Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 17

This article was downloaded by: [Universite De Paris 1]

On: 27 July 2013, At: 11:11


Publisher: Routledge
Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office:
Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK

The Journal of Architecture


Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription
information:
http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rjar20

Of stylised species and specious styles


a
Amy Kulper
a
University of Michigan, USA
Published online: 01 Dec 2006.

To cite this article: Amy Kulper (2006) Of stylised species and specious styles, The Journal of Architecture,
11:4, 391-406, DOI: 10.1080/13602360601037693

To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/13602360601037693

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of all the information (the “Content”)
contained in the publications on our platform. However, Taylor & Francis, our agents, and our
licensors make no representations or warranties whatsoever as to the accuracy, completeness, or
suitability for any purpose of the Content. Any opinions and views expressed in this publication
are the opinions and views of the authors, and are not the views of or endorsed by Taylor &
Francis. The accuracy of the Content should not be relied upon and should be independently
verified with primary sources of information. Taylor and Francis shall not be liable for any
losses, actions, claims, proceedings, demands, costs, expenses, damages, and other liabilities
whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with, in relation to or
arising out of the use of the Content.

This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Any substantial
or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing, systematic supply, or
distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. Terms & Conditions of access and use
can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditions
391

The Journal
of Architecture
Volume 11
Number 4

Of stylised species and


specious styles

Amy Kulper
Downloaded by [Universite De Paris 1] at 11:11 27 July 2013

University of Michigan, USA

In all unimportant matters, style, not sincerity is we have been enabled to remark the works of
the essential. In all important matters, style, not man, and the gradual development of his ideas,
sincerity, is the essential. especially in Art, leading to a variety of so-called
Oscar Wilde, 1894 “styles”, which answer in a measure to the varied
To what do we attribute the current profusion of “species” of Divinely created life.’1 The analogy of
biomorphic forms in our discipline? When architec- species and style in this description is the result of
tural practices employ versioning or rapid prototyp- an ongoing process of immanentisation, in which
ing technologies, how do we account for the external nature is conflated with human inner
impetus to represent development? When imple- nature through the identification of common vital
menting a parametric design, why do architects will- tendencies. This conflation ultimately fosters the
ingly cede creative control to recombinant human appropriation of the natural world’s creative
geometries? If rapid prototyping imagines the con- or generative capacities.2 This paper will begin with
flation of design and fabrication through automated a cursory description of certain formative moments
manufacturing, what are the disciplinary con- in the development of the species-style metaphor
sequences of these compressed processes of archi- in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries; it will
tectural design and production? Lurking behind all identify and describe operative categories of the
of these questions is the spectre of the species- metaphor—specifically, ‘stylised species’ and ‘spe-
style metaphor, and understanding the cultural cious styles’—and consider how the work of Gott-
conditions under which it was first formulated and fried Semper, Georges Cuvier, Owen Jones, Ernst
propagated will shed some light on current architec- Haeckel, and Karl Blossfeldt epitomises these dispa-
tural practices and predilections. To accomplish this, rate classifications; it will examine the role of the
we must return to the nineteenth century. species-style metaphor in Victor Horta’s architecture;
The year is 1851, and as visitors crowd into and it will conclude with some speculations about
Paxton’s Crystal Palace to attend the Great Exhibi- the impact of this organic metaphor on contempo-
tion, they witness a quite literal form of cultural rary architectural discourse and practice.
transparency. Housed within this extensive glass How did the species-style metaphor become such
wrapper, visitors find every sort of technological, a commonplace by the middle of the nineteenth
ethnographic, artistic, agricultural, and geological century? For the answer to this question we would
exhibit imaginable (Fig. 1). For those visitors have to go back to 1750 when, prior to writing his
curious about the odd juxtaposition of sculpture seminal Geschichte der Kunst Alterthums (an
and soil sample, painting and pigeon, maquette account of the history of Greek art), Johann
and machine, a glance at the official guidebook Joachim Winckelmann spent four years poring
offers this explanation: ‘Within the Palace itself, over Georges Buffon’s Histoire Naturelle. What did

# 2006 The Journal of Architecture 1360–2365 DOI: 10.1080/13602360601037693


392

Of stylised species and


specious styles
Amy Kulper
Downloaded by [Universite De Paris 1] at 11:11 27 July 2013

Figure 1. Taxonomy of
the Great Exhibition of
1851; from: 1851 Great
Exhibition Official
Catalogue with
Alphabetical and
Classified Index and
Price Lists (London,
William Clowes & Sons,
1851). Photograph
credit: Research Library,
The Getty Research
Institute, Los Angeles,
California (93-B19896).

