Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 5

book reviews | 323

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/bjaesthetics/article-abstract/50/3/323/48207 by Universidad de los Andes user on 12 December 2018


Beauty
roger scruton
oxford university press. 2009. pp. xi + 223. £10.99
(hbk).
In chapter 1 of his book on beauty Roger Scruton dis-
tinguishes two concepts of beauty. ‘In one sense
“beauty” means aesthetic success, in another sense it
means only a certain kind of aesthetic success’ (p. 16).
The kind in question is that sort of beauty which, as
Scruton puts it, takes our breath away, and he gives as
examples ‘Botticelli’s Birth of Venus, Keats’s Ode to a
Nightingale or Susannah’s aria in the garden in
Mozart’s The Marriage of Figaro’ (p. 16). One sees his
point. But he is not really concerned with this type of
beauty; his main concern lies with beauty ‘in its gen- Kant y páginas
que le dedica al punto
eral sense, as the subject-matter of aesthetic judge- de vista de Kant en la
belleza y el interés
desinteresado y el
ment’ (p. 17). Concerning this sense of the term placer.

‘beauty’, Scruton is attracted to a Kantian view and


devotes a few pages to exploring Kant’s view on
beauty and disinterested interest and pleasure (pp.
26–33). His remarks here in support of Kant’s posi-
tion are inconclusive, as they would have been had he
spent a great deal longer on them, since, as Scruton
acknowledges, Kant’s view are inevitably controver-
sial (p. 33). Indeed, Scruton goes on to say that he does
324 | book reviews

not want to claim that Kant’s views here are right— apart and untouchable has been defiled . . . [For the
they just form a useful starting point for reflection on jilted lover, what] was most beautiful to him has been
the concept of beauty (p. 33). This is all to the good: spoiled’ (pp. 52–53). And beauty involves, in the case

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/bjaesthetics/article-abstract/50/3/323/48207 by Universidad de los Andes user on 12 December 2018


too often in philosophy one fails to see the wood, the of human beings, so Scruton claims, the sense of the
overall view or outlook, for the trees, the detail of in- ‘transcendental subject’ (p. 53), or ‘the soul, the
dividual arguments, which are unlikely to accepted psyche, the self’ (p .51). Beauty in a human being is
anyway if one does not find oneself in sympathy with not just, or not really, the beauty of a body but the
the general view being offered—and so going straight beauty of the person as embodied (p. 47). Hence De ahí / por lo tanto

for the big picture has a lot to be said for it. In Scruton’s Scruton can write that ‘sexual interest, the sense of
case, the big picture involves, amongst other things, beauty and reverence for the sacred are proximate
the idea of the sacred and the desire to feel at home in states of mind, which feed into one another and grow
the world: from a common root’ (p. 57).
I suppose that it will be partly or evenly largely a
We can wander through this world alienated, re-
matter of temperament whether Scruton’s overall
sentful, full of suspicion and distrust. Or we can
view looks plausible to you, or even whether you want
find our home here, coming to rest in harmony
it to look plausible. It is built partly on an understand-
with others and ourselves. The experience of
ing of sexual desire which is, in my view, false—or,
beauty guides us along the second path: it tells us
more exactly, confuses sexual desire with erotic love.
that we are at home in the world, that the world
For Scruton claims that sexual desire is determinate:
is already ordered in our perceptions as a place
fit for the lives of beings like us. But . . . beings [T]here is a particular person that you want. Peo-
like us become at home in the world only by ac- ple are not interchangeable as objects of desire,
knowledging our ‘fallen’ condition. . . . Hence even if they are equally attractive. You can desire
the experience of beauty also points us beyond one person, and then another—you can even de-
this world, to a ‘kingdom of ends’ in which our sire both at the same time. But your desire for
immortal longings and our desire for perfection John or Mary cannot be satisfied by Alfred or
are finally answered. . . . [T]herefore, the feeling Jane: each desire is a desire specific to its object,
for beauty is proximate to the religious frame of since it is a desire for that person as the individual
mind, arising from a humble sense of living with that he is. (p. 44)
imperfections, while aspiring towards the highest
But while that may be true of erotic love or a sexual
unity with the transcendental. (pp. 174–175)
desire which otherwise expresses a concern or care
It is not entirely clear how this view fits in with Scru- for the other, this is surely not true of all sexual desire:
ton’s earlier remark that beauty can be, amongst other someone looking at pornography wants one or other of
things, disturbing, profane, and chilling (p. ix), but let those people represented, as Scruton knows (p. 185).
us leave that aside. The connection between beauty If you say that even in such a case the person in ques-
and the religious had, in any case, already come out tion has a different desire for each person he sees, then
earlier in the book, through reflection on the relation you are surely missing part of what pornography is
between human beauty—the topic of chapter 2—and about and one of the things that makes it so troubling.
the sacred. Scruton’s thought here finds its root—or, In any case, Scruton seems to admit this point when he
Aquí encuentra
su raíz at any rate, one of its roots—in the experience of grants that ‘[t]here is a distinction, familiar to all of us,
sexual jealousy: the amante
jiltedabandonado
lover feels that his former between an interest in a person’s body and an interest
beloved has become ‘polluted or desecrated. . . . This in a person as embodied’ (p. 47) . But if you are inter-
phenomenon parallels the sense of desecration
profanación
that ested in a person’s body, as the consumer of pornog-
attaches to the misuse of holy things. Something held raphy is, then you are still experiencing sexual desire,
book reviews | 325

of course, but one that precisely is not focused on this would not be better conveyed in some other way, a
individual. Further, cases such as the sex-starved pris- way in which the content did not come up against the
oner who longs for a woman surely cannot be accom- form or style so markedly. For one of the things with

