Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 4

H

Hart, H.L.A. in the world; in Hart’s terminology, these propo-


sitions “ascribe” legal conclusions (Hart
Brian H. Bix 1948–1949). Under this analysis, when a judge
Law and Philosophy, University of Minnesota, declares that “A and B have a valid contract,” that
Minneapolis, MN, USA judge is creating a new legal reality (in analogy to
the presiding clergy who states “I now pro-
nounced you man and wife”), rather than
Introduction purporting to describe some preexisting truth.
Secondly, Hart argued that legal reasoning and
H.L.A. (Herbert Lionel Adolphus) Hart legal concepts are essentially defeasible (Hart
(1907–1992) is probably the most influential 1948–1949, 174–183) – e.g., the way that offer,
English-language legal philosopher of the twenti- acceptance, and consideration (under English or
eth century. He is best known for his work on American law) are sufficient to show a contract to
theories of the nature of law, in particular, for his be valid, but if one of the party shows the contract
version of legal positivism. In addition, Hart made to have been entered under fraud or duress, the
important contributions to the debates about the contract then becomes void or voidable, despite
legal enforcement of morality, legal rights, causa- the presence of offer, acceptance, and consider-
tion, and punishment. There is a substantial liter- ation. Hart later disowned or downplayed both of
ature on his work – among the best sources are these ideas (e.g., Hart 1983, 1–2); however, the
MacCormick (2008) and Bayles (1992), the col- second, the defeasibility of legal reasoning and
lections Gavison (1987) and Hacker and Raz legal concepts, was nonetheless taken up, in dif-
(1977), and, for the works in the context of the ferent forms, by a number of scholars (e.g., Ferrer
life, Lacey (2004); many scholars continue to and Ratti 2012).
elaborate Hart’s approach to many topics.

Hart and Legal Positivism


Early Work
While how best to define and delimit the approach
In one of his earliest works, Hart introduced two to law and legal theory known as “legal positiv-
provocative ideas. First, he argued that judicial ism” remains controversial, that approach is gen-
decisions should be seen as performatives – not erally equated with the distinction between
propositions that purport to describe the world but questions of validity of legal norms and the label-
sentences that do something or change something ing of systems as “legal,” on one hand, and the
# Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2018
M. Sellers, S. Kirste (eds.), Encyclopedia of the Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy,
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6730-0_117-2
2 Hart, H.L.A.

(moral) merits of those norms or systems, on the normative social structure,” “the methodology of
other (Bix 2015, 33–37). Legal positivism is gen- the empirical sciences is useless; what is needed is
eral contrasted with natural law theory, which a ‘hermeneutic’ method which involves
holds (among other things) that moral evaluation portraying rule-governed behaviour as it appears
is central to determining whether a system war- to its participants” (Hart 1983, 13).
rants the label “law” or a rule is a valid legal norm Another contrast between Hart’s theory and
(or that this system and this norm are “law” and that of his predecessor, John Austin, regarded
“legal” in the fullest form or central case of those whether to think of legal rules as having a single
categories (Finnis 2011, 9–11)). essence. Against a view that reduced all legal rules
Hart’s significance was in moving the to variations on some single type, as Austin’s
(English-language) legal positivism of his time theory seemed to reduce all legal rules to com-
from the command theory associated with John mands (and Hans Kelsen’s comparable reduction
Austin toward a less empirical and more herme- of all legal rules to authorizations to officials to
neutic approach. Hart’s view of law was grounded impose sanctions (Kelsen 1967, 111–119)), Hart
on his views of rules, in particular on a view of the emphasized the multiplicity of law. He contrasted
difference between rules and habits. According to rules that imposed duties with those that conferred
Hart, the difference between these two kinds of powers (whether power conferred on officials
regularities of behavior can be seen through the within the legal system, or the delegation of cer-
participants’ attitudes. With habits, the statement tain legal powers to citizens, as can be said to
of the behavior is nothing more than a description: occur through the operation of rules for contracts,
e.g., I play basketball every Saturday. With a rule, wills, trusts, and so on), and he contrasted rules
however, the statement can take on additional that applied directly to citizens (“primary rules”)
roles: as an explanation, a justification, and a and rules that governed the operation of the rule
basis for criticizing deviation. The statement has system itself (“secondary rules”). The secondary
a normative role. Many people are not merely “in rules include rules of change, rules of adjudica-
the habit” of obeying the authorities; they have tion, and the rule of recognition. Hart further
internalized the rules as reasons for acting in argued that there were two necessary and suffi-
certain ways and for criticizing others when they cient conditions for the existence of a legal sys-
do not behave as required. tem: (1) that the valid rules of the system “must be
Hart argued that John Austin’s theory, with its generally obeyed” and (2) that the criteria set forth
equation of law with commands (orders backed by in the system’s rule of recognition “must be effec-
threats), invited a confusion between imposed tively accepted as common public standards of
force and accepted norms. Hart asserted that a official behaviour by its officials” (Hart 2012,
legal system is something different from, and 116).
presumably something better than, the rule over Central to Hart’s theory is the concept of a rule
a frightened populace by gangsters. Many citizens of recognition: the set of criteria by which the
do not act according to the law simply because of officials determine which rules are, and which
fear, simply because they feel coerced; citizens rules are not, part of the legal system. The stan-
who (in Hart’s terms) take an “internal point of dards applied are referred to as justifications for
view” toward the law view the law as giving them the actions of the officials, though to some extent
reasons for action. Hart’s emphasizing the internal the standards are also created by those actions.
perspective, his belief that one cannot understand The rule of recognition expresses, or symbolizes,
a social system unless one understands how the the basic tenet of legal positivism: that there are
people who created the system or who participate conventional criteria, agreed upon by officials, for
in the system perceive it, constituted a “herme- determining which rules are and which are not
neutic” approach, in contrast to the more “behav- part of the legal system; this in turn points to the
ioral” or “scientific” approach of other theorists. separation of the identification of the law from its
In Hart’s words, to understand “any form of moral evaluation and the separation of statements
Hart, H.L.A. 3

