Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 6

Doubt Truth to be a Liar

GRAHAM PRIEST

CLARENDON PRESS • OXFORD


Consistency and the Empirical Sciences 143

underrated-for example, by posirivists and empiricists. However, that it plays a


much more central role in science than in other in quiries can hardly be denied.
The disrinccion between what is observable and what is not, is not, itself entirely
9 unproblernaríc. Sorne states of affairs are certainly observable (such as me coloue of an
insect) and sorne are certainly not (such as rhe colour of a quark). But it is impossible
to draw a sharp boundary between what is, and what is notoWhat is observable may
Consistency and the Empirical Sciences depend on what aids to perception (such as a microscope) are used; or on how we
interprer our sensory input in me light of accepted theories (such as theories rhat tell us
that when we witness me tracks in a bubble chamber, we are seeing the tracks of charged
particles). However, as with all vague or context-dependant distinctions, me facr that
9.1 INTROOUCTION it is impossible ro drawa neat line berween its two sides does not mean thar mere is not
an importanr distinction to be drawn. (Compare: being a child and being an adult.)
What role does, or should, inconsistency play in me empirical sciences? This is me Let us now revisit me discussion of observation in secrion 3.5 with mis new context
question that is to be addressed in mis chapter. The question is hardlya new one, in mind. What can one see?2For a start, seeing, in me sense relevant to explanation
bur me development of modern formal paraconsistent logies has a profound irnpact and confirrnation, is propositional. We see that something is me case. We see that
on me subjecr. Paraconsistent logicians have realized that their subjecr has important me stars appear to be in a certain position and ask for an explanation, or use mis
implications for me empirical sciences and the philosophy thereof, [ but discussions of against a theory according to which they should appear somewhere else. As we noted
me applications of paraconsistent logic have focused largely on non-ernpirical areas, in section 3.5, sorne have thought that one cannot see that something is not me case.
such as semanties and metaphysics. Ir rherefore seems appropriate to address me We always see that sornething is me case, and then infer that something else is not me
question direccly. case. For example, we see that something is red and infer that it is not black. Whilst
I will first address the issue of the specificiry of me empirical sciences: observation. one may certainly do this, one need not: one can see directly thar sornerhing is not the
Next, we willlook at me role that inconsistency has played in science (henceforth in this case. Try a thought experimento I show you an ordinary apple and ask: is this black?
chapter, I will often take me qualifier 'empirical' for granted), and the relation of this You compare its colour with a mental paradigm of blackness, and it does not match;
to paraconsistent logic. This wiIl raise the question of how inconsistent information you say no.' Or again, you enter a room; me whole room is visible from where you
ought to be treated in science: what criteria, for example, may lead us to accepting an stand; mere is no one mere. You can see that Pierre is not in me room. You do not
inconsistent theory? And should such an acceptance ever be more than provisional? have to say: me things in the room are a chair, atable ... ; Pierre is not a chair, Pierre
These topies wiIl be addressed in me next secrions. An outcome of mis discussion is not atable ... ; therefore, etc." The very distincrion between seeing what is me case
will be that, in me light of developments in paraconsistent logic, we may well have and what is not me case is a false one. Sorne seeings are both, When talking of actual
to change our attitude to inconsistencies of certain kinds; such a change would open physical objects, to be transparent is not to be opaque and vice versa. But you can see
whole new possibilities in science itself that something is transparent and you can see thar something is opaque.
Ir should be remembered that seeing is not simply a matter of light rays hirring
me retina. Certainly, me eyes are involved in seeing, bur one needs more than eyes
9.2 INCONSISTENCY ANO OBSERVATION to see. If what one sees is to playa role in one's cognitive functioning, one must
also understand one's visual input. Hence, me categories of me understanding play
Before we can address me issue of me role of inconsistency in empirical sciences, it will a role. To see is ro interpret ones visual stimuli, by applying mese categories, either
be imporrant to discuss how such sciences differ from similar inquiries (which are often consciously or preconsciously; and mere is no reason why truth funcrions such as
intricarely connecred with thern), such as rnathematics and meraphysics, The standard negation or disjuncrion should not enter into me process of interpretation direcrly.
answer to mis question is that in me empirical sciences, but not the others, observation For exarnple, I can see that mis is a photograph of either Ned or Ted, idenrical twins
plays a role. In me more developed sciences such observations are obtained through such that I cannot tell me difference, without seeing that it is a photograph of Ned,
acrive experimentation. The observations serve to provide me ultimare explananda and inferring me disjuncrion.
for science, as weIl as providing important inputs into me evaluation of scientiíic
theories, This standard answer is not entirely unproblematic: me role of empirical
2 In what follows, I will restrict myself to discussing vision, since mis is by far me most important
data in science has often been overrared, and its role in areas such as philosophy
sensory modality in science; bur similar comments apply to me other senses.
, 1 am not suggesting mar all vision is paradigm-based in mis way, as should become clear in a
[ See, e.g. Priest and Routley (1989a),367-79, and Priest and Routley (1989b),494 tI momento " The example comes from Sartre (1943), ch. 1, sect. 2.
144 Rationality Consistency and the Empirical Sciences 145

