Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 7

Syst. Biol.

56(2):295-301,2007
Copyright (?) Society of Systematic Biologists
ISSN: 1063-5157 print / 1076-836X online
DOI: 10.1080/10635150701317401

Foundational Issues Concerning Taxa and Taxon Names


MARC ERESHEFSKY
Department of Philosophy, University of Calgary, 2500 University Drive, NW Calgary, Alberta T2N1N4, Canada; E-mail: ereshefs@ucalgary.ca

Abstract.—In a series of articles, Rieppel (2005, Biol. Philos. 20:465-487; 2006a, Cladistics 22:186-197; 2006b, Systematist
26:5-9), Keller et al. (2003, Bot. Rev. 69:93-110), and Nixon and Carpenter (2000, Cladistics 16:298-318) criticize the philo-
sophical foundations of the PhyloCode. They argue that species and higher taxa are not individuals, and they reject the view
that taxon names are rigid designators. Furthermore, they charge supporters of the individuality thesis and rigid desig-
nator theory with assuming essentialism, committing logical inconsistencies, and offering proposals that render taxonomy
untestable. These charges are unsound. Such charges turn on confusions over rigid designator theory and the distinction
between kinds and individuals. In addition, Rieppel's, Keller et al.'s, and Nixon and Carpenter's proposed alternatives
are no better and have their own problems. The individuality thesis and rigid designator theory should not be quickly
abandoned. [Individuals; kinds; PhyloCode; rigid designators; species; taxa; taxon names.]

In the 1960s and 1970s, Ghiselin (1966, 1974) and more essential properties. Those properties are qualita-
Hull (1976, 1978) wrote a series of articles suggesting tive or intrinsic properties of organisms, not relational

Downloaded from http://sysbio.oxfordjournals.org/ by guest on October 19, 2014


that species and higher taxa are individuals and that properties among organisms. In the last 50 years, many
taxon names are rigid designators. Many systematists philosophers and biologists have argued that species are
adopted Ghiselin and Hull's suggestions (Eldridge, 1985; not kinds with essences (Hull, 1965; Ghiselin, 1974; Mayr,
Cracraft, 1987; Ridley, 1989). Not everyone joined the in- 1976; Sober, 1980). They offer a number of arguments
dividuality camp (Farris, 1985; Ruse, 1987). In a series against species essentialism. A simple and classic one
of recent articles, Rieppel (2005,2006a, 2006b) rejects the concerns the "all and only" requirement of essentialism.
individuality thesis and its associated rigid designator Species essentialism requires the occurrence of one or
theory. He argues that taxa are not individuals but kinds, more essential properties in all the members of a species
and he maintains that taxon names are not rigid des- for the entire life of that species. Furthermore, it requires
ignators. In his articles, Rieppel addresses no less than that those essential properties occur in only the members
the philosophical foundations of taxonomy and nomen- of that species for the entire existence of life on Earth.
clature. However, his intended target is the PhyloCode Many biologists and philosophers are skeptical that this
(Cantino and de Queiroz, 2006), for he sees the indi- all and only requirement will be satisfied by all species,
viduality thesis and rigid designator theory as part of let alone by any species, given the forces of evolution
the philosophical foundation of the PhyloCode. Many (Ereshefsky, 2001). Such forces as mutation and recombi-
of Rieppel's arguments are drawn from earlier works by nation work against the occurrence of a biological trait in
Nixon and Carpenter (2000) and Keller et al. (2003). Their all the members of a species. Moreover, organisms in re-
goal is similar to Rieppel's. They attempt to undermine lated species inherit common genetic and developmen-
the PhyloCode by rejecting the individuality thesis or tal resources, causing the members of different species
expressing doubts over application of rigid designator to share similarities. Given the stringent requirements
theory to biological nomenclature. of essentialism and the confounding forces of evolu-
This paper does not argue for or against adopting the tion, species essentialism is no longer a viable systematic
PhyloCode. Instead it focuses on the foundational issues philosophy.
raised by Rieppel and others. Should we reject the thesis If species are not essentialist kinds, what is their on-
that taxa are individuals and return to an earlier concep- tological status? In the 1960s and 1970s Ghiselin (1966,
tion of taxa as kinds, as suggested by Rieppel and others? 1974) and Hull (1976,1978) wrote a series of articles cod-
Should we reject the idea that taxon names are rigid des- ifying the view that species and higher taxa are indi-
ignators? The arguments of this paper suggest that the viduals. Ghiselin and Hull draw the distinction between
answer to both questions is 'no.' In particular, this paper kinds and individuals along the lines of spatiotemporal
defends the individuality thesis and rigid designator the- restrictedness. Kinds are spatiotemporally unrestricted
ory from Rieppel's, Nixon and Carpenter's, and Keller entities. A chunk of metal is a member of the kind copper
et al.'s criticisms. so long as it has the essential atomic weight of copper,
regardless of its location in space and time. Individu-
als, on the other hand, are spatiotemporally restricted
THE ONTOLOGICAL STATUS OF TAXA entities. Consider the following contrast. Chemistry de-
Before examining Rieppel's (2005, 2006a, 2006b) and scribes various kinds of metal (copper, lead, and so on)
Keller et al.'s (2003) arguments that taxa are kinds and not and individual chunks of metal (the copper coin in my
individuals, let us review the background to this debate. pocket). Copper, the kind, can have members across the
The traditional account of kinds, dating back to Aristo- universe, but the parts of the copper coin in my pocket
tle, assumes that the members of a kind share a common must be located in a restricted space-time region to be
and unique essence. A kind's essence consists of one or parts of that chunk of metal. There are more stringent
295
296 SYSTEMATIC BIOLOGY VOL. 56