Winckelmann, an historian of ancient art, glean from death. Clearly, this enterprise involves the appropria-
Buffon’s detailed botanical accounts? From Buffon he tion of the idea of the lifespan of the biological
acquired a meticulously historicised sense of nature species and its application to artistic style. Winckel-
and natural species, which he developed into an mann’s emphasis on proof is also imported from
equally historicised sense of style. In the introduction natural history where it is used to establish coherence
to his text, Winckelmann writes: ‘The history of art is or identity between an individual specimen and the
intended to show the origin, progress, change, and species to which it belongs. Ultimately, the absolute
downfall of art, together with the different styles of certainty of this coherence between specimen and
nations, periods and artists, and to prove the whole species, between art object and style, led Winckel-
as far as it is possible, from the ancient monuments mann to speculate about the possibility of style
now in existence.’3 Implicit in Winckelmann’s descrip- being biologically transmitted.4
tion of the origin, progress, change, and downfall of Johann Wolfgang von Goethe equally contributed
artistic style, is a parallel notion of biological change: to the formulation of the species-style metaphor in
birth, teleological development, transformation, and the eighteenth century. Between 1786 and 1788,
393

The Journal
of Architecture
Volume 11
Number 4

biological discourse.7 For Goethe, the poetic


Downloaded by [Universite De Paris 1] at 11:11 27 July 2013

he traveled to Italy where he studied the art and


architecture of classical antiquity as well as botany. moment accounts for the imitation of the language
In an essay published the year after he returned of wood construction in ancient stone temples, and
entitled ‘Simple Imitation of Nature, Manner, proffers a theory of stylistic development that
Style’, Goethe’s aesthetic and scientific interests cogently explains this phenomenon. When applied
merged. Concerning the visual arts, he writes: to natural history, Goethe’s morphology eschews
It is obvious that . . . an artist can only become teleology; the development of form is not to be
greater and more significant if he adds to his understood as development towards an explicit
talents the expertise of a botanist; if he knows goal. In fact, he claims that teleology has obstructed
the influence of the different plants, from the the progress of natural history, although he is sym-
roots upwards, and their continuing and mutual pathetic to the human desire to ascribe intention
effect; if he observes and reflects on the succes- to nature’s actions: ‘Moreover, in himself and
sive development of the leaves, flowers, sex others he justifiably puts the greatest value on
organs, fruit and the new seed. Then he will not actions and deeds which are intentional and purpo-
simply demonstrate his taste by his choice of seful. It follows that he will attribute intent and
subject, but he will astonish and enlighten us by purpose to nature, for he will be unable to form a
his accurate representation of these character- larger concept of nature than of himself.’8 For
istics: and in this sense it could be said that he Goethe, one of the great advantages of morphology
has formed a style.5 is its capacity to operate independently—it does not
It is significant that Goethe turns to botany in his belong to chemistry, or biology, or botany, or art
description of style, not only because he is propaga- history—but it establishes an autonomous vantage
ting the species-style metaphor, but also because he point of formal development that potentially
brings to architectural discourse the possibility of benefits each of these disciplines.9 Finally, Goethe
considering the development of form, for which positions morphology as a critique of vitalist ten-
he coined the term ‘morphology’. In this sense, dencies in the sciences. The formation and trans-
Goethe provides one of the earliest examples of formation of organic bodies is not attributed to
explicit morphological thinking about architecture: the actions of a vital inner source, but to the recipro-
he redefines style as the accurate representation of city of intrinsic forces and extrinsic conditions.
development.6 How does Goethe’s morphological This brief examination of Winckelmann and
definition of style manifest itself aesthetically? If Goethe supplies some of the necessary background
we consider his notion of the ‘poetic moment’ in to an understanding of the species-style metaphor in
which he theorises that what is useful in one histori- the nineteenth century. At this juncture, it is impor-
cal period becomes representational in the next, we tant to ask how this conceptual conflation operates
witness an historical account of style that owes its metaphorically. Paul Ricoeur argues that metaphor is
confusion of causation with temporal succession to the result of the tension between two opposed
394