about what the law is from statements about what undergird society. Hart’s response largely tracked
it should be. John Stuart Mill’s “Harm Principle” (Mill 1974)
In discussing legal reasoning, Hart concluded but also introduced the important distinction
that judges inevitably use their discretion in hard between “conventional morality” (what people
cases to make new law, particularly on the occa- believe morality to required) and “critical moral-
sions where the legal rules have “open texture” ity” (what morality actually requires). Hart
(Hart 2012, 123–136). He also argued that this asserted that the defense of a community’s con-
was a benefit, not a problem, that judicial law- ventional morality would not justify the interfer-
making at the margins gave needed flexibility to ence with liberty that the legal enforcement of
the application of legal rules. (sexual) morality would entail, especially as
Prominent criticisms of Hart’s approach to law there was little evidence, historically, that changes
and legal theory include those derived from the in a society’s conventional morality generally
procedural natural law theory of Lon Fuller (1958, undermined society.
1969), the traditional (Thomistic) natural law the- Second, in the area of legal rights, Hart advo-
ory of John Finnis (2007, 2011), the interpretive cated a “will theory” (as contrasted to the “interest
theory of Ronald Dworkin (1977, 1986), and the theory”). This approach claimed that choice is
exclusive legal positivism of Joseph Raz (1990, central to the nature of rights. Hart analyzed rights
2009). Some of the most heated debates surround in terms of a protected bilateral liberty, with the
Dworkin’s critiques of Hart’s approach. Dworkin right holder “being given by the law exclusive
argued (among other things) that judges do not control, more or less extensive, over another per-
have discretion (in any strong or Meaning Full son’s duty so that in the area of conduct covered
sense of that term), but rather that there was by that duty the individual who has the right is a
always or almost always a preexisting right small-scale sovereign to whom the duty is owed”
answer to legal disputes, that legal systems (Hart 1982: 183).
contained principles as well as rules, and that no Third, Hart’s work on punishment (Hart 2008)
conventional and content-neutral “rule of recog- offered a compromise between consequentialist
nition” could distinguish legal from nonlegal and deontological schools, arguing for a deonto-
standards – that moral evaluation was central to logical/retributivist approach to whom to punish
determining what the law required. Hart replied to (no punishing of the innocent, regardless of how
some of Dworkin’s arguments in a posthumously good the consequences might be) but a conse-
published Postscript to his The Concept of Law quentialist approach to how much to punish.
(Hart 2012, 238–276). One should also mention the comprehensive
study Hart did with Tony Honoré on causation in
the law (Hart and Honoré 1985) and the valuable
Other Contributions efforts Hart gave to having the works of Jeremy
Bentham edited and published (a process that is
There is space only for brief mentions of other still ongoing under the auspices of The Bentham
areas where Hart’s works were influential. First, Project). Many of Hart’s writings on Bentham are
Hart had a series of exchanges with Lord Patrick brought together in a published collection (Hart
Devlin regarding the legal enforcement of moral 1982).
norms (Hart 1963; Devlin 1965). Devlin was
responding to the 1957 Wolfenden Report, which
had suggested that prostitution and homosexuality Conclusion
be decriminalized; the report argued that such
matters of “private morality” were not the law’s H. L. A. Hart’s primary significance for legal
business. Devlin argued that communities had a philosophy was his development of a hermeneutic
right to defend themselves against actions that and convention-based legal positivist theory of
would undermine the shared morality that the nature of law, an approach that remains central
4 Hart, H.L.A.