requirements on individuality in the literature; for ex- need not have traditional essential properties, so the
ample, the requirement that the parts of an individual standard criticisms of species essentialism are avoided.
must be spatiotemporally restricted and continually in- Furthermore, HPC theory allows that extrinsic relations
teracting (Ereshefsky, 2001). Hull and Ghiselin's require- play a significant role in explaining similarity among the
ment for individuality, however, is the minimal one of members of a kind. Essentialism assumes that the essence
spatiotemporal restrictedness. of a kind is an intrinsic property of a kind's members,
Ghiselin and Hull's argument that species are spa- such as the atomic structure of gold or the DNA of tigers.
tiotemporally restricted entities turns on the assumption HPC theory recognizes that both the intrinsic properties
that species are genealogical entities. All the organisms of organisms and the extrinsic relations among organ-
in a species are connected by heredity relations—they isms cause intraspecific similarities. For example, HPC
are offspring of conspecifks, or parents of conspecifics, theory but not essentialism cites interbreeding as a cause
or both. Reproductive relations require that organisms, of similarity among the organisms of a species.
or their parts (DNA, gametes), come into contact. Such Given the virtues of HPC theory, should we adopt
contact requires that parent and offspring, or their ap- the view, advocated by Rieppel (2005,2006a, 2006b) and
propriate parts, be connected in space and time. Though Keller et al. (2003) and others, that species and higher
not every member of a species must come in contact with taxa are HPC kinds? There are considerable problems
every other member, they all must be connected to the with treating taxa as HPC kinds. Consider an underly-
same genealogical nexus. The members of a species, in ing motivation for HPC theory. The world contains many
other words, must form a spatiotemporally continuous groups of entities with similar properties. HPC theory

Downloaded from http://sysbio.oxfordjournals.org/ by guest on October 19, 2014


entity. Hence, species are individuals. The same reason- aims to give an account of such similarity clusters. This is
ing applies to higher taxa. The parts of a higher taxa, their an important project, and there may be many HPC kinds
less inclusive taxa, must be genealogically connected and in the world, but taxa are not among them. HPC's empha-
occupy a particular space-time region. Therefore, higher sis on similarity is at odds with phylogenetic approaches
taxa are individuals. to taxonomy. HPC kinds are fundamentally similarity
Here is where Rieppel (2005,2006a, 2006b) and Keller classes, whereas taxa are fundamentally genealogical en-
et al.'s (2003) argument for taxa being kinds comes in. tities. Taxa, as we shall see, are not HPC kinds.
Rieppel and Keller et al. correctly point out that there In his discussion of whether higher taxa are HPC
are other accounts of kinds besides essentialism, so the kinds, Boyd considers whether there can be non-
failure of essentialism in biological taxonomy does not monophyletic taxa (1999a :180ff.). He asks if a para-
force us to adopt Ghiselin and Hull's individuality thesis. phyletic taxon whose members are roughly similar due
Rieppel and Keller et al. cite a recent nonessentialist ac- to similar homeostatic mechanisms is an HPC kind. His
count of kinds, Boyd's (1999a, 1999b) homeostatic prop- answer is 'yes.' Boyd (1999a:182) writes: "If there are
erty cluster (HPC) theory of kinds, and argue that taxa higher taxa that are real in this way, it is important to
should be considered HPC kinds. Rieppel and Keller note that there is no particular reason to believe that
et al. are not alone in claiming that taxa are HPC kinds their homeostatic property cluster definitions will honor
(see Boyd, 1999a; Griffiths, 1999; Wilson, 1999). Accord- strict monophyly.... Thus, even if a requirement of strict
ing to HPC theory, kinds are groups of entities that monophyly is appropriate for some higher taxa, it need
share stable similarities. HPC theory does not require not be so for [the] taxa in question." So taxa as HPC
that kinds have traditional essential properties. Never- kinds can be paraphyletic. This should not rest easily
theless, the similarities among the members of an HPC with those who believe that higher taxa must be mono-
kind must be stable enough to allow for successful in- phyletic nor with those that believe that species should
duction. That is, they must be stable enough to allow be monophyletic.
us to predict with better than chance probability that a Boyd also allows that taxa as HPC kinds can be poly-
member of an HPC kind will have certain properties. phyletic. Boyd (1999a:80) discusses a "species" that arises
HPC kinds are more than groups of entities that share through multiple hybridization events. Boyd charac-
stable clusters of similarities. HPC kinds also contain terizes this species as consisting of "distinct lineages"
"homeostatic causal mechanisms" that are responsible that have "commonalities in evolutionary tendencies"
for the similarities found among the members of a kind. (1999a:80). This species contains members with various
Such homeostatic mechanisms include interbreeding, se- phenotypic and genotypic similarities, yet the species
lection factors, developmental constraints, and common is merely a collection of spatiotemporally disconnected
inheritance. Boyd writes that species are HPC kinds be- lineages. This species, in other words, is not a single ge-
cause "species are defined . . . b y ...shared properties nealogical entity. Concerning this case, Boyd concludes
and by the mechanisms (including both 'external' mech- "I do not for better or worse, hold that HPC kinds
anisms and genetic transmission) which sustain their are defined by reference to historical relations among
homeostasis" (1999b:81). Boyd (1999a) argues that higher members, rather than by reference to shared properties"
taxa are HPC kinds as well. Rieppel (2005, 2006a) and (1999a:80). For Boyd, similarity trumps historical con-
Keller et al. (2003) concur that species and higher taxa nectedness. Boyd's preference for similarity-based kinds
are HPC kinds. allows species and higher taxa to be polyphyletic. More-
over, it allows taxa to be nongenealogical and hence non-
HPC theory provides a more promising account of
historical entities.
species and higher taxa than essentialism. HPC kinds
2007 ERESHEFSKY—TAXA AND TAXON NAMES 297

