Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 6

Susan Sontag

An argument about beauty

1
Responding at last, in April of 2002, to see past. The Pope likes venerable ideas.
the scandal created by the revelation of And beauty, as a term signifying (like
innumerable cover-ups of sexually pred- health) an indisputable excellence, has
atory priests, Pope John Paul II told the been a perennial resource in the issuing
American cardinals summoned to the of peremptory evaluations.
Vatican, “A great work of art may be Permanence, however, is not one of
blemished, but its beauty remains; and beauty’s more obvious attributes; and
this is a truth which any intellectually the contemplation of beauty, when it is
honest critic will recognize.” expert, may be wreathed in pathos, the
Is it too odd that the Pope likens the drama on which Shakespeare elaborates
Catholic Church to a great–that is, in many of the Sonnets. Traditional cele-
beautiful–work of art? Perhaps not, brations of beauty in Japan, like the
since the inane comparison allows him annual rite of cherry-blossom viewing,
to turn abhorrent misdeeds into some- are keenly elegiac; the most stirring
thing like the scratches in the print of a beauty is the most evanescent. To make
silent ½lm or craquelure covering the beauty in some sense imperishable re-
surface of an Old Master painting, blem- quired a lot of conceptual tinkering and
ishes that we reflexively screen out or transposing, but the idea was simply too
alluring, too potent, to be squandered on
Susan Sontag has been a Fellow of the American the praise of superior embodiments. The
Academy since 1993. Best known as a novelist and aim was to multiply the notion, to allow
essayist–her books have been translated into thir- for kinds of beauty, beauty with adjec-
ty-two languages–she has also written stories and tives, arranged on a scale of ascending
plays, written and directed movies, and worked as value and incorruptibility, with the
a theatre director in the United States and Europe. metaphorized uses (‘intellectual beauty,’
In 2000 she won the National Book Award for ‘spiritual beauty’) taking precedence
her novel “In America,” and in 2001 received the over what ordinary language extols as
Jerusalem Prize for the body of her work. Last beautiful–a gladness to the senses.
year, a new collection of essays, “Where the Stress The less ‘uplifting’ beauty of face and
Falls,” was published. Her next book, “Regarding body remains the most commonly visit-
the Pain of Others,” will appear in early 2003, ed site of the beautiful. But one would
and she is also writing another novel. hardly expect the Pope to invoke that
sense of beauty while constructing an
© 2002 by Susan Sontag exculpatory account of several genera-

