Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 8

REVIEW ESSAY

WILLIAM CAVANAUGH,
R ADICAL ORTHODOXY, AND
THE MYTH OF THE STATE
William T. Cavanaugh, The Myth of Religious Violence
(New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009)

Thaddeus J. Kozinski

Mythology  cannot be defeated in the more urgent. The nation-state needs the
sense that one wins over one’s opponent constant crisis of pluralism in order to
through the rigor of logic or the force enact the unum.2
of evidence; a mythology  cannot be
defeated through arguments that Nation-states are fetishes. They have
would reveal  it as groundless belief. power because people believe in the
.  .  . A mythology is utterly groundless, need for their security. They have power
hence stable. What characterizes  a because people will kill and die—
mythology  is not so much its crude or and sometimes torture—for them.
naive character—mythologies can be Christians in modernity have often
extremely complex and sophisticated— bought into a devil’s bargain in which
but, rather, its capacity to elude our the state is given control of our bodies
practices of verification and refutation.1 while the church supposedly retains our
souls. This arrangement would be bad
The nation-state is made stronger by the enough if it stopped there. But the state
absence of shared ends, and the absence cannot be expected to limit itself to the
indeed of any rational basis on which body; it will colonize the soul as well.3
to argue about ends. In the absence of
shared ends, devotion to the nation-
state as the end in itself becomes ever W illiam Cavanaugh is today’s greatest
mythbuster. In Torture and Eucharist,4
Thaddeus J. Kozinski teaches philosophy, theology, and humanities at Wyoming Catholic College and is the
author of The Political Problem of Religious Pluralism: And Why Philosophers Can’t Solve It.

136
WILLIAM CAVANAUGH, RADICAL ORTHODOXY, AND THE MYTH OF THE STATE

Cavanaugh busted the myth of torture: not spiritual aspirations; things come to repre-
a morally regrettable yet politically neces- sent freedom, status, and love. Above all,
sary tool to exact information for the sake of they represent the aspiration to escape time
state security and the common good; not “a and death by constantly seeking renewal in
merely physical assault on bodies” but a “for- created things.”9
mation of a social imagination.” As exempli- Cavanaugh’s latest book, The Myth of
fied by the Pinochet regime in Chile, state Religious Violence, is the culmination of his
torture is always a perverse liturgy offering previous mythbusting, incorporating and
sacrificial victims but precluding martyrs, extending his previous unmasking of state
and supplanting the Eucharistic sacrifice of torture, state politics, and state economics
the church. In Theopolitical Imagination,5 by completely unmasking the state itself,
Cavanaugh busted the myth of the “peace- providing a more complete and compelling
making” state. Alasdair MacIntyre, another historical, philosophical, and theological
formidable mythbuster, has written: argument. The übermythos at the heart of
the modern nation-state, and thus at the
The modern nation-state, in whatever heart of all its various economic, cultural,
guise, is a dangerous and unmanageable and political practices, is the myth of reli-
institution, presenting itself on the one gion as inherently violent, and the secular
hand as a bureaucratic supplier of goods as inherently peacemaking. Concomitant
and services, which is always about to, with this myth is the concept of religion
but never actually does, give its clients as transhistorical and transcultural, and its
value for money, and on the other as a separability from politics. These are both
repository of sacred values, which from the mythical creation and creators of the
time to time invites one to lay down nascent, modern, liberal nation-state of the
one’s life on its behalf. . . . It is like being Westphalian settlement.
asked to die for the telephone company.6 I do generally agree with and admire
Cavanaugh’s radically antiliberal historical
But, as Cavanaugh shows, it is more like revisionism and critical assessment of the
being asked to kill for the telephone company. contemporary nation-state. However, I do
The ultimate truth and holy reality is “what have some serious reservations about his con-
its members can agree is worth killing for, structive political project—what can possibly
or what they can be compelled to sacrifice replace the state, even if it is morally and
their lives for.”7 And today in the West, it is spiritually bankrupt and idolatrous? My sus-
the nation-state, not Jesus Christ, for which picion is, for Cavanaugh, nothing—and that
people are willing to suffer and cause death. this is a good thing. If Cavanaugh’s position
In Being Consumed: Economics and Christian amounts ultimately to Catholic anarchism,
Desire,8 Cavanaugh busted the myth of it is certainly not an acceptable position
consumer-capitalistic culture: not material- for anyone subscribing to Catholic social
istic at heart and productive of real wealth, teaching. I think that the great lacuna in
but a secularized perversion of the Christian Cavanaugh’s thought—a rationally plausible
spiritual quest to transcend the limits of the and genuinely Christian alternative to the
material world, and productive of nothing nation-state—may stem from his subscrip-
but “desire for desire”: “Things and brands tion to certain aspects of Radical Orthodoxy,
must be invested with mythologies, with specifically, its insufficient understanding of

