Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 12

Expression and Communication in Art

Author(s): Edward S. Casey


Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 30, No. 2 (Winter, 1971), pp. 197-
207
Published by: Wiley on behalf of The American Society for Aesthetics
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/429538 .
Accessed: 29/05/2014 11:04

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Wiley and The American Society for Aesthetics are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend
access to The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 129.49.23.145 on Thu, 29 May 2014 11:04:30 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
EDWARD S. CASEY

Expression and Communication


in Art

THE PHENOMENON OF EXPRESSION iS one ward criteria." 2 Variations on this theme


of the most elusive objects of philosophical can be seen in such otherwise diverse phi-
description. It is not unambiguously clear losophers as Wilfrid Sellars and Stuart
what kind of object expression is, or even Hampshire.3
whether it is an object at all. The very term Another form of the move toward the
ex-pression seems to suggest a process rather manifest and objective is found in certain
than an object: an exteriorizing of an inner versions of phenomenology. When Husserl
content. Both the process and the content discusses "expression" (Ausdruck) in Ideen
defy customary "objective" description; I, he links it with "logical signification,"
standards of exactitude and rigor de- that is, with the fully explicit, the concep-
manded elsewhere in philosophy or science tual, the objective, with the realm of Logos
appear to be inapplicable to such an inde- or language in its universal character.4 The
terminate phenomenon. Whether it is reduc- analytic criteria of conventionality and
ible to a process or not, an expressive phe- publicity are replaced by notions of pure
nomenon such as a gesture, a cry, or a conceptuality and explicit meaning. In
painting has an adumbrative aspect that both cases, however, we may observe a tend-
cannot be neglected in any adequate de- ency to narrow the phenomenon of expres-
scription. The penumbral quality of expres- sion to its most objective, specifiable dimen-
sion eludes the tenterhooks of a traditional sions. There is nothing noxious about this
empiricist approach as well as a method of recourse to objectivity, especially in the case
eidetic insight. of language. For language, whether in its
In this plight, the move is frequently ordinary or in an ideal form, is a kind of
made to limit description to the manifest expression that must possess certain objec-
content of expression, banishing any latent tive rules of interpretation and of syntax;
content to the realm of the unknowable. these and other factors make possible the
One version of this move is found in recent sedimentation and transmission of meaning
ordinary language philosophy; linguistic on which interpersonal communication de-
expression is located in behavioral patterns pends.
of "utterance," which occurs within a con- But it can be questioned whether other
text of social conventions. As Austin writes: forms of human expression depend to such
"There must exist an accepted conventional a degree as does language on determinate
procedure having a certain conventional ef- rules, contents, or contexts. These other
fect, the procedure to include the uttering forms of expression include myth, gesture,
of certain words by certain persons in cer- and art. None is accurately classifiable as
tain circumstances." 1 An "inner process," "language" except in an extremely atten-
as Wittgenstein said, "stands in need of out- uated sense. This is largely because in these
instances expression is predominantly tacit.
EDWARD S. CASEYis assistant professor of philosophy The expressive phenomena which we en-
at Yale University. counter here do not essentially possess the

This content downloaded from 129.49.23.145 on Thu, 29 May 2014 11:04:30 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
198 E DW A RD S. CA SEY

kind of dimensions which can be made phenomenon of expression in art, and


fully overt or explicit. Such overtness and largely to a prevalent form of its misinter-
explicitness are permanent and necessary pretation. Expression in art has often been
features of ordinary and ideal languages; understood in terms more appropriate to
this is especially the case if we assume that verbal expression, as if the latter formed a
the destiny of verbal language is indeed paradigm case for all types of expression.
linked with Logos as the basis for concep- This occurs most conspicuously when aes-
tual objectivity. thetic expression is confused with commu-
We should also notice that the phenome- nication, as we shall see. Of course, there
nal surface of language differs markedly are other ways in which the linguistic
from that found in gesture, myth, or art. model subtly infects our understanding of
The felt surface of language does not in artistic expression-for example, by leading
itself typically engage our attention; what is us to look for a "hidden" meaning not pres-
presented to us phonically or in print-the ent in what we shall call, following D. W.
"vehicle"- is normally surpassed and even Prall, the "aesthetic surface." 6 All too many
suppressed as we attend to the specific theories of art make this transphenomenal
meaning conveyed by this vehicle. Contrast- move, only to discover in the end that a
ingly, in mythic, gestural, and aesthetic return to the phenomenon as originally pre-
phenomena our attention is riveted directly sented-i.e., to the aesthetic surface itself-
onto the phenomenal surface; what we are is necessary. Since my emphasis will be on
looking for happens at or on this surface, this "return to the phenomenon," my ap-
not beyond or behind it. The expressive proach will be phenomenological in a sense
meaning is not experienced as detached broad enough to encompass, though criti-
from the presented gesture, myth, or work cally, the pioneering efforts of Husserl and
of art; it is felt as inherent in the phenome- Merleau-Ponty.
nal surface. This surface is apprehended as A final preliminary note: the aesthetic
an intentional, not an actual, object.5 As a surface is not necessarily superficial; it may
consequence, the aesthetic object cannot be possess its own peculiar depth. The amount
either as arbitrary or as determinate as the and kind of depth depend primarily on im-
corresponding object in linguistic expres- port and its mode of integration into the
sion. The aesthetic object is not a mere aesthetic object. Import is meaning or sig-
point of transition, but something essen- nificance as it is experienced in art: mean-
tially intransitive. Our attention is arrested ing without the typical conceptual proper-
at the phenomenal surface of this object; it ties of abstractness and universality. It is
is detained, or rather retained, there by an sense as incorporated into the aesthetic ob-
adhesion of consciousness to what is felt or ject; we could equally well call it "expres-
seen. This surface is the primary expressive sive meaning," that is, meaning that forms
phenomenon; even though it is an inten- part of the expressiveness of a given
tional object, it can no longer be said to be phenomenon.7 In any event, it is import
"objective" in the sense of standing over that constitutes the depth dimension of the
against us as does a resistant perceptual ob- aesthetic surface. This surface has at least
ject. Even the "psychic distance" required two other crucial dimensions: the percep-
by some art forms does not entail the objec- tual and the affective. The perceived in art
tivity of the phenomenon in any way is the structural or formal aspect of the sur-
strictly comparable to the objectivity which face; it is the most explicitly specifiable ele-
functions in language or in mere percep- ment, even though its complete description
tion. This does not mean that the experi- is not always possible. Feeling or affective
ences of art, myth, or gesture are wholly quality is the connective tissue of the aes-
"subjective" or purely personal; in fact, our thetic surface; it is a sensuous tonality that
adhesion to the presented surface precludes characterizes the aesthetic object as a whole.
any total assimilation of the object by the But it characterizes by individualizing-by
self. infusing the object with a unique affective
In this paper I shall restrict myself to the tone.