Dædalus Fall 2002 21


Susan tions’ worth of the clergy’s sexual mo- to mean ‘merely’ beautiful: there is no
Sontag lestation of children and protection of more vapid or philistine compliment.
on
beauty the molesters. More to the point–his Elsewhere, beauty still reigns, irre-
point–is the ‘higher’ beauty of art. pressible. (How could it not?) When
However much art may seem to be a that notorious beauty-lover Oscar Wilde
matter of surface and reception by the announced in The Decay of Lying, “No-
senses, it has generally been accorded an body of any real culture ever talks about
honorary citizenship in the domain of the beauty of a sunset. Sunsets are quite
‘inner’ (as opposed to ‘outer’) beauty. old-fashioned,” sunsets reeled under the
Beauty, it seems, is immutable, at least blow, then recovered. Les beaux-arts,
when incarnated–½xed–in the form of when summoned to a similar call to be
art, because it is in art that beauty as an up-to-date, did not. The subtraction of
idea, an eternal idea, is best embodied. beauty as a standard for art hardly sig-
Beauty (should you choose to use the nals a decline of the authority of beauty.
word that way) is deep, not super½cial; Rather, it testi½es to a decline in the be-
hidden, sometimes, rather than obvious; lief that there is something called art.
consoling, not troubling; indestructible,
as in art, rather than ephemeral, as in 3
nature. Beauty, the stipulatively uplifting Even when Beauty was an unquestioned
kind, perdures. criterion of value in the arts, it was
de½ned laterally, by evoking some other
2 quality that was supposed to be the
The best theory of beauty is its history. essence or sine qua non of something that
Thinking about the history of beauty was beautiful. A de½nition of the beauti-
means focusing on its deployment in the ful was no more (or less) than a com-
hands of speci½c communities. mendation of the beautiful. When, for
Communities dedicated by their lead- example, Lessing equated beauty with
ers to stemming what is perceived as a harmony, he was offering another gener-
noxious tide of innovative views have no al idea of what is excellent or desirable.
interest in modifying the bulwark pro- In the absence of a de½nition in the
vided by the use of beauty as unexcep- strict sense, there was supposed to be an
tionable commendation and consola- organ or capacity for registering beauty
tion. It is not surprising that John Paul (that is, value) in the arts, called ‘taste,’
II, and the preserve-and-conserve insti- and a canon of works discerned by peo-
tution for which he speaks, feels as com- ple of taste, seekers after more rare½ed
fortable with beauty as with the idea of grati½cations, adepts of connoisseur-
the good. ship. For in the arts–unlike life–beauty
It also seems inevitable that when, al- was not assumed to be necessarily appar-
most a century ago, the most prestigious ent, evident, obvious.
communities concerned with the ½ne The problem with taste was that, how-
arts dedicated themselves to drastic proj- ever much it resulted in periods of large
ects of innovation, beauty would turn up agreement within communities of art
on the front line of notions to be dis- lovers, it issued from private, immediate,
credited. Beauty could not but appear a and revocable responses to art. And the
conservative standard to the makers and consensus, however ½rm, was never
proclaimers of the new; Gertrude Stein more than local. To address this defect,
said that to call a work of art beautiful Kant–a dedicated universalizer–pro-
means that it is dead. Beautiful has come posed a distinctive faculty of ‘judgment’
22 Dædalus Fall 2002
with discernable principles of a general taste, except for occasions that allow one An
and abiding kind; the tastes legislated by to celebrate the defeat of snobbery and argument
this faculty of judgment, if properly re- the triumph of what was once conde-
flected upon, should be the possession of scended to as bad taste. Today, good
all. But ‘judgment’ did not have its in- taste seems even more retrograde an
tended effect of shoring up ‘taste’ or idea than beauty. Austere, dif½cult ‘mod-
making it, in a certain sense, more dem- ernist’ art and literature have come to
ocratic. For one thing, taste-as-princi- seem old-fashioned, a conspiracy of
pled-judgment was hard to apply, since it snobs. Innovation is relaxation now;
had the most tenuous connection with today’s E-Z Art gives the green light to
the actual works of art deemed incon- all. In the cultural climate favoring the
testably great or beautiful, unlike the pli- more user-friendly art of recent years,
able, empirical criterion of taste. And the beautiful seems, if not obvious, then
taste is now a far weaker, more assailable pretentious. Beauty continues to take a
notion than it was in the late eighteenth battering in what are called, absurdly,
century. Whose taste? Or, more insolent- our culture wars.
ly, who sez?
As the relativistic stance in cultural 4
matters pressed harder on the old assess- That beauty applied to some things and
ments, de½nitions of beauty–descrip- not to others, that it was a principle of
tions of its essence–became emptier. discrimination, was once its strength and
Beauty could no longer be something as appeal. Beauty belonged to the family of
positive as harmony. For Valéry, the na- notions that establish rank, and accord-
ture of beauty is that it cannot be de- ed well with social order unapologetic
