., Watson, D., & Doebbeling, B. N. (2002). Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feigning, and response
Confirmatory factor analyses of posttraumatic stress bias in psychiatric/psychological injury: Implications
symptoms in deployed and nondeployed veterans of for practice and court. Dordrecht, Netherlands:
the gulf war. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 111, Springer Science + Business Media.
637–647. Young, G., Lareau, C., & Pierre, B. (2014). One quintil-
Sonuga-Barke, E. J. S. (2014). Editorial: ‘What’s up, (R) lion ways to have PTSD comorbidity:
DoC?’ – can identifying core dimensions of early Recommendations for the Disordered DSM-5.
functioning help us understand, and then reduce, Psychological Injury and Law, 7, 61–74.
developmental risk for mental disorders? Journal of Yufik, T., & Simms, L. J. (2010). A meta-analytic investi-
Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 55, 849–851. gation of the structure of posttraumatic stress disorder
Sporns, O. (2011). Networks of the brain. Cambridge, symptoms. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 119,
MA: MIT Press. 764–776.
Sporns, O. (2012). Discovering the human connectome. Zlotnick, C., Johnson, D. M., Yen, S., Battle, C. L.,
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Sanislow, C. A., Skodol, A. E., et al. (2003). Clinical
Stein, D. J. (2014). An integrative approach to psychiatric features and impairment in women with borderline
diagnosis and research. World Psychiatry, 13, 51–53. personality disorder (BPD) with posttraumatic stress
van Dokkum, P., & Conroy, C. (2010). A substantial pop- disorder (PTSD), BPD without PTSD, and other per-
ulation of low-mass stars in luminous elliptical galax- sonality disorders with PTSD. Journal of Nervous and
ies. Nature, 468, 940–942. Mental Disorders, 191, 706–714.
Wakefield, J. C. (2014). Wittgenstein’s nightmare: Why Zoellner, L. A., Bedard-Gilligan, M. A., Jun, J. J., Marks,
the RDoC grid needs a conceptual dimension. World L. H., & Garcia, N. M. (2013). The evolving construct
Psychiatry, 13, 38–39. of posttraumatic stress disorder (PTSD): DSM-5 crite-
Weathers, F., Marx, B. P., Friedman, M. J., & Schnurr, ria changes and legal implications. Psychological
P. P. (2014). Posttraumatic stress disorder in the DSM- Injury and Law, 6, 277–289.
5: New criteria, new measures, and implications for Zoellner, L. A., Pruitt, L. D., Farach, F. J., & Jun, J. J.
assessment. Psychological Injury and Law, 7, 93–107. (2014). Understanding heterogeneity in PTSD: Fear,
Weinberger, D. R., & Goldberg, T. E. (2014). RDoCs dysphoria, and distress. Depression and Anxiety, 31,
redux. World Psychiatry, 13, 36–37. 97–106.
The Disordered DSM-5 Disorders
24

and removed in the DSM-5. The chapter also


Chapter Introduction deals with other aspects of the DSM-5, such as
personality disorder and malingering, while pro-
This chapter is the second of two chapters on posing an improved definition of the latter, as
specific categories in the DSM-5 (Diagnostic and well. By way of introducing a nosological
Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, Fifth approach different from the one that underwrites
Edition; American Psychiatric Association, 2013) the DSM project, the chapter concludes by exam-
related to psychological injury. In particular, the ining the approach of the ICD-11 (International
chapter deals with Neurocognitive Disorder Classification of Disorders, 11th Edition, World
(NCD) and Somatic Symptom Disorder (SSD). Health Organization, 2017) to PTSD.
The last chapter had shown that Posttraumatic
Stress Disorder (PTSD), as presented in the
DSM-5, is open to much criticism and also much Neurocognitive Disorder
uncertainty, and even to potential abuse in court
and related venues. The present chapter finds the Table 24.1 indicates that the DSM-5 (Diagnostic
same for NCD and SSD but, unfortunately, even and Statistical Manual for Mental Disorders,
to a greater degree than for PTSD. For both of the Fifth Edition; American Psychiatric Association,
disorders of focus in the present chapter (NCD 2013) diagnosis of Mild Neurocognitive Disorder
and SSD), it compares and contrasts the (NCD) leaves it open to much criticism and diag-
approaches taken in the DSM-IV-TR (Diagnostic nostic uncertainty. It is juxtaposed to Major
and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, NCD, with no intermediate Moderate level. The
Fourth Edition; Text Revision American type of neuropsychological or equivalent testing
Psychiatric Association, 2000) and in the DSM-5. needed to be undertaken for its diagnosis is not
The chapter critically reviews the changes from clearly specified, leaving it open to different
one edition to the next in these disorders. Also, it approaches that might lead to opposite conclu-
makes recommendations to improve both disor- sions in forensic cases.
ders in the next version of the DSM (DSM-5.1). Blazer (2013) cautioned that distinguishing
In particular, for NCD, it recommends that the between Mild and Major NCD has been chal-
exclusion of a moderate NCD in the DSM-5 is lenged as subjective and artificial. There is no
unwarranted and needs to be corrected. As for marker available for the distinction. It risks being
SSD, it proposes a quite revised approach to its misused.
criteria so that it respects better the category of Schultz (2010) had commented on NCD in the
pain disorder that had been in the DSM-IV-TR draft version of the DSM-5. She noted significant

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 611


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_24
612 24 The Disordered DSM-5 Disorders

Table 24.1 Mild neurocognitive disorder (TBI-related) in DSM-5


Criterion Descriptor Comment
A “Modest” cognitive decline Does “modest” mean mild or
moderate? It is acknowledged
in this regard that “precise
thresholds difficult to
determine” (p. 608)
A1 Mild decline –
A2 Modest impairment Mild or moderate?
Presumably documented Presumably?
Standardized neuropsychological testing or an Can any other assessment
equivalent quantified clinical assessment, including be equivalent?
“bedside” examination (in Table 1, p. 593).
B Does not interfere with ADLs, but greater effort/ However, it is acknowledged
compensation/accommodation possible there is “subtle” interference.
Moreover, is this criterion B
not more than a “subtle
interference?”
Neuropsychological testing Major: ≥ 2 SD (i.e., ≤ 3rd percentile) Too conservative?
thresholds (diagnostic feature) Minor: 1–2 SD (i.e., 3rd–16th percentile) Moderate?
Specifier Behavioral disturbance possible (e.g., clinically If attributed to mild case, is
significant psychotic, mood, agitation, apathy it still mild?
symptoms)
TBI specifiers In giving a diagnosis, the disorder is rated mild Room for confusion?
or moderate; the TBI is not rated
Functional (re TBI) Reported depressive symptoms could amplify Still mild?
cognitive and functional effects

questions on conceptual, evidentiary, psychomet- notable deficit for forensic principles in the 2013
ric, assessment, and practical bases. Moreover, final version of the diagnostic category of NCD
forensically, she noted room for loophole diagno- remains omission of the level of moderate
ses related to traumatic brain injury (TBI). She NCD. Therefore, cases of acquired TBI at this
reasoned that omission of a level of moderate level of cognitive disorder likely will be assigned
NCD will lead to incorrect classification of peo- a mild rather than a major category [the mild case
ple at this level into the less severe minor cate- had been referred to as minor in the draft version.]
gory. She queried the legitimacy of the threshold This greatly increases the risks under-representing
for the minor category at 1 standard deviation TBI at the moderate level. Moreover, the mild
(SD) below the mean (or the 16th percentile level of NCD is defined ambiguously enough to
level) in neuropsychological testing, which is over-represent nonproblematic concussion cases
typically considered low-average in (residual) within its range. Relative to the draft of the DSM-5
ability and, therefore, not an impairment. available in 2010, the final 2013 version now only
Moreover, Schultz (2010) wondered to what the prefers rather than prescribes neuropsychological
percentile ratings actually refer (e.g., single or assessment or quantification. Nevertheless,
multiple testing, one-session or multiple visits, according to Schultz (2013), the manner in which
comparison to population norms or pre-injury the criterion involved is phrased will further push
baseline). Forensically, Schultz (2010) concluded moderately injured TBI evaluees into the mild cat-
that the NCD diagnosis as presented does not egory. Other issues that had been raised by Schultz
adequately consider traumatic brain injury and (2013) included lack of guidelines for neuropsy-
the complexities of forensic practice. chological assessment and overreliance on effects
Schultz (2013) updated her 2010 (Schultz, on ADLs (activities of daily living) relative to
2010) evaluation of NCD in the DSM-5. The most other roles (e.g., work effects). To conclude, the
Somatic Symptom Disorder 613

category of mild NCD due to a traumatic brain diagnosing chronic pain from a psychological
injury is presented in a way that could prevent perspective, it has been considered a specifier of
successful claims when apparently warranted Somatic Symptom Disorder (SSD). In the DSM-
(Simpson, 2014). 5, somatoform disorders are now referred to as
somatic symptom and related disorders, and
SSD is one of them. The classification reduces
Somatic Symptom Disorder1 the number of these disorders and subcategories
to avoid problematic overlap that was present in
Chronic Pain in the DSM-IV-TR the DSM-IV-TR. Specifically, in the DSM-5,
aside from not including pain disorder, the diag-
From a psychological perspective, in the DSM- noses of somatization disorder, hypochondriasis,
IV-TR (Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of and undifferentiated somatoform disorder have
Mental Disorders, Fourth Edition, Text Revised; been removed.
American Psychiatric Association, 2000), Table 24.2 indicates that, in the DSM-5, SSD
chronic pain could be diagnosed as a separate can be used to specify pain as a predominant
disorder in the category of general somatoform complaint. However, there is no place for a
disorders; the label used was of pain disorder. diagnosis involving pain itself. In this regard,
The critical feature of pain disorder in the the difficulties with the new superordinate diag-
DSM-IV-TR is that pain experience presents as nosis of SSD in the DSM-5 could present con-
the predominant clinical focus and at a suffi- siderable complications for pain patients,
cient intensity level to warrant clinical atten- especially in the forensic or disability context.
tion. Another major aspect of pain disorder in How would a plaintiff’s legitimate pain com-
the DSM-IV-TR is that the pain is at the origin plaints from a psychological perspective be
of either (a) a distress that reaches clinical sig- received in court if there is no accompanying
nificance or (b) an impairment in important pain disorder diagnosis? Moreover, the new
areas (or area) of function (social/occupa- SSD was supposed to remove the subtle nega-
tional). The DSM-IV-TR requires specifying tive attribution associated with pain complaints
the chronicity of pain disorder (acute or that it is “all in the head.” However, although the
chronic). Importantly, pain disorder in the criteria appear to exclude “medically unex-
DSM-IV-TR could be qualified as involving a plained symptoms” as a factor, this type of stig-
general medical condition, psychological fac- matizing language still appears. Overall, in the
tors, or both (with the first option not consid- DSM-5, the option of pain-based diagnosis in
ered a psychological disorder itself). The terms of SSD only gives much room to deny
DSM-IV-TR conceptualization of pain disorder valid claims in court-type cases.
had been criticized as categorical and dualistic The developers of the DSM-5 purported that it
because its options include separation of psy- takes a different approach to the clinical realm of
chological factors and medical ones (Melzack individuals with pain because there are multiple
& Katz, 2006). avenues to consider its psychological effects. In
the DSM-5, individuals with chronic pain could
be diagnosed not only as having somatic SSD
Chronic Pain in the DSM-5 with predominant pain but also as exhibiting
either psychological factors affecting other medi-
Perhaps consistent with these criticisms, in the cal conditions or an adjustment disorder. As will
DSM-5, pain disorder has not been included as a be discussed later, this conceptualization is not
separate disorder. Instead, in particular, in without controversy. First, I examine SSD in
more depth and make suggestions to improve its
1
This section is based on Young (2013). diagnostic criteria.
614 24 The Disordered DSM-5 Disorders

Table 24.2 Somatic symptom disorder in DSM-5


Criterion Descriptor Comment
Exclusion Cannot be given in cases in which only a “medical Good
cause” has not been demonstrated
Inclusion Positive psychological symptoms required Good
(cognitive, affective, physical, behavioral)
Expression Personal suffering in sociocultural context Draft had referred directly to “biopsychosocial”
A “distressing” somatic symptoms(s) or “significant Ambiguous: why not use the usual “clinically
disruption in daily life” significant impairment in social, occupational,
and other important functional areas”
B Positive symptoms: Excessive (a) thoughts, (b) One or more required
anxiety, (c) time/energy devotion
C Persistent (typically, > 6 months), not necessarily Ambiguous: can it really come and go?
continuous
Specifier Somatic complaints “with predominant pain” Can this really capture the appropriate diagnosis
involve pain mostly of an individual experiencing psychologically-
mediated chronic pain?
Specifier “Persistent”: severe symptoms, marked Confusion with C; moreover, this is more than
impairment, and long duration (>6 months) persistent, as “severe” mentioned
Specifier Severity: mild = 1 symptom from B; moderate = 2; Confusion with “persistence” severity based on
severe = 2 symptoms, and also either (a) multiple either number or intensity of positive symptoms
somatic complaints or (b) one very severe one or somatic complaints, which is also confusing
Feature The person’s “suffering” is “authentic,” whether or So “medically unexplained symptoms” seem
not it is medically explained implicit in this diagnosis; not good
Feature Concurrent medical condition frequently co-occurs Good

Somatic Symptom Disorder health involved; and “excessive” time/energy


in the DSM-5 devoted to the symptom(s)/health. Criterion C
specifies that the duration must be more than 6
Major Criteria There are three major criteria months. The other two specifiers relate to per-
(A, B, C) for SSD in the DSM-5, coded as 300.82 sistence (present, absent) and severity (mild,
(and as F45.1 in the ICD; International moderate, severe).
Classification of Diseases system). Also, there are It is instructive to note that the DSM-5 draft’s
three specifiers, one of which is whether the recommendations to measure severity using cer-
somatic symptoms involved especially (“predom- tain recommended tests were not implemented in
inantly”) concern pain. the final version. This decision to abandon sever-
The first diagnostic criterion (A) for SSD is ity evaluation in the final version of the DSM-5
whether there is at least one somatic symptom appears to have happened in multiple places.
that is “distressing” to the patient, or that results
Criticism The DSM-5 proposal for SSD has
in “significant disruption” in daily living. The
met with telling criticism. Sykes (2012) queried
second diagnostic criterion (B) concerns
whether the construct of medically unexplained
whether there are thoughts/feelings/behaviors
physical symptoms, which have been overtly
about either the somatic symptom(s) or “associ-
removed from consideration in diagnosing the
ated health concerns” that are “excessive.” This
disorder, is still implicitly present. The category
criterion is indexed by at least one of the follow-
is considered weak, without a unifying principle,
ing: “disproportionate/persistent thinking about
and it leaves room for ambiguity. He queried why
the symptom(s)’ “seriousness;” persistent anxi-
a patient with a serious medical condition and
ety at a “high” level about the symptom(s)/
who shows concern for it should receive a mental
Somatic Symptom Disorder 615

disorder diagnosis. At the same time, he queried be offered only if it is maladaptive, extreme,
whether there are sufficient psychological criteria intrusive, impairing, grossly in excess, and so on,
in the diagnosis. in relation to diagnosed medical illnesses.
Frances and Chapman (2013) argued that the Rief and Martin (2014) criticized the decision
diagnostic thresholds for SSD are loose and will in the DSM-5 to abolish the distinction in Somatic
lead to false positive diagnoses. In diagnosing Symptom and Related Disorders of medically
patients, instead of using SSD, they suggested explained and medically unexplained somatic
use of adjustment disorder for cases of medical symptoms. They suggested splitting somatic
illness with psychological features. Frances symptom disorder into medically unexplained
(2013a) indicated that SSD could be used to mis- ones that are either mono- or poly-symptomatic,
label “a sizeable proportion of the population as and also including a type that is with a recog-
mentally ill” (because of its over-inclusive for- nized biomedical condition. In addition, they
mulation). For example, Dimsdale (2012) found advocated for the separation of pain disorder as a
it has a false positive rate of 7 % of healthy peo- distinct classification (as well as illness anxiety
ple in the general population. Frances (2013b) disorder).
added that its set of criteria seems subjective, Young (2010) addressed the decision in the
unreliable, and easy to meet. He considered it a DSM-5 of placing pain symptoms solely as a
“fatally flawed” “pseudodiagnosis” that will specifier of SSD. His main concerns with this
harm people. Rief, Mewes, Martin, Glaesmer, diagnostic approach, given SSD’s de-emphasis of
and Brähler (2011) found the criteria for SSD pain as primarily psychological, were that
“restrictive.” Sirri and Fava (2013) maintained patients with valid pain disorders would have
that the diagnosis appears to neglect “important their treatment needs questioned and their foren-
clinical phenomena,” such as “illness denial.” sic cases complicated. Moreover, the pejorative
Wollburg, Voigt, Braukhaus, Herzog, and Löwe (or stigmatizing) connotations associated with
(2013) recommended that criterion B should be the label would still exist, given the stigmatizing
split. Instead of one criterion on expressing dispro- properties of SSD, and given the frequent lack of
portionate and persistent thoughts about the seri- medical evidence of an injury and the frequent
ousness of symptoms experienced, there should be lack of one-to-one correspondence in a dose–
separate criteria of a self-concept of bodily weak- response relationship to physical injury and pain
ness and of somatic illness attribution. experience (Young, Kane, & Nicholson, 2007).
Frances (2013b) offered a revised version of At the forensic level, in contested cases, which
the clinical diagnostic criteria that included hav- are typical for pain patients, one side or the other
ing all three B symptoms rather than just one as will claim that the evidence is not as clear as
necessary for the diagnosis. He added that the stated by the other side (i.e., for or against, as the
criterion found for other disorders—of a signifi- case may be). When dealing with pain patients,
cant disruption/impairment—needs to be added this has been the case for diagnoses involving the
to SSD. He recommended that when a medical DSM-IV-TR, and the situation will be worse with
condition is certified as present, a criterion the DSM-5. It has implemented major changes in
should be added that the B symptoms should be how chronic pain is considered diagnostically,
“grossly in excess” of expectations. Moreover, a and they will function to increase confusion,
criterion is needed such that if no medical condi- legal contests, and quagmires in court.
tion is present, medical work-ups at suitable
intervals should be conducted to see if they
become ruled in. Also, he added the need for the My Specific Concerns for SSD
typical exclusionary clause about the disorder
not being diagnosed if better explained by a med- Table 24.3 examines critically some of the
ical disorder. In short, the SSD diagnosis should major points of contention in the SSD criteria.
616 24 The Disordered DSM-5 Disorders

Table 24.3 Comments on somatic symptom disorder in DSM-5 (American Psychiatric Association, 2013)
Criterion Descriptor Article Author’s Comment
Exclusion “Inappropriate” to diagnose in cases in which a Strong criterion
“medical cause” has not been “demonstrated”
Inclusion Positive psychological symptoms required Strong criterion
(cognitive, affective, physical, behavioral)
Expression Personal suffering in sociocultural context Draft had referred directly to “biopsychosocial”
A “distressing” somatic symptoms(s) or “significant Ambiguous: why not use the usual “clinically
disruption in daily life” significant impairment in social, occupational,
and other important functional areas”
B Positive symptoms: Excessive (a) thoughts, (b) One or more
anxiety, (c) time/energy devotion
C Persistent (typically, > 6 months), not necessarily Ambiguous: can it really come and go?
continuous
Specifier Somatic complaints “with predominant pain” Can this really capture the appropriate diagnosis
involve pain mostly of an individual experiencing psychologically-
mediated chronic pain?
Specifier “Persistent”: severe symptoms, marked Confusion with C; moreover, this is more than
impairment, and long duration (>6 months) persistent, as “severe” mentioned
Specifier Severity: mild = 1 symptom from B; moderate = 2; Confusion with “persistence” Severity based on
severe = 2 symptoms, and also either (a) multiple either number or intensity of positive symptoms
somatic complaints or (b) one very severe one or somatic complaints, which is also confusing
Feature The person’s “suffering” is “authentic,” whether or So “medically unexplained symptoms” seem
not it is medically explained implicit in this diagnosis; not appropriate
Feature Concurrent medical condition frequently co-occurs Good point

Some of the components in SSD are quite the category of SSD involving pain as a
positive, for example, it includes both specifier.
positive and negative symptoms , which is a
good distinction to make in defining
any psychologically-based somatic disorder. Alternative Diagnoses Involving Pain
Moreover, it includes cognitive, affective, in the DSM-5
behavioral, and physical symptoms, which is
a good idea for the same reason. However, Adjustment Disorder Note that the DSM-5 rec-
some of the terms in the diagnostic criteria of ommends alternative diagnoses to SDD (and the
SSD are ambiguous, such as the case for the pain specifier) for patients in pain. One option is to
terms of distress, disruption of daily life, per- diagnose an adjustment disorder, and another one
sistence, and severity. Moreover, SDD impli- is psychological factors affecting other medical
cates the need for a medical analysis, which conditions. From a psychological perspective, nei-
might be difficult to ascertain. ther of these options appears fully adequate to
One of the goals in revising SSD criteria describe the predominant pain complaints that
was to exclude “medically unexplained symp- characterize pain patients. For example, the
toms” as a factor, as mentioned. However, as DSM-5 text for adjustment disorder does not men-
noted it could be argued that this type of stig- tion pain as an identifiable stressor that could be
matizing language still appears. Overall, it can involved in causing its psychological symptoms.
be concluded that, not all the problems associ- That being said, the text in the DSM-5 for adjust-
ated with the DSM-IV-TR’s conceptualization ment disorder does mention that a medical condi-
of the diagnosis of pain disorder have been tion or illness can be considered sufficient as an
resolved in the DSM-5 by its replacement with identifiable stressor (p. 289, p. 323). Moreover, it
Recommendations for the DSM-5.1 617

might be argued that adjustment to chronic dis- being said, the manual does refer to early trauma,
ability, disease/condition, or illness is implicit in learning, cultural and social factors in the contri-
attributing the disorder. Nevertheless, without the butions to the genetic and biological vulnerabili-
option of the DSM-IV-TR’s pain disorder and only ties in somatic symptom and related disorders.]
having SSD available as a diagnosis, or perhaps Indeed, the term biopsychosocial was removed
adjustment disorder, as in the DSM-5, one could from inclusion in the 2010 draft of the DSM-5 for
argue that mental health assessors in the conten- the 2013 version.
tious area of psychological injuries who are con- The biopsychosocial nature of pain is illus-
ducting psychological assessments will be trated by studies on the effects of loneliness on its
incapable of establishing a valid diagnosable med- experience (Jaremka et al., 2014; Wolf & Davis,
ical disease/condition or disability directly related 2014). Also, goal-related behavior influences it
to the psychological difficulties associated with (Ewart, Elder, Laird, Shelby, & Walker, 2014;
pain experience. Karoly, Okun, Enders, & Tennen, 2014). In this
regard, that cognitive-behavior therapy can help
Psychological Factors Affecting Other Medical is noteworthy, as well (Kerns et al., 2014). The
Conditions As for psychological factors affect- complexity of pain experience is illustrated by
ing other medical conditions, its use in the the mutual maintenance influences on it and on
DSM-5 does apply to “idiopathic” medical symp- comorbid conditions (Ruiz-Párraga & López-
toms, including pain (p. 322), as well as pain- Martínez, 2014).
related functional syndromes (e.g., migraines). In attempting to diagnose patients with pain
Once more, the mention of medical pain and conditions, there is a frequent lack of one-to-one
headache symptoms presents problems to mental correspondence, or a dose–response relationship,
health assessors, who not being qualified as med- involving physical injury and pain experience
ical doctors, might have difficulty establishing (Gatchel et al., 2007; Melzack & Katz, 2012).
that these conditions are actually in the file and Psychological and social factors appear impor-
that the disorder can be attributed to the patient. tant contributors in understanding chronic pain.
Moreover, my concern is that in contested cases, Given the problems elucidated in the DSM-5’s
which are typical for pain patients, one side or the approach to chronic pain, in the following, I offer
other will claim that the evidence for or against an alternative diagnosis to SSD, termed Chronic
the pain-related medical condition is not as clear Pain Complications Disorder. Not only does it
as stated (i.e., for or against as the case may be). consider the biopsychosocial model, but also it
preserves the advantages found in SSD, as per
Table 24.3, while avoiding its disadvantages.
Recommendations for the DSM-5.1

Understanding Chronic Pain Chronic Pain Complications Disorder

The failure to consider chronic pain as the possi- In part, the present proposal on Chronic Pain
ble basis for a psychological disorder, as has Complications Disorder builds on Frances’s
occurred by elimination of pain disorder in the (2013b) proposal for a revised SSD. For exam-
DSM-5, is not consistent with current under- ple, rather than referring to excessive and persis-
standing of its nature. Further in this regard, tent preoccupations with somatic symptoms, as
although a biopsychosocial model seems appro- in the DSM-5, in his proposal in how to revise it,
priate in understanding and diagnosing pain con- he referred also to maladaptive, clearly dispro-
ditions (e.g., Gatchel, Peng, Peters, Fuchs, & portionate, intrusive, and extreme ones. Note
Turk, 2007), this term does not appear anywhere that I did not follow fully Frances’s (2013b) sug-
in the DSM-5, let alone in the pain section. [That gestion to have all three of cognitive, emotional,
618 24 The Disordered DSM-5 Disorders

and behavioral symptoms necessarily present to This replacement condition of SSD can be used in
receive a SSD diagnosis instead of only one or the next iteration of the DSM-5. The proposed
the other of them, as found in the DSM-5. Rather, pain category would help avoid some of the diffi-
I opted for the intermediate position of having culties associated with SSD in the DSM-5 and the
any two of these three symptoms present in the lack of a separate diagnostic entity from a psycho-
patient/evaluee to meet the threshold for the logical perspective in the DSM-5 for chronic pain.
cluster. This decision represents a balanced My proposal for a new DSM category of
approach. Chronic Pain Complications Disorder involves
Table 24.4 gives criteria for the proposed diag- five major criteria. (a) First, the patient/evaluee
nosis of Chronic Pain Complications Disorder. presents with pain in one or more anatomical

Table 24.4 Proposal for DSM 5.1: chronic pain complications disorder (diagnostic criteria)
Criterion Explanation
I. Apparent Authentic Biopsychosocial Presentation/Causation
A. Pain in one or more anatomical sites is distressing and is the predominant focus of the
clinical presentation
B. The pain causes clinically significant impairment in social, occupational, or other
important areas of functioning (post-pain onset complications)
C. Psychological factors are judged to have an important role in the onset, severity,
exacerbation, or maintenance of the pain (excessive, persistent, maladaptive thoughts,
feelings, or behaviors), as manifested by at least two of the following:
(a) thoughts about the symptom seriousness;
(b) anxiety about the experienced pain and its perceived consequences;
(c) time and energy expended about them
D. The symptom or deficit is not intentionally produced or feigned (as in Factitious
Disorder or Malingering)
E. The pain is not better accounted for by another disorder
Specifier
Duration: Acute: < 6 months Chronic: ≥ 6 months
Specifier
Severity: Mild Moderate Severe
Consider not diagnosing SSD Consider diagnosing SSD as a This level is definitely
as clinical, given its feature or subsyndromally, SSD
manageability at this level although this level is hard to
manage
Pain reported □ □ □
Distress reported □ □ □
Impairment reported □ □ □
II. If Confusing or Complicated Presentation/Causation
Specify Degree of Feigning, if any
□ Minor exaggeration □ Gross exaggeration □ Outright malingering
Specify Source of Confusion, if any
□ Can be fully explained by pre-existing factors (e.g., psychopathology)
□ Pre-existing factors exacerbate the pain
□ Post-onset factors exacerbate the pain (e.g., family, work, litigation, distress)
Specify Certainty of These Ratings
□ Unsure □ Some data □ Clear data
Note. All terms and qualifiers that could be ambiguous or contentious must be attributed only if clearly evidenced and
documented and go beyond the minimal/mild and, if applicable, the moderate range, as the case may be, for example:
(a) Excessive and persistent psychological factors in the pain experience; (b) Severe pain/distress/impairment; (c) Gross
exaggeration/malingering; and (d) Pre-existing and post-onset factors, as well as any extraneous factors (e.g., an unre-
lated death of a loved one)
Recommendations for the DSM-5.1 619

sites, and the pain is distressing and predominant a physiological origin and constitute expression
in focus. (b) Second, the pain disrupts in the per- of a disease, but psychological and social contri-
son important activities of daily life (social, butions could make it more for the patient than
occupational, etc.); this criterion constitutes the simply a medical disease.
focus in diagnosing clinical complications due to (d) Fourth, the proposal is detailed and clear
the pain experience. (c) Third, psychological fac- enough to help explain the diagnosis to patients/
tors are involved in the onset, severity, evaluees when it is attributed. Moreover, the table
exacerbation, or maintenance of the pain experi- presenting it refers to the need for evidence and
ence, or any combination of these factors. In this documentation so that the patient ends up more
regard, for the pain symptoms presented by the assured that than otherwise would be the case
person, there are excessive thoughts (re serious- about the validity of the diagnosis and, more
ness), feelings (e.g., anxiety), or behaviors (time/ important, the validity of their pain experience (it
energy spent). (d) Fourth, the person does not is not simply “all in their head”).
express feigning, dissimulation, or malingering, (e) Finally, by using more precise criteria that
and the like. (e) Fifth, the person’s symptoms need documentation before attribution, and also
cannot be accounted for by another DSM-5 dis- by acknowledging the issue that the patient’s pain
order. Further, specifiers relate to chronicity could be influenced by biopsychosocial factors, it
(chronic at 6 months or more), severity (re pain, becomes easier for the clinician/evaluator to rec-
distress, impairment), patient/evaluee validity ommend psychosocial intervention or psycho-
(credibility), and causality. therapy, aside from whatever pharmaceutical
There are several notable advantages to the medications might be prescribed. The current
present proposal for criteria of a new DSM cate- point indicates that the present proposal might
gory of Chronic Pain Complications Disorder. I make it easier to avoid undue influence of phar-
enumerate the following. maceutical companies on clinical practice and, as
(a) First, the proposal addresses the issue of well, serve to moderate the role that they might
diagnostic inflation by tightening the amount of have had in influencing the DSM-5 construction
subcriteria necessary for the diagnosis (in the process, while advocating for non-medicinal
polythetic Criterion C). It is conservative enough (psychological and related) solutions to patients’
to exclude milder or ambiguous cases. pain experience.
(b) Second, the proposal includes qualifiers The disorder proposed contains clauses that
that the assessor needs to arrive at conclusions consider whether the diagnosis is valid in terms
with documented evidence when considering of the need to rule out feigning, dissimulation,
terms such as: excessive; severe; distress; pre- gross exaggeration, malingering, etc., thereby
existing factors; and malingering. Given the dif- making it useful forensically. Of course, similar
ficulties and ambiguities associated with these clauses can be appended to any of the psycho-
terms, much work is needed on any accompany- logical injuries (e.g., PTSD, TBI, and major
ing text for the proposal so that it is clinically depression or any depressive disorder or anxiety
useful and scientifically valid. disorder when it develops after an event at issue).
(c) Third, the proposal avoids dualistic notions However, these other disorders already are
of pain. It refers to anatomically located pain, described in the DSM-5. In contrast, for pain
without anatomically-located a medical or tissue patients, work is needed for a dedicated pain-
damage origin. Also, it allows for a “role” of psy- related diagnosis in the DSM-5.1 that respects its
chological factors without denying the relevance complications, including those related to the per-
of associated tissue damage or medical condition. son’s validity in presentation.
The proposal is implicitly biopsychosocial in It is beyond the scope of the present paper to
conceptualization rather than either medical, psy- deal with the issue of the reliability and validity
chological, or both (to use the language of the of effectively ruling in or ruling out malingering,
dualistic DSM-IV-TR). Simply, pain might have and the reader is referred to Young (2014a) about
620 24 The Disordered DSM-5 Disorders

this issue. As per Young (2014a), evaluators who other users of the manual. For example, when vari-
undertake evaluations dealing with pain-cen- ous stakeholders consider the evaluations of men-
tered clinical presentations in the forensic dis- tal health assessors, such as adjusters/examiners,
ability and related context need to adopt rigorous arbitrators/workers in legal venues, and triers of
procedures in the assessment. fact (judges, juries) in court, will they query
Further, in the way the disorder is phrased in whether any of the clinician’s/assessor’s conclu-
the table, the functional impacts of the pain sions are valid? More likely than not, the confu-
experienced by the patient need to be addressed sions generated by the diagnostic approach to
(e.g., social, occupational role effects; constitut- chronic pain in the DSM-5 will be a source of dif-
ing clinical complications). In the forensic con- ficulty not only for mental health assessors but also
text, the value of identifying functional effects for those determining whether psychotherapy is
and disabilities of the event at issue (and their appropriate or adjudicating cases. This might serve
relation to symptoms, impairments, and disor- to aggravate the adversarial divide involving pain
ders) remains crucial. patients and plaintiffs in court and related venues.
Moreover, for chronic pain, if a psychological
diagnosis is called for and the assessor considers
it validly expressed, he or she should evaluate Other DSM-5 Considerations
sources of complications related to causality. The
criteria proposed for chronic pain complications Personality Disorder
disorder includes this factor.
Finally, by referring to chronic pain condi- The personality disorder (PD) DSM-5 draft pro-
tions as a complications disorder, the disorder is posal for change to PD diagnosis elicited a fire-
somewhat destigmatized. For example, in cases storm of criticism, and the new system was
of chronic pain evaluated as valid, the clinician/ relegated for further study. The DSM-5 draft pro-
assessor could explain to the patient/evaluee that posal had extensively revised the personality
the diagnostic issue is not that the pain is “all in disorder section but, due to criticism, the DSM-
the head” but that it is understood as authentic IV-TR version was retained. The latter was placed
and the complications for the person constitute in Sect. 2 of the DSM-5, and the proposal was
the main problems being addressed. placed in Appendix for consideration in the next
DSM version. Table 24.5 provides the criteria for
the proposed Antisocial Personality Disorder.
Painful Conclusions Given the lack of reliability of personality dis-
order in the field trials, the whole area needs
Assessment in the area of psychological injury reconceptualization. However, it is not clear that
and law often involves pain patients, and the the proposed alternative will fare better or be
DSM-5 changes to diagnosing chronic pain both clinically usable. Moreover, in the DSM-5, anti-
reduce its relevance and increase potential harm social personality disorder is considered one of
to patients and evaluees. The category of SSD the indicators of possible malingering. The diffi-
allows for pain as a specifier, but this is insuffi- culty in diagnosing it adds one more barrier in
cient to capture the psychological state of genu- considering the DSM-5 approach to malingering
ine pain patients/evaluees. In this regard, I have as valid and useful.
offered an alternative formulation for chronic The PD section of the manual continues to
pain that is partly based on SSD (referred to as spark criticism on both scientific and utility
Chronic Pain Complications Disorder). grounds (Livesley, 2013; Mullins-Sweatt,
The difficulties presented pertaining to the Bernstein, & Widiger, 2012; Verheul, 2012).
assessment and diagnosis of chronic pain in the Nevertheless, empirical research does present
DSM-5 might be confusing not only to assessors some findings in their favor (e.g., Morey &
working with it in diagnosing patients but also to Skodol, 2013). Hopwood and Sellbom (2013)
Other DSM-5 Considerations 621

Table 24.5 Proposed antisocial personality disorder for consideration in the next version of the DSM
Criterion Explanation
A Definitional impairment in personality functioning in at least one of the following areas: e.g., failure to
conform to lawful/ethical behavior; an egocentric, callous lack of concern for others; also deceitfulness,
irresponsibility, manipulativeness, and/or risk taking
A1 Identity. Egocentrism; self-esteem from personal gain, power, pleasure
A2 Self-direction. Goal setting based on personal gratification; absence of prosocial internal standards,
could include failure to conform to lawful/culturally normative ethical behavior
A3 Empathy. Lack of concern for feelings, needs, suffering of others; lack of remorse after hurting/
mistreating someone
A4 Intimacy. Incapacity for mutually intimate relationships, exploitation is primary means of relating,
including deceit, coercion; use of dominance, intimidation to control people
B Six or more of the following seven pathological personality traits
B1 Manipulativeness. An aspect of antagonism
B2 Callousness. An aspect of antagonism
B3 Deceitfulness. An aspect of antagonism
B4 Hostility. An aspect of antagonism
B5 Risk taking. An aspect of disinhibition
B6 Impulsivity. An aspect of disinhibition
B7 Irresponsibility. An aspect of disinhibition
Specifier At least 18 years of age

reviewed the evidence in favor of the new formu- Negative Emotionality; and (e) Detachment to
lation, which is based on dimensionally-described Introversion/Low Positive Emotionality.
personality traits. Anderson et al. (2012) conducted a study using
Quilty, Ayearst, Chmielewski, Pollock, and undergraduates, and administered the PID-5 and
Bagby (2013) found evidence supporting the the MMPI-2-RF, from which the PSY-5 scales
psychometric properties of the PID-5 (Personality can be scored. They found data in support of the
Inventory for DSM-5), which was developed by parallel between the PID-5 and PSY-5, except for
the Personality and Personality Disorders work- a slight variation for Antagonism.
group of the DSM-5 project (Krueger, Derringer, A measure of the classic Five Factor Model
Markon, Watson, & Skodol, 2012). In the clinical (FFM) of personality (FFM Rating Form,
setting used in the Quilty et al. study, the results Mullins-Sweatt, Jamerson, Samuel, Olson, &
generally indicated adequate internal consis- Widiger, 2006) has been shown to correspond to
tency, factor structure, and convergent validity of the PID-5, giving an opening for normative trait
most PID-5 domains and facets. research in personality disorder classification
Wygant and Sellbom (2012) noted that the (Thomas et al., 2013). Other research has sup-
PSY-5 (Personality Psychopathology Five; ported using the PAI (Personality Assessment
Harkness & McNulty, 1994), part of the MMPI-2 Inventory; Morey, 2007) in DSM-5 PD assess-
(The Minnesota Multiphasic Personality ment, because of its “broad” convergence with
Inventory-2; Butcher et al., 2001)/MMPI-2-RF the DSM-5 traits (Hopwood et al., 2013).
(The Minnesota Multiphasic Personality Markon, Quilty, Bagby, and Krueger (2013)
Inventory-2 Restructured Form; Ben-Porath & developed an informant version of the PID-5.
Tellegen, 2008/2011), corresponds well to the
domains of the DSM-5. In particular, (a) DSM-5
Antagonism is akin to PSY-5 Aggressiveness; (b) Depression
Schizotypy (psychoticism) to Psychoticism; (c)
Disinhibition to Disconstraint; (d) Negative Gotlib and LeMoult (2014) summarized the
Emotionality (affectivity) to Neuroticism/ changes in depression-related disorders in the
622 24 The Disordered DSM-5 Disorders

DSM-5 relative to the DSM-IV-TR. They noted expresses the inclusion fallacy mentioned for the
that the essential symptoms of the critical disorder first factor. Given these concerns, Boone (2011)
of major depression have not changed. The changes and others have indicated that the DSM-IV-TR
to the depression-related disorders and their orga- does not appear sufficiently accurate with respect
nization include various additions, deletions, and to malingering.
movement from and to appendices. They noted the Note that Table 24.6 shows that there are some
controversies in the area and the as-yet unexplored “minor” changes to the definition of malingering
consequences of various changes. Overall, they in the DSM-5 relative to the approach in the
suggested that the changes have served the goal of DSM-IV-TR. However, some of the ones included
coming closer to better reliability and validity on might not be minor in that they appear to lower
the treatment of depression-related disorders in the somewhat the bar for its attribution. [Then again,
DSM-5. excluding the term from the subject index, as
However, Gotlib and LeMoult (2014) appeared happened in the DSM-5 manual, seems to raise it
to support inclusion of premenstrual dysphoric out of existence!]
disorder in the DSM-5, as well as removal of the In Young (2014a, 2014b), I noted that the
bereavement exclusion from major depressive DSM-IV-TR approach to the definition malinger-
disorder. They acknowledged criticism of these ing can be qualified by the separation of its two
decisions (e.g., diagnostic inflation, pathologiz- major components. That is, the definition implies
ing normal responses, stigmatization), but essen- the presence of either (a) overt, outright, frank,
tially took the pragmatic view that these disorders and conscious, intentional fabrication, feigning,
will enable insurance coverage for affected or dissimulation of symptoms, disorders disabili-
individuals. ties, or functional impairments for external incen-
tives, such as financial gain, and for which there
is incontrovertible, indisputable, or compelling
Malingering evidence, or (b) conscious, intentional gross
exaggerations of symptoms, disorders, disabili-
Definition Young (2014a) noted that, in the psy- ties, or functional impairments that clearly are
chiatric approach, malingering involves the greater than the moderate level, for the same
“intentional production of false or grossly exag- external incentives, and for which there is incon-
gerated physical or psychological symptoms” trovertible or compelling evidence.
that derives from “motivation by external Young (2014a, 2014b) further qualified that,
incentives,” for example, for obtaining financial in malingering, unlike what is specified in the
compensation (in the DSM-IV-TR). DSM definition, the intention is not to “produce”
The DSM-IV-TR specifies that any combina- false or exaggerated symptoms but to clinically
tion of the following four factors strongly sug- present with them. For example, symptoms that
gests possible malingering: (a) the referral are self-reported are not “produced” per se; they
context is medicolegal; (b) the objective findings are merely presented in description to the evalua-
are “markedly” different from the evaluee’s tor as part of the presenting problem. There might
claimed “stress or disability”; (c) the evaluee is be no symptoms produced, per se. Second, even
not cooperative with the assessment procedure or if there were symptoms produced, the process of
with suggested treatments; and (d) the evaluee is somatization could be in play. Moreover, even in
diagnosed with antisocial personality disorder. the case of somatization, the symptoms produced
However, the first of the four mentioned fac- might be on purpose for financial gain, or malin-
tors automatically and erroneously brands each gering, rather than being unconscious. For exam-
evaluee in forensic disability examinations as a ple, one could firmly wish that one has been
possible malingerer; the second and third factors injured (although one has not) and the stress, lack
might reflect the confrontational nature of these of sleep, anger against the insurance process,
types of examinations; and the fourth factor etc., all conspire to produce pain and related
Other DSM-5 Considerations 623

Table 24.6 Changes to malingering in DSM-5


Criterion Descriptor Change
Superordinate Nonadherence to medical treatment In the DSM-IV, had been under
category “Additional conditions” for clinical
focus
Criteria “Any combination” of the four criteria leads to Same (i.e., 2 or more of the 4)
“strong suspicion”
Criterion 1 Referral to an attorney, but also could be self- Had been only referral to an attorney.
referral to the attorney This lowers the bar
Criterion 2 Marked discrepancy between claims and Had been only objective findings. This
“objective findings and observations” lowers the bar
Criterion 3 Lack of cooperation/compliance Same
Criterion 4 Antisocial personality disorder Same
Elaboration “Definite” evidence of “feigning” “suggests” Added
malingering if the “apparent” goal is to obtain an
incentive, such as financial (“money”)
Definite feigning evidence = “clear evidence” of Added; but how are home observations
“loss of function” in examination but not at home obtained? Are they always needed?
“Symptom relief” could be obtained by Deleted; good idea
“suggestion” or “hypnosis”
Section Other conditions that may be focus of clinical However, it is entered after a subheading
placement attention nonadherence to medical treatment,
which is confusing because malingering
might involve overly zealous adherence
to medical treatment.
Index entry – Removed [Has malingering really ceased
to exist?] Solution: put it back

claimable symptoms. That is, a conscious pro- note that, in cases of partial malingering, there
cess of presenting with symptoms might serve to still might be valid aspects of the evaluee’s pre-
actually produce them. Further, the conscious, sentation and performance that require regular
fabricated origin of the symptoms no longer assessment for diagnosis, functional deficit and
might be recalled. In this regard, the putative disability, treatment recommendations, and con-
claimable symptoms become seemingly genuine clusions on prognosis.
only after intentional exaggeration or malinger- Finally, note that a definition of malingering
ing produces them. One way or another, symp- that includes the requirement of specification of
toms are produced by an otherwise false belief, degree to the point that it might be mild should
and the origin of the intent is suppressed or is not be conflated with equating mild or minimal
forgotten, conveniently or otherwise. exaggeration to genuine malingering. That is,
Aside from these considerations about somati- mild exaggeration should be excluded as part of
zation, a revised approach to malingering should the definition of malingering and should not be
add a qualifier that the malingering could be par- included as an example of mild malingering.
tial rather than full, and also mild rather than In short, an improved definition of malinger-
moderate or severe, but no less in need of detec- ing would involve the following:
tion. That is, once malingering is concluded to
Malingering is the intentional presentation with
have taken place, it should be specified for cer- false or grossly exaggerated symptoms [physical,
tain relevant attributes, such as the extent of its mental health, or both; full or partial; mild, moder-
range and its degree of intensity. ate, or severe], for purposes of obtaining an exter-
Note that inclusion of partial and mild malin- nal incentive, such as monetary compensation for
an injury and/or avoiding/evading work, military
gering in the definition should not obscure that duty, or criminal prosecution.
some malingering had taken place. In addition,
624 24 The Disordered DSM-5 Disorders

Other advantages of the proposed definition procedure to their model (however, in a seem-
to note is that the use of the word “presentation” ingly inconsistent way). (c) For the exclusionary
instead of “production” more clearly covers criterion, they reported it as dropped from their
negative symptoms as well as positive ones, revised system but, in actuality, they kept it
such as failing to present capable of work when (however, in a revised way that did not broaden
that is not the case. Moreover, other changes that but constrained use of the model).
I made to the definition: (a) allow for combined The original 1999 MND model has an impor-
physical and psychological symptoms, (b) value tant place in the history of the field, and still can
all mental health perspectives, and (c) allow for be considered a model that has the potential to
both trying to obtain financial compensation and become the gold standard in the field of malin-
also avoiding work. gering detection. However, the specific form of
the model that might reach that status might
Detection Systems Slick, Sherman, and Iverson relate more to my revision of it more than the
(1999) developed criteria for Malingered revision of the original authors.
Neurocognitive Dysfunction (MND). The latter Bianchini, Curtis, and Greve (2013) indicated
represented a major advance in the field because that the MPRD could be used with other condi-
it systematized the existing conceptualization tions, such as PTSD, because it concerns exagger-
and research on malingered disability and related ation and malingering, in general. However, they
response biases in neurocognitive and related failed to consider that inspection of their system
disability assessments. There is another system reveals that it includes quite pain-specific criteria.
for detecting malingering, one for pain-related
presentations (the MPRD, Malingered Pain-
Related Disability; Bianchini, Greve, & Glynn, Comment
2005). Also, Rubenzer (2009) recommended
tests for detecting malingered PTSD. But there This concludes presentation of major DSM-5 cat-
has not been a malingering detection system, per egories and also commentary on their criticisms
se, for PTSD. Based on the work of these leaders, and limitations. Generally, the DSM-5 psychiat-
I developed such a system in Young (2014a, ric categories need further work to meet accept-
2015). Moreover, it was created so that, with able reliability standards. Their exact wording
minor changes, it is also applicable to MND and should be vetted and then their reliability deter-
MPRD cases. mined. In further versions of the DSM-5, differ-
Slick and Sherman (2012, 2013) revised their ent approaches to classification should be
1999 MND model for the detection of malinger- examined. For example, to end the chapter, I look
ing, especially by broadening the criteria. at the ICD-11.
However, for each of their changes to the MND
model [(a) broadening compelling inconsisten-
cies, (b) using likelihood ratio chaining and posi- The ICD-11
tive predictive power, and (c) removing the
exclusion criterion], the decisions taken were Complex PTSD
either not entirely clear or were insufficient. For
example, (a) for the case of the inconsistencies, I Maercker et al. (2013) described how the
have developed a much more elaborate scheme International Classification of Diseases-11 (ICD-
in my revised MND model. (b) For the Larrabee, 11, due in 2017) is dealing with categories of
Greiffenstein, Greve, and Bianchini (2007) LR mental disorders that are associated with stress.
(likelihood ratio chaining) and PPP (positive pre- Like for the DSM-5, they are separating stress
dictive power) technique, Slick and Sherman disorders from other mental disorders. However,
(2012, 2013) had indicated that their use would many of their decisions take a different direction
be premature but, nevertheless, they added the than in the DSM-5.
The ICD-11 625

They noted that in the ICD-11 draft, for each lasts for only days. The authors concluded that
disorder due to stress, the stressor is a “necessary the proposed ICD-11 system will be user-friendly,
not sufficient” causal factor. The stressors include including for low-resource and humanitarian
those that are within the normal range of human populations.
experience (e.g., for adjustment disorder) and
those that are “exceptionally severe” (e.g., for
PTSD). In defining the disorders, the ICD-11 Evidence
adopts a clinical utility focus. In this regard, for
PTSD, they simplified it only to disorder-specific Wolf et al. (2015) queried the validity of proposing
symptoms and they excluded non-specific symp- that CPTSD should be split from PTSD, as being
toms that are also part of other disorders (e.g., proposed for the ICD-11. In each of community
Brewin, Lanius, Novac, Schnyder, & Galea, and military samples, factor modeling indicated
2009). Moreover, they used only three symptom two classes, but they were related to disorder
clusters—(a) re-experiencing the traumatic event; severity and not the PTSD-CPTSD distinction.
(b) avoidance of reminders; (c) and perceiving To illustrate the difficulties presented by the
heightened current threats as evidenced by arousal DSM-5 approach to diagnosis for PTSD, con-
(Forbes et al., 2011). They qualified that the event sider the following. O’Donnell et al. (2014) dem-
at issue must be “extremely threatening or hor- onstrated that the prevalence rate of PTSD for the
rific.” They noted that, to differentiate PTSD from DSM-5 and the ICD-11 criteria differs markedly
normal reactions to extreme stressors, the person in the two diagnostic systems. They found that,
must express a functional impairment as well as for injury patients, PTSD was diagnosed twice as
symptoms of a particular duration. much using the DSM-5 criteria compared to
The other mental disorders involving stress in those of the ICD-11 (6.7 % vs. 3.3 %, respec-
the ICD-11 include complex PTSD (CPTSD). tively). In the DSM-5, 20 criteria symptoms are
The stressors in such cases involve ones that are listed, although only a handful of them for any
severe and prolonged, and they usually include one patient are needed for the diagnosis. In the
several or repeated adverse events, such as in ICD-11, as mentioned, only a few core symptoms
sexual abuse (Cloitre et al., 2009; Weiss, 2012). are required for diagnosis (Maercker et al., 2013).
The disorder is also accompanied by “enduring Perhaps reducing PTSD diagnostic symptoms
disturbances” in the areas of self, affect, and especially to core ones will constrain its diagno-
interpersonal relations. The inclusion of complex sis, a process that should help reduce its preva-
PTSD in the ICD-11 contrasts with its exclusion lence not only in using the ICD-11 but also could
in the DSM-5. help in the next versions of the DSM-5, should
A notable addition to the stress disorders is the they go that route.
inclusion of prolonged grief disorder, which is
distinct from depression. In contrast, the DSM-5
allows for a brief grief reaction to be considered Conclusions
as an expression of major depressive disorder.
Therefore, the DSM-5 approach differs from the The present chapter on specific DSM-5 disorders
ICD-11 approach in two ways—first, in the leaves as much doubt about them as the general
DSM-5, the grief reaction can be brief yet still criticisms of the DSM-5 reviewed in the prior chap-
disordered. Second, it is not considered separate ter. The disorders reviewed reveal multiple minor
from depression, unlike in the ICD-11 proposal. and some major difficulties, and should be revised
In the latter proposal, adjustment disorder is a accordingly. Even the disorders touted as quite reli-
mental condition or a maladaptive reaction aris- able, such as the one of PTSD, suffer on close
ing from a significant life event. Relative to the inspection of their criteria and the research related
ICD-10, its definition has been tightened. It is to them. The area of psychological injury and law
more than a non-clinical acute stress reaction that deals with PTSD, pain, and TBI, in particular, and
626 24 The Disordered DSM-5 Disorders

for all three areas, the present chapter (and the American Psychiatric Association. (2000). Diagnostic
companion one before it) pinpoint considerable and statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM-
IV-TR (4th ed., text rev.). Washington, DC: Author.
concern. The same applies to entities in the Anderson, J. L., Sellbom, M., Bagby, R. M., Quilty, L. C.,
DSM-5 that have not changed relative to the Veltri, C. O. C., Markon, K. E., et al. (2012). On the
DSM-IV-TR, such as malingering. In the present convergence between PSY-5 domains and PID-5
chapter, I end up making specific proposals how domains and facets: Implications for assessment of
DSM-5 personality traits. Assessment, 20, 286–294.
chronic pain and malingering can be redefined in Ben-Porath, Y. S., & Tellegen, A. (2008/2011). The
the next iteration of the DSM-5. Review of the Minnesota Multiphasic Personality Inventory-2
ICD-11 proposal for stress disorders, as pre- Restructured Form (MMPI-2-RF): Manual for admin-
sented by Maercker et al. (2013), leaves much istration, scoring, and interpretation. Minnesota, MN:
University of Minnesota Press.
room to ponder the approach taken for these dis- Bianchini, K. J., Curtis, K. L., & Greve, K. W. (2013).
orders in the DSM-5. For example, for PTSD, Cognitive performance validity assessment in mild
they emphasize disorder-specific symptoms and traumatic brain injury, physical pain, and posttrau-
also group them into three clusters. They allow matic stress. In D. A. Carone & S. S. Bush (Eds.), Mild
traumatic brain injury: System validity assessment
for CPTSD. As for bereavement, they consider it and malingering (pp. 323–346). New York: Springer.
separate from depression and, moreover, it must Bianchini, K. J., Greve, K. W., & Glynn, G. (2005). On
be prolonged. These and other decisions for the the diagnosis of malingered pain-related disability:
ICD-11 will only serve to accentuate the debate Lessons from cognitive malingering research. The
Spine Journal, 5, 404–417.
about the utility and validity of aspects of the Blazer, D. (2013). Neurocognitive disorders in DSM-5.
DSM-5. American Journal of Psychiatry, 170, 585–587.
Boone, K. B. (2011). Clarification or confusion? A review
of Rogers, Bender, and Johnson’s a critical analysis of
the MND criteria for feigned cognitive impairment:
Chapter Conclusions Implications for forensic practice and research.
Psychological Injury and Law, 4, 157–162.
This chapter and the prior one have critically Brewin, C. R., Lanius, R. A., Novac, A., Schnyder, U., &
Galea, S. (2009). Reformulating PTSD for DSM-V:
examined both the RDoC (Insel et al., 2010; Insel Life after criterion A. Journal of Traumatic Stress, 22,
& Lieberman, 2013) project and the DSM-5. I 366–373.
have showed that both are vast projects that need Butcher, J. N., Graham, J. R., Ben-Porath, Y. S., Tellegen,
to be respected for their scope, but both suffer A., Dahlstrom, W. G., & Kaemmer, B. (2001). MMPI-
2: Manual for administration, scoring, and interpreta-
from the same disorder or disease. That is, both tion. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press
do not respect enough or include enough the bio- (Rev. ed).
psychosocial approach to mental illness. For both Cloitre, M., Stolbach, B. C., Herman, J. L., van der Kolk,
these grand projects, I end up making pertinent B., Pynoos, R., Wang, J., et al. (2009). A developmen-
tal approach to complex PTSD: Childhood and adult
suggestions for their improvement in these cumulative trauma as predictors of symptom complex-
regards. ity. Journal of Traumatic Stress, 22, 399–408.
In the following chapter of the present work, I Dimsdale, J. E. (2012, May). DSM-5 proposals for
move from dealing with psychiatric classification somatic symptom disorders. Paper presented at the
165th annual meeting of American Psychiatric
and diagnosis, as in the DSM-5, to broader con- Association, Philadelphia, PA.
siderations. These include discussion of causality Ewart, C. K., Elder, G. J., Laird, K. T., Shelby, G. D., &
and etiology, in particular. Then, I suggest rec- Walker, L. S. (2014). Can agonistic striving lead to
ommendations for psychiatry and classification. unexplained illness? Implicit goals, pain tolerance,
and somatic symptoms in adolescents and adults.
Finally, I present conclusions related to practice. Health Psychology, 33, 977–985.
Forbes, D., Lockwood, E., Elhai, J. D., Creamer, M.,
O’Donnell, M., Bryant, R., et al. (2011). An examina-
tion of the structure of posttraumatic stress disorder in
References relation to the anxiety and depressive disorders.
Journal of Affective Disorders, 132, 165–172.
American Psychiatric Association. (2013). Diagnostic Frances, A. (2013a). Essentials of psychiatric diagnosis:
and statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM-5 Responding to the challenge of DSM-5. New York:
(5th ed.). Washington, DC: Author. Guilford Press.
References 627

Frances, A. (2013b). DSM in philosophyland: Curiouser Livesley, W. J. (2013). The DSM-5 personality disorder
and curiouser. In J. Paris & J. Phillips (Eds.), Making proposal and future directions in the diagnostic clas-
the DSM-5: Concepts and controversies (pp. 95–103). sification of personality disorder. Psychopathology,
New York: Springer. 46, 207–216.
Frances, A., & Chapman, S. (2013). DSM-5 somatic Maercker, A., Brewin, C. R., Bryant, R. A., Cloitre, M.,
symptom disorder mislabels medical illness as mental Reed, G. M., van Ommeren, M., et al. (2013).
disorder. Australian and New Zealand Journal of Proposals for mental disorders specifically associated
Psychiatry, 47, 483–489. with stress in the International Classification of
Gatchel, R. J., Peng, Y. B., Peters, M. L., Fuchs, P. N., & Diseases-11. The Lancet, 381, 1683–1685.
Turk, D. C. (2007). The biopsychosocial approach to Markon, K. E., Quilty, L. C., Bagby, R. M., & Krueger, R.
chronic pain: Scientific advances and future direc- (2013). The developmental and psychometric proper-
tions. Psychological Bulletin, 133, 581–624. ties of an informant-report form of the personality
Gotlib, I. H., & LeMoult, J. (2014). The “ins” and “outs” inventory for DSM-5 (PID-5). Assessment, 20,
of the depressive disorders section of DSM-5. Clinical 370–383.
Psychology: Science and Practice, 21, 193–207. Melzack, R., & Katz, J. (2006). Pain in the 21st century:
Harkness, A. R., & McNulty, J. L. (1994). The personality The neuromatrix and beyond. In G. Young, A. W.
psychopathology five (PSY-5): Issues from the pages Kane, & K. Nicholson (Eds.), Psychological knowl-
of a diagnostic manual instead of a dictionary. In edge in court: PTSD, pain, and TBI (pp. 129–148).
S. Stephen & L. Maurice (Eds.), Differentiating New York: Springer Science + Business Media.
normal and abnormal personality (pp. 291–315). Melzack, R., & Katz, J. (2012). Pain. Wiley
New York: Springer. Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science, 4, 1–15.
Hopwood, C. J., & Sellbom, M. (2013). Implications of Morey, L. C. (2007). Professional manual for the person-
DSM-5 personality traits for forensic psychology. ality assessment inventory. Odessa, FL: Psychological
Psychological Injury and Law, 6, 314–323. Assessment Resources.
Hopwood, C. J., Wright, A. G. C., Krueger, R. F., Schade, Morey, L. C., & Skodol, A. E. (2013). Convergence
N., Markon, K. E., & Morey, L. C. (2013). DSM-5 between DSM-IV-TR and DSM-5 diagnostic models
pathological personality traits and the personality for personality disorder: Evaluation of strategies for
assessment inventory. Assessment, 20, 269–285. establishing diagnostic thresholds. Journal of
Insel, T. R., Cuthbert, B. N., Garvey, M. A., Heinssen, Psychiatric Practice, 19, 179–193.
R. K., Pine, D. S., Quinn, K. J., et al. (2010). Research Mullins-Sweatt, S. N., Bernstein, D. P., & Widiger, T. A.
domain criteria (RDoC): Toward a new classification (2012). Retention or deletion of personality disorder
framework for research on mental disorders. American diagnoses for DSM-5: An expert consensus approach.
Journal of Psychiatry, 167, 748–751. Journal of Personality Disorders, 26, 689–703.
Insel, T. R., & Lieberman, J. A. (2013). DSM-5 and Mullins-Sweatt, S. N., Jamerson, J. E., Samuel, D. B.,
RDoC: Shared interests. The National Institute of Olson, D. R., & Widiger, T. A. (2006). Psychometric
Mental Health. Retrieved from http://www.nimh.nih. properties of an abbreviated instrument of the five-
gov/news/science-news/2013/dsm-5-and-rdoc-shared-- factor model. Assessment, 13, 119–137.
interests.shtml O’Donnell, M. L., Alkemade, N., Nickerson, A., Creamer,
Jaremka, L. M., Andridge, R. R., Fagundes, C. P., Alfano, M., McFarlane, A. C., Silove, D., et al. (2014). Impact
C. M., Povoski, S. P., Lipari, A. M., et al. (2014). Pain, of the diagnostic changes to post-traumatic stress dis-
depression, and fatigue: Loneliness as a longitudinal order for DSM-5 and the proposed changes to ICD-11.
risk factor. Health Psychology, 33, 948–957. British Journal of Psychiatry, 205, 230–235.
Karoly, P., Okun, M. A., Enders, C., & Tennen, H. (2014). Quilty, L. C., Ayearst, L., Chmielewski, M., Pollock, B. G.,
Effects of pain intensity on goal schemas and goal pursuit: & Bagby, R. M. (2013). The psychometric properties
A daily diary study. Health Psychology, 33, 968–976. of the personality inventory for DSM-5 in an APA
Kerns, R. D., Burns, J. W., Shulman, M., Jensen, M. P., DSM-5 field trial sample. Assessment, 20, 362–369.
Nielson, W. R., Czlapinski, R., et al. (2014). Can we Rief, W., & Martin, A. (2014). How to use the new DSM-5
improve cognitive-behavioral therapy for chronic back somatic symptom disorder diagnosis in research and
pain treatment engagement and adherence? A con- practice: A critical evaluation and a proposal for modi-
trolled trial of tailored versus standard therapy. Health fication. Annual Review of Clinical Psychology, 10,
Psychology, 33, 938–947. 339–367.
Krueger, R. F., Derringer, J., Markon, K. E., Watson, D., Rief, W., Mewes, R., Martin, A., Glaesmer, H., & Brähler,
& Skodol, A. E. (2012). Initial construction of a mal- E. (2011). Evaluating new proposals for the psychiat-
adaptive personality trait model and inventory for ric classification of patients with multiple somatic
DSM-5. Psychological Medicine, 42, 1879–1890. symptoms. Psychosomatic Medicine, 73, 760–768.
Larrabee, G. J., Greiffenstein, M. F., Greve, K. W., & Rubenzer, S. (2009). Posttraumatic stress disorder:
Bianchini, K. J. (2007). Refining diagnostic criteria Assessing response style and malingering.
for malingering. In G. J. Larrabee (Ed.), Evaluation of Psychological Injury and Law, 2, 114–142.
malingering in the neuropsychological examination Ruiz-Párraga, G. T., & López-Martínez, A. E. (2014). The
(pp. 334–371). New York: Oxford University Press. contribution of posttraumatic stress symptoms to
628 24 The Disordered DSM-5 Disorders

chronic pain adjustment. Health Psychology, 33, Weiss, D. S. (2012). Introduction to the special feature on
968–976. complex PTSD. Journal of Traumatic Stress, 25,
Schultz, I. Z. (2010). Neurocognitive disorders in DSM- 239–240.
V: Forensic perspective. Psychological Injury and Wolf, E. J., Miller, M. W., Kilpatrick, D., Resnick, H. S.,
Law, 3, 271–288. Badour, C. L., Marx, B. P., et al. (2015). ICD-11 com-
Schultz, I. Z. (2013). DSM-5 neurocognitive disorders: plex PTSD in U.S. national and veteran samples:
Validity, reliability, fairness, and utility in forensic Prevalence and structural associations with PTSD.
applications. Psychological Injury and Law, 6, Clinical Psychological Science, 3, 215–229.
299–306. Wolf, L. D., & Davis, M. C. (2014). Loneliness, daily
Simpson, J. R. (2014). DSM-5 and neurocognitive disor- pain, and perceptions of interpersonal events in adults
ders. The Journal of the American Academy of with fibromyalgia. Health Psychology, 33, 929–937.
Psychiatry and the Law, 42, 159–164. Wollburg, E., Voigt, K., Braukhaus, C., Herzog, A., &
Sirri, L., & Fava, G. A. (2013). Diagnostic criteria for psy- Löwe, B. (2013). Construct validity and descriptive
chosomatic research and somatic symptom disorders. validity of somatoform disorder in light of proposed
International Review of Psychiatry, 25, 19–30. changes for the DSM-5. Journal of Psychosomatic
Slick, D. J., & Sherman, E. M. S. (2012). Differential Research, 74, 18–24.
diagnosis of malingering and related clinical presenta- World Health Organization. (2017). International
tions. In E. M. S. Sherman & B. L. Brooks (Eds.), Classification of Disease, 11th Revision.
Pediatric forensic neuropsychology (pp. 113–135). Wygant, D. B., & Sellbom, M. (2012). Viewing psychopa-
New York: Oxford University Press. thy from the perspective of the personality psychopa-
Slick, D. J., & Sherman, E. M. S. (2013). Differential thology five model: Implications for DSM-5. Journal
diagnosis of malingering. In D. A. Carone & S. S. of Personality Disorders, 26, 717–726.
Bush (Eds.), Mild traumatic brain injury: System Young, G. (2010). Chronic pain in the DSM-IV and the
validity assessment and malingering (pp. 57–72). DSM-5 draft: The pain of it all. Psychological Injury
New York: Springer. and Law, 3, 289–294.
Slick, D. J., Sherman, E. M., & Iverson, G. L. (1999). Young, G. (2013). Ill-treatment of pain in the DSM-5.
Diagnostic criteria for malingered neurocognitive dys- Psychological Injury and Law, 6, 307–313.
function: Proposed standards for clinical practice and Young, G. (2014a). Malingering, feigning, and response
research. The Clinical Neuropsychologist, 13, bias in psychiatric/psychological injury: Implications
545–561. for practice and court. Dordrecht, Netherlands:
Sykes, R. (2012). The DSM 5 website proposals for Springer Science + Business Media.
somatic symptom disorder: Three central problems. Young, G. (2014b). Psychological injury and law II: A cri-
Psychosomatics, 53, 524–531. tique of psychological injury and law: Implications for
Thomas, K. M., Yalch, M. M., Krueger, R. F., Wright, mental health policy and ethics. Mental Health Law
A. G. C., Markon, K. E., & Hopwood, C. J. (2013). and Policy Journal, 3, 417–470.
The convergent structure of DSM-5 personality trait Young, G. (2015). Detection system for malingered PTSD
facets and five factor model trait domains. Assessment, and related response biases. Psychological Injury and
20, 308–311. Law, 8, 169–183.
Verheul, R. (2012). Personality disorder proposal for Young, G., Kane, A. W., & Nicholson, K. (2007). (Eds.).
DSM-5: A heroic and innovative but nevertheless fun- Causality of psychological injury: Presenting evi-
damentally flawed attempt to improve DSM-IV. dence in court. New York: Springer Science + Business
Clinical Psychology and Psychotherapy, 19, 369–371. Media.
DSM-5: Recommendations
25

Revision; World Health Organization, 2007,


Chapter Introduction 2017) but, instead, I recommend using the man-
ual that is best for any disorder at hand, no matter
Given the comments, concerns, criticisms, and which one might be involved.
possible harm related to the DSM-5 (Diagnostic
and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, Fifth
Edition; American Psychiatric Association, Causality and Etiology
2013), it needs revision to become more clini- in Psychology and Psychiatry
cally useful, reliable, and valid. The present
chapter emphasizes that this should begin with The present book is especially about the causes of
better conceptualization, including of etiology behavior, both normal and psychopathological.
and of an overarching model. In this regard, it Behavioral causation in psychopathology is
examines an extended biopsychosocial model. referred to as etiology. In the medical model, spe-
The chapter considers new ways of conceiving cific diseases have specific etiologies and specific
endophenotypes in terms of the biopsychosocial cures/treatments. However, the etiology of psychi-
model. The chapter presents an integrative model atric mental disorder is not that straightforward.
of etiology involving combined top-down and Coghill (2014) editorialized that the complex-
bottom-up processes (related to mental disorder ity and heterogeneity of causality in childhood
and symptoms, respectively). Also, a critical way disorder should be acknowledged. Generally, dis-
of improving the reliability in diagnosis involves orders are multicausal and nonspecific or nonlin-
improving the assessment process. In this regard, ear in causality (Coghill, Seth, & Matthews,
I make recommendations related to structuring 2014). Moreover, the concept of psychiatric dis-
areas in assessments. order, itself, is not straightforward. Disorders as
Finally, I deal with practical and court matters, presently defined often share more similarities
as well as ethics. It should be noted that mental than differences (Karalunas, Geurts, Konrad,
health practitioners of all stripes should consider Bender, & Nigg, 2014). The field needs to con-
these practical issues that I raise. For example, I sider that, just as etiology is multicausal, mental
recommend not using uniquely the DSM-5, illness is multifactorial in the sense that it does
DSM-IV-TR (Diagnostic and Statistical Manual not compartmentalize easily into distinct, sepa-
of Mental Disorders, Fourth Edition, Text rate disorders. Moreover, the problems in these
Revised; American Psychiatric Association, regards might relate to the way disorders are rep-
2000), or the ICD 10 or 11 (International resented—that is, as a set of possible symptoms
Classification of Diseases, 10th Revision or 11th with many possible combinations, and, also,

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 629


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_25
630 25 DSM-5: Recommendations

among the symptoms are those that might be juvenile or beginning level of their scientific
common to multiple disorders. Perhaps there is investigation.
an efficient solution to the dilemma of organizing Kendler (2008) adopted a systems view of eti-
better the multiple symptoms in psychopathol- ology of psychiatric illness. He indicated that the
ogy, the multiple disorders involved, and the factors involved include biological, psychologi-
large amount of comorbidities and common cal, and sociocultural perspectives. He contrasted
symptoms therein. Perhaps it is best to focus on this approach with hard “reductionism,” which is
what makes each disorder distinct from others more biological, and, also, he contrasted this
and, in doing so, this might serve to reduce their approach with hard “emergentism,” which is
amount, simplify the search for their causal fac- more mental or social in mechanism. In Kendler’s
tors, and help in finding efficacious treatment. In multilevel approach, the mechanisms are com-
this regard, the concept of having separate core, plex, nonadditive, nondecomposable, nonsubsti-
primary and non-core, common symptoms in dis- tutable, interrelational, intricate, pluralistic,
order has a place in psychiatry, but with espe- multilevel, context-dependent, and both within
cially only the former being important and outside the individual. The mechanisms
diagnostically, etiologically, and therapeutically. allow an easy flow for integration of biological,
In the following, I examine other concepts rel- psychological, and social elements into causal
evant to the search for etiological sources to men- processes. The parts of the system are organized
tal disorders, concentrating on the work of into higher levels within contexts, and they
Kendler. His work has inspired my own, which exhibit part-whole or component-system syner-
ends up quite consistent with his concepts. gistic relations. The process involves feedback,
or causal-loop recursive relationships, that are
both top-down and bottom-up. Kendler (2008)
Concepts concluded that causal networks underlying psy-
chiatric disorder contain multiple, nonlinear
Kendler (2015) argued for an approach of “lim- interactions and causal loops.
ited” realism for psychiatric nosology. Psychiatry Kendler, Zachar, and Craver (2011) contrasted
needs a less ambitious framework for its truth (a) the essentialist, (b) socially-constructed, and
seeking than outright (scientific) realism, given (c) practical approaches to understanding psychi-
its limitations. The contrasting position to real- atric disorders, leading to their approach of (d)
ism is instrumentalism, which is about establish- mechanistic property clusters (MPCs). The
ing useful concepts rather than ones with more essentialist model argues that a causal essence is
absolute truth. “Pessimistic induction” supports directly responsible for the critical features that
an instrumental as opposed to a realism approach characterize a disorder (see Fig. 25.1). The
to psychiatric nosology. Coherence theory is con- socially-constructed model maintains that disor-
sistent with the latter view of truth. In this regard, ders are understood as social and cultural con-
as long as a proposed diagnostic category “fits structions. The practical model views disorders
well” with other aspects of which we know about from an instrumentalist, pragmatic perspective;
confidently related to the diagnostic category at as long as the disorder is clinically useful, it is not
issue, it contributes to nosology in psychiatry. irrelevant even if it is not genuine.
Instrumentalism has a certain place in nosology In the MPC approach, the authors account for
in that categories that work for psychiatry instru- the fact that psychiatric disorders are multifacto-
mentally help predict and manipulate the world. rial and “fuzzy” sets. They are complex, mutually-
The overall psychiatric classificatory project reinforcing networks related to causal structures
reflects realism, thought, and Kendler refers to it or mechanisms. The model facilitates psychiatry
as a “type” one. However, in psychiatric nosol- developing a more causally-based classification
ogy, the specific categories reflect a humbler system. MPC allows for individual differences in
approach to truth, which is consistent with the psychiatric disorder manifestation, in that it
Causality and Etiology in Psychology and Psychiatry 631

S5 S1 C4

D
C3 CS C1

S4 S2

S3
C2

Fig. 25.1 An essentialist model of symptoms/signs (S)


and clusters. In an essentialist model of a psychiatric dis-
order (D), an essence is responsible directly and causally
for its critical signs and symptoms (S). Adapted from
Kendler et al. (2011)
S4

S5 S1

S3 SS S1

S4 S2
S2

Fig. 25.3 A mixed model of multifactorial causes and


S3 symptom clusters of psychiatric disorder. In this mixed
model of psychiatric disorder, a series of multifactorial
Fig. 25.2 A nonessentialist model of symptoms/signs (S) causes (C1 to C4) in a causal system (CS) interact with
and clusters. The individual clinical features are causally each other to produce an underlying system state (SS)
interrelated to one another but not to a putative latent, orga- that, in turn, leads to the individual symptoms/signs (S1 to
nizing universally-labeled disorder that is responsible for S4), which, in their turn, could causally interact amongst
them. The clusters could organize such that one symptom themselves. Adapted from Kendler et al. (2011)
(set) causes (an)other(s). Adapted from Kendler et al. (2011)

considers that there is no single set of traits for tain or reinforce each other and appear more or
disorders. Rather, the traits involved cluster near less stable.
one or another in a “feature space.” There is no Another way to understand the MPC model
one deterministic symptom cluster, nor is there is shown in Fig. 25.3. A series of causes interact
one cause for disorder. That is, cause is consid- to produce a latent underlying state that influ-
ered “messy” and, also, clusters are considered ences symptom expression over time. There is
imperfect or heterogeneous. However, this fuzzi- no single causal mechanism, but multiple ones.
ness does not mean that there is instability in a Despite some stability, the relevant causal fea-
disorder. There are common co-occurrences of tures express a probabilistic relationship with
features because of the way causal mechanisms the clusters of symptoms and signs. Causes are
work, as shown in Fig. 25.2. Individual symp- not deterministic, but act to change the degree
toms or signs interact so that they mutually sus- of probability that symptoms (or their sets) will
632 25 DSM-5: Recommendations

be manifested. Because there are numerous schizophrenia. Specifically, a disordered stress


overlapping mechanisms, linear relationships response might serve to decouple frontal-striatal
between cause and effect, or between mecha- and frontal-limbic neuronal networks in at-risk
nism and diagnoses, are illusory. Kendler et al. youth.
(2011) noted that Borsboom (2008) presented a In relation to underlying epigenetic factors
similar model, which he termed the causal sys- acting in conjunction with genetic, environmen-
tem approach. tal, and neuronal network ones, epigenetic effects
Kendler et al. (2011) concluded that sets of might impact progressively gene expression in
symptoms are connected through sets of causal critical networks during successive developmen-
relationships. Moreover, they believed that their tal epochs (Millan, 2013). The effects on the
approach is consistent with a prototypical per- growing person could relate to increased stress
spective on psychiatric disorder. In this approach, sensitivity as stress-sensitive genes relating to the
exemplar cases rather than lists of symptoms are hypothalamic pituitary adrenal (HPA) axis are
used to operationalize disorders, and so the impacted. For example, Fillman, Sinclair, Fung,
approach allows for variation in individual cases Webster, and Shannon Weickert (2014) found
and symptom expression. This is the consistent differences in gene expression in stress-related
with the notion that boundaries of “kinds” of psy- genes as per post-mortem brain tissue analysis in
chiatric illness are fuzzier than proposed in the schizophrenics (relative to individuals with other
essentialist approach. The authors argued that psychiatric disorders and controls). Once more,
disorders should be defined at the level of prop- the authors invoked the hope for finding biologi-
erty clusters that are underpinned by dysfunc- cal signatures of psychiatric disease in early and
tional, yet self-sustaining mechanisms. progressive epigenetic effects.
Kendler (2012) added further to his etiological
approach to nosology. He argued for fuzzy, cross-
level mechanisms as sources of psychiatric disor- Other Considerations
der. Etiology is multiple and higher-order rather
than simplistic and singly caused. Cross-level Networks Arguello and Gogos (2012) noted the
mechanisms are “fuzzy sets” over etiological lev- extensive etiological and pathophysiological het-
els that lead to individual variations in manifesta- erogeneity and overlap related to psychiatric dis-
tion of a psychiatric disorder. order. They suggested that the temporal dynamics
Genes constitute important etiological sources of synaptic plasticity in specific neural circuits
in psychiatric illness. But, as Kendler has empha- could play a role in phenotypic expression of
sized, psychiatric etiology is multifactorial. clinical disorders. This might be the case even
Moreover, genes themselves are part of a larger more so than genetic and environmental causes.
genomic system in which the environment can Factors to consider in this regard include altera-
affect their workings through epigenesis. tions in synaptic growth and maintenance, synap-
togenesis, and axonal guidance, and their
developmental changes and trajectories neurody-
Epigenetics namically and as they assemble and communi-
cate within neural circuits.
Diwadkar, Bustamante, Rai, and Uddin (2014) van Os, Delespaul, Wigman, Myin-Germeys,
argued that epigenetics could affect gene expres- and Wichers (2013) also adopted a system-based
sion levels that mediate the stress response in at- approach to psychiatric classification. They
risk individuals for schizophrenia. The functional argued for a contextual precision diagnosis
consequences would lie in impaired cognitive approach across stages of psychopathology that
consequences dependent on or subserved by respects the need for more individualized con-
affected brain networks. Thus, epigenetics stands siderations. That is, diagnoses need to include
as the proximate mediator in the pathway to (a) precision, (b) context, and (c) stages, in
Causality and Etiology in Psychology and Psychiatry 633

which (a) causal influences in system networks along with their individualized approach, their
are recognized, (b) symptoms are understood as nosological recommendations could include
responses to context, and (c) they are understood common syndromal groupings that are higher-
to develop over time. order and more severe.
In terms of a contextual precision diagnosis, The approach of Borsboom and colleagues is
van Os et al. (2013) maintained that disorders are quite compatible with the psychiatric approach
manifested heterogeneously and so should be involving systems of symptoms and their causal
subject to personalized diagnosis based on pat- underpinnings. Borsboom (2008) explained ren-
terns of symptom expression in context. They dition of the difference between the traditional
indicated that symptoms are manifested in inter- latent variable model of a disorder and a net-
acting circuits, combinations, or sets (including worked causal model. In the former one, underly-
in feedback both within and over levels and in ing constructs are considered sources of symptom
interactions at the micro-moment and over time) expression. In the latter networked model, symp-
that are connected through systems of causal toms can possess linkages independent of any
relations, thereby allowing for individualized co- underlying source (see Chap. 6).
occurrence of different symptoms (Borsboom, The network construct is applied to how per-
Cramer, Schmittmann, Epskamp, & Waldorp, sonality test items are organized. The traditional
2011; Kendler et al., 2011). reflective model places a latent construct at the
van Os et al. (2013) concluded that contextual epicenter of item loadings, explaining their indi-
precision diagnosis can capture well individual- vidual expression via common linkage to it. The
ized, idiopathic symptom expression and so formative model runs in the reverse direction,
replace nomothetic approaches to classification with items contributing to the composite variable
(McGorry & van Os, 2013). Figure 25.4 presents representing them. The network model avoids
in detail their contextual precision diagnostic altogether central representations and seeks to
model (also see Wigman, Collip, et al., 2013; represent item linkages and their strengths in a
Wigman, van Os, et al., 2013). They noted that, nodal network with edges (links) (see Chap. 7).

d h

Cheer-
a Paranoia c e g
fulness

b f

Note: positive recursive feedback

negative “repellor” feedback

Fig. 25.4 Contextual precision diagnosis. Symptom links ple, stress leads to paranoia, low mood, and anxiety, and
can vary in strength of associations. Symptoms form cir- also decreased cheerfulness. Both have a strong tendency
cuit patterns of mental state, resulting in a causal circuit. A to persist over time, allowing for stable symptoms.
strong positive feedback loop exists between similar symp- Adapted from van Os et al. (2013), originally from
toms and a negative one across opposite ones. For exam- Wigman, Collip et al. (2013); Wigman, van Os et al. (2013)
634 25 DSM-5: Recommendations

Brains Goodkind et al. (2015) conducted two Poldrack et al. (2011) took a very broad view
studies, one with patients and one with healthy of where cognition fits into the relation between
controls. In the patient study, they supported a neural systems and syndromes (see Fig. 25.5).
transdiagnostic perspective of mental illness They included in their model the DLPFC (dorsal
by finding a common gray matter loss in three lateral prefrontal cortex), executive processes
brain regions in participant groups having (e.g., working memory updating), and response
diagnoses as diverse as schizophrenia, bipolar inhibition. The signaling pathways include the
disorder, depression, addiction, obsessive- neurotransmitter dopamine. The model adds
compulsive disorder, and anxiety. For the first genetic covariations, including catechol-O-
of their two studies, they conducted a meta- methyltransferase (COMT) and dopamine recep-
analysis of 193 research studies involving tor D2 (DRD2) genetic variants for dopamine.
almost 16,000 individuals. Also, in a second
data gathering undertaking, they studied three
independent sets of healthy participants for the A Combined Top-Down/Bottom-Up
interconnections of the three index regions Integrated Causal (Etiological)
with other regions with gray matter loss in the Model of Mental Disorder
diagnostic groups mentioned.
To delve further into their two studies, for the There are both top-down and bottom-up models
first patient one, Goodkind et al. (2015) exam- of the relationship between mental disorder and
ined patient/control differences in regional symptoms. Whether in terms of full disorder or a
brain volume from whole-brain structural neu- cluster in a disorder, a top-down model under-
roimaging data (in studies reporting coordinates stands the relationship between disorder and
in a defined stereotaxic space), referred to as symptom in terms of an underlying psychologi-
voxel-based morphometry (VBM). The com- cal construct that represents, integrates, or allows
mon gray matter loss regions across the diverse for (or causes) the symptoms expressive of it
diagnoses involved the anterior insula (left and (Borsboom, 2008; McNally et al., 2015;
right) and the dorsal anterior cingulate (dACC). Schmittmann et al., 2013). This type of modeling
These regions are associated with executive is standard in the field (e.g., for psychiatric diag-
function. There were some between-diagnosis nostic manuals, for psychological tests). In the
gray matter volume differences, especially bottom-up approach to relating mental disorder
involving schizophrenia. and symptoms, the latter rather than the former
The second parallel study with healthy indi- have causal primacy, and their interrelationship
viduals showed that these regions formed a net- represents, informs, and defines the link between
work both during task performance (mostly on disorder and symptom (whether in a full disorder
executive function) and also at rest. Indeed, the or a cluster within one). Wigman et al. (2015)
more the controls in this study evidenced gray have elaborated a combined approach to top-
matter loss in this network, the lower was their down and bottom-up modeling of the relation-
executive function performance. ship of symptoms to mental disorder. However,
Generally, the results speak to a shared neuro- in their approach, top-down statistical approaches
biological structural substrate or endophenotype were applied to networked connections (and not
across psychopathology, even if a diverse set of the states/symptoms involved themselves).
etiologies might be involved. The authors con- In the present integrative model of mental dis-
cluded that the results are consistent with the order (see Fig. 25.6), causation is deemed to lie in
goals of the RDoC project (Research Domain of both top-down and bottom-up processes that
Criteria; Insel et al., 2010) on the dimensional reciprocally interact. The underlying emergent,
biological underpinnings to psychopathology, higher-order psychological phenomenon, such as
which stands in contrast to the DSM-5 categori- PTSD, should influence symptom expression in
cal approach. context, but the array and dynamic interaction of
Endophenotypes 635

SYNDROME Schizophrenia Bipolar Disorder ADHD

COGNITION WM Updating Response Inhibition

Response inhibition is
related to VLPFC activity
as found in the contrast of
stop vs. go trials in the
Stop Signal Task

NEURAL DL PFC VL PFC


SYSTEM

SIGNALLING
D1 D2 A2a
PATHWAY

GENE COMT DRD2 ADRA2a

Fig. 25.5 Relating biological functions and processes to alpha-2-adrenergic receptor. The links between the differ-
psychiatric symptoms and syndromes. Abbreviations. ent levels reflect possible empirical relations; the strength
ADHD = attention deficit hyperactivity disorder, WM = of the links (indexed by their width) is proportional to the
working memory, DL PFC = dorsolateral prefrontal strength of the scientific literature findings involving
cortex, VL PFC = ventrolateral prefrontal cortex, D = them. Each link can be specified for empirical results in
dopamine, A = adrenergic, COMT = catechol-O-methyl- the literature, as noted for one of them. Adapted from
transferase, DRD2 = dopamine receptor D2, ADRA2a = Poldrack et al. (2011)

the symptoms involved should influence the components of the model. I elaborated this model
nature of the higher-order construct, as well. The in order to accommodate the different views of
different levels of the disorder in these regards, bottom-up and top-down processes in causality
its symptoms, and any associated comorbidities over symptoms and mental health as found in
and their symptoms constitute dynamic states, McNally et al. (2015) and Wigman et al. (2015).
their changes, and the transitions between them
(which sometimes should lead to newly emergent
states in disorder and symptom trajectory). Endophenotypes
Figure 25.7 further elaborates the relationship
between top-down and bottom-up processes in Concept
the causal relationship between symptoms and
mental health. It incorporates the model of emer- One criticism of the biomarker approach to psy-
gent circular causality in Young (2011) and chopathology and psychiatric disorder is that the
applies it to each of the bottom-up and top-down disorders are polygenetic and little progress has
636 25 DSM-5: Recommendations

S1*

(S4) Cluster S2
1*

(S3)

S1*
S1*

(S4) (Cluster S2 Mental (S4) Cluster 2 S2


4) Disorder

(S3) (S3)

S1*

(S4) (Cluster S2
3)

(S3)

Fig. 25.6 Integrated causal model of mental disorders parentheses indicate that mental disorders might have
(bottom up, top down). The figure depicts the relationship only 2 clusters, and a cluster might have only 2 symptoms.
between symptoms and mental disorder (or a symptom Of course, either might have more items (i.e., clusters or
cluster of one) as dynamically reciprocal in causation. The symptoms, respectively). Of the clusters in any mental
mental disorder constitutes an underlying, higher-order disorder, for the symptoms, it would be beneficial to spec-
level in the patient’s mental state symptoms, while the ify which ones are core/primary. For the model presented
symptoms interact at lower-levels of the system, with both in the figure, these could be the first clusters or symptoms
the top-down and bottom-up influences dynamically influ- that are specified by the asterisks
encing each other in context and over time. Note. The

been made in relating genes to global syndromes In Gottesman’s model, gene regions might
or disorders, such as schizophrenia. Gottesman help specify endophenotypes (such as cell
(e.g., Gottesman & Gould, 2003) developed the abnormalities or brain function) that interact
concept of endophenotypes to improve the search with environment and susceptibility factors to
for gene-disorder relations. Endophenotypes produce schizophrenia. Research seeks the best
especially are considered biological, in that they candidate endophenotypes in its search for rela-
are intermediate expressions of a disorder tions in gene loci-disorder outcome. Usually,
between genes and global outcome, for example, they are biological and often neuroendopheno-
measures involving brain activity or lobes of the typic. For example, Sherin and Nemeroff (2011)
brain (see Fig. 25.8). described the candidate endophenotypes for
Endophenotypes 637

a Emergent Bottom-Up Circular Causality

Superordinate level
(constructed from lower-order levels/ sublevels; distinct from them)

Emergent new levels


(constructed from system elements; distinct from them; also, their
interactions might create new lower-order levels/ sublevels)

System elements
(e.g., symptoms; also, their interaction influences/ creates their
elements) 1

b Emergent Top-Down Circular Causality

Superordinate level
(influences/ creates lower (sub)levels/ elements)

Lower-order levels/ sublevels


(influence/ create their elements)

System elements in each level/ sublevel


(as elements change, potential for bottom-up emergent circular
causality begins a new) 2

Note. 1 Configuration/ pattern changes possible, too, within and between (sub) levels.
2 Bottom-up and top-down causal processes work together reciprocally in system causality

Fig. 25.7 The interaction of top-down and bottom-up influence/create their configuration/patterning, expres-
emergent circular causality. The figure illustrates the sion, or even denovo emergence. This process may occur
dynamic interaction of bottom-up and top-down processes both through movement from lower to higher levels in the
both within and across levels in a system, including the level hierarchy involved (bottom-up), or from higher to
possibility of emergence of new symptoms, levels, and lower levels (top-down), or reciprocally in both ways. In
sublevels. It also indicates the change of patterning or essence, the figure clarifies that bottom-up processes work
configuration possible within and between levels in the both within and between levels, as do top-down processes,
system dynamics involved. Briefly, as system elements in system function. Adapted from Young (2015)
(e.g., symptoms) or levels/sublevels interact, they might

posttraumatic stress disorder (PTSD; see sidered as primary ones [genes → (other biol-
Table 25.1). Chapter 21 expands that description ogy) → psychology = diathesis and stress
to contemporary findings. (environment) → psychopathology]. In more recent
Miller and Rockstroh (2013) provided an views, causality in psychopathology resides in a
expansive and nuanced view of endophenotypes nomological network organized among relevant
in psychopathology. They contrasted the tradi- factors rather than their causal linking in a sequen-
tional approach to understanding psychopathol- tial manner. The networks are complex patterns of
ogy with an endophenotypic approach, but noted regularities, and they constitute an indefinite set of
conceptual, methodological, and empirical cau- reciprocal, mutually-influencing, recursive rela-
tions as they proceeded. tionships. In this conception, genes do not set the
In the traditional view, psychopathology results stage, with environment merely combining addi-
from a linear causal chain, with earlier links con- tively or incrementally with them to create fixed
638 25 DSM-5: Recommendations

High

Harmful
Susceptibility

Liability to
Schizophrenia Reaction Surface
N/A Schizophrenia Spectrum

Environment

Protective
Low

Development (Age)

(endophenotypes to schizophrenia)

Sample Candidate Endophenotypes


Working Memory
Sensorimotor Gating
Oculomotor Function
Glial Cell Abnormalities

(genes to endophenotypes)

Sample Quantitative Trait Loci in Genome


1q41, 1q42.1 (disrupted-in-schizophrenia 1 gene)
22q11.21 (catechol-O-methyltransferase)
8p21 (neuregulin)
6p22-24 (dysbindin)

Fig. 25.8 Sample gene regions, genes, and possible expressing schizophrenia. Gene regions with more consis-
endophenotypes implicated in schizophrenia. Dynamic tent linkage findings are in bold. Adapted from Gottesman
developmental interplay among genetic, environmental, and Gould (2003)
and epigenetic factors produces cumulative liability to

outcomes. Similarly, endophenotypes, which can multiple brain regions have been implicated for
be conceived as mid-system, midlevel, or down- multiple executive function deficits, but should
stream (e.g., neuronal) phenotypes, including they be considered as separate or as integrated
behavioral ones that might be closer to their pre- circuits in endophenotypic conceptualizations
sumed genetic/biological associations, should not related to the disorder? Moreover, are the circuits
be construed in a linear model and simply inserted and their associated genetic facilitators a function
in the chain from gene to behavior (Gottesman & of additive or interactive functions? The authors
Gould, 2003). proposed something more than these options—
Miller and Rockstroh (2013) addressed the that both the psychological and neural levels
appropriate granularity in defining relevant endo- involved might be emergent, whole, dynamical,
phenotypes that might be implicated in psycho- webbed, superordinate, multilevel networks. The
pathology. For example, in schizophrenia, network concept constitutes the best way to
Interim Conclusion 639

Table 25.1 Summary of neurobiological features with potential endophenotype (a) being associated
identified abnormalities and functional implications in with the illness at issue; (b) demonstrating herita-
patients with posttraumatic stress disorder
bility; (c) generally evidencing detectability
Feature Change independent of the target illness’s current expres-
A. Neuroendocrine sion; (d) co-segregating within families of pro-
HPA Hypocortisolism
bands having the illness; (e) being more common
Augmented level of CRH
in healthy family members of probands than in
HPT Abnormal T3:T4 ratio
the general population; and (f) being measured
B. Neurochemical
reliably.
Catecholamines Augmented dopamine,
norepinephrine levels/activity According to these criteria, the results of the
Serotonin Less concentrations of 5HT in literature review on selected candidate endophe-
dorsal, median, dorsal/median raphe notypes for depression indicated some strong
Amino acids Less GABA activity support—for neuroticism, in particular; as well as
Augmented glutamate for elevated morning cortisol level and the corti-
Peptides Less plasma NPY sol awakening response; asymmetry of cortical
Augmented CSF β-endorphine electrical activity (normally the left side is associ-
Hippocampus Less volume/activity ated with approach behavior/positive affect and
Amygdala Augmented activity the right with withdrawal/negative affect); deficits
Cortex Less prefrontal, anterior cingulate in reward learning; and memory/attention biases.
volume
Less medial prefrontal activity
Adapted from Sherin and Nemeroff (2011)
Abbreviations. HPA = hypothalamic pituitary adrenal Interim Conclusion
axis, HPT = hypothalamic pituitary thyroid axis,
CRH = corticotrophin-releasing hormone, 5-HT = serotonin, The field of psychiatry can profit from these
GABA = γ-aminobutyric acid, NPY = neuropeptide Y,
novel ideas on etiology by addressing the follow-
CSF = cerebrospinal fluid
ing issues. It should develop (a) an integrated
biopsychosocial model that includes systems and
approach causation of any associated psychiatric networks, (b) an integration of categorical and
abnormalities, because the ones at issue when dimensional approaches to classification that
they might express deficiencies in executive con- reflects the integrated biopsychosocial model,
trol. Given their large-scale focus, most likely, and (c) a way of systematizing the clinical assess-
some of the networks at work psychiatrically ment that could give more credence to any diag-
should be transdiagnostic, and inform traditional nostic conclusion, no matter which diagnostic
psychiatric manual-based comorbidities. The classification system is used. In the next part of
network concept in psychiatry is not compatible the chapter, I offer a suite of recommendations
with a linear model that genes are the beginning consistent with these ideas that suggests ways the
of development toward psychopathology in a DSM enterprise can evolve in a dynamically
causal chain. To conclude, Miller and Rockstroh evolving discipline of psychiatry, being part of its
(2013) noted that there is no serial causality in growth and contributing to it.
psychopathology but a rich causal cascade. Network approaches, by definition, empha-
Goldstein and Klein (2014) used the size which symptoms in a set are core com-
Gottesman and Gould criteria (Chan & pared to secondary or less important, which
Gottesman, 2008; Gottesman & Gould, 2003; will help reduce the fuzziness of psychiatric
Gould & Gottesman, 2006) for determining when categories that emerge by their use without sac-
a construct could be considered an endopheno- rificing the notion of probabilistic, fuzzy
type. They determined that, for depression, sev- boundaries characterizing them. Network con-
eral candidate endophenotypes met the criteria to cepts address individual differences in symp-
a sufficient degree. The criteria involved the tom expression and understanding, which will
640 25 DSM-5: Recommendations

facilitate precision and personalized medicine/ An Endophenotypic Model


treatment. The suite of recommendations that I
propose for psychiatric nosology derives from The search for endophenotypes in relation to psy-
the scientific domain, but they are meant to be chiatric disorder should take a broader view than
clinical useful (or instrumental). The recom- the standard one. If psychiatric illness is related
mendations begin with a biopsychosocial to biopsychosocial factors, then candidate endo-
model of endophenotypes, which prepares the phenotypes for any specific disorder could
way for other recommendations related to the include variables other than biological ones.
biopsychosocial model. Also, they might be represented by specific net-
works of symptoms in the sense described by
Borsboom and colleagues (e.g., Borsboom,
Recommendations 2008). In this regard, Table 25.2 presents an
expansive model of endophenotypes that includes
Psychiatry needs an integrative model that functions and behavior/test items, including in
respects the multiple, individuated symptom networked ways, as well as environment, devel-
expressions encountered in patients and also the opment, and therapeutic agents.
multiple intervention/treatment options available In Table 25.2, I organized candidate endophe-
in the field, including auxiliary ones such as in notypes according to complexity and degree to
psychology. Moreover, the integrative model which they are distal from genotype. The model
should be informed by the biopsychosocial is general and applicable to any mental disorder,
model. Finally, it can serve the field if it is linked although, for environment, I included abuse and
to contemporary advances in understanding etiol- trauma. I put at the end of the table Gottesman
ogy as systems, such as nonlinear dynamics and and Gould’s (2003) listing of environment and
network modeling. development in their work on endophenotypes.

Table 25.2 Candidate endophenotypes: a vertical and horizontal model


Level
Area Vertical Horizontal
Genome Transcriptome Protein
Epigenome Marks
Neurome Nervous system Peripheral/central
(neuroendophenotype) Neurons Dendrites/synapses
Neurotransmitters Dopamine/serotonin, etc.
Brain Neurons Network
Astrocytes Network
Region Network
Lobe Network
Function Control Executive reflective/automatic habitual
Activation/inhibition Coordination/discoordination
Behavior Single Symptom
Set Syndrome/disorder
Assessment Test Above cut score
Battery Multiple results
Environment Pre-existing Adversity, chronic abuse
Differential susceptibility Perceptual, allelic
Trauma Exposure, horrific
Development Age Younger, older
Learning Coping/resilience, catastrophize
Therapy Pharmacological Multiple
Psychological Multiple
Recommendations 641

The table includes an area between the areas of study and has emerged important in the litera-
of brain and behavior that concerns of function, ture. Their widely distributed modality would
emphasizing control and inhibition. In addition, make them harder to detect individually but their
for each area of possible endophenotype, I give integrated nature would make the detection closer
examples both vertically in terms of complexity, to the actual manner in which the brain functions.
or other qualifications, and horizontally in terms A science of individual differences of disorder
of subareas. that is based on biological markers (biomarkers),
For the genome level, I added epigenetics. For yet includes a role for environment (context),
neuroendophenotypes, I gave the full range of development, and the person’s individual path-
areas in the neurome. For the brain, I emphasized ways and proclivities (e.g., personality, coping),
networks as much as individual components. would frame the model as a biopsychosocial one.
Further, behaviors can be single or collections, as Young, Lareau, and Pierre (2014) have high-
can be test measures. lighted the relevance of the latter for PTSD.
The environment and developmental levels of The neuroscientifically-based RDoC criteria
the model stand as relevant contextual modifiers (Insel & Lieberman, 2013) might emphasize the
in understanding endophenotypes. Therapeutic biological substrate of disorders at the expense of
agents can act at any area and level of the model, multifactorial influences, as found in the biopsy-
and indicate endophenotypic interactions, as chosocial model. In this regard, I have presented
could the environmental and developmental a model for study of endophenotypes that respects
levels. multiple influences on etiology of psychiatric
The table illustrates that the association of disorder, including the psychosocial, without
genetic loci to disease by way of endophenotypes sacrificing the goal of finding causal links from
needs to consider the complex array of candi- genes to behavior. The DSM-5 has been widely
dates at multiple levels of analysis. It queries the criticized (e.g., Young, 2013; Young et al., 2014),
efficacy of considering gene-disorder linkages at but if it takes the premature step of adhering
the macro-level in terms of diagnostic categories, especially to standard endophenotypic and RDoC
such as found in the DSM-5 (Diagnostic and models in its revisions, it risks further alienating
Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, Fifth multiple stakeholders and users.
Edition; American Psychiatric Association, The field is far from establishing a reliable and
2013) and the upcoming ICD-11 (International valid detection system of disorder that can apply
Classification of Diseases, 11th Revision; World effectively in individual cases based on physio-
Health Organization, 2017). logical and neuronal parameters. Nevertheless,
sufficient progress has been made such that bio-
logical measures related to disorder could one
Critique day add incremental validity and complement
traditional assessment procedures in increasing
Although the work in the area of endophenotypes the probability of certainty in assessment and
(Gottesman & Gould, 2003) and genetics (Wilker diagnostic conclusions. However, at present and
& Kolassa, 2013) might be construed as highly in the near future, it would be premature to seek
biological in focus, the interactions of the individual biomarkers of disorder for such pur-
environment with the genome, for example, poses, given the current state of knowledge in the
through allostatic load (McEwen, 2006) and field, even if it is burgeoning. Nevertheless,
long-lasting and transmittable epigenetic stamps workers in the area should keep up to date on the
(Meaney, 2010; Szyf, 2013), illustrate that indi- literature for breakthroughs in these regards. For
vidual pathways either toward the development example, the research on the five-factor model of
of disorder or toward resilience are not only PTSD (Elhai et al., 2011) and its relation to
biologically-determined. The construct of neural Gene × Environment (G × E) interactions (e.g.,
networks (Sporns, 2012) cuts across these areas Pietrzak et al., 2014) constitutes an important
642 25 DSM-5: Recommendations

thrust in the search for valid endophenotypes in respect to the population at issue. Diagnoses
PTSD and the search for individual-case primary, might involve the placement of an individual on
core (bio)markers. relevant collective continua. The model is a prob-
abilistic, statistical one.
In contrast to the traditional categorical and
Modeling dimensional models, the biopsychosocial model
being proposed is a systemic, dynamic, and
Table 25.3 summarizes the argument that the integrated one that considers: (a) the multifacto-
extended biopsychosocial model supported in the rial causes in illness expression; (b) the individ-
present work can serve as an adequate basis for ual ways that its symptoms are manifested in
elaborating a scientifically-informed and clini- networked patterns; and (c) the individualized
cally useful psychiatric diagnostic classification medicine or intervention/treatment approaches
system. It looks at the questions of mental disor- that would be consistent with the patterns. An
der, diagnoses, etiology, and underlying model in extended biopsychosocial model considers the
terms of the traditional categorical and dimen- possibility of nonlinear dynamical transitions in
sional approaches to nosology as well as of the mental health, or from one attractor (health) to
biopsychosocial approach being advocated. another (dysfunction; Young, 2011). The patterns
In this representation of the categorical in the system are both micro- or local and macro-
approach to psychiatric classification, mental dis- or global across different levels. Mind is self-
order is considered an all-or-none medical dis- organizing and emergent from biological and
ease with each disorder (operationalized by brain processes, and its pattern could reflect the
criteria, including polythetic ones for the symp- assembly of categorical states, dimensions, and
toms), such that each disorder is a natural kind their combinations. Patterns are constantly con-
carved at the joints, with clear etiology (biologi- structed in the person, and psychiatric approaches
cal in nature), uniform symptom expression, and to disorder should be individualized to fit this
corresponding unifocal (read; psychopharmaceu- individualizing symptom reality.
tical) intervention and treatment direction. As for Figure 25.9 presents another way of distin-
the dimensional approach, it denies separate cat- guishing the standard approaches to psychiatry
egories of disorder, viewing mental illness as and an integrated biopsychosocial one. In the
ranging on continua that are quantifiable. standard approach, effort is expended to find dis-
Statistically, the model might include compari- tinctive mental disorder. Workers then seek out
son of individuals to norms, or otherwise esti- their causes, especially genetically and physio-
mate their relative placement or deviation with logically as biomarkers, e.g., in the brain. The

Table 25.3 Approaches to psychiatric classification


Approach
Issue Categorical Dimensional Biopsychosocial
Mental disorder All-or-none disease Threshold on normal curve Dysfunctional (network)
presence or other estimated or pattern for context
normative distribution
Diagnoses Entities with specific Degree of difficulty on Local and global (attractor)
symptom arrays, and relevant continua (normative) system patterns (focus:
corresponding causes individual, population)
and treatments (natural (variables: categorical,
kinds, but polythetic) dimensional)
Etiology (causation) Biological (genetic, Probabilistic Systemic, dynamic
physiological)
Underlying model Medical/disease Statistical/deviation Integrated/illness
Treatment Of the disease, common Of the disease, common Of the person, individual
Recommendations 643

Fig. 25.9 Revised model of causation in a Standard Psychiatric Model


psychiatry. Instead of inferring cause from
the diagnosis, representing the constellation Common
of symptoms, the latter are analyzed for Category
networks, which themselves are causal. This Diagnosed
process allows for personalized treatment Helps Find Cause
and consideration of diagnosis as secondary
in importance

Common
Cause(s)
Treatment
Inferred
Prescribed

b Biopsychosocial Psychiatric/ Medical Model

Individual’s
Networking System is the
Cause

Personalized
Category
Treatment
Inferred
Prescribed

categories are associated with one-size-fit-all Practice


intervention/treatment.
In contrast, in the proposed extended biopsy- Table 25.4 reviews the manner in which a com-
chosocial model, the symptom complex of the bined categorical, dimensional, and biopsycho-
patient is cardinal, as is its linkages in individual- social approach to psychiatry can help the field in
ized patterns. The network of nodes, edges (rela- assessment, diagnosis, and treatment. Categories
tions), and context gives a workable and dimensions are considered “fuzzy” concepts
understanding of the patient. The clinician might with no clear boundaries, such that each can be
then find that the case description matches a conceived as the other if defined and organized
diagnostic categorical one, e.g., being close to a appropriately. The work in this regard must start
prototype or close to a polythetic category (and with assessment. This process, too, concerns both
perhaps even a dimensional construction of dis- categorical and dimensional constructs; and if
order). Etiology does not lie in an external source these constructs can be simplified into a clinically-
that impacts the system, but in the organization friendly and usable framework, the assessments
of the symptom complex of the individual in will be quasi-standardized to allow for simplified
relation to the multifactorial proximal and distal effective diagnosis.
(close and far, e.g., genetic) causes. With clear In this regard, in the next portion of the pres-
perspective on person and causation, individual- ent work, I provide a coherent yet accessible
ized medicine approaches to intervention and approach to assessment that prepares the way for
treatment are facilitated, including of the psy- a more reliable diagnosis process. In this sense,
chosocial and not only the biological or psycho- just as the categories are the dimensions and the
pharmacological type. dimensions are the categories so, too, is the
644 25 DSM-5: Recommendations

Table 25.4 Hybrid categorical/dimensional systems approach to psychiatry


System Explanation
The categories are the dimensions Evaluate patients dimensionally on multiple relevant categories (0, 1, 2)
(dimensionalize the categories)
The dimensions are the categories These ratings give the basis for finding the closest (hopefully accurate)
(categorize the dimensions) diagnostic categories needed from diagnostic manual
The dimensions and categories for a The categories and dimensions form the individual’s network of causal
(hybrid) biopsychosocial system symptom/dysfunction/disorder/impairment/disability and treatment complex

assessment the diagnosis and the diagnosis the Table 25.5 Proposed psychiatric assessment dimensions
assessment. Grouping Dimensions
This interweaving of psychiatric constructs Major Communication/language
that are fuzzy into dialectical relations that are Mood
reciprocal speaks to the proposed extended bio- Thought
psychosocial model’s system and network char- Activity/energy
acteristics, in which the symptom patterns are Function
also causes. Further, there is no pathway from Secondary Environment/context
cause to symptoms to treatment that is linear in Relations (e.g., family, partner)
this model. Social skills
In the end, psychiatry distinguishes itself from Coping
other medical specialties by its emphasis on the Self/personality
whole person. Mental state is embedded in mul- Auxiliary Age (stage, development)
tiple physiological and brain states that are in Gender
Culture/minority
interaction, and psychiatry can stand at the
Socioeconomic status
forefront in adapting a systemic approach, such
Medical/physical/neurovegetative
as the one being presented.
“Dimensional” Spectrum location
With an approach such as this, the undue
Frequency
importance given to diagnosis will lose some of Duration
its edge, and it will become only one point of an Temporal
equilibrated psychiatric process. Diagnosis does Intensity/severity
not constitute the final arbiter of the nature of the Complicating Self-control
patient’s dysfunction, but it is simply an ongoing Substance (ab)use
statement that summarizes the most important Self-deception
aspect of the patient, that is, the network of symp- Other-deception
toms involved in the biopsychosocial context. By Aberrant/inappropriate
taking an approach such as this, psychiatry would Rating 0
address its problem with clinical utility in diag- (1/2)
nosis and intervention/treatment. 1
To conclude, I offer a tentative structure or tem- (1 ½)
plate for an organized psychiatric assessment pro- 2
cedure that includes ratings that are amenable to NA/TBA
reliability research. Table 25.5 constitutes an
introductory table that presents the five major precision and detail on their nature and they should
areas or categories of psychiatric assessment that constitute the focus in assessment. In the ensuing
should be accounted for with each patient, as well six tables, for each of the psychiatric areas of
as a ratings table. The five core psychiatric areas in assessment in the proposed system, I present their
assessment concern: (a) major; (b) secondary; (c) subcategories of the core areas are presented in the
auxiliary; (d) “dimensional,” and (e) complicating ensuing six tables (see Tables 25.6, 25.7, 25.8,
categories. Their subcategories or dimensions give 25.9, 25.10, and 25.11).
Recommendations 645

Table 25.6 Proposed major psychiatric assessment dimensions


Dimension Explanation
Communication/language Ability to listen and express oneself, verbally and nonverbally; pragmatic, social use
of language
Mood A primary manifestation of psychological distress relates to maladaptive emotional or
affective experience and expression. There are four major negative moods: depression,
anxiety, anger–aggression, and fear, as well as others (specify); also suicidality
Thought Thoughts are psychiatrically relevant as thought disorders, cognitive disorders,
memory/concentration disturbance, maladaptive thinking, intelligence, insight,
judgment, and dissociation
Activity/energy Activity ranges from inertia and withdrawal to mania. It also includes motivation/
interest and also repetitions
Function Impairments in work, school, care giving and other roles, and in ADLs (activities of
daily living)

Table 25.7 Proposed secondary psychiatric assessment Table 25.9 Proposed “dimensional” dimensions in psy-
dimensions chiatric assessment
Dimension Explanation Dimension Explanation
Environment/context Stressors, trauma, court case, Spectrum location E.g., autism
triggers, buffers Frequency Intermittent/infrequent
Relations (e.g., Significant others, social Often/constant
family, partner) network, leisure activities Duration In minutes (0), days (1), weeks (2),
Social skills In dyads, groups; competition, months (3), years (4)
cooperation; helping, hurting Temporal (In)stability
others Course
Coping Vulnerabilities or resilience Sequentially (interruptions,
and growth; emotion vs. organization)
problem-focused Intensity/severity Mild to serious
Self/personality Primary characteristics, traits,
self-esteem, assertiveness,
five-factor model/Psy-5 model

Table 25.10 Proposed complicating dimensions in psy-


Table 25.8 Proposed auxiliary psychiatric assessment chiatric assessment
dimensions
Dimension Explanation
Dimension Explanation Self-control Goals/planning, inhibition,
Age (stage, Chronologically; in relation flexibility
development) to developmental level, or Substance (Ab)use Use, dependence, abuse,
perhaps stage (e.g., Erikson, in withdrawal
or related models) Self-deception Unconscious, naïve,
Gender Sex, orientation, roles repression, unrealistic
Culture/minority Country, racism/persecution, Other-deception Conscious, lying/
group norms manipulation, malingering,
Socioeconomic status Poverty, opportunities criminal activity
Medical/physical/ Health, body, sleep, eating, Aberrant/inappropriate Not quantitatively different,
neurovegetative pain, self-injury, exercise, etc. but qualitatively different

As for diagnosis, if the assessment is compre- match for the assessment findings. If diagnosis
hensive in this way, or, another equivalent one, it stems from a comprehensive assessment, and the
will be much easier for the clinician to refer to the diagnostic categories available, the nosological
various diagnostic manuals (DSM-IV-TR, DSM- system used have some of the fuzzy properties
5, ICD-10, 11) and to find the best diagnostic mentioned, the clinician would be adopting a
646 25 DSM-5: Recommendations

Table 25.11 Rating scale for each psychiatric dimension Chapter Conclusions
Level Explanation
0 Absent For DSM-5 and Etiology
(1/2) Rarely a problem
1 Sometimes a problem The DSM-5 is the most recent iteration of the
(1 ½) Often a problem DSM enterprise, and it is both strongly defended
2 Always (or almost always) a problem and roundly criticized. It needs to be clinically
NA/TBA Insufficient evidence to judge useful yet scientifically-informed and validated,
Note. Where several types of problems exist for a dimen- so that the work groups involved in creating its
sion, rate the most important one(s)
different versions often strike compromises. The
Note. ½—points are optional, for research purposes
DSM-5 will change in the DSM versions to fol-
low, and the present chapter has made multiple
process that would circumvent possible criti- recommendations in this regard. Perhaps the
cisms of the diagnoses offered, especially if they most salient refers to the new model of etiology
are derived from a scientific reasoning process. that I have proposed. That is, I describe a new
One or the other of the major psychiatric diag- model for the causality (or etiology) of mental
nostic manuals might become obligatory in a cli- disorder in terms of the dynamic, reciprocally
nician’s jurisdiction, and used without qualms in interactive nature that it has with symptoms. In
this regard. However, the clinician should be suf- this regard, the model is a top-down/bottom-up
ficiently informed to justify any critique in the integrative one that considers a role in the etiol-
field of any manual. In this regard, the prudent ogy of mental disorders both of higher-order
clinician might decide to consider the alternate psychological constructs, such as PTSD, and of
assessment process offered in the present chapter, the symptoms (and clusters) that express the
with its comprehensive assessment approach, disorders.
because it would facilitate use of a scientific rea-
soning process in the diagnoses offered.
For Assessment

Ethics In the following, I turn to practical considerations


for forensic/disability assessment of psychologi-
Figure 25.10 brings an important perspective to cal injury cases. This sets the stage for conclu-
the present work. It underscores that a proper sions on how to deal with diagnoses in court.
ethical stance is needed in all aspects of our train- In assessing psychological injury, assessors
ing, education, and work. By constantly evaluat- ask: (a) to what extent the event at claim has con-
ing each aspect of our work from a meta-ethical tributed to the presenting condition of the com-
framework, and not just from the point of view of plainant; (b) what diagnoses and disabilities do
professional principle and codes, any dilemma the symptoms are represent, if any; (c) how can
related to using one psychiatric manual or the factors such as possible malingering be ruled out,
other will be obviated. The best judge of how to e.g., which tests to use; and (d) are there
use the DSM-5 and scrutinize it for its problems functional impacts that can be causally linked to
reside in each of the professionals using it. In this the event (e.g., in work, child care, studies).
regard, in this present work, I have provided a A combined biopsychosocial/forensic model
general guide to the DSM-5 that could be useful should inform/guide assessments, whether for
to the reader. However, the responsibility for how tort, disability claims, requesting treatment plans,
it is used lies directly in the laps of the reader. etc. A comprehensive, scientifically-informed,
Then, its disposition and critique should inform and impartial approach is needed in all work in
each professional using it, but in a dispassionate psychological injury cases. Assessments should
and critical way. use the most reliable, valid, and accurate tests,
Chapter Conclusions 647

Reflective Participation Consideration/


(Meta-Theories/ Consultation
Theories) (Principles, Codes)

Ethical Decision Making Ethical Issues


(Dynamic, Reflective) (Conflicts, Dilemmas)

Education, Training
(Teaching, Research,
(Continuing Education,
Related Functions)
Continuing Training)

Report,
Knowledge Testimony, Tort,
(Science, Ethics) Court

Mental Health Provider


(Dynamic, Reflective)
Positive Testing
Ethics and Tests

Scientific,
Assessment
Evidence-Supported
(Therapy)
Approach

Impartial Referral
Approach Source

Practice, Experience
Comprehensive
(Graduation,
Approach
Supervision)

Fig. 25.10 Broad ethics in psychological injury and law. Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business
The figure outlines a broad ethical model for practice in Media. Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feigning, and
psychological injury and law. It describes the typical steps response bias in psychiatric/psychological injury:
in education and practice, and emphasizes a scientific and Implications for Practice and court. Dordrecht,
ethical approach to the work that is impartial and compre- Netherlands: Springer Science + Business Media; with
hensive. This way, any ethical dilemma should be resolv- kind permission from Springer Science + Business Media
able by referring to ethical rules, principles, and theories. B. V. [Figure 22.4, Page 588]

aside from conducting interviews and accessing more recently, the MMPI-2-RF (The Minnesota
collateral information. Multiphasic Personality Inventory-2 Restructured
Workers in the area need to adopt a multitrait- Form; Ben-Porath & Tellegen, 2008/2011). When
multimethod testing approach having acceptable evidence for possible malingering is found, the
sensitivity and specificity (to deal with false posi- assessor needs to examine the array of multiple
tives and negatives). They need to use reliable and reliable data gathered on the individual (from test-
valid instruments for the question at hand, such as ing, interview, collateral sources) in order to rule
the MMPI-2 (The Minnesota Multiphasic out alternative explanations before arriving at a
Personality Inventory-2; Butcher et al., 2001) and, conclusion that malingering is a reasonable
648 25 DSM-5: Recommendations

possibility. However, there are ways of describing the product that resulted. However, its goals were
problematic presentations that do not have direct, fine and future iterations will be an improvement.
incontrovertible evidence of malingering. Perhaps the best statement for court is that the
DSM-5 will be followed not by the DSM-6 in
10–15 years, but, it appears, shortly by the 5.1, so
For Reports/Court that conclusions for any one case in using the
DSM-IV-TR or the DSM-5 should be seen in that
The DSM-5 presents quandaries for use in reports light.
and in court due to its numerous criticisms and If the case is civil, the evidential bar is “more
limitations. For court purposes, it is always best likely than not,” but, if the case is for criminal
to conduct comprehensive interviews and consul- court, the bar is the more stringent one of “beyond
tation of records to get a functional perspective of a reasonable doubt.” These different criteria
the person, and use the diagnoses as supplements, might impact the certainty statements evaluators
and this might be especially true after the contro- need to offer about their diagnoses using the
versy about the DSM-5. DSM-IV-TR or DSM-5.
Perhaps for court, workers should specify Aside from all the general issues about the
each disorder attributed in the evaluation both in DSM-5 (e.g., overpathologizing, ethics of work-
terms of the DSM-IV-TR and DSM-5 and should groups), the specific disorders, too, can be criti-
indicate which one is primary for the case at cized from a forensic perspective. About the
hand. When the criteria for a disorder have DSM-5 PTSD criteria relative to those of the
changed in the DSM-5 relative to the DSM- DSM-IV-TR, there are some changes to consider
IV-TR, knowledge of the scientific validity of the forensically. For example, the A2 criterion is
disorder(s) at issue in the literature would help removed, which will open the floodgates to more
justify the choice of using as primary the DSM- forensic cases. Not only are there three more
IV-TR or DSM-5. Similarly, in diagnosing new symptoms in the DSM-5 relative to the DSM-
disorders in the DSM-5 that were not in the IV-TR, they are arranged into four clusters of the
DSM-IV-TR, knowledge of the literature will symptoms, not three as before, so that all PTSD-
help determine their validity. Finally, some of the related psychometric tests will have to be redone,
disorders in the DSM-IV-TR can be contested on which will also complicate forensic cases.
a scientific basis even if they had not been From a forensic perspective, I checked in
changed in the DSM-5, so they, too, can also be detail the fourth PTSD DSM-5 symptom cluster.
questioned for their validity. It is on arousal/reactivity. There are now six
Of course, an evaluator might find that no symptoms in it, not five. The new one is reckless
diagnosis, impairment, or disorder fits a particu- or self-destructive behavior, which will compli-
lar case because of malingering or gross exag- cate things forensically. The irritability/anger
geration. The definition of malingering has not outburst criterion now includes the qualifier
changed in DSM-5, but it, too, has been shown to “with little or no provocation” and, also, it adds
be problematic. Use of a good battery of tests the words “verbal/physical aggression toward
could help with that imbroglio, but these, them- people,” which will complicate things forensi-
selves, are subject to controversy in some cally. There is a new specifier (dissociative symp-
quarters. toms, depersonalization/derealization), which
As the years progress, we might find that too will complicate things forensically. Other
insurers, worker’s compensation, veteran’s forensic complications include the criterion of a
administration, the court, state associations, or 6-month delay allowed before making the diag-
even the literature will make strong recommen- nosis. Because of these and other matters raised
dations on using the DSM-IV-TR or the DSM-5. in the present work, please consult my proposal
Unfortunately, the field is in flux about diagnosis presented elsewhere on a new diagnostic entry to
because of the process in making the DSM-5 and the DSM 5.1—DSM 5 Confusion Disorder.
References 649

Finally, for recent work on causal etiology, Diwadkar, V. A., Bustamante, A., Rai, H., & Uddin, M.
and testing models of psychopathology please (2014). Epigenetics, stress and their potential impact
on brain network function: A focus on the schizophre-
consult Vaidyanathan, Vrieze, and Iacono (2015) nia diatheses. Frontiers in Psychiatry, 5, 71.
and commentaries, e.g., Lilienfeld and Pinto doi:10.3389/fpsyt.2014.00071.
(2015), Regier (2015), Widiger, Crego, and Elhai, J. D., Biehn, T. L., Armour, C., Klopper, J. J., Frueh,
Oltmanns (2015). Essentially, the authors call for B. C., & Palmieri, P. A. (2011). Evidence of a unique
PTSD construct represented by PTSD’s D1-D3 symp-
better theory, better method, and better nosology toms. Journal of Anxiety Disorders, 25, 340–345.
as it applies to psychopathology, its development Fillman, S. G., Sinclair, D., Fung, S. J., Webster, M. J., &
in the DSM-5, and the RDoC, as well as public Shannon Weickert, C. (2014). Markers of inflamma-
policy. I strongly endorse all of these goals while tion and stress distinguish subsets of individuals with
schizophrenia and bipolar disorder. Translational
proposing in this chapter specific recommenda- Psychiatry, 4, e365. doi:10.1038/tp.2014.8.
tions aimed at them. Goldstein, B. L., & Klein, D. N. (2014). A review of
selected candidate endophenotypes for depression.
Clinical Psychology Review, 34, 417–427.
Goodkind, M., Eickhoff, S. B., Oathes, D. J., Jiang, Y.,
References Chang, A., Jones-Hagata, L. B., et al. (2015).
Identification of a common neurobiological substrate
American Psychiatric Association. (2013). Diagnostic for mental illness. The Journal of American Medial
and statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM-5 Association: Psychiatry, 72, 305–315.
(5th ed.). Washington, DC: Author. Gottesman, I. I., & Gould, T. D. (2003). The endopheno-
American Psychiatric Association. (2000). Diagnostic type concept in psychiatry: Etymology and strategic
and statistical manual of mental disorders (4th ed., intentions. American Journal of Psychiatry, 160,
text rev.). Washington, DC: Author. 636–645.
Arguello, P. A., & Gogos, J. A. (2012). Genetic and cogni- Gould, T. D., & Gottesman, I. I. (2006). Psychiatric endo-
tive windows into circuit mechanisms of psychiatric phenotypes and the development of valid animal mod-
disease. Trends in Neurosciences, 35, 3–13. els. Genes, Brain and Behavior, 5, 113–119.
Ben-Porath, Y. S., & Tellegen, A. (2008/2011). The Insel, T., Cuthbert, B., Garvey, M., Heinssen, R., Pine,
Minnesota Multiphasic Personality Inventory-2 D. S., Quinn, K., et al. (2010). Research domain crite-
Restructured Form (MMPI-2-RF): Manual for admin- ria (RDoC): Toward a new classification framework
istration, scoring, and interpretation. Minnesota, MN: for reach on mental disorders. The American Journal
University of Minnesota Press. of Psychiatry, 167, 748–751.
Borsboom, D. (2008). Psychometric perspectives on diag- Insel, T. R., & Lieberman, J. A. (2013). DSM-5 and
nostic systems. Journal of Clinical Psychology, 64, RDoC: Shared interests. The National Institute of
1089–1108. Mental Health. Retrieved from http://www.nimh.nih.
Borsboom, D., Cramer, A. O., Schmittmann, V. D., gov/news/science-news/2013/dsm-5-and-rdoc-shared--
Epskamp, S., & Waldorp, L. J. (2011). The small interests.shtml
world of psychopathology. PLoS One, 6, e27407. Karalunas, S. L., Geurts, H. M., Konrad, K., Bender, S., &
doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0027407. Nigg, J. T. (2014). Annual research review: Reaction
Butcher, J. N., Graham, J. R., Ben-Porath, Y. S., Tellegen, time variability in ADHD and autism spectrum disor-
A., Dahlstrom, W. G., & Kaemmer, B. (2001). MMPI- ders: Measurement and mechanisms of a proposed
2: Manual for administration, scoring, and interpreta- trans-diagnostic phenotype. Journal of Child
tion (Revth ed.). Minneapolis, MN: University of Psychology and Psychiatry, 55, 685–710.
Minnesota Press. Kendler, K. S. (2008). Explanatory models for psychiatric
Chan, R. C. K., & Gottesman, I. I. (2008). Neurological illness. American Journal of Psychiatry, 165, 695–702.
soft signs as candidate endophenotypes for schizophre- Kendler, K. S. (2012). The dappled nature of causes of
nia: A shooting star or a Northern star? Neuroscience psychiatric illness: Replacing the organic-functional/
& Biobehavioral Reviews, 32, 957–971. hardware-software dichotomy with empirically based
Coghill, D. (2014). Editorial: Acknowledging complexity pluralism. Molecular Psychiatry, 17, 377–388.
and heterogeneity in causality – Implications of recent Kendler, K. S. (2015). Toward a limited realism for psy-
insights into neuropsychology of childhood disorders chiatric nosology based on the coherence theory of
for clinical practice. Journal of Child Psychology and truth. Psychological Medicine, 45, 1115–1118.
Psychiatry, 55, 737–740. Kendler, K. S., Zachar, P., & Craver, C. (2011). What
Coghill, D., Seth, S., & Matthews, K. (2014). The neuro- kinds of things are psychiatric disorders? Psychological
psychological effects of chronic methylphenidate on Medicine, 41, 1143–1150.
drug-native boys with attention-deficit/hyperactivity Lilienfeld, S. O., & Pinto, M. D. (2015). Risky tests of
disorder. Biological Psychiatry, 62, 954–962. etiological models in psychopathology research: The
650 25 DSM-5: Recommendations

need for meta-methodology. Psychological Inquiry, ciplinary integration in moving psychopathology