This content downloaded from 129.49.23.145 on Thu, 29 May 2014 11:04:30 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Expression and Communication in Art 199
I veying thoughts, and art to transmitting
feelings. On the one hand, no one can deny
There is a recurrent tendency to connect, that there is expressive language (as in po-
and even to identify, expression and com- etry) or emotive language (as in a cry)
munication in art. Thus Martin Foss states whose content is primarily affective, not in-
flatly that "expression in the field of art is tellectual. Even if the ultimate telos of lan-
always communication." 8 Joseph Margolis guage is conceptual, it may still retain the
has observed recently that "the theory of capacity to convey and evoke emotions. In a
expression tends to encourage us to think of sense, it must keep this capacity, since emo-
fine art and the appreciation of fine art in tions are not always adequately expressed
terms of a communicative pattern between by gestures-as we know from the trying
artist and spectator." 9 This tendency is not experience of viewing a foreign film whose
confined to contemporary aestheticians: language is wholly unknown to us. On the
John Dewey claimed that "because the ob- other hand, art is not limited to feeling for
jects of art are expressive, they com- its content; it may also possess import. Ad-
municate." 10 Indeed, one discovers al- mittedly, the latter is not strictly conceptual
ready in Plato the idea that truly expressive in character, but neither can it be reduced
art communicates, almost in spite of itself, a to, or identified with, feeling or sentiment.14
specific message. In general, it has been the We should pay special attention to the
more austere and moralistic interpretations model of communication which Tolstoy
of art that, from Plato through Sartre, have and others assume to function both in art
most emphatically stressed its communica- and in language. Transmission is the key
tive aspect, often placing expression in the term used in describing this model, and it
service of communication. Yet even theories implies a sending of something across or
relatively unburdened by moral preoccupa- through a medium to reach a certain spe-
tions have understood art as a form of com- cific destination. There are three critical el-
munication, whether of thoughts or of feel- ements in this act of transmission: a content
ings; thus Kant, who limits art to being a transmitted, a medium through which the
"symbol" of morality, nevertheless links ex- content is transmitted, and the object at
pression and communication in art.ll which the transmission is aimed. Tolstoy
One reason for this pervasive though ulti- spells this out explicitly at another point in
mately perverse view of art is, as I have al- his discussion in "What is Art?":
ready suggested, a misleading use of linguis-
tic models for understanding aesthetic ex- To evoke in oneself a feeling one has once ex-
perienced, and having evoked it in oneself, then,
pression. Since language clearly communi- by means of movements, lines, colors, sounds, or
cates-indeed, is the chief means of commu- forms expressed in words, so to transmit that feel-
nication between human beings-expres- ing that others may experience the same feeling-
sion is held to do something similar. "Art, this is the activity of art.'5
like speech," said Tolstoy, "is a means of Leaving aside the question of what
communication." 12 Of course, such a bald "evoke" means here, we may observe the
assertion must be further qualified, for art main consequence of the three-term analysis
cannot communicate exactly as language of expression as communication: the rela-
loes or it might become superfluous. Hence tive devaluation of the middle term, which
Tolstoy adds that "whereas by words a man becomes merely a medium or means for
transmits his thoughts to another, by means conveying feeling from artist to spectator.
of art he transmits his feelings." 13 We may This devaluation is already a clue that
take this as a classic statement of the thesis something has gone wrong with the analy-
that expression in art is an activity of quasi- sis. For aesthetic experience is focused on
or paralinguistic communication. We must the aesthetic surface-in short, on the very
examine more closely the assumptions and "movements, lines, colors, sounds, or forms"
implications of such a contention. which Tolstoy sees as the mere means to
One assumption which we can reject im- something further. In aesthetic experience
mediately is that language is limited to con- itself, however, they are apprehended as in-

