Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 6

American Economic Association

Libertarian Paternalism
Author(s): Richard H. Thaler and Cass R. Sunstein
Reviewed work(s):
Source: The American Economic Review, Vol. 93, No. 2, Papers and Proceedings of the One
Hundred Fifteenth Annual Meeting of the American Economic Association, Washington, DC,
January 3-5, 2003 (May, 2003), pp. 175-179
Published by: American Economic Association
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3132220 .
Accessed: 08/08/2012 13:46

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

American Economic Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The
American Economic Review.

http://www.jstor.org
BEHAVIORAL
ECONOMICS,PUBLICPOLICY,AND PATERNALISMt

LibertarianPaternalism

By RICHARDH. THALER
ANDCASSR. SUNSTEIN*

Many economists are libertariansand con- appears to be paternalistic, which it is, but
sider the term "paternalistic"to be derogatory. would anyone advocate options 2 or 3?
Most would think that the phrase libertarian The second misconceptionis thatpaternalism
paternalismis an oxymoron.The modest goal of always involves coercion. As the cafeteria ex-
this essay is to encourageeconomists to rethink ample illustrates,the choice of which order to
their views on paternalism.We believe that the presentfood items does not coerce anyone to do
anti-paternalistic fervor expressed by many anything, yet one might prefer some orders to
economists is based on a combinationof a false others on paternalistic grounds. Would many
assumption and at least two misconceptions. object to putting the fruit before the desserts at
The false assumptionis thatpeople always (usu- an elementary school cafeteria if the outcome
ally?) make choices that are in their best inter- were to increasethe consumptionratioof apples
est. This claim is either tautological, and to Twinkies? Is this questionfundamentallydif-
therefore uninteresting, or testable. We claim ferentif the customersare adults?If no coercion
that it is testable and false-indeed, obviously is involved, we think that some types of pater-
false. nalism should be acceptable to even the most
The first misconception is that there are via- ardentlibertarian.We call such actions libertar-
ble alternativesto paternalism.In many situa- ian paternalism.
tions, some organizationor agent must make a In our understanding,a policy counts as "pa-
choice that will affect the choices of some other ternalistic" if it is selected with the goal of
people. The point applies to both private and influencing the choices of affected parties in a
public actors. Consider the problem facing the way that will make those parties better off. We
director of a company cafeteria who discovers intend"betteroff' to be measuredas objectively
that the order in which food is arrangedinflu- as possible, and we clearly do not always equate
ences the choices people make. To simplify, revealed preference with welfare. That is, we
consider three alternative strategies: (1) she emphasize the possibility that in some cases
could make choices that she thinks would make individuals make inferior choices, choices that
the customers best off; (2) she could make they would change if they had complete infor-
choices at random;or (3) she could maliciously mation, unlimited cognitive abilities, and no
choose those items that she thinks would make lack of willpower. Once it is understood that
the customers as obese as possible. Option 1 some organizational decisions are inevitable,
that a form of paternalismcannot be avoided,
*Discussants: RobertE. Hall, Stanford and that the alternativesto paternalism(such as
University;Gary
Becker, University of Chicago; RobertBarro,HarvardUni- choosing options to make people sick, obese, or
versity. generally worse off) are unattractive,we can
* Thaler:Departmentof Economics and Behavioral Sci- abandonthe less interestingquestionof whether
ence, University of Chicago GraduateSchool of Business, to be paternalisticor not and turn to the more
1101 E. 58th Street, Chicago, IL 60637 (e-mail: constructivequestion of how to choose among
thaler@gsb.uchicago.edu);Sunstein: Law School and De- paternalisticoptions.1
partmentof Political Science, University of Chicago, 1111
E. 60th Street, Chicago, IL 60637 (e-mail: csunstei@
midway.uchicago.edu).We are gratefulto RichardEpstein,
Russ Fuller, Owen Lamont, Eric Posner, Richard Posner, 1 Readers interested in this
topic should also consult
and David Wilcox for valuable comments on a previous Colin Camereret al. (2001) for an illuminatingdiscussion of
draft. related issues. That paper shares with the papers in this
175
176 AEA PAPERSAND PROCEEDINGS MAY2003