Of stylised species and


specious styles
Amy Kulper

interpretations in an utterance.10 In the case of the


Downloaded by [Universite De Paris 1] at 11:11 27 July 2013

individual taste. Simultaneously, style lost the


species-style metaphor, the opposed interpretations ethical content of its rhetorical meaning, in which
would be the diversity of species produced by acting in accordance with nature meant possessing
nature’s generative capacity versus the variety of the knowledge to act appropriately in a given situ-
styles produced by humanity’s creative genius. Also ation. When style began increasingly to emulate
essential to the metaphor for Ricoeur is the ‘appear- species in the nineteenth century, it merely took on
ance of kinship where ordinary vision does not per- the appearance of an accordance with nature.14
ceive any relationship.’11 With regard to the The examination of a handful of late nineteenth
species-style metaphor, this kinship is the tacit century architects and naturalists, including
belief that nature’s generative capacity and human- Semper, Blossfeldt, Jones and Haeckel, will lend cre-
ity’s creative genius are similar productive processes. dence to the above categorisations of stylised
Ricoeur concludes, ‘A metaphor, in short, tells us species and specious styles. Gottfried Semper, who
something new about reality.’12 At its best, the designed the Canadian, Danish, Egyptian and
species-style metaphor elucidates the similarities Swedish displays for the Crystal Palace, was no
and differences between techniques for natural stranger to the issues of classification and display
and cultural production and between the classifica- raised in the exhibition organisation. While studying
tory schemas for objects of nature and culture. in Paris between 1826 and 1830, he often visited the
If species refers to the appearance or outward Jardin des Plantes and became particularly fasci-
form of an organism as the criterion for identity nated by the displays of fossils and skeletons
and classification, and style emerges from a rhetori- arranged by the great naturalist Georges Cuvier.
cal context in which it refers to the internal coher- Cuvier’s contribution to biological taxonomy is the
ence of nature, then how do we arrive at the assertion that the classification of organisms
terminology of ‘stylised species’ and ‘specious should be based upon their function, their form
styles’?13 With specious styles, the similarities being simply a result of that function. In a lecture
between two opposed interpretations are seized given in 1853, Semper speculates about the possible
upon at the expense of their respective differences. applications of this principle to architecture: ‘Such a
The metaphor tells us nothing new about reality; method, similar to the one followed by Baron Cuvier,
in fact, it is a dead metaphor by virtue of its reified when applied to art and especially to architecture,
meaning and frequent usage. The conflation of would at least help to gain a clear survey of the
species and style is due to the historical process of whole field and perhaps even the basis of a theory
immanentisation in which style loses its rhetorical of style and a kind of Topica or method of invention,
connotation as the internal coherence of nature which could lead to some knowledge of the natural
and comes to be understood as the internal coher- process of invention.’15
ence of human inner nature. This shift renders Thus, for Semper, Cuvier’s classification according
style a contingency of personal preference and to the behaviour and function of species becomes
395

The Journal
of Architecture
Volume 11
Number 4
Downloaded by [Universite De Paris 1] at 11:11 27 July 2013

the inspiration for a theory of architectural style Figure 2. Plate 96 from


linked explicitly to natural operations of production. Karl Blossfeldt’s
Urformen der Kunst
When Semper defines style as ‘. . . the accord of an
illustrating a common
object with its genesis, and with all preconditions monkshood plant
and circumstances of its becoming’, he re-orients enlarged six times;
the species-style metaphor toward issues of emer- from: Art Forms in
gence.16 Thus, in preserving the tensional play of Nature, Karl Blossfeldt
(London, A. Zwemmer,
the species-style metaphor, Semper’s contributions
1929). Photograph
fall under the category of stylised species. Semper credit: # 2006 Karl
engages two opposed interpretations: the ordering Blossfeldt Archiv/Ann
of species according to their respective functions U. Jürgen Wilde, Köln/
and the ordering of architectural style according to Artists Rights Society
(ARS), NY.
function or type. He intuits the appearance of
kinship by grasping parallel processes of natural
and cultural invention. In his hands, the species-
style metaphor reveals something new about
reality; specifically, that both species and style can
encompass and accommodate formal emergence.
Karl Blossfeldt, a botanist who began teaching in
Berlin in 1898, organised a plate archive of plant
photographs from which he made prints for instruc-
tional use. In 1928, when he published the first
120 plates of Urformen der Kunst, a collection of
plant specimens to be shared with fellow botanists,
he could not have anticipated their tremendous we remember that [Paul] Klee and, even more
impact on aesthetic discourse. His photographic [Vassily] Kandinsky, worked for so long on the elab-
reproductions, like this image of a common oration of forms which only the intervention of the
monkshood plant, were enlarged anywhere from microscope could—brusquely and violently—reveal
three to fifteen times their original size, replicating to us, we notice that these enlargements of
the experience of viewing botanical specimens the plants also contain original stylistic forms
under a microscope (Fig. 2). The premise of these [Stilformen].’17 In Blossfeldt’s work Benjamin is
photographs is that to see nature magnified is to seeing original stylistic forms within the magnifi-
be privy to its inner workings, the vital spirit that cation of the species. Here, the species-style meta-
animates its creative process. In a 1928 review of phor introduces vitalism to aesthetic discourse and
Blossfeldt’s work, Walter Benjamin remarks: ‘When offers the possibility that original stylistic forms
396

Of stylised species and


specious styles
Amy Kulper
Downloaded by [Universite De Paris 1] at 11:11 27 July 2013