This content downloaded from 129.49.23.145 on Thu, 29 May 2014 11:04:30 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
200 EDWARD S. CASEY

herently attractive in themselves. Whether content becomes determinate by embodi-


it is feeling or thought on which we focus, ment in the aesthetic object during and
we contemplate it as ingredient in the aes- through the expressive act. In itself, this is
thetic surface, not as merely conveyed by it. certainly correct: if anything is determinate
The locus of what is expressed resides in in art, it is the embodied feeling or
the expressive object itself, not behind it in thought, not its disincarnate forerunner or
the artist's intentions or beyond it in the separable message.
spectator's reactions. We might call this The main problem with Merleau-Ponty's
phenomenon of surface presentation "fron- move, however, is that it ends by misinter-
tality," provided this term not be paired preting the nature of the aesthetic object
with a complementary "posteriority." Aes- itself. No longer viewed as an ephemeral
thetic frontality has been emphasized in di- medium, the object is given an actuality
verse ways, from the hieratic Egyptian pro- that it does not possess as experienced, that
file to "hard-edge" and "op" art, but its is, as an intentional object. It is said, for
meaning in the present context is simply example, to be a continuation of the body's
that the aesthetic surface presents itself as expressivity: "the expressive operation of
irrevocably frontal; even the unseen sides of the body, initiated by the slightest percep-
a three-dimensional sculpture present them- tion, is expanded into painting and into
selves as potential "fronts." This means art." 18 But if the work of art is an exten-
that our aesthetic attention is directed pri- sion of the body, it is at most an intentional
marily to the presented surface. Thus the or perhaps imaginary extension-not in the
"transmitted" content is seen more truly as sense of a phantom projection but of an
intromitted-sent from within the aesthetic object with a capacity to awaken or revive
object, not merely conveyed by or across it. our kinesthetic and synesthetic powers.
Yet even the metaphor of "sending" is More commonly, however, the aesthetic
questionable, since what is sent is normally object is interpreted as a mere perceptual
considered to be a message of some sort. object, e.g., as a "vehicle" or "support" for
The model of transmission especially en- non-material content or value.19 The bur-
courages the interpretation of content as den of objectivity is thus shifted from the
message. Thus Roger Fry writes: "If we message to the medium itself, and we end
take an analogy from the wireless-the art- with a doctrine of expression as a property
ist is the transmitter, the work of art the of perceptual qualities. This result is seen
medium, and the spectator the receiver ... in the writings of Rudolf Arnheim, who
for the message to come through, the re- claims that artistic "expression is an inher-
ceiver must be more or less in tune." 16 ent characteristic of perceptual patterns ...
Such a message or communique may con- [and] its manifestations in the human figure
tain a thought or a feeling; but in either are but a special case of a more general
case it will possess a definite form, so that it phenomenon." 20 In this view, the expres-
can be sent or imparted intact. On the com- sive medium is given objectivity through a
munication model, there is a tendency to reduction to its perceptual determinants;
consider aesthetic content as something even the body's expressiveness, seen as pri-
quite determinate, even when the term mes- mary by Merleau-Ponty, is held to be deriv-
sage is not explicitly used. Merleau-Ponty ative from the putative perceptual absolute
appears to succumb to this temptation found in perceptual patterns.
when he writes that "aesthetic expression What is missing from an interpretation
confers on what it expresses [i.e., its con- such as Arnheim's is an adequate apprecia-
tent] an existence in itself, installs it in na- tion of the distinction between the sensuous
ture as a thing perceived and accessible to and the perceptual in art. The sensuous is
all." 17 At least this is not to claim, as Tol- the affective dimension which accounts for
stoy and Fry would, that the communicated the cohesiveness of the expressive, as well as
content exists as determinate before the act for the feeling of continuity between aes-
of expression. Instead, Merleau-Ponty thetic object and spectator. The latter feels
wishes to underline the way in which the as well as perceives art; what he perceives