I. Are ChoicesRational? most recent statement to the lab). They were


then shown the probabilitydistributionsof ex-
The presumption that individual choices pected retirementincome for three investment
should be free from interference is usually portfolios just labeled A, B, and C. Unbe-
based on the assumptionthat people do a good knownst to the subjects, the three portfolios
job of makingchoices, or at least that they do a were their own and portfolios mimicking the
far betterjob than thirdpartiescould do. As far average and median choices of their fellow em-
as we can tell, there is little empirical support ployees. The distributionsof expected returns
for this claim. Research by psychologists and were computedusing the software of Financial
economists over the past three decades has Engines, the financial information company
raised questions about the rationality of the founded by William Sharpe. On average, the
judgments and decisions that individualsmake. subjectsratedthe averageportfolioequally with
People do not exhibit rationalexpectations,fail their own portfolio, and they judged the median
to make forecasts that are consistent with portfolio to be significantlymore attractivethan
Bayes' rule, use heuristics that lead them to their own. Indeed, only 20 percent of the sub-
make systematic blunders, exhibit preference jects preferredtheir own portfolio to the me-
reversals(thatis, they preferA to B and B to A) dian portfolio. Apparently,people do not gain
and make different choices depending on the much by choosing investment portfolios for
wording of the problem (for many examples, themselves.
see the two recent collections of papers by
Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky [2000] II. Is PaternalismInevitable?
and by Thomas Gilovich et al. [2002]). Further-
more, in the context of intertemporalchoice, As the cafeterialine example discussed above
people exhibit dynamic inconsistency, valuing illustrates, planners are forced to make some
present consumption much more than future design choices. A simple and importantexam-
consumption.In other words, people have self- ple is the selection of a "default option" to
control problems (see the other papers in this determine what happens if an agent fails to
session [James Choi et al., 2003b; Ted choose for himself. In a fully rational world
O'Donoghue and MatthewRabin, 2003] for de- such design choices would have little effect (at
tails and references). least in high-stakes situations) because agents
Many economists are skeptical of some of would simply choose the best option for them
these findings, thinking that people may do a regardless of the default. However, numerous
betterjob of choosing in the "real world" than experimentsillustratethat there is a very strong
they do in the laboratory.However, studies of "statusquo" bias (see William Samuelson and
actual choices for high stakes reveal many of Richard Zeckhauser, 1988; Kahneman et al.,
the same problems. For example, the Surgeon 1991). The existing arrangement,whether set
General reports that 61 percent of Americans out by private institutions or by government,
are either overweight or obese. Given the ad- tends to stick.
verse effects obesity has on health, it is hard to One illustration of this phenomenon comes
claim that Americans are eating optimal diets. from studies of automaticenrollmentin 401(k)
Another illustrationcomes from the domain employee savings plans. Most 401(k) plans use
of savings behavior. Shlomo Benartzi and Tha- an opt-in design. When employees firstbecome
ler (2002) investigate how much investors like eligible to participatein the 401(k) plan, they
the portfolios they have selected in their receive some plan information and an enroll-
defined-contributionsavings plans. Employees ment form that must be completed in order to
volunteeredto sharetheirportfoliochoices with join. Under the alternativeof automaticenroll-
the investigators (by bringing a copy of their ment, employees receive the same information
but are told thatunless they opt out, they will be
enrolled in the plan (with some default options
for savings rates and asset allocation). In com-
session the common goal of devising policies thathelp some
agents who are making some mistake,while minimizingthe panies that offer a "match" (the employer
costs imposed on others. matches the employee's contributionsaccord-
VOL.93 NO. 2 BEHAVIORALECONOMICS,PUBLIC POLICY,AND PATERNALISM 177