need not reside in hypothetical historical precedents entrenches the publication in an extensive tradition
such as the primitive hut, so central to eighteenth of pattern books (Fig. 3). However, the final plates
century debates on the origins of architecture, but in the collection deviate from the rigid taxonomic
are, rather, innate, acting as stylistic catalysts to survey of ornament from the past. Under the
developing forms. Blossfeldt’s photographs preserve rubric of ‘Leaves and Flowers from Nature’, Jones
the tension of the species-style metaphor, and in this includes ornament of his own design (Fig. 4). To
sense, would be categorised as stylised species. The the casual observer, these plates more closely
two opposed interpretations of the metaphor in his approximate botanical illustrations than ornamental
work are the scientific and aesthetic fetishism of samples. Rendered as line drawings in a style popu-
organic form. Microscopic magnification reveals a larised by the eighteenth century naturalist Carl
kinship where ordinary vision does not perceive a Linnaeus, Jones’s ornament consists of numbered
relationship: in this case, the potential for vitalism specimens depicted in exacting detail in full-page
to have both scientific and aesthetic applications. layouts, emancipating them from the represen-
Finally, the metaphor reveals something new about tational conventions of the pattern book. The
reality when it posits the possibility that both realism of Jones’s renderings, their inherent lack of
natural and cultural objects contain original stylistic ornamental flourish, closes the gap between the dis-
forms [Stilformen]. parate realms of science and aesthetics. Here, style is
To the species-style metaphor, Owen Jones, the species. The species-style metaphor has elided to
architect who designed the colour scheme of the become a tautology.
interior structure for the Crystal Palace, contributes In an 1879 text entitled The Evolution of Man, the
the idea that nature is not the only material suitable German zoologist Ernst Haeckel advances what
for taxonomic description and organisation. would later be referred to as the recapitulation
Through Jones’s publications the possibility of a cul- theory.19 The theory, which holds that the embryo-
tural taxonomy emerged. In the illustrations of his nic development of an organism encapsulates the
1865 book The Grammar of Ornament, Jones does evolutionary descent of the species, is both an
for ornamental style what Buffon did for botanic attempt to historicise biology and to theorise
species. But there is a disparity between the illus- development. In his 1899 book Kunstformen der
trations and the text of Jones’s book. Jones cautions Natur, Haeckel includes a plate that gives aesthetic
his reader: ‘The principles discoverable in the works expression to his scientific theory.20 Plate 95
of the past belong to us; not so the results. It is (Fig. 5) illustrates the recapitulation theory by seam-
taking the ends for the means.’18 Even though the lessly juxtaposing embryonic forms of contemporary
text explicitly argues against the use of his plates echinoderms with fossilised echinoderms of the
as a visual lexicon, the representational conventions Palaeozoic era. In a single image, Haeckel conflates
he employs for the visual display of historical orna- the development of a single organism within the
ment—gridded pages of isolated samples—firmly species with the evolution of the entire species.
397

The Journal
of Architecture
Volume 11
Number 4
Downloaded by [Universite De Paris 1] at 11:11 27 July 2013

Figure 3. Plate VII from


Owen Jones’s The
Grammar of Ornament
depicting Egyptian
ornament in a typical
taxonomic format;
from: The Grammar of
Ornament (New York,
Dover Publications, Inc.,
1987). Photograph
credit: # The Grammar
of Ornament/Owen
Jones/Dover
Publications, Inc.
398

Of stylised species and


specious styles
Amy Kulper
Downloaded by [Universite De Paris 1] at 11:11 27 July 2013

Figure 4. Plate XCVII


from Owen Jones’s The
Grammar of Ornament
depicting Jones’s own
ornamental designs
under the title ‘Leaves
and Flowers from
Nature’; from: The
Grammar of Ornament
(New York, Dover
Publications, Inc.,
1987). Photograph
credit: # The Grammar
of Ornament/Owen
Jones/Dover
Publications, Inc.

Figure 5. Plate 95 from


Ernst Haeckel’s
Kunstformen der Natur
illustrating Haeckel’s
recapitulation theory;
from: Art Forms in
Nature (New York,
Dover Publications, Inc.,
1974). Photograph
credit: # Art Forms in
Nature/Ernst Haeckel/
Dover Publications, Inc.
The plates from this book attest to the proximity of Medusa, in Jena. Similarly, René Binet appropriated
the scientific and the aesthetic at the close of the Haeckel’s radiolarian with his monumental entrance
nineteenth century: both de-contextualise their gate for the Paris World Exposition of 1900. These
objects of study; both emphasise form; and both examples fall under the rubric of specious styles.
are interested in questions concerning the gene- The species-style metaphor is once again rendered
ration and development of form. In fact, for a tautology; for Haeckel and Binet, species is style.21
Haeckel the scientific and aesthetic are virtually A closer reading of one body of work, that of the
interchangeable as evidenced by his use of an Belgian art nouveau architect Victor Horta, will
image of a jellyfish with the scientific name expose many nuanced manifestations within the
Toreuma as both Plate 28 in his book, and as an spectrum of possibilities that stretches between sty-
ornamental ceiling motif in his home, the Villa lised species and specious styles in this period. While
399

The Journal
of Architecture
Volume 11
Number 4
Downloaded by [Universite De Paris 1] at 11:11 27 July 2013

