Euthanasia has been a controversial topic for decades. It involves issues of patient rights, life and death, the proper function of doctors, the ethics of suicide, and the overlap between law and morality.
Brain Death, Coma, and Persistent Vegetative State
In 1968 , an ad hoc committee of the Harvard Medical School was set up to establish criteria for determining when someone is dead. This committee determined that someone should be considered dead if he has permanently lost all detectable brain function. This condition is now known as whole brain death and is the primary criterion used for the legal determination of death. Whole brain death is distinguished from other conditions such as persistent vegetative state (PVS). In PVS, the individual has lost all cerebral cortex function but has retained some good brain stem function. The result is that the individual in this state will never regain consciousness but can often breathe naturally and needs no artificial aid to maintain circulation. A disconcerting aspect of PVS is that patients in this state are unconscious but “awake.” In contrast, someone who is not totally brain dead but who is in a coma is unconscious but “asleep.” His or her brain stem functions poorly, and thus this person does not live as long as someone in a persistent vegetative state. If we use whole brain death criteria to determine whether someone is dead, then neither a person in a persistent vegetative state nor a person in a coma is dead. In these cases, euthanasia questions about whether to let them die can be raised. On the other hand, if someone is dead by whole brain death criteria, then disconnecting equipment is not any form of euthanasia. We cannot let someone die who is already dead.
Meaning and Types of Euthanasia
The term euthanasia has Greek roots and literally means “good death.” Euthanasia is of two types, Active and Passive euthanasia. Passive euthanasia refers to stopping or not starting some treatment and letting a patient die. The person’s condition causes his or her death. It is now a common practice and is not prohibited by law. In recent years, many doctors, as many as 96%, have withdrawn or with-held life prolonging treatment for their patients. Most of the time, this is done at the request of the patient or the patient’s family. In some cases, doctors have done this on their own either without consulting patients or their families or even against their wishes. The reasons given in either case were generally that such treatment would not extend the patient’s life for long or that the patient’s life would not be worth lengthening such as when they were not expected to regain consciousness ( cases Karen Quinlan & Nancy Curzan page 139). Active euthanasia is using certain death causing means to bring about or cause the death of a person. In the past, it used to be called “mercy killing.” Drugs are the most common means. Rather than letting a person die, these means are used actually to kill the person. This is generally regarded as much more problematic and is generally legally prohibited. Physician- Assisted Suicide This issue is related to that of euthanasia because one form “ physician-assisted suicide” is a form of suicide. In these cases, the physician does not actually inject a patient with a death causing drug as in active euthanasia, but provides patients with drugs that they will take themselves. It is thus basically a form of suicide, with the doctor providing the means to carry it out. Just as questions can be raised about whether suicide is ever morally acceptable, so also can questions be raised about whether it is morally permissible for physicians or others to help someone commit suicide. What is also different about doctor assisted suicide is that it involves doctors. It thus jumps the barrier that prevents doctors from actually doing something that will cause the death of a person. In some ways’ it looks like active euthanasia. ( case pathologist Jack Kevorkian page 141 last paragraph) Pain Medication That Causes Death One type of action may be confused with active euthanasia but ought to be distinguished from it: giving pain medication to gravely ill and dying patients. Physicians are often hesitant to prescribe sufficient pain medication to such patients because they fear that the medication will actually cause their deaths. They fear this would be considered comparable to mercy killing or active euthanasia which is legally impermissible. Some philosophers believe that the principle of double effect may be of some help here. According to the principle of double effect, it may be morally permissible to administer a drug with the intention of relieving pain (a good effect) even though we know or foresee that our action also may have a bad effect (weakening a person and risking his death). The idea behind the double effect principle is that there is a moral difference between intending to kill someone and intending to relieve pain. There is a moral difference between intending that someone die by means of one’s action (giving a drug overdose) and foreseeing that they will die because of one’s action (giving medication to relieve pain). Doing the latter is not, strictly speaking, active euthanasia. Ordinary and Extraordinary Measures Measures that are ineffective or excessively burdensome are called extraordinary by philosophers. There are other cases in which what is refused would actually