Now, suppose that a and f3 are states of affairs observable at me same time and an experiment and observe that --.a. Simple-rninded falsificationists would suggest
place, from me same perspective, etc., as I discussed in section 3.5; then, as argued that this shows that T is wrong and is to be ditched, But many philosophers of
rhere, so is rheir conjunction. We can see rhat something is a unicorn; we can see that it science have pointed out that this does not necessarily happen.? The contradiction
is green. Hence, we can see that it is a green unicorn. Thus, if a and ....,a are observable may be treated as the site of an anomaly: both T and --.a may be accepted pro temo
states of affairs, so is a 1\ =a, Of course, this is not to say that the conjunction is T will not be jettisoned until we have a better alternative; --.a will not be jettisoned
observed; merely that ir is observable-mat is, it is of a kind such that if it were ro be until we have an explanation of why our observation was incorrecto Examples of this
me case, it could be seen. kind in me history of science are many. The precession of the perihelion of Mercury,
In reply to me suggestion that it might be impossible to see inconsistent states of at odds with received facts about the heavenly bodies and Newtonian dynamics, was
affairs because our perceptual apparatus imposes sorne "consistency Iilrer", it suffices known for a long time before the rejection ofNewtonian dynamics in favour of special
to note, as we saw in section 3.5, that we perceive impossible situations in various relativiry. Prout's hypothesis was widely accepted by many chemists even though it was
visual illusions. Thus, there are many well-known impossible figures (of the kind, for known to be at odds with empirical data (much of which was subsequently rejected).
example, employed by Escher in his drawings); there are perceptual sets where people And so on.!?
report seeing things as simultaneously red and green; there are situations where things The second kind of inconsistency, between theory and theory, is less frequently
appear ro be moving and not moving. Let me just remind the reader of one of these, noted, but cerrainly occurs. This is when we have two well-accepted theories, TI and
me last." This is commonly known as me waterfall illusion. After conditioning the T2, which have inconsistent consequences. Again, though this may be noted as the
visual field by showing it constant motion of a certain kind, saya spinning spiral, one sire of a problem, both TI and T2 are retained until a suitable replacement theory
then looks at a stationary scene. The scene appears to move in the opposite direction, for one or both is found. An example of this concerns the age of the earth in late
but nothing in the scene changes its position, for example, an object at the top of nineteenth-century science. According to evolutionary theory (which was, by that
the visual field does not move round to the bottom. W'hat we see appears to be both time, well accepted), the age of the earth had to be hundreds of millions of years;
moving and stationary; this is the natural way of describing ones visual sensations. Of bur according to received thermodynamics, the sun-and so the earth-could not
course, perception in the cases I have described is not veridical:" mese are illusions, and possibly be that old. (The issue was resolved only in the twentieth century with the
things are not really mus; but that is how they would appear if things were mus. There discovery of radioactiviry, a hitherto unsuspected form of heat-generation.) Another,
is therefore nothing about our visual system that requires perception to be consistent. contemporary, example: the theories of relativity and quantum theory are known to
be mutually inconsistent."
The third example of an inconsistency is when a theory is self-inconsistent. This
could arise because a theory has inconsistent observational consequences, though
9.3 TYPES OF INCONSISTENCY 1know of no interesting cases of this in the history of science. W'hat there cerrainly have
been are inconsistent theories where the inconsistencies are located internally, away
Let us now turn to the issue ofinconsistency in science. The inconsistencies in question from observational consequences. For example, for over a hundred years Newtonian
here are inconsistencies in what are accepted scientific beliefs. Many historians and dynamics was based on the old calculus, in which infinitesimals had inconsistent prop-
philosophers of science have observed that there are such inconsistencies-indeed erties (being both non-zero, at one point in computations, and zero at others). Another,
that they are common---even in contemporary science.' If we distinguish between particularly striking, example is Bohr's theory of the atom, which included both clas-
observation and theory (what cannot be observed), rhen three different rypes of contra- sical electrodynamic principIes and quantum principIes that were quite inconsistent
diction are particularly noteworthy for our purposes: between theory and observation, with them. Though the theory was cerrainly considered as problematic, irs empirica!
between theory and theory, and internal to a theory itselt." Let us look at mese three
in more detail.
Inconsistency between theory and observation is me most obvious example. We
9 e.g. Kuhn (1970), Lakatos (1970), Feyerabend (1975). This Iiterarure is quite old now, and
have a well-received theory, T, with a certain observable consequence, a. We then run many aspectsof the philosophy ofKuhn, Feyerabed, et al. have been subject to telling criticismoMuch
of the brunt of the criricim has fallen on the Kuhn/Feyerabend claims about incommensurabiliry.
s Details of examples such as this can be found in most books on vision and visual illusions, e.g. This is irrelevant to the present manero
Robinson (1972). Examples of mis kind are further discussed in Feyerabend (1975), 258 fE la In such situations, scientists may well, of course, have ideas about how to resolve the contra-
6 Which is not ro say that a perception of a contradictory state of affairs cannot be veridical. But
diction. But investigating possible ways of making a belief revision is not the same thing as making a
as we saw in sect. 3.5, mere are good reasons ro suppose rhat those 1 have described are nor. revision. Revisions in accepted wisdom are not made until one of these ways looks as though it will
7 For example, Lakatos (1970), Feyerabend (1975), ch. 5, which can be consulted for details of
work.
11 This is not to say that individual scientists will endorse things of the form el and -.a, much less
many of me following examples.
el /\ -.a. As I will we note in a minute, scientific knowledge is chunked, the chunks often belonging
8 A good general discussion of kinds of problem situations in science, including those involving
various kinds of contradictions, can be found in Laudan (1977), chs. 1,2. ro different experts. el may well belong to one chunk, and -.a to another.
146 Rationality Consistencyand tbe Empirical Sciences 147