½ned; beauty is precisely ‘the ineffable.’ about station, class, hierarchy, and the
The failure of the notion of beauty re- right to exclude.
flects the discrediting of the prestige of What had been a virtue of the concept
judgment itself, as something that could became its liability. Beauty, which once
conceivably be impartial or objective, seemed vulnerable because it was too
not always self-serving or self-referring. general, loose, porous, was revealed as–
It also reflects the discrediting of binary on the contrary–excluding too much.
discourses in the arts. Beauty de½nes it- Discrimination, once a positive faculty
self as the antithesis of the ugly. Obvi- (meaning re½ned judgment, high stan-
ously, you can’t say something is beauti- dards, fastidiousness), turned negative:
ful if you’re not willing to say something it meant prejudice, bigotry, blindness to
is ugly. But there are more and more ta- the virtues of what was not identical
boos about calling something, anything, with oneself.
ugly. (For an explanation, look ½rst not The strongest, most successful move
at the rise of so-called political correct- against beauty was in the arts: beauty,
ness, but at the evolving ideology of con- and the caring about beauty, was restric-
sumerism, then at the complicity be- tive; as the current idiom has it, elitist.
tween these two.) The point is to ½nd Our appreciations, it was felt, could be
what is beautiful in what has not hither- so much more inclusive if we said that
to been regarded as beautiful (or: the something, instead of being beautiful,
beautiful in the ugly). was ‘interesting.’
Similarly, there is more and more re- Of course, when people said a work of
sistance to the idea of ‘good taste,’ that art was interesting, this did not mean
is, to the dichotomy good taste/bad that they necessarily liked it–much less
Dædalus Fall 2002 23
Susan that they thought it beautiful. It usually judgment of beauty (or of goodness).
Sontag
on meant no more than they thought they The interesting is now mainly a con-
beauty ought to like it. Or that they liked it, sort sumerist concept, bent on enlarging its
of, even though it wasn’t beautiful. domain: the more things that become
Or they might describe something as interesting, the more the marketplace
interesting to avoid the banality of call- grows. The boring–understood as an
ing it beautiful. Photography was the art absence, an emptiness–implies its anti-
where ‘the interesting’ ½rst triumphed, dote: the promiscuous, empty af½rma-
and early on: the new, photographic way tions of the interesting. It is a peculiarly
of seeing proposed everything as a po- inconclusive way of experiencing reality.
tential subject for the camera. The beau- In order to enrich this deprived take
tiful could not have yielded such a range on our experiences, one would have to
of subjects; and soon came to seem un- acknowledge a full notion of boredom:
cool to boot as a judgment. Of a photo- depression, rage (suppressed despair).
graph of a sunset, a beautiful sunset, Then one could work toward a full no-
anyone with minimal standards of ver- tion of the interesting. But that quality
bal sophistication might well prefer to of experience–of feeling–one would
say, “Yes, the photograph is interesting.” probably no longer even want to call
interesting.
5
What is interesting? Mostly, what has 6
not previously been thought beautiful Beauty can illustrate an ideal; a perfec-
(or good). The sick are interesting, as tion. Or, because of its identi½cation
Nietzsche points out. The wicked, too. with women (more accurately, with
To name something as interesting im- Woman), it can trigger the usual ambiv-
plies challenging old orders of praise; alence that stems from the age-old deni-
such judgments aspire to be found inso- gration of the feminine. Much of the dis-
lent or at least ingenious. Connoisseurs crediting of beauty needs to be under-
of the interesting–whose antonym is stood as a result of the gender inflection.
the boring–appreciate clash, not har- Misogyny, too, might underlie the urge
mony. Liberalism is boring, declares to metaphorize beauty, thereby promot-
Carl Schmitt in The Concept of the Politi- ing it out of the realm of the ‘merely’
cal, written in 1932 (the following year he feminine, the unserious, the specious.
joined the Nazi Party). A politics con- For if women are worshiped because
ducted according to liberal principles they are beautiful, they are condescend-
lacks drama, flavor, conflict, while ed to for their preoccupation with mak-
strong autocratic politics–and war– ing or keeping themselves beautiful.
are interesting. Beauty is theatrical, it is for being looked
Long use of ‘the interesting’ as a crite- at and admired; and the word is as likely
rion of value has, inevitably, weakened to suggest the beauty industry (beauty
its transgressive bite. What is left of the magazines, beauty parlors, beauty prod-
old insolence lies mainly in its disdain ucts)–the theatre of feminine frivoli-
for the consequences of actions and of ty–as the beauties of art and of nature.
judgments. As for the truthfulness of the How else to explain the association of
ascription–that does not even enter the beauty–i.e., women–with mindless-
story. One calls something interesting ness? To be concerned with one’s own
precisely so as not to have to commit to a beauty is to risk the charge of narcissism

