Вы находитесь на странице: 1из 17

Journal of Economic Literature 2013, 51(2), 528–543

http://dx.doi.org/10.1257/jel.51.2.528

Incorporating Limited Rationality


into Economics †

Matthew Rabin*

Harstad and Selten (this forum) raise interesting questions about the relative promise of
optimization models and bounded-rationality models in making progress in economics.
This article builds from their analysis by indicating the potential for using neoclassical
(broadly defined) optimization models to integrate insights from psychology on the
limits to rationality into economics. I lay out an approach to making (imperfect and
incremental) improvements over previous economic theory by incorporating greater
realism while attempting to maintain the breadth of application, the precision of
predictions, and the insights of neoclassical theory. I then discuss how many human
limits to full rationality are, in fact, well understood in terms of optimization.
(  JEL B49, D01, D03, D81, D84)

1.  Introduction Optimization-Based Models of Strategic


Thinking and Learning in Games,” offers

I n a thoughtful and well-hyphenated


article, “Bounded-Rationality Models:
­
Tasks to Become Intellectually Competitive,”
perspectives on a set of strategic and mar-
ket topics (e.g., asset bubbles) closer to those
topics focused on by Harstad and Selten. I
Harstad and Selten (this volume) lay out focus more on limits to rationality that might
some challenges to neoclassical economics— help explain consumer and savings behavior,
and a refreshingly serious challenge to those risky choice, and other classical problems of
trying to improve it. I offer some thoughts individual decision making.
on their article and their challenge. The set In footnote 1, Harstad and Selten cor-
of topics I emphasize differs significantly rectly note that many researchers trying to
from theirs. This is due in part to different improve the psychological realism of eco-
interests and knowledge. It is also because nomics do not necessarily see themselves
of division of labor: Crawford’s contribution as bounded-rationality theorists outside the
to this forum, “Boundedly Rational versus realm of neoclassical theory, broadly defined.
Nor even do we all eschew optimization
* University of California, Berkeley. I thank Tristan models. Harstad and Selten themselves note
Gagnon-Bartsch for valuable research assistance, and Vince that there are virtues to optimization as a
Crawford, Janet Currie, Erik Eyster, Tristan Gagnon-Bartsch, methodology. Instead, their article is explicit
and Ron Harstad for helpful comments.
† 
Go to http://dx.doi.org/10.1257/jel.51.2.528 to visit the in understanding its virtues, and lays out the
article page and view author disclosure statement(s). challenge for those proposing alternatives to

528
Rabin: Incorporating Limited Rationality into Economics 529

match some of those virtues. The articles by the neoclassical model.2 But other examples
Harstad and Selten and by Crawford together of human limits to rationality, I will argue,
provide a very useful and thoughtful pre- are genuinely best understood in terms of
sentation of the necessity and prospects for optimization models. As surely as optimiza-
departing from optimization models in the tion captures cases of fully rational behav-
set of topics they discuss. I agree with many ior, it captures the psychology and resulting
of their arguments. As such, my article is not behavior of some limits to rationality.
so much a rejoinder to Harstad and Selten’s The case for optimization models of lim-
article as it is an addendum listing some cur- ited rationality largely reflects an insight
rent and potential research incorporating from psychology that is underappreciated by
limited rationality into a more neoclassical economists: not all limits to rationality are
framework. By discussing some principles based on computational unmanageability.
and examples of current research, I hope to Many of the ways humans are less than fully
give readers a richer sense of the benefits rational are not because the right answers
and surprising possibilities for using opti- are so complex. They are instead because
mization models to understand the implica- the wrong answers are so enticing. Human
tions of limits to rationality. In the process, intuition leads us astray in all sorts of ways
my article will make more salient some types that are simply not well described in terms
of human errors that seem downplayed by of the difficulty or complexity of problems
the community of scholars grappling with that bounded-rationality models seem best
bounded-rationality models. suited for. The pervasiveness of bounds
As the other articles in this forum note, errors where people are daunted by the task
much of the recent literature modifying neo- of optimization, or are simply not geared to
classical economics is about improving the it, should not be doubted. But astray errors,
realism of preferences by altering the util- as one might call them, likewise seem per-
ity function in ways that are fully compatible vasive, and especially amenable to neoclas-
with rationality, and hence quite obviously sical modeling. We can capture many errors
conducive to models that assume people in terms of systematic mistakes in the proxi-
optimize.1 This article outlines a perspective mate value function people maximize (quasi-
that may appear more surprising: that many maximization models) or where the beliefs
limits to rationality can be usefully studied incorporated into their maximizations are
with optimization models. Some of the exam- systematically distorted (quasi-Bayesian
ples are rather Procrustean: the underlying models). The general sensibility and empha-
psychology does not have a very optimizing sis of economic theorists, experimental
feel to it, but can be crammed into the opti- economists, and others lead them to neglect
mization framework to leverage the power of important examples of limited rationality
that are important for economics.

2 The distinction between optimization models and


1 As Harstad and Selten note in the context of prefer- bounded-rationality models is not so clear; at some level,
ence reversals, some of the psychologically inspired new they are probably isomorphic to the types of limits I dis-
models of preferences may have properties that econo- cuss in this article. Nor is the labeling important. But even
mists had previously associated with irrationality and which when they are distinct, we can still leave open the ques-
may require a somewhat different toolbox. Fully rational tion of what models to use. And, especially in those cases
theories of belief-based utility, such as K​  o​
˝ s  zegi (2010) and where we all agree that the optimization models are wrong,
K​  o​
˝ s zegi and Rabin (2006, 2009), generate time inconsis- the different articles constituting this forum will help see a
tencies and violations of other axioms that economists had range of perspectives on the costs and benefits of moving
been in the habit of associating with rationality. forward with models that are wrong but useful.
530 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. LI (June 2013)

Studying astray errors rather than bounds discussed in Rabin (forthcoming), which has
errors allows methodological advantages been employed in many papers: formulate
that facilitate meeting the challenges that models that offer complete mappings from
Harstad and Selten lay out. They directly environment to outcome, using as much as
suggest that we should not be too eager to possible the same set of variables as in tra-
move away from optimization models. It ditional models, and embed both the earlier
is easier to study astray errors than bound (neoclassical) model and the limited-ratio-
errors using optimization models because nality model as parameter values. The com-
the former involve behavior that is richly petition between the old and new models is
purposeful and driven by a logic that the then half done—we’ve shown the two mod-
economic agent finds compelling. Fully els to be structurally comparable in terms of
rational investors who understand random- degrees of freedom, applicability, etc. And
ness and who want to retire wealthy will the second half of the competition is put into
maximize their risk-adjusted expected sav- motion: the models can be compared and
ings with investment strategies that are best judged, in a fair fight, by establishing point
given their (correct) notion of randomness. estimates and confidence intervals on the
But investors who believe in a false law of parameter values.
averages, expecting that good luck tends Section 2 explains and illustrates this
to be followed by bad and bad luck tends approach. I provide many examples of basic
to be followed by good, will also maximize models that improve the realism of econom-
their risk-adjusted expected savings given ics in very structured, disciplined—competi-
their perceptions of randomness. Would-be tive—ways using optimization models that
exercisers who rationally forecast systematic closely resemble existing models. And I lay
taste change due to habit formation and due out concrete general criteria for realism-
to fluctuations in energy will plan to care- improving theories that make explicit their
fully develop an exercise habit and will also power and scope—their ability to make pre-
know that they should not radically change cise predictions and their general applicabil-
plans in reaction to temporary fluctuations ity—and very explicit their relationship to
in enthusiasm. But those who systematically existing models.3 I also discuss more gener-
underappreciate taste change will not make ally an orientation toward incremental prog-
any plans based on inducing good habits but ress in improving models that can be used to
may make unfortunate long-term plans (such improve theoretical and empirical econom-
as joining a gym) based on falsely extrapo- ics. Section 3 turns to the methodological
lating temporary enthusiasm. Elaborate, and substantive case for optimization-based
goal-driven plans are the stuff of savvy maxi- models of limited rationality, by briefly illus-
mizers who correctly understand both the trating human biases and limits that, by dint
laws of statistics and their own future utility. of being driven by mistaken intuitions rather
But elaborate, goal-driven plans are also the than automatic or rule-of-thumb behavior,
stuff of those who both misunderstand statis- are at their core optimization models. I con-
tics and systematically mispredict their own clude in section 4 with a very brief discus-
future behavior. sion of the movement toward integrating
A second methodological advantage of this
approach is that it embraces with enthusiasm
Harstad and Selten’s goal of making alterna- 3 Much of my discussion in this section reflects
tive models competitive with the current arguments I have made elsewhere, especially Rabin
paradigm. These models use an approach (forthcoming).
Rabin: Incorporating Limited Rationality into Economics 531