HPC theory is a vast improvement over essentialism. of being properly related to a common and unique ances-
It does not attribute essential traits to taxa. Furthermore, tor, whereas all chunks of gold have the qualitative prop-
it allows that such relations as interbreeding, geneal- erty of having a certain atomic weight. When Rieppel and
ogy and frequency-dependent selection are mechanisms Keller et al. charge supporters of the individuality the-
that cause similarities among the organisms of a species. sis of essentialism they conflate origin essentialism and
However, HPC theory is not historical enough to provide qualitative essentialism. As a result, Rieppel and Keller
a proper account of species and higher taxa. The root of et al. conflate the distinction between individuals and
the problem is that HPC theory is in the business of estab- kinds. Individuals and kinds are two different types of
lishing classes of similar organisms, whereas species and ontological categories, and those categories are accom-
higher taxa are historical entities. History in HPC theory panied by different approaches to scientific explanation
may play a role in explaining similarity (for example, and taxonomy. Conflating the two rides roughshod over
that inherited genetic and developmental resources con- two distinct scientific practices.
tribute to phenotypic similarity), but HPC kinds need Consider the central ontological difference between
not be historical entities. Notice the depth of the prob- individuals and kinds. Being a part of a particular in-
lem of applying HPC theory to species and higher taxa. dividual requires having the proper causal relations to
The problem is not merely that HPC theory allows taxa the other parts of that individual. Membership in a kind,
to be paraphyletic or polyphyletic, but that HPC theory on the other hand, turns on having the proper similarity
allows taxa to be nonhistorical entities. to other members of that kind. This fundamental dif-
Let us turn to Rieppel and Keller et al.'s criticism of ference gives rise to different explanatory practices. For