predications were so much better than those of any other theory at the time that it really had a contradiccory age." Similarly, in rhe Bohr theory of the atom, the drawing
had no real competitor.'? of conclusions was restricted to well-defined consistent chunks, possibly in accord-
ance wirh sorne pragmatically determined-but srill dererminate=-considerations."
A conclusion dtawn may then have been fed into another consistent chunk which
9.4 HANDLING INCONSISTENCY contained information inconsistent with that in the first chunk.16Whether adjunctive
paraconsistent logics have, hisrorically, ever been used in handling inconsistencies is
As we have seen, the corpus of scientific beliefs may, oc is even likely to be, inconsistent a different matter, and is rather doubtful. At any rare, I know of no examples where
at any time. Bur from things accepted, scientists infer other things ro be accepted, this is clearly the case.
and they do not infer arbitrary condusions. Ir follows that the inference proced-
ure employed here must be a paraconsisrent one (where an arbitrary tx and -,ct do
~ot en~ail an arbitrary {J). What paraconsistent inference procedure is employed in
inconsistent cases is another question; there is no a priori reason to suppose that it 9.5 ACCEPTING INCONSISTENT INFORMATION
must be one of the standard rnonotonic paraconsistent logics, or even that it musr
be monotonic at all. Nor should one suppose that ir must be the same in every case. We have seen that inconsistent information has sometimes been accepted in che hisrory
What is guaranteed is that there rnust be sorne systematic procedure for drawing of science; we have also seen, at least in outline, why this does not lead to disaster.
conclusions, and which does not permit drawing an arbitrary conclusion from a con- None of this shows that rhe inconsistent information ought ro have been accepted (even
tradiction. What procedure is or was employed in any given case is a matter for detailed provisionally). But the situation seems ro have arisen so frequenrly that ir is implausible
investigation. ro level at the scientific community charges ofblatant and frequent irrationaliry, This,
I do not inrend to discuss detailed examples here; but for what follows, it will be rherefore, raises the question of the conditions under which it is reasonable ro accept
important for us ro distinguish between two different kinds of paraconsistent logic: an inconsistent theory or other body of information.
adjuncrive and non-adjunctive. In adjunctive paraconsistent logics, such as standard The question of what makes it reasonable to accept any theory is a familiar one
relevant logics and da Costas C systems, the rule of adjunction, a, {J f- ct A {J, is in contemporary philosophy of science, and a very difficult one. Neither do 1 inrend
valido In non-adjunctive systems, such as discussive logics, ir is noto Non-adjunctive to advance a detailed answer to that question here. But let us recall the account of
paraconsisrent logics often employ sorne chunking procedure. Because of rhe failure of rational belief developed in the previous two chapters.
adjunction, one cannot simply put arbirrary premises together and draw condusions. The doxastic goodness of a theory may be evaluated under a number of orthogonal
If the inference procedure is not to be impoverished, it is usually necessary to be able criteria. A major criterio n is empirical adequacy. For any observational consequence,