new models of limited rationality into main- bleed into underappreciation of progress
stream empirical and theoretical economics. in both their own and others’ research pro-
grams. It is hard to know what counterfactu-
als to compare a program to. But this article
2.  Competitive Models
contributes to the forum by enumerating
Since all models are wrong, and all para- some of the current models of limited ratio-
digms have their limits, it is always a difficult nality that are being introduced to improve
judgment call as to when and how to empha- economic theory and empirical economics.
size the severity of the shortfalls of prevailing These models may still miss too much of the
approaches—and when to call for the devel- bounded in bounded rationality.
opment of a new paradigm. Nor is it even Rabin (forthcoming) proposes an
clear what is inside a paradigm and what is approach to improving the psychological
outside. And it certainly does not ultimately realism of economics while maintaining its
matter what labels we use. Especially in the conventional techniques, of formal theo-
domain of rationality (and behavioral eco- retical and empirical analysis using tractable
nomics), much unintentional harm and dis- models focused on prediction and estima-
traction and obfuscation has been caused by tion. The emphasis is on developing models
enthusiasm for categorizing models rather improving behavioral realism that can be
than elucidating specific empirical claims. used as inputs into economic theory by dint
Harstad and Selten thankfully avoid all that, of their precision and broad applicability.4
and are thoughtful and balanced in their Striving for realism-improving theories to be
approach. But my own judgment is that their maximally useful to core economic research
assessment of the neoclassical research pro- suggests a particular approach: portable
gram is too dire. We all in this forum believe extensions of existing models (PEEMs). One
working to reduce its shortcomings is worth should (a) extend the existing model by for-
the time of economists—more time than it is mulating a modification that embeds it as a
getting. But part of the case for the approach constellation of parameter values with the
I advocate perhaps comes from greater con-
fidence that the core of microeconomic the- 4 The desire for maximal precision of new theories
ory and empirical work has been a success, does not come from confidence that the theories are
and is continuing as a success. And, most right. Besides enhancing their usefulness, in fact, one
importantly in this context, that it is amena- value of precision is that it highlights flaws to aid in fur-
ther improvements. Indeed, in the context of this forum, I
ble to rapid improvements by incorporating would emphasize a macro version of this claim: it may be
limited-rationality models. that the most efficient and useful way to reach what may
On the other hand, the entire premise of eventually feel like a new paradigm is in incremental steps.
In fact, with caution given the brilliance of the research-
their article is to acknowledge the merits of ers and research involved, it is my guess that the line of
the neoclassical optimization paradigm and research in the tradition of Simon (1955) and Newell and
the burden on bounded-rationality models Simon (1972) generates too much emphasis on shortcom-
ings of existing models and—largely as collateral damage
to add value to this approach. I am struck by from its wonderful emphasis on evidence and intuition
Harstad and Selten’s thoughtful observation about the way people behave in real-world problem-solv-
that generations of scholars have put effort ing—is too oriented toward lists of specific shortcomings.
The greater emphasis on generalizable alternative predic-
into bounded rationality without delivering a tions in the approaches inspired by Kahneman and Tversky
serious rival to the neoclassical model. The (2000), and discussed in reviews by Rabin (1998, 2002b)
high standard they hold new approaches to is and DellaVigna (2009), may have a greater target chance
of both near-term improvements in workaday economic
laudable when applied to one’s own research research and long-term improvements in the structure of
approach, as they are doing, but may also economics.
532 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. LI (June 2013)

new ­ psychological assumptions as alterna- Schmeidler 1989).5 Although all these mod-
tive parameter values, and (b) make it por- els were developed with elegant generality
table by defining it across domains using the and formulated with axioms capturing basic
same independent variables as in existing principles, in the context of monetary risk
research, or proposing measurable new vari- they have all lent themselves to providing
ables. To further their integration into main- precise alternatives defined in the same set
stream economics, PEEMs lend themselves of situations to which classical wealth-based
to two types of comparative statics. The first expected utility applies.
is to look within chosen environments at The model of reference-dependent pref-
how predictions change with the parameter erences developed in K​   o​
˝ s zegi and Rabin
values. This allows us to test their empirical (2006, 2007, 2009) likewise attempts to
validity in comparison to existing theories by bring some of the insights from Kahneman
estimating those parameters, and to see their and Tversky’s (1979) prospect theory toward
potential value added in comparison to exist- ­general applicability. In a simple linear form
ing theories by seeing how those parameters of the model, they take any classical eco-
do and don’t matter in important economic nomic situation and make an alternative pre-
contexts. The second type of comparative diction based on the idea that people don’t
statics is the more traditional one: fixing only care about absolute consumption, but
the parameter values that accord with the about consumption relative to reference
improved assumptions, how does changing levels. Under uncertainty or in determin-
the environment affect economic outcomes? istic settings, when trading off consump-
Applying this form of comparative statics tion in different dimensions (quality versus
indicates that the improved psychological price on a given consumer item, or differ-
realism is ready for economic primetime. If ent items in a bundle of goods), people are
one views hypothesis testing and comparative more bothered by losses relative to a refer-
statics as empirical and theoretical competi- ence point than pleased by gains. A key to
tions, then this approach sets up the compe- the PEEMishness of the model is that refer-
tition Harstad and Selten talk about. Rabin ence points are pinned down: they assume
(forthcoming) argues that this competition is people’s reference points are their expected
an important way forward for improvements consumption, and make a unique prediction
in economic models, disciplining both those in most settings. This is done by assuming a
proposing the theories and those doubting person behaves according to preferred per-
them in a way that pushes research toward sonal equilibrium: she chooses her favorite
constructive, normal-science debates. consumption plan such that, if she has the
An early and successful example of this reference point corresponding to expecting
methodology, in the domain of preferences to follow the plan, she will do so. K​   o​szegi
˝  and
under uncertainty, is the literature provid- Rabin (2006) show that, in static settings
ing alternatives to classical expected utility. with no uncertainty, the prediction of the
Beginning with Machina (1982), researchers model corresponds to the classical predic-
have introduced realistic aspects of prefer- tions of consumer theory, but it makes pre-
ences precluded from the expected-utility cise alternative predictions in settings with
formulation, ranging from nonlinear prob- either dynamic choice or where there is
ability weighting (Tversky and Kahneman intrinsic uncertainty or surprise. The model
1992 and Prelec 1998), to disappointment
(Bell 1985, Loomes and Sugden 1986, and 5 See Harless and Camerer (1994) for an excellent con-
Gul 1991), to ambiguity aversion (Gilboa and ceptual and empirical review of these models.
Rabin: Incorporating Limited Rationality into Economics 533