Downloaded from http://sysbio.oxfordjournals.org/ by guest on October 19, 2014


the individuality thesis. Supporters of the individuality individuals, we explain both the similarity and variation
thesis deny that taxa have qualitative essences. However, among the parts of an individual by citing the causal
Keller et al. (2003) and Rieppel (2006a) argue that the indi- relations among its parts. More concretely, for a taxon,
viduality thesis entails a commitment to essentialism. On we explain both the similarities and differences among
the individuality thesis, taxa have unique evolutionary its members by citing its population structure—the rela-
origins. A monophyletic taxon, for example, consists of tions among those members (Sober, 1980; Ereshefsky and
all and only the descendents of a common and unique an- Matthen, 2005). Explanations concerning the members of
cestor. Consequently, all the members of a monophyletic kinds are quite different. For kinds, only the similarities
taxon have a common and unique ancestor. Rieppel calls among the members of a kind are explained. Consider
this "origin essentialism" (1996a:191). According to Riep- essentialism and HPC theory. Those accounts cite mech-
pel and Keller et al., the individuality thesis assumes anisms, either essences or homeostatic mechanisms, to
rather than avoids essentialism. Thus, Rieppel charges explain the similarity among the members of a kind. No
that the individuality thesis and its associated rigid des- heterostatic mechanisms are posited by kind theorists to
ignator theory of taxon names are "wedded to essential- explain differences among the members of a kind. Varia-
ism" (2006a:191). Later he writes that supporters of the tion among the members of a kind is accidental, whereas
individuality thesis are "caught in essentialism" (Riep- variation among the parts of an individual is often due
pel, 2006a: 196). Similarly, Keller et al. charge support- to the structure of the individual. For example, the sex
ers of the individuality thesis with committing "major ratio found in a species is the result of such factors as
logical inconsistencies" (2003:99). We will get to the se- inheritance systems and frequency-dependent selection.
mantics of taxon names in the next section, but first let us Theories of kinds (essentialism and HPC theory) are in
consider the charge that the individuality thesis assumes the business of explaining similarity, not variation, yet
essentialism. variation is a fundamental feature of species and higher
Rieppel and Keller et al.'s argument trades on an taxa. Theories of individuality explain both similarity
equivocation over the word "essentialism." Two types and variability.
of essentialism are being discussed, qualitative essential- Individuals and kinds are very different types of on-
ism and origin essentialism (de Queiroz, 1992). Qualitative tological entities. Yet supporters of HPC theory often
essentialism assumes that the members of a kind share a conflate the two, suggesting that individuals are just a
qualitative essence—a character that makes no reference type of kind (Boyd, 1999a:163) or that the distinction be-
to a particular time or place. Such characters are intrinsic tween kinds and individuals is "outdated" (Keller et al.,
properties of organisms. Origin essentialism asserts that 2003:93-94). To think there is no distinction between
the members of a taxon have a common and unique phy- kinds and individuals is to conflate two fundamentally
logenetic origin. Such essences are relations among or- different approaches to explanation and taxonomy. Fur-
ganisms. According to origin essentialism, membership thermore, as we have seen, Rieppel (2006a) and Keller
in a taxon depends on being a descendent of a particular et al. (2003) equate origin essentialism with qualita-
ancestor. The difference between qualitative essentialism tive essentialism and attack the thesis that taxa are in-
and origin essentialism is the difference between kinds dividuals as a form of essentialism. However, origin
and individuals as articulated by Ghiselin and Hull. For essentialism is no more qualitative essentialism than in-
instance, Hull (1976:187) writes, "[Tlhe individual-class dividuals are kinds. In sum, then, Rieppel and Keller et al.
distinction used in this paper hinges on distinguishing have not established that taxa are kinds, nor have they
spatiotemporal properties from all other properties." All shown that the individuality thesis is based on outdated
members of Diapsida share the spatiotemporal property metaphysics.
298 SYSTEMATIC BIOLOGY VOL. 56

TAXON NAMES scientific knowledge advances. In 1897, Thomson refined


The meaning of taxon names has been hotly debated Stoney's theory of electrons using his atomic theory of
in the last 15 years. Supporters of the individuality thesis electrons. Thomson's theory was subsequently falsified
(Ghiselin, 1974,1997; Hull, 1976,1978) believe that taxon and replaced by Lorentz's theory of electrons. According
names should be treated as rigid designators. Rieppel to rigid designator theor)', the word "electron" referred
(2005, 2006a) and Nixon and Carpenter (2000) disagree to the same type of scientific entity despite a change in
and argue that treating taxon names as rigid designa- associated theory. Rigid designator theory allows scien-
tors is a mistake. They also criticize supporters of the tists to talk about the same; entities while improving their
PhyloCode for adopting rigid designator theory. Before theories of those entities through empirical investigation.
turning to Rieppel, Nixon, and Carpenter's criticisms, let Nearly 40 years ago, Hull (1976,1978) suggested that
us look at the background to rigid designator theory. species names should be treated as rigid designators.
Rigid designator theory was introduced by Putnam One reason, as Rieppel (2005:271; 2006a:187) observes,
(1970) and Kripke (1972) as a response to the then ac- is that species evolve and change over time. If the mean-
cepted semantic account of scientific terms, definite de- ing of a species name is a definite description that cites
scription theory. Roughly, definite description theory a certain set of characteristics, we may find that such
holds that the meaning of a scientific term is determined a description does not apply to some members of the
by that term's corresponding theory. The meaning of species. The problem is ontological: species vary and
"electron," for example, is set by how that word func- evolve; hence, there is likely no definite description as-
tions in the appropriate scientific theory. Because the sociated with a species for the entire life of that species.