to contemporary Anglo-American jurisprudence. Finnis JM (2011) Natural law and natural rights, 2nd edn.
He is also properly remembered for important Oxford University Press, Oxford
Fuller LL (1958) Positivism and fidelity to law – a reply to
works on causation, punishment, defeasibility, Professor Hart. Harv Law Rev 71:630–672
the will theory of rights, limitations on the legal Fuller LL (1969) The morality of law, rev edn. Yale Uni-
enforcement of morality, and Jeremy Bentham. versity Press, New Haven
Gavison R (ed) (1987) Issues in contemporary legal phi-
losophy: the influence of H. L. A. Hart. Clarendon
Press, Oxford
Cross-References Hacker PMS, Raz J (eds) (1977) Law, morality and society:
essays in honour of H.L.A. Hart. Clarendon Press,
▶ Descriptive Legal Theory Oxford
Hart HLA (1948–1949) The ascription of responsibility
▶ Dworkin, Ronald: Legal Philosophy and rights. Proc Aristot Soc 49:171–194
▶ Exclusive Legal Positivism Hart HLA (1955) Theory and definition in jurisprudence.
▶ Hermeneutical Legal Theory Proc Aristot Soc 29:239–264
▶ Inclusive Legal Positivism Hart HLA (1958) Positivism and the separation of law and
morals. Harv Law Rev 71:593–629
▶ Legal Conventionalism Hart HLA (1963) Law, liberty, and morality. Oxford Uni-
▶ Positive Law and Natural Law versity Press, Oxford
▶ Raz, Joseph Hart HLA (1982) Essays on Bentham: jurisprudence and
political theory. Clarendon Press, Oxford
Hart HLA (1983) Essays in jurisprudence and philosophy.
Clarendon Press, Oxford
References Hart HLA (2008) Punishment and responsibility: essays in
the philosophy of law, 2nd edn. Oxford University
Bayles MD (1992) Hart’s legal philosophy: an examina- Press, Oxford
tion. Kluwer, Dordrecht Hart HLA (2012) The concept of law, 3rd edn. Oxford
Bix BH (2015) Jurisprudence: theory and context, 7th edn. University Press, Oxford
Sweet & Maxwell, London Hart HLA, Honoré T (1985) Causation in the law, 2nd edn.
Coleman J (ed) (2001) Hart’s postscript: essays on the Oxford University Press, Oxford
postscript to the concept of law. Oxford University Kelsen H (1967) The pure theory of law. University of
Press, Oxford California Press, Berkeley
Devlin P (1965) The enforcement of morals. Oxford Uni- Lacey N (2004) A life of H. L. A. Hart: the nightmare and
versity Press, Oxford the noble dream. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Dworkin R (1977) Taking rights seriously. Harvard Uni- MacCormick N (2008) H.L.A. Hart, 2nd edn. Stanford,
versity Press, Cambridge, MA Stanford University Press
Dworkin R (1986) Law’s empire. Harvard University Mill JS (1974) On liberty. Penguin Books,
Press, Cambridge, MA Harmondsworth. (originally published 1859)
Ferrer JB, Ratti GB (eds) (2012) The logic of legal require- Raz J (1990) Practical reason and norms. Princeton Uni-
ments: essays on defeasibility. Oxford University versity Press, Princeton
Press, Oxford Raz J (2009) The authority of law: essays on law and
Finnis JM (2007) On Hart’s ways: law as reason and as morality, 2nd edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford
fact. American J Jurisprud 52:25–53

Вам также может понравиться