inevitability of style itself. In Horta’s work, the coher- Figure 6. Hybrid


ence between the detail and the spatial situation is element from Victor
Horta’s Maison and
informed by the tenets of Gesamtkunstwerk. In a
Atelier (1898 – 1901);
hybrid element from the Maison and Atelier Horta from: Victor Horta,
(1898 –1901), the connectivity of column, light David Dernie (London,
fixture, handrail, armrest, seat back, heating grate Academy Group Ltd,
is purely a result of style, which transcends material 1995). Photograph
credit: Alastair Carew-
and functional differences, yielding a cohesive whole
Cox # 2006 – Horta/
(Fig. 6). While the parts are easily identified and SOFAM – Belgium.
classified, the whole defies such categorisation; it
is more than the sum of its parts. The certitude
that every living thing belongs to a species mandates
that all forms of architectural production exhibit sty-
listic coherence. As a result of the species-style
metaphor, scientific certitude becomes aesthetic
mandate.
Another indication of the species-style metaphor
in Horta’s work resides in his deployment of style
as language. Horta’s position can be located some-
where between Goethe’s assertion of style as a
language that reveals the nature of things, and
Owen Jones’s taxonomy of ornament, which
it is clearly Horta’s intention to produce work that renders style a de-situated language that can be uni-
would be classified as stylised species, work that versally deployed according to certain grammatical
engages the metaphorical tension between the aes- principles. This sort of Jonesian classificatory think-
thetic and scientific realms, he occasionally falls prey ing in Horta’s work is evidenced by a drawing in
to the seduction of specious styles. his sketchbook depicting the taxonomy of door iron-
The hegemony and inevitability of style in Horta’s mongery used in his various houses, or by the repeti-
work is one intriguing manifestation of the species- tious and almost indiscriminate use of similar
style metaphor. Winckelmann’s aesthetic interpret- ornamental motifs, such as columns with burgeon-
ation of the coherence between species and speci- ing capitals, in vastly different circumstances in his
men suggests that the species-style metaphor body of work.
theorises the part-to-whole relationship in architec- In natural history, at times species are represented
tural discourse in a way that assures, not only the as taxonomies, in which de-contextualised speci-
dominance of stylistic concerns, but also the very mens are arranged according to the imposition of
400

Of stylised species and


specious styles
Amy Kulper
Downloaded by [Universite De Paris 1] at 11:11 27 July 2013

Figure 7. Winter rational order, and at times species are represented


Garden Mural of Victor in their natural habitats, like the museum diorama,
Horta’s Hôtel Tassel
in which they are situated within their natural
(1893 – 97); from: Victor
Horta, David Dernie environments. Similarly, styles appear in both
(London, Academy de-contextualised taxonomies and situated environ-
Group Ltd, 1995). ments. Horta’s projects run the gamut between
Photograph credit: these two extremes. If we look at his use of orna-
Alastair Carew-Cox #
ment in the Hôtel Tassel (1893 –97), we discover
2006 – Horta/
SOFAM – Belgium. that Horta makes a conscientious effort to deploy
natural ornamental motifs that are appropriate to
their contexts. For example, in the winter garden,
the space for the collection of exotic plant species
and curiosities, Horta uses a repetitious ornamental
motif resembling wallpaper (Fig. 7). Here, the taxo-
nomic referential structure of the space—a space
for collection and display—warrants a repetitive,
de-contextualised ornamental motif. In another
site-specific mural, this one occupying a curved
soffit connecting the mezzanine balcony to the
salon below, the balustrade rotates to accommodate
magic lantern projections, and thus the space is,
programmatically, a space for illusions (Fig. 8).
Horta’s mural also engages in the production of and between ornament and structure, this mural
illusion. Rendered in the same colour as the iron- speaks not only to the stark juxtaposition of the
work of the ground floor structural system, this two enterprises, but suggests a potentially seamless
mural propagates the illusion of a seamless tran- continuity between the beautiful and the useful.
sition from three-dimensional structure to two- Finally, the mural occupying the main stairwell
dimensional decoration. In terms of the overall deserves consideration (Fig. 9). Responding to the
grammar of ornament, Horta allows the ornament programmatic specificity of a stairwell, a place of
of the mural to become frame, imitating and com- movement and ascension, and the locus of the
pleting the logic of the structural system below, mobilised viewer, the generative inner nature of
while programmatically anticipating the frame, this mural resists pictorial capture. The mural reflects
both implied and actual, of the magic lantern the thematic topography of the house, which
projection. Located on the literal threshold moves from the dark, compressed and cavernous
between photographic and architectural illusion, space of the entrance vestibule to the light,
401

The Journal
of Architecture
Volume 11
Number 4
Downloaded by [Universite De Paris 1] at 11:11 27 July 2013

Horta is equally influenced by the species-style Figure 8. Mural viewed


metaphor in his propensity for style to engage incre- from the mezzanine
balcony of Victor
ments of natural development and biological life-
Horta’s Hôtel Tassel
span. If Winckelmann was the first to project (1893 – 97); from: Victor
biological lifespan onto style, while Goethe Horta, David Dernie
equated style with the accurate representation of (London, Academy
development, and Semper claimed that style was Group Ltd, 1995).
Photograph credit:
the accord of an object with its genesis, while
Alastair Carew-Cox #
Haeckel utilised the recapitulation theory as an 2006 – Horta/
occasion to aestheticise development, then it may SOFAM – Belgium.
not be surprising that natural development and bio-
logical lifespan feature prominently in Horta’s work.
But what are their respective roles? In the species-
style analogy, taxonomic schematisations of species
find their corollary in historicist representations of
style, and this is precisely what Horta and his
fellow art nouveau architects sought to avoid. In
choosing nature as their source of inspiration, and
representing the natural as it develops and
emerges, art nouveau practitioners hoped to
eschew the prevalent problems of their day—specifi-
cally, stylistic relativism and historical eclecticism.
extended and ethereal space of the first floor One example of Horta’s work that closely resembles
landing. This metaphorical movement from earth Haeckel’s illustration of his recapitulation theory is
to sky and from darkness to light is depicted in the column detail from the façade of the Hôtel
the mural’s transitions of coloration, density, and Tassel. Just as Haeckel brazenly juxtaposes Palaeo-
materiality, as the tendrils that extend to the zoic and contemporary specimens, Horta overtly
upper landing seem almost to dissolve or demateria- positions classical stone columns next to a decidedly
lise in the intense light. Thus, we can see that at modern curved and riveted iron lintel. Recalling
times Horta adapts an ornamental motif to the Goethe’s characterisation of the poetic moment in
function or programme of its specific situation which what is useful in one period becomes rep-
within the house, while at others, he capitulates resentational in the next, this combination of
to the de-contextualising influence of scientific tax- modern lintel and ancient column seems to illustrate
onomy; the former is an instance of stylised species, a kind of ‘abridged evolution’, akin to Gaston
the latter, an example of specious style. Bachelard’s definition of the ornamental category
402