137
MODERN AGE 2012

the real autonomy, though a relative and in which the overlapping jurisdictions,
circumscribed one, of philosophy. allegiances, and customs of the medieval
In the first chapter, Cavanaugh analyzes order were flattened and circumscribed
the work of nine mainstream scholars into the new creation of the sovereign
whose work incorporates and promotes the state (not always yet nation-state), a
myth of religious violence. None of them, centralizing power with a monopoly on
as Cavanaugh masterfully demonstrates, is violence within a defined territory.11
able coherently to separate religious from
secular violence. But to convince themselves In the last chapter, Cavanaugh brings his
and their readers that they can, they impose argument home, as it were, and shows the
an a priori identification of all organized uses to which the myth has been put in
violence as religious, no nationalism as reli- American foreign and domestic policy: court
gious, and all secular violence as peacemak- decisions that marginalize Christianity and
ing. Cavanaugh’s deconstruction of these idolize patriotism; military actions that
scholars is not only devastating but also demonize Muslims and angelize torture.
illuminating, for it reveals that academia is This is a superb and challenging book in
thoroughly blinded by this myth and is its which I think Cavanaugh has successfully
main propagandist. In the second chapter, “busted” the myth of the state as peace-
Cavanaugh shows that religion as commonly maker and religious-violence savior. But I
understood today, as a transhistorical and have two lingering questions about The Myth
transcultural conceptual genus, is not just of Religious Violence as well as Cavanaugh’s
incoherent but “is itself part of a particular general state-busting project. The first is
configuration of power, that of the modern, whether Cavanaugh is successful in truly
liberal nation-state as it developed in the destroying the myth of religious violence—or
West” (9). any of the myths he has tackled thus far in
In the third chapter, Cavanaugh builds his career. And this doubt has nothing to
upon and deepens his 1995 landmark essay do with Cavanaugh as a scholar. I consider
“A Fire Enough to Consume the House: The Cavanaugh’s unmasking of secular ideology
Wars of Religion and the Rise of the State,”10 to be effective and highly credible, and I
in which he argues that the modern state think that reading his work, as well as that
was instrumental in creating the mytho- of the other authors of Radical Orthodoxy, is
logical identity of man as an autonomous, vitally important for conservative theists so
atomistic “individual,” with no intrinsic and that any idols in our thinking can be recog-
constitutive ties to other men, and the main nized and summarily smashed.
catalyst for the breakup of the religious unity However, deconstructing an ideology or
of Christendom. Indeed, the state itself was smashing an idol is not the same as annihilat-
directly responsible for the violent religious ing a myth; for I think myths are much more
conflicts that, according to the myth, neces- foundational and formative, akin to the soil
sitated the centralized, “religiously neutral,” in which and by which poisonous ideology
“peacemaking” power of the state: and idols grow, and thus more insidious. And
if the myth of religious violence is the top-
The rise of the state was not necessitated soil, as it were, then the “bottomsoil” is the
by the “Wars of Religion”; rather, these myth of modernity itself. I think the work
wars were the birth pangs of the state, of Pierre Manent (who explicitly defends