26, 253–258. forward. Psychological Inquiry, 26, 209–230.
McEwen, B. S. (2006). Protective and damaging effects of van Os, J., Delespaul, P., Wigman, J., Myin-Germeys, I.,
stress mediators: Central role of the brain. Dialogues & Wichers, M. (2013). Psychiatry beyond labels:
in Clinical Neuroscience, 8, 367–381. Introducing contextual precision diagnosis across
McGorry, P., & van Os, J. (2013). Redeeming diagnosis in stages of psychopathology. Psychological Medicine,
psychiatry: Timing versus specificity. Lancet, 381, 43, 1563–1567.
343–345. Widiger, T. A., Crego, C., & Oltmanns, J. R. (2015). The
McNally, R. J., Robinaugh, D. J., Wu, G. W. Y., Wang, L., validation of a classification of psychopathology.
Deserno, M. K., & Borsboom, D. (2015). Mental dis- Psychological Inquiry, 26, 272–278.
orders as causal systems: A network approach to post- Wigman, J. T., Collip, D., Wichers, M., Delespaul, P.,
traumatic stress disorder. Clinical Psychological Derom, C., Thiery, E., et al. (2013). Altered transfer of
Science, 3, 836–849. momentary mental states (ATOMS) as the basic unit
Meaney, M. J. (2010). Epigenetics and the biological defi- of psychosis liability in interaction with environment
nition of gene x environment interactions. Child and emotions. PLoS One, 8, e54653. doi:10.1371/
Development, 81, 41–79. journal.pone.0054653.
Millan, M. J. (2013). An epigenetic framework for neuro- Wigman, J. T., van Os, J., Borsboom, D., Wardenaar,
developmental disorders: From pathogenesis to poten- K. J., Epskamp, S., Klippel, A., et al. (2015). Exploring
tial therapy. Neuropharmacology, 68, 2–82. the underlying structure of mental disorders: Cross-
Miller, G. A., & Rockstroh, B. (2013). Endophenotypes in diagnostic differences and similarities from a network
psychopathology research: Where do we stand? perspective using both a top-down and a bottom-up
Annual Review of Clinical Psychology, 9, 177–213. approach. Psychological Medicine, 45, 2375–2387.
Pietrzak, R. H., Feder, A., Schechter, C. B., Singh, R., Wigman, J. T., van Os, J., Thiery, E., Derom, C., Collip,
Cancelmo, L., Bromet, E. J., et al. (2014). Dimensional D., Jacobs, N., et al. (2013). Psychiatric diagnosis
structure and course of post-traumatic stress symp- revisited: Towards a system of staging and profiling
tomatology in World Trade Center responders. combining nomothetic and idiographic parameters of
Psychological Medicine, 44, 2085–2098. momentary mental states. PLoS One, 8, e59559.
Poldrack, R. A., Kittur, A., Kalar, D., Miller, E., Seppa, doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0059559.
C., Gil, Y., et al. (2011). The cognitive atlas: Towards Wilker, S., & Kolassa, I.-T. (2013). The formation of a
a knowledge foundation for cognitive neuroscience. neural fear network in posttraumatic stress disorder:
Frontiers in Neuroinformatics, 5, 17. doi:10.3389/ Insights from molecular genetics. Clinical
fninf.2011.00017. Psychological Science, 1, 452–469.
Regier, D. A. (2015). Potential DSM-5 and RDoC syn- World Health Organization. (2007). International
ergy for mental health research, treatment, and health Statistical Classification of Diseases and Related
policy advances. Psychological Inquiry, 26, 268–271. Health Problems 10th Revision. Retrieved from http://
Schmittmann, V. D., Cramer, A. O. J., Waldorp, L. J., www.who.int/classifications/icd/en/
Epskamp, S., Kievit, R. A., & Borsboom, D. (2013). World Health Organization. (2017). International
Deconstructing the construct: A network perspective Classification of Disease, 11th Revision.
on psychological phenomena. New Ideas in Psychology, Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-Piagetian
31, 43–53. perspectives. New York: Springer Science + Business
Sherin, J. E., & Nemeroff, C. B. (2011). Post-traumatic Media.
stress disorder: The neurobiological impact of psycho- Young, G. (2013). Breaking bad: DSM-5 description,
logical trauma. Dialogues in Clinical Neuroscience, criticism, and recommendations. Psychological Injury
13, 263–278. and Law, 6, 345–348.
Sporns, O. (2012). Discovering the human connectome. Young, G. (2015). Causality in psychiatry: On nosology,
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. etiology, and networks. Frontiers in Psychiatry, 6.
Szyf, M. (2013). How do environments talk to genes? Young, G., Lareau, C., & Pierre, B. (2014). One quintillion
Nature Neuroscience, 16, 2–4. ways to have PTSD comorbidity: Recommendations
Vaidyanathan, U., Vrieze, S. I., & Iacono, W. G. (2015). for the disordered DSM-5. Psychological Injury and
The power of theory, research design, and transdis- Law, 7, 61–74.
Part V
Personal Contributions to the Study
of Causality in Behavior: New Models
Causality in Psychological Injury
and Law: Basics and Critics 26

chronic pain and its limiting effects). Note that


Chapter Introduction the latter biopsychosocial factors might involve
pre-existing factors sufficiently severe enough to
The present chapter includes the description of excuse the negligent action at issue or perhaps
the criminal forensic approach to causality and just a minor exacerbating factor in the outcome at
the excusing conditions of criminal culpability. hand. In such cases, the event at issue is not even
This enables a comparison with the civil, tort, material or contributory to the post-event psy-
and related disability approaches to causation. chological condition/disorder(s), and to their
Outside of the differential legal issues of criminal course and functional impacts.
responsibility and criminal negligence that are The chapter concludes with provision of new
involved, respectively, for criminal conduct and terms that might help disambiguate the legal
for negligence, such as in motor vehicle acci- terms used in causal analysis (cause in fact, prox-
dents (MVAs), I maintain that the biopsychoso- imate cause). In this regard, I propose use of the
cial model applies equally to both types of cases. superordinate, general term of proximate causa-
On the one hand, in the criminal context, one tion for both of these latter terms, as well as use
could ask to what extent the perpetrator’s behav- in their stead of the specific terms of legal causes
ior had been caused by any of the biopsychoso- in fact and liable cause, respectively. In addition,
cial factors that might have been involved, or the term of “biopsychosocial causation” could be
their interaction. Note that, in the criminal con- used in either the criminal or civil (e.g., tort) con-
text, the presence of these factors does not auto- text to help understand the behavior at issue
matically lead to exoneration for the crime at (respectively, criminal conduct versus survivor
issue. The insanity defense, for example, sets a psychological condition, after a tortious negli-
high bar or threshold for disculpability due to gent event, for example).
psychological factors. As for the negligence in
tort and related venues in court in disability cases
undertaken by forensic evaluators, one needs to Introduction
establish whether the survivor involved has a
compensable functional- (or role-) related dis- The law constitutes a bulwark in our society that
ability (with the presence of a disorder or condi- helps keep us civil and safe. It is constructed dif-
tion constituting a secondary factor). Further, in ferently in different countries and, in our case,
this regard, one needs to establish whether the reflects the highest ideals of human nature, trying
disability might be understood or explained psy- to balance individual rights with the common
chologically by biopsychosocial factors (e.g., good. Laws need to be equitable, fair, and just. At

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 653


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_26
654 26 Causality in Psychological Injury and Law: Basics and Critics

the same time, they are not made without consul- other words, does the tortious act factually and
tation with multiple stakeholders, including med- logically precede the harm incurred by the event
ical doctors, public policy experts, insurers, and in question? For the bar of direct causation, the
mental health professionals. reasonable person test is applied—normally,
Moreover, many cases that are brought to would another person in the same situation as the
court need experts to help resolve disputes, such defendant have reasonably predicted that the act
as in tort claims after personal injury. (or its lack) would have caused the harm at issue?
Psychologists, psychiatrists, and others in the Citing Daller (2000), McLearen et al. (2004)
mental health field need proper education and noted that “proximate” cause is not defined the
training for their roles in such cases, or else their same way in different jurisdictions. In this regard,
reports and testimony will not be deemed admis- legal standards vary by case law in indicating
sible, or worse, their qualifications will not be which harms that have been incurred involve a
considered to have met the accepted bar of com- legally protected right or interest that can be pur-
petence. For example, they need to understand sued for legal damages.
the legal terms that are involved, how to translate Young and Drogin (2014) further noted that
them into psychological practice, and so on. They Foote and Lareau (2013) maintained that in court,
need to use the best psychometric tests in their the plaintiff must establish that the defendant had
assessments and arrive at scientifically-informed, been derelict and breached a duty sufficiently to
impartial conclusions. They need to know how to cause a harm, which for psychiatric/psychologi-
deal with court and with testifying on the stand. cal harm, involves “negligent infliction of emo-
They need to know how to address ultimate tional distress,” or NIED. In emotional claims in
issues, such as relating to disability and its cau- court, the zone-of danger rule allows for emo-
sality. Cases in the field of psychological injury tional claims without a concomitant physical
often especially hinge on the latter evaluation. injury, and it has broadened such that bystanders
can claim damages just by witnessing a horrific
trauma to a family member, although there are
Causality and Causation Terms limits imposed on the rule (e.g., Thing v. La
in Law Chusa, 1989).
Causality represents a difficult issue to ana-
Law lyze among the four D’s even though it is perti-
nent to every tort and related forensic disability
According to Young and Drogin (2014), Young case. Piechowski (2014) noted that, in the foren-
and Kane (2007) pointed out that a tort is a pri- sic context, psychological damages are impair-
vate or civil wrong or injury, such as in a negli- ment- rather than diagnosis-related (e.g.,
gent or intentionally tortious act, for which a trier Greenberg, Otto, & Long, 2003). That is, func-
of fact evaluates whether it deserves an award of tional impacts are the focus of legal action rather
compensation or damages (McLearen, Pietz, & than anything like the diagnosis; disorder, per se.
Denney, 2004). The process of proving that tor- Psychological condition in terms of diagnosis or
tious conduct had taken place in court depends on disorder does not confer in and of themselves
meeting four criteria, which have been referred to impairment or disability without considering
as the “4 Ds”: duty; dereliction; direct causation; match with the environment, (for example, jobs/
and damages (also see Piechowski, 2014). their demands) and the functional impact that
If dereliction of duty by the negligent party, result if there is a sufficient mismatch in these
such as in a motor vehicle accident (MVA) is regards. Further, in a causal determination for the
established in the case at issue, then the causal tort or related case to have any weight, the impair-
question must be satisfied—is there direct causa- ments and functional impacts for the evaluee in
tion, that is, is the dereliction of duty, or its lack, question need to be demonstrated as causally
the “proximate cause” of the injury at issue; in related to the event at issue.
Causality and Causation Terms in Law 655

Causality and Causation The court noted that causation has been long con-
sidered a “hybrid concept” (Hart & Honoré,
Young and Drogin (2014) described that Young 1959). The court referred to the “but-for” test of
(2008) had noted that the definition of causality causality and that terms such as “results from,”
varies across disciplines and, as per Young and “because of,” “based on,” and “by reason of” are
Shore (2007), even within law, there is no con- consistent with the “but-for” test.
sensus on its definition and conceptualization. The less demanding standards of causality,
Moreover, the confusion about causality extends such as being a “substantial” or “contributing”
into other disciplines. For example, in philoso- factor, is more “permissive” and potentially
phy, Russell represents the philosophers who allows any act or omission, no matter how
deny that causality can be determined, so that the “small,” to serve as a contributing factor in cau-
concept of causality is confused and confusing sality determination in any case. The court could
(e.g., Lucy, 2007). not determine any means of differentiating “too
Young (2008) continued that, in law, the “but- insubstantial” and “substantial” causation in the
for” test cannot cover all contingencies, espe- criminal context.
cially dual or preemptive, duplicative, joint, However, for the US Supreme Court, in the
serial, or severing causality. Therefore, other cau- indexed case, in tort law “material” or “substan-
sality tests have been applied to cases such as tial” factors could constitute “a cause” of an
these (especially, the material contributions test: event at issue (Keeton, Dobbs, Keeton, & Owen,
as long as the event at issue has contributed more 1984); in the civil context it is acceptable to have
than a minor degree to the liability at issue, it is a more lax burden of proof that makes a material
considered responsible at least in part). Wright contribution to an event at issue sufficient to ren-
(2007) had argued that the NESS test of causality der it liable.
(necessary element of a sufficient set, “a particu- Young and Drogin (2014) concluded that in
lar condition is a cause of or contributes to a spe- the civil arena, generally, and the one of psycho-
cific consequence if and only if it is a necessary logical injury, particularly, the material or sub-
element of a set of antecedent actual conditions stantial contribution test of causality constitutes
that had been sufficient for the occurrence of the an adequate basis for apportioning causality in
consequence”) could help in this regard. However, the typical multifactorial causality case involved
Lucy (2007) maintained that the NESS test also in tortious and otherwise liable events at issue.
has limits, such as difficulty in differentiating pri- Overall, with respect to causality in the psycho-
mary cause in circumstances with multiple logical injury context, in the law involved, the
causes. but-for test is consonant with the material contri-
Garner (2009) wrote that for causation in the butions test, but events at claim are embedded in
legal context, the causative event needs to be the a broad multifactorial causal complex that
proximate, dominant, responsible, or essential includes: (a) pre-event psychological vulnerabili-
one, or at least contributory, substantive, or mate- ties if not psychopathologies; (b) complexities in
rial; it needs to be more than tangential or “de the event at claim, including the perceived, sub-
minimus.” Material cause is the term most often jective individualized element of participants; (c)
used and it refers either to the sole legal or legiti- extraneous factors, such as unanticipated job loss
mate cause of an event at claim or a factor that is or the death of a family member incidentally to
part of it (a contribution that is necessary and suf- the event at issue that could complicate psycho-
ficient). The “substantial” contributions test in logical course and outcome; and (d) post-event
causality is recognized in the American Law developments in terms of course and outcome,
Institute (ALI) tort statement (American Law (which might be normative, or consistent with the
Institute, 2000; Piechowski, 2014). average in clinical and non-litigating popula-
The issue of causation was discussed in the tions, or rather, exacerbated by the insurance pro-
SCOTUS case, 571 US (No. 12-7515) (2014). cess, litigation distress, iatrogenesis, and the
656 26 Causality in Psychological Injury and Law: Basics and Critics

adversarial divide, among other factors unique to probability at the basis of general causation
the area of psychological injury and law, as per research is insufficient to establish individual
below). causation. Concrete, particular evidence relevant
Song (2014) reviewed the tests of causation in to the case at hand also is necessary. Hogg (2011)
insurance contract law. The area is considered and Cranor (2011) supported Wright’s NESS
incoherent and uncertain, but the proximity model of causation (necessary element in a suf-
threshold of causation is considered the predomi- ficient set) and that it can apply to individual
nant test. The “but for” test that is predominant in cases; in this regard, it need not apply fully in
tort only has an occasional influence in insurance such cases. It has the advantage of being broader
law. Causation is “central” to both types of liabil- than the traditional “but-for” test and, also, it can
ities. Proximity does not refer to the most recent, help parse joint causation. However, Spector
immediate, or most remote, distant element of a (2011) found that the NESS model is lacking.
causal chain. Rather, the liable cause is the “fire- Bagshaw (2011) referred to “causal contribu-
starter,” the peril in the efficient chain that consti- tions,” “operative mechanisms,” and “the natural
tutes “profoundly” the effective starting point of process” in causality. He also referred to “causal
the loss at issue, unless there is (also) an interven- potency.”
ing, outstanding causal addition to the chain. Barth, Kertay, and Steinberg (2014) reviewed
Hodgson (2011) differentiated the concept of causation in mental illness. They noted that
an all-inclusive, deterministic “cone of causa- attributing a diagnosis does not carry with it any
tion” stretching back from the relevant anteced- implications for causal analysis. Overdiagnosis is
ent event in time to the law’s need to select producing “fake epidemics.” Diagnostic manuals
legally-relevant necessary conditions in causal- are not meant to serve forensic needs. They con-
ity. Intervening events could break the chain of ducted a literature review of 41 diagnoses, and
causation and emerge as primary legally. The could not find one having credible scientific sup-
complexity of such cases explains why in the law port for legal standards of causation for mental
of torts, more than for any other topic, causation illness. In general, there is no scientific justifica-
has “plagued” both scholars and the court tion for the legal level for any claim of causation
(Fleming, 1998). for any mental illness. There is also the issue of
Goldberg (2011a, 2011b, 2011c) had noted malingering in such claims.
that the central problem in tort law is that of
establishing causation. Hoffmann (2011) sug-
gested that instead of referring to proof of causa- New Terms
tion, law would best use the terminology of
“causal requirements.” Similarly, Bagshaw In Young (2010), I described that Golding and
(2011) noted that Stapleton (2009) referred to Edmundson (2005) had reviewed the epistemo-
causation as “involvement” (involving, one thing logical framework of law. In their view, the two
bringing about another). main perspectives on the construction of law are
Dawid (2011) considered that general causa- (a) the legal positivist-legal realistic one and (b)
tion based on population experiments differs the contrasting one of natural (moral) law. Young
from individual causation, and even the best (2008) argued that, at the epistemological level,
experimental evidence does not clearly apply to the law should establish an integrative, middle
particular cases at hand. Rather, at best, it has ground in its approach to causality and causation.
implications for the range of probability that That is, the epistemological approach of law to
might apply in individual causation. Goldberg causal factors should not be based solely on
(2011d) argued that an absence of findings on either the principled (natural, moral) or prag-
general causation should automatically exclude matic (positivism, realism) perspectives; rather,
consideration of possible individual causation. an integrative middle ground should be con-
Wright (2011) added that the statistical structed with respect to the said issue having both
Negligence and Law 657

together, through a synthetic integration. proximate cause. Specifically, the term of “causes
Specifically, on the one hand, a synthetic legal in fact,” which are also called legal causes, should
perspective on causality and causation should be be called legal causes in fact. Also, the term of
established on the basis of fundamental legal liable cause should replace the one of proximate
principles, for example, related to rights and jus- cause.
tice. Also, on the other hand, laws related to cau-
sality and causation should have leeway for
flexible and pragmatic adaptation to social and Negligence and Law
other issues.
In Young (2010), I queried the confusion Green (2014) noted that the concept of causation
inherent in legal terminology related to causality and its application in negligence cases, such as
and causation. Proximate cause refers to action- tort, is “complicated, convoluted, and confused.”
able causes in fact that reach thresholds of liabil- She developed a pragmatic, practical test of cau-
ity, or which reach sufficient degree in damages sation, referred to as the Necessary Breach
incurred as determined legally in the jurisdiction Analysis (NBA). It does not try to define causa-
at issue; such level of damages incurred permits tion nor give an abstract, academic, philosophi-
opening the case involved to legal (and financial) cal, pronouncement of what it means for a cause
action for appropriate compensation for the out- to exist. Rather, it is a forensic means for dealing
come at issue. Causes in fact set the stage for robustly with causation on a case-by-case basis.
considering an act of negligence as actionable for In the NBA, )the first stage establishes whether
compensation; causes in fact refer to causes or not a breach of duty changed the normal course
established in law as responsible for damages of events resulting in damage that would not have
incurred and, therefore, as potentially actionable, otherwise happened. In the second stage, the
irrespective of whether or not they meet the determination for each defendant involved is
required degree of liability thresholds. Garner whether her or his breach was “operative” when
(2004) stated that this type of cause is a “but-for” the damage occurred.
one, in that it refers to the cause without which The NBA )algorithm keeps the classic but-for
the event at issue would not have taken place. test as the best one for establishing causation due
Alternate terms for causes in fact include factual to negligence. It can account for overdetermined
causes. cause, i.e., two or more causes each sufficient by
Of concern, the term “proximate cause” in the itself to produce the damage. It obviates the need
legal field is not defined clearly enough accord- to consider pre-emption, i.e., causes that never
ing to the leading law dictionary (Garner, 2004). become operative (hypotheticals). The NBA ini-
It usually refers to the liability component of a tially aggregates all potential causal factors, but
“cause in fact,” but also can refer to a cause in then proceeds to rule in or out on a factual basis
fact, itself, or even to both! Moreover, Moore which ones are relevant to the case at hand.
(2009) had noted that the term is a misnomer. Green (2014) noted that the facts in the case
Therefore, in an effort to bring structure to the must be established with certainty. However, in
confusion evident in the critical terms in the field contrast, for meeting the legal test in these types
of civil law related to causal factors, Young of cases, it is established according to the stan-
(2010) argued that, the law should create a super- dard of balance of probabilities/preponderance of
ordinate term for causes in fact and proximate the evidence. The factual elements of the case
cause, such as use of the term of proximate cau- should not be determined according to this less
sation as a combined term; conceptually, this new demanding standard.
term indicates events that are together both caus- A breach might be material (relevant, or a part
ally contributory and potentially actionable and of the cause that surpasses the minimal range), in
liable legally. Young (2010) further suggested a larger multifactorial causal array. In this sense, it
new names for the terms of cause in fact and needs to be shown that the material contributor is
658 26 Causality in Psychological Injury and Law: Basics and Critics

at least either a part-cause or had caused a part of each considered an important source of influence
an injury. This criterion still demands the but-for and biases on psychological injury. Young (2014)
test for determination. Green (2014) concluded described that “litigation distress” refers to iatro-
that although the more-likely-than-not standard is genic or stressful factors in the insurance and
a probability estimate, legally, decisions involve a legal process; they add to patient stresses, thereby
certainty in an all-or-none fashion. complicating recovery. Young noted that the psy-
In short, Green (2014) has shown that, for chological injuries of complainants have been
court in negligence/tort type cases—facts have to referred to as a “compensation neurosis” (litiga-
be definitive; yet meeting the legal test at issue tion resolution cures the complaints at source).
needs to be only established at the level of more However, although this might be true at an indi-
than probable; also causes might be legally vidual level for a case at hand, there is insuffi-
acceptable as part causes; and despite all this, in cient evidence to support this claim at the general
legal decisions, any uncertainty or hedges lead- population level. For example, complainant psy-
ing to them do not detract from the ultimate chological injuries generally do not heal “magi-
necessity to state that what had taken place either cally” after having received their financial
happened absolutely or not, with all the attendant settlements (see Call, 2003).
consequences to the decision involved being That being said, the iatrogenic effects in psy-
determined thusly. No wonder court is confusing chological injury cases might be quite palpable,
to the uninitiated in mental health practice. and in different ways depending on the extent of
injuries and the extent of feigning involved, if
any. In this regard, the evaluee might be quite
Psychological Injury and Law influenced by the litigation process and by iatro-
genic factors. I should point out that this state of
According to Young and Drogin (2014), psycho- affairs could work toward favoring the defense
logical injury and law is an emerging field in as well as the plaintiff. On the plaintiff side,
mental health law and assessment. It deals with complainants original psychological injuries
tort, worker compensation, disability insurance, might be valid, with no or very little exaggera-
and related cases that involve psychological tion, and the injuries worsen due to undue insur-
impairment and disability, for issues such as ance and defense pressures, for instance, in
posttraumatic stress disorder (PTSD), mild trau- repeated denials of the validity of their claims
matic brain injury (TBI), and chronic pain. The and of their needed treatments and repeated
major areas in the field of psychological injury stressful and confrontational assessments. In
and law, as presented in the masthead of the jour- contrast, on the insurer and defense side, com-
nal Psychological Injury and Law (springer. plainants might have minor injuries, exaggerate
com), involve: law, forensics, assessment, malin- or even malinger, and get stresses only because
gering and symptom validity tests (SVTs, also the repeated treatment denials and assessments
referred to as PVTs, performance validity tests), implicate that they will not get any monetary
disability and return to work, practice affairs, compensation. For example, evaluees might be
PTSD, (chronic) pain, TBI, rehabilitation, dis- stressed by insurance examinations and defense
crimination and harassment, ethics, and general medicolegal examinations because they are anx-
interest and controversies. Malingering is an ious about their malingering, fabrication, and
essential axis for all these topics, as are fabricat- deception being exposed.
ing/feigning, and even exaggerating, in general, Young (2008) examined systemic issues in
including for purposes of monetary gain, or causality assessment. He pointed to the types of
response biases and threats to validity, in stresses associated with the insurance process.
general. With respect to the patient side of the equation in
Tables 26.1 and 26.2 present the major terms the insurance process, Young (2014) especially
and concepts used in the present chapter, with dealt with the issue of malingering. For example,
Psychological Injury and Law 659

Table 26.1 Major terms in psychological injury and law


Term Explanation
Compensation neurosis A complainant is “cured” of psychological symptoms once litigation ends
Conversion disorder Unconsciously motivated feigning of sensory/motor deficits
Cry for help Symptom exaggeration/engaging in dramatization behavior in order for complaints to be
heard “by the evaluator”
Exaggeration Conscious or unconscious; the evaluee presents her/his genuine symptoms or impairments
caused by an injury as much worse than their actual case
Factitious disorder Internally motivated and intentional symptom production is high; the intentional production of
symptoms for purposes of adopting the sick role rather than for receiving external incentives
Feigning Deliberate fabrication/gross exaggeration of psychological/physical symptoms (Rogers, 2008)
Gray zone A possible/probable, indeterminate, ambiguous presentation/performance
Malingering The intentional feigning of physical/psychological symptoms that is motivated by external
incentives or to acquire external outcomes (e.g., financial gain, avoiding to return to work;
American Psychiatric Association, 2013)
Somatization disorder The promotion of somatic symptoms/impairment by one’s significant distress via
nonconscious processes
Adapted from Young (2014)

Table 26.2 Factors contributing to difficulties in evaluations: litigation/iatrogenic


Type Examples
Adversarial divide Plaintiff-defense
Any legal adversarial process
Iatrogenic (stress/psychological reaction at any point) Multiple assessments (treatment providers)
Multiple treatments
Multiple assessments (plaintiff)
Multiple assessments (defense)
Insurance process (stress/psychological reaction at any point) Claims initiated
Multiple letters/forms
Claims denied (e.g., for treatments/supports)
Third party attitude
Litigation distress (stress/psychological reaction at any point) Potential litigation events
Engaging attorneys
Litigation steps begin
Courts (or related venues)
Adapted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young (2014); with kind permission from Springer
Science + Business Media B. V. [Table 14.10, p. 373]

early after the onset of the pain at issue, a patient ments coincide with the decision to sue for dam-
might not score in the range on respondent valid- ages due to the original injuries, even if they had
ity scales that indicates feigning to any degree, been healing, and with resultant consultation of a
but might reach that level months or years later. plaintiff attorney.
The interpretation of these results could indicate Another issue in this regard could involve the
the pain patient being assessed is demonstrating complainant obtaining different test results at a
increasing pain and desperation, but another pos- similar point in time by assessors working for
sible interpretation is that the said evaluee has plaintiff and defense. For example, if the test
attained notable elevations on subsequent respon- results show greater pain experience exaggera-
dent validity scales, after a lack of elevations in tion with the defense attorney assessor relative to
these regards previously, because the later assess- the plaintiff one, a possible interpretation might
660 26 Causality in Psychological Injury and Law: Basics and Critics

be that the patient appraises that the defense sense, the adversarial divide refers to the plaintiff
examination is confrontational (and, indeed, it and defense opposition in tort and related cases
might be), leading to the greater exaggeration in and, in the broader sense, also it refers to the
this context, either in order to reflect a desire to related agents and institutions that function
be heard or out of exasperation at the confronta- within it, such as insurers and professional evalu-
tion. That is, it could be that litigation distress is ators, including mental health ones, who might
an issue to consider in differing simultaneous be aligned with one side or the other. Therefore,
outcomes associated with plaintiff vs. defense the divide captures within its net evaluators,
assessments due to the adversarial pressure on including mental health ones, given the specific
the assessors stemming form the divide and the types of biases that might influence them, such as
influence of this factor on evaluees. confirmatory bias (defined as evaluators giving
To be fair, opposite simultaneous defense and more weight to information consistent with their
plaintiff results might obtain because the plaintiff belief relative to other opinions; Kane & Dvoskin,
assessors put the evaluee at ease knowing that 2011).
they will be leaning toward them in their conclu- The multiple factors involved in psychological
sions, and the evaluees are aware of this to begin, injury cases render them complex, controversial,
at any rate. Therefore, in these regards, it is the and “gray zone,” rather than clearly black or
insurer and defense assessors who handle best white. Young (2014) referred to the difficulty in
the required neutral stance in the assessment. assessing complainants manifesting problematic
That is, there is anti-litigation distress in the presentations and performances, or ones residing
plaintiff examinations compared to regular and in the so-called gray zone. Many of them will
not unseemly stress in the insurer–defense ones, present and perform in an ambiguous, mixed, or
which makes the insurer–defense ones seem the uncertain way, being indeterminate in their pre-
more stressful ones on comparison! sentation and performance. Gray-zone refers not
Moreover, the adversarial divide could act only to complainant status in presentation and
directly on other parties in the system. For exam- performance but also to the difficulty in interpre-
ple, in attorney coaching, legal representatives tation of their presentation and performance.
either advise complainants how to present and Young (2014) added that, in cases that fit the gray
perform in evaluations, or they provide material zone, the conclusion on evaluee credibility might
to the complainants to learn how to do this (the be in dispute in the two sides involved in evaluat-
material might even be posted on a firm’s web- ing the examinee, and that the uncertainty either
site!). On the other side of the coin, rather than way leads to the types of disagreements that are
complainants, defense attorneys might “train” or prevalent in the adversarial divide in the field.
entrain third parties, e.g., claims adjusters/adjudi- Young (2014) continued that an adequate
cators, in how to handle cases to their advantage; model of evaluee validity in presentation and per-
also, senior third party executives might train or formance in evaluations should accommodate the
entrain not only these administrators how to han- ambiguities presented by many evaluees, that is,
dle cases in this way to their advantage but also when their evidence is not clear-cut either way.
independent medical examination (IME) evalua- For example, in the gray zone, evaluees might
tors in these regards. exaggerate moderately, or inconsistencies/dis-
In general, Young (2014) noted that the sys- crepancies might be found in the file that are
tem in which a person with psychological inju- moderate, yet the evaluee could still judged to be
ries functions might be filled with bias. Typically, expressing credible symptoms. In this regard,
this refers to evaluee bias, such as negative there might be a cry for help at work. Further,
response bias in testing, including to the point of even gross exaggerations could reflect a cry for
malingering, but also it could refer to the adver- help (e.g., in the case of desperate patients being
sarial divide in which workers in the system other consistently and unjustly denied treatments);
than complainants must navigate. In the narrow however, any assessment that leads to this type of
Medical Injury and Law 661

conclusion should be well-justified. In another another. A direct causal association refers to the
example, as noted above, at the other extreme, necessary and sufficient requirement for the cause
even a mild or minimal exaggeration could be at issue. An indirect one indicates other contribut-
totally consciously fabricated for financial gain. ing factors need to be present. Proximate cause
In all these cases, evaluees appear to fit the gray refers to causes in fact having legal liability.
zone, and explanations why they fall one way or Often, it is established by counterfactual or “but-
the other on the credibility continuum should be for” arguments. They noted that different jurisdic-
offered. Young (2014) concluded that the best tions have particular standards of legal liability.
way to minimize the uncertainty in cases of psy- Hegmann, Thiese, Oostema, and Melhorn
chological injury about examinee credibility is to (2014) noted that population-level research on
proceed from a scientific perspective—that is, (a) causation could help address whether an “expo-
know well the scientific literature, assuming that sure” contributes significantly to the develop-
it has been undertaken in a way that is applicable ment, aggravation, or maintenance of a condition.
to the case at hand; (b) use scientifically-informed The 1965 Hill criteria provide a useful frame-
methods and procedures; and (c) use scientific work in this regard. The most important ones are
reasoning in arriving at interpretations and temporality, strength of association, dose–
conclusions. response relationship, and consistency.
Brooks and Melhorn (2014) addressed appor-
tionment in causation. Medical causation is typi-
Medical Injury and Law cally multifactorial, and there is no simple way to
isolate the degree of contribution of the legally
Melhorn, Talmage, Ackerman, and Hyman relevant factors. Indeed, the task might be impos-
(2014) presented the medical view of causation sible in some situations.
in disease and injury, including at the psychiatric Fries, Melhorn, Hyman, and Talmage (2014)
level. The book, on occupational medicine, is focused on the medical examination in terms of
meant to accompany the AMA Guides to the establishing causality. Much of the chapter pres-
evaluation of permanent impairment (American ents medical ways of detecting symptom magni-
Medical Association Guides, Sixth Edition; fication or disease fabrication.
Rondinelli et al., 2008), which has important Talmage, Freeman, Melhorn, and Hyman
legal implications, given the latter’s widespread (2014) described how to present conclusions in
use in disability and related determinations. reports, including on causality. For example, it
Melhorn, Talmage, et al. (2014) indicated that must be proved that the negligence at issue actu-
the definition of causation is “elusive” in some ally caused the injury at issue. Discussion of the
situations. Yet, it is crucial in establishing liabil- proximate cause should include not only consid-
ity in medical cases. Moreover, scientific and eration of the but-for argument but also have a
legal approaches often “are in conflict.” Causation reasonableness component (the injury should
in occupational medicine must consider all inter- have been reasonably anticipated or foreseen as a
active and biopsychosocial factors, including normal outcome of the negligence at issue).
those that are pre-existing. Other factors to con- Talmage, Melhorn, Ackerman, and Barth
sider in this regard involve, on the one hand, (2014) argued that, generally, musculoskeletal
fraud (including by the insurer, employer, and disorders are conditions of uncertain pathophysi-
physician) and, on the other hand, malingering by ology. They are influenced by psychological and
the claimant. social (e.g., work) factors. For example, pessi-
Melhorn, Ackerman, Glass, Deitz, and mism about the return to work could be involved.
Babitsky (2014) explained that there is a chasm in Moreover, complainants might not be fully forth-
medical and legal concepts of causation. In law, coming of past pain complaints or of psychosocial
“cause in fact” is the event that “brings about” confounders.
662 26 Causality in Psychological Injury and Law: Basics and Critics

DePaolo and Rassp (2014) elaborated the legal Table 26.3 Definition of key terms related to causality
approach to causation. They noted that, whether Term Definition
from the plaintiff or defense side, attorneys focus Causal test In tort and related law, the “but-for” test
on the “facts.” Legal causation involves responsi- is primary—causation is evident when
the outcome at issue would not have
bility for the negligence. Liability can be divided
transpired absent or without the
according to apportionment of cause, if applica- occurrence of the event at claim or
ble. There might be intervening causes, but proxi- action of the responsible party. Other
mate causation can take them into account by tests have been proposed, but the
material or substantial contribution test
establishing the chain of causation.
allows for attribution of liable causation
Moore (2014) contributed that, legally, causa- without the event at issue necessarily
tion is established on the basis of factual evidence, being primary.
so that it is case-by-case and not absolute. Causality Relation between cause and effect;
Causation determination is neither art nor science, process more than product. Used
interchangeably with the term causation.
but fact-based, so that it must rely on evidence
Causation Production of effect(s) by cause(s);
that is relevant to the case at hand (the evidence product more than process.
must not be immaterial). The evidence must be General Refers to causation in the general
substantial, probative (helpful), reasonable, cred- causation population—at the statistical or normative
ible, and so on, and it must meet the court’s stan- level is the issue at hand or at claim (e.g.,
dard of proof (e.g., more likely than not). toxic exposure, MVA) an inducing factor
in individuals of the outcome that ensued
Deitz (2014) added that basis for claims needs (e.g., illness, injury).
to be “clear.” Sometimes percentages are used to Specific In cases in which general causation
define clarity (Overpeck, Krohn, Rabine, & causation applies, does the event at issue lead to
Lovan, 2014). liable results (illness, injury) to the point
that damages can be pursued?
Overall, the medical approach to causation in
the civil context is consistent with the psychologi- Note. The terms in this table were defined based on Garner
(2004), Mish (2003), and Young and Shore (2007).
cal one. There are legal thresholds and concepts to Adopted with permission of Elsevier. Reprinted from
consider but, generally, the causation must be International Journal of Law and Psychiatry, Vol. 32,
material even if it is part of a multifactorial or bio- Young, G., Causes in the construction of causal law: A
psychosocial nexus. Population-level research is psycho-ecological model, Pages 73–83, Copyright 2010;
with kind permission from Elsevier. [Table 1, Page 75]
important to consider, as well as is case law.
Malingering is always a concern. Assessment
needs to be fact-based and comprehensive. definitional distinction between causation and
In the following, I move from the civil to the causality is ambiguous (Young & Shore, 2007),
criminal context in terms of the topic of causality and the terms are used interchangeably. In the
in psychological assessment. I find some basic criminal context, on the one hand, causality refers
similarities in the two areas, despite evident to establishing the alleged perpetrator’s responsi-
differences. bility for the criminal act at issue in terms of the
person’s mental state (mens rea) and, on the other
hand, if the person is found to have committed the
Psychological Causality act, whether the insanity defense absolves guilt.
in Criminal Cases To remind, for comparison purposes, in the
forensic disability and related context, causality
Introduction refers to whether the index event is a material or
contributing cause in the multifactorial array that
Young (2015) noted that causality (or causation) is had led to the psychological condition at issue.
central to every legal case, yet its underlying philo- There is no question of guilt to consider in civil
sophical, legal, and psychological definitions and cases; simply, does the victim (survivor) express a
conceptions vary (see Tables 26.3 and 26.4). The compensable psychological condition? There is
Psychological Causality in Criminal Cases 663

Table 26.4 Key terms related to causation and causality firing the weapon at issue in conjunction and there is
Term = Meaning (simplified) also another potentially lethal action by someone
Key terms related to causality and causation in law: else). That is, for the example given, in cases of
Concurrent = Joint; Contributing = Secondary; apparently simultaneous criminal lethal action,
Immediate a = Most recent; Intervening = Added; which one of the two involved is the “but-for”
Joint = Multiple; Material = Part of joint;
Proximate = Dominant (direct); Remote b = Initial,
responsible one? (b) On the other hand, for the dis-
too far removed; Superseding = Replacing dominant ability context, it concerns whether the claimed psy-
Key terms related to causality and causation in chological condition would be present only because
medicine: of the negligent incident at issue. Normally, the latter
Component = Part of multiple; negligent event at issue is distinguished from the
Exacerbating = Worsening; Exciting = Direct;
criminal one by its negligence compared to the vol-
Immediate a = Beginning, initial;
Predisposing = Susceptible; Primary = Principle; untary intent behind it in the criminal case, yet both
Remote b = Predisposing, secondary; Secondary = Not involve the same counterfactual argument in estab-
principle; Ultimate = Remote lishing causality.
Key terms related to causality and causation in
psychology:
Catalytic = Facilitative; Latent = Delayed;
Maintaining = Current; Mediating = Intervening;
Biopsychosocial Model
Multiple = Multifactorial; Original = Remote, initial;
Remote = Initial; Triggering = Immediatea In the literature, in general, the nature of causa-
Key terms related to causality and causation in tion in forensic psychiatry and psychology is
philosophy: viewed as deriving from a “multiplicity of
First = Remoteb; Immediatea = Last; Principle = Primary causes” (Silva, 2009), and the causal factors can
Adapted from Young (2008) be referred to as a “biopsychosociocultural”
Note. The footnoted terms indicate the confusions in their
use in law, psychiatry/psychology, and philosophy. The nexus (Bernston, 2006). For example, dysfunction
difficulty in translating legal terms to the mental health or insult to the brain might lead to influence on or
field, and vice versa is compounded when the terms have more directly affect behavior, but this biological
different meanings in the various disciplines involved. For factor must be seen in context of the whole inter-
example, the footnoted term “immediate” (a) might mean
either most recent or last part of a causal chain, which connected causes that are involved.
surely seeds immediate confusion to the unwary. A remote Steinert and Whittington (2013) adopted a sim-
component of a causal chain might be involved, neverthe- ilar approach to understanding the origins of vio-
less, as a predisposing factor. In translating between law lence. In their “bio-psycho-social” approach,
and mental health, another term that is confusing concerns
“reliability,” which means “validity” in law as understood individual dispositions relate to an interrelation of:
in psychology (it refers to replicability in psychology, (a) biological factors, such as prefrontal brain
which is of less relevance than validity). In short, address- structure functioning and genetics; (b) psychologi-
ing the reliability of a causal argument could evoke differ- cal and neuropsychological ones, such as mental
ent associations in attorneys, judges, psychiatrists, and
psychologists illness and impulsivity; and (c) social factors, such
as poverty and peer group influence. According to
Steinert and Whittington, the situation that triggers
no evaluation of the perpetrator (i.e., the negligent the violence at issue is complex, as well, and can
party); simply, once more, only the survivor’s include experienced or imagined provocation or
condition is at issue. Nevertheless, there are com- threat. Moreover, the violent act is committed in
monalities across the two contexts to consider. relation to the facilitating and inhibiting factors
In both the criminal and tort or disability con- that might be at play, which include substance
texts, the legal test is a counterfactual one. (a) On the misuse and fear of punishment, respectively.
one hand, for the criminal context, the counterfac- As much as is the situation in the civil context,
tual, but-for argument refers to whether the outcome such as tort or related disability cases, the psy-
involved (e.g., death) would have resulted absent the chological state of the perpetrator of criminal
act (e.g., who is responsible when the case involves conduct can be analyzed from a biopsychosocial
664 26 Causality in Psychological Injury and Law: Basics and Critics

perspective. In this vein, in the civil case, such as volition, or both at the time of the offense at
in tort, forensic disability, and related assess- issue. According to the authors, “mens rea” refers
ments, the evaluator needs to consider pre- to the intent, purpose, or knowledge component
existing, precipitating, and perpetuating causal of the mental state of the perpetrator at the time
factors, with personal and social resilience and of the conduct involved in the prohibited act
protective factors considered, as well. In the (“actus reus”).
criminal context, the same biopsychosocial Goldstein et al. (2013) continued that even
model with all these variables applies, but with when the perpetrator of a crime meets the required
the evaluation of mental competence and volun- standard of proof of guilt of “beyond a reason-
tariness added as a critical factor. In this regard, able doubt,” an “affirmative” defense could be
evaluators need to be wary of simplistic models; launched. That is, the defense attorneys could
for example, the growth in neurolaw has led to have the defendant exonerated on the basis of
use of neuroscience in court, but it risks reducing either a valid justification or an excuse. The latter
the complexity of criminal cases to unifactorial, includes satisfying the criteria for “legal insan-
biological models. ity;” in this defense, if the perpetrator is “irratio-
nal” to the degree needed, then he/she will be
judged not guilty and considered a “nonrespon-
Mens Rea sible agent.”
Goldstein et al. (2013) added that the criminal
In the following, I analyze in depth the approach conduct at issue has to be a “voluntary” act
to causality in the criminal context. Zapf, according to legal definition. That is, the act in
Golding, Roesch, and Pirelli (2014) underscored question had to be intentional and undertaken
the tension in law between strict, objective liabil- during a state in which the defendant had been of
ity and subjective liability as it applies to estab- reasonably integrated consciousness. Otherwise,
lishing criminal responsibility and to working as obtains in significant dissociation, the behav-
from a sense of “fairness” or “justice” in court. ior at issue is judged as being the product of an
Briefly, criminal guilt in committing a proscribed “automatism.”
behavior (actus reus) requires meeting an appro- Goldstein et al. (2013) further noted that a
priate threshold in both degree of and type of legal insanity claim typically involves a “defect”
mental capacity and intentionality (mens rea) of cognition, but also it could involve maintain-
before the guilt can be related to “culpable own- ing a defect of “control capacity”; that is, the per-
ership” of the act. Zapf et al. (2014) noted that, son at the time of the improper act had a lack of
outside of any debate about its scientific validity, ability to control his/her conduct. However, the
the issue of mens rea (for an actus reus) is inte- latter volitional “prong” in an excusing defense
gral to the fabric of criminal law. has been criticized as not being independent of
Causality in the criminal forensic context cen- the cognitive one. Nevertheless, the control inca-
ters on the concept of responsibility. In criminal pacity argument as an excusing condition in a
cases, such as lethal actions, Goldstein, Morse, defense against criminal charges is still proffered
and Packer (2013) emphasized that causal to court.
responsibility and moral responsibility need to be Goldstein et al. (2013) tackled the issue of
distinguished. For example, the victim might be whether having “free will” should be part of the
aggressed by a perpetrator who cannot be con- elements to consider in a crime and whether its
ceived as a morally responsible agent even if the absence can be used as an excusing condition.
actions involved had caused the outcome at issue. According to them, arguments related to free will
Culpability in the legal sense of the word depends are irrelevant to the question of criminal guilt. The
on evaluating the actor’s mental state at the time concept of free will is a distracting confusion in
of the criminal act at issue. Mental state assess- law; it is more the province of philosophy than
ments need to evaluate and to retrospectively law, and the issue of free will itself cannot decide
reconstruct the alleged perpetrator’s cognition, its legitimacy. Even though, philosophically, we
Psychological Causality in Criminal Cases 665

live in a deterministic world (although I add that Wallace (2014) argued that the basis for legal
there are compatibilist arguments in philosophy), responsibility is not physical but mental and
legally, in that world, offenders still can express behavioral. The person has to conduct him- or
valid mens rea and they are morally responsible herself reasonably; it is not the brain behaving,
for their crimes. Similarly, even if all phenomena nor can the brain explain away any lack in this
in the world are fully caused, deterministic con- regard. The law’s approach to causality is based
cepts of causality such as this cannot be used as an on the person as agent, not on the brain nor any
excuse to deny moral culpability for a crime. mechanism. Conscious states (including inten-
Moreover, the presence of mental abnormality tions, knowledge, comprehension, rationality,
cannot be considered, pro forma, the cause of a and control of compulsion) cause behavior. The
crime, nor a reason why one was compelled to brain does not include circuits or pathways of
commit it; therefore, its presence cannot be used responsibility (e.g., Morse, 2006).
to exonerate criminal guilt (except in cases in Sadoff and Dattilio (2011) described that the
which its presence created a threshold lack of insanity defense has roots in texts written back
either comprehension of the nature of the act thousands of years. Perlin (1989) had noted that
involved or sufficient self-control in relation to it). its modern roots extend back 700 years. The clas-
Continuing with the question of free will in sic case in which the matter was raised in a con-
behavior, Winters, Globokar, and Roberson temporary way is R. V. McNaughten. Sadoff and
(2014) introduced models of crime and causation Dattilio (2011) clarified that the McNaughten test
of criminal behavior. They contrasted the does not concern whether the criminal defendant
approaches of classicalism and positivism. The had known the difference between right and
core assumption of the former view is that human wrong. Rather, the legal test involved is whether
behavior is shaped by the rational use of free will. the alleged perpetrator had known what she or he
For the latter view, in contrast, behavior is shaped, had been doing in the middle of doing the crimi-
deterministically, by biological, psychological, nal act at issue and whether she or he had known
and social forces. Although implicit in their for- that the particular act at issue had been wrong.
mulation, the authors did not explicitly refer to a Therefore, the McNaughten test of criminal act
biopsychosocial view. and mens rea is specific both in time and to event.
Biological approaches include genetics, neu- Frederick (2012) described that different juris-
rophysiology, biochemical, and evolutionary dictions vary widely in the laws concerning
approaches. For example, the six genes to date insanity. Nevertheless, there are also commonali-
that have been associated with violence, aggres- ties over jurisdictions in how insanity is legally
sion, or conduct disorder include: Dopamine defined. For example, jurisdictions agree that the
transporter gene 1 (DAT1), Dopamine D2 recep- mental impairment at issue in legal insanity argu-
tor gene (DRD2), Dopamine D4 receptor gene ments needs to be serious in nature in order to
(DRD4), Serotonin transporter gene (5-HTTLPR), constitute a sufficient basis for arriving at a judg-
catechol-O-methyltransferase gene (COMT), and ment of legal insanity. In this regard, factors such
Monoamine oxidase A gene (MAOA). as personality disorder and repetitive criminal
Appelbaum and Scurich (2014) reviewed the activity do not qualify for a valid defense of legal
literature on genetic influence on criminal activ- insanity. Instead, the most common disorders/
ity. Genetic factors appear to account for 40–50 % conditions associated with the insanity defense
of the variance in its transmission. Heritabilities involve attributions of psychosis, brain disorder,
have been found up to 57 % for aggressive behav- mental retardation, bipolar disorder, and disso-
ior and 67 % for antisocial behavior (Tuvblad, ciative disorder. Each of these disorders/condi-
Narusyte, Grann, Sarnecki, & Lichtenstein, tions could very well lead to disruptions in
2011). The genes involved include MAOA (Caspi thought and in self-awareness that impact nega-
et al., 2002), COMT, DAT1, DRD2, DRD4, and tively the perpetrator’s capacity to appreciate the
5-HTTLPR (Ferguson & Beaver, 2009). nature of the criminal actions that had been
666 26 Causality in Psychological Injury and Law: Basics and Critics

undertaken at the time of their commission. In American state that requires multiple, independent
this regard, mental health assessors need to eval- evaluations of the issue (Hawaii). The researchers
uate defendants carefully about their capacities had an N of 165 criminal cases that included 483
for “knowing” and “appreciating” not in general forensic evaluation reports for verification of inter-
but at the time of the alleged act. evaluator agreement. The results showed that full
Similarly, Melton, Petrila, Poythress, and agreement on insanity or its absence, which typi-
Slobogin (2007) related that the mental “disease cally involved three evaluators, was found in
or defect” at issue involved in an insanity defense 55.1 % of the cases (on the presence of sanity,
for a criminal act must “cause” either the crimi- 38.2 %; on insanity, 17.0 %). As for disagreements
nal act itself or the excusing condition for it. If related to sanity, a majority of them were about the
the mental abnormality in question in the case at presence or absence of insanity, per se (30 %),
hand cannot be shown to have affected the perpe- with the remainder of the disagreements about
trator’s alleged actions, then, at the legal level, it whether the sanity opinion can be given (14.5 %).
will be considered “irrelevant.” The researchers reported that both psychotic disor-
Melton et al. (2007) continued, and referred to der and psychiatric hospitalization shortly before
the “but-for” causality test. In this regard—it the offense at hand led to greater agreement about
must be shown that without the presence of the insanity among the conclusions of evaluators.
mental disorder at issue, the alleged criminal act
would not have been committed. However, the
but-for test is not easily satisfied. For example, Neurolaw
the mental disorder in question might have led to
unconscious factors or it might have involved In the following, I return to the question of the
biological (e.g., genetic) ones, but criminal causes of criminal conduct in terms of voluntari-
responsibility is not absolved merely by its pres- ness, but add to it the discussion of biopsychoso-
ence. Antecedent factors such as these must reach cial causation. Silva (2009) formulated an
legal thresholds, or else they remain, simply, rel- argument countering the biological point of view
evant to understanding causation, in general, but as being the sole causative factor in criminal con-
not criminal responsibility, in particular. duct. He argued that the law is concerned with
As for the legal threshold at issue, Melton the responsibility (voluntariness) of the criminal
et al. (2007) informed that establishing criminal act at issue, and it presumes that voluntariness is
responsibility depends especially on establishing always present unless proven otherwise to the
rationality in the reasons for the act in question. required standard of proof. Neuroscience is not
In the purview of the law, responsibility for one’s able to find an association involving criminal
actions always exists, and also criminal responsi- responsibility and neuronal or brain factors
bility will not be exonerated, unless the irratio- because human responsibility lies in considering
nality required for an insanity determination in humans in toto and not in their brains considered
the case at hand can be clearly established for the in isolation (Gazzaniga & Steven, 2004). As
timeframe of the harm incurred at issue. Silva (2009) noted, people are held responsible
Finally, the concepts involved in establishing for their actions, and it is not legally defensible to
criminal responsibility need to be fixed in law, hold that their brains alone are responsible for
but it appears that they are continually being their actions (Morse, 2006).
challenged and changing. Moreover, forensic Schleim (2012) supported a similar position
evaluators do not necessarily agree on the insan- on the inappropriate focus on the brain in the
ity defense, which contributes to the uncertainty context of recent pushes in neurolaw. He main-
in the area. tained that there is neither a “seat of morality”
In this regard, Gowensmith, Murrie, and nor of appropriate behavior within the brain. The
Boccaccini (2013) investigated the reliability of associations found in the literature across the
forensic evaluations of legal insanity in an brain and behaviors are not consistent and,
Psychological Causality in Criminal Cases 667

moreover, they cannot explain, diagnose, or pre- measured in a brain scanner, cannot be shown
dict behavior. Brain factors, and even more to constitute a “necessary, sufficient, or predis-
remote putative causes of behavior, do not pro- posing” causal factor for the behavior involved
vide biomarkers of psychiatric disorder or legally in a particular study, let alone in the real world
relevant psychiatric conditions. The danger of the of a particular case at hand to which its labora-
data with respect to neurolaw for a case at hand is tory results might be generalized, for example,
that they are misused in court. to a particular criminal act at issue.
Moriarty, Langleben, and Provenzale (2013) Morse (2011b) added that in court the ques-
adopted a similar position on the limited value of tion is not whether behavior is caused (because
brain scan data in forensic criminal cases. all behavior is caused) but whether the legal cri-
Testimony that such data can be used as evidence teria of criminal conduct have been satisfied. No
of brain trauma for a case at hand does not suffi- matter what are the cause(s) of a behavior at issue
ciently analyze the “reliability and validity” of (and even if they are known to reside in biologi-
the scan data, and also it can be “potentially cal, psychological, or social factors, or in their
misleading.” combination, or even if the cause(s) of a behavior
Meltzer et al. (2013) noted that Consensus are unknown), the legal test of responsibility for
medical “statements” support the limited rele- an alleged criminal act does not include causality
vance of neuroimaging data in court. Also, factors underlying the behavior; exoneration of
Meltzer et al. (2013) addressed the difficulty of moral culpability for criminal conduct takes
inferring human behavior or motivation from place only in light of an excusing condition.
neuroimaging data. The state of the brain scan- Morse (2011b) continued that “causal knowl-
ning field does not yet allow the specification of edge” could be “sufficiently precise” to contrib-
causal relationships in brain findings and mental ute to the determination of “whether or the
states related to criminal responsibility or its likelihood” that the legal threshold involved for
excusing. Meltzer et al. (2013) called for “more the criminal offense in question had been “satis-
searching judicial analysis” of brain scan evi- fied,” although an excusing condition still might
dence in court. be involved even if its cause is unknown. Finally,
Morse (2011a) couched his call for a need for causal knowledge might help explain why a per-
caution on bringing neurolaw to court in catchy petrator’s rationality might have been fully or
phrases yet cogent analysis. He called for the partly impaired at the time of a criminal act; how-
abandonment of “neuroexuberance,” while ask- ever, the excusing condition lies not in the causa-
ing for a better use of appropriate “translation” of tion of the impairment of the rationality at issue
neuroscience to law with the goal of attaining but in the impairment of the rationality itself at
“neuromodesty” and of avoiding “brain over- the time of the event. For these and other reasons,
claim syndrome.” Morse qualified the law’s the data that neuroimaging of the brain can pro-
approach to criminal responsibility and compe- vide to court are modest, at best, and, generally,
tence in trials for a criminal act as “behavioral,” the causation implied does not bear on the central
unlike the case for neuroscientific understanding question of responsibility or its exoneration.
of behavior, which is “mechanistic.” Although That being said, many authors give some lee-
“brain causation” might be part of the causation way in the use of neuroimaging data in court, for
for a behavior, understanding causation in any instance, in the mitigation of sentencing. For
way, including in terms of brain causation, does example, Casartelli and Chiamulera (2013) con-
not help mitigate or excuse a criminal act at issue sidered that it is “necessary” although not suffi-
(believing that it does constitutes the “fundamen- cient to use neuroscientific data in forensic
tal psychological error”). psychiatric evaluations. Also, Meynen (2013)
Brain causation by itself does not mean that reasoned that neuroscientific data can inform of
we are non-agentic, compelled automatons in the nature of the decision-making process of
behavior. Moreover, brain activity, such as accused perpetrators of prohibited criminal acts
668 26 Causality in Psychological Injury and Law: Basics and Critics

in question during psychiatric assessments of who do the deciding of their behavior after
their criminal responsibility. Further, Penney weighing the outcomes of possible decisions in
(2012) opined that, in some cases, neuroscientific this regard. The brain might “afford” this agency
data might be useful in establishing the validity but does not cause it alone.
of the attempted excusing argument of total inca- Human agency needs to be considered from a
pacity to have impulse control associated with multi-faceted, pluralistic perspective. In this vein,
the act in question. Martin (2012) adopted a model that is quite bio-
The insanity defense is accompanied by vari- psychosocial and one that is quite consistent with
ous nuances. For example, Claydon (2012) noted my own view on the causality of behavior. He
that there are cultural and jurisdictional differ- referred to the developmental emergence of self-
ences in neuroscientific defenses related to men- determination (agency) within an evolutionary,
tal condition, as well as racial ones. [With respect biophysical/sociocultural context. For Martin
to the latter, consult the research by Korn, (2012), people can be simultaneously “deter-
Johnson, and Chun (2012) and Perry, Neltner, mined” and self-determinate as complex causal
and Allen (2013)]. Moreover, there is a range of agents. [Note. I had referred to my equivalent
other issues, from folk psychology consider- biopsychosocial model as one that is develop-
ations (conceptions of the average person) to mental, evolutionary, and “biopersonalsocial.”]
philosophical/jurisprudence issues (conceptions
of legal scholars), such as the deterrent value of
being conservative about insanity defenses New Term
(Aggarwal & Ford, 2013). Together, these further
considerations indicate that the issues of criminal Beyond the issue of causality in the sense of
responsibility, the insanity defense, and the cau- responsibility, voluntariness, and cognitive con-
sation that might underlie them are as much cul- trol in the criminal act at issue, or their lack as in
tural and social constructions as legal and the excusing insanity defense, and beyond the
psychiatric/psychological ones. Nevertheless, the issue that free will and determinism are irrelevant
evidentiary standards required of good science to the question, the field of forensic criminal psy-
(Kaufmann, 2013) call for a “cautious” approach chology and psychiatry also is addressing the
to this area of forensics (Morse, 2011a). causation of the criminal act in order to obtain
To summarize this section of the chapter on possible mitigation of sentencing, in particular.
neurolaw, Satel and Lilienfeld (2013) have writ- That being said, although criminal responsibility
ten an accessible book, entitled “Brainwashed,” can be exonerated for reasons such as reaching
that dispels some of the incorrect logic in the use the bar of legally-defined insanity, in many cases,
of the new neuroscientific procedures in court. In the causation that presumably underlies psychiat-
the end, the authors maintained that the brain ric/psychological states at the time of an alleged
does not make people behave; rather, people criminal act cannot be scientifically established
themselves do that. Therefore, in this regard, the with sufficient precision in order to address the
brain is not the responsible agent for people’s matter unequivocally. Moreover, there is usually
(potential) control of their behavior. Granted, the more than one cause involved in the causation of
brain constitutes an important substrate underly- a criminal act, in the sense that it is best con-
ing behavior, but it does not stand as the unique ceived from the biopsychosocial framework,
determinant of behavior. To think otherwise con- even if individually and collectively the factors
stitutes “neurocentrism.” For Satel and Lilienfeld involved do not qualify for the insanity defense.
(2013), there is no “neurosignature” of guilt, Considering that, in any endeavor to under-
even though the scientific level might reduce peo- stand human behavior, the biopsychosocial
ple to their brain function. Satel and Lilienfeld approach provides a plausible model, a more
(2013) concluded that people are agentic selves general term on causality that integrates this
Chapter Conclusions 669

term could prove useful. As it exists, the term Chapter Conclusions


biopsychosocial helps integrate the various
physical/psychological, personal (coping, per- This sojourn in this chapter into the causality of
sonality, etc.), and sociocultural (family, neigh- psychological injuries in relation to law has not
borhood. society) factors applicable to been a secondary exercise because, in general,
understanding the origins of behavior in a legal the concepts in this field for causality are con-
case at hand. In this sense, as has been argued sistent with and informative for the discipline
above, the model applies to both the criminal and of psychology and of related ones. Psychological
tort contexts. Further, it helps us understand the injuries involve biological, personal, and social
limits of neurolaw in court. Neurosciences afford factors. They involve pre-existing, precipitat-
only one avenue in understanding causation of ing, and propagating factors. Their discernment
behavior and it clearly risks excluding psychoso- relies on “but-for” argumentation, or the coun-
cial factors that complement biological ones in terfactual. In the end, it seeks the necessary and
this regard. sufficient, material cause to the injury in the
In this sense, for understanding behavior in event at claim, as well as other factors that
either the criminal or civil (e.g., tort) context, might be involved. These types of consider-
the medical, mental health, and legal fields ations in causality determination in legal cases
might want to investigate the value of referring are complementary to those in other areas of
to “biopsychosocial causality” in order to spec- mental health practice. However, the legal bars
ify its multifactorial components and interac- set, such as for reaching thresholds of action-
tions and to address the common issues that able negligence and tort, or catastrophic impair-
these fields have about causality of behavior ment, are not typically encountered in other
(e.g., in criminal conduct by a perpetrator and in areas of mental health practice or of psychol-
survivor psychological condition after a negli- ogy, in general.
gent act, respectively). Unifying causality Moreover, this area of causality study involves
understanding in criminal and civil contexts types of influences not typically encountered in
might help unify forensic psychology, too, the field, such as iatrogenesis, or how the system
which often shows disjoint between the criminal can harm complainants, and also the biased
and civil (e.g., tort) sides. nature of the system in which complainants find
To conclude, I propose a concept that might themselves. The chapter also deals with differ-
help disambiguate the legal terms used in causal ences between causality in psychological injury
analysis. The term “biopsychosocial” causation cases and in criminal cases. It does find some
might be used profitably to address causality both commonalities in this regard, such as the impor-
in the criminal and civil (e.g., tort) context (e.g., tance of factors that speak to the biopsychosocial
criminal conduct and survivor psychological model. Nevertheless, in the criminal context, the
condition after a tortious event, respectively). accused needs to meet the bar of having know-
The term would give sufficient leeway for under- ingly committed a wrong, and so is responsible
standing the multifactorial nature of behavioral for his or her transgressions (and this without the
causality in the legal context, and unify the presence of mitigating factors). Overall, this
approach to causality of behavior in the law with chapter and the next one indicate that the area of
related disciplines in mental health. the psychological injury and law has much to
In the following, I propose other terms that contribute to the study of causality, in general.
might help legally in understanding causation. Causality is central to most every case in law, and
This time, my suggestions concern legal lan- what we learn about it in the area of psychologi-
guage itself. First, I review causality and causa- cal injury and law should be central to its under-
tion in civil law. standing in psychology, in general.
670 26 Causality in Psychological Injury and Law: Basics and Critics

References Ackerman III, & M. H. Hyman (Eds.), AMA guides to


the evaluation of disease and injury causation (2nd
ed., pp. 657–666). Chicago, IL: American Medical
Aggarwal, N. K., & Ford, E. (2013). The neuroethics and
Association.
neurolaw of brain injury. Behavioral Sciences and the
DePaolo, D. J., & Rassp, R. G. (2014). Causation: The
Law, 31, 789–802.
attorney’s perspective. In J. M. Melhorn, J. B. Talmage,
American Law Institute. (2000). A concise restatement of
W. E. Ackerman III, & M. H. Hyman (Eds.), AMA
torts. St. Paul, MN: Author.
guides to the evaluation of disease and injury causa-
American Psychiatric Association. (2013). Diagnostic and
tion (2nd ed., pp. 615–626). Chicago, IL: American
statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM-V (5th
Medical Association.
ed.). Washington: American Psychiatric Association.
Ferguson, C. J., & Beaver, K. M. (2009). Natural born
Appelbaum, P. S., & Scurich, N. (2014). Impact of behav-
killers: The genetic origins of extreme violence.
ioral genetic evidence on the adjudication of criminal
Aggression and Violent Behavior, 14, 286–294.
behavior. The Journal of the American Academy of
Fleming, J. G. (1998). The law of torts (9th ed.). Sydney,
Psychiatry and the Law, 42, 91–100.
Australia: Thomson Professional Publishing.
Bagshaw, R. (2011). Causing the behaviour of others and
Foote, W. E., & Lareau, C. R. (2013). Psychological eval-
other causal mixtures. In R. Goldberg (Ed.), Perspectives
uation of emotional damages in tort cases. In R. K.
on causation (pp. 361–381). Oxford, UK: Hart.
Otto & I. B. Weiner (Eds.), Handbook of psychology:
Barth, R. J., Kertay, L., & Steinberg, J. S. (2014). Mental Vol. 11. Forensic psychology (2nd ed., pp. 172–200).
illness. In J. M. Melhorn, J. B. Talmage, W. E. Ackerman Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.
III, & M. H. Hyman (Eds.), AMA guides to the evalua- Frederick, R. I. (2012). Insanity defense, diminished
tion of disease and injury causation (2nd ed., pp. 485– capacity, mitigation. In D. Faust (Ed.), Coping with
523). Chicago, IL: American Medical Association. psychiatric and psychological testimony (6th ed.,
Bernston, G. (2006). Reasoning about brains. In pp. 535–541). New York: Oxford University Press.
J. Cacioppo, P. Visser, & C. Pickett (Eds.), Social neu- Fries, I. B., Melhorn, J. M., Hyman, M. H., & Talmage,
roscience: People thinking about thinking people J. B. (2014). The causality examination. In J. M.
(pp. 1–11). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Melhorn, J. B. Talmage, W. E. Ackerman III, & M. H.
Brooks, C. N., & Melhorn, J. M. (2014). Apportionment. Hyman (Eds.), AMA guides to the evaluation of dis-
In J. M. Melhorn, J. B. Talmage, W. E. Ackerman III, ease and injury causation (2nd ed., pp. 149–173).
& M. H. Hyman (Eds.), AMA guides to the evaluation Chicago, IL: American Medical Association.
of disease and injury causation (2nd ed., pp. 139– Garner, B. A. (Ed.). (2004). Black’s law dictionary (8th
148). Chicago, IL: American Medical Association. ed.). St. Paul, MN: West.
Call, J. A. (2003). Liability for psychological injury: Garner, B. A. (Ed.). (2009). Black’s law dictionary (9th
History of the concept. In I. Z. Schultz & D. O. Brady ed.). St. Paul, MN: West.
(Eds.), Psychological injuries at trial (pp. 40–64). Gazzaniga, M. S., & Steven, M. S. (2004). Free will in
Chicago, IL: American Bar Association. twenty-first century: A discussion of neuroscience and
Casartelli, L., & Chiamulera, C. (2013). Which future for the law. In B. Garland & M. S. Frankel (Eds.),
neuroscience in forensic psychiatry: Theoretical hur- Neuroscience and the law: Brain, mind, and the scales
dles and empirical chances. Frontiers in Psychiatry, 4, of justice (pp. 51–70). New York: Dana Press.
74. doi:10.3389/fpsyt.2013.00074. Goldberg, R. (2011a). Perspectives on causation. Oxford,
Caspi, A., McClay, J., Moffitt, T. E., Mill, J., Martin, J., UK: Hart.
Craig, I. W., et al. (2002). Role of genotype in the Goldberg, R. (2011b). Preface. In R. Goldberg (Ed.),
cycle of violence in maltreated children. Science, 297, Perspectives on causation. Oxford, UK: Hart.
851–854. Goldberg, R. (2011c). Introduction. In R. Goldberg (Ed.),
Claydon, L. (2012). Are there lessons to be learned from a Perspectives on causation (pp. xix–xxx). Oxford, UK:
more scientific approach to mental condition defences? Hart.
International Journal of Law and Psychiatry, 35, 88–98. Goldberg, R. (2011d). Using scientific evidence to resolve
Cranor, C. F. (2011). The challenge of developing science causation problems in product liability: UK, US and
for the law of torts. In R. Goldberg (Ed.), Perspectives French experiences. In R. Goldberg (Ed.), Perspectives
on causation (pp. 261–281). Oxford, UK: Hart. on causation (pp. 149–178). Oxford, UK: Hart.
Daller, M. F. (2000). Tort law desk reference: A fifty state Golding, M., & Edmundson, W. (Eds.). (2005). The
compendium. New York: Aspen Law and Business. Blackwell guide to the philosophy of law and legal
Dawid, A. P. (2011). The role of scientific and statistical theory. Oxford, UK: Blackwell.
evidence in assessing causality. In R. Goldberg (Ed.), Goldstein, A. L., Morse, S. J., & Packer, I. K. (2013).
Perspectives on causation (pp. 133–147). Oxford, UK: Evaluation in criminal responsibility. In R. K. Otto &
Hart. I. B. Weiner (Eds.), Handbook of psychology. Vol. 11:
Deitz, D. C. (2014). Causation: The insurer’s (payer’s) Forensic psychology (2nd ed., pp. 440–472). Hoboken,
perspective. In J. M. Melhorn, J. B. Talmage, W. E. NJ: Wiley.
References 671

Gowensmith, W. N., Murrie, D. C., & Boccaccini, M. T. evaluation of disease and injury causation (2nd ed.,
(2013). How reliable are forensic evaluations of legal pp. 15–104). Chicago, IL: American Medical Association.
sanity? Law and Human Behavior, 37, 98–106. Melhorn, J. M., Talmage, J. B., Ackerman, W. E., III, &
Green, S. (2014). Causation in negligence. Oxford, UK: Hyman, M. H. (2014). AMA guides to the evaluation
Hart. of disease and injury causation (2nd ed.). Chicago, IL:
Greenberg, S. A., Otto, R. K., & Long, A. C. (2003). The American Medical Association.
utility of psychological testing in assessing emotional Melton, G. D., Petrila, J., Poythress, N. G., & Slobogin, C.
damages in personal injury litigation. Assessment, 10, (2007). A closer look at the insanity defense. In G. D.
411–419. Melton, J. Petrila, N. G. Poythress, & C. Slobogin
Hart, H. L. A., & Honoré, T. (1959). Causation in the law (Eds.), Psychological evaluations for the courts: A
(2nd ed.). Oxford, UK: Clarendon. handbook for mental health professionals and lawyers
Hegmann, K. T., Thiese, M. S., Oostema, S. J., & Melhorn, (3rd ed., pp. 209–217). New York: Guilford Press.
J. M. (2014). Causal associations and determination of Meltzer, C., Sze, G., Rommelfanger, K., Kinlaw, K.,
work-relatedness. In J. M. Melhorn, J. B. Talmage, Banja, J., & Wolpe, P. (2013). Guidelines for the ethi-
W. E. Ackerman III, & M. H. Hyman (Eds.), AMA cal use of NeuroImages in medical testimony: Report
guides to the evaluation of disease and injury causa- of a multi-disciplinary consensus conference.
tion (2nd ed., pp. 105–114). Chicago, IL: American American Journal of Neuroradiology, 35, 632–637.
Medical Association. Meynen, G. (2013). A neurolaw perspective on psychiat-
Hodgson, D. (2011). Intervening causation law: Common ric assessments of criminal responsibility: Decision-
law, civil law and comparative law perspectives. making, mental disorder, and the brain. International
Saarbrücken, Germany: Lambert Academic. Journal of Law & Psychiatry, 36, 93–99.
Hoffmann, R. T. H. L. (2011). Causation. In R. Goldberg Mish, F. C. (Ed.). (2003). Merriam-Webster’s collegiate dic-
(Ed.), Perspectives on causation (pp. 3–10). Oxford, tionary (11th ed.). Springfield, MA: Merriam-Webster.
UK: Hart. Moore, B. E. (2014). Causation: A judge’s perspective.
Hogg, M. (2011). Developing causal doctrine. In In J. M. Melhorn, J. B. Talmage, W. E. Ackerman III,
R. Goldberg (Ed.), Perspectives on causation & M. H. Hyman (Eds.), AMA guides to the evalua-
(pp. 41–56). Oxford, UK: Hart. tion of disease and injury causation (2nd ed.,
Kane, A. W., & Dvoskin, J. A. (2011). Evaluation for per- pp. 627–644). Chicago, IL: American Medical
sonal injury claims. New York: Oxford University Press. Association.
Kaufmann, P. M. (2013). Neuropsychologist experts and Moore, M. S. (2009). Causation and responsibility: An
neurolaw: Cases, controversies, and admissibility chal- essay in law, morals, and metaphysics. New York:
lenges. Behavioral Sciences and the Law, 31, 739–755. Oxford University Press.
Keeton, W., Dobbs, D., Keeton, R., & Owen, D. (1984). Moriarty, J. C., Langleben, D. D., & Provenzale, J. M.
Causation in fact. In W. L. Prosser & P. Keeton (Eds.), (2013). Brain trauma, PET scans and forensic com-
Prosser and Keeton on torts (5th ed., pp. 263–271). St. plexity. Behavioral Sciences & the Law, 31, 702–720.
Paul, MN: West. Morse, S. J. (2006). Brain overclaim syndrome and crimi-
Korn, H. A., Johnson, M. A., & Chun, M. M. (2012). nal responsibility: A diagnostic note. Ohio State
Neurolaw: Differential brain activity for Black and Journal of Criminal Law, 3, 397–412.
White faces predicts damage awards in hypothetical Morse, S. J. (2011a). The status of neurolaw: A plea for
employment discrimination cases. Social current modesty and future cautious optimism. Journal
Neuroscience, 7, 398–409. of Psychiatry & Law, 39, 595–626.
Lucy, W. (2007). Philosophy of private law. Oxford, UK: Morse, S. J. (2011b). Gene-environment interactions,
Oxford University Press. criminal responsibility, and sentencing. In K. A.
Martin, J. (2012). Agent causation and compatibilism Dodge & M. Rutter (Eds.), Gene-environment interac-
reconsidered: The evolutionary and developmental tions in developmental psychopathology (pp. 207–
emergence of self-determining persons. Journal of 234). New York: Guilford Press.
Consciousness Studies, 19, 161–175. Overpeck, D. L., Krohn, M., Rabine, M., & Lovan, D. T.
McLearen, A. M., Pietz, C. A., & Denney, R. L. (2004). (2014). Causation: The workers’ compensation com-
Evaluation of psychological damages. In mission perspective. In J. M. Melhorn, J. B. Talmage,
W. O’Donohue & E. R. Levensky (Eds.), Handbook of W. E. Ackerman III, & M. H. Hyman (Eds.), AMA
forensic psychology: Resource for mental health and guides to the evaluation of disease and injury causa-
legal processionals (pp. 267–299). San Diego, CA: tion (2nd ed., pp. 665–671). Chicago, IL: American
Elsevier Academic Press. Medical Association.
Melhorn, J. M., Ackerman, W. E., III, Glass, L. S., Deitz, Penney, S. (2012). Impulse control and criminal responsi-
D. C., & Babitsky, S. (2014). Understanding work- bility: Lessons from neuroscience. International
relatedness. In J. M. Melhorn, J. B. Talmage, W. E. Journal of Law and Psychiatry, 35, 99–103.
Ackerman III, & M. H. Hyman (Eds.), AMA guides to the
672 26 Causality in Psychological Injury and Law: Basics and Critics
Perlin, J. (1989). A forest journey: The role of wood in the Ackerman III, & M. H. Hyman (Eds.), AMA guides to
development of civilization. Cambridge, MA: Harvard the evaluation of disease and injury causation (2nd
University Press. ed., pp. 389–410). Chicago, IL: American Medical
Perry, B. L., Neltner, M., & Allen, T. (2013). A paradox Association.
of bias: Racial differences in forensic psychiatric Thing v. La Chusa, 771 P.2d 814 (Cal. 1989).
diagnosis and determinations of criminal responsibil- Tuvblad, C., Narusyte, J., Grann, M., Sarnecki, J., &
ity. Race and Social Problems, 5, 239–249. Lichtenstein, P. (2011). The genetic and environmental
Piechowski, L. D. (2014). Conducting personal injury etiology of antisocial behavior from childhood to
evaluations. In I. B. Weiner & R. K. Otto (Eds.), The emerging adulthood. Behavior Genetics, 41, 629–640.
handbook of forensic psychology (4th ed., pp. 171– Wallace, D. L. (2014). Addiction postulates and legal cau-
196). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley. sation, or who’s in charge, person or brain? The
Rogers, R. (2008). An introduction to response styles. In Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and
R. Rogers (Ed.), Clinical assessment of malingering the Law, 41, 92–97.
and deception (3rd ed., pp. 3–13). New York: Guilford Winters, R. C., Globokar, J. L., & Roberson, C. (2014). An
Press. introduction to crime and crime causation. Boca
R. V. McNaughten, 8 Eng. Rep. 718 (1843). Raton, FL: CRC Press, Taylor & Francis Group.
Rondinelli, R. D., Genovese, E., Katz, R. T., Mayer, T. G., Wright, R. W. (2007). Acts and omissions as positive and
Müller, K. L., Ranavaya, M. L., et al. (2008). Guides negative causes. In J. W. Neyers, E. Chambers, & S. J.
to the evaluation of permanent impairment (6th ed.). Pitel (Eds.), Emerging issues in tort law (pp. 287–
Chicago, IL: American Medical Association. 307). Oxford/Portland, OR: Hart.
Sadoff, R. L., & Dattilio, F. M. (2011). Criminal responsi- Wright, R. W. (2011). The NESS account of natural cau-
bility. In E. Y. Drogin, F. M. Dattilio, R. L. Sadoff, & sation: A response to criticisms. In R. Goldberg (Ed.),
T. G. Gutheil (Eds.), Handbook of forensic assess- Perspectives on causation (pp. 195–220). Oxford, UK:
ment: Psychological and psychiatric perspectives Hart.
(pp. 121–144). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley. Young, G. (2008). Causality and causation in law, medi-
Satel, S., & Lilienfeld, S. O. (2013). Brainwashed: The cine, psychiatry, and psychology: Progression or regres-
seductive appeal of mindless neuroscience. New York: sion? Psychological Injury and Law, 1, 161–181.
Basic Books. Young, G. (2010). Causes in the construction of causal
Schleim, S. (2012). Brains in context in the neurolaw law: A psycho-ecological model. International
debate: The examples of free will and “dangerous” Journal of Law and Psychiatry, 32, 73–83.
brains. International Journal of Law and Psychiatry, Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feigning, and response
35, 104–111. bias in psychiatric/psychological injury: Implications
Silva, J. A. (2009). Forensic psychiatry, neuroscience, and for practice and court. Dordrecht, Netherlands:
the law. Journal of American Academy Psychiatry and Springer Science + Business Media.
the Law, 37, 489–502. Young, G. (2015). Causality in criminal forensic and in
Song, M. (2014). Causation in insurance contract law. civil disability cases: Legal and psychological com-
New York: Routledge. parison. International Journal of Law and Psychiatry,
Spector, H. (2011). The MMTS analysis of causation. In 42–43, 114–120.
R. Goldberg (Ed.), Perspectives on causation Young, G., & Drogin, E. (2014). Psychological injury and
(pp. 339–359). Oxford, UK: Hart. law I: Causality, malingering, and PTSD. Mental
Stapleton, J. (2009). Causation in the law. In H. Beebee, Health Law & Policy Journal, 3, 373–417.
C. Hitchcock, & P. Menzies (Eds.), The Oxford hand- Young, G., & Kane, A. W. (2007). Causality in psychol-
book of causation (pp. 744–769). New York: Oxford ogy and law. In G. Young, A. W. Kane, & K. Nicholson
University Press. (Eds.), Causality of psychological injury: Presenting
Steinert, T., & Whittington, R. (2013). A bio-psycho- evidence in court (pp. 13–47). New York: Springer
social model of violence related to mental health prob- Science + Business Media.
lems. International Journal of Law and Psychiatry, Young, G., & Shore, R. (2007). Dictionary of terms
36, 168–175. related to causality, causation, law, and psychology. In
Talmage, J. B., Freeman, G. C., Melhorn, J. M., & Hyman, G. Young, A. W. Kane, & K. Nicholson (Eds.),
M. H. (2014). Report writing. In J. M. Melhorn, J. B. Causality of psychological injury: Presenting evi-
Talmage, W. E. Ackerman III, & M. H. Hyman (Eds.), dence in court (pp. 87–135). New York: Springer
AMA guides to the evaluation of disease and injury Science Business + Media.
causation (2nd ed., pp. 175–241). Chicago, IL: Zapf, P. A., Golding, S. L., Roesch, R., & Pirelli, G.
American Medical Association. (2014). Assessing criminal responsibility. In I. B.
Talmage, J. B., Melhorn, J. M., Ackerman, W. E., III, & Weiner & R. K. Otto (Eds.), The handbook of forensic
Barth, R. J. (2014). Musculoskeletal disorders: psychology (4th ed., pp. 315–351). Hoboken, NJ:
Conditions of uncertain pathophysiology – Acute and Wiley.
chronic pain. In J. M. Melhorn, J. B. Talmage, W. E.
Causality in Psychological Injury
and Law: Models 27

ance, and legal processes in these types of cases


Chapter Introduction can be iatrogenic for complainants/evaluees.
Given this preamble on the field psychologi-
As reviewed in the preceding chapter, psycho- cal injury and law, the first part of the chapter
logical injuries refer to psychological conditions focuses on extant models related to psychologi-
that eventuate after negligent actions and that cal injury and law and to causality in the field. In
cause mental harm and disability sufficient from this regard, the chapter works toward proposing
a legal standpoint to activate claims against the an inclusive model that incorporates iatrogenesis,
liable party, e.g., conditions such as posttrau- which is critical in the field of psychological
matic stress disorder (PTSD), chronic pain, and injury and law, but which, generally, is given less
mild traumatic brain injury (TBI). The said con- importance in psychology relative to medicine.
ditions and functional impairments result from Specifically, the chapter presents models using
events at claim such as motor vehicle accidents dimensions related to intention and deception.
(MVAs) and work injuries, which lead to corre- That is, it examines models involving the inter-
sponding legal actions in the venues at issue, section of dimensional spaces that can include
such as in tort and worker compensation claims, both valid psychological conditions and pro-
respectively. cesses, such as somatization, that might derive
Psychological injury and law is best conceived due to negligence, and also the category of nega-
as an area that integrates the biopsychosocial and tive response biases, including of malingering
forensic perspectives. The latter is involved both (which negates any possibility of having a valid
through the careful assessment procedures psychological condition). This prepares the way
requires in the typical psychological injury case for my own model on the matter, which is novel
and in the possibility that malingering and related in how it creates a central space for more ambig-
negative response biases mark a case. However, uous, gray-zone cases. Also, it is novel in the
possible biases in psychological injury cases are placement in one of the four quadrants of the
not limited to the examinee. That is, the psycho- two-dimensional space of the model a construct
logical injury case might be marked not only by related to a cry for help, termed a desperation cry.
possible biases expressed by complainants/eval- This term captures the nature of the cry in legiti-
uees, but also it could involve biases implicit or mate complainants in psychological injury cases
explicit in evaluators, as well as any third parties who feel that they are not being heard and are
involved. Finally, in terms of understanding all being subject to undue pressures. A major goal in
the impacts that can complicate cases of psycho- constructing this model had been to show how
logical injury, participation in the medical, insur- iatrogenesis fits into the system that acts on the

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 673


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_27
674 27 Causality in Psychological Injury and Law: Models

genuinely injured (or malingering) complainant/ conditions, and related ones that might develop
evaluee. after an event, such as in a worker compensation
In conclusion, the role of the adversarial case or a tort one involving a MVA, reflect multi-
(plaintiff-defense) divide is ubiquitous in this factorial causality. A biopsychosocial model
area of practice, and recommendations are made combined with a forensic one is the best way to
for dealing with it and also with other ways in approach the causation, assessment and diagno-
which effective and ethical practice might be sis, and treatment of psychological injuries.
compromised. Overall, one can conclude that Iatrogenesis can fit nicely as one factor in this
much of the causality of psychological injuries type of model.
that are attributed to an event at issue in a claim
might be subject to legal dispute and, therefore,
needs careful vetting. Terms

Iatrogenesis in psychology refers to the process


Iatrogenesis in Psychological Injury in which mental health workers generate a mental
health condition or disorder through their
This chapter deals with a construct that is rela- demeanor, assessment, diagnosis, advice, com-
tively poorly discussed in the psychological lit- ment, or treatment or other intervention.
erature—that of iatrogenesis. The first part of the Iatrogenesis is commonly considered in the med-
section deals with the term itself and then moves ical field, in general, but is rarely considered in
to related ones in the psychological injury and psychology. However, in the area of psychologi-
law context, such as litigation distress and the cal injury and law, iatrogenesis is considered one
insurance process. The next part of the section part of the multifactorial causality of patients’
reviews the relevant literature, focusing on iatro- psychiatric/psychological condition. These causal
genesis in the case of the major psychological factors not only include those that are pre-event,
injuries (PTSD, TBI, and chronic pain (and event, and post-event related, but also systemic
somatization)). Also, in this regard, it considers ones, such as iatrogenesis, litigation distress, the
the concept of compensation neurosis. insurance process, and the adversarial (plaintiff-
Iatrogenesis is a concept commonly encoun- defense) divide.
tered in medicine, in general. However, it is less Iatrogenesis is a term that originated in medi-
prevalent in psychiatry and psychology. In the cine but is quite applicable to psychology.
area of psychological injury and law, iatrogenesis However, it is not as prevalent in the research on
is encountered when treating professionals and and even the lexicon in psychology compared to
disability examiners unjustly dismiss valid medicine. For purposes of making this point, I
claims. Also, the converse of unjustly promoting entered the term of iatrogenesis in PubMed, a
invalid claims takes place. Iatrogenesis should be medical literature search engine, and the number
considered as part of a larger system in which of articles tagged with the term approached 30,000.
there is litigation distress, stress from the insur- As for PsychInfo, the search engine for psychol-
ance process, and so on, impacting the complain- ogy (acknowledging that PubMed and PsychInfo
ant or evaluee. At the same time, individuals cannot be so clearly divided in their contents), the
might unduly exaggerate or even malinger about number of tagged articles barely surpassed the 100
their symptoms, impairments, and disabilities, or mark. Rees (2012) noted that the prevention for
have their attorneys encourage and coach the iatrogenic psychological harm is just as important
same. It remains difficult to tease out the effect of as preventing physical harm, so that the goal of the
iatrogenesis on the development of psychological present piece to bring to the fore this issue in the
injuries, such as the major ones of chronic pain, psychological literature is timely.
PTSD, and propagation of mild TBI into a persis- From the point of view of medicine, the term
tent post-concussive syndrome (PPCS). These iatrogenesis concerns a harm induced by medical
Iatrogenesis in Psychological Injury 675

advice or treatment given to patients by medical PTSD. They presented two cases in which
doctors. Causally, the harm would not have arisen apparently well-intentioned treatment providers
but for the intervention or advice involved diagnosed PTSD inappropriately, causing unnec-
(Wikipedia, 2014). For the discipline of psychol- essary complications.
ogy, Melton, Petrila, Poythress, and Slobogin As for mild TBI/PPCS, several workers have
(2007) provided a definition of iatrogenesis con- referred to iatrogenetic effects, as well, for this
cerning a disorder that is precipitated, induced, or psychological injury (e.g., Bender & Matusewicz,
exacerbated by a mental health worker’s attitude, 2013). For example, the diagnosis of PPCS can
evaluation, comment, or intervention. The defini- be a self-propagating factor independent of any
tion could be more global by including iatrogen- other factors, such as the short-lived effect of the
esis related to diagnostic issues. In this regard, I original concussion, which might be associated
would add that giving a psychological diagnosis with it.
also could be iatrogenic, for example, if it is
incorrect, or if there is no diagnosis at all that is
applicable but one is made anyway. Also, miss- Context
ing a relevant diagnosis could be quite devastat-
ing to mental health and, therefore, constitute an When they are valid, the psychological injuries
iatrogenic factor. involved in actionable claims are multifactorial in
In all these regards, from a psychological per- their causality (e.g., Young, 2007, 2008a, 2008b,
spective, an integrated approach to iatrogenesis is 2008c, 2010, 2011, 2014a; Young & Yehuda,
that it consists of a product and a process. First, at 2006). However, as noted, aside from biological
the level of process, it generates an iatrogenic ill- (e.g., pathophysiological), psychological (e.g.,
ness, disease, disorder, or condition through its poor coping, personality), and social (e.g., poor
harmful process. Second, at the level of product, support) factors, part of the causal nexus might
the iatrogenic process consists of the interaction include iatrogenic effects. Moreover, because of
of the patient and the mental health worker (e.g., the legal context in which these types of injuries
psychologist, psychiatrist) such that, together, the are considered, one finds causal factors unique to
demeanor, assessment, diagnosis, advice, com- these injuries. That is, in psychological injury
ment, and/or treatment/intervention of the latter cases, there are multiple possible factors extrane-
adversely impact the psychological condition of ous to the typical biopsychosocial network in
the former. mental health causality. For example, they con-
About iatrogenesis and particular psychologi- cern how complainants are perceived (e.g., hon-
cal injuries, Schatman (2011) commented on an est or not) by those named in legal actions (e.g.,
article by Perret and Rosen (2011). Perret and the presumed negligent party and insurers (and
Rosen addressed pain physicians’ overreliance their legal representatives)).
upon opioid analgesics in primary treatment, Moreover, the adversarial insurance and
despite chronic opioid therapy’s lack of sufficient defense side against plaintiff actions have their
evidence bases. Schatman noted the problems of own biases. Therefore, iatrogenesis stands as but
potential safety issues involved and also the iatro- one complicating causal factor among the many
genetic effects that could result. These negative in the system impacting the complainant, and
effects could impact both particular individuals together they should be viewed as constituting a
and society, in general. The concerns of Perret powerful system that impacts the complainant.
and Rosen (2011) and Schatman (2011) echo Because the full system picture in causality of
those of Illich (1974). Aside from describing psychological injuries includes factors impacting
clinical iatrogenesis, Illich also described social the person beyond the usual psychological con-
iatrogenesis and cultural iatrogenesis. siderations, they detract from the person’s sense
Andrikopoulos and Greiffenstein (2012) of control and can have impacts that affect their
referred to iatrogenesis in the diagnosis of recovery from their psychological injuries.
676 27 Causality in Psychological Injury and Law: Models

Furthermore, patients might experience not only action and court) might be iatrogenic. In this
iatrogenic pressures and also litigation distress, regard, one could label the effect of the insurance
they might have vulnerable histories, personali- process on psychological injury claimants as
ties, or psychopathologies that can explain either “insurogenic” or the like (with the effect being
in part or in full. When the latter is the case, their worrisome in different ways for exaggerating and
present psychological condition might not relate non-exaggerating complainants).
at all to the negligent event at issue, and so their Young and Kane (2007; also Young, 2014b)
claims for post-event psychological injuries presented a multifactorial framework in the cau-
should be deemed invalid. sality of psychological injury. Part of the context
Returning to the question of their honesty, involved the factor of iatrogenic psychotherapy.
they might be unconsciously or consciously The overall model included pre-existing, causal
exaggerating or even feigning their symptoms, event, and post-event outcome factors. The effect
impairments, disorders, and disabilities (e.g., of iatrogenic therapy and litigation distress might
malingering). Note that symptom fabrication/ even begin at the time of the event (think—inap-
feigning/exaggeration for unconscious reasons is propriate critical incident counseling and ambu-
not the same as malingering and, moreover, this lance chasers, respectively). Therefore,
process can take place even consciously (as a cry iatrogenesis not only affects the particular indi-
for help). viduals involved but also has pernicious effects
Historically in the field of psychological on society, in general.
injury and law, Schultz (2003) put together the The next part of the present chapter reviews
first monograph on the topic, and Young followed recent publications on the multiple systemic fac-
suit (Young, Kane, & Nicholson, 2006, 2007; tors that affect particular psychological condi-
also see Koch, Douglas, Nichols, & O’Neill, tions, impairments, and disabilities in
2006; Schultz, 2008; Schultz & Stewart, 2008; psychological injury cases. They illustrate the
Young, 2008a, 2008b, 2008c). Schultz and col- problems in dealing with these types of cases,
leagues recognized iatrogenesis as one causal including in terms of iatrogenesis.
factor in psychological injuries, including it as
part of a biopsychosocial and forensic model. As
well, her model included recognition of other How Systemic Factors Influence
factors that I have mentioned, such litigation Outcome in Psychological Injury
factors.
Also in this regard, in Schultz (2003), Call Posttraumatic Stress Disorder
(2003) discussed the stressful nature of the legal
process on psychological injury claims. He noted Bootzin and Bailey (2005) examined three spe-
that the evidence does not support the contention cific psychological treatments that had been
that psychological symptoms improve once the intended to produce positive therapeutic effect;
litigation process comes to an end. Similarly, however, to the contrary, negative outcomes
Bryant and Harvey (2003) found that litigation occurred (i.e., critical incident stress debriefing
status had little effect on the maintenance of for PTSD; group therapy for adolescents with
PTSD, return to work, and so on. Tellingly, Call conduct disorders; and psychotherapy for disso-
(2003) argued that litigation can contribute to and ciative disorder). The authors noted that, in the
maintain psychological trauma. When this hap- case of all three treatments, there was a dynamic
pens, he referred to it being “jurisogenic” or “cri- interaction between specific and nonspecific
togenic”—terms that are akin to iatrogenic. mechanisms, which in some cases maximized the
Young and Kane (2007) concurred, but added negative effects of therapeutic interventions.
that the whole insurance process (from starting a Iatrogenic effect emerges when intended and
claim and treatment, to going to multiple medical unintended diagnosis or treatment interacts to
and other assessments, to passing through tort produce negative outcomes for the individual.
How Systemic Factors Influence Outcome in Psychological Injury 677

Bootzin and Bailey (2005) suggested that further These include pre-injury factors, injury factors,
research is needed to examine the interaction of and post-injury factors. The pre-injury ones
specific and nonspecific mechanisms in order to might be sufficient to explain any and all adverse
minimize iatrogenic effects. outcomes, such as PPCS. The post-injury factors
include ones unrelated to the event at claim, and
these might, as well, fully explain any PPCS. The
Traumatic Brain Injury negative response bias ones include malingering,
which would nullify any attribution of PPCS.
Iverson and Lange (2012) showed that the com- Bender and Matusewicz (2013) examined the
plications in assessment include expectation area of post-concussive syndrome (PCS) and fac-
effects, which, in this case, means that injured tors that could explain the persistence of PCS,
individuals believe that certain symptoms will such as malingering. They queried the validity of
develop inevitably as a result of their injury. In PCS—it lacks specificity, its diagnostic utility is
this regard, just by itself, for injured patients, questionable, and the dividing line between it and
having received a diagnosis is sufficient to affect genuine symptomatology due to mild TBI is not
their presentation and performance. Further, in specifiable. Furthermore, it is subject to extrane-
iatrogenesis, treating professionals might provide ous factors, such as iatrogenic and “jurisogenic”
diagnoses that are incorrect and, consequently, ones, which complicate its explanation in terms
the patients engage in behavior that facilitates a of malingering. Also, “compensation neurosis”
“self-fulfilling prophecy.” Iverson and Lange might lead to exaggeration of symptoms, which
(2012) added that, in the “good-old-days” bias, would then be “mostly internally-generated moti-
evaluees over-report how well they had been vation.” In addition, there are psychological fac-
doing prior to the event at issue. In the nocebo tors that develop post-injury that might interfere
effect, expectations also are involved (see next). with recovery (e.g., depression, poor coping).
Vanderploeg, Belanger, and Kaufmann (2014) Moreover, illness perceptions in patients might
described the concept of nocebo effect in psycho- lead to adoption of the sick role. The authors
logical injury (in the case of mild TBI leading to added that expectations of what the symptoms
PPCS). Nocebo effects refer to the mere expecta- might mean influence patient presentation (called
tion that treatment or intervention will harm, “expectation as etiology,” “diagnostic threat”).
which leads to the creation of or increase in Finally, evaluees might minimize pre-injury fac-
symptoms. The nocebo is harmless or inert but, tors, which could influence (or even “create”)
to the contrary, the outcome is harmful or nega- their presentation and performance.
tive. Further, inappropriate expectations or
beliefs can be conveyed and lead to iatrogenic
processes. Moreover, in the litigation context, Pain
treating professionals, attorneys, and plaintiff
experts might excessively focus on the event at In somatoform and dissociative disorders, Merten
issue as the sole cause of the outcome involved and Merckelbach (2013) argued that SVT (symp-
(e.g., negative expectations for recovery). Hahn tom validity test) failure and negative response
(1999) referred to nocebo as “expectations of bias in evaluees especially indicate their uncoop-
sickness,” which goes hand in hand with erativeness, lack of genuine presentation, and
iatrogenesis. lack of face value in presented life history and
Figure 27.1 presents a graphic depiction of the symptoms. Further, neither psychological prob-
multiple factors to consider in one type of psy- lems (such as unconscious conflicts and depres-
chological injury—mild TBI (after Iverson, sion) nor context (e.g., a cry for help) could
2011, 2012). The figure includes a role for iatro- explain evaluee negative response bias in terms
genesis. It places iatrogenesis in the full spectrum other than malingering. Finally, evaluees in non-
of factors that could influence evaluee outcome. litigating contexts might have “hidden agendas”
678 27 Causality in Psychological Injury and Law: Models

Preinjury Factors Injury Factors Postinjury Factors

Personality Macroscopic or Microstructural Injury


Characteristics or Injury Effects Altered Neurotransmitter System
Disorders (Biological) Neurocognitive or Neurobehavioral
Mild TBI
Problems

Biopsychosocial
Resilience/ Uncomplicated Mental Health Problems
Hardiness Psychological Sleep Disturbance/ Insomnia
Effects Chronic Pain
Depression
Post-Concussion- Anxiety/ Stress/ Worry
Biopsychosocial Like Symptoms PTSD (posttraumatic stress disorder)
Vulnerability Substance abuse
and Functional
Problems

Complicating Maladaptive Coping


Preexisting Mental Catastrophizing
Health Problems Psychological
Effects Expectations & Good-Old-Days
Bias
Nocebo Effect & Diagnosis Threat
Substance Abuse Cognitive Hypochrondriasis &
PPCS Preoccupation
Developing Lifestyle & Family Dynamics
Prior Brain (Persistent Changes
Injuries post-concussive Reinforced Illness Behavior
syndrome) Anger/ Bitterness
Perceived Injustice
Prior Medical or Justification/ Entitlement
Neurological
Problems
Complicating Iatrogenesis
Psycholegal Litigation Distress
Effects Insurance Process
Adversarial Divide

Negative Malingering
Response Bias Feigning
Exaggeration

Fig. 27.1 A biopsychosocial conceptual model of poor as the role of litigation distress, iatrogenesis, the insurance
outcome after mild traumatic brain injury. Note. The orig- process, and the adversarial (plaintiff-defense) divide).
inal figure of their model of poor outcome from mild trau- The original figure has been altered to put distal pre-injury
matic brain disorder (TBI) did not mention malingering, factors to the left, injury factors medially, and the post-
feigning, and exaggeration (negative response bias), nor injury factor to the right. Adapted from Iverson (2011,
did it include separately complicating legal effects (such 2012)

about the outcome of litigation factors (e.g., Young (2008b) further pointed to the work of
seeking benefits). Johnson (2008), who described chronic stress in
Young (2008b) referred to Deary, Chalder, relation to the HPA (hypothalamic–pituitary–
and Sharpe (2007), who presented a cognitive- adrenal) axis in MUS. In the normal process, an
behavioral model of medically unexplained initial increase in cortisol in reaction to stress
symptoms (MUS). In a somatization process, decreases through feedback mechanisms. When
symptom generation takes place because of the system is disturbed, the cycle is interrupted.
three factors—predisposing, precipitating, and Hypercortisolism is perpetuated by chronic or
perpetuating ones. Overall, chronic pain needs multiple stressors that produce, at first, hypercor-
to be understood in a systems perspective that tisolism but, with chronicity, both exhaustion and
examines the whole, including iatrogenic effects hypocortisolism develop. Specifically, when
due to medical uncertainty and lack of medical stress becomes chronic, the HPA axis is pushed
explanation/guidance. Moreover, a systems toward hypocortisolism instead of hypercorti-
model usually specifies sources of individual solism. Moreover, there are individual differ-
differences. ences in hypocortisolism, including those related
How Systemic Factors Influence Outcome in Psychological Injury 679

to decrease in free cortisol, cortisol resistance, cess might derive not only from patients’
and reduced biosynthesis of cortisol; indeed, for conscious and unconscious motivations for unfair
some individuals, the development of hypocorti- financial compensation but also from undue pres-
solism does not take place. The allostatic load sures brought to bear by insurers or in Insurer
model is a related one to that of somatization; it Examinations (IEs) and the subsequent unjust
explains how chronic stress creates the condi- denial of claims. Moreover, the notion of com-
tions for decline in health (McEwen & Lasley, pensation neurosis might be difficult to diagnose
2003). All these models are biopsychosocial in with any reliability, given its inclusion of con-
nature. scious and unconscious motivations, internal and
external incentives, and so on. However, that
being said, to their credit, Hall and Hall (2012)
Compensation Neurosis have acknowledged the complexity involved in
the process of symptom hardening in patients,
Hall and Hall (2012) proposed that the concept of and underscored that it might exclude the event at
“compensation neurosis” (Kennedy, 1946; claim as any part of the causes involved.
Miller, 1961a, 1961b) still should be current in Disability claims and disability evaluations
the field. Compensation neurosis concerns symp- take place in an adversarial procedure, which
tom exaggeration related to not only the prospect serves to increase the psychological costs for the
of secondary gain in a case but also to internal complainant (more anger, wanting revenge, loss
motivations (e.g., stress from the case; stress aversion). Furthermore, in order to make clear
from treatment issues; effects on somatization; their claim to evaluators, the stress of the com-
aspects of personality, such as dependence). The pensation/insurance/litigation process might lead
difference between compensation neurosis and evaluees to try too hard rather than less hard.
malingering is that in the former the presence of Therefore, when suboptimal effort or symptom
internal motivations is much more than the exter- magnification is evident in disability assessment,
nal incentives but, for the latter, the presence of this may occur for reasons other than conscious
external incentives is the sole motivator. processes and malingering. That being said, the
According to Hall and Hall (2012), compensa- insurance process might be stressful or effortful
tion neurosis does not refer to symptom absence, not only because of trying harder but also because
in that there are physical symptoms involved. of efforts to falsely present or produce symptoms,
Rather, it refers to the causes for the symptoms, as in malingering.
which do not involve “real” injuries related to the Overall, the biopsychosocial approach stands
event at hand; instead, they are seen to reflect as an inclusive one, but it needs to incorporate a
psychosomatic processes. Moreover, because of systemic or forensic component for better appli-
their personality structure, those reacting this cability in the area of psychological injury and
way might be individuals who are prone to react law. In the present context, the systemic/forensic
to in this manner and develop symptoms beyond aspect refers not only to possible malingering by
those expected by the events at claim (and so the examinee but also to the host of iatrogenic
manifesting compensation neurosis as presently factors in the insurance process and in medicole-
defined). About the stress of the case at hand, gal proceedings that deal with the examinee.
Hall and Hall (2012) concluded that it includes Also, it refers to the effect on psychological
conscious and unconscious pressures that influ- injury complainants of potential monetary and
ence the complainant not to improve. In all these related compensation (from legal actions). For
senses, it easy to understand how the legal and example, to present a balanced view, rather than
disability arena can be considered iatrogenic. just noting the possible deleterious effect of the
To conclude the presentation of the paper by legal and related system on individual complain-
Hall and Hall (2012), in Young (2014a), I noted ants when they have their legitimate injuries
that the iatrogenic potential in the insurance pro- denied, potential financial and other benefits that
680 27 Causality in Psychological Injury and Law: Models

are claimed by the individual or plaintiff (and The individual, therefore, might facilitate in
contested by the third payor/defendant) might an unconscious way the development, amplifica-
function to activate unconscious somatization tion, magnification, or exacerbation of symp-
processes in ways totally independent of the toms, even to the level of being serious, for initial
legitimate effects of the event at issue. And, these conscious reasons of financial gain or secondary
unconscious somatization processes, conse- gain that are either conveniently forgotten or
quently, would act to exacerbate injury-related unconsciously suppressed to justify the legal
symptoms, with the worsened symptoms so actions undertaken for the gain. The uncon-
caused presented as event-related and thus merit- sciously driven, centrally-mediated sensitization
ing compensation, aside from any question of processes that take place for financial ends might
conscious malingering that might further lead to even balance out or counter times when the eval-
claims of worsening symptoms. Kirmayer and uee had initially engaged in good effort to miti-
Taillefer (1997) also had integrated forensic com- gate the losses involved, both physically and
ponents into their model of somatoform symp- psychologically. That is, internally-generated
toms. Their category of social responses includes physiological and stress responses might, for
the effects of treatment providers, work condi- financial gain, serve to undermine any improve-
tions and, of note, the disability insurance and ments made post-injury, with the reasons ulti-
compensation systems. mately being the conscious search for financial
profit that only later slips into unconscious pro-
cesses. Moreover, the individual might become
Conclusion increasingly adamant that the event at claim is
responsible for all the effects of the event
So far, somatization and malingering, the former involved, believing this very strongly and without
being an unconscious process, and the latter a recall of the original conscious motivation to
conscious one, have been discussed mostly as exaggerate for financial gain.
two independent pathways to symptom exagger- Therefore, given the somatization that is acti-
ation. However, there might be ways in which the vated in this scenario, the evaluator should con-
two processes combine to the point of creating sider that the symptoms presented/produced in a
disability. For example, an initial injury might be scenario like it should be interpreted as being
relatively mild but is exacerbated by conscious related to a desire for financial gain, or malin-
wishes for monetary gain that eventually becomes gered. The somatization-malingering model
unconscious. In such cases, the process of enter- being presented excludes from its organization
taining unconscious wishes to obtain compensa- solely conscious malingering for financial gain,
tion, at a level beyond what might be indicated by given that somatization, per se, would not taking
the nature of the genuine injuries involved, prop- place when malingering alone is at issue.
agates post-event symptoms to the point that they Of course, there is very little way to prove step
attain thresholds of impairment and disability. by step the model presented in any one case.
For example, the patient ends up firmly believing However, by presenting it, I am alerting assessors
that he/she has been injured seriously (although to the complex processes that might be involved
that had not been the case), and aside from the in malingering. Others refer to partial compared
stress, lack of sleep, anger against the insurance to full malingering, which is only somewhat
process, and so on, that might act to worsen equivalent to my argument. In the end, only care-
symptoms, most of the symptom worsening, if ful, comprehensive assessment with multiple
not all of it, is due to conscious wishes for mon- testing can differentiate full, partial, and related
etary gain in legal actions that transforms to malingering, and other negative response biases,
unconscious wishes that conspire to produce the as well as feigning and non-credible presentation
serious pain involved and all related symptoms. and performance, in general.
New Model of Causation in Psychological Injury, Including Iatrogenesis 681

To summarize the various scenarios just offered to how the field functions generally. The field of
for the types of evaluee psychological processes psychological injury and law is a young one and,
that might be involved in psychological injuries, at the outset, in helping to coalesce it, I was con-
the process involved is the following. First, a con- cerned in developing integrative models (e.g., for
scious incentive for financial gain develops and chronic pain, see Young & Chapman, 2007).
interrupts legitimate recovery from injuries in an
event at claim after a genuine conscious effort to
mitigate loss, and involving, at most, a relatively Coping
minor injury at that. Then, the person slips into an
unconscious mode in which the originally con- Introduction In Young (2008c), I had created
sciously exacerbated/created symptoms in the per- an integrated biopsychosocial and forensic
son take on an unconscious life of their own, and model of coping applicable to the field of
the person might become increasingly strident and psychological injury and law. The model is
feeling entitled despite an absence originally of illustrated in the table accompanying the text; it
any genuine serious injury. gives its basic parameters and dimensions (see
Young (2014b) developed several models Table 27.1). Note that the model includes litiga-
related to the causation of psychological injury tion factors and, also, it points to factors compat-
and the manner in which causality is conceived ible with iatrogenesis, although this term is not
and constructed in the legal system. In the fol- used explicitly.
lowing, I review these models, and present a After further discussion of this model in
model that I have developed to integrate them, a what follows, I present a more generalized psy-
model that includes iatrogenesis. The model is chological model of legal causality, as origi-
forensic in focus, as well. Therefore, it can nally described in Young (2010). Finally, this
accommodate complex evaluee scenarios in the section of the chapter reviews a balanced model
gray zone. that I have recently developed of bias in the
system in which psychological injuries are con-
sidered (Young, 2014a). It examines not only
New Model of Causation patient biases but also broader systemic ones.
in Psychological Injury, These various models that I have developed
Including Iatrogenesis have prepared the way for the integrated one on
the various strands in the present chapter, as
Introduction they apply to the relationship of malingering,
somatization, psychiatric disorder, iatrogene-
In the following, I review various models appli- sis, and related constructs. Before arriving at
cable to the field of psychological injury and law. this final step in the chapter on an integrated
The first one considered is a biopsychosocial and model of biases in the field, I review others
forensic model of coping in psychological injury models that attempt to integrate the influences
that I had developed (Young, 2008c). It includes in these regards in the field. These other models
mention of iatrogenesis and so is pertinent to the that have been created have oriented me in my
present discussion of theory in psychological modeling endeavors.
injury and law. However, iatrogenesis must be
seen in the broader multifactorial causal complex Model As mentioned, the biopsychosocial foren-
of psychological injuries, and so modeling in the sic model of coping presented in Young (2008c)
area should take a broad, systemic approach of does not include iatrogenesis, per se, although it
not only factors affecting the individual evaluee considers other related factors that impact psy-
but also factors affecting the evaluators of eval- chological injuries, such as coping with the med-
uees and the whole system, too. Therefore, it ico/psycholegal context and the insurance process.
helps to see broad causal models not only In terms of the biopsychosocial influences on cop-
applicable to these injuries specifically but also ing, as indicated in Table 27.1, biological factors
682 27 Causality in Psychological Injury and Law: Models

Table 27.1 Components of a biopsychosocial forensic model of coping


Biological factors Psychological factors Sociocultural factors Forensic factors
Health condition Coping strategies Socioeconomics Medico/psycholegal context
Symptoms Behavior Work, school Apparent effort, malingering
Severity Appraisals, cognition Family, spouse Forensic appraisals, cognitions
Chronicity Affect Friends Pre-existing coping quality
Disability Role strain Community Barriers to good coping
Genetics, congenital Resilience, resistance Social support Impacts on coping skills
Gender, sex Personality Family doctor New techniques learned
Age Intellectual abilities Health care, caregivers Openness to learning
Medications, Social skills Insurance Adherence to learning,
treatments mitigation
Stress responses Coping history Legal support Coping with service providers
Addictions Resilience history Culture Coping with insurance
Medical history Psychological history Ecology Coping with court, law
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2008c). Coping in psychological injury: A
biopsychosocial and forensic perspective. Psychological Injury and Law, 1, 276–286; with kind permission from
Springer Science + Business Media B. V. [Table 1, Page 283]

include effects of genetics, stress responses, and In this regard, individuals with psychological
addictions. Psychological factors include roles for injuries might appraise that the compounding
coping skills, cognitive appraisals, and personal- stresses of iatrogenic, insurance, and legal-related
ity. Sociocultural factors include influences from matters are taxing beyond acceptable thresholds
work, insurance, and health care provider support. of their coping capacities. Or, they might believe
Forensic factors include consequences of mitiga- that their monthly financial benefits are capped
tion of loss, coping with court/law, and too low in their insurance policy (or perhaps
malingering. inappropriately by the adjudicator involved) and,
Young (2008c) noted that therapy should as a result, they and their family are suffering for
address the forensic appraisals, or cognitive eval- reasons beyond their control. These types of
uations and perceptions that are related to the forensic appraisals in psychological injury cases,
legal context, which might get in the way of or potentially destructive thought processes,
effective coping. These forensic appraisals refer would act to compound the stresses that survivors
to the cognitions that complainants might develop with psychological injuries making legal claims
in the context of their psychological injuries and for their injuries are experiencing from their
the pursuit of their case in court. Although the legitimate injuries.
filter of attempting to feign for monetary gain, as Or, other forensic appraisals might be
in malingering, represents an obvious if not noto- formed that serve to undermine any recovery
rious forensic appraisal that might influence taking place for their psychological injuries.
complainants in their claims to court, there are For example, individuals might believe that
others that complicate the forensic assessment their treatment providers do not understand
process and also the understanding by the courts their injuries and, therefore, these patients
and related venues of psychological injuries. resort to constantly seeking medical cures, even
Moreover, these other forensic appraisals, which though psychological ones should be targeted.
are more likely to be present, could discourage Also, they might appraise that their insurer is
optimal recovery, even if they are unrelated to denying access to needed therapies without
intentions to deceive for monetary gain. good medical reason and, as a result, the
New Model of Causation in Psychological Injury, Including Iatrogenesis 683

patients feel an increased stress, which func- also assessors might feel influenced by the divide,
tions to aggravate their injuries. for example, to engage in biased and incomplete
assessments for the benefit of either the plaintiff
or defense side. Further in this regard, the evi-
Psycho-Ecological Model dence gathered in an assessment might be
insufficiently reliable and valid to meet admissi-
Introduction Young (2010) described another bility standards of good compared to poor or junk
model in the field of psychological injury and law science, and not function to help the court accord-
that is related to iatrogenesis, the psycho- ing to extant criteria of good science for court
ecological model of legal causality. The model in purposes, as elucidated in Daubert v. Merrell
Young (2010) is not just on causality in law but Dow Pharmaceuticals, Inc. (1993), in particular,
how laws related to causality and related matters and subsequent rulings in the Daubert trilogy.
get constructed. In this regard, the model consists These latter rulings require that evidence pre-
of five concentric circles that represent the series sented to court should be more probative than
of increasing distal interacting influences on the prejudicial relative to a case at hand, and fit it rel-
construction of law as one gravitates away from evantly. Also, many other factors could adversely
the inner circle. Therefore, the model is depicted impact and mitigate against impartial assess-
as a series of concentric circles, for example, ments, such as use of biased research. The latter
with the person in a case represented in the mid- might involve conflicts of interest and litigation
dle and the impacts of increasingly distal influ- science, which involves science targeting legal
ences on the person represented by the concentric questions without the expected parameters of
circles, but with the influences in the circles independent science. When presenting evidence
mutually influencing each other. to court in a case at hand, the scientific process
By the term the construction of law, I am not followed should be neutral throughout, from
referring to the procedures in drafting laws but to assessment and testing, to diagnosis and ruling in
the wider dynamics involved. We need a complex or out of malingering and related negative
model of legal causality and its construction response biases, to conclusions proffered, or else
because legal terms and tests are not as clear as the evidence could be considered impartial and
they need to be. Also, the dynamics involved in not meeting the criteria of good science as spelled
the creation of causal tests and thresholds in the out in the field, in general.
legal system are influenced by factors that go For Young (2010), in order to better grasp the
beyond the law, per se. causality of psychological injuries and the con-
struction of laws related to them, models need to
Model The model specifies the layers of influ- consider the psychology of all actors and agents
ence not only tests of causality in the legal arena in the system, and not just that of complainants.
but also those that influence the psychological Granted, the post-incident mental health of a
injuries of complainants. In this regard, the circle complainant might be malingered or might be
that is closer to any case at hand functions as a compromised by pre-existing mental health diffi-
direct impact on the person—that is, as repre- culties (e.g., personality disorder, psychopathol-
sented in the circle, the adversarial divide serves ogy; and not only by whether the person is
as an immediate influence that exerts pressure on engaging in anything like malingering), so that
the person, on the one hand, but also on the court the causality of the psychological injuries at issue
system in terms, on the other hand, in terms of the might be difficult to ascertain. That being said,
pressures that it exerts on other actors in the sys- beyond this consideration, other aspects of the
tem, including attorneys and insurers. In this system could influence outcome of cases outside
regard, not only might the person be influenced of the psychology of the complainant. For exam-
to exaggerate symptoms or even malinger, but ple, judges’ dispositions might impact their
684 27 Causality in Psychological Injury and Law: Models

reactions and preferences in admissibility hear- the wronged, those seeking justice, and its most
ings. Most important, as mentioned, attorneys vulnerable are important. Moreover, societal atti-
argue their case from the adversarial divide, which tudes in this regard play an indirect role in legal
has profound effects on legal proceedings right construction. They could very well influence
from the first contact with complainants. Also, parties seeking to influence the process of law
experts who are evaluating complainants might be construction for their own interests. In short, the
influenced by the legal referral source within the influences that affect how laws are constructed,
divide, especially because of their own self- ultimately, include all of us as a society. For the
interest and gratifications (e.g., monetary; Young legal context of psychological injury and law,
et al., 2007). Finally, there are wider sociocultural some of the shortcomings found in relevant laws,
and historicopolitical considerations impacting and in their ultimate disposition and effects,
the construction of laws related to psychological might reflect our own shortsightedness.
injuries in court and related venues, not the least To summarize, the psycho-ecological model
of which might be inordinate pressures on gov- of causality as developed by Young (2010) is an
ernment agencies by the insurance industry. integrated one for court purposes that incorpo-
rates process (e.g., good law) and product (e.g.,
Comment To conclude, in Young (2010), I good mental health evaluation). I use the label of
noted that the insurance industry in the legal “psycho-ecological” to emphasize the role of
arena acts as a pressure on impartiality. Also, context in constructing law and also the role of
industry stakeholders generally bring pressure on psychological factors in all major actors and
the government to enact laws favorable to their agents involved in the system in which complain-
interests. ants find themselves. These influences range
In this regard, Haack (2008) has revisited the from the individual complainants involved, to the
testimony proffered by experts in Daubert v. professionals involved, including attorneys and
Merrell Dow Pharmaceuticals, Inc. (1993), mental health evaluators, to institutions, such as
through the parallel case of Blum v. Merrell Dow that of the insurance industry, and to the wider
Pharmaceuticals (764 A.2d 1, 2000) in the US society, which means all of us in our attitudes.
state of Pennsylvania. In this revealing case,
Judge Bernstein exposed the lack of forthright-
ness in the testimony that had been offered in Biases
Daubert.
For example, a senior executive in the drug Introduction In Young (2014a), I developed a
company involved in Daubert admitted to pick- model that extended my work in Young (2010)
ing and choosing information over a 30-year on the widespread biases that can influence com-
period. One scientist after another who had par- plainants, evaluators, and parts of the system in
ticipated in Daubert admitted to their lack of sci- psychological injury cases. In that book, I pre-
entific rigor under Judge Bernstein’s “devastating sented a model of the dimensions underlying
scrutiny” in Blum. For instance, one expert systemic influences on evaluees claiming psy-
acknowledged that the biomedical company chological injuries and their assessment.
involved had consistently “underreported” the
adverse effects of the medication at issue, and Model The integrated model that I developed on
another expert testified that the company had influences on all actors and agents in the psycho-
supported research out of its legal defense funds. logical injury and law context includes a role for
Young (2010) noted that his psycho-ecological conscious influences for financial gain, in partic-
model of law construction also considers mental ular, not only for complainants but also for other
health at this level because the general approach systemic actors in the tort and disability context
of a society toward its members, its minorities, (see Fig. 27.2). For example, the top part of the
a Evaluees (and Treatment Providers)
External Negative
[Providers
pro-plaintiff] (Symptom Exaggeration)

[Adversarial]

Type
Unconscious Conscious State Conscious

Incentive
Evaluee
Response [Divide]
Biases

Positive [Providers
(Symptom Minimization) pro-defense]
Internal

b Claim Evaluators (including Psychiatrists, Psychologists, Attorneys; Insurers)


External
[Evaluators Exaggeration
pro-plaintiff]

[Adversarial]
Type

Unconscious Conscious State Conscious


Incentive

Evaluator [Divide]
Response
Biases

[Evaluators
Minimization
pro-defense]
Internal

Fig. 27.2 Financial and psychological pressures influ- with respect to either their patients’ attorneys or their
encing evaluees/clients and evaluators/treatment provid- insurers. (b) The second part of the figure indicates that
ers. (a) The figure illustrates the potential of evaluees to the same pressures apply to the full range of evaluating
malinger or engage in self-unfavorable, non-credible pre- professionals on a case, including mental health profes-
sentations. They might act consciously for external sionals, and not only insurers and attorneys. Valid claims
rewards/financial gains by expressing negative response might be denied because of undue influence stemming
bias or excessive symptom exaggeration, for example. from the adversarial divide, or invalid claims might be
Other types of symptom exaggeration might be uncon- supported. Adopted with permission of Springer Science
scious and for internal incentives, for example, as might + Business Media. Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feign-
be found in factitious disorder. Evaluees might express ing, and response bias in psychiatric/psychological
symptom minimization in a positive response bias. The injury: Implications for Practice and court. Dordrecht,
adversarial divide refers to whether evaluators fall on the Netherlands: Springer Science + Business Media; with
plaintiff or defense side of the case at hand, but even treat- kind permission from Springer Science + Business Media
ment providers might be unduly influenced by it, e.g., B. V. [Figure 5.1, Page 112]
686 27 Causality in Psychological Injury and Law: Models

figure indicates that treatment providers might be Young (2014a) concluded that a science-
influenced inappropriately by the adversarial informed, comprehensive, and impartial approach
divide and, therefore, either support inappropri- to assessments can provide some balance to these
ately or deny inappropriately a patient’s treat- diverse biasing influences in psychological injury
ment plan. In this regard, in this model, as with cases. A science-first approach applies to how
others in this chapter, I emphasize that the influ- data are gathered reliably, how the data are inter-
ence of bias on actors and agents in psychologi- preted, and how they are presented to court. In
cal injury cases and related disability systems this way, additional sources of bias, such as evi-
might not be limited just to its effect on com- dent in iatrogenesis, the insurance process, litiga-
plainants (e.g., as in malingering). tion distress, and the adversarial divide, are
The bottom part of the figure specifies a minimized, countered, and reduced to a level at
dimension in psychological injury work showing which they cannot do harm, whether this
that more than complainants and plaintiffs might approach applies to the injured party or to the
engage in behavior for financial gain, whether for system as a whole (e.g., the insurer).
reasons that are conscious or unconscious. In this In this way, additional sources of bias, such as
regard, as mentioned previously, insurers might found in each of iatrogenesis, the insurance pro-
also behave inappropriately, for example, by cess, litigation distress, and the adversarial
denying valid treatment plans. Also, plaintiff divide, are minimized, countered, and do less or
attorneys might inappropriately coach plaintiffs no harm. Mental health assessors have an impor-
how to cheat the system (or simply have informa- tant equilibrating role to play in this imbalanced
tion on their websites, e.g., about the symptoms system when they adopt this up-front scientific
of PTSD, that indirectly do the same). To con- attitude; biases would be diminished, both in
clude, the range of influences on the individual at terms of dealing with the injured and being part
the center of a psychological injury case might be of the system (e.g., the insurer). For example, in
extensive, going well beyond anything like hav- a balanced approach to assessment of complain-
ing a motivation to malinger. ants, appropriate screening for negative response
That being said, Young (2014a) noted that, in bias would benefit insurers. And, not overinter-
cases of psychological injury, malingerers cost preting cases as malingered ones would benefit
the system immensely. Therefore, the best complainants.
malingering detection methods and systems
need to be used, in order to arrive at accuracy in Comment Greiffenstein and Kaufmann (2012)
malingering detection and attribution. At the addressed one component of the biases in the
same time, evaluees might express exaggeration legal side of the system in which psychological
and biases for reasons that might be more injury is involved, and their work is consistent
unconsciously than consciously motivated (i.e., with my approach. The authors described legal
exaggerating for reasons that do not involve proceedings that take place in adversarial set-
financial gain). Factors other than malingering tings, and they noted that attorneys are “zealous”
might explain their exaggerations, and these advocates in this regard. That is, the goal for
might be legitimate (e.g., crying out for help, attorneys in psychological injury cases is to
catastrophizing). Or, a patient might persist in “win” in the proceedings, a goal that is consid-
seeking compensation despite symptom amelio- ered more important than functioning with accu-
ration, in the mistaken belief that the negligent racy and objectivity. Moreover, from the point of
party should pay for the transgression at issue view of attorneys, justice is considered more
consistent with the level of the original injury important than truth itself. This does not mean
and no matter what had been the ultimate out- that in their ethics and training, and later practice,
come of their injuries, e.g., full or great attorneys are given license to lie. Nevertheless,
improvement. the legal agenda in psychological injury cases
Iatrogenesis 687

does allow attorneys to exclude expert or other tions and categories of malingering, factitious
reports if they are not supportive of the goal of disorder, and other related psychiatric disorders.
advocating successfully for their clients. That is, The said models include psychological condi-
from the perspective of an attorney, no matter tions that might be problematic in court, such as
what the side, an accurate, comprehensive, and conversion disorder or somatoform disorder.
balanced report might not be helpful or might Among these models, one finds my own (Young,
even be harmful to the case at hand. 2014a). All of these models take a dimensional
Young (2014a) concluded that working in the approach, with aspects such as intention ranging
area of psychological injury is challenging not from clear to minimal or no overt motivation.
only because of the need for an integrated After this section, as presented in Young (2014a),
biopsychosocial and functional perspective, but I propose a new integrated model along these
also because of the difficulties presented by the lines, and include the concepts of iatrogenesis,
additional stresses that accompany the forensic, insurance process, litigation distress, and the
insurance, and legal contexts. For example, adversarial divide. But, first, consider the follow-
injured parties might have to deal with (a) anger ing related models that have influenced the con-
about the insurance process, (b) anxiety about struction of my own integrated one.
medical examinations, (c) anxiety about insur-
ance examinations, (d) the stress of cross-
examinations, (e) the losses due to their inability Other Models
to work, or (f) stress from having physical thera-
pies terminated prematurely in valid cases or, (a) Ruff and Jamora (2009) modeled the rela-
conversely, stress from being detected in not giv- tionship of malingering, factitious disorder,
ing adequate effort in physical therapies and also and exaggeration/reduced effort in the space
continuously exaggerating symptoms, even to the created by juxtaposing two dimensions, as
point of malingering. Given the forensic and well. For them, the two dimensions involved
legal aspects of psychological injury cases, men- those of: (a) incentive (which can be either
tal health professionals should carefully keep internal or external) and (b) consciousness
track of their patients’ apparent effort/motiva- (which can be either conscious or uncon-
tion, compliance/adherence to treatment, coop- scious). Ruff and Jamora added the socio-
eration in completing therapeutic homework cultural context as an encompassing
assignments, and, in general, their attempts to background to their dimensional model (see
mitigate loss. Functioning in this manner would Fig. 27.3).
ensure that workers in the field obtain valid deter- (b) Boone (2011) developed a unidimensional
minations of patient symptoms, impairments, model of malingering and psychiatric disor-
disorders, and disabilities, or conversely, that the der involving deception. She placed malin-
role of exaggeration, response bias, and possible gering on the “other deception” end of the
malingering in patient performance and presenta- deception continuum, and somatoform disor-
tion is addressed adequately. der, or adopting the sick role, on the “self-
deception one” (see Fig. 27.4).
(c) Bass and Halligan (2007) used a two-
Iatrogenesis dimensional model to represent malingering
and related negative response biases. Their
Introduction model consisted of the dimensions of (a)
choice: which can be either intentional or
Several models have been constructed that repre- non-intentional; and (b) responsibility: which
sent the relationships among intentionality and can be either exculpated or in deception. The
deception in behavior to the psychological condi- two dimensions, when aligned on the vertical
688 27 Causality in Psychological Injury and Law: Models

Fig. 27.3 The

Unconscious
relationship between
conscious/unconscious Factitious
and incentive in Disorder
understanding factitious
disorder and
Exaggeration
malingering. Symptom
Poor effort

Consciousness
invalidity is difficult to
differentiate from OR
malingering, poor effort,
and exaggeration. Exaggeration
Moreover, the latter two Poor effort
might take place for
either conscious or
unconscious reasons.
Conscious

Adapted from Ruff and


Jamora (2009) Malingering

Internal Incentive External Incentive


Incentive

Sociocultural Context

Fig. 27.4 The


relationship between
disorder and deception
in understanding in
somatoform presentation
and malingering
presentation. Malingering
Somatoform (multiple relevant
Malingering is related to (adopting sick
deceiving others, test failure/
Disorder

role) evaluations)
somatoform disorder to
deceiving oneself.
Psychological testing
can help differentiate
them (e.g., using the
MMPI-2-RF). Adapted
from Boone (2011)

Self Other

Deception

and horizontal axes, create a space in which tion and related states, as well more genuine
both disorders and complicating factors can psychiatric/psychosocial disorders.
be situated (see Fig. 27.5). In this regard, the (d) Similarly, Hall and Hall (2012) used a two-
space created by the two dimensions involved dimensional model to represent the various
allows one to place malingering/exaggera- negative response biases and disorders in
Iatrogenesis 689

Fig. 27.5 The

Exculpated
relationship between Psychiatric Disorder
responsibility and
intention in the Psychosocial Disorder
generation of
malingering. Diagnosis
of disorder (and
attribution of

Responsibility
malingering) depends on
where the evaluee stands
with respect to two
dimensions, involving
Exaggerated
intention and
responsibility, in
particular. The assessor
does not consider just the
choice of assigning
Deception

disorder or some form of


deception (e.g., Malingered
malingering).
Exaggeration might also
be a valid option to Non-intentional Intentional
consider. Adapted from
Bass and Halligan (2007)
Intentionality

Fig. 27.6 The


relationship between Conversion
Internal

Disorder Factitious
motivation and choice in
Disorder
the generation of
malingering. Diagnosis
of disorder (and
attribution of
malingering) depends on
Motivation

where the evaluee stands Compensation


with respect to two Neurosis
dimensions, involving
intention and choice, in
particular. The assessor
does not just consider
the choice of assigning
disorder or some form of
deception (e.g.,
External

malingering).
Compensation neurosis Malingered
might also be a valid
option to consider.
Adapted from Hall and Non-intentional Intentional
Hall (2012)
Choice

psychological injury cases. The dimensions My Integrated Model of Causality in


concern the level of (a) choice (intentional, Psychological Injury and Complicating
non-intentional) and (b) motivation (internal, Factors, Including Iatrogenesis
external). They allow one to place in the
space created malingering, factitious disor- Model In the following, I present a model that is
der, conversion disorder, and compensation based on the prior models that are outlined above.
neurosis (see Fig. 27.6). The focus of the present model relates to a
690 27 Causality in Psychological Injury and Law: Models

Litigation Distress
(Desperation cry for Malingering
High help) Malingering
Possible/ Probable

Noncredible
DEGREE OF EXTERNAL-ORIENTED INTENTION/

Gray Zone
MOTIVATION/ CONSCIOUSNESS

Individual/
Context ª

DEGREE OF DECEPTION/ RESPONSIBILITY


Low High
Sociocultural
Background

Exaggeration

Feigning

Problematic Presentation/
Psychiatric Disorder Performance Factitious
Low

(somatization, Disorder
conversion)

AGE/ DEVELOPMENT

Fig. 27.7 Model of intention and deception in forensic As for the four quadrants of the model, they help
and related disability evaluations and claims. Behavior in define and differentiate four crucial conditions in the psy-
forensic and related contexts of disability evaluations and chological injury and law context. Assessors might diag-
claims is influenced by multiple factors other than the nose a psychiatric disorder when there appears to be
event at claim and any subsequent injuries, physical or absent or low conscious intentionality in behavior, presen-
psychological. This behavior appears to vary along two tation, and performance related to externally-oriented
major dimensions, relating to intentionality and decep- motivations. These would include the complicating
tion. Developmental age and sociocultural context also diagnoses in psychological injuries related to somatiza-
are important to consider. Intention might be external, tion and conversion diagnoses (i.e., in the DSM-5
conscious (e.g., for financial gain) or internal, uncon- (Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders,
scious (e.g., in illness behavior that promotes overly solic- Fifth Edition; American Psychiatric Association, 2013),
itous behavior). The central part of the figure indicates these refer to conversion (functional) disorder and com-
that there is a gray zone in evaluee presentation and per- plex somatic symptom disorder, respectively). When there
formance that makes it difficult to attribute a diagnosis or is absent to low externally-oriented intention/motivation/
to infer malingering. Evaluee behavior that elicits doubt conscious state, but the degree of deception is high, the
can be described as feigning, non-credible, and so on. If appropriate diagnosis might be factitious disorder. As for
the evidence is clear for a disorder or syndrome, however, the high end of intentionality related to externally driven
a diagnosis such as posttraumatic stress disorder (PTSD), incentives, for upper-end levels of deception, malingering
pain disorder, or mild traumatic brain injury (TBI) can be is an appropriate inference. As for absent to low levels of
given. However, the diagnosis might be one involving a deception at this level of intentionality, a desperate cry for
disorder or condition less clearly related to the event at help can be attributed (related to litigation distress, for
claim, such as conversion disorder. Also, factors such as example). Note. ªContext: (1) Degree to which deception
litigation distress and the insurance process might be is an adaptation that is acceptable and/or is coached. (2)
responsible for a cry for help, including unconsciously Degree system exacerbates symptoms (iatrogenesis;
and out of desperation, rather than it reflecting anything insurance process; litigation distress; adversarial divide,
like malingering. etc.). (3) Culture, race, etc.
Iatrogenesis 691

continuum of credible/non-credible presentation/ proposing presently in this chapter on malinger-


performances in terms of two dimensions— ing and related presentations/performances con-
related to (a) whether the individual is expressing siders the following three factors. These factors
deception or responsibility and (b) whether the concern: (a) context; (b) how the dimensions
nature of their expression is intentional or not involved intersect; and (c) the manner of place-
(see Fig. 27.7). In contrast to the prior models, ment in the dimensional space involved those
I indicate that determination of either valid presentations and performances that are not
psychological conditions or of malingering and problematic, and not clearly disorder at one
related negative response biases is difficult extreme nor malingered at the other. The fol-
because many cases in the area involve uncer- lowing section of the chapter presents material
tainty, ambiguity, indecision, and imprecision in related to these factors involved in the model
diagnosis and ruling in or out complicating fac- currently being discussed.
tors such as malingering. That is, even though my
model resembles the others by using the dimen- (a) The context is important in psychological
sions of deception/responsibility and intention, injury cases. In such cases, evaluee behavior
the middle area involving the so-called gray zone is influenced by the complete system in
takes prominence. which the evaluation takes place. The eval-
That is, by considering these two dimensions uee might demonstrate incentive for mone-
of deception/responsibility and degree of inten- tary gain and attempt to consciously fabricate
tionality simultaneously, my model places many and deceive. At the same time, the evaluee
psychological injury cases, which usually do not might be subject to systematic pressures to
present or perform unambiguously, as often lying deny valid injury claims; moreover, in this
in the intermediate gray zone. The latter could process, even treating professionals might
include the exaggerations mentioned in the model play a role, for example, by denying valid
of Bass and Halligan (2007), which they sepa- claims themselves (one aspect of iatrogene-
rated from malingering, which is an approach sis). Therefore, on the one hand, the evaluee
consistent with my own. However, even exag- might express a culture of entitlement/accep-
geration presents difficulties in determining their tance of deception as an adaptation, or even
intent, and they could constitute malingering, be influenced toward this attitude by its
depending on what is found in the whole exam- coaching (e.g., by the plaintiff attorney in the
inee file, including on testing. In this regard, in adversarial divide). These factors stand out
Young (2014a), I acknowledged the complica- as possible important ones in what has been
tions and difficulties in discerning the status of called the disability epidemic (e.g., Bass &
the validity of psychological injury claims, and Halligan, 2014; Bass, Halligan, & Oakley,
noted that, because of the multiple factors 2003). Moreover, treating professionals
involved in cases, (a) even mild exaggerations might contribute to this epidemic in an
could be non-credible and (b) gross exaggera- unwitting fashion, for example, by promot-
tions could be credible. [Note. Aside from the ing false or exaggerated claims as involving
major axes of intention and deception/responsi- disability or by administering inappropriate
bility and the consideration of context, a third or even harmful therapy or intervention
dimension of the model could include develop- (which is another aspect of iatrogenesis).
mental level or age.] Conversely, in psychological injury cases,
there might be systemic factors minimizing
Factors Aside from incorporating the claims (and iatrogenically harming patients)
approaches and issues inherent in prior models through factors such as the insurance pro-
of the relationship of intent and deception with cess, litigation distress, and the behavior and
respect to malingering or nonconscious-derived actions defense attorneys in the adversarial
disorders, the combined model that I am divide.
692 27 Causality in Psychological Injury and Law: Models

(b) The two dimensions typically considered cases that involve only mild exaggeration,
in extant models relating malingering, are placed in the central portions in the
factitious disorder, and so on, as reviewed model, and not the outer edges. To remind in
above, appear to represent (1) degree of this regard, mild exaggeration does not con-
externally-oriented intention/motivation/ stitute malingering (Bass & Halligan, 2007,
conscious awareness, and (2) degree of 2014; Young, 2014a). That is, presentations
deception/responsibility. These dimensions and performances of these types in psycho-
are continual rather than categorical, in the logical injury cases should not be considered
sense they are not all or none in nature, but as belonging to an outer end of any quadrant
they represent different degrees of the behav- in the proposed model, that is, as clear signs
ior involved, i.e., intent and deception/ of malingering.
responsibility. Their intersection creates a (c) The upshot of the prior explanation of the
2 × 2 axis model that allows for different present model on the nature of presentation
degrees of intent and deception/responsibil- and performance of psychological injury
ity in psychological injury cases, at least in complainants in terms of the dimensions of
the sense of how these dimensions are deception/responsibility and intent is that the
defined. Moreover, the two-dimensional center of the two-dimensional space that is
space created by the juxtaposition of the axes created by juxtaposing the dimensions should
allow for the placement of relevant catego- be reserved for the ambiguous, indeterminate
ries and conditions in the psychological gray-zone cases, which are problematic for
injury and law context, including all of those assessors because they do not clearly indi-
mentioned in the prior models reviewed cate either outright malingering at one
above. That is, the intersection of the dimen- extreme or genuine disorder at the other
sions of intent and deception/responsibility extreme. Aspects of behavior in these cases
affords the location in the space created of related to mild exaggeration might fit best in
the categories and conditions of malingering, this central location of the model, which is
factitious disorder, and so on.In the model reserved for ambiguous or less clear cases, or
that I developed, given the central impor- for those not clearly disordered nor malin-
tance given to gray-zone cases and the place- gered, for example.
ment of these gray-zone cases in the middle
of the model in the figure, I positioned these Given these considerations, Fig. 27.7 consti-
other major constructs being considered tutes an integrated model of the relationship
(e.g., malingering, genuine psychological among malingering, factitious disorder, and other
disorders) at the outer edges in the two- disorders, as they fit into the dimensions of
dimensional space created by juxtaposing the degree of external/internal-oriented intentional-
two axes involved, that is, in the extreme ity and degree of deception/responsibility.
outer portions of the four quadrants created Further, prior models had not considered the
by their orthogonal alignment. That is, unique combination of overt externally-oriented
because the more definite conditions and cat- intentionality in the motivation of complainants
egories are more extreme in terms of their coupled with an absence deception for purposes
standing with respect to the continual dimen- of monetary gain. In this regard, it makes sense to
sions of intent and deception/responsibility refer to this particular combination in the psy-
relative to gray-zone cases that form the chology of psychological injury complainants as
heart of the present model, these conditions/ litigation distress or a cry for help. The latter term
categories have been placed at the outer might be used when the evidence points to any
edges of the model.Therefore, less contro- degree of exaggeration in patient presentation
versial performances and presentations of and performance, perhaps along with mitigating
psychological injury cases, such as those complicating factors, such as psychopathology,
Iatrogenesis 693

yet malingering does not seem apparent. psychological injury and law, leading to better
Therefore, the assessor must seek other explana- assessments, interpretations of the reliable data
tions for the behavior without using the explana- gathered in them, and the ruling in or out of com-
tion of malingering. It is surprising that the prior plications, including that of malingering. The
models discussed do not mention this common model includes important factors in its dimen-
opposition of malingering and a cry for help, but sions, which concern intention and deception for
I have rectified the lack in my equivalent model, the most part, and it adds a component not con-
which suggests alternative interpretations possi- sidered in prior models, related to a cry for help.
ble for exaggeration that exclude noncredibility This addition helps fill the four quadrants of the
or malingering. model created by the juxtaposition of its two
However, that being said, cries for help can major axes or dimensions. Also, the model
derive from both conscious and unconscious excludes for the most part from consideration at
influences, and it is important to differentiate the crucial outer areas of the four quadrants
these motivations in the gray zone. In this sense, I involved aspects of cases and their assessment
suggest a new term for conscious intentional that might be minor considerations, such as mild
externally-oriented motivation without deception, exaggeration. In this regard, also, it considers
per se, in the cries for help of psychological injury gray zone, ambiguous cases in which psychologi-
complainants, that of “desperation cry.” It distin- cal injury cases are difficult to disambiguate as
guishes from unconscious cries for help that take being part of the central area of the model.
place because one is overwhelmed and is reaching Evaluators in this area of practice of psychologi-
out for help in a way that is out of awareness. An cal injury and law need to function from a
advantage of this term of desperation cry is that it scientifically-informed approach in their evalua-
reflects the typical meaning of the term of a cry tions, which need to be comprehensive and
for help in psychological injury cases (i.e., a con- impartial, as well, so that the present model might
scious pleading for help in desperation). help in this regard by helping seeing the relation-
ship of the major complications in the area, such
Conclusion As for conclusions that should be as malingering, exaggeration, iatrogenesis, litiga-
offered in these types of assessments of psycho- tion distress, and the insurance process.
logical injury cases, professionals dealing with In the development of psychological injuries,
problematic presentations and performances, but such as the major ones of chronic pain, PTSD,
without clear evidence of malingering, per se, and propagation of mild TBI into PPCS, it
should refer to feigning or dissimulation, in gen- remains difficult to tease out the effect of
eral, or even to noncredibility or possible/proba- iatrogenesis, and apportioning its role in the mul-
ble malingering. Further, the astute assessor who tifactorial causality involved. These major psy-
has enough valid evidence to indicate that gray- chological injury conditions, and related ones
zone cases are quite non-credible will find the that might develop after an event at claim, such as
language needed in the conclusions proffered to in a worker compensation case or in a tort case
discredit enough the examinee, yet without using involving a MVA, reflect a multifactorial causal-
the term of malingering. ity that has biopsychosocial origins. However,
To conclude, I have created a model that inte- given the legal side of psychological injury cases,
grates the major themes of the chapter, both in they need careful scrutiny for the validity of the
terms of conditions that might arise to complicate conditions claimed. In this regard, a biopsycho-
a clear understanding of the psychological out- social model combined with a forensic one is the
come of an event at claim, and in terms of com- best way to understand the causation of claimed
plicating factors in establishing causality, from conditions, the actual conditions involved, and
iatrogenesis to malingering. This model could the best treatment for the psychological injuries
help disambiguate complex cases in the areas of involved. Iatrogenesis fits nicely as one factor in
694 27 Causality in Psychological Injury and Law: Models

this type of model. It can exacerbate or even cre- Specifically in this chapter, I underscore the
ate psychological conditions, so that it should be value of a combined biopsychosocial and foren-
part of the causal evaluative process in these sic approach in psychological injury cases. Also,
types of cases. In my own work in the area, when I propose an integrative model that considers the
litigation or insurance distress appears to be a relationship among malingering, litigation
causative factor among others, for example, I will distress, and psychiatric disorders, including fac-
indicate this in my conclusions to the assessment. titious disorder, and processes that affect presen-
Needless to say, the presence of iatrogenesis tation and performance in these types of cases,
and related complications in causal analyses of such as somatization, deception, and conscious
psychological injury claims renders the cases motivation for financial gain. This new model
forensically challenging. Nevertheless, in the includes placement of iatrogenesis among the
complex scenarios of complainants filing legal multiple influences on psychological injury pre-
claims for damages, assessors need to determine sentations. In addition, it places a new concept
whether the event at issue contributed more than that I developed among the possible complica-
minimally (substantially, materially) to the psy- tions in psychological injury cases, or that of a
chological condition that might have developed conscious desperation cry for help. Also, the
post-event, and considering iatrogenesis and chapter analyzes the role of biasing effects of
related complications should be part of the com- other actors and agents in the system, such as
prehensive assessments undertaken. treatment providers, insurers, and attorneys.