­ arameterized by η ≥ 0, the degree to


is p framework in this domain are McKelvey and
which one cares about news about gains Palfrey’s (1996) quantal-response equilib-
and losses, λ ≥ 1, the degree to which one rium and Eyster and Rabin’s (2005) cursed
is more bothered by unexpected losses in equilibrium. In McKelvey and Palfrey, a
consumption relative to unexpected gains, parameter λ ≥ 0 captures the propensity of
and γ ∈ [0, 1], the degree to which people players to make random mistakes, with an
care about news about future consumption equilibrium assumption pinning down other
relative to news about contemporaneous subjects’ beliefs; in Eyster and Rabin’s (2005)
consumption. (Classical reference-inde- cursed equilibrium, parameter χ ∈ [0, 1]
pendent preferences correspond to η = 0.) captures the degree to which players neglect
Perhaps the most active area of formulat- the informational content in other players’
ing general alternatives to more traditional behavior.7 Although, as with Nash equilib-
neoclassical models is in departures from rium, they do not always predict a unique
narrow self-interest. Following a long tradi- equilibrium, they are defined in all games
tion in economics, recent models building solely by the parameters and the structure
from Bolton (1991) and Rabin (1993) have of the game. As such, they provide exact
tried to study social preferences based on competitors to Bayesian Nash equilibrium
laboratory data. Inspired by simple mod- and other classical game-theoretic solution
els by Fehr and Schmidt (1999) and Bolton concepts.8
and Ockenfels (2000), Charness and Rabin Moving to limited-rationality models of
(2002) specify a simple form where subjects individual choice, several formal models
who get more money than others put weight fall into the category of quasi-maximiza-
ρ > 0 on those others’ payoffs and 1 − ρ on tion models I discuss below. Loewenstein,
their own payoff, and when behind the other O’Donoghue, and Rabin (2003) develop a
subject put weight σ > 0 on those others and model where economic actors underappre-
1 − σ on their own payoff.6 These simple ciate taste change. Relying on the timing of
models ignore intentions-based reciproc- utility and using a simple linear form, the
ity motives; theories such as the full model model predicts a particular form of people
contained in Charness and Rabin (2002), having irrational beliefs of their own future
Dufwenberg and Kirchsteiger (2004) and behavior: they believe their future tastes will
Falk and Fischbacher (2006) follow Rabin be more like their current tastes than they
(1993) in formally modeling reciprocity con- are. The error is parameterized by 0 ≤ α ≤  1,
cerns into the utility function. where α = 1 means a person fully projects
Closer to the topic of this forum, models
have been developed to capture departures 7 See also Esponda (2008) for a variant of cursed equi-
from full rationality. Crawford (this forum) librium. Although applied solely in simplified form to a
discusses various approaches; two mod- model of naive social learning, Eyster and Rabin (2008)
els that most closely fit the formal PEEM define for all games a form of naive, face-value inference,
parameterized by υ ∈ [0, 1].
8 The alternative cognitive-hierarchy models discussed
by Crawford (this forum), like Stahl and Wilson (1994),
6 Although it is doubtful the parameters are very stable Camerer, Ho, and Chong (2004), Crawford and Iriberri
outside the lab, in a broad class of games estimates are (2007), and Crawford, Costas-Gomes, and Iriberri (2013)
often around ρ = 0.4 and σ > 0 is very close to zero. are not fully closed in the way I emphasize here insofar as
Notwithstanding a heavy emphasis in early literature on the level-0 play is not derived formulaically from the game.
the idea that subjects dislike getting less money than other But they can be completed with any level 0, and also typi-
subjects, a small but positive value of σ is clearly more cally provide unique, and hence more disciplined, predic-
common once allocational preferences are disentangled tions once a level-0 is chosen, than do cursed equilibrium
from reciprocity. and quantal-response equilibrium.
534 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. LI (June 2013)

her current tastes onto her future tastes, and papers have developed quasi-­ Bayesian
α = 0 implies full rationality. These models ­ odels of updating, discussed below. Rabin
m
show that adding realistic systematic biases (2002a) captures the idea that people believe
in how we predict our future utility can com- in the Law of Small Numbers (a term first
pete on power and scope with the full-ratio- formulated by Kahneman and Tversky 1973)
nality model. Barberis and Huang (2009) whereby people erroneously exaggerate the
develop a formal parameterized model of likelihood that underlying population pro-
narrow bracketing, following on the tradition portions will show up even in small samples.
of Benartzi and Thaler (1995), Kahneman Rabin and Vayanos (2010) extend this model
and Lovallo (1993), and Read, Loewenstein, to capture the related gambler’s fallacy,
and Rabin (1999), whereby agents maxi- whereby people expect recent positive out-
mize prospect-theory preferences but fail comes to be counteracted in the short term
to consider how gains and losses across dif- by negative ones; one parameter is used to
ferent choices might cancel each other out. determine how intensely an agent expects
Barberis and Huang assume that people recent signals to be counteracted, and a sec-
partially maximize the normatively appro- ond parameter captures the memory for how
priate combined outcomes from separate long ago agents expect signals to influence
choices, but erroneously partially maximize current outcomes. Benjamin, Rabin, and
the separate choices, parameterizing the Raymond (2012) model a non-belief in the
degree of narrow bracketing by the param- law of large numbers whereby decisionmak-
eter υ ∈ [0, 1]. Surely the most successful ers underappreciate the central limit theo-
PEEM to date is the simple model devel- rem, and assign positive probability to even
oped by Strotz (1956) and rejuvenated by huge samples not closely resembling the
Laibson (1997), on what O’Donoghue and underlying population.
Rabin (1999) refer to as present bias: param- Although the goal is to provide new mod-
eter β captures short-term impatience, els that are fully competitive with earlier
and parameter β​ ​   captures misprediction of economic theory, there is a catch to all these
future impatience. These models are applied models. Even when the independent vari-
widely, improving economic research by any ables are imported from regularly used eco-
standard that embraces the value of concep- nomic theories, the extended models often
tual and empirical insights on economically require interpretations that go beyond the
important topics. original model. Several of the non-expected-
Recent papers also develop formal mod- utility models, and the game-theoretic
els of biases in statistical reasoning, although models by McKelvey and Palfrey (1996)
typically in less general settings than the and Eyster and Rabin (2005), permit literal
models above. Grether (1980, 1992) models extensions (when literally applied) with no
base-rate neglect for the purposes of empiri- additional structure. But almost all the other
cal testing in a simple way, where decision- models do rely on adding further structure
makers apply Bayes Rule in updating, but, in than is a literal part the previous neoclassi-
the logarithmic form of Bayes Rule, weigh cal model they are modifying. The model of
the base rate by only α < 1. Proper Bayesian present bias, for instance, requires interpre-
updating corresponds to α = 1, while α = 0 tations of the time-delivery of utility flows
corresponds to maximal base-rate neglect that need not per se be considered a primitive
in which priors are neglected altogether. of models without present bias. Fortunately,
Building on an approach pioneered by the timing of utility is obvious, observable,
Barberis, Shleifer, and Vishny (1998), ­several and well understood in p ­ revailing contexts.
Rabin: Incorporating Limited Rationality into Economics 535

