Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 5

R

Richard Dawkins on Constraints on widely understood that natural selection builds


Natural Selection suboptimal adaptations because of the following
key constraints.
Laith Al-Shawaf1 and Kareem Zreik2
1
Department of Psychology, University of Time Lags
Colorado – Colorado Springs, Colorado Springs, Evolution by natural selection is a gradual, step-
CO, USA by-step process. As a consequence, organisms are
2
Department of Economics, Lebanese American adapted to past circumstances, not present cir-
University, Beirut, Lebanon cumstances. If it so happens that the environment
has not changed much, then organisms may be
well-adapted to their current environment. But if
Introduction the environment they inhabit has changed, organ-
isms can exhibit maladaptive behaviors simply
Richard Dawkins presents a nuanced take on opti- because environmental change has taken place
mality in his seminal work The Extended Pheno- faster than the slow, cumulative process of evolu-
type. Dawkins’s central argument is that tion by natural selection.
optimality is not attainable in nature because of For example, humans are adapted to a time in
constraints on the process of natural selection. He which food was scarce. As such, our species has
focuses his discussion on six key constraints: time evolved taste preferences for calorie-dense foods,
lags, historical constraints, tradeoffs (which he fat, and sugar (Buss 2015). In the calorie- and
calls constraints of costs and materials), con- nutrient-scarce environments in which we
straints due to available genetic variation, imper- evolved, these preferences were adaptive. By con-
fection due to selection operating at different trast, in modern environments with an over-
levels, and constraints due to environmental abundance of fast food, these evolved taste
unpredictability. preferences lead to obesity, type II diabetes, and
Together, these six constraints on optimality cardiovascular disease. They are no longer adap-
offer a deeper understanding of how natural selec- tive because of the discrepancy between the envi-
tion works and the kinds of outcomes it produces. ronment in which we evolved and the one we
They also help lay to rest the erroneous view that currently inhabit (Nesse and Williams 1994).
evolutionists endorse a Panglossian, pan- Stated differently, the environment has changed
adaptationist view in which every aspect of ani- too fast for selection to keep up: time lags have
mals’ bodies and brains is optimally designed. No rendered our adaptive taste preferences maladap-
credible evolutionist thinks this. Instead, it is tive in modern environments.
# Springer International Publishing AG 2018
T.K. Shackelford, V.A. Weekes-Shackelford (eds.), Encyclopedia of Evolutionary Psychological Science,
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-16999-6_2172-1
2 Richard Dawkins on Constraints on Natural Selection

Historical Constraints more robust bones but diminished capacity to flee,


History provides a second key constraint on the or enhanced capacity to flee but more vulnerable
power of natural selection. When an engineer sets bones. Some tradeoffs are simply unavoidable.
out to build something, she can always start over if The blind Mexican cavefish (Astyanax
something goes wrong in the process. By contrast, mexicanus) illustrates the same point. Over mil-
natural selection is constrained by millions of lions of years, this fish has lost its sight. One
years of history. Once a certain body plan or hypothesis for how this happened involves
nervous system is in place, certain areas of evolu- tradeoffs: the Mexican cavefish may have lost its
tionary “design space” are closed off for that eyes because vision requires energy-hungry neu-
lineage, and others are rendered less “evolvable” rons, and in a pitch-black cave it is a waste of
(Dennett 1996). In other words, the phylogenetic metabolic resources to build and maintain a visual
background of a species affects what it is capable system. In such an environment, those physiolog-
of evolving next: history constrains evolution. ical resources can be more profitably channeled
Consider the case of how jet engines super- toward something else – cell repair, immune func-
seded propeller engines (Dawkins 1999). tion, or a stronger tailfin, for example.
Designers of the first jet engine had a blank canvas The key point is that every adaptation imposes
from which to construct prototypes. This meant a cost. These costs lead to unavoidable tradeoffs –
that they were not forced to stick with any initial and if the tradeoff is truly unavoidable, then it is
mistakes or missteps they made – they were free to impossible to optimize the traits being traded off
start from scratch if needed. Moreover, in the case against one another. Because of this, tradeoffs
of humanly engineered machines, there is no need lead inexorably to suboptimal designs.
for each new step in the process to be an improve-
ment on its predecessor: our foresight enables us Available Genetic Variation
to add or change parts that have no immediate Natural selection cannot make new genes arise out
effect, but that will eventually improve the of thin air; it can only work with whatever genetic
machine’s functioning when the design is material happens to be available in a population at
complete. a given time. As a result, the availability of genetic
Natural selection has neither of these luxuries. variation is a key constraint on natural selection.
It cannot start from scratch; it can only build upon To put it differently, it is impossible for natural
what is already there – and every single interme- selection to produce an adaptation – let alone an
diate step must function better than its predeces- optimally designed one – if the relevant genes are
sor. These constraints limit the power of natural simply not present in the population.
selection to produce optimally designed mecha- It is difficult to exaggerate the importance of
nisms. The consequence is suboptimal designs this point. The selection pressure for a particular
such as the vertebrate eye, which has a blindspot trait may be exceedingly strong, but this will not
and appears to be installed backwards (Dawkins matter at all if there is no genetic variation under-
1999). Such a design is suboptimal by engineering lying that trait. No matter what other factors are in
standards – but there are limits on natural selec- place, the trait in question will not evolve unless
tion that do not exist in engineering. there happens to be genetic variation for it in the
population. An analogous constraint in human
Tradeoffs engineering would be the following: it is impos-
Every adaptation comes with a cost, and this sible to build something – no matter how badly we
makes tradeoffs inevitable. For example, gazelles need it – if we simply do not have the raw mate-
under predation pressure from wolves may evolve rials with which to build it.
longer legs, enabling them to run faster and Artificial selection on cattle illustrates this
increase their likelihood of escape. But longer point. Researchers carried out experiments in an
leg bones are more brittle and more likely to attempt to produce more heifer (female) calves
break. The gazelle thus faces a cost either way: rather than bull calves, as only heifers produce
Richard Dawkins on Constraints on Natural Selection 3