Chapter Conclusions Recommendations

Summary Psychological injury and law is a burgeoning


area of study and practice that asks for an appro-
The present chapter and the last one have consid- priate ethical stance to resist its pulls and pushes.
ered causality in the field of psychological injury Often, these are implicit, and by becoming famil-
and law. The first one reviewed concepts of cau- iar with how it functions systematically, the pro-
sality that are applicable to forensic psychology fessional is better protected. Also, mental health
both in the criminal and civil contexts, including workers need to be aware of their ethical obliga-
of psychological injury and law. Also, it empha- tions to function with integrity, impartiality, and
sized the value of the biopsychosocial model in fairness (see Table 27.2).
this regard, both for understanding the actions The field of psychological injury and law can
of criminal perpetrators and the psychological develop further if it were taught in graduate pro-
effects (psychological injuries, e.g., PTSD) of grams. Young (2014a) argued that graduate edu-
survivors in civil negligence cases, such as in cation programs need to consider the appropriate
tort. The present chapter takes a broader view of fundamentals for practice in the area of psycho-
causality in the civil context of psychological logical injury and law. Students need to be made
injuries by exploring both models that attempt to aware of: (a) the scientific foundations and con-
integrate the biopsychosocial and forensic troversies that are inherent in the area; (b) the
aspects of such cases and other models related to nature of the adversarial divide in tort and other
bias, malingering, intent, deception, and possible court venues; (c) the best evidence available on
psychological disorder in claimants. In this assessment tests and procedures; and (d) also the
regard, I focus on the relatively neglected area in best empirical support for therapeutic interven-
psychology of iatrogenesis, which is a prevalent tion practice. Their practical experience should
one in medicine, and I develop a model inclusive emphasize: (a) state-of-the-art scientific knowl-
of it in understanding the full causal system in edge in the area; (b) the effect of bias in the field,
psychological injury claims. with examination of both sides of debates that
References 695

Table 27.2 American Psychological Association foren- healthy ones. I would broaden this suggestion to
sic practice guidelines: responsibilities
investigate all manners of cases that reside in the
Principle Explanation gray zone in this area relative to the other types of
Impartiality When providing expert testimony, cases (e.g., known malingering, healthy). Until
and fairness providing therapeutic services, and
so on, forensic workers strive to be
this type of research is undertaken, the research
accurate, impartial, fair, and on putative known malingerers relative to other
independent (Ethical Principles of control groups would seem to be missing critical
Psychologists and Code of Conduct groups that would enable more accurate interpre-
Standard 2.01, American
Psychological Association, 2002).
tations of the results in this type of research.
They appreciate the adversarial As for recommendations in dealing with
nature in legal systems and aim to iatrogenesis in the context of psychological inju-
treat all participants with ries, all parties in the system should be aware of
impartiality, and they also strive to
weigh all data, opinions, and rival
its potential presence and pernicious effects.
hypotheses impartially. Psychological iatrogenesis has been given little
When conducting forensic consideration in the literature compared to medi-
evaluations, forensic practitioners cal iatrogenesis. But its effects could be just as
aim for an unbiased and impartial
assessment, and they aim to avoid
harmful. Iatrogenesis is part of a multifactorial
partisan presentation of evidence complex system that patients have to learn about
that is unrepresentative, incomplete, and deal with. However, treatment providers and
or inaccurate, which might mislead others in the system dealing with patients have to
fact finders. This guideline does not
preclude an assertive presentation
be equally aware of it and related factors. The
of the data gathered and the mental health of patients deserves nothing less.
reasoning used in arriving at any Patients require best ethical practices in dealing
conclusion or professional product with them from all parties in the system involved
based on that data.
(Young, 2014a).
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business To conclude the chapter, I contend that use of
Media. Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feigning, and
response bias in psychiatric/psychological injury: the models in the present chapter, including my
Implications for Practice and court. Dordrecht, penultimate one, in understanding psychologi-
Netherlands: Springer Science + Business Media; with cal injury complainants and arriving at valid
kind permission from Springer Science + Business Media interpretations and conclusions about them is
B. V. [Table 22.1, Page 469]
consistent with the scientifically-informed,
comprehensive, and impartial approach needed
take place in the literature; and (c) training in and in assessments in the area. This approach is
use of tests having forensically-acceptable psy- expected both by professional practice stan-
chometric properties (reliability, validity, etc.) for dards and ethics and by court and related ven-
relevant populations. Continuing education ues, and is the best one to guarantee fruitful
opportunities also should emphasize these major career longevity.
themes for ethical and effective practice.
Researchers need to tackle the controversial,
contentious, and divisive issues in the field,
including the role of iatrogenesis, litigation References
distress, and so on. Young (2014a) maintained
that it appears that no research deals with: (a) American Psychiatric Association. (2013). Diagnostic
known patients who cry for help/catastrophize/ and statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM-5
(5th ed.). Washington, DC: Author.
somaticize, or express litigation distress, etc., (b) American Psychological Association. (2002). Ethical
in comparison to known or presumably known principles of psychologists and code of conduct.
malingerers and the usual control groups, e.g., American Psychologist, 57, 1060–1073.
696 27 Causality in Psychological Injury and Law: Models

Andrikopoulos, J., & Greiffenstein, M. F. (2012). Iatrogenesis. (n.d.). In Wikipedia. Retrieved April 17,
Something to talk about? The status of post-traumatic 2014, from http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Iatrogenesis
stress disorder in clinical neuropsychology. In G. J. Illich, I. (1974). Medical nemesis: The expropriation of
Larrabee (Ed.), Forensic neuropsychology: A scientific health. London: Calder & Boyars.
approach (2nd ed., pp. 365–400). New York: Oxford Iverson, G. L. (2011). Evidence-based neuropsychologi-
University Press. cal assessment of sport-related concussion. In F. M.
Bass, C., & Halligan, P. W. (2007). Illness related decep- Webbe (Ed.), Handbook of sport neuropsychology
tion: Social or psychiatric problem? Journal of the (pp. 131–154). New York: Springer.
Royal Society of Medicine, 100, 81–84. Iverson, G. L. (2012). A biopsychosocial conceptualiza-
Bass, C., & Halligan, P. W. (2014). Factitious disorders tion of poor outcome from mild traumatic brain injury.
and malingering: Challenges for clinical assessment In J. J. Vasterling, R. A. Bryant, & T. M. Keane (Eds.),
and management. The Lancet, 383, 1422–1432. PTSD and mild traumatic brain injury (pp. 37–60).
Bass, C., Halligan, P. W., & Oakley, D. A. (2003). New York: Guilford Press.
Malingering and illness deception. Oxford, UK: Iverson, G. L., & Lange, R. T. (2012). Traumatic brain
Oxford University Press. injury in the workplace. In S. S. Bush & G. L. Iverson
Bender, S. D., & Matusewicz, M. (2013). PCS, iatrogenic (Eds.), Neuropsychological assessment of work-
symptoms, and malingering following concussion. related injuries (pp. 9–67). New York: Guilford Press.
Psychological Injury and Law, 6, 113–121. Johnson, S. K. (2008). Medically unexplained illness:
Blum v. Merrell Dow Pharmaceuticals, Inc., 764 A.2d 1 Gender and biopsychosocial implications. Washington,
(2000). DC: American Psychological Association.
Boone, K. (2011). Somatoform disorders, factitious disor- Kennedy, F. (1946). The mind of the injured worker: Its
der, and malingering. In M. R. Schoenberg & J. G. effects on disability periods. Compensation Medicine,
Scott (Eds.), The little black book of neuropsychology: 1, 19–21.
A syndrome-based approach (pp. 551–565). Kirmayer, L. J., & Taillefer, S. (1997). Somatoform disor-
New York: Springer Science + Business Media. ders. In S. M. Turner & M. Hersen (Eds.), Adult psy-
Bootzin, R. R., & Bailey, E. T. (2005). Understanding pla- chopathology and diagnosis (pp. 410–472). New York:
cebo, nocebo, and iatrogenic treatment effects. Journal Wiley.
of Clinical Psychology, 61, 871–880. Koch, W. J., Douglas, K. S., Nichols, T. L., & O’Neill,
Bryant, R. A., & Harvey, A. G. (2003). The influence of M. L. (2006). Psychological injuries: Forensic assess-
litigation on maintenance of posttraumatic stress dis- ment, treatment, and law. New York: Oxford
order. The Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, University Press.
191, 191–193. McEwen, B., & Lasley, E. N. (2003). Allostatic load:
Call, J. A. (2003). Liability for psychological injury: When protection gives way to damage. Advances in
History of the concept. In I. Z. Schultz & D. O. Brady Mind-Body Medicine, 19, 29–44.
(Eds.), Psychological injuries at trial (pp. 40–64). Melton, G. D., Petrila, J., Poythress, N. G., & Slobogin, C.
Chicago, IL: American Bar Association. (2007). A closer look at the insanity defense. In G. D.
Daubert v. Merrell Dow Pharmaceuticals, Inc., 509 U.S. Melton, J. Petrila, N. G. Poythress, & C. Slobogin
579, 113 S. Ct. 2786 (1993). (Eds.), Psychological evaluations for the courts: A
Deary, V., Chalder, T., & Sharpe, M. (2007). The cogni- handbook for mental health professionals and lawyers
tive behavioral model of medically unexplained symp- (3rd ed., pp. 209–217). New York: Guilford Press.
toms: A theoretical and empirical review. Clinical Merten, T., & Merckelbach, H. (2013). Symptom validity
Psychology Review, 27, 781–797. testing in somatoform and dissociative disorders: A
Greiffenstein, M. F., & Kaufmann, P. M. (2012). critical review. Psychological Injury and Law, 6,
Neuropsychology and the law: Principles of produc- 122–137.
tive attorney-neuropsychologist relations. In G. J. Miller, H. (1961a). Accident neurosis. British Medical
Larrabee (Ed.), Forensic neuropsychology: A scientific Journal, 1, 919–925.
approach (2nd ed., pp. 23–69). New York: Oxford Miller, H. (1961b). Accident neurosis II. British Medical
University Press. Journal, 1, 992–998.
Haack, S. (2008). The whole truth and nothing but the Perret, D., & Rosen, C. A. (2011). A physician driven solu-
truth. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 32, 20–35. tion – the Association for Medical Ethics, the Physician
Hahn, R. A. (1999). Expectations of sickness: Concept payment Sunshine Act, and ethical challenges in pain
and evidence of the nocebo phenomenon. In I. Kirsch medicine. Pain Medicine, 12, 1361–1375.
(Ed.), How expectancies shape experience (pp. 333– Rees, C. (2012). Iatrogenic psychological harm. Archives
356). Washington, DC: American Psychological of Disease in Childhood, 97, 440–446.
Association. Ruff, R. M., & Jamora, C. W. (2009). Myths and mild
Hall, R. C. W., & Hall, R. C. W. (2012). Compensation traumatic brain injury. Psychology Injury and Law, 2,
neurosis: A too quickly forgotten concept? Journal of 34–42.
the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law, 40, Schatman, M. E. (2011). Editorial: The suppression of
390–398. evidence-basis in pain medicine and the physician-
References 697

driven quest to re-establish it. Pain Medicine, 12, Young, G. (2011). Erratum to: Trends in psychological/
1358–1360. psychiatric injury and law: Continuing education,
Schultz, I. Z. (2003). Psychological causality determina- practice comments, recommendations. Psycho
tion in personal injury and workers’ compensation logical Injury and Law, 4, 56–87. [Originally pub-
contexts. In I. Z. Schultz & D. O. Brady (Eds.), lished in 2010 in Psychological Injury and Law, 3,
Psychological injuries at trial (pp. 102–125). Chicago, 323–355.]
IL: American Bar Association. Young, G. (2014a). Malingering, feigning, and response
Schultz, I. Z. (2008). Disentangling disability quagmire in bias in psychiatric/psychological injury: Implications
psychological injury and law. Part I. Disability and for practice and court. Dordrecht, Netherlands:
return to work: Theories, methods and application. Springer Science + Business Media.
Psychological Injury and Law, 1, 94–102. Young, G. (2014b). Psychological injury and law II:
Schultz, I. Z., & Stewart, A. M. (2008). Disentangling dis- Implications for mental health policy and ethics.
ability quagmire in psychological injury and law. Part Mental Health Law & Policy Journal, 3, 418–470.
II. Evolution of disability models: Conceptual, meth- Young, G., & Chapman, C. R. (2007). Pain, affect, non-
odological and forensic issues. Psychological Injury linear dynamical systems, and chronic pain:
and Law, 1, 103–121. Bringing order to disorder. In G. Young, A. W.
Vanderploeg, R., Belanger, H. G., & Kaufmann, P. M. (2014). Kane, & K. Nicholson (Eds.), Causality of psycho-
Nocebo effects and mild traumatic brain injury: Legal logical injury: Presenting evidence in court
implications. Psychological Injury and Law, 7, 245–254. (pp. 197–241). New York: Springer Science +
Young, G. (2007). Causality: Concepts, issues, and rec- Business Media.
ommendations. In G. Young, A. W. Kane, & Young, G., & Kane, A. W. (2007). Causality in psychol-
K. Nicholson (Eds.), Causality of psychological ogy and law. In G. Young, A. W. Kane, & K. Nicholson
injury: Presenting evidence in court (pp. 49–86). (Eds.), Causality of psychological injury: Presenting
New York: Springer Science + Business Media. evidence in court (pp. 13–47). New York: Springer
Young, G. (2008a). Causality and causation in law, medi- Science + Business Media.
cine, psychiatry, and psychology: Progression or Young, G., Kane, A. W., & Nicholson, K. (Eds.).
regression? Psychological Injury and Law, 1, (2006). Psychological knowledge in court: PTSD,
161–181. pain, and TBI. New York: Springer Science +
Young, G. (2008b). Somatization and medically unexplained Business Media.
symptoms in psychological injury: Diagnoses and Young, G., Kane, W., & Nicholson, K. (2007). Causality
dynamics. Psychological Injury and Law, 1, 224–242. of psychological injury: Presenting evidence in court.
Young, G. (2008c). Coping in psychological injury: A New York: Springer Science + Business Media.
biopsychosocial and forensic perspective. Young, G., & Yehuda, R. (2006). Understanding PTSD:
Psychological Injury and Law, 1, 276–286. Implications for court. In G. Young, A. W. Kane, &
Young, G. (2010). Causes in the construction of causal K. Nicholson (Eds.), Psychological knowledge in
law: A psycho-ecological model. International court: PTSD, pain, and TBI (pp. 55–69). New York:
Journal of Law and Psychiatry, 33, 73–83. Springer Science + Business Media.
Stimulus–Organism–Response
Model: SORing to New Heights 28

Response) one. The model indicates that stimuli


Chapter Introduction might elicit different responses depending on the
state of the organism; that is, the organism medi-
Workers have suggested inverting the causal order ates the relationship between a stimulus and a
involving behavior by placing organism factors response. It is interesting to note that Woodworth
before stimulus ones. Moreover, contemporary (1918) entitled his book, Dynamic Psychology,
brain theory (Friston, 2010) has referred to hidden anticipating some 100 years ago contemporary
states involving the environment, as well as prob- developments in the field.
abilistic and generative Bayesian constructs Another founder of the discipline of psychology
behind sensation and perception, and so on. The also queried the validity of stimulus–response
fuzzy nature of each of the stimulus, the organism psychology. Thurstone (1923) developed a model
(or its brain), and even the response calls for a striking in its use of contemporary terminology.
more inclusive S–O–R (Stimulus–Organism– First, he indicated that, in the traditional model,
Response) model. The chapter reviews the litera- mind mediates between stimuli and response.
ture on the issues related to fuzzy stimulus, Then, he presented his model in which the per-
organism, and response, leading to presentation of son is diagrammatically represented to the left,
the S–O–R Brain/Agent/Mind/Person (BAMP) or before the stimulus rather than after it, lead-
model. Behavior is the reflection of a dynamical, ing to response. He said that “the causal sequence
self-organized, emergent, and hierarchical pro- [starts] with the person himself” (p. 355). That
cess in which (a) the structure of the environment is, the causal sequence starts with “the dynamic
does not stand outside the organism and (b) the living self” and the stimulus is considered “caus-
response of the organism is conditioned by factors ally intermediate.” The person not only utilizes
such as motivation, anticipation, and personality. incoming stimuli but also “hunts” for stimuli
(c) Moreover, the responses are complex and con- relevant to one’s ongoing personal mental life,
ditional, without a necessary determinism. including of motives. Therefore, in his model,
an external energy source, which in other models
might be labeled the stimulus, leads to an inter-
History nal stimulus and an internal hunt for an external
stimulus, thereby producing the desired external
Originally, Woodworth (e.g., 1918) developed the stimulus, and so leading to a response.
S–O–R (Stimulus–Organism–Response) model, Note that the S–O–R model is still being used
and it reflected a functionalist approach differen- in consumer psychology (see Jacoby, 2002, for a
tiated from strictly a behaviorist S–R (Stimulus– revised version). It is interesting to note that, in

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 699


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_28
700 28 Stimulus–Organism–Response Model: SORing to New Heights

this contemporary S–O–R model, organismic person and also the nature of behavior as response
factors precede stimulus ones, leading to a entity, or output. In the following, I elaborate
response. The organismic factors and stimulus further the concepts of “fuzzy” stimulus, “fuzzy”
ones are termed drives and cues, respectively, organism, and “fuzzy” response.
and the response is differentiated into hierarchies
and tendencies.
What Is a Fuzzy Stimulus?

Contemporary Theory Precursors

Fuzziness Gibson (1966, 1979/1986) developed an ecologi-


cal model of affordances in the environment to
Theories in psychology that are more contempo- counter the mechanistic view. Affordances allow
rary also refer to the ambiguity or probability of action possibilities, in the same sense as stairs
psychological phenomena. For example, Reyna allow stair climbing. The concept implicates the
and Brainerd (1995, 2011) proposed fuzzy-trace environment as meaningful, or of value in and of
theory especially for memory and other cognitive itself. Information in the environment specifies
phenomena, including cognitive development. affordances. Organisms can perceive directly
Their model is a dual-process one in which the affordances so that meaning does not originate
individual forms mental representation evidence mentally or internally. Rather than being a collec-
through either specific verbatim traces or gist tion of stimulus causes of responses, the environ-
traces, the latter of which are fuzzier representa- ment is not directly causal. Instead, it is a
tions of past events than the former. manifold of action possibilities.
Friston (2010) has proposed a unified, global The organism is an agent of action, rather
brain theory that presents a contemporary than a passive puppet. Agents have properties, as
approach to understanding the “hidden states” of does the environment, and their relations define
the environment and dynamical systems theory. affordances. The same object might have differ-
He proposed that a “free energy” principle under- ent affordances for different organisms, or even
lies behavioral (action, perception, learning) and for one organism at different developmental
brain activity. Under the free-energy principle, epochs. That being said, affordances do not
behavior and brain work according to “optimiza- change as the needs of the organism change.
tion,” which concerns either value (e.g., expected They are ecological properties of the environ-
reward or utility), or its complement, that of “sur- ment, not reflections of mind. They are extracted
prise” (prediction error, expected cost). or obtained information, and they do not impose
or cause behavior; as agent, the organism exhib-
its constraint over behavior, or control of it (in
Comment the sense of regulation).
Reed (1982, 1985, 1993, 1996) developed fur-
Just as the philosophical and epistemological ther Gibson’s ecological model in terms of
stances that one could adopt in psychology are agency. He contended that an organism is in
subject to debate, and might be considered charge of its own actions, having self-control.
“messy,” the same appears to apply to the funda- Intentions are patterns of action organization.
mental notions in psychology of stimulus, per- According to Withagen, de Poel, Araújo, and
son, and response. Is the stimulus an external Pepping (2012), the mechanistic perspective of
energy impingement that the person faithfully behavior dominated psychology until more eco-
apperceives and processes into matched adaptive logical ones developed. In the mechanistic world-
response, with the three components in this view, mind and behavior are understood as chains
behavioral formula distinct? Recent research is of causes and effects, e.g., stimuli in the environ-
questioning the separation of environment and ment cause responses.
What Is a Fuzzy Stimulus? 701

Model relegated out by inhibition. [Note that Friston


(e.g., 2010) has developed a hierarchical predic-
Perception Clark (2013a) has presented a tive processing model that includes action.
potentially unified science of action and mind. It For Friston, both perception and action are
is based on a hierarchical generative model, or probabilistically-based activities, and their link-
hierarchical prediction approach, to the brain as ages extend to cognition.]
machine unifying perception and action. In order
to minimize prediction error, the brain is a pre- Surprisal Another major aspect of Clark’s
dictive machine in the sense of constantly trying (2013a) Bayesian approach to core human func-
to match incoming sensory inputs with top-down tions concerns situated agents. For example, per-
predictions or expectations, in a delicate balance ception and action work together to reduce
with bottom-up processes. “surprisal” (“surprise” in Friston, 2010). Surprisal
The world presents as perturbing signal measures the implausibility of a sensory state in
sources that higher-level brain systems model light of a given model of the environment.
perceptually in order to predict their “hidden” Perception acts to reduce surprisal by matching
causal structure based on created multiple, linked input and prior prediction (expectation). Action
perceptual models. As predictive errors arise, the acts to reduce it by altering the environment
models are revised. The models are probabilistic, (even bodily movement) so that sensory input
signal-based, and construct-driven inferences. matches prediction. Therefore, both perception
The body receives and reacts to the signals and, and action selectively sample and actively sculpt
in perception, the causes for the effects are the environment, as in situated or embodied cog-
inferred, but as part of multiple probability distri- nition. We behave in order to self-structure infor-
butions. That is, even for a single effect, multiple mation flow through our actions, which allows
causes are possible. Models of distal causes are for learning and inference.
not just constructed from accumulated bottom-up
data, because the brain acts top-down to create Social At the social level, our cognition becomes
models with best fit to the data. socially situated so that prediction error construc-
It is in this sense that the perceptual models tion is mutual, communal, synchronized, shared,
created by the brain are considered generative. and distributed. Also, in order to create the best
Generative models attempt to capture, in the sta- models of reality, we use culture to refine our pre-
tistical structure of stimulus arrays in schemata, dictions, launching them only to have them re-
the “causal matrix” responsible for the structure. enter. The inputs are designed, producing
The models are hierarchical (multilevel, bidirec- “designer environments” that engineer socially
tional) in that the causal web that is created bal- our permeable cognition, allowing its intergen-
ances in an ongoing fashion lower-level top-down erational transmission on social scaffolds (a con-
tracks or trains of constructed data. Sensory data cept similar to neuroconstructivism; Mareschal
become selected, sculpted, predictive codes, or et al., 2007).
“virtual” renditions. Perception is not a map of
signals and inner state; rather, it is a constructed Comment The commentaries to the Clark
state that, at its base, is probabilistic, predictive, (2013a) article serve to expand its scope. For
and inferential. example, Seth and Critchley (2013) attempted to
bridge it with emotion; and Hirsh, Mar, and
Prediction Prediction takes place in multiple lev- Peterson (2013) considered adding narrative con-
els of the processing hierarchy, which are locked struction. Clark (2013b) concluded that the
in an integrated “predictive coding regime.” The action-oriented predictive processing inherent in
hypothesis that is becoming percept, or driving his model constitutes a mechanism linked to core
signal, makes the best predictions, with others forms of brain-based processing.
702 28 Stimulus–Organism–Response Model: SORing to New Heights

Others social cue integration. Probabilities that are more


neutral than negative might be overinflated (for
Social Zaki (2013) proposed a common cue example, P|anger (my example) derives from a
integration framework for physical perception neutral stare). Textual cues might be misjudged,
and social cognition (e.g., perceiving the mind of and priors might be overestimated (elevated)
others) despite the lower processing level (e.g., P|anger arouses an aggressive response). In
involved in physical perception. Research in the the example provided, aggression even could be
former has indicated that perception involves a provoked inappropriately to a disordered or
“pervasive” multimodal, multisensory unifica- delinquent degree.
tion or integration, which can be modeled by
Bayesian probabilities. Development As for precursors of probability
In a social process integration perspective on estimation, Frankenhuis, Gergely, and Watson
social cues in social cognition, streams are no (2013) referred to children using conditional
longer considered separate or isolated, but are probability estimates of environmental harsh-
integrated and co-activated (e.g., mentalizing and ness and unpredictability. In “prospective” prob-
experience sharing), and with shared brain ability, infants might observe that maternal
regions associated with them. “Real-world” smiles follow cooing. In “retrospective” proba-
social cognition involves complex social cues bility, the estimate is about the cooing preceding
that require difficult, “noisy” task performance, the smiling. Infants not only engage in contin-
so that cue integration, or interactions between gency detection like this in their immediate envi-
multiple social signals and social information ronment, but also they use it as a guide in long
processing streams, is required. term development. Good prediction facilitates
That signals are noisy and probabilistic sug- control; however, in compromised environments
gests that Bayesian models can apply to them. (harsh, unpredictable), control is variable.
Objects and events produce perceptual signals Therefore, in terms of evolutionary life-history
having conditional probabilities [e.g., P strategies, early environmental predictions might
(red|engine) refers to the probability of seeing provide impetus toward adapting fast or slow
“red” given a “fire engine”]. To form perceptual evolutionary strategies (e.g., early female men-
cues at the level of Bayesian probabilities, the arche and reproduction).
perceiver integrates probabilities such as these
with prior knowledge (e.g., P|engine), and the Affordances Withagen et al. (2012) added to
perceptual cues themselves have probabilities this rich modeling of the environment in relation
associated with them. to behavior by postulating that affordances do
The latter probabilities associated with the not simply suggest action possibilities but also
perceptual inferences are each proportional to might invite them or even prompt or urge them,
the probabilities connecting the inferred percep- as in immediately drawing the person to them.
tion to the sensory cues encountered in relation This suggests that afforded invitations exist in a
to priors (e.g., P(engine|red, siren) × P(red|engin mutualistic relationship between the organism
e) × P(siren|engine) × P(engine)). Similarly, judg- and the environment, in light of the multi-
ing that a gold-medal winner is crying for joy dimensional properties of both. In this concep-
and not happiness is a probabilistic inference tion, although affordances are construed as
that can be represented by P (happy|crying, med properties of objects, their invitations reflect the
al) × P(crying|happy) × P(happy|medal) × P relationship between object and organism.
(happy). Invitations vary with properties of the organism
Zaki (2013) labeled perceivers as “lay” as it develops in context or culture and from its
Bayesians. He concluded that individuals with evolutionary history. Invitations can be declined,
social impairments might have difficulty with and so do not constitute causes.
What Is a Fuzzy System? 703

What Is a Fuzzy Organism? Marken and Mansell (2013) addressed the


fuzziness in psychology in a similar way. They
By “fuzzy” organism, I refer to the “messy” pro- argued that the traditional model of behavior,
cesses involved in dealing with incoming infor- being caused by events in the environment, does
mation and preparing outgoing response. Clearly, not account for either feedback effects of the
in this regard, there is no one-to-one relationship. behavior or its goal, which is to protect from dis-
For example, the input into the organism is both turbances (Powers, 1973, 1978). Organisms are
at least partially constructed by the organism and considered control systems acting to preserve
also enters and alters the processing machinery (goal) states, so that behavior is the control of
of the organism. Moreover, the latter machinery perception. Causality runs circularly rather than
is by no means a technologically sophisticated linearly, or in a closed (negative feedback) loop
and unchanging smooth-running engine with a in which sensory input is simultaneously both a
primary central command input analyzer and cause and an effect of output, the goal of which is
response generator. There are candidate primary to counter or resist disturbance. Causality does
components in these regards, such as self- not start or end with genes, but with the whole
regulation or control and its constituent major behavioral system.
tools, including attention and memory (e.g., Michel (2013) proposed a similar model
working memory), inhibition, and other execu- from his work in developmental psychology.
tive skills (such as set shifting). Moreover, the Genes carry information and are involved in
processor has important affective components, behavioral causality but neither in a governing
too, including affective schemas and filters nor primarily responsible way. [Yet the power of
related to temperamental and experiential influ- biological argumentation about behavior is not
ences. Given the potential of the socioaffective/ subsiding. For example, Peterson, Sznycer, Sell,
motivational aspect of the organism to affect Cosmides, and Tooby (2013) advocated for an
deployment of other processing components, evolutionary perspective on the politics of
individual differences in motivation, self- resource distribution.]
regulation, and related components constitute the Generally, we can conclude that behavior is
quintessential fuzzy component of the organism. not simply a linear output after mediation of the
effects of external stimuli, but even might be the
factor that determines what the incoming stimuli
What Is Fuzzy Response? might be. The mechanisms of adaptation do not
separate stimulus–organism–response, and mod-
The model of stimulus in the external world, els about their relationship should be constructed
organism as mediator of its apperception and from that perspective.
preparation of the response, and the response
itself as a third fuzzy step in behavior rests
increasingly on contemporary scientific findings. What Is a Fuzzy System?
That is, as with the discussion above of the fuzzy
nature of stimulus and organism, response pro- Nonlinear dynamical systems theory (NLDST)
cesses are messy themselves, with ongoing provides the answer. NLDST is a theory that is
online adjustments to situational conditions and well-suited to the describing and explaining all
planning priorities. In systems and network mod- types of change (Thelen & Smith, 1994). There
els, responses are part of behavioral states and are variants of the theory, including catastrophe
cannot be separated from them. They emerge as theory, that have been applied to psychological
confluences that might not even be predictable phenomena (e.g., Witkiewitz & Marlatt, 2007).
and reflective of ongoing state, but as novel, self- Moreover, NLDST is split into at least two major
organized entities far-from-equilibrium, and camps, with the major difference concerning
nonetheless (or rather, especially) adaptive. whether states are always soft-assembled de novo
704 28 Stimulus–Organism–Response Model: SORing to New Heights

bottom-up in an ongoing fashion without, as well, Revised S–O–R Model


hierarchically more complex levels that work top-
down, or whether states can have reciprocally Model
bottom-up and top-down influences. The latter
approach is more conducive to the development of Figure 28.1 presents a revised S–O–R model that
increasingly complex states in the system analo- maintains the standard sequence of critical com-
gous to those of stages in the developing human p o n e n t s — s t i m u l u s – o rg a n i s m – r e s p o n s e .
(e.g., van Geert, 2012). Finally, there are models However, the model makes clear that stimulus
that are quite similar to NLDST ones, in particular, and organism properties are co-active in eliciting
connectionist models (Tryon, 2012). Both models response. The model is general enough to apply
lead to empirical predictions that have been con- to humans, animals, and any biological entity,
firmed developmentally. However, NLDST often organ, or agent, including the brain or neuron.
is applied to a broader range of areas, even abiotic The model is presented in terms of boundaries
(but for human case, often it is applied metaphori- between stimulus and organism, but the literature
cally rather than mathematically). indicates that the boundary is fuzzy, as are stimu-
Some cardinal features of NLDST include lus and organism properties, e.g., in the sense of
self-organization, hierarchical organization, probability models to describe them, and even in
emergence, attractor formation, far-from- their active generation of models as they function
equilibrium, and system perturbation. Systems or have an impact. In this sense, the response end
are wholes in which the whole is greater than the of the S–O–R model is equally probabilistic; that
sum of the parts. The wetness of water (H2O) is, responses are neither definitive nor fixed
cannot be predicted by knowing the properties of exclusively by prior events. As in NLDST, likeli-
the component hydrogen and oxygen atoms. As hoods in state positioning in state response
the parts (elements) coalesce into configurations, regimes are indeterministic proximally even if
patterns, or higher-order structures, they do so they function deterministically according to
without a preprogrammed template or central global attractors.
generator governing the assembly. Rather, the The proposed revised S–O–R model includes
elements converge on states that are dynamically feedback mechanisms that can either amplify or
open, graceful, and least dissipative of entropy, de-amplify stimuli/state patterns that are in prog-
avoiding disequilibrium and disintegration. The ress (positive and negative feedback, respec-
states might have multiple hierarchical levels, tively). Moreover, feedback mechanisms have
also for which the wholes are not predicted from feedforward properties when they function, in
the parts. The self-organization toward unpre- terms of anticipations or expectations that cana-
dictable patterns, states, or other dynamics is lize/filter stimuli toward desired/predicted
referred to as emergence. States might take the options. Priors in state are not simply static inputs
form of attractors, or a set range toward which into a processing system, in that they are colored
specified variables in the system move at multi- by feedback mechanisms such as these toward
ple points over time, even if slightly different co-active shaping and changing tendencies of the
each time. Attractors tend to stability and resist adapting organism/system.
system perturbations, but when at far-from- The final general aspect of the revised S–O–R
equilibrium, they risk variability, transition, and model concerns its adaptive adjustment over con-
gravitation to new attractor ensembles. As states text and time. Organisms/organizations/organs
self-organize this way in systems into attractor (Os) have evolved to optimize adaptation to con-
formations, there might be more than one to tingencies in environment, and they do so dynam-
which the system visits, and new ones are gener- ically as they and it changes over time (changing
ated at bifurcation or other transition points; either developmentally or in terms of altered
some might be maladaptive, as in chronic pain complexity, depending on the type of “O”
states/attractors (Young, 2011). involved).
Revised S–O–R Model 705

S O R
Stimulus Organism Response
Starting point (organization/ organ) Reflex
Sensation (individual, entity) (taxis; tropism)
Sensory input Repertoire
Signal Ontogenesis (of behavior)
Sampled data (development, transformation) (Re)action
Situation (proaction)
Stress(or) Self-Organization Representation
Schema (dynamical) Redescription
Surround Relationship
State Optimization Role
(existing) (adaptation) (Re)adjustment
System perturbation (Re)organization
Survival Orchestra (Re)equilibration
Score (orchestration) Emergence
(musical) (new state)
[input] Processing Reproduction
(patterning) (health; evolution, parenting)
(programming) the 3Rs:
Responsibility
(and respect, reason)
Rhythm
(rhapsody, reggae, symphony)
[output]

B P
A M
Brain Agent Mind Person
Biology Actor Mental Perception
(genes) Appraiser (e.g., belief; Processing
Body Adaptor sense of free Personality/Self
(e.g., neurons, Assembly will) Problem
lobes, (network) Model/ solving/Coping
hemispheres, Attractor Modeling Peoples
connections) Activation/ Memory (gender, culture)
Inhibition Motivation
Coordination Mood

Context & Time

Fig. 28.1 The S–O(BAMP)–R causal psychological presently constituted and forecasting future environments
model: from stimulus and schema to response and repre- in which the organism (person) might live.
sentation. This figure presents an expanded S–R (stimu- The environment provides information to which the
lus–response) model of behavior that includes organismic organism must adapt in the present to survive and facili-
(person, O) mediational components. The model is tate reproduction (presently or later on, depending on
referred to as the S–O–R one, with added subcomponents developmental level, if this applies to the organism). The
expanding the O portion (BAMP – S–O(BAMP)–R organism builds schemas to represent the environmental
model). information serving as filters in dealing with new incom-
The stimulus component of the model expands the ing information. The schemas might simply be patterns of
immediate instigator of behavior into a suite of potential metabolic activity that have been constructed or entrained
initiators. The fundamental starting point might not only by previous environmental conditions and encounters. Or,
be a simple stimulus but also a whole context (situation) for more advanced organisms, they could include patterns
or even a complex stressor. of neuronal and central or nervous system activity.
Stimuli, situation, and stressor are never fully objec- Together, no matter what their complexity, the schemas of
tive or empirical, given the important role of perception an organism contribute to constructing its current state.
and cognitive filter in behavior. There might be feed Organisms constitute systems of stimulus sensing,
(backward, forward) mechanisms that alter the objective stimulus modulation, and stimulus responsiveness. Their
physics or signals in an incoming array. Sensation and current state both resists reactivity and change to incom-
sensory input might not reflect, already at this step in ing input (system perturbations) and is actively open to
behavior and its mediation, the empirical reality of the their reception, mediation, and potential change, even to
surround. Sampling of input has beneficial adaptive (evo- new or emergent state and system configurations. Systems
lutionary) advantages in assessing the environment as function both to adapt to changes in stimuli and to change
706 28 Stimulus–Organism–Response Model: SORing to New Heights

Fig. 28.1 (continued)


as they adapt to them, all in the service of survival and cal system transformation, a minor perturbation can initiate
reproduction in an evolutionary sense. Organismic stimuli the said transformation. When the change in a system is
sensing, mediating, and reactive mechanisms could be unpredictable from knowledge of its components and the
considered the equivalent of a symphonic orchestra con- incoming input or perturbation, we refer to emergence of a
ducting a systemic and adaptive integration of its many new state in its phase space.
components in order to arrive at an aesthetic, artistic, or Systems do not function teleologically with a known,
holistically functioning outcome. In this sense, the stimuli presumably more adaptive, functional, or complex end-
of the environment, at least in the way perceived and con- point. These latter outcomes of systems transformation are
structed by the organism from the empirics of stimuli not inscribed in systems in any way. However, as systems
qualities, could be considered the dynamical score that gravitate to optimal solutions to their state structure in
inputs into the producing component of the orchestral ongoing context, the solutions reached need to be graceful,
system. Behavior is a wonderful adaptive outcome of an fit the context, efficient, and adaptive in an ongoing sense
exquisitely evolved “scientific” machine with rhythmic, and also in an evolutionary sense, if that is applicable.
musical, esthetic, and “artistic” structure and adaptivity. In this sense, systems need to be plastic and surround-
The O component of the S–O(BAMP)–P model refers responsive. At the same time, they need to be able to keep
to more than an organism. At one extreme, it refers also to their integrity and coherent adaptive functionality that has
components of the organism, its organs (or even organ- worked to date. To help in this regard, systems need to
elles), if you will. At the other extreme, it refers also to engage in forecasting what should work in upcoming envi-
aggregates of organisms into groups, such as organizations ronments. There is a constant balancing of and struggle
or other entities. The individual (component) in the model between seeking equilibrium and also degrees of change
could be either a stand-alone figure or part of a collective. as systems enter disequilibrium. Optimization refers to the
Either way, it is the focal agent or actor in the system need to balance well these opposing tendencies, adapt well
involved. For more complex species, organisms refer to to ongoing contextual parameters and their change, and
individual members. They might have individuating psy- find pathways and solutions that are fit for survival and
chological attributes. For mammals, and especially human reproduction, both in the present niche and in future ones
and nonhuman primates, this is especially the case. We that might be encountered (and predicted).
then refer to a person, persons, a people, and peoples. To use the music analogy given above, if the behav-
Organisms that are more advanced develop. This ioral system can be characterized as a symphonic produc-
could refer both to individual members of a species/ tion and its support mechanisms, the organism aspect of
group/structure, or their components. Development is the S–O(BAMP)–R model is analogous to the orchestra.
termed ontogenesis, for example, when it is contrasted It needs the stimulus score to play its music, and the sym-
with phylogenesis in evolution. Organisms transform, in phony made in consequence constitutes the response or
general. Even when they resist change, they transform. output component of the orchestral process, but it could
For example, their structure and behavior might be con- not be produced without the orchestra.
servatively strengthened in ongoing configuration after However, the orchestra in this system does not have a
perturbation, which is still a type of transformation. conductor or a chief orchestrator. System control resides
In their moment-to-moment adaptation, organisms are in the totality of the system, its components, its levels, its
not static, but they constantly sample the environment, structure, its functionality, and its behavior, as well as the
test it and its structure and function, and so on. They stimuli, context, and surround involved in it. In the human
achieve equilibrium by constant, ongoing microadapta- behavioral system, we might think that we ourselves have
tions, and, if not closed nor inherently static and rigidly ultimate authority and decision-making (and follow-
fixed, they attune to the constant microchanges in the through) power. However, we ourselves constitute but
environment. one element in the system, albeit perhaps the most impor-
Organisms (organs, organization, etc.) that are open tant one.
systems often function according to nonlinear dynamical Systems have products as outputs, but they arrive at
system forces. They self-organize without influences of their outcomes through processes and their mechanisms.
preformed templates or central control mechanisms, but These, too, are in constant development and alteration, or
constantly adjust and adapt online. Their state at any at the edge of change, as with brain growth and its change
moment is not the continuation of a previous state but an in the human case. The O portion of the S–O(BAMP)–R
ongoing restructuring and configuration of all the internal model is a processor as much as a producer. To use the
elements and external impacts involved. If the present state music analogy, we orchestrate behavior through the
resembles the previous one, it is because the reassembly of orchestration process that manages us and that we man-
the system has arrived at the same optimally adaptive solu- age. The program involved is not inherent to the system,
tion as had fit the previous one. That being said, system or fixed, but responsive, adaptive, changeable, and liable
states might change with time, and radically so. The system to growth as much as the production aspect of behavior.
could self-organize away from the structure of a prior state, In the end, systems are vibrant wholes greater than the
and sometimes this takes place even with minor input sum of their parts. They create and live patterns that are
change, as in the so-called butterfly effect. If systems are more than their components, inputs, and outputs. They
already structured far-from-equilibrium at the point of radi- monitor output, they even change with predictions of out-
Revised S–O–R Model 707

Fig. 28.1 (continued)


put, and they are pattern machines nonpareil. In living and activation as behavior adapts moment-to-moment
systems, the patterns achieve a musicality, a rhythm, and online (micro) (and even long term (macro) through coor-
even grand symphonies from neural firing patterns to dinated executive control (planning) and behavioral
behavioral output designs. It is our responsibility, or at processes).
least each of us who are so capable, of having ourselves The M portion of the BAMP model in S–O(BAMP)–R
and also those around us reach these levels, instead of model refers to the mind, in particular. Once more, even
wading in self-indulgence and having the other succumb nonliving systems might have a “mind,” e.g., in their
to the adversities and tragedies of life. organizational function. Mind generates product (models)
The figure elaborates on the organism component of through process (modeling). Models might be lower-
the S–O–R model by referring to BAMP, or Brain, order cognitive or even sensorimotor schemas. They
Agent, Mind (Model/Modeling), and Person. B stands could refer to higher-order outputs, such as representa-
for biology, in general, at least for living systems; for tions and even hypotheses, theories, and scientific mod-
nonliving ones such as organizations, they still have a els. Medium-range models refer to beliefs, thoughts, and
“basics” through their self-organizing activity. Whether, so on. Cognition is subserved by memory and propped by
living or nonliving, organisms have bodies, or a struc- motivation and mood. It is a complex output influenced
tural morphology and energetic input–output relations to by brain, body, and all aspects mental and related
keep them functioning. For an actual brain, the neurons, constituents.
regions, and their pathways constitute the components The P in the BAMP of S–O(BAMP)–R model refers
or structural architecture. However, the dynamic neural especially to the person who does the behaving. The per-
connections or networks that they form are equally son does not respond directly to stimuli but perceives and
important. modulates them as they are processed. Personal factors
The A in the BAMP model component of the S–O–R affect the processing, such as through personality, mood,
model refers to the organism as agent. Agents act based memory, attentional skills, and problem solving and cop-
on information to produce adaptive outcomes. Rather ing approaches. The individual has varied capacities and
than functioning passively in this regard, they are active temperament, and her or his unique constellation navi-
contributors to the process, appraising with filters the gates the stimulus perception and related response output
input, organizing it (e.g., chunking), and also organizing function in individual ways, yet with group memberships
responses, while using feedback and feedforward mecha- and considerations influencing and molding the system.
nisms to help refine the system and anticipate its upcom- These include powerful influences of culture, gender,
ing needs or likely environment. The agent is the critical age, majority/minority, ethnic status, disability status,
adaptor, but is not the sole seat of control, and never dis- and so on.
charges its control function without consideration of and The last component of the S–O–R complex of the
participation in context, attuning to it. present model of stimulus–response connection clarifies
Agents in systems could be whole living organisms, the R or response component. Behavior output might be
organizations of individuals, or parts of either. In models simple in terms of reflexes or related functions but also it
of human behavior, agents are not necessarily individual might be complex in terms of repertoires of actions or
people. Agents are constituted by networks and they orga- representations (or redescriptions) of action. It might be
nize networks. Generally, network or pattern assembly is social in terms of role and relationship behaviors or com-
soft, or tuned to the exigencies of the environment, and plex to the point of large organizational output. Behavior
they are flexible. Assemblies might articulate apparently is not necessarily a passive response and, indeed, often is
constant patterns, but they re-assemble at each moment. active, pro-active, prospective, and engineering of the
They might reconfigure in the same way as prior assem- environment, social relationships, and self toward cre-
bly patterns when they are the most adaptive, which often ative and successful adaptation. We adjust and readjust,
is the case. In NLDST language, systems form attractors, organize and reorganize, and equilibrate and re-equilibrate
or regions in their state space to which systems flow con- constantly and even collectively. States solidify, modify,
stantly at the global level even if local or specific changes or even alter in full, realizing new, emergent qualitative
in system functioning are dynamically flexible and unpre- states. We survive (healthily) and reproduce in our behav-
dictable directly. ior. We have evolved this way and develop this way, for
One cohering function that cuts across agent (person), example, toward and through parenting.
brain, belief (mind), and behavior concerns activation/ The 3 R’s might be reading, writing, and arithmetic,
inhibition coordination. Young (2011) considered this but they are also giving respect, using reason, and taking
interplay a unifying mechanism in understanding the dif- responsibility. The challenge to do so is constant and, in
ferent levels of functioning within and across brain and this regard, we undertake and rededicate to multiple re-
behavior. At all levels, activations generate adaptive activ- responsibilities (Young, 2011). Whatever our culture, the
ity and also inhibitions coordinated with it to control rhythm of our life becomes a rhapsody to the extent we
interference. The universal mechanism involved is not make it so, everything else being equal. Our R’s to S’s
about inhibition alone, which is necessary to be sure, but should always aim for such heights, both for us and oth-
is about the subtle interdigitated links between inhibition ers. Partly adapted from Young (2011), Fig. 2.11, p. 43
708 28 Stimulus–Organism–Response Model: SORing to New Heights

The overall label that I used to represent the pres- Organism/Organ/Organization The mediator
ent revised S–O–R model is S–O(BAMP)–R. This between stimuli and response is not a passive
acronym represents the multiple types of “S”s receptacle, but a dynamic, active, filtering and
involved in the model and the multiple types or constructing one that aims at facilitating adaptive
“R”s. The Ss and Rs in the model are far removed prediction forward in time so that, in conse-
from the classic stimulus and response formulation quence, it works backward in dealing with stim-
in that, in each case, they reflect the multidimen- uli. The complex just described indicates that the
sionality and fuzziness that is evident therein. organism and its environmental context consti-
Moreover, I have qualified the O component of the tute a quintessential example of a system.
model by BAMP because many of the multiple With respect to dynamical systems theory and
components involved are readily represented by other nonlinear models applied to behavior, the
words beginning with B, A, M, and P. individual’s behavior and relations to the environ-
In terms of the particulars of the revised ment constitute a state in the state space of its tra-
S–O–R model, in the following I analyze in detail jectories as it transforms in response to system
each of the S, O, and R terms. This leads to pre- perturbations. The latter might be quite minor, as in
sentation of the BAMP portion of the model. the butterfly effect, but still lead to massive, quali-
tative change, e.g., shifts in state to different or
higher-order attractors (basins to which the sys-
Stimuli tem’s trajectory repeatedly gravitates globally
despite minor variations locally; there might be one
According to the Gibsonian perspective, stimuli to several attractors in adapted living systems).
exist as affordances in the environment and they To remind, in this revised S–O–R model, the
are not simply constructed de novo by the organ- entity that processes the input to produce an out-
ism. Stimuli consist of dynamic properties, such put might be an individual organism, or a collec-
as differential arrays, fields, and forces. These are tion into a group. Also, it might be a working
received, sensed, and perceived, depending on structure of the individual or group, such as a
the complexity of the organism, organization, or social (business, political, cultural) organization.
organ involved. They constitute sensory input, Finally, it might be an organ of the entity. In the
signals, or sampled data. They are part of a wider living case, this would concern especially brains
situation, context, or niche. They might be in more complex organisms. Also, it would con-
appraised as stressors, including life-threatening cern the networks of neurons and other intercon-
or otherwise dangerous ones. The organism or nections in the active brain. Organs also refer to
organ transforms the stimulus properties into neurons themselves, which are no longer under-
receptive fields, neuronal or network firings and, stood as passive transmission devices but also as
ultimately, some form of integration or abstrac- active and integrative responders to incoming
tion, including even in the so-called concept cells signals and tonically active cells. Indeed, they
or grandmother cells (e.g., to integrate firings possess thousands of synapses so that their orga-
related to the hand, Quiroga, 2012). In humans, nizational and informational capacities are mas-
the first abstractions after reflexes are termed sive and complexly distributed in parallel, as
schemas, for example, in the infant’s sensorimo- much as the neuronal networks or cell assemblies
tor schemas in Piagetian theory. of which they might be a part. Further, neurons
are actively in communication with glial cells
(astrocytes) that not only provide support but
Organism also constitute a parallel transmission engine,
albeit slower than in the case of neurons. The
Introduction “O” is for organism and related integration of neurons and astrocytes in coupled
terms, but also for optimization and orchestra. In arrangements at synapses is referred to as the
the following, I review each of these aspects. “tripartite neuron” (De Pittà et al., 2012).
Revised S–O–R Model 709

Whatever the entity—organism, organization, The concept of optimization is not found


or organ—it transforms. In the human and mam- directly in NLDST, but it relates to the one of
malian case, in particular, we refer to the change ongoing search for equilibrium and interference
process as development or ontogenesis. But all with entropic disorganization. Moreover, the
living organisms adapt and change as they engage work of Friston (2010) on brain theory (free
in commerce with the environment or surround. energy, “surprise,” etc.) has presented optimiza-
Groups and organizations change, as well. Aside tion as the common construct underlying diverse
from progressive change, the change could be brain theories. To conclude, from an optimization
regressive, or it could involve resistance to perspective, stimuli, information, bits, sensory
change in the solidification of state despite ongo- input, data, signals, sensations, situations, stress-
ing input, which in a certain sense is a type of ors, and so on, are highly selective and focused
change relative to prior state given that, in a sys- toward optimizing adaptation, survival, and repro-
tem, state is reconfigured constantly and its duction. They compose or reflect patterns, in that
apparent maintenance in form and characteristics the patterns self-organize and emerge in states
simply is a repetition of the best adaptive pattern beyond what can be predicted by the properties of
or configuration in the present context of the state the inputs themselves. The organism/organiza-
compared to the prior one. tion/organ together constitutes a supreme creator
of patterns (patterner) but without pre-existing
Optimization Intelligence is defined as involv- programs to guide the way. Novel states arise out
ing adaptation to the environment (Sternberg, of the matrix of elemental interactions, including
2012). Evolution concerns adaptive selection of at higher, more complex levels.
gene-supported traits of the phenotype that better
allow for survival and reproduction. Cognitive Orchestra As for a good metaphor for the
behavioral therapy involves working on mal- S–O–R mediating mechanism of the system
adaptive thoughts. However, contemporary con- involved, it concerns musical production, which
cepts of adaptation in any of these spheres have begins with a stimulus score, continues with an
transformed the concept of adaptation to a orchestra that orchestrates the music; and also the
dynamic, even pro-active one, e.g., intelligence is production could constitute a symphony inclu-
about altering the environment, and not just pas- sive of its rhythms. This metaphor leads to pre-
sively adapting (Sternberg, 2012); genes involve sentation of details of the response component of
correlated gene–environment interactions, e.g., the present model.
active evocative ones (Jaffee, 2011); and psycho-
therapy involves indirect facilitated change, as in
solution-focused therapy (see Young, 1997). Response
Evolutionary theory has avoided using the
term optimization, because adaptation to the About the response component of the revised
environmental niche should not involve one S–O–R model, I have indicated that it includes a
“best,” qualitatively superior, or complex way. range of responses possible, from the most sim-
However, a rejiggling of the concept so that it ple (reflex) to the most complex (responsibility,
equates with the traditional understanding of reason, respect; Sternberg, 2012). Out of a vast
adaptation should be considered. For example, repertoire of behavior, the entity responds in
workers have developed dynamical evolutionary reaction, action, or proaction. The response
models (e.g., Badcock, 2012) and genes in their might be mediated by a simpler abstraction, such
interactions with the environment often lead to as a schema or network, but more advanced rep-
alternate or secondary phenotypes that optimize resentations (redescriptions) might be involved.
survival and reproduction in difficult circum- Responses could be individual or social (relations,
stances (life-history theory; Belsky & Pluess, roles) and, ultimately, they need to be mature,
2009a; Simpson & Belsky, 2008). generative, and physically or psychologically
710 28 Stimulus–Organism–Response Model: SORing to New Heights

healthy in order to permit better adaptation and Finally, certain alleles (in a process of differ-
also to facilitate prospering in the long term. ential susceptibility) might lead to phenotypic
Responses entail new adaptations of the sys- susceptibilities that are not only maladaptive
tem to the changing stimuli parameters and how (e.g., increased antisociality in deleterious envi-
they are processed. There is readjustment/reorga- ronments) but also could be quite adaptive (e.g.,
nization and requilibration and, hopefully, in a advantageously developed in supportive environ-
constructive way. There is emergence in the con- ments) because the susceptibilities act to gener-
fluence of, or engagement with, the environment, ally increase volatility to the environment or the
entity, and response, leading to new system reaction range (Belsky & Pluess, 2009a, 2009b;
states. The differentiation and integration of the independent of any main effect in positive or
states involved feed back into the environmental negative direction that supportive or adverse
context, stimuli, and flow in which the entity is environments might elicit). This type of G × E
embedded, streamlining an increased probability interaction illustrates the dynamic interaction of
of better adaptation and optimization as the (liv- genes, environment, and development. New
ing) process continues. models have emerged in this regard referred to as
G × E × D models.
The brain is an exquisitely complex organ,
Further Details from neurons and networks, to pathways and
lobes, to hemispheres and connections. It has
Introduction The bottom portion of Fig. 28.1 been referred to as being constituted by the
provides further details of the entity involved as it “Connectome” (Sporns, 2011, 2012). In a reduc-
engages in the processing and responding to tionist perspective, behavior can be considered as
environmental stimuli and their schematic direct reflection of physiological activity of the
abstractions. In the human case, and for advanced body and brain. There is no intermediate engine
animal forms, the nervous system is the seat of or homunculus, no self apart from the workings
input stimuli processing and of output respond- of the material action of neurons, neurotransmit-
ing. The body and brain develop because of ters, and so on, and their interaction. The brain is
genes, environment, and their interaction. The comprised of quadrillions of connections, and it
interaction might involve Gene × Environment is a computational workhorse that surpasses any
(G × E) interactions in which certain alleles in the robot or artificial intelligence (AI) program,
context of certain environments produce out- except in speed and factors related to it. However,
comes different than those deriving from any the brain is an organ subject to dynamical pro-
other genetic–environmental combination (or cesses, such as has been described by Friston
different from the outcome of either acting pri- (2010). Just as emergent phenomena can arise in
marily alone; main effects). behavioral system states, similar constructions
However, genes have their effects through obtain from brain activity. Barrett (Barrett, 2012;
probabilistic epigenetic processes and through Barrett & Bliss-Moreau, 2009) has referred to
several levels of the developmental manifold, “psychological primitives” that constitute the
from proteins, to nervous systems, to behavior building blocks of behavior (e.g., core affects).
(Gottlieb, 2007). Moreover, contemporary They might not be as complex as advanced rea-
approaches to epigenesis (Meaney, 2010) are soning and emotional processes, but they are
overturning traditional understanding of how emergent in their way and allow for further emer-
genes work, because genes can be “silenced” in gence of more complex psychological phenom-
their promoter regions by DNA methylation and ena (e.g., thinking and “affecting”).
other processes, e.g., involving histones. Further,
epigenetically-silenced genes can transmit their B In the BAMP component of the Organismic
marks or stamps across generations. (O) portion of the revised S–O–R model, the “B”
Reflections 711

portion of the organism refers to the biological Individual differences are shaped by genes,
(brain, body) base of the behavior. It contributes environment, and genetic–environmental inter-
to producing behavior from the filtered percep- actions, to be sure, but also by the role of the per-
tions it schematizes. Physiological processes son him- or herself in development. Piaget
constitute the body and brain, and the brain inte- referred to the person as the third “(tertium) quid”
grates stimuli effects in its adaptive preparation or force in development. He advocated for the
for response. child as an active constructor of her or his cogni-
tive development. Already in terms of individual
A The “A” key words in the model refer to the differences, information processing depends, in
agent/actor/appraiser of the stimuli at hand (as part, on the history of environmental presenta-
well as the responses to be made), in addition to tions to the developing child/person in family,
the networked assembly or attractors that define school, neighborhood, community, culture, and
the system. The organism is an integrated per- country. However, individual differences are
ceiver and producer in a poised state that bal- accentuated by individualized schemes and rep-
ances stasis, chaos, and change. resentations created by the person; they serve as
personally-constructed perceptual and cognitive
M As for the “M” portion, it refers to the mind of filters in addressing and functioning adaptively in
the person, the mental life from thought to emo- the environment.
tion to willed action. Inputs are (a) stored and Each of us has a unique complex of resilience,
moderated in memory (short/long; procedural- coping; vulnerabilities, risks; strengths, weak-
implicit/declarative (semantic, episodic), (b) nesses; skills, lacunae; problem solving, problem
affected by motivation and mood, and (c) pro- ignoring; adaptive behavior, maladaptive behav-
cessed in working memory and by other executive ior; good habits, bad habits; and so on. Each of us
processes including planning/problem solving. varies in degree of curiosity, exploration, open-
Baumeister and colleagues have shown that ness; externalization, extroversion; energy, activity,
part of mental life includes believing in free will, activation; inhibition, internalization, introver-
which has important consequences for behavior sion; optimism, pessimism; and so on. Each of us
(e.g., Baumeister & Brewer, 2012). Having a is varied along important dimensions of tempera-
sense of free will augments self-control but, at ment and personality; degree of security and
the same time, depletion of self-control affects trust; independence and identity; nurturance
one’s sense of free will. There are individual dif- and affiliation; and so on. As our temperament
ferences in believing in free will and its conse- and personality and related factors develop and
quent effects, e.g., related to personality. change over time and in context, we become the
people we are, contributing to our own growth
P This brings us to the person or “P” compo- and that of others.
nent to the revised S–O–R model. Psychology is
not only about common laws and principles gov-
erning behavior but also about relevant individ- Reflections
ual and group differences, including those that
make each of us unique. Variation in behavior Fuzziness
might be noise in some senses but, for the study
of individual and group differences, it is the Research has shown that stimuli do not stand as
essential focus (which is also the case for clear signals that cleanly enter the system but,
NDLST). As the present model applies to rather, they are subtle in array, energy, force, and
humans, a person is involved but, generally, for field variations that receptive and perceptual
the model, any entity or agent acting on stimuli structures of the organism struggle to accurately
toward producing responses could be the proces- decipher while otherwise functioning adaptively
sor of input leading to output. in context over multiple spheres. Organisms are
712 28 Stimulus–Organism–Response Model: SORing to New Heights

constantly making probability estimates of what itself, cannot be proved. However, perhaps the
are the stimuli in the environment and what notion that we can change our behavior construc-
responses are optimally best in light of them, tively once we believe in and have a sense of free
aside from proactively influencing them. Prior will is the most important truth about our behav-
states influence present ones, in Bayesian dynam- ior. The belief gives us a power to act positively,
ics, but because the internal states themselves are morally, responsibly, and in a caring, empathic
fuzzy, as well as the stimuli in the environment, way. Each such minuscule act of empathy might
the links between stimuli-processing and not seem much, but each functions like a “psycho-
response are not as clear-cut as some models logical Higgs Boson,” constituting the basic con-
might predict. Indeed, prediction or prospection stituent of our higher-order faculties in our
is a cardinal human attribute (Seligman, Railton, personal, familial, group, and wider behavior.
Baumeister, & Sripada, 2013) and it is a probabi- We are adaptive probability modelers engaged
listic enterprise that clearly is not deterministic. in making constant probability estimates. We are
It must be recalled that information is defined implicit computational machines, learning to
as the reduction of uncertainty and, of course, make at times explicit probability-based deci-
absolute certainty can never be ascertained. In sions, and we follow through on them for our
considering the putative Heisenberg principle, own and others adaptive benefit. This reality of
the principle of entanglement, and other quantum how we function might not prove that we have
phenomena in the microworld (and perhaps in free will, but it sets the stage for understanding
the more macro world of human activity; think ourselves as the opposite of deterministic beings
the new field of quantum biology), causation/ without a chance of having free will.
causality does not lie simply in straightforward
linkages of cause and effect, because all compo-
nents of the equation—stimulus, organism, and Causality
response—can be uncertain, probabilistic, fuzzy,
and indeterministic. Like some who conjecture about time, perhaps
causality doesn’t exist (acausalism). Or, perhaps
it is the only thing that exists in the physical
Philosophy world, which surely it does, but it is fuzzy in the
psychological world. Stimuli and responses are
In the case of human affairs, the philosophical varied, complex components of the behavioral
issue of determinism vs. indeterminism cannot be unfolding in humans, but without their causal
approached as one in which truth one way or the linkaging, even if that is fuzzy, too, neither would
other can be established. Perhaps it is best, like exist. We live as a result of caused behavior and,
many other aspects of human conceptualization, also, much of our learning is about causation and
to accept mystery. One dictum is that God does the question of “why” so that we can better adapt
not play with dice. This presupposes that the uni- and prosper in our context. Perhaps, at the psy-
verse is determined and our behaviors are its chological level, we are complex causal
products. But in the new conceptualizations in machines, both in how we develop out of the
psychology being discussed, we learn that we cauldron of gene–environment–personal interac-
intervene in our own behavior and future, and tions and how we have effect on others and the
even in our understanding of the past. We have world around us.
choices available to us, and when we act on them In summary, the causality of human behavior
constructively by way of believing in and sensing is not a straight-through sequential process from
of our free will, we make better choices. stimulus, situation, or event to response, act, and
Philosophy might not be satisfied with this practi- outcome. The person is both mediator and mod-
cal position, that believing in and sensing free will erator in the process, influencing it both directly
makes an important difference, because free will, and indirectly. Stimuli do not just happen before
Reflections 713

entering as input into the processors of the person 2011). Whether it concerns brain or behavior, or
in a passive way. Rather, the person actively fil- their various levels, activity takes place not only
ters the stimuli, constructs their schemas and rep- by appropriate activation but also by appropriate
resentations and, moreover, the person even acts inhibition. Think of the infant’s finely-tuned
on the environment to shape it to extant adaptive reaching hand and then open and grasp move-
needs, thereby altering stimuli even before they ment, and how much successive activations and
exist. Therefore, stimuli are not absolute but prob- inhibitions must take place in a coordinated fash-
abilistic, and reflect the optimization involved in ion both in behavior and brain for the movement
response choice, construction, decision-making, to succeed in its objective. [I have argued, by the
enactment, monitoring, and revision. Falling trees way, that the functional specialization involved
do not make sounds if organisms are not around to in left hemisphere “dominance” concerns a supe-
hear them. Similarly, causation in human behav- rior skill in activation/inhibition coordination
ior involves the person as genuine, active, and (Young, 2011).]
proactive participant. As much as are stimuli and To continue the analogy with the physical
responses, causal linkages in behavior are world, we can ask to what extent the physical
humanly influenced and probabilistic, and they universe exhibits properties related to activation/
are phenomena on which we ourselves can act to inhibition coordination, and if the answer is posi-
alter putative deterministic outcomes. tive, it would help promote the idea that causality
In this line of reasoning, there appears to be is central both to the physical and psychological
symmetry across the physical and psychological worlds because of common change mechanisms
worlds in terms of space, time, and causality. In in both spheres. In this regard, systems theory
the quantum and cosmic reality of the former, provides an answer. Systems tend to equilibrium
that is the physical universe, physical space-time even in a far-from-equilibrium state because they
is considered a unified multi-dimension that tend to dampen the effects of perturbation, even
curves and in which causality is predominant. if major. This obtains until the system is pushed
Similarly, in the latter, that is, at the psychological beyond the threshold of change and, then, even a
level, psychological space-time could be consid- minor perturbation can promote a chaotic
ered a unified multi-dimension, one that exists response to a new state configuration, aside from
only because it is punctuated by causal stimuli, the fact that systems might gravitate to the regime
events, and perceptions and their responses, in which equilibrium and disequilibrium co-exist
effects, and outcomes. Given the nonlinearity at the cusp ready for change. Given this descrip-
involved, the causal manifold of living also tion of systems, it would appear that the dynamic
would appear to be curved, and at times cata- in system activity relates to ongoing coordination
strophically so. of inhibitory (I) and activation (A). Therefore,
Further to this line of reasoning, causality the mathematical formulae that characterize both
becomes central to the behavioral enterprise and physical and psychological systems could
it should become central to its study in psychol- involve A/I causal functions.
ogy. Causality encompasses all things psycho-
logical and the relationships in its linkages define
equally both the stimuli, situational, and event Dimensions
factors in its sequence and the response, act, and
outcome factors after them, as well as, the organ- Figure 28.2 explores dimensions in behavior per-
ism/person/agent factors that mediate, moderate, taining to S–O–R modeling of behavior. First,
or otherwise intervene in establishing the behavior develops, especially in higher-order
linkages. organisms. Second, mechanisms assure constant,
An important cross-level concept that helps adaptive function, including in feedback and
characterize activity in the causal manifold con- feedforward mechanisms. Third, individuals
cerns activation–inhibition coordination (Young, participate in social activities, and these vary
714 28 Stimulus–Organism–Response Model: SORing to New Heights

Low/ 0

S Modality
Stimulus Objective/ Subjective/
Affordances/ Constructions/
Realism Relativism

Sociality High
X

Scheme

O(P1) Modality
Motivation

Organism Reception/ Conception/


Arousal Personality
Attention Appraisal/
Perception/ Interpretation Emotion
Memory
Sociality Co-Scheme
=
Cooperative/
Collective

R Modality
Response Reactive/ Active/
Automatic/ Reflective/
Unconscious Conscious

Competition/
Sociality Co-optive

Feedback (Reactive) TIME Feedforward (Proactive)

Fig. 28.2 Dimensions of modality and sociality in stimu- For each of the components of the stimulus, the process-
lus–organism–response modeling of developing behav- ing individual, and the response, there are both modality
ior. 1In higher-order organisms, especially for humans, and sociality dimensions to consider. With increasing
the organism (person) increasingly includes effects due to psychological complexity, there is greater influence of
attention, motivation, emotion, and personality, with each motivation, attention, emotion, personality [and cogni-
dimension varying in degree of being adaptive/maladap- tion] to consider, as well as, for each of stimulus, process-
tive, equilibrated, positive/negative, intense or not, etc. ing, and response

according to whether the S, O, or R component of for example, is their affordances perceived accu-
the model is being examined. For the Stimulus, rately and do they lead to appropriate action? Or
sociality refers to the degree the S is social. For is the S perceived subjectively and relativisti-
organism, it refers to whether the appraising of cally, or is socially constructed? Modality for O
the S is individual or collective (e.g., schemes vs. refers to the quality of the appraisal of S involved.
co-schemes). For Response, it refers to whether For example, both lower-order, e.g., attention,
cooperative or competitive social dynamics are and higher-order, e.g., interpretation, factors are
involved. involved. These might include complex meaning
As for modality, this dimension also varies and meaning-making, as in the narratives that we
over S, O, and R. For S, it refers to the degree to construct and use as guides in life. Finally, modal-
which an S is taken objectively and realistically, ity for R refers to whether we use deliberative,
Chapter Conclusions 715

reflective, slower, conscious thought to guide us of view that could be seen as co-existential
or whether we act and react reflexively with (Young, 1997). For psychology, this refers to the
reflexes in a manner that is quick, automatic, and lack of distinct entities and timeframes for each
unconscious (e.g., Kahneman, 2011; Stanovich, of the components of the stimulus–organism–
West, & Toplak, 2014). [Note, I have argued that response input-processing-output sequence.
each of these two types or systems of thought can The present book, in particular, deals with
be decomposed into at least two subtypes accord- causality and free will in behavior from a systems
ing to Piagetian/Neo-Piagetian theory, i.e., senso- perspective. Local dynamics might be probabilis-
rimotor and pre-operational thought and concrete tic without determinate outcome but, at a global
operational and formal, abstract thought, respec- level, in the nonlinear dynamical case, systems
tively (Young, 2011).] inevitably gravitate to deterministic outcomes, as
As a conclusion to the S–O(BAMP)–R model per attractor regimes.
that I have developed, it is important to note that However, in applying this conceptual map to
the individualistic, unique processing, and prod- free will in psychology, or at least its belief and
ucts involved might go awry or be disturbed to having a sense that it exists, I would argue that,
the point of being maladaptive, disequilibrated, even at the global level, the condition of having a
majorly negative, and so on. Of course, genes, belief in and a sense of free will removes the indi-
environment, and their interaction influence how vidual out of the deterministic orbit. The person
this happens. However, we are agents, selves, becomes the parameter that can move attractors
whole persons, and adaptive beings who have a to new regions of state space, so to speak. The
role in our own development and behavior, so person becomes the effector or agent that can
that our behavior does not have to be determinis- move psychological states even beyond the far-
tically maladaptive even if all the stimuli, situa- from-equilibrium, cusp-of-change boundary or,
tions, stressors, and processing capacities and if you will, to uncharted attractor regions consis-
qualities suggest that this type of outcome is tent with the correlated state that one’s agency
inevitable. In the end, we have a say in “who” we had moved it toward. In “gene–environment cor-
are and “how” we are, to the point that we might relations” (rGE; see Chap. 11), genes can evoke
say to ourselves and everyone around us that, actively behavior and environmental response
despite everything involved in the past and pres- consistent with their dynamic. Analogously, in
ent, “I define who I am and how I am.” “free will/environment correlations,” to coin a
term, it is the belief in free will and its effects, as
well as having a sense of free will, that help direct
Chapter Conclusions behavior this way (see Table 28.1).
Let me continue the analogy that free will is
In relation to the overriding issue in the present an affordance. It exists in the membrane of pos-
book of causality, the present chapter has consid- sibilities that bind the universe, and it attracts
ered basic philosophical issues in psychology people to its possibilities. However, being an
(especially reductionism, constructivism, deter- affordance does not mean automatic entry in the
minism, and probabilistic emergence), and basic
units in psychology (stimulus input, organismic
Table 28.1 Local and global determinism and indeter-
processing, response output). In both cases, for minism in relation to causality
philosophy and psychology, the issues consid-
Local Global
ered lead to the conclusion that fuzziness best
Causality in Probabilistic Lawful fixed
characterizes the conceptual bases involved. For universe fuzzy determinate
philosophy, this refers to the need for a model of Indeterminate
behavior that is less deterministic than some Free will in Probabilistic Probabilistic
maintain and that affords the possibility of free psychology fuzzy fuzzy
will, in an all-inclusive model of different points Indeterminate Indeterminate
716 28 Stimulus–Organism–Response Model: SORing to New Heights

apperceiving or exposed system; rather free will Jacoby, J. (2002). Stimulus-organism-response reconsid-
is but an invitation to its possibility and it is our- ered: An evolutionary step in modeling (consumer)
behaviour. Journal of Consumer Psychology, 12, 51–57.
selves who have to engage it. The beauty of the Jaffee, S. R. (2011). Genotype-environment correlations:
invitation is that surely we have the capacity to Definitions, methods of measurement, and implica-
accept free will into our personal system and tions for research on adolescent psychopathology. In
become it as we cause our own behavior. K. S. Kendler, S. R. Jaffee, & D. Romer (Eds.), The
dynamic genome and mental health: The role of genes
and environments in youth development (pp. 79–102).
New York: Oxford University Press.
References Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking fast and slow. New York:
Farrar, Straus, and Giroux.
Badcock, P. B. (2012). Evolutionary systems theory: A Mareschal, D., Johnson, M. H., Siros, S., Spratling,
unifying meta-theory of psychological science. Review M. W., Thomas, M. S. C., & Westermann, G. (2007).
of General Psychology, 16, 10–23. Neuroconstructivism: How the brain constructs cogni-
Barrett, L. F. (2012). Emotions are real. Emotion, 12, tion (Vol. 1). New York: Oxford University Press.
413–429. Marken, R. S., & Mansell, W. (2013). Perceptual control
Barrett, L. F., & Bliss-Moreau, E. (2009). Affect as a psy- as a unifying concept in psychology. Review of
chological primitive. Advances in Experimental Social General Psychology, 17, 190–195.
Psychology, 41, 167–218. Meaney, M. J. (2010). Epigenetics and the biological defi-
Baumeister, R. F., & Brewer, L. E. (2012). Believing ver- nition of gene x environment interactions. Child
sus disbelieving in free will: Correlates and conse- Development, 81, 41–79.
quences. Social and Personality Psychology Compass, Michel, G. F. (2013). The role of developmental psycho-
6, 736–745. biology in the unification of psychology. Review of
Belsky, J., & Pluess, M. (2009a). Beyond diathesis stress: General Psychology, 17, 210–215.
Differential susceptibility to environmental influences. Peterson, M. B., Sznycer, D., Sell, A., Cosmides, L., &
Psychological Bulletin, 135, 885–908. Tooby, J. (2013). The ancestral logic of politics:
Belsky, J., & Pluess, M. (2009b). The nature (and nur- Upper-body strength regulates men’s assertion of self-
ture?) of plasticity in early human development. interest over economic redistribution. Psychological
Perspectives on Psychological Science, 4, 345–351. Science, 24, 1098–1103.
Clark, A. (2013a). Whatever next? Predictive brains, situ- Power, W. T. (1973). Behavior: The control of perception.
ated agents, and the future of cognitive science. Chicago, IL: Aldine.
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36, 1–24. Power, W. T. (1978). Quantitative analysis of purposive
Clark, A. (2013b). Are we predictive engines? Perils, systems: Some spadework at the foundations of scien-
prospects, and the puzzle of the porous perceiver. tific psychology. Psychological Review, 85, 417–435.
Behavior and Brain Sciences, 36, 53–64. Reed, E. S. (1982). An outline of a theory of action sys-
De Pittà, M., Volman, V., Berry, H., Parpura, V., Volterra, tems. Journal of Motor Behavior, 14, 98–134.
A., & Ben-Jacob, E. (2012). Computational quest for Reed, E. S. (1985). An ecological approach to the evolu-
understanding the role of astrocyte signaling in synap- tion of behavior. In J. Johnson & A. Pietrewicz (Eds.),
tic transmission and plasticity. Frontiers in Issues in the ecological study of learning (pp. 357–
Computational Neuroscience, 6, 98. doi:10.3389/ 383). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
fncom.2012.00098. Reed, E. S. (1993). The intention to use a specific affor-
Frankenhuis, W. E., Gergely, G., & Watson, J. S. (2013). dance: A framework for psychology. In R. Wozniak &
Infants may use contingency analysis to estimate envi- K. Fischer (Eds.), Development in context: Acting and
ronmental states: An evolutionary, life-history perspec- thinking in specific environments (pp. 45–75).
tive. Child Development Perspectives, 7, 115–120. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Friston, K. (2010). The free-energy principle: A unified Reed, E. S. (1996). Encountering the world: Toward an
brain theory? Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 11, ecological psychology. New York: Oxford University
127–138. Press.
Gibson, J. J. (1966). The senses considered as perceptual Reyna, V. F., & Brainerd, C. J. (1995). Fuzzy-trace theory:
systems. Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin. An interim synthesis. Learning and Individual
Gibson, J. J. (1979/1986). The ecological approach to Differences, 7, 1–75.
visual perception. Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin. Reyna, V. F., & Brainerd, C. J. (2011). Dual processes in
Gottlieb, G. (2007). Probabilistic epigenesis. decision making and developmental neuroscience: A
Developmental Science, 10, 1–11. fuzzy-trace model. Developmental Review, 31,
Hirsh, J. B., Mar, R. A., & Peterson, J. B. (2013). Personal 180–206.
narratives as the highest level of cognitive integration. Seligman, M. E. P., Railton, P., Baumeister, R. F., &
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36, 36–37. Sripada, C. (2013). Navigating into the future or
References 717

driven by the past. Perspectives on Psychological Tryon, W. W. (2012). A connectionist network


Science, 8, 119–141. approach to psychological science: Core and corol-
Seth, A. K., & Critchley, H. D. (2013). Extending predic- lary principles. Review of General Psychology, 16,
tive processing to the body: Emotion as interoceptive 305–317.
inference. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36, 47–48. van Geert, P. (2012). Dynamic systems. In B. Laursen,
Simpson, J. A., & Belsky, J. (2008). Attachment theory T. D. Little, & N. A. Card (Eds.), Handbook of devel-
within a modern evolutionary framework. In J. Cassidy opmental research methods (pp. 725–741). New York:
& P. R. Shaver (Eds.), Handbook of attachment: Guilford Press.
Theory, research, and clinical applications (2nd ed., Withagen, R., de Poel, H. J., Araújo, D., & Pepping, G.-J.
pp. 131–157). New York: Guilford Press. (2012). Affordances can invite behavior:
Sporns, O. (2011). Networks of the brain. Cambridge, Reconsidering the relationship between affordances
MA: MIT Press. and agency. New Ideas in Psychology, 30, 250–258.
Sporns, O. (2012). Discovering the human connectome. Witkiewitz, K., & Marlatt, G. A. (2007). Modeling the
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. complexity of post-treatment drinking: It’s a rocky
Stanovich, K. E., West, R. F., & Toplak, M. E. (2014). road to relapse. Clinical Psychology Review, 27,
Rationality, intelligence, and the defining features of type 724–738.
1 and type 2 processing. In J. W. Sherman, B. Gawronski, Woodworth, R. S. (1918). Dynamic psychology.
& Y. Trope (Eds.), Dual-process theories of the social New York: Columbia University Press.
mind (pp. 80–91). New York: Guilford Press. Young, G. (1997). Adult development, therapy, and cul-
Sternberg, R. J. (2012). Intelligence. Wiley Interdisciplinary ture: A postmodern synthesis. New York: Plenum.
Reviews: Cognitive Science, 3, 501–511. Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
Thelen, E., & Smith, L. B. (1994). A dynamic systems Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science +
approach to the development of cognition and action. Business Media.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Zaki, J. (2013). Cue integration: A common framework
Thurstone, L. L. (1923). The stimulus–response fallacy in for social cognition and physical perception.
psychology. Psychological Review, 30, 354–369. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 8, 296–312.
Networked Causal Terms
29

Chapter Introduction Terms

The next two chapters of the book are on novel Standard


concepts that I have created related to the subject
of causality. In order to promote the importance The first table in this chapter on terminology related
of the study of the causality of behavior, I have to causality explains some basic terms in the pres-
tried to create concepts and terms that bring it to ent work (see Table 29.1). I have undertaken this
the fore. One integrative way of understanding step in order to avoid any perception of imprecision
causality in psychology revolves around the con- or use of jargon. First, it gives explanations for
cept of networks. In this regard, I propose an critical, common terms, such as genetics, evolu-
Integrated Cross-Network (ICN) model of psy- tion, development, and systems. It includes descrip-
chological causality. In the chapter, I present a tion of the biopsychosocial and related models. The
table that I developed that includes critical inte- latter model is an important one in the present work
grative (and sometimes novel) terms related to because of its integrative nature. The table also
this construct. Another integrative model that I gives supplemental terms, including some complex
developed for present purposes concerns the con- ones, such as the differential susceptibility model.
cept of Genes × Environment × Organism × Devel
opment × Systems, which attempts to capture a
good range of causal influences on behavior. This Innovation
model also is presented in tabular format. A new
model that I created about causality that might Landscapes Table 29.1 follows and it presents
have integrative applications for psychology terms that I innovated about causality related to
involves Coexistential Intraactive Causality. I psychology and psychopathology. First, I
created these diverse terms in order to capture the describe the concept of the causal landscape. It
dynamic nature of behavior in the causal nexus, refers to range of causal influences on behavior,
and also to serve as an instigating suite of con- the models of those influences, and the concepts
cepts in the study of psychology and causality. that are developed to understand causality. We

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 719


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_29
Table 29.1 Causality in psychology: key terms
720

Term Explanation
Psychology Psychology is more than the study of behavior, which is its traditional definition. Among other considerations, it is also the study of its development,
and its relationship to the brain–behavior relationships, to evolution, and to causality
Behavior Refers to the output of psychological systems and to the processes governing them. Takes place at the level of action and its tendencies, and of
cognition and emotion, and their constituents and interactions. Behaviors have to be understood at the level of the causal linkages producing them
and the causal effects that they have. As an analogy, we could describe clouds and leave it at that, but they are best understood when we can understand
their origins and determinants in physical and chemical processes (with biological ones involved, too). For behavior, the analogy applies especially to
areas such as development, abnormal development, and psychopathology. The study of behavior independent of causality paints a limited picture and
might ellipse background and downstream information not only essential in understanding it but also in even redescribing it more accurately
Development One definition involves change in behavior and another involves its organization, including steps/phases/stages; but also conserving gains, avoiding
regression, if possible
Psychopathology Disturbances and disorders in behavior
Model A theory/metatheory that is heuristic, perhaps mathematical, integrative, potentially testable, with operationalized predictions
System Dynamical, self-organizing, emergent, multiple level, hierarchical, reciprocally, bottom-up and top-down, probabilistic/stochastic
Causal Proximal and distal influences and mechanisms and their interaction in eliciting/maintaining relevant effecting-effector (determined) relations. They
might be conservative/canalyzed/stable or changing/cascading/unstable
Biopsychosocial A model of behavior and its function/dysfunction related to biological, psychological, and social components. Referred to as biopersonalsocial
by Young (2011). Related models are diathesis/stress, person × environment, and risk-resilience
Biopersonalsocial A model in which behavior is considered the interactive product of biological (e.g., genetic), personal (e.g., personality, coping, curiosity, free will),
and social (environmental, contextual) factors with evolutionary and developmental dynamics involved. The biopersonalsocial model is consistent
with the biopsychosocial one, in that the component related to the organism (person) is added to the terminology in the model without diminishing
the others as psychologically relevant. A term created to counteract the ambiguity in calling referring to the biopsychosocial model as a psychological
one—it weakens to a dualistic conception
Generative Generative refers to part or whole individual/structure or phenotypic (endophenotypic) growth promotion/maintenance. It might also entail negative
growth/degeneration/maladaptation
Governing Steer, direct, influence, guide, control
Not in a homuncular, machine-within-the-machine sense, but in a dynamic, self-regulating sense
29

Gene/genetic/ The units of, as well as entirety of, an organism’s hereditary information, e.g., DNA, including its allelic make-up in the individual. The genotype is
genotypic/ an organism’s complete hereditary information. The phenotype is its observed properties (morphological, physiological, behavioral). Endophenotypes
genomic are intermediary aspects of the phenotype with downstream genetic connections
Genetic Genes, genome, genetic material, DNA
Epigenetic/ Study of heritable changes in gene expression/phenotype induced by mechanisms beyond changes in underlying DNA sequence (e.g., gene silencing
epigenomic by acting on promoter regions). Collectively, epigenetic changes constitute the epigenome
Evolution Intergenerational change in inherited characteristics of biological populations, including to the point of speciation
Networked Causal Terms
Adaptation An evolved (through natural selection) and currently maintained trait contributing to the survival and fitness or reproductive success of an individual.
(Darwinian) An adaptation might include differential options in phenotypic expression that serves fitness. “Natural selection has also maintained variation (adaptive
Terms

individual differences)” (Ellis, Boyce, Belsky, Bakermans-Kranenburg, & van IJzendoorn, 2011, p. 7), or differential susceptibilities to environmental
variations, even if apparently for worse in a fitness sense in the long term time frame (but not the short term)
Natural selection A gradual, non-random process that alters the relative frequency of biological traits in a population by way of differential reproduction of individuals
possessing the traits
Fitness (survival/ The ability to survive and reproduce. Traits that contribute to survival and reproduction increase their frequency in a population over generations
reproduction) through the process of natural selection
Differential More malleable individuals are more susceptible to environmental influences, both for better or worse. For these individuals, development is more
susceptibility positive than the norm in supportive environments but also more adverse in negative ones. Nevertheless, the adverse development in the latter case
(dandelion/ might bring adaptive advantages, in a fitness/evolutionary sense. Therefore, it has been labeled metaphorically as the orchid phenotype (susceptible)
orchid) compared to an opposing dandelion one (can grow anywhere). The model contrasts with the traditional diathesis-stress model of maladaptive behavior/
psychopathology (vulnerabilities in interaction with stress lead to developmental psychopathology)
Life history Study of how organisms allocate time, energy, and resources to different activities at each phase over the life cycle. Each phase needs to be addressed
theory adaptively
Evolutionary/ Origin and alteration of species by natural selection and other evolutionary pressures throughout development
Developmental
(Evo/Devo)
Phylogenetic/ Ontogeny refers to the developmental, (real or lived) temporal history of an organism, whereas phylogeny refers to its evolution. Development
ontogenetic refers to change in behavior or its organization over an organism’s lifetime, i.e., it is akin to ontogeny, not phylogeny. Development is ontogenetic
stabilization/continuity and change/transformation in product (morphology, physiology, body, brain, behavior, and its organization, including phases/
steps/stages) and process
Ecological niche The resources/competitors in an organism’s/population’s context that govern its way of life (responding and altering). Constructed niche refers to
changes in the niche created by the organism and its activities
Environment/ Context/surroundings and their factors/interactions that affect an organism/population, including other organisms and their relations
ecology
Sociocultural Refers to a human individual/population in its ecological context, especially in terms of relations. A wider term would be sociocultural/
historicopolitical, in order to refer to cultural changes over time and how they are embedded in wider societal organizations
Organism/ Individuals of a species, a living system. Note that the adjective in this context does not refer to holistic, organic approaches in psychology
organismic
Organization/ Social structures evolve too. Many of the terms in the model as they apply to individuals can apply equally to societal-type systems
institution
Group The term is meant to cover different social structures. In the evolutionary sense, it indicates that one focus concerns group selection, distinct from
natural selection. In this model, selection can operate on entire groups and lead to group-like traits, even at the sacrifice of individual fitness, at least
when constraints mitigating against it do not apply
(Re)Organization Concerns processes governing behavioral development, which might concern its organization and reorganization, rather than specific behaviors, per se
(continued)
721
Table 29.1 (continue)
722

Term Explanation
Optimization Evolution considers maximizing survival and reproductive fitness (adaptation), without concern for one optimal strategy and, indeed, from the
empirical point of view, none exists in an evolutionary sense. The term optimization is used in the sense of maximizing survival and reproductive
fitness for living systems/organisms/individuals and also assuring survival and growth of institutions/organizations/social structures
Dynamical In a system, the whole is greater than the sum of the parts. In dynamical systems, prior states predict present ones (a fixed rule defines the movement
(nonlinear) of a point in temporally-mediated geometric space). In nonlinear dynamical systems, the local behavior of the system might appear unpredictable or
system random, but it is still globally deterministic. Nonlinear dynamical systems are marked by self-organized phase transitions in state space leading to
emergent reorganizations or attractors that resist disequilibrium from perturbations until they are pushed beyond parameters at bifurcation points or
the cusp of change
Quantitative/ Development could be continuous, gradual, and without phases, steps, stages, or an increasingly complexity, but also it could be marked by abrupt
qualitative shifts in organization distinct from prior organizations, as in stages. Feedback (negative, positive) and feedforward mechanisms could speed up or
contain cascades in development. Change could be constructive, positive (virtuous) or destructive, negative (vicious)
Stimulus/ Behaviorism studies behavior as stimulus–response connections and the mechanisms that change them (e.g., reinforcement), doing so without
response (input/ reference to the organism’s black box (e.g., mental, brain). In the information-processing approach, language equivalent to stimulus–response is
output) input–output, as in computers. In this model, attention and motivation are important as mediators. Similarly, in appraising stressors, stimuli might be
appraised differentially (e.g., one person’s threat is not another’s; there are individual differences according to subjective experience). In this regard,
different schools of thought vary as to what degree stimuli are “constructed” by the person. Similarly, responses behave differently according to
adaptive parameters. For example, they could vary in terms of their automaticity or reflectiveness. The former is fast, intuitive, unconscious and the
latter is slow, deliberate, and conscious
Strategic/ Strategizing refers to the active mental process in problem solving and directing behavior. In evolution, one discusses strategies in terms of options
strategizing that genes might help promote in phenotypic adaptation, depending on differential qualities in the environment. The application of evolutionary
strategies to humans does not mean the same as conscious strategies in human behavior
Stochastic/ A stochastic system contains non-deterministic states. The successive states of the system are influenced by previous states and probabilistic or
probabilistic random elements. Keeping in mind NLDST, local, in-the-moment states might be probabilistic but global patterns are deterministic or non-random
Deterministic A system is deterministic when randomness is not a factor in determining its future states. Philosophically, there is debate whether determinism
applies universally to events and behavior. Psychologically, belief in free will constitutes an example in which determinism can take a back seat to
psychological processes within the person. Systems not functioning deterministically could be termed adeterministic
29

Emergent A rearrangement of entities into new patterns that are unpredictable from knowledge of the entities. For example, in H2O (water), wetness is not
predictable from knowledge of the properties of H or O. In children’s play, games are unpredictable from knowledge of any one child
Approach/ Approach and withdrawal concern more than the direction of behavior, because it could refer to tendencies not expressed due to context. Also,
Withdrawal approach might be the product of either activation or of release of inhibition. Also, it could refer to negative emotions, such as approaching in anger.
Withdrawal could refer to movement away but also to shutting down, although the polar opposite of approach refers to the movement option
Activation/ Critical mechanism functioning in multiple levels of behavior, brain, and components/levels, including the genetic
inhibition
coordination
Networked Causal Terms
Integrated Cross-Network Model 723

are active seekers and users of causal concepts. nary framework that links critical concepts in
Also in this regard, the concept of causal ecologi- psychology and causality. Although many of
cal expanses/fields refers to the dynamic causal- the terms in the framework are ones that are
ity manifold, for example, in relation to symptom innovative, they are extensions of standard
networks. concepts in psychology. Table 29.2 gives the
key terms in the framework. I refer to the
Embodiism A pair of concepts that are espe- framework as the ICN framework of psychol-
cially important in the present book concerns ogy and causality because the concept of net-
“embodied causation” and “causal embodiment.” work is becoming one that is cross-disciplinary.
Together, these concepts refer to the embodied Moreover, in and of itself, it is an integrative
cognitive origin of causality and its understand- term. The table indicates that the ICN model
ing, and also to the essential nature of causality in should apply to major areas of psychology and,
human behavior. When these concepts are applied aside from the ones that listed in it, the areas
to disturbed behavior and psychopathology, they include social psychology, cognitive psychol-
are referred to as embodied etiology and etiologi- ogy, psychopathology, and neuropsychology.
cal embodiment, respectively. Table 29.3 indicates that the essential focus of
the framework is on change and behavior and
Homo Causa Collectively, the terms related to how it takes place. Aside from the processes
causality that I have created, as presented in this listed, there are many additions that could be
chapter, specifically, as well as the contents of the made, including those of genetics/epigenetics
present book, generally, underscore that Homo and activation/inhibition coordination.
Sapiens should be called Homo Causa or (Homo
Humanus Causa).
Model
Causal Particles In addition, whether we speak
of human behavior or of the physical universe, In the following, I briefly address some of the
one concept that could unify the importance of key terms in the ICN framework, as listed in
causality is that both the behavior and the wider Table 29.2, which include: cross-networks, con-
world are constituted by “causal particles,” which nectome, yoking, peridynamical, constrained
I refer to as “causicles.” I describe in more depth emergence, neoreductioconstructivism, bioper-
below the concept of causal particles/causicles. sonalsocial, micro–macro hypertransactionalism,
causality systematization/systematizing causality,
Comment From a scientific point of view, at the ontophylogenetic/phyloontogenetic, and mul-
psychological and psychiatric levels, the empiri- ticausal systems. These terms give the range of
cal task should be to discover causal relations and concepts involved in the ICN framework.
their import for normal behavior and also how it
(and they) can go awry. In the following, I pres-
ent an integrated model of causality for psychol- Cross-Networks
ogy and psychiatry based on networks.
Cross-networks refer to multiple network inter-
connections, such as found in neuronal net-
Integrated Cross-Network Model works and the connectome (Sporns, 2011,
2012). Nonlinear dynamical systems theory
Introduction (NLDST) includes concepts related to net-
works, such as patterns, configurations, assem-
Although causality is an important, ubiquitous bled states, and attractors and, also, one version
theme in psychology, it is not dealt with in a of complexity theory (Holland, 2012) empha-
coherent manner. I have constructed a prelimi- sizes networks.
Table 29.2 Integrated terminology of psychological causality/causation, including an integrated cross-network (ICN) model (behavior, development, psychopathology)
724

Term Explanation
Causal landscape The range of causal factors that influence behavior, as well as the diverse models of how they affect behavior
Causal ecological expanses Causality does not lie in an aggregate of direct and indirect factors. Rather, it consists of a field of interacting and emergent constituents from
(fields) more indirect to direct ones, and related risk factors, moderators, and mediators. The components are not isolated and additive but they form
a fluid, metamorphosing manifold that dynamically changes in context and in relation to symptom network expression and plasticity
Causal complexity The process of establishing the causal network governing a system, and also differentiating causal and acausal influences in a system
as it becomes more complex (complexifies) over time, thereby establishing the causal dynamic of the system
Deterministic complexity The process of differentiating deterministic and adeterministic causal influences in the causal network in a system as it becomes more
complex/complexifies (in complexification)
Embodied causation The acquisition and appreciation of causal understanding through body-focused/body-centric, sensorimotor activity and influence. The
concept summarizes a unique, unifying approach to understanding causality in behavior in psychology, etiology in psychopathology in
psychiatry. At the level of causation, the term refers to a multifactorial, integrated network, and dynamical approach to understanding
causality in behavior, while admitting to limits in present knowledge and science of that understanding. At the level of embodiment,
the term refers to the fuzziness in separating environment, organism, and response. Causation does not lie out there independently in
the world acting passively on us. Rather, it exists in continual interaction with the adaptive and apperceiving nature of the organism in
relationship with the environment through its perceptual and action control mechanisms, and cognitive ones, if they are applicable.
Therefore, causality resides in the organism or the person, as the case may be, including the body and mind, and starting with the body
in that the individual develops mostly from and initial physical state to an integrated physical and mental one
Causal embodiment Causality is the context in which behavior lives and is defined. We are active agents of causality search, participation, understanding,
and use for Darwinian (selection) survival and reproduction and related processes
Embodied etiology Embodied causation in the context of disturbed, disordered, dysfunctional (developmental) behavior
Etiological embodiment Causal embodiment that goes awry in disturbed, disordered, dysfunctional (developmental) behavior
Cross-network (integrated) Networks concern collections of relational data and their representations. They can exist at multiple levels that form larger networks. Cross-
networks refer to connected networks either within a level of a system or over levels. They might be localized or dispersed and distributed
System cohesion and Cohesion refers to integration within an element of a system (think; within a sentence) and coherence to integration across them
coherence connectivity (think, across sentences or even a paragraph), with across-level integrations involving different strata or multiple-level connectivities
(think narrative)
29

Peridynamical Linear systems are ones that can be mapped for outputs according to inputs and functions such that there might be one-to-one and
related slope functions. Nonlinear dynamical systems are ones that can be represented by differential equations such that inputs and
outputs are not necessarily linear but can exhibit exponentially different outputs compared to the inputs. The term “peridynamical”
refers to systems that might involve dynamical systematization in at least some (if not all) phases of its phase space mapping or
trajectory. For example, in human development, trajectories might be especially or uniquely linear, but qualitative jumps in
organization, i.e., stages, might be found, as well. Formally, a peridynamical system is one that either includes nonlinear dynamical
system components in part or in full, or ones that could transform into them
Constrained emergence The concept of constrained emergence indicates that system change that leads to novel organizational outputs cannot take any and
every form or pattern possible because of the constraints in the characteristics of the constituent elements involved and in the
Networked Causal Terms

characteristics of their interaction in promoting novel outputs


Circular causal emergence Circular causality refers to the reciprocal interactions between different levels of a system. Circular causal emergence specifies that
the interactions can become constitutive of emergent properties, entities, or levels in the system (within or across the levels) beyond
anything predictable from knowledge of the elements involved
Neoreductioconstructivism There is a tension in psychology and other disciplines about whether reality is positivist, empiricist, and somewhat independent of the
observer, or whether it is personally and socially constructed. Reductionism refers to simplifying complex phenomena, including the
psychological, to underlying and constituent elements and processes, such as to brain activity and function in the case of psychology.
A combined view would acknowledge the objective reality of the external world, in part, while admitting to personal/social
constructivist, subjective influence. “Neoreductioconstructivism” refers to not only an integration of reductionism and constructivism
into a unified conception but also to a superordinate concept about reality in which the person actively contributes to her/his
integration and the person condition others (or the environment) and is conditioned by them
Micro/macro Transactionalism in psychology refers to the moment-to-moment interaction of the person in the environment and how each modifies
Integrated Cross-Network Model

hypertransactionalism the other from second to second. “Hypertransactionalism” refers to the rapid, pervasive, multiple-level, and powerful transactions that
take place across person and environment. Moreover, it can happen both at the micro- and macro-levels, or extreme micro- (nano) and
extreme macro- (giga/mega) levels
Causality systematization/ Systems are causality machines and also machines that produce causality. They exist only because of causality and through their
systemizing causality causality. In their activity, they systematize causality and, as they function in causality, they are systematizing of themselves and their
context
Ontophylogenetic/ Ontogeny and phylogeny are intimately linked not in the sense that the former recapitulates the latter but in the sense that each
Phyloontogenetic acquisition of the phenotype at a particular developmental level that is linked to the genotype in some way has evolved because of its
immediate adaptive fitness advantage in the age period concerned. Also, the plasticity of the ontogenetic process flexibility enables
phenotypic variants to emerge that, if linked to the genotype, could enable better Darwinian survival and eventually reproduction. The
term “ontophylogenetic/phyloontogenetic” captures this intimate linkage in a unifying process of ontogeny and phylogeny to the point
that neither can exist without the other and each aliments the other
Individualizing/commonalizing Systems exist in multiple, coordinated opponent, or dialectical relationships. For example, this includes the interrelation of top-down
and bottom-up causation or causality. Another example relates to their ongoing, de novo dynamical construction from the array of
system components extant at any one moment. This means that a system state is always individualized and novel at each moment of
its existence. Nevertheless, the system patterns might give the impression of being universal or standard. However, this appearance is
valid only in the sense that the system states resemble each other over a period of time. Thus, although the system states appear to
have a common structure and the system appears stable and constant, it is only because the system has reconstituted itself in an
adaptive form in a highly similar way or even in an identical way in each minimal time unit of the time period involved. State
commonality is a surface although valid appearance that reflects moment-to-moment individualization in the system. Note that
because of a system’s appearance of communalization, it might not be easy to detect its constant individualization. Overall,
individualization is its predominant property relative to communalization, although the latter can serve as a good shorthand in
describing it. This description of the individualizing and commonalizing properties of systems is akin to describing them in terms of
attractors, which have both local individualized trajectories and global representative patterns in their basins. In general, system
communalization can be captured by some sort of mathematical representation, but the formula cannot capture each expression of the
system nor its range. At the same time, without commonalizing mathematical representations of a system, its diverse patterns and
individual differences, as well as chaotic noise, could become too complex to grasp and discern
725

(continued)
Table 29.2 (continued)
726

Term Explanation
Biopersonalsocial (biopsychosocial) This refers to the concept developed in Young (2011) about the biopsychosocial model. Young modified the classic term in the way
indicated so that is reflects a genuine psychological model, which includes a role for the active self and components of the person’s
psychology in outputting behavior
Biopsychosocial etiology In the field of medicine and its subfield of psychiatry, causation of disease is referred to as etiology. An appropriate causal or
(symptoms, etiological model of psychiatric disorder or illness understands the conditions involved as more than a biological-oriented disease but
networks, intervention/therapy) as expressions of biopsychosocial factors. Similarly, the networks of symptoms expressed are biopsychosocial in nature. Finally, the
appropriate interventions/treatments normally should be biopsychosocial
Basics Behavioral Community A variation of the biopsychosocial model that applies equally to nonliving systems. In this regard, the basics refer to (a) the
Model constituents of the systems involved, (b) the behavior and its dynamics involved, and the community in the full context involved. The
basics cannot be biological for nonliving systems, the term behavior applies equally to living and nonliving systems, as does the term
community
Multicausal biopsychosocial Systems are multifactorial/multicomponential in causality. They have multiple levels, and the levels interact both in defining
systems themselves in their activity and in their causality. In psychology and psychiatry, the multicausal systems are integrally biopsychosocial
in nature, as is the system as a whole. Biopsychosocial models now include nonlinear dynamical system properties, and also
complexity ones
A ∪ I: Inter- and Intra-level The concept of circular causality or circular causal emergence does not specify the mechanism involved in the constitutive emergence
activation–inhibition of the particular property, entity, or level that coalesces. However, activation–inhibition coordination is a process that might underlie
coordination cohesion and multiple levels of behavior and brain processes, serving to create cohesion, or coherent intrasystem linkages
coherence
Fuzzy probabilistics In a deterministic universe, knowledge of what had happened previously will predict what will happen or, stated differently, given
pre-existing conditions, nothing other than what has happened after them could have happened. This concept is based on assumptions
that (a) events and conditions can be specified (are separable and identifiable events or conditions). (b) Moreover, the said events and
conditions are positivistically and empirically genuine, without subjective, constructed, apperceived impressions about their existence.
(c) Finally, they are individually or (sub)collectively associated with definite probabilities both in their initial appearance and their
effects. However, all three of these fundamental assumptions can be challenged in the psychological universe. (1) Conditions and events
are not distinct, isolatable, objective entities but, rather, they are fuzzy, messy, subjective (person-mediated) constructions that are only
partially related to input parameters. (2) Also, they influence each other in systemic interactions, which moreover can create emergent
29

conditions/events, properties, relations, etc., so that they do not have clear probabilities associated with each of them, either in terms of
their manifestation in the cause-effect milieu or of the level of certainty of their effects. People might tend more toward establishing
cognitive structures with properties more reflective of determinism or stochasticism. However, in these regards, these cognitive
structures normally end up as fuzzy or indeterminate hybridizations. Therefore, human determinism tends toward an indeterminate
determinism with inchoate partial deterministic mechanisms in place; also, human stochasticism tends toward an exacting
probalisticism with the probabilities in the sequential unfolding of events precisely defined. The human mentally normatively gravitates
between these thresholds into a zone of fuzzy probabilistics for the most part, with much individual variation in the process. There is
room for an inexact admixture of the exact deterministic and in exact probabilistic cognitive structure that make up our cognition
Networked Causal Terms
Psychological Co-universe/ The psychological universe is governed neither purely deterministically nor probabilistically, but it is person- or individual-focused
Relaverse and filtered, with feedback from the person into appreciation of the conditions and events about him or her and also feedforward into
shaping particular putative cause-outcome conditionals. However, every person is a fuzzy analytic and prediction process mechanism
of input and output, so that people live in a constant flux of fuzzy probabilities. The outside world is not a given in reality nor is it
directly acted upon. Rather, it is participated in and co-constructed by the participation process, which itself is a reflection of the
variegated individuality of person as much as the individualized vicissitudes of the relational matrix involved in the participation. In
this sense, there is not simply a person-focused psychological universe, a mental landscape within the person. Rather, there is only a
psychological co-universe, which is participatory with multiple, shared relationships. The psychological co-universe in which we live
also can be called a psychological “Relaverse.” These terms imply a co-actional, relationally constituted psychological world in each
of us that emerges from the person through relational activity; and also from which the person emerges (co-constituted by its (the
Relaverse’s) activity as much as the person’s own)
Integrated Cross-Network Model

Homo Causa Homo sapiens can be perceived in terms of a penultimate motivation and ability to search for, participate in, understand, and use
causality in behavior because it is part of our evolutionary heritage, facilitating Darwinian survival and reproduction (selection) and
related processes
Causal particles (Causicles) The essence of the physical, chemical, and behavioral universe. Agents and objects exist in light of the causal relations that they seek,
participate in, try to understand, and use adaptively
Causal weirdness The more we learn about causality and causation, the more it becomes apparent that they cannot be explained in standard ways nor
does the reality to which they are addressed match standard and logically coherent understandings
Dark causality Just as in physics, in which there are the concepts of dark matter and dark energy, we should entertain that there are invisible and
indeterminate realities about causality in the physical and psychological worlds that defy standard explanations yet that are no less real
727
728 29 Networked Causal Terms

Table 29.3 Change processes and related terms in the Basic Behavioral Community
ICN: integrated cross-network model
Category Minor Major Note that one way of referring to biopsychoso-
Standard Stable Unstable cial/biopersonalsocial model is generically so
change terms Static Dynamic that it applies to even nonliving systems. That is,
Equilibrium Disequilibrium all systems have elements of some sort that—link
Other Conservation Transition to biological or related physical properties; in
change terms Linear Nonlinear
one way or another, all systems behave, and;
Instantiation Transformation
finally, all systems have their elements function
Reduction Construction
in community. In this regard, see Fig. 29.1 that
Resistance Revolution
presents a generic, basic behavioral community
Merging Emergence
model of causality in system function.
Horizontal move Vertical leap
Adjust Cascade
Refine Rupture
Return Retool Intrapersonal, Interpersonal,
Quantitative Qualitative Interfaced
Other terms Local Global
Micro Macro Cross-networks could exist not only within the
Deterministic Stochastic brain network (intrapersonal connectome), but
Predictable Unpredictable also in the social one (interpersonal connectome),
Ordered Unordered linking brain to brain in a certain sense. In addi-
Chartable Unchartable tion, the person today is becoming increasingly
Bounded Unbounded connected to, or interfaced with, the technologi-
Top-down Bottom-up cal world, and advances in these regards augur

Biopsychosocial Model
(BPS Model = BPSM)

Specific to humans Generic to all life

Biobehavioralcommunity
Biopersonalsocial Model
Model

Generic to all Adapting Systems

Basics/ Behavioral/ Community Model

- Any BPSM and its variants vary according to context, time (development), and systemic
(e.g., nonlinear; support/ nonsupport) factors

Fig. 29.1 Basic/behavioral/community model of causality


Integrated Cross-Network Model 729

well for spinal cord injury, neurodegenerative is more than the sum of the parts, the concept of
diseases, and so on. However, people, in general, constrained emergence acknowledges that the
have always expressed interconnectivity with the nature of the whole that emerges is somewhat con-
natural and material world (interfaced connec- strained by the nature of the parts.
tome). These three domains of the cross-network
system of the person (intrapersonal, interper-
sonal, interfaced) constitute a unified tripartite Neoreductioconstructionism
cross-network system.
Neoreductioconstructionism is a term to indi-
cate that both positivist, empirical and personal,
Yoking social construction components contribute to
perceived reality in an interaction that surpasses
Yoked networks refer to the dynamical nature of both. In Young (2011), I described a more elabo-
network self-assembly to facilitate successful rate epistemological model of co-existentialism,
contextual adaptation (e.g., problem discernment but essentially it can be conceptualized in these
and resolution). Just as behaviors coalesce into terms.
adaptive patterns from among the elements avail-
able in a system, so can underlying and associ-
ated neuronal networks. [Also, note that Young Biopersonalsocial
(2011) has hypothesized that Neo-Piagetian
stages and substages do not disappear as more In Young (2011), I also modified the term biopsy-
advanced ones develop but that they remain chosocial to biopersonalsocial. A psychological
actively available (perhaps in more evolved model needs to include all three components of
forms) for purposes of yoking to higher-order the latter term in interaction in producing behav-
ones in order to decipher and resolve contextual ior. The personal components indicate that
adaptation and problems.] behavioral expression is actively influenced by
the mediation of ourselves and not just by nature
and nurture.
Peridynamical

Peridynamical is a term constructed to describe Hypertransactionalism


systems that might include dynamical processes
or systems that could gravitate to a nonlinear Micro/macro hypertransactionalism refers to the
dynamical regime. Development provides the dynamic, ongoing, continual interaction between
classic example, with some aspects residing on person and environment at multiple temporal lev-
the cusp of order and disorder, which facilitates els. Both person and environment are intrinsi-
to state transitions in state space due to nonlinear cally transformed nano-second by nano-second
dynamical forces (Young, 2011). in their encounter, and their reciprocal interac-
tions over time can lead to transformative (con-
strained) emergence. Environment enters the
Constrained Emergence person, getting under the skin, even acting on
genes through epigenetic mechanisms, such as
Constrained emergence refers to the property of gene silencing. At the same time, the person acts
nonlinear dynamical system to follow trajectories adaptively on the environment, constructing
in which system elements coalesce into new pat- niches and engaging in correlated behavior to
terns, configurations, states, or attractors that are reflect one’s genotypic expression. Therefore,
unpredictable from simple knowledge of the con- just as the person becomes the environment the
stituent elements. Although it is true that the whole environment becomes the person.
730 29 Networked Causal Terms

Causal System GEODS Model

The term “causality systematization/systemizing Introduction


causality” refers to the causal nature of behav-
ioral systems, both in terms of having diverse The genetic study of behavior has differentiated
influences and producing diverse outcomes from to include Gene–Environmental interactions
multiple factors. Systems are not only defined by (G × E). Table 29.4 explains an expanded G × E
their causal properties but also exist by and model that includes organism, development, and
through them. systems (O, D, S = GEODS). G × E typically
refers to a statistical interaction that narrows
genetic effects to the simultaneous present of par-
Ontogeny/Phylogeny ticular genomic alleles and particular environ-
ments. The interaction might even be narrowed
The term “ontophylogenetic/phyloontogenetic” further to having its effect in particular develop-
refers to the intimate link between ontogeny and mental periods (G × E × D). The systems get com-
phylogeny both in developmental expression and plicated by G × G interactions and by E × E
in species’ evolution and speciation. Each devel- interactions added to the equation, as well as
opmental step exists because of selection for its their various combinations.
immediate adaptive fitness and not just what it
leads to in the adult. Each phenotypic form is par-
tially the expression of genotype-related succes- Model
sive developmental (evolved) forms.
The present model examines G × E (and G × E × D)
interactions more globally in terms of the factors
Multifactorial that influence behavior. Although these three
types of factors are crucial, they do not act pas-
Systems are multicausal in origin and determi- sively in that the person (O; organism, individ-
nants, and self-organize into coherent and cohe- ual) has a role to play in his/her own development,
sive forms that gracefully accommodate to their especially at the human level (e.g., personality,
constituents, the characteristics of the latter, and motivation, curiosity, coping). Also, the whole
how they interact. System interaction includes system (S) in which behavior takes place needs to
bottom-up and top-down forces that exert influ- be considered. For example, NLDST describes
ence at the multiple levels in the hierarchical emergent qualitative leaps in behavior and its
arrangement that the system elements form, organization that might take place due to the mul-
including emergent ones. tifactorial impacts on systems. Genes and envi-
ronment have their influences on a wider
developing system, which might function to
Fuzziness either constrain or amplify their interactive influ-
ences. The tables illustrate a move from analyz-
Systems can be described for the universe, in ing behavior at the statistical, narrowing level of
general, and for the “psychological universe” in interaction to the broadening systemic level of
particular. In this regard, I refer to the fuzzy prob- interaction.
abilistics in the psychological universe, which is The table addresses complex issues in NLDST,
consistent with a Bayesian approach to psycho- such as creation of attractors and chaos theory.
logical phenomena and a non-deterministic solu- Genetic and genomic theories are evolving
tion to the question of whether we have free will, quickly to include epigenetic effects, and -omics,
a capacity to choose for ourselves, and the ability in general, are proliferating. The multiple com-
to be part of our own causality. plications and complexities in behavioral genesis
GEODS Model 731

Table 29.4 Gene × environment × organism × development × systems (GEODS) model


Variation
Component Statistical Conceptual
Gene × Environment ANOVA (analysis of variance) and Genes and Environment interact in the
(G × E) multiple regression. Specific levels sense that both Nature and Nurture
of main effects differentially involved; contribute in full to behavior (and not
they constitute multiplicative or interactive only particular alleles in particular
interaction effects (e.g., 2-way, as environments)
indicated by X) - to -
- to - Genetic and environmental variations
Advanced techniques (e.g., PCA, principle act as differential influences (indirect
components analysis; HLM, hierarchical moderation; direct mediation) on
linear modeling) behavior; behavior systems exhibit
[Complicated by G × G (epistatic) and E × E complexity
interactions]
Development (add D; Statistical interactions are 3-way. Genes and Environment work their
G × E × D) Outcome (dependent variables) of G × E multiplicative interaction in different
interactions vary with developmental ways at different developmental periods
(D) as another independent - to -
variable There might be sensitive periods, or
- to - critical windows development in which
Advanced techniques genes and their interactions have more
or exclusive effects. The pattern could
include several such phases over the
lifespan, with different yet homologous
or equivalent outcome measures
involved (heterotypic continuity)
Organism (add O; N of studies would have to be high enough Organism (individual, person) variables
G × E × O × D) to allow for 4-way statistical interactions, could concern ones related to attention/
either in (M) AN(C)OVAs or multiple motivation, cognition/appraisals,
regression curiosity/appraisals, personality/
- to - temperament, coping/resilience, mood/
Aside from variations in factor/main effect self, majority/minority status
levels related to G, E, D, and O, sex or (demographics), and so on, as further
gender influences on behavior; the person
as a main effect/fact complicates matters, has a behavioral determination and
especially for 4-way statistical interactions expression
in MANANOVs, ANOVAs and - to -
multiple regression Organism variables might concern
correlated genetic ones, such as in
evocative or active gene–environment
correlation interactions or in niche
construction, in which organisms play
an active part in changing or eliciting
change in their environments
- to -
Complex factors, such as a belief in
free will and unconscious influences,
can influence/supercede genetic,
environmental, and other factors in their
influence on behavior and its choices
(continued)
732 29 Networked Causal Terms

Table 29.4 (continued)


Variation
Component Statistical Conceptual
Systems (add S; NLDST is mathematically grounded The systems model does not analyze
G × E × O × S) in approaches quite different from separately each variable of a set of
classic parametric approaches in variables one by one and for their main
psychology (e.g., differential equations) effects and interactive effects on other
- to - variables. Rather, a systems approach
The variation in the system variables seeks interactive patterns across all the
constitutes the foci of attention rather elements of the system and the manner
than being considered confounding “noise” in which they form patterns, or new
superordinate variables. Transformative
system change might include those
that are self-organized emergent ones,
such as in the creation of new attractors,
attractor splitting at bifurcation points,
major chaotic transitions even with minor
perturbations at far-from-equilibrium
points, the butterfly effect, etc.
- to -
In the following, I elaborate each of the
terms G, E, O, D, S. (G) generative
growth/maintenance promoting,
governing gene/genetic/genomic,
genotypic/genetic material in concert
with epigenetic/epigenomic, and marks/
stamps silencing genes × (E)
environmental/ecological (constructed)
niche, ecological/sociocultural (and
historicopolitical) influences × (O)
organismic/institutional/group/
organization (individual organism/
organ) and its (re)organization/
optimization (adaptation, susceptibility,
diathesis), and differentiation × (D)
development (ontogenesis), which is
also Darwinian (evolution,
phylogenesis, natural selection, survival/
reproduction/propagation, fitness)
nonlinear, self-organizational
(potentially emergent) as well as
dialectical/relational
and dynamical. It can be quantitative/
qualitative, and transformational/
plastic. It can include differential
susceptibility to environment (e.g.,
aversive, supportive environments
might affect development differentially
for certain alleles, not others) × (S)
stimulus/response (and organismic)
strategic/strategizing system (canalyzed/
constrained, yet stochastic/probabilistic,
or deterministic) that produces
activation/inhibition coordination
output in multiple hierarchical levels
of the system phenotype (approach/
withdrawal, physiology, neuronal,
neural, brain, neuropsychological,
behavioral, psychological).
(continued)
Eye-Catching Causal Terms 733

Table 29.4 (continued)


Variation
Component Statistical Conceptual
GEODS: The standard manner of representing
G∪E∪O∪D∪S Gene × Environment interaction is
(Gene × Environment × G × E. it has been expanded to include
Organism × G × E × D. These types of interactions
Development × are statistical, in the sense that a
System interaction) particular allele in conjunction with a
particular environment increases the
probability of a particular outcome
(perhaps only
at a particular developmental time).
However, Nature × Nurture is another
way of considering biological and
experiential (including cultural)
interactions. In this conception, the
factors are not involved in a statistical
interaction, but
they reciprocally influence each other,
with both contributing to
(developmental) outcome. This type of
concept can be represented as N ∪ N,
in which ∪ is a union symbol. For the
G × E interaction, to indicate how genes
and environment might interact
generally in a constitutive rather than a
statistical way, the representation of
G ∪ E could be used. In this regard, a
general model of Gene ∪ Environment
interaction that includes not only
development but also the organism and
the system as a whole could be
represented by G ∪ E ∪ O ∪ D ∪ S (or
simply GEODS).

are being better studied in multiple disciplines. In Eye-Catching Causal Terms


this regard, only a systems point of view can
accommodate to the multivariable and interactive The Causal Zoo
dynamics of behavioral complexity and its
development. “Causal weirdness” is the only term that fits the
phenomena that are emerging in science about
causality for both the microscopic, quantum and
Comment macroscopic, cosmic worlds, as explained next.
Not being an expert in these disciplines, I refer to
However, the field is far from having sufficiently popular science magazines to explain these
overarching and fully operationalized (and fully causal findings.
testable) model. New models need to be suffi- von Baeyer (2013) explained that, in the quan-
ciently developed and flexible enough to accom- tum realm, particles appear to occupy two loca-
modate the ever burgeoning, exponentially tions simultaneously, in a process of entanglement
growing research and theory that are being or “spooky” action at a distance. The particles,
published. such as electrons, appear to travel at a speed greater
734 29 Networked Causal Terms

than that of light, considered the upper limit of If the quantum world, already weird and
known speed is our known cosmic world. In this spooky in its standard formulation, is even
view, particles are represented by wave functions. stranger so that it reflects collective coordination
By calculating a particle’s wave function over time, of personal belief about wave function and quan-
probabilities related to its properties, such as their tum particles in action, the causal forces involved
estimated location, can be derived. in its activity must be inscrutable and intangible,
According to a new model, Quantum Bayesian perhaps like Einstein in Wonderland. The only
Theory (QBism), the problems and paradoxes metaphor that comes to mind to explain it is
associated with the standard quantum model con- “causal weirdness.” In the next paragraphs, I
cern assuming that a wave function is real. explain another metaphor that captures the
Rather, according to QBism, there is no objective unseizeable nature of causality, that of “dark
reality. Simply, it is a mathematical formula used causality.”
to assign one’s personal belief. Therefore, the Powell (2013) described the extent to which
person’s own choices and actions affect the quan- our universe is visible and invisible. The visible
tum system and its calculated properties in a way component consists of light, energy, matter, the
that is inherently uncertain. Earth, and the infinite number of cosmic particles
Moreover, different people can have different and bodies in the universe. However, our uni-
quantum-related wave functions and, therefore, verse is expanding at a rate that does not fit what
perceive differently the properties of the quan- we know of the visible universe, so there must be
tum system. A collective, coherent worldview of dark matter and energy to account for this and
the quantum world emerges from inter-observer related phenomena.
communication about observers’ private under- Scientists are finding not only about dark mat-
standing of wave functions. As observers modify ter and dark energy but also about their proper-
suddenly their personal wave functions, and ties, including their dynamic transformative
revisit their probability assignments, the wave properties. In this regard, dark matter might be
function “collapses” to a particular value after able to become visible. Moreover, the ultimate
having “spread out” after prior observation/cal- end-point of the logic entailed by this possibility
culation, so that apparent violations of the prin- is that there are dark universes in parallel with
ciple that particles can only be in one place at a ours.
time are more subjective than objective. In this sense, I propose that just as there is
According to QBism, the quantum system has dark matter and dark energy, there must also be
not changed, because wave functions are merely “dark causality.” Simply, causality is so multifac-
probability calculating tools and are subjective torial and complex that the algorithms of its
and personal rather than objective and real. The emergence and influence might be hidden,
only change that takes place with respect to wave ephemeral, ever-changing, and perhaps indeci-
functions is in the belief about personally- pherable to a degree for at least part of the time.
relevant wave functions, which are individually
selected by observers in order to “encapsulate”
personal expectations. [Note that this is not to Causicles
suggest that a person’s state of mind brings the
world into being.] “Causalization” could be the relevant catch-
The implication of QBism is that reality is phrase to capture the participation of causality in
shaped actively by ourselves and, moreover, as interactive reality, or the extent to which causal-
observers of this reality, our free will participates ity defines the universe more than the actions,
by setting its measurements. The act of measur- objects, and sequences involved. Causality could
ing creates the property in question, shaping it be the “sine quo non” or “nonpareil” variable in
“just a little” by its “participation” in a type of defining reality, which might therefore consist
“birthing” moment. uniquely of “causal particles” (“causicles”).
Coexistential Causal Intraactivism 735

To carry the concept enunciated to its logical and that free will is essential to all these aspects
extreme, the causal co-ordinations between of understanding causality and behavior. In all
effector (actuator) and effect (linked outcome) these regards, the unifying model that emerged
constitute the universe, and they need to be con- from my end-of-book reflection is that of
sidered as a “garden” of entities, both micro- and “Co-existential Causality” or, more precisely,
macroscopic, which defines all things, agents, that of “Co-existential Causal Intraactivism.” Let
organisms and, indeed, matter and energy in me explain.
both the physical and psychological worlds.
One of the hot topics in theology, cosmology, Coexistential
particle physics, and many other disciplines is the The term “co-existential” refers to the dialectical
topic about why we exist and why the universe existence of and interaction among diverse com-
exists. For example, the Big Bang might lie at the ponents of a topic at issue. I have applied the
origin of the universe in its present state, but it term to the epistemological stances that have
does not explain its source or reason. The answers been expressed about realism and constructiv-
to questions like these await further scientific and ism, for example, arguing that an integrated
conceptual inquiry. However, surely it can be framework would acknowledge the possibility of
argued that the universe would not exist without and even the necessity of having both views inte-
causal particles and their underlying stitching grated into one totality. Just as a photon of light
together of its constituents and also their stitch- can be viewed as a wave or a particle, depending
ing of our reality-informed conceptions of it. To on the observer and observation process, so can
conclude, causality constitutes each of the uni- one view among many views on a particular topic
verse, ourselves, and our interactions with it. reflect aspects of the ontology of the phenome-
Without it, there would be neither a universe nor non even if it apparently in contradiction with
ourselves. We are exquisitely and elegantly others. That is, in the totality of views seen
honed to live causality and to contribute to it. together, each might contribute to the whole even
if any two of them seem in opposition.