24 Dædalus Fall 2002


and frivolity. Consider all the beauty becomes available over a deep, lifelong An
argument
synonyms, starting with the ‘lovely,’ the engagement with the aesthetic cannot, I
merely ‘pretty,’ which cry out for a virile venture to say, be duplicated by any
transposition. other kind of seriousness. Indeed, the
“Handsome is as handsome does.” various de½nitions of beauty come at
(But not: “Beautiful is as beautiful least as close to a plausible characteriza-
does.”) Though it applies no less than tion of virtue, and of a fuller humanity,
does ‘beautiful’ to appearance, ‘hand- as the attempts to de½ne goodness as
some’–free of associations with the such.
feminine–seems a more sober, less
gushing way of commending. Beauty is 8
not ordinarily associated with gravitas. Beauty is part of the history of idealiz-
Thus one might prefer to call the vehicle ing, which is itself part of the history of
for delivering searing images of war and consolation. But beauty may not always
atrocity a ‘handsome book,’ as I did in console. The beauty of face and ½gure
the preface to a recent compilation of torments, subjugates; that beauty is
photographs by Don McCullin, lest call- imperious. The beauty that is human,
ing it a ‘beautiful book’ (which it was) and the beauty that is made (art)–both
would seem an affront to its appalling raise the fantasy of possession. Our
subject. model of the disinterested comes from
the beauty of nature–a nature that is
7 distant, overarching, unpossessable.
It’s usually assumed that beauty is, al- From a letter written by a German sol-
most tautologically, an ‘aesthetic’ cate- dier standing guard in the Russian win-
gory, which puts it, according to many, ter in late December of 1942: “The most
on a collision course with the ethical. beautiful Christmas I had ever seen,
But beauty, even beauty in the amoral made entirely of disinterested emotions
mode, is never naked. And the ascription and stripped of all tawdry trimmings. I
of beauty is never unmixed with moral was all alone beneath an enormous
values. Far from the aesthetic and the starred sky, and I can remember a tear
ethical being poles apart, as Kierkegaard running down my frozen cheek, a tear
and Tolstoy insisted, the aesthetic is it- neither of pain nor of joy but of emotion
self a quasi-moral project. Arguments created by intense experience. . . .”1
about beauty since Plato are stocked Unlike beauty, often fragile and imper-
with questions about the proper relation manent, the capacity to be overwhelmed
to the beautiful (the irresistibly, en- by the beautiful is astonishingly sturdy
thrallingly beautiful), which is thought and survives amidst the harshest distrac-
to flow from the nature of beauty itself. tions. Even war, even the prospect of
The perennial tendency to make of certain death, cannot expunge it.
beauty itself a binary concept, to split it
up into ‘inner’ and ‘outer,’ ‘higher’ and 9
‘lower’ beauty, is the usual way that The beauty of art is better, ‘higher,’
judgments of the beautiful are colonized according to Hegel, than the beauty of
by moral judgments. From a Nietz-
schean (or Wildean) point of view, this 1 Quoted in Stephen G. Fritz, Frontsoldaten:
may be improper, but it seems to me The German Soldier in World War II (Lexington,
unavoidable. And the wisdom that Ky.: University Press of Kentucky, 1995), 130.

Dædalus Fall 2002 25


Susan nature because it is made by human
Sontag
on beings and is the work of the spirit. But
beauty the discerning of beauty in nature is also
the result of traditions of consciousness,
and of culture–in Hegel’s language, of
spirit.
The responses to beauty in art and to
beauty in nature are interdependent. As
Wilde pointed out, art does more than
school us on how and what to appreciate
in nature. (He was thinking of poetry
and painting. Today the standards of
beauty in nature are largely set by pho-
tography.) What is beautiful reminds us
of nature as such–of what lies beyond
the human and the made–and thereby
stimulates and deepens our sense of the
sheer spread and fullness of reality, inan-
imate as well as pulsing, that surrounds
us all.
A happy by-product of this insight, if
insight it is: beauty regains its solidity,
its inevitability, as a judgment needed to
make sense of a large portion of one’s
energies, af½nities, and admirations;
and the usurping notions appear ludi-
crous.
Imagine saying, “That sunset is inter-
esting.”

26 Dædalus Fall 2002

Вам также может понравиться