Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 25

The Methodology of Positive Accounting

Charles Christenson

The Accounting Review, Vol. 58, No. 1. (Jan., 1983), pp. 1-22.

Stable URL:
http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0001-4826%28198301%2958%3A1%3C1%3ATMOPA%3E2.0.CO%3B2-Z

The Accounting Review is currently published by American Accounting Association.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at
http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained
prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in
the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at
http://www.jstor.org/journals/aaasoc.html.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.

The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academic
journals and scholarly literature from around the world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers,
and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community take
advantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

http://www.jstor.org
Thu Dec 20 00:11:25 2007
T H E ACCOUNTING REVIEW
Vol. LVIII, NO. 1
January 1983

The Methodology of

Positive Accounting

Charles Christenson
ABSTRACT: Jensen, Watts and Zimmerman (referred to hereafter, following Jensen
[I 9761, as "the Rochester School of Accounting") have charged that most accounting
theories are "unscientific" because they are "normative." They advocate the development
of "positive" theories to explain actual accounting practice. The program of the Rochester
School raises a number of methodological issues that are addressed in this article. First,
it is argued that the Rochester School's criticism of traditional accounting theory is off
the mark because of a failure to distinguish between two different levels of phenomena.
Second, it is argued that the concept of "positive" theory is based on the misconception
(derived from nineteenth-century positivism) that empirical science is concerned solely
with the actual, with "what is." Empirical theories, it is shown, are negative in their
import; they state what is to be taken as empirically impossible. Third, it is shown that
"negative" theories of the sort described in this article are exactly what is needed in
predictive, explanatory, and normative reasoning. Finally, it is argued that the standards
advocated by the Rochester School for the appraisal of their own theories are so weak
that those theories fail to satisfy Popper's [I 9591 proposal for demarking science from
metaphysics.

ERALDING an "emerging Rochester answers to the normative questions they


School of Accounting," Jensen continue to ask . . . " [p. 121.
[I9761 charged that "research in Research supported by the Division of Research,
accounting has been (with one or two Harvard University Graduate School of Business Ad-
notable exceptions) unscientific. . . ministration, out of funds provided by the Associates of
the Harvard Business School. For comments on earlier
[blecause the focus of this research has drafts of this article, I am indebted to Rashad Abdel-
been overwhelmingly normative and defi- khalik, Robert Anthony, W. W. Cooper, Anthony
nitional" [p. 111. In accounting, he said, Hopwood, Robert Jaedicke, Spiro J. Latsis, E. A. Lowe,
Richard Mattessich, Merton Miller, Joseph G. San
"'theory' has come to mean normative Miguel, Edward Stamp, Robert Sterling, Tony Tinker,
proposition. The so-called accounting Richard Vancil, H. Martin Weingartner, and two an-
theory texts are almost entirely devoted onymous reviewers. I have also benefited from the
comments of the participants in the Seminar in Financial
to the examination of questions of a Accounting and Financial Analysis at the Harvard
'what ought to be done' nature" [p. 1I]. Business School; the Workshop in Accounting at the
Jensen called for "[tlhe development of a Sloan School of Management, Massachusetts Institute
of Technology; and the Workshop in Methodology and
positive theory of accounting [which] Accounting of the European Institute for Advanced
will explain why accounting is what it is, Studies in Management.
why accountants do what they do, and Charles Christenson is Royal Little
what effects these phenomena have on Professor of Business Administration,
people and resource utilization" [p. 131. Harvard University.
Without such "positive theory," he said, Manuscript received July 1981.
"neither academics nor professionals will Revision received April 1982.
make significant progress in obtaining Accepted May 1982.
The Accounting Review, January 1983

Subsequently, Jensen's colleagues today are well trained in research meth-


Watts and Zimmerman have carried the ods but hardly at all in methodology.'
banner of Positive Accounting forward Machlup [I9631 distinguishes the two:
in a series of articles which repeat several Methodology, in the sense in which literate
of Jensen's themes. Watts [1977, p. 541, people use the word, is a branch of philosophy
for example, calls the traditional financial or of logic. . . . Semiliterates adopt the word
accounting literature "unscientific" be- when they are concerned neither with philoso-
cause it "concentrates on prescriptions" phy nor with logic, but simply with methods.
and gives "[vlery little attention . . . to Instead of "statistical techniques" they would
say "statistical methodology," and instead
developing a theory. . . to explain why of "research methods" they love to say
financial statements take their current "research methodology."
form." Watts and Zimmerman [1978,
pp. 112-1131 argue that "a positive "The methodology of a science," as
theory of the determination of accounting Blaug [1980, p. 471 says, "is its rationale
standards" is necessary "to determine if for accepting or rejecting its theories or
prescriptions from normative theories . . . hypotheses." Thus, methodology is nor-
are feasible." In a later paper, while mative, and for that reason it would
continuing to distinguish between presumably be called unscientific by
"positive" and "normative" theories, Jensen and watt^.^ Yet, obviously no
they make it clear that they award the science can exist without making method-
honorific "theory" to the normative ological commitments. Hayek [1952, p.
accounting literature only to avoid "se- 371 even asserts that science as a whole is
mantic debate"; they "would prefer to normative : "Its concern is not what men
reserve the term 'theory' for principles think about the world and how they con-
advanced to explain a set of phenomena" sequently behave, but what they ought to
[Watts and Zimmerman, 1979, p. 273 think" [emphasis supplied].
n. 11. Zimmerman [1980, pp. 107-1081 Like other normative judgments,
says that "positive research seeks to methodological ones may be made with
develop a theory that can explain ob- varying degrees of self-consciousness. In
served phenomena." Watts and Zimmer-
man, then, appear to be the principal ' Zimmerman [1980, p. 1201 asserts that the time is
members of the "Rochester School" now propitious for positive research in accounting be-
announced by Jensen. cause accounting researchers are becoming increasingly
well trained in economic theory and research methods.
Each of the two articles coauthored by If Blaug [1980, p. xiii] is to be believed, however, this is
Watts and Zimmerman cited above won no cause for complacency. He says that "the average
the AICPA's award for a Notable Con- modern economist has little use for methodological
inquiries" and that, "to be perfectly frank, economic
tribution to the Accounting Literature in methodology has little place in the training of modern
its year of publication, and an article by economists."
Zimmerman [I9791 seeking to develop a It is not surprising that positivists such as Jensen and
Watts hold methodology in low esteem. As Popper [1959,
"positive" explanation of cost allocation p. 511 observes, it is a characteristically positivist dogma
won the Competitive Manuscript Award to deride methodology as "unscientific" and "meaning-
of the AAA. That these articles are con- less": "The positivist dislikes the idea that there should
be meaningful problems outside the field of 'positive'
sidered "top of the heap" is, I shall argue, empirical science. . . . He dislikes the idea that there
a sad commentary on the standards used should be a genuine theory of knowledge, an epistemol-
in evaluating contemporary accounting ogy or a methodology." This dogma does not enable
positivists to avoid methodological commitments but
research. This is a reflection, I would say, only makes it less likely that they will be self-conscious
of the fact that accounting researchers about the commitments they make.
Christenson