Coexistential Causal Intraactivism Intraaction


The term “intraactivism” is quite complementary
Model to the one of co-existentialism. It refers to more
than the interaction among components of a phe-
Introduction nomenon, whether behavioral, theoretical, or
In reflecting on the integrative theoretical efforts otherwise, because the construct of an interaction
in psychology that are being made involving the among components presupposes that the compo-
biopsychosocial model, dynamical systems the- nents can exist independently of the interaction,
ory, and the embodiment model, as well as oth- be dissociated from it and exist otherwise, and
ers, such as those of networks and affordances, it exist as separate entities that might conjoin at one
struck me that that I could carry further the moment but not at another. However, the term of
notions: (a) that causality is central to under- intraactivism connotes a reality much more com-
standing behavior; (b) that causality is central to plex and participatory or lived for both the com-
the activity of human behavior; (c) that causality ponents at issue in a phenomenon and their
can help cohere the diverse models on human interaction. That is, the components in an intraac-
behavior; (d) that causality can help the field of tivist system exist because of and through the
psychology cohere, as well, and it can do the interactions (of the intraaction type, or simply,
same for related disciplines; (e) that humans are “intraactive interaction”) involved. Thus, the
really Homo Causa in several ways, such as in intraactive interaction in a system at issue is cen-
their causalization processes and their effective tral to the phenomenon more than the compo-
adaptation requiring causal understanding; (f) nents. The components cannot be dissociated or
736 29 Networked Causal Terms

separated from the interactions involved and can- Note that the term intraactivism is different
not exist by themselves. They never exist without than the ones of interactionism, interactionalism,
being in intraactive interaction. They owe their interactism, and interactivism (e.g., Bickhard,
existence to their intraactive interactions and, 2012; Campbell, 2014) because it considers that
also, the nature of these intraactive interactions any term that incorporates the word interactions,
that are involved define their properties. by definition, implies that the components in the
In this regard, as traditionally defined, interac- reciprocally-defining meeting of the components
tions do not even exist. The term presupposes might be independent entities that exist outside
that there are components interacting and that the meeting, which is contradictory to how meet-
interactions relate them. However, in the concept ings are being defined in the concept of intraac-
of intraactions, the components are fluid and tivism. That being said, the concept borrows
defined by their interrelations and, also, the con- heavily from the one of interactivism. Finally,
stituting interactions involved supercede them. note that the term intraactivism is a quite novel
Because they do not exist in and of themselves, one, and for sake of simplicity, I keep using the
their interactions, as traditionally defined, do not term interactions in the explication of the con-
exist either. Therefore, the implication is that the cept, but, as indicated already, at the same time, I
intraactions are the system rather than the puta- qualify the interaction as an intraactive one.
tive system components and their interactions
being the system. Causality
If we carry this argument to its extreme, it Adding the term of causality (or causal) to the
means that reality is constituted by intraactions term of intraaction accomplishes several objec-
and, also, the components of reality are only tives. First, it indicates the centrality of causality
intraactions. Components do not exist indepen- for relevant psychological theorizing, as per the
dent of them. various points made about the goals of creating
Therefore, it is important that work is under- such a term. Second, it allows me to continue
taken to define intraaction systemics, or what emphasizing causality as a cohering theme to the
constitutes the nature of intraactions. Network present work, one that goes beyond the focus on
modeling gives us a beginning language in this any of free will, the biopsychosocial model, evo-
regard, and so does systems theory. However, I lution or development, including my own model
could add that variations in intraaction types in these regards (Young, 2011), and so on.
might involve—intraactive system stability
induction or its alteration; intraactive system Conclusion
component stabilization or their transformation; Putting together the terms of coexistential,
various reciprocal interactions, feedback loop- causal, and intraactivism gives a powerful inte-
ing; growth containment/pruning vs. augmenta- grative psychological model that demonstrates
tion/promotion, which includes enhancing the following with respect to the five goals in cre-
adaptive organization vs. regression/dissolution ating the term that were elucidated above. That
induction; and all with and between different lev- is, the new Coexistential Causal Intraactivism
els of the system to the point that self- model that I am creating helps integrate under-
organizational emergence can take place even at standing of—human behavior; the activity of
the intraactive level. In this regard, emergence human behavior; models in psychology; psychol-
deriving from intraactive interactions could ogy itself; how humans are Homo Causa; and the
involve both the nature of the components critical role of free will in all these aspects.
involved and the nature of the intraactions them-
selves, with any of these having properties that Human Behavior (a) Causality is so central to
are defined uniquely by the continual, participa- the understanding behavior that a model that pur-
tory interdigitation of the components involved ports to explain behavior in all its complexity
in the intraactive interactions. needs to include the term in one way or another in
Coexistential Causal Intraactivism 737

its title. Behavior cannot be fully understood they interact. The concept of intraactivism allows
without understanding both its “what” and for both grasping the manner of component
“why,” and, indeed, the why takes prominence intraactive interaction in behavioral causation
over the what—the product in behavior derives among the biological, personal, and social com-
from a process that shapes it, impregnates it, epit- ponents involved and the nature of the behavior
omizes it, and gives it its substance and identity. itself. In this regard, I have argued that a mecha-
nism that speaks to the intraactive constitutive-
Activity (b) Human activity is especially causal ness among the components of the biopsychosocial
in nature in both the means and the ends of model involves activation/inhibition coordina-
behavior. Cognition, emotion, and action are tion, and the nature of the behavioral process
embedded in and focus on causality, and they are reflective of this concept, by definition, is one
an intraactive product of the resonating, intraac- that expresses perfectly intraactivism.
tivist engagement of the person with the niche as
the person undertakes efforts to arrive at contex- Systems Examination of systems theory and
tually adaptive ends, which can be achieved best the model of embodiment lead to the same con-
when the person is the top causal engine in the clusion—that the notion of Coexistential Causal
environment, acting on it toward evolutionary Intraactivism suggests ways that the models
survival and reproduction in one way or another can be extended toward their integration with
(while respecting it). other models and also toward a model that inte-
grates all of them. For instance, for systems
theory, the concept of emergence through self
Models organization is critical in helping explain how
behavior can become increasingly complex and
Introduction (c) Adopting a coexistential differentiated and escape reductionist influ-
stance to various integrative models in psychol- ences and tendencies. The concept of circular
ogy permits seeing each of them as valuable and causality has been used to explain the move-
contributing different aspects to the integration. ment out of one level of a system into a more
Adding in causality as central to this theoretical advanced one in its hierarchical arrangement,
integration enables us to see each of the contribu- producing an emergent behavior or a new
tory models in a different light, but also empha- behavioral organization or level, and I have
sizes that, inevitably, they deal with causality one modified the concept by referring to a circular
way or another. Finally, considering the integra- causal emergence (Young, 2011).
tion of various psychological theories from the The levels of a system are not separate, though,
point of view of intraactivism indicates how they and, in this regard, they should be subject to the
could be combined themselves through their con- same kind of reciprocal intraactivism that I have
ceptual interaction. Also, the term of intraactiv- explained to apply to linked components of a
ism indicates that the nature of the integration of phenomenon, including for behavior and its cau-
psychological theories toward their unification sation. That is, in circular causal emergence
should emphasize the constitutive intraactive between levels and components of a system that
interaction that the term implies both for the creates new emergent components or levels, the
expression of behavior and also how its causes nature of the constituting interactions that takes
interact, going beyond each of them in creating place to create the emergence is not the tradi-
the whole and intraactive person. tional interactive one that has been described but
the new intraactive one that is being posited.
Biopsychosocial For example, the biopsycho-
social model considers the major components to Embodiment As for embodiment, this model
behavioral causality in its formulation, but it is could profit from considering that the linkages
missing a good mechanistic explanation in how between physical, corporal, bodily, and brain
738 29 Networked Causal Terms

structure and functioning and those involving create a whole that denies their separability,
behavior, action, mind, cognition, and emotion, as while, at the same time, defining them. Perhaps
well as the linkages between people, are dynami- the term of the biopersonalsocial model that I
cally intraactivist and formative of the components created can serve that goal, although it was not
in the intraactive interactions. Body does not meet constructed for this purpose. That is, the word
mind and interact with it, but their intraaction cre- personal exists in the term, but not as a separate
ates both. People are not independent agents who one from the bio and social terms preceding and
communicate as separate bodies, but they are following it, respectively, so it might fit the bill.
intraactively created in their intraactive interac- For the systems model, emergence might
tions. For example, listening and talking both are take place in systems, and that would suggest a
constitutively intraactive. In this regard, as I just kind of intraactivism. However, as shown above
wrote to my family as they communicated about in discussing the concept of circular causal
communication—when you listen, it has to be in emergence, the concept of emergence in sys-
an active way in which what you hear genuinely tems theory still involves components, or per-
enters and transforms the networks in your haps levels, in interaction, albeit reciprocal.
thoughts and being, assuming that they have some Moreover, emergence is not the only end-point
value. When you talk, it is much the same process. or pathway in systems. There might be minor
You consider the context, person, and ongoing changes or no changes despite perturbations. In
conversation and speak with new constructions this model, components can exist as indepen-
that fit the moment, including novel ones never dent entities that conjoin in patterns or configu-
thought or said. The other is not just a sounding rations, as needed, but still keep their properties.
board but also a prism in which your ideas radiate Compared to the approach of intraactivism, the
back into yourself in multiple changing forms and interactions that take place in standard systems
lights and also affect the other in the same way. theory allows for a causality that can be a sim-
ple affair instead of emanating from a complex-
Comment That said, any of the major extant ity landscape of intraactions involving the
theories in psychology can be modified in some inevitable creation of new properties of compo-
way to fit the intraactivist concept. For example, nents and redefining them.
in a dynamically growing model of embodi- This example illustrates that: (a) intraactivism
ment, theorists should not reject that realism is constitutive of phenomena such as reality, and
and constructivism can co-exist in one model (b) components of phenomena subject to intraac-
and that the person can be viewed from the lens tivism are defined by them, and this obtains even
of both models. in their properties. However, even if at the sur-
The same proviso applies to the revised con- face it seems that these are apparently contradic-
ceptions of the biopsychosocial and systems tory statements about the nature of things, they
models that I have presented. For the biopsycho- reflect a deeper reality—recall that I have argued
social model, the three major constituents that that apparently contradictory and opposition
interact to create its term also interact to create things might exist simultaneously in the essence
the person, but in the model as presently con- of things because they can express a dual nature
structed, each of its constituent components can like do photons of light, being either particle or
stand as independent entities. Each can exist wave depending on the observer/observation pro-
beyond their interaction as direct causal influ- cess. In this regard, there is no contradiction in
ences on the person. admitting a dialectic between opposite poles of a
However, from the perspective of intraactiv- phenomenon and, as I have argued for the school
ism, the biopsychosocial model needs some way of relationism itself in Chap. 35, there is no con-
of realizing that three terms that comprise it are tradiction in having a dialectic between a pole
indissociable, mutually constitutive, and serve to that is dialectical in nature, such as relationism,
Coexistential Causal Intraactivism 739

and one that is not, such as realism, especially if Psychology


one is seeking a superordinate model that can
accommodate both their advantages and Introduction (d) Psychology is a discipline that
disadvantages. is a science. It attempts to understand behavior,
its organization, and its causes. It uses scientific
Network The network model has much poten- methodology to investigate the nature of behav-
tial toward the unification of psychology ior, and scientific reasoning to explain the out-
because it resembles the systems model, and comes of its investigations. It is a science that is
even has surpassed it in some ways, for exam- continually evolving in conceptualization,
ple, through its concepts of centrality, effi- methodology, and aims. It has a practical side, of
ciency, betweenness, small worlds, hubs, and course, in its clinical applications, in particular.
so on. Without belaboring the point, it could In this regard, it uses the scientific method and
profit from the presently proposed coexisten- experimentation to determine best practices that
tial, causal, and intraactivist behavioral model are evidence-supported. However, there are tens
by emphasizing that networks involve the con- of schools of psychotherapy that have been cre-
stitutiveness inherent in the model. Networks ated, and the research in their support, at times, is
exist not as passive relay stations but as criticized for lacking external and ecological
dynamically living and active pathways that validity. Also, the diagnostic manuals of disor-
are even more important that the localized ders developed in psychiatry have hundreds of
components or regions involved in the transi- categories that they include, and their clinical
tioning between them. utility has been questioned. In response, there is a
movement to retreat to the medical model and
Affordances As for the model of affordances, neuroscience as the basis for understanding men-
it could be improved by reconfiguring it in terms tal illness and how to best treat it (the RDoC proj-
of intraactivism in the sense that the invitations ect; Research Domain of Criteria; Insel et al.,
proffered by salient environmental cues need to 2010; Insel & Lieberman, 2013).
be better reinforced as reciprocally-defined However, if psychology (and psychiatry)
intraactive products more than as independently would attempt to integrate across—experimental
existing environmental properties. Causality work and clinical practice; its major therapeutic
inheres in organism–environment relations schools under one rubric; the disparate disorders
more than organisms acting on the environment into a coherent framework that reduces their over-
or the environment dictating to the organism whelming complexity; and the medical model
how to act. with ones such as the biopsychosocial one—it
might advance beyond the inherent limitations
Comment At this juncture, given that the cen- and contradictions that are evident in its present
tral argument has been made, I refrain from con- state. The degree to which the presently proposed
tinuing the exercise of showing how the model of Coexistential Causal Intraactivism can
concepts of co-existentialism, causality, and help arrive at these goals is addressed next.
intraactivism, along with their combination in The model being proposed can especially help
the model that I have created of Coexistential psychology cohere over its various divisions and
Causal Intraactivism, can help toward refining splits, and also resolve some of its inconsisten-
other major models in psychology and move cies and contradictions, if not its controversies,
them toward an integration that would help because, above all, it offers an integrative model
unify the field of psychology itself. Instead, in of human behavior. It places at the apex of human
the following, I explore directly the latter propo- activity causally-oriented behavior and the
sition in depth. intraactivist nature of behavioral manifestation
740 29 Networked Causal Terms

and its creation, in which intraactive interactions be less of a missed guesswork and more of an
are the constituents of behavior more than the appropriately informed scientific enterprise.
components in these interactions, and also inter- That being said, I remind that in the search for
actions between people define their essence more the unification of psychology, there can never be
than their personhood that they bring to the inter- one best answer, even the one that I am suggest-
action. It depicts the causal mechanisms underly- ing as leading toward a better unification. It is
ing behavior as multiple, reciprocally interacting, better to refer to the process of unifying psychol-
and intraactivist, with emergence a possible out- ogy rather than the state of its unification. Both
come through these interactions in the causal process and product work together intraactively
web that is greater than the sum of the parts and in systems, and the same would apply to how
even defining of the parts. psychology works, and moreover, the process is
continual and the resultant product ever-changing.
Application Because of the apogeal under- That is why the present book refers to the project
standing of behavior that the Coexistential Causal of unifying psychology (and of causality). As
Intraactivist model permits, the various models long as we are on that path, the field can prosper
that have been proposed to explain behavior can and avoid some of its ingrowing.
be subsumed under its guise through the types of
expansions that I have provided above. The dif- Homo Causa (e) This present book has empha-
ferences among the models can be accommo- sized causality as central to behavior, but it has
dated by appropriate extensions and modifications now shifted to a model in which intraactivism is
to make them more similar to each other and considered critical to explaining behavior and its
reflective of a broader, superordinate model causes. In this regard, I still consider humans as
involving co-existentialism, causality, and causalization machines and the engagement in
intraactivism. Furthermore, this type of thinking causal thought and related behavior as the supreme
can be applied to the schism between experimen- markers of our adaptive efforts. For me, intraactiv-
tal and clinical work because people’s behavior ism as a concept does not override the one of cau-
could be explained using these types of concepts, sality in the characterization of our exceptionalism.
whether they fall in the normal, adaptive range or Causality is the focus of what we do because of its
the abnormal, disordered one. Also, the diagnos- evolutionary advantages, and intraactivism helps
tic manuals would be revised to accommodate to explain how we causalize and also what is the
the relational, intraactive turn and to fixate less nature of the behaviors that we use in doing so.
on the internally disordered model of mental ill- There is no need to call humans Homo Intraactivus
ness. This relational stance applies both between instead of Homo Causa in the present formulation
the person and the environment and between one of what especially makes us human. The same
symptom and the next. For the former, mental applies to the concept of co-existentialism. That
disorder might not lie in a fixed symptom list but being said, the present integrative model of behav-
in how each symptom relates to and derives from ior of Coexistential Causal Intraactivism rein-
the context as much as from the so-called forces, by its very nature and label, the importance
internally-generated and constitutional factors. of causality in human behavior and its essence. In
For the former, symptom causality might not lie this sense, this addition to the present work adds to
in relation to a latent psychological construct or the message that causality is central to understand-
factor but to the intraactive interactional chains ing human behavior.
from one symptom to the next and how they
relate to context. Finally, treatments would Free Will (f) Finally, free will is another concept
become whole because the person could be that has been emphasized in the present work, and
understood better as a whole, and the medical one needs to ask if my appreciation of its relevance
model would be complemented by the biopsy- for understanding human behavior and its causes
chosocial and intraactivist one. Etiology would has changed because of the new model that I have
Chapter Conclusions 741

created on Coexistential Causal Intraactivism. To integral to these themes about causality, given
the contrary, the grounds for maintaining that free their supreme role in behavioral causality.
will is an emergent phenomenon and that behavior Moreover, the notion of applying together the con-
cannot be reduced to deterministic influences has cepts of coexistentiality, causality, and intraaction-
been reinforced by the concept of intraactivism, as ality in phenomena would appear to have wider
well as the application of the one of co-existential- applicability than the topic of the present book.
ism to the present question. Intraactivism, by defi-
nition, facilitates emergence, and free will cannot Broad Intraactive Ethics For example, I have
exist otherwise. proposed a model of broad ethics (Young, 2014)
and it reflects the concept of “broad intraactive
ethics” for mental health (Young, 2015). In this
Conclusions regard, ethical behavior should not be considered
a component of our professional (or personal)
Coexistential Causal Intraactionism Coexisten- life, but constitutive from it and a product of the
tial Causal Intraactionism is a concept that I created multiple, lived intraactive interactions in which
to help summarize the essence of the present book, we engage. Ethics might rise to the surface as a
and a Google search on April 13, 2015, indicated topic to consider in dilemmas, but their solution
absolutely no entry for the term of intraaction in the can arrive best if we are proactive, positive about
listing offered. The term represents a superordinate it, immersed in it, and informed by it, and living
model of phenomena that includes behavior and its it in each micromoment of our professional lives.
causation. The concept involved is nonlinear in Ethics does not reside in the components of the
nature, as in systems theory, and it resembles this guidelines, standards, and writings on the topic,
latter model through its opening to emergence as a but in how we are constituted at the ethical level
possible outcome of the intraactive interaction by them as we interact intraactively with them
dynamics that might take place. However, it differs and apply them constitutively in our relationships
from system theory concepts through the constitu- with patients, colleagues, and society.
tive nature of the interactions that it proposes to take
place among the components of the system as it
arranges and rearranges its patterns over them. To Chapter Conclusions
remind, a system exists through the interaction of its
components, which are intraactive interactions, and The present chapter defines both basic and criti-
not in the separate components of the system as they cal terms in the field of psychology that help
interact. To simplify, pattern (or component configu- understand causality. Some of the basic terms
ration) is system, and system is not components cre- have been used throughout the present book, but
ating pattern. are clarified in this chapter. Some of the terms
This type of conceptualization, when coupled are new to the present work, and have been cre-
with the concepts of co-existential and causality, ated in order to help move the study of causality
can serve as an overarching concept that—inte- in psychology more toward center stage, or at
grates the major themes of the book; underscores least to promote thinking about this critical area.
the centrality of causality both to understanding The critical novel models developed in the chap-
behavior and in the activity of behavior; points to ter pertaining to causality in psychology relate to
the centrality of causality to psychology (and the constructs of networks and intraactivism.
related disciplines) and that it can serve as a focus The chapter also shows the complexity involved
of integration for it; and that free will and related in gene–environment interactions by indicating
concepts, such as free will belief, having a sense of that development, the organism, and systems
free will, freedom in being, and free being, are also are involved.
742 29 Networked Causal Terms

References Insel, T. R., & Lieberman, J. A. (2013). DSM-5 and


RDoC: Shared interests. The National Institute of
Mental Health. http://www.nimh.nih.gov/news/
Bickhard, M. H. (2012). A progress ontology for persons
science-news/2013/dsm-5-and-rdoc-shared-interests.
and their development. New Ideas in Psychology, 30,
shtml
107–119.
Powell, C. (2013). Darklands of the cosmos. Discover,
Campbell, R. L. (2014). Giving naturalism a chance:
90–93.
Interactivism, emergence, and nonlinearity. Cosmos
Sporns, O. (2011). Networks of the brain. Cambridge,
and History, 10, 118–130.
MA: MIT Press.
Ellis, B. J., Boyce, W. T., Belsky, J., Bakermans-
Sporns, O. (2012). Discovering the human connectome.
Kranenburg, M. J., & van IJzendoorn, M. H.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
(2011). Differential susceptibility to the environ-
von Baeyer, H. C. (2013). Quantum weirdness? It’s all in
ment: An evolutionary-neurodevelopmental theory.
your mind. Scientific American, 308(6), 47–51.
Development and Psychopathology, 23, 7–28.
Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
Holland, J. H. (2012). Signals and boundaries: Building Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science +
blocks for complex adaptive systems. Cambridge, MA: Business Media.
MIT Press. Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feigning, and response
Insel, T. R., Cuthbert, B. N., Garvey, M. A., Heinssen, bias in psychiatric/psychological injury: Implications
R. K., Pine, D. S., Quinn, K. J., et al. (2010). Research for practice and court. Dordrecht, Netherlands:
domain criteria (RDoC): Toward a new classification Springer Science + Business Media.
framework for research on mental disorders. American Young, G. (2015, in preparation). A Broad Ethics model.
Journal of Psychiatry, 167, 748–751. Ethics, Medicine, and Public Health, 1.
Change Mechanisms
30

my work on stages and substages in development,


Chapter Introduction and the change processes and mechanisms
involved therein.] In this regard, the chapter
The last chapter on concepts and terms in the concludes by presenting models related to readi-
field of the psychological study of causality ness for change and dimensions of change. The
reviewed both basic and new concepts. The latter last part of the chapter expands the concept of
focused on an integrated network model as well intraaction, as well.
as an intraactive model. The present chapter
concentrates on the behavioral change process
and its mechanism. In this regard, it describes in Neuromal Network
depth the activation/inhibition coordination
model that I have developed. Introduction
First, the chapter expands the network model
into the “neurome” (or neuromal network), a The manner in which systems can self-organize
term that I created in order to capture the full to create emergent phenomena resides in its con-
range of neuronal/central nervous system factors cept of (a) interactions between components to
involved in behavior. I explain the construct of create amalgams distinct from the components
the neuromal network and the change mecha- and (b) interactions of components within levels
nisms and processes that affect it. to create superordinate levels. Circular causality
As with the present book, in general, these derives through these interactions and refers to
change processes and mechanisms are seen to the reciprocal vertical nested interactions over
especially relate to nonlinear dynamical systems lower- and higher-order levels of a system
theory (NLDST), also called chaos theory, and to (Lewis, 2000a, 2000b, 2005) as well as horizon-
concept of activation/inhibition coordination. I tal within-level interactions or couplings in the
explore the model from several different system.
perspectives. Jost, Bertschinger, and Olbrich (2010) pre-
In addition, I introduce in much more detail sented a model of system emergence based on
than before my five stages × five substages model top levels of a system having higher “scales” or
of Neo-Piagetian development (Young, 2011) regularities not accessible at lower levels, nor
and show how it applies to change processes and inferable from them. A level of a system that is
also to mechanisms. [Note that this part of the superordinate to another one gains in resistance
chapter helps to prepare the way for the final part to change that would take place at lower levels
of the book, which explores in much more detail due to perturbations by the superordinate level

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 743


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_30
744 30 Change Mechanisms

acting to “enslave” variables at lower levels, lifespan. The crux of the model concerns the
thereby bringing stability to the system. developing “neuromal network” complex that
In Young (2011), I proposed the concept of can dynamically self-assemble at increasingly
“circular emergence” to account for the process sophisticated emergent levels supportive of
of emergence. In this model of emergence, differ- increasingly sophisticated cognitive capacities
ent levels of a system not only are reciprocally related to local and/or domain-specific skills,
coordinated, but also they are reciprocally emer- such as executive function and self-regulation,
gent and bootstrapping, allowing both upper and and to global and/or more advanced steps or even
lower levels of a system to undergo emergent stages, such as in Neo-Piagetian models. By neu-
change within themselves beyond creation of any romal, I refer to the full range of neurome con-
new superordinate levels. stituents, from neurons and neurotransmitters, to
Finally, according to Young (2011), the neuronal and cross-neuronal networks, to cortical
mechanism that allows the preservation or con- lobes and hemispheres.
servation as well as the escape from far-from- In this model that I have developed, the neu-
equilibrium of system state concerns activation/ rome is an environmentally-responsive, vital,
inhibition coordination. This union of funda- cue-detecting apparatus that is stochastic or
mental system forces might act to help the sys- probabilistically-tuned about each of (a) the
tem resist change or help it facilitate the nature of environmental cues, (b) the perceptual
exploration of novel spaces beyond basic regions and cognitive systems that deal with them, and
(attractor basins) to which a system might typi- (c) the response options and actions that it gener-
cally gravitate or explore, thereby giving it new ates. It is phenotypically plastic, especially given
flexibility to either remain unchanged or to its ongoing developmental modification, even if
change in its plasticity. it is comprised, in part, of genetically-proximal
The concepts of system self-assembly, circu- (neuro)endophenotypic constructions. It is adap-
lar causality, circular emergence, and so on, tive in its function in an evolutionary sense of
apply generally to any system adapting to its con- serving and promoting survival and reproduc-
text. When applied to human development, there tion, as well as adapting in an ongoing sense in
are specifics to add, including those related to matching organism needs to ongoing environ-
genes (and their biological transcriptions), the mental exigencies.
environment, neuronally, or of others, such as in The neuromal network is an exquisitely devel-
parenting, and for the person as a whole. opmental one, both in terms of local, micro-
In the following, I expand these concepts to developmental transactive processes online in
apply to the neurome, which is a catchword that I context and global, macro-developmental, trans-
created to represent the nervous system and its formative ones over ontogenetic time (e.g.,
components from a network and systems per- months, years). By development, I refer to change
spective. The model is quite developmental, as in behavior and its organization that includes not
well. only cognitive ones but also related ones that are
social and emotional ones, such that behavioral
regulation concerns an executive control at all
Model these levels. Behavior at any one time is a reflec-
tion of multiple forces biologically and environ-
Table 30.1 presents a model of emergence in mentally, but the person also contributes actively
behavior that is developmentally-tuned and that to the probabilistic sampling of behavior, their
allows for development of increasingly complex, processing, and the decisions taken on options to
advanced, or higher-order stages throughout the follow in action.
Activation/Inhibition Coordination 745

Table 30.1 An adapting neuromal network complex—an integrated cross-network (ICN) model: terms
Element Definition
Probabilistic, plastic Not fixed, but influenced by pre-existing states; open to experience, sampled;
with response options, including anticipatory ones
Adaptive/adapting Ongoing adjustment and evolutionarily selected
Dynamic, self-organizing Self-assembling, including with possible major state transitions to different
areas of the system’s state space, even after minor perturbations if far from
equilibrium
Emergent, hierarchical Systems are multilevel, expressing reciprocal circular causality over
top-down and bottom-up levels/influences, allowing for level reorganization
and even superordinate level creation
Cognition (dual process) For cognitive architecture: stages and substages. For self-regulation/executive
control: automatic, fast, unconscious; reflective, deliberate, slow, conscious
Activation/inhibition coordination At each level of a system (and also between them), the dynamic mechanism
of adaptation could be described in terms of multiple parameters, including
energy flow, information, resources, degrees of freedom, equilibrium, and
adaptability. One metric that might be common to these approaches involves
activation/inhibition coordination. Whether examining the person at the level
of brain, neuron, behavior, personality, or social adaptation, activation/
inhibition coordination describes both the process and output
Integrative system Systems are multilevel hierarchical arrangements that take the form or pattern
that best fits its extant components in context. As they accommodate, they
become open to further growth toward complexity, as new input/energy,
information either arrives or is sought
Neuromal The collection that is the brain, central nervous system, neurons, neuronal
networks, neurotransmitters, etc.
Neuromal networked The neurome refers to the collection of neuronal and related agents, including
neurotransmitters, the various nervous systems, and the brain and its compo-
nents. They form networks at each level and are networked amongst them

Activation/Inhibition Coordination These explanations of system emergence are


not necessarily equivalent and at the same level
Model of explication of system dynamics. Nevertheless,
they share common assumptions about nonlinear
I have described previously in the present book dynamical system function. (a) Systems are self-
the concept of activation/inhibition coordination. organizing and there is no central pattern genera-
In this section, I expand the concept to show how tor. Systems inherently seek gracefully the best
it can promote emergent change in behavior and adaptive, online fit of extant components in con-
its organization, in the context of elaborating the text in the patterns that they construct. (b)
concept of the neurome. Systems exist in tension or in balance at many
The dynamic alteration of extant regimes in a levels—locally and globally; probabilistically
system’s state space has been described in terms and deterministically; randomly and predictably;
of (a) reaching critical thresholds of index param- tendency to stability/equilibrium/order and ten-
eters, (b) the butterfly effect, or major changes in dency to change/disequilibrium/disorder; famil-
state due to minor perturbations at far-from- iar, repeating trajectories and novel, transient
equilibrium conditions, (c) accommodating to ones; increasing and decreasing degrees of free-
changing entropic conditions via the metric of dom; and simplicity and complexity.
free energy, (d) increasing ultimate degrees of However, despite the broad understanding of
freedom in system responsiveness at higher lev- system dynamics in relation to emergence, to my
els, partly by enslaving and reducing degrees of knowledge there has not been one metric pro-
freedom in components at lower levels, and so on. posed related to change toward the novel that is
746 30 Change Mechanisms

equivalent to the principles underlying the lent developmental and behavioral emergence. In
dynamic of atom combination in forming aggre- this regard, both neuromal network activity and
gated compounds and molecules. In this regard, I behavior would seem to be constituted by, and
propose that the concept of activation/inhibition facilitated by, activation/inhibition coordination.
coordination holds this potential. To represent better the activation/inhibition
In this regard, activation/inhibition coordina- coordination mechanism dynamic, first I indicate
tion potentially constitutes a common metric how emergence can be represented in a system
over the multiple levels of the neuromal and through the example of water. The classic exam-
behavioral system that allows their integration ple of emergence in NLDST concerns how water
through reciprocal causality both within and emerges from the adhering of hydrogen and oxy-
across levels. Keep in mind that activation at one gen (H2O); its property of wetness is unpredict-
level might take place in order to inhibit activity, able from the properties of its constituent atoms.
or vice versa, with the same applying to relations One can represent the process of emergence and
in these functions over levels. maintenance of water in the following way:
This mechanism has the capacity to temper H2O × E/T × S = Current State of H2O. That is,
constant change dynamics in the system with bal- water exists in a water cycle managed by energy
anced conserving tendencies so that change is (E) that circulates in and interacts with the sys-
environmentally-matched and developmentally tem over time (T) as it governs state system (S)
constructive. As different system levels (higher, transitions.
lower, top-down, bottom-up) organize and reor- To illustrate this argument, as mentioned, acti-
ganize in a process of graceful or economic vation/inhibition coordination can be represented
accommodation to the constant input of the envi- as I ∪ A, with ∪ representing union, as in set the-
ronment toward adaptation, change, growth, and ory. It is important to note that in the model, acti-
complexification, the mechanism of activation/ vation/inhibition coordination refers both to the
inhibition coordination could be the one that per- mechanism of system change (or stability preser-
mits the different components and interactions in vation) and to a way of describing the behavior of
the system both within and between levels to the system. Activation/inhibition coordination
reciprocally and circularly interrelate, and even seems to be both a common descriptive device
to evolve self-assembling and emergent new and an actuating mechanism at multiple levels of
superordinate levels. Note that the concept of systems, for example, even in neurons. Therefore,
activation/inhibition coordination can be repre- the concept can apply across the full range of
sented by the union function (∪), as in I ∪ A. Also behavior, brain, and the neurome.
note that I place inhibition before activation in Figure 30.1 indicates that as “A ∪ I” processes
the symbolization of the concept because the work, allowing for reciprocal system interac-
inhibitory component of the mechanism is the tions, they form unions themselves, both hori-
one that allows the coordination involved to take zontally within system levels and vertically over
place smoothly. levels. This process includes the formation of
new, superordinate levels, which then are emer-
gent ones, the nature of which is unpredictable
Emergence from how the system existed before the
emergence.
Figure 30.1 illustrates how the mechanism of In this regard, the figure indicates that, as acti-
activation/inhibition coordination (I ∪ A) could vation/inhibition coordination entities recipro-
function to create refinements within extant cally interact and lead to superordinate union
levels of a system that help promote emergent, entities of activation/inhibition coordination, the
new superordinate ones. The figure emphasizes entities could have properties distinct from the
the process of circular emergence in the neuro- component ones involved in the union in terms of
mal network leading to corresponding, equiva- activation/inhibition coordination, per se. Instead
Activation/Inhibition Coordination 747

I∪A123
Integration

I∪A12 I∪A
23

Part
of
n(n)
I∪A1 I∪A2 I∪A
3
I∪A

Development

Fig. 30.1 Multilevel, circularly emerging, is a union or compound function the properties of which
activation/inhibition coordination neuromal network. are different than those of its components (I, A). As I ∪ A
Note. I = inhibition; A = activation; ∪ = coordination entities interact and interrelate reciprocally, they form
(union); 1, 2, 3 = first-order network; 12, 23 = second- unions themselves, both horizontally within system levels
order network; 123 = third-order network; nn – nth and vertically over levels, including the formation of new,
order = n(n); = reciprocal causality (top-down, bottom- superordinate levels. This process describes how emer-
gence might take place in systems that are neuronal and
up, including union). Activation/inhibition coordination behavioral in ways analogous to the classic example of
(I ∪ A) can be used both to describe behavior and to qual- how atoms combine to form molecules with properties
ify the process involved in its unfolding. It applies to all different from those of the constituents (e.g., wetness in
levels of the neuronal (neuromal) network and behavior. It water, H2O)

of seeing the fields of behavior, brain, and other following way: I ∪ A (Behavior) × E/T × S = Current
related entities as distinct and descriptively dis- State of I ∪ A (Behavior). That is, behavior can be
similar, once can simply state that the parameters expressed by an activation/inhibition coordination
in the expression of behavior or output at any that exists in a system cycle managed by energy (E)
level of a system can be described in terms of that circulates in and interacts with the system over
I ∪ A and, equivalently, the underpinning mecha- time (T) as it governs behavioral state system (S)
nisms in body and brain that are associated with transitions. Note that the formula for brain function
the behavioral output of the system involved can is the same: I ∪ A (Brain function) × E/T × S = Current
be represented by the same formula. State of I ∪ A (Brain function). That is, behavior can
In terms of a formula equivalent to the one for be expressed by an activation/inhibition coordina-
water that I constructed and presented above, it tion that exists in a system cycle managed by energy
would appear that behavior can be represented in the (E) that circulates in and interacts with the system
748 30 Change Mechanisms

over time (T) as it governs behavioral state system system processes, such as chaotic change in
(S) transitions: I ∪ A (Behavior) × E/T × S = Current attractor pattern reconfiguration.
State of I ∪ A (Behavior). If one were to construct a
general formula over brain and behavior expressed
in terms of activation/inhibition coordination, it Activation/Inhibition Coordination
might look like the following: behavior/brain/neuro-
mal function can be expressed by an activation/inhi- In Young (2011), I indicated how activation/inhi-
bition coordination that exists in a system cycle bition coordination could be involved in each
managed by energy (E) that circulates in and inter- step of a generic change model based on my Neo-
acts with the system over time (T) as it governs Piagetian cognitive developmental model.
behavior/brain/neuromal function state system (S) Table 30.2 indicates the extent and type of activa-
transitions. Mathematically, the specific formula tion/inhibition coordination associated with the
would be I ∪ A (behavior/brain/neuromal func- present model of steps in the change process.
tion) × E/T × S = Current State of I ∪ A (behavior/ There are five steps in the present generic change
brain/neuromal function). model. Each one appears to witness an increase
in the sophistication of activation/inhibition
coordination processes, e.g., from fleeting, to
Comment flowing, to flexible. The range of application of
the activation/inhibition coordination increases,
If the proposal makes sense, more work is needed as well, from specific and local to spreading and
to marry it to mathematical approaches in general. The nature of the activation/inhibition
NLDST. In the following, I return to the concept coordination evolves from a short-term simpler
of the neurome and its relation to activation/inhi- variety to a long-term complex variety.
bition coordination. The table illustrates the steps in the process:
(a) The column that presents the five steps in the
generic sequence indicates an initial coordination
Steps of the elements; (b) In the next step, they form a
dominant-subordinate hierarchical relationship;
In the following, I examine how the present five- (c) Next, the hierarchical relationship evolves
step model of development and the equivalent into a more systematic relationship; (d) This
one of generic change relate mechanisms that leads to expansion of the new relationship type
might help move them through the steps involved. throughout the system; (e) Finally, the elements
First, I show this for activation/inhibition coordi- arrive at an integration, which is a step that pre-
nation and then I show it for nonlinear dynamical pares for a repeat of the cycle.

Table 30.2 Activation/inhibition dynamics within each step of the present generic change model
Step Activation/inhibition coordination Range Type
Coordination Fleeting Specific Short-term simpler
Hierarchization Fixing Local Inhibitory, long damping
Systematization Flowing, refining Modular Short term, complex
or long term, simpler
Multiplication Flexing Spreading, Long term, complex
modifying
Integration Flexible General Sophisticated, complex
Recursion begins (coordination) Fleeting Specific Short term, simpler
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science + Business Media; with kind permission from Springer
Science + Business Media B. V. [Table 35.6, Page 829]
Steps 749

The rows of the table indicate the characteris- Complex Adaptive Systems, which in turn could
tics of each step in terms of activation/inhibition complexify into superordinate ones. Now, these
coordination. For example, the systematization five undergirding steps to change in developmen-
row indicates that as new systems within systems tal and any living system might apply to nonliv-
form, the activation/coordination dynamic is a ing ones, too.
short-term but complex one that leads to a modu- Therefore, the five-step sequence on change
lar and internally flowing organization reflective mechanisms that I have described from the point of
of its new, localized consistency. Note that the view of NLDST and complexity theory constitutes
last row of the table specifies that should a cyclic a generic model of stages of change. In generic
recursion of steps take place, it will be based on change processes, product and process merge. Just
the new integrated acquisition of the last step in as activation/inhibition coordination seems to con-
the step cycle. As a new cycle begins with a new stitute a generic change mechanism over brain,
coordination, it could involve the integrated sys- behavior, and so on, so might the chaotic processes
temic structure that had emerged in the prior step being described. The five-step model of the pro-
coordinating with an equivalent structure in its cesses facilitating change is based on NLDST and
field or with a different one at its level, or it could complexity theory, but it gives a seamless sequence
involve the new acquisition coordinating or com- of transitions that enable the emergence of higher-
peting with the one of a lower-order level. order levels from lower-level ones. For each stages
of the present model, there appears to be an under-
lying nonlinear dynamical and complexity force
Chaos that is involved related to attractor reorganization
that is exceedingly complex to the point that the
The present model posits that there are five major system expresses integration over the multiplici-
stages in development (see Table 30.3). In the ties in its manifold. The dynamical evolution
table (adapted from Young, 2011), I show how described should undergird the processes of change
transitions from one stage to the next might involved not only when sequencing developmental
involve change in attractor configuration, as stages, such as the one in the table, but also for
specified in chaos theory. The latter specifies that ones in nonliving realms, too.
chaotic attractors develop after point ones form
cyclical attractors. However, there is little work
on how cyclical attractors transform beyond indi- Comment
cating that there might be continual bifurcations.
In this regard, especially for living systems, I In this section of the chapter, I have presented
speculated that the multiple attractors involved two mechanisms of generic change mechanisms,
might reflect Kauffman’s (1993) concept of and one could ask if they are equivalent,

Table 30.3 Five-step Neo-Piagetian model of stages of change, with underlying nonlinear dynamical system transition
mechanism
Generic stage of change and
Stage of development generic change mechanisms Nonlinear dynamical system transitions to the stage
Reflexive Coordination Point Attractors (2)
Sensorimotor Hierarchization Cyclical attractor (over the 2 points)
Perioperational Systematization Chaotic attractor
Abstract Multiplication Complex adaptive system processes (Inhabiting cusp
between order and disorder)
Collective intelligence Integration Superordinate complex adaptive system processes
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science + Business Media; with kind permission from Springer
Science + Business Media B. V. [Table 28.1, Page 647; slightly modified; see Figure 30.4, too]
750 30 Change Mechanisms

complementary, consistent, and so on. If they are chization, systematization, multiplication, and
both equally applicable, one could ask which is integration. The model consists of five stages
more general, for example. In this regard, the one with five substages each, or 25 steps in develop-
of nonlinear dynamical/complexity modeling is ment across the lifespan.
the more general, in that its mechanism involves
transformation of attractor state configurations,
which is a concept that has wide applicability in Readiness for Change
the sciences, and applies equally to the chaos of
nonliving as well as living systems. Nevertheless, Introduction
attractor configuration and reconfigurations can
be seen to involve activation/inhibition coordina- In the prior section, mechanisms of change were
tion, and so the other mechanism discussed in discussed, but not much was said with respect to
this section appears complementary to the sys- system readiness for change. For example, one
tems one. Moreover, one could argue that the could ask whether a system resides at the transi-
economic adaptation of attractor state reorgani- tion point to change, how did it get there, and
zation that takes place in systems appears to be how does it proceed from there. In the follow-
one in which the far-from-equilibrium dynamic ing, I elaborate further on readiness for change.
in which they might be found is accommodated In this regard, I use NLDST terminology, such
after undue strain on its activation/inhibition as control parameters that reside at the threshold
coordination properties both within and among for change, and collector variables that “collect”
the attractors involved. the system at issue into variables that represent
I wonder to what extent the evolution of the it and are triggered in the change (Thelen &
universe toward creation of the planet earth and Smith, 1994).
our presence on it can be captured by a model of Developmentally, systems integrate biologi-
attractor reconfiguration into complexity land- cal, environmental, and organismic (self)
scapes, such as the one presented, and, if so where readiness-for-change factors in context and also
do we stand at present in that sequence. Probably, over developmental time. Readiness for change
we are in the fourth stage of multiplication before has been discussed at other points in the present
the fifth one integration, which will be a prelimi- book, and typically it has been applied to accept-
nary step to the reverse process of dissolution and ing change and implementing it toward healthier
extinction, e.g., as our star sun becomes a super lifestyles and improved subjective well being, as
nova and the process continues with the universe well as in changes needed for dealing with dis-
spreading into a plasma void. ease or disability, including of mental health.
In the next section of the present chapter, I As applied to systems models, the concept
examiner the concept of readiness for change needs to consider what variables represent the
from the point of view of NLDST, and create a critical parameters that reside at the point of
new model that depicts the process. Then, I change in the system (or the range in critical vari-
examine new ways of conceiving dimensions of able values in this regard), as well as what
change. In terms of these dimensions, I apply variable represents the system and is subject to
them to my own developmental model. To the change. To this point, we have described sys-
remind, one model of major qualitative change in tem change in terms of factors such as attractor
development is the Neo-Piagetian one presented configuration and reconfiguration, but underlying
in Young (2011), which has five stages: (a) an these types of change are specific variables that
early reflexive stage; (b) an infant sensorimotor represent the attractor basins involved and the
stage; (c) child perioperational (pre-operational, movement in and out of them.
concrete co-operational) stage; (d) a formal, On the one hand, then, attractors change state
abstract stage; and (e) an adult collective intelli- because the critical variable that acts at the
gence stage. There are five substages within each threshold point of change has attained the index
stage that cyclically repeat: coordination, hierar- levels that promote the change. This process
Readiness for Change 751

serves to lead the interaction involved to thresh- With respect to the first part of the figure, gen-
old levels that are facilitative of change in the erally, a system involving changes in state could
critical variables and the term used to represent be indexed by critical variables representing the
them, for example, at system bifurcation points, factors behind the change (e.g., causal collector
involves the concept of control or of change in variables). This happens in context developmen-
order. Therefore, the variables involved are tally, at diverse local and global levels.
referred to as control or order parameters. In State/system change could be minor to major
keeping with the goal of the present chapter to either quantitatively or qualitatively, with the lat-
create new terminology related to causality, I ter possibly including novel, emergent change.
refer to these critical parameters of change in sys- Systems are not necessarily in state of change or
tems as “causal” control/order parameters. Also preparatory to it. That is, they resist change and
in keeping with the present work, it would appear conserve state, even if far-from-equilibrium.
that the changes involved are especially related However, in a certain sense, even this constitutes
to network structure, complexity, and adaptivity. change, because the state is preserved despite
In terms of the term used for the variables that new inputs into the system from one moment to
index a system and alters as it proceeds to change, the next, or despite dissipation in the energy in
the one that has been applied is “collector” vari- the system if nothing is added to it.
ables. They incorporate the different degrees of From a developmental perspective, a good
freedom in the system into a master variable repre- example of system state changes relates to the
senting the degree of freedom relevant to change. Piagetian sequence of changes in stage (or sub-
As for specific conceptual specification of the stage), as in the infant sensorimotor period. In
two variables in question—causal control/order this regard, Piaget applied NLDST to how
parameters/variables and collector variables, in changes in stage might take place in development
NLDST, the former index potential system and, in Young (2011), I elaborated further, such
change factors should their critical thresholds be as with the concept of transitions in attractor
traversed and the latter “represent” the system, organization and reorganization that might take
“compressing” or reducing its lower-level place in development, as described previously in
degrees of freedom, opening it to higher-order this chapter. That being said, I consider that fur-
transition. These variables are akin to indepen- ther work is needed in this regard, and developed
dent and dependent variables, respectively. the model in the figure.
Specifically, I reasoned that or the infancy
period, whether conceived of as core knowledge,
Model early (quasi)representations, Piagetian schemes,
or other cognitive structures or modules, includ-
Introduction We are ready to address directly ing up to the level of (sub)stages, a general
Fig. 30.2, which is about readiness for change/ model is needed to indicate how cognitive struc-
transition state in causal control (order) parame- tures develop, even to the point of qualitative,
ters and activity in dimensions of change in state emergent growth in overall stage structure.
collector variables, which function together to Therefore, I worked to develop a model of readi-
leads to local/global networked change in devel- ness for change that applies not only to the
opmental structures/unit and levels. The figure Piagetian version of the substages of the infancy
consists of three parts, dealing with the two vari- period but also to other approaches that work
ables mentioned and the change in state that toward understanding infant cognition. In this
results from the workings of the factors that they regard, I refer to the general concept of net-
represent. This work includes presentation of a worked change in this model.
more mathematically-based model of the change Examination of Fig. 30.2 reveals that it con-
process that lies in the control/order and collector sists of three parts, with the first (“a”) part of the
variables, or at least the factors in change that figure indicating the causal factors in cognitive
they represent. structure (and in any) development. The second
a Causal Control (Order) Parameter b State Collector Variable
High

Readiness

High

Cross/ Inter-
Readiness

network
Global
Environment

Depth Across
Global
Cross/ Intra-Network
Contextual Match

Contextual Match
Biology
Network Unit (N)
N/A Readiness
Local (Micro, e.g., schema) Global (Macro, e.g., stage)

Self Depth
(Organism) Within

Local
N/A
Local
Low

Low
N/A

Development (Time) Development (Time)

c Change (Development)/Structural Transition


(Outcomes)
High

Major
Qualitative

Major
Contextual Match

Quantitative

Minor Major

Emergent
Minor

Minor
Low

Development (Time)

Fig. 30.2 Readiness for change/transition (RC/TR) in needing appropriate contextual organization to facilitate
causal control (order) parameter(s) (CCP) and state collec- change (referred to as “contextual match”). That is, the
tor variable (SCV) (a) Note. CCP = Causal control param- same three axes are used to elaborate the central compo-
eter in generic “readiness for change”/transition of state nents of the three portions of figure.
model. (b) Note. SCV = State collector variable; cross- In (a), the three major axes involve the primary influ-
network integration in activity in dimensions of change. ences on behavior of biology, environment, and person
Unit refers to local (L), smaller-order schemas up to global (self, organism). The figure refers to the readiness of
(G), larger-order constructs, such as stages. Depth refers to change/transition in each of these spheres. Collectively, as
degree of change either within or over levels of the system, the three spheres reach the necessary thresholds for readi-
e.g., smaller-order (L) or larger-order (G, networked). (c) ness for change/transition, the integrated control parameter
Note. Local (L)/global (G) networked change (N) in devel- that organizes (is organized by) them constitutes a causal
opmental structures/unit and level(s). Change (develop- impetus for state (system) change.
ment) [C(D)] is a function (f) of reaching SCV threshold in In the second portion of the figure (b), the collector
relation to the nature of system activity structure and asso- variable of the state (system) can be represented by activity
ciated level(s)). in major aspects of the system. These include the three
This figure presents a combined dynamical/network dimensions of size of unit involved (local, global) and
model of developmental change. It uses the language of depth of change (within the unit, local to global, intra-net-
NLDST—changes in control parameters alter collector work; and across the unit, local to global, inter-network).
variables in systems to the point of threshold for change, The proposed state collector variable would vary in the
which elicits self-organized (and potentially novel/emer- dynamic it covered or represented, depending on the size
gent, qualitatively distinct) re-organization of the system. and depth of the system variables involved.
The model also uses the language of networks, in that The three major axes in the third (c) portion of the fig-
instead of referring to system states and levels, it includes ure indicate that the resultant change in the state/system
intra- and inter-level cross-network integrations. after the control parameter involved acts on the collector
The three portions of the figure (a, b, c) have the con- variable involved might be quantitative, qualitative, and
stant axes of allowing change over developmental time and even emergent in self organization dynamic
Readiness for Change 753

(“b”) component of the figure indicates the out- as opposed to being too specific and simplified
come potentials at threshold variables involved (and easily quantified).
in the transitions to change in the system at issue.
The third part of the figure (“c”) concerns the State Collector Variables The dimensions of
resultant change in systems according to whether the state collector variable in the model that
the change is emergent, qualitative, and major, or serves as the immediate transition mechanism for
their opposites. Together, the three components change of system state, once readiness for change
of the model help specify the state of systems that of state is achieved, is conceptualized as one that
are poised at the point of readiness for change, is cross-network in integration. It, too, is not a
and what might be the outcome. simplified, specific, and readily quantified vari-
able, but an integrative, synergistic one that
Causal Control Parameters In this regard, the might lead to state change at any of multiple lev-
model that I have developed integrating the con- els in the system at hand, whether local or global.
cepts of causal control parameters and collector The structure involved could be local (schematic)
variables, as well as system state (change) out- or global (macro, e.g., representation, even (sub)
come, is referred to as the Readiness for Change stage), and the degree or depth of change within
or Transition State model because, as systems (intra-level) or over (inter-level) levels might be
function in context, their incorporative, assimila- local or global, but either way involving increased
tive, and accommodatory activity pushes them to cross-network integration at the implicated level.
the “cusp of change,” in which they are more
open to change, including of a more radical, Network Change Therefore, in the model, as
qualitative nature. Yet the factors together that shown in the third part of the figure, development
promote possible change in the system must is conceived as an increasing network construc-
reach a certain stretching point that leads to tion (cross-network) over its elements and levels,
change, and these can be modeled as indicated. to the point that nonlinear dynamic shifts in state
Both the first two parts of the figure consider might take place as the threshold or cusp of
the situational and developmental (time) factors change is traversed. The latter might take place
involved in potential change. The context needs directly and in proportion to input, context vari-
to match with, facilitate, or promote the need for ables, or perturbation conditions (quantitative).
change, whereas the nature and complexity of But, more likely, the system resists equilibrium
change might be influenced by developmental change until at far-from-equilibrium and then
epoch. The first part of the figure conceptualizes self-organizes into a new regime (qualitative
readiness for change, or being in a state pre- change) that might even have emergent state con-
pared for transition, as involving a synergistic struction characteristics beyond less complex
amalgam of biological, environmental, and self- qualitative state transitions. The types of change
(organismic) constructive variables that coalesce can be modeled whether part of a stage model or
to the cusp of change in the system at hand. The not, because qualitative shifts in state structure
three dimensions vary from lack of readiness for are not limited to stage models.
change to full readiness and, collectively, they I illustrate the latter principle by noting the fol-
need to interact to create an inertial impetus lowing. The present model is consistent with the
causally toward change. This type of interaction microgenetic information processing view, which
does not refer to the statistic G × E type, in accentuates a wave pattern in problem solving
which both of specific genetic (allelic) and envi- when performance is analyzed for strategy effi-
ronmental factors need to be present, but to an ciency. The child generally progresses from use of
additive, multiplicative, cascading interaction of one less efficient strategy to another, improving
multiple sources toward the cusp of change and speed and accuracy, to arrive at the most efficient
its tipping point. In this sense, causal control strategy (Siegler, 2006, after Berk, 2013). One can
parameters are conceived of as representations apply Young’s (2011) Neo-Piagetian model to this
of factors that are more generic or generalized micro-developmental process, because that model
754 30 Change Mechanisms

applies not only to changes over stages and sub- Environment (E)—e.g., object available for
stages but even to micro changes. This eventuates applying sensorimotor scheme; social support
because the model was structured to reflect a frac- facilitating readiness for change
talization process in which the change process in Biology (B)—e.g., maturation of frontal
stages, substages, and micro changes are equiva- lobes allows necessary organization, inhibitory
lent in passing through the sequence of the steps control
of coordination, hierarchization, systematization, Self (S)/Organism (O)—e.g., self-regulation
multiplication, and integration. Therefore, increased allows for appropriate self, emotional, and social
strategy efficiency in problem solving might follow control/interaction
a wave over phases of coordination, hierarchiza- I have tried to create a specific mathematical
tion, systematization, multiplication, and integra- formula to represent the developmental process.
tion. Coincidentally, Siegler’s wave model includes This attempt to create a viable mathematical for-
five increasingly useful steps in strategy use. mula in this regard focuses on systems theory
[They are not phrased in language that could be concepts, but in a way that allows for change
transposed into the coordination to integration either with respect to stages or more generically.
sequence, but with reworking they might be.] They need further work and operationalization.
The upshot of the comparison of my stage The following section of the chapters moves
model with micro change models is that just as the from readiness for change to dimensions in
former is open to the model of readiness for change change. They carry the impact of the causal
that has been formulated in the present section so change factors impinging on systems.
are other models that are nonstage ones. If the for-
mer has a structure that opens it to transitioning of
the type described in the present model, so too do Dimensions of Change
other models that allow for qualitative change or
shifts to more developmentally advanced structure Dimensions
even if not of the stage variety.
Introduction Tables 30.4, 30.5, 30.6, 30.7,
30.8, and 30.9 present the most important charac-
Comment teristics evident in change processes in systems,
especially from a nonlinear dynamical, complex-
As a conclusion about the model of change pre- ity, and network point of view. The tables list
sented in Fig. 30.2, note that it can be summa- major and other dimensions/factors, respectively,
rized by the three indicated formula found in general change processes, nonlinear dynami-
below. The first concerns causal control param- cal systems, and networks. This organization
eters, the second concerns system collector vari- might not work for all readers, but it helps serve
ables, and the third concerns change resulting as an integrative frame for further elaboration.
from their dynamic. Also, the tables do not include any mathematical
The figure indicates a model of behavioral work that corresponds to the concepts; therefore,
change, as applied to development but applicable much re-organization, mathematical expression,
to any psychological change. I have formulated and gathering of empirical support for the frame
the model as a series of equations. In this regard: should continue.
(1) CCP f ((B, E, S(O)) [i, c] RC/TR)
i = individualized (development is about indi- Evolvability/Developability/Versatility Evolv-
vidual differences) ability concerns the capacity of a system for
c = universal generic constant (but develop- evolving adaptively. It relates to natural selection
ment is also about norms and universals) not just of an adaptive phenotype with under-
(2) SCV (RC/TR) f ([i, c] CCP) girded genotype but also of phenotypes so well-
(3) C(D) f ((SCV) (N [L, G])) undergirded with the genetic potential for its
Dimensions of Change 755

Table 30.4 Major dimensions/factors of change processes Table 30.7 Other dimensions/factors of dynamic char-
in systems acteristics of systems
Dimension/factor Examples/poles Dimension/factor Examples/poles
Target Molecule, cell, organism (human), Range Local, global
community Predictability Predictable, unpredictable
Evolvability/ Low, high Degree One unit, bi, system-wide
developability Level Bottom, top
Time Online, ontogenetic, evolutionary Direction Horizontal, vertical
Context/niche Unconducive/conducive Hierarchy Strata, nests
Conservability Resistant/fixed, robust/stretchable Feedback Negative, positive, forward
Flexibility Passive/reactive, versatile/active Scale repetitions Attractors, fractals
Dynamic Linear, nonlinear
Regime Stable, cusp/edge, unstable
Table 30.8 Major dimensions/factors of network pro-
cesses in systems
Table 30.5 Other dimensions/factors of change pro-
cesses in systems Dimension/factor Example/poles
Components Units/nodes, links/edges
Dimensions/factor Examples/poles
Modifiability Core (no), peripheral (yes)
Turbulence Prechange, continuous
Architecture Hubs/primary, secondary
Flow (energy, resources) Punctuated, continuous
Scope Features, form, function
Change amount Minor, major
Energy, resources Incorporation, dissipation,
Change quality Qualitative, quantitative (information) exchange/seeking
Change intensity Burst, bump Tightness Loose, cohesion, coherence
Change frequency Frequent/multiple, Sequencibility Sequences, simultaneous
intermittent, isolated
Causality Privileged, distributed
Change speed Fast, slow
Change duration Long, short
Table 30.9 Other dimensions/factors of network pro-
cesses in systems
Table 30.6 Major dimensions/factors of dynamic charac-
teristics of systems Dimension/factor Examples/poles
Dimension/factor Examples/poles Yoking Permanent/binding, transient/
non-binding
Constituents Elements/states, patterns/space
Autonomy Maintained, chunked
Openness Open to input, closed
Locality Localized, dispersed
Order Ordered, unordered
Optimization Increasing, irrelevant
Perturbation Far from equilibrium, catastrophe
(butterfly effect) Complexity Increasing, irrelevant
Status Equilibrium, disequilibrium/far Control Increasing, irrelevant
from equilibrium Success Adaptive, maladaptive
Threshold Control parameter/bifurcation; Freedom In degrees of freedom, in freedom
holistic, self-assembly of action, in beliefs of free will
Self-organization Lateral, novel/emergence
Emergence Constrained, unconstrained
Attractors Point/cyclical, chaotic, multiple

diversity to enable it to continue to evolve (e.g., bility in ontogeny as opposed to differential phy-
Colegrave & Collins, 2008; Pigliucci, 2008; logenetic flexibility.
Wagner, 2005). The fundamental assumption underlying the
Table 30.4 expands the concept of evolvability combined differential flexibility in ontogeny and
to include “developability.” This allows inclusion phylogeny presented in the present frame is that
of differential capacity for developmental flexi- of “versatility.” Systems evidence change in a
756 30 Change Mechanisms

dynamic way. This happens to the point that they described cover biotic units, from molecules/cells
gravitate to regions in which they are poised for to organisms/communities. With revision, they
change. could readily include abiotic nonliving systems,
Moreover, in that region, they adaptively seek including galactic and other “Big History” entities.
out and promote new regions reflective of their The timelines of system change could be online
diversity that can further promote that diversity. and rapidly unfolding, as in molecular or micro/
The cascading result of their change over the nano interactions, or phylogenetically long and
time scale involved is an increasing complex and even “universally” so. Systems are differentially
potentially successfully effort to better challenge, primed for change not only constitutionally but
adapt to, control, and even alter their environ- also contextually. Some environments are more
ment for their improved fitness, or their survival propitious than others for supporting change.
and reproduction. Change takes place out of the balance of two
Systems do not just express evolvability; they orthogonal tendencies—to conserve stability and
actively create opportunities for emergence of to generate change. Conserving systems could be
new features, structures, and functions that can inordinately inflexible or, rather, they could be
promote it even more. Similarly, in developabil- flexibly stretchable to a degree, with their elastic-
ity, systems actively seek out dynamic contingen- ity being better able to resist perturbations that
cies that promote and take advantage of their are more than minor. Systems vary in their flexi-
flexibility. bility for change, too, as discussed above.
However, not all systems are equally adept in The tension between change and its resistance
their evolvability/developability/versatility/flexib in systems creates a constant dynamic that inter-
ility. There are individual differences in this acts with energy and other input and also with
regard even in normative environments. context or niche and other considerations, espe-
Moreover, in their differential flexibility, systems cially in terms of individual differences, to
differ in their capacity to adjust to adverse envi- determine change potential and activation. The
ronments, and this type of difference is evident changes could be linear or dynamically nonlin-
even in supportive ones. ear, and in the latter, the system could stand at the
In child development, for example, the con- cusp or edge of change, away from equilibrium
cept that fits the present modeling is differential (even far from it), ready to escape into more
biological or environmental susceptibility to con- turbulence and instability, which is a risky but
text (Belsky & Pluess, 2013; Ellis, Boyce, Belsky, probabilistically viable stepping stone to
Bakermans-Kranenburg, & van IJzendoorn, increased adaptability, complexity, and stability.
2011). In this model, susceptibility genes afford
negative outcomes in adverse environments but Energy The next Table 30.5 in the series addresses
positive ones in supportive environment, while energy flow and turbulence in the system. If it is
other related alleles are not susceptible either way. open, resources enter the system (energy, informa-
In the present context, one could generalize tion) and are exchanged. Stimuli and related inputs
the differential flexibility in the latter concepts might perturb the system, creating turbulence in
and term it “differential evolvability susceptibil- structure and opening it to change. Often, turbu-
ity” or “differential developability susceptibil- lence is greater prior to change, and it could be
ity.” A common term that works might be excited during it. Both flow and turbulence could
“differential system versatility” or flexibility. be punctuated, or intermittent. The change that
results would vary on the usual dimensions of mag-
Extensions The remainder of Table 30.4 con- nitude, frequency, speed, duration, intensity, and
cerns expansion of the concept of differential flex- quality, with qualitative change corresponding to
ibility or versatility in systems. The systems being new states, stages, and so on.
Dimensions of Change 757

Dynamics As for the two tables (Tables 30.6 Networks As for the two tables (Tables 30.8
and 30.7) on dynamic characteristics of systems, and 30.9) on networks, networks are types of sys-
they concern how element units combine into tems for which the unit components are termed
patterns in state space and also how the systems nodes and their links are termed edges. Some are
can change when open, for example, from order primary in the sense of being cores or hubs (e.g.,
to disorder, or vice versa. Stimuli perturb the sys- with consistency), or multiple nodes and edges.
tem, leading to major change when it is far-from- Network architecture also includes descriptors,
equilibrium, even when the perturbation is minor such as features, form or structure, and function.
(the butterfly effect). Systems could change at They include incoming resources (e.g., energy)
specific thresholds of control parameters (e.g., at that are not only used but also sought (because of
bifurcation points), or also as an action of the dissipation). The structure of networks could be
whole system in unsustainable disequilibrium. loose or less coupled or more cohesive and coher-
As system trajectories in state space repeat- ent (in edges, across edges). The nodes could
edly visit the same basin or basins, systems self- possess sequential relations or simultaneous
organize into attractor regimes, which are locally ones, and, if the former, could express local cau-
indeterministic but globally deterministic. The sality involving them, although causality could
attractors can self-assemble into new regimes at be widely distributed in overall system activity.
bifurcation points, or in crossing saddle points Networks can express coupling/linkages that
(e.g., becoming multiple/chaotic instead of sim- are quite bound toward permanency, or they
pler point attractors or cyclical attractors). could be more loosely associated. As units
Emergence is a cardinal feature of nonlinear coalesce or chunk into higher-order structures,
dynamical systems because the form taken might they can possess some degree of autonomy, or
be totally unpredictable from the parts, and also not. Chunks can be local or wider. Networks can
the properties involved might be totally novel grow toward increasing optimization or complex-
compared to those of the parts (priors, constitu- ity, becoming more adaptive and integrated. They
ents). However, to a degree, emergent patterns can evidence greater control of the environment
are still constrained by prior state configuration. and greater adaptive success. They can demon-
As for other aspects of dynamical systems, they strate freedom in their degrees of freedom, free-
vary in focus/range (local, global), predictability dom of action and, for human system entities,
(stochastic/random, deterministic), and extent of belief in and sense of free will.
action [one unit, bi-unit (e.g., coupling), or multi-
ple-unit (up to system-wide)]. They vary in hierar-
chization (present, absent, and, if present, type, Comment
e.g., strata/layers vs. nests/embeddings). The lev-
els can work bottom-up, top-down, or both (recip- Systems can change in so may varied ways that
rocally). They can work within a level (horizontally) the dimensional change model that I have
or across them (vertically). Upper levels can regu- described in system change stands as a good
late or “enslave lower ones,” reducing their degrees complement to the readiness for change model
of freedom (but increasing their own). described just before it. Together, the two models
The feedback involved in systems can dampen, point to the complexity in change in systems and,
change, or accentuate them (e.g., negative, posi- therefore, in behavioral causality, as well.
tive feedback), or it can alter future activity in a The following section of the chapter examines
feedforward mechanism. Systems can repeat the developmental change process, in particular.
activity not only in the sense of attractors return- First, it considers the nativist position compared
ing to global basins but also in terms of multiple to the empiricist one, and then it attempts an inte-
scale equivalences at different levels (e.g., frac- gration using my model as a basis. Note that else-
tals; think the equivalence in patterns of waves at where in the present book I have considered the
the beach and in a bay). integration of nativist and empiricist positions in
758 30 Change Mechanisms

development and referred to a combined model Model


as neoreductioconstructivist. In the present
approach, I am more specific how this type of Figure 30.4 illustrates that domains can evolve
combined model would look like in terms of my through infant sensorimotor stages conceived
own. generically in the Neo-Piagetian perspective
(Young, 2011). The domains might be core, nativ-
ist ones or others more open to experiential con-
Infant Development struction. The classic Piagetian view of domain
transitions is limited to certain areas, such as
Introduction object permanence. In contrast, the Neo-Piagetian
model constitutes a generalized change descrip-
According to Berk (2013), the core knowledge tion that can accommodate the perspective of core
view of infant thought considers that there are knowledge acquisitions and other contemporary
innate, specialized knowledge systems that leave findings for infancy, including nascent intention-
the young infant equipped for rapid development ality, theory of mind, and morality.
of critical modules in cognition (e.g., Spelke &
Kinzler, 2007). Two primary core knowledge Biology The figure integrates competing views
domains concern physical and numerical knowl- of early infant cognitive sensorimotor develop-
edge (e.g., about objects and their effects and ment, which opposes nonstage innate, nativist,
about keeping track of the amount of objects, and constructionist (sub)stage approaches.
respectively). Figures 30.3 and 30.4 present a Figure 30.4 indicates that domains of develop-
new way of looking at the issue, with Figure 30.3 ment could be generic but also quite specific to
on mechanism and Figure 30.4 on content. core, nativist ones. The latter domain model

Mental Schema in a
Domain (Attractor) 1. Two point attractors juxtaposed (Independent)

Readiness for Change/ 2. Cyclical attractor (oscillations across simpler


Transition State component options of an attractor), perhaps based on
(Attractor conjoined point attractors
modification)

3. Chaotic attractor (Increasingly ordered attractor at


State Change Reaches the global level with local unpredictability. The system
Threshold gravitates to the same pattern and depends on initial
(New Attractor) condition sensitivity)

Spreading 4. Inhabiting order-disorder cusp (Attractor regimes shift


Change in multiple sets by inhabiting a particular zone that seeks
(Attractors) change according to Kauffman (1993), leading to
Complex Adaptive System (CAS) (multiple attractors)

Broad Change 5. Superordinate complex adaptive systems (multiple


(Attractor integration) CAS)

Fig. 30.3 An Attractor Complexity Domain one applicable to other change processes. Relative to
Developmental Model. The figure presents a five-step Young (2011) this version adds a step of two independent
model of change involving the elaboration of attractors attractors (juxtaposed), which coordinate (cyclical attrac-
that is consistent with the Neo-Piagetian five-stage model tor) and become “chaotic” (moving to the cusp of change
of Young (2011). The five step-change model is a generic and CAS development)
a Domain Construction/ Scaffolding

Nativist Empirical
Core Knowledge X Refinement,
Domains Release

“Innate” Environment minorly contributory


e.g., - Numerosity
- Other physical
properties
Biologically prepared

OR

Constructed
General X Empirical
Domains Induction

- e.g., Piagetian (actively constructed) - Environmental/ Elaboration


- means-end - Support/ Facilitation
- object (permanence)
- categories
- space
- time
- causality

b (Sub)Stage Construction/ Scaffolding Outcome

Piagetian (specific to sensorimotor stage)

1. Reflex exercise (0-1 month)


2. Primary circular reactions (1-4)
3. Secondary circular reactions (4-8)
4. Coordination of secondary schemes (8-12)
5. Tertiary circular reactions (12-18)
6. Inventing new means by mental combination (18-24)

OR

Neo-Piagetian (generic, recursive within each stage)

1. Coordination (equivalent of 2nd Piagetian sensorimotor substage)


2. Hierarchization (3rd)
3. Systematization (4th)
4. Multiplication (5th)
5. Integration (6th) [with Reflex exercise shunted to its own stage,
beginning prenatally, and also involving five substages]

Fig. 30.4 An Integrative Model of Core Knowledge core knowledge/ nativist approach to early cognitive
(Nativist), Piagetian, Neo-Piagetian, and Empiricist development and the Piagetian one ending with my Neo-
Approaches to Infant Cognitive and Sensorimotor Piagetian model (Young, 2011)
Development. The figure presents the opposition of the
760 30 Change Mechanisms

appears to stand in opposition to a Neo-Piagetian tems theory provides an avenue for specifying change
substage developmental process. This seems the mechanisms, as per the last portion of the figure.
case because Piaget had described a general
model of substages in the sensorimotor stage of Mechanism In this regard, for mechanisms of
infancy, but he applied it to specific domains such change in my model, Fig. 30.3 presents Young’s
as object permanence, means-end, and causality. (2011) translation of his Neo-Piagetian change
In this regard, the modular and generic are both model into the language of attractors and complex
present in Piaget’s model. adaptive systems, which I had presented previ-
ously in the chapter. As (sub)systems at whatever
Environment The environment plays a funda- level of complexity self-organize, over time, they
mental role in any model of cognitive develop- create more adaptive attractors in their state con-
ment and, for core knowledge domains that are figurations and also their complexity increases,
biologically prepared, the environment functions permitting increasing flexibility and adaptivity.
in a refining, reciprocal interactive modality [Note that the process of attractor differentiation
rather than as one that is more raw inductive, and described in Fig. 30.3 is consistent with that in
elaborative. It is not conceived as separate but as Young (2011), but is changed slightly in the pres-
reciprocal, mutual, and interactive, or giving ent version, as indicated in the Figure Caption.]
scaffolding support. As for the Piagetian perspec-
tive, the environment is not considered modular
in the sense of the core, nativist one, for which Comment
the environment offers specific behaviors to the
developing child in support of specific modular The present chapter concerns new terms and
domains. Rather, for Piaget, the environment models related to causality, and the last portion of
serves a general alimentary function that pro- it has covered my own developmental model
motes passage through the generic sequence of (Young, 2011). Given the value and validity that
substages in the infancy period. Moreover, for I see in this model and the arguments made for it
Piaget, the environment is less important than the (e.g., how it fills gaps in other stage models and
child her- or himself in promoting change. how it can better explain experimental data
derived from them), my model should take a cen-
Self That is, Piaget had emphasized the construc- tral place in new conceptions about development
tivist nature of the child’s cognitive activity and and its causality. In the following, I carry this
that the child activity pursues that construction. argument one step further by presenting other
Therefore, the model in the figure allows for an extensions of my model, this time not just for
active role of the developing person (infant) in his/ infancy but also across the age spectrum. Note
her own development through the constructive pro- that beyond what I have given about my model in
cess in cognition, as had been described by Piaget. this latter part of the present chapter, I describe in
depth my model (and its extensions) in the next
Combined Figure 30.4 presents specific details six chapters of the present book.
of Piaget’s sensorimotor substage series. There
are six substages, and they begin with reflex
exercise and end with mental combinations, but General Development
still in the sensorimotor modality to a degree. The
figure shows how the six substages can be trans- Introduction
lated into the current Neo-Piagetian (sub)stage
model, as described previously in the chapter. The next three tables provide further details on
As for the causal factors involved in the substage the cognitive (mis)perception of the other (by the
transitions of my model, it should be clear by now self) component of Young’s (2011) model. They
that I support a multifactorial model that is apply to development throughout the lifespan,
biopsychosocial in nature. At the same time, sys- extending the presentation in the prior section of
General Development 761

the chapter on infancy. Specifically, they deal but give examples related to different targets
with the nature of child discipline, relationships, (children, partners, minorities). This prepares the
and how we treat minorities. They cover develop- way for relating the styles to the cognitive (mis)
ment over the lifespan in these areas, as well. perception of the other and the present five stages
in Neo-Piagetian cognitive development. Their
relationship to the latter is more in terms of how
How We Treat Each Other the other is perceived rather than the cognitive
level in the thinking involved.
In Young (2011), I described that management
style takes five forms (negate, dominate, relegate,
delegate, and integrate), and I related the styles to Management Style
the present model of five stages in Neo-Piagetian
development through the concept of the cognitive Table 30.11 presents five management styles that
(mis)perception of the other. Table 30.10 gives can be considered corresponding offshoots to the
more details of the styles, which is new to the five levels of cognitive (mis)perception of the
present book. Table 30.11 presents the styles in other that Young had derived from the Neo-
terms of the model of the cognitive (mis)percep- Piagetian stage model. The styles range from
tion of the other. Table 30.12 relates the styles to negation to integration. (a) In the management
the five Neo-Piagetian stages in Young (2011), style of negation, the supervisor engages in
but includes the Piagetian stages of preoperations behavior involving—overloading, treating
and concrete operations. poorly, rejecting, and denying. (b) In domination,
Specifically for Table 30.10, it indicates the the supervisor acts to—subjugate, repress,
way we treat children, our partners, and minori- oppose, impose, and manipulate. (c) In relega-
ties resemble each other in terms of five types tion, the supervisor’s behaviors include—neu-
that range from the most inequitable to the highly tralize, channel, assimilate, and pacify. (d) Next,
equitable. For consistency, I kept the original in delegation, one might—offer responsibility,
styles that I created for the management context, show concern, and liberate somewhat. (e) In the

Table 30.10 How we treat children, partners, and minorities


Style Examples
Negate The child is abused in neglected, fails to thrive, and is even shaken to death or murdered.
The partner is severely beaten, raped, stalked, and even murdered.
The minorities are denied basic human rights, tortured, persecuted to death, and subject to
genocide.
Dominate The child is totally controlled, disregarded, and treated harshly as an object worthy of little.
The partner is objectified, subsumed to basic/crude desires, overcontrolled, etc.
The minorities are considered inferior, persecuted for protests, consigned to poverty, etc.
Relegate The child is considered as a means to an end, treated with little respect, given little mental
space, etc.
The partner is treated in the same way.
So are minorities.
Delegate The child is supported in her/ his growth at most levels. There are some issues in giving full
freedoms to explore self and other as the child develops into the teen years.
A similar pattern applies to partners, but in terms of fully trusting the other.
A similar attitude is applied to minorities.
Integrate From the beginning, the parent wants the child to develop optimally at all levels and promotes
the same, giving warmth and appropriate limit setting.
Partners are treated with utmost respect and trust, and responds with the same in mutual
growth.
Majority-minority relations reflect this attitude, as well.
762 30 Change Mechanisms

Table 30.11 Five management styles according to Because these five management styles reflect
Young’s Neo-Piagetian stage model how the person might behave in the task of deal-
Management ing with others, one can qualify the scheme as
style Description dealing with the psychology or personal side of
Negate Overlord, treat poorly, reject, deny the person rather than the biological or environ-
Dominate Subjugate, repress, oppose, impose,
mental side. However, making these types of dis-
manipulate
Relegate Neutralize, channel, assimilate, pacify
tinctions for such a complex behavior is more of a
Delegate Offer responsibility, show concern, heuristic than a natural separation into categories.
liberate somewhat
Integrate Promote individual and collective
action, creativity, thought, freedom Cognitive (Mis)Perception of the Other
and awareness; empower, humanize,
trust others’ wisdom; facilitate
emergence of constant adaptation and In the following, I provide a model of the cogni-
growth; coparticipate in process tive (mis)perception of the other as per Young
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business (1997, 2011), but slightly modified (see Table
Media. Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: 30.12). In the original, I emphasized how the other
Neo-Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer can be misperceived according to the perceiver’s
Science + Business Media; with kind permission from
Springer Science + Business Media B. V. [Table 18.5,
diminution of the psychological integrity of the
Page 428] perceived. I described the five steps involved, and
related them to the five Neo-Piagetian stages of
the present model. Moreover, I indicated that the
penultimate management style in integration, the five substages that cyclically recur in the Neo-
supervisor works toward—promoting individual Piagetian model apply to the cognitive (mis)per-
and collective action, creativity, thought, free- ception of the other, as well, providing scales to
dom, and awareness; empower, humanize, trust measure the (mis)perception in terms of these sub-
others’ wisdom; facilitate emergence of constant stages. In the present rendition of the model, i give
adaptation and growth, and co-participate in the only two levels beyond the stages and they are the
process. pre-operational and concrete operational levels
These five management styles reflect the from Piaget’s model (for the perioperational stage,
Neo-Piagetian cognitive levels in Young’s which he referred to as Representational). I have
(2011) model of reflexive, sensorimotor, periop- used this two-level approach for that stage else-
erational, abstract, and collective intelligence, where in this book.
respectively. The adult might functioning cogni- Essentially, the model indicates that when the
tively at the upper level of the model, however, person is misperceived as someone to pacify
function in management style might not take into assimilation, this can happen in first-order
place at the corresponding level, but a lower (pre-operational) and second-order (concrete
one. Therefore, management styles involving operational) ways. In the former, compared to
abuse or domination are potentiated when the the latter case, the cognitive sophistication
other is perceived as reflexive or not cognitively attributed to the other is primitively logical and
functional, for example. In contrast, when a the pacification should be easier.
manager or a management team is functioning
at the highest level of collective intelligence,
and the management team perceives the other Comment
through this lens, better teamwork in the work
environment could be promoted, for example, The next part of the present chapter returns to a
through brainstorming for the common com- concept described in the last chapter, that of intraac-
pany (financial) good (and creating a good tion. In the following, I examine some of the exten-
group harmony, as well). sions that could be made for this concept.
Intraactive Terminology 763

Table 30.12 The cognitive (mis)perception of the other and individual/group response at each cognitive stage
Stage Cognitive Misperception of the Other Individual/ Group Response (A vs. B)
a. Reflexive Negate (abuse/ reject/ deny) Obliteration vs. nihilism
b. Sensorimotor Subjugate (repress, oppose/ compete, Sterilization vs. revolution
impose, manipulate)
c. Perioperational Pacify/tantalize Assimilation vs. resistance
Preoperational First-order First-order
Concrete operational Second-order Second-order
d. Abstract Limit, partially liberate Involution vs. evolution
e. Collective intelligence Humanize Equalization vs. emancipation
The model of the cognitive (mis)perception of the other indicates that, at the lowest levels of (mis)perception of the
other, we treat the person as an infant or young child (levels a-b) of the model). Because of the devaluing nature of these
levels, the person is considered as not having much equal rights, which thereby justifies any abuse or suppression under-
taken. (c) As for perceiving the other only in terms of the person being akin to an older child, at best, the person engag-
ing in the misperception treats the other as someone who could be canalized or manipulated easily, due to their perceived
lack of cognitive sophistication. In the last stages of the model (d-e), the person perceives the other as a teenager or
adult, or in the more mature levels of the model. The table also indicates how individuals or groups might respond to
the perceiver misattributing maximum cognitive capacity and engaging in mistreatment as a result.
Note. Individuals might be children or partners and the group might be minorities as perceived by majorities. When the
misperception is equivalent to the reflexive level, the other will be overpowered and feel obliterated. If there is an effort
to avoid obliteration, the only option might be a nihilistic, chaotic behavior, because all others might be not even pos-
sible. For the perception of being like a sensorimotor entity at best, the perceived might feel neutralized or sterilized. If
there is any fight possible, it will be more overt than nihilism and be overtly a revolutionary one. If the person is per-
ceived equivalent to child-like with some cognitive skills at best, it will foster a more subtle aggressive counter response,
should it take place, which we call resistance. The first-order level will be more intuitive/ automatic than logical/ reflec-
tive, consistent with the preoperational stage associated with it. If the stage is the concrete operational one, the second-
order level of resistance will have logical/ reflective elements, but limited to the physical, tangible environment and
options rather than abstract, intangible ones. The latter type will be found is the evolutionary/ emancipation responses
of the later responses of the individual group.
The table has presented a model of the cognitive (mis)perception of the other or how individuals perceive the other
according to their own predominant developmental socioemotional level. Most likely, each individual simultaneously
functions at all five levels of the model (in terms of actual, desired or most mature behavior, etc). Also, the relative
proportion of the five levels in any one person should vary according to situation, issue, person being related to, his or
her own history, and so on. The same applies to the development in couples and societies; they might also have one
major way of (mis)perceiving of the other, but do vary. Adopted with permission of Springer Science+Business Media.
Young, G. (1997). Adult development, therapy, and culture: A postmodern synthesis. New York: Plenum; with kind
permission from Springer Science+Business Media B. V. [Table7.1, Page. 156; slightly modified]

Intraactive Terminology themselves beyond the whole system they form


and that transform them. This concept is so new,
Introduction even if it is related to other ones, such as interac-
tivism, that a Google search did not find even one
In the last chapter, I presented the concept of entry with this terminology [Most Google
intraaction that I developed to indicate, for any searches give hundreds of thousands or millions
phenomenon, the centrality of relations among of listed entries within nano-seconds of data
components relative to the centrality of the com- mining.]
ponents, themselves, along with their interactions
in which the components remain separate and
unchanged by the interactions in the phenome- Application
non. In this concept, the intraactive interactions
among the components of the phenomenon even The concept of intraactions could have far-
define the components of the phenomenon so that reaching implications for specifying and under-
neither components nor their interactions exist by standing other concepts in psychology, such as
764 30 Change Mechanisms

many of those in the present book. In this regard, personality, hierarchical needs, and motivation.
instead of referring to causality alone, given the At the applied level, it would make sense to refer
nature of the concept of intraactivism and its to intraactive psychotherapy and to define mental
implications for behavior, I suggest that a rele- disorders and categories in these terms.
vant extension of the concept of causality would
be to refer to it as “intraactive causality.” This
new concept implies that, not only is causality Conclusion
multifactorial and interactive, but also the nature
of the causation involved takes precedence over Finally, some of the models that I developed
the components and their interactions and, could be respecified as intraactive—for example,
indeed, helps specify, modify, and define the intraactive stage models, the intraactive Piagetian,
components as well as their interactions. Eriksonian, and Maslovian models, and the
For example, instead of referring to genes intraactive stimulus–organism–response model.
interacting with the environment, and the person On the one hand, the concept of intraaction could
contributing to the interaction (e.g., through free have very limited scope, and just remain one
will), it would be more exact to say that intraactive other way to describe interactions. However, on
genes intraact with the intraactive environment the other hand, it might help give a superordinate
and the intraactive free will belief in the person/ framework, worldview, or metatheory that is
self to create a superordinate intraactive causal applicable not only to integrating work in the
system of behavior that leads to behavioral causa- area of causality but also work attempting to inte-
tion. That is, the new terminology for genes, envi- grate psychology itself.
ronment, and person speak to their intraactive
essence, their intraactive interaction, and their
intraactive causality. In an intraactive sense, the Chapter Conclusions
boundaries of each of the components in behav-
ioral causality are “fuzzy” and “get under the skin” The present chapter has presented novel concepts
of each other. related to behavioral causality and has integrated
Continuing in this vein, the concept of intraac- many of the themes critical to the present work.
tion can be applied to other principle concepts in One of the most fundamental is that of activation/
the present book, leading to their conceptual inhibition coordination, which is considered a
modification in a way similar to that just described primary mechanism in behavioral causality. Note
for causality. Therefore, one can speak of intraac- that development involves potential movement
tive networks, intraactive systems, the intraactive toward integration. With respect to the concept at
biopsychosocial model, intraactive embodiment, hand of activation/inhibition coordination, inte-
and so on. We can even describe the intraactive gration refers to increasing adaptive flexibility
person, the intraactive self, the intraactive brain, that is entailed in the increasing optimization of
the intraactive body, and the intraactive mind. activation/inhibition coordination that is found at
The different free will concepts in the book, such advanced, higher-order levels of the system. The
as freedom in being and having a sense of free levels become both more simple through super-
will, could be described in these terms. Other ordinate enslavement of its patterning over lower
terms that could be so described include freeing levels (chunking might be another term), as well
the brain and emergence. If behavior is intraac- as more complex through the increasing scope of
tive, then its evolution and development should control over behavior and adaptation that it
be described in these terms, too. One could spec- allows.
ify each of learning, empathy, theory of mind, The new terms in the chapter include the one
executive function, cognition, activation/inhibi- of neuromal networks, which highlights how
tion coordination, and so on, as intraactive. behavior is developed systemically. Also, it
Similarly, one could refer to intraactive emotions, expands the concept of intraactions. The chapter
References 765

deals extensively with the change processes and Jost, J., Bertschinger, N., & Olbrich, E. (2010).
mechanisms, readiness for and dimensions of Emergence. New Ideas in Psychology, 28, 265–273.
Kauffman, S. (1993). The origins of order: Self-
change, and my Neo-Piagetian (sub)stage model organization and selection in evolution. New York:
(Young, 2011). It re-emphasizes the centrality for Oxford University Press.
the study of causality in behavior of NLDST and Lewis, M. D. (2000a). The promise of dynamic systems
the concept of activation/inhibition coordination approaches for an integrated account of human devel-
opment. Child Development, 71, 36–43.
as a general mechanism. Despite the importance Lewis, M. D. (2000b). Emotional self-organization at
of the study of behavioral causality in psychol- three time scales. In M. D. Lewis & I. Granic (Eds.),
ogy, it lacks consistent focus on the topic. Toward Emotion, development, and self-organization:
unifying both the study of causality and the field Dynamic systems approaches to emotional
development (pp. 37–69). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
of psychology, itself, this chapter and the one University Press.
before it, which also presents new concepts and Lewis, M. D. (2005). Bridging emotion theory and neuro-
terms for the field, could serve as springboards biology through dynamic systems modeling.
for future thought and research on the topic. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 28, 169–245.
Nowak, M. A., & Highfield, R. (2011). Supercooperators:
The last part of the book that follows this pres- Altruism, evolution, and why we need each other to
ent chapter comprises six chapters that explain succeed. New York: Free Press.
further my Neo-Piagetian stage model and its Pigliucci, M. (2008). Is evolvability evolvable? Nature
implications. These include development of a Reviews Genetics, 9, 75–82.
Siegler, R. S. (2006). Microgenetic analyses of learning.
revision of my revised Neo-Maslovian model, as
In W. Damon, R. M. Lerner, D. Kuhn, & R. S. Siegler
well as a Neo-Kuhnian model of paradigm shift (Eds.), Handbook of child psychology: Cognition, per-
in science and scholarship, which should be inno- ception, and language (6th ed., Vol. 2, pp. 464–510).
vations worth examining by themselves. New York: Wiley.
Spelke, E. S., & Kinzler, K. D. (2007). Core knowledge.
Developmental Science, 10, 89–96.
Thelen, E., & Smith, L. B. (1994). A dynamic systems
References approach to the development of cognition and action.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Belsky, J., & Pluess, M. (2013). Beyond risk, resilience Wagner, A. (2005). Robustness and evolvability in living
and dysregulation: Phenotypic plasticity and human systems. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
development. Development and Psychopathology, 25, Wilson, D. S. (2009). Convergent cultural evolution
1243–1261. and multilevel selection: Reply to comments on
Berk, M. (2013). The DSM-5: Hyperbole, hope, or Janet Landa’s ‘The bioeconomics of homogenous
hypothesis? BioMed Central Medicine, 11, 128. middleman groups as adaptive units: Theory and
Colegrave, N., & Collins, S. (2008). Experimental evolu- empirical evidence viewed from a group selection
tion: Experimental evolution and evolvability. framework’. Journal of Bioeconomics, 11,
Heredity, 100, 464–470. 185–190.
Ellis, B. J., Boyce, W. T., Belsky, J., Bakermans- Young, G. (1997). Adult development, therapy, and cul-
Kranenburg, M. J., & van IJzendoorn, M. H. (2011). ture: A postmodern synthesis. New York: Plenum.
Differential susceptibility to the environment: An Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
evolutionary-neurodevelopmental theory. Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer
Development and Psychopathology, 23, 7–28. Science + Business Media.
Part VI
The Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian Model
A Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian
25-Step (Sub)Stage Model 31

The next six chapters of the present book espe-


Chapter Introduction cially elaborate from the perspective of causality
the model presented in Young (2011), consider-
The book began with a general view of causality in ing that it is developmental, biopsychosocial, and
philosophy and science, in particular. It considered systems in orientation. In this present chapter and
inclusive models, such as the biopsychosocial one, the ones to follow in this regard, I describe the
and emphasized the biological bases of behavior original model and innovations for it that further
(genes, brain), along with their interactions help establish it as an important base in under-
with the environment (Gene × Environment (G × E) standing causality in the psychological sciences.
interaction, epigenesis, cultural neuroscience, early The innovations in understanding causality
adversity effects, and so on). It turned to the topic of behavior in this last series of chapters of the
of development, including with respect to evolu- present work are not just based on extensions of
tion and on causal learning. It considered the topic my Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian developmen-
of free will, consistent with my emphasis that we tal model but considers other models related to it,
can contribute to our own development as a third such as Maslow’s and Kuhn’s. However, it cre-
force beyond nature and nurture. The book moved ates new models based on the latter ones, further-
to applied chapters, especially on psychopathology ing my approach of elaborating innovations
and the DSM-5 (Diagnostic and Statistical Manual related to causality in order to give it a more cen-
of Mental Disorders, Fifth Edition; American tral role in psychology. Also, this last portion of
Psychiatric Association, 2013). Next, it considered the book ends with a new integrative model of
innovations in understanding causality, including causality in behavior that is not based on my
new terms and my own models. developmental model, which is intended to spark
Up to this point, then, I have concentrated on interest and research in the field.
describing contemporary approaches to causality In this present chapter, I present especially the
in psychology, aside from a brief introduction to basics of the cognitive component of the com-
my model to several points in the book, but espe- bined Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian that I have
cially toward the end of the last chapter (e.g., developed. The first part of the chapter reviews
Young, 2011), and mentioned only briefly at the model, in general, including in terms of the
certain points the 25-step (5 stages × 5 substages) biological, environmental, and personal (psycho-
Neo-Piagetian cognitive developmental lifespan logical) factors involved. This part of the chapter
model at the heart of that book (the model also is taken from Young (2011). It includes the con-
includes a 25-step Neo-Eriksonian stage model that cept of yoking (sub)stages. The second part of the
corresponds to the cognitive one; see Table 31.1). chapter gives extensions of the cognitive portion

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 769


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_31
770

Table 31.1 A model of 25 steps in Neo-Piagetian cognitive development and Neo-Eriksonian social-affective development
Level Neo-Piagetian stage Substage Age range Neo-Eriksonian stage Neo-Eriksonian substage
1 Reflexive Coordination Earlier fetal life Non-participatory Distance acts vs. no acts
2 Hierarchization Quite premature reflexive socio-emotions Nursing vs. rootless acts
3 Systematization Somewhat premature Outcome vs. outcast acts
4 Multiplication Full-term newborn Care giving vs. careless giving acts
5 Integration 0–1 month Emotional vs. malemotional acts
6 Sensorimotor Coordination 1–4 months Pre-participatory Dyadic vs. dysdyadic acts
7 Hierarchization 4–8 months socio-affects Trust vs. mistrust acts
8 Systematization 8–12 months Sociability vs. unsociability acts
9 Multiplication 12–18 months Autonomy vs. doubt acts
10 Integration 18–24 months Interdigitational vs. dedigitational acts
31

11 Perioperational Coordination 2–3.5 years Peri-participatory social Superordinate vs. discoordinate acts (quasi-participatory)
12 Hierarchization 3.5–5 years cognitions Initiative vs. guilt acts
13 Systematization 5–7 years Identification vs. problematic identification acts
14 Multiplication 7–9 years Industry vs. inferiority acts (participatory)
15 Integration 9–11 years Role vs. role confusion acts
16 Abstract Coordination 11–13 years Hyper-participatory social Conscious vs. contraconscious acts
17 Hierarchization 13–16 years mutuality Identity vs. identity diffusion acts
18 Systematization 16–19 years Nurturing vs. misnurturing acts
19 Multiplication 19–22 years Intimacy vs. isolation acts
20 Integration 22–25 years Universal vs. self-singular acts
21 Collective intelligence Coordination 25–28 years Superordinate Metacollecting vs. disillusionment acts
22 Hierarchization 28–39 years participatory collective Generativity vs. self-absorption acts
23 Systematization 39–50 years sociality Catalytic vs. midlife crisis acts
24 Multiplication 50–61 years Ego integrity vs. despair acts
25 Integration 61– years Cathartic vs. abandonment acts
Adopted from Young (2011, 2012)
A Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian 25-Step (Sub)Stage Model
The Present Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian Stage and Substage Model 771

of the model into areas such as belief in free will development, but substages only for the first one.
and ethical thought. This part of the chapter is [Moreover, he referred to these substages as
based on Young (2014). stages!] Erikson had described eight major stages
The chapter following this one expands on the in developments, but no substages. In these
socioaffective aspect of the combined Neo- regards, I referred to five major cognitive stages
Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian model. This next in development, with cyclically referring sub-
chapter is based on Young (2011). It especially stages, and applied the same procedure to the
deals with my revisions of Erikson’s and Eriksonian series after having added 17 steps to
Maslow’s models. The last three chapters of the bring it to 25 total steps. Also note that in devel-
book are filled with many innovative concepts oping and naming any new stages and substages
that could help toward unifying both the study of in the two 25-step series, cognitive Neo-Piagetian
causality in psychology and the field of psychol- and socioaffective Neo-Eriksonian, I considered
ogy itself. Some of these include innovations both the nature of the original reduced series
based on my developmental model or the generic involved (cognitive Piagetian, socioaffective
one based on it. Eriksonian), as well as what was required in
terms of being coherent with the cyclically recur-
ring five substages over the five stages.
The Present Neo-Piagetian/ The cognitive portion of stage names borrows
Neo-Eriksonian Stage clearly from Piaget. The five-step substage
and Substage Model sequence is based on the Piagetian infant senso-
rimotor substage series (6). However, the first
Model one of the six has been removed and placed as a
separate stage (reflexive, and having its own sub-
Table 31.1 presents the essentials of the present stages), beginning in the prenatal period, some-
model of Neo-Piagetian cognitive development thing that Piaget had not contemplated. The
throughout the lifespan and its corresponding childhood perioperational stage constitutes a
Neo-Eriksonian levels (Young, 2011 and, as combined stage involving Piaget’s preoperational
modified in Young, 2012). The model consists of and concrete operational stages. [Piaget had
25 steps in development, comprising five stages referred to the period of Representation when he
and five cyclically recurring substages within referred to these combined stages.] For the ado-
each of them. Additionally, given the underlying lescent period, often I emphasize its abstract
change process that characterizes the recurring nature although also I use Piaget’s label of formal
substages, each substage could pass through the operations. The collective stage refers to the adult
same cyclic recursion at its level, in a fractaliza- ability to create superordinate abstract structures,
tion process, leading to a model of 125 possible to brainstorm together, to coordinate affect in
steps in development. [The fractal model is com- cognitive processes, etc.
pleted by noting that the five major stages in the The series of 25 Neo-Eriksonian stages and
model themselves can be reworked to describe substages in the present model corresponds to the
them as involving the five-step sequence from cognitive one. The table indicates the placement
coordination to integration.] of the eight original Eriksonian stages within the
To introduce, this combined Neo-Piagetian/ 25-step Neo-Eriksonian sequence and the overall
Neo-Eriksonian model, it constitutes the first correspondence of each of the steps in the 25-step
lifespan model of corresponding cognitive- Neo-Eriksonian sequence with the equivalent
affective stages in development. Before describ- cognitive step in the 25-step cognitive sequence.
ing in full, it is important to note some Within the 25-step Neo-Eriksonian sequence, one
terminological inconsistencies in comparing the finds the names of the 17 new steps that I created
various one developmental models in this sec- needed to add to the original eight-step sequence
tion. Piaget had described four major stages in in order to complete the cognitive-affective
772 31 A Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian 25-Step (Sub)Stage Model

correspondence over the 25 steps of the parallel related to biology, environment, and self. The
Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian model. tables’ columns are taken from Young (2011).
In terms of the placement of the original eight Together, they indicate the biopsychosocial nature
Eriksonian steps and their parallel with the cogni- of development, as emphasized in Young (2011).
tive steps that correspond best to them from For each step in the developmental model, the
among the 25 steps of the model, it is noteworthy second column of the table describes the underly-
that the eight original Eriksonian steps appear to ing biology involved at two levels. This second
emerge in parallel with the second and fourth sub- column is from Tables 26.1 to 26.10 in Young
stages of each of the last four cognitive Neo- (2011). It presents central specializations associ-
Piagetian stages. That is, looking at the major ated with each (sub)stage of the model and inhib-
stages that Erikson had described over the lifes- itory function therein. That is, first, it gives the
pan, it appears that he focused on steps in the pres- type of central developments taking place in
ent more inclusive model that concern elaborations terms of activation/inhibition coordination. In
(the hierarchization and multiplication substages; Young (2011), I gave this mechanism cardinal
2, 4) more than major advances (coordination, the importance in underpinning both brain and
first substage; systematization, the third; and inte- behavioral development. Also, the column lists
gration, the fifth in the series of five substages that evolutionary origins that might be associated
recur in each stage). As for naming the new 17 with the steps of the model.
Neo-Eriksonian stages in the present model, I The third column of the table gives the corre-
continued the Eriksonian tradition used in label- sponding step in the cognitive (mis)perception of
ing the original eight stages in terms of describing the other that is associated with each of the steps
them as polarities, but also I included the concept in the model, which is an aspect of the develop-
of “acts” in naming them. For the negative poles, ing person’s psychology, as deriving from lived
I avoided repeating prepositions such as “mis-” or experience in the environment. The third column
“dis-,” choosing a more varied nomenclature. is from Tables 14.2 to 14.6 in Young (2011). The
Note that, the 25-step developmental sequence steps in cognitive (mis)perception of the other
that I have developed in the present model is a refer to how others treat people when they do not
modal one. The model holds that each individual perceive and treat them optimally, e.g., as infan-
traverses differently the 25-step sequence. For tile and deserving of abuse. This type of behavior
example, although an individual might be at an stands as a proxy for an essential component of
advanced stage cognitively, on the one hand, that the environment in development.
stage might not be used to the fullest in cognitive The last column in the table gives the label for
problem solving. Moreover, the person might not the step in self-development that corresponds to
be at all at the corresponding socioaffective stage each of the 25 steps in development. The fourth
due to the negative effects of early adversity column is from Table 24.2 to 24.6 in Young
(e.g., maltreatment) or current conditions (e.g., (2011). It describes the steps in social self work-
trauma). The model provides a normative model ing schemata according to the model. This com-
that covers the lifespan but, more important, it ponent of the table represents one important
emphasizes the individual differences that take aspect of the “psychology” of the developing
place on its scaffold due to the multiple causal individual (the self-concept is core to one’s per-
factors influencing development. sonal representation). This column completes giv-
ing some details of my model that illustrates its
compatibility with the biopsychosocial approach.
The Model as Biopsychosocial The model of the cognitive (mis)perception of
the other, as presented in Young (2011), indicates
Tables 31.2, 31.3, 31.4, 31.5, and 31.6 elaborates that, at the lowest levels of (mis)perception of the
the 25-step Neo-Piagetian cognitive developmen- other, we treat the target person as an infant or
tal model that I have constructed with details young child despite their actual age (levels a–b of
The Present Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian Stage and Substage Model 773

Table 31.2 Neo-Piagetian reflexive stage models in development (in five steps): biology, environment, self (Young, 2011)
Environment
(Sub)Stages Biology (how parent treats child) Self
Coordination At first, reflex centers mature The child is seen as an No schemata other than
without stimulus sensitive extension of the parent’s self reflex pairings
activating mechanisms; so that he or she can negate,
nevertheless, they discharge, and abuse, reject, deny, and behave
this occurs even in pairs through absolutely, with overt insults
lateral inhibition–activation and rejection toward the child.
interplay The intonation is abrasive,
Evolutionary origin: Reptilian I negative, and rejecting
Hierarchization Fixed order established in reflex The child’s reasoning or Reflex pairs coordinate
pairs by one-way inhibitory position is attacked, criticized, and react to stimuli
suppression of direction in their or rejected. The parent overtly
functional linkage. Also, full denies the possibility of the
stimulus-provoked reflex arcs child being correct
develop through control by
inhibition–disinhibition timing
Evolutionary origin: Reptilian II
Systematization Above process expands to The child’s reasoning or Primitive schemata form
include other components at position is overtly dismissed in visual, auditory, haptic,
second or both phases of with no effort to olfactory, gustatory, and
movement. This may involve constructively redirect or kinesthetic activity/
coupling with other reflexes and/ guide understanding of the exploration; with
or interdigitation with extrareflex other’s viewpoint. The child is intermodal system
neuronal centers primarily told that he or she is “wrong,” coordinations
sensory-perceptual in nature but there is no effort to explain
Evolutionary origin: Reptilian III why
Multiplication Level 3 units coordinated Only part of the child’s Consistencies in care
sequentially in time by behavior or argument is giving lead to the
inhibition–activation balancing treated as indicated in the formation of bodily
Evolutionary origin: Reptilian IV previous substage components-of-context
associations. Patterned
schemata fire mechanically
Integration Movement becomes partly Despite such behavior, part of Independent schemata that
reflex-free as neuronal clusters the child’s behavior or are not reflex controlled
incorporate via own inhibition– argument is acknowledged or allow contextually-
activation balancing extrareflex listened to by the parent. adjusted, patterned
neuronal centers involved in There is a differentiation and behavior with emotional
control of spatiotemporal reversibility evident in the integrations
changes willingness to acknowledge/
Evolutionary origin: Reptilian V listen to the child
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science + Business Media; with kind permission from Springer
Science + Business Media B. V. [Second column from Table 26.1, Page 598, its second column, and from Table 26.6, Page
607, its last column; Third column: Table 14.2, Page 318, Fourth column: Table 24.2, Page 565, its second column]

the five-step model). Because of the devaluing misperception treats the target as someone who
nature of these levels, the target is considered as could be canalized or manipulated easily, due to
not having much equal rights, which facilitates their perceived lack of cognitive sophistication.
any abuse or suppression undertaken. As for per- In the last two stages of the model (d–e), the per-
ceiving the target at the third level of the model, son perceives the target in a way consistent with
or only in terms of the person being akin to an their age, that is, as a teenager or adult, or in a
older child at best, the person engaging in the more mature way.
Table 31.3 Neo-Piagetian sensorimotor stage models in development (in five steps): biology, environment, self (Young, 2011)
(Sub)Stages Biology Environment (how parent treats child) Self
Coordination By recruitment process similar to that in step 5, There is a high degree of parental control, subjugation, Working schemata become increasingly coordinative of the
larger neuronal clusters form. They require repression, authoritarianism, opposition, imposition, socializing self and the other, but only in the sense of partial
intracluster inhibition–activation synchrony so manipulation, and dominance in the conversation. It is components of both (e.g., the baby is contented and experiences
that movement sequence is controlled for fine shaped directly by the parent’s ideas or agenda. The pleasure)
interference by perseverations, and intruding child has no independent thought, but waits for the
similar movements parent to provide direction. The parent uses language
Evolutionary origin: Paleomammalian I to control the child’s physical actions and behaviors.
An order is given that directs the path in the
conversation (e.g., “You don’t have to say that,” or
“You’d better … You have to … You must …”)
Hierarchization Neuronal cluster interdigitation goes one step The child’s reasoning-position is competed with, As the infant develops a sense of trust, context-activated goals are
beyond as pairs form a hierarchy with one contradicted, countered, or opposed in an effort to added to developing schemata, which take on a hierarchical
subsumed to another by inhibition–activation subvert, manipulate, control, or undermine it structure (e.g., components of self are interested and delighted in
regulation. The fine interference control other)
described above also applies here
Evolutionary origin: Paleomammalian II
Systematization Above process expands to permit larger The child clearly is directed to speak or act in a Working schemata include self-defined goals, primitive
zone-area mobilization. Neuronal cluster particular way with no constructive explanation given representations such as images of the caregiver, and the desire for
hierarchies are synchronized to permit inhibitory as to why (e.g., “No,” “Tell me about …,” “Why don’t intersubjectivity and proximity and contact. The emotional side of
control of gross interference at outset and you …”) the developing cognitive-affective structure includes feelings of
throughout unrelated neuronal clusters affection and comfort
Evolutionary origin: Paleomammalian III
Multiplication Widespread expansion into extra zone-area Only part of the child’s discourse is manipulated. The one-year-old infant acts increasingly autonomous through
surround is a major step, ensuring that the gross Manipulative suggestions are made that flow from that planned exploratory behavior eagerly implemented, although this
interference control described above comes to part of the child’s previous discourse that seems to does not happen with explicit plans at the behavior’s outset (it is
include multiple surround neuronal clusters have been judged possibly acceptable to the parent “accidental”). The social other is integral to the working schemata
Evolutionary origin: Early prosimian being formed, but as an object of sensorimotoric-emotional activity
rather than a preconceived representational goal. The primary
care-giver who has been sensitive in the first year so that the infant
feels “loved” is sought actively in reunion after a brief separation
Integration The range of interference control now extends Despite some signs of parental manipulation, etc., Infants at 18 months of age enact symbolically guided, planned
cross zone-area, i.e., intrahemispherically to suggestions are made in a way that appears to give the activity, but always with a sensori-motoric and affective base.
some extend child a chance to use them or not They experience appreciation and pride. Others are understood in
Evolutionary origin: Early monkey (e.g., “You know that you could get what you want if terms of the plans, and with consistent participation in them. The
you did it this way.”). infant varies plans involving them on purpose to see the effect
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science + Business Media;
with kind permission from Springer Science + Business Media B. V. [Second column from Table 26.2, Page 599–600, its second column, and from Table 26.6, Page 607, its last column; Third
column: Table 14.3, Page 318, Fourth column: Table 24.3, Page 566, its second column]
Table 31.4 Neo-Piagetian developmental model of the perioperational stage (in five steps): biology, environment, self (Young, 2011)
(Sub)Stages Biology Environment (how parent treats child) Self
Coordination The process in level 10 radiates across the The parent channels/neutralizes/pacifies the child by disrupting/disorganizing/confusing the child In symbol plan
hemisphere, permitting cross zone-areas to (e.g., “You’re not thinking right”). The parent gives “I don’t know” answers to questions. The child coordinations, the child’s
being to form interlinked pairs directly attempts to keep the discussion going, but the parent does not participate or give an answer plans are more focused on
Evolutionary origin: Early ape to allow the discussion to proceed. Indiscriminate rewards are used to foster a climate of compliance/ self egocentrically, and the
assumption other, while schematized
more holistically, needs to
adjust. A sense of the other
as a loving one grows
Hierarchization Zone-areas in the same hemisphere form With a younger child, passive listening without comments or encouragement is a type of pacification- The child’s symbol plans
inhibition barriers between them to better channeling, because the child’s thought cannot be advanced, coherent, etc., in and of itself. With an are more differentiated,
control interference during their older child, a parent can pacify-channel in more indirect ways (e.g., ignore the child’s thought, with an initiative
interrelating and simultaneous functioning invalidate it; turn to own ideas after child’s speaking turn without acknowledgement of listening). subordinating the other,
Evolutionary origin: Australopithecus The parent is passive with no verbal or nonverbal expressions, direction, or guidance. The parent who is still responded to
afarensis may acknowledge her or his listening role (e.g., “Hmm hmm”). The parent parrots or paraphrases the with an overriding love,
child’s comments or requests minor restatements. Minor corrections are given by the parent (in however
vocabulary, pronunciation, grammar), but with no new information. The Parent may make a direct
request for information, or may ask a direct question (e.g., “Say that again,” “What do you think
about …”). The child is rewarded if he or she follows the parent’s lead or suggestions, or if the
(implicit) promise of such is possible. The result is that the same comments or ideas occur during the
discussion. No advances in storytelling or thought are made. An intermediary value of 12.5 is
assigned when the parent asks for clarification, e.g., “Is this what you mean?” or corrects
constructively, (but still with the limit that channeling, neutralizing, or pacifying is taking place)
Systematization Interhemispheric communication The parent points out a position/option that is different from the child’s own without constructive The “I” can take primary
collaboration (controlled in left explanation (e.g., “Couldn’t it be that …”, or “Yes, but another way is …”). Or the parent enunciates perspectives of the self/
hemisphere) by commissural (corpus own thought or position with some explanation other through symbol plan
callosum) inhibition–activation systems and Eriksonian
coordination allows brain-wide “industry,” guided by others
Multiplication mobilization. Several phases probably Despite some signs of channeling or pacification, a part of the child’s discourse is acknowledged/ This ability grows and
occur, involving intrahemispheric accepted/praised on its own terms. The parent clearly acknowledges the child’s answer or comment others are seen to evaluate
incorporation of emerging anterior areas but without accepting it (e.g., “Yes, I know what you mean,” or “I was just going to ask you that.”). the self
into the process. The frontal regions, for The parent shows some evidence of warmth and active interest in the child’s position, although the
example, are known for inhibition of conversation is not completely interactive
action to allow for evaluation
Integration A glimmer of possibility is left open for the child’s position or argument to emerge as being correct, The child’s working
Evolutionary origin: Homo habilis for
but in the context of others. The parent points out relationships between the child’s position and (an) schemata include testing of
systematization; Homo erectus for
other(s), their own, etc., integrating the child’s view as one differentiated member of a larger different roles, with others
multiplication; and Archaic Homo sapiens
perspective (e.g., “You’re right, but …”) seen as modelers and
for integration
accepting of this dynamic
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science + Business Media;
with kind permission from Springer Science + Business Media B. V. [Second column from Table 26.3, Page 600–601, its second column, and from Table 26.6, Page 607, its last column; Third
column: Table 14.4, Page 319, Fourth column: Table 24.4, Page 567, its second column]
776

Table 31.5 Neo-Piagetian abstract stage models in development (in five steps): biology, environment, self (Young, 2011)
(Sub)Stages Biology Environment (how parent treats child) Self
Coordination The process is level 15 expands to The parent indirectly encourages partially independent, novel Conscious “I” weighs abstractly
integration of major anterior (frontal) areas. thought of other possible dimensions to the story/reasoning
Welsh and Pennington (1988) describe how position, or the way given dimensions may interact (e.g., “Can you
these may emerge think of anything else”; “Why do you say that?”; “What else did he
Evolutionary origin: Homo sapiens do or say?”; “How does this relate to that?”). The parent suggests
that more may be possible or that there’s something important
missing (e.g., “Didn’t you forget something?”). The parent does not
provide information, but hints at a direction so the child can take
the lead of the discussion. The parent listens to the child’s response
31

and continues the conversation by building on the child’s responses


or by asking indirect questions
Hierarchization Interhemispheric integration (controlled in Part of the child’s reasoning is praised, reinforced by the parent Identity “I” tests and seeks identity
the left hemisphere) occurs by optimal directly with a constructive comment (e.g., “That’s a really good
synchronization of inhibition–activation idea because …”). The parent encourages the child to continue
coordination. Several phases may occur, and with her on his position/idea/comment. The parent allows the child
in the last one the integration may include to control the pace and direction of the discussion
Systematization inhibition of major self-reinforcing systems The child’s whole story/reasoning/position is shown to be valid in a Conscientious “I” undertakes
Evolutionary origin: Cromagnon people for constructive way adult- (like) functions
Multiplication hierarchization; contemporary people for The child is prompted to expand on the immediate/proximate Relativistic “I” delves and debates
systematization, multiplication, and implications of her or his story/reason/position
integration
Integration The child is prompted to see how her or his story/reason/position Universal “I” harmonizes
fits into a larger picture and may be harmonious with it
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science + Business
Media; with kind permission from Springer Science + Business Media B. V. [Second column from Table 26.4, Page 601, its second column, and from Table 26.6, Page 607, its
last column; Third column: Table 14.5, Page 320, Fourth column: Table 24.5, Page 567, its second column]
A Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian 25-Step (Sub)Stage Model
Table 31.6 Neo-Piagetian collective intelligence stage models in development (in five steps): biology, environment, self (Young, 2011)
(Sub)Stages Biology Environment (how parent treats child) Self
Coordination To this point, I have emphasized The child is prompted to indirectly seek or explore alternative scenarios, The self is collective, fused,
macroprocesses in activation–inhibition stories, perspectives, even ones not espoused by the parent her or himself and and coordinative
coordination in the brain relating to which may be discrepant from the parent’s own point of vie. The parent
increasing intra- and interzone/region should be encouraging a “collective” attitude/moral/value in this line of
integrations. However, throughout the discourse as he or she proceeds (e.g., “Is there another way of seeing …”)
Hierarchization process of hemispheric specialization The prompts above given to the child are given in a direct manner, but only The self knows priorities, is
and of brain growth, in general, for part of, not a full, perspective. The child is encouraged to see where multiply complex, and can
microprocesses are taking place related trade-offs, negotiations, bargaining, or give-and-take may apply to certain give multiply, and not for
to synaptogenesis, dendritic arborization, collective-oriented positions. However, the parent instills in the child the idea taking
synaptic pruning, and sculpting. In a that one of them is dominant over the other(s)
Systematization certain sense, circuitry formation and The prompts above are direct, and are aimed at eliciting a whole new At midlife, the self can
synaptic pruning/reorganization involve perspective. The parent encourages the child to consider alternative collective create and work to transform
neuronal activation and inhibition positions as being part of a larger system, and that all are considered equally personal, social, work, and
coordination processes at the microlevel valid, legitimate, and in a dynamic relationship with each other community systems
that complement the processes at the
Multiplication The parent encourages the child to see the implications of adopting large The elder self reviews the
macrolevel. To arrive at any of the
The Present Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian Stage and Substage Model

systems and to compare them. The parent and child discuss together multiplicity of life and lives
postformal stages in brain function and
similarities and differences among them. The parent and child together
specializations, the macro- and
realize that these sometimes conflicting systems can exist simultaneously
microprocesses should be working in a
Integration complete, optimal balance The parent encourages explicit attempts to put all previous systems into an An integrated “I” is really an
Evolutionary origin: Contemporary overarching principle, tempered by contextual pragmatic realities, e.g., living integrated “We” at life’s end
people for all with and growing from conflict
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science + Business
Media; with kind permission from Springer Science + Business Media B. V. [Second column from Table 26.5, Page 602, its second column, and from Table 26.6, Page 607, its last
column; Third column: Table 14.6, Page 320, Fourth column: Table 24.6, Page 567, its second column]
777
778 31 A Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian 25-Step (Sub)Stage Model

Biology Elaborated in the Model Broad Steps in Evolution

Activation/Inhibition Coordination As for other biological underpinnings to the pres-


ent 25-step developmental model, in Young
In the following, I elaborate the biological bases (2011), I described the evolutionary origins
corresponding to my 25-step Neo-Piagetian cog- related to the 25-step developmental model. The
nitive developmental model (Young, 2011). second column of Tables 31.2, 31.3, 31.4, 31.5,
Inhibitory skills are essential for survival, devel- and 31.6 includes these evolutionary correspon-
opment, self-regulation, and adaptive behavior. dences. The sequence is based on work on the
For example, behavior expresses exquisite coor- evolution of lateralization.
dination of activation not only in muscle activa- In this regard, MacNeilage, Studdert-Kennedy,
tion and interference control, but also in one’s and Lindblom (1987, 1988) hypothesized that
social synchronization with others. In this regard, early prosimians manifested a left hemisphere-
I have written controlled whole-body postural organization.
The complementary specialization of the right
The concept of inhibition applies fluidly across
many levels of psychological analysis … There are hemisphere in early prosimians concerned left-
biochemical mediators of inhibition. Inhibition is a hand, visually-directed activities (e.g., reaching).
central characteristic of neuronal network and cen- Next in evolution, early higher primates evolved
tral nervous system function. Importance is
to locomote quadrupedally. Thus, the left hemi-
attached to inhibition in overt behavior at multiple
levels: motoric, cognitive, social, personality, etc. sphere’s specialization for whole-body postural
Even environmental influences … can be con- control evolved into bimanual foraging in the
ceived in these terms (Young, 1990, p. 119). environment. The left hand evolved to support
right-hand manipulation. MacNeilage et al.
As Young (2011) noted, according to Aron (1987, 1988) suggested possible paleo-
(2008), a cardinal hypothesis about the role of the mammalian precursor steps in the evolution of
frontal cortex in executive control is that it func- laterality, and they have also suggested possible
tions to “inhibit and activate” representations in intermediate nonhuman primate steps involving
subcortical or posterior cortical brain regions. As early monkeys versus apes, in particular.
for my particular approach to inhibition in brain– Corballis (1989, 1991, 1992) depicted a
behavior relations, I have maintained that activa- seven-step sequence in the evolution of human
tion/inhibition coordination is critical to left laterality and related behavior. First, early ape
hemispheric function and, as a corollary, other ancestors evidenced some asymmetries in behav-
types of less complex inhibition are localized in ior and brain organization and also in language
the right hemisphere (Young, 2011). by manual gesture.
As applied to the present 25-step stage model, Then, the first hominids, Australopithecus afa-
the concept of activation–inhibition coordination rensis, emerged about 4–8 million years ago.
helps understand the increasing complexity of They showed upright posture, bipedalism, and
brain organization at each step. As lateralization freeing of the hands. Later australopithecines
proceeds through the phases in the 25-step (gracile, africanus) were quite similar.
sequence, it is argued that the deployment of an Then, Homo habilis evolved, as early as a lit-
activation–inhibition coordination or balancing tle over 2 million years ago. This species was
helps integrate newly matured zones with previ- characterized by both a larger brain and by a tool
ously functional ones. Also, the recent work on culture. The majority of the individuals in the
dynamic coordinations and networks in the brain species were right-handers, and apparently pos-
(Sporns, 2011, 2012) speaks to the issue of acti- sessed in the left hemisphere a larger speech pro-
vation–inhibition coordination in the brain duction (Broca’s) area as well as probably a
throughout the lifespan. larger speech reception (Wernicke’s) area.
Biology Elaborated in the Model 779

Then, Homo erectus evolved about 1.5 mil- combined 11-step evolutionary sequence and the
lion years ago. Their tool culture advanced to current 25-step developmental one would place
involve biface hand axes. the start of the former at the eighth level of
The next milestone, about 300,000 years ago, the latter, as shown in Table 31.1.
witnessed the evolution of Neandertal and other
Archaic homo sapiens. Their cranial size was
equivalent to that of contemporary humans. Mind Evolving
Homo sapiens sapiens evolved about 150,000–
200,000 years ago. They manifested extremely As noted in Young (2011), Donald (2008) and
adaptive, rapid speech, and also a flexibility and Mithen (2007) have described other sequences in
open-endedness (generativity) in tool-blade man- the evolution of behavior, in this case that of the
ufacture and use. evolution of mind. Donald (2008) hypothesized
Finally, Cromagnon people evolved about that there are three major “stages” in the cultural-
37,000 years ago. They exhibited an explosion in cognitive evolution of the hominid mind. The
culture (e.g., in blade technology, cave art, body stages involve shifting (a) from the marginally
ornaments). symbolic, (b) to the proto-symbolic, and then (c)
By combining the two phylogenetic progres- to the fully symbolic mind. According to Donald
sions just presented by MacNeilage et al. and by (2008), the corresponding age periods in the evo-
Corballis, in Young (2011), after eliminating lutionary course of these three evolutionary
redundancies, I arrived at a sequence in primate acquisitions, respectively, are about: (a) 2–4 mil-
and hominid evolution made up of up to 11 steps. lion years ago when the first hominid species
The 11 steps include the following landmark appeared, (b) then about 400,000 years ago when
points in evolution: paleo-mammalian; early the species homo sapiens first appeared, and (c)
prosimian; ancestral monkey; ancestral ape; then when the modern mind emerged in humans.
Australopithecus afarensis; Homo habilis; Homo Donald labeled the three stages as (a) mimetic,
erectus; Archaic homo sapiens; Homo sapiens (b) mythic, and (c) theoretic, respectively. The
sapiens; Cromagnon people; and contemporary mimetic stage involved nonverbal action model-
people. ing and imitation. The mythic step involved
The 25-step ontogenetic sequence presented in advanced linguistic skills. Finally, the theoretic
my model seems to have correspondences with transition involved extensive use of symbols, for-
the phylogenetic emergence of our species, as malisms, and external storage of memory. Before
shown in column 2 of Tables 31.2, 31.3, 31.4, these three stages appeared, Donald indicated
31.5, and 31.6. There may not be a one-to-one par- that the Miocene primates had developed an
allel in the development of stages in ontogeny and episodic-type mind. The episodic step involved
the evolutionary steps in phylogeny (ancestral complex event representation.
ones) because of processes such as neoteny and Mithen (2007) described five steps in the evo-
acceleration (Gould, 1977), which function to lution of the human mind, stretching from 2 mil-
alter or affect the former sequence in relation to lion years ago to 50,000 years ago, and he also
the latter. [Neoteny concerns a retardation or delay mentioned changes in the mind that had devel-
in the appearance or full maturation of a develop- oped after the Ice Age, 10,000 years ago. In the
ing behavior relative to the status predicted for it first step, between 1.5 and 2 million years ago, an
on the basis of prior evolution. Acceleration refers advance in brain size allowed our ancestors,
to the inverse of this process.] Homo ergaster, to develop a theory of mind.
Nevertheless, comparison of developmental Next, about 0.5 million years ago, a specialized
and evolutionary sequences that have been intelligence evolved to allow for interaction with
described can be instructive. In this regard, the the social, natural, and technological milieux.
best fit of the MacNeilage et al.-Corballis Then, about 0.25 million years ago, an advanced
780 31 A Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian 25-Step (Sub)Stage Model

holistic communication allowed advanced vocal- 3000 years, as societies became more organized.
gestural communicative abilities, or proto- This proposed step in human evolution of mind
language. Next, Homo sapiens developed a reflects the equivalent last step or substage in
cognitive fluidity, which concerns cross-modal each stage of my developmental model, which is
thought, and this happened about 100,000 years referred to as integration.
ago. It permitted major cultural advances. In the Finally, in my model, I describe the adult as
next step, beginning 50,000 years ago, modern developing a postformal stage of collective intel-
humans developed an “extended” mind. We could ligence. This would seem to be a very recent
extend beyond our brain into the material culture. acquisition in the evolution of the human mind,
Finally, 10,000 years ago, with the end of the Ice and one limited (hopefully only for the moment)
Age, people began farming by using their intelli- in the percentage of people expressing it. As with
gence. They developed advanced intellectual the other stages in the mode, it passes through a
skills, such as creating metaphors and analogies. five-step or substage sequence from coordination
The work of Donald and Mithen is comple- to integration or, at least should.
mentary in their descriptions of the evolution of
the human mind. Donald’s mythic stage corre-
sponds to Mithen’s one of holistic communica- Psychology Elaborated in the Model
tion about 300,000 years ago (in Neandertals).
His theoretic stage corresponds to Mithen’s As a proxy for self-development, the model
description of the modern mind as extended. refers to social self working schemata. This con-
Their combined models allow for an eight-step cept is an elaboration of the one of internal work-
sequence in the evolution of the modern mind. ing model in the attachment literature (Young,
Moreover, the sequence fits nicely into my own 2011). I have posited that, as with any normative
model. In particular, the eight steps in the com- cognitive acquisition, the present Neo-Piagetian
bined Donald–Mithen sequence in the evolution cognitive model of 25 steps in development
of mind is one that corresponds to the first eight speaks to how social self working schemata
steps of the ten steps in my developmental model evolve throughout the lifespan. The tables give
that covers the perioperational stage and the only positive schemata, rather than the equiva-
abstract stage. It will be recalled that in each of lents that could derive in aversive, abuse, or oth-
these stages, I describe five substages. erwise negative environments. The schemata
Therefore, by looking further at my model for include reference to critical emotions and also to
those steps that have no correspondence with the modeling following the work of Erikson.
combined Donald–Mithen sequence on the ori- The first table of the series is on the reflex
gins of the modern mind, I would add that after stage, which is the first in my five-stage Neo-
the post-Ice Age acquisitions in the evolution of Piagetian development sequence (the others being
mind described by Mithen, two more steps in the sensorimotor, perioperational, abstract, and col-
evolution of the mind took place. First, the lective intelligence). The table indicates that
abstract systems that had developed beginning working schemata in the first month include basic
about 10,000 years ago entered a phase of multi- emotional components, and also that the caregiver
plication, or spreading out the term used in the already could be manifesting sensitive care in an
present model for the fourth step or substage impactful way. The next table on the sensorimotor
within the development of each stage. Most prob- stage presents the critical period in the first 2
ably, this took place about 5000 years ago, hap- years of life when working schemata are develop-
pening with the establishment of small ing their secure or insecure characteristics. For the
non-farming communities. Next, the various self, the schemata evolve in this stage from ones
abstract systems that had developed became concerned with social coordination to those
more integrated into coherent abstract structures. involved in active attachment and feeling loved, to
This most probably took place within the last schemata that are more symbolic, even if still sen-
Yoking Further Explained 781

sorimotor. For the other, the schemata move from functioning cognitively at the upper level of the
working models of initial social interactions, model, but might not be functioning in co-man-
trust, and caregivers being security-promoting, to agement style at the corresponding level (rather,
genuine interactions with and constancy in object. at lower ones). Therefore, management styles
In the perioperational stage, working schemata of involving abuse or domination are potentiated
the self are marked by egocentric conceptions. when the other is perceived as reflexive or not
They move to a better perspective-taking of the cognitively functional (at best). In contrast, when
other, and to testing different roles. The other a manager or a management team is functioning
evolves from being conceived as being adjustable at the highest level of collective intelligence, and
and to a person having rules and modulating the management team perceives the other through
growth, to being capable of evaluating and of this lens, better teamwork in the work environ-
modeling roles. In the abstract stage, the working ment could be promoted, for example, including
model of the self develops from a conscious being the emphasis on brainstorming at this stage.
to a conscientious and universalizing one.
Symmetrically, ideally, the other acts to raise con-
sciousness, conscientiousness, and universal Interim Conclusion
empathy. In the collective stage, the self moves
toward generativity, midlife, and end-of-life con- This section of the present work has presented
cerns. The other is conceived in a mirror way. the 25-step stage model of development described
in Young (2011, 2012). It elaborated its corre-
spondences with the biopsychosocial model,
Environment Elaborated starting with its biological (central, evolutionary)
in the Model correspondences, in particular. Also, it presented
the cognitive (mis)perceptions of the other that
The model of the cognitive (mis)perception of the are associated with each step, as a proxy for the
other has been applied to management style in environmental impacts of the environment on the
Young (2011). In the management style of nega- developing person. Finally, it turned to the psy-
tion, the supervisor engages in behavior involv- chological component by examining evolution of
ing overloading, treating poorly, rejecting, and social self working schemata that are aspects of
denying; in domination, the supervisor engages self-development.
in behavior involving subjugating, repressing, The three areas of the present model involving
opposing, imposing, and manipulating; in relega- biology, environment, and psychology express a
tion, the supervisor engages in behavior involv- consistency with the biopsychosocial model, and
ing neutralizing, channeling, assimilating, and illustrate how its 25 steps can flesh out a refined
pacifying; in delegation, the supervisor engages version of the biopsychosocial model.
in behavior involving offering responsibility, In the next part of the present work, I present
showing concern, and liberating somewhat; further expansions of the 25-step model as pre-
lastly, in integration, the supervisor engages in sented in Young (2011). It helps set the stage for
behavior involving promoting individual and col- presentation of other extensions of my work.
lective action, creativity, thought, freedom, and
awareness; empowering, humanizing, trusting
others’ wisdom; and facilitating emergence Yoking Further Explained
of constant adaptation and growth, as well as
coparticipating in process. These five manage- Introduction
ment styles reflect the Neo-Piagetian cognitive
levels in Young’s (2011) model of reflexive, sen- Table 31.7 illustrates how Piagetian stages that
sorimotor, perioperational, abstract, and collec- develop could co-exist in thought, and how even
tive intelligence, respectively. The adult might be lower-order ones, such as pre-operational thought
782 31 A Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian 25-Step (Sub)Stage Model

Table 31.7 Yoking in cognitive development: how different Neo-Piagetian stages are combined in thought
Pre-intuitive Intuitive Logical thought
Cognitive stage Reflexive Sensorimotor Perioperational Abstract (formal) Collective intelligence
Reflexive O XX XX XX XX
Sensorimotor XX O XX XX XX
Perioperational XX XX O XX XX
Abstract (formal) XX XX XX O XX
Collective XX XX XX XX O
intelligence
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science + Business Media; with kind permission from Springer
Science + Business Media B. V. [Table 17.4, Page 408]
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feigning, and response
bias in psychiatric/ psychological injury: Implications for Practice and court. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer
Science + Business Media; with kind permission from Springer Science + Business Media B. V. [Table 23.10, Page 603]

and its intuitive component, might be hierarchi- the diagonal represent the yoking of the paired
cally predominant in cognitive deployment. stages. Developmental stage yoking means that
Yoking could lead to lower-order cognitive the lower-order stage of any pair is still present in
stages becoming predominant in various stage development even as the higher-order one to
combinations constructed or becoming active in which it is connected emerges. Moreover, they
problem solving and thought. There are multiple do not remain in their original form, but both
advantages to use of automatic, intuitive, fast alter in their reciprocal organization through the
prelogical thought (Barrouillet, 2011; Kahneman, yoking. For example, perioperational cognitive
2011; Stanovich, West, & Toplak, 2011). structures could be coupled with sensorimotor
However, problem solving often requires higher- schemes. Of course, yoking could involve more
order thought. Aside from genetic/biological vul- than two stages. Further, it could involve sub-
nerabilities leading to inappropriate use of or stages rather than stages, making the process
ability to switch to or have logical though lead in quite complex.
cognitive yoking during problem solving, there
might be environmental factors at play, as well,
such as early childhood abuse or later injury, ill- Backward–Forward
ness, or environmental insult and stress. When
this happens in the rehabilitative context, the When the yoking involves a higher-order struc-
therapist needs to understand that ineffective ture as dominant, the yoking can be qualified
problem solving might result from an inefficient, as backward. But when the yoking involves
nonlogical cognitive mode of thought used habit- the lower-order stage structure as primary, the
ually instead of any inability to problem solving, yoking is considered forward. For example,
per se, and appropriate steps can be taken to have sensorimotor skills could be yoked to concrete
the patient increase logical thought processes. operational ones in the perioperational phase.
In the table, the stage couplings under the
diagonal represent backward yoking, and those
Yoking above it represent forward yoking. Normally,
backward yoking is the more advanced type of
The diagonal line represents the development of stage structure yoking. However, for adaptive
the five Neo-Piagetian stages of the present problem-solving forward yoking could be
model. The stages that are paired by the intersec- crucial. The context determines the priorities in
tion of the columns and rows and that are not on this regard.
Chapter Conclusions 783

Because of backward and forward yoking, the Dual Track Stages


developing person has more than one set of cog-
nitive repertoires available for problem solving. The implication is that each stage in cognitive
By taking into account the possibility of triplets development follows two tracks. First, it lays
and larger aggregates in stage structure forma- the seeds for the development of the stage that
tions, it can be shown that the amount of poten- emerges from it as the next step in the qualita-
tial stage structure yoking is quite large. tively advancing series of steps in cognitive
Cognitive adaptation has available multiple development. Second, it continues to develop
yoking possibilities. Moreover, socioaffective for what it is at an increasing level of complex-
consideration could interfere in appropriate ity through the stages that follow it in develop-
cognitive yoking and problem solving. In this ment. For example, sensorimotor intelligence
regard, consider the pull of regressive socioaf- never leaves us, and serves us in good stead
fective yoking of Neo-Eriksonian step acquisi- throughout our lives. However, this happens as
tions as an example. part of the adaptive strategies that we use to
accomplish daily tasks, solve daily difficulties
and problems, and develop expertise in areas
Multiply Intelligent related to it.