be effective for curing or making a life threatening condition better. And yet decisions are made not to use these measures and to let the person to die. These measures are called ordinary, not because they are common but because they promise reasonable hope of benefit. With ordinary measures, the chances that the treatment will help are good, and the expected results are also good. Voluntary and Nonvoluntary Euthanasia In many cases, it is the person whose life is at issue who makes the decision about what is to be done. This is voluntary euthanasia. In other cases people other than the one whose life is at issue decide what is to be done. These are cases of non voluntary euthanasia. Non voluntary simply means not through the will of the individual. It does not mean against their will. Sometimes others must make the decision because the person or patient is incapable of doing so. This is true of infants and small children and a person who is in a coma or permanent vegetative state also in cases of people who are minimally competent, as in cases of senility or certain psychiatric disorders. Moral Judgments about Euthanasia One way to answer the question whether euthanasia of a certain type is morally justifiable is to use the distinction made between consequentialist theories (such as utilitarianism) and nonconsequentialist theories (such as Kant’s moral theory or natural law theory). If you think that it is the consequences rather than the nature of actions themselves that matter morally, then you can focus on those considerations. If you think that we should judge whether some action is right or wrong in itself for some reasons, then you can focus on non consequentialist considerations and reasons. The Moral Significance of Voluntariness An individual’s rights over his or her own life are highly valued. Yet there are limits to it. It is limited, for example, when it conflicts with the interests or rights of others. How important is voluntary consent? Consequentialist Considerations One major method of deciding moral right or wrong appeals to the consequences of our actions (act utilitarian) or practices (rule utilitarian). From this perspective, voluntariness matters morally only to the extent that it affects human happiness and welfare. Respecting people’s own choices about how they will die surely would have some beneficial consequences. For example, when people know that they will be allowed to make decisions about their own lives and not be forced into things against their will, then they will gain a certain peace of mind. These are the good consequentialist reasons to respect a person’s wishes in euthanasia cases. But it is not just the person who is dying who will be affected by the decision. Thus, it also can be argued that the effects on others, on their feelings, for example, are also relevant to the moral decision making. However, individual decisions are not always wise and do not always work for the greatest benefit of the person making them or for others. For example, critics of euthanasia worry that people who are ill or disabled would refuse certain lifesaving treatment because they lack or do not know about services, support, and money that are available to them. On consequentialist grounds, we should do what, is most likely to bring about the greatest happiness, not only of ourselves but also to all those affected by our actions. It does not in itself matter who makes the judgment. From the viewpoint of rule utilitarian thinking, we ought to consider which policy would maximize happiness. Would a policy that universally follows individual requests about dying be most likely to maximize happiness? Or would a policy that gives no special weight to individual desires, but which directs us to do whatever some panel decides, be more likely to have the best outcome? Or would some moderate policy be best, such as one that gives special but not absolute weight to what a person wants? An example of such a policy might be one in which the burden of proof not to do what a person wishes is placed on those who would refuse it. Non consequentialist Considerations To appeal to the value of personal freedom in euthanasia decisions is to appeal to a nonconsequentialist reason. The idea is that freedom is a good in itself and therefore carries heavy moral weight. We like to think of ourselves, as masters of our own fate. According to Kant, persons are unique in being able to choose freely, and this ought to be respected. However, in many euthanasia cases a person’s mental competence and thus autonomy is compromised by fear and lack of understanding. Illness makes a person more subject to undue influence or coercion. There is also a high correlation between suicide and depression. “The most seriously depressed patients were twice as likely to have considered suicide as all terminally ill patients. How in such instances do we know what the person really wants? These are problems which arise when we attempt to respect autonomy. ActiveVersus Passive Euthanasia The moral question about Active and Passive euthanasia is: Is there any moral difference between them? Is active euthanasia more morally problematic than passive euthanasia? Or are they on a moral par such that if passive euthanasia is morally permissible in some cases then so is active euthanasia? Is physician assisted suicide any more or less problematic than cases in which the physician