the more established sciences, which have "should" and each question on the
a research tradition of proven fruitfulness "positive" list contains the words "why,"
to follow, awareness of methodological "what," or "how."
issues among what Kuhn [I9701 calls There is a second, more subtle differ-
"normal scientists" may be low. But as ence between the two lists. Every question
Friedman [1953, p. 401 argues, "more on the first list is about the description of
than other scientists, social scientists accounting entities [Kohler, 1975, p. 141.
need to be self-conscious about their Every question on the second list, in
methodology." Samuelson [1962, p. 211 contrast, is about the description and
for once agrees: "Paradoxically, the soft explanation of the behavior of accoun-
sciences that are still akin to an art benefit tants, i.e., those persons responsible in
more from an explicit awareness of the some way for the description of account-
canons of scientific method. . . than do ing entities.
the hard sciences, where doing what Thus, in his attempt to illustrate the
comes naturally will protect even a fool positive-normative distinction, Jensen
from gross methodological error." has managed to confound it with another
In the interests of consciousness- -that between phenomenal domains at
raising among accounting researchers, two different levels. Jensen's confusion is
therefore, I will examine in this article the of exactly the type warned against by
following questions raised by the method- Popper [1972, pp. 176-1771, who points
ology of the Rochester School. What out that the problem of understanding
should be the domain of accounting the behavior of a problem-solver is on a
theory? What, if anything, is a "positive" higher level than the problem which
theory? How can scientific theories be concerns the problem-solver :
used in explanation, prediction, and
The problem of understanding is a metaprob-
prescription? How should scientific lem. . . . Accordingly, the theory designed to
theories be appraised? solve the problem of understanding is a
metatheory. . . . We have to distinguish clearly
between the metaproblems and metatheories
"To have a science of anything," of the historian of science . . . and the prob-
lems and theories of the scientists. . . . It is
according to Caws [1972, p. 721, "is first only too easy to mix these two up . . .
to have recognized a domain and a set of
phenomena in that domain, and second To clarify matters, I propose a three-
to have devised a theory whose inputs way classification of accounting problems
and outputs are [descriptions of] phe- rather than the one-way, positive-norma-
nomena in the domain (the first observa- tive classification suggested by Jensen.
tions, the second predictions) and whose With respect to a given problem, the first
terms may describe the underlying reality question to be asked is whether it is, in
of the d ~ m a i n . " ~ Popper's terms, a problem or a meta-
To illustrate the distinction between problem. To use an accounting example,
"normative" and "positive" research are we concerned with the problem faced
questions, Jensen [1976, pp. 11-12] pre- by General Electric's management in
sents two lists of examples, reproduced deciding what to present in the company's
as Figure 1. The most obvious difference financial statements for 1981? Or are we
between the two lists-as Jensen in-
I have interpolated the two bracketed words into
tended-is that each question on the Caws's statement in anticipation of a point to be devel-
"normative" list contains the word oped later in this article.
The Accounting Review, January 1983
FIGURE 1
EXAMPLES
OF "NORMATIVE" AND "POSITIVE"QUESTIONS
[Jensen, 1976, pp. 11-12]
"Normative" Questions "Positive" Questions

1) How should leases be treated on the 1) There is much discussion in the literature regarding the "needs"
balance sheet? of those using accounting reports. Why is there little or no
2) Should replacement (or liquidation) attention paid to the "needs" of the suppliers of accounting
values be used in the balance sheet reports? What are the supply-side forces, and what impact do
and income statements? they have on accounting practices?
3) How should changing price levels be 2) Why do most firms continue to allocate overhead charges to
accounted for? performance centers?
4) How should changes in foreign ex- 3) Why do firms change accounting techniques?
change rates be accounted for by 4) Why do firms change auditors?
firms with foreign interests? 5) Why has the accounting profession been cursed with a strong
5) How should inventories be valued? authoritative bias-resulting in the establishment of profes-
6) What should be reported in annual sional bodies such as the CAP, APB, and FASB to rule on
financial statements? "generally accepted accounting techniques?"
7) Should interim financial statements 6) How have court regulation and rulings influenced accounting
be audited? practice?
8) How should minority interests in 7) Why do firms continue to use historical cost depreciation for
subsidiaries be treated in consoli- other than tax purposes?
dated statements? 8) Why are public accounting firms organized as partnerships?
9) Why is fund accounting so different from corporate account-
ing?
10) What impact has the CPA certification procedure had on the
practice of accounting and on research in accounting?
11) What have been the effects on the focus of research of account-
ing educational programs which require faculty to expend
substantial effort teaching institutionally oriented material
aimed at the CPA exam?
12) Why does the accounting field place an emphasis on "profes-
sionalism" and "professional ethics?"

concerned with the metaproblem of tion or a proposal. Do we want to know


understanding why management made what method GE uses for inventory
the choices it did? valuation? Or are we instead concerned
For reasons to be stated in Section 11, with what method they should use?
I wish to avoid use of the term "positive." In Section I1 I will show that proposi-
As an alternative to the positive-norma- tions-statements of fact-are of two
tive distinction, therefore, I will use what distinct logical forms: observational and
Popper [1966, vol. ii, p. 3831 has referred theoretical. If the research problem we
to as the dualism of "propositions, which are classifying is to be resolved by a prop-
state facts, and proposals, which propose osition, then a third question must be
policies, including principles or standards asked : Is the required proposition obser-
of policy." Questions on Jensen's first list vational or theoretical?
call for proposals in response; those on Figure 2 shows how this classification
his second list call for propositions. The scheme would apply to various kinds of
second question to be asked in classifying accounting-relatedproblems. In each cell
research problems, then, is whether our of the figure, I have indicated the actors
problem is to be resolved with a proposi- who would be concerned with the ac-
Christenson

Character of Prohlern Resolution

Proposition

Prohlern Level Observational Theoretical Proposal

Primary
(Accounting Entities) Practicing Some accounting Entity managers
accountants theorists

Meta Historians, economists, and sociologists of Accounting


(Accountants, managers, accounting (such as Rochester School) methodologists
and users) (most accounting
"theorists")

counting problems falling in that cell. criticized by the Rochester School are
The first row of the table is concerned concerned with how practicing accoun-
with problems at the primary level, tants ought to describe accounting enti-
about the state or behavior of accounting ties. They are metaproblems whose solu-
entities. The financial statements of an tions are proposals, and therefore they
accounting entity have the character of belong in the rightmost cell of the bottom
observational propositions. Therefore, row. I have said above that financial state-
practicing accountants, who are con- ments of an accounting entity have the
cerned with constructing (or "verifying") character of observational hypotheses. I
these statements on the basis of analyses would therefore call those who are con-
of the entity's actual transactions, belong cerned with the rationale for accepting or
in the first cell of this row. rejecting these descriptions "methodolo-
It has been suggested [FASB, 19781 gists" rather than "theorists."
that an objective of financial reporting The program of the Rochester School
for an entity is to enable the prediction of is concerned with describing, predicting,
its future cash flows. In Section 111, I will and explaining the behavior of accoun-
show that predictions require not only tants and managers, not that of account-
observational propositions, such as finan- ing entities. Therefore it also belongs on
cial statements, but also primary-level the metalevel, but in the leftmost cell. (I
theories. The second cell of the first row have not shown the division of this cell
would be the concern of those who are into "observational" and "theoretical.")
interested in constructing predictive The discipline of the Rochester School
theories of this kind. might be called "history of accounting"
The managers of an accounting entity or "economics of accounting," since it
are concerned with what the transactions uses concepts and methods from both
of the entity (as distinct from their history and economics. I prefer to call it
accounting representation) ought to be. "sociology of accounting," using "soci-
These problems fall in the rightmost cell ology" in the inclusive sense of Pareto
of the first row. [1935, p. 31: "Human society is the
The problems considered in the tradi- subject of many researches. . . . To the
tional "accounting theory" literature synthesis of them all, which aims at
The Accouhting Review, January 1983
studying human society in general, we except in direct quotation from the
may give the name of s~ciology."~ Rochester School, I have generally en-
Having sorted matters out as shown in closed the word "positive" in quotation
Figure 2, I will now make a few observa- marks. In this usage, I am following the
tions. First, the problems addressed by example of Einstein [1944, p. 2811, who
both the traditional accounting literature wrote that "just as on the part of a real
and the program of the Rochester School philosopher, quotation-marks are used
occur at the metalevel. For this reason, I here to introduce an illegitimate concept,
would argue that neither the traditional which the reader is asked to permit for the
literature nor the Rochester School is moment, although the concept is suspect
directly concerned with what should in the eyes of the philosophical police."
properly be called "accounting theory." In this section, I will present the
Such theory belongs to the primary level. grounds the "philosophical police" have
This is consistent with usage in the estab- for suspecting the concept of "'positive'
lished sciences : Chemical theory consists theory." As is appropriate when legiti-
of propositions about the behavior of macy has been questioned, I will begin by
chemical entities (molecules and atoms), discussing ancestry. Then I will show the
not about the behavior of chemist^.^ deficiencies of the concept from a
Second, I agree with the Rochester methodological perspective.
School that a scientific theory should be
useful in predicting and explaining the Ancestry of the Concept
phenomena that occur in its domain. The Rochester School has drawn its
However, it is "positive" theory at the concept of "'positive' theory" from that
primary level that is required to predict guru of the Chicago School of Eco-
the behavior of accounting entities, not nomics, Milton Friedman.6 Zimmerman
theory at the metalevel where the Roches- [1980, p. 1071 cites a well-known essay in
ter School has directed its attention. which Friedman [I9531 argued "for
Moreover, as I have already argued, the distinguishing positive economics sharply
development of good "positive" theory from normative economics" [pp. 6-71. It
at the primary level requires sound was Friedman's judgment that "a con-
"normative" theory-methodology-at Jensen [1976, p. IS] disdains "sociological" explana-
the metalevel. tion as too narrow, advocating instead a model of
"resourceful, evaluative, maximizing man (REMM)."
It is as if Jensen had advised his fellow See also Meckling [1976]. Pareto [I9351 argues, on the
financial economists to cease their "un- other hand, that the standard economic assumption that
scientific" interest in "normative and people act in accordance with their perceived self-interest
is inadequate to explain observed social phenomena and
definitional" questions such as "How he therefore advocates augmenting this assumption with
should market efficiency be defined?', sociological premises. Jensen [1976, p. 141 advises
and to turn their attention instead to accounting researchers to become more familiar with
Pareto's ideas. Perhaps he should follow his own advice!
trying to explain the behavior of other A special problem in the social sciences is that the
financial economists. The latter would be social scientist, as a human being, is also a social entity-
a fascinating investigation, and useful for and every human being is at least an amateur social
some purposes, but it would hardly have scientist. This makes it much more difficult to distinguish
between primary and meta levels, but it does not make it
improved our understanding of financial any less important.
markets. Significantly, both Jensen and Watts earned their
Ph.D.s at the University of Chicago, and, of 17 persons
acknowledged by Watts and Zimmerman [1979, p. 2731,
at least eight (including Jensen) did graduate work at
The reader will have observed that, Chicago and three others have taught there.
Christenson