This begs the question of how many types of


intelligence does the individual call forth in prob- Multiple Intelligences
lem solving at any one time, and how they are
organized when there are multiples. It also raises In terms of concept of multiple intelligences, it
the question of the nature of multiple intelli- appears that the present model can accommodate
gences, because there are myriad patterns of the concept. For example, the sequence of five
stage structure couplings that could take place in stages in development could be used to represent
cognitive activity. Note the contrast in this type five types of multiple intelligences. Because each
of conception of multiple intelligences compared stage persists even after others have developed
to the classic models of Gardner (2011) and having more complexity, at any one time in
Sternberg (2012), which do not concern stages. development after the infancy period, the devel-
For example, in my approach to multiple intelli- oping person can draw upon, as required, at least
gences, one could ask when lower-order stages two of the stages.
are primary in yoking, does this mean that the Moreover, when yoking is involved, the dual
individual is functioning at a lower level cogni- structures imply a second or combined tier of
tively? Perhaps not, because it is the nature of the multiple intelligences. Therefore, cognitive stage
combination in context that must be taken into structure yoking is a concept that could help
account, e.g., the primary stage might be abso- explain that any of lower level types of multiple
lutely essential even if lower-order. Moreover, intelligences represented by the first few of the
the secondary, higher-order one might still have a five stages of the present model might function
role in determining the overall level of the cou- more or less at upper level in cognitive activity
plings and work to modify the activity of the when they are coupled with those levels.
lower-order one involved. As development pro-
ceeds, these lower-order coupled stages could
continue to improve in capacity, scope, automa- Chapter Conclusions
ticity, recruitment, refinement, and extension
when called forth in similar circumstances to the The present chapter presents the essentials of
first time that they were yoked to higher-order Young’s (2011) model of 25 parallel steps (5
ones, but without affecting greatly the chief char- stages × 5 substages) in cognitive (Neo-
acteristics of the higher-order level. Piagetian) and socioaffective (Neo-Eriksonian)
784 31 A Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian 25-Step (Sub)Stage Model

development. It reviews the steps in the model Barrouillet, P. (2011). Dual-process theories of reasoning:
The test of development. Developmental Review, 31,
and its organization into stages and substages. It
151–179.
shows how it treats biological, psychological, Corballis, M. C. (1989). Laterality and human evolution.
and environmental aspects, thereby making it Psychological Review, 96, 492–505.
consistent with a developmental biopsychoso- Corballis, M. C. (1991). The lop-sided ape: Evolution
of the generative mind. New York: Oxford University
cial model.
Press.
The chapter includes the concept of yoking, Corballis, M. C. (1992). On the evolution of language and
which means that the person functioning cogni- generativity. Cognition, 44, 197–226.
tively not only might use the most advanced Donald, M. (2008). How culture and brain mechanisms
cognitive acquisitions for the issue at hand but interact in decision-making. In C. Engel & W. Singer
(Eds.), Better than conscious? Decision-making, the
also hinge to it other lower-order acquisitions. human mind, and implications for institutions
Moreover, unlike in some views of stage mod- (pp. 191–225). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
els, the present version allows for the parallel Gardner, H. E. (2011). Frames of mind: The theory of mul-
existence of lower-order and higher-order ones tiple intelligence. Philadelphia, PA: Basic Books.
Gould, S. J. (1977). Ontogeny and phylogeny. Cambridge,
because the former are not totally subsumed in MA: Belknap.
the latter, but remain available for use, albeit Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking fast and slow. New York:
developing all along. Through the concept of Farrar, Straus, and Giroux.
yoking, the present model addresses the concept MacNeilage, P. F., Studdert-Kennedy, M. G., & Lindblom,
B. (1987). Primate handedness reconsidered.
of multiple intelligences in the following way. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 10, 247–263.
That is, rather than a model of multiple intelli- MacNeilage, P. F., Studdert-Kennedy, M. G., & Lindblom,
gence involving independent acquisitions, in B. (1988). Primate handedness: A foot in the door.
terms of the present 25-step developmental Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 11, 737–746.
Mithen, S. (2007). Key changes in the evolution of human
model, multiple intelligences concern the yok-
psychology. In S. W. Gangestad & J. A. Simpson (Eds.),
ing of primary, more advanced stages and sec- The evolution of mind: Fundamental questions and
ondary, lower-order ones stages (or their controversies (pp. 256–266). New York: Guilford Press.
substages) that might help for an issue at hand. Sporns, O. (2011). Networks of the brain. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Therefore, the different intelligences in my
Sporns, O. (2012). Discovering the human connectome.
approach to the question relate to the stages in Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
the model presented and, moreover, they can be Stanovich, K. E., West, R. F., & Toplak, M. E. (2011). The
yoked in context as the situation requires. [Note complexity of developmental predictions from dual
that the concept of cognitive Neo-Piagetian process models. Developmental Review, 31, 103–118.
Sternberg, R. J. (2012). Intelligence. Wiley Interdisciplinary
yoking also can apply to yoking of socioaffec- Reviews: Cognitive Science, 3, 501–511.
tive Neo-Eriksonian developmental steps, as in Welsh, M., & Pennington, B. (1988). Assessing frontal lobe
the example of possible regression to a previ- functioning in children: Views from developmental
ously mastered lower-order step, perhaps while psychology. Developmental Psychology, 4, 199–230.
Young, G. (1990). Early neuropsychological develop-
it is still coupled to others, including the cur- ment: Lateralization of functions - hemispheric spe-
rent, most advanced yet less central one to ongo- cialization. In C. A. Hauert (Ed.), Developmental
ing functioning.] psychology: Cognitive, perceptuo-motor and neuro-
psychological perspectives (pp. 113–181). Amsterdam,
Netherlands: North Holland.
Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
References Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer
Science + Business Media.
American Psychiatric Association. (2013). Diagnostic Young, G. (2012). A unitary Neo-Piagetian/Neo-
and statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM-5 Eriksonian model of development: Fundamental
(5th ed.). Washington, DC: Author. assumptions and meta-issues. New Ideas in
Aron, A. R. (2008). Progress in executive-function Psychology, 30, 241–249.
research: From tasks to functions to regions networks. Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feigning, and response
Current Directions in Psychological Science, 17, bias in psychiatric/psychological injury: Implications
124–129. for practice and court. Dordrecht, Netherlands:
Springer Science + Business Media.
Further Expansions of the Present
Stage Models 32

To begin, it is worth reminding that the pres-


Chapter Introduction ent model is unique in proposing, for the full
lifespan, parallel Neo-Piagetian and Neo-
The present chapter especially elaborates the Eriksonian stages and substages (5 × 5 = 25 steps).
socioaffective (Neo-Eriksonian and Neo- Moreover, the present model lends itself to dis-
Maslovian) side of my combined cognitive/ covering the uniqueness of the human species.
socioaffective (sub)stage model of develop-
ment, as presented in Young (2011). It includes
examination not only of the revised Eriksonian Human Exceptionalism
and Maslovian models but also extensions,
including in revisions of dual process thinking, On the one hand, we are the only species that
free will development, and ethical thought, as develops out of the preoperational stage of Piaget,
well as how re-responsibilities might develop (a aside perhaps for a few isolated cognitive skills
Neo-Lévinasian concept). Finally, I show how that might be found in other species. Second, our
the present model applies to the development of capacity to develop cognitively to such an
the communal cognitive enterprise of science advanced degree is facilitated not only by bio-
building. In particular, I apply the present model logical factors (e.g., a lengthier developmental
to the evolution of developmental psychology as period) but also by environmental ones (e.g., our
a discipline and also to evolution of evolution better educational procedures and processes).
itself. Among others, Young (2011) pointed out that
Meltzoff, Kuhl, Movellan, and Sejnowski (2009)
and Tomasello and Carpenter (2007) considered
Neo-Piagetian enhanced or instructed learning as constitutive of
our human uniqueness. Also, both emphasized
Introduction the importance of early inter-subjectivity and
mentalization in human development. The joint
After having constructed the 25-step model of attention, empathic understanding, cooperative
development in Young (2011), I sought ways it communication, and social collaboration together
could be expanded to deal with some of the criti- undoubtedly contribute to our capacity both to
cal issues in development. This section of the be educated from an early age and also to
present chapter reviews some of these extensions educate children (a process to which I refer as
of my model found in Young (2011). “co-education”).

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 785


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_32
786 32 Further Expansions of the Present Stage Models

Social-Emotional Cognition-Emotion-Body of the Other The


table describes a revised model of theory of mind,
Theory of Mind Social cognition might be seen and how it might develop through the stages of the
to develop from the perspective of the present present developmental model. For several reasons,
25-step model (see Table 32.1). (a) In this regard the concept that I have developed for theory of
(and consistent with the literature review in mind is referred to as “cognition-emotion-body of
Chap. 17), the model specifies that the neonate the other.” First, perspective-taking about the
develops a reflexive inter-subjectivity, as in neo- other, or the development of relevant precursors in
natal imitation, that is facilitated by intramodal this ability, can happen at any age. Therefore, the
visual-kinesthetic processes. (b) Next, the infant concept of a “theory” of mind is one that is too
in the first 2 years develops an embodied mental- cognitive and limited. Similarly, the component of
ization, facilitated by sensorimotor developmen- the term that refers to “mind” is too limited and
tal processes. (c) Then, the preschooler acquires limiting. As we develop perspective of the other, it
representational capacities that lead to perspec- is not only about mind, but also about affective and
tive-taking of the other, or the so-called theory of corporal manifestations and processes. Finally, by
mind. This appears to happen in two steps—a including all three components of the term
first-order theory of mind, as revealed in the clas- (cognition-emotion-body) in the term, we
sic false belief task, and a second-order theory of acknowledge the embodied nature of theory of
mind, for example, in the Eyes task. This two- mind, how it can begin developing in the earlier,
step acquisition in theory of mind would seem to more physical stages (reflexive, sensorimotor),
correspond to the development of Piagetian pre- and how it is relational, participatory, and cocon-
operational and initial concrete operational structed. Compared to the term theory of mind, the
thought, respectively. Also, there are precursors one of cognition-emotion-body of the other is a
in the sensorimotor period that develop related to holistic concept and, as such, includes a contextual
theory of mind. (d, e) Next, the teenager develops ground in its unfolding.
more advanced perceptions and also taking the
perspective of the other, in terms of the transition Coeducation In terms of the concept of coedu-
of these capacities according to the development cation, I developed it from the concept of coap-
of abstract thought (which leads to postformal propriation (Young, 1997), which itself was
equivalents in the adult). [In the table, I list the developed from the concept of appropriation.
stages of the model, but it can be expanded to Developing individuals learn of and internalize
include the model’s component of cyclically the world into coschemes and co-operations, in a
recurring substages.] shared, relational participation with the world.

Table 32.1 Stages in construction of the cognitive-emotion-body of the other and in coeducation
Stage Cognition-emotion-body of the other Coeducation
Reflexive Nascent intersubjectivity Scaffolded holding
Sensorimotor Embodied intentionality Exploration promoting
Perioperational Theory of mind Instructional, teaching
Preoperational First-order Informal
Concrete operational Second-order Formal
Abstract Third-order theory of mind Real-world, transitional
Collective intelligence Postformal theory of mind School of life, mentoring
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2011). Development and causality:
Neo-Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science + Business Media; with kind permission from Springer
Science + Business Media B. V. [Table 15.1, Page 350]
Neo-Piagetian 787

Similarly, as individuals develop, they are terms of the core characteristic of each, and then
instructed, taught, or educated in a shared, rela- extending the revised theory of mind sequence in
tional participation with the world, as promoted the prior table to a corresponding sequence for
by parents, peers, and other significant adults, as empathy.
well as by associated technological and institu- First, the five cognitive stages of the present
tional tools or procedures. In their turn, children model can be reworked to reflect a transition in
act on the enhanced educational contexts that are development through five steps moving from
provided to them, thereby altering to a degree the the physical to the spiritual. For example, the
educational contents and mechanisms received. reflex period is especially a physical one, while the
The particular advances in the cognition- adult one potentially is quite spiritual. In between
emotion-body of the other in the early stages of these stages, development moves through an emo-
life refer to (a) reflexive, nascent intersubjectivity tional, cognitive, and consciousness sequence.
and (b) sensorimotor, embodied intentionality. Granted, in infancy, cognition and emotions are
The corresponding coeducational functions that developing jointly, in that both are involved inti-
can serve to both buffer and to optimize their mately in all the stage. However, the core infant
development refer to a scaffolded holding frame characteristic would seem more emotional than
and exploration promotion, respectively. (c) As the cognitive, and for the older child it develops
child enters the preschool and school-age years, an toward the reverse. For the adolescent, modally,
explicit theory of mind develops (first order, then consciousness develops in the sense of becoming
second order), as described in the literature. These aware of the self, and of one’s own development
acquisitions could be related, in part, to Piagetian and past, and in reflecting on and perhaps trying to
stage acquisitions. (d, e) The teenager and adult change the self, or one’s identity.
become more differentiated in their theories of As for extending the revised theory of mind
mind according to their increasing cognitive skills. model associated with the present developmental
For the child, coeducation takes the form of infor- model, as presented in Table 32.2, for the levels
mal and formal modeling, instruction, teaching, of empathy in the model, I refer to quasi-logical
and education. For the teenager and adult, coedu- and (concrete) logical steps in development of
cation is about preparing for and engaging in the cognitive empathy. These are terms that parallel
real world, whether at school or in work. Piaget’s pre-operational and concrete operational
stages. They are borrowed from Baldwin (see
Empathy The next table (Table 32.2) expands Young, 2011).
further the present developmental model by Note that in the table, I refer to the development
reframing the five major stages of the model in of empathy in the reflexive period as “somatic

Table 32.2 Neo-Piagetian cognitive, empathy, and theory of mind development


Neo-Piagetian stage Major focus Empathy level Theory of mind level
Reflexive Physical Somatic empathy Preparation (nascent intersubjectivity)
Sensorimotor Emotional Emotional empathy Sensorimotor representation (embodied intentionality)
Perioperational Cognitive Cognitive empathy “Theory” theory
(representation) – Quasi-logical – First-order
– Preoperational – Logical – Second-order
– Concrete operational
Abstract Conscious Conscious empathy Third-order
Collective intelligence Spiritual Spiritual empathy Postformal
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science + Business Media; with kind permission from Springer Science +
Business Media B. V. [Second column: Table 35.7, Page 832; Fourth column: Table 15.1, Page 350]
788 32 Further Expansions of the Present Stage Models

empathy.” As far as I know, this is a term new to Consciousness Freud had proposed that the
the field of psychology, and by this, I mean that the unconscious especially develops in the preschool
bases for further development of empathy after the years, as part of a process of repression of
neonatal period are present in preliminary fashion parentally-unacceptable libidinally-promoted
already at this age, being “prepared” and embod- desires. Another understanding of consciousness
ied in the early cognitive and socioaffective devel- considers it as becoming aware of life and the self,
opment of the child (Hamlin, 2014). for example, in the teen years when abstract thought
develops. Carrying this concept one step further,
one way of labeling adult consciousness would be
Free Will to call it “supra-consciousness.” Before the uncon-
scious develops, prior steps in its emergence could
Model Table 32.3 presents a philosophical and be labeled proto- and non-consciousness.
psychological model of higher-order human
motivations and aspirations. In this regard, Free Will In terms of corresponding steps in the
Baumeister (2008) noted that functioning as if development of free will, according to the model,
one has free will involves self-control and decid- it moves from the expression of will in the
ing things rationally. Free will becomes evident infancy period to the child gaining more control
by acting responsibly, deliberating consciously, of it in childhood. It manifests as the traditional
behaving agentically and autonomously, and understanding of the term in adolescence (having
comporting in a civilized manner. choice, deliberating, etc.), and only in the adult
According to me, having a sense of free will period can it arrive at the advanced and nuanced
develops in the context of a psychology imbued level described above.
with a sense of responsibility in the Lévinasian
sense of facing and feeling responsible for the Responsibility Table 32.3 indicates how the
disadvantaged other. Responsibility is not just sense of responsibility grows with developmental
about discharging daily tasks; more important, it stage.
is about growing to be and about constantly desir- (a) In terms of responsibility, or its lack, in the
ing to become, in the Heideggerian sense, of first stage of the present model, the reflexive
“being in the world.” period involves the fetus being responsive
Table 32.3 indicates that having a sense of but not initiatory. There is no inkling of
free will develops as part of a complex involving responsibility.
self-control, consciousness, and taking responsi- (b) In the sensorimotor stage, the infant is more
bility. In the following, I examine each of these active and agentic, as well as voluntary and
components from the perspective of the present selective to some degree. In this sense, the
model. infant can be considered “response-able.”

Table 32.3 A philosophy of Re-Responsibilities and of freedom from will


Level of free
Neo-Piagetian stage Level of self-control Level of consciousness will Level of responsibility
Reflexive Involuntary Non-conscious – Responsive
Sensorimotor Voluntary Pre-conscious Will Response-able
Perioperational Social-cognitive Unconscious Will free Responsibility
Abstract Formal-identity Conscious Free will Re-Responsibility
Collective intelligence Collective Supra-conscious Free Re-Responsibilities
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science + Business Media; with kind permission from Springer Science +
Business Media B. V. [Table 35.2, Page 813]
Neo-Eriksonian 789

(c) As for the child, logic in the Piagetian sense crisis, danger, challenge, or issue that needs to be
develops. The child is capable of undertaking navigated in mutuality with the environment.
responsibility, but at first, is limited by the Each step is a psychosocial one, and is described
concrete (nonconserving) nature of his/her in terms of specific positive and negative poles
logic, which changes as the concrete period (e.g., trust vs. mistrust). As described at the out-
develops. set of the chapter, I elaborated Erikson’s eight-
(d) The adolescent is capable of rededication to step developmental sequence into a 25-step
responsibility. In this regard, I refer to the Neo-Eriksonian one (being consistent with the
process as involving Re-Responsibility. parallel 25-step Neo-Piagetian sequence).
(e) Finally, the adult arrives at the level of The tables present only the negative poles in
advanced psychological maturity that can the present 25-step Neo-Eriksonian model. They
accompany the stage of collective intelli- include descriptions of the emotions that are
gence. Therefore, the adult can have the important at each step. They describe the type of
sense of Re-Responsibility become multiple dysregulation in social interaction and support
and varied, in a process that I characterize as that promotes movement to the negative side of
involving Re-Responsibilities. each polarity.
The tables help clarify the 17 steps that I
added to Erikson’s original 8-step sequence in
Neo-Eriksonian order to arrive at a 25-step model corresponding
to the 25-step Neo-Piagetian one. For example,
Model in the sensorimotor stage, I suggest that Erikson’s
trust can develop only after some degree of social
Tables 32.4, 32.5, 32.6, 32.7, and 32.8 present in interaction, as in the proposed dyadic step
depth the Neo-Eriksonian model that was hypothesized to precede the stage of trust. In the
described in Young (2011, 2012). Erikson char- perioperational stage, I suggest that the pre-
acterized each stage in his eight-step model as a schooler does not pass directly from Erikson’s

Table 32.4 Dangers in development in the reflex substages


Level Danger and opposition in substage
1. Distance acts Distance regulation to target is irregular, too forward, or rarely “near.” Without a primary
vs. No stance base, behavior is undifferentiated.
2. Nursing vs. Basic reflexive survival mechanisms are awry, e.g., in reacting to stimuli or in nursing. Given
Rootless acts an absence of physical alimentation, behavior is without orientation or stability.
3. Outcome vs. Target-related appetitive behavior is contextually inappropriate, over- or underenergized, too
Outcast acts negative (e.g., avoidance, crying), etc. Because of this foundation, behavior may promote rejection.
4. Care giving vs. The caregiver system is not activated appropriately (e.g., newborn too passive or tests
Careless giving caregivers’ limits, e.g., too much crying, colicky behavior). Caregivers bring their own
acts agenda, and this may be maladaptive (e.g., indifference, postpartum depression, abuse). The
will to live may be compromised by long term, ineffective, nonoptimal, or emotionally absent
care giving due to problems with infants, caregivers, or their match.
5. Emotional vs. Evaluations along emotion-related dimensions (e.g., whether goals being interfered with) are
Malemotional inaccurate. Component emotional reactions are problematic. In short, emotional scripts are
acts not functioning normatively (e.g., too damped, too negative). For example, infants manifest
distress in unpredictable ways, are not soothed in normal manner, are too fussy, and are never
engaged by sensorily interesting spectacles/objects. The same extremes may be evident in
other emotions as they emerge in the succeeding substages. As in prior substage [and in all
subsequent substages], caregivers may contribute to these difficulties.
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science + Business Media; with kind permission from Springer Science +
Business Media B. V. [Table 20.11, Page 476]
790 32 Further Expansions of the Present Stage Models

Table 32.5 Dangers in development in the sensorimotor substages


Level Danger and opposition in substage
6. Dyadic vs. Dysdyadic acts Social dialogue is marked by poor synchrony with partner, incorrect
reading of partner, misplaced actions, variable reactions, too demanding
bids, excessive turning off, deficient learning skill, etc. The pleasure and
joy typically inherent in a dyadic interaction with caregivers may be
replaced by much frustration, gaze aversion, and disinterest instead.
7. Trust vs. Mistrust acts A sense of mistrust in oneself and the social world takes hold, for care
giving is unreliable, intermittent, or otherwise negative (e.g., rejecting,
overintrusive smothering). Infants cannot create a normal, mutually-
regulated, hierarchical integration with the caregiver where at times infants
are dominant and at times subordinate in a reciprocal balance of play.
Emotions that emerge involve fear, sadness, crankiness, etc.
8. Sociability vs. Unsociability acts A lack of sociability pervades social intercourse with the caregiver, family,
and strangers. Insecurity in the attachment relationship solidifies in either
an anxious avoidant or anxious ambivalent-resistant (mixed) fashion.
Infants do not share with caregivers sitting as a secure base, fail to adapt to
their departure, ignore them, or are ambivalent on their return, and are not
optimally interactive or are negative with strangers. Thus, we see emotions
such as worry, dislike, aggressive displacement, and displacement escape.
9. Autonomy vs. Doubt acts A sense of autonomy is stifled, for toddlers develop pervading, overly-
dependent behavior, doubt, hesitation, inertia, or lack of self confidence.
Deliberate trial-and-error exploring becomes chaotic, trying, erroneous,
imploring (dependency), flat in affect, or with exaggerated fear. Dependent
behavior brings with it emotions such as jealousy, greed, and defiance.
10. Interdigitational vs. Mutuality in play is impossible, for young children cannot partake in
Dedigitational acts prolonged, reciprocal, peaceful exchanges, have no facility in smoothly
entering such social relations, and are either too. Overpowering/possessive
or too submissive/subjugated when participating in them. Thus, give and
take social behavior may be avoided. Children evaluate others with
contempt, not appreciation, and evaluate themselves with the same and a
sense of rejection, not pride
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science + Business Media; with kind permission from Springer Science +
Business Media B. V. [Table 20.12, Page 476]

Table 32.6 Dangers in development in the perioperational substages


Level Danger and opposition in substage
11. Superordinate vs. Disjointed, inappropriately juxtaposed oppositions in social behavior manifest. Children
Discoordinate acts seem incoherent, fragmented, and without refined social skills. Language does not fit
context, actions mismatch intentions, and emotions improperly contrast. This may be
evident (in different ways) both over long stretches and neighboring behaviors. The
normal egocentrism of children is inappropriate or compromised, for the “ego” is
dispersed or fractionated.
12. Initiative vs. Guilt Initiative is damped by (familial) conflict deriving from too intrusive impositions or
acts fantasies. This may even result in the Oedipus conflict (see Chap. 2). The nascent
superego is saturated with guilt related to repressed wishes. Adoption of the same-sex
parental identity in a nonvolatile manner is jeopardized.
13. Gender vs. Identification with the primary characteristics of the parents is undermined, for the
Problematic process may be limited to frontal negative attributes (e.g., anger, rejection, confused
gender acts signals) or dismissed, producing a frontal negativity (aggressivity, avoidance,
depression). This attitude may carry over into peer- and school-related activity (e.g.,
disobeying parental wishes; compensatory over-inclusion of negative peer models in
behavior; resistance, underachievement in schooling). Self-devaluation is seeded.
(continued)
Neo-Eriksonian 791

Table 32.6 (continued)


Level Danger and opposition in substage
14. Industry vs. The problems above are magnified, resulting in a sense of rebelliousness, inferiority, or
Inferiority acts inadequacy. Chains of fight and/or flight become linked in children’s minds,
overwhelming their ego’s image of itself. A propensity to over control may develop as a
defense mechanism, leading to exploitation, manipulation, deception, etc.
15. Role vs. Role The social roles imagined in the context of family, friends, school, and other institutions
confusion acts are limited and limiting. These roles are restricted ones, overreactions, compensations of
lack, etc., befitting the sense of rebelliousness and/or inferiority developed previously.
This emotional cauldron may produce a social (external), role-oriented individual trying
to mask internal conflicts.
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science + Business Media; with kind permission from Springer Science +
Business Media B. V. [Table 20.13, Page 477]

Table 32.7 Dangers in development in the abstract substages


Level Danger and opposition in substage
16. Conscious vs. Young adolescents can lapse into conscious self depreciation, a closure to freeing repressed
Contra- thoughts, cynical ridicule of others and their constructive efforts, and “turning off” free
conscious acts thinking altogether. One reaction to this confusion may be to conform excessively, and
adopt the role identifications perceived as preferred by parents, peers, teachers, etc.
17. Identity vs. The search for identity can be subverted, postponed, meander, lead to back alleys, etc., as
Identity Erikson described.
diffusion acts
18. Nurturing vs. Responsible adult roles cannot be envisioned. Decisions are not subjected to critical,
Misnurturing personal standards. Social relations are more undirectional or parallel than reciprocal. Work
acts and school activities are not future-directed and may be demeaned. Any nurturing is
superficial and considered superfluous.
19. Intimacy vs. This pattern continues, but more so, for multiple adult roles may be foisted on the
Isolation acts individual by society. Abandonment of any such roles undertaken, or other self- and
other-destructive behavior, becomes possible, yielding sentiments of loneliness, isolation,
etc. Instead of a relativist, unique, yet mutual self, there is an absolute, desolate one.
20. Universal vs. Rather than encouraging others’ development, the self implodes in self-indulgent acts,
Self-singular acts or worse.
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science + Business Media; with kind permission from Springer Science +
Business Media B. V. [Table 20.14, Page 478]

Table 32.8 Dangers in development in the collective intelligence substages


Level Danger and opposition in substage
21. Meta-collecting vs. Disillusionment with society, with groups, and with constructive activity can pervade
Disillusionment acts the individual, for the notion of profiting from collective symbiosis is not entertained.
22. Generativity vs. Generative role models with family, at work, and in the community are sacrificed for
Self-absorption acts self-absorption, a sense of emptiness, and stagnation.
23. Catalytic vs. Midlife Midlife crisis develops; for instead of emerging as a force in whatever collective is of
crisis acts concern, the adult pays the price for having skirted the collective. The confusions and
changes engendered are unconscious attempts to return to prior levels through
misapplied catalytic discoveries, shifts, inversions, etc., in thought.
24. Ego integrity vs. Disappointment with the meaningless felt in life sets in.
Despair acts
25. Cathartic vs. The elderly unwisely shut out spiritual experiences, denying any fellowship with
Abandonment acts humanity, the unknown, and the infinity.
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science + Business Media; with kind permission from Springer Science +
Business Media B. V. [Table 20.15, Page 479]
792 32 Further Expansions of the Present Stage Models

initiative to industry, but first develops into an person passes through each of the original eight
intermediary stage of gender acts. In the abstract Eriksonian stages. Dunkel and Sefcek (2009)
stage, I propose that Erikson’s famous stage of argued that each of the slow and fast lifestyles
identity should be preceded by a stage involving have developmental consequences throughout
the emergence of consciousness. In the collective the lifespan. Their pilot research supported the
stage, Eriksonian generativity has been truncated model that the negative poles of the oppositions
to allow for a midlife stage, which involves in each original Eriksonian stage are associated
midlife crisis when it is negative. with fast lifestyles, in particular. Del Giudice
(2014) proposed a similar model of psychopa-
thology, but without the Eriksonian component.
Elaboration Rather, he focused on which disorders are associ-
ated with slow and fast strategies.
Dunkel and Sefcek (2009) related life history Aside from its possible application to a more
theory to Eriksonian lifespan development (see detailed elaboration of steps in fast and slow
Fig. 32.1). Dunkel and Sefcek developed a model life history strategies, the present 25-step Neo-
of developmental psychopathology involving Eriksonian model of development affords a more
fast and slow life history strategies, and the nuanced and complete view of developmental psy-
authors showed how the strategies change as the chopathology, in general. From a Neo-Eriksonian

Despair vs. Integrity

Stagnation vs. Generativity

Isolation vs. Intimacy

Role confusion vs. Identity formation

Inferiority vs. Industry

Guilt vs. Initiative

Shame vs. Autonomy

Mistrust vs. Trust

Faster Slower

Fig. 32.1 Crises/challenges in Eriksonian life span stages behavior; quantity reproductive strategy; short-term pair
affected by faster (resource-challenged) and slower life bonds; and little parental investment. Slower trajectory
history developmental trajectories. Faster life history tra- has opposite characteristics. Adapted from Dunkel and
jectory includes high environmental stress and/or father Sefcek (2009)
absence; fast development/early maturation; early sexual
Neo-Maslovian Model 793

point of view, it allows for specification of the Neo-Maslovian Model


specific problems, disturbances, and psychopa-
thologies that might arise at each developmental Introduction
stage over the lifespan. I am not suggesting that the
model permits determination of possible psychiat- In Young (2011), not only did I present a revised
ric diagnostic categories at each developmental Neo-Eriksonian model but also a revised one for
phase. Instead, it appears that the model can be Maslow’s model based on the revised Neo-
used to create a rich description of the develop- Eriksonian one. Maslow’s model is a classic,
mental difficulties and dysfunctionalities that and is the most downloaded work related to psy-
could arise at each developmental stage. chology, so it still has much contemporary cur-
rency. In revising Maslow’s model in the image
of my own, I followed another recent effort that
Yoking I considered needed reworking itself.
Schaller, Neuberg, Griskevicius, and Kenrick
The present model includes the concept of yok- (2010) presented a revised version of Maslow’s
ing across cognitive stages and substages, which model based on evolutionary theory. Maslow’s
is quite applicable to its parallel socioaffective (1943, 1970) classic model of hierarchy of needs
series. Cognitively, in Young (2011), I had consists of five levels. They involve: (a) immedi-
described how, even as the adult functions in the ate physiological needs; (b) safety; (c) love
postformal collective intelligence stage in prob- (affection, belongingness); (d) esteem (respect);
lem solving, when the context determines it, the and (e) self-actualization (see Fig. 32.2). Maslow
person can integrate lower-level stages with considered the needs as having a sequence of pri-
higher-order ones in the problem solving pro- ority, depending on the context confronted by the
cesses. Similarly, at the socioaffective level, we individual. Also, for Maslow, they have develop-
might function from a combined framework of mental priority, in that as people mature, they
pertinent or persistent Neo-Eriksonian (sub) move from lower to higher levels in the hierar-
stages. It is common in the psychodynamic tradi- chy. In this sense, self-actualization represents
tion to refer to fixations, regressions, etc., in the highest level of psychological maturity.
active stage functioning in development. In my It stands at the apex of his pyramidal model.
model, I would underscore yoking over different Working from evolutionary theory, Schaller
(sub)stages in these regards. Therefore, in terms et al. (2010) developed a seven-level revised model
of the present model, the clinicians might be able of Maslow’s classic five-level one. In this regard,
to specify that one particular stage seems to mark Kenrick, Griskevicius, Neuberg, and Schaller
current psychiatric function, it is quite a few steps (2010) questioned the placement of self-actualiza-
behind what is expected, it is yoked to other steps tion at the top of the hierarchy. Also, they queried
both before and after it in the normative sequence, the validity of placing sexual needs at the bottom of
and so on. the hierarchy. Further, they criticized using the label
of love in the middle of the hierarchy.
However, their revised model might be too
Comment biologically-based in evolutionary theory.
Moreover, there is no valid reason to consider
To conclude, as has been evident throughout my self-actualization at a lower level than any other
work, we owe much to Piaget, in that he provided concept for the adult not to consider physiologi-
a framework that I could elaborate into a 25-step cal needs as anything but the lowest level of the
developmental progression. Moreover, it permit- hierarchy. However, the original model can be
ted me to expand it to a parallel Neo-Eriksonian reworked to accommodate to the concerns of
developmental sequence. Kenrick et al. (2010), which is the approach that
794 32 Further Expansions of the Present Stage Models

Self- Relatedness-
Definitional Self
Actualizing Actualizing
Generativity Generativity

Self-Definitional Relatedness-Self
Identity Self-Esteem Identity Self-Esteem

Self-Definitional Relatedness-Self
Affiliative Initiative Affiliative Initiative

Self-Definitional Relatedness-Self
Safety/ Trust Safety/ Trust

Self-Definitional Relatedness-Self
Physiological Needs/ Survival Physiological Needs/ Reproduction

Fig. 32.2 Neo-Maslovian hierarchy of self-definitional New York: Springer Science + Business Media; with kind
and relatedness self needs. Adopted with permission of permission from Springer Science + Business Media B. V.
Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2011). [Figure 19.3, Page 452]
Development and causality: Neo-Piagetian perspectives.

I took. Before explaining how I modified Fitting with Blatt (2008), as a starting point in
Maslow’s model in light of Kenrick et al.’s con- my revision of Maslow’s model of five levels in a
cerns, I describe my approach to the revision of hierarchy of needs, I developed a model that
Maslow, because the accommodations made in includes for each of the levels a self-other dis-
my work based on Kenrick et al. fit that revision. tinction. The figure that I developed to represent
the model adds to the standard five-level hierar-
chy, as created by Maslow, a perpendicular inter-
Model section that divides the triangle in half, one for
more direct personal concerns and one for con-
Roots I have developed a revised model of cerns more about the other. To remind, this inno-
Maslow’s hierarchy of needs that considers sev- vation in the modeling process fits the work of
eral other theories. In this regard, I included: (a) Blatt (2008), who described that there are two
the Eriksonian perspective; (b) Blatt’s (2008) basic self- and other-related experiences—self-
work on the polarities in experience of self- definition and relatedness.
definition and relatedness, so that the model is About the inclusion of the model of Erikson in
not just about the self (e.g., as in self-actualization) the revised model, I showed how his description
but also about the role of the other, and even of the stages in development map onto the upper
larger collective issues in society; and (c) as per four levels of Maslow’s hierarchy of needs, and
Kenrick et al. (2010), the work of Darwinian on not just the top level of self-actualization. In par-
evolutionary processes, but in an approach that ticular, I have proposed that, for each of the upper
includes cultural perspectives (see Fig. 32.2). four levels of Maslow’s hierarchy, two of Erikson’s
Neo-Maslovian Model 795

original eight stages fit the levels involved. as survival-related, and also others related to
Therefore, for example, for the upper level of sexual activity as reproductive-related. Note
Maslow’s model involving self-actualization, not that this does not imply that sexual activity is
only have I de-emphasized the self component of active in the neonatal period; only that its
the term but also I believe that this level could precursors relate to that level and, as the per-
include the stage in development after the self- son develops and that level grows to include
actualizing one, or that of ego integrity. actual sexual activity, it fits the model in the
In terms of Maslow’s middle level of love, way indicated.
I used Kenrick et al.’s (2010) elaborated term for (b) The level of safety in Maslow’s model of
it (affiliation). However, I showed how Maslow’s needs and motivations has been expanded to
use of the example of affection in the love cate- include the psychological security engen-
gory fits Blatt’s (2008) concept of self-definition. dered by positive attachment experiences.
Also, I showed how Maslow’s example of The latter develops in a majority of infants,
belongingness in love fits Blatt’s (2008) concept but depends on the quality of care received.
of relatedness. Attachment processes are comparable to the
Finally, in terms of Darwinian evolutionary ones concerning the development of trust in
underpinnings in the model, I left Maslow’s Eriksonian modeling, and both develop in
placement of sex as a basic biological need that the first year.
should go at the bottom of the hierarchy. However, (c) In the next level, Maslow’s concept of love as
I separated it from hunger and related motiva- affection and belongingness has been both
tions by placing the latter under self-definitional split and expanded. On the one hand, affec-
needs and the former under relatedness needs. tion has been placed with the self-definitional
component of the model and belongingness
Branches Ultimately, the revisions in my Neo- with the one of relatedness. On the other hand,
Maslovian model allow for a correspondence in the model addresses affiliation rather than
the five levels of the model and the five stages of love, per se, and it includes education and
the present Neo-Piagetian model. The following instruction as part of what affiliation is about.
explains this Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Maslovian par- (d) For Maslow, esteem and respect constitute
allel in development. the next motivational need in the hierarchy. I
have elaborated the concept to include self-
(a) The lower biological levels involve Maslow’s definitional and relatedness components.
immediate physiological needs and safety (e) For the penultimate level of self-actualization
needs. However, they have been expanded to in Maslow’s model, Kenrick et al. (2010)
include self-related components other-related modified it so that it is replaced by family
ones, and they include Darwinian processes and related needs. However, I have already
in their description. In this regard, in the explained how I handled Kenrick et al.’s
present model, I separate sex from other insistence that the ultimate Maslovian needs
basic biological needs by placing it in the concern Darwinian survival and reproductive
component of the model about relatedness. needs. Moreover, family relates to Erikson’s
In addition, this allows me to refer to other concept of generativity in the adult period. In
basic biological processes, such as nursing, generativity, the individual focuses not just
as part of the relatedness portion of the on family but also on work, community, and
model. Once this type of distinction was the wider collective. Adults seek meaning in
made, I could relate both types of survival their lives and their context, and they try to
needs to Darwinian processes. Specifically, obtain for their children optimal educational
in terms of the concept of natural selection and instructional experiences. In this regard,
for purposes of survival and reproduction, adults even form formal educational institu-
one would categorize needs such as nursing tions and other instructional opportunities,
796 32 Further Expansions of the Present Stage Models

with parents contributing either directly or superego; and personal/self; ego), but in a way
indirectly, thereby helping not only their much less refined than is the present case.
children but also other children. Overall, by In the coordination phase of developmental
including generativity in the penultimate psychology, before WWII in the last century, the
level of Maslow’s model that already includes major theories of behaviorism, ethology, and
self-actualization, and by adding to that level Piaget’s stage model emerged. These models
a distinction between self and other, my revi- allowed for the elaboration of the major influ-
sion of the model to include family on the ences that Freud had presented in his model.
relatedness part of the model in this penulti- In the next stage, after WWII, the discipline
mate stage makes sense. witnessed the creation of attachment theory,
social learning theory, and Erikson’s theory. In
addition, Neo-Piagetians differentiated the stages
Development in Piaget’s theory.
Outside of Development In addition to those theories, new models devel-
oped. They concerned the information-processing
Introduction model, the sociocultural model of Vygotsky, sys-
tems theory, and the ecological model.
In Young (2011), I applied the five-step Neo- The modeling process continues in develop-
Piagetian stage model outside of human develop- mental psychology. More recent models in the
ment. This could happen because it allows for a field include the developmental biopsychosocial
modeling process that could be used generically model, diathesis-stress models of developmental
to describe stages in development in nonliving psychopathology, and interdisciplinary models,
systems. For example, its stages have been rede- e.g., behavior genetics.
scribed in terms of the sequence of the labels for The table illustrates clearly how the various
its substages of coordination, hierarchization, theories that have evolved in developmental psy-
systematization, multiplication, and integration. chology fit the present model of change. Even
The latter terms can be used to describe changes though we are not dealing with a living system,
in nonliving systems, where applicable. the system involved still matches the model.
Given these considerations, I applied the pres-
ent model to two sequences in the growth of sci-
ence. On the one hand, the model was used to Evolution
structure the development of developmental psy-
chology itself (see Table 32.9). On the other hand, As for how evolution has evolved according to
it applies to the evolution of Darwin’s theorizing. the steps of the present model, consider the fol-
lowing, in which I present a sequence of steps as
possible ones in the growth of Darwinian thought.
Psychology Once more, the steps relate to the present model
of coordination, hierarchization, systematization,
The table indicates that the various theories in multiplication, and integration.
developmental psychology, and the periods in (a) First, the concept of natural selection could be
which they evolved. Moreover, the table relates construed as the first step of five in the devel-
these theories to the present model of change opment toward a complex theory of evolution.
of coordination, hierarchization, systematization, Specifically, the construction of the concept of
multiplication, and integration. In this regard, the natural selection by Darwin involved coordi-
Freudian psychodynamic model stands as a preco- nating the major components of the concept
ordination one. It elucidated the major influences into a coherent theory (e.g., concerning natu-
on development (the biological; id; environmental; ral variation, competition, etc.).
Development Outside of Development 797

Table 32.9 Growth of scientific thought in developmental psychology


Stages Explanation
Precoordination The Freudian psychodynamic model represents a pre-coordination phase. The major elements
involved as influences on the developing human were first elucidated together by Freud (the
biological; id; environmental; superego; and personal/self; ego). This prepared the way for their
separation in individual theories that deal with them.
Coordination The first genuine phase in the evolution of developmental psychology took place in the period
before WWII in the last century. Three major theories emerged in this period—behaviorism,
ethology, and Piaget’s stage model. Behaviorism cast its stone against the inherent mentalism of
the Freudian model, arguing that behavior can be understood uniquely through the
environmental and learning contingencies impinging on and reinforcing the child, for example,
through classical conditioning. It focused on the biological bases of behavior by developing
more refined models related to imprinting and instincts. He focused on the developing child’s
contribution to her or his own behavior, through natural activity, active construction of cognitive
schemas, and so forth. Thus, the major influences that Freud had presented in his model on the
developing person were each elaborated in more refined models, but they focused especially on
one or the other of the influences, without attempting more integrative models where the
influences were on more of an equal footing.
Hierarchization Later behavioral models added the learning mechanism of operant conditioning. Instead of
classical conditioning, which elaborated by association the stimuli that could instigate
responses, operant conditioning elaborated the responses that could be elicited by stimuli
through the reinforcement histories to which emitted behavior could be subjected. Ethology
added explanations of behavior that emphasized fixed action patterns and innate releasing
mechanisms. Piagetians explored the role of environmental effects through décalages, training
studies, and simplified tasks. Freudian models explored further the role of the nonlibidinal
sources in development (Jung, Adler) and examined further the ego in development.
Systematization In the next stage in the development of the discipline of developmental psychology, the
discipline found its voice and developed models unique to it. The school of ethology influenced
the development of attachment theory, in which biological mechanisms related to seeking and
maintaining proximity and contact were considered to interact with the quality of care giving
received, leading to the development already in the first year of life of either secure or insecure
attachments. Social learning theory added observational learning to the behavioral mechanisms
in learning, and introduced motivation and attentional mechanisms in learning, as well. Erikson
differentiated Freudian theory in several ways that gave more of a role to the person as he or she
developed. His innovations included rendering the stages involved more psychosocial than
psychosexual in origin. Neo-Piagetians differentiated the stages in Piaget’s theory, adding a
postformal period, in particular, and positing cyclic recursions in substages.
Multiplication In addition to those theories that differentiated from the original ones that had developed in the
field at the outset, new paradigms in the field of developmental psychology emerged in the
1970s and 1980s. In the information-processing model of development, the computer provides
the analogy and guide to how development is conceived. The socio-cultural model built on the
work of Vygotsky, whose ideas had been isolated from the West, delaying its impact. He
published in the 1930s, but became prominent in the West well after WWII. In systems theory,
families are considered as wholes, and the whole system of the family and its members is
considered greater than the sum of its parts. In the ecological model, the child is conceived of as
an organism with initial characteristics that interact with an environment that can be
differentiated into multiple components.
Integration Subsequent models in the field of developmental psychology have been trying to differentiate
further and integrate these diverse theories that had developed in prior stages of the discipline
(e.g., the developmental biopsychosocial model, diathesis-stress models of developmental
psychopathology, current systems models). Moreover, developmental psychology is becoming
increasingly interdisciplinary, borrowing from and integrating both biological and cultural
scholarship (e.g., behavior genetics, cultural and minority studies, respectively). Furthermore, a
common Piagetian–Eriksonian stage framework is being constructed [and that has been the goal
of the present work].
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science + Business Media; with kind permission from Springer Science +
Business Media B. V. [Excerpt, Pages 718–724]
798 32 Further Expansions of the Present Stage Models

(b) Darwin’s two innovations after he had devel- the evolution of the discipline and that also inte-
oped the concept of natural selection (sexual grate them and their continuing innovations in a
selection; human evolution) could be taken comprehensive framework, it can be conjectured
to reflect expansion of his base idea into a that the field of developmental psychology is just
hierarchical structure of ideas, with the the- beginning the integrative phase of its growth.
ory of evolution at the apex, as per the pres-
ent model. That is, as Darwin expanded the
concept of natural selection, the new models Revising Steps
were not equivalent in emphasis and scope to
natural selection, but devolved from it as part Introduction
of his movement toward a more encompass-
ing model. In the next section of the chapter, I illustrate how
(c) Darwin never arrived at a fully integrated critical concepts that have been discussed in the
theory of evolution, leaving the task to biolo- present work can be extended by explaining how
gists who followed. It could be argued that the they might develop in terms of the present model.
“modern synthesis” that developed in the last These areas include the ones of dual process
century (it incorporated genetics) constituted thinking, free will, and ethical thought.
the first step in that direction. In terms of the
present model, that synthesis could be taken
to reflect the substage of systematization. Dual Process Revised
(d) In terms of the present model, the recent
development of the “extended synthesis” Table 32.10 presents a stage model of the devel-
could reflect the multiplication phase in the opment of intuitive and logical thought based on
evolution of evolution. Evolution now my Neo-Piagetian stage model (Young, 2011).
involves epigenetics, evo-devo, gene-cul- Using this five-stage Neo-Piagetian model, and
tural co-evolution, multilevel selection, and focusing on the distinction between intuitive (pre-
so on. operational) and logical thought (rational thought,
(e) In the integrative step of elaborating concrete operational thought onward), I have
Darwin’s work, new ideas and discoveries reworked the distinction between Kahneman’s
keep moving us forward. However, as yet, (2011) and Stanovich, West, and Toplak (2011)
we have not developed a fully integrated Type I/System I thought and Type II/System II
model of evolution. thought in terms of the stages in development
indicated. This approach has led to the construct
that the more advanced rational, logical thought
Comment compared to intuitive thought in the two type/sys-
tem modes consists of three qualitatively differ-
I conclude that the tour of past and contemporary ent and successively more advanced skill sets.
theories in the area of developmental psychology These latter three rational thought systems/types
and Darwinian thought in terms of the present are considered: (a) basic rational; (b) advanced
model had been illuminating. Also, the process rational; and (c) supra-rational skills and their
that was followed points to the validity of the pres- underlying Neo-Piagetian stage acquisitions.
ent model, given the parallel it has with the steps Also, the first-developing intuitive thought
in the evolution of the discipline of developmental appears to consist of two successive acquisi-
psychology and of Darwinian thought. However, tions—more reflexive and more sensorimotor.
until there are overarching models in the disci- Note that according to the present concept of yok-
pline of developmental psychology that both ing, the dual process model can have both aspects
respect the theories that have been fundamental in activated and used simultaneously.
Revising Steps 799

Table 32.10 Multiple processing intuitive and reasoning In this regard, according to the steps described
systems in thought and their development
in the table, it could be that an emerging belief in
Neo-Piagetian stage Thought system/type free will in the abstract coordination stage
Reflexive 0 Reflexive becomes subservient, submissive, or controlled
Sensorimotor 1 Pre-intuitive by its opposite belief of a lack of free will, lead-
Perioperational 2 Representational ing to its systematic absence. Then, a belief in an
– Preoperational 2a—Intuitive
absence of free will begins a process of
– Concrete operational 2b—Rational
propagation throughout the developing thought
Abstract 3 Advanced rational
of the person, culminating in a pervasive belief or
Collective 4 Supra-rational
theory that it can never exist. Or, there might be
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business
Media. Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feigning, and
isolated free will beliefs that develop for particu-
response bias in psychiatric/psychological injury: lar domains or issues in the person, but ones that
Implications for Practice and court. Dordrecht, are never dominant. Next, any effort to create
Netherlands: Springer Science + Business Media; with systemic beliefs on the topic fails—to the con-
kind permission from Springer Science + Business Media
B. V. [Table 23.9, Page 602]
trary, the belief of the absence of free will sys-
Note. The table shows the equivalent of the steps in tematically takes hold. Then, the latter absence of
Young’s (2011) Neo-Piagetian model and the concepts of belief starts spreading in the general belief sys-
thinking types in the model of dual processing, e.g., tem, or at the level of it multiplication in the sys-
Stanovich et al.’s (2011) Type I or System I thinking com-
pared to Type II/System II; or Kahneman’s (2011) Intuitive
tem involved. Finally, the upshot is that there
vs. Rational thought. Similarly, more and less refined could be a total, full-scale lack in development of
thought types related to pre-operational, intuitive and con- values related to free will, such as in superordi-
crete/formal (abstract) operational thought are possible nate, morals, altruistic intentions.
according to Piaget (e.g., Barrouillet, 2011). However,
Piagetians note that having the potential to think abstractly
does not mean it happens, as would any one else.
Moreover, even when in the abstract stage, individuals Ethical Thought Revised
might think at other, less advanced levels. I refer to this as
yoking, and explain that the concept multiple intelligences
refers to the co-presence of these different Neo-Piagetian
In Table 32.12, I develop a more general, inclu-
modes of thinking, with the more advanced one present sive, and qualified golden rule by following the
not necessarily being the central one yoked to. In short, steps of the present Neo-Piagetian model within
thinking rationally and abstractly is a complex affair, the collective intelligence, or superordinate
influencing greatly the capacity to choose freely, see or
create options, plan, etc. The more we gravitate to the
abstract thought. Generally, ethics evolves in the
abstract level compared to the intuitive level, the more we sequence of considering cases, rules, codes, prin-
have a sense of freedom, choose appropriately, and feel ciples, and theories (see Young, 2014). This
free. However, factors such as developmental impacts, sequence matches the steps in the present model
stress, illness, and injury could complicate the process
in the following way, beginning with the first one
of coordination and proceeding through to the
fifth one integration.
Free Will Revised
(a) Coordination In the present model at the
To illustrate the applicability of my stage model level of collective intelligence, abstract thought
to the psychotherapeutic context, Table 32.11 grows through an initial coordination of abstract
shows how growth in the belief of free will might ideas. For the present case, a conundrum arises in
take place according to the steps of Young’s considering which is primary—the classic golden
(2011) stage model. Psychotherapists should be rule (“do unto others as you would have them do
attuned to this growth model and, also, how unto you”) or the corollary inverse one also used
belief in free will can be lost or degenerate, e.g., (“do not do unto others as you would not have
due to pain, injury, or illness. them do unto you”). Through the cognitive
800 32 Further Expansions of the Present Stage Models

Table 32.11 Development (and loss) of a belief in having a sense of free will
Stage Level Description
Abstract Coordination The abstract idea that one could have a sense of control and
(Piagetian formal stage) determine one’s options, choosing the one best for us in
context, emerges. It is juxtaposed to the opposite notion of a
lack of control/free will/ability to choose freely, etc.
Hierarchization The cognitive dissonance, compare/contrast process/
indecisions, etc., created by the juxtaposition of concepts of
free will in the prior level begins to resolve, in that the
concept of free will becomes the primary belief to which its
deterministic opposite becomes subordinated
Systematization The evolving concept of free will elaborates, as contingencies
and contexts are considered and incorporated into a more
systemic concept. The adolescent entertains a strong belief in
free will, although its lack might also hold sway, depending
on circumstances, manipulation, ego depletion, resource
depletion, cognitive load, etc.
Multiplication Once systematized, the belief in free will entrenches beyond
its initial locus of application (e.g., I can go out with my
friends when I want and do what I want), into other areas,
perhaps related to parental input (e.g., Sure you can go out,
but demonstrate you deserve it, do all your course work first,
be responsible and phone in, etc.)
Integration The belief in free will becomes a generalized concept that
characterizes abstract thought processes and is applied
uniformly even if hesitantly to new contingencies and
contexts. It facilitates a forward, proactive approach to
planning, problem solving, etc.
Collective intelligence Coordination The belief in free will develops into a superordinate abstract
(Neo-Piagetian structure, beginning integration with other developing
postformal stage) abstract structures, such as those related to values and morals.
That is, the adult develops a higher-order conception of free
will that includes the ability to create one’s own value and
moral system, one’s life path, etc. It is more than a belief that
one can have free will in a particular contingency/context but
that one can create ways of living imbued throughout with
free will even in the most complex choices that one has to
make and the most complex situations that one has to
confront. This belief is juxtaposed with times when it is not
yet apparent, creating conflict, dissonance, etc.
Hierarchization The emerging superordinate belief in free will exhibits a
dominant–subordinate relationship, with the concept evident
about free will that is in place primary over when it is not
evident
Systematization As contingencies and contexts are considered, the
superordinate free will belief refines into a coherent structure
Multiplication Once fully matured, the concept spreads out throughout the
cognitive architecture of the person, for example,
impregnating it with its accompanying higher-order values
and morals
Integration The superordinate free will belief ends up as an integrated
whole that governs cognitive and affective life in its entire
vicissitudes. The process is a never-ending struggle to keep it
prominent and vigilant
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feigning, and response
bias in psychiatric/psychological injury: Implications for Practice and court. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer Science
+ Business Media; with kind permission from Springer Science + Business Media B. V. [Table 24.6, Page 622]
Revising Steps 801

Table 32.12 Golden rule: growth of ethical thought and practice


Level Description
Coordination (Cases) Do unto others as you would have them do unto you
Do not do unto others as you would not have them do unto you
Or,
Strive to do good, benefit, help, and safeguard (Beneficence)
Do no harm (Nonmaleficence)
Hierarchization (Rules) Consider positive ethics and, therefore, place the do-strive axis as primary relative
to the do-not axis
Systematization (Codes) Consider that do/striving is an act rather than a whole behavior having thought and
feeling. Ethics concerns meeting the other in active, lived participation by the whole
person with the whole. This could be called living in a mode of being rather than
only living in a mode of doing/acting
Consider that being ethical and living wholly in the moment with the other should
not expressly involve expectation of return from the other for any good, benefit,
safeguarding, or helpful act, although inevitably people behaving ethically might
bring it full circle with ample return
Multiplication (Principles) Consider that the golden rule should be clearly inclusive of others of different ages,
conditions (e.g., psychiatric, disability), groups (e.g., gender, race, minority, culture)
The golden rule should reflect the individual and group difference of the person
living it
The person should live it according to not only personal experience but also
education, training, and practice, such as in university study or in the helping
professions. Knowledge and its application stems from both subjective and
objective learning
The golden rule could be direct but also indirect (e.g., as a role model; indeed, being
a good role model might have the most inspirational influence)
When lived and applied, the golden rule should act to promote the same good,
beneficial, safeguarding, and helpful attitude in the receiving other person(s)
The golden rule should work best when it emanates from a helpful, peaceful, and
stimulating attitude or light that is projected and felt
The golden rule concerns all others and, moreover, the planet as a whole, as well as
beyond
There is one proviso: living the golden rule does not mean abrogating one’s
responsibility to do no harm to one’s self/family, etc. That is, applying the golden rule
should not be done blindly or naively in a way that the person is taken advantage of
Integration (Theories) Consider that the optimal golden rule should be dynamically open and responsive to
changes and growth in the person, other peoples, times and culture, and ethical
understanding and models
We should continuously step back reflectively to examine our ethical and moral
assumptions and how to live them well
Therefore, the integrative golden rule that I am proposing is the following: Be unto
others, no matter their age and condition, at the highest level of good and morality
as reflects your positive lived participation and positive experience in the world, as
well as your academic and personal studies and exploration, while acknowledging
that there are personal, familial, cultural, and other group differences, as well as
changes and growth over time in people and their daily living and thinking; and,
aside from being a superior role model of such for the other, encourage the same
superior attitude in the other and in all others, all this being done without expecting
anything for yourself nor behaving in any way that is aimed at bringing advantage
to yourself (but in a way that checks for being taken advantage of); that is, an
appropriate golden rule to guide ways of daily living is to be, to do, and to behave in
a way that maximizes a peaceful, stimulating, and helpful attitude in yourself and
shown to others, which will inevitably bear positive fruit for each and every one of
us and also for the planet and beyond, by the positive light and sense of helpfulness
and help that it shows and seeds
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feigning, and response
bias in psychiatric/psychological injury: Implications for Practice and court. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer Science
+ Business Media; with kind permission from Springer Science + Business Media B. V. [Table 24.5, Page 619]
Note. The levels refer to the substages in Young’s (2011) model
802 32 Further Expansions of the Present Stage Models

dissonance created in comparing and contrasting learning; and (c) they should be modeled appropri-
the two dicta, especially in dilemmas found in ately, thereby better facilitating the same attitude in
actual cases that are confronted, the growth of a the receiving party or parties. As moral/ethical sys-
more refined, integrated golden rule can take tems expand and spread into different areas of
place. There is a similar opposition in the ethics moral thought, their reach extends in a multiplica-
of mental health. It has been difficult to decide tive process.
which is primary—the principle of beneficence
(“strive to do good, benefit, help, and safeguard”) (e) Integration The golden rule or “theory” that
or nonmaleficence (“do no harm”). develops will not only consider these factors but
also will be open to dynamic change as the per-
(b) Hierarchization In order to clarify the pri- son or institutions/organizations/peoples living it
macy question and elaborate further the golden (in active, shared participation) continuously
rule, it can help to examine positive ethics, or reflect on the models involved and how they were
being proactive and constructive ethically. In this derived and can still grow, thereby leading to a
regard, the positive side of the opposition involv- broad, integrative, changing meta-model. It
ing “do unto/do good” compared to “do not do should be noted that the penultimate golden rule
unto/do not harm” should predominate, with the that one constructs in this regard could serve the
negative aspect subsumed under it in a more inclu- general meta-reflective process in the construc-
sive rule. This sets up a hierarchical relationship tion of personal and professional broad models of
preparatory to further development of the rule. therapy and of ethics.

(c) Systematization For creating a more system- The next table (Table 32.13) illustrates that the
wide or codified understanding and application of sequence in the development of ethical thought in
the paired golden rules, with one predominant and the superordinate collective intelligence stage is
positive, and the one phrased negatively but sec- preceded by a single-order abstract sequence of
ondary considered and as its inverse (but with steps at the preceding stage of formal thought. In
both considering all relevant contingencies and addition, it suggests that the development of cog-
contexts), one needs to consider various ethical nition about psychotherapy can follow the same
qualifiers that serve to both differentiate and gen- single-order abstract formulation through each of
eralize the golden rule, rendering it more inclu- the five substages involved.
sive and nuanced. The qualifiers that I consider (a) Specifically, particular cases involving helping
important in this regard relate to the following: (a) or altruistic motives, in general, might provoke
the act of doing is insufficient as ethical behavior. dilemmas that challenge existing concepts and
It should reflect a whole-being perspective; (b) procedure in ways of dealing with people’s
doing/being in order to receive favor, in turn, is problems, difficulties, and issues. The dilemma
less altruistic than genuine and full giving without could be (a) a personal one in the case of a
the expectation of return; and (c) that being said, non-professional or (b) a professional one in
if all the people involved in behaving by, and the case of a practitioner or student (e.g., in
receiving the benefits of, the golden rule abide by placement, in supervision). In this coordina-
its moral suasion, reciprocity is inevitable. tion substage, for the professional or student,
the dilemma should reflect conflict that is pres-
(d) Multiplication As for developing higher-order ent in past psychotherapeutic modes and in
ethical and behavioral moral pathways and guiding present ones, as well as movement toward
models or theories based on principles: (a) they their coordination or juxtaposition in thought
should allow for inclusive doing and being, or giv- (therapeutic coordination).
ing of the self; (b) they should integrate subjective, (b) Then in a hierarchization step, a newer model
experiential learning and objective educational should begin to develop, which at first
(reading/academic and, if applicable, professional) involves developing a clear hierarchical
Revising Steps 803

Table 32.13 Stages in the development of broad personal and professional ethical perspectives and broad helping
motives and professional therapy perspectives
Stage Substage Ethical perspective Mental health perspective
Collective Integration Superordinate Ethical Superordinate Therapeutic Theories/
intelligence Theories/Meta-Ethics Orientations
(Neo-Piagetian Multiplication Superordinate Ethical Superordinate Therapeutic Principles
postformal stage) Principles
Systematization Superordinate Ethical Codes Superordinate Therapeutic Guidelines/Codes
Hierarchization Superordinate Ethical Rules Superordinate Therapeutic Rules/
Techniques/Procedures
Coordination Particular Superordinate Particular Superordinate Therapeutic Cases
Ethical Cases (Dilemmas) (Dilemmas)
Abstract Integration Ethical Theory Therapeutic Theory/Orientation
(Piagetian formal Multiplication Ethical Principle Therapeutic Principle
stage) Systematization Ethical Code Therapeutic Guideline/Code
Hierarchization Ethical Rule Therapeutic Rule/Technique/Procedure
Coordination Particular Ethical Particular Therapeutic Case (Dilemma)
Case (Dilemma)
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feigning, and response
bias in psychiatric/psychological injury: Implications for Practice and court. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer Science
+ Business Media; with kind permission from Springer Science + Business Media B. V. [Table 24.3, Page 615]

structure to which the past model is sub- meta-reflective perspective, in a therapeutic


sumed under the developing one. This is meta-theoretical approach, for example, render-
equivalent to forming a therapeutic rule. ing it open to further dynamical change. In this
(c) In systematization, a loose collection of rules way, ethical thought potentially is in constant
should develop, leading to creation of an examination and advance.
organized structure. As the hierarchization In the next cycle, the therapeutic model devel-
solidifies into a rule, or new system, with oped in the prior stage transforms at a superordi-
other contingencies and contexts incorpo- nate level to include second-order abstract
rated to make it tighter yet flexible, a struc- structures and processes.
tured therapeutic system or guideline should (a) Multiple dilemmas in different domains/
develop that, for present purposes, could be modules are coordinated simultaneously, in a
considered a therapeutic “code.” process of coordination.
(d) Therapeutic systems, once formed, extend (b) This leads to the step of hierarchizing super-
into therapeutic practice, creating a loose col- ordinate therapeutic rules.
lection of them involving different domains (c) The rules develop into systemic structured
and therapeutic modules. This fits the step of guidelines or “codes” (e.g., personal, practi-
multiplication in the present model, in which tioner or professional, organizational ones).
an underlying principle seems evident. (d) From the dispersion of codes, therapeutic
(e) As a therapeutic system is applied to multi- principles are being distilled.
ple areas, expanding its use and utility, the (e) As they coalesce into superordinate thera-
therapeutic system should grow toward peutic theories, the principles gain broad
therapeutic theory. A therapeutic theory application and flexibility.
achieves an integrated, generalized yet There is one more area to which I have applied
individualized model of therapeutic knowl- my step model that I would like to present in this
edge, theory, and practice that is dynami- chapter. It concerns how controversies initiate
cally flexible. and evolve. This section of the chapter has an
At each step in the transformative process, applied component, related to therapy, just as the
once formed, the step is examined from a present one on ethics has had.
804 32 Further Expansions of the Present Stage Models

Controversy and even illogical, irrational way, with


absence of the constructive investigation and
Next, in Table 32.14, I indicate how Young’s conceptualization required to deal with it.
(2011) stage model can apply to controversies (d) In the fourth step of multiplication, the con-
and related oppositions. I show the transforma- troversy that has tilted inappropriately to one
tive effect that controversy can have in an area of side might spread to other aspects of thought
thought, and, conversely, how it can become in the area involved, further damping appro-
entrenched, perhaps to the detriment to the area priate investigation and conceptualization.
of thought. (e) Finally, in integration, the marked, negative
Moreover, the table applies to the internal discord in the area becomes permanent to the
“controversies” that patients undergoing psy- point that one can refer to the “divide” in the
chotherapy might express as they react to cogni- area. To conclude, the application of the
tive dissonance (and how that can be promoted present model to the area of controversy
to further their progress, e.g., the belief “I can’t indicates its applicability to areas other than
get better” juxtaposed with the notion the per- development.
son can improve). In addition, it applies to con-
troversies and conflicts in groups of more than
one person (dyads, couples, families, institu- Chapter Conclusions
tions, societies).
(a) First, the poles of the controversy at hand are This chapter completes the two describing the
juxtaposed. However, the different, outlying current Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian model of
approach is denied any adequate space or the steps in development. The steps are descrip-
role, is unjustly criticized, or perhaps is even tive of change in human growth, but they are
condemned. representative of change processes, in general.
(b) In the second step of hierarchization, even They are constituted by five stages that pass
more intensive support is given to pole of the through five substages each in a cyclical recur-
controversy with which one aligns. sion. The stages and substages in the present
(c) Next, in systematization, the side aligned model help revise Maslov’s model, which has
with is totally centralized, and perhaps the five needs in a hierarchical model, but which is
other side is treated in a negative, vitriolic, also developmental.

Table 32.14 The transformative effect of controversy (or its entrenchment)


Level Description
Coordination Controversy (or, discordant item, issue, dilemma, debate) emerges involving juxtaposition
of a standard and a different approach, aspect, empirical finding, etc.
Hierarchization Investigation and conceptualization leads to one or other component to be considered primary,
dominant, e.g., with other criticized, invalidated, e.g., point by point. Of course, proponents
of either side have differing opinions of which component is primary, dominant
Systematization The controversy becomes centralized in the overall thought process, discipline, etc.
Multiplication Further investigation and conceptualization might lead to (a) it drop out as important; or
continue on and (b) remain as is and strident; (c) amplify, become reinforced; (d) transform,
taking on new dimensions; or (e) otherwise extend in centralization
Integration The controversy eventually resolves, with one view predominating and becoming standard.
It has extended to the point of informing all or much of the thought process involved
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feigning, and response
bias in psychiatric/psychological injury: Implications for Practice and court. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer Science
+ Business Media; with kind permission from Springer Science + Business Media B. V. [Table 24.7, Page 624]
References 805

References Maslow, A. H. (1943). A theory of human motivation.


Psychological Review, 50, 370–396.
Maslow, A. H. (1970). Motivation and personality (2nd
Barrouillet, P. (2011). Dual-process theories of reasoning:
ed.). New York: Harper and Row.
The test of development. Developmental Review, 31,
Meltzoff, A. N., Kuhl, P. K., Movellan, J., & Sejnowski,
151–179.
T. J. (2009). Foundations for a new science of learn-
Baumeister, R. F. (2008). Free will in scientific psychol-
ing. Science, 325, 284–288.
ogy. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 3, 14–19.
Schaller, M., Neuberg, S. L., Griskevicius, V., & Kenrick,
Blatt, S. J. (2008). Polarities of experience: Relatedness
D. T. (2010). Pyramid power: A reply to commentar-
and self-definition in personality development,
ies. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 5,
psychopathology, and the therapeutic process.
335–337.
Washington, DC: American Psychological
Stanovich, K. E., West, R. F., & Toplak, M. E. (2011). The
Association.
complexity of developmental predictions from dual
Del Giudice, M. (2014). An evolutionary life history
process models. Developmental Review, 31, 103–118.
framework for psychopathology. Psychological
Tomasello, M., & Carpenter, M. (2007). Shared intention-
Inquiry, 25, 261–300.
ality. Developmental Science, 10, 121–125.
Dunkel, C. S., & Sefcek, J. A. (2009). Eriksonian lifespan
Young, G. (1997). Adult development, therapy, and cul-
theory and life history theory: An integration using the
ture: A postmodern synthesis. New York: Plenum.
example of identity formation. Review of General
Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
Psychology, 13, 13–23.
Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science +
Hamlin, J. K. (2014). The conceptual and empirical case
Business Media.
for social evaluation in infancy. Human Development,
Young, G. (2012). A unitary Neo-Piagetian/Neo-
57, 250–258.
Eriksonian model of development: Fundamental
Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking fast and slow. New York:
assumptions and meta-issues. New Ideas in
Farrar, Straus, and Giroux.
Psychology, 30, 241–249.
Kenrick, D. T., Griskevicius, V., Neuberg, S. L., &
Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feigning, and response
Schaller, M. (2010). Renovating the pyramid of needs:
bias in psychiatric/psychological injury: Implications
Contemporary extensions built upon ancient founda-
for practice and court. Dordrecht, Netherlands:
tions. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 5,
Springer Science + Business Media.
292–314.
Generic Change Model
33

These various approaches, and that of


Chapter Introduction Prochaska lend themselves to the language of
complexity, attractors, and how they can trans-
This chapter examines a generic change model form. This hearkens to my approach in Young
based on the present developmental model, as (2011) that the development from attractors to
described in the prior two chapters. Aside from more advanced complexity landscapes under-
examining its applicability in re-interpreting girds the development of cognitive schemes and
other models of change in its own terms, I apply operations through the various cognitive stages
it also to change in nonliving systems. A model and substages in the Neo-Piagetian approach that
that resembles mine is the readiness for change I have modeled.
model (Maddox, 1995; Prochaska, DiClemente,
& Norcross, 1992). In their model, the change
process proceeds through the phases of Generic Change
contemplation/preparation to action/maintenance,
and to resolution. In Young (2011), I showed how Model
the five steps in their model can be reworked in
terms of my own (see Table 33.1). In Young (2011), I presented a Neo-Piagetian
Most of this present chapter is based on new model of stages and substages in development
material not covered in Young (2011, 2014). that includes five stages over the lifespan, with
After an introduction in which the readiness for each having five cyclically recurring substages.
change model is reworked to fit the present In addition, I showed how it could apply to other
generic change model, it is applied to pain areas of psychology. Finally, I showed that it is
patients. The areas covered also include transfor- underpinned by generic change processes based
mation in discovering learning, dealing with in attractors being altered dynamically, so that it
open-ended change, executive function, is applicable to general changes, such as might be
psychotherapy, evolution, and causality, includ- found in evolution of a discipline or biological
ing in the differentiation of genetic-based mod- evolution. Moreover, it addresses mechanisms,
els. Some of the work in the chapter addresses including nonlinear dynamical ones (facilitating
my five-stage developmental model rather than transitions), activation/inhibition coordination
the generic change one, but the material fits this ones (integrating the brain–behavior axes), and
chapter better than elsewhere (e.g., on the rela- evolutionary ones (associated with the major
tionship between evolutionary mechanisms and stages of the model). The common fractal-type
development). pattern across these differing developmental and

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 807


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_33
808 33 Generic Change Model

Table 33.1 Parallel five-step models of stages of change Comment


in therapy and generic model
Stages of change in therapy Generic stages of change Young (2011) showed that the mechanisms of
Contemplation Coordination change undergirding his five-step developmental
Preparation Hierarchization change sequence could reflect a nonlinear dynami-
Action Systematization cal system evolution involving attractors and com-
Maintenance Multiplication plex adaptive systems. If systems gravitate to this
Resolution Integration
change dynamic, with its five steps, then the out-
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business come of the process should be five types of stages
Media. Young, G. (2011). Development and causality:
Neo-Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science in change across the board for nonlinear dynamical
+ Business Media; with kind permission from Springer systems, whether living or nonliving. Systems that
Science + Business Media B. V. [Table 31.3, Page 726] conform to nonlinear dynamical principles should
Note. The stage model of therapy is presented in Prochaska evolve in the sequence indicated because, as they
et al. (1994) and Maddox (1995). The stages of change
model include a last resolution stage that is mentioned seek far-from-equilibrium conditions that maxi-
rarely in the literature, nevertheless, but is part of the orig- mize adaptivity, the possibility of change in the
inal conceptualization of the model (e.g., Maddox, 1995; direction indicated increases because it offers the
Prochaska et al., 1994) best economical and elegant alternative in terms of
system tension reduction and flexibility.

related transition sequences concerns coordina-


tion, hierarchization, systematization, multiplica- Stages of Change in Pain
tion, and integration.
In developing the recursive substage sequence Introduction
for my model, I based the work on Piaget’s sen-
sorimotor substage series. I found generic In Young (2011), I described a model of changes
descriptions for them reflecting the essence of in pain experience that is compatible with the
their characteristics so that they could be applied present generic change model. Prochaska,
readily to the successive stages in development Norcross, and DiClemente’s (1994) developed a
right into the adult period. In effect, they can be model on stages of change, I have shown that it is
applied generically to multiple systems (both compatible with my own, using the example of
living and non-living) that change and evolve both progressive and to regressive changes in the
(see Table 33.1). pain patient. In the following, I give details of the
progressive and regressive steps that pain patients
might experience according to my adapted ver-
Application sion of their model (see Fig. 33.1 and Table 33.3).

As per Young (2011), Table 33.2 indicates the


multiple domains in living and nonliving sys- Progressive
tems that seem to reflect a five-step generic
change process. The behavioral domains include (a) Specifically, in terms of the stage of contem-
not only psychological ones but also economic/ plating change, the person appears to be coordi-
political ones, for example. For nonliving ones, nating the phases involving present condition and
five-step models, or their equivalent, even have future possibility. For pain patients in therapy,
been found with processes of change in the therefore, the model suggests that, first, they
universe. It might be more than coincidence show a readiness for change by coordinating their
that a host of domains express five-step change understanding of their present condition with an
sequences. understanding of how much they can improve.
Stages of Change in Pain 809

Table 33.2 Five stages in system growth in various models of living and nonliving systems
Topic Source Stages
Expertise Sharpless and Barber (2009) Novice. Advanced beginner. Competence. Proficiency. Expertise.
Leadership Boyatzis (2008) Seeing desired future. How acts with others. Developing
learning agenda. Experimenting with new habitats.
Others helping us.
Business Zadek (2004) Denial/defensive. Compliance. Managerial: Managing
responsibility. Strategic: Responsible business strategies.
Toward civil action.
Economies Rostow (1990) Traditional society. Preconditions for take-off. Take-off.
Drive to maturity. High mass consumption.
Disciplines Piaget and Garcia (1989) Intra-object. Inter-object. Trans-object. [Expanded to five
stages in the text.]
Politics Paxton (1998) New way. Rooting. Arrival in power. Exercise of power.
Dual power.
Non-living/ Salthe (2007) Global microscopic disorder. Local orders, global disorders.
Systems/ Global order. Accelerated expansion. Global symmetry.
Big Bang
Bios/Generic Sabelli (2005) Flux (continually reversing). Action processes (directed
processes change). Information (co-creation). Structuration (transient
stability, expanding). Organization (creating).
Complex systems Chen and Fang (2008) Initial. Differentiation. Evolution. Formation. Matured.
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science + Business Media; with kind permission from Springer Science +
Business Media B. V. [Table 31.1, Page 713]

(b) In the next step of preparing/deciding/ (e) Finally, the Prochaska et al. step of prob-
determining in transitions in therapy, the per- lem resolution indicates that the system is in
son appears to be hierarchically organizing dynamic integration, as Young’s (2011) model
commitment and planning as primary in work- would predict. In this vein, in the last stage of
ing toward goals. That is, pain patients appear integration, pain patients appear to attain an
to hierarchically organize as primary a will to increasingly healthier lifestyle that is freer of
effect change. pain, or at least of its limitations.
(c) In the next stage of deliberate action, sys-
tematization seems to characterize psychological
organization, given that deliberate action implies Regressive
a systemic plan of action. In this regard, pain
patients appear to engage in deliberate action in However, conversely, pain patients can sink
order to change, such as participating more effec- increasingly toward the chronic state, and this
tively in psychotherapy, so that a systematized process could be modeled by the same five
application is evident in their behavior. stages of the present model, but in reverse. (a)
(d) Next in the model, the maintenance In the coordination stage of chronic pain devel-
phase is consistent with the spreading out or opment, the negative effects of acute pain are
propagation of gains that have been made into becoming synchronized with the patient’s nor-
wider regions of the system, similar to what I mal ongoing lifestyle. (b) In the hierarchization
would call multiplication. Thus, pain patients stage that develops next, their chronic pain
seem to expand their motivated attitude and becomes pervasive, and is the primary orga-
newly acquired habits into other aspects of nizer relative to their prior lifestyle. (c) In the
their lives. next stage, the patients develop a persistent
810 33 Generic Change Model

Progression Regression Common Change


(e.g., in treating chronic pain, in (e.g., in chronic pain, development, Process
improving self-regulation) lack of self-regulation)

Coordination Preliminary Juxtaposition


(Contemplation) (of old & new)

Hierarchization Prominent Dissonance (old still


(Preparation) dominant, but new,
growing)

Systematization Persistent Distancing (new


(Action) takes precedence)

Multiplication Propagation Propagation (new


(Maintenance) extends)

Integration Entrenchment Reflection (new


(Resolution) dominant; only one)

Fig. 33.1 A dynamical model of self-control, system contribute to longer-term changes, as per part (a) of the
resources, and system depletion. Self-control needs to be figure. Being a dynamical systems model, it is open to
considered in the broader context of self-regulation. The self-organizing, nonlinear, qualitative (emergent) changes
model in the figure first considers progressive and regres- in state. The activation/inhibition coordination dynamic is
sive changes that are possible in self-regulation according essential in this process. The first part of the figure pro-
to an equivalent model for chronic pain (steps in treat- vides a common micro change process that applies to
ment, steps toward chronicity, respectively). The second change sequences, whether progressive or regressive.
part of the figure presents an integrated model of self- Moreover, it is presented in language that is generic
control within a self-regulatory framework. It integrates enough to apply to macro change processes. The five steps
the resource depletion model of Baumeister (2008; in change that seem to explain generically the five steps
Galinsky, Maddux, Gilin, & White, 2008), the motiva- involved in the sequence of coordination, hierarchization,
tional emphasis in Inzlicht and Schmeichel (2012, 2013), systematization, multiplication, and integration that char-
the cost-benefit model of Kurzban, Duckworth, Kable, acterize the present model appears to involve: juxtaposi-
and Myers (2013a, 2013b; which includes motivational tion, dissonance, distancing, propagation, and reflection.
and other factors), and the balance model of Heatherton For a more elaborate description of the mechanisms
(Heatherton & Wagner, 2011; Wagner & Heatherton, underlying the change process, refer to Young (2011)
2013). The model is a dynamical systems one that
accounts for moment-to-moment changes, which in turn

Table 33.3 Stages of change model


Stage Explanation
Precontemplation The person has no intention to change the behavior at issue in the foreseeable future. Most
people in this stage are aware or are underaware of their issues.
Contemplation The person is aware that issues exist. They think seriously thinking about overcoming them, but they
have not yet committed to taking action. Contemplators struggle with their conflicts and with the
amount of effort, energy, and regression that might be involved in overcoming them.
Preparation Individuals are intending to take action in the next month and are reporting some small
behavioral changes (“baby steps”). Although they have made some improvement in their issues,
people in this stage have not yet reached a threshold allowing for effective action.
Action Individuals behave to modify their issues, experiences, and/or context in order to overcome their
difficulties. Actions might be undertaken in overt behavior for timeframe from 1 day to 6 months.
(continued)
Information Processing 811

Table 33.3 (continued)


Stage Explanation
Maintenance The person works to prevent relapse and to consolidate all gains made during the prior stage.
This stage extends from 6 months beyond the last one for an indeterminate period. He/she acts
to remain free of the issue and/or consistently engages in a new countering behavior for more
than 6 months.
Resolution The person resolves the issues that had been confronted but still needs to control the possibility
of incompatible behavior that had been controlled arising again.
Adapted from Norcross, Krebs, and Prochaska (2011)
Note. The stages of change model include a last resolution stage that is mentioned rarely in the literature but is nevertheless
part of the original conceptualization of the model (e.g., Maddox, 1995; Prochaska et al., 1994)

chronic pain lifestyle, so that it in this sense it a goal for the situation. Fourth, they generate
systematizes. (d) Next, chronic pain patients possible responses to the encoded cues. Fifth,
have their pain lifestyle gradually spread they engage in decision-making and enact a
throughout all aspects of their lives. (e) Finally, response.
for these patients, the pain has become deeply
entrenched, resistant to treatment, and might
even characterize an aspect of their personal Model
identity.
(a) The first step in Dodge et al.’s (2013) social
information processing model is analogous to a
Comment coordination process response to the situation. This
obtains in that accurate coding is contrasted with
Pain patients are fragile and can slip into healthy possible inaccurate perceptions or hypervigilance
or pain state attractor regimes (Young, 2011). to threat cues, which is involved in aggressive
Depending on the direction taken, they can gravi- behavior (the subject of the Dodge et al. model).
tate to set points in which pain predominates (b) Next, the interpretation involved could
(regressive) or in which participation in therapy have subsumed under inappropriate hostile attri-
can help (progressive). butions any accurate perceptions, or vice versa,
depending on whether there is an aggression-
linked bias. This is consistent with the hierarchiza-
Information Processing tion process described in the Neo-Piagetian model.
(c) Next, the adoption of a goal in the Dodge
Introduction et al. model is consistent with the systematization
process in the Young model. Goal adaptation appears
Young’s (2011) Neo-Piagetian (sub)stage model a central axis on which adaptation proceeds.
(five substages in each of five stages) applies to (d) Fourth, generating possible behavioral
online, micro-analytic task problem-solving and responses in the former model is akin to the mul-
not only to macro-developmental stage transi- tiplication process in the latter model. As goals
tions. At the micro-analytic level, the work of lead to possible responses, a multiplication pro-
Dodge, Godwin, and The Conduct Problems cess seems evident.
Prevention Research Group (2013) is consistent (e) Finally, decision-making/enacting in social
with the present proposed change sequence. information processing in Dodge et al. reflects
Dodge et al. (2013) presented an information the integration process in the cognitive develop-
processing model that takes place in five steps. mental model in Young. Enacting the chosen
First, individuals encode situational cues. Next, option is consistent with an integration view of
they interpret the encoded cues. Third, they adopt the last step in social information processing.
812 33 Generic Change Model

Discovering Learning Then, through experimentation, akin to multiplica-


tion in my model, new psychological acquisitions
Introduction are realized, leading to an integrative “resonance.”

In Young (2011), I showed how Boyatzis’s (2008)


five-step change process in management is consis- Comment
tent with my Neo-Piagetian change model.
Boyatzis (2006) also has a corresponding model of In this regard, Young (2011) analyzed Harter’s
self-directed learning that suggests five levels. (e.g., 2012) model of self processes. He noted
Dyck and Lovelace (2012) have applied the model that, although it is presented as consistent with the
to worksite health promotion. The model is an Neo-Piagetian models of Case (1992) and Fischer
intentional change one. In it, one compares the (a) (1980), it can be reworked to fit Young’s model.
ideal self and (b) real self to develop a (c) learning
agenda, which leads to (d) new behavior and also
(e) relationships that can help in this regard. This is Open-Ended Change
not quite a stage model but it is partially consistent
with the present Neo-Piagetian one (see Table 33.4). Introduction

Wilson, Hayes, Biglan, and Embry (2014) pre-


Model sented a science of intentional change applicable
both to individuals (e.g., in therapy) and larger
In Young (2011), the change process is considered groups. The work of interest to me especially con-
to move from a stage of coordination of two pos- cerned one of the commentaries. Peschl and
sibilities, old and new, to the hierarchization of the Fundneider (2014) commented that Scharmer
new and old. Then, a system develops. In the fourth (2007) had developed a model of change (see
step, it expands in application in the individual’s Table 33.5). I found it quite similar to my own
psychology, leading to a fifth integrative step. The model, especially if one considers theirs a sequence.
parallel in Boyatzis’s and Young’s work are evi- However, I added an integration step to their model
dent. In this regard, Boyatzis’s step of self-directed because their suggested result for the fourth stage
learning involves the contrast of an ideal and real better fit a new fifth level than simply the output of
self, leading to a self-building agenda (system). a fourth level.

Table 33.4 Boyatzis’s theory of self-directed learning combined with discoveries, positive and negative emotional
attractors, and health promotion applications
Example of positive
Discovery Name Explanation and negative health attractors
1. Ideal self Who do I want to be? Personal vision vs. Unarticulated
Vision
2. Real self Who am I? Strengths vs. Gaps
– Where my ideal and real self are similar
– Where my ideal and real self are different
3. Learning agenda Building on my strengths while reducing gaps Seeking knowledge and abilities
vs. Complying with authorities
4. Practice and Creating and building new neural pathways Trying out new lifestyles/
experimentation through practicing to mastery routines vs. Repeating existing
New behavior, thoughts, and feelings through ones
experimentation
5. Resonant, trusting Resonant relationships that help, support, Connecting with others vs.
relationships and encourage each step in the process Obtaining constructive feedback
Adapted from Boyatzis (2006) and Dyck and Lovelace (2012)
Executive Function 813

Table 33.5 Nonexclusive strategies and levels for dealing with (open-ended) change, with last level added to fit current model
Level Strategy Question (Cognitive) Activities
Precoordination 0. Re-acting Which solutions exist already? Downloading/applying existing
solutions; no change
Coordination 1. Re-structuring What structures are behind these Adapting/optimizing structures
solutions
Hierarchization 2. Re-designing What patterns of perception Redirecting standpoint; perceptions/
and thinking can help? knowledge (owner, others)
Systematization 3. Reframing What are the bases of my Reflecting, reframing, questioning and
thinking, its deep assumptions? dialogue/leaving behind deep
assumptions; new structures of thinking
and new assumptions and principles
Multiplication 4. Re-generating Existential questions concerning Opening up to new uncharted spaces
the core and its potentialities of potential; what wants to emerge?
Integration 5. [Re-Newal] Integration Profoundly or presencing new
knowledge from the perspective of
future possibilities
Adapted from Scharmer (2007) in Wilson et al. (2014)

Model
Executive Function
The description of their strategies is quite consis-
tent with the five-step generic change process in Introduction
my model. (0) Re-acting in their model involves
no change, so is like the pre-coordination level in Barkley (2012) has presented a five-step model
my model. (1) Re-structuring involves adapting for the development of executive function (EF)
structures behind existing solutions, which might that is consistent with the Young Neo-Piagetian
be parallel to what I refer to as coordination. [In model (see Table 33.6). EF is defined as self-
coordination, one juxtaposes elements]. (2) regulation, or self-directed action aimed at goal
Re-designing refers to redirecting, which could choosing and what is needed to create, enact, and
be a parallel to hierarchization in my model. [In sustain actions toward the goals. An appropriate
hierarchization, one places primary elements as definition of EF should consider contextual, per-
dominant to subordinate ones]. (3) Reframing sonal, and social-cultural factors. EF develops
refers to developing new structures, which con- from a pre-executive level to five EF levels.
stitutes a procedure that matches the systematiza-
tion step in my model. (4) Re-generating involves
opening to uncharted spaces, which is quite like Model
my step of multiplication. (5) The result of regen-
erating, as described in Peschl and Fundneider (a) The pre-executive level involves routine
(2014) and in Scharmer (2007), is “profoundly attention, motor, and primary emotional func-
new” knowledge, which is akin to integration in tions, among others. This makes it consistent
my own model. Also in this regard, Peschl and with the reflexive stage in Young.
Fundneider (2014) emphasized that the output of (b) The instrumental, self-directed level
their change model is “learning from the future as includes self-directed attention, self-directed
it emerges.” Note that this extension of their sensory-motor action, etc., and appears “early in
model is consistent with my own because I cre- development,” so it is consistent with the
ated the last step (term) of “Re-Newal.” Piagetian sensorimotor stage, also found in
814 33 Generic Change Model

Table 33.6 The extended function (EF) phenotype Comment


executive
Number Level Barkley’s developmental model of EF is highly
0 Pre-executive consistent with the present Neo-Piagetian stage
1 Instrumental—self-directed model. EF is considered an important mechanis-
2 Methodical—self-reliant tic underpinning to cognitive development (e.g.,
3 Tactical—reciprocal Zelazo, 2004). Barkley’s model could use some
4 Strategic—cooperative
refinement to make it more consistent with the
5 Extended—utilitarian
present Neo-Piagetian stage model. For example,
Adapted from Barkley (2012)
how does inhibition coordinate with activation at
The hierarchical arrangement of six phenotypic EF levels
involves a bidirectional flow of information between the each level and allow increasing sophistication in
levels. Information from a lower level flows upward to a self-regulation? In Young (2011), I speculated on
higher level, and management of a lower level may be the centrality of activation/inhibition coordina-
exerted downward by a higher level
tion in development and, in this regard, Barkley
(2012) considers inhibition a cardinal EF func-
Young (2011). However, this level in Barkley tion. More work is needed in expanding his
also includes verbally-mediated behaviors, so model to allow for the dynamic control inhibition
expands into later infancy at least. affords in its coordination with activation over
(c1) The next EF level to develop is the increasing wider domains and more advanced
methodical, self-reliant level. It involves self- levels in development.
directed action, problem solving, social
independence, etc., so it is consistent with the
pre-operational stage of Piaget, which is the first Patients
part of Young’s perioperational stage. However,
some of the skills at this level could apply to Introduction
either earlier or later cognitive levels, at least in
how they are described. In the following, I show how the present five-step
(c2) Next, tactical-reciprocal EF develops. It change model (coordination, hierarchization, sys-
includes use of tactics, group living, beginning of tematization, multiplication, coordination) can be
economic behavior, etc., so it is consistent with used to build a better understanding of the patient
Piaget’s concrete operational period, the second in psychotherapy and be used to apply psycho-
part of the perioperational stage. therapeutic techniques beyond traditional ways
(d) In the ensuing EF level, strategic coopera- of using them. Note that this effort integrates
tive behavior develops. This includes use of strat- some of the material in the present work already
egies and social cohesion, and it could end in presented, such as how dysfunctional thoughts or
principled-mutualistic self-regulation. Clearly, emotions build, or how the five-step model can be
this is consistent with Piagetian formal abstract used to explain readiness for change.
thought, also found in Young (2011).
(e) The final EF level develops in some indi-
viduals (and societies). It refers to the extended Model
utilitarian zone. This involved reflection on the
wider culture, one’s place in it, and how it can be For example, the stories patients tell themselves
improved. It involves obtaining relevant feedback about themselves and also about others can be
in order to improve the “extended” phenotype. In seen from five-step construction process (see
this regard, Young (2011) similarly referred to Table 33.7). To what extent are the stories (a)
the postformal Neo-Piagetian stage as a collec- coordinated over juxtaposed elements, (b) hierar-
tive intelligence. chized from the axis of a predominant element,
Case Formulation 815

Table 33.7 The stories patients tell: a five-step generic hypothesis formation and testing. In this regard,
change model of their evolution in psychotherapy
the five generic steps of change that I have cre-
Step Explanation ated, and that I have applied to how science
Coordination The patient’s narrative is builds itself through these steps (e.g., develop-
juxtaposed to possibilities
mental psychology, see Chap. 31), would seem to
presented by the therapist through
sensitive guidance. represent a generic knowledge building and inte-
Hierarchization The patient begins to place the new gration process that could apply to professional
story elements in at least one knowledge building in case formulation.
location of his/her narrative as a
possible new outlook.
Systematization The process takes hold and the new
story inhabits the narrative landscape Model
of the patient for that issue.
Multiplication The new story propagates throughout Specifically, the five-step model that I have con-
the patient’s narrative structure. structed affords differentiation and refinement of
Integration It forms an integrated totality of extant models of the patient’s presenting difficul-
new habits, both in daily living and
ties as they are explored, tested, and modified in
in understanding past issues, leading
to better optics for the future. session. Therefore, in applying the five-step
model to patient sessions, in the same manner as
scientists (or scholars generally) approach their
(c) systematized over elements on the basis of the task, the psychotherapist first, engages in (a)
predominant one (or another that has replaced it), knowledge search and (b) hypothesis formula-
(d) extended/expanded/multiplied out into the tion, and then (c) model testing and (d)
general narrative of the patient, and (e) even inte- elaboration, (e) to the point of acquiring an inte-
grated as a coherent theme in that narrative? grative understanding. In the following, I elabo-
rate further these psychotherapeutic steps, but in
combination with my componential psychothera-
Case Formulation peutic model that asks that the whole person be
treated than adopting any one single approach,
Introduction school of thought, technique, etc.
(a) In the stage of coordination of case formu-
Table 33.8 presents a transdiagnostic model of lation using the present transdiagnostic therapeu-
psychotherapy. It considers the patient from a tic approach, the therapist and patient collaborate
holistic perspective, trying to cover the major to elucidate the primary components that are at
components that might be dealt with in psycho- issue for the person in need of psychotherapy
therapy. It places the whole person and his or her from among the 10 components of the model.
needs and aspirations as the apex of treatment. From the basis of the presenting problem as iden-
Anything like (a) particular diagnoses derived tified by the patient, the therapist and patient
from psychiatric manuals, (b) schools of thera- gather the relevant psychological issues, symp-
peutic thought, and (c) particular therapeutic toms, and presumed facts that govern the presen-
techniques are considered subordinate to the tation, and develop a profile of (juxtaposed)
needs and goals of the person in psychotherapy. information acquired.
In Young (2014), I presented the model without (b) In the stage of hierarchization, the thera-
indicating how it can be applied according to the pist formulates a hypothesis of the primary issues
present five-stage generic change model. In the involved in the case at hand, and the implications
following, I indicate how such a case formulation for treatment. The therapist might refer to the
process might work (see Table 33.9). 10-component transdiagnostic model in this
In creating a model of case formulation, I regard, and hierarchize the components accord-
draw a parallel with the scientific process of ing to which ones are primary and need treatment
816 33 Generic Change Model

Table 33.8 Componential approach to psychotherapy: the ten major components of the person in psychotherapy
Component Explanation
1. Psychoeducational, Much of the feedback functions to alleviate incorrect knowledge about the
instructional client’s condition, and how therapy can help.
2. Physiological Relaxation Relaxation techniques allow the individual to moderate initial reactions to stress
techniques and emotions, reduce long term stress reactions, learn to maintain equilibrium
when confronted with new stresses, and so on.
2a. Physiological Breathing In my approach, I indicate that any breathing technique itself is secondary to
techniques focusing on the rhythms of the breathing, etc.
2b. Physiological Progressive Essentially, the client is asked to contract or flex and then stretch or extend zones
muscle relaxation of the body in a sequential manner.
2c. Physiological Biofeedback At the core, the person learns to control physiological activity
3. Behavioral General Reinforcements are administered after a desired behavior so that the frequency of
its emission is increased. Also, much behavior is acquired through observational
learning, imitation, and so on. This is especially important with children.
3a. Behavioral Additional Systematic desensitization involves exposing the individual to the problematic
behavioral techniques emotional, arousing, or feared stimulus or situation. However, the exposure is
for anxiety graduated and the arousal is dampened by simultaneous relaxation exercises.
Systematic desensitization
3b. Behavioral Additional In exposure therapy, clients safely confront their fears in a systematic way.
behavioral techniques for Relaxation techniques are learned as adjuncts.
anxiety
Exposure therapy
3c. Behavioral Additional The goal is to have clients gain mastery in a safe environment of neurovegetative
behavioral techniques reactions that mimic the ones that they may have experienced during episodes of
for anxiety psychological trauma/distress.
Interoceptive Awareness/
Sensitization
4. Action tendencies, Learning to better redirect, moderate, inhibit, or otherwise control bad habits that
inhibitory control are interfering, disruptive, and so on, is facilitated by techniques that inhibit
negative activity, such as using breathing techniques at the first sign of
inappropriate or exaggerated emotional upset.
5. Cognitive Cognitive therapy is a restructuration process that helps clients alter unhelpful,
unrealistic, impairing, irrational, dysfunctional, or otherwise inappropriate thoughts.
6. Affective, emotional, At the emotional level, a common technique is to encourage clients to try to find
intrapersonal the meaning behind the emotion being expressed, and to work toward solving the
issues raised in this exploration and insight. Constructive affective self-
statements include: “Some worry is motivating; too much is not”; “I’m worried
because I want to change.”
7. Social, relational, The therapist uses the necessary techniques in working with clients to optimize this
interpersonal area of functioning. Interpersonal therapy focuses on these issues, in particular.
8. Self esteem, motivational The therapist helps the client construct a new, more positive story about the self
relative to past stories that have been learned.
9. Coping, problem solving Optimal coping when confronted by problems or stress of any kind is partly
cognitive and partly strategic. Moreover, the therapist guides the client in
learning different ways to cope, and, depending on context, ones that are more
problem-focused than emotion-focused.
10. Broader cognitive Although cognitive therapy concerns itself with beliefs that reflect wider
constructions concerns in terms of self-confidence, attributions of intentions of others, and so
on, there also broader or macro level cognitions that one should consider, such as
narratives, life stories, scripts, and existential schemas
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2008). Psychotherapy for psychological injury:
A biopsychosocial and forensic perspective. Psychological Injury and Law, 1, 287–310; with kind permission from Springer
Science + Business Media B. V. [Page 302–306]. The table is adapted, while the text on the right-hand column is adopted
Note. The whole-person, componential approach to therapy is based on understanding the individualized symptom/
impairment/disability profile of the person, if any. The profile is established after a scientifically-informed, impartial,
and comprehensive assessment. The therapy involves an integrated, individualized therapeutic program based on tech-
niques, principles, and schools/theories that address the components involved
Education 817

Table 33.9 Case formulation according to the five-step lines, and prepares for transitioning control to
generic change model
patient of the management of the symptoms, the
Step Explanation self, and the present and future, rather than hav-
Coordination Gather issues, symptoms, “facts” in ing psychotherapy in control of these issues.
case (collaboratively).
Both therapist and patient arrive at a comprehen-
Hierarchization Develop initial hypotheses of the
primary issue(s) and treatment needs.
sive understanding of the patient and her/his
Revise as new information and needs, goals, and appropriate helping mecha-
responses to implemented therapies/ nisms through their collaborative effort.
techniques become evident.
Systematization Arrive at clear understanding of
primary issue(s) and treatment need(s).
Education
Multiplication Determine the degree to which they
have affected other aspects of the
patient’s psychology and those of Introduction
any significant others that might be
involved. These examples further illustrate the generalizing
Integration Proceed to firm up insight in the
nature of the five-step change sequence that I have
patient, encourage/monitor techniques
that have been effective, and transfer posited. Other applications follow. For teaching,
full responsibility for their use (and the goal also is both to understand the learning
the person’s growth) to the patient. difficulties being encountered by the child and to
deal effectively with the issues encountered. In
these regards, the five-step change model that is at
first. Generally, though, a whole-person perspec- the heart of the present section of this work can be
tive is kept in mind. As formulation (and therapy) used to understand at which step in the change
proceeds, hypotheses might be revised as new process each student finds him- or herself for each
information is gathered. particular domain of learning and study.
(c) The therapist arrives at a working hypoth-
esis of the patient that potentially can serve
toward the development of an integrated frame- Learning
work for understanding and for treatment. As
well at this juncture, the therapist might acceler- (a) For example, have the students acquired the
ate the process of working toward patient insight. correct information needed and coordinated it?
This description of the third step in the proposed (b) Have they formed preliminary hierarchical
five-step psychotherapeutic sequence constitutes structures of the information? (c) Is a model, con-
the phase of systematization in therapy. cept, theory, hypothesis, or other cognitive frame
(d) Next, the collaborative patient–therapist (e.g., schema, representation), depending on the
relationship enters a new phase of working on the age and problem at issue, emerging from the
range of issues that bedevil the patient or compli- coordination and hierarchization process? (d)
cate daily living. Also, it deals with past issues Does the cognitive structure show signs of
and forward direction (anticipation of issues and spreading into the full cognitive system involved,
planning for them). According to the present five- multiplying in its reach? (e) Finally, has this
step change model, this psychotherapeutic step is process led to the construction of a fully inte-
one involving multiplication. grated new cognitive structure in the student?
(e) Finally, in the stage of integration in psy-
chotherapy, the therapist, who has been working
on all relevant affected components in the psy- Teaching
chology of the patient according to the compo-
nential model, arrives at an overarching (a) As for teaching, has the teacher presented to
framework. The therapist works toward the the students information that can be readily coor-
patient acquiring necessary insight along these dinated/juxtaposed, and so on? (b) Is the teacher
818 33 Generic Change Model

guiding them in creating glimpses of an organiza- I showed how Feist’s work is consistent with my
tion with the kernel of a new idea that can sub- own. Then, I turn to Dunbar’s work on social
sume the information coordinated to a beginning drivers in evolution, which, like the other work in
and then a more complete degree? (c) Is a teach- this section, is consistent with my own.
ing process in place to facilitate student acquisi-
tion of more coherent systematic cognitive
constructs? (d) If so, does the teacher help these Mechanisms
generalize? (e) Is the fifth-step of integration of
the problem domain by the student enabled by Nowak (2012) explained his model of five mech-
the teaching methods and means used? anisms that could contribute to the evolution of
cooperation. They involve: (a) direct reciproc-
ity—these are conditional strategies that depend
Interim Conclusion on previous outcomes with the other individual;
(b) indirect reciprocity—conditional strategies
These examples illustrate that the five-step are influenced by what is learned about the repu-
change process described in the present work has tation of the other individual; (c) spatial selec-
quite general applications. It could not be too dif- tion—neighbors are prone to help each other; (d)
ficult to generalize the model to any instructive or multi-level selection—includes group selection
learning situation, such as parenting and the (everything else being equal, groups of coopera-
application of discipline, and, for the child, tors are evolutionarily advantaged); and (e) kin
observational learning, imitation, and emulation. selection—conditional strategies are based on
These examples, and further ones that can be cre- genetic relatedness (closer relatives are favored;
ated, illustrate that the present five-step change a concept not to be confused with that of inclu-
model could lead to a paradigmatic change in sive fitness). This model is consistent with
understanding human behavior and its transfor- Nowak, Tarnita, and Wilson (2010), who main-
mation across a wide spectrum of situations. tained that individual level and other evolution-
The causal nature behind the human condition ary mechanisms complement group selection
might lie greatly in the proposed sequence. processes in the evolution of cooperation.
Causality is not just about Nature × Nurture, or Similarly, Nowak presented this work with col-
even Nature × Nurture × Self, as I have been sug- leagues (e.g., Rand & Nowak, 2013).
gesting. It is also about the mechanisms of change Young (2011) has shown that the five mecha-
in the micro-acquisitions in development, learn- nisms at work in human cooperation according to
ing, and so on, and the factors that promote them. Nowak are consistent with his developmental
In these regards, the present five-step change model. Moreover, the correspondence proposed
model might constitute a cardinal mechanism in across evolutionary mechanism and stage in
human behavior expression and its causal change development occurs in one-to-one way. This
at all levels. illustrates not only the value of my revision of the
multilevel model based on the work of Nowak
but also the value of my developmental model.
Evolution

Introduction Model

In the following, I examine the evolutionary pro- Multilevel selection includes five levels accord-
cess both in terms of mechanism (e.g., natural ing to the present model (see Table 33.10). The
selection) and product (stages). For the former, I levels are presented on the left side of the table
elaborated the model of Nowak and for the latter and are reworkings of Nowak’s model. He refers
Evolution 819

Table 33.10 Five evolutionary mechanisms in a revised model of multilevel selection as applied to the origins of the
current developmental stage model
Mechanism Explanation
Natural selection For the manner in which individual-level selection influences the expression of cognitive stage
acquisitions, the behaviors of the stage facilitated (reflexive) appear directly aimed at resource
accrual (surviving the first days, sucking nourishment, etc.). In this regard, they seem to have
evolved due to natural selection, and are based on the evolutionary competition among
individuals whose phenotypic expressions had included underpinning genotypes involving
reflexive cognition. This does not deny that parents provide the opportunities for the reflexive
behaviors that are needed to sustain life (and that behavior at this age involves more than this
set of behaviors).
Kin selection In kin selection and its associated cognitive level of sensorimotor intelligence, which begins in
the first month, an increased resource networking is facilitated through recruitment of parental
or other kin care. Children at this age engage in sensorimotor behavior that facilitates family
care giving and kin cooperativity. For example, there is family play, imitation, learning,
affection, etc., that takes place with siblings.
Group-for- In the next level in the present model of multilevel selection, group selection is involved, but
Individual only in that members of the group (children) have developed behaviors that allow them to take
selection advantage of group-selected traits. In this sense, the range of genetic resources to which the
individual has access for survival and reproductive needs expands to members of the group,
whether kin or non-kin, who are acting to create social and institutional structures that
facilitate obtaining the survival and reproductive advantages.
The cognitive level promoted by the level of Group-for-Individual behavior concerns
Piagetian representational structures, which allow for symbolic thought, language use, and so
on, through pre-operations and concrete operations. The latter, in particular, permit logical
thought to be expressed in the physical contexts that the child encounters, such as in the
particular school subjects to which school-age children are exposed.
Note that in the case of children profiting from learning and educational structures, one cannot
speak of immediate reproductive advantages. However, the social and cognitive skills
developed in the teaching and learning that takes place in educational and instructional settings,
as well as the inter-peer social interactions and links promoted, serve these goals in the long
term. That is, the resource networking involved in children attending school and otherwise
profiting from learning opportunities created by the group might not be readily apparent,
because the information and knowledge-base acquired in the educational learning situations, as
well as the social connections, might reveal their adaptive advantages only later in development.
Reciprocity Next, reciprocal altruism or selection acts to increase the scope of gene pools aiding
individual’s survival and reproduction by capturing non-kin. In this sense, the formal abstract
thought promoted encourages expanded peer and social interaction, mutually beneficial social
exchanges, alliances and pacts, the tracking of resource donation and receipt, the monitoring of
cooperation and free loading, and so on. This helps enhance resource networking access,
acquisition, management, and replenishment, all necessary for survival, reproduction,
adaptedness, and fitness.
Individual-for- Finally, classical group selection, or Individual-for-Group selection, through the collective
Group selection intelligence that it facilitates and the social and work groupings that it promotes, acts to increase
the array of actors contributing to an individual’s fitness, whether kin or non-kin. This acts to
increase the extent of resource networking and accrual available to the individual for survival and
reproduction. Also, the behavior allows the group to increase its resource access, acquisition,
management, and replenishment [think of brainstorming at work], profiting all individuals in the
group who are creating the collective product, and others who are indirectly involved [e.g., the
profitability of the whole company increases]. Granted, the behavior expressed by the individual
may be self-sacrificial, but this need not be the case. Moreover, even if it is, the activity is oriented
to increasing group competitiveness, so functions to ensure survival and reproduction of all its
members, on the average, whether self or other, or whether kin or non-kin. Other examples for
this type of collective intelligence refer to creation of informal and formal educational and
learning opportunities.
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science + Business Media; with kind permission from Springer Science +
Business Media B. V. [Excerpt, Pages 752–753]
820 33 Generic Change Model

to the evolutionary mechanisms of direct and Comment


indirect reciprocity, spatial selection, multilevel
selection (which includes group selection), and In keeping with my model in which natural
kin selection. I refer to individual or natural selection is the first evolutionary mechanism in
selection, kin selection, group for individual the evolution of cooperation, and indeed, the
selection, reciprocity, and individual-for group- process of gene co-opting toward the service of
selection (i.e., like group selection). In my model, the evolutionary needs of the individual can
the levels reflect increasing gene co-opting of the help explain the other mechanisms involved, I
other toward individual survival and reproduc- note that Hunt (2012) queried whether the evo-
tion, and I posit that they have been applied lution of the classic example of eusociality in
sequentially in the evolution of human coopera- worker behavior in the social insects did not
tive behavior. Also, I add a new mechanism of involve, at first, individual selection, only to
group for individual selection, such as found in progress later to influence through multilevel
educating children. In the following, I show how selection (including of group selection). Indeed,
the five different evolutionary mechanisms in my Darwin (1859) had written that the example of
model relate to the evolution of the five stages in tribal-related “sacrifice” for the “common
development in my model. good” could be evolutionarily advantageous
(a) First, in humans, the first cognitive devel- and “this would be natural selection” (described
opmental stage of reflexes appears to be the out- in Nowak, 2012).
come of straightforward natural selection at the However, all this does not deny that group
individual level. These behaviors seem essential selection is empirically-supported and subject to
for survival and reproduction at the individual myth (Eldakar & Wilson, 2011; Sober & Wilson,
level. 2011). Group adaptation requires more than
(b) Sensorimotor intelligence is partly a prod- group selection, but the latter can be integral to
uct of kin selection. This obtains because the it. Sober and Wilson (2011) concluded that group
infant profits in its survival and reproduction by selection and individual selection are linked.
the family links needed, by the behavior of fam- To conclude, I note that Nowak (2012)
ily members co-opted in her or his care, etc. referred to humans as “supercooperators.”
(c) With perioperational or representational Perhaps the co-cultural/evolutionary model and
thought, the child can partake in group-created research on the topic can lead to an integrated
and group-governed education and learning regi- model.
mens; the impact of Group-for-Individual evolu-
tionary selection pressure and the child’s adaptive
response to the activity it promotes seems partly Stages
involved.
(d) With abstract thought, the teenager can Introduction
create complex links with peers, including non-
kin. This behavior appears partly a product of Feist (2004, 2006) used Piagetian theory as a
reciprocal altruism or selection. basis for a model of cognitive evolution in homi-
(e) With collective intelligence, such as in nids (see Table 33.11). He identified: (a) a sensory
brainstorming, the group outcome in the cogni- phase; (b) a pre-representational one; (c) a repre-
tive activity helps the group arrive at an adaptive sentational one; and (d) a meta-representational
and even competitive outcome. At this stage, the one. The phases evolved, respectively, in ances-
multilevel selection level of Individual-for-Group tral monkeys, great apes, and humans, and the
selection seems to partly apply. last one in modern humans.
Stages 821

Table 33.11 Piagetian stages in hominid cognitive evolution


Phase Taxon Piagetian stage
Sensory Monkeys ESM LSM
Pre-representational Great apes ESM LSM EPO
Australopithecus ESM LSM EPO LPO?
Homo habilis–rudolfensis ESM LSM EPO LPO
Representational Homo ergaster–erectus ESM LSM EPO LPO ECO
Archaic Homo sapiens ESM LSM EPO LPO ECO LCO
Homo neanderthalensis ESM LSM EPO LPO ECO LCO
Meta-representational Modern humans ESM LSM EPO LPO ECO LCO FO
Adopted by permission of Yale University Press. Feist, G. J. (2006). The psychology of science and the origins of the scien-
tific mind. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Reprinted by permission of Yale University Press. [Table 8.2, Page 173]
Abbreviations. E Early, L Late, SM Sensorimotor, PO Preoperational, CO Concrete Operational, FO Formal Operational
Note. Taxa in italics are based on inferences from the archeological record and are hypotheses and conjectures as much
as description of fact (cf. Donald, 1991; Mithen, 1996; Parker & McKinney, 1999, p. 279)
Feist’s (2006) work is relevant to the present work on two grounds. First, it supports use of Piaget’s developmental
model in understanding evolutionary changes in thought, which is the same approach taken in Young (2011). Second,
the evolutionary sequence that it describes is consistent with the one in Young (2011). Note, however, that Young (2011)
has a more elaborate Piagetian model that applies to evolutionary stages both before that of ancestral nonhuman
primates and into substages of modern humans

As for the origins of scientific thinking, Feist pattern recognition; (d) hypothesis testing; and
(2006) presented a model analogous to the four- (e) causal thinking (Table 33.12). There are
step hominid cognitive evolution one that he had other components added to each phase. This
described. He referred to the (a) preverbal, (b) model speaks to my Neo-Piagetian substage
verbal, (c) applied, and (d) pure phases, respec- one of five substages cyclically recurring within
tively (see Table 33.11). each stage.

Model Comment

According to Feist (2006), the Piagetian stages Feist’s (2006) work presaged some of the
associated with these evolutionary stages are the themes in my own Neo-Piagetian model of
sensorimotor, preoperational, concrete opera- development (Young, 2011) and how it can be
tional, and formal operational, respectively. Feist applied both to (a) understanding evolution and
referred to the research of Parker and McKinney (b) the origins of scientific thought. However,
(1999) on nonhuman primates, who, like him- my model is based on five stages with five sub-
self, viewed the correspondence between stages each, whereas he uses the classic
Piagetian developmental stages and the steps Piagetian four-stage sequence, as well as a five-
toward the evolution of human behavior as mutu- stage component recycling within them.
ally informative. This model speaks to my Neo- Moreover, I applied my model to science by
Piagetian stage one, in which there are five showing how disciplines such as developmental
stages. psychology or evolutionary thought can be
For his work on growth in scientific thought, modeled to grow according to these stages (and
it is interesting that he referred to five core substages; see Chap. 31). Nevertheless, it is
components within each phase that develop heartening to see another worker approaching
sequentially (but not just linearly, also dynami- both the evolution of behavior and the develop-
cally): (a) observation; (b) categorization; (c) ment of scientific thought from a stage frame-
822

Table 33.12 Phases of scientific thinking and their key components, forms of thought, and age
Phase
Preverbal Verbal Applied Pure
Components Observation Observation Observation Observation
Categorization Categorization Categorization Categorization
Pattern recognition Pattern recognition Pattern recognition Pattern recognition
Hypothesis testing Hypothesis testing Hypothesis testing Hypothesis testing
Causal thinking Causal thinking Causal thinking Causal thinking
Explanation/theory Explanation/theory Explanation/theory
Control (magic) Control Control
Measurement Measurement
Incipient math Developed math
Controlled experimentation
Forms of thought Implicit representational Implicit meta-representational Implicit–explicit Explicit meta-representational
meta-representational
Age 1.8 million years ago 100 thousand years ago 30 thousand years ago 2.6 thousand years ago
Adopted from Feist (2006)
Note. Feist’s (2006) model of evolution in the phases of scientific thought is quite consistent with my development model, which I also applied both to evolution and the growth
of scientific thought (e.g., Darwin’s theorizing, growth in psychological models since Freud) (see Young, 2011). Feist’s repetitive cycle from observation to causal thinking is a
five-step one consistent with the five substages of my model. His four-step stage model from ancestral humans to contemporary ones could use another stage mirroring more
recent progress in scientific thought. This would render his model comparable to my five-stage developmental one that I applied to growth in scientific thought (which ends in a
postformal Neo-Piagetian one beyond the Piagetian abstract, formal stage, which I refer to as a superordinate collective intelligence). However, in successive states Feist does
add 12 steps beyond the original five ones, as well, arriving at a total of five more steps by the last pure stage. This renders our two models different, with his involving 10 steps
33

and mine 5 in the penultimate period. Nevertheless, one could argue that the pure stage of scientific thinking in modern humans in Feist’s work consists of 10 steps because it
reflects the two cognitive stages of adolescent abstract thought and adult collective intelligence in my model, each of which goes through the same five substages, for a total of
10 steps, too. In this regard, the first and sixth stages in Feist’s sequence should reflect the substage of coordination in my model, in which entities are juxtaposed. In this regard,
one could argue that observation involves juxtaposition of data and then explanation/theory formulation involves juxtaposition of concepts. As for the last steps in each of the
five-steps involved in the comparison between Feist and Young, once could argue that both causal thinking and controlled experimentation represent integrations of the preceding
four steps involved. Admittedly, the middle three steps in the two five-step recursive cycles involved do not easily match up, so that more conceptual work appears needed
Generic Change Model
Social Driver 823

work, and one based on Piaget, analogously to (Henzi et al., 2007; Stiller & Dunbar, 2007). [I
the approach that I have taken. note that this model is somewhat consistent with
my own five-step developmental stage model.]
Dunbar (2013) related these five developmen-
Social Driver tal levels of intentionality to the person’s grow-
ing circles of acquaintanceship or social
Introduction networks. In particular, they correspond approxi-
mately to <5, 5, 15, 50, and 150 people, respec-
Dunbar (2013) presented the social brain hypoth- tively (see Fig. 33.2). He added that, as adulthood
esis, which describes an evolutionarily-derived proceeds, the network can grow to 500 and, then,
neocortical basis for social cognition. Social life 1500 people, which is the upper limit of personal
in primate societies is complex and computation- recognition in a circle.
ally demanding. Primates have large brains
because of the evolutionary driver for the need of
social bonding, or having deep social ties. Bonding Comment
is a dual cognitive and emotional process that is
developmentally-rooted. Brain region volume In my cognitive developmental model, consisting
actually causally to determine potential compe- of 25 steps (5 stages × 5 substages over the lifes-
tence in social cognition, and sets the capacity for pan, Young, 2011), a basis might be provided for
the extent of an individual’s social network. Dunbar’s proposed five levels of intentionality in
development and social network size. Perhaps
Dunbar’s five-step model of intentionality and
Model corresponding network size relate somewhat to
the sensorimotor, preoperational, concrete opera-
According to Dunbar (2013), in humans, develop- tional, and formal operational stages of Piaget,
mentally, it appears there are transitions in inten- and the postformal adult level. In my model, I
tionality over five levels. The infant could be add an early reflexive stage and collapse the pre-
considered pre-theory of mind, with the next step operational and concrete operational ones into a
at age 4 involving formal theory of mind. Next, perioperational stage. However, often I keep the
levels 3, 4, and 5 in intentionality appear to separation between these two phases within my
develop at ages 8, 12, and 18 years, respectively. combined perioperational stage. Further work is
The levels that are proposed were derived from a needed on the possible relationship of Neo-
study of estimate of mind states of story characters Piagetian stage theory, intentionality, network

Fig. 33.2 Circles of


acquaintances (As): Friends 150 As
an evolutionary model. The
circles of acquaintances refer to Good Friends 50 As
the “circles of acquaintanceship.”
Social networks form series of Best Friends 5 As
hierarchically embedded levels of
acquaintanceship that organize in Intimates 15 As
a very consistent way (in scales
of approximately 5 intimates, 15 Person
best friends, 50 good friends, and
150 friends, with each level
inclusive of its inner ones) (Hill
& Dunbar, 2003; Roberts &
Dunbar, 2011; Zhou, Sornette,
Hill, & Dunbar, 2005). Adapted
from Dunbar (2013)
824 33 Generic Change Model

size, underpinning brain regions, and the concept processes outside the individual, such as collec-
of the social brain and its evolution. tive search processes including ones driven by
computer data mining. Second, the figure that I
created on the five steps on data mining illus-
Data Driver trates how the present generic change model can
help understand work on change processes that
Figure 33.3 presents an interesting application of are not theoretically informed. That is, I could
the current five-step generic change step model. I only add a fifth step to the sequence that I had
took the work of Sporns on data mining and con- detected in the work of Sporns on the topic
figured it into a five-step process that is consis- because I applied the current model that I had
tent with the current generic change model. I had developed and saw the need for a new step.
to add a fifth stage to accomplish this task. Finally, this exercise on reinterpreting the steps in
This application of the current model to data mining according to the current five-step
Sporns’ (2011, 2012) work on data driver illus- generic change sequence adds to the validation of
trates two important points. First, the current the five-stage Neo-Piagetian cognitive develop-
generic change model is applicable to change mental model on which it is based (Young, 2011).

