Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 2

GUEST EDITORIAL

The Dogma of “The” Scientific Method

T his is the challenge of science—


to shed dogma and get closer to
the truth.
— Rudolph Tanzi & Ann Parson
al, some statistical, some based
on controls, some on similarity
relationships, some on elaborate
thought experiments, and so on.
through synthesizing observa-
tions on biogeography, fossils,
organismal design, population
growth, and limited resources.
Again, we think students should Only subsequently did he recon-
(2000, p. 2)
be encouraged to think about evi- struct it as “one long argument”
It’s altogether too easy to dence and argument broadly. in the Origin of Species (Mayr,
reduce all method in science to a 1991). In their more recent and
Consider just a few historical
simple algorithm. Hypothesize, monumental work on Darwin’s
examples. First, note Watson and
deduce (or predict), test, evaluate, finches, Rosemary and Peter
Crick’s landmark model of DNA.
conclude. It seems like a handy Grant have simply extracted sig-
It was just that: a model. They
formula for authority. “The” nificant patterns from volumi-
drew on data already available.
Scientific Method (expressed in nous data they collected over
They also played with cardboard
this way) haunts the introductions many years (Weiner, 1994; Grant
templates of nucleotide bases
of textbooks, lab report guide- & Grant, 2002). No hypothesis.
(Watson, 1968). Yes, their
lines, and science fair standards. No experiment. No control. If
hypothesis of semi-conservative
Yet we consider it a poor model for such great heroes of biology did
replication was eventually tested
learning about method in science. not use the prescribed Scientific
by Meselson and Stahl—later. But
We endorse instead teaching Method, how can anyone justifi-
even that involved enormous
about the Scientists’ Toolbox. ably portray it as “the” method of
experimental creativity (Holmes,
Science draws on a suite of meth- science?
2001). Consider, too, Mendel’s
ods, not just one. The methods discoveries in inheritance. Scientific papers do indeed
also include model-building, Mendel did not test just seven seem to follow the scientific
analogy, pattern-recognition, traits, cleverly chosen in advance method. But they are reconstructed
induction, blind search and selec- (as the story is often told). accounts of completed work. They
tion, raw data harvesting, com- Rather, he seems to have fol- are composed to fit a standardized
puter simulation, experimental lowed twenty-two traits, hoping publication format. They do not
tinkering, chance and (yes) play, for patterns to emerge. He ulti- describe how research always
among others. The toolbox con- mately abandoned those he occurs in practice (Medawar,
cept remedies two major prob- found confusing (Di Trocchio, 1964; Bazerman, 1988; Knorr-
lems in the conventional view. 1991). Nobelist Thomas Hunt Cetina, 1984).
First, it credits the substantial Morgan, in Mendel’s wake, did The chief problem we see is
work—scientific work—in develop- not discover sex-linkage through that students come to believe that
ing concepts, or hypotheses. any formal hypothesis about the Scientific Method guarantees
Science is creative. Even to pur- inheritance. He was looking for discovery and unambiguous, reli-
sue the popular strategy of falsifi- species-level mutations. When he able conclusions. Uncertainty,
cation, one must first have imagi- first encountered his famous incompleteness, or revision are
native conjectures. We need to white-eyed mutant, he did not excluded. Of course, science is
foster such creative thinking immediately frame a prospective fallible. But how? The Scientific
skills among students. Second, conclusion. Rather, he probed Method does not say. Bauer
the toolbox view supports many and observed, not sure what he (1992) has nicely profiled how
means for finding evidence— had found (Allen, 1978). Or con- the mythic Method misleads. For
some direct, some indirect, some sider Darwin. Darwin arrived at Bauer, scientific ideas develop
experimental, some observation- natural selection, of course, gradually, subjected to successive