ing to some formula, often a 50-percent match perhapsbecause it seems to have resulted from
up to some cap), most employees eventually do some conscious thoughtaboutwhat makes most
join the plan, but enrollments occur much sense for most people. But there is a separate
sooner under automatic enrollment. For exam- explanation, involving inertia. For any em-
ple, Brigitte Madrian and Dennis Shea (2001) ployee, a change from any status quo entails
found that initial enrollmentsjumped from 49 time and effort, and many people seem to prefer
percentto 86 percent,and Choi et al. (2002) find to avoid both of these, especially if they are
similar results for other companies. prone to procrastination.When default rules are
Should the adoptionof automaticenrollment "sticky" and affect choices as a result, inertia
be consideredpaternalistic?And, if so, should it might be the major reason.
therefore be seen as a kind of officious med- For presentpurposes,the choice among these
dling with employee preferences? We answer variousexplanationsdoes not much matter.The
these questions yes and no respectively. If the point is only that paternalism,in the form of
employer thinks (correctly, we believe) that effects on individual choices, is often unavoid-
most employees would preferto join the 401(k) able. When paternalismseems absent, it is usu-
plan if they took the time to think about it and ally because the startingpoint appearsso natural
did not lose the enrollmentform, then by choos- and obvious that its preference-shapingeffects
ing automaticenrollmentthey are acting pater- are invisible to most observers. But those ef-
nalistically. They are attempting to steer fects are nonetheless there. Of course it is usu-
employees' choices in directions that will pro- ally good not to block choices, and we do not
mote employees' welfare. But since no one is mean to defend non-libertarian paternalism
forced to do anything, we think this steering here. But in an important respect, the anti-
should be considered unobjectionableto liber- paternalisticposition is incoherent.
tarians.The employer must choose some set of
rules, and either plan affects employees' III. Beyondthe Inevitable(but Still Libertarian)
choices. No law of nature says that, in the
absence of an affirmativeelection by employ- The inevitabilityof paternalismis most clear
ees, zero percent of earnings will go into a when the plannerhas to choose default rules. It
retirement plan. Because both plans alter is reasonableto ask whetherthe plannershould
choices, neither one can be said, more than the go beyond the inevitable. Take the cafeteria
other, to count as a form of objectionable example discussed above. Putting the fruit be-
meddling. fore the desserts is a fairly mild intervention.A
Quick-minded readers might be tempted to more intrusive step would be to place the des-
think that there is a way out of this dilemma. serts in anotherlocation altogether,so that din-
Employers could avoid choosing a default if ers have to get up and get a dessert after they
they required employees to make a choice, ei- have finished the rest of their meal. This step
therin or out. But some thoughtreveals thatthis raises the transactionscosts of eating dessert,
is not at all a way out of the dilemma;rather,it and according to a standardeconomic analysis
is simply another option among many that the the proposal is unattractive:it seems to make
employer can elect. In fact, Choi et al. (2003a) dessert-eatersworse off and no one better off.
find thatthis rule increasesenrollments(relative But once self-controlcosts are incorporated,we
to the opt-in rule) though by not as much as can see that some diners would prefer this ar-
automaticenrollment.Furthermore,the very re- rangement,namely, those who would eat a des-
quirementthat employees make a choice has a sert if it were put in front of them but would
paternalisticelement. Many employees do not resist temptation if given a little help. To the
want to have to make a choice (and would extent that the dessert location is not hard to
choose not to have to do so). Should employers find, and no choice is forbidden,this approach
really force them to choose? meets libertarianmuster.
Why, exactly, does the setting of defaults In the domain of employee savings, Thaler
have such large effects? With respect to sav- and Benartzi (2003) have proposeda method of
ings, the designateddefaultplan apparentlycar- increasing contributions to 401(k) plans that
ries a certain legitimacy for many employees, also meets the libertariantest. Under this plan,
178 AEA PAPERSAND PROCEEDINGS MAY2003

called Save More Tomorrow, employees are often depends on the startingpoint, and hence
invited to sign up for a programin which their the startingpoint cannot be selected by asking
contributionsto the savings plan are increased what people choose. In these circumstances,the
annually whenever they get a raise. Once em- libertarianpaternalistwould seek indirectprox-
ployees join the plan, they stay in until they opt ies for welfare:methodsthattest whetherone or
out or reach the maximum savings rate in the anotherapproachis welfare-promotingwithout
plan. In the first company to use this plan, the relying on unreliable guesswork about that
employees who joined increased their savings question. We suggest three possible methods.
rates from 3.5 percent to 11.6 percentin a little First, the libertarianpaternalistmight select
over two years (three raises). Very few of the the approachthat the majoritywould choose if
employees who join the plan drop out. This is explicit choices were required and revealed.
successful libertarianpaternalismin action. Useful though it is, this market-mimickingap-
proach raises its own problems. Perhaps the
IV. How to Choose:The Toolbox majority's choices would be insufficiently in-
of the LibertarianPaternalist formed. Perhaps those choices, in fact, would
not promotethe majority'swelfare. At least as a
How should sensible planners(a category we presumption,however, it makes sense to follow
mean to include anyone who must design plans those choices, if the planner knows what they
for others, from human-resourcedirectors to would be. A deeper problem is that the major-
bureaucratsto kings) choose among possible ity's choices might themselves be a function of
systems, given that some choice is necessary? the startingpoint or the default rule. If so, the
We suggest two approachesto this problem. problem of circularity dooms the market-
If feasible, a comparison of possible rules mimicking approach. But in some cases, at
should be done using a form of cost-benefit least, the majorityis likely to go one way or the
analysis.The goal of a cost-benefit studywould otherregardlessof the startingpoint; and to that
be to measure the full ramificationsof any de- extent, the market-mimickingstrategy seems
sign choice. To illustrate, take the example of quite workable.
automatic enrollment. Under automatic enroll- Second, the libertarianpaternalistmight se-
ment some employees will join the plan who lect the approach that would force people to
otherwise would not. Presumably, some are make their choices explicit. This approach
made better off (especially if there is an em- might be chosen if the market-mimickingstrat-
ployer match), but some may be made worse egy fails, either because of the circularityprob-
off (e.g., those who are highly liquidity- lem or because the planner does not know
constrained).If the issue were just enrollment, which approachwould in fact be chosen by the
we would guess that the gains would exceed the majority.We have seen the possibility of forced
losses. We base this guess partly on revealed choices in the context of retirementplans; it
choices. Most employees do join the plan even- would be easy to find other examples. Here too,
tually, and very few who are automaticallyen- however, there is a risk that the choices that are
rolled opt out when they figure out what has actually elicited will be inadequatelyinformed
happenedto them. We also judge that the costs or will not promote welfare. In the case of
of having too little saved up for retirementare retirementplans, for example, forced choices
typically greaterthan the costs of having saved have been found to produce higher participa-
too much. tion rates than requiring opt-ins, but lower
In many cases, however, the plannerwill be rates than requiringopt-outs. If it is likely that
unable to make a direct inquiry into welfare, automatic enrollment is welfare-promoting,
either because too little informationis available perhaps automatic enrollment should be pre-
or because the costs of doing the analysis are ferred over forced choices. The only sugges-
not warranted.The committed anti-paternalist tion is that, where the social planner is unsure
might say, in such cases, that people should how to handle the welfare question, he might
simply be permittedto choose as they see fit. devise a strategythatrequirespeople to choose.
We hope thatwe have said enough to show why Third, the libertarianpaternalistmight select
this response is unhelpful.What people choose the approachthat minimizesthe numberof opt-
VOL.93 NO. 2 BEHAVIORALECONOMICS,PUBLIC POLICY,AND PATERNALISM 179