Step Description Output

1. Coordination Data mining Identification of


components

Identification of
2. Hierarchization Bioinformatics interactions

Identification of
3. Systematization Modeling interaction types

Quantification of
interactions

4. Multiplication Expansion of Model’s applied to


Modeling Data new areas
Creation

5. Integration Integrative Overarching


Modeling models derived

Fig. 33.3 The creation of models from data to integra- (Young, 2011), as presented in column 1, and to make his
tion. The figure illustrates that, according to Sporns model consistent with mine, I added an intermediate step
(2012), the four steps in the creation of connectome after the third one. Adapted from Sauer, Heinemann, and
models proceeds from data mining to integration. I have Zamboni (2007) in Sporns (2012)
developed a similar sequence for change processes
Causality 825

Causality on behavior has evolved to allow for their inter-


action. G × E is a variant that restricts the interac-
Introduction tion to certain alleles being present in certain
conditions (see Fig. 33.4). But the concept of
The present section illustrates how the generic G × E, itself, has evolved in that genes are now
five-step change model that I have constructed understood to be influenced by environmental-
can be used to show how models in the field mediated epigenetic (gene-silencing) effects.
might evolve from their present state. First, I Also, the environment is not an independent
show how this could happen for the model of entity relative to genes, in that it responds in a
G × E (Genetics × Environment). Then, I do the correlated way (passive, evocative, active) to
same for causal mapping models. Finally, I take genetic influences.
one of my own models and apply to it this logic That is, genes and environment reciprocally
(on S–O–R; see Chap. 28). influence each other through epigenesis. Also,
genes and environment reciprocally influence
each other through correlated G × E interactions.
Genes/Epigenesis One could modify this model by indicating the
distal risk resilience/facilitative factors that indi-
For the G × E work, to begin, I present a figure vidualize the developing person in a complete
that helps review this area. Figure 33.4 illustrates biopsychosocial interaction. The model could be
how the traditional concept of Nature × Nurture modified even further by attempting a full-scale
interacting in behavior has evolved. The concept integration that includes in it evolution, develop-
of separate genetic and environmental influences ment, learning, and context.

a Nature x Nurture (vs. G x E) Target Gene Present

- general Yes No
- applies to all aspects of
development Yes X
Environment
- not specific, unlike G x E
Factor
- incomplete; should be Nature: Present
Nurture x Self No X X

b Genes x Environment (G x E) (vs. New Genetics)


- genes and environment are separate entities
Epigenesis
that interact when certain specific alleles/
polymorphisms are present, but they can
have their effects only when certain specific
environments are present GxE
- e.g., the 5-HTTLPR x Maltreatment
interaction leads to antisocial-related
behavior (Caspi, McClay, Moffitt, Mill, rGE
Martin, Craig, Taylor, & Poulton, 2002) (correlated gene x
environment)

Fig. 33.4 Meanings of Genes × Environment. Nature and interactions (G × E). G × E is a concept evolving itself, for
nurture are no longer considered separate, additive influ- example, because of epigenesis (e) and correlated G × E
ences on behavior. They interact, as in Genes × Environment (rG × E)
826 33 Generic Change Model

Steps Model

1. Coordination G, E

2. Hierarchization GxE

Epigenesis (e)

3. Systematization
GxE

rGE (r)

e
Distal antecedent/ Proximal triggering/
risk/ resilience/ buffering
4. Multiplication facilitative individualizing
individualizing
GxE factors
factors (biopsychosocial)
(biopsychosocial)
r

e
Distal antecedent/ Proximal triggering/
risk/ resilience/ buffering
5. Integration facilitative individualizing
individualizing
GxE factors
factors (biopsychosocial)
(biopsychosocial)
r

Learning
Development
Evolution
Context

Fig. 33.5 Origins of a comprehensive model of G × E cept of G × E influenced by epigenesis (e) and by
relations. The figure illustrates how the concept of G × E correlated G × E (rG × E, or r) (step 3). The present model-
can be modeled to undergo change according to the pres- ing effort led me to add steps 4 and 5 in accord with the
ent five-step change model. This figure presents the con- generic change model described in the present work

These various steps in the evolution toward an Causal Graphs


integrative genetic/environmental model can be
arrayed into the five steps consistent with the Other causal models described in the present
present generic change model (see Fig. 33.5). In work can be elaborated within the framework of
this regard, (a) in the coordination phase, genes the five-step generic change model that I have
and environment are considered separate influ- constructed. In this regard, Fig. 33.6 presents
ences (are juxtaposed). (b) Next, their interaction how graphic representation of cause–effect rela-
can be considered as a hierarchization. (c) Adding tions can be shown to have grown from (a) a
epigenetic and correlated G × E effects system- basic coordinated juxtaposition (A → B), (b) to a
atizes G × E. (d) Adding the distal and proximal hierarchization (e.g., both A, B to C) and, then,
individualizing components is equivalent to (c) to a systematization (reciprocity among A, B,
multiplying it out. (e) Finally, the fifth step is a C). (d) A multiplication elaboration of the model
genuinely integrating one. would look like the ones in causal mapping
Causality 827

Step Model

1. Coordination A B

A
2. Hierarchization C
B

A
3. Systematization C
B

DISTAL PROXIMAL OUTCOME

4. Multiplication B D F

D1 E

DISTAL PROXIMAL OUTCOME

5. Integration B D F

D1 E

Learning
Development
Evolution
Context

Fig. 33.6 Origins of a comprehensive graph model of distal-proximal outcomes. Using the same logic as in the prior
figure, this figure illustrates how graphs representing causal processes can be represented in a five-step change sequence

modeling (e.g., Sloman, 2005). (e) In the inte- Fig. 33.7). This figure on the evolution of the S–O–R
gration step, models such as these would add the model begins with (a) the coordinated juxtaposition
evolution, development, learning, and contex- of S (stimulus) and R (response). (b) Then, the inter-
tual component. mediary of the O (organism) is added as a hierar-
chizing component. (c) The S–O(BAMP)–R model
that I created is based on the S–O–R one, and is a
Stimulus–Response systems approach. (d) By adding distal and proxi-
mal individualizing components the revised S–O–R
The revised S–O–R model that I have developed model is being multiplied out. (e) Finally, the fifth
can be seen to evolve in the same five steps as step adds the evolution, development, learning, and
the revised integrated G × E one in Fig. 33.5 and the context components to the expanded model, giving
revised causal mapping one in Fig. 33.6 (see it an integrative framework.
828 33 Generic Change Model

Step Model

1. Coordination S–R

2. Hierarchization S–O–R

3. Systematization S – O(BAMP)– R

Distal antecedent/ Proximal


risk/ resilience/ triggering/
4. Multiplication facilitative buffering
S – O(BAMP)– R
individualizing individualizing
factors factors
(biopsychosocial) (biopsychosocial)

Distal antecedent/ Proximal


risk/ resilience/ triggering/
facilitative S – O(BAMP)– R buffering
5. Integration individualizing individualizing
factors factors
(biopsychosocial) (biopsychosocial)

Learning
Development
Evolution
Context

Fig. 33.7 Origins of a comprehensive model of S–R rela- S–R model (and S–O–R) can be elaborated through five
tions. The prior figures illustrated how the concept of steps consistent with the present five-step generic change
G × E and causal mapping can be modeled in a five-step model to arrive at a more inclusive, integrated one
generic change process. In this figure, I indicate how the

in information processing and executive func-


Chapter Conclusions tioning. It can help explain both progressive and
regressive changes in pain patients. It can help
In Young (2011), I had shown that the develop- in understanding psychotherapy both in terms of
mental model that I had created reflects generic case formulation and the narratives patients tell.
change processes. Moreover, I had found similar It applies to teaching and learning. A large sec-
patterns in other areas of psychology and other tion of the chapter deals with changes evident in
disciplines, including the same five-step pat- and through evolution. Finally, I even apply the
terns in non-living systems. In the present chap- model to show how genetics and epigenesis can
ter, I continue to apply the five-step generic be perceived through the model, as can other
change model to understanding transformation, causality-related processes, such as causal graph
whether in development or more generally. The modeling.
proposed generic change model is consistent Overall, the present generic change model has
with other five-step change models, such as the both forward and backward ramifications. On the
one of readiness for change. It is consistent with one hand, it should be able to expand its scope of
other five-step psychological models, such as application. On the other hand, it speaks to the
References 829

validity of the developmental model from which I have hypothesized to be the case for the sub-
it is derived (my combined Neo-Piagetian/Neo- stages of my model, (e.g., microgenetically for
Eriksonian (sub)stage model, Young, 2011). particular skills, for particular tasks), or parallel
Although I have presented a generic change acquisitions that do the same, as I have hypoth-
model that has wide applicability and that speaks esized to be the case for Neo-Eriksonian and
to the validity of the developmental model from Neo-Maslovian growth (or blockages and even
which it is derived, reversing perspectives sug- reversals in these regards, (or in others, such as in
gests that had the generic change model been the development of chronic pain)).
constructed first, it would illustrate that the range To conclude, human emergence in the uni-
of phenomena that it could help explain and place verse might be the inevitable result of a fractal-
in a unifying light stretches not only from multi- ization process governing the management of
ple phenomena to the universe itself but also to energy from one level to the next and the process
the child and to development of the child. That is, of development within humans might reflect the
if the five-step sequence in the generic change same dynamic, with my model offering the nature
model is compatible as a mechanistic explanation of the fractalization process involved. In this
of the origins of multiple phenomena that func- sense, humans are indeed the children of the uni-
tion as open systems subject to nonlinear dynam- verse. Moreover, because of this, studying the
ical change sequences, including the level of the development of the child offers a window to the
universe, then its applicability to the level of the origins of the universe.
child is not only not surprising but also quite
exemplary of the processes involved.
Carrying this argument one step further, the References
implication is that the common fractalization
process that helps in the elegant, efficient trans- Barkley, R. A. (2012). Executive functions: What they are,
formation of the disordered nature of dissipative how they work, and why they evolved. New York:
Guilford Press.
energy flow into increasing order and graceful Baumeister, R. F. (2008). Free will in scientific psychol-
accommodation reaches from the grandest scales ogy. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 3,
to the minutest, and the change processes in the 14–19.
child is a middle level in the self-similarities Boyatzis, R. E. (2006). An overview of intentional change
from a complexity perspective. Journal of Management
over different orders in the fractalization pro- Development, 25, 607–623.
cesses in the different micro to macro levels of Boyatzis, R. E. (2008). Leadership development from a
the universe. That is, the sequence of steps of complexity perspective. Consulting Psychology
coordination, hierarchization, systematization, Journal: Practice and Research, 60, 298–313.
Case, R. (1992). The mind’s staircase. Hillsdale, NJ:
multiplication, and integration, [as underwritten Erlbaum.
by a parallel sequence of changes in attractor Chen, Y., & Fang, M. Q. (2008). A five-stage model for
organization (cyclical, chaotic, gravitating to the the evolvement of complex system, apocalypse and
cusp of change, multiple attractors in a complex prospect from research on emergence. Xitong
Gongcheng Lilun Yu Shijian/System Engineering
adaptive system, superordinate in this regard)] Theory and Practice, 28, 40–44.
that I found in child development based on analy- Darwin, C. (1871). The descent of man, and selection in
sis of the empirical descriptions made by Piaget relation to sex. London: John Murray.
of cognitive development in the substages of the Dodge, K. A., Godwin, J., & The Conduct Problems
Prevention Research Group. (2013). Social-
sensorimotor stage has served me in construct- information-processing patterns mediate the impact of
ing a generic model that I applied not only to preventive intervention on adolescent antisocial
prior and subsequent stages in the sequence of behavior. Psychological Science, 24, 456–465.
stages in my Neo-Piagetian cognitive model but Donald, M. (1991). Origins of the modern mind: Three
stages in the evolution of culture and cognition.
also to other systems, including nonliving ones. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Also, these systems might have components Dunbar, R. I. M. (2013). An evolutionary basis for social
that go through the same five-step sequence, as cognition. In M. Legerstee, D. W. Haley, & M. H.
830 33 Generic Change Model

Bornstein (Eds.), The infant mind: Origins of the Mithen, S. (1996). The prehistory of the mind: The cogni-
social brain (pp. 3–19). New York: Guilford Press. tive origins of art and science. London, UK: Thames
Dyck, L. R., & Lovelace, K. J. (2012). Finding a fit with and Hudson.
fitness: Applying intentional change theory in work- Norcross, J. C., Krebs, P. M., & Prochaska, J. O. (2011).
site health promotion programming. Journal of Stages of change. In J. C. Norcross (Ed.),
Workplace Behavioral Health, 27, 12–31. Psychotherapy relationships that work: Evidence-
Eldakar, M. T., & Wilson, D. S. (2011). Eight criticisms based responsiveness (2nd ed., pp. 279–300).
not to make about group selection. Evolution, 65, New York: Oxford University Press.
1523–1526. Nowak, M. A. (2012). Evolving cooperation. Journal of
Feist, G. J. (2004). Domain-specific creativity in the phys- Theoretical Biology, 299, 1–8.
ical sciences. In J. C. Kaufman & J. Baer (Eds.), Nowak, M. A., Tarnita, C. E., & Wilson, E. O. (2010). The
Creativity across domains: Faces of the muse evolution of eusociality. Nature, 466, 1057–1062.
(pp. 123–137). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Parker, S. T., & McKinney, M. L. (1999). Origins of intel-
Feist, G. J. (2006). The psychology of science and the ori- ligence: The evolution of cognitive development in
gins of the scientific mind. New Haven, CT: Yale monkeys, apes, and humans. Baltimore, MD: Johns
University Press. Hopkins University Press.
Fischer, K. W. (1980). A theory of cognitive development: Paxton, R. O. (1998). The five stages of fascism. The
The control and construction of hierarchies of skills. Journal of Modern History, 70, 1–23.
Psychological Review, 87, 477–531. Peschl, M. F., & Fundneider, T. (2014). Evolving the
Galinsky, A. D., Maddux, W. W., Gilin, D., & White, J. D. future by learning from the future (as it emerges)?
(2008). Why it pays to get inside the head of your Toward an epistemology of change. Behavioral and
opponent: The differential effects of perspective tak- Brain Sciences, 37, 433–434.
ing and empathy in negotiations. Psychological Piaget, J., & Garcia, R. (1989). Psychogenesis and the
Science, 19, 378–384. history of science. New York: Columbia University
Harter, S. (2012). Emerging self-processes during child- Press.
hood and adolescence. In M. R. Leary & J. P. Tangney Prochaska, J. O., DiClemente, C. C., & Norcross, J. C.
(Eds.), Handbook of self and identity (2nd ed., (1992). In search of how people change: Applications
pp. 680–715). New York: Guilford Press. to addictive behaviors. American Psychologist, 47,
Heatherton, T. F., & Wagner, D. D. (2011). Cognitive neu- 1102–1114.
roscience of self-regulation failure. Trends in Prochaska, J. O., Norcross, J. C., & DiClemente, C. C.
Cognitive Sciences, 15, 132–139. (1994). Changing for good: The revolutionary program
Henzi, P., de Sousa Pereira, L., Hawker-Bond, D., Stiller, that explains the six stages of change and teaches you
J., Dunbar, R. I. M., & Barrett, L. (2007). Look who’s how to free yourself from bad habits. New York: Morrow.
talking: Developmental trends in the size of conversa- Rand, D. G., & Nowak, M. A. (2013). Human coopera-
tional cliques. Evolution and Human Behavior, 28, tion. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 17, 413–425.
66–74. Roberts, S. B. G., & Dunbar, R. I. M. (2011).
Hill, R. A., & Dunbar, R. I. M. (2003). Social network size Communication in social networks: Effects of kinship,
in humans. Human Nature, 14, 53–72. network size, and emotional closeness. Personal
Hunt, J. H. (2012). A conceptual model for the origin of Relationships, 18, 439–452.
worker behaviour and adaptation of eusociality. Rostow, W. W. (1990). The stages of economic growth:
Journal of Evolutionary Biology, 25, 1–19. A non-communist manifesto. New York: Cambridge
Inzlicht, M., & Schmeichel, B. J. (2012). What is ego University Press.
depletion? Toward a mechanistic revision of the Sabelli, H. (2005). Bios: A study of creation. Singapore:
resource model of self-control. Perspectives on World Scientific.
Psychological Science, 7, 450–463. Salthe, S. N. (2007). The natural philosophy of work.
Inzlicht, M., & Schmeichel, B. J. (2013). Beyond simple Entropy, 9, 83–99.
utility in predicting self-control fatigue: A proximate Sauer, U., Heinemann, M., & Zamboni, N. (2007). Getting
alternative to the opportunity cost model. Behavioral closer to the whole picture. Science, 316, 593–597.
and Brain Sciences, 36, 695–696. Scharmer, C. O. (2007). Theory U. leading from the future
Kurzban, R., Duckworth, A., Kable, J. W., & Myers, as it emerges. The social technology of presencing.
J. (2013a). An opportunity cost model of subjective Paper presented at a meeting of the Society for
effort and task performance. Behavioral and Brain Organization Learning.
Sciences, 36, 661–679. Sharpless, B. A., & Barber, J. P. (2009). A conceptual and
Kurzban, R., Duckworth, A., Kable, J. W., & Myers, empirical review of the meaning, measurement, devel-
J. (2013b). Cost-benefit models as the next, best option opment, and teaching of intervention competence in
for understanding subjective effort. Behavioral and clinical psychology. Clinical Psychology Review, 29,
Brain Sciences, 36, 707–726. 47–56.
Maddox, J. E. (1995). Yes, people can change, but can Sloman, S. (2005). Causal models: How people think
psychotherapists? Contemporary Psychology, 40, about the world and its alternatives. New York:
1047–1048. Oxford University Press.
References 831

Sober, E., & Wilson, D. S. (2011). Adaptation and natural Young, G. (2008). Causality and causation in law, medi-
selection revisited. Journal of Evolutionary Biology, cine, psychiatry, and psychology: Progression or regres-
24, 462–468. sion? Psychological Injury and Law, 1, 161–181.
Sporns, O. (2011). Networks of the brain. Cambridge, Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
MA: MIT Press. Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science +
Sporns, O. (2012). Discovering the human connectome. Business Media.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feigning, and response
Stiller, J., & Dunbar, R. (2007). Perspective-taking and bias in psychiatric/psychological injury: Implications
social network size in humans. Social Networks, 29, for practice and court. Dordrecht, Netherlands:
93–104. Springer Science + Business Media.
Wagner, D. D., & Heatherton, T. F. (2013). Self-regulatory Zadek, S. (2004). The path to corporate responsibility.
depletion increases emotional reactivity in the amyg- Harvard Business Review, 82, 125–132.
dala. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience, 8, Zelazo, P. D. (2004). The development of conscious control
410–417. in childhood. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8, 12–17.
Wilson, D. S., Hayes, S. C., Biglan, A., & Embry, D. D. Zhou, W.-X., Sornette, D., Hill, R. A., & Dunbar, R. I. M.
(2014). Evolving the future: Toward a science of (2005). Discrete hierarchical organization of social
intentional change. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, group sizes. Proceedings of the Royal Society:
37, 395–460. B. Biological Sciences, 272, 439–444.
Revising Maslow
34

that the revised Neo-Maslovian model that I have


Chapter Introduction created especially is an embodied one.
The beginning of the chapter continues with
Maslow’s (1943) hierarchical model of needs, elaborations by Blatt and colleagues and Ryan
motivation, and development is one of the most and colleagues on their seminal models on self/
well-known in psychology. In Young (2011), I personality. Blatt (2008) had proposed a duality
modified it so that its five levels correspond to the in experience model and Ryan, Deci, and col-
five stages of my Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian leagues’ one with tripartite distinctions.
model. In the present chapter, once more, I mod- Further, I develop the concepts of “psycho-
ify this Maslovian approach to needs, motivation, logical completeness” and “psychological com-
and development by considering, in particular, pleting” as involved in the apex of human self
recent work on moral and foundational motives and personality development. The concepts con-
(Haidt, Janoff-Bulman and colleagues, e.g., stitute good complements to those of Maslow
Haidt, 2012; Janoff-Bulman & Carnes, 2013) and and Erikson (self-actualization, generativity,
on motivation (Forbes, 2011). The main difficul- respectively).
ties related to these sources concern their lack of In revising the Neo-Maslovian model,
developmental factors. Maslow’s model itself I reworked those of Haidt, Janoff-Bulman, and
had a developmental component only as a sec- Forbes. In each case, I showed how their models
ondary aspect. can be revised to fit the current one. In particular,
Maslow’s model focuses on self-actualization, I rework their models from a developmental
but in Young (2011), I revised his model by framework. For example, in this regard,
incorporating Blatt’s (2008) model of self- I reworked Haidt’s model of moral foundations
definition and relatedness. Motivations and needs (which alternatively has been described as being
would seem to require both a self- and other- constituted by four, five, or six foundations), to
focus. In the present revision of this model, I arrive at a five-foundation one, but with varia-
include a third component to needs and motives, tions for the personal, interpersonal, and environ-
that of the material environmental world. This mental spheres, and one consistent with the
approach is consistent with the work on Deci and present five-step developmental sequence.
Ryan (e.g., 1991), who add a competence factor Janoff-Bulman and Carnes’ (2013) moral motive
to their equivalent model. model also integrates into the present model.
The present chapter begins by describing When referring to the motivational component of
Kyselo’s (2014) enactive-based self model. This my model, I use the terminology of “foundational
prepares the way for the chapter’s conclusions moral motives” to indicate the integration that

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 833


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_34
834 34 Revising Maslow

I undertook of the prior work of Haidt, Janoff- deployed or characterize behavior. In this regard,
Bulman, and colleagues. the basic needs level in Maslow would carry for-
The chapter concludes with presentation of a ward and still constitute relevant psychological
questionnaire that I developed on political atti- function in a yoking process even as the highest-
tudes. It concerns societal control, in general. order levels of the model of self (self-
Moreover, it allows for independent response on a actualization, generativity, etc.) are active in
Likert scale for conservative and liberal attitudes, behavior. That is, even the most abstract of
rather than considering them as polar opposites. behavioral function potentially carries with it the
most basic physical (and for cognition, senso-
rimotor), enactive function.
Models

Revised Maslow in Young (2011) Re-Revising Maslow


in the Present Book
Model Young’s (2011) Neo-Maslovian model
organizes Maslow’s hierarchical needs model into Later in the chapter, I argue that the Neo-
a developmental one that shows that it parallels Maslovian model that I have developed could be
Young’s Neo-Piagetian and Neo-Eriksonian mod- revised even further by adding a third component
els. To review, the cognitive stage portion of my to the self, that of a competent, material environ-
model is Neo-Piagetian, and I describe five cogni- mental one. We relate not only to ourselves and
tive stages (reflexive, sensorimotor, periopera- to others, but also to the environment and objects.
tional [pre-operational and concrete operational], As we shall see, this addition to the model is
formal abstract, and postformal collective intelli- based on the work of Deci, Ryan, Forbes, and
gence), with each stage having cyclically recur- others, but stands apart from them, as well.
ring substages. Moreover, each of the 25 steps in
the model (5 stages × 5 substages) witnesses a
corresponding development of a Neo-Eriksonian Enaction
level (also 25, Erikson’s 8 and 17 others fitted to
the model). As for my Neo-Maslovian model, I Model Kyselo (2014) presented an enactive
showed how Maslow’s five hierarchical needs model of the self that combines together the social
map onto my five Neo-Piagetian stages, therefore, as constitutive, the individual as locus of the self,
with five developmental steps implicated in the and the embodied perspective of the body as
each level of the hierarchical needs model, as well mediator of a unified self. For Kyselo, the self-
(see Fig. 32.2, in Chap. 32). identity individuates through the process of self-
Further, in Young (2011), I showed how distinction and also the process of participation
Maslow’s model should include two components with others. Body, self, and sociality are interre-
related to the self (self-definitional and related- lated. We are at once embodied beings and situ-
ness, as per Blatt’s (2008) concept of polarities of ated social beings; we cannot be reduced from our
experience). In this regard, for each of the steps constitutiveness among these components in our
in the development of hierarchical needs in identity to our brain. As we develop, we move
Maslow, one should consider the growth that from basic sensorimotor cognition to forms that
takes place in each of these self components. are psychologically and socially mediated. The
body and brain change in status as they become
Comment In Young (2011), I also developed both the means and mediator of the self, becom-
the concept of yoking, in which earlier develop- ing matrices of an enacted social reality. At the
mental levels might stay in function and carry same time, body and brain are the seats of the
forward (albeit modified) as other levels are imprint of the social on the person. The external
Models 835

world is not independent of the self and, recipro- Taken together, both Kyselo’s unified model
cally, selves are not independent of the external of self and also my work that is consistent with it
word. The body-social split (essentialist) problem (e.g., in my Neo-Maslovian model of
is resolved by not only seeing the plurality of self self-development, Young, 2011) afford a more
but also by seeing the synthesis of its whole. holistic understanding of the self. However,
Kyselo continued that identity refers to self- because I have integrated Blatt’s (2008) work
generated, self-determined autonomy, a coherent into my own, I have provided the basis for a
unity co-constituted with interacting others in developmental account of self-development that
the social world. The self is embodied in bodily fits and elaborates Kyselo’s (2014) account.
processes (i.e., sensorimotor structure, Gallese, Development is not separate from any behavior,
2014). Also, it is intersubjective, yet supported and needs to be understood as the primary consti-
by the body’s mechanisms (e.g., mirror neurons, tuting force of any behavior. The body-self model
Gallese, 2013). Identity is constituted by an inter- elaborated by Kyselo (2014) is complementary to
connected network of processes that serves to my own, which should be considered a develop-
protect the self from both dissolution and isola- mental enactive approach to the self and, there-
tion. The body is part of the interface involved in fore, a broadening one of Kyselo’s (2014) work.
organizing social life. Autonomy is socially
enacted, and social enaction participates in the
co-construction of an individuating, identifying, Polarities of Experience
embodying self.
The process that promotes this reciprocating Model Luyten and Blatt (2013) elaborated Blatt’s
mutuality between self and other lies in individu- (2008) model of the self on polarities of experi-
ation “through and from the world.” It promotes ence, which involves interpersonal relatedness and
emancipation, but one still predicated on the con- self-definition. The duality compares to similar
straints of bodily, self, and social processes. We models, such as Bakan’s (1966) one of commu-
are “needful,” and social, yet in search of eman- nion and agency and Deci and Ryan’s (2013) one
cipatory freedom. Adaptive regulation involves of relatedness and autonomy/competence. In their
finding balance in our yearning for distinctive- article, Luyten and Blatt (2013) extended the
ness and for connection in participation. model to disruptions in personality development.
They developed a prototype approach to personal-
Comment This approach taken by Kyselo ity disorder related to dependence and self-critical
(2014) on a unifying concept of the self in the dimensions of personality organization derived
“body social” is a coherent one. However, she from Blatt’s (2008) model.
does not treat much the developmental dimen-
sion, although mentioning it briefly. Her work is Comment However, other work has extended
consistent with mine in several major ways. First, Blatt and colleagues work beyond a polarity in
she seeks a unified account of the self that experience to a tripartite distinction. The model
includes the embodied, dynamic perspective. developed in the present chapter is consistent
Second, she emphasizes its social nature. Third, with the latter approach. That being said, I have
she argues for a mutuality in these currents, lead- undertaken this development in a unique way, as
ing to an integrated whole. Fourth, her concept of shall be shown below.
distinction and participation as two coordinated
poles in her unified perspective of the self is con-
sistent with the work of Blatt (2008), on which I Self-Determination
have based my Neo-Maslovian model. Fifth, we
would both agree that emancipating toward a Model Weinstein, Przybylski, and Ryan (2013)
sense of freedom is central to psychological explored the question of unified self-functioning or
growth, but there are constraints, including of personality integration. The concept of the integra-
needs (which is consistent with Maslow, as well). tive process in self/personality psychology dates to
836 34 Revising Maslow

Freud (1927/1961) and includes Rogers (1963). Neo-Maslovian model, but helps add an additional
Ryan and Deci (2000, 2008) have developed self- component. As integration takes place in the
determination theory (SDT), in which internaliza- developing person, a concept that could be used to
tion and integration constitute fundamental processes reflect the integration involved is “psychological
involved (a) in attaining vitality and energy, good completeness.” Given that the process is dynami-
health and wellness, and relational benefits and (b) cal and ongoing, I also refer to “psychological
in promoting autonomous, personal-value, and life- completing.” These terms allow differentiation of
goal congruent behavior, leading to a sense of the terms: (a) integration in the SDT sense; (b) ego
authenticity and full-life engagement. integrity, the last stage in development in Erikson’s
Weinstein et al. (2013) identified three subpro- model; and (c) integration as the last step in devel-
cesses or facets that are involved in unified self/ opment in Young’s (2011) model. Approaching/
personality integration. They include: (a) aware- achieving a sense of psychological completing/
ness (access to self-knowledge; Brown & Ryan, completeness would constitute a continual, life-
2003); (b) personal ownership/autonomy (taking long developmental process. It should reach the
responsibility/identifying with one’s attitudes/ peak in the sense of being psychologically mature
actions or emotions/decisions/thoughts; Weinstein, and wise when it is properly promoted in the envi-
Deci, & Ryan, 2011); and (c) nondefensive pro- ronment (at least in a biologically-predisposed and
cessing (approach-related coping avoidance or healthy individual), which would dynamically
defensive blocking of self-knowledge into con- lead further to an ingrained health and wellness, as
sciousness; Weinstein, Brown, & Ryan, 2009). described by Weinstein et al. (2013).
In terms of factors that promote integration in Note that I have not adopted outright Deci and
life, early on, unconditional regard is important Ryan’s approach to self/personality in my own
and, later in life, autonomy-supportive social model. It stands as one influence only in this
environments help (Weinstein et al., 2012). As regard. Generally, the new work in Weinstein
for associations with the brain, research with et al. (2013) is informative, but does not address
fMRI (functional magnetic resonance imaging) well Blatt’s (2008) emphasis on relatedness to
has linked autonomous activity with the insular accompany self-definition, which is the theoreti-
cortex (Lee, Reeve, Xue, & Xiong, 2012). cal model that is at the basis of my revision of
Similarly, Legault and Inzlicht (2012) have found Maslow.
that integration-related processes in self-
regulation were reflected in electroencephalo-
graphic event-related potentials, leading them to Moral Motives
discuss the “self-determined brain.”
Thagard and Wood (2015) proposed a similar Model Janoff-Bulman and Carnes (2013) pre-
tripartite-self model involving representation, sented a model of moral motives, and they
effecting, and changing. The representing self addressed the issue of differences in the motiva-
involves self-depicting (to self, to others), such as tional base of people judged as liberal or conser-
in their people’s self concepts and self- vative (see Fig. 34.1). They defined morality as a
presentation. The effecting self concerns self system of rules and behavioral regulation to
enhancement/limitation (e.g., self-regulation). facilitate and coordinate optimal social living or
The changing self is more long term (about self group living. Traditionally, it is concerned with
development, expansions). The authors described justice and rights (e.g., Kohlberg, 1981, 1984).
the self as a multilevel system. Its range is being broadened to include moral
foundations or motives (Haidt, 2007, 2008; Haidt
Comment The work by Deci, Ryan, and col- & Kesebir, 2010).
leagues in their SDT model is noteworthy for Janoff-Bulman and Carnes (2013) presented
its emphasis on self and personality unification/ a model of moral motives based on two axes,
integration. It is consistent with the present revised one with two levels and one with three of
Models 837

Self Other Group


(Personal) (Interpersonal) (Collective)

Protect/ Social order/


Inhibition Self-restraint/
Do not harm Communal
(proscriptive Moderation
solidarity
regulation)

Provide/ Social justice/


Activation Communal
Industry Help be fair
(prescriptive responsibility
regulation)

Fig. 34.1 Model of moral motives according to mode influence is evident in the model of moral motives (in the
and target. Janoff-Bulman and colleagues have presented mode) and the targets of the activation/inhibition balance
a model of moral motives that focuses on protection/pro- in the motives might be self, other, or group (focus). Note.
scription/inhibition vs. provision/prescription/activation The model constitutes one that expands the traditional
in conjunction with the targets of self, other, and group. It duality of experience approach (Blatt, 2008) into three tar-
is consistent with the present emphasis that activation/ gets (personal, interpersonal, collective). Adapted from
inhibition coordination is a common metric organizing Janoff-Bulman and Carnes (2013)
brain and behavior (Young, 2011). An activation/inhibition

them—proscriptive/prescriptive moral regulation based on avoidance, and it deals with what should
and self/other/group focus (personal, interper- not be done, as well as dealing with restraint, over-
sonal, collective, respectively; e.g., Brewer & coming temptation, protecting from harm, and
Gardner, 1996; Gilbert, Fiske, & Gardner, 1998; inhibition. Prescriptive morality is based on acti-
see Fig. 34.1). They considered self-restraint/ vation, what should be done, providing for well-
moderation and industriousness as proscriptive being, and helping. This dual system of moral
and prescriptive moral motives, respectively. The regulation parallels parental behavior in instilling
classic motives of not harming and helping were do’s and don’ts (e.g., do toy clean up; do not do
considered the equivalent interpersonal motives, that, respectively; Aksan & Kochanska, 2005;
and the group motives already mentioned, social Kochanska, 2002).
order and social justice, were considered the Proscriptive moral regulation is condemna-
equivalent group ones in their model. tory and stricter relative to prescriptive moral
A predominant perspective on behavioral self- regulation, which is commendatory. These moral
regulation involves dual regulation by approach/ regulatory patterns fit the general negativity bias
activation vs. avoidance/inhibition (Carver & that is considered important in moving people to
Scheier, 2008). The behavioral inhibition system behave (Baumeister, Brataslavsky, Finkenauer,
is an aversive motivational one based in avoid- & Vohs, 2001); that is, there is greater motiva-
ance and in sensitivity to negative outcomes/pun- tional potency when outcomes are negative com-
ishment. The behavioral activation system is an pared to positive. In this regard, the difference
appetitive motivation one based in approach and between prescriptive vs. proscriptive morality
in sensitivity to rewards/positive outcomes. reflects the philosophical positions of deontology
Janoff-Bulman and colleagues applied the dif- vs. consequentialism. The former involves strict
ference between the approach/activation and mandatory rules and is associated with proscrip-
avoidance/inhibition self-regulation systems to the tive morality; whereas the latter focuses on the
difference between proscriptive and prescriptive consequences of moral acts, so is discretionary
morality (Janoff-Bulman, 2012; Janoff-Bulman, and utilitarian (the greatest good for the most
Sheikh, & Hepp, 2009). Proscriptive morality is people), and thus fits the prescriptive approach.
838 34 Revising Maslow

There are two evolutionary views of moral (e) purity. The types of corresponding evil
regulation. The traditional view is that altruism is involve, respectively, (a) cruelty/violence, (b)
undertaken for selfish reasons (e.g., Hamilton, racism/oppression, (c) traitors/out-group, (d)
1964). More contemporary versions consider that anarchists/revolutionaries, and (e) atheists/hedo-
altruism at least partly reflects group selection in nists. In general in this chapter, I refer to the
a multi-level selection model (e.g., Wilson, model as one on foundational motives.
2012). Constraining selfishness involves pro- Haidt’s moral foundation model lists two indi-
scriptive moral regulation. In contrast, tapping vidualizing contractual approaches to society—
altruistic motivation involves prescriptive moral harm/care and fairness/reciprocity (see Table 34.2,
regulation. A proscriptive virtue might be gener- Foundations of Intuitive Ethics). As well, it
osity, whereas a proscriptive one might be self- includes three binding foundations about group-
discipline. A proscriptive vice might be greed, ing people—in-group/loyalty, authority/respect,
and a prescriptive one might be apathy (Carnes & and purity/sanctity. Haidt (2012) added Liberty as
Janoff-Bulman, 2012). a moral foundation, which appears individualiz-
ing (see Table 34.3, which gives my revision of
Comment Later in the chapter, I analyze the Haidt’s approach to purity/ sanctity). Haidt
moral motive approach of Janoff-Bulman and extended with colleagues this model to moral dif-
colleagues in relation to development. Just as ferences in liberals and conservatives (e.g.,
Maslow’s model of hierarchical needs is develop- Graham et al., 2011). According to them, liberals
mental and can be mapped onto my own develop- value the individualizing moral foundations,
mental model, so can the work on moral motives. whereas conservatives value the binding ones.
In this regard, Janoff-Bulman and Carnes seem to Moreover, provocatively, they argued that liberals
have a developmental movement in their pro- rely on only the individualizing ones, unlike
scriptive/prescriptive axis, with the prospective conservatives, who value all five foundations.
one emerging first in development. Janoff-Bulman and Carnes (2013) took issue
with Haidt’s work at several levels. First, they
argued that moral motives include self ones, such
Moral Foundations as self-restraint, and not just individualizing (or
interpersonal) and binding (or group) ones.
Model Graham and Haidt (2012) listed five Second, the motives can be classified according
foundations of evil based on Haidt and Joseph’s to their proscriptive or prescriptive orientation.
(2004) five innate psychological foundations of Third, the Haidt model excludes a relevant group
moral systems (see Table 34.1). The moral foun- motive, that of social justice/communal responsi-
dations involve (a) harm (or its avoidance), (b) bility. Using Janoff-Bulman’s terms, the latter is
fairness, (c) in-group behavior, (d) authority, and prescriptive, in contrast to another one—social

Table 34.1 Five moral/ethical foundations/sources and associated sacred values and types of evil
Dimension
Foundation/source Sacred value Type of evil
Harm Nurturance/care, peace Cruelty/violence
Fairness Justice, reciprocity Racism/oppression
In-group Loyalty, group self-sacrifice Treachery/out-group
Authority Respect/tradition, honor Anarchism/revolution
Purity Chastity/piety, self-control Atheism/hedonism
Adopted from Graham and Haidt (2012)
Note. Variously, Haidt and colleagues have described four, five, and six moral/ethical foundations.
The first four in this table appear constant to the different versions. The two poles of sacred values and
evil are not the same as in the original formulations, adding to them
Models 839

Table 34.2 Foundations of intuitive ethics


Foundations
Axes Harm/care Fairness/reciprocity In-group/loyalty Authority/respect
Adaptive challenge Protect and care for Reap benefits of two-way Reap benefits of Negotiate
young, vulnerable, or cooperation with non-kin group cooperation hierarchy, defer
injured kin (e.g., selectively
offspring)
Proper domain Suffering, distress, Cheating, cooperation, Threat or challenge Signs of
(adaptive triggers) or threat to one’s kin deception to group dominance and
(e.g., expressed by an submission
offspring)
Actual domain Newborn seals, Romantic partner fidelity, Sports teams Bosses, respected
(examples of modern attractive cartoon vending machines that do one roots for, professionals
triggers) characters not work community cohesion
Characteristic Compassion Anger, gratitude, guilt Group pride, Respect, fear
emotions belongingness;
rage at a traitor
Relevant virtues Caring, kindness Fairness, justice, honesty, Loyalty, patriotism, Obedience,
(and vices) (cruelty) trustworthiness (dishonesty) self-sacrifice (treason, deference
cowardice) (disobedience,
uppitiness)
Adopted from Haidt and Joseph (2007) and adapted from Haidt (2012). Adopted by permission of Oxford University
Press. Haidt, J., & Joseph, C. (2007). The moral mind: How five sets of innate intuitions guide the development of many
culture-specific virtues, and perhaps even modules. In P. Carruthers, S. Laurence, & S. Stich (Eds.), The innate mind:
Volume 3: Foundations and the future (pp. 367–392). New York: Oxford University Press. Reprinted by permission of
Oxford University Press, USA. [Table 19.1, Page 382]
Note. In this work on four of the original foundations by Haidt and colleagues, they are described along axes related to
adaptation, triggers, and emotions/values. It excludes sanctity/degradation, which later was described as involving
purity/sanctity

order/communal solidarity—which is proscrip- respectively). The reader should note that both
tive. The former is associated with liberalism and models under discussion have separated interper-
the latter with conservatism, whereas both are sonal focus from group/social focus, while
associated with individualizing and binding Janoff-Bulman and Carnes have added a focus
moral foundations. In this regard, developmental that is on the self.
research is finding parallels in parental attitude
early in life and later political ideology (Fraley,
Griffin, Belsky, & Roisman, 2012; Janoff- Integrated Motivations
Bulman, Carnes, & Sheikh, 2014).
Model Forbes (2011) constructed a model of
Comment Although the model by Janoff- motivation built on prior models. Motivation, or
Bulman and Carnes (2013) on moral motives the motor/driver of behavior, is an important
addresses some of the concerns presented by causal construct of human action, emotion, and
Haidt’s one, both models are missing some thought, and stretches back to the roots of con-
important aspects, especially a developmental temporary study of psychology (e.g., Freud,
framework. In this regard, Haidt might have a 1933; Maslow, 1943). Forbes viewed motiva-
developmental component within each of his tions as emergent psychological phenomena
individualizing and binding foundations, given deriving from a biological substrate (Table 34.3).
that they first list, respectively, harm/care and in- Forbes (2011) categorized the emotions into a
group/loyalty compared to more advanced types grid of nine blocks that involved two change
(e.g., fairness/reciprocity and authority/respect, axes—focus of aspiration (change where) and
840 34 Revising Maslow

Table 34.3 Other foundations of intuitive ethics


Foundations
Purity/sanctity (Haidt
Axes & Joseph, 2007) Purity/sanctity Liberty (Haidt, 2012)
Adaptive challenge Avoid microbes Participate in spirituality/giving of Living in small groups
and parasites self for common good without where one might
(contaminants) anticipation of reward, but without encounter domination,
self-harm, too bullying/constraint
Proper domain Waste products, Improve lot of other/group; Signs of attempted
(adaptive triggers) with disease people betterment of relationships, social domination/aggressive
surround, community/culture, etc., control
which acts to increase sense of
psychological maturity, wisdom, flow,
presence, etc. [and which in turn acts
to increase motive to help others]
Actual domain Taboo ideas (fascism, More than suffering/distress/threat; Rise of a (would-be)
(examples of communism, racism) rather bootstrap other/group for the dominator/political abuse
modern triggers) better and help them do the same; be
inspired/inspire
Characteristic Having disgust Serenity, peace Righteous/group unifying
emotions anger/hatred of oppression
Relevant virtues Showing temperance, Respect of other/role modeling; Freedom fighter/revolution
(and vices) chastity, piety, allows helping of others to help against tyranny
cleanliness (lust, themselves (a sanctuary) (disrespect)
intemperance)
Adopted from Haidt and Joseph (2007) and adapted from Haidt (2012). Adopted by permission of Oxford University
Press. Haidt, J., & Joseph, C. (2007). The moral mind: How five sets of innate intuitions guide the development of many
culture-specific virtues, and perhaps even modules. In P. Carruthers, S. Laurence, & S. Stich (Eds.), The innate mind:
Volume 3: Foundations and the future (pp. 367–392). New York: Oxford University Press. Reprinted by permission of
Oxford University Press, USA. [Table 19.1, Page 382]
Note. I created the second purity/sanctity foundation. Haidt had described it in terms mixing physical purity needs, and
emotions/concepts. In my version, I focused on spirituality/giving/helping, which is a quite different approach

Table 34.4 Framework of human motivations according to focus and level of aspiration
Focus
Enhancing in the level Intrapersonal (self context) Instrumental (material context) Interpersonal (social context)
Expectations (being) Security Empowering Belonging
Experiences (doing) Identity Engaging Nurturing
Outcomes (having) Mastering Achieving Esteem
Adopted from Forbes (2011)
Note. The model does not consider development to a sufficient degree, and has been modified accordingly

level of aspiration (type of change). The former Comment It should be noted that Forbes (2011)
included the categories of “intrapsychic” (e.g., framed his model developmentally as a macro-
sense of self), “instrumental” (e.g., relation to the developmental stage-like movement across the
material world), and interpersonal (e.g., on social three realms of focus of aspiration—from (a) self
relationships; see Table 34.4). Levels of aspira- to (b) material world to (c) social world. In this
tion included: (a) change in potential/expectation; regard, he referred to Piaget (1937; Piaget &
(b) change in process/experience; and (c) change Inhelder, 1967). However, I will show that it
in outcomes/evaluation. Deci and Ryan (1991, is more likely that the stage-like macro-
1995) elaborated a triarchic model of innate, uni- developmental pathway should concern his axis
versal needs similar to that of Forbes (the need for of level of aspiration, that is, (a) enhanced expec-
autonomy, competence, and relatedness). tations, (b) experiences, and (c) outcomes (which
Revising the Maslow Revision 841

he considered a micro-developmental sequence Finally, referring to his instrumental progres-


rather than a macro-developmental one). sion, in order to arrive at a consistency across the
intrapsychic and instrumental domains, it would
Model As mentioned, Forbes (2011) described appear that the survival level should be placed
his unified motivational model in terms of nine at the beginning of the intrapsychic progression,
motivational domains formed by the intersection and also should be matched by an early devel-
of the axes of focus and level of aspiration. The oping action/approach or exploration/curiosity
intrapsychic triad include: (a) security (e.g., one in the instrumental progression. Also, note
Maslow, 1943, 1955, 1967; and also Bowlby, that, macro-developmentally, engagement and
1969/1999; and Erikson, 1959); (b) identity (e.g., empowerment should be switched in position in
Erikson, 1979); and (c) mastery (e.g., self- that engagement should precede empowerment.
actualization; Maslow, 1943). The three instru- In his integrative motivational model, Forbes
mental motivations concern: (a) empowerment (2011) contrasted self, social world, and material
(e.g., self-efficacy; Bandura, 1977, 1986, 1997; world motives. This tripartite distinction could
Murray, 1938); (b) engagement (e.g., Murray, help or organize better the prior models on moti-
1938); and (c) achievement (e.g., McClelland, vations and needs. I note that Janoff-Bulman also
1961). As for the interpersonal motivation triplet, had a tripartite distinction in her work. It was
it concerns (a) belonging (e.g., James, 1890/1950; related to personal, interpersonal, and group foci,
Mead, 1934); (b) nurturance (Bowlby, 1969/1999, but not environmental ones. A model that more
1979); and (c) self-esteem (e.g., Maslow, 1943). closely resembles that of Forbes is the one of Deci
and Ryan (2013) in which autonomy, relatedness,
Comment Given my stage model in Young and competence are included. Competence, or
(2011; see Table 31.1 in Chap. 31), and examin- mastery, might parallel functioning well in the
ing directly Erikson’s and Maslow’s original environment, for example
models, it appears that the movement in Forbes
(2011) in the intrapsychic realm for level of aspi-
ration from—security to identity to mastery (e.g., Revising the Maslow Revision
self-actualization)—fits a macro, stage-like
developmental progression. Moreover, in this Introduction
sense, the motivations of Forbes’ interpersonal
realm complement that progression more than a The different models on the self in relation to
micro-developmental one. For example, belong- motivation, morals, and development that have
ing would seem to emerge before identity and been reviewed have helped me revise my prior
nurturing after it, as found in Young (2011), and revision of Maslow (Young, 2011; see Fig. 34.2).
Forbes’ esteem appears analogous to identity. In that model, basically, I had divided the classic
Also, referring to Maslow (1943), who con- Maslovian model of five hierarchical needs into
sidered his hierarchical needs model a develop- self-definitional and relatedness components.
mental one, there appears to be missing from Below, I give the rational for a third component to
Forbes’ progression, whether in terms of focus or the revised Neo-Maslovian model. Then, I pro-
level of aspiration, a survival-related motivation pose the five foundational moral motives that seem
at the beginning. Moreover, his closing mastering associated with each of the five hierarchical needs,
level for the intrapsychic self might be best and how they vary over the three components of
reserved for his instrumental, material-world pro- the model. Before proceeding to these steps in my
gression, with the label of self-actualization used theorizing, I indicate the assumptions that I used as
instead of mastery for this intrapsychic level. I developed the revised Neo-Maslovian model.
842 34 Revising Maslow

Communal
Communal (Supra)
(Supra) Psychological
Collective Completeness/
Intelligences Completing/
Integrity/
Integrating

Self- Environmental Relatedness-


Definitional (Ecological) Self Self
Actualizing Eco-Mastery Actualizing
Generativity Actualizing Generativity
(Intrapersonal) Generativity (Interpersonal,
(Extrapersonal) Group)

Self-Definitional Environmental Relatedness-Self


Identity Self- (Ecological) Self Identity Self-
Esteem Identity Self- Esteem
(Intrapersonal) Esteem (Interpersonal,
Achievement Group)
Self-Definitional Environmental Relatedness-Self
Affiliative Initiative (Ecological) Self Affiliative Initiative
(Intrapersonal) Affiliative Initiative (Interpersonal, Group)
Empowerment

Self-Definitional Environmental Relatedness-Self


Safety/ Trust (Ecological) Self Safety/ Trust
(Intrapersonal) Safety/ Trust (Interpersonal, Group)
Engagement

Self-Definitional Environmental Relatedness-Self


Physiological Needs/ Survival (Ecological) Self Physiological Needs/ Reproduction
(Intrapersonal) Action/ Approach (Interpersonal, Group)
(Physiological
Needs/ Survival)

Fig. 34.2 Neo-Maslovian hierarchy of self-definitional, Erikson’s stages involved in each case. As for the most
relatedness self, and environmental self needs. The figure basic physiological level of needs, I referred to the
gives simplified terms for each of the revised motivational Darwinian concept of survival and reproduction, using the
needs in the combined model of Maslow (1943, 1970), latter for the personal component and the former for the
Erikson (1980), and Blatt (2008). The major revision enter- relatedness component. Note that the terms used to describe
tained of Maslow concerns dividing his different levels of the needs also refer to attachment theory for the safety level
needs in two components, depending on what part of the self and affiliation instead of love for the middle level (after
is involved. The left-hand column refers to the needs related Kenrick, Griskevicius, Neuberg, & Schaller, 2010).
to the personal self, while the right-hand column refers to The Piagetian component of the model adds an extra
the needs of the self in relationship. Blatt referred to polari- level at the peak to account for changes in cognition and
ties of experience in terms of self-definition and relatedness, behavior that would derive as the person transitions from
and I borrowed these terms for this aspect of the model. the formal to the postformal period, which I refer to as the
In addition, for this version of the Neo-Maslovian stage of collective intelligence (Young, 2011). Another
model in present book relative to the original revision in change made to the original Maslovian revision of the
Young (2011), I added a middle column related to a third hierarchy of needs model is that I included a superordi-
component of the person, or the mastery/competence nate level to the one of self-actualization and related psy-
instrumental/environment aspect of behavior. In particu- chological development, such as generativity. This new
lar, this aspect of the model is derived from Forbes (2011), partial level of the penultimate level in the model concerns
Deci and Ryan (1995), Haidt (2012), and Janoff-Bulman “psychological completeness,” which is partially akin to
and colleagues (e.g., Janoff-Bulman, 2009). Erikson’s ego integrity and which corresponds to the stage
As for Erikson’s model of eight stages in lifespan devel- of collective intelligence cognitively in my own model.
opment, there appear to be two stages in his model that cor- Adapted in part with permission from Springer Science +
respond to each of the four more advanced needs of Business Media. Young (2011); with kind permission
Maslow’s model. Therefore, in deriving the labels for the from Springer Science + Business Media B.V. [Figure
present combined model, I referred to the first of the two 19.3, Page 452]
Environmental Self 843

Assumptions or developmental steps can be added to the


revised Neo-Maslovian model that I had created
(a) The model should include a developmental in Young (2011), consisting of relations with the
component. Needs, drives, motivations, and other material world. That is, Young’s (2011) original
affective processes emerge in development, for Neo-Maslovian model is based partially on the
example, partly based on underpinning cognitive work of Blatt (2008) and his conception of two
acquisitions and learning. A developmentally- selves, but we now see that there appears to be
informed model of motivation does not mean that three instead of two primary components to the
the motivations involved begin functioning in a self that develops, a self-definitional one and a
mature way at the point of their emergence. relatedness one, as per Blatt (2008), but also a
Rather, the origins of the motivation are laid in material, instrumental self, as per Forbes (2011;
the groundwork of their emergence in the speci- see Table 34.5).
fied levels, and they can continue to develop with Another concept that applies to this instru-
growth in cognition and learning and in emotion mental mode is competence or mastery. Note that
and sociality. the concepts involved, such as mastery, have dif-
(b) The motivations in the integrated model ferent meanings in different areas of psychology
should address the three self/social spheres con- and, in my work here, they are defined especially
sidered in the various models: self, environment, relative their place in the present model. In this
other/group. In my revision of Maslow, I con- sense, the mastery in the present context could be
sider the dyadic other and multiple-other group referred to as “eco-mastery.” Eco-activism is an
levels together, except where necessary to spec- example of such a moral attitude.
ify the difference. Therefore, in this regard, I suggest that an
(c) Motivations should be described generally, “environmental self” or ecological self develops.
but also they should apply specifically to the [A Google search failed to find any reference to
moral domain. There is overlap in motivations an environmental self, although an ecological
that apply to the self, social, and material/envi- self is mentioned in the ecology literature.] Note
ronmental worlds. Moreover, there is overlap in that an environmental self that acts morally might
motivations that are not considered directly moral deal with the biotic as well as abiotic environ-
and those that are considered directly moral. For ment, and might include actions toward aspects
example, I might strive to obtain liberty for of the environment relative to groups, such as
myself, but a corollary motive is that the striving preserving and improving neighborhoods.
should become applied to the social world, too.
Indeed, it can be argued that one cannot really
strive for genuine liberty only in one sphere or Comment
the other. Also, in this sense, moral/foundational
motives apply not only to the social world but To review, the prior Neo-Maslovian model that I
also to the material/environmental one (think had created in Young (2011) had split the classic
eco-activism). triangular model of Maslow on hierarchy of
needs in terms of two half columns (on the self-
definitional and relational selves), but the present
Environmental Self version has three component columns instead of
two, with the third one involving a mastering self.
Model This new conception of how Maslow’s model
should be revised led me to slightly modify the
According to these suggestions and the review of notion underpinning the two existing columns.
the relevant models above, especially of Forbes Specifically, the relational self is understood to
(2011) emphasis on mastery in motivation, it apply to interpersonal or group spheres. In bal-
would appear a third ladder of hierarchical needs ance, the self-definitional self is referred to as
844 34 Revising Maslow

Table 34.5 Five foundational moral motives in relation to Neo-Maslovian needs and Neo-Piagetian developmental
level
Relation to the self
Relation to need (Neo-Maslovian)/ Relatedness self (other)/
developmental level (Neo-Piagetian) Definitional self Environmental self relatedness self (group)
Actualizing generativity/collective Liberty, humanizing Planetary activism (or Purity/sanctity (other,
intelligence seeking concern): eco-mastery group)
(striving toward full
potential in relation to
planetary activism or
concern)
Identity self-esteem/abstract Conscious identifying Achievement (obtaining Conscious social
intelligence of values/morality positive results, feeling application of values/
proud) morality (other, group)
Affiliative initiative/perioperational Fairness, reciprocity, Empowerment (being Authority/respect
intelligence (preoperational, valuing equal to the task, (other, group)
concrete operational) capable, and free to act)
Safety, trust/sensorimotor Harm reducing/care Engagement Loyalty (other, group)
intelligence promoting (productivity involved,
absorbed, excited)
Physiological survival/reproduction/ Life preservation Action/approach Life preservation
reflexive intelligence (self) (exploration, curiosity) (other, group)
Note. The first column is based on Young’s (2011) model of Neo-Piagetian cognitive development (five stages) and the
corresponding reworking of Maslow’s (1943) needs hierarchy into a developmental model. The second and fourth col-
umns reflect the original two halves of the Young Neo-Maslovian model as applied to the self-definitional and relational
selves (Blatt, 2008). However, they have been reworked in terms of Haidt’s (2012) model of five foundational moral
motives. Also considered were Janoff-Bulman and Carnes’s (2013) model of moral motives. The third column is based
on Forbes (2011) work on motives related to the environment, as adjusted to fit the five-stage model described
By examining the various terms/concepts in the columns, the degree of conceptual integration and coherence over the
various models that have inspired the present work becomes clear
In the first column, the integration of Maslovian, Eriksonian, and Piagetian terms/concepts is evident in the hierarchical,
developmental model proposed to modify/replace the original authors of these seminal models
In the second column, the work of Haidt is emphasized, but this is achieved in concert with the work of Blatt on the defi-
nitional self. I added some terms allowing for better paralleling with my model
In the third column on the environmental self, which follows from the work of Forbes (but is also consistent with Deci
& Ryan, 1995), I refer to planetary activism/eco-mastery (and related achievement/empowerment/engagement/action).
This type of self is an addition to the duality model of Blatt, but adds a wider focus to understanding the self/personality
and motives/ethics
The last column puts together Blatt’s concept of relatedness with Janoff-Bulman’s focus on other/group and Haidt’s
work on purity/sanctity and other moral motives. Once more, they are reworked to fit the present five-step model

intrapersonal. As for the new column, the devel- mentally and in how they have to be revised to fit
opment of motives relative to the material world my own model. Also, I relate them to the self-
is generalized to refer to the environmental self. definitional, individualizing side or sphere of the
model and the relational, group side or sphere.
This is the first time that I have attempted to
Five Foundational Moral Motives expand the two sides of the model, so that the
previous analysis of the foundational and moral
Introduction motives has proven useful for my present
theorizing.
In the following, I re-examine the previously The next task, then, is to reorganize the foun-
described models of motives that were described dational motives so that they fit the present
by Haidt and by Janoff-Bulman and their col- model, which has five levels each with a self and
leagues. In particular, I consider them develop- relatedness side to consider (as well as an
Five Foundational Moral Motives 845

environmental one, which is not relevant to the to consciously identifying values/morality. In this
present exercise). After this next section of the regard, given that there are five levels in the
chapter, I turn to the moral motives for a similar Maslovian approach to needs/motives, it would
reworking. appear that the fourth one of identity/self-esteem
Before beginning the elaboration of the five level that manifests at the time of the adolescent
foundational moral motives, it must be kept in age period should include moral foundational
mind that the axis on which I constructed them motives related to consciousness, in the sense of
relate to the present revised Neo-Maslovian awareness of self and personal growth. As for the
model, which itself is based on a revised Neo- earliest level of need/survival, the motive appears
Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian model. Therefore, in to involve survival (e.g., avoid suicide, murder).
choosing the final names for the foundational Moreover, in developing this model of
moral motives, I avoided using the terminology motives in relation to level of hierarchical needs
of the work on which it was based (on founda- and their development, I used similar terminol-
tional motives and on moral motives). On the one ogy for the three selves associated with the
hand, as we shall see, they did not cover the full model. Haidt’s work especially helped with the
range of motives required in a complete model self-definitional (individual, personal) and relat-
that extends from mine. On the other hand, the edness (other, group) sides of the model. In fol-
labels used by the others best serve as exemplars lowing up the analysis above in terms of which
of the more general terms that I created. of the foundational motives aligns with which of
the five levels of my model, in the following, I
determine which side at any one level (self-defi-
Revising Foundational Motives nitional or relatedness) they align with best. (a)
For safety/trust, I placed Haidt’s harm reducing/
Revision I tried to place Haidt’s foundational care promoting on the individualizing, self-defi-
moral motives in a developmental sequence that nitional level and placed his loyalty on the social,
fits the present model. As a general guide, I relatedness side. (b) For affiliative/initiative,
remind that Maslow’s five levels of hierarchi- Haidt’s fairness/reciprocity went to the personal
cally arranged needs include ones related to— side and his authority/respect to the social one.
physical needs, emotional security, social (c) For the self-actualization/generativity, the
affiliation, self-esteem, and self-actualization, assignments were for liberty and purity/sanctity
which I have modified, e.g., referring to safety on the self-definitional and relatedness sides,
and trust for the second step. In this regard, the respectively.
harm/care level in Haidt’s model appears to cor- Next, I justify the placement of the founda-
respond to the level of safety/trust in mine, as tional motives at the levels of my Neo-Maslovian
does loyalty. Fairness/reciprocity and authority/ model by showing why they do not fit the two
respect seem to correspond to affiliative initia- levels for which I had to create other motives of
tive. Liberty and purity/sanctity would corre- this nature to complete alignment of the five lev-
spond to self-actualization/generativity. [Note els of my model with five types of foundational
that I use the term purity/sanctity with the highest motives (and different ones than Haidt had pro-
moral connotations of the term, e.g., spiritually posed). In this regard, none of Haidt’s founda-
giving of the self with expectation of no return tional motives are similar to the first Maslovian
(within the limits of avoiding self-harm).] level of physical survival needs. The closest
Note that I had difficulty aligning the founda- might be avoiding harm, but that aligns better
tional motives with the levels in my model, and with the next level of providing safety or security.
had to add ones for the first and fourth levels. In Second, fairness/reciprocity aligns with affilia-
this regard, for the physiological/survival level, I tive/initiative, and might be considered as part of
added motives related to life preservation. For the the next level upward of identity/self-esteem, as
self-esteem/identity level, I added motives related well. However, they would have to evolve from
846 34 Revising Maslow

the level of the person behaving with these char- to—physiological/survival, safety/trust, affilia-
acteristics in concrete context into more abstract tive/initiative, identity/self-esteem, and actualiz-
values/morals in order to fit the fourth level better ing/generative. Also, there are three types of
than the third. selves that are related to each of them—the self-
Also, note that the foundational motives of lib- definitional (individual) one, the relatedness
erty, fairness/reciprocity, and the others especially (social/group) one, and the material/competent
fit into the self-definitional, individualizing side in (environmental) one. The present task then is to
the present model, but they help qualify the relat- align the model of moral motives to my model.
edness one, as well. In this regard, we can add to To remind, that model includes group level moral
them qualifiers such as seeking, valuing, and pro- motives as well as self and other ones, with all
moting (e.g., liberty-seeking, fairness-valuing, three of these types having motives at the pre-
care promoting). This makes them consistent with scriptive and proscriptive levels.
the social/group/other side of the model, in which Generally, the group motives (social order and
the motives are more outward than inward, per- social justice) in the moral motive model Janoff-
sonal, and self-definition related. Bulman and Carnes (2013) fit the group or relat-
edness motives listed in the present model.
Comment Note that my model of the cognitive However, careful inspection of the foundational
(mis)perception of the other (Young, 2011), moral motives in my model reveals only some
which is developmental, given that it stems from correspondence between my model and the one
my Neo-Piagetian model of cognitive of moral motives.
development, also corresponds to the Maslovian First in this regard, their social order moral
one and the related ones on foundational and motive appears to precede developmentally the
moral motives, especially in the way that I have social justice one. Second, therefore the two
revised them. In this sense, it might serve as a moral motives do not correspond to the same
cognitive foundation for understanding the devel- level in my model even if they are placed at the
opment of the foundational and moral motives. same level in their model. That is, social order
In the following, I turn to my analysis and aligns with the authority/respect level in my
revision of the model of moral motives, showing model, and social justice would align with the
how it can fit my own Neo-Maslovian model. At level above that on conscious social application
the same time, I refer to how the former can help of values/morality. Fourth, social order includes
explain the development of the relatedness/group communal solidarity, which might make this
side of my model. Therefore, we will see that portion of it align best with the loyalty motive in
some of the revision to my model already the level before the one where I have indicated it
described in analyzing the model of foundational fits. Fifth, their social justice motive also
motives borrowed from the model of moral includes communal responsibility, which makes
motives, as well. this component of it correspond to the purity/
sanctity motive in the upper level of the model,
involving spirituality/behaving for the common
Revising Moral Motives good.
About the interpersonal motives in the moral
Revision It is helpful to consider how the spe- motive model in Janoff-Bulman and Carnes
cific motivations described in the model of moral (2013) and their relationship to the self-
motives in Janoff-Bulman and Carnes (2013) definitional, individual foundational moral
map onto the present model. I accomplish this motives of my model and their arrangement into
task in several steps. I remind that in my model five levels in it the interpersonal motives in
there are five levels related to my revision of Janoff-Bulman and Carnes (2013) appear to map
Maslow’s hierarchy of needs that are related onto the present model, but not according to their
Naming the Five Foundational Moral Motives 847

placement in the interpersonal sphere of their Creating Environmental Motives


model. (a) That is, they appear to correspond to
categories in the definitional self (relatedness, Model Recall that the third component of a
personal) sphere of the present model rather than revised Neo-Maslovian model related to the self
the interpersonal one. (b) In this regard, for the concerned the material, environmental world,
second category in Janoff-Bulman and Carnes in and acting with mastery or competence within it.
the interpersonal sphere, the moral motive is In terms of how the foundational moral motives
helping/fairness. (c) This category can be split, might pass through a five-step sequence of hier-
and, in so doing, the fairness component corre- archical needs, I propose the following; they
sponds to Haidt’s foundational moral model cat- would involve from lowest to highest level—
egory of fairness/reciprocity, which lies in the action/approach (exploration/curiosity), engage-
third level of my model. The helping component ment, empowerment, achievement, and mastery.
perhaps fits Haidt’s Liberty category, which lies These five levels in hierarchical need develop-
in the fifth level of my model. (d) As for the other ment related to the environmental self correspond
interpersonal motive in Janoff-Bulman, the one to the five general levels of the model—respec-
of not harming corresponds to Haidt’s harm/care tively, physiological needs/survival, safety/trust,
category, and so is placed in the second level of affiliative/initiative, self-esteem/identity, and
my model. actualization/generativity.
About Janoff-Bulman and Carnes (2013) pro-
posed self (personal) moral motives, they do not Comment These five levels, as found with the
align very well with the categories in the spheres foundational moral motives that are proposed
of the present model. In this sense, self-restraint to arise in correspondence to those for the indi-
would appear to be a general self-regulatory skill vidual and other/group moral spheres, are dif-
that applies to motivation in any sphere, personal, ferentiated aspects of the five motives for the
social, or group, and industriousness is a higher- self at issue, rather than separate ones.
order skill that helps in any higher-order category Therefore the model of five foundational moral
of any sphere, as well. motives that I have developed includes ones
that develop sequentially and that apply to three
Comment As shown in a previous section of different spheres.
the chapter, Haidt’s foundational motive model
included motives that aligned with three of the
five levels of the present model, and one of them Naming the Five Foundational
could be seen as a ready precursor to one more Moral Motives
level. As shown in the present section of the
chapter, Janoff-Bulman’s moral motive model Introduction
has components that align with four of the levels
in my model, but this became clear only after I The best terms to integrate the different types of
made the effort to show the parallels between the motives associated with the three spheres of indi-
models using components in the moral motive vidual, social, and environmental should avoid
ones. Overall, both the foundational and the the exemplars derived from Haidt and Janoff-
moral motive models have not considered any Bulman and colleagues and, as well, should
motives related to the first level of my model, respect the theoretical origins that drove their
and I had to create them without their work as a creation, which is my revised Neo-Maslovian
guide. However, it was not difficult to do so, model. In this regard, the best names for the foun-
given Maslow’s description of the needs at this dational moral motives should not be ones like
level as physiological, leading me to create a loyalty and justice, but ones anchored in
survival-related motive referred to as self Maslovian, Piagetian, and Eriksonian terminol-
preservation. ogy. In this sense, I did not deviate too much
848 34 Revising Maslow

from them as I reflected on the present task of moral motive involved is Self/Other/
naming the foundational moral motives. Environment Affiliative Initiative.
Moreover, the labels chosen should be general (d) Next, the foundational moral motive of Self/
enough to cover the three spheres at each level of Other/Environment Identity Self-Esteem
individual, social, and environmental. Therefore, develops. Our identities and sense of self grow
for the five levels of the present model, the best as we relate well to others, the environment,
labels for the five foundational moral motives and our inner workings. We become sure of
involve the following. our moral ideas and outreach, and might apply
them with consuming passion. This promotes
a sense of (subjective) well being and health
Names that we might transfer to the development of
same in others and the environment.
(a) The most basic hierarchical need level is (e) In the penultimate step in the development of
concerned with physiological needs and sur- hierarchical needs and foundational moral
vival, and I have referred to the motive motives, we become concerned with genera-
involved at this level as life preservation. In tivity in the widest sense of the word and, in
this regard, in order to cover the three spheres activating moral behavior in this regard, we
involved, I refer to the most primary founda- self-actualize optimally with consequences
tional moral motive as Self/Other/ for the self-actualization of others. There is a
Environment Life Preservation. Although it self/other actualization that develops or,
develops first in life, it carries forward more precisely for the foundational moral
throughout life and, at the moral level, allows motive involved, a Self/Other/Environment
for behavior at the highest moral levels, such Actualizing Generativity. We are constantly
as great acts of courage in saving people, ani- and widely moral at the highest levels in all
mals, and even the planet as a whole. our responsibilities and endeavors, in what
(b) Next, the hierarchical need involved con- can be referred to as a process of participa-
cerns safety/trust, and at this level behavior tory morality.
relates to caring for the self, other, and envi-
ronment, and not doing them harm. This
need (and associated moral motive) develops Poles
in infancy and continues throughout the
lifespan. It leads to constant vigilance about Haidt and colleagues had related their model of
all those around us, as well as ourselves, foundational motives to adaptive challenges,
therefore, the best label to represent it is Self/ domains, related emotions, and virtues/vices. I
Other/Environment Safety/Trust. have incorporated some of these themes in my
(c) Third, the hierarchical need that develops description of my version of the motives in the
concerns affiliative initiative. It enables above. However, instead of replicating in much
activity and moral motivation related to detail his approach to the nature of the founda-
dynamically interdigitating with the self and tional motives in describing my own version, I
with the other, as well, in the material world, prefer to keep the emphasis on their develop-
thereby developing a sense of mastery and mental origins in the models of Maslow, Piaget,
competence in these spheres, preparatory to and Erikson. In the latter sense, one can present
the development of identity and self-esteem. the various foundational moral motives as oppo-
In this phase, we learn to use well our social sitions, poles, crises, or challenges with which
skills and create social groups, which can act we struggle, for example, just as Erikson did for
together for moral outcomes, for example. In his eight developmental stages (e.g., trust vs.
this regard, the best label for the foundational mistrust).
Naming the Five Foundational Moral Motives 849

(a) In this regard, the first foundational moral (e) In the highest level in foundational moral
motive of Self/Other/Environment Life motive expression, when it is compromised,
Preservation should be considered as an it is more like Self/Other/Environment Moral
opposition of Self/Other/Environment Life Stagnation in Generativity. The person lives
Preservation vs. Self/Other/Environment without any moral values, and is just con-
Life Destruction. When causes of behav- cerned for the most basis needs, even if act-
ior lead to great difficulties in surmounting ing in a presumed generative way, e.g., in
this latter challenge, behavior could develop family and at work. Perhaps there is perfunc-
toward the destructive pole of the opposi- tory moral behavior at the surface, but no
tion (for example, which could lead to the depth in it (nor rationale or reason for it, if it
development and implementation of evil in is present). A moral void exists that the per-
behavior). son might try to fill with amoral behavior,
(b) Next, Self/Other/Environment Safety/Trust along with a constant stream of amoral
should be seen in opposition to Self/Other/ thought.
Environment Safety Lack/Mistrust. When
this crisis is not navigated well, the dangers
relate to adopting unsafe behavior and feel- Conclusion
ing an absence of security. The moral out-
come might be wanton disregard for self, I have prepared a table that presents the model of
other, and environment. the five foundational moral motives just described
(c) Third, Self/Other/Environment Affiliative (see Table 34.6). In the table, I indicate that a
Initiative has as its opposite pole Disaffiliative summary label for the issues that have to be navi-
Inertia. The person disengages, retreats, and gated for each of the five issues related to the five
withdraws morally, and vicious circles might foundational moral motives relate to the sequence
develop in reaction, for example, leading to dif- of—physiological needs, emotional security, con-
ficulties in dealing fairly and with authority. nection (social, cognitive), conscious abstraction,
(d) Then, instead of Self/Other/Environment and participatory morality. I chose these terms
Identity Self-Esteem, the person develops the because, from a developmental perspective and
opposite moral perspective of Self/Other/ considering the various steps in Maslow, Piaget,
Environment Identity Self-Esteem Difficulty and Erikson in this regard, the five-step passage
or Disturbance. This might involve not devel- indicated fits. It might be useful in the psycho-
oping moral values that guide daily life, and therapeutic context, given the problematic behav-
the person loses moral concern and compass iors that it describes as possible for each level. In
even when actively participating in life. this regard, the therapist would focus on the issues
One’s sense of self is compromised, adding at each of levels of the model that are relevant for
to difficulties in establishing a suite of appro- the patient at hand, and investigate their develop-
priate moral values. mental underpinnings, where appropriate.

Table 34.6 A model of five foundational moral motives in terms of oppositional poles
Pole
Self/other/environment motive origin Positive Negative
Physiological survival Life preservation Life destruction
Security (emotional) Safety, trust Safety lack/mistrust
Connection (cognitive, social) Affiliative/initiative Disaffiliative/inertia
Conscious abstraction Identity/self-esteem Its difficulty/disturbance
Participatory morality Actualizing/generativity Moral stagnation in generativity
850 34 Revising Maslow

Mechanism level, but precursors might be evident earlier.


Once more, Erikson’s model serves as an exam-
The self develops toward unity and integration in ple; i.e., although identity is considered to emerge
terms of its change processes and motivational in adolescence in his model, he considered that
bases. The transformation involved is dynamical, precursors emerge earlier; also, identity factors
self-organizational, emergent, constantly de were judged to be present at each stage after
novo, ebbing and flowing with gains and losses, adolescence.
and constantly seeking equilibrium at increas-
ingly more refined levels throughout the diverse
levels of its manifold. New Questionnaire
Although I have developed a model of founda-
tional moral motives, many factors can hinder their Introduction Based on the concept of the cog-
optimal manifestation and application. They pres- nitive (mis)perception of the other, one could
ent categories and classes that vary on a host of establish the degree to which respondents main-
parameters, and perhaps the most important is the tain that the government (conservative option) or
degree to which they are inhibited in or activated in people (liberal option) should be (a) controlling
their ability to motivate, instigate, or otherwise people or (b) empowering them. The Neo-
propulse the person into action. For each motiva- Piagetian stage model of development (Young,
tion, multiple variables might preclude their capac- 2011) consists of five stages, and the five-level
ity to be efficient and effective, including adverse model of the cognitive (mis)perception of the
life experiences, psychopathology, stressors in other is based on it. Advocating that people need
context, and self-regulation deficiencies. to be controlled (whether by government or
That is, although motivations might emerge people) is consistent with the lower levels of the
developmentally at a particular point in time, con- cognitive (mis)perception model (which means
sistent with their associated cognitive underpin- respondents might be cognitively developed to
ning, they are highly dependent on the type of higher stages but misperceive others as reflecting
environment in which the individual is parented, lower levels of development, capacity, merit,
schooled, etc. If the latter is supportive, the motiva- etc.). Advocating that people need concern
tions take a positive turn; if not, they can manifest directed toward them and need to be empowered
negatively (in this regard, Erikson’s developmental (whether by government or people) is consistent
model of challenges or crises at each stage serves with the higher levels of the model. Irrespective
as the classic prototype). of the level of control preferred, respondents
Also for the mechanisms involved, one that should vary in whether they adapt a conservative
I have found important in multiple areas of or liberal attitude in these regards. Moreover,
psychology, brain, and behavior concerns acti- there might be relevant psychological correlates
vation/inhibition coordination (Young, 2011). not only for the level of control advocated but
Janoff-Bulman and Carnes (2013) emphasized also for their indicated political attitudes.
the activation/approach and inhibition/aversion Janoff-Bulman (2012) offered an account of
self-regulation systems as important in moral how conservatives and liberals differ psychologi-
motivation. I would add that it is the intricate cally, as reviewed briefly earlier in the chapter.
coordination of activation and inhibition that pro- According to her, liberalism is associated with
vides the central and behavioral machinery for approach regulation and conservativism with
the unfolding of complex moral cognition, atti- avoidance regulation (e.g., Janoff-Bulman, 2009).
tudes, motives, and behavior. Therefore, liberals focus on “prescriptive” moral
Finally, the present model might place a par- orientation or “shoulds” and conservatives on
ticular motivation at a certain developmental “proscriptive” moral orientation or “should nots.”
New Questionnaire 851

Conservatives wish to protect members of society, The scale is based on several assumptions.
whereas liberals wish to provide for their welfare. First, political ideology concerns the degree to
Conservatives are concerned about societal losses, which people should be controlled, in general.
not gains but, for liberals, it is the opposite. Second, both liberals and conservatives will vary
Conservatives seek social order relative to social in their opinions on the matter, and both are capa-
justice, but it is the reverse for liberals. ble of imposing either great or little control on
Conservatives focus on life style issues, unlike lib- people. Third, respondents filling in the question-
erals, who focus on equity ones. Liberals are con- naire might reflect mixed attitudes in these
cerned with positive obligations, but conservatives regards, so it should allow for varying mixtures.
focus on prohibition. In short, according to Janoff- Fourth, the questionnaire should be developed
Bulman (2012), conservatives aim to “advance” from a valid theoretical framework. In this regard,
the common “good,” whereas liberals aim to pre- I referred to Young’s (2011) developmental
vent the “bad” being inflicted on group members. model of the cognitive (mis)perception of the
other (see Chap. 31). The model examines how
Questionnaire Given the issues discussed with people vary in their respect of their children, part-
respect to conflicts in the literature (a) about con- ner, and minorities based on their developmental
servatives and liberals and their personal attri- level. The model is Neo-Piagetian cognitively
butes and, (b) about how to best measure their and has 25 steps, but also it describes parallel
political ideology, I developed a scale on the lat- Neo-Eriksonian steps. Therefore, people could
ter that could be used to help elucidate valid dif- vary in the degree of control that they think peo-
ferences in the former (see Table 34.7). ple need according to the steps of the model;

Table 34.7 Five-point societal control questionnaire (in relation to conservatism–liberalism attitude) [according to
Young’s (2011) five-stage Neo-Piagetian model of the cognitive (mis)perception of the other]
Instructions
First, read the five questions, which describe different levels of control of people (from needing total control to
deserving the opposite of total empowerment). Then, starting with Question “A,” answer the questions. For each
question, you decide who should be doing the control—the government (conservative option), and/or the people
(liberal option), and also judge how much control should be applied, on a scale from 0 to 5.
Question A: PEOPLE NEED TO BE TOTALLY CONTROLLED
People need to be totally controlled and totally restricted.
Conservative Option: The government needs to prevent bad things, so the government should do this, as well as
other institutions/groups that they organize (that is, the people themselves should not do this).
0 1 2 3 4 5
NEVER RARELY SOMETIMES FREQUENTLY MOSTLY ALWAYS
Liberal Option: The government needs to promote good things, and the people themselves should develop the
self-control needed, as well as other institutions/groups that they organize (that is, the government should not do
this for the people).
0 1 2 3 4 5
NEVER RARELY SOMETIMES FREQUENTLY MOSTLY ALWAYS
Question B: PEOPLE NEED TO BE CONTROLLED A LOT, NOT TOTALLY
People should not be treated so poorly as in Question “A,” but they still need control, imposition, manipulation, and so on.
Conservative Option: The government needs to prevent bad things, so the government should do this, as well as
other institutions/groups that they organize (that is, the people themselves should not do this).
0 1 2 3 4 5
NEVER RARELY SOMETIMES FREQUENTLY MOSTLY ALWAYS
Liberal Option: The government needs to promote good things, and the people themselves should develop the
self-control needed, as well as other institutions/groups that they organize (that is, the government should not do
this for the people).
0 1 2 3 4 5
(continued)
852 34 Revising Maslow

Table 34.7 (continued)


NEVER RARELY SOMETIMES FREQUENTLY MOSTLY ALWAYS
Question C: PEOPLE NEED TO BE CHANNELED MORE THAN CONTROLLED
People should not be treated this badly (as in Question “B”), but they still need to be channeled, pacified, or neutralized.
Conservation Option: The government needs to prevent bad things, so the government should do this, as well as
other institutions/groups that they organize (that is, the people themselves should not do this).
0 1 2 3 4 5
NEVER RARELY SOMETIMES FREQUENTLY MOSTLY ALWAYS
Liberal Option: The government needs to promote good things, and the people themselves should develop the
self-control needed, as well as other institutions/groups that they organize (that is, the government should not do
this for the people).
0 1 2 3 4 5
NEVER RARELY SOMETIMES FREQUENTLY MOSTLY ALWAYS
Question D: PEOPLE NEED OTHERS TO HAVE CONCERN FOR THEIR WELFARE, NOT THEIR
CONTROL
People should be treated with concern for their welfare, offered responsibility, and so on.
Conservation Option: The government needs to prevent bad things, so the government should do this, as well as
other institutions/groups that they organize (that is, the people themselves should not do this).
0 1 2 3 4 5
NEVER RARELY SOMETIMES FREQUENTLY MOSTLY ALWAYS
Liberal Option: The government needs to promote good things, and the people themselves should develop the
self-control needed, as well as other institutions/groups that they organize (that is, the government should not do
this for the people).
0 1 2 3 4 5
NEVER RARELY SOMETIMES FREQUENTLY MOSTLY ALWAYS
Question E: PEOPLE NEED FULL EMPOWERMENT, THE OPPOSITE OF CONTROL
People are capable of helping and trusting each other, and they should be totally empowered to fully grow and also
to help others to do the same.
Conservation Option: The government needs to prevent bad things, so the government should do this, as well as
other institutions/groups that they organize (that is, the people themselves should not do this).
0 1 2 3 4 5
NEVER RARELY SOMETIMES FREQUENTLY MOSTLY ALWAYS
Liberal Option: The government needs to promote good things, and the people themselves should develop the
self-control needed, as well as other institutions/groups that they organize (that is, the government should not do
this for the people).
0 1 2 3 4 5
NEVER RARELY SOMETIMES FREQUENTLY MOSTLY ALWAYS

political ideology, personality, and free will to


however, whether government or the people determine the multiple influences on and out-
themselves should do this, and to what degree, comes of political ideology.
would depend on other factors that influence
political ideology.

Comment The questionnaire is nuanced, and Chapter Conclusions


can give data related to level and extent of belief
that people need to be controlled and whether The revision of Maslow’s classic hierarchical
this should take place more conservatively, liber- needs/motivation model has been an extremely
ally, or both. After the scale is validated, it could broad-ranging endeavor. On the one hand, it
be used in conjunction with other measures of involved better understanding of psychological
References 853

maturity, which he defined in terms of self- Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 71,
83–93.
actualization. In the current approach, not only
Brown, K. W., & Ryan, R. M. (2003). The benefits of
do I integrate the work of Erikson on generativ- being present: Mindfulness and its role in psychological
ity but also I add the concepts of psychological well-being. Journal of Personality and Social
completeness/psychological completing. As for Psychology, 84, 822–848.
Carnes, N. C., & Janoff-Bulman, R. (2012). Harm, help,
the basic physiological needs/motivations that
and the nature of (im)moral (in)action. Psychological
carry forward in development and that are con- Inquiry, 23, 137–142.
sistently present as essential in life, I consider Carver, C. S., & Scheier, M. F. (2008). Feedback pro-
them embodied processes that lead to embodied cesses in the simultaneous regulation of affect and
action. In J. Y. Shah & W. L. Gardner (Eds.), Handbook
activities, either by themselves or as incorpo-
of motivation science (pp. 308–324). New York:
rated into higher-order needs/motives. We are Guilford Press.
enactive, participatory beings, and even the sim- Deci, E. L., & Ryan, R. M. (1991). A motivational approach
plest of physiological activities are primed and to self: Integration in personality. In R. Dienstbier (Ed.),
Nebraska Symposium on Motivation: Perspectives on
promoted in the social world. In this sense, each
motivation (Vol. 38, pp. 237–288). Lincoln, NE:
step in development (or moving up the hierar- University of Nebraska Press.
chy of needs/motives that corresponds to these Deci, E. L., & Ryan, R. M. (1995). Human autonomy: The
steps) is embodied themselves. How they yoke basis for true self-esteem. In M. H. Kernis (Ed.), Plenum
series in social/clinical psychology. Efficacy, agency,
together in the adaptive flux of life reflects not
and self-esteem (pp. 31–49). New York: Plenum.
only an internal process of needs and motives Deci, E. L., & Ryan, R. M. (2013). The importance of
but also an external relational adaptation to the autonomy for development and well-being. In B. W.
social and environmental field in which we nav- Sokol, M. E. Grouzet, & U. Müller (Eds.), Self-
regulation and autonomy: Social and developmental
igate, adjust, and adapt, in the balance of self,
dimensions of human conduct (pp. 19–46). New York:
other, and world. Cambridge University Press.
Erikson, E. (1959). Identity and the life cycle. New York:
International Universities Press.
Erikson, E. (1979). Dimensions of a new identity: The
References Jefferson lectures in the humanities. New York: Norton.
Erikson, E. H. (1980). Identity and the life cycle. New
Aksan, N., & Kochanska, G. (2005). Conscience in child- York: Norton.
hood: Old questions, new answers. Developmental Forbes, D. L. (2011). Toward a unified model of
Psychology, 41, 506–516. human motivation. Review of General Psychology, 15,
Bakan, D. (1966). The duality of human existence: An 85–98.
essay on psychology and religion. Chicago: Rand Fraley, R. C., Griffin, B. N., Belsky, J., & Roisman, G. I.
McNally. (2012). Developmental antecedents of political ideol-
Bandura, A. (1977). Self-efficacy: Toward a unifying the- ogy: A longitudinal investigation from birth to age 18
ory of behavioral change. Psychological Review, 84, years. Psychological Science, 23, 1425–1431.
191–215. Freud, S. (1927/1961). The ego and the id. In J. Strachey
Bandura, A. (1986). Social foundations of thought and (Ed.), and J. Riviere (Trans.), The standard edition of
action: A social cognitive theory. Englewood Cliffs, the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud.
NJ: Prentice Hall. New York: Norton. (Original work published 1927)
Bandura, A. (1997). Self-efficacy: The exercise of control. Freud, S. (1933). Warum krieg (Why war)? Standard
New York: Freeman. Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of
Baumeister, R. F., Brataslavsky, E., Finkenauer, C., & Sigmund Freud, 22, 197–224. London: Hogarth Press.
Vohs, K. D. (2001). Bad is stronger than good. Review Gallese, V. (2013). Mirror neurons, embodied simulation
of General Psychology, 5, 323–370. and a second-person approach to mindreading. Cortex,
Blatt, S. J. (2008). Polarities of experience: Relatedness 49, 2954–2956.
and self-definition in personality development, psycho- Gallese, V. (2014). Bodily selves in relation:
pathology, and the therapeutic process. Washington, Embodied simulation as second-person perspective on
DC: American Psychological Association. intersubjectivity. Philosophical Transaction of the
Bowlby, J. (1969/1999). Attachment and loss, Vols. 1–3. Royal Society B Biological Sciences, 369.
New York: Basic Books. Gilbert, D. T., Fiske, S. T., & Gardner, L. (Eds.). (1998).
Bowlby, J. (1979). The making and breaking of affectional Handbook of social psychology (4th ed.). New York:
bonds. London, UK: Tavistock. McGraw-Hill.
Brewer, M. D., & Gardner, W. (1996). Who is this “we”? Graham, J., & Haidt, J. (2012). Sacred values and evil
Levels of collective identity and self representations. adversaries: A moral foundations approach. In
854 34 Revising Maslow

M. Mikulincer & P. R. Shaver (Eds.), The social psy- Kohlberg, L. (1981). The psychology of moral develop-
chology of morality: Exploring the causes of good and ment (Essays on moral development: Volume 1). San
evil (pp. 11–31). Washington, DC: American Francisco, CA: Harper & Row.
Psychological Association. Kohlberg, L. (1984). The psychology of moral develop-
Graham, J., Nosek, B. A., Haidt, J., Iyer, R., Koleva, S., & ment (Essays on moral development: Volume 2). San
Ditto, P. H. (2011). Mapping the moral domain. Francisco, CA: Harper & Row.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 96, Kyselo, M. (2014). The body social: An enactive approach
1029–1046. to the self. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 986.
Haidt, J. (2007). The new synthesis in moral psychology. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00986.
Science, 316, 998–1002. Lee, W., Reeve, J., Xue, Y., & Xiong, J. (2012). Neural
Haidt, J. (2008). Morality. Perspectives on Psychological differences between intrinsic reasons for doing versus
Science, 3, 65–72. extrinsic reasons for doing: An fMRI study.
Haidt, J. (2012). The righteous mind: Why good people are Neuroscience Research, 73, 68–72.
divided by politics and religion. New York: Pantheon. Legault, L., & Inzlicht, M. (2012). Self-determination,
Haidt, J., & Joseph, C. (2004). Intuitive ethics: How self-regulation, and the brain: Autonomy improves
innately prepared intuitions generate culturally vari- performance by enhancing neuroaffective responsive-
able virtues. Daedalus, 133, 55–66. ness to self-regulation failure. Journal of Personality
Haidt, J., & Joseph, C. (2007). The moral mind: How five and Social Psychology, 105, 123–138.
sets of innate intuitions guide the development of Luyten, P., & Blatt, S. J. (2013). Interpersonal relatedness
many cultural-specific virtues, and perhaps even mod- and self-definition in normal and disrupted personality
ules. In P. Carruthers, S. Laurence, & S. Stich (Eds.), development. American Psychologist, 68, 172–183.
The innate mind: Foundations and the future (Vol. 3, Maslow, A. H. (1943). A theory of human motivation.
pp. 367–392). New York: Oxford University Press. Psychological Review, 50, 370–396.
Haidt, J., & Kesebir, S. (2010). Morality. In S. T. Fiske, Maslow, A. H. (1955). Deficiency motivation and growth
D. T. Gilbert, & G. Lindzey (Eds.), Handbook of motivation. In M. R. Jones (Ed.), Nebraska Symposium
social psychology (5th ed., pp. 797–832). Hoboken, on Motivation: 1955. Lincoln, NE: University of
NJ: Wiley. Nebraska Press.
Hamilton, W. (1964). The genetical evolution of social Maslow, A. H. (1967). Self-actualization and beyond. In
behavior I and II. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 7, J. F. T. Bugental (Ed.), Challenges of humanistic psy-
1–52. chology. New York: McGraw-Hill.
James, W. (1890/1950). The principles of psychology. McClelland, D. (1961). The achieving society. Princeton,
Mineola, NY: Dover. NJ: Van Nostrand.
Janoff-Bulman, R. (2009). To provide or protect: Mead, G. H. (1934). In C. W. Morris (Ed.), Mind, self, and
Motivational bases of political liberalism and conser- society. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
vatism. Psychological Inquiry, 20, 120–128. Murray, H. A. (1938). Explorations in personality.
Janoff-Bulman, R. (2012). Conscience: The do’s and Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
don’ts of moral regulation. In M. Milkuciner & Piaget, J. (1937). La construction du réel chez l’enfant
P. Shaver (Eds.), The social psychology of morality: [The construction of reality in the child]. Neuchatel,
Exploring the causes of good and evil (pp. 131–148). Switzerland: Delachaux et Niestlé.
Washington, DC: American Psychological Piaget, J., & Inhelder, B. (1967). The child’s conception
Association. of space. In The coordination of perspectives, 8
Janoff-Bulman, R., & Carnes, N. C. (2013). Surveying the (pp. 209–246). New York: Norton.
moral landscape: Moral motives and group-based Rogers, C. R. (1963). The actualizing tendency in relation
moralities. Personality and Social Psychology Review, to “motives” and to consciousness. In M. R. Jones
17, 219–236. (Ed.), Nebraska Symposium on Motivation (Vol. 11,
Janoff-Bulman, R., Carnes, N., & Sheikh, S. (2014). pp. 1–24). Lincoln, NE: University of Nebraska Press.
Parenting style and politics: Early bases of distinct Ryan, R. M., & Deci, E. L. (2000). Self-determination
moral orientations. Journal of Social and Political theory and the facilitation of intrinsic motivation,
Psychology, 2. doi:10.5964/jspp.v2i1.243. social development, and well-being. American
Janoff-Bulman, R., Sheikh, S., & Hepp, S. (2009). Psychologist, 55, 68–78.
Proscriptive versus prescriptive morality: Two faces of Ryan, R. M., & Deci, E. L. (2008). From ego-depletion to
moral regulation. Journal of Personality and Social vitality: Theory and findings concerning the facilitation
Psychology, 96, 521–537. of energy available to the self. Social and Personality
Kenrick, D. T., Griskevicius, V., Neuberg, S. L., & Schaller, Psychology Compass, 2, 702–717.
M. (2010). Renovating the pyramid of needs: Thagard, P., & Wood, J. V. (2015). Eighty phenomena
Contemporary extensions built upon ancient foundations. about the self: Representation, evaluation, regulation,
Perspectives on Psychological Science, 5, 292–314. and change. Frontiers in Psychology, 6, 334.
Kochanska, G. (2002). Committed compliance, moral doi:10.3389/psyg.2015.00334.
self, and internalization: A mediational model. Weinstein, N., Brown, K. W., & Ryan, R. M. (2009). A
Developmental Psychology, 38, 339–351. multi-method examination of the effects of mindful-
34 Revising Maslow 855

ness on stress attribution, coping, and emotional well- Weinstein, N., Ryan, W. S., DeHaan, C. R., Przybylski,
being. Journal of Research in Personality, 43, A. K., Legate, N., & Ryan, R. M. (2012). Parental
374–385. autonomy support and discrepancies between implicit
Weinstein, N., Deci, E., & Ryan, R. M. (2011). and explicit sexual identities: Dynamics of self-
Motivational determinants of integrating positive and acceptance and defense. Journal of Personality and
negative past identities. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 102, 815–832.
Social Psychology, 100, 527–544. Wilson, E. O. (2012). The social conquest of earth.
Weinstein, N., Przybylski, A. K., & Ryan, R. M. (2013). New York: Norton.
The integrative process: New research and future Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
directions. Current Directions in Psychological Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science +
Science, 22, 69–74. Business Media.
Staging Revolutions
and Paradigms 35

present modeling process to the intellectual


Chapter Introduction endeavor of epistemology in philosophy. It con-
cludes by returning to the concept of the causal
The present chapter describes a revised approach self that was introduced at the beginning of the
to Kuhn’s (1962, 1970) concept of scientific par- book in the first chapter, and shows how the
adigm and its change (Overton, 2013). Then, it chapters from after that one to the present one
proceeds to modify it, in turn, according to the includes relevant concepts and research toward
present five-step model of generic change. establishing the nature of the causal self and the
First, the chapter presents Overton’s (2013) value of the concept for unifying psychology.
advance in understanding paradigmatic structure
and change relative to the original Kuhn position.
Overton’s revision of Kuhn’s model involves five Kuhn’s Model of Paradigm Change
levels from domain of inquiry to metatheoretical
worldview. Then, I present a reworking of this Model
revised Kuhnian model, including use of the con-
cept of “paradigmatic meta-modeling” or a step According to Overton (2013), Kuhn (1962, 1970)
in the modeling process beyond the ones consid- had described a broad meaning of paradigm, so
ered to date for the establishment and change of that it includes a disciplinary matrix, which
paradigms. involves a network of shared metaphysical
The remainder of the chapter considers appli- beliefs (e.g., analogies, metaphors) and values.
cations and implications of the revised Neo- In his conception, worldviews are constitutive
Kuhnian model. For example, I show how the features of scientific activity. This approach
process that I followed in building my present contrasts with that of neopositivism and
Neo-Piagetian and parallel Neo-Eriksonian conventionalism (e.g., Popper, 1959, 1970), for
model fits the evolving nature of science as mod- which metaphysical concepts are “purely heuris-
eled in my Neo-Kuhnian perspective. Then, I tic.” In this latter “scientific realism” perspective,
consider the crucial issue of whether causality rigid empiricism/objective truth can be estab-
can be considered as a unifying focus in psychol- lished by “hard data” gathered after conjecture in
ogy, and indicate how the search for causality can a discovering and justification process, which
be modeled according to my present five-step includes refutable, falsifiable hypotheses that are
generic change model, which is based on the put to the test. However, by adding a constitutive
Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian one. The chapter metaphysical component to scientific activity,
continues with examples of application of the Kuhn’s new worldview of scientific paradigm

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 857


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_35
858 35 Staging Revolutions and Paradigms

rejected the scientific epistemology of empiri- of the hierarchy of nested levels, and function
cism (although not empirical study itself!). Also, like worldviews. Next, positive heuristics are like
it rejected a scientific ontology of “fixed objec- midlevel metatheories. Then, families of theories
tivist foundationalism,” which was instrumental constitute a lower level in the nest. Finally, the
for the extant but limited worldview. Therefore, lowest level involves a “belt of auxiliary hypoth-
Kuhn’s new epistemology was “constructivist” eses” that are empirically testable, falsifiable, and
and the ontology involved activity and engage- refutable.
ment by scientists as contributory to and influ-
encing of the scientific process and product.
Revising Kuhn on Paradigm

Comment Relationism

Others who contributed to the shift in scientific Overton (2013) proposed a nested model of the
paradigms include Wittgenstein (1958) and concept of scientific paradigm (Kuhn, 1962,
Gadamer (1989), and their logic of a “hermeneu- 1970). In his model, the construct of relationism
tical circle.” Science accrues knowledge not just is placed at its summit. Other aspects of the
by hypothetico-deductive explanation and induc- model include midrange metatheories, theories,
tive logic but also by an “abductive” logic that is hypotheses, and domains at consecutive lower
more inclusive (e.g., of background ideas) and levels (see Fig. 35.1).
that is relational. Overton (2013) explained that metatheories
Lakatos (1970, 1978) and Laudan (1977) provide a coherent framework of background
extended Kuhn’s worldview approach to scien- concepts, meanings, resources, and guidelines
tific paradigm by more clearly distinguishing the that provide context for the construction of theo-
nested conceptual layers involved. Hard core ries. Similarly, metamethods provide a frame for
concepts of a “research” paradigm are at the apex methods (principles that guide empirical inquiry).

Fig. 35.1 Nested concepts of


a scientific paradigm. The Metatheoretical Level
(Worldviews)
figure shows five levels of the
(For example, Mechanistic, Relationism)
nested concepts of a scientific
paradigm for a domain.
Adapted from Overton (2013,
2015) Mid-Range Metatheory Level
(For example, Evolution, Developmental Stage
Models)

Theoretical Level
(For example, Information processing, Piaget, Erikson, Vygotsky)

Empirically Testable Hypotheses


(Research studies)

Domain of Inquiry
A Neo-Kuhnian Approach 859

Specifically, a metatheory consists of a coherent Comment


set of principles and rules (and their narrative)
that both describes and delimits the acceptability In the next section of the chapter, I modify
and meaningfulness of theory or conceptual Overton’s (2013) Kuhnian model. I show that my
exploration of a domain and its empirical phe- version is consistent with the present 25-step
nomena. Metamethods describe and delimit the Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian developmental
means of inquiry in a discipline. model. Generally, the compatibility of a revised
Overton (2013) referred to scientific disci- Kuhnian model of scientific paradigm with my
plines and paradigms, in particular, but I will try own model gives the latter incremental validity,
to elaborate a paradigmatic frame applicable to while giving the former some grounding in a
any field of scholarship. In this regard, there is generic model of change.
little need to change Overton’s terminology for
the proposed Neo-Kuhnian model. However, for
methodology, I refer not only to observation, A Neo-Kuhnian Approach
experimentation, or other rigorous method of
data collection, but also to any means of logical Model
analysis of natural phenomena and the product of
human activity that helps denote its constituent Overton (2013) has presented a model of para-
elements that are helpful for theorizing (which digm and its change in the sciences that involves
stands in reciprocal relationship to the methods five steps (as per Fig. 35.1). However, his model
of inquiry in the domain of focus). could be expanded by separating into two distinct
Overton (2013) continued that the broadest streams metatheory and theory, and then showing
metatheories in terms of generality and abstract- how each develops (e.g., into worldview and inte-
ness are worldviews. They consist of a coherent grative theories, respectively). Moreover, a
set of principles in epistemology and ontology revised Overtonian model of scientific paradigm
(issues about the source/justification of knowl- should show how the two streams of metatheory
edge and the fundamental categories of reality, and theory interact at each level of the nested
respectively). Worldviews present frameworks hierarchy within each stream.
about visions of the nature of the world and the In this regard, in the following, I elaborate a
nature of how we know it. Midrange metatheo- new Kuhnian model of scientific evolution and
ries are less broad, general, and abstract than revolution (as well as the same for rigorous
meta-theories, and they are more specific to the scholarship, in general), using the present five-
domain of inquiry involved. Theories vary in step model of change. This latter change model
level, too, being either broad or narrow. They underlies the model of steps in cognitive develop-
align both with the “observational field” of the ment that I described in Young (2011; 25 steps,
domain and a superordinate metaview. having 5 stages × 5 recurrent substages, with 5
Overton (2013) noted that counter evidence to a steps possible within each of the substages, in a
hypothesis does not literally falsify it in the world- fractalization process).
view approach of constructivism. Rather, lack of That is, based on Overton’s (2013) five-step
evidence in support of a hypothesis functions as an Kuhnian model, after its separation into two
anomaly in the problem-solving process associ- streams, and also based on my five-step generic
ated with the paradigm involved. However, a gath- change model, I added new components to create
ering of sufficient anomalies eventually triggers a two new parallel five-step sequences in each of
scientific crisis that leads to alternative paradigms. metatheory and theory building. Then, I deter-
The “gestalt switch” in the trigger is pragmatic and mined a common five-step sequence that encom-
heuristic more than realistic. passes both (see Table 35.1).
860 35 Staging Revolutions and Paradigms

Table 35.1 The relation of theory, metatheory, and paradigm metamodel in scholarship, in general, and science, in
particular
Area in construction
Stage Theory Metatheory/worldview Theory creation Paradigmatic
examples metamodel
Coordination Gathering extent data Gathering extant Domain; Coordinated
and concepts in domain metaconcepts in domain Development gathering of domain
of (empirical) inquiry of reflection components (facts,
constructs)
Hierarchization Subserving acquired Subserving acquired Stage modeling Hierarchical
knowledge to testable knowledge to criticism- arrangement of
hypotheses and their resistant metaconcepts knowledge and
(empirical) testing; impervious to falsification; critical analysis
proof of concept thought experiments
Systematization Creating mini-theories Creating Piagetian series Systematizing
(leaving the silos), mini-metatheories (e.g., infant mini-metamodels of
including with further sensorimotor knowledge base
(empirical) inquiry substage for object
permanence);
Erikson on steps in
identity
development
Multiplication Expanding broader Expanding broader Piagetian stage Multiplying
theories (leaving the metatheories (midrange) theory metamodel scope
silos), including further Eriksonian stage and application in
(empirical) inquiry theory domain(s)
Integration Integrating theory in Integrating metatheory Neo-Piagetian stage Integrative
the domain, including in the domain theory metamodeling
with further (empirical) Neo-Eriksonian
inquiry stage theory
Coordination Five-step process repeats in the multiple Combined Coordinating over
Neo-Piagetian/ domains
Neo-Eriksonian
stage theory
(Young, 2011, 2012)

In regards to the latter, scientists, scholars, and steps in my generic change model, then show
other deep thinkers move fluidly between theory how it applies to the change process in para-
creation and metatheoretical reflection. The con- digms. Specifically, the proposed five steps in
joint dialectic between the two modalities leads change in paradigm relate to the five steps in my
to creation of an integrated perspective on inves- generic change model of coordination, hierar-
tigation of the domains(s) at issue and metare- chization, systematization, multiplication, and
flection of their concepts, methods, and data or integration. The five-step change model is
field of elements. In my model, I refer to this described generically so that it can apply to any
intellectual process that serves toward integrating entity in change, within limits, including nonliv-
nature of theory and metatheory as meta- ing systems. In this regard, in Young (2011), I
modeling. Therefore, I added a column to the applied it to the development of scientific thought
table referred to as paradigmatic meta-modeling. related to developmental psychology and also to
Next, I describe the details of the model in the Darwinian evolution (see Chap. 12). Therefore,
table, and their relationship to my own models. I the model is amenable to extension toward
start on the left of the table by referring to the five explaining paradigm change.
A Neo-Kuhnian Approach 861

Steps impetus for data gathering might be a (testable)


hypothesis with an explicit prediction, or the idea
In this regard, the nested levels of growth in involved could be less specific.
thought about theory, metatheory, and paradig- (b) Either way, after having gathered (coordi-
matic metamodels that I have constructed in a nating) the key elements in a domain, the investi-
revised Kuhnian/Overtonian model of scientific gator then enters the step of hierarchization and
paradigms and their change consists of five lev- proceeds to develop a hypothesis of the model in
els, and these are based on the five levels of which new data are sought in the domain. The
change in Young’s (2011) model of change. investigator subordinates the search for data to
Using the same type of logic as used in my exten- some hypothesis or search concept. Methodology
sion of my five-step change model to growth in proceeds to operationalization and a design that
scientific thought in these two latter examples, I allows appropriate data gathering, and conse-
formulated five steps in change in each of the col- quent inference, which might end up concluding
umns in Table 35.1 related to the development of that either there is a lack of positive, supportive
theory, metatheory, and paradigmatic metamodel results (toward falsifiability) or, instead, support-
in the growth of scientific paradigm. ive ones of the hypothesis or search concept at
In addition, I repeated the coordination level issue.
at the end of the five-step series of paradigmatic The process described is explicit for science
change in order to indicate that the growth pro- but, for other areas of scholarship, it might apply
cess can continue after passage through the first and be implicit and aspirational, and perhaps
cycle through more advanced cycles, continuing having rigorous enough procedures and logical-
as each cycle is complete. In the present case, this based criticism and inference, thereby allowing
would refer to coordinating of paradigmatic “proof of concept.” The data involved in nonsci-
metamodels and their related metatheories and entific scholarship might not be the hard,
worldviews. In this regard, I do not maintain that empirical-type that science seeks but, neverthe-
relationism has become the predominant scien- less, still these data could be well-defined units of
tific paradigm, nor should it be exclusively so. information. Moreover, the relational stance that
That is, this should not be the case, given the is part of this integrated model that I have created
advantages of the empiricist, neopositivist, and does not admit to context-free, free-standing sci-
scientific realism approach. The latter worldview entific bits of information, given their constitu-
is in need of monitoring for its excesses (e.g., tive nature, so that the distinction between
reductionism), but it does not require scientific scientific and nonscientific data might not be as
surgery or a full ablation. Rather, it needs coordi- clear-cut as some presume.
nation with the former, the worldview of relation- (c) In the third step of theory construction,
ism. Therefore, it appears to me that we need a after the hierarchical phase and the one of coordi-
productive, constant dialectic between positiv- nation, the new data acquired might be organized
ism/empiricism and constructivism/relationism systematically into a theory, one that can be fur-
in scholarship/science, in general. The table indi- ther tested and one that can help explain the data
cates the five steps through which this suggested that has been gathered and allows for new predic-
process might proceed. tions. When new data deriving from hypothesis-
The column that is easiest to grasp in the table testing are relatively narrow in scope, the
relates to theory. The five steps involved in theory investigator is working toward creating mini-
building relate to: (a) selecting the domain and theories. If the data are inter-, trans-, or otherwise
coordinating the gathering of domain data and multidisciplinary, or even simply cross-domain
concepts. For science, data would refer to outputs within a discipline, the investigator might be
of observation, experimentation, and other legiti- leaving the “silo” toward higher-order data and
mate means of empirical investigation. The initial conceptual integration.
862 35 Staging Revolutions and Paradigms

(d) This process of theory construction accel- 25-step model, the characteristics of any one step
erates in the next step in theorizing, in which in the latter socioaffective sequence matched its
broader theories are created, perhaps with more pair in the former cognitive one. In short, the
synthetic methodologies and data-seeking proce- theory building process in which I engaged built
dures, as well a process that I refer to as multipli- on Piaget’s and Erikson’s extant theories to create
cation. The original systemic model is used to a superordinate model that expanded both of
traverse a broad range of areas in order to expand them so that the new proposed respective path-
its scope and also show its utility in reframing ways are seen to emerge in parallel and match
them in its image. over the lifespan.
(e) Next, in integrative theory building, inves- In doing this, looking back, I followed the
tigators build theories that encapsulate much of theory building model of five steps described in
the data and concepts in a domain, which allows the table.
for testable predictions of new supportive data by (a) That is, first, I coordinated the two major
way of falsifiable hypotheses, and also they per- prior Neo-Piagetian stage models in cognitive
mit valid critique of competing theories. The lat- development. In juxtaposing them, their overlaps
ter might include revealing their empirical and and lacunae became evident.
conceptual errors or limitations, explaining their (b) Then, based on the above juxtaposition, I
data and concepts in a better way, and so on. showed what was missing in each. I especially
[Indeed this type of criticism is part of the scien- found it useful to show how the missing elements
tific or logical reasoning process that should be in their models led to incorrect or incomplete
evident at each stage in theory construction.] understanding of the domain.
(c) This led to the creation of my own model
to accommodate to the missing and incorrect ele-
Example ments of the prior models. I showed how it could
better explain those inconsistencies and also indi-
The table gives an example of theory building cate new ways forward in understanding the field.
based on my own work (Young, 2011, 2012) on That I used what I consider Piaget’s best empiri-
the present 25-step model of development. The cal work, on the steps in infant sensorimotor
domain concerns my interest in finding parallel development, to elaborate the theory, seemed
cognitive and affective developmental sequences quite supportive of it. [My elaboration of
in development over the lifespan based on Erikson’s model did not depend on comparison
Piaget’s work, in particular. Both Case (e.g., of Neo-Eriksonian models because there have not
1992) and Fischer (1980; Fischer & Biddell, been any, aside perhaps Marcia’s work (1980) on
2006) had attempted an integration such as this. identity, which does not help in revising Erikson’s
In my conceptualization, I juxtaposed their mod- eight-step stage sequence.]
els in a table and compared and contrasted their The two integrative models that I created, one
approaches, leading to my own Neo-Piagetian cognitive and one socioaffective, not only were
model of five stages in development. Using built on prior theories and built to parallel each
Piaget’s sensorimotor series of steps in the other. That is, in this regard, I had attempted to
infancy period, I created generic labels for the create a more superordinate level of model
steps that could apply to early or later stages, or building.
any change process for that matter, even nonliv- Specifically, the Neo-Piagetian and Neo-
ing (this led to a 5 stage × 5 substage model). Eriksonian (sub)stage series that I created
Then, I created a comparable Neo-Eriksonian allowed the first-ever integrative, cross-domain,
sequence, adding 17 steps to his 8-step stage lifespan model in the field (Young, 2011, 2012).
sequence. I assured that within each step of the Therefore, I believe that I have reached the step
correspondence between the Neo-Piagetian and of systematization in my model building of
the Neo-Eriksonian sequences in the combined development and change.
Unifying Psychology 863

(d–e) Also, the level of theorizing is ready to Critical analysis and reasoning would be used,
proceed to the next integrative plane in my model but, as with all equivalent hierarchical steps in
(multiplication), and it is ready for further inte- theory and metatheory building, some of the first
gration after that. I have begun this process in tentative hierarchical arrangements could be sub-
Young (2014), and it continues in the present ject to revision or even complete change after fur-
work, including with the present model on theory, ther critical analysis. Eventually, a more
metatheory, and paradigmatic metamodel rela- systematic mini-metamodel would be created, to
tionships in scientific paradigm construction and use the language of the equivalent steps for the-
their own five-step evolution. An integrated the- ory and metatheory at this level. Once achieved,
ory on development, change mechanisms, causal- the model could be extended in the domain at
ity, and so on, awaits further thought and effort. issue, or even out of it, or otherwise applied and
This ends presentation of the theory building multiplied. Eventually, an integrated metamodel
component of the present model of growth in sci- could be created ready for coordination with oth-
entific paradigm, as presented in the table. In the ers over domains, in a cycle of a paradigmatic
following, I continue to apply the present model growth.
to theory building, this time to show how it can
help integrate or unify psychology itself.
Theories

Unifying Psychology The present work is based on many critical


sources other than those involving Piaget and
Modeling Erikson (see Fig. 35.2). The bottom portion of
the figure gives the names of critical theorists that
In the following, I review briefly the five steps in have influenced my understanding of causality
the evolution of metatheory or worldview. It (e.g., Gibson, Bowlby, but especially Darwin,
moves from a coordinated gathering of relevant whose evolutionary theory guided me in my doc-
material, to a hierarchical arrangement of knowl- toral dissertation; Young & Gouin Décarie,
edge, to a presumably inclusive and airtight 1977). The upper portion of the figure lists areas
model (called a metaconcept for present pur- of study important to the present work, especially
poses). The process involved might include those related to genetics and to the brain. There
thought experiments, as in philosophy. In system- are some areas of study important to psychopa-
atization, a mini-metatheory might be established, thology (e.g., differential susceptibility). Finally,
leading to its multiplicative expansion into a there are some that attempt to be unifying (e.g.,
broader, mid-range metatheory, which might then embodiment, dynamical systems theory, the bio-
lead to a more integrative one over the domain psychosocial model).
involved. The process might repeat at a superor- For the middle of the figure, I placed a concept
dinate level, leading to a dialectical fusion of that has not been considered as potentially unify-
competing or complementary metatheories into a ing but it cuts across many areas of brain and
higher-order union, through another cycle of the behavior and could be an important common uni-
five steps involved. fying behavioral mechanism (activation/inhibi-
In the process of creating paradigmatic tion coordination; Young, 2011). However, the
metamodels that reciprocally interrelate theory central concept of the present work, that of cau-
and metatheory at each step of their creation, the sality, would seem to be the most appropriate uni-
same five-step sequence applies. After coordinat- fying construct for psychology and related
ing information and constructing the theories and disciplines. It is central to every area of inquiry
metatheories involved, the knowledge acquired on the nature of humans, of nature itself, and of
would be tentatively arranged hierarchically in the world and universe. Perhaps because of its
what makes first sense for an overarching frame. centrality and pervasiveness, it has been left
864 35 Staging Revolutions and Paradigms

Biopsychosocial Model
(e.g., brain, self/ free Dynamical Systems
Neuronal will, culture) Model (self-organization,
Networks emergence, attractors)

New Genetics Embodiment


(G x E, rGE)

Differential
Epigenetics Susceptibility
Concept Bank
[Central Bank –
Programming, Activation/ Inhibition
Forecasting Diathesis-Stress
Coordination;
Currency – Causality]
Darwin (and life Gibson
history theory) (affordances)

Vygotsky
Bowlby (sociocultural)
(attachment)
Erikson Piaget
(psychosocial stages) Freud (cognitive
(psychodynamical developmental stages)
model)

Fig. 35.2 Influential theorizing contributing to the present model of causality as a unifying concept in psychology
(and science, scholarship) (noninclusive)

Table 35.2 Stages in scientific (natural, scholarly) exploration


Question
Level What information; observation; data (product) Why (process)
Coordination Surface search Tentative explanation
Hierarchization Subsurface probe Causal mapping
Systematization Deep micro understanding Mechanistic understanding
Multiplication Extension/application System-wide elaboration
Integration Broad macro understanding Global causality
Coordination Five-step process repeats in the multiple

aside in efforts to unify psychology. However, humans, of nature, and of the world/universe).
the present work is dedicated toward filling this The table indicates that the cardinal questions in
conceptual gap. our explorations in these regards concern the
“what” (product), or the description of the phe-
nomenon at issue (also other terms in this regard
The Model include the “which,” the “where”) and the “why”
(process) of the phenomenon at issue, or the cau-
Table 35.2 presents my concluding arguments on sality (also the “how”). We gather information on
the centrality of causality for the unification of a topic of interest, perhaps act to create new
psychology and of related disciplines (as well as information, draw back and reflect toward under-
any rigorous study or scholarship on the nature of standing it, and conjecture about the causes.
Unifying Psychology 865

Moreover, for each of the two major questions “co-existential.” One axis of the model pre-
at issue, of what and why, (and I acknowledge sented considers that some points of view on
they can be subdivided, as with Aristotle’s four the matter deny that knowledge acquisition of
causes and Tinbergen’s (1963) four questions), reality is a social process, while other schools
the answers become more refined as we proceed; do not. Another axis in the model relates to
moreover, I posit that the evolution of our under- whether objective reality influences its acquisi-
standing of the what and why of behavior follow tion, and opinions differ on this issue, too (see
the same five-step sequence as in other growth Table 35.3).
models in the present work. The combined epistemological view pre-
In this regard, at the level of the what, the five sented, which reflects the integration of the six
steps in growth in our inquiry concern surface approaches evident on the matter in the intersec-
search (coordination), subsurface probe (hierar- tion of the two axes of the model, melds the dif-
chization), forming a deeper understanding, but ferent constructivist and realistic tendencies in
at the micro level (systematization), extension/ epistemological stance. In this regard, the com-
application once achieved (multiplication), and bined or co-existential epistemological model
then a broad integrative macro-understanding. that I created describes a multifactorial, relativis-
For the question of why, the corresponding tic, and dialectical position on the validity of
causal advances move through tentative explora- each of the six perspectives involved in under-
tion in coordination, to causal mapping (in standing the knowledge acquisition process of
hierarchization), and then to the critical level of reality. On the one hand, objective elements in
mechanistic understanding in correspondence reality can “inform and dictate” their subjective
with deep micro-understanding. The last two construction by the individual. Moreover, this
steps refer to elaboration throughout the system might happen in a process of “social co-construc-
involved (multiplication) and, finally, global cau- tion.” On the other hand, at the same time,
sality for the macro integration level. although elements of an individual’s reality seem
Of course, casual “why” process elucidation especially constructed socially, there are also
could lag behind descriptive “what” product elu- objectives/elements in reality that would appear
cidation in the steps involved. At some point, the “universally apperceived.”
advances in what and why understanding The integrated epistemological model pre-
coalesce into a repeat process of differentiating a sented might make logical sense, but its manner
broader search and understanding of multiple of construction in each of us needs to go through
“whats” and “whys.” The human imperative asks its own learning process. In this sense, just as I
for nothing else. have described how science constructs paradig-
matic understanding, and that it appears that each
of the apparently contradictory positivistic and
Philosophy relational approaches have their positive attri-
butes that lend themselves to the development of
In the following, I provide another way that the a combined, superordinate science and scholar-
present five-step generic change model can be ship construction, each of the schools of thought
applied to philosophy, and take as a starting point in epistemology, although apparently contradic-
a model developed in Young (2011). Using my tory, have their positive attributes that lend them-
models of epistemology and of the change pro- selves to their unification in a superordinate
cess, I show how epistemological models can be co-existential model. The more realistic or con-
constructed toward increasing integration. structivist, schools of thought in epistemology
In terms of epistemology, in Young (2011), I might not be separable at all, and are constituted
presented a flexible, synthetic, overarching through their interaction (or intraaction), lending
stance about the constructed knowledge acqui- themselves to the creation of a superordinate
sition process of reality that I referred to as structure. Therefore, as we navigate these sticky
866 35 Staging Revolutions and Paradigms

Table 35.3 Epistemological stances about constructed knowledge acquisition of realitya

Is knowledge acquisition of Does objective reality influence its acquisition?


reality social? No Yes
Not relevant Reality is constructed (Radical, material Reality informs its gradual construction
constructivism) (Critical, final constructivism)
Not necessarily Constructing is reality (Existentialism) Reality dictates its construction
(Efficient, objective constructivism)
Yes Shared constructing is reality (Social, Reality informs its social construction
formal constructivism) (Coconstructivism)
The table summarizes six schools of thought about constructivist epistemology. They are classified according to their
perspective on two major issues: (1) Does objective reality influence knowledge acquisition? (2) Is knowledge acquisi-
tion always a process of social construction? Three of the six schools of epistemology being considered do not adhere
to the view that objective reality can influence very directly the acquisition of knowledge. First, radical constructivism
argues that reality does not influence the knowledge acquisition process and that reality is apprehended or invented
through mental approximations. In this view, social processes are not necessarily inherently important in knowledge
comprehension. Second, existentialism attributes fundamental importance to the social process in knowledge acquisi-
tion. Participatory co-beings share cultural meanings. In existentialism, constructing seems crucial in the acquisition of
knowledge. Third, social constructivism adds that only through social dialogue could constructs of reality emerge and
change. Three of the six epistemological schools under discussion argue that objective reality can directly affect the
process of knowledge acquisition. First, critical or alternative constructivism (e.g., Piaget) maintains that humans gradu-
ally acquire an increasing accuracy in their representation of reality through interactions with reality. Reality construc-
tion is not necessarily a social act, however. Second, efficient constructivism perceives reality’s roles as more direct and
immediate in fostering its own understanding. Social objects might be involved in the process of knowledge acquisition,
but not necessarily so. Third, in co-constructivism, objective reality always co-participates in or informs the social
dialogue in which conceptions of reality become formulated. The present approach is to consider each of the schools
valid, as none can take precedence or can even exclude the others in all circumstances in thought. Therefore, the model
that I am proposing is multifactorial, relativistic, and dialectical, but respects each of the approaches for their contribu-
tions to understanding knowledge acquisition and reality. Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business
Media. Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer
Science + Business Media; with kind permission from Springer Science + Business Media B. V. [Table 35.1, Page 810]
a
Also applies to the epistemology about constructed knowledge acquisition of paradigms

philosophical issues, the present five-step generic hierarchization, systematization, multiplication,


change model should apply to how the superordi- integration). For example, for the second stage
nate structure is created. of constructing superordinate abstract structures,
Given the presently suggested sequence of I have traced one integrated solution through these
coordination, hierarchization, systematization, five steps, as presented in Table 35.4.
multiplication, and integration in thought processes The general message that follows elaboration
within the development of abstract understanding of this five-step sequence for epistemological con-
and, then, in the development of superordinate struction is that it might help in most any complex
abstract understanding, grosso modo, first, at an problem solving and logical analysis. The second
abstract and then at a superordinate abstract level, message is that the integrated epistemological
it would seem that we might proceed through model presented in Table 35.4 can help decipher a
phases toward the integration of constructive and more complex model of the creation of paradig-
realist epistemologies. Specifically, in our search matic thought. It would appear that more than an
for understanding, we might grapple with how to integration of positivistic and relational perspec-
integrate the variants of the extant models within tives is required, as I had argued previously, in that
each of these epistemologies by passing through both views can be further differentiated along the
the five-stage sequence described (coordination, lines of the five steps suggested in the table.
Causal Self 867

Table 35.4 Epistemological construction according to the present five-step generic change model
Step Explanation
Abstract coordination Two models juxtaposed
Abstract hierarchization One hierarchized as predominant
Abstract systematization New system subsuming both created
Abstract multiplication Other extent models reworked into system
Abstract integration Integrated model developed
Superordinate abstract coordination Cycle repeats, e.g., for positivism or constructivism, depending on
which one had been developed first in the above, or perhaps both
develop. Ultimately, both streams might be integrated into an
overarching epistemological framework

direction to our behavior. In this regard, free will


Causal Self exists and helps render us causal selves.
For many models of behavior that we exam-
Introduction ine, there is room for personal contributions to
the causation of our behavior, with clear excep-
This section of the chapter stands as an overview tions found in reductionist views such as radical
of the book and its major theme that causality can behaviorism and extreme neuroscience. The self
help in the unification of psychology. I have can constitute the third force or tertium quid in
argued that causality is central to psychology in behavioral causality. Behavior can be emergent.
two major ways. First, it constitutes one part of Psychotherapy is based on the assumption that
the task to describe the “what” and the “why” of people can learn to take better control of their
behavior. Second, causality is central to our lives. Folk psychology admits to a belief in per-
thought and behavior. In this regard, I have called sonal control and common sense psychology
our species Homo Causa, and argued that the key would agree. The concept of the causal self
characteristic of the self is the causal one, leading helps unify these and related conceptions to
me to create the term of the “causal self.” In the indicate that the person can be an active agent in
following, I survey some critical concepts in the determining her or his own behavior and that
book that inform the concept of the causal self and behavior can emerge from its system beyond
also the importance of the causal self for grasping what the component pattern in the system at any
human nature and human exceptionality. one time might dictate. We are more than our
past and present when we intervene between
them and our future.
Model Causality can be graphed and analyzed statis-
tically in extremis, but in the end it is individually-
The present work emphasizes the essential role of determined, and created in context from moment
free will in behavior. It promotes the concept of to moment rather than reflecting statistical proce-
freedom in being (free will belief and having a dures and populations norms. Each moment of
sense of free will) as integral to the personal com- our lives can take new directions based on our
ponent to the biopsychosocial model of behavioral causality determinations, and components of our
causality. We ourselves potentially constitute the behavioral system, such as our self-determining
critical, active axis of the determining forces of causal axes in thought and behavior, can lead us
our behavior, even surpassing those of the more toward better adaptive ends than our biology and
passive but nevertheless potent forces of biology environment might dictate. We are causality
and environment. This concept helps specify the engines who function toward adaptive ends that
apex of causal action in the self, in which the free- are individually-determined, including in creation
dom of being, belief in free will, and having a of a better functioning causal self that can help
sense of free will contribute to the control and free us from those more passive influences on us.
868 35 Staging Revolutions and Paradigms

The section on the brain in the book refers to Neo-Piagetian model. The stages in the develop-
the connectome and the section on genes refers to ment of the causal self are called—(a) reflexive
multiple-omics. However, despite the fast- precausal, (b) sensorimotor causal, (c) periopera-
accelerating work on the biological contributions tional causal, (d) abstract causal, and (e)
to biology, as well as on the environmental side collective intelligence causal. The cognitive logic
(e.g., work on early adversity), behavior is always associated with each of the stages, can be charac-
a reflection of biological and environmental terized, respectively, as (a) nonlogical, (b) pre-
influences acting together. However, even that logical, (c) perilogical (which refers to
interaction is compounded by its interaction with quasilogical in the first preoperational part of the
each of us as independent, active agents contrib- stage and logical in the second concrete opera-
uting to our own causality. To explain behavior, tional part of the stage), and then (d) hyperlogi-
there is not just Nature or Nurture, or Nature and cal, and (e) logical at a collective superordinate
Nurture, but also Nature, Nurture, and Ourselves level. Therefore, in terms of working models for
(including our Causal Selves). free will and for the causal self, simply enough,
I have revised Maslow’s model of hierarchical one could describe them as, respectively, free
needs to integrate a tripartite distinction in the will/causal self—(a) precausal nonlogical mod-
self, which I refer to as the self-definitional self, els, (b) sensorimotor prelogical causal models,
relatedness self, and environmental or mastery/ (c) perioperational perilogical (quasilogical and
competent self. Certainly, the concept of the logical) causal models, (d) abstract hyperlogical
causal self can enrich understanding of the com- causal models, and (e) superordinate collective
ponent selves of this model. Moreover, in the intelligence causal models. Within each of the
model, the selves are considered to develop five stages in the development of these working
through five steps, ones related to my develop- models, as with other similar models in my work,
mental model and onto which Maslow’s five lev- they should pass through five substages related to
els of Maslow’s hierarchical needs map quite coordination, hierarchization, systemization,
well. In this regard, the growth of the causal self multiplication, and integration. To see how a
would seem to follow the same progression. Note model of stages with substages works in present-
that I applied my model to the growth of social ing cognitive development related to internal
self working models, a concept that I developed working models, refer to Tables 31.2–31.6 in
for attachment theory, and this model might Chap. 31 where social self working models/sche-
speak to the causal self, as well. mata applied to the development of the social
In Table 35.5, I elaborate further these ideas. self. These series of tables illustrate well how the
Essentially, the table indicates that the causal models/schemata related to free will/causal self
self develops in five stages according to my models would change over the lifespan.

Table 35.5 Free will/causal self working models


Stage Logic Free will/causal self working models
Reflexive precausal self Nonlogical Precausal nonlogical models
Sensorimotor causal self Prelogical Sensorimotor prelogical causal models
Perioperational causal self Perilogical Perioperational perilogical
(quasilogical and logical) (quasilogical and logical) causal models
Abstract causal self Hyperlogical Abstract hyperlogical causal models
Collective intelligence causal Collective superordinate Superordinate collective intelligence causal
self logical models
Adopted with permission of Springer Science + Business Media. Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science + Business Media; with kind permission from Springer
Science + Business Media B. V. [Third column: Table 17.1, Page 393]
References 869

Conclusion Theoretical models of human development (Vol. 1,


pp. 313–399). New York: Wiley.
Gadamer, H. G. (1989). Truth and method (J. Weinsheimer
In the present book I created many more concepts & D. Marshall, Trans.), (2nd ed.). New York:
related to causality, such as embodied causality, Crossroad. (Original work published 1960).
and together they could help in differentiating the Kuhn, T. S. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions.
Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
concept of the causal self. Causality would seem
Kuhn, T. S. (1970). The structure of scientific revolutions
to be a central unifying concept in psychology, (2nd ed.). Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
and the causal self could be helpful toward cen- Lakatos, I. (1970). Falsification and the methodology of
tral unifying concept for both. That being said, scientific research programmes. In I. Lakatos &
A. Musgrave (Eds.), Criticism and the growth of
the concept of causal self constitutes a heuristic
knowledge (pp. 91–196). New York: Cambridge
one, and our psychology might not include a sin- University Press.
gle central locus of causality-related personhood. Lakatos, I. (1978). The methodology of scientific research
As argued, the concept could help unify the study programmes: Philosophical papers (Vol. 1).
New York: Cambridge University Press.
of causality in behavior, psychology itself, and
Laudan, L. (1977). Progress and its problems: Towards a
perhaps even different concepts of the self, but theory of scientific growth. Berkeley, CA: University
not by itself nor toward considering it the be all of California Press.
and end all in behavioral causality. Marcia, J. E. (1980). Identity in adolescence. In J. Adleson
(Ed.), Handbook of adolescent psychology (pp. 159–
187). New York: Wiley.
Overton, W. F. (2013). Relationism and relational devel-
Chapter Conclusions opmental systems: A paradigm for developmental sci-
ence in the post-Cartesian era. In R. M. Lerner & J. B.
Benson (Eds.), Advances in child development and
The present chapter is recursive/reflexive one in
behavior. Embodiment and epigenesis: Theoretical
that it has elucidated how scientific paradigms and methodological issues in understanding the role
change, and I applied the model to understanding of biology within the relational developmental system.
how the model from which it was derived (Young, Part A: Philosophical, theoretical, and biological
dimensions (Vol. 44, pp. 21–64). Oxford, UK: Elsevier.
2011; on parallels in Neo-Piagetian and Neo-
Overton, W. F. (2015). Taking conceptual analyses seri-
Eriksonian (sub)stage acquisitions) reflects the ously. Research in Human Development, 12,
structuration and change process described in it. 163–171.
The Neo-Kuhnian model that I have developed Popper, K. (1959). The logic of scientific discovery.
London: Hutchinson.
has the potential to establish the change process
Popper, K. (1970). Normal science and its dangers. In
in any type of scholarship, not just science. I. Lakatos & A. Musgrave (Eds.), Criticism and the
Moreover, it illustrates, in general, that the growth of knowledge (pp. 51–58). New York:
generic change model that I have developed Cambridge University Press.
Tinbergen, N. (1963). On aims and methods in ethology.
based on the Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian
Zeitschrift für Tierpsychologie, 20, 410–433.
developmental model that I have created might Wittgenstein, L. (1958/1953). Philosophical investiga-
have extensive applicability. tions (G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.), (3rd ed.).
Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall. (Original work
published 1953).
Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
References Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer
Science + Business Media.
Case, R. (1992). Neo-Piagetian theories of child develop- Young, G. (2012). A unitary Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian
ment. In R. J. Sternberg & C. A. Berg (Eds.), model of development: Fundamental assumptions and
Intellectual development (pp. 161–196). New York: meta-issues. New Ideas in Psychology, 30, 241–249.
Cambridge University Press. Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feigning, and response
Fischer, K. W. (1980). A theory of cognitive development: bias in psychiatric/psychological injury: Implications
The control and construction of hierarchies of skills. for practice and court. Dordrecht, Netherlands:
Psychological Review, 87, 477–531. Springer Science + Business Media.
Fischer, K. W., & Biddell, T. R. (2006). Dynamic develop- Young, G., & Gouin Décarie, T. (1977). An ethology-
ment of action and thought. In W. Damon & R. M. based catalogue of facial/vocal behavior in infancy.
Lerner (Eds.), Handbook of child psychology: Animal Behavior, 25, 95–107.
New Directions in Psychological
Causality 36

topics of the book. In addition, I examine changes


Chapter Introduction in worldview with the model, as well as a mecha-
nism in change itself (activation–inhibition coor-
In this chapter, I review the models by (a) Barlow, dination). The chapter concludes with brief
Ellard, Sauer-Zavala, Bullis, and Carl (2014) on mention of the limits of my modeling endeavors.
neuroticism, (b) Verbruggen, McLaren, and Also, it asks to what degree causality can become
Chambers (2014) on self-control, and (c) Kopala- an integrating construct in psychology and to what
Sibley and Zuroff (2014) on self-definition and degree psychology can be integrated. It ends at the
relatedness. In addition, I present modifications beginning, returning to consider the book’s initial
of the graphic depictions of their models in light goals and the manner in which they were met.
of the generic approach adopted.
Based on their attempts to grasp the causality
in these areas, I created an integrated generic Models of Neuroticism, Self-Control,
graphic model of behavioral causality. The causal and Self/Other
model includes distal and proximal influences.
The central construct in the former type of influ- Neuroticism
ence is the biopsychosocial model. For the latter,
it involves an interaction of top-down, macro- Barlow et al. (2014) postulated that the origins of
and bottom-up micro-processes. For behavior, neuroticism lay in a set of triple vulnerabilities—
the outcome includes possible disorder and dys- a general biological one, a general psychological
function as well as normal behavior. The model one, and a specific psychological one (see
involves evolutionary and developmental factors, Fig. 36.1). Neuroticism develops when the psy-
and includes context. As a type of proof of con- chological vulnerability acts on the effects of ear-
cept, once the generic model was created, I pro- lier vulnerabilities.
ceeded to apply it to the area of free will and The general, largely learned psychological
self-control depletion. Then, I turned to applying vulnerability in the development of neuroticism
it to the area of Posttraumatic Stress Disorder consists of a heightened sense of unpredictability/
(PTSD). Also, it appeared to help see the larger uncontrollability, and associated effects resulting
picture of causality generally. from early adverse experience. The specific psy-
To close this last chapter of the book (and the chological vulnerability that is involved at the
book, as well), I return to my five-step generic time of the disorder helps channel the neuroticism
change model, in particular. I apply it to multiple developed from the general vulnerabilities into
areas, but focus on free will, one of the primary specific disorders. The general vulnerabilities

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 871


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_36
872 36 New Directions in Psychological Causality

1. Early 3. Later
biological psychological
vulnerability vulnerability

Dysregulation
Neurotic Disordered
of stress
Symptoms Emotions
response

2. Early
psychological
vulnerability

Fig. 36.1 The triple vulnerability model of neuroticism/ chological) and later psychological ones. The mediators
emotional disorder. Neuroticism/emotionally disordered include the early effects on the stress response. Adapted
behavior arises from both early vulnerabilities (biopsy- from Barlow et al. (2014)

apply earlier on, and they lead to early dysregula- In their model, Verbruggen et al. (2014) place
tion of neural circuits and hormonal functioning distal factors to the left. Development and learn-
associated with heightened response to stress, ing constitute factors that influence the more
threat, and fear, e.g., hyperexcitability and exag- proximal mechanisms in behavioral control. The
gerated or inappropriate arousal. latter mechanisms include rule construction, pre-
dictive control, and outcome monitoring. They
are facilitated by cue detection and selection,
Self-Control leading to execution of the behavior involved.