This content downloaded from 129.49.23.145 on Thu, 29 May 2014 11:04:30 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Expression and Communication in Art 201
are certain structural patterns, but he feels structural element within which the sen-
their impact and tension. Affective content suous appears.
in art cannot be reduced to perceptual giv- These two primary forms of the commu-
ens. The perceived must mingle and blend nication thesis are sometimes combined in a
with elements of affect and import to com- third view. The aesthetic object is seen as
pose the complex aesthetic surface; the per- both perceptually expressive in itself and
ceived is not merely the empirical support yet also as indicative of a transphenomenal
for this surface, and it is not the sole basis content. The medium retains a certain sub-
for the intransitive character of the aes- stantiality only to become a sign for this
thetic object. It is only one element among ultimate "meaning" of the work. Such a
others equally crucial. meaning is not conveyed to the spectator
directly (as in the ideal of the first view) but
II as indicated by the perceptual medium.
Thus the medium becomes the medium for
Thus far, we have observed two ways of the message in the sense that all indicative
construing the thesis that expression in art signs stand "for" their designatum. The me-
is a form of communication. First, the phe- dium acts as what Tolstoy, in another pas-
nomenon of art is seen as analogous to lan- sage, calls an "external indication": "Art
guage, hence as possessing a determinate begins when one person, with the object of
content transmitted through a diaphanous joining another or others to himself in one
medium. This content may be viewed as and the same feeling, expresses that feeling
pure feeling, as with Tolstoy; but it is even by certain external indications." 21 On this
more frequently interpreted as thought in view, expressivity in art becomes a phenom-
the form of a moral truth, as in Plato or enon of indication, in which content is
Sartre. In general, the more determinate communicated indicatively by the percep-
the content, the less important the medium tual ("external") medium.
is held to be; the acme of expressive com- To understand why this claim is false, we
munication would be reached if the me- need to know more about the nature of
dium were to become wholly transparent or indication. Husserl provides an acute analy-
even to disappear altogether. But there is a sis of this basic sign-function in the first of
second view of communication whereby the his Logische Untersuchungen. Husserl sees
analogy with language is muted, and the indication as a relation of sign-reference be-
medium is raised into special prominence. tween one term, of whose existence one has
Expressivity is located squarely within the present perceptual knowledge, and another
perceptual patterns of the medium, as in term whose existence is known or presumed
Arnheim's contention, and it is this expres- on the basis of the first. Thus the indicative
sivity that is said to be communicated to relation is indexical or denotative, the exist-
the spectator. This interpretation has the ence of one term serving to convince the
merit of not confusing "what is expressed" sign-interpreter of the existence of the
with something mental or conceptual, but other. If such a relation were to be found in
it tends to reduce the expressed to the per- art as Tolstoy claims, the aesthetic surface
would have to be interpreted as a percep-
ceptually determinate, as we saw in the
statement from Merleau-Ponty. This is the tual object indexically pointing to another
position of extreme perceptual objectivism object (which could itself be perceptual or
in art; the aesthetic object becomes a tran- conceptual in character). The only link be-
tween the two phenomena would be an act
scendent perceived particular. The role of of "association" whereby the one motivated
feeling is neglected-not only the viewer's us to believe in the other.
or artist's feeling but more crucially the sen- Yet nothing like this occurs in our expe-
suousness that permeates the aesthetic rience of genuinely expressive art. There is
surface as a whole. This sensuous factor no indexical, hence external, relation either
cannot be equated with what is perceived; within the aesthetic object or between this
on the contrary, the perceived is only the object and some other object. Instead, all

This content downloaded from 129.49.23.145 on Thu, 29 May 2014 11:04:30 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
202 EDWARD S. CASEY

significant elements in aesthetic experience manifestation. Croce, who rejects the no-
are apprehended as copresent and copre- tion of communication in art as belonging
sented. At most, the various aspects or ele- to mere "technique" and hence to the
ments resemble each other iconically-in an "practical" sphere, nevertheless contends
act of reciprocal mimesis-but they do not that artistic expression includes "every sort
denote one another. Only if the sensuous of manifestation." 23 D. W. Gotshalk defines
surface were converted into a hard percep- expression as "a kind of objectification or
tulm or if the import were transformed into objective manifestation of whatever is said
a pure concept, would we begin to have a to be expressed." 24 In contrast with com-
situation in which indication could occur munication, manifestation as a term has the
in art. But this would mean the destruction merit of de-emphasizing the notion that art
of the aesthetic surface. Whatever the ori- merely transmits a given content to the
gin of the elements in this surface, once spectator. Instead, it stresses the presenta-
they are part of the aesthetic object they tional character of the aesthetic object. The
must all exhibit a common sensuousness for model for manifestation is often an act of
expression in art to be possible. This sen- "disclosure" which may (a) take time in
suousness acts as an indelible monogram which to unfold; (b) require extensive inter-
and cannot be distorted or reduced without pretation; (c) retain some unapprehended
losing the unique affective quality that pro- aspects even following disclosure. This view
vides the aesthetic object with its character- of manifestation lies at the heart of many
istic coherence. The intrusion of the indica- theories of art as possessing symbolic, meta-
tive relation into this rich qualitative tex- physical, or ontological significance. Hei-
ture would mean the disintegration of a degger's interpretive essays on Holderlin
seamless whole. are among the more extravagant examples
We should also observe that if Husserl is of this type of approach.25
correct, all communication is indicative in Yet the idea of art as manifestation is
nature; and strictly speaking, communica- subject to the same basic error as the theo-
tion is restricted to language. Thus he ries of art as communication examined
writes that "in communicative discourse all above. For manifestation is itself a form of
expressions function as indices." 22 As a re- indication understood in the broad Hus-
sult, any attempt to interpret art as commu- serlian sense of Anzeige to which we have
nicative in nature will fail, for it will always appealed. In fact, it is a modification of the
involve the more or less pronounced effort communicative act. This is most clearly
to force indication into the heart of expres- seen in Husserl's further analysis of verbal
sion. Yet the two are incompatible in art-a communication, where there is said to be a
fact we realize each time we are confronted mutual manifestation between speaker and
with the grosser forms of Socialist Realism. hearer of their respective "psychic experi-
Only in language and (less explicitly) in ences" (Erlebnisse). Such experiences form
gesture can expression and communication the content of manifestation: a content in-
coexist successfully. And while communica- dicated by the spoken or written words of
tion is a legitimate and necessary feature of discourse. These words are taken as "dis-
language and gesture, it is a falsifying and tinctive signs" (Kennzeichen) of psychic
even corrupting presence in art, diverting content. But manifestation, so conceived,
art from its proper purpose: expression. would be as destructive of the aesthetic sur-
face as was the original thesis of communi-
III cation. The autonomy of this surface is de-
nied in analyzing it into signs designating
The communication theory of art dies otherwise inaccessible inner experiences.
hard. It tends to reappear under guises On Husserl's view, in expression proper
more sophisticated than Tolstoy's simple no such signs are necessary; all indicative
transmission model or his related view that relations of association or motivation disap-
the work of art is an indicative sign. One of pear. A signification (Bedeutung) animates
the most frequent of these guises is that of the expression. This signification is a self-