138
WILLIAM CAVANAUGH, RADICAL ORTHODOXY, AND THE MYTH OF THE STATE

the nation-state) and Charles Taylor (whose but how this conversion might take place,
work presents a more complex and positive what Christians can do to bring it about, and
engagement with modernity) must be held what its political implications might be are
in dialectical tension with Cavanaugh’s; things Cavanaugh curiously sidesteps. This
both Taylor and Manent make a compelling brings me to my second reservation.
case for the inescapability of modernity and What precisely are the political implica-
the normative necessity of the nation-state, tions of Cavanaugh’s project? It is one thing
and thus a certain level of invulnerability of to dispel the mythology of the modern
their myths. Cavanaugh’s theological-cum- nation-state; it is another to dispel the state
historical-cum-sociological-cum-psycho- itself in the process. The question is whether
logical arguments unmasking the myths of Cavanaugh’s mythbusting of state violence
modernity are rigorous, compelling, erudite, does not itself do violence, intellectually
and even prophetic—but is unmasking speaking, to the state. Yes, the contemporary
enough? state is corrupt and violent, but if there is
As René Girard’s lifework has shown, ever to be a genuine, common-good com-
it takes more than rational argument to munity, organized and protected by law, not
overcome the religious myths that veil the just by voluntary, small-scale communities of
primordial murders upon which all cultures virtue with no coercive teeth, then there does
are created. The scapegoating mechanism need to be some form of state government
channels the sins of concupiscence, self- to protect such communities by creating and
righteousness, and murder into a culture- enforcing laws.
creating, disorder-dispelling, and salvation- The answer may very well be a slow, care-
offering communal ritual. God became man ful, and prudent dismantling of the leviathan,
to save us from sin, death, and the devil, but scapegoating, idolatrous nation-state; but
the scapegoating ritual closely resembles the the end of this cannot be a stateless society!
culminating apotheosis of this unholy trin- What we need are human-scale, tradition-
ity, and we need to be saved from this ritual homogeneous, genuinely political states that
by first becoming aware of it. By the incarna- can actually embody and effect a nature-
tion, crucifixion, death, and resurrection of perfecting common good open to and per-
Christ, the blinders have been removed, as vaded by the Divine. Both Cavanaugh and
we are redeemed from scapegoating through MacIntyre, however, seem to want nothing to
scapegoating—in realizing, for the first time do with any kind of state, even a small-scale
in history, the innocence of Him whom we state embodying and informed by nonliberal
have pierced. political and economic practice and theory.
Cavanaugh writes, “The myth of religious Is this because any state in the modern world
violence can only be undone by showing that would still owe its origin and identity to the
it lacks the resources to solve the very prob- modern liberalism they both detest?
lem it identifies” (7). But if Girard is right, For Cavanaugh to render his state-hate
to unveil and overcome the state’s seductive, credible and ethical for readers, he must pro-
secret scapegoating, it is not enough to expose vide good answers to these questions: Why
its mythical veil; the state at its very heart precisely is the nation-state incompatible
must be converted, redeemed, and trans- with genuine political activity? MacIntyre,
formed. Only the power of the gospel can do for example, explains his rejection of the
this, as both Girard and Cavanaugh insist, nation-state in quantitative terms, with its

139
MODERN AGE 2012

great size precluding it from embodying a civil liberties. . . . For the contemporary
consensus on a particular tradition of ratio- state could not adopt a point of view on
nality and conception of the good; but he the human good as its own without to a
also speaks in qualitative terms, suggesting significant degree distorting, degrading
that it is the state’s complex, bureaucratic and discrediting that point of view. It
structure that prevents it from performing would put those values to the service of
genuine political activity. its own political and economic power
If size, however, is not the essential prob- and so degrade and discredit them.12
lem, could the nation-state embody genuine
political activity in the event of a nation- If the state is as amoral a structure as
wide consensus on a particular conception of MacIntyre and Cavanaugh claim it to be, it
the good? If a nation-wide consensus is too is not clear why its “neutrality is never real”;
much to ask, could a state embody good pol- for why could the desired neutrality not
itics if its size and scope were small enough be produced in an essentially morally neu-
to procure a real consensus, yet larger than tral structure? If state neutrality cannot be
the local, politically anemic communities he effected, does this suggest that the state is an
and MacIntyre prescribe? The fundamental essentially moral entity? If the state’s com-
question is whether there is something essen- plexity and bureaucracy render it impervious
tially and irredeemably antipolitical about to being infused with moral substance, then
the modern state, regardless of accidental how could it ever manage to behave in the
differences like size, scope, and complexity, morally nonneutral manner they both claim
whether the political model of the nation- it inevitably does?
state is necessarily bound up with the errors In any case, there seems no reason not
and defects of modern, post-Enlightenment to attempt to shape the state’s nonneutral-
thought and culture. ity in accordance with a true conception of
Cavanaugh does not provide adequate the good by working to lessen its size and
answers to these important questions. For complexity in order to make it more ame-
example, his judgment that the modern state nable to moral influence and embodiment;
cannot embody a genuine politics is based on one could begin with the state’s more modest
his notion of the modern state’s incapacity and accommodating embodiments, such as
to embody conceptions of the good. But on local and municipal governments. In short,
examination, this notion is confusing. On it does not seem reasonable to abandon a
the one hand, Cavanaugh and MacIntyre potentially harmful agent of such immense
insist that the state should not embody a con- power to its own anarchic whims, as it were,
ception of the good; but on the other, they foregoing even the attempt to infuse it with
admit that the state cannot help but embody and direct it to moral goods. If the expla-
some particular conception of the good. In nation for the inevitably moral bias of the
MacIntyre’s words: state is that it is structurally and irreversibly
immoral, then this severe judgment requires
Even though that neutrality is never real, both an adequate philosophical explanation
it is an important fiction, and those of and historical demonstration, neither of
us who recognize its importance as well which Cavanaugh provides.
as its fictional character will agree with I wonder if the absence of clear answers to
liberals in upholding a certain range of these vital questions stems from Cavanaugh’s