sensus on 'correct' economic policy de- positive nor normative in Keynes's sense,
pends much less on the progress of neither statements of the actual nor of the
normative economics proper than on the ideal. Rather, they are statements of the
progress of a positive economics yielding possible.
conclusions that are, and deserve to be, The Rochester School's concept of
widely accepted" [p. 61. Friedman does "'positive' theory" is philosophically
not use the term "positive theory," but he suspect, then, because it reflects the
does say that "the ultimate goal of a posi- erroneous belief that a scientific theory
tive science is the development of a constitutes "systematized knowledge
'theory' or 'hypothesis' that yields valid concerning what is." A theory is no such
and meaningful (i.e., not truistic) predic- thing. Moreover, the Keynes-Friedman-
tions about phenomena not yet observed" Rochester concept of "'positive' science"
[p. 71. The echoes of Friedman in the is also philosophically suspect, since, to
program of the Rochester School are the extent that science is theoretical,
clear. science is not concerned solely with "what
Friedman credits his distinction be- is."
tween "positive" and "normative" sci- Both terms-"'positive' science" and
ence to J. N. Keynes, who wrote [1891, "'positive' theoryv-are misleading and
pp. 34-35]:7 ought to be abandoned. There is a per-
[ A ]positiue science may be defined as a body
fectly good substitute for the term "posi-
of systematized knowledge concerning what tive" to refer to sciences that are con-
is; a normative or regulative science as a body cerned with propositions-matters of
of systematized knowledge relating to criteria fact-rather than with proposals-ques-
of what ought to be, and concerned therefore tions of value. It is the term "empirical,"
with the ideal as distinguished from the which I will use henceforth.
actual . . .
Besides, why should anyone want to
The concept of "positive science" was stand next to a dead philosophical
popular throughout the nineteenth cen- movement?
tury. It was associated with a philosophi-
cal school called "positivism," which Product us. Process Views of Science
held that only the methods of the natural Empirical science can be viewed either
sciences provide "positive knowledge" of as a product (a body of systematized
"what is." knowledge, in Keynes's terms) or as a
As a philosophy of science, positivism process (the human activity producing the
is no longer taken seriously. Passmore knowledge). Positivists have emphasized
[1967, p. 561, for example, says that the product view of science, as exempli-
"logical positivism [the last vestige of fied by Keynes's definition and by the
positivism] is dead, or as dead as a philo- logical positivists' preoccupation with
sophical movement ever becomes." the formal structure of empirical propo-
Part of what killed logical positivism sitions. The newer philosophy of science
was the failure of its program to establish
the traditional positivist dogma that the ' From the final clause of this quotation I infer that
Keynes believed that "positive science" is concerned with
propositions of the established sciences "the actual." I shall criticize this notion later in this
such as physics, chemistry, and biology section. Friedman, incidentally, does not quote this
refer only to the actual, i.e., to "what is." clause. Nor does Zimmerman [1980, p. 1071, who appar-
ently did not consult the original source. Perhaps that is
These sciences use theories. Theoretical why he misattributes the quotation to "J. M. Keynes,"
propositions, as I will show, are neither confusing Neville Keynes with his son Maynard.
The Accounting Review, January 1983

emphasizes the process view. An early tivists in considering empirical science,


exponent of this view, Popper, proposed as a body of knowledge, to be a col-
that "empirical science should be char- lection of propositions. He also agrees
acterized by its methods: by our manner with the positivists in accepting "'the
of dealing with scientific systems : by what fundamental thesis of empiricism'-the
we do with them and what we do to thesis that experience alone can decide
them," and not "merely by the formal or upon the truth or falsity of scientific state-
logical structure of its statements" ments.. . " [Popper, 1959, p. 421. On
[Popper, 1959, p. 501. the other hand, Popper also accepts
Popper argues, on the other hand, that Hume's proof [I739 (1888), p. 1391 that
the first step in understanding any process experience can never conclusively estab-
should be an examination of its product lish the truth of any statement." He is
[Popper, 1972, p. 1141. This should be thus led to ask whether it is possible to
the case whether our interest is empirical, save the fundamental thesis by demand-
in which case we start with an actual ing only one-sided decidability; by re-
product and seek to explain it in terms of quiring, that is, that only the falsity of
the process that produced it; or norma- scientific statements be decidable by
tive, in which case we start with an ideal experience.
product and seek to design a process that Popper concludes that one-sided
will produce it.* decidability-falsifiability-is possible,
Since Popper's concern is with method- but only ifscientistsfollow certain method-
ology-the normative theory of science ological norms. What preserves the em-
-he is led to analyze what a body of pirical character of science as a body of
empirical knowledge ideally ought to be, knowledge are these norms, and not the
including its logical s t r ~ c t u r eHe
. ~ starts logical form of its propositions. It is this
from the premise that the aim of science conclusion, of course, that drives Popper
is to explain observed phenomena, al- to the process view of science.
though he observes that a body of From a strictly logical point of view,
knowledge that is explanatory will also a proposition is falsified not by experience
be useful as an instrument for prediction but only by the acceptance of another
and for technological application. So far, proposition with which it is logically
it will be seen, the Rochester School's "
inconsistent. Accordingly, Popper de-
concept of science is consistent with
Popper's, although some differences will 13 As Popper says [1972, p. 1151, "In all sciences, the
appear later. ordinary approach is from the effects [products] to the
I will summarize Popper's concept of causes [processes]."
This has led many of Popper's critics to miss the
an empirical theory in the remainder of point that his ultimate concern is with the process of
this section. Then, in Section 111, I will science rather than with its product, and to assume that
show what we may do with such a theory, he has proposed only some minor improvements to the
logical positivist program, such as replacing its verifica-
by way of explanation, prediction, and tionist criterion of meaning with a falsificationist one.
prescription. Finally, in Section IV, I will For one such critic who eventually saw the light-" it
discuss what we should do to an empirical came to me as a revelationw-see Bar-Hillel [1974, p.
3331.
theory before we accept it, and show that l o Russell [1946, p. 6731, an empiricist himself, some-
these norms are violated by the Rochester what despairingly refers to this as "Hume's destruction
School. of empiricism" and says that its natural sequel has been
"the growth of unreason throughout the nineteenth
Empirical Propositions century and what has passed of the twentieth."
Cf. Einstein [1944, p. 2871, who refers to "the gulf-
Popper agrees with the logical posi- logically unbridgeable-which separates the world of
Christenson

fines a proposition as falsifiable (and falsifiability and observability, is not a