Models of social preferences likewise require Although research is necessarily still at the
cardinal interpretations of material payoffs, stage of estimating parameters (and, obvi-
such as money, before those models that ously, building new models and modifying
specify exact parameters are pinned down. previous iterations), a theme of the literature
Likewise, models like K​   ˝ s zegi and Rabin
o​ is that the improvements are coming from
(2006) that in principle pin down exact alter- precise alternatives, not degrees of freedom.
native predictions in all situations require a The variant of prospect theory in K​   o​szegi
˝  and
cardinal interpretation of the consumption Rabin (2006, 2007) corresponding to η = 1,
utility as it appears in economic models. λ = 3, α = 0.88 probably fits large ranges of
In addition, an assumption of what aspects data better than classical reference-indepen-
of consumption constitute distinct hedonic dent model corresponding to η = 0. Eyster
dimensions must be specified in a way not and Rabin (2005) propose that estimating a
demanded of classical consumer theory. Yet type of information neglect by χ = 0.5 fits
these too are rarely that ambiguous or sub- evidence across games better than the fully
ject to hidden specification mining in par- rational χ = 0. Models of p ­ resent bias and
ticular applications. Models of probability naivety ­specifying β =  0.7, β​ ​   = 0.8 surely
judgment that depart from Bayesian reason- fit most data ­better than the classical param-
ing, on the other hand, often require even eters β = ​ β​  = 1. Indeed, in this domain a
more ancillary assumptions specifying how good guess is that improved assumptions will
decisionmakers frame hypotheses. Models fit behavior better while removing a degree
of narrow framing, like Barberis and Huang of freedom: instead of trying to fit data with
(2009), must make strong assumptions about wildly varying values for the traditional dis-
how people separate their decisions. count factor, δ, once we use better values of β
In other cases, the parameters are likely to and β​
​    we can also restrict our models to the
be affected by factors outside the model to more reasonable yearly δ ≈ 0.95. Laboratory
the point where they are unstable. Care must data and early field estimates suggest that a
be taken, however, not to invoke the insta- good guess about the degree of underappre-
bility of specifications to favor worse stable ciation in taste predictions across settings as
models over better stable models simply modeled by Loewenstein, O’Donoghue, and
because that is what earlier models assumed. Rabin (2003) is that a misprediction param-
For instance, the model that parameterizes eter of α = 0.5 may generally fit better than
inattentiveness to the information contained the fully rational α = 0. Rabin and Vayanos
in others’ behavior, as formalized by Eyster (2010) and subsequent work estimate that
and Rabin (2005), is clearly missing varia- the gambler’s fallacy of (α, δ) = (0.2, 0.7) fits
tion due to factors missing from the model, better than the Bayesian α = 0. Benjamin,
such as experience of economic actors and Rabin, and Raymond (2012) estimate the
the salience of the information. This means degree of nonbelief in the law of large num-
assuming the empirical average χ = 0.5 (say) bers across a wide range of experiments at
rather than a less-pinned-down χ ∈ [0, 1] ψ ∈ [7, 15] rather than the Bayesian model
may sacrifice too much realism for the sake of ψ = ∞. Such numbers will surely not hold
of precision—but assuming a universal up or be stable, and several are simply best
χ = 0 as current game theory does sacrifices guesses I am listing here. But the effort to
even more. do so reflects an increasing standard in the
Insofar as these new models leave open literature that some fixed parameterization
parameters, they will of course increase of alternative models ought to fit better than
degrees of freedom in making predictions. the rational model across settings, rather
536 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. LI (June 2013)

than performing well solely from degrees of having them as judiciously applied addenda
freedom or selectivity of examples. to rational models. My worry is that, short of
This standard, in turn, reflects a growing extremely tight empirical attention, applica-
emphasis in this research program on making tions of the models as replacements for the
pervasive improvements rather than finding neoclassical paradigm may worsen our pre-
particular cases where new models do well. dictions in general.
It is right to cut slack for new insights dur- To my mind, there is a simple and com-
ing early stages of development—evidence- mon reason why some bounded-rationality
gathering and theory-forming under extreme models are so unlikely to perform well across
and selective circumstances can be the best contexts: too much realistic rationality is
way to understand the logic and potential being left out. Many models of reinforce-
of new models. But if the long-run goal is ment learning, for instance, assume neither
for newer models that explain things better a priori rationality nor anything like Nash
than the traditional model, care should be equilibrium. Yet virtually all applications—
taken to investigate whether the new models either by design in the laboratory or by intu-
improve insight on average. ition in thought experiments—presort the
I believe that this is especially important environment so that there is little scope for
in the context of judging bounded-rationality irrationality to lead people far astray. Of the
models. In my view, many new models and thousands of disastrous things all of us could
explanations for experimental findings look do in virtually every new situation we face in
artificially good and artificially insightful in life—including all situations economists care
the very limited domain to which they are about—basic reason whittles away all but a
applied. Although this is a problem for all few. That is, assumptions of rationality and
sorts of bounded-rationality and behavioral- Nash equilibrium do much of the heavy lift-
economic theories, and a ubiquitous prob- ing of restricting predictions, and only then
lem for less formal theories people provide do other theories improve our predictions
for their experimental results, it may be that further. It is good, practical science to focus
procedurally rational models may be espe- on what the existing neoclassical models
cially susceptible to the illusion of explanatory are missing. But when it comes to formu-
power. Roughly put, the models inherently lating the general models that are serious
steer us toward judging them solely in the competitors to full rationality, recognition
specific contexts where the procedures make of the pervasive power of rationality and
basic rational sense and seem intuitively equilibrium suggests we need the new mod-
likely—omitting all the cases where they els to be far closer to the old models than
predict badly. In contrast, although (say) often proposed. Although in the interim it
the tendency to infer too much from small makes sense to formulate models that make
samples is centrally mediated by whether we improvements in specific contexts, one les-
pay attention to the data, in virtually every son from this perspective is that researchers
situation where economists had previously ought to imagine how they might eventually
applied the Bayesian-updating model, the combine new theories with a core of strong
law-of-small-numbers inference model may rationality. I believe the types of models I
improve our predictions. I am not as sanguine discuss above and below are more oriented
as others that bounded-rationality models of toward that. Indeed, the PEEMs almost by
the sort emphasized in much of the litera- structure have the feature that they replicate
ture have the language or aspiration to apply the rational model in all the ways that are not
so broadly. We are still likely to ­benefit from the specific focus of the modifications.
Rabin: Incorporating Limited Rationality into Economics 537