140
WILLIAM CAVANAUGH, RADICAL ORTHODOXY, AND THE MYTH OF THE STATE

association with Radical Orthodoxy. I work, an implication even of the


myself find much to commend in this move- inevitable liberalism of philosophy itself.14
ment, but I also see some things to criticize,
and even to condemn. For example, John I must say I am sympathetic with Milbank’s
Milbank’s critique of liberal, globalist capi- critique of MacIntyre here. Milbank charac-
talism is top-notch, yet his understanding of terizes his own project as “a temeritous attempt
the character of philosophy and its relation to radicalize the thought of MacIntyre”15 and
to theology is problematic, and insofar as MacIntyre’s project does require radicalizing.
Cavanaugh’s political analysis stems from As Tracey Rowland has written:
or is sympathetic to this understanding, it is
bound to be deficient. MacIntyre’s work alone does not,
For Milbank, philosophy itself, however however, provide a comprehensive
radical, cannot mount an effective critique of post-modern Augustinian Thomist
liberalism and the modern state because it is critique of the culture of modernity and
limited by its own methodology; its abstract- understanding of the role of culture in
ness and formalism prevent it from making moral formation. For this it is necessary
the kind of substantive and content-rich to venture beyond the boundaries of
moral and theological judgments that could philosophy to the realm of theology. This
expose liberalism’s bankruptcy and present a is because the culture of modernity and
viable alternative to the modern nation-state. its practices have been formed not only
Even MacIntyre’s deeply anti-Enlightenment by the severance of the orders of faith and
theory of tradition-constituted rationality is reason, but also, more fundamentally, by
much too abstract and formal, for Milbank, those of nature and grace. . . . Although
to grasp effectively alternative conceptions of MacIntyre has examined the failure of
rationality and virtue incommensurable in the Enlightenment’s attempt to construct
formative content: “Virtue, dialectics, and a conception of human flourishing upon
the notion of tradition in general” are not an allegedly theologically disengaged
adequate to defeat liberalism, because there rationality, he has not examined the
are no “arguments against nihilism of this theological counterpoint to this project,
general kind.”13 For Milbank, any attempt namely, the attempted severance of the
to refute liberalism using a “content-free” orders of nature and grace.16
methodology is akin to using liberalism to
attack liberalism: The problem is, as Milbank rightly char-
acterizes it, a strictly philosophical approach:
The tradition-specific content that one “I approach social theory finally as a theo-
pours into this container [“a general logian, while he approaches it as a philoso-
conception of the structure of an pher. The key point at issue here is the role
ethics of virtue and its accompanying that must be accorded to Christianity and
psychology”] cannot easily come under Christian theology.”
discussion by MacIntyre because it Although Milbank is justified in saying
does not fall within the purview of that reluctance to utilize the resources of
philosophy as he understands it. Thus theology renders certain fundamental argu-
at the philosophic level, an air of non- ments against liberalism less effective than
commitment hovers over MacIntyre’s they could be, if Milbank is implying that

141
MODERN AGE 2012

what is required to defeat liberalism is the analysis on its own terms absorbed into an
wholesale supplanting of philosophy by theol- all-encompassing theological rhetoric. And
ogy, he is moving dangerously close to a kind I think that the unanswered questions we
of fideistic, theological totalitarianism. have seen in Cavanaugh are the result of a
If Milbank is correct in claiming that all philosophical deficiency in his project.
traditions are grounded primarily in mythos, Ironically Cavanaugh’s proposed solu-
not logos (though he is not saying that mythos tion bears a striking similarity to prag-
excludes logos), and that rational argument is matic liberalism (Jeffrey Stout and Gary
inextricably bound up with rhetorical per- Gutting18) in its rejection of the capacity
suasion and subordinate to it, then any proj- for a rational defense of a tradition to
ect aiming at the articulation of a rationally those outside it, and thus the rejection of a
persuasive argument for a tradition-diverse natural-law-embodying-and-upholding state.
audience, that is, any philosophical project Both Cavanaugh and Milbank absolutize
with live democratic political implications, Christian tradition to such an extent that it
must fail. Such a project could only serve to makes rational evaluation and adjudication
perpetuate the violent and nihilistic mythos of the claims of one’s own tradition and rival
of modern “secular reason.” Only the articu- claims between traditions impossible, and it
lation of an alternative mythos, grounded in tends to minimize the need for a provision-
the rational “ungroundedness” of Christian ally “tradition-neutral” (insofar as that is
theology, would suffice: possible) public space for such adjudication
to take place and eventually issue in real
One’s only resort at this juncture, other political instantiations of Christian truth and
than mystical despair, is to return to practice. If a morally grounded political order
the demonstration that nihilism, as an in a tradition-pluralistic society were at all
ontology, is also no more than a mythos. possible, perhaps only as the first step toward
To counter it, one cannot resuscitate a genuinely Christian politics where the
liberal humanism, but one can try to put church would not be relegated to the status
forward an alternative mythos, equally of a merely natural and human community,
unfounded, but nonetheless embodying the theological antiliberalism of Cavanaugh
an “ontology of peace,” which conceives could not articulate its blueprint, as it would
differences as analogically related, rather presuppose the capacity of intertraditional
than equivocally at variance.17 rationality.
I have not the space here to consider all the
Yet, Milbank’s project, insofar as it problems of those aspects of Cavanaugh’s
privileges mythos over logos and rhetoric over constructive project that seem, prima facie,
dialectic, cannot give and, as far as I can anarchist; but suffice it to say, if it is anar-
tell, has not given a persuasive philosophical chist, it contradicts the political philosophy
account of the why and how of such a radi- and theology first articulated authoritatively
calization; the supplanting or at least down- in explicit terms by Leo XIII and continued
playing of moral and political philosophy by by all subsequent popes. Benedict XVI has
theology may be philosophically defensible, in no way advocated a secular, state-centered
but Milbank does not provide an adequate liberal democracy as the perennial political
philosophical defense of it. It is a purely theo- ideal for Christians, but he certainly has
logical one with any genuine philosophic not condemned nation-state politics tout