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/bjaesthetics/article-abstract/50/3/323/48207 by Universidad de los Andes user on 12 December 2018


modated by Scruton’s view, since the prisoner both which Scruton is grappling at least some of the time,
has a sexual desire and wants some woman or other: his implicitly and at a level just below the surface of the
desire is not one for a given individual. Scruton could text, is how he could articulate his view in the terms
deny the prisoner has a genuine sexual desire, but that available in contemporary philosophy. In my view, it
looks wildly implausible. In truth, Scruton is not really is clear that Scruton’s range of emotional and spiri-
telling what sexual desire is, but what it ought to be tual sympathies, his sense of the human condition,
(he later calls this desire ‘normal desire’, p. 159): and the range of concepts to which he would like to
appeal, burst the bounds of what is available in phi-
Humanity is a kind of extended rescue opera-
losophy to such a degree that he shows, not only the
tion, in which drives and needs are lifted from
richness and complexity of his own mind and tem-
the realm of transferable appetites, and focused in
perament, but also the limitations of that philosophy.
another way, so as to target free individuals, sin-
All of this connects in various complicated ways
gled out and appreciated as ‘ends in themselves’.
with Scruton’s claim that the pursuit of beauty and the
(p. 46)
pursuit of truth can come into conflict: ‘The love of
In reality, sexual desire can be (I do not say always is) myths, stories and rituals, the need for consolation
transferable—but erotic love is not. It is as if Scruton and harmony, the deep desire for order all have drawn
is telling us that we should always be vigilant that our people to religious beliefs regardless of whether those
sexual desires be ‘rescued’ from their nature as drives beliefs true’ (p. 3). Scruton is walking on shaky ground
and needs and transformed at every point into forms here, and he knows it. It is hard to resist the thought
of love. There is something lovely in that view—as that underlying Scruton’s view is a horrible fear that a
there is in so much of what Scruton says in this book— kind of Schopenhauerean–Nietzschean view of things
but it seems to me clear that he is not providing a phil- might be right, and that one has to find ways of avert-
osophical analysis of the way the world is, but telling ing one’s gaze. The experience of beauty helps us do
us how he would like it to be. this. Scruton is, so far as one can tell on the evidence
Be that as it may, Scruton’s view of the connection presented here, one of the disinherited minds that Er-
between beauty, sexual desire, and the sacred repre- ich Heller so acutely analysed: a mind longing for faith
sents not something that could possibly be arrived at in a world hostile to belief and divided in itself be-
by any argument, let alone one of the kind that (ana- tween a remorseless intellect which tells us ‘that we
lytic) philosophers like to employ. And, in truth, are not very reliably at home/in the interpreted world’
Scruton is not really articulating an argument at these as Rilke has it (Duino Elegies, ‘First Elegy’) and a soul
points in his book so much as conveying a world- that wants to believe otherwise.
view, a general outlook on things. It is, as I have al- If we were to believe ourselves at home in the
ready suggested, a lovely view, even noble in its world, then the experience of the beauty of the natu-
aspiration, and one must be grateful to Scruton for ral world might help and Scruton devotes his third
articulating it, but one wonders whether something chapter to such beauty. As Scruton writes: ‘The expe-
that goes by the name of ‘philosophy’ is really the rience of natural beauty . . . contains a reassurance that
best way of conveying this view. Those who look for this world is a right and fitting place to be—a home in
tight argument in the style of analytic philosophy will which our human powers and prospects find confir-
be disappointed, I think, and those others, such as mation’ (p. 65). Having dismissed the attempt by the
myself, who are sceptical about that kind of argument ‘Marxist tradition’ (p. 62) to suggest that the experi-
from the first, will wonder whether Scruton’s view ence of natural beauty is really a matter of interpreting
326 | book reviews

the natural world in ‘bourgeois’ terms, and having interesting and profound remarks about the point of
made one or two remarks about the notion of the sub- art: ‘Art answers the riddle of existence: it tells us why
lime, Scruton again suggests a connection between the we exist by imbuing our lives with a sense of fitting-