Downloaded from http://sysbio.oxfordjournals.org/ by guest on October 19, 2014


meaning of a scientific term is given by its correspond- There are also epistemological reasons why definite de-
ing theory, changes or disagreement in theory implies scription definitions are problematic for species names,
that the same term refers to different classes of entities. and these reasons are very much in line with Putnam and
According to definite description theory, when Thom- Kripke's reasons for rejecting definite descriptions. The
son and Lorentz used the term "electron" they referred type specimen, or set of specimens, chosen for a species
to different clusters of entities given their different theo- may not be statistically typical of a species. The prob-
ries of electrons. Putnam and Kripke reasoned that there lem is epistemological because the information we have
is something wrong with definite description theory, for about the species via the type specimen does not pro-
surely scientists holding different theories can neverthe- vide an accurate representation of the species. On the
less talk about the same entities. In biology, Linnaeus, other hand, if we treat a species name as a rigid designa-
Mayr, and Hennig offered different accounts of species, tor and the description of the type specimen as part of the
but arguably they talked about the same kind of entity. If species' stereotype, no such problem occurs. A species'
"species" referred to a different type of entity every time stereotype consists of the description of the species' type
a scientist introduced a new account of species, then there specimen and hypotheses about the species' attributes
would be no scientific progress on the nature of species— and contents. We might later learn that those hypothe-
there would just be multiple theories of species referring ses are inaccurate as we discover new information about
to different kinds of entities. Putnam and Kripke believed the species. Nevertheless, the species name continues to
that the meaning of a scientific term cannot be wedded to refer to the same species even though our knowledge of
its use in a particular theory; otherwise, communication the species changes.
and progress across scientific theories would falter. Following Hull, supporters of the PhyloCode (de
As an alternative, Kripke and Putnam suggested that Queiroz and Gauthier, 1992,1994; de Queiroz, 1992,1995)
scientific terms are rigid designators. According to rigid suggest an approach to higher taxa names similar to
designator theory, the meaning of a scientific term is its rigid designator theory. De Queiroz and Gauthier's mo-
referent—the entity or group of entities named by the tivation is twofold. First, they believe that taxon names
term. The meaning of the term "electron" is the total- should be defined in terms of phylogenetic relations
ity of electrons in the world. Following Putnam's (1970) rather than characters. Second, they want to increase the
account, a term is introduced via ostension using a stereo- stability of taxon names such that a taxon name will con-
type to fix that term to its referent. A stereotype is a tinue to refer to a taxon despite a change in our knowl-
putative theory about the entities in question. Stereo- edge of that taxon's characters, level of inclusiveness,
type theories include scientific theories and common be- or internal taxa. This second desire is aligned with the
liefs about those entities. Consider the history of the primary aim of rigid designator theory: stability in a
term "electron." Stoney introduced "electron" in 1891 taxon's name despite a change in knowledge concern-
using the broad description "natural units of electricity" ing that taxon. According to de Queiroz and Gauthier, a
(Hacking, 1983:83). Ideas or concepts are necessary to taxon name is attached to a particular taxon in an osten-
fix a term to a referent, and those ideas are introduced in sion event using one of several phylogenetic definitions.
the stereotype. There is no pure ostension in science in the For example, the name "Z" is fixed to a taxon using the
sense that a scientist merely points with her finger to the node-based definition "Z" refers to the least inclusive
scientific entity in question and utters a name for that en- clade containing species A and B. This is very much like
tity (we will return to this point later). The ideas cited in Kripke's and Putnam's accounts of rigid designators be-
stereotypes are often incorrect and replaced by others as cause "Z" is rigidly attached to a clade by ostension. A
2007 ERESHEFSKY—TAXA AND TAXON NAMES 299

phylogenetic definition is akin to the description of a edge of a taxon can change, yet the meaning of its name,
type specimen of a species: both are used to attach a its referent, remains the same. For Rieppel's argument to
name to a taxon. The stereotype associated with a higher be effective he needs to give a reason why a change in
taxon name includes its phylogenetic definition as well our knowledge of the composition of a taxon implies a
as hypotheses concerning the taxon's phylogeny, con- change in the meaning of that taxon's name. Otherwise,
tent, and characters. We may later learn that those hy- Rieppel is merely assuming what he wants to prove.
potheses are incorrect as we discover new information Rieppel's examples only show that he and supporters
about the taxon. Nevertheless, the taxon name continues of rigid designator theory have different intuitions con-
to refer to the same taxon even though our knowledge cerning the meanings of taxon names.
of that taxon has changed. Rieppel (2005, 2006a) provides other arguments
Rieppel (2005,2006a) and Nixon and Carpenter (2000) against rigid designator theory. One such argument, first
launch a number of criticisms of rigid designator the- launched by Nixon and Carpenter (2000) and Keller et al.
ory. Those criticisms attack both rigid designator theory (2003), is that the application of rigid designator theory
generally and its application to biological nomenclature. in the PhyloCode renders our use of taxon names insen-
Let us start with an argument strategy Rieppel uses in a sitive to empirical evidence. For example, Keller et al.
handful of examples. In each example he suggests that an (2003:101) write that "De Queiroz and Gauthier's phy-
empirical discovery concerning a taxon implies a change logenetic definitions are irrefutable a priori statements."
in meaning of that taxon's name. Consider Rieppel's ex- Keller et al. (2003:101) add that such definitions are "ana-
amples involving the discovery of synonymy (Rieppel, lytically true and hence not amenable to revision in light