This content downloaded from 129.49.23.145 on Thu, 29 May 2014 11:04:30 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Expression and Communication in Art 203
sufficient content; there is no further pri- ception in which all reference is (a) internal
mary reference to something else (though and (b) iconic in nature. The principal le-
there can be secondary references). Expres- gitimate sign-relation is one of mutual re-
sion in its pure state occurs prototypically semblance between elements within the aes-
in silent monologue, where all one's psychic thetic surface. If this reciprocal similarity is
acts are experienced "at once" (im selben consummately successful, the work of art
Azugenblick). In such a state, all manifesta- presents itself as an icon of itself-i.e., as a
tion, even to oneself, becomes unnecessary self-resembling sign in which the terms are
because one is already fully revealed to one- no longer radically distinct but potentially
self. This means that the perceptual factor, identical. A coalescence of similarities tends
bound up with all indicative signs, may toward, even if it never fully achieves,
even be eliminated: iconic self-identity.28
that which is to serve as an index (a distinctive
sign) must be perceived by us as existent (da-
IV
seiend). This holds especially for expressions in
communicative discourse, but not for expressions In speaking of communication and mani-
in solitary discourse.26 festation in art, we have been able to make
only indirect references to the role of the
Therefore, manifestation is inexorably other. I would like now to consider the
ap
bound up with communication (we commu-
prehension of the other viewed as a possible
nicate by means of manifesting our psychic
analogue to the contemplation of the aes-
states), and both phenomena are indicative thetic object. This analogy has been ex-
by nature. They both lack what only pure ploited by a number of aestheticians. Miikel
expression possessess: an intrinsic significa- Dufrenne likens the aesthetic object to a
tion or meaning. This meaning animates
"quasi-subject" because of its near-human
the expression. Lacking this animation, expressivity; the aesthetic
object is seen as
communication and manifestation are de- an
analogue of a human face or body.29 R.
pendent on perceptual existents in the form G. Collingwood compares the experience of
of indicative signs; hence they are empiri- art to the
speaker-hearer relation in spoken
cally mediated in character. The mundane discourse: just as thought can be recon-
substantiality of these signs is a surrogate structed on the basis of the appropriate
for the immediacy and direct animation of sounds, so the work of art can be "re-en-
pure expression, which can deploy itself acted" by the spectator on the basis of cer-
freely in the imaginary. tain "impressions." Collingwood calls this
For this reason, expression in art is itself
process one of "communication," though he
never pure. The perceptual component can cautions that it is not a matter of mere
never be wholly eliminated as in interior transmission.30 The
assumption is made
monologue. What can and must be brack- that the impressions, also called "psychical
eted, however, is the perceptual component feelings," function much as words do: that
apprehended as an indicative sign. This ex- communicating with, and apprehending,
clusion of the indicative sign-relation from the other are events
parallel to what hap-
art applies both to its apparent denotative pens in the
experience of art as expressive.
aspect (e.g., in representational painting) Dufrenne makes much the same
and to its authentic connotative aspect (by tion. But is the assump-
assumption valid?
which the aesthetic object may possess a I do not believe that it is. It is true that
plural import). The aesthetic surface is nei- the aesthetic object and the other both pos-
ther an isolated indicative sign nor itself a sess an expressivity which we sometimes call
species of indicative sign-language. It is not by the same name: "physiognomic." By this,
even "self-designating," if this term is taken we presumably mean that
expressive fea-
to mean a re-introduction of the indexical tures in a work of art may have a
strikingly
relation in terms of self-reference.27Rather, human "look," although there may be no
the aesthetic surface is an automomous tex- recognizably human object present or de-
ture of presented import, feeling, and per- picted. Thus we might catch ourselves say-