Verbruggen et al. (2014) presented a mechanistic


model of self-control involving (at the most basic Self/Other
level) cognitive processes of signal detection,
action selection, and action execution (see Kopala-Sibley and Zuroff (2014) developed a
Fig. 36.2). The authors argued that more general model of the origins of Blatt’s (2008) self-
concepts, such as the putative role of inhibition in definitional and relatedness domains (see
action control and behavior change, lack suffi- Fig. 36.3). Self-definition refers to the person’s
cient explanatory power. habitual patterns of thoughts, feelings, and
Models of Neuroticism, Self-Control, and Self/Other 873

Rule Proactive
Learning Outcome
acquisition control
Development (Associate) and (advance monitoring
maintenance preparation)

Cue Cue Action


Detection Selection Execution

Milliseconds/ seconds Minutes/ hours/ days Months/ years

Timeframe

Fig. 36.2 Cues and actions as the basis of behavior. The between cues and action (over different temporal frames
figure illustrates how rule acquisition/maintenance, proac- and with influences of learning and development
tive control/advance preparation, and outcome monitoring involved). Adapted from Verbruggen et al. (2014)
all involve detection/selection and execution in the link

Possible moderators (e.g.,


identification with parent)

Genes

Self-definition
Possible mediators Self
Genes may (e.g., internalized
moderate psychological Continued
parenting messages of experiences
worthlessness pertaining to
Early experience (“never good self-definition or
(e.g., parenting: control, enough”) relatedness
criticism, low care, abuse,
neglect)
Possible mediators Ecological
Temperament (e.g., internalized context
may moderate psychological
messages of Relatedness
parenting
unloveability (“no Self
one will love me”)

Temperament

Fig. 36.3 A proposed model of the development of self- sages of self-worth and loveability. Relative to the other
definition and relatedness. Based on the work of Blatt models in this chapter by Barlow et al. (2014) and
(2008) on self-definition and relatedness, Kopala-Sibley Verbruggen et al. (2014), the work of Kopala-Sibley and
and Zuroff (2014) developed a model that illustrates the Zuroff (2014) has provided a more detailed framework for
range of influences on their development. The influences understanding both distal and proximal factors in behav-
include distal genetic and temporal ones, as well as early ioral outcomes (e.g., genes, early experience, tempera-
experiences. The model includes proximal moderators ment, and mediators and moderators, respectively).
and mediators, including internalized psychological mes- Adapted from Kopala-Sibley and Zuroff (2014)
874 36 New Directions in Psychological Causality

actions directed toward oneself, while related- include in it (a) the development of self (self-
ness refers to their direction toward the other. definitional, relatedness) and also (b) action
Respectively, they involve the personality factors control [borrowed from Kopala-Sibley and
of self-criticism/autonomy/perfectionism and of Zuroff (2014), and Verbruggen et al. (2014),
dependency/sociotropy. The model developed by respectively]. In this regard, the Kopala-Sibley
Kopala-Sibley and Zuroff (2014) on self and and Zuroff (2014) work justifies the use of inter-
other includes distal influences, such as genes nal psychological messages in the integrated
and temperament, early developmental experi- model to accompany the Barlow et al. (2014)
ences (e.g., in parenting), possible mediators and emphasis on vulnerabilities [and susceptibilities
moderators (e.g., internalized psychological mes- (after Belsky & Pluess, 2009)] as well as specific
sages), and contextual and continuing experienc- later triggers; the Verbruggen et al. (2014) work
ing factors. justifies adding to it proximal micro- and macro-
genetic processes, such as in the detection and
selection of cues.
Revising the Models of Neuroticism, With this framework, I proceeded to develop a
Self-Control, and Self/Other generic model of behavioral causation in graphic
format. However, I sought to include the full pan-
Neuroticism oply of possible causal factors in behavior. In this
regard, first, I placed development and learning,
The figure created by Barlow et al. (2014) to rep- which are the first two of the five constructs
resent their triple-vulnerability model of neuroti- arrayed to the left in the Verbruggen et al. (2014)
cism could be altered to include some of the model, as part of the distal mechanisms that influ-
distal risk factors for neuroticism that they men- ence behavior. I placed these at the bottom of the
tioned, such as genetics and parenting practices. figure. Also, I added evolutionary mechanisms
In addition, one could add proximal risk factors, and context to the bottom of the figure.
such as internalized messages about the self and Once this latter step of integrating the work of
environment (for example, from attachment the- Verbruggen et al. (2014) into Barlow et al.’s
ory, being loved and loveable; see Young, 2011). (2014) model of neuroticism, I continued to add
Psychological factors include locus of control other components of their work to the model. In
(Rotter, 1966) and negative attributional style this regard, I placed the last of their five processes
(Alloy et al., 2012), as discussed in Barlow et al. of monitoring as part of the outcome configura-
(2014). Also, related to outcome, one could add tion constructed to the right in the figure, which
the behavioral and emotional dysregulation that includes their concept of triggers. Next, the basic
accompanies neuroticism and emotional disor- cognitive processes of detection and selection
der. Overall, one could encompass the model were organized as part of the influences on out-
within the biopsychosocial framework. come working in conjunction with triggering.
Finally, in constructing an integrated model of Note that the execution component of the triad of
the origins of neuroticism in the way indicated, cognitive processes in their model also was
one could borrow from a general framework for moved to the outcome portion of the revised
graphing behavior origins. The framework model. [Further work on Verbruggen et al.’s
should involve the biopsychosocial and distal model that I undertook is described in the next
factors placed to the left, physiological and neu- section of the chapter.]
ral (network) factors in the middle along with Given these parameters and considerations, I
other micro- and macro-processes in context, and developed a revised model of the origins of neu-
outcomes (e.g., disorders) to the right, along with roticism and emotional disorder. It includes not
monitoring and feedback functions. only Barlow et al.’s (2014) model as a starting
Additionally, in developing an integrated the- point (e.g., the triple vulnerabilities), but also
ory of neuroticism/emotional disorder, one could adds multiple biopsychosocial factors to the distal
Revising the Models of Neuroticism, Self-Control, and Self/Other 875

Distal Influences Proximal Influences Outcome/ Behavior


(mediated, direct; moderated, indirect)

Macroprocesses (e.g., in behavioral Specific


Early (Psychological)
(Dys)Control/ executive function)
Vulnerability Trigger

Behavioral Emotional
Biology (e.g., (Dys) (Dys)
genes) x Detection/ Execution/
Regulation Regulation
Environment Selection Monitoring/
(e.g., parents) Consequences
(x Self) (e.g.,
temperament) = (Dys)Regulated (Dys)functional Embodied
Neurotransmitter Cognitive (Reflexive/ Reflective) **Neuroticism **Emotional
Biopsychosocial
Neural Network Socio (Community) Affectivity Disorder
(distal
antecedent/ risk Stress Response (Reactivity)
resilience/ Influence on Influence on
facilitative Motivation Activation/ self/ internal other/ external
individualizing (Goal- Inhibition integrity integrity
factors) Direction) Coordination

Early Microprocesses Memory (Network/ State History)/


Susceptibility (e.g., online/ ongoing dynamic Message/ Meaning/ Mind (e.g.,
computational adaptation) valued, valuable, or not)

Learning
Development (and Accrued Experience)
Evolution
Context (Supportive/ Unsupportive)

** The stars indicate the unique aspects of the figure relative to the generic model.

Fig. 36.4 A revised model of the development of neuroti- (supportive, unsupportive). The early vulnerabilities/sus-
cism/disordered emotions. The two boxes containing the ceptibilities work to affect behavior not only through an
critical starred concepts of the diagram that are develop- altered stress response but also through effects on central
ing and transforming relate to effects that are both internal (neural, network), components. The proximal influences
(e.g., on the self concept) and external (e.g., on concepts include top-down macro-processes in behavior control/
of how one should interact with others). executive function and also bottom-up micro—ones,
For example, in the present case, one might develop including motivation/goal direction and activation/inhibi-
neuroticism, which concerns instability in relations, and tion coordination (Young, 2011). Micro-processes refer to
this might become a vulnerability factor for a specific men- online, ongoing adaptation (statistical, computational) that
tal disorder, but in each case there are effects on self- is dynamically adaptive. The proximal influences can be
concept both about the self and the social concept of the summarized as a vital preparatory state of the organism in
other. The figure expands the model of Barlow et al. (2014) terms of (dys)function in the multiple arenas of behavior,
by including causal influences under the categories of dis- from the physical (embodied) to the cognitive (reflexive to
tal, proximal, and outcome. In the following, I describe the reflective), to the social (community), to the affective
constitution of the model generically, and this description (reactive, as well). The action outcomes of the behavioral
applies to subsequent examples to which the generic model process that are executed include triggers that are detected/
is applied. Behavior is influenced causally by multiple fac- selected and also monitoring that leads to feedback. The
tors, from distal to proximal to concurrent. The distal vari- whole system involved retains a memory, which for either
ables include biological, psychological, and social ones, simpler organisms or epochs in development could be
including self factors. They include early vulnerabilities, referred to as state history or network adjustment. For
as well as susceptibilities (Belsky & Pluess, 2009). They either more advanced organisms or developmental epochs,
also include influences of evolutionary, developmental, system memories could involve internal messages with
and learning factors, all having their effects in context meaning in mind (e.g., I am valued, the world values me)

factors involved. Also, it adds an elaborate, medi- Self-Control


ating base intermediate between distal factors and
outcome (see Fig. 36.4). Also, I added the concept I revised the graph of Verbruggen et al.’s (2014)
of individualizing factors to the distal influences action/self-control model (see Fig. 36.5) to make
of the model. it consistent with my revision of Barlow et al.’s
876 36 New Directions in Psychological Causality

Distal Influences Proximal Influences Outcome/ Behavior


(mediated, direct; moderated, indirect)

Macroprocesses (e.g., in behavioral Specific


Early (Psychological)
(Dys)Control/ executive function)
Vulnerability Trigger
Biology (e.g.,
genes) x
Environment Behavioral Emotional
(Dys) (Dys) Detection/ Execution/
(e.g., parents) Selection Monitoring/
(x Self) (e.g., Regulation Regulation
Consequences
temperament) =
Biopsychosocial (Dys)Regulated (Dys)functional Embodied
(distal Neurotransmitter Cognitive (Reflexive/ Reflective) **Problem **Problem
antecedent/ risk Neural Network Socio (Community) Affectivity Discovery Solving
resilience/ Stress Response (Reactivity)
facilitative
individualizing Influence on Influence on
factors) Motivation Activation/ self/ internal other/ external
(Goal- Inhibition integrity integrity
Direction) Coordination

Early Microprocesses Memory (Network/ State History)/


Susceptibility (e.g., online/ ongoing dynamic Message/ Meaning/ Mind (e.g.,
computational adaptation) valued, valuable, or not)

Learning (Associative)
Development (and Accrued Experience)
Evolution
Context (Supportive/ Unsupportive)

Fig. 36.5 A revised model of action control and behavior generic but that are specific to the area of study, in this
change. The figure illustrates how the model of action case action/self-control, I placed in the boxes the terms
control in Verbruggen et al. (2014; see Figure 36.2) can be Problem Discovering and Problem Solving. This is con-
modified according to a generic template of the causality sistent with the focus of the Verbruggen et al. (2014)
of behavior. For the two boxes in the model that are not article

(2014) model of neuroticism. Notice that I Self/Other


included behavior/emotional (dys)regulation as
top-down influences of the micro–macro proxi- In Fig. 36.6, I present a revised model of Kopala-
mal processes in behavioral determination. In Sibley and Zuroff’s (2014) model of the develop-
this regard, motivation and activation/inhibition ment of self-definition and relatedness. I place
coordination constitute bottom-up micro- distal factors at the left, along with the general
processes in ongoing/online dynamic (computa- label of an inclusive biopsychosocial model. The
tional) adaptation. For the central portion in the middle of the diagram includes relevant proximal
model of proximal influences on outcome/behav- processes, both micro- and macro-, of which self-
ior, I included the concepts of embodiment and regulation (control, behavioral, emotional), gen-
cognitive social affectivity. The added terms erally, constitutes an important one. At the right
(reflexive/reflective for cognition; community of the model, I place outcomes, in particular, as
for social, and reactivity for affectivity) are related to self-definition and relatedness selves.
included to make the model applicable to most Also, to the right I place other aspects, such as the
species and also to early phases of development internalized psychological messages, as well as
of any species. The addition of these constructs action execution and monitoring, which were
to the present generic model of behavioral cau- mentioned in the elaboration of more inclusive
sality is justified at different junctures of the models for both neuroticism and action/self-
present work. control discussed previously.
Revising Free Will 877

Distal Influences Proximal Influences Outcome/ Behavior


(mediated, direct; moderated, indirect)

Early Macroprocesses (e.g. in behavioral Specific


Vulnerability (Dys)Control/ executive function) (Psychological)
Trigger

Biology (e.g., Behavioral Emotional Detection/ Execution/


genes) x (Dys) (Dys) Selection Monitoring/
Environment Regulation Regulation Consequences
(e.g., parents)
(x Self) (e.g.,
temperament) = (Dys)Regulated (Dys)functional Embodied **Self- **Relatedness
Biopsychosocial Neurotransmitter Cognitive (Reflexive/ Reflective) Definitional Self
(distal Neural Network Socio (Community) Affectivity Self (Components)
antecedent/ risk Stress Response (Reactivity) (Components)
resilience/
facilitative Motivation Activation/ Influence on Influence on
individualizing (Goal- Inhibition self/ internal other/ external
factors) Direction) Coordination integrity integrity

Early Microprocesses Memory (Network/ State History)/


Susceptibility (e.g., online/ ongoing dynamic Message/ Meaning/ Mind (e.g.,
computational adaptation) valued, valuable, or not)

Learning
Development (and Accrued Experience)
Evolution
Context (Supportive/ Unsupportive)

Fig. 36.6 A revised model of the development of self- The figure presents a revised model of self-definition and
definition and relatedness. The model in the figure is a relatedness development. Both of the latter are central to
variation of the generic one developed on the basis of the Blatt’s (2008) model of polarities of experience. For the
ones by Barlow et al. (2014) on neuroticism/emotional two boxes in the model that are not generic but that are
disorder, Verbruggen et al. (2014) on action control, and specific to the area of study, I placed in the boxes the terms
Kopala-Sibley and Zuroff (2014) on self-development. related to self-definition and relatedness

Revising Free Will of their psychology and their origins. However,


by adopting a biopsychosocial framework for
Finally, it is worth noting that the present effort to their multifactorial expression and causality, as
model generically the causality of behavior in being done presently, they are placed more cen-
graph format has been constructed to the point trally in a generic causal understanding of behav-
that it can accommodate most any behavior. All ior, including its mechanisms.
that is needed is to include the behavior of inter- For the topic of free will, Fig. 36.7 indicates the
est in the two starred boxes, as I have done for relationship of free will belief and having a sense
neuroticism, for example. In this regard, one of free will. The former is more cognitive, and the
major focus of the present work is on free will latter is more affective. They express an intimate
belief. Therefore, a comprehensive model of the reciprocity. As for ego/resource depletion, a deplet-
construct would place it in the present graphical ing task in self-control needs to be understood in its
model of behavioral causality in the way indi- broad biopsychosocial context of self-regulation
cated (see Fig. 36.7). In Fig. 36.8, I made a simi- (cognitive/affective). Therefore, although deple-
lar graph for ego/resource depletion, which is tion might obtain in the laboratory for a sequence
related to free will and self-control. In both cases, of relevant tasks, the characteristics and origins of
the constructs have been limited in contemporary ego/resource depletion involve broad factors that
study in terms of understanding the complexity complicate any simple understanding of its effects.
878 36 New Directions in Psychological Causality

Distal Influences Proximal Influences Outcome/ Behavior


(mediated, direct; moderated, indirect)

Specific
Macroprocesses (e.g., in behavioral (Psychological)
Early (Dys)Control/ executive function) Trigger
Vulnerability

Behavioral Emotional
Biology (e.g., Detection/ Execution/
(Dys) (Dys)
genes) x Selection Monitoring/
Regulation Regulation
Environment Consequences
(e.g., parents)
(x Self) (e.g., (Dys)functional Embodied
temperament) = (Dys)Regulated **Free Will **Having a
Cognitive (Reflexive/
Biopsychosocial Neurotransmitter Belief Sense of Free
Reflective) Socio (Community)
(distal Neural Network Will
Affectivity (Reactivity)
antecedent/ risk Stress Response
resilience/ Influence on Influence on
facilitative Motivation Activation/
(Goal- Inhibition self/ internal other/ external
individualizing
Direction) Coordination integrity integrity
factors)

Microprocesses
(e.g., online/ ongoing dynamic Memory (Network/ State History)/
Early
computational adaptation) Message/ Meaning/ Mind (e.g.,
Susceptibility
valued, valuable, or not)

Learning
Development (and Accrued Experience)
Evolution
Context (Supportive/ Unsupportive)

Fig. 36.7 Model of the causality of free will belief and ences in free will belief and their origins. Free will belief
having a sense of free will. This model is consistent with is the cognitive component of a broader concept of free
the present generic approach to understanding the causal- will that I have developed, which includes the affective
ity of behavior in graphic format, including in terms of component of having a sense of free will. These two
distal and proximal factors from a biopsychosocial per- aspects of the psychology of free will stand in a reciprocal
spective and also with developmental and evolutionary relationship and mutually influence each other, aside from
influences taken into consideration, in particular. The being influenced by a multiple biopsychosocial factors
model is applicable to the question of individual differ- presented in the graph

The power of the present generic model of the literature relating PTSD to general negative
causality is that it opens up new avenues of inves- affectivity (see Chap. 21).
tigation to the behavior of interest that might not
have been evident beforehand. Also, it suggests
that common causal mechanisms and pathways Further Revising Causality
govern the causality of multiple behaviors, and of Behavior
findings in one area could speak to others.
To close the book, I propose other ways the pres-
ent generic change model can be applied to the
Revising PTSD major themes of the present work. Also, I focus
on the integrative nature of the biopersonalsocial
In this regard, I have placed the disorder PTSD (biopsychosocial) model that I have created, as
in the context of the generic model of behav- well as my Neo-Piagetian (sub)stage model. The
ioral causality that I have developed (see last portion of the book is presented especially in
Fig. 36.9). It includes an interaction between tabular and figure format, with table notes and
instability and the expression of the disorder. figure captions providing much detail. These
This parallels the graph for neuroticism, in tables and figures should be considered as pro-
which this instability stood in interaction with posals for future directions in the synthetic effort
emotional disorder. Also, it is consistent with constituted by the present work.
Further Revising Causality of Behavior 879

Distal Influences Proximal Influences Outcome/ Behavior


(mediated, direct; moderated, indirect)

Specific
Macroprocesses (e.g., in behavioral (Psychological)
Early Trigger
(Dys)Control/ executive function)
Vulnerability
Biology (e.g.,
genes) x
Behavioral Emotional Detection/ Execution/
Environment
(Dys) (Dys) Selection Monitoring/
(e.g., parents)
(x Self) (e.g., Regulation Regulation Consequences
temperament) =
Biopsychosocial (Dys)Regulated (Dys)functional Embodied **Task 1 **Task 2
(distal Neurotransmitter Cognitive (Reflexive/ Reflective) (Depleting) (Depleted?)
antecedent/ risk Neural Network Socio (Community) Affectivity
resilience/ Stress Response (Reactivity)
facilitative
individualizing Influence on Influence on
factors) Motivation Activation/ self/ internal other/ external
(Goal- Inhibition integrity integrity
Direction) Coordination

Early Microprocesses Memory (Network/ State History)/


Susceptibility (e.g., online/ ongoing dynamic Message/ Meaning/ Mind (e.g.,
computational adaptation) valued, valuable, or not)

Learning
Development (and Accrued Experience)
Evolution
Context (Supportive/ Unsupportive)

Fig. 36.8 A revised model of the development of ego- consist of a potentially depleting one and then a possibly
depletion. Free will exercise is related to effective option depleted one. Given the biopsychosocial nature posited
selection and implementation. It requires good executive for depletion, the typical depletion tasks might not actu-
function. However, the resources in self-control are ally work as indicated in laboratory studies. Moreover, in
depletable. Engaging in a demanding task that diminishes valid ecological contexts, we engage constantly in poten-
one’s sense of self-control could affect performance on a tially self-control depleting tasks but multiple factors
similar task afterwards. The ego or resource depletion might act to inhibit or activate the effects of putatively
model is a unidimensional one on force of will being valid self-control depletion tasks on actual self-control
important in depletion effects in self-control. However, I depletion, as in successive maintenance or loss of self-
have argued that self-control depletion is multifactorial control over a series of potentially self-control depleting
and involves biological, psychological, and social factors, tasks (that is, in ecologically valid contexts, there might
including motivation. be more than two depletion tasks involved). Finally, even
The generic model of causality that I have developed the anticipation of participating in the first task might
not only is applicable to free will belief/having a sense of already alter self-control in a subsequent one, so the tasks
free will, as in Figure 36.7, but also it is applicable to the often stand in a reciprocal relationship
depletion effect. That is, Tasks 1 and 2 in a depletion study

Table 36.1 indicates how the present five-step ment might arise according to the present Neo-
generic change model can apply to a single acqui- Piagetian stage model.
sition, and not just the synchronization of two, as The next graphics relate to the present bioper-
has been emphasized to date. Table 36.2 shows sonalsocial model (Tables 36.5, 36.6, 36.7, and
how this might apply to the acquisition of free 36.8 and Fig. 36.10). The first shows how it has
will belief. developed from the biopsychosocial one and can
The next two tables relate to the overarching be extended. The second indicates its relation to
concept of the present work of Freedom in Being the worldview of relationism as well as other key
(Tables 36.3 and 36.4). The first table of the two models that are described in the present work. The
shows how its two components of free will belief third one indicates its relationship to the basic
and having a sense of free will can come to inte- freedoms in brain, behavior, and being. The next
grate. The second table illustrates how the free table indicates how the worldview of relationism
decision process that accompanies its develop- constitutively incorporates other worldviews and
880 36 New Directions in Psychological Causality

Distal Influences Proximal Influences Outcome/ Behavior


(mediated, direct; moderated, indirect)

Specific
Macroprocesses (e.g., in behavioral (Psychological)
Early Trigger
(Dys)Control/ executive function)
Vulnerability
Biology (e.g.,
genes) x
Behavioral Emotional Detection/ Execution/
Environment
(Dys) (Dys) Selection Monitoring/
(e.g., parents)
(x Self) (e.g., Regulation Regulation Consequences
temperament) =
Biopsychosocial (Dys)Regulated (Dys)functional Embodied **Posttraumatic
(distal Neurotransmitter Cognitive (Reflexive/ Reflective) **Instability/ Stress Disorder
antecedent/ risk Neural Network Socio (Community) Affectivity Resilience (PTSD)
resilience/ Stress Response (Reactivity)
facilitative
individualizing Influence on Influence on
factors) Motivation Activation/ self/ internal other/ external
(Goal- Inhibition integrity integrity
Direction) Coordination

Early Microprocesses Memory (Network/ State History)/


Susceptibility (e.g., online/ ongoing dynamic Message/ Meaning/ Mind (e.g.,
computational adaptation) valued, valuable, or not)

Learning
Development (and Accrued Experience)
Evolution
Context (Supportive/ Unsupportive)

Fig. 36.9 A revised model of the development of post- disorder. The figure illustrates that it can help explain the
traumatic stress disorder (PTSD). The generic behavioral multifactorial causal nature of PTSD
causality model can be applied to most any psychiatric

should not necessarily deny a place for them. The motivation. The generic model created also
last table of the present book indicates how the includes room for a role in causation of develop-
basic change mechanisms presumed to underlie ment and learning as well as evolution, while
development—that of activation/inhibition coor- considering context (e.g., supportive, unsupport-
dination—can grow through the present five-step ive). The model is generic, but it is equally highly
generic change model to become flexibly adaptive individualistic in that the causal nexus that char-
in governing brain, behavior, self, and their acterizes any one individual for any one outcome
growth. of focus applies uniquely to that person.
The generic model of behavioral causality that
I have created includes a major section on inter-
Chapter Conclusions mediate, proximal influences that mediate
between distal ones and outcome. They include
The generic change model of behavioral causal- both macro- and micro-processes. The former
ity that I have developed integrates the major involve behavior/emotional (dys)control/(dys)
themes of the present book. As a general frame- regulation, in particular. The latter involve moti-
work, I adopted the biopsychosocial model. It vation and ongoing processes in adaptation, such
afforded me the opportunity to list biological, as facilitated by activation/inhibition coordina-
environmental, and self-factors as part of the tion. At the core of micro/macro processes in
causal factors in behavior. The model considers proximal influences on behavior lie embodied
as part of the constellation of forces in the origins cognitive and socioemotional (re)activity/(dys)
of behavior early distal ones, aside from more functionality. The site of early dysregulation in
immediate proximal, triggering ones. Mediators behavior lies in the stress system. When it is dys-
between distal and proximal influences in behav- regulated, the effects extend beyond the HPA
ioral causality are important to consider, e.g., (hypothalamic pituitary adrenal) axis and related
Chapter Conclusions 881

Table 36.1 Two pathways toward system integration Table 36.2 Steps in growth of free will (belief, having a
sense)
Indeterminate
Step Juxtaposition presence Growth in having
Coordination A, B A, Ā Growth in free a sense of free
Step will beliefa willb
Hierarchization A×B A/Ā
Coordination
Systematization AB A FWB, FWB SFW, SFW
Multiplication AB1 × AB2 × A1 × A2 × Hierarchization
FWB × FWB SFW × SFW
Integration ABi Ai
Systematization FWB SFW
Note. A = phenomenon present; Ā = absent
Multiplication FWB1 × FWB2 × SFW1 × SFW2 ×
B = second phenomenon
× = interaction, can also be represented by U; as the inter- Integration FWBi SFWi
action solidifies, one or the other component becomes The figure depicts the steps in the development of compo-
predominant, perhaps variably nents of freedom in being through the five steps of the
To this juncture in my theoretical work on the generic proposed generic change model:
change model and its applications to development, I have (a). First, in the step of the coordination, the person
considered the first step of coordination as involving the develops the component involved, but not in a full manner
juxtaposition of two components, which then proceed to a (only partially in one or some) context(s) or domain(s).
hierarchical organization across them, leading to their The person deals with the juxtaposition of having the
systematization and, ultimately, to their integration. component either actively present or not having it,
However, another pathway from coordination to integra- depending on context, state, etc., in a transitional manner.
tion in generic/developmental change could involve the (b). In the next of hierarchization, the component takes
juxtaposition of a component transiently or partially pres- hold and comes to dominate its lack of presence. The per-
ent with its absence. Then, as the component grows in son might oscillate between its presence and lack, but its
presence, it creates a hierarchical arrangement involving increasing presence resolves the cognitive (and emo-
its presence primary relative to its absence. This then tional) dissonance of its lack toward its presence.
leads to its systematization as fully present, preparing the (c). Eventually, the component is systematized to its full
way to multiplying it out and then being integrated more presence in the context(s)/domain(s) at issue.
fully over the domain in question (d). Then, the component spreads throughout the psy-
chological architecture involved. At each expansion, the
dissonance described above manifests and resolves.
stress response components to related neurotrans-
(e). Finally, it becomes a generalizable constant presence
mitters and neuronal networks. In early adversity, Note. aFree Will Belief = FWB; not having it is repre-
fetal or early programming might take place and sented by FWB
b
serve to fix heightened stress reactivity in the Having a Sense of Free Will = SFW; not having it is rep-
resented by SFW
long term.
The output portion of the generic model of
behavioral causation that I have developed To conclude the chapter (as well as the book),
involves a specific trigger being activated, or it is important to note the limits of the generic
somehow involved, which leads to detection/ behavioral causality model that I have created.
selection and then behavioral execution and its First, although it includes development as part of
consequences. Both the self and other are the causal change process, it does not try to dif-
affected. The message/meaning of the outcome ferentiate the role of various developmental mod-
behavior become embedded in memory/mind. els in its working, including the present
Behavior causality involves much more than Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian 25-step develop-
this generic overview. At the same time, often mental model. Also, the disadvantage of being a
workers do not try to see the overall scope of the generic model is that it might not apply equally to
causality that might be involved in their area of all behavioral phenomena. In this sense, the limits
interest, and their models end up narrow in of the model include both under-reach and over-
scope. Hopefully, the present generic model of reach. Future work on the causality of behavior
behavioral causality and, as well, the book, in can address these lacunae in the present model-
general, helps broaden understanding of behav- ing, not only for the ones in the present chapter
ioral causality. but also for all those presented in this book.
882 36 New Directions in Psychological Causality

Table 36.3 Origins of a comprehensive model of of behavior and how it can go awry and become
free will
disturbed.
Steps Model Therefore, the goals that I have adopted for
Coordination Free will, having a sense of free will the book have not only theoretical importance
Hierarchization Free will × having a sense of free will but also practical relevance. Having an integrated
Systematization Freedom in Being
understanding of the “why” of behavior neces-
sarily compliments and guides understanding of
Free Will x Having a the “what” of behavior. Understanding the sys-
Sense of Free Will = FOB
tem of behavior means understanding the product
(or outcome), as well as the process (or multiple
Freeing the Brain determining factors). In this regard, the book
Multiplication FOB1 × FOB2 × highlights a model of behavior that is multifacto-
Integration FOBi rial, biopsychosocial, and integrative of Nature,
The figure illustrates the manner in which the components Nurture, and the self as major factors in the ori-
in the growth of freedom in being conjoin into a system- gins of behavior.
atized and integrated psychological entity. Freedom in
being appears to be a psychological emergence that relates
Moreover, the self is not a passive agent in
to the most mature psychological acquisition, along with behavioral causality, but an active one. Further,
concepts such as wisdom and Eriksonian generativity: the self is characterized potentially by freedom in
(a). In the step of coordination, the two components are being, or grows toward it, depending on the age
juxtaposed
(b). Next, they begin to cohere, with the absence of
of the person involved. Freedom in being involves
coherence subordinate to its presence a belief component and a sense of having free
(c). Next, the components form a system, with a coher- will. Both need to develop appropriately, and
ing entity emerging of freedom in being that encompasses they are part of our evolutionary heritage because
both
(d). Then, the systematization process in the prior stage
of their adaptive significance. Behavior can be
expands over contexts/domains emergent from the full system, which it is embed-
(e). Finally, an integrative freedom in being emerges that ded both internally and externally in the possibil-
is generalized across contexts/domains, in a constant way ity of an emergence of, and this includes freedom
in the person
in being.
Paradoxically, as we mature into freedom in
being, we choose to limit our freedoms especially
to our primary responsibilities, such as self,
family, work, and society. I refer to this undertak-
Book Conclusions ing of our responsibilities as Re-Responsibilities.
Freedom in being means approaching with psy-
The End chological maturity each of our responsibilities
and rededicating ourselves constantly to them.
The goal of the present book has been to empha- Therefore, my understanding of the integrated
size the centrality of causality in the study of nature of causality and its capacity to help inte-
behavior and to support it as an integrative focus grate psychology places at its apex the concept of
in psychology. These goals are ongoing ones for freedom in being and all that it entails for behav-
which I have made some progress and which ior. Asking to place causality as the integrating
need further work to arrive at satisfactory ends. force in psychology is insufficient without hav-
Both goals are daunting ones, but the expansive ing a model of the ultimate nature of the human
range of the book suggests that both goals are condition, which includes a place for free will,
reachable. Both the “what” and the “why” of and a critical one at that. In this regard, I hope the
behavior need to be understood in depth in order present book has offered a model of causality that
to obtain a more complete insight into the nature integrates key causal factors.
Book Conclusions 883

Table 36.4 Stages in the development of freedom in being


Stage Substage Free decision Growth in free being
Collective Integration Superordinate free-decision Superordinate freeing
intelligence (sense, being, brain) theories/meta-ethics theories/orientations
(Neo-Piagetian Multiplication Superordinate free-decision (sense, being, Superordinate freeing
(adult) postformal brian) principles principles
stage) Systematization Superordinate free-decision Superordinate freeing
(sense, being, brain) codes guidelines/codes
Hierarchization Superordinate free-decision (sense, being, Superordinate freeing rules/
brain) rules techniques/procedures
Coordination Particular superordinate free-decision Particular superordinate
(sense, being, brain) cases (dilemmas) freeing cases (dilemmas)
Abstract (Piagetian Integration Free-decision (sense, being, brain) theory Freeing theory/orientation
(adolescent) formal Multiplication Free-decision (sense, being, brain) principle Freeing principle
stage) Systematization Free-decision (sense, being, brain) code Freeing guideline/code
Hierarchization Free-decision (sense, being, brain) rule Freeing rule/technique/
procedure
Coordination Particular free-decision (sense, being, Particular freeing case
brain) case (dilemma) (dilemma)
Adapted from Young (2014), Table 24.3
Note. The two prior figures indicate the manner in which the growth in freedom in being takes place microdevelopmen-
tally, without considering the underlying limitations imposed by the general cognitive development of the person (and
associated socioaffective development). Young’s (2011) Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian model of 25 steps in develop-
ment (5 stages × 5 substages) considers the last 10 steps to develop according to Piaget’s formal, abstract adolescent-
initiated stage, and then a postformal Neo-Piagetian one in the adult termed collective intelligence. Young (2014) applied
this model to the steps in the growth of ethical thought, showing how it could pass through the sequence of considering
cases, rules, codes, principles, and theories first at a uniconstruct level then at a superordinate construct level.
In the table, I have modified the model of development of ethical thought to apply to growth in free being, doing so by
proposing a developmental sequence in the thought process of free decision making akin to the ethical one, which then
undergirds the corresponding growth in free being. The concept of free being revolves around growth in free will belief
and having a sense of free will, which is included in the decision-making column. Also, it mentions the free brain based
on Friston’s work of the brain adapting to minimizing free energy as it attempts to reduce uncertainty. Finally, consistent
with the theme of the table, I refer to the decision-making process in the growth of freedom in being as one of “free
decision” making.
As for the growth of free being itself as facilitated by the growth in free decision making capacity, I refer to the sequence
from case to theory as “freeing” case(s), rule(s), code(s), principle(s), and theory(ies) passing sequentially through the
successive stages of uniconstructs and superordinate ones (in the abstract and collective intelligence stages,
respectively).
To conclude, the present model of the growth of freedom in being is based on a Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian (sub)
stage model. The growth is limited cognitively by the constraints of the corresponding Neo-Piagetian cognitive acquisi-
tion. Perhaps more importantly, also it is limited by the difficulties that might arise in the corresponding Neo-Eriksonian
socioaffective acquisitions. In this sense, the proposed model of the growth of freedom in being might provide a valu-
able framework not only in understanding the person but also in working through psychotherapy toward improving
freedom in being

The Beginning First, it has considered many of the fundamen-


tal assumptions behind the book that had been
This book on causality of behavior constitutes a laid out at its beginning, but one that needs fur-
grand project. In this epilogue, I look back to its ther elaboration is the issue of behavioral change.
roots in the first few chapters, in order to give a Causality is about changing inertial forces so that
survey of how it has addressed some of its pri- change takes place; as well, it refers to arriving at
mary goals in these regards. changes that do not simply and always reflect on
884 36 New Directions in Psychological Causality

Table 36.5 Steps in the development of biopsychosocial genes/epigenetics and differential susceptibility
understanding
models; cognitive appraisals; and sociocultural
Steps Model and environmental context, including of early
Coordination Medical model (biology); adversity; (c) the self, including of free will
Psychosocial factor (PS)
working models in psychotherapy; and (d) non-
Hierarchization Biopsychosocial model (BPS)
linear dynamical systems models and related
(e.g., in illness, in
psychotherapy) ones in the network model.
Systematization Biopersonalsocial model (BPS Third, the book has elaborated many of the
revised = BPSr) areas in Fig. 3.4 in Chap. 3 on the causality land-
Multiplication BPSr1 × BPSr2 × scape, making it genuinely interdisciplinary. For
Integration BPSri example, aside from its heavy emphasis on major
Note. The table illustrates the evolution of the biopsycho- biological fields, such as neuroscience, genetics,
social model. It integrates the medical (biological) and evolution, and psychiatry, as well as many areas
psychosocial dualistic notions of illness/disease and how
of development, it examines the philosophy of
to treat it. In my version of it, I refer to the biopersonalso-
cial model in order to accentuate that all three components causality, the view of Big History on causality,
contribute to the psychology of illness. The model can be the psychiatric approach to psychopathology and
expanded beyond illness conceptions to areas such as its diagnosis in the DSM-5 (Diagnostic and
development. Finally, it can grow to represent a compre-
Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, Fifth
hensive integrative framework for behavior and causality
Edition; American Psychiatric Association,
a one-to-one, direct basis changes in incoming 2013), causality in law, statistical approaches to
energy, information, or stimulus parameters. In causality, and systems and network approaches to
psychology, this means that behavioral changes causality.
are person-mediated as much as biologically- or As the area of study of causality in psychol-
environmentally-mediated, and that even a minor ogy and related disciplines continues to cohere,
alteration to input might effect large behavioral there will be increasing conceptual refinement,
change (even a self-organizational, emergent empirical study, and applications to practice and
one) or, in contrast, that a major alteration in this society that will be beneficial and that will lead to
regard might effect no change in behavior. causality taking its rightful place as an interdisci-
In this regard, the present book presents mod- plinary lynchpin. The present book has begun
els of change, including generic and develop- with this proposition and is meant to inspire oth-
mental ones, that address these and related issues. ers along this journey.
For example, based on my cognitive develop- Humans are the products of an exquisitely
mental (sub)stage model of development, I complex causality. In this regard, we thrive when
expanded it to address socioaffective develop- we understand causality and use it effectively,
ment (Neo-Eriksonian and Neo-Maslovian mod- whether in the intrapersonal, interpersonal, or
els) and analogous generic change in scientific material worlds. Also, part of our essence is about
paradigms (a Neo-Kuhnian model). causality. In this regard, I have referred to our
Second, the book has considered the dimen- species as Homo Causa and the self as causal.
sions that had been posited for causality (in rela- Humans are unique in many ways, and aside from
tion to free will). These include: the dimensions the free will that I have emphasized in this vein,
of (a) time, (b) the person, as in the biopsycho- the subject of causality also marks our exception-
social model, (c) self-control, and (d) mecha- alism. It is a privilege to be a sentient human on
nism. Examples of the dimensions that have this planet, which is in so much need of our wis-
been addressed in the present book include, dom. The proper understanding of causality and
respectively: (a) the proximal and distal time- its implications and applications might constitute
frames; for example, respectively, immediate one axis to help us to improve we, ourselves, and
stimulus-organism-response dynamics and evo- all those around us, as well as the planet that is so
lution and life history theory; (b) the brain, heavily dependent on us.
Book Conclusions

Table 36.6 Organization of predominant themes in an integrative framework for psychology focusing on the biopsychosocial model
Step Theme Example Cross-step
Integration Metatheory/worldview Relationism Causality
Multiplication Midrange metatheory Biopsychosocial (e.g., integrating, respectively, genetics/epigenetics—brain; Activation–Inhibition coordination
self/free will belief; family) Dynamical systems (including
Systematization Mini-theory Illness disease modeling (translational psychiatry/psychology) emergence)
Networks
Hierarchization Hypotheses and empirical Need to treat all of biological, psychological, social in order to help patients
Evolution
research in domains Rigorous multifactorial investigation of multiple illness/disease domains Embodiment
Coordination Domains Disease/illness categorized/dimensionalized Developmental process
Learning
Contextual sensitivity
Culture/environment
Note. The table attempts an integration of the basic themes in the present work. The table describes the steps in the growth of an integrative framework for psychology from
domain to metatheory (Overton, 2015), with a focus on the biopsychosocial model. I relate the model to my own five-step generic sequence. The example shows how the bio-
psychosocial model fits into the sequence from domain study to the worldview of relationism. In order to show how this sequence for a central model of the present work relates
to other models described in the book, I list them as cross-step influences for each step of the model
885
886 36 New Directions in Psychological Causality

Table 36.7 Steps in the development of world view modeling


Steps Model
Coordination Internal reductionistic/external positivistic (Realism); Internal processing/external participation
(Relativism) R, R
Hierarchization R×R
Systematization +/-

RxR = relationism (r)

+/-
Multiplication r1 × r2 ×
Integration ri
The figure illustrates how the metatheoretical view of relationism might reflect the juxtaposition and then systematiza-
tion and integration of realism and relativism according to the present five-step generic model of change. At the same
time, it is worth noting that a fully mature model of relationism in psychology should integrate in a comprehensive
systems approach its original components. Both realism and relativism should not be considered as separable compo-
nents of relationism but as constitutive components still having value because of the strengths of their modeling

Table 36.8 Steps in the differentiation of activation/inhibition coordination


Step Representation Explanation
Coordination A1, I1 Activation, Inhibition juxtaposed in one domain
Hierarchization A1 X I1 They coordinate reciprocally, with one or other
dominant (not subordinate) but variably
Systematization +/- They form a system in which they dynamically
coordinate, including with activation of
inhibition, inhibition of activation, etc., leading
A1 X I1 to an overall inter-related system

+/-
Multiplication +/- +/- Activation/inhibition coordination systems
spread over domains and interact and
coordinate over them
A1 X I1 X A2 X I2 X

+/- +/-
Integration +/- A generalized activation–inhibition
coordination system manifests
Ai X Ii

+/-

Note. The table indicates how activation/inhibition coordination might develop through the present five-step generic
change model. As they coordinate and hierarchize, systematize, multiply and integrate, they include reciprocal feedback
and feedforward processes that subserve equilibrium building, flexibility, and adaptation, both within domains and over
them, to the point of creating a generic, multiflexible mechanism in organization of brain (biology) behavior and their
relationship in context and in the self
Book Conclusions 887

Biopersonalsocial Biopersonalsocial Biopersonalsocial

(Perceived)
Reality Causality Behavior

Stimulus Organism Response

Bayesian Processor/ Person Buffering/ Bootstrapping


Prediction/ (including education,
Prospection psychotherapy)

Free will belief,


Freeing the Brain having sense of Freeing behavior
free will

Biopersonalsocial Biopersonalsocial Biopersonalsocial

Evolution
Development
Learning
Context

Fig. 36.10 The biopersonalsocial model of the basic leave degrees of freedom for freer, less constrained
freedoms in brain, behavior, and being. The figure response.
attempts another way of integrating the basic themes of Development proceeds toward an integrated maturity
the present work, this time in terms of the key terms in its of self as freedom in being, composed of free will belief
title. It illustrates the reciprocal interaction across and having a sense of free will. The environment might
stimulus-processor-response, with these components no contribute by acting toward freeing the processor/person
longer considered as sequential steps in perception and in this regard. The brain is one seat of interacting biologi-
action (Clark, 2013). Causality no longer is considered to cal, environmental, and self forces in development in the
reside in the first step in this progression, but emanates, as growth to freedom. The latter is not about freedom to
well, from feedback from the processor (organism, per- choose and act on any whim but to choose and act on
son), for example. Stimuli are not absolute, external enti- responsibility, which paradoxically works against and in
ties but probabilistic, Bayesian predictions derived from control of impulsive, non-responsible promoting whims.
their affordances, and ones that lead to feedforward pre- Freedom in being is especially about arriving to the point
dictions/prospection. The environment can buffer impact of being able to free the being of others while having this
of stimuli, as well (or accentuate them), with processing further free one’s being (and not self-sacrifice to its detri-
mechanisms involved. The brain works to reduce uncer- ment or in being taken advantage of)
tainty, surprise, and free energy, which paradoxically

Finally, I address the title of the book and how system, psychology should be continually adapt-
successfully the book has treated it. The book’s ing and changing and avoid stasis and stagnation
title indicates its focus and concerns “Unifying in favor of constructive change and growth.
Causality and Psychology: Being, Brain, and In terms of the causality project implicated in the
Behavior.” As argued at the book’s outset, it is title of the present book, I would like to think that
impossible to unify psychology in terms of one the book has advanced the cause, so to speak. It has
overarching model, theory, approach, operation, offered pathways toward integrating behavioral
or any one answer or product. However, by taking causality itself and toward integrating it in psychol-
a process, pathway, or ongoing project view of ogy. In this regard, it has helped psychology, itself,
psychology’s integration, the task is facilitated, move toward the unifying pathway or process called
although it can never be completed. As with any for by the present book. Let the project continue.
888 36 New Directions in Psychological Causality

References Kopala-Sibley, D. C., & Zuroff, D. C. (2014). The devel-


opmental origins of personality factors from the self-
definitional and relatedness domains: A review of
Alloy, L. B., Black, S. K., Young, M. E., Goldstein, K. E.,
theory and research. Review of General Psychology,
Shapero, B. G., Stange, J. P., et al. (2012). Cognitive
18, 137–155.
vulnerabilities and depression versus other psychopa-
Overton, W. F. (2015). Relational developmental systems
thology symptoms and diagnoses in early adolescence.
and developmental science. In R. M. Lerner, W. F.
Journal of Clinical Child & Adolescent Psychology,
Overton, & P. C. Molenaar (Eds.), Handbook of child
41, 539–560.
psychology and developmental science, Vol. 1: Theory
American Psychiatric Association. (2013). Diagnostic
and method (7th ed., pp. 9–62). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.
and statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM-5
Rotter, J. B. (1966). Generalized expectancies for internal
(5th ed.). Washington, DC: Author.
versus external control of reinforcement. Psychological
Barlow, D. H., Ellard, K. K., Sauer-Zavala, S., Bullis, J. R.,
Monographs, 80, 1–28.
& Carl, J. R. (2014). The origins of trait neuroticism.
Verbruggen, F., McLaren, I. P. L., & Chambers, C. D.
Perspectives on Psychological Science, 9, 481–496.
(2014). Banishing the control homunculi in studies of
Belsky, J., & Pluess, M. (2009). The nature (and nurture?)
action control and behavior change. Psychological
of plasticity in early human development. Perspectives
Science, 9, 497–524.
on Psychological Science, 4, 345–351.
Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
Blatt, S. J. (2008). Polarities of experience: Relatedness
Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science +
and self-definition in personality development, psycho-
Business Media.
pathology, and the therapeutic process. Washington,
Young, G. (2014). Malingering, feigning, and response
DC: American Psychological Association.
bias in psychiatric/psychological injury: Implications
Clark, A. (2013). Whatever next? Predictive brains, situ-
for practice and court. Dordrecht, Netherlands:
ated agents, and the future of cognitive science.
Springer Science + Business Media.
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36, 1–24.
Epilogue
37

behavior. These research areas reviewed include:


Epilogue Summary (a) genes and environment; (b) development; (c)
free will and self-control; and (d) PTSD. Much of
This last portion to the book was added as a final the literature review in this section highlights
literature review and it led to further conceptual- models that inform causality, with certain
ization related to the causality of behavior. After domains of study highlighted, as well.
an introduction, it examines recent literature on Then, the epilogue presents recent work on
genes, environment, development, free will, self- models critical to the present book: (a) the rela-
control, and posttraumatic stress disorder (PTSD). tional model; (b) the Piagetian model and Neo-
Next, it looks at recent work on critical models in Piagetian variants; (c) the network model; and (d)
the field, including the relational, Piagetian/Neo- NLDST. Next, the epilogue shifts to review of
Piagetian, network (including in neurocircuitry), causal modeling.
and nonlinear dynamical systems theory The conclusions at this point in the epilogue
(NLDST), and the ones related to causality (e.g., indicate directions for further modeling related to
top-down processes). The epilogue concludes the causality of behavior. The new models that I
with new models that I created on symptom net- have proposed in this epilogue include: (a) an
work-construct relations, the nature of stages, and extended hybrid system-construct model (Young,
multiple emotional (socio-affective) intelligences. 2015a); (b) a reconceptualization of cognitive
Conclusions emphasize the individual as the core stages; and (c) a reconceptualization of emotional
focus of causal modeling, with normative, popu- intelligence.
lation-level research providing an informed basis
for understanding individual behavioral causality. Major Points Before reviewing in depth the
I conclude that the study of causality and the uni- recent literature, I present its major points. For the
fication of psychology are reciprocal processes area of genes and environment, the review high-
that constitute ongoing and dynamic projects to lights the exquisite interaction between these sub-
which the present book has contributed. strates in development. The field of behavioral
genetics has received both praise for the replica-
bility of its major findings and a caution about its
Introduction limits and misinterpretations. The genetics sec-
tion also describes recent research on gene–envi-
Prelude In closing the book, I conducted a final ronment interaction and the differential
literature review on topics central to it, as well as susceptibility model. Then, it considers the bur-
proposing new models related to the causality of geoning area of epigenetics, which indicates how

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 889


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7_37
890 37 Epilogue

the environment can get “under the skin” and even tutes the cause of behavior because elements in the
affect multiple generations. The environment sec- system might have causal priority.
tion gives nuanced findings on the effects of the Lourenço (2016) defended the standard
early environment on development and cultural Piagetian view of stages, e.g., hierarchical and
differences related to intelligence. integrated, but did not defend his four-step stage
For development, the research points to critical sequence, per se. I will show that the standard
models in the area, such as the newer biopsychoso- view of stages needs elaboration, as does the
cial one gaining increasing influence and the classic standard four-stage sequence of Piaget.
Eriksonian one. Some of the domains in develop- Mascolo and Fischer (2015) presented their
ment mentioned include causal learning, which Neo-Piagetian five-step model of stages; the model
highlights that children develop a “causal stance.” includes the recursive recycling substages. However,
The area of free will does not constitute just a I show how their view includes developmental
philosophical one about whether it exists but also sequences that better fit my own Neo-Piagetian
a psychological one about the positive effects of model (five-stage × five-substage lifespan develop-
believing in free will. Free will belief is one of mental model; Young, 2011). In this section of the
the factors that guide behavior and allow for self- epilogue, also I present Case’s Neo-Piagetian model
control. Also, it can be depleted, being a limited of central conceptual structures, even though there
resource. is no recent research on it. Case conceived of central
As for PTSD, a central issue relates to its clus- conceptual structures as a better way to understand
ter or factor structure. The DSM-5 (Diagnostic the nature of within-stage organization. This pre-
and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, Fifth pares the way for my later presentation of a new
Edition; American Psychiatric Association, way to conceive the nature of stages in development
2013) has organized PTSD’s 20 symptoms into that brings the understanding a long way from
four clusters, and included supplementary ones Piaget and also other Neo-Piagetians.
related to a dissociation subtype. The empirical The network model considers nodes and edges
research supports a dimensional structure for the in their relations, for example, in social networks,
DSM-5 PTSD symptoms. Confirmatory factor neuronal circuitry, symptom networks, and others.
analysis (CFA) indicates up to seven of them and, Networks are characterized by hubs, their centrality
in Young (2015b, 2016), I proposed an eight (e.g., betweenness), and so on, and they might even
cluster/factor model that includes dissociation. possess “small world” structures (high global con-
PTSD has been shown to have biological bases in nectivity and clustering). In this regard, Sporns and
genes and the brain, with the HPA (hypothalamic colleagues had described the Connectome in neuro-
pituitary adrenal) axis one of the mediators in the nal networks and, in this epilogue, I present his hier-
pathway to its expression. That said, PTSD could archical modeling of modules and of “modules
be feigned for monetary gain (e.g., Young, within modules” at levels superordinate to basic
2015c), and the DSM of which it is a part has networks. This type of modeling is consistent with
been criticized, e.g., for its categorical approach NLDST (e.g., intermediate levels to lower-order
and for how it was constructed in working groups. and superordinate ones) and with my own applica-
The most recent work on the relational model tions to symptom-construct relations and to within-
shows its value relative to the Cartesian reduction- stage central conceptual structure organization.
ist one that dominates much of psychology, but it NLDST is another model central to the present
now emphasizes “process” instead of causality, per book. A major point of disagreement in the field is
se. However, there is no reason not to see these lat- the extent to which systems can possess emergent
ter two concepts as complementary and as alternate levels that function top down and in complement to
ways of trying to understand the why of behavior. bottom-up lower-order ones. The concept of recip-
In my view, the concept of causality includes the rocal causality affords a bridge between lower level
dynamic processes behind the construction and and higher levels in systems, and allows for emer-
development of behavior, and vice versa. It is insuf- gence of the latter in ways that they are irreducible
ficient to say the system and its functioning consti- to the former. Attractors are central to NLDST con-
Introduction 891

ceptualization. Simply, they refer to regions in the order levels. Psychological constructs could be
state space of system dynamics to which system conceived of higher-order system levels interact-
trajectories consistently return. In Young (2011), I ing with lower-order ones in individualized ways
showed how systems can evolve not only from the for particular people.
standard model of point to oscillatory to chaotic (b) When applied to the nature of stages, this
attractors but also to more complex adaptive sys- type of modeling allows for multiple, interacting
tems (CAS) with multiple attractors, as in living levels that are constructed individually in con-
systems, and even to attractor dynamics superordi- text, with increasing sophistication in higher-
nate to that. The five-step sequence in attractor order levels as they differentiate into rules,
evolvability described has been proposed as a representations, operations, and abstract formu-
generic change model and as underlying the five- lations. The concept of hierarchical, multiple,
stage developmental sequence in my Neo-Piagetian and interacting, reciprocally-causal levels (and,
model (Young, 2011). Later in the chapter, I apply therefore, emerging ones, too) in a system can
the model further to the area of multiple socio- help explain both the nature of stages and how
affective intelligences, which is a new concept they are individualized, as well the mechanisms
developed in this last part of the book. that propel their evolution through qualitatively
Continuing its review, in the next portion of the distinct organizations (i.e., higher-order stages).
epilogue, I consider recent work on the topic of This stage evolution happens, as well, through
causality. The top-down approach to causality in processes equivalent to the accommodation and
systems is gaining traction. I show how it is provid- assimilation duality in equilibration that Piaget
ing a different optic to sciences such as physics and described, in that the schemes so structured within
biology. At the level of the brain, it works to influ- levels keep being applied and generalized and then
ence lower-order levels, e.g., as in frontal neurocir- chunk as they become too complex, and also ready
cuitry influencing attentional processes. This work for the next applications horizontal, lateral and
reinforces my point of view on hierarchical system vertical, discontinuous generalizations. The child
modeling, i.e., of a multilevel, hierarchical system contributes to this process by way of her or his
approach relevant across multiple areas of science, active constructions, curiosity, motivation, meta-
including in understanding new areas that I develop cognition, distancing reflections, and so on.
in this epilogue on the causality of behavior. (c) As for the novel concept of multiple emo-
tional intelligences, it is an extension of the one that
New Work The last part of the epilogue before I developed for multiple (cognitive) intelligences,
the conclusion examines three models that I have in general. For present purposes, I now refer to the
created that inform the causality of behavior. (a) latter as multiple cognitive intelligences in order to
The first model combines network modeling and distinguish it from multiple emotional intelli-
NLDST; (b) the second model applies the new gences. Moreover, I generalize the latter concept
model just described to a better understanding of by referring to it as involving multiple socio-affec-
stages, especially in terms of its ongoing, dynamic, tive intelligences. In essence, just as multiple cog-
and individualized nature; and (c) the third model nitive intelligences refer to the yoking of
reconfigures emotional intelligence as multiple, Neo-Piagetian stages and substages (as conceived
yoked, and reflective of the present model of Neo- in my 2011 model, in particular) to resolve tasks
Eriksonian stages, with the factors in traditional and problems confronting the individual, so to are
emotional intelligence considered the domains of multiple socio-affective intelligences a reflection of
the new model. my model. That is, for each Neo-Piagetian cogni-
A common structure to these three models tive (sub)stage that I describe in my model, there is
relates to a hierarchical multilevel systems view a corresponding Neo-Eriksonian (sub)stage. With
involving reciprocal causality. (a) For example, respect to conceiving them as multiple socio-affec-
networks focus on lower-order system structure tive intelligences, the latter can be combined in
while NLDST allows for emergence of higher- individualized ways online to resolve the socio-
892 37 Epilogue

affective tasks and problems confronting the indi- Genes and Environment
vidual, with the added constraint that past
difficulties in navigating the challenges in the (sub) The book has considered in depth the genetic basis
stages involved might make the skills associate of behavior, in concert with other influences. The
with them less than optimally available, or even recent literature provides examples related to the
having the negative poles associated with each areas of behavior genetics, Gene × Environment
(sub)stage predominant relative to the positive one Interactions (G × E), and differential susceptibility.
(e.g., as in Trust vs. Mistrust). Recall that, simply, G × E involves the vulnerabil-
To summarize, I had applied the concept of ity of certain alleles and environmental experi-
(sub)stage yoking to the multiple cognitive intel- ences working in concert for risk and
ligence model, and in the present rendition of the psychopathology, while differential susceptibil-
concept, I show how it acts to build individualized ity refers to risk alleles not only conferring vulner-
hierarchical models of higher-order and lower- abilities in adverse environments but also positive
order levels in both multiple cognitive and socio- developmental trajectories in supportive ones. The
affective intelligences. recent research reviewed does not consider other
areas related to genetics that were discussed in the
Conclusion The conclusion to the epilogue book, e.g., correlated gene–environment interac-
considers the nature of causality of behavior tions, but they, too, indicate the dynamic nature of
from both a normative and an individualized per- gene–environment relations and the futile task of
spective. I end up giving primacy to the latter, considering them separately or statically.
with the former constituting a basis for under-
standing the latter. The study of causality is rel-
evant in its own right, but its application to better Genes
ensuring optimal development, resolving psy-
chopathology, and improving the human condi- Behavior Genetics Plomin, DeFries, Knopik,
tion, in general, accelerates it to the vanguard of and Neiderhiser (2016) extolled the field of
the field of behavioral study and mental health behavioral genetics for the replicability of its
broadly considered. It is indeed the coalescing, major findings. Some of the points raised con-
integrating, unifying axis in this area, and one cerned environment as much as genetics. Also,
that is evolving constantly. The epilogue con- they had applied implications.
cludes that the study of behavioral causality and For Plomin et al. (2016), a replicated finding
the unification of psychology are reciprocal pro- in behavior genetics is that all psychological
cesses and that they constitute ongoing and “traits” show significant, substantial “genetic
dynamic projects to which the present book influence.” Traits concern enduring characteristics
hopes to elevate as central to the field. related to intelligence, personality, and psycho-
Before beginning presentation of the epilogue pathology (e.g., schizophrenia), in particular. In
in depth, I note that there is some overlap with all three cases, the research points to heritability
material in prior chapters. On the one hand, this is estimates between 30 and 50 %. It is noted that
inevitable given that in the epilogue I review the estimates are below 100 %, which allows for
many major areas of the book for new material environmental influence. Also, heritability for a
since the time I had written the prior chapters. On trait is “caused” by multiple genes, each having
the other hand, I treat material presented previ- only a small effect.
ously in new ways. Some of the areas that repeat When traits are related phenotypically in
in the epilogue include those related to my own research, a significant mediation by genetic fac-
conceptualizations (e.g., my 25-step stage model), tors is shown and it is “substantial.” Also, herita-
and the attractor/complexity model considered as bility increases throughout development (at least
underlying them. Even here, I present conceptual for intelligence), which is related to findings of
innovations related to them. age-to-age stability due to genetics.
Genes and Environment 893

The environment can be measured and, fur- children at 30, 42, and 54 months of age (N = 145)
ther, the results in this research also reveal genetic was predicted by an interaction between observed
mediation (e.g., parenting being mediated genet- maternal parenting at the child age of 30 months
ically). Further, the relationship between envi- and variants of the dopamine transporter gene,
ronmental measures and psychological traits SLC6A3 (solute carrier family C6, member 3).
reveals genetic mediation. Genetic research has Specifically, children without the intron
served to highlight that sibling similarities are not 8-A/intron 13-G; intron 8-A3′-UTR (untrans-
due to growing up in the same family, because lated) VNTR (variable number tandem repeat)-10;
genetics “accounts for” these sibling similarities. or intron 13-G-3′-UTR VNTR-10 haplotypes,
Finally, environment and genetics both influence which are associated with reduced SLC6A3 gene
psychopathology. Also, genetic research sup- expression and so lower dopamine function, had
ports a dimensional (quantitative) perspective their EC altered according to maternal parental
on psychopathology, which is more accepted in quality. That is, they showed higher EC in con-
psychology, relative to the categorical (qualita- junction with less supportive maternal parenting.
tive) approach (psychiatric, DSM). At first glance, these results seem counterintui-
In response to the article, by Plomin et al. tive. However, they suggest that, for the G × E
(2016), Turkheimer (2016) criticized the concept involved, the children exposed to a less supportive
of “genetic influence,” referring to it as “vague.” environment having the haplotypes noted had, as a
He considered the concept of “heritability” a result, “decreased” reactivity/sensitivity to the
“fraught” one. Empirically, he contested the find- environment, thereby “blocking” its influence,
ings in the field of behavior genetics, arguing that “resisting” the adversity involved, and so demon-
“differences in midrange heritabilities do not rep- strating “resilience,” as per their higher EC.
licate” (p. 25) and “differences in heritabilities
among traits do not replicate” (p. 26). He advised Differential Susceptibility In terms of external-
to consider the context as a variable that affects izing behavior trajectories, Trucco, Villafuerte,
genes and environment. Heitzeg, Burmeister, and Zucker (2016) found
In the end, Turkheimer (2016) maintained that, that adolescents with the minor allele (GG) of
“genetic influence is real.” However, it must be the GABA receptor subunit alpha-2 (GABRA2
shown at the level of “strong genetic explanation,” (rs279827, rs27926, rs279858)) were greatly sus-
or in terms of specific “latent genetic mechanisms” ceptible to either of adverse or adaptive parenting
(etiology). Moreover, the traits studied in this (as measured by an aspect of parental monitoring
regard cannot be operationalized “ambiguously.” called parental knowledge). Specifically, the
Finally, the research designs should avoid over- GABRA2 gene is located on chromosome 4. It
inflated results, as in candidate gene association codes for the alpha-2 subunit of the receptor of
studies. Even genome wide association studies the neurotransmitter GABA-A. Alpha 2 GABA-A
(GWAS) are nothing more than “p hacking,” with receptors are ones that are expressed especially
results significant due to Type I error. in the amygdala. GABRA2 variants seem to
Lee and McGue (2016) were more apprecia- heighten activity in this and related brain areas,
tive of the potential of GWAS, suggesting that, and are related, then, to heightened emotional
for the study of behavioral traits, the findings are responsiveness/sensitivity to social context.
now “highly credible.” For example, the results In the Trucco et al. (2016) study, three single
of their study on the genes associated by GWAS nucleotide polymorphisms (SNPs) were exam-
for educational attainment (Rietveld et al., 2013) ined (rs279827, rs279826, and rs279858), but
have been replicated in their as-yet unpublished with rs279827 of focus because the other two
extension and replication study. demonstrate “high linkage.” The subjects were
involved in the Michigan longitudinal study,
Gene × Environment Li et al. (2016) reported a which included high-risk families (N = 504),
study on the genetic contributions to resilience in beginning at age 3 and ending at age 17. The
children. The level of effortful control (EC) in YSR (Youth Self-Report; Achenbach & Rescorla,
894 37 Epilogue

2001) was used to examine externalizing behav- ically, we might not reach the level of being a fully
ior from age 11 on and the PM-YF (Parent blossoming orchid. I note that this version of the
Monitoring-Youth Form; Chilcoat & Anthony, flowering metaphor for susceptibility genes in rela-
1996) to assess parental knowledge. tion to environment quality lacks a flower type for
As for the specific results, GG carriers were the potential orchid that wilts badly in environ-
more likely to be in the group of low-risk exter- ments that are non-supportive. Also, it gives dande-
nalizing subjects, as determined by growth mix- lions a bad name. In today’s culture, dandelions are
ture modeling (GMM), if they reported high considered as salad delicacies as well as great
parental knowledge but, conversely, they were sources to make wine. Therefore, the orchid-dan-
less likely to belong to this group for reports of delion model of differential susceptibility needs to
low parental knowledge. According to the be contextualized. In this regard, perhaps we should
authors, this pattern of results represents the dif- refer to it as Contextual Orchid-Dandelion Model.
ferential susceptibility model. Doing so would help account for findings for indi-
Another study examined differential suscepti- viduals with susceptibility alleles that adverse or
bility in adolescent antisocial behavior (ASB) for nonsupportive environments might steel processes
the serotonin transporter linked polymorphic involved in resilience, e.g., promoting better execu-
region (5-HTTLPR) genotype in relation to sensi- tive function, instead of merely leading to deleteri-
tivity to perceived parental support (Tung & Lee, ous developmental consequences.
2016). The study examined class trajectories and
differentiated overt and covert ASB. It was a lon- Epigenetics Lester, Conradt, and Marsit (2016)
gitudinal study of a sample of 2558 individuals described the important role of epigenetics in
followed from ages 11 to 26 over three waves. As development. It involves mechanisms such as
for differential susceptibility results, the long- DNA methylation “marking” genes in the pro-
long (ll) homozygous allele pair genotype seemed moter region without changing the underlying
to function like a “plasticity genotype” for the DNA sequence (of four chemical bases, A, C, T,
trajectory group of overt ASB that peaked in ado- G; paired as A-T and G-C, with C (cytosine) the
lescence, while the short (s) allele carriers (ss, ll) most important base in epigenetics). In DNA
were responsive to quality of perceived parental methylation, a methyl group is added to a chemi-
support in the late onset trajectory group. cal base C, and typically this takes place when
Specifically, with respect to probability of mem- the C is next to a G (guanine; referred to as a CpG
bership in the adolescent-peak trajectory and in site (p = phosphate)). CpG pairs typically are con-
relation to perceived parental support, for centrated in a gene’s promoter region. Areas of
s-carriers, the slope increased monotonically high CpG site concentration are called CpG
while, for ll carriers, the slope decreased. The islands. They are subject to methylation, and the
same pattern was found for probability of mem- genes involved negatively have their ability to be
bership in the late onset trajectory, respectively, read by transcriptional machinery and produce
for ll carriers and s-carriers, that is, in a pattern the RNA and proteins for the codes involved
opposite for this class compared to the prior one. affected by methylation. Unlike what is typically
believed, methylation does not “silence” genes
Comment Recall that the metaphor used for this but only “dims” them, depending on the extent of
new differential susceptibility model of genes and methylation (or other epigenetic processes).
development is one involving flowers. About one For example, the gene NR3C1 encodes geneti-
sixth of us have so-called susceptibility alleles, and cally the glucocorticoid receptor (GR) and it is
they allow us to flower into orchids in a supportive involved in cortisol regulation. GR is the receptor
environment for the behavior at issue, e.g., the site to which cortisol “binds.” Methylation of the
potential for ASD being quite low rather than high. gene NR3C1 leads to reduced gene expression,
Most other people are more like dandelions than and so a smaller availability in number of GR pro-
orchids. That is, most of us will fare well enough in teins (and fewer sites for cortical binding), further
any environment, supportive or not, but, metaphor- leading to higher levels of circulating cortisol.
Genes and Environment 895

Stroud et al. (2016) showed how early adversity Grizenko, Fortier, Gaudreau-Simard, Jolicoeur,
impacts methylation of the NR3C1gene. That is, and Joober (2015) found that maternal stress dur-
the effect of adversity on behavior is mediated by ing pregnancy predicted ADHD (attention deficit
gene methylation, as with this example. A standard hyperactivity disorder) symptomatology, includ-
finding in the field is that the environment induces ing for internalizing and externalizing behavior
methylation that impacts the brain and behavior. as measured by the CBCL (Child Behavior
Furthermore, the methylated gene is passed on to Checklist; Achenbach, 1991). Tearne et al. (2015)
the next generation, thereby having intergeneration found a relationship between known prenatal risk
effects even in the absence of the environmental factors and mental health, as measured by the
factors that had first caused the methylation. CBCL, up to 14 years of age. Martinez-Torteya,
Bogat, Levendosky, and von Eye (2016) showed
Comment Keating (2016) added that the types that prenatal intimate partner violence exposure
of adversity that can induce methylation include predicted childhood internalizing and externaliz-
SES (socioeconomic status); parental sensitivity/ ing symptoms (as per the CBCL, among other
acceptance/rejection; child abuse; neonatal inten- measures), as well as high cortisol secretion
sive care stay; and maternal smoking. The health (indicative of HPA axis reactivity).
consequences include ones ranging from; those The predictors in this type of research on
early in life (e.g., neonatal neurobehavioral effects of early environment on development
integrity); to ones in infancy (temperament; include birth weight and the findings of vulnera-
Montirosso et al., 2016); childhood (internalizing bility extended into adulthood (e.g., social trust;
symptoms; Parade et al., 2016); adolescence Peterson & Aarøe, 2015). The results support
(psychosocial adjustment; Naumova et al., 2016); different models, including the adaptive calibra-
and young adulthood (psychiatric symptom- tion one in the latter study and differential sus-
atology; Smearman et al., 2016). The latter study ceptibility in Kopala-Sibley et al. (2015). In this
involved the oxytocin receptor (OXTR). Other regard, Kopala-Sibley et al. (2015) found that
genes subject to methylation effects and conse- better quality parent–child relationship predicted
quent mental health effects include SLC6A4, decreased negative emotionality for children
which regulates serotonin exposure (Montirosso with elevated cortisol reactivity but increases in
et al., 2016). The prior chapters in the book deal- positive emotionality in children with low corti-
ing with epigenetics describe multiple genes sub- sol reactivity.
ject to methylation, including many involved in As well, ELS has been related to biological
neurotransmitter regulation. effects in the hippocampus, and it is mediated par-
tially by long-term effects on GC (glucocorticoid
signaling) pathways, neurotrophin ones, or both
Environment (Daskalakis, De Kloet, Yehuda, Malaspina, &
Kranz, 2015). Factors in early life adversity also
Early Life Stress The most recent studies have been related to inflammation at midlife, in
reviewed on early life stress (ELS) and related results supportive of the stress accumulation model,
factors together accentuate the role of the early which, at the same time, does not deny a role for
environment on long-term development espe- the additive effects of recent stressors (Hostinar,
cially when the environment is adverse. Mroczek, Lachman, Seeman, & Miller, 2015).
Moreover, the research traces the physiological Adult outcome also includes cortical thickness
effects that result and contribute to the develop- measures (Sylvester et al., 2016) but, in this case,
ment of developmental psychopathology in a cas- the predictor involved early childhood inhibition.
cade effect. At the same time, as well, recent
research points to the influence of and interaction Maltreatment Scarpa (2015) qualified that child
with genetic and more congenital factors in these maladjustment is related to either hypo- or hyper-
regards. In the following, I review quite briefly arousal. Jedd et al. (2015) related childhood mal-
select findings on ELS and related factors. treatment to altered functional connectivity in the
896 37 Epilogue

amygdala and other effects on frontolimbic cir- (e.g., Caspi et al., 2002, 2003) and epigenesis
cuitry. Peckins, Susman, Negriff, Noll, and Trickett (e.g., Meaney, 2010). Similarly, Leerkes and
(2015) related child maltreatment to blunted corti- Parade (2015) referred to the model of differ-
sol profiles, with adaptive calibration eventually ential susceptibility (Belsky, Bakermans-
tempering the difference between maltreated and Kranenburg, & van IJzendoorn, 2007). In this
non-maltreated participants. Hanson, Knodt, Brigidi, regard, Gordon and Feldman (2015) underscored
and Hariri (2015) found that stress sensitization in biopsychosocial development through behavioral
child maltreatment participants seemed to affect synchrony with the mother, biological synchrony,
the uncinate fasciculus connecting the amygdala and contextual synchrony in adaptive child devel-
and ventromedial PFC (prefrontal cortex). opment. For example, Feldman, Vengrober, and
Genetically, Thibodeau, Cicchetti, and Ebstein (2014) related child PTSD development
Rogosch (2015) found an association of child to genetics, sensitive maternal support, and
maltreatment to dopaminergic genes (in African behavioral withdrawal vs. comfort seeking (the
American children; in a complex relationship latter being more predictive of better outcome).
with impulsivity and ASB). Tyrka et al. (2015)
related it to the FK506 binding protein 5 gene Eriksonian Model Malone, Liu, Vaillant, Rentz,
(FKBP5) in terms of lower levels of methylation and Waldinger (2016) referred to Vaillant and
(epigenesis) at CpG sites in intron 7. Räikkönen Milofsky’s (1980) revised Eriksonian model that
et al. (2015) related placental expression of genes inserted a stage of middle adulthood after
regulating glucocorticoid and serotonin function intimacy/isolation and a stage of old age after
to infant regulatory behavior, through its media- generativity/stagnation. These stages were num-
tion of maternal depressive symptoms during bered 6a and 7a, respectively, in the Eriksonian
pregnancy on infant challenges in regulatory sequence. Moreover, they were not given sepa-
behavior. A twin study (Gagne & Saudino, 2016) rate “crises,” as found in the Eriksonian model
also related genetic factors to childhood inhibi- for the original eight-step sequence.
tory control.
Other Models The Piagetian model and its Neo-
Comment The role of the environment in behav- Piagetian variants are presented below, as is the
ioral causality is indisputable. The field of genetics relational one. The embodied developmental
is rapidly evolving to include topics that reflect model is implicated in the next section. It is
environmental influence, such as G × E, differential beyond the scope of the epilogue to consider the
susceptibility, and epigenetics. Moreover, the work research on every important developmental
on environmental influence on behavior includes model. One that is not discussed is the evolution-
models on ELS, the effects of maltreatment, and ary, life history one, for example. The reader is
stress accumulation. Of course, parenting is critical referred to earlier chapters of the book on this
to behavioral development and will remain the cen- model. In the following, I have selected examples
tral axis of the ecology involved in behavioral cau- of recent developmental research that reveals the
sality, as reviewed, in part, in the following. precocity of infant development. However, this
should not be taken to support a strictly nativist
view of development. Early appearing skills
Development might be foundational but not determinant. For
example, not only is early experience important
Models in the transactional trajectories that follow from
these early skills, but also other models, includ-
Biopsychosocial Model Calkins (2015) has ing my own, refer to the transformations, e.g.,
brought the biopsychosocial approach center through developmental substages, that these
stage in the study of infant development. She early skills negotiate. The review that follows
viewed that the spurs to the growth of this also indicates the primordial role that causal
approach laid in the work on G × E interactions learning and reasoning play in development.
Free Will and Self-Control 897

As argued elsewhere in the book, we are indeed Christensen and Michael (2016) referred to an
Homo Causa. earlier developing “mind reading” system that
employs “simple representations” toward arriv-
ing at “fast, resource-efficient” more advanced
Domains mind-reading representation processing.

Motor Libertus, Joh, and Needham (2015) Comment In short, we are a social, develop-
found that motor training at 3 months of age was mental, and innovative species that uses simpler
related to object exploration at 15 months of age. and more advanced cognitive processes even in
The results showed that new motor skills have the infancy period. However, I have maintained
developmental cascade effects on ongoing learn- throughout that the acquisitions that develop in
ing opportunities and even the stimulation infancy should not be viewed as separate skills
directed toward the child. but as part of holistic (sub)stages, as indicated by
the (Neo-)Piagetian model that I have developed
Cognition Baillargeon, Scott, and Bian (2016) (Young, 2011). Specifically, both psychological
defended the view that infants are capable of “psy- reasoning and mind-reading, as well as related
chological reasoning.” Infants are capable of cognitive acquisitions, should not be viewed
making sense of others’ actions; for example, solely in terms of whether they are innate, foun-
infants who observe agents acting in a simple dational, and prepared or in terms of whether
scene appear to infer their mental states and then they are gradually acquired, are simple and non-
use them to predict and to interpret their subse- representational to begin, and so on. Rather, all of
quent actions (and to self-guide their own actions these acquisitions should be viewed as subject to
vis-à-vis the agent). Baillargeon et al. (2016) a multi-step evolution through many substages in
added that infants are “born equipped” with the first year from the reflexive to the sensorimo-
this “foundational” system of psychological tor to the peri (pre) operational and, therefore,
reasoning. more than acquisitions with only simple two-step
transitions from initial to a more elaborate struc-
Causal Learning Recent research on the devel- ture and function. That being said, the nature of
opment of causal learning continues to show the such a stage model needs the types of revisions
centrality of causality as part of exceptional descried in this epilogue, as per below.
human attributes. Rakison, Smith, and Ali (2016)
showed that 22 month olds expect that the second
object in a delayed launching sequence should Free Will and Self-Control
contain a moving, dynamic component. Alvarez
and Booth (2016) described that preschoolers Free Will
adopt a “causal stance” and that, moreover, its
“strength” is related to maternal “explanatory” Introduction Philosophically, the existence of
communication. free will constitutes a topic of interminable
debate that is irresolvable. However, psychologi-
Cultural Learning Cultural learning is crucial cally, the belief in free will has many positive
to human learning, for example, as shown in the consequences. Topics related to free will include
research on causal learning just mentioned. the ones of prospection and self-control. Simply,
Further, Legare and Nielsen (2015) considered the former involves planning ahead and the latter
the dual engines of cultural learning as imitation appropriate behavioral selection and implemen-
and innovation. Heyes (2015) related it to social tation. Self-control can be depleted, e.g., in the
learning. Grossmann (2015) referred to the social second of two demanding tasks.
information processing capacity of the infant Baumeister and Monroe (2014) touted
brain, referring to it as a “social brain.” “responsible autonomy” as the folk psychological
898 37 Epilogue

conception of free will. That is, operatively, free seven major factors: desire; high-order goal;
will involves “being responsible” and “exercising desire-goal conflict; control motivation; control
autonomy.” Free will belief “arises” in social capacity; control effort; and enactment con-
structures through the need for self-regulation, straints. The moderators in helping determine
choosing appropriately (consciously and without effort control deployment include: desire
coercion) in acts of commission or omission, and strength; perceived skill; and competing goals.
also in the need to regulate others (e.g., moral The authors concluded that competing models
judgment/punishment). involving “will power” and the like (as in
Baumeister’s) are vague and lack integration.
Belief Feldman, Chandrashekar, and Wong
(2016) found that belief in free will predicted bet- Comment In the present causal model of behav-
ter academic performance (course and semester ior, at the personal level, factors such as curiosity,
grades) in university students. They maintained coping, and free will are as much part of the
that belief in free will facilitates long-term goal biopsychosocial, multifactorial influences on
pursuit (as well as having social benefits). behavior as are genetics, physiology, the brain,
Baumeister and Monroe (2014) reviewed the evolution, and other biological factors, as well as
extensive research showing that free will belief has the family, schools, and society and other
positive consequences. Among the notable conse- ecological/environmental factors. In this regard,
quences, one finds effects on academic motivation in this book, I have elaborated a model of self-
and success, even when all other variables that control that is biopsychosocial and has incorpo-
might be at issue are controlled as covariates. rated motivation and other factors mentioned in
this section. Further, I also maintained that, among
Prospection Baumeister, Vohs, and Oettingen the personal factors that influence behavior, free
(2016) emphasized the pragmatic aspect of pro- will belief stands as the most important. This is
spective thinking. For them, people think about reflected in the free will therapeutic approach that
the future in order to give guidance to their I elucidated in one of the chapters in the book.
behavior toward actualizing desirable outcomes. The following section turns to psychopathol-
ogy and the DSM-5, through the topic of PTSD. It
is a disorder that is biopsychosocial in nature, but
Self-Control work with patients expressing it requires an
additional forensic perspective, as in the detec-
Ego-Depletion Baumeister and Monroe (2014) tion of its feigning for monetary gain. The section
advocated that the model of “ego-depletion” (or begins with discussion of the nature of PTSD;
“strength”) governs the function of self- then, it considers factors in its etiology.
regulation, but that it is carefully regulated
because it is a limited resource. They advocated
for a physiological model, in particular, related to Posttraumatic Stress Disorder
blood glucose availability.
Orquin and Kurzban (2015) held that Dimensions
Baumeister’s concept that blood glucose deple-
tion helps explain self-regulation depletion does The cluster structure of the 20 PTSD symptoms
not apply uniformly to decision-making. In par- in the DSM-5 has been investigated with CFA.
ticular, self-control and its depletion varies, with PTSD in the DSM-5 had been built on a four-
food-related and nonfood related situations hav- cluster model, but this four-cluster approach has
ing differential effects (e.g., on willingness to not been supported in the recent research. For
play/work). example, Armour et al. (2015) even found a
Kotabe and Hofmann (2015) proposed an seven-factor solution of how the 20 DSM-5
integrated model of self-control that included PTSD symptoms are distributed according to CFA.
Posttraumatic Stress Disorder 899

This finding has been replicated by the research solution, e.g., perhaps even cultural differences
of Wang et al. (2015). apply in this regard.
As for some methodological detail in the To conclude, the exact cluster/dimensional
research just mentioned, the seven factors in structure of PTSD still has not been firmly
Armour et al. (2015), who studied two trauma- established. That being said, the minimum amount
exposed samples, involved: re-experiencing, of clusters/dimensions that seem to be involved
avoidance, negative affect, anhedonia, external- stands at six, which really is seven if one adds a
izing behavior, anxious arousal, and dysphoria dissociative subtype, as per Young (2015b, 2016).
arousal. The number of symptoms in each cluster Moreover, there might be eight such clusters/
involved, respectively: 5, 2, 4, 3, 2, 2, and 2. dimensions (as per Young again). Finally, deter-
Wang et al. (2015) obtained their comparable mining which of the 20 symptoms of PTSD that
results with Chinese adolescent earthquake survi- are core seems essential, perhaps even for better
vors; however, they referred to the first factor as understanding the biological underpinnings to it
intrusion. In Young (2015b), I had proposed that and also what might be its biomarkers.
a composite model of seven clusters in PTSD
should refer to re-experiencing/intrusion.
Other research has supported a six-factor Genes and Brain
model for the 20 DSM-5 PTSD symptoms (Liu
et al., 2014; Tsai et al., 2015). More recently, In this regard, Ashley-Koch et al. (2015) under-
Konecky, Meyer, Kimbrel, and Morissette took a GWAS of PTSD in Iraq-Afghanistan the-
(2015) found a six-factor in their small sample of ater military veterans. PTSD was evaluated using
military veterans. Zelazany and Simms (2015) DSM-IV-TR criteria. There were some genes spe-
also found a six-factor solution, but stated that a cific to groups (e.g., Black, White), while others
larger sample might have given a seven-factor emerged in combined analysis. They included
solution. protein kinase type 1 alpha cGMP-dependent
Based on the seven-factor model, Young (PRKG1) and DEAD box polypeptide 60-like
(2015b) proposed an eight-cluster one, with the (DDX60L). These genes are not the ones usually
eighth one involving the dissociative subtype. associated with PTSD (e.g., 5-HTTLPR). Goenjian
Miller, Wolf, and Keane (2014) cited evidence in et al. (2015) added that PTSD symptomatology
support of the addition of the dissociative subtype appears related not only to COMT but also to
to the DSM-5. This justifies considering dissoci- TPH-2 genes (tryptophan hydroxylase 2).
ation as the eight PTSD cluster or dimension. Using fMRI (functional magnetic resonance
Aside from proposing eight clusters/dimensions imaging), Zhang et al. (2015) examined altera-
for PTSD, Young (2015b, 2016) also indicated tions in resting state functional connectivity (FC)
which symptoms are core for each of them. in PTSD patients and controls (N = 20). PTSD
Young (2016) concluded that the nature of the was evaluated according to the DSM-IV
dimensional structure of PTSD symptoms (Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental
depends on: the models tested; whether the DSM- Disorders, Fourth Edition; American Psychiatric
IV-TR (Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Association, 1994) using the instrument devel-
Mental Disorders, Fourth Edition, Text Revised; oped by Blake et al. (1995).
American Psychiatric Association, 2000) and its As for the results, relative to controls, PTSD
17 symptoms or the DSM-5 and its 20 symp- patients evidenced decreased intranetwork FC
toms had been the basis for the research; the within the anterior DMN (default mode network),
population examined (e.g., civilian or military; posterior DMN, and the SN (salience network),
external event trauma-exposed or other); and a as well as the sensorimotor network (SMN) and
host of other variables (sample size, their gender, auditory network (AN), but not in the CEN (cen-
etc.). Perhaps the nature of the PTSD tral executive network). Other results concerned
cluster/dimensional structure does not have one increased FC between posterior DMN and SN.
900 37 Epilogue

These sample studies on PTSD reveal the rich (International Classification of Disease, 11th
biological research being undertaken to round Edition; World Health Organization, 2017).
out understanding of PTSD. They speak to the Moreover, these nosological systems are not
genetic and brain networking associations with without criticisms. Demazeux and Singy (2015)
PTSD. The mediating pathways from genes to referred to the theoretical, epistemological, and
brain to behavior include the stress response sys- social weaknesses of the DSM-5. Demazeux
tem, e.g., the HPA axis and cortisol production. (2015) referred to its chaotic revision process,
As discussed in the early adversity/maltreatment and the absence of the consideration of causality
section of this epilogue, dysregulation of the related to the listed mental disorders. Poland
stress response is critical to mental equilibrium (2015) criticized its categories as artificial and its
and, in the present case, both hypo- and hyper- approach as atheoretic (apart from its biocentric
cortisolism due to chronic stressors adds to the approach). Also, it is medical-focused, individual-
vulnerability to and expression of PTSD. focused or decontextualized, and symptom-
focused. Tsou (2015) advocated for inclusion of
a theoretical pluralism in the DSM-5 and inclu-
Malingering sion of the causes of its listed disorders, while
admitting that the latter goal has to be long term.
As shown in Young (2016), Suhr (2015) advo- Kirk, Cohen, and Gomory (2015) even referred
cated for a biopsychosocial approach to assess- to the moral insolvency of the DSM-5, e.g.,
ment, giving importance to the forensic task of because of the financial conflicts of interest
assessing for noncredible responding. In this among the members of its work groups (and one
regard, she referred to at least 20 % of PTSD can add the background presence of Big Pharma).
claimants exhibiting noncredible responding (cit- In the next sections, the epilogue turns to criti-
ing Elhai et al., 2004; Frueh et al., 2005). cal models in the present book, reviewing ones
Moreover, Young (2015c) conducted a litera- already mentioned as per the recent literature and
ture review, and showed that the frequently cited adding new conceptual material for consider-
percentage that malingering takes place in foren- ation. In terms of the latter, I build on my previ-
sic and related disability assessments at the rate ously presented models and add others.
of 40 ± 10 % (Larrabee, Millis, & Meyers, 2009)
is not supported by the empirical research.
Rather, the research shows that malingering in Modeling
the forensic disability and related assessment
context is more toward the rate of 15 ± 15 %, The Relational Model
although malingering could be more frequent in
cases of PPCS (persistent post-concussive syn- Overton and Molenaar (2015) have placed on a
drome) after mTBI. In addition, problematic pre- par the process-relational and relational-
sentations, such as feigning, in general, could be developmental-systems view in the paradigm
toward 50 % or more. In such cases, there are shift that is taking place in developmental sci-
other ways of suggesting poor evaluee effort or ence. For example, development derives from
lack of credibility, without using the “M” word. multiple coacting influences in a constructive,
nonlinear, epigenetic (in the sense of being prob-
abilistic) process over multiple time scales and at
DSM-5 multiple levels.
Overton (2015) qualified that viewing nature
PTSD is listed in different ways in major noso- as “process” stands in opposition to the view of
logical systems. For example, the DSM-5 does nature as being “substance,” which is a Cartesian
not include the diagnosis of complex PTSD, perspective. For Overton (2015), the relational as
which is projected for inclusion in the ICD-11 opposed to the Cartesian view fits with an
Modeling 901

approach to explanation of nature that it is best structures (“structures d’ensemble”) that are in
considered “multiple” instead of just the product equilibration (not easily perturbed). Stages are
of “efficient, material” causal factors. Overton “descriptive,” not “explanatory.” Moreover, there
(2015) continued that the “process-relational” is no inconsistency in advocating for stages
approach that is embodied in this metatheoretical despite the finding of “décalage” or uneven
worldview differs from the mechanistic, development within a domain/stage due to task
Cartesian, reductionist one. He added that the complexity differences. Also, micro-development
Piagetian developmental model has been aligned does appear continuous, which is not evidence
with the latter view in some readings, but this is a against the discontinuity in development that the
misunderstanding of Piaget’s interdependent, macro-development of stages represents. In terms
non-dualist, and “non-splittable” stance (for of the causality behind development, Lourenço
structure and function, for example). (2016) maintained that Piaget anticipated the
Overton (2015) offered a lifespan stage model dynamic and complexity models that are current
of development much like that of Piaget. He today.
referred to the four stages involved as practical
(action systems), symbolic (representations), Comment Barrouillet (2015) and Carey,
reflective (second-order representations), and Zaitchik, and Bascandziev (2015) also affirmed
“trans-reflective” (third-order representations), the value of Piaget’s stage model. Bjorklund
with a biological basis/embodiment included at (2015) provided an evolutionary perspective and
each stage, and with earlier stages still active as Zelazo (2015) emphasized the role of executive
higher-order stages appear. His reworking of function, with Goldin-Meadow (2015) highlight-
Piaget’s stage concept is interesting, especially ing the action/gestural component in influences
the notion that stages can be active simultane- on cognitive development. Rochat (2015) pre-
ously and are not integrated and no longer func- sented a stage model of levels of awareness. It is
tional with the appearance of each new stage not consistent with Piaget’s model nor is it con-
[Also see Rochat (2015) below, in this regard]. sistent with Neo-Piagetian ones, such as Fischer’s
Overton (2015) argued that the concepts of (1980). However, it is valuable for its “onion”
mechanism and causation have “no place” in the metaphor of levels in development in which older
process-relational view. However, he equated and newer levels can co-exist and function in
mechanism and cause with “external split-off” parallel.
forces, which are not the sole factors in contem- To conclude, the recent literature on cognitive
porary understanding of causality (Young, 2011, developmental stages supports the Piagetian
as well as the present book). That being said, in approach but does not explicitly refer to the value
the present view, the “what” and the “why” of of Piaget’s four-step stage sequence itself.
development, or the product and process, are Mascolo and Fischer (2015) presented an alterna-
inseparable components of development, as tive to that sequence, in their Neo-Piagetian
Overton would argue. model, but in the following I indicate some diffi-
culties with it.

Piagetian Modeling
Neo-Piagetian Model
Stages Lourenço (2016) maintained that the
Piagetian concept of stages is still valid because Fischer’s Model Mascolo and Fischer (2015)
its criticisms are based on misunderstandings and reviewed Fischer’s (1980) Neo-Piagetian model
also the evidence provided for their existence is of development and its implications for social
supportive. Developmental stages are hierarchi- and emotional development, in particular. In
cal or invariant in order; integrative of prior Fischer’s model, stages are referred to as tiers
stages yet with consolidating transitions between and substages as levels. There are five stages
them; and characterized as wholes or overarching (reflexes, sensorimotor actions, representations,
902 37 Epilogue

abstractions, principles), with three cyclic sub- which, in contrast, is generally called for in my
stages recurring in the first four of them (which model. That is, Mascolo and Fischer (2015) had
are referred to as: single, mapping, system). included a substage that is representational in
Generally, my model (Young, 2011) includes nature, which is consistent with each of the work
five stages, which concern reflexes, sensorimotor of Piaget, Case, and myself. Specifically, the
actions, representations (perioperations), abstract missing substage at 2 years had been referred to
(formal) thought, and superordinate abstract (col- as “compounded representations/internalized
lective) intelligence. There are five cyclically standards” (Mascolo & Fischer, 2007). Moreover,
recurring substages, which are referred to as the single representation substage at 18–24
coordination, hierarchization, systematization, months had been qualified as “evoked and sup-
multiplication, and integration. Thus, my model ported,” which, to me, indicates its less than pure
includes 25 (sub)stages/steps over the lifespan, representational status.
which is much more than the number in Fischer Inexplicably, in Mascolo and Fischer (2015),
(and in Case, 1998, too, which is a competing the new substage used to help explain the devel-
Neo-Piagetian model). opment of socio-affective acquisitions in their
In the following, I review the difference in prior work on emotional development (Mascolo
approach to substages from the 18-month-old & Fischer, 2007) was not applied to their new
period to the next years as found in Mascolo and work on a related developmental topic, that of
Fischer (2015), Fischer, 1980 and Young (2011). moral action in three domains considered. That
In my model, the 18–24 month age period is is, they reverted to Fischer’s general model in
associated with the present sensorimotor sub- which a substage at 2 years of age is excluded.
stage of integration. Then, at 2 years, the repre- Moreover, they did not refer to the 18- to
sentational stage begins (perioperations), with 24-month age period, at least at this point, as
the first substage being one of coordination. being “evoked and supported.”
Next, at 3.5 years, the substage of hierarchization Next, I examine the specific examples pro-
begins. These substages in my model are the ones vided for moral development in Mascolo and
equivalent to those in Mascolo and Fischer’s Fischer (2015), which permits me to show their
(2015) treatment of the development of emo- lacunae relative to my own model. In Mascolo
tions, which constituted a good portion of the and Fischer (2015), the moral action domain of
examples covered in their work. Before criticiz- autonomy/rights develops from the substage of
ing that work, I give my general critique of single representation of possession (“mine”) at
Fischer’s model, as presented in Young (2011). the 18- to 24-month age period to that of reci-
In Young (2011), I showed that Fischer’s procity (give me toy, return it) at 3.5–4.5 years.
model appears to be missing substages at 2, 7, As mentioned, but worthy of repetition, in their
and 9, years, in particular, as well as prenatally description of this development passage, as per
and in the adult period, unlike in my own the general critique I had presented in Young
5-stage × 5-substage lifelong developmental (2011) of the Fischerian model, there is no sub-
model. Also, I showed how the examples pro- stage between the two substages presented that is
vided by Fischer and colleagues for the devel- applicable to 2 years of age. In this regard, I
opment of emotions better fit my model than would add to their substage sequence something
theirs. For example, in reference to the substage like their substage found in Mascolo and Fischer
at 18–24 months, the examples provided were as (2007), that is, their substage of “compounded
much sensorimotor in nature as purely represen- representations/internalized standards.” In other
tation, counter to the Fischerian model that words, at this age, there should be the substage of
claims that, at this age, representation emerges. representations/internalized standards or an
Also, in reference to the missing substage at 2 equivalent. Using their examples, it would be
years, Fischer provided for the first (and only) captured by the child returning to the scene, after
time in his lifetime body of work a substage, a child has transgressed someone’s rights (e.g.,
Modeling 903

inappropriately saying “mine”), in order to say, A major difficulty with stage models, in gen-
“Sorry” (as opposed to simply saying “Sorry” eral, relates to how causally the abrupt jumps in
without a return component). Of course, another discontinuous stage-to-stage development take
option would be to use my own model in this place. Moreover, the nature of stage organization
regard, which refers to coordinated representa- within each stage needs to be clarified better, as
tions at this age (indeed, the example provided well as how they evolve internally (e.g., from
fits this terminology, too). initial schema to more complex within-stage
The clearest example of the need to differenti- structures). Case’s concept of central conceptual
ate a 2-year-old level of representation from ones structures provides fertile ground for new ideas
for 18 to 24 months and for 3.5–4.5 years in the on these matters. I have dealt with these issues in
work of Mascolo and Fischer (2015) concerns the present book, but explore them further in the
the domain that they presented of developing following.
concern for others. In the examples that they pro-
vided for an 18-month-old, a child accidentally
hurts the mother and says “kiss, kiss” before Central Conceptual Structures
kissing the mother. The action component to
the representation is evident, which I highlight as Model Young (2011) described that Case,
the reason for considering this age at one still Okamoto, Henderson, and McKeough (1993)
involving sensorimotor actions, as Piaget had defined central conceptual structures in terms of
maintained (and unlike what they maintained). organized systems of similar semantic nodes or
For an older child (30 months), in the example sets and relations, having both general cross-
provided, the concern for others is expressed ver- domain properties and particular domain con-
bally only (“poor Donna crying”), which, more- straints formed in context. The domains could be
over, appears to be a compounded or coordinated numerical, narrative, social, etc. Case (1998)
representation (“poor” + “crying”), to use their elaborated that they begin as a mental model, then
language (or a coordinated representation, to use coalesce into sub-dimensions in the domain, and
my language). Clearly, the example reflects a rep- then an explicit rule for modeling inter-
resentation without an action component. dimensional relations. Mental states are inner
However, in Mascolo and Fischer (2015), despite state schemas that develop from events (e.g., wit-
the differences that they reflect about representa- nessed) and they alternate with actions that they
tion for the two ages involved, the two examples cause, being transformed by them, in turn. As an
that they give are both referred to as representa- example, the actions deriving from mental states
tional (at the substage of single representations). in narrative conceptual structures could include
inferences on mental states, perceived causes, etc.
Comment To summarize, Fischer’s Neo- Case et al. (1993) tested for the presence of
Piagetian model has fewer substages over the conceptual mental structures by administering a
lifespan than my own, and there are striking lacu- broad range of quantitative and social tasks to 5-
nae in substages that should be present, including and 8-year-olds. They found a moderate degree
at 2 years of age. Moreover, for the same age of inter-task correlations within each domain,
periods, the description that I give of the sub- and less so between them. Further, factor analy-
stages that make sense are not the same as those sis revealed similar results. In terms of cognitive
in Fischer, e.g., at 18 months of age. To conclude, levels in development (a concept similar to sub-
the value of the Piagetian approach is uncon- stages), 70 % of the participants scored within
tested, as evidenced in the current literature half of one level on each of the two sets of tasks.
review. However, the present Neo-Piagetian As for related research, McKeough and
model might offer new avenues in conceptualiza- Griffiths (2010) found similar results for 4- to
tion and application relative to others (e.g., 12-year-old story telling performance, indicative
Fischer 1980; and Mascolo and Fischer 2015). of conceptual structure development and evolution.
904 37 Epilogue

Demetriou, Spanoudis, and Mouyi (2010) con- tight as to conform to the network concept of
ducted research on different domains, elaborating “small-world structure.” Specifically, small-world
changes every 2 years (or over classes) in the structures involve “high global connectivity”
domains of number, causal understanding, space, established through “short-cuts,” in conjunction
and verbal skills. Young (2011) concluded that with “high clustering.” For example, positive atti-
central conceptual structures are “intermediary” tudes could exhibit a small-world structure, and one
structures between “local schemes” and large that excludes negative attitudes.
units, such as (sub)stages. Nodes vary not only in their cluster alignment
but also with their “structural importance” (or cen-
Comment Although formulated outside of con- trality; with measures of centrality involving
cepts related to systems theory, hierarchies of “betweenness,” “degree,” and “closeness”).
multiple levels in system dynamics, and so on, the According to Dalege et al., (2016), this has impli-
concept of central conceptual structures speaks to cations for understanding networks more widely in
concepts such as these. For example, central con- terms of NLDST. In this regard, the more strongly
ceptual structures are comprised of a hierarchy connected are components, such as attitude net-
involving more general rules, sub-dimensions, works, the more likely they form a small set of
and mental models. In my work below, elaborat- attractors (e.g., positive and negative attitudes).
ing the concept of central conceptual structures, I The disadvantage of highly-connected networks is
refer to these three different levels in their evolu- that ambivalence or conflict among elements (e.g.,
tion as developing mental schemas, then specific specific attitudes) could arise easier than for cases
rules, and then general rules. In terms of the criti- in which there are weakly connected ones. Finally,
cal aspect of individual differences in develop- it is important to note that networks such as those
ment, as systems theory would predict, they allow relating to attitudes are subject to growth over time
for differential expression in context, including (Bringmann et al., 2013).
differences in different domains and a lack of In other work that addresses networks, Sporns
clear correlation of development across domains. and Betzel (2016) described that networks form
In the following, I present other models that speak “communities” or clusters of “dense connected”
to similar issues, toward arriving at a new concep- nodes, which are referred to as “modules.” The
tualization of the inner workings of stages that is communities consist of building blocks of sub-
consistent with systems theory. networks. For Sporns and Betzel (2016), net-
works are “strongly coupled” subcomponent
networks among nodes and linking edges. Edges
The Network Model can link nodes either within modules or between
them. If a node is highly connected, it is called a
Model Dalege, Borsboom, van Harreveld, van den “hub.” Provincial hubs involve node connectivity
Berg, and Conner (2016) described a model of atti- mostly in the same community, in contrast to
tudes that is based on the network model (e.g., connector hubs, which relate nodes belonging to
Borsboom & Cramer, 2013). It includes interaction different communities.
of evaluative reactions and their interactions, in For Sporns and Betzel (2016), modules are
turn, which “arise through direct causal influ- efficient organizational plans because they allow
ences” and mechanisms. In the network model, for adaptability, robustness, evolvability, resil-
relations among components (variables) comprise ience, stability, buffering, cost reduction, syn-
an ensemble of causally-connected components. chronization, and processing efficiency (at least
“Tight clusters” form across similar components, for brain networks, collectively referred to as the
e.g., evaluative reactions. These component clus- Connectome). Hierarchical modularity consists
ters are conceptualized as “nodes,” with node links of “modules within modules” over multiple “spa-
termed “edges.” Further, components such as atti- tial scales” [One can refer to modules within
tudes form network structures. They might be so modules as “sub-modules.”]
Modeling 905

According to Sporns and Betzel (2016), this Therefore, in my model of increasing com-
type of organization facilitates the attractor plexity in attractor organization as systems
dynamic of “criticality” in complex neuronal evolve, especially in the living and human case,
dynamics (Rubinov, Sporns, Thivierge, & but potentially in anything, such as ecological or
Breakspear, 2011). Criticality (Bak, 1996) con- cosmological systems, there is a natural progres-
stitutes an important concept in systems theory, sion from point and cyclical attractors to chaotic
because it helps predict the thresholds when the and cusp of change regimes, and then to Complex
system at issue reaches bifurcation points in Adaptive and Superordinate Complex Adaptive
which attractor regimes are altered (think of regimes. That said, as mentioned below, the
trickling sand falling on the top point of a sand direction of the evolution of the contents of the
pile and releasing an “avalanche”). attractors might be negative and not positive, as
with entrenchment of disorder rather then their
Comment In this section of their work, Sporns mitigation in therapy.
and Betzel (2016) are relating network theory Witherington (2015) specified that, in attrac-
and NLDST. This approach is quite consistent tor dynamics in NLDST, context-general system
with my own. organization can remain stable despite fluctua-
tion in system content/activity over time/context.
The qualitative pattern in attractor dynamics per-
Nonlinear Dynamical Systems Theory sists globally despite local variation (or micro-
development, online behavior). New levels of
Model Specifically, in NLDST, systems gravi- organization can emerge in a system through its
tate to attractor basins in which their repeated variable micro-level component coactions.
trajectories settle, such as might be evident in One approach to NLDST views the global
systems that remain stable despite perturbation higher-order patterns, structures, forms, levels, or
that takes them far-from-equilibrium, or systems organizations as incapable of top-down influence
that adopt configurations akin to the well-known, on lower levels because, rather than being
chaotic attractor regime, and so on. Attractors are independently substantive, they are only epiphe-
mathematical representations of state space pat- nomena of lower-level process dynamics in real
terning of systems as they change in their phase time (e.g., Thelen & Smith, 2006), while another
portraits. Attractors come in multiple types, such view considers that upper levels of a system can
as point attractors and oscillatory ones from point be “explanatory” of lower levels (e.g., Lewis,
to point. As they evolve, they take on more com- 2005). In this latter view, emergent levels are
plex patterns, especially of the chaotic variety, “causally irreducible.” They possess the capacity
which marks a trajectory toward living on the for downward, “systematic causation” through
edge of chaos, or on the cusp of change between the “constraints” of their properties. In this view,
order and disorder. the various levels of the system—higher-order,
Living systems are characterized by inhabit- top-down and lower-order, bottom-up—stand as
ing this latter state space in order to facilitate “cause and effect for each other.”
rapid response to ongoing conditions and changes Lewis’s (2005) concepts of reciprocal causal-
online; and, also, multiple attractors characterize ity and circular causality within and between lev-
them. Kauffman (1993) developed the concept of els of a system illustrate the view of system
CAS to indicate the complexity of systems organization as being comprised of levels in
beyond attractors, such as might be found in the which top-down ones can have causal downward
self-organization inherent in human behavior. In effects. For example, an emotional episode might
this regard, in Young (2011), I argued that CAS last seconds in micro-development. Over time,
could develop superordinate regimes, just as these episodes consolidate into moods of up to
attractors can create multiple complex solutions. weeks in duration. Then, in higher-order patterning,
906 37 Epilogue

personality develops over the years. Further, also that the higher-order levels might be dys-
emotional interpretations (EIs) arise out of emo- functional rather than only more functional as
tional “appraisal” and emotion “elements” they develop. For example, I described how
through coupling and synchronization with each NLDST can help explain shifts in symptoms
other and in interaction with “emotional feeling toward more entrenched or, in contrast, toward
states.” As EIs stabilize, they can be represented less dysfunctional presentations. This type of
as attractors, and an individual’s state space in its negative evolution in the content of attractors
behavioral landscape might have “multiple EI despite the increasing complexity in their struc-
attractors.” Moods arise in this micro- ture also is illustrated in the figure. Later, I refer
developmental context, and then personality fol- to this aspect of my model to the development of
lows. In this regard, personality is an emergent multiple emotional intelligences.
level in developmental behavioral system organi- In the following, I examine the concept of
zation that is “hierarchically-nested” and self- causality, in general, as presented in recent
organizing” through processes of “assembly” and publications. I emphasize the top-down influ-
upward constraints from lower-order (e.g., mood) ence of higher-order levels in a system toward
levels (as much as it imposes downward con- developing a generic hybrid model involving, as
straints on lower-order levels). well, the reciprocal influence of bottom-up
lower-order levels.
Comment Notice the three-level hierarchical
system structure described by Lewis (2005) for
affect—emotions to moods to personality. And Causality
notice how it moves from micro-, ongoing feel-
ings to stable, macro- long-term patterns in per- Introduction
sonality. On the one hand, this work supports the
application of a multilevel hierarchical approach After considering the models of stress causation
to stage development as appears later in the epi- and stress generation in the relationship between
logue. On the other hand, it shows how micro- stress and internalized psychological disorders,
time processes can lead to macro-time stabilities Phillips, Carroll, and Der (2015) investigated in
that are included in stage consolidation and tran- adults the different predictions consonant with
sition, also as shown below. the models. They found that, for depression, a
Two further points are worth considering stress causation concept best modeled the rela-
about NLDST, especially as it applies to behav- tionship involved (stress in the prior 2 years
ior and development (Young, 2011). First, it causes depression), but the inverse causal direc-
allows for the evolution of attractor configurations tion was found for anxiety (stress-generated situ-
from the simplest to the most complex, e.g., from ations cause anxiety). Moreover, sex differences
point attractors to cyclical and chaotic ones. That were involved.
is, it concerns the deep level of mechanisms in This study illustrates the complexity in dealing
the change process, including toward attractor with causality and behavior, even for linear models,
configurations that are multiple, as with living let alone the nonlinear ones we have been discuss-
systems. My version of this type of modeling ing. There is no clear universal pathway for the
adds to the evolution of complexity in single simplest of relations studied. The question becomes
attractors the notion that there can be multiple much more complex when vast amounts of vari-
attractors, e.g., as represented by CAS (and ables are considered. Also, when the variables
superordinate complex adaptive systems in express nonlinear relations, the ability to decipher
attractor organization) (Young, 2011). underlying causes in the data descriptions obtained
Second, in Young (2011), not only did I sup- becomes exponentially more difficult.
port the view that emergent levels in a system can Philosophically, there is a school of thought
exert top-down forces on lower-order levels but that denies causation (Russell, 1918). Empirically,
Causality 907

the same is happening. The movement toward the latter predicted reaction time results, showing
Big Data and our data-driven society that is downward effects on sensory regions supportive
emerging because of the Internet values, above of selective attention. They concluded that fron-
all, the massive information available and its toparietal structural connectivity mediates in a
mining. Chandler (2015) maintained that, in the top-down way the neuronal synchronization
world of Big Data, the world is becoming one associated with selective attention.
“without causation.” Knowledge of causal con-
nection is no longer relevant to the adaptation to Biology Friston, Levin, Sengupta, and Pezzulo
real-time challenges and the information pro- (2015) applied a concept from neuroscience to
vided by Big Data in this adaptation. Chandler biological regulation. Friston (2010) had devel-
(2015) was not enamored of the dynamic of this oped a “unified brain theory” based on the “free
development, and he called for an accommoda- energy principle,” which is a variant of the one of
tion with the world prior to Big Data. In this thermodynamic regulation. In this application of
regard, he referred to the value offered by com- the principle to biology, with colleagues (Friston
plexity and emergent causality for animating the et al., 2015), he argued that bottom-up models
critical approach needed toward Big Data. of molecular protein pathways are insufficient to
understand morphogenesis. Specifically, these lin-
ear models are insufficient to explain the devel-
Areas opment of large-scale morphogenetic shapes
(e.g., in embryogenesis). However, top- down
Physics Ellis, Noble, and O’Connor (2012) “constructivist” models can help in this regard,
specified that, generally, causation is considered by explaining the dynamics in the emergence
from a bottom-up perspective (e.g., elementary of complex patterns and their “remodeling”
objects exert force on each other) but, throughout toward the target anatomy. A dynamical approach
the sciences, “solid evidence” supports that top- allows for “morphogenetic self-organization.”
down causation takes place (e.g., as per attractor For Friston et al. (2015), the principle “inher-
science, ecosystem adaptation). They cautioned ent” to system output is “free energy minimiza-
that systems express hierarchical levels that influ- tion,” which involves conceptualizing “the
ence each other and that “interlevel” causation minimization” of thermodynamic free energy in
takes place between neighboring levels in a terms of a “variational free energy” (p. 2). The
hierarchy. mathematics described is beyond the scope of the
Ellis et al. (2012) defined top-down causation present work, but the simulations undertaken in
as involving “higher level features” functioning to their work involved “generative models” based
exert “irreducible productive” “causal influence” on “fixed-point” attractors.
on processes that are lower level. The emergence
involved is both “diachronic” (not predictive from
a prior state) and “synchronic” (not derivable from Comment
laws governing anything at lower levels).
As this review indicates, recent work on causality
Brain Network theory provides an example of has emphasized the top-down causation afforded
top-down control in brain activity. Marshall, by higher-order levels in systems. This idea has
Bergmann, and Jensen (2015) found that “stron- been applied to the areas of physics, biology, and
ger” volume in the medial branch of the superior the brain, in particular, in the material that I
longitudinal fasciculus (SLF), which is a white selected for review. It is a segue into the following
matter tract that connects parietal regions to fron- model in which bottom-up and top-down causal
tal control areas, led to better ability to modulate influences are described for higher-order and
alpha and gamma band synchronization. In turn, lower-order levels of systems, respectively, and
908 37 Epilogue

that these differing causal influences and associ- Comment


ated levels in a system can work in a coordinated
way in a hybrid model of system causality. Therefore, according to the model that I devel-
oped integrating bottom-up and top-down causa-
tion across levels of a system (Young, 2015a),
New Hybrid Symptom Network causality resides in the rich dynamical systemic
Construct Model interactions and reciprocal influences amongst
the various levels of a system and their nexus
Model nodes, elements, element (sub)sets, constructs,
and other aspects inherent in them, such as
The next section of the epilogue presents an inte- symptom and disorder. Specifically, for the topic
grative model of the symptom network and latent at issue of symptom networks and constructs
variable models concerning symptom-mental such as PTSD, symptoms have causal effects on
disorder relationship (see Fig. 37.1). It avoids each other but, reciprocally, constructs have
some of the pitfalls of prior attempts to do causal effects on them. In this sense, constructs,
the same (as described in Young, 2015a). such as mental disorder, are emergent, irreduc-
Nevertheless, it is an initial conceptualization ible entities that can affect and even initiate the
that itself has limitations, such as not yet being symptoms.
mathematically grounded nor empirically tested.
The lower levels of the model being presented
refer to symptoms and their interactions, as per Application
network theory (e.g., PTSD; McNally et al.,
2015). The higher levels of the model refer to In the following, I apply the hybrid symptom
psychological constructs, such as PTSD or network/construct model that I developed such
depression, and the clusters of symptoms that that an intermediate level in the hierarchy of lev-
might comprise them. els involved is required. Instead of just top-down,
Figure 37.1 shows that, for any one construct higher-order levels and bottom-up, lower-order
or cluster in mental disorder, there is both a top- ones, I add a middle level in the understanding of
down influence/creation of symptoms and bot- PTSD that refers to the individual’s causal per-
tom-up ones, that is, from symptom interactions ception of her/his symptoms.
upward to effects on construct/cluster. Moreover, As reviewed in Young (2016), in Frewen,
these top-down and bottom-up effects can func- Schmittmann, Bringmann, and Borsboom (2013),
tion at intermediate levels. Further, the interac- university undergraduates (N = 288) answered a
tions can take place not only horizontally (among questionnaire (40 items) related to Major Depressive
symptoms; among levels/sublevels; among their Episode, PTSD (DSM-IV-TR consistent), symp-
configurations/patterns) but also vertically toms of other anxiety disorders, and other symp-
(upward or downward over (sub)levels). toms. Upon statistical analysis, in terms of symptom
New to my modeling of symptoms-disorder networks, the two symptoms of flashbacks and
relations, Fig. 37.2 expands the prior figure by avoidance of reminders of the trauma experienced
expanding the relationship between symptom were evident in many feedback loops. Also, anxious
and disorder to comorbid condition(s). I arrived worrying, depressed mood, and trauma memory
at this expansion by considering that if any one symptoms most influenced other symptoms; and
disorder and its symptoms can be represented as the ones most influenced were about emotions or
a system with multiple intra- and inter-level functional problems (e.g., numbing, work,
interactions, so can the ensemble of symptoms respectively).
over comorbid conditions. The figure caption of Frewen et al. (2013) added superordinate
the model gives its details. influences on symptom expression related to the
New Hybrid Symptom Network Construct Model 909

S1*

(S4) Cluster 1* S2

(S3)

S1* S1*

(S4) (Cluster 4) S2 PTSD (S4) Cluster 2 S2

(S3) (S3)

S1*

(S4) Cluster 3 S2

(S3)

Fig. 37.1 Integrative causal symptom-construct model in parentheses indicate that PTSD might have only three clus-
mental disorder. The figure depicts the relationship between ters (as in the DSM-IV), and a cluster might have only two
symptoms and mental disorder (or a symptom cluster of symptoms. Of course, depending on the disorder involved
one) as being dynamically reciprocal in causation. The either might have more items (i.e., clusters or symptoms,
mental disorder constitutes an underlying, higher-order respectively). Of the clusters in any mental disorder, for
level in the patient’s mental state symptoms, while the their symptoms, it would be beneficial to specify which
symptoms interact at lower-levels of the system, with both ones are core/primary. For the model presented in the fig-
the top-down and bottom-up influences dynamically influ- ure, these could be the first clusters or symptoms that are
encing each other in context and over time. Note: The specified by the asterisks. Adopted from Young (2015a)

causal interaction between networked symptoms the symptoms as causal of them in individualized
and the person’s higher-order perception of cau- ways alters their networking and the nature of the
sality. That is, I conclude that the expression of superordinate construct.
PTSD is not only about symptoms and the con- In summary, Frewen et al. (2013) have elabo-
struct interacting. Also, it is about the personal rated a level of understanding of PTSD and
appraisal of how an individual’s perception of comorbid symptoms that speaks to the person’s
910 37 Epilogue

C1

C4 Disorder C2

C3
Context

CO1

Comorbid
(CO4) (ities) (CO2)

(CO3)

Time (Dev)

Fig. 37.2 An integrative (bottom-up, top-down) disorder able) reciprocally-related causal influences on behavior.
and comorbid(ities). The figure illustrates how a disorder The figure does not deal with the issue of whether mental
and its comorbidity/comorbidities (CO) might relate to disorder can be carved so neatly at its joints into separate
each other in exacerbation, mutual maintenance, or simply and comorbid mental disorders. This figure works for
in creating a larger symptom complex. It considers disorder PTSD and its comorbidities.
and its symptom cluster (C), viewing their relationship as Finally, the current approach to a hybrid symptom net-
reciprocally causal with the disorder at issue. The same can work/mental disorder construct model can be expanded to
be said for how symptoms interrelate or network amongst include intermediate levels outside of symptoms clusters
themselves. Therefore, the figure includes the notion that, within disorders. In this regard, the patients’ perceptions of
for any one disorder and its comorbid condition(s), there their symptoms could alter the nature of the symptom expe-
are both bottom-up (interactive symptom; interactive clus- rience and how they interact with lower (symptom) and
ters; interactive comorbidities) and top-down (latent vari- higher (construct) levels. Adopted from Young (2015a)

causal perceptions of the symptomatology Comment


involved. In the following, I consider the broader
implications of their work. For example, causal- The results in Frewen et al. (2013) speak to my
ity is as much a matter of internal perception as hybrid symptom network-construct model of
external force impact. symptoms, clusters, and the construct of PTSD
New Hybrid Symptom Network Construct Model 911

(Young, 2015a). In my model, as mentioned, Conclusion


there is a not only a symptom network, bottom-
up level but also a construct, top-down level. I have presented a hybrid symptom
Furthermore, these levels interact reciprocally. In network/psychological construct model of men-
their case, the top-down level influencing symp- tal disorder that allows for reciprocal top-down
tom networks is causal perception. and bottom-up influences. I described the model
A model that combines their approach and as one involving systems with multiple interact-
mine would consist of three levels—a higher- ing levels. The process-relational view (e.g.,
order construct one, a lower-order symptom net- Witherington, 2015), the network view as applied
work one, and an intermediate one concerning to attitudes (Dalege et al., 2016), and the network
the causal effect of a person’s perception of the model as applied to modules in the brain (Sporns
symptoms and their networks. These appraisals & Betzel, 2016) all speak to this type of concep-
might be the important components shaping, tion of multiple interacting levels in systems (and
reciprocally, in a bottom-up way the lower-order higher-order levels emergent from activity in the
symptom networks and, simultaneously, the lower-order ones).
nature of the higher-order constructs (and clus- In the following, to conclude the book, I pro-
ters) in PTSD. This type of modeling should be pose that this type of modeling can be applied to
transferable to other disorders, their networks, other areas not only in the cognitive (e.g., devel-
and their personal perceptions. opment, attitudes) domain, the neuroscientific
In Young (2016), I argued exactly for this type one (e.g., modules in the Connectome), and the
of model integration for PTSD that a superordi- mental disorder one (e.g., to PTSD), but also in
nate integration of the two models of Frewen et al. other domains. In this regard, I focus on new con-
(2013) and Young (2015a) on the causality of psy- ceptions of stages of emotional intelligence, in
chopathology (e.g., for PTSD), would place an particular.
intermediate level of patient construals of causal- Specifically, the hierarchical multilevel model
ity as a mediator between symptoms in the lower implicit in the symptom-perception-construct
level of the system involved and latent constructs model of layers in understanding mental disorder
in the higher level involved (and symptom clusters (Young, 2015a, 2016) can be applied in a revi-
could be related to both, as well). Moreover, I had sion of the understanding of stages in develop-
maintained that this new level of patient causal ment. They have been described as hierarchical,
perception of the symptoms involved, itself, integrative, and so on, and having décalages to
would be reciprocally related to the lower and account for their uneven development both over
higher levels in the symptom configuration and within tasks and domains (Lourenço, 2016).
through system dynamics. However, below, I criticized the vague nature of
I would add to this description of a hybrid hierarchical integration in explaining stages.
symptom network-psychological construct In this regard, a hybrid network-construct
model of PTSD that not only could it apply to model with multiple hierarchical levels might be
other disorders but also that it leads to a major better able to account for individual differences
conceptual shift of the nature of mental disorder. in mastery of tasks and domains in stage-related
They are more than DSM symptom lists. They cognitive development. For example, Case’s
are not uniform expressions of naturally present concept of central conceptual structures in differ-
categories carved by nature at the joints. Rather, ent domains (e.g., quantitative, social, narrative)
they are dynamic entities that are individually has been developed to explain better Piaget’s
expressed yet still exist as superordinate, emer- concept of “structures d’ensemble.” This notion
gent, higher-order mental conditions or wholes of central conceptual structures could be
that can influence in a top-down way the symp- reworked into systems design, that is, as struc-
toms involved (and in individual ways because of tures with each of higher-order, intermediate, and
their individual configurations). lower-order levels that develop in different ways
912 37 Epilogue

for each individual, depending on biological, discontinuous macro-developments involving


environment, and other (e.g., motivational) fac- stages remain elusive in extant models.
tors, i.e., according to biopsychosocial factors. In The goal of the next section is to address these
the following, I flesh out this model of an elabo- issues, especially in terms of applying a hierar-
ration of central conceptual structures to explain chical model of system levels that behave nonlin-
better cognitive stages. early to the second question of within-stage
organization and the third of developing schemes
within a stage. This model permits extensions
Reconceptualizing Cognitive Stages into the first question of how the stages move
from one to the next, as well.
Existing Concept

As described previously, according to Lourenço Reconceptualization


(2016), Piaget considered developmental stages
as—hierarchical or invariant in order; integrative Model In the following, I present through five
of prior stages yet with consolidating transitions figures a full model that I have developed to
between them; and characterized as wholes or explain better development both within and
overarching “structures d’ensemble” that are in across levels of a cognitive structure, and even
equilibration. They express a “décalage” (uneven within and across levels of a developmental sub-
development) within a domain/stage due to task stage or stage. The figure captions give much of
complexity differences. the details of the model and, in the next para-
graphs, I give an overview.
Essentially, the model is multifactorial, and
Comment explains that multilevel hierarchical models lay
at the heart of development. On the one hand,
The concept of stages in the Piagetian tradition is they can represent the development of a concep-
incomplete in at least three levels. (a) First, there tual structure related to a set of a few tasks all the
is no plausible mechanism that can account for way to a set of domains within a stage. Moreover,
the discontinuous transition from one stage to the the structure could advance to a new level of skill
next. To say that the stages are integrative speaks that is qualitatively distinct and represents a new
neither to their emergence at new levels nor how (sub)stage.
the integration takes place. (b) Second, there is The first of the figures (Fig. 37.3) presents the
no plausible understanding of how the uneven way in which a new mental schema that develops
and individualized nature of within-stage organi- for a particular domain in a particular stage for a
zation that takes place is structured, aside from particular child might grow to a rule over exam-
saying that there are décalages. (c) Third, there is plars and then a generalized rule, preparatory to
no plausible explanation of how schemas within the start of a new stage. This model is based on
a particular stage transform toward higher-order attractor/complexity/systems theory modeling
structures, other than indicating that there are (after Young, 2011). Then, I expand this work by
transitions involved. starting with the simplest of models and works up
Granted, Piaget and Neo-Piagetians have to the one I have developed involving the differ-
elaborated concepts in these regards related to ential, temporary yoking of skills from different
information processing, in particular, e.g., mem- stages for any immediate task or problem at hand
ory, executive function, and they have touched (Fig. 37.4). The next figure deals with individual
upon systems theory (Mascolo & Fischer, 2015). differences in development, both intra-individual
However, the precise details needed about cau- and inter-individual. These differences could be
sality for moving from ongoing, continuous within or across tasks/subdomains/domains
micro-developments in one task or the other to within a child or across children in these regards
Reconceptualizing Cognitive Stages 913

Step Representation Possible Explanation

0. Precoordination Fixed-point attractor: represents a mental


schema that had developed

Two fixed-point attractors: juxtaposed


I 1. Coordination (e.g., a mental schema that exists, a new
one applied to new tasks/ problems)

Oscillatory cycle attractor: represents


2. Hierarchization the coordination of the original and
new versions of the schema

Chaotic attractor (system): develops, i.e.,


3. Systematization the newer version of the mental schema
subsumes the others, forming one explicit
rule

Gravitating to the cusp between order and


4. Multiplication disorder, an attractor (complexity) landscape
… emergences (complex adaptive system): the
new systematized rule propagates

5. Integration
Superordinate attractor complexity
landscape: the new generalized rule is
widely entrenched in the individual’s

behavior

New cycle of fixed-point


attractor evolution: begins with
II. Coordination, etc. the new integration in the prior
(cyclic recursion) … stage constituting a fixed-point
attractor, leading to coordination/
oscillation

Fig. 37.3 Conceptual control structure development In another example, the attractor/complexity model
within a domain in terms of attractors/complexity. As men- can be applied to disorder/disability or competing health
tal schemas emerge and spread within a particular domain trajectories, so that the states of health and disorder/dys-
of a particular stage of cognitive development, they should function/disability involved could be seen to pass through
first be juxtaposed in coordination, then hierarchized with five steps of change from a simpler coordination to a quite
the new one predominant, and then systematized into a stable integration.
new rule. Next, they should spread out or multiply through- Another applied example would be for dealing with
out the system, leading to integration of a generalized rule the challenges/crises presented by each new Eriksonian/
that covers all exemplars within the individual’s particular Freudian stage that might develop. Do they begin with a
cognitive development for the stage at issue. challenge/crisis and their solutions, in a coordination
This five-step sequence might correspond to changes in that leads toward resolution and growth, or do they lapse
attractor-complexity organization. That is, attractors might into entrenchment in the crises inherent in the challenges
gravitate from fixed point to oscillatory and chaotic ones and get worse as development continues, but still toward
and then to more complex architecture involving the cusp integration, albeit in a negative mode? This model of
of change to CAS and superordinate complex systems. attractor evolution can be applied generically to change
This model has been applied to substage changes in in both living and nonliving systems, assuming a consis-
Young’s (2011) Neo-Piagetian cognitive developmental tency for the appropriate conditions of nonlinear dynam-
model. Also, it might apply to both higher (e.g., stage) and ical system functioning. It can be applied to different
lower (i.e., domain transitions as they move through the levels of a system because of fractal dynamics, e.g., from
phases of coordination (after pre-coordination) hierar- one developmental stage to the next, within each of the
chization, systematization, multiplication, and integration, substages involved, within domains within substages,
with a cyclic recursion potentially taking place after that. and so on
914 37 Epilogue

a b

d
c

ei. eii. eiii. eiv.