3.  Optimal Models of Limited Rationality Wagenaar 1991), and the hot-hand fallacy
(see, e.g., Gilovich, Vallone, and Tversky
I now turn to the case for modeling cer- 1985) all concentrate on biased tendencies
tain types of economically relevant errors in to see imaginary patterns. The rational way
terms of optimization models, based on the to do the familiar task of predicting the like-
joint attractions of psychological realism and lihood that the next flip of a coin is tails has
methodological benefits. a happy simplicity to it.10 But people have
Economists have an intuition and disposi- far more complicated beliefs that differ-
tion to model bounded rationality in terms of ent answers are needed for predictions fol-
complexity and inattention. The idea is often lowing HTHHHH versus HTTHTH versus
that people are cognitive misers: we humans THTHTH.11 And traders appear not to ask
wisely choose not to figure out all the exact the very simple question who in the market
right solutions to all the problems that face is trading with me, and why?, or to come up
us.9 This intuition is often on target. But one with the near inevitable and perspective-
of the biggest lessons of some branches of changing answer that it is somebody who is
psychology is how many errors are simply himself trying to make money from differ-
not in any useful sense conceptualized this ent beliefs about an asset. The logic of real-
way. The degree to which attention to small- izing that in the future you’ll have just the
scale risks reflects rational maximization of same self-control problem as now is no more
news-utility preferences or reflects errors is a complicated than the belief that beginning
difficult question. But evidence suggests that tomorrow you will reform your ways; just less
small-scale risk aversion is not only an error, psychologically compelling. The logic that
but a rather effortful one: consumers would you will crave food in the future when hun-
be better off simply never buying small-scale gry, or (if addicted) crave a drug when you’ve
insurance and extended warranties. And gone too long without a hit, is cognitively
they would leave the store sooner. Among available to all as a familiar fact of life; but
the many errors small investors make, the it does not grab our attention at moments of
inability to see incredibly complicated arbi- decisionmaking when we are currently sated
trage opportunities in real time might be with food or drug.
costly. Whether it is true and important that Nor do all errors come from lack of effort
arbitrage opportunities are left on the table to overcome them, or intellectual or physical
by those that don’t see them, a far more per- laziness. People may not spend much effort
vasive error is that people tend to see pat- predicting coin flips, but many spend huge
terns that are not there. Research on illusory amounts of time trying to see the patterns in
correlation (e.g., Chapman and Chapman stocks that, for any plausible money-making
1969 and Hamilton and Gifford 1976), the opportunities, are best approximated by
gambler’s fallacy (see, e.g., Bar-Hillel and a random walk. Not only may we maintain
naiveté about our self-control problems in
defiance of any attentive learning rule—we
9 Economists are, I think, drawn to complexity explana- may put a lot of intellectual energy into not
tions for limited rationality for several reasons. The main learning. The right explanation for misbehav-
and best reason is its realism: it is intuitive and it is true
that many of our limits come from the sheer impossibility ior could eliminate convoluted, complicated,
of attending to everything or fully maximizing when we do
pay attention. But it also seems to have an appeal based on
its affinity with computer science and math, rather than 10  0.5.
psychology, and its greater amenability to deriving assump- 11 Subjects tend to predict lower and lower chances of
tions from first principles rather than empirical evidence. tails going from the first to the third sequence.
538 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. LI (June 2013)

and time-consuming stories; the 1,000 differ- set she is choosing from. The three main
ent reasons why you didn’t start your diet or classes of such quasi-maximization errors are
dissertation the previous 1,000 days could be what might be called (a) narrow bracketing,
replaced with the simpler right answer—you (b) present bias and hyperbolic discounting,
didn’t have the willpower. Or you think you’ll and (c) projection bias in predicting future
not drink or have unsafe sex or smoke when utility. Narrow bracketing is where people
you go out tonight, rather than think the maximize their true utility functions among
equally simple (and truer) hypothesis that each choice set they focus on, but don’t inte-
you’ll likely do the same things you always grate others. Present bias is where, moment
do.12 Such effortful errors are most strikingly by moment, a person maximizes full inter-
inconsistent with the bounded-rationality temporal utility, but at each moment tends
metaphor when they involve a great deal of to overweight current utility. (And may mis-
planning and actions. If per DellaVigna and predict the propensity to do so in the future.)
Malmendier (2006) we actively join gyms Projection bias is where, because of current
and make other long-term plans for virtuous tastes or current focus, people (actively or
activities in irrational ways, it would appear passively) mispredict the utility of future
that there is a whole lot of optimization going situations. Formally, all these errors can be
on. Just the wrong kind. conceptualized as follows. As a function of
As noted earlier, one major class of opti- a person’s environment, the person makes
mization-based errors can be conceptualized choices from a choice set, and maximizes a
as very close to utility maximization: situation particular goal: Ma​x​  x∈X​v(x). But people may
by situation, people have reasonably focused either focus on the wrong choice set (nar-
goals, and maximize those goals reasonably row bracketing), overweight near-term util-
well. We can model a person as engaging in ity (present bias) or mispredict future utility
traditional constrained maximization at each (projection bias).
moment in time. But we specify the exact Present bias and naiveté about pres-
mistake the person is making in which func- ent bias as modeled by Laibson (1997) and
tion she is maximizing, or in what choice O’Donoghue and Rabin (1999, 2001) is the
most well known of these quasi-maximization
errors. The third example, projection bias as
12 There are two important caveats to this perspective. modeled by Loewenstein, O’Donoghue, and
First, it is slightly misleading to frame things in terms of Rabin (2003), applies in situations where
how simple an answer is. An answer can be simple without
it being easy to figure out. But many of these errors seem tastes change over time, either due to tem-
robust to simple communication of the right answer by a porary fluctuations (such as mood swings, or
trustworthy person in a way that could happen only when a satiation and deprivation of food or drugs),
person is enticed by a countervailing intuition. Second, we
need to be somewhat careful that the simplicity of a correct or due to longer term adaptation (such as
answer in a particular class of situations doesn’t require the to our standard of living) or habit formation
complex and time-consuming task for people to identify (such as exercise, or addiction to a drug).
what situations they are in. Maybe the fact that we should
not extrapolate our current tastes in cases where our Changing tastes are a fact about utility, not
tastes predictably change belies the fact that on average an indication of irrationality. The error:
our future tastes will be our current ones; simply assum- people systematically underappreciate (even
ing no change may be a simple rule of thumb. This too
seems wildly miscalibrated. “Ignore current hunger” seems very predictable) changes in their tastes, and
not only a simpler rule of thumb than “extrapolate current hence falsely project their current tastes
hunger,” but it also seems the mastering of improved rules onto the future. Formally, Loewenstein,
like this is almost always employed in comparably impor-
tant confrontations with binary variation in life that do not O’Donoghue, and Rabin (2003) offer an
implicate the hold that current cravings have on us. alternative to the rational-choice a­ ssumption
Rabin: Incorporating Limited Rationality into Economics 539