hence potentially belonging to the body matter of strict logic; a proposition once
of empirical knowledge) if and only if corroborated may be falsified by later
there is at least one observational propo- evidence. Thus the acceptance of a
sition (or basic statement, in Popper's proposition into the body of empirical
own terminology) with which it is science is always tentative.
logically inconsistent.
An observational proposition asserts Logical Form of Observational Proposi-
that an observable event is occurring in a tions and Theoretical Propositions
specified individual region of space and As noted above, an observational
time. The requirements that the event be proposition asserts that an observable
"observable" in a "specified individual" event is occurring in a specified individual
region are necessary to insure that obser- region of space and time. The logical form
vational propositions are themselves of an observational proposition is
falsifiable12 [Popper, 1959, Section 281. exemplified by the paradigm :
Whether a proposition is an observa- There is an occurrence of the event
tional proposition is partly a matter of S in the region K.
fact. Whether certain events are observ- (1)
able may depend, for example, on the The region K may also be interpreted as
state of the art of scientific instrumenta- an event. It is, however, a singular event
tion and may thus change over time, since it contains at most one occur-
whereas logical form is immutable. rence.13 The event S, on the other hand,
Falsification must be distinguished has no restriction on the number of
from falsifiability. A proposition is occurrences it might have and so is called
falsified if and only if an observational universal.
proposition is accepted with which it is The joint event AB is defined as the
logically inconsistent. Falsification in- event that includes all those occurrences
volves not only a logical element, the that are occurrences of both the event A
inconsistency of two propositions, but and the event B. Using this concept, we
also a nonlogical element, the decision to can rewrite (1) as :
accept the falsifying observational propo- There is an occurrence of
sition. Logic alone cannot compel one to the event SK. (2)
accept a falsifying observational proposi-
tion. It is the nonlogical element which The event SK contains at most one
enables theories to evade even falsifi- occurrence and is therefore singular.
cation by experience unless methodologi- The two preceding paragraphs may be
cal safeguards are adopted. summarized by saying that the logical
Thus, Popper [1959, p. 541 is led to lay form of an observational proposition is
down a "supreme rule . . . which says that of a singular existential proposition:
that the other rules of scientific procedure
must be designed in such a way that they sensory experiences from the world of concepts and
do not protect any statement in science propositions."
l Z Popper, whose concern is primarily with the physi-
against falsification." An important sub- cal sciences, uses only the method of spacetime coordina-
sidiary rule is that a proposition should tion to individuate occurrences. In the biological and
be accepted into the body of empirical social sciences other methods of individuation may be
knowledge only if it has been corrobor- required; e.g., the numerical tagging of biological
specimens.
ated, meaning that it has survived serious l 3 As stated at note 12, the singularity is necessary to
attempts to refute it. Corroboration, like make an observational sentence falsifiable.
The Accounting Review, January 1983
singular, because it refers to a singular
event; and existential, because it asserts
that an occurrence of that event exists.
The complementary event A is defined
as the event that includes all those occur- Existential Import
Range o f '
rences that are not occurrences of A. As Applicability Positive Negathre
an example of the use of this concept,
consider the proposition: Singular Observational Not
Proposition Falsifiable
There is an occurrence of
the event SK. (3) Strictly Not Empirical
Universal Falsifiable Law
This is a singular existential proposition
and therefore an observational proposi-
tion. Moreover, its acceptance would negative existential ;observational propo-
falsify (2), since SK and SK are logically sitions are positive existential. Second,
incompatible events; if any event is theoretical propositions are strictly uni-
occurring in the region K, it is either S or versal; observational propositions are
S, not both. singular. Observational propositions as-
Next consider the proposition : sert what is. Theoretical propositions
assert what is not, anywhere in spacetime.
There is no occurrence of To have an empirical theory of a phe-
the event S. (4) nomenal domain, then, means to have:
This proposition is neither singular (it (1) A collection of logically possible
refers only to the universal event S) nor events, including some elementary
existential (it denies, rather than asserts, events plus all the self-consistent
the existence of occurrences of a certain compound events that can be con-
kind). Yet it is falsifiable!14 It is falsified structed from the elementary ones
by the acceptance of (2), which asserts by the operations of forming com-
the existence of an occurrence of S in a plements and intersections; and
singular region. Therefore, according to (2) One or more empirical laws, each
Popper's proposal, (4) must be counted of which prohibits at least one
as an empirical proposition-although observable event.
it certainly is not a statement of "what is." Thus, of the class of logically possible
Proposition (4) can be called a law events recognized by a theory, the theory
since, like the laws passed by legislative asserts that only members of a proper
bodies, it prohibits the occurrence of subclass are empirically possible.
certain events.15 It is also the paradigm
of a theoretical proposition. Thus, we
can conclude that the logical form of a l4 It is not effectively verifiable, since all of spacetime
theoretical proposition, or law, is that of a would have to be searched to prove that there is no
strictly universal negative-existential counterexample. Nor is it "confirmable" in the sense of
being rendered more probable by favorable evidence.
propostion. The essence of Hume's anti-inductivist argument is that
As shown in Figure 3, theoretical no amount of favorable evidence to a proposition such
propositions, or laws, are distinguished as (4) can preclude the possibility of a counterexample.
l 5 "Not for nothing do we call the laws of nature
from observational propositions in two 'laws,"' as Popper [1959, p. 411 says. "The more they
ways. First, theoretical propositions are prohibit the more they say."
Christenson

The Universal Conditional Forms of Laws events can be stated in the form of a uni-
Some empirical laws have, besides the versal conditional proposition."
negative existential form already dis- By a kind of optical illusion, the uni-
cussed, two logically-equivalent alternate versal conditional form has misled many
forms. Most methodologists have methodologists into thinking that a law
focused their attention on these alternate such as (7) has positive import and is
forms, or even on only one of them. This "confirmed" by an observation of the
has been a source of a considerable event RS. ("The evidence is consistent
amount of confusion about the relation- with the theory," they would say.)
ship of laws to empirical evidence.16 Hempel [I9461 has pointed out that this
The laws in question are those that view leads to a paradox.18 For, it can be
prohibit the joint occurrence of two or seen that (5) is also logically equivalent
more events. An example might be: to :
There is no occurrence of For all x : If x is an occurrence of the
the event RS. (5) event S then x is an occur-
rence of the event R, (8)
This asserts that the events R and S never
occur in conjunction with each other. The logical form of (8) is called the
From the definition of the comple- contrapositive, but it is obviously just
mentary event, it is obviously equivalent another version of the universal condi-
to assert: tional form.
Here is the paradox: If observation of
All occurrences of the event R are an instance of RS "confirms" (7), then
occurrences of the event S. (6) observation of an instance of RS "con-
To use a familiar example, "All men are firms" (8) and therefore, by virtue of the
mortal" is logically equivalent to "There logical equivalence, it also "confirms"
is no immortal man." (7). To be concrete, the law "All crows
In modern mathematical logic, (6) is are black" is equally confirmed by ob-
further analyzed into : serving a black crow and a nonblack
l 6 For example, Nagel [1963, p. 2151 has suggested
For all x: If x is an occurrence of that Friedman's [1953, p. 141 argument that the "as-
the event R then x is an sumptions" of a theory need not be "realistic" is based
occurrence of the event on the erroneous notion that the antecedent of a universal
S. (7) conditional proposition is an assumption of a theory.
Another example of a confusion, to be discussed
The logical form of (7) is that of a uni- shortly, is Hempel's paradox of confirmation.
l 7 Zimmerman [1980, p. 1081 says, "A positive theory
versal conditional proposition : universal is of the form, 'If A then B', that is capable of being
because of the prefixed phrase "For all refuted." This represents some progress over the state-
x" (called the "universal quantifier" in ment by Watts and Zimmerman [1979, p. 2731: "We
would prefer to reserve the term 'theory' . . . for sets of
logic), and conditional because of the hypotheses which have been confirmed [sic]." Yet
"if. . . then . . . " clause. The sentence Zimmerman commits three technical errors in his short
following the "if," "x is an occurrence of sentence: (1) he omits reference to universal quantifica-
the event R," is called the antecedent of tion over a free variable, (2) he omits the restriction of
the conditional form to those laws which prohibit a
the conditional ; and the sentence follow- joint event, and (3) he calls the conditional "positive"
ing the "then," "x is an occurrence of the when in fact it has only negative import.
l 8 Hempel's "paradox of confirmation" is discussed
event S," is called its consequent. by Ijiri [1975, pp. 165-1671, Since I consider Hempel's
Thus, every empirical law that pro- paradox to be a reductio ad absurdurn of the concept of
hibits the joint occurrence of two or more confirmation, I do not agree with Ijiri's analysis.
The Accounting Review, January 1983

FIGURE 4
HOWSEVERALKINDSOF ~NFORMATIONARE COMBINED IN PREDICTION
(Shaded areas represent events excluded in region K)