This content downloaded from 129.49.23.145 on Thu, 29 May 2014 11:04:30 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
204 EDWARD S. CASEY

ing that a certain abstract expressionist other is in terms of how we perceive the
painting is suffused with a frenetic quality two phenomena in question. In the case of
quite similar to the personality of someone the other person, what we perceive is taken
we know. Of course, the descriptive terms as a sign of something inherently non-per-
of the analogy are often imprecise, since ceptual-i.e., inner thoughts and feelings
physiognomic characters are notoriously which on principle can never become ob-
difficult to name with precision. But it is jects of perception. When we perceive the
undeniable that on occasion we may feel a aesthetic object, however, the perceptual el-
"community of essence" between a person ement is not taken as a sign or even as a
(often the artist himself) and a painting. symbol of something unperceivable, but as
What must rather be denied is that the aes- a constituent part of the aesthetic surface.
thetic object always, or necessarily, possesses In the latter, feeling and thought are ren-
a distinctly physiognomic aura. It may be dered sensuous, hence can coexist with the
felt as non-human altogether, as in certain perceived in a common affective whole.
of Tanguy's desolate surrealist landscapes. Thus perception is indispensable in art,
Thus the physiognomic is by no means a but its aim is exhausted in what is con-
permanent trait of art, which can be expres- cretely presented, whereas the perception of
sive in other ways. the other typically transcends the presented
There is a more fundamental respect, toward what Husserl calls the "appre-
however, in which confrontation with art sented."32 The appresented supplements
differs from confrontation with the other. the directly presented because of the una-
This is found in the fact that the other vailability of the other's Erlebnis. By con-
possesses a privacy and inwardness denied trast, the work of art is capable of self-pres-
to the aesthetic object regarded as a surface entation, that is, an open disclosure of its
with no aesthetically relevant interior. Yet surface without any significant undisclosed
the other's interiority is inalienable, even residue. Hence appresentational supple-
though we cannot feel his experience from mentation is not necessary.
within. There is no direct or privileged ac- This point can be made without invok-
cess to the other's "inscape"; only the other ing the elaborate trappings involved in
can live his own psychic acts immediately Husserl's theory of the analogical "transfer
and simultaneously. Hence we can ap- of sense" that occurs in perceiving the
proach these inner acts in the other only other. All we need observe is that interper-
indirectly, by inferring their existence from sonal expression in language or gesture is
certain indicative signs. The necessity for not only incomplete but inevitably indica-
such signs is the result of the radical non- tive as well. The other can never express
presence of the other's Erlebnisse to us; we himself with his "whole being." 33 Bodily
need the mediating clues provided by writ- gestures are never totally expressive because
ten or spoken language, by certain bodily they aim constantly at an exteriorization; as
gestures, clothing habits, etc. Only these Merleau-Ponty said, they "recuperate the
manifest the other. As Jacques Derrida re- world," making "what they aim at appear
marks, "if communication or manifestation outside." 34 This means that in the case of
is essentially indicative, this is because the the other's gesture the perceptual element is
presence of the other's Erlebnis is refused to never made wholly congruent with the
our originary intuition." 31 In art, however, affective or thought dimensions; rather, the
we have no need of such clues, for there is perceptual tends to achieve a determinate-
nothing interior or hidden to be revealed. ness that is exterior in character, as if the
Indication is absent from aesthetic expres- phenomenal crust could somehow restore or
sion because it would fulfill no function at least signify its inner core. It is this very
there; in fact, its encroachment upon ex- exteriority that is subdued, if not entirely
pression represents, as we have seen, the de- eliminated, in art-without a compensating
struction of the latter. interiority being required. The perceived
Another way of viewing the basic differ- remains, but not as an exteriorizing or out-
ence between the aesthetic object and the standing factor. It merges with the other

This content downloaded from 129.49.23.145 on Thu, 29 May 2014 11:04:30 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Expression and Communication in Art 205
ingredients of the aesthetic surface. In this and this retains an abiding "coefficient of
way, it avoids playing an indicative role, adversity." 38 Dewey claimed that "to ex-
allowing aesthetic expression to emerge press is to stay by, to carry forward in de-
from the surface as a whole. velopment, to work out to completion." 39
The relation to the other, by contrast, is But such completion is not possible in
always marked by the indicative. Thus Hus- aesthetic expression; if it were, art would
serl revealingly sought pure expression pre- be no longer necessary; it would be merely
cisely in the suspension of this relation, in a historical gesture annihilating itself in its
"the solitary life of the soul." 35 For pure very accomplishment.
expressivity to occur, the relation to the It is at this concluding point that we
other must be bracketed, since the irrevoca- must distinguish aesthetic expression from
ble non-presence of the other's inner self the givenness of an essence. An essence in
demands indicative mediation. It is in this the Husserlian sense possesses full self-pres-
sense that "the relation to the other as non- ence and intuitive plenitude; thus it is ca-
presence represents the impurity of pable of giving itself "in person." Such
expression." 36 We should add that if pure total self-givenness is not an inherent fea-
expressivity is to be found in the self-pres- ture of the aesthetic object. It would be
ence of the transcendental ego,37 a corre- more accurate to speak of "self-presenta-
sponding sheer expressivity is present in tion" in art, recalling that the "self" in
art, from which the perceptual component question is only a quasi-self. In any case,
cannot be wholly removed. But it can be the aesthetic surface does not present itself
removed qua indicative, and we may con- with the "originary evidence" of an essence,
clude that art is like a "quasi-subject" not and there is no "adequate insight" that
in its physiognomic character but rather in could grasp it as a total phenomenon. The
the very absence of indicative relations. role of the perceptual component may be
Neither the transcendental ego nor the modified through an "aesthetic reduction"
work of art needs the mediation of indica- of the indicative and the distracting, but it
tive signs to realize their distinctive forms can never be wholly removed so as to reveal
of presence. an intuitive content belonging to the
sphere of Logos. Husserl's analysis in Ideen
V I, suggestive as it is with respect to expres-
sion in art, assumes throughout that expres-
But if expression in art can thus be sion, once fully achieved, belongs to "the
"sheer," it cannot be total. Even if sen- original medium of the Logos." 40 Expres-
suousness (operating through temporal and sion is "integral," that is, total, when it
spatial schemata) is capable of unifying the "places the seal of conceptual signification
notional and perceptual components of the on all of the synthetic forms and matters of
aesthetic object into a single, continuous the underlying level." 41
aesthetic surface in which expression is un- This may indeed be the case with regard
defiled by indicative relations, the resulting to language, but in the aesthetic surface
expressiveness is not totally expressive. A signification is not so much delimiting as
sheer phenomenon is not necessarily a total delimited. In this phenomenon, significa-
phenomenon. In fact, a total expression tion exists in the form of import, and im-
would be, through its very excess, inexpres- port is fused with the other pervasive ele-
sive. Expression in art requires resistance, ments. The animated expressiveness of the
limitation, form-hence a certain incom- whole is held tensionally at the surface; it is
pleteness. Expressive animation in art oper- not allowed to escape from this surface to-
ates only against and within the aesthetic ward a separate conceptual domain. Struc-
medium; this medium, whether it is con- ture or form in art comes largely from the
ceived as predominantly perceptual, imagi- perceived, not the conceived; but percep-
national, or affective, cannot be eliminated tual presence is itself exceeded by the em-
to reveal die Sache selbst. The only "thing blematic expressivity spread sensuously
itself" in art is the sheer aesthetic surface, throughout the felt surface. The depths of