to put sorne premises together (into a chunk). A simple procedure is ro put together a, that a theory entails, if a is observed, this is a good mark. Ifit is not, this is a black
any bunch of premises that are murually consistent; but there are more sophisticared mark. Empirical adequacy is, perhaps, the most important criterio n in science. Ir is,
ones." at least, the one that mainly distinguishes the empirical sciences from similar invest-
?ne th.ing t~t is dear .fro~ a fairly cursory consideration of the scienrific handling igations. But it is certainly not the only one; nor can ir be. Ir is at least rheorerically
of mconsistent information IS that the inference procedure employed is ofien of a possible ro have different theories that are both empirically adequate; more commonly,
non-adjunctive, chunking, variery, For example, given the dispute about me age of it happens that no theory in me field is entirely empirically adequate. Hence other
the earth at the end of the nineteenth century; no one conjoined the views that the criteria have also ro be employed. There is a multitude of these;" philosophers may
earth was hundreds of millions of years old, and that it was not, lO infer that the earth disagree both about what they are, and about how, exactly, ro understand thern, but
rhe following have certainly been suggesred, and are very plausible. Good-making fea-
12 Ir.might. be su~ested that in the situations rnentioned the scienrific cornmuniry did nor really
tures indude: simplicity, ontologicalleanness (Occam's razor), explanatory power, a
accep~lll.consIStenCles ..Rather, they had degrees of belief in various propositions, and their degrees low degree of ad hocness, unity, fruitfulness, The converse features are bad: complexiry,
of belief III the conrradictory a and -'a were lessthan l. Now, it may well be the case that there are
de~rees of ~lief,. and that acceptance is to be understood as having a sufficienclyhigh degree; but
this suggestlOnWlll.re~ly help. For example, given the inconsistency berween the theory of evolution 14 Which is not to say that people did not notice thar the theories together entail something of
an~ th~rmodynamlcs, It would follow that one or both of these theories was believed to degree ':::;0.5, the form a /\ -.a. and so conclude that there was a problem here; merely chat the corpus of accepted
whlch ISto say that one or both of these was not accepted at all, which is untrue. Or if both were beliefswas nor closed under an adjunctive logic.
accepted to degree 0.5, and one sets the leve! of acceptance at this figure, then inconsistencies were 15 Many non-monotonic (paraconsistent) logics incorporare pragmatic features of chis kind; for
accepted, as claimed. example. in che ordering relation with respect ro which minimization is defined. See sect. 11.10.
13 For ~ general account of para.consi~ent logic, see Priest (2002b). On non-adjunctive srraregies, 16 For a more decailed discussion. see Smich (1988). Brown (1990) and, especially,Brown (1993)
s~, espeClally,sect. ~.2. A non-adJuncuve strategy which seems particularly apt for handling many and Brown and Priest (2004).
hlstoncal examples ISdescribed in Brown and Priesr (2004). 17 See. e.g. Quine and Ullian (1970). ch. 5. Kuhn (1977). Lycan (1988). ch. 7.
148 Rationality Consistency and the Empirical Sciences 149