(a) Law (b) Initial Conditions (c) Prediction

noncrow-such as a green vase. In fact, predictive, explanatory and normative


almost anything one might observe is reasoning. (Since exactly the same kind
consistent with a law and therefore of theory is used in all three kinds of
"confirms" it ! reasoning, I find it more appropriate to
The paradox arises because the univer- distinguish kinds of reasoning rather
sal conditional forms (7) and (8) make it than kinds of theories.)
appear that a law says something positive, Predictive Reasoning
i.e., that it asserts that something is the
case. It is then natural to think that A prediction is, for present purposes,
positive evidence supports or "confirms" simply one or more observational propo-
the law. The paradox disappears with sitions that refer to as yet unobserved
the recognition that both (7) and (8) occurrences, whether these occurrences
reduce to the canonical form (9,which are in the future or in the past.
does not assert anything positive. The Since a theory states only what is
law "There are no nonblack crows" is empirically possible, not what is actually
refuted by the observation of a nonblack the case, in general no positive prediction
crow, but it is not "confirmed" by any- can be derived from a theory alone. Sup-
thing [Quine, 19741. pose, for example, that we are given a
theory consisting of a single law, "There
is no occurrence of the event RS." From
this law we can deduce "negative" pre-
The Rochester School demands that dictions of the form, "The event RS is
what they call a "positive" theory ought not occurring in the spacetime region
"to predict" [Watts and Zimmerman, K." Except for RS, however, any event
1979, p. 2741, "to explain a set of phe- might be occurring in region K. Each of
nomena" [Watts and Zimmerman, 1979, the atomic events R , R, S, and S is
p. 273, n. 11, and to enable one "to deter- empirically possible, for example, as well
mine if prescriptions from normative as all the joint events that can be con-
theories . . . are feasible" [Watts and structed from them except RS (see Figure
Zimmerman, 1978, pp. 112-1 131. 4(a)).
I will now show how an empirical A definite prediction can be derived
theory of the "negative" form discussed with the right kind of additional informa-
in the preceding section can be used in tion. Suppose we are given the observa-
Christenson 13

tional proposition, "The event R is ing the behavior of the entity (a primary-
occurring in the spacetime region K." As level theory, in terms of Section I).
shown in Figure 4(b), this sentence rules
out the occurrence in that region of the Explanatory Reasoning
event R. Combining this information From a purely logical perspective, the
with that contained in the law, we can explanation of a singular occurrence is
conclude (see Figure 4(c)) that all possi- the mirror image of prediction. In the
bilities are excluded except RS, the joint case of prediction, we are given an em-
occurrence of R and S. Thus, we can pirical theory and some inputs (state-
derive the prediction, "The event S is ments of initial conditions); we seek to
occurring in the spacetime region K." derive a proposition describing an as-yet-
An observational proposition used in unobserved occurrence. In the case of
deriving a prediction is called a statement explanation, we are given an observed
of initial conditions [Popper, 1959, p. 591. occurrence; we seek both an explanatory
Thus, in order to deduce a positive theory and some statements of initial
prediction, one needs in general both an conditions (the explicans) from which we
empirical theory (one or more laws) and can derive a sentence (the explicandum)
one or more statements of initial condi- describing the observed occurrence. This
tions. In terms of Caws's characterization process may be represented by the follow-
of a theory (quoted at the beginning of ing schema :
L 1 , L z,..., L, (Laws)
To Find : (Explicans)
C C , . . . ,C (Initial Conditions)
Given : :. E (Explicandum)

Section I), the inputs to a theory are In some cases, characteristic of what
statements of initial conditions, the out- Kuhn [I9701 calls "normal science," we
puts are predictions. Both inputs and may already have a set of well-corrobo-
outputs are descriptions of occurrences rated laws, so that the process of finding
in the phenomenal domain. This may be an explanation reduces to finding a set of
represented by the following schema : initial conditions. Where we do not have

(Laws)
(Initial Conditions)
(Prediction)
To give an accounting example, sup-
pose we are interested in predicting the such laws but must discover them, finding
future cash flows of an accounting an appropriate description of the expli-
entity. In Section I, I suggested that the candum becomes a necessary part of the
financial statements of an accounting process of explaining it. Since, in a scien-
entity have the character of observational tific system, occurrences are described in
propositions. For purposes of prediction terms of events, finding an appropriate
they would constitute the statements of description of the explicandum means
initial conditions. The schema shows finding an appropriate event structure (or
that, in addition to these statements, we "conceptual framework") for the phe-
would need an empirical theory govern- nomenal domain.
14 The Accounting Review, January 1983

Normative Reasoning require the explanatory concepts of the


Empirical theories can be used as theory ("mass" and "force" in the
guides to action in two different ways, example). Second, they require that at
corresponding respectively to predictive least some of these explanatory concepts
and explanatory reasoning. To distin- correspond to controllable events, since
guish the two ways, Popper [1957, p. 431 it is through manipulation of these events
has called the predictions yielded by that the desired outcome is obtained.
predictive reasoning prophecies and has Normative reasoning, the derivation
pointed out that predictions of a com- of technological predictions, follows this
schema :I9
L , L , . . . ,L (Empirical Laws
To Find :
C , C , . . . ,C (Controllable Initial Conditions)
Given : :. S (Desired Final State)

pletely different kind, which he calls When there is a well-established em-


technological predictions, can be derived pirical science applying to his problem,
by a process analogous to explanatory the technological predictor may find the
reasoning. In the case of a prophecy, relevant laws within that body of knowl-
according to Popper, "we are told about edge rather than having to develop them
an event which we can do nothing to from scratch. The modern mechanical
prevent. Its practical value lies in one engineer, for example, applies the laws of
being warned of the predicted event, so the science of mechanics. Before there is
that we can side-step it or meet it pre- such a science, however, the practitioner
pared." Technological predictions, in faces exactly the same logical problem as
contrast, "form a basis of engineering. a scientist searching for an explanatory
They are, so to speak, constructive, theory [Christenson, 19761.
intimating the steps open to us ifwe want
to achieve certain results." I will refer to Analysis and Synthesis
the derivation of technological predic- Note that there is a close formal
tions as "normative reasoning." resemblance between the schema for
As an example of a technological pre- normative reasoning and that for ex-
diction, one can calculate with the aid of planatory reasoning. In each case we are
Newton's theory of gravitation the force given the conclusion of a deductive argu-
that would have to be applied to a given ment, and we seek to find the premises
mass on the earth's surface in order to l9 As Simon [1965] points out, the initial conditions
place it in orbit. It is interesting that and the description of the desired final state in this
Newton himself anticipated this techno- schema will not be observational propositions but rather
what he calls commands and what I have earlier called
logical application of his theory [Newton, proposals. With a couple of restrictions, however, these
1729, p. 5511. Of course, a test of this commands can be treated for logical purposes as if they
particular prediction was not techno- were observational propositions. The following analogy
may be enlightening. In a linear programming problem,
logically feasible for nearly a quarter of a the constraint set and the objective function usually
millenium! But it could not be derived at define what is empirically possible, and thus correspond
all from earlier theories which lacked the to the set of empirical laws. The command "maximize
the objective function" characterizes the desired final
dynamical concepts of mass and force. state. The values of the variables appearing in the con-
Two points may be observed from this straints and the objective function are the controllable
example. First, technological predictions initial conditions.
Christenson

from which it can be deduced. In other of this state of affairs, and they lead to
words, we reason in the reverse of the different conclusions regarding the ap-
deductive direction. There is this differ- praisal of theories.
ence: In explanatory reasoning, we ac- According to one methodological view,
cept the explicandum as true on the basis called instrumentalism, explanation is
of observation; we terminate reverse nothing but prediction in reverse, or, to
reasoning when we have found laws and put it a little differently, a theory is
initial conditions that we likewise accept nothing but an instrument for prediction.
as true on the basis of observation. In The credo of instrumentalism has been
normative reasoning, we desire that the characterized as follows : In explanatory
description of a certain final state be reasoning, both the statements of initial
true; we terminate reverse reasoning conditions and the explicandum describe
when we have found laws that we accept aspects of reality, to-wit, occurrences in
as true and controllable initial conditions the phenomenal domain. In contrast, the
that we can make true by our actions.20 theory itself does not describe any aspect
In ancient Greek geometry, forward or of reality. Reality, according to the
deductive reasoning, which was used in instrumentalist, consists of nothing but
"proofs," was known as the "method of occurrences of events [Popper, 1965, p.
synthesis," since in it a number of condi- 1081.
tions are combined or synthesized to ~~strumentalism, it may be noted, is a
produce a single result. Reverse reason- slightly liberalized version of positivism.
ing, which seeks to discover the necessary Positivism awards scientific status only
conditions, was known as the "method to statements of "what is." Instrumental-
of analysis." The two methods are dis- ism differs from strict positivism in ad-
cussed by Polya [1945, pp. 141-1 541. See mitting that theories, although they can-
also Hintikka and Remes [1974, Chapter not be reduced to statements of "what is,"
1x1. are nevertheless needed in science. It
claims, however, that their utility is only
IV. TIIEAPPRAISAL OF THEORIES as instruments for prediction, and not as
My purpose in this section is not to descriptions of reality. Positivism and
appraise the theories of the Rochester instrumentalism both agree that only
School but rather to criticize the stan- observational propositions describe
dards by which they think a theory ought reality.
to be appraised, that is to say, their An alternative methodological view,
methodology. It is not possible, of course, called realism, agrees that explanation is
to draw a clean line between these two (logically speaking) prediction in reverse
purposes. The essence of my criticism of and that, therefore, a theory that explains
the Rochester School's methodology is can also be used as an instrument for
that they use it to defend their theories prediction. Realism also admits that
against what would be appropriate criti- some theories may be nothing but instru-
cism. ments for prediction. Realism holds,
however, that for a theory to be consid-
Instrumentalism vs. Realism ered explanatory, it must be more than
In Section I11 it was noted that, from a an instrument for prediction. It must also
purely logical point of view, explanation Reverse reasoning is, of course, the method used in
is prediction in reverse. There are two reasoning from a product to the process that produces
divergent methodological interpretations it, as discussed in Section 111 of this article.
The Accounting Review, January 1983