This content downloaded from 129.49.23.145 on Thu, 29 May 2014 11:04:30 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
206 EDWARD S. CASEY

this surface are only obliquely, never trans- in this compresence. At best, a vivid com-
parently, given; no essence, least of all an munion takes place: an experience in which
essence of expressiveness itself, is shown on aesthetic expression is most fully realized.
or through its dense affective texture.42 But
the expression never becomes wholly exter-
nal; it does not give itself away; it never 1J. L. Austin, How to Do Things with Words (Ox-
becomes entirely express. What Merleau- ford Univ. Press, 1965), p. 26.
Ponty once said of language is, in this case, 2 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investiga-
more descriptive of art: it cannot "detach tions, 1: 580.
8See, for example, Sellars, Science and Metaphys-
itself entirely from the precariousness of the ics (Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1968) pp. 73-77; Hamp-
forms of mute expression, reabsorb its own shire, Feeling and Expression (H. K. Lewis, 1961),
contingency, or consume itself to make the passim.
4 Ideen I, sec. 124-27.
things themselves appear." 43 Art holds its
6 For this distinction, see J. N. Findlay, "The Per-
expressiveness within or on its surface ap- spicuous and the Poignant: Two Aesthetic Funda-
prehended as a self-continuous, frontal phe- mentals," in British Journal of Aesthetics 7 (1967):
nomenon with its own peculiar depth. This 13.
expressiveness is neither explicitly sayable 6 See D. W. Prall, Aesthetic Judgment (New York:
in language nor adequately intuitable in ei- Crowell, 1929), passim.
7 On the concept of "expressive meaning," see
detic insight. The voices of art are indeed Paul C. Hayner, "Expressive Meaning," in Journal
the voices of silence, as Malraux said so of Philosophy 53 (1956): 149; and my "Meaning in
eloquently; but these voices can also be Art," in New Essays in Phenomenology, ed. James
sheerly expressive and thoroughly ani- M. Edie (Chicago: Quadrangle, 1969).
8 Symbol and Myth in Human Experience (Prince-
mated.
ton Univ. Press, 1949), p. 117. Cf. the statement of
Therefore, if expression in art is never L. Abercrombie: "expression in art is also communi-
total, it is at least sensuously alive; and it is cation" (in "Communication versus Expression in
this affective aliveness that, drawing con- Art," British Journal of Psychology 14 [1923]: 70).
9 Philosophy Looks at the Arts (New York: Scrib-
sciousness toward adhesion to the aesthetic
ner's, 1962), p. 29.
surface, quickens our life of feeling. Expres- 10Art as Experience (New York: Capricorn, 1958),
sion in art is misconstrued as communica- p. 104.
tion, but it may be interpreted as commun- 11The Critique of Judgment, trans. James C.
ion between the work of art and the specta- Meredith (Oxford Univ. Press, 1952), pp. 180, 183-
tor. Rare though it is, it is precisely in such 84.
12""What Is Art?" in Tolstoy on Art, trans. and ed.
an experience that expression in art is most Aylmer Maude (Oxford Univ. Press, 1924), p. 278.
nearly complete. Yet as it is never fully "Ibid., p. 171.
complete, genuine aesthetic expression can- 14This is the danger that lurks behind C. J. Du-
not be assimilated to other modes of expres- casse's use of the term "emotional import" or Su-
sanne Langer's similar "vital import"; both seem to
sion which, like language, are capable of suggest that feeling and meaning become wholly in-
contextual or conceptual objectivity and distinguishable in the aesthetic object. I shall main-
which can thus play a role in communica- tain that they blend without losing their singular
tion or manifestation. Truly expressive art identities. See C. J. Ducasse, Art, the Critics, and
You (New York, 1955), pp. 52-56; S. Langer, Feeling
does not communicate; it possesses neither and Form (New York, 1953), pp. 31, 52, 59, 65, as
the basis (indicative sign-relations) nor the well as her Problems of Art (New York, 1957), pp.
content (the "message") of communication. 59-60.
Its sensuousness provides the foundation 1""What Is Art?" p. 173; in italics in the original.
for contemplation and, ultimately, com- See also M. Heidegger's similar analysis of communi-
cation in Being and Time, trans. C. Robinson & J.
munion. The latter defies objective descrip- Macquarrie (New York: Harper, 1962), pp. 197-8,
tion, since in this experience the aesthetic 205,211-12.
object qua object dissolves. We are left not so ' Last Lectures (Cambridge, 1939); quoted by E.
much with a process as with a continuous H. Gombrich, Meditations on a Hobby Horse (New
York: Phaidon, 1965), p. 56.
phenomenon in which consciousness and 17Phenomenology of Perception, trans. C. Smith
aesthetic surface momentarily coalesce. (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1962), p. 183;
Nothing is transmitted or even manifested cf. M. Heidegger, p. 266.