Of stylised species and


specious styles
Amy Kulper
Downloaded by [Universite De Paris 1] at 11:11 27 July 2013

Figure 9. Main stairway development towards an end. The teleological


mural of Victor Horta’s imperative of style in Horta’s work manifests itself
Hôtel Tassel (1893 – 97);
in the typological consistency of his projects. His
from: Victor Horta,
David Dernie (London, houses, designed for different clients, on different
Academy Group Ltd, sites, under different circumstances are possessed
1995). Photograph of certain typological consistencies that potentially
credit: Alastair Carew- render them specious styles. Horta’s repetitive use
Cox # 2006 – Horta/
of a vertical topography that presents a movement
SOFAM – Belgium.
from darkness to light with a staircase as a central
iconic figure suggests that the answer to the ques-
tion—development to what end?—is a foregone
conclusion. The emergent nature in his domestic
projects repeatedly develops towards an immanent
representation of cosmological transcendence.23
This typological consistency is associated with the
teleological imperative of style in Horta’s work. Its
tendency towards universality, its indifference to
the specific situations of the individual houses,
makes this a specious aspect of Horta’s art
nouveau style.
Finally, the species-style metaphor manifests itself
in Horta’s work by way of a vital impulse. Blossfeldt’s
of the grotesque.22 What makes this example an magnified images of plant specimens call attention
instance of specious style in Horta’s work is that, to the migration of vitalism from biological to aes-
like Haeckel, he is concerned primarily with the thetic discourse. In opposition to mechanistic theo-
appearance of development at the expense of the ries of development, the vitalists posit an essential
behaviour of development. and vital force as the catalyst to all biological trans-
When style engages issues of natural develop- formations. Walter Benjamin likens this to the aes-
ment in nineteenth-century architectural discourse, thetic Stilformen, or original stylistic forms in which
the question that is raised is development towards the vital impulse is located. This vital impulse
what? Semper’s adaptation of Cuvier’s functional informs Horta’s style, specifically his tendency con-
classification brought function, programme and sistently to represent burgeoning or emergent
typology to the forefront of architectural interest, nature. In his lectures and writing, Horta stresses
and with this came a teleological inclination—a the importance of becoming a student of nature
tacit assumption that development is always so that one can represent its every nuance and
403

The Journal
of Architecture
Volume 11
Number 4
Downloaded by [Universite De Paris 1] at 11:11 27 July 2013

stage of development, and although his sketches graphy and selective laser sintering, it is apparent
prove him to be a man of his word, his architecture that species is no longer like style; species is style.
focuses exclusively on emergent natural motifs.24 We are awash in buzzwords like forces, dynamics,
Horta’s ornamental style captures nature at the performance, emergence, efficiency, and adap-
moment of its genesis, the instant when it is ani- tation, but as provocative as these terms are, they
mated by a vital force. To the degree that this rep- seem inseparable from the biomorphic aesthetic
resents Horta’s desire to capture the behaviour of upon whose coattails they first entered the
nature, it is an example of stylised species; to the discipline.
extent that it visually codifies the appearance and The guidebook to the Crystal Palace described the
behaviour of nature, it is an instance of specious ‘works of man . . . leading to a variety of so-called
style. styles’ as they corresponded to the ‘varied species
The species-style metaphor is responsible for of Divinely created life.’ In the context of the nine-
keeping certain parallel questions in the aesthetic teenth century, the species-style metaphor focused
and scientific realms alive; such as, whether style is upon ‘what’ nature and culture produce. When con-
based upon external appearance or internal beha- sidering the question of species and style in our con-
viour, and whether the identity of a species resides temporary context, interest has shifted from ‘what’
in its diverse forms or in its various functions. What nature and culture produce, to the ‘how’ of
is evident from this examination is that the concep- natural and cultural production. The unrealised
tual analogy, and ultimately, the conflation of promise of Goethe’s morphology is that it presciently
species and style, engenders a persistent dialectic reflects this shift in interest from the appearance of
in modern architectural discourse that made func- the natural to its behaviour. What can contemporary
tion and typology preoccupations of the early twen- architectural discourse learn from Goethe’s
tieth century, and ‘performativity’ and morphology morphology?
concerns of the early twenty-first century. As the One of Goethe’s fundamental claims about mor-
species-style metaphor became increasingly phology is that its intention is to portray rather
common in the discipline of architecture, however, than explain.25 Morphology did not develop as a
the creative tension at the core of the analogous particular science, but as a kind of meta-science in
relationship between the scientific and aesthetic which representations of development were privi-
realms was supplanted by mere affinity: disparate leged over explanations of development. Goethe
interpretations became synonymous, and the recognised that species and styles are epistemologi-
species-style metaphor elided to become a tautol- cally different, but the meta-category of mor-
ogy. This brings us full circle to the contemporary phology allowed him to seize upon their
status of species and style within our discipline. In representational similarities. Thus, the discursive,
this moment of blobs and biomorphic forms, para- the logical and the explanatory had no role in his
metric modeling and rapid prototyping, stereolitho- discussion of style. From Goethe, architectural
404