be interpretible as a description of a far as to say 11953, p. 141 that "truly


deeper reality that underlies the surface important and significant hypotheses
reality of the phenomenal domain of will be found to have 'assumptions' that
occurrences. are wildly inaccurate descriptive repre-
A theory known to be false can still sentations of reality [i.e., are false], and,
yield predictions that are highly accurate, in general, the more significant the theory,
or at least sufficiently accurate for many the more unrealistic the assumptions (in
practical purposes. Newton's gravita- this sen~e)."~'
tional theory, and even the Ptolemaic In my opinion, instrumentalism is a
theory, are still adequate for many mistaken philosophy of science. It results,
astronomical predictions. On the other I think, from confusing an empirical law,
hand, an explanation that is false is no in its universal conditional form, with a
explanation at all. An explanatory theory rule of logical inference.22 Rules of
is supposed to answer the question inference may be said to be valid or
"why," and a false answer to the question invalid, but empirical laws are true or
is certainly unsatisfactory. For this rea- false. Also, instrumentalism has the
son, Einstein's theory has replaced New- effect (and, in Friedman's case, the
ton's as an explanation. An explanatory intent) of shielding some of the proposi-
theory, in short, ought to be true (or at tions of a theoretical system from falsifi-
least not be known to be false), a merely cation. As I indicated in Section 111,
predictive theory need not be [Popper, this robs these propositions of any claim
1972, p. 1921. to belong to empirical science. (Perhaps
Although the Rochester School claims that's why Friedman prefers the term
to base its positivist methodology on "'positive' science.") Finally, instru-
Friedman [1953], they diverge from him mentalism is incompatible with the
on the issue of instrumentalism vs. method of analysis since, in that method,
realism. Friedman puts great stress on we terminate reverse reasoning only
the predictive function of theory and when we have discovered premises that
downplays the explanatory function. By are both sufficient to predict observed
my count, he uses the words "explain" or occurrences and are "already known or
"explanation" only four times in a 40- admittedly true," or at least not known
page essay. Each time, he encloses the to be false. For essentially the same
word in quotation marks (as if to signify reason, theories that have only an instru-
he is using an illegitimate concept) and mental interpretation are useless in nor-
makes clear that what he really means by mative reasoning as described in Section
the terms is correct prediction.
Friedman's position is avowedly *' Friedman's instrumentalism may be contrasted with
instrumentalist [Boland, 19791. He says, the realism of Galileo [1967, p. 3411, who said a p
for example, that "the only [my emphasis] provingly that Copernicus "very well understood that
although the celestial appearances might be saved by
relevant test of the validity [his emphasis] means of assumptions essentially false in nature, it
of a hypothesis is comparison of its would be very much better if he could derive them from
predictions with experience" [1953, pp. true suppositions." Galileo could have avoided trial by
the Inquisition by accepting Cardinal Bellarmino's
8-91. It is notable that, in addition to suggestion that he adopt an instrumentalist interpreta-
insisting that its instrumental value is the tion of the Copernican Theory.
only relevant test of a theory, Friedman 22 Popper himself acknowledges 11959, p. 761 that at
the time he wrote the original German version ofhis book
also speaks of the validity of a theory he was confused about the distinction between a condi-
rather than its truth. Friedman goes so tional proposition and a rule of logical inference.
Christenson

111; only theories that are at least a good Popper [1972, p. 3531, however, calls
approximation to the truth are acceptable the notion that an explicans is corrobo-
for this purpose. rated23 by drawing correct predictions
The Rochester School, however, is from it "incorrect and grossly mislead-
immune to any criticism of instrumental- ing." He points out that "A true predic-
ism, since it abandons (perhaps unself- tion may easily have been validly deduced
consciously) that part of Friedman's from an explicans that is false." As we
methodology. It places the greater stress have seen in Section 11, a theory as a col-
on theories that describe and explain, lection of laws has no positive import,
and it mentions prediction relatively in- and almost all observations will be
frequently, usually in a context where the consistent with (i.e., will not contradict)
testing of a theory through its predictions even a false theory. Therefore, we cannot
rather than its instrumental use is the infer the truth of a theory from the truth
issue. Jensen's list of "positive" questions of predictions drawn from it. In short,
(Figure 1) illustrates this emphasis on the Rochester School's notion that an
explanation rather than prediction. And explanatory theory is made acceptable
Watts and Zimmerman [1979, p. 2741 merely by successful prediction is logi-
proudly claim that their theory not only cally fallacious.
"predicts that accounting theory will be On the other hand, a false conclusion
used to 'buttress preconceived notions"' to an argument does entail the falsity of
but also that "it explains why." its premises. If, therefore, a prediction
If someone questions the realism of derived from an explanatory argument
part of Friedman's theories, he can fall turns out to be false, we can be sure that
back behind his instrumentalist ramparts the explicans is also false. "This means,"
and argue that the criticism is irrelevant; as Popper [1972, p. 3531 says, "that a
the theories with which he is concerned prediction can be used to corroborate a
do not purport to explain but only to theory only if its comparison with obser-
predict, and so long as they predict vations might be regarded as a serious
correctly they are adequate. The same attempt at testing the explicans-a
defense is not available to the Rochester serious attempt at refuting it. A 'risky'
School. The Rochester School's theories prediction of this kind may be called
must either be realistic or they must be 'relevant to a test of the theory."'
rejected as explanations. Since an explicans consists of at least
two premises-a law and a statement of
Appraisal of an Explanatory Theory initial conditions-the fact that the
The Rochester School appears to falsity of the conclusion implies the
believe that the only way one can test the falsity of the explicans does not determine
truth of a theory is to derive predictions how this falsity is to be distributed over
from it. They also appear to believe that the terms of the explicans. That is, the
correct predictions make a theory more falsity of the explicans may mean that the
acceptable. [Watts and Zimmerman, law(s) are true and the initial conditions
1978, p. 125; 1979, p. 283; Zimmerman, false; that the law(s) are false and the
1980, p. 1221. (As a matter of fact, as I will
show later, Watts and Zimmerman claim AS indicated in Section I1 above, Popper considers
that their theories should be accepted a theory to be corroborated only if it has survived serious
attempts to refute it. His reasons for preferring the term
even though predictions derived from "corroboration" to the term "confirmation" are given
them are false.) in [1959, pp. 251-252, n. '11.
The Accounting Review, January 1983

initial conditions true; or that both are The Issue of "Exceptions"