This content downloaded from 129.49.23.145 on Thu, 29 May 2014 11:04:30 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Expression and Communication in Art 207
1Signes (Gallimard, 1960), p. 87; Signs, trans. prets self-reference in terms of denotation, as on p.
Richard C. McCleary (Northwestern Univ. Press, 59 n; see also p. 4 f.
1964), p. 70. 'gSee Mikel Dufrenne, Phenomdnologie de l'ex-
18I am thinking especially of Max Scheler's con- perience esthetique (Presses Universitaires de France,
cept of Traiger as this has been applied to aesthetics 1953), I: 197,200,249,255-6,291, 302, 306 f., 408-9.
by Eugen Fink in his essay "Vergegenwartigung und Principles of Art (Oxford Univ. Press, 1938), p.
Bild" (esp. sec. 31-33), reprinted in Fink's Studien 140.
zur Phiinomenologie (Nijhoff, 1966). 31La Voix et le phdnomene (Paris: Presses Uni-
20 R. Arnheim, Art and Visual Perception (Univ. versitaires de France, 1967), p. 43.
of California Press, 1963), pp. 347-48. 82See Cartesian Meditations, trans. D. Cairns
Tolstoy, p. 171. (Nijhoff, 1960), sec. 50-54.
22See E. Husserl, Logische Untersuchungen (Nie- 33As Pauline Kael claims of Greta Garbo in her
meyer, 1913), vol. II, I, chap. 1, sec. 7. review "In Vain" in the New Yorker, Jan. 11, 1969,
23 B. Croce, Aesthetic, trans. D. Ainslie (New York, p. 64.
1956), p. 8. "Signes, p. 84; Signs, p. 67; my italics. Cf. M.
24 D. W. Gotshalk, "Aesthetic Expression," JAAC, Heidegger, "What is expressed is precisely. . Being-
(Sept. 1954): p. 80. outside" (Being and Time, p. 205).
25 See M. Heidegger, Eriauterungen zu Holderlins 3 Logische Untersuchungen, vol. II, I, sec. 8.
Dichtung (Frankfort: Klostermann, 1951). " J. Derrida, p. 44.
26 Husserl, Logische Untersuchungen, vol. II, I, 37 For this notion, see Husserl, Ideen II (Nijhoff,
sec. 8: my italics. 1952), p. 105.
27Eugen Fink employs this term in his Studien "8This term, first used by Gaston Bachelard, is
zur Phdnomenologie, p. 72. Of course, "self-designa- developed by Jean-Paul Sartre in Being and Noth-
tion" does have the merit of underlining the in- ingness, trans. Hazel Barnes (Philosophical Library,
transitive character of the work of art; but this in- 1956), pt. 4.
transitivity should not be conceived in terms of an 89J. Dewey, Art as Experience, p. 64.
internal indicative relation. 40Sec. 126.
28I1 am thinking of icon in the sense of "iconic 41Ibid.
sign" as originally formulated by C. S. Peirce in 421 am thinking here of Bernard Bosanquet's use
Collected Papers, ed. C. Hartshorne and P. Weiss of the term "expressive a priori" in Three Lectures
(Harvard Univ. Press, 1960), 2.282, 3.556, 4.448, on Aesthetic (New York: Macmillan, 1923), chap. 2;
4.531. One could also speak here of "metaphorical see also Mikel Dufrenne, The Notion of the A
self-exemplification" in following out the suggestions Priori, trans. Edward S. Casey (Northwestern Univ.
of Nelson Goodman in Languages of Art (New York: Press, 1966), pp. 110-13.
Bobbs-Merrill, 1968), chap. 2. But Goodman inter- 43Signes, p. 98; Signs, p. 78.

This content downloaded from 129.49.23.145 on Thu, 29 May 2014 11:04:30 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Вам также может понравиться