outs. For example, very few employees opt out and the Path of Least Resistance," in James
of the 401(k) plan when they are automatically M. Poterba,ed., Taxpolicy and the economy,
enrolled,though many opt in underthe standard Vol. 16. Cambridge,MA: MIT Press, 2002,
enrollmentprocedure.This is an ex post inquiry pp. 67-113.
into people's preferences, in contrast to the ex . "BenignPaternalismand Active Deci-
ante approachfavoredby the market-mimicking sions: A Natural Experiment."Working pa-
strategy.With those numbers,there is reason to per, University of Chicago, GraduateSchool
thinkthat automaticenrollmentis better,if only of Business, 2003a.
because more people are sufficiently satisfiedto . "Optimal Defaults." American Eco-
leave it in place. nomic Review, May 2003b (Papers and Pro-
ceedings), 93(2), pp. 180-85.
V. Conclusion Gilovich,Thomas;Griffin,Dale and Kahneman,
Daniel, eds. Heuristics and biases: The psy-
Our goal here has been to defend libertarian chology of intuitive judgment. Cambridge,
paternalism, an approach that preserves free- U.K.: CambridgeUniversity Press, 2002.
dom of choice but that authorizesboth private Kahneman,Daniel;Knetsch,Jack L. and Thaler,
and public institutionsto steer people in direc- Richard H. "The Endowment Effect, Loss
tions that will promotetheir welfare. Some kind Aversion, and Status Quo Bias." Journal of
of paternalismis likely whenever such institu- Economic Perspectives, Winter 1991, 5(1),
tions set out arrangementsthat will prevail un- pp. 193-206.
less people affirmatively choose otherwise. In Kahneman, Daniel and Tversky, Amos, eds.
these circumstances,the goal should be to avoid Choices, values, and frames. Cambridge,
random, arbitrary,or harmful effects and to U.K.: CambridgeUniversity Press, 2000.
produce a situation that is likely to promote Madrian,Brigitteand Shea,Dennis."ThePower
people's welfare, suitably defined. of Suggestion: Inertiain 401(k) Participation
and Savings Behavior."QuarterlyJournal of
REFERENCES Economics, November 2001, 116(4), pp.
1149-87.
Benartzi,Shlomoand Thaler,RichardH. "How O'Donoghue,Ted and Rabin, Matthew."Study-
Much Is Investor Autonomy Worth?"Jour- ing Optimal Paternalism, Illustrated by a
nal of Finance, August 2002, 57(4), pp. Model of Sin Taxes." American Economic
1593-1616. Review, May 2003 (Papers and Proceed-
Camerer, Colin; Issacharoff, Samuel; Loewen- ings), 93(2), pp. 186-91.
stein, George; O'Donoghue,Ted and Rabin, Samuelson,Williamand Zeckhauser,RichardJ.
Matthew. "Regulation for Conservatives: "StatusQuo Bias in Decision Making."Jour-
Behavioral Economics and the Case for nal of Risk and Uncertainty, March 1988,
Asymmetric Paternalism." Working paper, 1(1), pp. 7-59.
CaliforniaInstitute of Technology, 2001. Thaler,RichardH. and Benartzi,Shlomo."Save
Choi,James;Laibson,David;Madrian,BrigitteC. More Tomorrow:Using BehavioralEconom-
and Metrick,Andrew."Defined Contribution ics to IncreaseEmployee Saving."Journal of
Pensions: Plan Rules, ParticipantDecisions, Political Economy, 2003 (forthcoming).

Вам также может понравиться