ontological extravagance, explanatory poveny, much ad hocness, fragmentation, observation, something needs to be revised. For if theory T entails a, but -.a is
barrenness." observed, not a, we again have an empirical inadequacy. It may be retorted that if
The exact number of, and details concerning, criteria of these kinds, though a inconsistencies are acceptable, maybe a r.-.a is true after all. But again, since a r.-.a
highly important and interesting question, need not detain us here. The important is an observable state of affairs, and one that is not observed in the situation described,
points are Ca)that there is a multitude, and (b) that the criteria do not necessarily we have an empirical inadequacy: if a r. -.a were true, so would a be, and this is
hang together. One theory, say Bohr's theory of the atorn, may have a high degree precisely what is not observed.
of empirical adequacy, be very fruitful, but inconsistent. Another may be consistent, What if a conrradiction is one berween theory and theory, or internal to a theory,
have a lesser degree of empirical adequacy, and be rather ad hoc.As I have argued in the not spilling over into observation? Here, the situation is more complicated. Suppose,
previous rwo chapters, one theory is rationally preferable 10 another if it is sufficiencly first, that one is an insrrumentalist: then all one caces about is the empirical adequacy
better on a sufficient number of criteria. of a theory; if a contradiction is located deep in the heart of theory, this is of no
This account, rough as it may be, is sufficient to demonstrate a number of things. momento But if, as I think correct-though I shall not argue it here-one should,
It shows why theory choice is a messy business: there is no simple algorithm. It shows in general, be a realist about scientific theories, the matter is different, and depends
why, within certain limirs, mere may be room ro disagree over which theory is better: crucially on how this inconsistency is handled. If it is handled by a chunking strategy,
if no theory is overall best, people may reasonably disagree. AlI this is familiar from then the theory is not a candidate for the truth. If a is true and -.a is true, then so
standard philosophy of science. As we noted in previous chapters, it shows two further is their conjunction. If a theory refuses to allow this move then the theory cannot be
things. First, it shows how and when it may be rational to accept an inconsistent theory: correct, and we know this."
when, despite its inconsistency, it is markedly better than its rivals on sufficiencly many If, on the other hand, the inconsistency is handled with an adjunctive paraconsistent
other criteria. Secondly, it shows when it may be right to reject an inconsistent theory, logic, there is no reason, as far as I can see, why we should not suppose the theory or
even when inconsistency may be rationally tolerable: when a rival theory scores higher theories in question to be correcto In particular, then, a theoretical inconsistency that
on sufficiencly many criteria. That is, it shows how theories may be "falsified", even if is handled adjunctively is not, in itself a reason to suppose that the theory cannot, in
inconsistencies are sometimes tolerable. the long run, be allowed to stand. Any argurnent to the effect that such inconsistencies
are ulrirnately unacceptable must be a quite general and apriori defence of the Law of
Non-Contradiction in the appropriate form: any contradiction is known, in advance,
to rule a theory out as a candidate for the truth. I know of no such argurnent that
9.6 INCONSISTENCY ANO TRUTH works. AlI fail, usually by simply begging the question in sorne way." Thus, if we are
realists, we will let our best theory, provided that ir is not ruled out as a candidate
But should an inconsistent corpus of belief be accepted only provisionally, until a fOI truth on other grounds, inform us as 10 what reality is like; and if our theory is
better one can be found; or can it be accepted as a candidate for the final truth? inconsistent, there is no reason to suppose that the theory does not get ir right: reality
Several comments are peninent here. First, there is no such thing as certainty about itself is inconsistent. In other words, inconsistencies of this kind in science do not
anything in science. Any rheory or set of theories, whether consistent or inconsistent, mandare that the acceptance of the theory or theories in question be provisional in
should be endorsed fallibly. All theories go beyond me data-which is itself, in any
any special way."
case, "theory laden". In mis sense, the acceptance of anything is only ever provisional.
But is there something special about inconsistency in this regard? Here, it seems to
me, me nature of the inconsistency is relevant. Note, first, that if a theory is empirically
inadequate, however acceptable it is, the received information is not a candidate for 9.7 INCONSISTENT MATHEMATICS
me truth, at least as things stand. If a theory entails an observable consequence a, and
a is not perceived, sornerhing is wrong, either with our theory or with our perceptions; It is here that me impact of paraconsistent logic is revisionary-indeed, revolutionary.
sornething needs to be fixed. In particular, then, if a theory entails fJ " -'fJ, where fJ is The Law of Non-Contradiction has been well entrenched in Western thought-and
sorne observation staternent, then if such a contradiction is not observed, something
is wrong. As I have already argued, fJ " -'fJ is a perfeccly observable state of affairs. 19 20 More generally, if the inconsistency is handled with an inference mechanism that does not