false. The fact that the Rochester School only
The fact that a prediction permits a test weakly tests its theories becomes less
only of the explicans as a whole leads to significant, perhaps, when we observe
the methodological norm that an expli- that their theories fail even these weak
cans should be considered satisfactory tests. That is, their theories yield false
prior to testing only if its terms are predictions, which are then excused
independently testable. That is to say, if a away.
prediction intended as a test of an expli- Watts and Zimmerman [1978, p. 118,
cans fails, we can determine which of the n. 241 tell us, for example, that their
premises is (are) responsible for the theory of corporate lobbying on ac-
failure only if we can test each of them counting standards "is developed for
independently of the others. firms in the same industry that only
But, as Zimmerman [1980, p. 1221 has differ by size." In testing the theory,
acknowledged, he and Watts in their therefore, a control by industry should
several articles have made "simplifying clearly be used. Instead, Watts and
assumptions regarding (unobservable) Zimmerman pool their data across in-
relative costs," assumptions that at times dustries. This tends to obscure the fact
"appear arbitrary and ex post." Zimmer- that the two firms in the retail industry
man attempts to excuse the use of untest- behave in exactly the opposite way to
able assumptions by saying that "if they that predicted. We also observe a con-
yield testable implications that are con- trary-to-prediction rank reversal in the
sistent with the evidence in replications, responses of the oil industry. Finally, as
then progress towards a positive theory the authors themselves note, at least
of accounting is achieved." This flies in three firms who were predicted to submit
the face of the logical fact that the truth to the FASB did not submit.24
of an explicandum does not entail the Since this article is a critique of the
truth of its explicans. Rochester School's methodology rather
There is a way in which a theory can than of their theories, my concern is less
be tested without introducing initial con- with the fact that the Rochester School's
ditions. Although initial conditions are "explanations" were falsified at the first
required to make a positive prediction, a attempt to test them, than with the
theory negatively predicts, without initial rationalizations used by Watts and Zim-
conditions, that certain logically possible merman to "explain" these falsifications.
events will not occur. If one is seriously We are told, for example, that "we can
interested in testing a theory, then, rather only expect a positive theory to hold on
than an entire explicans, one could average" [Watts and Zimmerman, 1978,
specify what these prohibited events are p. 127, n. 371. We are also advised "to
and where, in the light perhaps of back- remember that as in all empirical theories
ground knowledge, they would be most we are concerned with general trends"
likely to occur; and one would then do [Watts and Zimmerman, 1979, pp. 288-
one's damndest to find these prohibited 2891, where "general" is used in the weak
occurrences. That would be the kind of
severe test Popper calls "relevant." The 24 The three firms are identified at one point as IBM,

search for correct predictions engaged in U. S . Steel, and Chrysler; later in the same paragraph
two of the three are identified as IBM and General Tele-
by the Rochester School is simply not phone. No explanation is given of this obvious incon-
"relevant." sistency [Watts and Zimmerman, 1978, p. 1271.
Christenson

sense of "true or applicable in most exceptions by drawing an irrelevant


instances but not all" rather than in the analogy with the toss of a coin : They say
strong sense of "relating to, concerned that "one or two 'heads' is not sufficient
with, or applicable to every member of a to reject the hypothesis that a given coin
class" [American Heritage Dictionary, is 'fair'." The analogy is irrelevant
1969, p. 5481. In other words, we are told because, in the case of a fair coin, we are
without any evidence or argument that dealing with a stochastic law, which
since all empirical theories admit excep- asserts that events occur with specifically
tions we needn't worry about the excep- stated numerical probabilities derived
tions to the Rochester School's theory. from symmetry considerations. There is
In responding to this argument, I will nothing remotely comparable to such a
again follow Jensen's advice and consult law in the theories of the Rochester
Pareto, who tells us:
A 'law' that has exceptions, that is to say, a
As Blaug [1976, p. 1731 has written,
uniformity which is not uniform, is an "Much empirical work in economics is
expression devoid of meaning. . . . If one like 'playing tennis with the net down':
grants to a person who is stating a law that instead of attempting to refute testable
his law may have its exceptions, he can always predictions, economists spend much of
meet every fact that is adduced against him their time showing that the real world
with the excuse that it is an "exception," and
he will never be caught in the wrong. And that bears out their predictions, thus replacing
is exactly what literary economists, moralists, falsification, which is difficult, with con-
and metaphysicists d o [Pareto, 1935, Section firmation, which is easy." The work of
1689, no. 31. the Rochester School is certainly no ex-
And that, of course, is also exactly ception to this "general trend."
what Watts and Zimmerman do! VI. SUMMARY AND CONCLUSION
If astronomers were interested only in
general trends, the assertion that the The main criticisms of the methodol-
heavenly bodies move uniformly from ogy of Positive Accounting advanced in
east to west would be a satisfactory this article are the following:
theory, since only a handful of pesky 1. The Rochester School's assertion
bodies (planets and comets) behave ex- that the kind of "positive" research
ceptionally. Almost the entire history of they are undertaking is a prerequi-
astronomy, however, consists of attempts site for normative accounting
to explain these exceptions rather than to theory is based on a confusion of
excuse them.25 Even the Ptolemaic as- phenomenal domains at two differ-
tronomers had the good sense to add ent levels (accounting entities vs.
another epicycle or equant when needed! accountants), and is mistaken.
Pareto concluded the statement quoted 2. The concept of "'positive' theory"
above by saying, "A law [that admits is drawn from an obsolete philoso-
exceptions] has no significance, and phy of science and is in any case a
knowledge of it is not of the slightest misnomer, because the theories of
use." By arguing that their theories admit
exceptions, Watts and Zimmerman con- 25 Cf. Holton and Brush [1973, p. 4301.
demn them as insignificant and useless. I l6 Because their theories are not formulated in sto-
agree. chastic terms, I have not discussed in this article the
nature of stochastic laws and the particular problems
Watts and Zimmerman [1979, p. 2881 involved in testing them. Popper [1959, Chapter VIII]
also attempt to deal with the problem of discusses these problems in detail.
The Accounting Review, January 1983

empirical science make no positive deficiencies in their program, while ac-


statement of "what is." knowledging that they will be the main
3. Although a theory may be used beneficiaries of this activity.
merely for prediction even if it is The Rochester School ought to put its
known to be false, an explanatory own program in order before it asks
theory of the type sought by the others to take that program seriously. A
Rochester School, or one that is to useful first step would be for them to stick
be used to test normative proposals, with one set of phenomena until they
ought not to be known to be false. have understood it well and satisfactorily
The method of analysis, which explained it, rather than leaping to a
reasons backward from the phe- different phenomenal domain in each
nomena to premises which are new article in an effort to establish
acceptable on the basis of indepen- squatters' rights.27 They should follow
dent evidence, is the appropriate the advice of Newton, who said (quoted
method for constructing explana- by Guerlac [1973, p. 3851) :
tory theories. But if without deriving the properties of things
4. Contrary to the empirical method from Phaenomena you feign Hypotheses and
of subjecting theories to severe think by them to explain all nature you may
attempts to falsify them, the make a plausible systeme of Philosophy for
Rochester School introduces ad hoc getting your self a name, but your systeme
arguments to excuse the failures of will be little better than a Romance. To ex-
plain all nature is too difficult a task for any
their theories. This tactic is a one man or even for any one age. Tis much
violation of the norms which, ac- better to do a little with certainty and leave the
cording to Popper [1959, Section rest for others that come after you than to
201, must be followed if a system of explain all things by conjecture without mak-
propositions is to be considered ing sure of any thing.
"scientific." Newton himself set an appropriate
Of course, Watts and Zimmerman example, refraining from publishing his
[1979, p. 2901 do say, "We do not contend lunar theory for nearly twenty years while
that all issues are settled, but rather en- he attempted to resolve discrepancies
courage others to pursue, correct, and between its predictions and observational
extend our analysis." data. As Lakatos [1978, vol. i, p. 2161
This encouragement is a trap for the observes, "The first dozen [versions of
unwary. As the authors point out earlier Newton's theory] ended up in Newton's
in the same article [p. 2861, "Researchers wastepaper-basket." In a footnote, La-
have non-pecuniary incentives to be well- katos explains :
known, and this reputation is rewarded 'Wastepaper-baskets' were containers used
by a higher salary and a plenitude of in the seventeenth century for the disposal of
research funds." A footnote adds that some first versions of manuscripts which self-
"Higher compensation will accrue to the criticism-or private criticism of learned
friends-ruled,out on the first reading. In our
most prolific, articulate, and creative age of publication explosion most people have
advocates-to those who are able to
establish early property rights in a topic
and thus must be cited by later theorists" 27 Watts and Zimmerman [1978], for example, deals

[p. 286, n. 461. with the behavior of practicing financial accountants and
managers; Watts and Zimmerman [1979], with that of
In other words, the Rochester School academic accountants; and Zimmerman [1979], with
is inviting other researchers to repair the that of cost accountants.
Christenson 21

no time to read their manuscripts, and the The old ways still have much to recom-

function of wastepaper-baskets has now been mend them.

taken over by scientificjournals.