EDITORIAL 485
645
filters. There is no unique algorithm The reasoning shouldn’t seem for- References
yielding absolute truth. We believe eign. Students should see that when
that students need to learn how sci- we apply these same methods to Allen, G.E. (1978). Thomas Hunt Morgan:
ence can be limited, how some evi- understanding the natural world, we The Man and His Science. Princeton,
dence can be complex, and how call it science. NJ: Princeton University Press.
some questions can be unresolved. Anand, P. (2002). Decision-making
That, in turn, helps them under- We thus encourage our col-
leagues to teach the suite of skills in when science is ambiguous. Science,
stand how (or when) we should 295, 1839.
trust scientific claims. Such judg- science. ABT is an excellent resource.
ment is especially important as more In just the past two years, articles Bauer, H.H. (1992). Scientific Literacy and
and more public decisions involve have featured such skills as: the Myth of the Scientific Method.
Urbana, IL: University of Illinois
complex and/or ongoing science • framing inquiry questions Press.
(Anand, 2002). (Marbach-Ad & Clawasen,
63/6), Bazerman, C. (1988). Shaping Written
Given that the conventional Knowledge: The Genre and Activity of
Scientific Method does not adequate- • building hypotheses (Hoese the Experimental Article in Science.
ly describe the richness of science, we & Nowicki, 63/3), Madison, WI: University of
marvel at its hold on the school Wisconsin Press.
mindset. Why the entrenched • designing experiments
dogma? At one level, the simplicity (Deutch, 63/4; Temple, Di Trocchio, F. (1991). Mendel’s experi-
may be merely convenient. But the 64/1), and ments: a reinterpretation. Journal of
the History of Biology, 24, 485-519.
dogmas may be deeper. Those who • integrating and assessing
actively defend the Scientific Method data from multiple methods Einstein, A. (1954). Ideas and Opinions.
(recently in ABT: Lawson, September, (Singer, Hagen & Sheehy, New York: Dell.
2000; McPherson, April, 2001) seem 63/7).
concerned with the privilege of sci- Grant, P.R. & Grant, B. R. (2002).
In addition, we advocate historical Unpredictable evolution in a 30-
ence. For them, science is special. It is
year study of Darwin’s finches.
beyond the ordinary. It is exclusive. case studies, which allow students to
Science, 296, 707-711.
The Scientific Method demarcates see biology in action (e.g., Hagen,
Science with a capital ‘S’. Without Allchin & Singer, 1996; reviewed in Hagen, J.B., Allchin, D. & Singer, F.
discipline, it would seem, no claim is ABT, April, 1999). (1996). Doing Biology, Glenview, IL:
any better than any other. Order Harper Collins.
If one must characterize method
seems secured by rule-following and Holmes, F.L. (2001). Meselson, Stahl, and
in science concisely, let it be some-
conformism. Portrayed in this way, of the Replication of DNA: A History of
thing like this:
course, the promise of The Scientific ‘The Most Beautiful Experiment in
Method seems grossly overstated. Yet Scientists follow hunches, clues, Biology’. New Haven, CT: Yale
we wonder how prevalent this per- and questions obtained from observa- University Press.
spective is. tions, earlier claims, reading, etc. They
Knorr-Cetina, K. (1984). The Manufacture
explore how to generate relevant infor-
We agree instead with Albert of Knowledge. Oxford: Pergamon
mation. They consider possible sources Press.
Einstein (even though he was not a
of error. They engage others in inter-
biologist!): “The whole of science is
preting evidence. Results usually lead Mayr, E. (1991). One Long Argument.
nothing more than a refinement of every- Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
to more questions. Ideas are refined.
day thinking” (Einstein, 1954, p. 283). Press.
Some change, some are abandoned.
Accordingly, a conception of scientific
method should grow out of familiar Yes, teach how to pose hypothe- Medawar, P. (1964). Is the scientific
experience. It should complement ses. Yes, teach controlled experi- report fraudulent? Yes: It misrepre-
and extend ordinary discovery ments. As tools. And don’t stop sents scientific thought. Saturday
processes. And it should highlight Review, 47(August 1, 1964), 42-43.
there. Viewing science as con-
how to establish reliable evidence—an strained by one privileged method is Tanzi, R.E. & Parson, A.B. (2000).
aim shared, for example, by journal- greatly impoverished. We do science Decoding Darkness. Cambridge, MA:
ists and judges. A physician diagnos- in many ways. Let’s teach the Perseus.
ing an illness, a mechanic trou- Scientists’ Toolbox.
Watson, J.D. (1968). The Double Helix.
bleshooting a car, a detective tracking
New York: Atheneum.
a crime all use the same methods as Dan Wivagg
scientists, although in different con- Douglas Allchin Weiner, J. (1994). The Beak of the Finch.
texts. Lab work should make sense. allchin@pclink.com New York: Vintage Books.

646 THE AMERICAN BIOLOGY TEACHER, VOLUME 64, NO. 9, NOVEMBER/DECEMBER 2002

Вам также может понравиться