Moreover, if the inconsistency in me scientific corpus is berween a theory and an respect truth-preservation, such as that of Brown and Priest (2004), the same condusion follows.
21 The major arguments are those advanced or inspired by Aristole in Metaphysics r. We sawwhy

these fail in Chapter l.


18 The question of whether consistencylinconsistency should be on these lists is not as obvious as 22 This raises the following question. Suppose that we have a theory based on a non-adjunctive
it might seem. See sect. 7.4. logic. This, as 1 have argued, is not an ultimately acceptable theory. Why can we not turn it into
19 Thus, even if one suggested that one contradictory perceptually occluded the other, as discussed one, simply by changing the underlying logic to an adjunctive (uuth-tracking) one? This may be a
in sect. 3.5, we would need sorne (presumably psychological) explanation of why this is the case. possibiliry,though not if changing the logic results in the theory being empirically inadequate-which
is normally why a non-adjunctive procedure is used in the first place.
. ,~
150 Rationality Consistencyand tbe Empírica! Sciences 151
so science-since the canonization of Arisrotle, whose defence of the law has rarely Such an understanding is bound to reflecr into our understanding of the rarionality
been challenged. Hence, scientists and philosophers have not been prepared to brook of theory-choice, in the ways that I have indicated. Perhaps most importanrly of all,
rhe thought rhat an inconsistent theory of any kind might be true. But subscribing to paraconsistency may open the gate to important new kinds of theory within science
the l.aw is not rationally mandatory, as I argued in Chapter 7, and as the development itself. Where this will alllead, one cannot even begin to speculate.
of paraconsisrent logics has played a large role in showing. Once this fact is digested, One branch of science-though perhaps not empirical science-as traditionally
scientists may well-justifiably-take a different attitude to inconsistent theories of conceived, is logic. The nature of chis brings us to the fourth part of the book. And
the appropriate kind. Indeed, they may even develop inconsistent theories, if these about the nature oflogic, one can do a lot more than speculate,
have the right empirical consequences, just as paraconsistent logicians have articulated
inconsistent theories of sernantics to handle rhe paradoxes of self-reference.
In modern science, the inferentially sophisticated part is nearly always marhern-
atical. An appropriate rnathernatical theory is found, and its theorems are applied.
Hence, a Iikely way for an inconsistent theory to arise now in science is via the applic-
ation of an inconsistent rnathematical theory. Though the construction ofinconsistent
mathernatical theories (based on adjunctive paraconsistent logics) is relarively new,
there are already a number: inconsistent number theories, linear algebras, category
theories; and it is clear that there is much more scope in this area." These theories
have not been developed with an eye to their applicability in science-just as classical
group theory was noto But once the paraconsistent revolution has been digested, it
is by no means implausible ro suppose that these theories, or ones like them, may
find physical application-just as group theory did. For example, we might determine
that certain physical magnitudes appear to be governed by the laws of sorne incon-
sistent arithmetic, where, for example, if n and m are magnitudes no smaller than
sorne constant k, n m + = +
k (as well as its being the case that n m :f: k)Y There
are, after all, plenty of episodes in the history of science in which we carne to accept
that certain physical magnitudes have somewhat surprising mathematical properties
(being imaginary, non-commuting, etc.), Why not inconsistencyr"

9.8 CONCLUSION

I believe that the developrnent of modern formal paraconsistent logics is one of the
most significant intellectual developments of the rwentieth century. In challenging
entrenched Western attitudes to inconsistency that are over 2,000 years old, it has
the potenrial to ricochet through all of our intellectual life-and empirical science
wears no buller-proof vest. As we have seen, empirical scientists have always rolerated,
and operared within, inconsistency in certain ways. One of the liberating effects of
paraconsistency should be to allow us to understand berter exactly how chis proceeded.

23 For inconsistent arithmeric, see Priest (1997 a) and (2000c). On inconsistent mathematics in
general, see Mortensen (1995).
24 I will returo to this idea in sect. 10.7. There iseven one place where an inconsistent mathematics
might possibly find an application already. In the rwo-slit experiment in quantum mechanics, the
causal anomoly can be resolved by supposing that the photon does the impossible, going through
the two slits simultaneously, and handling this with an adjunctive paraconsistenr probabiliry theory.
For details, see Priest and Routley (1989a), 377 f.
25 Which is not to say that an inconsisrenr mathematical theory must be inrerprered realistically.
Such theories may have instrumental uses, jusr as much as consisrent theories.

Вам также может понравиться