REFERENCES
American Heritage Dictionary (1969) (Houghton Mifflin Co., 1969).
Bar-Hillel, Y. (1974), "Popper's Theory of Corroboration," in Paul A. Schilpp (ed.), The Philosophy of
Karl Popper (Open Court, 1974), pp. 332-348.
Blaug, Mark (1976), "Kuhn versus Lakatos, or Paradigms versus research programmes in the history of
economics," in S. J. Latsis (ed.), Method and Appraisal in Economics (Cambridge University Press,
1976), pp. 149-180.
(1980), The Methodology of Economics (Cambridge University Press, 1980).
Boland, L. A. (1979), "A Critique of Friedman's Critics," Journal of Economic Literature (June 1979),
pp. 503-522.
Caws, Peter (1972), "Accounting Research-Science or Methodology?", in R. R. Sterling (ed.), Research
Methodology in Accounting (Scholars Book Co., 1972), pp. 71-73.
Christenson, Charles (1976), "Proposals for a Program of Empirical Research Into the Properties of
Triangles." Decision Sciences (October 1976). pp. 63 1-648.
Einstein, Albert (1944), "Remarks on Bertrand Russell's Theory of Knowledge," in Paul A. Schilpp (ed.),
The Philosophy of Bertrand Russell (Open Court, 1944), pp. 277-291.
Financial Accounting Standards Board (1978), "Objectives of Financial Reporting by Business Enter-
prises," Statement of Financial Accounting Concepts No. 1 (FASB, 1978).
Friedman, Milton (1953), "The Methodology of Positive Economics," in Essays in Positice Economics
(University of Chicago Press, 1953), pp. 3-43,
Galilei, Galileo (1967), Dialogue Concerning the Twlo Chief World Systems (University of California
Press, 1967; translation from the 1632 Italian version by Stillman Drake).
Guerlac, Henry (1973), "Newton and the Method of Analysis" in Dictionary of the History of Ideas
(Charles Scribner's Sons. 1973) pp. 378-391.
Hayek, F. A. (1952), The Counter-Recolution of Science (Free Press, 1952).
Hempel, Carl G. (1946), "A Note on the Paradoxes of Confirmation," Mind(January, 1946), pp. 79-82.
Hintikka, Jaakko, and Unto Remes (1974), The Method of Analysis (D. Reidel, 1974).
Holton, Gerald, and S. G . Brush (1973), Introduction to Concepts and Theories in Physical Science
(Addison-Wesley, 1973).
Hume, David (1739), A Treatise of Human Nature (Oxford, 1888; reprinted from the original 1739
edition and edited by L. A. Selby-Bigge).
Ijiri, Yuji, (1975), Theory of Accounting Measurement. Studies in Accounting Research #10 (American
Accounting Association, 1975).
Jensen, M. C. (1976), "Reflections on the State of Accounting Research and the Regulation of Account-
ing," Stanford Lectures in Accounting 1976 (Graduate School of Business, Stanford University, 1976),
pp. 11-19.
Keynes, J. N. (1891), The Scope and Method of Political Economv (Macmillan, 1891).
Kohler, Eric L. (1975), A Dictionary for Accountants (Prentice-Hall, 1975).
Kuhn, T. S. (1970), The Structure of Scientific Rez;olutions (University of Chicago Press, 1970).
Lakatos, Imre, (1978), Philosophical Papers (2 vols.) (Cambridge University Press, 1978).
Machlup, Fritz (1963), "Introductory Remarks," American Economic Reriew (May 1963). p. 204.
Meckling, W. H. (1976), "Values and the Choice of the Model of the Individual in the Social Sciences,"
Rerue Suisse d'Economie Politique et de Statistique (December. 1976). pp. 545-560.
Nagel, Ernest (1963), "Assumptions in Economic Theory," American Economic R e ~ i e w(May 1963), pp.
21 1-219.
Newton, Isaac (1729), Principia (University of California Press, 1934; reprinted from the English transla-
tion of 1729).
Pareto, ~ i l f r e d o(1935), Treatise on General Sociology (Harcourt, Brace & Co., 1935; translated by
Andrew Bongiorno and Arthur Livingston from the 1923 Italian edition).
T h e Accounting Review, January 1983

Passmore, John (1967), "Logical Positivism," in The Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Collier-Macmillan,


1967), pp. 52-57.
Polya, George (1945), How to Solve It (Princeton University Press, 1945).
Popper, K. R. (1957), The Powrty of Historicism (Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1957).
(1959), The Logic of Scientific Discovery (Basic Books, 1959).
(1965), Conjectures and Refutations (Harper & Row, 1965).
(1966), The Open Society and Its Enemies (Princeton University Press, 1966).
(1972). Objectice Knowledge (Oxford, 1972).
Quine, W. V. 0. (1974), "On Popper's Negative Methodology," in Paul A. Schilpp (ed.), The Philosophy
of Karl Popper (Open Court, 1974), pp. 218-220.
Russell, Bertrand (1946), A History of Western Philosophy (Simon & Shuster, 1946).
Samuelson, P. A. (1962), Problems of the American Economy (Stamp Memorial Lecture, 1962).
Simon, H. A. (1965), "The Logic of Rational Decision," British Journalfor the Philosophy of Science
(November, 1965), pp. 169-1 86.
Watts, R. L. (1977), "Corporate Financial Statements, A Product of the Market and Political Processes,"
Australian Journal of Management (April 1977), pp. 53-75.
Watts, R. L., and J. L. Zimmerman (1978), "Towards a Positive Theory of the Determination of Account-
ing Standards," THEACCOUNTING REVIEW (January 1978), pp. 112-134.
(1979), "The Demand for and Supply of Accounting Theories: The Market for Excuses," THE
ACCOUNTING REVIEW (April 1979), pp. 273-305.
Zimmerman, J. L. (1979), "The Costs and Benefits of Cost Allocations," THEACCOUNTING REVIEW (July
1979), pp. 504-52 1.
(1980), "Positive Research in Accounting," in R. D. Nair and T. H. Williams (eds.), Perspectices
on Research (Graduate School of Business, University of Wisconsin, 1980), pp. 107-128.
http://www.jstor.org

LINKED CITATIONS
- Page 1 of 2 -

You have printed the following article:


The Methodology of Positive Accounting
Charles Christenson
The Accounting Review, Vol. 58, No. 1. (Jan., 1983), pp. 1-22.
Stable URL:
http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0001-4826%28198301%2958%3A1%3C1%3ATMOPA%3E2.0.CO%3B2-Z

This article references the following linked citations. If you are trying to access articles from an
off-campus location, you may be required to first logon via your library web site to access JSTOR. Please
visit your library's website or contact a librarian to learn about options for remote access to JSTOR.

[Footnotes]

16
Introductory Remarks
Fritz Machlup
The American Economic Review, Vol. 53, No. 2, Papers and Proceedings of the Seventy-Fifth
Annual Meeting of the American Economic Association. (May, 1963), p. 204.
Stable URL:
http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0002-8282%28196305%2953%3A2%3C204%3AIR%3E2.0.CO%3B2-A

19
The Logic of Rational Decision
Herbert A. Simon
The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 16, No. 63. (Nov., 1965), pp. 169-186.
Stable URL:
http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0007-0882%28196511%2916%3A63%3C169%3ATLORD%3E2.0.CO%3B2-I

References

A Critique of Friedman's Critics


Lawrence A. Boland
Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. 17, No. 2. (Jun., 1979), pp. 503-522.
Stable URL:
http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0022-0515%28197906%2917%3A2%3C503%3AACOFC%3E2.0.CO%3B2-H

NOTE: The reference numbering from the original has been maintained in this citation list.
http://www.jstor.org

LINKED CITATIONS
- Page 2 of 2 -

A Note on the Parodoxes of Confirmation


Carl G. Hempel
Mind, New Series, Vol. 55, No. 217. (Jan., 1946), pp. 79-82.
Stable URL:
http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0026-4423%28194601%292%3A55%3A217%3C79%3AANOTPO%3E2.0.CO%3B2-0

Introductory Remarks
Fritz Machlup
The American Economic Review, Vol. 53, No. 2, Papers and Proceedings of the Seventy-Fifth
Annual Meeting of the American Economic Association. (May, 1963), p. 204.
Stable URL:
http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0002-8282%28196305%2953%3A2%3C204%3AIR%3E2.0.CO%3B2-A

Assumptions in Economic Theory


Ernest Nagel
The American Economic Review, Vol. 53, No. 2, Papers and Proceedings of the Seventy-Fifth
Annual Meeting of the American Economic Association. (May, 1963), pp. 211-219.
Stable URL:
http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0002-8282%28196305%2953%3A2%3C211%3AAIET%3E2.0.CO%3B2-I

The Logic of Rational Decision


Herbert A. Simon
The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 16, No. 63. (Nov., 1965), pp. 169-186.
Stable URL:
http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0007-0882%28196511%2916%3A63%3C169%3ATLORD%3E2.0.CO%3B2-I

NOTE: The reference numbering from the original has been maintained in this citation list.

Вам также может понравиться