milk. However, it turned out that the genetic var- mechanism of flight to fail in a severe hurricane.
iation required for this outcome (producing more Unpredictable catastrophes can kill even the most
female offspring) did not exist, so the experi- well-adapted organisms. As Dawkins puts it, “it
menters were unable to produce the desired sex will usually be impossible to cater to every con-
ratio (Dawkins 1999). The key point is this: if the ceivable contingency of detail, and any given ani-
relevant genetic variation does not exist, the trait mal will therefore frequently be observed to make
will not evolve – no matter how long natural ‘mistakes’, which can be fatal” (Dawkins 1999).
selection operates and how strong the selection Stated differently, organisms are adapted, on
pressure is. Natural selection is unavoidably average, to the statistical conditions of their envi-
constrained by the raw material that happens to ronments. But no matter how well designed an
be available in the population at the time. animal’s flight or vision or bipedalism might be,
some environmental events are anomalous and
Imperfections at One Level Due to Selection at unpredictable. Natural selection is constrained
Another Level by this unpredictability, and cannot build biolog-
Optimality in nature is also constrained by the fact ical mechanisms that are somehow immune to
that selection at one level can lead to maladaptive random environmental accidents. Environmental
effects at another level. Dawkins describes this in unpredictability thus acts as a sixth key constraint
the following way: “selection at the level of the on the power of natural selection.
gene can give rise to apparent imperfections at the
level of the individual” (Dawkins 1999). Further Constraints: Antagonistic pleiotropy and
Heterozygous advantage provides an illustra- the conflict between survival & reproduction
tive example. In such cases, a gene may be posi- These six limits on the power of natural selec-
tively selected because of its beneficial effects tion to produce optimally designed mechanisms
when in a heterozygous state. But when in a are not exhaustive, but space considerations pro-
homozygous state, the effects of such a gene are hibit us from offering a comprehensive account of
harmful. For example, the allele for sickle-cell all the constraints on natural selection. We briefly
anemia has been selected for because it is protec- mention two others here: (a) conflicts between
tive against malaria in a heterozygous state. How- survival and reproduction and (b) antagonistic
ever, if a person inherits two copies of this allele, pleiotropy.
he or she will develop sickle-cell anemia, which Survival and reproduction often come into
can be fatal (Allison 1954). It is thus possible for conflict in nature. Because differential reproduc-
selection at the genic level to have detrimental tion, not survival, is the bottom line of evolution,
effects on an organism’s health. And because it when they do conflict, reproduction inevitably
is impossible to optimize two conflicting levels trumps survival (Alcock 2009; Dawkins 1976;
(genic and individual) simultaneously, suboptimal Williams 1966). The peacock’s tail illustrates
outcomes are unavoidable. this well. It is a burden to survival: cumbersome,
metabolically expensive, and a hindrance when it
Mistakes Due to Environmental comes to escaping from predators. But peacock
Unpredictability genes build these tails anyway because peahens
Dawkins’s final constraint is that of environmen- are attracted to them – such is the power of sexual
tal unpredictability. Animals may be exceedingly selection. The key point regarding the conflict
well adapted to their environments, but since between survival and reproduction is this: because
some environmental events are inherently it is impossible to simultaneously optimize two
unpredictable, mistakes and missteps are conflicting outcomes (survival and reproduction),
inevitable. suboptimal outcomes are inevitable. And because
For example, a bird may be well adapted to fly differential reproductive success – not survival –
in conditions that are, on average, favorable to is the currency of evolution by natural selection,
flight. But it would not be surprising for the design for reproduction takes precedence. This
4 Richard Dawkins on Constraints on Natural Selection