Of stylised species and


specious styles
Amy Kulper
Downloaded by [Universite De Paris 1] at 11:11 27 July 2013

discourse must learn that when it embraces the mor- styles? In order to address the profusion and ubi-
phological, it is not required to capitulate to the logic quity of biomorphic forms, we must shift our
and intelligibility of scientific thought. Goethe also emphasis from the appearance of species to the
believed that morphology should eschew teleology. behaviour of species. When employing rapid proto-
Instinctively he knew that the question of ‘develop- typing technologies, we must be cognisant of the
ment toward what end?’ was too easily and thought- distinction between formal iterations and formal
lessly answered by the production of an image. In development. Currently, prototypes are generated
eschewing teleology, Goethe’s morphology avoids through a quasi-scientific process aimed at expand-
portraying mere appearances or images of species, ing formal options while excluding authorial intent.
and as we have seen in numerous examples, this is Paradoxically, at the conclusion of this process, the
one area in which the species-style metaphor consist- architect must choose one model, allowing aesthetic
ently lapses into tautology. From Goethe, architec- preference to muddy the scientific waters. Framing
tural discourse must learn that a genuine interest in the prototypes as developments rather than iter-
morphology engages the representation of change, ations potentially lends the process an evaluative
and that this representational interest is completely structure that is not purely subjective. Parametric
detached from any biomorphic aesthetic. Finally, design can reinstate the metaphorical tension to
Goethe argues that morphology legitimises itself by the species-style comparison by expanding the
establishing a new vantage point from which form field of parameters beyond the information and
may be considered: the vantage point of change, recombinant geometries of species, to the constitu-
transformation, and development. In this sense, he ents of spatial experience that have traditionally
is orienting morphology towards the behaviour of belonged to style. And finally, the conflation of
species. From Goethe, architectural discourse must design and fabrication through automated manu-
learn that establishing a new vantage point about facturing is a practice that appears directly to
the change, transformation, and development of emulate nature’s generative capacity, which draws
form does not mean that interests in flows, forces, no such distinction between design and production;
dynamics, adaptation, performance and emergence but rather than guaranteeing natural qualities of
should supplant other considerations of spatial emergence, it ensures the cultural commodification
experience; nor does it mean that formal interests of architecture. Can we observe the possibilities of
should eclipse all other interests. architectural form from a new vantage point or are
This essay began with some speculations about we resigned to the propagation of specious styles?
the impact of the species-style metaphor on
current architectural practices. It will conclude with Notes and references
a question. How can we as a discipline restore the 1. Great Exhibition Catalogue of 1851, 4 vols, Guide to
metaphorical tension to the species-style analogy; the Crystal Palace and Park, volume iv (London,
or, how do we avoid the propagation of specious Crystal Palace Library, 1854), p.104.
405

The Journal
of Architecture
Volume 11
Number 4
Downloaded by [Universite De Paris 1] at 11:11 27 July 2013