Development

Development

Development

Development

1 2 3 4 1 2 3 4 1 2 3 4 1 2 3 4

Stage Stage Stage Stage

Fig. 37.4 Different conceptions of development. (a) Parallel stages develop in that new stages do not incorpo-
Development is linear and can cur in multiple directions rate or displace prior ones. Stage development is non-
over time: for example, it could be progressive (line slant- integrative rather than integrative. New stages appear
ing upward), regressive (downward), flat, with all path- without incorporating prior ones. The prior ones continue
ways possible even in one child, depending on the task to develop even after the ones more complex than them
and context; development takes place in continuous ways appear. The skills of the prior and new stages can function
in these various pathways. (b) Development is stepwise: together, being yoked as needed by the task or problem at
with stages, milestones, etc. It takes place in discontinu- hand. (e) Different stage (or substage) yokings: (i) only
ous ways; e.g., Piagetian cognitive development; the highest level one is necessary for the task or problem
Eriksonian socio-affective development. Stages are hier- at hand; (ii) a lower one is added; (iii) all are added; (iv)
archical and integrative, with new ones incorporating its the highest one isn’t the primary one needed; not all
prior ones. (c) Development reaches bifurcation points or needed. Note: Each of these (sub)stage yoking configura-
other ways in which it splits, changes, or alters. For exam- tions can be adaptive or maladaptive. Perhaps the highest
ple, with respect to bifurcation points, in systems theory, one isn’t the best for a task at hand. Perhaps the ones
state configuration reaches critical threshold and splits; deployed are used inefficiently, are compromised by brain
different state configurations (e.g., attractors) arise. (d) damage, psychological problems, etc.
Reconceptualizing Cognitive Stages 915

a constructs, with intermediate levels between


X+1 them: and other work, such as the application of
NLDST to attitudes (see previously). The figure
indicates a smoothed version of the model and a
Development

“messier” one that better reflects what real-life


cognitive growth would look like.
The next two figures consider mechanisms of
change, including the one inherent in NLDST of
Stage X

emergence. This takes place through spontaneous


self-organization among system elements when
the system configuration is “stretched” beyond
A B C D E carrying capacity and, therefore, more graceful
Domains (or Task in a Domain) patterns arise. However, I point out that there are
limits to the emergence, for example, if the sys-
tem “machinery” of components included does
b not support certain higher-order configurations
X+1

(read as, for example—abstract thought would be


impossible at certain ages and in all nonhuman
Development

species).
Specifically, Fig. 37.7 illustrates that the
mechanisms of change in development involve
both lateral, horizontal mechanisms within a
level/substage/stage and vertical mechanisms
Stage X

upward to higher-order ones. The process of gen-


eralization seems involved in both types. In both
cases, better energetic management seems to be
A B C D E involved. The previous discussion of reciprocal
Domains (or Task in a Domain) causality among levels of a hierarchy also applies
here. As for Fig. 37.8, it speaks to the concept of
Fig. 37.5 Individual differences in stage development
within children and across their within-stage domains
activation/inhibition coordination and another
(intra-individual) or across children (inter-individual). involving energetics, that of vitality and
The figure illustrates development within a stage mostly. reverberation. The former has been discussed
It takes place over in different ways for different children, throughout the book, while the latter is new to it.
both within a domain or across domains, as per the differ-
ent trajectories outlined in the first part of the figure com-
The vitality/reverberation energetics model
pared to the second. For some tasks (domains), indicates that the energy involved in cognitive
development traverses boundaries separating the nature of growth comes from the child through motivation
acquisitions in one stage to the next, as per the second part and the like. Energetics is not simply about what
of the figure. Case (1998) referred to the development of
the cognitive schemas in a domain as central conceptual
“cold” entities within a cognitive system experi-
structures. My version of the concept emphasizes the task/ ence as it equilibrates but also about the “hot”
domain individual differences involved and that they can energy of curiosity, effort, motivation, a desire to
develop according to (sub)stages learn, and so on.
This energy reflects a vitality in the child, and
(Fig. 37.5). The figure after that (Fig. 37.6) is the one that can be dispersed with multiple reverber-
most complex because it deals with the concept ations in the child’s psychological architecture
of hierarchical multilevel systems in develop- and cognitive functionality. Many factors can
ment. The concept integrates work on: systems influence it, including the hot energy of proper
theory (NLDST): network theory; my hybrid parental support, school environment, and so on.
model of symptom networks and psychological At the other extreme, many factors can affect it
916 37 Epilogue

X+1

(a) smoothed (without


décalages and isolates)
Development

(b) décalages and isolates


included in this part
Stage X

A B

Domain

Fig. 37.6 A hierarchical multilevel systems model of tral theme. Part (b) shows a messier but more probable
across-domain/task organization in development. The fig- developmental pathway in these regards. For example,
ure illustrates how central conceptual structures grow different but related acquisitions emerge at different times
within a stage, or perhaps into a higher-order one, too (in (décalages) and some are orphaned isolates not related to
the part of the figure to the right, at the top). Central con- others. Moreover, part (a) can represent a different
ceptual structures apply to particular domains or subdo- domain, subdomain, or lower-order task collection in the
mains (which are task collections; e.g., quantitative, same child, indicative of intra-individual differences in
social, narrative). Part (a) shows that they might develop domain mastery within a stage. Finally, it indicates that
from lower-order schemas into second-order consolida- domain development within a stage can traverse the
tions (or more, depending on the complexity involved). threshold boundary of the nature of skills applicable to
They could end with superordinate upper-level integra- one stage compared to the one preceding it. Note that the
tions, such as mathematical rules, ordered social skill sets, arrows ↔ indicate interactions between levels, intra-
or narrative plot structure knowledge. domain acquisitions, and inter-domain acquisitions. The
Part (a) is a smooth rendition, with differential timing points represent critical initial nodes or hubs at which a
of different but equivalent acquisitions shown to emerge domain schema or related acquisition develops, leading to
at the same time and with all acquisitions related to a cen- its spread
Reconceptualizing Cognitive Stages 917

Development

Domains

b
Development

Domains

Fig. 37.7 Mechanisms of change in domain/task hierar- the most advanced structure within the stage at issue or,
chical multilevel systems, both within and across stages also, it could be preparatory to another one that is penul-
(intrastage, interstage). Part (a) illustrates how change timate, or a qualitatively superior stage. See the text for
can take place within a stage from the point of view of discussion of the reciprocal causality that might be
developmental stages. The development is on-line, local, involved across levels. This is indicated by the vertical
continuous, task-by-task, strategy-by-strategy. The arrow in the figure.
scheme involved is applied perhaps with minor adjust- Note: The developmental change mechanisms being
ment. It happens repeatedly, though, creating storage described are complemented by model of transitions in
and organization issues. All told, the growth is horizon- attractor complexity in a process of generic change that
tal rather than vertical. The generalization is lateral I have described. For simplicity, in the figures in this sec-
rather than emergent to a new level. The horizontal, lat- tion, I have graphed three-level hierarchical multilevel
eral development within a level is indicated by the hori- systems, but alluded to more possible levels. It could be
zontal arrow. that five levels, as per Fig. 37.1’s depiction of a generic
Part (b) illustrates that development could also be attractor-complexity transition sequence, is optimal and
toward increasing complexity. For example, a schema applies equally to (sub)domains/task collections within
becomes broader and flexible in application, and perhaps any one stage as they complexify.
even reaching threshold for a level that is more represen- I have applied the concept of evolving attractors to
tative, like a rule or operation. This takes place because cognitive development. However, now that I am showing
the energetic weight of maintaining a multitude of sche- parallels in multiple cognitive and emotion-related intel-
matic variations at the same level, as per the process in ligences according to my model, the attractor evolution
(a), overwhelms the system, or pushes it to the edge of model might help in understanding the development of
ongoing system configuration dissolution, and over, multiple emotion-related intelligences.
through the perturbations involved. The child has mas- Also, about change mechanisms in cognitive devel-
tered enough variations of the basic scheme to seek out opment, Piaget (1970) referred to the concept of “reflec-
generalities in the vertical level, or in terms of an tive abstraction” in facilitating cognitive growth, which
increasing generalized skill/rule/thought. This might could be type of reflective distancing or metacognition.
prepare the way for one or more additional more According to me, this process illustrates the child’s active
advanced levels in the system, the latter of which could contribution to her own development. Pulling back to
be the final one for the domain at issue over the tasks observe, act on, coordinate, unify, etc., demands both under-
involved. In addition, this final one could be either only standing and a will to full application, as per Fig. 37.8
918 37 Epilogue

Development Inhibition

Activation
Domain

b
Development

Vitality
Reverberation

Domain

Fig. 37.8 Activation/inhibition coordination and vitality/ tem composite of elements involved, must be able to
reverberation in domain/task change. Part (a) indicates that support a change to qualitatively distinct levels. Systems
development both within a level, or stage grosso modo, have their reaction ranges just as gene complexes might.
takes place through activation/inhibition coordination. The Part (b) reinforces that development is not machine-
concentric circles indicate it can vary in strength. like or passive. It involves the individual in active, dynamic
Activation/inhibition coordination applies across the board participation, including through motivation, giving effort,
to developmental and behavioral phenomena, from brain, deploying energy effectively, showing curiosity, paying
to behavior, to social interaction, and so on. Activation/ attention, absorbing or learning, persevering or otherwise
inhibition coordination applies to the horizontal, lateral coping well, and so on. The concentric circles indicate that
interactions necessary for schema expansion and adjust- this active glue in development which we addressing can
ment that takes place for tasks, subdomains, and domains. vary, for example, in the energetic metrics of vitality and
Also, it applies vertically to the growth toward more com- reverberation. With the right context, skill, and approach to
plex levels and even into new stages. That being said, there the task or problem at hand, in conjunction with the right
are limits to upward growth in these regards. The develop- “machinery,” emergence to new levels in the domain(s) or
mental, biological, and behavioral “machinery,” or the sys- (sub)stages at issue is facilitated

detrimentally, including parental abuse, school Comment In the prior section, I have explained a
indifference, and so on. Needless to say, the model of cognitive development that covers
model could include biological factors that mechanisms of change within a level/
impact child energetics, such as neurodevelop- substage/stage and upward to new ones. I termi-
mental difficulties. nated with a model of energetics related to the
Multiple Emotional Intelligences 919

motivation, curiosity, etc., of the child, and indi- are in verbal reasoning, perceptual (or visuo-
cated the factors that can affect it, such as spatial) reasoning, working memory, and pro-
parental/school ones. This latter model provides a cessing speed. The WISC-IV has 2–3 subtests
good segue into the socio-affective realm and how that contribute to each of the four factor scores
it develops from one level, substage, or stage to (e.g., respectively, vocabulary, block design, digit
the next. My developmental model (Young, 2011) span, and symbol search).
is not only cognitive and Neo-Piagetian but also In order to broaden understanding of intelli-
socio-affective Neo-Eriksonian in its stage con- gence and its testing beyond predictors of aca-
ception. In this regard, in the following, I attempt demic achievement and because of alternate
to show how the concept of emotional intelligence conceptualizations that do not give primacy to
can be reworked into a stage model and, more- one full-scale score being representative of gen-
over, one that is multiple (e.g., with stage yoking), eral intelligence, alternate models of intelligence
just as I have done with cognitive development. and its testing have been developed. Gardner and
Before beginning, I review the concept of Sternberg have presented the most noteworthy
multiple intelligences and then examine the con- theories on multiple intelligence. Gardner (1983,
cept of emotional intelligence. Both areas do not 1993) and Chen and Gardner (2011) presented a
involve stage conceptions. Both areas mention model of independent intelligences that went
domains and similar concepts. It is not difficult to beyond the traditional domains. Aside from lin-
argue that for each domain involved, they could guistic, logico-mathematical, and spatial intelli-
pass through a stage sequence, and moreover, gence, Gardiner added other intelligences, such
that the stages could be yoked. as ones that are musical, naturalistic,
bodily/kinesthetic, intrapersonal, and interper-
sonal. As for Sternberg (1985, 2015), the three
Multiple Emotional Intelligences components of intelligence include not only the
standard analytic one but also practical and cre-
Multiple Intelligences ative ones. Both Gardner and Sternberg, or their
colleagues and those who follow them, have
Model The standard model of intelligence is developed tests of their models. For example,
predicated on the assumption that items on the IQ Ekinici (2014) determined which of the intelli-
(intelligent quotient) test can give scores that pre- gences in the two models under discussion best
dict academic performance, especially school predicted academic achievement in Turkish pri-
grades (Berk, 2013; Berk & Meyers, 2016; mary school children.
Ekinici, 2014; Chen & Gardner, 2011; Sternberg,
2015; Young, 2011). Furthermore, it maintains New Model The model of multiple intelligences
that the aggregate of the scores into a total or relates to children but it is still not developmental
intelligence quotient score (IQ) can represent enough. For example, do all of the intelligences
one’s general intelligence because it is an inte- start from birth? How do they grow, simply quan-
grated adaptive function. That is, in factor ana- titatively? In order to respond to these types of
lytic research on intelligence testing, a general or criticisms, Young (2011) developed a model of
g factor is found, and others more specific to multiple intelligences that is based on his Neo-
domains. Further, in this psychometric approach, Piagetian model. In particular, the five
tests are constructed that are arranged hierarchi- Neo-Piagetian stages of his model were consid-
cally such that the full-scale IQ can be decom- ered different intelligences. Moreover, in solving
posed into broad processing scores reflective of tasks and problems, Young posited that they are
factors in empirical studies. For example, the deployed together as required, in a yoking pro-
WISC-IV (Wechsler Intelligence Scale for cess. For example, one task might require the
Children, Fourth Edition, 2003) has four broad highest stage/type of thought available to solve a
intellectual factors aside from its IQ score, which problem, with the second-highest subsidiary to
920 37 Epilogue

that one. For another child on a different task, socio-affective in nature and not Piagetian-based,
perhaps a lower level stage and its associated they are posited to develop in sequence over the
thought is best, and there are two higher-order lifespan): (a) Non-participatory reflexive socio-
ones that are yoked to it. This modeling is consis- emotions (up to the first month of life); (b) Pre-
tent with the onion metaphor of cognitive func- participatory socio-affects (the young child); (c)
tioning (Rochat, 2015) and Overton’s (2015) Peri-participatory social cognitions (middle
Neo-Piagetian approach in which stages persist childhood); (d) Hyper-participatory social mutu-
in development even after new ones are formed. ality (the teenager), and (e) Superordinate partici-
Young (2011) added that Gardiner’s different patory collective sociality (the adult).
types of multiple intelligences are simply As can be seen, I organized the definitions of
domains in which the various stages in his model the five sets of Neo-Eriksonian substages accord-
might pass through. As for Sternberg, his three ing to the concept of “participation” in social
intelligences are complementary adaptive functions relations. Therefore, for the first Neo-Eriksonian
in this process. Young noted that the environment stage, or group of five substages, corresponding
determines, too, how intelligence develops (e.g., to the first Reflexive Neo-Piagetian cognitive
support vs. abuse), and that personal factors are stage of the present model, I considered them as
involved, for example, motivation, curiosity, and “non-participatory” and “reflexive.” However, I
socio-affective factors. also considered them as socioemotional because
the stage ends after birth with the Neo-Eriksonian
Comment In this epilogue, I extend the model steps of caregiving acts and emotional acts.
that I developed on multiple intelligences to emo- As for the second Neo-Eriksonian stage, it
tional intelligence. The latter is a domain-based reflects its Neo-Piagetian sensorimotor equiva-
approach as much is the case for cognitive intel- lent stage, and is heavily associated with emo-
ligence, and factor analytic studies predominate. tional expressions serving to intercoordinate the
There is little developmental work on the topic, baby and the caregiver. Nevertheless, there is a
and none that considers it from the way I would, lack of the genuine participation acts in this age
that is, in terms of passage through developmen- period. Therefore, the label for this stage involved
tal stages. the concept of “pre-participatory.”
Before presenting my model of multiple Corresponding to the third cognitive stage
emotional intelligences, I note that the stage under discussion, called perioperational, appears
component of the model to which I refer is not to be a Neo-Eriksonian one in which the child is
the Neo-Piagetian one but the corresponding reaching more genuine participatory socio-
Neo-Eriksonian one that I developed (Young, affective social coordinations. Therefore, I
2011). In this regard, just as the cognitive devel- referred to “peri-participatory” socio-affectivity
opmental model that I proposed in revision of as the correct Neo-Eriksonian description for this
Piaget has 25 steps over the lifespan (5 stages × 5 stage. Within it, just as one finds preoperations
cyclically recurring substages), so does the cor- and concrete operations on the cognitive side,
responding Neo-Eriksonian one. In this latter one should find quasi-participatory and full par-
model, I placed Erikson’s eight stages in relation ticipatory socio-affectivity. In addition, the label
to the corresponding step to which they seemed for this third Neo-Eriksonian stage includes the
to be in parallel in the Neo-Piagetian steps that I concept of socio-cognition because of the exten-
had created, and then added 17 new ones to com- sive development in this age period of aspects of
plete the cycle of 25 steps. socio-cognition, such as theory of mind and
In Young (2012), I gave labels to each set of self-regulation.
five Neo-Eriksonian substages that correspond to The fourth and fifth Neo-Eriksonian stages
each set of five Neo-Piagetian substages (the five being proposed in the present model reflect socio-
stages of that model). The five terms are the fol- affective development that goes beyond basic
lowing (and, as representations of stages, albeit interactive participations in several ways. First,
Multiple Emotional Intelligences 921

the socio-affective interchanges of adolescents In the next section, I describe emotional intel-
and emerging adults can be considered “hyper- ligence, which prepares the way for presentation
participatory” in that they include the develop- of my model of multiple emotional intelligences.
ment of conscious awareness, identity, nurturing, After undertaking the latter task, I consider the
intimacy, and more universal acts. Of course, as mechanisms that might underlie its expression in
with any of the Neo-Eriksonian stages, these the individual.
tasks might be compromised as the challenges
that they present are not met because of difficult
circumstances, effects of poor navigation of prior Emotional Intelligence
stages, and so on.
The fifth Neo-Eriksonian stage corresponds to
the Neo-Piagetian cognitive stage of collective Model Emotional intelligence (EI) is defined as
intelligence. The latter is considered to include a set of competences that allow people to process
superordinate abstract systems. Therefore, the emotion-related information toward using the
label that I have given for this phase of develop- information acquired in guiding thought and
ment includes the terms “superordinate participa- behavior (Mayer, Roberts, & Barsade, 2008).
tory” as well as “collective sociality.” The test developed for operationalizing EI
These five Neo-Eriksonian substage sets can (MSCEIT; Mayer-Salovey-Caruso Emotional
be considered the equivalent of stages in the Intelligence Test; Mayer, Salovey, & Caruso,
Neo-Eriksonian model. It is with these I 2002) includes 141 items that yields an FEI (full
worked with, rather than the original Eriksonian scale EI) and two domain scores, each with two
stages, as I was constructing a model of the branch scores: (a) Experiential EI; and (b)
components of what constitutes multiple emo- Strategic EI. The former involves tasks on the
tional intelligences. perception of emotions and others on their use.
As mentioned, but amplified here, a major dif- The latter involves tasks related to understanding
ference in the parallel Neo-Eriksonian and Neo- emotions and also managing emotions. There are
Piagetian steps in development that I have eight tasks on the MSCEIT. Operskalski, Paul,
described is that the former relative to the latter Colom, Barbey, and Grafman (2015) showed, in
are much more sensitive to environmental dis- a factor analytic study with 130 combat veterans
ruption. By their very nature, they represent chal- having focal penetrating traumatic brain injuries
lenges that the developing person must confront, (TBI), that task scores organize into four factors
and the negative poles of the challenges, if pre- corresponding to the branch scales of the
dominant relative to the positive poles because of MSCEIT, with two tasks associated with each
experience, can lead to delays in development, factor (faces, pictures for perceiving emotions;
baggage to work through, fixations, and even sensations, facilitation for using emotions;
regression. blends, changes for understanding emotions; and
Note that, for terminology, I refer to multiple emotional management and social management
intelligences as multiple cognitive intelligences for managing emotions).
and multiple emotional intelligences as multiple Operskalski et al. (2015) conducted a study on
socio-affective intelligences. This is consistent the neural networks associated with the
with the view that emotions serve social func- four-factor structure of emotional intelligence.
tions, as in social cognition, and also Erikson’s They used voxel-based lesion symptom mapping
emphasis on both the mutuality with the socio- to determine neural substrates of the factors.
cultural milieu in development, and the nature of They found core, domain-general common ones
his stages (which he referred to as psychosocial and peripheral, task-specific ones.
rather than psychosexual; Berk, 2013; Berk & The results showed that impairments, as
Meyers, 2016). shown by test results, in the ability to perceive
922 37 Epilogue

emotional information was associated with selec- Multiple Emotional Intelligences


tive engagement deficits in the medial ventral
temporal cortex and the lateral PFC. The associa- Model In this section of the epilogue, I present a
tion for managing emotions was with the orbito- novel hypothesis about emotional intelligence,
frontal and parietal cortices. There were no which consists of several parts—(a) Emotional
associations for the other two facets of emotional intelligence is multiple, as in my model for cogni-
intelligence. As for core, common neural sub- tive intelligence; (b) With respect to stages, it
strates, they concerned the social processing and develops like the cognitive aspect of intelligence
knowledge networks within the frontal, temporal, (as per the Piagetian view); (c) The intelligences
and parietal cortices. involved can be yoked for the socio-affective task
The authors concluded that the sub-facets of at hand, just as with my model of yoked cognitive
the two main areas of emotional intelligence intelligences; (d) The multiple emotional intelli-
(experiential, strategic) represent “separable but gences can apply to different domains, as argued
related” processing. The results speak to a “net- for the model of multiple cognitive intelligences;
worked” brain substrate in emotional intelli- (e) The development involved takes place accord-
gence, as opposed to a “modular” one. That ing to the construction of schemas that are similar
being said, the networks involved might not be to those in the more cognitive domains; (f) The
unique to emotional intelligence functioning, mechanisms involved are the same as those driving
and also they might connect to larger net- cognitive development, as presented in the model
works not involved particularly in emotional in this epilogue, e.g., with emergence; multiple,
intelligence. hierarchical levels; horizontal and vertical mecha-
nisms; reciprocal causality; activation/inhibition
Comment The current concept of emotional coordination; vitality/reverberation, so on; (g) The
intelligence allows for scales that are general and emotional/socio-affective and cognitive realms are
also scales that are specific to functions (areas), not really dissociable—they are separated in the
such as strategic and experiential. Moreover, the literature either as a matter of convenience or in
latter have two scales (sub-facets) associated with acknowledgement of the complexity in considering
each of them. them together, especially in the developmental and
The work on emotional intelligence has lifespan context. In reality, they are mutually inter-
focused not only on its factorial structure but also active realms, feeding each other, engaging in
on its possible corresponding brain network reciprocal feedback, and cascades from one to the
underpinnings. Gardner had also attempted to use other over development; and (h) The development
neuroscientific research to justify his multiple in the emotional/socio-affective realm is not only
intelligences. multiple and parallels the development of the cog-
It would appear that there is much similarity nitive realm in many ways, but also it is exquisitely
with models of intelligence at the cognitive individual like in the latter realm, with intra-indi-
level that are built on finding an overall IQ, and vidual and inter-individual variation the norm.
then process scores with several tests under In the present model, the matrix of multiple
each of them, in a three-level hierarchical emotional intelligences involve the stages of
model, and the model of the structure of emo- Neo-Eriksonian growth as per the model in
tional intelligence just described, with its over- Young (2011) and the domains to which they can
all score, main areas, and sub-facets. In the be applied, as per the work of Mayer and Salovey,
following, on the basis of the Neo-Eriksonian in particular. The stages in Neo-Eriksonian
stage model that I have developed (Young, growth that I have described above include: (a)
2011), I present an alternative emotional intel- Non-participatory reflexive socio-emotions (up
ligence model that is also hierarchical and con- to the first month of life); (b) Pre-participatory
sisting of three levels (or more). socio-affects (including Erikson’s stages of Trust
Multiple Emotional Intelligences 923

vs. Mistrust and Autonomy vs. Doubt); (c) Peri- A patient might present with Identity issues
participatory social cognitions (includes Initiative that are still quite present in the late 20s, or
vs. Guilt; Industry vs. Inferiority); (d) Hyper- emerging adulthood. Moreover, a primary reason
participatory social mutuality (Identity vs. might be relationship issues, perhaps due to ques-
Identity Diffusion; Intimacy vs. Isolation), and tions related to Trust, hearkening back to an
(e) Superordinate participatory collective social- unsupportive first year or years of life. The
ity (Generativity vs. Self-Absorption; Ego domains that are largely affected in this type of
Integrity vs. Despair). According to the literature example would be social (information process-
on emotional intelligence, the domains in emo- ing, skills).
tional intelligence include: (a) Experiential emo- So far, this example reflects a standard
tional intelligence (the perception of emotions Eriksonian conceptualization of a personal prob-
and their use); and (b) Strategic emotional intel- lem. However, even then, there are the advan-
ligence (understanding emotions and managing tages inherent in the present yoking concept that
emotions). Because I have expanded the present can help. In particular, we can consider the fol-
model to include the Neo-Eriksonian perspective lowing: how the skills in the Neo-Eriksonian
and not just emotional intelligence, I refer to it as stages involved are juxtaposed; which ones are
a model of socio-affective multiple intelligences. considered primary; which ones yoke to or mask
In this regard, the domains are more numerous secondary ones; if there is rapid de-yoking in cir-
than those of Mayer, Salovey, and colleagues. cumstances where the yoking no longer applies
For example, one could add domains related to to solve the task/problem at hand; and so on. The
social interaction information processing and dynamics described above cognitively in online
social interaction skills. adaptive yoking would apply to the micro-
As for individual differences in the model pre- moments of stages yoking socio-affectively and
sented, the Neo-Eriksonian nature of the model so the 25 steps in the Neo-Eriksonian stages
already lends it to allowing for individual differ- would not just be functioning as large challenges
ences. Each stage presents challenges or crises to and crises that dominate the socio-affective life
navigate and these are affected by the degree of of the individual as a slowly-moving or an
mutuality with the environment. Also, by adding unmoveable block. That is, the mechanisms of
in my model a yoking component to the multiple change as described in the cognitive realm above
intelligences, the particular combination of would apply the same way to this area of devel-
socio-affective skills that are deployed for any opment, as micro-changes that at times lead to
one individual in any one context are innumera- not only horizontal change but also vertical
ble, and the one manifested for any one individ- change in a process of macro-changes, either
ual in any one context, most likely, will be unique upward or downward, depending on the factors
to him or her. Granted, there might be similar involved. Of course, a great challenge both in
classes of individuals in these regards, but these self-promoted growing efforts and in psychother-
similarities should not mask the individualized apy would be to discern these micro-change pat-
stance each of us takes in our participation in the terns and understand the conscious and
socio-affective tasks and problems at hand that unconscious dynamics that produce them.
we face in our daily lives. A second example of yoking of Eriksonian
Some examples help illustrate the yoking con- stages in this new concept being proposed of
cept as applied to Neo-Eriksonian stages. I give multiple emotional, or socio-affective, intelli-
examples related to substages, the development gences includes the following. This time, con-
of which is more fine-grained. Moreover, it sider a patient who has Initiative and Generativity
affords using as examples in the substages in my problems. He has a family but cannot keep a job
model the original eight Eriksonian stages, which because of flagging or failing motivation that
simplifies the concept for the reader. he does not understand, despite having all the
924 37 Epilogue

requisite skills and job support. The domains dedicated to that proposition and the continuing
involved are emotional at the base, because he project it entails.
has difficulties with aspects of both experiencing At press time, Harré and Moghaddam (2016)
emotions and their strategic use. For example, the have edited a useful book on causality in social
perception of emotions is compromised as is psychology and related social contexts. In Harré
their management. Therefore, he does not feel (2016) referred to the different “causal formats”
the other, empathize, read the mind from the per- and “causal discourses” of disciplines. He con-
spective of the other, etc., nor have good emo- sidered the concept of causation more specific
tional regulation and self-control skills. In the than the one of causality with the former refer-
end, he is judged bright but lacking in empathy ring to relations involving “particulars” and the
and emotional control. In terms of his Neo- former more generic “processes.” The book
Eriksonian development, his emotional deficits avoids jargon, and the first part is philosophical
manifest in his generative tasks, including at in subject matter. The most relevant chapter for
work and home. His lack of initiative is tinged present purposes is on mental health.
with some guilt, but less than might be expected As a final comment to the book, its major
according to the Eriksonian model, because of strength is its comprehensive literature review
his emotional deficits. and its conceptual integration. The major limita-
As for the micro-moment changes that take tion of the book is it’s broad range, which has to
place as he navigates the day, the more he can be the case because of its subject matter, and
mask his difficulties, the less temper he displays, some of the redundancies across chapters, which
but his energetics take him only so far, and explo- are inevitable because of its scope.
sions of anger might mar not only his personal
life but work life and his ability to keep his fam-
ily and job. Psychotherapy is addressing his pres- Epilogue Conclusions
ent control problems and past developmental
issues, in part by asking for micro-moment Epilogues are afterthoughts and, in the present
awareness along the lines of the parameters of the case, the thoughts involved complement very
case conceptualization just enunciated as well as well the text of the book that had been written
understanding how to change (and foster prepara- before it was formulated. The book has examined
tion for change). the multiple causal influences on development,
from genes to environment to free will and other
Comment This section of the epilogue is the personal contributions to our behavior. The epi-
final one, and therefore, it stands as the final one logue has solidified the systems point of view in
of the book before the last concluding comment. conceptualizing behavior and its causes. It has
The Neo-Eriksonian multiple socio-affective reinforced the interaction between top-down and
emotional intelligences model presented appears bottom-up influences in systems (and in behav-
a promising model because of its implications for ior), and has provided additional ways of con-
psychotherapy, as indicated by the examples pro- ceiving of stages in development and the domains
vided. As with all new models in the present that grow in development. In this regard, free will
book, it needs refinement, operationalization, and belief is a critical domain in cognition that can
testing. develop in individual ways as per the present
The study of causality, in general, requires rig- modeling exercise. At one point, it could become
orous study and research in all these ways. As the the superordinate concept in the hierarchy of
research is undertaken, the vitality and reverbera- beliefs related to causality and, therefore, influ-
tions that the work might gather could animate ence self-control, making correct choices, and
further efforts toward unifying psychology with following through appropriately in our behavior,
causality as a central component. The book is including at the moral level. Consequently, in
References 925

this vein, a systems view of behavior allows for Armour, C., Tsai, J., Durham, T. A., Charak, R., Biehn,
T. L., Elhai, J. D., et al. (2015). Dimensional structure
the bootstrapping of self-related factors into the
of DSM-5 posttraumatic stress symptoms: Support for
gene/biology × environment/social factors that a hybrid anhedonia and externalizing behaviors model.
influence behavioral expression. Journal of Psychiatric Research, 61, 106–113.
Even if there are powerful models in behav- Ashley-Koch, A. E., Garrett, M. E., Gibson, J., Liu, Y.,
Dennis, M. F., Kimbrel, N. A., Veterans Affairs Mid-
ioral causality, such as the biopsychosocial one,
Atlantic Mental Illness Research, Education, and
it is important to note that causal modeling in Clinical Center Workgroup, Beckham, J. C., & Hauser,
psychology should be more about the individual M. A. (2015). Genome-wide association study of post-
than the general population to which models in traumatic stress disorder in a cohort of Iraq-
Afghanistan era veterans. Journal of Affective
psychology might be typically aimed. Behavior
Disorders, 184, 225–234.
can be described from both a normative and an Baillargeon, R., Scott, R. M., & Bian, L. (2016).
individualized perspective. However, normative Psychological reasoning in infancy. Annual Review of
data are averaged over individuals, and the types Psychology, 67, 159–186.
Bak, P. (1996). How nature works: The science of self-
of modeling being considered, e.g., systems the-
organized criticality. New York: Springer-Verlag.
ory, gives primacy to the structure of individual Barrouillet, P. (2015). Theories of cognitive development:
behavior and its function. From Piaget to today. Developmental Review, 38, 1–12.
The study of causality needs to become central Baumeister, R. F., & Monroe, A. E. (2014). Recent
research on free will: Conceptualizations, beliefs, and
in psychology, both in its own right and for its
processes. Advances in Experimental Social
application to better ensuring optimal develop- Psychology, 50, 1–52.
ment, resolving psychopathology, and improving Baumeister, R. F., Vohs, K. D., & Oettingen, G. (2016).
the human condition, in general. This book has Pragmatic prospection: How and why people think
about the future. Review of General Psychology. http://
tried to propel its study into the vanguard of the
dx.doi.org/10.1037/gpr0000060
field of psychology and related disciplines. It can Belsky, J., Bakermans-Kranenburg, M. J., & van IJzendoorn,
become the coalescing, integrating, unifying axis M. H. (2007). For better and for worse: Differential sus-
in this area, but it is a topic that is evolving con- ceptibility to environmental influences. Current
Directions in Psychological Science, 16, 300–304.
stantly. This epilogue (and the book) concludes that
Berk, L. E. (2013). Child development (9th ed.). Boston,
the study of behavioral causality and the process of MA: Pearson.
unifying psychology are reciprocal dynamic proj- Berk, L. E., & Meyers, A. B. (2016). Infants, children,
ects to which the present book is dedicated. and adolescents (8th ed.). Old Tappan, NJ: Pearson
Education.
Bjorklund, D. F. (2015). Developing adaptations.
Developmental Review, 38, 13–35.
References Blake, D., Weathers, F., Nagy, L., Kaloupek, D., Gusman,
F., Charney, D. S., et al. (1995). Development of a
Achenbach, T. M. (1991). The child behavior check- clinician-administered PTSD scale. Journal of
list/4–18. Burlington, VT: University of Vermont. Traumatic Stress, 8, 75–90.
Achenbach, T. M., & Rescorla, L. A. (2001). Youth self- Borsboom, D., & Cramer, A. O. J. (2013). Network analy-
report for ages 11–18. Burlington, VT: ASEBA. sis: An integrative approach to the structure of psycho-
Alvarez, A., & Booth, A. E. (2016). Exploring individual pathology. Annual Review of Clinical Psychology, 9,
differences in preschoolers’ causal stance. 91–121.
Developmental Psychology, 42, 411–422. Bringmann, L. F., Vissers, N., Wichers, M., Geschwind,
American Psychiatric Association. (1994). Diagnostic N., Kuppens, P., Peeters, F., et al. (2013). A network
and statistical manual of mental disorders (4th ed.). approach to psychopathology: New insights into clini-
Washington, DC: Author. cal longitudinal data. PLoS One, 8, e60188.
American Psychiatric Association. (2013). Diagnostic Calkins, S. D. (2015). Handbook of infant biopsychoso-
and statistical manual of mental disorders (5th ed.). cial development. New York: Guilford Press.
Washington, DC: Author. Carey, S., Zaitchik, D., & Bascandziev, I. (2015). Theories
American Psychiatric Association. (2000). Diagnostic of development: In dialog with Jean Piaget.
and statistical manual of mental disorders (4th ed., Developmental Review, 38, 36–54.
text rev.). Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Case, R. (1998). The development of conceptual struc-
Association. tures. In W. Damon, D. Kuhn, & R. S. Siegler (Eds.),
926 37 Epilogue

Handbook of child psychology: Vol. 2. Cognition, Ekinici, B. (2014). The relationship among Sternberg’s
perception & language (5th ed., pp. 745–800). triarchic abilities, Gardner’s multiple intelligences,
New York: Wiley. and academic achievement. Social Behavior and
Case, R., Okamoto, Y., Henderson, B., & McKeough, A. Personality, 42, 625–634.
(1993). Individual variability and consistency in cog- Elhai, J. D., Naifeh, J. A., Zucker, I. S., Gold, S. N.,
nitive development: New evidence for the existence of Deitsch, S. E., & Frueh, B. C. (2004). Discriminating
central conceptual structures. In R. Case & malingered from genuine civilian posttraumatic stress
W. Edelstein (Eds.), Contributions to human develop- disorder: A validation of three MMPI-2 Infrequency
ment (The new structuralism in cognitive develop- scales (F, Fp, and Fptsd). Assessment, 11, 139–144.
ment: Theory and research on individual pathways, Ellis, G. F. R., Nobel, D., & O’Connor, T. (2012). Top-
Vol. 23, pp. 71–100). New York: Karger. down causation: An integrating theme within and
Caspi, A., McClay, J., Moffitt, T., Mill, J., Martin, J., across the sciences. Interface Focus, 2, 1–3.
Craig, I. W., et al. (2002). Role of genotype in the Feldman, G., Chandrashekar, S. P., & Wong, K. F. E.
cycle of violence in maltreated children. Science, 297, (2016). The freedom to excel: Belief in free will pre-
851–854. dicts better academic performance. Personality and
Caspi, A., Sugden, K., Moffitt, T. E., Taylor, A., Craig, Individual Differences, 90, 377–383.
I. W., Harrington, H., et al. (2003). Influence of life Feldman, R., Vengrober, A., & Ebstein, R. P. (2014).
stress on depression: Moderation by a polymorphism Affiliation buffers stress: Cumulative genetic risk in
in the 5-HTTgene. Science, 301, 386–389. oxytocin-vasopressin genes combines with early care-
Chandler, D. (2015). A world without causation: Big data giving to predict PTSD in war-exposed young chil-
and the coming of age posthumanism. Millennium: dren. Transcultural Psychiatry, 4, e370.
Journal of International Studies, 43, 833–851. Fischer, K. W. (1980). A theory of cognitive development:
Chen, J., & Gardner, H. (2011). Assessment of intellectual The control and construction of hierarchies of skills.
profiles: A perspective from multiple intelligence the- Psychological Review, 87, 477–531.
ory. In D. Flanagan & C. Graham (Eds.), Contemporary Frewen, P. A., Schmittmann, V. D., Bringmann, L. F., &
intellectual assessment (3rd ed., pp. 145–155). Borsboom, D. (2013). Perceived causal relations
New York: Guilford Press. between anxiety, posttraumatic stress and depression:
Chilcoat, H. D., & Anthony, J. C. (1996). Impact of parent Extension to moderation, mediation, and network
monitoring on initiation of drug use through late child- analysis. European Journal of Psychotraumatology, 4,
hood. Journal of American Academy of Child & 1–14.
Adolescent Psychiatry, 35, 91–100. Friston, K. (2010). The free-energy principle: A unified
Christensen, W., & Michael, J. (2016). From two systems brain theory? Nature Reviews: Neuroscience, 11,
to a multi-systems architecture for mindreading. New 127–138.
Ideas in Psychology, 40, 48–64. Friston, K., Levin, M., Sengupta, B., & Pezzulo, G.
Dalege, J., Borsboom, D., van Harreveld, F., van den (2015). Knowing one’s place: A free-energy approach
Berg, H., & Conner, M. (2016). Toward a formalized to pattern regulation. Journal of Royal Society
account of attitudes: The causal attitude network Interface, 12, 1–12.
(CAN) model. Psychological Review, 123, 2–22. Frueh, B. C., Elhai, J. D., Grubaugh, A. L., Monnier, J.,
Daskalakis, N. P., De Kloet, E. R., Yehuda, R., Malaspina, Kashdan, T. B., Sauvageot, J. A., et al. (2005).
D., & Kranz, T. M. (2015). Early life stress effects on Documented combat exposure of US veterans seeking
glucocorticoid-BDNF interplay in the hippocampus. treatment for combat-related post-traumatic stress dis-
Frontiers in Molecular Neuroscience, 8. doi:10.3389/ order. British Journal of Psychiatry, 186, 467–472.
inmol.2015.00068 Gagne, J. R., & Saudino, K. J. (2016). The development of
Demazeux, S. (2015). The ideal of scientific progress and inhibitory control in early childhood: A twin study from
the DSM. In S. Demazeux & P. Singy (Eds.), The 2–3 years. Developmental Psychology, 52, 391–399.
DSM-5 in perspective: Philosophical reflections on Gardner, H. (1983). Frames of mind: The theory of multi-
the psychiatric babel (pp. 3–24). Dordrecht, ple intelligences. New York: Basic Books.
Netherlands: Springer Science + Business Media. Gardner, H. (1993). Multiple intelligences: The theory in
Demazeux, S., & Singy, P. (2015). The DSM-5 in perspec- practice. New York: Basic Books.
tive: Philosophical reflections on the psychiatric Goenjian, A. K., Noble, E. P., Steinberg, A. M., Walling,
babel. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer Science + D. P., Stepanyan, S. T., Dandekar, S., et al. (2015).
Business Media. Association of COMT and TPH-2 genes with DSM-5
Demetriou, A., Spanoudis, G., & Mouyi, A. (2010). A based PTSD symptoms. Journal of Affective Disorders,
three-level model of the developing mind: Functional 172, 472–478.
and neuronal substantiation and educational implica- Goldin-Meadow, S. (2015). From action to abstraction:
tions. In M. Ferrari & L. Vuletic (Eds.), The develop- Gesture as a mechanism of change. Developmental
mental relations between mind, brain and education Review, 38, 167–184.
(pp. 9–48). New York: Springer Science + Business Gordon, I., & Feldman, R. (2015). A biopsychosocial per-
Media. spective on synchrony and the development of human
References 927

parental care. In S. D. Calkins (Ed.), Handbook of childhood. Developmental Science. doi:10.1111/


infant biopsychosocial development (pp. 283–312). desc.12378.
New York: Guilford Press. Kotabe, H. P., & Hofmann, W. (2015). On integrating the
Grizenko, N., Fortier, M.-È., Gaudreau-Simard, M., components of self-control. Perspectives on
Jolicoeur, C., & Joober, R. (2015). The effect of Psychological Science, 10, 618–638.
maternal stress during pregnancy on IQ and ADHD Larrabee, G. J., Millis, S. R., & Meyers, J. E. (2009). 40
symptomatology. Journal of the Canadian Academy of plus or minus 10, a new magical number: Reply to
Child and Adolescent Psychiatry, 24, 92–99. Russell. The Clinical Neuropsychologist, 23,
Grossmann, T. (2015). The development of social brain 841–849.
functions in infancy. Psychology Bulletin, 141, Lee, J. J., & McGue, M. (2016). Why behavioral genetics
1266–1287. matters: Comment on Plomin et al. (2016).
Hanson, J. L., Knodt, A. R., Brigidi, B. D., & Hariri, A. R. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 11, 29–30.
(2015). Lower structural integrity of the uncinate fas- Leerkes, E. M., & Parade, S. H. (2015). A psychobiologi-
ciculus is associated with a history of child maltreat- cal perspective on emotional development within the
ment and future psychological vulnerability to stress. family context. In S. D. Calkins (Ed.), Handbook of
Development and Psychopathology, 27, 1611–1619. infant biopsychosocial development (pp. 206–231).
Harré, R. (2016). The discourse frame. In R. Harré & New York: Guilford Press.
F. M. Maghaddam (Eds.), Questioning causality: Legare, C. H., & Nielsen, M. (2015). Imitation and inno-
Scientific explorations of cause and consequence vation: The dual engines of cultural learning. Trends in
across social contexts (pp. 3–20). Santa Barbara, CA: Cognitive Sciences, 19, 688–699.
ABC-CLIO, LLC. Lester, B. M., Conradt, E., & Marsit, C. (2016).
Harré, R., & Maghaddam, F. M. (2016). Questioning cau- Introduction to the special section on epigenetics.
sality: Scientific explorations of cause and conse- Child Development, 87, 29–37.
quence across social contexts. Santa Barbara, CA: Lewis, M. D. (2005). Bridging emotion theory and neuro-
ABC-CLIO, LLC. biology through dynamic systems modeling.
Heyes, C. (2015). When does social learning become cul- Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 28, 169–245.
tural learning? Developmental Science. doi:10.1111/ Li, Y., Sulik, M. J., Eisenberg, N., Spinrad, T. L., Lemery-
desc.12350. Chalfant, K., Stover, D. A., et al. (2016). Predicting
Hostinar, C. E., Mroczek, D. K., Lachman, M. E., Seeman, childhood effortful control from interactions between
T. E., & Miller, G. E. (2015). Addictive contributions early parental quality and children’s dopamine trans-
of childhood adversity and recent stressors to inflam- porter gene haplotypes. Development and
mation at midlife: Findings from the MIDUS study. Psychopathology, 28, 199–212.
Developmental Psychology, 11, 1630–1644. Libertus, K., Joh, A. S., & Needham, A. W. (2015). Motor
Jedd, K., Hunt, R. H., Cicchetti, D., Hunt, E., Cowell, training at 3 months affects object exploration 12 months
R. A., Rogosch, F. A., et al. (2015). Long-term conse- later. Developmental Science. doi:10.1111/desc.12370.
quences of childhood maltreatment: Altered amygdala Liu, P., Wang, L., Cao, C., Wang, R., Zhang, J., Zhang, B.,
functional connectivity. Development and et al. (2014). The underlying dimensions of DSM-5
Psychopathology, 27, 1577–1589. posttraumatic stress disorder symptoms in an epige-
Kauffman, S. (1993). The origins of order: Self- miological sample of Chinese earthquake survivors.
organization and selection in evolution. New York: Journal of Anxiety Disorders, 28, 345–351.
Oxford University Press. Lourenço, O. M. (2016). Developmental stages, Piagetian
Keating, D. P. (2016). Transformative role of epigenetics stages in particular: A critical review. New Ideas in
in child development research: Commentary on the Psychology, 40, 123–137.
special section. Child Development, 87, 135–142. Malone, J. C., Liu, S. R., Vaillant, G. E., Rentz, D. M., &
Kirk, S. A., Cohen, D., & Gomory, T. (2015). DSM-5: Waldinger, R. J. (2016). Midlife Eriksonian psychoso-
The delayed demise of descriptive diagnosis. In cial development: Setting the stage for late-life cogni-
S. Demazeux & P. Singy (Eds.), The DSM-5 in per- tive and emotional health. Developmental Psychology,
spective: Philosophical reflections on the psychiatric 52, 496–508.
babel (pp. 63–81). Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer Marshall, T. R., Bergmann, T. O., & Jensen, O. (2015).
Science + Business Media. Frontoparietal structural connectivity mediates the
Konecky, B., Meyer, E. C., Kimbrel, N. A., & Morissette, top-down control of neuronal synchronization associ-
S. B. (2015). The structure of DSM-5 posttraumatic ated with selective attention. PLoS Biology, 13,
stress disorder symptoms in war veterans. Anxiety, Stress, e1002272.
& Coping. doi:10.1080/10615806.2015.1081178 Martinez-Torteya, C., Bogat, G. A., Levendosky, A. A., &
Kopala-Sibley, D. C., Dougherty, L. R., Dyson, M. W., von Eye, A. (2016). The influence of prenatal intimate
Laptook, R. S., Olino, T. M., Bufferd, S. J., et al. partner violence exposure on hypothalamic-pituitary-
(2015). Early childhood cortisol reactivity moderates adrenal axis reactivity and childhood internalizing and
the effects of parent–child relationship quality on the externalizing symptoms. Development and
development of children’s temperament in early Psychopathology, 28, 55–72.
928 37 Epilogue

Mascolo, M. F., & Fischer, K. W. (2007). The codevelop- of the issues. In W. F. Overton & P. C. M. Molenaar
ment of self and sociomoral emotions during the tod- (Eds.), Handbook of child psychology and develop-
dler years. In C. A. Brownell & C. B. Kopp (Eds.), mental science. Vol. 1: Theory and method (7th ed.,
Socioemotional development in the toddler years: pp. 49–62). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.
Transitions and transformation (pp. 66–99). Parade, S. H., Ridout, K. K., Seifer, R., Armstrong, D. A.,
New York: Guilford Press. Marsit, C. J., McWilliams, M. A., et al. (2016).
Mascolo, M. F., & Fischer, K. W. (2015). Dynamic devel- Methylation of the glucocorticoid receptor gene pro-
opment of thinking, feeling, and acting. In W. F. moter in preschoolers: Links with internalizing behav-
Overton & P. C. M. Molenaar (Eds.), Handbook of ior problems. Child Development, 87, 86–97.
child psychology and developmental science. Vol. 1: Peckins, M. K., Susman, E. J., Negriff, S., Noll, J., &
Theory and method (7th ed., pp. 240–317). Hoboken, Trickett, P. K. (2015). Cortisol profiles: A test for
NJ: Wiley. adaptive calibration of the stress response system in
Mayer, J., Roberts, R., & Barsade, S. (2008). Human abil- maltreated and nonmaltreated youth. Development
ities: Emotional intelligence. Annual Review of and Psychopathology, 27, 1461–1470.
Psychology, 59, 507–536. Peterson, M. B., & Aarøe, L. (2015). Birth weight and
Mayer, J., Salovey, P., & Caruso, D. (2002). Mayer-Salovey- social trust in adulthood: Evidence for early calibra-
Caruso emotional intelligence test (Version 2.0). User’s tion of social cognition. Psychological Science, 26,
manual. Toronto, CA: Multi-Health Systems. 1681–1692.
McKeough, A., & Griffiths, S. (2010). Adolescent narra- Phillips, A. C., Carroll, D., & Der, G. (2015). Negative life
tive thought: Developmental and neurological evi- events and symptoms of depression and anxiety:
dence in support of central social structures. In Stress causation and/ or stress generation. Anxiety,
M. Ferrari & L. Vuletic (Eds.), Developmental rela- Stress, & Coping, 28, 357–371.
tions among mind, brain and education (pp. 213–230). Piaget, J. (1970). Structuralism. (C. Maschler, Trans.).
New York: Springer Science + Business Media. New York: Basic Books (Original work published in 1968).
McNally, R. J., Robinaugh, D. J., Wu, G. W. Y., Wang, L., Plomin, R., DeFries, J. C., Knopik, V. S., & Neiderhiser,
Deserno, M. K., & Borsboom, D. (2015). Mental dis- J. M. (2016). Top 10 replicated findings from behav-
orders as causal systems: A network approach to post- ioral genetics. Perspectives on Psychological Science,
traumatic stress disorder. Clinical Psychological 11, 3–23.
Science, 3, 836–849. Poland, J. (2015). DSM-5 and research concerning mental
Meaney, M. (2010). Epigenetics and the biological defini- illness. In S. Demazeux & P. Singy (Eds.), The
tion of gene x environment interactions. Child DSM-5 in perspective: Philosophical reflections on
Development, 81, 49–71. the psychiatric babel (pp. 25–42). Dordrecht,
Miller, M. W., Wolf, E. J., & Keane, T. M. (2014). Netherlands: Springer Science + Business Media.
Posttraumatic stress disorder in DSM-5: New criteria Räikkönen, K., Pesonen, A.-K., O’Reilly, J. R., Tuovinen,
and controversies. Clinical Psychology: Science and S., Lahti, M., Kajantie, E., et al. (2015). Maternal
Practice, 21, 208–220. depressive symptoms during pregnancy, placental
Montirosso, R., Provenzi, L., Fumagalli, M., Sirgiovanni, expression of genes regulating glucocorticoid and
I., Giorda, R., Pozzoli, U., et al. (2016). Serotonin serotonin function and infant regulatory behaviors.
transporter gene (SLC6A4) methylation associates Psychological Medicine, 45, 3217–3226.
with NICU stay and 3-month-old temperament in pre- Rakison, D. H., Smith, G. H., & Ali, A. (2016). Who is the
term infants. Child Development, 87, 38–48. dynamic duo? How infants learn about the identity of
Naumova, O. Y., Hein, S., Suderman, M., Barbot, B., Lee, objects in a causal chain. Developmental Psychology,
M., Raefski, A., et al. (2016). Epigenetic patterns 52, 355–363.
modulate the connection between developmental Rietveld, C. A., Medland, S. F., Derringer, J., Yang, J.,
dynamics of parenting and offspring psychosocial Esko, T., Martin, N. W., et al. (2013). GWAS of
adjustment. Child Development, 87, 98–110. 126,559 individuals identifies genetic variants associ-
Operskalski, J. T., Paul, E. J., Colom, R., Barbey, A. K., & ated with educational attainment. Science, 340,
Grafman, J. (2015). Lesion mapping the four-factor 1467–1471.
structure of emotional intelligence. Frontiers in Human Rochat, P. (2015). Layers of awareness in development.
Neuroscience, 9, 649. doi:10.3389/fnhum.2015.00649. Developmental Review, 38, 122–145.
Orquin, J. L., & Kurzban, R. (2015). A meta-analysis of Rubinov, M., Sporns, O., Thivierge, J. P., & Breakspear,
blood glucose effects on human decision making. M. (2011). Neurobiologically realistic determinants of
Psychological Bulletin. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/ self-organized criticality in networks of spiking neu-
bul0000035 rons. PLOS Computational Biology, 7, e1002038.
Overton, W. F. (2015). Processes, relations, and relational- Russell, B. (1918). Mysticism and logic. London: Allen &
developmental-systems. In W. F. Overton & P. C. Unwin.
M. Molenaar (Eds.), Handbook of child psychology Scarpa, A. (2015). Physiological arousal and its dysregu-
and developmental science. Vol. 1: Theory and method lation in child maladjustment. Current Directions in
(7th ed., pp. 63–157). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley. Psychological Science, 24, 345–351.
Overton, W. F., & Molenaar, P. C. M. (2015). Concepts, Smearman, E. L., Almli, L. M., Conneely, K. N., Brody,
theory, and method in developmental science: A view G. H., Sales, J. M., Bradley, B., et al. (2016). Oxytocin
References 929

receptor genetic and epigenetic variations: Association Tung, I., & Lee, S. S. (2016). Latent trajectories of adoles-
with child abuse and psychiatric symptoms. Child cent antisocial behavior: Serotonin transporter linked
Development, 87, 122–134. polymorphic region (5-HTTLPR) genotype influences
Sporns, O., & Betzel, R. F. (2016). Modular brain net- sensitivity to perceived parental support. Developmental
works. Annual Review of Psychology, 67, 613–640. Psychopathology. doi:10.1017/S0954579416000031.
Sternberg, R. J. (1985). Beyond IQ: A triarchic theory of Turkheimer, E. (2016). Weak genetic explanation 20 years
human intelligence. New York: Cambridge University later: Reply to Plomin et al. (2016). Perspectives on
Press. Psychological Science, 11, 24–28.
Sternberg, R. J. (2015). Multiple intelligences in the new Tyrka, A. R., Ridout, K. K., Parade, S. H., Paquette, A.,
age of thinking. In S. Goldstein, D. Princiotta, & J. A. Marsit, C. J., & Seifer, R. (2015). Childhood maltreat-
Naglier (Eds.), Handbook of intelligence: Evolutionary ment and methylation of FK506 binding protein 5
theory, historical perspective, and current concepts gene (FKBP5). Development and Psychopathology,
(pp. 229–241). New York: Springer Science Business 27, 1637–1645.
+ Business Media. Vaillant, G. E., & Milofsky, E. (1980). Natural history of
Stroud, L. R., Papandonatos, G. D., Salisbury, A. L., male psychological health: IX. Empirical evidence for
Phipps, M. G., Huestis, M. A., Niaura, R., et al. Erikson’s model of the life cycle. The American
(2016). Epigenetic regulation of placental NR3C1: Journal of Psychiatry, 137, 1348–1359.
Mechanism underlying prenatal programming of Wang, L., Zhang, L., Armour, C., Cao, C., Qing, Y.,
infant neurobehavior by maternal smoking. Child Zhang, J., et al. (2015). Assessing the underlying
Development, 87, 49–60. dimensionality of DSM-5 PTSD symptoms in Chinese
Suhr, J. A. (2015). Psychological assessment: A problem- adolescents surviving the 2008 Wenchuan earthquake.
solving approach. New York: Guilford Press. Journal of Anxiety Disorders, 21, 90–97.
Sylvester, C. M., Barch, D. M., Harms, M. P., Belden, Wechsler, D. (2003). Wechsler intelligence scale for chil-
A. C., Oakberg, T. J., Gold, A. L., et al. (2016). Early dren (4th ed.). San Antonio, TX: Psychological
childhood behavioral inhibition predicts cortical Corporation.
thickness in adulthood. Journal of American Academy Witherington, D. C. (2015). Dynamic systems in develop-
of Child & Adolescent Psychiatry, 55, 122–129. mental science. In W. F. Overton & P. C. M. Molenaar
Tearne, J. E., Allen, K. L., Herbison, C. E., Lawrence, (Eds.), Handbook of child psychology and develop-
D., Whitehouse, A. J. O., Sawyer, M. G., et al. mental science. Vol. 1: Theory and method (7th ed.,
(2015). The association between prenatal environ- pp. 158–239). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.
ment and children’s mental health trajectories from 2 World Health Organization. (2017). International classifi-
to 14 years. European Child Adolescent Psychiatry, cation of disease, 11th Revision.
24, 1015–1024. Young, G. (2016). PTSD in court. International Journal
Thelen, E., & Smith, L. B. (2006). Dynamic systems theo- of Law and Psychiatry, 38.
ries. In R. M. Lerner (Ed.), Handbook of child psychol- Young, G. (2011). Development and causality: Neo-
ogy. Vol. 1: Theoretical models and human development Piagetian perspectives. New York: Springer Science +
(6th ed., pp. 258–312). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley. Business Media.
Thibodeau, E. L., Cicchetti, D., & Rogosch, F. A. (2015). Young, G. (2012). A unitary Neo-Piagetian/Neo-Eriksonian
Child maltreatment, impulsivity, and antisocial behav- model of development: Fundamental assumptions and
ior in African American children: Moderation effects meta-issues. New Ideas in Psychology, 30, 241–249.
from a cumulative dopaminergic gene index. Young, G. (2015a). Causality in psychiatry: A hybrid
Development and Psychopathology, 27, 1621–1636. symptom network construct model. Frontiers in
Trucco, E. M., Villafuerte, S., Heitzeg, M. M., Burmeister, Psychiatry, 6, 164. doi:10.3389/psyt.2015.00164.
M., & Zucker, R. A. (2016). Susceptibility effects of Young, G. (2015b). Dimensions and dissociation in PTSD
GABA receptor subunit alpha-2 (GABRA2) variants in the DSM-5: Towards eight core symptoms.
and parental monitoring on externalizing behavior tra- Psychological Injury and Law, 8, 219–232.
jectories: Risk and protection conveyed by the minor Young, G. (2015c). Malingering in forensic disability-
allele. Development and Psychopathology, 28, 15–26. related assessments: Prevalence 15 +/− 15%.
Tsai, J., Harpaz-Rotem, I., Armour, C., Southwick, S. M., Psychological Injury and Law, 8, 188–199.
Krystal, J. H., & Pietrzak, R. H. (2015). Dimensional Zelazany, K., & Simms, L. J. (2015). Confirmatory factor
structure of DSM-5 posttraumatic stress disorder analysis of DSM-5 posttraumatic stress disorder
symptoms: Results from the National Health and symptoms in psychiatric samples differing in Criterion
Resilience in Veterans Study. Journal of Clinical A status. Journal of Anxiety Disorders, 34, 15–23.
Psychiatry, 76, 546–553. Zelazo, P. D. (2015). Executive function: Reflection, itera-
Tsou, J. Y. (2015). DSM-5 and psychiatry’s second revolu- tive reprocessing, complexity, and the developing
tion: Descriptive vs. theoretical approaches to psychi- brain. Developmental Review, 38, 55–68.
atric classification. In S. Demazeux & P. Singy (Eds.), Zhang, Y., Liu, F., Chen, H., Li, M., Duan, X., Xie, B.,
The DSM-5 in perspective: Philosophical reflections et al. (2015). Intranetwork and internetwork functional
on the psychiatric babel (pp. 43–62). Dordrecht, connectivity alterations in post-traumatic stress disor-
Netherlands: Springer Science + Business Media. der. Journal of Affective Disorders, 187, 114–121.
Index

A Allostasis, 333, 338


Abstract, 770, 771, 780–782 Allostasis overload, 95
Abstract causal, 868 Allostatic load model (ALM), 305, 317
Acausalism, 29 Allostatic overload (AL), 333, 334, 337
ACC. See Anterior cingulate cortex (ACC) α-amino-3-hydroxy-5-methyl-4-isoxazolepropionic acid
Acceleration, 779 (AMPA), 166
Acceptance and commitment therapy (ACT), 529 Alpha, noradrenergic (noradrenergic α), 39
Acetylation, 203, 204 Alpha 2c noradrenergic receptor polymorphism
Acid phosphatase 5, tartrate resistant (APC5), 547 (α2cDel1322-325), 39
Action stage, 807–810 Alternate splicing, 205
Action variable, 165 Alternative explanation exclusion, 133
Activation/inhibition coordination, 19 Altruism, 838
Activation of gratification, 483 Altruistic motivation, 838
Active rGE, 261 Ambiguity/probability of psychological phenomena, 700
Activities of daily living (ADLs), 612 American Psychiatric Association (APA), 565, 580
Actus reus, 664 Amygdala, 39
Acute stress disorder (ASD), 574 Amygdala-cingulate neurocircuitry, 557
Acute threat (fear), 592 Analogy, 130, 135
Adaptable elements, 109 Analysis of variance (ANOVA), 232
Adaptation (Darwinian), 721 Aneuploidy, 204, 205
Adaptive calibration model (ACM), 305, 317 Angular gyrus (AG), 158
Adenine (A), 207 Animistic thought, 525
Adenylate cyclase-activating polypeptide 1 (pituitary) Annexin A2 (ANXA2), 547
(ADCYAP1), 547 Antecedent behavior consequence (ABC) model, 514
Adenylate cyclase-activating polypeptide 1 (pituitary) Anterior cingulate, 39
receptor type 1 (ADCYAP1R1), 547 Anterior cingulate cortex (ACC), 158, 159
Adeterminism, 75 Anterior insula (AI), 158, 159
Adeterministic, 71, 75 Anterior midcingulate cortex (aMCC), 79
Adjacency matrix, 154 Anti-free will, 457
Adjustment disorder, 574 Anti-litigation distress, 660
Adrenocorticotropin hormone (ACTH), 545 Antisocial behavior, 25, 33, 34
Advanced rational, 798 Anxiety disorders, 573, 574
Adversarial divide, 656, 659, 660 Anxious distress specifier, 573
Affect sharing device (AFS), 367 Apparent causation model, 453
Affiliative/initiative, 845–848 Apparent mental causation, 29
Affordances, 700, 702, 708, 714, 715 Appraisal processes, 423
Agency, 49, 50, 64 Approach/withdrawal, 722
Agent-based modeling, 106, 109 Approach-withdrawal emotion model, 182
Agent-neutral morality, 364 Appropriation, 786
Agents, 27, 29, 31, 35 Arcuate fasciculus (AF), 179, 180, 185, 187, 194
Agoraphobia, 573 Area MT+, 79
Alcohol use disorder (AUD), 142 Arginine vasopressin receptor 1A gene (AVPR1A),
Alerting network, 208 210, 217
Alleles, 202, 203, 207, 208, 211, 217, 219 Argonaute (Ago) protein, 204
(allo)pregnanolone (ALLO), 39 Arousal/regulatory systems, 578

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 931


G. Young, Unifying Causality and Psychology, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-24094-7
932 Index

Artificial neural networks (ANNs), 213 Behavioral causation, 3


Associative vs. rule-based dual process mode, 487, 488 Behavioral community model, 726, 728
Assortivity, 154 Behavioral domain theory (BDT), 31, 122, 123
Astrocytes, 32 Behavioral investment theory, 10
Asymptotic model of free will, 82 Behavioral lateralities, 33
ATPase, class V, type 10A (ATP10A), 547 Behavioral rating inventory of executive function
Attachment theory, 53 (BRIEF), 184
Attention(al), 78, 79, 82, 97, 101, 161, 184–187, 190 Behavioral risk factors, 340
bias, 97 Behavioral synchrony, 896
control, 365, 375 Behavior genetics, 892, 893
inhibition, 422 Behavior inhibition systems (BIS), 193
process, 423, 434, 435 Being-becoming-world, 6, 7
Attention deficit hyperactivity disorder (ADHD), 203, Belt of auxiliary hypotheses, 858
210, 214, 573 Betweenness centrality, 153
Attractors, 17, 31, 54, 67, 82, 93, 94, 101, 104, 107, 162, Bifurcation point, 433
438, 466, 704 Big Five personality traits, 493
configuration, 749, 750 Big history, 10, 12
dynamics, 112, 166 Big Psychology, 12
networks, 166 Bilateral dorsal anterior insula, 79
neural networks, 112 Bilateral frontal eye fields, 79
reconfiguration, 750 Bilateral frontocentral motor system, 102
states, 112 Bilateral superior temporal sulcus, 79
Auditory system (AS), 156 Biobehavioral-community model, 728
Australopithecus afarensis, 775, 778, 779 Biobehavioral synchrony, 36, 37
Authoritarian parenting style, 375 Biocultural co-construction, 285
Authority/respect, 838, 839, 845 Bioecological G x E environment, 232
Autism spectrum conditions (ASC), 210 Biointelligence, 34
Autism spectrum disorder (ASD), 194, 573, 575, 576 Biological embedding, 547
Autobiographical self, 376 Biological gradient, 130
Automatically-located pain, 619 Biological markers, 577, 579
Automaticity, 461, 462, 465 Biological sensitivity to context theory (BSCT), 306, 310
Autonomic nervous system (ANS), 320, 321 Biological synchrony, 896
Autonomous, 485, 486, 489 Biomarker, 122, 140–143
Autonomy vs. doubt acts, 770 Biopersonalsocial model, 73
Average causal mediation effect (ACME), 31, 132 Biopsychosocial causality, 60, 61
Axonal guidance, 632 Biopsychosocial causation, 41
Biopsychosocial complex, 56
Biopsychosocial ecological system, 285
B Biopsychosocial etiology, 726
Backward yoking, 782 Biopsychosocial forensic model of coping, 681, 682
Basal forebrain, 362 Biopsychosocial inputs, 97
Basal ganglia, 79 Biopsychosocial model, 4, 11, 12, 15, 20
Basic behavioral community model, 728 Biopsychosocial outputs, 97
Basic rational, 798 Biopsychosocial practice, 94
Bayesian analysis (BA), 127 Biopsychosocial processes, 97
Bayesian brain hypothesis, 164 Biopsychosocial systems theory, 95
Bayesian brain model, 164 Biosocial constructionist, 428
Bayesian information criterion (BIC), 604 Bipolar disorders, 573, 575, 576
Bayesian learning model, 387–391 Biopsychosociocultural, 663–666
Bayesian model, 32 Blank slate, 356
Bayesian networks, 65 Blicket, 388, 404
Bayesian probability network model, 105 Blood glucose depletion, 478
Bayesian surprise, 164 Blood-oxygen-level dependent functional magnetic
Bayes-optimal, 163, 164 resonance imaging (BOLD-fMRI), 160
Baye’s theorem (BT), 32, 128 Body-centric processes, 98
BDNF-tyrosine kinase B (TrkB), 542 Body-directed attention, 78, 79
Behavioral activation system (BAS), 193, 194 Body-self model, 835
Behavioral causality, 5, 6, 8, 11, 12, 15, 17–20, 892, Boolean networks, 107
896, 925 Borderline personality disorder (BPD), 603, 605
Index 933

Bottom-up model, 11, 16, 17, 19 Causal formats, 924


Bottom-up processes, 54 Causal graph modeling, 5, 13
Bottom-up theory, 74 Causal hypothesis, 47
Box-and-arrow schematic diagrams, 73 Causal identification, 126
Brain-behavior processes, 45 Causal inferences, 47
Brain–body–environment-body-brain system, 103 Causalism, 29
Brain–body–environment coupling, 429 Causality, 3–20, 23–35, 37, 39, 41–68, 71–87, 93–114,
Brain–body–environment landscape, 31 121–143, 151, 162, 166, 169–172, 177, 190, 201,
Brainbow, 466 206, 216, 220, 235, 244, 255, 261–263, 269, 270,
Brain causation, 667 278, 283, 297, 298, 321, 345, 356, 364, 377, 387,
Brain-derived neurotrophic factor (BDNF), 34–36, 39 391–395, 400–402, 404–408, 410, 420, 429, 431,
Brain neurocircuitry network, 537 436, 440, 456, 465, 466, 471, 477, 491–493,
Brief psychotic disorder, 575 502–506, 517, 537, 567–569, 582, 584, 585, 593,
Broad ethics, 741 596, 607, 619, 620, 626, 639–632, 635, 637, 639,
Broad intraactive ethics, 741 646, 653–669, 673–695, 703, 712–713, 715,
But-for test, 48, 58 719–728, 730, 733–741, 743–749, 751, 755, 757,
Butterfly effect, 94 760, 762, 764, 765, 769, 771, 773–777, 782,
786–791, 794, 797, 807–809, 818, 819, 825–829,
857, 863–869, 871–887, 889–892, 896, 897, 900,
C 901, 905–912, 915, 917, 922, 924, 925
Cacti, 32 Causality assessment, 658
Calcium channel, voltage-dependent, beta 2 subunit Causality engine, 28, 29, 502–506
(CACNB2), 215 Causality-informative behavior, 37
Calcium channel, voltage-dependent, L type, alpha 1C Causality scholarship, 76
subunit (CACNA1C), 215 Causality systematization/systematizing causality,
Campbell’s causal model (CCM), 124, 125 724–727, 730
cAMP responsive element binding protein 1 (CREB1), 204 Causalization, 734, 735, 740
Candidate genes (cG), 33, 39 Causal knowledge, 64, 667
Candidate gene x environment interaction (cG x E), 228, Causal landscape, 29
229, 235, 236, 241–243, 246, 248 Causal learning/mapping, 45, 57
Cannabinoid receptor, type 1 gene (CNR1), 210 Causal manipulation, 126
Cannabinoid type 1 receptor (CB1R), 39 Causal maps, 65
Caregiving vs. careless giving acts, 770 Causal matrix, 47
Cartesian, 27 Causal mechanisms, 64
Catalytic, 663 Causal modeling, 889, 925
Catalytic vs. midlife crisis act, 770 Causal modeling framework, 66
Catatonic schizophrenia subtype, 573 Causal model mapping, 394
Catecholamine reuptake, 480 Causal networks, 66
Catechol-O-methyltransferase (COMT), 34, 36, 39 Causal order parameters, 751
Categorical approach, 570 Causal particles, 723, 727, 734, 735
Categorical/nonormal variables, 132 Causal perception, 400, 403
Category reliability, 582 Causal pies, 126
Cathartic vs. abandonment acts, 770 Causal potency, 656
Causal Bayes nets, 388 Causal process, 47, 49, 61
Causal bias, 408 Causal reasoning process, 47, 408
Causal circular emergence, 9 Causal relatedness, 66
Causal cognition, 390, 404, 408, 410 Causal relations, 65–67
Causal complexification/complexity, 297 Causal requirements, 656
Causal contributions, 656 Causal risk factors, 568, 569
Causal control parameters, 753, 754 Causal self, 3, 5, 6
Causal determination, 24 Causal signatures, 569
Causal discourses, 924 Causal streams, 29
Causal ecological expanses (fields), 724 Causal structures, 65, 66
Causal efficacy, 451 of mechanisms, 84
Causal embodiment, 94, 106 Causal system (CS) approach, 631, 632
Causal epidemiological model, 125 Causal test, 662
Causal essence, 630 Causal theory of measurement (CTM), 31, 123
Causal explanation, 126 Causal tree, 220
Causal flow, 32, 158 Causal weirdness, 727, 733, 734
934 Index

Causation, 3, 12–14, 18 Cognitive developmental model, 387–391, 397–399, 401,


determination, 662 402, 406
Cause in fact, 653, 657, 661 Cognitive empathy, 787
Causicles, 41 Cognitive flexibility, 421, 424
Central conceptual structures, 890, 903–904, 911, 912, Cognitive (mis)perception, 42
915, 916 Cognitive niche construction, 284
Central executive network (CEN), 32 Cognitive risk factors, 340
Centrality, 155, 156, 162 Cognitive schema modeling, 410
Centralization, 153 Cognitive social affectivity, 876
Centration, 525 Cognitive systems, 578
Cerebrospinal fluid (CSF), 639 Cognitive theory, 537
Change process, 807, 808, 810, 812, 817, 818, 824, 828, Cognomen, 438
829 Coherence, 130
Chaos of change, 17 connectivity, 724
Chaos theory, 743, 749 theory, 630
Chaotic attractor, 749 Cold causality, 29
Chemokine (C-X-C motif) ligand 1 (CXCL1), 547 Collective autocatalytic sets, 31, 107
Chemosignals, 102 Collective intelligence
Child Behavior Checklist (CBCL), 239, 242 causal, 868
Childhood bipolar disorder, 576 stage, 365, 380
Chi-square, 128, 136 Collective intentionality, 36
Cholinergic receptor nicotinic alpha 4 gene (CHRNA4), Collective morality, 36
209 Collector variables, 750–754
Chromosome, 207, 215 Common disease-common variant (CD-CV) hypothesis,
Chronic pain, 26, 40, 41 217, 218
Chronic pain complications disorder, 40 Common disease-genome epigenome (CD-GE), 218
Cingulate cortex, 157 Common disease-rare variant (CD-RV) hypothesis, 218
Cingulo-opercular network, 79 Common sense, 81
Circle of acquaintanceship, 823 Communication disorders, 573
Circular causal emergence, 725, 726, 737, 738 Communicative memories, 97
Circular causality, 9, 16, 905 Comorbidities, 593, 596, 605
Civil, 653, 655, 657, 662, 663, 669 Compatibilism, 29, 30
Civil case, 664 Compensation neurosis, 658, 659
Classical conditioning, 537 Competence self, 6
Classicalism, 665 Complex adaptive systems (CAS), 31
Clinical iatrogenesis, 675 Complex causal behavioral system, 34
Clinical utility, 574, 577, 584 Complexity
Clique, 153 pyramids, 31
Closeness centrality, 153 theory, 54
Clustering, 153, 155, 171 Complex network theory, 113
Coappropriation, 786 Complex PTSD (CPTSD), 602
Coconstructivism, 866 Comprehensive structural equation model, 132
Codes for the cholinergic muscarinic 2 receptor Conceived transcriptional response to adversity (CTRA),
(CHRM2), 51 294
Codons, 207 Concentration networks, 139
Co-education, 785, 786 Concept cells, 32
Coefficient, 155 Conceptualization, 72, 78, 79, 87
Co-evolution, 109 Concurrent, 663
Coexistential causal intraactionism, 26, 41 Conditional adaptation, 308, 310, 317
Coexistential causal intraactive model, 11 Conditional GC, 138
Co-existential epistemology, 75 Conditional necessity, 80
Coexistential intraactive causality, 719 Cone of causation, 656
Co-existentialism, 30 Confidence intervals, 128
Co-existential model, 4 Configural frequency analysis, 137
for epistemology, 72 Confined memories, 97
Co-existential philosophical model, 43 Confirmatory bias, 660
Cognition-emotion-body, 786, 787 Confirmatory factor analysis (CFA), 140, 142
Cognitive appraisals, 537 Confounder bias, 131, 132
Cognitive behavior therapy (CBT), 514, 529 Connectional families, 156
Index 935

Connectional fingerprints, 156 Correlated G x E (rGE), 25, 30, 33


Connectionist model, 73 Corticospinal tract, 179
Connection matrix/matrices, 32, 154 Corticotrophin releasing hormone (CRH), 545
Connectomal fingerprints, 156 Corticotrophin-releasing factor (CRF), 39
Connectome, 30, 32 Corticotropin releasing hormone receptor 1 gene
Connectomics, 32, 156 (CRHR1), 34
Connector hubs, 155, 905 Cortisol awakening response, 639
Conscious abstraction, 849 Cortisol receptor, 36
Conscious awareness, 452, 461, 463 Cost-benefit analysis, 492
Conscious causation, 38 Counterfactual causal models in testing, 31
Conscious control, 50 Counterfactual causation, 123
Conscious empathy, 787 Counterfactual model, 58
Conscious intention, 452, 453, 468 Counterfactual theories in philosophy, 49
Consciously exaggerating, 676 Counterfactual-manipulationist, 84
Consciousness, 45, 47, 49, 50, 58, 64 Covariation, 124, 133
Conscious reasoning, 452, 463 C-reactive protein (CRP), 238
Conscious states, 665 Credibility interval, 129
Conscious vs. contraconscious acts, 770 Criminal negligence, 653
Conservation of resources (COR), 484 Criminal responsibility, 653, 664, 666–668
Conservatism, 375, 376 Criterial causation, 29, 77
Conservatism–liberalism attitude, 850–851 Criticality, 32, 157, 160, 162
Conservatives, 470 Critogenic, 676
Consilience, 12 Cronbach’s alpha, 556
Consistency, 127, 130, 135 Cross-lagged panel modeling (CLPM), 132
Constitutive reductionism, 71, 72, 75 Cross-lateralized manual behavior, 177
Constrained emergence, 724–727, 729 Cross-level mechanisms, 632
Constraining selfishness, 838 Cross-network model, 45, 67
Constructionism, 71, 76, 78 Cry for help, 659, 660
Construction of law, 683, 684 C-type lectin domain family 9, member A (CLEC9A), 547
Constructive neutral evolution, 280 Cultural epigenetics, 269
Constructive other-deception, 518 Cultural evolution, 36
Constructive self-deception, 518 Cultural group selection, 36
Constructivism, 72–73 Cultural iatrogenesis, 675
Constructivist, 3, 8, 13 Cultural learning, 366
Construct validity, 124, 127 Cultural neuroscience, 24, 34, 35
Contemplation stage, 807, 808, 810 Cultural niche construction, 284
Contemporary brain theory, 699 Culture-gene co-evolution theory, 265–267
Contextual emergence, 80 Culture-related evolution, 280
Contextual match, 752 Cusp of change, 157, 162
Contextual orchid-dandelion model, 894 Cyclical attractor, 749, 757
Contextual precision diagnosis, 632, 633 Cyclic path, 154
Contextual synchrony, 896 Cytochrome c oxidase subunit II (COX2), 35
Continuous time modeling (CTM), 132 Cytogenetic, 207
Control Cytosine (C), 207
networks, 160 Cytosine-guanine dinucleotides (CpG), 255, 256, 260, 261
parameters, 31
processes, 57
Conventionalism, 857 D
Convergent cross-mapping (CC-M), 32, 138 Damages, 654, 657, 659, 662
Conversion disorder, 574 Dandelion phenotype, 311
Coordinated secondary schemas, 378 Dark causality, 727, 734
Coordination, 366, 379, 380 Dasein, 6, 7
Copy number polymorphisms, 203 Data driver, 824
Copy number variations (CNV), 34 Daubert trilogy, 683
Core, 158–162 DEAD box polypeptide 60-like (DDX60L), 899
affect generation, 78, 79 Décalage, 901, 911, 912, 916
knowledge model, 370 Deception, 673, 687–694
Corollary epigenesis, 555 Decision theoretic approach, 32
Corpus callosum, 184 Default brain network (DFN), 480, 485
936 Index

Default mode network (DMN), 32 Dimension(al)


Default network, 78, 79 approach, 570, 571, 581
Defendants, 654, 657, 664–666 in causality, 29
Deferred adaptation, 276, 285 of change, 743, 750, 751, 754–758
Degree centrality, 153 of severity, 571
Dehydroepiandrosterone, or its sulfated derivative Direct causation, 654
(DHEA (S)), 39 Direct causes, 125
Delay of gratification, 520 Directed acyclic graphs (DAGs) model, 31
Deliberation thinking modes, 488 Direct reciprocity, 818, 820
Dendritic branching, 555 Disability, 595, 596, 602
Density, 153, 165 epidemic, 691
Deontology vs. consequentialism, 837 Discovery learning, 42
Deoxyribonucleic acid (DNA), 201–204, 206, 207, Disembodied cognition, 99, 100
211–214, 217 Disorganized schizophrenia subtype, 573
demethylation, 256, 259 Disorganized speech, 573
methylation, 34 Dispositionalism, 29, 84–85
Depersonalization, 598, 601 Disruptive mood dysregulation disorder, 573, 575
Depletion of regulatory control hypothesis, 480 Dissimulation, 619, 622
Depressive disorder, 573, 575, 583 Dissociative disorder, 574
Derealization, 598, 601 Dissociative identity disorder, 577
Dereliction, of duty, 654 Distal risk factors, 340
Desperation cry, 673, 693, 694 Distance acts vs. no acts, 770
Destructive other-deception, 518 Distances, 154, 157
Destructive self-deception, 517, 518 Distractor resistance, 193
Determinants, 3 DNA (cytosine-5)-methlytransferase 3 alpha
Determinism, 29 (DNMT3a), 256
Deterministic, 722 DNA (cytosine-5)-methlytransferase 3 beta
complexity, 724 (DNMT3b), 256
mappings variable, 165 DNA binding protein inhibitor (ID-3), 260
Developability, 754–756 DNA methyltransferases (DNMTs), 204
Development(al) DNA methyltransferases-3L (DNMT3L), 547
changes, 113 DNF. See Dynamic neural field (DNF)
homotypy, 231 Domain-general learning, 393
neuroplasticity, 594 Domain-specific learning, 393
niche construction, 283, 284 Domain-specific skills, 744
plasticity, 275, 285, 286, 568 Dopamine, 207–209
psychobiology, 277, 279 Dopamine active transporter 1 gene (DAT1), 34
psychology, 278 Dopamine beta-hydroxylase (DBH), 142
stage yoking, 782 Dopamine receptor D2 (DRD2), 39
Developmental quotient (DQ), 182 Dopamine receptor D4 (DRD4), 34
Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, Dopamine type 1 (DA1), 39
Fifth Edition (DSM-5), 23, 24, 26, 38, 41 Dorsal attentional network (DAN), 79, 156
four-dimensional structure, 557 Dorsal limbic circuits, 357
Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, Dorsal posterior parietal cortex, 79
Fourth Edition, Text Revised (DSM-IV-TR), 40 Dorsolateral prefrontal cortex (DLPFC), 79
Diagnostic inflation, 575, 580 Dorsomedial prefrontal cortex (dMPFC), 210
Diagnostic threat, 677 Double-stranded helix, 207
Dialectical semi-compatibilism, 30 Down-regulation model, 480
Diameter, 153, 154 DRD4 7-repeat allele, 207
Diathesis-stress model, 36 DRD4 7-repeat polymorphism, 321, 322
Differential developability susceptibility, 756 DSM-5 four-dimensional structure, 557
Differential environmental susceptibility model, 309, 321 DSM-IV Global Assessment of Functioning (GAF)
Differential evolvability susceptibility, 756 scale, 551
Differential flexibility, 755, 756 DSM-IV three-dimensional structure, 557
Differential genetic susceptibility model, 259 Dualism/anti-reductionism, 29, 493–495
Differential susceptibility model, 23, 25, 29, 34–36 Dualistic conceptions, 468
Differential system flexibility, 756 Dual model, 424
Differential system versatility, 756 of self-control failure, 424
Diffusion tensor imaging (DTI), 180, 194 Dual process cognitive model, 38
DiGeorge critical region 8 (DGCR8), 204 Dual process model, 359
Index 937

Dual-process theories, 487 Embodied intentionality, 786, 787


Dual representation theories, 487 Embodied mentalization, 786
Dual selection model, 193 Embodied motivation, 103, 104
Dual system theories, 487 Embodied sense of having free will, 28, 29
Duty, 654, 657 Embodiment, 355, 356, 360–364
Dyadic vs. dysdyadic acts, 770 Embodiment modeling, 4, 12, 20
Dynamical evolutionary psychology (DEP), 279 Embryogenesis, 256, 259
Dynamical/network model of developmental change, 752 Emergence, 3, 8, 9, 16, 18, 162
Dynamical systems, 16 Emergent behavior, 109
Dynamic attentional model, 208 Emergent circular causality, 46
Dynamic causal modeling (DCM), 32 Emergent constructionism, 71
Dynamic complexity theory, 126 Emergent constructivist, 71, 73
Dynamic dominance hypothesis, 189 Emergentism, 464
Dynamic neural field (DNF) Emergent phenomena, 286
model, 440, 441 Emergent systems modeling of behavior, 12
theory, 55 Emergent theory of mind, 419
Dysfunction, 568, 578, 580, 581, 584–586 Emotional contagion, 358
Emotional empathy, 787
Emotional intelligence (EI), 424
E Emotional interpretations (EIs), 906
Early adversity, 25, 31, 34, 36 Emotional maturity, 81, 82
Early affective attunement mechanism, 367 Emotional processing theories, 537
Eco-activism, 843 Emotional vs. malemotional acts, 770
Ecological affordances, 104 Emotion-generating process, 423
Ecological generalizations, 137 Emotion regulation, 423
Ecological model of affordances, 700 Empathy, 355–358, 365, 367, 368, 370, 373, 378, 380
Ecological niche, 721 Empirical enactivism, 361
Ecological self, 6 Empiricist, 50
Ecological validity, 38 Emulation, 37, 366, 367
Ecology, 14 Enactive-based self model, 833
Eco-mastery, 843 Enactive mind, 100
Econiches, 164 Endocannabinoid system, 552
Ecopathology, 47 Endocrine stress systems, 545
Ecoresilience, 47 Endophenotypes, 26, 39, 40
Edge, 154, 155, 157, 160, 162, 171, 173 Endophenotypic candidate, 592
of chaos, 279 Enduring effects model, 25, 36, 331–333
Effective connectivity, 154, 164 Energy depletion, 478, 486
Efficiency, 157, 162, 167 Energy dynamics, 29
Efficient cause, 85–86 Energy flow, 63
Effortful control, 893 Energy rate density, 63
Egalitarian parenting style, 375 Enlightened self-interest, 50
Egocentric, 419 Ensuing EF level, 814
Egocentrism, 525 Entanglement, 81
Ego-depletion model, 478, 479, 481, 484, 491 Entorhinal cortex, 79
Ego integrity vs. despair acts, 770 Entropy, 151, 162, 164, 165
Electroencephalography (EEG), 136 Environmental epigenomics, 203
Elemental constructionism, 78 Environmental/mastery/competent self, 6, 43, 868
Elemental constructivism, 29 Epicognitive, 438
Eliminative reductionism, 29, 72 Epidemiology, 13–15
Eliminative reductionistic, 594 Epigenesis, 23, 34–36, 39, 42
Emancipation, 835 Epigenetically silenced genes, 710
Embodied affectivity, 101 Epigenetic effect, 255, 257, 258, 260, 261
Embodied causation, 94, 106 Epigenetic landscapes, 545
Embodied cognition, 98–102, 104–106 Epigenetic modification, 255–257, 270
Embodied dynamical decision state network, 455 Epigenetic programming, 545, 546
Embodied emergence, 28 Epigenetics, 24, 25, 30, 34, 35
Embodied etiology, 106 Epigenome, 202, 255, 258, 259
Embodied free being, 28, 29 Epigenomics, 201, 218
Embodied free will, 28 Epimutations, 277
Embodied free will belief, 28, 29 Epistasis, 220
938 Index

Epistatis (G x G x E), 220, 270 False belief, 37


Epistemological model, 75 False negatives, 580
ERD. See Event-related desynchronization (ERD False positives, 580, 581
Erikson, Erik, 377 Far-from-equilibrium, 9
Error-related negativity (ERN), 478 Fast Fourier Transform (FFT), 480
Essentialist model, 630, 631 Fast life history, 318, 320
Etiological embodiment, 31 Fatal diagnosis, 581
Etiology, 566–569, 571, 577, 578, 580 Fatalistic determinism, 457
Etiopathogenesis, 544 Fear conditioning, 538, 539, 541, 550
Eusociality, 52 Fear extinction learning, 538, 541, 551
Evaluee bias, 660 Fear network model, 537
Event-related desynchronization (ERD), 363 Feedback, 153, 169
Event-related potentials (ERPs), 161 Feedback loop, 520
Evidence-based practice (EBP), 84 Feed forward mechanism, 97
Evocative (reactive) rGE, 255, 261–264 Feigning, 596
Evo-devo, 278, 280, 281 Fetal programming, 25, 36, 269
Evolution, 10–12, 14–16 First-order emergence, 440
Evolutionary causation, 63 First-order theory of mind, 786
Evolutionary developmental biology, 277–279 Fischer’s Neo-Piagetian model, 901–903
Evolutionary developmental psychology, 276–279 Fitness (survival/reproduction), 721
Evolutionary psychology, 35, 276, 277, 279, 305, 366 Five factor model, 375
Evolutionary systems theory, 275, 277–279, 284 Fixed objectivist foundationalism, 858
Evolutionary theory, 275, 278, 284, 320, 335, 709, 793, Fixed-point attractor, 907
863 FKBP5 gene exon 1 promoter region (FKBP51), 548
Evolvability, 34 FK506 binding protein 5, 141
Exacerbating, 653, 663 Flow, 153, 157, 168
Exaggeration, 26 Fluid genome, 429
Excitatory pyramidal cells, 166 Fluid intelligence, 422
Exciting, 663 Flynn effect, 287
Executive attention network, 208 Force dynamics model, 105
Executive control, 422, 424, 425, 481–483 Force dynamics theory, 429, 436
Executive control network (ECN), 78, 79, 156 Forebrain acetylcholine projections, 357
Executive function (EF), 30 Forensic appraisals, 682
Executive network, 78 Forensic disability, 654, 662, 664
Existentialism, 866 Forensic psychology, 669
Exons, 204 Forkhead box P2 gene (FOXP2), 217
Expectation as etiology, 677 Formal cause, 86
Expectation effects, 677 Formal/abstract stage, 380
Experience sampling method (ESM), 142 Formative model, 123
Experimental hypothesis, 127 Formative test validity model, 31
Exploration promotion, 787 Forward yoking, 782, 783
Exportin-5 (Exp5) pathway, 204 Foundational moral motives, 833, 841, 844–850
Extended synthesis, 798 Fractal dimensions (FD), 113
Extended utilitarian zone, 814 Fractalization process, 754
External dynamics, 67 Fractal model, 31, 771
Externalizing learning, 357 Framework theories, 389, 406
External validity, 47 Free action variable, 165
Exteroceptive sensory perception, 79 Freedom in being, 3–8, 11
Exteroceptive sensory regions, 79 Free energy, 700, 709, 745, 883, 887, 907
Exteroreceptive sensory systems, 549 Free energy principle, 32, 104
Extinction, 538, 539, 541, 549, 551, 552 Freeing the brain, 3, 8
Extraversion, 289, 290 Free will, 3, 5, 7, 11, 19, 924
inventory, 493, 495
in psychotherapy, 11
F working models, 529–531
Face validity, 370 Free Will and Determinism Plus Scale (FAD-Plus), 457,
Factitious disorder, 574 459, 470
FAD-Plus. See Free Will and Determinism Plus Scale Frontal eye fields (FEF), 482
(FAD-Plus) Frontal operculum, 79
Fairness/reciprocity, 838, 839, 845–847 Fronto-insular cortex (FIC), 158
Index 939

Frontolimbic circuitry, 896 Genome, 201–203, 206, 213–215, 217, 218, 221
Fronto-parietal network (FPN), 79, 160 Genome-wide association studies (GWAS), 33
Fronto-striato-cerebellar circuits, 210 Genome-wide complex trait analysis (GCTA), 33
Frustrative nonreward, 592 Genomics, 201, 214, 216–218
Functional analytic clinical case diagrams (FACCDs), Germline, 202
32, 134, 135 Germline inheritance, 203
Functional brain networks, 159 Gibbs energy, 165
Functional connectivity, 154, 158, 161 Gibsonian affordances, 103
Functional connectome, 78 Glial cells, 169, 555
Functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI), 136 Glial cell astrocytes, 169, 708
Functional polymorphism, 50 Gliotransmitters, 169
Functional transcranial Doppler ultrasound (FTCD), 187 Global attractor landscape, 167
Fusiform gyrus, 79 Global dynamics, 32, 164
Fuzzy organism, 700, 703 Global efficiency, 155
Fuzzy probabilistics, 726, 730 Global network dynamics, 158, 164
Fuzzy-trace theory, 700 Globus pallidus (GP), 481, 482
Glucocorticoid receptor (GR), 30
Glucocorticoid receptor corchaperone protein 5
G (FKBP5), 39
Gambling disorder, 574 Glutamate, 166
Gamma-aminobutyric acid (GABA), 39 Gnosons, 113
Gamma-aminobutyric acid A receptor, alpha 2 Goal activation, 103
(GABRA2), 142, 323 Goal-alignment model, 36, 368
Gene-based niche construction, 284 Goal-directed coordination, 420
Gene co-opting, 820 Go/no-go task, 188, 192, 193
Gene–culture co-evolution, 36 Good-old-days bias, 677
Gene x culture interaction, 265, 267, 268 Governing, 720
Gene culture interplay, 267, 269 Grandmother cells, 708
G x E x D interaction, 227, 235, 243, 244 Granger causality (GC), 32
Gene × Environment × Epigenetic interactions, 546 Granger modeling, 138
Gene × Environment × Epigenome interactions, 546 Gray zone, 596
Gene x environment exposure interaction, 219 Greedy reductionism, 72
Gene × Environment interaction, 33, 34 Griffith phases (GPs), 160
G x E x P (person) interaction, 255, 270 Growth mixture modeling (GMM), 894
G x E protection, 232 Gross exaggeration, 618, 619, 622
Gene x Experimental Environment interaction (G x Group
Eexp), 324, 325 focus, 837
Gene-gene interaction (G x G), 208 mindedness, 36, 364, 365
G x M (methylation) x E interaction, 258, 259 selection, 36
General causation, 48 Group-for-Individual selection, 819
General intelligence (g), 185 Growth curve models, 131
Generalist gene, 216–217 Guanine (G), 207
Generalizability, 124
Generalized anxiety disorder, 575, 583
Generalized linear mediation models (GLMs), 132 H
General negative affectivity, 878 Habituation, 539
General psychopathology factor (p), 216 Haplotypes, 211
Generative model, 163–165, 720 Hard compatibilism, 80
Generativity, 530, 833, 834, 842, 845, 847–849, 852 Hard determinism, 80, 83
vs. self-absorption acts, 770 Hard developmental systems theory, 275
Generic change mechanism, 17 Hard emergentism, 630
Generic change model, 11, 17 Hard incompatibilism, 83
Genes, 201–204, 206–217, 219, 220 Hard libertarianism, 83
Genes, environment, organism, development, systems Harm/care, 838, 839, 845
(GEODS) model, 41 Harmonious passion, 503
Gene x SES interaction, 264 Heart-rate variability (HRV), 478
Gene silencing, 33, 203, 218 Hebbian learning, 441
Genetic loci, 641 Hemispheric dominance, 177, 194
Genetic risk factors, 340 Hemispheric specialization, 11
Gene transcription, 205 Heritability, 202–204, 211–214, 218
940 Index

Hermeneutic realism, 99 I
Hermeneutical circle, 858 Iatrogenesis, 26, 41
Heschl’s gyrus cortex, 79 Iatrogenetic effects, 675
Heterozygous, 202 Iatrogenic effects, 658
Hidden causes, 32, 164, 165 Iatrogenic process, 675, 677
variable, 165 Iatrogenic psychotherapy, 676
Hidden econiches, 32 Identification vs. problematic identification acts, 770
Hidden parameters variable, 165 Identity vs. identity diffusion acts, 770
Hidden states variable, 165 Illness anxiety disorder, 574, 615
Hierarchical fingerprints, 156 Ignorability-based approach, 31
Hierarchical generative model, 164, 165 Imaging Gene x Environment interactions (IG x E), 228
Hierarchically mechanistic mind model, 278 Imitation, 367
Hierarchical modularity, 904 Immediate (proximal) cause, 133
Hierarchical prediction approach, 701 Impartiality and fairness, 694, 695
Hierarchical predictive processing model, 701 implementation intentions, 521
Hierarchical system modeling, 891 Implicit attitudes, 462
Hierarchization, 380 Imprinted genes, 258
High-degree node connectivity, 157 Inclusive fitness, 52
Higher-order relational cognition, 396, 404, 405 Incompatibilism, 76, 80, 81, 87
Higher-order risks, 569 Independent medical examination (IME), 660
Higher-order system organization, 61, 62, 67 Independent variables (X), 131
Hippocampus, 39 Indeterminism, 74, 77
poles, 362 Indirect causes, 125
Histone acetyltransferases (HATs), 204 Indirect reciprocity, 365
Histone deacetylase gene (HDC), 261 Individual differences, 16
Histone deacetylases (HDACs), 204 Individual fixed effects models, 131
Histone demethylases (HDMs), 204 Individual-for-Group selection, 819, 820
Histone methyltransferases (HMTs), 204 Individualism, 100
Histone modification, 203 Individualizing, 725
Histone proteins, 203, 204 Industry vs. inferiority acts (participatory), 770
Homeodynamic, 212 Infant attachment, 356, 360
Homeostasis, 157 Inference machines, 32
Homeostatic, 212 Inferentialist philosophical theory of causation, 76
Hominid cognitive evolution, 821 Inferior frontal cortex (iFC), 102
Homo Causa, 3, 18 Inferior frontal gyrus (IFG), 179, 185
Homo erectus, 365 Inferior frontal junction, 192
Homo ergaster, 779 Inferior occipitofrontal arcuate, 185
Homo habilis, 778, 779 Inferior parietal lobe (IPL), 79
Homo intraactivus, 740 Inferior parietal sulcus, 79
Homozygous, 202 Inferoparietal lobule, 179
Hot causality, 49, 55 Influence matrix, 10
HPA axis. See Hypothalamic pituitary adrenal (HPA) Information processing model, 42
axis In-group/loyalty, 838, 839
HPT. See Hypothalamic pituitary thyroid (HPT) Inhibition, 417, 420–426, 440–442
Hub, 151, 155, 157–160 of control, 483
Human exceptionalism, 11, 19 Inhibition of return (IOR), 192
Human scholarship, 12 Inhibitory control (IC), 239, 240
Hybrid symptom network construct model, 908–912 Inhibitory interneurons, 166
Hybrid symptom network-psychological construct Inhibitory suppression, 539
model, 911 Initiative vs. guilt acts, 770
Hypercollaboration, 36 Injury factors, 677, 678
Hyper-complex development network, 220 Insanity defense, 653, 662, 665, 666, 668
Hypercortisolism, 678 Insecure attachment, 342, 344
Hyperparameters, 128 Instrumentalism, 630
Hyper-participatory social mutuality, 770 Instrumental self-directed EF level, 813, 814
Hypertransactionalism, 725, 729 Instrumental variable method, 132
Hypochondriasis, 574 Insufficient but necessary components of necessary but
Hypocortisolism, 678 sufficient causes (INUS), 31
Hypothalamic pituitary adrenal (HPA) axis, 30, 35, 36 Insufficient cause, 133
Hypothalamic pituitary thyroid (HPT) axis, 639 Insula, 39
Index 941

Insurance contract law, 656 Intraactive networks, 764


Insurer Examinations (IEs), 679 Intraactive person, 764
Insurogenic, 676 Intraactive Piagetian model, 764
Integrated counterfactual approach (ICA), 31, 126 Intraactive psychotherapy, 764
Integrated cross network (ICN) model, 41 Intraactive self, 764
Integration, 356, 359, 361, 362, 367, 377, 380 Intraactive stage model, 764
Integrative cross-network, 67 Intraactive stimulus-organism-response model, 764
Integrative model of mental disorder, 634 Intraactive systems, 764
Integrative motivational model, 841 Intraactivism, 735–741
Integrative system, 745 Intramodal visual-kinesthetic processes, 786
Intellectual disability, 573, 575 Intraparietal sulcus (IPS), 188
Intellectualism, 100 Intrapersonal connectome, 728
Intelligence quotient (IQ), 184 Intrapsychic, 840, 841
Intention, 38, 58, 82, 101, 104, 111, 363, 364, 372, 373, conflicts, 465
379, 388, 396, 403, 404, 419, 420, 431, 434, Intrinsic brain network, 155
452–454, 463, 467, 470, 481, 486, 518, 521, 622, Intrinsic neural network, 568
665, 673, 682, 687, 689–693, 700, 790, 799, 810, Introjected, 485, 486
816 Introns, 204, 215
Intention(al) Intrusion resistance, 193
fabrication, 622 Intrusion symptoms, 597
inhibition, 481 Intuition thinking modes, 488
Intentionality, 64 Intuitive thought, 525
Intent to treat (ITT), 126 Inverse probability weighting, 132
Interactome, 220 Ionotropic N-methyl-D-aspartate NMDA 1 (GRIN1), 260
Interactomics, 218 Iowa Gambling Task, 193
Inter-affectivity, 101 Irreversibility, 525
Inter-and Intra-level activation–inhibition coordination Isomorphism, 464
cohesion and coherence, 726 Item response theory (IRT) analysis, 587
Interbodily resonance, 101
Interdependence hypothesis, 364
Interdigitational vs. dedigitational acts, 770 J
Interfaced connectome, 729 Joint, 655, 656, 663
Interference control, 421 activity, 372
Intermediate endophenotypes, 156 Jurisogenic, 676, 677
Intermediate phenotype, 592
Intermittent explosive disorder, 575
Internal decisions, 454 K
Internal dynamics, 67 Kin selection, 52
Internalism, 100 Kuhnian model of paradigms in scientific change, 27
Internalizing disorder, 529
Internalizing learning, 357
Internal validity, 47 L
International Classification of Functioning, Disability Lagged dependent variable (LDV) models, 131
and Health (ICF), 586 Latent change scores (LCS), 132
International Statistical Classification of Diseases and Latent class analysis (LCA), 604
Related Health Problems (ICD), 536 Latent composite variables, 170
Interpersonal connectome, 728 Latent construct model, 32, 33, 122
Intersubjectivity, 179 Latent growth curve modeling (LGM), 31, 132
Interventionism, 84 Latent profile analysis, 331
Intimacy vs. isolation acts, 770 Latent variable, 122, 123, 136, 139–141
Intraaction, 743, 763–764 model, 32, 33
Intraactive biopsychosocial model, 764 Lateral inhibitory dynamics, 441
Intraactive body, 764 Lateralization, 11
Intraactive brain, 764 Lateral orbitofrontal cortex, 79
Intraactive causality, 764 Law, 10, 11, 14
Intraactive embodiment, 764 Left frontal asymmetry (LFA), 186
Intraactive Eriksonian model, 764 Left hemisphere specialization, 33, 177–181, 184–186,
Intraactive interactional dynamics, 162 188–191, 193, 195
Intraactive Maslovian model, 764 Left-out variables error method (LOVE), 31, 132
Intraactive mind, 764 Legal causality, 681, 683
942 Index

Legal causation, 662 Manual lateralization, 177–179, 181, 183, 194


Legal insanity claim, 664 Manual specialization, 11, 33
Legal threshold, 662, 666, 667 MAOA × Maltreatment interaction, 33
Leukocyte telomere length (LTL), 296 Maslow’s hierarchy of needs model, 24
Liable cause, 653, 656, 657 Massive modularity hypothesis, 278
Liberalism, 375, 376 Mastery, 841, 843
Liberals, 470 Material cause, 85, 655, 669
Libertarian, 29 Material contribution test of causality, 655
Libertarianism, 83 Maternal programming, 206
Liberty, 838, 840, 845 Maternal synchrony, 182
Life history, 25, 30, 35, 36 Meaning, 523, 524
theory, 36 Means-end combinations, 378
Life preservation, 845, 848 Mechanism, 5, 8, 9, 11, 13, 17, 18
Likelihood ration chaining (LR), 624 Mechanistic property clusters (MPCs), 630, 631
Limbic-frontal neurocircuitry, 549 Medial orbitofrontal cortex, 79
Limbic system, 78 Medial posterior parietal cortex, 455
Limited-resource model, 477–479, 484 Medial prefrontal cortex (mPFC), 39
Litigation, 536 Medial temporal lobe, 79
distress, 655, 658–660 Mediation analyses, 132
Local dynamics, 32 Mediation of causal effect, 126
Local excitatory dynamics, 441 Mediator variables (M), 131
Local network dynamics, 166 Medical causation, 661
Local-specific skills, 744 Medically unexplained symptoms (MUS), 574
Locus coeruleus noradrenergic system (LC-NE), 309, Melanoma antigen (MAGE) family member, 547
310, 538, 550 Mendelian inheritance, 202
Locus of control, 457, 458 Mens rea, 41
Logical connection, 133 Mental activity, 100, 111, 114
Logical reasoning, 421, 460, 466 Mental combinations, 378
Logical thought, 525, 526, 530 Mental disorder, 568–570, 572, 574–581, 584, 585, 588
Log-precisions variable, 165 Mental health medical industrial complex (MHMIC),
Long allele (l), 186 579, 580
Longitudinal mediation analyses, 132 Mentalizing system (MZS), 489, 490
Loveome, 34 Mental mechanisms, 487
Lower-order system organization, 60, 61, 67 Meso-cortico-limbic network, 210
Low-informative, 128 Mesocorticostriatal circuitry, 209
Lysine (K), 204 Mesolimbic dopamine system, 356
Messenger ribonucleic acid (mRNA), 202, 204, 205, 207
Metacognition, 486
M Metacognitive processes, 422
Macro-development, 840, 841 Metacollecting vs. disillusionment acts, 770
Macro mind, 451 Meta-ethical framework, 646
Macroprocesses, 874–876, 880 Metagenome, 35
MAGE-like 2 (MAGEL2), 547 Metamethods, 858, 859
Magnetoencephalo-graphic (MEG), 184, 194 Meta-modeling, 857, 860
Main processes, 593 Meta-stability/quasi-stability, 32
Maintenance stage, 807–809, 811 Metatheory, 85, 86
Major depressive disorder (MDD), 573, 575, 581–583 Methodical self-reliant EF level, 814
Major depressive episodes (MDEs), 241 Methyl-CpG-binding protein 2 (MeCP2), 204
Major neurocognitive disorder, 574, 582 Methylome, 34
Malingered neurocognitive dysfunction (MND), 624 Methylphenidate, 480
Malingered pain-related disability (MPRD), 624 Michottean causal learning, 395
Malingering, 26, 40 Michottian collisions, 57
Maltreatment, 31, 33 Micro-development, 841
Management style in integration, 762 process, 744, 753
Management style of delegation, 761 Microgenetic information processing view, 753
Management style of domination, 761 Micro-indeterminacies, 452
Management style of negation, 761 Micro–macro hypertransactionalism, 724–727
Management style of relegation, 761 Micro mind, 451
Mannosidase, alpha, class 2c, member 1 (MAN2C1), Microprocesses, 874–876, 880
261, 547 Microribonucleic acid (miR), 555
Index 943

MicroRNA (miRNA) processing, 205 Mu suppression, 432


Midbrain periaqueductal gray (PAG), 79 Mutation, 202
Middle cingulated cortex (mCC), 79 Mutual influence mechanisms model, 134
Middle frontal gyrus (MFG), 188, 189 Mutualistic model, 121
Middle/inferior longitudinal fasiculi, 185 Mutualistic test validity model, 31
Mild malingering, 623 Mutual maintenance, 617
Mild neurocognitive disorder, 575 Myelination, 555
Mild traumatic brain injury (mTBI), 26 Mylohyoid muscle (MH), 363
Mind-body reductionism, 98
Mind-brain emergence, 113
Mindfulness, 111 N
Mind perception, 357 Narrative/self-autobiography/identity, 37
Minimal causal model, 32, 131 Nascent intersubjectivity, 786, 787
Minimal nativism, 388 Nativist, 361, 367–369, 380
The Minnesota Multiphasic Personality Inventory-2 enactivists, 361
(MMPI-2), 621 Natural experiments, 130, 131
Minnesota Multiphasic Personality Inventory-2 Natural pedagogy, 37, 284, 396, 397
Restructured Form (MMPI-2-RF), 602, 603 The Natural process, 656
Mirror neurons, 99 Natural selection, 50, 52, 58, 63
Mirror neuron system (MNS), 36 Nature, 3–5, 8, 11, 19
Mirror system, 31 Nature and nurture, 3, 11
Missing heritability problem, 212, 213 Necdin (NDN), 547
Modality, 714 Necessary Breach Analysis (NBA), 657
Model fitting, 128 Necessary cause, 133
Model of case formation, 815 Necessary element for the sufficiency of a sufficient set
Model of moral foundations, 833, 838–839 (NESS), 31
Moderation of causal effect, 126 Negative attributional style, 874
Modern synthesis, 798 Negative feedback, 97
Modularity, 153, 161 Negative log probability, 162, 164
Modulated allostasis, 335 Negative response bias, 660
Module, 153, 155, 161 Negative symptoms, 616, 624
Monism, 57 Negative valence systems, 578
Monoamine oxidase A (MAOA), 34, 36 Negligence in tort, 653
Mono-symptomatic, 615 Negligent infliction of emotional distress (NIED), 654
Moral cognition, 358 Negligent/intentionally tortious act, 654
Moral foundations, 833, 836, 838–839 Neoconstructivism, 71, 73–75
Morality, 355, 364, 367–373 Neo-Eriksonian model, 4, 11, 19
Moral motive, 833, 836–839, 844–850 Neogenetics/Neogenomics, 202–206
model, 833, 846, 847 Neo-Kuhnianism, 30
Moral responsibility, 80 Neo-Kuhnian model of paradigmatic change, 23, 27
Motif fingerprints, 156 Neo-Lamarckian, 202
Motivation, 522–523 Neoliberal, 376
Motor disorder, 573 Neo-Maslovian model, 10
Motor-exploratory competence, 430 Neo-Piagetian model, 4, 11, 19
Movement/vitality rhythms/contours, 101 Neopositivism, 857
Multiallelic/polygenetic, 202, 217 Neorealism, 99
Multicausal biopsychosocial systems, 726 Neoreductioconstructivism, 30
Multicausal systems, 724–727 Neoteny, 779
Multifactorial causality, 568 Nested environmental effect (G x E x E), 270
Multi-gene x multi-environment modeling, 50 Networks, 24, 28–33, 42
Multilevel selection, 818, 820 betweenness, 162
theory, 366 causal system model, 32
Multimodal convergence zones, 102 change, 753
Multiple emotional intelligences, 891, 906, 919–924 connectivity, 152
Multiple intelligence, 53 model, 14, 151–153, 156, 162, 167, 170–172
Multiple socio-affective intelligences, 891, 921 theory, 152
Multiplication, 380 Neural control network, 208
Multitrait-multimethod testing approach, 647 Neural network, 45
Multivariate pattern classification analysis (MVPA), 455 Neural somatotopy, 432
Musculoskeletal disorders, 661 Neurocentrism, 668
944 Index

Neurocognitive disorder (NCD), 40, 566, 574, 582, 583 Obsessive passion, 503
Neurodevelopmental disorder, 573 Occipital lobe, 79
Neuroemergence, 82 Offline embodiment, 99
Neuroendophenotype, 640, 641 Online embodiment, 99
Neuroendophenotypic vulnerability, 549 Ontogenesis, 705–707, 709
Neurogenesis, 552–553 Ontogenetic adaptation, 276
Neurolaw, 664, 666–668 Ontophylogenetic, 724–727, 730
Neuromal network model, 42 Open-ended change, 42
Neurome, 24, 26 Operant conditioning, 537
network complex, 743–748, 764 Operating principles, 487
Neuronal criterial causation, 77 Operative mechanisms, 656
Neuronal loss, 555 Optimization, 163, 164, 167, 700, 705–710, 713
Neuronal methylome, 257 Optimization theory in evolution, 285
Neuronal networks, 11 Orbitofrontal cortex, 358, 359, 362
Neuropeptide hormones, 356 Orbitofrontal region, 39
Neuropeptide Y (NPY), 39 Orchid phenotype, 311
Neuroscience, 14, 18 Orchids/dandelion hypothesis, 185
Neuroticism, 287, 289–292 Order parameters, 31
Neurotransmitter, 159, 169 Organismic integration/valuing, 485
N400 event related potential, 183 Organization/institution, 721
Niche construction, 35 Origins, 3, 12, 13, 19, 20
N-methyl-d-aspartate receptor (NMDA), 166 Oscillatory coupling, 160, 161
Nocebo effect, 677 Oscillatory cycle attractor, 891, 913
Node, 108 Other focus, 837
betweenness, 139 Outcome/dependent variables (Y), 131
closeness, 139 Outcome vs. outcast acts, 770
degree, 139 Overdiagnosis, 578, 580, 581
strength, 139 Overimitation, 37
Noncoding epigenetic modification, 203 Over-inclusive formulation, 615
Nonessentialist model, 631 Oxytocin (OXT), 210
Nonfundamental causality, 113 Oxytocin receptor (OXTR), 34
Nonlinear dynamical systems theory (NLDST), 8, 17, 20
Nonlinear dynamics, 50, 55
Nonlinear neural mechanisms, 451 P
Nonparametric structural equation models (NPSEMs), Pathoconnectomics, 32, 159
124, 128, 130, 131, 134, 136, 138 Pain disorder, 40
Non-participatory reflexive socio-emotions, 770 Paradigmatic meta-modeling, 860
Non-rule-defined learning (NRD), 481 Paradigms, 72, 85–87
Norepinephrine, 207, 208 Paranoid schizophrenia subtype, 573
receptor, 34 Parasympathetic nervous system, 310, 316
Norepinephrine transporter (NET), 34 Paraventricular nucleus (PVN), 553
Nosology, 566, 576, 579, 581 Parental embodied mentalizing, 360
Nuclear DNA, 203 Parietofrontal network, 188
Nuclear receptor subfamily 2, group c, member 1 Partial malingering, 623
(NR2C1), 36 Participatory morality, 848, 849
Nuclear receptor subfamily 3, group C, member 1 Partner choice model, 36, 371
(NR3C1), 35, 39 Passion, 31, 477, 503–506
Nucleotides, 207, 214 Passive perceptual system, 62
Nucleus accumbens, 182 Passive rGE, 261, 262, 264
Null hypothesis significance testing (NHST), 127 Path, 153–155, 158, 165, 172
Nursing vs. rootless acts, 770 Pathoconnectomics, 32, 159
Nurturant-type parenting, 368 Pathological memory, 538
Nurture, 3, 11, 15 Pavlovian memory circuits, 539
Nurturing vs. misnurturing acts, 770 Pearl’s causal model (PCM), 124, 125
Perception, 75, 77, 78
Perception–action mechanism, 36
O Perceptual control theory, 529
Objective liability, 664 Perceptual learning, 57
Observational causal learning/interventionist, 37, 395 Perceptual models, 701
Obsessive–compulsive disorder, 527 Perceptual-motor couplings, 434
Index 945

Performance validity (PVT), 602 Posterior probabilities intervals (PPIs), 128


Peridynamical, 724–727, 729 Post-formal theory of mind, 786
Perilogical, 868 Post-injury factor, 677, 678
Perioperational Postsynaptic excitatory firing potentials, 166
causal, 868 Postsynaptic inhibitory firing potentials, 166
stage, 380 Postsynaptic terminals, 169
Peri-participatory social cognitions, 770 Posttraumatic stress disorder (PTSD), 11, 26, 32, 39–41,
Peripheral nervous system, 72 43
Peri-traumatic emotionality, 601 Potential threat (anxiety), 592
Persistent depressive disorder, 573, 575 Power theory, 76
Persistent post-concussive syndrome (PPCS), 900 Practical model, 630
Personal agency, 477, 484, 503 Pragmatic neuroemergence view, 82
Personal belief, 457, 478–479, 485, 734 Precentral gyrus, 79
Personal belief/motivation model, 478–479, 485 Precipitating cause, 125
Personal bodily resonance, 101 Precision matrices variable, 165
Personality Assessment Inventory (PAI), 621 Precision-weighted prediction errors variable, 165
Personality Inventory for DSM-5 (PID-5), 621 Preconscious automaticity, 461
Personality Psychopathology Five (PSY-5), 621 Precontemplation stage, 810
Personal psychological process, 97 Precuneus, 79
Perspective taking, 521, 525 Prediction error, 700, 701
Pessimistic induction, 630 variable, 165
Phenome, 201, 221 Predisposing, 663, 667
Phenotypic expression, 162 cause, 125
Phenotypic plasticity, 206, 221 Pre-epimutations, 544
Philosophical semi-compatibilism, 83 Pre-executive EF level, 813, 814
Philosophy, 7, 11, 12, 14 Prefrontal cortex (PFC), 142
Phyloontogenetic, 724–727, 730 Prefrontal cortex alpha 2c (PFC α 2c), 39, 552
Physical causation, 37 Pre-injury factors, 677, 678
Physical resource model, 479 Premenstrual dysphoric disorder (PMDD), 581, 622
Physiological attunement, 36 Prenatal programming, 204
Piaget, J., 355 Preoperational/concrete operational stage, 380
Pituitary adenylate cyclase-activating peptide Preparation stage, 807–810
(PACAP), 546 Pre-participatory socio-affects, 770
Plaintiff, 654, 658–660, 662 Prescriptive morality, 837
Planetary activism, 844 Prescriptive moral regulation, 837, 838
Plasticity gene, 51, 313 Prescriptive response, 368, 376
Plausibility, 130, 132, 135 Pre-supplementary motor area (pre-SMA), 425
Pleiotropy, 213, 215, 220, 288 Presynaptic terminal, 169
Pluralist embodied model, 100 Primary auditory cortex, 79
Political ideology, 37 Primary circular reactions, 378
Polygenetic scores, 34 Primary impairments, 585
Polygenicity, 288 Primary miRNA (pri-miRNA), 204
Polymorphism, 202, 207–211, 214, 215, 217 Primary somatosensory cortex, 434
Poly-symptomatic, 615 Priming, 461, 462
Polythetic approach, 570, 578 Principal stratification, 132
Positive-negative emotion model, 178, 186, 714 Probabilism, 75
Positive predictive power (ppp), 624 Probabilistic, 25, 29, 37, 41
Positive sociality, 355 adeterministic, 71
Positive symptoms, 614, 616 causation, 74
Positive therapeutic effect, 676 emergence, 715
Positive valence systems, 578 epigenetic processes, 710
Positivism, 13, 16 fuzzy, 712
Positivistic reality, 71 Probabilisticism, 71, 74
Postcentral gyrus, 79 Probability landscape model, 206
Post-concussive syndrome (PCS), 674 Process causal models in testing, 31
Postconscious (goal-dependent) automaticity, 461 Pro forma, 665
Posterior cingulate cortex (PCC), 79 Pro-free will, 457
Posterior insula, 79 Program-level imitation, 367
Posterior parietal cortex (PPC), 158–160 Programmatic cause, 125
Posterior predictive p values (ppps), 128–129 Programming-reprogramming-disease model, 554
946 Index

Progressive changes in pain, 808–810 Quantum randomness, 453


Prolonged grief disorder, 625 Quantum universe, 74
Propensity score matching models, 131 Quasi experiments, 24, 130
Property dualism, 72 Quasilogical, 868
Proposal density variable, 165
Pro-prioception coupling, 101
Proprioceptive maps, 183 R
Proscriptive morality, 837 Radical causal pluralism, 76
Proscriptive moral regulation, 837 Radical embodied cognition model, 105
Proscriptive response, 368, 376 Radical embodied cognitive neuroscience, 100, 104
Prosocial behavior, 355–357, 365, 368, 370–373, 377, Radical embodied cognitive science, 100
378, 380 Radical enactivism, 31
Prosocial-construal model, 373 Radical novelty, 286
Prospective probability, 702 Random controlled trials (RCTs), 24, 84
Protein kinase type 1 alpha cGMP-dependent Random fluctuations variable, 165
(PRKG1), 899 Random network, 155
Proteomics, 218 Rational constructivism, 387, 391, 397–399, 402
Proto cadherin (PCDH) gene, 547–548 Re-acting change process, 813
Provincial hubs, 155, 904 Reaction norm, 218, 219
Proximal risk factor, 874 Reactivity, 365, 371
Proximate causation, 280 Readiness for change model, 42
Proximate cause, 653, 654, 657, 661 Readiness potential (RP), 452, 459
Pruning, 555 Realism, 630
Psychiatric causation, 568 Real mental causation model, 453, 454
Psychiatry, 10, 14 Real-world social cognition, 702
Psychoanalysis, 349 Receptor-interacting serine-threonine kinase 2 (RIPK2),
Psychodynamic, 570 261
Psycho-ecological model of legal causality, 683 Reciprocal altruism/selection, 819, 820
Psychogenic amnesia, 603, 604 Reciprocal causality, 890, 891, 905, 915, 917, 922
Psychological causality, 23, 43 Reciprocal causation, 349
Psychological completeness, 833, 836, 842, 853 Reciprocal determinism, 133
Psychological completing, 833, 836, 853 Reciprocity, 153
Psychological co-universe/relaverse, 727 Recognition density, 163, 164
Psychological injuries, 26, 41 Re-designing change process, 813
and law, 11 Reductionism, 16
Psychological primitives, 710 Reductionist, 3, 8
Psychological testing theory, 121 Reductionistic, 49, 60, 61
Psychological vulnerabilities, 596 Reflective abstraction, 213
Psychopathology, 47, 58 Reflective model, 123
Psychopharmacology, 568 Reflective self-control, 80
Psychosocial, 571, 578–580 Reflective test validity model, 31
acceleration theory, 308, 312, 318 Reflex exercise, 378
Psychosomatic conditions, 93 Reflexive, 770, 771, 781, 782
Public good, 37 precausal, 868
Pulvinar, 231 stage, 380
Pulvinar-amygdala-superior colliculus pathway, 191 Reframing change process, 813
Purity/sanctity, 838, 840, 845 Re-generating change process, 813
Purposive cause, 125 Regressive changes in pain, 808–811, 828
Regularity causal models in testing, 31
Regularity causation, 123
Q Regularity theory, 123
Qualitative, 722 Regulator of G-protein signaling 2 (RGS2), 39
Quantitative, 722 Relatedness self, 6, 794
Quantum Bayesian Theory (QBism), 734 Relational developmental systems, 85, 86
Quantum freedom, 453 Relational reasoning, 421
Quantum interference, 453 Relationism, 27, 29, 43
Quantum mechanical model, 206 Relative importance networks, 139
Quantum neoepistemology, 30, 75 Reliability, 566, 567, 570, 577, 580–583, 587
Quantum probability model, 37 Re-newal change process, 813
Index 947

Re-organization, 721 Secure attachment, 344, 346


Representational, 368, 378–380 Self, 3, 5–7, 9, 11, 13, 15, 18, 20
emergence, 74 focus, 837
stage, 378 preservation, 847
Representativeness, 124 Self-actualization, 793–796
Repression, 465 Self-affirmation, 522
Re-responsibility, 83 Self-awareness, 463
Research Domain of Criteria (RDoC) project, 26, 40 Self-control, 11, 16, 506, 507
Residual schizophrenia subtype, 573 degradation, 481
Resilience, 25, 30 depletion, 479, 483, 484
Resolution stage, 807–809, 811 deployment, 515
Resource depletion effect, 478 Self-deception, 517
Response biases, 658 Self-definition and relatedness, 794, 871–874, 876, 877
Response facilitation, 367 Self-definitional self, 6
Response inhibition, 422, 424 Self-determination, 485
Response process, 423 Self-determination theory (SDT), 836
Responsible autonomy, 897 Self-determined autonomy, 835
Resting state activity (RSA), 186 Self-directed learning, 812
Restrictive-type parenting, 368 Self-distinction, 834
Re-structuring change process, 813 Self-fulfilling prophecy, 677
Retinoid-related orphan receptor alpha (RORA) gene, 543 Self-gratification, 523
Retrieval suppression, 539 Self-identity, 834
Retrograde amnesia, 231 Self-locomotion, 101
Retroposons, 204 Self-narrative author, 376
Retrospective probability, 702 Self-organization, 31
Retrosplenial area, 79 Self-organizing, 9, 16
Reward anticipation, 357 Self/Other/Environment Actualizing Generativity, 848
Reward processing, 357 Self/Other/Environment Affiliative Initiative, 848, 849
neural circuitry, 209 Self/Other/Environment Disaffiliative Inertia, 849
Rich club, 155, 157, 162 Self/Other/Environment Identity Self-Esteem, 848, 849
Right hemisphere specialization, 177–180, 182, 185, Self/Other/Environment Identity Self-Esteem Difficulty
188–193 or Disturbance, 849
Risk factors, 227, 231, 233, 242 Self/Other/Environment Life Destruction, 848
RNA-induced silencing complex (RISC), 204 Self/Other/Environment Life Preservation, 848
Role vs. role confusion acts, 770 Self/Other/Environment Moral Stagnation in
Roughness matrices variable, 165 Generativity, 849
rs4680 (Val158Met), 323 Self/Other/Environment Safety Lack/Mistrust, 849
Rubin’s causal model (RCM), 124, 125 Self/Other/Environment Safety/Trust, 848, 849
Rule-defined learning (RD), 481 Self-regulation, 16
R. V. McNaughten, 665 Self-regulatory processes, 422
Semi-compatibilism in free will scholarship, 83
Semi-compatibilist, 29
S Semi-compatibilistic psychology model of free will, 83
Safety/trust, 845–848 Semiotic catalyzers, 111
Salience network (SN), 32 Semiotic regulators, 111
Scaffolded holding frame, 787 Sensitivity analysis, 128, 131
Scaffolded learning, 284 Sensorimotor, 356, 363, 377–380, 770, 771, 774,
Scale-free network, 155 780–783
Schema theories, 537 alpha suppression, 434
Schizophrenia, 569, 572, 573, 581, 582 causal, 868
Scientifically informed, 567 cortex, 79
Scientific determinism, 457 intelligence, 819, 820
Scientific realism, 857, 861 intentionality, 433
Secondary circularity, 104 schema, 393, 398, 402
Secondary circular reactions, 378, 379 thinking processes, 9
Secondary gain, 26 Sensorimotor system (SS), 156
Second-order emergence, 440 Sensory signals variable, 163, 165
Second-order theory of mind, 786 Sentiments, 357
Second-person morality, 364 Serotonin, 207, 208, 210
948 Index

Serotonin transporter polymorphism (5-HTTLPR), Somatization-malingering model, 680


34–36, 39 Somatoform disorders, 613
Serotonin 2A receptor (5-HTR2A), 142 S–O–R Brain/Agent/Mind/Person (BAMP) model, 699
Serotonin type 2 receptor (5HT2R), 39 Spatial selection, 818, 820
Set theory, 746 Specific causation, 48
Sexual selection theory, 309 Specificity, 130
Short allele (s), 186 Specific learning disorder, 573
Sibling fixed effects models, 131 Specific phobia, 573
Sigmund Freud, 464–465 Spectral GC, 137
Simple rules, 109 Speech-gesture mismatch, 429, 436
Single nucleotide polymorphisms (SNPs), 203, 211, Spiritual empathy, 787
213–215, 217 Stable systems, 110
Situated learning, 284 Stable unit treatment value assumption (SUTVA), 31
Situational realism, 10 Stages of change model, 808, 810–811
Situation modification process, 423 Standard deviation (SD), 612
Situation selection process, 423 State collector variables, 753
Skeletal muscle system, 549 State space modeling (SSM), 31, 132
Slow life history, 310, 317, 320 State spaces, 157, 164, 166, 172
Small world network, 155 State/system change, 751
Sociability vs. unsociability acts, 770 Statistical conclusion validity, 124
Social actor self, 376 Statistical mediation analysis, 31
Social affiliation, 368, 369 Statistical, probabilistic learning, 394
Social anxiety disorder (social phobia), 573 Statistics, 14
Social baseline model, 479, 485 Stimulus modulation, 705–707
Social bonds(ing), 356, 823 Stimulus-organism-response (S-O-R), 11
Social brain, 897 Stimulus-response (S-R) psychology, 699
Social brain hypothesis, 823 Stimulus responsiveness, 705–707
Social buffering, 25 Stimulus sensing, 705–707
Social cognition, 357, 359, 360, 362, 364 Stochastic network, 206
Social competence, 359, 361 Stochastic system, 722
Social conformity, 457 Stocks, 153
Social connectedness, 355, 370 Strategizing, 722
Social connection, 355, 356 Stressful life events (SLEs), 228, 237, 241
Social construction, 10, 71 Stress amplification model, 336
Social drivers, 42 Stress generation model, 338–340
Social genomics, 24, 35 Stress inoculation model, 336, 546
Social iatrogenesis, 675 Stress-response physiology, 36
Social information processing, 897 Stress response system, 309, 317
Social learning theory, 796, 797 Stress sensitization model, 348
Social normative model, 36 Striatum, 481, 482
Social schemata, 406 Structural brain networks, 152
Social self-working schemata, 772 Structural connectivity, 154
Societal lossness, 265 Structural equivalence, 153
Societal tightness, 265 Structural magnetic resonance imaging (sMRI), 555
Sociocognitive integration of abilities model (SOCIAL), Structural variations (SVs), 203
359 Structured Clinical Interview for DSM-IV Axis II
Socioeconomic status (SES), 31, 36 disorders (SCID-II), 239, 241
Soft determinism, 80, 524 Structured Clinical Interview for DSM-IV-TR (SCID-
Soft developmental systems theory, 275 IV-TR), 140
Soft libertarianism, 83 Structures d’ensemble, 901, 911, 912
Solute carrier family 6 member 2 (SLC6A2), 34 Subgenual anterior cingulated cortex, 79
Solute carrier family 6 member 3 (SLC6A3), 547 Subgenual prefrontal cortex, 373
Solute carrier family 6, member 4 (SLC6A4), 142 Subjective liability, 664
Somatic empathy, 787, 788 Substance abuse, 574, 575
Somatic inheritance, 203 Substance abuse disorder (SUD), 188, 192, 193
Somatic marker, 359 Substance dependence, 575
hypothesis, 36 Substance dualism, 72
Somatic mosaicism, 202, 204 Substantial contribution test of causality, 655
Somatic symptom and related disorders, 613, 615, 617 Substantial nigra pars compacta (SNc), 482
Somatic symptom disorder (SSD), 40, 575 Substantia nigra pars reticulate (SNr), 481, 482
Index 949

Subthalamic nucleus (STN), 482 Temporoparietal junction, 255, 267


Sufficient cause, 125, 126, 133 Tertium quid, 74, 711
Supercooperators, 820 Thalamus, 188
Superior colliculus (SC), 482 Theory building model, 862
Superior frontal cortex, 157 Theory of dual inheritance, 267
Superior frontal gyrus, 192 Theory of mind, 37, 42
Superior longitudinal fasciculus (SLF), 907 Therapeutic systems, 803
Superior parietal cortex, 157 Therapeutic theory, 803
Superior temporal gyrus, 362 Thermodynamic, 10, 12
Superior temporal sulcus (STS), 179, 180 Third-order emergence, 440
Superordinate attractor, 905, 911, 913, 921 Third-order theory of mind, 786
Superordinate complex adaptive, 905, 906 Threat-related attentional bias, 539
Superordinate complex adaptive system, 749 Thymine (T), 207
Superordinate meta-model of relationism, 12 Toll-like receptor 8 (TLR8), 547
Superordinate participatory collective sociality, 770 Top-down model, 11, 16, 17, 19
Superordinate vs. discoordinate acts (qusi-participatory), Top-down processes, 54
770 Topology, 154
Superorganism, 36, 366 Tort, 653–658, 660, 663, 664, 669
Superseding, 663 Tortious conduct, 654
Super sub-disciplines, 10 Trait impulsivity, 593
Supplementary eye fields (SEF), 482 Transactionalism, 725
Supplementary motor cortex, 158 Transcranial magnetic stimulation (TMS), 425
Supra-consciousness, 788 Transcription, 202–204, 207, 212, 217, 218
Suprahyoid muscles (SM), 394, 395 Transcriptome, 203, 218
Supramarginal gyrus, 102 Transdiagnostic model of psychotherapy, 815
Supramodal perception, 36 Transdisciplinarity, 334
Supra-rational, 798 Transgenerational effect, 35
Surprisal, 701 Transition state model, 753
Surprise, 151, 162–167 Transitivity, 153, 161
Sustained threat, 592 Translocated promoter region (TPR), 547
Sympathetic adrenal medullary (SAM) system, 30, 36 Transparallel processing, 113
Sympathetic adrenomedullary system, 141 Traumatic brain injury (TBI), 566, 583
Sympathetic nervous system (SNS), 292–294 Tree of knowledge system, 10
Symptomatology, 584 Triadic axis model of causality, 29
Symptom network approach, 140 Triggering, 663
Symptom network/construct interactive model, 908–912 Tripartite model, 424
Symptom-perception-construct model, 911 Tripartite neuron, 708
Symptom validity tests (SVTs), 658 Triple-vulnerability model of neuroticism, 874
Synapse formation, 555 True and hidden causes variable, 165
Synaptic cleft, 169 Trust vs. mistrust acts, 770
Synaptogenesis, 555 Tryptophan hydroxylase (TPH1), 235, 236
System, 46, 49, 50, 53–56, 60–63, 65–67 Tryptophan hydroxylase 2 (TPH-2) gene, 899
cohesion, 724 Tubulin Polymerization Promoting Protein (TPPP), 260
emergence, 743, 745 Two-factor learning model, 537
Systematization, 380 Type I error, 235
System I understanding of false belief, 401, 402 Type/System I, 463
Systems for Social Processes, 578 Type/System II, 463
Systems modeling, 45
Systems structure/Causal loop, 153
System state (SS), 631 U
Systems theory, 4, 9 Ultimate, 654, 658, 663
System II understanding of false belief, 402, 408, 410 causation, 280
System/Type III, 490, 491 responsibility, 80
Uncinate fasciculus, 896
Unconsciously exaggerating, 676
T Unconscious somatization processes, 680
Tactical-reciprocal EF level, 814 Unconscious thought theory, 462
Telomere length (TL), 296 Under-diagnosis, 580
Temporal poles, 359, 362, 373 Undifferentiated schizophrenia subtype, 573
Temporal precedence, 133 Unification of psychology, 892
950 Index

Unified brain theory, 907 Volitional freedom, 456


Unified psychology, 5, 9 Voluntariness, 664, 666, 668
Unifying psychology, 3, 5–10 Voluntary action/movement, 452, 454
Unitary model, 438 Voxel-based morphometry (VBM), 634
Universal vs. self-singular acts, 770 Vulnerability, 25
Unpredictability, 457, 465, 466 genes, 51
Unspecified mood disorder, 575
Upstream variable number tandem repeat (u-VNTR), 235
W
Wave models, 73
V Wechsler Adult Intelligence Test (WAIS), 185
Validity, 566, 567, 580–582, 584, 587 WHO’s Disability Assessment Schedule, 571
Val158Met polymorphism, 242, 244 Wide computationalism, 100
Variable number of random repeats (VNTR), 34 Willed intentions, 467
Vectors, 105 Will power, 478–479, 484, 491
Ventral attention network, 79 Wilson’s multilevel selection model, 838
Ventral limbic circuits, 357 Worker’s compensation, 648
Ventral medial prefrontal cortex (vMPFC), 158, 159 Working memory (WM), 188, 193, 420, 421, 423, 424,
Ventral striatum, 357, 362 435–437, 441
Ventral tegmental dopamine, 357 World-becoming-being, 6, 7
Ventromedial prefrontal cortex (vmPFC), 79 World Health Organization (WHO), 571
Versatility, 34, 754–756 World Health Organization Disability Assessment
Veteran’s administration, 648 Schedule 2.0 (WHODAS-2.0), 584, 586
Viscosity, 32, 164
Visual system (VS), 156
Visuospatial attention, 78 Y
Vitality/reverbation energetics model, 915, 918, 922, 924 Yoked networks, 729
Volitional action, 451, 467 Yoking, 9
Volitional control, 468, 470 Young Adult Self-Report (YAR), 186, 187

Вам также может понравиться