142
WILLIAM CAVANAUGH, RADICAL ORTHODOXY, AND THE MYTH OF THE STATE

court—on the contrary, in Caritas in Veritate the modern state is the Antichrist, I think
the pope advocates the creation of a state we can see that what is needed in our time
institution to help govern not only the nation to combat successfully dehumanizing and
but the global community. violent myths and institutions of any sort is
Certainly, Christians must reject the neu- a politically influential, robustly corporeal,
tered, privatized, individualized, and dis- and truly mystical—because not ­mythical—
embodied church the myth-intoxicated and body of Christ, with the authority and power
ever-expanding, anti-Christian secular state to tame and tutor today’s mythical regimes
demands. But even if we do not all agree that under the easy yoke of Christ.

1 Linda Zerilli, “Doing without Knowing: Feminism’s Politics of the Ordinary,” Political Theory 26, no. 4 (August, 1998): 443,
quoted in William Cavanaugh, The Myth of Religious Violence (Oxford University Press, 2009), 6.
2 William T. Cavanaugh, “From One City to Two: Christian Reimagining of Political Space,” Political Theology 7, no. 4 (2006):
306.
3 William T. Cavanaugh, Torture and Eucharist: Theology, Politics, and the Body of Christ (Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 1998),
195–96.
4 Ibid.
5 William T. Cavanaugh, Theopolitical Imagination: Discovering the Liturgy as a Political Act in an Age of Global Consumerism
(New York: T&T Clark, 2002).
6 Alasdair MacIntyre, “A Partial Response to My Critics,” in After MacIntyre: Critical Perspectives on the Work of Alasdair
MacIntyre, eds. John Horton and Susan Mendus (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1994), 303.
7 Carolyn Marvin and David W. Ingle, “Blood Sacrifice and the Nation: Revisiting Civil Religion,” Journal of the American
Academy of Religion 64, no. 4 (Winter 1996): 767, quoted in Cavanaugh, Myth of Religious Violence, 118.
8 William T. Cavanaugh, Being Consumed: Economics and Christian Desire (Grand Rapids: Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing
Company, 2008).
9 Ibid., 48.
10 William T. Cavanaugh, Modern Theology (1995) 2:4, 397–420.
11 William T. Cavanaugh, “Beyond Secular Parodies” in Radical Orthodoxy: A New Theology, ed. John Milbank, Graham Ward,
Catherine Pickstock (London: Routledge, 1998), 191.
12 Alasdair MacIntyre, “Toleration and the Goods of Conflict,” in The Politics of Toleration in Modern Life, ed., Susan Mendus
(Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1999), 143.
13 John Milbank, Theology and Social Theory: Beyond Secular Reason (Oxford: Blackwell, 1993), 327.
14 Ibid., 329.
15 Ibid., 327.
16 Tracey Rowland, Culture and the Thomist Tradition after Vatican II (London: Routledge, 2003), 6.
17 Ibid., 279.
18 Jeffrey Stout, Democracy and Tradition (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2004); Gary Gutting, Pragmatic Liberalism and
the Critique of Modernity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999).

143

Вам также может понравиться