Downloaded from http://sysbio.oxfordjournals.org/ by guest on October 19, 2014


2005:472; 2006a:191). Suppose two taxon names are mis- of new knowledge." Nixon and Carpenter (2000:315)
takenly assigned to two taxa, but in fact those names refer write that according to the PhyloCode, "[p] articular
to one taxon. That mistake is discovered years later and clades once named (created) are always true; these clades
the names are then considered synonymous. Rieppel as- henceforth always exist" (see also Rieppel, 2006a: 188-
serts that the recognition that two taxa are in fact one 190).
taxon implies that "a change of meaning must have oc- Contrary to such claims, rigid designator theory does
curred" (2006a: 191). In Rieppel's example, the taxon it- not turn biological taxonomy into a nonempirical, a
self has not changed, just the meaning of the names. Yet priori project. First, nothing in rigid designator theory
according to rigid designator theory, the meaning of a forces us to accept the existence of nonexistent entities.
name is just its referent, so Rieppel concludes that rigid Scientists once thought that phlogiston and caloric ex-
designator theory fails to capture the associated change isted. That is, the original stereotype theories associated
in meaning. Rieppel offers a variation on this type of with such terms assumed that phlogiston and caloric ex-
example. Suppose an empirical discovery implies that isted. The current theories associated with phlogiston
the composition of a taxon is different than previously and caloric assert that phlogiston and caloric do not ex-
thought (Rieppel, 2005,2006). Suppose we first think that ist. Similarly, nothing in rigid designator theory forces
Diapsida is part of the more inclusive taxon Reptilia, us to think that nonexistent taxa exist. Suppose a taxon
but later discover that Diapsida is not a part of Reptilia. name is applied to a group that we later discover is poly-
Our knowledge of Reptilia and Diapsida has changed. phyletic. We discover that the putative taxon is not a
Rieppel concludes that this "example shows once again clade and thus nonexistent from a phylogenetic perspec-
that the meaning of a taxon name is not exhausted by tive. Because we no longer believe that the taxon exists,
its referent,... but crucially depends on the potentially we no longer believe that the assigned taxon name refers
changing composition of a taxon" (2006a:191). Change to that taxon. Nothing in rigid designator theory forces
in composition does not imply a change in meaning on us to remain committed to the existence of a putative
rigid designator theory, so again Rieppel concludes that taxon that we later find does not exist.
rigid designator theory is inadequate. Second, Rieppel and Nixon and Carpenter employ the
Rieppel's examples are not effective counterexamples sort of examples cited earlier concerning synonymy and
to rigid designator theory. Rieppel's arguments concern- taxon composition to show that rigid designator theory
ing these examples commit the logical fallacy called beg- is insensitive to empirical evidence. In particular, they ar-
ging the question. That fallacy occurs when one attempts gue that rigid designator theory renders our use of taxon
to prove a conclusion by either implicitly or explicitly names insensitive to empirical evidence because, accord-
assuming that conclusion. Rieppel wants to derive the ing to that theory, a change in our knowledge of a taxon
conclusion that rigid designator theory is false, but he does not affect the meaning of its name. This charge, how-
derives that conclusion by implicitly assuming that rigid ever, trades on a confusion over the roles of semantics
designator theory is false. Consider his example where and epistemology in rigid designator theory. Consider
we discover that a taxon has a different composition Rieppel's example of discovered synonymy. We learn
than previously thought. Rieppel claims that this change that two taxon names refer to the same taxon. Rigid des-
in knowledge implies a change in the meaning of the ignator theory does not deny that we have learned some-
taxon's name. However, to make that claim is to implic- thing, namely that two taxon names refer to the same
itly assume that rigid designator theory is false, for rigid taxon. It does not preclude us from using that knowl-
designator theory denies that there is a change in mean- edge when we discuss those names or classify their as-
ing. Recall that for rigid designator theory our knowl- sociated taxa. Rigid designator theory merely denies that
300 SYSTEMATIC BIOLOGY VOL. 56

the referent of a scientific term, the entity itself, changes Stepping back from these details, I suspect that the
because we have attained new knowledge about it. The substantive complaint detractors of rigid designator
virtue of rigid designator theory is that it allows us to talk theory have with the PhyloCode has less to do with
about one and the same entity as our scientific knowledge general philosophical issues and more to do with
of that entity progresses. disagreements internal to biological systematics. In their
Another set of criticisms Rieppel (2006a) and Nixon criticisms of rigid designator theory and its application
and Carpenter (2000) offer against rigid designator the- to biological taxonomy, Rieppel, Keller et al, and Nixon
ory involves the process of ostension. For example, and Carpenter often focus on what Rieppel (2006a) calls
Rieppel (2006a) writes that mere ostension—the mere ut- "foundational" issues. They charge supporters of rigid
terance of a term and pointing to a type specimen—is not designator theory and the PhyloCode with adopting
sufficient to fix a term to a referent. This is quite right. essentialism, being logically inconsistent, and making
As mentioned earlier, concepts are involved in every in- taxonomy untestable. As we have seen, these philosoph-
stance of ostension in science. For example, the ostension ical charges are unsound. Nevertheless, there are impor-
of a taxon name involves such basic concepts as the no- tant disagreements between supporters and detractors
tion of being a single organism (the type specimen) and of rigid designator theory and the PhyloCode. For one,
the concept of being a monophyletic taxon. Ostension they disagree on what type of stability should be pre-
in science turns on robust background theories and as- ferred in taxonomy. For Nixon and Carpenter (2000:306),
sumptions; this is no news for rigid designator theory "[stability is measured... as the net change in terms of
for it is part of rigid designator theory. A different kind terminals originally included in a group compared to