that people maximize state-dependent ­utility, There are also now a class of models that
which can be represented (without dis- capture errors in people’s statistical reason-
counting) by ing that fully accord to neoclassical mod-
els of preference optimization, but simply
U​  t​ = ​∑​  τ=t ​ ​, ​s​τ​),
T
​   ​ ​ u(​cτ  build in a systematic misunderstanding of
statistics. In these quasi-Bayesian mod-
where u(​c​τ ​, ​s​τ​) is her instantaneous utility els, people maximize expected utility (or
in period τ, and ​cτ​​ is the person’s period-τ any other appropriate utility function), but
consumption vector which includes all
­ form their expectations based on wrong
period-τ behavior relevant for current or models of the world. Given prior probal-
future instantaneous utilities. The vector s​τ​ ​ istic beliefs π(h) about hypotheses h ∈ H,
is the person’s state in period τ, which incor- how does a person form updated beliefs,
porates all factors that affect instantaneous P(​h​∗​  |  e), about the likelihood that a particu-
utility besides current consumption. They lar hypothesis, ​h∗​ ​ ∈ H, is true upon observ-
assume that at time t a person maximizes ing evidence e? Proper Bayesian updating
implies that after observing information
˜  t​ = ​∑​  Tτ=t
​​ U​​    ​ ​​ ˜u ​ (​cτ 
​ ​, ​sτ​ ​ | ​st​​), ​e​1​, ​e2​ ​, … a person forms posterior beliefs
π(​e1​ ​, ​e​2​,  …  | ​h​ ​)π(​h​ ​)
∗ ∗
where ​˜u ​ (​c​τ ​, ​sτ​ ​ | ​st​​) is the prediction at time t B(​h∗​ ​ | ​e1​ ​, ​e​2​,  …)  = ​ __
  
    ​.
in state s​ t​​of u(​c​τ ​, ​sτ​ ​). Whereas rational expec- ​∑​  h∈H
  ​ ​ π(​e1

​ ​, ​e​2​,  …  |  h)π(h)
tations posits that ˜​ u ​ (​cτ​  ​, ​sτ​ ​ | ​st​​) = u(​cτ 
​ ​, ​sτ​ ​),
Loewenstein, O’Donoghue, and Rabin Some errors in statistical reasoning can be
(2003) assume that a person may suffer understood in terms of an alternative func-
from simple projection bias if there exists tional form of how people combine condi-
α ∈ [0, 1] such that for all c, s, and s′, tional probabilities and priors, by assuming
that people use some other functional form
​˜u ​ (c, s | s′  ) = (1 − α) u(c, s) + α u(c, s′  ).
P(​h∗​ ​ | ​e1​ ​, ​e​2​,  …)  =
This posits that at each moment in time
people have well-defined perceived utility f ({π(​e1​ ​, ​e​2​, … | h)​}h∈H
​ ​, {π(h)​}h∈H
​ ​).
from their courses of action, and take actions
to maximize their long-run happiness. This Most famously, people suffer from base-
is right or wrong in all the ways the ratio- rate neglect: they underuse the priors
nal model can be right or wrong, differing {π(h)​}h​ ∈H​ implying updated beliefs have
solely from this general principle of project- functional form
ing current tastes into the future. Projection
∗ ∗ α
π(​e1​ ​, ​e​2​,  …  | ​h​  ​)[π(​h​  ​)​]​  ​
bias can help understand mispredictions P(​h​  ∗​ | ​e1​ ​, ​e​2​,  …)  = ​ __
  
   α ​   ,
​∑​  h∈H
  ​ ​ π(​e1
​ ​, ​e​2​,  …  |  h)[π(h)​]​  ​

of food (Read and van Leeuwen 1998) and
drug (Badger et al. 2007) cravings, underap-
preciation of long-run habit formation (Levy with α ≤ 1.
2010 and Acland and Levy 2011), catalog More interestingly, many errors can be
clothing purchases (Conlin, O’Donoghue, modeled as people engaging in putatively
and Vogelsang 2007), and demand for swim- proper Bayesian updating, but with a precise
ming pools and convertible car roofs based way in which they either misobserve or mis-
on temporary weather fluctuations (Busse et understand how that evidence relates to the
al. 2012). hypotheses. Then r­esearchers ­ understand
540 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. LI (June 2013)

the implications of the error by studying a smart student should have given more good
a form of Bayesian updating that embeds answers than he remembers her giving.
the error. There are two ­categories of such
quasi-Bayesian updating that researchers
4.  Conclusion
have employed. Warped-model Bayesians
update according to One welcome feature of the article by
Harstad and Selten and the reply by Crawford

​˜ π ​(​e1​ ​, ​e2​ ​,  …  | ​h​  ​)π(​h​  ​)∗
P(​h​∗​ | ​e1​ ​, ​e​2​,  …)  = ​ __
  
    ​, is the attempt to relate models of bounded
​∑​  h∈H
  ​ ​​ ˜ π ​(​e1

​ ​, ​e​2​,  …  |  h)π(h) rationality to important economic phenom-
ena, such as asset-market bubbles. Although I
where ​˜ π ​(​e1​ ​, ​e​2​,  …  |  h) is a false (but inter- am not as optimistic as they are that the labo-
nally consistent) model of how signals are ratory evidence they bring to bear provides the
generated. This approach was pioneered by right building blocks for new models of behav-
Barberis, Shleifer, and Vishny (1998), and ior that drive real-world bubbles, the focus
adopted by Rabin (2002a) and Rabin and on the economic implications of new theories
Vayanos (2010) to capture false overconfi- of choice is an important step. This of course
dence that small samples resemble under- comes at a cost if it is too soon to try to apply
lying proportions, and Benjamin, Rabin, our models, or if economists studying real-
and Raymond (2012) to capture the false world empirical applications are not the target
belief that large samples might not resem- consumers of our new models. Yet thinking
ble underlying proportions. Other errors about the implications of new models in work-
are captured by assuming that people are aday applied-theory and empirical economics
information-misreading Baye-sians, updat- is a tremendously important component of the
ing according to program to improve psychological realism in
economics. First, it should not be controver-
sial that mainstream economic researchers are
P(​h​∗​  | ​e1​ ​, ​e​2​,  …)  =
the (eventual, downstream) target consumers.
π( f (​e1​ ​),  f (​e1​ ​, ​e​2​), …..), .. | ​h​ ​)π(​h​ ​)
∗ ∗ Second, it will provide guidance on which of
 ​ ___
   
     ​, the infinite ways we can improve the realism
​∑​  h∈H
  ​ ​ π( f (​e1

​ ​),  f (​e1​ ​, ​e​2​), …..), .. | h)π(h)
of economic assumptions are likely to be most
important. Third, it will provide some guid-
where f (​e1​ ​), f (​e1​ ​, ​e​2​) are misinterpreted sig- ance on the methodology researchers should
nals. Rabin and Schrag (1999) capture psy- employ to improve realism and the types of
chological evidence on confirmatory bias by models that will be most useful.
assuming that people tend to misread signals It is early days for the applications of
as supporting earlier hypotheses. Once a many optimization models of limited ratio-
teacher conjectures a student is smart rather nality, but I do think the more intimate ties
than stupid, he may interpret complicated between empirical economics and some of
answers in class during the semester as subtle these models bodes well, in comparison to
rather than confused. Mullainathan (2002) bounded-rationality models, for both their
models naive memory problems by assuming applicability and the speed at which the
people forget some signals—but update as if models themselves can be improved.13 It
the absence of signals contains information.
A teacher may not remember all the good 13 But see Spiegler (2011) for an excellent exploration of
answers a student provides in class, but may the potential of both genres of models to provide insights
assess the student harshly because he thinks into economic institutions and outcomes.
Rabin: Incorporating Limited Rationality into Economics 541