2. In what M.H. Abrams provocatively describes as a 8. Johann Wolfgang von Goethe, Goethe: Scientific
German theory of ‘vegetable genius’, Friedrich Studies, ed., Douglas Miller, trs., Douglas Miller, 12
Schelling, in his System of Transcendental Idealism of vols., vol. 12, Goethe (New York, Suhrkamp Publishers,
1800, suggests that productive activity includes not 1988), p.54. From the essay ‘Toward a General Com-
only ‘what is generally called art . . . that which is parative Theory’ written between 1790 and 1794,
practised with consciousness, deliberation, and reflec- and published in 1892: it addresses the problem of
tion, and can be taught and learned’, but also that physicotheology.
which cannot ‘be achieved by application or in any 9. Ibid., p.59. Goethe advances this argument in the essay
other way, but must be inherited as a free gift from ‘Observation on Morphology in General’, written in
nature.’ See M.H. Abrams, The Mirror and the Lamp: 1795 and published in 1891.
Romantic Theory and the Critical Tradition (Oxford, 10. Paul Ricoeur, Interpretation Theory: Discourse and the
Oxford University Press, 1971), p.209. Surplus of Meaning (Fort Worth, Texas Christian
3. Johann Joachim Winckelmann, History of the Art of University Press, 1976), p. 50.
Antiquity, eds, Julia Bloomfield et al., trs., Harry 11. Ibid., p. 51.
F. Mallgrave, Texts and Documents (Los Angeles, The 12. Ibid., p. 52.
Getty Research Institute, 2006), p. 71. 13. Marcus Tullius Cicero, De Oratore, ed., G.P. Gould, trs.,
4. Carlo Ginzburg, ‘Style as Inclusion, Style as Exclusion’, in H. Rackham, II vols, The Loeb Classical Library, Book III
Picturing Science, Producing Art, eds, Caroline A. Jones, (Cambridge, Harvard University Press, 1942), pp.7, 25.
Peter Galison (New York, Routledge, 1998), p. 34. Crassus, the protagonist of Cicero’s De Oratore
5. Johann Wolfgang von Goethe, ‘Simple Imitation of (55 BC), offers an early formulation of rhetorical style
Nature, Manner, Style’, in Goethe on Art, ed., John when he contends that in nature there are ‘a multi-
Gage (London, Scolar Press, 1980), p.23. plicity of things that are different from one another
6. Caroline van Eck, Organicism in Nineteenth-Century and yet esteemed as having a similar nature.’ It is
Architecture: An Inquiry into Its Theoretical and Philo- from this context that the definition of style as the
sophical Background (Amsterdam, Architectura & internal coherence of nature is derived.
Natura Press, 1994), p.100. 14. See Dalibor Vesely, Architecture in the Age of Divided
7. The theory of the poetic moment appears in an essay Representation: The Question of Creativity in the
by Goethe entitled ‘Palladio Architecture’ written in Shadow of Production (Cambridge, The MIT Press,
1795 and published posthumously. Goethe’s theory 2004), pp. 358 –366.
ensures the continuity of the qualities and appearance 15. van Eck, Organicism in Nineteenth-Century Architec-
of architecture, while claiming for architecture an ture: An Inquiry into Its Theoretical and Philosophical
autonomous aesthetic sensibility. See William Background, op.cit., p. 228.
Coleman, Biology in the Nineteenth Century: Problems 16. Gottfried Semper, Style in the Technical and Tectonic
of Form, Function, and Transformation (New York, Arts; or, Practical Aesthetics: A Handbook for Tech-
John Wiley & Son, Inc., 1971), p.161. Coleman refers nicians, Artists, and Friends of the Arts, eds, Julia
to the confusion of causation and temporal succession Bloomfield et al., trs, Harry F. Mallgrave and Michael
as the ‘great intellectual prejudice of nineteenth- Robinson, Texts & Documents (Los Angeles, Getty Pub-
century thought.’ lications, 2004), pp. 52 –53.
406

Of stylised species and


specious styles
Amy Kulper
Downloaded by [Universite De Paris 1] at 11:11 27 July 2013

17. Walter Benjamin, ‘New Things About Plants—A 23. This version of immanentism corresponds to one of its
Review of Karl Blossfeldt, Urformen der Kunst’, in, most radical manifestations in Husserl’s writing, where
Germany: The New Photography 1927 –1933, ed., it is posited as transcendence in immanence.
David Mellor (London, Lund Humphries, 1978), p. 21. 24. In an unpublished manuscript entitled Cours d’anato-
18. Owen Jones, The Grammar of Ornament (London, Day mie of 1921, Horta describes in great detail the need
and Son, Limited, 1865), p.8. to study nature in all of its nuanced manifestations:
19. Ernst Haeckel, The Evolution of Man: A Popular Exposition ‘Since then I have studied the life, the sleep, and the
of the Principal Points of Human Ontogeny and Phylo- death of plants, animals, and people, with keen inter-
geny, 2 vols (New York, D. Appleton and Company, 1879). est. How much my vision has broadened I could not
20. Richard Hartmann, ed., ‘Art Forms in Nature: The say. From leaves newly unfurled, and growing into
Prints of Ernst Haeckel’ (Munich, Prestel-Verlag, 1998). maturity, to those encountered in full bloom, scorched
21. See Robert Proctor’s paper, ‘Architecture from the cell- by the ardour of the sun in high August, to the same
soul: René Binet and Ernst Haeckel’, in this issue for a leaves dead of old age in October; from the leaves of
more thorough discussion of Binet’s appropriation of dawn to those of noon, of sunset, and of night. I
Haeckel’s theories. have studied all of their countenances with an interest
22. Gaston Bachelard, The Poetics of Space, trs., Maria which, unfortunately, my schedule is chary of letting
Jolas (New York, The Orion Press, 1964), pp. 108 – me fulfill. See Yolande Oostens-Wittamer, Victor
09. Bachelard writes: ‘And so, unbridled, bestial day- Horta: L’hôtel Solvay (Louvain-La-Neuve, Institut Supér-
dream produces a diagram for a shortened version of ieur D’Archéologie et D’Histoire de L’Art, 1980), pp.
animal evolution. In other words, in order to achieve 249– 50.
grotesqueness, it suffices to abridge evolution.’ 25. Goethe, Goethe: Scientific Studies, op. cit., p. 57.

Вам также может понравиться