Downloaded from http://sysbio.oxfordjournals.org/ by guest on October 19, 2014


of concern raised by Nixon and Carpenter (2000:310) is the group as defined on a new tree." Supporters of the
what they call "Accuracy in Pointing." Often the ini- PhyloCode, on the other hand, prefer keeping a taxon's
tial theoretical assumptions concerning a named entity ancestry stable (de Queiroz, 1995; Lee, 1996). Another
are found to be incorrect. Using the example of "Mam- disagreement concerns the types of features used for
mals," Nixon and Carpenter (2000) suggest that when the fixing a name to a taxon. Nixon and Carpenter and
corresponding taxon was first named, we thought that Rieppel prefer using putative synapomorphies and
the taxon contained Multituberculates. We now know homologies. Supporters of the PhyloCode prefer citing
it does not. Nixon and Carpenter (2000:310) conclude, putative phylogenetic relations. These differences have
"[t]he simple example of the case (e.g., the Mammals) in more to do with assumptions concerning the nature of
which an internal rearrangement within a clade results taxa and the types of evidence used for positing taxa
in the necessity for the name to be applied to a different than issues in the philosophy of science. Consequently,
(sub-)clade shows that this method of pointing is, simply philosophical criticisms of rigid designator theory and
put, inaccurate." They are right: ostension can be inac- its application to biological nomenclature do not address
curate, but rigid designator theory proponents are fully the substantive differences between supporters and
aware of this. That is why they believe that the theories detractors of the PhyloCode.
used during ostension, indeed during any stage of scien-
tific investigation, are provisional. This just echoes an un-
derlying motivation for rigid designator theory, namely CONCLUSION
that the theories concerning scientific entities change and The aim of this paper is not to defend a particular
progress. school of nomenclature but to address some recent ar-
Notice that the sort of inaccuracies that occur in guments concerning the philosophical foundations of
ostension occur in any approach to nomenclature. The taxonomy. Many biologists have adopted Ghiselin and
PhyloCode approach to ostension may result in inaccura- Hull's suggestions that species and higher taxa are in-
cies concerning the internal taxa of a taxon. Inaccuracies dividuals and that taxon names are rigid designators.
can also occur in the naming procedures advocated by Rieppel, Keller et al., and Nixon and Carpenter argue
Nixon and Carpenter (2000) and Rieppel (2006a). Nixon that we should drop the individuality thesis and return
and Carpenter suggest fixing a name to a taxon by using to the idea that species and higher taxa are kinds. They
a list of synapomorphies. Rieppel suggests using "rela- charge supporters of the individuality thesis with un-
tional properties that are homologies" to tie names to wittingly adopting essentialism and committing logi-
taxa (2006a:195). In either case, we can be wrong about cal inconsistencies. We have seen that such charges do
the set of characters or properties used to define a name. not stick. Moreover, we have seen that the account of
Perhaps some of the original putative synapomorphies kinds adopted by Rieppel and Keller et al., homeostatic
used to fix a name to taxon prove on further analysis not property cluster theory, emphasizes similarity over phy-
to be synapomorphies. It is common to learn that a puta- logeny, rendering homeostatic property cluster theory
tive homology is in fact a homoplasy. Fixing a name to a an inappropriate approach to species and higher taxa.
taxon via a taxonomic hypothesis, whether that hypoth- Turning to taxon names, we have seen a number of philo-
esis mentions descendents or homologies, can be inaccu- sophical charges against rigid designator theory and its
rate. Such inaccuracies are not limited to rigid designator application to taxon names. These arguments often turn
theory but are the result of a general fact about scientific on misconceptions of rigid designator theory. Further-
practice: scientists are not omniscient, so scientists often more, such philosophical criticisms do not address the
revise their initial theories concerning scientific entities. more substantive differences between supporters and
2007 ERESHEFSKY—TAXA AND TAXON NAMES 301

detractors of rigid designator theory such as the nature Ereshefsky, M. 2001. The poverty of the Linnaean hierarchy. Cambridge
of taxa and the evidence used for positing taxa. University Press, Cambridge, UK.
Ereshefsky, M., and M. Matthen. 2005. Taxonomy, polymorphism, and
This is not to say that the individuality thesis and rigid history: An introduction to population structure theory. Philos. Sci.
designator theory are perfect. No philosophical or sys- 72:1-21.
tematic theory is perfect. The philosopher Lakatos (1970) Farris, J. 1985. The pattern of cladistics. Cladistics 1:190-201.
recognized that all theories have their flaws and sug- Ghiselin, M. 1966. An application of the theory of definitions to sys-
gested that we should prefer one theory over another tematic principles. Syst. Zool. 15:127-130.
Ghiselin, M. 1974. A radical solution to the species problem. Syst. Zool.
when it is more progressive. Part of that progress is the- 23:536-544.
oretical progress, namely when a theory leads to new Ghiselin, M. 1997. Metaphysics and the origin of species. State Univer-
theoretical insights and theory development. The indi- sity of New York Press, Albany, New York.
viduality thesis has been a fruitful catalyst for systematic Gould, S. 2002. The structure of evolutionary theory. Harvard Univer-
theorizing (Eldredge, 1985; Cracraft, 1987; Gould, 2002). sity Press. Cambridge, Massachusetts.
Griffiths, P. 1999. Squaring the circle: Natural kinds with historical
Rigid designator theory has been successfully applied essences. Pages 209-228 in Species: New interdisciplinary essays
across scientific disciplines, from chemistry to physics to (R. Wilson, ed.). MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts.
biology. Though the individuality thesis and rigid des- Hacking, I. 1983. Representing and intervening. Introductory topics
ignator theory may not be perfect, they have stimulated in the philosophy of natural science. Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge, UK.
positive theoretical work in systematics and nomencla- Hull, D. 1965. The effect of essentialism on taxonomy: Two thousand
ture. The individuality thesis and rigid designator theory years of stasis. Br. Jr. Philos. Sci. 15:314-326,16:1-18.
should not be quickly abandoned. Hull, D. 1976. Are species really individuals? Syst. Zool. 25:174-191.