would be bad judgment to bet confidently References


against the potential insights of a research
Acland, Dan, and Matthew Levy. 2011. “Habit Forma-
line that has generated so much excitement tion, Naiveté, and Projection Bias in Gym Atten-
among economic theorists. And it would also dance.” Unpublished.
be bad empirical analysis—since models of Angeletos, George-Marios, David Laibson, Andrea
Repetto, Jeremy Tobacman, and Stephen Wein-
bounded rationality have already inspired berg. 2001. “The Hyberbolic Consumption Model:
new insights. But I think as we move forward Calibration, Simulation, and Empirical Evaluation.”
with economic implications, with theoretical Journal of Economic Perspectives 15 (3): 47–68.
Badger, Gary J., Warren K. Bickel, Louis A. Gior-
comparative statics and empirical measure- dano, Eric A. Jacobs, George Loewenstein, and
ment, some of the abstract and intuitive argu- Lisa Marsch. 2007. “Altered States: The Impact of
ments we have all provided in this forum will Immediate Craving on the Valuation of Current and
Future Opioids.” Journal of Health Economics 26 (5):
be given more productive structure. Many of 865–76.
the new optimization models are being inte- Barberis, Nicholas, and Ming Huang. 2009. “Prefer-
grated rapidly into economic analysis to the ences with Frames: A New Utility Specification That
Allows for the Framing of Risks.” Journal of Eco-
benefit of both economics and the new mod- nomic Dynamics and Control 33 (8): 1555–76.
els. For models of present bias, Strotz (1956) Barberis, Nicholas, Andrei Shleifer, and Robert Vishny.
and Laibson (1997) started with the impor- 1998. “A Model of Investor Sentiment.” Journal of
Financial Economics 49 (3): 307–43.
tant application to pared-down models of Bar-Hillel, Maya, and Willem A. Wagenaar. 1991. “The
savings and consumption. But the literature Perception of Randomness.” Advances in Applied
has since expanded rapidly to applications in Mathematics 12 (4): 428–54.
Bell, David E. 1985. “Disappointment in Decision
too many domains of economics to list here. Making under Uncertainty.” Operations Research 33
Angeletos et al. (2001) show how it can help (1): 1–27.
understand housing, credit-card, and other Benartzi, Shlomo, and Richard H. Thaler. 1995. “Myo-
pic Loss Aversion and the Equity Premium Puzzle.”
markets in the United States. And there is Quarterly Journal of Economics 110 (1): 73–92.
research now studying its implications for Benjamin, Daniel J., Matthew Rabin, and Collin Ray-
default effects and commitment devices in mond. 2012. “A Model of Non-belief in the Law of
Large Numbers.” Unpublished.
savings, as well as for smoking behavior, opti- Bolton, Gary E. 1991. “A Comparative Model of Bar-
mal taxation, etc. Models of the role of nar- gaining: Theory and Evidence.” American Economic
row bracketing in loss aversion, from risky Review 81 (5): 1096–1136.
Bolton, Gary E., and Axel Ockenfels. 2000. “ERC: A
choice (e.g., Benartzi and Thaler 1995) to Theory of Equity, Reciprocity, and Competition.”
labor supply (e.g., Camerer et al. 1997 and American Economic Review 90 (1): 166–93.
Crawford and Meng 2011), are also surely Busse, Meghan R., Devin G. Pope, Jaren C. Pope, and
Jorge Silva-Risso. 2012. “Projection Bias in the Car
going to improve empirical work. Analysis and Housing Markets.” Unpublished.
of the role of mispredicting future prefer- Camerer, Colin F., Linda Babcock, George Loewen-
ences, now studied in the context of cloth- stein, and Richard Thaler. 1997. “Labor Supply of
New York City Cabdrivers: One Day at a Time.”
ing, car, and housing choices (see Conlin, Quarterly Journal of Economics 112 (2): 407–41.
O’Donoghue, and Vogelsang 2007 and Busse Camerer, Colin F., Teck-Hua Ho, and Juin-Kuan Chong.
et al. 2012) are in earlier days. Little has yet 2004. “A Cognitive Hierarchy Model of Games.”
Quarterly Journal of Economics 119 (3): 861–98.
been done to integrate statistical errors, or Chapman, Loren J., and Jean P. Chapman. 1969. “Illu-
models of how people are neglectful and sory Correlation as an Obstacle to the Use of Valid
irrational in extracting information from Psychodiagnostic Signs.” Journal of Abnormal Psy-
chology 74 (3): 271–80.
other economic actors in strategic and mar- Charness, Gary, and Matthew Rabin. 2002. “Under-
ket contexts. But integrating the potential of standing Social Preferences with Simple Tests.”
portable models of erroneous beliefs—e.g., Quarterly Journal of Economics 117 (3): 817–69.
Conlin, Michael, Ted O’Donoghue, and Timothy J.
to form more realistic notions of the beliefs Vogelsang. 2007. “Projection Bias in Catalog Orders.”
of small investors in asset markets—is clear. American Economic Review 97 (4): 1217–49.
542 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. LI (June 2013)