actually administers the drug or uses other means to bring about death? Consequentialist Concerns If we take the perspective of the consequentialist or act utilitarian, we should only be concerned about our actions in terms of their consequences. The means by which the results come about do not matter in themselves. They matter only if they make a difference in the result. So, if a person’s death is the best outcome in a difficult situation, it would not matter whether it came about through the administration of a lethal drug dose or from the discontinuance of some life saving treatment. But, if one or the other means did make a difference in a person’s experience as when a person is relieved or pained more by one method than another, than this would count in favor of or against that method. If we take the perspective of a rule utilitarian, we would be concerned about the consequences of this or that practice of policy. Which policy would have the best result overall. Which would be the best policy? One that allowed those who were involved to choose active euthanasia, one that required active euthanasia in certain cases, one that permitted it only in rare cases, or one that prohibited it and attached legal penalties to it? Which policy would make more people happy and fewer people unhappy? People are concerned in particular about the effects of physician participation in the practice of euthanasia. Even, those who support physician assisted suicide and in some cases actual active euthanasia worry about whether these practices would be open to abuse. The names given to this argument that there would be abuse are; the “domino effect,” “wedge,” slippery slope,” “camel’s nose.” The idea is that if we permit active euthanasia in some cases, then we would slide and approve it in more and more cases until we were approving it in cases that were clearly unreasonable. Non consequentialist Concerns Arguments about the right to die or to make one’s own decision about dying are non consequentialist arguments. On the one hand, some people argue that respecting personal freedom is so important that it should override any concerns about bad results. Meaning that people should be allowed to end their lives when they choose as an expression of their autonomy or freedom, and this choice should be respected regardless of the consequences to others or even mistakes about their own cases. On the other hand, some people believe that there is a significant moral difference between killing another person or letting a person die. Killing people except in self defense is morally wrong, according to this view. Just why it is thought wrong is another matter. Reasons as to why killing is wrong are similar to those given by natural law theory, citing the innate drive towards living as a good in itself, it shouldn’t be suppressed. Kant also argues on similar grounds. Some people use religious reasons such as the belief that life and death decisions are for God and not ourselves to make. Others use reasons that rely on concerns about the gravity of ending a life directly and intentionally, that in doing so we ally ourselves with what is at best a necessary evil. Ordinary Versus Extraordinary Measures There is a disagreement about the use of these terms. If the terms mean commonness and uncommonness, then it is difficult to see how this makes a moral difference. But if the terms are defined in terms of benefit and burden, then that is relevant as these are moral terms. The question which arises is how to measure these benefits and burdens. Is financial cost to a family or society a part of the calculation? The danger of including the effect on others in the calculation and not just the benefits and burdens to the patient herself . is that we might say some people should die because the burden of taking care of them is just too great. If we know what are ordinary and extraordinary measures in a particular case, we would be able to decide whether there is good reason to provide the measures. If we judge them ordinary then they ought to be provided, if we judge them extraordinary then they probably need not be provided. Infant Euthanasia Every few years, a case of disputed life and death decisions regarding an infant seems to appear in the news. The cases which have drawn the most criticism are cases like the one in which an infant born with Down’s syndrome was left untreated and died. Down’s syndrome is a genetic anomaly that causes mental retardation and sometimes physical problems as well. In this case, the child had a repairable but life threatening blockage between the stomach and the small intestines. The parents refused permission for surgery to repair the problem, and the doctors followed their wishes and let the infant die. Critics of this case protested that this surgery was simple and effective, and the infant, although retarded, could lead a generally happy life. Not to treat in such a case has been interpreted as not using what would be considered ordinary means of life support, ordinary because the benefits to the patient would outweigh any burdens. Such cases have been criticized for their buck passing, that is, shifting responsibility for the death to nature, as though in this situation but not elsewhere in medicine we should “let nature take its nature.” Because the infant is not able to express his wishes, these will always be cases of nonvoluntary euthanasia.