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/bjaesthetics/article-abstract/50/3/323/48207 by Universidad de los Andes user on 12 December 2018


beautiful and the sacred by saying that reflection on ness’ (p. 128). He gives Schubert’s Winterreise as an
the beauty of the natural world ‘raises, for us, the root example: when rejected in love one can, says Scruton,
question of theology, namely, what purpose does this through this music, come to see one’s loss as necessary,
beauty serve?’ (p. 78). Of course, it is true that one as a form of suffering that is no longer arbitrary. This,
can be struck by the gratuitousness of the beauty of he says, is consoling.The point is elusive but wonderful
the natural world, but one might think nonetheless and I cannot do justice to it here. Suffice it to say
that it serves no purpose at all, even if we have a ten- that it provides, surely, the best short commentary on
dency to think it does. Scruton could say that it is Nietzsche’s claim that ‘Only as an aesthetic phenomenon
God’s purpose, and I cannot help feeling that this is is [sic] existence and the world eternally justified’ that
what he wants to say but cannot quite bring himself to is not a commentary on that claim. Or, at any rate,
say—here, in this context, at any rate. It is odd, in any one’s own existence and world.
case, that he does not explore at this point some of the In chapter 6 Scruton is worried about the justifica-
profound things that, for example, Simone Weil has to tion of judgements of taste and the question of objec-
say about natural beauty, which she thinks of as God’s tivity, but the chapter, though suggestive, is too brief
trap or snare (piège) for us, and its connection with the to deal with the matter in any detail. In any case, this
religious sensibility. issue, along with the parallel issue in ethics concerning
Chapter 4 of the book continues the theme con- the objectivity of moral judgements, seems to me to
cerning how we might find ourselves at home in the be badly misconceived by philosophers, who are
world, pointing out ways in which ordinary, everyday haunted in this area by the image of empirical claims,
attention to aesthetic matters—the design of doors, wanting the same kind of certainty in ethics and aes-
buildings and furniture, the planting and design of gar- thetics as there is there (hence, for example, the com-
dens, the setting of the table for a meal, and so on— parison between the colours of objects and moral and
can contribute to this. Chapter 5 rehearses some aesthetic properties, which Scruton, along with many
well-known distinctions in aesthetics—content and other philosophers, appeals to (p. 143)). But if I am
form; representation and expression—serving as a sure, as I am, that the music of Bach is greater than that
kind of swift introduction to these topics. In addition, of U2, to take one of Scruton’s examples (p. 133),
Scruton suggests that we can only really explain artis- what does it do for me if I insist, or claim that I have a
tic meaning through connecting works of art to human philosophical argument to show, that this is because
action, life, and emotion. This will sometimes be ‘[b]eauty is . . . firmly rooted in the scheme of things’
through figurative language—metaphor, simile, per- (p. 147)? If you cannot hear the wonder of Bach’s
sonification, and so on (pp. 123–124)—and some- work and prefer U2, then my having that conviction
times through placing ‘two things side by side, using about the scheme of things will do nothing to get you
no figure of speech, but simply letting the experience to hear things otherwise: only listening carefully, com-
of one leak into the experience of other’ (p. 124). paring, discussing, and so on, will do that, if anything
There is, in my view, much plausibility in this, and, does, as Scruton points out (pp. 137–140). But if you
indeed, I would be inclined to say that Scruton himself come to agree with me after all, then nothing is
does this kind of thing a great deal when he is explor- achieved by saying that now, at last, you are properly
ing the relation between the beautiful and the sacred— responsive to the scheme of things: that is just a round-
which is partly why I said earlier that he is not really about way of saying that you agree with me, for good
offering an argument for his view (in one sense at least reasons, that Bach’s music is greater than that of U2.
of the term). Chapter 5 also contains some extremely This is not to deny that one can say that it is true that
book reviews | 327

Bach is greater than U2. It is to resist a philosophical and kitsch by which we are surrounded in modern
construal of what that is, which is, I think, little more culture, but also a sense that modern people love
than an intellectual enterprise on my part to convince desecrating their world. There is, beneath Scruton’s

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/bjaesthetics/article-abstract/50/3/323/48207 by Universidad de los Andes user on 12 December 2018


me, and those who agree with me, that we are right. It optimistic, rather upbeat Kantian-inspired talk of us as
is a form of self-reassurance which is, as Adorno free, rational beings, a melancholy, gloomy, suspicious,
pointed out, the kind of thing that philosophy, in its even somewhat misanthropic attitude towards human
best forms, should aim to undermine. beings. This is not a criticism, but somehow or other
Chapter 7 returns to the relation between art, sex- one feels that Scruton has not made his peace with
uality, and beauty, containing a delightful short discus- these conflicting attitudes. That is probably one of the
sion of the nude in art, and making some comments things that makes him the kind of philosopher whose
on soft pornography. Chapter 8, the penultimate chap- work is most emphatically worth reading.
ter before the few concluding thoughts in chapter 9, is Christopher Hamilton
a kind of manifesto of culture, defending once again King’s College London
the ideas of the sacred and the beautiful, and express- christopher.hamilton@kcl.ac.uk
ing not only contempt for the seemingly limitless trash doi:10.1093/aesthj/ayq013

Вам также может понравиться