Downloaded from http://sysbio.oxfordjournals.org/ by guest on October 19, 2014


Hull, D. 1978. A matter of individuality. Philos. Sci. 45:335-360.
Keller, R., R. Boyd, and Q. Wheeler. 2003. The illogical basis of phylo-
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS genetic nomenclature. Bot. Rev. 69:93-110.
Kripke, S. 1972. Naming and necessity. Pages 253-355 in Semantics of
I thank Jason Anderson, Kevin de Queiroz, David Hull, Heather natural language (D. Davidson, G. Harmon, eds.). Reidel, Dordrecht.
Jamniczky, Michael Lee, Mohan Matthen, Elliott Sober, and John Lakatos, 1.1970. Falsification and the methodology of scientific research
Wilkins for their valuable comments on earlier drafts of this paper. programmes. Pages 91-195 in Criticism and the growth of knowl-
Financial support was provided by the Social Sciences and Human-
ities Research Council of Canada and the Calgary Institute for the edge (I. Lakatos, A. Musgrave, eds.). Cambridge University Press,
Humanities. Cambridge, UK.
Lee, M. 1996. The phylogenetic approach to taxonomy: Practical as-
pects. Zool. Scr. 25:187-190.
REFERENCES Mayr, E. 1976. Evolution and the diversity of life. Harvard University
Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts.
Boyd, R. 1999a. Homeostasis, species and higher taxa. Pages 141-185 Nixon, K., and J. Carpenter. 2000. On the other "phylogenetic system-
in Species: New interdisciplinary essays (R. Wilson, ed.). MIT Press. atics." Cladistics 16:298-318.
Cambridge, Massachusetts. Putnam, H. 1970. Is semantics possible? Pages 59-63 in Language, be-
Boyd, R. 1999b. Kinds, complexity and multiple realization: Comments lief, and metaphysics (H. Kiefer and M. Munitz, eds.). State Univer-
on Millikan's "Historical kinds and the special sciences." Philos. sity of New York Press, Albany, NY.
Studies 95:67-98. Ridley, M. 1989. The cladistic solution to the species problem. Biol.
Cantino, P., and K. de Queiroz. 2006. PhyloCode: A phylogenetic Philos. 4:1-16.
code of biological nomenclature version 3a. http://ohiou.edu/ Rieppel, O. 2005. Monophyly, paraphyly, and natural kinds. Biol. Phi-
PhyloCode. los. 20:465-487.
Cracraft, J. 1987. Species concepts and the ontology of evolution. Biol. Rieppel, 0.2006a. The PhyloCode: A critical discussion of its theoretical
Philos. 2:329-346. foundation. Cladistics 22:186-197.
de Queiroz, K. 1992. Phylogenetic definitions and taxonomic philoso- Rieppel, O. 2006b. The taxonomic hierarchy. Systematist 26:5-9.
phy. Biol. Philos. 7:295-313. Ruse, M. 1987. Biological species: Natural kinds, individuals, or what?
de Queiroz, K. 1995. The definition of species and clade names: A reply Br. Jr. Philos. Sci. 38:225-242.
to Ghiselin. Biol. Philos. 10:223-228. Sober, E. 1980. Evolution, population thinking and essentialism. Philos.
de Queiroz, K., and J. Gauthier. 1990. Phylogeny as a central principle Sci. 47:350-383.
in taxonomy: phylogenetic definitions of taxon names. Syst. Zool. Wilson, R. 1999. Realism, essence, and kind: Resuscitating species es-
39:307-322. sentialism? Pages 187-208 in Species: New interdisciplinary essays
de Queiroz, K., and J. Gauthier. 1992. Phylogenetic taxonomy. Annu. (R. Wilson, ed.). MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts.
Rev. Ecol. Syst. 23:499^80.
de Queiroz, K., and J. Gauthier. 1994. Toward a phylogenetic system of
biological nomenclature. TREE 9:27-31. First submitted 10 July 2006; reviews returned 5 Septmeber 2006;
Eldredge, N. 1985. Unfinished synthesis. Oxford University Press, final acceptance 28 November 2006
New York. Associate Editor: Michael Lee

Вам также может понравиться