often leads to suboptimal design for survival (see other available designs in the population at
e.g., Al-Shawaf et al. 2015). the time.
Antagonistic pleiotropy – a phenomenon in This definition of natural selection, together
which a single gene may have conflicting effects with the eight constraints discussed above,
(Nesse and Williams 1994; Williams 1957) – pro- explains why natural selection cannot produce
vides another constraint on optimality. For exam- optimally designed mechanisms in nature.
ple, some genes have beneficial effects in early We hope this entry helps elucidate the nature of
adulthood but detrimental effects in later adult- these constraints on natural selection, why they
hood. This is the case with genes for testosterone exist, and the important role Dawkins has played
production, as testosterone enhances male repro- in highlighting them. We also hope this entry
ductive success in early adulthood but increases underscores the erroneousness of the oft-repeated
susceptibility to a wide variety of diseases in later criticism that evolutionary scientists think adapta-
years (Trivers 1985; Williams and Nesse 1991). tions are optimally designed. They are not, of
And because selection is more powerful earlier in course – for all the above reasons. More impor-
the lifespan and weaker later in the lifespan (after tantly, it is thanks to evolutionary scientists – key
reproduction has already occurred; Nesse and among them Richard Dawkins – that we under-
Williams 1994; Williams 1957) it will favor genes stand the exact reasons why natural selection can-
that help the organism early in the lifespan even if not achieve optimality in nature.
they hurt it later on. In this way, antagonistic
pleiotropy – combined with the waning strength
of selection across the lifespan – constitutes Cross-References
another key driver of suboptimal design in nature.
▶ Adaptations: Products of Evolution
▶ Antagonistic Pleiotropy
Conclusion ▶ Evolutionary Mismatch/Time Lag
▶ Misconceptions in Evolutionary Psychology
Summary ▶ Misunderstandings About Natural Selection
Richard Dawkins’s seminal account of the limits ▶ Natural Selection
of natural selection focused on six key constraints: ▶ Optimal Designs
time lags, historical constraints, constraints due to ▶ Sexual Selection
available genetic variation, tradeoffs, imperfec- ▶ Survival and Reproduction
tion due to selection operating at different levels,
and constraints due to environmental
unpredictability. To these six key constraints, we References
briefly added two more: antagonistic pleiotropy
and the conflict between survival and Al-Shawaf, L., Conroy-Beam, D., Asao, K., & Buss, D. M.
reproduction. (2015). Human emotions: An evolutionary psycholog-
ical perspective. Emotion Review, 1–14.
One more theoretical point bears mentioning.
Alcock, J. (2009). Animal behavior: An evolutionary
Natural selection should not be understood as an approach. Sunderland: Sinauer Associates.
optimizing process at all – instead, it is a Allison, A. C. (1954). Protection afforded by sickle-cell
“meliorizing” process (Dawkins 1999). That is, trait against subtertian malarial infection. British Med-
ical Journal, 1(4857), 290–294.
natural selection does not produce the best design
Buss, D. M. (2015). Evolutionary psychology: The new
possible by engineering standards – rather, it pro- science of the mind (5th ed.). Boston: Pearson Educa-
duces designs that are better, on average, than the tion, Inc..
Richard Dawkins on Constraints on Natural Selection 5

Dawkins, R. (1976). The selfish gene. Oxford: Oxford Williams, G. C. (1966). Adaptation and natural selection.
University Press. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Dawkins, R. (1999). The extended phenotype: The long Williams, G. C. (1957). Pleiotropy, Natural Selection, and
reach of the gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press. the Evolution of Senescence. Evolution, 11(4),
Dennett, D. C. (1996). Darwin’s dangerous idea: Evolu- 398–411.
tion and the meanings of life. London: Penguin Books. Williams, G. C., & Nesse, R. M. (1991). The dawn of
Nesse, R. M., & Williams, G. C. (1994). Why we get sick. Darwinian medicine. Quarterly Review of Biology, 66,
New York: Times Books Random House. 1–22.
Trivers, R. (1985). Social evolution. Menlo Park:
Benjamin-Cummings.

Вам также может понравиться