Crawford, Vincent P. 2013. “Boundedly Rational versus Harless, David W., and Colin F. Camerer. 1994. “The
Optimization-Based Models of Strategic Thinking Predictive Utility of Generalized Expected Utility
and Learning in Games.” Journal of Economic Lit- Theories.” Econometrica 62 (6): 1251–89.
erature 51 (2). Harstad, Ronald M., and Reinhard Selten. 2013.
Crawford, Vincent P., Miguel A. Costa-Gomes, and “Bounded-Rationality Models: Tasks to Become
Nagore Iriberri. 2013. “Structural Models of Non- Intellectually Competitive.” Journal of Economic
equilibrium Strategic Thinking: Theory, Evidence, Literature 51 (2).
and Applications.” Journal of Economic Literature Kahneman, Daniel, and Dan Lovallo. 1993. “Timid
51 (1): 5–62. Choices and Bold Forecasts: A Cognitive Perspective
Crawford, Vincent P., and Nagore Iriberri. 2007. on Risk Taking.” Management Science 39 (1): 17–31.
“Level-k Auctions: Can a Nonequilibrium Model of Kahneman, Daniel, and Amos Tversky. 1973. “On the
Strategic Thinking Explain the Winner’s Curse and Psychology of Prediction.” Psychological Review 80
Overbidding in Private-Value Auctions?” Economet- (4): 237–51.
rica 75 (6): 1721–70. Kahneman, Daniel, and Amos Tversky. 1979. “Prospect
Crawford, Vincent P., and Juanjuan Meng. 2011. “New Theory: An Analysis of Decision under Risk.” Econo-
York City Cab Drivers’ Labor Supply Revisited: metrica 47 (2): 263–91.
Reference-Dependent Preferences with Rational- Kahneman, Daniel, and Amos Tversky, eds. 2000.
Expectations Targets for Hours and Income.” Ameri- Choices, Values, and Frames. Cambridge; New York
can Economic Review 101 (5): 1912–32. and Melbourne: Cambridge University Press; New
DellaVigna, Stefano. 2009. “Psychology and Econom- York: Russell Sage Foundation.
ics: Evidence from the Field.” Journal of Economic  
˝ s  zegi, Botond. 2010. “Utility from Anticipation and
K​ o​
Literature 47 (2): 315–72. Personal Equilibrium.” Economic Theory 44 (3):
DellaVigna, Stefano, and Ulrike Malmendier. 2006. 415–44.
“Paying Not to Go to the Gym.” American Economic K​  o​
˝ s zegi, Botond, and Matthew Rabin. 2006. “A
Review 96 (3): 694–719. Model of Reference-Dependent Preferences.” Quar-
Dufwenberg, Martin, and Georg Kirchsteiger. 2004. “A terly Journal of Economics 121 (4): 1133–65.
Theory of Sequential Reciprocity.” Games and Eco- K​  o​
˝ s zegi, Botond, and Matthew Rabin. 2007. “Refer-
nomic Behavior 47 (2): 268–98. ence-Dependent Risk Attitudes.” American Eco-
Esponda, Ignacio. 2008. “Behavioral Equilibrium in nomic Review 97 (4): 1047–73.
Economies with Adverse Selection.” American Eco-  
˝ s zegi, Botond, and Matthew Rabin. 2009. “Refer-
K​ o​
nomic Review 98 (4): 1269–91. ence-Dependent Consumption Plans.” American
Eyster, Erik, and Matthew Rabin. 2005. “Cursed Equi- Economic Review 99 (3): 909–36.
librium.” Econometrica 73 (5): 1623–72. Laibson, David. 1997. “Golden Eggs and Hyperbolic
Eyster, Erik, and Matthew Rabin. 2008. “Naïve Herd- Discounting.” Quarterly Journal of Economics 112
ing.” Unpublished. (2): 443–77.
Falk, Armin, and Urs Fischbacher. 2006. “A Theory of Levy, Matthew R. 2010. “An Empirical Analysis of
Reciprocity.” Games and Economic Behavior 54 (2): Biases in Cigarette Addiction.” Unpublished.
293–315. Loewenstein, George, Ted O’Donoghue, and Matthew
Fehr, Ernst, and Klaus M. Schmidt. 1999. “A Theory of Rabin. 2003. “Projection Bias in Predicting Future
Fairness, Competition, and Cooperation.” Quarterly Utility.” Quarterly Journal of Economics 118 (4):
Journal of Economics 114 (3): 817–68. 1209–48.
Gilboa, Itzhak, and David Schmeidler. 1989. “Maxmin Loomes, Graham, and Robert Sugden. 1986. “Disap-
Expected Utility with Non-unique Prior.” Journal of pointment and Dynamic Consistency in Choice
Mathematical Economics 18 (2): 141–53. under Uncertainty.” Review of Economic Studies 53
Gilovich, Thomas, Robert Vallone, and Amos Tversky. (2): 271–82.
1985. “The Hot Hand in Basketball: On the Misper- Machina, Mark J. 1982. “‘Expected Utility’ Analysis
ception of Random Sequences.” Cognitive Psychol- without the Independence Axiom.” Econometrica
ogy 17 (3): 295–314. 50 (2): 277–323.
Grether, David M. 1980. “Bayes Rule as a Descriptive McKelvey, Richard D., and Thomas R. Palfrey. 1996.
Model: The Representativeness Heuristic.” Quar- “A Statistical Theory of Equilibrium in Games.” Jap-
terly Journal of Economics 95 (3): 537–57. anese Economic Review 47 (2): 186–209.
Grether, David M. 1992. “Testing Bayes Rule and the Mullainathan, Sendhil. 2002. “A Memory-Based Model
Representativeness Heuristic: Some Experimental of Bounded Rationality.” Quarterly Journal of Eco-
Evidence.” Journal of Economic Behavior and Orga- nomics 117 (3): 735–74.
nization 17 (1): 31–57. Newell, Allen, and Herbert A. Simon. 1972. Human
Gul, Faruk. 1991. “A Theory of Disappointment Aver- Problem Solving. New York: Prentice Hall.
sion.” Econometrica 59 (3): 667–86. O’Donoghue, Ted, and Matthew Rabin. 1999. “Doing
Hamilton, David L., and Robert K. Gifford. 1976. It Now or Later.” American Economic Review 89 (1):
“Illusory Correlation in Interpersonal Perception: A 103–24.
Cognitive Basis of Stereotype Judgments.” Journal of O’Donoghue, Ted, and Matthew Rabin. 2001. “Choice
Experimental Social Psychology 12 (4): 392–407. and Procrastination.” Quarterly Journal of ­Economics
Rabin: Incorporating Limited Rationality into Economics 543

116 (1): 121–60. Read, Daniel, George Loewenstein, and Matthew


Prelec, Drazen. 1998. “The Probability Weighting Rabin. 1999. “Choice Bracketing.” Journal of Risk
Function.” Econometrica 66 (3): 497–527. and Uncertainty 19 (1–3): 171–97.
Rabin, Matthew. 1993. “Incorporating Fairness Read, Daniel, and Barbara van Leeuwen. 1998. “Pre-
into Game Theory and Economics.” American Eco- dicting Hunger: The Effects of Appetite and Delay
nomic Review 83 (5): 1281–1302. on Choice.” Organizational Behavior and Human
Rabin, Matthew. 1998. “Psychology and Economics.” Decision Processes 76 (2): 189–205.
Journal of Economic Literature 36 (1): 11–46. Simon, Herbert A. 1955. “A Behavioral Model of Ratio-
Rabin, Matthew. 2002a. “Inference by Believers in the nal Choice.” Quarterly Journal of Economics 69 (1):
Law of Small Numbers.” Quarterly Journal of Eco- 99–118.
nomics 117 (3): 775–816. Spiegler, Ran. 2011. Bounded Rationality and Indus-
Rabin, Matthew. 2002b. “A Perspective on Psychology trial Organization. Oxford and New York: Oxford
and Economics.” European Economic Review 46 University Press.
(4–5): 657–85. Stahl, Dale O., II, and Paul W. Wilson. 1994. “Experi-
Rabin, Matthew. 2013. “An Approach to Incorporating mental Evidence on Players’ Models of Other Play-
Psychology into Economics.” American Economic ers.” Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization
Review 103 (3): 617–22. 25 (3): 309–27.
Rabin, Matthew, and Joel L. Schrag. 1999. “First Im- Strotz, R. H. 1956. “Myopia and Inconsistency in
pressions Matter: A Model of Confirmatory Bias.” Dynamic Utility Maximization.” Review of Economic
Quarterly Journal of Economics 114 (1): 37–82. Studies 23 (3): 165–80.
Rabin, Matthew, and Dimitri Vayanos. 2010. “The Tversky, Amos, and Daniel Kahneman. 1992. “Advances
Gambler’s and Hot-Hand Fallacies: Theory and in Prospect Theory: Cumulative Representation of
Applications.” Review of Economic Studies 77 (2): Uncertainty.” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 5 (4):
730–78. 297–323.
This article has been cited by:

1. Ronald M. Harstad,, Reinhard Selten. 2013. Bounded-Rationality Models: Tasks to Become


Intellectually Competitive. Journal of Economic Literature 51:2, 496-511. [Abstract] [View PDF
article] [PDF with links]
2. Vincent P. Crawford. 2013. Boundedly Rational versus Optimization-Based Models of Strategic
Thinking and Learning in Games. Journal of Economic Literature 51:2, 512-527. [Abstract] [View
PDF article] [PDF with links]

Вам также может понравиться